REESE LIBRARY ; 1 1 1-: UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS " Nach cwigcn, chrnen, Grossen Gesetzen Miisscn wir alle Unseres Dascins Kreise vollenden. Nur allein der Mcnsch Vermag das Unmogliche; Er unterschcidct, Wahlet und richtet; Er kann dcm Augenbliclc Dauer verleihen. Er allein darf Den Guten loknen, Den Bosen strafen, Heilen und retten ; AUes Irrende, Schweifendc Nutzlich verbinden." GOETHE, "Das Gottliche. MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS AND OTHER ESSAYS BY ANDREW SETH, M.A., LL.D. (i PROFESSOR OF LOGIC AND METAPHYSICS IN THE UNIVERSITY OF EDINBURGH WILLIAM BLACKWOOD AND SONS EDINBURGH AND LONDON MDCCCXCVII 3 3 M3 76 PREFACE. THE title of this volume may seem disproportioned to its contents. A systematic discussion of "man's place in the cosmos " would obviously involve the whole range of science and of metaphysics. These essays make no pretence to be such a discussion. Nevertheless it is not unadvisedly that the title of the first paper has been extended to the volume as a whole, and thus used to indicate the general char- acter of its contents. The papers of which it is com- posed were written within the last six years, and are, in the first instance, a criticism of some of the more significant contributions to philosophy which have ap- peared during that period. They cannot, therefore, be taken as a series, in which there is a systematic progress from the earlier essays to those which follow. Vi PREFACE. But it will be found that they are all, at bottom, treat- ments of the same theme, man's relation to the forces of nature and to the absolute ground of things, or, in the words of the title, man's place in the cosmos. The books or pamphlets criticised were originally selected for criticism because of their bearing upon this funda- mental question, in which all vital interest in philoso- phy centres. And whatever the starting-point of the discussion may be, the main concern of every essay is to enforce the same view of the world and of man. That view I have described in one of the papers as humanism, in opposition to naturalism; in another reference, it might be described as ethicism, in opposi- tion to a too narrow intellectualism. Man as rational, and, in virtue of self-conscious reason, the free shaper of his own destiny, furnishes us, I contend, with our only indefeasible standard of value, and our clearest light as to the nature of the divine. He does what science, occupied only with the laws of events, and speculative metaphysics, when it surrenders itself to the exclusive guidance of the intellect, alike find un- intelligible, and are fain to pronounce impossible he acts. As Goethe puts it in a seeming paradox, Man alone achieves the impossible. But inexplicable, in a PREFACE. Vll sense, as man's personal agency is nay, the one per- petual miracle it is nevertheless our surest datum and our only clue to the mystery of existence. This position is maintained in several of the essays against the lower monism of the naturalistic systems. In the long essay entitled "A New Theory of the Absolute," it is defended against the Spinozism which permeates Mr Bradley's statement of metaphysical monism. This essay emphasises, on the one hand, the necessary limitations of human insight and, on the other hand, the validity or practical truth of our human rendering of the divine. Such a view of the cosmos must rest ultimately, I think, upon a conviction of the absolute value of the ethical life. For there is no such thing as a philosophy without assumptions. Every idealistic theory of the world has for its ultimate pre- miss a logically unsupported judgment of value a judgment which affirms an end of intrinsic worth, and accepts thereby a standard of unconditional obligation. On account of this unity of contention, the essays have been brought together, in the hope that they may serve a useful purpose. The paper on Professor Hux- ley's " Evolution and Ethics " appeared in ' Blackwood's Magazine/ three of the others in the 'Contemporary Vlll PEEFACE. Keview,' and the short paper on " The Use of the Term ' Naturalism,' " in the ' Philosophical Eeview.' To the editors and proprietors of these Keviews I am indebted for their courtesy in sanctioning this republication. The essays are republished without substantial alter- ation, but I have availed myself of the opportunity of revision, and have also reinserted a few passages which had been omitted, in order to bring the treatment within the ordinary compass of re view -articles. The second part of the essay on " The ' New ' Psychology and Automatism," though written in 1892 as an integral part of the discussion, is now printed for the first time. It gives the question a wider range, and will be found, I hope, to make the treatment more com- plete. Mechanism in physiology, " presentationism " in psychology, materialism and sheer pantheism in philosophy, may be regarded as different aspects of the same preconception the denial of the presence of a real cause at any point in the sequence of events. I desire in conclusion to express my thanks to my colleague, M. Charles Sarolea, for his kindness in read- ing the proofs and making many helpful suggestions. UNIVERSITY OF EDINBURGH, February 1897. CONTENTS, MAN S PLACE IN THE COSMOS PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN ... 1 THE PRESENT POSITION OF THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES AN INAUGURAL LECTURE, OCTOBER 1891 ... 34 THE " NEW " PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM (a) MUNSTERBERG'S ANALYSIS OF WILL ... 64 (6) KNOWLEDGE AND ACTIVITY . . . .114 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE MR BRADLEY'S ' APPEARANCE AND REALITY ' . . 129 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS . . . .226 NOTE A. THE USE OF THE TERM "NATURALISM" . . 289 NOTE B. THE LEGITIMACY OF THE ARGUMENT FROM CON- SEQUENCES . 304 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. pEOFESSOE HUXLEY'S Eomanes Lecture .on -*- " Evolution and Ethics " deservedly attracted a large amount of attention on its appearance. That attention was due not only to the importance of the subject handled and the reputation of the lecturer, but quite as much to the breadth and scope of the treatment, to the nobility of tone and the deep human feeling which characterised a singularly impressive utterance. Popular interest was also excited by the nature of the conclusion reached, which, in the mouth of the pioneer and prophet of evolution, had the air of being something like a palinode. Criticisms of the lecture appeared at the time by Mr Leslie Stephen in the ' Contemporary Eeview/ and by Mr Herbert 2 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. Spencer in a letter to the ' Athenaeum ' ; l and many discussions appeared in theological quarters. But the subject as a whole was pediaps dismissed from public attention before its significance had been exhausted, or indeed properly grasped. Professor Huxley's argu- ment and the criticisms it called forth illuminate most instructively some deep -seated ambiguities of philo- sophical terminology, and at the same time bring into sharp relief the fundamental difference of standpoint which divides philosophical thinkers. The questions at issue, moreover, are not merely speculative ; already they cast their shadow upon literature and life. The opportunity of elucidation is therefore in the best sense timely, and no apology seems needed for an attempt to recall attention to the points in dispute and to ac- centuate their significance. The outstanding feature of Professor Huxley's argu- ment is the sharp contrast drawn between nature and ethical man, and the sweeping indictment of " the cosmic process " at the bar of morality. The problem of suffering and the almost complete absence of any 1 The Eomanes Lecture was delivered on the 18th May 1893, and published shortly thereafter. Mr Spencer's letter appeared in the * Athenaeum ' of August 5, and Mr Leslie Stephen's article in the ' Con- temporary Keview ' of August 1893. The present paper was published in 'Blackwood's Magazine,' December 1893. PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 3 relation between suffering and moral desert is the theme from which he starts, and to which he con- tinually returns. " The dread problem of evil," " the moral indifference of nature," " the unfathomable in- justice of the nature of things " this is the aspect of the world which has burned itself deeply into the writer's soul, and which speaks in moving eloquence from his pages. The Buddhistic and the Stoic at- tempts to grapple with the problem are considered, and are found to end alike in absolute renunciation. " By the Tiber, as by the Ganges, ethical man admits that the cosmos is too strong for him ; and, destroying every bond which ties him to it by ascetic discipline, he seeks salvation in absolute renunciation " (p. 29). Is the antagonism, then, final and hopeless, or can modern science and philosophy offer any better re- conciliation of ethical man with the nature to which as an animal he belongs, and to whose vast uncon- scious forces he lies open on every side ? As Pro- fessor Huxley puts the question himself in his open- ing pages Is there or is there not " a sanction for morality in the ways of the cosmos " ? Man has built up " an artificial world within the cosmos " : has human society its roots and its justification in the underlying nature of the cosmos, or is it in 4 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. very truth an " artificial " world, which is at odds with that nature and must be in perpetual conflict with it ? The Stoic rule -which places virtue in " fol- lowing nature" is easily shown to be a phrase of many meanings, and to demand qualification by refer- ence, first, to the specific nature of man, and then to a higher nature or guiding faculty within the mind of man himself. But the modern ethics of evolution apparently claim to have bridged the gulf and to have made the ethical process continuous with the cosmic process of organic nature, they claim, in short, to exhibit the ethical life as only a continuation, on another plane, of the struggle for existence. If this claim is well founded, and the two worlds are really continuous, then the maxim, " Follow nature," will have been proved to be, after all, the sum and sub- stance of virtue. It is against this naturalisation of ethics that Pro- fessor Huxley protests in the strongest terms. He readily allows that the ethical evolutionists may be right in their natural history of the moral sentiments. But " as the immoral sentiments have no less been evolved, there is, so far, as much natural sanction for the one as the other. . . . Cosmic evolution may teach us how the good and the evil tendencies of man may PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 5 have come about; but, in itself, it is incompetent to furnish any better reason why what we call good is preferable to what we call evil, than we had before " (p. 31). That is to say, the origin of a belief and the validity of a belief, or the origin of a tendency and the ethical quality of that tendency, are logically two dis- tinct questions. But the evolutionist is apt to make the answer to the first do duty as an answer to the second also, because he has in reality no standard of appreciation to apply to any phenomenon except that of mere existence. " Whatever is, is right," or at all events, " Whatever is predominant, is right," is the only motto of the consistent evolutionist. This is embodied in the phrase " survival of the fittest," which is used illegitimately, as we shall see to effect the transition from the merely natural to the ethical world. In opposition to such theories, Professor Huxley con- tends that the analogies of the struggle for existence throw no light on the ethical nature of man. Cosmic nature is no school of virtue, but the headquarters of the enemy of ethical nature (p. 27). Self-assertion, the unscrupulous seizing upon all that can be grasped, the tenacious holding of all that can be kept, . . . constitute the essence of the struggle for existence. . . . For his suc- cessful progress as far as the savage state, man has been 6 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. largely indebted to those qualities which he shares with the ape and the tiger (p. 6). So far is this struggle from explaining morality that the practice of what is ethically best what we call good- ness or virtue involves a course of conduct which, in all respects, is opposed to that which leads to success in the cosmic struggle for existence. In place of ruthless self- assertion, it demands self-restraint; in place of thrusting aside, or treading down, all competitors, it requires that the individual shall not merely respect, but shall help, his fellows. ... It repudiates the gladiatorial theory of ex- istence. . . . Laws and moral precepts are directed to the end of curbing the cosmic process and reminding the individual of his duty to the community, to the protection and influence of which he owes, if not existence itself, at least the life of something better than a brutal savage. In short, "social progress means a checking of the cosmic process at every step, and the substitution for it of another which may be called the ethical process." This leads up to the characteristic call to arms with which the address concludes : " Let us understand, once for all, that the ethical progress of society depends, not on imitating the cosmic process, still less in running away from it, but in combating it" (pp. 33, 34). Such is the logical framework of the lecture. It is obvious that the important points of the treat- PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 7 merit are : (1) The emphasis laid upon the division between man and nature, which a reviewer in the ' Athenseum ' 1 called " an approximation to the Paul- ine dogma of nature and grace " : and (2) the mood of militant heroism, not untouched, however, by stoi- cal resignation, which naturally results from contem- plation of the unequal struggle between the microcosm and the macrocosm. Before proceeding to consider the consistency of Professor Huxley's argument and the ultimate ten- ability of his position, I wish to say, in regard to the first point, how timely, it seems to me, is his insistence on the gulf between man and non -human nature ; how sound is the stand he takes upon the ethical nature of man as that which is alone of sig- nificance and worth in the "transitory adjustment of contending forces," which otherwise constitutes the cosmos. Whether the breach is to be taken as abso- lute or not, it is at least apparent that if man with his virtues and vices be included simpliciter and with- out more ado in a merely natural order of facts, we inevitably tend to lose sight of that nature within na- ture which makes man what he is. The tendency so to include man has become a settled habit in much of 1 July 22, 1893. 8 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. our current literature. I need not speak of the docu- ments of so-called Naturalism, with their never-end- ing analysis of la bte Jmmaine analysis from which one would be slow to gather that any such qualities as justice, purity, or disinterested affection had ever disturbed the brutish annals of force and lust. But in other quarters, even where the picture is not so dark, the fashion still is to treat man as a natural product, not as the responsible shaper of his destiny, but, void of spiritual struggles and ideal hopes, as the unresisting channel of the impulses which sway him hither and thither, and issue now in one course of action, now in another. This literature is inartistic, even on its own terms, for, blinded by its material- istic fatalism, it does not even give us things as they are. The higher literature never forgets that man, as Pascal put it, is nobler than the universe ; and freedom (in some sense of that ambiguous term) must be held to be a postulate of true art no less than of morality. But besides being bad art, litera- ture of this sort has a subtly corrosive influence upon the ethical temper. For the power of will, as Lamen- nais said, is that in us which is most quickly used up : " Ce qui s'use le plus vite en nous, c'est la volonte." Hence the insidious force of the sugges- PROFESSOK HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 9 tion that we do not will at all, but are merely the instruments of our desires. For this is to justify, or at least to excuse, every passion on the ground of its "natural" origin. This temper of mind is found invading even more serious writers, and it is traceable ultimately to the same confusion between the laws of human conduct and the workings of nature in the irresponsible creatures of the field. M. Eenan, it will be remembered, delicately excuses himself in his ' Souvenirs ' rallies himself, as we may say on his continued practice of chastity : I continued to live in Paris as I had lived in the semi- nary. Later, I saw very well the vanity of that virtue as of all the rest. I recognised in particular that nature cares not at all whether man is chaste or not. I cannot rid my- self [he says elsewhere in the same volume] of the idea that after all it is perhaps the libertine who is right, and who practises the true philosophy of life. Many will remember, too, how Matthew Arnold took up this parable when he discoursed in America 011 the cult of the great goddess Lubricity, to which, as he said, contemporary France seemed more and more to be devoting herself. After much delicate banter and much direct plain-speaking, Mr Arnold turns upon M. Eenan and cuts to the root of the fallacy in a single sentence. " Instead of saying that 10 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. nature cares nothing about chastity, let us say that human nature, our nature, cares about it a great deal." And when we meet the same fallacy invad- ing our own literature, the same answer will suffice. I think it may be worth pointing out a notable in- stance in a novel widely read and highly praised within the last few years. Mr Hardy's ' Tess of the D'Urbervilles ' is unquestionably a powerful work, but it suffers, in my opinion, both artistically and ethically, from this tendency to assimilate the moral and the natural. To smack of the soil is in many senses a term of praise ; but even rustic men and women are not altogether products of the soil, and Mr Hardy is in danger of so regarding them. What I wish, however, to point out here is the pernicious fallacy which underlies a statement like the follow- ing. Tess, after she has fallen from her innocence, is wont to wander alone in the woods, a prey to her own reflections, "terrified without reason," says the author, by "a cloud of moral hobgoblins." It was they [he continues] that were out of harmony with the actual world, not she. Walking among the sleep- ing birds in the hedges, watching the skipping rabbits on a moonlit warren, or standing under a pheasant-laden bough, she looked upon herself as a figure of guilt intruding into the haunts of innocence. But all the while she was making PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 11 a distinction where there was no difference. Feeling her- self in antagonism, she was quite in accord. She had been made to break an accepted social law, but no law known to the environment in which she fancied herself such an anomaly. The implication of such a passage is that the "ac- cepted social law " is a mere convention, and that the deeper truth, "the actual world," is to be found in the hedgerows and the warrens. To satisfy an animal prompting without scruple or hesitation, and without the qualms of a fantastical remorse, is only to fulfil the law of nature, and to put one's self in harmony with one's surroundings. The shallow- ness of such revolt against "accepted social laws" is too apparent to need further exposure. A con- vention truly, in one sense, the moral law in ques- tion is ; but upon this convention the fabric of human society and all the sanctities of the family rest. He must be strangely blinded by a word who deems this sanction insufficient, or who would pit in such a case a " natural " impulse against a " social " law. In view of pervasive misconceptions and fallacies like these, it is eminently salutary, I repeat, to have our attention so impressively recalled by Professor Huxley to the idea of human life as an imperium OF THB UNIVERSITY 12 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. in imperio a realm which, though it rises out of nature, and remains exposed to the shock of natural forces, requires for its laws no foreign sanction, but bases them solely on the perfection of human nature itself. For, even though Professor Huxley's way of stating the opposition should prove ultimately unten- able, the breach between ethical man and pre-human nature constitutes without exception the most im- portant fact which the universe has to show ; and for a true understanding of the world it is far more vital to grasp the significance of this breach than to be misled by a cheap desire for unity and system into minimising, or even denying, the fact. It is time, however, to examine Professor Huxley's position and arguments more closely. His critics have not been slow to remark upon the ambiguity lurking in the phrase " cosmic process," which occurs so often throughout the lecture, in antithesis to the ethical process to the moral and social life of man. And they point with one accord to Note 19 as containing, in effect, a retractation of his own doctrine by Professor Huxley himself. " Of course, strictly speaking," we read in the note, " social life and the ethical process, in virtue of which it advances towards perfection, are part and parcel of the general process of evolution." As Mr PEOFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 13 Spencer pointedly asks, " If the ethical man is not a product of the cosmic process, what is he a product of ? " Or as Shakespeare expressed it in the often- quoted lines " Nature is made better by no means But nature makes that means : so, o'er that art, Which you say adds to nature, is an art That nature makes." If the cosmic process be understood in the full latitude of the phrase, this is, indeed, so obvious, and the critic's victory so easy, that it is hard to believe Professor Huxley's position rests altogether on a foundation so weak. The term " nature," and still more an expres- sion like " the cosmic process," may be taken in an all- inclusive sense as equivalent to the universe as a whole or the nature of things ; and if so, it is obvious that human nature with its ethical characteristics is em- braced within the larger whole. The unity of the cosmos in some sense is not so much a conclusion to be proved as an inevitable assumption. Professor Huxley apparently denies this unity in the text of his lecture, and is naturally obliged to reassert it in his note. This constitutes the weakness of his position. The part must be somehow included in the process of the whole ; there is no extra-cosmic source from which 14 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. a revolt against the principles of the cosmos could draw inspiration or support. Now the strength of the evolutionary theory of ethics lies in its frank recognition of the unity of the cosmos ; and in this it is, so far, at one with the philosophical doctrine of Idealism to which it is otherwise so much opposed the doctrine which finds the ultimate reality of the universe in mind or spirit, and its End in the perfecting of spiritual life. But each of these theories exhibits the unity of the world in its own way. The way taken by the ethical evolutionists is to naturalise morality, to assimilate ethical experience to nature, in the lower or narrower sense in which it is used to denote all that happens in the known world except the responsible activities of human beings. And it is against this removing of landmarks that Professor Huxley, rightly, as it seems to me, protests. For though Mr Spencer and Mr Leslie Stephen may be technically in the right, inasmuch as human nature is unquestionably part of the nature of things, it is the inherent tendency of their theories to substitute for this wider nature the laws and processes of that narrower, non-human world, to which the term nature is on the whole restricted by current usage. This tendency is inherent in every system which PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 15 takes as its sole principle of explanation the carrying back of facts or events to their antecedent conditions. And, as it happens, this is explicitly formulated by Mr Stephen, in his article in the ' Contemporary Eeview,' as the only permissible meaning of explanation : " To 'explain' a fact is to assign its causes that is, give the preceding set of facts out of which it arose." But surely, I may be asked, you do not intend to challenge a principle which underlies all scientific procedure, and which may even claim to be self-evident ? I certainly do not propose to deny the formal correctness of the principle, but I maintain most strongly that the cur- rent application of it covers a subtle and very serious fallacy, for the true nature of the cause only becomes apparent in the effect. Now, if we explain a fact by giving " the preceding set of facts out of which it arose," we practically resolve the fact into these ante- cedents that is to say, we identify it with them. When we are dealing with some limited sphere of phenomena, within which the facts are all of one order say, the laws of moving bodies as treated in mechanics there may be no practical disadvantage from this limited in- terpretation of causation. But when we pass from one order of facts to another say, from the inorganic to the organic, or, still more, from animal life to the self- 16 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. conscious life of man the inadequacy of such explana- tion stares us in the face. For " the preceding set of facts," which we treat as the cause or sufficient explan- ation of the phenomenon in question, is ex hypothesi different from the phenomenon it is said to explain ; and the difference is, that it consists of simpler ele- ments. To explain, according to this view, is to reduce to simpler conditions. But if the elements are really simpler, there is the fact of their combination into a more complex product to be explained, and the fact of their combination in such a way as to produce precisely the result in question. And if we choose to take the antecedent conditions, as they appear in themselves, apart from the all-important circumstance of the pro- duction of this effect, we have, no doubt, a " preceding set of facts/' but we certainly have not, in any true sense, the cause of the phenomenon. We have elimi- nated the very characteristic we set out to explain namely, the difference of the new phenomenon from the antecedents out of which it appears to have been evolved. Hence it is that, in the sense indicated, all explanation of the higher by the lower is philosophically a hysteron proteron. The antecedents assigned are not the causes of the consequents ; for by antecedents the naturalistic theories mean the antecedents in abstraction PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 17 from their consequents the antecedents taken as they appear in themselves, or as we might suppose them to be if no such consequents had ever issued from them. So conceived, however, the antecedents (matter and energy, for example) have no real existence they are mere entia rationis, abstract aspects of the one concrete fact which we call the universe. The true nature of the antecedents is only learned by reference to the consequents which follow ; or, as I put it before, the true nature of the cause only becomes apparent in the effect. All ultimate or philosophical explanation must look to the end. Hence the futility of all attempts to explain human life in terms of the merely animal, to explain life in terms of the inor- ganic, and ultimately to find a sufficient formula for the cosmic process in terms of the redistribution of matter and motion. If we are in earnest with the doctrine that the universe is one, we have to read back the nature of the latest consequent into the remotest antecedent. Only then is the one, in any true sense, the cause of the other. Applying this to the present question, we may say that, just as within the limits of the organic world there may be exhibited an intelligible evolution of living forms, so within the moral world we may B 18 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. certainly have an evolution of the moral sentiments and of the institutions which subserve ethical conduct. But as, in the one case, we must start with the fact of life that is to say, with the characteristic ways of behaving which are found in living matter and which are not found in dead matter so, in the other case, we must carry with us from the outset the charac- teristics or postulates of moral experience namely, self-consciousness, with the sense of responsibility, and the capacity for sympathy which is based on the ability to represent to one's self the life and feelings of another. Such an evolution within the moral sphere does not justify us in presenting morality as an " evolu- tion " from non-moral conditions that is, in resolving morality into non-moral elements. And this Mr Leslie Stephen seems to admit in an important passage of the article already referred to. " Morality proper," he says, " begins when sympathy begins ; when we really desire the happiness of others, or, as Kant says, when we treat other men as an end, and not simply as a means. Undoubtedly this involves a new principle no less than the essential principle of all true morality." I cannot but regard this as an important admission, but at the same time I am bound to say that, till I met this unexpected sentence of Mr Stephen's, I had supposed PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 19 that the admission of " a new principle " was precisely what the evolutionists were, of all things, most anxious to avoid. It seems to me, therefore, that though Professor Huxley may have put himself technically in the wrong by speaking of " the cosmical process," his contention is far from being so inept as a verbal criticism would make it appear. It is really directed against the sub- mergence of ethical man in the processes of non-ethical and non-human nature ; and if any justification is to be sought for the use of the phrase, we may find it in the tendency inherent in the evolutionary method of explanation the tendency already explained to sub- stantiate antecedents in abstraction from their conse- quents, and thus practically to identify the cosmos with its lowest aspects. If the evolutionists do not make this identification in their own minds, they are at least singularly successful in producing that impres- sion upon their readers. On another important point connected with, and indeed involved in, the foregoing, Professor Huxley, by an unguarded statement, laid himself open to a pretty obvious and apparently conclusive rejoinder. "The cosmic process," he says in one place, "has no sort of relation to moral ends." But " the moral indif- 20 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. ference of nature," even in the restricted sense of the term, cannot be maintained so absolutely. Nature undoubtedly puts a premium upon certain virtues, and punishes certain modes of excess and defect by decrease of vitality and positive pain. As Mr Stephen says : " That chastity, temperance, truthfulness, and energy are on the whole advantages both to the individual and the race does not, I fancy, require elaborate proof, nor need I argue at length that the races in which they are common will therefore have inevitable advantages in the struggle for existence." But if so, then it would seem that cosmic nature is not, as it was represented, "the headquarters of the enemy of ethical nature " ; to a certain extent it may even be regarded as a " school of virtue." The sphere, however, in which this holds true is a comparatively limited one, being substantially restricted to temper- ance, in the Greek sense of the word that is to say, moderation in the indulgence of the animal appetites, to which may, no doubt, be added, with Mr Stephen, energy. But nature, as distinct from that human nature which organises itself into societies and adds its own sanctions to the moral ideal which it is con- tinually widening and deepening non-human nature seems to have no sanctions even for such fundamental PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 21 virtues as truthfulness, justice, and beneficence, still less for the finer shades and higher nobilities of char- acter in which human nature flowers. And even in regard to the list of virtues cited, it might be argued that cosmic nature sanctions and furthers them only when we deliberately restrict our survey to the present stage of the evolutionary process the stage during which man has grown to be what he is on this planet. Within this limited period nature, through the struggle for existence, may be said to have favoured the evolu- tion of the morally best. But it is no intrinsic quality of the struggle to produce this result. Here, it appears to me, we strike upon the deeper truth which prompted Professor Huxley's somewhat unguarded statement, and we are under an important obligation to him for the exposure of what he appropriately calls " the fallacy of the fittest." Fittest [he writes] has a connotation of " best " ; and about best there hangs a moral flavour. In cosmic nature, however, what is "fittest" depends upon the conditions. Long since, I ventured to point out that if our hemisphere were to cool again, the survival of the fittest might bring about, in the vegetable kingdom, a population of more and more stunted and humbler and humbler organisms, until the "fittest" that survived might be nothing but lichens, diatoms, and such microscopic organisms as those which give red snow its colour; while, if it became hotter, the 22 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. pleasant valleys of the Thames and Isis might be unin- habitable by any animated beings save those that nourish in a tropical jungle. They,- as the fittest, the best adapted to the changed conditions, would survive (p. 32). Mr Spencer has been forward to emphasise his agree- ment with this position, and has recalled attention to an essay of his own, twenty years old. in which he makes the same distinction: The law is not the survival of the "better" or the " stronger," if we give to these words anything like their ordinary meanings. It is the survival of those which are constitutionally fittest to thrive under the conditions in which they are placed ; and very often that which, humanly speaking, is inferiority, causes the survival. Superiority, whether in size, strength, activity, or sagacity, is, other things equal, at the cost of diminished fertility ; and where the life led by a species does not demand these higher attributes, the species profits by decrease of them, and accompanying increase of fertility. This is the reason why there occur so many cases of retrograde metamorphosis. . . . When it is remembered that these cases outnumber all others, it will be seen that the expression " survivorship of the better " is wholly inappropriate. 1 Out of the mouth of two such witnesses this point may be taken as established. But if so, I entirely fail to see where, on naturalistic principles, we get our standard of higher and lower, of better and worse. 1 Essays, vol. i. p. 379, " Mr Martineau on Evolution." PKOFESSOK HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 23 If changed conditions of life were to lead to the de- humanising of the race, to the dropping one by one of the ethical qualities which we are accustomed to commend, whence the justification for pronouncing this process a " retrograde metamorphosis " ? There can be no other sense of better or worse, on the theory, than more or less successful adaptation to the con- ditions of the environment, and what survives is best just because it survives. The latest stage of the process must necessarily, therefore, be better than all that went before, from the mere fact that it has maintained itself. Mere existence is the only test we have to apply, and at every stage it would seem that we are bound to say, Whatever is, is right. But this is tantamount to saying that, when the theory of evolution is taken in its widest scope, it is not really legitimate to say that nature abets or sanctions morality; since the result of further evolution or, to speak more properly, of further cosmical changes might be to dethrone our present ethical conduct from its temporary position as the fittest, and to leave no scope for what we now regard as virtue. The k type of conduct which would then succeed, and which would so far have the sanction of nature on its side, we should be con- strained, it seems to me, to pronounce superior to 24 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. the conduct which, from our present point of view, seems to us better ; because the latter, if adopted, would in the altered circumstances set us at variance with our surroundings, and so fail. Failure or success in the struggle for existence must, on the theory, be the sole moral standard. Good is what survives ; evil is what once was fittest, but is so no longer. Thus, our present good may become nay, is inevitably be- coming evil, and that not, as might be contended, in the sense of merging in a higher good. We have no guarantee that the movement of change, miscalled evolution, must continue in the line of past progress : it may gradually, and as it were imperceptibly, assume another direction a direction which our present moral ideas would condemn as retrograde. Yet, none the less, the mere fact of change would be sufficient to convert our present good into evil. Such, I must insist, is the only logical position of a naturalistic ethics. But an important outcome of the recent discussion has been to show that the most prominent upholders of the theory do not hold it in its logical form. Mr Spencer, as we have seen, has strongly insisted that survival of the fittest does not mean survival of the better, or even of the stronger ; and Mr Stephen tells us that the struggle for existence, PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 25 instead of being the explanation of morality, " belongs to an underlying order of facts to which moral epithets cannot properly be applied. It denotes a condition of which the moralist has to take account, and to which morality has to be adapted, but which, just because it is a ' cosmic process/ cannot be altered, however much we may alter the conduct which it dictates." Surely this comes very near to admitting Professor Huxley's contention, that our moral standard is not derived from the struggle for existence, but rather implies its reversal, substituting for selfishness sympathy for others, and, in Mr Stephen's own words, "the sense of duty which each man owes to society at large." Mr Spencer speaks of an " ethical check " upon the struggle for existence: it is our duty, he says, " to mitigate the evils " which it entails in the social state. " The use of morality," says Mr Stephen, "is to humanise the struggle, to minimise the suffer- ings of those who lose the game, and to offer the prizes to the qualities which are advantageous to all, rather than to those which serve to intensify the bitterness of the conflict." But this is neither more nor less than to say that, as soon as man becomes social and moral, he has to act counter to the leading characteristics of the struggle for existence. He becomes animated by 26 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. other ideals, or, to speak more strictly, he then first be- comes capable of an ideal, of a sense of duty, instead of obeying without question- the routine of animal impulse. But if this is so, I still ask the evolutionist who has no other basis than the struggle for existence, how he accounts for the intrusion of these moral ideas and standards which presume to interfere with the cosmic process, and sit in judgment upon its results ? This question cannot be answered so long as we regard morality merely as an incidental result, a by-product, as it were, of the cosmical system. It is impossible on such a hypothesis to understand the magisterial assertion by itself of the part against the whole, its demands upon the universe, its unwavering condem- nation of the universe, if these demands are not met by the nature of things. All this would be an in- congruous, and even a ludicrous, spectacle if we had here to do with a natural phenomenon like any other. The moral and spiritual life remains, in short, unin- telligible, unless on the supposition that it is in reality the key to the world's meaning, the fact in the light of which all other phenomena must be read. We must be in earnest, I have already said, with the unity of the world, but we must not forget that, if regarded merely as a system of forces, the world possesses no such PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 27 unity. It acquires it only when regarded in the light of an End of absolute worth or value which is realised or attained in it. Such an End-in-itself, as Kant called it, we find only in the self-conscious life of man, in the world of Truth, Beauty, and Goodness which he builds up for himself, and of which he constitutes himself a citizen. If it were possible to consider the system of physical nature apart from the intelligent activities and emotions of rational beings, those worlds on worlds, " Rolling ever From creation to decay," would possess in themselves no spark of the value, the intrinsic worth, which we unhesitatingly assert to belong, at least in possibility, to the meanest human life. The endless redistribution of matter and motion in stupendous cycles of evolution and dissolution would be a world without any justification to offer for its existence a world which might just as well not have been. 1 But if we are honest with ourselves, I do not 1 Without encumbering the main argument by inopportune discus- sion; one may perhaps ask in a note in what sense even existence could be attributed to a system of unconscious forces a material world per se. We cannot perform the abstraction required of us in conceiving such a system. Nature refuses to be divorced from the thoughts and feelings of her children and her lords, and we need not be subjective idealists to hold the literal truth of ,the poet's words that " in our life alone does Nature live." 28 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. think we can embrace the conclusion that the cosmos is a mere brute fact of this description. The demand for an End-in-itself that is, for a fact of such a nature that its existence justifies itself is as much a necessity of reason as the necessity which impels us to refund any phenomenon into its antecedent con- ditions. And further, unless we sophisticate ourselves, we cannot doubt that we possess within ourselves in our moral experience most conspicuously an in- stance and a standard of what we mean by such intrinsic value. As Carlyle has put it in one of his finest passages, What, then, is man ! What, then, is man ! He endures but for an hour, and is crushed before the moth. Yet in the being and in the working of a faithful man is there already (as all faith, from the beginning, gives assurance) a something that pertains not to this wild death-element of Time ; that triumphs over Time, and is, and will be, when Time shall be no more. This conviction of the infinite significance and value of the ethical life is the only view-point from which, in Professor Huxley's words, we can " make existence intelligible and bring the order of things into harmony with the moral sense of man." And it is impossible to do the one of these things without the other. To understand the world is not merely to unravel the PEOFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 29 sequence of an intricate set of facts. So long as we cannot " bring the order of things into harmony with the moral sense of man," we cannot truly be said to have made existence intelligible: the world still re- mains for us, in Hume's words, " a riddle, an enigma, an inexplicable mystery." What, then, is Professor Huxley's final attitude? The lecture breathes throughout the loftiest temper of ethical idealism. It is the writer's keen sense of the superiority of ethical man to non-ethical nature that prompts him to pit Pascal's "thinking reed" in unequal struggle against the cosmic forces that en- velop him; and the noble words at the close stir the spirit by their impressive insistence on the imperish- able worth of human effort inspired by duty. Yet this unflinching conviction does not lead Professor Huxley to what seems the legitimate conclusion from it namely, that here only, in the life of ethical en- deavour, is the end and secret of the universe to be found. It serves but to accentuate the stern pathos of his view of human fate. His ultimate attitude is, theoretically, one of Agnosticism; personally and practically, one of Stoical heroism. Substantially the same attitude, it appears to me, is exemplified in the Pieligion of Humanity the same despair, I mean, of 30 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. harmonising human ideals with the course of the universe. The Religion of Humanity rightly finds in man alone any qualities which call for adoration or worship ; but it inconsistently supposes man to de- velop these qualities in a fundamentally non-ethical cosmos, and so fails to furnish a solution that can be accounted either metaphysically satisfying or ethically supporting. But we must bear in mind, I repeat, the principle of the unity of the world. The attitude of the -Agnostic and the Positivist is due to the separa- tion which they unconsciously insist on keeping up between nature and man. The temptation to do so is intelligible, for we have found that nature, taken in philosophical language as a thing in itself nature conceived as an independent system of causes cannot explain the ethical life of man, and we rightly refuse to blur and distort the characteristic features of moral experience by submerging it in the merely natural. We easily, therefore, continue to think of the system of natural causes as a world going its own way, ex- isting quite independently of the ethical beings who draw their breath within it. Man with his ideal standards and his infinite aspirations appears conse- quently upon the scene as an alien without rights in a world that knows him not. His life is an unex- PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 31 plained intrusion in a world organised on other prin- ciples, and no way adapted as a habitation for so disturbing and pretentious a guest. And the conse- quence is that he dashes his spirit against the steep crags of necessity, finds his ideals thwarted, his aspira- tions mocked, his tenderest affections turned to instru- ments of agony, and is driven, if not into passionate revolt or nerveless despair, then at best into stoical resolve. Some such mood as this appears also in much of Matthew Arnold's poetry, and is to my mind the explanation of its insistent note of sadness. " No, we are strangers here, the world is from of old, . . . To tunes we did not call, our being must keep chime." It is powerfully expressed in the famous monologue or chant in " Empedocles on Etna," with its deliberate renunciation of what the poet deems man's " boundless hopes " and " intemperate prayers." It inspires the fine lines to Fausta on " Eesignation," and reappears more incidentally in all his verse. But calm, as he himself reminds us, is not life's crown, though calm is well ; and the poet's " calm lucidity of soul " covers in this case the baffled retreat of the thinker. We have, in truth, no right to suppose an independent non-spiritual world on which human experience is in- 32 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. congruously superinduced. If we are really in earnest, at once with the unity -of the world and with the necessity of an intrinsically worthy end by reference to which existence may be explained, we must take our courage in both hands and carry our convictions to their legitimate conclusion. We must conclude that the end which we recognise as alone worthy of attain- ment is also the end of existence as such the open secret of the universe. No man writes more pessi- mistically than Kant of man's relation to the course of nature, so long as man is regarded merely as a sentient creature, susceptible to pleasure and pain. But man, as the subject of duty, and the heir of immortal hopes, is restored by Kant to that central position in the universe from which, as a merely physical being, Copernicus had degraded him. To a certain extent this conclusion must remain a conviction rather than a demonstration, for we cannot emerge altogether from the obscurities of our middle state, and there is much that may rightly disquiet and perplex our minds. But if it is in the needs of the moral life that we find our deepest principle of explanation, then it may be argued with some reason that this belongs to the nature of the case; for a scientific demonstration would not serve the purposes PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 33 of that life. The truly good man must choose good- ness on its own account ; he must be ready to serve God for naught, without being invaded by M. Eenan's doubts. As it has been finely put, he must possess "that rude old Norse nobility of soul, which saw virtue and vice alike go unrewarded, and was yet not shaken in its faith." l This old Norse nobility speaks to us again, in accents of the nineteenth century, in Professor Huxley's lecture. But because such is the temper of true virtue, it by no means follows that such virtue will not be rewarded with "the wages of going on, and not to die." 1 K. L. Stevenson, Preface to 'Familiar Studies of Men and Books.' THE PRESENT POSITION OF THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 1 "VTOU will not find it wonderful if my feelings are deeply stirred in appearing before you to-day for the first time in my new capacity. There is no honour 1 An Inaugural Lecture on assuming the duties of the Chair of Logic and Metaphysics in the University of Edinburgh, October 26, 1891. The Lecture is printed exactly as it was delivered, and the nature of the occasion will perhaps be held to excuse the personal references with which it opens. The general survey of the philosophical field which it undertakes, and the philosophical point of view indicated in the concluding pages, seem to give it a useful place in the present vol- ume. But to prevent misconception, it may be well to append here the Prefatory Note which accompanied it on its original appearance : " The title of this Lecture may seem to promise too much. The Lec- ture does not profess to deal with the circle of the philosophical sciences, but only with the subjects traditionally associated with a Chair of Logic and Metaphysics in Scotland. Moreover, as the occasion demanded, it is addressed not so much to the expert as to the large general public interested in philosophy." PRESENT POSITION OF THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 35 or privilege which I could possibly esteem higher than to teach philosophy in my own alma mater, and in the capital of my native land to teach, moreover, in the Chair which, through the lustre of its occupants for half a century, is, in the mind of the country (I think I may say it without offence) in some respects the most famous of Scottish philosophical Chairs. All this is ^deeply gratifying. But it also lays a heavy responsi- bility upon him who succeeds to such great traditions. He who did not feel diffident at stepping into the place of these eminent men would be unworthy of the trust committed to him. I am deeply sensible of my own deficiencies, but I hope, if it is granted me, to live and learn. It is also a very gratifying experience to join as a colleague those who were the guides of one's youth. All are not here ; but of the seven Professors of the Arts curriculum in my time only two have been re- moved by death. One, the genial and universally beloved Kelland, passed away in the ripeness of his years. The other leaves an untimely gap, which speaks of recent loss and a common sorrow. One whose welcome to-day would have sounded with peculiar pleasantness in my ears, the generous and high-souled Sellar, has gone from us too soon; and 36 THE PRESENT POSITION OF to those who knew him, his loss seems not less but greater as the days go by. All the more is it matter of heartfelt satisfaction to me that no such painful gap exists in connection with my own Chair that I succeed my honoured and be- loved teacher while he is yet among us in full health and in the unimpaired vigour of his powers. Long may he live to counsel us wisely and inspire us by his example, and to embody in literary form the ripe results of a life's reflection. In these circumstances, and in his presence, it is not for me to pronounce any eulogy upon his thirty-five years of strenuous and fruitful work in this university, or to attempt to sum up his happily unfinished achievement. But I will at least record a little of what I personally owe to him. He taught me to think ; and in the things of the mind that is the greatest gift for which one man can be in- debted to another. Seventeen years ago I entered the Junior Logic class of this university, with a mind opening perhaps to literature, but still substantially with a schoolboy's views of existence ; and there, in the admirably stimulating lectures to which I listened, a new world seemed to open before me. What the student most needs at such a period is to be intellectu- ally awakened. The crust of custom has to be broken, THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 37 and the sense of wonder and mystery stirred within him. He should not be crammed with ready-made solutions of difficulties he has never been made to feel. Eather should he be sent "voyaging through strange seas of thought alone." He has to be induced to ask himself the world-old questions, and to ponder the possible answers. Above all, the listener should be made to feel that the questions of which the Professor speaks are not merely information which he communi- cates that they are to him the most real things in the world, the recurring subjects of his deepest meditation. All this his students found realised in Professor Eraser's teaching. His sympathetic exposition enabled us to catch the spirit of the most diverse systems, while his searching criticism prevented us from resting in any of those facile solutions which owe their simplicity to the convenient elimination of intractable elements. The sense of mystery and complexity in things, which he brought so vividly home to us, inspired a wise dis- trust of extreme positions and of systems all too perfect for our mortal vision. This union of dialectical subtlety with a never-failing reverence for all that makes man man, and elevates him above himself, lives in the memory of many a pupil as no unworthy realisation of the ideal spirit of philosophy. I shall count myself 38 THE PRESENT POSITION OF happy if, with his mantle, some portion of his spirit shall be found to have descended upon his successor. I hope that, in the days to come, the dingy but famous class-room will be distinguished as of old by searching intellectual criticism and impartial debate, not divorced from that spirit of reverence and humility which alone can lead us into truth. That reminds me that you will expect to hear from a new Professor some indication of the view he takes of his subject, and of the present outlook in connection with it. Anything that can be said on an occasion like the present must necessarily be of a very general char- acter, but even so it may have a certain interest and usefulness. The discipline of the Chair, then, seems to me to be of a threefold character logical, psychological, and metaphysical or philosophical in the strict sense. That is to say, we study, in the first place, the nature of the reasoning process, or, to be more accurate, the nature of proof or evidence the conditions to which valid reasoning must conform. In the second place, we study, introspectively and otherwise, the pheno- mena of consciousness. We bring observation and experiment to bear upon those internal facts which are THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 39 for each of us the only facts immediately present to us, the facts through which we know all other facts. We try to analyse and lay bare the inmost nature of those functions of knowing, feeling, and willing which lie " closer to us than breathing, nearer than hands or feet," which constitute, in fact, our very life, the ex- pression of the self in time. In the third place, we study, under the title of philosophy proper, the two- fold question of Knowing and Being. On the one hand, we investigate human knowledge as to its con- stitutive notions and its scope or validity ; we discuss the question of the possibility of knowledge, as it is called, or the relation of knowledge to reality. This is what is termed Epistemology or Theory of Knowledge. On the other hand, so far as the discussion has not been already anticipated, we approach those questions as to the ultimate nature, the origin and destiny, of all that is, which have occupied the speculative intellect of mankind from the dawn of history, and will occupy it till its close. These may be embraced under the special title of Metaphysics, both Epistemology and Metaphysics falling under the wider designation of Philosophy. These three lines of training the logical, the psycho- logical, and the philosophical are cognate, and the 40 THE PRESENT POSITION OF first two are in a measure introductory or propaedeutic to the third. Both logic and psychology, at all events, if we go beneath the surface, lead us into the very heart of philosophical difficulties ; and most treatments of either subject involve a tissue of metaphysical as- sumptions, of which the writer is, in all probability, either quite unconscious or only half aware. But though the subjects are thus cognate and continuous, and so fitly combined under one Chair, the discipline they afford has in each case a character of its own. Logic gives a training almost purely abstract or formal, comparable in some respects with the mental discipline of mathematics a training in clearness of thinking, in accuracy of definition, in appreciation of what is meant by demonstration or proof. Psychology brings us face to face with a concrete subject-matter the actual facts of mental life. It views these facts, partly in them- selves, but largely in their connection with material con- ditions and accompaniments. So far as it approaches these facts by the ordinary methods of observation and experiment, classifying them and endeavour- ing to resolve complex phenomena into their simplest constituents or causes, so far it affords a scientific discipline comparable to that gained, say, in the study of one of the natural sciences. And if it often lacks THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 41 the exactness of the sciences of external nature, it has the advantage, as compared with them, of cultivating fresh powers of mind through the attitude of " reflec- tion" or introspection which it is forced to take up. Self-observation or introspection is by no means so easy as the observation of a foreign object. We can more easily analyse a substance in a phial before us than we can analyse the exact nature of what passes at any moment in our own mind. Hence Psychology, which incessantly calls for the exercise of this faculty, and sharpens and perfects it by constant use, was justly praised by Hamilton as one of the best gymnastics of the mind. Philosophy carries us into a more difficult region; for here we deal not with any particular de- partment of fact, but with the ultimate principles of knowledge and the ultimate constitution or meaning of the cosmos as such, including the prior question whether we are justified in speaking of a cosmos or orderly unity at all. These are questions of supreme and intimate concern to us all, seeing that they embrace the question of man's place and destiny in relation to the system of things. He to whom they have no voice must be either less or more than man. And I fail to see how any one can lay claim to a liberal education who is ignorant of what has been thought by the great 42 THE PRESENT POSITION OF minds of the past upon these subjects, or who is un- acquainted with the elements of the problems as they face us to-day. The rudiments of such a knowledge are necessary, were it for nothing else, to enable any one to take an intelligent part in the incessant discus- sion and conflict of opinion which is so marked a feature of the present time. This threefold discipline may be justified, therefore, in a liberal curriculum, whether we look at it, from the formal side, as a discipline of mental powers otherwise untrained as the cultivation of one whole side of human nature or, on the concrete side, as a communi- cation of knowledge of singular importance and inter- est. And its permanent value seems to me so high and unimpeachable, in both these respects, that it needs no defence at my hands. A defence is generally a con- fession of weakness. In offering such for philosophy, " we do it wrong, being so majestical." I turn, therefore, by preference, to say a little about the present outlook in the three departments to which reference has been made, and the way in which it seems to me that a philosophical Professor should shape his work at the present time. Logic I will pass over lightly almost with a word because, of the three, its discussions are most technical in character. THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 43 It appeals, therefore, least to a general audience. More- over, if we penetrate beneath the surface and examine the foundations on which it rests, we are immediately involved in difficult questions of general philosophy; and it becomes impossible to maintain a rigid distinc- tion between Logic and Epistemology and Metaphysics. For that reason the very conception or definition of the science has long been matter of keen debate, and at present the aspect of things is confessedly chaotic. The activity, however, in the higher theory of logic has of late been great both in this country and in Germany. I need only refer to the important treatises of Lotze, Sigwart, and Wundt in Germany, and of Bradley and Bosanquet in this country, not to speak of the more distinctively English work of Jevons, Venn, and others. The chaos, moreover, if at first bewildering, is not of the kind which should be disheartening to the serious student. It is of the kind which portends and accompanies growth, and bears in it the promise of future order. Evidently, however, such discus- sions do not lend themselves to exoteric exposition; they belong to the labours of an advanced class of metaphysics. The other aspect of Logic is the elementary doctrine which has so long formed part of the curriculum of 44 THE PRESENT POSITION OF educated Europe the ordinary formal logic, originally based upon Aristotle, to- which has come to be added some discussion of the theory of scientific method and the conditions of inductive proof. It has been the fashion of late with many philosophers to sneer at the logic of the schools ; but this is only justifiable, as it seems to me, when extravagant claims are made on its behalf. No doubt the ordinary logic depends on many uncriticised assumptions; its analysis of the process of thought is often superficial ; it cannot stand as a coherent philosophical doctrine. All this is granted. The whole discipline is essentially of an elementary and propaedeutic character ; it is a continuation, in a more abstract form, of the grammatical training re- ceived at school. But just this circumstance, that it continues and attaches itself to the studies of the school, gives it a peculiar claim to stand as the gate- way of the philosophical sciences ; whilst, on the other hand, the very defects and ambiguities which dis- cussion reveals in many of its conceptions form an excellent stimulus to the opening mind, and introduce the student insensibly to important psychological and metaphysical problems. The formal mechanism may certainly, in great part, be relegated with advantage to text-book work and tutorial instruction. But even THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 45 this is not to be despised ; I have always found it an admirable test in picking out the really clear-headed members of a class. Here there are no cloudy phrases in which to take refuge ; the issue is as clear and defi- nite as in a mathematical proposition, and inaccuracy of mind is tracked remorselessly down. In view of these merits, which the study undoubtedly possesses, I can- not share the contempt frequently expressed for the logic of the schools. Its names and distinctions, more- over, have entered so largely into the thought, and even the familiar language, of the civilised races, that a certain acquaintance with its forms and processes may well be demanded in the interests of historical