B 2.199 "DSHS UC-NRLF B 3 ^25 fiSl The Epistemological Function of the "Thing in Itself" in Kant's Philosophy A THESIS Presented to the University Faculty of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy, May, 1895 BY ALBERT ROSS HILL ^ The Epistemological Function of the "Thing in Itself" in Kant's Philosophy A THESIS Presented to the University Faculty of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy, May, 1895 BY ALBERT ROSS HILL TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGES Introduction 5-7 CHAPTER I Kant's Epiatemological development from 1755 to 1771 8-20 Sections 1 Period of Dogmatic rationalism (1755) 8-9 ^ In his writings between 1762 and 1766 Kant inclines towards Empiricism but he never becomes a strict Empiricist 9-12 3 The Inaugural Dissertation and transition to the Critique of Pure Reason 18-37 CHAPTER II The function of the 'thing in itself in the deter- mination of th* primary and secondary qualities of objects 21-47 1 None of the qualities of the objects of experience belong to things in themselves 21-23 2 To space and time there does not even correspond any qualities in things, but there must be at least a "power" in things which can cause or produce in us the so-called secondary qualities....: 23-25 3 Further questions as to the function of the 'thing in 'fteelf '. Befor^ :ajtaj! c^ these can be answered we itiust show*«fr(>ni-'t2ie'. Critique 25-27 /•A) : .that*, 'thir^ jn itse^if; "'transcendental object', ' • ''afrKi ''fi'Jmenbn'I fitt negative sense) are syn- onymous terms 27-30 (B) that the 'thing in itself affects sensibility so as to produce sensations within us 30-34 4 Sensation as such is a mere chaotic manifold and consequently is not responsible for either the gen- eral or particular form of spatial perception 34-39 V The particular figures in space are due to the ac- tivity of the a priori faculty of productive imag- ination. The 'thing in itself thus only supplies the rav? material for the construction of spatial relations 39-46 CHAPTER III The function of the 'thing in itself in determining the employment of the categories of the under- standing. I Problems of this chapter and recapitulations of re- sults already arrived at that are to be used here.... 47-49 II No order attributed to sensation throughout the Trancendental Deduction of the Categories. Ex- planation of apparently conflicting statements. Quotations from the Dialectic to show^ that Kant's own view^ of his Method agrees with our interpre- tation 49-58 III The Prolegomena and Dr. Stirling's interpretation of Kant 58-62 IV Kant's proof of the Principles or schematized Cat- egories. No question of this category being em- ployed no^v and another then 62-63 239400 PREFA CE AT the time of presenting this thesis to the Faculty of Cornell University for the doctorate, in the spring of 1895, I hoped to be able to return to the subject and make what J had done the basis for a more exten- sive investigation. I was especially anxious to enquire into the functions of the "thing in itself" in other por- tions of the Critical Philosophy. But the press of other duties has prevented me from carrying out this plan and the thesis is now published in the form m which it was first written. My obligations to various writers have been acknow- ledged throughout the thesis itself, and in addition I am deeply indebted to Professor J. E. Creighton of Cor- nell University, for inspiration, criticism, and guidance in the course of its preparation. For the positions taken, however, I am alone responsible. A. R. H. The Epistemological Function of the **Thing in Itself" in Kant's Philosophy INTRODUCTION To Kant's mind, the failure of all previous philoso- phy to construct a permanent system, and the frequent return of scepticism as the prevailing attitude of inves- tigators in that field, was due to what he conceived to be a This change of stand- point led Kant to seek for the forms or modes of per- ception and judgment which guide us in the knowing of objects. And since these forms or modes, as belonging to the nature of the mind, determine the manner in which we perceive and know, it follows as a matter of course, thought Kant, that we can never know things as they are in themselves, but only the manner in which they appear to us, i. e. , their phenomena. • The vast a priori machinery employed by Kant in his "construction of the object" seems to have so over- shadowed in his own mind, as it has in the minds of his students and interpreters since, the question of the contribution of the object itself (the "thing in itself") to that construction that we are given no explicit