REESE LIBRARY ; 1 1 1-: UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS " Nach cwigcn, chrnen, Grossen Gesetzen Miisscn wir alle Unseres Dascins Kreise vollenden. Nur allein der Mcnsch Vermag das Unmogliche; Er unterschcidct, Wahlet und richtet; Er kann dcm Augenbliclc Dauer verleihen. Er allein darf Den Guten loknen, Den Bosen strafen, Heilen und retten ; AUes Irrende, Schweifendc Nutzlich verbinden." GOETHE, "Das Gottliche. MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS AND OTHER ESSAYS BY ANDREW SETH, M.A., LL.D. (i PROFESSOR OF LOGIC AND METAPHYSICS IN THE UNIVERSITY OF EDINBURGH WILLIAM BLACKWOOD AND SONS EDINBURGH AND LONDON MDCCCXCVII 3 3 M3 76 PREFACE. THE title of this volume may seem disproportioned to its contents. A systematic discussion of "man's place in the cosmos " would obviously involve the whole range of science and of metaphysics. These essays make no pretence to be such a discussion. Nevertheless it is not unadvisedly that the title of the first paper has been extended to the volume as a whole, and thus used to indicate the general char- acter of its contents. The papers of which it is com- posed were written within the last six years, and are, in the first instance, a criticism of some of the more significant contributions to philosophy which have ap- peared during that period. They cannot, therefore, be taken as a series, in which there is a systematic progress from the earlier essays to those which follow. Vi PREFACE. But it will be found that they are all, at bottom, treat- ments of the same theme, man's relation to the forces of nature and to the absolute ground of things, or, in the words of the title, man's place in the cosmos. The books or pamphlets criticised were originally selected for criticism because of their bearing upon this funda- mental question, in which all vital interest in philoso- phy centres. And whatever the starting-point of the discussion may be, the main concern of every essay is to enforce the same view of the world and of man. That view I have described in one of the papers as humanism, in opposition to naturalism; in another reference, it might be described as ethicism, in opposi- tion to a too narrow intellectualism. Man as rational, and, in virtue of self-conscious reason, the free shaper of his own destiny, furnishes us, I contend, with our only indefeasible standard of value, and our clearest light as to the nature of the divine. He does what science, occupied only with the laws of events, and speculative metaphysics, when it surrenders itself to the exclusive guidance of the intellect, alike find un- intelligible, and are fain to pronounce impossible he acts. As Goethe puts it in a seeming paradox, Man alone achieves the impossible. But inexplicable, in a PREFACE. Vll sense, as man's personal agency is nay, the one per- petual miracle it is nevertheless our surest datum and our only clue to the mystery of existence. This position is maintained in several of the essays against the lower monism of the naturalistic systems. In the long essay entitled "A New Theory of the Absolute," it is defended against the Spinozism which permeates Mr Bradley's statement of metaphysical monism. This essay emphasises, on the one hand, the necessary limitations of human insight and, on the other hand, the validity or practical truth of our human rendering of the divine. Such a view of the cosmos must rest ultimately, I think, upon a conviction of the absolute value of the ethical life. For there is no such thing as a philosophy without assumptions. Every idealistic theory of the world has for its ultimate pre- miss a logically unsupported judgment of value a judgment which affirms an end of intrinsic worth, and accepts thereby a standard of unconditional obligation. On account of this unity of contention, the essays have been brought together, in the hope that they may serve a useful purpose. The paper on Professor Hux- ley's " Evolution and Ethics " appeared in ' Blackwood's Magazine/ three of the others in the 'Contemporary Vlll PEEFACE. Keview,' and the short paper on " The Use of the Term ' Naturalism,' " in the ' Philosophical Eeview.' To the editors and proprietors of these Keviews I am indebted for their courtesy in sanctioning this republication. The essays are republished without substantial alter- ation, but I have availed myself of the opportunity of revision, and have also reinserted a few passages which had been omitted, in order to bring the treatment within the ordinary compass of re view -articles. The second part of the essay on " The ' New ' Psychology and Automatism," though written in 1892 as an integral part of the discussion, is now printed for the first time. It gives the question a wider range, and will be found, I hope, to make the treatment more com- plete. Mechanism in physiology, " presentationism " in psychology, materialism and sheer pantheism in philosophy, may be regarded as different aspects of the same preconception the denial of the presence of a real cause at any point in the sequence of events. I desire in conclusion to express my thanks to my colleague, M. Charles Sarolea, for his kindness in read- ing the proofs and making many helpful suggestions. UNIVERSITY OF EDINBURGH, February 1897. CONTENTS, MAN S PLACE IN THE COSMOS PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN ... 1 THE PRESENT POSITION OF THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES AN INAUGURAL LECTURE, OCTOBER 1891 ... 34 THE " NEW " PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM (a) MUNSTERBERG'S ANALYSIS OF WILL ... 64 (6) KNOWLEDGE AND ACTIVITY . . . .114 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE MR BRADLEY'S ' APPEARANCE AND REALITY ' . . 129 MR BALFOUR AND HIS CRITICS . . . .226 NOTE A. THE USE OF THE TERM "NATURALISM" . . 289 NOTE B. THE LEGITIMACY OF THE ARGUMENT FROM CON- SEQUENCES . 304 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. pEOFESSOE HUXLEY'S Eomanes Lecture .on -*- " Evolution and Ethics " deservedly attracted a large amount of attention on its appearance. That attention was due not only to the importance of the subject handled and the reputation of the lecturer, but quite as much to the breadth and scope of the treatment, to the nobility of tone and the deep human feeling which characterised a singularly impressive utterance. Popular interest was also excited by the nature of the conclusion reached, which, in the mouth of the pioneer and prophet of evolution, had the air of being something like a palinode. Criticisms of the lecture appeared at the time by Mr Leslie Stephen in the ' Contemporary Eeview/ and by Mr Herbert 2 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. Spencer in a letter to the ' Athenaeum ' ; l and many discussions appeared in theological quarters. But the subject as a whole was pediaps dismissed from public attention before its significance had been exhausted, or indeed properly grasped. Professor Huxley's argu- ment and the criticisms it called forth illuminate most instructively some deep -seated ambiguities of philo- sophical terminology, and at the same time bring into sharp relief the fundamental difference of standpoint which divides philosophical thinkers. The questions at issue, moreover, are not merely speculative ; already they cast their shadow upon literature and life. The opportunity of elucidation is therefore in the best sense timely, and no apology seems needed for an attempt to recall attention to the points in dispute and to ac- centuate their significance. The outstanding feature of Professor Huxley's argu- ment is the sharp contrast drawn between nature and ethical man, and the sweeping indictment of " the cosmic process " at the bar of morality. The problem of suffering and the almost complete absence of any 1 The Eomanes Lecture was delivered on the 18th May 1893, and published shortly thereafter. Mr Spencer's letter appeared in the * Athenaeum ' of August 5, and Mr Leslie Stephen's article in the ' Con- temporary Keview ' of August 1893. The present paper was published in 'Blackwood's Magazine,' December 1893. PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 3 relation between suffering and moral desert is the theme from which he starts, and to which he con- tinually returns. " The dread problem of evil," " the moral indifference of nature," " the unfathomable in- justice of the nature of things " this is the aspect of the world which has burned itself deeply into the writer's soul, and which speaks in moving eloquence from his pages. The Buddhistic and the Stoic at- tempts to grapple with the problem are considered, and are found to end alike in absolute renunciation. " By the Tiber, as by the Ganges, ethical man admits that the cosmos is too strong for him ; and, destroying every bond which ties him to it by ascetic discipline, he seeks salvation in absolute renunciation " (p. 29). Is the antagonism, then, final and hopeless, or can modern science and philosophy offer any better re- conciliation of ethical man with the nature to which as an animal he belongs, and to whose vast uncon- scious forces he lies open on every side ? As Pro- fessor Huxley puts the question himself in his open- ing pages Is there or is there not " a sanction for morality in the ways of the cosmos " ? Man has built up " an artificial world within the cosmos " : has human society its roots and its justification in the underlying nature of the cosmos, or is it in 4 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. very truth an " artificial " world, which is at odds with that nature and must be in perpetual conflict with it ? The Stoic rule -which places virtue in " fol- lowing nature" is easily shown to be a phrase of many meanings, and to demand qualification by refer- ence, first, to the specific nature of man, and then to a higher nature or guiding faculty within the mind of man himself. But the modern ethics of evolution apparently claim to have bridged the gulf and to have made the ethical process continuous with the cosmic process of organic nature, they claim, in short, to exhibit the ethical life as only a continuation, on another plane, of the struggle for existence. If this claim is well founded, and the two worlds are really continuous, then the maxim, " Follow nature," will have been proved to be, after all, the sum and sub- stance of virtue. It is against this naturalisation of ethics that Pro- fessor Huxley protests in the strongest terms. He readily allows that the ethical evolutionists may be right in their natural history of the moral sentiments. But " as the immoral sentiments have no less been evolved, there is, so far, as much natural sanction for the one as the other. . . . Cosmic evolution may teach us how the good and the evil tendencies of man may PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 5 have come about; but, in itself, it is incompetent to furnish any better reason why what we call good is preferable to what we call evil, than we had before " (p. 31). That is to say, the origin of a belief and the validity of a belief, or the origin of a tendency and the ethical quality of that tendency, are logically two dis- tinct questions. But the evolutionist is apt to make the answer to the first do duty as an answer to the second also, because he has in reality no standard of appreciation to apply to any phenomenon except that of mere existence. " Whatever is, is right," or at all events, " Whatever is predominant, is right," is the only motto of the consistent evolutionist. This is embodied in the phrase " survival of the fittest," which is used illegitimately, as we shall see to effect the transition from the merely natural to the ethical world. In opposition to such theories, Professor Huxley con- tends that the analogies of the struggle for existence throw no light on the ethical nature of man. Cosmic nature is no school of virtue, but the headquarters of the enemy of ethical nature (p. 27). Self-assertion, the unscrupulous seizing upon all that can be grasped, the tenacious holding of all that can be kept, . . . constitute the essence of the struggle for existence. . . . For his suc- cessful progress as far as the savage state, man has been 6 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. largely indebted to those qualities which he shares with the ape and the tiger (p. 6). So far is this struggle from explaining morality that the practice of what is ethically best what we call good- ness or virtue involves a course of conduct which, in all respects, is opposed to that which leads to success in the cosmic struggle for existence. In place of ruthless self- assertion, it demands self-restraint; in place of thrusting aside, or treading down, all competitors, it requires that the individual shall not merely respect, but shall help, his fellows. ... It repudiates the gladiatorial theory of ex- istence. . . . Laws and moral precepts are directed to the end of curbing the cosmic process and reminding the individual of his duty to the community, to the protection and influence of which he owes, if not existence itself, at least the life of something better than a brutal savage. In short, "social progress means a checking of the cosmic process at every step, and the substitution for it of another which may be called the ethical process." This leads up to the characteristic call to arms with which the address concludes : " Let us understand, once for all, that the ethical progress of society depends, not on imitating the cosmic process, still less in running away from it, but in combating it" (pp. 33, 34). Such is the logical framework of the lecture. It is obvious that the important points of the treat- PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 7 merit are : (1) The emphasis laid upon the division between man and nature, which a reviewer in the ' Athenseum ' 1 called " an approximation to the Paul- ine dogma of nature and grace " : and (2) the mood of militant heroism, not untouched, however, by stoi- cal resignation, which naturally results from contem- plation of the unequal struggle between the microcosm and the macrocosm. Before proceeding to consider the consistency of Professor Huxley's argument and the ultimate ten- ability of his position, I wish to say, in regard to the first point, how timely, it seems to me, is his insistence on the gulf between man and non -human nature ; how sound is the stand he takes upon the ethical nature of man as that which is alone of sig- nificance and worth in the "transitory adjustment of contending forces," which otherwise constitutes the cosmos. Whether the breach is to be taken as abso- lute or not, it is at least apparent that if man with his virtues and vices be included simpliciter and with- out more ado in a merely natural order of facts, we inevitably tend to lose sight of that nature within na- ture which makes man what he is. The tendency so to include man has become a settled habit in much of 1 July 22, 1893. 8 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. our current literature. I need not speak of the docu- ments of so-called Naturalism, with their never-end- ing analysis of la bte Jmmaine analysis from which one would be slow to gather that any such qualities as justice, purity, or disinterested affection had ever disturbed the brutish annals of force and lust. But in other quarters, even where the picture is not so dark, the fashion still is to treat man as a natural product, not as the responsible shaper of his destiny, but, void of spiritual struggles and ideal hopes, as the unresisting channel of the impulses which sway him hither and thither, and issue now in one course of action, now in another. This literature is inartistic, even on its own terms, for, blinded by its material- istic fatalism, it does not even give us things as they are. The higher literature never forgets that man, as Pascal put it, is nobler than the universe ; and freedom (in some sense of that ambiguous term) must be held to be a postulate of true art no less than of morality. But besides being bad art, litera- ture of this sort has a subtly corrosive influence upon the ethical temper. For the power of will, as Lamen- nais said, is that in us which is most quickly used up : " Ce qui s'use le plus vite en nous, c'est la volonte." Hence the insidious force of the sugges- PROFESSOK HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 9 tion that we do not will at all, but are merely the instruments of our desires. For this is to justify, or at least to excuse, every passion on the ground of its "natural" origin. This temper of mind is found invading even more serious writers, and it is traceable ultimately to the same confusion between the laws of human conduct and the workings of nature in the irresponsible creatures of the field. M. Eenan, it will be remembered, delicately excuses himself in his ' Souvenirs ' rallies himself, as we may say on his continued practice of chastity : I continued to live in Paris as I had lived in the semi- nary. Later, I saw very well the vanity of that virtue as of all the rest. I recognised in particular that nature cares not at all whether man is chaste or not. I cannot rid my- self [he says elsewhere in the same volume] of the idea that after all it is perhaps the libertine who is right, and who practises the true philosophy of life. Many will remember, too, how Matthew Arnold took up this parable when he discoursed in America 011 the cult of the great goddess Lubricity, to which, as he said, contemporary France seemed more and more to be devoting herself. After much delicate banter and much direct plain-speaking, Mr Arnold turns upon M. Eenan and cuts to the root of the fallacy in a single sentence. " Instead of saying that 10 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. nature cares nothing about chastity, let us say that human nature, our nature, cares about it a great deal." And when we meet the same fallacy invad- ing our own literature, the same answer will suffice. I think it may be worth pointing out a notable in- stance in a novel widely read and highly praised within the last few years. Mr Hardy's ' Tess of the D'Urbervilles ' is unquestionably a powerful work, but it suffers, in my opinion, both artistically and ethically, from this tendency to assimilate the moral and the natural. To smack of the soil is in many senses a term of praise ; but even rustic men and women are not altogether products of the soil, and Mr Hardy is in danger of so regarding them. What I wish, however, to point out here is the pernicious fallacy which underlies a statement like the follow- ing. Tess, after she has fallen from her innocence, is wont to wander alone in the woods, a prey to her own reflections, "terrified without reason," says the author, by "a cloud of moral hobgoblins." It was they [he continues] that were out of harmony with the actual world, not she. Walking among the sleep- ing birds in the hedges, watching the skipping rabbits on a moonlit warren, or standing under a pheasant-laden bough, she looked upon herself as a figure of guilt intruding into the haunts of innocence. But all the while she was making PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 11 a distinction where there was no difference. Feeling her- self in antagonism, she was quite in accord. She had been made to break an accepted social law, but no law known to the environment in which she fancied herself such an anomaly. The implication of such a passage is that the "ac- cepted social law " is a mere convention, and that the deeper truth, "the actual world," is to be found in the hedgerows and the warrens. To satisfy an animal prompting without scruple or hesitation, and without the qualms of a fantastical remorse, is only to fulfil the law of nature, and to put one's self in harmony with one's surroundings. The shallow- ness of such revolt against "accepted social laws" is too apparent to need further exposure. A con- vention truly, in one sense, the moral law in ques- tion is ; but upon this convention the fabric of human society and all the sanctities of the family rest. He must be strangely blinded by a word who deems this sanction insufficient, or who would pit in such a case a " natural " impulse against a " social " law. In view of pervasive misconceptions and fallacies like these, it is eminently salutary, I repeat, to have our attention so impressively recalled by Professor Huxley to the idea of human life as an imperium OF THB UNIVERSITY 12 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. in imperio a realm which, though it rises out of nature, and remains exposed to the shock of natural forces, requires for its laws no foreign sanction, but bases them solely on the perfection of human nature itself. For, even though Professor Huxley's way of stating the opposition should prove ultimately unten- able, the breach between ethical man and pre-human nature constitutes without exception the most im- portant fact which the universe has to show ; and for a true understanding of the world it is far more vital to grasp the significance of this breach than to be misled by a cheap desire for unity and system into minimising, or even denying, the fact. It is time, however, to examine Professor Huxley's position and arguments more closely. His critics have not been slow to remark upon the ambiguity lurking in the phrase " cosmic process," which occurs so often throughout the lecture, in antithesis to the ethical process to the moral and social life of man. And they point with one accord to Note 19 as containing, in effect, a retractation of his own doctrine by Professor Huxley himself. " Of course, strictly speaking," we read in the note, " social life and the ethical process, in virtue of which it advances towards perfection, are part and parcel of the general process of evolution." As Mr PEOFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 13 Spencer pointedly asks, " If the ethical man is not a product of the cosmic process, what is he a product of ? " Or as Shakespeare expressed it in the often- quoted lines " Nature is made better by no means But nature makes that means : so, o'er that art, Which you say adds to nature, is an art That nature makes." If the cosmic process be understood in the full latitude of the phrase, this is, indeed, so obvious, and the critic's victory so easy, that it is hard to believe Professor Huxley's position rests altogether on a foundation so weak. The term " nature," and still more an expres- sion like " the cosmic process," may be taken in an all- inclusive sense as equivalent to the universe as a whole or the nature of things ; and if so, it is obvious that human nature with its ethical characteristics is em- braced within the larger whole. The unity of the cosmos in some sense is not so much a conclusion to be proved as an inevitable assumption. Professor Huxley apparently denies this unity in the text of his lecture, and is naturally obliged to reassert it in his note. This constitutes the weakness of his position. The part must be somehow included in the process of the whole ; there is no extra-cosmic source from which 14 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. a revolt against the principles of the cosmos could draw inspiration or support. Now the strength of the evolutionary theory of ethics lies in its frank recognition of the unity of the cosmos ; and in this it is, so far, at one with the philosophical doctrine of Idealism to which it is otherwise so much opposed the doctrine which finds the ultimate reality of the universe in mind or spirit, and its End in the perfecting of spiritual life. But each of these theories exhibits the unity of the world in its own way. The way taken by the ethical evolutionists is to naturalise morality, to assimilate ethical experience to nature, in the lower or narrower sense in which it is used to denote all that happens in the known world except the responsible activities of human beings. And it is against this removing of landmarks that Professor Huxley, rightly, as it seems to me, protests. For though Mr Spencer and Mr Leslie Stephen may be technically in the right, inasmuch as human nature is unquestionably part of the nature of things, it is the inherent tendency of their theories to substitute for this wider nature the laws and processes of that narrower, non-human world, to which the term nature is on the whole restricted by current usage. This tendency is inherent in every system which PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 15 takes as its sole principle of explanation the carrying back of facts or events to their antecedent conditions. And, as it happens, this is explicitly formulated by Mr Stephen, in his article in the ' Contemporary Eeview,' as the only permissible meaning of explanation : " To 'explain' a fact is to assign its causes that is, give the preceding set of facts out of which it arose." But surely, I may be asked, you do not intend to challenge a principle which underlies all scientific procedure, and which may even claim to be self-evident ? I certainly do not propose to deny the formal correctness of the principle, but I maintain most strongly that the cur- rent application of it covers a subtle and very serious fallacy, for the true nature of the cause only becomes apparent in the effect. Now, if we explain a fact by giving " the preceding set of facts out of which it arose," we practically resolve the fact into these ante- cedents that is to say, we identify it with them. When we are dealing with some limited sphere of phenomena, within which the facts are all of one order say, the laws of moving bodies as treated in mechanics there may be no practical disadvantage from this limited in- terpretation of causation. But when we pass from one order of facts to another say, from the inorganic to the organic, or, still more, from animal life to the self- 16 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. conscious life of man the inadequacy of such explana- tion stares us in the face. For " the preceding set of facts," which we treat as the cause or sufficient explan- ation of the phenomenon in question, is ex hypothesi different from the phenomenon it is said to explain ; and the difference is, that it consists of simpler ele- ments. To explain, according to this view, is to reduce to simpler conditions. But if the elements are really simpler, there is the fact of their combination into a more complex product to be explained, and the fact of their combination in such a way as to produce precisely the result in question. And if we choose to take the antecedent conditions, as they appear in themselves, apart from the all-important circumstance of the pro- duction of this effect, we have, no doubt, a " preceding set of facts/' but we certainly have not, in any true sense, the cause of the phenomenon. We have elimi- nated the very characteristic we set out to explain namely, the difference of the new phenomenon from the antecedents out of which it appears to have been evolved. Hence it is that, in the sense indicated, all explanation of the higher by the lower is philosophically a hysteron proteron. The antecedents assigned are not the causes of the consequents ; for by antecedents the naturalistic theories mean the antecedents in abstraction PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 17 from their consequents the antecedents taken as they appear in themselves, or as we might suppose them to be if no such consequents had ever issued from them. So conceived, however, the antecedents (matter and energy, for example) have no real existence they are mere entia rationis, abstract aspects of the one concrete fact which we call the universe. The true nature of the antecedents is only learned by reference to the consequents which follow ; or, as I put it before, the true nature of the cause only becomes apparent in the effect. All