culture. It is not so long since a somewhat similar contempt for Psychology was current in the leading idealistic school of this country. The horror of the true-blue experientialist for what he calls " metaphysics " was amply repaid by the tone of condescension and in- difference which the idealists adopted towards "em- pirical psychology." Misled by a name, they visited upon the head of an unoffending science the inade- quacies of Empiricism as a philosophical theory. Be- cause the chief cultivators of psychology in England had been of the Empiricist persuasion, and had fre- 46 THE PRESENT POSITION OF quently confounded the limits of psychology and meta- physics, the transcendentalists tabooed the science as beneath the notice of a philosopher. Hence a state of unnatural division and mutual distrust a distrust rooted in both cases largely in ignorance. To-day the situation is greatly changed. Psychology has become more scientific, and has thereby become more con- scious of her own aims, and, at the same time, of her necessary limitations. Ceasing to put herself forward as philosophy, she has entered upon a new period of development as science ; and in doing so she has disarmed the jealousy, and is even fast con- quering the indifference, of the transcendental philo- sopher. For whatever be the bearing of these psychological investigations upon philosophy be their importance in that connection great, or be it small it is at least certain that in the near future no philosopher will speak with authority, or will deserve so to speak, who does not show a competent acquaintance with the best work in psychology. The marvellous activity displayed just at present in the department of psychology constitutes, indeed, to an expert perhaps the most notable feature in the state of the philosophical sciences. In Germany and France, in America, and now in England, there may THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 47 almost be said to be a " boom " in that direction. In Britain the study of psychology is a native growth, and it had long flourished in the hands of the Associationists, such as Hartley, James and John Mill, and Professor Bain. But before such a school was heard of by name, the works of Hobbes, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume had brilliantly exemplified the national genius in that direction. As already indi- cated, however, the British thinkers of the past were far from keeping their psychology unadulterated. Betraying frequently an insular ignorance of the great metaphysical systems of ancient Greece and modern Europe, they gave us, in general, psychology and philosophy inextricably intermingled. The im- pulse towards a differentiation of provinces came from Germany, where the clearer formulation of aims and methods may be regarded as one beneficial result of the training which the German intellect has enjoyed at the hands of Kant and succeeding thinkers. But the influence of Germany upon psy- chological investigation has not been limited to this formal or methodic stimulus. There has been much good work done there in psychology since the time of Kant. The psychology of Herbart and his fol- lowers is in many respects the more elaborate counter- 48 THE PRESENT POSITION OF part of English Associationism ; and artificial as his constructions often seem,^ it is acute and able work, which no modern student of the subject can afford to neglect. The names of Lotze and Wundt repre- sent work at once brilliant and patient on independent lines, and bring before us also the close connection between psychology and physiology, which is the distinguishing mark of most recent investigation in this department. Some of Lotze's most characteristic work was contained in the book he called 'Medical Psychology ; ' and ' Physiological Psychology ' is the name Wundt gives to his important treatise. Psy- chology, physiology, and physics meet in the great works of Helmholtz on ' Sensations of Tone ' and ' Physiological Optics.' Another mark of recent in- vestigation is the potent influence exerted on psy- chology, as on all other departments of knowledge, by the conception of evolution. Wherever life is met with, there the psychologist now finds material for illustrating and enlarging his science. The old meaning of ^f%?) has been revived, and the begin- nings of a comparative psychology have come into being. The observation of abnormal mental develop- ments, such as insanity, hysteria, the hypnotic state, and similar phenomena, forms another field assiduously THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 49 cultivated by modern observers, especially in France, where, no less than in Germany and America, there is a large amount of psychological activity among the younger men. All these influences may be said to meet and come to fruition in the best English work of the last few years such work, I mean, as Mr Ward's masterly treatise in the ' Encyclopaedia Britannica,' and the rich and stimulating volumes published a year ago 1 by Professor James of Harvard. Such work may not unreasonably be taken as marking the new departure that has been achieved in psychology the critical maintenance of a purely psychological standpoint, the wider range of material, the more minute and experimental analysis. For one of the most striking results of the rap- prochement between psychology and physiology just referred to has been the attempt to introduce experi- ment into psychological science. Starting from the experiments of Weber and the more extended psycho- physical researches of Fechner, but taking a wider scope, there has sprung up a new line of inquiry, which, under the name of Experimental Psychology, sometimes aspires to the dignity of a separate dis- 1 In 1890. D 50 THE PRESENT POSITION OF cipline, and looks back with no little condescension upon the observational and descriptive science with which we are familiar. Wundt has been the leader of this movement, and Leipzig its great centre; but it is now widely spread in Germany, and has been enthusiastically taken up in America, where every well- equipped college aims at the establishment of a psychological or psycho-physical laboratory. England shows some disposition to follow in the wake. At least the University of Cambridge has voted a small sum for the same purpose, and the younger generation of Oxon- ians are found deserting the philosophy of Green to work in the laboratories of Freiburg, Leipzig, and Berlin. Let me say at once, to prevent misconception, that I think the experimental psychologists magnify their office overmuch. The field of experiment is necessarily limited ; it is limited to those cases where we are able to manipulate the physical and physiological processes which condition mental facts. The facts of sensation, the phenomena of movement, and the time occupied by the simpler mental processes, constitute, therefore, practically the whole accessible area. Within these limits, moreover, the results are often so contradictory as to leave everything in doubt ; where definite results THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 51 are obtainable, their value is often not apparent. Finally, many of the results are of a purely physio- logical nature, and are only by courtesy included in psychological science. These are the serious deductions which I think require to be made by a dispassionate observer of all this eager work. But the appetite for facts is a healthy symptom, and the whole movement is one which every student of psychology must take note of. We need not look for light from this quarter upon the problems of philosophy and the deeper mysteries of being ; but it is impossible that so much patient ingenuity should be devoted to analysing the substructure of our mental life without ultimately im- portant effects upon our knowledge of the psychological mechanism. A collateral effect of this scientific development of psychology has been an immense increase of detail- work. Already it is becoming more and more the practice for psychologists to publish elaborate mono- graphs on special phenomena, or on comparatively small departments of the subject. The number of psychological journals has also largely increased. One result of this is obvious. As psychology becomes in- creasingly scientific in character, and as the literature of the subject becomes more and more voluminous, 52 THE PRESENT POSITION OF the severance between philosophy and psychology must necessarily become more pronounced for it will become impossible for the same man to do original work in both departments. From the point of view of philosophy there might seem to be a certain ad- vantage in this, as effectually preventing any further confusion between the two spheres and sets of prob- lems. But this advantage is more apparent than real. For psychology, as the science of mental life, must always stand to philosophy in a more intimate rela- tion than any of the other sciences can. If the divorce, then, be carried so far that the philosopher and psy- chologist are no longer on speaking terms, the old evils will recur ; for a critical severance of provinces can be effected and maintained only by one who is familiar with both departments, even though his original work should lie only in one. It is to be hoped, therefore, that the psychologists of the future will all be trained in philosophy, and the philosophers in psychology. With this view, and in the present situation of affairs, I can- not help adding that it seems to me extremely desir- able, in a great university like this, that there should be a third man connected with the philosophical de- partment a Lecturer or Assistant-Professor specially charged with the teaching of psychology in its most THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 53 recent developments. Such work would lie, of course, largely with Honours students ; for psychological de- tail could not profitably replace to the Passman that introduction to the problems of philosophy and the history of thought which the retention of the Chair in a liberal curriculum is meant to ensure. To Philosophy, then, we come in the last place. It is by philosophy that this Chair and others like it in the Scottish universities must ultimately justify their existence ; and it is to the inbred Scottish bent towards philosophy that the public interest felt in them is due. The outlook here is not discouraging. Within the present century, as is well known, Comte promulgated his law of the three stages, representing metaphysics as a disease of childhood, like measles, which the race was in the act of outgrowing. And since then, Comtian and other influences have undoubtedly produced in many quarters a positivistic or agnostic attitude of mind, which gives itself great airs of finality from time to time in our newspapers and reviews. But metaphysics shows no inclination to die, by way of obliging these prophets of her decease. It is sufficient answer to their vaticinations to point to the marked revival of interest in philosophical discussion within recent years. There was a period, perhaps, when 54 THE PRESENT POSITION OF philosophical interest languished ; but there has seldom been a time when people were more anxious than they are at present to listen to any one who has anything to say. For indifferentism here, as Kant says, can be, in the nature of the case, no more than a temporary phase of feeling. " It is in reality vain to profess indifference in regard to such inquiries, the object of which cannot be indifferent to humanity." Apart from indifference, there was a time when the vast strides made by science more especially by the natural sciences in the third quarter of the present century fascinated men's attention, and diverted it from the problems which lie beneath and behind all science. But the very progress of science has brought men face to face once more with ultimate questions, and has revealed the impotence of science to deal with its own conditions and presuppositions. The needs of science itself call for a critical doctrine of knowledge as the basis of an ultimate theory of things. The idea entertained in some quarters that all difficulties would be solved by a scientific conception like that of evolu- tion, has been found illusory, inasmuch as that concep- tion itself requires a philosophical interpretation before it can throw any light at all upon the metaphysical question. History is not philosophy, and nothing is THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 55 explained merely by being thrown back in time. Evolution notwithstanding, the old questions all re- appear in a slightly altered form. They are brought to light again by the very success of science in dealing with her own problems. Philosophy is first, then, at the present day, a doctrine of knowledge ; and as such the critic of scientific cate- gories, to purge us of bad metaphysics. For the sweep- ing away of bad metaphysics is not the least important part of the philosophical task, and there is no meta- physics so bad as the metaphysics of the physicist or biologist when, in the strength of his own right arm, he makes a raid into philosophical territory. This critical office of Philosophy must also be extended to the metaphysical systems of the past. And in this connection we have one of the richest parts of the training afforded by a philosophical Chair ; for here the teacher must constitute himself the historian of thought, and, with a wise admixture of sympathy and criticism, introduce his hearers to the typical thinkers of the world " The dead but sceptred sovrans who still rule Our spirits from their urns." But this critical, and to a certain extent negative, work is not all. Philosophy must finally endeavour to 56 THE PRESENT POSITION OF be itself critically constructive, or, if that is a contra- diction in terms, it must endeavour to be constructive without forgetting its own critical strictures. The criticism of past philosophies, therefore, should not be purely negative. Truly light -giving and helpful criticism should seek to lead the learner, through the very consciousness of defects and inconsistencies in the systems examined, to a truer statement of the problem, and a more adequate solution. In this way, the systems of the past become so many stepping-stones on which we rise to fuller and clearer insight. And if, at the end, a completed system should still prove beyond our reach, the philosophical teacher will at least seek to indicate the general lines upon which an ultimately satisfactory theory must move. I have only time here to mention one or two points on which I think that a true philosophy should lay stress, and on which it should lay special stress at the present time. The first is the necessity of a ideological view of the universe. Trendelenburg, the eminent German Aristotelian, devotes one of the most interesting of his essays to illustrating what he calls the fundamental difference or antithesis between philo- sophical systems, the difference, namely, between the teleological and the mechanical point of view. Whether THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 57 an exhaustive classification of systems is possible on this basis or not, I believe with him that the antithesis he signalises is fundamental for philosophy ; and there is nothing of which I am more profoundly convinced than that philosophical truth lies, in this case, alto- gether with the teleological point of view. Any system which abandons this point of view lapses thereby from philosophy to science. The word teleology acts upon some people like a red rag upon a bull, from its association with certain old- fashioned arguments which explained particular pheno- mena from their supposed adaptation to external ends, more especially from their adaptation to the require- ments and conveniences of man. This paltry mechan- ical teleology was never at any time convincing to strong and sincere thinkers, and after being riddled by modern science, it may be held as finally beaten off the field. Its unsatisfactory character arose in great part from its taking facts in isolation, and then endeavour- ing artificially to fit them together in the relation of means and end. The philosophical teleology of which I speak concerns itself only with the End of the whole evolution. It concentrates itself upon the proof that there is an End, that there is an organic unity or pur- pose binding the whole process into one and making it 58 THE PRESENT POSITION OF intelligible in one word, that there is evolution and not merely aimless change. For it is only when con- templated in the light of a realised idea that any one speaks of a series of changes as steps in an evolution. A speculation which does not see that evolution spells purpose has not made clear to itself the difference between progress and aimless variation. Such specu- lation rests ultimately on a purely mechanical view of the universe. Let us try, therefore, in a sentence or two, to illu- minate by contrast these two opposite points of view. The mechanical view explains the universe as a col- location of mere facts so many real existences which just happen to be there. They are not there to ex- press any idea, meaning, or purpose : they have no further significance ; they simply are. Every change in these facts is completely determined by its immediate antecedents, acting as a blind vis a tergo. A cause may thus be assigned for every change, but a reason can be given for none ; for where there is no question of realising any idea or purpose, all change must be entirely motiveless. One collocation of facts is just as good as another. The mechanical explanation of things is thus a constant looking backward ; the teleo- logical or philosophical explanation, a looking forward THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 59 to the end or ultimate purpose which is being realised to the reason of the whole development, which is also in the deepest sense its cause. The mechanical explanation of any phenomenon is not false in itself. Nor need there be any quarrel between the causal and the teleological view of things, for they move upon different planes. The mechani- cally causal view only becomes false, when it professes to be a complete explanation of any phenomenon, and therefore, by implication, a philosophy of the universe. True, under certain limitations, as science, it is false when it puts itself forward as philosophy. Mechanical explanation is a proyressiis in infinitum, which can ultimately explain nothing. In the last resort, causce efficientes pendent afinalibus; the complete explanation of anything is only reached when we are able to view it in the light of a purpose, of which it forms an in- tegral part or element. Philosophy, therefore, stands or falls with the possibility of discovering a reasonable meaning or end in the universe. Every true phil- osophy is in this sense an attempted theodicy the vindication of a divine purpose in things. The antithesis of teleology and mechanism is, as you perceive, substantially the old opposition of Idealism and Materialism more strictly expressed. And it is 60 THE PRESENT POSITION OF equally obvious that while the mechanical view, through looking ever backward, finds an explanation of things in reducing them to their lowest terms, and presents us, for example, with matter and motion as philosophical ultimates, the teleological or idealistic view seeks the true explanation of the lower in the higher, of which it is the germ. For if the lower carries in it the promise and potency of the higher, then it must involve no less than a falsification of the facts to substantiate the lowest terms as indepen- dent self-existent facts, out of relation to the ultimate term in which we read the meaning of the whole de- velopment. That, however, is precisely what is done by all materialistic and quasi-materialistic systems. If philosophy, then, is the indication of an end, meaning, or purpose in the universe, what has phil- osophy to say, finally, as to the nature of the End ? Here again, it seems to me that philosophy has to wage unsparing battle against certain tendencies of our time. As it defends the truth of teleology in spite of former abuses of the principle, so it has to champion the truth underlying the old view which made man the centre of the universe. In a material aspect, man is but an atom or a point in the system of things, and we smile when we read in Cicero of THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 61 the heavenly redile who nightly lights the candles of the sky for our mortal comfort and convenience. But the Copernican view of the universe is pressed too far when we are invited, on the strength of it, to efface ourselves before the immensities of external nature. Much current thought is naturalistic at heart that is to say, it makes human nature only a part of nature in general, and seeks, therefore, to explain away the most fundamental characteristics of intelli- gence and moral life. As against this naturalistic tendency, philosophy must be unflinchingly human- istic, anthropocentric. Not to man as a creature specially located upon this earth, but to man and all creatures like him who are sharers in the life of thought, and called thereby to be authors of their own perfection to man as rational all things are relative. To him the creation looks ; for him all things are made. This is the imperishable grandeur of Hegel's system that he has given such sonorous utterance to this view, and expressed it with such magnificent confidence. I can- not always emulate his confidence, nor can I adopt as perfectly satisfactory his universalistic mode of expression. The achievements of the world -spirit do not move me to unqualified admiration, and I 62 THE PRESENT POSITION OF cannot accept the abstraction of the race in place of the living children of men. Even if the enormous spiral of human history is destined to wind itself at last to a point which may be called achievement, what, I ask, of the multitudes that perished by the way? " These all died, not having received the promises." What if there are no promises to them ? To me the old idea of the world as the training-ground of indi- vidual character seems to offer a much more human, and, I will add, a much more divine, solution than this pitiless procession of the car of progress. Happily, however, the one view does not necessarily exclude the other : we may rejoice in the progress of the race, and also believe in the future of the individual. Nature's profusion and nature's waste will doubtless be urged against us, when we plead for the rights of the individual life. But these are objections which every theodicy has to meet. I do not wish to minimise them : on the contrary, they appeal to me with painful force. But the possibility of any theodicy depends on our being able to show that nature and nature's ways of working are not the last word of creation. Nature is non-moral, indifferent, and pitiless; but man is pitiful, and human nature flowers in love and self- THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 63 denial, in purity and stainless honour. If these have no root in the nature of things, then indeed " The pillared firmament is rottenness, And earth's base built on stubble." But we do well, as Goethe teaches in one of his finest poems, to recognise in such attributes of human-kind our nearest glimpse into the nature of the divine. The part is not greater than the whole ; and we may rest assured that whatever of wisdom and goodness there is in us was not born out of nothing, but has its fount, somewhere and somehow, in a more perfect Goodness and Truth. THE "NEW PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. I 1 T. ALL who take an intelligent interest in the movement of contemporary thought whether it be philos- ophy more strictly so called, or the advance of science are aware of the great activity which has been shown of late years in the department of psychology. Till within the last half century or thereabouts, psychology had been an appanage of the philosophers ; and it can- not be said that they neglected this province of their dominion. In this country in particular in England and Scotland psychology has formed the bulk of our philosophic treatises ; and Hobbes, Locke, Berkeley, Hume, Hartley, Dr Thomas Brown, and the Mills, 1 An Address to the Edinburgh University Philosophical Society, November 9, 1892. THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 65 Beid, Stewart, and Hamilton, must always remain among the classics of the science. But it may be admitted that their work often shows a crossing of interests and of points of view. Questions of logic and theory of knowledge were mixed up with the more properly psychological inquiry. And, at other times, the investigation was subordinate to the establishment of some metaphysical theory. The distinguishing note of most recent psychology has therefore been insistence on the separation of psychology from philosophy, and on the maintenance of a purely psychological standpoint. In psychology, it is argued, we have a realm of pheno- mena, a moving world of causes and effects, which it is our business to investigate in the ordinary scientific way, with all the resources of observation and experiment. Imitating the example of physics, we have to reduce this world of complex phenomena to its ultimate con- stituents and the laws of their interaction, and we have to do this without any arridre pe?iste as to the bearing of our results on the ultimate problems of philosophy. No advice could be more excellent ; disinterestedness is the very watchword of science. But it seems to me that a good many of those who talk most loudly of " the new psychology " are exposed to the usual danger of re- action. The rise of this "scientific" psychology, as it E 66 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. also calls itself, is connected with the great develop- ment of science, especially, of the natural sciences, which has marked the present century. The growth of biology and physiology has naturally reacted powerfully upon the whole conception and method of psychological in- vestigation. And it is worth observing that the general scientific movement referred to coincided, especially in Germany, with a revulsion against the idealistic specu- lation which marked the beginning of the century. Probably the two were partly connected as cause and effect, the hunger for hard facts and patient detail- work being a healthy protest of the human spirit against over-hasty and over-confident attempts at universal synthesis. Any way, the new psychology, as I have said, has its roots in this movement. And therefore its absorbing concern was and is to keep itself clear of metaphysics, and of every hypothesis which it imagines to savour of that region of mysteries. To a large class of scientific and would-be scientific thinkers, metaphysics is what clericalism is to the French Liberal : it is the enemy, to be fought at all points. These two character- istics of this militant psychology its renunciation of metaphysics and its affiliation to biology are concisely put by Eibot, one of its standard-bearers : " The new psychology differs from the old in its spirit it is not metaphysical. It differs in its aim it only studies THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 67 phenomena. It differs in its methods it borrows them as far as possible from the biological sciences. Con- sequently the sphere of psychology specifies itself; it has for its subject nervous phenomena accompanied by consciousness." l I am far from asserting that this distrust is without historical justification. Natural explanations i.e., regulated sequences and coexistences of phenomena are what every science has to seek in its own sphere ; and, accordingly, science justly regards as suspect the explanation of any phenomenon by the immediate causality of a metaphysical agent. The interjection of such a causality into the empirical connections which she seeks to unravel, she treats as a form of ignava ratio. "It makes the investigation of causes a very easy task," says Kant, " if we refer such and such phenomena immediately to the unsearch- able will and counsel of the Supreme Wisdom, whereas we ought to investigate their causes in the general mechanism of matter. This is to consider the labour of reason as ended, when we have merely dispensed 1 ' La Psychologic Allemande,' Introduction. Ribot's deliverance dates from 1879, but precisely the same position is formulated in the open- ing and closing sentences of one of the most recent manuals on the sub- ject, Ziehen's ' Introduction to the Study of Physiological Psychology.' If the polemic against metaphysics is not always so marked, it is because the enemy is supposed to have been beaten off the field. 68 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. with its employment." l In the old psychology, this otiose method of explanation, by means of the soul and its faculties, was no doubt often resorted to. Hence, in shaking the dust of metaphysics off their feet, the new psychologists accepted from Lange 2 as their badge the somewhat paradoxical motto " Psycho- logy without a soul." As Kibot puts it triumphantly : " The soul and its faculties, the great entity and the little entities, disappear ; and we have to do only with internal events, events which, like sensations and images, are translations (so to speak) of physical events, or which, like ideas, movements, volitions, and desires, translate themselves into physical events." In this respect, however, the new psychology was not so original as it perhaps imagined. The attempt to dispense with a soul had been systematically made by Hume and the Associationists long before the second half of the nineteenth century. It was not simply the determination to discard the soul that stamped the new movement ; the second and more characteristic feature was the affiliation of psychology to physiology and to general biological science the study of the facts of consciousness consistently and exclusively in correla- 1 Werke, vol. iii. p. 468 (ed. Hartenstein). 2 Geschichte des Materialismus, vol. ii. p. 381. THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 69 tion with the organic facts of nerve and brain. This method of explanation was declined, as we know, by Locke and Hume ; and it has been made matter of reproach against a modern associationist like Mill, that he held by the old psychological method and went on " exactly as he might have gone on if he had lived in the days of Aristotle, ... at a time when a new method highly fertile in fact and of more fruitful promise was available." l The physiological method, in short, is the distinguishing mark, and "physiological psychology" is the term very generally given to the recent develop- ments of " psychology as a natural science." It is to be noted also that in speaking of the conditions of mental states (and it is agreed that the discovery of conditions constitutes scientific explanation) writers of this way of thinking have exclusively physiological conditions in view. Professor James tells us, for example, that he has " treated our passing thoughts as integers, and re- garded the mere laws of their coexistence with brain- states as the ultimate laws for our science ; " 2 and Mr Shadworth Hodgson defines psychology as " that posi- tive and special science which takes its stand upon the results of physiology and biology, and studies the phen- 1 Maudsley, Physiology of Mind, p. 76. 2 Principles of Psychology, Preface. 70 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. omena of sentience and consciousness in connection with their proximate conditions in individual living organisms." l Let me say at once that it is far from my intention to object to this intimate linking of the psychological and the biological. It may be taken as a postulate generally admitted, that our mental life is at every point physiologically conditioned ; and the physiologi- cal method of study does indeed promise, as its vot- aries say, to be most fruitful in its application. It alone furnishes the basis for introducing experiment into mental science ; and though it can only lay siege, as it were, to the outworks of the mental citadel, to the phenomena of sense-perception and movement and a few of the simpler aspects of the mental processes, yet the amount of patient detail-work accumulated in these departments, and the light thrown on other departments by the scientific study of abnormal mental states in their physiological relations, are already enriching the science in no ordinary degree, and transforming the very look of our psychological text-books. The philosopher would be singularly cross-grained who did not welcome this accumulation of material, and who did not congrat- ulate himself that all this detail-work was taken out of 1 Mind, vol. xi. p. 489 (October 1886). THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 71 his hands by those who, from their training and apti- tudes, can do it so much better. But he will reserve to himself, as philosopher, the ultimate verdict on the validity and sufficiency of the theory on which physi- ological psychology proceeds. For it is the most in- defeasible function of philosophy to act as critic of the sciences. The philosopher has to examine the concep- tions which each science accepts without criticism, and on which it proceeds in working out its results ; he has to point out the limits or conditions within which the conception or theory holds true. In other words, he has to restrain the ardour of the specialist who would build upon his results a philosophic theory of the uni- verse, by showing that the results which the investiga- tion seems to establish are really involved in the conceptions or standpoint from which it started, and are therefore in no sense to be accepted as an indepen- dent proof of the theory. I propose to show that this is pre-eminently the case with the main thesis of the " new " psychology at least in the hands of its most advanced representatives. In abjuring the soul and limiting itself to the concomitance of physical and psychical events, it is really dominated by a very definite theory which dictates the character of its results beforehand. 72 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. The result supposed to be proved, it had best be stated at once, is the complete parallelism of the bodily and the mental the denial, therefore, of any real causality to consciousness, which remains the inert accompaniment of a succession of physical changes over which it has no control. In a word, the result is the doctrine of human automatism. The doctrine of conscious automatism has been ventilated a good deal since 1870, or even earlier, by Mr Shadworth Hodgson, Professor Huxley, Professor Clifford, and others ; but, though no doubt definitely embraced by a few, it is safe to say that by the most it has been rather talked about, and toyed with, than fully conceived, much less believed. The doctrine has, however, been recently expressed with great clearness and force by Dr Munsterberg, who is perhaps the ablest and most stirring of the younger generation of physiological psychologists, and one whose theories have attracted considerable attention both in England and on the Continent. He teaches in the most unequivocal fashion that consciousness is simply, as he calls it, a " Begleiterscheinung," a concomitant phenomenon, or inactive accompaniment of a series of mechanical changes. Miinsterberg's work, which has appeared in a sue- THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 73 cession of pamphlets since the year 1888, takes largely the form of a polemic against Wundt's doctrine of Apperception. Wundt's ' Physiologische Psychologic/ first published in 1874, still remains, in its later editions, the most authoritative work on the subject ; and the psychological laboratory established by him in Leipzig in 1879, as the first of its kind, is still probably the chief centre of experimental work. But, although he may thus fairly be called the father of the whole movement, inasmuch as he has organised experimental psychology and induced the world to accept it as a new science, Wundt has never lent his countenance to the automatist conclusions which the young bloods are now drawing from their experimental labours. His doctrine of Apperception is far from clear, and its precise meaning has given rise to con- siderable controversy, but it seems to imply a function of subjective selection or central initiative analogous to what Dr Ward calls Attention ; and this is apparently in harmony with the general philosophical position which the author has elaborated in his recently pub- lished ' System of Philosophy.' But, be that as it may, it is at any rate certain that Wundt has been attacked by the upholders of thorough-going mechanism as an inconsistent and retrograde thinker for attributing 74 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. activity to the Subject. So much by way of explana- tion was necessary for the right understanding of Mlinsterberg's work. His first pamphlet in this con- troversy was ' Die Willenshandlung,' an analysis of the act of will, published early in 1888. This was followed in 1889-90 by three instalments of ' Contributions to Experimental Psychology/ in which, after an eluci- dation of principles, he endeavoured, by a series of carefully devised experiments, to assimilate the apper- ceptive process to the type of reflex action and thus reduce the whole conscious action to a play of asso- ciation. In 1891 he published an introduction to the study of psychology, 1 in the course of which we get a re-statement of his own position. The standpoint does not vary throughout the different expositions, and therefore, though illustrating freely from all, so far as they throw light upon my points, I will draw chiefly from the first and fullest statement that contained in his very acute analysis of the act of will. The ' Willenshandlung ' is divided into three parts, the first treating of the voluntary act as " movement- process " (B&wegungsvorgang) ; the second treating of it 1 ' Ueber Aufgaben und Methoden der Psychologic,' 1891. A fourth instalment of the ' Contributions to Experimental Psychology ' has since appeared. THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 75 as a phenomenon or appearance in consciousness (Be- wusstseinserscheinuny) ; and the third, which is intended to combine the results of the preceding parts, consider- ing the act of will in its totality as " conscious move- ment" (bewusste Bewegung). Mlinsterberg makes a start from the well-known saying of Kant : " That my will moves my arm is no whit more intelligible to me than if any one were to tell me that it could hold back the moon in its orbit." He accepts the problem as thus indicated : How does my will move my arm ? The first part of his treatise deals with the voluntary act exclusively from the physiological side, and analyses it into a series of movements. We may say analyses it necessarily into a series of movements, for the succession of bodily movements, whether visible movements of the limbs or molecular movements of the nerves and brain, are all of the process that could by any possibility be seen ; and reduction to processes which are intelligible in the sense of being pictorially presentable, is the pos- tulate of explanation which he lays down. 1 There is not much that is peculiar to Miinsterberg in this first section ; the same has been vividly put by many writers, 2 and in a sense this purely physical explana- 1 Zuriickfiihrung auf anschaulich verstanclliche Vorgange, p. 10. 2 Never better perhaps than by Lange, ' Geschichte des Materialismus,' 76 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. tion is true from the physiological side, though I think it is possible to show that/ even from the physiological standpoint, it is not the whole truth. Meanwhile it is vol. ii. p. 370. The passage has been often quoted, but may do duty again: "A merchant is sitting comfortably in his easy -chair, and would find it hard to say with what the greater part of his Ego is occupied whether with smoking, sleeping, reading the newspaper, or digestion. Suddenly the servant enters with a telegram which runs 'Antwerp, Jonas and Company failed.' 'Tell James to put the horses to.' The servant flies. The master has sprung to his feet, completely sobered ; some dozen paces through the room, down to his office, instructions given to the confidential clerk, letters dictated, telegrams despatched, then into the carriage. The horses pant ; he visits the bank, the exchange, his business friends. Before an hour is over, he throws himself again into his easy -chair with the sigh, ' Thank heaven, I have secured myself against the worst : now let me consider further. ' A splendid occasion for a picture of the soul. Terror, hope, feeling, calculation ruin and victory compressed into one moment. And that all aroused by a single idea ! What does not the human consciousness comprise ! " Softly, let us look at our man as an object in the material world. He springs up, why ? His muscles contract in the appropriate way. Why so ? They were moved by an impulse of nervous force which discharged the stored-up stock of elasticity. Whence this impulse? From the centre of the nervous system. How did it arise there ? Through the . . . soul. The curtain falls, the salto mortale is made from science to mythology." On the contrary, Lange proceeds, " we must trace back the physical series of causes through the brain to the first occasion of the whole sudden movement without taking any account whatever of the so-called consciousness. Or let us take it in the opposite direction. What came into the man ? The picture of certain strokes with blue pencil upon a white ground. Certain rays of light fell upon the retina, rays which in themselves do not develop more vital force in their vibra- tions than other light-rays. The vital force for the propagation of the impact is ready in the nerve as that for muscular contraction in the THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 77 enough to note the purely mechanical point of view and the explicit reduction of all physiological facts to physico-chemical processes. Passing to the more char- muscles : it can be discharged by the infinitely weak impact of the light- wave only as the elastic forces of the powder- cask are set free by the glimmering spark. But how comes it, then, that just these lines pro- duce in this man just this effect ? Every answer which falls back here upon ideas and the like is as good as no answer at all. I wish to see the channels, the paths of the vital force, the extent, the mode of propa- gation, and the sources of the physical and chemical processes from which the nervous impulses proceed which call into activity, and that precisely in the manner required for springing to one's feet, first the musculus psoas, then the rectus femoris, the vasti, and all the co-operating com- pany. I wish to see the far more important nervous streams which dis- tribute themselves to the organs of speech, the muscles of breathing, producing command, word, and call, and which, by way of sound-waves and the auditory nerves of other individuals, renew tenfold the same performance. I will, in a word, make a present for the time being of the so-called psychical action to the pedants of the schools, and will have the physical action which I see explained by physical causes." In like manner, Miinsterberg concludes that, "from the physiological stand- point there must correspond to every centrally initiated movement a complex of centripetal stimuli ; and in these stimuli acting from with- out, taken together with the existing structure and condition of the nervous mechanism, must lie the absolutely sufficient causes for the necessary occurrence of the definite act of will." Innumerable past stimuli in the life of the individual and the race are stored up as poten- tial energy in the nervous mechanism. Hence the sound-waves of a spoken word (on which, as in the case put by Lange, action follows) may represent "scarcely a millionth part of the joint-causes which bring about that particular movement in the hearer." But the mechanical determination by the joint-causes is as absolute here as in the case of the simplest reflex (pp. 17-20). It is, indeed, the avowed "postulate " of the whole investigation that the act of will shall be explained " als Mechanik der Atome" (p. 9). 78 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. acteristic psychological analysis, contained in the second part of the treatise, we find- that Mlinsterberg is at some pains at the outset to define the problem he sets himself. It is purely a problem of empirical psychology, and does not raise the metaphysical question as to the ultimate ground of phenomena or as to how consciousness exists at all. In that connection, Mlinsterberg seems to indi- cate that he regards Will, conceived as Schopenhauer conceived it, to be the most probable metaphysical hypothesis. His present investigation, however, has to do only with Will as a conscious fact ; it seeks " only to establish the conscious phenomena which are peculiar to the act of will" (p. 56). "Wherein consists the content of our inner experience, empirically given to each of us, which we designate will " (p. 60). Or, again, " For our investigation, limited as it is to facts, the will is a phenomenon like other phenomena ; and accordingly we have only to ask in what it consists, what regularly precedes it in consciousness, and what follows it " (p. 61). This strictly empirical character of the inquiry has one important consequence. It is well known [he proceeds] that modern psychology designates as sensations the ultimate irreducible .constitu- ents into which the content of consciousness (Bewusstseinsin- Tialt) may be analysed; ascribing to sensations a quality, THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 79 an intensity, and a tone of feeling which expresses their relations to consciousness. But, if sensation is the element of all psychical phenomena, and if, on the other hand, the will, so far as we are concerned with it, is only a pheno- menon of consciousness (Bewusstseinserscheinung), it follows necessarily that the will too is only a complex of sensations. 1 Having thus marked out his goal beforehand, Miin- sterberg proceeds to the actual analysis of the facts. He analyses first what he calls the inward activity of will i.e., the voluntary guidance of the train of thoughts in the form of attention; and secondly, the outward activity of will in bringing about muscular contractions. Under the first head, then, the question is, " Wherein consists the inner activity in the direction of the cur- rent of our ideas ? or, more precisely, what must be the nature of the feelings present in consciousness, if they are to produce in us the feeling of inward freedom, of active will ? " This more precise way of putting the question, it will be observed, is not without significance for the nature of the answer which it is to elicit. Let us get to the details, however. Four cases of the inward directive activity of will are analysed by 1 Page 62. The italics are Miinsterberg's own. It need hardly be pointed out that this astonishing invocation of "modern psychology" begs everything which is afterwards put forward as proved. Wundt criticises the assumption. ' Philosophische Studien,' vol. vi. p. 382 et seq. We shall return to it in discussing the theory as a whole. 80 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. Miinsterberg : (a) the case of voluntary recollection or trying to remember ; (b) the exercise of choice between different ideas presented, the concentration of attention upon one of these and its retention in the field of con- sciousness to the exclusion of the others ; (c) the case of logical thinking or reasoning, in which we pass along a definite and apparently self-directed path from prem- isses to conclusion; and (d) the case of simple atten- tion to an idea or percept which presents itself in con- sciousness. The analysis is most ingenious in the case of voluntary recollection and logical thinking. How is voluntary recollection distinguished from involuntary reminiscence ? If a fact a has been connected in experience with &, and the appearance of b calls up in consciousness the idea of a, I do not attribute to myself any voluntary action in the matter; I take it as an instance of the ordinary play of association. On the other hand, when I cannot remember a, when I seek it in my memory, recall to myself the place where I saw it, the connection in which I heard it, and when at last a actu- ally emerges in consciousness, then it was plainly my will (we say) which dragged to light the object of my search (p. 64). How does the case stand, however, when more closely analysed ? THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 81 If I try to remember a, if I seek it in my memory, a is of course* not itself present in consciousness, but what I do perceive does unquestionably correspond in content with a. So long as I have not found a, I feel, it is true, only an x, but I feel this a? in a series of relations, such that x can be only a and nothing else. I try to remember a word. In doing so, I see in memory the passage where I read the word, I remember the moment at which I heard it, I know exactly, too, the meaning of the word ; but the word itself is not present to me. At last it rises in consciousness. Can it be denied that that word was already given in its full content (vollinlialtlicli gegeben) in the series of ideational relations which I remembered 1 ? No doubt it was repre- sented in consciousness by entirely different qualities; it was given in its relations to other things, whereas it is afterwards distinguished by its own characteristics. But the two states of consciousness coincided with one another as to their inner meaning (p. 67). The only peculiarity, accordingly, which Mtinsterberg is prepared to admit in this process as contrasted with a case of involuntary association is that " the clear con- sciousness of the idea a was preceded by another state of consciousness which, in respect of its content, al- ready contained the idea ." He italicises this as the standing mark of voluntary control of our ideas. Eeasoning is distinguished, he argues, by the same characteristic. The premisses already contain the con- clusion, or, to put it more pointedly, the whole process of thought is determined from the outset by the idea F 82 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. of the end to be reached. In the second case mentioned above, where several ideas are presented, and we pur- posely retain one of them, a, the same thing manifestly holds. "Here," says Miinsterberg, "there is no need to prove that this a was in consciousness beforehand. The reasons why just a and not b remained in con- sciousness are admittedly only the occasions or motives of the voluntary act ; they are left therefore unnoticed here, the remaining behind is itself the achievement of the will (das Zurilckbleiben sellst ist die Willens- leistung)" The same line of argument explains his fourth case, the case of simple attention to any idea presented in consciousness. " In the first moment in which a sensation emerges in us, the perception appears involuntary, because the a was till then preceded by a not-a ; in the second moment, however, it appears to us as intentionally retained, just because we were already conscious of it in the preceding first moment." The solemnity with which this is propounded as a serious account of the facts in question would be too impudent if it stood alone; but Miinsterberg hastens to supplement it by reference to the bodily sensations which usually accompany acts like attention and selec- tion or efforts of thought and memory. He cites the admitted fact that there are feelings of innervation in THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 83 the sense-organ, when ideas of that particular sense are present in consciousness for any length of time. Whenever there is a strain of attention, other sensa- tions are usually present, such, for example, as feelings of tension in the skin of the head and the knitting of the brow in trying to remember or in thoughtful consideration. Nor are such feelings confined to the head ; they may be traced all over the trunk, and even in the extremities. Miinsterberg does not hold, how- ever, that such feelings of innervation necessarily accompany all voluntary activity. In reasonings or calculations that proceed without any particular diffi- culty, for example, they are not observable ; but just in these processes, he hastens to add, we are not specially conscious of our voluntary activity. It is only in subsequent reflection that we class them as acts of will, and in so doing, we fall back upon the criterion already signalised namely, the pre-existence of the idea in the preceding moment of consciousness. He concludes the first part of his psychological in- vestigation thus : The inner will has thus shown itself on analysis to be a very complicated group of ideas (ein sehr mannigfaltiges Vorstellungsgebilde), composed of certain definite series of ideas plus feelings of innervation. Nothing unknown, 84 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. nothing which stands over against the ideas as something heterogeneous, has been found, as we saw, in the first group of ideas or sensations ; it only remains, therefore, to ask whether any mysterious element is concealed in these innervation processes. Should these also be found to be a mere complex of sensations, the inner will would then be reduced to a series of sensations, each one of which is of the same order as blue, hard, sweet, or warm (p. 73). The consideration of the feelings of innervation cannot, however, be conveniently separated from the external action of the will upon the body, and so we pass to the second head of this psychological investigation. The stock example will suffice I lift an object with my hand. But the result of this experiment is usually a very poor one : the feeling of will which I seek (die gesuchte Willens- empfindung) I cannot discover in myself. I perceive just a slight feeling of tension in the head. For the rest, I am only conscious that I actually execute the movement viz., bending the joints of the elbow and hand. I feel no special impulse to the movement, lying in time between the theoretical intention and the practical execution of it. It is quite different, however [he proceeds], when I do not simply have the intention of lifting an object, and carry this out, but slowly analyse the movement for myself, and direct my attention to the individual parts of the bendings. Now I really perceive more than the actually executed move- ments ; the bending in the elbow is now preceded by the feeling of a peculiar impulse. It is not a general feeling THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 85 of exertion, but a quite specific impulse, which is different for every movement, and plainly stands in relation to the special performance intended. What, then, has analysis to say of these feelings of innervation which immediately precede the movement, and seem to be its cause ? Miinsterberg turns round triumphantly to apply his former criterion. What we call impulse in the case of muscular contraction is simply the circumstance that the idea of the effect to be produced precedes the effect as actually produced. The feeling of innervation is just the memory-idea of the movement anticipating the movement itself. There has been much discussion as to the precise nature of the so-called feelings of innervation ; but, as Wundt, who had formerly held an opposite theory, has explicitly accepted this view of them as the one most consonant with the present state of our knowledge of the subject, there is no need to reproduce here the arguments which go to establish the position. It commends itself by its naturalness and simplicity. When we are on the point, say, of making a stroke at a ball, we have a premonitory feeling of the energy which we are about to expend ; it seems to flow forth toward the limb which we are about to use. One theory, formerly a good deal in evidence, explained 86 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. this feeling as due to an immediate consciousness of outgoing energy ; but this physiological difficulties in the way of such a conception are great. It is not necessary here to decide whether an immediate con- sciousness of effort is or is not possible; but, in any case, this theory leaves unexplained the specific char- acter of the feeling in question. For it is to be ob- served that it is a premonitory feeling of the exertion of that limb, not merely a general consciousness of virtue going out from us. This is satisfactorily ex- plained by supposing, as Miinsterberg does, that it is due to the reproduction in memory of previous movements of the same nature. Plainly, however, Miinsterberg's theory of the feelings of innervation may be accepted, without admitting that this sequence of memory-image and actual perception constitutes, as he contends, the differentia and suffi- cient explanation of the voluntary act. But it will be observed how ingeniously Miinsterberg has reduced all cases of voluntary action internal and external to examples of the same phenomenon, namely, to cases of an idea or perception A preceded by a the same idea in a different form. " The feeling of innervation," as he puts it, "is an anticipated idea of the actual movement" (p. 88). Exactly the same analysis THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 87 applies to those voluntary actions which do not end in a muscular contraction but aim at the production of some effect in the external world. When I move my finger, not in order to practise the differ- ent movements, but to write something down; when I contract the muscles of my organs of speech, in order to make a communication to somebody; when I bend my arm in order to greet a passer-by, in all these cases I perceive in the first stadium the more or less distinct, more or less clearly represented, idea of the end ; and in the second stadium I have a sensation of (ich empfinde) the end as attained. That alone is the type of the external act of will (p. 89). However complicated the action is, extending possibly over a longer period of time (a journey, the erection of a building), it may always be resolved into the ultimate end in view and the subordinate actions which have to be performed in order to attain that end. In the pro- cess of execution, the ultimate end falls temporarily into the background, and the subordinate actions or means become, each in turn, in a definite series, the proximate end before the mind. And, step by step, the same analysis holds good : the end is first present as idea, then as a perception of accomplished fact. Mtin- sterberg goes on courageously to apply his analysis to the usually received distinction between desire and 88 will. " In order that the desire of an attainable object pass into the corresponding act of will, neither more nor less requires to be added than just the carrying out of the desire, so that the idea of the end may l>e com- pleted ~by the perception of its attainment!' " The liveli- est feeling of practical freedom cannot alter the fact that the will itself is nothing more than the perception (frequently accompanied by associated sensations of tension in the muscles of the head) of an effect at- tained by the movement of our own body, along with an antecedent idea of the same effect drawn from imagination i.e., in the last resort from memory ; this anticipated idea being given as feeling of inner- vation, when the effect is itself a bodily movement, " A theory of the soul does justice, therefore, to the whole field of psychical phenomena, if it assumes, as the only function of the soul, sensation characterised by quality, intensity, and tone of feeling ; a definite group of sensa- tions we call will" (p. 96). * This is the conclusion of the second part of the investigation. The first, or purely physiological, part, reduced the phenomenon to a series of reflex move- ments ; the second, or purely psychological, part, has reduced it to a series of sensations. The third, or 1 The italics are Miinsterberg's. THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 89 psycho-physical, parfc, investigates the relation of these two series to one another. We cannot believe that the two series are quite independent, and if we are driven to suppose that the one is conditioned by the other, there can be little hesitation in settling which is the conditioning factor. The psychical series is dis- continuous, constantly interrupted by perceptions which are shot inexplicably into its midst, without the possi- bility of causal explanation from the foregoing train of ideas ; there are many bodily functions which, so far as we know, are not represented in consciousness. These and similar considerations make the psychic series unfit to be the explaining factor, and accordingly Miinsterberg reaches the conclusion that "the series of conscious phenomena is conditioned by the regular course of material occurrence." This leads to the inquiry, What are the processes in the sensory-motor apparatus which correspond, when inwardly contem- plated, to the sensational complex called a volition? Mtinsterberg's results are reached in the course of an interesting, and in some respects brilliant, discussion as to the localisation of brain-function. It is beyond our interest to follow him in his detailed criticism of different theories. His own positions are mainly two : (1) that there are no specifically motor centres; and 90 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. (2) that perception and memory are connected with the same material substratum; or, to put it otherwise, that ideas of sensation and the corresponding ideas of memory are connected, not with different parts of the brain, but with the same set of material processes differently excited. There is much to be said for these conclusions. Whether the will is analysable into sen- sations and ideas or not, it is at least inseparable from them, and therefore we may reasonably conclude that the centres concerned in voluntary movement cannot be separated physiologically from the sensory regions of the brain. Similarly, it may be argued that in per- ception and memory the same brain- tracts are excited, the liveliness and strength of the impression being greater when its stimulus proceeds from its peri- pheral end-organs than when it is conducted by fibres of association from other parts of the cortex. On the physiological truth of these hypotheses I do not feel competent to decide, nor is it necessary for my purpose to do so. It is with Miinsterberg's appli- cation of them that we are concerned. " Every ganglion of the cerebral cortex," he resumes, " is thus end-organ of a centripetal path but every ganglion is also the initial organ of a motor path. Motor centres do not exist, therefore, or, more properly, every centre is sen- THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 91 sory and motor at once ; every motor impulse has its source in a sensory stimulus, and every sensory stimu- lation presses on into a motor path" (pp. 141, 142). What happens in consciousness, then, when a response to stimulus takes place ? At first, nothing precedes the movement except the sensation or perception which causes its discharge. The movement, in other words, " goes off," in a purely reflex way, through the force of the incoming stimulus. But as soon as the movement actually takes place, consciousness has something new before it namely, the feeling of movement produced in the contracted muscle. This feeling of movement follows, therefore, immediately upon the perception of the stimulus which discharged the movement; and the sensory excitation of the central ganglion which corresponds to this feeling of movement becomes connected accordingly by an association - path with the first excitation, which gave the impulse to the movement. If, now, this process is several times repeated, the con- nection becomes so close that the first excitation inevitably calls forth the second, directly by the path of association, before it has time to be produced by the actual contraction of the muscle. Psychologically expressed, that is as much as to say, the perception of the stimulus must call forth by association the memory-idea of the corresponding sensation 92 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. of movement, before that sensation itself is produced by the actual execution of the movement. The former process takes place by the shorter way of the association-paths in the hemisphere ; the latter requires first to be conducted to the muscle, the inertia of the muscle has to be overcome, the contraction to be actually produced, the sensory nerve to be affected, and the sensory stimulus conducted back to the cor- tex. All this occupies an appreciable time, and the sensory stimulus arrives accordingly considerably later. And now we see clearly why our feeling of innervation precedes the perception of the actual movement. In it, as the constant signal of movement, a signal that is also the actual counter- part of the movement, we involuntarily believe that we see the movement's cause. This is the type of voluntary action, from which all other forms may be developed (p. 145). Take, for example, an act of choice. Here we have, let us say, two stimuli, both alike in strength, but incapable of combination in a common reaction. At first no motor reaction can result, but each stimulated ganglion rouses the centres which are connected with it by association-paths ; and now it is not an opposition of stimulus against stimulus, but on both sides there collect the associations won by former experiences. In the first place, naturally, there is the associated idea of the movement corresponding to the stimulus. If this is stronger upon the one side than upon the other, or if it rouses more pleasurable feelings upon the one side than upon the other, then the corresponding movement will result. This is the type of any act THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 93 of choice ; but there may be indefinite complication, both in the nature of the stimulus and in the mass of associations brought to bear upon it. Still, however great the complication may be, the sensory stimuli with their associated ideas constitute the sufficient and only verifiable cause of the resultant movement ; or, as he puts it in another place, "the act of will is the motor discharge of sensory excitation, whether it be the sensation of a single stimulus or a world of internally and externally combined ideas. As soon as the sensory excitation-complex, the conscious con- tent of ideas, is there, the movement is necessarily given too " (p. 156). And thus the only psychical criterion of the will remains what it was found to be at the end of the psychological section namely, that before the perception of the actual result, the idea of the result is present in consciousness. We have the theory now pretty fully before us, and, as has been indicated, there is much in the physiological analysis that is freshly put and that claims consider- ation. It seems important to remember, alike in physiology and psychology, that the sensory centre in the brain, the central ending of the sensory nerve, does not constitute a terminus, and, consequently, that there is no such thing as passive sensation, sensation 94 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. which is simply received without producing further effects. All consciousness is impulsive. If the stimulus received does not find an immediate vent in movement, it irradiates other brain-tracts in the form of association. The phenomena of imitation, sugges- tion, and many other considerations, reinforce this conception of the dynamic quality which all sensations and ideas possess. Miinsterberg, however, has skil- fully woven these truths into the texture of a precon- ceived theory. In the very act of emphasising move- ment and the dynamic aspect of ideas, he eliminates altogether the notion of action or activity. Ideas " go off " or explode, as it were, in movement of their own accord. There is first the idea of the movement, as in contemplation ; and secondly, the perception of the movement, as executed. In other words, there is a series of happenings somehow passing before us, but no real activity, no real actor in the whole affair. In all so-called action, we only seem to act ; a sequence of ideas exhausts the phenomena of will. The conscious subject is reduced to an inactive spectator of these psychological happenings, which are themselves the inert accompaniments of certain transformations of matter and energy. There results, in fact, as indicated at the outset, the doctrine of conscious automatism in the most unqualified sense of the words. THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 95 Xow, I do not hesitate to say that this conclusion is in the strictest sense incredible ; no amount of so- called " evidence " in its favour would avail to make it even momentarily believable. But as the theory airs itself with a great deal of confidence, and troubles a good many minds, I will endeavour to show that such results are not reached by any cruel "logic of facts," but are all involved in a few erroneous psycho- logical presuppositions, perhaps I ought to say one fundamental prejudice, by which the analysis is vitiated from the outset. This prejudice may be called Pheno- menalism, or perhaps best Presentationism ; Wundt calls it in one place Intellectualism. It is the fore- gone conclusion that the conscious life is analysable without remainder into ideas or presentations. Evi- dently, if phenomena or objects of consciousness are alone to be accepted as facts, then all real activity on the part of the subject is necessarily eliminated; the subject remains only nominally, as a static impersonal condition of the series of events. If we insist upon phenomenalising the act of will, doubtless all the phenomena in the case are the ideas that precede and the perceptions that follow, with perhaps some feelings of tension in the head thrown in. But does it not require some effrontery to offer us these antecedent, concomitant, and sequent ideas as an account of the 96 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. volition itself. To attempt to analyse a volition into ideas is about as hopeful as trying to reduce miles and furlongs to pounds avoirdupois ; there is no common denominator. In the course of such analysis, the real fact of volition is necessarily dropped ; it is overlaid by the mass of antecedents, concomitants, and sequents which acute introspection enables us to discover. But, as M. Fouillee says, the physiological psychologists might fill volumes with their analysis of the sensations which accompany the voluntary act, without touching the essence of the act itself. 