state- ments by Kant in the matter; and, to my knowledge, no systematic investigation of the problem has been un- dertaken by any one of the host of writers, small and great, who have professed to furnish us with exposi- tions of his system. Accordingly it does not seem su- perfluous to institute an inquiry into ' 'the Epistemologi- 1 Kant's Werke, Vol. III. pp. 17 ff (Hartenstein). N. B. All references to Kant's works are to Hartenstein's Edition. cal function of the 'thing in itself in Kant's philoso- phy," as this essay aims to do. Here we shall not be concerned so much with the question whether Kant be- lieved in the existence of things in themselves as with this other, how much or how little does the so-called 'thing in itself contribute to our knowledge of objects? If it should be found that it contributes nothing at all, that for knowledge it has no function, then it will be time enough to ask, does the 'thing in itself exist for Kant? And if so, how does he arrive at this conclu- sion? If we adopt the terminology of common sense and call the a priori forms of Sensibility and the categories of the Understanding subjective, we may say that this essay aims to be an enquiry into the objective factors of knowledge, as set forth or implied in the philosophy of Kant. It will have to deal, then, primarily, with such questions as these:— What function has the 'thing in itself in determining the form of objects in experience and their relations to one another? Is there any char- acteristic in things which has .an influence in the deter- mination of the spatial relations of objects? Or even if the mind bring to objects their general spatial quality, what about the particular space forms ? Are these due to the action of the 'thing in itself upon sensibility, otherwise than the general quality of extension is ? In the case of the catagories, too, must the mind be re- garded as the sole agent in their adaptation, or, is the cue for their employment given in sense? And further, as the only means of finding an answer to the above questions, we must decide whether Kant attributed to the 'thing in itself the function of so affecting the senses as to produce sensations within us. These and similar questions will be of primary im- portance, and others will be discussed only in so far as an answer to them may serve to elucidate Kanf s thought concerning the former, or the implications of his general theory of knowledge as bearing on the main problem of the thesis. The greater part of the materials for the answer to our questions must, of course, be sought in the Crit- ique of Pure Reason, since here alone do we find what Kant himself would have been willing to recognize as his system of Epistemology. The Prolegomena, however, written presumably from the same point of view and in fact intended by Kant himself as a sort of popular expo- sition of the main principles of the Critique, may afford us some hints at least in our enquiry. And furthermore, whatever advantage arises from the historical treat- ment of a problem may be gained from a glance at Kant's earlier Epistemological writings, since he seems to exemplify in his own philosophical development al- most the whole history of philosophy in outline. ^ In par- ticular, his Inaugural Dissertation of 1770, signalizing as it does a turning point in Kant's philosophizing and yielding us for the first time in the history of his thought the explicit distinction between phenomena and things in themselves or noumena, may be worthy of more than a passing notice, since here we are introduced to that "method" of enquiry whose full fruitage is the Critique of Pure Reason. Accordingly, the first chapter of this thesis will be devoted to an outline of the historical de- velopment of Kant's Epistemology from the beginning of his literary activity till the time of the first publica- tion of the Critique, with particular attention to the In- augural Dissertation. After that we can proceed di- rectly to a discussion of the main problem of the thesis. iWindelband-Geschichte der Philosophie, Vol. II, p. 15.' 