ultimate or philosophical explanation must look to the end. Hence the futility of all attempts to explain human life in terms of the merely animal, to explain life in terms of the inor- ganic, and ultimately to find a sufficient formula for the cosmic process in terms of the redistribution of matter and motion. If we are in earnest with the doctrine that the universe is one, we have to read back the nature of the latest consequent into the remotest antecedent. Only then is the one, in any true sense, the cause of the other. Applying this to the present question, we may say that, just as within the limits of the organic world there may be exhibited an intelligible evolution of living forms, so within the moral world we may B 18 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. certainly have an evolution of the moral sentiments and of the institutions which subserve ethical conduct. But as, in the one case, we must start with the fact of life that is to say, with the characteristic ways of behaving which are found in living matter and which are not found in dead matter so, in the other case, we must carry with us from the outset the charac- teristics or postulates of moral experience namely, self-consciousness, with the sense of responsibility, and the capacity for sympathy which is based on the ability to represent to one's self the life and feelings of another. Such an evolution within the moral sphere does not justify us in presenting morality as an " evolu- tion " from non-moral conditions that is, in resolving morality into non-moral elements. And this Mr Leslie Stephen seems to admit in an important passage of the article already referred to. " Morality proper," he says, " begins when sympathy begins ; when we really desire the happiness of others, or, as Kant says, when we treat other men as an end, and not simply as a means. Undoubtedly this involves a new principle no less than the essential principle of all true morality." I cannot but regard this as an important admission, but at the same time I am bound to say that, till I met this unexpected sentence of Mr Stephen's, I had supposed PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 19 that the admission of " a new principle " was precisely what the evolutionists were, of all things, most anxious to avoid. It seems to me, therefore, that though Professor Huxley may have put himself technically in the wrong by speaking of " the cosmical process," his contention is far from being so inept as a verbal criticism would make it appear. It is really directed against the sub- mergence of ethical man in the processes of non-ethical and non-human nature ; and if any justification is to be sought for the use of the phrase, we may find it in the tendency inherent in the evolutionary method of explanation the tendency already explained to sub- stantiate antecedents in abstraction from their conse- quents, and thus practically to identify the cosmos with its lowest aspects. If the evolutionists do not make this identification in their own minds, they are at least singularly successful in producing that impres- sion upon their readers. On another important point connected with, and indeed involved in, the foregoing, Professor Huxley, by an unguarded statement, laid himself open to a pretty obvious and apparently conclusive rejoinder. "The cosmic process," he says in one place, "has no sort of relation to moral ends." But " the moral indif- 20 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. ference of nature," even in the restricted sense of the term, cannot be maintained so absolutely. Nature undoubtedly puts a premium upon certain virtues, and punishes certain modes of excess and defect by decrease of vitality and positive pain. As Mr Stephen says : " That chastity, temperance, truthfulness, and energy are on the whole advantages both to the individual and the race does not, I fancy, require elaborate proof, nor need I argue at length that the races in which they are common will therefore have inevitable advantages in the struggle for existence." But if so, then it would seem that cosmic nature is not, as it was represented, "the headquarters of the enemy of ethical nature " ; to a certain extent it may even be regarded as a " school of virtue." The sphere, however, in which this holds true is a comparatively limited one, being substantially restricted to temper- ance, in the Greek sense of the word that is to say, moderation in the indulgence of the animal appetites, to which may, no doubt, be added, with Mr Stephen, energy. But nature, as distinct from that human nature which organises itself into societies and adds its own sanctions to the moral ideal which it is con- tinually widening and deepening non-human nature seems to have no sanctions even for such fundamental PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 21 virtues as truthfulness, justice, and beneficence, still less for the finer shades and higher nobilities of char- acter in which human nature flowers. And even in regard to the list of virtues cited, it might be argued that cosmic nature sanctions and furthers them only when we deliberately restrict our survey to the present stage of the evolutionary process the stage during which man has grown to be what he is on this planet. Within this limited period nature, through the struggle for existence, may be said to have favoured the evolu- tion of the morally best. But it is no intrinsic quality of the struggle to produce this result. Here, it appears to me, we strike upon the deeper truth which prompted Professor Huxley's somewhat unguarded statement, and we are under an important obligation to him for the exposure of what he appropriately calls " the fallacy of the fittest." Fittest [he writes] has a connotation of " best " ; and about best there hangs a moral flavour. In cosmic nature, however, what is "fittest" depends upon the conditions. Long since, I ventured to point out that if our hemisphere were to cool again, the survival of the fittest might bring about, in the vegetable kingdom, a population of more and more stunted and humbler and humbler organisms, until the "fittest" that survived might be nothing but lichens, diatoms, and such microscopic organisms as those which give red snow its colour; while, if it became hotter, the 22 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. pleasant valleys of the Thames and Isis might be unin- habitable by any animated beings save those that nourish in a tropical jungle. They,- as the fittest, the best adapted to the changed conditions, would survive (p. 32). Mr Spencer has been forward to emphasise his agree- ment with this position, and has recalled attention to an essay of his own, twenty years old. in which he makes the same distinction: The law is not the survival of the "better" or the " stronger," if we give to these words anything like their ordinary meanings. It is the survival of those which are constitutionally fittest to thrive under the conditions in which they are placed ; and very often that which, humanly speaking, is inferiority, causes the survival. Superiority, whether in size, strength, activity, or sagacity, is, other things equal, at the cost of diminished fertility ; and where the life led by a species does not demand these higher attributes, the species profits by decrease of them, and accompanying increase of fertility. This is the reason why there occur so many cases of retrograde metamorphosis. . . . When it is remembered that these cases outnumber all others, it will be seen that the expression " survivorship of the better " is wholly inappropriate. 1 Out of the mouth of two such witnesses this point may be taken as established. But if so, I entirely fail to see where, on naturalistic principles, we get our standard of higher and lower, of better and worse. 1 Essays, vol. i. p. 379, " Mr Martineau on Evolution." PKOFESSOK HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 23 If changed conditions of life were to lead to the de- humanising of the race, to the dropping one by one of the ethical qualities which we are accustomed to commend, whence the justification for pronouncing this process a " retrograde metamorphosis " ? There can be no other sense of better or worse, on the theory, than more or less successful adaptation to the con- ditions of the environment, and what survives is best just because it survives. The latest stage of the process must necessarily, therefore, be better than all that went before, from the mere fact that it has maintained itself. Mere existence is the only test we have to apply, and at every stage it would seem that we are bound to say, Whatever is, is right. But this is tantamount to saying that, when the theory of evolution is taken in its widest scope, it is not really legitimate to say that nature abets or sanctions morality; since the result of further evolution or, to speak more properly, of further cosmical changes might be to dethrone our present ethical conduct from its temporary position as the fittest, and to leave no scope for what we now regard as virtue. The k type of conduct which would then succeed, and which would so far have the sanction of nature on its side, we should be con- strained, it seems to me, to pronounce superior to 24 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. the conduct which, from our present point of view, seems to us better ; because the latter, if adopted, would in the altered circumstances set us at variance with our surroundings, and so fail. Failure or success in the struggle for existence must, on the theory, be the sole moral standard. Good is what survives ; evil is what once was fittest, but is so no longer. Thus, our present good may become nay, is inevitably be- coming evil, and that not, as might be contended, in the sense of merging in a higher good. We have no guarantee that the movement of change, miscalled evolution, must continue in the line of past progress : it may gradually, and as it were imperceptibly, assume another direction a direction which our present moral ideas would condemn as retrograde. Yet, none the less, the mere fact of change would be sufficient to convert our present good into evil. Such, I must insist, is the only logical position of a naturalistic ethics. But an important outcome of the recent discussion has been to show that the most prominent upholders of the theory do not hold it in its logical form. Mr Spencer, as we have seen, has strongly insisted that survival of the fittest does not mean survival of the better, or even of the stronger ; and Mr Stephen tells us that the struggle for existence, PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 25 instead of being the explanation of morality, " belongs to an underlying order of facts to which moral epithets cannot properly be applied. It denotes a condition of which the moralist has to take account, and to which morality has to be adapted, but which, just because it is a ' cosmic process/ cannot be altered, however much we may alter the conduct which it dictates." Surely this comes very near to admitting Professor Huxley's contention, that our moral standard is not derived from the struggle for existence, but rather implies its reversal, substituting for selfishness sympathy for others, and, in Mr Stephen's own words, "the sense of duty which each man owes to society at large." Mr Spencer speaks of an " ethical check " upon the struggle for existence: it is our duty, he says, " to mitigate the evils " which it entails in the social state. " The use of morality," says Mr Stephen, "is to humanise the struggle, to minimise the suffer- ings of those who lose the game, and to offer the prizes to the qualities which are advantageous to all, rather than to those which serve to intensify the bitterness of the conflict." But this is neither more nor less than to say that, as soon as man becomes social and moral, he has to act counter to the leading characteristics of the struggle for existence. He becomes animated by 26 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. other ideals, or, to speak more strictly, he then first be- comes capable of an ideal, of a sense of duty, instead of obeying without question- the routine of animal impulse. But if this is so, I still ask the evolutionist who has no other basis than the struggle for existence, how he accounts for the intrusion of these moral ideas and standards which presume to interfere with the cosmic process, and sit in judgment upon its results ? This question cannot be answered so long as we regard morality merely as an incidental result, a by-product, as it were, of the cosmical system. It is impossible on such a hypothesis to understand the magisterial assertion by itself of the part against the whole, its demands upon the universe, its unwavering condem- nation of the universe, if these demands are not met by the nature of things. All this would be an in- congruous, and even a ludicrous, spectacle if we had here to do with a natural phenomenon like any other. The moral and spiritual life remains, in short, unin- telligible, unless on the supposition that it is in reality the key to the world's meaning, the fact in the light of which all other phenomena must be read. We must be in earnest, I have already said, with the unity of the world, but we must not forget that, if regarded merely as a system of forces, the world possesses no such PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 27 unity. It acquires it only when regarded in the light of an End of absolute worth or value which is realised or attained in it. Such an End-in-itself, as Kant called it, we find only in the self-conscious life of man, in the world of Truth, Beauty, and Goodness which he builds up for himself, and of which he constitutes himself a citizen. If it were possible to consider the system of physical nature apart from the intelligent activities and emotions of rational beings, those worlds on worlds, " Rolling ever From creation to decay," would possess in themselves no spark of the value, the intrinsic worth, which we unhesitatingly assert to belong, at least in possibility, to the meanest human life. The endless redistribution of matter and motion in stupendous cycles of evolution and dissolution would be a world without any justification to offer for its existence a world which might just as well not have been. 1 But if we are honest with ourselves, I do not 1 Without encumbering the main argument by inopportune discus- sion; one may perhaps ask in a note in what sense even existence could be attributed to a system of unconscious forces a material world per se. We cannot perform the abstraction required of us in conceiving such a system. Nature refuses to be divorced from the thoughts and feelings of her children and her lords, and we need not be subjective idealists to hold the literal truth of ,the poet's words that " in our life alone does Nature live." 28 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. think we can embrace the conclusion that the cosmos is a mere brute fact of this description. The demand for an End-in-itself that is, for a fact of such a nature that its existence justifies itself is as much a necessity of reason as the necessity which impels us to refund any phenomenon into its antecedent con- ditions. And further, unless we sophisticate ourselves, we cannot doubt that we possess within ourselves in our moral experience most conspicuously an in- stance and a standard of what we mean by such intrinsic value. As Carlyle has put it in one of his finest passages, What, then, is man ! What, then, is man ! He endures but for an hour, and is crushed before the moth. Yet in the being and in the working of a faithful man is there already (as all faith, from the beginning, gives assurance) a something that pertains not to this wild death-element of Time ; that triumphs over Time, and is, and will be, when Time shall be no more. This conviction of the infinite significance and value of the ethical life is the only view-point from which, in Professor Huxley's words, we can " make existence intelligible and bring the order of things into harmony with the moral sense of man." And it is impossible to do the one of these things without the other. To understand the world is not merely to unravel the PEOFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 29 sequence of an intricate set of facts. So long as we cannot " bring the order of things into harmony with the moral sense of man," we cannot truly be said to have made existence intelligible: the world still re- mains for us, in Hume's words, " a riddle, an enigma, an inexplicable mystery." What, then, is Professor Huxley's final attitude? The lecture breathes throughout the loftiest temper of ethical idealism. It is the writer's keen sense of the superiority of ethical man to non-ethical nature that prompts him to pit Pascal's "thinking reed" in unequal struggle against the cosmic forces that en- velop him; and the noble words at the close stir the spirit by their impressive insistence on the imperish- able worth of human effort inspired by duty. Yet this unflinching conviction does not lead Professor Huxley to what seems the legitimate conclusion from it namely, that here only, in the life of ethical en- deavour, is the end and secret of the universe to be found. It serves but to accentuate the stern pathos of his view of human fate. His ultimate attitude is, theoretically, one of Agnosticism; personally and practically, one of Stoical heroism. Substantially the same attitude, it appears to me, is exemplified in the Pieligion of Humanity the same despair, I mean, of 30 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. harmonising human ideals with the course of the universe. The Religion of Humanity rightly finds in man alone any qualities which call for adoration or worship ; but it inconsistently supposes man to de- velop these qualities in a fundamentally non-ethical cosmos, and so fails to furnish a solution that can be accounted either metaphysically satisfying or ethically supporting. But we must bear in mind, I repeat, the principle of the unity of the world. The attitude of the -Agnostic and the Positivist is due to the separa- tion which they unconsciously insist on keeping up between nature and man. The temptation to do so is intelligible, for we have found that nature, taken in philosophical language as a thing in itself nature conceived as an independent system of causes cannot explain the ethical life of man, and we rightly refuse to blur and distort the characteristic features of moral experience by submerging it in the merely natural. We easily, therefore, continue to think of the system of natural causes as a world going its own way, ex- isting quite independently of the ethical beings who draw their breath within it. Man with his ideal standards and his infinite aspirations appears conse- quently upon the scene as an alien without rights in a world that knows him not. His life is an unex- PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 31 plained intrusion in a world organised on other prin- ciples, and no way adapted as a habitation for so disturbing and pretentious a guest. And the conse- quence is that he dashes his spirit against the steep crags of necessity, finds his ideals thwarted, his aspira- tions mocked, his tenderest affections turned to instru- ments of agony, and is driven, if not into passionate revolt or nerveless despair, then at best into stoical resolve. Some such mood as this appears also in much of Matthew Arnold's poetry, and is to my mind the explanation of its insistent note of sadness. " No, we are strangers here, the world is from of old, . . . To tunes we did not call, our being must keep chime." It is powerfully expressed in the famous monologue or chant in " Empedocles on Etna," with its deliberate renunciation of what the poet deems man's " boundless hopes " and " intemperate prayers." It inspires the fine lines to Fausta on " Eesignation," and reappears more incidentally in all his verse. But calm, as he himself reminds us, is not life's crown, though calm is well ; and the poet's " calm lucidity of soul " covers in this case the baffled retreat of the thinker. We have, in truth, no right to suppose an independent non-spiritual world on which human experience is in- 32 MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOS. congruously superinduced. If we are really in earnest, at once with the unity -of the world and with the necessity of an intrinsically worthy end by reference to which existence may be explained, we must take our courage in both hands and carry our convictions to their legitimate conclusion. We must conclude that the end which we recognise as alone worthy of attain- ment is also the end of existence as such the open secret of the universe. No man writes more pessi- mistically than Kant of man's relation to the course of nature, so long as man is regarded merely as a sentient creature, susceptible to pleasure and pain. But man, as the subject of duty, and the heir of immortal hopes, is restored by Kant to that central position in the universe from which, as a merely physical being, Copernicus had degraded him. To a certain extent this conclusion must remain a conviction rather than a demonstration, for we cannot emerge altogether from the obscurities of our middle state, and there is much that may rightly disquiet and perplex our minds. But if it is in the needs of the moral life that we find our deepest principle of explanation, then it may be argued with some reason that this belongs to the nature of the case; for a scientific demonstration would not serve the purposes PROFESSOR HUXLEY ON NATURE AND MAN. 33 of that life. The truly good man must choose good- ness on its own account ; he must be ready to serve God for naught, without being invaded by M. Eenan's doubts. As it has been finely put, he must possess "that rude old Norse nobility of soul, which saw virtue and vice alike go unrewarded, and was yet not shaken in its faith." l This old Norse nobility speaks to us again, in accents of the nineteenth century, in Professor Huxley's lecture. But because such is the temper of true virtue, it by no means follows that such virtue will not be rewarded with "the wages of going on, and not to die." 1 K. L. Stevenson, Preface to 'Familiar Studies of Men and Books.' THE PRESENT POSITION OF THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 1 "VTOU will not find it wonderful if my feelings are deeply stirred in appearing before you to-day for the first time in my new capacity. There is no honour 1 An Inaugural Lecture on assuming the duties of the Chair of Logic and Metaphysics in the University of Edinburgh, October 26, 1891. The Lecture is printed exactly as it was delivered, and the nature of the occasion will perhaps be held to excuse the personal references with which it opens. The general survey of the philosophical field which it undertakes, and the philosophical point of view indicated in the concluding pages, seem to give it a useful place in the present vol- ume. But to prevent misconception, it may be well to append here the Prefatory Note which accompanied it on its original appearance : " The title of this Lecture may seem to promise too much. The Lec- ture does not profess to deal with the circle of the philosophical sciences, but only with the subjects traditionally associated with a Chair of Logic and Metaphysics in Scotland. Moreover, as the occasion demanded, it is addressed not so much to the expert as to the large general public interested in philosophy." PRESENT POSITION OF THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 35 or privilege which I could possibly esteem higher than to teach philosophy in my own alma mater, and in the capital of my native land to teach, moreover, in the Chair which, through the lustre of its occupants for half a century, is, in the mind of the country (I think I may say it without offence) in some respects the most famous of Scottish philosophical Chairs. All this is ^deeply gratifying. But it also lays a heavy responsi- bility upon him who succeeds to such great traditions. He who did not feel diffident at stepping into the place of these eminent men would be unworthy of the trust committed to him. I am deeply sensible of my own deficiencies, but I hope, if it is granted me, to live and learn. It is also a very gratifying experience to join as a colleague those who were the guides of one's youth. All are not here ; but of the seven Professors of the Arts curriculum in my time only two have been re- moved by death. One, the genial and universally beloved Kelland, passed away in the ripeness of his years. The other leaves an untimely gap, which speaks of recent loss and a common sorrow. One whose welcome to-day would have sounded with peculiar pleasantness in my ears, the generous and high-souled Sellar, has gone from us too soon; and 36 THE PRESENT POSITION OF to those who knew him, his loss seems not less but greater as the days go by. All the more is it matter of heartfelt satisfaction to me that no such painful gap exists in connection with my own Chair that I succeed my honoured and be- loved teacher while he is yet among us in full health and in the unimpaired vigour of his powers. Long may he live to counsel us wisely and inspire us by his example, and to embody in literary form the ripe results of a life's reflection. In these circumstances, and in his presence, it is not for me to pronounce any eulogy upon his thirty-five years of strenuous and fruitful work in this university, or to attempt to sum up his happily unfinished achievement. But I will at least record a little of what I personally owe to him. He taught me to think ; and in the things of the mind that is the greatest gift for which one man can be in- debted to another. Seventeen years ago I entered the Junior Logic class of this university, with a mind opening perhaps to literature, but still substantially with a schoolboy's views of existence ; and there, in the admirably stimulating lectures to which I listened, a new world seemed to open before me. What the student most needs at such a period is to be intellectu- ally awakened. The crust of custom has to be broken, THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 37 and the sense of wonder and mystery stirred within him. He should not be crammed with ready-made solutions of difficulties he has never been made to feel. Eather should he be sent "voyaging through strange seas of thought alone." He has to be induced to ask himself the world-old questions, and to ponder the possible answers. Above all, the listener should be made to feel that the questions of which the Professor speaks are not merely information which he communi- cates that they are to him the most real things in the world, the recurring subjects of his deepest meditation. All this his students found realised in Professor Eraser's teaching. His sympathetic exposition enabled us to catch the spirit of the most diverse systems, while his searching criticism prevented us from resting in any of those facile solutions which owe their simplicity to the convenient elimination of intractable elements. The sense of mystery and complexity in things, which he brought so vividly home to us, inspired a wise dis- trust of extreme positions and of systems all too perfect for our mortal vision. This union of dialectical subtlety with a never-failing reverence for all that makes man man, and elevates him above himself, lives in the memory of many a pupil as no unworthy realisation of the ideal spirit of philosophy. I shall count myself 38 THE PRESENT POSITION OF happy if, with his mantle, some portion of his spirit shall be found to have descended upon his successor. I hope that, in the days to come, the dingy but famous class-room will be distinguished as of old by searching intellectual criticism and impartial debate, not divorced from that spirit of reverence and humility which alone can lead us into truth. That reminds me that you will expect to hear from a new Professor some indication of the view he takes of his subject, and of the present outlook in connection with it. Anything that can be said on an occasion like the present must necessarily be of a very general char- acter, but even so it may have a certain interest and usefulness. The discipline of the Chair, then, seems to me to be of a threefold character logical, psychological, and metaphysical or philosophical in the strict sense. That is to say, we study, in the first place, the nature of the reasoning process, or, to be more accurate, the nature of proof or evidence the conditions to which valid reasoning must conform. In the second place, we study, introspectively and otherwise, the pheno- mena of consciousness. We bring observation and experiment to bear upon those internal facts which are THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 39 for each of us the only facts immediately present to us, the facts through which we know all other facts. We try to analyse and lay bare the inmost nature of those functions of knowing, feeling, and willing which lie " closer to us than breathing, nearer than hands or feet," which constitute, in fact, our very life, the ex- pression of the self in time. In the third place, we study, under the title of philosophy proper, the two- fold question of Knowing and Being. On the one hand, we investigate human knowledge as to its con- stitutive notions and its scope or validity ; we discuss the question of the possibility of knowledge, as it is called, or the relation of knowledge to reality. This is what is termed Epistemology or Theory of Knowledge. On the other hand, so far as the discussion has not been already anticipated, we approach those questions as to the ultimate nature, the origin and destiny, of all that is, which have occupied the speculative intellect of mankind from the dawn of history, and will occupy it till its close. These may be embraced under the special title of Metaphysics, both Epistemology and Metaphysics falling under the wider designation of Philosophy. These three lines of training the logical, the psycho- logical, and the philosophical are cognate, and the 40 THE PRESENT POSITION OF first two are in a measure introductory or propaedeutic to the third. Both logic and psychology, at all events, if we go beneath the surface, lead us into the very heart of philosophical difficulties ; and most treatments of either subject involve a tissue of metaphysical as- sumptions, of which the writer is, in all probability, either quite unconscious or only half aware. But though the subjects are thus cognate and continuous, and so fitly combined under one Chair, the discipline they afford has in each case a character of its own. Logic gives a training almost purely abstract or formal, comparable in some respects with the mental discipline of mathematics a training in clearness of thinking, in accuracy of definition, in appreciation of what is meant by demonstration or proof. Psychology brings us face to face with a concrete subject-matter the actual facts of mental life. It views these facts, partly in them- selves, but largely in their connection with material con- ditions and accompaniments. So far as it approaches these facts by the ordinary methods of observation and experiment, classifying them and endeavour- ing to resolve complex phenomena into their simplest constituents or causes, so far it affords a scientific discipline comparable to that gained, say, in the study of one of the natural sciences. And if it often lacks THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 41 the exactness of the sciences of external nature, it has the advantage, as compared with them, of cultivating fresh powers of mind through the attitude of " reflec- tion" or introspection which it is forced to take up. Self-observation or introspection is by no means so easy as the observation of a foreign object. We can more easily analyse a substance in a phial before us than we can analyse the exact nature of what passes at any moment in our own mind. Hence Psychology, which incessantly calls for the exercise of this faculty, and sharpens and perfects it by constant use, was justly praised by Hamilton as one of the best gymnastics of the mind. Philosophy carries us into a more difficult region; for here we deal not with any particular de- partment of fact, but with the ultimate principles of knowledge and the ultimate constitution or meaning of the cosmos as such, including the prior question whether we are justified in speaking of a cosmos or orderly unity at all. These are questions of supreme and intimate concern to us all, seeing that they embrace the question of man's place and destiny in relation to the system of things. He to whom they have no voice must be either less or more than man. And I fail to see how any one can lay claim to a liberal education who is ignorant of what has been thought by the great 42 THE PRESENT POSITION OF minds of the past upon these subjects, or who is un- acquainted with the elements of the problems as they face us to-day. The rudiments of such a knowledge are necessary, were it for nothing else, to enable any one to take an intelligent part in the incessant discus- sion and conflict of opinion which is so marked a feature of the present time. This threefold discipline may be justified, therefore, in a liberal curriculum, whether we look at it, from the formal side, as a discipline of mental powers otherwise untrained as the cultivation of one whole side of human nature or, on the concrete side, as a communi- cation of knowledge of singular importance and inter- est. And its permanent value seems to me so high and unimpeachable, in both these respects, that it needs no defence at my hands. A defence is generally a con- fession of weakness. In offering such for philosophy, " we do it wrong, being so majestical." I turn, therefore, by preference, to say a little about the present outlook in the three departments to which reference has been made, and the way in which it seems to me that a philosophical Professor should shape his work at the present time. Logic I will pass over lightly almost with a word because, of the three, its discussions are most technical in character. THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 43 It appeals, therefore, least to a general audience. More- over, if we penetrate beneath the surface and examine the foundations on which it rests, we are immediately involved in difficult questions of general philosophy; and it becomes impossible to maintain a rigid distinc- tion between Logic and Epistemology and Metaphysics. For that reason the very conception or definition of the science has long been matter of keen debate, and at present the aspect of things is confessedly chaotic. The activity, however, in the higher theory of logic has of late been great both in this country and in Germany. I need only refer to the important treatises of Lotze, Sigwart, and Wundt in Germany, and of Bradley and Bosanquet in this country, not to speak of the more distinctively English work of Jevons, Venn, and others. The chaos, moreover, if at first bewildering, is not of the kind which should be disheartening to the serious student. It is of the kind which portends and accompanies growth, and bears in it the promise of future order. Evidently, however, such discus- sions do not lend themselves to exoteric exposition; they belong to the labours of an advanced class of metaphysics. The other aspect of Logic is the elementary doctrine which has so long formed part of the curriculum of 44 THE PRESENT POSITION OF educated Europe the ordinary formal logic, originally based upon Aristotle, to- which has come to be added some discussion of the theory of scientific method and the conditions of inductive proof. It has been the fashion of late with many philosophers to sneer at the logic of the schools ; but this is only justifiable, as it seems to me, when extravagant claims are made on its behalf. No doubt the ordinary logic depends on many uncriticised assumptions; its analysis of the process of thought is often superficial ; it cannot stand as a coherent philosophical doctrine. All this is granted. The whole discipline is essentially of an elementary and propaedeutic character ; it is a continuation, in a more abstract form, of the grammatical training re- ceived at school. But just this circumstance, that it continues and attaches itself to the studies of the school, gives it a peculiar claim to stand as the gate- way of the philosophical sciences ; whilst, on the other hand, the very defects and ambiguities which dis- cussion reveals in many of its conceptions form an excellent stimulus to the opening mind, and introduce the student insensibly to important psychological and metaphysical problems. The formal mechanism may certainly, in great part, be relegated with advantage to text-book work and tutorial instruction. But even THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 45 this is not to be despised ; I have always found it an admirable test in picking out the really clear-headed members of a class. Here there are no cloudy phrases in which to take refuge ; the issue is as clear and defi- nite as in a mathematical proposition, and inaccuracy of mind is tracked remorselessly down. In view of these merits, which the study undoubtedly possesses, I can- not share the contempt frequently expressed for the logic of the schools. Its names and distinctions, more- over, have entered so largely into the thought, and even the familiar language, of the civilised races, that a certain acquaintance with its forms and processes may well be demanded in the interests of historical culture. It is not so long since a somewhat similar contempt for Psychology was current in the leading idealistic school of this country. The horror of the true-blue experientialist for what he calls " metaphysics " was amply repaid by the tone of condescension and in- difference which the idealists adopted towards "em- pirical psychology." Misled by a name, they visited upon the head of an unoffending science the inade- quacies of Empiricism as a philosophical theory. Be- cause the chief cultivators of psychology in England had been of the Empiricist persuasion, and had fre- 46 THE PRESENT POSITION OF quently confounded the limits of psychology and meta- physics, the transcendentalists tabooed the science as beneath the notice of a philosopher. Hence a state of unnatural division and mutual distrust a distrust rooted in both cases largely in ignorance. To-day the situation is greatly changed. Psychology has become more scientific, and has thereby become more con- scious of her own aims, and, at the same time, of her necessary limitations. Ceasing to put herself forward as philosophy, she has entered upon a new period of development as science ; and in doing so she has disarmed the jealousy, and is even fast con- quering the indifference, of the transcendental philo- sopher. For whatever be the bearing of these psychological investigations upon philosophy be their importance in that connection great, or be it small it is at least certain that in the near future no philosopher will speak with authority, or will deserve so to speak, who does not show a competent acquaintance with the best work in psychology. The marvellous activity displayed just at present in the department of psychology constitutes, indeed, to an expert perhaps the most notable feature in the state of the philosophical sciences. In Germany and France, in America, and now in England, there may THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 47 almost be said to be a " boom " in that direction. In Britain the study of psychology is a native growth, and it had long flourished in the hands of the Associationists, such as Hartley, James and John Mill, and Professor Bain. But before such a school was heard of by name, the works of Hobbes, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume had brilliantly exemplified the national genius in that direction. As already indi- cated, however, the British thinkers of the past were far from keeping their psychology unadulterated. Betraying frequently an insular ignorance of the great metaphysical systems of ancient Greece and modern Europe, they gave us, in general, psychology and philosophy inextricably intermingled. The im- pulse towards a differentiation of provinces came from Germany, where the clearer formulation of aims and methods may be regarded as one beneficial result of the training which the German intellect has enjoyed at the hands of Kant and succeeding thinkers. But the influence of Germany upon psy- chological investigation has not been limited to this formal or methodic stimulus. There has been much good work done there in psychology since the time of Kant. The psychology of Herbart and his fol- lowers is in many respects the more elaborate counter- 48 THE PRESENT POSITION OF part of English Associationism ; and artificial as his constructions often seem,^ it is acute and able work, which no modern student of the subject can afford to neglect. The names of Lotze and Wundt repre- sent work at once brilliant and patient on independent lines, and bring before us also the close connection between psychology and physiology, which is the distinguishing mark of most recent investigation in this department. Some of Lotze's most characteristic work was contained in the book he called 'Medical Psychology ; ' and ' Physiological Psychology ' is the name Wundt gives to his important treatise. Psy- chology, physiology, and physics meet in the great works of Helmholtz on ' Sensations of Tone ' and ' Physiological Optics.' Another mark of recent in- vestigation is the potent influence exerted on psy- chology, as on all other departments of knowledge, by the conception of evolution. Wherever life is met with, there the psychologist now finds material for illustrating and enlarging his science. The old meaning of ^f%?) has been revived, and the begin- nings of a comparative psychology have come into being. The observation of abnormal mental develop- ments, such as insanity, hysteria, the hypnotic state, and similar phenomena, forms another field assiduously THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 49 cultivated by modern observers, especially in France, where, no less than in Germany and America, there is a large amount of psychological activity among the younger men. All these influences may be said to meet and come to fruition in the best English work of the last few years such work, I mean, as Mr Ward's masterly treatise in the ' Encyclopaedia Britannica,' and the rich and stimulating volumes published a year ago 1 by Professor James of Harvard. Such work may not unreasonably be taken as marking the new departure that has been achieved in psychology the critical maintenance of a purely psychological standpoint, the wider range of material, the more minute and experimental analysis. For one of the most striking results of the rap- prochement between psychology and physiology just referred to has been the attempt to introduce experi- ment into psychological science. Starting from the experiments of Weber and the more extended psycho- physical researches of Fechner, but taking a wider scope, there has sprung up a new line of inquiry, which, under the name of Experimental Psychology, sometimes aspires to the dignity of a separate dis- 1 In 1890. D 50 THE PRESENT POSITION OF cipline, and looks back with no little condescension upon the observational and descriptive science with which we are familiar. Wundt has been the leader of this movement, and Leipzig its great centre; but it is now widely spread in Germany, and has been enthusiastically taken up in America, where every well- equipped college aims at the establishment of a psychological or psycho-physical laboratory. England shows some disposition to follow in the wake. At least the University of Cambridge has voted a small sum for the same purpose, and the younger generation of Oxon- ians are found deserting the philosophy of Green to work in the laboratories of Freiburg, Leipzig, and Berlin. Let me say at once, to prevent misconception, that I think the experimental psychologists magnify their office overmuch. The field of experiment is necessarily limited ; it is limited to those cases where we are able to manipulate the physical and physiological processes which condition mental facts. The facts of sensation, the phenomena of movement, and the time occupied by the simpler mental processes, constitute, therefore, practically the whole accessible area. Within these limits, moreover, the results are often so contradictory as to leave everything in doubt ; where definite results THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 51 are obtainable, their value is often not apparent. Finally, many of the results are of a purely physio- logical nature, and are only by courtesy included in psychological science. These are the serious deductions which I think require to be made by a dispassionate observer of all this eager work. But the appetite for facts is a healthy symptom, and the whole movement is one which every student of psychology must take note of. We need not look for light from this quarter upon the problems of philosophy and the deeper mysteries of being ; but it is impossible that so much patient ingenuity should be devoted to analysing the substructure of our mental life without ultimately im- portant effects upon our knowledge of the psychological mechanism. A collateral effect of this scientific development of psychology has been an immense increase of detail- work. Already it is becoming more and more the practice for psychologists to publish elaborate mono- graphs on special phenomena, or on comparatively small departments of the subject. The number of psychological journals has also largely increased. One result of this is obvious. As psychology becomes in- creasingly scientific in character, and as the literature of the subject becomes more and more voluminous, 52 THE PRESENT POSITION OF the severance between philosophy and psychology must necessarily become more pronounced for it will become impossible for the same man to do original work in both departments. From the point of view of philosophy there might seem to be a certain ad- vantage in this, as effectually preventing any further confusion between the two spheres and sets of prob- lems. But this advantage is more apparent than real. For psychology, as the science of mental life, must always stand to philosophy in a more intimate rela- tion than any of the other sciences can. If the divorce, then, be carried so far that the philosopher and psy- chologist are no longer on speaking terms, the old evils will recur ; for a critical severance of provinces can be effected and maintained only by one who is familiar with both departments, even though his original work should lie only in one. It is to be hoped, therefore, that the psychologists of the future will all be trained in philosophy, and the philosophers in psychology. With this view, and in the present situation of affairs, I can- not help adding that it seems to me extremely desir- able, in a great university like this, that there should be a third man connected with the philosophical de- partment a Lecturer or Assistant-Professor specially charged with the teaching of psychology in its most THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 53 recent developments. Such work would lie, of course, largely with Honours students ; for psychological de- tail could not profitably replace to the Passman that introduction to the problems of philosophy and the history of thought which the retention of the Chair in a liberal curriculum is meant to ensure. To Philosophy, then, we come in the last place. It is by philosophy that this Chair and others like it in the Scottish universities must ultimately justify their existence ; and it is to the inbred Scottish bent towards philosophy that the public interest felt in them is due. The outlook here is not discouraging. Within the present century, as is well known, Comte promulgated his law of the three stages, representing metaphysics as a disease of childhood, like measles, which the race was in the act of outgrowing. And since then, Comtian and other influences have undoubtedly produced in many quarters a positivistic or agnostic attitude of mind, which gives itself great airs of finality from time to time in our newspapers and reviews. But metaphysics shows no inclination to die, by way of obliging these prophets of her decease. It is sufficient answer to their vaticinations to point to the marked revival of interest in philosophical discussion within recent years. There was a period, perhaps, when 54 THE PRESENT POSITION OF philosophical interest languished ; but there has seldom been a time when people were more anxious than they are at present to listen to any one who has anything to say. For indifferentism here, as Kant says, can be, in the nature of the case, no more than a temporary phase of feeling. " It is in reality vain to profess indifference in regard to such inquiries, the object of which cannot be indifferent to humanity." Apart from indifference, there was a time when the vast strides made by science more especially by the natural sciences in the third quarter of the present century fascinated men's attention, and diverted it from the problems which lie beneath and behind all science. But the very progress of science has brought men face to face once more with ultimate questions, and has revealed the impotence of science to deal with its own conditions and presuppositions. The needs of science itself call for a critical doctrine of knowledge as the basis of an ultimate theory of things. The idea entertained in some quarters that all difficulties would be solved by a scientific conception like that of evolu- tion, has been found illusory, inasmuch as that concep- tion itself requires a philosophical interpretation before it can throw any light at all upon the metaphysical question. History is not philosophy, and nothing is THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 55 explained merely by being thrown back in time. Evolution notwithstanding, the old questions all re- appear in a slightly altered form. They are brought to light again by the very success of science in dealing with her own problems. Philosophy is first, then, at the present day, a doctrine of knowledge ; and as such the critic of scientific cate- gories, to purge us of bad metaphysics. For the sweep- ing away of bad metaphysics is not the least important part of the philosophical task, and there is no meta- physics so bad as the metaphysics of the physicist or biologist when, in the strength of his own right arm, he makes a raid into philosophical territory. This critical office of Philosophy must also be extended to the metaphysical systems of the past. And in this connection we have one of the richest parts of the training afforded by a philosophical Chair ; for here the teacher must constitute himself the historian of thought, and, with a wise admixture of sympathy and criticism, introduce his hearers to the typical thinkers of the world " The dead but sceptred sovrans who still rule Our spirits from their urns." But this critical, and to a certain extent negative, work is not all. Philosophy must finally endeavour to 56 THE PRESENT POSITION OF be itself critically constructive, or, if that is a contra- diction in terms, it must endeavour to be constructive without forgetting its own critical strictures. The criticism of past philosophies, therefore, should not be purely negative. Truly light -giving and helpful criticism should seek to lead the learner, through the very consciousness of defects and inconsistencies in the systems examined, to a truer statement of the problem, and a more adequate solution. In this way, the systems of the past become so many stepping-stones on which we rise to fuller and clearer insight. And if, at the end, a completed system should still prove beyond our reach, the philosophical teacher will at least seek to indicate the general lines upon which an ultimately satisfactory theory must move. I have only time here to mention one or two points on which I think that a true philosophy should lay stress, and on which it should lay special stress at the present time. The first is the necessity of a ideological view of the universe. Trendelenburg, the eminent German Aristotelian, devotes one of the most interesting of his essays to illustrating what he calls the fundamental difference or antithesis between philo- sophical systems, the difference, namely, between the teleological and the mechanical point of view. Whether THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 57 an exhaustive classification of systems is possible on this basis or not, I believe with him that the antithesis he signalises is fundamental for philosophy ; and there is nothing of which I am more profoundly convinced than that philosophical truth lies, in this case, alto- gether with the teleological point of view. Any system which abandons this point of view lapses thereby from philosophy to science. The word teleology acts upon some people like a red rag upon a bull, from its association with certain old- fashioned arguments which explained particular pheno- mena from their supposed adaptation to external ends, more especially from their adaptation to the require- ments and conveniences of man. This paltry mechan- ical teleology was never at any time convincing to strong and sincere thinkers, and after being riddled by modern science, it may be held as finally beaten off the field. Its unsatisfactory character arose in great part from its taking facts in isolation, and then endeavour- ing artificially to fit them together in the relation of means and end. The philosophical teleology of which I speak concerns itself only with the End of the whole evolution. It concentrates itself upon the proof that there is an End, that there is an organic unity or pur- pose binding the whole process into one and making it 58 THE PRESENT POSITION OF intelligible in one word, that there is evolution and not merely aimless change. For it is only when con- templated in the light of a realised idea that any one speaks of a series of changes as steps in an evolution. A speculation which does not see that evolution spells purpose has not made clear to itself the difference between progress and aimless variation. Such specu- lation rests ultimately on a purely mechanical view of the universe. Let us try, therefore, in a sentence or two, to illu- minate by contrast these two opposite points of view. The mechanical view explains the universe as a col- location of mere facts so many real existences which just happen to be there. They are not there to ex- press any idea, meaning, or purpose : they have no further significance ; they simply are. Every change in these facts is completely determined by its immediate antecedents, acting as a blind vis a tergo. A cause may thus be assigned for every change, but a reason can be given for none ; for where there is no question of realising any idea or purpose, all change must be entirely motiveless. One collocation of facts is just as good as another. The mechanical explanation of things is thus a constant looking backward ; the teleo- logical or philosophical explanation, a looking forward THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 59 to the end or ultimate purpose which is being realised to the reason of the whole development, which is also in the deepest sense its cause. The mechanical explanation of any phenomenon is not false in itself. Nor need there be any quarrel between the causal and the teleological view of things, for they move upon different planes. The mechani- cally causal view only becomes false, when it professes to be a complete explanation of any phenomenon, and therefore, by implication, a philosophy of the universe. True, under certain limitations, as science, it is false when it puts itself forward as philosophy. Mechanical explanation is a proyressiis in infinitum, which can ultimately explain nothing. In the last resort, causce efficientes pendent afinalibus; the complete explanation of anything is only reached when we are able to view it in the light of a purpose, of which it forms an in- tegral part or element. Philosophy, therefore, stands or falls with the possibility of discovering a reasonable meaning or end in the universe. Every true phil- osophy is in this sense an attempted theodicy the vindication of a divine purpose in things. The antithesis of teleology and mechanism is, as you perceive, substantially the old opposition of Idealism and Materialism more strictly expressed. And it is 60 THE PRESENT POSITION OF equally obvious that while the mechanical view, through looking ever backward, finds an explanation of things in reducing them to their lowest terms, and presents us, for example, with matter and motion as philosophical ultimates, the teleological or idealistic view seeks the true explanation of the lower in the higher, of which it is the germ. For if the lower carries in it the promise and potency of the higher, then it must involve no less than a falsification of the facts to substantiate the lowest terms as indepen- dent self-existent facts, out of relation to the ultimate term in which we read the meaning of the whole de- velopment. That, however, is precisely what is done by all materialistic and quasi-materialistic systems. If philosophy, then, is the indication of an end, meaning, or purpose in the universe, what has phil- osophy to say, finally, as to the nature of the End ? Here again, it seems to me that philosophy has to wage unsparing battle against certain tendencies of our time. As it defends the truth of teleology in spite of former abuses of the principle, so it has to champion the truth underlying the old view which made man the centre of the universe. In a material aspect, man is but an atom or a point in the system of things, and we smile when we read in Cicero of THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 61 the heavenly redile who nightly lights the candles of the sky for our mortal comfort and convenience. But the Copernican view of the universe is pressed too far when we are invited, on the strength of it, to efface ourselves before the immensities of external nature. Much current thought is naturalistic at heart that is to say, it makes human nature only a part of nature in general, and seeks, therefore, to explain away the most fundamental characteristics of intelli- gence and moral life. As against this naturalistic tendency, philosophy must be unflinchingly human- istic, anthropocentric. Not to man as a creature specially located upon this earth, but to man and all creatures like him who are sharers in the life of thought, and called thereby to be authors of their own perfection to man as rational all things are relative. To him the creation looks ; for him all things are made. This is the imperishable grandeur of Hegel's system that he has given such sonorous utterance to this view, and expressed it with such magnificent confidence. I can- not always emulate his confidence, nor can I adopt as perfectly satisfactory his universalistic mode of expression. The achievements of the world -spirit do not move me to unqualified admiration, and I 62 THE PRESENT POSITION OF cannot accept the abstraction of the race in place of the living children of men. Even if the enormous spiral of human history is destined to wind itself at last to a point which may be called achievement, what, I ask, of the multitudes that perished by the way? " These all died, not having received the promises." What if there are no promises to them ? To me the old idea of the world as the training-ground of indi- vidual character seems to offer a much more human, and, I will add, a much more divine, solution than this pitiless procession of the car of progress. Happily, however, the one view does not necessarily exclude the other : we may rejoice in the progress of the race, and also believe in the future of the individual. Nature's profusion and nature's waste will doubtless be urged against us, when we plead for the rights of the individual life. But these are objections which every theodicy has to meet. I do not wish to minimise them : on the contrary, they appeal to me with painful force. But the possibility of any theodicy depends on our being able to show that nature and nature's ways of working are not the last word of creation. Nature is non-moral, indifferent, and pitiless; but man is pitiful, and human nature flowers in love and self- THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES. 63 denial, in purity and stainless honour. If these have no root in the nature of things, then indeed " The pillared firmament is rottenness, And earth's base built on stubble." But we do well, as Goethe teaches in one of his finest poems, to recognise in such attributes of human-kind our nearest glimpse into the nature of the divine. The part is not greater than the whole ; and we may rest assured that whatever of wisdom and goodness there is in us was not born out of nothing, but has its fount, somewhere and somehow, in a more perfect Goodness and Truth. THE "NEW PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. I 1 T. ALL who take an intelligent interest in the movement of contemporary thought whether it be philos- ophy more strictly so called, or the advance of science are aware of the great activity which has been shown of late years in the department of psychology. Till within the last half century or thereabouts, psychology had been an appanage of the philosophers ; and it can- not be said that they neglected this province of their dominion. In this country in particular in England and Scotland psychology has formed the bulk of our philosophic treatises ; and Hobbes, Locke, Berkeley, Hume, Hartley, Dr Thomas Brown, and the Mills, 1 An Address to the Edinburgh University Philosophical Society, November 9, 1892. THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 65 Beid, Stewart, and Hamilton, must always remain among the classics of the science. But it may be admitted that their work often shows a crossing of interests and of points of view. Questions of logic and theory of knowledge were mixed up with the more properly psychological inquiry. And, at other times, the investigation was subordinate to the establishment of some metaphysical theory. The distinguishing note of most recent psychology has therefore been insistence on the separation of psychology from philosophy, and on the maintenance of a purely psychological standpoint. In psychology, it is argued, we have a realm of pheno- mena, a moving world of causes and effects, which it is our business to investigate in the ordinary scientific way, with all the resources of observation and experiment. Imitating the example of physics, we have to reduce this world of complex phenomena to its ultimate con- stituents and the laws of their interaction, and we have to do this without any arridre pe?iste as to the bearing of our results on the ultimate problems of philosophy. No advice could be more excellent ; disinterestedness is the very watchword of science. But it seems to me that a good many of those who talk most loudly of " the new psychology " are exposed to the usual danger of re- action. The rise of this "scientific" psychology, as it E 66 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. also calls itself, is connected with the great develop- ment of science, especially, of the natural sciences, which has marked the present century. The growth of biology and physiology has naturally reacted powerfully upon the whole conception and method of psychological in- vestigation. And it is worth observing that the general scientific movement referred to coincided, especially in Germany, with a revulsion against the idealistic specu- lation which marked the beginning of the century. Probably the two were partly connected as cause and effect, the hunger for hard facts and patient detail- work being a healthy protest of the human spirit against over-hasty and over-confident attempts at universal synthesis. Any way, the new psychology, as I have said, has its roots in this movement. And therefore its absorbing concern was and is to keep itself clear of metaphysics, and of every hypothesis which it imagines to savour of that region of mysteries. To a large class of scientific and would-be scientific thinkers, metaphysics is what clericalism is to the French Liberal : it is the enemy, to be fought at all points. These two character- istics of this militant psychology its renunciation of metaphysics and its affiliation to biology are concisely put by Eibot, one of its standard-bearers : " The new psychology differs from the old in its spirit it is not metaphysical. It differs in its aim it only studies THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 67 phenomena. It differs in its methods it borrows them as far as possible from the biological sciences. Con- sequently the sphere of psychology specifies itself; it has for its subject nervous phenomena accompanied by consciousness." l I am far from asserting that this distrust is without historical justification. Natural explanations i.e., regulated sequences and coexistences of phenomena are what every science has to seek in its own sphere ; and, accordingly, science justly regards as suspect the explanation of any phenomenon by the immediate causality of a metaphysical agent. The interjection of such a causality into the empirical connections which she seeks to unravel, she treats as a form of ignava ratio. "It makes the investigation of causes a very easy task," says Kant, " if we refer such and such phenomena immediately to the unsearch- able will and counsel of the Supreme Wisdom, whereas we ought to investigate their causes in the general mechanism of matter. This is to consider the labour of reason as ended, when we have merely dispensed 1 ' La Psychologic Allemande,' Introduction. Ribot's deliverance dates from 1879, but precisely the same position is formulated in the open- ing and closing sentences of one of the most recent manuals on the sub- ject, Ziehen's ' Introduction to the Study of Physiological Psychology.' If the polemic against metaphysics is not always so marked, it is because the enemy is supposed to have been beaten off the field. 68 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. with its employment." l In the old psychology, this otiose method of explanation, by means of the soul and its faculties, was no doubt often resorted to. Hence, in shaking the dust of metaphysics off their feet, the new psychologists accepted from Lange 2 as their badge the somewhat paradoxical motto " Psycho- logy without a soul." As Kibot puts it triumphantly : " The soul and its faculties, the great entity and the little entities, disappear ; and we have to do only with internal events, events which, like sensations and images, are translations (so to speak) of physical events, or which, like ideas, movements, volitions, and desires, translate themselves into physical events." In this respect, however, the new psychology was not so original as it perhaps imagined. The attempt to dispense with a soul had been systematically made by Hume and the Associationists long before the second half of the nineteenth century. It was not simply the determination to discard the soul that stamped the new movement ; the second and more characteristic feature was the affiliation of psychology to physiology and to general biological science the study of the facts of consciousness consistently and exclusively in correla- 1 Werke, vol. iii. p. 468 (ed. Hartenstein). 2 Geschichte des Materialismus, vol. ii. p. 381. THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 69 tion with the organic facts of nerve and brain. This method of explanation was declined, as we know, by Locke and Hume ; and it has been made matter of reproach against a modern associationist like Mill, that he held by the old psychological method and went on " exactly as he might have gone on if he had lived in the days of Aristotle, ... at a time when a new method highly fertile in fact and of more fruitful promise was available." l The physiological method, in short, is the distinguishing mark, and "physiological psychology" is the term very generally given to the recent develop- ments of " psychology as a natural science." It is to be noted also that in speaking of the conditions of mental states (and it is agreed that the discovery of conditions constitutes scientific explanation) writers of this way of thinking have exclusively physiological conditions in view. Professor James tells us, for example, that he has " treated our passing thoughts as integers, and re- garded the mere laws of their coexistence with brain- states as the ultimate laws for our science ; " 2 and Mr Shadworth Hodgson defines psychology as " that posi- tive and special science which takes its stand upon the results of physiology and biology, and studies the phen- 1 Maudsley, Physiology of Mind, p. 76. 2 Principles of Psychology, Preface. 70 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. omena of sentience and consciousness in connection with their proximate conditions in individual living organisms." l Let me say at once that it is far from my intention to object to this intimate linking of the psychological and the biological. It may be taken as a postulate generally admitted, that our mental life is at every point physiologically conditioned ; and the physiologi- cal method of study does indeed promise, as its vot- aries say, to be most fruitful in its application. It alone furnishes the basis for introducing experiment into mental science ; and though it can only lay siege, as it were, to the outworks of the mental citadel, to the phenomena of sense-perception and movement and a few of the simpler aspects of the mental processes, yet the amount of patient detail-work accumulated in these departments, and the light thrown on other departments by the scientific study of abnormal mental states in their physiological relations, are already enriching the science in no ordinary degree, and transforming the very look of our psychological text-books. The philosopher would be singularly cross-grained who did not welcome this accumulation of material, and who did not congrat- ulate himself that all this detail-work was taken out of 1 Mind, vol. xi. p. 489 (October 1886). THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 71 his hands by those who, from their training and apti- tudes, can do it so much better. But he will reserve to himself, as philosopher, the ultimate verdict on the validity and sufficiency of the theory on which physi- ological psychology proceeds. For it is the most in- defeasible function of philosophy to act as critic of the sciences. The philosopher has to examine the concep- tions which each science accepts without criticism, and on which it proceeds in working out its results ; he has to point out the limits or conditions within which the conception or theory holds true. In other words, he has to restrain the ardour of the specialist who would build upon his results a philosophic theory of the uni- verse, by showing that the results which the investiga- tion seems to establish are really involved in the conceptions or standpoint from which it started, and are therefore in no sense to be accepted as an indepen- dent proof of the theory. I propose to show that this is pre-eminently the case with the main thesis of the " new " psychology at least in the hands of its most advanced representatives. In abjuring the soul and limiting itself to the concomitance of physical and psychical events, it is really dominated by a very definite theory which dictates the character of its results beforehand. 72 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. The result supposed to be proved, it had best be stated at once, is the complete parallelism of the bodily and the mental the denial, therefore, of any real causality to consciousness, which remains the inert accompaniment of a succession of physical changes over which it has no control. In a word, the result is the doctrine of human automatism. The doctrine of conscious automatism has been ventilated a good deal since 1870, or even earlier, by Mr Shadworth Hodgson, Professor Huxley, Professor Clifford, and others ; but, though no doubt definitely embraced by a few, it is safe to say that by the most it has been rather talked about, and toyed with, than fully conceived, much less believed. The doctrine has, however, been recently expressed with great clearness and force by Dr Munsterberg, who is perhaps the ablest and most stirring of the younger generation of physiological psychologists, and one whose theories have attracted considerable attention both in England and on the Continent. He teaches in the most unequivocal fashion that consciousness is simply, as he calls it, a " Begleiterscheinung," a concomitant phenomenon, or inactive accompaniment of a series of mechanical changes. Miinsterberg's work, which has appeared in a sue- THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 73 cession of pamphlets since the year 1888, takes largely the form of a polemic against Wundt's doctrine of Apperception. Wundt's ' Physiologische Psychologic/ first published in 1874, still remains, in its later editions, the most authoritative work on the subject ; and the psychological laboratory established by him in Leipzig in 1879, as the first of its kind, is still probably the chief centre of experimental work. But, although he may thus fairly be called the father of the whole movement, inasmuch as he has organised experimental psychology and induced the world to accept it as a new science, Wundt has never lent his countenance to the automatist conclusions which the young bloods are now drawing from their experimental labours. His doctrine of Apperception is far from clear, and its precise meaning has given rise to con- siderable controversy, but it seems to imply a function of subjective selection or central initiative analogous to what Dr Ward calls Attention ; and this is apparently in harmony with the general philosophical position which the author has elaborated in his recently pub- lished ' System of Philosophy.' But, be that as it may, it is at any rate certain that Wundt has been attacked by the upholders of thorough-going mechanism as an inconsistent and retrograde thinker for attributing 74 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. activity to the Subject. So much by way of explana- tion was necessary for the right understanding of Mlinsterberg's work. His first pamphlet in this con- troversy was ' Die Willenshandlung,' an analysis of the act of will, published early in 1888. This was followed in 1889-90 by three instalments of ' Contributions to Experimental Psychology/ in which, after an eluci- dation of principles, he endeavoured, by a series of carefully devised experiments, to assimilate the apper- ceptive process to the type of reflex action and thus reduce the whole conscious action to a play of asso- ciation. In 1891 he published an introduction to the study of psychology, 1 in the course of which we get a re-statement of his own position. The standpoint does not vary throughout the different expositions, and therefore, though illustrating freely from all, so far as they throw light upon my points, I will draw chiefly from the first and fullest statement that contained in his very acute analysis of the act of will. The ' Willenshandlung ' is divided into three parts, the first treating of the voluntary act as " movement- process " (B&wegungsvorgang) ; the second treating of it 1 ' Ueber Aufgaben und Methoden der Psychologic,' 1891. A fourth instalment of the ' Contributions to Experimental Psychology ' has since appeared. THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 75 as a phenomenon or appearance in consciousness (Be- wusstseinserscheinuny) ; and the third, which is intended to combine the results of the preceding parts, consider- ing the act of will in its totality as " conscious move- ment" (bewusste Bewegung). Mlinsterberg makes a start from the well-known saying of Kant : " That my will moves my arm is no whit more intelligible to me than if any one were to tell me that it could hold back the moon in its orbit." He accepts the problem as thus indicated : How does my will move my arm ? The first part of his treatise deals with the voluntary act exclusively from the physiological side, and analyses it into a series of movements. We may say analyses it necessarily into a series of movements, for the succession of bodily movements, whether visible movements of the limbs or molecular movements of the nerves and brain, are all of the process that could by any possibility be seen ; and reduction to processes which are intelligible in the sense of being pictorially presentable, is the pos- tulate of explanation which he lays down. 1 There is not much that is peculiar to Miinsterberg in this first section ; the same has been vividly put by many writers, 2 and in a sense this purely physical explana- 1 Zuriickfiihrung auf anschaulich verstanclliche Vorgange, p. 10. 2 Never better perhaps than by Lange, ' Geschichte des Materialismus,' 76 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. tion is true from the physiological side, though I think it is possible to show that/ even from the physiological standpoint, it is not the whole truth. Meanwhile it is vol. ii. p. 370. The passage has been often quoted, but may do duty again: "A merchant is sitting comfortably in his easy -chair, and would find it hard to say with what the greater part of his Ego is occupied whether with smoking, sleeping, reading the newspaper, or digestion. Suddenly the servant enters with a telegram which runs 'Antwerp, Jonas and Company failed.' 'Tell James to put the horses to.' The servant flies. The master has sprung to his feet, completely sobered ; some dozen paces through the room, down to his office, instructions given to the confidential clerk, letters dictated, telegrams despatched, then into the carriage. The horses pant ; he visits the bank, the exchange, his business friends. Before an hour is over, he throws himself again into his easy -chair with the sigh, ' Thank heaven, I have secured myself against the worst : now let me consider further. ' A splendid occasion for a picture of the soul. Terror, hope, feeling, calculation ruin and victory compressed into one moment. And that all aroused by a single idea ! What does not the human consciousness comprise ! " Softly, let us look at our man as an object in the material world. He springs up, why ? His muscles contract in the appropriate way. Why so ? They were moved by an impulse of nervous force which discharged the stored-up stock of elasticity. Whence this impulse? From the centre of the nervous system. How did it arise there ? Through the . . . soul. The curtain falls, the salto mortale is made from science to mythology." On the contrary, Lange proceeds, " we must trace back the physical series of causes through the brain to the first occasion of the whole sudden movement without taking any account whatever of the so-called consciousness. Or let us take it in the opposite direction. What came into the man ? The picture of certain strokes with blue pencil upon a white ground. Certain rays of light fell upon the retina, rays which in themselves do not develop more vital force in their vibra- tions than other light-rays. The vital force for the propagation of the impact is ready in the nerve as that for muscular contraction in the THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 77 enough to note the purely mechanical point of view and the explicit reduction of all physiological facts to physico-chemical processes. Passing to the more char- muscles : it can be discharged by the infinitely weak impact of the light- wave only as the elastic forces of the powder- cask are set free by the glimmering spark. But how comes it, then, that just these lines pro- duce in this man just this effect ? Every answer which falls back here upon ideas and the like is as good as no answer at all. I wish to see the channels, the paths of the vital force, the extent, the mode of propa- gation, and the sources of the physical and chemical processes from which the nervous impulses proceed which call into activity, and that precisely in the manner required for springing to one's feet, first the musculus psoas, then the rectus femoris, the vasti, and all the co-operating com- pany. I wish to see the far more important nervous streams which dis- tribute themselves to the organs of speech, the muscles of breathing, producing command, word, and call, and which, by way of sound-waves and the auditory nerves of other individuals, renew tenfold the same performance. I will, in a word, make a present for the time being of the so-called psychical action to the pedants of the schools, and will have the physical action which I see explained by physical causes." In like manner, Miinsterberg concludes that, "from the physiological stand- point there must correspond to every centrally initiated movement a complex of centripetal stimuli ; and in these stimuli acting from with- out, taken together with the existing structure and condition of the nervous mechanism, must lie the absolutely sufficient causes for the necessary occurrence of the definite act of will." Innumerable past stimuli in the life of the individual and the race are stored up as poten- tial energy in the nervous mechanism. Hence the sound-waves of a spoken word (on which, as in the case put by Lange, action follows) may represent "scarcely a millionth part of the joint-causes which bring about that particular movement in the hearer." But the mechanical determination by the joint-causes is as absolute here as in the case of the simplest reflex (pp. 17-20). It is, indeed, the avowed "postulate " of the whole investigation that the act of will shall be explained " als Mechanik der Atome" (p. 9). 78 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. acteristic psychological analysis, contained in the second part of the treatise, we find- that Mlinsterberg is at some pains at the outset to define the problem he sets himself. It is purely a problem of empirical psychology, and does not raise the metaphysical question as to the ultimate ground of phenomena or as to how consciousness exists at all. In that connection, Mlinsterberg seems to indi- cate that he regards Will, conceived as Schopenhauer conceived it, to be the most probable metaphysical hypothesis. His present investigation, however, has to do only with Will as a conscious fact ; it seeks " only to establish the conscious phenomena which are peculiar to the act of will" (p. 56). "Wherein consists the content of our inner experience, empirically given to each of us, which we designate will " (p. 60). Or, again, " For our investigation, limited as it is to facts, the will is a phenomenon like other phenomena ; and accordingly we have only to ask in what it consists, what regularly precedes it in consciousness, and what follows it " (p. 61). This strictly empirical character of the inquiry has one important consequence. It is well known [he proceeds] that modern psychology designates as sensations the ultimate irreducible .constitu- ents into which the content of consciousness (Bewusstseinsin- Tialt) may be analysed; ascribing to sensations a quality, THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 79 an intensity, and a tone of feeling which expresses their relations to consciousness. But, if sensation is the element of all psychical phenomena, and if, on the other hand, the will, so far as we are concerned with it, is only a pheno- menon of consciousness (Bewusstseinserscheinung), it follows necessarily that the will too is only a complex of sensations. 1 Having thus marked out his goal beforehand, Miin- sterberg proceeds to the actual analysis of the facts. He analyses first what he calls the inward activity of will i.e., the voluntary guidance of the train of thoughts in the form of attention; and secondly, the outward activity of will in bringing about muscular contractions. Under the first head, then, the question is, " Wherein consists the inner activity in the direction of the cur- rent of our ideas ? or, more precisely, what must be the nature of the feelings present in consciousness, if they are to produce in us the feeling of inward freedom, of active will ? " This more precise way of putting the question, it will be observed, is not without significance for the nature of the answer which it is to elicit. Let us get to the details, however. Four cases of the inward directive activity of will are analysed by 1 Page 62. The italics are Miinsterberg's own. It need hardly be pointed out that this astonishing invocation of "modern psychology" begs everything which is afterwards put forward as proved. Wundt criticises the assumption. ' Philosophische Studien,' vol. vi. p. 382 et seq. We shall return to it in discussing the theory as a whole. 80 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. Miinsterberg : (a) the case of voluntary recollection or trying to remember ; (b) the exercise of choice between different ideas presented, the concentration of attention upon one of these and its retention in the field of con- sciousness to the exclusion of the others ; (c) the case of logical thinking or reasoning, in which we pass along a definite and apparently self-directed path from prem- isses to conclusion; and (d) the case of simple atten- tion to an idea or percept which presents itself in con- sciousness. The analysis is most ingenious in the case of voluntary recollection and logical thinking. How is voluntary recollection distinguished from involuntary reminiscence ? If a fact a has been connected in experience with &, and the appearance of b calls up in consciousness the idea of a, I do not attribute to myself any voluntary action in the matter; I take it as an instance of the ordinary play of association. On the other hand, when I cannot remember a, when I seek it in my memory, recall to myself the place where I saw it, the connection in which I heard it, and when at last a actu- ally emerges in consciousness, then it was plainly my will (we say) which dragged to light the object of my search (p. 64). How does the case stand, however, when more closely analysed ? THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 81 If I try to remember a, if I seek it in my memory, a is of course* not itself present in consciousness, but what I do perceive does unquestionably correspond in content with a. So long as I have not found a, I feel, it is true, only an x, but I feel this a? in a series of relations, such that x can be only a and nothing else. I try to remember a word. In doing so, I see in memory the passage where I read the word, I remember the moment at which I heard it, I know exactly, too, the meaning of the word ; but the word itself is not present to me. At last it rises in consciousness. Can it be denied that that word was already given in its full content (vollinlialtlicli gegeben) in the series of ideational relations which I remembered 1 ? No doubt it was repre- sented in consciousness by entirely different qualities; it was given in its relations to other things, whereas it is afterwards distinguished by its own characteristics. But the two states of consciousness coincided with one another as to their inner meaning (p. 67). The only peculiarity, accordingly, which Mtinsterberg is prepared to admit in this process as contrasted with a case of involuntary association is that " the clear con- sciousness of the idea a was preceded by another state of consciousness which, in respect of its content, al- ready contained the idea ." He italicises this as the standing mark of voluntary control of our ideas. Eeasoning is distinguished, he argues, by the same characteristic. The premisses already contain the con- clusion, or, to put it more pointedly, the whole process of thought is determined from the outset by the idea F 82 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. of the end to be reached. In the second case mentioned above, where several ideas are presented, and we pur- posely retain one of them, a, the same thing manifestly holds. "Here," says Miinsterberg, "there is no need to prove that this a was in consciousness beforehand. The reasons why just a and not b remained in con- sciousness are admittedly only the occasions or motives of the voluntary act ; they are left therefore unnoticed here, the remaining behind is itself the achievement of the will (das Zurilckbleiben sellst ist die Willens- leistung)" The same line of argument explains his fourth case, the case of simple attention to any idea presented in consciousness. " In the first moment in which a sensation emerges in us, the perception appears involuntary, because the a was till then preceded by a not-a ; in the second moment, however, it appears to us as intentionally retained, just because we were already conscious of it in the preceding first moment." The solemnity with which this is propounded as a serious account of the facts in question would be too impudent if it stood alone; but Miinsterberg hastens to supplement it by reference to the bodily sensations which usually accompany acts like attention and selec- tion or efforts of thought and memory. He cites the admitted fact that there are feelings of innervation in THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 83 the sense-organ, when ideas of that particular sense are present in consciousness for any length of time. Whenever there is a strain of attention, other sensa- tions are usually present, such, for example, as feelings of tension in the skin of the head and the knitting of the brow in trying to remember or in thoughtful consideration. Nor are such feelings confined to the head ; they may be traced all over the trunk, and even in the extremities. Miinsterberg does not hold, how- ever, that such feelings of innervation necessarily accompany all voluntary activity. In reasonings or calculations that proceed without any particular diffi- culty, for example, they are not observable ; but just in these processes, he hastens to add, we are not specially conscious of our voluntary activity. It is only in subsequent reflection that we class them as acts of will, and in so doing, we fall back upon the criterion already signalised namely, the pre-existence of the idea in the preceding moment of consciousness. He concludes the first part of his psychological in- vestigation thus : The inner will has thus shown itself on analysis to be a very complicated group of ideas (ein sehr mannigfaltiges Vorstellungsgebilde), composed of certain definite series of ideas plus feelings of innervation. Nothing unknown, 84 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. nothing which stands over against the ideas as something heterogeneous, has been found, as we saw, in the first group of ideas or sensations ; it only remains, therefore, to ask whether any mysterious element is concealed in these innervation processes. Should these also be found to be a mere complex of sensations, the inner will would then be reduced to a series of sensations, each one of which is of the same order as blue, hard, sweet, or warm (p. 73). The consideration of the feelings of innervation cannot, however, be conveniently separated from the external action of the will upon the body, and so we pass to the second head of this psychological investigation. The stock example will suffice I lift an object with my hand. But the result of this experiment is usually a very poor one : the feeling of will which I seek (die gesuchte Willens- empfindung) I cannot discover in myself. I perceive just a slight feeling of tension in the head. For the rest, I am only conscious that I actually execute the movement viz., bending the joints of the elbow and hand. I feel no special impulse to the movement, lying in time between the theoretical intention and the practical execution of it. It is quite different, however [he proceeds], when I do not simply have the intention of lifting an object, and carry this out, but slowly analyse the movement for myself, and direct my attention to the individual parts of the bendings. Now I really perceive more than the actually executed move- ments ; the bending in the elbow is now preceded by the feeling of a peculiar impulse. It is not a general feeling THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 85 of exertion, but a quite specific impulse, which is different for every movement, and plainly stands in relation to the special performance intended. What, then, has analysis to say of these feelings of innervation which immediately precede the movement, and seem to be its cause ? Miinsterberg turns round triumphantly to apply his former criterion. What we call impulse in the case of muscular contraction is simply the circumstance that the idea of the effect to be produced precedes the effect as actually produced. The feeling of innervation is just the memory-idea of the movement anticipating the movement itself. There has been much discussion as to the precise nature of the so-called feelings of innervation ; but, as Wundt, who had formerly held an opposite theory, has explicitly accepted this view of them as the one most consonant with the present state of our knowledge of the subject, there is no need to reproduce here the arguments which go to establish the position. It commends itself by its naturalness and simplicity. When we are on the point, say, of making a stroke at a ball, we have a premonitory feeling of the energy which we are about to expend ; it seems to flow forth toward the limb which we are about to use. One theory, formerly a good deal in evidence, explained 86 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. this feeling as due to an immediate consciousness of outgoing energy ; but this physiological difficulties in the way of such a conception are great. It is not necessary here to decide whether an immediate con- sciousness of effort is or is not possible; but, in any case, this theory leaves unexplained the specific char- acter of the feeling in question. For it is to be ob- served that it is a premonitory feeling of the exertion of that limb, not merely a general consciousness of virtue going out from us. This is satisfactorily ex- plained by supposing, as Miinsterberg does, that it is due to the reproduction in memory of previous movements of the same nature. Plainly, however, Miinsterberg's theory of the feelings of innervation may be accepted, without admitting that this sequence of memory-image and actual perception constitutes, as he contends, the differentia and suffi- cient explanation of the voluntary act. But it will be observed how ingeniously Miinsterberg has reduced all cases of voluntary action internal and external to examples of the same phenomenon, namely, to cases of an idea or perception A preceded by a the same idea in a different form. " The feeling of innervation," as he puts it, "is an anticipated idea of the actual movement" (p. 88). Exactly the same analysis THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 87 applies to those voluntary actions which do not end in a muscular contraction but aim at the production of some effect in the external world. When I move my finger, not in order to practise the differ- ent movements, but to write something down; when I contract the muscles of my organs of speech, in order to make a communication to somebody; when I bend my arm in order to greet a passer-by, in all these cases I perceive in the first stadium the more or less distinct, more or less clearly represented, idea of the end ; and in the second stadium I have a sensation of (ich empfinde) the end as attained. That alone is the type of the external act of will (p. 89). However complicated the action is, extending possibly over a longer period of time (a journey, the erection of a building), it may always be resolved into the ultimate end in view and the subordinate actions which have to be performed in order to attain that end. In the pro- cess of execution, the ultimate end falls temporarily into the background, and the subordinate actions or means become, each in turn, in a definite series, the proximate end before the mind. And, step by step, the same analysis holds good : the end is first present as idea, then as a perception of accomplished fact. Mtin- sterberg goes on courageously to apply his analysis to the usually received distinction between desire and 88 will. " In order that the desire of an attainable object pass into the corresponding act of will, neither more nor less requires to be added than just the carrying out of the desire, so that the idea of the end may l>e com- pleted ~by the perception of its attainment!' " The liveli- est feeling of practical freedom cannot alter the fact that the will itself is nothing more than the perception (frequently accompanied by associated sensations of tension in the muscles of the head) of an effect at- tained by the movement of our own body, along with an antecedent idea of the same effect drawn from imagination i.e., in the last resort from memory ; this anticipated idea being given as feeling of inner- vation, when the effect is itself a bodily movement, " A theory of the soul does justice, therefore, to the whole field of psychical phenomena, if it assumes, as the only function of the soul, sensation characterised by quality, intensity, and tone of feeling ; a definite group of sensa- tions we call will" (p. 96). * This is the conclusion of the second part of the investigation. The first, or purely physiological, part, reduced the phenomenon to a series of reflex move- ments ; the second, or purely psychological, part, has reduced it to a series of sensations. The third, or 1 The italics are Miinsterberg's. THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 89 psycho-physical, parfc, investigates the relation of these two series to one another. We cannot believe that the two series are quite independent, and if we are driven to suppose that the one is conditioned by the other, there can be little hesitation in settling which is the conditioning factor. The psychical series is dis- continuous, constantly interrupted by perceptions which are shot inexplicably into its midst, without the possi- bility of causal explanation from the foregoing train of ideas ; there are many bodily functions which, so far as we know, are not represented in consciousness. These and similar considerations make the psychic series unfit to be the explaining factor, and accordingly Miinsterberg reaches the conclusion that "the series of conscious phenomena is conditioned by the regular course of material occurrence." This leads to the inquiry, What are the processes in the sensory-motor apparatus which correspond, when inwardly contem- plated, to the sensational complex called a volition? Mtinsterberg's results are reached in the course of an interesting, and in some respects brilliant, discussion as to the localisation of brain-function. It is beyond our interest to follow him in his detailed criticism of different theories. His own positions are mainly two : (1) that there are no specifically motor centres; and 90 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. (2) that perception and memory are connected with the same material substratum; or, to put it otherwise, that ideas of sensation and the corresponding ideas of memory are connected, not with different parts of the brain, but with the same set of material processes differently excited. There is much to be said for these conclusions. Whether the will is analysable into sen- sations and ideas or not, it is at least inseparable from them, and therefore we may reasonably conclude that the centres concerned in voluntary movement cannot be separated physiologically from the sensory regions of the brain. Similarly, it may be argued that in per- ception and memory the same brain- tracts are excited, the liveliness and strength of the impression being greater when its stimulus proceeds from its peri- pheral end-organs than when it is conducted by fibres of association from other parts of the cortex. On the physiological truth of these hypotheses I do not feel competent to decide, nor is it necessary for my purpose to do so. It is with Miinsterberg's appli- cation of them that we are concerned. " Every ganglion of the cerebral cortex," he resumes, " is thus end-organ of a centripetal path but every ganglion is also the initial organ of a motor path. Motor centres do not exist, therefore, or, more properly, every centre is sen- THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 91 sory and motor at once ; every motor impulse has its source in a sensory stimulus, and every sensory stimu- lation presses on into a motor path" (pp. 141, 142). What happens in consciousness, then, when a response to stimulus takes place ? At first, nothing precedes the movement except the sensation or perception which causes its discharge. The movement, in other words, " goes off," in a purely reflex way, through the force of the incoming stimulus. But as soon as the movement actually takes place, consciousness has something new before it namely, the feeling of movement produced in the contracted muscle. This feeling of movement follows, therefore, immediately upon the perception of the stimulus which discharged the movement; and the sensory excitation of the central ganglion which corresponds to this feeling of movement becomes connected accordingly by an association - path with the first excitation, which gave the impulse to the movement. If, now, this process is several times repeated, the con- nection becomes so close that the first excitation inevitably calls forth the second, directly by the path of association, before it has time to be produced by the actual contraction of the muscle. Psychologically expressed, that is as much as to say, the perception of the stimulus must call forth by association the memory-idea of the corresponding sensation 92 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. of movement, before that sensation itself is produced by the actual execution of the movement. The former process takes place by the shorter way of the association-paths in the hemisphere ; the latter requires first to be conducted to the muscle, the inertia of the muscle has to be overcome, the contraction to be actually produced, the sensory nerve to be affected, and the sensory stimulus conducted back to the cor- tex. All this occupies an appreciable time, and the sensory stimulus arrives accordingly considerably later. And now we see clearly why our feeling of innervation precedes the perception of the actual movement. In it, as the constant signal of movement, a signal that is also the actual counter- part of the movement, we involuntarily believe that we see the movement's cause. This is the type of voluntary action, from which all other forms may be developed (p. 145). Take, for example, an act of choice. Here we have, let us say, two stimuli, both alike in strength, but incapable of combination in a common reaction. At first no motor reaction can result, but each stimulated ganglion rouses the centres which are connected with it by association-paths ; and now it is not an opposition of stimulus against stimulus, but on both sides there collect the associations won by former experiences. In the first place, naturally, there is the associated idea of the movement corresponding to the stimulus. If this is stronger upon the one side than upon the other, or if it rouses more pleasurable feelings upon the one side than upon the other, then the corresponding movement will result. This is the type of any act THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 93 of choice ; but there may be indefinite complication, both in the nature of the stimulus and in the mass of associations brought to bear upon it. Still, however great the complication may be, the sensory stimuli with their associated ideas constitute the sufficient and only verifiable cause of the resultant movement ; or, as he puts it in another place, "the act of will is the motor discharge of sensory excitation, whether it be the sensation of a single stimulus or a world of internally and externally combined ideas. As soon as the sensory excitation-complex, the conscious con- tent of ideas, is there, the movement is necessarily given too " (p. 156). And thus the only psychical criterion of the will remains what it was found to be at the end of the psychological section namely, that before the perception of the actual result, the idea of the result is present in consciousness. We have the theory now pretty fully before us, and, as has been indicated, there is much in the physiological analysis that is freshly put and that claims consider- ation. It seems important to remember, alike in physiology and psychology, that the sensory centre in the brain, the central ending of the sensory nerve, does not constitute a terminus, and, consequently, that there is no such thing as passive sensation, sensation 94 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. which is simply received without producing further effects. All consciousness is impulsive. If the stimulus received does not find an immediate vent in movement, it irradiates other brain-tracts in the form of association. The phenomena of imitation, sugges- tion, and many other considerations, reinforce this conception of the dynamic quality which all sensations and ideas possess. Miinsterberg, however, has skil- fully woven these truths into the texture of a precon- ceived theory. In the very act of emphasising move- ment and the dynamic aspect of ideas, he eliminates altogether the notion of action or activity. Ideas " go off " or explode, as it were, in movement of their own accord. There is first the idea of the movement, as in contemplation ; and secondly, the perception of the movement, as executed. In other words, there is a series of happenings somehow passing before us, but no real activity, no real actor in the whole affair. In all so-called action, we only seem to act ; a sequence of ideas exhausts the phenomena of will. The conscious subject is reduced to an inactive spectator of these psychological happenings, which are themselves the inert accompaniments of certain transformations of matter and energy. There results, in fact, as indicated at the outset, the doctrine of conscious automatism in the most unqualified sense of the words. THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 95 Xow, I do not hesitate to say that this conclusion is in the strictest sense incredible ; no amount of so- called " evidence " in its favour would avail to make it even momentarily believable. But as the theory airs itself with a great deal of confidence, and troubles a good many minds, I will endeavour to show that such results are not reached by any cruel "logic of facts," but are all involved in a few erroneous psycho- logical presuppositions, perhaps I ought to say one fundamental prejudice, by which the analysis is vitiated from the outset. This prejudice may be called Pheno- menalism, or perhaps best Presentationism ; Wundt calls it in one place Intellectualism. It is the fore- gone conclusion that the conscious life is analysable without remainder into ideas or presentations. Evi- dently, if phenomena or objects of consciousness are alone to be accepted as facts, then all real activity on the part of the subject is necessarily eliminated; the subject remains only nominally, as a static impersonal condition of the series of events. If we insist upon phenomenalising the act of will, doubtless all the phenomena in the case are the ideas that precede and the perceptions that follow, with perhaps some feelings of tension in the head thrown in. But does it not require some effrontery to offer us these antecedent, concomitant, and sequent ideas as an account of the 96 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. volition itself. To attempt to analyse a volition into ideas is about as hopeful as trying to reduce miles and furlongs to pounds avoirdupois ; there is no common denominator. In the course of such analysis, the real fact of volition is necessarily dropped ; it is overlaid by the mass of antecedents, concomitants, and sequents which acute introspection enables us to discover. But, as M. Fouillee says, the physiological psychologists might fill volumes with their analysis of the sensations which accompany the voluntary act, without touching the essence of the act itself. 1 The result of analysis infected with this phenomenal- istic prejudice is necessarily a Panphenomenalism essen- tially similar to that of Hume. There is the same elimination of all real causality : sequent ideas are all. And if, in deference to a quasi -Kantian theory of Knowledge, the Self or subject is apparently retained, this seeming difference from Hume is only skin-deep. For, as Miinsterberg tells us twice over, " the subject in question is entirely impersonal ; " 2 it is the static or logical condition of consciousness in general. The individual self is reduced, as with Hume, to groups and sequences of ideas ; it is an object in consciousness 1 Revue philosophique, vol. xxxii. p. 238. 2 Aufgabe cler Psychologie, pp. 99 and 130. THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 97 an object, presumably, for this impersonal spectator- subject. I pointed out in passing how entirely Miinster- berg's psychology was dominated by this phenomenal- istic point of view. It appears, incidentally, in the very expressions he uses, as a reference to the passages already quoted abundantly shows. In his equation of phenomenon with fact, in the constantly repeated use of the term Inhalt or content, it is presupposed that objects or presentations in consciousness are the only elements that will be allowed to stand as real. At times, Mlinsterberg speaks, even more naively, of " the sensation of will," of which he is in quest. This recalls, even verbally, Hume's famous expedition into his own interior, in order to discover the perception of the Self. Show me the impression from which the idea is derived, says Hume, and because no particular impression can be found, the idea is pronounced a fiction ; the Self is resolved into a bundle of perceptions. Show me the sensation to which the word " will " corresponds, says Miinsterberg, and finding a number of accompanying sensations, he mistakes these for the act of will itself, and concludes roundly, as we saw before, that " the will is only a complex of sensations." But this conclusion depends, on Mlinsterberg's own showing, 98 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. upon two all -important " ifs." If sensation is the sole element of all psychical phenomena, and if the will is only a phenomenon in consciousness, then, and only then, does it follow necessarily that the will is resolvable into a complex of sensations. In support of the first " if," Miinsterberg, as we have seen, has nothing to offer but a vague reference to " modern psychology." Wundt, in criticising his specu- lation, 1 justly censures this attempt to clothe an as- sumption with the air of an accepted truth, and to cover it with the aegis of " modern psychology." Wundt's own phraseology has wavered in his different editions, and its looseness may be partly responsible, as Dr Ward suggests, 2 for the extreme conclusions of his followers. Perhaps in view of these conclusions, he now explicitly disavows the resolution of all con- sciousness, including feeling and will, into sensational elements. Sensations, he holds, are the ultimate ele- ments of " those conscious contents which we refer to external objects " that is to say, of our perceptions or presentations. Whether this revised statement is un- exceptionable or not, such a position is at least in- telligible ; but it contains no warrant for identifying 1 Philosophische Studien, vol. vi. p. 382 et seq. ' 2 In an article in ' Mind,' January 1893. THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 99 feeling and will with any presentation or combination of such. There is, in fact, no distinction more fundamental to a sound psychology than that between the feeling- directed activity, which, under all its forms, from the simplest act of attention and response to stimulus, may be summarised as Will, and the content or matter with which that activity deals. Doubtless the two cannot be separated ; each is an abstraction without the other. But one thing at least is certain, that to resolve the fact of conscious experience into a sequence of presen- tations or conscious phenomena is to omit the vital characteristic of all consciousness. It is to offer us a machinery without any motor force; and when we mildly point out the omission, we are met by the ready but somewhat brazen retort, that the machinery is self-acting. Wundt comments acutely on the way in which this " intellectualistic " psychology substantialises ideas or presentations, treats them as if they were things or entities that could independently exist and interact. Even when it is admitted that presenta- tions have an existence only in and for consciousness, so that the unity of consciousness is acknowledged to be their necessary complement or point of reference, the ideas still seem to stand over against the conscious- 100 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. ness to which they are referred, and to carry on their evolutions independently. Consciousness, according to this way of thinking, becomes a mere form inclusive of a certain matter, but without influence upon it: it is regarded as purely speculative or contemplative ; an eye (shall we say ?) contemplating the movement, or, to be strict and to avoid metaphor, merely an ideal point of unity. Metaphor or no metaphor, the result of this way of looking at things is obvious. The whole weight is thrown upon the objects the ideas or pheno- mena, thus quasi -independently conceived and the recognition of the subject becomes an empty acknow- ledgment. It is entirely denuded of activity, all action being refunded into the play of presentations. 1 1 Dr Ward has very aptly called attention ('Mind,' xii. 50) to a current form of words which favours this habit of thought viz., the way we have of speaking of " conscious states " in abstraction from the activity of the conscious subject whose states they are. We get into the habit of thinking of the " states " " phenomena " is another word as if they existed separately, as if they interacted and established relations be- tween themselves, evolving in course of time the idea of the subject. But, in strictness, we have no right to speak of a state as conscious ; in so doing we are making an entity of it, and conferring upon an abstraction attributes which it can possess only as an element in the activity of a unitary conscious being. Dr Ward declaims with justi- fiable warmth against the confusion in which our psychological nomen- clature is involved. Even the favourite term " states of consciousness," of which " conscious states " may be supposed an abbreviation, is open to a similar objection. Consciousness, as the form of the word proclaims, is 101 For this assumption, however, there is an entire ab- sence of warrant. A psychology which aims at keeping in touch with fact must strenuously resist this subtle tendency to reduce everything to knowledge. Experi- ence is, in this reference, a wider term than knowledge ; and feeling and will are inexpugnable and irreducible features of experience. Knowledge, feeling, and will are three aspects of experience inseparable aspects, it may be freely admitted but none of them can be ex- pressed in terms of the others ; no one of them can be reduced to simpler elements, no one of them can, properly speaking, be defined or explained otherwise than by pointing to the living experience in which it is exemplified. Miinsterberg's position here is rather inconsistent ; he denies will as more than a complex of sensations, but he contrives to smuggle in feeling by calling it an attribute which every idea possesses. He follows Wundt in saying that every sensation, in addi- an abstraction ; it is the quality or characteristic of a subject or con- scious being. States are states of the conscious being, then, not states of consciousness. This is not a mere piece of verbal purism. A great deal of vague thinking thinking that has not faced an inevitable issue and made up its mind clearly finds a convenient refuge under the quasi-abstract term consciousness. People make no scruple about admitting or postulating a transcendental unity, a unity of conscious- ness, who would think their reputation for modernity at stake if they were taxed with upholding a soul or subject as a real being. 102 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. tion to its intensity and its quality (as touch or taste, red or blue, and so forth), also possesses a tone of feel- ing, or, as Professor Bain puts it, an emotional side; and to this third aspect of sensation, curiously enough, he allows that there is no material counterpart. 1 This statement is curious, not in itself, of course, but as coming from Miinsterberg. There can be no ma- terial counterpart, in Mtinsterberg's sense, just because feeling is not itself an object, phenomenon, presentation, or stimulus, but the attitude of the subject towards a given stimulus the relation of the stimulus to the life of the individual as a whole. This subjective apprecia- tion cannot, in the nature of the case, be represented in objective terms. Feeling, as Dr Ward says after Ham- ilton, is something subjectively subjective. If we are to be strict, we do not know feeling ; for knowledge is of objects, of phenomena, and feeling cannot be pheno- menalised. We experience feeling, and we know about it by its results ; but, using the term in this sense, we know only the causes, accompaniments, and consequents of feeling. It may be said that we remember our feel- ings and emotions, and that we must know them at the time, in order to remember. But we remember feeling only in the sense that, when the ideas which caused or 1 Willenshandlung, p. 137. THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 103 accompanied it are recalled, they are recalled with the same tone of feeling ; in other words, we re-experience in a fainter degree the feeling which we then felt. It is this characteristic of feeling that explains its frequent neglect by psychologists. For feeling cannot be recalled or considered, except in connection with its objective causes or accompaniments : in recording the facts, therefore, the psychologist is apt to forget the sub- jective tinge of the ideas or presentations, and to report upon them in an impersonal way, as, so to speak, ideas-in-themselves. But it was only in virtue of what I have called the subjective tinge that the ideas were his ideas at all, and had any relation to his life. As they presented themselves, they were felt to be either a furtherance or a hindrance to the vitality of the subject, to be either relevant to the dominant in- terests of the individual or discordant. Interest and desire are the result in the one case, indifference or repulsion in the other. And it can hardly be too strongly emphasised that the dynamic efficacy of ideas is entirely excited through the feeling subject. Ideas have hands and feet, as Hegel finely said, and how often are we told that ideas move the world. It is true, or at least we hope so. But every one must ac- knowledge that to speak in that way is to use a vivid 104 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. metaphorical shorthand. Ideas entertained tend to pass into action; a plan conceived and cherished tends to execute itself; but, as Fichte long ago said, the real force is not in the ideas, but in the will of the person who adopts them as his. So, when psychologists like Miinsterberg attribute the whole march of the conscious life to the dynamic influence of idea upon idea, it is well to remember again that this is at best a conven- ient shorthand. Ideas in themselves are pale and in- effective as the shades of Homeric mythology ; they are dynamic only as they pass through the needle's eye of the subject. It is the subject which acts upon its appreciation of the stimulus, and the emotional atti- tude of welcome or repulse is what is meant by feeling. In its earliest and simplest forms, such an emotional wave passes immediately into the appropriate motor response. The food is clutched or somehow absorbed, the disagreeable intrusion is evaded, edged away from, as far as the powers of the being admits of. Feeling, thus conceived, and allied thus closely with action, forms what may be called the driving-power in all life. Here we strike upon the roots of individuation, and when we say that, is it going too far to add, upon the fundamental characteristic of real existence ? In this connection I am confident that, whether we look at the THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 105 matter psychologically or physiologically, we are shut up to the conclusion that all action of living beings was originally feeling-prompted, and that what we call re- flex action is everywhere a secondary product, a de- graded form of purposive action. We know that many actions at first performed voluntarily, actions learned with effort by repeated forth-puttings of concentrated attention, become by degrees habitual, and are performed automatically without attention i.e., without any need for express volition to come into play at all. Great part of the detail of our daily life is handed over to mechanism in this way, and psychologists and physiolo- gists have not been slow to emphasise the beneficent operation of this fact. It is, indeed, the very condition of progress, that aptitudes once acquired should estab- lish themselves as definite tendencies within our mental and physical organism definite co-ordinations of stim- ulus and response which do their work without our active superintendence. The powers of intelligence and will the powers of personality, if I may so speak are thus set free for new tasks and further achieve- ments, till these in turn are, as it were, built into the structure of the Self. Only thus is the spirit fitted to advance upon its endless path. But mechanism is thus, in every sense, posterior to intelligence and 106 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. will; it is a means created and used by will. In a strict sense, will creates the reflex mechanism to which it afterwards deputes its functions. Mechanism, in fact, here as everywhere, is a means, something secondary ; it is impossible to conceive it as something primary, existing on its own account, much less as carrying in it the explanation of the higher con- scious and voluntary processes. Intelligent volition is not reflex action grown complicated, and so become conscious of itself. That is precisely to invert the true relation an inversion that would be ludicrous, if it were not disastrous. Eeflex action is purposive action grown unconscious or sub-conscious, according to the economy of nature, because consciousness is no longer necessary to its proper performance. It is not to be supposed, of course, that this takes place within the life-history of the individual human being, or of any highly developed organism. In such an organism, many reflex paths, many co-ordinations of stimulus and response, are doubtless fixed ; they have been established in the long process of race- evolution, and in virtue of their establishment that evolution has proceeded. But follow the process as far back as we may, all analogy points to the same conclusion namely, that feeling - prompted action, THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 107 i.e., action which is germinally purposive, germin- ally voluntary, is the Trporepov vo-i, the first in the order of nature. In the lowest organisms, the reaction upon stimulus may be so simple and uniform as to wear to an observer the appearance of a mere mechan- ical reflex. But this is, if I may so speak, to make the creature a mere outside ; it forgets, as this mechanical psychology is constantly forgetting, that wherever there is life, there is unity. Every organism is a unity, and resumes itself as a unity. Feeling is the inward ex- pression of this unity ; and, to my mind, it is not doubt- ful that the movement of attraction or repulsion, which, to us and from the outside, may seem a simple reflex, is to be interpreted rather as the total response of a ger- minal consciousness, as the expression of the being's likes and dislikes. Physiology, so long as it remains pure physiology, is perhaps debarred from taking account of feeling or consciousness as such. The psychical in all its forms lies outside the scope of physiological methods. But the self - preservative, recuperative, self-adaptive ten- dencies of organisms and organic tissue are the physiological way of expressing the same fact. Such a mode of expression is imperfect and mythological, perhaps, and one can understand that many physi- 108 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. ologists, supposing it to be put forward as an ex- planation of the facts, grow impatient and fall back upon a purely mechanical theory of vital function. But these expressions are in no sense explanations, as science uses that term ; they are rather finger-posts to the unexplained; they merely name or indicate the fundamental characteristic of life as such, which differentiates it from mechanism or what seems to us to be mechanism. Life is the presupposition of physiology, the fact on which its existence is based, a fact which it has simply to accept, as all the other sciences have to accept their own presuppositions. Its explanations move within the fact of life, and cannot be used to explain that fact itself, or, in other words, to explain it away. Yet that is, in substance, what a purely mechanical physiology tries to do. Physiology, for the last fifty years, has been dominated by a reaction against what is called vitalism. The older investigators were in the habit of calling in " vital force " as a deus ex machina to account for any phenomena which baffled their powers of natural explanation. Vital force, conceived as extraneously interfering with otherwise mechanical processes, was evidently a hypostatised entity of the worst type, and it was accordingly discarded by scientific physiology THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 109 as part of the baneful legacy of metaphysics. Mechani- cal explanation, or, in other words, the resolution of physiology into physics, became the watchword and ideal of the best workers. But they did not observe that they were in danger of throwing away the child with the bath, as the Germans say. After all, physiology is not physics ; living matter behaves differently from dead matter. What is the difference and the basis of the difference ? In rendering mechanically intelligible the inter-relation and interaction of this and the other part of the bodily structure, physiologists tend to forget that all such mechanical arrangements are arrangements in the service of life, arrangements per- fected in the living being (in all probability) by the responsive and self-adaptive action of its living ancestors in the course of ages. Picrposiveness is the notion upon which physiology is built, and it is worked into the whole theory of development ; yet it is a notion entirely alien to the blind vis a tergo of mechanism as such. The more clearly a physiologist realises what pure mechanism means, and the more fully he grasps the import of the facts he has to deal with, the more ready will be his acknowledgment that to call them mechani- cal is at best an analogy. They belong to a different order of facts ; life and purpose govern them from one 110 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. end to the other. A self-acting and self-regulating machine is only by an abuse of language spoken of as a machine at all. It is in vain therefore that many psychologists at the present time outdo the physiologists in the glibness with which they talk of nervous currents and explosions of nervous energy and paths of least resistance. The appearance of explanation conveyed by the use of the expression "path of least resistance" is in the last degree illusory. We are transferring an expression which has a perfectly definite and intelligible meaning in physics or mechanics to a sphere where the conditions are quite different, and where we are, moreover, almost quite ignorant as to the nature of what actually takes place. Path of least resistance means, in such a case, simply the particular reaction which we find the stimulus, as a matter of fact, to produce. We have no right to go further than this. The use of the physical phrase implies, however, that what takes place is pre- cisely the same as the selection of a channel made by a rill of water trickling down a hillside. This is to make the living being simply a network of pathways through which the energy of external nature takes its course soaks in, and oozes out again. But this is not a true account even of the humblest organism. Such a THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. Ill representation totally ignores the unitary character of the organic and sentient being. We are misled, in short, by words like currents, and energy, and least resistance. What do we mean by nerve currents ? Nerve currents cannot be treated in this isolated fashion, as if they took place in vacuo, or in an indifferent medium ; they take place in a living individual, and apart from the unity of that indi- vidual they are mere abstractions. A nerve cur- rent is a physiological process, which, originally and normally, means central stimulation and appropriate central reaction. You cannot separate either the appreciation of the stimulus or the reaction upon it from the organism as a whole. To speak psycho- logically, it is the living being, as a unity, that is aware of the sensation and responds to it. There is no need here to revive any hypothesis as to the specific seat of the soul, or to conceive any point of convergence in the brain for the multitudinous nerves of sensation and motion. However the nervous system acts, the unity of consciousness, as we experience it every moment, is proof sufficient of the fact that it does act as a unity. Every living being is a similar individuate unity. Abnormalities, as when the removal of the higher centres gives rise to the establishment of independent 112 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. unities (in the spinal cord, for example), are no argu- ments against what is here contended for ; they rather go to prove that even the mutilated organism, so long as it lives at all, reconstitutes itself into a kind of unity. A living being, then, is, at the very least, a centre of sensation and reaction ; and when sensation is so used, it means not only intellectual awareness of some pres- ence, but also a subjective drawing to, or away from, the intruder. This second element of feeling proper is the condition in virtue of which the sensation as know- ledge calls forth the reaction as will. The appetitive is the first phase of consciousness. And however the growth of the intellectual life and of volitional self- control may emancipate us from the promptings of the moment, it is to the end through feeling that the whole process of our life goes on. It is in feeling that we assert our individuality, give expression to our prefer- ences and distastes. Feeling leads each of us to select from the infinite of the knowable and do-able, that little world of interests and habits which differentiates us one from another, and gives to each his peculiar point of outlook upon the universe. The necessity of taking feeling first has led us in appearance away from our specific theme. But it is only in appearance, for it was impossible to separate THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 113 the treatment of feeling and will, and what has been said of the one applies mutatis mutandis to the other. The presentationists endeavoured to make feeling a relation between ideas, instead of the relation of ideas to the subject of them. If the subject has identified itself, as we say, with certain ideas or interests, then any idea which conflicts with these ideas will result in pain or displeasure to the subject. But here, as always, it is not the relations of ideas as such rela- tions, as it were, in the phenomenal plane but rela- tion to a subject, that constitutes the fact of feeling. Similarly with volition. Volition is the action of a subject, and as such, it cannot be phenomenalised. But this is just what the phenomenalists, from Hume to Mtinsterberg, insist on doing. They resolve voli- tion into a sequence of presentations ; first, an idea, then a perception (as we have seen Miinsterberg put it), but no intervening fiat, no power, no real action, nothing corresponding to what we mean by volition just the one first, and the other second. The answer to be made to this ingenious theorem has been indicated already. To ask to know the will as a presentation is to ask to know it as it is not. The phenomena which Miinsterberg offers us are very likely all the phenomena in the case, or if there are more, the others are like unto H 114 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. them. But his whole investigation is a petitio principii. The heading of the psychological section of his treatise runs, " The Will as a Phenomenon in Consciousness " ; and that we may be in no doubt as to his meaning, he says in his preface : " It might also run The Will as Idea (der Wille ah Vorstellung)." The will as idea that is the whole theory in a nutshell. No enemy could have put the case more conclusively against Mlinsterberg than he has done himself in these words, which are, nevertheless, the key - note of his whole inquiry. II. But this Presentationism or Phenomenalism, as has been already hinted, is not a new doctrine. It is a motive which has been widely influential in the history of philosophy. Let us generalise our conclusions, there- fore, and enforce them by historic example. Activity, as Berkeley long ago said, is not an idea, or anything like an idea, though doubtless activity is involved in the existence of any idea, seeing that ideas exist only for a subject, or, to be more exact, seeing that ideas, from the psychological point of view, are in every case just activities of some subject. But because, in the THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 115 nature of the case, action cannot be made a pres- entation of, cannot be held up as an object in the mental field of view, this theory proposes to efface activity altogether. In saying this, we are not attrib- uting to the Presentationists a conclusion which they disclaim. All real action, all real causality, is elimin- ated from their account of the universe as known. Causality is reduced, as with Hume, to mere sequence. We ourselves do not act we only seem to ourselves to act; in reality, we merely look on at happenings. Mlinsterberg suggests that the real agent in all these sequences, including the events which we mistakenly attribute to our own agency, may be, as Schopenhauer conceived, a unitary unconscious will. To this extent, therefore, he differs from Hume : he does not leave us with a purely sceptical phenomenalism. He is pre- pared to admit will or force, in this sense, as ultimate metaphysical reality and sole cause. But such an ad- mission has no bearing on our contention, so long as the psychological reality of the individual Will is denied. It must be admitted unreservedly that, if to know means to have a presentation before us, then we do not and cannot know the fact of our volitional activity. In this sense, we can only know the motives which led to it and the changes which followed upon it in the 116 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. phenomenal field. I am not advocating this usage, for I admit that it sounds -absurd to say that we do not know our own activity, our own existence. All I would urge is that, if the associations of " knowledge " with the objective, the presentable, the phenomenal, are ineradi- cable, then we shall be obliged to fall back upon some other term to express the acquaintance which the sub- ject has with his own activity. This is exactly the position which Berkeley took up, when he corrected his first impulse to resolve the Self into a procession of ideas. In his suggestive distinction between " ideas " and "notions," he anticipates and combats the Pan- phenomenalism of Hume and of such theories as we have been considering. There can be no idea formed [he says] of a soul or spirit ; for all ideas whatever being passive and inert, cannot re- present unto us by way of image or likeness that which acts. A little attention will make it plain to any one that to have an idea which shall be like that active principle of motion and change of ideas is absolutely impossible. Such is the nature of Spirit or that which acts, that it cannot be of itself perceived, but only by the effects which it pro- duceth. ... So far as I can see, the words will, soul, spirit, do not stand for different ideas, or in truth for any idea at all, but for something which is very different from ideas, and which, being an Agent, cannot be like unto or re- presented by any idea whatsoever, though it must be owned THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 117 at the same time that we have some notion of soul, spirit, and the operations of the mind, such as willing, loving, hating inasmuch as we know or understand the meaning of the words. 1 In a later section he formally repeats the distinction in the same terms 2 and adds : " I will not say that the terms idea and notion may not be used convertibly, if the world will have it so ; but yet it conduceth to clear- ness and propriety that we distinguish things very different by different names." And with his accus- tomed fine - edged irony, he remarks that " much scepticism about the nature of the soul " has arisen " from the opinion that spirits are to be known after the manner of an idea or sensation." "It is even probable that this opinion may have produced a doubt in some, whether they had any soul at all distinct from their body, since, upon inquiry, they could not find they had an idea of it." 3 The modern doctrine of automatism lends fresh point to this shaft of sarcasm. 1 Principles of Human Knowledge, section 27. 2 Section 142. "We may not, I think, strictly be said to have an idea of an active being or of an action, although we may be said to have a notion of any mind and its acts about ideas inasmuch as I know or understand what is meant by these words. What I know, that I have some notion of." 3 Section 137. The preceding section is also so aptly expressed, especially with reference to the subsequent argument of Hume, that I 118 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. Berkeley's proposed use of idea in this restricted or specific sense is equivalent to that of the modern terms presentation, phenomenon, or object ; and it will be observed how he expressly defines mind and spirit as " that which acts." It must be for ever impossible to phenomenalise an action ; we cannot objectify the subjective function as such. In his own words, that which acts cannot be itself perceived, but only by the effects which it produceth. But are we to conclude, therefore, that there is no activity in the case, that there is no active subject at all ? Surely not. On the contrary, it is in activity or the will that we, as it were, lay hold upon reality and have immediate assurance of it. And if, as already said, the associa- tions of " knowledge " are too narrow to permit of its application here, we must even fall back upon some cannot forbear reproducing it here. " It will perhaps be said that we want a sense (as some have imagined) proper to know substances withal, which, if we had, we might know our own soul as we do a triangle. To this I answer that, in case we had a new sense bestowed upon us, we could only receive thereby some new sensations or ideas of sense. But I believe nobody will say that what he means by the terms soul and substance is only some particular sort of idea or sensation. We may therefore infer that, all things duly considered, it is not more reasonable to think our faculties defective, in that they do not furnish us with an idea of spirit or active thinking substance, than it would be if we should blame them for not being able to comprehend a round square." THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 119 such phrase as "immediate assurance," "immediate experience," or " self-feeling." 1 There is, after all, a certain justification for the narrower use of the term knowledge. For is it not the case that knowledge, in its very nature, brings with it a species of foreignness ? Of course we all see clearly enough that there is another, and, I admit, a more im - portant sense, in which knowledge may truly be said to be just the overcoming, the banishing, of this strange- ness. The knower and his knowledge, as Aristotle said, are in a sense one. When we have thoughts, says Hegel, we recognise in nature's inner heart only our own reason, and feel at home there. " Spirit has the certainty which Adam had when he saw Eve. 'This is flesh of my flesh, and bone of my bone.' " No one, I say, will question that in this sense knowledge means unity, appropriation, the breaking down of the middle wall of partition. But that is without prejudice to the other and more subtle aspect of the case which I desire to emphasise. Knowledge, in its very nature, implies difference. What we know is an object, something held 1 The last phrase is used by Mr Bosanquet (Logic, vol. i. p. 77) in a passage in which he also speaks of "the immediate feeling of my own sentient existence that goes with " any act of perception. " Immediate experience" is used by Mr Stout in contrast to cognition or "discrim- inative thinking," 'Analytic Psychology,' Bk. I. c. i., and Bk. II. c. i. 120 THE as it were at a distance from us, something opposite to us. What we know is in fact always something different from ourselves. The knower and the known are never in this sense one, even in the limiting case of psycho- logical introspection. It is often said that here the observer and the observed are one and the same ; but the statement is not literally true. All intro- spection, it has been more truly said, is really retro- spection ; it is a post-mortem examination. When I know a state, that state has already ceased to exist as a living pulse of thought and feeling. It belongs to the past. I recognise it as having been mine ; but it is different from the present psychologically-minded self, intent upon its examination. 1 The case of introspec- tion has been mentioned, because there, if anywhere, it might be said that there was an identity of knowing and being. But, as we have just seen, it is not so. Knowing and being are not identical ; they cannot help being different. The fact is, we are face to face here with a constant characteristic of knowledge, and if, as we are apt to do, we take knowledge as exhaustive of 1 So Professor Sully and Professor James. The latest expression of this fact is perhaps to be found in Mr Stout's 'Analytic Psychology.' vol. i. p. 159 : " The immediate experience of any moment is never at that moment an object of thought." THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 121 experience, a far-reaching vista of consequences soon appears. We may interpret the characteristic in the relativistic sense which is so popular in agnostic and positivistic theories. We may say, knowledge never gives us the real thing; we are always going round about things, and always baffled with their mere out- sides. We know only phenomena; reality, whether of the self or the not-self, is beyond us. This is one line of thought which meets us in certain forms of Kantianism and Neo-Kantianism, in Hamilton, and in Spencer. Or, if we do not take this line, we fall into what I may call an Absolute Phenomenalism. In this case, we spurn the unknown and unknowable mystery of the relativists; we see that it is absurd to speak as if knowledge were constructed merely to baulk us. So far all seems well ; but we have not really escaped the consequences of accepting know- ledge as our ultimate. For we dissolve the universe altogether into objects or phenomena; all things and all finite persons, including ourselves, are merely objects in experience. And thus, in another way than the agnostic, we as surely deprive men and things of reality ; for mere objects are not real, they are halves craving completion. And that completion they do not get from the addition of a universal self. That uni- 122 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. versal self has itself no nerve of reality about it, if it is taken merely as the unifying self of knowledge. It is simply the formal unity of a spectacular process of phenomena. There is no warrant, on the theory, for understanding this self in any other way. If, then, we are to lay hold upon reality and lift our- selves out of the flux of phenomena, we must do so by a species of assurance different from knowledge, as knowledge has just been analysed and explained. Now, we have no such certainty of any reality, save the reality of self-existence. We know other things and other persons ; no sane person at least doubts that we do. But we do not immediately feel or experience their existence ; they are oilier beings, and their exist- ence is a hypothesis to explain certain phenomena of our own experience. And though the hypothesis is infinitely probable, it is theoretically open to doubt. Similarly, if we try to build even upon our own exist- ence as known, that existence tends to melt away into a dreamlike succession of phenomena passing before an inactive spectator, and the result is, that we fail to find reality anywhere. Existence resolves itself into a magic-lantern march of pictures, but, as Fichte says, without anything of which they are the pictures. It is not in knowledge, then, as such, but in feeling and THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 123 action, that reality is given. In saying this, I do not for a moment mean to do what I said before was im- possible, to divorce any of the three aspects of experi- ence from the others : the being who feels and acts must also know. Knowledge may even be said, with some truth, to be the pre-condition of the other two. But the immediate certainty of real existence attaches not to what is known in the knowledge, but to the accompanying awareness of subjective activity in the knowing act and the tinge of subjective feeling in connection with it. Knowledge is itself from this point of view an activity of the subject, and, as such, it will serve perfectly well as a basis of certainty. It is when the element of activity in knowledge is left out of sight, and attention is concentrated on the content or object of knowledge, that we enter upon a false path, and end in the self -contradictory notion of a knowledge which is nobody's knowledge, and a knowledge of nothing. But knowing is not a colour- less or impersonal function as it were a series of happenings in vacua. Every cognitive act is suffused with feeling, and in virtue of this suffusion it is felt by me as mine, by you as yours. In knowing any object, therefore, whether a thing in the external world or a state of his own mind, the knowing subject pos- 124 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. sesses, in this element of feeling, an immediate assur- ance of existence there and then. This certainty is, in the first instance, in the moment of acting, a pure immediacy, a mere awareness. After action, and to the psychological observer, it must be mediated by knowledge and reflection i.e., the changes are presented or represented in consciousness, and with them comes the feeling of self-origination, from which remembered conjunction springs the reasoned convic- tion of our active causality. But the reflective asser- tion of the psychologist depends entirely upon the immediate feeling the sense of living, as we might call it which went with the action originally. I feel the activity, the experience, at the moment, and in virtue of this immediate accompanying feeling, I after- wards acknowledge it as mine. It was not, therefore, without reason that Fichte 1 eventually returned to this primal certainty, as the sole means of escape from a limitless scepticism. Descartes's cogito, though intended to embrace the volitional aspect of consciousness, laid stress, designedly or not, upon the intellectual ; and the result was, that the real activity of the subject was discarded by his immediate successors. The content of consciousness 1 The reference is to his treatise on c The Vocation of Man. ' THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 125 became everything; the subject a mere empty vessel or form for the content. And in Spinoza, accordingly, we get a system or procession of idece, or modes of thought, and a parallel procession of ideata, the cor- responding modes of extension. The identity of in- tellect and will is one of Spinoza's central doctrines, and he presents us accordingly with a system in which real activity, or real causality, has as little place as it has in Miinsterberg's. His parallelism of modes of thought and modes of extension is, in fact, the very doctrine of Automatism which we have had under consideration. And it results from the very same considerations from exclusive attention to the intel- lect, to the knowledge-content of the mind. Scan the history of philosophy as we may, we shall find the same cause everywhere producing the same effect, now in a more materialistic form, now in the guise of Idealism ; but whether the automatism be materially or ideally conceived, matters practically not one jot. With the elimination of real causality from the course of things, the world is emptied of real meaning ; it is reduced to a spectacular sequence of happenings, which have no raison d'etre, seeing that all is absolutely predeter- mined from the outset. There is no life or reality in the show which passes before us ; for the nerve 126 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. of reality is furnished solely by the conviction of our own activity, our own real causality. And with the conviction of real activity, it is to be noted, goes the belief in an end or aim which the action is to realise. It is upon purposive, idea-guided action that Fichte takes his stand as the ultimate certainty. The idea is present to me, he says, not as a Naclibild or copy, an after -picture of an inde- pendent reality, but as a Vorbild, a fore-picture, an ideal or purpose, which does not yet exist, but which I have myself to make real. In the ingenious cari- cature which Miinsterberg offers us, he does not deny that this is the fundamental characteristic of voluntary action ; but, in accordance with his .presuppositions, he denies the reality of the nexus between the conception and its execution. It is undeniable that the one is before the other, but the first has no influence or efficacy in bringing about the second; for the whole train of happenings, he expressly tells us, is independ- ent of our consciousness. 1 The whole train is driven, in fact, a tergo by a Schopenhauerian dynamo-machine in the background. 1 Die Willenshandlung, p. 3. The bodily and the mental series, he says, are " zwei verschiedene Erscheinungsformen desselben einheitlichen, von unserem Bewusstsein unabhaugigen, wirklichen Geschehnisses. " THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. 127 The same line of thought which leads to the elimina- tion of real activity from the course of things, thus leads necessarily to the denial of purpose everywhere. And it is noteworthy, in this connection, that Spinoza is the most embittered opponent of any doctrine of teleology or final causes. To Spinoza, as to Mlinster- berg, all determination is mechanical, a tergo or from the past ; the notion of self-determination in view of ideas, determination a fronte or by the future, was inconceivable to him. The human being was to Spinoza as completely determined, and determined in the same way, as a stone propelled through the air. We do not know whether there is anywhere ' such purely mechanical causality as Spinoza took for granted in the case of the stone ; but we do know that that is not the mode in which the actions of conscious beings are determined. The causality of the future, or of the ideal, is coterminous at least with the confines of life. All action of living beings, I have argued, is originally purposive that is to say, in a wide sense, voluntary directed more or less clearly by the creature towards some aim. Only if this is so, is action in any sense an action of the creature itself, and not, in Mlinster- berg's language, "a phenomenal phase of the unitary happening " which goes on in the creature irrespective 128 THE "NEW" PSYCHOLOGY AND AUTOMATISM. of its feelings or desires. With the acknowledgment of purposive action, the wjiole process of things acquires a new aspect. It is no longer a motiveless procession of appearances, or, as Professor James well puts it, the dull rattling off of a chain forged ages ago. It is an evolution which is real at every point. And if it has seemed, in the course of this exposition, that knowledge and ideas have been depreciated at the expense of the will, they are here restored to their rightful function as the necessary conditions of selection or choice, the springs of all activity, and so the guiding star of all advance. But ideas in themselves are nothing, and the analysis of knowledge as knowledge can never give us reality. If we were to recast Descartes's formula, in the light of all that has come and gone in philosophy since his day, not Cogito ergo sum but Ago ergo sum is the form his maxim would take. A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 1 I. fTlHEEE can be little doubt among those qualified to judge, that Mr Bradley's 'Appearance and Eeality' is the most important metaphysical work which has appeared in England since the publication of Green's ' Introduction to Hume ' in 1874. It is so, in my opinion, not because its conclusions are likely to become assured possessions of philosophical thought, but because of the intrepidity of the treatment and the singularly stimulating quality which belongs to all that Mr Bradley writes. 1 Appearance and Reality : a Metaphysical Essay. By F. H. Bradley, LL.D. (Glasgow), Fellow of Merton College, Oxford. London: Swan Sonnenschein & Co. 1893. The criticism which follows appeared as two articles in the ' Contemporary Review ' of November and Decem- ber 1894. I 130 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. The author modestly says in his preface that his book does not design to be permanent. It is his contribution to the sceptical discipline of the English mind, from which he is not without hopes of seeing " a rational system of first principles " emerge. And it is true that the book is hardly likely to take its place as a classical treatise in the literature of the subject. The highly abstract character of most of the discussion, suggesting at times a delight in logic for logic's sake, the unadorned dryness (for the most part) of the style, and the seemingly deliberate per- versities of manner which mar it at times, forbid such a destiny. But the brilliant dialectic of which the book is full, the thoroughness and sincerity witli which it sifts the most vital questions, its ruthless criticism of conventional solutions, ensure for Mr Bradley's latest volume an important influence upon the thought of his contemporaries. Mr Bradley's courage is also to be commended in publishing a book which throughout deals avowedly and in set terms with " the Absolute." What a shock to the precisians of Agnosticism and the puritans of the empirical tradition ! This particular bogy, so potent in the middle of the century, has apparently lost its terror even for the English mind. As soon as A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 131 men began to reflect a little on what was meant by the term, it became evident that the ultimate object of philosophy always is, and must be, the Absolute. Mr Bradley's remarks, in his short Introduction, on the unavoidableness of metaphysical inquiry, the necessity of a new metaphysic for each fresh generation, and the utility of even an imperfect knowledge of the Absolute, may be commended to the candid reader who is still unconvinced, or perhaps a confirmed sceptic, on those points. The chapters of destructive criticism, which form the first part of the book, are largely in Hegel's manner, and the influence of Hegel is unquestionably predominant throughout. But in spite of this general indebtedness, the book is distinguished by an independ- ence of style and treatment not usual with followers of this master, or indeed of any master. But Mr Bradley has always insisted on calling his soul his own. Whatever else this volume may be, and whatever criti- cisms we may have to make upon it, it is certainly no easy reproduction of another man's thoughts: in the sweat of his own brow its author has conceived and executed it. This independence of treatment will prove of good omen, it may be hoped, for the future of philosophical 132 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. discussion among those who may be regarded, in a general way, as carrying on the traditions of Green arid representing the influence of Hegel, or at least of German Idealism, in British philosophy. In this connection, Mr Bradley's book may be said, perhaps, to mark the close of the period whose beginning was signalised, twenty-three years ago, by the publication of Green's work already mentioned. When we think of the Hamilton - Mill controversy in the sixties, it is obvious that serious study of the Critical Philosophy and German Idealism had yet to begin. Only the outworks of the Kantian scheme had been mastered even by the accredited leaders of British thought ; while Hegel, or at least his strangely refracted image, was simply the philosophical "bogy-man," useful to frighten back the unwary wanderer into the fold of Empiricism or the Philosophy of the Conditioned. Yet Hegel was probably the richest mind that had been devoted to philosophy since Aristotle, and, whatever judgment may be passed on his system as a logical whole, had done more than any other man to mould the thought of the century in all the humanistic sciences. The publication of Dr Hutchison Stirling's ' Secret of Hegel/ in 1865, first removed the reproach of ignorance A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 133 and indifference, or worse, from British philosophy. It was published in the same year as Mill's ' Examination of Hamilton,' and in the noisy, multitudinous echoes of that controversy, the accents of the new voice were partly drowned. But they penetrated, like tidings of a land that is very far off, to ears fit to receive them. While Mr Spencer's philosophy gradually established itself as the persuasion of the average man, the majority of serious thinkers in England were devot- ing themselves to the study of Kant and Hegel ; and Green's 'Introduction' was the first noteworthy symptom of this new direction of thought at the universities. The movement thus inaugurated has been growing in volume since then, and, as was to be expected, it has somewhat changed its character ; and Mr Bradley's book may perhaps be found in this respect to mark the end of the period of absorption or assimilation. During these Lehrjalire, English writers have repeated too anxiously, and with too minute exactitude, the formulae of a foreign master, treating them rather as oracles of truth than as utterances of finite wisdom, and showing too great a reluctance to submit them to legitimate criticism. But of late a calmer and more critical tone has been noticeable, and a more catholic spirit has shown itself. 134 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. Other names have claimed attention, such as Lotze on the one hand, and SchQpenhauer on the other (to mention only these two). As Mr Bradley puts it in his preface, " the present generation is learning that to gain education a man must study in more than one school." And the result of this wider range can hardly be other than to diminish the somewhat partisan zeal of the so-called neo-Hegelian party for the ipsissima verba of Hegel's theory, and to set them upon a more independent handling of the subject itself, in accordance with the genius of their own time and nation. Then the Lelirjalire and the Wanderjahre will be ended and the Meisterjahre will begin. For dis- ciples, as Bacon puts it in a well-known passage, do owe unto masters only a temporary belief and a sus- pension of their judgment till they be fully instructed, and not an absolute resignation or perpetual captivity. Though Germany once possessed the hegemony of Europe in matters philosophical, that time is past and the fact that it once existed constitutes no reason why we should remain in perpetual tutelage to German masters. "I have a high opinion," says Mr Bradley in his preface, "of the metaphysical powers of the English mind ; " and his book is conceived throughout in the spirit of intellectual freedom. A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 135 The author describes his work in the preface as " a critical discussion of first principles." " The chief need of English philosophy," he tells us, " is a sceptical study of first principles, and I do not know of any work which seems to meet this need sufficiently." The object of his own work is, therefore, " to stimulate inquiry and doubt " doubt or scepticism being understood to mean not doubt or disbelief in any particular tenets, but " an attempt to become aware of and to doubt all precon- ceptions." This is in Mr Bradley's mind and not without good reason the first and all-important con- dition of sound work in metaphysics. The short Intro- duction puts unanswerably the necessity and the utility of metaphysics. As it is impossible to abstain from thought about the universe, " the question is merely as to the way in which this should be done. . . . Meta- physics takes its stand on this side of human nature, this desire to think about and comprehend reality. And it merely asserts that, if the attempt is to be made, it should be done as thoroughly as our nature permits." On the second count, he maintains, as we have seen, that even a " miserably incomplete " know- ledge of the Absolute must have its usefulness. But in a passage of characteristic frankness and force he contends that, even if metaphysics has no positive 136 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. results, it would still be highly desirable that it should continue to be studied : There is, so far as I can see, no other way of protecting ourselves against dogmatic superstition. Our orthodox theology on the one hand, and our commonplace material- ism on the other (it is natural to take these as prominent instances) vanish like ghosts before the daylight of free sceptical inquiry. I do not mean, of course, to condemn wholly either of these beliefs ; but I am sure that either, when taken seriously, is the mutilation of our nature. Neither, as experience has amply shown, can now survive in the mind which has thought sincerely on first principles. That is one reason why I think that metaphysics, even if it end in total scepticism, should be studied by a certain number of persons. But, while thus insisting on the indispensable func- tion of metaphysical inquiry, Mr Bradley is not the man to magnify his office as metaphysician unduly. And in the Meredithian extracts from his note-book which conclude the preface, he characteristically turns the shafts of his irony against his own occupation. "Metaphysics," it is there written, "is the finding of bad reasons for what we believe upon instinct, but to find these reasons is no less an instinct." From the other glimpses vouchsafed into this note -book, its aphoristic treasures would appear to be of a highly various and piquant description. They cannot but A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 137 awaken an unchastened curiosity in the heart of many students, which it is to be hoped the owner of the note- book may take measures to satisfy. Mr Bradley starts with a threefold general definition of metaphysics. "We may agree, perhaps, to under- stand by metaphysics an attempt to know reality as against mere appearance, or the study of first prin- ciples or ultimate truths, or again the effort to com- prehend the universe, not simply piecemeal or by fragments, but somehow as a whole." These three definitions are plainly intended to be taken as equi- valent, but, though the third is probably the most satisfactory of the three, it is the first which gives the title to Mr Bradley 's volume, and it is the con- trast between appearance or, as he calls it here, "mere appearance" and reality that explains the two parts into which it falls. The first book, entitled " Appearance," is a sceptical or destructive criticism of the phenomenal world as inherently self -contradictory and incomprehensible, and therefore, in Mr Bradley's use of the word, unreal. The second book, entitled " Eeality," though also abounding in negative criticism of obnoxious "preconceptions," is the constructive complement of Book I., intended to describe the nature of the Absolute, in which the contradictionsof pheno- 138 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. mena must be somehow reconciled or overcome. It is important at the outlet, for the understanding of Mr Bradley 's argument, especially in its negative or sceptical aspect, to note the equivalence, or at least interchangeableness, of these different formulations of the metaphysician's task, even though his procedure and conclusions should turn out to be unduly dominated by the first. Keality is used by Mr Bradley through- out in the sense of ultimate reality, so that reality and the absolute are convertible terms, and he means by both " the universe " comprehended " somehow as a whole." Appearance, on the other hand, is applied to the whole of the phenomenal world. Appearances, of course, exist, as he repeatedly tells us, but they are not real, in the sense of being independent, self-con- tained and self-explanatory. We fall into hopeless contradictions if we attempt to take them so. Every finite or phenomenal fact betrays its character of " mere appearance " by the " ragged edges " which stamp it as a part torn out of its context. The self- contradiction of the part taken as the whole, the phenomenal taken as the real, is most obvious in the infinite progress upon which it launches us a species of treadmill exercise, best exemplified in the case of such notions as time, space, and causation. A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 139 The contradictions of the finite are, accordingly, the theme of Mr Bradley's First Book, in which he sets out to criticise the chief " ideas by which we try to under- stand the universe." Taking up, first, the popular scientific proposal to find the reality of the world in the primary qualities, he has little difficulty in showing that the line of thought which undermines the reality of the secondary qualities can be used with equal effect against the primary. The primary qualities cannot be conceived or presented without the second- ary ; and, further, we cannot think of extension with- out thinking at the same time of a " what " that is extended. Extension is, therefore, simply the abstrac- tion of one element from the rest, from which it is in reality inseparable an abstraction scientifically convenient, but metaphysically indefensible, when it puts itself forward as an ultimate account of things. The distinction of "substantive and adjective" the grouping of the world's contents into things and qualities is next taken up (chap, ii.) and declared to be "a clear makeshift." If we lay stress on the unity of the thing, then the plurality of its attributes is in no way explained ; they lie side by side in mere distinctness one from another, as so many independent coexistences. 140 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. The whole device is a clear makeshift. It consists in saying to the outside world, " I am the owner of these my adjectives," and to the properties, " I am but a relation, which leaves you your liberty." And to itself and for itself it is the futile pretence to have both characters at once. . . . The thing with its adjectives is a device for enjoying at once both variety and concord. But the distinctions, once made, fall apart from the thing, and away from one another, and our attempt to understand their relations brought us round merely to an unity, which confesses itself a pretence, or else falls back upon the old undivided substance which admits of no distinctions (p. 23). The next chapter (chap, iii.) analyses the ideas of quality and relation. Qualities depend upon the relation of things to one another; unrelated reals would be qualityless. But, on the other hand, "nothings cannot be related;" "relations must de- pend upon terms, just as much as terms upon rela- tions." Consequently, all thinking that moves by the machinery of terms and relations is pronounced to be "a makeshift, a device, a mere practical com- promise, most necessary, but in the end most inde- fensible." For there is the same attempt to bring di- versity into the unity of the thing, an attempt which proves impossible except by dividing the thing alto- gether into an endless process of relations. Hence, " our experience when relationed is not true ; " and A NEW THEOKY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 141 any one who has grasped the principle of this chapter, we are told, " will have condemned, almost without a hearing, the great mass of phenomena." Mr Bradley proceeds, however (in the next five chapters), to apply his principle more in detail to the cases of " space and time," " motion and change," " causation " and ''activity." In a time-honoured and somewhat well-worn argument, the aspects of discreteness and continuity in space are sceptically opposed to one another, and the conclusion reached that " space vanishes internally into relations between units which never can exist." Precisely the same argument holds of time ; hence, both are not real, but " contradictory appearances." The problem of change points back to the dilemma of the one and the many, the differences and the identity, the adjectives and the thing, the qualities and the relations. How anything can possibly be anything else was a question which defied our efforts. Change is little beyond an instance of this dilemma in principle. ... It asserts two of one, and so falls at once under the condemnation of our previous chapters. . . . Change, upon any hypothesis, is impossible. It can be no more than appearance (pp. 45-47). So with causation. If you resolve cause into identity, you eliminate the very fact to be explained the difference of the effect from its cause. For surely the 142 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. very problem of causation " consists in the differences and in their sequence in time." In fact, it is the old puzzle how to justify the attributing to a subject something other than itself, and which the subject is not. If " followed by B " is not the nature of A, then justify your predication. If it is essential to A, then justify, first, your taking A without it ; and in the next place show how, with such an incongruous nature, A can succeed in being more than unreal appearance" (p. 57). Activity is condemned because " nothing can be active without an occasion, and what is active, being made thus by the occasion, is so far passive." Hence, " it is certain that activity implies finitude, and otherwise possesses no meaning." It cannot, therefore, be an ultimate principle of explanation. Chap. viii. deals with " things," but the preceding argument has " under- mined and ruined " any meaning we can attach to the term. " The thing is a thing only if its existence goes beyond the now and extends into the past;" but "it does not appear how this relation of sameness can be real." "The identity of a thing lies in the view you take of it." "We seem driven to the conclusion that things are but appearances." So far, therefore, "our facts have turned out to be illusory," but we have been dealing up to this point with " the inanimate," and in order to complete his A NEW THEOKY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 143 argument Mr Bradley goes on in the next two chapters (chaps, ix. and x.) to criticise the claims of the Self to reality. In the first he passes in review different meanings of the self, and in the second he concludes that the self simply presents "the old puzzle as to the connection of diversity with unity." It will be necessary to return upon various points in these im- portant chapters, but we must first have Mr Bradley's main line of thought before us and the conclusion at which he arrives. It is sufficient, therefore, for the present, to note his verdict on the self, and the ground on which the verdict is explicitly based. "The con- sciousness of personal identity," he curiously says, " may be supposed to have some bearing on the reality of the self." Most people are probably benighted enough to think it has. But to my mind [proceeds Mr Bradley] it appears to be almost irrelevant. Of course the self, within limits and up to a certain point, is the same. ... As long as there re- mains in the self a certain basis of content, ideally the same, so long may the self recall anything once associated with that basis. . . . This, of course, shows that self-sameness exists as a fact, and that hence somehow an identical self is real. But, then, the question is how ? The question is whether we can state the existence and the continuity of a real self in a way which is intelligible, and which is not 144 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. ruined by the difficulties of previous discussions. Because, otherwise, we may have found an interesting fact, but most assuredly we have not found a tenable view about reality. . . . The end of metaphysics is to understand the uni- verse, to find a way of thinking about facts in general which is free from contradiction. . . . It is this, to repeat it once more, on which everything turns. The diversity and the unity must be brought to the light, and the principle must be seen to comprehend these. But the self is so far from supplying such a principle, that it seems, when not hiding itself in obscurity, a mere bundle of discrepancies. Our search has conducted us again, not to reality, but mere appearance (pp. 113, 120). The two short chapters on "Phenomenalism" and " Things in Themselves," which conclude the First Book, add nothing to this argument. They are rather of the nature of appendices, which deal effectively with these two phases of philosophic theory, as attempts either to evade the philosophical problem altogether, or to solve it by doubling it. As I am in complete agree- ment with Mr Bradley 's arguments in these pages, there is the less need to dwell upon them here. So I pass at once to the opening chapters of the Second Book, dealing with "The General Nature of Eeality," and containing the counter -stroke to the preceding negative polemic. The first position taken up is at once important, for A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 145 it alone enables a start to be made. Phenomena have been condemned as self-contradictory, but what is thus rejected as appearance admittedly still exists. " It cannot bodily be shelved and merely got rid of, and, therefore, since it must fall somewhere, it must belong to reality." Eeality, therefore, " must own," and some- how include, appearance ; it cannot be less than appear- ance. But whereas appearances, taken as real, proved self-contradictory, the absolute or ultimate reality must be " such that it does not contradict itself. This is our first criterion a criterion which has been implicit in all the preceding negative criticism." Accordingly... we may say, concludes Mr Bradley, that everything which appears is somehow real in such a way as to be self-consistent. . . . Appearance must belong to reality, and it must, therefore, be concordant and other than it seems. The bewildering mass of phenomenal diversity must hence somehow be at unity and self -consistent ; for it cannot be elsewhere than in reality, and reality excludes dis- cord. Or again, we may put it so ; the real is individual. It is one in the sense that its positive character embraces all deficiencies in an inclusive harmony (p. 140). In short, " reality must be a single whole " " a single system." In his second chapter Mr Bradley supple- ments this "formal and abstract" definition of the Absolute by identifying existence with "experience," K 146 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. laying down the position, almost in Berkeley's lan- guage, that existence has no meaning apart from sentient experience. " There is no being or fact out- side of that which is commonly called psychical existence." Any supposed fact, other than this, "is a vicious abstraction whose existence is meaningless nonsense, and is not possible." If we combine this with the former position, " our conclusion, so far, will be this, that the Absolute is one system, and that its contents are nothing but sentient experience. It will, hence, be a single and all-inclusive experience, which embraces every partial diversity in concord." Finally, Mr Bradley proceeds to ask whether we really have a positive idea of an Absolute, thus defined as " one com- prehensive sentience ; " and he answers that, while we cannot fully realise its existence, its main features are drawn from our own experience, and we have also a suggestion there of the unity of a whole embracing distinctions within itself. This we have in "mere feeling or immediate presentation," where we experi- ence as an undifferentiated whole, what we afterwards proceed, in the exercise of relational thought, to analyse into the known world of self and not -self, with all its manifold objects and distinctions. Combining this primitive experience of felt unity with the later ex- A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 147 perience of known diversity, we can recognise the latter as a transitional stage, and reach the idea of a higher experience in which thought shall, as it were, return to the immediacy of feeling. "We can form the general idea of an absolute intuition in which phenomenal distinctions are merged; a whole become immediate at a higher stage without losing any rich- ness." This view of the Absolute is developed and enforced in the immediately following chapter on "Thought and Keality" (chap, xv.) which, in various aspects, is one of the most important in the book. As such, it will claim our attention in the sequel ; but it is enough, in the meantime, to note a little more fully the nature of the results arrived at. The position reached is simply this, that "the relational form is a compromise on which thought stands and which it develops. It is an attempt to unite differences which have broken out of the felt totality" (p. 180). It is essentially an attempt to pass beyond itself and to recapture this immediate unity. But, both in theory and in practice, the attempt proves unsuccessful on the basis of thought or relation ; it resolves itself into the infinite progress. Thought's own ideal, there- fore, can be reached only by passing beyond thought. For us " this completion of thought beyond thought " 148 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. necessarily "remains for ever an other." Still " thought can form the idea of an apprehension, something like feeling in directness, which contains all the character sought by its relational efforts" "a total experience where will and thought and feeling may all once more be one," and where consequently the distinction between thought and its object between subject and predicate is likewise transcended. 1 We have now before us one complete phase of Mr Bradley 's position and argumentation, and it is time, therefore, to investigate critically the legitimacy of the method and the value of the conclusion. Mr Bradley started, as we saw, with two somewhat different defini- tions of the Absolute ; and, in like manner, his criticism throughout the First Book seems to rest upon two some- what different principles. The one condemns pheno- mena because they are fragmentary ; no object of experience is by itself a res completa, an independent and self-contained individual, strong in solid singleness, self-explaining, harmonious and all-inclusive. What- ever fact we take proves to be infected by external relations, and so carries us beyond itself, and ultimately brings in the whole context of the universe. Thus 1 See pp. 160, 172, 179, 181. A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 149 activity transforms itself into passivity, because we cannot think of activity as (so to speak) a mere bolt from the blue an unconditioned fiat out of a blank eternity. The beginning of the activity of anything depends, for our thinking, upon a stimulus from beyond the nature of the thing itself ; and the thing, therefore, is quite as much passive as active. This argument may be applied all round. Thought cannot rest in any finite individual, but is carried beyond it in an infinite pro- gress. So with any portion of space or time in which we arbitrarily and momentarily rest ; so with things, so last of all with the finite self. For I do not imagine that those who insist most strongly on the reality of the self, and hold that " it provides us with a type by the aid of which we may go on to comprehend the world/' are at all inclined to assert its reality in Mr Bradley's sense of all-inclusive self-sufficience. Obviously, the self of any individual, in the determinations of its character and the occasions of its activity, carries us beyond the self, just as in the case of things which are not selves. The self cannot be torn from its environment except by a process of violent abstraction ; and the environment, if we are to be exact, must be ultimately extended so as to include all time and all existence. To my mind, it requires no argument to establish the position that 150 A NEW THEOKY OF THE ABSOLUTE. there can be only one individual as a res completa, and consequently, in Mr Bradley's sense, only one reality, namely, the Absolute or the universe as a whole. To fail to realise this is to fail to rise to the light of reason at all ; it is, in Spinoza's phrase, to remain at the stage of "imagination," with its blind substantiation of the individuals of sense just as we find them, or seem to find them. In this whole line of argument, therefore including his admirable exposure of the fallacy of a plurality of independent reals Mr Bradley is certain to meet with hearty acquiescence in most quarters that are worth considering. But this line of argument does not seem sufficient of itself to justify the sweeping condemnation of phenomena as " mere appearance," " illusion," " self- contradictory appearance," "irrational appearance," " essentially made of inconsistencies," and the other terms of excommunication in which Mr Bradley in- dulges. Because a thing is not the Absolute, and never pretended to be, it seems a little hard to "ruin" its character by a string of bad names like this. And, as a matter of fact, the " ruin " in which Mr Bradley in- volves the phenomenal is more properly the consequence of a second line of argument, which is on the whole more prominent throughout the First Book. This argu- A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 151 ment is neither more nor less than the complete dis- crepancy of the One and the Many the impossibility of realising at all in thought any kind of identity in diversity. The passages quoted in the earlier part of this essay illustrate sufficiently the constant recur- rence of this idea. At the very outset, in dealing with substantive and adjective, it is referred to as " the old dilemma." If you predicate what is different, you ascribe to the subject what it is not ; and if you predi- cate what is not different, you say nothing at all (p. 20). The dilemma is, in truth, as old as the early Greek nominalists and sceptics who denied on these grounds the possibility of predication altogether, except in the form of an identical proposition. To say that " Socrates is good," would be to say the thing that is not; for " Socrates " and " good " are not the same, but different. "Socrates" is one idea, and "good" is another. "Socrates is Socrates," and " good is good ; " but that the one should be the other, is quite unintelligible. We are limited, therefore, to the one kind of proposition which we never make, A = A. Now, strange as it may seem, Mr Bradley's First Book is, in essence, neither more nor less than a restatement and re- enforcement of this sceptical thesis. He adopts this logic of abstract identity apparently without reserve, and because it brings him 152 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. to a dead-lock, he pronounces the actual world to be " unintelligible," " inconsistent," " self - contradictory," " irrational," " untrue," " illusory." His multitudinous repetitions seem designed to leave us in no doubt that it is everywhere the same touchstone which he applies. Thus, the conclusion of the third chapter, on " Eelation and Quality," is, as we have seen, that a relational way of thought is "a mere practical compromise, most necessary, but in the end most indefensible." We have to take reality [he continues] as Many, and to take it as One, and to avoid contradiction. . . . But when these inconsistencies are forced together, as in meta- physics they must be, the result is an open and staring discrepancy. . . . Our intellect, then, has been con- demned to confusion and bankruptcy, and the reality has been left outside uncomprehended (pp. 33, 34). In the next chapter, " Space ... is a peculiar form of the problem which we discussed in the last chapter, and is a special attempt to combine the irreconcilable " (p. 36). In the fifth chapter (in the passage already quoted) the problem of change points back to the dilemma of the One and the Many, the differences and the identity, the adjectives and the thing, the qualities and the relations. How anything can possibly be anything else was a question which defied our efforts. Change is little beyond an instance of this dilemma in A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 153 principle. . . . Change, it is obvious, must be a change of something, and it is obvious, further, that it contains diversity. Hence it asserts two of one, and so falls at once under the condemnation of our previous chapters (p. 45). So in the following chapter, on " Causation " : If the sequence of the effect is different from the cause, how is the ascription of the difference to be rationally defended ? If, on the other hand, it is not different, then causation does not exist, and its assertion is a farce (p. 55). We assert something of something else. ... It is the old puzzle, how to justify the attributing to a subject something other than itself, and which the subject is not (p. 57). Having found things "go to pieces" when confronted with this test, he finds the same result on applying it to the self. It is the old puzzle as to the connection of diversity with unity. As the diversity becomes more complex and the unity grows more concrete, we have, so far, found that our difficulties steadily increase, and the expectation of a sudden change and a happy solution, when we arrive at the self, seems hence little warranted. . . . You may say that we are each assured of our personal identity in a way in which we are not assured of the sameness of things. But this is unfortunately quite irrelevant to the question. That selves exist, and are identical in some sense, is indubitable. But the doubt is whether their sameness, as we apprehend it, is really intelligible. . . . Does it give an experience 154 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. by the help of which we can really understand the way in which diversity is harmonised 1 (pp. 103, 104). The self, as feeling, thrusts upon us, " in a still more apparent form, the discrepancy that lies between identity and diversity, immediate oneness and relation" (p. 107). If, again, self-consciousness is proposed as " a special way of intuition or perception," we are forced to ask (supposing such a " self-apprehension of the self as one and many " to exist) how it can " satisfy the claims of understanding." "For the contents of the intuition (this many in one), if you try to re- construct * them relationally, fall asunder forthwith. I am, in short, compelled to this conclusion, even if your intuition is a fact, it is not an under- standing of the self or of the world. It is a mere experience" (p. 108). In whatever aspect the self is taken, therefore, it does not teach us " how to under- stand diversity or unity" (p. 112). What we want is " a view . . . combining differences in one so as to turn the edge of criticism" (p. 114), and this we have not met with. The self, as will or volition, leaves us involved in all "the old troubles as to 1 The italics in the passage last quoted are Mr Bradley 's own, and I desire specially to call attention to the emphasis, as it corroborates my contention and contains the key to Mr Bradley's position. A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 155 diversity in union with sameness " (p. 115). In com- menting on the theory of Monads, towards the close of his discussion, he repeats his old question : Will it in the least show us how 1 the diversity can exist in harmony with the oneness, (p. 118). . . . "We have found so far [he says] that diversity and unity cannot be reconciled. Both in the existence of the whole self in relation with its contents, and in the various special forms which that existence takes, we have encountered everywhere the same trouble. We have had features which must come together, and yet were willing to do so in no way that we could find. In the self there is a variety, and in the self there is an unity ; but in attempting to understand how, we fall into inconsistencies which, therefore, cannot be truth (p. 118). The self, he finally concludes, does not yield us " any defensible thought, any intellectual principle, ly which it is possible to understand how diversity can be com- prehended in unity. It is this, to repeat it once more, on which everything turns. The diversity and the unity must be brought to the light, and the principle must be seen to comprehend these" (pp. 119, 120). The short chapter on " Phenomenalism " adds two further references to " the metaphysical problem of the Many in One" (pp. 124, 125); and, in the last chapter, things-in-themselves are found to " offer pre- 1 The italics are again Mr Bradley's own. 156 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. cisely the old jungle in which no way could be found " (p. 130). I have multiplied these references, at the risk of wearying the reader, in order to convince him, if he needs convincing, of the uniform and persistent nature of Mr Bradley 's demand. It seems to me, moreover, that Mr Bradley's position here conditions the whole nature of the results he arrives at later. For the logic of abstract identity which he brings into the field against phenomena is fatal in the end to his Absolute also, reducing it, in spite of Mr Bradley's disclaimer in spite of his sincere endeavour to avoid such a con- summation to the undifferentiated unity of Spinoza's Substance. According to this logic, each qualityless point remains identical with itself (A = A), and so does each unreferred quality, flying loose in the heaven of abstraction (red is red, a is a, and b is 5). But the living synthesis of fact the qualified thing, A that is a, b, c, d, any number of differences, in unity this, if not actually denied as in some sense existing, is yet declared to be unintelligible, hopelessly contradictory. But surely such an argument marks the very acme of logical perversity. Such an argument, in truth, imports into predication a meaning or intention of which predi- cation never dreams. When we say "man is mortal," A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 157 or "the beech has a smooth stem," we do not mean that the concept " man " is identical with the concept " mortal," or that the two concepts " beech " and " smooth - stemmed " are actually one and the same concept. What we mean is that the reality, which we have already qualified as "man" or "beech," is further qualified as " mortal " or " smooth-stemmed." All predication, in short, is about facts, not about concepts except in the special cases where we happen to be defining a word. Certainly every concept or meaning remains itself, and only itself, to all eternity. That at least is the convention on which logic stands; our terms must bear the same meaning throughout, otherwise all reasoning would be impossible. The law of identity or of non-contradiction means no more than this obviously indispensable con- vention a convention which, if we are so minded, we may truthfully describe as a fundamental and necessary law of thought, so long as we see clearly its innocent and unobtrusive meaning. The law of identity says that, if we predicate mortality of man, we cannot also predicate non-mortality ; it says that, if it is the nature of the beech to be smooth - stemmed, it cannot also be its nature to be rough-stemmed. But, as to the nature of predication, or as to the possibility or impos- 158 A NEW THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE. sibility of a thing existing as the unity of diverse qual- ities, it gives no verdict one way or another. These are questions of fact or of metaphysics which lie beyond its scope. To proceed, therefore, on the strength of the law of identity, to condemn the idea of a thing possessing qualities, or, in general, the idea of unity in diversity, as a contradiction in terms, is logically a complete nerd/Baa-is et? aXXo