R. C. ROSE. JVo. n LIBRARY 0NWERSITY Of CAUFORtM* SANOfQO presented to the LIBRARY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA SAN DIEGO by FRIENDS OF THE LIBRARY MR. JOHN H. RO.SK donor A THEORY OF CONDUCT A THEORY OF CONDUCT BY ARCHIBALD ALEXANDER FORMERLY PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN COLUMBIA COLLEGE NEW YORK CHARLES SCRIBNER'S SONS 1890 Copyright, 1890, BY CHARLES SCRIBNER'S SONS. All rights reserved. The Riverside Press, Cambridge, Mass., U. S. A. Electrotyped and Printed by H. O. Houghton & Company. CONTENTS. PAGB I. INTRODUCTION i II. THE THEORY OF RIGHT ... 20 III. THE THEORY OF DUTY . . .46 IV. THE NATURE OF CHARACTER . . 58 V. THE MOTIVE TO MORALITY . .80 A THEORY OF CONDUCT. I. Introduction. WITHIN the last few years there has been an unusual interest awakened in moral science. The causes of this are not hard to discover. In the first place, the history of philosophy shows that where a decay of belief in the popular religion is manifested among the more intellectual classes, there is likely to be a demand for something to take the place of the popu- lar religion. This demand is usually sup- plied by systems of morality which are often merely dogmatic guides for practi- cal life. For example, the philosophy be- fore Socrates, which was chiefly physical, 2 A Theory of Conduct. and the philosophy of the Socratic period, which was mainly metaphysical, were fol- lowed by the very practical systems of the Stoics, the Epicureans, and Skeptics, who sought to solve the problem of life and to present a philosophy of character. The systematic philosophy which supplanted the mythology of Greece, the popular creeds associated with the Olympian gods, had in some cases silenced the oracles, in others aroused doubts as to the reality of the heroic and dramatic figures of Homer and ^Eschylus. The Theogony of Hesiod was at length received with incredulity in later times, and new shrines and forms of worship had to be constructed to take the place of those which no longer at- tracted their devotees. Just as the pre- Sophistic thinkers had rested unsatisfied with a mythological explanation of Na- ture, and had set forth a science of the elements or an atomic theory ; so the post-Aristotelian thinkers looked askance at oracles and auguries, and applied, ac- Introduction. 3 cording to their lights, the methods of science to the conduct of men. It may indeed be said that the successful ad- vance of Christianity was due in some measure to the fact that the Stoic and Epicurean had taught in vain. The gos- pel addressed to the "weary and heavy laden " spoke to the jaded minds of those whose religion had lost its life, whose phi- losophy was insufficient. During the Patristic and Scholastic ages, when the Church supplied the rule of human conduct, and enforced its de- crees through the spiritual direction of the priesthood or the force of the civil authority, there was but little disposition toward original ethical inquiry. But with the religious doubts excited at the time of the Reformation came inquiries as to the application of the Christian code of morals ; and the seventeenth century is noted for the thorough and able discus- sions of the Jesuits and other learned writ- ers on practical ethics. The writings of 4 A Theory of Conduct. the Spanish and French casuists furnish a striking example of an attempt to place on a more rational foundation rules of ac- tion prescribed by the Church, but sub- jected to the criticism of the unbeliever. Ethical reaction in a different form is illustrated by the moral science of Ger- many during the latter half of the eigh- teenth century. The dogmatic philoso- phy which culminated in the system of Wolff did not set forth any original doc- trine of ethics. We must of course ex- cept Spinoza in making this general state- ment. But when the period of the Auf- kldrung came, and with it the skepticism with regard to ecclesiastical claims and Scriptural authority, there was a tendency on the part of many to look for princi- ples of action independent of Revelation. Until the publication of Kant's ethical treatises, some were disposed to borrow from abroad what they did not find at home. The Critique of Practical Reason cannot be well understood unless it is re- Introduction. 5 membered that the sentimental ethics of Scotland and the sensualistic ethics of France had found a place in many Ger- man minds. The ethical development in France, just before the revolution, was it- self partly a reaction against the ecclesi- asticism which Voltaire and some of his contemporaries had so vigorously and in- sidiously attacked. Analogous to such reactionary changes is the ethical movement in Great Britain and Germany at the present time. It is not that this age is generally over-skep- tical. On the contrary, it may be doubted whether there was ever a time when the great mass of the people in Europe and America were so effectively interested in religious affairs. This is shown in many ways, by financial expenditure, by sta- tistics as to the increased membership of orthodox communions, by energy in the support of missions, by a high class of re- ligious literature, and in some countries by a considerable improvement in moral 6 A Theory of Conduct. conduct. But among men of science and letters, among the learned and intellect- ual classes, there is a very large number of people who have lost either wholly or in part their faith in revealed religion. There are many, for example, who would not be willing to follow Hume's rigorous logic, but are quite ready to pursue the middle way of Agnosticism. There are many who admire the Old Testament for its literary qualities, and the New Testa- ment for its gracious teachings, but who refuse to accept the book of Genesis as a true account of the world's beginning, and the Sermon on the Mount as a code of action. Whether the doctrine of Evo- lution has been demonstrated to be true or not, whether it can be reconciled with the traditional creed or not, one thing seems to be quite certain : the gen- eral effect of the teachings of that the- ory has been prejudicial to religion, in making men disregard the authority of the Church. This has of course been due, to Introduction. 7 a very great extent, to the ignorance and imprudence of many who have had reli- gious zeal, but little scientific knowledge. How far men are justified in losing faith in revealed religion in so far as they ac- quire scientific knowledge is not to be considered here. What must be consid- ered is this, that the advance of natural science by the aid of the evolution-theory has been extraordinary, and has produced a reaction in many minds against what is often called Orthodoxy. This condition of affairs has been aggravated by the de- velopment of that historical school which can trace its lineage to Spinoza, and which in this century has found its most radical representatives at Tubingen. In its mod- ified form it has sympathizers in some Protestant theological seminaries. It has the same kind of respect for the Bible that Luther had for the Pope. It is not nec- essary to estimate here the value of its labors ; it is important to notice that the effect of its teaching has been to lessen 8 A Theory of Conduct. the authority and influence of Revelation, and to emphasize the importance of Rea- son. There are no longer open enemies to Christianity as able as Voltaire and Hume and the doubters of the eighteenth century. But quite as effective opposi- tion to the supremacy of Revelation in matters of faith can be maintained by men who have taken their degree in Di- vinity. While it is possible, and may be logical, to reject as unworthy of belief certain parts of the teaching of the Scrip- tures, and yet hold that in them is to be found the essence of ethical doctrine, it cannot be denied that the rejection of any part of Revelation on rational grounds in- volves the establishment of a principle on which such rejection is made. If the re- jected doctrine be ethical, and the prin- ciple on which it is rejected ethical, it follows that so far Revelation and ethics are independent. The spread of Agnos- ticism and of belief in the theory of Ev- olution has had a positive as well as a Introduction. 9 negative effect in the realm of ethics. It is not merely that unbelief in Revela- tion has been caused by these doctrines ; it is that they have furnished a founda- tion for ethical systems which are held to be in contradiction to those of revealed religion. It is natural, therefore, that those who have been led to doubt that which has been " revealed " should be will- ing to accept the logical conclusions of that which has given rise to the doubt. It may be asked, however, Cannot one who believes in the possibility of a ra- tional system of ethics be at the same time a believer in the ethics of Revela- tion ? Is it not possible that the conclu- sions of science and those of religion will be found to coincide ? It may be held that the ethical doctrine founded on Rea- son is in reality a vindication of the eth- ics of Revelation, or conversely that Rev- elation confirms what Reason finds to be true. This point will command our atten- tion elsewhere, and the apparent opposi- 10 A Theory of Conduct. tion beween Reason and Revelation will be noticed. For the present it is suffi- cient to say that the ethics of Revelation must be absolute, so that a criticism of such ethics from a rational point of view will be in part a criticism of what is called the theory of absolute right, or Intuition- alism. A glance at the number of important works on moral science which have lately appeared will, we believe, justify the propo- sitions stated above. The history of Eng- lish ethics during the nineteenth century gives a sufficient proof. The spread of what is popularly known as the utilitarian theory is usually attributed to Jeremy Ben- tham and his followers, but the theory is as old as systematic ethics themselves. It was Bentham who first stated it boldly. 