1 The result of analysis infected with this phenomenal- istic prejudice is necessarily a Panphenomenalism essen- tially similar to that of Hume. There is the same elimination of all real causality : sequent ideas are all. And if, in deference to a quasi -Kantian theory of Knowledge, the Self or subject is apparently retained, this seeming difference from Hume is only skin-deep. For, as Miinsterberg tells us twice over, " the subject in question is entirely impersonal ; " 2 it is the static or logical condition of consciousness in general. The individual self is reduced, as with Hume, to groups and sequences of ideas ; it is an object in consciousness 1 Revue philosophique, vol. xxxii. p. 238. 2 Aufgabe cler Psychologie, pp. 99 and 130. THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 97 an object, presumably, for this impersonal spectator- subject. I pointed out in passing how entirely Miinster- berg's psychology was dominated by this phenomenal- istic point of view. It appears, incidentally, in the very expressions he uses, as a reference to the passages already quoted abundantly shows. In his equation of phenomenon with fact, in the constantly repeated use of the term Inhalt or content, it is presupposed that objects or presentations in consciousness are the only elements that will be allowed to stand as real. At times, Mlinsterberg speaks, even more naively, of " the sensation of will," of which he is in quest. This recalls, even verbally, Hume's famous expedition into his own interior, in order to discover the perception of the Self. Show me the impression from which the idea is derived, says Hume, and because no particular impression can be found, the idea is pronounced a fiction ; the Self is resolved into a bundle of perceptions. Show me the sensation to which the word " will " corresponds, says Miinsterberg, and finding a number of accompanying sensations, he mistakes these for the act of will itself, and concludes roundly, as we saw before, that " the will is only a complex of sensations." But this conclusion depends, on Mlinsterberg's own showing, 98 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. upon two all -important " ifs." If sensation is the sole element of all psychical phenomena, and if the will is only a phenomenon in consciousness, then, and only then, does it follow necessarily that the will is resolvable into a complex of sensations. In support of the first " if," Miinsterberg, as we have seen, has nothing to offer but a vague reference to " modern psychology." Wundt, in criticising his specu- lation, 1 justly censures this attempt to clothe an as- sumption with the air of an accepted truth, and to cover it with the aegis of " modern psychology." Wundt's own phraseology has wavered in his different editions, and its looseness may be partly responsible, as Dr Ward suggests, 2 for the extreme conclusions of his followers. Perhaps in view of these conclusions, he now explicitly disavows the resolution of all con- sciousness, including feeling and will, into sensational elements. Sensations, he holds, are the ultimate ele- ments of " those conscious contents which we refer to external objects " that is to say, of our perceptions or presentations. Whether this revised statement is un- exceptionable or not, such a position is at least in- telligible ; but it contains no warrant for identifying 1 Philosophische Studien, vol. vi. p. 382 et seq. ' 2 In an article in ' Mind,' January 1893. THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 99 feeling and will with any presentation or combination of such. There is, in fact, no distinction more fundamental to a sound psychology than that between the feeling- directed activity, which, under all its forms, from the simplest act of attention and response to stimulus, may be summarised as Will, and the content or matter with which that activity deals. Doubtless the two cannot be separated ; each is an abstraction without the other. But one thing at least is certain, that to resolve the fact of conscious experience into a sequence of presen- tations or conscious phenomena is to omit the vital characteristic of all consciousness. It is to offer us a machinery without any motor force; and when we mildly point out the omission, we are met by the ready but somewhat brazen retort, that the machinery is self-acting. Wundt comments acutely on the way in which this " intellectualistic " psychology substantialises ideas or presentations, treats them as if they were things or entities that could independently exist and interact. Even when it is admitted that presenta- tions have an existence only in and for consciousness, so that the unity of consciousness is acknowledged to be their necessary complement or point of reference, the ideas still seem to stand over against the conscious- 100 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. ness to which they are referred, and to carry on their evolutions independently. Consciousness, according to this way of thinking, becomes a mere form inclusive of a certain matter, but without influence upon it: it is regarded as purely speculative or contemplative ; an eye (shall we say ?) contemplating the movement, or, to be strict and to avoid metaphor, merely an ideal point of unity. Metaphor or no metaphor, the result of this way of looking at things is obvious. The whole weight is thrown upon the objects the ideas or pheno- mena, thus quasi -independently conceived and the recognition of the subject becomes an empty acknow- ledgment. It is entirely denuded of activity, all action being refunded into the play of presentations. 1 1 Dr Ward has very aptly called attention ('Mind,' xii. 50) to a current form of words which favours this habit of thought viz., the way we have of speaking of " conscious states " in abstraction from the activity of the conscious subject whose states they are. We get into the habit of thinking of the " states " " phenomena " is another word as if they existed separately, as if they interacted and established relations be- tween themselves, evolving in course of time the idea of the subject. But, in strictness, we have no right to speak of a state as conscious ; in so doing we are making an entity of it, and conferring upon an abstraction attributes which it can possess only as an element in the activity of a unitary conscious being. Dr Ward declaims with justi- fiable warmth against the confusion in which our psychological nomen- clature is involved. Even the favourite term " states of consciousness," of which " conscious states " may be supposed an abbreviation, is open to a similar objection. Consciousness, as the form of the word proclaims, is 101 For this assumption, however, there is an entire ab- sence of warrant. A psychology which aims at keeping in touch with fact must strenuously resist this subtle tendency to reduce everything to knowledge. Experi- ence is, in this reference, a wider term than knowledge ; and feeling and will are inexpugnable and irreducible features of experience. Knowledge, feeling, and will are three aspects of experience inseparable aspects, it may be freely admitted but none of them can be ex- pressed in terms of the others ; no one of them can be reduced to simpler elements, no one of them can, properly speaking, be defined or explained otherwise than by pointing to the living experience in which it is exemplified. Miinsterberg's position here is rather inconsistent ; he denies will as more than a complex of sensations, but he contrives to smuggle in feeling by calling it an attribute which every idea possesses. He follows Wundt in saying that every sensation, in addi- an abstraction ; it is the quality or characteristic of a subject or con- scious being. States are states of the conscious being, then, not states of consciousness. This is not a mere piece of verbal purism. A great deal of vague thinking thinking that has not faced an inevitable issue and made up its mind clearly finds a convenient refuge under the quasi-abstract term consciousness. People make no scruple about admitting or postulating a transcendental unity, a unity of conscious- ness, who would think their reputation for modernity at stake if they were taxed with upholding a soul or subject as a real being. 102 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. tion to its intensity and its quality (as touch or taste, red or blue, and so forth), also possesses a tone of feel- ing, or, as Professor Bain puts it, an emotional side; and to this third aspect of sensation, curiously enough, he allows that there is no material counterpart. 1 This statement is curious, not in itself, of course, but as coming from Miinsterberg. There can be no ma- terial counterpart, in Mtinsterberg's sense, just because feeling is not itself an object, phenomenon, presentation, or stimulus, but the attitude of the subject towards a given stimulus the relation of the stimulus to the life of the individual as a whole. This subjective apprecia- tion cannot, in the nature of the case, be represented in objective terms. Feeling, as Dr Ward says after Ham- ilton, is something subjectively subjective. If we are to be strict, we do not know feeling ; for knowledge is of objects, of phenomena, and feeling cannot be pheno- menalised. We experience feeling, and we know about it by its results ; but, using the term in this sense, we know only the causes, accompaniments, and consequents of feeling. It may be said that we remember our feel- ings and emotions, and that we must know them at the time, in order to remember. But we remember feeling only in the sense that, when the ideas which caused or 1 Willenshandlung, p. 137. THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 103 accompanied it are recalled, they are recalled with the same tone of feeling ; in other words, we re-experience in a fainter degree the feeling which we then felt. It is this characteristic of feeling that explains its frequent neglect by psychologists. For feeling cannot be recalled or considered, except in connection with its objective causes or accompaniments : in recording the facts, therefore, the psychologist is apt to forget the sub- jective tinge of the ideas or presentations, and to report upon them in an impersonal way, as, so to speak, ideas-in-themselves. But it was only in virtue of what I have called the subjective tinge that the ideas were his ideas at all, and had any relation to his life. As they presented themselves, they were felt to be either a furtherance or a hindrance to the vitality of the subject, to be either relevant to the dominant in- terests of the individual or discordant. Interest and desire are the result in the one case, indifference or repulsion in the other. And it can hardly be too strongly emphasised that the dynamic efficacy of ideas is entirely excited through the feeling subject. Ideas have hands and feet, as Hegel finely said, and how often are we told that ideas move the world. It is true, or at least we hope so. But every one must ac- knowledge that to speak in that way is to use a vivid 104 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. metaphorical shorthand. Ideas entertained tend to pass into action; a plan conceived and cherished tends to execute itself; but, as Fichte long ago said, the real force is not in the ideas, but in the will of the person who adopts them as his. So, when psychologists like Miinsterberg attribute the whole march of the conscious life to the dynamic influence of idea upon idea, it is well to remember again that this is at best a conven- ient shorthand. Ideas in themselves are pale and in- effective as the shades of Homeric mythology ; they are dynamic only as they pass through the needle's eye of the subject. It is the subject which acts upon its appreciation of the stimulus, and the emotional atti- tude of welcome or repulse is what is meant by feeling. In its earliest and simplest forms, such an emotional wave passes immediately into the appropriate motor response. The food is clutched or somehow absorbed, the disagreeable intrusion is evaded, edged away from, as far as the powers of the being admits of. Feeling, thus conceived, and allied thus closely with action, forms what may be called the driving-power in all life. Here we strike upon the roots of individuation, and when we say that, is it going too far to add, upon the fundamental characteristic of real existence ? In this connection I am confident that, whether we look at the THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 105 matter psychologically or physiologically, we are shut up to the conclusion that all action of living beings was originally feeling-prompted, and that what we call re- flex action is everywhere a secondary product, a de- graded form of purposive action. We know that many actions at first performed voluntarily, actions learned with effort by repeated forth-puttings of concentrated attention, become by degrees habitual, and are performed automatically without attention i.e., without any need for express volition to come into play at all. Great part of the detail of our daily life is handed over to mechanism in this way, and psychologists and physiolo- gists have not been slow to emphasise the beneficent operation of this fact. It is, indeed, the very condition of progress, that aptitudes once acquired should estab- lish themselves as definite tendencies within our mental and physical organism definite co-ordinations of stim- ulus and response which do their work without our active superintendence. The powers of intelligence and will the powers of personality, if I may so speak are thus set free for new tasks and further achieve- ments, till these in turn are, as it were, built into the structure of the Self. Only thus is the spirit fitted to advance upon its endless path. But mechanism is thus, in every sense, posterior to intelligence and 106 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. will; it is a means created and used by will. In a strict sense, will creates the reflex mechanism to which it afterwards deputes its functions. Mechanism, in fact, here as everywhere, is a means, something secondary ; it is impossible to conceive it as something primary, existing on its own account, much less as carrying in it the explanation of the higher con- scious and voluntary processes. Intelligent volition is not reflex action grown complicated, and so become conscious of itself. That is precisely to invert the true relation an inversion that would be ludicrous, if it were not disastrous. Eeflex action is purposive action grown unconscious or sub-conscious, according to the economy of nature, because consciousness is no longer necessary to its proper performance. It is not to be supposed, of course, that this takes place within the life-history of the individual human being, or of any highly developed organism. In such an organism, many reflex paths, many co-ordinations of stimulus and response, are doubtless fixed ; they have been established in the long process of race- evolution, and in virtue of their establishment that evolution has proceeded. But follow the process as far back as we may, all analogy points to the same conclusion namely, that feeling - prompted action, THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 107 i.e., action which is germinally purposive, germin- ally voluntary, is the Trporepov <f>vo-i, the first in the order of nature. In the lowest organisms, the reaction upon stimulus may be so simple and uniform as to wear to an observer the appearance of a mere mechan- ical reflex. But this is, if I may so speak, to make the creature a mere outside ; it forgets, as this mechanical psychology is constantly forgetting, that wherever there is life, there is unity. Every organism is a unity, and resumes itself as a unity. Feeling is the inward ex- pression of this unity ; and, to my mind, it is not doubt- ful that the movement of attraction or repulsion, which, to us and from the outside, may seem a simple reflex, is to be interpreted rather as the total response of a ger- minal consciousness, as the expression of the being's likes and dislikes. Physiology, so long as it remains pure physiology, is perhaps debarred from taking account of feeling or consciousness as such. The psychical in all its forms lies outside the scope of physiological methods. But the self - preservative, recuperative, self-adaptive ten- dencies of organisms and organic tissue are the physiological way of expressing the same fact. Such a mode of expression is imperfect and mythological, perhaps, and one can understand that many physi- 108 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. ologists, supposing it to be put forward as an ex- planation of the facts, grow impatient and fall back upon a purely mechanical theory of vital function. But these expressions are in no sense explanations, as science uses that term ; they are rather finger-posts to the unexplained; they merely name or indicate the fundamental characteristic of life as such, which differentiates it from mechanism or what seems to us to be mechanism. Life is the presupposition of physiology, the fact on which its existence is based, a fact which it has simply to accept, as all the other sciences have to accept their own presuppositions. Its explanations move within the fact of life, and cannot be used to explain that fact itself, or, in other words, to explain it away. Yet that is, in substance, what a purely mechanical physiology tries to do. Physiology, for the last fifty years, has been dominated by a reaction against what is called vitalism. The older investigators were in the habit of calling in " vital force " as a deus ex machina to account for any phenomena which baffled their powers of natural explanation. Vital force, conceived as extraneously interfering with otherwise mechanical processes, was evidently a hypostatised entity of the worst type, and it was accordingly discarded by scientific physiology THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 109 as part of the baneful legacy of metaphysics. Mechani- cal explanation, or, in other words, the resolution of physiology into physics, became the watchword and ideal of the best workers. But they did not observe that they were in danger of throwing away the child with the bath, as the Germans say. After all, physiology is not physics ; living matter behaves differently from dead matter. What is the difference and the basis of the difference ? In rendering mechanically intelligible the inter-relation and interaction of this and the other part of the bodily structure, physiologists tend to forget that all such mechanical arrangements are arrangements in the service of life, arrangements per- fected in the living being (in all probability) by the responsive and self-adaptive action of its living ancestors in the course of ages. Picrposiveness is the notion upon which physiology is built, and it is worked into the whole theory of development ; yet it is a notion entirely alien to the blind vis a tergo of mechanism as such. The more clearly a physiologist realises what pure mechanism means, and the more fully he grasps the import of the facts he has to deal with, the more ready will be his acknowledgment that to call them mechani- cal is at best an analogy. They belong to a different order of facts ; life and purpose govern them from one 110 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. end to the other. A self-acting and self-regulating machine is only by an abuse of language spoken of as a machine at all. It is in vain therefore that many psychologists at the present time outdo the physiologists in the glibness with which they talk of nervous currents and explosions of nervous energy and paths of least resistance. The appearance of explanation conveyed by the use of the expression "path of least resistance" is in the last degree illusory. We are transferring an expression which has a perfectly definite and intelligible meaning in physics or mechanics to a sphere where the conditions are quite different, and where we are, moreover, almost quite ignorant as to the nature of what actually takes place. Path of least resistance means, in such a case, simply the particular reaction which we find the stimulus, as a matter of fact, to produce. We have no right to go further than this. The use of the physical phrase implies, however, that what takes place is pre- cisely the same as the selection of a channel made by a rill of water trickling down a hillside. This is to make the living being simply a network of pathways through which the energy of external nature takes its course soaks in, and oozes out again. But this is not a true account even of the humblest organism. Such a THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. Ill representation totally ignores the unitary character of the organic and sentient being. We are misled, in short, by words like currents, and energy, and least resistance. What do we mean by nerve currents ? Nerve currents cannot be treated in this isolated fashion, as if they took place in vacuo, or in an indifferent medium ; they take place in a living individual, and apart from the unity of that indi- vidual they are mere abstractions. A nerve cur- rent is a physiological process, which, originally and normally, means central stimulation and appropriate central reaction. You cannot separate either the appreciation of the stimulus or the reaction upon it from the organism as a whole. To speak psycho- logically, it is the living being, as a unity, that is aware of the sensation and responds to it. There is no need here to revive any hypothesis as to the specific seat of the soul, or to conceive any point of convergence in the brain for the multitudinous nerves of sensation and motion. However the nervous system acts, the unity of consciousness, as we experience it every moment, is proof sufficient of the fact that it does act as a unity. Every living being is a similar individuate unity. Abnormalities, as when the removal of the higher centres gives rise to the establishment of independent 112 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. unities (in the spinal cord, for example), are no argu- ments against what is here contended for ; they rather go to prove that even the mutilated organism, so long as it lives at all, reconstitutes itself into a kind of unity. A living being, then, is, at the very least, a centre of sensation and reaction ; and when sensation is so used, it means not only intellectual awareness of some pres- ence, but also a subjective drawing to, or away from, the intruder. This second element of feeling proper is the condition in virtue of which the sensation as know- ledge calls forth the reaction as will. The appetitive is the first phase of consciousness. And however the growth of the intellectual life and of volitional self- control may emancipate us from the promptings of the moment, it is to the end through feeling that the whole process of our life goes on. It is in feeling that we assert our individuality, give expression to our prefer- ences and distastes. Feeling leads each of us to select from the infinite of the knowable and do-able, that little world of interests and habits which differentiates us one from another, and gives to each his peculiar point of outlook upon the universe. The necessity of taking feeling first has led us in appearance away from our specific theme. But it is only in appearance, for it was impossible to separate THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 113 the treatment of feeling and will, and what has been said of the one applies mutatis mutandis to the other. The presentationists endeavoured to make feeling a relation between ideas, instead of the relation of ideas to the subject of them. If the subject has identified itself, as we say, with certain ideas or interests, then any idea which conflicts with these ideas will result in pain or displeasure to the subject. But here, as always, it is not the relations of ideas as such rela- tions, as it were, in the phenomenal plane but rela- tion to a subject, that constitutes the fact of feeling. Similarly with volition. Volition is the action of a subject, and as such, it cannot be phenomenalised. But this is just what the phenomenalists, from Hume to Mtinsterberg, insist on doing. They resolve voli- tion into a sequence of presentations ; first, an idea, then a perception (as we have seen Miinsterberg put it), but no intervening fiat, no power, no real action, nothing corresponding to what we mean by volition just the one first, and the other second. The answer to be made to this ingenious theorem has been indicated already. To ask to know the will as a presentation is to ask to know it as it is not. The phenomena which Miinsterberg offers us are very likely all the phenomena in the case, or if there are more, the others are like unto H 114 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. them. But his whole investigation is a petitio principii. The heading of the psychological section of his treatise runs, " The Will as a Phenomenon in Consciousness " ; and that we may be in no doubt as to his meaning, he says in his preface : " It might also run The Will as Idea (der Wille ah Vorstellung)." The will as idea that is the whole theory in a nutshell. No enemy could have put the case more conclusively against Mlinsterberg than he has done himself in these words, which are, nevertheless, the key - note of his whole inquiry. II. But this Presentationism or Phenomenalism, as has been already hinted, is not a new doctrine. It is a motive which has been widely influential in the history of philosophy. Let us generalise our conclusions, there- fore, and enforce them by historic example. Activity, as Berkeley long ago said, is not an idea, or anything like an idea, though doubtless activity is involved in the existence of any idea, seeing that ideas exist only for a subject, or, to be more exact, seeing that ideas, from the psychological point of view, are in every case just activities of some subject. But because, in the THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 115 nature of the case, action cannot be made a pres- entation of, cannot be held up as an object in the mental field of view, this theory proposes to efface activity altogether. In saying this, we are not attrib- uting to the Presentationists a conclusion which they disclaim. All real action, all real causality, is elimin- ated from their account of the universe as known. Causality is reduced, as with Hume, to mere sequence. We ourselves do not act we only seem to ourselves to act; in reality, we merely look on at happenings. Mlinsterberg suggests that the real agent in all these sequences, including the events which we mistakenly attribute to our own agency, may be, as Schopenhauer conceived, a unitary unconscious will. To this extent, therefore, he differs from Hume : he does not leave us with a purely sceptical phenomenalism. He is pre- pared to admit will or force, in this sense, as ultimate metaphysical reality and sole cause. But such an ad- mission has no bearing on our contention, so long as the psychological reality of the individual Will is denied. It must be admitted unreservedly that, if to know means to have a presentation before us, then we do not and cannot know the fact of our volitional activity. In this sense, we can only know the motives which led to it and the changes which followed upon it in the 116 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. phenomenal field. I am not advocating this usage, for I admit that it sounds -absurd to say that we do not know our own activity, our own existence. All I would urge is that, if the associations of " knowledge " with the objective, the presentable, the phenomenal, are ineradi- cable, then we shall be obliged to fall back upon some other term to express the acquaintance which the sub- ject has with his own activity. This is exactly the position which Berkeley took up, when he corrected his first impulse to resolve the Self into a procession of ideas. In his suggestive distinction between " ideas " and "notions," he anticipates and combats the Pan- phenomenalism of Hume and of such theories as we have been considering. There can be no idea formed [he says] of a soul or spirit ; for all ideas whatever being passive and inert, cannot re- present unto us by way of image or likeness that which acts. A little attention will make it plain to any one that to have an idea which shall be like that active principle of motion and change of ideas is absolutely impossible. Such is the nature of Spirit or that which acts, that it cannot be of itself perceived, but only by the effects which it pro- duceth. ... So far as I can see, the words will, soul, spirit, do not stand for different ideas, or in truth for any idea at all, but for something which is very different from ideas, and which, being an Agent, cannot be like unto or re- presented by any idea whatsoever, though it must be owned THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 117 at the same time that we have some notion of soul, spirit, and the operations of the mind, such as willing, loving, hating inasmuch as we know or understand the meaning of the words. 1 In a later section he formally repeats the distinction in the same terms 2 and adds : " I will not say that the terms idea and notion may not be used convertibly, if the world will have it so ; but yet it conduceth to clear- ness and propriety that we distinguish things very different by different names." And with his accus- tomed fine - edged irony, he remarks that " much scepticism about the nature of the soul " has arisen " from the opinion that spirits are to be known after the manner of an idea or sensation." "It is even probable that this opinion may have produced a doubt in some, whether they had any soul at all distinct from their body, since, upon inquiry, they could not find they had an idea of it." 3 The modern doctrine of automatism lends fresh point to this shaft of sarcasm. 1 Principles of Human Knowledge, section 27. 2 Section 142. "We may not, I think, strictly be said to have an idea of an active being or of an action, although we may be said to have a notion of any mind and its acts about ideas inasmuch as I know or understand what is meant by these words. What I know, that I have some notion of." 3 Section 137. The preceding section is also so aptly expressed, especially with reference to the subsequent argument of Hume, that I 118 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. Berkeley's proposed use of idea in this restricted or specific sense is equivalent to that of the modern terms presentation, phenomenon, or object ; and it will be observed how he expressly defines mind and spirit as " that which acts." It must be for ever impossible to phenomenalise an action ; we cannot objectify the subjective function as such. In his own words, that which acts cannot be itself perceived, but only by the effects which it produceth. But are we to conclude, therefore, that there is no activity in the case, that there is no active subject at all ? Surely not. On the contrary, it is in activity or the will that we, as it were, lay hold upon reality and have immediate assurance of it. And if, as already said, the associa- tions of " knowledge " are too narrow to permit of its application here, we must even fall back upon some cannot forbear reproducing it here. " It will perhaps be said that we want a sense (as some have imagined) proper to know substances withal, which, if we had, we might know our own soul as we do a triangle. To this I answer that, in case we had a new sense bestowed upon us, we could only receive thereby some new sensations or ideas of sense. But I believe nobody will say that what he means by the terms soul and substance is only some particular sort of idea or sensation. We may therefore infer that, all things duly considered, it is not more reasonable to think our faculties defective, in that they do not furnish us with an idea of spirit or active thinking substance, than it would be if we should blame them for not being able to comprehend a round square." THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 119 such phrase as "immediate assurance," "immediate experience," or " self-feeling." 1 There is, after all, a certain justification for the narrower use of the term knowledge. For is it not the case that knowledge, in its very nature, brings with it a species of foreignness ? Of course we all see clearly enough that there is another, and, I admit, a more im - portant sense, in which knowledge may truly be said to be just the overcoming, the banishing, of this strange- ness. The knower and his knowledge, as Aristotle said, are in a sense one. When we have thoughts, says Hegel, we recognise in nature's inner heart only our own reason, and feel at home there. " Spirit has the certainty which Adam had when he saw Eve. 'This is flesh of my flesh, and bone of my bone.' " No one, I say, will question that in this sense knowledge means unity, appropriation, the breaking down of the middle wall of partition. But that is without prejudice to the other and more subtle aspect of the case which I desire to emphasise. Knowledge, in its very nature, implies difference. What we know is an object, something held 1 The last phrase is used by Mr Bosanquet (Logic, vol. i. p. 77) in a passage in which he also speaks of "the immediate feeling of my own sentient existence that goes with " any act of perception. " Immediate experience" is used by Mr Stout in contrast to cognition or "discrim- inative thinking," 'Analytic Psychology,' Bk. I. c. i., and Bk. II. c. i. 120 THE as it were at a distance from us, something opposite to us. What we know is in fact always something different from ourselves. The knower and the known are never in this sense one, even in the limiting case of psycho- logical introspection. It is often said that here the observer and the observed are one and the same ; but the statement is not literally true. All intro- spection, it has been more truly said, is really retro- spection ; it is a post-mortem examination. When I know a state, that state has already ceased to exist as a living pulse of thought and feeling. It belongs to the past. I recognise it as having been mine ; but it is different from the present psychologically-minded self, intent upon its examination. 1 The case of introspec- tion has been mentioned, because there, if anywhere, it might be said that there was an identity of knowing and being. But, as we have just seen, it is not so. Knowing and being are not identical ; they cannot help being different. The fact is, we are face to face here with a constant characteristic of knowledge, and if, as we are apt to do, we take knowledge as exhaustive of 1 So Professor Sully and Professor James. The latest expression of this fact is perhaps to be found in Mr Stout's 'Analytic Psychology.' vol. i. p. 159 : " The immediate experience of any moment is never at that moment an object of thought." THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 121 experience, a far-reaching vista of consequences soon appears. We may interpret the characteristic in the relativistic sense which is so popular in agnostic and positivistic theories. We may say, knowledge never gives us the real thing; we are always going round about things, and always baffled with their mere out- sides. We know only phenomena; reality, whether of the self or the not-self, is beyond us. This is one line of thought which meets us in certain forms of Kantianism and Neo-Kantianism, in Hamilton, and in Spencer. Or, if we do not take this line, we fall into what I may call an Absolute Phenomenalism. In this case, we spurn the unknown and unknowable mystery of the relativists; we see that it is absurd to speak as if knowledge were constructed merely to baulk us. So far all seems well ; but we have not really escaped the consequences of accepting know- ledge as our ultimate. For we dissolve the universe altogether into objects or phenomena; all things and all finite persons, including ourselves, are merely objects in experience. And thus, in another way than the agnostic, we as surely deprive men and things of reality ; for mere objects are not real, they are halves craving completion. And that completion they do not get from the addition of a universal self. That uni- 122 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. versal self has itself no nerve of reality about it, if it is taken merely as the unifying self of knowledge. It is simply the formal unity of a spectacular process of phenomena. There is no warrant, on the theory, for understanding this self in any other way. If, then, we are to lay hold upon reality and lift our- selves out of the flux of phenomena, we must do so by a species of assurance different from knowledge, as knowledge has just been analysed and explained. Now, we have no such certainty of any reality, save the reality of self-existence. We know other things and other persons ; no sane person at least doubts that we do. But we do not immediately feel or experience their existence ; they are oilier beings, and their exist- ence is a hypothesis to explain certain phenomena of our own experience. And though the hypothesis is infinitely probable, it is theoretically open to doubt. Similarly, if we try to build even upon our own exist- ence as known, that existence tends to melt away into a dreamlike succession of phenomena passing before an inactive spectator, and the result is, that we fail to find reality anywhere. Existence resolves itself into a magic-lantern march of pictures, but, as Fichte says, without anything of which they are the pictures. It is not in knowledge, then, as such, but in feeling and THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 123 action, that reality is given. In saying this, I do not for a moment mean to do what I said before was im- possible, to divorce any of the three aspects of experi- ence from the others : the being who feels and acts must also know. Knowledge may even be said, with some truth, to be the pre-condition of the other two. But the immediate certainty of real existence attaches not to what is known in the knowledge, but to the accompanying awareness of subjective activity in the knowing act and the tinge of subjective feeling in connection with it. Knowledge is itself from this point of view an activity of the subject, and, as such, it will serve perfectly well as a basis of certainty. It is when the element of activity in knowledge is left out of sight, and attention is concentrated on the content or object of knowledge, that we enter upon a false path, and end in the self -contradictory notion of a knowledge which is nobody's knowledge, and a knowledge of nothing. But knowing is not a colour- less or impersonal function as it were a series of happenings in vacua. Every cognitive act is suffused with feeling, and in virtue of this suffusion it is felt by me as mine, by you as yours. In knowing any object, therefore, whether a thing in the external world or a state of his own mind, the knowing subject pos- 124 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. sesses, in this element of feeling, an immediate assur- ance of existence there and then. This certainty is, in the first instance, in the moment of acting, a pure immediacy, a mere awareness. After action, and to the psychological observer, it must be mediated by knowledge and reflection i.e., the changes are presented or represented in consciousness, and with them comes the feeling of self-origination, from which remembered conjunction springs the reasoned convic- tion of our active causality. But the reflective asser- tion of the psychologist depends entirely upon the immediate feeling the sense of living, as we might call it which went with the action originally. I feel the activity, the experience, at the moment, and in virtue of this immediate accompanying feeling, I after- wards acknowledge it as mine. It was not, therefore, without reason that Fichte 1 eventually returned to this primal certainty, as the sole means of escape from a limitless scepticism. Descartes's cogito, though intended to embrace the volitional aspect of consciousness, laid stress, designedly or not, upon the intellectual ; and the result was, that the real activity of the subject was discarded by his immediate successors. The content of consciousness 1 The reference is to his treatise on c The Vocation of Man. ' THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 125 became everything; the subject a mere empty vessel or form for the content. And in Spinoza, accordingly, we get a system or procession of idece, or modes of thought, and a parallel procession of ideata, the cor- responding modes of extension. The identity of in- tellect and will is one of Spinoza's central doctrines, and he presents us accordingly with a system in which real activity, or real causality, has as little place as it has in Miinsterberg's. His parallelism of modes of thought and modes of extension is, in fact, the very doctrine of Automatism which we have had under consideration. And it results from the very same considerations from exclusive attention to the intel- lect, to the knowledge-content of the mind. Scan the history of philosophy as we may, we shall find the same cause everywhere producing the same effect, now in a more materialistic form, now in the guise of Idealism ; but whether the automatism be materially or ideally conceived, matters practically not one jot. With the elimination of real causality from the course of things, the world is emptied of real meaning ; it is reduced to a spectacular sequence of happenings, which have no raison d'etre, seeing that all is absolutely predeter- mined from the outset. There is no life or reality in the show which passes before us ; for the nerve 126 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. of reality is furnished solely by the conviction of our own activity, our own real causality. And with the conviction of real activity, it is to be noted, goes the belief in an end or aim which the action is to realise. It is upon purposive, idea-guided action that Fichte takes his stand as the ultimate certainty. The idea is present to me, he says, not as a Naclibild or copy, an after -picture of an inde- pendent reality, but as a Vorbild, a fore-picture, an ideal or purpose, which does not yet exist, but which I have myself to make real. In the ingenious cari- cature which Miinsterberg offers us, he does not deny that this is the fundamental characteristic of voluntary action ; but, in accordance with his .presuppositions, he denies the reality of the nexus between the conception and its execution. It is undeniable that the one is before the other, but the first has no influence or efficacy in bringing about the second; for the whole train of happenings, he expressly tells us, is independ- ent of our consciousness. 1 The whole train is driven, in fact, a tergo by a Schopenhauerian dynamo-machine in the background. 1 Die Willenshandlung, p. 3. The bodily and the mental series, he says, are " zwei verschiedene Erscheinungsformen desselben einheitlichen, von unserem Bewusstsein unabhaugigen, wirklichen Geschehnisses. " THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 127 The same line of thought which leads to the elimina- tion of real activity from the course of things, thus leads necessarily to the denial of purpose everywhere. And it is noteworthy, in this connection, that Spinoza is the most embittered opponent of any doctrine of teleology or final causes. To Spinoza, as to Mlinster- berg, all determination is mechanical, a tergo or from the past ; the notion of self-determination in view of ideas, determination a fronte or by the future, was inconceivable to him. The human being was to Spinoza as completely determined, and determined in the same way, as a stone propelled through the air. We do not know whether there is anywhere ' such purely mechanical causality as Spinoza took for granted in the case of the stone ; but we do know that that is not the mode in which the actions of conscious beings are determined. The causality of the future, or of the ideal, is coterminous at least with the confines of life. All action of living beings, I have argued, is originally purposive that is to say, in a wide sense, voluntary directed more or less clearly by the creature towards some aim. Only if this is so, is action in any sense an action of the creature itself, and not, in Mlinster- berg's language, "a phenomenal phase of the unitary happening " which goes on in the creature irrespective 128 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. of its feelings or desires. With the acknowledgment of purposive action, the wjiole process of things acquires a new aspect. It is no longer a motiveless procession of appearances, or, as Professor James well puts it, the dull rattling off of a chain forged ages ago. It is an evolution which is real at every point. And if it has seemed, in the course of this exposition, that knowledge and ideas have been depreciated at the expense of the will, they are here restored to their rightful function as the necessary conditions of selection or choice, the springs of all activity, and so the guiding star of all advance. But ideas in themselves are nothing, and the analysis of knowledge as knowledge can never give us reality. If we were to recast Descartes's formula, in the light of all that has come and gone in philosophy since his day, not Cogito ergo sum but Ago ergo sum is the form his maxim would take. A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 1 I. fTlHEEE can be little doubt among those qualified to judge, that Mr Bradley's 'Appearance and Eeality' is the most important metaphysical work which has appeared in England since the publication of Green's ' Introduction to Hume ' in 1874. It is so, in my opinion, not because its conclusions are likely to become assured possessions of philosophical thought, but because of the intrepidity of the treatment and the singularly stimulating quality which belongs to all that Mr Bradley writes. 1 Appearance and Reality : a Metaphysical Essay. By F. H. Bradley, LL.D. (Glasgow), Fellow of Merton College, Oxford. London: Swan Sonnenschein & Co. 1893. The criticism which follows appeared as two articles in the ' Contemporary Review ' of November and Decem- ber 1894. I 130 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. The author modestly says in his preface that his book does not design to be permanent. It is his contribution to the sceptical discipline of the English mind, from which he is not without hopes of seeing " a rational system of first principles " emerge. And it is true that the book is hardly likely to take its place as a classical treatise in the literature of the subject. The highly abstract character of most of the discussion, suggesting at times a delight in logic for logic's sake, the unadorned dryness (for the most part) of the style, and the seemingly deliberate per- versities of manner which mar it at times, forbid such a destiny. But the brilliant dialectic of which the book is full, the thoroughness and sincerity witli which it sifts the most vital questions, its ruthless criticism of conventional solutions, ensure for Mr Bradley's latest volume an important influence upon the thought of his contemporaries. Mr Bradley's courage is also to be commended in publishing a book which throughout deals avowedly and in set terms with " the Absolute." What a shock to the precisians of Agnosticism and the puritans of the empirical tradition ! This particular bogy, so potent in the middle of the century, has apparently lost its terror even for the English mind. As soon as A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 131 men began to reflect a little on what was meant by the term, it became evident that the ultimate object of philosophy always is, and must be, the Absolute. Mr Bradley's remarks, in his short Introduction, on the unavoidableness of metaphysical inquiry, the necessity of a new metaphysic for each fresh generation, and the utility of even an imperfect knowledge of the Absolute, may be commended to the candid reader who is still unconvinced, or perhaps a confirmed sceptic, on those points. The chapters of destructive criticism, which form the first part of the book, are largely in Hegel's manner, and the influence of Hegel is unquestionably predominant throughout. But in spite of this general indebtedness, the book is distinguished by an independ- ence of style and treatment not usual with followers of this master, or indeed of any master. But Mr Bradley has always insisted on calling his soul his own. Whatever else this volume may be, and whatever criti- cisms we may have to make upon it, it is certainly no easy reproduction of another man's thoughts: in the sweat of his own brow its author has conceived and executed it. This independence of treatment will prove of good omen, it may be hoped, for the future of philosophical 132 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. discussion among those who may be regarded, in a general way, as carrying on the traditions of Green arid representing the influence of Hegel, or at least of German Idealism, in British philosophy. In this connection, Mr Bradley's book may be said, perhaps, to mark the close of the period whose beginning was signalised, twenty-three years ago, by the publication of Green's work already mentioned. When we think of the Hamilton - Mill controversy in the sixties, it is obvious that serious study of the Critical Philosophy and German Idealism had yet to begin. Only the outworks of the Kantian scheme had been mastered even by the accredited leaders of British thought ; while Hegel, or at least his strangely refracted image, was simply the philosophical "bogy-man," useful to frighten back the unwary wanderer into the fold of Empiricism or the Philosophy of the Conditioned. Yet Hegel was probably the richest mind that had been devoted to philosophy since Aristotle, and, whatever judgment may be passed on his system as a logical whole, had done more than any other man to mould the thought of the century in all the humanistic sciences. The publication of Dr Hutchison Stirling's ' Secret of Hegel/ in 1865, first removed the reproach of ignorance A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 133 and indifference, or worse, from British philosophy. It was published in the same year as Mill's ' Examination of Hamilton,' and in the noisy, multitudinous echoes of that controversy, the accents of the new voice were partly drowned. But they penetrated, like tidings of a land that is very far off, to ears fit to receive them. While Mr Spencer's philosophy gradually established itself as the persuasion of the average man, the majority of serious thinkers in England were devot- ing themselves to the study of Kant and Hegel ; and Green's 'Introduction' was the first noteworthy symptom of this new direction of thought at the universities. The movement thus inaugurated has been growing in volume since then, and, as was to be expected, it has somewhat changed its character ; and Mr Bradley's book may perhaps be found in this respect to mark the end of the period of absorption or assimilation. During these Lehrjalire, English writers have repeated too anxiously, and with too minute exactitude, the formulae of a foreign master, treating them rather as oracles of truth than as utterances of finite wisdom, and showing too great a reluctance to submit them to legitimate criticism. But of late a calmer and more critical tone has been noticeable, and a more catholic spirit has shown itself. 134 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. Other names have claimed attention, such as Lotze on the one hand, and SchQpenhauer on the other (to mention only these two). As Mr Bradley puts it in his preface, " the present generation is learning that to gain education a man must study in more than one school." And the result of this wider range can hardly be other than to diminish the somewhat partisan zeal of the so-called neo-Hegelian party for the ipsissima verba of Hegel's theory, and to set them upon a more independent handling of the subject itself, in accordance with the genius of their own time and nation. Then the Lelirjalire and the Wanderjahre will be ended and the Meisterjahre will begin. For dis- ciples, as Bacon puts it in a well-known passage, do owe unto masters only a temporary belief and a sus- pension of their judgment till they be fully instructed, and not an absolute resignation or perpetual captivity. Though Germany once possessed the hegemony of Europe in matters philosophical, that time is past and the fact that it once existed constitutes no reason why we should remain in perpetual tutelage to German masters. "I have a high opinion," says Mr Bradley in his preface, "of the metaphysical powers of the English mind ; " and his book is conceived throughout in the spirit of intellectual freedom. A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 135 The author describes his work in the preface as " a critical discussion of first principles." " The chief need of English philosophy," he tells us, " is a sceptical study of first principles, and I do not know of any work which seems to meet this need sufficiently." The object of his own work is, therefore, " to stimulate inquiry and doubt " doubt or scepticism being understood to mean not doubt or disbelief in any particular tenets, but " an attempt to become aware of and to doubt all precon- ceptions." This is in Mr Bradley's mind and not without good reason the first and all-important con- dition of sound work in metaphysics. The short Intro- duction puts unanswerably the necessity and the utility of metaphysics. As it is impossible to abstain from thought about the universe, " the question is merely as to the way in which this should be done. . . . Meta- physics takes its stand on this side of human nature, this desire to think about and comprehend reality. And it merely asserts that, if the attempt is to be made, it should be done as thoroughly as our nature permits." On the second count, he maintains, as we have seen, that even a " miserably incomplete " know- ledge of the Absolute must have its usefulness. But in a passage of characteristic frankness and force he contends that, even if metaphysics has no positive 136 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. results, it would still be highly desirable that it should continue to be studied : There is, so far as I can see, no other way of protecting ourselves against dogmatic superstition. Our orthodox theology on the one hand, and our commonplace material- ism on the other (it is natural to take these as prominent instances) vanish like ghosts before the daylight of free sceptical inquiry. I do not mean, of course, to condemn wholly either of these beliefs ; but I am sure that either, when taken seriously, is the mutilation of our nature. Neither, as experience has amply shown, can now survive in the mind which has thought sincerely on first principles. That is one reason why I think that metaphysics, even if it end in total scepticism, should be studied by a certain number of persons. But, while thus insisting on the indispensable func- tion of metaphysical inquiry, Mr Bradley is not the man to magnify his office as metaphysician unduly. And in the Meredithian extracts from his note-book which conclude the preface, he characteristically turns the shafts of his irony against his own occupation. "Metaphysics," it is there written, "is the finding of bad reasons for what we believe upon instinct, but to find these reasons is no less an instinct." From the other glimpses vouchsafed into this note -book, its aphoristic treasures would appear to be of a highly various and piquant description. They cannot but A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 137 awaken an unchastened curiosity in the heart of many students, which it is to be hoped the owner of the note- book may take measures to satisfy. Mr Bradley starts with a threefold general definition of metaphysics. "We may agree, perhaps, to under- stand by metaphysics an attempt to know reality as against mere appearance, or the study of first prin- ciples or ultimate truths, or again the effort to com- prehend the universe, not simply piecemeal or by fragments, but somehow as a whole." These three definitions are plainly intended to be taken as equi- valent, but, though the third is probably the most satisfactory of the three, it is the first which gives the title to Mr Bradley 's volume, and it is the con- trast between appearance or, as he calls it here, "mere appearance" and reality that explains the two parts into which it falls. The first book, entitled " Appearance," is a sceptical or destructive criticism of the phenomenal world as inherently self -contradictory and incomprehensible, and therefore, in Mr Bradley's use of the word, unreal. The second book, entitled " Eeality," though also abounding in negative criticism of obnoxious "preconceptions," is the constructive complement of Book I., intended to describe the nature of the Absolute, in which the contradictionsof pheno- 138 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. mena must be somehow reconciled or overcome. It is important at the outlet, for the understanding of Mr Bradley 's argument, especially in its negative or sceptical aspect, to note the equivalence, or at least interchangeableness, of these different formulations of the metaphysician's task, even though his procedure and conclusions should turn out to be unduly dominated by the first. Keality is used by Mr Bradley through- out in the sense of ultimate reality, so that reality and the absolute are convertible terms, and he means by both " the universe " comprehended " somehow as a whole." Appearance, on the other hand, is applied to the whole of the phenomenal world. Appearances, of course, exist, as he repeatedly tells us, but they are not real, in the sense of being independent, self-con- tained and self-explanatory. We fall into hopeless contradictions if we attempt to take them so. Every finite or phenomenal fact betrays its character of " mere appearance " by the " ragged edges " which stamp it as a part torn out of its context. The self- contradiction of the part taken as the whole, the phenomenal taken as the real, is most obvious in the infinite progress upon which it launches us a species of treadmill exercise, best exemplified in the case of such notions as time, space, and causation. A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 139 The contradictions of the finite are, accordingly, the theme of Mr Bradley's First Book, in which he sets out to criticise the chief " ideas by which we try to under- stand the universe." Taking up, first, the popular scientific proposal to find the reality of the world in the primary qualities, he has little difficulty in showing that the line of thought which undermines the reality of the secondary qualities can be used with equal effect against the primary. The primary qualities cannot be conceived or presented without the second- ary ; and, further, we cannot think of extension with- out thinking at the same time of a " what " that is extended. Extension is, therefore, simply the abstrac- tion of one element from the rest, from which it is in reality inseparable an abstraction scientifically convenient, but metaphysically indefensible, when it puts itself forward as an ultimate account of things. The distinction of "substantive and adjective" the grouping of the world's contents into things and qualities is next taken up (chap, ii.) and declared to be "a clear makeshift." If we lay stress on the unity of the thing, then the plurality of its attributes is in no way explained ; they lie side by side in mere distinctness one from another, as so many independent coexistences. 