7 H CHAPTER I. KANT'S EPISTEMOLOGICAL DEVELOPMENT (1755-1781) Section 1. Kant's mental history is divided, some- what roughly, by Paulsen, ^ —and Caird^ and Kuno Fisch- er^ make practically the same division— into three per- iods. Previous to 1760 Kant is an adherent "though a somewhat restless and dissatisfied adherent" of the Leibnitz- Wolffian Rationalism. Being at this time little interested in Epistemological problems, he has left us, to represent this period, only one short treatise that is of importance for our purpose, the Dissertation by which he qualified for teaching in llb^—' ' Principiorum Primorum Cognitionis Metaphysicae Nova Dilucidatio" . In this he defends that Rationalism whose chief Episte- mological dogma may be said in general to be that Rea- son is capable in her own strength of revealiyig the nature of things. He shares with it too the general confusion as revealed by all the German philosophers from Leibnitz to Kant,^ concerning the relation of the two principles which they attribute to the use of reason— that of con- tradiction and that of sufficient ground or reason. ^ On the one side he sets up the former as the highest prin- ciple of all truth, ^ and attempts to demonstrate the validity of the latter, thus identifying it in a last resort with the principle of contradiction.'^ This would leave Kant a consistent rationalist like Spinoza: the ground of knowledge would be identical with the cause in things.^ On the other hand, Kant denies outright the identity of cause and ground,^ and treats the principle of sufficient reason as at least partially independent of that of con- tradiction. ^^ The same might thus be said of Kant at this stage in his development as has been said of Wolff to v/nose school he now belongs, viz. , that in reality he has no theory of knowledge at all. ^^ So much, however, the attempted defense of Rationalism in this essay has ' Versuch ein Eutwichlungsgeschichte d. K. Erkenntniss theorie, p. 1-4. 2 Caird's Critical Philosophy of Kant. Vol. I, pp. 65-67. 3 Kuno Fischer— Gesch. d. neueren Phil. Vol. Ill, p. ? * Zeller, Gesch. d. Phil, in Deutschland seit Leibnitz, pp. 147 ff. ^ Paulsen's Versuch etc., p. 34. 6 Kant's Werke I, p. 377. ' Werke I, p. 374. ^ Paulsen's Versuch etc., p. 34. 8 Werke I, pp. 377 ff. ' o Caird, Grit. Phil. I. pp. 186 ff. ' 1 Zeller, Gesch. d. Phil. p. 218. done for Kant: it has brought him face to face with the problem concerning the connection of thought and real- ity. On reflection upon this problem and the implica- tions of his inherited Rationalism in regard to it, he seems to have been led to see the inadequacy of his first answer and the vascillating attitude of his school. Section II. The principle of Sufficient Reason proved to be the stimulating block for Kant.^ Setting out from a criticism of this principle, we find him in his writings between 1762 and 1766 gradually develop- ing in the direction of Empiricism, at least so far as that doctrine is negative, denying the possibility of ar- riving at a knowledge of things by means of pure reason. This is Kant's attitude during the second period of his mental development.^ It is represented by four treat- ises written during the years 1762-3, viz: "The False Subtilty of the Four Syllogistic Figures," "The Sole Ground for the Demonstration of the Being of God," an essay ' ' On the Evidence of the Principles of Nat- ural Theology and Morals, ' ' and ' 'An Attempt to Intro- duce the Conception of Negative Quantity into Philoso- phy. "^ To these should also be added "Dreams of a Ghost-Seer as illustrated by the Dreams of Metaphys- ic" published three years later. At the end of this period we find Kant practically declaring war against that Rationalism from which he had himself set out. And yet ' 'the despairing renunciation of Rationalism which shows itself in the 'Dreams' is only the final result of a course of investigation which is already begun in the 'Dilucidatio Nova'; and the in- tervening treatises enable us to connect the latter with the former almost without a break. "^ In the first of these treatises Kant points out that the movement of thought is purely analytic, proceeding according to the principle of Contradiction.^ And in the second, he goes on to enforce that lesson and its consequences for the prevailing Rationalism by contending that it is impossible by means of this principle alone to bridge the gulf between thought and reality.^ Following upon this is a criticism, in the prize essay 1 Paulsen's Versuch etc., pp. 1 and 37 ff. 2 Caird, Crit. Phil, of Kant, Vol. I, pp. 116-160; cf. also Paulsen's Versuch, etc., pp. 2 and 37-100. 3 That the above is the order in which these treatises were written has heen established by Benno Erdmann, Reflexionen Kant's, Introduction to Vol. II, pp. 17 ff. * Caird, Crit. Phil. Vol. I, p. 117. 5 Werke II, p. 57. 