1 It was found in a more or less explicit form in the doctrines of Hobbes and Hutcheson. The theory of the earlier Epicureans is 1 Vol. v. p. 20. Introduction. // a form of utilitarianism. Socrates and Plato in their doctrine that the General Good was the ethical end were stating the principle of utilitarianism in a partial and illogical way ; although Aristotle's view of happiness as something objective can hardly be classified with the doctrines of the school. According to Socrates and to Plato virtue is knowledge of the good. Socrates called it the chief good Plato more often, the ideal good ; but the essence of the good was its utility. This appears distinctly in more than one of the Platonic dialogues, but is directly contradicted in others. The utilitarian theory is a logical result of empiricism, so that John Stuart Mill's ethics was a proper consequence of his psychology as well as a modified form of Bentham's cynical teachings. When Darwin's theory of species and develop- ment had been followed by his crude sug- gestions as to moral doctrine, when Her- bert Spencer had shown implicitly by the principles of his Philosophy and Psychol- 12 A Theory of Conduct. ogy that those who accepted his teaching must build up a new system of ethics, there was a natural tendency toward an ethical reaction. Accordingly we find pub- lished in rapid succession treatises dealing with all sides of the ethical problem : ju- dicial works like that of Professor Sidg- wick, orthodox and conservative works like that of Dr. Martineau, evolutionary works like those of Mr. Spencer and Mr. Leslie Stephen, works imbued with the spirit and method of the absolute philosophy like those of Mr. Bradley and Mr. Green. It is not too much to say that the writings just referred to are the most valuable con- tributions to the literature of ethical sci- ence which this century has produced. Some of them have been expressions of radical doctrine, while some owe their ori- gin to the controversy which that radical doctrine has excited. Those which bear distinctly the marks of German thought have been more or less inspired by the teaching of Fichte and Hegel. Introduction. 13 It is my purpose to discuss as concisely as possible some of the more important principles which are the foundation of all ' moral science, and it is my hope that I may be able in setting aside much that is false, to arrive at conclusions which are beyond doubt. It is also my purpose to notice briefly the harmony of moral science and revealed religion. Moral conduct involves generally two things : i. A standard of Morality. 2. Volition. Where the volition is in agreement with the standard the action is moral or right. Where it is in disagreement, the action is immoral or wrong. There are indifferent actions, however, but these are in reality right actions. The test of an indifferent action is not that its performance is not wrong, but that its non-performance is as right as its performance. It will be ad- mitted on all sides that, if there be a moral science, there must be a moral standard. This standard may or may not be absolute and ultimate. If it be absolute and ulti- 14 A neory of Conduct. mate it is unnecessary to analyze it or to attempt its analysis into simple elements. If it be neither absolute nor ultimate, one has a right to inquire what its nature may be. One has a right to ask what makes the standard of right. It is possible to explain without analyzing even an absolute stand- ard. For example, without attempting to unfold the nature of Tightness, one may say that the standard is fixed by an author- ity such as the will of God ; or by an im- mutable principle according to which God directs his will and wills that man should act. But in these cases there is no higher court to which appeal can be made. The question Why is this absolutely right ? can be answered only by saying, Because God wills it or because it is in agreement with an immutable principle. Refuge cannot be taken in the proposition that right is what is in accordance with the " eternal fitness of things," for the term "fitness " becomes the object of inquiry, and fitness must mean Tightness or else the principle of Right is not absolute and ultimate. Introduction. /5 But the standard of morality may be re- garded as something relative or derived. It may be said that right actions are right because they are beneficent, because they tend to improve the condition of society, to advance its interests, and so to promote its happiness. It may be said that right- ness will then vary according to the con- ditions of society, so that what is right under some circumstances may be wrong under others. Morality from such a point of view has no absolute meaning, and may be shown to be derived from certain non- moral principles, such as sentiment, self- love, or custom and habit. It is the prob- lem of the scientific moralist who rejects the theory of an absolute right to explain the meaning and derivation of the relative right which is the standard of Moral Ac- tion. This makes a large part of moral inquiry an analysis of the term "ought." We ought to do what is right ? Right is what we ought to do. What ought to be done is a question which can be answered 1 6 A Theory of Conduct. in two general ways. It may be said the right ought to be done, and the right is ultimate ; or the right ought to be done, right being that which derives its right- ness from certain consequences. If a conclusion be reached as to the nature of right, one is forced to inquire, How can that which is right be known ? Is right correlate with knowledge, or with feeling, or with both ? Is right something of which I become aware by the rise of certain emotions, or is its reality deter- mined by an act of knowledge, or do both knowledge and emotion combine to inform me ? Several answers to these questions have been given. For the present I may leave the subject to consider generally the second main object of ethical inquiry which is volition. Every moral action is volun- tary. But every act of volition is complex. It implies a motive according to which the volition is made. It implies the action of the will itself, and the end of the action. As it will be necessary hereafter to dis- Introduction, 17 cuss the exact relation of the motive to the will, it is well here to define the terms just used. The motive may be said to consist of that state of mind which is the imme- diate occasion of the will's acting in a cer- tain way. It will be found that every act of the will involves an act of knowledge and a desire. The act of knowledge causes the desire. Two men may each have the same knowledge at a given moment, yet the desires awakened by such knowledge may be different. Motive, therefore, should properly comprehend not merely the know- ledge and the desire, but what is called character. It is customary, however, to regard the character as independent, and to confine the term " motive " to some im- pulse, or affection, or desire. But it will be seen that this obscures the important fact that the impulse or desire is so closely connected with the character of the per- son who wills, that the direction of the will in most cases may be said to depend i8 A Theory of Conduct. on the character. This may be explained by an illustration. Here are two men, A. and B. To follow a certain course of ac- tion is suggested by worldly considera- tions, such as ambition, enjoyment of ease, love of power. The same course of action lies open to each ; the same object ap- peals to each. In the case of A. the mo- tive of ambition is stronger than the mo- tive to do right. Why is this ? The only explanation to be found is in A.'s char- acter; for the same object is before B. The motives so called are not real mo- tives, but only tendencies. B. prefers to follow a moral course of action, because his desire to be moral is stronger than other desires. And why ? The only ex- planation to be found is in B.'s character. It will be suspected by some that this is urged to support a doctrine of the Free- dom of the Will ; but a later chapter will doubtless dispel such an impression. The end of voluntary action is not the motive, but usually excites the desire which moves Introduction. 19 the will. These general suggestions I have made before beginning an analysis of moral principles. The importance of such an analysis as I have just suggested is self-evident. It has been often observed that false mo- rality that is, morality founded on false principles is more dangerous than ac- tual immorality. The justification, on sup- posed moral principles, of wrong actions, is far more dangerous to the individual and to society than the performance of immoral actions which are admitted or rec- ognized as such. And it may be learned from history how often false systems of ethics have first corrupted society and % then led it to martyrdom. II. The Theory of Right. Two distinct questions present them- selves in connection with the theory of right, which I shall now attempt to an- swer : 1. What is the nature of right? 