U. C. L. A. EDUC. DEPT, THE LIBRARY OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LOS ANGELES Studies in the History of Educational Opinion from the Renaissance SonOon: C. J. CLAY AND SONS, CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE, AYE MARIA LANE. lasfloto: 50, WELLINGTON STREET. ltip>ig: F. A. BROCKHAUS. THE MACMILLAN COMPANY. Bombag anU Calcutta: MACMILLAN AND CO., LTD. \_All Rights Studies in the History of Educational Opinion from the Renaissance By S. S. LAURIE, A.M., LL.D. Professor of the Institutes and History of Education, University of Edinburgh. CAMBRIDGE : at the University Press. 1903 U. C. 1. A. EDUC. DEPT, PRINTED BY J. AND C. F. CLAY, AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS. Education 1! P I A Libm * U, U L, f\. / EDUC. DEPL PREFATORY NOTE. I VENTURE to issue these Lectures in the conviction that the study of the History of Education in the writings of the most distinguished representatives of various schools of thought * is an important part of the general preparation of those who adopt the profession of Schoolmaster. To present a general historical outline of opinion I have found in practice to be uninstructive as compared with an analytic exposition of the doctrines of eminent writers themselves. At the same time, the leading characteristics of the historical development have to be indicated. To deal with the whole question of education during the period of transition from the scholastic philosophy and monastic and cathedral schools down to these times or even to 1600, which may be regarded as the beginning of the Modern period, is beyond my power. And even if I had the necessary learning, I doubt if by so doing I would serve the purpose I have in view so well as by selecting representative 827733 VI PREFATORY NOTE men and interesting students of education in their methods. For my purpose is the education of those who mean to devote their lives to education. The student, who adds to a study of this volume the accounts of Rousseau, Pestalozzi and Froebel in Quick's Educational Biographies and some good exposition of Herbart, will have a very fair acquaintance with the main lines of educational opinion since the Renaissance. I would apologise for the large space I give to Locke, did I not think that his Thoughts read along with his Conduct of the Understanding is, spite of some obvious faults, the best treatise on education which has ever appeared with the (doubtful) exception of Quintilian. S. S. L. UNIVERSITY OF EDINBURGH, December 1902. NOTE. Four of the sixteen chapters of this volume have appeared in books now for some time out of print. CONTENTS. CHAPTER PAGE I. The Renaissance, 1320-1600 3 II. The Renaissance and the School First Period (1320-1450). Vittorino da Feltre, 1378-1446 . 18 III. The Second Period of the Renaissance (1450-1600). Trotzendorf; Sturm ; Neander .... 24 IV. Universities 31 V. " The Governour," by Sir Thomas Elyot ; ? 1490-1546 38 VI. Rabelais : Monk, Physician, Cure 1 of Meudon. I483(?)-I553. Note on Erasmus; 1466-1536 (P- 55) 46 VII. Roger Ascham, the Humanist; 1515-1568 . . 58 VIII. The Jesuits. Order founded 1534 .... 86 IX. Montaigne, the French Rationalist, 1533-1592 . . 94 THE MODERN PERIOD, FROM 1600 A.D. X. Francis Bacon, 1561-1626 119 XI. Comenius, the Sense-Encyclopaedist and Founder of Method; 1592-1671 138 XII. John Milton, the Classical Encyclopaedist ; 1608- 1674 159 XIII. John Locke, the English Rationalist ; 1632-1704 . 181 XIV. John Locke continued 208 XV. John Locke concluded. " The Conduct of the Understanding" 222 XVI. Herbert Spencer, the modern Sense-Realist . . 235 THE RENAISSANCE AND THE SCHOOL." CHAPTER I. THE RENAISSANCE, 13201600. First Period, 1320 1450. Second Period, 1450 1600. THE Renaissance, or the Revival of Letters, is the name by which we distinguish the period which saw the revolt of the intellect of Europe against Mediaevalism in all its forms, political, ecclesiastical, philosophical, and literary. It has correctly enough been called a ' Humanistic ' revival ; but the word ' Humanistic,' if it is to be a true designation, must be interpreted broadly and not confined to the revived interest in Litterae Humaniores. The revival, indeed, was inevitable from the day on which the intellect of Europe had built for itself a house to live in, and put on the roof, and made fast the doors. Thought on moral and religious questions had on certain lines exhausted itself and been rounded off, after having been organized into a system, provided with administrators and guarded by penalties. Of the Church Secular, the Church Monastic, and of Civil Polity this is true. Nay, of the Universities, presumed to be the centres of a living intellectual activity the mind of Europe it was also substantially true, from 1200 A.D. till the time of Descartes. The great organizing intellect of the Middle 4 THE RENAISSANCE, I32O-I6OO Ages was St Thomas Aquinas, who died in 1272. The disputa- tions, which gave zest to Academic life for centuries before and after St Thomas, contained, many of them, grave issues ; but they were all within certain recognized authoritative lines. And even where they raised questions that might have called forth answers fatal to the prevalent theological system, these were often discussed as matters purely intellectual, which, however they might be settled in the dialectical arena, could not disturb the dogmas of Faith. Even after the Revival was in full swing, doctors had, not seldom, one opinion for philosophic schools, another for the Church and the world outside. They were scarcely honest, as we now count honesty ; but intellectual honesty is in these days a cheap virtue ; and yet, spite of this, a good many think it even now too dear at the price to be paid for it. The House which mediaeval faith, scholastic philosophy and ecclesiastical administrative genius had built for itself, was, because of its very completeness, a prison. Perhaps it may safely be said that there is no possible organized system of thought and life, which could sustain for long its despotism over the mind of the higher races of men. Reason is in its essence free, and will always react against uniformity of opinion and custom. It is a disruptive force. The laying of the last stone of a temple is the beginning of its decay. At the same time let us note this fact, that had it not been for the freedom of discussion inevitably connected with the mediaeval Universities from the nth century onwards, the mind of Europe would not have been prepared for any new advance. The scholastic disputations and the revival of Hellenic abstract thought, while they gave form and stability to Catholic doctrine, yet stirred a speculative spirit which went far beyond the limits which the Church would have prescribed. We see this spirit operating as early as Abelard. The Hellenic literature and attitude to life was the great intellectual foe of the Church in the early centuries of the Christian era : again THE RENAISSANCE, I32O-l6oO 5 it intruded itself, and the conflict had to be renewed and is still progressing. It is, at bottom, a struggle between Naturalism in the broad Hellenic sense of that term and Supernaturalism. The former, while necessarily unstable, lends itself to progress ; the latter is, as authoritative, stable, and suspicious of all move- ment. But there were other precursors of the Renaissance. The Crusades had disturbed the mind of Europe and brought nations into contact with each other. Above all, they had brought the more thoughtful and inquiring minds into touch with Byzantine and Arabic learning, which was itself in the direct line of Hellenic tradition. Secondly, the general rise of nationalities and the beginnings of national vernacular litera- tures were indications of a stirring of the mind of Europe of which it would be difficult to find an explanation. The national songs and poems which formed the basis of the Romance of the Cid in Spain (from nSoA.D. onward), the Chansons de Geste of a still earlier date, the Provencal poets, the Niebelunglied in Germany (i3th century), the Scandinavian Sagas (from ninth century onwards), the Romance of Arthur among the Celts of England and its translation into English, the Romances (chief of which was Amadis of Gaul) were all unmistakable signs of the beginning of a way of looking at human life and of a free enjoyment of the human intellect in its own creations, which had little in common with the ecclesiasticism and monasticism of the ages prior to the i3th century 1 . It is probable, however, that the supreme agent in reinstating in man a belief in his natural powers was the intense intellectual activity at all University centres to which I have referred above, and which led to the raising of many questions which had been held to be finally settled. And 1 We get a very instructive account of the pre- Renaissance literary activity in Warton's History of English Poetry. 6 THE RENAISSANCE, 1320-1600 to this we may add the order of Chivalry so closely associated with individual prowess and character. Thus Europe passed out of a period of dogmatic and ecclesiastical bondage into the freer life of the modern world by very gradual steps, and found itself unawares in a new intellectual attitude to life and pos- sessed by a higher faith in human capacities and possibilities. This advance is correctly enough called the Renaissance. The new movement ran in three main streams which had a common source, and that common source was simply Reason itself as a free, and even rebellious, activity. These streams were Art, Religion, and Science, or, to put it otherwise, life in life itself and nature impelled by its fulness to seek the satis- faction of utterance in beautiful forms through the medium of language and the other materials and vehicles of artistic ex- pression; a new and deeper sense of the personal and immediate relation of the spirit of man to the moral order and to God ; and a pursuit of truth for its own sake. An immediate and fresh looking at man and human experience may be said to sum up the Revival. Thus we find living in the first period, Dante, Petrarch, Boccaccio, and Chaucer ; and also WyklifFe, Huss, and Jerome of Prag. When we consider the achievements of these men, and the still earlier vernacular literatures to which we have referred above, it is evident that the Renaissance was not dependent on the revival of Latin and Greek literature for its origin or its permanence. It was, however, inevitable that in seeking for an expression of Life and Art, the more active minds should be drawn to what was ready-made, but had been forgotten. Latin literature and, subsequently, the study of Greek, accordingly, were the two great occupations of the Humanists. In the middle of the i5th century, says Hallam, "The spirit of ancient learning was diffused," on the Italian side of the Alps. "The Greek language might then be learned in four or five cities, and an acquaintance with it was a recommendation to the favour of the great ; while the establishment of Universities at Pavia, THE RENAISSANCE, I32O-l6oO 7 Turin, Ferraraand Florence" (during the preceding generation) " bore witness to the generous emulation which they served to redouble and concentrate." Hallam, i. pt. i. ch. 2. Ambitious scholars from Northern lands visited Italy to participate in the new learning. Wessel was there in 1470, Rudolf Agricola in 1476. It is correct to say that the first period of what is commonly known as the Renaissance was, to begin with, solely, and till towards the end of the i5th century chiefly, Italian, whether we regard vernacular writings, the revived study of Latin and Greek literature, the growth of Art, or the reaction against mediaeval theology. Unfortunately, the new delight in literature, art, and a natural life, and the total breach with religious tradition, led to wide-spread scepticism and to a loosening of moral bonds. A life of pleasure and even of licence was characteristic of the time. Impatience with the theological conception of life took a negative character, and Christianity was nowhere at such a low ebb as in Rome and the other cities of Northern Italy. The second period of the Revival may be dated from the fall of the Eastern capital (1453), and the consequent dispersion of Greek scholars. This gave fresh life to the pursuit of ancient learning, just as Hellenic studies received a great impulse in ancient Rome after the fall of Corinth. The invention of printing also was a vital factor in securing the diffusion and permanence of Humanism, while the invention of the mariner's compass had a potent effect in extending the world-view. For more than a century, before and after the above date, men occupied themselves chiefly with Hellenic and Roman literature. Thereafter, the slowly growing vernacular and original literatures of Europe began to take form, and gradually to oust the ancients from exclusive possession. These continued to hold the field only in the schools. Art in painting and architecture continued to share in the general reawakening. The second stream of the rebirth, anticipated by Wykliff e 8 THE RENAISSANCE, I32O-l6oO Huss, and Jerome of Prag, was the Religious. In this field of thought, man longed to see through form, dogma and ritual into the realities of the life of the soul. The Human- istic movement was thus closely allied with the theological, north of the Alps. In Italy, theology had been abjured and moral laxity had been the result. North of the Alps, however, there was always present a genuine feeling for the spiritual life, although the Courts of Princes had been largely Italianized. A longing for 'reality' in divine things, as opposed to mere dogmatic form, was conspicuous in the Mystics and in such men as Wessel, of whom both Erasmus and Luther speak in laudatory terms. But prior to him, Florentius Radewin, with the consent of his master, Gerard Groote 1 , had founded the "Brothers of the Common Life" (Hieronymians), whose governing idea was life rather than doctrine, and who allied their religious aims with a restricted humanistic study. Floren- tius died in 1400, Wessel in 1489, and Thomas a Kempis in 1471. I name these men because the great intellectual and moral forces operating during the earlier portion of the second period are to be found chiefly north of the Alps, if we are to take a large view of the Renaissance. The pagan and unbelieving spirit among the Humanists of Italy was not shared by the Northern men. With them, Humanism and a reformed Theology based on the original Gospels went hand in hand. There was no separation of the Humanistic and the Religious revivals ; nor indeed, when Humanism at its first dawn was recognized by Catholic prelates in Italy, was it ever imagined that there could be any necessary antagonism. The houses and schools of the " brethren of the common life " spread throughout the Netherlands, Germany and France. The central motive-force was a religious one an attempt to return to a simple New Testament life. They had, as I have said above, a tendency to Mysticism. They were in fact Mystics, in so far as subjective feeling and an intense personal experience 1 Born at Deventer 1340. THE RENAISSANCE, I32O--l6oO 9 arising out of this, as opposed to elaborate dogma, governed their Christianity. It was natural that such men should think more of the education of the mass of the people than dogma- tists or the literary humanists could be expected to do. They welcomed humanistic learning certainly, but always as subordi- nate to the religious life ; and, for a time, only in the restricted form of classical Latin and the literature of the Romans. Even in the struggles of the Reformation period, we find in Luther (d. 1546) and Melanchthon (d. 1560) the Humanistic and the Theological in perfect harmony. It has been usual to regard the more literary Erasmus, because he disapproved of some of Luther's methods and of his insistence on the doctrine of Justification by Faith alone, as a kind of literary sce'ptic, like the neo-pagan Italians. This accusation, it seems to me, is no more true of him than it would be if directed against his English friends Colet and Sir Thomas More. These men represented what in this country has been called evangelical Broad-Church- ism, and worked in the genuine spirit of Protestantism and of a spiritual Christianity. The moderation of Erasmus as con- trasted with the fiery zeal of Luther does not detract from his earnestness. We find his humane and enlightened religious convictions stated in his Enchiridion and in his exquisite and sympathetic portraiture of the rare character of the Franciscan John Vitrarius 1 . The third stream of the Revival was a Scientific stream an extended knowledge of the earth and inquiry into the causes of things. This followed the literary and religious. Advanced spirits began to study nature as a system of laws and to supersede scholastic and theological a priori construc- tions by knowledge based on the observation of facts. This and the extension of geographical knowledge profoundly affected 1 See Drummond's Life of Erasmus, cap. IV. Also in his true "Method of Theology" in the Novum Testatnentum. IO THE RENAISSANCE, 1320-1600 the world-view of all thinking men. Columbus, Galilei, Pom- ponazzi, Ludovicus Vives all belong to the second period. The old order as represented by the Pope and Charles V. had now taken alarm and resisted all reform. The Church quickly gathered together its forces ; and by the decrees of the Council of Trent and the activity of its agents everywhere and, with the help of the Jesuits (1540) and the Inquisition, made great way in recovering its hold on the rebellious mind of Europe. Humanism, the reformed religion, and national liberty had now all to fight for their existence against the principle of imperial absolutism supported by clerical absolutism centred in the Pope. The larger and more vital human interest necessarily obscured the lesser, and what concerned the life of the masses of the people dwarfed the claims of Humanism and culture which were for the few. Moreover, the example of Italy had shown the world that a society whose dominating idea was Art contained the germs of the decay of morals and of all manly virtues. Man does not live by bread alone, that is to say, a material civilization: Italy placed it beyond all question that man cannot live by Art alone, however widely we interpret that word. Protestant and Catholic alike, in strengthening their de- fences, had to surround themselves with the buttresses of dogma; and thus the reformed religion, while retaining at its heart the principle of freedom, yet narrowed itself to a stringent orthodoxy which was, and still is, wherever it exists, almost as great an enemy to the life and art and free philosophy that are the essential characteristics of pure Humanism as the mediaeval system was before it was put on its defence. "U'ith this new orthodoxy was inseparably bound up an earnest ethical spirit, the principles of civil and religious liberty, and the eternal interests of the individual. Where could literature and art find a footing in the face of such important political and tremendous personal issues? Those belong to the 'world'; THE RENAISSANCE, 1320-1600 II and the true Christian, it was felt (as in the fourth century), can know nothing of them, or at best only play with them. We live in more fortunate times. The humanistic and the theo- logical now respect each other's aims the theological spirit having now accepted the best in literature and art and also that result of the Renaissance which we call science; and (what is of more importance), having become alive to funda- mental questions, recognizing that these can only be answered by the help of a free philosophy and scientific investigation which shall unite religious thought with the humanistic and naturalistic theory of life. But the parallel streams have not yet wholly mingled their waters : that cannot happen until religion shall have been wholly humanised, and philosophy, literature and science have been in their turn consecrated. In Italy we have, during this second period, in addition to those I have named, Pico, and his friends Politian and Ficino, and in the sphere of religion Savonarola (b. 1452); in Holland Erasmus, and in England his friends Grocyn, Linacre, Colet and More. Greek and a simpler theology than that of Aquinas had already established itself at Oxford, whither Erasmus came to extend his knowledge of it In Germany we have, among others, Rudolf Agricola and Reuchlin ; and in theology, the Mystics and Brethren of the Common Life, to whom I have already referred '. I am well aware that a brief survey of a great and complex historical movement is, simply because it is inadequate, to that extent inaccurate, but it is necessary to an intelligent comprehension of education as affected by the Renaissance that some such survey should be given.. We may take the date of the death of Melanchthon (1560) as sufficiently well 1 Chiefly owing to the writings of the Neo-Platonist the pseudo- Dionysius Areopagiticus, mysticism had never died out during the Middle Ages; and, in truth, the writings of Dionysius taken along with those of St Augustine entered, though not so largely as the philosophy of Aristotle, into the work of the Schoolmen. 12 THE RENAISSANCE, 1320-1600 indicating the period up to which the Religious Reformation and Humanism maintained a close alliance north of the Alps. The Humanism of the Reformation is, indeed, well represented by Melanchthon's text-books for school and college. To this date the Humanistic and Religious streams had not yet separated their waters. They now, however, began to diverge. The Order of the Jesuits was founded in 1540 and flung down the gauntlet to Protestantism, while so far recognizing the modern spirit as to take up into its educational system as much of the new Humanism as was thought safe. Unfortunately, the reformers of Church and School were too exclusively occupied with the instruction in the evangelical faith of the masses of the people to institute any agency of secondary education capable of coping with the Jesuit organization. The Hiero- nymians, or a Protestant Order on the same basis, and with the same aims, could alone have done for modern ideas what the Jesuits did for mediaeval doctrine and papal supremacy. The scattered efforts of a great humanistic teacher here and there were helpless in the presence of an organized force, with an educational method, and backed by all the power of the Roman Catholic Church. They confined themselves to the education of the upper section of society, whilst the educa- tional zeal of the Reformers, in perfect consistency with their point of view, expended itself (as I have indicated) chiefly on the common school and catechetical instruction. In the Uni- versities the pervading influence was still theological and Aristotelian. Classical Humanism had now reached the age of criticism and learned editions, culminating in those scholars, of whom the younger Scaliger and Casaubon may be regarded as principes. It is interesting to note in the divergent move- ments of religion and literature the same tendencies to criticism, revision and formulation after the first fervour had exhausted itself. And yet we may say that, down to about the THE RENAISSANCE, 1320-1600 13 year 1600, Latin 'style' was still the mark of the humanistic man of culture, just as a genuine faith in the living substance, as opposed to the dogmatic form, of Christianity was still the mark of the reformed theologian. The above brief survey will enable us to see how the study of language became the common bond between the literary and religious promoters of the Revival in the i5th and i6th centuries. A barbarous and monkish Latinity was the vehicle of a barbarous and monkish conception of life. We cannot separate Language and Thought. Hence the identification of the Humanistic Revival as Literary and Aesthetic with the study of Latin and Greek the two great vehicles of literature and art common to the European world. Hence, too, the identification of the revival of a pure Christianity with the critical study of the same languages and of Hebrew. Latin and Greek literature contained models of literary excellence, while Greek and Hebrew contained the primitive record of a great historical faith. To understand the true significance of the faith it was necessary to understand the original records in which it was given first to the world. The great weapon against the religious corruptions of the time accordingly was the Bible and nothing but the Bible, and its interpretation in the spirit of antiquity and unencumbered by the dogmatism of the Church and the dialectic of the schoolmen. This was the teaching of the great Erasmus, who was less scholastic than Luther, but as genuinely Christian. Men had to receive the truths of God anew and to start afresh, as it were. Hence, we may here say, the necessity of always maintaining scholarship in a historical Church, if it is not to become an organ of ignorant fanaticism and alienate all save the unhistorical vulgar ; nay, even because of its extravagances and supersti- tions, shut out the majority of reasonable men. In Philosophy, Literature, Art, Theology and, we may add, in Political Science also, we must ever and in all ages fall back on original sources, 14 THE RENAISSANCE, I32O-I6OO and be constantly bringing to light the primary significance of what has been achieved by our ancestors ; and this by a critical study not only of their language, but also of the conditions of past life. This, in fact, is History in its fundamental sense ; and it will be granted universally that, if man is a progressive being, he must understand the steps of his past progress, or, failing this, go on repeating the barbarisms, not only of language, but of thought and life, which preceded the great intellectual epochs of the Hebrews, the Greeks and the Romans, the nations which have laid the foundations of our modern poli- tical societies, our individual culture, our philosophies and our religious convictions. Language, being thus the common bond of all the workers of the Renaissance period, we must not be surprised that in the education of youth it should itself have become an object of idolatry and ultimately also of well-deserved satire. This was one of the extravagances that attend all great movements, whether they be intellectual or aesthetic, political or religious. Note also that the idolatry of language was a restoration of the ideal of education of Roman imperial times, viz. Oratory. But we must never forget that the revival of Greek and Hebrew had other than literary objects in view. Reuchlin, in first introducing these languages into Germany, with his intense humanism and simple scriptural Christianity, truly prepared the way for Luther, by fixing attention on the original records, and thus on the true meaning of the documents on which the Church was founded. It would be a great error, however, to suppose that the influence of the Renaissance on education was restricted to language. The Renaissance destroyed, as well as built up anew, in every department of education. "The education of the Middle Ages," says Mons. Compayre, " once rigid and repressive, which condemned the body to a regime too severe and the mind to a discipline too narrow, is now to be followed (at least in theory) by an education broader THE RENAISSANCE, I32O-l6oO 15 and more liberal ; which will give due attention to hygiene and physical exercises ; which will enfranchise the intelligence hitherto the prisoner of the syllogism ; which will substitute real studies for the verbal subtleties of dialectic ; which will give the preference to things over words ; which, finally, instead of developing but a single faculty, the reason, and instead of reducing man to a sort of dialectic automaton, will seek to develope the whole man in mind and body, taste and knowledge, heart and will " (p. 83). The Humanism of Italy in the i5th century gave Europe its new secondary school curriculum. Schoolmasters seem however never to have realized that the Humanistic school as originally conceived was much more than Humanistic; it was Renaissance. It embraced much more than grammar and,style. But even if we imitated the more eminent teachers of the 1 6th century in the greater breadth of our curriculum, it would be a mistake to allow ancient languages to dominate the whole system as we have done hitherto. The Humanists educated the few : we have now to give the higher education to all above a certain age, and it is incumbent on us to re- member this difference, and, in the light of it, to reconsider our educational instruments. And this we can do effectually only by considering the question of education itself what it means, what it proposes to itself as aim. And this again must be considered in close relation to the environment and duties of modern nations. If we should come to the conclusion that the purpose of educating a human mind can after all, even in the 20th century, be best attained by bringing modern boys into a living acquaintance with the literature of Greece and Rome, then let us lay all our strength on this and try at last to succeed. We have as yet failed. I should like the Conference of Headmasters (confidentially) to tell the public how many boys are annually stirred by a line of Homer, touched by a line of Virgil, or led to appreciate eloquence by 16 THE RENAISSANCE, I32O-l6oO an oration of Cicero or Demosthenes. Whether from want of method or some other cause, failure is the one word that is applicable to what we call ' classical ' education in the case of 95 per cent, of those who are said to have been ' put through ' it. And as to the remaining 5 per cent, the educational result has in not a few cases been narrowness and pedantry and preciosity the very negation of the true and living Renais- sance spirit. Personally I am disposed to think that there are no instruments that can compare with Latin and Greek literature if our purpose be culture. But to secure this result boys must, in the university, be fit to receive and in a position to continue the instruction which the school only begins. How many are fit to receive and what proportion of those who receive and respond are able, in face of the pressing demands of modern life, to acquire familiarity with the great masters of antiquity ? Can we think of no other scheme of education which will con- serve the past while fitting for the living present ? Can we find no modern definition of Humanism 1 ? In the preceding pages I have endeavoured to give a brief and general survey of the Renaissance down to 1600, and to indicate generally its relation to education in the larger sense. Our special business now is to speak of it solely in relation to the actual work of school and university ; and this I shall best do by adverting, to begin with, to the first period of the Revival 1320-1450 and to the celebrated Italian school of Vittorino da Feltre, which led the way for all Europe in point of time at least, if not as a model. Meanwhile let us note that we should expect to find in schools the fertilizing effects of what I have called the three streams of the Revival : the Literary, the Religious, and the Scientific. 