6 Werke II, pp. 115-117. ' 'On the Evidence of the Principles of Natural Theology and Morals," of the method employed by his predeces- sors of the Eighteenth Century. They, inspired by the great success of mathematical science, had been led to suppose that the same method might be employed to advantage in Metaphysics, and the result of their at- tempt had been fatal to the interests of philosophy. ^ The business of philosophy, Kant thinks, is to analyse and make clear given conceptions, while that of mathe- matics is, by means of arbitrary syntheses, to produce conceptions that are not given. Hence, the method of the latter cannot be applied in the investigations of the former. And in connexion with these conclusions con- cerning the method of philosophy, Kant claims that, while she has only one formal principle, viz., that of contradiction, there must be many material principles of knowledge.^ There must be a large number of fun- damental, though often obscure conceptions, to the analysis of which philosophy is called. In the fourth treatise of the year 1763, the Episte- mological results of the preceding three are more clearly asserted and Kant's break with the old Rationalism is no longer half-hearted but decided and clear. He has already told us that the movement of pure thought is solely analytic, that demonstration guided by the law of identity or contradiction can only analyze what is given, and rnust therefore start with many indemonstrable principles; and that, accordingly, pure thought or rea- son is unable in its own strength to get beyond itself and make connection with objective reality. And now, inthe treatise under discussion, he not only enforces still more clearly the above lessons but also goes beyond them by telling us in effect that, while the movem.ent of pure thought is analytic, that of knowledge is sym- pathetic. ^ Kant holds consistently now to the distinct- ion between logical ground and cause in things. And since the identity of these was, more or less clearly, the presupposition of all previous Rationalism, he may surely be said to have ceased to be a Rationalist. Is he then, at this stage in his development an Empiricist? Kant does not give us a positive answer to this question in the treatise concerning "Negative Quality" ; 1 Werke 11, pp. 291 ff. Cf. also Werke III. pp. 15 ff. 2 Werke II. p. 303. 3 Werke II. pp. 103-106. Cf. also Caird, Critical Philosophy of Kant. Vol. I. pp. 128 11; and Paulsen's Versuch etc., pp. 38 ff. 10 ' but one might suppose that when he denies the ability of reason to give us knowledge of facts, he must either conceive a third possibility or attribute that pov/er to experience. At all events, this latter is his answer in the "Dreams" published three years later, with which may be compared a letter to Mendelsohn on April 8th of the same year (1766).^ In the "Dreams" he says: ' 'The fundamental conceptions of things as causes and of their forces and actions are quite arbitrary when not taken from experience, and apart from experience we can never prove nor disprove them"^ Again in the let- ter just mentioned Kant asks: '4s it possible by rea- son to discover a primitive force, i. e. the first funda- mental relation of a cause and. an effect? I answer with certainty that it is impossible.' Hence, I am reduced to the conclusion that except in so far as such forces are given in experience they are only fictions of imagina- tion. "^ And yet there is a great difference between Kant's frame of mind at this time and the attitude of Hume toward the problem of causality. Both Kant and Hume appeal to experience as the sole source of all knowl- edge of ' 'matters of fact, ' ' but they understand exper- ience quite differently. For Hume experience is made up of a vast number of isolated and particular impres- sions and ideas. Each of these constituents exists in its own right and is received into the mind in its own particularity. But from what has been quoted from Kant it v/ill be seen that his view is a quite dif- ferent one. Experience yields for him not only im- pressions but also their arrangement. The connexion of cause and effect is mentioned by him as one of the facts learned from experience, the very connexion which Hume declared could not be derived from any im- pression. So that we may state the difference between Kant at this time and the great Empiricist, as follows: Kant holds that, except in so far as the relation of cause and effect is given in experience, it is only a fiction of the imagination. Hume said the same. It still remain- ed for Kant to go a step further and say with Hume: such a relation cannot be given in experience and there- fore it is a fiction of the imagination. Now it was just 1 Werke VIII, pp. 672 ff. 2 Werke II, p. 378 cf. Paulsen's Versuch, etc., p. 44; and Caird's Critical Phil- osophy of Kant, Vol. I, p. 154. 3 Werke VIII, p. 674. 