2. How is right known ? It is not necessary to discuss the ety- mology of the term. Right is the contra- dictory of wrong, but is not the contra- dictory of bad. Right is what is morally good. The great fault of ancient ethics, and of a great part of modern ethics, as many know, consists in the failure to dis- tinguish between what is right and what is good. The dialogues of Plato abound in examples of this confusion. The pun- ishment of a criminal, for example, may in some instances be bad for him. It may The Theory of Right. 21 cause him pain. It may harden instead of reforming him. It may put his family in distress. The Tightness of punishing him depends on some legal, and ultimately on some moral principle. What the nature of this principle is forms a most important question in eth- ics. The theory which is ordinarily called the theory of consequences makes the mo- rality of conduct depend primarily on the results of conduct. The result of moral conduct is happiness. The result of im- moral conduct is unhappiness. There is a difference of opinion as to the extent of happiness or unhappiness so involved. According to some it is the happiness or unhappiness of self which is in question ; according to others it is the happiness of others. In one case we have what is known as Egoism ; in the other what is known as Altruism. The theories are often described as egoistic and altruis- tic Hedonism. In both of them morality is primarily objective. The result, not 22 A Theory of Conduct. the motive, of conduct must be considered in order that the morality of the conduct may be estimated. To murder a man is wrong, because murder results in unhap- piness ; and so murderous motives are wrong, because they tend to cause mur- derous conduct. If happiness were the result of murderous conduct, and if un- happiness were produced by not murder- ing, then murder would be right and mur- derous motives would be right. To take human life in order to promote my own happiness is to act morally if I am an Egoist. To take it in order to promote the happiness of others is to act morally if I am an Altruist. In this way it is ar- gued that the execution of criminals, the taking of life in war, the taking of life in self-defense, are actions which cannot be judged of per se, but are to be judged from the amount of happiness or unhap- piness which results from them. From this point of view, in judging of conduct, the motive has a moral value only The Theory of Right. 23 in so far as it influences, or tends to in- fluence, the action. If I perform a be- nevolent action from motives of vanity, and that action is conducive to happiness, then my conduct is moral. It cannot, accord- ing to our premises, be said that the mo- tive is immoral because the consequences of the act produce happiness, and the motives of vanity produce, and tend to produce, the act. If it be said that such motives are moral in so far as they produce beneficent acts, but are immoral because they injure the character and corrupt so- ciety, it follows that our definition of con- duct must be modified, that it includes something more than motive, act, and end. According to the theory of conse- quences, the performance of an action detrimental to the happiness of self or of others is immoral, no matter what the character of the motive may be. It is no justification, then, of murder, or theft, or any interference with happiness, that it is committed with a good motive. However 24 A Theory of Conduct. good and pure the motive may be, the consequences of its influence are the tests of the moral conduct which it affects. The other general theory opposed to that of consequences is the theory that the Tightness or wrongness of actions is to be judged primarily by the motive, and only secondarily by the consequences. It is said fiat justitia mat cesium. Now it would manifestly be a most unhappy con- dition of affairs were the heavens to fall. According to the advocate of the theory of consequences, it would be plain that justice had not been done were the catas- trophe to happen. But to one who adopts the doctrine that the consequences are not the primary tests of moral conduct, it is quite possible that there should be un- happy consequences following a course of moral conduct. It may be remarked, how- ever, that this pessimistic view is rare, and the position of Kant is ordinarily taken that there is an agreement between morality and happiness, so that to follow The Theory of Right. 25 the one insures the other. If this view of what may be called intrinsic morality be adopted, there can be no such thing as casuistry. It can never be right to lie, because lying is intrinsically wrong. If it be said there are circumstances in which lying is right, there are occasions in which doing wrong is justified, and becomes right by reason of the consequences, then we abandon the position just referred to, and are taking up the theory of consequences. There are very few men in our time, how- ever, who are willing to follow this the- ory of right to its logical conclusions. Those who do so are usually looked upon as foolish or fanatical, while the social and legal sanctions are here in disagree- ment with the moral sanction. For if the consequences justify the sup- posed bad action, it is impossible to deny that the more serious the consequences anticipated from doing right, the more in- advisable it becomes that the right should be done. It is conceivable that the stand- 26 A Theory of Conduct. ard of right would then vary with the esti- mate made by moral agents as to the prob- able consequences. In looking generally at these two the- ories of right, it must be affirmed, with Bentham, that happiness is the end of all human action. It is the prime motive. It is generally admitted that the conduct of all men is consciously directed toward the attainment of happiness. One may go further and say that the conduct of each man is naturally directed toward the attainment of his own happiness. This proposition is different from the proposi- tion that each man ought so to direct his conduct. The selfishness which, accord- ing to writers like Hobbes, and La Roche- foucauld, and Helvetius, is the spring of all action is so common that it has led many to confound what is with what ought to be. If morality were something which would bring unhappiness, and if the road to happiness were the pursuit of immoral ends, no man would care to do what is The Theory of Right. 27 right. What does it signify that I break every rule of morality provided that I am happier from so doing? If you say you may be happy now, but eventually pain and remorse will take the place of your present enjoyment, you contradict the proposition with which we set out. We are accustomed to say that "in the end" a virtuous course of conduct will bring happiness. We endure present pains or inconveniences, we make present self-sac- rifices, as means to the furtherance of future and permanent happiness. Even those who sacrifice health, or life, or for- tune for others even martyrs who have forsaken a life of ease, and who have lan- guished in prisons or burned at the stake have had their eyes fixed on an eter- nity of joy which would be lost to them were they not to welcome the immediate pain. I affirm, then, that if there be dis- agreement between happiness and mo- rality, it is useless to attempt to persuade men to be moral. If a man be persuaded 28 A Theory of Conduct. that adultery, and murder, and theft are the means to eternal happiness, he will follow them in spite of any immutable prin- ciple or the still small voice of conscience. It is useless to tell such a man of the beauty of virtue, of the nobility of self- sacrifice, of the intrinsic Tightness of gen- erosity and kindness, if he believes that the exercise of such qualities will make him unhappy ; then he will prefer happi- ness to virtue, whether he be a sinner or a saint. But, as I said above, there are few who take so pessimistic a view, and men have been accustomed to regard vir- tuous conduct as the means to the high- est and most permanent happiness. So close has this identification of the two be- come, that one school of morals affirms the test of moral conduct to be the quan- tity of happiness which it brings. The most logical supporters of this theory con- sider that the conduct which we should call moral is that which produces the max- imum of happiness, irrespective of the The Theory of Right. 