1 The closing chapter of Professor Lodge's Close of the Middle Ages gives an excellent survey of the Renaissance Period, at once succinct and full. THE RENAISSANCE, 1320-1600 I/ The restoration of antiquity gave the chief direction to the work of the secondary schools for obvious reasons. It was only at school and in the university that a knowledge of the ancients could be obtained. Latin and Greek had to be laboriously acquired, whereas the active-minded student could read his Dante and Petrarch and all vernacular contributions to literature without the help of masters. This theory of secondary instruction soon prevailed over all Europe, and still governs the curriculum and aims of British secondary schools. Nor, indeed, would there be much to regret in this if boys got what they were supposed to get, and if the modern "Public School" were as broad and vivifying in its teaching as the earliest schools of the Renaissance both north and south of the Alps. Save in a few cases, the European schoolboy is as a matter of fact not humanized by Latin and Greek. And I hold that it is not, under modern conditions, possible to humanize him on so narrow a basis without a liberal use of translations, familiarity with vernacular literature and an introduction to national and universal history. L. CHAPTER II. THE RENAISSANCE AND THE SCHOOL- FIRST PERIOD (13201450). THE thought of the Middle Ages, penetrated and sustained (from A.D. 1050 at least) by the philosophy of Aristotle ', may be said to have summed itself up in the organizing intellect of St Thomas Aquinas, who died 1274. St Thomas was an Italian, and it is in Italy also that we find the earliest intellectual movements which are associated with the revival of letters. In Italy it began, in so far as it was not an outburst of native genius in the vernacular tongue, with a resuscitation of the country's own ancient literature. I have already said that it is incorrect to say that the new awakening of the mind of Europe to poetry and the arts was determined by the renewed interest in Virgil and Cicero and the subsequent influence of Greek writers. Europe had, in fact, long before begun to seek original expression for its own view of human life. The Provencal poetry, the Northern sagas, the Nibelungenlied, the poetry of the Anglo-Saxons, the mediaeval romances efflorescing in Amadis of Gaul, were the beginnings of a literature which owed nothing to a know- ledge of the ancients ; and it would be a curious speculation 1 Partially known. FIRST PERIOD. DA FELTRE 19 what modern literature would have been had it developed on its own independent lines. The rediscovery of the literary achievements of Rome and Greece accordingly, while they gave a powerful impulse to modern thought and linguistic expression, did not create it. And they gave more than impulse. They presented modern Europe, still struggling with its native forms of speech, with a perfected medium of sentiment and thought literary art of the highest kind. The natural result was that Latin, which had always remained, though barbarized, the language of the educated, was now considered to be the only worthy vehicle of expression. The revival of pure Latinity was thus identified with the revival of literature itself. It cannot be said that at any time this revival of Latin gave birth, save in the case of Erasmus, to genuine literature in Latin. Even Petrarch only partially succeeded. From first to last the writers of the Renaissance were imitative, and even consciously imitative ; and original genius could not find expression for itself through what was essentially a foreign medium. All that Latin even with the help of Greek could give, apart from the substance of thought, was vocables, form, and a standard of excellence. We are not far from the truth in saying that a genuine literature is not possible save as a native growth through the organ of the common speech of a people the mother-tongue of the writer. Vittorino da Feltre, 1378 1446. The typical school of the First Renaissance was that of Vittorino da Feltre, born 1378, died 1446. At Mantua, whither he had gone on the invitation of the lord of Mantua (Gonzaga), he opened a school for his children and such others as might be admitted. As directly connected with the reigning family this school might be called a Palatine school, like that of Charlemagne and the ninth century 1 . 1 Also the school of Nebuchadnezzar and of the Persian kings. 20 FIRST PERIOD. DA FELTRE The success of the school was due to the genius of Vittorino. Endowed with a large share of common sense, he was able to organize a school on the basis of Humanism which neither exaggerated the claims of the ancients nor broke with the mediaeval Christian ideal. The paganism, which already was infecting the Renaissance, was as far removed from Vittorino's sympathies as from those of the transalpine German Humanists of the second period of the Revival. His educational method was influenced by the ancients so far that a sound body was regarded as the condition of a sound mind. Hence games and bodily exercises, to which he attached great importance. The supreme aim, however, was the penetration of the Christian life with classical culture. But he did not exclude, as did many subsequent schools which called themselves Humanistic, other subjects of instruction. He believed that variety of work promoted greater energy and activity of mind in the pursuit of the dominant studies of the school. Arithmetic, geometry, natural philosophy, natural history and music were all admitted to the curriculum. As regards mere intellectual culture, this was measured by him, as by all Humanists every- where, by command over language. Ratio showed itself in Oratio. Hence the great attention paid to constant composition in Latin on the model of Cicero. In corporal punishment Vittorino did not believe. He could dispense with it ; and, indeed, I doubt if any great educator can be named who has not dispensed with it, save in the very last resort. The moral training of the pupils, extending even to their personal carriage, was, considering the looseness of the time, rigid in its character ; but it was accomplished by personal influence and supervision, not by coercion. Vespasiano says that Da Feltre's academy was a " sanctuary of manners, deeds, and words." Vittorino's school was thus, in marked contrast to the monastic and cathedral schools, an active, healthy, and happy school, with a clearly defined ethical character. We cannot read the account given by Mr Woodward and FIRST PERIOD. DA FELTRE 21 Mr Addington Symonds (resting largely on Rosmini's life of Da Feltre) without seeing that this typical Humanist, both in respect of aim and method, was a close follower of Quintilian 1 . The education given was Roman, not Hellenic, as became an Italian school. Much of Quintilian was known before Poggio discovered a complete MS. in 1414 at S. Gallen. Doubtless Vittorino had perused the whole. Vittorino died at the age of sixty-nine in 1446, the date at which one may fix the beginning of the second period of the Renaissance. " Wholly dedicated to the cares of teaching," says Mr Addington Symonds 2 , "more anxious to survive in the good fame of his scholars than to secure the immortality of literature, Vittorino bequeathed no writings to posterity. He lived to a hale and hearty old age, and when he died in 1446 it was found that the illustrious scholar, after enjoying for so many years the liberality of his princely patron, had not accumulated enough money to pay for his own funeral. What- ever he possessed he spent in charity during his lifetime, trusting to the kindness of his friends to bury him when dead. Few lives of which there is any record in history are so perfectly praiseworthy as Vittorino's : few men have more nobly realized the idea of living for the highest objects of their age; few have succeeded in keeping themselves so wholly unspotted by the vices of the world around them." The " importance of the position of Vittorino " (says Mr Woodward, p. 91) "lay partly in his own scholarship and reading but more in the genius which he manifested in reducing the vast body of rediscovered literature to the service of a new education" "The old ideal of knowledge, the growth of centuries, was replaced almost within a generation by a new one which should correspond in some way with a 1 "Roman Education," in The Historical Survey of Pre-Christian Edufation, Longmans, 1897. * Revival of Learning, p. 297. 22 FIRST PERIOD. DA FELTRE deeper sense of national continuity and of the breadth of human interests." "The relation of the new hope to the old faith, the balance between literary form and moral content, the conflict between the Greek ideal of the body and the asceticism of the Church here were some of the graver problems that pressed for attention." And I think that we may say that Vittorino solved these problems for himself and for the modern spirit in a combination of religious and Humanistic teaching well-fitted to produce the cultured gentle- man and capable citizen. Hallam (Lit. Hist. i. pt. i. cap. 2) says, " If Gasparin (of Bergamo) was the best writer of this generation, the most accomplished instructor was Victorin of Feltre, to whom the Marquis of Mantua entrusted the education of his own children. Many of the Italian nobility and some distinguished scholars were brought up under the care of Victorin in that city ; and in a very corrupt age he was still more zealous for their moral than their literary improvement. A pleasing account of his method of discipline will be found in Tiraboschi, or more fully in Corniani from a life written by one of Victorin's pupils, Prendilacqua. ' It could hardly be believed,' says Tiraboschi, 'that in an age of such rude manners a model of such perfect education could be found : if all to whom the care of youth is entrusted would make it theirs, what rich fruits they would derive from their labours ! ' The learning of Victorin was extensive ; he possessed a moderate library, and, rigidly demanding a minute exactness from his pupils in their interpretation of ancient authors as well as in their own compositions, laid the foundations of a propriety of style which the next age was to display." Among the writers on Education in Italy bred under the impulse of the first Revival were : (1) L. Bruni D'Arezzo who wrote De Studiis et Litter is about 1405. (2) Petrus Paulus Vergerius, one of the earliest humanistic FIRST PERIOD. DA FELTRE 23 writers on Education, who was born in 1349 and wrote a treatise, De ingenuis moribus, about 1392. (3) Battista Guarino, born in 1434, wrote De Ordine Docendi et Studendi (1459). (4) Aeneas Sylvius Piccolomini (Pope Pius II., died 1464), wrote a treatise, De Liberorum Educatione. These treatises have been translated by Mr Woodward in his excellent book, Vittorino da Feltre and other Humanist Educators (1897). They all breathe a common spirit. The materials of education, apart from a grounding in Christian faith and practice, are, whether we look to the making of the man or the citizen, Language and Literature as exemplified in the practice of Vittorino. This was the conviction of the Humanists. The Christian life was to be sustained and adorned by the life of culture, and culture was attainable only through the Roman classics, and to a limited extent the Greek writers. The methods of teaching and discipline advocated were, on the whole, much sounder than any that were prevalent even during the second Revival, and far in advance of the practice of secondary schools down to the present time. The training of the body and gymnastic were not lost sight of, I have said, nor were other subjects than Latin ignored. In brief, the whole educational movement of the First Renaissance and much of the Second was an attempt to restore the best type of Romano- Hellenic school as that is presented in Quintilian 1 . We are not, of course, to suppose that there were many schools modelled on that of Vittorino da Feltre or reaching the perfection conceived by those Italians who wrote on Education. But the general spirit and aim of the Humanists undoubtedly began to leaven much of the instruction and to suggest also a humaner moral discipline. 1 Greek was only beginning to be studied and taught. CHAPTER III. THE SECOND PERIOD OF THE RENAISSANCE (1450 1600). Trotzendorf; Sturm; Neander. IT was only in the sphere of Christian doctrinal reform that the first Revival can be said to have been operative north of the Alps. It was identified largely with the names of Wykliffe and Huss, and, we may add, Florentius Radewin (died 1400), the founder of the " Brothers of the Common Life," whose aim was practical Christianity (with a tendency to Mysticism) rather than the cultivation of scholastic theology or religious ritual. The second period of the Revival it is customary to date from 1453, the Fall of Constantinople. The renewed impulse given by the dispersion of Greek scholars, coinciding as it did with the earliest practical application of the printing art, guaranteed permanence. It was only this second Humanistic revival which fully reached Northern nations. To this period belong the transalpine names of Nicolaus of Cusa (d. 1464), at once schoolman,' Humanist, and religious reformer in the Catholic sense, Rudolf Agricola (d. 1485), Rabelais, Montaigne, Hegius, Erasmus, Sturm, etc. So early as 1476 we find Alex. Hegius at Deventer teaching the elements of Greek and a classical Latinity in the spirit of Humanism to the boy Erasmus among others. But it was quite the end of the century before this example was much followed. The Cathedral school of TROTZENDORF ; STURM ; NEANDER 25 Miinster under Langen and Murmellius was famous in the beginning of the :6th century. The best results of the Humanistic revival in the school were, however, not fully visible north of the Alps until Trot- zendorf, friend of Melanchthon, began his scholastic career in 1516 at Gorlitz and afterwards as rector (1524) of the Goldberg school. There were many schools, it is true, throughout Europe in which instruction was given on the lines of Trotzendorf, but none so celebrated as his. The organization of the school, the extent to which the elder boys were employed to assist the master both in the discipline and the teaching, the spirit of friendliness between the master and the elder pupils, all anticipate in a remarkable way what is related of Dr Arnold. His school was called a "second Latium." Latin alone was spoken, and the writing of themes in classical Latinity was one of the chief aims of the grammati- cal discipline. The authors read were, Cicero, Terence, Plautus, Virgil and Ovid. In addition to this, Greek grammar and selections from Greek authors formed part of the curriculum, while logic and rhetoric (the latter chiefly based on the study of Cicero's Orations, guided doubtless by the De Oratore] were taught. Natural philosophy, music, and arithmetic, as then understood, also received an adequate measure of attention. Religious teaching was a conspicuous feature of the school, no less than literature. From this course of instruction we may infer the character of the school, and of similar schools in their degree. He died in 1556. A very eminent schoolmaster he was. The course of school instruction under the Humanistic in- fluence may also be gathered from the record of John Sturm of Strassburg, where he began his celebrated Gymnasium in 1537, continuing to superintend it for forty-five years. Sturm, a distinguished scholar and theologian who had taught Greek in Paris, was allied more to the French and Calvinistic than the Lutheran reformers. He was a vigorous and stern 26 TROTZENDORF ; STURM ; NEANDER master and insisted on the strict obedience of his assistants in the Gymnasium as well as on application to study on the part of the boys. He was a typical disciplinarian. His great idea was education by means of Latin to which Greek was only accessory. The power of speech was with him almost an end in itself. Modern subjects, in so far as they were recognized in the school, were subordinate to the Latinizing of them. He desired that Latin should meet all the requirements of modern life, and it is not an exaggeration to say that educated Europe would now be speaking and writing in Latin alone, if Sturm had had his way 1 . His strong points as a school- master were the accuracy of work he demanded from each class and his power of organization. There were nine classes, beginning with boys of seven years of age. Each class had its master and each master had in his hand an epistle from the Rector which constituted his marching orders, so to speak. The Strassburg Gymnasium was in fact the model of the Jesuit schools and of all the secondary schools of Europe, much more than the more enlightened Lutheran and Italian schools. Sturm wrote extensively on the subject of Education. Michael Neander, again, pupil of Melanchthon, and rector of the Cloister school at Ilfeld in the Hartz, was born in 1525, and died in 1595. His conceptions of education were large and comprehensive. He had, I think, a more living mind than any other Northern schoolmaster. He even asked himself why he should teach Latin and Greek at all a daring, even audacious question in the full tide of Humanism. This openness of mind was, I say, of the essence of Humanism, though already many of the leading Humanists had foreclosed all such questions. Ciceronian Latin had become a fetich, as Erasmus saw. It was not possible for more than one generation of grown men to live solely by imitation. I do not say that Neander, or even 1 See footnote on p. 146. TROTZENDORF ; STURM ; NEANDER 27 Melanchthon, deliberately recognized this. They were too much involved in the movement. The question, indeed, could not arise with them ; for the duty of all men, then and there, was to connect the life of the modern world with the pre- Christian. And yet, where the true Hellenic spirit showed itself it could not but be a living and progressive spirit. Neander showed by his teaching and his curriculum that he possessed the true Hellenic spirit in fuller measure than most. History, geography, science, music, all entered into his school in addition to the traditionary (but reformed) grammar, rhetoric, and dialectic. He had to make books to supply his wants, where Melanchthon had not already anticipated him. A hand- book of natural philosophy and a Compendium Chronicorum (a kind of universal history) and a geography entitled Orbis Terrae Divisio came from his pen. Up to the sixteenth year Latin and Greek were the chief subjects studied ; but there was a wide course of reading so wide indeed that much of it must have been cursive. In the sixteenth year Hebrew was begun, and in the seventeenth and eighteenth the elements and chief precepta of logic and rhetoric ; and thereafter physics, geography, and history. If we compare this curriculum with that of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, we become alive to the barrenness of even our best schools, after the ardour of young Humanism had cooled. The realism, which is also the reality, of Humanism was, in truth, nobly illustrated at Ilfeld ; for there, under Neander, are found the direct con- tact of the young mind with a wide range of literature, with rhetoric, dialectic, history, and also with the world of nature. We are not to imagine, however, that there were many schools even in the earlier decades of the i6th century like those of Murmellius, Trotzendorf, Neander, and Sturm ; but there were not a few working on the same lines : and in England, after the reforms of Colet (friend of Erasmus and More) in the foundation of St Paul's, the stream of literary 28 TROTZENDORF ; STURM ; NEANDER Humanism flowed through many schools during the i6th century Stratford-on-Avon, among others, which Shakespeare attended. Elyot and Ascham (1515-1568) were along with Mulcaster its literary prophets. In the institutions of the men whom I have named we find the best types of the Humanistic school. There was in all of them, as in the earlier Italian school of Da Feltre, a com- bination of religious with Humanistic aims. The classical fervour of Italy and the religious earnestness of the North met in the educational leaders ; and many other teachers through- out Germany, France, and the Low Countries, though less personally distinguished, carried the same combined influences into the daily work of instruction. Nor did these combined aims ever after wholly cease to characterize the secondary schools of Europe. The general curriculum was, however, soon narrowed and the methods degenerated. The narrowing of the educational aim and the return to mere verbalism was, in truth, not long of coming. If it be the essence of Humanism in its larger meaning that it was an opening of men's eyes afresh to nature and life, the exhaustion of the new movement can be easily understood. For it is given to few men, and those chiefly of poetic temperament, to keep their eyes open for long. There is an instinctive craving for dogma and form ; for without these there is no intellectual repose. Each man's philosophy of life is fixed at the point where he grows tired of thinking, it has been said. Even the educated man begins to build his own prison-house very early. Especially must this be the case with teachers, simply because they have to teach ; and for this a schoolroom creed of some sort is necessary. They gladly accept what is offered them in the name of authority and tradition, and it is the letter of the doctrine, not the spirit, that governs. They imitate what they have seen done, or apply the technique of a new doctrine which they have once accepted as if it were a revelation. Some schoolmasters will resent this estimate; but the fact is, it is TROTZENDORF ; STURM ; NEANDER 2Q only those who recognize the truth of what I say as to the tendency of the pedagogic mind who do think, and keep them- selves fresh and open. The intellectual effort and the moral courage required to organize, and the personal enthusiasm re- quired to maintain, the inner life of the Humanistic school of the 1 5th and i6th centuries must have been the endowment of few. The second period of the Renaissance saw the philological and textual movement in full activity, and was distinguished by the names, among others, of the younger Scaliger and Casaubon, and on the religious side by the formulation of Protestant dogma. The schools unfortunately felt the movement at once, because of the tendency of all teaching to content itself with form and formula and precept. There was no agency for maintaining a scholastic aim and method ; the scholastic pro- fession in short was not a profession : it took the colour of the time. It had no independent vitality and no philosophic basis. But every great movement, even when it is spent, leaves some gain for the world. When we ask ourselves what the 1 6th century did for the secondary schools of Europe, we have only to compare the work of the old cathedral and monastery schools with those of the i6th and iyth centuries. The classical authors of Greece and Rome were now firmly es- tablished as instruments of instruction. It is true that the spirit of Vittorino da Feltre, of Neander and Sturm and Ascham was lost in the lyth century; but classical books remained, and could not be taken away. Grammar, though then (and now) badly taught, was simplified, because the text-books had been simplified. These were two solid facts which survived and defied the dullest of teachers. But it appears to me that this was all. The glimmerings of method and the ethical fervour born of the alliance of Humanism with the reformed Christianity had disappeared, and grammar and flagellation, twin brothers, had reasserted themselves 30 TROTZENDORF ; STURM ; NEANDER. indeed from many schools they had never disappeared. Many causes contributed to this : the school cannot be permanently in advance of the time, and every organ of progressive civiliza- tion must wait for peace among the nations. Meanwhile the great scheme of the evangelical Humanists which contemplated a vernacular education for all had received practical effect in many towns ; but as a universal scheme it had to wait (except in Scotland, and, later, in Saxony) on poli- tical enfranchisement for its full recognition ; and this was a business of about 300 years. The extension, however, of primary vernacular religious schools, which had existed in towns before the Reformation, had received a powerful impulse, and continued to advance wherever the reformed religion was honestly held as a religion of personal conviction and soul- experience. The central position of the Reformers was that between man and God in Christ the personal relation was immediate. No external authority could relieve a man of his duty to work out his own salvation. For this, knowledge of the truth assimilated by himself was essential, and this, again, was impossible without instruction. Popular education was thus a logical necessity of the position. CHAPTER IV. UNIVERSITIES. IN the Universities the permanent gain to the Humanists was chiefly the introduction of Latin literature, of Greek, a little mathematics, and the genuine Aristotle (though still taught chiefly through a Latin medium), aided by scholastic text-books and bald epitomes. The study of Civil Law had now also more reference to the spirit and life of antiquity, and Medicine began to be more scientific in its ground-work. These higher institutions were however essentially conservative and responded very slowly and unwillingly to the claims of Humanism and of the modern spirit generally. It has to be remembered that universities were for long placed in a difficult position. They were scholae publicae to which all might go, fit or unfit ; and so long as the secondary schools were few in number they had themselves to discharge the function of secondary schools, as they still do at Oxford and Cambridge in the case of all who are unable to pass the previous examination on entrance 1 , and also in the case of the ordinary pass- man. The necessity thus imposed on universities, and which led to their being attended by boys of 13 or 14, had in mediaeval times been fully accepted, especially at Paris. The result must have been a low standard 1 In the Scottish Universities all have to pass a preliminary examination on entrance. 