140 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. The whole device is a clear makeshift. It consists in saying to the outside world, " I am the owner of these my adjectives," and to the properties, " I am but a relation, which leaves you your liberty." And to itself and for itself it is the futile pretence to have both characters at once. . . . The thing with its adjectives is a device for enjoying at once both variety and concord. But the distinctions, once made, fall apart from the thing, and away from one another, and our attempt to understand their relations brought us round merely to an unity, which confesses itself a pretence, or else falls back upon the old undivided substance which admits of no distinctions (p. 23). The next chapter (chap, iii.) analyses the ideas of quality and relation. Qualities depend upon the relation of things to one another; unrelated reals would be qualityless. But, on the other hand, "nothings cannot be related;" "relations must de- pend upon terms, just as much as terms upon rela- tions." Consequently, all thinking that moves by the machinery of terms and relations is pronounced to be "a makeshift, a device, a mere practical com- promise, most necessary, but in the end most inde- fensible." For there is the same attempt to bring di- versity into the unity of the thing, an attempt which proves impossible except by dividing the thing alto- gether into an endless process of relations. Hence, " our experience when relationed is not true ; " and A NEW THEOKY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 141 any one who has grasped the principle of this chapter, we are told, " will have condemned, almost without a hearing, the great mass of phenomena." Mr Bradley proceeds, however (in the next five chapters), to apply his principle more in detail to the cases of " space and time," " motion and change," " causation " and ''activity." In a time-honoured and somewhat well-worn argument, the aspects of discreteness and continuity in space are sceptically opposed to one another, and the conclusion reached that " space vanishes internally into relations between units which never can exist." Precisely the same argument holds of time ; hence, both are not real, but " contradictory appearances." The problem of change points back to the dilemma of the one and the many, the differences and the identity, the adjectives and the thing, the qualities and the relations. How anything can possibly be anything else was a question which defied our efforts. Change is little beyond an instance of this dilemma in principle. ... It asserts two of one, and so falls at once under the condemnation of our previous chapters. . . . Change, upon any hypothesis, is impossible. It can be no more than appearance (pp. 45-47). So with causation. If you resolve cause into identity, you eliminate the very fact to be explained the difference of the effect from its cause. For surely the 142 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. very problem of causation " consists in the differences and in their sequence in time." In fact, it is the old puzzle how to justify the attributing to a subject something other than itself, and which the subject is not. If " followed by B " is not the nature of A, then justify your predication. If it is essential to A, then justify, first, your taking A without it ; and in the next place show how, with such an incongruous nature, A can succeed in being more than unreal appearance" (p. 57). Activity is condemned because " nothing can be active without an occasion, and what is active, being made thus by the occasion, is so far passive." Hence, " it is certain that activity implies finitude, and otherwise possesses no meaning." It cannot, therefore, be an ultimate principle of explanation. Chap. viii. deals with " things," but the preceding argument has " under- mined and ruined " any meaning we can attach to the term. " The thing is a thing only if its existence goes beyond the now and extends into the past;" but "it does not appear how this relation of sameness can be real." "The identity of a thing lies in the view you take of it." "We seem driven to the conclusion that things are but appearances." So far, therefore, "our facts have turned out to be illusory," but we have been dealing up to this point with " the inanimate," and in order to complete his A NEW THEOKY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 143 argument Mr Bradley goes on in the next two chapters (chaps, ix. and x.) to criticise the claims of the Self to reality. In the first he passes in review different meanings of the self, and in the second he concludes that the self simply presents "the old puzzle as to the connection of diversity with unity." It will be necessary to return upon various points in these im- portant chapters, but we must first have Mr Bradley's main line of thought before us and the conclusion at which he arrives. It is sufficient, therefore, for the present, to note his verdict on the self, and the ground on which the verdict is explicitly based. "The con- sciousness of personal identity," he curiously says, " may be supposed to have some bearing on the reality of the self." Most people are probably benighted enough to think it has. But to my mind [proceeds Mr Bradley] it appears to be almost irrelevant. Of course the self, within limits and up to a certain point, is the same. ... As long as there re- mains in the self a certain basis of content, ideally the same, so long may the self recall anything once associated with that basis. . . . This, of course, shows that self-sameness exists as a fact, and that hence somehow an identical self is real. But, then, the question is how ? The question is whether we can state the existence and the continuity of a real self in a way which is intelligible, and which is not 144 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. ruined by the difficulties of previous discussions. Because, otherwise, we may have found an interesting fact, but most assuredly we have not found a tenable view about reality. . . . The end of metaphysics is to understand the uni- verse, to find a way of thinking about facts in general which is free from contradiction. . . . It is this, to repeat it once more, on which everything turns. The diversity and the unity must be brought to the light, and the principle must be seen to comprehend these. But the self is so far from supplying such a principle, that it seems, when not hiding itself in obscurity, a mere bundle of discrepancies. Our search has conducted us again, not to reality, but mere appearance (pp. 113, 120). The two short chapters on "Phenomenalism" and " Things in Themselves," which conclude the First Book, add nothing to this argument. They are rather of the nature of appendices, which deal effectively with these two phases of philosophic theory, as attempts either to evade the philosophical problem altogether, or to solve it by doubling it. As I am in complete agree- ment with Mr Bradley 's arguments in these pages, there is the less need to dwell upon them here. So I pass at once to the opening chapters of the Second Book, dealing with "The General Nature of Eeality," and containing the counter -stroke to the preceding negative polemic. The first position taken up is at once important, for A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 145 it alone enables a start to be made. Phenomena have been condemned as self-contradictory, but what is thus rejected as appearance admittedly still exists. " It cannot bodily be shelved and merely got rid of, and, therefore, since it must fall somewhere, it must belong to reality." Eeality, therefore, " must own," and some- how include, appearance ; it cannot be less than appear- ance. But whereas appearances, taken as real, proved self-contradictory, the absolute or ultimate reality must be " such that it does not contradict itself. This is our first criterion a criterion which has been implicit in all the preceding negative criticism." Accordingly... we may say, concludes Mr Bradley, that everything which appears is somehow real in such a way as to be self-consistent. . . . Appearance must belong to reality, and it must, therefore, be concordant and other than it seems. The bewildering mass of phenomenal diversity must hence somehow be at unity and self -consistent ; for it cannot be elsewhere than in reality, and reality excludes dis- cord. Or again, we may put it so ; the real is individual. It is one in the sense that its positive character embraces all deficiencies in an inclusive harmony (p. 140). In short, " reality must be a single whole " " a single system." In his second chapter Mr Bradley supple- ments this "formal and abstract" definition of the Absolute by identifying existence with "experience," K 146 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. laying down the position, almost in Berkeley's lan- guage, that existence has no meaning apart from sentient experience. " There is no being or fact out- side of that which is commonly called psychical existence." Any supposed fact, other than this, "is a vicious abstraction whose existence is meaningless nonsense, and is not possible." If we combine this with the former position, " our conclusion, so far, will be this, that the Absolute is one system, and that its contents are nothing but sentient experience. It will, hence, be a single and all-inclusive experience, which embraces every partial diversity in concord." Finally, Mr Bradley proceeds to ask whether we really have a positive idea of an Absolute, thus defined as " one com- prehensive sentience ; " and he answers that, while we cannot fully realise its existence, its main features are drawn from our own experience, and we have also a suggestion there of the unity of a whole embracing distinctions within itself. This we have in "mere feeling or immediate presentation," where we experi- ence as an undifferentiated whole, what we afterwards proceed, in the exercise of relational thought, to analyse into the known world of self and not -self, with all its manifold objects and distinctions. Combining this primitive experience of felt unity with the later ex- A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 147 perience of known diversity, we can recognise the latter as a transitional stage, and reach the idea of a higher experience in which thought shall, as it were, return to the immediacy of feeling. "We can form the general idea of an absolute intuition in which phenomenal distinctions are merged; a whole become immediate at a higher stage without losing any rich- ness." This view of the Absolute is developed and enforced in the immediately following chapter on "Thought and Keality" (chap, xv.) which, in various aspects, is one of the most important in the book. As such, it will claim our attention in the sequel ; but it is enough, in the meantime, to note a little more fully the nature of the results arrived at. The position reached is simply this, that "the relational form is a compromise on which thought stands and which it develops. It is an attempt to unite differences which have broken out of the felt totality" (p. 180). It is essentially an attempt to pass beyond itself and to recapture this immediate unity. But, both in theory and in practice, the attempt proves unsuccessful on the basis of thought or relation ; it resolves itself into the infinite progress. Thought's own ideal, there- fore, can be reached only by passing beyond thought. For us " this completion of thought beyond thought " 148 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. necessarily "remains for ever an other." Still " thought can form the idea of an apprehension, something like feeling in directness, which contains all the character sought by its relational efforts" "a total experience where will and thought and feeling may all once more be one," and where consequently the distinction between thought and its object between subject and predicate is likewise transcended. 1 We have now before us one complete phase of Mr Bradley 's position and argumentation, and it is time, therefore, to investigate critically the legitimacy of the method and the value of the conclusion. Mr Bradley started, as we saw, with two somewhat different defini- tions of the Absolute ; and, in like manner, his criticism throughout the First Book seems to rest upon two some- what different principles. The one condemns pheno- mena because they are fragmentary ; no object of experience is by itself a res completa, an independent and self-contained individual, strong in solid singleness, self-explaining, harmonious and all-inclusive. What- ever fact we take proves to be infected by external relations, and so carries us beyond itself, and ultimately brings in the whole context of the universe. Thus 1 See pp. 160, 172, 179, 181. A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 149 activity transforms itself into passivity, because we cannot think of activity as (so to speak) a mere bolt from the blue an unconditioned fiat out of a blank eternity. The beginning of the activity of anything depends, for our thinking, upon a stimulus from beyond the nature of the thing itself ; and the thing, therefore, is quite as much passive as active. This argument may be applied all round. Thought cannot rest in any finite individual, but is carried beyond it in an infinite pro- gress. So with any portion of space or time in which we arbitrarily and momentarily rest ; so with things, so last of all with the finite self. For I do not imagine that those who insist most strongly on the reality of the self, and hold that " it provides us with a type by the aid of which we may go on to comprehend the world/' are at all inclined to assert its reality in Mr Bradley's sense of all-inclusive self-sufficience. Obviously, the self of any individual, in the determinations of its character and the occasions of its activity, carries us beyond the self, just as in the case of things which are not selves. The self cannot be torn from its environment except by a process of violent abstraction ; and the environment, if we are to be exact, must be ultimately extended so as to include all time and all existence. To my mind, it requires no argument to establish the position that 150 A NEW THEOKY OF THE ABSOLUTE. there can be only one individual as a res completa, and consequently, in Mr Bradley's sense, only one reality, namely, the Absolute or the universe as a whole. To fail to realise this is to fail to rise to the light of reason at all ; it is, in Spinoza's phrase, to remain at the stage of "imagination," with its blind substantiation of the individuals of sense just as we find them, or seem to find them. In this whole line of argument, therefore including his admirable exposure of the fallacy of a plurality of independent reals Mr Bradley is certain to meet with hearty acquiescence in most quarters that are worth considering. But this line of argument does not seem sufficient of itself to justify the sweeping condemnation of phenomena as " mere appearance," " illusion," " self- contradictory appearance," "irrational appearance," " essentially made of inconsistencies," and the other terms of excommunication in which Mr Bradley in- dulges. Because a thing is not the Absolute, and never pretended to be, it seems a little hard to "ruin" its character by a string of bad names like this. And, as a matter of fact, the " ruin " in which Mr Bradley in- volves the phenomenal is more properly the consequence of a second line of argument, which is on the whole more prominent throughout the First Book. This argu- A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 151 ment is neither more nor less than the complete dis- crepancy of the One and the Many the impossibility of realising at all in thought any kind of identity in diversity. The passages quoted in the earlier part of this essay illustrate sufficiently the constant recur- rence of this idea. At the very outset, in dealing with substantive and adjective, it is referred to as " the old dilemma." If you predicate what is different, you ascribe to the subject what it is not ; and if you predi- cate what is not different, you say nothing at all (p. 20). The dilemma is, in truth, as old as the early Greek nominalists and sceptics who denied on these grounds the possibility of predication altogether, except in the form of an identical proposition. To say that " Socrates is good," would be to say the thing that is not; for " Socrates " and " good " are not the same, but different. "Socrates" is one idea, and "good" is another. "Socrates is Socrates," and " good is good ; " but that the one should be the other, is quite unintelligible. We are limited, therefore, to the one kind of proposition which we never make, A = A. Now, strange as it may seem, Mr Bradley's First Book is, in essence, neither more nor less than a restatement and re- enforcement of this sceptical thesis. He adopts this logic of abstract identity apparently without reserve, and because it brings him 152 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. to a dead-lock, he pronounces the actual world to be " unintelligible," " inconsistent," " self - contradictory," " irrational," " untrue," " illusory." His multitudinous repetitions seem designed to leave us in no doubt that it is everywhere the same touchstone which he applies. Thus, the conclusion of the third chapter, on " Eelation and Quality," is, as we have seen, that a relational way of thought is "a mere practical compromise, most necessary, but in the end most indefensible." We have to take reality [he continues] as Many, and to take it as One, and to avoid contradiction. . . . But when these inconsistencies are forced together, as in meta- physics they must be, the result is an open and staring discrepancy. . . . Our intellect, then, has been con- demned to confusion and bankruptcy, and the reality has been left outside uncomprehended (pp. 33, 34). In the next chapter, " Space ... is a peculiar form of the problem which we discussed in the last chapter, and is a special attempt to combine the irreconcilable " (p. 36). In the fifth chapter (in the passage already quoted) the problem of change points back to the dilemma of the One and the Many, the differences and the identity, the adjectives and the thing, the qualities and the relations. How anything can possibly be anything else was a question which defied our efforts. Change is little beyond an instance of this dilemma in A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 153 principle. . . . Change, it is obvious, must be a change of something, and it is obvious, further, that it contains diversity. Hence it asserts two of one, and so falls at once under the condemnation of our previous chapters (p. 45). So in the following chapter, on " Causation " : If the sequence of the effect is different from the cause, how is the ascription of the difference to be rationally defended ? If, on the other hand, it is not different, then causation does not exist, and its assertion is a farce (p. 55). We assert something of something else. ... It is the old puzzle, how to justify the attributing to a subject something other than itself, and which the subject is not (p. 57). Having found things "go to pieces" when confronted with this test, he finds the same result on applying it to the self. It is the old puzzle as to the connection of diversity with unity. As the diversity becomes more complex and the unity grows more concrete, we have, so far, found that our difficulties steadily increase, and the expectation of a sudden change and a happy solution, when we arrive at the self, seems hence little warranted. . . . You may say that we are each assured of our personal identity in a way in which we are not assured of the sameness of things. But this is unfortunately quite irrelevant to the question. That selves exist, and are identical in some sense, is indubitable. But the doubt is whether their sameness, as we apprehend it, is really intelligible. . . . Does it give an experience 154 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. by the help of which we can really understand the way in which diversity is harmonised 1 (pp. 103, 104). The self, as feeling, thrusts upon us, " in a still more apparent form, the discrepancy that lies between identity and diversity, immediate oneness and relation" (p. 107). If, again, self-consciousness is proposed as " a special way of intuition or perception," we are forced to ask (supposing such a " self-apprehension of the self as one and many " to exist) how it can " satisfy the claims of understanding." "For the contents of the intuition (this many in one), if you try to re- construct * them relationally, fall asunder forthwith. I am, in short, compelled to this conclusion, even if your intuition is a fact, it is not an under- standing of the self or of the world. It is a mere experience" (p. 108). In whatever aspect the self is taken, therefore, it does not teach us " how to under- stand diversity or unity" (p. 112). What we want is " a view . . . combining differences in one so as to turn the edge of criticism" (p. 114), and this we have not met with. The self, as will or volition, leaves us involved in all "the old troubles as to 1 The italics in the passage last quoted are Mr Bradley 's own, and I desire specially to call attention to the emphasis, as it corroborates my contention and contains the key to Mr Bradley's position. A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 155 diversity in union with sameness " (p. 115). In com- menting on the theory of Monads, towards the close of his discussion, he repeats his old question : Will it in the least show us how 1 the diversity can exist in harmony with the oneness, (p. 118). . . . "We have found so far [he says] that diversity and unity cannot be reconciled. Both in the existence of the whole self in relation with its contents, and in the various special forms which that existence takes, we have encountered everywhere the same trouble. We have had features which must come together, and yet were willing to do so in no way that we could find. In the self there is a variety, and in the self there is an unity ; but in attempting to understand how, we fall into inconsistencies which, therefore, cannot be truth (p. 118). The self, he finally concludes, does not yield us " any defensible thought, any intellectual principle, ly which it is possible to understand how diversity can be com- prehended in unity. It is this, to repeat it once more, on which everything turns. The diversity and the unity must be brought to the light, and the principle must be seen to comprehend these" (pp. 119, 120). The short chapter on " Phenomenalism " adds two further references to " the metaphysical problem of the Many in One" (pp. 124, 125); and, in the last chapter, things-in-themselves are found to " offer pre- 1 The italics are again Mr Bradley's own. 156 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. cisely the old jungle in which no way could be found " (p. 130). I have multiplied these references, at the risk of wearying the reader, in order to convince him, if he needs convincing, of the uniform and persistent nature of Mr Bradley 's demand. It seems to me, moreover, that Mr Bradley's position here conditions the whole nature of the results he arrives at later. For the logic of abstract identity which he brings into the field against phenomena is fatal in the end to his Absolute also, reducing it, in spite of Mr Bradley's disclaimer in spite of his sincere endeavour to avoid such a con- summation to the undifferentiated unity of Spinoza's Substance. According to this logic, each qualityless point remains identical with itself (A = A), and so does each unreferred quality, flying loose in the heaven of abstraction (red is red, a is a, and b is 5). But the living synthesis of fact the qualified thing, A that is a, b, c, d, any number of differences, in unity this, if not actually denied as in some sense existing, is yet declared to be unintelligible, hopelessly contradictory. But surely such an argument marks the very acme of logical perversity. Such an argument, in truth, imports into predication a meaning or intention of which predi- cation never dreams. When we say "man is mortal," A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 157 or "the beech has a smooth stem," we do not mean that the concept " man " is identical with the concept " mortal," or that the two concepts " beech " and " smooth - stemmed " are actually one and the same concept. What we mean is that the reality, which we have already qualified as "man" or "beech," is further qualified as " mortal " or " smooth-stemmed." All predication, in short, is about facts, not about concepts except in the special cases where we happen to be defining a word. Certainly every concept or meaning remains itself, and only itself, to all eternity. That at least is the convention on which logic stands; our terms must bear the same meaning throughout, otherwise all reasoning would be impossible. The law of identity or of non-contradiction means no more than this obviously indispensable con- vention a convention which, if we are so minded, we may truthfully describe as a fundamental and necessary law of thought, so long as we see clearly its innocent and unobtrusive meaning. The law of identity says that, if we predicate mortality of man, we cannot also predicate non-mortality ; it says that, if it is the nature of the beech to be smooth - stemmed, it cannot also be its nature to be rough-stemmed. But, as to the nature of predication, or as to the possibility or impos- 158 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. sibility of a thing existing as the unity of diverse qual- ities, it gives no verdict one way or another. These are questions of fact or of metaphysics which lie beyond its scope. To proceed, therefore, on the strength of the law of identity, to condemn the idea of a thing possessing qualities, or, in general, the idea of unity in diversity, as a contradiction in terms, is logically a complete nerd/Baa-is et? aXXo <yevos. Now Mr Bradley tells us that "a thing without qualities is clearly unreal" (p. 130), and in his chapter on "Phenomenalism" he proves that the opposite attempt, to rest in qualities without a thing, is equally untrue to reality. But his own doctrine is that the attempt to think a thing with qualities, or, in general, the attempt to think a unity in diversity, ends in hopeless contradiction. It looks, therefore, as if thought were brought face to face with an absolute impasse. The whole force of his argument appears, however, to rest on this illegitimate extension to reality or experience of a law which holds true only of con- cepts, as concepts, in the narrow sense just explained. Eeality, it may be said boldly, is essentially a many-in- one, and this holds true of any part of reality i.e., of any existent fact. This, it seems to me, was the in- sight that lent force and cogency to Hegel's life-long A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 159 polemic against the abstract understanding and its vaunted law of non-contradiction. Against its abstract identity he held up the concrete facts of experience: there is nothing which is a mere one, an eternal self- sameness. Identity only exists through difference, unity through multiplicity. Such is the constant thesis of the Hegelian philosophy, of which Mr Bradley is one of the profoundest students; and it was, I confess, a surprise to me to find the ancient weapon of the sceptical schools so carefully furbished up and so confidently brandished. All the more so, because Mr Bradley himself, aliud agenda with the atomic sensationalism of the English tradition in view gives a most impressive statement of the true position, and declares in his own emphatic way that "every movement of our intellect rests wholly upon it," and that the contrary opinion is founded upon "one-sided and uncritical metaphysics," or " in short had no basis but confusion and traditional prejudice" (pp. 349-351). " There will be neither change nor endurance, and still less motion through space of an identical body ; there will neither be selves nor things, nor, in brief, any intelligible fact, unless on the assumption that sameness in diversity is real. Apart from this main principle of construction, we should be confined to the feeling 160 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. of a single moment." Now these " intelligible facts" are the very facts paraded as unintelligible in Book I. Hegel no doubt gave a dangerous opening to mis- conception, when he spoke of the dialectic as exhibiting itself in the conceptions of the " Logic." It is only by a sustained use of metaphor that the appearance of success is obtained ; for conceptions, as such, are pre- cisely what do not " pass over " into their opposites. The conception "One" never becomes the conception " Many." What is true is, that every fact can be shown to combine in itself these two aspects. It is in this way that Hegel uses the nature of reality to explode, and (by exploding) to unite, the fixed opposites of con- ceptual thought. These opposites, it must be remem- bered, are, and remain, opposites in the abstract world of logic ; viewed, that is to say, simply as meanings, the one remains just the opposite of the other. But this opposition of the two as meanings, as concepts, tells us nothing about the possibility or impossibility of a fact to which, in different aspects, both shall be applic- able. On that the nature of reality itself must decide : we must appeal to experience. In making this appeal, we have no need to go further than the fact of our own existence, which is indeed the key of the whole position. The self is very severely A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 161 handled by Mr Bradley, though he does admit at the close that it is " no doubt the highest form of experience which we have" (p. 119). His argument consists largely in enumerating, and setting against one another, different senses in which the term "self" has been, or is currently, used. Some of these may be dismissed as irrelevant that is to say, we may surrender them at once to Mr Bradley's criticism as of no particular interest. The remainder of his argument seems to me to rest partly on the first line of thought viz., that no self of which we have experience is an absolute, perfect, or self-sufficient unity, which, again, may be fully granted and partly on the practical difficulty of precisely defining the amount of diversity which shall be included within the unity of the individual self. Here also many a point might be surrendered to meet Mr Bradley's criticism. He reminds us, for example, that " in the lifetime of a man there are irreparable changes. Is he literally not the same man if loss, or death, or love, or banishment has turned the current of his life ? " (p. 79.) This is a question of degree. The wrench may be so great as actually, in the common phrase, to unhinge the mind; and in that case, we admittedly cease to regard the man as the same. His personality is altogether suspended; he L 162 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. is insane. So with " the strange selves of hypnotism," to which Mr Bradley several times refers. Such ab- normalities involve practical difficulties, just like the "monsters" to which Locke so frequently recurs, or the cases where it may be difficult to decide whether an object belongs to the animal or the vegetable kingdom. But they do not touch the question of principle with which we are here concerned. It is not necessary that a self should be an all-inclusive whole ; nor is it necessary that we should be able, in every case, to say what is a self and what is not a self. It is enough if there is such a thing as self- consciousness or personal identity at all. For that self - consciousness is the living experience of unity in diversity. Now Mr Bradley admits that "of course the self, within limits and up to a certain point, is the" same," though, as we saw, he strangely treats this conscious- ness of personal identity as " almost irrelevant." The key to this utterance is found in the following page, where he adds, " This, of course, shows that self- sameness exists as a fact, and that hence somehow an identical self must be real. But then the ques- tion is how?" (p. 113.) To this I see no answer save Lotze's retort in similar circumstances, that A NEW THEOEY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 163 such a question is as unreasonable, and as perfectly impossible to satisfy, as the demand to know how being is made. How there comes to be existence at all, and how existence or experience in its basal characteristics comes to be what it is these are questions which, so far as one can see, omniscience itself would not enable us to answer. The funda- mental nature of experience may enable us to ex- plain derivatively any special feature of experience; but that fundamental nature itself must be learned from experience and simply accepted. Now I main- tain that unity in multiplicity, identity in diversity, is just the ultimate nature of universal experience. Such a unity or identity is lived or experienced in every instance of self - conscious existence ; and it cannot be other than a misleading use of language to speak of our most intimate experience, the ultimate bed-rock of fact, as unintelligible or contradictory. The whole procedure of thought belies such a sup- position; for, instead of stumbling over this unity and identity as unintelligible, we proceed to make it the measure or standard of the intelligibility of every- thing else. The thing and its qualities is a mere analogue of the self as a many in one ; all our terms of explanation, all the categories of thought, are drawn 164 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. in like manner from the life of the self. They either reproduce it with more- or less fulness, or, if they do not do this, then they express one or other of its aspects. But it is our own fault if we choose to substantiate these aspects, stated thus for the moment in logical or ideal separation ; for they are never given or experienced separately. On the contrary, their concrete unity is the one fact behind which we cannot go. Thought, when it occupies itself in dissecting its own nature, is led into many a bog by the will-o'-the wisp of a false subtlety by none more so than by this phantasm of abstract identity. But thought, which is directed on its object, and bent only on learning more and more of the nature of things, never seeks thus to overleap itself, and consequently finds none of the unintelligibility of which Mr Bradley complains. In truth, as Berkeley happily puts it, philosophers are often indebted to their own pre- conceptions "for being ignorant of what everybody else knows perfectly well." And seriously, according to the well-worn brocard, if water chokes us what shall we drink ? If our own existence is unintelligible to us, where are we likely to find intelligibility ? If the one and the many are as absolutely incompatible as they have been A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 165 represented, how are they to be brought together at all ? In other words, if the criticism in the First Book is really valid, it would seem to be equally fatal to the construction of the Absolute attempted in the Second. For the Absolute, we have seen, must " own " or include appearances, and it must do so in such a way as to exclude contradiction. It is to be "a single and all- inclusive experience, which embraces every partial diversity in concord " (p. 147). Doubtless this is our ideal of what an Absolute should be ; but surely (to quote Mr Bradley's own words) we have here "at once upon our hands the One and the Many." This Absolute " offers precisely the old jungle in which no way could be found " ; and it is irrational to suppose that a sheer contradiction will prove more amenable, when multiplied to infinity, and housed in the Absolute. An unkind critic might say, indeed, with some show of reason, that Mr Bradley has the air of swallowing at a gulp, in Book II., what he had choked over in the successive chapters of Book I. For, if, as was insisted in the case of the self, " the question is how," the Second Book is full of the most ample acknowledgments that the " how " remains as insoluble as ever. " Certainly in the end," we are told, " to know how the One and the Many are united is beyond our powers. But in 166 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. the Absolute, somehow, we are convinced the problem is solved" (p. 281). But this is the language of pious conviction rather than of scientific demonstration ; and though the attentive reader discerns plainly the author's resolve that the Absolute has got to include all differ- ences and solve all contradictions, he will be apt to feel that the contradictions forced upon his notice throughout the book have been handed back to him, to digest as best he may. In the end, this impression would not, I think, be substantially incorrect ; and yet it would certainly not be entirely just to Mr Bradley, for he certainly does attempt in the Second Book to give in outline a theory of the " how." What he would undoubtedly have us regard as his real contribution towards a solution of the difficulty, is to be found in the chapter on " Thought and Eeality." He still maintains that the "contra- diction " is insoluble on the level of relational thought ; but founding in this chapter on the analogy of feeling, as containing the immediate experience of a whole, he throws out the idea of a supra-relational existence of the Absolute, which shall, so to speak, fuse once more, in an immediate unity, the differences which the process of knowledge has shown were implicit in the primitive undifferentiated unity of feeling. On A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 167 examination, however, it will be found, I think, that, in the end, this theory meets the difficulty by abolish- ing the differences. Instead, therefore, of being a real solution, it is at bottom a reaffirmation of Mr Bradley's fundamental preconception as to the incompatibility of the One and the Many. Notwithstanding this, the presentation of the theory is full of speculative interest. It is not a new thing in philosophy to attempt to name, and even to conceive, the divine life in this way, as a knowledge that is more than relational, that does not proceed from part to part, but sees the whole in every part, or rather sees all differences in unity, by a species of immediate apprehension or intuition. So much may be said to be a commonplace of philosophical theology. And in the Kantian and post-Kantian philosophy of Germany, as is well known, the doctrine of a per- ceptive understanding or an intellectual intuition played an important part. But what lends importance to this fresh attempt to put a meaning into the phrase is the independence of the treatment the way in which the idea is seen to grow organically out of the author's whole scheme of thought and also the deliberate endeavour which is made really "to form the idea" 168 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. of such an apprehension, even though only " in vague generality." But, ungracious return as it may seem for the metaphysical feast which Mr Bradley has spread, the objection must still be urged that this supra-relational reconciliation either remains, on the one hand, altogether a name for " we know not what," or, on the other hand, if we press the analogy of feeling, as Mr Bradley frequently does, and endeavour to con- struct, even in vague generality, the nature of the absolute experience, the conviction is forced upon us that this Absolute excludes contradiction, only because it excludes all variety and difference. In the former case, the diversity is acknowledged, but no light is thrown upon the problem of combining Many in One without contradiction. " In the end," says Mr Bradley, "the whole diversity must be attributed as adjectives to a unity which is not known" (p. 469). Our assertion of a unity becomes then no more than an expression of the faith that with God all things are possible. In the latter case, finite existence is an illusion, which ceases when the standpoint of the Absolute is reached. Finite existence is said to be harmonised, or, in Mr Bradley's favourite expression, "transmuted" in the Absolute ; but for transmuted, we also find such sinister A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 169 synonyms as "suppressed," "dissolved," "lost." In one place, "transmuted and destroyed" are expressly coupled ; while, in another, we are told that the " pro- cess of correction " which finite existence undergoes in the Absolute may " entirely dissipate its nature." Of course, Mr Bradley protests in numerous passages against this interpretation of his Absolute as a blank or undifferentiated unity, like Spinoza's Substance or Schelling's Neutrum, the night in which all cows are black. And we may readily believe that he does not mean simply to " merge " or " fuse " all distinctions into an indistinguishable mass, but somehow to retain them, in a richer form, in a single concrete experience. I will go further, and say that one whole line of Mr Bradley's thought the line in which he stands nearest to Hegel leads him to emphasise the function of differ- ence and the permanence of distinctions even within the Absolute. But that line of thought is more than neutralised by the Spinozistic or Schellingian tendency which we are at present considering. The best of intentions cannot avail him, therefore, against the manifest destiny of this way of thinking. In the very title of his book, Mr Bradley seems to me to have started upon the road which leads to this I, for " appearance " is certainly, on the whole, a 170 A NEW THEOKY OF THE ABSOLUTE. term of condemnation ; and, as we have seen, it is frequently qualified throughout the first book, and also in the second, as " mere appearance," and even as " illusion." Appearance, therefore, takes on, whether we will or no, the sense of illusory or unreal. And it is to be observed that Mr Bradley is con- sistent, to the end, in his refusal to tolerate difference. The distinction of subject and predicate remains to him a contradiction, an imperfection, and consequently must disappear in the Absolute ; and, with it, the dis- tinction of subject and object from which it is derived. And that the last vestige of difference may be seen to disappear from the pure aether of " all-pervasive trans- fusion," we have the position pushed to its most quixotic length in the sections of the concluding chapter which remind us that "not even absolute truth is quite true." It is not true, for the extra- ordinary reason that it is only true of reality ; it is not itself reality. The fatal "difference between subject and predicate " remains, and therefore " even absolute truth in the end seems thus to turn out erroneous " ! I cannot but think that speculation is here upon an entirely false track. What Mr Bradley really means, I suppose, is to renew his famous, and in my view important, protest against the identification of reality A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 171 with "an unearthly ballet of bloodless categories." He is arguing against the tendency, observable in some representatives of Hegelian thought, to overstate the position and function of knowledge. Because know- ledge (especially in its highest form as philosophy) is in its own sphere, as Mr Bradley puts it, " utterly all-inclusive " that is, because knowledge, if perfect, may be said ideally to grasp or include every aspect of reality these thinkers speak as if such knowledge were the reality " bodily," as if the universe were nothing but an intellectual process, a species of dia- lectic. Against this tendency Mr Bradley rightly urges, that " truth " or perfect knowledge is only one aspect of the universe or of experience. "The uni- verse is not known, and it never, as a whole, can be known, in such a sense that knowledge would be the same as experience or reality " (p. 547). " This general character of reality is not reality itself " (p. 547). Truth is not intellectually defective or limited, for the idea of an unknowable may easily be shown to be self-contradictory; it is not, therefore, "intellectually corrigible " " it cannot be intellectually transcended." Still there are other aspects of experience besides the intellectual, and if we are to have reality " bodily," we must "take in the remaining aspects of experience." 172 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. But this sound and valuable contention is surely pre- sented in a misleading, form, when Mr Bradley talks of an " internal discrepancy " which belongs to truth's proper character, and represents truth as achieving its consummation "in passing beyond itself, and in abolishing the difference between the subject and predicate " (p. 547). For " in this passage the proper nature of truth is, of course, transformed and perishes." But this extinction of difference throws us back at once on the distinctionless supra-essential one of mysticism, in which all " details are utterly pervaded and em- braced." The collapse of the distinction between subject and predicate (or subject and object) means, however, the extinction of self-consciousness altogether, and throws us back upon the state of dull, diffused feeling, which we suppose to be asymptotically ap- proached in the lowest organisms, and from which (in the same asymptotic fashion) we are accustomed to derive the beginnings of conscious life. Here, there- fore, extremes would meet with a vengeance, and the highest become interchangeable with the lowest." Dissatisfaction with the form of knowledge as such seems to me, I must confess, chimerical ; and I am sure that repudiation of it leads not to any higher unity, but to the pit of undifferentiated substance out A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 173 of which Hegel dug philosophy. And I venture to add that this is verified in Mr Bradley's own case. On this whole side of his thought, he seems to me to reproduce in essence, and often almost in expression, the Spinozistic doctrine of " imagination," which re- duces finite existence to a species of illusion. No doubt there were two tendencies at strife in Spinoza also. But his dominant thought is, " all determination is negation " ; and therefore all determinations are de- voured, like clouds before the sun, in the white light of the unica substantia. But if finite experience is illusory, and its distinctions simply disappear, then, of necessity, the unity which we reach by the denial of these distinctions is quite characterless ; we have illusion on the one side, and, as the counter -stroke, nonentity on the other. For does not Erigena tell us at the end of a similar line of thought, " Deus propter excellentiam non immerito nihil vocatur " a phrase the piety of which seems to me with difficulty to conceal its humour ? Mr Bradley displays an extraordinary fertility in metaphors to describe the consummation of finite ap- pearance in the Absolute; but the nature of these metaphors involuntarily confirms the view of his Absolute which we have already arrived at on general 174 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. principles. Appearances are merged, fused, blended, absorbed, run together,, dissolved in a higher unity, transformed, transmuted ; but to transform is found to mean the same thing as to dissipate, and to trans- mute is to " destroy " or to " suppress." To " embrace " and " harmonise " self-consciousness by transmuting and suppressing it as such (p. 183) recalls too vividly the Roman method of pacification : ubi solitudinem faciunt, pacem appellant. And if Spinoza's Absolute has been called a lion's den, the description is at least as applicable to Mr Bradley's. " All the content, which the struggle has generated, is brought home and is laid to rest undiminished in the perfect" (p. 244). Does not this suggest the stillness of the grave ? Or when we are told that " the finites blend and are resolved " (p. 429); that "every finite diversity is supplemented and transformed ; its private character remains and is but neutralised by complement and addition " ; does it not seem like saying " yes " and " no " in the same breath ? How can a private character remain, if it is neutralised ? Plus and minus are equivalent to noth- ing; our result is a blank Schellingian Neutrum. And Mr Bradley's statement, that " the theoretic ob- ject moves towards a consummation in which all dis- tinction and all ideality must be suppressed," is almost A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 175 verbally identical with Schelling's account of the ulti- mate goal of the finite Ego. The ultimate goal of the finite Ego is enlargement of its sphere till the attainment of identity with the infinite Ego. But the infinite Ego knows no object, and possesses, there- fore, no consciousness or unity of consciousness, such as we mean by personality. Consequently, the ultimate goal of all endeavour may also be represented as enlargement of the personality to infinity that is to say, as its annihil- at'on. The ultimate goal of the finite Ego, and not only of it but also of the Non-Ego the final goal, therefore, of the world is its annihilation as a world. 1 The coincidence seems worth noting, because it in- dicates that both thinkers are haunted by the same ideal, the ideal against which Hegel protests. So again, when talking of the finite self, Mr Bradley uses a metaphor which, though he excuses its " mise- rable inaccuracy," I cannot help regarding as exceed- ingly significant in this connection. " Because I can- not spread out my window until all is transparent, and all windows disappear, this does not justify me in insist- ing on my window-frame's rigidity. For that frame has, as such, no existence in reality, but only in our impotence " (p. 253). This seems to me as exact a re- production as can well be imagined of the Spinozistic 1 Vom Ich als Princip der Philosophie, 14. 176 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. doctrine of imaginatio. The window-frames of the self disappear or melt away, because in reality they do not exist at all ; it is our impotence which causes us to imagine this severance from others and from the source of all. According to the metaphor by which Erdmann illustrates Spinoza's system, wipe out from any spatial surface the lines which mark it off into distinct figures, and pure or empty space remains. Abolish, in like manner, all window -frames, and "limited transpar- encies " disappear, as Mr Bradley puts it, in " an all-embracing clearness." But, as we know, the dis- tinction of subject and object has disappeared with the other distinctions of finite appearance ; and the clearness, therefore, is not a vision seen by any self. It is the viewless unity of the absolutely infinite Substance. On whatever line of metaphor or analogy we follow Mr Bradley, the same result is arrived at the same inherent tendency of his thought is revealed. This is curiously seen in his recurring illustration from Love. Thought, he says, desires "a consummation in which it is lost." And he adds, by way of establishing such a possibility, " does not the river run into the sea and the self lose itself in love ? " (p. 173.) The river does run into the sea, but so far is the self from losing it- A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 177 self in love, that it may be said therein to attain to its intensest realisation not realisation in Mr Bradley's equivocal sense of " disappearing " or " ceasing," but realisation in the sense of intensest life and enjoyment in that particular finite centre. So, again, Mr Bradley tells us (p. 182) that, in feeling, thought, or volition, the one reality is present in " a form which does not satisfy." " In each it longs for that absolute self-fruition which comes only when the self bursts its limits and blends with another finite self." But the self never " bursts " and " blends " in the way suggested. In all enjoyment, in all fruition, there is the return of the self upon itself, without which consciousness would be impossible. What is meant by a self- fruition, in which the self disappears ? I do not mean to deny that in extreme sensual passion, and in the curiously allied mystical straining to swoon, as it were, into Deity, this self- deception is observable as to the goal pursued. But I assert that, in both cases, the desire is self-contradic- tory ; for of love, whether sexual or divine, the poet's words (in another sense) are true, that its dearest bond is "like in difference." If difference could be abolished, whether as regards two human beings or as regards a finite individual and its creative source, " sweet love were slain " its very conditions would be M 178 A NEW THEOKY OF THE ABSOLUTE. destroyed. Consciousness itself would be abolished, existence would collapse into nothingness. We come back, therefore, to our main contention. There is no contradiction in the form of knowledge as such, nor in finite experience merely on the ground that it is in this form. On the contrary, knowledge is rather, as Hegel said, the absolute relation ; and all speculation which proceeds by repudiation of this form is found historically to lead straight to the " abyss " of the older mystics. Mr Bradley's speculation simply repeats this lesson. Clearly, the finite is, in Mr Brad- ley's phrase, essentially self-transcendent. That is as much as to say, more simply, that our experience is fragmentary ; and however much we enlarge it, it still remains fragmentary. On all sides it seems to stretch infinitely beyond itself. Knowledge, it cannot be denied, is in our experience an infinite progress ; and if to have this character is to be contradictory, then the charge must be freely admitted. But it does not seem as if this defect this contradiction were inherent in the form of knowledge as such (the form of subject-object, unity in difference) ; the cause lies rather in our finite position, as that is determined in time and space. We work along infinite radii from an individual locus, but we cannot actually transport ourselves, as it were, to A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 179 the central hearth of the universe, from which we con- ceive that all may possibly be seen resumed into unity as a harmonious system. For an intelligence occupying that standpoint, the contradictions of finite experience might possibly disappear, without any abandonment of the form of knowledge. / But what is quite plain is, that we cannot by any possibility conceive the nature of that insight. We cannot step out of the infinite progress ourselves. So it is that in Spinoza's system the two sides are never brought together. We may transcend "imagination," and refuse to take facts in isolation ; we may trace out endlessly the dependence of any given fact upon the infinite series of its de- termining causes (nay, upon an infinite number of such converging series), but we never reach the absolute Substance, the immanent cause of the whole. So from the other side there is no process of self-determination by which we can pass from Substance to its infinite attributes, or from any attribute to its particular finite modes. If we could really contemplate existence from the point of view of the Absolute, doubtless the deriva- tion of the finite world might not be so inexplicable; but we never do reach that specular mount. When we attempt to assume such a standpoint, the result is, as with Spinoza, simply emptiness. Abstracting from 180 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. the finite, we have nothing left within our grasp. So it is again with Schelling.; and the side of Mr Bradley's thought which we have been considering verifies this experience afresh. Moreover, an analysis of the arguments by which Mr Bradley reaches his Absolute throws, I think, an instructive light upon its nature, and upon the value which the result can have for us. The Absolute is a high-sounding title, and rouses proportionate expecta- tions. Let us inquire whether these are satisfied ; let us ask ourselves precisely how much Mr Bradley's argu- ments suffice to establish. "Beality," he says, "must be a single whole." " The character of the real is to possess everything phenomenal in a harmonious form." Absolute Eeality, therefore, " embraces all differences in an inclusive harmony " (pp. 140, 143). " The standard " is always "the same," and it is applied always under the double form of inclusiveness and harmony" (p. 371). Now if this were advanced as a definition of the Absolute, it would obviously be a true, though not an exhaustive, definition. Taken as implying the ex- istence of the Absolute, it might also be accepted as the expression of an inextinguishable metaphysical faith. But when the Absolute in this sense is thrust A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 181 upon us as "indubitably real," something which it is actually impossible to doubt, the very excess of pro- testation awakens suspicion as to how much the har- mony and all-inclusiveness imply. And upon scrutiny, it seems to me, I must confess, that the assertion re- solves itself into something very like an identical proposition. The mere consideration, it might be urged, that the universe exists that Being is proves that it is in some sense a harmony. All its aspects co -exist, and the business of the universe goes on. Then, as to the systematic unity of the real, I doubt much, here too, whether what is really proved is not unduly magnified by the nature of the terms employed. Mr Bradley successfully disposes of the idea of a plurality of reals ; for each real would in that case be a universe by itself, or rather a bare unqualified point, and plurality could never emerge. The mere co-exist- ence of objects in Knowledge the fact that we are able to pass from one object to another is sufficient proof that they are not absolutely independent reals, but exist as parts of one universe that is, exist, in some sense, together. To suppose anything else would be to imagine the continuity of existence to come, as it were, suddenly to a stop in mecliis rebus. But does the postulate that the universe is one, in this sense, carry 182 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. us beyond the fact which it explains or names, the fact that we are able to pass indefinitely from one fact to other facts, reducing them to law as we proceed ? Does it carry us beyond the infinite progress of finite knowledge, and give us any real idea of an experience which resumes the life of all the worlds in a central or focal unity? I do not see that it does. Yet unity, harmony, system, must mean more than the almost tautologous result we have just considered, if their presence or absence is to be of any vital concern to men. But it will be said that these formal and abstract criteria must be supplemented by the further prin- ciple that reality, existence of any kind, is one with " sentience " or " sentient experience." Even if this be granted, however, I do not see that Mr Bradley's criteria enable us to pass from an aggregate of experi- ence to " one comprehensive sentience " or " total experience " (elsewhere spoken of as " an absolute intuition," " an individual intuition ") in the sense of a living, or, if I may so express myself again, a focal unity. They do not guarantee unity or harmony, ex- cept in the abstract and tautological sense already con- sidered ; and the fact that all the varieties of sentient experience coexist somehow, and are therefore com- A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 183 patible resulting even in a balance of pleasure on the whole is by no means equivalent to the assertion of a single Being by whom these experiences are felt as a whole, and who enjoys the balance of pleasure which, when " neutralised," " complemented," and " blended," they may be supposed to yield. The notion of a single life, in which and for which the experiences are organ- ically related and unified, is derived by Mr Bradley not from his criteria, but from the nature of the self ; although, strangely enough, in the sections of his book devoted to the self he does his best to disintegrate it into a mere aggregate. To extend the analogy of the self to the Absolute is probably inevitable, and I am far from objecting to it; although, in the form in which Mr Bradley presents the idea, it seems to come dangerously near to the crude conception of a Welt- seek, or soul of the world a fused aggregate or mass of sentience. As a speculation, however, that might pass, criticism in detail being reserved. But what I cannot see is, how Mr Bradley can claim the result as the immediate consequence of his criteria, and how he can speak of it as absolutely "certain" and "indubitably real." This claim is repeatedly made by Mr Bradley, in a piece of reasoning which is sufficiently remarkable 184 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. to challenge examination. The argument is introduced a great many times, almost in the same words, as finally closing discussion ; and evidently great stress is laid upon it. Curtly stated it is this " what is possible and what a general principle compels us to say must be, that certainly is" (p. 196); or still more shortly, "what may be, if it also must be, assuredly is" (p. 199). 1 "Here, as before, possibility is all we require to prove reality" (p. 218). The first of these passages is the concluding sentence of the chapter on " Error " ; the second occurs in the chapter which follows on " Evil " ; and the third in the chapter on "Temporal and Spatial Appearance." In the next chapter (chap, xix.), on " The This and the Mine," the argument is again repeated in exactly the same way, to clinch Mr Bradley 's position : " This consummation evidently is real, because on our principle it is neces- sary, and because again we have no reason to doubt that it is possible " (p. 227). These four chapters deal with recalcitrant facts or aspects of experience, which an opponent might advance as inconsistent with the view of the Absolute just expounded. In them, it must be said that Mr Bradley treats the difficulties in question somewhat lightly. He expressly repudiates the design 1 The italics in these two quotations are Mr Bradley's. A NEW THEOKY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 185 of " showing how " the facts are reconciled in the Abso- lute, and limits himself to the suggestion of possibilities which he seems sometimes not to take very seriously himself. Having done so, he turns upon us with the assertion that the abstract possibility is enough, for we have behind us the general principle of a " must." The Absolute must be all-inclusive and harmonious ; there is nothing about which we cannot say that possibly it may be included in the Absolute ; therefore every- thing is included in the Absolute. I cannot see that there is any real advance in the argument here. Un- less we can "show how" i.e., give some reasonable theory of the relation of these aspects to the Absolute we may as well remain content with the first step : the Absolute must be all-inclusive and harmonious, though we are quite unable to see how. How far we are from being able to see how, may be exemplified from a passage in Mr Bradley's treatment of evil : Our old principle may still serve to remove this objection. The collision and the strife may be an element in some fuller realisation. Just as in a machine the resistance and pressure of the parts subserves an end beyond any of them, if regarded by itself so at a much higher level it may be with the Absolute. Not only the collision but that specific feeling, by which it is accompanied and aggravated, can be taken up into an all-inclusive perfection. We do not know UNIVERSITY 186 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. how this is done, and ingenious metaphors (if we could find them) would not serve to explain it. ... Such a per- fect way of existence would, however, reconcile our jarring discords ; and I do not see how we can deny that such a harmony is possible (p. 203). This language is surely far more suggestive of pious hope than of philosophic insight ; and yet Mr Bradley proceeds in the very next sentence to conclude, " But if possible, then, as before, it is indubitably real." The reference here and repeatedly to " our old principle " recalls us, however, to the precise meaning which we found that principle must bear. It is simply the principle that reality must be one. " It must be single, because plurality contradicts itself " (p. 519). " Eeality is one system, which contains in itself all experience " (p. 536). " It must include and must harmonise every possible fragment of experience " (p. 548). These statements, taken from the recapitulatory and con- cluding chapters of the volume, prove afresh that the general principle, on which the whole is founded, is so extremely general as to be of no avail in " harmonising " experience in any vital sense. The "conclusion is certain, and to doubt it logically is impossible" (p. 518); but it is the perfectly abstract conclusion or assumption already discussed, that ex- A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 187 istence is in some sense one, and does not fundament- ally contradict itself, inasmuch as we see that " birth proceeds and things subsist." We are forced, therefore, to conclude that this argument, from necessity through possibility to reality, is more specious than sound, seeing that it passes from a unity and harmony which, as necessary, are purely abstract, to a unity and har- mony which, as real, are understood to imply the con- crete " perfection " of a single Being, and to include the "consummation" of "the main tendencies of our nature" (p. 148). It is, to all intents and purposes, an argument based on our ignorance of the possibilities, coupled with the general conviction that things must get along together somehow ; since it is plain that existent fact contains all opposites within itself, and still exists. This is certainly " a faith as vague as all unsweet " ; but I greatly fear that all conclusions about the universe which it is logically impossible to doubt will be found, on examination, to partake of a similar tautology, and to be of no more real value in proving the universe a harmonious and perfect system. Lest I should seem to exaggerate the vagueness of the result, I will add here a few quotations from Mr Bradley's Second Book, a selection from a larger an- /fa 188 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. thology. These passages seem to me to bear out the contention that, instead, of solving the contradictions of the First Book, the Second Book is mainly devoted to "laying them to rest in the Absolute" with a large draft upon our metaphysical faith. "Somehow an identical self must be real," said Mr Bradley in Book I., " but then the question is how ? " And accordingly the identical self was curtly dismissed, as riddled with contradictions. But " somehow " is the very word which has inscribed itself on page after page of Book II., with an almost pathetic frequency of repetition. Or, if the word itself does not occur, there is the admission that " we do not know how " the reconcilia- tion is effected ; but still " we may be sure " that the reconciliation is a fact. We may say that everything, which appears, is somehow real in such a way as to be self -consistent (p. 140). The bewildering mass of phenomenal diversity must hence somehow be at unity and self -consistent (p. 140). We know what is meant by an experience, which em- braces all divisions, and yet somehow possesses the direct nature of feeling (p. 160). If we can realise at all the general features of the Absolute, if we can see that somehow they come together in a way known vaguely and in the abstract, our result is certain (p. 160). We cannot understand how in the Absolute a rich A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 189 harmony embraces every special discord. But, on the other hand, we may be sure that this result is reached (p. 192). As with error, even our one-sidedness, our insistence and our disappointment, may somehow all subserve a harmony and go to perfect it (p. 201). Then follows the significant passage already quoted as to the possibility of collision and strife being an element in some fuller realisation : We do not know how this is done. Such a perfect way of existence would, however, reconcile our jarring discords (p. 202). All differences, we have urged repeatedly, come together in the Absolute. In this, how we do not know, all dis- tinctions are fused, and all relations disappear (p. 203). We do not know how all these partial unities come together in the Absolute, but we may be sure that the content of not one is obliterated (p. 204). To explain time and space, in the sense of showing how such appearances come to be, and again, how, without contradiction, they can be real in the Absolute, is certainly not my object. Anything of the kind, I am sure, is impossible (p. 205). Hence we are led to the conclusion that subject and predicate are identical, and that the separation and the change are only appearance. . . . They somehow are lost except as elements in a higher identity (p. 220). The plurality of presentations is a fact, and it, therefore, makes a difference to our Absolute. . . . And the Universe is richer, we may be sure, for all dividedness and variety. 