29 quality of that happiness ; and, conversely, immoral conduct tends to produce unhap- piness. The only reason why one kind of happiness should be sought rather than another (in so far as the ethical aspect of the matter is concerned) is on account of its greater intensity or more enduring character. As soon as we admit a differ- ence in the quality of pleasures, the theory of " happiness " as the test of morality is abandoned. All pleasures must be re- garded as having the same ethical value. This was the position taken by Bentham, and its modification by John Stuart Mill was inconsistent with the latter's utili- tarianism. For as soon as we admit a difference of moral quality in different kinds of happiness, we are obliged to ask why one kind is more moral than another, and thus set up a standard of morality other than the utilitarian. We have no right, then, to say that the pleasure of a man who is enjoying the delight of good eating and drinking is morally inferior to jo A Theory of Conduct. that of a man whose philanthropic soul is elated at seeing paupers warmed, and clothed, and fed, unless it can be shown that the latter pleasure is more intense or more lasting than the first. Both inten- sity and permanence depend, as will be seen, very largely on the character of the man. The prevailing tendency in the field of ethics is to reject Egoism and to advo- cate the altruistic theory. Moral conduct is that which produces the greatest hap- piness, not of self alone, but of the great- est number. What has been said above, however, with regard to the possible dis- agreement of happiness and moral con- duct is applicable here. It is impossible to persuade men to seek after the happi- ness of others unless they are convinced that such conduct will secure their own happiness. An amiable man is one who derives happiness in viewing the welfare of others ; a malevolent man is one who does not. It is important, therefore, to The Theory of Right. 31 remember that altruism cannot per se be a theory of morals which is practically valid, unless it be dependent on a theory of egoism. For example, I say to Mr. A. : Do what is right. He asks, What is right ? I reply, Act so as to secure the greatest happiness of the greatest number. He may answer, But why should I do that ? Now if I say, Because it is a law of God, or a law of conscience, or according to the eternal fitness of things, that you should so act, it is apparent that I abandon my theory of utilitarianism. If I say, Your nature is benevolent enough to answer your question, Mr. A. may say to me, thereby showing a most unpleas- ant side of his character, I am not a benevolent man. I do not care what be- comes of society so long as I am happy myself. The happiness of society, or what is often called the social organism, is the happiness of a collection of men. Some of them Mr. A. may care a great deal about : if he cares enough about them to $2 A Theory of Conduct. sacrifice his own happiness to theirs, he doubtless finds a recompense for his self- denial. It is irrelevant to say that he has, by his self-denial, set aside his own happiness. The fact that he acts as he does shows that he contemplates greater happiness from his action than if he re- frained and enjoyed immediate happiness. This aspect of conduct will be noticed more fully when the reasons why one should be moral are discussed. I am dis- posed to emphasize this relation which ex- ists between Egoism and Altruism. For it cannot be denied that the advocates of the latter, as well as those who deny both Egoism and Altruism, have encouraged what one might almost describe as hypoc- risy in their dealing with the motives of conduct. A man who conducts his ac- tions in order to promote the greatest happiness of the greatest number would not do so unless he believed that such conduct would promote his own happi- ness. Such a course of action may give The Theory of Right. 33 him immediate pain, and may involve the suffering on his part of future pain ; but unless he believed that it would insure him on the whole a greater amount of pleasure than of pain, he would not seek the happiness of others at the expense of his own happiness. It is indeed difficult to understand why the term self-denial should be applied to conduct which gives up immediate pleasure for the sake of pleasure in the future. To gratify one's desire to be benevolent, to act according to the sympathies of one's nature, to sat- isfy the intense longing that a man has to do good to those whom he loves, is not, scientifically speaking, self-denial at all. If I am a Sybarite, self-denial does not consist in preferring ease and the en- joyment of the good things of this life to sacrifice of these things for others. But if I am born with what men call a great and unselfish heart, if I am of a sympa- thetic nature, if I feel remorse and shame at neglecting the happiness of others, even 34 A Theory of Conduct. though I love the immediate pleasures of life, I shall be a Sybarite unless I desire to benefit others. The act of benefiting others is clearly a following of my own interest. It is not self-denial. What the immediate gratification of the appetites is to the Sybarite, the furtherance of the welfare of others is to the benevolent man. It would appear from what has been said, then, that I am identifying moral conduct with conduct in the interest of self, but this is not strictly true. It is one thing to say that all moral conduct promotes the happiness of self. One may go further and affirm that moral conduct is followed because it promotes the happiness of self. But it does not follow that all conduct which promotes the happiness of self is moral. We have to ask whether conduct promotes happiness because it is moral, or whether it is moral because it promotes happiness. There is undoubtedly a dis- tinction between different kinds of happi- The Theory of Right. 35 ness, a distinction which men generally recognize even if its scientific validity be questioned. For example, a higher moral quality is assigned to the happiness which comes from satisfying desires of an aesthetic and philanthropic kind than those which come from the gratification of the appetites of the body. But independent of the distinc- tion between moral and immoral pleasure or happiness is a recognized distinction between right and wrong apart from the happiness involved in conduct. It is held that what is right means something more than what is expedient or useful, and we are referred to certain broad and generally accepted propositions, such as : It is wrong to harm the innocent, the purity of woman should be respected, it is wrong to steal It is conceivable that a man should think it right to steal, should steal without being found out, in which case nobody's happi- ness would be affected except his own, and he would not necessarily be unhappy be- 36 A Theory of Conduct. cause no remorse would follow the deed by which he acquired property. It is conceiv- able that a man should kill another who had not wronged him, but who he might suppose had wronged him, who was gener- ally supposed by others to have wronged him, and society and law might assent to the act, the wrongness of which was not to be measured by the happiness produced. As a matter of fact, society passes judg- ment as to the Tightness or wrongness of actions without considering the happiness involved. Men have been led to affirm that there exists an absolute right or wrong which no circumstances can alter. Now I believe that the whole difficulty with regard to the nature of right is di- minished if we recognize the agreement between what is right and what brings happiness, in so far as to affirm that what is right tends to promote happiness of a more enduring kind than what is wrong does. We undoubtedly in many cases rec- ognize the right by the happiness which The Theory of Right. 37 follows its performance. According to some, our ideas with regard to duty and the moral code which is generally accepted among civilized nations are a result of long experience. It has been found that cer- tain general ways of action promote the general happiness more than others. These we call moral, and embody the results of experience in our customs or laws, in our social and moral rules, even in our religion. What is right, therefore, is determined by the custom or habit of the people. There is no general recognition of an absolute right or wrong ; the customary morality of Patagonia or Borneo is not the morality of England or Ireland. What is right in one country may be wrong in another. What is right in one century is wrong in another. This doctrine is reinforced by the discrep- ancy often noticed between the social and legal sanctions, or between the moral and religious sanction. Much light is thrown on this subject by inquiring into the theory of obligation and the manner in which $8 A Theory of Conduct. moral truth is known. For the present I would suggest that the theory which de- nies the existence of absolute morality must show why it is that while the general rules of morality accepted by one nation are undoubtedly promotive of happiness, those of another nation are quite the con- trary. Those who believe that there is an absolute right usually hold that it is uni- versally and intuitively known. The utili- tarian advances against this theory the very fact which he cannot explain in his own the variety of moral judgments. If the ideas of morality prevalent in what we call civilized society are merely a growth, why have they not grown in uncivilized so- ciety ? If these ideas are intuitive, why do the institutions of the Thug or the Dervish differ from those of an English clergyman ? An attempt is sometimes made to show that Right means what is fitting ; and that the moral ideal in man is analogous to the ideal with respect to ordinary objects. A good man is one who is adapted to his sur- The Theory of Right. 