11 this step v/hich Kant, though perhaps unwittingly, re- fused to take. It would seem as if at the time of writ- ing the "Dreams," this atomistic view of sensations had never occurred to Kant. He looks upon experience quite naively and proclaims that all knowledge of forces and their actions must be derived from experience if it is to be worth anything. It seems highly probable that the most powerful influence of Hume upon our philosopher must be ascribed to the time immediately following the publica- tion of the "Dreams."^ Though he has been acquainted with English Empiricism and no doubt with Hume him- self for some time, yet now he is first awakened from his ' 'dogmatic slumber' ' by discovering in the scepticism of Hume the necessary consequences of his own appeal to experience in opposition to the Rationalism under which he had been educated. Kant has only to see that experience, in the sense of sensations, can never give us apodictically certain and universally valid prop- ositions in order to reject it as the sole means of gaining a knowledge of things But the possibility of such knowledge will not be given up by Kant v/ithout a struggle. He has demon- strated the inadequacy of the old dogmsitic Ratio7ialism', the sceptical results of Hume's investigation have taught him that in perception his ideal of knowledge cannot be realized; but nothing daunted Kant applies himself to a new explanation of how we may arrive at a knowl- edge of things. With this explanation we enter upon the third period in the development of Kant's thought, w^hich opens with the publication of his Inaugural Dis- sertation in 1770, and ends for Epistemology, with the second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason in 1787. Section 3. In the Dissertation we meet for the first time in the history of Kant's thought, with the 1 Kuno Fischer (Gesch. d. u. Phil. HI, pp. 178 and 254) and also Zeller (Gesch. d. deut. Phil, etc., p. 417^ are inclined to place the infiuence of Hume as early as 176S. But while he undoubtedly knew something of Hume at that time, it seems cer- tain, as they admit, that Hume's doubts had not yet taken much hold upon him. (With this compare Paulsen's Versuch, etc., p. 100 and a few passages preceding). On the other hand, Caird (Grit. Phil, of Kant I, pp. 201 ff ) following Benno Erdmann (in an article in Archiv f. Gesch. d. Phil.), finds that the awakening of which Kant himself speaks occurs after the publication of the Dissertation. Caird quotes from Kant to prove that it was in the universalization of Hume's problem that he first found light and that universalization first took place in the Critique. In the same Quotation, however, Kant says that he had already assured himself that these prin- ciples e. g. causality come not from experience but from the mind itself, and this he knew when he wrote the Dissertation, as we shall see. It seems probable, then, that Hume's influence began to be felt at the time and in the way we have suggested, that not till afterwards, however, was its full significance realized and Kant driven to go beyond the Dissertation to the Critique. 12 distinction between phenomena and noumena, and in- deed in the same form in which it is found in Plato and other ancient writers, as Kant himself remarks. Like them, Kant bases that distinction upon the difference in the organs by means of which they are known. The senses give us things only as they appear to us or p/ie- nomena, ^the understanding things as they are or 7iou- mena Leibnitz had made somewhat the same distinction between Sensibility and Understanding, ^ but claimed for the former the ability to arrive at an obscure knowl- edge of things. Kant, however, makes the distinction absolute and opposes in strong terms the position held by Leibnitz. 3 For Kant sensibility is passive, the un- derstanding active; the former receptive, the latter spontaneous.^ If now we inquire for the motive which led Kant to recast this distinction of Leibnitz before adopting it as the foundation of his own system, we find, I think, that it is akin to that which led him to reject his own empiricism, or, rather, v/hich prevented him from ever actually becoming an empiricist. Reflexion upon what is implied in empiricism shows that it must doubt the applicability of mathematics to the objects of experi- ence,^ a doubt which Kant seems to have been never able to entertain. And on the other hand, since math- ematics is sensuous knowledge it affords an argument against the view of Leibnitz that all sensuous knowl- edge is obscure; for mathematics was to the whole eighteenth century the type of clear demonstration. So if Kant is to adopt this distinction of Leibnitz, there remains no alternative but to transform it and make it absolute.