190 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. Certainly in detail we do not know liow the separation is over- come. . . . But our ignorance here is no ground for rational opposition. Our principle assures us that the Absolute is superior to partition, and in some way is perfected by it (p. 226). The collision is resolved within that harmony where centre and circumference are one (p. 229). We have no basis on which to doubt that all content comes together harmoniously in the Absolute. . . . All this detail is not made one in any way which we can verify. That it is all reconciled we know, ~but how, in particular, is hid from us (p. 239). The Reality, therefore, must be One, not as excluding diversity, but as somehow including it in such a way as to transform its character (p. 241). We laid stress [he says in his "Recapitulation" (p. 242)] on the fact that the how ivas inexplicable. The material world is an incorrect, a one-sided, and self- contradictory appearance of the Real. ... In other words it is a diversity which, as we regard il, is not real, but which somehow, in all its fulness, enters into and perfects the life of the Universe. But, as to the manner in which it is included, we are unable to say anything (p. 266). Certainly, in the end, to know how the one and the many are united is beyond our power. But in the Absolute somehow, we are convinced, the problem is solved (p. 281). How these various modes come together into a single unity must remain unintelligible (p. 457). We have seen that the various aspects of experience imply one another, and that all point to a unity which comprehends and perfects them. And I would urge next, that the unity of these aspect^ is unknown. By this I A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 191 certainly do not mean to deny that it essentially is ex- perience, but it is an experience of which, as such, we have no direct knowledge. . . . In the end the whole diversity must be attributed as adjectives to a unity which is not known (pp. 468, 469). Mr Bradley's candour in this array of passages is obviously beyond all praise, but they surely amount precisely to the assurances of the mystic choir at the end of ' Faust ' : " Das Unzulangliche, hier wird's Ereigniss ; Das Uribeschreibliche, hier ist es gethan" Or in plain prose, so far as the result is metaphysically certain, it seems too vague to be of use ; where it offers itself as more, it remains the expression of a deep- seated faith, whose roots are ethico - religious and aesthetical rather than purely intellectual. II. That brings us, however, to an important turning- point in our investigation. It has been hinted more than once that Mr Bradley's volume seems the product of two conflicting tendencies or lines of thought. The first of these, the Spinozistic or Schellingian tendency, which is, on the whole, predominant, has been criticised 192 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. in the preceding pages. It shapes, perhaps uncon- sciously, the general view of the Absolute. In his second line of thought, Mr Bradley stands much more closely under the influence of Hegel. I propose, in what follows, to examine this second line of thought, and to consider the relation of Mr Bradley's theory as a whole to the Hegelian philosophy, and also to the limitations of human knowledge. The Spinozistic tendency, I have said, is, on the whole, the predominant tendency ; but the second line of thought appears in some important chapters, and also in the author's statement, towards the close, of the purpose he had in view in writing the book. The chapter which seems to me most fully to represent the second point of view is that on " Degrees of Truth and Eeality." According to the Spinozistic view, appear- ance is throughout illusion ; and the nature of the Absolute is to be reached by passing beyond appear- ances to a wholly different mode of being. But this Being, above or behind appearances, we naturally find to be entirely predicateless, for in abstracting from appearance we cut ourselves off from all positive know- ledge. According to the second view, which I have called for convenience the Hegelian, appearances are not contrasted in a body with the Absolute, and A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 193 branded as untrue or illusory ; on the contrary, it is recognised that, except in the world of appearances, we have, and can have, no clue to the nature of the Absolute. Attention is concentrated, therefore, in Hegelianism upon the world of appearances, with the result that this world is shown to be a graded or hier- archical system. In this system as a whole, the Absolute is said to be realised or revealed. But appearances only become a safe guide, when regard is had to the sys- tematic or hierarchical character of the revelation. This doctrine of degrees belongs unquestionably to the abiding essence of the Hegelian philosophy; and, although we have seen that Mr Bradley's speculations often convey another impression, it would appear from his account of the purpose of his volume (given in the concluding paragraphs) that this is the lesson his pages were meant to enforce. The immense import- ance of the Hegelian position, as against a twofold error, could not in fact be more forcibly put than is done by Mr Bradley in these sentences: It is a simple matter to conclude . . . that the Eeal sits apart, that it keeps state by itself and does not descend into phenomena. Or it is as cheap, again, to take up another side of the same error. The Keality is viewed, perhaps, as immanent in all its appearances, in such a way N 194 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. that it is, alike and equally, present in all. 1 Everything is so worthless on one hand, so divine on the other, that nothing can be viler or can be more sublime than anything else. It is against both sides of this mistake, it is against this empty transcendence and this shallow Pantheism, that our pages may be called one sustained polemic. The positive relation of every appearance as an adjective to Eeality ; and the presence of Eeality among its appearances in different degrees and with diverse values this double truth we have found to be the centre of philosophy (p. 551). This view is most consistently maintained, as I have indicated, in the chapter on "Degrees of Truth and Eeality " (chapter xxiv.), and those that follow. It is recognised as the ideal of a system of metaphysics " to show how the world, physical and spiritual, realises by various stages and degrees the one absolute principle " (p. 359). In another place he sketches the task of a " philosophy of Nature " thus : All appearances for metaphysics have degrees of reality. We have an idea of perfection or of individuality ; and, as we find that any form of existence more completely realises this idea, we assign to it its position in the scale of being. And in this scale (as we have seen) the lower, as its de- fects are made good, passes beyond itself into the higher. The end, or the absolute individuality, is also the principle. Present from the first, it supplies the test of its inferior 1 " As full, as perfect in a hair as heart," according to a line which Hegelian writers are fond of putting in the pillory. A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 195 stages, and, as these are included in fuller wholes, the prin- ciple grows in reality. Metaphysics, in short, can assign a meaning to perfection and progress though, as he immediately explains, there would, in setting out the various kinds of material phenomena " in an order of merit," be no reference to the scien- tific questions of genesis and progress in time. In a complete philosophy [he proceeds] the whole world of appearance would he set out as a progress. It would show a development of principle, though not a succession in time. . . . On this scale pure Spirit would mark the. extreme most removed from lifeless Nature. And, at each rising degree of this scale, we should find more of the first character with less of the second. The ideal of spirit, we may say, is directly opposed to mechanism. Spirit is a unity of the manifold in which the externality of the manifold has utterly ceased (pp. 497, 498). And in the opening of the final chapter he returns to emphasise this hierarchical aspect of appearances : " In the end no appearance, as such, can be real. But appearances fail of reality in varying degrees ; and to assert that one on the whole is worth no more than another, is fundamentally vicious" (p. 511). Yet, all through these chapters too, Mr Bradley is still bent upon reaching an esoteric existence of the Absolute, as suck, in contradistinction to its existence 196 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. in the system of its appearances. And if this quest does not lead him exactly to an " empty transcend- ence," it lands him in an abyss of Brahmanic indiffer- ence, which threatens to throw us back into the " shallow Pantheism " from which the doctrine of degrees was to deliver us. It prompts him to a series of utterances which, though the qualification of an " as such " may save them from the charge of direct verbal contradiction, are still the expression of two opposite philosophies. Thus, when he tells us (p. 486) with the aid of italics, "The Absolute is its appear- ances," and again, with the same aid (on p. 411), " The Absolute is not its appearances," he may perhaps claim with some reason to be enunciating two complementary half-truths. But when he declares emphatically in an eloquent passage (p. 550) There is no reality anywhere except in appearance, and in our appearance we can discover the main nature of real- ity. ... It is, really and indeed, this general character of the very universe itself which distinguishes for us the relative worth of appearances. . . . Higher, truer, more beautiful, better and more real these, on the whole, count in the universe as they count for us or, again (p. 430), "Whether anything is better or worse does without doubt make a difference to the A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 197 absolute ; and certainly the better anything is, the less totally in the end is its being overruled " ; and when he yet says, at other times, that " The Absolute is per- fect in all its detail, it is equally true and good through- out " (p. 401) ; that, " viewed in relation to the Absolute, there is nothing either good or bad, there is not any- thing better or worse " (p. 411) ; that " we may even say that every feature in the universe is absolutely good " (p. 412) the burden of the contradiction threatens to become excessive. We feel that we are losing our hold upon the first view altogether, and drifting back into the gulf of absolute indifference which the poets of mysticism, Eastern and Western, have hymned. The passages last quoted all occur, it is perhaps worth noting, in . the chapter on Goodness, in which Mr Bradley's zeal against what he calls "the common prejudice in favour of the ultimate truth of morality or religion" is perhaps not untinctured by counter- prejudice. His anxiety to expose what he quaintly calls "the radical vice of all goodness" betrays him into expressions which seem to take all vital, meaning out of his first set of phrases, and make the doctrine of degrees itself an illusion, instead of reflecting, as he says elsewhere, " the essential nature of the world." The essential nature of the world for metaphysics 198 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. turns out once more to be the identity in which all distinctions vanish to which all things, therefore, are the same. This is brought out, with almost startling distinctness, in the description in this chapter of the kind of consummation which the finite attains in the Absolute : In the Absolute everything finite attains the perfection which it seeks; but, upon the other hand, it cannot gain perfection precisely as it seeks it. For, as we have seen throughout, the finite is more or less transmuted, and, as such, disappears in being accomplished. This common des- tiny is assuredly the end of the Good. The ends sought by self-assertion and self-sacrifice are, each alike, unattain- able. The individual never can in himself become a har- monious system. . . . In the complete gift and dissipation of his personality, HE, as such, must vanish ; and, with that, the Good is, as such, transcended and submerged. . . . Most emphatically no self-assertion nor any self-sacrifice, nor any goodness or morality, has, as such, any reality in the Absolute (pp. 419, 420). 1 Comment would but weaken the audacious irony of phrases which make accomplishment tantamount to disappearance, and interpret the "gift" of personality i In this short passage it will be observed the phrase "as such" occurs no fewer than four times ; it would be interesting to calculate how often it occurs in the course of Mr Bradley's volume. It exactly corresponds to Spinoza's quatenus, which has been described as the magic formula which makes all things possible in his system. A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 199 as meaning the "dissipation" of the personality in question. But it is plain that, if every aspect of finite existence if all appearances, even the highest cease or disappear, " as such," in the Absolute, and we have no knowledge whatever of the Absolute as such, in which it is said to be preserved (" transmuted," "merged and recomposed," p. 306), then surely the Absolute is for us, in the Kantian phrase, as good as nothing at all. To say we know that it is ex- perience, when it is not like any experience that we know, does not seem greatly helpful. Mr Bradley tells us himself that "an absolute experience for us, emphatically, could be nothing" (p. 550); and again he says more explicitly in a passage which has been already quoted: "The unity of these aspects is un- known. But this I certainly do not mean to deny, that it essentially is experience, but it is an experience of which, as such, we can have no direct knowledge. . . . In the end the whole diversity must be attributed as adjectives to a unity which is not Jcnoivn" (pp. 468, 469). The last passage certainly carries us very near the perilous verge of Agnosticism, if indeed it does not take us well over it. What becomes of the sustained polemic against "empty transcendence" (of which 200 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. Agnosticism is the most accentuated expression) if we are forced to admit that, though the Absolute en- gulfs, and in engulfing harmonises, all we know, it is itself not known ? We have no reason to suspect either the good faith or the accuracy of the account which Mr Bradley gives of the purpose of his book Much of the polemic of the latter part of the book is directed against empty transcendence and shallow Pantheism ; and when this polemic is going on, and Mr Bradley is insisting that the Absolute is its ap- pearance (" there is no reality at all anywhere except in appearance," p. 550), then he is also found teaching the doctrine of degrees, and insisting that our scale of worth discovers to us the main nature of reality. But when he is engaged in his favourite occupation of dissolving finite experience in contradictions, and insisting that the Absolute is not its appearances, the other half-truth seems entirely forgotten. In discard- ing appearance, he falls back himself into an empty transcendence which, by the very energy with which it repudiates all the distinctions of finite existence, re- duces all the aspects of experience to a dead level of indifference, and thus strikes round once more into that shallow Pantheism from which we were promised a deliverance the Pantheism to which "nothing can A NEW THEOEY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 201 be viler or can be more sublime than anything else." For empty transcendence and shallow Pantheism are two sides of the same mistake, and although Mr Bradley makes a strenuous effort, in his second or Hegelian line of thought, to combat and disavow the error, he cannot cut himself loose from the implications of his Spinoz- istic logic. The result is, that what I have called the Hegelian passages have the air of being more or less inconsequent disclaimers in a book which, as a whole, expresses an essentially Brahmanic attitude of mind. Nevertheless, Mr Bradley seems to me to have rendered a very important service to philosophy in this book. I will endeavour shortly to indicate what I consider that service to be. Mr Bradley has at- tempted to supplement Hegel, or to make an advance upon Hegel, in one important particular. Hegel's philosophy is notoriously a philosophy of immanence, and a vindication of the validity of knowledge. Its polemical emphasis is directed against the agnostic relativism of the Kantian " Critique," with its doctrine of the thing-in-itself, and against the easy mysticism of the Schellingian Identitatsphilosophie, which are both expressions, in different directions, of an empty transcendence. By exposing the impossible nature of 202 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. the ideals which underlie these doctrines, and vindi- cating the omnipresence of difference, as woven into the very fibre of existence, Hegel closed one long chapter of philosophical thought although his results in this respect may doubtless not have been assimilated, even yet, by many of our popular leaders of opinion. But in reaction against this error, Hegel's gift of forcible statement led him into expressions which seem to imply a no less questionable extreme. In preaching the truth that the nature of the Absolute is revealed in the world of its appearances, not craftily concealed behind them, he seems to pass to a sheer identification of the two. Now it is unquestionably true that the two aspects must be everywhere com- bined : an Absolute which does not appear or reveal itself, and an appearance without something which appears, are correlative abstractions. But that is not tantamount to saying that the appearance of the Absolute to itself is identical with the appearance which the world presents to the Hegelian philosopher. Hegel, however, tends to put the philosopher in the place of Deity, and literally to identify the history of humanity with the development of the Absolute. It was this aspect of the Hegelian system which called forth Lotze's sarcastic reference to the A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 203 dialectical idyll of an Absolute whose spiritual evolu- tion was confined to the shores of the Mediterranean. I do not think the presence of this tendency in Hegel can fairly be denied. It is an overstatement, as I hold, and as I may partly be able to show, of a great truth ; but, to my mind, the deification of humanity only re- quires to be clearly stated, in order to condemn itself. This aspect of the Hegelian system found an inadequate counterpoise in the logical dialectic of the categories, from which standpoint the time-process is reduced to a projection of thought - distinctions in a series of dissolving views, and the ultimate reality of existence seems to be placed in a timeless system of abstract conceptions. The logical strain in Hegelianism had been showing some signs of vitality in England, when Mr Bradley, in his ' Principles of Logic ' (1883), uttered his memorable protest against the reduction of the universe to an " unearthly ballet of bloodless categories." Since then, it may be said to have fallen into the back- ground, much as it did in Germany, and the school has mainly devoted itself to the historical development of God. Sometimes this is done, as it is by Hegel himself, with an attempt, either unconscious or deliberate, to keep out of view the ultimate implications of the position, as bearing on the doctrine of the being and 204 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. nature of God. At other times, the identification of man with God is made with an under - current of negative polemic, resulting in a phase of thought which may fairly be described as Hegelian positivism. If I read Mr Bradley aright, he has clearly realised that neither of these positions can be entertained for a moment, as literal and ultimate truth. Life is more than logic, and God is more than man. The categories that is to say, the structure of reason may be said to constitute the essence of God, the ground-plan of the world ; we can understand such a statement and recog- nise the truth it expresses. But " neither gods nor men are in very truth logical categories." And again, God is in history without doubt ; but yet we trust He has a richer outlook than He enjoys through any pair of human eyes. Eealising, then, these twin defects of the Hegelian position, Mr Bradley, in this volume, has made a strenuous attempt to treat the life of the Absolute as a reality. With the instinct of the true thinker, he recalls us from a too narrow Humanism to an insight into the vastness of the sustaining life that " operates unspent " throughout the universe. This insight is no doubt as simple as it is profound ; and it is sufficiently strange that man should forget his position as a finite incident in the plan of things, and measure himself A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 205 with the immeasurable Spirit of the Universe. Still the fact remains, that the most elementary truths are sometimes most easily forgotten, in the eagerness of a polemic against some particular error. We become so preoccupied with the ideas which we perceive to be true in that particular reference, as against the error we are combating, that we forget the essentially limited nature of the truth we are defending. We forget the limited sphere within which both affirmation and denial have relevancy. Indeed, we become so jealous on behalf of the truth for which we tight, that we cannot brook the least criticism upon it. We con- found in a common condemnation the man who denies its legitimate truth, because he lags at the standpoint of exploded error, and the man who, having got beyond these controversial issues, calls attention to the modifi- cations which the principle must submit to, before it can be advanced as the absolute verity. Elemental, therefore, as the truth is, the stress which Mr Bradley lays, throughout his volume, upon the necessarily superhuman character of the Absolute its inexpressible and incomprehensible transcendence of human conditions of being and thinking is a salutary correction to a good deal of current specula- tion. After all, if it comes to a question of reality, 206 A NEW THEOEY OF THE ABSOLUTE. the Absolute is the great and only Beality. We have reality only within its -all - comprehensive bounds. True, therefore, as it is, in the proper reference, to say that the Absolute realises itself in human self- consciousness, it becomes fundamentally absurd, if the saying is taken to mean that the Absolute exists, so to speak, by the grace of man, and lives only in the breath of his nostrils. Is it not both absurd and blasphemous to suppose that the Power which cradles and encompasses all our lives is not itself a living fact, and that it is reserved for man to bring the Absolute, as it were, to the birth ? A moment's reflection con- vinces us that it is so, and also that it must be essen- tially impossible for a finite being to realise the manner of that Absolute Life. But Mr Bradley has not been content simply to restore to us this fundamental insight. He is a meta- physician, and his book, if not presenting a complete system of philosophy, yet contains a pretty definite theory of the Absolute. And the curious thing is that, based as it is upon an important truth, and aiming at correcting an undoubted defect in the Hegelian state- ment, the theory turns out to be further from the truth turns out, at all events, to be more misleading than the theory it attempts to improve. But I perhaps A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 207 exaggerate the strangeness of the phenomenon, for the result is, in the circumstances, inevitable, as soon as we proceed to a constructive account of absolute expe- rience. As water cannot rise higher than its source, so our speculative grasp cannot transcend the experience which is ours in this seed-plot of Time. The higher may comprehend the lower, but how shall the lower reach out to comprehend the higher ? Denying, there- fore, that the life of the Absolute can be construed in terms of our actual human experience, even in its highest reaches, Mr Bradley is obliged, as we have seen, to fall back upon the analogy of a lower life, out of which our conscious experience seems to rise the life of feeling. It would be trite to dwell here on the ambiguities of the term " feeling " and the varieties of usage in its regard. It will be sufficient if we understand the meaning Mr Bradley intends to convey. Mere feeling, he would probably acknowledge, is a state which we never actually realise, though we seem to approximate to it at times, and conceive it to be approached asymp- totically in the lowest forms of organic life. Never- theless, it is not to be denied that feeling, in Mr Bradley's usage, represents one feature one funda- mental aspect of our actual experience. All our 208 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. experience is rooted in the immediacy of perception; and feeling names this .perceptual or immediate aspect, as opposed to the conceptual or abstract world, which we rear on the basis of inner or outer perception, and offer as its explanation or interpretation. I foresee the outcry that will be raised, in certain quarters, against this way of stating the fact, and I hasten to add that this in no way implies the separability of these two aspects in actual experience. Our actual perceptions are full of the distinctions of thought; a state of pure perception, entirely without the shaping presence of the conceptions of the under- standing, can only be regarded as a Trpcorij v\r), a vanishing-point or limitative conception, essentially unrealisable within experience. The notion from which empiricism started, that the object of perception is given, as we perceive it, without any activity of thought the notion that thought simply analytically assorts the objects of which we thus passively become aware, doing them up into classes and discovering their laws of combination this complete severance of perception from thought we are surely at liberty to treat nowadays as an exploded fiction. But the amplest acknowledg- ment of the victory of transcendentalism in this con- troversy leaves the immediacy of perception untouched, A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 209 and leaves the difference as wide as ever between the concrete world of fact, which reveals itself in percep- tion (inner and outer), and the abstractions of con- ception as such. Conception deals wholly with dbstracta, with isolated aspects or points of view. Such are the discrete or abstract units which, from its very nature, it cannot fuse into continuity, and the multiplicities which it cannot resolve into unity. It can never, therefore, express the facts of experience as they exist ; in trying to do so, it inevitably falls into contradictions or an- tinomies. It then proceeds, on the basis of its own impotence, to impeach our whole experience as con- tradictory, and no better than an illusion. But if its impotence is perfectly intelligible is seen indeed to be inevitable then experience itself can hardly be called unintelligible. It may be unintelligible in a technical use of the word ; in the sense that it cannot be reduced to, or exhaustively expressed in, the abstrac- tions which the isolating touch of understanding frames. But this is merely to say that understanding is not itself life, but a useful instrument in the service of life. In the only reasonable sense of intelligibility, life or ex- perience is itself the norm of intelligibility. We find united there all the aspects which, merely by detecting o 210 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. and naming them, understanding tends to fix in isola- tion and mutual repugnance. Take the typical instance of unity and multiplicity, which furnished forth Mr Bradley's whole First Book. The unity of the self and its states is the sufficient, and the only possible, answer to the so-called contradiction. True, you cannot name unity and multiplicity, in the same indivisible moment of time ; you must get your breath, as it were, after articulating the one, before you go on to the other. And what applies to the articulation of the words applies to the mental thinking of the thoughts. If you think of the unity of the Self, you necessarily pause upon that aspect, before supplementing it by turning round the eye of the mind to the other aspect, multi- plicity. In conception, the mind takes a step, as it were, from the one to the other, and so the two come to ap- pear separate. Then dialectic supervenes, and tells us that A is A, and, consequently, these two can never be brought together; whereas we have simply looked at one fact from two sides. That one fact our own inmost experience exhibits the two sides indissolubly united, and, accordingly, instead of calling this a con- tradiction, we adopt it as the norm of all our ex- planations. All our experience, then, is rooted in the immediacy A NEW THEOKY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 211 of perception, and experience, from the perceptive side, is a continuum in which we make distinctions. As we do not "make" them in an arbitrary sense, we may also be said to find them. They were not there for us till we made them ; but, in making them, we hold our- selves to be analysing more exactly what was implicit in the presentation from the first to be acquiring, in short, a fuller and truer knowledge of the fact. The whole progress of knowledge appears, therefore, as the breaking up of what is given as a vague mass of feeling or undefined consciousness, which can hardly as yet be described even as general awareness. Inasmuch as this state is assumed to occur in the experience of some individual creature, and to constitute the whole state of the creature in question, it may be permissible to speak of it (with Mr Bradley) as an undifferentiated unity, an undivided whole. This inexhaustible back- ground of " feeling " constitutes for us the being of the world (including ourselves), and, in that sense, it is the ultimate subject of all predication ; but, obviously, it is only so far as it becomes determined or formed, that we can say anything about it. In its character of unexhausted remainder, it is not anything we actually realise; it cannot itself be properly spoken of as ex- perience, although it is that out of which all experience 212 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. seems to arise. It is essentially a limitative concep- tion, and, as such, it is the necessary implicate of our experience ; but again, as such, it cannot be con- structed within experience. We approach it per mam negativam, only approximating towards it by throwing out one determination after another; and, if we examine our supposed realisation, we find that we have merely thrown our negatives into a positive form. But what is itself describable only by negatives, and what, if realisable, would mean a lapse into uncon- sciousness, cannot be expected to throw any valuable light upon the nature of an absolute experience. That experience, as we have seen, is to be a whole in which the distinctions elicited in the progress of knowledge are again to be merged in such a way that thought returns to the immediacy of feeling; but it is added that, " in that higher unity no fraction of anything is lost " (p. 182). We have already examined this notion, and come to the conclusion that, though Mr Bradley says, and is bound to say, that all the " richness," all the distinctions, of the world we know are somehow conserved for the Absolute, the main principle on which his criticism depends points directly to the collapse of all distinction whatever; and he seems himself con- A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 213 tinually impelled in that direction. Here we need only add that, if the utter unity of feeling, out of which our experience seems to take its rise, is an utter unity into which all distinctions collapse, and so a purely negative conception, it will be equally negative when transferred to the other end of the scale, and used to illustrate the transcendent unity in which all the differences of finite experience are resolved. In short, in the one case as in the other, we are dealing with a limitative conception, which it is sheerly impossible for us positively to construct, or, in any true sense, to conceive. Our experience has the stamp of incompleteness upon it; it has the ap- pearance of moving from an unknown source to an unknown goal. This incompleteness is expressed in the two limitative conceptions we have had before us, the unity below and the unity above experience, the extreme of mere sense and the extreme of omni- science. Within experience we may approximate to one extreme or the other, but any attempt positively to realise either leaves us baffled, with nothing in our grasp. Beyond experience, in short, all is and must be, for us, absolute emptiness ; and whatever " sail- broad vans" we spread for flight, we drop at once plumb down, like Milton's Satan, in a vast vacuity. 214 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. It is impossible, therefore, to construct for ourselves, even in outline or vague, generality, the nature of an absolute experience. Our general descriptions are seen, on examination, to be either purely formal, and, as I have argued, identical propositions, or they are postu- lates of faith, realised, we believe, somehow, but always with this for an afterword, that the " how " is hidden from us. And this is so for the simplest of all reasons, because we are men and not God. We are ourselves immersed in the process of the universe. We can only live our own life, and see through our own eyes. If we could do more, that would mean that we our- selves had vanished from the universe ; the place which had known us would know us no more, and there would be, as it were, a gap created in the tissue of the world. Take the crucial case of time. " If time is not un- real," says Mr Bradley, "our Absolute is an illusion" (p. 206). But, however " contradictory " we may find the infinite progress to be, which time involves, can we even adumbrate to ourselves what " a timeless reality " would be ? I am quite certain, for my own part, that the utmost we can attain is the idea of something permanent in time, lasting unchanged through time ; but that leaves us with all the difficulties of the infinite series still on our hands. Mr Bradley 's suggestion A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 215 that there may be many time-series in the Absolute, unrelated to one another, seems to me to throw no light on the subject whatever. The notion of many " times " seems to me one of these empty possibilities inconceivable verbal combinations which Mr Bradley elsewhere, I think, discourages. All our notions of reality being drawn necessarily from our own experience, and all our experience being in time, a timeless reality remains for our minds as inconceivable as wooden iron. Besides, the difficulty of passing from the timed to the timeless remains just as great, whether the times be many or one. Mr Bradley's attempt to determine the Absolute " as such " i.e., the Absolute as beyond or more than the process of human experience has the unexpected re- sult, therefore, which I indicated a few pages back. It proves an unexpected vindication of the real strength of the Hegelian position. The cloud of negations in which the attempt involves us, the abstract and empty character of the Absolute supposed to be reached, are a fresh and involuntary confirmation of Hegel's wisdom in refusing to step beyond the circle of knowledge and the process of history. I have said, and I repeat, that Hegel's identification of the Absolute with human ex- perience is indefensible. Nevertheless, his refusal to 216 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. seek the character of the Absolute elsewhere than in its appearances i.e., in hurnan experience was entirely justified. As we have no predicates save those drawn from this experience, the attempt to determine the Absolute, so far as it is something more than this experience, necessarily throws us back upon the purely indeterminate, and we drift easily towards the doctrine of the Unknowable. Professor Eoyce has already accused Mr Bradley of this tendency. 1 The fruitfulness of Hegel's philosophy lay in his repudiation of this barren search. The real is revealed in its ap- pearances, and is not to be sought behind or beyond them. Extension of experience will bring increased and deepened knowledge of the Absolute : " For all experience is an arch wherethrough Gleams that untra veiled world whose margin fades For ever and for ever when I move." But as we shift our margin and enter that untravelled world, however far we go, the new is still an extension of the old on the same plane the plane of finite ex- perience not a passage to another species of insight. Along with this resolute correlation of the real with its manifestations, there goes in Hegel the organisation of the phenomenal world itself. Eelieved from an im- possible quest, he devotes himself to the exposition of 1 Philosophical Review, vol. iii. p. 217. A NEW THEORY OF THE 217 experience as the only possible revelation of the Abso- lute for us, and he finds it to be not an indifferent congeries, but a graded system. The significance of this doctrine of degrees I have already dwelt on, in commenting upon what seem to me two conflicting lines of thought in Mr Bradley's book. The result for Hegel of this doctrine, taken together with his fundamental correlation of the real with its manifes- tation, was, not unnaturally perhaps, a theory which identified, or seemed to identify, the Absolute with the culminating aspects of human experience in art, reli- gion, the State, and philosophical system. The theory is false only so far as it is taken to confine the Spirit of the universe to these earthly tabernacles. So under- stood, it cabins the spirit of man within a narrow and self-sufficient positivism. It undermines the sentiment of reverence, and dulls our sense of the infinite great- ness and the infinite mystery of the world. But it is profoundly true, so far as it asserts that, only by predi- cates drawn from these spheres, can we determine the Absolute at all, and that, moreover, such determination is substantially, though doubtless not literally, true : " So weit das Ohr, so weit das Auge reicht, Du findest nur Bekanntes, das ihm gleicht, Und deines Geistes hochster Feuerflug Hat schon am Gleichniss, hat am Bild, genug." 218 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. The dangers that lurk in any attempt to determine the Absolute as such are well exemplified, I think, in the negations to which Mr Bradley is driven. Thus " morality cannot (as such) be ascribed to the " Abso- lute " (p. 197). " Goodness as such is but appearance, and is transcended in the Absolute" (p. 429). "Will cannot belong as such to the Absolute " (p. 413). In the Absolute even thought must "lose and transcend its proper self" (p. 182). "If the term 'personal' is to bear anything like its ordinary sense, then assuredly the Absolute is not merely personal " (p. 531). " The Absolute is not personal, nor is it moral, nor is it beautiful or true" (p. 533). What is the inevitable effect upon the mind of this cluster of negations ? Surely it will be this : Either the Absolute will be regarded as a mere Unknowable with which we have no concern, or the denial of will, intellect, morality, personality, beauty, and truth will be taken to mean that the Absolute is a unity indifferent to these higher aspects of experience. It will be regarded as non- moral and impersonal in the sense of being below these distinctions ; and our Absolute will then remark- ably resemble the soulless substance of the materialist. Nothing is more certain than that extremes meet in this fashion, and that the attempt to reach the super- human falls back into the infra -human. Now Mr A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 219 Bradley, of course, intends his unity to be a higher, not a lower unity. " The Absolute is not personal, because it is personal and more. It is, in a word, super-personal" (p. 531). But he is not blind to the danger that lurks in his denials. "It is better," he even warns us, if there is a risk of falling back upon the lower unity, " to affirm personality than to call the Absolute impersonal." But there is more than a risk, I maintain ; there is a certainty that this will be the result. And therefore the conclusion deducible from Mr Bradley's discussion seems to me to be that the attempt, metaphysically, scientifically, or literally 1 to determine the Absolute as such, is necessarily barren. Where the definition is not tautologous, it is a com- plex of negations, and if not technically untrue, it has in its suggestions the effect of an untruth. Our statements about the Absolute i. e., the ultimate nature of things are actually nearer the truth when they give up the pretence of literal exactitude, and speak in terms (say) of morality and religion, apply- ing to it the characteristics of our own highest experi- ence. Such language recognises itself in general (or, at least, it certainly should recognise itself) as pos- sessing only symbolical truth, as being, in fact, "thrown out," as Matthew Arnold used to say, at a 1 I use these for the moment as equivalent terms. 220 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. vast reality. But both religion and the higher poetry just because they give f up the pretence of an im- possible exactitude carry us, I cannot doubt, nearer to the meaning of the world than the formulae of an abstract metaphysics. Such a conclusion may be decried as Agnostic, but names need frighten no one. The Agnosticism which rests on the idea of an unknowable thing-in-itself the Agnosticism which many of Kant's and Spencer's arguments would establish is certainly baseless ; but there are regions of speculation where Agnosticism is the only healthy attitude. Such a region I hold to be that of the Absolute as such. If it be objected that the mere mention of such an Absolute is an acknow- ledgment of the Thing-in-itself, I must allow myself Mr Bradley's privilege, and simply " doubt if the ob- jector can understand " (p. 183). It is, in a word, not an Absolute -in -itself, but the Absolute -for -itself, of which we are speaking. It is the nature of the existence which the Absolute has or enjoys for itself. This is incomprehensible, save by the Abso- lute itself. Because it is incomprehensible by the finite mind, it . does not, however, follow that such an all-embracing experience is not a Eeality ; and the A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 221 denial of such a possibility would seem to be more than presumptuous. So far, therefore, as the Hegelian philosophy disregarded this wider outlook, and im- plicitly identified the Absolute with the process of finite experience, its scheme of things is out of pro- portion, and the ineffable transcendence of the Absol- ute as such required reassertion. But this reassertion must not be construed to mean that our own existence is a vain show which throws no light on the real nature of things. Eightly Agnostic as regards the nature of the Absolute as such, no shadow of doubt need fall on our experience as a true revelation of the Absolute for us. Hegel was right in seeking the Absolute within experience, and finding it too ; for certainly we can neither seek it nor find it anywhere else. The truth about the Absolute which we extract from our experience is, doubtless, not the final truth. It may be taken up and superseded in a wider or fuller truth ; and in this way we might pass, in successive cycles of finite existence, from sphere to sphere of experience, from orb to orb of truth. But even the highest would still remain a finite truth, and fall infinitely short of the truth of God. Such a doc- trine of relativity in no way invalidates the truthful- ness of the revelation at any given stage. The fact 222 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. that the truth I reach is the truth for me, does not make it, on that account, .less true. It is true, so far as it goes ; and if my experience can carry me no further, I am justified in treating it as ultimate, until it is superseded. Should it ever be superseded, I shall then see both how it is modified by being compre- hended in a higher truth, and also how it and no other statement of the truth could have been true at my former standpoint. But "before the higher standpoint is reached, to seek to discredit our present insight by the general reflection that its truth is partial and requires correction this is a perfectly empty truth which, in its bearing upon human life, may easily come to have the effect of an untruth. We hear much in denunci- ation of the practice of testing truth by its supposed consequences. And no doubt the argument is often a weapon in the hands of obscurantism and timid con- servatism. Yet, in the long-run, truth and life are not dissevered, and there is a line of Goethe's which ex- presses, with his usual calmness and breadth, the in- sight of which the popular doctrine is a superficial distortion, Was fruchtbar ist, allein ist wahr. While Mr Bradley 's main thought, therefore, un- doubtedly possesses a real importance as emancipat- ing us from the too narrow humanism of a dogmatic A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 223 Hegelianism, the impression produced by his volume upon an unbiassed mind will be, I fancy, to foster a wise Agnosticism in regard to assertions about the Absolute as such. Human experience, not as itself the Absolute "bodily," but as constituting the only accessible and authentic revelation of its nature to us, is the true subject-matter of Philosophy. And here, as Mr Bradley says, " the doctrine of degrees in Eeality and Truth is the fundamental answer to our problem " (p. 487). Mr Bradley, as we have seen, acknowledges his special indebtedness to Hegel in this part of his discussion; but, in its general form, the doctrine is no exclusive property of any philosophical school. Eather it has always been " Der Volker loblicher Gebrauch Dass jeglicher das Beste was er kennt, Er Gott, ja seinen Gott, benennt." We speak most truly, most in accordance with the real nature of things, when we thus characterise the Absolute in terms of the best we know. But that Hegel has given systematic expression to this old world -wisdom gives his system a place in history quite beyond the brilliant but arbitrary specu- lations of individual genius, and ensures for it an abiding influence upon modern thought. It must be 224 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. acknowledged, however, that, in his hands, the doctrine of degrees tends to assume, a too purely intellectual and formalistic character. If we look simply at his own methodic statement, the scale seems to resolve itself into a series of repetitions of the fundamental formula of the One and the Many. As we rise in the scale, we get more comprehensive wholes wholes, too, which include a more intricate complexity of detail, and which embrace their detail in a more intimate union. We have thus a series of types (different powers or Potenzeri) of the same formula. But the realisation of this ab- stract scheme possesses in itself no interest or import- ance. It is the content of any experience which makes it " higher " in any vital sense, and makes it of decisive importance in an inquiry as to the meaning of experi- ence as a whole. Hegel's results in this connection are substantially true, just because they are based not upon the mere application of a formula, but upon an implicit reference to the content of experience and the judgments of value which that legitimates. The formula itself is derived, in fact, from the self-conscious life of man, and to Hegel, in even a wider sense than to Kant, man in his typical activities is an End-in-himself. The life, that is to say, which is guided by the ideals of Truth, Beauty and Goodness, and which partially A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 225 realises these, possesses an absolute and indefeasible worth. It is only in such judgments of value that we can be said to possess "an absolute criterion." Mr Bradley says in more than one place that we possess such a criterion, but he also, like Hegel, confines him- self too exclusively throughout his book to the in- tellectual necessities of all-inclusiveness and internal harmony, which, we found, did not carry us so far as he supposed. Our idea of what the Absolute must be is founded on the ideal necessities which our nature compels us to acknowledge. But the ideal necessities in question are not merely intellectual ; they are sesthetical, ethical, and religious as well. For "we must believe" (to quote Mr Bradley's own words) " that reality satisfies our whole being ; our main wants for Truth and Life, and for Beauty and Good- ness must all find satisfaction " (p. 159). The necessity of our belief is not due, however, to any esoteric assurance on the point which we possess direct from the Absolute. It is an absolute certainty in the sense simply that it is an ultimate judgment on our part. It represents our deepest conviction as to absolute and relative worth a conviction which does not admit of being supported, and therefore does not admit of being assailed, by argument. p ME BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS, niHEEE is some danger that the philosophical import- -*- ance of Mr Balfour's c Foundations of Belief ' may be obscured by the very circumstances which gave the book for a time such an extraordinary prominence. The tide of reviews and criticisms, which flowed so high in the weeks and months immediately following its appearance, has, for the time at least, completely ebbed ; and the volatile curiosity of the general public has doubtless been transferred to other themes. But the book appeals to deeper interests and a more per- manent audience. To that audience I venture to submit the following reconsideration of the subject. The multifarious and divergent estimates of the book may themselves serve, I think, by the very misap- prehensions they reveal, to set its essential argument in a clearer light. And in the second place, I de- MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 227 sire to call attention to an important change, an im- portant advance, as it seems to me, in Mr Balfour's philosophical position, since the publication of his earlier volume. No critic, so far as I know, has commented on this change, although it serves, in great measure, to explain the conflicting judgments of Mr Balfour's argument ; and the author himself seems hardly aware that he has in any way shifted his ground. But however insensible the advance may have been, and however closely the two positions may still seem at times to approach one another, the difference between them, from the point of view of philosophical construction, is vital. Eeviews and criticisms always indicate the personal equation of the reviewer. But in Mr Balfour's case the divergence of the critical voices had in it some of the elements of surprise. It was to be expected that naturalists and theologians would judge the book by different standards, and take diametrically opposite views of its value.; and it is true that in general the Naturalist denounced it as " a plea for supernaturalism," or as "written in the interest of the powers that be and the established creed." But theologians them- selves were found as widely at issue with one another. It would have been natural, again, to find reviewers 228 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. of a Eadical tendency inclined to pick flaws in the book, and those of a Conservative colour inclined to bless it altogether. And no doubt such a stream of tendency may be traced in some of the less important notices of the daily and weekly press. But perhaps the most acrid and unsympathetic notices that were written appeared in the Tory columns of ' Blackwood ' and the ' Saturday Eeview.' The contrast of opinions was fairly typified in the titles given in the same week to their articles by two of our prominent weeklies. " Mr Balfour as a Christian " was the one headline; "Mr Balfour the Sceptic" was the other. Both are written avowedly from an orthodox Christian standpoint ; yet the one finds " the last hundred pages of the book," that is to say, the constructive sugges- tions towards a provisional philosophy, "almost un- readable." "We are supposed," says the critic, "to be taught theories of ' beliefs and realities ' ; but we find the beliefs qualified out of existence, and the reality attenuated till it is slighter than a shadow." The other reviewer is of opinion that Mr Balfour writes in these sections of his book "with amazing fresh- ness and interest"; and he concludes by saying that " preachers will find much in it to repay their study, and to contribute to their work." If we confine our MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 229 attention to theologians who write above their own signature, Principal Fairbairn confesses to "deep disappointment." "Pleasure turned to pain, as the underlying philosophy was seen to be shifting sand rather than solid rock; the farther the reading pro- ceeded, the less satisfactory the argument appeared." Professor Marcus Dods, on the contrary, declares that " if Mr Balfour's volume is the result of his enforced absence from the helm of the State, it is a strong argument for the continuance of the Liberal Government." He compares the book to Butler's 'Analogy,' and adds that "there are many who have read the older master with dissatisfaction, who will find in the teacher of to-day the conviction and help they seek." Looking at another part of the field, we find Mr Alfred Benn, who writes in the main from the Naturalistic standpoint, confidently recommending the book to Eoman Catholic believers " as bringing water to their mill." But Dr Barry, who is doubtless more entitled to speak for the Eoman Catholic theologians, pronounces, in the 'Dublin Eeview,' that "the foun- dation is not true and will never stand." " Universal doubt, rather than religious dogma, will gain by the stroke that smites reason to the ground." " Montaigne 230 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. had said all these things before, with infinite vivacity and eloquence, but to the praise of a dissolving and pernicious doubt rather than to the gain of Chris- tianity." For Montaigne, the writer in 'Blackwood' substitutes Pilate and Mephistopheles. " God forbid," he ejaculates, " that religion should ever be led to rest its case on pleadings like these ! " In sum, it may be said that while many representa- tives of the Churches accept the new champion with acclamation, and without too narrow a scrutiny of his weapons or methods of warfare, an important section will have none of such a defender. They are more afraid of what they take to be the sceptical premisses of the book, than grateful for its orthodox conclusions. " Non tali auxilio" they seem to say ; " we prefer to fight with our own weapons, and take the chances of the war." Which of these two last-named parties is the better advised, and what is the truth about the scepticism which is said to pervade the book, and to defeat what was avowedly the author's intention in writing it ? In general, is there any explanation to be found in the book itself of these contradictory estimates of its con- tents and result ? If, as I am convinced, the volume is much more than the tour de force of an eminent MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 231 statesman, and the wonder of a literary season, this is a question which it will well repay us to consider. I do not speak here of the classical graces and felicities of the style, which have been on all hands sufficiently acknowledged. Whether the argument, moreover, is in all points consistent with itself, whether all the posi- tions advanced are equally tenable, these are questions on which we may easily differ ; but to fail to recognise the vitality of the discussions, the mastery with which the great philosophical debate is handled, is to show a mind which either cannot rise above long-incrusted prejudice, or cannot detach itself from the technical shibboleths of its own philosophic sect. What then, let us ask, does the book itself profess to be ? It is an inquiry into " the foundations of belief," and the sub-title (" Notes introductory to the Study of Theology ") indicates at once the practical, or perhaps one might rather say more broadly the human, interest that underlies and prompts the investigation. Through- out the book, nothing is more remarkable than the spirit of intellectual detachment which it exhibits, the perfect freedom, at times one might say the airy free- dom, with which the discussion is conducted. Yet we are made to feel that it has not been undertaken 232 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. for the mere delight of dialectic fence. The book is in- spired by a keen human interest, which breaks through, from time to time, in passages of deep feeling or in- dignant irony. The author conceives the spiritual heritage of mankind to be endangered by certain cur- rent assumptions of a would-be philosophic nature. He submits these assumptions, accordingly, to scrutiny (and with them the assumptions that underlie the whole fabric of human knowledge), in order to discover whether we are really under an intellectual obligation to surrender the beliefs in question beliefs as to the cause of the world and man's place in it, which form the basis of all theological teaching, and which con- stitute what may be called the spiritual view of the world. Mr Balfour's attitude, it will be seen from what has been said, is to a large extent the same as when he wrote his 'Defence of Philosophic Doubt' in 1879. The fact that the earlier work is described, in a sub- title, as " an Essay on the Foundations of Belief," indi- cates the amount of ground which the two volumes occupy in common ; and the second part of the present work ("Some Eeasons for Belief") is largely a more popular restatement of some of the criticisms contained in ' Philosophic Doubt.' The motive of the two books MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 233 is also the same ; for, in his first publication also, the avowed occasion of Mr Balfour's attack was the ag- gressive attitude assumed towards religion by " ad- vanced thinkers," who claimed to speak in the name of science. But though the two books have much in common, it would be a mistake to suppose that Mr Balfour has, in the second, simply repeated, with variations, the theme of the first. The many resem- blances of the two volumes have fostered the impres- sion that this is the case ; and I cannot but think that injustice has been thereby done to the scope of the argument in the 'Foundations of Belief.' Under this impression, the sceptical criticism of Empiricism and Transcendentalism, and the laudation of Authority, assumed an undue importance, over- shadowing what I take to be the substantive thesis of the book and its more enduring contribution to philosophical thought. Some have maintained, indeed, that ' The Foundations of Belief ' is a misnomer (like the chapter on snakes in Iceland), inasmuch as the whole purpose of the book is to prove that belief has no foundations. This, as I hope to show, is true of the more recent argument only in a technical sense which robs the assertion of its sting. But it might claim to be a fairly accurate description of the position in 234 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. which we are left at the conclusion of the earlier volume. The ' Defence of Philosophic Doubt ' is really an exposition of the purest scepticism. It is, accord- ing to the author's own description, a piece of purely destructive criticism, directed against the foundations of scientific knowledge, or what claims to be such. The argument is conducted, it is true, with an arribre pensfo in the shape of " practical results " which it is supposed to yield in the interests of religious truth. But the actual conclusion drawn is, that both the creed of religion and the creed of science are equally baseless, in the sense of being "incapable of any rational de- fence." Hence Mr Balfour concludes that "religion is at any rate no worse off than science in the matter of proof" (pp. 315-319). We have as much right to believe the one as the other. " I am content to regard the two great creeds by which we attempt to regulate our lives as resting in the main upon separate bases. So long, therefore, as neither of them can lay claim to philosophic probability, discrepancies which exist, or may hereafter arise, between them cannot be considered as bearing more heavily against the one than against the other" (p. 322). Both science and theology have " claims on our belief," but these claims are not to be construed as reasons. MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 235 Whatever they may be, they are not rational grounds of conviction. ... It would be more proper to describe them as a kind of inward inclination or impulse, falling far short of or, I should perhaps rather say, altogether differing in kind from philosophic certitude, leaving the reason, there- fore, unsatisfied, but amounting, nevertheless, to a practical cause of belief, from the effects of which we do not even desire to be released (p. 317). If it be objected tha't this " impulse " is not universal, Mr Balfour rejoins that to build upon the universality of the impulse would be to erect the impulse to believe into a reason for believing, and so entirely to misread the situation. The contention expressly is that there is no reason for belief in either case ; and where the impulse is wanting in any number of individuals, we simply note its absence in their case, as we note its presence in other individuals. But there can be no argument in such a matter from one individual to another. I and an indefinite number of other persons, if we con- template religion and science as unproved systems of belief standing side by side, feel a practical need for both. . . . But as no legitimate argument can be founded on the mere existence of this need or impulse, so no legitimate argument can be founded on any differences which psychological analysis may detect between different cases of its manifesta- tion. We are in this matter, unfortunately, altogether outside the sphere of Reason (p. 320). 