39 roundings, just as a good knife cuts well, or a good house is comfortable and lasting. This attempt is a mere evasion of the ques- tion, which may be put thus : Why is a moral man adapted to his surroundings, or, as we are sometimes prosily told, fitted to fulfill the end of his being ? Is it because he is happier ? If so, we are utilitarians. Is it because he is conforming to some principle of fitness ? If so, we are no nearer an explanation than before. The ordinary supporter of the ethics of Mr. Darwin's school finds fault with the doc- trine of Absolute Morality, because it does not take into account the growth of man in adaptation to his surroundings or " envi- ronment." The advocate of the Absolute theory may complain that no standard is furnished by the Evolutionist to test the adaptation of conduct to surroundings. Why is it more moral to be adapted to one's surroundings than not to be so adapted ? A country gentleman with a good digestion, an active liver, a warm- 40 A Theory of Conduct. hearted generosity, is well adapted to his surroundings. It is no trouble for him to keep his temper, his needs are well sup- plied, and he is charitable to his neighbors. Is he a more moral man than the mission- ary who makes his family weep by taking his departure to the coast of Africa to speak for a while to unappreciative negroes and suffer martyrdom like One whose teaching he proclaims ? If Right be a growth, the result of de- velopment, we may inquire, Where did the idea come from what was its genesis ? The term evidently is applied, as I have said, to that which one ought to do. Now, however men may differ as to ivhat they ought to do, however they may differ as to the absolute character of right, they agree substantially as to the existence of duty or obligation. We are led to inquire, then, How can we know what we ought to do ? There are two general theories as to the knowledge of moral distinctions. The first of these may be called The TJjeory of Right. 41 1. The a priori, or intuitional view. 2. The a posteriori, or empirical view. Neither of these I regard as wholly sat- isfactory, but they may be stated as fol- lows : The intuitional theory of knowledge maintains the absolute character of Right and Wrong. This absolute Right and Wrong is known intuitively, consequently the knowledge is uniform, or should be uniform. The problem of the intuitionist is to explain the diversity of moral judg- ments among men. There is no moral proposition as to conduct universally ac- cepted by all men, unless it be that men should do their duty. So soon as the ques- tion is asked, "What is my duty?" a vari- ety of answers is given. The variety is explained by the intuitionist in various ways. Men are perverted, according to him, in their judgment as to right and wrong. But no adequate explanation is offered as to why this perversion is pos- sible. It is said that morality is so often 42 A Theory of Conduct. opposed to one's apparent interest and ap- petite that the feelings have undermined the judgment, just as a lover may overlook the faults of the woman whom he loves, or the partisan in politics may regard the demagogue as a statesman. If this be so, then the moral judgment cannot be an in- tuitive judgment. Intuitive judgments are necessary, and it is inconceivable that non- essential propositions should overbalance necessary judgments. The apparent con- flict between morality and self-interest may be referred to in order to explain immoral actions, but is in no way sufficient to ex- plain judgments which contradict so-called necessary truths. A favorite form of intuitionism may be noticed as affording an illustration of what has just been said. There is said to be a judgment as to the morality of individual actions or states of mind concerning which Tightness or wrongness is predicated ; for example: "Murder is wrong," "Selfish- ness is wrong," "Charity is right." The The Theory of Right. 43 subject of the moral judgment is gained from experience. But all moral or immoral actions involve some principle. This prin- ciple is known intuitively by the Reason. If there is an agreement between the fact of experience and the moral principle, we are able to predicate Tightness of the event ; if there is disagreement, we predicate the contrary, just as we compare the reckoning about concrete objects in arithmetic with the general axioms on which our reckoning is based, and just as we refer successive events to the principle of causality. Without disputing the psychological cor- rectness of this theory, I would point out the fact that it fails altogether to explain the diversity of moral judgments. Men make mistakes in counting, but when the rules of reckoning are explained to them the necessity of those rules is recognized. In the same way, it may be said, the savage may be civilized and made to appreciate the fact that he should not steal ; but the necessity of the principle that the theft 44 -d Theory of Conduct. is wrong is altogether different from the necessity that four is more than two, or that twice five are ten. We conclude that the light of reason or of nature does not give an immediate or intuitive knowledge of moral truth. The advocate of the a posteriori school advances at this point and offers the ex- planation of the diversity of moral judg- ments among men, which we have already had occasion to notice and to criticise. We are confronted, then, with the fol- lowing problems : If the idea of right is simply the result of what men have found to be conducive to happiness, why do we regard morality as something obligatory in- stead of something merely expedient ? If, on the other hand, the knowledge of Right is necessary, why is it not universal ? I believe that the science of ethics furnishes no answer to the question "What is Right ? " But this does not imply that there is no absolute right. On the contrary, it seems highly probable that such a right The Theory of Right. 45 exists, on account of the universal preva- lence of the idea of Duty. The science of ethics thus reveals no definite ideal except that of Happiness as the goal of human conduct. It tells us that there is a right which we ought to regard as the ideal, but what that right is it does not reveal. Men are at sea without a compass on a starless night ; they are bound for a port which they cannot find ; which is not on their charts, for it is still undiscovered. If they can but avoid shipwreck and reach any shore, they have done all that is possible, and must be content to know, after they come to anchor, whether they have been brought into their desired haven. III. The Nature of Duty. IN the foregoing chapter the conclusion was reached that man does not know what he ought to do, but that he ought to do something; that is, that there is such a thing as duty, and that it is an universally prevalent idea. The conception of duty or obligation is either original or derived. Those who affirm that duty is not an orig- inal conception may be asked to explain its origin, and attempts have been made to furnish such an explanation. All theories upon this point may be fairly and conven- iently divided into two classes : 1. The objective theory. 2. The subjective theory. i. The first of these regards duty as a product of law, and law as the product of fear and ultimately of expediency. This The Nature of Duty. 47 conclusion has been presented with great force by some who have applied the hy- pothesis of evolution to the explanation of ethical doctrine. Without going further back in development than the beginning of human history, it may be said that the idea of ought comes from the idea of must : so that moral obligation is an idea the source of which is to be found in social and legal obligation. The authority of the parent over the child has given rise to the idea that the commands of the former are bind- ing upon the latter. The unquestioned commands of early years become part and parcel of the rule which guides the child until in more mature years another rule of action is prescribed by the society in which the man lives, and the sanctions of the law bind him to courses of action which soci- ety regards as right, and deter him from actions which he regards as wrong. The rule changes, but the conception of duty remains. The law may be a law of love in family life, a law of sympathy or interest 48 A Theory of Conduct. in social life, a law of fear in civil life, but the habitual restraint of earlier periods be- comes the imperative "duty" of maturity. This theory fails to account for the author- ity of the parent, of society, of the law, except on the basis of love and fear. The child may obey the parent from love, and obey the law from fear. But suppose that on reaching maturity a question arises, "Ought I to obey my father or obey the law ? " the ought would appear to be an idea independent of both parent and law. Or, if it be said that sympathy or benevolence is the origin of duty, the question arises, Why does man have to ask " ought I to be sympathetic toward this man or that ; ought I to feel this benevolence " ? It is highly probable, if not absolutely certain, that the question of duty is antecedent to the question of love or fear. But it may be said, the fact is that certain acts are expe- dient and others inexpedient, and it may be asked, Is not expediency the source of duty ? But if it be possible to ask the The Nature of Duty. 49 question, Is it or is it not my duty to do what is expedient ? then the idea of duty is logically antecedent to that of expedi- ency. 2. The origin of duty, however, may be said to be subjective, and to be found in self-interest. Just as it is to my interest to obey the law, to respect the mandates of society, and the authority of my par- ents ; so the apprehension of this fact raises in me the idea of duty, because my own self-interest is evidently the most im- portant interest with which I am con- cerned. To this the reply may be made that in this case self-interest and duty should not only always coincide, but that they should seem to coincide. This we know is very far from being the case. Even where the agreement between self- interest and duty is apprehended, so that one cannot ask, Ought I to follow self- interest ? so certainly is the answer affirma- tive, it is plain that the very affirmation, It is my duty to seek my own interest, 50 A Theory of Conduct. implies a conception of duty not derived from self-interest but independent of it. I am willing to admit that self-interest can- not be resolved into any simpler elements, that egoism is a necessary quality of the human mind, but the history of society shows very plainly that duty too is neces- sary. Let us take an interesting example and consider the ethical position of an ori- ental devotee, who does not believe in a happy immortality but expects eternal an- nihilation. Such an one will inflict horri- ble tortures upon his body, because he thinks such torture is demanded by his duty. According to the doctrine of the foregoing chapter, he would not inflict the torture unless he desired to do it, and so far his motive is egoistic. But the im- mediate thought before his mind is the thought of duty. He inflicts the torture, not because he loves the torture, but be- cause he loves his duty. While he loves duty more than the torture, he does not love duty more than he does himself, be- The Nature of Duty. 51 cause his self-interest impels him to do his duty, and to do his duty is to him desira- ble. Self-love, or egoism, is a far broader conception than that of duty, because it includes the conception of all acts which are not morally obligatory and yet are performed for the happiness of self. But duty is independent of egoism. For even if it be claimed that all moral conduct is egoistic, it must be borne in mind that ego- istic conduct is only, the content of duty and not a necessary part of the conception of duty as such. One may believe it to be his duty to help others at his own incon- venience, and may refuse to do his duty. Another may believe it to be his duty to work for his own interest, and he may seem to decline to work for his own interest. Rightly or wrongly, we separate between duty and egoistic conduct. But as I have already said, the moment I ask the per- fectly rational question, Ought I to be selfish? I have thrown into jeopardy the subjective theory of the derivation of duty. 52 A Theory of Conduct. The conception of obligation is neces- sary. Just as the laws of space and time and of causality are necessary conditions of mathematical and natural science, so the law of duty is a necessary condition of ethical science. That I ought to do my duty is a necessary proposition. The con- tent of duty is various and accidental. Ac- cordingly we find egoism or altruism or re- ligion filling the empty form. Duty will lead one into the temple of Venus, another into the monastery ; in one nation it will make the mother sacrifice her own life for her child, in another to cast the child into the sacred river ; in one nation it will se- cure the condemnation of vice and crime, in another it will make them objects of worship. Like some mysterious oracle, it calls on men to act and does not tell them what to do. It will be seen at once, by any one fa- miliar with the Critical Philosophy, that the conclusion I have reached with regard to the nature of obligation is in some The Nature of Duty. 5 f respects analogous to the Kantian doctrine as to synthetic judgments a priori. The judgment of what it is our duty to do is an a posteriori judgment. The judgment that conduct is related to duty as being right or wrong is an a priori judgment. It is im- possible to conceive of conduct which is not either wrong or not wrong, but there may be a variety of conclusions reached as to what is wrong and what is not wrong. An illustration of the principle of causality will make this doctrine of duty still plainer. A certain change in nature is observed. What the cause of that change may be is not known, but investigation may reveal the cause, and yet different investigators may reach different conclusions as to what produced the change. That there was a cause for the change requires no demon- stration. The fact that there was a cause is a necessary truth. A terrific' explosion occurs and a building is found- in ruins. The police attribute the shock to dynamite ; some think that it was due to the weak- 54 A Theory of Conduct. ness of the boiler, others to gunpowder; the proprietor explains that it came from the carelessness of the engineer who had charge of the boiler. He reaches the con- clusion empirically, and shows empirically that other explanations of the disaster are unfounded, but in every case reference was made to the principle of causality which forbade the idea that the disaster was uncaused. A man kills another. At once the question is asked, Was the killing right or wrong ? Opinions differ. Some say he did right, others that he did wrong, and no decision is reached. All recognize the fact when it is brought to their notice that the action was either right or not right. The form of duty is referred to just as in the purely intellectual case the form of causal- ity is referred to. This I conceive to be the relation subsisting between the That and the What of morality. If it be admitted, however, that duty exists, it becomes im- portant to determine what one's duty is, and here it is that experience comes to our The Nature of Duty. 55 aid, and the question may be discussed, What shall we do ? Here, too, is to be ap- plied once more the doctrine already no- ticed, that there must be an agreement be- tween morality and happiness in order to insure the performance of moral conduct. The term duty, then, is to be applied to an aprioriiorm of knowledge. The a posteriori knowledge of which that form is the con- dition is a product of experience. Unless men are Pessimists it must be held that there is an agreement between morality and happiness. It is reasonable to con- clude that the conduct which results in the greatest amount of happiness is the most moral conduct, i. e., is conduct which we ought to follow. Such a theory as that which I have just suggested raises the same question with regard to the form of the moral judgment which is raised with regard to other neces- sary forms of judgment. It raises the old issue between the a priori and a posteriori schools of philosophy, Can we explain 56 A Theory of Conduct. necessary truth by means of experience? Experience is ultimately an appeal to the senses, and it must be shown empirically that what we call the form of obligation or duty has its origin in the ordinary percep- tions of the five senses, or in the more inti- mate sensations of pleasure and pain. The utter dissimilarity between sensations such as color and sound and touch make the ex- planation of the idea of duty from these even more uncertain than the explanation of causality or space or time from such im- pressions. The utter independence of pleasurable conduct and conduct which ought to be performed, in the mature mind, render it extremely improbable that what is pleasurable has given rise to the idea of duty. Such a result could be traced only by a patient following of the development of mind from its earliest stages, even if those stages belong to forms of primitive organic existence. How far this can be done is very uncertain. It seems to me that the most important question that the The Nature of Duty. 57 theory of knowledge presents to us is the question whether necessary truth can be shown not to be ultimate. So far no the- ory of the evolution of morality has given any definite account of the origin of moral obligation. Of the development of judg- ments as to right and wrong we have many accounts, but the formation of a moral judgment about anything implies the form of oughtness as the logical condition with- out which the moral judgment, whether mistaken or not, could not be framed. IV. The Nature of Character. THE evidence of the nature of Charac- ter is to be determined by experience. A man forms a judgment with respect to his own character by reviewing his past thoughts and actions ; he estimates the character of his fellow-men by inferences from their expressions of thought. In modern ethical science the place of char- acter has acquired great importance, espe- cially in connection with the doctrine of the will. For example, when the deter- minist, in defending his position, argues that the will is governed by motives which are beyond the control of the agent, it is affirmed on the contrary by the advocates of freedom that the effect of the motives is conditioned by the character, and that character determines the will. Character The Nature of Character. 