32 UNIVERSITIES of general attainment, except for a select few. Then, the practice of giving school instruction at the universities reacted everywhere throughout Europe to prevent the erection of secondary schools. But the general conception of a university as a school of the higher faculties, law, medicine, theology, and of philosophy (which also was practically a higher faculty) was never quite lost sight of. In Italy during the i5th and i6th centuries Professors of Latin and Greek literature gathered round them at University and Court centres all who desired culture as opposed to professional instruction, but the universities them- selves were not re-organized on a Humanistic basis. The lecturers were in truth constantly moving from place to place like the Greek Rhetoricians in Roman imperial times. Prior to the i6th century the higher university intellect occupied itself in the department of Arts mainly with logic and metaphysics, as interpreted by the schoolmen in un- classical Latin, and too often based on a partially understood Aristotle. But in the midst of all this they were trying to read for themselves the riddle of life and thought, and they were accomplishing great things, when we consider the con- ditions under which they worked and the complex dogmatism which they had to rationalize. "Scarcely thirty years ago," says Erasmus (1516) in a letter to a friend (quoted in Seebohm's Oxford Reformers, p. 399), " nothing was taught at Cambridge but the pan'a logicalia of Alexander, antiquated exercises from Aristotle, and the ' Quaestiones ' of Scotus. In process of time improved studies were added, viz., mathematics, a new, or at all events a renovated Aristotle, and a knowledge of Greek letters." After the i5th century, though scholastic logic and disputations still occupied the field, yet the ultimate reference was now to a better understood authority. Luther desired to see the curriculum relieved from the Aristotelian metaphysics, ethics, and physics, as taught from text-books, and confined to the logic, rhetoric, and poetics in the original, or studied in epitomes of the original. Cicero's UNIVERSITIES *33 rhetoric also he advocated, but without cumbrous commentaries. These philosophic studies, with the addition of Latin, Greek and Hebrew and their literatures, would have constituted Luther's scheme of university reform ; and substantially also Melanchthon's. And this with the introduction of a better mathematics was in truth the general line which reform took where it was welcomed. At best, however, it was only initiated. In short, even after the i6th century, the Aristotelian encyclopaedia (metaphysics, logic, ethics, poetics, politics, physics) was the ideal curriculum ; but now more genuinely Aristotelian than formerly, and not so thickly overlaid with commentary. The mass of students, however, could never get beyond their text-books, and these were still highly scholastic in their form. Thus the complaints of men like Bacon (b, 1561), and subsequently Milton (b. 1608), re-echoed by all educational reformers, were fully justified. In truth, the resettlement of the Faith of Europe, and the great political issues everywhere at stake, added to the natural conservatism of universities, and the inadequate preparation of those coming to them from secondary schools retarded the full growth of modern ideas in the higher education. And yet the planting of mathematics and Greek in Academic Halls and the study of the ancient literatures, by the few at least, were permanent gains. The universities, however, like the rest of the world, had to wait for Bacon and Descartes and Newton, before they could begin to throw off their mediaevalism ; and they, doubt- less, owed it to the growth of modern literatures that the true purpose of studying the ancient classics was kept alive by being understood. George Buchanan, the Scottish Humanist, who had taught in the Humanistic College (secondary school) of Bordeaux when Montaigne was a pupil there, and was familiar with the work of the University of Paris, drew up a scheme for the reform of the University of St Andrews, which was printed in 1570. This is to my mind a very interesting document, 34 UNIVERSITIES as being a product of the Humanistic revival, and a record of the university scheme of the Humanists 1 . It is well worthy of our attention as showing the then curriculum of a good university, and I shall give the substance of it. In what we should call the secondary school, but what Buchanan calls (as being part of the university) the " College of Humanity," the course was to extend over six years. From the first, all were required to speak Latin and write a Latin theme daily. Their first reading-book was to be Terence, and thereafter Cicero, Ovid, Virgil and Horace. In the fourth year they were to begin Greek, and in their fifth and sixth, read Homer and Hesiod. The boys were then to be admitted to the " College of Philosophy " the university proper and after two years' study they were eligible for the degree of bachelor, the subjects of examination being dialectic, logic and morals. The next year and a half was devoted to natural philosophy, mathematics and metaphysics, after which they received their licencia (equivalent to M.A.). Those intended for the Church then proceeded to the "College of Divinity," where they studied Hebrew, law and theology, expounding passages of Scripture and holding disputations. This scheme of Buchanan's has close affinities to the organization of the Jesuit ' colleges ' and academies, the full organization of which was brought into operation about the same time. In estimating the work of the universities, we must bear in mind that the want of books determined largely the method of teaching. The difficulties by which the diffusion of learning was beset before the invention of printing, may be gathered from the historians of the period, and are well summed up in the following quotation from Mr J. A. Symonds' Renaissance in Italy. "Very few of the students whom the master saw before him possessed more than meagre portions of the text of Virgil or of Cicero ; they had no notes, grammars, lexicons, 1 Hume Brown's vernacular writings of Buchanan (Scots Texts Society). UNIVERSITIES 35 or dictionaries of antiquities and mythology to help them. It was therefore necessary for the lecturer to dictate quota- tions, to repeat parallel passages at full length, to explain geographical and historical allusions, to analyse the structure of sentences in detail, to provide copious illustrations of gram- matical usage, to trace the stages by which a word acquired its meaning in a special context, to command a full vocabulary of synonyms, to give rules for orthography and to have the whole Pantheon at his fingers' ends. In addition to this, he was expected to comment upon the meaning of his author, to interpret his philosophy, to point out the beauties of his style, to introduce appropriate moral disquisition on his doctrine, to sketch his biography, and to give some account of his -relation to the history of his country and to his pre- decessors in the field of letters. " In short, the professor of rhetoric had to be a grammarian, a philologer, an historian, a stylist and a sage in one. He was obliged to pretend at least to an encyclopaedic knowledge of the classics, and to retain whole volumes in his memory. All these requirements, which seem to have been satisfied by such men as Filelfo and Poliziano, made the Professor of Eloquence for so the varied subject-matter of Humanism was often called a very different business from that which occupies a lecturer of the present century. Scores of students, old and young, with nothing but pen and paper on the desks before them, sat patiently recording what the lecturer said. At the end of his discourses on the Georgia or the Verrines, each of them carried away a compendious volume, containing a tran- script of the author's text, together with a miscellaneous mass of notes, critical, explanatory, ethical, aesthetical, historical, and biographical. In other words, a book had been dictated, and as many scores of copies as there were attentive pupils had been made. The language used was Latin. No dialect of Italian could have been intelligible to the students of different nationalities who crowded the lecture-rooms. The 32 36 UNIVERSITIES elementary education in grammar requisite for following a professorial course of lectures had been previously provided by the teachers of the Latin schools which depended for maintenance partly on the State and partly on private enterprise." Even after the invention of printing, books were scarce and dear and had often to be dispensed with. Hallam {Literature of Europe, chap. iv. 2, 31) says: "The process of learning without books was tedious and difficult, but not impracticable for the diligent. The teacher provided himself with a lexicon which was in common use among his pupils and with one of the grammars [he is referring to the teaching of Greek] published on the Continent, from which he gave oral lectures, and portions of which were transcribed by each student. The books read in the lecture-room were probably copied out in the same manner, the abbreviations giving some facility to a cursive hand ; and thus the deficiency of impressions was in some degree supplied, just as before the invention of printing. The labour of acquiring knowledge strengthened, as it always does, the memory ; it excited an industry which surmounted every obstacle, and yielded to no fatigue; and we may thus account for that copiousness of verbal learning which sometimes astonishes us in the scholars of the i6th century, and in which they seem to surpass the more exact philologers of later ages'." Unquestionably learning without books had its advantages, but without the cheapening of the art of printing neither learning nor education could ever have been wide-spread. I have endeavoured very briefly to sum up the gains of the Revival, in so far as it was educational, after it had hardened down into formula and routine. It must be admitted that, even in its narrowest conception, the curriculum of study 1 In connexion with this, see an interesting passage in Plato's Phaedrus (Jowett's translation, i. p. 63). UNIVERSITIES 37 afforded materials, both in the school and the university, whereby a true education might be given by capable men to competent students especially after the invention of printing. But materials do not themselves suffice : there can be no education where there is no life, no vital intercourse of mind with mind in pursuit of some ideal aim, whether that be style, science, philosophy, Protestant dogma, or Catholic doctrine. The fire burns out, and all that has not gone off in smoke is ashes, and with these generations of youth must content them- selves, except where they are re-lighted here and there by the rare genius of an eminent teacher. It cannot be expected that the average schoolmaster or professor should rise above the spirit and methods of the age in which he lives. Great scholars, jurists and theologians, were notwithstanding produced, while the mass of students had now gained access to classical literature and the elements of mathematics. But in the secondary school, and for the ordinary boy, as for the ordinary teacher, life was almost as dreary as ever. Grammar was the despot and rote- memory the slave. Verbalism had again reasserted itself, though now, it is true, with higher aims. The attempt to introduce real studies, even history and geography, broke down. In fact, how could it be otherwise? Who, or what agency was there to organize the spirit of the Revival in the school domain and sustain the teacher's ambition to the level which it had reached in a few enthusiastic and original minds ? After the preceding brief survey, the characteristics of the Revival in education will best be studied, I think, in the writings of representative men whom I proceed to speak of. CHAPTER V. "THE GOVERNOUR," by Sir Thomas Elyot ; d. 1546. The Governour, by Sir Thomas Elyot, was unknown save to the learned few until it was edited and reprinted by Mr Croft in 1880. The writer was a lawyer, and after holding a legal office for some time he was appointed by Wolsey Clerk of the Council of King Henry VIII. in 1523. He died in 1546. The Governour was printed 1530-31. The Institutio Principis Christiani of Erasmus is referred to by him, and he is indebted also to other writers (among whom I would include Plutarch). I think Elyot's book of historical importance for two reasons : first because it seems to have been the first treatise in English written in the spirit of the earlier Italian Humanists, and secondly because it must have exercised influence on the mind of Roger Ascham. It would not serve much purpose to expound the whole of The Governour. I can give the reader a fair acquaint- ance with its spirit and aims by stringing together its leading precepts, and so letting Elyot speak for himself. Colet, I may mention, died only 10 or 12 years before the publication of Elyot's book, but it was only incidentally that he wrote on education, although historically he was an important figure as founder of the Humanistic School of St Paul's. Accordingly Elyot's work may be accepted as the first full exposition of the Humanistic point of view, not only in English but also in England. THE GOVERNOUR 39 Early Training. "Moreover to the nurse should be appointed another woman of approved virtue, discretion, and gravity, who shall not suffer, in the child's presence, to be shown any act or tache (quality) dishonest or any wanton or unclean word to be spoken : and for that cause all. men, except physicians only, should be excluded and kept out of the nursery. Perchance some will scorn me for that I am so serious, saying that there is no such damage to be feared in an infant, who for tenderness of years hath not the understanding to discern good from evil. And yet no man will deny, but in that innocency he will discern milk from butter, and bread from pap, and ere he can speak he will with his hand or countenance signify which he desireth. And I verily do suppose that in the brains and hearts of children, which be members spiritual, whiles they be tender, and the little slips of reason begin in them to burgeon, there may happen by evil custom some pestiferous dew of vice to pierce the said members, and infect and corrupt the soft and tender buds, whereby the fruit may grow wild, and some time contain in it fervent and mortal poison, to the utter destruction of a realm. "And we have in daily experience that little infants essayeth to follow, not only the words, but also the facts and gesture, of them that be provect (advanced) in years. For we daily hear, to our great heaviness, children swear great oaths and speak lascivious and unclean words, by the example of other whom they hear, whereat the lewd parents do rejoice, soon after, or in this world, or elsewhere, to their great pain and torment. Con- trarywise, we behold some children kneeling in their games before images, and holding up their little white hands, do move their pretty mouths as they were praying : other going and singing as it were in procession : whereby they do express their disposition to the imitation of those things, be they good or evil, which they usually do see or hear. Wherefore not only princes, 40 THE GOVERNOUR but also all other children, from their nurses' paps, are to be kept diligently from the hearing or seeing of any vice or evil tache. And incontinent as soon as they can speak, it behoveth, with most pleasant allurings, to instil in them sweet manners and virtuous custom. Also to provide for them such companions and playfellows which shall not do in his presence any reproach- able act or speak any unclean word or oath, nor to advance him with flattery, remembering his nobility, or any other like thing wherein he might glory : unless it be to persuade him to virtue, or to withdraw him from vice, in the remembering to him the danger of his evil example." Beginnings of Latin. " But there can be nothing more convenient than by little and little to train and exercise them in speaking of Latin : informing them to know first the names in Latin of all things that cometh in sight, and to name all the parts of their bodies : and giving them somewhat that they covet or desire, in most gentle manner to teach them to ask it again in Latin. And if by this means they may be induced to understand and speak Latin ; it shall afterwards be less grief to them, in a manner, to learn anything, where they understand the language wherein it is written. And, as touching grammar, there is at this day better introductions, and more facile, than ever before were made, concerning as well Greek as Latin, if they be wisely chosen. * * * "And in this wise may they be instructed, without any violence or enforcing : using the more part of the time, until they come to the age of seven years, in such dissports as do appertain to children, wherein is no resemblance or simili- tude of vice." Variety of occupation. " The discretion of a tutor consisteth in temperance : that is to say, that he suffer not the child to be fatigued with con- THE GOVERNOUR 41 tinual study or learning, wherewith the delicate and tender wit may be dulled or oppressed : but that there may be therewith interlaced and mixed some pleasant learning and exercise, as playing on instruments of music." Latin not to be seriously begun till the child knows his own tongue. Qualification of teacher. Discipline. "After that the child hath been pleasantly trained, and induced to know the parts of speech, and can separate one of them from another, in his own language, it shall then be time that his tutor or governor do make diligent search for such a master as is excellently learned both in Greek and Latin, and therewithal is of sober and virtuous disposition, specially chaste of living, and of much affability and patience : lest by any unclean example the tender mind of the child may ,be infected, hard afterwards to be recovered. For the natures of children be not so much or soon advanced by things well done or spoken, as they be hindered and corrupted by that which in acts or words is wantonly expressed. Also by a cruel and irous master the wits of children be dulled ; and that thing for the which children be oftentimes beaten is to them ever after fastidious : whereof we need no better author for witness than daily experience. Wherefore the most neces- sary things to be observed by a master in his disciples or scholars (as Lycon, the noble grammarian, said) is shamefast- ness and praise. By shamefastness, as it were with a bridle, they rule as well their deeds as their appetites. And desire of praise addeth a sharp spur to their disposition toward learning and virtue. According thereunto Quintilian, instructing an orator, desireth such a child to be given unto him, whom commendation fervently stirreth, glory provoketh, and being vanquished weepeth. That child (saith he) is to be fed with ambition, him a little chiding sore biteth, in him no part of sloth is to be feared. And if nature disposeth not^the child's 42 THE GOVERNOUR wit to receive learning, but rather otherwise, it is to be applied with more diligence and also policy, as choosing some book, whereof the argument or matter approacheth most nigh to the child's inclination or fantasy, so that it be not extremely vicious, and therewith by little and little, as it were with a pleasant sauce, provoke him to have a good appetite to study." After seven years of age the boy should learn Greek before Latin, meanwhile practising Latin colloquially with his fellows and masters. If this be not done, then at least the serious study of both languages should be begun at the same time. Grammar not to be too prolonged. Authors to be read as soon as possible. Method : Committing to memory. " Grammar being but an introduction to the understanding of authors, if it be made too long or exquisite to the learner, it in a manner mortifieth his courage : And by that time he cometh to the most sweet and pleasant reading of old authors, the sparks of fervent desire of learning is extinct with the burden of grammar, like as a little fire is soon quenched with a great heap of small sticks : so that it can never come to the principal logs where it should long burn in a great pleasant fire. " Now to follow my purpose : after a few and quick rules of grammar, immediately, or interlacing it therewith, would be read to the child ^Esop's Fables in Greek : in which argument children much do delight. And surely it is a much pleasant lesson and also profitable, as well for that it is elegant and brief (and notwithstanding it hath much variety in words, and therewith much helpeth to the understanding of Greek), as also in those fables is included much moral and politic wisdom. Wherefore, in the teaching of them, the master diligently must gather together those fables which may be most accommodate to the advancement of some virtue, whereto he perceiveth the child inclined : or to the rebuke of some vice, whereto he THE GOVERNOUR 43 findeth his nature disposed. And therein the master ought to exercise his wit, as well to make the child plainly to understand the fable, as also declaring the signification thereof compen- diously and to the purpose, foreseen alway, that, as well this lesson, as all other authors which the child shall learn, either Greek or Latin, verse or prose, be perfectly had without the book : whereby he shall not only attain plenty of the tongues called Copie (Copia) but also increase and nourish remembrance wonderfully." Lucian, Aristophanes and Homer are next recommended to Virgil, Ovid and Lucan ; considerable portions of which Elyot will have the boy familiar with by the time he is 14 years old. Thereafter Logic (Topics), Rhetoric (Quintilian) and the Orators, Greek and Latin. He strongly urges the teaching of Geography and the study of Maps. Then History as in Livy, Caesar, Sallust, Xenophon. Then after he is 17 years old the first two books of Aristotle's Ethics, Cicero's De Officiis, and Plato. Deficiencies of Schoolmasters. The true method of teaching Literature. " Lord God, how many good and clean wits of children be now-a-days perished by ignorant schoolmasters. How little substantial doctrine is apprehended by the fewness of good grammarians. Notwithstanding I know that there be some well learned, which have taught, and also do teach, but God knoweth a few, and they with small effect, having thereto no comfort, their aptest and most proper scholars, after they be well instructed in speaking Latin, and understanding some poets, being taken from their school by their parents, and either be brought to the court, and made lackeys or pages, or else are bound apprentices ; whereby the worship that the master, above any reward, coveteth to have by the praise of his scholar, is utterly drowned; whereof I have heard school- 44 THE GOVERNOUR masters, very well learned, of good right complain. But yet (as I said) the fewness of good grammarians is a great impedi- ment of doctrine. (And here I would the readers should mark that I note to be few good grammarians, and not none.) I call not them grammarians, which only can teach or make rules, whereby a child shall only learn to speak congruous Latin, or to make six verses standing in one foot, wherein perchance shall be neither sentence nor eloquence. But I name him a grammarian, by the authority of Quintilian, that speaking Latin elegantly, can expound good authors, expressing the invention and disposition of the matter, their style or form of eloquence, explicating the figures as well of sentences as words, leaving no thing, person, or place, named by the author, undeclared or hidden from his scholars. Wherefore Quintilian saith, it is not enough for him to have read poets, but all kinds of writing must also be sought for ; not for the histories only, but also for the propriety of words, which commonly do receive their authority of noble authors. Moreover without music grammar may not be perfect ; for as much as therein must be spoken of metres and harmonies, called rythmi in Greek. Neither if he have not the knowledge of stars, he may under- stand poets, which in description of times (I omit other things) they treat of the rising and going down of planets. Also he may not be ignorant in philosophy, for many places that be almost in every poet fetched out of the most subtle part of natural questions. These be well nigh the words of Quintilian. " Then behold how few grammarians after this description be in this realm." His remarks on the method of teaching literature are beyond all question the best ever written in so far as my knowledge extends. Elyot then goes on to advocate games, such as tennis, dumb-bells, wrestling, running, swimming, fencing, riding and dancing ; above all archery. THE GOVERNOUR 45 Painting and carving should be taught to boys where there is any natural talent in that way. Music also is to be taught but not indulged in to excess. As regards discipline Elyot was much in advance of his time. Hallam {Literature of Europe, chap. vn. 2, 32) says : " Elyot deprecates [as we have seen] ' cruel and irous school- masters, by whom the wits of children be dulled, whereof we need no better author to witness than daily experience.' All testimonies concur to this savage ill-treatment of boys in the schools of this period. The fierceness of the Tudor government, the religious intolerance, the polemical brutality, the rigorous justice, when justice it was, of our laws, seem to have en- gendered a harshness of character, which displayed itself in severity of discipline, when it did not even reach the point of arbitrary or malignant cruelty. Everyone knows the behaviour of Lady Jane Grey's parents' towards their accomplished and admirable child ; the slave of their temper in her brief life, the victim of their ambition in death. The story told by Erasmus of Colet is also a little too trite for repetition. The general fact is indubitable, and I think we may ascribe much of the hypocrisy and disingenuousness which became almost national characteristics in this and the first part of the next century to the rigid scheme of domestic discipline so frequently adopted : though I will not say but that we owe some part of the firmness and power of self-command, which were equally manifest in the English character, to the same cause." Taking Elyot as a whole we find him to be a genuine believer in the power of education and an admirable repre- sentative in England of the fine Humanism of Da Feltre, and one of the most charming writers on education that ever wrote. 1 Alluded to by Ascham in his Scholemaster. CHAPTER VI. RABELAIS: MONK, PHYSICIAN, CURE OF MEUDON. 1483 (?) 1553. \Note on Erasmus (page 55).] A CONTEMPORARY of Elyot, but a man of a very different type, was Rabelais. In his great satire and burlesque, the Life of the Great Gargantua, we have some remarks on the education of the hero and, afterwards, advice addressed by Gargantua to his son Pantagruel, giving his own views of the education which he wished him to receive from his tutors'. Rabelais satirizes word-teaching the grammar and logic instruction of his time pointing out, by producing a cultured youth of the name of Eudemon (an extravagant illustration, of course, like everything in Rabelais), how the ends of education might be attained without the absorption of all the lumber of the Schools. He gives prominence to Latin and Greek, as was inevitable, because these languages contained (for the Western European, at least) all learning both of the past and co- temporary world : but he would direct the attention of the pupils to the real instruction which these languages gave as opposed to the technicalities and formalities of Logic, Rhetoric, and Grammar the trivium of the Middle Ages. 1 Book i. caps. 14, 15, 21, 22, 24 ; Book II. caps. 5, 6, 18. RABELAIS 47 In these few words I believe I have summed up the chief lessons which Rabelais teaches. His aim, in brief, is the expansion and enrichment of the human mind as opposed to the overloading of it with the subtleties and superfluous details of a formal grammar, and a still more formal scholasticism. This appears from the account he gives of Gargantua's own education, conducted in the age of pedantry. Gargantua's own education. " Presently they appointed him a great sophister-doctor, called Master Tubal Holofernes, who taught him his A B C so well that he could say it by heart backwards ; and about this he was five years and three months. Then read he to him, Donat (the popular Latin Grammar for the Middle Ages), Le Facet, Theodolet, and Alanus in Parabolis'. About this he was thirteen years six months and two weeks. But you must remark, that in the meantime he did learn to write in Gothic characters, and that he wrote all his books ; for the art of printing was not then in use. "And did ordinarily carry a huge writing-case, weighing about seven thousand quintals, the pen-case whereof was as big and as heavy as the pillar of Enay ; and the horn was hanged to it in great iron-chains, it being of the wideness to hold a ton of merchandise. " After that was read to him, the Book de Modis Significandi, with the Commentaries of Hurtbise, of Fasquin, of Tropditeux, of Gaulhault, of John Calf (Jehan le veau), of Billonio, of Brelinguandus, and a rabble of others ; and herein he spent more than eighteen years and eleven months, and was so well versed therein, that to try masteries in school disputes with 1 Notes explanatory of the books used by Gargantua will be found in Fran9ois Rabelais. Gedanken uber Erziehnng und Unterricht, by Dr Arnstadt, Leipzig, (n. d.) 48 RABELAIS his own co-disciples he would recite it by heart backwards ; and did sometimes prove on his finger-ends to his mother ' Quod de Modis Significandi non erat Scientia.' Then was read to him the Compost [for knowing the age of the moon, etc.] on which he spent sixteen years and two months. And at that very time, which was in the year 1420, his said Preceptor died. "Afterwards he got an old coughing fellow to teach him, named Master Jobelin Bride, who read unto him Hugutio, Hebrard's ' Graecism,' the ' Doctrinale ' [a metrical Latin grammar], the 'Partes,' the 'Quid est,' the ' Supplementum, Marmotretus, De Moribus in Mensa Servandis,' Seneca 'de quatuor Virtutibus Cardinalibus,' ' Passavantus cum Com- mento'; and 'Dormi Secure,' for the holidays, and other such like stuff; by reading of which he became as wise as any we have since baked in an oven." But what was the result of all this ? " That he did profit nothing ; but, which is worse, grew thereby a fool, a sot, a dolt, and a blockhead." Being introduced to a youth of excellent accomplishments, called Eudemon, who had followed a more modern style of education intelligence instead of mere technical memory having been cultivated Grandgousier there- upon resolves to send his son 'to Paris, placing him under Ponocrates, the tutor of the charming Eudemon. We have an account of his life there, which was devoted to hard work, bodily and mental. In the midst of much absurdity and grotesque ex- aggeration we see that athletics, mathematics, medicine, music, and the reading of classic authors, constituted his chief studies. Rabelais points to the importance of method when he re- presents Ponocrates, the tutor of Eudemon, as studying the character and natural bent of his pupil Gargantua. He also points to the value of manual work; for Gargantua and his companions "did recreate themselves with bottling hay, cleav- ing and sawing wood, and threshing sheaves of corn in the barn. They also studied the art of painting and carving." RABELAIS 49 At a subsequent period Gargantua writes a letter of advice to his own son Pantagruel, in which we find the views of Rabelais further developed. Athletics, music, classical studies, and the study of Nature are all included in his proposed curriculum. Religious instruction is to be from the Bible as opposed to both scholastic theology and ceremonialism. The aim is, like that of Montaigne subsequently, to develope the pupil's (mm thought. The letter is as follows : ***** "But although my deceased father, of happy memory, Grandgousier, had bent his best endeavours to make me profit in all perfection and political knowledge, and that my labour and study was fully correspondent to, yea, went beyond his desire ; nevertheless, as thou may'st well understand, the time then was not so proper and fit for learning as it is at present, neither had I plenty of such good masters as thou hast had : for that time was darksome, obscured with clouds of ignorance, and savouring a little of the infelicity and calamity of the Goths, who had, wherever they set footing, destroyed all good literature, which in my age hath by the divine goodness been restored unto its former light and dignity, and that with such amendment and increase of knowledge, that now hardly should I be admitted with the first form of the little Grammar school- boys : I say, I, who in my school-days was (and that justly) reputed the most learned of that age. Which I do not speak in vain-boasting. ***** "Now it is that the minds of men are qualified with all manner of discipline, and the old sciences revived, which for many ages were extinct : now it is, that the learned languages are to their pristine purity restored, viz. Greek (without which a man may be ashamed to account himself a scholar), Hebrew, Arabic, Chaldean, and Latin. Printing likewise is now in use, so elegant, and so correct, that better cannot be imagined, although it was found out in my time but by divine inspiration ; L. 4 50 RABELAIS as by a diabolical suggestion, on the other side, was the in- vention of ordnance. All the world is full of knowing men, of most learned school-masters, and vast libraries ; and it appears to me as a truth, that neither in Plato's time, nor Cicero's, nor Papinian's, there was ever such conveniency for studying, as we see at this day there is. Nor must any adventure hence- forward to come in public, or represent himself in company, that hath not been pretty well polished in the shop of Minerva. I see robbers, hangmen, free-booters, tapsters, ostlers, and such like, of the very rubbish of the people, more learned now, than the doctors and preachers were in my time. " What shall I say ? The very women and children have aspired to this praise and celestial manna of good learning ; yet so it is, that at the age I am now of, I have been con- strained to learn the Greek tongue which I contemned not like Cato, but had not the leisure in my younger years to attend the study of it. And I take much delight in the reading of Plutarch's morals, the pleasant dialogues of Plato, the monuments of Pausanias, and the antiquities of Athenaeus, whilst I w r ait the hour wherein God my Creator shall call me, and command me to depart from this earth and transitory pilgrimage. Wherefore, my son, I admonish thee to employ thy youth to profit as well as thou canst, both in thy studies and in virtue. Thou art at Paris, where the laudable examples of many brave men may stir up thy mind to many gallant actions ; and hast likewise for thy tutor the learned Epistemon, who by his lively and vocal documents may instruct thee in the arts and sciences. " I intend, and will have it so, that thou leam the languages perfectly. First of all, the Greek, as Quintilian will have it; secondly the Latin ; and then the Hebrew, for the holy Scripture's sake. And then the Chaldee and Arabic likewise. And that thou frame thy style in Greek, in imitation of Plato ; and for the Latin, after Cicero. Let there be no history which thou shall not have ready in thy memory ; and to help thee RABELAIS 5 1 therein, the books of cosmography will be very conducible. Of the liberal arts of geometry, arithmetic, and music, I gave thee some taste when thou wert yet little, and not above five or six years old ; proceed further in them and learn the remainder if thou canst. As for astronomy, study all the rules thereof: let pass nevertheless the divining and judicial astrology, and the art of Lullius, as being nothing else but plain cheats and vanities. As for the civil law, of that I would have thee to know the texts by heart, and then to compare them with Philosophy. " Now in matter of the knowledge of the works of nature, I would have thee to study that exactly ; so that there be no sea, river or fountain, of which thou dost not know the fishes ; all the fowls of the air; all the several kinds of shrubs and trees, whether in forest or orchard ; all the sorts of herbs and flowers that grow upon the ground ; all the various metals that are hid within the bowels of the earth ; together with all the diversity of precious stones that are to be seen in the orient and south parts of the world; let nothing of all these be hidden from thee. Then fail not most carefully to peruse the books of the great Arabian and Latin physicians : not despising the Talmudists and Cabalists ; and by frequent anatomies get thee the perfect knowledge of the microcosm, which is man. And at some hours of the day apply thy mind to the study of the holy Scriptures : first in Greek, the New Testament with the Epistles of the Apostles ; and then the Old Testament, in Hebrew. In brief, let me see thee an abyss and bottomless pit of knowledge : for from henceforward, as thou growest great and becomest a man, thou must part from this tranquillity and rest of study; thou must" learn chivalry, warfare, and the exercise of the field, the better thereby to defend our house and our friends and to succour and protect them at all their needs against the invasion and assaults of evil-doers. " Furthermore I will that very shortly thou try how much thou hast profited, which thou canst not better do than by 42 52 RABELAIS maintaining publicly theses and conclusions in all arts, against all persons whatsoever, and by haunting the company of learned men, both at Paris and otherwhere. But because, as the wise man Solomon saith, wisdom entereth not into a malicious mind and that science without conscience is but the ruin of the soul ; it behoveth thee to serve, to love, to fear God, and on Him to cast all thy thoughts and all thy hope, and by faith formed in charity, to cleave unto Him so that thou may'st never be separated from Him by thy sins. Suspect the abuses of the world ; set not thy heart upon vanity, for this life is transitory ; but the word of the Lord endureth for ever. Be serviceable to all thy neighbours, and love them as thyself; reverence thy preceptors; shun the conversation of those wnom thou desirest not to resemble, and receive not in vain the graces that God hath bestowed upon thee. And when thou shall see that thou hast attained all the knowledge that is to be acquired in that part, return unto me, that I may see thee and give thee my blessing before I die. My son, the peace and grace of our Lord be with thee. Amen. Thy father, GARGANTUA. FROM UTOPIA, the i-]th day of the month of March." There is in this letter much extravagance, and it is to be presumed that Rabelais did not regard his whole scheme as practicable, while yet holding to its main purport. If we collate this letter with Gargantua's own education in Paris, the opinions of Rabelais on education may be summed up as follows : He was bitterly opposed to the grammatical and scholastic studies of his time, and had a wholesome dislike of commentators and critics. He accepted to the full the teaching of the Humanistic revival and desired to send the pupil direct to the works of great writers, and away from futile RABELAIS 53 rhetorical rules and empty dialectic. In truth, Rabelais, like Montaigne and all educational reformers, felt with Cleanthes, the philosopher, who, looking back on a better time, says " tune quidem ipsa res exercebatur, nunc autem verba solum." He certainly inculcates the study of languages ; but this not for the sake of languages, but merely because in no other way could the treasures of literature be reached. He urges also the study of science, and commends personal contact with nature. In general, he sees the importance of instruction through the senses and advocates a wide range of realistic study. Attention to the body and to personal habits, and a good bearing, are also important in Rabelais' eyes. He keeps in view a good, useful and becoming life as the practical end of all education. It seems to me absurd to call Rabelais a ' realist ' because he holds these views. His aim is an intellectual and moral one, and for the attainment of this he recommends the humanistic instruments. If he seems to dwell on the import- ance of a wide and encyclopaedic knowledge of things, it has to be remembered that he was led to exaggerate this aspect of education through his antagonism to grammarians and school- men, and their useless burdening and choking both of the intellect and memories of their pupils with the mere dead forms, grammatical, rhetorical, and logical, of true knowledge. He was no more a realist than Montaigne, who was twenty years old when Rabelais died, and who advocated the views of his precursor at greater length, with a more penetrating insight, and in a more genial, gentle, and rational spirit. With Mon- taigne the end of education was summed up in the word ' philosophy,' by which he meant wisdom and the conduct of life. A similar aim unquestionably runs through Rabelais/ teaching. The real was opposed to the formal throughout. Religion, again, was with him simple, pure, practical: more nearly allied to the Protestant than the Roman Catholic conception 54 RABELAIS of the religious life. Both Rabelais and Montaigne alike were, I hold, Humanists, not Realists, although they naturally emphasized the knowledge of things, because (as I have already said) of the time in which they lived and the special evils they had to combat. No one will hesitate to give Rabelais the credit of having recalled attention to the study of Nature and to the poetic enjoyment of it, as elements in the education of a man. But this does not make him a Sense-Realist. The importance of Physical Training was also first, in modern times, urged by Rabelais, although it had already received practical attention from leading Renaissance school- masters. And when the weather will not admit of outdoor athletics, he makes Gargantua give himself to indoor manual occupation. In truth, there is a great deal in Rabelais brief as his treatment of the subject is. The large and liberal curriculum contemplated, including gymnastic and military training as well as music, suggests that Milton's Tractate owed not a little to Rabelais, as did also Locke's Thoughts through the mediation of Montaigne. I would direct your attention to this : the further we extend our study of writers on Education, the more are we struck with the substantial unity of opinion and object among the greatest of them. Rabelais and Montaigne would have subscribed to almost every word of the early Italian Humanists, and these Humanists, again, reproduced Quintilian. All alike have always before them, as the outcome of all sound teaching, a self-active, living mind. " Accendere animos" is the aim. Plutarch reminds us that the soul is not a vessel to fill, but a hearth on which to kindle a fire. And if the intellectual aim is always the same with the best writers, so even still more are they at one on the supreme importance of moral education and the value of gymnastic. It is with the rise of the Baconian school that a new idea enters. It is, then, chiefly by acquiring that man is to be ERASMUS 55 educated. Knowledge takes the place of wisdom, moral precepts of moral training and personal discipline. This is what is com- monly meant by Realism. But even with Ratke and Comenius and their numerous followers, the ultimate purpose is the same as with other writers, viz. wisdom and virtue ; but they ex- aggerate the value of mere instruction as insuring these. The contribution to the science of education made by the Baconian school is not so much in the attention they gave to sense-realism as in the department of method. Locke's Thoughts will be found to be a wise mixture of the Baconian views and of Montaigne. In the Conduct of the Understanding, however, the discipline of the intellect is the theme ; and that valuable treatise virtually, in my opinion, restores the grammar and dialectic of the Middle Ages, but these based on the vernacular and on the analysis of concrete writings by the pupil, and not to be attained by the study of formal grammars and logics. NOTE ON ERASMUS; b. 1466, d. 1536. Erasmus was the most brilliant man of the second period of the Revival. I have not had time to study all he has said on Education, and I consequently content myself with this note. The educational programme of this eminent scholar and thinker was that of the Italian Humanists : Return to the ancients ; classical tongues to be studied in the sources, and no longer in barbarous manuals ; rhetorical exercises to be substituted for use- less and obscure dialectic ; the study of nature to animate and vivify literary studies ; the largest possible diffusion of human knowledge without distinction of age or sex 1 . He severely criticised universities as the homes of mediaeval barbarism and obscurantism, and he advocated strongly a milder discipline in all schools, and cheerful and sanitary class-rooms. There can be little doubt that Ascham was as largely influenced by Erasmus as by Quintilian. It is superfluous to say that school- 1 Buisson's Dictionnairc de Pedagogie. 56 ERASMUS masters listened to neither the one nor the other. Even in these days we see that the tendency of the majority of secondary school- masters is to look with all the suspicion which ignorance engenders on all serious study of the principles, aims, and methods of the work to which they have devoted their lives. Some have however advanced far enough to write sentimentally and prettily about it. The most important educational works of Erasmus, apart from his Adages and Colloquies, were the following. [In what follows, I quote from Payne's translation of Compayre"'s History of Pedagogy.] Educational Works of Erasmus. In his book, On the Order of Study (De Ratione Studii\ he seeks out the rules for instruction in literature, for the study of grammar, for the cultivation of the memory, and for the explication of the Greek and Latin authors. Another treatise, entitled Of the First Liberal Education of Children (De Pueris statim ac liber aliter instituendis], is still more important, and covers the whole field of education. Erasmus here studies the character of the child, the question of knowing whether the first years of child-life can be turned to good account, and the measures that are to be taken with early life. He also recommends methods that are attractive, and heartily condemns the barbarous discipline which reigned in the schools of his time. Erasmus is one of the first educators who comprehended the importance of politeness. In an age still uncouth, when the manners of even the cultivated classes tolerated usages that the most ignorant rustic of to-day would scorn, it was good to call the attention to outward appearances and the social value of politeness. Erasmus knew perfectly well that politeness has a moral side, that it is not a matter of pure convention, but that it proceeds from the inner disposition of a well-ordered soul. So he assigns it an important place in education. The Instruction of Women was advocated by Erasmus. The scholars of the Renaissance generally did not exclude women from all participation in the literary treasures that a recovered antiquity had disclosed to themselves. Erasmus admits them to an equal share. ERASMUS 57 In the Colloquy of the Abbe and the Educated Woman, Magdala claims for herself the right to learn Latin, " so that she may hold converse each day with so many authors who are so eloquent, so instructive, so wise, and such good counsellors." In the book called Christian Marriage, Erasmus banters young ladies who learn only to make a bow, to hold the hands crossed, to bite their lips when they laugh, to eat and drink as little as possible at table, after having taken ample portions in private. More ambitious for the wife, Erasmus recommends her to pursue the studies which will assist her in educating her own children, and in taking part in the intellectual life of her husband 1 . 1 Ludovicus Vives, a contemporary of Erasmus (1492-1540), a Spanish writer of great eminence, expressed similar ideas on the education of women. He recommends young women to read Plato and Seneca. CHAPTER VII. ROGER ASCHAM, THE HUMANIST 1 ; b. 1515, d. 1568. THE leading topic of Ascham's Scholemastcr is the classical languages and literatures as instruments of the education of youth. Mulcaster and Brinsley were the first to advocate the teaching of English 2 . " Roger Ascham," says Thomas Fuller, " was born at Kirkby-weik in this County (Yorkshire) ; and bred in Saint John's Colledge in Cambridge, under Doctor Medcalfe, that good Governour, who, whet-stone-like, though dull in himself, by his encouragement, set an edge on most excellent wits in that foundation. Indeed Ascham came to Cambridge just at the dawning of Learning, and staid therein till the bright-day thereof, his own endeavours contributing much light thereunto. He was Oratour and Greek Professour in the University (places of some sympathy, which have often met in the same person) ; and in the beginning of the Raign of Queen Mary, within three days, wrote letters to fourty-seven severall Princes, whereof the meanest was a Cardinal. He travailed into Germany, and there contracted familiarity with John Sturmius and other learned men ; and, 1 The quotations which follow are from Bennet's quarto edition, 1761. 2 There is a great deal of interesting information on the pre- Reformation schools in Furnivall's Education in Early England. ROGER ASCHAM, THE HUMANIST 59 after his return, was a kind of teacher to the Lady Elizabeth, to whom (after she was Queen} he became her Secretary for her Latine letters. "In a word, he was an honest man and a good shooter; Archery (whereof he wrote a Book called ' Too P- 5- " It i s virtue, direct virtue which is the hard and valuable part to be aimed at in education and not a forward pertness or any little arts of shifting. All other considerations and accomplishments should give way and be postponed to this. This is the solid and substantial good, which tutors should not only read lectures and talk of, but the labour and art of education should furnish the mind with, fasten there, and never cease, till the young man had a true relish for it and placed his strength, his glory and his pleasure in it." (Note here that Locke contrasts Domestic Education with Public Education in the English sense. The Scottish and German system would be in his view the next best ; in fact the best, if we consider that Locke's system, even if the best theoretically, is impracticable for all save a few wealthy. \Ve have only to introduce morality as a conscious end and object into our public day schools to have as perfect a system as the conditions of life admit of.) Virtue, then, by which is here meant the subjection of our inclinations to duty, is the main thing. How is this to be taught ? According to Locke almost wholly by training : not by instruc- tion. The great governing rule of Method here is, that you yourself afford in your own person an example of virtue. 7 1, p. 5 1. " Maxima debetur pueris reverentia." You must JOHN LOCKE, THE ENGLISH RATIONALIST 2OI do nothing before them which you would not have them imitate nothing which you would regard as a fault in your pupil. But virtue is a general term, and we must be watchful of our pupils so that vices as they arise may be checked and tendencies to virtue encouraged. If we would detect these incipient vices we should watch children at play when they fancy themselves unnoticed. Locke does not exhaust the various vices and virtues, nor does he follow any intelligible order in discussing them, as might have been expected from the author of the Essay on the Human Understanding. He seems very much to take them up as they occur to him, and deals with their superficial aspect only ; but in spite of this, there are few books better suited to form an elementary manual of morals and manners than the sections in Locke's treatise which deal with the various moralities, or rather immoralities. I shall take up only a few of those which Locke deals with, as a specimen of his way of looking at moral training. ( i ) Love of Power. When watching children at play we shall see that special development of selfishness which we call Love of Power. This must be curbed, because it is the root of almost all injustice and contention and if we do not restrain it we cannot lay the " foundations of a good and worthy man." To check this vice Locke proposes that "children ( 107) should never have what their inclinations lead them to ask for, unless it be the satisfaction of their actual needs. They should be trained so that they would not dare to express their desires when these were mere fancies, and the parent should as occasion served reward them for their general restraint and self-denial by indulgence." Locke here, it seems to me, advocates an unnatural and irrational system, as I have previously pointed out. If a child 202 JOHN LOCKE, THE ENGLISH RATIONALIST desires a box of sweetmeats or a cricket-ball or a pair of skates, why should he not desire them ? And if he desire them why should he not express his desire to his parents or master? Locke's system, in fact, introduces a forced and artificial relation between parents and children, out of which love and sympathy and that mutual confidence which is the source of all true moral influence over the young cannot possibly grow. If we lose this, what have we gained ? Nothing. Moreover, the suggestion is based on an inadequate moral analysis. Children are just like ourselves. \Ve desire many things which we cannot get : there is nothing wrong in desiring them, or in expressing our desires. The wrong consists in not sacrificing our desires to higher considerations. So with children : let Johnny have his box of sweetmeats by all means, if there is no higher considera- tion forbidding it. If there be; e.g. if his having them prevents his brothers or sisters having what is necessary for them ; or if it be a purely selfish desire, he intending to eat them all himself; or if it be a question between spending the money in gratifying this desire or in relieving the hunger of some poor destitute child, put these motives before him and get him himself to crucify his love of sweetmeats for the sake of these higher things. A child well brought up will do so. It is the supplying of the higher motives wherewith to suppress the lower that moral training consists in. The mere law or command of a superior is to be resorted to only if moral motives fail. And even then, not by way of defeating the child's desire, but with a view to impress him with your conviction of its unworthiness. How can you do this at all, if you refuse satisfaction on every side indiscriminately, thus substituting your ipse dixit for the true spirit of morality ? Locke is, I think, more successful in suggesting the true way of combating selfishness and love of power when he speaks of the virtues of liberality and justice. JOHN LOCKE, THE ENGLISH RATIONALIST 203 (2) Liberality. Encourage children to be kind and generous to each other, and let them see that the esteem and commendation of others always attend the exercise of generosity. (3) Justice. no, p. 90. "Great care is to be taken that children transgress not the rules of justice, and whenever they do, they should be set right, and if there be occasion for it severely re- buked." Through ignorance, children are "apt to deviate from just measures of right and wrong, and, consequently, even the least slip in this great social virtue should be taken notice of and rectified." Wonder and abhorrence should be expressed at any unjust act, and the foundations of justice laid in the practice of liberality. As they grow in years they will under- stand better what justice means, and if then or indeed at any time an act of injustice proceeds not from mistake but per- verseness, and gentle rebukes fail, " rougher remedies " must be resorted to. For example, the father or tutor may keep forcibly from them something they think their own, and so show how little advantage they are likely to gain by appropriating unjustly what is another's so long as there are people stronger than they. But the best way is when they are yet young to implant in them an ingenuous detestation of all injustice. (4) Cowardice and Fortitude. Again, in speaking of the moral fault of cowardice, and the virtue of fortitude, Locke suggests the hardening of children to blows and making light of their pains lest we soften them too much. Nay we are sometimes to subject them to pain with a view to hardening. This strikes us as unsound. There are pains enough without inventing them. And again it is unnatural, because a child should express its suffering and be sympathised with within limits, so long as the expression is not 204 JOHN LOCKE, THE ENGLISH RATIONALIST excessive. It is the excess which is wrong. If I knock my knuckles against a door I probably utter some impatient word, and I confess I think none the worse of myself for doing so. I should be ashamed, however, of myself if I gave any sign of pain even when I burnt my finger if there were sufficient reason for concealing my suffering. So with children. Let us be reasonable and not exaggerate acts which in themselves are truly of little importance, of great importance only when higher considerations enter. By just and rational treatment we shall, nay we cannot but, form the highest character. Artificial pretences are out of place. (5) Cruelty. On the subject of cruelty, Locke thinks that the tendency which many children have to inflict pain on the lower animals should be carefully watched, and in connexion with this he animadverts strongly on the manners of wealthy children towards servants. (6) Sauntering or Idleness. First make sure whether it be at his lessons only that the boy is idle. If he is active in other things there is hope of him, and by counsel or severe measures you may get him to reform. If, however, the idleness be constitutional the case is more difficult. The only remark of Locke's of any value with respect to such cases is to watch the boy and see whether he has a liking for any one thing and encourage this. For the main object is to get him to overcome the constitutional tendency, by- getting him to work at something, be it what it may beetle- collecting or carpentering, if not Latin or French. The above question naturally suggests again to Locke's mind the question of compulsion, and he finds the means of JOHN LOCKE, THE ENGLISH RATIONALIST 2O5 getting children to attend to lessons by making their play a task. Order a boy to whip his top and not to stop for a certain time, and the boy will at once get disgusted with the amusement and gladly accept his reading or writing, as a change. Whatever elder people choose to make a reward or a task can be made so. Playthings. As to playthings : let the children have very few, and invent what more they want for themselves. Nothing is more hurtful than an excessive abundance of toys. It tends to create luxurious habits and immoderate desires. (7) Lying. 