^ Thus results his theory of the receptivity of sense and the spontaneity of thought as fundamental to his system, both as enunciated in the Dissertation and as remodeled and further developed in the Critique of Pure Reason.'' Having noted then the point of most importance for us in this treatise of Kant, viz. , the absolute distinction 1 Werke II, p. 400 (sections 3 and 4 of Dissertation) . 2 Nouveaux Essais Book IV, chapter 3. 3 Werke II, pp. 400-402. * Werke III, pp. 52 and 82. _ 5 I do not mean that it is on this point alone that Kant objects to the results of empiricism, but for the present purpose it seems of most importance. See Werke IV, p. 20, and Paulsen's Versuch, etc., pp. 132, 136, and 141. ^ cf.Windleband, Gesch. d. Phil. Vol. II, p. 32; also an article in Vierteljahrschrift, Vol. I, p. 239, "Verschiedene Phasen d. Kant'schen Lehre vom Ding an Sich." 7 cf. Caird, Grit. Phil. VoL I, p. 171 and Paulsen's Versuch, etc., p. 115. 13 between sense and thought, and the revival in connec- tion with that of the old Platonic division of all objects into phenomena and noumena, let us now go on to en- quire more fully into Kant's theory of knowledge in re- gard to each of these classes of objects. In the case of sensuous knowledge we must distin- guish the matter from the form^ The former is given in the sensation, which is due to the action of an object upon the sensibility. The latter, on the other hand, is due to the activity of the mind, according to whose laws the raw material of sensations is formed into orderly perceptions. The laws or forms to which all perception must conform are Space and Time,^ which are thus not qualities of things in themselves but only forms of per- ception under which all things must appear to us. In anticipation we may here add that the intellect has also a function to perform in relation to these per- ceptions. By the logical use of the understanding they are subordinated to conceptions, which conceptions are themselves often won by a process of abstraction from perceptions, and thus the whole of experience is formed.^ What is of particular interest to us here, however, is the doctrine that space and time are not qualities of things, but forms which the mind brings to perceptions. They are not abstracted from experience as presenting to us objects in space and time, but through them our spatial and temporal experience is rendered possible. If such forms were not contributed by the mind, the per- ception of objects as beside one another in space and af- ter one another in time, would not be possible.^ It would seem, then, that the object has no func- tion here in the determination of those qualities which Locke designated as primary, though Kant himself does not seem to have ever raised the question whether any quality exists in the thing in virtue of which its action upon our sensibility leads us to perceive it not only as in space, but also endowed with a shape peculiar to itself. Doubtless the question never entered into Kant's mind, after having once decided that all form comes from the mind, and why should it? Nor does Kant give any ex- plicit answer to this question in the Critique, though, I 1 Werke II, p. 400. ^ Werke 11, p. 405 (section 13 of Dissertation). 3 Werke II, p. 401 (section 5, end). * Werke II, pp. 406-413 (sections 14 and 15 of Dissertation). 14 think, we shall find that the implications of his theory are quite unmistakable. But of this again. We must further ask, does Kant mean to imply, in his theory that sensation gives us the unformed matter of perception, that sensation reveals to us the true qual- ities of the object? In other words, is Kant's theory of the phenomenal nature of sensuous knowledge a conclu- sion from the apriority of space and time? If it is, then the former question must be answered in the affirmative; since we should only have to abstract from the forms of space and tim^e in order to get at the real qualities of things, if their presence alone renders phe- nom.enal all our perception of objects. It cannot be that such is Kant's position. Notice what he says in Section 4 of the Dissertation: "Since whatever is in sensuous knowledge depends upon the subject's peculiar nature, as the latter is capable of receiving somie modification or other from the presence of objects which, on account of subjective variety, may be different in different subjects, whilst whatever knowledge is exempt from such sub- jective conditions, regards the object only; it is plain that what is sensuously thought is the representation of things as they appear, while the intellectual presenta- tions are the representations of things as they are."''