59 becomes in this way more or less identi- fied with the person of a man, with his real self. We speak, for example, of a person not merely having, but being, a bad character. Let us suppose, for example, the case of a man whose desire is excited toward some object which he feels that he ought not to possess. The immorality of the pleasurable conduct which is suggested to him is weighed in comparison with the morality of the painful conduct. Now it is argued that the motives alone are not sufficient to determine his conduct, but that character conditions the determina- tion. The problem, then, is to explain char- acter ; to show its origin. If we take the empirical view of the matter, the states of mind antecedent to the action of the will are causes of the will's action, and we are not at liberty to introduce any third some- thing, such as character or ego, to con- dition the effect of the motive. For the ego is not given empirically, and in that case character is either wholly or in part 60 A Theory of Conduct. unknown, or becomes simply a series of phenomena. A man's character is an inconstant something, changing with the change of phenomena. Abandoning, how- ever, the metaphysical view of character as related to self, we may notice its ethi- cal significance. A character which is morally good is one which has a tendency to effect right actions. Our estimate of what constitutes a good character will therefore vary according to the standard of morality adopted. For example, if we hold that the happiness of others is the standard of conduct, then a good char- acter means one which tends to promote such happiness. It happens, however, that either by per- sonal experience or training civilized peo- ple are in agreement generally as to the actions which are called moral, and we need not introduce at this point a discus- sion as to the moral standard. One or two illustrations may serve to make clear the conclusion which I am about to draw. 7 'be Nature of Character. 61 Let us suppose, in the first place, the case of a person who is born among crim- inals and trained to look upon moral ob- liquity as praiseworthy. He is educated so that he lives by theft, he is punished by the law, he is hardened by association with convicts, and is an outcast from so- ciety. The general tendency of his life is bad, and if he does right it is from the worst of motives. We say of such an one, his character is bad. Let us suppose the case of one born amid moral and religious surroundings, and throughout his early life warned and guarded against the "world, the flesh, and the devil ; " educated to respect the prop- erty, the feelings, of others. We say of such an one, his character is good. Let us suppose, however, that to the two men the same temptation comes ; for example, the commission of a murder to gain some important end. The former commits it on account of his surroundings having been so bad as to make him look 62 A Theory of Conduct. with but little horror on the awful conse- quences of taking human life. The sec- ond man resists the temptation because he has been differently trained. It is evi- dent that the character here has a control- ling influence in determining the man's actions ; but character has been modified by circumstances. If these be regarded for the present as typical cases, we may ask, Why did not the bad man resist the evil surroundings in time to make his char- acter good enough to avoid committing the murder ? We may ask in like manner, Why did not the good man resist the bad surroundings, and why did he reach a stage of demoralization which made him suc- cumb to the temptation to murder ? If such a condition of things was not possi- ble, it follows that character is made good or bad by the surroundings of a man ; and if this be so he cannot, according to his character, resist the influence of that which makes his character what it is. If we take the other alternative, then there is a char- The Nature of Character. 6) acter with which a man is born which de- termines whether he is able to resist evil influences. And here it seems to me we have presented to us a subject of surpass- ing importance and difficulty in the science of ethics. I am anxious in discussing it to avoid, as far as possible, needless opposi- tion to doctrines not essential to the point to be noticed. For this purpose I am ready to admit, for the sake of argument, that the will is free, and that motives in- duce, but do not compel, the agent to con- duct himself in such and such a way. Here is the solemn truth, however, which meets every one who observes human con- duct. Every man or woman who comes into the world comes " not in entire forget- fulness and not in utter nakedness." No mind is a tabula rasa, which begins its career on the day when the body is born. No nervous system which belongs to an infant body is isolated and distinct from the lives which have preceded it. On the contrary, every child expresses the result, 64 A Theory of Conduct. the last effect, of a long one may almost say an infinite series of causes. The parents and grandparents, many genera- tions of parents, may be known, but who can tell through what these ancestors have passed ? It is possible, and indeed almost certain, that in the long line of progeni- tors which aristocrat and pauper alike pos- sess, there have been here and there men of low, mean disposition; there have been men whose character seemed an emana- tion from hell ; men addicted to nameless crimes, to debauchery, to cruelty. There are those whose forefathers have been drunkards, or insane, or convicted felons. I am disposed to think that heirlooms of this kind are seldom wholly lost, for we can see how hereditary characteristics are perpetuated until they are stamped indeli- bly not only on families, but on races. There is a deep physiological and psycho- logical truth in the old-fashioned doctrine of original sin, and it is a serious fact to contemplate. It is impossible to tell when The Nature of Character. 65 a boy or girl is born what particular ten- dency may be lurking in his or her mind or body potentially, ready to spring up on some occasion being offered, and bring desolation and ruin. And if the hypothe- sis of Darwin be true, and our ancestry is not limited to the human species, one can- not say definitely that qualities belonging to the brutes have not left indelible marks upon our own highly perfected organisms. If such a view be regarded as fantastical, it is sufficient for us to notice how habits descend in families, even where the sur- roundings of the children differ from those of the parents. If the natural history of many of those who fill our asylums and prisons were studied, it would be found that the causes of these wandering minds and vicious lives were not independent of hereditary influences. The side of these facts which is most often noticed is the serious warning it gives to those about to marry to see to it that they do not know- ingly perpetuate corruption in the phy- 66 A Theory of Conduct. sique and morals of their children. But to my mind the more serious aspect is that which belongs to the possible moral train- ing of those who have inherited the tram- mels and vices which in many cases have wrecked the lives of their ancestors. It becomes a matter of vital importance to determine whether, if morality be largely dependent on character, and if one's char- acter be an inheritance which one's life simply wastes or puts out at interest, whether, I say, ethical science can furnish a moral code at all and insist that it should be obeyed. Whether, then, we adopt the doctrine of freedom or not, it cannot be denied that every man is born with certain inherited dispositions or tendencies, which are more or less eradicable, according to the strength of their persistence and the force of cir- cumstances. And it is an encouragement to the social reformer that in many cases men have not only been raised to a high plane of morality when their birth and sur- The Nature of Character. 67 roundings have been degraded, but also that many have been capable of elevation when removed from their low surround- ings. In opposition to these facts may be cited cases of some, the vices of whose ancestry have reappeared in their own lives in spite of all efforts at reform. The science of human nature has not reached a point where it is possible to distinguish between native and acquired qualities; but it is no less certain that inherited character is a powerful, though indetermi- nate, element in the composition of con- duct. When, therefore, it is affirmed that every man is the author of his own charac- ter, we must consider that an element in the formation of such character is inher- ited character. The importance of this view will be appreciated when it is remem- bered how strenuously men are everywhere seeking their own happiness, and how the ideal of happiness differs according to dif- ferent characters. There are cases in which a man, accord- 68 A Theory of Conduct. ing to his own confession and the testi- mony of his friends, lived a pure and ex- emplary life, who nevertheless succumbed to some severe temptation, and committed acts which men with a far worse experi- ence would hesitate to perform. There are virtuous women who commit deeds from which their abandoned sisters would often shrink. There are men of purity and benevolence who, when they fall, fall lower than the average of criminals. It is difficult to affirm of any man or woman that his or her character is good until their respective lives, with the temptations to which they have been subjected, are passed in review ; and it can hardly be called ac- cidental that the tombstone is the place where an estimate of character is most often to be found, although many epitaphs are lies. To those who look upon moral and immoral courses of conduct as effects of mere caprice, the estimate of real charac- ter is unimportant. But no one who looks at conduct scientifically can fail to be per- The Nature of Character. 69 plexed at the extraordinary deviations of good men into bad paths. We conclude that character often lies hidden in the realm of the unconscious. It is there- fore a truth of science as well as of re- ligion that in the crucible of life gold is often found in what seemed brass and clay, while many a highly valued gem is con- sumed in the devouring fire of experience. The problem of ethics is thus further complicated by the fact that every influ- ence for good may be brought to bear upon a man when his character is such that lit- tle benefit will follow from such influence. The principle of heredity is every day becoming more and more important in philosophy. In spite of the fact that it is very difficult to show any regularity or law in the transmission of qualities from parent to child, the fact that there is such a trans- mission is established beyond all doubt. The theory of development clearly shows that the individual life is not sufficient to explain the tendencies which characterize 70 A Theory of Conduct. it. Particularly in the lower animal world are the effects of heredity clearly appar- ent. This principle must be taken ac- count of by the psychologist as well as by the naturalist, particularly in the relation of the science of mind to neurology. It is clearly established that there is a cer- tain correspondence between the phenom- ena of mind and those of the central ner- vous system. According to some, there is more than a correspondence, and the phenomena of the one are causally related to those of the other. The embryonic brain is comparatively simple and homo- geneous in the earlier stages of its growth, and it is impossible to affirm that it pos- sesses any more psychological significance than the liver or the heart. But the fully developed central nervous system in man, by reason of its complexity, admits of many modifications which are difficult to trace, much less to explain. Yet, just as diseases of other organs are transmitted from parent to child, so peculiarities and The Nature of Character. // disorders of the nervous system are trans- mitted, and often a definite hereditary physical condition may be shown to be the cause of mental changes. But even where the causes of nervous phenomena cannot be traced, it can be observed that mental characteristics, the physical conditions or accompaniments of which are unknown, pass to a man from his progenitors. It is very easy to say that hereditary ten- dencies, however marked, may be over- come by education and training, so that even were a man to be born with a dis- tinctly vicious disposition, such a disposi- tion might be changed by virtuous sur- roundings. It is easy to say that such vicious hereditary characteristics are un- common. Indeed, with the exception of certain forms of disease, the qualities of mind and body which can be proved to be hereditary are in most cases trivial ; but the fact that these qualities are trans- mitted cannot be denied. If the effect of this transmission can be overcome, the 7-2 A Theory of Conduct. means of the overcoming must be an effort of the will, or of motives effected by one's surroundings, or both. If the hereditary tendency is overcome by an effort of the will, according to our premises the will is dependent on the character. A charac- ter, then, which changes its evil tenden- cies is, according to the hypothesis, an evil character, which is absurd. If the heredi- tary tendency is overcome by motives sup- plied by one's surroundings, then there is no freedom to change. But it can be shown that the same surroundings will produce different results upon different men, the difference in result being the effect of a difference of character. If both surroundings and character combine to ef- fect the change, there cannot be said to be freedom, for the surroundings are not the result of the man's volition, otherwise they are due to his character. But his character, before his surroundings have changed it, is something with which he has had nothing to do. A moral or an The Nature of Character. 73 immoral progenitor may have had a great deal to do with it, and such a progenitor may in turn examine his own pedigree to find remote causes for his individual char- acteristics. It may be said, however, that, independent of both character and sur- roundings, is the free ego or self, which controls man's moral action whatever the antecedents, whatever the surroundings. All roads lead to Rome ; and I have yet to find any doctrine of ethics which did not lead one to the question as to the freedom of the will. This is a subject which has been worn absolutely thread- bare in modern philosophy, and it is not my intention to attempt a solution of the problem in this treatise. Believing as I do that change is unthinkable except in the category of causation, the affirmation that the will is free, or that self is free to will, seems to me thoroughly unwarranted either by fact or reason. It has been said that either freedom is a fact or moral re- sponsibility is a delusion. Whether this y4 4 Theory cf Conduct. alternative is to be accepted or not, from a philosophical point of view, it would seem to be inadvisable to make our meta- physics or logic the slave of ethics. If self and character be identical, then the qualities of self are determined in the first instance independently of the will. It may be said, however, that self can modify its own character, that is, character is a spe- cies of veneer that one finds self covered with at birth ; but that on the presentation of motives self acts freely, and, removing one coat of veneer, applies another of a different kind. If we hold that self can be an object of knowledge, then it would be interesting to know wherein the self and the character differ. If, however, we hold the view that self is subject and is anterior to knowledge, the problem as to character and freedom has a very different meaning. Some of the great schools of modern German thought prefer to take the latter view. It is held that self, the ego, is not a phenomenon, is not given in The Nature of Character. 75 experience. Causality is a category appli- cable to phenomena only. It is logical, therefore, to regard self as independent of causality as itself a cause, but, even when viewed as changing, not an effect. The noumenal self, as Ding an sick, is not subject to the law of causation, and is therefore free. While this is logically plau- sible, it is an argument which will not bear close inspection. For example, the motive avarice, which is the effect on my charac- ter of the sight of gold, suggests that I should steal ; the motive compassion the effect upon my character of the sight of the owner of the gold suggests that I should not steal. Suppose that there is no third alternative. If the owner is ab- sent the compassion is absent, and theft follows. If the owner is present, it may be said that I can choose between steal- ing and not stealing. If I fail to steal, the failure is related to the motive as ef- fect to cause. It is of no importance that we speak of the ego willing, if the partic- j6 A Theory of Conduct. ular act of will would not have taken place in the absence of the motive : the motive is the cause, and the will is not free. The continuous action of surroundings on the will through the character produces a more or less decided tendency to will in a certain way. From this practical moral- ists draw the conclusion that indulgence of the appetites, for example, weakens the will, or, to speak more correctly, leads the will to will what satisfies the appetites. On the contrary, if the character of a man is sufficiently strong to overcome the influ- ence of surroundings which tend to make him indulge his appetites, a continued course of such willing increases the resist- ing power. We have in these cases a suf- ficient answer to a statement often made with regard to the comparative strength of character in different men. It is some- times said that a man who has successfully resisted a great temptation deserves as little credit as the one who has yielded to the same temptation ; because in the The Nature of Character. 77 former case the effort required was not so great as in the latter case. We are told that X., whose appetites are not so strong as those of Y., deserves less credit than Y. if they are resisted ; while if Y. yields to them his conduct is less culpable. This would be true if their characters were wholly formed and remained unchanged by their habits of volition and their surround- ings. But it may be the case that X. is able to resist the great temptation because he has accustomed himself to resist temp- tations in general, while Y. does not ap- preciate the greatness of the temptation until he is confronted with it. In case Y. does resist the temptation, other things being equal, the sum of the amounts of resistance to previous temptations in the case of X. may be far greater than the whole amount of resistance required by Y. in the great temptation supposed. It seems to me very doubtful whether the unconscious element in mental life is sufficiently considered. The qualities of 7