131. "Lying is so ready and cheap a cover for any mis- carriage and so much in fashion among all sorts of people that a child can hardly avoid observing the use which is made of it on all occasions, and so can scarce be kept without great care from getting into it. But it is so ill a quality and the mother of so many ill ones that spawn from it and take shelter under it, that a child should be brought up in the greatest horror of it imagin- able." The first lie, he thinks, should be treated with surprise and astonishment that such a thing should be possible. The second with coldness and displeasure of all about him. If this fail, the lying may be held to be deliberate and therefore a sign of obstinacy. In accordance with his fundamental idea, beating must now be resorted to. When children commit faults they will "like the rest of the sons of Adam be apt to make excuses." This borders on untruth and they must be urged to be ingenuous. But when they confess ingenuously they must be commended for this, and not punished for the fault which they have confessed. And this condonation of the fault should be thorough ; no allusion should afterwards be made to it. If sometimes there be a few slips in truth do not be too ready to take notice of them, lest the boy should feel that he has lost his reputation with you, than which nothing can be more 206 JOHN LOCKE, THE ENGLISH RATIONALIST hurtful. When you have once detected him in a lie you must be most vigilant and severe. (8) Truth and Good Nature. Having laid the foundations of virtue in a true knowledge of God, the next thing is to keep him exactly to speaking the truth and to cultivate his "good nature." By this Locke means his benevolence, for as he truly remarks "injustice generally springs from too great love of ourselves and too little of others." (9) Wisdom. Wisdom is the managing of one's affairs ably and with foresight in this world. It has however a moral side. In its full sense it can only be learned from experience and observa- tion, but we can at least guard the young, with a view to wisdom, against that "ape of wisdom" cunning, resorted to by those who cannot gain their ends by direct ways. Accustom them in truth and sincerity to a submission to reason, and as much as may be to reflection on their actions. ( i o) Good-breeding. On the subject of good-breeding Locke has some good observations. He speaks at length and with such wisdom and knowledge of the world that I would recommend teachers to read what he says. Indeed it is to young men and women alone that his remarks can be serviceable. In the case of mere boys, I think we have only to cultivate good-nature and a moderate estimate of themselves. The rest will come from the experience of life, and above all from the society they keep : for as Locke truly says, " the tincture of company sinks deeper than the outside." The breaches of good breeding he says may be all avoided by observing this one rule, " Not to think meanly of ourselves and not to think meanly of others." JOHN LOCKE, THE ENGLISH RATIONALIST 2O/ ( 1 1 ) Religion. Religion being (136) "the foundation of all virtue, there ought very early to be imprinted on a child's mind a true notion of God as of the independent Supreme Being, Author and Maker of all things, from Whom we receive all our good, Who loves us and gives us all things " : but this without any attempt to enter into the subtler questions of Deity. Simple prayer, night and morning, should be practised. CHAPTER XIV. JOHN LOCKE continued. Knowledge or Learning, (a) Method, (d) Materials, (c) The Recreative, (d) Qualification of the Teacher. LOCKE is a utilitarian in this sense that he holds that a boy should learn what will be useful to him as a man in intercourse with his fellows and in the conduct of ordinary affairs. He is also cyclopaedic, because he advocates the learning of the elements of many things. In both these respects Locke is in accord with almost every thinker in these days. It is only a gradually decreasing number of secondary schoolmasters who differ from him. Were it not however for the argument of the treatise on the Conduct of the Understanding we should quarrel with him as to his restricted use of the term "useful." Next to moral principles and a religious habit of mind, nothing surely is so " useful " to a man as a vigorous and sound judgment. The materials and methods of instruction have to be con- sidered in view of this supreme end what Locke himself would call Wisdom. The great merit of Locke is that he denounced the rigid classicism of his time which led to instruction exclusively in the instruments of knowledge and of thought not in knowledge and thought themselves. As regards materials of instruction Locke was a Realist as opposed to the Formalists, but this does not mean that he was a JOHN LOCKE 209 naturalistic realist. At the same time, it must be admitted that he had, like Comenius, the conspicuous defect that he was unable to comprehend the education which was to be found in literary expression and was not alive to the intellectual dis- cipline which grammatical studies yield. (a) Method. As regards method in instructing, Locke makes many pertinent remarks, but it had never occurred to him, though a philosopher, that method had a scientific basis in psychology. He dealt with the whole subject in a somewhat light, but by no means perfunctory, spirit. He considers that good methods may be easily found, and that as children natur- ally love knowledge, the task of instruction should not be so very difficult. " Knowledge," he says, "is grateful to the under- standing as light to the eyes." Outside the three "R's" his remarks are rather directed to what ought to be the matter of instruction than to the how of method, although his pages are full of admirable suggestions. Knowledge may be had "at a very easy rate by good methods," but he does not suggest anything save what are rightly to be called wise expedients rather than methods strictly so called. The most valuable of his remarks to be found in the Thoughts on the subject of method in general are these: (167) "Children's minds are narrow and weak and usually susceptible but of one thought at once. Whatever is in a child's head fills it for the time, especially if set on with any passion. It should, therefore, be the skill and art of the teacher to clear their heads of all other thoughts while they are learning of anything, the better to make room for what he would instil into them, that it may be received with attention and appli- cation, without which it leaves no impression. The natural temper of children disposes their minds to wander. Novelty alone takes them ; whatever that presents they are presently eager to have a taste of and are as soon satisfied with it. They quickly grow weary of the same thing, and so have L. 14 210 JOHN LOCKE almost their whole delight in change and variety. It is a contradiction to the natural state of childhood for them to fix their fleeting thoughts." Again he says that the success of instruction depends on the activity of the pupil's mind relatively to the instruction given and to its attractiveness. In this Locke is right. But he is wrong, I think, when he says that everything must be made pleasant and attractive. The object of education in so far as it is discipline is, as I have already pointed out, to induce a child to put pressure on himself and to initiate intellectual effort under a sense of duty. This is one of the "hardships of the mind" which every young person has to endure and overcome. It is moral as well as intellectual in its effect. In some of his utterances Locke seems to recognize this fact himself, but he certainly does not take firm hold of it. The sum of the matter is that the instruction should always be as pleasant and attractive as it can possibly be made, and for this we rely on Method. (b} Materials, As regards the matter of knowledge Locke lets us clearly understand that this is quite secondary. Virtue, wisdom, and breeding, these are the chief ends of education. Other things he only "allows to be necessary." We must however give an account, however brief, of this portion of Locke's treatise. Reading. The letters of the alphabet (Locke thinks) may be learned as an amusement. Let them be pasted on a many sided bale or on four dice, and let children amuse themselves by casting these and seeing what letter is thrown. Then when the letters are known let the same process be followed, the players seeing after every throw who has thrown most words. Thus much for learning to read. Cheat your pupil into it if you can. In this way he will soon be able to read some " easy pleasant book," Aesop's fables being the best, and if it has pictures in it so much the better. Reynard the Fox he also recommends. Learning by heart and learning to read should JOHN LOCKE 211 not be made to " clog one another," as it is essential that the reading should always be associated with pleasure. The Creed and Ten Commandments and Lord's Prayer for example should not be learned by heart from a book, but by the oral repetition of others. Locke complains of the want of pleasant and suitable reading for children. He objects to the promis- cuous reading of the Bible, for obvious reasons. Writing. This is to be begun only when the pupil can read English well, and first he should be taught to hold his pen right, and this before he is suffered to put it to paper. Then the proper placing of the paper and of his body is to be attended to. He should then trace over with black ink, letters lithographed in red ink. Then he may write without tracing. He recommends also shorthand. Drawing. This is recommended as a part of the education of a young gentleman : but solely because of its future utility. French and Latin. As soon as he can speak English it is time for him to learn some other language. This is to be talked into him, and begun early, that the organs of speech may be adapted to the French pronunciation. A year or two will enable a boy to speak French. Latin. When he can speak and read French well he should proceed to Latin. This should be learned in the same way, by talking and reading. "Latin I look upon as absolutely necessary to a gentleman." But can there be anything more absurd than forcing boys to learn Latin who will never need it afterwards, entering perhaps some trade? But custom is so strong that even tradesmen think that their children have not an orthodox education unless they learn Lilly's Grammar. The ordinary way of learning Latin is bad. The true way is by talking it into him, and thus he will learn easily what is usually whipped into boys over a period of 6 or 7 years. "Our knowledge [even of foreign tongues] should all begin in the things of sense and not in the abstractions of Logic and Metaphysics." 166, p. 140. 142 212 JOHN LOCKE If a man cannot be got who can teach your son in the way suggested, the next best thing is to give him some easy book with an interlinear word for word translation taking care that he makes himself perfect in one lesson before he goes to another. But as a preliminary it will be necessary that he first get the accidence by heart. More than this of grammar he need not have until he can himself read "Sanctii Minerva'." If a boy encounters difficulties in reading Latin do not trouble him to find them out, but tell him and help him on. Everything is to be made as easy and pleasant as possible. " Languages are to be learned by rote, custom, and memory." The grammar of a language he admits is to be studied critically, but only by professed scholars. In further considering the method of teaching Latin, he says that after some facility has been attained by reading the interlinear book, he may then be advanced to Justin or Eutropius, helping himself with an English translation. If this involves rote work what then? All languages are really learned by rote and are only well known when the words to express thought come readily without thought and without the conscious application of grammatical rules. Grammar is not on this account to be said to be of no use, but children in grammar schools should not be perplexed with it. People acquire great correctness and elegance in speaking a language who know nothing about its grammar. Conversation is that whereby people acquire languages. If grammar is to be studied with a view to greater correctness of speech it ought to be the grammar of our own tongue. At present one would think that all our youths were being trained to be teachers of the dead languages. Grammar, then, should be taught to those who desire to write or speak with elegance and to scholars, but only after they can speak and write the tongue whose grammar they study. [Note however that the accidence is to be got by 1 A treatise on Latin Grammar rather than a Latin Grammar (now forgotten). JOHN LOCKE 213 heart.] Its proper place in truth is as an introduction to rhetoric. The speaking and reading are all that is necessary to those who merely want a gentleman's acquaintance with a tongue: the critical knowledge is for those who have to write it with exactness. In any case there is no doubt in Locke's mind that those are tormented about grammar to whom it does not at all belong, " I mean children at the age wherein they are generally perplexed with it in grammar schools." 168, pp. 145, 146. He can scarcely find words strong enough to express his contempt for Latin in those schools that prepare for ordinary middle-class life. Latin is necessary to a "gentleman"; at least it was so in Locke's time, but the argument of utility, in the vulgar sense of that word, breaks down when we consider its employment as an instrument of education in the schools of the bourgeoisie. Let the scholar translate Latin into English, but as the mere learning of words is a very unpleasant business let him "join as much real knowledge with it as he can," beginning still with that which lies most obvious to the senses, such as is the knowledge of minerals, plants, and animals, and particularly timber and fruit trees * * " more especially geography, astronomy, and anatomy." ( 169.) [Here we see the influence of Milton.] But whatever he is taught let virtue be the chief end. Spite of all that has been said, a boy if he has to go to school must submit to the usual routine, but by all means try to get him exempt from writing Latin themes and, above all, verses. As to themes, Locke considers it an Egyptian tyranny to ask boys to write themes when they have not, by reason of their age and ignorance, the materials. He suggests their being induced to speak to a subject which they know something about without preparation. As to verses the school practice is absurd and indefensible. Locke had an aversion to poetry. He says that if a boy 214 JOHN LOCKE shows a poetic vein it should be stifled and suppressed, if he is not to grow up to a dislike of all other "callings and businesses " and to be led into frivolous company. Poetry and gaming go together. And even if any one desires to cultivate the poetic vein he will do it best by reading the poets certainly not by writing Latin verses. Locke further objects to learning parts of classical authors by heart as tending to make a pedant, and yet he commends the learning of beautiful passages, if selected for this reason, that they are beautiful. As to exercising the memory, that is not improved by learning by heart. The learning one class of things by heart does not improve the memory for others. "What the mind is intent upon and careful of that it re- members best" ( 176); and if we add to this order and method we have done all that can be done. Yet Locke does not mean that there should be no exercise of memory. Useful things and fine sayings might well be learned by heart and frequently called for that they may not be forgotten. Greek. When a youth is grown up he may acquire the Greek tongue for himself if he desire it, without the aid of a tutor. Greek is for a professed student and is not necessary to the equipment of a gentleman. Geography. While a child is learning French and Latin he should learn things through these arithmetic, geometry, geography, chronology and history. Geography should be begun with the globe ; as the leading outlines being dependent entirely on the eye will be learned readily. Arithmetic. When he has the natural parts of the globe in his memory it may then be time to begin arithmetic, which is the easiest and first sort of abstract reasoning that the mind is accustomed to and of universal application. A man cannot have too much of it. Along with this, the globe should again be studied, advancing from the terrestrial to the celestial globe. Then JOHN LOCKE 215 the planetary system should be taught to him; but always begin with what is plain and simple, and settle that well in the pupils' heads before proceeding further. " Give first one simple idea and see that they take it right and perfectly comprehend it, before you go further, and then add some other simple idea which lies next in your way to what you aim at, and so proceeding by gentle and insensible steps children, without confusion and amazement, will have their under- standings opened and their thoughts extended farther than could have been expected." ( 181.)' Geometry. The six books of Euclid should be learned in the ordinary school course : but it is in the essay on the Conduct of the Human Understanding, not here, that we find Locke's estimate of mathematics in education. He there says (Fowler's edition, section vn. p. 23) : " I have mentioned mathematics as a way to settle in the mind a habit of reasoning closely and in train ; not that I think it necessary that all men should be deep mathematicians, but that, having got the way of reasoning, which that study necessarily brings the mind to, they might be able to transfer it to other parts of knowledge, as they shall have occasion. For, in all sorts of reasoning every single argument should be managed as a mathematical demonstration; the connexion and dependence of ideas should be followed till the mind is brought to the source on which it bottoms, and observes the coherence all along; though in proofs of probability one such train is not enough to settle the judgment, as in demonstrative knowledge." Chronology. A boy should have a general knowledge of the great dates and epochs as preparatory, along with geography, to the proper understanding of history. History. This delights the young, and they should read history in Latin, e.g. Eutropius, Justin and Curtius, and thus prepare themselves for the more difficult authors. They need not be troubled as to the period at which they begin, because 1 The teaching of Locke's philosophy is to be seen in this. 2l6 JOHN LOCKE their chronology will keep them right. As boys grow up, history is an important subject as "the great mistress of prudence and civil knowledge." Ethics. This having been all along taught by practice rather than by rule, nothing more is needed than what the Bible, and, later, Tully's offices afford. Yet it is worthy of notice here that while Locke relies mainly on the formation of moral habits, he yet considers that the study of morality as maxims and precepts in other words, instruction in the substance of morality should enter into school-work. Civil Law. This should be studied in Puffendorf and Grotius. There he will be instructed in the natural rights of men and in the foundations of Civil Society. A virtuous young man who knows Latin and the Civil Law and writes a good hand, may be turned out into the world with the certainty that he will " find employment and esteem everywhere." Civil law and history are in Locke's opinion " studies which a gentleman should constantly dwell upon and never have done with." Law (Municipal}. A gentleman should not be ignorant of the law of his own country by studying the ancient books of the Common Law, and " taking a view of our English constitu- tion and Government." Then in connexion with this he should read the history of his own country. Rhetoric and Logic. These are not to be learned from books of rhetoric and logic, but from the study of good models and by practice. Style. As to style, youth should be trained to write, being practised first in narrative and then in epistolary composition. A gentleman should labour to get facility, clearness, and elegance, in expressing himself in his own tongue; and "to this purpose he should be daily exercised in it." Locke is bitterly satirical on the neglect of English composition in schools. " To mind what English his pupil speaks or writes is below the dignity of one bred up amongst Latin and Greek." JOHN LOCKE 217 Natural Philosophy. Locke thinks that the works of nature " are contrived by a wisdom and speak by ways too far surpassing our faculties to discover or capacities to conceive, for us ever to be able to reduce them into a science ! " There are two parts of Natural Science that which has to do with Spirit and that which has to do with Body. The study of Spirit or Spirits ought to precede that of Body, not as a science but as an enlargement of mind " towards a fuller com- prehension of the intellectual world to which we are led both by Reason and Revelation" ( 190). He thinks the best way of doing this would be the perusal of Bible history, in a book written for the young. This is all the more necessary " because matter being a thing that all our senses are constantly conversant with, it is so apt to possess the mind and exclude all other beings but matter, that prejudice grounded on such principles often leaves no room for the admittance of spirits or the allowing any such thing as immaterial beings in rerutn natura ; when yet it is evident that by mere matter and motion none of the great phenomena of nature can be resolved : to instance but that common one of gravity, which I think impossible to be explained by any natural operation of matter or any other law of motion but the positive will of a superior Being so ordering it." ( 192.)' The world, he says, is full of systems of Natural Philosophy, but as there is no true or certain science I conclude that none of them are to be read, though a gentleman may look into some of them to fit himself for conversation. Yet Locke adds laudation of the "incom- parable Mr Newton's " application of Mathematics to Natural Philosophy. Locke evidently means that too much occupation with the things of sense has a tendency to extrude moral and spiritual ideas from the mind of youth. This is much better put in 1 Locke tries to explain the Noachian Deluge by the alteration of the centre of the earth's gravity by the will of God. 218 JOHN LOCKE the Conduct of the Human Understanding (Fowler's edition, section ix.), where he says, "Outward corporeal objects, that constantly importune our senses and captivate our appetites, fail not to fill our heads with lively and lasting ideas of that kind. Here the mind needs not to be set upon getting greater store; they offer themselves fast enough, and are usually entertained in such plenty, and lodged so carefully, that the mind wants room or attention for others that it has more use and need of. To fit the understanding therefore for such reasoning as I have been above speaking of, care should be taken to fill it with moral and more abstract ideas ; for these not offering themselves to the senses, but being to be framed to the understanding, people are generally so neglectful of a faculty they are apt to think wants nothing, that I fear most men's minds are more unfurnished with such ideas than is imagined. They often use the words, and how can they be suspected to want the ideas?" We may fitly conclude Locke's views of the subjects and methods of instruction with his own words, "The tutor should remember that his business is not so much to teach his pupil all that is knowable as to raise in him a love and esteem of knowledge, and to put him in a right way of knowing and improving himself when he has a mind to it." 195, p. 171. (c) The Recreative. When we reflect that Locke was a physician and recall his remarks about the importance of having a body which would be a willing servant of the mind, his almost total omission of all that comes under the head of Gymnastic is strange. In Gymnastic in the form of games, apart from its influence on the body, there is also a species of moral training of great value which ought to have commended the subject to him. Nay in public schools it is often the chief moral training which those boys receive who are inapt to learn. When Locke speaks of bodily exercises he has in view only those exercises which make an accomplished gentleman JOHN LOCKE 219 and contribute to an easy bearing in society and to the en- joyment of life. Dancing for example is to be taught because it gives an easy and graceful motion to the body and " manliness." Music Locke sets little store by, but admits it as a recreation, since we cannot be always at work. Riding the " great horse " he commends as necessary to gentlemen, but fencing he discourages as leading to quarrels and duelling. As to recreations in addition to the usual exercises of the body, Locke recommends gardening, husbandry, and working in wood. Recreation "is not being idle but easing the wearied part by change of business." Again, he says, " nothing is recreation which is not done with delight." All sorts of manual occupations might be taken to, e.g. varnishing, graving, cutting precious stones, etc., etc. (d) The Qualifications oj a Teacher, and his personal re- lation to his Pupil. ( 94.) " The great work of a governor is to fashion the carriage and form the mind, to settle in his pupil good habits and the principles of virtue and wisdom ; to give him by little and little a view of mankind, and work him into a love and imitation of what is excellent and praiseworthy; and in the prosecution of it to give him vigour, activity, and industry. The studies which he sets him upon are but as it were the exercises of his faculties and employment of his time, to keep him from sauntering and idleness, to teach him application and accustom him to take pains, and to give him some little taste of what his own industry must perfect. For who expects that under a tutor a young gentleman should be an accomplished critic, orator, or logician ; go to the bottom of metaphysics, natural philosophy or mathematics, or be a master in history or chronology ? though something of each of these is to be taught him ; but it is only to open the door, that he may look in, and as it were begin an acquaintance, but not to dwell there ; 220 JOHN LOCKE and a governor would be much blamed that should keep his pupil too long and lead him too far in most of them. But of good breeding, knowledge of the world, virtue, industry and a love of reputation he cannot have too much ; and if he have these he will not long want what he needs or desires of the other. And since it cannot be hoped he should have time and strength to learn all things, most pains should be taken about that which is most necessary, and that principally looked after which will be of most and frequentest use to him in the world." In teaching, he says, try to dispose the mind of your pupil to his work, but remember the instability of children's minds and be easy with them. To rate and chide and punish is to instil a hatred of the lesson hour, and moreover it confuses the child's mind, so that he does not know what he is doing or what you are saying to him. ( 167.) "It is as impossible to draw fair and regular characters on a trembling mind as on a shaking paper. The great skill of a teacher is to get and keep the attention of his scholar; whilst he has that he is sure to advance as fast as the learner's abilities will carry him ; and without that, all his bustle and pother will be to little or no purpose. To attain this he should make the child comprehend (as much as may be) the usefulness of what he teaches him and let him see by what he has learnt that he can do something which he could not before. To this he should add sweetness in all his instructions and by a certain tender- ness in his whole carriage make the child sensible that he loves him and designs nothing but his good, the only way to beget love in the child which will make him hearken to his lessons and relish what he teaches him. Nothing but obstinacy should meet with any imperiousness or rough usage. All other faults should be corrected with a gentle hand, and kind engaging words will work better and more effectually upon a willing mind, and even prevent a good deal of that perverseness which rough and imperious usage often produces in well-disposed and generous minds. It is true, JOHN LOCKE 221 obstinacy and wilful neglect must be mastered even if it cost blows to do it : but I am apt to think perverseness in the pupils is often the effect of frowardness in the tutor ; and that most children would seldom have deserved blows, if needless and misapplied roughness had not taught them ill nature and given them an aversion for their teacher and all that comes from him. Inadvertency, forgetfulness, unsteadiness and wandering of thought are the natural faults of childhood, and, therefore, when they are not observed to be wilful, are to be mentioned softly and gained upon by time." He concludes his treatise by stating that he has made no pretension to write a full and "just" tractate, but only to record some general views " regarding the main end and aims of education, and these designed for a gentleman's son," and he commends them to those who " dare venture to consult their own reason in the education of their children rather than rely wholly upon old custom." CHAPTER XV. JOHN LOCKE concluded. Conduct of the Understanding. Method and Intellectual Discipline : Words : Judgments : Reasonings. LOCKE'S method in the department of instruction is not so much a method in any philosophic acceptation of the term as a collection of empirical rules and hints as to the easiest way of disposing of the difficulty of getting the work of mere learning well over. One might rightly conclude that Locke had never fairly faced the question of the discipline of intelligence as opposed to mere instruction, were it not for the Conduct of the Understanding the last of his writings. In this book the training and discipline of the intelligence is the theme, and while treating of this, many sound rules of general method are given and vividly illustrated. This essay, as Hallam truly says, is a " treatise on the moral discipline of the intellect." I shall first give a few extracts bearing on method generally and then on discipline of the intellect. JOHN LOCKE 223 (i) Method generally Step by Step Little by Little- Predisposing the mind of the Pupil Labour. i. The analytic method. ( xxxix.) 1 "Things that in a remote and confused view seem very obscure must be approached by gentle and regular steps ; and what is most visible, easy, and obvious in them, first considered. Reduce them into their distinct parts ; and then in their due order bring all that should be known concerning every one of these parts into plain and simple questions ; and then what was thought obscure, perplexed and too hard for our weak parts, will lay itself open to the understanding in a fair view, and let the mind into that which before it was awed with, and kept at a distance from as wholly mysterious." 2. Step by step: graduation of studies. ( xxxix.) "The surest way for a learner in this, as in all other cases, is not to advance by jumps and large strides ; let that which he sets himself to learn next be indeed the next ; i.e. as nearly conjoined with what he knows already as is possible ; let it be distinct but not remote from it : let it be new, and what he did not know before, that the understanding may advance ; but let it be as little at once as may be, that its advances may be clear and sure. All the ground that it gets this way it will hold. This distinct, gradual growth in knowledge is firm and sure ; it carries its own light with it in every step of its progression in an easy and orderly train ; than which there is nothing of more use to the understanding. And though this perhaps may seem a very slow and lingering way to knowledge, yet I dare confidently affirm that whoever will try it in himself or any one he will teach, shall find the advances greater in this method than they would in the same space of time have been in any other he could have taken." 1 Fowler's edition. 224 JOHN LOCKE 3. Little by little. The new out of the old. ( xxxix.) " I therefore take the liberty to repeat here again what I have said elsewhere, that in learning anything, as little should be proposed to the mind at once as is possible ; and, that being understood and fully mastered, to proceed to the next adjoining part yet unknown, simple, unperplexed proposition belonging to the matter in hand, and tending to the clearing what is principally designed." 4. Predisposing the mind of the Pupil and co-operation of the Teacher. ( xxx.) " He that will observe children will find that even when they endeavour their utmost, they cannot keep their minds from straggling. The way to cure it I am satisfied is not angry chiding or beating, for that presently fills their heads with all the ideas that fear, dread, or confusion can offer to them. To bring back gently their wandering thoughts by leading them into the path and going before them in the train they should pursue without any rebuke or so much as taking notice (where it can be avoided) of their roving, would I suppose sooner reconcile and inure them to attention than all those rougher methods, which more distract their thought and, hindering the application they would promote, introduce a contrary habit." 5. Labour necessary. ( xxxvni.) In his Thoughts Locke would have everything, as we found, made easy for the young learner, but in the Conduct of the Understanding he says, " We are born ignorant of everything. The superficies of things that surround them make impressions on the negligent, but nobody penetrates into the inside without labour, attention, and industry. Stones and timber grow of themselves, but yet there is no uniform pile with symmetry and convenience to JOHN LOCKE 225 lodge in, without toil and pains. God has made the intellectual world harmonious and beautiful without us ; but it will never come into our heads all at once ; we must bring it home piece- meal, and there set it up by our own industry, or else we shall have nothing but darkness and a chaos within, whatever order and light there be in things without us." (2) Discipline of the Intellect. I do not suppose anyone would be disposed to quarrel with the substance of Locke's views on moral training and discipline, nor yet in these days at least with his advocacy of a wide range of study, for boys, so long as the range was not so wide as to dissipate all the powers and train none. But I imagine all men who have thought about educational principles and aims must concur in feeling that instruction given on Locke's plan as contained in the Thoughts, would fail to give discipline or power to the intelligence. This would not be a matter to grieve over were it not that we cannot separate the intellectual and moral nature, and that the discipline of the intellect is a discipline of the will, and indirectly a training to virtue. In the Conduct of the Human Understanding, however, we find the necessary supplement to the Thoughts on this point as on others, for it is in fact a treatise on mental Discipline : and it is to this valuable essay that we must go, if we wish to know what Locke's idea was of the proper aim of education as regards the intellect. He there shows what a sound intellect and habit of mind are and what an unsound. His characteristics of the former constitute his educational ideal as regards intellect, his remarks on the latter point out what we have to guard against and correct both in ourselves and in those we educate. L. I 5 226 JOHN LOCKE Words and Judgments. Discipline is to be obtained by the analysis of words as the vehicles of things, the analysis and reconstruction in our own minds of the reasonings which we encounter in literature and by the exercise of our own reason. On these points let us see what Locke says. Analysis of Words. ( xv.) " The sure and only way to get true knowledge is to form in our minds clear settled notions of things, with names annexed to those determined ideas. These we are to consider and with their several relations and habitudes, and not amuse ourselves with floating names, and words of indetermined signi- fication, which we can use in several senses to serve a turn." Again he says (Fowler's edition, xxix.): " I have copiously enough spoken of the abuse of words in another place 1 , and therefore shall upon this reflection that the sciences are full of them, warn those that would conduct their understandings right, not to take any term howsoever authorised by the language of the schools, to stand for anything till they have an idea of it. A word may be of frequent use, and great credit, with several authors, and be by them made use of as if it stood for some real being; but yet, if he that reads cannot frame any distinct idea of that being, it is certainly to him a mere empty sound without a meaning ; and he learns no more by all that is said of it, or attributed to it, than if it were affirmed only of that bare empty sound. They who would advance in knowledge and not deceive and swell themselves with a little articulated air, should lay down this as a funda- mental rule not to take words for things, nor suppose that names in books signify real entities in nature till they can frame clear and distinct ideas of those entities." 1 In the Essay on the Human Understanding. JOHN LOCKE 227 Elsewhere : " Words are not made to conceal, but to declare and show something. Where they are by those who pretend to instruct, otherwise used, they conceal indeed something ; but that they conceal is nothing but the ignorance, error or sophistry of the talker ; for there is in truth nothing else under them." Analysis of the substance of Reading. When he speaks of Reading and the uselessness of it without analysis and thought, he has some remarks which notwithstanding their length I may here quote with advantage to all who read. xx. "This is that which I think great readers are apt to be mistaken in. Those who have read of everything, are thought to understand everything too ; but it is not always so. Reading furnishes the mind only with materials of knowledge; it is thinking makes what we read ours. We are of the ruminating kind, and it is not enough to cram ourselves with a great load of collections ; unless we chew them over again they will not give us strength and nourishment. There are indeed in some writers visible instances of deep thoughts, close and acute reasoning and ideas well pursued. The light these would give would be of great use, if their reader would observe and imitate them ; all the rest at best are but particulars fit to be turned into knowledge ; but that can be done only by our own meditation, and examining the reach, force, and coherence of what is said ; and then, as far as we apprehend and see the con- nexion of ideas, so far it is ours ; without that, it is but so much loose matter floating in our brain. The memory may be stored, but the judgment is little better, and the stock of knowledge not increased, by being able to repeat what others have said, or produce the arguments we have found in them. Such a knowledge as this is but knowledge by hearsay, and the ostentation of it is at best but talking by rote, and very often upon weak and wrong principles. For all that is to be 152 228 JOHN LOCKE found in books is not built upon true foundations, nor always rightly deduced from the principles it is pretended to be built on. Such an examen as is requisite to discover that, every reader's mind is not forward to make ; especially in those who have given themselves up to a party, and only hunt for what they can scrape together, that may favour and support the tenets of it. Such men wilfully exclude themselves from truth and from all true benefit to be derived by reading. Others of more indifferency often want attention and industry. The mind is backward in itself to be at the pains to trace every argument to its original, and to see upon what basis it stands and how firmly; but yet it is this that gives so much the advantage to one man more than another in reading. The mind should by severe rules be tied down to this, at first, uneasy task; use and exercise will give it facility. So that those who are accustomed to it, readily, as it were with one cast of the eye take a view of the argument and presently, in most cases, see where it bottoms. Those who have got this faculty, one may say, have got the true key of books and the clue to lead them through the mizmaze of variety of opinions and authors to truth and certainty. This young readers should be entered in, and showed the use of, that they might profit by their reading. Those who are strangers to it will be apt to think it too great a clog in the way of men's studies, and they will suspect they shall make but small progress, if, in the books they read, they must stand to examine and unravel every argument, and follow it step by step up to its original. " I answer, this is a good objection, and ought to weigh with those whose reading is designed for much talk and little knowledge, and I have nothing to say to it. But I am here inquiring into the conduct of the understanding in its progress towards knowledge ; and to those who aim at that, I may say, that he who fair and softly goes steadily forward in a course that points right, will sooner be at his journey's end than he JOHN LOCKE 229 that runs after every one he meets, though he gallop all day full speed. " To which let me add, that this way of thinking on, and profiting by what we read, will be a clog and rub to any one only in the beginning : when custom and exercise have made it familiar, it will be despatched on most occasions without resting or interruption in the course of our reading. The motions and views of a mind exercised that way are wonder- fully quick ; and a man used to such sort of reflections sees as much at one glimpse as would require a long discourse to lay before another, and make out in an entire and gradual deduction. Besides, that, when the first difficulties are over, the delight and sensible advantage it brings mightily en- courages and enlivens the mind in reading, which without this is very improperly called study.'' Reasoning and Principles. Then when he speaks of the necessity of reasoning, and resting our convictions on principles, he points out how generally men fail to use their reason. vi. " Few men (he says) are from their youth (observe from their yout/i) accustomed to strict reasoning, and to trace the dependence of any truth, in a long train of consequences, to its remotest principles and to observe its connexion ; and he that by frequent practice has not been used to this employ- ment of his understanding, it is no more wonder that he should not, when he is grown into years, be able to bring his mind to it, than that he should not be, on a sudden, able to grave or design, dance on the ropes, or write a good hand, who has never practised either of them. " Nay, the most of men are so wholly strangers to this, that they do not so much as perceive their want of it ; they despatch the ordinary business of their callings by rote, as we say, as they have learnt it ; and if at any time they miss success they impute it to anything rather than want of thought or skill." 230 JOHN LOCKE Again ( XLIV.) : " To accustom ourselves in any question proposed, to examine and find out upon what it bottoms. Most of the difficulties that come in our way, when well considered and traced, lead us to some proposition, which, known to be true, clears the doubt and gives an easy solution of the question : whilst topical and superficial arguments, of which there is store to be found on both sides, filling the head with variety of thoughts and the mouth with copious discourse, serve only to amuse the understanding, and entertain company, without coming to the bottom of the question, the only place of rest and stability for an inquisitive mind, whose tendency is only to truth and knowledge." Here then in these quotations we have laid down with sufficient clearness and vigour of language, wherein intellectual virtue consists in almost all the operations of the understand- ing. We now know what is the educational aim as regards intelligence. Is this intellectual excellence, the issue of which is truth and wisdom, to be acquired by simply wishing for it ? Certainly not. It is a habit of mind to which we have to be trained or to train ourselves, and is to be attained only (save in the case of genius) by a slow and laborious process of discipline. " What then," Locke says, " should be done in the case ? " ( vi.) " I answer, we should always remember what I said above that the faculties of our souls are improved and made useful to us just after the same manner as our bodies are. Would you have a man write or paint, dance or fence well, or perform any other manual operation dexterously and with ease; let him have ever so much vigour and activity, suppleness and address naturally, yet nobody expects this from him unless he has been used to it, and has employed time and pains in fashion- ing and forming his hand, or outward parts, to these motions. Just so it is in the mind, would you have a man reason well, you must use him to it betimes, exercise his mind in observing JOHN LOCKE 231 the connexion of ideas, and following them in train. Nothing does this better than Mathematics, which therefore I think should be taught all those who have the time and opportunity, not so much to make them mathematicians as to make them reasonable creatures; for though we all call ourselves so, because we are born to it if we please, yet we may truly say, nature gives us but the seeds of it: we are born to be, if we please, rational creatures ; but it is use and exercise only that make us so : and we are indeed so, no farther than industry and application have carried us. And, therefore, in ways of reason- ing, which men have not been used to, he that will observe the conclusions they take up must be satisfied they are not all rational." Elsewhere he says ( vi.), " What then can grown men never be improved or enlarged in their understandings? I say not so; but this I think I may say, that it will not be done without industry and appli- cation, which will require more time and pains than grown men settled in their course of life will allow to it, and there- fore very seldom is done. And this very capacity of attaining it by use and exercise only brings us back to that which I laid down before, that it is only practice that improves our minds as well as bodies, and we must expect nothing from our understandings any farther than they are perfected by habits." Conclusion, Locke has been called a Realist and Cyclopaedist, and perhaps if we are to classify him he would fall under these designations as compared with other men of his time were we to consider the Thoughts alone ; but the Conduct of the Under- standing throws fresh light on his position. As to Encyclopaedism he himself says : " Others that they may seem universally knowing, get a little smattering in every- 232 JOHN LOCKE thing. These may fill their heads with superficial notions of things, but are very much out of the way of attaining truth or knowledge." xvm. The general object of all instruction he puts before us in the following words (xix.): "The business of education is not to make the young perfect in any one of the sciences, but so to open and dispose their minds as may best make them capable of any, when they shall apply themselves to it. * * It is therefore to give them this freedom that I think they should be made to look into all sorts of knowledge and exercise their understanding in so wide a variety or stock of knowledge. But I do not propose it as a variety and stock of knowledge but a variety and freedom of thinking ; as an increase of the powers and activities of the mind, not as an enlargement of its possessions." It is now, I should say, sufficiently clear that if we wish fully to understand Locke's educational views we must read his Thoughts and his Conduct of the Understanding together. And if we do so we find on his own showing, not that Virtue in the moral sense and good manners and general information constitute the sole educational aim, but also Virtue of the Intellect. We also find on his own showing that this latter virtue is truly a training to accurate knowledge of things and words and the putting of a man in possession of his own Reason. We further find that an intellectual result so high is to be attained only by labour, by exercise, by discipline. Let us then read his educational system back from this its admitted aim, and we find it in complete discord with the prevalent tone of the section of the Thoughts which has to do with intelligence and instruction. It is in childhood and boyhood that we can alone sow the seeds of a good habit of Intelligence as well as of a good habit of Will according to Locke himself. The intelligence then has to be trained and disciplined as well as the moral nature. The materials of that training we may take from Locke's Thoughts, if we please, JOHN LOCKE 233 but the mode of procedure suggested by him is always vitiated by the exclusion of toil and the overcoming of difficulty. His method is in the Essay essentially subverted by himself. It seems accordingly to be a necessary consequence of Locke's position that through Language and Literature (not therefore excluding other instruments) we can best give that very dis- cipline which Locke finds to be necessary to the full growth of Reason. In respect then of Intellectual as well as Moral aims Locke, properly interpreted, is more of a Humanist than a Realist an unimaginative Humanist but yet a Humanist, though not of course in the narrow, classical sense. In respect of the matter of instruction he wisely includes much that did not till recently enter into the curriculum of schools, but he specially guards against too exclusive an occupation of the mind with sense-knowledge in a passage which I have quoted and which is repeated in the Conduct of the Understanding in another and a better form, a repetition which shows the importance he attached to this point. It may seem from the Thoughts that he at least verges on superficial encyclo- paedism, a characteristic generally of the Sense-realists ; but he even guards against this in a passage also cited above. He desires that boys in reading their own tongue or learning a foreign one read about things ; in other words acquire know- ledge as well as words, or rather, with words; and he also desires that many subjects should be taught which in his time were (and still are) neglected, but this does not con- stitute him a Realist in the naturalistic sense. He merely as a philosopher saw that young people must be occupied first and chiefly with the concrete. In this he agrees with Comenius and Milton, and every other competent writer. Encyclopaedism, let me add, in the vulgar sense of the word is a great error in the education of the adolescent, but during the sense and acquisitive period it is to be commended in order that we may attain our ultimate aim, which is that men 234 JOHN LOCKE should have a rational attitude to all knowledge, and be open to the influences and experiences and questions of life from day to day. Encyclopaedism, not of acquired knowledge, but of faculty and interest that is what we aim at. In respect then both of Aim, Method, and Matter of Edu- cation I claim Locke as essentially a Humanist, who had gone astray on the subject of language and discipline in his Thoughts, while he corrected himself in his Conduct of the Understanding. Had he deliberately connected the latter work with the former he would have seen the true significance, and indeed the necessity, of language-discipline in the school. By what other road indeed save Language and Mathematics is it possible for a man to reach that Ideal of Reason which he sketches in the more advanced book, the statement of his latest thoughts and not published till after his death ? Locke's supreme defect, which detracts from his Humanistic claims, was his inability to see the educative effect of literature as such, and his entire ignorance of the relation of the aesthetic emotions to the moral and religious education of youth. I have dwelt longer on Locke than on any other educational writer because I consider him the greatest of them all, in spite of his attitude to Language and Literature, and his encyclopaedism. After all, the encyclopaedism is justifiable from his point of view ; for he was considering the all-round education of a " young gentleman " only ; nor did he for a moment contemplate that all the subjects he recommends should be taught in schools. As to the middle and artizan classes, he belonged to his own epoch and considered that a knowledge of the Bible and of their own trades would suffice. Notwithstanding his debt to Rabelais, and still more to Mon- taigne, his educational conceptions are in the truest sense his own 1 . 1 His Essay on Study (collected from his Journal) should be read as an appendix to the Conduct of the Understanding. It is printed by Quick at the end of his edition of the Thoughts. CHAPTER XVI. HERBERT SPENCER, THE MODERN SENSE-REALIST. I HAD not intended in this volume to speak of the educa- tional system of any contemporary, but on reflection it seemed to me that an exception should be made in the case of Mr Herbert Spencer, whose little volume has had so wide a circulation. And this because I consider him to be the most eminent and most logical representative of the Naturalistic School of Philosophy, sometimes called Sensationalist, Utili- tarian and Phenomenalist 1 . It is most instructive I think to have before us an illustration of the fact that the philosophy of a man must determine his educational theory and his advice to the world as to educational practice. It is in the bearing of a philosophical theory on Moral Education the ethical ideal which we propose to ourselves in educating that we see the true significance of the philosophy we profess or affect, and it is this to which I would chiefly refer in the subsequent remarks. But first, in justice to Mr Spencer, I must say something on his educational aim. It is " Complete Living." No one can take exception to the phrase so far as it goes, but when we look to its definition by Mr Spencer himself, we find that it 1 Not that any of these terms accurately describes Mr Spencer's philo- sophical position. 236 HERBERT SPENCER, practically means the adaptation of man to his environment environment of nature and of other men with whom he is associated in a political society "in what way to treat the body ; in what way to treat the mind ; in what way to bring up a family ; in what way to behave as a citizen ; in what way to utilize those sources of happiness which nature supplies ; how to use all our faculties to the greatest advantage of ourselves and others." If we learn to do all this we have attained to " Complete Living." But inasmuch as we cannot exhaust a complete preparation, we must lay chief stress on the most important subjects. The subject of primary importance is the preservation of health and life. Therefore teach physiology, that is to say, in the sense of Hygiene. Next comes preparation for making a living, and as all industrial activities rest ultimately on science, the subject next in importance to physiology is Science in general and in particular. After this will naturally come instruction in the rearing of offspring. This also depends on Science. Then also the moral discipline of offspring can be illuminated only by mental science. Next come the functions of the Citizen History properly understood and presented, and Economics. The key is here again Science. Finally, those occupations which promote the enjoyment of life and are for leisure are not to be neglected, but postponed ; and even these things Literature, Art, etc., though it may not be at first sight obvious, rest for their true ap- preciation on Science. "Accomplishments, the fine Arts, Literature, etc.," all those things which constitute the efflor- escence of civilization should be wholly subordinate to that instruction and discipline on which investigation rests. "As they occupy the leisure part of life, so should they occupy tlie leisure part of education." THE MODERN SENSE-REALIST 237 Science, also, is not only best for knowledge, but for intel- lectual discipline. Nay also, it has direct bearing on the moral perceptions and the religious emotions. Thus to the question "What knowledge is of most worth?" the uniform reply is 'Science.' And to the question "What discipline is of most worth ? " the answer is again ' Science ' ; and this even in the moral and religious sphere. We see in all this the most logical and lucid exposition of the educational theory of the Sense-realistic school. It rests on a philosophy of man, which amounts to this, that man's task on this earth is, like that of any other sentient organism, to adapt himself to his environment in order that he may live comfortably, and, as a condition of comfort, reputably. Morality even is subordinated to comfortable living called Complete Living. The theory opposed to this, as light to darkness, we have called the Real-humanistic. Its aim is not complete living but complete life. It may be summed up as character and culture. It seeks to define the life of man as that of a spirit which rises above its environment and seeks ideal aims, ethical, aesthetic, and religious, and a will formed to right conduct. But it does not, on that account, ignore the claims of a knowledge of the phenomenal world and of society and of man's relations to both. It assumes this as necessary alike to conduct and the highest spiritual life; but in the education of the people, as in the development of the man to his full manhood, it regards the knowledge of all that has to do with the body and with nature as merely contributory to true education. The best reply to Spencer is Locke, although he was no idealist. And all I would say here is that, suppose we had a man with all the pigeon-holed acquirements that Mr Spencer would give him, we should say ' Now let us begin to educate him.' In fact suppose an anthropoid ape who had lost the divine gift of instinct and was endowed with the imperfect beginnings of reason instead, and Mr Spencer's system of 238 HERBERT SPENCER, education would be admirable. The literary, aesthetic, religious and even morality as an ideal system of perfection, are all decorative merely. The intelligent anthropoid ape's desire for decoration would be satisfied with coloured ribbons and straw which please the village idiot, and would rightly be postponed to material necessities. Man's function on earth, we believe, is to use his environment as a mere basis for higher things the things by which men truly live, and these must from the first and all through, constitute the substance of his education. Assuredly, we all hope never to be, and never to meet, that incorporation of the elements of all the sciences which Mr Spencer calls a man, even though endowed with the pru- dential bourgeois morality which by the help of the police keeps things going. A classical prig and pedant is bad enough, but, after all, he is in touch with the best in humanity : the prig pedant who has fed on the dry crumbs of science since he was a baby would be wholly intolerable. There is surely some other ideal of the completely educated man which carries us far beyond the sphere of " complete living " in the Spencerian sense. The total inadequacy of sense-realism to conceive such a theory will I think be well illustrated by turning to Mr Spencer's special treatment of Moral Education which has not so far as I know been subjected to adverse criticism, attention having for the most part been directed to the in- tellectual part of his treatise. But before doing so I would say that Mr Spencer's chapter on Method, although it is, perhaps because it is, a collection of recognized precepts lucidly and logically put, is well worthy of the perusal, both of teachers and theorists. Moral Education. A Criticism. I heartily concur with Mr Spencer, both in the beginning and the conclusion of his chapter on " Moral Education." His first paragraph concludes with this utterance : " The subject THE MODERN SENSE-REALIST 239 which involves all other subjects, and therefore the subject in which education should culminate, is the Theory and Practice of Education." We cannot, of course, teach boys and girls at school how to discharge their duties as parents : at the school age, such instructions could have no link of association with the knowledge and experience of the boy and girl, and would, therefore, be wholly futile. We teach children these, their future duties, by being ourselves an example to them, which they will remember and imitate : nothing in education is so potent as tradition early received. But when Spencer suggests that the education of young men and women should culminate in the study of education that is to say, of moral education I think he gives utterance to a novel idea, which is not to be set hastily aside because of its novelty. Perhaps it will one day be accepted as a truism at least as regards young women. I re- member, many years ago, being much impressed, but, of course, not surprised, when I beheld young ladies hurrying in consider- able numbers to University lectures in Logic, Latin, Mathematics, and Physiology, while the subject which most nearly concerned the future life of more than ninety per cent, of them, viz., Edu- cation, was taken only by the few who meant to be school teachers. It will not always be so. Mothers of the wealthier classes will tell us that they have no time for the training of their children ; the demands of society are too exacting to admit of it. The day will come, if the race is to make progress, when it will be the other way about, and " Society " will have to content itself with taking a second place, while the duties of the nursery and the parlour will make good their prior claim. If the mother, though never the sole, yet always (theoretically, at least) the chief educator, is unfit for these duties, as is too commonly the case, it is just as well that she should delegate them, for, as Spencer truly says, "The defects of children mirror the defects of their parents " a remark to be extended, I need scarcely say, from the parent to the teacher. That the teacher who professes to be an educator should study education 240 HERBERT SPENCER, before he enters on his task would seem to be a proposition beyond all question, and yet it is still questioned by not a few survivals of a passing generation at Eton and elsewhere. Mr Spencer adverts to the irrational severity of domestic discipline, but he omits the still greater evils which flow from the training which is irrationally indulgent. In this respect Locke takes a much firmer and more profound view of the re- lation between parent and child, though he errs in the excessive severity which lies at the foundation of his system of moral training. We are not to suppose that over-indulgence is limited to the well-to-do ; it is even more common among the poor varied, of course, with fits of passion. The following incident (a part of my own personal experience) sums up the attitude of the indulgent maternal mind : " Why do you not send your children to school? " said the minister to a fisherwoman in a Banffshire village. " Because they dinna want to gang," answers the mother. " But, surely, it is not what they want that you should think of, but what is good for them." "Oh, puir things," retorts the mother, "they maun hae their ane wull, for it's a' we puir folk hae to gie them"! So far, I say, we shall concur with Mr Spencer. But now he plunges into a sea of error, putting what he has to say, however, in a way so lucid, pleasant, and seeming-logical as to seduce the young reader into the acceptance of a fatal doctrine a doctrine, moreover, which, if understood and held, degrades the position, by degrading the aims and work, of the educator. He discusses the end or aim of moral education, and the relation of this end or aim to an ideal morality and an ideal system of training. Adaptation to environment governs all he says in the moral, as it did in the intellectual, education of the young. Here I shall let Spencer speak for himself before I proceed to criticize his position : " Even were there methods by which the desired end [the THE MODERN SENSE-REALIST 24! practice of an ideal system of morality] could be at once effected, and even had fathers and mothers sufficient insight, sympathy, and self-command to employ these methods consis- tently, it might still be contended that it would be of no use to reform family government faster than other things are reformed. What is it we aim to do ? Is it not that education, of whatever kind, has for its proximate end to prepare a child for the business of life to produce a citizen who, while he is well-conducted, is also able to make his way in the world? And does not making his way in the world (by which we mean, not the acquirement of wealth, but of the funds requisite for bringing-up a family) does not this imply a certain fitness for the world as it now is ? And if by any system of culture an ideal human being could be produced, is it not doubtful whether he would be fit for the world as it now is ? May we not, on the contrary, suspect that his too keen sense of rectitude, and too elevated standard of conduct, would make life intolerable or even impossible ? And, however admirable the result might be, considered individually, would it not be self-defeating in so far as society and posterity are concerned ? There is much reason for thinking that, as in a nation so in a family, the kind of government is, on the whole, about as good as the general state of human nature permits it to be. We may argue that, in the one case, as in the other, the average character of the people determines the quality of the control exercised. In both cases it may be inferred that amelioration of the average character leads to an amelioration of system ; and further that, were it impossible to ameliorate the system without the average character being first ameliorated, evil rather than good would follow. Such degree of harshness as children now experience from their parents and teachers may be regarded as but a preparation for that greater harshness which they will meet with on entering the world. And it may be argued that, were it possible for parents and teachers to treat them with perfect equity and entire sympathy, it would but intensify the sufferings L. 16 242 HERBERT SPENCER, which the selfishness of men must, in after life, inflict on them. "'But does not this prove too much?' someone will ask. ' If no system of moral training can forthwith make children what they should be if, even were there a system that would do this, existing parents are too imperfect to carry it out and if, even could such a system be successfully carried out, its results would be disastrously incongruous with the present state of society does it not follow that to reform the system now in use is neither practicable nor desirable?' No. It merely follows that reform in domestic government must go on part passu with other reforms. It merely follows that methods of discipline neither can be nor should be ameliorated except by instalments. It merely follows that the dictates of abstract rectitude will, in practice, inevitably be subordinated by the present state of human nature by the imperfections alike of children, of parents, and of society and can only be better fulfilled as the general character becomes better. '"At any rate, then,' may rejoin our critic, 'it is clearly use- less to set up any ideal standard of family discipline. There can be no advantage in elaborating and recommending methods that are in advance of the time.' Again we contend for the contrary. Just as in the case of political government, though pure rectitude may be at present impracticable, it is requisite to know where the right lies, in order that the changes we make may be towards the right instead of away from it ; so, in the case of domestic government, an ideal must be upheld, that there may be gradual approximations to it. We need fear no evil consequences from the maintenance of such an ideal. On the average, the constitutional conservatism of mankind is strong enough to prevent too rapid a change. Things are so organized that, until men have grown up to the level of a higher belief, they cannot receive it ; nominally they may hold it, but not virtually. And, even when the truth gets recognized, the obstacles to conformity with it are so persistent as to outlive THE MODERN SENSE-REALIST 243 the patience of philanthropists, and even of philosophers. We may be sure, therefore, that the difficulties in the way of a normal government of children will always put an adequate check upon the efforts to realize it." Note now the "proxi- mate end" of moral education, as defined by Spencer (p. 99), viz.: "to produce a citizen who is well-conducted, and is also able to make his way in the world," that is to say, "acquire the funds requisite for bringing-up a family." This "proximate end" he elsewhere identifies with the "practical ideal." We at once quarrel with Mr Spencer's conception of the moral or ethical end. If he simply means that, try as we may, we ourselves shall never be able to lead ideal lives or train up others to lead them, he utters a commonplace which is all too true ; but this is not what he means, as we may see from the rest of his argument. Although it may be that we must often enough be content with the attainment of a "proxi- mate end," in the sense of an approximation to an ideal end, the approximation is not our end or aim. The proximate end, as conceived by Mr Spencer, has its value; but as an edu- cational end it is contemptible, and would take the very heart out of any teacher worth his salt. There is such a conception as that of the ideal man : that is to say, the man to whom the great ethical ideas of justice, benevolence, integrity, purity, and the thought of God in whom all ideals rest, are a sacred possession, and who strives daily to make them the guide of his conduct, though they may often lead him to suffering, nay, sometimes to death. No man succeeds perfectly ; but, that each may be even such as he is, it is necessary that he strive after something higher than his actual attainment or the prac- tical ideal. In the ideas resides the imperative moral law, and it is this the true man would fain, by God's help, fulfil. The fulfilment of the law in the ideas is the spiritual life the true life of a rational spirit; all else is life inadequate and im- perfect. This true life is, for each, simply the completion of himself as man. All created things tend unconsciously or 1 6 2 244 HERBERT SPENCER, consciously, through the forces within them, to their own fulfilment or completion, while the self-conscious man purposely endeavours to realize that fulfilment in himself, if he is to be truly man. This, I submit, is the true doctrine ; and it is to this we have to educate children and youths ; and if we fail, accept our failure. It is also, substantially at least, the doctrine of Plato, Aristotle, and the New Testament. I must assume that you have read the relative passages in Spencer. If you have, you will have learned that the young must not be trained to seek and serve the ideal, but for the " world as it now is." If too good for it, or trying to rise above the average, first the child, then the youth, and finally the man will suffer. We must abjure the highest, because it leads to possible pain this pain having chiefly or wholly to do with our "getting on." We must not try to be better than our neighbours. If a youth has ideals of conduct, he must keep them under lock and key. They are too good for daily use. He had better, I should say, expunge them from his mind altogether, lest he should inadvertently act in accordance with them. His best course would be not to deny their existence, but to write them on a card, and hang them on his walls, to be read over say, on birthdays ; but, when he has read them, he must, with a cynical smile, exclaim : " All these I shall not observe from my youth up. These are the solid coins of fools, but only the counters of wise men in this sense : that the wise do not deny their absolute truth as symbolic of something or other which is real and true ideally, but they must not treat these idealities as realities here and now in this world. They are for some other place and time." This is no misrepresentation of our author, for he admits that there is a true ideal ; it is to be known to us that we may be aware "where the truth lies," and to guide us in making cautious and calculated changes in the right and true direction; but that is all. You may live, more or less, according to an ideal standard, and teach others to live according to an ideal THE MODERN SENSE-REALIST 245 standard, but only in so far as it does not separate you and others too far from the common motives that govern the average man. Out of a kind consideration for those who have an ideal standard, Spencer condescends to say, that if we only work in the direction of it, without trying too hard, "we need fear no evil consequences"! (p. 101). Such, according to Spencer, is the moral aim generally, and such the place and dangers of the ideal. I would remark that this practical ideal of Spencer's is not an ideal at all. There cannot, if there is any meaning in words, be two ideals. The practical ideal, which he commends, is the ideal ; the other ideal what we should call the ideal is with him so remote as to be little better than an illusion. What reality can there be in that which cannot be used ? " Let us now," he says, " consider the true aims and methods." But there is confusion here, for he has already given us his true aim, which is that a man shall be trained "to be no better than he should be," to use a phrase which is strictly true of Spencer's aim, and conveys also its criticism. Spencer has already, I repeat, got his aim or end in the sphere of moral education, and what he now proceeds to consider are the methods whereby we may attain that aim or end how we are to train children to be as good as their neighbours, and prevent their being any better, lest "evil consequences" should follow. But he is, very naturally indeed, necessarily, when he begins to think of method led aside for a moment to consider the final standard or criterion of all morality whatsoever. He has already said, remember, that our approximate end, as he calls it, is to produce a well- conducted citizen, who "can make his living," etc. That there is an ideal greater and higher than this, however, he admits, but he sets it aside as if it were the dream of enthusiasts something we may as well know, that our conduct generally, and our teaching generally, may tend that way, so far as it 246 HERBERT SPENCER, t's quite safe. There might, he grants, flow "evil consequences" even from merely keeping ideals in view; there is some danger in this, but he trusts to human wickedness and weakness to obviate these evils. That is to say, the evil in men may be trusted to obviate the evils arising from the pursuit of the ideal good a singular position ! There is manifestly some- thing hopelessly mixed here, to say the least. The evil in man is to be relied on to keep him safe from evil a re- markable assertion ! We wonder what the author can mean by "evil," and in what sense he uses the word. And he must sympathise with the wonder of his reader, for he proceeds to consider how the (dangerous) true and absolute ideal in life and conduct is ascertained. By what mark shall I know it when I see it? What is its criterion? Important this, because it may not only make the whole argument logical and coherent, but also, perhaps, suggest a method of procedure in educating the young. The criterion or standard he seeks is thus propounded : that conduct is right and good "whose total consequences are beneficial"; and by the word 'beneficial' he means "resulting in happiness." This is the way (we are told) we find the true the moral ideal. But as he has already said that we must not make the ideal our aim in educating, but that our aim should rather be the adapting of the young to the time and circumstances in which they live a training of them to a kind of average morality which sets aside the ideal and perfection as idle dreams the standard of the said ideal which he now exhibits to us lands him in endless contradictions. If the ideal is that whose total consequences are most pleasurable and beneficial, then, surely, we ought always ourselves to aim at the "most pleasur- able and beneficial," in other words, the true ideal, and train the young to do so ; for, if we do not aim at it, we shall be aiming at something which is not pleasant and beneficial, or, at best, only in a minor and subordinate degree pleasant and beneficial. To do what is most pleasant and beneficial to you THE MODERN SENSE-REALIST 247 as a man, would, inasmuch as it is the true ideal, be unpleasant and unbeneficial ! Has he not already virtually said, "Be not too good, lest you suffer in this unsatisfactory world"? And now he tells us that the goodest goodness is the pleasantest thing goin: How, then, by pursuing this goodest goodness this true and absolute ideal can I suffer at least in the moral and spiritual sense? Why should I content myself with hanging up ideal principles on the wall, and suspending them in my daily conduct? How, in short, can that which is "pleasant and beneficial " be undesirable, according to Spencer's theory of morals? Not to aim at the "ideal" is to aim at that which is not pleasant and beneficial, according to Mr Spencer's own theory, or, at least, not so pleasant and beneficial as the ideal, by his own showing, is. This is a singular result of the happiness theory of morals. He would rejoin, doubtless, that the practical ideal it is which contradicts the true ideal. Men are not yet ready for the pleasures of the true ideal ; it would be painful to them, not pleasant; striving itself, in fact, is unpleasant ; therefore, don't strive. Now, I do not think we can let such an argument pass with- out protest. If the true ideal is the most pleasurable in its consequences, it can have been ascertained only by experience if not the experience of everybody, yet the experience of Mr Spencer and other thinking men. If so, then it is surely his duty to educate to this " highest pleasure," this true ideal, and not to allow his fellow-men to go on living without even trying to get the "greatest pleasure." Doubtless, he might reply : "I cannot admit the duty, because I know very well the mass of mankind cannot rise to such enjoyments." Then, we say : Why talk about the true ideal at all, and dangle it before their eyes as a thing first to be looked at and then to be looked away from? For, if it is the highest pleasure, it can exist to their consciousness at all only in so far (according to your criterion) as it is conceived as the highest pleasure the ideal. For the ideal and the highest pleasure are interchangeable terms. 248 HERBERT SPENCER, Accordingly, it can only add to their pain, not their pleasure, to see the highest pleasure, and then to be told to rest content with the lower pleasure, as best suited to them. And, again, if they pursue the lower pleasure, as best suited to them and their environment, this must mean that they get more pleasure out of the lesser pleasure than they could out of the so-called greater pleasure. Their ideal is, in short, the lesser pleasure, and they have as much right to call it the true ideal as you have to call the scheme of life hanging on the wall the true ideal. " So long as they are happy, what's the odds?" True, Mr Spencer might say : " I do not try to teach what I regard as the highest pleasure, the true ideal, to children and men because I would not disturb them in their greatest pleasure [beer and skittles], though it is really painful to them more than they know ; but to pursue the true greatest pleasure, the true ideal, would be more painful still." Then, may I not rejoin, neither the true ideal nor the pursuit of the true ideal is so pleasurable to them as their own lower ideal, and (according to you) greater pain? That is to say, they already have the true ideal, and not you at all. They have summed up one way, and you have summed up another ; your criterion or standard is manifestly no standard, for a standard is not a standard unless it is a fixed something by which all else can be measured. Pleasure and pain, we may conclude, are not the criteria of virtue and vice. Another answer to the question, "Why do you not train men to the highest pleasure, the true ideal?" might be this. Mr Spencer might, quite consistently, say that he did not try to teach men the highest pleasure, the true ideal, because it was such a bore to him. In other words, the mere labour of doing so was a pain greater than any pleasure that could come out of it to him, and, as detracting from his pleasure, detract consequently from his own ideal moral state. In brief, to attempt to convert men to his ideal, he would, in his own person, be untrue to the standard of all morality the greatest THE MODERN SENSE-REALIST 249 sum of pleasure ; nay, inasmuch as it would be purposely done, he would be profoundly immoral in so acting, so far as his own ethical completeness was concerned. Nay, further, knowing, as he did, the pain they would suffer from pursuing his ideal, his purpose would be a purpose of evil at best, a doing evil that good might, perhaps, come. But, surely, we ought not to be afraid to teach men the true ideal the most pleasurable ; for has it not been already said that, men being so wicked and weak, we need not anticipate any "evil consequences" from keeping the ideal in view. This ought to console us, and encourage us in teaching the true ideal. "Do not hang back," he might say, "for the pursuit of that which is absolutely pleasant and beneficial (the true ideal) will not result in evil consequences (i.e. the unpleasant and unbeneficial) so much as we might fear (!), because men have such a strong natural bias to the unpleasant and unbeneficial." It is assumed, remember, all this while, that there exists a true moral ideal ; it is distinctly stated that that moral ideal yields the maximum of pleasure, and is finally to be tested by its power to do so ; but we are to set it aside in favour of the relatively right and good the practical ideal of that which shall make us good enough, and no more, for the society into which we are born. In other words, we are to adopt as our standard the less pleasurable and the less beneficial meanwhile, in order that we may secure the maximum of pleasure obtain- able now and here London, 1902 the maximum possibile varying as we may happen to be in England or France or Syria or India or China. Why are we to do so? Because if a man aimed at true and genuine pleasure and happiness, and so lived, or strove to live, the true ideal life, he would, inasmuch as his " sense of rectitude " would then be too keen and his standard of conduct too " elevated " (p. 99), fail to secure the greatest pleasure and benefit ; therefore, the standard of conduct is never that which would yield to a man the greatest pleasure and benefit, but that which would, taking all his circumstances 250 HERBERT SPENCER, into consideration, yield the greatest pleasure and benefit in his own judgment at the moment. As it is absurd, in such a case, to suppose a man not choosing the greater pleasure, we may be sure he always does so ; consequently, every man is always moral, always in harmony with his ideal, i.e., his greatest pleasure and happiness at the time. And yet there can be no doubt that Mr Spencer does actually believe in a true moral ideal which, though measured by pleasure, is different from a "practical" ideal also measured by pleasure. But, if we are to measure conduct by the sum of the pleasurable which it yields, and not by law, how can any ideal be truer than another ? Mr Spencer has no right to speak of a true ideal which shall be a standard for all ; one man's ideal is as good as another's if it happens to be the greatest pleasure for him, which we may always presume it is, for why should he not choose pleasure ? What prevents him doing as he pleases, unless it be the policeman ? But although Mr Spencer has, in my opinion, no philosophical right to speak of a true ideal, he yet does so, and sets this true ideal against the practical ideal. The former, Spencer evidently quite honestly holds to be truly morality as being the true ideal ; the latter, then, is not morality at all, but an approximation, an adaptation of some of the truths of morality to the average of a particular time, place, and circumstance. This latter is always at war with the former the true ideal and our business is, according to Mr Spencer, after taking a passing glance at the impossible true ideal of conduct to educate ourselves and others in that which is not too moral that is to say, not too pleasure-giving, not too bene- ficial in its results! It is manifest, then, that the " practical " moral ideal, which is to be the working ideal of teacher and parent, is a gathering together of the dubious and admittedly defective, untrue, and pain-giving principles which regulate the Church, the Market, and 'Change, and training our children in these. Be just, but not too just ; be benevolent, but not too benevolent ; be self- THE MODERN SENSE-REALIST 251 controlled, but not too self-controlled ; be pure, but not too pure ; be virtuous, but not too virtuous ; be good, but not too good : this is the working ideal. Where, then, can the true ideal the just, the good, the noble, the heroic, the self-sacrificing, and so forth be all this while ? In Spencer's view, doubtless, as well as in ours, this ideal is in the thoughts of all the wise of all ages, who have preached it and pressed it on men, not altogether in vain. Have they been wrong to preach it as yielding a scheme of conduct? If not, are we wrong to teach it? Shall we de- liberately counterwork it ? Shall we set aside Christ and Paul, and all the philosophers and poets, and say to them, " Go to, do not interfere with our practical teaching; do not fill our children's heads with ideal nonsense. We have to prepare for the world that now is, and the world is to him who can take it ; and he alone can take it who sands the sugar of his justice, who waters the milk of his human-kindness, who mixes his truthfulness with prevarications, his wisdom with cunning, his self-sacrifice with selfishness, his reverence with impudence, his nobleness with ignobleness, his virtue with vice, his good with evil." If Mr Spencer does not mean this, what does he mean ? Do you not feel that there is an error somewhere, that Mr Spencer and his school either use language in a non-natural sense, or that they are hopelessly wrong in their attempts to give the philosophy of the moral and spiritual life of man ? The maximum of pleasure, now and here, is to be your aim, and you are not to bother yourselves or your pupils about the true ideal (the most pleasurable, note), save by a passing allusion to what is essentially an illusion. Now, to compare such teaching as this of Spencer's with that of Greek or Roman thought, would be an insult to the latter. Nay, even the edu- cated Chinaman would abjure it, and as to Christianity, what shall we say ? Is this the teaching of Christ ? And yet our training colleges exist as Christian institutions. The Churches are eager to take Government money to conduct these colleges 252 HERBERT SPENCER, in order that, at the very fountain-head, they may guarantee Christian teachers and Christian teaching ; and this is the book 1 which those who are shortly to be placed in a position of authority over the coming generation are told to study as if it were a Gospel a new evangel to English men and women. In one room the Churches teach Christ, and in the other Spencer Christ the teacher of Divine law, the preacher of transcendent ideals, the priest of self-sacrifice. I do not doubt that the training college authorities, generally at least, try to counteract this teaching ; but is it wise to give young and whoUy unformed minds such a foundation for their philosophy of life ? According to Spencer, Christ on the cross, and all the crucified and self-sacrificed martyrs, were enjoying the greatest sum of pleasure possible for them. I ask you : Is this the true reading of history? According to Spencer, it was foolish of Christ and the others ; they were mistaken. They were blind to their environment. Unadapted to their environment they did not "survive." Mr Spencer might, perhaps, admit that they were nobly blind; but he must at heart despise their intelligence, and denounce their blunder. No wonder the people mocked at them and went off self-corn placently to their beer and skittles their greatest sum of pleasure, and, therefore, as moral and as lofty as the faith of the martyr on the cross or the rack. Alas, for Christ and the others, who misprized the common pleasures of life ; tliey had made a mistake in arithmetic. That figure there on the board, running into the thousands, with a fraction (a circulating decimal, and a little elusive), represents pleasures; it has to be divided by something called the "sum," and these mistaken martyrs brought out a wrong quotient. It would be out of place here to enter further into philo- sophical argument than we have done. But, speaking generally, 1 It is no longer specially recommended. THE MODERN SENSE-REALIST 253 I may say that the Christian faith (it matters not to what extent men may differ regarding facts and doctrines) always includes this ethical substance, viz. the innate instincts and needs of man's nature, as a complex of feeling, tendency, emotion, and reason, yield to us, in the long-run, certain ethical ideas for example, truthfulness, benevolence, justice, integrity, purity, self-sacrifice, and so forth ; these ideas, in their highest and purest form, constitute the law of our nature the law of God in us. It matters not that these ideas may have taken gener- ations to grow, if they are the true reading of the moral and spiritual nature of man. It is precisely these ideas, in their most generalized and universal form, with Divine law inherent in them, that constitute the ethical ideal ; and up to this we have ourselves to strive, and up to this we have to educate the young. The process by which we educate them we call training to the good, and discipline to duty ; and the question of method, which so much concerns us as teachers, is simply an inquiry into the " way " whereby we may build up this ethical ideal in the minds of children and youths, and make it the motive force in their conduct of life, as at once the law of God and alone the true life of man on earth here and now. This brings us to the question of method, as dealt with by Mr Spencer. As might be expected, his method is the method of conse- quences. We accept this. In our own adult case, however, the consequences of misconduct are the inner pain of sentiment ignored, of a foregone ideal, of a broken law, of an outraged nature, of God defied ; and in the case of the young, the pain of the disapprobation of teachers and parents, as embodying for the young the ideal and the law. Material consequences may or may not follow that is to say, the punishment of the body in various ways, direct and indirect, positive and negative. Whether they should ever follow is one of the debated ques- tions. 254 HERBERT SPENCER, You will see that, even to train up children to be no better than they should be, and always to choose what yields the most pleasure, some method is wanted. They have to be taught wherein their true pleasure lies when they are men, although it may seem not to be their true pleasure when children, because of their immaturity of judgment. How are we to proceed? Doubtless, if we may make a reasonable inference from a statement in the beginning of the chapter, Spencer would say, along with all other educational moralists, "By example." But, outside example, some other mode of procedure is necessary. This mode of procedure is called a method. Now, it is manifest that if morality is identical with the most beneficial or pleasing consequences, I must train to morality by painful consequences. The child-sum of pleasures must bjs rectified by the adult-sum. Mr Spencer points out, I have just said, that the method is the method of consequences ; but the consequences are, in the larger part of his argument, always material, not moral with the boy, the pain of burning his finger or having to put right what he has put wrong ; with the man, indigestion or the pain of being deprived of his salary or the injury to his prospects of salary. Thus, he says, the child and the youth attain to a " knowledge of right and wrong by personal experience of good and bad consequences." If I amuse myself by sticking a pin into my leg, I feel pain, and I seek some other amusement in future. There is here what Spencer calls a "natural reaction" that is to say, nature instantaneously punishes an infraction of nature's laws. Spencer's main proposition, then, as regards method of moral training is, let the reaction of nature take place. Now, it is not morally wrong to stick a pin into my leg. It is merely a physical miscalculation. Mr Spencer confounds moral and emotional with purely physical reactions. When a little boy, in his anger, smashes his mother's best china- bowl, the natural reaction is a feeling of great satisfaction. When he burns his THE MODERN SENSE-REALIST 255 catechism in the hope of so ending a painful series of daily lessons, the flames are less bright and joyous than those that blaze up in his own heart. This is, as a matter of fact, the natural reaction. Then, again, when he climbs a tree, and falls and breaks a leg, the natural reaction of his being such a goose as to lose hold of one footing before he has secured the next is manifest. He has broken a physical law, but not a moral law, and must take the physical consequences. If he has taken firm hold, and secures the object of his ambition the thrush's nest and sells the eggs for 6d. apiece, he now enjoys the natural reaction, as before he suffered from it. It is quite clear from these illustrations that "natural reactions" are outside the moral sphere altogether, and that if there be anything immoral in his act, it must arise in some other way. In what way ? It arises from the fact that he has broken a moral law ; and that moral law can only be to a child the command of his parents and teachers. What, then, is the natural reaction? Spencer gets so confused over his natural reactions that he begins, towards the end of this chapter, to see that he is some- how wrong, and says that the disapprobation of the parent or teacher is itself a "natural reaction." Here he is at last on the right scent. But what becomes of his original "natural" reaction? The natural reactions he has been talking of are the reactions of nature in the sense of physical laws. He would now include the parent's disapprobation under the same head, using the word " natural " in the vulgar sense of what might be "reasonably expected to follow." I see my boy in the tree where he has been told not to go. Am I cunningly to shake it, that I may cause him to fall and break his leg, and so facilitate the natural reaction? What natural reaction the reaction of physical law or of moral law? Is this to be his punishment, a fall that breaks his leg, and to which I have cunningly contributed ? I think not. The parent who did it would soon be in the hands of the police. In fact, the much-lauded doctrine of natural reactions in 256 HERBERT SPENCER, the sense of reactions of physical law, carries us a very little way indeed. At best it is a physical reaction to a breach of physical law. We are compelled from the first to consider moral re- actions for moral offences, and let the physical blunders correct themselves, after we have given due warning. No parent or teacher needs to be told that ninety-nine per cent, of the wrong-doing of the young is, not a breach of physical laws, but simply disobedience the breach of moral law as that is centred in the parent or teacher, the moral authority set over them. There would be no natural reaction (i.e., no material consequences) at all in the great majority of cases of wrong-doing, and the majority of the remainder would be pleasant were it not for the purposed intervention of the parent or teacher, who deliberately inflicts certain unpleasant material consequences under the name of punishments. And Mr Spencer himself is compelled to admit that this is so, for when he leaves certain little childish faults behind him, he virtually admits that he is on the wrong track, and has to rest the training of the child on the simple approval or disapproval of the master or parent, with such punishments, if any, as they may choose to inflict. There is no other course open to him. In the sphere of child-morality there is no " natural ' : reaction available, except approval or disapproval. But if this is so in all important cases, it is equally true of the unimportant. The child who makes a litter (to take Mr Spencer's illustration), and is required as a punishment to put things right, is not morally educated by that, but by the disapproval of his mother, who emphasizes her disapproval by imposing this task a course of conduct on her part to be justified by the fact that it impresses her disapproval and puts it in a concrete form. Again, the restitution of a stolen knife, or of the knife of another lost through carelessness, does not give rise to any moral feeling ; that moral feeling must precede the restitution, this latter being only the outward and visible sign of an inward spiritual grace. So the boy, of whom Spencer speaks, who, having been kindly THE MODERN SENSE-REALIST 257 and generously treated by an elder, declines to do a kindness to him in return, and, when he finds the consequences of it in the elder refusing to amuse him any more, then, and not till then, of his own accord brings him his shaving water and boots in order to restore friendly relations, has gone through no moral training at all, except in so far as he first felt the disapprobation of his elder, &&&, feeling that, felt his own unworthiness, and then tried to make amends. And what does Mr Spencer himself say of the father who has the " perfect confidence and affection of his children " ? He says that the said father finds that the "simple display of his approbation or disapprobation gives him abundant power of control." Of course it does. But is this the calculation of material consequences by the children ? If so, they are mean and demoralized little monsters. Thus the method of Spencer, no less than his end and criterion, breaks down all round, even taking him on his own showing ; and, in so many words, he has to tell us at last what he ought to have told us in the beginning, that the disappro- bation or approbation of the teacher is itself a " natural reaction," and this is not a reaction of nature at all, but a moral consequence. Mr Spencer, when he gets on the right track, begins to talk of sympathy between parent and child, and the power of approbation and disapprobation where this sym- pathy exists. With all this I believe we should all substantially concur, as well as with his remarks on the importance of not expecting children to be too good, and so forth. But as regards the moral end, the moral aim, the moral motive, the moral criterion, and the moral method, his doctrine is always wrong, and sometimes pernicious. Then, when he begins at last to see light, in the course of his fluent argument, instead of tearing up his MS. and beginning over again from a new and higher point of view, he involves himself in intellectual confusion and moral contradiction, as he did when he spoke of true and practical ideals. The old doctrine of " natural reactions," which Mr Spencer L. 17 258 HERBERT SPENCER, fathers anew, simply amounts to this : " We see how nature inflicts a physical penalty for a breach of physical law ; if, then, we desire to inflict a physical punishment over and above the moral penalty, so as to emphasize the breach of moral law, let us take a hint from nature, and let our physical punishment, as far as possible, have some relation to the physical character of the moral offence. It is not a method of moral education at all ; but simplya Rule to guide us when we find it necessary to mark, in an external way, our disapproval or condemnation the dis- approval being the essential punishment, and the gain of that disapproval being the stirring-up of a moral emotion in the breasts of the young. Even as a rule for our guidance in carrying our moral disapproval out into painful material conse- quences, the method of natural reactions is of very restricted application. Bentham's word is much preferable. Let the punishment, he says, be " characteristical." It is the voice of moral authority, and the force of example in the parent and teacher, that teach morality. In brief, and without dwelling longer on the subject, I repeat that the whole principle of natural reactions does not touch the theory of punishment for moral offences, but at best only gives a rule for the selection of physical punishments when we have once made up our mind, on moral grounds, to inflict them, and then, if possible, they should certainly be " characteristical." I would impress the futility of the so-called method on you with a few additional remarks. It is evident enough that, follow- ing the rule of natural reactions without considering moral elements, we should constantly be led into blunders. When a boy breaks a wine-glass through carelessness, we might say that he should be required to replace it; but "nature" does not require this, and to insist on it would be unjust. If he is the son of poor parents, and makes great efforts to economize, with a view to replacing it, he does so because of his feeling of sympathy with his parents in their loss, and of vexation with himself, as having inadvertently caused a loss. The replace- THE MODERN SENSE-REALIST 259 ment, then, is a moral act pure and simple, and has nothing to do with nature's reactions. If, again, he has broken the glass intentionally, in order to pay his parents out for some imaginary injustice, there is no natural reaction of replacement, but quite the reverse. He would like to break two glasses. This is the natural reaction ; and, if I wish to correct the boy, I must first get him to feel what the good boy, who inadvertently broke the glass, felt, and, out of the strength of that feeling, condemn himself, and seek to make restitution. Bentham's recommenda- tion is a sound one, because, among other advantages, it admits of our bringing in reason and common-sense to control nature's reactions, which are generally irrational. A good thing it is that we have to determine punishments, and not nature ; for nature is blind, and stupid, and often cruel. Spencer says that natural reactions are "pure justice." On the contrary, they very seldom are justice at all, if men do not guide and control them. Natural reactions are constantly too slight for the offence, more frequently too grave. Two boys are clambering over a high wall. They have no right to do so, but " boys will be boys," and one falls and breaks his leg ; the other falls, and escapes with a slight bruise. Which of them has been justly treated by nature? Both boys will certainly be more careful in future, but the boy who broke his leg will, perhaps, be, ever after, afraid of high places. This, surely, is an unfortunate result. Courage is a virtue. By over-severity, nature has extinguished the growth of a possible virtue. An infant puts his finger into a candle-flame. Surely, the punishment of hours of pain is too severe. In truth, nature is a very hard task-master, and if we were to follow her example we should often be most unjust. A boy snaps the blade of his knife through carelessness. Let him be punished by going without a knife, Mr Spencer would say. This may be called a natural reaction, but why should I permit nature to inflict it ? I have to consider the boy's motive. What is there that is morally wrong in snapping the blade of his knife through carelessness ? 26O HERBERT SPENCER, I should say, regret the incident with him, and give him a shilling to buy another knife. If there is anything wrong in the snapping of the blade, it must have been that he did it purposely, or while using it for some purpose forbidden by you. The wrong then is breach of law imposed by authority. So with a child littering the floor. Punish by making the child set everything in order again, says Mr Spencer. But why punish at all ? There is nothing wrong in littering the floor ; it is a very innocent and very pleasant and seductive amusement. The natural reaction is a disposition to make the litter greater than ever, that the joy may grow with the mess. The wrong exists only if you, the parent, have forbidden it. Here, again then, the wrong is against law as imposed by authority. Mr Spencer has exag- gerated the range and misinterpreted the meaning of nature's reactions. In the whole of moral training it is the motive of the child's act that you have to consider ; other offences due to thoughtlessness or redundancy of animal life must be kept out- side the moral sphere and gently dealt with. One of Mr Spencer's punishments shows, in an amusing way, how little he has realized the difficulties of the teacher and parent : "Stop pocket-money," he says. How many boys have any pocket-money to stop ? It is as if you were to pass a law to punish thieves by increasing their income-tax. One excellent result, however, it seems, would flow from Mr Spencer's doctrine. He tells us that parents, having to reflect, after a misdemeanour, as to the proper natural reaction applicable to that particular misdemeanour, would learn self- control, and no longer punish impulsively. This is like telling an angry man to count twenty before he speaks. It manifestly assumes that the parent already sees the importance of self- control, and desires and endeavours to exercise it. If he does, the end is gained without the help of the necessity of consider- ing natural reactions. He cannot consider these until he has first controlled himself. THE MODERN SENSE-REALIST 26l I would, in conclusion, point out that Mr Spencer's method is a method of merely negative training in morality ; not a word is said about positive training. Negative training can repress the external exhibition of a vice, while the vice itself may be more deeply rooted than ever. I say there is no positive training to moral ideas, and to a habit of virtue : but with Spencer's moral theory how could there be ? The theory is : Do so-and-so or you will suffer ; you will get the minimum of pleasure and the maximum of pain, and the maximum of pain is vice. Accordingly you cannot train except negatively, if you are to work out this theory consistently. And negative training will produce only negative results. I hope that these critical notes have made it clear : (i) that Mr Spencer's ideal aim in education is false : (2) that his standard of morality is false : (3) that his " method " of moral education is nothing save a Rule to help you in selecting a punishment in certain cases ; and that of very restricted appli- cation : (4) that, while there is much sound practical advice scattered throughout the chapter, the whole argument is as confused as it is misleading and pernicious, until he comes to the moral instrument of approbation and disapprobation, as resting on sympathy : (5) that the Spencerian moral training would be exclusively negative and deterrent training, and only incidentally and uncertainly secure the positive results at which the parent and teacher alike aim. For the attainment of this, not for punishing error, we want a method a method which shall have for its aim the true ideal ; for, we are assured by Quintilian and all the wise, that we can reach any height worth reaching only by striving to reach the top of the hill not by sitting down despairingly at the foot of it or building a hut with a good kitchen and comfortable bed one-third of the way up. CAMBRIDGE: PRINTED BY j. AND c. r. CLAY AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS. BY THE SAME AUTHOR. The Institutes of Education. 2nd ed. OLIVER AND BOYD, EDINBURGH. Primary Instruction in relation to Education. 6th ed. OLIVER AND BOYD, EDINBURGH. Language and Linguistic Method in the School. 4th ed. OLIVER AND BOYD, EDINBURGH. The Training of Teachers and Methods of Instruc- tion. 2nd ed. THE UNIVERSITY PRESS, CAMBRIDGE. The Life and Educational Writings of John Amos Comenius. 6th ed. THE UNIVERSITY PRESS, CAMBRIDGE. Historical Survey of pre-Christian Education. 2nd ed. LONGMANS, GREEN AND CO., LONDON AND NEW YORK. University of California A N REG '? NAL LIBRAR Y FACILITY Hilgard Avenue, Los Angeles, CA 90024-1388 Return this material to the library from which it was borrowed. Z WEEK OCT 6 THE LIBRARY '"" '"" UC80UTHERN REGIONAL