236 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. Such passages are obviously a formulation of the purest scepticism which can weU be conceived. To find their parallel we must go back to Hume the Hume of the ' Treatise/ who also concludes that after the most accurate and exact of my reasonings, I can give no reason why I should assent to it, and feel nothing hut a strong propensity to consider objects strongly in that view under which they appear to me. ... I may, nay, I must yield to the current of nature in submitting to my senses and understanding; and in this blind submission I show most perfectly my sceptical disposition and principles. ... If we believe that fire warms or water refreshes, it is only because it costs us too much pains to think otherwise (part iv. section 7). Moreover, the earlier volume contains no indication, or next to none, of the precise nature of the theological beliefs by which the author would supplement the creed of science. Mr Balfour apparently identifies himself with "the ordinary believer" (p. 325). His language seems to imply an uncriticised acceptance of the traditional creed as a whole. It can hardly, however, be argued with any plausibility that the impulse to religious belief extends to the details of a dogmatic scheme like that of historical Christianity. Hence, the man who believes on such terms seems to have no course open to him but unquestioning submis- sion to authority and tradition. MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 237 The impression, therefore, produced by the earlier volume and I think not unnaturally produced was that it was essentially a new version of the often- repeated attempt to aggrandise authority by sapping the foundations of all rational certainty; an attempt, therefore, to found religious faith upon intellectual scepticism. Taken barely thus, and as historically exemplified in writers like Pascal, Newman, and Mansel, such an attitude obviously surrenders all claim to rational criticism of the dogmas offered for acceptance, and offers no safeguard against the re -invasion of the grossest superstition. A more dangerous defence of religious truth cannot, I think, be imagined. And if this is supposed to be the sum of Mr Balfour's contribution in the 'Foundations of Belief,' I can understand Principal Fairbairn's "deep disappointment " with the volume, and his comparison of the author's method to that of "the blind Samson who sacrificed himself, in order that he might the more effectually bury the Philistines under the ruins of their own temple." As Dr Barry puts it, " Universal doubt, rather than religious dogma, will gain by the stroke that smites Eeason to the ground." But, in this respect, the two books do not appear to me to stand upon the same level. It is not without 238 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. significance that the title of the first has for its leading word " doubt," while the* leading word of that of the second is "belief." Although the later volume takes up into itself the distinctive theses of the earlier, and elaborates them in some cases with far greater resources of irony and felicitous illustration (for example, in Part III. on " Some Causes of Belief "), the second work is undoubtedly to be understood, in the main, as the constructive complement of the first. Its principal line of argument, that from needs to their satisfaction, is implied in a few phrases in the con- cluding pages of the ' Defence of Philosophical Doubt ' ; but it is here developed in such a way as to overshadow, and, indeed, to place in a new light, the sceptical argumentation with which it is associated. The first and the last of the four parts into which the book is divided are, in this respect, completely new, and could almost be read perhaps, I might say, they would retain their substantive value without the intervention of the sceptical analysis contained in Parts II. and III. At all events, when the argument of the volume is considered as a whole, and in its logical sequence, Mr Balfour's " scepticism " is seen to be of a strictly limited and hypothetical character. If its scope has been exaggerated, that is largely due to the influence MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 239 of an unfortunate terminology. But the majority of the critics, coming to the book with the current idea of the author's position derived from the previous volume, were not prepared to catch the true perspective of the argument. Those parts of it with which they seemed to be already familiar bulked more largely in their eyes than the more fundamental, but perhaps more unassuming, line of thought upon which Mr Balfour here depends for his positive conclusions. Mr Balfour has himself also partly to blame for the misconception. In the chapters on " Philosophy and Eationalism " and on " Eeason and Authority," he has devoted himself, with manifest relish, to the task of exposing the ineptitude of much of the language habit- ually indulged in by the devotees of pure reason. In this part of the book he has given the reins to his powers of epigram and irony, and he displays an almost wilful pleasure in shocking the reader by the audacity with which he tears to pieces the most respectable commonplaces. The outcome of these chapters, taken by themselves, appears to be a depreciation of reason which verges on cynicism, and a corresponding glorifi- cation of authority as the principle of coherence and continuity in human life and society. The very choice of the obnoxious term " authority " to designate the 240 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. group of causes which Mr Balfour here opposes to " reason " may be looked upon as part of the " delight of battle " which so plainly inspires this section of the book. The defence of authority might have been sup- posed in these days to be limited to those whom Pro- fessor James lately described with more force than politeness as " the stall-fed officials of an established Church." Yet, meeting it here in Mr Balfour's pages, the exasperated critics, after the first impulse of in- dignation, determined that it was the natural and becoming attitude of the Tory leader, and communi- cated this to the British public as the gist of the book. It has to be added, however, in extenuation of this misapprehension, that the chapters in question are so brilliantly written, and, in spite of apparent paradoxes, so full of the wisdom of life, that they cannot but dwell in the memory of most readers, when they come to give an account of the book. But for my own part, sorry as I should be to miss these brilliant and suggestive dissertations, taken as such on their own merits, I am so far from regarding them as the essence of the book that, looking merely to the coherence of the main argument, I have sometimes been inclined to echo Dr Barry's complaint that Mr Balfour has interposed these sections " almost wan- MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 241 tonly, between his criticism of the Naturalist and his apology for the Theologian." Such a drastic " cut " is, of course, not seriously to be thought of. The author in these chapters unquestionably advances positions which are much too important to be treated merely as incidents ; and their elimination would greatly alter the character of the book. I refer especially to the limitation of Eeason to conscious ratiocination, and the treatment of Eationalism as undeveloped and in- consequent Naturalism. Both these propositions, if understood in the sense which has been commonly put upon them, appear to me philosophically untenable, as well as inconsistent with Mr Balfour's own argument. But a closer examination of the sections in question, in their relation to the rest of the book, has convinced me that the general impression of their meaning is largely a misapprehension, caused by Mr Balfour's terminology, and that, when taken in their true in- tention, they bear a much more harmless, indeed, a perfectly defensible, sense. Without proposing to de- fend his terminology, I am prepared, therefore, to do more justice to the logical sequence of Mr Balfour's thought than is implied in Dr Barry's stricture. But I have no hesitation in saying that if it were necessary to put upon these chapters the interpretation put by 242 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. Dr Barry and many other critics, it would be impos- sible to reconcile this part of the book with the con- structive philosophy suggested in Part IV. This, as I take it, is the explanation of the divergences of critical opinion, to which reference was made at the outset. Failing to detect the coherence between these two parts of the book, the critic is, in a manner, obliged to choose between them ; and, according as he chooses the one or the other, he effects a corresponding change in the centre of gravity of the volume. A short review of the course of the discussion will, I think, substantiate this view of the true perspec- tive of the argument. It will at the same time fur- nish evidence of the change which has, to some extent unconsciously, effected itself in Mr Balfour's own position. The book is divided, it will be remembered, into four parts, called respectively, " Some Consequences of Belief," " Some Eeasons for Belief," " Some Causes of Belief," and " Suggestions towards a Provisional Philosophy." Mr Balfour begins, that is to say, by drawing out the implications of Naturalism in the domain of ethics and esthetics, and exhibiting the general aspect which the world presents according to MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 243 " this theory of the non-rational origin of reason." The substance of current morality, he points out, is taken for granted by the naturalistic evolutionist, as it is, curiously enough, by the most various schools of moralists. But, in this case, there is a fundamental " incongruity between the sentiments subservient to morality and the naturalistic account of their origin." Nature's sole aim, according to the theory, is the sur- vival of the individual or the race in the struggle for existence. There can be no ground, therefore, for drawing a distinction in favour of any of the pro- cesses, physiological or psychological, by which the indi- vidual or the race is benefited. . . . We can hardly doubt that the august sentiments which cling to the ideas of duty and sacrifice are nothing better than a device of nature to trick us into the performance of altruistic actions. ... It is because, in the struggle for existence, the altruistic virtues are an advantage to the family, the tribe, or the nation, but not always an advantage to the individual; it is because man comes into the world richly endowed with the inheri- tance of self -regarding instincts and appetites required by his animal progenitors, but poor indeed in any inbred in- clination to the unselfishness necessary to the wellbeing of the society in which he lives ; it is because in no other way can the original impulses be displaced by those of later growth to the degree required by public utility, that Nature, indifferent to our happiness, indifferent to our morals, but sedulous of our survival, commends disinterested virtue to 244 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. our practice by decking it out in all the splendour which the specifically ethical sentiments alone are capable of supplying (pp. 16, 17). In a world, indeed, in which we recognise that " our conduct was determined for us by the distribution of unthinking forces in pre-solar seons," the emotions with which we are wont to contemplate virtuous actions become entirely unmeaning. Moreover, there is the same want of harmony " between the demands of the ethical imagination and what naturalism tells us con- cerning the final goal of all human endeavour " (p. 26). " We desire, and desire most passionately when we are most ourselves, to give our service to that which is universal and to that which is abiding." But man, according to Naturalism, is " no more than a pheno- menon among phenomena, a natural object among other natural objects. His very existence is an acci- dent, his story a brief and transitory episode in the life of one of the meanest of the planets ; " l and as this lesson is driven home, " we may well feel inclined to ask whether so transitory and unimportant an accident 1 Did space permit I would fain transcribe the whole of the striking passage in which Mr Balfour depicts the ultimate issue of Natural- ism a passage in which speculative imagination and intense human feeling have combined to add a page of rare and moving eloquence to English literature. MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 245 in the general scheme of things as the fortunes of the human race can any longer satisfy aspirations and emotions nourished upon beliefs in the Everlasting and the Divine." We may expect, in short, in the case of those holding the naturalistic creed, " that the more thoroughly the intellect is saturated with its essential teaching, the more certain are the sentiments violently and unnaturally associated with it to languish or to die." The obvious objection that among the professors of naturalism are to be found some of the most shining examples of unselfish virtue, is met by the parable of the parasites. " Biologists tell us of parasites which live, and can only live, within the bodies of animals more highly organised than they." Similarly, the spiritual life of such men is " sheltered by convictions which belong not to them but to the society of which they form a part ; it is nourished by processes in which they take no share." The argument based upon such examples would not hold, therefore, of a society com- pletely impregnated by naturalistic principles. But the further and apparently more radical objec- tion has been raised, that Mr Balfour has presented the world with a caricature of Naturalism, even in its purely theoretical aspect. He is fighting, it is said, 246 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. with a man of straw, with a bogy of his own creation. There are no Naturalists, in Mr Balfour's sense of the term; existing Naturalists would disclaim, with one accord, the creed which he puts in their mouth. The disclaimer has, as a matter of fact, been made in many quarters since the appearance of the volume, with con- siderable display of indignation ; and I think we may readily admit the sincerity of those who make it, without concluding, on that account, that Mr Balfour has been terrifying himself and his readers by a fancy sketch. Tew persons take the trouble to connect their various opinions into a coherent system of belief; many points have commonly been left vague, others have been qualified by inconsistent admissions. Hence they fail to recognise the lineaments of a system which they have never consciously surveyed as a whole, much less embraced, and from which, when stated with rigor- ous consistency and remorseless clearness, they shrink with unaffected horror. But this constitutes no im- peachment of Mr Balfour's method. Only by the development of a system into all its consequences can the true features of the system be discerned, and judg- ment passed upon its adequacy. And, for my own part, I cannot admit that Mr Balfour's picture is too highly coloured. MR BALFOUE AND HIS CRITICS. 247 The distinction between Naturalism and Science has also to be kept carefully in view at this point. Many critics have fallen into the mistake of supposing that Mr Balfour has a quarrel with Science, and that his object is to discredit its methods and results. They have accused him of identifying Naturalism and Science, of treating the former creed as the inevitable inference from scientific facts and theories, and of attributing it accordingly to all scientific men. Many honest pro- tests have been made, from the side of Science, against this supposed identification. On the other hand, the Naturalists, less ingenuously perhaps, have sedulously fostered the same impression. As no one can seriously hope to prevail in a contest with Science, they have put it about that the whole attack is no more than a display of dialectic fireworks, of which nobody is a penny the worse. They have pursued in this their accustomed tactics ; it has been long their practice to seek shelter behind the segis of Science. But, on the present occasion, it is not Mr Balfour 's fault if the stratagem succeeds; he has denounced it in advance. In concluding his criticism of " The Philosophic Basis of Naturalism," he is at special pains to expose the speculative, but quite illusory, title by which the empiri- cal school have endeavoured to associate Naturalism and 248 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. Science in a kind of joint supremacy over the thoughts and consciences of mankind. . . . With empirical philosophy [he says in a characteristic passage], considered as a tentative contribution to the theory of Science, I have no desire to pick a quarrel. That it should fail is nothing; other phil- osophies have failed. Such is, after all, the common lot. . . . But that it should develop into Naturalism, and then, on the strength of labours which it has not endured, of vic- tories which it has not won, and of scientific triumphs in which it has no right to share, presume, in spite of its speculative insufficiency, to dictate terms of surrender to every other system of belief, is altogether intolerable. Who would pay the slightest attention to Naturalism if it did not force itself into the retinue of science, assume her livery, and claim, as a kind of poor relation, in some sort to represent her authority and to speak with her voice. Of itself it is nothing. It neither ministers to the needs of mankind, nor does it satisfy their reason (p. 135). It is not with Science, or with scientific results as such, that Mr Balfour has any quarrel. I do not know any modern philosophical book which indicates more unqualified acceptance of these results, or which is more pervaded by the atmosphere of the most recent science. It is the naturalistic interpretation of science which he attacks, the attempt to make Science do duty for philosophy, to substitute the history of a process for a theory of its ultimate ground and source. There is not a proposition of science, even the most material- MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 249 istic in seeming, which may not be unhesitatingly ac- cepted, if combined with Bacon's acknowledgment of " a divine marshal." And this is a question on which Science, dealing only with secondary causes and the sequences of phenomena, is necessarily dumb. Having thus in Part I. reduced Naturalism to its essentials, and developed it into its consequences, Mr Balfour proceeds (in Part II.) to examine the philo- sophic basis of the theory, and the rational justification which it has to offer of its first principles. For such a justification he naturally turns first to empirical phil- osophy. He begins, however, by remarking most truly upon the comparative neglect by all schools (at least before Kant) of a philosophy of science, or, to put it more broadly, of a theory of knowledge, and in par- ticular upon the tendency of the empirical school to substitute psychology for philosophy to deal "with the origins of what we believe rather than with its justification." "A full and systematic attempt, first to enumerate, and then to justify, the presuppositions on which all science finally rests, has, it seems to me, still to be made." And he lays down the unquestion- ably sound position that " no general theory of know- ledge has the least chance of being successful, which does not explicitly include within the circuit of its 250 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. criticism, not only the beliefs which seem to us to be dubious, but those also /which we hold with the most perfect practical assurance/' "Nothing stands more in need of demonstration than the obvious." After effectively contrasting the common-sense view of the world, based upon the immediate judgments of perception, with the scientific account of material reality, and contrasting both with the train of psychical se- quences from which they are supposed to be deduced, he proceeds to apply to empirical philosophy his test of a satisfactory theory, securely grounded and firmly concatenated. Does it admit of being stated "as a series of premisses and conclusions, starting from those which are axiomatic i.e., for which proof can be neither given nor required and running on through a continuous series of binding inferences until the whole of knowledge is caught up and ordered in the meshes of this all-inclusive dialectic network ? " The argument proper is compressed here within small compass, partly because Mr Balfour is able to refer to his more detailed and technical treatment in ' Philosophic Doubt,' partly because it is, in reality, so easy to show that Hume's is the only legitimate con- clusion that can be drawn from any philosophy " which depends for its premisses in the last resort upon the MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 251 particulars revealed to us in perceptive experience alone." As he pointedly says : Nothing in the history of speculation is more astonishing, nothing, if I am to speak my whole mind, is more absurd, than the way in which Hume's philosophic progeny, a most distinguished race, have, in spite of all their differences, yet been able to agree, loth that experience is essentially as Hume described it, and that from such an experience can be rationally extracted anything even in the remotest de- gree resembling the existing system of the natural sciences. The whole fabric of the sciences depends upon the principle of universal causation, but it is impossible to extract from particular experiences anything more than the habit of expecting among sequences familiar to us in the petty round of daily life the recurrence of something resembling a former con- sequent, following on the heels of something resembling a former antecedent. . . . When we come to the more com- plex phenomena with which we have to deal, the plain lesson taught by personal observation is not the regularity, but the irregularity, of Nature. . . . This apparent ir- regularity of Nature, obvious enough when we turn our attention to it, escapes our habitual notice, of course, be- cause we invariably attribute the want of observed uni- formity to the errors of the observer. And without doubt we do well. But what does this imply ? It implies that we bring to the interpretation of our sense-perception the 252 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. principle of causation ready-made. It implies that we do not believe the world to be governed by immutable law, because our experiences appear to be regular ; but that we believe that our experiences, in spite of their apparent irregularity, follow some (perhaps) unknown rule, because we first believe the world to be governed by immutable law. But this is as much as to say that the principle is not proved by experience, but that experience is understood in the light of the principle (pv- 132, 133). With this important conclusion Mr Balfour passes to the consideration of "Transcendental Idealism." This chapter is printed by the author in smaller type than the rest of the book, and the general reader is recommended to omit it. I propose on this occasion to claim the privilege of the general reader for a variety of reasons. In the first place, the position which Mr Balfour ' has himself assigned to it indicates that it stands to some extent apart from the main argument of the book, which is intelligible and sufficiently com- plete without it. Moreover, it is limited, for the most part, to a criticism of the idealistic theory as it appears in the works of the late Professor Green. As a matter of fact, I am in agreement with most of the criticisms which Mr Balfour here makes upon Green's formulae. But the weaknesses of Green's version of idealism have (thanks largely to Mr Balfour's criticisms of MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 253 earlier date) come to be pretty widely acknowledged, even by Idealists themselves, and his specific doctrines do not occupy, therefore, the position of authority in the school which they held when Mr Balfour began to write. It may be said also, that in pressing his critical advantage over Green, Mr Balfour, in this chapter, is disposed to put out of sight the larger aspects of ideal- ism, and to forget the real affinities of the idealistic theory to his own constructive doctrines. I will try to show, before I close, that these affinities have been underestimated, both by Mr Balfour himself and by his idealist critics. In what follows, we enter upon the most question- able part of Mr Balfour's speculations, a part in which his use of terms has proved, and could hardly fail to prove, misleading. The sections to which I refer, the last two chapters of Part II. and the whole of Part III., begin by drawing from the foregoing investigations the ill-omened, and purely Humian, conclusion that " Cer- titude is found to be the child, not of reason, but of custom." " If this be true," continues Mr Balfour, " it is plainly a fact of capital importance. It must re- volutionise our whole attitude towards the problems presented to us by science, ethics, and theology." Obviously, we must refuse "arbitrarily to erect one 254 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. department of belief (the scientific) into a lawgiver for all the others." Here Mr Balfour, for the moment, does not advance beyond the attitude which he inculcated as the " Prac- tical Eesult " of ' Philosophic Doubt.' Both creeds, he there argued, the creed of Science and the creed of Eeligion, being equally without rational foundation, it is quite indefensible to make one the norm of the other. Later on in the present volume, Mr Balfour expressly discards the remedy which " consists in simply setting up, side by side with the creed of natural science, another and supplementary set of beliefs which may minister to needs and aspirations which Science cannot meet" (p. 186). He recognises how impossible it is " to acquiesce in this unconsidered division of the ' whole ' of knowledge into two or more unconnected fragments" (p. 187), and accepts as a necessary ideal, and one which, at least in part, he attempts himself to realise, " the unification of all be- lief into an ordered whole, compacted into one coherent structure under the stress of reason " (p. 233). But, in the sections we are considering, he continues to work the earlier sceptical vein. This is exemplified in the account of reason and rationalism which follows, certain passages of which are among the most unguarded in ME BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 255 the book, and have given offence in quarters where, it is certain, they were never intended to do so. Mr Balfour, it will be remembered, repeatedly connects rationalism and naturalism, treating the latter as the logical outcome of the former, the former as merely a half-way house to the latter, occupied by thinkers too timid or too inconsequent to realise their proper destination. " Naturalism," he says, " is the completed product of Bationalism" (p. 173); again he speaks of "rationalising methods and naturalistic results" (p. 174) ; " Eationalism," he repeats, " is the high road to naturalism " (p. 175) ; " Eationalism is Naturalism in embryo" (p. 185). Now if Reason is used here in the large, philosophic sense of the word, and if by Rationalism is understood any system of thought which builds unreservedly upon Reason, and involves no other organ for the appre- hension of truth, then it must be admitted that these propositions are among the most insidious and sub- versive which it is possible to conceive. It must have been such statements that Mr Benn had in view when he recommended the volume to Roman Catholics as bringing water to their mill. So interpreted, they would compel us to class the systems of Plato and Aristotle, Kant and Hegel, as Naturalism in embryo, 256 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. because they build throughout upon the rational nature of man, without feeling it necessary to invoke, without, indeed, leaving any place for, the supernatural in the ecclesiastical sense of the term. Mr Balfour explains, however, at the outset that he proposes to "employ the word in a much more restricted sense." He will use it, he says, to indicate a special form of that reaction against dogmatic theology which may be said with sufficient accuracy to have taken its rise in the Renaissance, to have increased in volume during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, and to have reached its most complete expression in the Natural- ism which has occupied our attention through the first portion of these Notes (p. 168). Even this definition, as it stands, is too wide, if we are to acquiesce in the censures heaped upon Rationalism, and in the account which Mr Balfour gives of its necessary goal. For the definition would naturally include the whole movement of modern thought Descartes and Leibniz, as well as Hobbes and Hume, Kant, Fichte, and Hegel, as well as Comte, Mill, and Spencer. And, in that case, it cannot easily be dis- tinguished from similar dicta of Newman and other Catholic theologians. But, in point of fact, Mr Balfour uses the term in a still more special and restricted MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 257 sense than his own definition might lead us to expect. He understands by it, he says, " a view of the universe based exclusively upon the prevalent mode of inter- preting sense -perception" (p. 170); it involves "the assumption that the kind of 'experience' which gave us natural science was the sole basis of knowledge" (p. 171). His definition would therefore apply, at most, to the empirical or sensationalist philosophies; and the course of the discussion makes it plain that he has in view, not so much the systems of philoso- phers, 1 as the body of thought occupied largely with theological and social discussion, which arrogated to itself, in the second half of the eighteenth century, the prerogatives of reason and common-sense. To this widespread movement in England and Germany a movement characteristic of the eighteenth century, though doubtless having its origin in an earlier period, and continuing its influence into the present century the name Eationalism, in a specific sense, is very frequently applied in philosophical and theological writing. It is the period which Hegelian writers commonly designate as that of the Aufklarung or Enlightenment. That these are the discussions and 1 " nationalists," he says, "as such, are not philosophers. e . They judge as men of the world" (p. 171). R 258 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. this the temper of mind which Mr Balfour intends to condemn, is proved, to my mind, beyond doubt, by the chapter on "Kationalist Orthodoxy," which concludes this part of the book. It has often been remarked that the orthodox defenders of Christianity were as completely under the influence of the domi- nant spirit as its assailants. The presuppositions and methods of both parties were the same. The attack was delivered and the defence conducted with the same weapons. Mr Balfour accordingly turns, in this chapter, to the defenders of the faith, and condemns unsparingly the inadequacy both of the systems of " Natural Eeligion " and of the " Christian evidences " which were then so much in vogue. By this method of treatment, he declares, theology becomes a mere annex or appendix to Science, a mere footnote to history. . . . "We are no longer dealing with a creed whose real premisses lie deep in the nature of things. . . . We are asked to believe the Universe to have been designed by a Deity for the same sort of reason that we believe Canter- bury Cathedral to have been designed by an architect ; and to believe in the events narrated in the Gospels for the same sort of reason that we believe in the murder of Thomas a Becket (p. 178). Professor Wallace is one of the critics who censures most severely Mr Balfour's dealings with Eeason and ME BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 259 Eationalism ; but in a chapter of his recent Pro- legomena to Hegel's 'Logic/ entitled "Two Ages of Keason/' he comments in a similar strain upon the period and spirit in question, and even while em- phasising the larger use of Eeason, his language ac- knowledges the frequent appropriation of Eeason and Eationalism (but especially of the latter) in a narrower or lower sense : The eighteenth century, it has been often said, was a rationalising, unhistorical age. ... To simplify, to level, to render intelligible and self -consistent, was the task of enlightenment in dealing with all institutions. It was assumed that the standard of adjudication was to be found in the averagely educated and generally cultured individual among the class of more or less " advanced thinkers " who asked the questions and set up the aims. . . . They took themselves as the types of humanity and what their under- standings found acceptable they dubbed rational : all else was a survival from the ages of darkness. But, in course of time, he proceeds, it was made apparent that intelligence, with its hard-and-fast formulae, its logical principles, its keen analysis, was not deep enough or wide enough to justify its claim to the august title of reason. . . . There are more things in heaven and earth than are heard of in the philosophy of the logical intellect. This phrase, " the logical intellect," or, as he elsewhere varies it, the " merely intellectual and abstract in- 260 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. telligence," exactly covers the old Eationalism which Mr Balfour attacks. Professor Wallace contrasts it with " the Eeason of German Idealism," which he describes as "intelligence charged with emotion, full of reverence, reverent above all to the majesty of that divinity which, much disguised and weather- beaten, like Glaucus of the sea, resides in common and natural humanity." But these words might have been written as a description of the provisional phil- osophy which Mr Balfour sketches in his concluding chapters, and proposes to substitute for Naturalism and abstract Eationalism. They dwell, at any rate, with felicitous emphasis on its leading characteristics ; and, on this showing, Mr Balfour's ' Suggestions,' no less than German Idealism, might fairly be styled a doc- trine of the larger Eeason. In the substance of his contention, therefore, Mr Balfour may claim to have powerful philosophical support from a quarter sufficiently free from the sus- picion of clericalism or supernaturalism ; and even his terminology, when examined, is found not to stray so far from common usage. Eationalism is, I think, most commonly used in the hard and narrow sense he attributes to it. At the same time, the usage is undeniably open to misconception ; and it was a thou- MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 261 sand pities that it was not more carefully fenced about with explanation. Moreover, what a man may safely do often depends on his own past record. Mr Balfour's antecedent reputation for scepticism (not undeserved, as we saw) made it almost certain that, in his case, an attack on Eationalism would be interpreted in the worst sense. And when to this was added the glorifi- cation of authority at the expense of reason, in the chapters which immediately follow, this interpretation became inevitable. The dissertation on Authority and Eeason may be best understood as a supplement to the criticism of Eationalism which precedes it. After denying the competency of the logical intellect to solve the phil- osophical problem, Mr Balfour proceeds to show, by reference to everyday experience, how few human beliefs have been reached by a conscious process of ratiocination in the minds of the individuals who hold them. He amplifies, that is to say, the Humian dictum quoted above, that certitude is the child not of reason but of custom. The vast majority of our beliefs, of our ethical, social, and religious beliefs in particular, are in this sense without a logical substructure; they have been generated in the individual by "custom, education, public opinion, the contagious convictions 262 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. of countrymen, family, party, or Church." Immense tracts of human life thiis lie apparently altogether out- side the purview of the abstract reason ; indeed, so far from the mass of our fundamental beliefs de- pending on the reasoned assent of the individuals who entertain them, we know from history that when men do begin to analyse their beliefs and usages, their abstract theorising is apt to be purely disintegrative in its tendency. Stated in this form, Mr Balfour's contention is so obviously true that it is difficult to imagine any one dissenting from it. But he has chosen to express his meaning by opposing Authority to Eeason, and contrasting its beneficent and all - pervading influence with "the comparative pettiness of the role played by reasoning in human affairs." To Eeason we are in some measure beholden, though not, perhaps, so much as we suppose, for hourly aid in managing so much of the trifling portion of our personal affairs intrusted to ourselves by nature as we do not happen to have already surrendered to the control of habit. By reason also is directed, or misdirected, the public policy of communities within the narrow limits of deviation per- mitted by accepted custom and tradition. . . . (But) if we are to judge with equity between these rival claimants, we must not forget that it is Authority rather than Reason to which, in the main, we owe, not religion only, but ethics MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 263 and politics ; that it is Authority which supplies us with essential elements in the premisses of science ; that it is Authority rather than Eeason which lays deep the foun- dations of social life; that it is Authority rather than Eeason which cements its superstructure (pp. 227-229). Mr Balfour must have foreseen that round phrases like these there would gather at once a hubbub of excited and ill-informed controversy; and the love of mischief would seem to have had some share in promp- ting their use. Both the terms are, in this respect, unfortunate. In the case of "Eeason," Mr Balfour remarks, in a note, that the term is used "in its ordinary and popular, not in its transcendental sense ; there is no question here of the Logos, or Absolute Eeason"; and the course of the discussion makes it plain that he uses it as strictly equivalent to " reason- ing," or conscious logical ratiocination. The two terms, " reason " and " reasoning," sometimes cross and recross one another several times in the course of the same page, with no distinction between them. Now, this usage is no doubt common among the older English thinkers ; but it is certainly not the ordinary sense of the term in recent philosophic writing. Eeason, if it does not always explicitly convey a larger meaning, at least constantly tends to assume that sense, and by no 264 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. means only with thinkers of a transcendental cast. Mr Balfour himself speaks of Naturalism as deposing " Eeason from its ancient position as the ground of all existence" (p. 75) ; he speaks of Eeason as "the roof and crown of things " of the universe as " the creation of Eeason" (p. 72), and of all things as working to- gether " towards a reasonable end " (p. 83). Clearly, when he uses these expressions, he has something more in view than the "intellect," or "discursive reason," which is only " permitted to have a hand in the simplest jobs" (p. 72). It is the limited range of the latter which he intends to contrast with the omnipresent action of authority ; but by insisting, as he does repeatedly, on the "non-rational" character of the causes which he groups under that name, he conveys the impression that they have no relation to Eeason in the larger sense that they are really what he calls in one place " utterances of unreason." Then, again, the use of the term Authority in this connection has even less excuse. It has no justification in ordinary usage ; on the contrary, owing to the fixed associations of the word, it is a use which invites mis- conception. What are the causes which Mr Balfour groups under this head? He enumerates them vari- ously, but they include " custom, education, public MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 265 opinion" (p. 213), "the contagious convictions of countrymen, family, party, or Church," and, not least, " the spirit of the age," producing a certain " psycho- logical ' atmosphere/ or ' climate,' favourable to the life of certain modes of belief, unfavourable, and even fatal, to the life of others " (p. 206). Habit, in the manage- ment of our personal affairs, is also contrasted with Eeason, as we have seen, in the same way as " accepted custom and tradition," in the direction of the public policy of communities ; and both are apparently in- cluded under the head of authority. " Authority," he says in the passage which most nearly approaches to a definition " Authority, as I have been using the term, is in all cases contrasted with Eeason, and stands for that group of non-rational causes, moral, social, and educational, which produces its results by psychic processes other than reasoning" (p. 219). This ap- pears to me to involve a complete departure from ordinary usage. Newman, it is true, gives a similar extension to the term in a note to his ' Apologia,' but he acknowledges that he is using the word " in a broad sense " ; and even there the reference seems to be, not to the unconscious action of the forces referred to, but to the conscious use of them as sanctions. Certainly in ordinary usage the term is limited conveniently 266 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. and intelligibly limited to the conscious adoption by the individual of the beliefs of some other person, or of some historical organisation, without personal exam- ination of the beliefs in question. Mr Balfour refers to this usage, which he distinguishes from his own. He rightly points out that in this sense Authority "becomes a species of Keason," but a reason which can in no case furnish us with the foundation for a system of belief, seeing that there is always involved a prior reason for submitting individual belief and conduct to the particular authority in question. But however inconsistent it may be to appeal to Authority as a logical foundation for a system of beliefs, the fact remains that the term Authority has been appropriated, by almost universal usage, to designate this attitude of conscious submission on the part of the individual reasoner ; and Mr Balfour can hardly fail, therefore, to be misunderstood when he uses it in a sense so widely different. He uses it to cover the manifold forces that unconsciously mould the belief and con- duct of the individual, his own training in the past, his social environment, the historic life of the com- munity and the race to which he belongs above all, the influence of history. As it is put by a German reviewer, otherwise sympathetic, who objects to the MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 267 misleading implications of the term Authority : " What Mr Balfour says may all be covered by the proposition that we men, in our higher spiritual life, are the pro- ducts of history before we are its producers, and that in this double relation of ours to history the weight is permanently to be placed upon the first member, upon our dependence on the historical factors which surround and determine us." l But if this is so, it disposes at once of the absolute opposition supposed to exist between these two groups of causes. Habits are, as it were, the deposits of reason. An action is first performed consciously, with minute supervision of every step or detail; but, according to the beneficent provision of nature, the action goes more smoothly the oftener it is repeated, and the active supervision of consciousness is no longer required. The action has become habitual, and the higher energies of the living creature are set at liberty for the performance of new tasks, the acquirement of other dexterities. This applies to the humblest bodily exercises ; but we have only to recall Aristotle's defini- tion of virtue as a habit, to recognise that it holds equally in the highest reaches of the ethical life. Habit, being thus the creation of reason, cannot be 1 Professor Kaftan in the ' Preussische Jahrbiicher,' vol. Ixxxii. 268 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. opposed to it as an alien force. And the same is true of custom, tradition, public opinion, the spirit of the age. They are non-rational, certainly, in the sense that their determining influence over the individual does not depend on a conscious process of ratiocination on his part a progress from premisses to conclusion. But customs and institutions are themselves originally the product of the conscious activities of human beings. They constitute, in their first intention, the objective realisation of a rational system; and so long as they continue to hold society together at all, they still are this in their degree. Doubtless, no customs or institu- tions are the adequate or final embodiment of Eeason ; and hence they are subject to progressive modification, or, if you like, rationalisation. In this way, the old comes to be opposed to the new, and to be regarded as a mere obstruction on the path of Eeason. But tra- dition and custom are opposed to Eeason, only as the good is opposed to the better. They have their birth from Eeason originally, and they continue throughout accessible to its transforming influence. In fact, it does not seem too much to say that Mr Balfour, continuing in these chapters his attack upon the abstract, or, as he afterwards calls it, the "un- assisted Eeason" of the rationalists, is really vindi- MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 269 eating, in his own way, that larger sense of Eeason, characteristic of the present century, which recognises that thought becomes formal and empty, just in propor- tion as it cuts itself adrift from the historical develop- ment of mankind. To take only the case of ethics, the advance of historical study has long lifted us above the notion of an abstract conscience, promulgating to all men the same perfect moral law. The content of the moral law grows every way from age to age. The progress of man upwards, from " the ape and tiger " to the civilisation of the present day with its altruistic and humanitarian ideals this whole ethical process with the customs and institutions in which it embodies itself, its laws, its public opinion, its shifting but ever deepening and widening ideals of honour and chivalry, of heroism or saintly life, of justice and self-control all this development can only be rightly understood when regarded as the progressive revelation from within of an ideal of goodness, which in itself is the most real of realities. From this development we derive the substance of the ethical code. If, like Kant, we neglect to root the individual in the cor- porate life of humanity, the categorical imperative remains a form void of specific content a command which refuses to translate itself into any concrete duty. 270 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. In ethics, as in other spheres, the advance of specula- tive thought since Kant has mainly consisted in sur- mounting the abstract and unhistoric individualism of preceding philosophy. Hence, as Professor Wallace eloquently puts it, in its modern conception, "Phil- osophy is not the work of abstract or ' unassisted ' Reason. The pure reason of philosophers is a reason which has been purified of dross, corruption, and sluggishness by the discipline of the sciences, by the heroism and conscientiousness of religion, by the fair and noble intuitions of art; otherwise it is little worth." 1 To this view of Reason, to this interpretation of the historical process, Mr Balfour seems to be working his way, even in those sections which appear at first sight, owing to their unfortunate terminology, most uncom- promisingly opposed to it. The sheer distinction be- tween Reason and Authority, or, as we may agree to put it, between Reason and History, is not in the end adopted as true. It is employed as a weapon with which to destroy Naturalism and the barren Rational- ism whose offspring Naturalism is represented as being. It is in this sense an argumentum ad hominem. If we limit reason to the discursive intellect in its conscious 1 'Fortnightly Review,' April 1895. MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 271 exercise, and if we refuse to take a theistic view of man and the world, then undoubtedly the beliefs and prac- tices which fill out our life must appear as the products of non-rational causes, just as our existence as living and conscious beings is itself, on these terms, the outcome of unreasoning material forces. But the whole aim of the demonstration is to impress upon the reader the necessity of the theistic postulate. That this is the real significance of Mr Balfour's argument, and the true place of this discussion in the sequence of his thought, is proved by the account he gives of it himself, in retrospect, in his concluding chapter. The fundamental difficulty of Naturalism, he says, the difficulty the book is designed to press home, is the ineffaceable incongruity between the origin of our beliefs, so far as these can be revealed to us by Science, and the beliefs themselves. This it was that, as I showed in the first part of this Essay, touched with the frost of scepticism our ideals of conduct and our ideals of beauty. This it was that, as I showed in the Second Part, cut down scientific philosophy to the root. And all the later discussions with which I have occupied the attention of the reader, serve but to emphasise afresh the inextricable confusion which the naturalistic hypothesis introduces into every department of speculation and practice, by refusing to allow us to penetrate beyond the phenomenal causes, by which, in the order of 272 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. Nature, our beliefs are produced. . . . When once we have realised the scientific truth that at the root of every rational process lies an irrational one ; that reason, from a scientific point of view, is itself a natural product ; and that the whole material on which it works is due to causes, physical, physiological, and social, which it neither creates nor con- trols, we shall be driven in mere self-defence to hold that, behind these non-rational forces, and above them, guiding them by slow degrees, and, as it were, with difficulty, to a rational issue, stands that Supreme Reason in whom we must thus believe, if we are to believe in anything (pp. 321-323). The last sentences carry us already far into the heart of Part IV., in which the author passes from criticism to the more difficult task of construction. If the preconception of Mr Balfour's misology and scepti- cism still lingers in any reader's mind, it should be effectually dispelled by his language here. He ex- pressly denies " that the object aimed at in preceding discussions is to discredit reason " (p. 246), and declares that " the unification of all belief into an ordered whole compacted into one coherent structure under the stress of reason is an ideal which we can never abandon" (p. 233). But, as he truly adds, " Eeason is not honoured by pretending that she has done what, as a matter of fact, is still undone"; "the best system we can hope to construct will suffer from gaps and MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 273 rents, from loose ends and ragged edges. It does not, however, follow from this that it will be without a high degree of value." If we have to submit, as I think we must, to an incom- plete rationalisation of belief, this ought not to be because, in a fit of intellectual despair, we are driven to treat Reason as an illusion ; nor yet because we have deliberately resolved to transfer our allegiance to irrational or non-rational inclin- ation; but because Reason itself assures us that such a course is, at the lowest, the least irrational one open to us (p. 234). What is this but an acknowledgment in fitting terms of the incompleteness and imperfection of any finite synthesis ? I do not understand, and I do not envy, the state of mind of the thinker who is not prepared to make a similar confession. Proceeding, then, to "rationalise," to "unify," or "co-ordinate," as far as may be, our various beliefs, Mr Balfour begins by setting the Naturalistic theory aside as inherently irrational. Naturalism had been condemned, in the first part of the volume, because it did not satisfy the demands of our ethical nature. He here pronounces more generally that, inasmuch as the Whole of which we desire a reasoned knowledge includes human consciousness as an element, we must s 274 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. refuse to " regard any system which, like Naturalism, leaves large tracts and aspects of that consciousness unaccounted for and derelict as other than, to that extent at least, irrational" (p. 250). Moreover, it was shown in Part II. that the body of beliefs about the material world which we take for granted in ordinary experience, and which science presents us with in an elaborated form, cannot themselves be exhibited as a series of logical conclusions for which the particulars of sense furnish the premisses. It had to be regarded rather as an assumption which we found it necessary to make in practical life ; as Mr Balf our here expresses him- self, it is essentially the satisfaction of a need. Doubt- less the belief in question possesses an " inevitable " and " coercive " character not shared by other beliefs ; but that constitutes no logical justification for erecting the judgments of sense-perception into a norm or standard, by which all other beliefs must be judged. To do so would be to substitute "psychological compulsion for rational necessity." Universality and necessity, as here exemplified, may be "marks of the elementary and primitive character of the beliefs," but hardly "badges of pre-eminence." It is the plain dictate of reason that our scheme, " though it be founded on the last resort upon our needs, shall at least take account MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 275 of other needs than those we share with our brute progenitors." And on this point Mr Balfour appeals to the example of the great masters of speculation. Though they have not, it may be, succeeded in supplying us with a satisfactory explanation of the Universe, at least the Universe which they have sought to explain has been something more than a mere collection of hypostatised sense-perceptions, packed side by side in space, and follow- ing each other with blind uniformity in time (p. 243). The argument from needs to their satisfaction, here generalised, is the constructive principle on which Mr Balfour depends, and furnishes, I think, the key to a true understanding of the book. The author himself recognises that the argument is one which requires to be applied with great caution, if the wish is not to be father to the thought ; and he apparently lays no stress on this particular way of formulating it. Whether this correspondence is best described as that which obtains between a "need" and its "satisfaction," may be open to question. But, at all events, let it be understood that if the relation described is, on the one side, something different from that between a premiss and its conclusion, so, on the other, it is intended to be equally remote from that between a desire and its fulfilment. That it has not the logical validity of the first, I have already admitted, or rather asserted. That it has not the casual, wavering, and purely " subjective " character of the second, 276 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. is not less true. For the correspondence postulated is not between the fleeting fancies of the individual and the immutable verities of an unseen world, but between these characteristics of our nature which we recognise as that in us which, though not necessarily the strongest, is the highest; which, though not always the most universal, is neverthe- less the best (pp. 247, 248). Instead of further abstract debate as to the scope and legitimacy of the argument, let us see how Mr Balfour applies it. Its true nature will be best shown by the concrete examples of its use, and we shall then be better able to form a judgment as to its legitimacy. It is first applied, in the intellectual sphere, to demon- strate the implications or presuppositions of the scientific view itself, or of the mere fact that we know. Mr Balfour had already pointed out, in dealing with our belief in the uniformity of nature, that this belief can- not be proved by the facts, seeing that it is a postulate implied in the very idea of investigating facts. In these constructive chapters, he amplifies this thought in a remarkably fresh and striking way. After dealing instructively with some of the usual arguments for Theism, he proceeds to push the question a stage further back. But "something may also be inferred from the mere fact that we know, a fact which, like every other, has to be accounted for." And after some MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 277 luminous pages, in which he presses home the funda- mental inconsequence of Naturalism, in requiring us " to accept a system as rational, one of whose doctrines is that the system itself is the product of causes which have no tendency to truth rather than falsehood, or to falsehood rather than truth," l he concludes : " I do not believe that any escape from these perplexities is possible, unless we are prepared to bring to the study of the world the presupposition that it was the work of a rational Being, who made it intelligible, and at the same time made us, in however feeble a fashion, able to understand it" (p. 301). Theism is thus a "presupposition," "not only tolerated but actually required by Science " (p. 321). It is " forced upon us by the single assumption that Science is not an illusion." As he put it before, we are "driven in mere self-defence " to the belief in a Supreme Eeason directing the apparently non-rational forces of nature ; we "must" believe in Supreme Reason, "if we are to believe in anything." But this admission, if once made, cannot stand alone. If we " postulate a rational God in the interests of Science, we can scarcely de- 1 One might say, indeed, that the very notion of truth is an inex- plicable excrescence or inconsequence in a world where everything simply is or happens. 278 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. cline to postulate a moral God in the interests of Morality." And, in th'e light of this presupposition, the whole process by which the ethical code and the moral sentiments have been slowly developed appears in a different setting, as "an instrument for carrying out a divine purpose/' as a divine education of the human race. Such, without following them into details, are the important conclusions which Mr Balfour reaches by the method of argument he follows. When they are thus stated summarily, and detached from some of the discussions which accompany them, the philoso- phical student can hardly fail to remark the striking- resemblance of Mr Balfour's mode of argument to the transcendental method of Kant, and the affinity of his conclusions to those of Kant's idealistic successors. In saying this, it is far from my intention to depre- ciate the freshness and independence of Mr Balfour's treatment; on the contrary, he has, I think, accom- plished a remarkable feat in working his way from a different starting-point, and to a large extent by a different route, to this fundamental argument. And he has made it doubly his own by clothing it in pel- lucid English, which he who runs may read. It is the transcendental argument stated with a luminous sim- MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 279 plicity, as it might have been stated by Hume, had he returned in maturer life to the metaphysical medi- tations of his youth. But the argument itself is in substance identical with that which Kant patiently dug from the d&yris of rationalism, and built into a system, so palpably artificial in its details and so cumbrously pedantic in its terminology, that the philosophical world has been engaged ever since in quarrelling over its interpretation. When we pene- trate beneath the portentous phrases to the compara- tively humble truth which they labour to express, Kant's "objective unity of apperception," as the supreme condition of the possibility of experience, is simply the assertion that the idea of "a nature" or a rational system is not a conclusion from particular facts, but is involved, as a postulate or presupposition, in there being any experience of facts at all. And when, at the close of his investigation, he emphasises the adaptation of phenomena to our faculty of cognition, as proof of a harmony between sense and understanding, that is to say, ultimately, a harmony between the world and the mind; when he argues that this adaptation justifies us in treating reality as everywhere rational- isable, and therefore as if it were the product of a supreme reason ; this, in more scholastic form, and 280 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. with Kant's well-known reservation as to the merely regulative character of -the Ideas of Eeason, is neither more nor less than the argument from the mere fact that we know. But to colligate Kant's different state- ments, and to disengage what is central and vital in his argument from its perplexing and useless integu- ments, is a task which demands both philosophical and exegetical skill. The English world has as yet failed, for the most part, to grasp Kant's way of putting this argument ; we shall be curious to see whether it proves more accessible to Mr Balfour's presentation of it. Mr Balfour himself does not seem to be aware how closely the general attitude of mind he recommends in Part IV. corresponds to the transcendental proof from the possibility of experience. In the earlier part of his work, he emphasises the impossibility of reaching a satisfactory foundation by means of "inferences of the ordinary pattern" (p. 186). He recognises that, in his own argument, the relation between needs and their satisfaction is "something different from that between a premiss and a conclusion " (p. 248) ; and at the close of the theistic argument which we have just examined (from the mere fact that we know), he seems to hesitate whether the term proof can be properly applied to it. " Theism," he says, " whether or not it can in the MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. strict meaning of the word be described as proved by Science, is a principle which Science . . . requires for its own completion. . . . Our knowledge of that system is inexplicable unless we assume for it a rational Author " (p. 302). In such passages, it seems almost as if the writer were feeling his way to a new point of view, and were hardly aware of the strength of his own method. It is unduly to disparage the nature of his argument to contrast it with logical procedure, or to hesitate to call it a proof. It implies, certainly, the abandonment of the old ideal of a philosophical system, " as a series of premisses and conclusions, starting from those which are axiomatic i.e., for which proof can neither be given nor required, and running on through a continuous series of binding inferences, until the whole of knowledge is caught up and ordered in the meshes of this all-inclusive dialectic network" (p. 105). If by premisses, in other words, we understand either isolated intuitions or the particulars of sense, then it may be said that the transcendental argument neither starts from premisses nor arrives at a conclusion. Yet, in a more vital sense, experience itself, as a concrete fact demanding explanation, constitutes the premiss from which we advance (or rather regress) to its im- plied condition or explaining cause. The postulate or 282 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. presupposition thus reached is, from one point of view, a conclusion ; from another, it is the ultimate premiss on which all our conclusions in a certain department or, in this case, all conclusions whatever depend. If we can speak, as Mr Balfour himself does, of the pre- supposition as "actually required by science," as " forced upon us by the mere assumption that Science is not an illusion " as a necessary assumption, " if we are to believe in anything" then it seems to me a merely technical question, whether we agree to call the process of reaching it an inference or not. We have, at all events, the element of logical necessity in its most unequivocal form. The Kantian terms, postulates, presuppositions (im- plications also, I think) are used from time to time by Mr Balfour, either as nouns or verbs. As a general term, postulate seems to me much the best. Need and satisfaction are probably words of too every- day a character to express a fundamental speculative position ; they are too coloured by the associations of life to express a philosophical meaning with precision. No doubt the word " need " often appeals to us, just by its breadth and simplicity, and in some connections no word would seem so appropriate. But to many it seems little more than a glorified wish ; and although MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 283 this is unjust, it cannot be denied that the associations of the word are too predominantly emotional. Now when we speak even of ethical or religious needs, it is not only the emotional disappointment, the collapse of hope and joy, that is referred to, but the fact that the denial of the postulated reality inverts the whole proportions of our life, irrationalises the whole scheme of things presupposed by our ordinary experience. The word postulate seems to express admirably both this element of intellectual necessity in the argument, and, at the same time, the subjective element, which is undoubtedly also present. For universal scepticism admits of no refutation ; a man must admit certain aspects of experience before any argument can be founded upon them. But no nice question of terminology need affect our sense of the importance and fundamental truth of the argument itself. The acknowledgment of rational necessity which it involves rather, I should say, the insistence on rational necessity constitutes the advance in Mr Balfour's thought on which I have desired to lay stress. Although at times his phrase- ology may waver, and we may catch the echo of passages in ' Philosophic Doubt ' which identify "needs" with " non - rational impulses," yet, on the 284 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. whole, the difference of tone is marked. The needs are here presented as the needs of reason itself. In the case of the intellectual argument, this may perhaps be allowed to be obvious. But it is no less so in the case of the ethical. Whereas he had formerly said "I and an indefinite number of other persons feel a practical need for [ethical and religious beliefs], but no legitimate argument can be founded on the mere existence of this need or impulse. We are on this matter, unfortunately, altogether outside the sphere of Eeason," he now condemns the Naturalistic theory as " irrational," and claims that his own is founded on " the plain dictates of reason." From the former standpoint, argument is impossible, and is admitted to be so ; but in the present volume we are no longer "outside the sphere of Eeason." The whole scheme of construction implies that we have passed from " psychological compulsion " to " rational necessity." Mr Balfour may be said to be trying, throughout the volume, to establish a definition of truth or of Keason which shall be at once more comprehensive and more self-consistent than that which limits it to the facts and laws of physical Science. The truth, if fully known, must include, he argues, a satisfactory ex- planation of our ethical, sesthetical, and religious ideas MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. 285 and sentiments. The self-styled truth that fails to do this is a fragment which men have mistaken for the whole a fragment, moreover, which cannot even supply its own foundation. Such a system arrogates to itself unjustly the august name of truth, for truth cannot land us in an open contradiction between equally fundamental constituents of our nature. But if this is so, the appeal of the volume is not from truth to authority but from a partial to a fuller truth, from man conceived as mere abstract intellect to human nature as a whole. In his method, as I have said, Mr Balfour resembles Kant, and, like Kant, he passes from the intellectual to the ethical domain. But, in his conclusions, he approaches more nearly the general position of Hegel. In the metaphysical application of his thought, he enforces the dependence of the subjective reason of the individual on the objective reason of the historic process, and recognises a cosmic or Absolute Reason as the ground of the whole development. What dis- tinguishes all three alike is (in one way of putting it) the unwavering humanism of their point of view, as opposed to the naturalism of those who would crush the spirit of man by thrusting upon it the immensities of physical nature, of infinite space and endless time. 286 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. Mr Balfour, in some searching pages, has exposed the fallacy of such a mode of argument : material grandeur and moral excellences, as he well says, are incom- mensurable quantities. And in the age-long debate which has divided thinkers since the time of Democ- ritus and Plato, this has been the essential import of all the great idealistic systems Travrwv xprujudrtov /jierpov avOpwTTos. This thesis, first formulated by scepticism, is in point of fact, when properly inter- preted, profoundly true. Our own nature is, from the very circumstances of the case, the only measuring- rod which we can apply to the universe. " A harmony of some sort between our inner selves and the universe of which we form a part is a tacit postulate," as Mr Balfour says, "of every belief we entertain about phenomena." Our intellect is, after all, as much ours as any other part of our being, and in accepting the account of science as true, the Naturalist is involun- tarily postulating harmony, to that extent, between himself and the universe. But why should this harmony be limited to the intellectual activities of sense-perception ? It is impossible to show that this limitation is other than arbitrary, and that we have not as good a right to use as our touchstone of reality those inspirations of goodness which are the spur of MR BALFOUK AND HIS CRITICS. 287 all our endeavour, and those visions of beauty and of harmonious truth which are a master-light of all our seeing. Man must be anthropomorphic. What we ask is simply that his anthropomorphism shall be deliberate, consistent, and critical, instead of being un- conscious, partial, and arbitrary. But if, in these latter remarks, I have emphasised the affinity of Mr Balfour's thought to these systems of the larger Keason of which Hegel's is the most convenient example, the affinity is obviously not to be understood in any narrow or rigid sense. His whole intellectual temper is different ; some might say it is more sceptical, others might say it is more human, by which I mean more cognisant of the limita- tions of humanity. There is one important Hegelian doctrine at least with which Mr Balfour is strenuously at one the doctrine of " degrees of truth," the insight that all truth is a matter of approximation, that no error is wholly false and no finite truth is wholly true. This doctrine, recently re-expounded by Mr Bradley with so much force, is an integral part of Hegelian thought, but a part strangely forgotten in the claim of the system to represent absolute truth, to be indeed the insight of the Absolute Being into his own essence and history. The temper of Mr Balfour's book is 288 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS. well exhibited by contrast in a characteristic passage, with which this long review may fitly close : I like to think of the human race, from whatever stock its members may have sprung, in whatever age they may be born, whatever creed they may profess, together in the presence of the One Reality, engaged not wholly in vain, in spelling out some fragments of its message. All share its being ; to none are its oracles wholly dumb. And if, both in the natural world and in the spiritual, the advancement we have made 011 our forefathers be so great that our in- terpretation seems indefinitely removed from that which primitive man could alone apprehend, and wherewith he had to be content, it may be, indeed I think it is, the case that our approximate guesses are closer to his than they are to their common Object, and that, far as we seem to have travelled, yet, measured on the celestial scale, our intellectual progress is scarcely to be discerned, so minute is the parallax of Infinite Truth. NOTE A. THE USE OF THE TERM "NATURALISM.' ONE of the results of Mr Balfour's ' Foundations of Belief has been to bring to light some serious, and even remarkable, divergences of view as to the meaning and precise application of current philosophical terms. This was particularly the case in regard to the term Naturalism, which is so prominent in Mr Balfour's argument. Much of the criticism of the book took, in fact, the form of an indignant repudiation of the author's use of names. It may perhaps, therefore, contribute to the fixing of philosophical usage in this case, and in the case of some other terms frequently conjoined with it, if, starting from Mr Balfour's defini- tions, we examine his usage in the light of some of the chief objections taken to it. In his introductory chapter, Mr Balfour thus indi- T 290 THE USE OF THE TERM "NATURALISM." cates the system of thought against which his book is directed : Whatever the name selected, the thing itself is suffi- ciently easy to describe. For its leading doctrines are that we may know phenomena and the laws by which they are connected but nothing more. " More " there may or may not be, but if it exists we can never apprehend it; and whatever the World may be " in its reality " (suppos- ing such an expression to be otherwise than meaningless), the World for us, the World with which alone we are con- cerned, or of which we alone can have any cognisance, is that World which is revealed to us through perception, and which is the subject-matter of the Natural Sciences. Here, and here only, are we on firm ground. Here, and here only, can we discover anything which deserves to be described as Knowledge. Here, and here only, may we profitably exercise our reason or gather the fruits of Wisdom (p. 7). In another passage he speaks of " the two elements composing the naturalistic creed : the one positive, con- sisting, broadly speaking, of the teaching contained in the general body of the natural sciences; the other negative, expressed in the doctrine that beyond these limits, wherever they may happen to lie, nothing is, and nothing can be, known " (p. 92) ; and again of " the assumption that the kind of ' experience ' which gave us natural science was the sole basis of knowledge," and " the further inference that nothing deserved to be THE USE OF THE TERM " NATURALISM." 291 called Knowledge which did not come within the circle of the natural sciences " (p. 171). " After all," he says in another place, "Naturalism is nothing more than the assertion that empirical methods are valid and that no others are so " (p. 134). In these passages the theory is defined by reference to its presuppositions or method; when we look at the resulting body of doc- trine, we find that the theory attempts " the impossible task of extracting reason from unreason " (p. 301). It involves the deposition of Reason from its ancient position as the ground of all existence to that of an expedient among other ex- pedients for the maintenance of organic life ; an expedient, moreover, which is temporary in its character and insig- nificant in its effects. An irrational Universe which acci- dentally turns out a few reasoning animals at one corner of it, as a rich man may experiment at one end of his park with some curious " sport " accidentally produced among his flocks and herds, is a Universe which we might well despise, if we did not ourselves share its degradation (p. 75). And, finally, the naturalistic catechism which he elaborates at the conclusion of the first part of the volume clearly identifies Naturalism with consistent Materialism (pp. 83-85). To the system whose substantive doctrines he thus 292 THE USE OF THE TEEM "NATURALISM." indicates, Mr Balfour applies throughout his volume the term Naturalism. "" Agnosticism, Positivism, Em- piricism," he says, "have all been used more or less correctly to describe this scheme of thought, though in the following pages, for reasons with which it is not necessary to trouble the reader, the term which I shall commonly employ is Naturalism." This pas- sage and the usage it indicates have called forth em- phatic disclaimers from the patrons or representatives of the views which are here practically identified. Each objects to be identified with any of the others, and they all disclaim responsibility for the system of doctrines attributed to them in common. Professor Huxley, not unnaturally jealous for the honour of the term which he invented, objected " to making Agnosti- cism the scapegoat, on whose head the philosophic sins of the companions with whom it is improperly associated may be conveniently piled up " ; while Mr Erederic Harrison, as a Positivist, is still more wroth to find himself identified with the Agnostics, against whom he has so often gone forth to war in the Ke- views. "The passage just quoted," he says, "is a coagulated clot of confusion and misstatement " from which it is easy to see that Mr Harrison is very angry indeed. Professor Wallace, on the other hand, THE USE OF THE TERM "NATURALISM." 293 though himself accepting in the main an Idealism of the Hegelian type, puts a lance in rest for Naturalism, which he seems to think has been hardly treated in being identified with its own extreme consequences. " Its faults," he says, " spring from a creditable motive. It is the desire to be honest, to say only what you can prove, to require thorough continuity and con- sistency in the whole realm of accepted truths. 1 Naturalism was a reaction from the follies of Super- naturalism." Naturalism [he says again] was at the outset and in es- sence a negation, not of the supernatural in general, but of a supernatural conceived as incoherent, arbitrary, and chaotic ; a protest against a conception which separated God from the world, as a potter from his clay, against the ignava ratio which took customary sequences of events as needing 1 I cannot help remarking the striking similarity between this ac- count of Naturalism and Professor Huxley's truly extraordinary definition of Agnosticism as consisting essentially " in the application of a single principle, which is the fundamental axiom of modern science. Positively, this principle may be thus expressed : in matters of the intellect, follow your reason as far as it will take you, without regard to any other consideration. And negatively : in matters of the intellect, do not pretend that conclusions are certain which are not demonstrated or demonstrable." On this showing, we should all desire with one accord to take service under the Agnostic flag, for Agnosticism, so defined, is another name for intellectual honesty. Similarly, on Professor Wallace's showing, no self-respecting person would permit himself to be called anything but a Naturalist. 294 THE USE OF THE TERM "NATURALISM." no explanation, and looked for special revelation from por- tents and wonders. 1 Understanding Supernaturalism in this sense, Professor Wallace regrets "that some recognition of the inner aims of Eationalism and Naturalism is not vouchsafed," and he would evidently prefer to rehabilitate the term Naturalism and follow that banner, rather than be suspected of any complicity with a discredited Super- naturalism. To this Mr Balfour might easily retort that his purpose was not an historical review of the progress of opinion, but an attempt to deal directly with current ways of looking at the universe, using terms as nearly as possible in the sense which is most general in philosophic usage, and which they tend to bear in the vocabulary of educated people. And al- though Naturalism, as a matter of etymology and his- tory, may take its rise as merely the denial of an external and arbitrary Supernaturalism, I think there can be no reasonable doubt that the name has acquired within the present century the signification which Mr Balfour gives it, and that it has, indeed, of late been gradually supplanting other terms as the most fitting designation for the system of beliefs in question. 1 These quotations are from an article by Professor Wallace in the ' Fortnightly Keview ' for April 1895. THE USE OF THE TERM "NATURALISM." 295 Naturalism, in accepted phraseology, is a name appli- cable to any system which, as Mr Balfour expresses it, finds the metaphysical or permanent reality of the universe in " the world which is revealed to us through perception and which is the subject-matter of the Natural Sciences." Naturalism is, therefore, practi- cally identical with Materialism, though it may not pretend to explain the origin of the phenomena of consciousness from matter in motion, but may content itself, in that regard, with a doctrine of concomitance. In any case, the fundamental explanation the central fact of the universe is to be found, according to the theory, not in the phenomena of consciousness with their rational and ethical implications, but in the mechanical system of causes and effects of which con- sciousness seems to be the outcome or accompaniment. If that is so, any attempt to re-define Naturalism in such a way that absolute Idealism might reasonably be included under it, could only result in still further confusing the issues. The " New Naturalism," of which Professor Wallace constitutes himself the champion, would have, as he says, " to repair the defects of the Old." But when repairs are so extensive as to alter the whole structure and outlook of the building, the question as to the identity of the edifice becomes a point 296 THE USE OF THE TERM "NATURALISM." of casuistry. Naturalism, in ordinary usage, is the anti- thesis not merely of the Supernaturalism which finds its support in supposed divine " interference," but also of every spiritual or idealistic theory of the universe. The wide influence of Mr Balfour's book must have largely contributed to stereotype this use of the term ; and, from the point of view of philosophical terminology, I cannot regard this as other than a fortunate result. As a standing designation, it is distinctly preferable in point of accuracy to any of the terms which Mr Balfour mentions as currently, but somewhat loosely, in use as synonyms. The absence of God and im- mortality from the Positivist scheme may well seem to the ordinary man to leave no practical difference between that doctrine and the theory of Naturalism. Yet, from a philosophical point of view, the difference is not unimportant. Though, in its denials, Positivism makes common cause with Naturalism, its constructive doctrine is borrowed from Idealism, or, if you like, from Christianity. In the stress which Positivism lays upon man, even to the extent of calling itself the religion of Humanity, Positivism echoes the thought of Pascal, that man the dying reed is greater than the universe by which he dies, that there is no com- mon measure for the immensities of the physical uni- THE USE OF THE TERM " NATURALISM." 297 verse and the spring of love, of thought, of reverence that wells in a human heart. To this Positivism owes its vitality, for the germ of the higher religions is this sense of the truly infinite, the truly adorable, as re- vealed in man alone. " Comtianism," Dr Hutchison Stirling has aptly said, "bears to Hegelianism a re- lation very similar to that of Mahometanism to Chris- tianity" (Schwegler, p. 464). If we generalise the statement, we may, I think, recognise in Positivism an idealism manqutf an idealism with strange defects and inconsistencies but still a doctrine in spirit and intention widely removed from mere Materialism. It is well, therefore, not to ignore this difference, but to continue to use the term in a narrower and specific sense, as applicable to the different sects which appeal to Comte as their founder and claim to represent the Eeligion of Humanity. Naturalism seems also more accurately descriptive than Agnosticism ; for the theory in question is essen- tially a negative dogmatism, whereas Agnosticism, ac- cording to its etymology and according to the intention of the inventor of the term, is meant to convey only an expression of ignorance, a balance of the intellect, a refusal to pronounce upon ultimate problems either in one sense or in another. "A plague o' both your 298 THE USE OF THE TEEM "NATURALISM." houses" is, in effect, the language held by Professor Huxley to the partisans of Idealism and Materialism alike, in his well-known essay " On the Physical Basis of Life," in the essay " On Descartes," and in many other places. The materialistic position that there is nothing in the world hut matter, force, and necessity is as utterly devoid of justification as the most baseless of theological dogmas. The fundamental doctrines of Materialism, like those of Spiritualism and most other "isms," lie outside the limits of philosophical inquiry, and David Hume's great service to humanity is his irrefragable demonstration of what these limits are. (Collected Essays, vol. i. p. 162.) No doubt it is difficult constantly to keep oneself cor- rectly balanced upon the razor-edge of agnostic ortho- doxy. Professor Huxley tells us that, "the further Science advances, the more extensively and consistently will all the phenomena of Nature be represented by materialistic formulae and symbols " ; and though he enters his protest against the error of mistaking the symbols for real entities, he admits, in doing so, that it is a mistake only too easy to fall into. The Agnostic, like David Hume, who is here invoked as patron of the creed, is apt to reserve his denials for " divinity or school metaphysics," while he views with something THE USE OF THE TERM "NATURALISM." 299 like equanimity the materialistic conclusions drawn from the advance of science. He is certain that he knows nothing of spiritual realities or agents; theo- retically, he should be equally certain of his ignorance of reality or agency in the case of natural phenomena. But, as he is constantly occupied with the latter, his hand becomes subdued to what it works in. As man, moreover, is not a creature of pure reason alone, the senses assert their imperious sway over his practical beliefs, and his position becomes indistinguishable from Materialism pure and simple. Still, in spite of the fatal facility with which the one may glide into the other, we have in strictness no more right to identify the two, than a naturalist would have to deny the difference between two species because of the existence of intermediate forms in which they continuously ap- proach one another. Definition in such cases must be by type. The typical Agnostic, like Huxley, is clearly distinguished from the typical Materialist. It would be an unjustifiable and quite unnecessary removal of landmarks, therefore, to use the two terms indiscrimin- ately. No one in these days will allow that he is a Materialist ; but Naturalism supplies exactly the term needed to enable us to surmount this verbal difficulty, while Agnosticism may be conveniently retained to 300 THE USE OF THE TERM "NATURALISM." designate the quasi-sceptical position which it etymo- logically suggests. 1 The only legitimate objection to this use of the term Naturalism is that urged by Professor Wallace. Naturalism, in a certain context, appears as the an- tithesis of Supernaturalism ; and he who attacks Natur- alism may accordingly be supposed to do so in the interest of "miracles" and other "supernatural" adjuncts of theology. Some parts of the discussion in Mr Balfour's concluding chapters certainly seem to favour this view of his argument. But there are others which suggest a larger interpretation, as where he expressly discards what he calls " the common division between ' natural ' and ' supernatural.' " We cannot consent [he proceeds], to see the " preferential working of Divine Power " only in those religious manifesta- tions which refuse to accommodate themselves to our con- ception (whatever that may be) of the strictly " natural " order of the world ; nor can we deny a Divine origin to those aspects of religious development which natural laws seem competent to explain. The familiar distinction, in- deed, between " natural " and " supernatural " coincides neither with that between natural and spiritual, nor with 1 Empiricism may be disregarded in this connection, as a term which is no longer much in popular use. It tends to become restricted to the bloodless controversies of the schools, and even there it suggests, perhaps, a more or less obsolete formulation of the issues. THE USE OF THE TERM "NATURALISM." 301 that between " preferential action " and " non-preferential," nor with that between phenomenal and noumenal. It is perhaps less important than is sometimes supposed." Quite in keeping with this is the fine passage which follows on Inspiration, as " limited to no age, to no country, no people" (pp. 330, 331). But whatever Mr Balfour's personal attitude may be towards the supernatural in the ordinary theological sense of that word (and that is a matter which does not concern us here), it is sufficiently plain that this is not the kernel of the argument. Even when he comes to deal with the central article of the Christian faith, it is not on the extra-naturalness of certain facts that the emphasis is laid, but upon the adapta- tion of the doctrine to the needs of man upon what might be called, therefore, in the highest sense, its "naturalness." The antithesis which runs through the volume, and which must impress itself upon any candid reader, is not that between the natural and a so-called supernatural, but between the natural and the spiritual, between nature, as "revealed to us through perception," and that higher nature in nature which makes us men and gives us an earnest of the Divine. This antithesis also has the sanction of usage on its side. Both in theological and in philosophical 302 THE USE OF THE TERM "NATURALISM." writing, the natural and the spiritual are as currently and intelligibly opposed lo one another as the natural and the supernatural. The moral world of persons is constantly contrasted with the natural world of things. What other interpretation is to be put upon Leibniz's " Kingdom of Nature and Kingdom of Grace," upon Kant's opposition of the Sensible and the In- telligible World ? " Nature," says Jacobi, " conceals God. Man reveals God." "Man Supernatural" is the title chosen by Professor Campbell Eraser for one of his recent Gifford Lectures. " As a merely sentient being man is wholly, or almost wholly, an event in the orderly natural system. In his moral acts man appears to exemplify that final principle on which natural order ultimately depends." "Nature," says Green, concluding his long argument for a spiritual principle, "implies a principle which is non-natural" (Proleg., p. 56). I quote these prominent expressions of widely different thinkers, not because I regard them all as equally sound, or any of them perhaps as beyond criticism, but simply to prove how widely current is the narrower sense of " Nature " which is embodied in Mr Balfour's use of Naturalism. In not one of the passages quoted is there the least sugges- tion of the supernatural in the mechanical and external THE USE OF THE TERM " NATURALISM." 303 sense of popular theology. The contrast is substanti- ally between the material and the ideal, the natural and the spiritual. If we turn to the histories of philosophy and their classifications of philosophical doctrine, we find also that the usage is no innovation. When Schwegler applies the term Naturalism to the doctrine of Democritus, when Ueberweg uses it as an equivalent to Materialism in his account of the French Encyclopaedists, and describes in the same way the transformation which the Hegelian system underwent at the hands of Feuerbach, both apparently appeal to accepted usage. No apology is offered for the intro- duction of the term, nor does the reader feel that any explanation is required of a terminology so appropriate. The conjecture is permissible that Mr Balfour's usage would also have been accepted without cavil but for the sub-title of the volume, which seems to make the whole discussion ancillary to the study of theology. The air of England is charged with ecclesiasticism, and this was sufficient to create an inveterate prejudice in many minds, and to rouse in many more the sus- picion of an arri&re pensfo. For there are many, un- fortunately, who are more jealous of the encroachments of the supernatural than alive to the conservation of the spiritual truths of which it has been the vehicle. NOTE B. THE LEGITIMACY OF THE ARGUMENT FROM CONSEQUENCES. MR BALFOUR'S general mode of procedure has been unsparingly condemned in many quarters, on the ground that his inquiry is avowedly undertaken in the interest of certain beliefs as to the course of the world and man's place in it. The motive of the in- vestigation, it is said, discredits its results in advance. It is not a disinterested quest of truth, but a piece of special pleading in support of beliefs whose truth is assumed without investigation, on the strength of certain supposed "needs" of the individual and the race. But the needs of the race, still more of the individual, have no relevance, when the question is one of the facts of existence. Proud man has long enough indulged himself in this comforting but fatuous course of reasoning, and imposed his own image upon THE ARGUMENT FROM CONSEQUENCES. 305 the world. Man's needs must bend before nature's necessities. It is time for him to accept his true place in the cosmic scheme. If science teaches us our insignificance and evanescence, we have no option but to accept that teaching, however wounding to our pride or lacerating to our emotions it may be. Thus, in familiar accents, with a measure of right on their side, and a still greater measure of plausi- bility, we can hear the devotees of "truth" exclaim. And their indignation is naturally redoubled when Mr Balfour, in the first part of his book, deliberately proceeds to test the doctrines of "Naturalism" by their consequences that is to say, by the consequences, or supposed consequences, to morality and life of their general adoption as a working creed. Here at least, we can hear them say, is a method of polemic, which it might have been supposed was obsolete. Mr Bal- four himself admits that his procedure is not the most logical, but he blandly adds that he has adopted it in order to arrest the attention of "the general reader." Could there be a more unblushing admission or a more demoralising mode of argument ? This line of objection, which rests upon the same notion of truth, has even more show of reason than the first; and it may be freely admitted that the u 306 THE LEGITIMACY OF THE argument in terrorem, from the supposed consequences of a doctrine, is peculiarly liable to abuse, and also that it has frequently been idly invoked in the past. Beliefs which were held to be essential to the religious life or the stability of the social fabric have been abandoned without any signs of injury to either, and doctrines which were declared to strike at the roots of both religion and society have become part of our common teaching; and yet the heavens have not fallen, as it was confidently prophesied they would. Nothing, in short, is more wonderful than the power of adaptation which experience shows man to possess in the matter of belief. Yet while this is both true and reassuring, we must remember that experience only proves its truth within certain limits. Profound as the changes of belief have been in the past, the doctrines that have been from time to time abandoned or embraced must still be pronounced to be concerned with details, as compared with the fundamental issue between Materialism or Naturalism and a spiritual or idealistic view of man's place in the universe. This, it may be fairly argued, is not an issue between different forms of an ethical or social creed, but be- tween belief and no-belief ; inasmuch as the material- istic scheme affords no legitimate basis for ethical AKGUMENT FKOM CONSEQUENCES. 307 endeavour or ethical precept. No human society has ever been based upon the conclusions of materialism, and wherever this negative creed has become widely spread among individuals (in cultivated society under the Eoman empire, for example, or in the same circles in France before the Eevolution) the result has been visible in moral deterioration and social disintegration. The teaching of experience, therefore, does not dis- courage the application of the argument from conse- quences in an ultimate resort, however much it may cast ridicule upon misguided attempts to invoke this ultima ratio for any of the changing forms in which mankind have embodied their spiritual experience. For the ultima ratio of every creed, the ultima ratio of truth itself, is that it works ; and no greater condem- nation can be passed upon a doctrine or system than that, if it were true, human life, as it has been lived by the best of the race, would cease to be reasonable, or rather, would become a phenomenon whose emer- gence it was impossible to explain. This consideration tends also to rob the previous objection of a good deal of its plausibility. " Truth " has become in these days a kind of Juggernaut, whose car is periodically dragged abroad in triumph by its self-immolating worshippers. There is much question- 308 THE ARGUMENT FROM CONSEQUENCES. begging done under cover of devotion to " truth." The ethical life has also its- certainties and its postulates ; and a man is not necessarily evading truth, when he rejects a creed, because it has no place within it for those postulates of the ethical or spiritual life which to him are the most fundamental certainties of all. Nor is he convicted of prejudice, because he avows that the defence of these postulates is the motive of his specu- lative inquiry. Mr Balfour, as has been argued in the preceding essay, may be said to be trying throughout his volume to establish a definition of truth or of Eeason, which shall be at once more comprehensive and more self -consistent than that which limits it to the facts and laws of physical science. But if this is so, then the appeal of the volume is not from truth to authority, or from truth to subjective cravings, but from a partial and fragmentary truth to a fuller truth ; and the argument may fairly claim to be judged on its merits, without any importation of the odium anti- theologicum. PRINTED BT WILLIAM BLACKWOOD AND SONS. BY THE SAME AUTHOR. SCOTTISH PHILOSOPHY. A COMPARISON OP THE SCOTTISH AND GERMAN ANSWERS TO HUME. Balfour Philo- sophical Lectures, University of Edinburgh. First Series. By ANDREW SETH, M.A., LL.D., Professor of Logic and Meta- physics in the University of Edinburgh. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 5s. " We cannot read even a few pages of this book without feeling that Professor Seth is fully competent for the task he has undertaken. The style is lucid, simple, and direct The volume is at once acute and deep, and one which we can cordially commend to all students of philosophy." British Quarterly Review. HEGELIANISM AND PERSONALITY. Balfour Phil- osophical Lectures. Second Series. By the SAME AUTHOR. Crown 8vo, 5s. " They embody an acute and thoughtful criticism of the theory of Hegel and his followers in England and Germany The most rever- ent disciple of Hegel can read the lectures with pleasure and study them with profit." Scotsman. " It is a significant book Nothing more need be said than that it is excellent, and gives a very lucid account of the chief positions in Hegel's doctrine." Oxford Magazine. " The book is really a good one, and ought to be welcome wherever clear exposition and clear criticism are held in estimation." Aberdeen Journal. WILLIAM BLACKWOOD & SONS, EDINBURGH AND LONDON. A STUDY OF ET1ICAL PEINCIPLES. BY JAMES SETH, M.A., Professor of Moral Philosophy in Cornell University, U.S.A. Second Edition, Revised. Post 8vo, 10s. 6d. net. " One of the finest products of scholarship which America has given us for some time He does not write merely to convince us of the truth of his own theory, he gives us an orderly and tolerant account of other theories that have been held and still are held by other men. Thus it at once serves the purpose both of the student and of the gen- eral reader." Expository Times. " This is an excellent book, well written and well reasoned, not over subtle, yet with real philosophical grasp and insight, distinguished by competent knowledge, careful analysis, candid yet discriminative criticism, and a moral purpose and conviction, all too rare in ethical treatises, which makes the reader feel that he has to do with an author to whom the ideal is the real, and the obligatory an imperative that will not be denied." Speaker. " Professor Seth travels over a wide field, and indeed touches upon all the important questions which in recent years have been opened by ethical inquiry Sounder and more enlightening criticism it would be impossible to find. There is no emergence at any point of the slightest degree of partisanship, prejudice, or heat His style is remarkably lucid and agreeable, so that distinct literary flavour accom- panies the severest thinking." Professor MARCUS DODS in the British Weekly. " One of the most important books which have been published in philosophy in recent years Marked not less by keen moral insight than by conspicuous dialectical skill." Standard. WILLIAM BLACKWOOD & SONS, EDINBURGH AND LONDON. Catalogue of Messrs Blackwood & Sons Publications PHILOSOPHICAL CLASSICS FOR ENGLISH READERS, EDITED BY WILLIAM KNIGHT, LL.D., Professor of Moral Philosophy in the University of St Andrews. In crown 8vo Volumes, with Portraits, price 3s. 6d. Contents of the Series. DESCARTES, by Professor Mahaffy, Dub- | by Professor Flint, Edinburgh. HOBBES, 'the Very BACON : Nichol. the same Campbell lin. BUTLER, by Rev. W. Lucas Collins, M.A. BERKELEY, by Professor Campbell Fraser. FICHTE, by Professor Adamson, Glasgow. KANT, by Professor Wallace, Oxford. HAMILTON, by Professor Veitch, Glasgow. HEGEL, by the Master of Balliol. LEIBNIZ, by J. Theodore Merz. Vico by Professor Groom Robertson, by the Editor. SPINOZA, by Rev. Principal Caird, Glasgow. - Part I. The Life, by Professor BACON : Part II. Philosophy, by Author. LOCKE, by Professor Fraser. FOREIGN CLASSICS FOR ENGLISH READERS, EDITED BY MRS OLIPHANT. In crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. Contents of the Series. DANTE, by the Editor. VOLTAIRE, by General Sir E. B. Hamley, K.C.B. PASCAL, by Principal Tulloch. PET- RARCH, by Henry Reeve, C.B. GOETHE, by A. Hayward, Q.C. MOLIERE, by the Editor and F. Tarver, M.A. MONTAIGNE, by Rev. W. L. Collins, M.A. RABELAIS, by Sir Walter Besant. CALDERON, by E. J. Hasell. SAINT SIMON, by Clifton W. Collins, M. A. CERVANTES, by the Editor. CORNEILLE AND RACINE, by Henry M. Trollope. MADAME DE SEVIGNE, by Miss Thackeray. LA FON- TAINE, AND OTHER FRENCH FABULISTS, by Rev. W. Lucas Collins, M.A. SCHIL- LER, by James Sime, M.A., Author of 'Lessing, his Life and Writings.' TASSO, by E. J. Hasell. ROUSSEAU, by Henry Grey Graham. ALFRED DE MUSSET, by C. F. Oliphant. ANCIENT CLASSICS FOR ENGLISH READERS, EDITED BY THE EEV. W. LUCAS COLLINS, M.A. CHEAP RE-ISSUE. In limp cloth, fcap. Svo, price Is. each. Tioo Volumes will be issued Monthly in the following order : HESIOD AND THEOGNIS, J. Davies. \ PLAUTUS AND TERENCE, The Editor. / HOMER : ILIAD, . . The Editor. \ p , HOMER: ODYSSEY, . The Editor, i e HERODOTUS, C^SAR, . . . . G. C. Swayne. Anthony Trollope. VIRGIL, The Editor. ) HORACE, . Sir Theodore Martin, f ^SCHYLUS, . Bishop Copleston. ) , XENOPHON, . . Sir Alex. Grant. j" ** CICERO, The Editor. \ SOPHOCLES,. . . C. W. Collins. / PLINY, . Church and Brodribb. \-n anl , EURIPIDES, . . . W. B. Donne. f Meaa V' Ready. JUVENAL, . . ARISTOPHANES, E. Walford. The Editor. TACITUS, . . . . W. B. Donne. LUCIAN, The Editor. PLATO C. W. Collins. GREEK ANTHOLOGY, Lord Neaves. LIVY, The Editor. ) _ OVID, .... Rev. A. Church. j vec - CATULLUS, TIBULLUS, AND PRO- PERTIUS, .... J. Davies. DEMOSTHENES, . W. J. Brodribb Nov. 1898. Jan. ARISTOTLE, . THUCYDIDES, Sir Alex. Grant. ) . . The Editor. J LUCRETIUS, . . W. H. Mallock. \ ,, -, PINDAR, . . Rev. F. D. Morice. f Marcn - CATALOGUE OF MESSES BLACKWOOD & SONS' P UBLICA TION S. ALISON. History of Europe. By Sir AKCHIBALD ALISON, Bart., D.C.L. 1. From the Commencement of the French Revolution to the Battle of Waterloo. LIBRARY EDITION, 14 vols., with Portraits. Demy 8vo, 10, 10s. ANOTHER EDITION, in 20 vols. crown 8vo, 6. PEOPLE'S EDITION 13 vols. crown 8vo, 2, 11s. 2. Continuation to the Accession of Louis Napoleon. LIBRARY EDITION, 8 vols. 8vo, 6, 7s. 6d. PEOPLE'S EDITION, 8 vols, crown 8vo. 34s. Epitome of Alison's History of Europe. Thirtieth Thou- sand, 7s. 6d. Atlas to Alison's History of Europe. By A. Keith Johnston. LIBRARY EDITION, demy 4to, 3, 3s. PEOPLE'S EDITION, 31s. 6d. Life of John Duke of Marlborough. With some Account of his Contemporaries, and of the War of the Succession. Third Edition. 2 vols. 8vo. Portraits and Maps, 30s. Essays : Historical, Political, and Miscellaneous. 3 vols. demy 8vo, 45s. ACROSS FRANCE IN A CARAVAN : BEING SOME ACCOUNT OF A JOURNEY FROM BORDEAUX TO GENOA IN THE ' ' ESCARGOT," taken in the Winter 1889-90. By the Author of ' A Day of my Life at Eton.' With fifty Illustrations by John Wallace, after Sketches by the Author, and a Map. Cheap Edition, demy 8vo, 7s. 6d. ACTA SANCTORUM HIBERNIJE ; Ex Codice Salmanticensi. Nunc primum integre edita opera CAROLI DE SMEDT et JOSEPHI DE BACKER, e Soc. Jesu, Hagiographorum Bollandianorum ; Auctore et Sumptus Largiente JOANNE PATRICIO MARCHIONE BOTHAE. In One handsome 4to Volume, bound in half roxburghe, 2, 2s. ; in paper cover, 31s. 6d. ADOLPHUS. Some Memories of Paris. By F. ADOLPHUS. Crown 8vo, 6s. AFLALO. A Sketch of the Natural History (Vertebrates) of the British Islands. By F. G. AFLALO, F.R.G.S., F.Z.S., Author of ' A Sketch of the Natural History of Australia,' &c. With numerous Illustrations by Lodge and Bennett. In 1 vol. crown 8vo. [In the press. AIRMAN. Manures and the Principles of Manuring. By C. M. AIKMAN, D.Sc., F.R.S.E., &c., Professor of Chemistry, Glasgow Veterinary College; Examiner in Chemistry, University of Glasgow, &c. Crown 8vo, 6s. 6d. Farmyard Manure : Its Nature, Composition, and Treatment. Crown 8vo, Is. 6d, List of Books Published by AIRD. Poetical Works of Thomas Aird. Fifth Edition, with Memoir of the Author by the Rev. JABDINE WALLACE, and Portrait. Crown 8vo, 7s. fid. ALLARDYCE. The City of Sunshine. By ALEXANDER ALLARDYCE, Author of ' Earlscourt, 1 &c. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. Balmoral : A Romance of the Queen's Country. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. ALMOND. Sermons by a Lay Head-master. By HELY HUTCH- INSON ALMOND, M.A. Oxon., Head-Master of Loretto School. Crown 8vo, 5s. ANCIENT CLASSICS FOR ENGLISH READERS. Edited by Rev. W. LUCAS COLLINS, M.A. Price Is. each. For List of Vols. seep. 2. ANDERSON. Daniel in the Critics' Den. A Reply to Dean Farrar's 'Book of Daniel.' By ROBERT ANDERSON, LL.D., Barrister-at-Law, Assistant Commissioner of Police of the Metropolis ; Author of ' The Coming Prince,' ' Human Destiny,' &c. Post 8vo, 4s. 6d. AYTOUN. Lays of the Scottish Cavaliers, and other Poems. By W. EDMONDSTOUNE AYTOTIN, D.C.L., Professor of Rhetoric and Belles-Lettres in the University of Edinburgh. New Edition. Fcap. 8vo, 3s. 6d. ANOTHER EDITION. Fcap. 8vo, 7s. 6d. CHEAP EDITION. Is. Cloth, Is. 3d. An Illustrated Edition of the Lays of the Scottish Cavaliers. From designs by Sir NOEL PATON. Cheaper Edition. Small 4to, 10s. 6d. Bothwell : a Poem. Third Edition. Fcap., 7s. 6d. Poems and Ballads of Goethe. Translated by Professor AYTOUN and Sir THEODORE MARTIN, K.C.B. Third Edition. Fcap., 6s. The Ballads of Scotland. Edited by Professor AYTOUN. Fourth Edition. 2 vols. fcap. 8vo, 12s. Memoir of William E. Aytoun, D.C.L. By Sir THEODORE MARTIN, K.C.B. With Portrait. Post 8vo, 12s. BEDFORD & COLLINS. Annals of the Free Foresters, from 1856 to the Present Day. By W. K. R. BEDFORD, W. E. W. COLLINS, and other Contributors. With 55 Portraits and 59 other Illustrations. Demy 8vo, 21s. net. BELLAIRS. Gossips with Girls and Maidens, Betrothed and Free. By LADY BELLAIRS. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Cloth, extra gilt edges, 5s. BELLESHEIM. History of the Catholic Church of Scotland. From the Introduction of Christianity to the Present Day. By ALPHONS BEL- LESHEIM, D.D., Canon of Aix-la-Chapelle. Translated, with Notes and Additions, by D. OSWALD HUNTER BLAIR, O.S.B., Monk of Fort Augustus. Cheap Edition. Complete in 4 vols. demy 8vo, with Maps. Price 21s. net. BENTINCK. Racing Life of Lord George Cavendish Bentinck, M.P., and other Reminiscences. By JOHN KENT, Private Trainer to the Good- wood Stable. Edited by the Hon. FRANCIS LAWLEY. With Twenty-three full- page Plates, and Facsimile Letter. Third Edition. Demy 8vo, 25s. BEVERIDGE. Culross and Tulliallan ; or, Perthshire on Forth. Its History and Antiquities. With Elucidations of Scottish Life and Character from the Burgh and Kirk-Session Records of that District. By DAVID BEVERIDGR. 2 vols. 8vo, with Illustrations, 42s. Between the Ochils and the Forth ; or, From Stirling Bridge to Aberdour. Crown 8vo, s. William Blackwood and Sons, BICKERDYKE. A Banished Beauty. By JOHN BICKERDYKE, Author of ' Days in Thule, with Rod, Gun, and Camera, 1 ' The Book of the All- Round Angler, 1 'Curiosities of Ale and Beer,' &c. With Illustrations. Crown 8vo, 6s. BIRCH. Examples of Stables, Hunting-Boxes, Kennels, Racing Estab- lishments, &c. By JOHN BIRCH, Architect, Author of ' Country Architecture, &c. With 30 Plates. Royal 8vo, 7s. Examples of Labourers' Cottages, &c. With Plans for Im- proving the Dwellings of the Poor in Large Towns. With 34 Plates. Royal 8vo, 7s. Picturesque Lodges. A Series of Designs for Gate Lodges, Park Entrances, Keepers', Gardeners', Bailiffs', Grooms', Upper and Under Ser- vants' Lodges, and other Rural Residences. With 16 Plates. 4to, 12s. 6d. BLACK. Heligoland and the Islands of the North Sea. By WILLIAM GEORGE BLACK. Crown 8vo, 4s. BLACKIE. Lays and Legends of Ancient Greece. By JOHN STUART BLACKIE, Emeritus Professor of Greek in the University of Edinburgh. Second Edition. Fcap. 8vo, 5s. The Wisdom of Goethe. Fcap. 8vo. Cloth, extra gilt, 6s. Scottish Song : Its Wealth, Wisdom, and Social Significance. Crown 8vo. With Music. 7s. 6d. A Song of Heroes. Crown 8vo, 6s. John Stuart Blackie : A Biography. By ANNA M. STODDART. With 3 Plates. Third Edition. 2 vols. demy 8vo, 21s. POPULAR EDITION. With Portrait. Crown 8vo, 6s. BLACKMORE. The Maid of Sker. By R. D. BLACKMORE, Author of ' Lorna Doone, 1 &c. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. Cheaper Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Dariel : A Romance of Surrey. With 14 Illustrations by Chris. Hammond. Crown 8vo. 6s. BLACKWOOD. Annals of a Publishing House. William Blackwood and his Sons ; Their Magazine and Friends. By Mrs OLIPHANT. With Four Portraits, demy 8vo. Vols. I. and II. 2, 2s. Blackwood's Magazine, from Commencement in 1817 to May 1897. Nos. 1 to 979, forming 160 Volumes. Index to Blackwood's Magazine. Vols. 1 to 50. 8vo, 15s. Tales from Blackwood. First Series. Price One Shilling each, in Paper Cover. Sold separately at all Railway Bookstalls. They may also be had bound in 12 vols., cloth, 18s. Half calf, richly gilt, 30s. Or the 12 vols. in 6, roxburghe, 21s. Half red morocco, 28s. Tales from Blackwood. Second Series. Complete in Twenty- four Shilling Parts. Handsomely bound in 12 vols., cloth, 30s. In leather back, roxburghe style, 37s. 6d. Half calf, gilt, 52s. 6d. Half morocco, 55s. Tales from Blackwood. Third Series. Complete in Twelve Shilling Parts. Handsomely bound in 6 vols., cloth, 15s.; and in 12 vols., cloth, 18s. The 6 vols. in roxburghe, 21s. Half calf, 25s. Half morocco, 28s. Travel, Adventure, and Sport. From ' Blackwood's Magazine. Uniform with 'Tales from Blackwood.' In Twelve Parts, each price Is. Hand- somely bound in 6 vols., cloth, 15s. And in half calf, 25s. List of Books Published by BLACKWOOD. New Educational Series. See separate Catalogue. New Uniform Series of Novels (Copyright). Crown 8vo, cloth. Price 3s. 6d. each. Now ready : THE MAID OF SKER. By R. D. Blackmore. WENDERHOLME. By P. G. Hamerton. THE STORY OF MARGREDEL. By D. Storrar Meldrum. Miss MARJORIBANKS. By Mrs Oliphant. THE PERPETUAL CURATE, and THE RECTOR. By the Same. SALEM CHAPEL, and THE DOCTOR'S FAMILY. By the Same. A SENSITIVE PLANT. By E. D. Gerard. LADY LEE'S WIDOWHOOD. By General Sir E. B. Hamley. KATIE STEWART, and other Stories. By Mrs Oliphant. VALENTINE AND HIS BROTHER. By the Same. SONS AND DAUGHTERS. By the Same. MARMORNE. By P. G. Hamerton. REATA. By E. D. Gerard. BEGGAR MY NEIGHBOUR. By the Same. THE WATERS OF HERCULES. By the Same. FAIR TO SEE. By L. W. M. Lockhart. MINE is THINE. By the Same. DOUBLES AND QUITS. By the Same. ALTIORA PETO. By Laurence Oliphant. PICCADILLY. By the Same. With Illustra- tions. LADY BABY. By D. Gerard. THE BLACKSMITH OF VOE. By Paul Gushing. THE DILEMMA. By the Author of ' The Battle of Dorking.' MY TRIVIAL LIFE AND MISFORTUNE. By A Plain Woman. POOR NELLIE. By the Same. Standard Novels. Uniform in size and binding. Each complete in one Volume. FLORIN SERIES, Illustrated Boards,. Bound in Cloth, 2s. 6d. TOM CRINGLE'S LOG. By Michael Scott. THE CRUISE OF THE MIDGE. By the Same. CYRIL THORNTON. By Captain Hamilton. ANNALS OF THE PARISH. By John Gait. THE PROVOST, &c. By the Same. SIR ANDREW WYLIE. By the Same. THE ENTAIL. By the Same. Miss MOLLY. By Beatrice May Butt. REGINALD DALTON. By J. G. Lockhart. SHILLING SERIES, Illustrated Cover. Bound in Cloth, Is. 6d. THE RECTOR, and THE DOCTOR'S FAMILY. SIR FRIZZLE PUMPKIN, NIGHTS AT MESS &c. By D. M. THE SUBALTERN. LIFE IN THE FAR WEST. By VALERIUS : A Lockhart. By Mrs Oliphant. THE LIFE OF MANSIE WAUCH. Moir. PENINSULAR SCENES AND SKETCHES. F. Hardman. PEN OWEN. By Dean Hook. ADAM BLAIR. By J. G. Lockhart. LADY LEE'S WIDOWHOOD. By General Sir E. B. Hamley. SALEM CHAPEL. By Mrs Oliphant. THE PERPETUAL CURATE. By the Same. Miss MARJORIBANKS. By the Same. JOHN : A Love Story. By the Same. By G. F. Ruxton. Roman Story. By J. G. BON GAULTIER'S BOOK OF BALLADS. Fifteenth Edi- tion. With Illustrations by Doyle, Leech, and Crowquill. Fcap. 8vo, 5s. BOWHILL. Questions and Answers in the Theory and Practice of Military Topography. By Major J. H. BOWHILL. In 1 vol. crown 8vo. With Atlas containing 34 working plans and diagrams. [In the press. BRADDON. Thirty Years of Shikar. By Sir EDWARD BRADDON, K.C.M.G. With Illustrations by G. D. Giles, and Map of Oudh Forest Tracts and Nepal Terai. Demy 8vo, 18s. BROUGHAM. Memoirs of the Life and Times of Henry Lord Brougham. Written by HIMSELF. 3 vols. 8vo, 2, 8s. The Volumes are sold separately, price 16s. each. BROWN. The Forester : A Practical Treatise on the Planting and Tending of Forest-trees and the General Management of Woodlands. By JAMES BROWN, LL.D. Sixth Edition, Enlarged. Edited by JOHN NISBET, D.O3c., Author of ' British Forest Trees,' &c. In 2 vols. royal 8vo, with 350 Illustra- tions, 42s. net. Also being issued in 15 Monthly parts, price 2s. 6d. net each. [Parts 1 to S ready. BROWN. A Manual of Botany, Anatomical and Physiological. For the Use of Students. By ROBERT BROWN, M.A., Ph.D. Crown 8vo, with numerous Illustrations, 12s. 6d. William Blackwood and Sons. BKUCE. In Clover and Heather. Poems by WALLACE BRTJCE. New and Enlarged Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. A limited number of Copies of the First Edition, on large hand-made paper, 12s. 6d. Here's a Hand. Addresses and Poems. Crown 8vo, 5s. Large Paper Edition, limited to 100 copies, price 21s. BUCHAN. Introductory Text-Book of Meteorology. By ALEX- ANDER BUCHAN, LL.D., F.B.S.E., Secretary of the Scottish Meteorological Society, &c. New Edition. Crown 8vo, with Coloured Charts and Engravings. [In preparation. BURBIDGE. Domestic Floriculture, Window Gardening, and Floral Decora- tions. Being Practical Directions for the Propagation, Culture, and Arrangement of Plants and Flowers as Domestic Ornaments. By F. W. BURBIDGE. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, with numerous Illustrations, 7s. 6d. Cultivated Plants : Their Propagation and Improvement. Including Natural and Artificial Hybridisation, Raising from Seed, Cuttings and Layers, Grafting and Budding, as applied to the Families and Genera in Cultivation. Crown 8vo, with numerous Illustrations, 12s. 6d. BURGESS. The Viking Path : A Tale of the White Christ. By J. J. HALDANE BURGESS, Author of ' Rasmie's Buddie,' 'Shetland Sketches,' &c. Crown 8vo, 6s. BURKE. The Flowering of the Almond Tree, and other Poems. By CHRISTIAN BURKE. Pott 4to, 5s. BURROWS. Commentaries on the History of England, from the Earliest Times to 1865. By MONTAGU BURROWS, Chichele Professor of Modern History in the University of Oxford; Captain R.N. ; F.S.A., &c. ; "Officier de 1'In- struction Publique," France. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. The History of the Foreign Policy of Great Britain. Demy 8vo, 12s. BURTON. The History of Scotland : From Agricola's Invasion to the Extinction of the last Jacobite Insurrection. By JOHN HILL BURTON, D.C.L., Historiographer - Royal for Scotland. Cheaper Edition. In 8 monthly vols. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. each. History of the British Empire during the Reign of Queen Anne. In 3 vols. 8vo. 36s. . The Scot Abroad. Third Edition. Crown 8vo, 10s. 6d. The Book-Hunter. New Edition. With Portrait. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. BUTCHER. Armenosa of Egypt. A Romance of the Arab Conquest. By the Very Rev. Dean BUTCHER, D.D., F.S.A., Chaplain at Cairo. Crown 8vo, 6s. BUTE. The Altus of St Columba. With a Prose Paraphrase and Notes. In paper cover, 2s. 6d. BUTE, MACPHAIL, AND LONSDALE. The Arms of the Royal and Parliamentary Burghs of Scotland. By JOHN, MARQUESS OP BUTE, K.T., J. R. N. MACPHAIL, and H. W. LONSDALE. With 140 Woodcuts. In 1 vol. crown 4to. [In the press. BUTLER. The Ancient Church and Parish of Abernethy, Perthshire. A Historical Study. By Rev. D. BUTLER, M.A., Minister of the Parish. With Collotype Illustrations. In 1 vol. crown 4to. [In the press. BUTT. Theatricals : An Interlude. By BEATRICE MAY BUTT. Crown ^Svo, 6s. Miss Molly. Cheap Edition, 2s. Eugenie. Crown 8vo, 6s. 6d. List of Books Published by BUTT. .^Elizabeth, and other Sketches. Crown 8vo, 6s. Delicia. New Edition. Cipwn 8vo, 2s. 6d. CAIRD. Sermons. By JOHN CAIRD, D.D., Principal of the University of Glasgow. Seventeenth Thousand. Fcap. 8vo, 5s. CALDWELL. Schopenhauer's System in its Philosophical Sig- nificance (the Shaw Fellowship Lectures, 1893). By WILLIAM CALDWELL, M.A., D.Sc., Professor of Moral and Social Philosophy, Northwestern University, U.S.A. ; formerly Assistant to the Professor of Logic and Metaphysics, Edin., and Examiner in Philosophy in the University of St Andrews. Demy 8vo, 10s. 6d. net. CALLWELL. The Effect of Maritime Command on Land Campaigns since Waterloo. By Major C. E. CALLWELL, R.A. With Plans. Post 8vo, 6s. net. CAMPBELL. Records of Argyll. Legends, Traditions, and Re- collections of Argyllshire Highlanders, collected chiefly from the Gaelic. With Notes on the Antiquity of the Dress, Clan Colours, or Tartans of the Highlanders. By Lord ARCHIBALD CAMPBELL. Illustrated with Nineteen full-page Etchings. 4to, printed on hand-made paper, 3, 3s. CANTON. A Lost Epic, and other Poems. By WILLIAM CANTON. Crown 8vo, 5s. CARSTAIRS. Human Nature in Rural India. By R. CARSTAIRS. Crown 8vo, 6s. British Work in India. Crown 8vo, 6s. CAUVIN. A Treasury of the English and German Languages. Compiled from the best Authors and Lexicographers in both Languages. By JOSEPH CAUVIN, LL.D. and Ph.D., of the University of Gottingen, &c. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. CHARTERIS. Canonicity ; or, Early Testimonies to the Exist- ence and Use of the Books of the New Testament. Based on Kirchhoffer'B 'Quellensammlung.' Edited by A. H. CHARTERIS, D.D., Professor of Biblical Criticism in the University of Edinburgh. 8vo, 18s. CHENNELLS. Recollections of an Egyptian Princess. By her English Governess (Miss E. CHENNELLS). Being a Record of Five Years' Residence at the Court of Ismael Pasha Khedive. Second Edition. With Three Portraits. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. CHESNEY. The Dilemma. By General Sir GEORGE CHESNEY, K.C.B., M.P., Author of 'The Battle of Dorking,' &c. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. CHRISTISON. Early Fortifications in Scotland : Motes, Camps, and Forts. Being the Rhind Lectures in Archaeology for 1893. By DAVID CHRISTISON, M.D. With numerous Illustrations and Maps. In 1 vol. pott 4to. [In the press. CHRISTISON. Life of Sir Robert Christison, Bart., M.D., D.C.L. Oxon., Professor of Medical Jurisprudence in the University of Edin- burgh. Edited by his SONS. In 2 vols. 8vo. Vol. I. Autobiography. 16s. Vol. II. Memoirs. 16s. CHURCH. Chapters in an Adventurous Life. Sir Richard Church in Italy and Greece. By E. M. CHURCH. With Photogravure Portrait. Demy 8vo, 10s. 6d. CHURCH SERVICE SOCIETY. A Book of Common Order : being Forms of Worship issued by the Church Service Society. Seventh Edition, carefully revised. In 1 vol. crown 8vo, cloth, 3s. 6d. ; French morocco, 5s. Also in 2 vols. crown 8vo cloth, 4s. ; French morocco, 6s. 6d. William Blackwood and Sons. CHURCH SERVICE SOCIETY. Daily Offices for Morning and Evening Prayer throughout the Week. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Order of Divine Service for Children. Issued by the Church Service Society. With Scottish Hymnal. Cloth, 3d. CLOUSTON. Popular Tales and Fictions: their Migrations and Transformations. By W. A. CLOUSTON, Editor of ' Arabian Poetry for Eng- lish Eeaders,' &c. 2 vols. post 8vo, roxburghe binding, 25s. COCHRAN. A Handy Text-Book of Military Law. Compiled chiefly to assist Officers preparing for Examination ; also for all Officers of the Regular and Auxiliary Forces. Comprising also a Synopsis of part of the Army Act. By Major F. COCHRAN, Hampshire Regiment Garrison Instructor, North British District. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. COLQUHOUN. The Moor and the Loch. Containing Minute Instructions in all Highland Sports, with Wanderings over Crag and Corrie, Flood and Fell. By JOHN COLQUHOUN. Cheap Edition. With Illustrations. Demy 8vo, 10s. 6d. COLVILE. Round the Black Man's Garden. By Lady Z. COL- VILE, F.R.G.S. With 2 Maps and 50 Illustrations from Drawings by the Author and from Photographs. Demy 8vo, 16s. CONDER. The Bible and the East. By Lieut. -Col. C. R. CONDER, R.E., LL.D., D.C.L., M.R.A.S., Author of ' Tent Work in Palestine, <fcc. With Illustrations and a Map. Crown 8vo, 5s. CONSTITUTION AND LAW OF THE CHURCH OF SCOTLAND. With an Introductory Note by the late Principal Tulloch. New Edition, Revised and Enlarged. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. COTTERILL. Suggested Reforms in Public Schools. By C. C. COTTERILL, M.A. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. COUNTY HISTORIES OF SCOTLAND. In demy 8vo vol- umes of about 350 pp. each. With Maps. Price 7s. 6d. net. Fife and Kinross. By ^ENEAS J. G. MACKAY, LL.D., Sheriff of these Counties. Dumfries and Galloway. By Sir HERBERT MAXWELL, Bart., M.P. Moray and Nairn. By CHARLES RAMPINI, LL.D., Sheriff- Substitute of these Counties. Inverness. By J. CAMERON LEES, D.D. [Others in preparation. CRAWFORD. Saracinesca. By F. MARION CRAWFORD, Author of ' Mr Isaacs,' &c., &c. Cheap, Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. CRAWFORD. The Doctrine of Holy Scripture respecting the Atonement. By the late THOMAS J. CRAWFORD, D.D., Professor of Divinity in the University of Edinburgh. Fifth Edition. 8vo, 12s. The Fatherhood of God, Considered in its General and Special Aspects. Third Edition, Revised and Enlarged. 8vo, 9s. The Preaching of the Cross, and other Sermons. 8vo, 7s. 6d. The Mysteries of Christianity. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. CROSS. Impressions of Dante, and of the New World ; with a Few Words on Bimetallism. By J. W. CKOSS, Editor of ' George Eliot's Life, as related in her Letters and Journals." Post 8vo, 6s. CUMBERLAND. Sport on the Pamirs and Turkistan Steppes. By Major C. S. CUMBERLAND. With Map and Frontispiece. Demy 8vo, 10s. 6d. CURSE OF INTELLECT. Third Edition. Fcap. 8vo, 2s. 6d. net. CUSHING. The Blacksmith of Voe. By PAUL CUSHING, Author of ' The Bull i' th' Thorn, ' ' Cut with his own Diamond. 1 Cheap Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. 10 Lttt of Books Published by N>riolk_ Brcics ^d Rivers : DABBISHIRE. Physical Maps for the use of History M, M.A, Trinity CoDtge, OxfonL Two Series: I ten EL: 7 li -_i_: -I 'JnAepnu. or, The Waterways, . : - : --..-;-.,: I. - I -_. LA WARR. An Eastern Cnrise in the 'Edeline,' By the GOGXCHB DK LA YAZJL I Chntrslcd Cover. t*. DESCARTES. The Method, Meditations, and Principles of Phflo- f.; r 7. -:---- -J :-- -- - ': - --- - - ---- :-'-. - - :--_ : "- - ^ . \ " _ L. : ." -" " ~M. "-\ '. : ' ". ";-. i ". - ~ - ". - J. '-';' DOGS, OUR^DQMESTIC ATED : Their Treatment in reference DOUGLAa The Ethics of John Stuart Mill. By CHARLES DOUGLAS, ;->.^ -: i-J " Crown 8vo, DOUGLAS. C*dnese Stories. By ROBEET K. DOUGLAS. With DOUGLAS. Iras : A Mystery. By THEO. DOUGLAS, Authorof DU CAXtTleOdys^y of Homer, Books L-XIL Translated DUDGEOIT. CBAKLO DC CASK, K.CJLG. fero, 10*. 6d. DUXSMORE. Mannal of the LAW of Scotland as to the Rela- DZLEWICKL v*t-a~A in flesh, By M. H. DZEEWICKL In 1 " V- v"i -;. '.".-. ;:.. ELIOT. George Eliofs life, Belated in Her Letters and Journals. j^ii *>*%> I li l.i.W.Cmam. Wij- Qe^T^^s 1 ^!^ "'l^Rirta^a^i other Wrli^of "G*crarV zHot StoSJd EditionX 21 volmnes, ciMm fMt iBMidknBdoa, gOtteK ^L Cd. per Mi.; or te i ' Life and Works of George Eliot (Cabinet Edition). 24 r _ . ..''. j. - - - .,.-*-.-<. S<ms. n ELIOTL Crown Svo, 7s. 6<L Daniel Deronda. Crown 8ro, 7a. 6d. w Edi:i?n. O: -^ 5v.^ 5.5. <* Tbeophrastus Suck New Edition. Orowm Crown 8vov5& other Poems, Old and New. Royal 8ro in FEXXELL AXB OX2ALLAGHAX. A Prince of Tyrone. By *UW PtaBCTULMMJ J. g. OT?4H Mi>m. CW( $TO fek FERGUSON. Sir Samuel Ferguson in the Ireland of hk Day. _ ^^olrortwite. i vob. poet Svo^ U&. FERRIER Worka of the > to Jmea Ferrjer, RA. Lectures on AeEarh-Gwek Philosophy. *th Edition. 10s.6d. Phiksonhkal Remains, including the Lectures on Early MhSMMiai; Si Ata i %to Third Edition, 10s. 6d. ares on the Eariy Oreo so^hi.*: Raawia* i lit TMfcMi^i Wi Wfrhi FLINT, taM4Mi^^__ . - ::-: tike Groan Lecture for 1887-38. Bemg tlie Baird Lecture for 187& Ninth Edition, ^TlSoH^ Being the Band Lecture for 1ST?. IQRK^f^SD^roS^^^KNGgJSH READERa Edited FOSrS^Th^^^%d^ GravmtTO.ta. 12 List of Books Published by FRANCILLON. Gods and Heroes ; or, The Kingdom of Jupiter. By R. B. FRANCILLON. With 8 Illustrations. Crown 8vo, 5s. FRANCIS. Among the Untrodden Ways. By M. E. FRANCIS (Mrs Francis Blundell), Author of tin a North Country Village,' 'A Daughter of the Soil,' ' Frieze and Fustian,' &c. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. FRASER. Philosophy of Theism. Being the Gifford Lectures delivered before the University of Edinburgh in 1894-95. First Series. By ALEXANDER CAMPBELL FRASER, D.C.L. Oxford; Emeritus Professor of Logic and Meta- physics in the University of Edinburgh. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. net. Philosophy of Theism. Being the Gifford Lectures delivered before the University of Edinburgh in 1895-96. Second Series. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. net. FRASER. St Mary's of Old Montrose : A History of the Parish of Maryton. By the Rev. WILLIAM RUXTON FRASER, M.A., F.S.A. Scot., Emeritus Minister of Maryton ; Author of ' History of the Parish and Burgh of Laurencekirk.' Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. FULLARTON. Merlin : A Dramatic Poem. By RALPH MACLEOD FULLAR- TON. Crown 8vo, 5s. Tanhauser. Crown 8vo, 6s. Lallan Sangs and German Lyrics. Crown 8vo, 5s. GALT. Novels by JOHN GALT. With General Introduction and Prefatory Notes by S. R. CROCKETT. The Text Revised and Edited by D. STORRAR MELD RUM, Author of ' The Story of Margredel. ' With Photogravure Illustrations from Drawings by John Wallace. Fcap. 8vo, 3s. net each vol. ANNALS OF THE PARISH, and THE AYRSHIRE LEGATEES. 2 vols. SIR ANDREW WYLIE. 2 vols. THE ENTAIL ; or, The Lairds of Grippy. 2 vols. THE PRO- VOST, and THE LAST OF THE LAIRDS. 2 vols. See also STANDARD NOVELS, p. 6. GENERAL ASSEMBLY OF THE CHURCH OF SCOTLAND. Scottish Hymnal, With Appendix Incorporated. Published for use in Churches by Authority of the General Assembly. 1. Large type, cloth, red edges, 2s. 6d.; French morocco, 4s. 2. Bourgeois type, limp cloth, Is.; French morocco, 2s. 3. Nonpareil type, cloth, red edges, 6d.; French morocco, Is. 4d. 4. Paper covers, 3d. 5. Sunday-School Edition, paper covers, Id., cloth, 2d. No. 1, bound with the Psalms and Paraphrases, French morocco, 8s. No. 2, bound with the Psalms and Paraphrases, cloth, 2s. ; French morocco, 3s. Prayers for Social and Family Worship. Prepared by a Special Committee of the General Assembly of the Church of Scotland. Entirely New Edition, Revised and Enlarged. Fcap. 8vo, red edges, 2s. Prayers for Family Worship. A Selection of Four Weeks' Prayers. New Edition. Authorised by the General Assembly of the Church of Scotland. Fcap. 8vo, red edges, Is. 6d. One Hundred Prayers. Prepared by the Committee on Aids to Devotion. 16mo, cloth limp, 6d. Morning and Evening Prayers for Affixing to Bibles. Prepared by the Committee on Aids to Devotion. Id. for 6, or Is. per 100. GERARD. Reata: What's in a Name. By E. D. GERARD. Cheap Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Beggar my Neighbour. Cheap Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. The Waters of Hercules. Cheap Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. A Sensitive Plant. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. William Blackvuood and Sons. 13 GERARD. A Foreigner. An Anglo -German Study. By E. GERARD. Crown 8vo, 6s. The Land beyond the Forest. Facts, Figures, and Fancies from Transylvania. With Maps and Illustrations. 2 vols. post 8vo, 25s. Bis : Some Tales Retold. Crown 8vo, 6s. A Secret Mission. 2 vols. crown 8vo, 17s. An Electric Shock, and other Stories. Crown 8vo, 6s. GERARD. A Spotless Reputation. By DOROTHEA GERARD. Third Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. The Wrong Man. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. Lady Baby. Cheap Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Recha. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. The Rich Miss Riddell. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. GERARD. Stonyhurst Latin Grammar. By Rev. JOHN GERARD. Second Edition. Pcap. 8vo, 3s. GORDON CUMMING. At Home in Fiji. By C. F. GORDON GUMMING. Fourth Edition, post 8vo. ^ With Illustrations and Map. 7s. 6d. A Lady's Cruise in a French Man-of-War. New and Cheaper Edition. 8vo. With Illustrations and Map. 12s. 6d. Fire-Fountains. The Kingdom of Hawaii: Its Volcanoes, and the History of its Missions. With Map and Illustrations. 2 vols. 8vo, 25s. Wanderings in China. New and Cheaper Edition. 8vo, with Illustrations, 10s. Granite Crags : The Yo-semitd Region of California. Illus- trated with 8 Engravings. New and Cheaper Edition. 8vo, 8s. 6d. GRAHAM. Manual of the Elections (Scot.) (Corrupt and Illegal Practices) Act, 1890. With Analysis, Relative Act of Sederunt, Appendix con- taining the Corrupt Practices Acts of 1883 and 1885, and Copious Index. By J. EDWARD GRAHAM, Advocate. 8vo, 4s. 6d. GRAND. A Domestic Experiment. By SARAH GRAND, Author of ' The Heavenly Twins,' ' Ideala : A Study from Life.' Crown 8vo, 6s. Singularly Deluded. Crown 8vo, 6s. GRANT. Bush-Life in Queensland. By A. C. GRANT. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. GRIER. In Furthest Ind. The Narrative of Mr EDWARD CARLYON of Ellswether, in the County of Northampton, and late of the Honourable East India Company's Service, Gentleman. Wrote by his own hand in the year of grace 1697. Edited, with a few Explanatory Notes, by SYDNEY C. GRIER. Post 8vo, 6s. His Excellency's English Governess. Crown 8vo, 6s. An Uncrowned King : A Romance of High Politics. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. Peace with Honour. Crown 8vo, 6s. GUTHRIE - SMITH. Crispus : A Drama. By H. GTTTHRIE- SMITH. Fcap. 4to, 5s. HAGGARD. Under Crescent and Star. By Lieut.-Col. ANDREW HAGGARD, D.S.O., Author of 'Dodo and I,' 'Tempest Torn,' &c. With a Portrait. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. HALDANE. Subtropical Cultivations and Climates. A Handy Book for Planters, Colonists, and Settlers. By R. C. HALDANE. Post 8vo, 9s. 14 List of Books Published by HAMERTON. Wenderholme : A Story of Lancashire and Yorkshire Life. By P. G. HAMERTON, Author of 'A Painter's Camp.' New Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Marmorne. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. HAMILTON. Lectures on Metaphysics. By Sir WILLIAM HAMILTON, Bart., Professor of Logic and Metaphysics in the University of Edinburgh. Edited by the Rev. H. L. MANSEL, B.C., LL.D., Dean of St Paul's; and JOHN VEITCH, M.A., LL.D., Professor of Logic and Rhetoric, Glasgow. Seventh Edition. 2 vols. 8vo, 24s. Lectures on Logic. Edited by the SAME. Third Edition Revised. 2 vols., 24s. Discussions on Philosophy and Literature, Education and University Reform. Third Edition. 8vo, 21s. Memoir of Sir William Hamilton, Bart., Professor of Logic and Metaphysics in the University of Edinburgh. By Professor VEITCH, of the University of Glasgow. 8vo, with Portrait, 18s. Sir William Hamilton : The Man and his Philosophy. Two Lectures delivered before the Edinburgh Philosophical Institution, January and February 1883. By Professor VEITCH. Crown 8vo, 2s. HAMLEY. The Operations of War Explained and Illustrated. By General Sir EDWARD BRUCE HAMLEY, K.C.B., K.C.M.G. FifCh Edition, Revised throughout. 4to, with numerous Illustrations, 30s. National Defence ; Articles and Speeches. Post 8vo, 6s. Shakespeare's Funeral, and other Papers. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. Thomas Carlyle : An Essay. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. On Outposts. Second Edition. 8vo, 2s. Wellington's Career ; A Military and Political Summary. Crown 8vo, 2s. Lady Lee's Widowhood. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Cheaper Edition, 2s. 6d. Our Poor Relations. A Philozoic Essay. With Illustrations, chiefly by Ernest Griset. Crown 8vo, cloth gilt, 3s. 6d. The Life of General Sir Edward Bruce Hamley, K.C.B., K.C.M.G. By ALEXANDER INNES SHAND. With two Photogravure Portraits and other Illustrations. Cheaper Edition. With a Statement by Mr EDWARD HAMLEY. 2 vols. demy 8vo, 10s. 6d. HANNAY. The Later Renaissance. By.DAviD HANNAY. Being the second volume of 'Periods of European Literature.' Edited by Professor Saintsbury. In 1 vol. crown 8vo. [in the press. HARE. Down the Village Street : Scenes in a West Country Hamlet. By CHRISTOPHER HARE. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. HARRADEN. In Varying Moods : Short Stories. By BEATRICE HARRADEN, Author of ' Ships that Pass in the Night.' Twelfth Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d Hilda Strafford, and The Remittance Man. Two Californian Stories. Tenth Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. fid. Echoes of Olden Days. With 40 Illustrations by H. R. Millar. In 1 vol. square crown 8vo. [I n the press. HARRIS. From Batum to Baghdad, vid Tiflis, Tabriz, and Persian Kurdistan. By WALTER B. HARRIS, F.R.G.S., Author of 'The Land of an African Sultan ; Travels in Morocco, 1 &c. With numerous Illustrations and 2 Maps. Demy 8vo, 12s. William Blackwood and Sons. 15 HARRIS. Tafilet. The Narrative of a Journey of Exploration to the Atlas Mountains and the Oases of the North-West Sahara. With Illustrations by Maurice Romberg from Sketches and Photographs by the Author, and Two Maps. Demy 8vo, 12s. A Journey through the Yemen, and some General Remarks upon that Country. With 3 Maps and numerous Illustrations by Forestier and Wallace from Sketches and Photographs taken by the Author. Demy 8vo, 16s. Danovitch, and other Stories. Crown 8vo, 6s. HAWKER. The Prose Works of Rev. R. S. HAWKER, Vicar of Morwenstow. Including 'Footprints of Former Men in Far Corn wall.' Re-edited, with Sketches never before published. With a Frontispiece. Crown 8vo 3s 6d HAY. The Works of the Right Rev. Dr George Hay, Bishop of Edinburgh. Edited under the Supervision of the Right Rev. Bishop STRAIN. With Memoir and Portrait of the Author. 5 vols. crown 8vo, bound in extra cloth, 1, Is. The following Volumes may be had separately viz. : The Devout Christian Instructed in the Law of Christ from the Written Word. 2 vols., 8s. The Pious Christian Instructed in the Nature and Practice of the Principal Exercises of Piety. 1 vol., 3s. HEATLEY. The Horse- Owner's Safeguard. A Handy Medical Guide for every Man who owns a Horse. By G. S. HEATLEY, M.R.C.V.S. Crown 8vo, 5s. The Stock-Owner's Guide. A Handy Medical Treatise for every Man who owns an Ox or a Cow. Crown 8vo, 4s. 6d. HEDDERWICK. Lays of Middle Age ; and other Poems. By JAMES HEDDERWICK, LL.D., Author of 'Backward Glances.' Price 3s. 6d. HEMANS. The Poetical Works of Mrs Hemans. Copyright Editions. Royal 8vo, 5s. The Same with Engravings, cloth, gilt edges, 7s. 6d. Select Poems of Mrs Hemans. Fcap., cloth, gilt edges, 3s. HERKLESS. Cardinal Beaton: Priest and Politician. By JOHN HERKLESS, Professor of Church History, St Andrews. With a Portrait. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. HEWISON. The Isle of Bute in the Olden Time. With Illus- trations, Maps, and Plans. By JAMES KING HEWISON, M.A., F.S.A. (Scot.), Minister of Rothesay. Vol. I., Celtic Saints and Heroes. Crown 4to, 15s. net. Vol. II. , The Royal Stewards and the Brandanes. Crown 4to, 15s. net. HIBBEN. Inductive Logic. By JOHN GRIER HIBBEN, Ph.D., Assistant Professor of Logic in Princeton University, U.S.A. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. net. HILDE BRAND. The Early Relations between Britain and Scandinavia. Being the Rhind Lectures in Archaeology for 1896. By Dr HANS HILDEBRAND, Royal Antiquary of Sweden. With Illustrations. In 1 vol. post 8vo. [In the press. HOME PRAYERS. By Ministers of the Church of Scotland and Members of the Church Service Society. Second Edition. Fcap. 8vo, 3s. HORNBY. Admiral of the Fleet Sir Geoffrey Phipps Hornby, G.C.B. A Biography. By Mrs FRED. EGERTON. With Three Portraits. Demy HUTCHINSON. Hints on the Game of Golf. By HORACE G. HUTCHINSON. Ninth Edition, Enlarged. Fcap. 8vo, cloth, Is. HYSLOP. The Elements of Ethics. By JAMES H. HYSLOP, Ph.D., Instructor in Ethics, Columbia College, New York, Author of 'The Elements of Logic.' Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. net. IDDESLEIGH. Life, Letters, and Diaries of Sir Stafford North- cote, First Earl of Iddesleigh. By ANDREW LANG. With Three Portraits and a View of Pynes. Third Edition. 2 vols. post 8vo, 31s. 6d. POPULAR EDITION. With Portrait and View of Pynes. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d 1 6 List of Books Published by INDEX GEOGRAPHICUS : Being a List, alphabetically ar- ranged, of the Principal Places on the Globe, with the Countries and Subdivisions of the Countries in which they are situated, and their Latitudes and Longitudes. Imperial 8vo, pp. 676, 21s. JEAN JAMBON. Our Trip to Blunder-land ; or, Grand Ex- cursion to Blundertown and Back. By JEAN JAMBON. With Sixty Illustrations designed by CHARLES DOYLE, engraved by DALZIEL. Fourth Thousand. Cloth, gilt edges, 6s. 6d. Cheap Edition, cloth, 3s. 6d. Boards, 2s. 6d. JEBB. A Strange Career. The Life and Adventures of JOHN GLADWYN JEBB. By his Widow. With an Introduction by H. RIDER HAGGARD, and an Electrogravure Portrait of Mr Jebb. Third Edition. Demy 8vo, 10s. 6d. CHEAP EDITION. With Illustrations by John Wallace. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Some Unconventional People. By Mrs GLADWYN JEBB, Author of ' Life and Adventures of J. G. Jebb.' With Illustrations. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. JERNINGHAM. Reminiscences of an Attache*. By HUBERT E. H. JERNINGHAM. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 5s Diane de Breteuille. A Love Story. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. JOHNSTON. The Chemistry of Common Life. By Professor J. F. W. JOHNSTON. New Edition, Revised. By ARTHUR HERBERT CHURCH, M.A. Oxon.; Author of ' Pood : its Sources, Constituents, and Uses,' &c. With Maps and 102 Engravings. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. Elements of Agricultural Chemistry. An entirely New Edition from the Edition by Sir CHARLES A. CAMERON, M.D., F.R.C.S.I., &c. Revised and brought down to date by C. M. AIRMAN, M.A., B.Sc., F.R.S.E., Professor of Chemistry, Glasgow Veterinary College. 17th Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. 6d. Catechism of Agricultural Chemistry. An entirely New Edition from the Edition by Sir CHARLES A. CAMERON. Revised and Enlarged by C. M. AIRMAN, M.A., &c. 95th Thousand. With numerous Illustrations. Crown 8vo, Is. JOHNSTON. Agricultural Holdings (Scotland) Acts, 1883 and 1889 ; and the Ground Game Act, 1880. With Notes, and Summary of Procedure, &c. By CHRISTOPHER N. JOHNSTON, M.A., Advocate. Demy 8vo, 5s. JOKAI. Timar's Two Worlds. By MAURUS JOKAI. Authorised Translation by Mrs HEGAN KENNARD. Cheap Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. KEBBEL. The Old and the New : English Country Life. By T. E. KEBBEL, M. A., Author of ' The Agricultural Labourers,' ' Essays in History and Politics,' ' Life of Lord Beaconsfield.' Crown 8vo, 5s. KERR. St Andrews in 1645-46. By D. R. KERR. Crown Svo, 2s. 6d. KINGLAKE. History of the Invasion of the Crimea. By A. W. KINGLAKE. Cabinet Edition, Revised. With an Index to the Complete Work. Illustrated with Maps and Plans. Complete in 9 vols., crown Svo, at 6s. each. Abridged Edition for Military Students. Revised by Lieut.-Col. Sir GEORGE SYDENHAM CLARKE, K.C.M.G., R.E. In 1 vol. demy Svo. [In the press. History of the Invasion of the Crimea. Demy Svo. Vol. VI. Winter Troubles. With a Map, 16s. Vols. VII. and VIII. From the Morrow of Inkerman to the Death of Lord Raglan With an Index to the Whole Work. With Maps and Plans. 28s. Eothen. A New Edition, uniform with the Cabinet Edition of the ' History of the Invasion of the Crimea. ' 6s. CHEAPER EDITION. With Portrait and Biographical Sketch of the Author. Crown Svo, 3s. 6d. Popular Edition, in paper cover, Is. net. William Blackwood and Sons. 17 KIRBY. In Haunts of Wild Game: A Hunter -Naturalist's Wanderings from Kahlamba to Libombo. By FREDERICK VAUGHAN KIRBY, F.Z.S. (Maqaqamba). With numerous Illustrations by Charles "Whymper, and a Map. Large demy 8vo, 25s. KNEIPP. My Water -Cure. As Tested through more than Thirty Years, and Described for the Healing of Diseases and the Preservation of Health. By SEBASTIAN KNEIPP, Parish Priest of WOrishofen (Bavaria). With a Portrait and other Illustrations. Authorised English Translation from the Thirtieth German Edition, by A. de F. Cheap Edition. With an Appendix, con- taining the Latest Developments of Pfarrer Kneipp's System, and a Preface by E. Gerard. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. KNOLLYS. The Elements of Field-Artillery. Designed for the Use of Infantry and Cavalry Officers. By HENRY KNOLLYS, Colonel Royal Artillery; Author of 'From Sedan to Saarbriick,' Editor of 'Incidents in the Sepoy War,' &c. With Engravings. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. LANG. Life, Letters, and Diaries of Sir Stafford Northcote, First Earl of Iddesleigh. By ANDREW LANG. With Three Portraits and a View of Pynes. Third Edition. 2 vols. post 8vo, 31s. 6d. POPULAR EDITION. With Portrait and View of Pynes. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. The Highlands in 1749. From the King's Collection MSS., with an Introduction and Notes. In 1 vol. crown 8vo. [In the prest. LANG. The Expansion of the Christian Life. The Duff Lec- tures for 1897. By the Rev. J. MARSHALL LANG, D.D. In 1 vol. crown 8vo. [In the press. LEES. A Handbook of the Sheriff and Justice of Peace Small Debt Courts. With Notes, References, and Forms. By J. M. LEES, Advocate, Sheriff of Stirling, Dumbarton, and Clackmannan. 8vo, 7s. 6d. LINDSAY. Recent Advances in Theistic Philosophy of Religion. By Rev. JAMES LINDSAY, M.A., B.D., B.Sc., F.R.S.E., F.G.S., Minister of the Parish of St Andrew's, Kilmarnock. Demy 8vo, 12s. 6d. net. The Progressiveness of Modern Christian Thought. Crown 8vo, 6s. Essays, Literary and Philosophical. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. The Significance of the Old Testament for Modern Theology. Crown 8vo, Is. net. The Teaching Function of the Modern Pulpit. Crown 8vo, Is. net. LOCKHART. Doubles and Quits. By LAURENCE W. M. LOCKHART. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Fair to See. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Mine is Thine. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. LOCKHART. The Church of Scotland in the Thirteenth Century. The Life and Times of David de Bernham of St Andrews (Bishop), A.D. 1239 to 1253. With List of Churches dedicated by him, and Dates. By WILLIAM LOCKHART, A.M., D.D., F.S.A. Scot., Minister of Colinton Parish. 2d Edition. 8vo, 6s. Dies Tristes : Sermons for Seasons of Sorrow. Crown 8vo, 6s. LORIMER. The Institutes of Law : A Treatise of the Principles of Juris- prudence as determined by Nature. By the late JAMES LORIMER, Professor of Public Law and of the Law of Nature and Nations in the University of Edin- burgh. New Edition, Revised and much Enlarged. 8vo, 18s. 1 8 List of Books Published by LORIMER. The Institutes of the Law of Nations. A Treatise of the Jural Relation of Separate Political Communities. In 2 vols. 8vo. Volume I., price 16s. Volume II., price 20s. LUGARD. The Rise of our East African Empire : Early Efforts in Uganda and Nyasaland. By F. D. LUGARD, Captain Norfolk Regiment. With 130 Illustrations from Drawings and Photographs under the personal superintendence of the Author, and 14 specially prepared Maps. In 2 vols. large demy 8vo, 42s. M'CHESNEY. Miriam Cromwell, Royalist : A Romance of the Great Rebel- lion. By DORA GREENWELL M'CHESNEY. Crown 8vo, 6s. Kathleen Clare : Her Book, 1637-41. With Frontispiece, and five full-page Illustrations by James A. Shearman. Crown 8vo, 6s. M'COMBIE. Cattle and Cattle-Breeders. By WILLIAM M'CoMBiE, Tillyfour. New Edition, Enlarged, with Memoir of the Author by JAMES MACDONALD, F.R.S.E., Secretary Highland and Agricultural Society of Scotland. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. M'CRIE. Works of the Rev. Thomas M'Crie, D.D. Uniform Edition. 4 vols. crown 8vo, 24s. Life of John Knox. Crown 8vo, 6s. Another Edition, 3s. 6d. Life of Andrew Melville. Crown 8vo, 6s. History of the Progress and Suppression of the Reformation in Italy in the Sixteenth Century. Crown 8vo, 4s. History of the Progress and Suppression of the Reformation in Spain in the Sixteenth Century. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. M'CRIE. The Public Worship of Presbyterian Scotland. Histori- cally treated. With copious Notes, Appendices, and Index. The Fourteenth Series of the Cunningham Lectures. By the Rev. CHARLES G. M'CRIE, D.D. Demy 8vo, 10s. 6d. MACDONALD. A Manual of the Criminal Law (Scotland) Pro- cedure Act, 1887. By NORMAN DORAN MACDONALD. Revised by the LORD JUSTICE-CLERK. 8vo, 10s. 6d. MACDONALD AND SINCLAIR. History of Polled Aberdeen and Angus Cattle. Giving an Account of the Origin, Improvement, and Charac- teristics of the Breed. By JAMES MACDONALD and JAMES SINCLAIR. Illustrated with numerous Animal Portraits. Post 8vo, 12s. 6d. MACDOUGALL AND DODDS. A Manual of the Local Govern- ment (Scotland) Act, 1894. With Introduction, Explanatory Notes, and Copious Index. By J. PATTEN MACDOUGALL, Legal Secretary to the Lord Advocate, and J. M. DODDS. Tenth Thousand, Revised. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. net. MACINTYRE. Hindu - Koh : Wanderings and Wild Sports on and beyond the Himalayas. By Major-General DONALD MACINTYRE, V.C., late Prince of Wales' Own Goorkhas, F.R.G.S. Dedicated to H.R.H. The Prince of Wales. New and Cheaper Edition, Revised, with numerous Illustrations. Post 8vo, 3s. 6d. MACKAY. Elements of Modern Geography. By the Rev. ALEXANDER MACKAY, LL.D., F.R.G.S. 55th Thousand, Revised to the present time. Crown 8vo, pp. 300, 3s. The Intermediate Geography. Intended as an Intermediate Book between the Author's 'Outlines of Geography' and 'Elements of Geo- graphy.' Eighteenth Edition, Revised. Fcap. 8vo, pp. 238, 2s. Outlines of Modern Geography. 191st Thousand, Revised to the present time. Fcap. 8vo, pp. 128, Is. Elements of Physiography. New Edition. Rewritten and Enlarged. With numerous Illustrations. Crown 8vo. [In the press. William Blackwood and Sons. 19 MACKENZIE. Studies in Roman Law. With Comparative Views of the Laws of France, England, and Scotland. By Lord MACKENZIE, one of the Judges of the Court of Session in Scotland. Sixth Edition, Edited by JOHN KIRKPATRICK, M.A., LL.B., Advocate, Professor of History in the University of Edinburgh. 8vo, 12s. MACPHERSON. Glimpses of Church and Social Life in the Highlands in Olden Times. By ALEXANDER MACPHERSON, F.S.A. Scot. With <6 Photogravure Portraits and other full-page Illustrations. Small 4to, 25s. M'PHERSON. Golf and Golfers. Past and Present. By J. GORDON M'PHERSON, Ph.D., F.R.S.E. With an Introduction by the Right Hon. A. J. BALFOUR, and a Portrait of the Author. Fcap. 8vo, Is. 6d. MACRAE. A Handbook of Deer-Stalking. By ALEXANDER MACRAE, late Forester to Lord Henry Bentinck. With Introduction by Horatio Ross, Esq. Fcap. 8vo, with 2 Photographs from Life. 3s. 6d. MAIN. Three Hundred English Sonnets. Chosen and Edited by DAVID M. MAIN. New Edition. Fcap. 8vo, 3s. 6d . MAIR. A Digest of Laws and Decisions, Ecclesiastical and Civil, relating to the Constitution, Practice, and Affairs of the Church of Scot- land. With Notes and Forms of Procedure. By the Rev. WILLIAM MAIR, D.D., Minister of the Parish of Earlston. New Edition, Revised. Crown 8vo, 9s. net. MARCHMONT AND THE HUMES OF POLWARTH. By One of their Descendants. With numerous Portraits and other Illustrations. Crown 4to, 21s. net. MARSHMAN. History of India. From the Earliest Period to the present time. By JOHN CLARK MARSHMAN, C.S.I. Third and Cheaper Edition. Post 8vo, with Map, 6s. MARTIN. The ^Eneid of Virgil. Books I.- VI. Translated by Sir THEO- DORE MARTIN, K.C.B. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. Goethe's Faust. Part I. Translated into English Verse. Second Edition, crown 8vo, 6s. Ninth Edition, fcap. 8vo, 3s. 6d. Goethe's Faust. Part II. Translated into English Verse. Second Edition, Revised. Fcap. 8vo, 6s. The Works of Horace. Translated into English Verse, with Life and Notes. 2 vols. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 21s. Poems and Ballads of Heinrich Heine. Done into English Verse. Third Edition. Small crown 8vo, 5s. The Song of the Bell, and other Translations from Schiller, Goethe, Uhland, and Others. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. Madonna Pia : A Tragedy ; and Three Other Dramas. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. Catullus. With Life and Notes. Second Edition, Revised and Corrected. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. The ' Vita Nuova ' of Dante. Translated, with an Introduction and Notes. Third Edition. Small crown 8vo, 5s. Aladdin: A Dramatic Poem. By ADAM OEHLENSCHLAEGER. Fcap. 8vo, 5s. Correggio : A Tragedy. By OEHLENSCHLAEGER. With Notes. Fcap. 8vo, 3s. MARTIN. On some of Shakespeare's Female Characters. By HELENA FAUCIT, Lady MARTIN. Dedicated by permission to Her Most Gracious Majesty the Queen. Fifth Edition. With a Portrait by Lehmann. Demy 8vo, 7s. 6d. MARWICK. Observations on the Law and Practice in regard to Municipal Elections and the Conduct of the Business of Town Councils and Commissioners of Police in Scotland. By Sir JAMES D. MARWICK, LL.D., Town-Clerk of Glasgow. Royal 8vo, 30s. 2O List of Books Published by MATHESON. Can the Old Faith Live with the New ? or, The Problem of Evolution and Revelation. By the Rev. GEORGE MATHESON, D.D. Third Edi- tion. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. The Psalmist and the Scientist ; or, Modern Value of the Reli- gious Sentiment. Third Edition. Crown 8vo, 5s. Spiritual Development of St Paul. Third Edition. Cr. 8vo, 5s. The Distinctive Messages of the Old Religions. Second Edi- tion. Crown 8vo, 5s. Sacred Songs. New and Cheaper Edition. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. MATHIESON. The Supremacy and Sufficiency of Jesus Christ our Lord, as set forth in the Epistle to the Hebrews. By J. E. MATHIESON, Superintendent of Mildmay Conference Hall, 1880 to 1890. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. MAURICE. The Balance of Military Power in Europe. An Examination of the War Resources of Great Britain and the Continental States. By Colonel MAURICE, R.A., Professor of Military Art and History at the Royal Staff College. Crown 8vo, with a Map, 6s. MAXWELL. A Duke of Britain. A Romance of the Fourth Century. By Sir HERBERT MAXWELL, Bart., M.P., F.S.A., &c., Author of 'Passages in the Life of Sir Lucian Elphin.' Fourth Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. Life and Times of the Rt. Hon. William Henry Smith, M.P. "With Portraits and numerous Illustrations by Herbert Railton, G. L. Seymour, and Others. 2 vols. demy 8vo, 25s. POPULAR EDITION. With a Portrait and other Illustrations. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Scottish Land-Names : Their Origin and Meaning. Being the Rhind Lectures in Archaeology for 1893. Post 8vo, 6s. Meridiana : Noontide Essays. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. Post Meridiana : Afternoon Essays. Post 8vo, 6s. Dumfries and Galloway. Being one of the Volumes of the County Histories of Scotland. With Four Maps. Demy 8vo, 7s. 6d. net. MELDRUM. The Story of Margre*del : Being a Fireside History of a Fife- shire Family. By D. STORRAR MELDRUM. Cheap Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Grey Mantle and Gold Fringe. Crown 8vo, 6s. MELLONE. Principles of Philosophical Criticism. By S. H. MELLONK. In 1 vol. post 8vo. [In the press. MERZ. A History of European Thought in the Nineteenth Cen- tury. By JOHN THEODORE MERZ. Vol. I., post 8vo, 10s. 6d. net. MICHIE. The Larch : Being a Practical Treatise on its Culture and General Management. By CHRISTOPHER Y. MICHIE, Forester, Cullen House. Crown 8vo, with Illustrations. New and Cheaper Edition, Enlarged, 5s. The Practice of Forestry. Crown 8vo, with Illustrations. 6s. M1DDLETON. The Story of Alastair Bhan Comyn; or, The Tragedy of Dunphail. A Tale of Tradition and Romance. By the Lady MIDDLE- TON. Square 8vo, 10s. Cheaper Edition, 5s. MIDDLETON. Latin Verse Unseens. By G. MIBDLETON, M.A., Lecturer in Latin, Aberdeen University ; late Scholar of Emmanuel College. Cam- bridge ; Joint- Author of ' Student's Companion to Latin Authors.' Crown 8vo, Is. 6d. MILLER. The Dream of Mr H , the Herbalist. By HUGH MILLER, F.R.S.E., late H.M. Geological Survey, Author of 'Landscape Geology.' With a Photogravure Frontispiece. Crown Svo, 2s. 6d. MILLS. Greek Verse Unseens. By T. R. MILLS, M.A., late Lecturer in Greek, Aberdeen University ; formerly Scholar of Wadham College, Oxford ; Joint- Author of ' Student's Companion to Latin Authors. In 1 vol. crown Svo. [In the press. William Blackwood and Sons. 21 MINTO. A Manual of English Prose Literature, Biographical and Critical: designed mainly to show Characteristics of Style. By W. MINTO, M.A., Hon. LL.D. of St Andrews ; Professor of Logic in the University of Aber- deen. Third Edition, Revised. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. Characteristics of English Poets, from Chaucer to Shirley. New Edition, Eevised. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. Plain Principles of Prose Composition. Crown 8vo, Is. 6d. The Literature of the Georgian Era. Edited, with a Bio- graphical Introduction, by Professor KNIGHT, St Andrews. Post 8vo, 6s. MOIR. Life of Mansie Wauch, Tailor in Dalkeith. By D. M. MOIR. With CRUIKSHANK'S Illustrations. Cheaper Edition. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. Another Edition, without Illustrations, fcap. 8vo, Is. 6d. MOLE. For the Sake of a Slandered Woman. By MAKION MOLE. Fcap. 8vo, 2s. 6d. net. MOMERIE. Defects of Modern Christianity, and other Sermons. By Rev. ALFRED WILLIAMS MOMERIE, M.A., D.Sc., LL.D. Fifth Edition. Crown 8vo, 5s. The Basis of Religion. Being an Examination of Natural Religion. Third Edition. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. The Origin of Evil, and other Sermons. Eighth Edition, Enlarged. Crown 8vo, 5s. Personality. The Beginning and End of Metaphysics, and a Necessary Assumption in all Positive Philosophy. Fifth Edition, Revised. Crown 8vo, 3s. Agnosticism. Fourth Edition, Revised. Crown 8vo, 5s. Preaching and Hearing ; and other Sermons. Fourth Edition, Enlarged. Crown 8vo, 5s. Belief in God. Third Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. Inspiration ; and other Sermons. Second Edition, Enlarged. Crown 8vo, 5s. Church and Creed. Third Edition. Crown 8vo, 4s. 6d. The Future of Religion, and other Essays. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. The English Church and the Romish Schism. Second Edition; Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. MONCREIFF. The Provost- Marshal. A Romance of the Middle Shires. By the Hon. FREDERICK MONCREIFF. Crown 8vo, 6s. The X Jewel. A Romance of the Days of James VI. Crown 8vo, 6s. MONTAGUE. Military Topography. Illustrated by Practical Examples of a Practical Subject. By Major-General W. E. MONTAGUE, C.B., P.S.C., late Garrison Instructor Intelligence Department, Author of ' Campaign- ing in South Africa.' With Forty-one Diagrams. Crown 8vo, 5s. MONTALEMBERT. Memoir of Count de Montalembert. A Chapter of Recent French History. By Mrs OLIPHANT, Author of the ' Life of Edward Irving,' &c. 2 vols. crown 8vo, 1, 4s. MORISON. Doorside Ditties. By JEANIE MORISON. With a Frontis- piece. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. ^Eolus. A Romance in Lyrics. Crown 8vo, 3s. There as Here. Crown 8vo, 3s. %* A limited impression on hand-made paper, bound in vellum, 7s. 6d. Selections from Poems. Crown 8vo, 4s. 6d. Sordello. An Outline Analysis of Mr Browning's Poem. Crown 8vo, 3s. 22 List of Books Published by MORISON. Of "Fifine at the Fair," "Christmas Eve and Easter Day, and other of Mr Browning's Poems. Crown 8vo, 3s. The Purpose of the Ages. Crown 8vo, 9s. Gordon : An Our-day Idyll. 'Crown 8vo, 3s. Saint Isadora, and other Poems. Crown 8vo, Is. 6d. Snatches of Song. Paper, Is. 6d. ; cloth, 3s. Pontius Pilate. Paper, Is. 6d. ; cloth, 3s. Mill o 3 Forres. Crown 8vo, Is. Ane Booke of Ballades. Fcap. 4to, Is. MUNRO. The Lost Pibroch, and other Sheiling Stories. By NEIL MUNRO. Crown 8vo, 6s. MUNRO. Rambles and Studies in Bosnia- Herzegovina and Dalmatia. With an Account of the Proceedings of the Congress of Archaeologists and Anthropologists held at Sarajevo in 1894. By ROBERT MUNRO, M.A., M.D., F.R.S.E., Author of ' The Lake- Dwellings of Europe,' &c. With numerous Illus- trations. Deiny 8vo, 12s. 6d. net. Prehistoric Problems. With numerous Illustrations. Demy 8vo, 10s. net. MUNRO. On Valuation of Property. By WILLIAM MUNRO, M.A., Her Majesty's Assessor of Railways and Canals for Scotland. Second Edition, Revised and Enlarged. 8vo, 3s. 6d. MURDOCH. Manual of the Law of Insolvency and Bankruptcy : Comprehending a Summary of the Law of Insolvency, Notour Bankruptcy, Composition - Contracts, Trust -Deeds, Cessios, and Sequestrations; and the Winding-up of Joint-Stock Companies in Scotland; with Annotations on the various Insolvency and Bankruptcy Statutes; and with Forms of Procedure applicable to these Subjects. By JAMES MURDOCH, Member of the Faculty of Procurators in Glasgow. Fifth Edition, Revised and Enlarged. 8vo, 12s. net. MURRAY. A Popular Manual of Finance. By SYDNEY J. MURRAY. In 1 vol. crown 8vo. [In the press. MYERS. A Manual of Classical Geography. By JOHN L. MYERS, M.A., Fellow of Magdalene College ; Lecturer and Tutor, Christ Church, Oxford. In 1 vol. crown 8vo. [In the, press. MY TRIVIAL LIFE AND MISFORTUNE: A Gossip with no Plot in Particular. By A PLAIN WOMAN. Cheap Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. By the SAME AUTHOR. POOR NELLIE. Cheap Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. NAPIER. The Construction of the Wonderful Canon of Loga- rithms. By JOHN NAPIER of Merchiston. Translated, with Notes, and a Catalogue of Napier's Works, by WILLIAM RAE MACDONALD. Small 4to, 15s. A few large-paper copies on Whatman paper, 30s. LEAVES. Songs and Verses, Social and Scientific. By An Old Contributor to 'Maga.' By the Hon. Lord NEAVES. Fifth Edition. Fcap. 8vo, 4s. NICHOLSON. A Manual of Zoology, for the Use of Students. With a General Introduction on the Principles of Zoology. By HENRY ALLEYNE NICHOLSON, M.D., D.Sc., F.L.S., F.G.S., Regius Professor of Natural History in the University of Aberdeen. Seventh Edition, Rewritten and Enlarged. Post 8vo, pp. 956, with 555 Engravings on Wood, 18s. Text-Book of Zoology, for Junior Students. Fifth Edition, Rewritten and Enlarged. Crown 8vo, with 358 Engravings on Wood, 10s. 6d. Introductory Text-Book of Zoology, for the Use of Junior Classes. New Edition, Revised and Enlarged. [In the press. William Blackwood and Sons. 23 NICHOLSON. A Manual of Palaeontology, for the Use of Students. With a General Introduction on the Principles of Palaeontology. By Professor H. ALLEYNE NICHOLSON and RICHARD LYDEKKER, B.A. Third -Edition, entirely Rewritten and greatly Enlarged. 2 vols. 8vo, 3, 3s. The Ancient Life-History of the Earth. An Outline of the Principles and Leading Facts of Palseontological Science. Crown 8vo, with 276 Engravings, 10s. 6d. On the "Tabulate Corals" of the Palaeozoic Period, with Critical Descriptions of Illustrative Species. Illustrated with 15 Lithographed Plates and numerous Engravings. Super-royal 8vo, 21s. Synopsis of the Classification of the Animal Kingdom. 8vo, with 106 Illustrations, 6s. On the Structure and Affinities of the Genus Monticulipora and its Sub-Genera, with Critical Descriptions of Illustrative Species. Illustrated with numerous Engravings on Wood and Lithographed Plates. Super-royal 8vo, 18s. NICHOLSON. Thoth. A Romance. By JOSEPH SHIELD NICHOLSON, M.A., D.Sc., Professor of Commercial and Political Economy and Mercantile Law in the University of Edinburgh. Third Edition. Crown 8vo, 4s. 6d. A Dreamer of Dreams. A Modern Romance. Second Edi- tion. Crown 8vo, 6s. NICOLSON AND MURE. A Handbook to the Local Govern- ment (Scotland) Act, 1889. With Introduction, Explanatory Notes, and Index. By J. BADENACH NICOLSON, Advocate, Counsel to the Scotch Education Department, and W. J. MURE, Advocate, Legal Secretary to the Lord Advocate for Scotland. Ninth Reprint. 8vo, 5s. OLIPHANT. Masollam : A Problem of the Period. A Novel. By LAURENCE OLIPHANT. 3 vols. post 8vo, 25s. 6d. Scientific Religion ; or, Higher Possibilities of Life and Pmctice through the Operation of Natural Forces. Second Edition. 8vo, 16s. Altiora Peto. Cheap Edition. Crown 8vo, boards, 2s. 6d. ; cloth, 3s. 6d. Illustrated Edition. Crown 8vo, cloth, 6s. Piccadilly. With Illustrations by Richard Doyle. New Edi- tion, 3s. 6d. Cheap Edition, boards, 2s. 6d. Traits and Travesties ; Social and Political. Post 8vo, 10s. 6d. Episodes in a Life of Adventure; or, Moss from a Rolling Stone. Cheaper Edition. Post 8vo, 3s. 6d. Haifa: Life in Modern Palestine. Second Edition. Svo, 7s. 6d. The Land of Gilead. With Excursions in the Lebanon. With Illustrations and Maps. Demy 8vo, 21s. Memoir of the Life of Laurence Oliphant, and of Alice Oliphant, his Wife. By Mrs M. O. W. OLIPHANT. Seventh Edition. 2 vols. post 8vo, with Portraits. 21s. POPULAR EDITION. With a New Preface. Post 8vo, with Portraits. 7s. 6d. OLIPHANT. Annals of a Publishing House. William Blackwood and his Sons ; Their Magazine and Friends. By Mrs OLIPHANT. With Four Portraits. Demy Svo. Vols. I. and II. 2, 2s. Who was Lost and is Found. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. Miss Marjoribanks. New Edition. Crown Svo, 3s. 6d. The Perpetual Curate, and The Rector. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. 24 List of Books Published by OLIPHANT. Salem Chapel, and The Doctor's Family. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d Chronicles of Carlingford. .3 vols. crown 8vo, in uniform binding, gilt top, 3s. 6d. each. Katie Stewart, and other Stories. New Edition. Crown 8vo, cloth, 3s. 6d. Katie Stewart. Illustrated boards, 2s. 6d. Valentine and his Brother. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Sons and Daughters. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Two Stories of the Seen and the Unseen. The Open Door Old Lady Mary. Paper covers, Is. OLIPHANT. Notes of a Pilgrimage to Jerusalem and the Holy Land. By F. R. OLIPHANT. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. OSWALD. By Fell and Fjord ; or, Scenes and Studies in Ice- land. By B. J. OSWALD. Post 8vo, with Illustrations. 7s. 6d. PAGE. Introductory Text-Book of Geology. By DAVID PAGE, LL.D., Professor of Geology in the Durham University of Physical Science, Newcastle. With Engravings and Glossarial Index. New Edition. Revised by Professor LAPWORTH of Mason Science College, Birmingham. [In preparation. Advanced Text-Book of Geology, Descriptive and Industrial. With Engravings, and Glossary of Scientific Terms. New Edition. Revised by Professor LAPWORTH. [in preparation. Introductory Text-Book of Physical Geography. With Sketch- Maps and Illustrations. Edited by Professor LAPWORTH, LL.D., F.G.S., &c., Mason Science College, Birmingham. Thirteenth Edition, Revised and Enlarged. 2s. 6(1, Advanced Text-Book of Physical Geography. Third Edition. Revised and Enlarged by Professor LAPWORTH. With Engravings. 5s. PATERSON. A Manual of Agricultural Botany. From the German of Dr A. B. FRANK, Professor in the Royal Agricultural College, Berlin. Translated by JOHN W. PATERSON, B.Sc., Ph.D., Free Life Member of the High- land and Agricultural Society of Scotland, and of the Royal Agricultural Society of England. With over 100 Illustrations. In 1 vol. crown 8vo. [In the press. Spindrift. By Sir J. NOEL PATON. Fcap., cloth, 5s. Poems by a Painter. Fcap., cloth, 5s. PATRICK. The Apology of Origen in Reply to Celsus. A Chap- ter in the History of Apologetics. By the Rev. J. PATRICK, D.D. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. PAUL. History of the Royal Company of Archers, the Queen's Body-Guard for Scotland. By JAMES BALFOUR PAUL, Advocate of the Scottish Bar. Crown 4to, with Portraits and other Illustrations. 2, 2s. PEILE. Lawn Tennis as a Game of Skill. By Lieut. -Col. S. C. F. PEILE, B.S.C. Revised Edition, with new Scoring Rules. Fcap. 8vo, cloth, Is. PETTIGREW. The Handy Book of Bees, and their Profitable Management. By A. PETTIGREW. Fifth Edition, Enlarged, with Engravings. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6<I. PFLEIDERER. Philosophy and Development of Religion. Being the Edinburgh Gifford Lectures for 1894. By OTTO PFLEIDERER, D.D. Professor of Theology at Berlin University. In 2 vols. post 8vo, 15s. net. PHILLIPS. The Knight's Tale. By F. EMILY PHILLIPS, Author of ' The Education of Antonia.' Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. PHILOSOPHICAL CLASSICS FOR ENGLISH READERS. Edited by WILLIAM KNIGHT, LL.D., Professor of Moral Philosophy, University of St Andrews. In crown 8vo volumes, with Portraits, price 3s. 6d. [For List of Volumes, see page 2. William Blackwood and Sons. 25 POLLARD. A Study in Municipal Government : The Corpora- tion of Berlin. By JAMES POLLARD, C.A., Chairman of the Edinburgh Public Health Committee, and Secretary of the Edinburgh Chamber of Commerce. Second Edition, Revised. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. POLLOK. The Course of Time : A Poem. By ROBERT POLLOK, A.M. Cottage Edition, 32mo, 8d. The Same, cloth, gilt edges, Is. 6d. Another Edition, with Illustrations by Birket Foster and others, fcap., cloth, 3s. 6d., or with edges gilt, 4s. PORT ROYAL LOGIC. Translated from the French; with Introduction, Notes, and Appendix. By THOMAS SPENCER BAYNES, LL.D., Pro- fessor in the University of St Andrews. Tenth Edition, 12mo, 4s. POTTS AND DARNELL. Aditus Faciliores : An Easy Latin Construing Book, with Complete Vocabulary By A. W. POTTS, M.A., LL.D., and the Rev. C. DARNELL, M. A., Head-Master of Cargilfield Preparatory School Edinburgh. Tenth Edition, fcap. 8vo, 3s. 6d. Aditus Faciliores Graeci. An Easy Greek Construing Book, with Complete Vocabulary. Fifth Edition, Revised. Fcap. 8vo, 3s. POTTS. School Sermons. By the late ALEXANDER WM. POTTS, LL.D., First Head-Master of Fettes College. With a Memoir and Portrait. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. PRINGLE. The Live Stock of the Farm. By ROBERT O. PRINGLE. Third Edition. Revised and Edited by JAMES MACDONALD. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. PUBLIC GENERAL STATUTES AFFECTING SCOTLAND from 1707 to 1847, with Chronological Table and Index. 3 vols. large 8vo, 3, 3s. PUBLIC GENERAL STATUTES AFFECTING SCOTLAND, COLLECTION OF. Published Annually, with General Index. RAMSAY. Scotland and Scotsmen in the Eighteenth Century. Edited from the MSS. of JOHN RAMSAY, Esq. of Ochtertyre, by ALEXANDER ALLARDYCE, Author of 'Memoir of Admiral Lord Keith, K.B.,' &c. 2 vols. 8vo, 31s. 6d. RANJITSINHJI. The Jubilee Book of Cricket. By PRINCE , RANJITSINHJI. EDITION DE LUXE. Limited to 350 Copies, printed on hand made paper, and handsomely bound in buckram. Crown 4to, with 22 Photogravures and 85 full- page Plates. Each copy signed by Prince Ranjitsinhji. Price 5, 5s. net. FINE PAPER EDITION. Medium 8vo, with Photogravure Frontispiece and 106 full-page Plates on art paper. 25s. net. POPULAR EDITION. With 107 full-page Illustrations. Third Edition. Large crown 8vo, 6s. RANKIN. A Handbook of the Church of Scotland. By JAMES RANKIN, D.D., Minister of Muthill ; Author of 'Character Studies in the Old Testament, &c. An entirely New and much Enlarged Edition. Crown 8vo, with 2 Maps, 7s. 6d. The First Saints. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. The Creed in Scotland. An Exposition of the Apostles' Creed. With Extracts from Archbishop Hamilton's Catechism of 1552, John Calvin's Catechism of 1556, and a Catena of Ancient Latin and other Hymns. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. The Worthy Communicant. A Guide to the Devout Obser- vance of the Lord's Supper. Limp cloth, Is. 3d. The Young Churchman. Lessons on the Creed, the Com- mandments, the Means of Grace, and the Church. Limp cloth, Is. 3d. First Communion Lessons. 25th Edition. Paper Cover, 2d. RANKINE. A Hero of the Dark Continent. Memoir of Rev. Wm. Affleck Scott, M.A., M.B., C.M., Church of Scotland Missionary at Blantyre, British Central Africa. By W. HENRY RANKINE, B.D., Minister at Titwood. With a Portrait and other Illustrations. Cheap Edition. Crown 8vo, 2s. 26 List of Books Published by ROBERTSON. The Early Religion of Israel. As set forth by Biblical Writers and Modern Critical Historians. Being the Baird Lecture for 1888-89. By JAMES ROBERTSON, D.D., Professor of Oriental Languages in the University of Glasgow. Fourth Edition. Crown 8vo, 10s. 6d. ROBERTSON. Orellana, and other Poems. By J. LOGIE ROBERTSON, M.A. Pcap. 8vo. Printed on hand-made paper. 6s. A History of English Literature. For Secondary Schools. With an Introduction by Professor MASSON, Edinburgh University. Cr. 8vo, 3s. English Verse for Junior Classes. In Two Parts. Part I. Chaucer to Coleridge. Part II. Nineteenth Century Poets. Crown 8vo, each Is. 6d. net. Outlines of English Literature for Young Scholars. With Illustrative Specimens. Crown 8vo, Is. 6d. ROBINSON. Wild Traits in Tame Animals. Being some Familiar Studies in Evolution. By Louis ROBINSON, M.D. With Illustrations by STEPHEN T. DADD. In 1 vol. small demy Svo. [In the press. RODGER. Aberdeen Doctors at Home and Abroad. The Story of a Medical School. By ELLA HILL BURTON RODGER. Demy Svo, 10s. 6d. ROSCOE. Rambles with a Fishing-Rod. By E. S. ROSCOE. Crown Svo, 4s. 6d. ROSS AND SOMERVILLE. Beggars on Horseback : A Riding Tour in North Wales. By MARTIN Ross and E. (E. SOMERVILLE. With Illustra- tions by E. (E. SOMERVILLE. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d. RUTLAND. Notes of an Irish Tour in 1846. By the DUKE OP RUTLAND, G.C.B. (Lord JOHN MANNERS). New Edition. Crown Svo, 2s. 6d. Correspondence between the Right Honble. William Pitt and Charles Duke of Rutland, Lord - Lieutenant of Ireland, 1781-1787. With Introductory Note by JOHN DUKE OF RUTLAND. Svo, 7s. 6d. RUTLAND. Gems of German Poetry. Translated by the DUCHESS OF RUTLAND (Lady JOHN MANNERS). [New Edition in preparation. Impressions of Bad-Homburg. Comprising a Short Account of the Women's Associations of Germany under the Red Cross. Crown Svo, Is. 6d. Some Personal Recollections of the Later Years of the Earl of Beaconsfield, E.G. Sixth Edition. 6d. Employment of Women in the Public Service. 6d. Some of the Advantages of Easily Accessible Reading and Recreation Rooms and Free Libraries. With Remarks on Starting and Main- taining them. Second Edition. Crown Svo, Is. A Sequel to Rich Men's Dwellings, and other Occasional Papers. Crown Svo, 2s. 6d. Encouraging Experiences of Reading and Recreation Rooms, Aims of Guilds, Nottingham Social Guide, Existing Institutions, &c., &c. Crown Svo, Is. SAINTSBURY. The Flourishing of Romance and the Rise of Allegory (12th and 13th Centuries). By GEORGE SAINTSBURY, M.A.., Professor of Rhetoric and English Literature in Edinburgh University. Being the first vol- ume issued of "PERIODS OF EUROPEAN LITERATURE." Edited by Professor SAINTSBURY. Crown Svo, 5s. net. SCHEFFEL. The Trumpeter. A Romance of the Rhine. By JOSEPH VICTOR VON SCHEFFEL. Translated from the Two Hundredth German Edition by JESSIE BECK and LOUISA LORIMER. With an Introduction by Sir THEODORE MARTIN, K.C.B. Long Svo, 3s. 6d. SCHILLER. Wallenstein. A Dramatic Poem. By FRIEDRICH VON SCHILLER. Translated by C. G. N. LOCKHART. Fcap. Svo, 7s. 6d. William Blackwood and Sons. 27 SCOTT. Tom Cringle's Log. By MICHAEL SCOTT. New Edition. With 19 Pull-page Illustrations. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. SCOUGAL. Prisons and their Inmates; or, Scenes from a Silent World. By FRANCIS SCOUGAL. Crown 8vo, boards, 2s. SELKIKK. Poems. By J. B. SELKIEK, Author of 'Ethics and .Esthetics of Modern Poetry,' 'Bible Truths with Shakespearian Parallels,' &c. New and Enlarged Edition. Crown 8vo, printed on antique paper, 6s. SELLAR'S Manual of the Acts relating to Education in Scot- land. By J. EDWARD GRAHAM, B.A. Oxon.. Advocate. Ninth Edition. Demy 8vo, 12s. 6d. SETH. Scottish Philosophy. A Comparison of the Scottish and German Answers to Hume. Balfour Philosophical Lectures, University of Edinburgh. By ANDREW SETH, LL.D., Professor of Logic and Metaphysics in Edinburgh University. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 5s. Hegelianism and Personality. Balfour Philosophical Lectures. Second Series. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 5s. Man's Place in the Cosmos, and other Essays. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. net. Two Lectures on Theism. Delivered on the occasion of the Sesquicentennial Celebration of Princeton University. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. SETH. A Study of Ethical Principles. By JAMES SETH, M.A., Professor of Philosophy in Cornell University, U.S.A. New Edition, Revised. In 1 vol. post 8vo. [In the press. SHAD WELL. The Life of Colin Campbell, Lord Clyde. Illus- trated by Extracts from his Diary and Correspondence. By Lieutenant-General SHADWELL C.B. With Portrait, Maps, and Plans. 2 vols. 8vo, 36s. SHAND. The Life of General Sir Edward Bruce Hamley, K.C.B., K.C.M.G. By ALEX. INNES SHAND, Author of ' Kilcarra," 'Against Time,' &c. With two Photogravure Portraits and other Illustrations. Cheaper Edition, with a Statement by Mr Edward Hamley. 2 vols. demy 8vo, 10s. 6d. Letters from the West of Ireland. Reprinted from the ' Times.' Crown 8vo, 5s. SHARPS. Letters from and to Charles Kirkpatrick Sharpe. Edited by ALEXANDER ALLARDYCE, Author of ' Memoir of Admiral Lord Keith, K.B.,' &c. With a Memoir by the Rev. W. K. R. BEDFORD. In 2 vols. 8vo. Illustrated with Etchings and other Engravings. 2, 12s. 6d. SIM. Margaret Sim's Cookery. With an Introduction by L. B. WALFORD, Author of ' Mr Smith : A Part of his Life,' &c. Crown 8vo, 5s. SIMPSON. The Wild Rabbit in a New Aspect ; or, Rabbit- Warrens that Pay. A book for Landowners, Sportsmen, Land Agents, Farmers, Gamekeepers, and Allotment Holders. A Record of Recent Experiments con- ducted on the Estate of the Right Hon. the Earl of Wharncliffe at Wortley Hall. By J. SIMPSON. Second Edition, Enlarged. Small crown 8vo, 5s. SIMPSON. New Lights on Siberia. With an Account of a Journey on the Great Siberian Iron Road. By J. Y. SIMPSON. With numerous Illustrations. In 1 vol. demy 8vo. [In the press. SINCLAIR. Audrey Craven. By MAY SINCLAIR. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. SKELTON. The Table-Talk of Shirley. By JOHN SKELTON, Advocate, C.B., LL.D., Author of 'The Essays of Shirley.' With a Frontispiece. Sixth Edition, Revised and Enlarged. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. The Table- Talk of Shirley. Second Series. Summers and Winters at Balrnawhapple. With Illustrations. Two Volumes. Second Edition Post 8vo, 10s. net. 28 List of Books Published by SKELTON. Maitland of Lethington ; and the Scotland of Mary Stuart. A History. Limited Edition, with Portraits. Demy 8vo, 2 vols., 28s. net. The Handbook of Public Health. A Complete Edition of the Public Health and other Sanitary Acts relating to Scotland. Annotated, and with the Rules, Instructions and Decisions of the Board of Supervision brought up to date with relative forms. New Edition. Revised by A. MURRAY. In 1 vol. 8vo. [In the press. The Local Government (Scotland) Act in Relation to Public Health. A Handy Guide for County and District Councillors, Medical Officers, Sanitary Inspectors, and Members of Parochial Boards. Second Edition. With a new Preface on appointment of Sanitary Officers. Crown 8vo, 2s. SKRINE. Columba : A Drama. By JOHN HUNTLEY SKRINE, Warden of Glenalmond ; Author of ' A Memory of Edward Thring. 1 Fcap. 4to, 6s. SMITH. Thorndale ; or, The Conflict of Opinions. By WILLIAM SMITH, Author of ' A Discourse on Ethics,' &c. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 10s. 6d. Gravenhurst ; or, Thoughts on Good and Evil. Second Edi- tion. With Memoir and Portrait of the Author. Crown 8yo, 8s. The Story of William and Lucy Smith. Edited by GEORGE MERRIAM. Large post 8vo, 12s. 6d. SMITH. Memoir of the Families of M'Combie and Thorns, originally M'Intosh and M Thomas. Compiled from History and Tradition. By WILLIAM M'COMBIE SMITH. With Illustrations. 8vo, 7s. 6d. SMITH. Greek Testament Lessons for Colleges, Schools, and Private Students, consisting chiefly of the Sermon on the Mount and the Parables of our Lord. With Notes and Essays. By the Rev. J. HUNTER SMITH, M.A., King Edward's School, Birmingham. Crown 8vo, 6s. SMITH. The Secretary for Scotland. Being a Statement of the Powers and Duties of the new Scottish Office. With a Short Historical Intro- duction, and numerous references to important Administrative Documents. By W. C. SMITH, LL.B., Advocate. 8vo, 6s. "SON OF THE MARSHES, A." From Spring to Fall ; or, When Life Stirs. By " A SON OF THE MARSHES." Cheap Uniform Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Within an Hour of London Town : Among Wild Birds and their Haunts. Edited by J. A. OWEN. Cheap Uniform Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. With the Woodlanders and by the Tide. Cheap Uniform Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. On Surrey Hills. Cheap Uniform Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Annals of a Fishing Village. Cheap Uniform Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. SORLEY. The Ethics of Naturalism. Being the Shaw Fellow- ship Lectures, 1884. By W. R. SORLEY, M.A., Fellow of Trinity College, Cam- bridge, Professor of Moral Philosophy in the University of Aberdeen. Crown 8vo, 6s. SPROTT. The Worship and Offices of the Church of Scotland. By GEORGE W. SPROTT, D.D., Minister of North Berwick. Crown 8vo, 6s. STATISTICAL ACCOUNT OF SCOTLAND. Complete, with Index. 15 vols. 8vo, 16, 16s. STEEVENS. The Land of the Dollar. By G. W. STEEVENS, Author of 1 Naval Policy,' &c. Crown 8vo, 6s. With the Conquering Turk. With 4 Maps. In 1 vol. small demy Svo. [In the press. William Blackwood and Sons. 29 STEPHENS. The Book of the Farm ; detailing the Labours of the Farmer, Farm-Steward, Ploughman, Shepherd, Hedger, Farm-Labourer, Field-Worker, and Cattle-man. Illustrated with numerous Portraits of Animals and Engravings of Implements, and Plans of Farm Buildings. Fourth Edition. Revised, and in great part Re-written, by JAMES MACDONALD, F.R.S.E., Secretary Highland and Agricultural Society of Scotland. Complete in Six Divisional Volumes, bound in cloth, each 10s. 6d., or handsomely bound, in 3 volumes, with leather back and gilt top, 3, 3s. *** Also being issued in 20 monthly Parts, price 2s. 6d. net each. [Part I.-IV. read.y. Catechism of Practical Agriculture. 22d Thousand. Revised by JAMES MACDONALD, F.R.S.E. With numerous Illustrations. Crown 8vo, Is. The Book of Farm Implements and Machines. By J. SLIGHT and R. SCOTT BURN, Engineers. Edited by HENRY STEPHENS. Large 8vo, 2, 2s. STEVENSON. British Fungi. (Hymenomycetes.) By Rev. JOHN STEVENSON, Author of ' Mycologia Scotica,' Hon. Sec. Cryptogamic Society of Scotland. Vols. I. and II., post 8vo, with Illustrations, price 12s. 6d. net each. STEWART. Advice to Purchasers of Horses. By JOHN STEWART, V.S. New Edition. 2s. 6d. STODDART. John Stuart Blackie : A Biography. By ANNA M. STODDART. With 3 Plates. Third Edition. 2 vols. demy 8vo, 21s. POPULAR EDITION, with Portrait. Crown 8vo, 6s. Sir Philip Sidney : Servant of God. Illustrated by MARGARET L. HUGGINS. With a New Portrait of Sir Philip Sidney. Small 4to, with a specially designed Cover. 5s. STORMONTH. Dictionary of the English Language, Pronouncing, Etymo- logical, and Explanatory. By the Rev. JAMES STORMONTH. Revised by the Rev. P. H. PHELP. Library Edition. New and Cheaper Edition, with Supple- ment. Imperial 8vo, handsomely bound in half morocco, 18s. net. Etymological and Pronouncing Dictionary of the English Language. Including a very Copious Selection of Scientific Terms. For use in Schools and Colleges, and as a Book of General Reference. The Pronunciation carefully revised by the Rev. P. H. PHELP, M.A. Cantab. Thirteenth Edition, with Supplement. Crown 8vo, pp. 800. 7s. 6d. The School Dictionary. New Edition, Revised. [In preparation. STORY. The Apostolic Ministry in the Scottish Church (The Baird Lecture for 1897). By ROBERT HERBERT STORY, D.D. (Edin.), F.S.A. Scot., Professor of Ecclesiastical History in the University of Glasgow ; Principal Clerk of the General Assembly ; and Chaplain to the Queen. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. STORY. Nero; A Historical Play. By W. W. STORY, Author of ' Roba di Roma." Fcap. 8vo, 6s. Vallombrosa. Post 8vo, 5s. Poems. 2 vols., 7s. 6d. .''" Fiammetta. A Summer Idyl. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. , " Conversations in a Studio. 2 vols. crown 8vo, 12s. 6d. Excursions in Art and Letters. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. A Poet's Portfolio : Later Readings. 18mo, 3s. 6d. STRACHEY. Talk at a Country House. Fact and Fiction. By Sir EDWARD STPACHEY, Bart. With a Portrait of the Author. Crown 8vo, 4s. 8d. net. STURGIS. Little Comedies, Old and New.' |By JULIAN STURGIS. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. 30 List of Books Published by SUTHERLAND. Handbook of Hardy Herbaceous and Alpine Flowers, for General Garden Decoration. Containing Descriptions of upwards of 1000 Species of Ornamental Hardy Perennial and Alpine Plants ; along with Concise and Plain Instructions for their Propagation and Culture. By WILLIAM SUTHERLAND, Landscape Gardener; formerly Manager of the Herbaceous Depart- ment at Kew. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. TAYLOR. The Story of my Life. By the late Colonel MEADOWS TAYLOR, Author of 'The Confessions of a Thug,' &c., &c. Edited by his Daughter. New and Cheaper Edition, being the Fourth. Crown 8vo. 6s. THOMAS. The Woodland Life. By EDWAED THOMAS. With a Frontispiece. Square 8vo, 6s. THOMSON. The Diversions of a Prime Minister. By Basil Thomson. With a Map, numerous Illustrations by J. W. Cawston and others, and Repro- ductions of Rare Plates from Early Voyages of Sixteenth and Seventeenth Cen- turies. Small demy 8vo, 15s. South Sea Yarns. With 10 Full-page Illustrations. Cheaper Edition. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. THOMSON. Handy Book of the Flower-Garden : Being Practical Direc- tions for the Propagation, Culture, and Arrangement of Plants in Flower- Gardens all the year round. With Engraved Plans. By DAVID THOMSON, Gardener to his Grace the Duke of Buccleuch, K.T., at Drumlanrig. Fourth and Cheaper Edition. Crown 8vo, 5s. The Handy Book of Fruit -Culture under Glass: Being a series of Elaborate Practical Treatises on the Cultivation and Forcing of Pines, Vines, Peaches, Figs, Melons, Strawberries, and Cucumbers. With Engravings of Hothouses, &c. Second Edition, Revised and Enlarged. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. THOMSON. A Practical Treatise on the Cultivation of the Grape Vine. By WILLIAM THOMSON, Tweed Vineyards. Tenth Edition. 8vo, 5s. THOMSON. Cookery for the Sick and Convalescent. With Directions for the Preparation of Poultices, Fomentations, &c. By BARBARA THOMSON. Fcap. 8vo, Is. 6d. THORBURN. Asiatic Neighbours. By S. S. THORBTTRN, Bengal Civil Service, Author of 'Bannu; or, Our Afghan Frontier,' 'David Leslie: A Story of the Afghan Frontier,' 'Musalmans and Money-Lenders in the Pan- lab.' With Two Maps. Demy 8vo, 10s. 6d. net. THORNTON. Opposites. A Series of Essays on the Unpopular Sides of Popular Questions. By LEWIS THORNTON. 8vo, 12s. 6d. TIELE. Elements of the Science of Religion. Part I. Morpho- logical. Being the Gifford Lectures delivered before the University of Edinburgh in 1896. By C. P. TIELE, Theol.D., Litt.D. (Bonon.), Hon. M.R.A.S., &c., Pro- fessor of the Science of Religion in the University of Leiden. In 2 vols. Vol. I. post 8vo, 7s. fid. m't. TOKE. French Historical Unseens. For Army Classes. By N. E. TORE, B. A. In 1 vol. crown 8vo. [In the press. TRANSACTIONS OF THE HIGHLAND AND AGRICUL- TURAL -SOCIETY OF SCOTLAND. Published annually, price 5s. TRAVERS. Mona Maclean, Medical Student. A Novel. By GRAHAM TRAVERS. Twelfth Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. Fellow Travellers. Fourth Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. TRYON. Life of Vice-Admiral Sir George Tryon, K.C.B. By Rear-Admiral C. C. PENROSE FITZGERALD. With Two Portraits and numerous Illustrations. Second Edition. Demy 8vo, 21s. TULLpCH. Rational Theology and Christian Philosophy in England in the Seventeenth Century. By JOHN TULLOCH, D.D., Principal of St Mary's Col- lege in the University of St Andrews, and one of her Majesty's Chaplains in Ordinary in Scotland. Second Edition. 2 vols. 8vo, 16s. William Blackivood and Sons. 31 TULLOCH. Modern Theories in Philosophy and Religion. 8vo, 15s. Luther, and other Leaders of the Reformation. Third Edi- tion, Enlarged. Crown 8vo, 3s. 6d. Memoir of Principal Tulloch, D.D., LL.D. By Mrs OLIPHANT, Author of 'Life of Edward Irving.' Third and Cheaper Edition. 8vo, with Portrait, 7s. 6d. TWEEDIE. The Arabian Horse: His Country and People- By Major - General W. TWEEDIE, C.S.I., Bengal Staff Corps; for many years H.B.M.'s Consul-General, Baghdad, and Political Resident for the Government of India in Turkish Arabia. In one vol. royal 4to, with Seven Coloured Plates and other Illustrations, and a Map of the Country. Price 3, 3s. net. TYLER. The Whence and the Whither of Man. A Brief His- tory of his Origin and Development through Conformity to Environment. The Morse Lectures of 1895. By JOHN M. TYLER, Professor of Biology, Amherst Col- lege, U.S.A. Post 8vo, 6s. net. VEITCH. Memoir of John Veitch, LL.D., Professor of Logic and Rhetoric, University of Glasgow. By MARY R. L. BRYCE. With Portrait and 3 Photo- gravure Plates. Demy 8vo, 7s. 6d. Border Essays. By JOHN VEITCH, LL.D., Professor of Logic and Rhetoric, University of Glasgow. Crown 8vo, 4s. 6d. net. The History and Poetry of the Scottish Border : their Main Features and Relations. New and Enlarged Edition. 2 vols. demy 8vo, 16s. Institutes of Logic. Post 8vo, 12s. 6d. The Feeling for Nature in Scottish Poetry. From the Ear- liest Times to the Present Day. 2 vols. fcap. 8vo, in roxburghe binding, 15s. Merlin and other Poems. Fcap. 8vo, 4s. 6d, Knowing and Being. Essays in Philosophy. First Series. Crown 8vo, 5s. Dualism and Monism ; and other Essays. Essays in Phil- osophy. Second Series. With an Introduction by R. M. Wenley. Crown 8vo, 4s. 6d. net. VIRGIL. The ^Eneid of Virgil. Translated in English Blank Verse by G. K. RICKARDS, M.A., and Lord RAVENSWORTH. 2 vols. fcap. 8vo, 10s. WAGE. Christianity and Agnosticism. Reviews of some Recent Attacks on the Christian Faith. By HENRY WACE, D.D., Principal of King's College, London ; Preacher of Lincoln's Inn ; Chaplain to the Queen. Second Edition. Post 8vo, 10s. 6d. net. WADDELL. An Old Kirk Chronicle : Being a History of Auld- hame, Tyninghame, and Whitekirk, in East Lothian. From Session Records, 1615 to 1850. By Rev. P. HATELY WADDELL, B.D., Minister of the United Parish. Small Paper Edition, 200 Copies. Price 1. Large Paper Edition, 50 Copies. Price 1, 10s. WALDO. The Ban of the Gubbe. By CEDRIC DANE WALDO. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. WALFORD. Four Biographies from c Blackwood ' : Jane Taylor, Hannah More, Elizabeth Fry, Mary Somerville. By L. B. WALFORD. Crown 8vo, 5s. WARREN'S (SAMUEL) WORKS: Diary of a Late Physician. Cloth, 2s. 6d. ; boards, 2s Ten Thousand A- Year. Cloth, 3s. 6d. ; boards, 2s. 6d. Now and Then. The Lily and the Bee. Intellectual and Moral Development of the Present Age. 4s. 6d. Essays : Critical, Imaginative, and Juridical. 5s. 32 Books Published by William Blackwood and Sons. WENLEY. Socrates and Christ : A Study in the Philosophy of Religion. By R. M. WENLEY, M.A., D.Sc., D.Phil., Professor of Philosophy in the Univer- sity of Michigan, U.S.A. Crown^vo, 6s. Aspects of Pessimism. Crown 8vo, 6s. WHITE. The Eighteen Christian Centuries. By the Rev. JAMES WHITE. Seventh Edition. Post 8vo, with Index, 6s. History of France, from the Earliest Times. Sixth Thousand. Post 8vo, with Index, 6s. WHITE. Archaeological Sketches in Scotland Kintyre and Knapdale. By Colonel T. P. WHITE, B.B., of the Ordnance Survey. With numerous Illus- trations. 2 vols. folio, 4, 4s. Vol. I., Kintyre, sold separately, 2, 2s. The Ordnance Survey of the United Kingdom. A Popular Account. Crown 8vo, 5s. WILKES. Latin Historical Unseens. For Army Classes. By L. C. VAUGHAN WILKES, M.A. In 1 vol. crown 8vo. [In the press. WILLIAMSON. The Horticultural Handbook and Exhibitor's Guide. A Treatise on Cultivating, Exhibiting, and Judging Plants, Flowers, Fruits, and Vegetables. By W. WILLIAMSON, Gardener. Revised by MALCOLM DUNN, Gardener to his Grace the Duke of Buccleuch and Queensberry, Dalkeith Park. New and Cheaper Edition, enlarged. Crown 8vo, paper cover, 2s. ; cloth, 2s. 6d. WILLIAMSON. Poems of Nature and Life. By DAVID R. WILLIAMSON, Minister of Kirkmaiden. Fcap. 8vo, 3s. WILLS. Behind an Eastern Veil. A Plain Tale of Events occurring in the Experience of a Lady who had a unique opportunity of observ- ing the Inner Life of Ladies of the Upper Class in Persia. By C. J. WILLS, Author of ' In the Land of the Lion and Sun, 1 ' Persia as it is,' &c., &c. Cheaper Edition. Demy 8vo, 5s. WILSON. Works of Professor Wilson. Edited by his Son -in -Law, Professor FERRIER. 12 vols. crown 8vo, 2, 8s. Christopher in his Sporting-Jacket. 2 vols., 8s. Isle of Palms, City of the Plague, and other Poems. 4s. Lights and Shadows of Scottish Life, and other Tales. 4s. Essays, Critical and Imaginative. 4 vols., 16s. The Noctes Ambrosianse. 4 vols., 16s. Homer and his Translators, and the Greek Drama. Crown 8vo, 4s. WORSLEY. Homer's Odyssey. Translated into English Verse in the Spenserian Stanza. By PHILIP STANHOPE WORSLEY, M.A. New and Cheaper Edition. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. net. Homer's Iliad. Translated by P. S. Worsley and Prof. Con- ington. 2 vols. crown 8vo, 21s. YATE. England and Russia Face to Face in Asia. A Record of Travel with the Afghan Boundary Commission. By Captain A. C. YATE, Bombay Staff Corps. 8vo, with Maps and Illustrations, 21s. YATE. Northern Afghanistan; or, Letters from the Afghan Boundary Commission. By Major C. E. YATE, C.S.I., C.M.G., Bombay Staff Corps, F.R.G.S. 8vo, with Maps, 18s. YULE. Fortification : For the use of Officers in the Army, and Readers of Military History. By Colonel YULE, Bengal Engineers. 8vo, with Numerous Illustrations, 10s. 9/97. OF THE TTTTTVF.RSITY THIS BOOK IS DUE ON THE LAST DATE STAMPED BELOW AN INITIAL FINE OF 25 CENTS WILL BE ASSESSED FOR FAILURE TO RETURN THIS BOOK ON THE DATE DUE. THE PENALTY WILL INCREASE TO SO CENTS ON THE FOURTH DAY AND TO $1.OO ON .THE SEVENTH DAY OVERDUE. 27 1933 APR 2 2 1953 29AP'54HK 1954 L LD 21-50m-l,'33