- From the above quotation it will be seen that the argument for the phenomenal nature of sensuous knowl- edge is based on the fact that each person possesses his own peculiar organization, not on the theory of the apri- ority of space and time. The statement which I have just quoted is made before Kant has ever mentioned space or time, 2 even before he has made the distinction between form and matter of perception. Thus Kant's conclusion as to the phenomenal character of all human perception does not follow from his peculiar theory of space and time, but, rather, from a point of view, which is by no means new, and v/hich is most clearly expressed by Kant, himself, in the Prolegomena: "It is surely in- conceivable how the perception of a present thing should enable me to know it as it is in inself, seeing that its properties cannot pass over into my presentative faculty. "3 If Kant's only reason for regarding sensuous knowl- 1 Werke II, p. 400. 2 These forms of the sensible world are first mentioned as such in section 13 (n, 405). 3 Werke TV, p. 31 (section 9 of ProL). 15 edge as phenomenal were that all perception must con- form to the apriori forms of space and time, then the so-called secondary qualities would represent the true nature of things. I mention this point here because I think we shall find it of importance in dealing with that phase of our inquiry which will come v/ithin the second chapter of this essay. ^ The doctrine of the ajrriority of space at least seems to have been of importance to Kant chiefly as a means of establishing the apodictic certainty and imiversal validity of mathematical propositions in their application to objects of perception, ^ and this ques- tion does not concern us here. It gives Kant an oppor- tunity to re-instate, even if in a modified form, the Ra- tionalism which he had been so loath to give up, though for sensuous knowledge the qualification is now neces- sary : only for things as they appear, not as they are in themselves. Turning now to the other source of knowledge, the intellectual, we find that, according to the Dissertation, the intellect has a double use— a logical and areal.^ The logical use we have already noted: it consists in still further transforming our perceptions into experience by subordinating them to conceptions. But the real use of the intellect, and this is the im- portant one for us, is to produce pure concepts. These are won by paying heed to those laws which the mind employs in experience, such as Possibility, Necessity, Substance, Cause, etc. Such concepts are not to be sought in the senses, but in the pure intellect'. They are not to be found as parts of any sensuous perception, but are won for consciousness, as indicated above, through reflexion upon that experience in the formation of which they have already been unconsciously employed. Their validity is thus established by Kant on the same ground which Hume appealed to in rejecting them, viz., because they are not found in sensations as such.^ Having made the distinction mentioned above be- tween sense and understanding, Kant concludes, as we have seen, that while the senses give us things as they appear only, or phenomena, the understanding by means 1 I may say in advance that in the "Aesthetic" also I find no evidence for the ordinary interpretation that Kant concludes the unknowableness of things from the apriority of space and time. ■-* That it is the applicability of Mathematics for which Kant particularly con- tends is emphasized by Paulsen— Vei-such, pp. 6-8. 3 Werke II, p, 402 (section 8), ■* Paulsen's Versuch, etc., pp. 106 ff. 16 of its concepts reveals to us noumena or things as they are. As Kant says himself in a letter to Herz,^ the question how this latter is possible is not considered here. Kant seems to have simply adopted the stand- point of Antiquity whereby the phenomenon or object of sense is distinguished from the noumenon or object of the intellect, 2 and this notwithstanding the fact that he had seen the inability of pure thought to connect itself with the nature of things. ^ In connection with Kant's doctrine in the Disserta- tion, I wish to call attention particularly to his notion of a noumenon. It is, as we have seen, an intelligible thing, capable of definite determinations by means of the pure concepts of the understanding. These pure concepts or laws are the same as those afterwards given in the table of the categories in the Critique, so that in this connection there is a marked difference between the standpoints of 1770 and 1781. It is briefiyy-v this: