$ I ^.OF-CAll i,-M I 5 ^AHvaan-^ I s * * i 1 = oo ^ S 5 s S ^. .^OF-CAIIFO^ , S3 I! IB>)I M < I 1 S l 5 ^.^> L5 * 1 1 ,KlO$ANGFtfj i I i -n < > I & i II 9 S ^EUN!VFJ?% I S . if .-- THE LAW OF NATIONS; PRINCIPLES OF THE LAW OF NATURE, APPLIED TO CONDUCT AND AFFAIRS NATIONS AND SOTEEEIGNS. FROM THE FRENCH OP MONSIEUR DE VATTEL. Nihil est onim illi principi Deo qui omnem hunc mundum regit, quod quidem in terris fiat, accepting quam concilia coetusque hominum jure sociati, qua mitates appellantur." CICERO, Sou. SCIP. FROM THE NEW EDITION, JOSEPH CHITTY, ESQ. BARRISTER AT LAW. WITH ADDITIONAL NOTES AND REFERENCES, BY EDWAKD D. INGKAHAM, ESQ. T. & J. W. JOHNSON, LAW BOOKSELLEKS, v No. 197 CHESTNUT STREET. ' V1853. Entered according to Act of Congress, in the year 1852, by T. & J. W. JOHNSON, in the Clerk's Office of the District Court of the Eastern District of Pennsylvania. PREFACE TO THIS EDITION. THE text of the present translation of Yattel has been care- fully compared with that of the original work, in the first v> edition which appeared, (Londres, 1758, 2 vol. in quarto,) pub- lished at Neuchatel; in that of Amsterdam, (Van Harrevelt, 1775, 2 vol. in quarto,) the best known till recently; and in that of M. de Hofmans, (Paris, 1839, 2 vol. in octavo,) the last and best edition. Great care has been taken also in re- % gard to the British decisions cited by the English editor. It ^ was discovered, that many inaccuracies existed in the citations, ^ v particularly in the names of the cases cited, which have been corrected by references to the original reports of the decisions ; and wherever it appeared that the notes of the English editor ,> required additions to render the doctrine advanced in them \ clearer, or more intelligible, such additions have been made ; j care having been taken to distinguish the matter added by J enclosing it in brackets. The editor regrets very much that the size of the volume which would have been too much in- creased by such an extension did not permit him to annex to it the " Bibliographic choisie et systematique du Droit de la Nature et des Gens, et ^u Droit Public," of M. de Ho/mans, which is an excellent guide in the choice of Works upon a subject much less attended to than js demanded by its im- portance. Philadelphia, Sept. 29, 1852. iii ADVERTISEMENT TO THE EDITION OF A. D. 1797. AN undertaking this new edition of Monsieur De Vattel's trea- tise, it was not my intention to give what might strictly be called a new translation. To add the author's valuable notes from the posthumous edition, printed at Neufchatel in 1773, to correct some errors I had observed in the former version, and occasionally to amend the language where doubtful or obscure, were the utmost limits of my original plan. As I proceeded, however, my alterations became more numerous ; but whether they will be acknowledged as amendments, it must rest with the reader to determine. Even if this decision should be more favourable than I have any reason to expect, I lay no claim to praise for my humble eiforts, but shall esteem myself very fortunate if I escape the severity of censure for presenting the work to the public in a state still so far short of perfection. Conscious of its defects, I declare, with great sincerity, . . . Vcniam pro laude peto, laudatus abunde, Non fastiditus si tibi, lector, ero. THE EDITOR. London, May 1, 1797. PKEFACE TO THE PRESENT EDITION. J. HE merits and increasing utility of this admirable work have not, as yet, been sufficiently known, or justly appreciated. It has been generally supposed that it is only adapted for the study of sovereigns and statesmen, and in that view certainly the author's excellent Preface points out its pre-eminent im- portance. But it is of infinitely more extended utility. It con- tains a practical collection of ethics, principles, and rules of conduct to be observed and pursued, as well by private indivi- duals as by states, and these of the utmost practical importance to the well-being, happiness, and ultimate and permanent ad- vantage and benefit of all mankind ; and, therefore, ought to be studied by every gentleman of liberal education, and by youth, in whom the best moral principles should be inculcated. The work should be familiar in the Universities, and in every class above the inferior ranks of society. And, as regards lawyers, it contains the clearest rules of construing private contracts, and respecting the Admiralty and Insurance Law. The posi- tions of the author, moreover, have been so sensibly and clearly supported and explained, and so happily illustrated by histo- rical and other interesting examples, that the perusal cannot fail to entertain as well as instruct. The present Editor, therefore, affirms, without the hazard of contradiction, that every one who has attentively read this work, will admit that he has acquired a knowledge of superior sentiments and more 'important information than he ever derived from any other work. A2 V IV PREFACE TO THE PRESENT EDITION. Many years have elapsed since the original work was pub- lished, long before the invaluable decisions of Sir William Scott, Sir C. Robinson, and Sir John Nichol, and other emi- nent Judges in the Courts of Admiralty, and Prize and other Courts ; and the last edition, upon which any care was be- stowed, was published in A. D. 1797; since which time, and especially during the last general war, many most important rules respecting the Law of Nations were established. The object of the present Editor has, therefore, been to collect and condense, in numerous notes, the modern rules and decisions, and to fortify the positions in the text by references to other au- thors of eminence, and by which he hopes that this edition will be found of more practical utility, without interfering with the text, or materially increasing its size. The Editor had proposed to form an Index, so as to render the work more readily accessible ; but, in that desire, he has been overruled by the publishers, who think that the exceed- ingly full Analytical Table of Contents following the Preface, and naming the pages where each position is to be found, are sufficient, without increasing the bulk of the work, and, con- sequently, the expense. The Editor hopes that the student who may examine his numerous notes will not think that he has wasted time. J. CHITTY. Chambers, 6, Chancery Lane, November, 1833. PREFACE. J_ HE Law of Nations, though so noble and important a subject, has not, hitherto, been treated of with all the care it deserves. The greater part of mankind have, therefore, only a vague, a very incomplete, and often even a false notion of it. The generality of writers, and even celebrated authors, almost exclusively confine the name of "Law of Nations" to certain maxims and treatises recognised among nations, and which the mutual consent of the parties has rendered obligatory on them. This is confining within very narrow bounds a law so extensive in its own nature, and in which the whole human race are so intimately concerned ; it is, at the same time, a degradation of that law, in conse- quence of a misconception of its real origin. There certainly exists a natural law of nations, since the obligations of the law of nature are no less binding on states, on men united in political society, than on individuals. But, to acquire an exact know- ledge of that law, it is not sufficient to know what the law of nature prescribes to the individuals of the human race. The application of a rule to various subjects, can no otherwise be made than in a manner agreeable to the nature of each subject. Hence, it follows, that the natural law of nations is a particular science, consisting in a just and rational application of the law of nature to the affairs and conduct of nations or sovereigns. All treatises, therefore, in which the law of nations is blended and confounded with the ordinary law of nature, are incapable of conveying a distinct idea, or a substantial knoAvledge of the sacred law of nations. The Romans often confounded the law of nations with the law of nature, giving the name of "the law of 'nations" (Jus Gentium) to the law of nature, as being generally acknowledged and adopted by all civilized nations.* The definitions given by the emperor Justinian, of the law of nature, the law of nations, and the civil law, are well known. " The law of nature," says he, " is that which nature teaches to all animals" :"f thus he defines the natural law in its most extensive sense, not that natural law which is peculiar to man, and which is derived as well from his rational as from his animal nature. " The civil law," that emperor adds, " is that which each nation has established for herself, and which peculiarly belongs to each state or civil society. And that law, which na- * Neque vero hoc solnm naturS, id est, jure f Jus naturale est, quod natura omnia ani- gentium, ; -i- >,. ^ . j v 2 It is a moral person ...... ib. 3 Definition of the law of nations . . . . . ib. 4 In what light nations or states are to be considered . . Ivi 5 To what laws nations are subject . . . . . ib. 6 In what the law of nations originally consists '."" . . ib. 7 Definition of the necessary law of nations . .. . .' . Iviii 8 It is immutable . . . . . ib. 9 Nations can make no change in it, nor dispense with the obligations arising from it . . . . ^ '" ' . ib. 10 Society established by nature between all mankind . . . lix 11 And between all nations ...... Ix 12 The object of this society of nations . . . . bd 13 General obligation imposed by it . . ' . ib. 14 Explanation of this observation . . . . . ib. 15 The second general law is the liberty and independence of nations Ixii 16 Effect of that liberty . . . ..'"''. & 17 Distinctions between internal and external, perfect and imperfect obli- gations and rights .'.'! . . . . ib. 18 Equality of nations .' ." *t : T 1 " .* . Ixiii 19 Effect of that equality . . . . . . ib. 20 Each nation is mistress of her own actions, when they do not affect the perfect rights of others . . . . . ib. 21 Foundation of the voluntary law of nations . . -.'^ ?' ' ib. 22 Right of nations against the infractors of the law of nations . . Ixiv 23 Measure of that right . . ; '.- . ib 24 Conventional law of nations, or law of treaties . . . Ix 1 ! 25 Customary law of nations r .. . . . . ib 2*6 General rule respecting that law . . . . . ib 27 Positive law of nations ...... IxV. 28 General maxim respecting the use of the necessary and the voluntary law . . . . . . . . ' ib. xix XX CONTENTS. BOOK I. OF NATIONS CONSIDERED IN THEMSELVES. CHAP. I. Of Nations or Sovereign States. Sect. Page 1 Of the state, and of sovereignty .' ... 1 2 Authority of the body politic over the members . . ib. 3 Of the several kinds of government . ... . .2 4 What are sovereign states . . . . ib. 5 States bound by unequal alliance . . ' . . ib. 6 or by treaties of protection . . . . ib. 7 Tributary states ....... 3 8 Feudatory states .....% ib. 9 Two states subject to the same prince . . . . ib. 10 States forming a federal republic . . ..." ib. 11 A state that has passed under the dominion of another . . ib. 12 Objects of this treatise ...... 4 CHAP. II. General Principles of the Duties of a Nation towards herself. 13 A nation ought to act agreeably to her nature . . .4 14 Preservation and perfection of a nation .... ib. 15 End of civil society . . . .5 16 A nation is under an obligation to preserve herself . . ib. 17 and to preserve her members .... ib. 18 A nation has a right to every thing necessary for her preservation 6 19 She ought to avoid every thing that might occasion her destruction . ib. 20 Her right to every thing that may promote this end . . ib. 21 A nation ought to perfect herself and her condition . . . ib. 22 and to avoid every thing contrary to her perfection . 7 23 The right she derives from these obligations . . . ib. 24 Examples . . . . . . ib. 25 A nation ought to know herself . . . . .8 CHAP. HI. Of the Constitution of a State, and the Duties and Rights of a Nation in that respect. 26 Of the public authority . . .''. . ; . 8 27 What is the constitution of a state . . v . ib. 28 The nation ought to choose the best constitution . . .9 29 Political, fundamental, and civil laws . . f " . ib. 30 Support of the constitution, and obedience to the laws . . ib. 31 Right of a nation with respect to her constitution and government 10 CONTENTS. XXI Sect. Page 32 She may reform the government . . . . .10 33 and may alter the constitution . . . ib. 34 Of the legislative power, and whether it can alter the constitution . 11 35 The nation ought not to attempt it without great caution . 12 36 She is the judge of all disputes relative to the government . . ib. 37 No foreign power has a right to interfere . . . ib. CHAP. IV. Of the Sovereign, his Obligations, and his Rights. 38 Of the sovereign . . . . . . .12 39 He is solely established for the safety and advantage of society . 13 40 His representative character . . . . .14 41 He is intrusted with the obligations of the nation, and invested with her rights . . . . . . ib. 42 His duty with respect to the preservation and perfection of the nation ib. 43 His rights in that respect . . . ~. ** . ib. 44 He ought to know the nation . . t ^ > 15 45 Extent of his power : prerogatives of majesty . . . ib. 46 The prince is bound to respect and support the fundamental laws ib. 47 He may change the laws not fundamental . . ^ ' . .16 48 He is bound to maintain and observe the existing laws . . ib. 49 In what sense he is subject to the laws .... ib. 50 His person is sacred and inviolable . . . .17 51 But the nation may repress a tyrant, and renounce her allegiance to him ib. 52 Arbitration between the king and his subjects ... 20 53 Obedience which subjects owe to a sovereign . ; -4,, . 21 54 In what cases they may resist him . . ib. 55 Ministers . 23 CHAP. V. Of States, Elective, Siiccessive, or Hereditary, and of those called Patrimonial. 56 Elective states . . . . . .23 57 Whether elective kings be real sovereigns ... 24 58 Successive and hereditary states : origin of the right of succession . ib. 59 Other origin of that right . . . . . ib. 60 Other sources, which still amount to the same thing . . 24 61 A nation may change the order of the succession . . ib. 62 Kenunciations ..... ;.'. " * . 25 63 The order of succession ought commonly to be observed . . 26 64 Regents ... .... 27 65 Indivisibility of sovereignties . . . . . ib. 66 Who are to decide disputes respecting the succession to a sovereignty ib. 67 The right of succession not to depend on the judgment of a foreign power . . . . . . . .29 68 States called patrimonial ..... 30 69 Every true sovereignty is unalienable . . . .31 70 Duty of a prince who is empowered to nominate his successor . 32 71 His nomination must be sanctioned by at least the tacit ratification of the people ....... ib. XX11 CONTENTS. CHAP. VI. Principal Objects of a good Government; and first, to provide for the Neces- sities of the Nation. Sect. Pag 72 The object of society points out the duties of the sovereign : he is bound to procure plenty . . . . . .33 73 to take care that there be a sufficient number of workmen ib. 74 to prevent the emigration of those that are useful . ib. 75 Emissaries who entice them away . . . 34 76 Labour and industry must be encouraged . . ^. . ib. CHAP. VII, Of the Cultivation of the Soil. 77 Utility of Agriculture . . . . . .34 78 Regulations necessary in that respect : for the distribution of land ib. 79 for the protection of husbandmen . . . ..35 80 Husbandry ought to be placed in an honourable light . . ib. 81 Cultivation of the soil a natural obligation .... ib. 82 Public granaries ...... 36 CHAP. VIII. Of Commerce. 83 Domestic and foreign trade . . . . . .37 84 Utility of domestic trade . . . . . ib. 85 Utility of foreign trade . . . . . . ib. 86 Obligation to cultivate domestic trade . . . . ib. 87 Obligation to carry on foreign trade . . . .38 88 Foundation of the laws of commerce : right of purchasing . ib. 89 Right of selling . . . . . . . ib. 90 Prohibition of foreign merchandises . . . ^ , , 39 91 Nature of the right of purchasing . . . . ib. 92 Each nation to determine for herself how she will carry on commerce ib. 93 How a nation acquires a perfect right to a foreign trade . . 40 94 Simple permission to carry on trade .... ib. 95 Whether commercial rights be subject to prescription . . ib. 96 Imprescriptibility of rights founded on treaty ... 41 97 Monopolies, and trading companies with exclusive privileges . 42 98 Balance of trade, and attention of government in that respect . 43 99 Import duties . . . . . . . ib. CHAP. IX. Of the Care of the Public Ways; and of Tolls. 100 Utility of highways, canals, &c. . . . . .43 101 Duty of government in that respect . . ..;., . ib. 102 Its right in that respect . . . . ',, . ,. . 44 103 Foundation of the right to demand toll t*j . . . . . ib. 104 Abuse of that right ., . ., '.. . . ib. CONTENTS. Xxiil CHAP. X. Of Money and Exchange. Sect. Page 105 Establishment of money . . . . . .45 106 Duty of the nation or prince with respect to the coin . . ib. 107 Their rights in that respect . . . . .46 108 How one nation may injure another in the article of coin -< . 47 109 Exchange, and commercial laws . . . . ib. CHAP. XI. Second Object of a good Government, to procure the true Happiness of a, Nation. 110 A nation is bound to labour after her own happiness . . 47 111 Instruction . . . . . . i >, ib. 112 Education of youth . . <*nii#. . . .48 113 Arts and sciences ...... ib. 114 Freedom of philosophical discussion . . . .49 115 Love of virtue, and abhorrence of vice, to be excited . . 51 116 The nation may hence discover the intention of her rulers . ib. 117 The nation, or public'person, bound to perfect her understanding and will 52 118 and to direct the knowledge and virtues of the citizens to the welfare of the society . . -. -? 52 119 Love for their country . . . . . .53 120 in individuals . . . . . ib. 121 in the nation or state itself, and in the sovereign . ib. 122 Definition of the term " country" .... ib. 123 How shameful and criminal to injure our country . . 54 124 The glory of good citizens : Examples . . ' . '. ib. CHAP. XII. Of Piety and Religion. 125 Piety 55 126 It ought to be attended with knowledge . . . ib. 127 Religion, internal and external . ' ' . - ., / . .56 128 Rights of individuals : liberty of conscience . . . ib. 129 Public establishment of religion : rights and duties of the nation ib. 130 when there is as yet no established religion . 57 131 when there is an established religion . s .' '" . ib. 132 Duties and rights of the sovereign with respect to religion v 58 133 where there is an established religion . : ' V ' . 59 134 Objects of his care, and the means he ought to employ . 60 135 Toleration . . . . . . . ib. 136 How the prince is to act when the nation is resolved to change her religion . . . . . . . ib. 137 Difference of religion does not deprive a prince of his crown . 61 138 Duties and rights of the sovereign reconciled with those of the subjects ib. 139 The sovereign ought to have the inspection of the affairs of religion, and authority over those who teach it . . .62 140 He is bound to prevent the abuse of the established religion . 63 141 His authority over the ministers of religion . . . ib. CONTENTS. Sect. Page 142 Nature of that authority . . . , . .64 143 Rule to be observed with respect to ecclesiastics . . ib. 144 Recapitulation of the reasons which establish the sovereign's rights in matters of religion, ib. Authorities and examples . . 65 145 Pernicious consequences of the contrary opinion . . . ib. 146 Abuses particularized. 1. The power of the popes . . 66 147 2. Important employments conferred by a foreign power . 68 148 3. Powerful subjects dependent on a foreign court . ib. 149 4. Celibacy of the priests : Convents . . .69 150 5. Enormous pretensions of the clergy : Pre-eminence . 70 151 6. Independence, immunities . . ., , . .71 152 7. Immunity of church possessions ; , . . .. 72 153 8. Excommunication of men in office . . .73 154 9. and of sovereigns themselves ... 74 155 10. The clergy drawing every thing to themselves, and inter- rupting the course of justice . . . 75 156 11. Money drawn to Rome . . . . .76 157 12. Laws and customs inimical to the welfare of states . ib. CHAP. XIII. Of Justice and Polity. 158 A nation is bound to make justice flourish . . .77 159 to establish good laws .... ib. 160 to enforce them . . . . .78 161 Functions and duties of the prince in that respect . . ib. 162 How he is to dispense justice . . . . . ib. 163 His duty to appoint upright and enlightened judges . . ib 164 The ordinary courts should determine causes relating to the revenue 79 165 Necessary to establish supreme courts, from whose sentence there shall be no appeal . . . . . . ib. 166 The prince bound to observe the forms of justice . . 80 167 to support the authority of the judges, and enforce their decrees ....... ib. 168 Distributive justice : distribution of employments and rewards . ib. 169 Punishment of transgressors : foundation of the right of punishing 81 170 Criminal laws . . . . . . . ib. 171 Degree of punishment ..... 82 172 Execution of the laws . . . . . . ib. 173 Right of pardoning ...... 83 174 Internal police . . . . . . ib. 175 Duel or single combat . . . . .84 176 Means of putting a stop to that disorder .... ib. CHAP. XIV. Third Object of a good Government, to fortify itsdj 'against External Attacks. 177 A nation ought to fortify herself against external attacks . . 87 178 National strength . . . . . ib. 179 Increase of population . . . . . . ib. 180 Valour 88 181 Other military virtues . . . . . .89 CONTENTS. XXV Sect. Page 182 Riches . 89 183 Public revenues and taxes 90 184 The nation ought not to increase her power by unlawful means . ib. 185 Power is but relative ...... ib. CHAP. XV. Of the Glory of a Nation. 186 Advantages of glory . . . . . .91 187 Duty of the nation. How true glory is acquired . . ib. 188 Duty of the prince . . . . . . ib. 189 Duty of the citizens . . . , ; 92 190 Example of the Swiss . . . . . .16. 191 Attacking the glory of a nation is doing her an injury . . 93 CHAP. XVI. Protection sought by a Nation, and her voluntary submission to a Foreign Power. 192 Protection . . . . . . .93 193 Voluntary submission of one nation to another . . 94 194 Several kinds of submission . . . . . ib. 195 Right of the citizens when the nation submits to a foreign power ib. 196 These compacts annulled by the failure of protection . . 95 197 or by the infidelity of the party protected . . ib. 198 and by the encroachments of the protector . . ib. 199 How the right of the nation protected is lost by her silence . 96 CHAP. XVII. How a Nation may separate herself from the State of which she is a Member, and renounce her Allegiance to her Sovereign when she is not protected. 200 Difference between the present case and those in the preceding chapter 96 201 Duty of the members of a state, or subjects of a prince, who are in danger . . . . . . . .97 202 Their right when they are abandoned .... ib. CHAP. xvm. Establishment of a Nation in a Country. 203 Possession of a country by a nation . . . .98 204 Her right over the part in her possession . . . ib. 205 Acquisition of the sovereignty in a vacant country . . 99 206 Another manner of acquiring the empire in a free country . ib. 207 How a nation acquires the property of a desert country . . ib. 208 A question on this subject . . . . ib. 209 Whether it be lawful to take possession of part of a country inhabited only by a few wandering tribes . . . . 100 210 Colonies 101 4 C XXVI CONTENTS. CHAP. XIX. Of our Native Country, and various Matters relating to it. Sect. Pxge 211 What is our country . . . . . .101 212 Citizens and natives ...... ib. 213 Inhabitants . . . . . . .102 214 Naturalization . . . ,, . . . ib. 215 Citizens' children born in a foreign country . . . ib. 216 Children born at sea . . . . . . ib. 217 Children born in the armies of the state, or in the house of its minister at a foreign court ...... 103 218 Settlement . . . . . . . ib. 219 Vagrants ....... ib. 220 .Whether a person may quit his country .... ib. 221 How a person may absent himself for a time . . .105 222 Variation of the political laws in that respect : they must be obeyed ib. 223 Cases in which a citizen has a right to quit his country . . ib 224 Emigrants . . . ... , . 106 225 Sources of their right . . . . ... ib. 226 If the sovereign infringes their right, he injures them . . 107 227 Supplicants ...... L ib. 228 Exile and banishment . . . . . . ib. 229 The exile and the banished man have a right to live somewhere 108 230 Nature of that right . . . . . . ib. 231 Duty of nations towards them . . . ib. 232 A nation cannot punish them for faults committed out of her territories 109 233 except such as affect the common safety of mankind . ib. CHAP. XX. Public, Common, and Private Property. 234 What the Komans called res communes . . .... 109 235 Aggregate wealth of a nation, and its divisions . . ib. 236 Two modes of acquiring public property . . . .110 237 The income of the public property is naturally at the sovereign's dis- posal ....... ib. 238 The nation may grant him the use and property of her common pos- sessions ...... . ib. 239 or allow him the domain, and reserve to herself the use of them . . . .... ib. 240 Taxes Ill 241 The nation may reserve to herself the right of imposing them . ib. 242 Sovereign possessing that power . . . . . ib. 243 Duties of the prince with respect to taxes . , . 112 244 Eminent domain annexed to the sovereignty . * . . ib. 245 Dominion over public property . . . Tyf--' - . 113 246 -The sovereign may make laws respecting the use of things possessed in common . . . . . . ib. 247 Alienation of the property of a corporation . --..-. . ib. 248 Use of common property . . . ./*.' . 114 249 How each member is to enjoy it . . . . ib. 250 Eight of anticipation in the use of it . '- "'.' '* . . ib. 251 The same right in another case -V . . . ib. CONTENTS. XXV11 Sect. Page 252 Preservation and repairs of common possessions . . . 115 253 Duty and right of the sovereign in that respect . ib. 254 Private property . . . . , . ib. 255 The sovereign may subject it to regulations of police . . ib. 256 Inheritances . . ... .116 CHAP. XXI. Of the Alienation of the Public Property, or the Domain, and that of a Part of the State. 257 The nation may alienate her public property . ' . . 116 258 Duties of the nation in that respect .... ib. 259 Duties of the prince . ; . . . . 117 260 He cannot alienate the public property . ^ . . ib. 261 The nation may give him a right to do it . . . . ib. 262 Rules on that subject with respect to treaties between nation and nation ib. 263 Alienation of a part of the state : ". . . . . 118 264 Rights of the dismembered party .... ib. 265 Whether the prince has power to dismember the state . .119 CHAP. XXII. Of Rivers, Streams, and Lakes. 266 A river that separates two territories .... 120 267 Bed of a river which is dried up or takes another course . 121 268 Right of alluvion . . . . ib. 269 Whether alluvion produces any change in the right to a river . ib. 270 Consequence of a river changing its bed . ..<-,-. *i - . 122 271 Works tending to turn the current . . . . . A ib. 272 or generally prejudicial to the rights of others . . ib. 273 Rules relative to interfering rights . . *.; . ib. 274 Lakes . >, .. .. ww < . . 123 275 Increase of a lake . . :*<: - ',* ;,* . ib. 276 Land formed on the banks of a lake . .. ; .,.-: . .- . 125 277 Bed of a lake dried up . -.- 4 ,? > . ..,.,*.,. ib. 278 Jurisdiction over lakes and rivers .... ib. CHAP. XXIII. Of the Sea. 279 The sea, and its use . . . . . . 125 280 Whether the sea can be possessed, and its dominion appropriated ib. 281 Nobody has a right to appropriate to himself the use of the open sea ib. 282 A nation attempting to exclude another does her an injury . 126 283 She even does an injury to all nations .... ib. 284 She may acquire an exclusive right by treaties . . ib. 285 but not by prescription and long use . . . 127 286 unless by virtue of a tacit agreement . . ib. 287 The sea near the coasts may become property . . . ib. XXviii CONTENTS. Sect. Page 288 Another reason for appropriating the sea bordering on the coasts . 128 289 How far that possession may extend .... ib. 290 Shores and ports . . . 129 291 Bays and straits . . . j , ' . ib. 292 Straits in particular . . . . . .130 293 Right to wrecks . . . . . ib. 294 A sea inclosed within the territories of a nation . . . ib. 295 The parts of the sea possessed by a sovereign are within his jurisdiction 131 BOOK II. OF A NATION CONSIDERED IN HER RELATION TO OTHER STATES. CHAP. I. Of the common Duties of a Nation towards other States, or the Offices of Humanity between Nations. 1 Foundation of the common and mutual duties of nations . . 133 2 Offices of humanity, and their foundation . . . 134 3 General principles of all the mutual duties of nations . . 135 4 Duties of a nation for the preservation of others . . ib. 5 She is bound to assist a nation afflicted with famine or any other calamity ....... 136 6 She is bound to contribute" to the perfection of other states . . ib. 7 but not by force ..... 137 8 The right to require the offices of humanity . . . 138 9 The right of judging whether they are to be granted . . ib. 10 A nation is not to compel another to perform those offices of which the refusal is no wrong ...... ib. 11 Mutual love of nations . . . ib. 12 Each nation is bound to cultivate the friendship of others . ib. 13 to perfect herself, with the view to the advantage of others, and to set them good examples .... 139 14 to take care of their glory .... ib. 15 Difference of religion ought not to preclude the offices of humanity ib. 16 Rule and measure of the offices of humanity . . . 140 17 Particular limitation with respect to the prince . \ . . 141 18 No nation ought to injure others . ...,.' . . ib. 19 Offences . . . . .... ^ . 142 20 Bad custom of the ancients . . . . , - ; . 143 CHAP. II. Of the Mutual Commerce between Nations. 21 General obligation of nations to carry on mutual commerce . 143 22 They are bound to favour trade . . ' . . 144 23 Freedom of trade ... . ib. CONTENTS. Sect. Pane 24 Right of trading belonging to nations .... 144 25 Each nation is sole judge of the propriety of commerce on her own part ib. 26 Necessity of commercial treaties *. . . . 145 27 General rule concerning those treaties . . . . ib. 28 Duty of nations in making such treaties . . . ib. 29 Perpetual or temporary treaties, or treaties revocable at pleasure ib. 30 Nothing contrary to the tenor of a treaty can be granted to a third party 146 31 How far lawful to give up by treaty the liberty of trading with other nations . . . . . . . ib. 32 A nation may restrict her commerce in favour of another nation . ib. 33 A nation may appropriate to herself a particular branch of trade . 147 34 Consuls . ... ib. CHAP. m. Of the Dignity and Equality of Nations, of Titles, and other Marks of Honour. 35 Dignity of nations or sovereign states .... 149 36 Their equality . . . '*?"7 . . . ib. 37 Precedency >-v '/. . . . , r . ,,- ,, ;1 -*.v,, J ib. 38 The form of government is foreign to this question . . 150 39 A state ought to retain her rank, notwithstanding any changes in the form of her government . . . . ib. 40 Treaties and established customs are to be observed in that respect ib. 41 Name and honours given by the nation to her conductor . . 151 42 Whether a sovereign may assume what title and honours he pleases 152 43 Right of other nations in that respect . . . . . ib. 44 Their duty ....... ib. 45 How titles and honours may be secured . . " . . 153 46 We must conform to general custom .... ib. 47 Mutual respect due by sovereigns to each other . . . ib. 48 How a sovereign ought to maintain his dignity ^ . . 154 CHAP. IV. Of the Right to Security, and the Effects of the Sovereignty and Independence of Nations. 49 Right to security . . . . . . .154 50 It produces the right of resistance ^ . . -re . ib. 51 and that of obtaining reparation . . . - . 155 52 and the right of punishing ~f ** . . . ib. 53 Right of all nations against a mischievous people . . . ib. 54 No nation has a right to interfere in the government of another state ib. 55 One sovereign cannot make himself judge of the conduct of another ib. 56 How far lawful to interfere in a quarrel between a sovereign and his subjects ....... 156 57 Right of opposing the interference of foreign powers in the affairs of - government . . . . . . .157 58 The same right with respect to religion .... ib. 59 No nation can be constrained in religious concerns . . 158 60 Offices of humanity in these matters : missionaries . ib, c2 CONTENTS. Sect. Page 61 Circumspection to be used . . . . . 159 62 What a sovereign may do in favour of those who profess his religion in another state . . ib. CHAP. V. Of the Observance of Justice between Nations. 63 Necessity of the observance of justice in human society . . 160 64 Obligation of all nations to cultivate and observe justice . ib. 65 Right of refusing to submit to injustice .... ib. 66 This right is a perfect one . . 161 67 It produces the right of self-defence .... ib. 68 the right of doing ourselves justice . . . ib. 69 The right of punishing injustice . . . . . ib. 70 Right of all nations against one that openly despises justice . ib. CHAP. VI. Of the Concern a Nation may have in the Actions of her Citizens. 71 The sovereign is bound to avenge the wrongs of the state and to pro- tect the citizens . . . . . .161 72 He must not suffer his subjects to offend other nations or their citizens 162 73 The acts of individuals not imputable to the nation . . ib. 74 unless she approve or ratify them . . . ib. 75 Conduct to be pursued by the offended party . . . ib. 76 Duty of the aggressor's sovereign .... 163 77 If he refuses justice, he becomes a party in the fault and offence . ib. 78 Another case in which the nation is guilty of the crimes of the citizens 164 CHAP. VII. Effects of the Domain, between Nations. 79 General effects of the domain ..... 164 80 What is comprehended in the domain of a nation . . 165 81 The property of the citizens is the national property with respect to foreign states . . . . . . . ib. 82 A consequence of that principle . . . '. ib. 83 Connection of the domain of the nation with the sovereignty . ib. 84 Jurisdiction ....... 166 85 Effects of the Jurisdiction in foreign countries . . . ib. 86 Desert and uncultivated places .... 167 87 Duty of the nation in that respect .... 168 88 Right of possessing things that have no owner . . . ib. 89 Rights granted to another nation . . . . . ib. 90 Not allowable to expel a nation from the country she inhabits . ib. 91 nor to extend by violence the bounds of empire . . 169 92 The limits of territories ought to be carefully ascertained . ib. 93 Violation of territory . . . . . . ib. 94 Prohibition to enter the territory .... 170 95 A country possessed by several nations at the same time . . ib. 96 A country possessed by a private person . . ib. CONTENTS. XXXI Sect. p a g e 97 Independent families in a country .... 170 98 Possessions of certain places only, or of certain rights, in a vacant country . . . '".', . ... . 171 CHAP. VIII. Rules respecting Foreigners. 99 General idea of the conduct a state ought to observe towards foreigners 171 100 Entering the territory **> J **y . . .172 101 Foreigners are subject to the laws . . _ , . ib. 102 and punishable according to the laws f . v^ . ib. 103 Who is the judge of their disputes . ,,.,. ' (: r ,... * .. T ,?* -173 104 Protection due to foreigners . . . . ib. 105 Their duties . . . . . . . ib. 106 To what burthens they are subject t ' . . . 174 107 Foreigners continue members of their own nation . . ib. 108 The state has no right over the person of a foreigner . . ib. 109 nor over his property . '-- , -. : - : t j - . 174 110 Who are the heirs of a foreigner .'- ..'. ' . 175 111 Will of a foreigner . . ' -Vw # 112 Escheatage ....... 176 113 The right of traite foraine . . . . .177 114 Immovable property possessed by an alien . . . ib 115 Marriages of aliens . . . . . . ib. CHAP. IX. Of the Rights retained by all Nations after the Introduction of Domain and Property. 116 What are the rights of which men cannot be deprived . . 178 117 Rights still remaining from the primitive state of communion . ib. 118 Right retained by each nation over the property of others . . ib. 119 Right of necessity ... . *^ . ib. 188 Treaties made for the king and his successors . . . ib. 189 Treaties made for the good of the kingdom . . '' . ib. 190 How presumption ought to be founded in doubtful cases . 207 191 The obligations and rights resulting from a real treaty pass to the successors . . . . -, . . 208 192 Treaties accomplished once for all, and perfected v. ' . ib. 193 Treaties already accomplished on the one part t . . 209 194 The personal alliance expires if one of the parties ceases to reign 211 195 Treaties in their own nature personal .... ib. 196 Alliance concluded for the defence of the king and royal family ib. 197 Obligation of a real alliance, when the allied king is deposed . 212 CHAP. XIII. Of the Dissolution and Renewal of Treaties. 198 Expiration of alliances made for a limited time . . . 213 199 Renewal of treaties . . . . . ' . ib. 200 How a treaty is dissolved, when violated by one of the contracting parties 214 201 The violation of one treaty does not cancel another . . ib. 202 The violation of one article in a treaty may cancel the whole . 215 203 The treaty is void by the destruction of one of the contracting powers 216 204 Alliances of a state that has afterwards put herself under the protec- tion of another . . . - ,< . . . ib. 205 Treaties dissolved by mutual consent . " . '..'. . . 217 CHAP. XIV. Of other public Conventions) of those that are made by Subordinate Powers, -particularly of the, Agreement called in Latin Sponsio, and of Conven- tions between the Sovereign and Private Persons. 206 Conventions made by sovereigns ..... 218 207 Those made by subordinate powers . . . .it, 208 Treaties concluded by a public person, without orders from the sove- reign, or without sufficient powers .... 219 5 XXXIV CONTENTS. Sect. P*g 209 The agreement called sponsio .... 210 The state is not bound by such an agreement . . 220 211 To what the promiser is bound when it is disavowed . . ib. 212 To what the sovereign is bound .... 223 213 Private contracts of the sovereign . . . 226 214 Contracts made by him with private persons, in the name of the state ib. 215 They are binding on the nation, and on his. successors . . 227 216 Debts of the sovereign and the state .... ib. 217 Donations of the sovereign ..... 228 CHAP. XV. Of the Faith of Treaties. 218 What is sacred among nations ..... 229 219 Treaties sacred between nations .... ib. 220 The faith of treaties is sacred . . . . . ib. 221 He who violates his treaties, violates the law of nations . ib. 222 Right of nations against him who disregards the faith of treaties . 230 223 The law of nations violated by the popes . . . ib. 224 This abuse authorized by princes . . . 231 225 Use of an oath in treaties. It does not constitute the obligation 232 226 It does not change the nature of obligations . . . ib. 227 It gives no pre-eminence to one treaty above another . . ib. 228 It cannot give force to a treaty that is invalid . . . 233 229 Asseverations ...... ib. 230 The faith of treaties does not depend on the difference of religion . ib. 231 Precaution to be taken in wording treaties . . . ib. 232 Subterfuges in treaties ...... 234 233 An evidently false interpretation inconsistent with the faith of treaties ib. 234 Faith tacitly pledged . . . . . . ib. CHAP. XVI. Of Securities given for the Observance of Treaties. 235 Guaranty . . . . . . .235 236 It gives the guarantee no right to interfere unasked in the execution of a treaty ....... 236 237 Nature of the obligation it imposes .... ib. 238 The guaranty cannot impair the rights of a third party . ib. 239 Duration of the guaranty ...... 237 240 Treaties with surety ...... ib. 241 Pawns, securities, and mortgages . . . . . ib. 242 A nation's right over what she holds as a pledge . - . v ib. 243 How she is obliged to restore it . . ': . .238 244 How she may appropriate it to herself .... ib. 245 Hostages . . . . . . . ib. 246 What right we have over hostages .... 239 247 Their liberty alone is pledged . . . . . ib. 248 When they are to be sent back .... ib. 249 Whether they may be detained on any other account . . ib. 250 They may be detained for their own actions . . . 240 251 Of the support of hostages . . . . ib. CONTENTS. XXXV Sect. Page 252 A subject cannot refuse to be a hostage . . . .241 253 Rank of the hostages . . ..... ib. 254 They ought not to make their escape .... ib. 255 Whether a hostage who diea is to be replaced . . . 242 256 Substitute for a hostage . . . . ib. 257 Hostage succeeding to the crown .... ib. 258 The liability of the hostage ends with the treaty . . . ib. 259 The violation of the treaty is an injury done to the hostages . ib. 260 The fate of the hostage when he who has given him fails in his en- gagements . . . . . .... 243 261 Right founded on custom . . . . . . ib. CHAP. XVII. Of the Interpretation of Treaties. 262 Necessity of establishing rules of interpretation . . . 244 263 First general maxim it is not allowable to interpret what has no need of interpretation . . . . . ib. 264 Second general maxim if he who could and ought to have explained himself, has not done it, it is to his own detriment . . 245 265 Third general maxim neither of the contracting parties has a right to interpret the treaty according to his own fancy . . ib. 266 Fourth general maxim what is sufficiently declared is to be taken for true . . . . . . . . ib. 267 "We ought to attend rather to the words of the person promising, than to those of the party stipulating .... ib. 268 Fifth general maxim the interpretation ought to be made according to certain rules .' . . . . . 246 269 The faith of treaties imposes an obligation to follow those rules 247 270 General rule of interpretation . . . . , r ' . ib. 271 The terms are to be explained conformably to common usage . 248 272 Interpretation of ancient treaties . . . .- . . ib. 273 Quibbles on words . V . .' .-..; E ; . 249 274 A rule on that subject . , ' .V v .. . . . . ib. 275 Mental reservations . ' . . \ ' . - . t 'j. 276 Interpretation of technical terms . . . . . ib. 277 Terms whose signification admits of degrees . , . 250 278 Figurative expressions . . ',' . * . , ib. 279 Equivocal expressions . . . . . . ib. 280 The rule for these two cases '. '. '. .'./". . .251 281 Not necessary to give a term the same sense everywhere in the same deed 252 282 We ought to reject every interpretation which leads to an absurdity ib. 283 or which renders the act null and void of effect . . 253 284 Obscure expressions interpreted by others more clear in the same author ........ 254 285 Interpretation founded on the connection of the discourse . ib. 286 Interpretation drawn from the connection and relation of the things themselves ....... 255 287 Interpretation founded on the reason of the deed . . . 256 288 Where many reasons have concurred to determine the will . ib. 289 What constitutes a sufficient reason for an act of the will . 257 XXXVI CONTENTS. Sect. Page 290 Extensive interpretation founded on the reason of the act . . 257 291 Frauds tending to elude laws or promises . . .258 292 Restrictive interpretation ...... 259 293 Its use, in order to avoid falling into absurdities, or into what is un- lawful . . . . . . . . ib. 294 or what is too severe and burthensome . . 260 295 How it ought to restrict the signification agreeably to the subject ib. 296 How a change happening in the state of things may form an exception 261 297 Interpretation of a deed in unforeseen cases . . . 262 298 Reasons arising from the possibility, and not the existence of a thing ib. 299 Expressions susceptible of an extensive and a limited sense . 263 300 Things favourable, and things odious .... ib. 301 What tends to the common advantage, and to equality, is favourable : the contrary is odious ...... 264 302 What is useful to human society, is favourable : the contrary is odious 265 303 Whatever contains a penalty is odious .... ib. 304 Whatever renders a deed void is odious . . . ib. 305 Whatever tends to change the present state of things, is odious : the contrary is favourable . . . . ib. 306 Things of a mixed nature ..... 266 307 Interpretation of favourable things .... ib. 308 Interpretation of odious things ..... 267 309 Examples .... 268 310 How we ought to interpret deeds of pure liberality . . 270 311 Collision of laws or treaties ..... 271 312 First rule in cases of collision . . . . ib. 313 Second rule ....... ib. 314 Third rule . . . . . . . ib. 315 Fourth rule ....... 272 316 Fifth rule . . . . . . ib. 317 Sixth rule 273 318 Seventh rule . ~ . . . * . . ib. 319 Eighth rule . . . . . .274 320 Ninth rule ib. 321 Tenth rule .... . ib. 322 General remark on the manner of observing all the preceding rules ib. CHAP. XVIH. Of the Mode of terminating Disputes between Nations. 323 General direction on this subject ..... 274 324 Every nation is bound to give satisfaction respecting the just com- plaints of another ...... 275 325 How nations may abandon their rights and just complaints . . ib. 326 Means suggested by the law of nature for terminating their disputes : amicable accommodation . . . . , 276 327 Compromise . . . .;,... . . ib. 328 Mediation ....... ib. 329 Arbitration . . . .".", . 277 330 Conferences and congresses ..... 278 331 Distinction to be made between evident and doubtful cases . ib. 332 Essential rights, and those of less importance . * . . 279 CONTENTS. XXXV11 Sect. Page 333 How we acquire a right of recurring to force in a doubtful case . 280 334 and even without attempting other measures . ib. 335 Voluntary law of nations on that subject .... ib. 336 Equitable conditions to be offered .... 281 337 Possessor's right in doubtful cases .... 282 338 How reparation of an injury is to be sought . . . ib. 339 Retaliation . ..... ib. 340 Various modes of punishing, without having recourse to arms . 283 341 Retortion . . . . . . . ib. 342 Reprisals ....... ib. 343 What is required to render them lawful .... 284 344 Upon what effects reprisals are made . . . ib. 345 The state is bound to compensate those who suffer by reprisals . 285 346 The sovereign alone can order reprisals . ib. 347 Reprisals against a nation for actions of her subjects, and in favour of the injured subjects ...... ib. 348 but not in favour of foreigners . . . ib. 349 Those who have given cause for reprisals are bound to indemnify those who suffer by them . . . . . 286 350 What may be deemed a refusal to do justice . . . 287 351 Subjects arrested by way of reprisals . . . . ib. 352 Our right against those who oppose reprisals . ,; , ; * . 288 353 Just reprisals do not afford a just cause for war . . . ib. 354 How we ought to confine ourselves to reprisals, or at length proceed to hostilities ib. BOOK III. OF WAR. CHAP. I. Of War, its different Kinds, and the Right of making War. 1 Definition of war .... . . . . . 291 2 Public war . . . , . . . . ib. 3 Right of making war . . . . . . ib. 4 It belongs only to the sovereign power . . . . . 292 5 Defensive and offensive war ..... 293 CHAP. II. Of the Instruments of War, the Raising of Troops, &c. their Commanders, or the Subordinate Powers in War. 6 Instruments of war ....... 293 7 Right of levying troops ...... 294 8 Obligation of the citizens or subjects ..... ib.+ 9 Enlisting or raising of troops . . . . ib. XXXV111 CONTENTS. Sect. Page 10 Whether there be any exemptions from carrying arms . . 294 11 Soldiers' pay and quarters ..... 296 12 Hospitals for invalids . . . . . . ib. 13 Mercenary soldiers ...... 297 14 Rule to be observed in their enlistment .... 298 15 Enlisting in foreign countries ..... 16. 16 Obligation of soldiers . . . . 299 17 Military laws ....... ib. 18 Military discipline . . . . ib. 19 Subordinate powers in war . . . . . ib. 20 How their promises bind the sovereign . . 300 21 In what cases their promises bind only themselves . . ib. 22 Their assumption of an authority which they do not possess . ib. 23 How they bind their inferiors ..... 301 CHAP. JfL. Of the Just Causes of War. 24 War never to be undertaken without very cogent reasons . . 301 25 Justificatory reasons, and motives for making war . . ib. 26 What is in general a just cause of war .... 302 27 What war is unjust ...... ib. 28 The object of war ..... . ib. 29 Both justificatory reasons and proper motives requisite in undertaking a war . . . . . . .303 30 Proper motives vicious motives . . . . ib. 31 War undertaken upon just grounds, but from vicious motives . ib. 32 Pretexts ........ 304 33 War undertaken merely for advantage . ib. 34 Nations who make war without reason or apparent motives . . 305 35 How defensive war is just or unjust .... ib. 36 How it may become just against an offensive war which was originally just . . . . . . . . ib. 37 How an offensive war is just in an evident cause . . ib. 38 in a doubtful cause . . . . .306 39 War cannot be just on both sides .... ib. 40 Sometimes reputed lawful . . . . . . ib. 41 War undertaken to punish a nation .... 307 42 Whether the aggrandizement of a neighbouring power can authorize a war against him ... . . ib. 43 Alone, and of itself, it cannot give a right to attack him . 308 44 How the appearances of danger give that right . '. . 309 45 Anothet case more evident . . . . .310 46 Other allowable means of defence against a formidable power . 311 47 Political equilibrium ...... ib. 48 Ways of maintaining it . . . .312 49 How he that destroys the equilibrium may be restrained, or even weakened . . . . ... . ib. , 50 Behaviour allowable towards a neighbour preparing for war . .313 CONTENTS. XXXIX CHAP. IV. Of the Declaration of War, and of War in due Form. Sect. Page 51 Declaration of war : necessity thereof . . . .315 52 What it is to contain . . . . . ib. 53 It is simple or conditional . . . . . .316 54 The right to make war ceases on the offer of equitable conditions ib. 55 Formalities of a declaration of war .... ib. 56 Other reasons for the necessity of its publication . . ib. 57 Defensive war requires no declaration .... 317 58 When it may be omitted in an offensive war . . . ib. 59 It is not to be omitted by way of retaliation . . . ib. 60 Time of the declaration . . . . ib. 61 Duty of the inhabitants on a foreign army's entering a country before a declaration of war . . . . . . ib. 62 Commencement of hostilities ..... 318 63 Conduct to be observed towards the enemy's subjects who are in the country at the time of the declaration of war . . . ib. 64 Publication of the war, and manifestoes . . . ib. v 65 Decorum and moderation to be observed in the manifestoes . 319 66 What is a lawful war in due form . . . ib. 67 It is to be distinguished from informal and unlawful war . . 320 68 Grounds of this distinction ib. CHAP. V. Of the Enemy , and of Things belonging to the Enemy. 69 Who is an enemy . . ' . . * V '" . . .321 70 All the subjects of the two states at war are enemies . . ib. 71 and continue to be enemies in all places . . . ib. 72 Whether women and children are to be accounted enemies . ib. 73 Things belonging to an enemy ..... 322 74 continue such everywhere .... ib. 75 Neutral things found with an enemy .... ib. 76 Lands possessed by foreigners in an enemy's country . . ib. 77 Things due to the enemy by a third party . . . . ib. CHAP^VI. Of the Enemy's Allies, of Warlike Associations, of Auxiliaries and Sub sidies. 78 Treaties relative to war . . . . . .323 79 Defensive and offensive alliances . . . ib. 80 Difference between warlike alliances and defensive treaties . . 324 81 Auxiliary troops ...... ib. 82 Subsidies . . . . . . . . ib. 83 When a nation is authorized to assist another . . . ib. 84 and to make alliances for war . . ib. Xl CONTENTS. Sect. Page 85 Alliances made with a nation actually engaged in war . . 325 86 Tacit clause in every warlike alliance . . . ib. 87 To refuse succours for an unjust war is no breach of alliance . 326 88 What the casus fcederis is ..... ib. 89 It never takes place in an unjust war .... ib. 90 How it exists in a defensive war . . . ib. 91 and in a treaty of a guaranty . . . ib. 92 The succour is not due under an inability to furnish it, or when the public safety would be exposed .... ib. 93 Other cases : two of the parties in an alliance coming to a rupture 327 94 Refusal of the succours due in virtue of an alliance . . ib. 95 The enemy's associates . . . ., . .328 96 Those who make a common cause with the enemy are his associates ib. 97 and those who assist him, without being obliged to it by treaties . . . . . . . ib. 98 or who are in an offensive alliance with him . 329 99 How a defensive alliance associates with the enemy . . ib. 100 Another case ....... ib. 101 In what case it doee not produce the same effect . . . 330 102 Whether it be necessary to declare war against the enemy's associates 331 CHAP. VII. Of Neutrality, and the Passage of Troops through a Neutral Country. 103 Neutral nations . . .'< . . , . . .332 104 Conduct to be pursued by a neutral nation . . . ib. 105 An ally may furnish the succour due from him, and remain neuter 333 106 Right of remaining neuter . . . . . ib. 107 Treaties of neutrality . . . . . . ib. 108 Additional reasons for making those treaties . . . 334 109 Foundation of the rules of neutrality .... ib. 110 How levies may be allowed, money lent, and every kind of things sold, without a breach of neutrality . . . ib. 111 Trade of neutral nations with those which are at war . . 335 112 Contraband goods ...... 336 113 Whether such goods may be confiscated .... 337 114 Searching neutral ships . . . . .339 115 Enemy's property on board a neutral ship .... ib. 116 Neutral property on board an enemy's ship . ... .. . . ib. 117 Trade with a besieged town . . . . . ib. 118 Impartial offices of neutrals ." . . . . 340 119 Passage of troops through a neutral country . . . ib. 120 Passage to be asked . . . . ib. 121 It may be refused for good reasons '_ . ^, , vf ,, . a . 341 122 In what case it may be forced . . . , . vl . ib. 123 The fear of danger authorizes a refusal .... 342 124 or a demand of every reasonable security . . ib. 125 Whether always necessary to give every kind of security required . ib. 126 Equality to be observed towards both parties, as to the passage 343 127 No complaint lies against a neutral state for granting a passage . ib. CONTENTS. Xli Sect. Page 128 That state may refuse it from fear of the resentment of the opposite party . . ... 343 129 and lest her country should become the theatre of war ib. 130 What is included in the grant of passage . . . . 344 131 Safety of the passage . . . . . ib. 132 No hostility to be committed in a neutral country . . . ib. 133 Neutral country not to afford a retreat to troops, that they may again attack their enemies . . . 345 134 Conduct to be pursued by troops passing through a neutral country ib. 135 A passage may be refused for a war evidently unjust . . ib. CHAP. VIII. Of the Sights of Nations in War, and first, of what we have a Right to do, and what we are allowed to do, to the Enemy's Person in a just War. 136 General principle of the rights against an enemy in a just war . 346 137 Difference between what we have a right to do, and what is barely allowed to be done with impunity between enemies . . ib. 138 The right to weaken an enemy by every justifiable method . 347 139 The right over the enemy's person .... ib. 140 Limits of that right : an enemy not to be killed after ceasing to resist ib. 141 A particular case in which quarter may be refused . . 348 142 Reprisals . . . . ' . . . . ib. 143 Whether a governor of a town can be punished with death for an obstinate defence ...... 349 144 Fugitives and deserters ...... 351 145 Women, children, the aged, and sick .... ib. 146 Clergy, men of letters, &c. . . .' ^ . 352 147 Peasants, and, in general, all who do not carry arms . ' . ib. 148 The right of making prisoners of war . ,.... . . 353 149 A prisoner of war not to be put to death . ' . 354 150 How prisoners of war are to be treated . . , -.. . ib. 151 Whether prisoners, who cannot be kept or fed, may be put to death 355 152 Whether prisoners of war may be made slaves . . . 356 153 Exchange and ransom of prisoners .... 357 154 The state is bound to procure their release . . . ib. 155 Whether an enemy may lawfully be assassinated or poisoned . 358 156 Whether poisoned weapons may be used in war . . 361 157 Whether springs may be poisoned . """*' . ib. 158 Disposition to be entertained towards an enemy . . 362 159 Tenderness for the person of a king who is in arms against us ^ . 363 CHAP. IX. Of the Right of War, with Respect to Things belonging to the Enemy. 160 Principles of the right over things belonging to the enemy . 364 161 The right of seizing them . . . . ib. 162 What is taken from the enemy by way of penalty . . ib. 163 What is withheld from him, in order to oblige him to give just satis- faction ....... 365 6 D 2 Xlll CONTENTS. Sect. Page 164 Booty 365 165 Contribution ....... 366 166 Waste and destruction . . . . . . ib. 167 Ravaging and burning ..... 367 168 What things are to be spared . . . . .368 169 Bombarding towns ...... ib. 170 Demolition of fortresses . . . . . 369 171 Safeguards ....... ib, 172 General rule of moderation respecting the evil which may be done to an enemy . . . . . . ib. 173 Rule of the voluntary law of nations on the same subject . ib. CHAP. X. Of Faith between Enemies, of Stratagems, Artifices in War, Spies, and some other Practices. 174 Faith to be sacred between enemies .... 371 175 What treaties are to be observed between enemies . . 372 176 On what occasions they may be broken .... ib. 177 Lies . . . . . . . . ib. 178 Stratagems and artifices in war ..... 373 179 Spies 375 180 Clandestine seduction of the enemy's people . . . 376 181 Whether the offers of a traitor may be accepted . . 377 182 Deceitful intelligence . . . . . . ib. CHAP. XI. Of the Sovereign who wages an unjust war. 183 An unjust war gives no right whatever . . . % 378 184 Great guilt of the sovereign who undertakes it . . ib. 185 His obligations ....... 379 186 Difficulty of repairing the injury he has done . . . ib. 187 Whether the nation and the military are bound to any thing . 380 CHAP. XH. Of the Voluntary Law of Nations, as it regards the Effects of Regular Warfare, independently of the Justice of the Cause. 188 Nations not rigidly to enforce the law of nature against each other 381 189 Why they are bound to admit the voluntary law of nations . ib. 190 Regular war, as to its effects, is to be accounted just on both sides 382 191 Whatever is permitted to one party, is so to the other . ib. 192 The voluntary law gives no more than impunity to him who wages an unjust war ....... 383 CONTENTS. Xliii CHAP. xm. Of Acquisitions by War, and particularly of Conquests. Seet. Pag 193 War a mode of acquisition ..... 384 194 Measure of the right it gives . . . . ib. 195 Rules of the voluntary law of nations . . . .385 19Q Acquisition of movable property .... ib. 197 Acquisition of immovables, or conquest .... 386 198 How to transfer them validly . . . . 387 199 Conditions on which a conquered town is acquired . . ib. 200 Lands of private persons . . . . . 388 201 Conquest of the whole state . . . . . ib. 202 To whom the conquest belongs . . . .391 203 Whether we are to set at liberty a people whom the enemy had un- justly conquered .... . . . . . ib. CHAP. XIV. Of the Right of Postliminium. 204 Definition of the right of postliminium .... 392 205 Foundation of that right . . . ' . ib. 206 ]Jow it takes effect ...... 393 207 Whether it takes effect among the allies . . . ib. 208 Of no validity in neutral nations . . . . . ib. 209 What things are recoverable by that right . . . 394 210 Of those who cannot return by the right of postliminium . . ib. 211 They enjoy that right when retaken .... ib. 212 Whether that right extends to their property alienated by the enemy 395 213 Whether a nation that has been entirely subdued can enjoy the right of pcstliminium ...... 396 214 Right of postliminium for what is restored at the peace . . 397 215 and for things ceded to the enemy . . . ib. 216 The right of postliminium does not exist after a peace . . ib. 217 Why always in force for prisoners .... ib. 218 They are free even by escaping into a neutral country . . ib. 219 How the rights and obligations of prisoners subsist . . 398 220 Testament of a prisoner of war . . . . . ib. 221 Marriage ...... ib. 222 Regulations established by treaty or custom, respecting postliminium ib. CHAP. XV. Of the Right of Private Persons in War. 223 Subjects cannot commit hostilities without the sovereign's order 399 224 That order may be general or particular .... ib. 225 Source of the necessity of such an order . . . ib. 226 Why the law of nations should have adopted this rule . . ib. 227 Precise meaning of the order ..... 400 228. What may be undertaken by private persons, presuming on the sovereign's will ...... ib. 229 Privateers . . . . . . . ib. 230 Volunteers ....... 401 xliv CONTENTS. Sect, Page 231 What soldiers and subalterns may do . . . .401 232 Whether the state is bound to indemnify the subjects for damages sustained in war ..... 402 CHAP. XVI. Of various Conventions made during the Course of the War. 233 Truce and suspension of arms . . . . 404 234 does not terminate the war .... ib. 235 A truce is either partial or general .... ib. 236 General truce for many years .... ib. 237 By whom those agreements may be concluded . . . 405 238 The sovereign's faith engaged in them . . . 406 239 When the truce begins to be obligatory .... ib. 240 Publication of the truce . . . . . ib. 241 Subjects contravening the truce . . . . . ib. 242 Violation of the truce . . . . . 407 243 Stipulation of a penalty against the infractor , , < . ib. 244 Time of the truce . . . . . . ib. 245 Effects of a truce : what is allowed or not, during its continuance. First rule Each party may do at home what they have a right to do in time of peace ...... 408 246 Second rule not to take advantage of the truce in doing what hos- tilities would have prevented .... 409 247 for instance, continuing the works of a siege, or repairing breaches . . . . . . . ib. 248 or introducing succours .... ib. 249 Distinction of a particular case ..... 410 250 Retreat of an army during a suspension of hostilities . . ib. 251 Third rule Nothing to be attempted in contested places, but every thing to be left as it was . . . . .411 252 Places quitted or neglected by the enemy . . . ib. 253 Subjects inclined to revolt against their prince not to be received during the truce . . . . . ib. 254 much less to be solicited to treason . . ib. 255 Persons or effects of enemies not to be seized during the truce . ib. 256 Right of postliminium during the truce . . . ib. 257 Intercourse allowed during a truce .... ib. 258 Persons detained by unsurmountable obstacles after the expiration of the truce . . . . . . 412 259 Particular conditions added to truces . . ' " .' : . ib. 260 At the expiration of the truce the war recommences without any new declaration . . . . . . ib. 261 Capitulations ; and by whom they may be concluded . . ib. 262 Clauses contained in them . . - ' . . 413 263 Observance of capitulations, and its utility . , . 414 264 Promises made to the enemy by individuals . . . ib. CHAP. XVII. Of Safe-conducts and Passports, and Questions on the Hansom of Prisoners of War. 265 Nature of safe-conducts and passports . . . . 416 266 From what authority they emanate . . *~< . . ib. 267 Not transferable from one person to another . . . ib. CONTENTS. xlv Sect. Page 268 Extent of the promised security ..... 416 269 How to judge of the right derived from a safe conduct . . 417 270 Whether it includes baggage and domestics . . . ib. 271 Safe conduct granted to the father does not include his family . ib. 272 Safe conduct given in general to any one and his retinue . . ib. 273 Term of the safe conduct ..... 418 274 A person unavoidably detained beyond the term . . ib 275 The safe conduct does not expire at the death of him who gave it ib. 276 How it may be revoked . . . . . ib. 277 Safe conduct, with the clause " for such time as we shall think fit" ib. 278 Conventions relating to the ransom of prisoners . . . 419 279 The right of demanding a ransom may be transferred . . ib. 280 What may annul the convention made for the rate of the ransom . ib. 281 A prisoner dying before payment of ransom . . . ib. 282 Prisoner released on condition of procuring the release of another . 420 283 Prisoner retaken before he has paid his former ransom . ib. 284 Prisoner rescued before he has received his liberty . . ib. 285 Whether the things which a prisoner has found means to conceal, belong to him ...... 421 286 Hostage given for the release of a prisoner . . . ib. CHAP. xvin. Of Civil War. 287 Foundation of the sovereign's rights against the rebels . . 421 288 Who are rebels ...... 422 289 Popular commotion, insurrection, sedition .... ib. 290 How the sovereign is to suppress them . . . ib. 291 He is bound to perform the promises he has made to the rebels . 423 292 Civil war 424 293 A civil war produces two independent parties . . .425 294 They are to observe the common laws of war . . . ib. 295 The effects of civil war distinguished according to cases . . 426 296 Conduct to be pursued by foreign nations . . . 427 BOOK IV. OF THE RESTORATION OF PEACE ; AND OF EMBASSIES. CHAP. I. Of Peace, and the Obligation to cultivate it. 1 What peace is ....... 429 2 Obligation of cultivating it ..... 430 3 The sovereign's obligation in that respect .... ib. 4 Extent of that duty ...... ib. 5 Disturbers of the public peace . . . . .431 6 How far war may be continued . . . . . ib. 7 Peace the end of war . . , . . . 432 8 General effects of peace . . . . ib. Xlvi CONTENTS. CHAP. II. Treaties of Peace. Sect. Pag* 9 Definition of a treaty of peace ..... 432 10 By whom it may be concluded . . . . . ib. 11 Alienations nnde by a treaty of peace ^ . . . . 433 12 How the sovereign may, in a treaty, dispose of what concerns individuals 435 13 Whether a king who is a prisoner of war can make a peace . . ib. 14 Whether peace can be made with an usurper . . . 436 15 Allies included in the treaty of peace . * . . ib. 16 Associates to treat, each for himself .... 437 17 Mediation . . . . . . . ib. 18 On what footing peace may be concluded . . . ib. 19 General effect of the treaty of peace .... 438 20 Amnesty ...... 439 21 Things not mentioned in the treaty .... ib. 22 Things not included in the compromise or amnesty . . ib. 23 Former treaties, mentioned or confirmed in the new, are a part of it 440 CHAP. III. Of the Execution of the Treaty of Peace. 24 When the obligation of the treaty commences . . . 440 25 Publication of the peace . . . . ib. 26 Time of the execution ...... 441 27 A lawful excuse to be admitted .... ib. 28 The promise is void when the party to whom it was made has himself hindered the performance of it . . . . . ib. 29 Cessation of contributions ..... 442 30 Products of the thing restored or ceded .... ib. 31 In what condition things are to be restored . . . ib. 32 The interpretation of a treaty of peace is to be against the superior party 443 33 Names of ceded countries . . . . ib. 34 Restoration not to be understood of those who have voluntarily given themselves up . . . . . . 444 CHAP. IV. Of the Observance and Breach of the Treaty of Peace. 35 The treaty of peace binds the nation and successors . . . 444 36 It is to be faithfully observed . . . . ib. 37 The plea of fear or force does not dispense with the observance . 445 38 How many ways a treaty of peace may be broken ' . . 446 39 by a conduct contrary to the nature of every treaty of peace ib. 40 To take up arms for a fresh cause is no breach of the treaty of peace ib. 41 A subsequent alliance with an enemy is likewise no breach of the treaty 447 42 Why a distinction is to be made between a new war and a breach of the treaty . . . . . . . ib. 43 Justifiable self-defence is no breach of the treaty . . 448 44 Causes of rupture on account of allies .... 449 45 The treaty is broken by what is contrary to its particular nature ib. 46 by the violation of any article .... ib. 47 The violation of a single article breaks the whole treaty . . ib. CONTENTS. Xlvii Sect, Page 48 Whether a distinction may here be made between the more and the less important articles ...... 450 49 Penalty annexed to the violation of an article . . . ib. 50 Studied delays . . . . . . ib. 51 Unsurmountable impediments . . . . . ib. 52 Infractions of the treaty of peace by the subjects . . . 451 53 or by allies ...... ib. 54 Right of the offended party against him who has violated the treaty 452 CHAP. V. Of the Right of Embassy, or the Right of sending and receiving Public Ministers. 55 It is necessary that nations be enabled to treat and communicate together 452 56 They do that by the agency of public ministers . . . 453 57 Every sovereign state has a right to send and receive public ministers ib. 58 An unequal alliance, or a treaty of protection, does not take away that right . . . . . . . . ib. 59 Right of the princes and states of the empire in that respect . ib. 60 Cities that have the right of banner . . . . 454 61 Ministers of viceroys . . . . . ' . 455 62 Ministers of the nation or of the regents during an interregnum . ib. 63 Sovereign molesting another in the exercise of the right of embassy ib. 64 What is allowable in that respect in time of war . . ib. 65 The minister of a friendly power is to be received . . . 456 66 Resident ministers ...... ib. 67 Admission of an enemy's ministers .... 457 68 Whether ministers may be received from or sent to an usurper . ib. CHAP. VI. Of the several Orders of Public Ministers, of the Representative Character, and of the Honours due to Ministers. 69 Origin of the several orders of public ministers . . . 459 70 Representative character . . . . . ib. 71 Ambassadors . . . . . . . ib. 72 Envoys ....... 460 73 Residents . . . . . . . . ib. 74 Ministers ....... ib. 75 Consuls, agents, deputies, commissioners, &c. 461 76 Credentials . . . . . . ib. 77 Instructions . . . . . . . ib. 78 Right of sending ambassadors . . . . ib. 79 Honours due to ambassadors . . . . ". 462 CHAP. VII. Of the Rights, Privileges, and Immunities of Ambassadors, and other Public Ministers. 80 Respect due to public ministers ..... 464 81 Their persons sacred and inviolable .... ib. 82 Particular protection due to them ..... 465 83 When it commences ...... 466 84 What is due to them in the countries through which they pass . ib. Xlviii CONTENTS. Sect. Page 85 Ambassadors going to an enemy's country .... 467 86 Embassies between enemies . . . . . ib. 87 Heralds, trumpeters, and drummers .... 468 88 Ministers, trumpeters, &c., to be respected even in a civil war . ib. 89 Sometimes they may be refused admittance . . . 469 90 Every thing which has the appearance of insult to them must be avoided ib. 91 By and to whom they may be sent . . . . 470 92 Independence of foreign ministers .... ib. 93 How the foreign minister is to behave .... 472 94 How he may be punished for ordinary transgressions . . 475 95 for faults committed against the prince . . ib. 96 Right of ordering away an ambassador who is guilty or justly suspected ib. 97 Right of repressing him by force, if he behaves as an enemy . 476 98 Ambassador forming dangerous plots and conspiracies . . ib. 99 What may be done to him according to the exigency of the case . 478 100 Ambassador attempting against the sovereign's life . . 479 101 Two remarkable instances respecting the immunities of public ministers 480 102 Whether reprisals may be made on an ambassador . . 481 103 Agreement of nations concerning the privileges of ambassadors . 482 104 Free exercise of religion ..... 483 105 Whether an ambassador be exempted from all imposts . . 484 106 Obligation founded on use and custom . . . 485 107 A minister whose character is not public .... ib. 108 A sovereign in a foreign country . . . 486 109 Deputies to the states ...... 487 CHAP. VIII. Of the Judge of Ambassadors in Civil Cases. 110 The ambassador is exempt from the civil jurisdiction of the country where he resides . . . . . .488 111 How he may voluntarily subject himself to it . . . 489 112 A minister who is a subject of the state where he is employed . 490 113 Immunity of the minister extends to his property . . 491 114 The exemption cannot extend to effects belonging to any trade the minister may carry on . . . . . . 492 115 nor to immovable property which he possesses in the country 493 116 How justice may be obtained against an ambassador . . ib. CHAP. IX. Of the Ambassador's House and Domestics. 117 The ambassador's house ...... 494 118 Right of asylum ...... 495 119 Exemption of an ambassador's carriages .... 496 120 of his retinue ..... 497 121 of his wife and family . . . . . ib. 122 of the secretary of the embassy . . . ib. 123 of the ambassador's couriers and despatches . . 498 124 The ambassador's authority over his retinue . . . ib. 125 When the rights of an ambassador expire .... 500 126 Cases when new credentials are necessary . . . ib. 127 Conclusion . . . , . . . ib. THE LAW OF NATIONS. PRELIMINARIES. IDEA AND GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF THE LAW OF NATIONS. JN ATIONS or states are bodies politic, societies of men 1. united together for the purpose of promoting their mutual is meant b ? safety and advantage by the joint efforts of their combined g t at*. 10n strength. Such a society has her affairs and her interests ; she de- 2. it is liberates and takes resolutions in common ; thus becoming a moral per ~ moral person, who possesses an understanding and a will pe- S01 culiar to herself, and is susceptible of obligations and rights. To establish on a solid foundation the obligations and ? 3. Defini- ng fas of nations, is the design of this work. tion of the The Law of Nations is the science which teaches the rights ^ subsisting between nations or states, and the obligations cor- respondent to those rights.(T) (1) The Law of Nations modifies the intercourse of independent com- monwealths in peace, and prescribes limits to their hostilities in war. It prescribes, that in peace nations should do each other as much good, and in time of war as little harm, as may be possi- ble, without injuring their own proper real interests. The laws of nations, in short, establish that principle and rule of conduct which should prevent the strongest nation from abusing its power, and induce it to act justly and gene- rously towards other states, upon the broad principle that true happiness, whether of a single individual or of several, can only result from each adopting conduct influenced by a sin- increase the general wel- fare of all mankind. (Post, $ 13, 14 ; General Mackintosh, Dis. 3, 4 ; Montesq. de views of the 1'Esprit des Lois, liv. 1, c. 3 ; and see law of na- 1 Bla. Com. 34 to 44 ; 4 Bla. Com. 66, tions, and 67.) In cases of doubt arising upon how it is to what is the Law of Nations, it is now be ascer- an admitted rule among all Euro- tained. pean nations, that our common reli- gion, Christianity, pointing out the principles of natural justice, should be equally appealed to and observed by all as an unfailing rule of construc- tion. (2 Ward's Law of Nations, pp. 11, 339, 340.) The difficulty is, that there is no general moral international code framed by the consent of the Eu- ropean powers, so desirable to be fixed, especially at this period, when harmony happily appears to subsist, and most N. B. The notes numbered as 1, 2, 3, 4, Ac., and in general concluding with 0., are by the present Editor. 7 E 49 Iv IDEA AND GENERAL PRINCIPLES ,IMI- I n this treatise it will appear, in what manner States, as ^ such, ought to regulate all their actions. We shall examine of the nations of Europe have, by re- cent experience, become practically convinced of the advantages that would result from the establishment of fixed general rules, so as to reconcile the fre- quent discordancy of the decisions of their various prize tribunals and upon other contests. The statesmen of the higher powers of Europe would immor- talize themselves by introducing such a code, and no period of history for the purpose has been so favourable and op- portune. (See Atcheson's Report of the case of Havelock v. Rockwood, Pre- face i.) The law of nations is adopted in Great Britain in its full and most liberal extent by the common law, and is held to be part of the law of the land ; and all statutes relating to foreign affairs should be framed with reference to that rule. (4 Bla. Com. 67.) But still there is no general code; and to the regret that none has been introduced, may be also added, the want of an interna- tional court or tribunal, to decide upon and enforce the law of nations when disputed ; and consequently, although when states are temperately inclined to ascertain and be governed by the law of nations, there will be little doubt upon the decision, or of the adoption of measures the most just ; yet, if a state will not listen to the immutable principles of reason, upon the basis of which the imperfect law of nations is founded, then the only remedy is to appeal to arms; and hence frequently the just cause of war, which, if there were a fixed code, with a proper tribu- nal to construe it, would in general be prevented. The pre- The sources from whence is to be sent sources gathered information what is the posi- of inforaa- tive Law of Nations generally and per- tion upon manently binding upon all independent the law of states f are acknowledged to be of three Nations. descriptions : First, the long and ordi- nary PRACTICE of nations, which affords evidence of a general custom, tacitly agreed to be observed until expressly abrogated. Secondly, the RECITALS of what is acknowledged to have been the law or practice of nations, and which recitals will frequently be found in modern treaties. Thirdly, the WRIT- INGS of eminent authors, who have long, as it were by a concurrence of testi- 50 mony and opinion, declared what is the existing international jurisprudence. Thus Lord Mansfield, in Triquet v. Bath, (3 Burr. Rep. 1481,) stated as the declaration of Lord Talbot, that the law of nations is to be collected from the practice of different nations, (and see per Sir William Scott, in The Fladoyen, 1 Rob. Rep. 115, post, Ixiii. n. (7),) and the authority of writers, such as Gro- tius, Barbeyrac, Bijnkershock, Wic- quefort, Ac., there being no English writer of eminence upon the subject; and English elementary writers of high authority have also acknowledged that such foreign authors are authorities to ascertain the law of nations. (Comyn's Digest, tit. "Ambassador," B. ; Viner's Ab. "Merchant," A. 1; and 3 Bla. Com. 273.) To these are to be added, Puffendorf, Wolf, Selden, Valen, Cle- rac, Pothier, Burlamaqui, Emerigon, Roccus, Casegis, Loecenius, Santerna, Maline, Molloy, and above all, the pre- sent work of Vattel; to which may be added some modern works of great ability, but not yet acknowledged to be such high general authority as the for- mer, viz. Ward's and Marten's Law of Nations, and the recent valuable French publication, Cours de Droit Public Interne et Externe, par le Com- mandeur Silvestre Pinheiro Ferreira, Ministre D'Etat au Paris, 1830, which embraces the French modern view of the law of nations upon most of the subjects discussed in Vattel and some others. It was from the more ancient of these several authors, and other similar re- sources, that Lord Mansfield framed the celebrated letter of the Duke of Newcastle to the King of Prussia's Secretary, which is considered a stand- ard of authority, upon the laws of nations, as far as respects the then disputed right to search for and seize enemies' property on board neutral ships in certain cases in time of war. (See Holliday's Life of Lord Mansfield, vol. 2, p. 424, Ac., and Col- lectanea Juridica, 1 vol. 129; see also Viveash v. Seeker, 3 Maule & Selwyn, 284, in which Lord Ellenborough quotes several of the above authors, to ascertain the law of nations upon the privilege of consuls.) Upon some parts of the law of OF THE LAW OF NATIONS. Iv the Obligations of a people, as well towards themselves as towards other nations ; and by that means we shall discover nations, especially that relating to mari- time affairs, there are ancient codes, which either originated in authority, or were afterwards acknowledged to have become such; but still those codes in the present state of commercial in- tercourse are imperfect Of those are the Rhodian Laws, being one of the earliest systems of marine law, but which was superseded by the collec- tion entitled Consolato del Mare, Gro- tius, Book 3, ch. 1, s. 5, n. 6. Next in order are the Laics of Oleron, pro- mulgated about the thirteenth century. Another system of international law was framed by the deputies of the Hanseatic League in 1597, and which was confirmed with additions in 1614, and has obtained much consideration in the maritime jurisprudence of na- tions. (See remarks on that code, 2 Ward's Law of Nations, 276 to 290). But the most complete and compre- hensive system of the marine law of nations is the celebrated Ordinance of Marine of Louis XIV., published in 1681, and which, coupled with the commentary of Valin, Lord Mansfield always treated as of the highest au- thority. (See 1 Marshall on Insurance, Prelim. Dis. 18.) In modern times, in order to pre- vent any dispute upon the existence or application of the general law of nations, either pending peace, or at or after the subsequently breaking out of war between two or more independent states, it has become the practice to enter into express treaties, carefully pro- viding for every contingency, and especially modifying and softening the injurious consequences of sudden war upon the commercial and other inter- course 'between the two states, and sometimes even wholly changing the character of war or of alienage, and even enabling a foreign alien enemy during war to retain his interest in land in the opponent country. (See an illustrating instance in Sutton v. Sutton, 1 Russ. & My. Rep. 663.) {Society, Ac. v. New Ha- ven, 8 Wheat R. 464. } In these cases, the treaty between the two contract- ing states either alters, or expressly de- clares the law of nations, and binds each. But still questions upon the general law of nations will frequently arise, and it will then become necessary to recur to the other evidence of what is the law of nations, viz. the previous ordinary and general or particular practice, or the opinion of the authors before alluded to. In the latter part of the last, and in the present century, a great accession of learning, information, and authority upon the law of nations has been af- forded by the valuable decisions of Sir W. Scott, (afterwards Lord Stowell,) and Sir J. Nicholl in the Court of Ad- miralty and Prize Court, and by seve- ral decisions in our Courts of Law and Equity. The known learning and scrupulous justice evinced in those decisions, have commanded the respect, the admiration and adoption, of all the European states, and of that modern, enlightened, and energetic nation, America. To these may be added, Chalmer's Collection of Opinions, which contain great learning upon many sub- jects of the public affairs of nations. These have been fully published since Vattel wrote; and the editor has at- tempted to improve this edition, by occasionally referring in the notes to the reports and work alluded to. The editor has also, in his Treatise on Com- mercial Law, and in a Summary of the Law of Nations, endeavoured to take a more extended view of some of those branches of the law of nations, princi- pally as it affects foreign commerce, and of the decisions and works subse- quent to the publication of Vattel. If the perfect general rights or law of Violation nations be violated, then it appears to O f Law of be conceded, that such violation may Nations, be the actual and avowed ground of a wncn a just war ; and it is even laid down that ground of it is the duty of every nation to chas- war . tise the nation guilty of the aggression. (Vattel, post, Book I. chap, xxiii. g 283, p. 126; Book II. chap. ii. g 24, p. 144; | 65, 66, 67, p. 160, 161.) Unhappily, especially in modern times, we have found that the law of nations has sometimes been set at naught by overpowerful states, adher- ing (to use the words of an English monarch) rather to Common Law than stopping to inquire whether the law of nature and of justice had not become, and been declared in that instance, part of the law of nations. It may therefore be asked, of what utility is the law of nations, since it is of such 51 Iv IDEA AND GENERAL PRINCIPLES PHELIMI- the Rights which result from these obligations. For, the NABI " 8 ' right being nothing more than the power of doing what is C I Y * 3 morally possible, that is to say, what is proper and consist- ent with duty, it is evident that right is derived from duty, or passive obligation, the obligation we lie under to act in such or such manner. It is therefore necessary that a Na- tion should acquire a knowledge.of the obligations incumbent on her, in order that she may not only avoid all violation of her duty, but also be able distinctly to ascertain her rights, or what she may lawfully require from other nations. 4. In Nations being composed of men naturally free and inde- what light pendent, and who, before the establishment of civil societies, "totes' are to ^ ve( ^ together m the state of nature, Nations, or sovereign be consi- states, are to be considered as so many free persons living dered. together in the state of nature. No nent or ge- imperfect and inefficient obligation? The answer is, that all nations, al- though for a time astounded and sur- prised by the unexpected aggression of an oppressive and ambitions conqueror, will yet ultimately feel, and endeavour to give effect to, the true law of na- tions, lest, by suffering its continued violations, they may individually be sacrificed ; and consequently, as in the instance alluded to, they will ulti- mately coalesce and associate in one common cause, to humiliate and over- come the proud invader of all just rights and principles. It is therefore of the highest importance to collect all the principles and rules, which, in cases of doubt, must ever be consulted, at least by statesmen, in endeavouring to settle differences between differing states ; and no authority stands higher in this respect than Vattel. There is no permanent and general international court, and it will be found, , , that in general the sovereign, or go- vernment of each state, who has the power of declaring war and peace, has also, as an incident, sole power of de- ciding upon questions of booty, cap- ture, prize, and hostile seizure, though sometimes that power is delegated, as in Great Britain, as respects maritime seizures, by commission to the judge of the Admiralty Court, with an ap- peal from his decisions to the Privy Council. In these cases no other mu- nicipal court has cognizance in case of any hostile seizure. Elphintton v. Be- dreeehund, Knapp's Rep. 316 to 361 ; and Hill v. 'lieardon, 2 Russ. Rep. 608, and further, post, p. 392. So there is no general international court in which 52 a treaty can be directly enforced, al- though, collaterally, its meaning may be discussed in a municipal court ; therefore, no bill to enforce a treaty can be sustained in equity. Nabob of Carnatic v. East India Company, 2 Ves. jun. 56 ; and Hill v. JRcardon, 2 Sim. A Stu. 437 ; 2 Russ. Rep. 608. Sometimes, however, especially in modern times, treaties, confirmed by temporary statutes in each country, ap- point a temporary international court, with limited powers, to decide upon certain claims, and to be satisfied out of an appointed public fund. Thus, in the treaty of peace between Great Britain and France, and by the 59 G. 3, c. 31, certain commissioners were ap- pointed to carry into effect the con- ventions for liquidating the claims of British subjects on the French govern- ment, with an appeal to the Privy Council. In these cases, the appointed jurisdiction is exclusive, and no other municipal court has any power as re- gards the adjustment of the claims be- tween the two subjects of each coun- try ; though, as between private indi- viduals, if any claimant stand in the situation of an agent or trustee, then, in a court of equity, he may be com- pelled to act as a trustee of the sum awarded to him. Hill v. lieardon, Jac. Rep. 84; 2 Russ. Rep. 608 to 633, over-ruling the Vice-Chancellor's de- cision in 2 Sim. & Stu. 437. C. { Co- megyg v. Vance, 1 Peters S. C. Rep. 193, decided upon the Treaty with Spain, which coded Florida to the United States, dated May 2d, 1819. See also Leitapies v. Inyraham, 5 Barr, 71, and the cases cited.} NARIES. OF THE LAW OF NATIONS. h It is a settled point with writers on the natural law, that PRELIMI- all men inherit from nature a perfect liberty and independ- ence, of which they cannot be deprived without their own consent. In a State, the individual citizens do not enjoy them fully and absolutely, because they have made a partial surrender of them to the sovereign. But the body of the nation, the State, remains absolutely free and independent with respect to all other men, and all other Nations, as long as it has not voluntarily submitted to them. As men are subject to the laws of nature, and as their g 5. To union in civil society cannot have exempted them from the ' " obligation to observe those laws, since by that union they 1 do not cease to be men, the entire nation, whose common will is but the result of the united wills of the citizens, re- mains subject to the laivs of nature, and is bound to respect them in all her proceedings. And since right arises from ob- ligation, as we have just observed ( 3), the nation possesses also the same rights which nature has conferred upon men in order to enable them to perform their duties. We must therefore apply to nations the rules of the law $ 6. in of nature, in order to discover what their obligations are, and wh t the what their rights : consequently, the law of Nations is origin- ^ w of ? a : ally no other than the law of Nature applied to Nations. n ^y ^J But as the application of a rule cannot be just and reason- sists. able unless it be made in a manner suitable to the subject, we are not to imagine that the law of nations is precisely and in every case the same as the law of nature, with the difference only of the subjects to which it is applied, so as to allow of our substituting nations for individuals. A state or civil so- ciety is a subject very different from an individual of the hu- man race ; from which circumstance, pursuant to the law of nature itself, there result, in many cases, very different obliga- tions and rights : since the same general rule, applied to two subjects, cannot produce exactly the same decisions, when the subjects are different ; and a particular rule which is per- [ Ivii ] fectly just with respect to one subject, is not applicable to another subject of a quite different nature. There are many cases, therefore, in which the law of Nature does not decide between state and state in the same manner as it would between man and man. We must therefore know how to accommodate the application of it to different sub- jects ; and it is the art of thus applying it with a precision founded on right reason, that renders the law of Nations a distinct science.(2) (2) M. de Vattel then proceeds to heads First, the natural law of na- state the different heads of interna- tions ; and secondly, the positive. The tional law, which has been variously former is that of God and our con- subdivided by other writers. The science, and consequently immutable, clearest division is under too principal and ought to be the basis of the posi- Iviii IDEA AND GENERAL PRINCIPLES 7. Defini tion of the necessary law of na- tions. We call that the Necessary Law of Nations which consists in the application of the law of nature to Nations. It is Necessary because nations are absolutely bound to observe it. This law contains the precepts prescribed by the law of nature to States, on whom that law is not less obligatory than on in- tive laws of nations. The positive is threefold; First, the universal volun- tary law or uniform practice of nations in general ; secondly, the customary law; and thirdly, the conventional lain or treaties. (See 1 Chitt/s Commer- cial Law, 25 to 47.) C. The following note of a former edi- tor is deservedly retained. The study of the science of the law of nations presupposes an acquaint- ance with the ordinary law of nature, of which human individuals are the objects. Nevertheless, for the sake of those who have not systematically studied that law, it will not be amiss to give in this place a general idea of it The natural law is the science of the laws of nature, of those laws which nature imposes on mankind, or to which they are subject by the very cir- cumstance of their being men ; a sci- ence, whose first principle is this axiom of incontestable truth " The great end of every being en8bwed with in- tellect and sentiment, is happiness." It is by the desire alone of that happi- ness, that we can bind a creature pos- sessed of the faculty of thought, and form the ties of that obligation which shall make him submit to any rule. Now, by studying the nature of things, and that of man in particular, we may thence deduce the rules which man must follow in order to attain his great end, to obtain the most perfect hap- piness of which he is susceptible. We call those rules the natural laws, or the laws of nature. They are certain, they are sacred, and obligatory on every man possessed of reason, inde- pendently of every other considera- tion than that of his nature, and even though we should suppose him totally ignorant of the existence of a God. But the sublime consideration of an eternal, necessary, infinite Being, the author of the universe, adds the most lively energy to the law of nature, and carries it to the highest degree of per- fection. That necessary Being ne- cessarily unites in himself all perfec- tion : he is, therefore, superlatively good, and displays his goodness by 54 forming creatures susceptible of hap- piness. It is then his wish that his creatures should be as happy as is con- sistent with their nature : consequently, it is his will that they should, in their whole conduct, follow the rules which that same nature lays down for them, as the most certain road to happiness. Thus the will of the Creator perfectly coincides with the simple indications of nature ; and those two sources pro- ducing the same law, unite in forming the same obligation. The whole re- verts to the first great end of man, which is happiness. It was to con- duct him to that great end that the laws of nature were ordained : it is from the desire pf happiness that his obliga- tion to observe those laws arises. There is, therefore, no man^what- ever may be his ideas respecting the origin of the universe even if he had the misfortune to be an atheist who is not bound to obey the laws of na- ture. They are necessary to the gene- ral happiness of mankind; and who- ever should reject them, whoever should openly despise them, would by such conduct alone declare himself an ene- my to the human race, and deserve to be treated as such. Now, one of the first truths which the study of man re- veals to ns, and which is a necessary consequence of his nature, is, that in a state of lonely separation from the rest of his species, ho cannot attain his great end happiness : and the reason is, that he was intended to live in society with his fellow-creatures. Nature, herself, therefore, has esta- blished that society, whoso great end is the common advantage of all its members; and the means of attaining that end constitute the rules that each individual is bound to observe in his whole conduct. Such are the natural laws of human society. Having thus given a general idea of them, which is sufficient for any intelligent reader, and is developed at large in several valuable works, let us return to the par- ticular object of this treatise. Note ed. A. D. 1797. OF THE LAW OF NATIONS. Iviti dividuals, since states are composed of men, their resolutions PRELIMI- are taken by men, and the law of nature is binding on all NARIKS ' men, under whatever relation they act. This is the law which Grotius, and those who follow him, call the Internal law of Nations, on account of its being obligatory on nations in point of conscience.^) Several writers term it the Na- tural laiv of Nations. Since therefore the necessary law of nations consists in the g s. It is application of the law of nature to states, which law is im- immutable, mutable, as being founded on the nature of things, and par- ticularly on the nature of man, it follows that the Necessary law of nations is immutable. Whence, as this law is immutable, and the obligations that g 9. Nations arise from it necessary and indispensable, nations can neither can make make any changes in it by their conventions, dispense with it no chan g e in their own conduct, nor reciprocally release each other from ^sj* " 8 e r the observance of it. with the ob- This is the principle by which we may distinguish lawful ligations conventions or treaties from those that are not lawful, and ^ isin s from innocent and rational customs from those that are unjust or 1 ' censurable. There are things, just in themselves, and allowed by the necessary law of nations, on which states may mutually agree with each other, and which they may consecrate and enforce by their manners and customs. There are others of an in- [ lix ] different nature, respecting which, it rests at the option of nations to make in their treaties whatever agreements they please, or to introduce whatever custom or practice they think proper. But every treaty, every custom, which con- travenes the injunctions or prohibitions of the Necessary law of nations is unlawful. It will appear, however, in the sequel, that it is only by the Internal law, by the law of Conscience, such conventions or treaties are always condemned as unlaw- ful, and that, for reasons which shall be given in their pro- per place, they are nevertheless often valid by the external law. Nations being free and independent, though the con- duct of one of them be illegal and condemnable by the laws of conscience, the others are bound to acquiesce in it, when it does not infringe upon their perfect rights. The liberty of that nation would not remain entire, if the others were to arrogate to themselves the right of inspecting and regulating her actions ; an assumption on their part, that would be con- trary to the law of nature, which declares every nation free and independent of all the others. Man is so formed by nature, that he cannot supply all his 10. S( own wants, but necessarily stands in need of the intercourse ci ^y esta- and assistance of his fellow-creatures, whether for his imme- J^^f by between all (3) See this position illustrated, mercial Law, 28, and n. (4), pott, Ix. mankind. Mackintosh, Dis. 7; 1 Chitty's Com- C. 55 Ik IDEA AND GENERAL PRINCIPLES PRELIMI- diate preservation, or for the sake of perfecting his nature, and enjoying such a life as is suitable to a rational being. This is sufficiently proved by experience. We have in- stances of persons, who, having grown up to manhood among the bears of the forest, enjoyed not the use of speech or of reason, but were, like the brute beasts, possessed only of sen- sitive faculties. We see moreover that nature has refused to bestow on men the same strength and natural weapons of de- fence with which she has furnished other animals having, in lieu of those advantages, endowed mankind with the faculties of speech and reason, or at least a capability of acquiring them by an intercourse with their fellow-creatures. Speech enables them to communicate with each other, to give each other mutual assistance, to perfect their reason and know- ledge ; and having thus become intelligent, they find a thou- sand methods of preserving themselves, and supplying their wants. Each individual, moreover, is intimately conscious that he can neither live happily nor improve his nature with- out the intercourse and assistance of others. Since, there- fore, nature has thus formed mankind, it is a convincing [ lx ] proof of her intention that they should communicate with, and mutually aid and assist each other. Hence is deduced the establishment of natural society among men. The general law of that society z's, that each indivi- dual should do for the others every thing which their necessities require, and which he can perform without neglecting the duty that he orves to himself: (4) a law which all men must observe in order to live in a manner consonant to their nature, and conformable to the views of their common Creator, a law which our own safety, our happiness, our dearest interests, ought to render sacred to every one of us. Such is the gene- ral obligation that binds us to the observance of our duties : let us fulfil them with care, if we would wisely endeavour to promote our own advantage.(5) (4) Ante, Mi. n. (2), post, lx. n. (4). whether the precise acts required of (5) See the same position, post, him be or be not such as their own \ 13, and post, chap. ii. g 2 and 88. municipal law will enforce ; just so a The natural, or primary law, is that state, in its relations with other states, of God and our conscience, the law is bound to conduct herself in the which enjoins us to do good to our spirit of justice, benevolence, and good neighbour, whether in literal strictness faith, even though there be no positive he may have a perfect right to demand rules of international law, by the let- such treatment from us or not. This ter of which she may bo actually tied is a law that ought to bo as strong in down. The same rules of morality obligation as the most distinct and which hold togqther men in families, positive rule, though it may not al- and which form families into a corn- ways be capable of the samo precise monwealth, also link together several definition, nor consequently may al- commonwealths as members of tho low tho samo remedies to enforce its ob- great society of mankind. Common- gervance. As an individual is bound wealths, as well as private men, are by the law of nature to deal honour- liable to injury, and capable of benefit ably and truly with other individuals, from each other; it is therefore their 66 OF THE LAW OF NATIONS. lx It is easy to conceive what exalted felicity the world would PKELIMI- enjoy, were all men willing to observe the rule that we have NARIES - just laid down. On the contrary, if each man wholly and immediately directs all his thoughts to his own interest, if he does nothing for the sake of other men, the whole human race together will be immersed in the deepest wretchedness. Let us therefore endeavour to promote the general happiness of mankind : all mankind, in return, will endeavour to promote ours, and thus we shall establish our felicity on the most solid foundations. The universal society of the human race being an institu- 1 JJ^J d tion of nature herself, that is to say, a necessary consequence J^ions? of the nature of man, all men, in whatever stations they are placed, are bound to cultivate it, and to discharge its duties. They cannot liberate themselves from the obligation by any convention, by any private association. When, there- fore, they unite in civil society for the purpose of forming a separate state or nation, they may indeed enter into particu- lar engagements towards those with whom they associate themselves ; but they remain still bound to the performance of their duties towards the rest of mankind. All the differ- ence consists in this, that having agreed to act in common, and having resigned their rights and submitted their will to the body of the society, in every thing that concerns their common welfare, it thenceforward belongs to that body, that state, and its rulers, to fulfil the duties of humanity towards [ Ixi ] strangers, in every thing that no longer depends on the liberty of individuals ; and it is the state more particularly that is to perform those duties towards other states. We have already seen, ( 5), that men united in society remain subject to the obligations imposed upon them by human nature. That society, considered as a moral person, since possessed of an understanding, volition, and strength peculiar to itself, is therefore obliged to live on the same terms with other socie- ties or states, as individual man was obliged, before those establishments, to live with other men, that is to say, accord- ing to the laws of the natural society established among the human race, with the difference only of such exceptions as may arise from the different nature of the subjects. duty to reverence, to practise, and to ty's Commercial Law, 28; Mackin- enforce, those rales of justice which tosh, Disc. 7; Peake's Rep. 116; 2 control and restrain injury, which Hen. Bla. 259 ; and see ante, \ 1 ; and regulate and augment benefit, which see extract from Mr. Pitt's celebrated preserve civilized states in a tolerable speech on concluding the commercial condition of security from wrong, and treaty between Great Britain and which, if they could be generally France in A. D. 1786, and in which he cteyed, would establish, and penna- powerfully refuted the doctrine of na- nently maintain, the well-being of the tional and hereditary antipathy between universal commonwealth of the human England and France, post, book ii. chap. race. (See Observations in 1 Chit- ii. 3 21, p. 144. C. 8 57 Ixi IDEA AND GENERAL PRINCIPLES pRELiiri- Since the object of the natural society established between ^ all mankind is that they should lend each other mutual as- o\/ect of 16 8 ^ s ^ ance J i n order to attain perfection themselves, and to this 6 sod- render their condition as perfect as possible, and since na- ety of na- tions, considered as so many free persons living together in tions. a state of nature, are bound to cultivate human society with each other, the object of the great society established by nature between all nations is also the interchange of mutual assistance for their own improvement, and that of their con- dition. I is. First The first general law that we discover in the very object general ob- o f the society of nations, is that each individual nation is v^g 011 ".* bound to contribute every thing in her power to the happiness nations, but an ^ perfection of all the others.* not to pre- But the duties that we owe to ourselves being unquestion- judice itself, ably paramount to those we owe to others, a nation owes herself in the first instance, and in preference to all other nations, to do every thing she can to promote her own hap- g 14. Ex- piness and perfection. (I say, every thing she can, not only pianation in a physical but in a moral sense, that is, every thing of this ob- that she can do lawfully, and consistently ivith justice and sen-ation. h onour ^ When, therefore, she cannot contribute to the wel- fare of another nation without doing an essential injury to [ Ixii ] herself, her obligation ceases on that particular occasion, and she is considered as lying under a disability to perform the office in question. (6) g 15. The Nations being free and independent of each other, in the second ge- same manner as men are naturally free and independent, the nerai law second general law of their society is, that each nation should fraud in- ~ ^ e ^ e ft * n ^ e P eaceao ^ e enjoyment of that liberty which she in- dependence herits from nature. The natural society of nations cannot of nations, subsist, unless the natural rights of each be duly respected. No nation is willing to renounce her liberty ; she will rather break off all commerce with those states that should attempt to infringe upon it. g 16. Effect As a consequence of that liberty and independence, it ex- of that liber- clusively belongs to each nation to form her own judgment of *y- what her conscience prescribes to her, of what she can or cannot do, of what it is proper or improper for her to do : and * Xenophon points out the true rea- n. (1), Ix. n. (5); Book ii. chap. ii. $ 21, son of this first of all duties, and esta- p. 144, post. C. Wishes its necessity, in the following (6) Puffendorf, b. iii. c. 3, 8. 6, p. 29, words: "If we see a man who is uni- writes clearly and decidedly on this formly eager to pursue his own pri- important subject; he observes "The vate advantage, without regard to the law of humanity does not seem to oblige rules of honour or the duties of friend- us to grant passage to any other ship, why should we in any emer- goods, except such as are absolutely gency think of sparing him?" Note necessary for the support of their edit. A. D. 1797. See modern author!- life to whom they are thus conveyed." ties in support of that position, ante, Iv. C. OF THE LAW OF NATIONS. Ixii of course it rests solely with her to examine and determine PK E "MI- whether she can perform any office for another nation without - neglecting the duty which she owes to herself. In all cases, therefore, in which a nation has the right of judging what her duty requires, no other nation can compel her to act in such or such particular manner : for any attempt at such compulsion would be an infringement on the liberty of nations. We have no right to use constraint against a free person, ex- cept in those cases where such person is bound to perform some particular thing for us, and for some particular reason which does not depend on his judgment, in those cases, in short, where we have a perfect right against him. In order perfectly to understand this, it is necessary to ob- 17- Dis- serve, that the obligation, and the right which corresponds tmctlo s be - to or is derived from it, are distinguished into external and nal and n e e x" internal. The obligation is internal, as it binds the con- temai, per- science, and is deduced from the rules of our duty : it is ex- feet and im- ternal, as it is considered relatively to other men, and pro- pei 3Ct obll ~ duces some right between them. The internal obligation is ^ghta S always the same in its nature, though it varies in degree ; but the external obligation is divided into perfect and imperfect; and the right that results from it is also perfect or imperfect. The perfect right is that Avhich is accompanied by the right of compelling those who refuse to fulfil the correspondent ob- ligation ; the imperfect right is unaccompanied by that right of compulsion. The perfect obligation is that which gives to [ Ixiii ] the opposite party the right of compulsion; the imperfect gives him only a right to ask. It is now easy to conceive why the right is always imper- fect, when the correspondent obligation depends on the judg- ment of the party in whose breast it exists ; for if, in such a case, we had a right to compel him, he would no longer enjoy the freedom of determination respecting the conduct he is to pursue in order to obey the dictates of his own conscience. Our obligation is always imperfect with respect to other people, while we possess the liberty of judging how we are to act : and we retain that liberty on all occasions where we ought to be free. Since men are naturally equal, and a perfect equality pre- is. Equal- vails in their rights and obligations, as equally proceeding ** y " f na " from nature Nations composed of men, and considered as tlons ' so many free persons living together in a state of nature, are naturally equal, and inherit from nature the same obligations and rights. Power or weakness does not in this respect pro- duce any difference. A dwarf is as much a man as a giant ; a small republic is no less a sovereign state than the most powerful kingdom. By a necessary consequence of that equality, whatever is M- lawful for one nation is equally lawful for any other ; and f ^ whatever is unjustifiable in the one is equally so in the other. eqi Ixlii IDEA AND GENERAL PRINCIPLES PRELIM!- A nation then is mistress of her own actions so long as yARIE8 -. they do not affect the proper and perfect rights of any other 2 20. Each na tion so long as she is only internally bound, and does not mistress 8 of ^ e un( ^ er anv external and perfect obligation. If she makes her own ac- an ill use f her liberty, she is guilty of a breach of duty ; tions when but other nations are bound to acquiesce in her conduct, they do not s i nce they have no right to dictate to her. ^rfect 116 Since nations- are free, independent, and equal and since rights of eacn possesses the right of judging, according to the dictates others. of her conscience, what conduct she is to pursue in order to fulfil her duties ; the effect of the whole is, to produce, at ~ least externally and in the eyes of mankind, a perfect - equality of rights between nations, in the administration of tary law of their affairs and the pursuit of their pretensions, without re- nations, gard to the intrinsic justice of their conduct, of which others have no right to form a definitive judgment ; so that what- ever may be done by any one nation may be done by any [ Ixiv ] other ; and they ought, in human society, to be considered as possessing equal rights. Each nation in fact maintains that she has justice on her side in every dispute that happens to arise ; and it does not belong to either of the parties interested, or to other nations, to pronounce a judgment on the contested question. The party who is in the wrong is guilty of a crime against her own conscience ; but as there exists a possibility that she may perhaps have justice on her side, we cannot accuse her of violating the laws of society. It is therefore necessary, on many occasions, that nations should suffer certain things to be done, though in their own nature unjust and condemnable ; because they cannot oppose them by open force, without violating the liberty of some particular state, and destroying the foundations of their natural society. And since they are bound to cultivate that society, it is of course presumed that all nations have con- sented to the principle we have just established. The rules that are deduced from it constitute what Monsieur Wolf calls "the voluntary law of nations;" and there is no reason why we should not use the same term, although we thought it necessary to deviate from that great man in our manner of establishing the foundation of that law. (7) (7) The natural primary or internal voluntary law, or those rules which are law of nations which is thus binding considered to have become law by the in conscience, and immutable, it must uniform practice of nations in general, be admitted, is mere theory, until it has and by the manifest utility of the rules been assented to by a state as binding themselves ; secondly, the customary on her : but besides that law of con- law, or that which, from motives of science, which, until so assented to, is convenience, has by tacit but implied imperfect, there is what is termed the agreement prevailed, not generally in- potitive or secondary law of nations, and deed among all nations, nor with BO which is threefold ; first, the universal paramount utility as to become a por- 60 OF THE LAW OF NATIONS. IxiV The laws of natural society are of such importance to the ""*i- safety of all states, that, if the custom once prevailed of NARIE8 - trampling them under foot, no nation could flatter herself ^ 22- Rl s nt with the hope of preserving her national existence, and en- ag^uSfe joying domestic tranquillity, however attentive to pursue infractors every measure dictated by the most consummate prudence, of the law justice, and moderation.* Now all men and all states have of nations - a perfect right to those things that are necessary for their preservation, since that right corresponds to an indispensa- Right of de- Die obligation. All nations have therefore a right to resort clarin s war - to forcible means for the purpose of repressing any one par- ticular nation who openly violates the laws of the society which Nature has established between them, or who directly attacks the welfare and safety of that society. But care must be taken not to extend that right to the \ 23. Mea- prejudice of the liberty of nations. They are all free and sure of that independent, but bound to observe the laws of that society nght ' which Nature has established between them ; and so far bound, that, when any of them violates those laws, the others have a right to repress her. The conduct of each nation, [ Ixv ] therefore, is no further subject to the control of the others, than as the interests of natural society are concerned. The general and common right of nations over the conduct of any sovereign state is only commensurate to the object of that society which exists between them. tion of universal voluntary law, but bear you out in a further progress ; enough to have acquired a prescriptive thus, for instance, on mere general obligation among certain states, so principles, it is lawful to destroy your situated as to be mutually benefited by enemy, and mere general principles it, as the customary law prevailing make no great difference as to the among different nations in the whale manner by which this is to be effected ; fishery, and illustrated by the decision but the conventional law of mankind, in Penning* v. Lord Grenville, 1 Taunt, which is evidenced in their practice, Rep. 241, 248, upon the division of the does make a distinction, and allows profits arising from a whale when killed some and prohibits other modes of de- by the crews of several boats ; and struction ; and a belligerent is bound thirdly, the conventional law, or that to confine himself to those modes which is agreed between particular states which the common practice of mankind by express treaties, a law binding only has employed, and to relinquish " those upon the parties among whom such which the same practice has not treaties are in force. See 1 Chitty's brought within the ordinary exercise Commercial Law, 28, 29, and see post, of war, however sanctioned by its prin- 2 27, p. 66. ciples and purposes :" so it has ever In the case of the ship, Flad Oyen, been the practice of nations to bring 1 Rob. Rep. 115, Sir William Scott ob- vessels captured by them into their own served, " A great part of the law of ports, and to condemn them as prize in nations stands on the usage and prac- their own Admiralty Courts ; and there- tice of nations, and on no other founda- fore a sentence of condemnation in the tion : it is introduced, indeed, by gene- neutral country would be illegal and ral principles, but it travels with those void. Ibid. C. general principles only to a certain ex- * Etenim si hsec pertubare omnia tent; and if it stops there, you are et permiscere volumus, totam vitam, not at liberty to go farther and to say, periculosam, insidiosam, infestamque that Here general speculations would reddeinus. Cicero in Verr. ii. 15. F 61 iXV IDEA AND GENERAL PRINCIPLES PBELIMI- The several engagements into which nations may enter IIES ' produce a new kind of law of nations, called Conventional, Con - or of Treaties. As it is evident that a treaty binds none kut the contracting parties, the conventional law of nations tions, or law is not a universal but a particular law. All that can be done of treaties, on this subject, in a treatise on the Law of Nations, is to lay down those general rules which nations are bound to observe with respect to their treaties. A minute detail of the various agreements made between particular nations, and of the rights and obligations thence resulting, is matter of fact, and belongs to the province of history. # 25. Cus- Certain maxims and customs, consecrated by long use, and tomary law observed by nations in their mutual intercourse with each other as a kind of law, form the Customary Law of Nations, or the Custom of Nations. (8) This law is founded on a tacit consent, or, if you please, on a tacit convention of the nations, that observe it towards each other. Whence it appears that it is not obligatory except on those nations who have adopted it, and that it is not universal, any more than the conven- tional law. The same remark, therefore, is equally applica- ble to this customary law, viz. that a minute detail of its par- ticulars does not belong to a systematic treatise on the law of nations, but that we must content ourselves with giving a general theory of it ; that is to say, the rules which are to be observed in it, as well with a view to its effects, as to its substance : and with respect to the latter, those rules will serve to distinguish lawful and innocent customs from those that are unjust and unlawful. I 26. Gene- When a custom or usage is generally established, either rai rule re- b e t we en all the civilized nations in the world, or only between that law. those of a certain continent, as of Europe, for example, or between those who have a more frequent intercoui'se with * for the object of the present work, it is sufficient to establish the general principles necessary for the decision of those dis- putes that may arise between nations. g 4. What Every nation that governs itself, under what form soever, are sove- without dependence on any foreign power, is a Sovereign reign states, fitafa. Its rights are naturally, the same as those of any other state. Such are the moral persons who live together in a natural society, subject to the law of nations. To give a na- tion a right to make an immediate figure in this grand society, it is sufficient that it be really sovereign and independent, that is, that it govern itself by its own authority and la\vs. g 5. Of We ought, therefore, to account as sovereign states those states bound which have united themselves to another more powerful, by by unequal an une q ua l alliance, in which, as Aristotle says, to the more alliance. powerful is given more honour, and to the weaker, more as- sistance. The conditions of those unequal alliances may be infinitely varied. But whatever they are, provided the inferior ally reserve to itself the sovereignty, or the right of governing its own body, it ought to be considered as an independent state, that keeps up an intercourse with others under the authority of the law of nations. 2 6. Or by Consequently a weak state, which, in order to provide for treaties of its safety, places itself under the protection of a more power- protection. f u i On6j an( j en g a ges, in return, to perform several offices 3 ] equivalent to that protection, without however divesting itself of the right of government and sovereignty, that state, I say, does not, on this account, cease to rank among the sove- reigns who acknowledge no other law than that of nations. (12) * Nor shall we examine which of minished through your fault." " True," those different kinds of government is replied the king : " I shall leave them the best. It will be sufficient to say a smaller portion of it; but it will in general, that the monarchical form rest upon a firmer basis." The Lace- appears preferable to every other, pro- daemonians, during a certain period, vided the power of the sovereign be had two chiefs to whom they very im- limited, and not absolute, qui [prin- properly gave the title of kings. They cipatus] turn demum regius est, si in- were magistrates, who possessed a very tra modestiae et mediocritatis fines so limited power, and whom it was not contineat, excessu potestatis, quam im- unusual to cite before the tribunal of prudentes in dies augere satagunt, justice, to arrest, to condemn to minuitur, penitusque corrunipitur, Nos death. Sweden acts with less impro- stulti, majoris, potentials specie decepti, priety in continuing to bestow on he* dilabimur in contrarium, non satis chief the title of king, although she hw considerantes earn demum tutam esso circumscribed his power within very potentiam quae viribus modum imponit. narrow bounds. IIo shares not hie The maxim has both truth and wisdom authority with a colleague, he is on its side. The author here quotes hereditary, and the state has, from the saying of Theopompus, king of time immemorial, borne the title of a Sparta, who, returning to his house kingdom. Edit. A. D. 1797. amidst the acclamations of the peo- (12) This and other rules respect- pie, after the establishment of the ing smaller states sometimes form the Ephori " You will leave to your chil- subject of consideration even in the dren (said his wife) an authority di- Municipal Courts. In case of a re- 66 SOVEREIGN STATES. There occurs no greater difficulty with respect to tributary BOOK i. states ; for though the payment of tribute to a foreign power CHAP- *' i 1 1- _ 1_ J.-L - J: : C j.1 _ I. does in some degree diminish the dignity of those states, from 2 5' C its being a confession of their weakness, yet it suffers their g^ t e S Ury sovereignty to subsist entire. The custom of paying tribute was formerly very common, the weaker by that means pur- chasing of their more powerful neighbour an exemption from oppression, or at that price securing his protection, without ceasing to be sovereigns. The Germanic nations introduced another custom that 8. Of of requiring homage from a state either vanquished, or too feudatory weak to make resistance. Sometimes even, a prince has states ' given sovereignties in fee, and sovereigns have voluntarily rendered themselves feudatories to others. \ \ When the homage leaves independency and sovereign au- thority in the administration of the state, and only means certain duties to the lord of the fee, or even a mere honorary . acknowledgment, it does not prevent the state or the feuda- J tory prince being strictly sovereign. The king of Naples pays homage for his kingdom to the pope, and is nevertheless V reckoned among the principal sovereigns of Europe. Two sovereign states may also be subject to the same 9. Of two prince, without any dependence on each other, and each may * totes sub - retain all its rights as a free and sovereign state. The king^J ^^ of Prussia is sovereign prince of Neufchatel in Switzerland, without that principality being in any manner united to his other dominions ; so that the people of Neufchatel, in virtue of their franchises, may serve a foreign power at war with the king of Prussia, provided that the war be not on account of that principality. Finally, several sovereign and independent states may 10. Of unite themselves together by a perpetual confederacy, with- f tates form - out ceasing to be, each individually, a perfect state. They inr will together constitute a federal republic: their joint de- liberations will not impair the sovereignty of each member, though they may, in certain respects, put some restraint on the exercise of it, in virtue of voluntary engagements. A per- son does not cease to be free and independent, when he is obliged to fulfil engagements which he has voluntarily contracted. Such were formerly the cities of Greece ; such are at present the Seven United Provinces of the Netherlands,(13) and such the members of the Helvetic body. volted colony, or part of a parent or Thompson v. Powles, 2 Sim. Rep. 202 ; principal state, no subject of another Yrisarri v. Clement, 2 Car. & P. 223; state can legally make a contract with 11 B. Moore, 308; 3 Bing. 432; and it or assist the same without leave of post. C. { The United States v. Palmer, his own government, before its sepa- 3 Wheat 610. See Cherriot v. Foussat, rate independence has been recog- 3 Binn. 252.} nised by his own government. Jones (13) Of course, the words " at pre- v. Garcia del Rio, 1 Turn. & Russ. 297 ; sent" refer only to the time when 67 3 GENERAL PRINCIPLES OP BOOK i. But a people that has passed under the dominion of an- . CHAP ' * other is no longer a state, and can no longer avail itself directly g 11. Of a O f the law of nations. Such were the nations and kingdoms state that ^^ the Romans rendered subject to their empire ; the has passed ,. i i 11 > t i under the generality even of those whom they honoured with the name dominion of of friends and allies no longer formed real states. Within another. themselves they were governed by their own laws and magis- [ 4 ] trates ; but without, they were in every thing obliged to follow the orders of Rome ; they dared not of themselves either to make war or contract alliances ; and could not treat with nations. \ 12. The The law of nations is the law of sovereigns ; free and inde- objects of pendent states are moral persons, whose rights and obligations this treatise. ^ Q are ^ Q es t a kii sn j, n this treatise. CHAP. II. CHAP, n. GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF THE DUTIES OF A NATION TOWARDS ITSELF. 13. A na- IF the rights of a nation spring from its obligations, it is toact U a Sbt P rinci P all y from those tb - at relate to itself - Jt wil1 further gre'eabiy to appear, that its duties towards others depend very much on its nature, its duties towards itself, as the former are to be regulated ( 14 ) and measured by the latter. As we are then to treat of the obligations and rights of nations, an attention to order re- quires that we should begin by establishing what each nation owes to itself. The general and fundamental rule of our duties towards ourselves is, that every moral being ought to live in a manner conformable to his nature, natures convenienter vivere.(14) A nation is a being determined by its essential attributes, that has its own nature, and can act in conformity to it. There are then actions of a nation as such, wherein it is con- cerned in its national character, and which are either suitable Vattel wrote, and it is unnecessary to has acquired powers far beyond its mention otherwise than thus cursorily diminutive extent. These being esta- the notorious recent changes. C. blished, it becomes the duty of such (14) If to particularize may be a state, and of those exercising the allowed, we may instance Great Bri- powers of government, to cultivate and tain. Comparatively, with regard to improve these natural advantages ; and dimensions, it would be but an insig- in that view the ancient exclusive nificant state ; but with regard to its navigation system, constituting Eng- insular situation and excellent ports, land the carrier of Europe and the and its proximity to Europe, and above world, were highly laudable ; and it is all the singularly manly, brave, and to be hoped that a return of the system, adventurous character of its natives, injudiciously abandoned, mil ere long it has been capable of acquiring and take place. C. 68 CHAP. THE DUTIES OF A NATION, ETC. or opposite to what constitutes it a nation ; so that it is not BOOK i. a matter of indifference whether it performs some of those . actions, and omits others. In this respect, the Law of Nature prescribes it certain duties. We shall see, in this first hook, what conduct a nation ought to observe, in order that it may not be wanting to itself. But we shall first sketch out a general idea of this subject. He who no longer exists can have no duties to perform : and ? u. of a moral being is charged with obligations to himself, only with the preser- a view to his perfection and happiness : for to preserve and to perfection* perfect his own nature, is the sum of all his duties to himself. O f a na tion. The preservation of a nation consists in the duration of the political association by which it is formed. If a period is put to this association, the nation or state no longer subsists, though the individuals that composed it still exist. The perfection of a nation is found in what renders it capable of obtaining the end of civil society ; and a nation is in a perfect state, when nothing necessary is wanting to arrive at that end. We know that the perfection of a thing con- sists, generally, in the perfect agreement of all its constituent parts to tend to the same end. A nation being a multitude of men united together in civil society if in that multitude all conspire to attain the end proposed in forming a civil society, the nation is perfect ; and it is more or less so, according as it approaches more or less to that perfect agree- [ 5 ] ment. In the same manner its external state will be more or less perfect, according as it concurs with the interior per- fection of the nation. The end or object of civil society is to procure for the 15 - What citizens whatever they stand in need of for the necessities, j^!j e en . d of the conveniences, the accommodation of life, and, in general, c " whatever constitutes happiness, with the peaceful possession of property, a method of obtaining justice with security, and, finally, a mutual defence against all external violence. It is now easy to form a just idea of the perfection of a state or nation : every thing in it must conspire to promote the ends we have pointed out. In the act of association, by virtue of which a multitude 16. A na- of men form together a state or nation, each individual has tion is under entered into engagements with all, to promote the general J ." n ^ ig *' welfare ; and all have entered into engagements with each S e velteeH. individual, to facilitate for him the means of supplying his necessities, and to protect and defend him. It is manifest that these reciprocal engagements can no otherwise be fulfilled than by maintaining the political association. The entire nation is then obliged to maintain that association ; and as their preservation depends on its continuance, it thence follows that every nation is obliged to perform the duty of self-preservation. This obligation, so natural to each individual of God's 5 GENERAL PRINCIPLES OP BOOK i. creation, is not derived to nations immediately from nature, CHAP> "' but from the agreement by which civil society is formed : it is therefore not absolute, but conditional, that is to say, it supposes a human act, to wit, the social compact. And as compacts may be dissolved by common consent of the parties if the individuals that compose a nation should unanimously agree to break the link that binds them, it would be lawful for them to do so, and thus to destroy the state or nation ; but they would doubtless incur a degree of guilt, if they took this step without just and weighty reasons ; for civil societies are approved by the Law of Nature, which recommends them to mankind, as the true means of supplying all their wants, and of effectually advancing towards their own perfection. Moreover, civil society is so useful, nay so necessary to all citizens, that it may well be considered as morally impossible for them to consent unanimously to break it without necessity. But what citizens may or ought to do what the majority of them may resolve in certain cases of necessity or of pressing exigency are questions that will be treated of elsewhere : they cannot be solidly determined without some principles which we have not yet established. For the present, it is sufficient to have proved, that, in general, as long as the poli- tical society subsists, the whole nation is obliged to endeavour to maintain it. 17. And If a nation is obliged to preserve itself, it is no less obliged to preserve care f u ijy to preserve all its members. The nation owes this !rs ' to itself, since the loss even of one of its members weakens it, and is injurious to its preservation. It owes this also to the members in particular, in consequence of the very act of asso- ciation ; for those who compose a nation are united for their j] 6 ] defence and common advantage ; and none can justly be de- prived of this union, and of the advantages he expects to de- rive from it, while he on his side fulfils the conditions.(15) The body of a nation cannot then abandon a province, a town, or even a single individual who is a part of it, unless compelled to it by necessity, or indispensably obliged to it by the strongest reasons founded on the public safety.(16) 1 18. A na- Since then a nation is obliged to preserve itself, it has a tion has a right to every tiling necessary for its preservation. For the ever* Thin ^ aw ^ ^ ature gi yes us a right to every thing without which necessary^ we cannot fulfil our obligation ; otherwise it would oblige us (15) This principle is in every re- self. This is the principle upon which spect recognised and acted upon by is founded the rule " Nemo potent cxuerc our municipal law. It is in respect of, patriam," Calvin's case, 7 Coke, 25 , and as a due return for, the protection Co. Lit 129, a; and see an interest- every natural born subject is entitled ing application of that rule in Mac- to, and actually does, by law, receive donald's case, Forster's Crown Law. from the instant of his birth, that all 59. C. the obligations of allegiance attach (16) In tracing the consequences of upon him, and from which he cannot this rule, we shall hereafter perceive how by any act of his own emancipate him- important is the rule itself. C. 70 THE DUTIES OF A NATION, ETC. O to do impossibilities, or rather would contradict itself in pre- BOOK i. scribing us a duty, and at the same time debarring us of the CHAf ' "' only means of fulfilling it. It will doubtless be here under- stood, that those means ought not to be unjust in themselves, or such as are absolutely forbidden by the Law of Nature. As it is impossible that it should ever permit the use of such means, if on a particular occasion no other present them- selves for fulfilling a general obligation, the obligation must, in that particular instance, be looked on as impossible, and consequently void. By an evident consequence from what has been said, a na- g 19. it tion ought carefully to avoid, as much as possible, whatever ought to might cause its destruction, or that of the state, which is the t a id *^ same thing. might oec* A nation or state has a right to every thing that can help s i on its de- to ward off imminent danger, and keep at a distance whatever struction. is capable of causing its ruin ; and that from the very same ? 20 : Of reasons that establish its right to the things necessary to its everything preservation. (17) that may The second general duty of a nation towards itself is to promote labour at its own perfection and that of its state. It is this * h " end - double perfection that renders a nation capable of attaining | on ' ough a ~. the end of civil society : it would be absurd to unite in to perfect society, and yet not endeavour to promote the end of that itself and union *** Here the entire body of a nation, and each individual citi- zen, are bound by a double obligation, the one immediately proceeding from nature, and the other resulting from their reciprocal engagements. Nature lays an obligation upon each man to labour after his own perfection ; and in so doing, he labours after that of civil society, which could not fail to be very flourishing, were it composed of none but good citizens. But the individual finding in a well-regulated society the most powerful succours to enable him to fulfil the task which Na- ture imposes upon him in relation to himself, for becoming better, and consequently more happy he is doubtless obliged to contribute all in his power to render that society more perfect. All the citizens who form a political society reciprocally engage to advance the common welfare, and as far as possi- [ 7 ] ble to promote the advantage of each member. Since then the perfection of the society is what enables it to secure equally the happiness of the body and that of the members, the grand object of the engagements and duties of a citizen is to aim at this perfection. This is more particularly the (17) Salus popnli suprema eat lex. the property of any private individual. Upon this principle it has been esta- See Governors, IV- not say, with some writers, that private virtues are not the virtues of kings a maxim of superficial politicians, or of [ 14 ] those who are very inaccurate in their expressions. Good- ness, friendship, gratitude, are still virtues on the throne ; and would to God they were always to be found there ! But a wise king does not yield an undiscerning obedience to their impulse. He cherishes them, ke cultivates them in his private life ; but in state affairs he listens only to justice and sound policy. And why? because he knows that the government was intrusted to him only for the happiness of society, and that, therefore, he ought not to consult his own pleasure in the use he makes of his power. He tempers his goodness with wisdom; he gives to friendship his domestic and private favours ; he distributes posts and employments according to merit ; public rewards to services done to the state. In a word, he uses the public power only with a view to the public welfare. All this is comprehended in that fine saying of Lewis XII. : " A king of France does not revenge the in- juries of a duke of Orleans." g 40. Of his A political society is a moral person (Prelim. 2) inasmuch representa- ag it has an understanding and a will, of which it makes use tive charac- f or ^ con( j uc t; O f fa affairs, and is capable of obligations and rights. When, therefore, a people confer the sovereignty on any one person, they invest him with their understanding and will, and make over to him their obligations and rights, so far as relates to the administration of the state, and to the exercise of the public authority. The sovereign, or conductor of the state, thus becoming the depositary of the obligations and rights relative to government, in him is found the moral person, who, without absolutely ceasing to exist in the nation, acts thenceforwards only in him and by him. Such is the origin of the representative character attributed to the sove- reign. He represents the nation in all the affairs in which he may happen to be engaged as a sovereign. It does not debase the dignity of the greatest monarch to attribute to him this representative character ; on the contrary, nothing sheds a greater lustre on it, since the monarch thus unites in ntmste? '* *" s own P erson a ^ tne ma jesty that belongs to the entire body witiTthe ob- of the nation. ligations of The sovereign, thus clothed with the public authority, with the nation, every thing that constitutes the moral personality of the ^ t d h i ^ ested nation, of course becomes bound by the obligations of that rights nation, and invested with its rights. | 42. His All that has been said in Chap. II. of the general duties duty with of a nation towards itself particularly regards the sovereign, respect jj e j s ^he depositary of the empire, and of the power of com- vatioTami manding whatever conduces .to the public welfare; he ought, perfection of therefore, as a tender and wise father, and as a faithful ad- the nation, ministrator, to watch for the nation, and take care to preserve 80 OF THE SOVEREIGN. 14 it, and render it more perfect ; to better its state, and to BOOK i. secure it, as far as possible, against every thing that threatens CHAP - IY - . its safety or its happiness. Hence all the rights which a nation derives from its obli- g 43. His gation to preserve and perfect itself, and to improve its state, rights in this (see 18, 20, and 23, of this book) ; all these rights, I say, res P ect - reside in the sovereign, who is therefore indifferently called [ 15 ] the conductor of the society, superior, prince, &c. We have observed above, that every nation ought to know $ 44. He itself. This obligation devolves on the sovereign, since it is ought to he who is to watch over the preservation and perfection of kD w the the nation. The duty which the law of nature here imposes on the conductors of nations is of extreme importance, and of considerable extent. They ought exactly to know the whole country subject to their authority; its qualities, de- fects, advantages, and situation with regard to the neigh- bouring states ; and they ought to acquire a perfect know- ledge of the manners and general inclinations of their people, their virtues, vices, talents, &c. All these branches of know- ledge are necessary to enable them to govern properly. The prince derives his authority from the nation ; he pos- g 45. The sesses just so much of it as they have thought proper to intrust extent of his him with.* If the nation has plainly and simply invested powen him with the sovereignty, without limitation or division, he is supposed to be invested with all the prerogatives, without Preroga- which the sovereign command or authority could not be ex- tives of ma - erted in the manner most conducive to the public welfare. Jesty< These are called regal prerogatives, or the prerogatives of But when the sovereign power is limited and regulated by g 45. The the fundamental laws of the state, those laws show the prince prince the extent and bounds of his power, and the manner in which ou s ht to he is to exert it. The prince is therefore strictly obliged not only to respect, but also to support them. The constitution f un da- and the fundamental laws -are the plan on which the nation mental has resolved to labour for the attainment of happiness ; the laws< execution is intrusted to the prince. Let him religiously follow this plan ; let him consider the fundamental laws as inviolable and sacred rules ; and remember that the moment he deviates from them, his commands become unjust, and are but a criminal abuse of the power with which he is intrusted. He is, by virtue of that power, the guardian and defender of ' * Neque enim se princeps reipublicaa the sovereign. Quod caput est, sit et singulorum dominum arbitrabitur, principi persuasum, totius reipublicae quamvis assentatoribus id in aurem majorem quam ipsius unius auctorita- insusurrantibus, sed rectorem mercede tern esse : neque pessimis hominibus a civibus designata, quam augere, nisi credat diversum affirmantibus gratifi- ipsis volentibus, nefas existimabit. candi studio ; quce magna pernicies est Ibid. c. v. From this principle it fol- Ibid, lows that the nation is superior to 11 81 15 OP THE SOVEREIGN. BOOK T. the laws : and while it is his duty to restrain each daring CHAP, iv. Y j i ator O f them, ought he himself to trample them under foot?* 1 47. He If the prince be invested with the legislative power, he may, may change accor( Ji n g to his wisdom, and when the public advantage re- fnndamen- quires it, abolish those laws that are not fundamental, and taL make new ones. (See what we have said on this subject, in the preceding chapter, 34.) 48. He But while these laws exist, the sovereign ought religiously ought to to maintain and observe them. They are the foundation of wTd'observe ^ e public tranquillity, and the firmest support of the sove- the existing reign authority. Every thing is uncertain, violent, and subject laws. to revolutions, in those unhappy states where arbitrary power has placed her throne. It is therefore the true interest of the prince, as well as his duty, to maintain and respect the laws ; he ought to submit to them himself. We find this truth esta- blished in a piece published by order of Lewis XIV., one of the most absolute princes that ever reigned in Europe. "Let it not be said that the sovereign is not subject to the laws of his state, since the contrary proposition is one of the truths of the law of nations, which flattery has sometimes attacked, and which good princes have always defended, as a tutelar divinity of their states, "f g 49. in But it is necessary to explain this submission of the prince he^ubit to the laWS * First ' he ou g ht ' as we nave J ust seen > to follow to the 8 laws' their regulations in all the acts of his administration. In the second place, he is himself subject, in his private affairs, to all the laws that relate to property. I say, "in his private affairs;" for when he acts as a sovereign prince, and in the name of the state, he is subject only to the fundamental laws, and the law of nations. In the third place, the prince is sub- ject to certain regulations of general polity, considered by the state as inviolable, unless he be excepted in express terms by the law, or tacitly by a necessary consequence of his dignity. * In some countries, formal pre- past generations, who formerly made cautions are taken against the abuse effectual use of arms and decrees to of power. "Reflecting among other reduce within proper bounds such of things (says Grotius), that princes are their sovereigns as had transgressed often found to make no scruple of vio- the line of duty, whether through their lating their promises under the stale own licentiousness or the artifices of pretext of the public good, the people their flatterers. Thus it happened to of Brabant, in order to obviate that John the Second ; nor would they con- inconvenience, established the custom sent to make peace with him or his of never admitting their prince to the successors, until those princes had en- possession of the government without tered into a solemn engagement to having previously made with him a secure the citizens in the enjoyment covenant, that, whenever ho may hap- of their privileges." Annals of the pen to violate the laws of the country, Netherlands, Book II. note, edit. A. D. they shall be absolved from the oath 1797. of obedience they had sworn to him, f A treatise on the right of the queen until ample reparation be made for to several states of the Spanish mon- the outrages committed. The truth archy, 1667, in 12mo, Part II. p. 191. of this is confirmed by the example of OF THE SOVEREIGN. 16 I here speak of the laws that relate to the situation of indi- BOOK i. viduals, and particularly of those that regulate the validity CHAP ' **' of marriages. These laws are established to ascertain the state of families : now the royal family is that of all others the most important to be certainly known. But, fourthly, we shall observe in general, with respect to this question, that, if the prince is invested with a, full, absolute, and unlimited sovereignty, he is above the laws, which derive from him all their force ; and he may dispense with his own observance of [ 17 ] them, whenever natural justice and equity will permit him. Fifthly, as to the laws relative to morals and good order, the prince ought doubtless to respect them, and to support them by his example. But, sixthly, he is certainly above all civil penal laws. The majesty of a sovereign will not admit of his being punished like a private person ; and his functions are too exalted to allow of his being molested under pretence of a fault that does not directly concern the government of the, state. It is not sufficient that the prince be above the penal laws : ? 50. His even the interest of nations requires that we should go some- P er ^ on " f a - thing farther. The sovereign is the soul of the society ; if T i he be not held in veneration by the people, and in perfect security, the public peace, and the happiness and safety of the state, are in continual danger. The safety of the nation then necessarily requires that the person of the prince be sacred and inviolable. The Roman people bestowed this privilege on their tribunes, in order that they might meet with no ob- struction in defending them, and that no apprehension might disturb them in the discharge of their office. The cares, the employments of a sovereign, are of much greater importance than those of the tribunes were, and not less dangerous, if he be not provided with a powerful defence. It is impossible even for the most just and wise monarch not to make mal- contents ; and ought the state to continue exposed to the dan- ger of losing so valuable a prince by the hand of an assassin ? The monstrous and absurd doctrine, that a private person is permitted to kill a bad prince, deprived the French, in the beginning of the last century, of a hero who was truly the father of his people.* Whatever a prince may be, it is an enormous crime against a nation to deprive them of a sove- reign whom they think proper to obey.f * Since the above was written, France made by Damien to assassinate Louis has witnessed a renewal of those hor- J5TF.] Note, edit. A.D. 1797. rors. She sighs at the idea of having f In Mariana's work, above quoted, given birth to a monster capable of I find (chap. vii. towards the end) a violating the majesty of kings in the remarkable instance of the errors into person of a prince, whom the qualities which we are apt to be led by a subtle of his heart entitle to the love of his sophistry destitute of sound principles, subjects and the veneration of foreign- That author allows us to poison a ers. [The author alludes to the attempt tyrant, and even a public enemy, pro- 83 17 OF THE SOVEREIGN. BOOK i. But this high attribute of sovereignty is no reason why the CHAP, iv. na tjp n should not curb an insupportable tyrant, pronounce 51. But sentence on him (still respecting in his person the majesty of ma "curT ^ s ran ^) an< ^ withdraw itself from his obedience. To this a tyrant, indisputable right a powerful republic owes its birth. The and with- tyranny exercised by Philip II. in the Netherlands excited draw itself those provinces to rise : seven of them, closely confederated, obedience bravely maintained their liberties, under the conduct of the heroes of the House of Orange ; and Spain, after several vain [ 18 ] and ruinous efforts, acknowledged them sovereign and inde- pendent states. If the authority of the prince is limited and regulated by the fundamental laws, the prince, on exceeding the bounds prescribed him, commands without any right and even without a just title : the nation is not obliged to obey him, but may resist his unjust attempts. As soon as a prince attacks the constitution of the state, he breaks the contract which bound the people to him ; the people become free by the act of the sovereign, and can no longer view him but as a usurper who would load them with oppression. This truth is acknowledged by every sensible writer, whose pen is not enslaved by fear, or sold for hire. But some celebrated authors maintain, that if the prince is invested with the supreme command in a full and absolute manner, nobody has a right to resist him, much less to curb him, and that naught remains for the nation but to suffer and obey with patience. This is founded upon the supposition that such a sovereign is not accountable to any person for the manner in which he governs, and that if the nation might control his actions and resist him where it thinks them unjust, his authority would no longer be absolute ; which would be contrary to this hypothesis. They say that an absolute sovereign completely possesses all the political authority of the society, which no- body can oppose ; that, if he abuses it, he does ill indeed, and wounds his conscience ; but that his commands are not the less obligatory, as being founded on a lawful right to com- mand ; that the nation, by giving him absoulte authority, has reserved no share of it to itself, and has submitted to his discretion, &c. We might be content with answering, that vided it bo done without obliging him, person who administered the poison. either by force or through mistake or Ne cogatur tantum sciens aut impru- ignorance, to concur in the act that dens sibi conscire mortem; quod esse causes his own death, which would be nefas judicamus, veneno in potu aut the case, for instance, in presenting him cibo, quod hauriat qui perimendus ost, a poisoned draught. For (says he), in aut simili alia retemperato. A fine thus leading him to an act of suicide, reason, truly ! Was Mariana disposed although committed through ignorance, to insult the understandings of his read- we make him violate the natural law ers, or only desirous of throwing a which forbids each individual to take slight varnish over the detestable doc- away his own life ; and the crime of trine contained in that chapter ? Note, him who thus unknowingly poisons him- edit. A. D. 1797. self redounds on the real author, the 84 OF THE SOVEREIGN. 18 in this light there is not any sovereign who is completely and BOOK i. fully absolute. But in order to remove all these vain subtle- CHAF ' "* ties, let us remember the essential end of civil society. Is it not to labour in concert for the common happiness of all ? Was it not with this view that every citizen divested himself of his rights, and resigned his liberty ? Could the society make such use of its authority as irrevocably to surrender itself and all its members to the discretion of a cruel tyrant ? No, certainly, since it would no longer possess any right itself, if it were disposed to oppress a part of the citizens. When, therefore, it confers the supreme and absolute govern- ment, without an express reserve, it is necessarily with the tacit reserve that the sovereign shall use it for the safety of the people, and not for their ruin. If he becomes the scourge of the state, he degrades himself; he is no better than a public enemy, against whom the nation may and ought to defend itself ; and if he has carried his tyranny to the utmost height, why should even the life of so cruel and perfidious an enemy be spared ? Who shall presume to blame the conduct of the Roman senate, that declared Nero an enemy to his country ? But it is of the utmost importance to observe, that this [ 19 ] judgment can only be passed by the nation, or by a body which represents it, and that the nation itself cannot make any attempt on the person of the sovereign, except in cases of extreme necessity, and when the prince, by violating the laws, and threatening the safety of his people, puts himself in a state of war against them. It is the person of the sove- reign, not that of an unnatural tyrant and a public enemy, that the interest of the nation declares sacred and inviolable. We seldom see such monsters as Nero. In the more common cases, when a prince violates the fundamental laws ; when he attacks the liberties and privileges of his subjects ; or (if he be absolute) when his government, without being carried to extreme violence, manifestly tends to the ruin of the nation ; it may resist him, pass sentence on him, and withdraw from his obedience ; but though this may be done, still his person should be spared, and that for the welfare of the state.* It * Dissimulandum censeo quatenus Henrico hujus abnepote ob ignaviam salus publica patiatur, privatimque pravosque mores abdicate procerum corruptis moribus princeps contingat; suffrages, primum Alfonsus ejus frater, alioquin si rempublicam in periculum recte an secus non dispute, sed tamen ' vocat, si patrise religionis contemptor in tenera setate rex est proclamatus : existit, neque medicinam ullam re- deinde defuncto Alfonso, Elisabeths cipit, abdicandum judico, alium sub- ejus soror, Henrico invito, renim sum- stituendum ; quod in Hispania non mam ad se traxit, regio tantum nomine semel fuisse factum scimus : quasi fera abstinens dum ille vixit. Mariana, de irritata, omnium telis peti debet, cum, Rege et Regis Institut. Lib. I. c. iii. humanitate abdicata, tyrannum induit. To this authority, furnished by Spain, Sic Petro rege ob immanitatem dejecto join that of Scotland, proved by- the publice, Henrieus ejus frater, quamvis letter of the barons to the pope, dated ex impari matxe, regnum obtinuit Sic April 6, 1320, requesting him to pre- H 85 20 OF THE SOVEREIGN. BOOK i. is above a century since the English took up arms against CHAP. IY. their king, and obliged him to descend from the thr ne. A set of able, enterprising men, spurred on by ambition, took advantage of the terrible ferment caused by fanaticism and party spirit ; and Great Britain suffered her sovereign to die unworthily on a scaffold. The nation coming to itself dis- covered its former blindness. If, to this day, it still annually makes a solemn atonement, it is not only, from the opinion that the unfortunate Charles I. did not deserve so cruel a fate, but, doubtless, from a conviction that the very safety of the state requires the person of the sovereign to be held sacred and inviolable, and that the whole nation ought to render this maxim venerable, by paying respect to it when the care of its own preservation will permit. One word more on the distinction that is endeavoured to be made here in favour of an absolute sovereign. Whoever has well weighed the force of the indisputable principles we have established, will be convinced, that when it is necessary to resist a prince who has become a tyrant, the right of the people is still the same, whether that prince was made abso- lute by the laws, or was not ; because that right is derived Tail on the king of England to desist from his enterprises against Scotland. After having spoken of the evils they had suffered from him, they add A quibus malis innumeris, ipso juvante qui post vulnera medetur et sanat, liberati sumus per serenissimum prin- cipem regem et dominum nostrum, dominum Robertum, qui pro populo et hasreditate suis do manibus inimicorum liberandis, quasi alter Maccabaeus aut Josue, labores et taedia, inedias et pe- ricula, laeto sustinuit animo. Quern etiam divina dispositio, et ( juxta leges et consuetudines nostras, quas usque ad mortem sustinere volumus) juris successio, et debitus nostrorum con- sensus et assensus nostrum fecerunt principem atque regem: cui, tanquam illi per quern sains in populo facta est, pro nostra libertate tuenda, tarn jure qnam meritis tenemur, et volumus in omnibus adhaerere. Quern, si ab in- ceptis desistet, regi Anglorum aut Anglis nos aut regnum nostrum volons subjicere, tanquam inimicum nostrum et sui nostrique juris subversorem, statim espellere nitemur, et alium regem nostrum, qui ad defensionem nostram sufficiet, faciemus: quia, quamdiu centum viri remanserint, nun- quam Anglorum dominio aliquatenus volumus subjugari. Non enim propter gloriam, divitias, ant honores pugna- mus, sed propter libertateni solummodo, 86 quam nemo, bonus nisi simul cum vita amittit. "In the year 1581" (says Grotius, Ann. Book III.) "the confederated provinces of the Netherlands after having for nine years continued to wage war against Philip the Second, without ceasing to acknowledge him as their sovereign at length solemnly deprived him of the authority he had possessed over their country, because he bad violated their laws and privi- leges." The author afterwards ob- serves, that " France, Spain herself, England, Sweden, Denmark, furnish instances of kings deposed by their people; so that there are at present few sovereigns in Europe whose right to the crown rests on any other founda- tion than the right which the people possess of divesting their sovereign of his power when he makes an ill use of it." Pursuant to this idea, the United Provinces, in their justificatory letters on that subject, addressed to the princes of the empire and the king of Denmark after having enumerated the oppressive acts of the king of Spain, added "Then, by a mode which has been often enough adopted even by those nations that now live under kingly government, we wrested the sovereignty from him whose actions were all contrary to the duty of a prince." Ibid. Note, edit A. D. 1797. OF THE SOVEREIGN. 20 from what is the object of all political society the safety of BOOK i. the nation, which is the supreme laAV.* But, if the distinc- " AP ' IY '. tion of which we are treating is of no moment with respect to the right, it can he of none in practice, with respect to expe- diency. As it is very difficult to oppose an absolute prince, and it cannot be done without raising great disturbances in the state, and the most violent and dangerous commotions, it ought to be attempted only in cases of extremity, when the public miseries are raised to such a height that the people may say with Tacitus, miseram pacem vel bello bene mutari, that it is better to expose themselves to a civil war than to endure them. But if the prince's authority is limited, if it in some respects depends on a senate, or a parliament that represents the nation, there are means of resisting and curbing him, without exposing the state to violent shocks. When mild and innocent remedies can be applied to the evil, there can be no reason for Avaiting until it becomes extreme. But however limited a prince's authority may be, he is 52. Arbu conimonly very jealous of it; it seldom happens that he pa- tration be- tiently suffers resistance, and peaceably submits to the judg- t T een the ment of his people. Can he want support, while he is the ^^,,,.,8. distributor of favours ? We see too many base and ambitious [ 2l ] souls, for whom the state of a rich and decorated slave has more charms than that of a modest and virtuous citizen. It is therefore always difficult for a nation to resist a prince and pronounce sentence on his conduct, without exposing the state to dangerous troubles, and to shocks capable of overturning it. This has sometimes occasioned a compromise between the prince and the subjects, to submit to the decision of a friendly power all the disputes that might arise between them. Thus the kings of Denmark, by solemn treaties, formerly referred to those of Sweden the differences that might arise between them and their senate ; and this the kings of Sweden have also done with regard to those of Denmark. The princes and states of West Friesland, and the burgesses of Embden, have in the same manner constituted the republic of the United Provinces the judge of their differences. The princes and the city of Neufchatel established, in 1406, the canton of Berne perpetual judge and arbitrator of their disputes. Thus also, according to the spirit of the Helvetic confederacy, the entire body takes cognisance of the disturbances that arise in any * Populi patroni non pauciora neque Est tamen salutaris cogitatio, nt sit minora praesidia habent. Certe a repub- principibus persuasum, si rempublicam lica, unde ortum habct regia pofcestas, oppresserint, si vitiis et foeditate intole- rebus exigentibus, regens in jus vocari randi erunt, ea se conditione vivere, ut potest, et, si sanitatem respuat, princi- non jure tantum, sed cum laude et patu spoliari j neque ita in principem gloria, perimi possint Ibid. Note, edit, jura potestatis transtulit, ut non sibi A. D. 1797. majorem reservarit potestatem. Ibid, cap. vi. 87 21 OP THE SOVEREIGN. BOOK i. of the confederated states, though each of them is truly sove- CHAP. iv. re jg n an( j independent. g 53. The As soon as a nation acknowledges a prince for its lawful obedience sovereign, all the citizens owe him a faithful ohedience. He which sub- neither govern the state, nor perform what the nation ex- jects owe to i /> i HI -i n i a sovereign, pects from him, if he be not punctually obeyed, {subjects then have no right, in doubtful cases, to examine the wisdom or justice of their sovereign's ^commands ; this examination belongs to the prince : his subjects ought to suppose (if there be a possibility of supposing it) that all his orders are just and salutary : he alone is accountable for the evil that may result from them. I 54. In Nevertheless this ought not to be entirely a blind obedi- what cases ence. No engagement can oblige, or even authorize, a man tbC ^tT y * v il a * e * ne l aw f na ture. All authors who have any re- gard to conscience or decency agree that no one ought to obey such commands as are evidently contrary to that sacred law. Those governors of places who bravely refused to exe- cute the barbarous orders of Charles IX. on the memorable day of St. Bartholomew, have been universally praised ; and the court did not dare to punish them, at least openly. "Sire," said the brave Orte, governor of Bayonne, in his letter, "I have communicated your majesty's command to your faithful inhabitants and warriors in the garrison ; and I have found there only good citizens and brave soldiers, but not a single executioner : wherefore both they and I most humbly entreat your majesty to be pleased to employ our hands and our lives in things that are possible, however hazardous they may be ; and we will exert ourselves to the last drop of our blood in the execution of them."* The Count [ 22 ] de Tende, Charny, and others, replied to those who brought them the orders of the court, " that they had too great a re- spect for the king, to believe that such barbarous orders came from him." It is more difficult to determine in what cases a subject may not only refuse to obey, but even resist a sovereign, and op- pose his violence by force. When a sovereign does injury to any one, he acts without any real authority ; but we ought not thence to conclude hastily that the subject may resist him. The nature of sovereignty, and the welfare of the state, will not permit citizens to oppose a prince whenever his com- mands appear to them unjust or prejudicial. This would be falling back into the state of nature, and rendering govern- ment impossible. A subject ought patiently to suffer from the prince doubtful wrongs, and wrongs that are supportable ; the former, because whoever has submitted to the decision of a judge, is no longer capable of deciding his own pretensions ; and as to those that are supportable, they ought to be sacri- * Mezeray's History of France, vol. ii. p. 1107. OF THE SOVEREIGN. 22 ficed to the peace and safety of the state, on account of the BOOK * great advantages obtained by living in society. It is pre- CHAF ' IV '- sumed, as matter of course, that every citizen has tacitly en- gaged to observe this moderation ; because, without it, society could not exist. But when the injuries are manifest and atrocious, when a prince, without any apparent reason, attempts to deprive us of life, or of those things the loss of which would render life irksome, who can dispute our right to resist him ? Self-preservation is not only a natural right, but an obligation imposed by nature, and no man can entirely and absolutely renounce it. And though he might give it up, can he be considered as having done it by his political en- gagements, since he entered into society only to establish his own safety upon a more solid basis ? The welfare of society does not require such a sacrifice ; and, as Barbeyrac well observes in his notes on Grotius, "If the public interest re- quires that those who obey should suffer some inconvenience, it is no less for the public interest that those who command should be afraid of driving their patience to the utmost ex- tremity."* The prince who violates all laws, who no longer observes any measures, and who would in his transports of fury take away the life of an innocent person, divests himself of his character, and is no longer to be considered in any other light than that of an unjust and outrageous enemy, against whom his people are allowed to defend themselves. The person of the sovereign is sacred and inviolable : but he who, after having lost all the sentiments of a sovereign, divests himself even of the appearances and exterior conduct of a monarch, degrades himself: he no longer retains the sacred character of a sovereign, and cannot retain the prerogatives attached to that exalted rank. However, if this prince is not a monster, if he is furious only against us in particular, and [ 23 ] from the effects of a sudden transport or a violent passion, and is supportable to the rest of the nation, the respect we ought to pay to the tranquillity of the state is such, and the respect due to sovereign majesty so powerful, that we are strictly obliged to seek every other means of preservation, rather than to put his person in danger. Every one knows the example set by David : he fled, he kept himself con- cealed, to secure himself from Saul's fury, and more than once spared the life of his persecutor. When the reason of ,. Charles VI. of France was suddenly disordered by a fatal accident, he in his fury killed several of those who surrounded him : none of them thought of securing his own life at the ex- pense of that of the king ; they only endeavoured to disarm and secure him. They did their duty like men of honour and faithful subjects, in exposing their lives to save that of this unfortunate monarch : such a sacrifice is due to the state and * De Jure Belli & Pacis, lib. i. cap. iv. Z 11. n. 2. 12 H 2 89 23 OF STATES ELECTIVE, BOOS CHAP, g 55. Of ministers. K * to sovereign majesty : furious from the derangement of his faculties, Charles was not guilty : he might recover his health, and again become a good king. What has been said is sufficient for the intention of this work : the reader may see these questions treated more at large in many books that are well known. We shall conclude this subject with an important observation. A sovereign is undoubtedly allowed to employ ministers to ease him in the painful offices of government ; but he ought never to surren- der his authority to them. When a nation chooses a con- ductor, it is not with a view that he should deliver up his charge into other hands. Ministers ought only to be instru- ments in the hands of the prince ; he ought constantly to direct them, and continually endeavour to know whether they act according to his intentions. If the imbecility of age, or any infirmity, render him incapable of governing, a regent ought to be nominated, according to the laws of the state : but when once the sovereign is capable of holding the reins, let him insist on being served, but never suffer himself to be superseded. The last kings of France of the first race sur- rendered the government and authority to the mayors of the palace : thus becoming mere phantoms, they justly lost the title and honours of a dignity of which they had abandoned the functions. The nation has every thing to gain in crown- ing an all-powerful minister, for he will improve that soil as his own inheritance, which he plundered whilst he only reaped precarious advantages from it. CHAP. V. CHAP. Y. OF STATES ELECTIVE, SUCCESSIVE OR HEREDITARY, AND OF THOSE CALLED PATRIMONIAL. g 56. Of WE have seen in the preceding chapter, that it originally ective belongs to a nation to confer the supreme authority, and to ltes ' choose the person by whom it is to be governed. If it confers [ 24 ] the sovereignty on him for his own person only, reserving to itself the right of choosing a successor after the sovereign's death, the state is elective. As soon as the prince is elected according to the laws, he enters into the possession of all the prerogatives which those laws annex to his dignity. 57. Whe- It has been debated, whether elective kings and princes are ther elective real sovereigns. But he who lays any stress on this circum- kings are gtance must have only a very confused idea of sovereignty. reigns. " ^ ne manner i n which a prince obtains his dignity has nothing to do with determining its nature. We must consider, first, whether the nation itself forms an independent society (see 90 SUCCESSIVE, OR HEREDITARY, ETC. 24 chap. 1), and secondly, what is the extent of the power it has BOOK i. intrusted to the prince. Whenever the chief of an independ- ... CHAP> T '- ent state really represents his nation, he ought to he consid- ered as a true sovereign ( 40), even though his authority should be limited in several respects. When a nation would avoid the troubles which seldom fail ? 58. Of to accompany the election of a sovereign, it makes its choice for a long succession of years, by establishing the right of succession, or by rendering the crown hereditary in a family, states. according to the order and rules that appear most agreeable The ri g in to that nation. The name of an Hereditary State or Kingdom jj is given to that where the successor is appointed by the same sion> law that regulates the successions of individuals. The Suc- cessive Kingdom is that where a person succeeds according to a particular fundamental law of the state. Thus the lineal suc- cession, and of males alone, is established in France. The right of succession is not always the primitive esta- % 59. Other blishment of a nation ; it may have been introduced by the origins of concession of another sovereign, and even by usurpation. But thls nght ' when it is supported by long possession, the people are con- sidered as consenting to it ; and this tacit consent renders it lawful, though the source be vicious. It rests then on the foundation we have already pointed out a foundation that alone is lawful and incapable of being shaken, and to which we must ever revert. The same right, according to Grotius and the generality I 60. other of writers, may be derived from other sources, as conquest, ^ c c h es Btil] or the right of a proprietor, who, being master of a country, ^^m* to should invite inhabitants to settle there, and give them lands, the same on condition of their acknowledging him and his heirs for thing, their sovereigns. But as it is absurd to suppose that a society of men can place themselves in subjection otherwise than with a view to their own safety and welfare, and still more that they can bind their posterity on any other footing, it ulti- mately amounts to the same thing ; and it must still be said that the succession is established by the express will, or the tacit consent of the nation, for the welfare and safety of the state. It thus remains an undeniable truth, that in all cases the 61. A na- succession is established or received only with a view to the tion ma y public Avelfare and the general safety. If it happened then ^e^oVtoe that the order established in this respect became destructive succession. to the state, the nation would certainly have a right to change it by a new law. Salus populi suprema lex, the safety of [ 25 ] the people is the supreme law ; and this law is agreeable to the strictest justice, the people having united in society only with a view to their safety and greater advantage.* * Ximirum, quod publics salutis bus exigentibus, immutari quid obstat? causa et communi consensu statutum MARIANA, ibid. c. iy. est,,eadem multitudinis voluntate, re- 91 25 OF STATES ELECTIVE, BOOK i. This pretended proprietary right attributed to princes is a CHAP, v. c hj mera> produced by an abuse which its supporters would fain make of the laws respecting private inheritances. The state neither is nor can be a patrimony, since the end of patrimony is the advantage of the possessor, whereas the prince is established only for the advantage of the state.* The consequence is evident : if a nation plainly perceives that the heir of her prince would be a pernicious sovereign, she has a right to exclude him. The authors, whom we oppose, grant this right to a des- potic prince, while they refuse it to nations. This is because they consider such a prince as a real proprietor of the empire, and will not acknowledge that the care of their own safety, and the right to govern themselves, still essentially belong to the society, although they have intrusted them, even without any express reserve, to a monarch and his heirs. In their opinion, the kingdom is the inheritance of the prince, in the same manner as his field and his flocks a maxim injurious to human nature, and which they would not have dared to advance in an enlightened age, if it had not the support of an authority which too often proves stronger than reason and justice. | 62. Of re- A nation may, for the same reason, oblige one branch who nuncmtions. removes to another country, to renounce all claim to the crown, as a daughter who marries a foreign prince. These renunciations, required or approved by the state, are per- fectly valid, since they are equivalent to a law that such persons and their posterity should be excluded from the throne. Thus the laws of England have for ever rejected every Roman Catholic. " Thus a law of Russia, made at [ 26 ] the beginning of the reign of Elizabeth, most wisely excludes from the possession of the crown every heir possessed of * When Philip II. resigned the been nations who governed themselves Netherlands to his daughter Isabella by popular assemblies, or by a senate ; Clara Eugenia, it was said (according there have been others who intrusted to the testimony of Grotius) that it was the general management of their con- Betting a dangerous precedent, for a cerns to princes. For it is not to be prince to treat free citizens as his pro- imagined, it was added, that legitimate perty, and barter them away like do- sovereignties have originated from any mestic slaves; that, among barbari- other source than the consent of the ans, indeed, the extraordinary practice people, who gave themselves all up to sometimes obtained of transferring go- a single person, or, for the sake of vernments by will or donation, because avoiding the tumults and discord of those people were incapable of discern- elections, to a whole family ; and those ing the difference between a prince to whom they thus committed them- and a master ; but that those, whom selves were induced, by the prospect superior knowledge enabled to distin- of honourable pre-eminence alone, to guish between what is lawful and what accept a dignity by which they were is not, could plainly perceive that the bound to promote the general welfare administration of a state is the pro- of their fellow-citizens in preference to perty of the people (thence usually de- their own private advantage. GROTIUS. nominated res-publica) ; and that, as in Hist of the Disturbances in the Ne- every period of the world there have therlands, book ii. Edit. A. D. 1797. 02 SUCCESSIVE, OR HEREDITARY, ETC. 26 another monarchy ; and thus the law of Portugal disqualifies BOOK i. every foreigner who lays claim to the crown by right of blood."* CHAP, v. Some celebrated authors, in other respects very learned and judicious, have then deviated from the true principles in treating of renunciations. They have largely expatiated on the rights of children born or to be born, of the transmission of those rights, &c. But they ought to have considered the succession less as a property of the reigning family, than as a law of the state. From this clear and incontestable prin- ciple, we easily deduce the whole doctrine of renunciations. Those required or approved by the state are valid and sacred: they are fundamental laws : those not authorized by the state can only be obligatory on the prince who made them. They cannot injure his posterity, and he himself may recede from them in case the state stands in need of him and gives him an invitation : for he owes his services to a people who had committed their safety to his care. For the same reason, the prince cannot lawfully resign at an unseasonable junc- ture, to the detriment of the state, and abandon in imminent danger a nation that had put itself under his care.f In ordinary cases, when the state may follow the established 63. The rule without being exposed to very great and manifest danger, orde . r of 8UO ' it is certain that every descendant ought to succeed when the ought com order of succession calls him to the throne, however great monly to be may appear his incapacity to rule by himself. This is a con- kept. (23) sequence of the spirit of the law that established the succession : for the people had recourse to it only to prevent the troubles which would otherwise be almost inevitable at every change. Now little advances would have been made towards obtaining this end, if, at the death of a prince, the people were allowed to examine the capacity of his heir, before they acknowledged him for their sovereign. " What a door would this open for usurpers or malcontents! It was to avoid these inconve- niences that the order of succession was established; and nothing more wise could have been done, since by this means no more is required than his being the king's son, and his being actually alive, which can admit of no dispute : but, on the other hand, there is no rule fixed to judge of the capacity or incapacity to reign."J Though the succession was not established for the particular advantage of the sovereign and his family, but for that of the state, the heir-apparent has nevertheless a right, to which justice requires that regard should be paid. His right is subordinate to that of the nation, and to the safety of the state ; but it ought to take place when the public welfare does not oppose it. (23) * Spirit of Laws, book xxvi. chap. J Memorial in behalf of Madame de xxiii., where may be seen very good po- Longueville, concerning the principality litical reasons for these regulations. of Neufchatel, in 1672. -f- See further on. (23) See this doctrine illustrated in 1 Bla. Com. 247-8. C. 93 27 BOOK I. CHAP. V. 64. Of regents. g 65. indi- visibiiity of overeign- 66. Who are to de- cide dis- successon to a sove- reignty. OF STATES ELECTIVE, These reasons have the greater weight, since the law or the state may remedy the incapacity of the prince by nomi- nating a regent, as is practised in cases of minority. This regent is, during the whole time of his administration, invested with the royal authority ; but he exercises it in the king's name. (24) The principles we have just established , pecting the suc- cessive or hereditary right, manifestly show that a prince has no right to divide his state among his children. Every sovereignty, properly so called, is, in its own nature, one and indivisible, since those who have united in society cannot be separated in spite of themselves. Those partitions, so con- trary to the nature of sovereignty and the preservation of states, have been much in use ; but an end has been put to them, wherever the people, and princes themselves, have had a clear view of their greatest interest, and the foundation of their safety. But when a prince has united several different nations under his authority, his empire is then properly an assem- blage of several societies subject to the same head; and there exists no natural objection to his dividing them among his children : he may distribute them, if there be neither law nor compact to the contrary, and if each of those nations consents to receive the sovereign he appoints for it. For this reason, France was divisible under the first two races.* But being entirely consolidated under the third, it has since been con- sidered as a single kingdom ; it has become indivisible, and a fundamental law has declared it so. That law, wisely pro- viding for the preservation and splendour of the kingdom, irrevocably unites to the crown all the acquisitions of its kings. The same principles will also furnish us with the solution of a celebrated question. When the right of succession becomes uncertain in a successive or hereditary state, and two or three competitors lay claim to the crown, it is asked, "Who shall be the judge of their pretensions?" Some learned men, resting on the opinion that sovereigns are sub- ject to no other judge but God, have maintained that the competitors for the crown, while their right remains uncer- tain, ought either to come to an amicable compromise, enter into articles among themselves, choose arbitrators, have re- course even to the drawing of lots, or, finally, determine the dispute by arms ; and that the subjects cannot in any manner decide the question. One might be astonished that celebrated authors should have maintained such a doctrine. But since, even in speculative philosophy, there is nothing so absurd as not to have been advanced by one or other of the philoso- (24) Ante, p. 26, n. C. * But it is to be observed that those partitions were not made without the 94 approbation and consent of the respecf- ive states. SUCCESSIVE, OR HEREDITARY, ETC. pliers,* what can be expected from the human mind, when BOOK seduced by interest or fear ? What ! in a question that con CHAP ' cerns none so much as the nation that relates to a power established only with a view to the happiness of the people in a quarrel that is to decide for ever their dearest interests, and their very safety are they to stand by as unconcerned spectators ? Are they to allow strangers, or the blind decision of arms, to appoint them a master, as a flock of sheep are to wait till it be determined whether they are to be delivered up to the butcher, or restored to the care of their shepherd ? But, say they, the nation has divested itself of all juris- diction, by giving itself up to a sovereign ; it has submitted to the reigning family ; it has given to those who are descended from that family a right which nobody can take from them ; it has established them its superiors, and can no longer judge them. Very well ! But does it not belong to that same nation to acknowledge the person to whom its duty binds it, and prevent its being delivered up to another ? And since it has established the law of succession, who is more capable or has a better right to identify the individual whom the fundamental law had in view, and has pointed out as the suc- cessor? We may affirm, then, without hesitation, that the decision of this grand controversy belongs to the nation, and to the nation alone. Even if the competitors have agreed among themselves, or have chosen, arbitrators, the nation is not obliged to submit to their regulations, unless it has con- sented to the transaction or compromise princes not acknow- ledged, and whose right is uncertain, not being in any manner \ able to dispose of its obedience. The nation acknowledges no superior judge in an affair that relates to its most sacred duties and most precious rights. Grotius and Puffendorf differ in reality but little from our opinion ; but would not have the decision of the people or state called a juridical sentence (judicium jurisdictionis). Well ! be it so : we shall not dispute about words. However, there is something more in the case than a mere examination of the competitors' rights, in order to submit to him who has the best. All the disputes that arise in society are to be judged and decided by the public authority. As soon as the right of succession is found uncertain, the sovereign authority returns for a time to the body of the state, which is to exer- cise it, either by itself or by it representatives, till the true sovereign be known. " The contest on this right suspending the functions in the person of the sovereign, the authority naturally returns to the subjects, not for them to retain it, but to prove on which of the competitors it lawfully devolves, and then to commit it to his hands. It would not be difficult to * Ncsico quomodo nihil tarn absurde philosophorum. Cicero, do Divinat. dici potest, quod non dicatur ab aliquo lib. ii. 95 28 OF STATES ELECTIVE, BOOK r. support, by an infinite number of examples, a truth so evi- ~. CHAP. v * dent by the light of reason : it is sufficient to remember that the states of France, after the death of Charles the Fair, terminated the famous dispute between Philip de Valois and L 29 ] the king of England (Edward III.), and that those states, though subject to him in whose favour they granted the de- cision, were nevertheless the judges of the dispute." * of Arragon that decided the succession to that kingdom, in favour of Ferdinand, grandfather of Ferdinand the husband of Isabella, queen of Castile, in preference to the other re- lations of Martin, king of Arragon, who asserted that the kingdom belonged to them.f In the kingdom of Jerusalem also, it was the states that decided the disputes of those who made pretensions to it ; as is proved by several examples in the foreign political history.! The states of the principality of Neufchatel have often, in the form of a juridical sentence, pronounced on the succes- sion to the sovereignty. In the year 1707, they decided be- tween a great number of competitors, and their decision in favour of the king of Prussia was acknowledged by all Europe in the treaty of Utrecht. 67. That The better to secure the succession in a certain and inva- the right to riable order, it is at present an established rule in all Christian the succes- s t a tes (Portugal excepted), that no descendant of the sovereign noTtTde- can succee d to the crown, unless he be the issue of a marriage pend on the that is conformable to the laws of the country. As the nation judgment has established the succession, to the nation alone belongs the of a foreign p 0wer O f acknowledging those who are capable of succeeding ; power ' and consequently, on its judgment and laws alone must de- pend the validity of the marriage of its sovereigns, and the legitimacy of their birth. If education had not the power of familiarizing the human mind to the greatest absurdities, is there any man of sense who would not be struck with astonishment to see so many nations suffer the legitimacy and right of their princes to de- pend on a foreign power ? The court of Rome has invented an infinite number of obstructions and cases of invalidity in marriages, and at the same time arrogates to itself the right of judging of their validity, and of removing the obstruc- tions ; so that a prince of its communion cannot in certain cases be so much his own master as to contract a marriage necessary to the safety of the state. Jane, the only daughter of Henry IV,, king of Castile, found this true by cruel expe- rience. Some rebels published abroad that she owed her birth to Bertrand de la Cueva, the king's favourite ; and notwith- * Answer in behalf of Madame de J See the same memorial, which Longueville to a memorial in behalf of quotes P. Labbe's Royal Abridgment, Madame de Nemours. t Ibid. page 501, Ac. 96 SUCCESSIVE, OR HEREDITARY, ETC. 29 standing the declarations and last will of that prince, who BOOK i. explicitly and invariably acknowledged Jane for his daughter, CHAP ' Y ' and nominated her his heiress, they called to the crown Isa- bella, Henry's sister, and wife to Ferdinand, heir of Arragon. The grandees of Jane's party had provided her a powerful [ 30 ] resource, by negotiating a marriage between her and Alphon- sus, king of Portugal : but as that prince was Jane's uncle, it was necessary to obtain a dispensation from the pope ; and Pius II., who was in the interest of Ferdinand and Isabella, refused to grant the dispensation, though such alliances were then very common. These difficulties cooled the ardour of the Portuguese monarch, and abated the zeal of the faithful Castilians. Every thing succeeded with Isabella, and the un- fortunate Jane took the veil, in order to secure, by this heroic sacrifice, the peace of Castile.* If the prince proceeds and marries, notwithstanding the pope's refusal, he exposes his dominions to the most fatal troubles. What would have become of England, if the Re- formation had not been happily established, when the pope presumed to declare Queen Elizabeth illegitimate, and incapa- ble of wearing the crown ? A great emperor, Lewis of Bavaria, boldly asserted the rights of his crown in this respect. In the diplomatic code of the law of nations by Leibnitz, we findf two acts, in which that prince condemns, as an invasion of the imperial autho- rity, the doctrine that attributes to any other power but his own, the right of granting dispensations, and of judging of the validity of marriages, in the places under his jurisdiction : but he was neither well supported in his lifetime, nor imitated by his successors. Finally, there are states whose sovereign may choose his ? 68 - Of successor, and even transfer the crown to another during his state . s cal . le , d ' , & patrimonial. * I take this historical passage from says he, nobis rite debitam et conces- M. Du Port de Tertre's Conspiracies, sum. To him I refer ; for I have not the ori- P. 156. Forma dispensations super ginal historians by me. However, I do amnitate consanguinitatis inter Lu- not enter into the question relating to dovicum marchionem Brandenburg et the birth of Jane : this would here be Margaretham ducissam Kurinthitc, nee of no use. The princess had not been non legitimatio liberorum procreando- declared a bastard according to the rum, fautic per dom. Ludovic. IV. Rom. laws ; the king acknowledged her for imper. his daughter ; and besides, whether she It is only human law, says the empe- was or was not legitimate, the incon- ror, that hinders these marriages intra veniences resulting from the pope's re- gradus affinitatis sangninis, prsesertim fusal still remained the same with re- intra fratres et sorores. De cujus legis spect to her and the king of Portugal. prseceptis dispensare solummodo pertinet Note, edit. 1797. ad auctoritatem imperatoris seu prinei- { P. 154. Forma divortii matrimo- pis Romanorum. He then opposes and nialis inter Johannern filium regis Bo- condemns the opinion of those who dare hemiae et Margaretham ducissam Ka- to say that these dispensations depend rinthiae. This divorce is given by the on ecclesiastics. Both this act and the emperor on account of the impoten- former are dated in the year 1341. oy of the husband, per auctoritatem, Note, edit. A. D. 1797. 13 I 97 30 OF STATES ELECTIVE, BOOK i. life: these are commonly called patrimonial t kingdoms or .-CHAP. Y ' states : but let us reject so unjust and so improper an epithet, which can only serve to inspire some sovereigns with ideas very opposite to those they ought to entertain. We have shown ( 61) that a state cannot be a patrimony. But it may happen that a nation, either through unbounded confidence in its prince, or for some other reason, has intrusted him with the care of appointing his successor, and even consented to [ 31 ] receive, if he thinks proper, another sovereign from his hands. Thus we see that Peter I., emperor of Russia, nominated his wife to succeed him, though he had children. I 69. Every But when a prince chooses his successor, or when he cedes true sove- the crown to another, properly speaking, he only nominates, reignty is jyy virtue of the power with which he is, either expressly or e ' by tacit consent, intrusted he only nominates, I say, the person who is to govern the state after him. This neither is nor can be an alienation, properly so called. Every true sovereignty is, in its own nature, unalienable. We shall be easily convinced of this, if we pay attention to the origin and end of political society, and of the supreme authority. A nation becomes incorporated into a society, to labour for the common welfare as it shall think proper, and to live accord- ing to its own laws. With this view it establishes a public authority. If it intrusts that authority to a prince, even with the power of transferring it to other hands, this can never take place without the express and unanimous consent of the citizens, with the right of really alienating or subject- ing the state to another body politic : for the individuals who have formed this society, entered into it in order to live in an independent state, and not under a foreign yoke. Let not any other source of this right be alleged in objection to our argument, as conquest, for instance ; for we have already shown ( 60) that these different sources ultimately revert to the true principles on which all just governments are founded. While the victor does not treat his conquest according to those principles, the state of war still in some measure sub- sists : but the moment he places it in a civil state, his rights are proportioned by the principles of that state. I know that many authors, and particularly Grotius,* give long enumerations of the alienations of sovereignties. But the examples often prove only the abuse of power, not the right. And besides, the people consented to the alienation, either willingly or by force. What could the inhabitants of Pergamus, Bithynia, and Gyrene do, when their kings gave them, by their last wills, to the Roman people ? Nothing remained for them, but to submit with a good grace to so powerful a legatee. To furnish an example capable of serving as an authority, they should have produced an instance of a * Grotius De jure Belli et Pacis, lib. i. cap. iii. I 12. SUCCESSIVE, OR HEREDITARY, ETC. 31 people resisting a similar bequest of their sovereign, and BOOK i. whose resistance had been generally condemned as unjust and CHAP ' Y> . rebellious. Had Peter I., who nominated his wife to succeed him, attempted to subject his empire to the grand seignior, or to some other neighbouring power, can we imagine that the Russians would have suffered it, or that their resistance would have passed for a revolt ? We do not find in Europe any great state that is reputed alienable. If some petty princi- palities have been considered as such, it is because they were not true sovereignties. They were fiefs of the empire, enjoying a greater or less degree of liberty : their masters L "* J made a traffic of the rights they possessed over those terri- tories : but they could not withdraw them from a dependence on the empire. Let us conclude then, that, as the nation alone has a right to subject itself to a foreign power, the right of really alien- ating the state can never belong to the sovereign, unless it be expressly given him by the entire body of the people.* Neither are we to presume that he possesses a right to nomi- nate his successor or surrender the sceptre to other hands, a right which must be founded on an express consent, on a law of the state, or on long custom, justified by the tacit consent of the people. If the power of nominating his successor is intrusted to the 70. Duty sovereign, he ought to have no other view in his choice but of a prince the advantage and safety of the state. He himself was es- W ^ 18 J|~ tablished only for this end ( 39) ; the liberty of transferring nominate his power to another could then be granted to him only with his suc- the same view. It would be absurd to consider it as a prero- cessor. gative useful to the prince, and which he may turn to his own private advantage. Peter the Great proposed only the welfare of the empire when he left the crown to his wife. He knew that heroine to be the most capable person to follow his views, and perfect the great things he had begun, and therefore preferred her to his son, who was still too young. If we often found on the throne such elevated minds as Peter's, a nation could not adopt a wiser plan, in order to ensure to itself a good government, than to intrust the prince, by a fundamental law, with the power of appointing his successor. This would be a much more certain method than the order of birth. The Ro- man emperors, who had no male children, appointed a succes- sor by adoption. To this custom Rome was indebted for a * * The pope, opposing the attempt them." On which occasion the French made upon England by Louis, the son nobles unanimously exclaimed, that they of Philip Augustus, and alleging, as his would, to their last breath, maintain pretext, that John had rendered himself this truth, " that no prince can, of his a vassal of the holy see, received for own private will, give away his king- answer, among other arguments, " that dom, or render it tributary, and thus a sovereign had no right to dispose of enslave the nobility." Velly's Hist of his states without the consent of his France, vol. iii. p. 491. barons, who were bound to defend 99 32 PRINCIPAL OBJECTS OF BOOK I. CHAP. V. 71. He must have at least a tacit rati- fication. [33] series of sovereigns unequalled in history, Nerva, Trajan, . Adrian, Antoninus, Marcus Aurelius. What princes ! Does the right of birth often place such on the throne ? We may go still farther, and boldly assert, that, as the safety of the whole nation is deeply interested in so import- ant a transaction, the consent and ratification of the people or state is necessary to give it full and entire effect, at least their tacit consent and ratification. If an emperor of Russia thought proper to nominate for his successor a person noto- riously unworthy of the crown, it is not at all probable that vast empire would blindly submit to so pernicious an appoint- ment. And who shall presume to blame a nation for refus- ing to run headlong to ruin out of respect to the last orders )f its prince ? As soon as the people submit to the sovereign appointed to rule over them, they tacitly ratify the choice made by the last prince ; and the new monarch enters into all the rights of his predecessor. ties of the sovereign. CHAP. VI. CHAP, vi. PRINCIPAL OBJECTS OF A GOOD GOVERNMENT ; AND FIRST TO PROVIDE FOR THE NECESSITIES OF THE NATION. 72. The AFTER these observations on the constitution of the state, object of so- let us now proceed to the principal objects of a good govern- ment. We have seen above ( 41 and 42) that the prince, on his being invested with the sovereign authority, is charged with the duties of the nation in relation to government. In treating of the principal objects of a wise administration, we at once show the duties of a nation towards itself, and those of the sovereign towards his people. A wise conductor of the state will find in the objects of civil society the general rule and indication of his duties. The society is established with the view of procuring, to those who are its members, the necessaries, conveniences, and even pleasures of life, and, in general, every thing necessary to their happiness, of enabling each individual peaceably to enjoy his own property, and to obtain justice with safety and certainty, and, finally, of defending themselves in a body He ought to against all external violence ( 15). The nation, or its con- procure ductor, should first apply to the business of providing for all plenty. the wants of the people, and producing a happy plenty of all the necessaries of life, with its conveniences and innnocent and laudable enjoyments. (25) As an easy life without lux- (25) See the general doctrine, that the at large, 2 Malthus, 433 ; 2 Smith, W. N. happiness of a people depends on the 200 ; 2 Paley, Mor. Phil. 345 ; Sir J. quantity of productive labour and em- Child on Trade, 167-8 ; and Tucker on ployment, and the consequent return Trade, part ii. sections 4, 7, 8 ; 1 Chit- of produce and remuneration, discussed ty's Commercial Law, 1, Ac. C. 100 A GOOD GOVERNMENT. 33 ury contributes to the happiness of men, it likewise enables BOOK i. them to labour with greater safety and success after their CHAF ' YI> own perfection, which is their grand and principal duty, and one of the ends they ought to have in view when they unite in society. To succeed in procuring this abundance of every thing, it 73. To is necessary to take care that there be a sufficient number of take care able workmen in every useful or necessary profession. (26) J* a * JJjJJ 8 An attentive application on the part of government, wise re- ci * * t 8 n nn [_ gulations, and assistance properly granted, will produce this ber of work- effect, without using constraint, which is always fatal to in- men. dustry. Those workmen that are useful ought to be retained in 74. To the state ; to succeed in retaining them, the public authority prevent the has certainly a right to use contraint, if necessary. (27) Every citizen owes his personal services to his country ; and a t h a t mechanic, in particular, who has been reared, educated, and useful, instructed in its bosom, cannot lawfully leave it, and carry to a foreign land that industry which he acquired at home, un- less his country has no occasion for him, (27) or he cannot there obtain the just fruit of his labour and abilities. Em- [ 34 ] ployment must then be procured for him ; and, if, while able to obtain a decent livelihood in his own country, he would without reason abandon it, the state has a right to detain him. (28) But a very moderate use ought to be made of this right, and only in important or necessary cases. Liberty is the soul of abilities and industry : frequently a mechanic or an artist, after having long travelled abroad, is attracted home to his native soil by a natural affection, and returns more expert and better qualified to render his country useful services. If certain extraordinary cases be excepted, it is best in this affair to practise the mild methods of protection, ea- -/,:;,. , couragement, &c., and to leave the rest to that natural love felt by all men for the places of their birth. As to those emissaries who come into a country to entice \ 75. Emis- away useful subjects, the sovereign has a right to punish them sarie s who severely, and has just cause of complaint against the power entice them by whom they are employed. In another place, we shall treat more particularly of the general question, whether a citizen be permitted to quit the (26) There were in England many this rule, 5 Geo. I. c. 27; 23 Geo. II. enactments enforcing this supposed c. 13 ; 14 Geo. III. c. 71 ; 4 Bla. Com. policy, and prohibiting various work- 160 ; but repealed by 5 Geo. IV. c. 97. men from leaving the kingdom. See 5 C. Geo. I. c. 27; 23 Geo. II. c. 13; 14 (28) See also the power of prevent- Geo. III. c. 71 ; 4 Bla. Com. 160. But, ing a subject, or even a foreigner, going according to more modern policy, these abroad. Flack v. Holm, 1 Jac. & Walk. enactments were repealed by 5 Geo. IV. Rep. 405, and post, $ 222 and Book II. c. 97.-C. | 108.-C. (27) See the English acts enforcing 1 2 101 34 OF THE CULTIVATION OF THE SOIL. BOOK i. society of which he is a member. The particular reasons CHAP. vr. concern } n g useful workmen are sufficient here. 1 76. La- The state ought to encourage labour, to animate indus- bour and try, (29) to excite abilities, to propose honours, rewards, privi- musTbYen ^ e 8 es > an( ^ so * or( ^ er matters that every one may live by his couraged. industry. In this particular, England deserves to be held up as an example. The parliament incessantly attends to these important affairs, in which neither care nor expense is spared. (30) And do we not even see a society of excellent citizens formed with this view, and devoting considerable sums to this use ? Premiums are also distributed in Ireland to the mechanics who most distinguish themselves in their pro- fession. Can such a state fail of being powerful and happy ? CHAP VII. OF THE CULTIVATION OF THE SOIL. (31) 77. The OF all the arts, tillage, or agriculture, is doubtless the most utility of useful and necessary, as being the source whence the nation tillage. (31) derives it s subsistence. The cultivation of the soil causes it to produce an infinite increase ; it forms the surest resource and the most solid fund of riches and commerce, for a nation that enjoys a happy climate. 78. Regu- This object then deserves the utmost attention of the go- lations ne- yernment. The sovereign ought to neglect no means of ren- thisTespect Bering the land under his jurisdiction as well cultivated as possible. He ought not to allow either communities or pri- vate persons to acquire large tracts of land, and leave them For the dis- uncultivated. Those rights of common, which deprive the pro- tribution of prietor of the free liberty of disposing of his land which will land - not allow him to enclose and cultivate it in the most advan- [ 35 ] tageous manner ; those rights, I say, are inimical to the wel- fare of the state, and ought to be suppressed, or reduced to just bounds. Notwithstanding the introduction of private property among the citizens, the nation has still a right to take the most effectual measures to cause the aggregate soil of the country to produce the greatest and most advantageous revenue possible. (32) (29) Ante, $ 72, note (25). C. gislative enactments respecting the cul (30) How far the interference of the tivation of the soil or employment of legislature is advisable, and when see its produce, each individual being left the authorities and arguments collected, to his own discretion ; but to prevent 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, 4 to 7, and the injurious sale of farming produce, post, $ 98. C. thereby impoverishing the land, there is (31) As to the subject of this chapter, an express enactment enforcing public see further authorities, Chitty's Com- policy in that respect. See 56 Geo. III. mercial Law, vol. i. chap. 1. C. c. 50, and its recitals. In France there (32) In England there are few le- are express provisions punishing indi- 102 OF THE CULTIVATION OF THE SOIL. 35 The government ought carefully to avoid every thing ca- BOOK i. pable of discouraging the husbandman, or of diverting him from the labours of agriculture. Those taxes those excessive ? 79 - For and ill-proportioned impositions, the burden of which falls j io e n p jf ^us- almost entirely on the cultivators and the oppressions they bandmen. suffer from the officers who levy them deprive the unhappy peasant of the means of cultivating the earth, and depopulate the country. Spain is the most fertile and the worst culti- vated country in Europe. The church there possesses too much land ; and the contractors for the royal magazines, being authorized to purchase, at a low price, all the corn they find in the possession of a peasant, above what is necessary for the subsistence of himself and his family, so greatly dis- courage the husbandman, that he sows no more corn than is barely necessary for the support of his own household. Hence the frequent scarcity in a country capable of feeding its neighbours. Another abuse injurious to agriculture is the contempt so. Hus- cast upon the husbandman. The tradesmen in cities even ban "* ry the most servile mechanics the idle citizens consider him J!f ced n ^ B that cultivates the earth with a disdainful eye ; they humble honourable and discourage him ; they dare to despise a profession that light feeds the human race the natural employment of man. A little insignificant haberdasher, a tailor, places far beneath him the beloved employment of the first consuls and dictators of Rome ! China has wisely prevented this abuse : agricul- ture is there held in honour ; and to preserve this happy mode of thinking, the emperor himself, followed by his whole court, annually, on a solemn day, sets his hand to the plough, and sows a small piece of land. Hence China is the best cultivated country in the world ; it feeds an immense multi- tude of inhabitants who at first sight appear to the traveller too numerous for the space they occupy. The cultivation of the soil deserves the attention of the 81. The government, not only on account of the invaluable advantages cultivation that flow from it, but from its being an obligation imposed by JJJJ ' nature on mankind. The whole earth is destined to feed its obligation. inhabitants ; but this it would be incapable of doing if it were uncultivated. Every nation is then obliged by the law of nature to cultivate the land that has fallen to its share ; and it has no right to enlarge its boundaries, or have recourse to the assistance of other nations, but in proportion as the land in its possession is incapable of furnishing it with necessaries. Those nations (such as the ancient Germans, and some modern [ 36 ] Tartars) who inhabit fertile countries, but disdain to culti- vate their lands, and choose rather to live by plunder, are wanting to themselves, are injurious to all their neighbours, riduals who suffer injurious weeds to ceedingly salutary if introduced into ,eed on land to the injury of their neigh- this country. _ C. oours, a regulation which would be ex- 103 36 OF THE CULTIVATION OP THE SOIL. BOOK i. an( j deserve to be extirpated as savage and pernicious beasts CHAP. vii. rj^ere are others, who, to avoid labour, choose to live only by hunting, and their flocks. This might, doubtless, be allowed in the first ages of the world, when the earth, without cultivation, produced more than was sufficient to feed its small number of inhabitants. But at present, when the hu- man race is so greatly multiplied, it could not subsist if all nations were disposed to live in that manner. Those who still pursue this idle mode of life, usurp more extensive terri- tories than, with a reasonable share of labour, they would have occasion for, and have, therefore, no reason to complain, if other nations, more industrious and too closely confined, come to take possession of a part of those lands. Thus, though the conquest of the civilized empires of Peru and Mexico was a notorious usurpation, the establishment of many colonies on the continent of North America might, on their confining themselves within just bounds, be extremely lawful. The people of those extensive tracts rather ranged through than inhabited them. g 82. Of The establishment of public granaries is an excellent re- public gra- gulation for preventing scarcity. But great care should be naries. taken to prevent their being managed with a mercantile spirit, and with views of profit. This would be establishing a monopoly, which would not be the less unlawful for its be- ing carried on by the magistrate. These granaries should be filled in times of the greatest plenty, and take off the corn that would lie on the husbandman's hands, or be car- ried in too great quantities to foreign countries : they should be opened when corn is dear, and keep it at a reasonable price. If in a time of plenty they prevent that necessary commodity from easily falling to a very low price, this incon- venience is more than compensated by the relief they afford in times of dearth : or rather, it is no inconvenience at all ; for, when corn is sold extremely cheap, the manufacturer, in order to obtain a preference, is tempted to undersell his neighbours, by offering his goods at a price which he is after- wards obliged to raise (and this produces great disorders in commerce, by putting it out of its course) ; or he accus- toms himself to an easy life, which he cannot support in harder times. It would be of advantage to manufactures and to commerce to have the subsistence of workmen regu- larly kept at a moderate and nearly equal price. In short, public granaries keep in the state quantities of corn that would be sent abroad at too cheap a rate, and must be pur- chased again, and brought back at a very great expense after a bad harvest, which is a real loss to the nation. These establishments, however, do not hinder the corn trade. If the country, one year with another, produces more than is sufficient for the support of her inhabitants, the superfluity will still be sent abroad ; but it will be sent at a higher and fairer price. 104 OF COMMERCE. 37 BOOK I. CHAP. VIII. CHAP. VIII. r 37 -, OF COMMERCE. (33) IT is commerce that enables individuals and whole nations g 83 Of to procure those commodities which they stand in need of, home and but cannot find at home. Commerce is divided into home foreign and foreign trade. (34) The former is that carried on in the 1 "" 16 ' state between the several inhabitants ; the latter is carried on with foreign nations. The home trade of a nation is of great use ; it furnishes all g 34 utility the citizens with the means of procuring whatever they want, of the home as either necessary, useful, or agreeable ; it causes a circu- tr&de - lation of money, excites industry, animates labour, and, by affording subsistence to a great number of people, contributes to increase the population and power of the state. The same reasons show the use of foreign trade, which is g 35. utility moreover attended with these two advantages : 1. By trad- of foreign ing with foreigners, a nation procures such things as neither trade - nature nor art can furnish in the country it occupies. And secondly, if its foreign trade be properly directed, it increases the riches of the nation, and may become the source of wealth and plenty. Of this the example of the Carthaginians among the ancients, and that of the English and Dutch among the moderns, afford remarkable proofs. Carthage, by her riches, counter-balanced the fortune, courage, and greatness of Rome. Holland has amassed immense sums in her marshes ; a com- pany of her merchants possesses whole kingdoms in the East, and the governor of Batavia exercises command over the monarchs of India. To what a degree of power and glory has England arrived ! Formerly her warlike princes and in- habitants made glorious conquests, which they afterwards lost by those reverses of fortune so frequent in war ; at present, it is chiefly commerce that places in her hand the balance of Europe. Nations are obliged to cultivate the home trade, first, f 86. Obli- because it is clearly demonstrated from the law of nature, e ati . on to that mankind ought mutually to assist each other, and, asf ultlvat6 ! he far as in their power, contribute to the perfection and hap- piness of their fellow-creatures : whence arises, after the in- troduction of private property, the obligation to resign to others, at a fair price, those things which they have occasion for, and which we do not destine for our own use. Secondly, (33) See the authorities and doctrines carrying trade, formerly one of the prin- on the advantage of commerce and com- cipal sources of British wealth and mercial regulations, 1 Chitty's Commer- power. See authorities, 1 Chitty's Com- cial Law, 1 to 106.-C. mercia l Law, 7, 8, Ae.-C. (34) To these are to he added the I* 105 195165 CHAP. V OF COMMERCE. BOOKJ. society being established with the view that each may pro- cure whatever things are necessary to his own perfection and happiness and a home trade being the means of obtaining them the obligations to carry on and improve this trade are derived from the very compact on which the society was [ 38 ] formed. Finally, being advantageous to the nation, it is a duty the people owe to themselves, to make this commerce flourish. 87. Obii- For the same reason, drawn' from the welfare of the state, gation to and also to procure for the citizens every thing they want, a carry on nation is obliged to promote and carry on a foreign trade. S? n ^ a ^ *k e m d ern stat es, England is most distinguished in this respect. The parliament have their eyes constantly fixed on this important object ; they effectually protect the navigation of the merchants, and, by considerable bounties, favour the exportation of superfluous commodities and mer- chandises. In a very sensible production,* may be seen the valuable advantages that kingdom has derived from such judicious regulations. 88. Foun- Let us now see what are the laws of nature and the rights dation of of nations in respect to the commerce they carry on with the laws of eac fa O th er . Men are obliged mutually to assist each other as much as possible, and to contribute to the perfection and happiness of their fellow-creatures (Prelim. 10) ; (35) whence it follows, as we have said above ( 86), that, after the intro- duction of private property, it became a duty to sell to each other, at a fair price, what the possessor himself has no occa- sion for, and what is necessary to others ; because, since that introduction of private property, no one can, by any other means, procure the different things that may be necessary or useful to him, and calculated to render life pleasant and agree- Right of able. Now, since right springs from obligation (Prelim. 3), buying. the obligation which we have just established gives every man the right of procuring the things he wants, by purchasing them at a reasonable price from those who have themselves no occasion for them. (36) We have also seen (Prelim. 5) that men could not free themselves from the authority of the laws of nature by uniting in civil society, and that the whole nation remains equally * Remarks on the Advantages and in concluding the commercial treaty Disadvantages of France and Great with France in 1786, though a great number of years (40) The perpetual obligation to censured by some as evidently advan- purchase Port wines from Portugal in tageous to Portugal and disadvantage- exchange for British woollen cloths was ous to Great Britain. 2 Smith, W. N. established by the celebrated treaty of 338 to 341 ; Tucker on Trade, 356 ; Methuen, A. n. 1703 ( so called because and 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, 619. concluded by Sir P. Methuen), with C. Portugal : a treaty which has been 110 OF COMMERCE. 42 are suffered to elapse without its being used ; because this BOOK i. right is a simple power, jus merce facidtatis, which she is at CHAP - YIU - liberty to use or not, whenever she pleases. Certain circumstances, however, may render a different decision necessary, because they imply a change in the nature of the right in question. For instance, if it appears evident, that the nation granting this right granted it only with a view of procuring a species of merchandise of which she stands in need, and if the nation which obtained the right of selling neglects to furnish those merchandises, and another offers to bring them regularly, on condition of having an exclusive privilege, it appears certain that the privilege may be granted to the latter. Thus the nation that had the right of selling would lose it, because she had not fulfilled the tacit condition. Commerce is a common benefit to a nation ; and all her ? 97. Of members have an equal right to it. Monopoly, therefore, in mon P ol i es > general, is contrary to the rights of the citizens. However, complniesf this rule has its exceptions, suggested even by the interest of W uh exciu- the nation : and a wise government may, in certain cases, sive privi- justly establish monopolies. There are commercial enter- le s es - ( 41 ) prises that cannot be carried on without an energy that (41) See the advantages and dis- advantages resulting from commercial companies and foreign monopolies, and upon colonization in general, 1 Chit- ty's Commercial Law, 631 to 689 ; and see some sensible observations on the Impolicy of Exclusive Companies, Evans on Statutes, Class III. title In- surance, p. 231. Dr. Adam Smith, in his Wealth of Nations, book iv. c. 7, p. 379, &c. and Dean Tucker, in his Essay on Trade, 67 to 71 (but see Id. 40, 41), admit, that, to induce specu- lating and enterprising individuals to embark their capitals in expensive un- dertakings, probably generally bene- ficial in the result, but which could not be pursued by single individuals, it may be expedient originally to afford them a monopoly ; but that, after they , have acquired a liberal profit, the trade ought to be thrown open. Again, when a country becomes too densely populated, and many subjects are out of employ and restless, then there may be another reason for encourag- ing the creation of foreign companies. A celebrated diplomatist, and an acute observer of human nature (M. Talley- rand), has justly said, that the art of putting men into their proper places is, perhaps, the first science of govern- ment ; but that of finding the proper place for the discontented is assuredly the most difficult ; and the presenting to their imagination in a distant coun- try, perspective views, on which their thoughts and desires may fix them- selves, is one of the solutions of this difficulty. In the development of the motives which determined the estab- lishment of the ancient colonies we easily remark, that, at the very time they were indispensable, they were voluntary; that they were presented by the governments as an allurement, not as a punishment. Bodies politic ought to reserve to themselves the means of placing to advantage, at a distance from their immediate seat, that superabundance of citizens who from time to time threaten their tran- quilliti/. Thus, with new views of life, and the content springing from the full employment of the aspiring mind of man, and under the influence of re- newed hope, the bad, the idle, and the turbulent may be rendered useful mem- bers of society. Our colonies, then, pre- sent such a field for the promotion of human happiness, such a scope for the noblest purposes of philanthropy, that we cannot be led to think their inte- rests will be overlooked by a wise legis- lature or government. C. Ill 42 OF COMMERCE. BOOK i. requires considerable funds, which surpass the ability of in- CFIAP. YIII. dividuals. There are others that would soon become ruinous, were they not conducted with great prudence, with one regu- lar spirit, and according to well-supported maxims and rules. These branches of trade cannot be indiscriminately carried on by individuals : companies are therefore formed, under the authority of government ; and these companies cannot subsist without an exclusive privilege. It is therefore advantageous to the nation to grant them : hence have arisen, in different countries, those powerful companies that carry on commerce with the East. When the subjects of the United Provinces established themselves in the Indies on the ruin of their ene- mies the Portuguese, individual merchants would not have dared to think of such an arduous enterprise ; and the state itself, wholly taken up with the defence of its liberty against the Spaniards, had not the means of attempting it. It is also certain beyond all doubt, that, whenever any in- dividual offers, on condition of obtaining an exclusive privilege, to establish a particular branch of commerce or manufacture which the nation has not the means of carrying on, the sove- reign may grant him such privilege. But whenever any branch of commerce may be left open to the whole nation, without producing any inconvenience or being less advantageous to the state, a restriction of that commerce to a few privileged individuals is a violation of the rights of all the other citizens. And even when such a com- merce requires considerable expenses to maintain forts, men of war, &c., this being a national affair, the state may defray those expenses, and, as an encouragement to industry, leave the profits of the trade to the merchants. This is sometimes [ 43 ] done in England. g 98. Ba- The conductor of a nation ought to take particular care to lance of encourage the commerce that is advantageous to his people, attention of an( ^ to 8U PP ress or l a j restraints upon that which is to their government disadvantage. (42) Gold and silver having become the com- in this respect (42 ) Tnig is a que8t ionabk policy. 125, 201, 204; 3 Id. 183 j Malthus, It has been laid down by some of the 196; 2 Paley, Mor. Phil. 400, 402; most eminent writers on political econo- 3 Hume, Hist. 403 ; Sir J. Child on my, that every active interference of Trade, 2d part, 46, 81, 86, 132, 154 to the legislature with its subjects, by 164 ; and Buchanan's Observations on prohibiting or restraining any particu- Smith's W. of N. 2d ed. vol. 4, page lar branch of honest labour, or by en- 156, 157 ; Introduc. 3 Lord Sheffield's couraging any particular branch at the Strictures on Navigation System, 3 expense of the others, whether in agri- Adolph. 163, and see ante, chap. 6, culture or commerce, has uniformly re- and 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, 4 tarded the advances of public opulence, to 7. and that the sound policy of a legislator But as regards the encouragement is not to impose restrictions or regula- or discouragement of any particular tions upon domestic industry, but ra- branch of trade, there is another mo- ther to prevent them from being im- tive for interference which powerfully posed by the contrivance or folly of influences, viz. the increase of revenue, others. See 2 Smith, W. N. 118, for whenever the luxury or other wish 112 PUBLIC WAYS. 43 mon standard of the value of all the articles of commerce, the BOOK T - trade that brings into the state a greater quantity of these CHAP - YI "-. metals than it carries out, is an advantageous trade ; and, on the contrary, that is a ruinous one, which causes more gold and silver to be sent abroad, than it brings home. This is what is called the balance of trade. The ability of those who have the direction of it, consists in making that balance turn in favour of the nation. Of all the measures that a wise government may take with 2 99 . Im- this view, we shall only touch here on import duties. When ^ dutie8 - the conductors of a state, without absolutely forcing trade, are nevertheless desirous of diverting it into other channels, they lay such duties on the merchandises they would discou- rage as will prevent their consumption. Thus, French wines are charged with very high duties in England, while the duties on those of Portugal are very moderate, because England sells few of her productions to France, while she sells large quantities to Portugal. There is nothing in this con- duct that is not very wise and extremely just; and France has no reason to complain of it every nation having an un- doubted right to make what conditions she thinks proper, with respect to receiving foreign merchandises, and being even at liberty to refuse taking them at all. CHAP. IX. OF THE CARE OF THE PUBLIC WAYS OF COMMUNICATION, CHAP, ix. AND THE RIGHT OF TOLL. THE utility of highways, bridges, canals, and, in a word, 100. TJti- of all safe and commodious ways of communication, cannot Ht y of hi s h - be doubted. They facilitate the trade between one place and ^ s '^ *" another, and render the conveyance of merchandise less ex- na pensive, as well as more certain and easy. The merchants are enabled to sell at a better price, and to obtain the pre- ference ; an attraction is held out to foreigners, whose mer- chandises are carried through the country, and diffuse wealth in all the places through which they pass. France and Hol- land feel the happy consequences of this from daily expe- . rience. (44) of the people introduces a foreign, or and export duties, bounties and draw- even a domestic article to greater con- backs, which, since Vattel wrote, have sumption, a moderate charge upon the become extensive branches of law, same, though in a degree restrictive upon highly important to be studied. See an the consumption, will in general be a attempt of the editor to arrange them, proper tax. Ibid. C. in 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, Index, (43) This is a very slight allusion to titles Import and Export. C. the very important regulation of import (44) But although, since Vattel 15 K2 113 PUBLIC WAYS. One of the principal things that ought to employ the at- ition of the government with respect to the welfare of the 2 ioi. Duty public in general, and of trade in particular, must then relate menUn^h' * ^ e highways, canals, &c., in which nothing ought to be respect. * neglected to render them safe and commodious. France is one of those states where this duty to the public is discharged with the greatest attention and magnificence. Numerous [ 44 ] patroles everywhere watch over the safety of travellers : mag- nificent roads, bridges, and canals, facilitate the communica- tion between one province and another : Lewis XIV. joined the two seas by a work worthy of the Romans. 1 102. its The whole nation ought, doubtless, to contribute to such ^ nthls useful undertakings. When therefore the laying out and repairing of highways, bridges, and canals, would be too great a burden on the ordinary revenues of the state, the government may oblige the people to labour at them, or to contribute to the expense. (45) The peasants, in some of the provinces of France, have been heard to murmur at the labours imposed upon them for the construction of roads : but ex- perience had no sooner made them sensible of their true interest, than they blessed the authors of the undertaking. | 103 ^ F un - The construction and preservation of all these works being attended with great expense, the nation may very justly oblige all those to contribute to them, who receive advantage from their use : this is the legitimate origin of the right of toll. It is just that a traveller, and especially a merchant, who receives advantage from a bridge, a canal, or a road, in his own passage, and in the more commodious conveyance of wrote, France greatly advanced in the ply of proper food in return for his improvement of her roads, yet England labour. C. has surpassed all other nations in the (46) As to the right to toll, Ac., see facilities of internal intercourse by new Grotius, b. ii. chap. 2, 14, p. 154 ; canals, railways, and other improve- Puffendorff, book iii. chap. 3, g 6, p. ments sanctioned by the legislature. 29, 30; 1 Bla. Com. 287; 1 Chitty's With respect to which, see the enact- Commercial Law, 103 to 106; 2 Id. ments and decisions, 2 Chitty's Commer- 139, 140. It has been observed, that cial Law, 127 to 141. C. of all the taxes with which the inhabi- (45) This position of a government's tants of this country are burdened, right to oblige the people to labour on there is perhaps none so odious as the the roads as thus stated, would startle turnpike duty. On the continent no an Englishman. In England there is such interruption in travelling is ex- no such direct power. The 34 Geo. 3, perienced, and tolls have been abolished c. 74, B. 4, it is true, requires each oc- on the northern side of the metropolis, cupier to send his carts and horses, and London. Lord Byron, in his eulogy labourers, to work on the roads; but upon English roads, humorously ob- then, if he neglect to do so, he is sub- serves ject only to a moderate penalty, just .. what , dei.ghtfoi thing-, a rornpike rd, sufficient to enable the surveyor to hire so .mooth, level, .uchamodeof .having the like assistance elsewhere: and as The earth, M .carce the eagle in the broad ,. Air can accomplish with bis wide wing, waving. tO men, even a pauper IS Subject to no Had .uch been cut in Phaeton', time, Ibe god penalty for refusing to work, excepting Had told hi. n to Mtbfjr hi. craving that, if he do so, he will not then be j l H'^"*,^^ *,?* ** "" ' entitled to parochial relief. If he work, cut. x. 7& c. he is entitled to pay in money, or sup- 114 PUBLIC WAYS. 44 his merchandise, should help to defray the expense of these BOOK i. useful establishments, by a moderate contribution : and if the _ CHAP - " state thinks proper to exempt the citizens from paying it, she is under no obligation to gratify strangers in this particular. But a law so just in its origin frequently degenerates into gi<)4. Abuse great abuses. There are countries where no care is taken of this ri g ht - of the highways, and where nevertheless considerable tolls ^ are exacted. A lord of a manor, who happens to possess a stripe of land terminating on a river, there establishes a toll, though he is not at a farthing's expense in keeping up the navigation of the river, and rendering it convenient. This is a manifest extortion, and an infringement of the natural rights of mankind. For the division of lands, and their be- coming private property, could never deprive any man of the right of passage, when not the least injury is done to the person through whose territory he passes. Every man in- herits this right from nature, and cannot justly be forced to purchase it. (47) But the arbitrary or customary law of nations at present tolerates this abuse, while it is not carried to such an excess as to destroy commerce. People do not, however, submit without difficulty, except in the case of those tolls which are established by ancient usage : and the imposition of new ones is often a source of disputes. The Swiss formerly made war on the Dukes of Milan, on account of some oppressions of this nature. This right of tolls is also further abused, when the passenger is obliged to contribute too much, and what bears no proportion to the expense of preserving these public passages. (48) At present, to avoid all difficulty and oppression, nations settle these points by treaties. (47) This position requires explana- 1 Burr. 292. In the absence of such tion and qualification. As respects a custom or prescription, no right to ap- public navigable river, every part of proach a river over private grounds the navigable stream must ever remain exists. Parthericke v. Mason, 2 Chitty's free and open from its communication Rep. 658 ; Wyatt v. Thompson, 1 Esp. with the sea to its extreme navigable Rep. 252. { Ohess v. Manown, 3 Watts, point; but the absolute right to ap- Rep. 219; Cooper v. Smith, 9 Serg. A proach it on each side, can only be Rawle, 26. } So, if a private individual by public and general ways. Conse- make and repair a bridge over a river, quently, if an individual have land ad- he may insist upon any person using joining a river, he may reasonably it paying him a toll, as in the instance refuse permission to any person to go of Putney and Fulham bridge. In over it to approach the river, and de- these cases the demand of an exorbi- mand any sum he thinks fit for the tant toll may be illiberal, but is no permission, unless there be a public more illegal than a nation's refusing way over it Nor have the public to sell its superfluous produce, or to any right at common law to tow on admit free passage through its country, the banks of an ancient navigable The right to pass at a moderate toll river; Ball v. Herbert, 3 Term Rep. is a moral but imperfect right, ante, 253 ; though it may exist by custom g 91. C. or prescription. Pierce v. Fauconberge, (48) See n. 47, ante. 115 45 OF MONEY AND EXCHANGE. BOOK I. CHAP. X. CHAP. X. OF MONEY AND EXCHANGE. (49) 105. Es- IN the first ages, after the introduction of private property, tabiishment p e0 pl e exchanged their superfluous commodities and effects oney ' for those they wanted. Afterwards gold and silver hecame the common standard of the value of all things : and to pre- vent the people from being cheated, the mode was introduced of stamping pieces of gold and silver in the name of the state, with the figure of the prince, or some other impression, as the seal and pledge of their value. This institution is of great use and infinite convenience : it is easy to see how much it facilitates commerce. Nations or sovereigns cannot therefore bestow too much attention on an affair of such importance, g 106. Duty The impression on the coin becoming the seal of its stand- f the nation ar( j an( j ^jgh^ a moment's reflection will convince us that withTelpect tne coinage of money ought not to be left indiscriminately to the coin, free to every individual ; for, by that means, frauds would become too common the coin would soon lose the public confidence ; and this would destroy a most useful institution. Hence money is coined by the authority and in the name of the state or prince, who are its surety ; they ought, therefore, to have a quantity of it coined sufficient to answer the neces- sities of the country, and to take care that it be good, that is to say, that its intrinsic value bear a just proportion to its extrinsic or numerary value. It is true, that, in a pressing necessity, the state would have a right to order the citizens to receive the coin at a price superior to its real value : but as foreigners will not receive it at that price, the nation gains nothing by this proceeding ; it is only a temporary palliative for the evil, without effecting a radical cure. This excess of value, added in an arbitrary manner to the coin, is a real debt which the sovereign con- tracts with individuals : and, in strict justice, this crisis of affairs being over, that money ought to be called in at the expense of the state, and paid for in other specie, according to the natural standard : otherwise, this kind of burden, laid on in the hour.f necessity, would fall solely on those who re- ceived this arbitrary money in payment, which would be unjust. Besides, experience has shown that such a resource is destruc- tive to trade, by destroying the confidence both of foreigners and citizens raising in proportion the price of every thing (49) The modern law of nations, and Id. 84 to 120 ; 1 Chitty's Commercial the municipal law of England, as to Law, 583 ; 2 Id. 179 to 187, and statutes coin, bullion, and money, will be found and decisions there collected. C. collected in 1 Bla. Com. 276 to 280; 4 116 OF MONEY AND EXCHANGE. 45 and inducing every one to lock up or send abroad the good BOOK r. old specie ; whereby a temporary stop is put to the circulation CHAP ' * of money. So that it is the duty of every nation and of every sovereign to abstain, as much as possible, from so dangerous an experiment, and rather to have recourse to extraordinary [ 46 ] taxes and contributions to support the pressing exigencies of the state.* Since the state is surety for the goodness of the money g 107. Their and its currency, the public authority alone has the right of rights in this coining it. Those who counterfeit it, violate the rights of respect, the sovereign, whether they make it of the same standard and value or not. These are called false-coiners, and their crime is justly considered as one of the most heinous nature. For if they coin base money, they rob both the public and the prince ; and if they coin good, they usurp the preroga- tive of the sovereign. They will never be inclined to coin good money unless there be a profit on the coinage : and in this case they rob the state of a profit which exclusively be- * In Boizard's Treatise on Coin, we find the following observations : " It is worthy of remark, that, when our kings debased the coin, they kept the circum- stance a secret from the people : wit- ness the ordinance of Philip de Valois in 1350, by which he ordered Tournois Doubles to be coined 2d. 5$gr. fine, which was, in fact, a debasement of the coin. In that ordinance, address- ing the officers of the mint, he says ' Upon the oath by which you are bound to the king, keep this affair as secret as you possibly can, that neither the bank- ers nor others may, by your means, ac- quire any knowledge of it ; for if, through you, it comes to be known, you shall be punished for the offence in such man- ner as shall serve as an example to others.'" The same author quotes other similar ordinances of the same king, and one issued by the Dauphin, who governed the kingdom as regent during the captivity of King John, dated June 27, 1360, by virtue of which the mint-masters, directing the officers en- gaged in the coinage to coin white Denicrs Id. 12gr. fine, at the same time expressly command them to keep this order secret, and, "if any persons should make inquiry respecting their standard, to maintain that they were 2d. fine." Chap. xxix. The kings [of France] had recourse to this strange expedient in cases of urgent necessity ; but they saw its in- justice. The same author, speaking of the debasement of coin, or the va- rious modes of reducing its intrinsic value, says "These expedients are but rarely resorted to, because they give occasion to the exportation or melting down of the good specie, and to the in- troduction and circulation of foreign coin raise the price of every thing- impoverish individuals diminish the revenue, which is paid in specie of in- ferior value and sometimes put a total stop to commerce. This truth has been so well understood in all ages, that those princes who had recourse to one or other of these modes of debasing the coin in difficult times, ceased to prac- tise it the moment the necessity ceased to exist." We have, on this subject, an ordinance of Philip the Fair, issued in May, 1295, which announces, that, "The king having reduced the coin both in fineness and weight, and ex- pecting to be obliged to make a further reduction in order to retrieve his affairs, but knowing himself to be, in con- science, responsible for the injury caused to the state by such reduction, pledges himself to the people of his kingdom, by solemn charter, that, as soon as his affairs are retrieved, he will restore the coin to its proper standard and value, at his own private cost and expense, and will himself bear all the loss and waste. And, in addition to this engagement, Dame Joan, Queen of France and Navarre, pledges her reve- nues and dower for the same purpose.* Note, edit A. D. 1797. 117 46 OF MONEY AND EXCHANGE. BOOK r. longs to it. In both cases they do an injury to the sove- CHAP ' *' reign ; for the public faith being surety for the money, the sovereign alone has a right to have it coined. For this rea- son the right of coming is placed among the prerogatives of majesty, and Bodinus relates,* that Sigismund Augustus, king of Poland, having granted this privilege to the duke of Prussia, in the year 1543, the states of the country passc>d a decree in which it was asserted that the king could not grant that privilege, it being inseparable from the crown. [ 47 ] The same author observes, that, although many lords and bishops of France had formerly the privilege of coining mo- ney, it was still considered as coined by the king's authority : and the kings of France at last withdrew all those privileges, on account of their being often abused. 108. How From the principles just laid down, it is easy to conclude, one nation that if one nation counterfeits the money of another, or if she allows and protects false-coiners who presume to do it, she does that nation an injury. But commonly criminals of this class find no protection anywhere all princes being equally interested in exterminating them. (50) g 109. Of There is another custom more modern, and of no less use exchange, to commerce than the establishment of coin, namely exchange, and the laws or tne tra ffi c O f bankers, by means of which a merchant re- merce." m ^ s i mm 6 nse sums from one end of the world to the other, at a very trifling expense, and, if he pleases, without risk. For the same reason that sovereigns are obliged to protect commerce, they are obliged to support this custom, by good laws, in which every merchant, whether citizen or foreigner, may find security. In general, it is equally the interest and the duty of every nation to have wise and equitable commer- cial laws established in the country. may injure another in the article of coin. * In his Republic, book i. chap. x. (50) This is a sound principle, which ought to be extended so as to deny ef- fect to any fraud upon a foreign nation or its subjects. But in England a nar- row and immoral policy prevails of not noticing frauds upon the revenue of a foreign state. Roach v. Edie, 6 Term Rep. 425 ; Boucher v. Lawrence, R. T. Hardw. 198 ; Holman v. Johnson, Cowp. 343; James v. Catherwood, 3 Dowl. A Ryl. 190. { Cambioso'g Ex. v. Maffet's Assignees, 2 Wash. C. C. Rep. 99.} And so far has this narrow doctrine been carried, in disgrace of this country, that, in Smith v. Marconnay, 2 Peake's Rep. 81, it was held, that the maker of paper in England, knowingly made by him for the purpose of forging assignats upon the same, to be exported to France in order to commit frauds there on other persons, might recover damages for not accepting such paper pursuant to contract. So a master of an English ship was even allowed to recover sal- vage for bringing homo his captured vessel, by deceptively inducing the ene- my to release the vessel on his giving a ransom bill, payment of which he took care to countermand in London. 2 Dod- son's R. 74. 118 A GOOD GOVERNMENT, ETC. 47 BOOK I. CHAP. XI. CHAP. XI. SECOND OBJECT OF A GOOD GOVERNMENT, TO PROCURE THE TRUE HAPPINESS OF THE NATION. LET us continue to lay open the principal objects of a good no. A n- government. What we have said in the five preceding chap- tion ou s^ ters relates to the care of providing for the necessities of the aft^teown people, and procuring plenty in the state : this is a point of happiness. necessity ; but it is not sufficient for the happiness of a na- tion. Experience shows that a people may be unhappy in the midst of all earthly enjoyments, and in the possession of the greatest riches. Whatever may enable mankind to enjoy a true and solid felicity, is a second object that deserves the most serious attention of the government. Happiness is the point where centre all those duties which individuals and na- tions owe to themselves ; and this is the great end of the law of nature. The desire of happiness is the powerful spring that puts man in motion : felicity is the end they all have in view, and it ought to be the grand object of the public will (Prelim. 5). It is then the duty of those who form this public will, or of those who represent it the rulers of the nation to labour for the happiness of the people, to watch continually over it, and to promote it to the utmost of their power. To succeed in this, it is necessary to instruct the people to ? m. in- seek felicity where it is to be found ; that is, in their own struction - perfection, and to teach them the means of obtaining it. The sovereign cannot, then, take too much pains in instruct- r 43 i ing and enlightening his people, and in forming them to use- ful knowledge and wise discipline. Let us leave a hatred of the sciences to the despotic tyrants of the east: they are afraid of having their people instructed, because they choose to rule over slaves. But though they are obeyed with the most abject submission, they frequently experience the effects of disobedience and revolt. A just and wise prince feels no apprehensions from the light of knowledge : he knows that it is ever advantageous to a good government. If men of learn- ing know that liberty is the natural inheritance of mankind ; on the other hand they are more fully sensible than their neighbours, how necessary it is, for their own advantage, that this liberty should be subject to a lawful authority: in- capable of being slaves, they are faithful subjects. The first impressions made on the mind are of the utmost g 112. Edu- importance for the remainder of Hfe. In the tender years cation of of infancy and youth, the human mind and heart easily re- youth ' ceive the seeds of good or evil. Hence the education of youth is one of the most important affairs that deserve the 119 48 SECOND OBJECT OF BOOK CHAP. XI. x - attention of the government. It ought not to be entirely left to fathers. The most certain way of forming good citi- zens is to found good establishments for public education, to provide them with able masters direct them with prudence and pursue such mild and suitable measures, that the citi- zens will not neglect to take advantage of them. How ad- mirable was the education of the Romans, in the flourishing ages of their republic, and how< admirably was it calculated to form great men ! The young men put themselves under the patronage of some illustrious person; they frequented his house, accompanied him wherever he went, and equally im- proved by his instructions and example : their very sports and amusements were exercises proper to form soldiers. The same practice prevailed at Sparta ; and this was one of the wisest institutions of the incomparable Lycurgus. That legis- lator and philosopher entered into the most minute details respecting the education of youth,* being persuaded that on that depended the prosperity and glory of his republic. 113. Arts "Who can doubt that the sovereign the whole nation m sciences. OU gj^ ^ Q encoura g e the arts and sciences ? To say nothing of the many useful inventions that strike the eye of every be- holder, literature and the polite arts enlighten the mind and soften the manners : and if study does not always inspire the love of virtue, it is because it sometimes, and even too often, unhappily meets with an incorrigibly vicious heart. The nation and its conductors ought then to protect men of learning and great artists, and to call forth talents by honours and rewards. Let the friends of barbarism declaim against the sciences and polite arts ; let us, without deigning to an- [ 49 ] swer their vain reasonings, content ourselves with appealing to experience. Let us compare England, France, Holland, and several towns of Switzerland and Germany, to the many regions that lie buried in ignorance, and see where we can find the greater number of honest men and good citizens. It would be a gross error to oppose against us the example of Sparta, and that of ancient Rome. They, it is true, neglected curious speculations, and those .branches of knowledge and art that were purely subservient to pleasure and amusement ; but the solid and practical sciences morality, jurisprudence, politics, and war were cultivated by them, especially by the Romans, with a degree of attention superior to what we be- stow upon them. In the present age, the utility of literature and the polite arts is pretty generally acknowledged, as is likewise the neces- sity of encouraging them. The immortal Peter I. thought that without their assistance he could not entirely civilize Russia, and render it flourishing. In England, learning and abilities lead to honour and riches. Newton was honoured, * See Xenophon, Lacedcemon. RespuUica. 120 A GOOD GOVERNMENT, ETC. 49 protected, and rewarded while living, and after his death, his BOOK * tomb was placed among those of kings. France also, in this CHAP - " respect, deserves particular praise ; to the munificence of her kings she is indebted for several establishments that are no less useful than glorious. The Royal Academy of Sciences diffuses on every side the light of knowledge and the desire of instruction. Louis XV. furnished the means of sending to search, under the equator and the polar circle, for the proof of an important truth ; and we at present know what was be- fore only believed on the strength of Newton's calculations. Happy will that kingdom be, if the too general taste of the age does not make the people neglect solid knowledge, to give themselves up to that which is merely amusing, and if those who fear the light do not succeed in extinguishing the blaze of science ! I speak of the freedom of philosophical discussion, which g 114. Free- is the soul of the republic of letters. What can genius pro- dom of phi- duce, when trammelled by fear ? Can the greatest man that ^ s P hl _ cal ever lived contribute much towards enlightening the minds of his fellow-citizens, if he finds himself constantly exposed to the cavils of captious and ignorant bigots if he is obliged to be continually on his guard, to avoid being accused by innu- endo-mongers of indirectly attacking the received opinions ? I know that liberty has its proper bounds that a wise govern- ment ought to have an eye to the press, and not to allow the publication of scandalous productions, which attack morality, government, or the established religion. But yet, great care should be taken not to extinguish a light that may afford the state the most valuable advantages. Few men know how to keep a just medium ; and the office of literary censor ought to be intrusted to none but those who are at once both prudent and enlightened. Why should they search in a book for what the author does not appear to have intended to put into it? And when a writer's thoughts and discourses are wholly em- [ 50 ] ployed on philosophy, ought a malicious adversary to be list- ened to, who would set him at variance with religion ? So far from disturbing a philosopher on account of his opinions, the magistrate ought to chastise those who publicly charge him with impiety, when in his Avritings he shows respect to the religion of the state. The Romans seem to have been formed to give examples to the universe. That wise people carefully supported the worship and religious ceremonies established by law, and left the field open to the speculations of philosophers. Ciceroa senator, aconsul, an augur ridicules superstition, attacks it, and demolishes it in his philosophical writings ; and, in so doing, he thought he was only promoting his own hap- piness and that of his fellow-citizens : but he observes that "to destroy superstition is not destroying religion ; for," says he, 'Jit becomes a wise man to respect the institutions and religious ceremonies of his ancestors : and it is sufficient to 16 L 121 SECOND OBJECT OF contemplate the beauty of the world, and the admirable order e ce i es t;i a ]i bodies, in order to be convinced of the exist- ence of an eternal and all-perfect being, who is entitled to the veneration of the human race."* And in his Dialogues on the Nature of the Gods, he introduces Cotta the academic, who was high-priest, attacking with great freedom the opinions of the stoics, and declaring that he should always be ready to defend the established religion^ from which he saw the republic had derived great advantages ; that neither the learned nor the ignorant should make him abandon it : he then says to his adversary, " These are my thoughts, both as pontiff and as Cotta. But do you, as a philosopher, bring me over to your opinion by the strength of your arguments : for a philosopher ought to prove to me the truth of the religion he would have me embrace, whereas I ought in this respect to believe our forefathers, even without proof, "f Let us add experience to these examples and authorities. Never did a philosopher occasion disturbances in the state, or in religion, by his opinions : they would make no noise among the people, nor ever offend the weak, if malice or in- temperate zeal did not take pains to discover a pretended venom lurking in them. It is by him who endeavours to place [ 51 ] the opinions of a great man in opposition to the doctrines and worship established by law, that the state is disturbed, and religion brought into danger. g 115. Lore To instruct the nation is not sufficient : in order to conduct of virtue, ft to happiness, it is still more necessary to inspire the people rence of"*" w ^ * ne l ve f virtue, and the abhorrence of vice. Those vice, to be wno are deeply versed in the study of morality are convinced excited. that virtue is the true and only path that leads to happiness ; so that its maxims are but the art of living happily; and he must be very ignorant of politics, who does not perceive how much more capable a virtuous nation will be, than any other, of forming a state that shall be at once happy, tranquil, flourishing, solid, respected by its neighbours, and formidable to its enemies. The interest of the prince must then concur * Nam, ut vere loquamur, superstitio fusa per gentes oppressit omnium fere animos, atque omnium imbecillitatom occupavit. . . . multum enim et nobismet ipsis ct nostris profuturi videbamur, si earn funditus sustulissemus. Nee vero (id enim diligenter intelligi volo) su- peretitione tollenda religio tollitur. Nam et majorum institute tueri, sacris caoremoniisquo rctinendis, sapientis est: et esse praestantem aliquam acternamque naturam, et earn suspiciendam, admi- randamque hominum generi,pulchritudo mundi, ordoque coelestium cogit confi- teri. De Divinatione, lib. li. 122 f Harum ego rcligionem imllam un- quam contemnendam putavi : mihique ita persuasi, Romulum auspiciis, Nu- mam sacris constitutis, fundamenta jecisse nostrae civi profecto sine sum rum immortalium t sentiat. Fae nui quid tu sentias: a is, quae nunquam placatione Deo- .11 esse potuisset. Habes, Balbe, quid otta, quid pontifex ego intelligam, e enim philosopho rationem accipere debeo religionis ; ma- joribus autem nostris, etiam nulla ra- tione reddita, credere. De Natura Deo- rum, lib. iii. A GOOD GOVERNMENT, ETC. 51 with his duty and the dictates of his conscience, in engaging BOOK him to watch attentively over an affair of such importance. CHAP ' "' Let him employ all his authority in order to encourage virtue, and suppress vice : let the public establishments be all directed to this end : let his own conduct, his example, and the distri- bution of favours, posts, and dignities, all have the same ten- dency. Let him extend his attention even to the private life of the citizens, and banish from the state whatever is only calculated to corrupt the manners of the people. It belongs to politics to teach him in detail the different means of attain- ing this desirable end to show him those he should prefer, and those he ought to avoid, on account of the dangers that might attend the execution, and the abuses that might be made of them. We shall here only observe, in general, that vice may be suppressed by chastisements, but that mild and gentle methods alone can elevate men to the dignity of virtue ; it may be inspired, but it cannot be commanded. It is an incontestable truth, that the virtues of the citizens ? 116. The constitute the most happy dispositions that can be desired by natlon ma 7 a just and wise government. Here then is an infallible cr i- C overthe terion, by which the nation may judge of the intentions of intention of those who govern it. If they endeavour to render the great its rulers. and the common people virtuous, their views are pure and upright ; and you may rest assured that they solely aim at the great end of government the happiness and glory of the nation. But if they corrupt the morals of the people, spread a taste for luxury, effeminacy, a rage for licentious pleasures if they stimulate the higher orders to a ruinous pomp and extravagance beware, citizens ! beware of those corruptors ! they only aim at purchasing slaves in order to exercise over them an arbitrary sway. If a prince has the smallest share of moderation, he will never have recourse to these odious methods. Satisfied with his superior station and the power given him by the laws, he proposes to reign with glory and safety ; he loves his people, and desires to render them happy. But his ministers are in general impatient of resistance, and cannot brook the slightest opposition : if he surrenders to them his authority, they are [ 52 ] more haughty and intractable than their master : they feel not for his people the same love that he feels: "let the na- tion be corrupted (say they) provided it do but obey." They dread the courage and firmness inspired by virtue, and know that the distributor of favours rules as he pleases over men whose hearts are accessible to avarice. Thus a wretch who exercises the most infamous of all professions, perverts the inclinations of a young victim of her odious traffic ; she prompts her to luxury and epicurism ; she inspires her with voluptuousness and vanity, in order the more certainly to betray her to a rich seducer. This base and unworthy crea- ture is sometimes chastised by the magistrate ; but the minis- 123 52 SECOND OBJECT OF BOOK i. ter, who is infinitely more guilty, wallows in wealth, and is CHAP. xi. j nveg ^ e( j w ^h nonour and authority. Posterity, however, will do him justice, and detest the corruptor of a respectable nation. 117. The If governors endeavoured to fulfil the obligations which the state, or the j aw Q f na t ure i a ys upon them with respect to themselves, and g" n , ^ught" i n tne "* character of conductors of the state, they would be to perfect incapable of ever giving into the odious abuse just mentioned. its under- Hitherto we have considered the obligation a nation is under standing ^ Q ac q u j re knowledge and virtue, or to perfect its understand- ing and will ; that obligation, I say, we have considered in re- lation to the individuals that compose a nation ; it also belongs in a proper and singular manner to the conductors of the state. A nation, while she acts in common, or in a body, is a moral person (Prelim. 2) that has an understanding and will of her own, and is not less obliged than any individual to obey the laws of nature (Book I. 5), and to improve her faculties (Book I. 21). That moral person resides in those who are invested with the public authority, and represent the entire nation. Whether this be the common council of the nation, an aristocratic body, or a monarch, this conductor and repre- sentative of the nation, this sovereign, of whatever kind, is therefore indispensably obliged to procure all the knowledge and information necessary to govern well, and to acquire the practice and habit of all the virtues suitable to a sovereign. And as this obligation is imposed with a view to the public welfare, he ought to direct all his knowledge, and all his vir- tues, to the safety of the state, the end of evil society, g us. And He ought even to direct, as much as possible, all the abili- to direct the ties, the knowledge, and the virtues of the citizens to this andtirtSs S reat 6I1 ^ ' S that ^^ ma> ? n0t ^ ^ USe ^ to tne ^~ of the citu viduals who possess them, but also to the state. This is one zens to the of the great secrets in the art of reigning. The state will be welfare of powerful and happy, if the good qualities of the subject, pass- tie 8ociet y- ing beyond the narrow sphere of private virtues, become civic virtues. This happy disposition raised the Roman republic to the highest pitch of power and glory. 119. Love The grand secret of giving to the virtues of individuals a for their urn so advantageous to the state, is to inspire the citizens mtry. ^^ an ar( j en |. j ove f or their country. It will then naturally [ 53 ] follow, that each will endeavour to serve the state, and to apply all his powers and abilities to the advantage and glory of the nation. This love of their country is natural to all men. The good and wise Author of nature has taken care to bind them, by a kind of instinct, to the places where they received their first breath, and they love their own nation, as a thing with which they are intimately connected. But it often happens that some causes unhappily weaken or destroy this natural impression. The injustice or the severity of the government too easily effaces it from the hearts of the sub- jects ; can self-love attach an individual to the affairs of a 124 A GOOD GOVERNMENT, ETC. 53 country where every thing is done with a view to a single per- BOOK i. son ? far from it : we see, on the contrary, that free nations CHAP - xr " are passionately interested in the glory and the happiness of their country. Let us call to mind the citizens of Rome in the happy days of the republic, and consider, in modern times, the English and the Swiss. The love and affection a man feels for the state of which 120. in he is a member, is a necessary consequence of the wise and individuals, rational love he owes to himself, since his own happiness is connected with that of his country. This sensation ought also to flow from the engagements he has entered into with society. He has promised to procure its safety and advan- tage as far as in his power : and how can he serve it with zeal, fidelity, or courage, if he has not a real love for it ? The nation in a body ought doubtless to love itself, and desire 121. in its own happiness as a nation. The sensation is too natural the nation to admit of any failure in this obligation : but this duty relates r state it- i -i i ii i , . i v self, and in more particularly to the conductor, the sovereign, who repre- the goye _ sents the nation, and acts in its name. He ought to love it re i g n. as what is most dear to him, to prefer it to every thing, for it is the only lawful object of his care, and of his actions, in every thing he does by virtue of the public authority. The monster who does not love his people is no better than an odious usurper, and deserves, no doubt, to be hurled from the throne. There is no kingdom where the statue of Codrus ought not to be placed before the palace of the sovereign. That magnanimous king of Athens sacrificed his life for his people.* That great prince and Louis XII. are illustrious models of the tender love a sovereign owes to his subjects. The term, Country, seems to be pretty generally known : g 122. DO- but as it is taken in different senses, it may not be unuseful finition of to give it here an exact definition. It commonly signifies the the term State of which one is a member : in this sense 1 we have used country - it in the preceding sections ; and it is to be thus understood [ 54 ] in the law of nations. In a more confined sense, and more agreeably to its ety- mology, this term signifies the state, or even more particularly the town or place where our parents had their fixed residence at the moment of our birth. In this sense, it is justly said, that our country cannot be changed, and always remains the same, to whatsoever place we may afterwards remove. A man ought to preserve gratitude and affection for the state to which he is indebted for his education, and of which his parents were members when they gave him birth. But as various lawful reasons may oblige him to choose another coun- try, that is, to become a member of another society; so, * His country being attacked by the should remain victorious, Codrus dis- Heraclidse, he consulted the oracle of guised himself, and, rushing into the Apollo ; and being answered, that the battle, was killed by one of the enemy's people whose chief should be slain soldiers. L2 125 OBJECT OF A GOOD GOVERNMENT. shameful and crimi- nal to in- jure our country. 124. The glory of good citi- zens. (51) Examples. BOOK i. when we speak in general of the duty to our country, the CHAP, xi. term is to be understood as meaning the state of which a man is an actual member ; since it is the latter, in preference to every other state, that he is bound to serve with his utmost efforts. \ 123. How If every man is obliged to entertain a sincere love for his country, and to promote its welfare as far as in his power, it is a shameful and detestable crime to injure that very country. He who becomes guilty of it, violates his most sacred en- gagements, and sinks into base ingratitude : he dishonours himself by the blackest perfidy, since he abuses the confidence of his fellow-citizens, and treats as enemies those who had a right to expect his assistance and services. We see traitors to their country only among those men who are solely sensi- ble to base interest, who only seek their own immediate ad- vantage, and whose hearts are incapable of every sentiment of affection for others. They are, therefore, justly detested by mankind in general, as the most infamous of all villains. On the contrary, those generous citizens are loaded with honour and praise, who, not content with barely avoiding a failure in duty to their country, make noble efforts in her favour, and are capable of making her the greatest sacrifices. The names of Brutus, Curtius, and the two Decii, will live as long as that of Rome. The Swiss will never forget Ar- nold de Winkelried, that hero, whose exploit would have deserved to be transmitted to posterity by the pen of a Livy. He truly devoted his life for his country's sake : but he de- voted it as a general, as an undaunted warrior, not as a su- perstitious visionary. That nobleman, who was of the country of Underwald, seeing, at the battle of Sempach, that his countrymen could not break through the Austrians, because the latter, armed cap-a-pie, had dismounted, and, forming a close battalion, presented a front covered with steel, and bristling with pikes and lances, formed the generous design of sacrificing himself for his country. "My friends," said he to the Swiss, who began to be dispirited, " I will this day give my life to procure you the victory : I only recommend to you ray family : follow me, and act in consequence of what [ 55 ] you see me do." At these words he ranged them in that form which the Romans called cuncus, and placing himself in the point of the triangle, marched to the centre of the enemy ; when, embracing between his arms as many of the enemy's pikes as he could compass, he threw himself to the ground, thus opening for his followers a passage to penetrate into the midst of this thick battalion. The Austrians, once broken, were conquered, as the weight of their armour then became fatal to them, and the Swiss obtained a complete victory.* (51) See observations, poet, $ 190, 1386. The Austrian army consisted p. 92. C. of four thousand chosen men, among * This affair happened in the year whom were a great number of princes, 126 OF PIETY AND RELIGION. 55 BOOK I. CHAP. XII. CHAP. XII. OF PIETY AND RELIGION. PIETY and religion have an essential influence on the 125. Of happiness of a nation, and, from their importance, deserve a piety, particular chapter. Nothing is so proper as piety to strength- en virtue, and give it its due extent. By the word Piety, I mean a disposition of soul that leads us to direct all our actions towards the Deity, and to endeavour to please him in every thing we do. To the practice of this virtue all mankind are indispensably obliged : it is the purest source of their felicity ; and those who unite in civil society are under still greater obligations to practise it. A nation ought then to be pious. The superiors intrusted with the public affairs should constantly endeavour to deserve the approba- tion of their divine Master ; and whatever they do in the name of the state, ought to be regulated by this grand view. The care of forming pious dispositions in all the people should be constantly one of the principal objects of their vigilance, and from this the state will derive very great advantages. A serious attention to merit, in all our actions, the approbation of an infinitely wise Being, cannot fail of producing excellent citizens. Enlightened piety in the people is the firmest sup- port of a lawful authority ; and, in the sovereign's heart, it is the pledge of the people's safety, and excites their confi- dence. Ye lords of the earth, who acknowledge no superior here below, what security can we have for the purity of your intentions, if we do not conceive you to be deeply impressed with respect for the common Father and Lord of men, and animated with a desire to please him ? We have already insinuated that piety ought to be at- 126. It tended with knowledge. In vain would we propose to please ou g ht to be God, if we know not the means of doing it. But what a al *? n ? ed ., i , ,, ,. , with know- deluge of evils arises, when men, heated by so powerful a ledge motive, are prompted to take methods that are equally false [ 56 ] and pernicious ! A blind piety only produces superstitious bigots, fanatics, and persecutors, a thousand times more dan- gerous and destructive to society than libertines are. There have appeared barbarous tyrants who have talked of nothing but the glory of God, while they crushed the people, and counts, and nobility of distinguished noblemen of the best families in Ger- rank, all armed from head to foot. many. History of the Helvetic Con- The Swiss were no more than thirteen federacy, by DE WATTEVJLLE, vol. i. p. hundred men, ill armed. In this battle, 183. TSCHUDI. ETTERLIN. SCHODE- the duke of Austria perished, with two LER. K.t: B.MAX. [See the national thousand of his forces, in which num- consequences of this valour, stated post, ber were six hundred and seventy-six 190, pp. 92-3.] 127 56 OF PIETY AND RELIGION. BOOK i. trampled under foot the most sacred laws of nature. It was CHAP, xii. f rom a refinement of piety, that the anabaptists of the six- teenth century refused all obedience to the powers of the earth. James Clement and Ravaillac,* those execrable par- ricides, thought themselves animated by the most sublime devotion. 127. Of Religion consists in the doctrines concerning the Deity and religion in- ^ e things of another life, and in the worship appointed to externaT *k e honour of the Supreme Being. So far as it is seated in the heart, it is an affair of conscience, in which every one ought to be directed by his own understanding : but so far as it is external, and publicly established, it is an affair of state. g 128. Every man is obliged to endeavour to obtain just ideas of Rights of God, to know his laws, his views with respect to his crea- individuals. turegj an( j the en( j f()r w kj ch they were create( J. M an (Joubt- leSS owes the most pure love, the most profound respect to his Creator; and to keep alive these dispositions, and act in consequence of them, he should honour God in all his actions, and show, by the most suitable means, the sentiments that fill Liberty of his mind. This short explanation is sufficient to prove that conscience. man } s essentially and necessarily free to make use of his own choice in matters of religion. His belief is not to be commanded ; and what kind of worship must that be which is produced by force ? Worship consists in certain actions performed with an immediate view to the honour of God ; there can be no worship proper for any man, which he does not believe suitable to that end. The obligation of sincerely endeavouring to know God, of serving him, and adoring him from the bottom of the heart, being imposed on man by his very nature, it is impossible that, by his engagements with society, he should have exonerated himself from that duty, or deprived himself of the liberty which is absolutely neces- sary for the performance of it. It must then be concluded, that liberty of conscience is a natural and inviolable right. It is a disgrace to human nature, that a truth of this kind should stand in need of proof. 129. Pub- But we should take care not to extend this liberty beyond lie establish- jt s j us t bounds. In religious affairs a citizen has only a "8 nt to ke free from compulsion, but can by no means claim that of openly doing what he pleases, without regard to the [ 57 ] consequences it may produce on society. (52) The establish- ment of religion by law, and its public exercise, are matters of state, and are necessarily under the jurisdiction of the * The former assassinated Henry III. to have been an impostor, and a mur- of France ; the latter murdered his sue- derer in principle, and a fanatic, is an cessor, Henry IV. indictable misdemeanor at common law. (52) AVith respect to these in Eng- Rex v. Waddington, 1 Barn. & Cress. 26. land, and punishments for the viola- And as to modern regulation, see 4 Bla. tion, see 4 Bla. Com. 41 to 66. Bias- Com. 443. C. phemy, or a libel, stating our Saviour 128 OF PIETY AND RELIGION. 5 political authority. If all men are bound to serve God, the BOOK ] entire nation, in her national capacity, is doubtless obliged to serve and honour him (Prelim. 5). And as this important duty is to be discharged by the nation in whatever manner nation . she judges best, to the nation it belongs to determine what religion she will follow, and what public worship she thinks proper to establish. If there be as yet no religion established by public autho- $ 130. when rity, the nation ought to use the utmost care, in order to there is as know and establish the best. That which shall have the ap- y e * no esta - probation of the majority shall be received, and publicly esta- JJj d r< Wished by law ; by which means it will become the religion of the state. But if a considerable part of the nation is ob- stinately bent upon following another, it is asked What does the law of nations require in such a case ? Let us first re- member that liberty of conscience is a natural right, and that there must be no constraint in this respect. There remain then but two methods to take, either to permit this party of the citizens to exercise the religion they choose to profess, or to separate them from the society, leaving them their property, and their share of the country that belonged to the nation in common, and thus to form two new states instead of one. The latter method appears by no -means proper : it would weaken the nation, and thus would be inconsistent with that regard which she owes to her own preservation. It is therefore of more advantage to adopt the former method, and thus to establish two religions in the state. But if these re- ligions are too incompatible ; if there be reason to fear that they will produce divisions among the citizens, and disorder in public affairs, there is a third method, a wise medium be- tween the two former, of which the Swiss have furnished ex- amples. The cantons of Glaris and Appenzel were, in the sixteenth century, each divided into two parts : the one pre- served the Romish religion, and the other embraced the Refor- mation ; each part has a distinct government of its own for domestic affairs ; but on foreign affairs they unite, and form but one and the same republic, one and the same canton. Finally, if the number of citizens who would profess a dif- ferent religion from that established by the nation be incon- siderable ; and if, for good and just reasons, it be thought improper to allow the exercise of several religions in the state those citizens have a right to sell their lands, to retire with * their families, and take all their property with them. For their engagements to society, and their submission to the public authority, can never oblige them to violate their con- sciences. If the society will not allow me to do that to which I think myself bound by an indispensable obligation, it is obliged to allow me permission to depart. When the choice of a religion is already made, and there is ? 131. When one established by law, the nation ought to protect and sup- there * M 17 129 58 OF PIETY AND RELIGION. BOOK CHAP. T - port that religion, and preserve it as an establishment of the y- greatest importance, without, however, blindly rejecting the religion. changes that may be proposed to render it more pure and useful : for we ought, in all things, to aim at perfection ( 21). But as all innovations, in this case, are full of danger, and can seldom be produced without disturbances, they ought not to be attempted upon slight grounds, without necessity, or very important reasons. It solely belongs to the society, the state, the entire nation, to determine the necessity or propriety of those changes ; and no private individual has a right to attempt them by his own authority, nor consequently to preach to the people a new doctrine. Let him offer his sentiments to the conductors of the nation, and submit to the orders he re- ceives from them. But if a new religion spreads, and becomes fixed in the minds of the people, as it commonly happens, independently of the public authority, and without any deliberation in com- mon, it will be then necessary to adopt the mode of reasoning we followed in the preceding section on the case of choosing a religion ; to pay attention to the number of those who follow the new opinions to remember that no earthly power has authority over the consciences of men, and to unite the maxims of sound policy with those of justice and equity. $ 132. Du- We have thus given a brief compendium of the duties and ties and rights of a nation with regard to religion. Let us now come sovereign & * * nose f tne sovereign. These cannot be exactly the same with regard as those of the nation which the sovereign represents. The to religion, nature of the subject opposes it ; for in religion nobody can give up his liberty. To give a clear and distinct view of those rights and duties of the prince, and to establish them on a solid basis, it is necessary here to refer to the distinction we have made in the two preceding sections : if there is question of establishing a religion in a state that has not yet received one, the sovereign may doubtless favour that which to him appears the true or the best religion, may have it announced to the people, and, by mild and suitable means, endeavour to establish it : he is even bound to do this, because he is obliged to attend to every thing that concerns the happiness of the nation. But in this he has no right to use authority and constraint. Since there was no religion established in the society when he received his authority, the people gave him no power in this respect ; the support of the laAvs relating to religion is no part of his office, and does not belong to the au- thority with which they intrusted him. Numa was the founder of the religion of the ancient Romans : but he persuaded the people to receive it. If he had been able to command in that instance, he would not have had recourse to the revelations of the nymph Egeria. Though the sovereign cannot exert any authority in order to establish a religion where there is none, he is authorized, and even obliged, to employ all his 130 OP PIETY AND RELIGION. 59 power to hinder the introduction of one which he judges per- BOOK i. nicious to morality and dangerous to the state. For he ought CHAP - xn - to preserve his people from every thing that may be injurious to them ; and so far is a new doctrine from being an excep- tion to this rule, that it is one of its most important objects. We shall see, in the following sections, what are the duties and rights of the prince in regard to the religion publicly es- tablished. The prince, or the conductor, to whom the nation has in- g 133. trusted the care of the government and the exercise of the wh ere sovereign power, is obliged to watch over the preservation of ther * s , a , i T i i i_v i j i j i_ established the received religion, the worship established by law, and has religion . a right to restrain those who attempt to destroy or disturb it. But to acquit himself of this duty in a manner equally just and wise, he ought never to lose sight of the character in which he is called to act, and the reason of his being invested with it. Religion is of extreme importance to the peace and welfare of society ; and the prince is obliged to have an eye to every thing in which the state is interested. This is all that calls him to interfere in religion, or to protect and defend it. It is therefore upon this footing only that he can inter- fere : consequently, he ought to exert his authority against those alone whose conduct in religious matters is prejudicial or dangerous to the state ; but he must not extend it to pre- tended crimes against God, the punishment of which exclu- sively belongs to the Sovereign Judge, the searcher of hearts. Let us remember that religion is no farther an affair of state, than as it is exterior and publicly established : that of the heart can only depend on the conscience. The prince has no right to punish any persons but those that disturb society; and it would be very unjust in him to inflict pains and penal- ties on any person whatsoever for his private opinions, when that person neither takes pains to divulge them, nor to obtain followers. It is a principle of fanaticism, a source of evils and of the most notorious injustice, to imagine that frail mor- tals ought to take up the cause of God, maintain his glory by acts of violence, and avenge him on his enemies. Let us only give to sovereigns, said a great statesman and an excellent citizen* let us give them, for the common advantage, the power of punishing whatever is injurious to charity in so- ciety. It appertains not to human justice to become the aven- ger of what concerns the cause of Gf-od.'f Cicero, who was as * able and as great in state affairs as in philosophy and elo- quence, thought like the Duke of Sully. In the laws he pro- poses relating to religion, he says, on the subject of piety and interior religion, " if any one transgresses, God will re- venge it:" but he declares the crime capital that should be * The Duke de Sully ; see his Me- f Deorum injuriae diis curse. Tacit. moirs digested by M. de 1'Ecluse, vol. v. Ann. book i. c. 73. pp. 135, 136. 131 5y OF PIETY AND KELIGION. BOOK i. committed against the religious ceremonies established for pub CHAP. xii. jj c a g- a j rg? an( j j n w hj c h the whole state is concerned.* The [ 60 ] wise Romans were very far from persecuting a man for his creed ; they only required that people should not disturb the public order. 134. Ob- The creeds or opinions of individuals, their sentiments with jects of his respect to the Deity, in a word, interior religion should, ^e^^n like piety, be the object of the^ prince's attention: he should he ought to neglect no means of enabling his subjects to discover the truth, employ. and of inspiring them with good sentiments ; but he should employ for this purpose only mild and paternal methods."!* Here he cannot command ( 128). It is in external religion and its public exercise that his authority may be employed. His task is to preserve it, and to prevent the disorders and troubles it may occasion. To preserve religion, he ought to maintain it in the purity of its institution, to take care that it be faithfully observed in all its public acts and ceremonies, and punish those who dare to attack it openly. But he can require nothing by force except silence, and ought never to oblige any person to bear a part in external ceremonies : by constraint, he would only produce disturbances or hypocrisy. A diversity of opinions and worship has often produced disorders and fatal dissensions in a state : and for this rea- son, many will allow but one and the same religion. A pru- dent and equitable sovereign will, in particular conjunctures, see whether it be proper to tolerate or forbid the exercise of several different kinds of worship. 135. Of But, in general, we may boldly affirm that the most cer- toieration. tain and equitable means of preventing the disorders that may ( 53 ) be occasioned by difference of religion, is a universal tolera- tion of all religions which contain no tenets that are danger- ous either to morality or to the state. Let interested priests declaim ! they would not trample under foot the laws of hu- manity, and those of God himself, to make their doctrine triumph, if it were not the foundation on which are erected their opulence, luxury, and power. Do but crush the spirit of persecution, punish severely whoever shall dare to dis- turb others on account of their creed, and you will see all sects living in peace in their common country, and ambitious of producing good citizens. Holland, and the states of the King of Prussia, furnish a proof of this: Calvinists, Lutherans, Catholics, Pietists, Socinians, Jews, all live there in peace, because they are equally protected by the sovereign ; and none are punished, but the disturbers of the tranquillity of others. * Qui secus faxit, Deus ipse vindex gib. lib. i. What a fine lesson does erit Qui non paruerit, capitale this pagan philosopher give to Chris- esto. De Legib. lib. ii. tians ! f Quas (religiones) non metu, sed (53) See the modern enactments, 4 ea conjunctione quae est homini cum Bla. Com. 440, 443 ; Id. 52, 53, in the Deo, conservandas puto. Cicero de Le- notes. C. 132 OF PIETY AND RELIGION. 60 If, in spite of the prince's care to preserve the established BOOK i. religion, the entire nation, or the greater part of it, should CHAP ' XI1 ' be disgusted with it, and desire to have it changed, the sove-? 136 - What reign cannot do violence to his people, nor constrain them in oughttodo an affair of this nature. The public religion was established w hen the for the safety and advantage of the nation : and, besides its nation is re- proving inefficacious when it ceases to influence the heart, the s lved to sovereign has here no other authority than that which results from the trust reposed in him by the people, and they have only committed to him that of protecting whatever religion [ 61 they think proper to profess. But at the same time it is very just that the prince should 2 137. have the liberty of continuing in the profession of his own fe ' ence religion, without losing his crown. Provided that he protect the religion of the state, this is all that can be required of a prince of him. In general, a difference of religion can never make tis crown, any prince forfeit his claims to the sovereignty, unless a fun- damental law ordain it otherwise. The pagan Romans did not cease to obey Constantine when he embraced Christian- ity ; nor did the Christians revolt from Julian after he had quitted it.* We have established liberty of conscience for individuals 138. Da- ( 128). However, we have also shown that the sovereign t ! ei ? and , x , >. , , .' , ,,. G , rights of the has a right, and is even under an obligation, to protect and S0 v er eign support the religion of the state, and not suffer any person reconciled to attempt to corrupt or destroy it, that he may even, ac- with those cording to circumstances, permit only one kind of public ? f the sub " worship throughout the whole country. Let us reconcile je those different duties and rights, between which it may be thought that there is some contradiction : let us, if possible, omit no material argument on so important and delicate a subject. If the sovereign will allow the public exercise of only one and the same religion, let him oblige nobody to do any thing contrary to his conscience ; let no subject be forced to bear a part in a worship which he disapproves, or to profess a reli- gion which he believes to be false ; but let the subject on his part rest content with avoiding the guilt of a shameful hypocrisy; let him, according to the light of his own know- ledge, serve God in private and in his own house persuaded that Providence does not call upon him for public worship, since it has placed him in such circumstances that he cannot perform it without creating disturbances in the state. God would have us obey our sovereign, and avoid every thing that * When the chief part of the people nevertheless still retained all her rights. in the principality of Neufchatel and The state counsel enacted ecclesiastical Vallangin embraced the reformed re- laws and constitutions similar to those ligion in the sixteenth century, Joan of of the reformed churches in Switzerland, Hochberg, their sovereign, continued to and the princess gave them her sane- live in the Roman Catholic faith, and tion. M 133 61 OF PIETY AND RELIGION. c^p K xn ma y k e pernicious to society. These are immutable precepts CHAP. xii. ^ t ^ e j aw O f na t ure . th e precept that enjoins public wor- ship is conditional, and dependent on the effects which that worship may produce. Interior worship is necessary in its own nature ; and we ought to confine ourselves to it, in all cases in which it is most convenient. Public worship is ap- pointed for the edification of men in glorifying God : but it counteracts that end, and ceases to be laudable, on those oc- [ 62 ] casions when it only produces disturbances, and gives offence. If any one believes it absolutely necessary, let him quit the country where he is not allowed to perform it according to the dictates of his own conscience ; let him go and join those who profess the same religion with himself. g 139. The The prodigious influence of religion on the peace and wel- fare of society incontrovertibly proves that the conductor of have the in- * ne state ought to have the inspection of what relates to it, spection of and an authority over the ministers who teach it. The end the affairs O f society and of civil government necessarily requires that of f ellg ! on ' he who exercises the supreme power should be invested with rUy over a ^ the rights without which he could not exercise it in a those who manner the most advantageous to the state. These are the teach it prerogatives of majesty ( 45), of which no sovereign can di- vest himself, without the express consent of the nation. The inspection of the affairs of religion, and the authority over its ministers, constitute, therefore, one of the most important of those prerogatives, since, without this power, the sovereign would never be able to prevent the disturbances that religion might occasion in the state, nor to employ that powerful en- gine in promoting the welfare and safety of the society. It would be certainly very strange that a multitude of men who united themselves in society for their common advantage, that each might, in tranquillity, labour to supply his necessi- ties, promote his own perfection and happiness, and live as becomes a rational being : it would be very strange, I say, that such a society should not have a right to follow their own judgment in an affair of the utmost importance ; to de- termine what they think most suitable with regard to religion ; and to take care that nothing dangerous or hurtful be mixed with it. Who shall dare to dispute that an independent na- tion has, in this respect as in all others, a right to proceed according to the light of conscience ? and when once she has made choice of a particular religion and worship, may she not confer on her conductor all the power she possesses of regu- lating and directing that religion and worship, and enforcing their observance ? Let us not be told that the management of sacred things belongs not to a profane hand. Such discourses, when brought to the bar of reason, are found to be only vain declamations. There is nothing on earth more august and sacred than a sove- reign ; and why should God, who calls him by his providence OF PIETY AND RELIGION. t>2 to watch over the safety and happiness of a whole nation, de- c * K n prive him of the direction of the most powerful spring that actuates mankind ? The law of nature secures to him this right, with all others that are essential to good government ; and nothing is to be found in Scripture that changes this dis- position. Among the Jews, neither the king nor any other person could make any innovation in the law of Moses ; hut the sovereign attended to its preservation, and could check the high priest when he deviated from his duty. Where is it asserted in the New Testament, that a Christian prince has nothing to do with religious affairs? Submission and obe- dience to the superior powers are there clearly and expressly enjoined. It were in vain to object to us the example of the [ 63 ] apostles, who preached the gospel in opposition to the will of sovereigns : whoever would deviate from the ordinary rules, must have a divine mission, and establish his authority by miracles. No person can dispute that the sovereign has a right to take care that nothing contrary to the welfare and safety of the state be introduced into religion ; and, consequently, he must have a right to examine its doctrines, and to point out what is to be taught, and what is to be suppressed in silence. The sovereign ought, likewise, to watch attentively, in order 2 14 ^- ^ to prevent the established religion from being employed to ^entth9 sinister purposes, either by making use of its discipline to a b us e of tb gratify hatred, avarice, or other passions, or presenting its received re- doctrines in a light that may prove prejudicial to the state. Of wild reveries, seraphic devotions, and sublime speculations, what would be the consequences to society, if it entirely con- sisted of individuals whose intellects were weak, and whose hearts were easily governed ? the consequences would be a renunciation of the world, a general neglect of business and of honest labour. This society of pretended saints would become an easy and certain prey to the first ambitious neigh- bour ; or if suffered to live in peace, it would not survive the first generation ; both sexes, consecrating their chastity to God, would refuse to co-operate in the designs of their Crea- tor, and to comply with the requisitions of nature and of the state. Unluckily for the missionaries, it evidently appears, even from Father Charlevoix' History of New France, that their labours were the principal cause of the ruin of the Hu- rons. That author expressly says, that a great number of those converts would think of nothing but the faith that they forgot their activity and valour that divisions arose between them and the rest of the nation, &c. That nation was, there- fore, soon destroyed by the Iroquois, whom they had before been accustomed to conquer.* To the prince's inspection of the affairs and concerns of * History of New France, books v. vi. viL 135 63 OF PIETY AND RELIGION. BOOK i. religion we have joined an authority over its ministers : with- ^^^ out the latter power, the former would be nugatory and inef- 41. The f ec t ua j . they are both derived from the same principle. It authority " * s absurd, and contrary to the first foundations of society, over the mi- that any citizens should claim an independence of the sove- nisters of reign authority, in offices of such importance to the repose, religion. ^ b. a ppi nes s, and safety of the state. This is establishing two independent powers in tlje same society an unfailing source of division, disturbance, and ruin. There is but one supreme power in the state ; the functions of the subordinate powers vary according to their different objects : ecclesias- tics, magistrates, and commanders of the troops, are all [ 64 ] officers of the republic, each in his own department ; and all are equally accountable to the sovereign. g 142. Na- A prince cannot, indeed, justly oblige an ecclesiastic to autIrit thlS P reac ^ a doctrine, or to perform a religious rite, which the n y ' latter does not think agreeable to the will of God. But if the minister cannot, in this respect, conform to the will of his sovereign, he ought to resign his station, and consider himself as a man who is not called to fill it two things being neces- sary for the discharge of the duty annexed to it, viz. to teach and behave with sincerity, according to the dictates of his own conscience, and to conform to the prince's intentions and the laws of the state. Who can forbear being filled with in- dignation, at seeing a bishop audaciously resist the orders of the sovereign, and the decrees of the supreme tribunals, so- lemnly declaring that he thinks himself accountable to God alone for the power with which he is intrusted ? j? 143. Rule On the other hand, if the clergy are rendered contempti- to be ob- ki e? it w iu foe out O f their power to produce the fruits for relict to* whicn their ministr y was appointed. The rule that should ecclesiastics. e followed with respect to them may be comprised in a few words : let them enjoy a large portion of esteem ; but let them have no authority, and still less any claim to inde- pendence. In the first place, let the clergy, as well as every other order of men, be, in their functions, as in every thing else, subject to the public power, and accountable to the sovereign for their conduct. Secondly, let the prince take care to render the ministers of religion respectable in the eyes of the people ; let him trust them with the degree of authority necessary to enable them to discharge their duty with success ; let him, in case of need, support them with the power he possesses. Every man in office ought to be vested with an authority commensurate to his functions ; otherwise he will be unable to discharge them in a proper manner. I see no reason why the clergy should be excepted from this general rule; only the prince should be more particularly watchful that they do not abuse their authority ; the affair being altogether the most delicate, and the most fruitful in dangers. If he renders the character of churchmen respecta- 136 OF PIETY AND RELIGION. 64 ble, he should take care that this respect be not carried to c JJJ K ^j such a superstitious veneration as shall arm the hand of an CH ' ambitious priest with a powerful engine with which he may force weak minds into whatever direction he pleases. When once the clergy become a separate body, they become formida- ble. The Romans (we shall often have occasion to recur to them) the wise Romans elected from among the senators their pontifex-maximus and the principal ministers of the altar ; they knew no distinction between clergy and laity ; nor had they a set of gownsmen to constitute a separate class from the rest of the citizens. If the sovereign be deprived of this power in matters of f if*. Re- religion, and this authority over the clergy, how shall he pre- ca P 1 * ulatlon serve the religion pure from the admixture of any thing con- ons ^[^ trary to the welfare of the state ? How can he cause it to be establish the constantly taught and practised in the manner most conducive sovereign's to the public Avelfare ? and, especially, how can he prevent ngh *f m the disorders it may occasion, either by its doctrines, or the ^iigion. manner in which its discipline is exerted ? These cares and j" 65 1 duties can only belong to the sovereign, and nothing can dis- pense with his discharging them. Hence we see that the prerogatives of the crown, in eccle- Authorities siastical affairs, have been constantly and faithfully defended and exam- by the parliaments of France. The wise and learned magis- ples ' trates, of whom those illustrious bodies are composed, are sensible of the maxims which sound reason dictates on this subject. They know how important it is not to suffer an affair of so delicate a nature, so extensive in its connections and influence, and so momentous in its consequences, to be placed beyond the reach of the public authority. What ! Shall ecclesiastics presume to propose to the people, as an article of faith, some obscure and useless dogma, which con- stitutes no essential part of the received religion ? shall they exclude from the church, and defame those who do not show a blind obedience ? shall they refuse them the sacraments, and even the rites of burial ? and shall not the prince have power to protect his subjects, and preserve the kingdom from a dangerous schism ? The kings of England have asserted the prerogatives of their crown : they have caused themselves to be acknowledged heads of the church : and this regulation is equally approved by reason and sound policy, and is also conformable to ancient custom. The first Christian emperors exercised all the func- tions of heads of the church ; they made laws on subjects relating to it,* summoned councils, and presided in them, appointed and deposed bishops, &c. In Switzerland there are wise republics, whose sovereigns, knowing the full extent of the supreme authority, have rendered the ministers of * See the Theodosian Code, 18 M 2 137 65 OF PIETY AND RELIGION. BOOK i. religion subject to it, without offering violence to their con- CHAP. xir. sc i ences> They have prepared a formulary of the doctrines that are to be preached, and published laws of ecclesiastical discipline, such as they would have it exercised in the coun- tries under their jurisdiction, in order that those who will not conform to these establishments may not devote them- selves to the service of the church. They keep all the min- isters of religion in a lawful dependence, and suffer no exertion of church discipline but under their own authority. It is not probable that religion will ever occasion disturbances in these republics. g us. Per- If Constantino and his successors had caused themselves nicious con- to be formally acknowledged heads of the church, and if sequences Christian kings and princes had, in this instance, known how of the con- .. . , * /. . , , -, -, trary opi- * maintain the rights of sovereignty, would the world ever nion. have witnessed those horrid disorders produced by the pride and ambition of some popes and ecclesiastics, emboldened by [ 66 ] the weakness of princes, and supported by the superstition of the people, rivers of blood shed in the quarrels of monks, about speculative questions that were often unintelligible and almost always as useless to the salvation of souls as in them- selves indifferent to the welfare of society citizens and even brothers armed against each other, subjects excited to revolt, and kings hurled from their thrones ? Tantum religio potuit suadere malorum I The history of the emperors Henry IV., Frederick I., Frederick II., and Louis of Bavaria, is well known. Was it not the independence of the ecclesiastics, was it not that system in which the affairs of religion are submitted to a foreign power, that plunged France into the horrors of the league, and had nearly deprived her of the best and greatest of her kings ? Had it not been for that strange and danger- ous system, would a foreigner, Pope Sextus V., have under- taken to violate the fundamental law of the kingdom, and declared the lawful heir incapable of wearing the crown? Would the world have seen, at other times and in other places,* the succession to the crown rendered uncertain by a bare informality the want of a dispensation, whose validity was disputed, and which a foreign prelate claimed the sole right of granting ? Would that same foreigner have arro- gated to himself the power of pronouncing on the legitimacy pf the issue of a king ? Would kings have been assassinated in consequence of a detestable doctrine ?f Would a part of France have been afraid to acknowledge the best of their kings,| until he had received absolution from Rome ? And, would many other princes have been unable to give a solid * In England under Henry VIII. \ Though Henry IV. returned to the j" Henry III. and Henry IV. assas- Romish religion, a great number of sinated by fanatics, who thought they Catholics did not dare to acknowledge were serving God and the church by him until ho had received the pope's stabbing their king. absolution. 138 OF PIETY AND KELIGION. 66 peace to their people, because no decision could be formed BOOK r. within their own dominions on articles or conditions in which _ CHAP - *", religion was interested ?* All we have advanced on this subject, so evidently flows 146. The from the notions of independence and sovereignty, that it will abuses par- never be disputed by any honest man who endeavours to re a- * lc ^;f' rized - son justly. If a state cannot finally determine every thing e j of t h w " relating to religion, the nation is not free, and the prince is popes, but half a sovereign. There is no medium in this case ; either each state must, within its own territories, possess supreme power in this respect, as well as in all others, or we must adopt the system of Boniface VIII. , and consider all Roman Catholic countries as forming only one state, of which the pope shall be the supreme head, and the kings subordinate administrators of temporal affairs, each in his province, nearly as the sultans were formerly under the authority of the caliphs. We know that the above-mentioned pope had the presumption to write to Philip the Fair, king of France, Scire te volumus, quod in spiritualibus et temporalibus nobis subes'f [ 67 ] "We would have thee know that thou art subject to us as well in temporals as in spirituals." And we may see in the canon law| his famous bull Unam sanctam, in which he at- tributes to the church two swords, or a double power, spiritual and temporal, condemns those who think otherwise, as men, who, after the example of the Manicheans, establish two principles, and finally declares, that it is an article of faith, necessary to salvation, to believe that every human creature is subject to the Roman pontiff. We shall consider the enormous power of the popes as the first abuse that sprung from this system, which divests sove- reigns of their authority in matters of religion. This power in a foreign court directly militates against the independence * Many kings of France in the civil posed him. In short, here are the ex- wars on account of religion. pressions he made use of in addressing f Tun-ctin. Hist. Ecclesiast. Compen- the council assembled at Home on the dium, p. 1S2. Where may also be occasion: "Agite nunc, quseso, patres seen the resolute answer of the king et principes sanctissimi, ut omnis mun- of France. dus intelligat et cognoscat, quia si po- J Extravag. Commun. lib. i. tit. De testis in ccelo ligare et solvere, potestis Majoritate & Oledientia. in terra imperia, regna, principatus, g Gregory VII. endeavoured to ren- ducatus, marchias, comitatus, et omni- der almost all the states of Europe um hominum possessiones, pro meritis tributary to him. He maintained that tollere unicuique et concedere." NA- Hungary, Dalmatia, Russia, Spain, TAL, ALEX. Dissert. Hist. Eccl. s. xi. and and Corsica, were absolutely his pro- xii. p. 384. perty, as successor to St. Peter, or were The canon law boldly decides that feudatory dependencies of the holy see. the regal power is subordinate to the GREG. Epist. Condi, vol. vi. Edit, priesthood. "Imperium non prseest Harduin. He summoned the emperor sacerdotio, sed subest, et ei obedire te- Henry IV. to appear before him, and netur." RTJBBJC. ch. ri. De Major, et make his defence against the accusa- Obed. " Et est multum allegabile," is tions of some of his subjects : and, on the complaisant remark of the write- the emperor's non-compliance, he de- of the article. 139 CHAP. XII. 67 OF PIETY AND RELIGION. O f nations and the sovereignty of princes. It is capable of overturning a state ; and wherever it is acknowledged, the sovereign finds it impossible to exercise his authority in such a manner as is most for the advantage of the nation. We have already, in the last section, given several remarkable instances of this ; and history presents others without number. The senate of Sweden having condemned Trollius, archbishop of Upsal, for the crime of rebellion, to be degraded from his see, and to end his days in a monastery, pope Leo X. had the audacity to excommunicate the administrator Steno and the whole senate, and sentenced them to rebuild, at their own ex- pense, a fortress belonging to the archbishop, which they had caused to be demolished, and pay a fine of a hundred thousand ducats to the deposed prelate.* The barbarous Christiern, king of Denmark, took advantage of this decree, to lay waste the territories of Sweden, and to spill the blood of the most illustrious of her nobility. Paul V. thundered out an inter- dict against Venice, on account of some very wise laws made with respect to the government of the city, but which dis- pleased that pontiff, who thus threw the republic into an em- barrassment, from which all the wisdom and firmness of the 68 ] senate found it difficult to extricate it. Pius V., in his bull, In Ccena Domini, of the year 1567, declares, that all princes who shall introduce into their dominions any new taxes, of what nature soever they be, or shall increase the ancient ones, without having first obtained the approbation of the holy see, are ipso facto excommunicated. Is not this a direct attack on the independence of nations, and a subversion of the au- thority of sovereigns ? In those unhappy times, those dark ages that preceded the revival of literature and the Reformation, the popes at- tempted to regulate the actions of princes, under the pretence of conscience to judge of the validity of their treaties to break their alliances, and declare them null and void. But those attempts met with a vigorous resistance, even in a country which is generally thought to have then possessed valour alone, with a very small portion of knowledge. The pope's nuncio, in order to detach the Swiss from the interests of France, published a monitory against all those cantons that favoured Charles VIII., declaring them excommunicated, if within the space of fifteen days they did not abandon the cause of that prince, and enter into the confederacy which was formed against him ; but the Swiss opposed this act, by protesting against it as an iniquitous abuse, and caused their protest to be publicly posted up in all the places under their jurisdiction : thus showing their contempt for a proceeding that was equally absurd and derogatory to the rights of sove- * History of the Revolutiont in Sweden. 140 OP PIETY AND RELIGION. O reigns.* We shall mention several other similar attempts, BOOK i. when we come to treat of the faith of treaties. CHAP " * n ' This power in the popes has given birth to another abuse, 147. that deserves the utmost attention from a wise government. 2 - We see several countries in which ecclesiastical dignities, and mencoJ-~ all the higher benefices, are distributed by a foreign power ferredbya by the pope who bestows them on his creatures, and very foreign often on men who are not subjects of the state. This practice P wer - is at once a violation of the nation's rights, and of the prin- ciples of common policy. A nation ought not to suffer fo- reigners to dictate laws to her, to interfere in her concerns, or deprive her of her natural advantages ; and yet, how does it happen that so many states still tamely suffer a foreigner to dispose of posts and employments of the highest importance to their peace and happiness ? The princes who consented to the introduction of so enormous an abuse were equally wanting to themselves and their people. In our times, the court of Spain has been obliged to expend immense sums, in order to recover, without danger, the peaceable possession of a right which essentially belonged to the nation or its head. Even in those states whose sovereigns have preserved so 148. important a prerogative of the crown, the abuse in a great 3 - P werful measure subsists. The sovereign nominates, indeed, to bishop- * ^^J ^ rics and great benefices ; but his authority is not sufficient to a foreign enable the" persons nominated to enter on the exercise of their court, functions ; they must also have bulls from Rome.f By this [ 69 ] and a thousand other links of attachment, the whole body of the clergy in those countries still depend on the court of Rome ; from it they expect dignities ; from it that purple, which, according to the proud pretensions of those who are invested with it, renders them equal to sovereigns. From the resentment of that court they have every thing to fear ; and of course we see them almost invariably disposed to gratify it on every occasion. On the other hand, the court of Rome supports those clergy with all her might, assists them by her politics and credit, protects them against their enemies, and against those who would set bounds to their power nay, often against the just indignation of their sovereign ; and by this means attaches them to her still more strongly. Is it not doing an injury to the rights of society, and shocking the first elements of government, thus to suffer a great number of subjects, and even subjects in high posts, to be dependent on a foreign prince, and entirely devoted to him ? Would a * Vogel'a Historical and Political had to encounter, when he wished to Treatise on the Alliances between France confer the archbishopric of Sens on and the Thirteen Cantotw, pp. 33 and Renauld de Baune, archbishop of Bour- 36. gea, who had saved France, by receiving f- We may see, in the letters of Cardi- that great prince into the Roman Catho- nal d'Ossat, what difficulties, what op- lie church, position, what long delays, Henry IV. 141 by OF PIETY AND RELIGION. BOOK i. prudent sovereign receive men who preached such doctrines ? CHAP. xii. rrh ere neec i e( j no m0 re to cause all the missionaries to be driven from China. 149. it was f or the purpose of more firmly securing the attach- bac T Qf the men * ^ churchmen that the celibacy of the clergy was in- priests. vented. A priest, a prelate, already bound to the see of Rome by his functions and his hopes, is further detached from his country, by the celibacy he is obliged to observe. He is not connected with civil society by a family : his grand inte- rests are all centred in the church ; and, provided he has the pope's favour, he has no further concern : in what country soever he was born, Rome is his refuge, the centre of his adopted country. Everybody knows that the religious orders are a sort of papal militia, spread over the face of the earth, to support and advance the interests of their monarch. This is doubtless a strange abuse a subversion of the first laws of society. But this is not all : if the prelates were married, they might enrich the state with a number of good citizens ; rich benefices affording them the means of giving their legiti- Convents. mate children a suitable education. But what a multitude of men are there in convents, consecrated to idleness under the cloak of devotion ! Equally useless to society in peace and war, they neither serve it by their labour in necessary professions, nor by their courage in arms : yet they enjoy immense revenues ; and the people are obliged, by the sweat of their brow, to furnish support for these swarms of slug- gards. What should we think of a husbandman who pro- [ 70 ] tected useless hornets, to devour the honey of his bees ?* It is not the fault of the fanatic preachers of overstrained sanctity, if all their devotees do not imitate the celibacy of the monks. How happened it that princes could suffer them publicly to extol, as the most sublime virtue, a practice equally repugnant to nature, and pernicious to society? Among the Romans, laws were made to diminish the number of those who lived in celibacy, and to favour marriage :f but superstition soon attacked such just and wise regulations ; and the Christian emperors, persuaded by churchmen, thought themselves obliged to abrogate them.J Several of the fa- thers of the church have censured those laws against celi- bacy doubtless, says a great man, with a laudable zeal for the things of another life ; but with very little knoivledge of the affairs of this. This great man lived in the church of Rome : he did not dare to assert, in direct terms, that volun- tary celibacy is to be condemned even with respect to con- * This reflection has no relation to always laudable, and may become very the religious houses in which literature useful to the state, is cultivated. Establishments that af- f The Papia-Poppaean law. ford to learned men a peaceful retreat, j In the Theodosian Code, and that leisure and tranquillity re- \ The president de Montesquieu, in quired in deep scientific research, are his Spirit of Laws. 142 OF PIETY AND RELIGION. 70 science and the things of another life : but it is certainly a BOOK i. conduct well becoming genuine piety, to conform ourselves to CHAP - *" nature, to fulfil the views of the Creator, and to labour for the welfare of society. If a person is capable of rearing a family, let him marry, let him be attentive to give his chil- dren a good education: in so doing, he will discharge his duty, and be undoubtedly in the road to salvation. The enormous and dangerous pretensions of the clergy ? 150. are also another consequence of this system, which places 5 - Enor ' every thing relating to religion beyond the reach of the"^g C J f civil power. In the first place, the ecclesiastics, under pre- the clergy, tence of the holiness of their functions, have raised them- selves above all the other citizens, even the principal magis- Pre ' emi ' trates : and, contrary to the express injunctions of their ner master, who said to his apostles, seek not the first places at feasts, they have almost everywhere arrogated to themselves the first rank. Their head, in the Roman church, obliges sovereigns to kiss his feet ; emperors have held the bridle of his horse ; and if bishops or even simple priests do not at present raise themselves above their prince, it is because the times will not permit it : they have not always been so mo- dest; and one of their writers has had the assurance to assert, that a priest is as much above a Icing as a man is above a beast.*- How many authors, better known and more esteemed than the one just quoted, have taken a pleasure in praising and extolling that silly speech attributed to the emperor [ 71 ] Theodosius the First Ambrose has taught me the great dif- ference there is between the empire and the priesthood ! We have already observed that ecclesiastics ought to be honoured: but modesty, and even humility, should charac- terize them : and does it become them to forget it in their own conduct, while they preach it to others ? I would not mention a vain ceremonial, were it not attended with very material consequences, from the pride with which it inspires many priests, and the impressions it may make on the minds of the people. It is essentially necessary to good order, that subjects should behold none in society so respectable as their sovereign, and, next to him, those on whom he has devolved a part of his authority. Ecclesiastics have not stopped in so fair a path. Not con- 151. 6. In. tented with rendering themselves independent with respect to dependence, their functions, by the aid of the court of Rome, they have Immunitie8 - even attempted to withdraw themselves entirely, and in every respect, from all subjection to the political authority. There have been times when an ecclesiastic could not be brought before a secular tribunal for any crime whatsoever. f The * Tantum sacerdos proestat regi, quan- f The congregation of Immunities turn homo bestia:. Stanislaus Orichovius. has decided that the cognisance of Vide Tribbcchor. Exerc. 1, ad Baron, causes against ecclesiastics, even for Annal.Sect 2, et Thomas. Nut.ad.Lancell. the crime of high treason, exclusively 143 OF PIETY AND RELIGION. BOOK I. CHAP. XII. canon law declares expressly, It is indecent for laymen to judge a churchman* The popes Paul III., Pius V., and Urban VIII., excommunicated all lay judges who should presume to undertake the trial of ecclesiastics. Even the bishops of France have not been afraid to say on several occasions, that they did not depend on any temporal prince ; and, in 1656, the general assembly of the French clergy had the assurance to use the following expressions " The decree of council having been read, was disapproved by the assembly, because it leaves the king judge over the bishops, and seems to subject their immunities to his judges ."f There are decrees of the popes that excommunicate whoever im- prisons a bishop. According to the principles of the church of Rome, a prince has not the power of punishing an eccle- siastic with death, though a rebel or a malefactor ; he must first apply to the ecclesiastical power ; and the latter will, if it thinks proper, deliver up the culprit to the secular arm, after having degraded him.J History affords us a thousand belongs to the spiritual court : " Cog- nitio causae contra ecclesiasticos, etiam pro delicto hrsic majestatis, feri debet a judice ecclesiastico." RICCI Synops. Decret. et Resol. S. Congreg. Immunit. p. 105. A constitution of pope Ur- ban VI. pronounces those sovereigns or magistrates guilty of sacrilege, who shall banish an ecclesiastic from their territories, and declares them to have ipso facto incurred the sentence of ex- communication. Cap. II. De Fora. Compet in VII. To this immunity may be added the indulgence shown by the ecclesiastical tribunals to the clergy, on whom they never inflicted any but slight punishments, even for the most atrocious crimes. The dread- ful disorders that arose from this cause, at length produced their own remedy in France, where the clergy were at length subjected to the temporal juris- diction for all transgressions that are in- jurious to society. See PAPON Arrets Notables, book i. tit. v. act 34. * Indecorum est laicos homines viros ecclesiasticos judicare. Can. in nona actione 22, xvi. q. 7. f See the Statement of Facts on the System of Independence of Bishops. J In the year 1725, a parish priest, of the canton of Lucerne, having re- fused to appear before the supreme council, was, for his contumacy, ba- nished from the canton. Hereupon his diocesan, the bishop of Constance, had the assurance to write to the coun- cil that they had infringed the ecclesi- astical immunities that "it is unlaw- ful to subject the ministers of God to the decisions of the temporal power." In these pretensions he was sanctioned by the approbation of the pope's nun- cio and the court of Rome. But the council of Lucerne firmly supported the rights of sovereignty, and, without en- gaging with the bishop in a controversy which would have been derogatory to their dignity, answered him "Your lordship quotes various passages from the writings of the fathers, which we, on our side, might also quote in our own favour, if it were necessary, or if there was question of deciding the con- test by dint of quotation. But let your lordship rest assured that we have a right to summon before us a priest, our natural subject, who encroaches on our prerogatives to point out to him his error to exhort him to a reform of his conduct and, in consequence of his obstinate disobedience, after repeat- ed citations, to banish him from our dominions. We have not the least doubt that this right belongs to us; and we are determined to defend it. And indeed it ought not to be proposed to any sovereign to appear as party in a contest with a refractory subject like him to refer the cause to the decision of a third party, whoever he be and run the risk of being condemned to tolerate in the state a person of such character, with what dignity soever he might be invested," Ac. The bishop of Constance had proceeded so far as to assert, in his letter to the canton, dated December 18th, 1725, that OF PIETY AND RELIGION. 72 examples of bishops who remained unpunished, or were but BOOK i. slightly chastised, for crimes for which nobles of the highest CHAP - xn - rank forfeited their lives. John de Braganza, king of Portu- gal, justly inflicted the penalty of death on those noblemen who had conspired his destruction : but he did not dare to put to death the archbishop of Braga, the author of that detestable plot.* For an entire body of men, numerous and powerful, to stand beyond the reach of the public authority, and be de- pendent on a foreign court, is an entire subversion of order in the republic, and a manifest diminution of the sovereignty. This is a mortal stab given to society, whose very essence it is, that every citizen should be subject to the public autho- rity. Indeed the immunity which the clergy arrogate to themselves in this respect, is so inimical to the natural and necessary rights of a nation, that the king himself has not the power of granting it. But churchmen will tell us they derive this immunity from God himself ; but till they have furnished some proof of their pretensions, let us adhere to this certain principle, that God desires the safety of states, and not that which will only be productive of disorder and destruction to them. The same immunity is claimed for the possessions of the 152. church. The state might, no doubt, exempt those posses- 7 - immuni- sions from every species of tax at a time when they were ty ^ e ^ scarcely sufficient for the support of the ecclesiastics ; but, p ' for that favour, these men ought to be indebted to the public authority alone, which has always a right to revoke it, when- ever the welfare of the state makes it necessary. It being one of the fundamental and essential laws of every society, that, in case of necessity, the wealth of all the members ought [ 73 ] to contribute proportionally to the common necessities the prince himself cannot, of his own authority, grant a total exemption to a very numerous and rich body, without being guilty of extreme injustice to the rest of his subjects, on whom, in consequence of that exemption, the whole weight of the burden will fall. The possessions of the church are so far from being en- titled to an exemption on account of their being consecrated to God, that, on the contrary, it is for that very reason they ought to be taken the first for the use and safety of the state. For nothing is more agreeable to the common Father of man- *- kind than to save a state from ruin. God himself having no need of anything, the consecration of wealth to him is but a dedication of it to such uses as shall be agreeable to him. Besides, a great part of the revenues of the church, by the " churchmen, as soon as they have fore." Memorial on the Dispute between received holy orders, ceased to be natu- the Pope and the Canton of Lucerne, ral subjects, and are thus released from p. 65. the bondage in which they lived be- * Revolutions of Portugal. 19 N 145 73 OF PIETY AND RELIGION. BOOK i. confession of the clergy themselves, is destined for the poor. CHAP. xn. - c *' . ..... , J When the state is in necessity, it is doubtless the first and principal pauper, and the most worthy of assistance. We may extend this principle even to the most common cases, and safely assert that to supply a part of the current ex- penses of the state from the revenues of the church, and thus take so much from the weight of the people's burden, is really giving a part of those revenues to the poor, according to their original destination. But it is really contrary to religion and the intentions of the founders to waste in pomp, luxury, and epicurism, those revenues that ought to be consecrated to the relief of the poor.* Not satisfied, however, with rendering themselves inde- muniTation P en( ient, the ecclesiastics undertook to bring mankind under of men in their dominion ; and indeed they had reason to despise the office. stupid mortals who suffered them to proceed in their plan. Excommunication was a formidable weapon among ignorant and superstitious men, who neither knew how to keep it within its proper bounds, nor to distinguish between the use and the abuse of it. Hence arose disorders which have pre- vailed in some protestant countries. Churchmen have pre- sumed, by their own authority alone, to excommunicate men in high employments, magistrates whose functions were daily useful to society and have boldly asserted that those officers of the state, being struck with the thunders of the church, could no longer discharge the duties of their posts. What a perversion of order and reason ! What ! shall not a nation be allowed to intrust its affairs, its happiness, its repose and safety, to the hands of those whom it deems the most skilful and the most worthy of that trust ? Shall the power of a churchman, whenever he pleases, deprive the state of its wisest conductors, of its firmest supports, and rob the prince of his most faithful servants ? So absurd a pretension has been condemned by princes, and even by prelates, respect- able for their character and judgment. We read in the 171st letter of Ives de Chartres, to the Archbishop of Sens, that the royal capitularies (conformably to the thirteenth canon of the [ 74 ] twelfth council of Toledo, held in the year 681) enjoined the priests to admit to their conversation all those whom the king's majesty had received into favour, or entertained at his table, though they had been excommunicated by them, or by others, in order that the church might not appear to reject or condemn those whom the king was pleased to employ in his service.* The excommunications pronounced against the sovereigns themselves, and accompanied with the absolution of their subjects from their oaths of allegiance, put the finishing stroke to this enormous abuse ; and it is almost incredible * See Letters on the Pretensions of the Clergy. OF PIETY AND RELIGION. 74 that nations should have suffered such odious procedures. BOOK i. We have slightly touched on this subject in 145 and 146. CHAP " The thirteenth century gives striking instances of it. Otho IV. for endeavouring to oblige several provinces of Italy to submit to the laws of the empire, was excommunicated and deprived of the empire by Innocent III. and his subjects absolved from their oath of allegiance. Finally, this unfor- tunate emperor, being abandoned by the princes, was obliged to resign the crown to Frederic II. John, king of England, endeavouring to maintain the rights of his kingdom in the election of an archbishop of Canterbury, found himself ex- posed to the audacious enterprises of the same pope. Inno- cent excommunicated the king laid the whole kingdom under an interdict had the presumption to declare John unworthy of the throne, and to absolve his subjects from their oath of fidelity ; he stirred up the clergy against him excited his subjects to rebel solicited the king of France to take up arms to dethrone him publishing, at the same time, a cru- sade against him, as he would have done against the Sara- cens. The king of England at first appeared determined to defend himself with vigour ; but soon losing courage, he suf- fered himself to be brought to such an excess of infamy, as to resign his kingdoms into the hands of the pope's legate, to receive them back from him, and hold them as a fief of the church^ on condition of paying tribute.* The popes were not the only persons guilty of such enor- mities : there have also been councils who bore a part in them. That of Lyons, summoned by Innocent IV., in the year 1245, had the audacity to cite the emperor Frederic II. to appear before them in order to exculpate himself from the charges brought against him threatening him with the thunders of the church if he failed to do it. That great prince did not give himself much trouble about so irregular a proceeding. He said "that the pope aimed at rendering himself both a judge and a sovereign ; but that, from all an- tiquity, the emperors themselves had called councils, where the popes and prelates rendered to them, as to their sove- reigns, the respect and obedience that was their due."f The [ 75 ] emperor, however, thinking it necessary to yield a little to the superstition of the times, condescended to send ambassa- dors to the council, to defend his cause ; but this did not prevent the pope from excommunicating him, and declaring him deprived of the crown. Frederic, like a man of a su- perior genius, laughed at the empty thunders of the Vatican, , and proved himself able to preserve the crown in spite of the election of Henry, Landgrave of Thuringia, whom the eccle- siastical electors, and many bishops, had presumed to declare * Matthew Paris. Turretin. Compend. -f- HEISS'S History of the Empire, book Hist. Ecdea. Seoul, xiii. ii. chap. xvi. 147 75 OF PIETY AND RELIGION. BOOK i. king of the Romans but who obtained little more by that CHAP, xir. e i ec tion, than the ridiculous title of king of the priests. I should never have done, were I to accumulate examples ; but those I have already quoted are but too many for the honour of humanity. It is an humiliating sight to behold the excess of folly to which superstition had reduced the nations of Europe in those unhappy times.* 155. By means of the same spiritual arms, the clergy drew 10. The every thing to themselves, usurped the authority of the tri- bunals, and disturbed the course of justice. They claimed a right to take cognisance of all causes on account of sin, of themselves, which (says Innocent IH.f) every man of sense must know and disturb- i na t the cognisance belongs to our ministry. In the year 13 ??' the P rela ! es of Fran ce had the assurance to tell King Philip de Valois, that, to prevent causes of any kind from being brought before the ecclesiastical courts, was depriving the church of all its rights, omnia ecclesiarum jura tollere^. And accordingly, it was their aim to have to themselves the decision of all disputes. They boldly opposed the civil au- thority, and made themselves feared by proceeding in the way of excommunication. It even happened sometimes, that as dioceses were not always confined to the extent of the [ 76 ] political territory, a bishop would summon foreigners before his tribunal, for causes purely civil, and take upon him to decide them, in manifest violation of the rights of nations. To such a height had the disorder arisen three or four cen- turies ago, that our wise ancestors thought themselves obliged to take serious measures to put a stop to it, and stipulated, in their treaties, that none of the confederates should be sum- * Sovereigns were sometimes found, should acknowledge him as king, or who, without considering future con- perform towards him any of the duties sequences, favoured the papal en- of a subject. He then offered Arragon croachments when they were likely and Catalonia to the Count de Valois, to prove advantageous to their own second son of Philip the Bold, on con- interests. Thus, Louis VIII., king dition that he and his successors should of France, wishing to invade the terri- acknowledge themselves vassals of the tories of the Count of Toulouse, under holy see, take an oath of fealty to the pretence of making war on the Albi- pope, and pay him a yearly tribute, genses, requested of the pope, among The king of France assembled the other things, " that he would issue a barons and prelates of his kingdom, to bull declaring that the two Raymonds, deliberate on the pope's offer, and they father and son, together with all their advised him to accept of it. " Strange adherents, associates, and allies, had blindness of kings and their counsel- been and were deprived of all their lors !" exclaims, with good reason, a possessions." VELLY'S Hist, of France, modern historian ; " they did not per- vol. iv. p. 33. Of a similar nature to ceive, that, by thus accepting king- the preceding is the following remark- doms from the hands of the pope, they able fact: Pope Martin IV. excom- strengthened and established his pre- municated Peter, king of Arragon, tensions to the right of deposing thera- declared that he had forfeited his king- selves." VELLY'S History of France, dom, all his lands, and even the regal vol. vi. p. 190. dignity, and pronounced his subjects f In cap. Novit. de Judicis. absolved from their oath of allegiance. j See Leibnitii Codex, Juris Gent. He even excommunicated all who Diplomat. Dipl. LXVII. g 9. 148 OF PIETY AND RELIGION. 76 moned before spiritual courts, for money debts, since every BOOK i. one ought to be contented with the ordinary modes of justice CHAP - xir -.. that were observed in the country.* We find in history, that the Swiss on many occasions repressed the encroachments of the bishops and their judges. Over every affair of life they extended their authority, under pretence that conscience was concerned. They obliged new-married husbands to purchase permission to lie with their wives the first three nights after marriage.f This burlesque invention leads us to remark another abuse, 156. manifestly contrary to the rules of a wise policy, and to the V 1 * Mone y duty a nation owes to herself; I mean the immense su which bulls, dispensations, &c., annually drew to Rome, from all the countries in communion with her. How much might be said on the scandalous trade of indulgences ! but it at last became ruinous to the court of Rome, which, by endeavour- ing to gain too much, suffered irreparable losses. Finally, that independent authority intrusted to ecclesi- g 157. astics, who were often incapable of understanding the true !2. L maxims of government, or too careless to take the trouble of and studying them, and whose minds were wholly occupied by a ^ welfare visionary fanaticism, by empty speculations, and notions of of states. a chimerical and overstrained purity, that authority, I say, produced, under the pretence of sanctity, laws and customs that were pernicious to the state. Some of these we have noticed; but a very remarkable instance is mentioned by Grotius. " In the ancient Greek church," says he, " was long observed a canon, by which those who had killed an enemy in any war whatsoever were excommunicated for three years :"J a fine reward decreed for the heroes who defended their country, instead of the crowns and triumphs with which pagan Rome had been accustomed to honour them ! Pagan Rome became mistress of the world ; she adorned her bravest warriors with crowns. The empire, having embraced Chris- tianity, soon became a prey to barbarians ; her subjects, by defending her, incurred the penalty of a degrading excom- munication. By devoting themselves to an idle life, they thought themselves pursuing the path to heaven, and actually found themselves in the high road to riches and greatness. * Ibid. Alliance of Zurich with the upon ; they would have made no great antons of Uri, Schweitz, and Under- profit of any other, wald, dated May 1, 1351, 7. J De Jure Belli et Pacts, lib. ii. cap. f See A Regulation of Parliament in xxiv. He quotes Basil ad Amphiloch. re arret of March 19, 1409. Spirit of x. 13. Zonarca* in Niceph. Phoc. vol. Laws. These (says Montesquieu) were iii. the very best nights they could pitch ii 2 149 TT OF JUSTICE AND POLITY. BOOK I. CHAP. XIH. to make justice reign. CHAP. XIII. OF JUSTICE AND POLITY. g 158. A na- NEXT to the care of religion, one of the principal duties tion ought O f a na tion relates to justice: They ought to employ their utmost attention in causing it to prevail in the state, and to take proper measures for having it dispensed to every one in the most certain, the most speedy, and the least burdensome manner. This obligation flows from the object proposed by uniting in civil society, and from the social compact itself. We have seen ( 15), that men have bound themselves by the engagements of society, and consented to divest themselves, in its favour, of a part of their natural liberty, only with a view of peaceably enjoying what belongs to them, and ob- taining justice with certainty. The nation would therefore neglect her duty to herself, and deceive the individuals, if she did not seriously endeavour to make the strictest justice prevail. This attention she owes to her own happiness, re- pose, and prosperity. Confusion, disorder, and despondency will soon arise in a state, when the citizens are not sure of easily and speedily obtaining justice in all their disputes ; without this, the civil virtues will become extinguished, and the society weakened. There are two methods of making justice flourish good laws, and the attention of the superiors to see them executed. In treating of the constitution of a state (Chap. III.), we have already shown that a nation ought to establish just and wise laws, and have also pointed out the reasons why we can- not here enter into the particulars of those laws. If men were always equally just, equitable, and enlightened, the laws of nature would doubtless be sufficient for society. But ignorance, the illusions of self-love, and the violence of the passions, too often render these sacred laws ineffectual. And we see, in consequence, that all well-governed nations have perceived the necessity of enacting positive laws. There is a necessity for general and formal regulations, that each may clearly know his own rights, without being misled by self- deception. Sometimes even it is necessary to deviate from natural equity, in order to prevent abuses and frauds, and to accommodate ourselves to circumstances ; and, since the sen- sation of duty has frequently so little influence on the heart of man, a penal sanction becomes necessary, to give the laws their full efficacy. Thus is the law of nature converted into civil law.* It would be dangerous to commit the interests of the citizens to the mere discretion of those who are to dis- 159. To establish good laws. * See a dissertation on this subject, in the Loiair Philosophique, p. 71. 150 BOOK I. CHAP. Xn OF JUSTICE AND POLITY. 77 pense justice. The legislator should assist the understanding of the judges, force their prejudices and inclinations, and sub- due their will, by simple, fixed, and certain rules. These, again, are the civil laws. [ 78 ] The best laws are useless, if they be not observed. The ico. TO nation ought then to take pains to support them, and to cause enforce them to be respected and punctually executed : with this view * em * she cannot adopt measures too just, too extensive, or too ef- fectual ; for hence, in a great degree, depend her happiness, glory, and tranquillity. We have already observed ( 41) that the sovereign, who iei. represents a nation and is invested with its authority, is also Functions charged with its duties. An attention to make justice flourish J^f'^ in the state must then be one of the principal functions of the n th^ P * prince ; and nothing can be more worthy of the sovereign speck majesty. The emperor Justinian thus begins his book of the Institutes : Imperatoriam majcstatem non solum armis deco- ratam, sed etiam legibus oportet esse armatam, ut utrumque tcmpus, et bellorum et pads, recte possit gubernari. The de- gree of power intrusted by the nation to the head of the state, is then the rule of his duties and his functions in the admin- istration of justice. As the nation may either reserve the legislative power to itself, or intrust it to a select body, it has also a right, if it thinks proper, to. establish a supreme tribunal to judge of all disputes, independently of the prince. But the conductor of the state must naturally have a consid- erable share in legislation, and it may even be entirely intrusted to him. In this last case, it is he who must establish salutary laws, dictated by wisdom and equity : but in all cases, he should be the guardian of the law ; he should watch over those who are invested with authority, and confine each individual within the bounds of duty. The executive power naturally belongs to the sovereign, g 162. How to every conductor of a people : he is supposed to be in- he is to vested with it, in its fullest extent, when the fundamental ?jjjf" e laws do not restrict it. When the laws are established, it JUS is the prince's province to have them put in execution. To support them with vigour, and to make a just application of them to all cases that present themselves, is what we call rendering justice. And this is the duty of the sovereign, who is naturally the judge of his people. We have seen the chiefs of some small states perform these functions themselves : but this custom becomes inconvenient, and even impossible in a great kingdom. The best and safest method of distributing justice is by 163. He establishing judges, distinguished by their integrity and ou s h . tto knowledge, to take cognisance of all the disputes that mayJJJ^J 11 " arise between the citizens. It is impossible for the prince to and upright take upon himself this painful task : he cannot spare sufficient judges. time either for the thorough investigation of all causes, or 151 78 OF JUSTICE AND POLITY. BOOK i. even for the acquisition of the knowledge necessary to decide CHAP, xm. t h em> As the sovereign cannot personally discharge all the functions of government, he should, with a just discernment, reserve to himself such as he can successfully perform, and are of most importance, intrusting the others to officers and magistrates who shall execute them under his authority. There is no inconvenience in trusting the decision of a law- [ 79 ] suit to a body of prudent, honest, and enlightened men : on the contrary it is the best mode the prince can possibly adopt ; and he fully acquits himself of the duty he owes to his people in this particular, when he gives them judges adorned with all the qualities suitable to ministers of justice : he has then nothing more to do but to watch over their conduct, in order that they may not neglect their duty. 164. The The establishment of courts of justice is particularly ne- ordinary cessary for the decision of all fiscal causes, that is to say, T^id d a ^ *^ e Disputes ^at ma y ar i se between the subjects on the termine " one hand, and, on the other, the persons who exert the pro- causes re- fitable prerogatives of the prince. It would be very unbe- lating to the coming, and highly improper for a prince, to take upon him revenue. ^ gj ve j u ^g men t in his own cause : he cannot be too much on his guard against the illusions of interest and self-love ; and even though he were capable of resisting their influence, still he ought not to expose his character to the rash judg- ments of the multitude. These important reasons ought even to prevent his submitting the decision of causes in which he is concerned, to the ministers and counsellors particularly at- tached to his person. In all well-regulated states, in coun- tries that are really states, and not the dominions of a despot, the ordinary tribunals decide all causes in which the sovereign is a party, with as much freedom as those between private persons. 1 165. The end of all trials at law is justly to determine the dis- There ought putes that arise between the citizens. If, therefore, suits are to be esta- prosecuted before an inferior judge, who examines all the cir- blished su- r *. i . ,1 . preme cumstances and proofs relating to them, it is very proper, courts of that, for the greater safety, the party condemned should be justice allowed to appeal to a superior tribunal, where the sentence wherem O f tne f ormer judge may be examined, and reversed, if it ap- Bhouid be P ear * he ill-founded. But it is necessary that this supreme finally de- tribunal should have the authority of pronouncing a definitive termined. sentence without appeal : otherwise the whole proceeding will be vain, and the dispute can never be determined. The custom of having recourse to the prince himself, by laying a complaint at the foot of the throne, when the cause has been finally determined by a supreme court, appears to be subject to very great inconveniences. It is more easy to deceive the prince by specious reasons, than a number of magistrates well skilled in the knowledge of the laws ; and experience too plainly shows what powerful resources are derived from favour 152 OF JUSTICE AND POLITY. IV and intrigue in the courts of kings. If this practice he autho- BOOK r. rized by the laws of the state, the prince ought always to fear CHAP - xm - that these complaints are only formed with a view of protract- ing a suit, and procrastinating a just condemnation. A just and wise sovereign will not admit them without great caution ; and if he reverses the sentence that is complained of, he ought not to try the cause himself, but submit it to the examination of another tribunal, as is the practice in France. The ruin- ous length of these proceedings authorizes us to say that it is [ 80 ] more convenient and advantageous to the state, to establish a sovereign tribunal, whose definitive decrees should not be sub- ject to a reversal even by the prince himself. It is sufficient for the security of justice that the sovereign keep a watchful eye over the judges and magistrates, in the same manner as he is bound to watch all the other officers in the state, and that he have power to call to an account and to punish such as are guilty of prevarication. When once this sovereign tribunal is established, the prince ? 166. The cannot meddle with its decrees ; and, in general, he is abso- P rince lutely obliged to preserve and maintain the forms of justice. "f se ^g ^ Every attempt to violate them is an assumption of arbitrary f orms O f power, to which it cannot be presumed that any nation could justice, ever have intended to subject itself. When those forms are defective, it is the business of the legislator to reform them. This being done or procured in a manner agreeable to the fundamental laws, will be one of the most salutary benefits the sovereign can bestow upon his peo- ple. To preserve the citizens from the danger of ruining themselves in defending their rights, to repress and destroy that monster, chicanery, will be an action more glorious in the eyes of the wise man, than all the exploits of a conqueror. Justice is administered in the name of the sovereign ; the g 167. The prince relies on the judgment of the courts, and, with good prince reason, looks upon their decisions as sound law and justice. ougbt to . His part in this branch of the government is then to maintain authority of the authority of the judges, and to cause their sentences to the judges, be executed ; without which they would be vain and delusive ; for justice would not be rendered to the citizens. There is another kind of justice named attributive or distri-$U8. Of butive, which in general consists in treating everyone accord- distributive ing to his deserts. This virtue ought to regulate the distribu- J ^ lc d ' stri _ tion of public employments, honours, and rewards in a state, bution of It is, in the first place, a duty the nation owes to herself, to employ- encourage good citizens, to excite every one to virtue by hon- ments and ours and rewards, and to intrust with employments such per- rewards> sons only as are capable of properly discharging them. In the next place, it is a duty the nation owes to individuals, to show herself duly attentive to reward and honour merit. Al- though a sovereign has the power of distributing his favours and employments to whomsoever he pleases, and nobody has a 20 153 80 OF JUSTICE AND POLITY. SOOK i. perfect right to any post or dignity, yet a man who by in- CHAP. xin. j. enge a ppii ca tion has qualified himself to become useful to his country, and he who has rendered some signal service to the state, may justly complain if the prince overlooks them, in order to advance useless men without merit. This is treating them with an ingratitude that is wholly unjustifiable, and adapted only to extinguish emulation. There is hardly any fault that in the course of time can become more prejudicial to a state : it introduces into it a general relaxation ; and its public affairs, being managed by incompetent hands, cannot [ 81 ] fail to be attended with ill-success. A powerful state may support itself for some time by its own weight ; but at length it falls into decay ; and this is perhaps one of the principal causes of those revolutions observable in great empires. The sovereign is attentive to the choice of those he employs, while he feels himself obliged to watch over his own safety, and to be on his guard : but when once he thinks himself elevated to such a pitch of greatness and power as leaves him nothing to fear, he follows his own caprice, and all public offices are dis- tributed by favour. g 169. Pun- The punishment of trangressors commonly belongs to dis- ishment of tributive justice, of which it is really a breach ; since good ^ansgres- or( | er re q u } res that malefactors should be made to suffer the punishments they have deserved. But, if we would clearly establish this on its true foundations, we must recur to first Foundation p r i nc ipi es . The right of punishing, which in a state of nature of punish- Belongs to each individual, is founded on the right of personal ing. safety. Every man has a right to preserve himself from in- jury, and by force to provide for his own security against those who unjustly attack him. For this purpose he may, when injured, inflict a punishment on the aggressor, as well with the view of putting it out of his power to injure him for the future, or of reforming him, as of restraining, by his ex- ample, all those who might be tempted to imitate him. Now, when men unite in society, as the society is thenceforward charged with the duty of providing for the safety of its mem- bers, the individuals all resign to it their private right of pun- ishing. To the whole body, therefore, it belongs to avenge private injuries, while it protects the citizens at large. And as it is a moral person, capable also of being injured, it has a right to provide for its own safety, by punishing those who trespass against it ; that is to say, it has a right to punish public delinquents. Hence arises the right of the sword, which belongs to a nation, or to its conductor. When the society use it against another nation, they make war ; when they exert it in punishing an individual, they exercise vindictive justice. Two things are to be considered in this part of government, the laws, and their execution. 2 170. Crf- It would be dangerous to leave the punishment of transgres- minai laws. sors entirely to the discretion of those who are invested with 154 OF JUSTICE AND POLITY. 81 authority. The passions might interfere in a business which BOOK T - ought to be regulated only by justice and wisdom. The pun '- ishment pre-ordained for an evil action, lays a more effectual restraint on the wicked than a vague fear, in which they may deceive themselves. In short, the people, who are commonly moved at the sight of a suffering wretch, are better convinced of the justice of his punishment, when it is inflicted by the laws themselves. Every well-governed state ought then to have its laws for the punishment of criminals. It belongs to the legisla- tive power, whatever that be, to establish them with justice and . wisdom. But this is not a proper place for giving a general theory of them : we shall therefore only say that each nation ought, in this as in every other instance, to choose such laws as may best suit her peculiar circumstances. We shall only make one observation, which is connected ? i?i. De- with the subject in hand, and relates to the degree of punish- & r e of P un - ment. From the foundation even of the right of punishing, 1S r m go' T and from the lawful end of inflicting penalties, arises the ne- ^ * cessity of keeping them within just bounds. Since they are designed to procure the safety of the state and of the citizens, they ought never to be extended beyond what that safety re- quires. To say that any punishment is just since the trans- gressor knew before-hand the penalty he was about to incur, is using a barbarous language, repugnant to humanity, and to the law of nature, which forbids our doing any ill to others, unless they lay us under the necessity of inflicting it in our own defence and for 'our own security. Whenever then a particular crime is not much to be feared in society, as when the opportunities of committing it are very rare, or when the subjects are not inclined to it, too rigorous punishments ought not to be used to suppress it. Attention ought also to be paid to the nature of the crime ; and the punishment should be proportioned to the degree of injury done to the public tran- quillity and the safety of society, and the wickedness it sup- poses in the criminal. These maxims are not only dictated by justice and equity, but also as forcibly recommended by prudence and the art of government. Experience shows us that the imagination becomes familiarized to objects which are frequently present- ed to it. If, therefore, terrible punishments are multiplied, the people will become daily less affected by them, and at length contract, like the Japanese, a savage and ferocious character : these bloody spectacles will then no longer pro- duce the effect designed ; for they will cease to terrify the wicked. It is with these examples as with honours : a prince who multiplies titles and distinctions to excess, soon depre- ciates them, and makes an injudicious use of one of the most powerful and convenient springs of government. When we recollect the practice of the ancient Romans with respect to criminals when we reflect on their scrupulous attention to 155 82 OF JUSTICE AND POLITY. BOOK i. spare the blood of the citizens, we cannot fail to be struck CHAP, xin. a j. see j n g w j t |j h^ little ceremony it is now-a-days shed in the generality of states. Was then the Roman republic but ill governed ? Does better order and greater security reign among us? It is not so much the cruelty of the punishments, as a strict punctuality in enforcing the penal code, that keeps mankind within the bounds of duty : and if simple robbery is punished with death, what further punishment is reserved to check the hand of the murderer ? 172. EX- The execution of the laws belongs to the conductor of the ecution of state : he is intrusted with the care of it, and is indispensably the laws, obliged to discharge it with wisdom. The prince then is to see that the criminal laws be put in execution ; but he is not to attempt in his own person to try the guilty. Besides the [ 83 ] reasons we have already alleged in treating of civil causes, and which are of still greater weight in regard to those of a crimi- nal nature to appear in the character of a judge pronouncing sentence on a wretched criminal, would ill become the majesty of the sovereign, who ought in every thing to appear as the father of his people. It is a very wise maxim commonly re- ceived in France, that the prince ought to reserve to himself all matters of favour, and leave it to the magistrates to execute the rigour of justice. But then justice ought to be exercised in his name, and under his authority. A good prince will keep a watchful eye over the conduct of the magistrates ; he will oblige them to observe scrupulously the established forms, and will himself take care never to break through them. Every sovereign who neglects or violates the forms of justice in the prosecution of criminals, makes large strides towards tyranny ; and the liberty of the citizens is at an end when once they cease to be cei-tain that they cannot be condemned, except in pursuance of the laws, according to the established forms, and by their ordinary judges. The custom of committing the trial of the accused party to commissioners chosen at the plea- sure of the court, was the tyrannical invention of some minis : ters who abused the authority of their master. By this irregu- lar and odious procedure, a famous minister always succeed- ed in destroying his enemies. A good prince will never give his consent to such a proceeding, if he has sufficient discern- ment to foresee the dreadful abuse his ministers may make of it. If the prince ought not to pass sentence himself for the same reason, he ought not to aggravate the sentence passed by the judges. 1 173. Right The very nature of government requires that the executor n f J )ardon- of the laws should have the power of dispensing with them when this may be done without injury to any person, and in certain particular cases where the welfare of the state requires an exception. Hence the right of granting pardons is one of the attributes of sovereignty. But, in his whole conduct, in his severity as well as his mercy, the sovereign ought to have 156 OF JUSTICE AND POLITY. 83 no other object in view than the greater advantage of soci- BOOK i. ety. A wise prince knows how to reconcile justice with CHAP- "" clemency the care of the public safety with that pity which is due to the unfortunate. The internal police consists in the attention of the prince 174. in- and magistrates to preserve every thing in order. Wise re- *? rnal P- gulations ought to prescribe whatever will best contribute to llce- the public safety, utility, and convenience ; and those who are invested with authority cannot be too attentive to enforce them. By a wise police, the sovereign accustoms the people to order and obedience, and preserves peace, tranquillity, and concord among the citizens. The magistrates of Holland are said to possess extraordinary talents in this respect : a better police prevails in their cities, and even their establishments in the Indies, than in any other places in the known world. [ 84 ] Laws and the authority of the magistrates having been sub- 2 i? 5 - Duel stituted in the room of private war, the conductors of a nation or 81 " gle ought not to suffer individuals to attempt to do themselves jus- ?^ tice, when they can have recourse to the magistrates. Duelling that species of combat, in which the parties engage on account of a private quarrel is a manifest disorder, repugnant to the ends of civil society. This frenzy was unknown to the an- cient Greeks and Romans, who raised to such a height the glory of their arms : we received it from barbarous nations who knew no other law but the sword. Louis XIV. deserves the greatest praise for his endeavours to abolish this savage custom. But Avhy was not that prince made sensible that the most g 176. severe punishments were incapable of curing the rage for du- Means of elling ? They did not reach the source of the evil ; and since P uttm & * a ridiculous prejudice had persuaded all the nobility and gen- f tlemen of the army, that a man who wears a sword is bound in honour to avenge with his own hand the least injury he has received ; this is the principle on which it is proper to proceed. We must destroy this prejudice, or restrain it by a motive of the same nature. While a nobleman, by obeying the law, shall be regarded by his equals as a coward and as a man dis- honoured while an officer in the same case shall be forced to quit the service can you hinder his fighting by threatening him with death ? On the contrary, he will place a part of his bravery in doubly exposing his life in order to wash away the affront. And, certainly, while the prejudice subsists, while a nobleman or an officer cannot act in opposition to it, without embittering the rest of his life, I do not know whether we can justly punish him who is forced to submit to his tyranny, or whether he be very guilty with respect to morality. That (54) As to the legal view of the of- Aid. 462 ; and Burn's J. 26 ed. tit- fence of duelling in England, see 6 East " Duelling." Rep. 260 ; 2 East Rep. 581 ; 2 Barn. & 157 84 OF JUSTICE AND POLITY. BOOK i. worldly honour, be it as false and chimerical as you please, is CHAP, xm. j. Q fa m a su kstantial and necessary possession, since without it he can neither live with his equals, nor exercise a profession that is often his only resource. When, therefore, any insolent fellow would unjustly ravish from him that chimera so esteem- ed and so necessary, why may he not defend it as he would his life and property against a robber ? As the state does not permit an individual to pursue, with arms in his hand the usur- per of his property, because he may obtain justice from the magistrate so, if the sovereign will not allow him to draw his sword against the man from whom he has received an insult, he ought necessarily to take such measures that the patience and obedience of the citizen who has been insulted shall not prove prejudicial to him. Society cannot deprive man of his natural right of making war against an aggressor, without fur- nishing him with some other means of securing himself from the evil his enemy would do him. On all those occasions where the public authority cannot lend us its assistance, we resume our original and natural right of self-defence. Thus a traveller may, without hesitation, kill the robber who at- r 85 1 tacks him on the highway ; because it would, at that moment, be in vain for him to implore the protection of the laws and of the magistrate. Thus a chaste virgin would be praised for taking away the life of a brutal ravisher who attempted to force her to his desires. Till men have got rid of this Gothic idea, that honour obliges them, even in contempt of the laws, to avenge their per- sonal injuries with their own hands, the most effectual method of putting a stop to the effects of this prejudice would perhaps be to make a total distinction between the offended and the aggressor to pardon the former without difficulty, when it appears that his honour has been really attacked and to ex- ercise justice without mercy on the party who has committed the outrage. And as to those who draw the sword for trifles and punctilios, for little piques, or railleries in which honour is not concerned, I would have them severely punished. By this means a restraint would be put on those peevish and in- solent folks who often reduce even the moderate men to a necessity of chastising them. Every one would be on his guard, to avoid being considered as the aggressor ; and with a view to gain the advantage of engaging in duel (if un- avoidable) without incurring the penalties of the law, both parties would curb their passions ; by which means the quarrel would fall of itself, and be attended with no con- sequences. It frequently happens that a bully is at bottom a coward ; he gives himself haughty airs, and offers insult, in hopes that the rigour of the law will oblige people to put up with his insolence. And what is the consequence ? A man of spirit will run every risk, rather than submit to be insult- ed : the aggressor dares not recede : and a combat ensues, 158 OF JUSTICE AND POLITY. 85 which would not have taken place, if the latter could have BOOK * once imagined that there was nothing to prevent the other HAP ' XI "' from chastising him for his presumption the offended per- son being acquitted by the same law that condemns the ag- gressor. To this first law, whose efficacy would, I doubt not, be soon proved by experience, it would be proper to add the following regulations : 1. Since it is an established custom that the nobility and military men should appear armed, even in time of peace, care should be taken to enforce a rigid observance of the laws which allow the privilege of wearing swords to these two orders of men only. 2. It would be proper to establish a particular court, to determine, in a summary manner, all affairs of honour between persons of these two orders. The marshals' court in France is in possession of this power ; and it might be invested with it in a more formal manner and to a greater extent. The governors of provinces and strong places, with their general officers the colonels and captains of each regiment might, in this particular, act as deputies to the marshals. These courts, each in his own department, should alone confer the right of wearing a sword. Every no- bleman at sixteen or eighteen years of age, and every soldier at his entrance into the regiment, should be obliged to appear before the court to receive the sword. 3. On its being there [ 86 ] delivered to him, he should be informed that it is intrusted to him only for the defence of his country ; and care might be taken to inspire him with true ideas of honour. 4. It appears to me of great importance to establish, for different cases, pun- ishments of a different nature. Whoever should so far forget himself, as, either by word or deed, to insult a man who wears a sword, might be degraded from the rank of nobility, deprived of the privilege of carrying arms, and subjected to corporal punishment even the punishment of death, according to the grossness of the insult : and, as I before observed, no favour should be shown to the offender in case a duel was the conse- quence, while at the same time the other party should stand fully acquitted. Those who fight on slight occasions, I would not have condemned to death, unless in such cases where the author of the quarrel he, I mean, who carried it so far as to draw his sword, or to give the challenge has killed his ad- versary. People hope to escape punishment when it is too severe ; and, besides, a capital punishment in such cases is not considered as infamous. But let them be ignominiously de- graded from the rank of nobility and the use of arms, and for ever deprived of the right of wearing a sword, without the least hope of pardon : this would be the most proper method to re- strain men of spirit, provided that due care was taken to make a distinction between different offenders, according to the de- gree of the offence. As to persons below the rank of nobility, and who do not belong to the army, their quarrels should be 159 86 THIRD OBJECT OF A GOOD GOVERNMENT, DEFENCE. BOOK i. i e ft to the cognisance of the ordinary courts, which in case of CHAP. xiir. bioo^ghg^ should punish the offenders according to the com- mon laws against violence and murder. It should be the same with respect to any quarrel that might arise between a com- moner and a man entitled to carry arms : it is the business of the ordinary magistrate to preserve order and peace between those two classes of men, who cannot have any points of hon- our to settle the one with the other. To protect the people against the violence of those' who wear the sword, and to punish the former severely if they should dare to insult the latter, should further be, as it is at present, the business of the magistrate. I am sanguine enough to believe that these regulations, and this method of proceeding, if strictly adhered to, would extir- pate that monster, duelling, which the most severe laws have been unable to restrain. They go to the source of the evil, by preventing quarrels, and oppose a lively sensation of true and real honour to that false and punctilious honour which occa- sions the spilling of so much blood. It would be worthy a great monarch to make a trial of it : its success would immor- talize his name : and by the bare attempt he would merit the love and gratitude of his people. [ 8T ] CHAP. XIV. CHAP. XIY. THE THIRD OBJECT OF A GOOD GOVERNMENT, TO FORTIFY ITSELF AGAINST EXTERNAL ATTACKS. ? 177. A na- WE have treated at large of what relates to the felicity of tion ought a na tion : the subject is equally copious and complicated. -^ e ^ us now proceed to a third division of the duties which a external at- naton owes to itself, a third object of good government. One tacks. of the ends of political society is to defend itself with its com- bined strength against all external insult or violence ( 15). If the society is not in a condition to repulse an aggressor, it is very imperfect, it is unequal to the principal object of its destination, and cannot long subsist. The nation ought to put itself in such a state as to be able to repel and humble an unjust enemy : this is an important duty, which the care of its own perfection, and even of its preservation, imposes both on the state and its conductor. 178. Na- It is its strength alone that can enable a nation to repulse tionai all aggressors, to secure its rights, and render itself every- strength. wnere respectable. It is called upon by every possible motive to neglect no circumstance that can tend to place it in this happy situation. The strength of a state consists in three things, the number of the citizens, their military virtues, and 160 THIRD OBJECT OF A GOOD GOVERNMENT, DEFENCE. 87 AP. XIV. their riches. Under this last article we may comprehend fort- _BOOK resses, artillery, arms, horses, ammunition, and, in general,-" all that immense apparatus at present necessary in war, since they can all be procured with money. To increase the number of the citizens as far as it is pos- ? 179 - In - sible or convenient, is then one of the first objects that claim c ase . f the attentive care of the state or its conductor : and this will be F^" a successfully effected by complying with the obligation to procure the country a plenty of the necessaries of life, by enabling the people to support their families with the fruits of their labour, by giving proper directions that the poorer classes, and especially the husbandmen, be not harassed and oppressed by the levying of taxes, by governing with mildness, and in a manner which, instead of disgusting and dispersing the present subjects of the state, shall rather attract new ones, and, finally, by encouraging marriage, after the example of the Romans. That nation, so attentive to every thing capable of increasing and supporting their power, made wise laws against celibacy (as we have already observed in 149), and granted privileges and exemptions to married men, particularly to those who had numerous families : laws that were equally wise and just, since a citizen who rears [ 88 ] subjects for the state has a right to expect more favour from it than the man who chooses to live for himself alone.* Every thing tending to depopulate a country is a defect in a state not overstocked with inhabitants. We have already spoken of convents and the celibacy of priests. It is strange that establishments so directly repugnant to the duties of a man and citizen, as well as to the advantage and safety of society, should have found such favour, and that princes, in- stead of opposing them, as it was their duty to do, should have protected and enriched them. ' A system of policy, that dex- trously took advantage of superstition to extend its own power, led princes and subjects astray, caused them to mistake their real duties, and blinded sovereigns even with respect to their own interest. Experience seems at length to have opened the eyes of nations and their conductors ; the pope himself (let us mention it to the honour of Benedict XIV.) endeavors grad- (55) This subject, and the necessity and in favour of celibacy. "Videtur for endeavouring to discourage the in- esse matrimonii et stupri differentia, crease of population, have, in recent (says Tertullian) : sed utrobique est years, occasioned the publication of communicatio.f Ergo, inquis, et primas numerous works. See them commented nuptios damnas? Nee immerito, quo- upon. 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, 1, 2, niam et ipsse constant ex eo quod est Ac. stuprum." EXHORT. CASTIT. And thus * It is impossible to suppress the Jerome : " Hanc tantum esso differenti- emotions of indignation that arise on am inter uxorem et scortum, quod reading what some of the fathers of the tolerabilius sit uni esse prostitutam church have written against marriage, quam pluribus." f Contaminatio. EDIT. 21 o2 161 88 THIRD OBJECT OF A GOOD GOVERNMENT, DEFENCE. BOOK i. ually to reform so palpable an abuse ; by his orders, none of CHAP. XIY. j^s dominions are any longer permitted to take the vow of celibacy before they are twenty-five years of age. That wise pontiff gives the sovereigns of his communion a salutary ex- ample ; he invites them to attend at length to. the safety of their states, to narrow at least, if they cannot entirely close up, the avenues of that sink that drains their dominions. Take a view of Germany ; and there, in countries which are in all other respects upon an equal footing, you will see the protest- ant states twice as populous as the catholic ones. Compare the desert state of Spain with that of England, teeming with inhabitants : survey many fine provinces, even in France, destitute of hands to till the soil ; and then tell me, whether the many thousands of both sexes, who are now locked up in convents, would not serve God and their country infinitely better by peopling those fertile plains with useful cultivators ? It is true, indeed, that the catholic cantons of Switzerland are nevertheless very populous : but this is owing to a profound peace, and the nature of the government, which abundantly repair the losses occasioned by convents. Liberty is able to remedy the greatest evils; it is the soul of a state, and was with great justice called by the Romans alma Libertas. \ iso. Va- A cowardly and undisciplined multitude are incapable of re- lour, pulsing a warlike enemy : the strength of the state consists less in the number than the military virtues of its citizens. Va- lour, that heroic virtue which makes us undauntedly encounter [ 89 ] danger in defence of our country, is the firmest support of the state : it renders it formidable to its enemies, and often even saves it the trouble of defending itself. A state whose repu- tation in this respect is once well established, will be seldom attacked, if it does not provoke other states by its enterprises. For above two centuries the Swiss have enjoyed a profound peace, while the din of arms resounded all around them, and the rest of Europe was desolated by the ravages of war. Na- ture gives the foundation of valour ; but various causes may animate it, weaken it, and even destroy it. A nation ought then to seek after and cultivate a virtue so useful ; and a prudent sovereign will take all possible measures to inspire his subjects with it : his wisdom will point out to him the means. It is this generous flame that animates the French nobility : fired with a love of glory and of their country, they fly to battle, and cheerfully spill their blood in the field of honour. To what an extent would they not carry their con- quests, if that kingdom were surrounded by nations less war- like ! The Briton, generous and intrepid, resembles a lion in combat ; and, in general, the nations of Europe surpass in bravery all the other people upon earth. \ 181. But valour alone is not always successful in war : constant Other mili- success can only be obtained by an assemblage of all the mi- wry virtue?, jitary virtues. History shows us the importance of ability 162 THIRD OBJECT OF A GOOD GOVERNMENT, DEFENCE. 89 in the commanders, of military discipline, frugality, bodily BOOK i. strength, dexterity, and being inured to fatigue and labour. CHAP - XIV .:. These are so many distinct branches which a nation ought carefully to cultivate. It was the assemblage of all these that raised so high the glory of the Romans, and rendered them the masters of the world. It were a mistake to suppose that valour alone produced those illustrious exploits of the ancient Swiss the victories of Morgarten, Sempach, Laupen, Morat, and many others. The Swiss not only fought with intrepidity : they studied the art of war, they inured them- selves to its toils, they accustomed themselves to the prac- tice of all its manoeuvres, and their very love of liberty made them submit to a discipline which could alone secure to them that treasure, and save their country. Their troops were no less celebrated for their discipline than their bravery. Me- zeray, after having given an account of the behaviour of the Swiss at the battle of Dreux, adds these remarkable words : "in the opinion of all the officers of both sides who were pre- sent, the Swiss, in that battle, under every trial, against in- fantry and cavalry, against French and against Germans, gained the palm for military discipline, and acquired the re- putation of being the best infantry in the world."* Finally, the wealth of a nation constitutes a considerable g 182. part of its power, especially in modern times, when war re- Riches, quires such immense expenses. It is not simply in the re- venues of the sovereign, or the public treasure, that the riches of a nation consist : its opulence is also rated from the wealth [ 90 ] of individuals. We commonly call a nation rich, when it contains a great number of citizens in easy and affluent cir- cumstances. The wealth of private persons really increases the strength of the nation ; since they are capable of contri- buting large sums towards supplying the necessities of the state, and that, in a case of extremity, the sovereign may even employ all the riches of his subjects in the defence, and for the safety of the state, in virtue of the supreme command with which he is invested, as we shall hereafter show. The nation, then, ought to endeavour to acquire those public and private riches that are of such use to it : and this is a new reason for encouraging a commerce with other nations, which is the source from whence they flow, and a new motive for the sovereign to keep a watchful eye over the different branches of foreign trade carried on by his subjects, in order that he may preserve and protect the profitable branches, and cut off those that occasion the exportation of gold and silver. It is requisite that the state should possess an income pro- g 183. Pub- portionate to its necessary expenditures. That income may lic revenues be supplied by various means, by lands reserved for that and taxes> * History of France, vol. ii. p. 888. OF THE GLORY OF A NATION. BOOK i. purpose, by contributions, taxes of different kinds, &c. but CHAP, xiv. o f ^ g su hj ec t we shall treat in another place. 184. The We have here summed up the principal ingredients that nation ought constitute that strength which a nation ought to augment and crease its i m P rove - Can it be necessary to add the observation, that power by ii- this desirable object is not to be pursued by any other me- legal means, thods than such as are just and innocent ? A laudable end is not sufficient to sanctify the t means; for these ought to be in their own nature lawful. The law of nature cannot con- tradict itself: if it forbids an action as unjust or dishonest in its own nature, it can never permit it for any purpose what- ever. And therefore in those cases where that object, in itself so valuable and so praiseworthy, cannot be attained without employing unlawful means, it ought to be considered as unattainable, and consequently be relinquished. Thus, we shall show, in treating of the just causes of war, that a nation is not allowed to attack another with a view to aggrandize itself by subduing and giving law to the latter. This is just the same as if a private person should attempt to enrich him- self by seizing his neighbour's property. 185. Pow- The power of a nation is relative, and ought to be measured ens but re- ^y ^at Q f j tg neighbours, or of all the nations from whom it has any thing to fear. The state is sufficiently powerful when it is capable of causing itself to be respected, and of repelling whoever would attack it. It may be placed in this happy situation, either by keeping up its own strength equal or even superior to that of its neighbours, or by preventing their rising to a predominant and formidable power. But we can- not show here in what cases and by what means a state may [ 91 ] justly set bounds to the power of another. It is necessary, first, to explain the duties of a nation towards others, in order to combine them afterwards with its duties towards itself. For the present, we shall only observe, that a nation, while it obeys the dictates of prudence and wise policy in this in- stance, ought never to lose sight of the maxims of justice. CHAP. XV. OF THE GLORY OF A NATION. 186. Ad- THE glory of a nation is intimately connected with its vantages of p 0wer? an( j indeed forms a considerable part of it. It is this brilliant advantage that procures it the esteem of other na- tions, and renders it respectable to its neighbours. A nation whose reputation is well established especially one whose glory is illustrious is courted by all sovereigns ; they desire its friendship, and are afraid of offending it. Its friends, and 164 OF THE GLORY OF A NATION. 91 those who wish to become so, favour its enterprises ; and BOOK ' those who envy its prosperity are afraid to show their ill-will. CHAP - XY - It is, then, of great advantage to a nation to establish its g isr. Duty reputation and glory ; hence, this becomes one of the most of the na- important of the duties it owes to itself. True glory consists tion> in the favourable opinion of men of wisdom and discern- ment ; it is acquired by the virtues or good qualities of the head and the heart, and by great actions, which are the fruits of those virtues. A nation may have a two-fold claim HOW true to it ; first, by what it does in its national character, by the s lor y is ac- conduct of those who have the administration of its affairs, j n genial, we attribute a virtue or a vice to a peo- 2 189. Duty pj e ^ wnen that vice or that virtue is frequently observed among zens. 6 C *~ them. We say that a nation is warlike, when it produces a great number of brave warriors ; that it is learned, when there are many learned men among the citizens ; and that it excels in the arts, when it produces many able artists. On the other hand, we call it cowardly, lazy, or stupid, when men of those characters are more numerous there than else- where. The citizens, being obliged to labour with all their might to promote the welfare and advantage of their country, not only owe to themselves the care of deserving a good re- putation, but they also owe it to the nation, whose glory is so liable to be influenced by theirs. Bacon, Newton, Descartes, Leibnitz, and Bernouilli, have each done honour to his native country, and essentially benefited it by the glory he acquired. Great ministers, and great generals an Oxenstiern, a Tu- renne, a Marlborough, a Ruyter serve their country in a double capacity, both by their actions and by their glory. On the other hand, the fear of reflecting a disgrace on his country will furnish the good citizen with a new motive for abstaining from every dishonourable action. And the prince ought not to suffer his subjects to give themselves up to vices capable of bringing infamy on the nation, or even of simply tarnishing the brightness of its glory ; he has a right to sup- press and to punish scandalous enormities, which do a real injury to the state. g 190. Ex- The example of the Swiss is very capable of showing how ample of advantageous glory may prove to a nation. (56) The high the Swiss. re p u t a tion they have acquired for their valour, and which they still gloriously support, has preserved them in peace for above two centuries, and rendered all the powers of Europe desirous of their assistance. Louis XL, while dauphin, was witness of the prodigies of valour they performed at the [ 93 ] battle of St. Jacques, near Basle, and he immediately formed the design of closely attaching to his interest so intrepid a nation.* The twelve hundred gallant heroes, who on this occasion attacked an army of between fifty and sixty thou- sand veteran troops, first defeated the vanguard of the Ar- magnacs, which was eighteen thousand strong ; afterwards, rashly engaging the main body of the army, they perished almost to a man, without being able to complete their victory, f But, besides their terrifying the enemy, and preserving (56) This observation properly refers considered by their countrymen as to ante, $ 124, p. 54. cowards that had preferred a life of * See the Memoirs of Comines. shame to the honour of dying for their ( Of this small army, " eleven hun- country." History of the Helvetic Con- dred and fifty-eight were counted dead federacy, by M. de Watteville, vol. i. p. on the field, and thirty -two wounded. 250. Tschudi, p. 425. Twelve men only escaped, who were 166 OF THE PROTECTION SOUGHT BY A NATION. Switzerland from a ruinous invasion, they rendered her essen- BOOK i^ tial service by the glory they acquired for her arms. A re- putation for an inviolable fidelity is no less advantageous to that nation ; and they have at all times been jealous of pre- serving it. The canton of Zug punished with death that un- worthy soldier who betrayed the confidence of the duke of Milan by discovering that prince to the French, when, -to escape them, he had disguised himself in the habit of the Swiss, and placed himself in their ranks as they were march- ing out of Novara.* Since the glory of a nation is a real and substantial ad- 191- A t- vantage, she has a right to defend it, as well as her other ad- JJJ?*,** vantages. He who attacks her glory does her an injury ; and nation is do _ she has a right to exact of him, even by force of arms, a just i ng he reparation. We cannot, then, condemn those measures, some- injury. times taken by sovereigns to support or avenge the dignity of their crown. They are equally just and necessary. If, when they do not proceed from too lofty pretensions, we at- tribute them to a vain pride, we only betray the grossest igno- rance of the art of reigning : and despise one of the firmest supports of the greatness and safety of a state. er an CHAP. XVI. CHAP. XVI. OF THE PROTECTION SOUGHT BY A NATION, AND ITS VOLUN- TARY SUBMISSION TO A FOREIGN POWER. WHEN a nation is not capable of preserving herself from 192. Pro- insult and oppression, she may procure the protection of a teotion. more powerful state. If she obtains this by only engaging to perform certain articles, as to pay a tribute in return for the safety obtained, to furnish her protector with troops, and to embark in all his wars as a joint concern, but still [ 94 ] reserving to herself the right of administering her own govern- ment at pleasure, it is a simple treaty of protection, that does not all derogate from her sovereignty, and differs not from the ordinary treaties of alliance, otherwise than as it creates a difference in the dignity of the contracting parties. But this matter is sometimes carried still farther : and, al- 193 - v - though a nation is under an obligation to preserve with the JjJPjJJJ b ~ utmost care the liberty and independence it inherits from one na tion nature, yet when it has not sufficient strength of itself, and to another, feels itself unable to resist its enemies, it may lawfully sub- ject itself to a more powerful nation on certain conditions * Vogel's Historical and political France and the Thirteen Cantons, p. Treatise of the Alliances between 75, 76. 167 94 OF THE PROTECTION SOUGHT BY A NATION. BOOK i. agreed to by both parties : and the compact or treaty of sub- CHAP. xvi. m j s gi on w in thenceforward be the measure and rule of the rights of each. For, since the people who enter into subjec- tion resign a right which naturally belongs to them, and trans- fer it to the other nation, they are perfectly at liberty to an- nex what conditions they please to this transfer ; and the other party, by accepting their submission on this footing, engages to observe religiously all the clauses of the treaty. 194. So- This submission may be varied to infinity, according to the verai kinds ^i}j of the contracting parties : it may either leave the infe- 6ion UbmiS ~ r * or na ti n a P ai> t f the sovereignty, restraining it only in cer- tain respects, or it may totally abolish it, so that the superior nation shall become the sovereign of the other, or, finally, the lesser nation may be incorporated with the greater, in order thenceforward to form with it but one and the same state : and then the citizens of the former will have the same privileges as those with whom they are united. . The Roman history furnishes examples of each of these three kinds of sub- mission, 1. The allies of the Roman people, such as the in- habitants of Latium were for a long time, who, in several re- spects, depended on Rome, but, in all others, were governed according to their own laws, and by their own magistrates ; 2. The countries reduced to Roman provinces, as Capua, whose inhabitants submitted absolutely to the Romans; * 3. The nations to which Rome granted the freedom of the city. In after times the emperors granted that privilege to all the nations subject to the empire, and thus transformed all their subjects into citizens. \ 195. Right In the case of a real subjection to a foreign power, the of the citi- citizens who do not approve this change are not obliged to the nitron submit to it : they ought to be allowed to sell their effects submits to a and retire elsewhere. For, my having entered into a society foreign pow- does not oblige me to follow its fate, when it dissolves itself er - in order to submit to a foreign dominion. I submitted to the society as it then was, to live in that society as the member of a sovereign state, and not in another : I am bound to obey it, while it remains a political society : but, when it divests [ 95 ] itself of that quality in order to receive its laws from another state, it breaks the bond of union between its members, and releases them from their obligations. 196. When a nation has placed itself under the protection of These com- another that is more powerful, or has even entered into sub- pacts annul- j ec tion to it with a view to receiving its protection, if the failure of 6 ^^ er does not effectually protect the other in case of need, protection, it is manifest, that, by failing in its engagements, it loses all the rights it had acquired by the convention, and that the other, being disengaged from the obligation it had contracted, * Itaque populum Campanum, ur- patres conscript!, populique Romani bemque Capuam, agros, delubra deflm, ditionem dedimus. LIVY, book vii. divina huinanaque omnia, in restrain, c. 31. 168 OF THE PROTECTION SOUGHT BY A NATION. 95 re-enters into the possession of all its rights, and recovers its BOOK i. independence, or its liberty. It is to be observed that this CHAP - XYI i takes place even in cases where the protector does not fail in his engagements through the want of good faith, but merely through inability. For, the weaker nation having submitted only for the sake of obtaining protection, if the other proves unable to fulfil that essential condition, the compact is dis- solved ; the weaker resumes its rights, and may, if it thinks proper, have recourse to a more effectual protection.* Thus, the dukes of Austria, who had acquired a right of protection, and in some sort a sovereignty over the city of Lucerne, being unwilling or unable to protect it effectually, that city con- cluded an alliance with the three first cantons ; and the dukes having carried their complaint to the emperor, the inhabit- ants of Lucerne replied, " that they had used the natural right common to all men, by which every one is permitted to endeavour to procure his own safety when he is abandoned by those who are obliged to grant him assistance, "f The law is the same with respect to both the contracting 197. Or parties : if the party protected do not fulfil their engage- b y. . tlie " lfi * ments with fidelity, the protector is discharged from his ; ^f^^ e may afterwards refuse his protection, and declare the treaty tectcd. broken, in case the situation of his affairs renders such a step advisable. In virtue of the same principle which discharges one of the 198 - AnJ contracting parties when the other fails in his engagements, by th f en ~ if the more powerful nation should assume a greater autho- of the pro . rity over the weaker one than the treaty of protection or sub- tector. mission allows, the latter may consider the treaty as broken, and provide for its safety according to its own discretion. If it were otherwise, the inferior nation would lose by a conven- tion which it had only formed with a view to its safety ; and if it were still bound by its engagements when its protector abuses them and openly violates his own, the treaty Avould, to the weaker party, prove a downright deception. However, [ 96 ] as some people maintain, that, in this case, the inferior nation has only the right of resistance and of imploring foreign aid, and particularly as the weak cannot take too many pre- cautions against the powerful, who are skilful in colouring over their enterprises, the safest way is to insert in this kind of treaty a clause declaring it null and void whenever the * We speak here of a nation that f See The History of Switzerland. has rendered itself subject to another, The United Provinces, having been and not of one that has incorporated obliged to rely wholly on their own itself with another state, so as to con- efforts in defending themselves against stitute a part of it. The latter stands Spain, would no longer acknowledge in the same predicament with all th- any dependence on the empire from other citizens. Of this case we shalJ which they had received no assistance, treat in the following chapter. GROTIUS, Hist, of the Troubles in the Low Countries, b. xvi. p. 627. 22 P 169 96 HOW A NATION MAY SEPARATE ITSELF. BOOK i. superior power shall arrogate to itself any rights not expressly CHAP, xvi. grante d by the treaty. 199. How But if the nation that is protected, or that has placed the right of itself in subjection on certain conditions, does not resist the ^rotectecHs encroacnments f that power from which it has sought sup- lost by Its^ P ort if ^ ma kes no opposition to them if it preserves a silence. profound silence, when it might and ought to speak its pa- tient acquiescence becomes in.Jength of time a tacit consent that legitimates the rights of the usurper. There would be no stability in the affairs of men, and especially in those of nations, if long possession, accompanied by the silence of the persons concerned, did not produce a degree of right. But it must be observed, that silence, in order to show tacit con- sent, ought to be voluntary. If the inferior nation proves that violence and fear prevented its giving testimonies of its opposition, nothing can be concluded from its silence, which therefore gives no right to the usurper. CHAP. XVII. CHAP, xvn. HOW A NATION MAY SEPARATE ITSELF FROM THE STATE OF WHICH IT IS A MEMBER, OR RENOUNCE ITS ALLEGIANCE TO ITS SOVEREIGN WHEN IT IS NOT PROTECTED. 200. Dif- WE have said that an independent nation, which, without ference be- becoming a member of another state, has voluntarily rendered tween the itself dependent on, or subject to it, in order to obtain pro- and those^n t ect i n ? i s released from its engagements as soon as that pro- the preced- tection fails, even though the failure happen through the ing chapter, inability of the protector. But we are not to conclude that it is precisely the same case with every nation that cannot ob- tain speedy and effectual protection from its natural sovereign or the state of which it is a member. The two cases are very different. In the former, a free nation becomes subject to another state, not to partake of all the other's advantages, and form with it an absolute union of interests (for, if the more powerful state were -willing to confer so great a favour, the weaker one would be incorporated, not subjected), but to obtain protection alone by the sacrifice of its liberty, without expecting any other return. When, therefore, the sole and indispensable condition of its subjection is (from what cause soever) not complied with, it is free from its engagements ; and its duty towards itself obliges it to take fresh methods to provide for its own security. But the several members of one individual state, as they all equally participate in the advan- tages it procures, are bound uniformly to support it : they have entered into mutual engagements to continue united iro HOW A NATION MAY SEPARATE ITSELF. 97 with each other, and to have on all occasions but one common BOOK i. cause. If those who are menaced or attacked might sepa- OHAP - xv "- rate themselves from the others, in order to avoid a present danger, every state would soon be dismembered and destroyed. It is, then, essentially necessary for the safety of society, and even for the welfare 'of all its members, that each part should with all its might resist a common enemy, rather than sepa- rate from the others ; and this is consequently one of the necessary conditions of the political association. The natural subjects of a prince are bound to him without any other reserve than the observation of the fundamental laws ; it is their duty to remain faithful to him, as it is his, on the other hand, to take care to govern them well : both parties have but one common interest ; the people and the prince together constitute but one complete whole, one and the same society. It is, then, an essential and necessary condition of the poli- tical society, that the subjects remain united to their prince as far as in their power. (57) When, therefore, a city or a province is threatened or actu- 201. Du- y attacked, it must not, for the sake of escaping the danger, the principal establishment, or mother-country, naturally be- comes a part of the state, equally with its ancient possessions. Whenever, therefore, the political laws, or treaties, make no distinction between them, every thing said of the territory of a nation, must also extend to its colonies. CHAP. XIX. OF OUR NATIVE COUNTRY, AND SEVERAL THINGS THAT CHAP, six. RELATE TO IT. THE whole of the countries possessed by a nation and sub- 211. What ject to its laws, forms, as we have already said, its territory, is our coun- and is the common country of all the individuals of the na- tT ?- tion. We have been obliged to anticipate the definition of the term, native country ( 122), because our subject led us to treat of the love of our country a virtue so excellent and so necessary in a state. Supposing, then, this definition al- ready known, it remains that we should explain several things that have a relation to this subject, and answer the questions that naturally arise from it. * History of the English Colonies in North America. 101 OF OUR NATIVE COUNTRY, ETC. BOOK i. The citizens are the members of the civil society ; bound CHAP, xix- to this society by certain duties, and subject to its authority, 212. cm- they equally participate in its advantages. The natives, or natural-born citizens, are those born in the country, of pa- rents who are citizens. As the society cannot exist and per- petuate itself otherwise than by the children of the citizens, those children naturally follow the condition of their fathers, and succeed to all their rights. The society is supposed to desire this, in consequence of what it owes to its own preser- vation ; and it is presumed, as matter of course, that each citizen, on entering into society, reserves to his children the right of becoming members of it. The country of the fa- thers is therefore that of the children ; and these become true citizens merely by their tacit consent. We shall soon see whether, on their coming to the years of discretion, they may renounce their right, and what they owe to the society in which they were born. I say, that, in order to be of the country, it is necessary that a person be born of a father who is a citizen ; for, if be is born there of a foreigner, it will be [ 102 ] only the place of his birth, and not his country. ? 213. in- The inhabitants, as distinguished from citizens, are fo- habitants. reigners, who are permitted to settle and stay in the country. Bound to the society by their residence, they are subject to the laws of the state while they reside in it ; and they are obliged to defend it, because it grants them protection, though they do not participate in all the rights of citizens. They enjoy only the advantages which the law or custom gives them. The perpetual inhabitants are those who have received the right of perpetual residence. These are a kind of citizens of an inferior order, and are united to the society without par- ticipating in all its advantages. Their children follow the condition of their fathers ; and, as the state has given to these the right of perpetual residence, their right passes to their posterity. g 214. Na- A nation, or the sovereign who represents it, may grant to turaiization. a foreigner the quality of citizen, by admitting him into the ( 58 ) body of the political society. This is called naturalization. There are some states in which the sovereign cannot grant to a foreigner all the rights of citizens, for example, that of (58) See fully in general, and of 39, 43, 45 ; and see Reeves, 2d ed. 328, naturalization in Great Britain in par- 330, and 37 Geo. 3, c. 97. C. ticular, 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, {A native citizen of the United States 123 to 131 ; 1 Bla. Com. 369 ; Bac. Ab. cannot throw off his allegiance to the Aliens. A naturalization in a foreign government, without an Act of Con- country, without license, will not dis- gress authorizing him to do so. Miller charge a natural-born subject from his v. The Resolution, 2 Dall. 10; Shanks v. allegiance, 2 Chalmer's Col. Opin. 363. Dupont, 3 Pet S. C. Rep. 246 ; Coxe v. But a natural-born subject of England, Mcllvaine, 4 Cranch, 209 ; The Santis- naturalized in America, was holden to sitna Trinidada, 7 Wheat. Rep. 283 ; be entitled to trade as an American The United States v. Gillies, Peter's C. subject to the East Indies, 8 Term Rep. C. Rep. 159.} 176 OF OUR NATIVE COUNTRY, ETC. 102 holding public offices and where, consequently, he has the BOOK i. power of granting only an imperfect naturalization. It is CHAP - XIX - here a regulation of the fundamental law, which limits the power of the prince. In other states, as in England and Poland, the prince cannot naturalize a single person, without the concurrence of the nation, represented by its deputies. Finally, there are states, as, for instance, England, where the single circumstance of being born in the country naturalizes the children of a foreigner. It is asked whether the children born of citizens in a 215. Chit- foreign country are citizens? The laws have decided this dren of cit i- question in several countries, and their regulations must be ^foreign 1 "' followed.(59) By the law of nature alone, children follow country, the condition of their fathers, and enter into all their rights ( 212) ; the place of birth produces no change in this parti- cular, and cannot, of itself, furnish any reason for taking from a child what nature has given him; I say "of itself," for, civil or political laws may, for particular reasons, ordain otherwise. But I suppose that the father has not entirely quitted his country in order to settle elsewhere. If he has fixed his abode in a foreign country, he is become a member of another society, at least as a perpetual inhabitant; and his children will be members of it also. As to children born at sea, if they are born in those parts 216. Chil- of it that are possessed by their nation, they are born in the dren born at country : if it is on the open sea, there is no reason to make sea * a distinction between them and those who are born in the country; for, naturally, it is our extraction, not the place of our birth, that gives us rights: and if the children are born in a vessel belonging to the nation, they may be reputed born in its territories ; for, it is natural to consider the vessels of a nation as parts of its territory, especially when they sail upon a free sea, since the state retains its jurisdiction over those vessels. And as, according to the commonly received custom, this jurisdiction is preserved over the vessels, even in parts of the sea subject to a foreign dominion, all the children born in the vessels of a nation are considered as born in its terri- tory. For the same reason, those born in a foreign vessel are reputed born in a foreign country, unless their birth took place in a port belonging to their own nation : for, the port is more particularly a part of the territory ; and the mother, though at that moment on board a foreign vessel, is not on that account out of the country. I suppose that she and her husband have not quitted their native country to settle else- where. [ 103 ] For the same reasons also, children born out of the coun-2ir. Chil try, in the armies of the state, or in the house of its minister at d* en born i* a foreign court, are reputed born in the country ; for a citi- the armies of the state (59) See 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, 114, n. 1 ; 115, n. 1. 23 103 OF OUR NATIVE COUNTRY, ETC. HOOK i. zen who is absent with his family, on the service of the state, CHAP, xix. b u t still dependent on it, and subject to its jurisdiction, can- or in the not be considered as having quitted its territory. house of its Settlement is a fixed residence in any place, with an inten- Tforef r at t * on of a ^ wa J s staying there. A man does not, then, esta- court! lgn blish his settlement in any place, unless he makes sufficiently 218. Set- known his intention of fixing there, either tacitly or by an tlement. express declaration. However, this declaration is no reason why, if he afterwards changes his mind, he may not transfer his settlement elsewhere. In this sense, a person who stops at a place upon business, even though he stay a long time, has only a simple habitation there, but has no settlement. Thus, the envoy of a foreign prince has not his settlement at the court where he resides. The natural, or original settlement, is that which we ac- quire by birth, in the place where our father has his ; and we are considered as retaining it, till we have abandoned it, in order to choose another. The acquired settlement (adsciti- tium] is that where we settle by our own choice. 219. Va- Vagrants are people who have no settlement. Conse- grants. quently, those born of vagrant parents have no country, since a man's country is the place where, at the time of his birth, his parents had their settlement ( 122), or it is the state of which his father was then a member, which comes to the same point ; for, to settle for ever in a nation, is to become a mem- ber of it, at least as a perpetual inhabitant, if not with all the privileges of a citizen. We may, however, consider the coun- try of a vagrant to be that of his child, while that vagrant is considered as not having absolutely renounced his natural or original settlement. 220. Whe- Many distinctions will be necessary, in order to give a com- ther a per- pl e te solution to the celebrated question, whether a man may quit his country or the society of which he is a member. (60) country. ! The children are bound by natural ties to the society in which they were born ; they are under an obligation to show themselves grateful for the protection it has afforded to their fathers, and are in a great measure indebted to it for their birth and education. They ought, therefore, to love it, as we have already shown ( 122), to express a just gratitude to it, and requite its services as far as possible, by serving it in turn. We have observed above ( 212), that they have a right to enter into the society of which their fathers were members. [ 104 ] But every man is born free ; and the son of a citizen, when come to the years of discretion, may examine whether it be convenient for him to join the society for which he was des- tined by his birth. If he does not find it advantageous to remain in it, he is at liberty to quit it, on making it a com* (60) In Great Britain, the established 1 Bla. C. 369, 3 Chit. Com. Law, 129 maxim is nemo potest exuere pat)~ium, to 132. 178 OF OUR NATIVE COUNTRY, ETC. 104 pensation for what it has done in his favour,* and preserv- BOOK i. ing, as far as his new engagements will allow him, the senti- CHAP, xnc. ments of love and gratitude he owes it. A man's obligations to his natural country may, however, change, lessen, or en- tirely vanish, according as he shall have quitted it lawfully, and with good reason, in order to choose another, or has been banished from it deservedly or unjustly, in due form of law or by violence. 2. As soon as the son of a citizen attains the age of man- hood, and acts as a citizen, he tacitly assumes that character ; his obligations, like those of others who expressly and for- mally enter into engagements with society, become stronger and more extensive : but the case is very different with re- spect to him of whom we have been speaking. When a so- ciety has not been formed for a determinate time, it is allow- able to quit it, when that separation can take place without detriment to the society. A citizen m< r y therefore quit the state of which he is a member, provided it be not in such a conjuncture when he cannot abandon it without doing it a visible injury. But we must here draw a distinction between what may in strict justice be done, and what is honourable and conformable to every duty in a word, between the in- ternal and the external obligation. Every man has a right to quit his country, in order to settle in any other, when by that step he does not endanger the welfare of his country. But a good citizen will never determine on such a step with- out necessity, or without very strong reasons. It is taking a dishonourable advantage of our liberty, to quit our asso- ciates upon slight pretences, after having derived considerable advantages from them ; and this is the case of every citizen, with respect to his country. 3. As to those who have the cowardice to abandon their country in a time of danger, and seek to secure themselves, instead of defending it, they manifestly violate the social compact, by which all the contracting parties engaged to de- fend themselves in a united body, and in concert ; they are infamous deserters, whom the state has a right to punish severely.f * This is the foundation of the tax moted in the army of Saxony, had, with paid on quitting a country, called, in the permission of his former sovereign, Latin, census emigrations. sold the property he possessed in Li- t Charles XII. condemned to death vonia. He had therefore quitted his and executed General Patkul, a native own country, to choose another (as of Livonia, whom he had made prisoner every free citizen is at liberty to do, in an engagement with the Saxons, except, as we have observed above, at But the sentence and execution were a critical moment, when the circum- tt violation of the laws of justice. Pat- stances of his country require the aid Kul, it is true, had been born a subject of all her sons), and the king of Sweden, of the king of Sweden ; but he had by permitting him to sell his property, quitted his native country at the age hud consented to his emigration, of twelve years, and having been pro- 179 105 OF OUR NATIVE COUNTRY, ETC. BOOK i. In a time of peace and tranquillity, when the country has CHAP, xi^ no ac t ua i nee( j O f a ii ner children, the very welfare of the 221. How s tate, and that of the citizens, requires that every individual ma^absent ^ e at l^erty to travel on business, provided that he be always himself for ready to return, whenever the public interest recalls him. It a time. is not presumed that any man has bound himself to the so- ciety of which he is a member, by an engagement never to leave the country when the interest of his affairs requires it, and when he can absent himself without injury to his country. 222. Vari- The political laws of nations vary greatly in this respect, ation of the j n S0 me nations, it is at all times, except in case of actual kwfhfthis war ' a ^ owe ^ to every citizen to absent himself, and even to respect. (6i) q 11 ^ tne country altogether, whenever he thinks proper, with- These must out alleging any reason for it. This liberty, contrary in its be obeyed. own nature to the welfare and safety of society, can nowhere be tolerated but in a country destitute of resources and inca- pable of supplying the wants of its inhabitants. In such a country there can only be an imperfect society ; for civil society ought to be capable of enabling all its members to procure, by their labour and industry, all the necessaries of life : unless it effects this, it has no right to require them to devote themselves entirely to it. In some other states, every citizen is left at liberty to travel abroad on business, but not to quit his country altogether, without the express permission of the sovereign. Finally, there are states where the rigour of the government will not permit any one Avhatsoever to go out of the country without passports in form, which are even not granted without great difficulty. In all these cases, it is necessary to conform to the laws, when they are made by a lawful authority. But, in the last-mentioned case, the sove- reign abuses his power, and reduces his subjects to an insup- portable slavery, if he refuses them permission to travel for their own advantage, when he might grant it to them without inconvenience, and without danger to the state. Nay, it will presently appear, that, on certain occasions, he cannot, under any pretext, detain persons who wish to quit the country, with the intention of abandoning it for ever. 223. Cases There are cases in which a citizen has an absolute right in which a to renounce his country, and abandon it entirely a right ^ * f un d e( l on reasons derived from the very nature of the social compact. 1. If the citizen cannot procure subsistence in his own country, it is undoubtedly lawful for liim to seek it else- where. For, political or civil society being entered into only with a view of facilitating to each of its members the means of supporting himself, and of living in happiness and safety, it would be absurd to pretend that a member, whom it cannot furnish with such things as are most necessary, has not a right to leave it. (61) See post, Book II. ch. viii. 103, p. 731 to 733, as to writs of ne exeat p. 174, and Chitty's General Practice, rec/no. OF OUR NATIVE COUNTRY, ETC. 10ft 2. If the body of the society, or he who represents it, ab- BOOK i. solutely fail to discharge their obligations towards a citizen, CHAP - XIX - the latter may withdraw himself. For, if one of the contract- ing parties does not observe his engagements, the other is no longer bound to fulfil his ; as the contract is reciprocal be- [ 106 ] tween the society and its members. It is on the same prin- ciple, also, that the society may expel a member who violates its laws. 3. If the major part of the nation, or the sovereign who represents it, attempt to enact laws relative to matters in which the social compact cannot oblige every citizen to sub- mission, those who are averse to these laws have a right to quit the society, and go settle elsewhere. For instance, if the sovereign, or the greater part of the nation, will allow but one religion in the state, those who believe and profess another religion have a right to withdraw, and to take with them their families and effects. For, they cannot be supposed to have subjected themselves to the authority of men, in affairs of conscience ;* and if the society suffers and is weakened by their departure, the blame must be imputed to the intolerant party ; for it is they who fail in their observance of the social compact it is they who violate it, and force the others to a separation. We have elsewhere touched upon some other in- stances of this third case, that of a popular state wishing to have a sovereign ( 33), and that of an independent nation taking the resolution to submit to a foreign power ( 195). Those who quit their country for any lawful reason, with 1 224. Emi- a design to settle elsewhere, and take their families and pro- s rants - perty with them, are called emigrants. Their right to emigrate may arise from several sources. I 225. 1. In the cases we have just mentioned ( 223), it is a natural So rces of right, which is certainly reserved to each individual in the their nsht ' very compact itself by. which civil society was formed. 2. The liberty of emigration may, in certain cases, be se- cured to the citizens by a fundamental law of the state. The citizens of Neufchatel and Valangin in Switzerland may quit the country and carry off their effects at their own pleasure, without even paying any duties. 3. It may be voluntarily granted them by the sovereign. 4. This right may be derived from some treaty made with a foreign power, by which a sovereign has promised to leave full liberty to those of his subjects, who, for a certain reason on account of religion, for instance desire to transplant themselves into the territories of that power. There are such treaties between the German princes, particularly for Ceases in which religion is concerned. In Switzerland like- wise, a citizen of Bern who wishes to emigrate to Fribourg, and there profess the religion of the place, and, reciprocally, * See above, the chapter on Religion. Q 181 106 OF OUR NATIVE COUNTRY, ETC. BOOK i. a citizen of Fribourg who, for a similar reason, is desirous of CHAP. xix. rem0 vmg t Bern, has a right to quit his native country, and carry off with him all his property. It appears from several passages in history, particularly the history of Switzerland and the neighbouring countries, that the law of nations, established there by custom some ages back, did not permit a state to receive the subjects of another state into the number of its citizens. This vicious [ 107 ] custom had no other foundation than the slavery to which the people were then reduced. A prince, a lord, ranked his sub- jects under the head of his private property ; he calculated their number as he did that of his flocks ; and, to the disgrace of human nature, this strange abuse is not yet everywhere eradicated. I 226. If If the sovereign attempts to molest those who have a right the sove- to emigrate, he does them an injury ; and the injured indi- reign m- yiduals may lawfully implore the protection of the power who fringes their . .-,,. ! . '., * m , , T-" j TITM right, he in- 1S willing to receive them. Thus we have seen Frederic Wil- jures'them. liam, king of Prussia, grant his protection to the emigrant Protestants of Saltzburgh. g 227. Sup- The name of supplicants is given to all fugitives who im- piicants. plore the protection of a sovereign against the nation or prince they have quitted. We cannot solidly establish what the law of nations determines with respect to them, until we have treated of the duties of one nation towards others. 228. Ex- Finally, exile is another manner of leaving our country, lie and ba- An ex ii e j s a man driven from the place of his settlement, or ient constrained to quit it, but without a mark of infamy. Ba- nishment is a similar expulsion, with a mark of infamy an- nexed.* Both may be for a limited time, or for ever. If an exile, or banished man, had his settlement in his own country, he is exiled or banished from his country. It is, however, proper to observe that common usage applies also the terms exile and banishment to the expulsion of a foreigner who is driven from a country where he had no settlement, and to which he is, either for a limited time, or for ever, prohibited to return. As a man may be deprived of any right whatsoever by way of punishment exile, which deprives him of the right of dwelling in a certain place, may be inflicted as a punishment : banishment is always one ; for, a mark of infamy cannot be set on any one, but with a view of punishing him for a fault, either real or pretended. When the society has excluded one of its members by a * The common acceptation of these by some disgrace at court." The reason two terms is not repugnant to our ap- is plain : such a condemnation from the plication of them. The French aca- tribunal of justice entails infamy on demy says, "Banishment is only ap- the emigrant; whereas a disgrace at plied to condemnations in duo course court does not usually involve the same of law. Exile is only an absence caused consequence. 182 OF OUK NATIVE COUNTRY, ETC. perpetual banishment, he is only banished from the lands of BOOA i. that society, and it cannot hinder him from living wherever CHA1> - xlx - else he pleases ; for, after having driven him out, it can no longer claim any authority over him. The contrary, how- ever, may take place by particular conventions between two or more states. Thus, every member of the Helvetic con- federacy may banish its own subjects out of the territories of Switzerland in general ; and in this case the banished person will not be allowed to live in any of the cantons, or in the territories of their allies. Exile is divided into voluntary and involuntary. It is vo- luntary, when a man quits his settlement to escape some punishment, or to avoid some calamity and involuntary, [ 108 ] when it is the effect of a superior order. Sometimes a particular place is appointed, where the exiled person is to -remain during his exile ; or a certain space is particularized, which he is forbid to enter. These various circumstances and modifications depend on him who has the power of sending into exile. A man, by being exiled or banished, does not forfeit the 229. The human character, nor consequently his right to dwell some- xll f * n< * where on earth. He derives this right from nature, or rather n^have a from its Author, who has destined the earth for the habitation r i g ht to live of mankind ; and the introduction of property cannot have somewhere, impaired the right which every man has to the use of such things as are absolutely necessary a right which he brings with him into the world at the moment of his birth. But though this right is necessary and perfect in the gene- 230. Na- ral view of it, we must not forget that it is but imperfect with ture of *h respect to each particular country. For, on the other hand, nght ' every nation has a right to refuse admitting a foreigner into her territory, when he cannot enter it without exposing the nation to evident danger, or doing her a manifest injury. What she owes to herself, the care of her own safety, gives her this right ; and, in virtue of her natural liberty, it be- longs to the nation to judge, whether her circumstances will or will not justify the admission of that foreigner (Prelim. 16). He cannot, then, settle by a full right, and as he pleases, in the place he has chosen, but must ask permission of the chief of the place ; and, if it is refused, it is his duty to submit. However, as property could not be introduced to the pre- 231. Duty judice of the right acquired by every human creature, of not f natjons being absolutely deprived of such things as are necessary tnwar(1s no nation can, Avithout good reasons, refuse even a perpetual residence to a man driven from his country. But, if particular and substantial reasons prevent her from affording him an asvlum, this man has no longer any right to demand it be- cause, in such a case, the country inhabited by the nation 183 towards them. 108 OF OUR NATIVE COUNTRY, ETC. BOOK i. cannot, at the same time, serve for her own use, and that of CHAP, xix. t kj s f ore jg neri Now, supposing even that things are still in common, nobody can arrogate to himself the use of a thing which actually serves to supply the wants of another. Thus, a nation, whose lands are scarcely sufficient to supply the wants of the citizens, is not obliged to receive into its territo- ries a company of fugitives or exiles. Thus, it ought even absolutely to r' ject them, if they are infected with a conta- gious disease. Thus, also, it has a right to send them else- where, if it has just cause to fear that they will corrupt the manners of the citizens, that they will create religious disturb- ances, or occasion any other disorder, contrary to the public safety. In a word, it has a right, and is even obliged, to follow, in this respect, the suggestions of prudence. But this prudence should be free from unnecessary suspicion and jealousy ; it should not be carried so far as to refuse a [ 109 ] retreat to the unfortunate, for slight reasons, and on ground- less and frivolous fears. The means of tempering it will be, never to lose sight of that charity and commiseration which are due to the unhappy. We must not suppress these feelings even for those who have fallen into misfortune through their own fault. For, we ought to hate the crime, but love the man, since all mankind ought to love each other. e 232. A If an exiled or banished man has been driven from his nation can- country for any crime, it does not belong to the nation in he has taken refuge to punish him for that fault com- - in a foreign country. For, nature does not give to mitted out men or to nations any right to inflict punishment, except for of its terri- their own defence and safety ( 169) ; whence it follows that tories; we canno t punish any but those by whom we have been in- jured. I 233. ex- But this very reason shows, that, although the justice of cept such each nation ought in general to be confined to the punishment as affect the O f cr i mes committed in its own territories, we ought to except safetyTf fr m this rule those villains, who, by the nature and habitual mankind, frequency of their crimes, violate all public security, and de- clare themselves the enemies of the human race. Poisoners, assassins, and incendiaries by profession, may be exterminated wherever they are seized; for they attack and injure all nations by trampling under foot the foundations of their com- mon safety. Thus, pirates are sent to the gibbet by the first into whose hands they fall. If the sovereign of the country where crimes of that nature have been, committed, reclaims the perpetrators of them, in order to bring them to punish- men, they ought to be surrendered to him, as being the person who is principally interested in punishing them in an exemplary manner. And as it is proper to have criminals regularly convicted by a trial in due form of law, 184 OF PUBLIC, COMMON, AND PRIVATE PROPERTY. 109 S a S< lass t mitted. (62) this is a second reason for delivering up malefactors of BOOK i. that class to the states where their crimes have been com- CHAP - XIX . CHAP. XX. OP PUBLIC, COMMON, AND PRIVATE PROPERTY. LET us now see what is the nature of the different things 234. What contained in the country possessed by a nation, and endeavour the Romans to establish the general principles of the law by which they "^^J are regulated. This subject is treated by civilians under the c " title de rerum divisione. There are things which in their own nature cannot be possessed : there are others, of which nobody claims the property, and which remain common, as in their primitive state, when a nation takes possession of a country : the Roman lawyers called those things res communes, things common : such were, with them, the air, the running water, the sea, the fish, and wild beasts. Every thing susceptible of property is considered as be- ? 235. Ag- longing to the nation that possesses the country, and as form- s re g ate ing the aggregate mass of its wealth. But the nation does we * lth of * 11 i i i mi nation, and not possess all those things in the same manner. Those not j ts divisions, divided between particular communities, or among the indi- [ HO ] viduals of a nation, are called public property. Some are reserved for the necessities of the state, and form the demesne of the crown, or of the republic : others remain common to all the citizens, who take advantage of them, each according to his necessities, or according to the laws which regulate their use ; and these are called common property. There are others that belong to some body or community, termed joint property, res universitatis ; and these are, with respect to this body in particular, what the public property is with respect to the whole nation. As the nation may be considered as a great community, we may indifferently give the name of com- mon property to those things that belong to it in common, in (62) A distinction has usually been 9 Barn. & Cress. 446. {A foreign taken between capital offences and mere government has no right, by the Law misdemeanors, and for one state to al- of Nations, to demand of the govern- low the taking and removing an offen- ment of the United States a surrender der of the former class back into the of a citizen or subject of such foreign country where the offence was com- government, who has committed a crime mitted, in order to take his trial in the in his own country. Such a right can latter, but not so in case of misdemean- only exist by treaty. Comm. v. Deacon, ore. But sometimes, as upon a charge 10 Serg. & Raw. 125 ; Case of Dos Santos, of perjury, a foreign country will allow 2 Brocken. Rep. 493. The Case of the removal of an offender even in case Hobins, Bee's Rep. 266, was under the of a misdemeanor. See Ex parte Scott, treaty with Great Britain.} 24 2 U 185 110 OF PUBLIC, COMMON, ANP BOOK i. such a manner that all the citizens may make use of them, CHAP. xx. an( j Q th ose that are possessed in the same manner by a body or community : the same rules hold good with respect to both. Finally, the property possessed by individuals is termed pri- vate property, res singulorem. % 236. Two When a nation in a body takes possession of a country, ways of ac- every thing that is not divided among its members remains qumng common to the whole nation, and is called public property. There is a second way whereby a nation, and, in general, every community, may acquire possessions, viz. by the will of whosoever thinks proper to convey to it, under any title whatsoever, the domain or property of what he possesses. 237. The As soon as the nation commits the reins of government to revenues of the hands of a prince, it is considered as committing to him, the public a tne same time, the means of governing. Since, therefore, naturally 'aT * ne mcome f the public property, of the domain. of the the sove- state, is destined for the expenses of government, it is natu- reign's dis- rally at the prince's disposal, and ought always to be consi- posal. dered in this light, unless the nation has, in express terms, excepted it in conferring the supreme authority, and has pro- vided in some other manner for its disposal, and for the ne- cessary expenses of the state, and the support of the prince's person and household. Whenever, therefore, the prince is purely and simply invested with the sovereign authority, it includes a full discretional power to dispose of the public re- venues. The duty of the sovereign, indeed, obliges him to apply those revenues only to the necessities of the state ; but he alone is to determine the proper application of them, and is not accountable for them to any person. 238. The The nation may invest the superior with the sole use of i :-i nation may common possessions, and thus add them to the domain of thfe grant him g t a te. It may even cede the property of them to him. But the use and . J property of * nis cession M the use or property requires an express act of its common the proprietor, which is the nation. It is difficult to found it possessions, on a tacit consent, because fear too often hinders the subjects from protesting against the unjust encroachments of the sovereign. 239. or The people may even allow the superior the domain of the allow him things they possess in common, and reserve to themselves the the domain, uge Q f tnem j n tne wno le or in part. Thus, the domain of a t^ itself* 3 the river, for instance, may be ceded to the prince, while the people use of them, reserve to themselves the use of it for navigation, fishing, the [ 111 ] watering of cattle, &c. They may also allow the prince the sole right of fishing, &c., in that river. In a word, the peo- ple may cede to the superior whatever right they please over the common possessions of the nation ; but all those particu- lar rights rights do not naturally, and of themselves, flow from the sovereignty. 2 240. If the income of the public property, or of the domain, is Taxes. not sufficient for the public wants, the state supplies the de- 186 PRIVATE PROPERTY. Ill ficiency by taxes. These ought to be regulated in such a BOOK i. manner, that all the citizens may pay their quota in proper- CHAP - x i tion to their abilities, and the advantages they reap from the society. All the members of civil society being equally oblige'd to contribute, according to their abilities, to its ad- vantage and safety, they cannot refuse to furnish the subsi- dies necessary to its preservation, when they are demanded by lawful authority. Many nations have been unwilling to commit to the prince g 241. The a trust of so delicate a nature, or to grant him a power that nation may he may so easily abuse. In establishing a domain for the f ese ' e * support of the sovereign and the ordinary expenses of the right of imm state, they have reserved to themselves the right of providing, posing by themselves or their representatives, for extraordinary them, wants, in imposing taxes payable by all the inhabitants. In England, the king lays the necessities of the state before the parliament ; that body, composed of the representatives of the nation, deliberates, and, with the concurrence of the king, determines the sum to be raised, and the manner of raising it. (63) And of the use the king makes of the money thus raised, that same body obliges him to render it an account. In other states, where the sovereign possesses the full and g 242. Of absolute authority, it is he alone that imposes taxes, regulates the sove- the manner of raising them, and makes use of them as he reign y ho thinks proper, without giving an account to anybody. The French king at present enjoys this authority, (64) with the simple formality of causing his edicts to be registered by the parliament ; and that body has a right to make humble re- monstrances, if it sees any inconveniences attending the im- position ordered by the prince : a wise establishment for causing truth, and the cries of the people, to reach the ears of the sovereign, and for setting some bounds to his extrava- gance, or to the avidity of the ministers and persons con- cerned in the revenue.* (63) All money bills, imposing a tax, dis. But Peter, Count de Lara, vigor- must originate in and be passed by the ously opposed the measure, " contrac- House of Commons, and afterwards taque nobilium manu, ex conventu dis- submitted to the lords and the king for cedit, armis tueri paratus partam armis their sanction, before they can become et virtute a majoribus immunitatem, law. neque passurum affirmans nobilitatis (64) This was, of course, when Vattel opprimendae atque novis vectigalibus wrote, and before the Revolution. vexandae ab eo aditu initium fieri ; Mau- * Too great attention cannot be ros opprimere non esse tanti, ut gravi- used in watching the imposition of ori servitute rempublieam implicari si- taxes, which, once introduced, not only nant. Rex, periculo permotus, ab ea continue, but are so easily multiplied. cogitatione desistit. Petrum nobiles, Alphonso VIII. king of Castile, be- consilio communicato, quotannis convi- sieging a city belonging to the Moors vio excipere decreverunt, ipsum et pos- (Concham urbein in Celtiberis), and teros, navatse operee mercedem, rei being in want of money, applied to the gestaj bons-e posteritati monumentum, states of his kingdom for permission to documentumque ne quavis occasione impose, on every free inhabitant, a jus libertatis imminui patiantur." MA- capitation-tax of five golden marave- RIAXA. 187 112 OF PUBLIC, COMMON, AND BOOK i. The prince who is invested with the power of taxing his CHAP. xx. p e0 pi e OU ght by no means to consider the money thus raised g 243. Du- as his own property. He ought never to lose sight of the end ties of the f or -which this power was granted him : the nation was willing * ena ^ e n * provide, as it should seem best to his wisdom, for the necessities of the state. If he diverts this money to other uses, if he consumes it in idle luxury, to gratify his pleasures, to satiate the avarice of his mistresses and favour- ites, we hesitate not to declare to those sovereigns who are still capable of listening to the voice of truth, that such a one is not less guilty, nay, that he is a thousand times more so, than a private person who makes use of his neighbours' pro- perty to gratify his irregular passions. Injustice, though screened from punishment, is not the less shameful, g 244. Emi- Every thing in the political society ought to tend to the nent domain good of the community ; and, since even the persons, of the thHove to c iti zens are subject to this rule, their property cannot be ex- reignty. cepted. The state could not subsist, or constantly administer the public affairs in the most advantageous manner, if it had not a power to dispose occasionally of all kinds of property subject to its authority. It is even to be presumed, that, when the nation takes possession of a country, the property of cer- tain things is given up to the individuals only with this reserve. The right which belongs to the society, or to the sovereign, of disposing, in case of necessity, and for the public safety, of all the wealth contained in the state, is called the eminent domain. It is evident that this right is, in certain cases, necessary to him who governs, and consequently is a part of the empire, or sovereign power, and ought to be placed in the number of the prerogatives of majesty ( 45). When, therefore, the people confer the empire on any one, they at the same time invest him with the eminent domain, unless it be expressly reserved. Every prince, who is truly sovereign, is invested with this right when the nation has not excepted it, however limited his authority may be in other respects. If the sovereign disposes of the public property in virtue of his eminent domain, the alienation is valid, as having been made with sufficient powers. When, in a case of necessity, he disposes in like manner of the possessions of a community, or an individual, the aliena- tion will, for the same reason, be valid. But justice requires that this community, or this individual, be indemnified at the public charge : and if the treasury is not able to bear the expense, all the citizens are obliged to contribute to it ; for, the burdens of the state ought to be supported equally, or in [ 113 ] a just proportion. The same rules are applicable to this case as to the loss of merchandise thrown overboard to save the vessel. a 245. GO- Besides the eminent domain, the sovereignty gives a right vernment of of another nature over all public, common, and private pro- PRIVATE PROPERTY. 113 perty, that is, the empire, or the right of command in all BOOK r. places of the country belonging to the nation. The supreme CHAP - xx : power extends to every thing that passes in the state, wher- P ublic P r - ever it is transacted; and, consequently, the sovereign com- perty> mands in all public places, on rivers, on highways, in deserts, &c. Every thing that happens there is subject to his au- thority. In virtue of the same authority, the sovereign may make 246. The laws to regulate the manner in which common property is to superior be used, as well the property of the nation at large, as that ^ ^ e of distinct bodies or corporations. He cannot, indeed, take,.^^ 1 ^ away their right from those who have a share in that property : the use of but the care he ought to take of the public repose, and of the things pos- common advantage of the citizens, gives him doubtless a right sessed m to establish laws tending to this end, and, consequently, to regulate the manner in which things possessed in common are to be enjoyed. This affair might give room for abuses, and excite disturbances, which it is important to the state to pre- vent, and against which the prince is obliged to take just measures. Thus, the sovereign may establish wise laws with respect to hunting and fishing, forbid them in the seasons of propagation, prohibit the use of certain nets, and of every destructive method, &c. But, as it is only in the character of the common father, governor, and guardian of his people, that the sovereign has a right to make those laws, he ought never to lose sight of the ends which he is called upon to ac- complish by enacting them ; and if, upon those subjects, he makes any regulations with any other view than that of the public welfare, he abuses his power. A corporation, as well as every other proprietor, has a 247. Alien- right to alienate and mortgage its property : but the present ation f the members ought never to lose sight of the destination of that P r P ert y of joint property, nor dispose of it otherwise than for the ad- tion rponi vantage of the body, or in cases of necessity. If they alien- ate it with any other view, they abuse their power, and trans- gress against the duty they own to their own corporation and their posterity ; and the prince, in quality of common father, has a right to oppose the measure. Besides, the interest of the state requires that the property of corporations be not squandered away ; which gives the prince intrusted with the care of watching over the public safety, a new right to prevent the alienation of such property. It is then very proper to ordain in a state, that the alienation of the pro- perty of corporations should be invalid, without the consent of the superior powers. And indeed the civil law, in this respect, gives to corporations the rights of minors. But this is strictly no more than a civil law ; and the opinion of those who make the law of nature alone * sufficient authority to take from a corporation the power of alienating their pro- 189 114 OF PUBLIC, COMMON, AND BOOK i. perty without the consent of the sovereign, appears to me CHAP, xx. j. Q k e VQ - ( j Q f oun( j a ti onj an d contrary to the notion of pro- perty. A corporation, it is true, may have received pro- perty, either from their predecessors or from any other per- sons, with a clause that disables them from alienating it : but in this case they have only the perpetual use of it, not the entire and free property. If any of their property was solely given for the preservation of the body, it is evident that the corporation has not a right to alienate it, except in. a case of extreme necessity : and whatever property they may have received from the sovereign is presumed to be of that nature. 248. Use All the members of a corporation have an equal right to j! co e t mon the use of its common property. But, respecting the manner per y. ^ en j y' n g -^ ^ Q body of the corporation may make such regulations as they think proper, provided that those regula- tions be not inconsistent with that equality which ought to be preserved in a communion of property. Thus, a corpo- ration may determine the use of a common forest or pasture, either allowing it to all the members according to their wants or allotting to each an equal share ; but they have not a right to exclude any one of the number, or to make a distinc- tion to his disadvantage, by assigning him a less share than that of the others. 249. How All the members of a body having an equal right to its each mem- common property, each individual ought so to manage in ber is to en- ^ j n g advantage of it, as not in any wise to injure the com- mon use. According to this rule, an individual is not per- mitted to construct upon any river that is public property, any work capable of rendering it less convenient for the use of every one else, as, erecting mills, making a trench to turn the water upon his own lands, &c. If he attempts it, he ar- rogates to himself a private right, derogatory to the common right of the public. g 250. night The right of anticipation (jus prseventionis) ought to be of anticipa- faithfully observed in the use of common things which can- not be used by several persons at the same time. This name is given to the right which the first comer acquires to the use of things of this nature. For instance, if I am actually drawing water from a common or public well, another who comes after me cannot drive me away to draw out of it him- self: and he ought to wait till I have done. For, I make use of my right in drawing that water, and nobody can dis- turb me : a second, who has an equal right, cannot assert it to the prejudice of mine ; to stop me by his arrival would be arrogating to himself a better right than he allows me, and thereby violating the law of equality. j 251. The The same rule ought to be observed in regard to those same right common things which are consumed in using them. They 190 PRIVATE PROPERTY. 114 belong to the person who first takes possession of them with BOOK m. the intention of applying them to his own use : and a second, cnA ?- x gi who comes after, has no right to take them from him. I re- in another pair to a common forest, and begin to fell a tree : you come case- in afterwards, and would wish to have the same tree : you cannot take it from me : for this would be arrogating to your- self a right superior to mine, whereas our rights are equal. [ 115 ] The rule in this case is the same as that which the law of nature prescribes in the use of the productions of the earth before the introduction of property. The expenses necessary for the preservation or reparation 252. Pro of the things that belong to the public, or to a community, serration ought to be equally borne by all who have a share in them, a d re P airs , , , i_ j f j_i_ f common whether the necessary sums be drawn from the common possegs i ons> coffer, or that each individual contributes his quota. The nation, the corporation, and, in general, every collective body, may also establish extraordinary taxes, imposts, or annual contributions, to defray these expenses, provided there be no oppressive exaction in the case, and that the money so levied be faithfully applied to the use for which it was raised. To this end, also, as we have before observed ( 103), toll- duties are lawfully established. Highways, bridges, and causeways are things of a public nature, from which all who pass over them derive advantage : it is therefore just that all those pasengers should contribute to their support. We shall see presently that the sovereign ought to provide | 253. Duty for the preservation of the public property. He is no less and ri s h t f obliged, as the conductor of the whole nation, to watch over *|\ e ^^" thia the preservation of the property of a corporation. It is the respect? interest of the state at large that a corporation should not fall into indigence by the ill conduct of its members for the time being. And, as every obligation generates the corre- spondent right which is necessary to discharge it, the sove- reign has here a right to oblige the corporation to conform to their duty. If, therefore, he perceives, for instance, that they suffer their necessary buildings to fall to ruin, or that they destroy their forests, he has a right to prescribe what they ought to do, and to put his orders in force. We have but a few words to say with respect to private I 254. Pri- property : every proprietor has a right to make what use he vate P r - pleases of his own substance, and to dispose of it as he perfcy * pleases, when the rights of a third person are not involved in the business. The sovereign, however, as the father of his people, may and ought to set bounds to a prodigal, and to prevent his running to ruin, especially if this prodigal be the father of a family. (65) But he must take care not to (65) In Great Britain no such right person, or defrauds a person who has of interference exists, and a person may insured against fire. Co. Lit 254; Sa- lay waste or even burn his own property, villc's case, For. 6, 3 Thomas Co. Lit. unless he thereby endangers a third 243, n. (m). C. 191 115 OF PUBLIC, COMMON, AND PRIVATE PROPERTY. BOOK r. extend this right of inspection so far as to lay a restraint on JTHAP. xx. k' s gubjectg j n the administration of their affairs which would be no less injurious to the true welfare of the state than to the just liberty of the citizens. The particulars of this subject belong to public law and politics. 255. The It must also be observed, that individuals are not so per- sovereign f ec tly free in the economy or government of their affairs as iuo reguia- no * * ^ e su ^j ec t to the laws and regulations of police made tions of po- by the sovereign. For instahce, if vineyards are multiplied lice. to too great an extent in a country which is in want of corn, the sovereign may forbid the planting of the vine in fields proper for tillage ; for here the public welfare and the safety of the state are concerned. When a reason of such import- ance requires it, the sovereign or the magistrate may oblige [ 116 ] an individual to sell all the provisions in his possession above what are necessary for the subsistence of his family, and may fix the price he shall receive for them. (66) The public au- thority may and ought to hinder monopolies, and suppress all practices tending to raise the price of provisions to which practices the Romans applied the expressions annonam in- cendere, comprimere, vexare. $ 256. In- Every man may naturally choose the person to whom he heritances. -would leave his property after his death, as long as his right is not limited by some indispensable obligation as, for in- stance, that of providing for the subsistence of his children. (67) The children also have naturally a right to inherit their fa- ther's property in equal proportions. But this is no reason why particular laws may not be established in a state, with regard to testaments and inheritances a respect being, how- ever, paid to the essential laws of nature. Thus, by a rule established in many places with a view to support noble fami- lies, the eldest son is, of right, his father's principal heir. Lands perpetually appropriated to the eldest male heir of a family, belong to him by virtue of another right, which has its source in the will of the person who, being sole owner of those lands, has bequeathed them in that manner. (66) In Great Britain no such inter- (67) In England a parent has an abso- ference now takes place, though formerly lute right to devise or bequeath all his it was exercised. See 1 Bla. Com. property to a stranger in exclusion of 287. C. his children. 192 OF THE ALIENATION OF THE PUBLIC PROPERTY. 116 BOOK I. CHAP. XXI. CHAP. XXI. OF THE ALIENATION OF THE PUBLIC PROPERTY, OR THE DOMAIN, AND THAT OF A PART OF THE STATE. THE nation, being the sole mistress of the property in her 257. The possession, may dispose of it as she thinks proper, and may nation may lawfully alienate or mortgage it. This right is a necessary "JjJ* 1 * jj" consequence of the full and absolute domain : the exercise pe rty Pn of it is restrained by the law of nature only with respect to proprietors who have not the use of reason necessary for the management of their affairs ; which is not the case with a nation. Those who think otherwise, cannot allege any solid reason for their opinion ; and it would follow from their prin- ciples that no safe contract can be entered into with any na- tion ; a conclusion which attacks the foundation of all public treaties. But it is very just to say, that the nation ought carefully g 258. Du- to preserve her public property to make a proper use of ties of a na- it not to dispose of it without good reasons, nor to alienate tion in this or mortgage it but for a manifest public advantage, or in case respeck< of a pressing necessity. This is an evident consequence of the duties a nation owes to herself. The public property is extremely useful and even necessary to the nation ; and she cannot squander it improperly without injuring herself, and shamefully neglecting the duty of self-preservation. I speak of the public property, strictly so called, or the domain of the state. Alienating its revenues is cutting the sinews of government. As to the property common to all the citizens, the nation does an injury to those who derive advantage from it, if she alienates it without necessity, or without cogent [ 117 J reasons. She has a right to do this as proprietor of these possessions ; but she ought not to dispose of them except in a manner that is consistent with the duties which the body owes to its members. The same duties lie on the prince, the director of the na- f 259. u- tion : he ought to watch over the preservation and prudent tie . s * * he management of the public property to stop and prevent pnnce< all waste of it and not suffer it to be applied to improper uses. The prince, or the superior of the society, whatever he is, g 260. He being naturally no more than the administrator, and not the cannot proprietor of the state, his authority, as sovereign or head of the nation, does not of itself give him a right to alienate or mortgage the public property. The general rule then is, that the superior cannot dispose of the public property, as to its substance the right to do this being reserved to the proprietor alone, since proprietorship is defined to be the right to dispose 25 R 193 117 , OF THE ALIENATION OF BOOK i. of a thing substantially. If the superior exceeds his powers CHAP, xxi. w j t ]j respect to this property, the alienation he makes of it will be invalid, and may at any time be revoked by his suc- cessor, or by the nation. This is the law generally received in France ; and it was upon this principle that the duke of Sully* advised Henry IV. to resume the possession of all the domains of the crown alienated by his predecessors. 261. The The nation, having the fre t e disposal of all the property nation may belonging to her ( 257), may convey her right to the sove- right uTit' rc ig n > an d consequently confer upon him that of alienating and mortgaging the public property. But this right not being necessary to the conductor of the state, to enable him to ren- der the people happy by his government it is not to be pre- sumed that the nation have given it to him; and, if they have not made an express law for that purpose, we are to conclude that the prince is not invested with it, unless he has received full, unlimited, and absolute authority. 261. Rules The rules we have just established relate to alienations of on this sub- p UD li c property in favour of individuals. The question assumes TecMx* re ~ a different aspect when it relates to alienations made by one treaties be- nation to another :f it requires other principles to decide it in tween na- the different cases that may present themselves. Let us en- tion and deavour to give a general theory of them. 1. It is necessary that nations should be able to treat and contract validly with each other, since they would otherwise find it impossible to bring their affairs to an issue, or to obtain the blessings of peace with any degree of certainty. Whence it follows, that, when a nation has ceded any part of its pro- perty to another, the cession ought to be deemed valid and f 118 "j irrevocable, as in fact it is, in virtue of the notion of pro- perty. This principle cannot be shaken by any fundamental law by which a nation might pretend to deprive themselves of the power of alienating what belongs to them : for, this would be depriving themselves of all power to form contracts with other nations, or attempting to deceive them. A nation with such a law ought never to treat concerning its property : if it is obliged to it by necessity, or determined to do it for its own advantage, the moment it broaches a treaty on the subject, it renounces its fundamental law. It is seldom disputed that an entire nation may alienate what belongs to itself: but it is asked, whether its conductor, its sovereign, has this power ? The question may be determined by the fundamental laws. But, if the laws say nothing on this subject, then we have recourse to our second principle, viz. 2. If the nation has conferred the full sovereignty on its conductor if it has intrusted to him the care, and, without * See his Memoirs. t Quod domania regnorum inalien- contra alias gentes divino privilegio abilia et semper revocabilia dicuntur, opus foret. Leibnitz, Prafat. ad Cod. id respectu privatorum intelligitur ; nam Jur. Gent. Dip lumat. 194 THE PUBLIC PROPERTY. 118 reserve, given him the right, of treating and contracting with BOOK i. other states, it is considered as having invested him with all CHAP, xxi. the powers necessary to make a valid contract. The prince is then the organ of the nation : what he does is considered as the act of the nation itself; and, though he is not the owner of the public property, his alienations of it are valid, as being duly authorized. The question becomes more distinct, when it relates, not to 263. Alien- the alienation of some parts of the public property, but to ation of a the dismembering of the nation or state itself the cession^ ofthe of a town or a province that constitutes a part of it. This question, however, admits of a sound decision on the same principles. A nation ought to preserve itself ( 26) it ought to preserve all its members it cannot abandon them; and it is under an engagement to support them in their rank as mem- bers of the nation ( 17). It has not, then, a right to traffic with their rank and liberty, on account of any advantages it may expect to derive from such a negotiation. They have joined the society for the purpose of being members of it they submit to the authority of the state for the purpose of promoting in concert their common welfare and safety, and not of being at its disposal, like a farm or a herd of cattle. But the nation may lawfully abandon them in a case of ex- treme necessity ; and she has a right to cut them off" from the body, if the public safety requires it. When, therefore, in such a case, the state gives up a town or a province to a neighbour or to a powerful enemy, the cession ought to remain valid as to the state, since she had a right to make it: uor can she any longer lay claim to the town or province thus alienated, since she has relinquished every right she could have over it. But the province or town thus abandoned and dismembered 264 - from the state, is not obliged to receive the new master whom ^^^g m the state attempts to set over it. Being separated from the bered p art y" society of which it was a member, it resumes all its original rights ; and if it be capable of defending its liberty against the prince who would subject it to his authority, it may law- fully resist him. Francis I. having engaged, by the treaty [ 119 ] of Madrid, to cede the duchy of Burgundy to the emperor Charles V., the states of that province declared, " that, hav- ing never been subject but to the crown of France, they would die subject to it ; and that, if the king abandoned them, they would take up arms, and endeavour to set themselves at lib- erty, rather than pass into a new state of subjection."* It is true, subjects are seldom able to make resistance on such occasions ; and, in general, their wisest plan will be to submit to their new master, and endeavour to obtain the best terms they can. * Mezeray's History of France, vol. ii. p. 458. 119 OF THE ALIENATION OF THE PUBLIC PKOPERTY. 265. Whether the prince has power to dismcm- ber the state. Has the prince, or the superior of whatever kind, a power to dismember the state ? We answer as we have done with respect to the domain : if the fundamental laws forbid all dismemberment by the sovereign, he cannot do it without the concurrence of the nation or its representatives. But, if the laws are silent, and if the prince has received a full and ab- solute authority, he is then the depositary of the rights of the nation, and the organ by which it declares its will. The na- tion ought never to abandon its members but in a case of necessity, or with a view to the public safety, and to preserve itself from total ruin ; and the prince ought not to give them up except for the same reasons. But, since he has received an absolute authority, it belongs to him to judge of the neces- sity of the case, and of what the safety of the state requires. On occasion of the above-mentioned treaty of Madrid, the principal persons in France, assembled at Cognag after the king's return, unanimously resolved, " that his authority did not extend so far as to dismember the crown."* The treaty was declared void, as being contrary to the fundamental law of the kingdom : and, indeed, it had been concluded without sufficient powers : for, as the laws in express terms refused to the king the power of dismembering the kingdom, the con- currence of the nation was necessary for that purpose ; and it might give its consent by the medium of the states-general. Charles V. ought not to have released his prisoner before those very states had approved the treaty ; or rather,- making a more generous use of his victory, he should have imposed less rigorous conditions, such as Francis I. would have been able to comply with, and such as he could not, without dis- honour, have refused to perform. But now that there are no longer any meetings of the states-general in France, the king remains the sole organ of the state, with respect to other powers : these latter have a right to take his will for that of all France ; and the cessions the king might make them would remain valid, in virtue of the tacit consent by which the nation has vested the king with unlimited powers to treat with them. Were it otherwise, no solid treaty could be en- tered into with the crown of France. For greater security, [ 120 ] however, other powers have often required that their treaties should be registered in the parliament of Paris ; but at present even this formality seems to be laid aside. * Mezeray's History of France, vol. ii. p. 458. 196 OF RIVERS, STREAMS, AND LAKES. 120 BOOK I. CHAP. xxn. CHAP. XXII. OF RIVERS, STREAMS, AND LAKES. WHEN a nation takes possession of a country, with a view 266. A ri- to settle there, it takes possession of every thing included in ver that se- it, as lands, lakes, rivers, &c. But it may happen that the country is bounded and separated from another by a river ; in which case, it is asked, to whom this river belongs. It is manifest, from the principles established in Chap. XVIII., that it ought to belong to the nation who first took possession of it. This principle cannot be denied ; but the difficulty is, to make the application. It is not easy to determine which of the two neighbouring nations was the first to take possession of a river that separates them. For the decision of such questions, the rules which may be deduced from the principles of the law of nations are as follow : 1. When a nation takes possession of a country bounded by a river, she is considered as appropriating to herself the river also : for, the utility of a river is too great to admit a supposition that the nation did not intend to reserve it to her- self. Consequently, the nation that first established her do- minion on one of the banks of the river is considered as being the first possessor of all that part of the river which bounds her territory. When there is question of a very broad river, this presumption admits not of a doubt, so far, at least, as relates to a part of the river's breadth ; and the strength of the presumption increases or diminishes in an inverse ratio with the breadth of a river ; for, the narrower the river is, the more does the safety and convenience of its use require that it should be subject entirely to the empire and property of that nation. (68) 2. If that nation has made any use of the river, as, for navigating or fishing, it is presumed with the greatest cer- tainty that she has resolved to appropriate the river to her own use. 3. If, of two nations inhabiting the opposite banks of the river, neither party can prove that they themselves, or those whose rights they inherit, were the first settlers in those tracts, it is to be supposed that both nations came there at the same time, since neither of them can give any reason for claiming the preference ; and in this case the dominion of each will extend to the middle of the river. (*) (68) As regards private rights, there Doug. 411. {Palmer v. Hicks, 6 Johns, is no legal presumption that the soil Rep. 133.} of a navigable river belongs to the own- (1) { 5 Wheat Rep. 374, 379 j 3 Mass, ers of the adjoining lands, ex utraque Rep. 147.} parte, or otherwise. Bex v. Smith, 2 B2 197 120 OP RIVERS, STREAMS, AND LAKES. BOOK i. 4. A long and undisputed possession establishes the right CHAP. xxn. Q nations, (69) otherwise there could be no peace, no stabi- lity between them ; and notorious facts must be admitted to prove the possession. Thus, when from time immemorial a nation has, without contradiction, exercised the sovereignty [ 121 ] upon a river which forms her boundary, nobody can dis- pute with that nation the supreme dominion over the river in question. 5. Finally, if treaties determine any thing on this question, they must be observed. To decide it by accurate and express stipulations, is the safest mode ; and such is, in fact, the me- thod taken by most powers at present. 267. Of If a river leaves its bed, whether it be dried up or takes the bed of a its course elsewhere, the bed belongs to the owner of the f lv ! r . ^ hlch river ; for, the bed is a part of the river ; and he who had is dried up. '.'- . . / i ,, -, or takes an- appropriated to himself the whole, had necessarily appro- other course, priated to himself all its parts. The If a territory which terminates on a river has no other right of ai- boundary than that river, it is one of those territories that hmon.(70) j laye na t ura ] or indeterminate bounds (territoria arcifinia), and it enjoys the right of alluvion ; that is to say, every gra- dual increase of soil, every addition which the current of the river may make to its bank on that side, is an addition to that territory, stands in the same predicament with it, and belongs to the same owner. For, if I take possession of a piece of land, declaring that I will have for its boundary the river which washes its side, or if it is given to me upon that footing, I thus acquire, beforehand, the right of allu- vion ; and, consequently, I alone may appropriate to myself whatever additions the current of the river may insensibly make to my land : I say " insensibly," because in the very uncommon case called avulsion, when the violence of the stream separates a considerable part from one piece of land and joins it to another, but in such manner that it can still be identified, the property of the soil so removed naturally continues vested in its former owner. The civil laws have thus provided against and decided this case, when it happens be- tween individual and individual ; they ought to unite equity with the welfare of the state, and the care of preventing litigations. In case of doubt, every territory terminating on a river is presumed to have no other boundary than the river itself; because nothing is more natural than to take a river for a (69) Aa to what ia a sufficiently long 178 ; 4 Dowl. A Ry. 790 ; 3 Barn. & and undisturbed possession, by the law Cres. 91, S. C.; 5 Bing. 163, 169; 1 of France, Jersey, and England, in Thomas Co. Lit. 47, in note ; Scultes on general, see Eenett v. Pipon, Knapp's Aquatic Rights ; Chitty's General Prac- Rep. 67. tice, 199, 200. {2 Johns. Rep. 322; 3 (70) As to the rights of alluvion, or Mass. Rep. 325; 2 Hall's L. Journ. 307; gudden derelict in general, see The King 5 Hall's L. Journ. 1, 113.} v. Yarborough, 1 Dow Rep. New Series, 198 OF RIVERS, STREAMS, AND LAKES. 121 boundary, when a settlement is made ; and wherever there is BOOK i. a doubt, that is always to be presumed which is most natural CHAP - xxn - and most probable. As soon as it is determined that a river constitutes the g 269. Whe- boundary line between two territories, whether it remains com- ther aiiu- mon to the inhabitants on each side of its banks, or whether vion P r - each shares half of it, or, finally, whether it belongs entirely c j^t"n to one of them, their rights with respect to the river are in t ho rfght to no wise changed by the alluvion. If, therefore, it happens, a river, that, by a natural effect of the current, one of the two terri- tories receives an increase, while the river gradually en- croaches on the opposite bank, the river still remains the na- tural boundary of the two territories, and notwithstanding the progressive changes in its course, each retains over it the same rights which it possessed before ; so that, if, for instance, it be divided in the middle between the owners of the oppo- site banks, that middle, though it changes its place, will con- tinue to be the line of separation between the two neighbours. The one loses, it is true, while the other gains ; but nature alone produces this change : she destroys the land of the one, [ 122 ] while she forms new land for the other. The case cannot be otherwise determined, since they have taken the river alone for their limits. But if, instead of a gradual and progressive change of its g 270. bed, the river, by an accident merely natural, turns entirely What is the out of its course, and runs into one of the two neighbouring J^ e r 7^ n states, the bed which it has abandoned becomes, thencefor- * h ^ " r ita ward, their boundary, and remains the property of the for- bed. mer owner of the river ( 267) ; the river itself is, as it were, annihilated in all that part, while it is reproduced in its new bed, and there belongs only to the state in which it flows. This case is very different from that of a river which changes its course without going out of the same state. The latter, in its new course, continues to belong to its former owner, whether that owner be the state, or any individual to whom the state has given it ; because rivers belong to the public in whatever part of the country they flow. Of the bed which it has abandoned, a moiety accrues to the contigu- ous lands on each side, if they are lands that have natural boundaries, with the right of alluvion. That bed (notwith- standing what we have said in 267) is no longer the pro- perty of the public, because of the right of alluvion vested in the owners of its banks, and because the public held pos- session of the bed only on account of its containing a river. But, if the adjacent lands have not natural boundaries, the public still retains the property of the bed. The new soil over which the river takes its course is lost to the proprietor, because all the rivers in the country belong to the public. It is not allowable to raise any works on the bank of &%2n. river, which have a tendency to turn its course, and to cast Works 199 122 OF RIVERS, STREAMS, AND LAKES. BOOK i. it upon the opposite bank : this would be promoting our own CHAP, xxn. a( jvantage a ^ our neighbour's expense. Each can only secure tending to himself, and hinder the current from undermining and carry- current 6 1 S &Way ^ ^^ ^ TviT^or in ^ n g enera ^ no person ought to build on a river, any more general, ' than elsewhere, any work that is prejudicial to his neigh- prejudicial hour's rights. If a river belongs to one nation, and another to the rights h as an incontestible right to navigate it, the former cannot (73)* efS erect upon it a dam or a mill which might render it unfit for navigation. The right which the owners of the river possess in this case is only that of a limited property ; and, in the exercise of it, they are bound to respect the rights of others, g 273. Rules But, when two different rights to the same thing happen to in relation clash with each other, it is not always easy to determine to interfer- wn i cn ought to yield to the other : the point cannot be satis- mg ng s. f ac j- or j}y decided, without attentively considering the nature of the rights, and their origin. For example, a river belongs to me, but you have a right to fish in it : and the question is, whether I may erect mills on my river, whereby the fishery will become more difficult and less advantageous ? The na- [ 123 ] ture of our rights seems to determine the question in the affirmative. I, as proprietor, have an essential right over the river itself: you have only a right to make use of it a right which is merely accessory, and dependent on mine ; you have but a general right to fish as you can in my river, such as you happen to find it, and in whatever state I may think fit to possess it. I do not deprive you of your right by erect- ing my mills : it still exists in the general view of it ; and, if it becomes less useful to you, it is by accident, and because it is dependent on the exercise of mine. (74) The case is different with respect to the right of naviga- tion, of which we have spoken. This right necessarily sup- poses that the river shall remain free and navigable, and therefore excludes every work that will entirely interrupt its navigation. The antiquity and origin of the rights serve, no less than their nature, to determine the question. The more ancient (71) This principle of the law of in the current. Rex v. Paghnm, 8 Barn, nations has been ably discussed as part to the former ; for, it could only be established on this foot- ing, unless the possessor of the first right has expressly con- sented to its being limited. In the same manner, rights ceded by the proprietor of any thing are considered as ceded without prejudice to the other rights that belong to him, and only so far as they are consist- ent with these latter, unless an express declaration, or the very nature of the right, determine it otherwise. If I have ceded to another the right of fishing in my river, it is mani- fest that I have ceded it without prejudice to my other rights, and that I remain free to build on that river such works as I think proper, even though they should injure the fishery, pro- vided they do not altogether destroy it. (75) A work of this latter kind, such as a dam that would hinder the fish from ascending it, could not be built but in case of necessity, and on making, according to circumstances, an adequate compen- sation to the person who has a right to fish there. What we have said of rivers and streams, may be easily 274. applied to lakes. Every lake, entirely included in a country, Lakes - belongs to the nation that is the proprietor of that country ; for in taking possession of a territory, a nation is considered as having appropriated to itself every thing included in it ; and, as it seldom happens that the property of a lake of any con- siderable extent falls to the share of individuals, it remains common to the nation. If this lake is situated between two states, it is presumed to be divided between them at the mid- dle, while there is no title, no constant and manifest custom, to determine otherwise. What has been said of the right of alluvion, in speaking of g 275. In- rivers, is also to be understood as applying to lakes. When crease of a a lake which bounds a state belongs entirely to it, every in- lake ' crease in the extent of that lake falls under the same predi- cament as the lake itself; but it is necessary that the increase should be insensible, as that of land in alluvion, and moreover that it be real, constant, and complete. To explain myself more fully, 1. 1 speak of insensible increase: this is the reverse of alluvion ; the question here relates to the increase of a lake, as, [ 124 ] in the other case, to an increase of soil. If this increase be not insensible, if the lake, overflowing its banks, inundates a large tract of land, this new portion of the lake, this tract thus covered with water, still belongs to its former owner. Upon what principles can we found the acquisition of it in behalf of the owner of the lake? The space is very easily identified, though it has changed its nature : and it is too considerable to admit a presumption that the owner had no intention to preserve it to himself, notwithstanding the changes that might happen to it. (75) See note 74, ante, p. 122. 124 OF RIVERS, STREAMS, AND LAKES. BOOK i. But, 2. If the lake insensibly undermines a part of the CHAP, xxii. pp OS it e territory, destroys it, and renders it impossible to be known, by fixing itself there, and adding it to its bed, that part of the territory is lost to its former owner ; it no longer exists ; and the whole of the lake thus increased still belongs to the same state as before. 3. If some of the lands bordering on the lake are only over- flowed at high water, this transient accident cannot produce any change in their dependence. The reason why the soil which the lake invades by little and little belongs to the owner of the lake and is lost to its former proprietor, is, because the proprietor has no other boundary than the lake, nor any other marks than its banks, to ascertain how far his posses- sions extend. If the water advances insensibly, he loses ; if it retires in like manner, he gains : such must have been the intention of the nations who have respectively appropriated to themselves the lake and the adjacent lands : it can scarce- ly be supposed that they had any other intention. But a territory overflowed for a time is not confounded with the rest of the lake : it can still be recognised ; and the owner may still retain his right of property in it. Were it other- wise, a town overflowed by a lake would become subject to a different government during the inundation, and return to its former sovereign as soon as the waters were dried up. 4. For the same reasons, if the waters of the lake, pene- trating by an opening into the neighbouring country, there form a bay, or new lake, joined to the first by a canal, this new body of water and the canal belong to the owner of the country in which they are formed. For the boundaries are easily ascertained : and we are not to presume an intention of , relinquishing so considerable a tract of land in case of its happening to be invaded by the waters of an adjoining lake. It must be observed that we here treat the question as arising between two states : it is to be decided by other princi- ples when it relates to proprietors who are members of the same state. In the latter case, it is not merely the bounds of the soil, but also its nature and use, -that determine the possession of it. An individual who possesses a field on the borders of a lake, cannot enjoy it as a field when it is over- flowed ; and a person who has, for instance, the right of fish- ing in the lake, may exert his right in this new extent : if the [ 125 ] waters retire, the field is restored to the use of its former owner. If the lake penetrates by an opening into the low lands in its neighbourhood, and there forms a permanent in- undation, this new lake belongs to the public, because all lakes belong to the public. 276. Land The same principles show, that if the lake insensibly forms formed on an accession of land on its banks, either by retiring or in any the banks O ther manner, this increase of land belongs to the country ' which it joins, when that country has no other boundary than 202 ' OP THE SEA. 125 It is the same thing as alluvion on the banks of BOOK i. CHAP. XXII. the lake. ,, . the river. But, if the lake happened to be suddenly dried up, either 277. Bed totally or in a great part of it, the bed would remain in the of . a lake possession of the sovereign of the lake ; the nature of the soil, so easily known, sufficiently marking out the limits. The empire or jurisdiction over lakes and rivers is subject ? 278. Ju- to the same rules as the property of them, in all the cases di 1 ti n which we have examined. Each state naturally possesses it r * over the whole or the part of which it possesses the domain. We have seen ( 245) that the nation, or its sovereign, com- mands in all places in its possession. CHAP. XXIII. OF THE SEA. (76) CHAP. xxin. IN order to complete the exposition of the principles of the 279. Ttj law of nations with respect to the things a nation may pos- sea > and its sess, it remains to treat of the open sea. The use of the open use< sea consists in navigation, and in fishing ; along its coasts it is moreover of use for the procuring of several things found near the shore, such as shell-fish, amber, pearls, &c., for the (76) As to the dominion of the main seas, and right to limit the passage there- on, and the claim of the English in the British seas and elsewhere, in general, see the authorities collected in 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, 88 to 108. With re- spect to the view taken by the English law of rights in and connected with the sea and sea-shore, the doctrine is, that the sea is the property of the king ; and that so is the land beneath, except such part of that land as is capable of being usefully occupied without prejudice to navigation, and of which a subject has either had a grant from the king, or has so exclusively used it for so long a time as to confer on him a title by pro- scription. In the latter case, a pre- sumption is raised that the king has either granted him an exclusive right to it, or has permitted him to have pos- session of it, and to employ his money and labour upon it, so as to confer upon him a title by occupation, the founda- tion of most of the rights to property in land. This is the law of England, and also of Jersey, and some other islands belonging to Great Britain. Senest v. Pipon, Knapp's Rep. 67; Blundett v. Cotterall, 5 Bar. & Aid. 268,- and The King v. Lord Yarborotigh, 3 Bar. A Cres. 91, and 1 Dow's Appeal Cases, New Series, 178. In the first mentioned case, it was decided that the lord of a manor cannot establish a claim to the exclusive right of cutting sea-weed on rocks below low-water mark, except by a grant from the king, or by such long and undis- turbed enjoyment of it (viz. at least for twenty years continuously) as to give him a title by prescription ; and that the possession necessary to constitute a title by prescription must be uninter- rupted and peaceable, both according to the law of England, the civil law, and those of France, Normandy, and Jersey. But, where artificial cuts or recesses have been made on the sea-shore, into and over which the sea afterwards flows, then, in the absence of proof as to acts of ownership, the soil of these recesses is to be presumed to have belonged to the owner of the adjacent estate, and not to the crown. Lowe v. Govett, 3 Bar. & Adol. 863. C. 203 125 OF THE SEA. BOOK r. making of salt, and finally, for the establishment of places of CHAP, xxni. re t rea t an d security for vessels. g 280. Whe- The open sea is not of such a nature as to admit the holding t'her the sea possession of it, since no settlement can be formed on it, so can be pos- as J.Q nm( j er others from passing. But a nation powerful at itTdomi" 1 sea mav f rD id others to fish in it and to navigate it ; declar- nion appro- ing that she appropriates to herself the dominion over it, and priated. that she will destroy the vessels that shall dare to appear in it without her permission. Let us see whether she has a right to do this. g 281. No- It is manifest that the use of the open sea, which consists body has a in navigation and fishing, is innocent and inexhaustible ; that right to ap- j s to g ne k nav ior a tes or fishes in the open sea does no propnate to . . r' , e , . , , tc himself the in j ur j to any one, and the sea, in these two respects, is sum- use of the cient for all mankind. Now, nature does not give to man a open sea. right of appropriating to himself things that may be inno- cently used, and that are inexhaustible, and sufiicient for all. For, since those things, while common to all, are sufiicient to supply the wants of each, whoever should, to the exclusion of all other participants, attempt to render himself sole pro- T 126 ] prietor of them, would unreasonably wrest the bounteous gifts of nature from the parties excluded. The earth no longer furnishing, without culture, the things necessary or useful to the human race, who were extremely multiplied, it became necessary to introduce the right of property, in order that each might apply himself with more success to the cultivation of what had fallen to his share, and multiply, by his labour, the necessaries and conveniences of life. It is for this reason the law of nature approves the rights of dominion and pro- perty, which put an end to the primitive manner of living in common. But this reason cannot apply to things which are in themselves inexhaustible; and, consequently, it cannot furnish any just grounds for seizing the exclusive possession of them. If the free and common use of a thing of this na- ture was prejudicial or dangerous to a nation, the care of their own safety would authorize them to reduce that thing under their own dominion, if possible, in order to restrict the use of it by such precautions as prudence might dictate to them. But this is not the case with the open sea, on which people may sail and fish without the least prejudice to any person whatsoever, and without putting any one in danger. No nation, therefore, has a right to take possession of the open sea, or claim the sole use of it, to the exclusion of other nations. The kings of Portugal formerly arrogated to them- selves the empire of the seas of Guinea and the East Indies;* but the other maritime powers gave themselves little trouble about such a pretension. The right of navigating and fishing in the open sea being * See Grotius's Mare Liberum, and Selden's Mare Clausum, lib. i. cap. xrii. 204 OF THE SEA. 126 then a right common to all men, the nation that attempts to BOOK r. exclude another from that advantage does her an injury, and CHAP- XX111 ' furnishes her with sufficient grounds for commencing hostili- 282. The ties, since nature authorizes a nation to repel an injury that nation that is, to make use of force against whoever would deprive her J^JJJJ 8 to of her rights. another, Nay, more, a nation, which, without a legitimate claim, does it an would arrogate to itself an exclusive right to the sea, and jtfjjy- support its pretensions by force, does an injury to all nations ; jj ven ' doeg it infringes their common right ; and they are justifiable in a n injury to forming a general combination against it, in order to repress all nations, such an attempt. Nations have the greatest interest in caus- ing the law of nations, which is the basis of their tranquil- lity, to be universally respected. If any one openly tram- ples it under foot, they all may and ought to rise up against him ; and, by uniting their forces to chastise the common enemy, they will discharge their duty towards themselves, and towards human society, of which they are members (Prelim. 22). However, as every one is at liberty to renounce his right, 284. it a nation may acquire exclusive rights of navigation and fish- ma y acquiro ing, by treaties, in which other nations renounce in its favour a . n B1 the rights they derive from nature. The latter are obliged " s to observe their treaties ; and the nation they have favoured has a right to maintain by force the possession of its advan- tages. Thus, the house of Austria has renounced, in favour [ 127 ] of England and Holland, the right of sending vessels from the Netherlands to the East Indies. In G-rotius, de Jure Belli et Pads, lib. ii. cap. iii. 15, may be found many instances of similar treaties. As the rights of navigation and of fishing, and other rights 285. but which may be exercised on the sea, belong to the class of not ; b 7 ? re * those rights of mere ability (jura merce facultatis), which ^^g are imprescriptible ( 95), they cannot be lost for want of use. U se,(77) Consequently, although a nation should happen to have been, from time immemorial, in sole possession of the navigation or fishery in certain seas, it cannot, on this foundation, claim an exclusive right to those advantages. For, though others have not made use of their common right to navigation and fishery in those seas, it does not thence follow that they have had any intention to renounce it ; and they are entitled to exert it whenever they think proper. (78) But it may happen that the non-usage of the right may 286. un- assume the nature of a consent or tacit agreement, and thus less b ^ vir ; become a title in favour of one nation against another. When ^ u * " a nation that is in possession of the navigation and fishery (77) See observations and authorities, tion not successfully litigated will pre- 1 Chit. Com, L. 287, n. 4, 5. vent a right, see the judgment in JBenest (78) As to the effect of twenty years' v. Pipon, Knapp's Rep. 67. C. uninterrupted use, and what interrup- 8 205 127 OF THE SEA. BOOK i. in certain tracts of sea claims an exclusive right to them, and CHAP, xxm. forfodg a j} participation on the part of other nations, if the others obey that prohibition with sufficient marks of acquies- cence, they tacitly renounce their own right in favour of that nation, and establish for her a new right, which she may after- wards lawfully maintain against them, especially when it is confirmed by long use. (79) 287. The The various uses of the sea, near the coasts render it very sea near the susce ptible of property. It furnishes fish, shells, pearls, am- becomeT 7 ^er, & c - ^ow, * n a11 ^ ese respects, its use is not inexhausti- property. ble : wherefore, the nation, to whom the coasts belong, may appropriate to themselves, and convert to their own profit, an advantage which nature has so placed within their reach as to enable them conveniently to take possession of it, in the same manner as they possessed themselves of the domi- nion of the land they inhabit. Who can doubt that the pearl fisheries of Bahrem and Ceylon may lawfully become pro- perty ? And though, where the catching of fish is the only object, the fishery appears less liable to be exhausted, yet, if a nation have on their coast a particular fishery of a profita- ble nature, and of which they may become masters, shall they not be permitted to appropriate to themselves that bounteous gift of nature, as an appendage to the country they possess, and to reserve to themselves the great advantages which their commerce may thence derive in case there be a sufficient abundance of fish to furnish the neighbouring nations ? But if, so far from taking possession of it, the nation has once acknowledged the common right of other nations to come and fish there, it can no longer exclude them from it ; it has left that fishery in its primitive freedom, at least with respect to those who have been accustomed to take advantage of it. The English not having originally taken exclusive possession of the herring fishery on their coasts, it is become common [ 128 ] to them with other nations. g 288. An- A nation may appropriate to herself those things of which other reason t ne f ree an( j common use would be prejudicial or dangerous f 'riatin >r the * ^ er ' ^*" 8 ia a second reason for which governments ex- seaVorder- 6 * en ^ their dominion over the sea along their coasts as far as ing on the they are able to protect their right. It is of considerable im- coasts. (80) portance to the safety and welfare of the state that a general liberty be not allowed to all comers to approach so near their possessions, especially with ships of war, as to hinder the ap- proach of trading nations, and molest their navigation. Dur- ing the war between Spain and the United Provinces, James L, king of England, marked out along his coasts certain bound- aries, within which he declared that he would not suffer any of the powers at war to pursue their enemies, nor even allow (79) See further, 1 Chit Com. L. 94, (80) See further, 1 Chit. Com. L. 92, n. 1 ; ib. 98, a. 1. C. n. 2 ; ib. 94, n. 1 ; ib. 95, n. 1 ; Puff. b. 3, c. 3, a. 6, p. 69. C. 206 OF THE SEA. 128 their armed vessels to stop and observe the ships that should BOOK i. enter or sail out of the ports.* These parts of the sea, thus CHAP ' XXI "' subject to a nation, are comprehended in her territory ; nor must any one navigate them without her consent. But, to vessels that are not liable to suspici9n, she cannot, without a breach of duty, refuse permission to approach for harmless purposes, since it is a duty incumbent on every proprietor to allow to strangers a free passage, even by land, when it may be done without damage or danger. It is true that the state itself is sole judge of what is proper to be done in every par- ticular case that occurs ; and, if it judges amiss, it is to blame : but the others are bound to submit. It is otherwise, however, in cases of necessity, as, for instance, when a ves- sel is obliged to enter a road which belongs to you, in order to shelter herself from a tempest. In this case, the right of entering wherever we can, provided we cause no damage, or that we repair any damage done, is, as we shall show more at large, a remnant of the primitive freedom of which no man can be supposed to have divested himself; and the vessel may lawfully enter in spite of you, if you unjustly refuse her permission. It is not easy to determine to what distance a nation may 289. How extend its rights over the sea by which it is surrounded. Bo- far * his P S - dinusf pretends, that according to the common right of all ^^ ? 8 ^ maritime nations, the prince's dominion extends to the distance of thirty leagues from the coast. But this exact determina- tion can only be founded on a general consent of nations, which it would be difficult to prove. Each state may, on this head, make what regulation it pleases so far as respects the transactions of the citizens with each other, or their concerns with the sovereign : but, between nation and nation, all that can reasonably be said is, that in general, the dominion of the state over the neighbouring sea extends as far as her safety renders it necessary and her power is able to assert it ; since, on the one hand, she cannot appropriate to herself a thing that is common to all mankind, such as the sea, except so far as she has need of it for some lawful end ( 281), and, on the other, it would be a vain and ridiculous pretension to claim a [ 129 ] right which she were wholly unable to assert. The fleets of England have given room to her kings to claim the empire of the seas which surround that island, even as far as the opposite coasts. | Selden relates a solemn act, by which it appears, that, in the time of Edward I., that empire was acknowledged by the greatest part of the maritime nations of Europe ; and the republic of the United Provinces acknowledged it, in some * Selden's Mare Clausum, lib. ii. f In his Republic, book i. c. x. (81) See further, Puff. b. 4, c. 5, s. 9, j See Selden's Mare Clausum. pp. 167, 8; 1 Chit. Com. L. 99, n. 1 ; g Ibid. lib. 2, cap. xxviii. ib. 100, n. 1 ; ib. 101, n. 2 ; ib. 101, n. 4; ib.287, n. 7; ib. 441, n. 5. 207 lUy OF THE SEA. BOOK i. measure, by the treaty of Breda, in 1667, at least so far as CHAP, xxin. re | a ted to the honours of the flag. But solidly to establish a right of such extent, it were necessary to prove very clearly the express or tacit consent of all the powers concerned. The French have never agree4 to this pretension of England ; and, in that very treaty of Breda just mentioned, Louis XIV. would not even suffer the channel to be called the English channel, or the British sea. The republic of Venice claims the empire of the Adriatic, and everybody knows the ceremony annually performed upon that account. In confirmation of this right we are referred to the examples of Uladislaus, king of Naples, of the emperor Frederic III., and of some of the kings of Hungary, who asked permission of the Venetians for their vessels to pass through that sea.* That the empire of the Adriatic belongs to the republic to a certain distance from her coasts, in the places of which she can keep possession, and of which the possession is important to her own safety, appears to me incontestable : but I doubt very much whether any power is at present disposed to acknowledge her sovereignty over the whole Adriatic sea. Such pretensions to empire are respected as long as the nation that makes them is able to assert them by force ; but they vanish of course on the decline of her power. At present the whole space of the sea within cannon shot of the coast is considered as making a part of the territory ; and, for that reason, a vessel taken under the cannon of a neutral fortress is not a lawful prize. (82) g 290. The shores of the sea incontestably belong to the nation Shores and that possesses the country of which they are a part ; and they ports. (83) b e l on g to the class of public things. If civilians have set them down as things common to all mankind (res communes), it is only in regard to their use ; and we are not thence to conclude that they considered them as independent of the empire : the very contrary appears from a great number of laws. Ports and harbours are manifestly an appendage to and even a part of the country, and consequently are the property of the nation. Whatever is said of the land itself will equally apply to them, so far as respects the consequences of the domain and of the empire. I 291. Bays All we have said of the parts of the sea near the coast, may and straits, be said more particularly, and with much greater reason, of ( 84 ) roads, bays, and straits, as still more capable of being pos- [ 130 ] sessed, and of greater importance to the safety of the country. But I speak of bays and straits of small extent, and not of * See Selden's Mare Clausum, lib. i. right to cut sea-weed on rocks situate cap. xvi. below low-water mark, but by express (82) Pott, b. 3, c. 7, g 132, p. 344. C. grant from the king, or uninterrupted (83) See further 1 Chitty's Com- presumption. Benest v. Pipon, Knapp's mercial Law, 100, n. 2. The sea-shore, Rep. 67. below low-water mark, primd facie be- (84) See 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, longs to the king and all his subjects, 100, n. 3. C. and no subject can claim an exclusive 208 OP THE SEA. 130 those great tracts of sea to which these names are sometimes BOOK i. given, as Hudson's Bay and the Straits of Magellan, over CHAP - XXIIt - which the empire cannot extend, and still less a right of pro- perty. A bay, whose entrance can be defended, may be pos- sessed and rendered subject to the laws of the sovereign ; and it is important that it should be so, since the country might be much more easily insulted in such a place, than on the coast that lies exposed to the winds and the impetuosity of the waves. It must be remarked, with regard to straits, that, when 292. they serve for a communication between two seas, the naviga- straits in tion of which is common to all, or several nations, the nation which possesses the strait cannot refuse the others a passage through it, provided that passage be innocent and attended with no danger to herself. By refusing it without just reasons, she would deprive those nations of an advantage granted them by nature ; and indeed, the right to such a passage is a rem- nant of the primitive liberty enjoyed by all mankind. No- thing but the care of his own safety can authorize the owner of the strait to make use of certain precautions, and to require certain formalities, commonly established by the custom of nations. He has a right to levy a moderate tax on the ves- sels that pass, partly on account of the inconvenience they give him, by obliging him to be on his guard partly as a return for the safety he procures them by protecting them from their enemies, by keeping pirates at a distance, and by defraying the expense attendant on the support of light-houses, sea-marks, and other things necessary to the safety of mari- ners. Thus, the king of Denmark requires a custom at the straits of the Sound. Such j ight ought to be founded on the same reasons, and subject to the same rules, as the tolls estab- lished on land, or on a river. (See 103 and 104.) It is necessary to mention the right to wrecks a right which 293. was the wretched offspring of barbarism, and which has almost Ri s ht to everywhere fortunately disappeared with its parent. Justice wrecks< ( 86 ) and humanity cannot allow of it, except in those cases only where the proprietors of the effects saved from a wreck cannot possibly be discovered. In such cases, those effects belong to the person who is the first to take possession of them, or to the sovereign, if the law reserves them for him. If a sea is entirely enclosed by the territories of a nation, 294. A and has no other communication with the ocean than by a se . a enclosed channel of which that nation may take possession, it appear s^J^*^ that such a sea is no less capable of being occupied, and be- a nation! coming property, than the land ; and it ought to follow the (85) See 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, in general modern cases, Ship Augusta, 101, n. 1. C. 1 Hagg. Rep. 16 ; and The Bailiffs, &c., (86) The right to wreck is not unfre- of Dumcich v. Sterry, 1 Barn. & Adolph. quently the subject of litigation in the 831. C. Municipal Courts of Great Britain ; see 27 s 2 209 130 OF THE SEA. BOOK r. fate of the country that surrounds it. The Mediterranean, CHAP, xxiii. j n f ormer times, was absolutely enclosed within the territories of the Romans ; and that people, by rendering themselves masters of the strait which joins it to the ocean, might subject the Mediterranean to their empire, and assume the dominion over it. They did not, by such procedure, injure the rights of other nations ; a particular sea being manifestly designed [ 131 ] by nature for the use of the countries and nations that sur- round it. Besides, by barring the entrance of the Mediter- ranean against all suspected vessels, the Romans, by one single stroke, secured the immense extent of their coasts : and this reason was sufficient to authorize them to take possession of it. And, as it had absolutely no communication but with the states which belonged to them, they were at liberty to permit or prohibit the entrance into it, in the same manner as into any of their towns or provinces. 295. The When a nation takes possession of certain parts of the sea, parts of the ^ takes possession of the empire over them, as well as of the ed^Ta* 688 " domain, on the same principle which we advanced in treating power are of the land ( 205). These parts of the sea are within the within its jurisdiction of the nation, and a part of its territory : the jurisdiction, sovereign commands there ; he makes laws, and may punish those who violate them ; in a word, he has the same rights there as on land, and, in general, every right which the laws of the state allow him. It is, however, true that the empire and the domain, or pro- perty, are not inseparable in their own nature, even in a sove- reign state.* As a nation may possess the domain or pro- perty of a tract of land or sea, without having the sovereignty of it, so it may likewise happen that she shall possess the sovereignty of a place, of which the property or the domain, with respect to use, belongs to some other nation. But it is always presumed, that, Avhen a nation possesses the useful domain of any place whatsoever, she has also the higher do- main and empire, or the sovereignty ( 205). We cannot, however, from the possession of the empire, infer, with equal probability, a coexistent possession of the useful domain ; for, a nation may have good reasons for claiming the empire over a country, and particularly over a tract of sea, with- out pretending to have any property in it, or any useful do- main. The English have never claimed the property of all the seas over which they have claimed the empire. (88) (87) See further, 1 Chitty's Commer- mercial Law, 101, 2, 3. As to the cial Law, 95, n. 3 ; Qrotius, b. 2, c. 3, a. duty of the flay, or the obligation upon 13, p. 166. C. other nations to pay a particular mark * See Book II. 83. of respect to British men-of-war, by (88) As to the British seas, and the striking their flag or lowering their claims of the English of empire over topsail, formerly claimed, and so ob- the seas in general, see Selden's Mare noxious to foreign shipping, see id. Clausum, b. 2, c. 1, p. 182, and other 101, 2 ; Molloy, b. 1, c. 5, ss. 11 ; and authorities collected 1 Chitty's Com- see Postlewaite's Diet, tit Sea, British ; 210 OF THE SEA. 131 This is all we have to say in this first book. A more mi- BOOK i. nute detail of the duties and rights of a nation, considered in CHAP - xxlir - herself, would lead us too far. Such detail must, as we have already observed, be sought for in particular treatises on the public and political law. We are very far from flattering ourselves that we have omitted no important article ; this is a slight sketch of an immense picture : but an intelligent reader will without difficulty supply all our omissions by mak- ing a proper application of the general principles : we have taken the utmost care solidly to establish those principles, and to develop them with precision and perspicuity. Marten's L. Nat. 168, 9172, 175 ; Com. tween ships, see Court de Droit Public Dig. Navigation, A. And, as to the Interne et Externe, torn. 2, p. 30 to 84, French view of the right of the sea, and id. 396 to 406. C. and of the respects to be observed "03- 211 133 BOOK II. OF A NATION CONSIDERED IN ITS RELATION TO OTHERS. CHAP. I. OF THE OFFICES OF HUMANITY BETWEEN NATIONS. t. Foun- 1 HE following maxims will appear very strange to cabinet tion'of politicians ; and such is the misfortune of mankind, that, to II. datio t e common manv O f those re fined conductors of nations, the doctrine of and mutual , . J . .,, . , . . .. ' duties of this chapter will be a subject of ridicule. Be it so ; but we nations, will, nevertheless, boldly lay down what the law of nature prescribes to nations. Shall we be intimidated by ridicule, when we speak after Cicero ? That great man held the reins of the most powerful state that ever existed ; and in that station he appeared no less eminent than at the bar. The punctual observance of the law of nature he considered as the most salutary policy to the state. In my preface, I have already quoted this fine passage Nihil est quod adhuc de republica putem dictum, et quo possim longius progredi, nisi sit confirmatum, non modo falsum esse illud, sine injuria non posse, sed hoc verissimum, sine summa justitia rempublicam regi non posse.* I might say on good grounds, that, by the words summa justitia, Cicero means that universal justice which consists in completely fulfilling the law of nature. But in another place he explains himself more clearly on this head, and gives us sufficiently to understand that he does not [ 134 ] confine the mutual duties of men to the observance of justice, properly so called. "Nothing," says he, "is more agree- able to nature, more capable of affording true satisfaction, than, in imitation of Hercules, to undertake even the most arduous and painful labours for the benefit and preservation of all nations." Magis est secundum naturam, pro omnibus gentibus, si fieri possit, conservandis aut juvandis, maximos labores molestiasque suscipere, imitantem Herculem ilium, quem hominum fama, beneficiorum memor, in concilium cce- lestium collocavit, quam vivere in solitudine, non modo sine * Fragm. ex lib. ii. De Republica. 212 COMMON DUTIES OF A NATION, ETC. 13-1 ullis molestiis, sed etiam in maximis voluptatibus, dbundan- BOOK n. tern omnibus copiis, ut excellas etiam pulchritudine et viribus. CHAP ' Ij Quocirca optima quisque et splendidissimo ingenio longe illam vitam Jiuic anteponit.* In the same chapter, Cicero ex- pressly refutes those who are for excluding foreigners from the benefit of those duties to which they acknowledge them- selves bound towards their fellow-citizens. Qui autem civium rationem dicunt habendam, externorum negant, hi dirimunt communem humani generis societatem; qua sublata, benefi- centia, liberalitas, bonitas, justitia, funditus tollitur ; quse qui tollunt, etiam adversus Deos immortales impii judicandi sunt; ab Us enim constitutam inter homines societatem ever- tunt. And why should we not hope still to find, among those who are at the head of affairs, some wise individuals who are convinced of this great truth, that virtue is, even for sove- reigns and political bodies, the most certain road to prosperity and happiness ? There is at least one benefit to be expected from the open assertion and publication of sound maxims, which is, that even those who relish them the least are there- by laid under a necessity of keeping Avithin some bounds, lest they should forfeit their characters altogether. To flatter ourselves with the vain expectation that men, and especially men in power, will be inclined strictly to conform to the laws of nature, would be a gross mistake ; and to renounce all hope of making impression on some of them, would be to give up mankind for lost. Nations, being obliged by nature reciprocally to cultivate human society (Prelim. 11), are bound to observe towards each other all the duties which the safety and advantage of that society require. The offices of humanity are those succours, those duties, I 2. Offices which men owe to each other, as men, that is, as social be- of humani - ings formed to live in society, and standing in need of mu - theiTfoun tual assistance for their preservation and happiness, and to dation. enable them to live in a manner conformable to their nature. Now, the laws of nature being no less obligatory on nations than on individuals (Prelim. 5), whatever duties each man oives to other men, the same does each nation, in its way. owe to other nations (Prelim. 10, &c.). Such is the foundation of those common duties of those offices of humanity to which nations are reciprocally bound towards each other. They consist, generally, in doing every thing in our power [ 1-35 ] for the preservation and happiness of others, as far as such conduct is reconcilable with our duties towards ourselves. The nature and essence of man, who, without the assist- 3. Gene- ance of his fellow-men, is unable to supply all his wants, to ral P rlnci P le preserve himself, to render himself perfect, and to live hap- ^ u ^ a * J u _ ties of nh- * De Officiis, lib. iii. cap. 5. tious. 213 135 COMMON DUTIES OF A NATION BOOK n. pily, plainly show us that he is destined to live in society, in _ CHAP. i. ^ e interchange of mutual aid ; and, consequently, that all men are, by their very nature and essence, obliged to unite their common efforts for the perfection of their own being and that of their condition. The surest method of succeed- ing in this pursuit is, that each individual should exert his efforts first for himself and then for others. Hence it fol- lows, that, whatever we owe to ourselves, we likewise owe to others, so far as they stand in 'need of assistance, and we can grant it to them without being wanting to ourselves. Since, then, one nation, in its way, otves to another nation every duty that one man owes to another man, we may confidently lay down this general principle : one state owes to another state whatever it owes to itself, so far as that other stands in real need of its assistance, and the former can grant it without neglecting the duties it owes to itself. Such is the eternal and immutable law of nature. Those who might be alarmed at this doctrine, as totally subversive of the maxims of sound policy, will be relieved from their apprehensions by the two following considerations : 1. Social bodies or sovereign states are much more capa- ble of supplying all their wants than individual men are ; and mutual assistance is not so necessary among them, nor so frequently required. Now, in those particulars which a nation can itself perform, no succour is due to it from others. 2. The duties of a nation towards itself, and chiefly the care of its own safety, require much more circumspection and reserve than need be observed by an individual in giving as- sistance to others. This remark we shall soon illustrate. 4. Duties Of all the duties of a nation towards itself, the chief ob- of a nation ject is its preservation and perfection, together with that of servationTf itS State ' The detail givifT ALL men ought to find on earth the things they stand in tfonofTa"- n eed of. In the primitive state of communion, they took them tions to car- wherever they happened to meet with them, if another had ry on mu- no t before appropriated them to his own use. The introduc- merce m ^ on ^ Dominion an( ^ property could not deprive men of so essential a right; and, consequently, it cannot take place without leaving them, in general, some mean of procuring what is useful or necessary to them. This mean is commerce ; by it every man may still supply his wants. Things being now become property, there is no obtaining them without the owner's consent, nor are they usually to be had for nothing ; but they may be bought, or exchanged for other things of equal value. Men are, therefore, under an obligation to carry on that commerce with each other, if they wish not to deviate from the vieius of nature ; and this obligation extends also to whole nations or states (Prelim. 5). It is seldom that nature is seen in one place to produce every thing necessary for the use of man ; one country abounds in corn, another in pastures and cattle, a third in timber and metals, &c. If all those countries trade together, as is agreeable to human nature, no [ 144 ] one of them will be without such things as are useful and necessary ; and the views of nature, our common mother, will be fulfilled. Further, one country is fitter for some kind of products than another, as, for instance, fitter for the vine than for tillage. If trade and barter take place, every nation, on the certainty of procuring what it wants, will employ its land and its industry in the most advantageous manner, and man- kind in general prove gainers by it. Such are the foundations of the general obligation incumbent on nations reciprocally to cultivate commerce. (97) (97) The restrictions on trade, which freedom being very favourable to corn- have been enforced absolutely or con- merce, it is implied in the duties of na- ditionally, by almost all the powerful tions that they should support it as far nations of the world, have been the as possible, instead of cramping it by cause of a thousand wars, and the unnecessary burdens or restrictions; ground-work of innumerable treaties; and this position is supported by the and, therefore, it is important that we reasons thus urged by Vattel (supra, should give them full consideration. g 21). With respect to the freedom of trade, It was this feeling that influenced it has been laid down by the wisest of that celebrated statesman, Mr. Pitt, in politicians and best of men, that every concluding the commercial treaty with nation ought not only to countenance France, in 1786. Great Britain and trade as far as it reasonably can, but France had, for centuries before, con- even to protect and favour it; and that, trary to every sound principle of policy, 224 MUTUAL COMMERCE OF NATIONS. 144 Every nation ought, therefore, not only to countenance BOOKII. trade, as far as it reasonably can, but even to protect and fa- CHAP - " vour it. The care of the public roads, the safety of travel- 22. They lers, the establishment of ports, of places of sale, of well- should fa- regulated fairs, all contribute to this end. And, where these vour tra(le ' are attended with expense, the nation, as we have already ob- served (Book I. 103), may, by tolls and other duties equita- bly proportioned, indemnify itself for its disbursements. Freedom being very favourable to commerce, it is implied, 23. Free- in the duties of nations, that they should support it as far as dom of possible, instead of cramping it by unnecessary burdens or restrictions. Wherefore, those private privileges and tolls, which obtain in many places, and press so heavily on corn- acted as rival enemies,* and their com- mercial policy was dictated by the same spirit which prompted their un- happy wars; insomuch, that, though they possessed the materials of a most extensive commerce the one abound- ing in all that art and industry can supply, and the other in productions of a more favoured soil and climate the exchange of their peculiar produce was discouraged bjr a complicated sys- tem of restraint and heavy duties.f The object of the commercial treaty alluded to was, to abolish those per- nicious restraints, and, by connecting the two countries in the bonds of a reciprocal trade, to pledge them, by their mutual interest, to an oblivion of their ancient animosities. The view in which that treaty originated was ex- plained by Mr. Pitt, when it was sub- mitted to Parliament; and the senti- ments which he expressed gave to this measure a remarkable character of moderation and wisdom. In reply to an argument inculcating constant jealousy of France,^ he inquired, " whether, in using the word jealousy, it was meant to recommend to this country such a species of jealousy as should be either mad or blind, such a species of jealousy as should induce her either madly to throw away what was to make her happy, or blindly grasp at that which must end in her rum 1 Was the ne- cessity of a perpetual animosity with France so evident and so pressing that for it we were to sacrifice every com- mercial advantage we might expect from a friendly intercourse with that country 1 or, was a pacific connection between the two kingdoms so highly offensive that even an extension of com- merce could not counterpoise it 1" To- wards the close of the same speech, he observes, " The quarrels between France and Britain had too long oon- tinued to harass not only those two great nations themselves, but had fre- quently embroiled the peace of Europe ; nay, had disturbed the tranquillity of the most remote parts of the world. They had, by their past conduct, acted as if they were intended for the de- struction of each other ; but he hoped the time was now come when they should justify the order of the universe, and show that they were better calcu- lated for the more amiable purposes of friendly intercourse and mutual bene- volence." "Considering the treaty," he continued, " in a political view, he should not hesitate to contend against the too frequently advanced doctrine, that France was and must be the un- alterable enemy of Britain ; his mind revolted from this position as monstrous and impossible. To suppose that any nation was unalterably the enemy of another, was weak and childish: it had neither its foundation in the expe- rience of nations nor in the history of man. It was a libel on the constitution of political societies, and supposed diabo- lical malice in the original frame of man." C. * 2 Smith's Wealth of Nations, pp. 226-7, 252-3 ; Tucker's Pamphlet, Cm Bono. f See Smith's Wealth of Nations, vol. 4, 169, per Buchanan; and see An- derson's Hist. Com. vol. 4, pp. 634 to 639. *9 225 144 MUTUAL COMMERCE OF NATIONS. BOOK ii. merce, are deservedly to be reprobated, unless founded on CHAP, ii. ver y important reasons arising from the public good. 24. Right Every nation, in virtue of her natural liberty, has a right of trading, to trade with those who are willing to correspond with such belonging to ntent j ong . an( j to mo i es ^ her i n ^he exercise of her right is doing her an injury. (98) The Portuguese, at the time of their great power in the East Indies, were for excluding all other European nations front any commerce with the In- dians ; but such a pretension, no less iniquitous than chime- rical, was treated with contempt ; and the other nations agreed to consider any acts of violence in support of it, as just grounds for making war against the Portuguese. ^Chis common right of all nations is, at present, generally acknow- ledged under the appellation of freedom of trade. 25. Each But, although it be in general the duty of a nation to nation is carry on commerce Avith others, and, though each nation has sole judge & right to trade with those countries that are willing to en- of the pro- . . , , , . , p , . priety of courage her on the other hand, a nation ought to decline a commerce commerce which is disadvantageous or dangerous (Book I. on her own 98) ; and since, in case of collision, her duties to herself are part.(99) paramount to her duties to others, she has a full and clear right to regulate her conduct, in this respect, by the consi- deration of what her advantage or safety requires. We have already seen (Book I. 92), that each nation is, on her own part, the sole judge whether or not it be convenient for her to cultivate such or such branch of commerce. She may, there- fore, either embrace or reject any commercial proposals from foreign nations, without affording them any just grounds to accuse her of injustice, or to demand a reason for such re- fusal, much less to make use of compulsion. She is free in [ 145 ] the administration of her affairs, without being accountable to any other. The obligation of trading with other nations is in itself an imperfect obligation (Prelim. 17), and gives them only an imperfect right ; so that, in cases where the commerce would be detrimental, that obligation is entirely void. When the Spaniards attacked the Americans, under a pretence that those people refused to traffic with them, they only endeavoured to throw a colourable veil over their own insatiable avarice. 26. Ne- These few remarks, together with what we have already cessity of __ commercial ^ Jt ig & general ^ of the law positioni It there seems that an ex _ of nations, that, in time of peace, no elusive trade may be acquired by a nation is entitled to limit or impose treaty with the nations of India who regulations upon the commerce which have not before entered into a rcstrio any other independent state may think tive treaty. See also 1 Chit. Com. L. fit to carry on, either externally, with 76. C. the natives of other independent states, (99) See further, 1 Chit. Com. L. or internally, amongst its own subjects. 80, n. 2 ; Grotius, 158 ; Puff. b. 4, c. 6, Puffend. b. 4, c. 5, s. 10, p. 168 ; Mar- s. 10, p. 168. ten's L. N. 152-3 ; where sec the dif- (100) See, more fully, 1 Chitty's ferent authorities in support of this Com. L. 35. 226 MUTUAL COMMERCE OF NATIONS. 145 said on the subject (Book I. Chap. VIII.), may suffice to BOOK n. establish the principles of the natural law of nations respect- CHAP - " ing the mutual commerce of states. It is not difficult to point out, in general, what are the duties of nations in this respect, and what the law of nature prescribes to them for the good of the great society of mankind. But, as each na- tion is only so far obliged to carry on commerce with others as she can do it without being wanting to herself, and as the whole ultimately depends on the judgment that each state may form of what it can and ought to do in particular cases, nations cannot count on any thing more than generalities, such as, the inherent liberty of each to carry on trade, and, moreover, on imperfect rights, which depend on the judgment of others, and, consequently, are ever uncertain'. Where- fore, if they wish to secure to themselves any definite and constant advantages, they must procure them by treaties. Since a nation has a full right to regulate herself in com- 27. Gene- mercial affairs by what is useful or advantageous to her, she ral rale . may make such commercial treaties as she thinks proper ; and no other nation has a right to take offence, provided those treaties do not affect the perfect rights of others. If, by the engagements contracted, a nation, unnecessarily, or without powerful reasons, renders herself incapable of join- ing in the general trade which nature recommends between nations, she trespasses against her duty. But, the nation being the sole judge in this case (Prelim. 16), other nations are bound to respect her natural liberty to acquiesce in her determination, and even to suppose that she is actuated by substantial reasons. Every commercial treaty, therefore, which does not impair the perfect right of others, is allowa- ble between nations ; nor can the execution of it be lawfully opposed. But those commercial treaties alone are in them- selves just and commendable, which pay to the general inte- rest of mankind as great a degree of respect as is possible and reasonable in the particular case. As express promises and engagements should be inviolable, 28. Duty every wise and virtuous nation will be attentive to examine of nations and weigh a commercial treaty before she concludes it, an to take care that she be not thereby engaged to any thing tieg * contrary to the duties which she owes to herself and others. Nations may, in their treaties, insert such clauses and con- 29. Per- ditions as they think proper ; they are at liberty to make P etual or them perpetual, or temporary, or dependent on certain events. Jj^^fr It is usually most prudent not to engage for ever, as circum- p^^g i stances may afterwards intervene, by which the treaty might t j- eaties re . become very oppressive to one of the contracting parties. A vocable at nation may confine a treaty to the grant of only a precarious pleasure, right reserving to herself the liberty of revoking it at plea- sure. We have already observed (Book I. 94) that a simple permission does not, any more than long custom (Ibid. 95), 146 MUTUAL COMMERCE OF NATIONS. BOOK n. give any perfect right to a trade. These things namely. CHAP, n. permission and customs are therefore not to be confounded with treaties, not even with those which give only a preca- rious right. so. No- When once a nation has entered into engagements by thing con- treaty, she is no longer at liberty to do, in favour of others, tenor of a con t rai T t tne tenor of the treaty, what she might otherwise treaty can have granted to them agreeably to the duties of humanity or be granted the general obligation of mutual commerce ; for she is to do to a third f or others no more than what is in her power ; and, having party- deprived herself of the liberty of disposing of a thing, that thing is no longer in her power. Therefore, when a nation has engaged to another that she will sell certain merchandise or produce to the latter only as, for instance, corn she can no longer sell it to any other. The case is the same in a contract to purchase certain goods of that nation alone. 31. How But it will be asked, how and on what occasions a nation far lawful to may enter into engagements which deprive her of the liberty Slat "the 7 to fulfil her duties to others - As the duties we owe to our - liberty of selves are paramount to those we owe to others, if a nation trading with finds her safety and substantial advantage in a treaty of this other na- nature, she is unquestionably justifiable in contracting it, espe- tions> cially as she does not thereby interrupt the general commerce of nations, but simply causes one particular branch of her own commerce to pass through other hands, or insures to a particular people certain things of which they stand in need. If a state which stands in need of salt can secure a supply of it from another, by engaging to sell her corn and cattle only to that other nation, who will doubt but that she has a right to conclude so salutary a treaty ? In this case, her corn or cattle are goods which she disposes of for supplying her own wants. But, from what we have observed ( 28), engage- ments of this kind are not to be entered into without very good reasons. However, be the reasons good or bad, the treaty is still valid, and other nations have no right to op- pose it ( 27). 32. A na- Every one is at liberty to renounce Ms right ; a nation, tion may therefore, may lay a restriction on her commerce in favour corameroe ^ anotner nation, and engage not to traffic in a certain kind in favour of ^ goods, or to forbear trading with such and such a country, another. &c. And, in departing from such engagements, she acts against the perfect right of the nation with which she has con- tracted, and the latter has a right to restrain her. The natural liberty of trade is not hurt by treaties of this nature ; for that liberty consists only in every nation being unmolested in her right to carry on commerce with those that consent to [ 147 ] traffic with her; each one remaining free to embrace or de- cline a particular branch of commerce, as she shall judge most advantageous to the state. Nations not only carry on trade for the sake of procuring MUTUAL COMMERCE OF NATIONS. 147 necessary or useful articles, but also with a view to make it BOOK n. a source of opulence. Now, wherever a profit is to be made, CHAP, n. it is equally lawful for every one to participate in it : but the 33. A na- niost diligent may lawfully anticipate the others by taking tion may possession of an advantage which lies open to the first occu- a PP r P riate pier ; he may even secure the whole entirely to himself, if ^2^. he has any lawful means of appropriating it. When, there- branch of fore, a particular nation is in sole possession of certain articles, trade, another nation may lawfully procure to herself by treaty the advantage of being the only buyer, and then sell them again all over the world. And, as it is indifferent to nations from what hand they receive the commodities they want, provided they obtain them at a reasonable price, the monopoly of this nation does not clash with the general duties of humanity, provided that she do not take advantage of it to set an un- reasonable and exorbitant price on her goods. Should she, by an abuse of her monopoly, exact an immoderate profit, this would be an offence against the law of nature, as, by such an exaction, she either deprives other nations of a necessary or agreeable article which nature designed for all men, or obliges them to purchase it at too dear a rate : nevertheless, she does not do them any positive wrong, because, strictly speak- ing, and according to external right, the owner of a commo- dity may either keep it or set what price he pleases on it. Thus, the Dutch, by a treaty with the king of Ceylon, have wholly engrossed the cinnamon trade : yet, whilst they keep their profits within just limits, other nations have no right to complain. But, were the necessaries of life in question were the monopolist inclined to raise them to an excessive price other nations would be authorized by the care of their own safety, and for the advantage of human society, to form a general combination in order to reduce a greedy oppressor to reasonable terms. The right to necessaries is very different from that to things adapted only to convenience and pleasure, which we may dispense with if they be too dear. It would be absurd that the subsistence and being of other nations should depend on the caprice or avidity of one. Among the modern institutions for the advantage of com- 34. Con- merce, one of the most useful is that of consuls, or persons suk - ( 11 ) (101) See further as to consuls, post, and see decisions Albreton v. Sussman, B. 4, ch. 8, s. 75, p. 461. This and 2 Ves. & B. 323 ; 4 Bar. & Cres. 886; the following sections are much too 8 Moore's Rep. 632; 7 T. R. 251 ; concise upon the important subject of 8 East, 364 ; 2 Chalm. Opin. 294. A consuls. See more fully 1 Chitty's foreign consul cannot sue a merchant Commercial Law, 48 to 73 ; statute here for any supposed services in that 6 Geo. 4, c. 87 ; Warden on Consular character De Lima v. Haldimand, Establishments, Paris, A. p. 1813; 1 R yan & Moody, 45 : nor is he pri- Madame de Steck, a Berlin, 1790 ; vileged from arrest, Vweash v. Belcher, Anderson's Hist. Commerce, index, 3 Mau. & Selw. 284. {He is liable titles, Conservator," and Consul ;" as garnishee in the case of a foreign U 229 147 MUTUAL COMMERCE OF NATIONS. BOOK ii. residing in the large trading cities, and especially the sea- CHAP. ii. _ p 0r t s> O f foreign countries, with a commission to watch over the rights and privileges of their nation, and to decide dis- putes between her merchants there. When a nation trades largely with a country, it is requisite to have there a person charged with such a commission : and, as the state which allows of this commerce mus.t naturally favour it, for the same reason, also, it must admit the consul. But, there being no absolute and perfect obligation to this, the nation [ 148 ] that wishes to have a consul, must procure this right by the commercial treaty itself. The consul being charged with the affairs of his sovereign, and receiving his orders, continues his subject, and account- able to him for his actions. The consul is no public minister (as will appear by what we shall say of the character of ministers, in our fourth book), and cannot pretend to the privileges annexed to such character. Yet, bearing his sovereign's commission, and being in this quality received by the prince in whose dominions he resides, he is, in a certain degree, entitled to the protection of the law of nations. This sovereign, by the very act of receiving him, tacitly engages to allow him all the liberty and safety necessary to the proper discharge of his functions, without which the admission of the consul would be nugatory and delusive. The functions of a consul require, in the first place, that he be not a subject of the state where he resides : as, in this case, he would be. obliged in all things to conform to its orders, and thus not be at liberty to acquit himself of the duties of his office. They seem even to require that the consul should be inde- rdent of the ordinary criminal justice of the place where resides, so as not to be molested or imprisoned unless he himself violate the law of nations by some enormous crime. And, though the importance of the consular functions be not so great as to procure to the consul's person the inviola- bility and absolute independence enjoyed by public ministers, yet, being under the particular protection of the sovereign who employs him, and intrusted with the care of his concerns, if he commits any crime, the respect due to his master requires that he should be sent home to be punished. Such is the mode pursued by states that are inclined to preserve a good understanding with each other. But the surest way is, expressly to settle all these matters, as far as practicable, by the commercial treaty. attachment in the State courts, Kid- Ravara, 2 Ball. Rep. 297; Conim. v. der/mv. J fl%er,2Miles'sRep.242; and Kozloff, 5 Serg. & Rawle, 545; The to indictment for misdemeanour in the State v. De la Forest, 2 Nott & McCord's courts of the United States, which Rep. 545, contra.} have exclusive jurisdiction, U. States v. 230 DIGNITY AND EQUALITY OF NATIONS. 148 Wicquefort, in his treatise of The Ambassador, Book I. BOOK n. 5, says, that consuls do not enjoy the protection of the law CHAP - " of nations, and that, both in civil and criminal cases, they are subject to the justice of the place where they reside. But the very instances he quotes contradict his proposition. The states-general of the United Provinces, whose consul had been affronted and put under arrest by the governor of Cadiz, com- plained of it to the court of Madrid as a breach of the law of nations. And, in the year 1634, the republic of Venice was near coming to a rupture with pope Urban VIII. on account of the violence offered to the Venetian consul by the governor of Ancona. The governor, suspecting this consul to have given information detrimental to the commerce of An- cona, had persecuted him, seized his furniture and papers, and caused him to be summoned, declared guilty of contumacy, and banished under pretence that, contrary to public prohi- bition, he had caused goods to be unloaded in a time of con- [ 149 ] tagion. This consul's successor he likewise imprisoned. The Venetian senate warmly insisted on having due satisfaction: and, on the interposition of the ministers of France, who were apprehensive of an open rupture, the pope obliged the governor of Ancona to give the republic satisfaction accordingly. In default of treaties, custom is to be the rule on these occasions ; for, a prince, who receives a consul without ex- press conditions, is supposed to receive him on the footing established by custom. CHAP. III. OF THE DIGNITY AND EQUALITY OF NATIONS OF TITLES, AND CHAP, in. OTHER MARKS OF HONOUR. EVERY nation, every sovereign and independent state, 35. Dig- deserves consideration and respect, because it makes an im- nit y of na - mediate figure in the grand society of the human race, is tions r independent of all earthly power, and is an assemblage of a great number of men, which is, doubtless, more considerable than any individual. The sovereign represents his whole nation ; he unites in his person all its majesty. No indivi- dual, though ever so free and independent, can be placed in competition with a sovereign ; this would be putting a single person upon an equality with a united multitude of his equals. Nations and sovereigns are, therefore, under an obligation, and at the same time have a right, to maintain their dignity, and to cause it to be respected, as being of the utmost im- portance to their safety and tranquillity. 231 149 DIGNITY AND EQUALITY OF NATIONS. BOOK ii. We have already observed (Prelim. 18) that nature has CHAP, in. established a perfect equality of rights between independent 3G. Their nations. Consequently, none can naturally lay claim to any equality, superior prerogative : for, whatever privileges any one of them derives from freedom and sovereignty, the others equally derive the same from the same source. 37. Pre- And since precedency or pre-eminence of rank is a prero- cedency. gative, no nation, no sovereign", can naturally claim it as a right. Why should nations that are not dependent on him give up any point to him against their will ? However, as a powerful and extensive state is much more considerable in universal society than a small state, it is reasonable that the latter should yield to the former on occasions where one must necessarily yield to the other, as, in an assembly, and should pay it those mere ceremonial deferences which do not, in fact, destroy their equality, and only show a superiority of order, a first place among equals. Other nations will natu- rally assign the first place to the more powerful state ; and it would be equally useless as ridiculous for the weaker one obstinately to contend about it. The antiquity of the state enters also into consideration on these occasions : a new [ 150 ] comer cannot dispossess any one of the honours he has en- joyed ; and he must produce very strong reasons, before he can obtain a preference. 38. The The form of government is naturally foreign to this ques- formofgo- tion. The dignity, the majesty, resides originally in the vemmentis b 0( jy O f t ^ e state . t j lat O f t h e sovereign is derived from his thhTques- representing the nation. And, can it be imagined that a tion. state possesses more or less dignity according as it is governed by a single person or by many ? At present kings claim a superiority of rank over republics : but this pretension has no other support than the superiority of their strength. For- merly, the Roman republic considered all kings as very far beneath them : but the monarchs of Europe, finding none but feeble republics to oppose them, have disdained to admit them to an equality. The republic of Venice, and that of the United Provinces, have obtained the honours of crowned heads ; but their ambassadors yield precedency to those of kings. 39. A In consequence of what we have just established, if the state ought f orm O f government in a nation happens to be changed, she rank^nof 8 w ^ 8 *^ preserve the same honours and rank of which she withstand- was before in possession. When England had abolished roy- ing any alty, Cromwell would suffer no abatement of the honours that changes in na ^ been paid to the crown or to the nation; and he every- itT f om- f where maintained the English ambassadors in the rank they ment . had always possessed. 40. In If * ne grades of precedency have been settled by treaties, this respect, or by long custom founded on tacit consent, it is necessary treaties and to conform to the established rule. To dispute with a prince DIGNITY AND EQUALITY OP NATIONS. 150 the rank he has acquired in this manner, is doing him an BOOK n. injury, inasmuch as it is an expression of contempt for him, CHAP, m. or a violation of engagements that secure to him a right, established Thus, by the injudicious partition between the sons of Charle- customs magne, the elder having obtained the empire, the younger, ou g ht * be who received the kingdom of France, yielded precedency to serve ' him the more readily, as there still remained at that time a recent idea of the majesty of the real Roman empire. His successors followed the rule they found established : they were imitated by the other kings of Europe ; and thus the imperial crown continues to possess, without opposition, the first rank in Christendom. With most of the other crowns, the point of precedency remains yet undetermined. Some people would have us to look upon the precedency of the emperor as something more than the first place among equals ; they would fain attribute to him a superiority over all kings, and, in a word, make him the temporal head of Christendom.* And it, in fact, appears that many empe- rors entertained ideas of such pretensions, as if, by reviving the name of the Roman empire, they could also revive its rights. Other states have been on their guard against these pretensions. We may see in Mezeray f the precautions taken [ 151 ] by king Charles V. when the emperor Charles IV. visited France, "for fear," says the historian, "lest that prince, and his son, the king of the Romans, should found any right of superiority on his courtesy." Bodinus relates,! that "the French took great offence at the Emperor Sigismund's placing himself in the royal seat in full parliament, and at his having knighted the Senechal de Beaucaire," adding, that, "to repair the egregious error they had committed in suffering it, they would not allow the same emperor, when at Lyons, to make the Count of Savoy a duke." At present, a king of France would doubtless think it a degradation of his dignity, were he to intimate the most distant idea that another might claim any authority in his kingdom. || As a nation may confer on her conductor what degree of 41. Of the authority and what rights she thinks proper, she is equally name ***& * Bartolus went so far as to say, that Count Provana, the king of Sardinia's " all those were heretics who did not minister, to sign a deed, in which he believe that the emperor was lord of the declared that neither his own sovereign whole earth." See Bodinus's Republic, nor any other prince had a right to dis- book i. ch. ix. p. m. 139. pute pre-eminence with the emperor. t History of France, explanation of Its contents being made public, the the medals of Charles V. kings made such heavy complaints on j In his Republic, p. 138. the occasion, that Provana was re- U Pentherrieder, minister plenipo- called, and the emperor ordered his tentiary of the emperor at the congress minister to suppress the deed, affect- of Cambray, made an attempt to insure ing, at the same time, a profound igno- to his master an incontestable superi- ranee of the whole transaction : and ority and pre-eminence over all the thus the affair was dropped. Memoirs other crowned heads. He induced of Mons. de St. Philippe, vol. iv. p. 194. 30 u 2 233 151 DIGNITY AND EQUALITY OF NATIONS. BOOK ii. free in regard to the name, the titles, and honours with CHAP, in. -which she may choose to decorate him. But discretion and given by the the care of her reputation require that she should not, in nation to its this respect, deviate too far from the customs commonly conductor, established among civilized nations. Let us further observe, that, in this point, she ought to be guided by prudence, and inclined to proportion the titles and honours of her chief to the power he possesses, and 'to the degree of authority with which she chooses to invest him. Titles and honours, it is true, determine nothing : they are but empty names, and vain ceremonies, when they are misplaced : yet, who does not know how powerful an influence they have on the minds of mankind? This is, then, a more serious affair than it appears at the first glance. The nation ought to take care not to debase herself before other states, and not to degrade her chief by too humble a title : she ought to be still more careful not to swell his heart by a vain name, by unbounded honours, so as to inspire him with the idea of arrogating to himself a commensurate authority over her, or of acquiring a proportionate power by unjust conquests. On the other hand, an exalted title may engage the chief to support, with greater firmness, the dignity of the nation. Prudence is guided by circumstances, and, on every occasion, keeps within due bounds. "Royalty," says a respectable author, who may be believed on this subject, "rescued the house of Brandenburg from that yoke of servitude under which the house of Austria then kept all the German princes. This was a bait which Frederic I. threw out to all his pos- terity, saying to them, as it were, I have acquired a title for [ 152 ] you ; do you render yourselves worthy of it : I have laid the foundations of your greatness ; it is you who are to finish the work."* 42. Whe- If the conductor of the state is sovereign, he has in his ther a sove- hands the rights and authority of the political society ; and reign may consequently he may himself determine what title he will what title assume, and what honours shall be paid to him, unless these and honours have been already determined by the fundamental laws, or he pleases, that the limits which have been set to his power manifestly oppose such as he wishes to assume. His subjects are equally obliged to obey him in this as in whatever he commands by virtue of a lawful authority. Thus, the Czar Peter I., grounding his pretensions on the vast extent of his dominions, took upon himself the title of emperor. 43. itight But foreign nations are not obliged to give way to the will of other na- O f a sovereign who assumes a new title, or of a people who respecT CaH thelr Chief ^ What name the y P lease 't * Memoirs of the House of Branden- -" Olivarius, Dominus Protector An- burg. glise, Scotise, et Hibernise, Ludovico f Cromwell, in writing to Louis the XIV. Francorum Regi Christianissime Fourteenth, used the following style : Rex." And the subscription was 234 DIGNITY AND EQUALITY OF NATIONS. 152 However, if this title has nothing unreasonable, or con- BOOK n. trary to received customs, it is altogether agreeable to the CHAP - m - mutual duties which bind nations together, to give to a sove- 44. Their reign or conductor of a state the same title that is given him duty, by his people. But, if this title is contrary to custom if it implies attributes which do not belong to him who affects it, foreign nations may refuse it without his having reason to complain. The title of "Majesty" is consecrated by custom to monarchs who command great nations. The emperors of Germany have long affected to reserve it to themselves, as belonging solely to the imperial crown. But the kings asserted with reason that there was nothing on earth more eminent or more august than their dignity : they therefore refused the title of Majesty to him who refused it to them;* and at present, except in a few instances founded on parti- cular reasons, the title of Majesty is a peculiar attribute of the royal character. As it would be ridiculous for a petty prince to take the title of king, and assume the style of " Majesty," foreign nations, by refusing to comply with this whim, do nothing but what is conformable to reason and their duty. However, if there reigns anywhere a sovereign, who, notwithstanding the small extent of his power, is accustomed to receive from his neighbours the title of king, distant nations who would j~ 153 ~j carry on an intercourse with him cannot refuse him that title. It belongs not to them to reform the customs of distant countries. The sovereign who wishes constantly to receive certain 45. How titles and honours from other powers, must secure them by* ltlesand treaties. Those who have entered into engagements in this j way are obliged to conform to them, and cannot deviate cured. from the treaties without doing him an injury. Thus, in the examples we have produced ( 41 and 42), the czar and the king of Prussia took care to negotiate beforehand with the courts in friendship with them, to secure their being ac- knowledged under the new titles they intended to assume. The popes have formerly pretended that it belonged to the tiara alone to create new crowns ; they had the confi- dence to expect that the superstition of princes and nations would allow them so sublime a prerogative. But it was In Aula nostra Alba. Vester bonus * At the famous treaty of West- amicus." The court of France was phalia, the plenipotentiaries of France highly offended at this form of address, agreed with those of the emperor, The ambassador Boreel, in a letter to that the king and queen writing the Pensionary De Witt, dated May 25, with their own hand to the emperor, 1655, said that Cromwell's letter had and giving him the title of majesty, not been presented, and that those who he should answer them, with his own were charged with the delivery of it, hand, and give them the same title." had withheld it, through an apprehen- Letter of the plenipotentiaries to M. sion of its giving rise to some misunder- de Brienne, Oct. 15th, 1646. standing between the two countries. 153 DIGNITY AND EQUALITY OF NATIONS. BOOK ii. eclipsed at the revival of letters.* The emperors of Ger- CHAP, in. m any, who formed the same pretensions, were at least coun- tenanced by the example of the ancient Roman emperors. They only want the same power in order to have the same right. 46. We In default of treaties, we ought, with respect to titles, and, must coi> j n genial, every other mark of honour, to conform to the neral cusT" ru ^ e established by general custom. To attempt a deviation torn. (102) from it with respect to a nation or sovereign, when there is no particular reason for such innovation, is expressing either contempt or ill-will towards them ; a conduct equally incon- sistent with sound policy and with the duties that nations owe to each other. (102) 47. Mu- The greatest monarch ought to respect in every sovereign tual respect the eminent character with which he is invested. The in- which sove- dependence, the equality of nations, the reciprocal duties of to 1 each We hunrnmtVj all these circumstances should induce him to pay, other. even to the chief of a petty state, the respect due to the station which he fills. The weakest state is composed of men as well as the most powerful : and our duties are the same towards all those who do "not depend on us. But this precept of the law of nature does not extend be- yond what is essential to the respect which independent nations owe to each other, or that conduct, in a word, which shows that we acknowledge a state or its chief to be truly independent and sovereign, and consequently entitled to every thing due to the quality of sovereignty. But, on the other hand, a great monarch being, as we have already ob- served, a very important personage in human society, it is natural, that, in matters merely ceremonial, and not deroga- tory to the equality of rights between nations, he should [ 154 ] receive honours to which a petty prince can have no preten- sions : and the latter cannot refuse to pay the former every mark of respect which is not inconsistent with his own inde- pendence and sovereignty. 48. How Every nation, every sovereign, ought to maintain their a sovereign dignity ( 35) by causing due respect to be paid to them ; ought to maintain his dignity. * Catholic princes receive still from of 2<1 vol. p. 324. See, as to the sea (103) the pope titles that relate to religion, and incidents, ante, 125 and 131 in Benedict XIV. gave that of "Most notes ; and Cours de Droit Public, torn. Faithful" to the king of Portugal ; 2, p. 80 to 84, and 396 to 406. C. and the condescension of other princes (103) The House of Lords recently, connived at the imperative style in rather facetiously, maintained the dig- which the bull is couched. It is dated nity of the king of Spain, by declining December 23, 1748. to give him costs, on the same principle (102) Formerly all nations used to that our king do*-) not recover costs, observe, in the British seas, the mark saying, we will not disparage the dig- of honour, by lowering the flag or top- nity of the king of Spain by giving sail to an English man of war, called him costs. Hewlett \. King of Spain, the duty of the flag. See 1 Chitty's on appeal from Chancery to House of Commercial Law, 102; and see end Lords, 1 Dow Rep. New Series, 177. 236 OF THE RIGHT TO SECURITY, ETC. 154 and, especially, they ought not to suffer that dignity to be BOOK n. impaired. If, then, there are titles and honours, which, by CHAP, in. constant custom, belong to a prince, he may insist upon them ; and he ought to do it on occasions where his glory is concerned. But it is proper to distinguish between neglect or the omis- sion of what the established usage requires, and positive acts of disrespect and insult. The prince may complain of an instance of neglect, and, if it be not repaired, may consider it as an indication of ill-will : he has a right to demand, even by force of arms, the reparation of an insult. The czar Peter the First, in his manifesto against Sweden, complained that the cannon had not been fired on his passing at Riga. He might think it strange that they did not pay him this mark of respect, and he might complain of it ; but, to have made this the subject of a war, must have indicated a preposterous prodigality of human blood. CHAP. IV. OF THE RIGHT TO SECURITY, AND THE EFFECTS OF THE SOVE- CHAP. TV. REIGNTY AND INDEPENDENCE OF NATIONS. (104) IN vain does nature prescribe to nations, as well as to indi- 49. Right viduals, the care of self-preservation, and of advancing their to security, own perfection and happiness, if she does not give them a right to preserve themselves from every thing that might render this care ineffectual. This right is nothing more than a moral power of acting, that is, the power of doing what is morally possible what is proper and conformable to our duties. We have, then, in general, a right to do whatever is necessary to the discharge of our duties. Every nation, as well as every man, has, therefore, a right to prevent other nations from obstructing her preservation, her perfection, and happiness, that is, to preserve herself from all injuries ( 18) : and this right is a perfect one, since it is given to satisfy a natural and indispensable obligation : for, when we cannot use constraint in order to cause our rights to be re- spected, their effects are very uncertain. It is this right to preserve herself from all injury that is called the right to security. It is safest to prevent the evil when it can be prevented. 50. Itpro- A nation has a right to resist an injurious attempt, and to d . uces the make use of force and every honourable expedient against (104) As to the independence of Public. Paris, A. D. 1830, torn. 2, 1st nations, see in general, Cours de Droit part, article ii. pp. 3 to 15. 237 154 OF THE RIGHT TO SECURITY, ETC. BOOK n. whosoever is actually engaged in opposition to her, and even CHAP, iv. to anticipate his machinations, observing, however, not to attack him upon vague and uncertain suspicions, lest she should incur the imputation of becoming herself an unjust [ 155 ] aggressor. 51. and When the evil is done, the same right to security autho- that of ob- rizes the offended party to endeavour to obtain a complete t ^tio n re ~ reparation, and to employ force for that purpose, if neces- sary. 52. and Finally, the offended party have a right to provide for the right of their future security, and to chastise the offender, by inflict- pumshmg. -^ U p 0n kj m a punishment capable of deterring him thence- forward from similar aggressions, and of intimidating those who might be tempted to imitate him. They may even, if necessary, disable the aggressor from doing further injury. They only make use of their right, in all these measures, which they adopt with good reason : and if evil thence results to him who has reduced them to the necessity of taking such steps, he must impute the consequences only to his own in- justice. 53. Right If, then, there is any\here a nation of a restless and mis- of all na- chievous disposition, ever ready to injure others, to traverse a^misdtue" 8 their designs, and to excite domestic disturbances in their vou; people dominions, it is not to be doubted that all the others have a right to form a coalition in order to repress and chastise that nation, and to put it for ever after out of her power to injure them. Such would be the just fruits of the policy which Machiavel praises in Caesar Borgia. The conduct followed by Philip II. king of Spain, was calculated to unite all Europe against him ; and it was from just reasons that Henry the Great formed the design of humbling a power whose strength was formidable, and whose maxims were pernicious. The three preceding propositions are so many principles that furnish the various foundations for a just war, as we shall see in the proper place. 54. No -^ * s an evident consequence of the liberty and independ- nation has ence of nations, that all have a right to be governed as they a right to think proper, and that no state has the smallest right to re m interfere in the government of another. Of all the rights menfofan- * na * can belong to a nation, sovereignty is, doubtless, the other state, most precious, and that which other nations ought the most scrupulously to respect, if they would not do her an in- jury. (105) The sovereign is he to whom the nation has intrusted the (105) Nor has a subject of one state state assist a revolted colony, it is just a right to enter into any contract with, ground of war on the part of the parent or to assist the revolted colony of an- state. Thompson v. Powles, 2 Simon's other before the same has been for- Rep. 194; Taylor v. Barclay, id. 213. mally recognised as an independent Ante, p. 141, note 95. state by its own government ; and if a OF THE RIGHT TO SECURITY, ETC. 155 empire and the care of the government : she has invested him BOOK n. with her rights ; she alone is directly interested in the manner CHAP, iv. in which the conductor she has chosen makes use of his power. 55. One It does not, then, belong to any foreign power to take cog- sovereign nisance of the administration of that sovereign, to set himself cannotmake up for a judge of his conduct, and to oblige him to alter it. jjj^o^ If he loads his subjects with taxes, and if he treats them with conduct of severity, the nation alone is concerned in the business ; and another, no other is called upon to oblige him to amend his conduct, and follow more wise and equitable maxims. It is the part of prudence to point out the occasions when officious and ami- cable representations may be made to him. The Spaniards violated all rules when they set themselves up as judges of the Inca Athualpa. If that prince had violated the law of nations with respect to them, they would have had a right to [ 156 ] punish him. But they accused him of having put some of his subjects to death, of having had several wives, &c. things, for which he was not at all accountable to them ; and, to fill up the measure of their extravagant injustice, they condemned him by the laws of Spain.* But, if the prince, by violating the fundamental laws, gives 55. HOW his subjects a legal right to resist him, if tyranny, becom- far lawful to ing insupportable, obliges the nation to rise in their own de- i nter f ere in fence, every foreign power has a right to succour an op- ^ e ^era a pressed people who implore their assistance. The English S0 vereign justly complained of James II. The nobility and the most and his sub- distinguished patriots having determined to check him in theJ ects * prosecution of his schemes, which manifestly tended to over- throw the constitution, and to destroy the liberties and the religion of the people, applied for assistance to the United Provinces. The authority of the Prince of Orange had, doubtless, an influence on the deliberations of the states- general ; but it did not lead them to the commission of an act of injustice : for, when a people, from good reasons take up arms against an oppressor, it is but an act of justice and generosity to assist brave men in the defence of their liber- ties. Whenever, therefore, matters are carried so far as to produce a civil war, foreign powers may assist that party which appears to them to have justice on its side. He who assists an odious tyrant, he who declares for an unjust and rebellious people, violates his duty. But, when the bands of the political society are broken, or at least suspended, between the sovereign and his people, the contending parties may then be considered as two distinct powers ; and, since they are both equally independent of all foreign authority, nobody has a right to judge them. Either may be in the right ; and each of those who grant their assistance may ima- gine that he is acting in support of the better cause. It fol- Garcillasso de la Vega. 156 OF THE RIGHT TO SECURITY, ETC. BOOK ii. lows, then, in virtue of the voluntary law of nations (see CHAP, iv. Prelim. 21), that the two parties may act as having an equal right, and behave to each other accordingly till the decision of the affair. But we ought not to abuse this maxim, and make a handle of it to authorize odious machinations against the internal tranquillity of states. It is a violation of the law of nations to invite those subjects to revolt who actually pay obedience to their sovereign, though they complain of his government. The practice of nations is conformable to our maxims. When the German protestants came to the assistance of the reformed party in France, the court never attempted to treat them otherwise than on the usual footing of enemies in general, and according to the laws of war. France was at the same time engaged in assisting the Netherlands then in arms against Spain, and expected that her troops should be considered in no other light than as auxiliaries in a regular war. But no power ever fails to complain, as of an atrocious wrong, if any one attempts by his emissaries to excite his subjects to revolt. [ 157 ] As to those monsters who, under the title of sovereigns, render themselves the scourges and horror of the human race, they are savage beasts, whom every brave man may justly exterminate from the face of the earth. All antiquity has praised Hercules for delivering the world from an Antaeas, a Busiris, and a Diomede. 57. Right After having established the position that foreign nations of opposing have no right to interfere in the government of an independ- the interfer- t state ft j s not diffi cu it to prove that the latter has a right enceoffor- . . _ L, , , ,. eign powers * oppose such interference. To govern herself according to in the affairs her own pleasure, is a necessary part of her independence, of govern- A sovereign state cannot be constrained in this respect, except . ment * it be from a particular right which she has herself given to other states by her treaties ; and, even if she has given them such a right, yet it cannot, in an affair of so delicate a nature as that of government, be extended beyond the clear and express terms of the treaties. In every other case, a sove- reign has a right to treat those as enemies who attempt to interfere in his domestic affairs otherwise than by their good offices. 58. The Religion is in every sense an object of great importance to same rights a na tion, and one of the most interesting subjects on which g overnmen * can De employed. An independent people are accountable for their religion to God alone; in this par- ticular, as in every other, they have a right to regulate their conduct according to the dictates of their own conscience, and to prevent all foreign interference in an affair of so deli- cate a nature.* The custom, long kept up in Christendom, When, however, we see a party the religion we profess, and :u neigh - inflamed with deadly hatred against bouring prince persecuting in oonse- 240 OF THE RIGHT TO SECURITY, ETC. 157 of causing all the affairs of religion to be decided and regu- BOOK n. lated in a general council, could only have been introduced CHAP, iv. by the singular circumstance of the submission of the whole church to the same civil government, the Roman empire. When that empire was overthrown, and gave place to many independent kingdoms, this custom was found contrary to the first principles of government, to the very idea of inde- pendent states and political societies. It was, however, long supported by prejudice, ignorance, and superstition, by the authority of the popes and the power of the clergy, and still respected even at the time of the reformation. The states who had embraced the reformed religion offered to submit to the decisions of an impartial council lawfully assembled. At present they would not hesitate to declare, that, in matters of religion, they are equally independent of every power on earth, as they are in the affairs of civil government. The general and absolute authority of the pope and council is [ 158 ] absurd in every other system than that of those popes who strove to unite all Christendom in a single body, of which they pretended to be the supreme monarchs.* But even Catholic sovereigns have endeavoured to restrain that autho- rity within such limits as are consistent with their supreme power : they do not receive the decrees of councils or the popes' bulls till they have caused them to be examined ; and these ecclesiastical laws are of no force in their dominions unless confirmed by the prince. In the first book of this work, Chap. XII. we have sufficiently established the rights of a state in matters of religion ; and we introduce them here again, only to draw just consequences from them with respect to the conduct which nations ought to observe towards each other. It is, then, certain that we cannot, in opposition to the will 59. Nona- of a nation, interfere in her religious concerns, without vio- tlon can b lating her rights, and doing her an injury. Much less are ^freTect we allowed to employ force of arms to oblige her to receive to religion. a doctrine and a worship which we consider as divine. What right have men to set themselves up as the defenders and pro- tectors of the cause of God ? He can, whenever he pleases, lead nations to the knowledge of himself, by more effectual means than those of violence. Persecutors make no true con- verts. The monstrous maxim of extending religion by the sword, is a subversion of the rights of mankind, and the most quence the professors of that religion, nature requires that I should antici- it is lawful for us to give assistance to pate and prevent the evil which may the sufferers, as it was well remarked thence result to myself." Le Vassor, by James I. of England to Bouillon History of Louis XIII. the ambassador of Mary de Medici, * See above, 46, and Bodinus's queen-regent of France," When my Republic, book i. c. ix, with his quo- neighbours are attacked in a quarrel tations, p. m. 139. in which I am interested, the law of 31 V 241 158 OF THE RIGHT TO SECURITY, ETC. BOOK n. terrible scourge of nations. Every madman will fancy he is CHAP, iv. fighting in the cause of God, and every aspiring spirit will use that pretext as a cloak for his ambition. While Char- lemagne was ravaging Saxony with fire and sword, in order to plant Christianity there, the successors of Mohammed were ravaging Asia and Africa, to establish the Koran in those parts. 60. Offi- B u t it is an office of humanity to labour, by mild and law- manit in ^ means > * persuade a nation to receive a religion which these mat- we believe to be the only one that is true and salutary. Mis- ters, sionaries may be sent to instruct the people ; and this care is Missiona- altogether comformable to the attention which every nation ries. owes to the perfection and happiness of others. But it must be observed, that, in order to avoid doing an injury to the rights of a sovereign, the missionaries ought to abstain from preaching clandestinely, or without his permission, a new doc- trine to his people. He may refuse to accept their proffered services ; and, if he orders them to leave his dominions, they ought to obey. They should have a very express order from the King of kings, before they can lawfully disobey a sove- reign who commands according to the extent of his power ; and the prince who is not convinced of that extraordinary order of the Deity, will do no more than exert his lawful rights, in punishing a missionary for disobedience. But, what if the nation, or a considerable part of the people, are desirous of retaining the missionary, and following his doc- [ 159 ] trine ? In a former part of the work (Book I. 128136), we have established the rights of the nation and those of the citizens; and thither we refer for an answer to this question. 61. Cir- This is a very delicate subject; and we cannot authorize cumspection an inconsiderate zeal for malting proselytes, without endan- gering the tranquillity of all nations, and even exposing those who are engaged in making converts to act inconsistently with their duty, at the very time they imagine they are accom- plishing the most meritorious work. For, it is certainly per- forming a very bad office to a nation, and doing her an essen- tial injury, to spread a false and dangerous religion among the inhabitants. Now, there is no person who does not be- lieve his own religion to be the only true and safe one. Re- commend, kindle in all hearts, the ardent zeal of the missiona- ries, and you will see Europe inundated with Lamas, Bonzes, and Dervises, while monks of all kinds will overrun Asia and Africa. Protestant ministers will crowd to Spain and Italy, in defiance of the Inquisition, while the Jesuits will spread themselves among the Protestants in order to bring them back into the pale of the church. Let the Catholics reproach the Protestants as much as they please with their lukewarmness, the conduct of the latter is undoubtedly more agreeable to reason and the law of nations. True zeal applies itself to the task of making a holy religion flourish in the countries 242 OF THE RIGHT TO SECURITY, ETC. 159 -where it is received, and of rendering it useful to the man- BOOK u. ners of the people and to the state : and, without forestalling CHAP. IT. the dispositions of Providence, it can find sufficient employ- ment at home, until an invitation come from foreign nations, or a very evident commission be given from heaven, to preach that religion abroad. Finally, let us add, that, before we can lawfully undertake to preach a particular religion to the various nations of the earth, we must ourselves be thoroughly convinced of its truth by the most serious examination. " What ! can Christians doubt of their religion ?" The Mo- hammedan entertains no doubt of his. Be ever ready to impart your knowledge, simply and sincerely expose the principles of your belief to those who are desirous of hearing you : instruct them, convince them by evidence, but seek not to hurry them away with the fire of enthusiasm. It is a suffi- cient charge on each of us, to be responsible for his own con- science. Thus, neither will the light of knowledge be refused to any who wish to receive it, nor will a turbulent zeal disturb the peace of nations. When a religion is persecuted in one country, foreign na- 62. What tions who profess it may intercede for their brethren : but a sovereign this is all they can lawfully do, unless the persecution be car- ^ u ^ J- n ried to an intolerable excess : then, indeed, it becomes a case tnose wno of manifest tyranny, in opposition to which all nations are profess his allowed to assist an unhappy people ( 56). A regard to religion in their own safety may also authorize them to undertake the g t "* her defence of the persecuted sufferers. A king of France re- plied to the ambassadors who solicited him to suffer his sub- jects of the reformed religion to live in peace, "that he was master in his own kingdom." But the Protestant sovereigns, who saw a general conspiracy of the Catholics obstinately [ 160 ] bent on their destruction, were so far masters on their side as to be at liberty to give assistance to a body of men who might strengthen their party, and help them to preserve themselves from the ruin with which they were threatened. All distinctions of states and nations are to be disregarded, when there is question of forming a coalition against a set of madmen who would exterminate all those that do not im- plicitly receive their doctrines. 248 160 OE THE OBSERVANCE OF JUSTICE BETWEEN NATIONS. BOOK II. CHAP. V. CHAP. V. OF THE OBSERVANCE OF JUSTICE BETWEEN NATIONS. 63. lye- JUSTICE ' is the basis of all society, the sure bond of all cesslt y ftlie commerce. Human society, far from being an intercourse of^u&tLcein ^ assistance and good offices, would be no longer any thing human so- but a vast scene of robbery, if no respect were paid to this ciety. virtue, which secures to every one his own. It is still more necessary between nations than between individuals ; because injustice produces more dreadful consequences in the quarrels of these powerful bodies politic, and it is more difficult to obtain redress. The obligation imposed on all men to be just is easily demonstrated from the law of nature. We here take that obligation for granted (as being sufficiently known), and content ourselves with observing that it is not only indispen- sably binding on nations (Prelim. 5), but even still more sacred with respect to them, from the importance of its con- sequences. 64. Obli- All nations are therefore under a strict obligation to culti- gatkm of all V ate justice towards each other, to observe it scrupulously, cultivate anc ^ care f u ^y to abstain from every thing that may violate it. and observe Each ought to render to the others what belongs to them, to justice. respect their rights, and to leave them in the peaceable en- joyment of them.* 65. Right From this indispensable obligation which nature imposes of refusing on nations, as well as from those obligations which each na- in'ustice 1 10 tion owes to nerself 5 results the right of every state not to suffer any of her rights to be taken away, or any thing which lawfully belongs to her : for, in opposing this, she only acts in conformity to all her duties ; and therein consists the right [ 161 ] ( 49). 66. This This right is a perfect one, that is to say, it is accompa- right is a n i e( j w ith the right of using force in order to assert it. In pe one. ya j n wou ] ( j na t u re give us a right to refuse submitting to in- justice, in vain would she oblige others to be just in their dealings with us, if we could not lawfully make use of force, * Might not this duty be extended be executed on requisition made by those to the execution of sentences passed in parliaments. But I do not know that other countries according to the neces- the tribunals of this country act in the sary and usual forms ? On this subject same manner with respect to sentences M. Van Bouningin wrote as follows to passed in Holland ; and, if they do not, M. De Witt, Oct. 15, 1666 : By what an agreement might be made, that the courts of Holland have decreed in the sentences passed on either side against affair of one Koningh, of Rotterdam, I subjects of the other state shall only see they suppose that ever,y judgment take effect on such property as the con- pronounced by the parliaments of demned party is found to possess in France against the inhabitants of Hoi- the state where the sentence has been land injudicio contradictor io, ought to given." 244 CONCERN OF A NATION IN THE ACTIONS OF HER CITIZENS. 161 when they refused to discharge this duty. The just would BOOK n. lie at the mercy of avarice and injustice, and all their rights CHAP - Y - would soon become useless. From the foregoing right arise, as distinct branches, first, 67. It pro- the right of a just defence, which belongs to every nation, ducesl.The or the right of making use of force against whoever attacks jgj of her and her rights. This is the foundation of defensive war. Secondly, the right to obtain justice by force, if we cannot 68 - 2 - The obtain it otherwise, or to pursue our right by force of arms. ^J^!J| in8 This is the foundation of offensive war. justice. An intentional act of injustice is undoubtedly an injury. 69. The We have, then, a right to punish it, as we have shown above, right of pun- in speaking of injuries in general ( 52). The right of refus- ^ ce ng mjus " ing to suffer injustice is a branch of the right to security. Let us apply to the unjust what we have said above ( 53) 70. Right of a mischievous nation. If there were a people who made / ^ na ; open profession of trampling justice under foot, who ^e- ^" s t ^|^ nst spised and violated the rights of others whenever they found op enly de- an opportunity, the interest of human society would author- spises jus- ize all the other nations to form a confederacy in order to hum- tice - ble and chastise the delinquents. We do not here forget the maxim established in our Preliminaries, that it does not be- long to nations to usurp the power of being judges of each other. In particular cases, where there is room for (the smallest doubt, it ought to be supposed that each of the parties may have some right : and the injustice of the party that has committed the injury may proceed from error, and not from a general contempt of justice. But if, by her constant max- ims, and by the whole tenor of her conduct, a nation evidently proves herself to be actuated by that mischievous disposition, if she regards no right as sacred, the safety of the human race requires that she should be repressed. To form and sup- port an unjust pretension, is only doing an injury to the party whose interests are affected by that pretension ; but, to de- spise justice in general, is doing an injury to all nations. CHAP. VI. OF THE CONCERN A NATION MAY HAVE IN THE ACTIONS OF CHAP - YI -_ HER CITIZENS. WE have seen in the preceding chapters what are the com- 71. The mon duties of nations towards each other, how they ought sovereign mutually to respect each other, and to abstain from all injury "jj JJJ " and all offence, and how justice and equity ought to reign injuries of between them in their whole conduct. But hitherto we have the state, only considered the actions of the body of the nation, of the *"*& to P r - V2 245 161 CONCERN OF A NATION BOOK ii- state, of the sovereign. Private persons who are memhers CHAP. YI. O f one nation, may offend and ill-treat the citizens of another, tect the citi- and may injure a foreign sovereign : it remains for us to zens. examine what share a state may have in the actions of her L 1"2 ] citizens, and what are the rights and obligations of sovereigns in this respect. Whoever offends the state, v injures its rights, disturbs its tranquillity, or does it a prejudice in any manner whatsoever, declares himself its enemy, and exposes himself to be justly punished for it. Whoever uses a citizen ill, indirectly offends the state, which is bound to protect this citizen ; and the sovereign of the latter should avenge his wrongs, punish the aggressor, and, if possible, oblige him to make full repara- tion ; since otherwise the citizen would not obtain the great end of the civil association, which is, safety. 72. He But, on the other hand, the nation or the sovereign ought ought not to not to suffer the citizens to do an injury to the subjects of an- suSTto other state ' much less to offend that state itself : and this > not offend other on ty because no sovereign ought to permit those who are nations or under his command to violate the precepts of the law of na- their citi- ture, which forbids all injuries, but also because nations zens. ought mutually to respect each other, to abstain from all offence, from all injury, from all wrong, in a word, from every thing that may be of prejudice to others. If a sove- reign, who might keep his subjects within the rules of justice and peace, suffers them to injure a foreign nation either in its body or its members, he does no less injury to that nation than if he injured it himself. In short, the safety of the state, and that of human society, requires this attention from every sovereign. If you let loose the reins to your subjects against foreign nations, these will behave in the same manner to you ; and, instead of that friendly intercourse which nature has established between all men, we shall see nothing but one vast and dreadful scene of plunder between nation and nation. 73. The However, as it is impossible for the best regulated state, acts of indi- or f or the most vigilant and absolute sovereign, to model at ^ t u t a o ls b ^ re his pleasure all the actions of his subjects, and to confine imputed to them on every occasion to the most exact obedience, it would the nation, be unjust to impute to the nation or the sovereign every fault committed by the citizens. We ought not, then, to say, in general, that we have received an injury from a nation because we have received it from one of its members. 74. unless But, if a nation or its chief approves and ratifies the act it approves of the individual, it then becomes a public concern ; and the or ratifies i n j ure( j party is to consider the nation as the real author of the injury, of which the citizen was perhaps only the instru- 75. Con- ment. obstrted'b If the offended state has in her P ower tne individual who ^^offended nas done the injury, she may without scruple bring him to party. justice and punish him. If he has escaped and returned to IN THE ACTIONS OP HER CITIZENS. 162 his own country, she ought to apply to his sovereign to have BOOK n. justice done in the case. CHAr - - And, since the latter ought not to suffer his subjects to [ 163 ] molest the subjects of other states, or to do them an injury, 76. Duty much less to give open, audacious offence to foreign powers, of the a g- he ought to compel the transgressor to make reparation for i es f or ' s s - the damage or injury, if possible, or to inflict on him an ex- emplary punishment ; or, finally, according the nature and cir- cumstances of the case, to deliver him up to the offended state, to be there brought to justice. This is pretty generally ob- served with respect to great crimes, which are equally con- trary to the laws and safety of all nations. Assassins, incen- diaries, and robbers, are seized everywhere, at the desire of the sovereign in whose territories the crime was committed, and are delivered up to his justice. The matter is carried still farther in states that are more closely connected by friend- ship and good neighbourhood. Even in cases of ordinary trangressions, which are only subjects of civil prosecution, either with a view to the recovery of damages, or the inflic- tion of a slight civil punishment, the subjects of two neigh- bouring states are reciprocally obliged to appear before the magistrate of the place where they are accused of having failed in their duty. Upon a requisition of that magistrate, called Letters Rogatory, they are summoned in due form by their own magistrates, and obliged to appear. An admirable institution, by means of which many neighbouring states live together in peace, and seem to form only one republic ! This is in force throughout all Switzerland. As soon as the Let- ters Rogatory are issued in form, the superior of the accused is bound to enforce them. It belongs not to him to examine whether the accusation be true or false : he is to presume on the justice of his neighbour, and not suffer any doubts on his own part to impair an institution so well calculated to pre- serve harmony and good understanding between the states. However, if by constant experience he should find that his subjects are oppressed by the neighbouring magistrates who summon them before their tribunals, it would undoubtedly be right in him to reflect on the protection due to his people, and to refuse the rogatories till satisfaction were given for the abuses committed, and proper steps taken to prevent a repe- tition of them. But, in such case, it would be his duty to allege his reasons, and set them forth in the clearest point of view. The sovereign who refuses to cause reparation to be made 77. If he for the damage done by his subject, or to punish the offender, refuses jus- or, finally, to deliver _ him up, renders himself in some mea- ^^^ sure an accomplice in the injury, and becomes responsible party jn t hr for it. But, if he delivers up either the property of the fault and offender, as an indemnification, in cases that will admit of offence, pecuniary compensation or his person, in order that he may 247 163 EFFECTS OF THE DOMAIN BETWEEN NATIONS. BOOK ii. suffer the punishment due to his crime, the offended party CHAP, vi. J^ no f ur ther demand on him. King Demetrius, having de- [ 164 ] livered to the Romans those who had killed their ambassador, the senate sent them back, resolving to reserve to themselves the liberty of punishing that crime, by avenging it on the king himself, or on his dominions.* If this was really the case, and if the king had no share in the murder of the Ro- man ambassador, the conduct v of the senate was highly unjust, and only worthy of men who sought but a pretext to cover their ambitious enterprises. other casein Finally, there is another case where the nation in general which the ' IS gu^ty of the crimes of its members. That is, when, by nation is its manners, and by the maxims of its government, it accus- guilty of the toms and authorizes its citizens indiscriminately to plunder thTcitizens anc ^ ma ^ rea * ; foreigners, to make inroads into the neighbour- ' ing countries, &c. Thus, the nation of the Usbecks is guilty of all the robberies committed by the individuals of which it is composed. The princes whose subjects are robbed and massacred, and whose lands are infested by those robbers, may justly level their vengeance against the nation at large. (106) Nay, more ; all nations have a right to enter into a league against such a people, to repress them, and to treat them as the common enemies of the human race. The Christian nations would be no less justifiable in forming a confe- deracy against the states of Barbary, in order to destroy those haunts of pirates, Avith whom the love of plunder, or the fear of just punishment, is the only rule of peace and war. But these piratical adventurers are wise enough to re- spect those who are most able to chastise them ; and the na- tions that are able to keep the avenues of a rich branch of commerce open for themselves, are not sorry to see them shut against others. CHAP. VII. EFFECTS OF THE DOMAIN BETWEEN NATIONS. 79. Gene- \\T E have explained, in Chap. XVIII. Book I., how a na- f ^ on ta ^ es P ossess ^ on ^ a country, and at the same time gains ' possession of the domain and government therof. That coun- try, with every thing included in it, becomes the property of the nation in general. Let us now see what are the effects of this property, with respect to other nations. The full do- main is necessarily a peculiar and exclusive right ; for, if I * See Polybius, quoted by Barbey- (106) It was on this ground that the rac, in his notes on Grotius, book iii. French nation so recently took posses- chap, xxiv. vii. sion of Algiers.- C. 248 EFFECTS OF THE DOMAIN BETWEEN NATIONS. 164 have a full right to dispose of a thing as I please, it thence BOOK n - follows that others have no right to it at all, since, if they OHAP ' Y "' had any, I could not freely dispose of it. The private domain of the citizens may be limited and restrained in several ways by the laws of the state, and it always is so by the eminent domain of the sovereign ; but the general domain of the na- tion is full and absolute, since there exists no authority upon earth "by which it can be limited : it therefore excludes all right on the part of foreigners. And, as the rights of a nation ought to be respected by all others ( 64), none can form any [ 165 ] pretensions to the country which belongs to that nation, nor ought to dispose of it without her consent, any more than of the things contained in the country. The domiin of the nation extends to every thing she pos- so. What sesses by a just title : it comprehends her ancient and original j^JJfj^ possessions, and all her acquisitions made by means which are ^"domain just in themselves, or admitted as such among nations, con- O f a nation, cessions, purchases, conquests made in the regular war, &c. And by her possessions we ought not only to understand her territories, but all the rights she enjoys. Even the property of the individuals is, in the aggregate, 81. The to be considered as the property of the nation, with respect property of to other states. It, in some sort, really belongs to her, from [ g ^g 1 " 8 the right she has over the property of her citizens, because per ty of the it constitutes a part of the sum total of her riches, and aug- nation, with nients her power. She is interested in that property by her respect to obligation to protect all her members. In short, it cannot be ^"j otherwise, since nations act and treat together as bodies in their quality of political societies, and are considered as so many moral persons. All those who form a society, a nation being considered by foreign nations as constituting only one whole, one single person, all their wealth together can only be considered as the wealth of that same person. And this is so true, that each political society may, if it pleases, establish within itself a community of goods, as Campanella did in his republic of the sun. Others will not inquire what it does in this respect: its domestic regulations make no change in its rights with respect to foreigners nor in the manner in which they ought to consider the aggregate of its property, in what way soever it is possessed. By an immediate consequence of this principle, if one na- 82. A con- tion has a right to any part of the property of another, she sequence of has an indiscriminate right to the property of the citizens of ^ pnncl " the latter nation until the debt be discharged. This maxim p e is of great use, as shall hereafter be shown. 8 3. Con- The general domain of the nation over the lands she inhabits nection of is naturally connected with the empire ; for, in establishing the Domain herself in a vacant country, the nation certainly does not in- j^^JJ" tend to possess it in subjection to any other power: and, can t h e sove . we suppose an independent nation not vested with the absolute reigmv. 32 249 165 EFFECTS OF THE DOMAIN BETWEEN NATIONS. BOOK ii. command in her domestic concerns ? Thus, we have already CHAP. YII. observed (Book I, 205), that, in taking possession cf a country, the nation is presumed to take possession of its government at the same time. We shall here proceed further, and show the natural connection of these two rights in in in- dependent nation. How could she govern herself at h^r own pleasure in the country she inhabits, if she cannot truly and absolutely dispose of it ? A^id how could she have the full and absolute domain of a place where she has not the command ? Another's sovereignty, and the rights it comprehends, must deprive her of the free disposal of that place. Add to this [ 166 ] the eminent domain which constitutes a part of the sovereignty (Book I, 244), and you will the better perceive the intimate connection existing between the domain and the sovereignty of the nation. And, accordingly, what is called the high domain, which is nothing but the domain of the body of the nation, or of the sovereign who represents it, is everywhere considered as inseparable from the sovereignty. The useful domain, or the domain confined to the rights that may belong to an individual in the state, may be separated from the sovereignty: and nothing prevents the possibility of its be- longing to a nation in places that are not under her juris- diction. Thus, many sovereigns have fiefs, and other pos- sessions, in the territories of another prince : in these cases they possess them in the manner of private individuals. 84. Juris- The sovereignty united to the domain establishes the ju- diction. risdiction of the nation in her territories, or the country that belongs to her. It is her province, or that of her sovereign, to exercise justice in all the places under her jurisdiction, to take cognisance of the crimes committed, and the differences that arise in the country. Other nations ought to respect this right. And, as the administration of justice necessarily requires that every de- finitive sentence, regularly pronounced, be esteemed just, and executed as such, when once a cause in which foreigners are interested has been decided in form, the sovereign of the de- fendants cannot hear their complaints. To undertake to ex- amine the justice of a definitive sentence is an attack on the jurisdiction of him who has passed it. The prince, therefore, ought not to interfere in the causes of his subjects in foreign countries, and grant them his protection, excepting in cases where justice is refused, or palpable and evident injustice done, or rules and forms openly violated, or, finally, an odious distinction made, to the prejudice of his subjects, or of fo- reigners in general. The British court established this maxim, with great strength of evidence, on occasion of the Prussian vessels seized and declared lawful prizes during the last war.* * See the report made to the King Murray. It is an excellent piece on of Great Britain by Sir George Lee, the law of nations. Dr. Paul, Sir Dudley Ryder, and Mr. 250 EFFECTS OF THE DOMAIN BETWEEN NATIONS. 166 What is here said has no relation to the merits of that par- BOOK H. ticular cause, since they must depend on facts. CHAP, yn. In consequence of these rights of jurisdiction, the decisions 85. Effects made by the judge of the place within the extent of his power f tlie J uns ' ought to be respected, and to take effect even in foreign coun- f< ^ e -^ m tries. For instance, it belongs to the domestic judge to nomi- countries, nate tutors and guardians for minors and idiots. The law of (107) (107) This principle appears to be now settled by the law and practice of na- tions; but, nevertheless, subject to cer- tain general wholesome rules, essential to be adhered to in order to prevent the effect of partial and unjust sentences and decisions. The respected decisions which have given rise to discussion, have principally been in foreign Courts of Admiralty, or Prize Courts ; and the law respecting them has been better settled by the decisions of Sir W. Scott and Sir J. Nichol, so universally re- spected, than at any other period of his- tory. By the long-established doctrine in England, and by the more recent general practice of European nations, a sentence of condemnation, pronounced in a court of competent jurisdiction, is essential, completely to transfer the legal interest in property captured as prize, (per Sir W. Scott, in The Flail Oyen, 1 Rob. Rep. 115). And, in order to constitute a legal prize-court to pro- nounce a binding sentence, by the law of nations, certain requisites are es- sential. The celebrated report drawn up by Lord Mansfield and signed by him and other very eminent personages as their opinion, contains much of the law of nations upon the subject. (See Postle. Universal Diet, of Trade and Commerce, article Silesia, 4th ed. ; and 1 Col. Jurid. 133; and see Undo v. Rodney, 2 Doug. 613, and Le Caux v. Eden, id. 594.) One rule was there laid down, that the condemnation must have been pronounced by a court be- longing to the belligerent country. (See id., and Havelock v. Rockwood, Atche- son's Rep. 7 & 8 ; 8 Term Rep. 288 ; 1 Col. Jurid. 130.) Secondly, the court must have, at the time it pronounced sentence of condemnation, actually sat in the country to which it belonged, and not within the dominions of any foreign prince, whether neutral or an ally ; for, otherwise, a captor might have innu- merable seats of war, and elude the fair chance of recaption whilst the vessel or property was in progress towards a proper condemning port (Havelock v. Rockicood, Atcheson's Rep. 8 & 49; The Flad Oyen, 1 Rob. Rep. 115, 8 Term Rep. 270, in notes.) Thirdly, the ship, or other property condemned as prize, must, at the time of condemnation, in general, be actually in the country where the sentence was pronounced. Per Sir W. Scott, in The Flad Oyen, 1 Rob. Rep. 115, where see some exceptions ; and see also Havelock v. Rockivood, Atch. Rep. 49 ; {Jolly v. The Neptune, 2 Pet. Adm. Dec. 345 ; Findlay v. The William, 1 Pet. Adm. Dec. 12.} See other cases in 1 Har- rison's Index, pp. 687 to 689. By the marine law of England, as practised in the High Court of Admi- ralty, it was formerly held that there was no change of property in case of recaption, so as to bar the original owner in favour of a vendee or recaptor, until there had been a sentence of con- demnation (2 Burr. 696 ; Undo v. Rod- ney 4- another, 2 Douglas, 616 ; 1 Rob. Rep. 139) ; and now by statutes 13 Geo. 2, c. 4, s. 18, and 29 Geo. 2, c. 34, s. 24, in case of recapture, the jus postli- minii is extended, and continues for ever, upon payment of certain salvage, which is regulated and fixed by 33 Geo. 3, c. 66, s. 42. (See 2 Burr. 696, 1209, &c.) And, when the private property of an allied sovereign is recap- tured from the enemy, it is to be re- stored to him free from salvage, or even expense (Alexander, 2 Dodson's Rep. 37). With respect to the effect in England of foreign judgments, decrees, and sentences, the present general rule is, that, if they were decided in a fo- reign court, of competent jurisdiction, they shall be admitted as prima facie valid and binding on the parties in all other countries, but not conclusively so. (See the cases referred to in note (a) to Naoelli v. Ross, 2 Bam. & Adolph. 765; and see Frankland v. M'Gusty, Knapp's Rep. 295; 1 Ves. 159; 2 Strange, 733 ; 2 Bing. 380 ; 3 Bing. 353 ; 4 Barn. & Cres. 637 ; Tarleton v. Tarleton, 4 Maule & Sel. 20 ; Kennedy v. Cassilis, 2 Swanst 325) ; fCalhoun 251 166 EFFECTS OF THE DOMAIN BETWEEN NATIONS. BOOK n. nations, which has an eye to the common advantage and the CHAP. TII. g 00( j harmony of nations, requires, therefore, that such nomi- nation of a tutor or guardian be valid, and acknowledged in all countries where the pupil may have any concerns. Use v. Fitzsimons, 1 Bin. Rep. 293; Cal- breath v. Gracy, 1 Wash. C. C. Rep. 219.} And it was held, that a decree^ of the sale of a ship made in an Ame- rican court of competent jurisdiction, pending war with this country, was to be received in the Court of Admiralty in England as legally operative. (The Experiments, 2 Dods. Rep. 46, 47) ; ^Thirty, &c. v. Boyle, 9 Cranch, 191}. So, a marriage, established by the sen- tence of a foreign court having proper jurisdiction, has even been considered as conclusive by the law of nations (Roach v. Gavan, 1 Ves. sen. 159); {Story, Conf. Laws, p. 103, ed. 1834} ; and it was laid down by De Grey, C. J. that the judgment of a court of com- petent jurisdiction directly upon a point, is, as a plea, a bar, or, as evidence, con- clusive, between the same parties upon the same matter directly in question in another court. (See Duchess of King- ston's case, 20 Howcll's State Trials, 538 ; and see Bui. N. Pri. 244 ; Phillips v. Hunter, 2 Hen. Bla. 402, per Eyre, C. J. ; and see, as to that point, 1 Phil- lipps on Evid. part ii. c. 2 and 3, {vol. 4, Am. ed. 1839, New York, pages 856 to 915} ; and Starkie on Evid. part ii. 67, 68 ; Frankland \.M'Gus!y, I Knapp's Rep. 274; Buchanan v. Rucker, 1 Campb. 63, 180, n., 9 East, 192, S. C.; Sadler v. Robins, id. 280, 253 ; Cavan v. Stewart, 1 Stark. Rep. 525 ; and see 1 Chitty's Com. L. 61 to 65.) But such foreign decision is not conclusive like the judgment of a court of record in England ; and, therefore, if a man recover a judgment or sen- tence in France for money due to him, the debt must be considered here in England as only a simple contract debt, and the statute of limitations will run upon it (Dupleix v. De Jioven, 2 Vem. 540) : and the sentence of a court of summary jurisdiction in France can- not be pleaded to a bill in Chancery in England for the same matter (Gage v. Bulkeky, 3 Atk. 215); and it should seem, that even a recovery of a judg- ment upon a bond in a foreign country is no bar to an action here on the same bond. (Foster v. Vassall, 3 Atk. 589, decided upon an Irish bond and judgment before the Union.) It is true 252 that there are cases which seem to decide that such foreign judgments are conclusive. (See Newland v. Horseman, 1 Vern. 21.) In a late case the Vice- Chancellor held that the grounds of a foreign judgment cannot be reviewed in the courts of this country, and that, therefore, a bill for a discovery and a commission to examine witnesses in Antigua, in aid of the parties' defence to an action brought on the judgment in this country, was demurrable. (Martin v. Nicholls, 3 Simon's Rep. 458, cited by Parke, J., in Bequest v. McCarthy, 2 Barn. & Adol. 954 ; see also Kennedy v. Cassilis, 2 Swans. 326.) But that doctrine is not sustainable, and, there- fore, upon an appeal to the Privy Council from a decree of the court of justice at Demerara, such decree being for a sum of money alleged to be due on foreign judgments, was reversed, on the ground that such court of justice had erroneously determined that those judgments were conclusive when they were only prima facie evidence of the debt, and it was competent to the ori' ginal defendant to show that the judg- ment had been improperly obtained. (Frankland v. M'Gusty and Others, Knapp's Rep. 274.) If, therefore, a foreign judgment appear upon the face of it to have proceeded, either wholly in the defendant's absence, and with- out his having had any opportunity of knowing of the proceeding, and defend- ing it, and, therefore, manifestly against justice ; or if the decision has manifestly proceeded upon false premises, or in- adequate reasons, or upon a mistake of local or foreign law, and which ought to have occasioned a different decision (Novelli v. Rosf, 2 Barn. & Adol. 757) ; or, even if either of those objections be shown by extrinsic evidence (Frankland v. M'Gusty, Knapp's Rep. 274 to 310; semble, overruling the contrary decision in Martin v. Nicolls, 3 Simon's Rep. 458, and 2 Swans. 326) ; then, it seems now to be clearly settled, at least in England, that the foreign decision will not be binding or valid (id. ibid.) Thus, it was recently held, that, where the French courts had in their decrees, on the face of them, mistaken the law of England as to the effect of a cancel- EFFECTS OF THE DOMAIN BETWEEN NATIONS. 166 was made of this maxim in the year 1672, even with respect BOOK n. to a sovereign. The abbe D' Orleans, sovereign prince of CHAP, vii. Neufchatel, in Switzerland, being incapable of managing his [ 167 ] own affairs, the king of France appointed, as his guardian, his mother, the duchess-dowager of Longueville. The duch- ess of Nemours, sister to that prince, laid claim to the guar- dianship for the principality of Neufchatel : but the title of the duchess of Longueville was acknowledged by the three estates of the country. Her counsel rested her cause on the lation of the acceptance of a bill by mis- take, and had, on that ground, and con- trary to the English law, adjudged that the defendant, as well as the plaintiff, was discharged from liability by such cancellation, when, according to the English law, they remained liable, it was held, in the Court of King's Bench in England, that the defendant was still liable to be sued by the plaintiff for the debt in respect of which the bills were given, notwithstanding the de- cree. (Novflli v. Rossi, 2 Barn. & Adolp. 757.) And, upon appeal to the Privy- Council, a decree of the court of jus- tice of Demerara, for a sum of money had left property there, due upon three foreign judgments in Forrest.) St. Vincent's, was reversed, on the ground that those judgments had been improperly obtained. (Frankland v. M< Gusty, Knapp's Rep. 274.) So, if it appear on the face of the proceedings, or otherwise, that the defendant in the foreign court was absent from the country before the suit was commenced, the judgment against him may be deemed invalid. (Buchanan v. Rucker, 1 Campb. 63, 9 East Rep. 192 ; Cavan v. Stewart, 1 Stark. Rep. 525 ; Frank- land v. M'Gusty, Knapp's Rep. 304.) the Attorney-General should commu- nicate with the absent party ; it was held, that such law was not so con- trary to national justice as to render void a judgment obtained against a party who had resided within the juris- diction of the court at the time when the cause of action accrued, but had withdrawn himself before the proceed- ings were commenced. (Ibid. ; Douglas v. Forrest, 4 Bing. 686 ; 1 Moore & Pay. 663.) So, horning, in Scotland (though the party was absent), was held legal, where the defendant had been domiciled in that country, and (Douglas v. In England, the judgment of an English court of record, however in- ferior, is conclusive, until reversed by writ of error (1 Doug. 5), and even English judgments of inferior courts, not of record, are to some purposes conclusive, unless it appear upon the face of the proceedings to have been un- fairly obtained (2 Burr. 1009; 2 Bing. 216). But the judgment of an infe- rior court may be controverted, when it appears that the proceedings have been bad in law, as, where a summons But, to render a foreign judgment void, and attachment, which ought to have on the ground that it is contrary to the been successive proceedings, in default law of the country where it was given, or to reason and justice, it must be shown clearly and unequivocally to be of appearance to the former, were is- sued against the defendant at the same time, and returnable at the same time, so. (Becquet v. McCarthy, 3 Barn. & and to which the defendant never ap- Adolp. 951.) But, if the error do not appear upon the face of the proceeding and the party complaining of the judg- peared (3 Barn. & Cres. 772 ; 5 Dowl. & Ryl. 719, S. C.) ; and it seems that the judgment of an inferior court may ment himself was misled, and sub- be avoided, by proof that the cause of mitted to the decision instead of pro- action did not arise within the jurisdio testing against it, he is too late to com- plain upon an appeal against it. (Mac- allislerv. Macallister, 4 Wilson & Shaw, tion of the court. (Willes, 36 n.; 2 Bing. 213.) With respect to the proof of foreign 142, 147.) And where the law of a judgments and decrees in England, it has British colony required, that, on a suit been decided, that an exemplification instituted against an absent party, the of a sentence in Holland under the process should be served upon the common seal of the States, may be read King's Attorney-General in the colony, in evidence in a suit in Chancery. but it was not expressly provided that Anon. 9 Mod. 56. W 253 167 EFFECTS OF THE DOMAIN BETWEEN NATIONS. BOOK n. circumstance of her having been nominated guardian by the CHAP, vii. domestic judge.* This was a very wrong application of a just principle : for, the prince's domestic residence could be no where but in his state : and it was only by the decree of the three estates, who alone had a right to choose a guardian for their sovereign, that the authority of the duchess of Longue- ville became firm and lawful at Neufchatel. In the same manner the validity of a testament, (108) as Wills and testaments. * Memorial in behalf of the duchess of Longueville, 1672. (108) See post Book II. ch. VIII. 103, p. 173, and 111, p. 175. It is now settled in Great Britain that a will is to be construed, inter- preted, and given effect to, according to the law of the country where it was made and where the testator had his domi- cile, and every court in ever)' country is bound to construe it accordingly. (Trotter v. Trotter, 3 Wilson & Shaw, Rep. on Appeal Cases, 407, 414, in House of Lords, appeal from Scotland.) And, therefore, where a native of Scot- land, domiciled in India, but who pos- sessed heritable bonds in Scotland, as well as personal property there, and, also, in India, having executed a will in India, ineffectual to convey Scotch heri- tage; and a question having arisen whether his heir-at-law (who claimed the heritable bonds as heir) was also entitled to a share of the movable pro- perty, as legatee under the will it was held in the House of Lords, in Eng- land (affirming the judgment of the court below), that the construction of the will, as to whether it expressed an intention to pass the Scotch heritable bonds, and the legal consequences of that construction, must be determined by the law of the land where it was made; and where the testator had his domicile, namely India, that is, by the law of England; and this although the will was the sub- ject of judicial inquiry in the courts of Scotland ; for, these courts also are bound to decide according to the law of the place where the will was made. (Id. ibid. 414.) A will must be inter- preted according to the law of the coun- try where it is made, and where the party making the will has his domicile. There are certain rules of construction adopted in the courts, and the expres- sions which are made use of in a will, and the language of a will, have fre- quently reference to those rules of con- struction ; and it would be productive, therefore, of the most mischievous con- 254 sequences, and in many instances de- feat the intention of the testator, if those rules were to be altogether disre- garded, and the judges of a foreign court (which it may be considered, in relation to the will), without reference to that knowledge which it is desirable to obtain of the law of the country in which the will was made, were to in- terpret the will according to their own rules of construction. That would also be productive of another inconvenience, namely, that the will might have a con- struction put upon it in the English courts different from that which might be put upon it in the foreign country. It appears to me, my Lords, that there is no solid ground for the objection; but that, where a will is executed in a foreign country by a person having his domicile in that country, with respect to that person's property, the will must be interpreted according to the law of the country where it is made ; it must, if it comes into question, in any pro- ceeding, have the same interpretation put upon it as would be put upon it in any tribunal of the country where it was made." Per Lord Chancellor. But, where a will was made by a native of Scotland, dotnidledin England, and having personal property only there, and who went for a short time to Scot- land, and there executed his will in the Scotch form, and registered it there, and afterwards died in England, it was held that such will must be construed according to the law of England, (Jln- struther v. Chalmers, 2 Simons, 1). It should seem, therefore, that in some cases, as respects personalty, the domi- cile of the testator is to be regarded rather than the precise place of signing the will (id. ibid., sed quere). A will made in Jamaica devising rents, issues, and profits of an estate there, passes slaves, mules, cattle, and machinery, (3 Simons, 398, Lushington v. Sewell, 1 Simons, 435, S. P.), though a devise of a farm in England would not pass farming utensils. (Stewart v. EFFECTS OF THE DOMAIN BETWEEN NATIONS. 167 to its form, can only be decided by the domestic judge, whose BOOK n sentence delivered in form ought to be everywhere acknow- CHAP - YI1 ' ledged. But, without affecting the validity of the testament itself, the bequests contained in it may be disputed before the judge of the place where the effects are situated, because those effects can only be disposed of conformably to the laws of the country. Thus, the abbs' D' Orleans above mentioned having appointed the prince of Conti his universal legatee, the three estates of Neufchatel, without waiting till the parlia- ment of Paris should pronounce their decision on the question of two contradictory wills made by the abbe* D'Orle'ans, gave the investiture of the principality to the duchess of Nemours, declaring that the sovereignty was unalienable. Besides, it might have been said on this occasion also, that the domestic residence of the prince could be nowhere but in the state. As every thing included in the country belongs to the 86. Desert nation, and, as none but the nation, or the person on whom a . nd u " cul - she has devolved her right, is authorized to dispose of those things ( 79), if she has left uncultivated and desert places in the country, no person whatever has a right to take pos- session of them without her consent. Though she does not make actual use of them, those places still belong to her ; she has an interest in preserving them for future use, and is not accountable to any person for the manner in which she makes use of her property. It is, however, necessary to recollect here what we have observed above (Book I. 81). No nation can lawfully appropriate to herself a too disproportionate ex- tent of country, and reduce other nations to want subsistence, and a place of abode. A German chief, in the time of Nero, said to the Romans, "As heaven belongs to the gods, so the earth is given to the human race ; and desert countries are common to all,"* giving those proud conquerors to under- stand that they had no right to reserve and appropriate to themselves a country which they left desert. The Romans [ 168 ] had laid waste a chain of country along the Rhine, to cover their provinces from the incursions of the barbarians. The German's remonstrance would have had a good foundation, had the Romans pretended to keep without reason a vast country which was of no use to them : but those lands which they would not suffer to be inhabited, serving as a rampart against foreign nations, were of considerable use to the empire. When there is not this singular circumstance, it is equally 87. Duty agreeable to the dictates of huma,nity, and to the particular respect. Maryat, 11 Ves.657.) So, if a Dutch- (Anon. 9 Mod. 66, and see Bowaman man be possessed of real estate in Hoi- v. Reeve, Pre. Ch. 577.) A will of land, and personal estate in England, property entirely abroad may be proved and devise his real estate to A., and there. (Jaunay v. Sealey, 1 Vern. 397.) his personal to B., the personal shall * Sicut coelum diis, ita terras generi be first applied to pay debts in Hoi- mortalium datas; quseque vacuse, eas land, though real estate is liable there, publicas esse. TACIT. 255 168 EFFECTS OF THE DOMAIN BETWEEN NATIONS. K advantage of the state, to give those desert tracts to foreign- _CHAP._VII._ erg W k are willing to clear the land and to render it valuable. The beneficence of the state thus turns to her own advantage ; she acquires new subjects, and augments her riches and power. This is the practice in America ; and, by this wise method, the English have carried their settlements in the new world to a degree of power which has considerably increased that of the nation. Thus, also, tne king of Prussia endeavours to re-people his states laid waste by the calamities of former wars. 88. Right The nation that possesses a country is at liberty to leave >f P h- SeSS " * n *^ e P r i m iti ve state of communion certain things that have that havTno as J e * no Owner 5 or t appropriate to herself the right of owner. possessing those things, as well as every other advantage which that country is capable of affording. And, as such a right is of use, it is, in case of doubt, presumed that the nation has reserved it to herself. It belongs to her, then, to the exclusion of foreigners, unless her laws expressly declare otherwise ; as those of the Romans, which left wild beasts, fish, &c., in the primitive state of communion. No foreigner, therefore, has a natural right to hunt or fish in the terri- tories of a state, to appropriate to himself a treasure found there, &c. g 89. Rights There exists no reason why a nation, or a sovereign, if au- granted to thorized by the laws, may not grant various privileges in their another na- territories to another nation, or to foreigners in general, since every one may dispose of his own property as he thinks fit. Thus, several sovereigns in the Indies have granted to the trading nations of Europe the privilege of having factories, ports, and even fortresses and garrisons in certain places within their dominions. We may in the same manner grant the right of fishing in a river, or on the coast, that of hunting in the forests, &c., and, when once these rights have been validly ceded, they constitute a part of the possessions of him who has acquired them, and ought to be respected in the same manner as his former possessions. g 90. It is Whoever agrees that robbery is a crime, and that we are Webfdrive not a ^ owe( ^ to ta ^ e fa^le possession of our neighbour's a nation l out.P r P er ty> w ^ acknowledge, without any other proof, that no of a country nation has a right to expel another people from the country which it in- they inhabit, in order to settle in'it herself. Notwithstanding habits, f^g extreme inequality of climates and soils, every people ought to be contented with that which has fallen to their share. [ 169 ] Will the conductors of nations despise a rule that constitutes all their safety in civil society ? Let this sacred rule be en- tirely forgotten, and the peasant will quit his thatched cottage to invade the palaces of the great, or the delightful possessions of the rich. The ancient Helvetians, discontented with their native soil, burned all their habitations, and commenced their march, in order to establish themselves, sword in hand, in the fertile plains of southern Gaul. But they received a terrible 256 EFFECTS OF THE DOMAIN BETWEEN NATIONS. 169 lesson from a conqueror of superior abilities to themselves, BOOK n. and who paid still less regard to the laws of justice. Csesar _ HAP- Y "' defeated them, and drove them back into their own country. Their posterity, however, more wise than they, confine their views to the preservation of the lands and the independence they have received from nature : they live contented, and the labour of free hands counterbalances the sterility of the soil. There are conquerors, who, aspiring after nothing more g 91, nor to than the extension of the boundaries of their dominions, with- extend by out expelling the inhabitants from a country, content them- violence the i i. i j.i. i ii-i. 1.1. bounds of selves with subduing them ; a violence less barbarous, but empire not less unjust : while they spare the property of individuals, they seize all the rights of the nation, and of the sovereign. Since the least encroachment on the territory of another 92. The is an act of injustice, in order to avoid the commission of limits of any such act, and to prevent every subject of discord, every terr ' tone * occasion of quarrel, the limits of territories ought to be marked ^fefum- out with clearness and precision. If those who drew up the settled, treaty of Utrecht had bestowed on so important a subject all the attention it deserved, we should not see France and Eng- land in arms, in order to decide by a bloody war what are to be the boundaries of their possessions in America. But the makers of treaties often designedly leave in them some obscu- rity, some uncertainty, in order to reserve for their nation a pretext for a rupture : an unworthy artifice in a transaction wherein good faith alone ought to preside ! We have also seen commissioners endeavouring to overreach or corrupt those of a neighbouring state, in order to gain for their master an unjust acquisition of a few leagues of territory. How can princes or ministers stoop to dirty tricks that would dishonour a private man ? We should not only refrain from usurping the territory of g 93. Viola- others ; we should also respect, and abstain from every act tion of ter - contrary to the rights of the sovereign : for, a foreign nation nior ?- can claim no right in it ( 79). We cannot, then, without doing an injury to a state, enter its territories with force and arms in pursuit of a criminal, and take him from thence. This would at once be a violation of the safety of the state, and a trespass on the rights of empire or supreme authority vested in the sovereign. This is what is called a violation of territory ; and among nations there is nothing more gene- rally acknowledged as an injury that ought to be vigorously repelled by every state that would not suffer itself to be op- pressed. We shall make use of this principle in speaking of war, which gives occasion for many questions on the rights of territory. The sovereign may forbid the entrance of his territory 3 94 . Pro . hibition to (109) See further as to the subject A 84, 85; Marten's Law of Nations, enter the of this section, 1 Chit. Com. Law, 73 153. territory. 33 w2 257 (109) 170 EFFECTS OF THE DOMAIN BETWEEN NATION8. BOOK n. either to foreigners in general or in particular cases, or to CHAP. YII. cer t a i n persons or for certain particular purposes, according as he may think it advantageous to the state. There is no- thing in all this that does not flow from the rights of domain and sovereignty : every one is obliged to pay respect to the prohibition ; and whoever dares to violate it, incurs the penalty decreed to render it effectual, But the prohibition ought to be known, as well as the penalty annexed to disobedience : those who are ignorant of it, ought to be informed of it when they approach to enter the country. Formerly the Chinese, fear- ing lest the intercourse of strangers should corrupt the man- ners of the nation, and impair the maxims of a wise but sin-, gular government, forbade all people entering the empire : a prohibition that was not at all inconsistent with justice, pro- vided they did not refuse human assistance to those whom tempest or necessity obliged to approach their frontiers. It was salutary to the nation, without violating the rights of any individual, or even the duties of humanity, which permits us. in case of competition, to prefer ourselves to others, g 95. A If at the same time two or more nations discover and take country pos- possession of an island or any other desert land without an sessed by Owner5 they ought to agree between themselves, and make an tiJniTat'the equitable partition ; but, if they cannot agree, each will have same time, the right of empire and the domain in the parts in which they first settled. 96. A An independent individual, whether he has been driven country pos- from his country, or has legally quitted it of his own accord, sessed by a ma y se ttl e j n a C0 untry which he finds without an owner, and there possess an independent domain. Whoever would after- wards make himself master of the entire country, could not do it with justice without respecting the rights and independ- ence of this person. But, if he himself finds a sufficient number of men who are willing to live under his laws, he may form a new state within the country he has discovered, and possess there both the domain and the empire. But, if this individual should arrogate to himself alone an exclusive right to a country, there to reign monarch without subjects, his vain pretensions would be justly held in contempt : a rash and ridiculous possession can produce no real right. There are also other means by which a private person may found a new state. Thus, in the eleventh century, some Norman noblemen founded a new empire in Sicily, after hav- ing wrested that island by conquest from the common enemies of the Christian name. The custom of the nation permitted the citizens to quit their country in order to seek their for- tune elsewhere. 97. inde- When several independent families are settled in a country, pendent fa- they possess the free domain, but without sovereignty, since miiies in a they do not form a political society. Nobody can seize the em pire of that country ; since this would be reducing tho&e 258 EFFECTS OF THE DOMAIN BETWEEN NATIONS. 170 families to subjection against their will ; and no man has a BOOK n. right to command men who are born free, unless they volun- CHAP - - tarily submit to him. If those families have fixed settlements, the place possessed by each is the peculiar property of that family : the rest of [ 171 ] the country of which they make no use, being left in the primitive state of communion, belongs to the first occupant. Whoever chooses to settle there, may lawfully take possession of it. Families wandering in a country, as the nations of shep- herds, and ranging through it as their wants require, possess it in common : it belongs to them to the exclusion of all other nations ; and we .cannot, without injustice, deprive them of the tracts of country of which they make use. But, let us here recollect what we have said more than once (Book I. 81 and 209, Book II. 69). The savages of North Ame- rica had no right to appropriate all that vast continent to themselves ; and since they were unable to inhabit the whole of those regions, other nations might, without injustice, set- tle in some parts of them, provided they left the natives a sufficiency of land. If the pastoral Arabs would carefully cultivate the soil, a less space might be sufficient for them. Nevertheless, no other nation has a right to narrow their boundaries, unless she be under an absolute want of land. For, in short, they possess their country ; they make use of it after their manner ; they reap from it an advantage suit- able to their manner of life, respecting which they have no laws to receive from any one. In a case of pressing neces- sity, I think people might, without injustice, settle in a part of that country, on teaching the Arabs the means of render- ing it, by the cultivation of the earth, sufficient for their own wants, and those of the new inhabitants. It may happen that a nation is contented with possessing $ 98. Pos- only certain places, or appropriating to itself certain rights, session of in a country that has not an owner, without being solicitous cemin to take possession of the whole country. In this case, an- J r "J* C eSin other nation may take possession of what the first has neg- rights, in a lected ; but this cannot be done without allowing all the rights vacant acquired by the first to subsist in their full and absolute inde- C0untl 7- pendence. In such cases, it is proper that regulations should be made^by treaty ; and this precaution is seldom neglected among civilized nations. 259 171 RULES WITH RESPECT TO FOREIGNERS. BOOK II. CHAP. VIII. CHAP. VIII. RULES WITH RESPECT TO FOREIGNERS. 99. Gene- WE have already treated^Book I. 213) of tie inhabi- 1 ldca of tants, or persons who reside in a country where they are not the state* 10 citizens. We shall here treat only of those foreigners who ought to ob- pass through or sojourn in a country, either on business, or serve to- merely as travellers. The relation that subsists between them wards fo- an( j ^ e g OC j[ e ty j n which they now live the objects of their journey, and of their temporary residence the duties of hu- manity the rights, the interest, and the safety of the state which harbours them the rights of that to which they belong [ 172 ] all these principles, combined and applied according to cases and circumstances, serve to determine the conduct that ought to be observed towards them, and to point out our right and our duty with respect to them. But the intention of this chapter is not so much to show what humanity and justice require towards foreigners, as to establish the rules of the law of nations on this subject rules tending to secure the rights of all parties, and to prevent the repose of nations being dis- turbed by the quarrels of individuals. g 100. En- Since the lord of the territory may, whenever he thinks tering the proper, forbid its being entered ( 94), he has, no doubt, a territory, power to annex what conditions he pleases to the permission to enter. This, as we have already said, is a consequence of the right of domain. Can it be necessary to add, that the owner of the territory ought, in this instance, to respect the duties of humanity ? The case is the same with all rights whatever : the proprietor may use them at his discretion ; and, in so doing, he does not injure any person ; but, if he would be free from guilt, and keep his conscience pure, he will never use them but in such manner as is most conformable to his duty. We speak here, in general, of the rights which belong to the lord of the country, reserving for the following chapter the examination of the cases in which he cannot refuse an entrance into his territory ; and we shall see, in Chap. X., how his duty towards all mankind obliges him, on other occasions, to allow a free passage through, and a residence in his state. If the sovereign annexes any particular condition to the permission to enter his territories, he ought to have measures taken to make foreigners acquainted with it, when they pre- sent themselves on the frontier. There are states, such as China and Japan, into which all foreigners are forbid to penetrate without an express permis- (110) See more fully, Grotiua, book 2, chap. 2, p. 153; 1 Chit. Com. L. 86, 87. 260 KULES WITH RESPECT TO FOREIGNERS. 172 sion ; but, in Europe, the access is everywhere free to every BOOK n. person who is not an enemy of the state, except, in some CHAP - Tm : countries, to vagabonds and outcasts. But, even in those countries which every foreigner may 101. FO- freely enter, the sovereign is supposed to allow him access reigners are only upon this tacit condition, that he be subject to the laws, I mean the general laws made to maintain good order, and which have no relation to the title of citizen or of subject of the state. The public safety, the rights of the nation and of the prince, necessarily require this condition ; and the foreigner tacitly submits to it, as soon as he enters the coun- try, as he cannot presume that he has access upon any other footing. The sovereignty is the right to command in the whole country ; and the laws are not simply confined to regu- lating the conduct of the citizens towards each other, but also determine what is to be observed by all orders of people throughout the whole extent of the state. In virtue of this submission, foreigners who commit faults g 102. and are to be punished according to the laws of the country. The punishable object of punishment is to cause the laws to be respected, an to maintain order and safety. r For the same reason, disputes that may arise between foreign- g 103. who ers, or between a foreigner and a citizen, are to be determined is the judge by the judge of the place, and according to the laws of the of their dls - place. (Ill) And, as the dispute properly arises from the putes ' (111) {In the courts of the United amity with another state, the courts of States alien friends are entitled to claim the latter ought not to give effect to the same protection of their rights as it. In neither case ought the accidental citizens. Taylor v. Carpenter, 3 Story's removal of either of the parties into a Rep. 458.} See ante, 166, in notes, as foreign country, or his prosecuting his to foreign judgments. The doctrine remedy there, alter the substance of the here advanced by Vattel (excepting as remedy ; and, however inconvenient regards land) is contrary to the present and difficult it may be to investigate French Code, and many other authors, and accurately ascertain the precise Upon principle, it should seem, that if state of foreign law, still, if courts will a contract or right be created in one entertain jurisdiction over such cases, country, and be there by the lex loci they ought to administer the law so as subjected to certain qualifications, and to give effect to the transaction pre- clothed with certain privileges, it ought cisely the same as if it had been liti- to be enforced if at all as against all gated in the country where created ; the original parties, precisely the same for, otherwise the original expectations, in a foreign country as it would be in rights, and interests of the parties would that where it was created ; and this, not be given effect to ; and it would be although it be a negotiable security, conceded that, more especially after a and the interest therein vested in a competent local court has already de- third person resident in a foreign cided upon the transaction (without any country, because the latter ought, apparent injustice,) such decision ought when he takes it, to inquire into the to be conclusive in all other courts and circumstances and law which affected countries. it in the place where it was made. These principles are fully acknow- And (I fortiori it should seem that if a ledgod and given effect to in the pre- contract or transaction were in viola- sent French Code and in their admi- tion of the state regulations of a foreign nistration of the law. (See Pardessus, nation where it was made, as in fraud Droit Commercial, vol. 1, p. 455, 4 id. of its revenue, and such state is in 196, 205, 209 to 211, and 220 to 223, 261 1T3 RULES WITH RESPECT TO FOREIGNERS. BOOK ii. refusal of the defendant, who maintains that he is not bound CHAP. YIII. to p er f orm wnat i s required of him, it follows, from the same principle, that every defendant ought to be prosecuted before his own judge, who alone has a right to condemn him, and titles, "Dee Conflitede Legislation relatif an Commerce ;" " De V application de lois estrangeres relatives & la forme des actes ;" "De V interpretation des actes f aits en pays estrangers ;" " De I' execution des actes fails en pays estrangers.") Thus, in their courts it has been considered, that, if a bill of exchange be made in a fo- reign country, defective according to the French law, but valid according to the foreign law, it must nevertheless be given effect to in the French courts, even against a French endorser, "par ce que les regies sur la validiti intrinseque des conventions, sont derivees du droit natural, et sont de toutes les legislations ;" and in the case of limitations, it is laid down that the law of prescriptions prevailing in the country where the contract was made, though different from that in France, must, in their courts, be given effect to. (4 Pardessus, 223.) They admit the difficulty of as- certaining correctly the foreign law, but consider that difficulty as not con- stituting any sufficient grounds for re- lieving their courts from the necessity of giving full effect to the contract ac- cording to the law of the place where it was made. (4 Pardessus, 246.) When the foreign law differs from that where the suit is depending, undoubtedly the party relying on the foreign law must prove it. (Drown v. Lacy, 1 Dowl. & Byl. Ni. Pri. Cas. 41, n. (a). As to the evidence, see post, note.) In Great Britain the same theory is professed, and prevails to a limited extent; but the courts have so nar- rowedly applied it, that, as regards the process for the recovery of the claim, and the time when it must be commenced, it is a doctrine rather in name than in practice, excepting in a few instances as regards foreign marriages, and a few other cases. Dalrymple v. Dalrymplc, Hagg. Rep. 54 ; Lacon v. Higgins, 1 Dowl. & Ryl. XL Pri. Rep. 38; Roach v. Garvan, 1 Ves. 159.) In theory it is laid down, that effect ought to be given to contracts, and especially to bills of exchange according to the law of the country where the contract was made, and in which it was to bo performed, and not according to the law of the country into which either or all may ro- 262 move ; for, what is not an obligation in one place cannot, by the laws of another country, become such in another place. (The King of Spain v. Machado, 4 Russ. Rep. 239 ; Burrows v. Jcmino, 2 Stra. 733; Sel. Cas. 144, S. C. ; Potter v. Brown, 5 East, 130 ; Chitty on Bills, 8th edit, 191.) And a foreign marriage, if celebrated according to the lex loci, will be valid, though in a form quite different to that prescribed by English law. Lacon v. Higgins, 1 Dowl. TnT a right, and is even in duty bound to prohibit them, or to . subject to certain conditions the permission to contract them: and, as it belongs to the nation or to her sovereign to deter- mine what appears most conducive to the welfare of the state, other nations ought to acquiesce in the regulations which any sovereign state has made on this head. Citizens are almost everywhere forbid to marry foreign wives of a different religion ; and in many parts of Switzerland a citizen cannot marry a foreign woman, unless he prove that she brings him in mar- riage a certain sum fixed by the law. CHAP. IX. [ 178 ] OF THE RIGHTS RETAINED BY ALL NATIONS AFTER THE CHAP, ix. INTRODUCTION OF DOMAIN AND PROPERTY. IF an obligation, as we have before observed, gives a right \ lie. What to those things without which it cannot be fulfilled, every ab- are the solute, necessary, and indispensable obligation produces H^j^men this manner rights equally absolute, necessary, and indefea- cannot be sible. Nature imposes no obligations on men without giving deprived, them the means of fulfilling them. They have an absolute right to the necessary use of those means : nothing can deprive them of that right, as nothing can dispense with their fulfilling their natural obligations. In the primitive state of communion, men had, without dis- 117. Right tinction, a right to the use of every thing, as far as was ne- sti11 remain- cessary to the discharge of their natural obligations. And, JUSS**" as nothing could deprive them of this right, the introduction ^"teVfcom- of domain and property could not take place without leaving munion. to every man the necessary use of things, that is to say, the use absolutely required for the fulfilment of natural obli- gations. We cannot, then, suppose the introduction to have taken place without this tacit restriction, that every man should still preserve some right to the things subjected to pro- perty, in those cases where, without this right, he would re- main absolutely deprived of the necessary use of things of this nature. This right is a necessary remnant of the primitive state of communion. Notwithstanding the domain of nations, therefore, each ? 118 - Ri g h * nation still retains some right to what is possessed by others, retained . bv in those cases where she would find herself deprived of the J"J ^ m as evidence of the law of that country, of France. (Lacon v. Hiygini, 1 Dowl- and, therefore, I shall act upon that ing & Ryland, Ni. Pri. Cases, 38; 3 authority, and receive the printed copy Stark. Rep. 176, S. C.; Sutler v. Free- now produced as evidence of the law man, Ambl. 303.) 271 178 RIGHTS WHICH BELONG TO ALL NATIONS. BOOK n. necessary use of certain things if she were to be absolutely debarred from using them by the consideration of their be- CHAP. property of } n g O ther people's property. We ought carefully to weigh every circumstance in order to make a just application of this principle. 119. Right I say the same of the right of necessity. We thus call the of necessity, r ight which necessity alone gives to the performance of cer- tain actions that are otherwise' unlawful, when, without these actions, it is impossible to fulfil an indispensable obligation. But it is carefully to be noted, that, in such a case, the obli- gation must really be an indispensable one, and the act in question the only means of fulfilling that obligation. If either of these conditions be wanting, the right of necessity does not exist on the occasion. We may see these subjects discussed in treatises on the law of nature, and particularly in that of Mr. Wolf. I confine myself here to a brief sum- mary of those principles whose aid is necessary to us in de- [ 179 ] veloping the rights of nations. 120. Right The earth was designed to feed its inhabitants ; and he who of procuring j g j n wan t O f every thing is not obliged to starve because all b^fbrce 113 P r P ert J is vested in others. When, therefore, a nation is (fig) ' in absolute want of provisions, she may compel her neigh- bours who have more than they want for themselves to supply her with a share of them, at a fair price ; she may even take it by force, if they will not sell it. Extreme necessity re- vives the primitive communion, the abolition of which ought to deprive no person of the necessaries of life ( 117). The same right belongs to individuals, when a foreign nation re- fuses them a just assistance. Captain Bontekoe, a Dutchman, having lost his vessel at sea, escaped in his boat, with a part of his crew, and landed on an Indian coast, where the bar- barous inhabitants refusing him provisions, the Dutch obtained them sword in hand.* 1 121. Right In the same manner, if a nation has a pressing want of the of making ghips, wagons, horses, or even the personal labour of foreign- thin ^ that ers ' sne ma 7 ma ^ e use ^ them, either by free consent or by belong to force, provided that the proprietors be not under the same others. (119) necessity. But, as she has no more right to these things than necessity gives her, she ought to pay for the use she makes of them, if she has the means of paying. The practice of Europe is conformable to this maxim. In cases of necessity, a nation sometimes presses foreign vessels which happen to be in her ports ; but she pays a compensation for the services performed by them. g 122. Right Let us say a few words on a more singular case, since au- of carrying thors have treated of it a case in which at present, people off women. (119) See the doctrine of Preemption, * Bonketoe's Voyage, in the Voyage* 1 Chitty's Com. Law, 103, 104, 105, 446, of the Dutch to the East Indies. 447. 272 EIGHTS WHICH BELOXG TO ALL NATIONS. 179 are never reduced to employ force. A nation cannot preserve BOOK n. and perpetuate itself, except by propagation. A nation of CHAP ' IX " men has, therefore, a right to procure women, who are abso- lutely necessary to its preservation ; and if its neighbours, who have a redundancy of females, refuse to give some of them in marriage to those men, the latter may justly have recourse to force. We have a famous example of this in the rape of the Sabine women.* But, though a nation is allowed to procure for itself, even by force of arms, the liberty of obtaining women in marriage, no woman in particular can be constrained in her choice, nor become, by right, the wife of a man who carries her off by force a circumstance which has not been attended to by those who have decided, without restriction, that the Romans did not commit an act of injustice on that oc- casion, f It is true that the Sabine women submitted to their fate with a good grace ; and, when their nation took up arms to avenge them, it sufficiently appeared, from the ardour with which those women rushed between the combatants, that they willingly acknowledged the Romans for their lawful husbands. "We may further add, that, if the Romans, as many pretend, were originally only a band of robbers united under Romulus, they did not form a true nation, or a legitimate state ; the [ 180 ] neighbouring nations had a just right to refuse them women ; and the law of nature, which approves no civil society but such as is legitimate, did not require them to furnish that society of vagabonds and robbers with the means of perpetu- ating itself; much less did it authorize the latter to procure those means by force. In the same manner, no nation was obliged to furnish the Amazons with males. That nation of women, if it ever existed, put itself, by its own fault, out of a condition to support itself without foreign assistance. The right of passage is also a remnant of the primitive state ills. Right of communion, in which the entire earth was common to all of passage, mankind, and the passage was everywhere free to each indi-^ 120 ^ vidual according to his necessities. Nobody can be entirely deprived of this right ( 117) ; but the exercise of it is limited by the introduction of domain and property : since they have been introduced, we cannot exert that right without paying due regard to the private rights of others. The effect of pro- perty is, to give the proprietor's advantage a preference over that of all others. When, therefore, the owner of a territory thinks proper to refuse you admission into it, you must, in order to enter it in spite of him, have some reason more * Livy, book i. and states that the law of humanity f Wolfii Jus Gent. g 341. does not seem to oblige us to grant pas- (120) See fully 1 Chitty's Com. L., 84 ; sage to any other goods except such as are Grotius, book ii. chap. ii. p. 153, states absolutely necessary for the purpose of that a nation is bound to grant free pas- their life to whom they are thus con- sage without reserve or discretion. But veyed. Puff, book iii. chap. iii. 6, Puffendorf appears to agree with Vattel, p. 29. 35 273 180 EIGHTS WHICH BELONG TO ALL NATIONS. BOOK n. cogent than all his reasons to the contrary. Such is the right - CHAP - 1X :_ O f necessity : this authorizes an act on your part, which on other occasions would be unlawful, viz. a,n infringement of the right of domain. When a real necessity obliges you to enter into the territory of others, for instance, if you cannot other- wise escape from imminent danger, or if you have no other passage for procuring the means of subsistence, or those of satisfying some other indispensable obligation, you may force a passage when it is unjustly refused. But, if an equal necessity obliges the proprietor to refuse you entrance, he refuses it justly ; and his right is paramount to yours. Thus, a vessel driven by stress of weather has a right to enter, even by force, into a foreign port. But, if that vessel is affected with the plague, the owner of the port may fire upon it and beat it off, without any violation either of justice, or even of charity, which, in such a case, ought doubtless to begin at home. 1 124. and of The right of passage through a country would in most cases procuring k e useless, without that of procuring necessaries at a fair necessaries, ^^ . an( j we k ave a j rea( jy Sn0 wn ( 120) that in case of ne- cessity it is lawful to take provisions even by force. 1 125. Right In speaking of exile and banishment, we have observed of dwelling (B 00 k I. 229231) that every man has a right to dwell to f"* el 8 B somewhere upon earth. What we have shown with respect to individuals may be applied to whole nations. If a people are driven from the place of their abode, they have a right to seek a retreat : the nation to which they make application ought then to grant them a place of habitation, at least for a time, if she has not very important reasons for a refusal. But, if the country inhabited by this nation is scarcely suffi- cient for herself, she is under no obligation to allow a band of foreigners to settle in it for ever : she may even dismiss [ 181 ] them at once, if it be not convenient to her to grant them a permanent settlement. As they have the resource of seek- ing an establishment elsewhere, they cannot claim any autho- rity from the right of necessity, to stay in spite of the owners of the country. But it is necessary, in short, that these fugitives should find a retreat ; and, if everybody rejects them, they will be justifiable in making a settlement in the first country where they find land enough for themselves, without depriving the inhabitants of what is sufficient for them. But, even in this case, their necessity gives them only the right of habitation ; and they are bound to submit to all the conditions, not absolutely intolerable, which may be im- posed on them by the master of the country, such as pay- ing him tribute, becoming his subjects, or at least living under his protection, and, in certain respects, depending on him. This right, as well aS the two preceding, is a remnant of the primitive state of communion. g 126. We have been occasionally obliged to anticipate the subject Things of O f tne p resen t chapter, in order to follow the order of the 274 EIGHTS WHICH BELONG TO ALL NATIONS. 181 different subjects that presented themselves. Thus, in speak- BOOK n. ing of the open sea, we have remarked (Book I. 281) that CHAP - IX ' those things, the use of which is inexhaustible, cannot fall wl ch the under the domain or property of any one ; because, in that J^^g 1 " free and independent state in which nature has produced them, they may be equally useful to all men. And, as to those things even which in other respects are subject to do- main, if their use is inexhaustible, they remain common with respect to that use. Thus a river may be subject both to do- main and empire ; but, in quality of running water, it remains common, that is to say, the owner of the river cannot hin- der any one from drinking and drawing water out of it. Thus, the sea, even in those parts that are held in possession, being sufficient for the navigation of all mankind, he who has the domain cannot refuse a passage through it to any vessel from which he has nothing to fear. But it may happen, by accident, that this inexhaustible use of the thing may be justly refused by the owner, when people cannot take advan- tage of it without incommoding him or doing him a prejudice. For instance, if you cannot come to my river for water without passing over my land and damaging the crop it bears, I may for that reason debar you from the inexhaustible use of the running water : in which case, it is but through accident you are de- prived of it. This leads us to speak of another right which has a great connection with that just mentioned, and is even derived from it ; that is, the right of innocent use. We call innocent use, or innocent advantage, that which 127. Right may be derived from a thing without causing either loss or of innocent inconvenience to the proprietor; and the right of innocent*' use is the right we have to that advantage or use which may be made of things belonging to another, without causing him either loss or inconvenience. I have said that this right is derived from the right to things of which the use is inex- haustible. In fact, a thing that may be useful to any one [ 182 ] without loss or inconvenience to the owner, is, in this respect, inexhaustible in the use ; and that is the reason why the law of nature still allows all men a right to it notwithstanding the introduction of domain and property. Nature, who de- signs her gifts for the common advantage of mankind, does not allow us to prevent the application of those gifts to a useful purpose which they may be made to serve without any preju- dice to the proprietor, and without any diminution of the utility and advantages he is capable of deriving from his rights. This right of innocent use is not a perfect right, like that ? 128. Na- of necessity : for, it belongs to the owner to judge whether ture of this the use we wish to make of a thing that belongs to him will [JJ not be attended with damage or inconvenience. If others should presume to decide on the occasion, and, in case of re- fusal, to compel the proprietor, he would be no longer master of his own property. It may frequently happen that the 275 182 BIGHTS WHICH BELONG TO ALL NATIONS. BOOK n. person who wishes to derive advantage from a thing shall CHAP, ix. ^ eem t k e uge Q f - t p er f ect iy innocent, though it is not so in fact ; and if, in such case, he attempts to force the proprietor, he exposes himself to the risk of committing an act of injus- tice; nay, he actually commits one, since he infringes the owner's right to judge of what is proper to be done on the occasion. In all cases, therefore, which admit of any doubt, we have only an imperfect right to the innocent use of things that belong to others. 1 129. and But, when the innocence of the use is evident, and abso- in cases not lutely indubitable, the refusal is an injury. For, in addition doubtful. f. a manifest violation of the rights of the party by whom that innocent use is required, such refusal is moreover a tes- timony of an injurious disposition of hatred or contempt for him. To refuse a merchant-ship the liberty of passing through a strait, to fishermen that of drying their nets on the sea- shore, or of watering at a river, is an evident infringement of the right they have to the innocent use of things in those cases. But in every case, if we are not pressed by necessity, we may ask the owner his reasons for the refusal, and if he gives none, we may consider him as an unjust man ; or an enemy, with whom we are to act according to the rules of prudence. In general, we should regulate our sentiments and conduct towards him, according to the greater or lesser weight of the reasons on which he acts. g 130. Ex- All nations do therefore still retain a general right to the ercise of this innocent use of things that are under the domain of any one individual nation. But, in the particular application of this tions. right? it is the nation in whom the property is vested that is to determine whether the use which others Avish to make of what belongs to her be really innocent: and, if she gives them a denial, she ought to allege her reasons ; as she must not deprive others of their right from mere caprioe. All this is founded in justice : for, it must be remembered that the innocent use of things is not comprehended in the domain, or [ 183 ] the exclusive property. The domain gives only the right of judging, in particular cases, whether the use be really inno- cent. Now, he who judges ought to have his reasons ; and he should mention them, if he would have us think that he forms any judgment, and not that he acts from caprice or ill- nature. All this, I say, is founded in justice. In the next chapter, we shall see the line of conduct which a nation is, by her duty to other nations, bound to observe in the exer- cise of her rights. 276 HOW A NATION IS TO USE HER BIGHT OP DOMAIN. 183 BOOK II. CHAP. X. CHAP. X. HOW A NATION IS TO USE HER RIGHT OF DOMAIN, IN ORDER TO DISCHARGE HER DUTIES TOWARDS OTHER NATIONS, WITH RESPECT TO THE INNOCENT USE OF THINGS. SINCE the law of nations treats as well of the duties of I isi. Ge- states as of their rights, it is not sufficient that we have ex- n r ^ duty plained, on the subject of innocent use, what all nations have ^ a right to require from the proprietor : we are now to con- sider what influence his duties to others ought to have on the proprietor's conduct. As it belongs to him to judge whether the use be really innocent, and not productive of any detri- ment or inconvenience to himself, he ought not to give a re- fusal unless it be grounded upon real and substantial reasons : this is a maxim of equity : he ought not even to stop at trifles, a slight loss, or any little inconvenience : humanity forbids this ; and the mutual love which men owe to each other, re- quires greater sacrifices. It would certainly be too great a deviation from that universal benevolence which ought to unite the human race, to refuse a considerable advantage to an in- dividual, or to a whole nation, whenever the grant of it might happen to be productive of the most trifling loss or the slight- est inconvenience to ourselves. In this respect, therefore, a nation ought on all occasions to regulate her conduct by rea- sons proportioned to the advantages and necessities of others, and to reckon as nothing a small expense or a supportable inconvenience, when great good will thence result to another nation. But she is under no obligation to incur heavy ex- penses or embarrassments, for the sake of furnishing others with the use of any thing, when such use is neither necessary nor of any great utility to them. The sacrifice we here require is not contrary to the interests of the nation : it is natural to think that the others will behave in the same manner in return ; and how great the advantages that will result to all states from such a line of conduct ! The introduction of property cannot be supposed to have 132. in- deprived nations of the general right of traversing the earth nocent pas- for the purposes of mutual intercourse, of carrying on com- sa s e - ( m ) merce with each other, and for other just reasons. It is only on particular occasions, when the owner of a country thinks it would be prejudicial or dangerous to allow a passage through [ 184 ] it, that he ought to refuse permission to pass. He is there- fore bound to grant a passage for lawful purposes, whenever he can do it without inconvenience to himself. And he can- (121) See, in general, 1 Chitty's Com. Law, 84, 88. Y 277 184 HOW A NATION IS TO USE HER RIGHT OF DOMAIN. BOOK n. not lawfully annex burdensome conditions to a permission , CHAP " *' which he is obliged to grant, and which he cannot refuse if he wishes to discharge his duty, and not abuse his right of pro- perty. The count of Lupfen having improperly stopped some merchandise in Alsace, and complaints being made on the subject to the emperor Sigismund, who was then at the council of Constance, that prince assembled the electors, princes, and deputies of towns, to examine the affair. The opinion of the burgrave of Nuremberg deserves to be men- tioned: "God," said he, "has created heaven for himself and his saints, and has given the earth to mankind, intending it for the advantage of the poor as well as of the rich. The roads are for their use, and God has not subjected them to any taxes." He condemned the count of Lupfen to restore the merchandise, and to pay costs and damages, because he could not justify his seizure by any peculiar right. The emperor approved this opinion, and passed sentence accordingly.* 133. Sure- But, if any apprehension of danger arise from the grant re* uked b<> ^ l^erty to P ass tnrou g a a country, the state has a right to require sureties : the party who wishes to pass cannot refuse them, a passage being only so far due to him as it is attended with no inconvenience. 134. Pas- In like manner, a passage ought also to be granted for sage of mer- merchandise : and, as this is in general productive of no in- (122) 1S6 ' convenience, to refuse it without just reason is injuring a nation, and endeavouring to deprive her of the means of car- rying on a trade with other states. If this passage occasions any inconvenience, any expense for the preservation of canals and highways, we may exact a compensation for it by toll duties (Book I. 103). g 135. Resi- In explaining the effects of domain we have said above the entrance into it, or permit it on such conditions as he thinks proper. We were then treating of his external right, that right which foreigners are bound to respect. But now that we are considering the matter in another view, and as it relates to his duties and to his internal right, we may venture to assert that he cannot, without particular and important reasons, refuse permission, either to pass through or reside in the country, to foreigners who desire it for lawful purposes. For, their passage or their residence being in this case an in- nocent advantage, the law of nature does not give him a right to refuse it : and, though other nations and other men in ge- neral are obliged to submit to his judgment ( 128 and 130), he does not the less offend against his duty, if he refuses without sufficient reason : he then acts without any true right ; he only abuses his external right. He cannot, therefore, * Stettler, vol. i. p. 114. Tschudi, (122) Puffendorf, b. 3, ch. 3, s. 6, vol. ii. pp. 27, 28. p. 29. 278 HOW A NATION IS TO USE HER RIGHT OF DOMAIN. 185 without some particular and cogent reason, refuse the liberty BOOK n. of residence to a foreigner who comes into the country with HAP ' x '.. the hope of recovering his health, or for the sake of acquir- ing instruction in the schools and academies. A difference in religion is not a sufficient reason to exclude him, provided he do not engage in controversial disputes with a view to dissemi- nate his tenets : for, that difference does not deprive him of the rights of humanity. "We have seen ( 125) how the right of necessity may in $ ise. HOW certain cases authorize a people, who are driven from the we are to place of their residence, to settle in the territory of another * ct t ward3 nation. Every state ought, doubtless, to grant to so unf or- .J^ 1 desire tunate a people every aid and assistance which she can be- a perpetual stow without being wanting to herself: but to grant them an residence, establishment in the territories of the nation, is a very deli- cate step, the consequences of which should be maturely con- sidered by the conductor of the state. The emperors Probus and Valens experienced the evil effects of their conduct in having admitted into the territories of the empire numerous bands of Gepidse, Vandals, Goths, and other barbarians.* If the sovereign finds that such a step would be attended with too great an inconvenience or danger, he has a right to refuse an establishment to those fugitive people, or to adopt, on their admission, every precaution that prudence can dic- tate to him. One of the safest will be, not to permit those foreigners to reside together in the same part of the country, there to keep up the form of a separate nation. Men who have not been able to defend their own country, cannot pre- tend to any right to establish themselves in the territory of another, in order to maintain themselves there as a nation in a body.f The sovereign who harbours them may therefore disperse them, and distribute them into the towns and pro- vinces that are in want of inhabitants. In this manner his charity will turn to his own advantage, to the increase of his power, and to the greater benefit of the state. What a dif- ference is observable in Brandenburg since the settlement of the French refugees ! The great elector, Frederic William, offered an asylum to those unfortunate people ; he provided for their expenses on the road, and with truly regal munifi- cence established them in his states ; by which conduct that beneficent and generous prince merited the title of a wise and able politician. When, by the laws or the custom of a state, certain actions isr. Right are generally permitted to foreigners, as, for instance, tra- accruing * Vopiscus, Prob. c. xviii. Ammian. seized, that it was not just for them to Marcell. lib. xxxi. Socrat. Hist Eccles. invade the territories of others, since lib. iv. c. 28. they had not been able to defend their f Caasar replied to the Tenchtheri own. Neque verum ease, qui suos fines and Usipetos, who wanted to retain tueri non potnerint, alienos occupare. De possession of the territories they had Bello Gallico, lib. iv. cap. vi. 279 J85 HOW A NATION IS TO USE HER RIGHT OF DOMAIN. BOOK ii. veiling freely through the country without any express per- CHAP ' x- mission, marrying there, buying or selling merchandise, hunt- from a ge- ~ m g^ fishing, &c., we cannot exclude any one nation from the mission 01 "" benefit of the general permission, without doing her an in- f 186 1 J ur y' un ^ ess there be some particular and lawful reason for J refusing to that nation what is granted indiscriminately to others. The question here, it is to be observed, only relates to those actions which are productive of innocent advantage: and, as the nation allows them to foreigners without distinc- tion, she, by the very nature of that general permission, af- fords a sufficient proof that she deems them innocent with respect to herself; which amounts to a declaration that fo- reigners have a right to them ( 127) : the innocence of such acts is manifested by the confession of the state ; and the refusal of an advantage that is manifestly innocent, is an in- jury ( 129). Besides, to attempt without any reason to lay one nation under a prohibition where an indiscriminate per- mission is enjoyed by all others, is an injurious distinction, since it can only proceed from hatred or contempt. If there be any particular and well-founded reason for the exception, the advantage resulting from the act in question can no longer be deemed an innocent one with respect to the excepted na- tion ; consequently no injury is done to them. The state may also, by way of punishment, except from the general permission a people who have given her just cause of com- plaint. g 138. A As to rights of this nature granted to one or more nations right grant- for particular reasons, they are conferred on them as favours, ed as a fa- e jther by treaty, or through gratitude for some particular ser- vice : those to whom the same rights are refused cannot con- sider themselves as offended. The nation does not esteem the advantage accruing from those acts to be an innocent one, since she does not indiscriminately allow them to all nations : and she may confer on whom she pleases any rights over her own property, without affording just grounds to anybody else, either for uttering a complaint, or forming pretensions to the same favour. g 139. The Humanity is not confined to the bare grant of a permission nation ought to foreign nations to make an innocent use of what belongs to be cour- ^ Q ug . ft moreover requires that we should even facilitate to them the means of deriving advantage from it, so far as we can do this without injury to ourselves. Thus, it becomes a well-regulated state to promote the general establishment of inns where travellers may procure lodging and food at a fair price, to watch over their safety, and to see that they be treated with equity and humanity. A polite nation should give the kindest reception to foreigners, receive them with politeness, and on every occasion show a disposition to oblige them. By these means every citizen, while he discharges his duty to mankind in general, will at the same time render OF USUCAPTION AND PRESCRIPTION AMONG NATIONS. 186 essential services to his country. Glory is the certain reward BOOK n. of virtue ; and the good-will which is gained by an amia- CHAP> *' ble character, is often productive of consequences highly im- portant to the state. No nation is entitled to greater praise in this respect than the French : foreigners nowhere meet a reception more agreeable, or better calculated to prevent their regretting the immense sums they annually spend at Paris. CHAP. XI. [ 187 ] OF USUCAPTION AND PRESCRIPTION AMONG NATIONS. (123) CHAP - " LET us conclude what relates to domain and property with an examination of a celebrated question on which the learned a^ much divided. It is asked whether usueaption and pre- scription can take place between independent nations and states. Usueaption is the acquisition of domain founded on a long g 140. De- possession, uninterrupted and undisputed that is to say, fiction of an acquisition solely proved by this possession. Wolf defines it, an acquisition of domain founded on a presumed desertion. His definition explains the manner in which a long and peace- able possession may serve to establish the acquisition of do- main. Modestinus, Digest, lib. 3, de Usurp, et Usucap., says, in conformity to the principles of the Roman law, that usu- eaption is the acquisition of domain by possession continued during a certain period prescribed by law. These three defi- nitions are by no means incompatible with each other ; and it is easy to reconcile them by setting aside what relates to the civil law in the last of the three. In the first of them, we have endeavoured clearly to express the idea commonly affixed to the term usueaption. Prescription is the exclusion of all pretensions to a right an exclusion founded on the length of time during which that right has been neglected : or, according to Wolf's definition, it is the loss of an inherent right by virtue of a presumed consent. This definition, too, is just; that is, it explains how a right may be forfeited by long neglect ; and it agrees with the nominal definition we give of the term, prescription, in which we confine ourselves to the meaning usually annexed to the word. As to the rest, the term usueaption is but lit- tle used in French ; and the word prescription implies, in that (123) We have seen that twenty years' creates a right. See ante, 125 to 127 ; undisturbed possession or enjoyment of and see Jlenest v. Pipon, Knapp's Rep. an easement or profit amongst nations, 60 to 73 ; where see the law of nations as well as amongst private individuals, fully examined. C. 36 Y 2 281 187 OP USUCAPTION AND PRESCRIPTION AMONG NATIONS. BOOK ii. language, every thing expressed by the Latin terms umcapio CHAP, xi. an( j p rsescr iptj ; wherefore we shall make use of the word prescription wherever we have not particular reasons for em- ploying the other. 141. Usu- Now, to decide the question we have proposed, we must caption and fi rs t see whether usucaption and prescription are derived from prescription t j^ j aw O f na t ure . Many illustrious authors have asserted tbTiaw of an d proved them to he so.* .f hough in this treatise we fre- nature. quently suppose the reader acquainted with the law of nature, it is proper in this place to establish the decision, since the affair is disputed. Nature has not herself established a private property over any of her gifts, and particularly over land; she only ap- proves its establishment, for the advantage of the human [ 188 ] race. On this ground, then, it would be absurd to suppose, that, after the introduction of domain and property, the law of nature can secure to a proprietor any right capable of in- troducing disorder into human society. Such would be the right of entirely neglecting a thing that belongs to him, of leaving it during a long space of time under all the appear- ances of a thing utterly abandoned or not belonging to him, and of coming at length to wrest it from a bona fide possessor, who has perhaps dearly purchased his title to it, who has received it as an inheritance from his progenitors, or as a por- tion with his wife, and who might have made other acquisi- tions, had he been able to discover that the one in question was neither solid nor lawful. Far from giving such a right, the law of nature lays an injunction on the proprietor to take care of his property, and imposes on him an obligation to make known his rights, that others may not be led into error : it is on these conditions alone that she approves of the pro- perty vested in him, and secures him in the possession. If he has neglected it for such a length of time that he cannot now be admitted to reclaim it without endangering the rights of others, the law of nature will no longer allow him to re- vive and assert his claims. We must not therefore conceive the right of private property to be a right of so extensive and imprescriptible a nature, that the proprietor may, at the risk of every inconvenience thence resulting to human society, absolutely neglect it for a length of time, and afterwards re- claim it, according to his caprice. With what other view than that of the peace, the safety, and the advantage of human society, does the law of nature ordain that all men should respect the right of private property in him who makes use of it ? For the same reason, therefore, the same law requires that every proprietor who for a long time and without any just reason neglects his right, should be presumed to have * See Grotius de Jure Belli et Pacis, Gent. lib. iv. cap. xii. and especially lib. ii. cap. iv. Puffendorf, Jus Nat. et Wolfius, Jus Nat. part iii. cap. vii. 282 OF USUCAPTION AND PRESCRIPTION AMONG NAilONS. 188 entirely renounced and abandoned it. This is what forms the BOOK " absolute presumption (juris et de jure) of its abandonment, a presumption, upon which another person is legally entitled to appropriate to himself the thing so abandoned. The ab- solute presumption does not here signify a conjecture of the secret intentions of the proprietor, but a maxim which the law of nature ordains should be considered as true and inva- riable, and this with a view of maintaining peace and order among men. Such presumption therefore confirms a title as firm and just as that of property itself, and established and supported by the same reasons. The bona fide possessor, resting his title on a presumption of this kind, has, then, a right which is approved by the law of nature ; and that law, which requires that the rights of each individual should be stable and certain, does not allow any man to disturb him in his possession. The right of usucaption properly signifies that the bona fide possessor is not obliged to suffer his right of property to be disputed after a long-continued and peaceable possession on his part : he proves that right by the very circumstance of possession, and sets up the plea of prescription in bar to [ 189 ] the claims of the pretended proprietor. Nothing can be more equitable than this rule. If the claimant were permitted to prove his property, he might happen to bring proofs very convincing indeed in appearance, but, in fact, deriving all their force only from the loss or destruction of some docu- ment or deed which would have proved how he had either lost or transferred his right. Would it be reasonable that he should be allowed to call in question the rights of the pos- sessor, when by his own fault he has suffered matters to pro- ceed to such a state that there would be danger of mistaking the truth ? If it be necessary that one of the two should be exposed to lose his property, it is just it should be the party who is in fault. It is true, that, if the bona fide possessor should discover, with perfect certainty, that the claimant is the real proprie- tor, and has never abandoned his right, he is bound in con- science, and by the internal principles of justice, to make restitution of whatever accession of wealth he has derived from the property of the claimant. But this estimation is not easily made ; and it depends on circumstances. As prescription cannot be grounded on any but an abso- ? I 42 - Whai lute or lawful presumption, it has no foundation, if the pro- f ound |jJ^J prietor has not really neglected his right. This condition fo/JJ^Jy implies three particulars : 1, that the proprietor cannot allege prescription an invincible ignorance, either on his own part, or on that of the persons from whom he derives his right ; 2, that he can- not justify his silence by lawful and substantial reasons ; 3, that he has neglected his right, or kept silence during a con- siderable number of years : for, the negligence of a few years, 283 189 OF USUCAPTION AND PRESCRIPTION AMONG NATIONS. BOOK IL being incapable of producing confusion and rendering doubt- CHAP. xi. u | k e res p ec ti ve rights of the parties, is not sufficient to found or authorize a presumption of relinquishment. It is impossible to determine by the law of nature the number of years required to found a prescription : this depends on the nature of the property disputed, and the circumstances of the case. 143. im- What we have remarked in the preceding section, relates TeTcriUion to ordinary prescription. There is another called immemo- n ' rial, because it is founded on immemorial possession, that is, on a possession, the origin of which is unknown, or so deeply involved in obscurity, as to allow no possibility of prov- ing whether the possessor has really derived his right from the original proprietor, or received the possession from another. This immemorial prescription secures the possessor's right, beyond the power of recovery : for, it affords a legal pre- sumption that he is the proprietor, as long as the adverse party fails to adduce substantial reasons in support of his claim : and, indeed, whence could these reasons be derived, since the origin of the possession is lost in the obscurity of time ? It ought even to secure the possessor against every pretension contrary to his right. What would be the case were it per- mitted to call in question a right acknowledged time immemo- rial, when the means of proving it were destroyed by time ? Immemorial possession, therefore, is an irrefragable title, and [ 190 ] immemorial prescription admits of no exception : both are founded on a presumption which the law of nature directs us to receive as an incontestable truth. 2 144. In cases of ordinary prescription, the same argument can- Claimant ai- not be used against a claimant who alleges just reasons for leging rea- n i s silence, as, the impossibility of speaking, or a well-founded Sence* *"* ^ ear ' ^ C "> ^ ecause t ^ iere * s tnen no longer any room for a pre- sumption that he has abandoned his right. It is not his fault if people have thought themselves authorized to form such a presumption ; nor ought he to suffer in consequence : he can- not therefore be debarved the liberty of clearly proving his property. This method of defence in bar of prescription has been often employed against princes whose formidable power had long silenced the feeble victims of their usurpations. g 145. Pro- It is also very evident that we cannot plead prescription prietor suf- j n opposition to a proprietor who, being for the present un- showto a ^ e to prosecute his right, confines himself to a notification, thaUwMioes by any token whatever, sufficient to show that it is not his not mean to intention to abandon it. Protests answer this purpose. With abandon his sovereigns it is usual to retain the title and arms of a sove- reignty or a province, as an evidence that they do not relin- quish their claims to it. i 146. Pre- Every proprietor who expressly commits, or omits, certain ecription acts, which he cannot commit or omit without renouncing his founded on r ight, sufficiently indicates by such commission or omission 284 OF USUCAPTION AND PRESCRIPTION AMONG NATIONS. 190 that it is not his intention to preserve it, unless, by an express BOOK n. reservation, he declare the contrary. We are undoubtedly CttAP< XI ' authorized to consider as true what he sufficiently manifests the actions on occasions where he ought to declare the truth : conse- rie " quently, we may lawfully presume that he abandons his right ; and, if he would afterwards resume it, we can plead prescrip- tion in bar to his claim. After having shown that usucaption and prescription are 147. Usu- founded in the law of nature, it is easy to prove that they caption and are equally a part of the law of nations, and ought to take prescription place between different states. For, the law of nations is but bttweeiTna- the law of nature applied to nations in a manner suitable to tions. the parties concerned (Prelim. 6). And so far is the nature of the parties from affording them an exemption in the case, that usucaption and prescription are much more necessary between sovereign states than between individuals. Their quarrels are of much greater consequence ; their disputes are usually terminated only by bloody wars ; and consequently the peace and happiness of mankind much more powerfully require that possession on the part of sovereigns should not be easily disturbed, and that, if it has for a considerable length of time continued uncontested, it should be deemed just and indisputable. Were we allowed to recur to antiquity on every occasion, there are few sovereigns who could enjoy their rights in security, and there would be no peace to be hoped for on earth. It must however be confessed, that, between nations, the 148. More rights of usucaption and prescription are often more difficult difficult be - in their application, so far as they are founded on a presump- t ^*g ll t " ar ~ tion drawn from long silence. Nobody is ignorant how dan- f oun d them gerous it commonly is for a weak state even to hint a claim on a pre'- to the possessions of a powerful monarch. In such a case, B * ni $ a *$ therefore, it is not easy to deduce from long silence a legal des presumption of abandonment. To this we may add, that, as [ 191 ] the ruler of the society has usually no power to alienate what belongs to the state, his silence, even though sufficient to afford a presumption of abandonment on his own part, can- not impair the national right or that of his successors. The question then will be, whether the nation has neglected to supply the omission caused by the silence of her ruler, or has participated in it by a tacit approbation. But there are other principles that establish the use and 1 149. Other force of prescription between nations. The tranquillity of principles the people, the safety of states, the happiness of the human th r f sc e r f? rc< race, do not allow that the possessions, empire, and other ticn?" 1 * rights of nations should remain uncertain, subject to dispute, and ever ready to occasion bloody wars. Between nations, therefore, it becomes necessary to admit prescription founded on length of time as a valid and incontestable title. If any nation has kept silence through fear, and as it were through 285 191 OF USUCAPTION AND PRESCRIPTION AMONG NATIONw. BOOK n. necessity, the loss of her right is a misfortune which she ought , CHAP - XI " patiently to bear, since she could not avoid it: and why should she not submit to this as well as to have her towns and pro- vinces taken from her by an unjust conqueror, and to be forced to cede them to him by treaty ? It is, however, only in cases of long-continued, undisputed, and uninterrupted possession, that prescription is established on these grounds, because it is necessary that affairs should some time or other be brought to a conclusion, and settled on a firm and solid foundation. But the case is different with a possession of only a few years' continuance, during which the party whose rights are invaded may from prudential reasons find it expe- dient to keep silence, without at the same time affording room to accuse him of suffering things to become uncertain, and of renewing quarrels without end. As to immemorial prescription, what we have said respect- ing it ( 143) is sufficient to convince every one that it ought necessarily to take place between nations. g 150. Ef- Usucaption and prescription being so necessary to the tran- fects of the quillity and happiness of human society, it is justly presumed voluntary ^j. a }} na tions have consented to admit the lawful and rea- t ^ ^ ig sonable use of them, with a view to the general advantage, subject. and even to the private interest of each individual nation. Prescription of many years' standing, as well as usucap- tion, is, then, established by the voluntary law of nations (Prelim. 21). Nay, more, as by virtue of that law nations are, in all doubtful cases, supposed to stand on a footing of equal right in treating with each other (ibid.), prescription, when founded on long undisputed possession, ought to have its full effect between nations, without admitting any allegation of the pos- [ 192 ] session being unjust, unless the evidence to prove it be very clear and convincing indeed. For, without such evidence, every nation is to be considered as a bona fide possessor. Such is the right that a sovereign state ought to allow to other states ; but to herself she should only allow the use of the internal and necessary right (Prelim. 28). It is the bona fide possessor alone whose prescription will stand the test of conscience. 1 151. Law Since prescription is subject to so many difficulties, it would of treaties ^ e ver y p r0 p er that adjoining nations should by treaty adopt in this" 8 m some ru l e on th* 8 subject, particularly with respect to the matter. number of years required to found a lawful prescription, since this latter point cannot in general be determined by the law of nature alone. If, in default of treaties, custom has de- termined any thing in this matter, the nations between whom this custom is in force, ought to conform to it (Prelim. 26). 286 OF TKEATIES OF ALLIANCE, ETC. 192 BOOK n. CHAP. XII. CHAP. XII. OF TREATIES OF ALLIANCE, AND OTHER PUBLIC TREA- TIES. (124) THE subject of treaties is undoubtedly one of the most im- 152. Na- portant that the mutual relations and affairs of nations can ture of teea - present us with. Having but too much reason to be con-* 168 *^ 24 vinced of the little dependence that is to be placed on the natural obligations of bodies politic, and on the reciprocal duties imposed upon them by humanity, the most prudent nations endeavour to procure by treaties those succours and advantages which the law of nature would insure to them, if it were not rendered ineffectual by the pernicious counsels of a false policy. A treaty, in Latin fcedus, is a compact made with a view to the public welfare by the superior power, either for per- petuity, or for a considerable time. The compacts which have temporary matters for their ob- us. p ac - ject are called agreements, conventions, and pactions. They tions, agree- are accomplished by one single act, and not by repeated acts. ments > or These compacts are perfected in their execution once for all : treaties receive a successive execution whose duration equals that of the treaty. Public treaties can only be made by the superior powers, ? 154. By by sovereigns, who contract in the name of the state. Thus, ^ hom trea - conventions, made between sovereigns respecting their own tiesare private affairs, and those between a sovereign and a private person, are not public treaties. The sovereign who possesses the full and absolute authority has, doubtless, a right to treat in the name of the state he represents ; and his engagements are binding on the whole nation. But all rulers of states have not a power to make public treaties by their own authority alone : some are obliged to take the advice of a senate, or of the representatives of the [ 193 ] nation. It is from the fundamental laws of each state that we must learn where resides the authority that is capable of contracting with validity in the name of the state. Notwithstanding our assertion above, that public treaties are made only by the superior powers, treaties of that nature may nevertheless be entered into by princes or communities, who have a right to contract them, either by the concession of the sovereign, or by the fundamental laws of the state, by particular reservations, or by custom. Thus, the princes and (124) See in general, as to the law 47; and, as to commercial treaties in of nations respecting treaties, post, particular, 53, and 615 to 630 ; and see Book IV. Chap. II. Ac., page 432 to each separate treaty, 2 Chitty's Com. 452, 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, 38 to Law, p. 183. 287 193 OF TREATIES OF ALLIANCE. IAP. XII. BOOK n. free cities of Germany, though dependent on the emperor "* . and the empire, have the right of forming alliances with foreign powers. The constitutions of the empire give them, in this as in many other respects, the rights of sovereignty. Some cities of Switzerland, though subject to a prince, have made alliances with the cantons : the permission or toleration of the sovereign has given birth to such treaties, and long custom has established the right to contract them. ? 155. Who- As a state that has put herself under the protection of an- ther a state Q^er, has not on tha^. account forfeited her character of sove- tection P may rei g nt j (Book I. 192), she may make treaties and contract make trea- alliances, unless she has, in the treaty of protection, expressly ties. renounced that right. But she continues for ever after bound by this treaty of protection, so that she cannot enter into any engagements contrary to it, that is to say, engagements which violate the express conditions of the protection, or that are in their own nature repugnant to every treaty of protec- tion. Thus, the protected state cannot promise assistance to the enemies of her protector, nor grant them a passage, g 156. Trea- Sovereigns treat with each other through the medium of ties con- agents or proxies who are invested with sufficient powers for the purpose, and are commonly called plenipotentiaries. To their office we may apply all the rules of natural law which tiaries. respect things done by commission. The rights of the proxy are determined by the instructions that are given him : he must not deviate from them ; but every promise which he makes in the terms of his commission, and within the extent of his powers, is binding on his constituent. At present, in order to avoid all danger and difficulty, princes reserve to themselves the power of ratifying what has been concluded upon in their name by their ministers. The plenipotentiary commission is but a procuration cum lilera. If this commission were to have its full effect, they could not be too circumspect in giving it. But, as princes cannot other- wise than by force of arms be compelled to fulfil their engage- ments, it is customary to place no dependence on their treaties, till they have agreed to and ratified them. Thus, as every agreement made by the minister remains invalid till sanctioned by the prince's ratification, there is less danger in vesting him with unlimited powers. But, before a prince can honourably [ 194 ] refuse to ratify a compact made in virtue of such plenipoten- tiary commission, he should be able to allege strong and sub- stantial reasons, and, in particular, to prove that his minister has deviated from his instructions. g 157. Va- A treaty is valid if there be no defect in the manner in lidity of which it has been concluded : and for this purpose nothing treaties. m ore can be required than a sufficient power in the contract- ing parties, and their mutual consent sufficiently declared. J 158. in- An injury cannot, then, render a treaty invalid. He who jury does enters into engagements ought carefully to weigh every thing 288 AND OTHER PUBLIC TREATIES. 194 before he concludes them ; he may do what he pleases with BOOK IT. his own property, forego his rights, and renounce his advan- CHAP, xir. tages, as he thinks proper ; the acceptor is not obliged to in- not render quire into his motives, and to estimate their due weight. If we them void, might recede from a treaty because we found ourselves injured by it, there would be no stability in the contracts of nations. Civil laws may set bounds to injury, and determine what de- gree of it shall be capable of invalidating a contract. But sove- reigns are subject to no superior judge. How shall they be able to prove the injury to each other's satisfaction ? Who shall determine the degree of it sufficient to invalidate a treaty ? The peace and happiness of nations manifestly require that their treaties should not depend on so vague and dangerous a plea of invalidity. A sovereign nevertheless is in conscience bound to pay a 159. Duty regard to equity, and to observe it as much as possible in all of . natlonsm his treaties. And, if it happens that a treaty which he has * l res P ect- concluded with upright intentions, and without perceiving any unfairness in it, should eventually prove disadvantageous to an ally, nothing can be more honourable, more praiseworthy, more conformable to the reciprocal duties of nations, than to relax the terms of such treaty as far as he can do it consist- ently with his duty to himself, and without exposing himself to danger, or incurring a considerable loss. Though a simple injury, or some disadvantage in a treaty, 160. Nul- be not sufficient to invalidate it, the case is not the same with ^x of trea - those inconveniences that would lead to the ruin of the nation, j^f ^mf* Since, in the formation of every treaty, the contracting parties c i ous to the must be vested with sufficient powers for the purpose, a treaty state, pernicious to the state is null, and not at all obligatory, as no [ 195 ] conductor of a nation has the power to enter into engage- ments to do such things as are capable of destroying the state, for whose safety the government is intrusted to him. The nation itself, being necessarily obliged to perform every thing required for its preservation and safety (Book I. 16, &c.), cannot enter into engagements contrary to its indispensable obligations. In the year 1506, the states-general of the kingdom of France, assembled at Tours, engaged Louis XII. to break the treaty he had concluded with the emperor Maxi- milian and the archduke Philip, his son, because that treaty was pernicious to the kingdom. They also decided that neither the treaty, nor the oath that had accompanied it, could be binding on the king, who had no right to alienate the property of the crown.* We have treated of this latter source of invalidity in the twenty-first chapter of Book I. For the same reason the want of sufficient powers a 161. Nul- treaty concluded for an unjust or dishonest purpose is abso-^y oftrea - lutely null and void, nobody having a right to engage to do * See the French historians. 37 Z 289 195 OP TREATIES OF ALLIANCE, BOOK n. things contrary to the law of nature. Thus, an offensive CHAP, xii. alliance, made for the purpose of plundering a nation from or dishonest whom no injury has been received, may or rather ought to be purpose. broken. 162. Whe- It is asked, whether it be allowable to contract an alliance ther an alh- w jth a nation that does not profess the true religion, and contracted C wne ther treaties made with the enemies of the faith are valid, with those Grotius has treated this subject at large :* and the discussion who do not might have been necessary at a time when party -rage still profess the obscured those principles which it had long caused to be for- gion* 61 ' g ott en ; but we may venture to believe that it would be super- fluous in the present age. The law of nature alone regulates the treaties of nations : the difference of religion is a thing absolutely foreign to them. Different people treat with each other in quality of men, and not under the character of Chris- tians, or of Mohammedans. Their common safety requires that they should be capable of treating with each other, and of treating with security. Any religion that should in this case clash with the law of nature, would, on the very face of it, wear the stamp of reprobation, and could not pretend to derive its origin from the great Author of nature, who is ever steady, ever consistent with himself. But, if the maxims of a religion tend to establish it by violence, and to oppress all those who will not embrace it, the law of nature forbids us to favour that religion, or to contract any unnecessary alliances with [ 196 ] its inhuman followers, and the common safety of mankind invites them rather to enter into an alliance against such a people, to repress such outrageous fanatics, who disturb the public repose and threaten all nations. 163. Obli- Jt i s a settled point in natural law, that he who has made observirf a P rom ^ se * an J one ^ as conferred upon him a real right to require the thing promised, and, consequently, that the breach of a perfect promise is a violation of another person's right, and as evidently an act of injustice as it would be to rob a man of his property. The tranquillity, the happiness, the security of the human race, wholly depend on justice, on the obligation of paying a regard to the rights of others. The respect which others pay to our rights of domain and property constitutes the security of our actual possessions ; the faith of promises is our security for things that cannot be delivered or executed upon the spot. There would no longer be any security, no longer any commerce between mankind, if they did not think themselves obliged to keep faith with each other, and to perform their promises. This obligation is, then, as necessary as it is natural and indubita- ble, between nations that live together in a state of nature, and acknowledge no superior upon earth, to maintain order and peace in their society. Nations, therefore, and their con- * De Jure Belli et Pads. lib. ii. cap. xv. 8, et seq. 290 AND OTHER PUBLIC TREATIES. 196 ductors, ought inviolably to observe their promises and their BOOK n. treaties. This great truth, though too often neglected in CHAP - XIt - practice, is generally acknowledged by all nations :* the re- proach of perfidy is esteemed by sovereigns a most atrocious affront ; yet he who does not observe a treaty is certainly perfidious, since he violates his faith. On the contrary, no- thing adds so great a glory to a prince, and to the nation he governs, as the reputation of an inviolable fidelity in the per- formance of promises. By such honourable conduct, as much or even more than by her valour, the Swiss nation has ren- dered herself respectable throughout Europe, and is de- servedly courted by the greatest monarchs who intrust their personal safety to a body-guard of her citizens. The parlia- ment of England has more than once thanked the king for his fidelity and zeal in succouring the allies of his crown. This national magnanimity is the source of immortal glory ; it presents a firm basis on which nations may build their con- fidence ; and thus it becomes an unfailing source of power and splendour. As the engagements of a treaty impose on the one hand a 154. The perfect obligation, they produce on the other a perfect right, violation of The breach of a treaty is therefore a violation of the perfect a treatv . is right of the party with whom we have contracted ; and this ^ s ^ e is an act of injustice against him. A sovereign already bound by a treaty cannot enter into 155. Trea- others contrary to the first. The things respecting which ties cannot he has entered into engagements are no longer at his disposal. be made If it happens that a posterior treaty be found, in any parti- ^T^rea cular point, to clash with one of more ancient date, the new dy existing treaty is null and void with respect to that point, inasmuch as it tends to dispose of a thing that is no longer in the power of him who appears to dispose of it. (We are here to be under- stood as speaking of treaties made with different powers.) If the prior treaty is kept secret, it would be an act of con- summate perfidy to conclude a contrary one, which may be rendered void whenever occasion serves. Nay, even to enter into engagements, which, from the eventual turn of affairs, may chance at a future day to militate against the secret treaty, and from that very circumstance to prove ineffectual and nugatory, is by no means justifiable, unless we have the ability to make ample compensation to our new ally : other- wise it would be practising a deception on him, to promise him a thing without informing him that cases may possibly occur which will not allow us to substantiate our promise. The ally thus deceived is undoubtedly at liberty to renounce the treaty : but, if he chooses rather to adhere to it, it will hold good with [ 197 ] respect to all the articles that do not clash with the prior treaty. Mohammed warmly recommend- treaties. Ockley's History of the Sa- ed to his disciples the observance of racens, vol. i. 291 197 OF TREATIES OF ALLIANCE, BOOK ii. There is nothing to prevent a sovereign from entering into CHAP, xn. engagements of the same nature with two or more nations, if 166. How he be able to fulfil those several engagements to his different treaties may allies at the same time. For instance, a commercial treaty beconcluded w j^h one na tion does not deprive us of the liberty of afterwards nations with contracting similar engagements with other states, unless we the same have, in the former treaty, bojmd ourselves by a promise not view. to grant the same advantages to any other nation. We may in the same manner promise to assist two different allies with troops, if we are able to furnish them, or if there is no pro- bability that both will have occasion for them at the same time. 167. The If nevertheless the contrary happens, the more ancient more an- a ]iy j s entitled to a preference : for, the engagement was pure entitled to a a absolute with respect to him ; whereas we could not con- preference, tract with the more recent ally, without a reservation of the rights of the former. Such reservation is founded in justice, and is tacitly understood, even if not expressly made. 168. We The justice of the cause is another ground of preference owe no as- De t ween two allies. We ought even to refuse assistance to an unjust * ne one wnose cause is unjust, whether he be at war with one war. of our allies, or with another state : to assist him on such occasion, would in the event be the same thing as if we had contracted an alliance for an unjust purpose ; which we are not allowed to do ( 161). No one can be validly engaged to support injustice. 169. Ge- Grotius divides treaties into two general classes, first, n.eral ^ 1V1 " those which turn merely on things to which the parties were ties! Ea ~ already bound by the law of nature, secondly, those by which they enter into further engagements.* By the former 1. Those we acquire a perfect right to things to which we before had that f elate only an imperfect right, so that we may thenceforward de- to things al- J , r , i i_ / -i j i ready due mand as our due what before we could only request as an by the law office of humanity. Such treaties became very necessary be- of nature, tween the nations of antiquity, who, as we have already ob- served, did not think themselves bound to any duty towards people who were not in the number of their allies. They are useful even between the most polished nations, in ord the better to secure the succours they may expect, to deter- mine the measure and degree of those succours, and to show on what they have to depend, to regulate what cannot in general be determined by the law of nature, and thus to obviate all difficulties, by providing against the various inter- pretations of that law. Finally, as no nation possesses inex- haustible means of assistance, it is prudent to secure to our- selves a peculiar right to that assistance which cannot be granted to all the world. To this first class belong all simple treaties of peace and friendship, when the engagements which we thereby contract * De Jure Belli et Pacis, lib. ii. cap. xv. 5 292 b- ds I AND OTHEE PUBLIC TREATIES. 198 make no addition to those duties that men owe to each other BOOK n. as brethren and as members of the human society : such are CHAP, xn. those treaties that permit commerce, passage, &c. If the assistance and offices that are due by virtue of such 170. Col- a treaty should on any occasion prove incompatible with the lision of duties a nation owes to herself, or with what the sovereign t ! iese . trea " owes to his own nation, the case is tacitly and necessarily S 1 ^ 11 " 3 excepted in the treaty. For, neither the nation nor the owe to our- sovereign could enter into an engagement to neglect the care selves. of their own safety, or the safety of the state, in order to contribute to that of their ally. If the sovereign, in order to preserve his own nation, has occasion for the things he has promised in the treaty, if, for instance, he has engaged to furnish corn, and in a time of dearth he has scarcely suf- ficient for the subsistence of his subjects, he ought without hesitation to give a preference to his own nation ; for, it is only so far as he has it in his power to give assistance to a foreign nation, that he naturally owes such assistance ; and it was upon that footing alone that he could promise it in a treaty. Now, it is not in his power to deprive his own nation of the means of subsistence in order to assist another nation at their expense. Necessity here forms an exception, and he does not violate the treaty, because he cannot fulfil it. The treaties by which we simply agree not to do any evilm.Trea- to an ally, to abstain, with respect to him, from all harm, ties in which offence, and injury, are not necessary, and produce no new we barcl y ., '. i i i i 1 J / promise to right, since every individual already possesses a perfect natu- $ no ^ ral right to be exempt from harm, injury, and real offence, jury. Such treaties, however, become very useful, and accidentally necessary, among those barbarous nations who think they have a right to act as they please towards foreigners. They are not wholly useless with nations less savage, who, without so far divesting themselves of humanity, entertain a much less powerful sense of a natural obligation, than of one which they have themselves contracted by solemn engagements : and would to God that this manner of thinking were entirely confined to barbarians ! We see too frequent effects of it among those who boast of a perfection much superior to the law of nature. But the imputation of perfidy is prejudicial to the rulers of nations, and thus becomes formidable even to those who are little solicitous to merit the appellation of vir- tuous men, and who feel no scruple in silencing the re- proaches of conscience. Treaties by which we contract engagements that were not m. Trea- imposed on us by the law of nature, are either equal or un- ties ? on ' . t Equal treaties are those in which the contracting parties are not na- promise the same things, or things that are equivalent, or, turally due. finally, things that are equitably proportioned, so that the Equal condition of the parties is equal. Such is, for example, a reaties ' Z2 293 198 OF TREATIES OF ALLIANCE, BOOK ii. defensive alliance, in which the parties reciprocally stipulate CHAP, xii. for the same succours. Such is an offensive alliance, in 199 ] which it is agreed that each of the allies shall furnish the same number of vessels, the same number of troops, of cavalry and infantry, or an equivalent in vessels, in troops, in artillery, or in money. Such is also a league in which the quota of each of the allies is regulated in proportion to the interest he takes or may have in the design of the league. Thus, the emperor and the king of England, in order to in- duce the states-general of the United Provinces to accede to the treaty of Vienna of the 16th of March, 1731, consented that the republic should only promise to her allies the assist- ance of four thousand foot and a thousand horse, though they engaged, in case of an attack upon the republic, to furnish her, each, with eight thousand foot and four thousand horse. "VVe are also to place in the class of equal treaties those which stipulate that the allies shall consider themselves as embarked in a common cause, and shall act with all their strength. Notwithstanding a real inequality in their strength, they are nevertheless willing in this instance to consider it as equal. Equal treaties may be subdivided into as many species as there are of different transactions between sovereigns. Thus, they treat of the conditions of commerce, of their mutual defence, of associations in war, of reciprocally granting each other a passage, or refusing it to the enemies of their ally ; they engage not to build fortresses in certain places, &c. But it. would be needless to enter into these particulars : generals are sufficient, and are easily applied to particular cases. 173. Ob- Nations being no less obliged than individuals to pay a ligationof regard to equity, they ought, as much as possible, to pre- serve ec l ua lity in their treaties. When, therefore, the parties are a ^le reciprocally to afford each other equal advantages, the law of nature requires that their treaties should be equal, unless there exist some particular reason for deviating from that equality, such, for instance, as gratitude for a former benefit, the hope of gaining the inviolable attachment of a nation, some private motive, which renders one of the con- tracting parties particularly anxious to have the treaty con- cluded, &c. Nay, viewing the transaction in its proper point of light, the consideration of that particular reason restores to the treaty that equality which seems to be destroyed by the difference of the things promised. I see those pretended great politicians smile, who employ all their subtilty in circumventing those with whom they treat, and in so managing the conditions of the treaty, that all the advantages shall accrue to their masters. Far from blushing at a conduct so contrary to equity, to rectitude and natural honesty, they glory in it, and think themselves entitled to the appellation of able negotiators. How long shall we continue to see men in public characters take a pride in practices that 294 AND OTHER PUBLIC TREATIES. 199 would disgrace a private individual ? The private man, if he BOOK n. is void of conscience, laughs also at the rules of morality and CHAP, xu. justice ; but he laughs in secret : it would be dangerous and prejudicial to him to make a public mockery of them. Men [ 200 ] in power more openly sacrifice honour and honesty to present advantage : but, fortunately for mankind, it often happens that such seeming advantage proves fatal to them ; and even between sovereigns, candour and rectitude are found to be the safest policy. All the subtilties, all the tergiversations of a famous minister, on the occasion of a treaty in which Spain was deeply interested, turned at length to his own confusion, and to the detriment of his master; while Eng- land, by her good faith and generosity to her allies, gained immense credit, and rose to the highest pitch of influence and respectability. When people speak of equal treaties, they have commonly 174. Dtf. in their minds a double idea of equality, viz. equality in the ference be- engagements, and equality in the dignity of the contracting twee n e( l ua l parties. It becomes therefore necessary to remove all ambi- g 16 ^^!) guity ; and for that purpose, we may make a distinction be- a nces. tween equal treaties and equal alliances. Equal treaties are those in which there is an equality in the promises made, as we have above explained ( 172) ; and equal alliances, those in which equal treats with equal, making no difference in the dignity of the contracting parties, or, at least, admitting no too glaring superiority, but merely a pre-eminence of honour and rank. Thus kings treat with the emperor on a footing of equality, though they do not hesitate to allow him precedency; thus great republics treat with kings on the same footing, notwithstanding the pre-eminence which the former now-a- days yield to the latter. Thus all true sovereigns ought to treat with the most powerful monarch, since they are as really sovereigns, and as independent as himself. (See 37 of this Book.) Unequal treaties are those in which the allies do not reci-i 7 5. u n procally promise to each other the same things, or things equal trea- equivalent ; and an alliance is unequal when it makes a differ- ties and )"* ence in the dignity of the contracting parties. It is true, that JJ^j dh ~ most commonly an unequal treaty will be at the same time an an ' unequal alliance ; as great potentates are seldom accustomed to give or to promise more than is given or promised to them, unless such concessions be fully compensated in the article of honour and glory ; and, on the other hand, a weak state does not submit to burdensome conditions without being obliged also to acknowledge the superiority of her ally. Those unequal treaties that are at the same time unequal alliances, are divided into two classes, the first consisting of those where the inequality prevails on the side of the more con- siderable power, the second comprehending treaties where the inequality is on the side of the inferior power. 295 200 OF TKEATIES OF ALLIANCE, BOOK ii. Treaties of the former class, without attributing to the more CUAV. xu. powerful of the contracting parties any right over the weaker, simply allow him a superiority of honours and respect. We have treated of this in Book I. 5. Frequently a great mo- narch, wishing to engage a weaker state in his interest, offers ( 201 ] her advantageous conditions, promises her gratuitous suc- cours, or greater than he stimulates for himself: but at the same time he claims a superiority of dignity, and requires re- spect from his ally. It is this last particular which renders the alliance unequal : and to this circumstance we must atten- tively advert ; for, with alliances of this nature we are not to confound those in which the parties treat on a footing of equal- ity, though the more powerful of the allies, for particular reasons, gives more than he receives, promises his assistance gratis, without requiring gratuitous assistance in his turn, or promises more considerable succours, or even the assistance of all his forces : here the alliance is equal, but the treaty is unequal, unless indeed we may be allowed to say, that, as the party who makes the greater concessions has a greater interest in concluding the treaty, this consideration restores the equality. Thus, at a time when France found herself em- barrassed in a momentous war with the house of Austria, and the cardinal de Richelieu wished to humble that formi- dable power, he, like an able minister, concluded a treaty with Gustavus Adolphus, in which all the advantage appeared to be on the side of Sweden. From a bare consideration of the stipulations of that treaty, it would have been pronounced an unequal one ; but the advantages which France derived from it, amply compensated for that inequality. The alliance of France with the Swiss, if we regard the stipulations alone, is an unequal treaty ; but the valour of the Swiss troops has long since counterbalanced that inequality; and the differ- ence in the interests and wants of the parties serves still further to preserve the equilibrium. France, often involved in bloody wars, has received essential services from the Swiss : the Helvetic body, void of ambition, and untainted with the spirit of conquest, may live in peace with the whole world ; they have nothing to fear, since they have feelingly convinced the ambitious, that the love of liberty gives the nation suffi- cient strength to defend her frontiers. This alliance may at certain times have appeared unequal : our forefathers* paid little attention to ceremony : but, in reality, and especially since the absolute independence of the Swiss is acknowledged by the empire itself, the alliance is certainly equal, although the Helvetic body do not hesitate to yield to the king of France all that pre-eminence which the established usage of modern Europe attributes to crowned heads, and especially to great monarchs. * The author was a native of Switzerland. AND OTHER PUBLIC TREATIES. 201 Treaties in which the inequality prevails on the side of the BOOK H. inferior power that is to say, those which impose on the CHAP - *" weaker party more extensive obligations or greater burdens, or bind him down to oppressive or disagreeable conditions, these unequal treaties, I say, are always at the same time unequal alliances; for, the weaker party never submits to burdensome conditions, without being obliged also to acknow- ledge the superiority of his ally. These conditions are com- monly imposed by the conqueror, or dictated by necessity, r 202 ] which obliges a weak state to seek the protection or assist- ance of another more powerful ; and by this very step, the weaker state acknowledges her own inferiority. Besides, this forced inequality in a treaty of alliance is a disparage- ment to her, and lowers her dignity, at the same time that it exalts that of her more powerful ally. Sometimes also, the weaker state not being in a condition to promise the same suc- cours as the more powerful one, it becomes necessary that she should compensate for her inability in this point, by engage- ments which degrade her below her ally, and often even sub- ject her, in various respects, to his will. Of this kind are all those treaties in which the weaker party alone engages not to make war without the consent of her more powerful ally, to have the same friends and the same enemies with him, to support and respect his dignity, to have no fortresses in certain places, not to trade or raise soldiers in certain free countries, to deliver up her vessels of war, and not to build others, as was the case of the Carthaginians when treating with their Roman conquerors, to keep up only a certain number of troops, &c. These unequal alliances are subdivided into two kinds ; they either impair the sovereignty, or they do not. We have slightly touched on this in Book I. Ch. I. and XVI. The sovereignty subsists entire and unimpaired when none of its constituent rights are transferred to the superior ally, or rendered, as to the exertion of them, dependent on his will. But the sovereignty is impaired when any of its rights are ceded to an ally, or even if the use of them be merely rendered dependent on the will of that ally. For example, the treaty does not impair the sovereignty, if the weaker state only promises not to attack a certain nation without the consent of her ally. By such an engagement she neither divests herself of her right, nor subjects the exertion of it to another's will ; she only consents to a restriction in favour of her ally : and thus she incurs no greater diminution of liberty than is incurred by promises of every kind. Such reservations are every day stipulated in alliances that are perfectly equal. But, if either of the contracting parties engages not to make war against any one whatsoever without the consent or permission of an ally who on his side does not make the same promise, the former contracts an unequal alii- 38 297 202 OF TREATIES OF ALLIANCE, BOOK ii. ance, with diminution of sovereignty ; for he deprives him- CHAP, xii. S elf O f one O f t^ mos t important branches of the sovereign power, or renders the exertion of it dependent on another's will. The Carthaginians having, in the treaty that termi- nated the second Punic war, promised not to make war on any state without the consent of the Roman people, were thenceforward, and for that reason, considered as dependent on the Romans. 176. How When a nation is forced to submit to the will of a superior ai1 u ' j ian ? e power, she may lawfully renounce her former treaties, if the nution'of" P ar ty w ^ n w ^ m s ^ e i g obliged to enter into an alliance re- sovereignty quires it of her. As she then loses a part of her sovereignty, may annul her ancient treaties fall to the ground together with the power preceding ^hat had concluded them. This is a necessity that cannot be ^OAO -| imputed to her as a crime : and since she would have a right J to place herself in a state of absolute subjection, and to re- nounce her own sovereign, if she found such measures neces- sary for her preservation, by a much stronger reason, she has a right, under the same necessity, to abandon her allies. But a generous people will exhaust every resource before they will submit to terms so severe and so humiliating. 177. We In general, as every nation ought to be jealous of her glory, ought to careful of maintaining her dignity, and preserving her inde- much as pendence, nothing short of the last extremity, or motives the possible most weighty and substantial, ought ever to induce a people making un- to contract an unequal alliance. This observation is particu- equal alh- i ar jy meant to apply to treaties where the inequality prevails on the side of the weaker ally, and still more particularly to those unequal alliances that degrade the sovereignty. Men of courage and spirit will accept such treaties from no other hands but those of imperious necessity. 178. Mu- Notwithstanding every argument which selfish policy may tual duties SU gg e st to the contrary, we must either pronounce sovereigns witlTrerect * ^ e aDS l ute ty emancipated from all subjection to the law to unequal of nature, or agree that it is not lawful for them, without alliances, just reasons, to compel weaker states to sacrifice their dig- nity, much less their liberty, by unequal alliances. Nations owe to each other the same assistance, the same respect, the same friendship, as individuals living in a state of nature. Far from seeking to humble a weaker neighbour, and to de- spoil her of her most valuable advantages, they will respect and maintain her dignity and her liberty, if they are inspired by virtue more than by pride if they are actuated by prin- ciples of honour more than by the meaner views of sordid interest nay, if they have but sufficient discernment to dis- tinguish their real interests. Nothing more firmly secures the power of a great monarch than his attention and respect to all other sovereigns. The more cautious he is to avoid offending his weaker brethren, the greater esteem he testifies for them, the more will they revere him in turn ; they feel AND OTHER PUBLIC TREATIES. 203 an affection for a power whose superiority over them is dis- BOOK u. played only by the conferring of favours : they cling to such CHAF - x* 1 - a monarch as their prop and support ; and he becomes the arbiter of nations. Had his demeanour been stamped with arrogance, he would have been the object of their jealousy and fear, and might perhaps have one day sunk under their united efforts. But, as the weaker party ought, in his necessity, to accept 179. In with gratitude the assistance of the more powerful, and not alliances to refuse him such honours and respect as are nattering to j^JJ'JJ 6 the person who receives them, without degrading him by " ^ ^/ whom they are rendered; so, on the other hand, nothing is side of the more conformable to the law of nature than a generous grant more P W - of assistance from the more powerful state, unaccompanied erfil1 party< by any demand of a return, or, at least, of an equivalent. And in this instance also, there exists an inseparable connec- [ 204 ] tion between interest and duty. Sound policy holds out a caution to a powerful nation not to suffer the lesser states in her neighbourhood to be oppressed. If she abandon them to the ambition of a conqueror, he will soon become formidable to herself. Accordingly, sovereigns, who are in general suf- ficiently attentive to their own interests, seldom fail to reduce this maxim to practice. Hence those alliances, sometimes against the house of Austria, sometimes against its rival, according as the power of the one or the other preponderates. Hence that balance of power, the object of perpetual nego- tiations and wars. When a weak and poor nation has occasion for assistance of another kind when she is afflicted by famine we have seen ( 5), that those nations who have provisions ought to supply her at a fair price. It were noble and generous to furnish them at an under price, or to make her a present of them, if she be incapable of paying their value. To oblige her to purchase them by an unequal alliance, and especially at the expense of her liberty to treat her as Joseph for- merly treated the Egyptians would be a cruelty almost as dreadful as suffering her to perish with famine. But there are cases where the inequality of treaties and iso. How alliances, dictated by some particular reasons, is not contrary inequality to equity, nor, consequently, to the law of nature. Such, in ^fjjjjj. general, are all those cases in which the duties that a nation ces may be owes to herself, or those which she owes to other nations, pre- conformable scribe to her a departure from the line of equality. If, for to the law instance, a weak state attempts, without necessity, to erect a of nature - fortress, which she is incapable of defending, in a place where it might become very dangerous to her neighbour if ever it should fall into the hands of a powerful enemy, that neigh- bour may oppose the construction of the fortress ; and, if he does not find it convenient to pay the lesser state a compen- sation for complying with his desire, he may force her com- 204 OF TREATIES OF ALLIANCE, BOOK n. pliance, by threatening to block up the roads and avenues of CHAP, xn. communication, to prohibit all intercourse between the two nations, to build fortresses, or to keep an army on the fron- tier, to consider that little state in a suspicious light, &c. He thus indeed imposes an unequal condition ; but his conduct is authorized by the care of his own safety. In the same man- ner he may oppose the forming of a highway, that would open to an enemy an entrance into his state. War might furnish us with a multitude of other examples. But rights of this nature are frequently abused ; and it requires no less mode- ration than prudence to avoid turning them into oppression. Sometimes those duties to which other nations have a claim, recommend and authorize inequality in a contrary sense, without affording any ground of imputation against a sovereign, of having neglected the duty which he owes to himself or to his people. Thus, gratitude the desire of showing his deep sense of a favour received may induce a generous sovereign to enter into an alliance with joy, and to [ 205 ] give in the treaty more than he receives. 181. Ine- It is also consistent with justice to impose the conditions quality im- o f an unequal treaty, or even an unequal alliance, by way of penalty, in order to punish an unjust aggressor, and ren- der him incapable of easily injuring us for the time to come. Such was the treaty to which the elder Scipio Africanus forced the Carthaginians to submit, after he had defeated Hannibal. The conqueror often dictates such terms : and his conduct in this instance is no violation of the laws of justice or equity, provided he do not transgress the bounds of moderation, after he has been crowned with success in a just and neces- sary war. 182. Other The different treaties of protection those by which a state kinds of renders itself tributary or feudatory to another form so which we man y different kinds of unequal alliances. But we shall not elsewhere Cn repeat here what we have said respecting them in Book I. Chap. I. and XVI. 183. Per- By another general division of treaties or alliances, they reaHreaties ai o i -if i the king- itself. Such treaty is therefore a real one. dom. Independently even of this express declaration, when a [ 207 ] treaty is made for the purpose of procuring to the state a certain advantage which is in its own nature permanent and unfailing, there is no reason to suppose that the prince by whom the treaty has been concluded, intended to limit it to the duration of his own life. Such a treaty ought therefore to be considered as a real one, unless there exist very power- ful evidence to prove that the party with whom it was made granted the advantage in question only out of regard to the prince then reigning, and as a personal favour : in which case the treaty terminates with the life of the prince, as the motive for the concession expires with him. But such a reservation is not to be presumed on slight grounds : for, it would seem, that, if the contracting parties had had it in contemplation, they should have expressed it in the treaty. 190. How In case of doubt, where there exists no circumstance by presump- which we can clearly prove either the personality or the tion ought rea jity of a treaty, it ought to be presumed a real treaty if it to be found- > a j. c r 1,1 A - t ? e j- ed in doubt- chiefly consists 01 favourable articles, if of odious ones, a ful cases, personal treaty. By favourable articles we mean those which tend to the mutual advantage of the contracting powers, and which equally favour both parties ; by odious articles, we understand those which onerate one of the parties only, or which impose a much heavier burden upon the one than upon the other. We shall treat this subject more at large in the chapter on the "Interpretation of Treaties." Nothing is more conformable to reason and equity than this rule. When- ever absolute certainty is unattainable in the affairs of men, we must have recourse to presumption. Now, if the con- tracting powers have not explained themselves, it is natural, when the question relates to things favourable, and equally 302 AND OTHER PUBLIC TREATIES. 207 advantageous to the two allies, to presume that it was their BOOK u. intention to make a real treaty, as being the more advan- CHAP - XJI - tageous to their respective kingdoms: and if we are mistaken in this presumption, we do no injury to either party. But, if there be any thing odious in the engagements, if one of the contracting states finds itself overburdened by them, how can it be presumed that the prince who entered into such engagements intended to lay that burden upon his king- dom in perpetuity ? Every sovereign is presumed to desire the safety and advantage of the state with which he is in- trusted : wherefore it cannot be supposed that he has con- sented to load it for ever with a burdensome obligation. If necessity rendered such a measure unavoidable, it was in- cumbent on his ally to have the matter explicitly ascertained at the time ; and it is probable that he would not have neg- lected this precaution, well knowing that mankind in gene- ral, and sovereigns in particular, seldom submit to heavy and disagreeable burdens, unless bound to do so by formal obliga- tions. If it happens then that the presumption is a mistake, and makes him lose something of his right, it is a consequence of his own negligence. To this AVC may add, that, if either the one or the other must sacrifice a part of his right, it will be a less grievous violation of the laws of equity that the lat- [ 208 ] ter should forego an expected advantage, than that the former should suffer a positive loss and detriment. This is the fa- mous distinction de lucro captando, and de damno vitando. We do not hesitate to include equal treaties of commerce in the number of those that are favourable, since they are in general advantageous, and perfectly conformable to the law of nature. As to alliances made on account of war, Grotius says with reason, that " defensive alliances are more of a favourable nature, offensive alliances have something in them that approaches nearer to what is burdensome or odious."* We could not dispense with the preceding brief summary of those discussions, lest we should in this part of our trea- tise leave a disgusting chasm. They are, however, but sel- dom resorted to in modern practice, as sovereigns at present generally take the prudent precaution of explicitly ascertain- ing the duration of their treaties. They treat for themselves and their successors, for themselves and their kingdoms, for perpetuity, for a certain number of years, &c. or they treat only for the time of their own reign, for an affair peculiar to themselves, for their families, &c. Since public treaties, even those of a personal nature, con- 191. The eluded by a king, or by any other sovereign who is invested obligati with sufficient power, are treaties of state, and obligatory w the whole nation ( 186), real treaties, which were intended * De Jure Belli et Pacis, lib. ii. cap. xvi. 16. 208 OF TREATIES OF ALLIANCE, BOOK n. to subsist independently of the person who has concluded CHAP, xn. them, are undoubtedly binding on his successors ; and the from a real obligation which such treaties impose on the state passes treaty pass successively to all her rulers as soon as they assume the pub- to the sue- jj c authority. The case is the same with respect to the !0rs ' rights acquired by those treaties : they are acquired for the state, and successively pass tocher conductors. It is at present a pretty general custom for the successor to confirm or renew even real alliances concluded by his pre- decessors : and prudence requires that this precaution should not be neglected, since men pay greater respect to an obli- gation which they have themselves contracted, than to one which devolves on them from another quarter, or to which they have only tacitly subjected themselves. The reason is, that, in the former case, they consider their word to be en- gaged, and, in the latter, their conscience alone. i92.Trea- The treaties that have no relation to the performance of ties accom- re iterated acts, but merely relate to transient and single acts pushed once , . , i j j ,. A v / i j j for all and wnicn are concluded at once, those treaties (unless indeed perfected, it be more proper to call them by another name*) those conventions, those compacts, which are accomplished once for all, and not by successive acts, are no sooner executed than [ 209 ] they are completed and perfected. If they are valid, they have in their own nature a perpetual and irrevocable effect : nor have we them in view when we inquire whether a treaty be real or personal. Puffendorf f gives us the following rules to direct us in this inquiry "1. That the successors are bound to observe the treaties of peace concluded by their predecessors. 2. That a successor should observe all the lawful conventions by which his predecessor has transferred any right to a third party." This is evidently wandering from the point in question : it is only saying that what is done with validity by a prince, cannot be annulled by his successors. And who doubts it ? A treaty of peace is in its own nature made with a view to its perpetual duration : and, as soon as it is once duly concluded and ratified, the affair is at an end ; the treaty must be accomplished on both sides, and observed according to its tenor. If it is executed upon the spot, there ends the business at once. But, if the treaty contains engagements for the performance of succes- sive and reiterated acts, it will still be necessary to examine, according to the rules we have laid down, whether it be in this respect real or personal, whether the contracting par- ties intended to bind their successors to the performance of those acts, or only promised them for the time of their own reign. In the same manner, as soon as a right is transferred by a lawful convention, it no longer belongs to the state that * See Chap. XII. 153, of this book. t Law of Nature and Nations, book 8, c. 9, 8. AND OTHER PUBLIC TREATIES. 209 has ceded it ; the affair is concluded and terminated. But, BOOK n. if the successor discovers any flaw in the deed of transfer, CHAP - xn - and proves it, he is not to he accused of maintaining that the convention is not obligatory on him, and refusing to fulfil it ; he only shows that such convention has not taken place : for a defective and invalid deed is a nullity, and to be consi- dered as having never existed. The third rule given by Puffendorf is no less useless with 193 - T respect to this question. It is, " that if, after the other ally Jj^jJ* has already executed something to which he was bound by e^th virtue of the treaty, the king happens to die before he has one part, accomplished in his turn what he had engaged to perform, his successor is indispensably obliged to perform it. For, what the other ally has executed under the condition of re- ceiving an equivalent, having turned to the advantage of the state, or at least having been done with that view, it is clear, that, if he does not receive the return for which he had stipulated, he then acquires the same right as a man who has paid what he did not owe ; and, therefore, the successor is obliged to allow him a complete indemnification for what he has done or given, or to make good, on his own part, what his predecessor had engaged to perform." All this, I say, is foreign to our question. If the alliance is real, it still sub- sists, notwithstanding the death of one of the contracting parties ; if it is personal, it expires with them, or either of them ( 183). But, when a personal alliance comes to be dissolved in this manner, it is quite a different question to [ 210 ascertain what one of the allied states is bound to perform, in case the other has already executed something in pursuance of the treaty : and this question is to be determined on very different principles. It is necessary to distinguish the nature of what has been done pursuant to the treaty. If it has been any of those determinate and substantial acts which it is usual with contracting parties mutually to promise to each other in exchange, or by way of equivalent, there can be no doubt that he who has received, ought to give what he has promised in return, if he would adhere to the agreement, and is obliged to adhere to it : if he is not bound, and is unwilling to adhere to it, he ought to restore what he has received, to replace things in their former state, or to indemnify the ally from whom he has received the advantage in question. To act otherwise, would be keeping possession of another's property. In this case, the ally is in the situation, not of a man who has paid what he did not owe, but of one who has paid be- forehand for a thing that has not been delivered to him. But, if the personal treaty related to any of those uncertain and contingent acts which are to be performed as occasions offer, of those promises which are not obligatory if an op- portunity of fulfilling them does not occur, it is only on occasion likewise that the performance of similar acts is due 39 2A2 305 210 OF TREATIES OF ALLIANCE, BOOK n. in return : and, when the term of the alliance is expired, CHAP, xii. neither of the parties remains bound by any obligation. In a defensive alliance, for instance, two kings have reciprocally promised each other a gratuitous assistance during the term of their lives : one of them is attacked : he is succoured by his ally, and dies before he has an opportunity to succour him in his turn : the alliance is at an end, and no obligation thence devolves on the successor of the deceased, except in- deed that he certainly owes a debt of gratitude to the sove- reign who has given a salutary assistance to his state. And we must not pronounce such an alliance an injurious one to the ally who has given assistance without receiving any. His treaty was one of those speculating contracts in which the advantages or disadvantages wholly depend on chance : he might have gained by it, though it has been his fate to lose. We might here propose another question. The personal alliance expiring at the death of one of the allies, if the sur- vivor, under an idea that it is to subsist with the successor, fulfils the treaty on his part in favour of the latter, defends his country, saves some of his towns, or furnishes provisions for his army, what ought the sovereign to do, who is thus succoured ? He ought, doubtless, either to suffer the alliance to subsist, as the ally of his predecessor has conceived that it was to subsist (and this will be a tacit renewal and exten- sion of the treaty) or to pay for the real service he has re- ceived, according to a just estimate of its importance, if he does not choose to continue that alliance. It would be in such a case as this that we might say with Puffendorf, that he 211 ] who has rendered such a service has acquired the right of a man who has paid what he did not owe. 194. The The duration of a personal alliance being restricted to the personal al- persons of the contracting sovereigns, if, from any cause hance ex-^ -whatsoever, one of them ceases to reign, the alliance ex- erf the con- pires : for they have contracted in quality of sovereigns ; and trading he who ceases to reign no longer exists as a sovereign, though power* he still lives as a man. Kings do not always treat solely and directly for their Tils' Trea- kingdoms ; sometimes, by virtue of the power they have in ties in their their hands, they make treaties relative to their own persons, own nature or their families; and this they may lawfully do, as the wel- personaL f are O f the state is interested in the safety and advantage of the sovereign, properly understood. These treaties are per- sonal in their own nature, and expire, of course, on the death of the king or the extinction of his family. Such is an alli- ance made for the defence of a king and his family. i6. Alii- It is asked, whether such an alliance subsists with the king ""!f T^~ an< ^ *^ e r y a l family, when, by some revolution, they are de- th" defence P rived of the rown " We have remarked above ( 194), that of the kiag a personal alliance expires with the reign of him who con- and the tracted it : but that is to be understood of an alliance formed AND OTHER PUBLIC TEEATIES. 211 with the state, and restricted, in its duration, to the reign of BOOK n. the contracting king. But the alliance of which we are now CHAP, xn. to treat, is of another nature. Although obligatory on the roya i state, since she is bound by all the public acts of her sove- family, reign, it is made directly in favour of the king and his family : it would, therefore, be absurd that it should be dissolved at the moment when they stand in need of it, and by the very event which it was intended to guard against. Besides, the king does not forfeit the character of royalty merely by the loss of his kingdom. If he is unjustly despoiled of it by an usurper, or by rebels, he still preserves his rights, among which are to be reckoned his alliances. But who shall judge whether a king has been dethroned lawfully or by violence ? An independent nation acknow- ledges no judge. If the body of the nation declare that the king has forfeited his right, by the abuse he has made of it, and depose him, they may justly do it when their grievances are well founded ; and no other power has a right to censure their conduct. The personal ally of this king ought not, therefore, to assist him against the nation who have made use of their right in deposing him: if he attempts it, he injures that nation. England declared war against Louis XIV., in the year 1688, for supporting the interests of James II., who had been formally deposed by the nation. The same coun- try declared war against him a second time, at the beginning of the present century, because that prince acknowledged the son of the deposed monarch, under the title of James III. In doubtful cases, and when the body of the nation has not pronounced, or has not pronounced freely, a sovereign ought [ 212 ] naturally to support and defend an ally ; and it is then that the voluntary law of nations subsists between different states. The party who have expelled the king maintain that they have right on their side : the unfortunate prince and his allies flatter themselves with having the same advantage ; and, as they have no common judge upon earth, there remains no other mode of deciding the contest than an appeal to arms : they, therefore, engage in a formal war. finally, when the foreign prince has faithfully fulfilled his engagements towards an unfortunate monarch, when he has done, in his defence, or to procure his restoration, every thing which, by the terms of the alliance, he was bound to do, if his efforts have proved ineffectual, it cannot be expected, by the dethroned prince, that he shall support an endless war in his favour, that he shall for ever continue at enmity with the nation or the sovereign who has deprived him of the throne. He must at length think of peace, abandon his un- fortunate ally, and consider him as having himself abandoned his right through necessity. Thus, Louis XIV. was obliged to abandon James II. and to acknowledge King William, though he had at first treated him as an usurper. 307 212 OF TREATIES OF ALLIANCE, ETC. BOOK n. The same question presents itself in real alliances, and, in CHAP, xii. general, in all alliances made with a state, and not in parti- 197. Obli- cular with a king, for the defence of his person. An ally gation of a ought, doubtless, to be defended against every invasion, real alliance a g a i ns t every foreign violence, and even against his rebellious allied kb!g subjects ; in the same manner a republic ought to be defended is deposed, against the enterprises of one who attempts to destroy the public liberty. But the other party in the alliance ought to recollect that he is the ally, and not the judge, of the state or the nation. If the nation has deposed her king in form, if the people of a republic have expelled their magistrates, and set themselves at liberty, or, either expressly or tacitly, acknowledged the authority of an usurper, to oppose these domestic regulations, or to dispute their justice or validity, would be interfering in the government of the nation, and doing her an injury (see 54, &c. of this Book.) The ally remains the ally of the state, notwithstanding the change that has happened in it. However, if this change renders the alliance useless, dangerous, or disagreeable to him, he is at liberty to renounce it : for, he may upon good grounds assert that he would not have entered into an alliance with that nation, had she been under her present form of government. To this case we may also apply what we have said above respecting a personal ally. However just the cause of that king may be, who is expelled from the throne either by his subjects or by a foreign usurper, his allies are not obliged to support an eternal war in his favour. After having made ineffectual efforts to reinstate him, they must at length restore to their people the blessings of peace ; they must come to an accommodation with the usurper, and for that purpose treat with him as with a lawful sovereign. Louis XIV., finding himself exhausted by a bloody and unsuccessful war, made [ 213 ] an offer, at Gertruydenberg, to abandon his grandson, whom -he had placed on the throne of Spain : and afterwards, when the aspect of affairs was changed, Charles of Austria, the rival of Philip, saw himself, in his turn, abandoned by his allies. They grew weary of exhausting their states in order to put him in possession of a crown to which they thought him justly entitled, but which they no longer saw any proba- bility of being able to procure for him. 308 OF THE DISSOLUTION AND RENEWAL OF TREATIES. 213 BOOK II. CHAP. XIII. CHAP. XIII. OF THE DISSOLUTION AND RENEWAL OF TREATIES. (125) AN alliance is dissolved at the expiration of the term for 198. Ex- which it had been concluded. This term is sometimes fixed, piration of as, when an alliance is made for a certain number of years ; jJJ sometimes it is uncertain, as in personal alliances, whose du- ii m i te d ration depends on the lives of the contracting powers. The time, term is likewise uncertain, when two or more sovereigns form an alliance with a view to some particular object; as, for instance, that of expelling a horde of barbarous invaders ^ from a neighbouring country, of reinstating a sovereign on his throne, &c. The duration of such an alliance depends on the completion jof the enterprise for which it was formed. Thus, in the last-mentioned instance, when the sovereign is restored, and so firmly seated on his throne as to be able to retain the undisturbed possession of it, the alliance, which was formed with a sole view to his restoration, is now at an end. But, on the other hand, if the enterprise prove unsuc- cessful, the moment his allies are convinced of the impossi- bility of carrying it into effect, the alliance is likewise at an end ; for it is time to renounce an undertaking when it is acknowledged to be impracticable. A treaty entered into for a limited time may be renewed 199. Re- by the common consent of the allies, which consent may be newal of either expressly or tacitly made known. When the treaty is treaties - expressly renewed, it is the same as if a new one were con- cluded, in all respects similar to the former. The tacit renewal of a treaty is not to be presumed upon slight grounds; for, engagements of so high importance are well entitled to the formality of an express consent. The presumption, therefore, of a tacit renewal must be founded on acts of such a nature as not to admit a doubt of their hav- ing been performed in pursuance of the treaty. But, even in this case, still another difficulty arises : for, according to the circumstances and nature of the acts in question, they may prove nothing more than a simple continuation or extension of the treaty, which is very different from a renewal, espe- cially as to the term of duration. For instance, England has [ 214 J entered into a subsidiary treaty with a German prince, who is to keep on foot, during ten years, a stated number of troops at the disposal of that country, on condition of receiving from her a certain yearly sum. The ten years being expired, the king of England causes the sum stipulated for one year to be (125) See, in general, Grotius, b. 3, to 47, 615 to 630, and ii. Index, tit c. 2; and 1 Chitty's Com. Law, 38 Treaties. 309 214 OF THE DISSOLUTION AND RENEWAL OF TREATIES. BOOK ii. paid : the ally receives it : thus the treaty is indeed tacitly CHAP, xni. continued for one year ; but it cannot be said to be renewed ; for the transaction of that year does not impose an obligation of doing the same thing for ten years successively. But, sup- posing a sovereign has, in consequence of an agreement with a neighbouring state, paid her a million of money for permis- sion to keep a garrison in one of her strongholds during ten years, if, at the expiration of that term, the sovereign, in- stead of withdrawing his garrison, makes his ally a tender of another million, and the latter accepts it, the treaty is, in this case, tacitly renewed. When the term for which the treaty was made is expired, each of the allies is perfectly free, and may consent or refuse to renew it, as he thinks proper. It must, however, be con- fessed, that, if one of the parties, who has almost singly reaped all the advantages of the treaty, should, without just and substantial reasons, refuse to renew it now that he thinks he will no longer stand in need of it, and foresees the time approaching when his ally may derive advantage from it in turn, such conduct would be dishonourable, inconsistent with that generosity which should characterize sovereigns, and widely distant from those sentiments of gratitude and friendship that are due to an old and faithful ally. It is but too common to see great potentates, when arrived at the sum- mit of power, neglect those who have assisted them in attain- ing it. 200. How Treaties contain promises that are perfect and reciprocal, a treaty is If one O f t ne allies fails in his engagements, the other may wher^viola com P e ^ n ^ m to fulfil them : a perfect promise confers a right ted by one * do so. But, if the latter has no other expedient than that of the con- of arms to force his ally to the performance of his promises, tracting h e w in sometimes find it more eligible to cancel the promises parties. Qn ^j g Qwn & ^ e a j g() ^ an( j ^ Q Dissolve the treaty. He has un- doubtedly a right to do this, since his promises were made only on condition that the ally should, on his part, execute every thing which he had engaged to perform. The party, therefore, who is offended or injured in those particulars which constitute the basis of the treaty, is at liberty to choose the alternative of either compelling a faithless ally to fulfil his engagements, or of declaring the treaty dissolved by his violation of it. On such an occasion, prudence and wise policy will point out the line of conduct to be pursued. 201. The But when there exist between allies two or more treaties, violation of different from and independent of each other, the violation docs'not 3 '' ^ one ^ t ^ lose treat ^ es does not directly disengage the in- cancel an- j ure d P ar *y from the obligations he has contracted in the other. others : for, the promises contained in these do not depend on those included in the violated treaty. But the offended [ 215 ] ally may, on the breach of one treaty by the other party, threaten him with a renunciation, on his own part, of all the 310 OF THE DISSOLUTION AND RENEWAL OF TREATIES. 215 other treaties by which they are united, and may put his BOOK n. threats in execution if the other disregards them. For, if any CHAP. xin. one wrests or withholds from me my right, I may, in the state of nature, in order to oblige him to do me justice, to punish him, or to indemnify myself, deprive him also of some of his rights, or seize and detain them till I have obtained complete satisfaction. And, if recourse is had to arms, in order to obtain satisfaction for the infringement of that treaty, the offended party begins by stripping his enemy of all the rights which had accrued to him from the different treaties subsist- ing between them : and we shall see, in treating of war, that he may do this with justice. Some writers* would extend what we have just said to the 202. The different articles of a treaty which have no connection with violation of the article that has been violated, saying we ought to con-JJ^J^j! sider those several articles as so many distinct treaties con- ^ a * cancc i eluded at the same time. They maintain, therefore, that, if the whole, either of the allies violates one article of the treaty, the other ( 126 ) has not immediately a right to cancel the entire treaty, but that he may either refuse, in his turn, what he had promised with a view to the violated article, or compel his ally to fulfil his promises if there still remains a possibility of fulfilling them, if not, to repair the damage ; and that for this pur- pose he may threaten to renounce the entire treaty, a menace which he may lawfully put in execution, if it be disregarded by the other. Such undoubtedly is the conduct which pru- dence, moderation, the love of peace, and charity would com- monly prescribe to nations. Who will deny this, and madly assert that sovereigns are allowed to have immediate recourse to arms, or even to break every treaty of alliance and friend- ship, for the least subject of complaint ? But the question here turns on the simple right, and not on the measures which are to be pursued in order to obtain justice ; and the principle upon which those writers ground their decision, appears to me utterly indefensible. We cannot consider the several articles of the same treaty as so many distinct and independ- ent treaties : for, though we do not see any immediate con- nection between some of those articles, they are all connected * See Wolfius, Jus Gent. 432. aliens but as native subjects of Great (126) In Sutton v. Sutton, 1 Russ. & Britain, and capable of inheriting and Mylne Rep. 663, A. D. 1830, it was holding such lands, notwithstanding a held in the Court of Chancery, that, subsequent war between the two coun- under the treaty of peace, 19 Nov. 1794, tries, and this in respect of the express between Great Britain and (the United provision which prevents a subsequent States of}- America, the act of 37 Geo. 3, war from wholly determining that part of c. 97, passed for the purpose of carrying the treaty. The Master of the Rolls there such treaty into execution, American ci- said, It is a reasonable construction, tizens, who held lands i Great Britain that it was the intention of the treaty on the 28th Oct. 1795, and their heirs that the operation of the treaty should and assigns, are at all times to be consi- be permanent, and not depend upon the dered, so far as regards these lands, not as continuance of a state of peace." 311 215 OF THE DISSOLUTION AND RENEWAL OF TREATIES. BOOK n. by this common relation, viz. that the contracting powers CHAP, xiii. nave agreed to some of them in consideration of the others, and by way of compensation. I would perhaps never have consented to this article, if my ally had not granted me an- other, which in its own nature has no relation to it. Every thing, therefore, which is comprehended in the same treaty, is of the same force and nature as a reciprocal promise, unless where a formal exception is made to the contrary. Grotius very properly observes that " every article of a treaty carries with it a condition, by the non-performance of which the treaty is wholly cancelled."* He adds, that a clause is some- times inserted to the following effect, viz. "that the violation of any one of the articles shall not cancel the whole treaty," in order that one of the parties may not have, in every slight offence, a pretext for receding from his engagements. This precaution is extremely prudent, and very conformable to the care which nations ought to take of preserving peace, [ 216 ] and rendering their alliances durable. (127) 203. The I n the same manner as a personal treaty expires at the treaty is void death of the king who has contracted it, a real treaty is dis- by the de- so lved, if one of the allied nations is destroyed, that is to one^fThe sav ' no * on ^ ^ *k e m en who compose it happen all to perish, contracting but, also if, from any cause whatsoever, it loses its national powers. quality, or that of a political and independent society. Thus, when a state is destroyed and the people are dispersed, or when they are subdued by a conqueror, all their alliances and treaties fall to the ground with the public power that had contracted them. But it is here to be observed, that treaties or alliances which impose a mutual obligation to perform cer- tain acts, and whose existence consequently depends on that of the contracting powers, are not to be confounded with those contracts by which a perfect right is once for all acquired, independent of any mutual performance of subsequent acts. If, for instance, a nation has for ever ceded to a neighbouring prince the right of fishing in a certain river, or that of keep- ing a garrison in a particular fortress, that prince does not lose his rights, even though the nation from whom he has re- ceived them happens to be subdued, or in any other manner subjected to a foreign dominion. His rights do not depend on the preservation of that nation : she had alienated them ; and the conqueror by whom she has been subjugated can only take what belonged to her. In the same manner, the debts of a nation, or those for which the sovereign has mortgaged any of his towns or provinces, are not cancelled by conquest. The king of Prussia, on acquiring Silesia by conquest and by the treaty of Breslau, took upon himself the debts for which * Grotius de Jure Belli et Pacis, lib. 1 Russ. & Mylne, 663, is an express ii. cap. xv. 15. decision upon such a provision even by (127) The case of Button v. Sutton, implication. 312 OF THE DISSOLUTION AND RENEWAL OF TREATIES. 216 that province stood mortgaged to some English merchants. BOOK n. In fact, his conquest extended no further than the acquisition CHAP, xm. of those rights which the house of Austria had possessed over the country ; and he could only take possession of Silesia, such as he found it at the time of the conquest, with all its rights and all its burdens. For a conqueror to refuse to pay the debts of a country he has subdued, would be robbing the creditors, with whom he is not at war. Since a nation or a state, of whatever kind, cannot make 204. Alli- any treaty contrary to those by which she is actually bound ances of a ( 165), she cannot put herself under the protection of another j^ 6 ^* state, without reserving all her alliances and all her existing war d s pu t treaties. For, the convention by which a state places herself herself un- under the protection of another sovereign, is a treaty ( 175) : der the pro- if she does it of her own accord, she ought to do it in such a j^g r f manner, that the new treaty may involve no infringement of her pre-existing ones. We have seen ( 176) what rights a [ 217 ] nation derives, in a case of necessity, from the duty of self- preservation. The alliances of a nation are therefore not dissolved when she puts herself under the protection of another state, unless they be incompatible with the conditions of that protection. The ties by which she was bound to her former allies still sub- sist, and those allies still remain bound by their engagements to her, as long as she has not put it out of her power to fulfil her engagements to them. When necessity obliges a people to put themselves under the protection of a foreign power, and to promise him the assistance of their whole force against all opponents whatso- ever, without excepting their allies, their former alliances do indeed subsist, so far as they are not incompatible with the new treaty of protection. But, if the case should happen, that a former ally enters into a war with the protector, the protected state will be obliged to declare for the latter, to whom she is bound by closer ties, and by a treaty which, in case of collision, is paramount to all the others. Thus the Nepesinians, having been obliged to submit to the Etrurians, thought themselves afterwards bound to adhere to their treaty of submission or capitulation, preferably to the alliance which had subsisted between them and the Romans : postquqm de- ditionis, quam societatis, fides sanctior erat, says Livy.* Finally, as treaties are made by the mutual agreement of 205. the parties, they may also be dissolved by mutual consent, at Treaties the free will of the contracting powers. And, even though a dissolved b y third party should find himself interested in the preservation JJj of the treaty, and should suffer by its dissolution, yet, if he had no share in making such treaty, and no direct promise had been made to him, those who have reciprocally made pro- * Lib. vi. cap. x. 40 2 B 313 217 OP OTHER PUBLIC CONVENTIONS, ETC. BOOK n. mises to each other, which eventually prove advantageous to CHAP, xin. that third party, may also reciprocally release each other from them, without consulting him, or without his having a right to oppose them. Two monarchs have bound themselves by a mutual promise to unite their forces for the defence of a neighbouring city ; that city derives advantage from their assistance ; but she has no right to it ; and, as soon as the two monarchs think proper mutually to dispense with their engagements, she will be deprived of their aid, but can have no reason to complain on the occasion, since no promise had been made to her. [ 218 ] CHAP. XIV. CHAP, xiv. OF OTHER PUBLIC CONVENTIONS, OF THOSE THAT ARE MADE BY SUBORDINATE POWERS, PARTICULARLY OF THE AGREE- MENT CALLED IN LATIN SPONSIO, AND OF CONVENTIONS OF SOVEREIGNS WITH PRIVATE PERSONS. 206. Con- THE public compacts, called conventions, articles of agree- ventions m ent, &c., when they are made between sovereigns, differ sovereigns. fr m treaties only in their object ( 153). What we have said of the validity of treaties, of their execution, of their dissolution, and of the obligations and rights that flow from them, is all applicable to the various conventions which sove- reigns may conclude with each other. Treaties, conventions, and agreements are all public engagements, in regard to which there is but one 'and the same right, and the same rules. We do not here wish to disgust the reader by unne- cessary repetitions : and it were equally unnecessary to enter into an enumeration of the various kinds of these conven- tions, which are always of the same nature, and differ only in the matter which constitutes their object. 207. But there are public conventions made by subordinate ^ hos fj. de powers, in virtue either of an express mandate from the natTpoiers. sovereign, or of the authority with which they are invested by the terms of their commission, and according as the nature of the affairs with which they are intrusted may admit or re- quire the exercise of that authority. The appellation of inferior or subordinate powers is given to public persons who exercise some portion of the sovereignty in the name and under the authority of the sovereign : such are magistrates established for the administration of justice, generals of armies, and ministers of state. When, by an express order from their sovereign on the particular occasion, and with sufficient powers derived from him for the purpose, those persons form a convention, such OF OTHER PUBLIC CONVENTIONS, ETC. 218 convention is made in the name of the sovereign himself, who BOOK n. contracts by the mediation and ministry of his delegate or CHAP. XIT. proxy : this is the case we have mentioned in 156. But public persons, by virtue of their office, or of the com- mission given to them, have also themselves the power of making conventions on public affairs, exercising on those occasions the right and authority of the sovereign by whom they are commissioned. There are two modes in which they acquire that power ; it is given to them in express terms by the sovereign : or it is naturally derived from their commis- sion itself, the nature of the affairs with which these persons and intrusted, requiring that they should have a power to make such conventions, especially in cases where they cannot await the orders of their sovereign. Thus, the governor of a [ 219 ] town, and the general who besieges it, have a power to settle the terms of capitulation ; and whatever agreement they thus form within the terms of their commission, is obligatory on the state or sovereign who has invested them with the power by which they conclude it. As conventions of this nature take place principally in war, we shall treat of them more at large in Book III. If a public person, an ambassador, or a general of an army, 208. exceeding the bounds of his commission, concludes a treaty Treaties or a convention without orders from the sovereign, or without jj n lu ^ c being authorized to do it by virtue of his office, the treaty is person^ null, as being made without sufficient powers ( 157) : it can- without not become valid without the express or tacit ratification of orders from the sovereign. The express ratification is a written deed by th . e sove ~ which the sovereign approves the treaty, and engages to ob- without* serve it. The tacit ratification is implied by certain steps sufficient which the sovereign is justly presumed to take only in pur- powers, suance of the treaty, and which he could not be supposed to take without considering it as concluded and agreed upon. Thus, on a treaty of peace being signed by public ministers who have even exceeded the orders of their sovereigns, if one of the sovereigns causes troops to pass on the footing of friends through the territories of his reconciled enemy, he tacitly ratifies the treaty of peace. But if, by a reservatory clause of the treaty, the ratification of the sovereign be re- quired, as such reservation is usually understood to imply an express ratification, it is absolutely requisite that the treaty be thus expressly ratified before it can acquire its full force. By the Latin term, sponsio, we express an agreement re- 209. The lating to affairs of state, made by a public person, who ex- 1 ceeds the bounds of his commission, and acts without the orders or command of the sovereign. The person who treats for the state in this manner without being commissioned for the purpose, promises of course to use his endeavours for pre- vailing on the state or sovereign to ratify the articles he has agreed to : otherwise his engagement would be nugatory and 315 219 OF OTHER PUBLIC CONVENTIONS, ETC. BOOK n. illusive. The foundation of this agreement can be no other, CHAP, xiv. on either side, than the hope of such ratification. The Roman history furnishes us with various instances of such agreements : the one that first arrests our attention is that which was concluded at the Furcse Caudinse the most famous instance on record, and one that has been discussed by the most celebrated writers. The consuls Titus Veturius Calvinus and Spurius Postumius, with the Roman army, being enclosed in the defiles of the Furcse Caudime, without hope of escaping, concluded a shameful agreement with the Sam- nites informing them, however, that they could not make a real public treaty (fcedus) without orders from the Roman people, without the feciales, and the ceremonies consecrated [ 220 ] by custom. The Samnite general contented himself with exacting a promise from the consuls and principal officers of the army, and obliging them to deliver him six hundred host- ages ; after which, having made the Roman troops lay down their arms, and obliged them to pass under the yoke, he dis- missed them. The senate, however, refused to accede to the treaty, delivered up those who had concluded it to the Sam- nites, who refused to receive them and then thought them- selves free from all obligation, and screened from all reproach.* Authors have entertained very different sentiments of this conduct. Some assert, that, if Rome did not choose to ratify the treaty, she ought to have replaced things in the same situ- ation they were in before the agreement, by sending back the whole army to their encampment at the Furcae Caudinoe: and this the Samnites also insisted upon. I confess that I am not entirely satisfied with the reasonings I have found on this question, even in authors whose eminent superiority I am in other respects fully inclined to acknowledge. Let us therefore endeavour, with the aid of their observations, to set the affair in a new light. 210. The It presents two questions first, what is the person bound to ^' W ^ k as ma ^ e an agreement (sponsor), if the state dis- avows it? Secondly, what is the state bound to do? But, agreement previous to the discussion of these questions, it is necessary to observe with Grotius,f that the state is not bound by an agreement of that nature. This is manifest, even from the definition of the agreement called sponsio. The state has not given orders to conclude it : neither has she in any man- ner whatever conferred the necessary powers for the pur- pose: she has neither expressly given them by her injunc- tions or by a plenipotentiary commission, nor tacitly by a natural or necessary consequence of the authority intrusted to him who makes the agreement (sponsori). The general of an army has, indeed, by virtue of his commission, a power to enter, as circumstances may require, into a private con- * Livy, lib. be. f De Jure Belli et Pacis, lib. ii. cap. iv. 16. 316 OF OTHER PUBLIC CONVENTIONS, ETC. 220 vention, a compact relative to himself, to his troops, or to BOOK n. the occurrences of war : but he has no power to conclude a CHAP, xiv. treaty of peace. He may bind himself, and the troops under his command, on all the occasions where his functions re- quire that he should have the power of treating ; but he can- not bind the state beyond the extent of his commission. Let us now see to what the person promising (sponsor) is 211. To bound, when the state disavows the agreement. We ought what the not here to deduce our arguments from the rules which ob- Jou^Jwh^n tain between private individuals under the law of nature : i t j s <&.. for, the nature of the things in question, and the situation avowed, of the contracting parties, necessarily make a difference be- tween the two cases. It is certain that, between individuals, he who purely and simply promises what depends on the will of another, without being authorized to make such promise, is obliged, if the other disavows the transaction, to accom- [ 221 ] plish himself what he has promised, to give an equivalent to restore things to their former state ; or, finally, to make full compensation to the person with whom he has treated, according to the various circumstances of the case. His promise (sponsio) can be understood in no other light. But this is not the case with respect to a public person, who, with- out orders and without authority, engages for the perform- ance of his sovereign. The question in such case relates to things that infinitely surpass his power and all his faculties things which he can neither execute himself nor cause to be executed, and for which he cannot offer either an equivalent or a compensation in any wise adequate : he is not even at liberty to give the enemy what he has promised, without au- thority: finally, it is equally out of his power to restore things entirely to their former state. The party who treats with him cannot expect any thing of this nature. If the promiser has deceived him by saying he was sufficiently au- thorized, he has a right to punish him. But if, like the Roman consuls at the Furcae Caudinse, the promiser has acted with sincerity, informing him that he had not a power to bind the state by a treaty, nothing else can be presumed, but that the other party was willing to run the risk of making a treaty that must become void, if not ratified, hoping that a regard for him who had promised, and for the hostages, would induce the sovereign to ratify what had been thus concluded. If the event deceives his hopes, he can only blame his own imprudence. An eager desire of obtaining peace on advan- tageous conditions, and the temptation of some present ad- vantages, may have been his only inducements to make so hazardous an agreement. This was judiciously observed by the consul Postumius himself, after his return to Rome. In his speech to the senate, as given to us by Livy, "Your generals," said he, "and those of the enemy, were equally guilty of imprudence, we, in incautiously involving ourselves 2B2 317 221 OF OTHER PUBLIC CONVENTIONS, ETC. BOOK ii. in a dangerous situation, they, in suffering a victory to escape CHAP xiv. them, of which the nature of the ground gave them a cer- tainty ; still distrusting their own advantages, and hasting, at any price, to disarm men who were ever formidable while they had arms in their hands. Why did they not keep us shut up in our camp ? Why did they not send to Rome, in order to treat for peace, on sure grounds, with the senate and the people?" It is manifest that the Samnites contented themselves with the hope that the engagement which the consuls and principal officers had entered into, and the desire of saving six hundred knights, left as hostages, would induce the Romans to ratify the agreement, considering, that, at all events, they should still have those six hundred hostages, with the arms and bag- gage of the army, and the vain, or rather, as it is proved by its consequences, the fatal glory, of having made them pass under the yoke. Under what obligation then were the consuls, and all the others who had joined with them in the promise (sponsor es) ? They themselves judged that they ought to be delivered up to [ 222 ] the Samnites. This was not a natural consequence of the agreement (spomionis] ; and from the observations above made, it does not appear that a general in such circumstances, having promised things which the promisee well knew to be out of his power, is obliged, on his promise being disavowed, to surrender his own person by way of compensation. But, as he has a power expressly to enter into such an engagement which lies fairly within the bounds of his commission, the custom of those times had doubtless rendered such engage- ment a tacit clause of the agreement called sponsio, since the Romans delivered up all the sponsores, all those who had pro- mised: this was a maxim of their fecial law.* If the sponsor has not expressly engaged to deliver himself up, and if established custom does not lay him under an obli- gation to do so, it would seem that he is bound to nothing further by his promise than honestly to endeavour, by every lawful means, to induce the sovereign to ratify what he has promised : and there cannot exist a doubt in the case, provided the treaty be at all equitable, advantageous to the state, or supportable in consideration of the misfortune from which it has preserved her. But, to set out with the intention of mak- ing a treaty the instrument to ward off a deadly blow from the state, and soon after to advise the sovereign to refuse his ratification, not because the treaty is insupportable, but be- * I have said in my preface, that it gave rise. They had also the care the fecial law of the Romans was their of the ceremonies on the declaration law of war. The college of the feciales of war, and on concluding treaties of were consulted on the causes that peace. The feciales were likewise con- might authorize the nation to engage suited, and their agency employed, in in a war, and on the questions to which all public treaties. OF OTHER PUBLIC CONVENTIONS, ETC. 222 cause an advantage may be taken of its having been concluded BOOK n. without authority such a proceeding would undoubtedly be CHAP - "^ a fraudulent and shameful abuse of the faith of treaties. But, what must the general do, who, in order to save his army, has been forced to conclude a treaty that is detrimental or dis- honourable to the state ? Must he advise the sovereign to ratify it ? He will content himself with laying open the mo- tives of his conduct, and the necessity that obliged him to treat : he will show, as Postumius did, that he alone is bound, and that he consents to be disowned and delivered up for the public safety. If the enemy are deceived, it is through their own folly. Was the general bound to inform them that, in all probability, his promises would not be ratified ? It would be too much to require this of him. In such a case, it is sufficient that he does not impose on the enemy by pretend- ing to more extensive powers than he really possesses, but contents himself with embracing the overtures which they make to him, without, on his side, holding forth any delusive hopes to decoy them into a treaty. It is the enemy's business to take all possible precautions for their own security : if they neglect them, why should not the general avail himself of their imprudence, as of an advantage presented to him by the hand of fortune ? "It is she," said Postumius, "who has saved our army, after having put it in danger. The enemy's head was turned in his prosperity ; and his advantages have been no more to him than a pleasant dream." If the Samnites had only required of the Roman generals and army such engagements as the nature of their situation, and their commission, empowered them to enter into, if they had obliged them to surrender themselves prisoners of war, or if, from their inability to hold them all prisoners, they had [ 223 ] dismissed them, upon their promise not to bear arms against them for some years, in case Rome should refuse to ratify the peace, the agreement would have been valid, as being made with sufficient powers ; and the whole army would have been bound to observe it ; for, it is absolutely necessary that the troops, or their officers, should have a power of entering into a contract on those occasions, and upon that footing. This is the case of capitulations, of which we shall speak in treating of war. If the promiser has made an equitable and honourable convention, on an affair of such a nature, that, in case the convention be disallowed, he still has it in his own power to indemnify the party with whom he has treated, he is pre- sumed to have personally pledged himself for suoh indemnifi- cation ; and he is bound to make it, in order to discharge his promise, as did Fabius Maximus in the instance mentioned by Grotius.* But there are occasions when the sovereign may * Lib. ii. chap. xv. 16. Fabius ment with the enemy which the se- Maximus having concluded an agree- nate disapproved, sold a piece of land 319 223 OF OTHER PUBLIC CONVENTIONS, ETC. BOOK ii. forbid him to act in that manner, or to give any thing to the CHAP, xiv. enemies of the state. 212. To We have shown that a state cannot be bound by an agree- what the ment made without her orders, and without her having granted sovereign is an y p OWer f or that purpose. But is she absolutely free from all obligation ? That is the point which now remains for us to examine. If matters as yet continue in their original situation, the state or the sovereign may simply disavow the treaty, which is of course done away by such disa- vowal, and becomes as perfect a nullity as if it had never ex- isted. But the sovereign ought to make known his intentions as soon as the treaty comes to his knowledge ; not, indeed, that his silence alone can give validity to a convention which the contracting parties have agreed not to consider as valid without his approbation ; but it would be a breach of good faith in him to suffer a sufficient time to elapse for the other party to execute, on his side, an agreement which he himself is determined not to ratify. If any thing has already been done in consequence of the agreement, if the party, who has treated with the sponsor, has on his side fulfilled his engagements, either in the whole or in part, is the other party, on disavowing the treaty, bound to indemnify him, or restore things to their former situation ? or is he allowed to reap the fruits of the treaty, [_ 224 ] at the same time that he refuses to ratify it ? We should here distinguish the nature of the things that have been exe- cuted, and that of the advantages which have thence accrued to the state. He who, having treated with a public person not furnished with sufficient powers, executes the agreement on his side without waiting for its ratification, is guilty of im- prudence, and commits an egregious error, into which he has not been led by the state with which he supposes he has con- tracted. If he has given up any part of his property, the other party is not justifiable in taking advantage of his folly, and retaining possession of what he has so given. Thus, when a state, thinking she has concluded a peace with the enemy's general, has in consequence delivered up one of her strong places, or given a sum of money, the sovereign of that general is, undoubtedly, bound to restore what he has re- ceived, if he does not choose to ratify the agreement. To act otherwise, would be enriching himself with another's property, and retaining that property without having any title to it. But, if the agreement has given nothing to the state which she did not before possess, if, as in that of the Furcse Cau- dinae, the advantage simply consists in her escape from an impending danger, her preservation from a threatened loss, for which he received two hundred ransom of the prisoners. Aurel. Vic- thousand sesterces, in order to make tor, de Viris Illustr. Plutarch's Life good his promise. It related to the of Fabius Maximus. 320 OF OTHER PUBLIC CONVENTIONS, ETC. 224 such advantage is a boon of fortune, which she may enjoy BOOK n. without scruple. Who would refuse to be saved by the folly CHAP ' XIY ' of his enemy? And who would think himself obliged to indemnify that enemy for the advantage he had suffered to escape him, when no fraud had been used to induce him to forego that advantage ? The Samnites pretended, that, if the Romans would not ratify the treaty made by their con- suls, they ought to send back the army to the Furcse Caudi- nae, and restore every thing to its former state. Two tri- bunes of the people, who had been in the number of the sponsores, and wished to avoid being delivered up, had the assurance to maintain the same doctrine ; and some authors have declared themselves of their opinion. What ! the Sam- nites take advantage of conjunctures, in order to give law to the Eomans, and to wrest from them a shameful treaty, they are so imprudent as to treat with the consuls, who ex- pressly declare themse'ves unauthorized to contract for the state, they suffer the Roman army to escape, after having covered them with infamy, and shall not the Romans take advantage of the folly of an enemy so void of generosity ? Must they either ratify a shameful treaty, or restore to the enemy all those advantages which the situation of the ground had given them, but which he had lost merely through his own folly ? Upon what principle can such a decision be founded ? Had Rome promised any thing to the Samnites ? Had she prevailed upon them to let her army go, previous to the rati- fication of the agreement made by the consuls ? If she had received any thing in consequence of that agreement, she would have been bound to restore it, as we have already said, because she would have possessed it without a title, on de- claring the treaty null. But she had no share in the conduct of her enemies : she did not contribute to the egregious blunder they had committed ; and she might as justly take [ 225 ] advantage of it, as generals in war do of the mistakes of an unskilful opponent. Suppose a conqueror after having con- cluded a treaty with ministers who have expressly reserved the ratification to their master, should have the imprudence to abandon all his conquests without waiting for such ratifi- cation, must the other, with a foolish generosity, invite him back to take possession of them again, in case the treaty be not ratified? I confess, however, and freely acknowledge, that, if the enemy who suffer an entire army to escape on the faith of an agreement concluded with the general, who is unprovided with sufficient powers, and a simple sponsor, I confess, I say, that, if the enemy have behaved generously, if they had not availed themselves of their advantages to dictate shame- ful or too severe conditions, equity requires that the estate should either ratify the agreement or conclude a new treaty on just and reasonable conditions, abating even of her pre- 41 321 225 OF OTHER PUBLIC CONVENTIONS, ETC. BOOK n. tensions as far as the public welfare will allow. For, we CHAP, xiv. OU ght never to abuse the generosity and noble confidence even of an enemy. Pufiendorf* thinks that the treaty at the Furcse Caudinae contained nothing that was too severe or insupportable. That author seems to make no great ac- count of the shame and ignominy with which it would have branded the whole republic. He did not see the full extent of the Roman policy, whicK would never permit them, in their greatest distresses, to accept a shameful treaty, or even to make peace on the footing of a conquered nation : a sub- lime policy, to which Rome was indebted for all her greatness. Finally, let us observe, that, when the inferior power has, without orders, and without authority, concluded an equitable and honourable treaty, to rescue the state from an imminent danger, if the sovereign afterwards, on seeing himself thus delivered, should refuse to ratify the treaty, not because he thinks it a disadvantageous one, but, merely through a wish to avoid performing those conditions which were annexed as the price of his deliverance, he would certainly act in oppo- sition to all the rules of honour and equity. This would be a case in which we might apply the maxim, summum jus, summa injuria. To the example we have drawn from the Roman history, let us add a famous one taken from modern history. The Swiss, dissatisfied with France, entered into an alliance with the em- peror against Louis XII. and made an irruption into Burgundy, in the year 1513. They laid siege to Dijon. La Trimouille, who commanded in the place, fearing that he should be unable to save it, treated with the Swiss, and, without waiting for a commission from the king, concluded an agreement, by virtue of which the king of France was to renounce his pretensions to the duchy of Milan, and to pay the Swiss, by settled in- stalments, the sum of six hundred thousand crowns ; whereas the Swiss, on their side, promised nothing further than to re- turn home to their own country, thus remaining at liberty to attack France again, if they thought proper. They re- ceived hostages, and departed. The king was very much dis- satisfied with the treaty, though it had saved Dijon, and rescued the kingdom from an imminent and alarming danger ; and he [ 226 ] refused to ratify it."f It is certain that La Trimouille had exceeded the powers he derived from his commission, espe- cially in promising that the king should renounce the duchy of Milan. It is probable, indeed, that his only view was to rid himself of an enemy whom it was less difficult to overreach in negotiation than to subdue in battle. Louis was not obliged to ratify and execute a treaty concluded without orders and without authority; and, if the Swiss were deceived, they * Jus Nat. et Gent. lib. yiii. cap. ix. f Guicciardini, book xii. chap, ii. I 12. De Watteville's History of the Helvetic Confederacy, part ii. p. 185, Ac. 322 OF OTHER PUBLIC CONVENTIONS, ETC. 226 could only blame their own imprudence. But, as it manifestly BOOK n. appeared that La Trimouille did not behave towards them with AP " XIV - candour and honesty, since he had deceived them on the sub- ject of the hostages, by giving, in that character, men of the meanest rank, instead of four of the most distinguished citi- zens, as he had promised,* the Swiss would have been justi- fiable in refusing to make peace without obtaining satisfaction for that act of perfidy, either by the surrender of him who was the author of it, or in some other manner. The promises, the conventions, all the private contracts of 213. Pri- the sovereign, are naturally subject to the same rules as those vate con ' of private persons. If any difficulties arise on the subject, it ^eitigu. * is equally conformable to the rules of decorum, to that deli- cacy of sentiment which ought to be particularly conspicuous in a sovereign, and to the love of justice, to cause them to be decided by the tribunals of the state. And such indeed is the practice of all civilized states that are governed by settled laws. The conventions and contracts which the sovereign, in his g 214. Con- sovereign character and in the name of the state, forms with fractf madc private individuals of a foreign nation, fall under the rules b ^ w e l * h we have laid down with respect to public treaties. In fact, ^nTin the when a sovereign enters into a contract with one who is name of the wholly independent of him and of the state, whether it be 8tate - with a private person, or with a nation or sovereign, this cir- cumstance does not produce any difference in the rights of the parties. If the private person who has treated with the sovereign is his subject, the rights of each party in this case also are the same : but there is a difference in the manner of deciding the controversies which may arise from the contract. That private person, being a subject of the state, is obliged to submit his pretensions to the established courts of justice. It is added by some writers on this subject, that the sovereign may rescind those contracts, if they prove inimical to the public welfare. Undoubtedly he may do so, but not upon any principle derived from the peculiar nature of such contracts : [ 227 ] it must be either upon the same principle which invalidates even a public treaty when it is ruinous to the state and incon- sistent with the public safety, or by virtue of the eminent domain, which gives the sovereign a right to dispose of the property of the citizens with a view to the common safety. We speak here of an absolute sovereign. It is from the con- stitution of each state that we are to learn who are the per- sons, and what is the power, entitled to contract in the name of the state, to exercise the supreme authority, and to pro- nounce on what the public welfare requires. When a lawful power contracts in the name of the state, it 215. They lays an obligation on the nation itself, and consequently on * Binding on the na- * See De Watteville's History of the Helvetic Confederacy, p. 190. 323 227 OF OTHER PUBLIC CONVENTIONS; ETC. BOOK n. all the future rulers of the society. When, therefore, a prince CHAP. XIY. k ag t ne power to form a contract in the name of the state, he tion, and on ] a y g an obligation on all his successors ; and these are not ^ors! UC< '~ l ess Doun d than himself to fulfil his engagements. 216. Debts The conductor of the nation may have dealings of his own, of the sove- and private debts ; and his private property alone is liable reign and f or fa e discharge of such debts. But loans contracted for j state. ^ e gery ;[ ce O f fa e s t a te, debts incurred in the administration of public affairs, are contracts in all the strictness of law, and obligatory on the state and the whole nation, which is indis- pensably bound to discharge those debts.* When once they have been contracted by lawful authority, the right of the creditor is indefeasible. Whether the money borrowed has been turned to the advantage of the state, or squandered in foolish expenses, is no concern of the person who has lent it : he has intrusted the nation with his property, and the nation is bound to restore it to him again : it is so much the worse for her, if she has committed the management of her affairs to improper hands. This maxim, however, has its bounds, founded even on the nature of the thing. The sovereign has not, in general, a power to render the state or body corporate liable for the debts he contracts, unless they be incurred with a view to the national advantage, and in order to enable him to provide for all occurrences. If he is absolute, it belongs to him alone to decide, in all doubtful cases, what the welfare and safety of the state require. But, if he should, without necessity, con- tract debts of immense magnitude and capable of ruining the nation for ever, there could not then exist any doubt in the case : the sovereign has evidently acted without authority ; and those who have lent him their money have imprudently [ 228 ] risked it. It cannot be presumed that a nation has ever con- sented to submit to utter ruin through the caprice and foolish prodigality of her ruler. As the national debts can only be paid by contributions and taxes, wherever the sovereign has not been intrusted by the nation with a power to levy taxes and contributions, or, in short, to raise supplies by his own authority, neither has he a power to renderher liable for what he borrows, or to in- volve the state in debt. Thus, the king of England, who has the right of making peace and war, has not that of contract- * In 1596, Philip II. declared him- could no longer find any one who was self a bankrupt, under pretence that an willing to lend him money ; and his unfair advantage had been taken of his affairs suffered so severely in conse- necossitios. His creditors loudly ex- quence, that he was obliged to replace claimed against his conduct, and as- things on their former footing, and to serted that no confidence could thence- heal the wound which he had given to forward be placed either in his word or the public faith. Grotius, Hist, of his treaties, since he interposed the the Disturbances in the Netherlands, royal authority to supersede them. He book 324 OF THE FAITH OF TREATIES. 228 ing national debts, without the concurrence of parliament : BOOK n. because he cannot, without their concurrence, levy any money CHAP - xiy> on his people. The case is not the same with the donations of the sove- 217. Do- reign as with his debts. When a sovereign has borrowed nations of without necessity, or for an unwise purpose, the creditor has th . e sove " intrusted the state with his property ; and it is just that the rei) state should restore it to him, if at the time of the transac- tion, he could entertain a reasonable presumption that it was to the state he was lending it. But, when the sovereign gives away any of the property of the state, a part of the national domain, a considerable fief, he has no right to make such grant except with a view to the public welfare, as a reward for services rendered to the state, or for some other reason- able cause, in which the nation is concerned : if he has made the donation without reason, and without a lawful cause, he has made it without authority. His successor, or the state, may at any time revoke such a grant ; nor would the revoca- tion be a wrong done to the grantee, since it does not deprive him of any thing which he could justly call his own. What we here advance holds true of every sovereign whom the law does not expressly invest with the free and absolute disposal of the national property : so dangerous a power is never to be founded on presumption. Immunities and privileges conferred by the mere liberality of the sovereign, are a kind of donations, and may be revoked in the same manner, if they prove detrimental to the state. But a sovereign cannot revoke them by his bare authority, unless he be absolute : and, even in this case, he ought to be cautious and moderate in the exertion of his power, uniting an equal share of prudence and equity on the occasion. Im- munities granted for particular reasons, or with a view to some return, partake of the nature of a burdensome contract, and can only be revoked in case of abuse, or when they be- come incompatible with the safety of the state. And if they be suppressed on this latter account, an indemnification is due to those who enjoyed them. CHAP. XV. [ 229 ] OF THE FAITH OF TREATIES. CHAP - * v - THOUGH we have sufficiently established ( 163 and 164) 218 -. the indispensable necessity of keeping promises, and observ- ^d'amo^g ing treaties, the ^subject is of such importance, that we cannot nat i ns. forbear considering it here in a more general view, as inter- esting, not only to contracting parties, but likewise to all nations, and to the universal society of mankind. 2C 325 229 OF THE FAITH OF TREATIES. BOOK H. Every thing which the public safety renders inviolable is CHAP, xv. sacre( j i n society. Thus, the person of the sovereign is sacred, because the safety of the state requires that he should be in perfect security, and above the reach of violence : thus the people of Rome declared the persons of their tribunes sacred, considering it as essential to their own safety that their defenders should be screened from all violence, and even ex- empt from fear. Every thing, therefore, which the common safety of mankind and the peace and security of human so- ciety require to be held inviolable, is a thing that should be sacred among nations. 219. Trea- Who can doubt that treaties are in the number of those things that are to be held sacred by nations ? By treaties en *^ e m <>st important affairs are determined ; by them the pre- tions. tensions of sovereigns are regulated ; on them nations are to depend for the acknowledgment of their rights, and the secu- rity of their dearest interests. Between bodies politic, be- tween sovereigns who acknowledge no superior on earth, treaties are the only means of adjusting their various pre- tensions, of establishing fixed rules of conduct, of ascer- taining what they are entitled to expect, and what they have to depend on. But treaties are no better than empty words, if nations do not consider them as respectable engagements, as rules which are to be inviolably observed by sovereigns, and held sacred throughout the whole earth. 220. The The faith of treaties, that firm and sincere resolution, faith of trea- that invariable constancy in fulfilling our engagements, of ties is sa- w hi c h we make profession in a treaty, is therefore to be held sacred and inviolable between the nations of the earth, whose safety and repose it secures : and, if mankind be not wilfully deficient in their duty to themselves, infamy must ever be the portion of him who violates his faith. g 221. He He who violates his treaties, violates at the same time the who violates law of nations ; for, he disregards the faith of treaties, that vioiataHhe ^^ w ^ c ^ *^ e ^ aw ^ nat i n s declares sacred ; and, so far law of na- as depends on him, he renders it vain and ineffectual. Doubly tions. guilty, he does an injury to his ally, he does an injury to all nations, and inflicts a wound on the great society of mankind. [ 230 ] " On the observance and execution of treaties," said a re- spectable sovereign, " depends all the security which princes and states have with respect to each other : and no depend- ence could henceforward be placed in future conventions if the existing ones were not to be observed."* g 222. Right As all nations are interested in maintaining the faith of of nations treaties, and causing it to be everywhere considered as sacred against him an( j inviolable, so likewise they are justifiable in forming a confederacy for the purpose of repressing him who testifies a * Resolution of the States-General, to the Memorial of the Marquis do St. of the 15th of March, 1726, in answer Philip, Ambassador of Spain. OF THE FAITH OF TREATIES. disregard for it, who openly sports with it, who violates BOOK n. and tramples it under foot. Such a man is a public enemy . CHAP - * Y - , who saps the foundations of the peace and common safety of s rds the nations. But we should be careful not to extend this maxim [f e l * h of teea " to the prejudice of that liberty and independence to which every nation has a claim. When a sovereign breaks his treaties, or refuses to fulfil them, this does not immediately imply that he considers them as empty names, and that he disregards the faith of treaties : he may have good reasons for thinking himself liberated from his engagements ; and other sovereigns have not a right to judge him. It is the sovereign who violates his engagements on pretences that are evidently frivolous, or who does not even think it worth his while to allege any pretence whatever, to give a colourable gloss to his conduct, and cast a veil over his want of faith, it is such a sovereign who deserves to be treated as an enemy to the human race. In treating of religion, in the first book of this work, we I 223 - Tk* eould not avoid giving several instances of the enormous lflw of . na ~ abuses which the popes formerly made of their authority. la ^ d t ha There was one in particular, which was equally injurious to all popes, states, and subversive of the law of nations. Several popes have undertaken to break the treaties of sovereigns ; they carried their daring audacity so far as to release a contract- ing power from his engagements, and to absolve him from the oaths by which he had confirmed them. Cesarini, legate of pope Eugenius the Fourth, wishing to break the treaty which Uladislaus, king of Poland and Hungary, had con- cluded with the sultan Amurath, pronounced, in the pope's name, the king's absolution from his oaths.* In those times of ignorance, people thought themselves really bound by no- thing but their oaths, and they attributed to the pope the power of absolving them from oaths of every kind. Uladislaus renewed hostilities against the Turks : but that prince, in other respects worthy of a better fate, paid dearly for perfidy, or rather for his superstitious weakness : he perished, with his army, near Varna : a loss which was fatal to Christen- dom, and brought on her by her spiritual head. The follow- ing epitaph was written on Uladislaus : Romulidas Cannae, ego Varnam clade notavi. Discite, mortales, non temerare fidem. Me nisi pontifices jussissent rumpere foedus, Non ferret Scythicum Pannonis ora jugum. Pope John XII. declared null the oath which the emperor [ 231 ] Louis of Bavaria, and his competitor Frederic of Austria, had mutually taken when the emperor set the latter at liberty. Philip, duke of Burgundy, abandoning the alliance of the * History of Poland, by the Chevalier Dlugoss, Neugobauer, Sarnicki, Herburt, de Solignac, vol. iv. 112. He quotes De Fulstin, Ac. 327 231 OF THE FAITH OF TREATIES. BOOK ii. English, procured from the pope and the council of Basil an CHAP, xv. ablution f r0 m his oath. And at a time when the revival of letters, and the establishment of the Reformation should have rendered the popes more circumspect, the legate Caraffa, in order to induce Henry II. of France to a renewal of hos- tilities, had the audacity to absolve him, in 1556, from the oath he had made to observe the truce of Vaucelles.* The famous peace of Westphalia displeasing the pope on many accounts, he did not confine himself to protesting against the articles of a treaty in which all Europe was interested : he published a bull, in which, from his own certain knowledge, and full ecclesiastical power, he declared several articles of the treaty null, vain, invalid, iniquitous, unjust, condemned, reprobated, frivolous, void of force and effect ; and that no- body was bound to observe them or any of them, though they were confirmed by oath. Nor was this all : his holiness, as- suming the tone of an absolute master, proceeds thus And, nevertheless, for the greater precaution, and as much as need be, from the same motions, knowledge, deliberations, and ple- nitude of power, we condemn, reprobate, break, annul, and deprive of all force and effect, the said articles, and all the other things prejudicial to the above, ^-c.f Who does not see that these daring acts of the popes, which were formerly very frequent, were violations of the law of nations, and directly tended to destroy all the bands that could unite mankind, and to sap the foundations of their tranquillity, or to render the pope sole arbiter of their affairs ? \ 224. This But who can restrain his indignation at seeing this strange abuse au- abuse authorized by princes themselves ? In the treaty con- ^kices 1 by eluded a * Vincennes, between Charles V. king of France, and Robert Stuart, king of Scotland, in 1371, it was agreed that the pope should absolve the Scots from all the oaths they had taken in swearing to a truce with the English, and that he [ 232 ] should promise never to absolve the French or Scots from the oaths they were about to make in swearing to the new treaty.^ \ 225. Use The custom generally received in former times, of swearing of an oath ^ ^ e observance of treaties, had furnished the popes with a '' pretext for claiming the power of breaking them, by absolv- ing the contracting parties from their oaths. But, in the constitute 0t P resent ^ a 7 even children know that an oath does not con- tte obiiga- st ^ute the obligation to keep a promise or a treaty : it only tion. (128) gives an additional strength to that obligation, by calling God * On these facts, see the French and out a previous declaration of hostili- Gcrman historians. " Thus war was ties." De Thou, lib. xvii. determined on in favour of the pope : f History of the Treaty of West- and after cardinal Caraffa, by virtue of phalia, by Father Bougeant, in 12mo. the powers vested in him by his holi- vol. vi. p. 413. ness, had absolved the king from the { Choisy's History of Charles V. p. oaths he had taken in ratification of 282. the truce, he even permitted him to (128) Paley, in his Moral Philoso- attack the emperor and his son with- phy, agrees in this view of moral obli- 328 OF THE FAITH OF TREATIES. to bear witness. A man of sense, a man of honour, does not BOOK n. think himself less bound by his word alone, by his faith once - Ap - * T ' . pledged, than if he had added the sanction of an oath. Cicero . would not have us to make much difference between a per- jurer and a liar. " The habit of lying (says that great man) paves the way to perjury. Whoever can be prevailed on to utter a falsehood, may be easily won over to commit perjury : for the man who has once deviated from the line of truth, generally feels as little scruple in consenting to a perjury as to a lie. For, what influence can the invocation of the gods have on the mind of him who is deaf to the voice of con- science ? The same punishment, therefore, which heaven has ordained for the perjurer, awaits also the liar : for it is not on account of the formula of words in which the oath is couched, but of the perfidy and villany displayed by the per- jurer in plotting harm against his neighbour, that the anger and indignation of the gods is roused."* The oath does not then produce a new obligation : it only gives additional force to the obligation imposed by the treaty, and in every thing shares the same fate with it. Where the treaty is of its own nature valid and obligatory, the oath (in itself a supererogatory obligation) is so too : but, where the treaty is void, the oath is void likewise. The oath is a personal act : it can therefore only regard ? 226. it the person of him who swears, whether he swears himself, or does not deputes another to swear in his name. However, as this act nature* of does not produce a new obligation, it makes no change in the obligations, nature of a treaty. Thus, an alliance confirmed by oath is so confirmed only with respect to him who has contracted it : but if it be a real alliance, it survives him, and passes to his successors as an alliance not confirmed by oath. For the same reason, since the oath can impose no other 1 227. it obligation than that which results from the treaty itself, it e iv . es no P re - gives no pre-eminence to one treaty, to the prejudice of those ^ that are not sworn to. And as, in case of two treaties clash- a b ov e ing with each other, the more ancient ally is to be preferred another. ( 167) ; the same rule should be observed, even though the more recent treaty has been confirmed by an oath. In the [ 232 ] same manner, since it is not allowable to engage in treaties gation. It is the modern policy to consuevit. Quis enim deprecatione restrain prospective oaths, or rather pro- deorum, non conscientiae fide commo- mises, and all extra-judicial oaths not vetur? Propterea, quse poena ab diis essential for eliciting evidence upon immortalibus perjuro, haec eadem men- past events. C. daci constituta est. Non enim ex pac- * At quid interest inter perjurum et tione verborum quibus jusjurandum mendacem? Qui mentiri solet, pejerare comprehenditur, sed ex perfidia et consuevit. Quern ego, ut mentiatur, malitia per quam insidise tenduntur inducere possum, ut pejeret, exorare alicui, dii immortales hominibus irasci facile potero : nam qui semel a veritate et succensere consuSrunt. Cicer. Ort. deflexit, hie non majori religione ad pro Q. Roscio, comoedo. perjurium quam ad mendacium perduci 42 2c2 329 233 OF THE FAITH OF TREATIES. BOOK n. inconsistent with existing ones ( 165), the circumstance of CHAP, xv. an Oa ^.j 1 w jjj no< . justify such treaties, nor give them sufficient validity to supersede those which are incompatible with them : if it had such an effect, this would be a convenient mode for princes to rid themselves of their engagements. 228. It Thus also an oath cannot give validity to a treaty that is cannot give O f its own nature invalid, justify a treaty which is in itself force to a ujyug^ or impose any obligation to fulfil a treaty, however lawfully concluded, when an occasion occurs in which the observance of it would be unlawful, as for instance, if the ally to whom succours have been promised undertakes a war that is manifestly unjust. In short, every treaty made for a dishonourable purpose ( 161), every treaty prejudicial to the state ( 160), or contrary to her fundamental laws (Book I. 265), being in its own nature void, the oath that may have been added to such a treaty is void likewise, and falls to the ground together with the covenant which it was intended to confirm. g 229. As- The asseverations used in entering into engagements are severations. f orms o f expression intended to give the greater force to pro- mises. Thus, kings promise in the most sacred manner, with good faith, solemnly, irrevocably, and engage their royal word, &c. A man of honour thinks himself sufficiently bound by his word alone : yet these asseverations are not useless, in- asmuch as they tend to prove that the contracting parties form their engagements deliberately, and with a knowledge of what they are about. Hence, consequently the violation of such engagements become the more disgraceful. With mankind, whose faith is so uncertain, every circumstance is to be turned to advantage : and since the sense of shame ope- rates more powerfully on their minds than the sentiment of duty, it would be imprudent to neglect this method. \ 230. The After what we have said above ( 162), it were unnecessary faith of to undertake in this place to prove that the faith of treaties noTdTend * ^ as no re l a ^ on * *^ e difference of religion, and cannot in any on the dif- manner depend upon it. The monstrous maxim, that no faith ference of is to be kept with heretics, might formerly raise its head amidst religion. the madness of party and the fury of superstition : but it is at present generally detested. $ 231. Pre- If the security of him who stipulates for anything in his cautions to own f avour prompts him to require precision, fulness, and wording ^ e greatest clearness in the expressions, good faith de- treaties, mands, on the other hand, that each party should express his promises clearly, and without the least ambiguity. The faith of treaties is basely prostituted by studying to couch them in vague or equivocal terms, to introduce ambiguous expressions, to reserve subjects of dispute, to overreach those with whom we treat, and outdo them in cunning and duplicity. Let the man who excels in these arts boast of his happy talents, and esteem himself a keen negotiator ; but reason and the sacred 330 OF THE FAITH OF TREATIES. 234 law of nature will class him as far beneath a vulgar cheat as BOOK n. the majesty of kings is exalted above private persons. True CHAP ' **' diplomatic skill consists in guarding against imposition, not in practising it. Subterfuges in a treaty are not less contrary to good faith. 232 - Sub - His catholic Majesty, Ferdinand, having concluded a treaty ^^ m with the archduke his son-in-law, thought he could evade it by privately protesting against the treaty : a puerile finesse ! which, without giving any right to that prince, only exposed his weakness and duplicity. The rules that establish a lawful interpretation of treaties ? 233 - Al are sufficiently important to be made the subject of a distinct jj^ 6 ^^ chapter. For the present, let us simply observe that an evi- p reta tion " dently false interpretation is the grossest imaginable violation inconsistent of the faith of treaties. He that resorts to such an expedient, with the either impudently sports with that sacred faith, or sufficiently faith . of evinces his inward conviction of the degree of moral turpitude annexed to the violation of it : he wishes to act a dishonest part, and yet preserve the character of an honest man : he is a puritanical impostor, who aggravates his crime by the addition of a detestable hypocrisy. Grotius quotes several instances of evidently false interpretations put upon treaties :* the Plateans, having promised the Thebans to restore their prisoners, restored them after they had put them to death. Pericles, having promised to spare the lives of such of the enemy as laid down their arms,f ordered all those to be killed who had iron clasps to their cloaks. A Roman general, J hav- ing agreed with Antiochus to restore him half of his fleet, caused 6ach of the ships to be sawed in two. All these in- terpretations are as fraudulent as that of Rhadamistus, who, according to Tacitus's account,|| having sworn to Mithridates that he would not employ either poison or the steel against him, caused him to be smothered under a heap of clothes. Our faith may be tacitly pledged, as well as expressly : it 234. Faith is sufficient that it be pledged, in order to become obligatory : ^titty the manner can make no difference in the case. The tacit pledged - pledging of faith is founded on a tacit consent ; and a tacit consent is that which, is, by fair deduction, inferred from our actions. Thus, as Grotius observes, whatever is included in the nature of certain acts which are agreed upon, is tacitly comprehended in the agreement : or, in other words, every thing which is indispensably necessary to give effect to the articles agreed on, is tacitly granted. If, for instance, a pro- mise is made to a hostile army who have advanced far into * De Jure Belli et Pacis, lib. ii. cap. J Q. Fabius Labeo, according to Va- xvi. \ 5. lerius Maximus ; Livy makes no men- f Literally, " laid down their iron or tion of the transaction. tteel :" hence the perfidious quibble on || Annal. lib. xii. the word iron, which cannot be so well Lib. iii. cap. xxiv. g 1. rendered in English. 235 OF SECURITIES GIVEN FOR BOOK ii. the country, that they shall be allowed to return home in CHAP, xv. sa f e ty ? ft i s manifest that they cannot be refused provisions ; for they cannot return without them. In the same manner, in demanding or accepting an interview, full security is tacitly promised. Livy justly says, that the Gallo-Greeks violated the law of nations in attacking the consul Manlius at the time when he was repairing to the place of interview to which they had invited him.* The emperor Valerian, having been defeated by Sapor, king of Persia, sent to him to sue for peace. Sapor declared that he wished to treat with the emperor in person ; and Valerian, having consented to the interview without any suspicion of fraud, was carried off by the perfidious enemy, who kept him a prisoner till his death, and treated him with the most brutal cruel ty.f Grotius, in treating of tacit conventions, speaks of those in which the parties pledge their faith by mute signs.! But we ought not to confound these two kinds of tacit conventions : for that consent which is sufficiently notified by a sign, is an express consent, as clearly as if it had been signified by the voice. Words themselves are but signs established by cus- tom : and there are mute signs which established custom renders as clear and as express as words. Thus, at the present day, by displaying a white flag, a parley is demanded, as ex- pressly as it could be done by the use of speech. Security is tacitly promised to the enemy who advances upon this invita- tion. CHAP. XVI. CHAP. XYI. OP SECURITIES GIVEN FOR THE OBSERVANCE OF TREATIES. g 235. Gua- CONVINCED by unhappy experience, that the faith of ranty. treaties, sacred and inviolable as it ought to be, does not always afford a sufficient assurance that they shall be punc- tually observed, mankind have sought for securities against perfidy, for methods, whose efficacy should not depend on the good faith of the contracting parties. A guaranty is one of these means. When those who make a treaty of peace, or any other treaty, are not perfectly easy with respect to its observance, they require the guaranty of a powerful sove- reign. The guarantee promises to maintain the conditions of the treaty, and to cause it to be observed. As he may find himself obliged to make use of force against the party who attempts to violate his promises, it is an engagement that * Livy, lib. xxxviii. cap. xxv. f The Life of Valerian in Crevior's History of the Emperors. j Lib. iii. cap. xxiv. 5. 882 THE OBSERVANCE OF TREATIES. 235 no sovereign ought to enter into lightly, and without good BOOK n. reason. Princes indeed seldom enter into it unless when they CBAP - * YI -. have an indirect interest in the observance of the treaty, or are induced by particular relations of friendship. The gua- [ 236 ] ranty may be promised equally to all the contracting parties, to some of them, or even to one alone : but it is commonly promised to all in general. It may also happen, when several sovereigns enter into a common alliance, that they all reci- procally pledge themselves to each other as guarantees for its observance. The guaranty is a kind of treaty, by which as- sistance and succours are promised to any one, in case he has need of them, in order to compel a faithless ally to fulfil his engagements. Guaranty being given in favour of the contracting powers, ? 236. it or of one of them, it does not authorize the guarantee to in- s iyes the terfere in the execution of the treaty, or to enforce the obser- ^ a r ^to vance of it, unasked, and of his own accord. If, by mutual interfere un- consent, the parties think proper to deviate from the tenor asked in the of the treaty, to alter some of the articles, or to cancel it alto- execution of gether, or if one party be willing to favour the other by a a treat y* relaxation of any claim, they have a right to do this, and the guarantee cannot oppose it. Simply bound by his pro- mise to support the party who should have reason to complain of the infraction of the treaty, he has acquired no rights for himself. The treaty was not made for him ; for, had that been the case, he would have been concerned, not merely as a guarantee, but as a principal in the contract. This obser- vation is of great importance : for care should be taken, lest, under colour of being a guarantee, a powerful sovereign should render himself the arbiter of the affairs of his neighbours, and pretend to give them law. But it is true, that, if the parties make any change in the articles of the treaty without the consent and concurrence of the guarantee, the latter is no longer bound to adhere to the guaranty ; for the treaty thus changed is no longer that which he guarantied. (129) As no nation is obliged to do any thing for another nation, g 237. Na- which that other is herself capable of doing, it naturally fol- ture of the lows that the guarantee is not bound to give his assistance except where the party to whom he has granted his guaranty is of himself unable to obtain justice. If there arises any dispute between the contracting parties respecting the sense of any article of the treaty, the guarantee is not immediately obliged to assist him in favour of whom he has given his guaranty. As he cannot engage to support injustice, he is to examine, and to search for the true sense (129) This principle of the law of viduals. 5 Barn. & Ores. 269; 2 Dowl. nations in this respect precisely applies & R. 22 ; 5 Bing. 485. C. to guaranties given by private indi- 333 236 OF SECURITIES GIVEN FOR BOOK n. of the treaty, to weigh the pretensions of him -who claims his CHAP, xvi. g uaran ty an d ? if he finds them ill founded, he may refuse to support them, without failing in his engagements. 238. The It is no less evident that the guaranty cannot impair the carmo'Thn "S^ 8 of any one who is not a party to the treaty. If, there- pair the f re > it happens that the guarantied treaty proves derogatory rights of a to the rights of those who are not concerned in it, the treaty third party, being unjust in this point, the guarantee is in no wise bound to procure the performance of it ; for, as we have shown above, he can never have incurred an obligation to support injustice. [ 237 ] This was the reason alleged by France, when, notwithstand- ing her having guarantied the famous pragmatic sanction of Charles VI., she declared for the house of Bavaria, in oppo- sition to the heiress of that emperor. This reason is incon- testably a good one, in the general view of it : and the only question to be decided at that time was, whether the court of France made a just application of it. Non nostrum inter vos tantas componere lites. I shall observe on this occasion, that, according to common usage, the term guaranty is often taken in a sense somewhat different from that we have given to it. For instance, most of the powers of Europe guarantied the act by which Charles VI. had regulated the succession to his dominions ; sove- reigns sometimes reciprocally guaranty their respective states. But we should rather denominate those transactions treaties of alliance, for the purpose, in the former case, of maintain- ing that rule of succession, and, in the latter, of supporting the possession of those states. 239. Du- The guaranty naturally subsists as long as the treaty that ration of the i s the object of it; and, in case of doubt, this ought always guaranty. ^ Q ^ p resume i ve as we ^ as ^ e w ^ P rom i ses ? as 5 f r instance, the payment of a sum of money, it is safer to demand a security than a guaranty : for the surety is bound to make good the promise in default of the principal, whereas the guarantee is only obliged to use his best endeavours to obtain a performance of the promise from him who has made it. ? 241. A nation may put some of her possessions into the hands Pawns, se- O f another, for the security of her promises, debts, or engage- 'm ments - If sne thus deposits movable property, she gives pledges. Poland formerly pledged a crown and other jewels to the sovereigns of Prussia. But sometimes towns and pro- vinces are given in pawn. If they are only pledged by a THE OBSERVANCE OF TREATIES. 237 deed which assigns them as security for a debt, they serve as BOOK n. a mortgage : if they are actually put into the hands of the ere- CHAP - XTI - ditor, or of him with whom the affair has been transacted, he holds them as pledges : and, if the revenues are ceded to him as an equivalent for the interest of the debt, the transaction is called a compact of antichresis. The right which the possession of a town or province con- 242. A fers upon him who holds it in pledge, extends no further than nation's to secure the payment of what is due to him, or the perform- j^ r ance of the promise that has been made to him. He may ^oids M** therefore retain the town or the province in his hands, till he pledge, is satisfied : but he has no right to make any change in it ; for that town, or that country, does not belong to him as pro- [ 238 ] prietor. He cannot even interfere in the government of it, beyond what is required for his own security, unless the empire, or the exercise of sovereignty, has been expressly made over to him. This last point is not naturally to be presumed, since it is sufficient for the security of the mort- gagee, that the country is put into his hands and under his power. Further, he is obliged, like every other person who has received a pledge, to preserve the country he holds as a security, and, as far as in his power, to prevent its suffering any damage or dilapidation : he is responsible for it ; and if the country is ruined through his fault, he is bound to in- demnify the state that intrusted him with the possession of it. If the sovereignty is deposited in his hands together with the country itself, he ought to govern it according to its constitution, and precisely in the same manner as the sovereign of the country was obliged to govern it ; for the latter could only pledge his lawful right. As soon as the debt is paid, or the treaty is fulfilled, the ? 243. How term of the security expires, and he who holds a town or a sheis province by this title is bound to restore it faithfully, in same state in which he received it, so far as this depends on him. But to those who have no law but their avarice, or their ambition who, like Achilles, place all their right in the point of their sword* a tempting allurement now presents itself: they have recourse to a thousand quibbles, a thousand pre- tences, to retain an important place, or a country which is conveniently situated for their purposes. The subject is too odious for us to allege examples : they are well enough known, and sufficiently numerous to convince every sensible nation, that it is very imprudent to make over such securities. But if the debt be not paid at the appointed time, or if the ? 244. treaty be not fulfilled, what has been given in security may she be retained and appropriated, or the mortgage seized, at least P^ until the debt be discharged, or a just compensation made. * Jura negat sibi nat, nihil HOB arrogat armis. HORAT. 238 OF SECURITIES GIVEN FOR The house of Savoy had mortgaged the country of Vaud to can tons of Bern and Fribourg ; and those two cantons, finding that no payments were made, had recourse to arms, and took possession of the country. The duke of Savoy, in- stead of immediately satisfying their just demands, opposed force to force, and gave them still further grounds of com- plaint : wherefore the cantons, finally successful in the con- test, have since retained possession of that fine country, as well for the payment of the debt, as to defray the expenses of the war, and to obtain a just indemnification. g 245. Finally, there is, in the way of security, another precau- Hostages. fo^ O f V ery ancient institution, and much used among nations which is, to require hostages. These are persons of conse- quence, delivered up by the promising party, to him with [ 239 ] whom he enters into an engagement, to be detained by the latter until the performance of the promises which are made to him. In this case, as well as in those above mentioned, the transaction is a pignorary contract, in which free men are delivered up, instead of towns, countries, or jewels. With respect to this contract, therefore, we may confine ourselves to those particular observations which the difference of the things pledged renders necessary. 246. What The sovereign who receives hostages has no other right right we over them than that of securing their persons, in order to have over detain them till the entire accomplishment of the promises ostages. o w hi c h they are the pledge. He may therefore take pre- cautions to prevent their escaping from him : but those pre- cautions should be moderated by humanity towards men whom he has no right to use ill ; and they ought not to be extended beyond what prudence requires. It is pleasing to behold the European nations in the pre- sent age content themselves with the bare parol of their host- ages. The English noblemen who were sent to France in that character, in pursuance of the treaty of Aix-la-Chapelle, in 1748, to stay till the restitution of Cape Breton, were solely bound by their word of honour, and lived at court, and at Paris, rather as ministers of their nation than as hostages. ? 247. Their ^k e lib er ty of the hostages is the only thing pledged : and w ^ ^ as g/ ven tnem Breaks his promise, they may be detained in captivity. Formerly they were in such cases put to death ; an inhuman cruelty, founded on an error. It was imagined that the sovereign might arbitrarily dispose of the lives of his subjects, or that every man was the master of his own life, and had a right to stake it as a pledge when he de- livered himself up as a hostage. 248. When As soon as the engagements are fulfilled, the cause for If ^ntback w kich the hostages were delivered no longer subsists : they ' then immediately become free, and ought to be restored with- out delay. They ought also to be restored, if the reason for which they were demanded does not take place : to detain 336 THE OBSERVANCE OF TREATIES. 239 them then would be to abuse the sacred faith upon which BOOK n. they are delivered. The perfidious Christiern II., king of CHAP ' XVI - Denmark, being delayed by contrary winds before Stockholm, and, together with his whole fleet, ready to perish with famine, made proposals of peace : whereupon, the adminis- trator, Steno, imprudently trusting to his promises, furnished the Danes with provisions, and even gave Gustavus and six other noblemen as hostages for the safety of the king, who pretended to have a desire to come on shore : but, with the first fair wind, Christiern weighed anchor, and carried off the hostages ; thus repaying the generosity of his enemy by an infamous act of treachery.* Hostages being delivered on the faith of treaties, and he 249. Whe- who receives them promising to restore them as soon as the ther the y promise of which they are the surety shall be fulfilled, such ^n ed e on e ~ engagements ought to be literally accomplished : and the any ot her hostages should be really and faithfully restored to their for- account mer condition, as soon as the accomplishment of the promise has disengaged them. It is, therefore, not allowable to de- tain them for any other cause ; and I am astonished to find [ 240 ] that some learned writers teach a contrary doctrine.f They ground their opinion upon the principle which authorizes a sovereign to seize and detain the subjects of another state in order to compel their rulers to do him justice. The prin- ciple is true ; but the application is not just. These authors seemed to have overlooked the circumstance, that, were it not for the faith of the treaty by virtue of which the hostage has been delivered, he would not be in the power of that sove- reign, nor exposed to be so easily seized ; and that the faith of such a treaty does not allow the sovereign to make any other use of his hostage than that for which he was intended, or to take advantage of his detention beyond what has been expressly stipulated. The hostage is delivered for the secu- rity of a promise, and for that alone. As soon, therefore, as the promise is fulfilled, the hostage, as we have just observed, ought to be restored to his former condition. To tell him that he is released as a hostage, but detained as a pledge for the security of any other pretension, would be taking advan- tage of his situation as a hostage, in evident violation of the spirit and even the letter of the convention, according to which, as soon as the promise is accomplished, the hostage is to be restored to himself and his country, and reinstated in his pristine rank, as if he had never been a hostage. With- out a rigid adherence to this principle, it would no longer be safe to give hostages, since princes might, on every occasion, easily devise some pretext for detaining them. Albert the Wise, duke of Austria, making war against the city of Zurich, * History of the Revolutions of Sweden. | Grotius, lib. iii. cap. xx. 55. Wolfius, Jus Gent. 503. 43 2 D 337 240 OF SECURITIES GIVEN FOR BOOK n. in the year 1351, the two parties referred the decision of their CHAP, xvr. ^p^es to arbitrators, and Zurich gave hostages. The arbi- trators passed an unjust sentence, dictated by partiality. Zurich, nevertheless, after having made a well-grounded com- plaint on the subject, determined to submit to their decision. But the duke formed new pretensions, and detained the hos- tages,* contrary to the faith of the compromise, and in evident contempt of the law of nations. 250. They But a hostage may be detained for his own actions, for may be de- crimes committed, or debts contracted in the country while he SSTowii * s * n hostage there. This is no violation of the faith of the actions. treaty. In order to be sure of recovering his liberty, accord- ing to the terms of the treaty, the hostage must not claim a right to commit, with impunity, any outrages against the na- tion by which he is kept ; and when he is about to depart, it is just that he should pay his debts. f 251. Of It is the party who gives the hostages that is to provide the support for their support ; for, it is by his order, and for his service, of hostages, ^at ^gy are j n nos t a ge. He who receives them for his own security is not bound to defray the expense of their subsist- ence, but simply that of their custody, if he thinks proper to [ 241 1 se ^ a g uar( l ver them. g 252. A The sovereign may dispose of his subjects for the service subject can- O f the state ; he may, therefore, give them also as hostages ; ie to and the person who is nominated for that purpose is bound e a ostage. ^ o bey, as he is, on every other occasion, when commanded for the service of his country. But, as the expenses ought to be borne equally by the citizens, the hostage is entitled to be defrayed and indemnified at the public charge. It is, evidently, a subject alone who can be given as a hos- tage against his will. With a vassal, the case is otherwise. What he owes to the sovereign, is determined by the condi- tions of his fief; and he is bound to nothing more. Accord- ingly, it is a decided point that a vassal cannot be constrained- to go as a hostage, unless he be at the same time a subject. Whoever has a power to make treaties or conventions, may give and receive hostages. For this reason, not only the sovereign, but also the subordinate authorities, have a right to give hostages in the agreements they make, according to the powers annexed to their office, and the extent of their commission. The governor of a town, and the besieging general, give and receive hostages for the security of the capitulation: whoever is under their command is bound to obey, if he is nominated for that purpose. | 253. Rank Hostages ought naturally to be persons of consequence, of the host- gince they are required as a security. Persons of mean con- es - dition would furnish but a feeble security, unless they were given in great numbers. Care is commonly taken to settle * Tschudi, voL L p. 421. THE OBSERVANCE OF TREATIES. 241 the rank of the hostages that are to be delivered ; and the BOOK n. violation of a compact in this particular is a flagrant derelic- CHAP ' XVI> tion of good faith and honour. It was a shameful act of perfidy in La Trimouille to give the Swiss only hostages from the dregs of the people, instead of four of the principal citi- zens of Dijon, as had been stipulated in the famous treaty we mentioned above ( 212). Sometimes the principal per- sons of the state, and even princes, are given in hostage. Francis I. gave his own sons as security for the treaty of Madrid. The sovereign who gives hostages ought to act ingenuously 2 2 J 4 - The y in the affair, giving them in reality as pledges of his word, ^^^J and, consequently, with the intention that they should be kept esc apc. till the entire accomplishment of his promise. He cannot, therefore, approve of their making their escape : and, if they take such a step, so far from harbouring them, he is bound to send them back. The hostage, on his side, conformably to the presumed intention of his sovereign, ought faithfully to remain with him to whom he is delivered, without endea- vouring to escape. Cloelia made her escape from the hands of Porsenna, to whom she had been delivered as a hostage ; but the Romans sent her back, that they might not incur the guilt of violating the treaty.* [ 242 ] If the hostage happens to die, he who has given him is not % 255. whe- obliged to replace him, unless this was made a part of the ther a host - agreement. The hostage was a security required of him:*? e e g T g ofco that security is lost without any fault on his side ; and there replaced, exists no reason why he should be obliged to give another. If any one substitutes himself for a time in the place of a 258. Of hostage, and the hostage happens in the interim to diea llimwho natural death, the substitute is free: for, in this case, things ^ f f \ are -to be replaced in the same situation in which they would hostage, have been if the hostage had not been permitted to absent himself and substitute another in his stead : and, for the same reason, the hostage is not free by the death of him who has taken his place only for a time. It would be quite the con- trary, if the hostage had been exchanged for another : the former would be absolutely free from all engagement ; and the person who had taken his place would alone be bound. If a prince who has been given in hostage succeeds to the ? 257. A crown, he ought to be released on the delivery of another bost *s c su<: - sufficient hostage, or a number of others, who shall together JJ^Vn. constitute an aggregate security equivalent to that which he himself afforded when he was originally given. This is evi- dent from the treaty itself, which did not import that the king should be a hostage. The detention of the king's per- son by a foreign power is a thing of too interesting a nature to admit a presumption that the state had intended to expose * Et Romani pignus pacis ex fcedere restituerunt. Tit Liv. lib. ii. cap. xiii. 242 SECURITIES GIVEN FOR THE OBSERVANCE OF TREATIES. BOOK n. herself to the consequences of such an event. Good faith _CHAP. XVI ' ought to preside in all conventions ; and the manifest or justly presumed intention of the contracting parties ought to be adhered to. If Francis I. had died after having given his sons as hostages, certainly the dauphin should have been released : for, he had been delivered only with a view of re- storing the king to his kingdom ; and, if the emperor had detained him, that view would have been frustrated, since the king of France would still have been a captive. It is evi- dent, that, in this reasoning, I proceed on the supposition that no violation of the treaty has taken place on the part of the state which has given a prince in hostage. In case that state had broken its promise, advantage might reasonably be taken of an event which rendered the hostage still more valuable, and his release the more necessary. 258. The The liability of a hostage, as that of a city or a country, liability of ex pi re s with the treaty which it was intended to secure mST ( 243 > 248 ) : and consequently, if the treaty is personal, the treaty, the hostage is free at the moment when one of the contract- ing powers happens to die. g 259. The The sovereign who breaks his word after having given host- violation of ages, does an injury, not only to the other contracting power, but also to the hostages themselves. For, though subjects are indeed bound to obey their sovereign who gives them in hostages, hostage, that sovereign has not a right wantonly to sacrifice [ 243 ] their liberty, and expose their lives to danger without just reasons. Delivered up as a security for their sovereign's promise, not for the purpose of suffering any harm, if he entails misfortune on them by violating his faith, he covers himself with double infamy. Pawns and mortgages serve as securities for what is due ; and their acquisition indemnifies the party to whom the other fails in his engagements. Host- ages are rather pledges of the faith of him who gives them ; and it is supposed that he would abhor the idea of sacrificing, innocent persons. But, if particular conjunctures oblige a sovereign to abandon the hostages, if, for example, the party who has received them violates his engagements in the first instance, and, in consequence of his violation, the treaty can no longer be accomplished without exposing the state to danger, no measure should be left untried for the delivery of those unfortunate hostages ; and the state cannot refuse to compensate them for their sufferings, and to make them amends, either in their own persons, or in those of their relatives. g 260. The At the moment when the sovereign who has given the hwrtMN* 6 hostage nas violated his faith, the latter ceases to retain the whence character of a hostage, and becomes a prisoner to the party who has who had received him, and who has now a right to detain him given him in in perpetual captivity. But it becomes a generous prince to fails in his re f ram f rom an ex ertion of his rights at the expense of an 340 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. 243 innocent individual. And as the hostage is no longer bound BOOK n. by any tie to his own sovereign who has perfidiously aban-- CHAP ' " doned him, if he chooses to transfer his allegiance to the engage- prince who is now the arbiter of his fate, the latter may ac- ments - quire a useful subject, instead of a wretched prisoner, the troublesome object of his commiseration. Or he may liberate and dismiss him, on settling with him the conditions. We have already observed that the life of a hostage can- 261. Of not be lawfully taken away on account of the perfidy of the the ri 8 ht party who has delivered him. The custom of nations, the " d m d u most constant practice, cannot justify such an instance of barbarous cruelty, repugnant to the law of nature. Even at a time when that dreadful custom was but too much autho- rized, the great Scipio publicly declared that he would not suffer his vengeance to fall on innocent hostages, but on the persons themselves who had incurred the guilt of perfidy, and that he was incapable of punishing any but armed enemies.* The emperor Julian made the same declaration, f All that such a custom can produce, is impunity among the nations who practice it. Whoever is guilty of it cannot complain that another is so too : but every nation may and ought to declare that she considers the action as a barbarity injurious to human nature. CHAP. XVII. [ 244 ] OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. (130) CHAP. XTII. IF the ideas of men were always distinct and perfectly g 262. Ne- (L'terminate, if, for the expression of those ideas, they had cessity of none but proper words, no terms but such as were clear, pre- establisl \ 5n s cise, and susceptible only of one sense, there would never J^r e tltbn. * Tit. Liv. lib. xxviii. cap. xxxiv. the same. (Ephinstone v. Sedreechund, t See Grotius, lib. iii. cap. xi. 18, Knapp's Rep. 340 ; Undo v. Rodney, not - 2 - Dougl. 313.) Political treaties be- (130) See further as to the construe- tween a foreign state and subjects of tion of treaties, post B. IV. Ch. III. 32, the crown of Great Britain, acting as post, 443. This chapter is highly an independent state under the powers important to be studied, in relation to granted by charter and act of parlia- questions respecting the construction ment, are not a subject of municipal of private contracts, statutes, &c., as jurisdiction: therefore, a bill founded well as of treaties, as many of the rules on such treaties by the nabob of Arcot are capable of general application, against the East India Company, was Questions respecting the conduction, dismissed. (Nabob of Carnatic v. East infraction, or observance of treaties, are India Company, 2 Ves. jun. 56 ; and not in general directly agitated in any see in general, Hill v. Reardon, 2 Sim. municipal court of law or equity of & Stu. 437; Jacob, Rep. 84; 2 Russ. Great Britain, at least as regards the Rep. 608 633; confirming the gene- adjustment of any claims between the ral rule, but admitting the jurisdiction respective states who were parties to of a court of equity, where there has 2 D 2 341 244 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK II, CHAP. X be any difficulty in discovering their meaning in the words lil by which they intended to express it : nothing more would be necessary than to understand the language. But, even on been a truit.) But, collaterally, courts of law very frequently have to discuss and to construe and give effect to trea- ties, as regards the private rights of.^ subjects ; and, after ascertaining the par- ticular object of the treaty, the courts then construe it nearly by the same rules as affect contracts between private individuals. (Per Eyre, C. J. in Mar- ryatt v. Wikon, 1 Bos. & Pul. 436 439. And see in general, as to the construc- tion of treaties, Marriott's case of Dutch ship, 12, 13, Ac.) One general rule to be ever kept in view is, that it is the essence of a definitive treaty of peace that the commercial friendly in- tercourse of the contracting powers must be replaced in its former state. (2 Chalmer's Opinion, 849.) Vattel, in pages 244274, elabo- rately lays down several rules for con- struing treaties. In a learned opinion upon the subject, it has been well ob- served, that treaties, being in their nature compacts superseding the com- mon usage, which is, strictly speaking, the law of nations, by particular stipu- lations, are to be argued upon the foot- ing of all obligations which arise from contract, expressed or tacit, whether quasi ex contractu, or necessarily implied by general words of comprehension ; and the principles of the civil law de obligationibiu, which is the law admitted by all nations in Europe, by most in their domestic and by all in national questions, must be allowed to arbitrate in deciding the validity, existence, and meaning of a public treaty, by the same rules and reasonings as when applied to any other contract of private life. Words or characters are merely used to convey, by marks or sounds, the ideas of consent, and to preserve the memory of compacts: now, the end being thus principally to be considered, and the means being regarded only as declarative of the end, if by any other means than by strict words a contract is implied, it is undoubtedly valid when- ever there appears, from any acts or reasonable interpretations of signs, an acknowledged consent, and equitable foundations of contracting; these cir- cumstances making the very substance of a contract. (Sir James Marriott's Opinion on the Duration of the Treaty of Neutrality in 1686, in Chalmer's 342 Collect, of Opinions, vol. 2, 345, 346.) Therefore, the rules of customary con- tracts between private individuals may in general be called in aid. However, in debating any question upon treaties arising between nation and nation, in the age we live in, it is necessary to keep in view the general state and con- dition of the contracting powers, from whence the arguments of public law can only be drawn with any just deci- sion. (2 Chalmer's Col. Op. 347.) It has also been considered that a general commercial treaty, not limited by its terms to a particular time, is only sus- pended by a war; and that, upon the return of peace, it will tacitly revive by implication, unless there be an express declaration to the contrary. (2 Chal- mer's Col. Op. 344355.) In the great case of Marryatt v. Wikon, upon the construction of the treaty between Great Britain and the United States, in error in the Exchequer Chamber, Eyre, Ch. J., after observing that a treaty should be construed liberally, and con- sistent with the good faith which al- ways distinguishes a great nation, said, that courts of law, although not the expounders of a treaty, yet when it is brought under their consideration in- cidentally, they must say how the treaty is to be understood between the parties to the action, and in doing which, they have but one rule by which to govern themselves. We are to construe this treaty as we would construe any other instrument, public or private ; we are to collect from the nature of the subject, from the words and the context, the true intent and meaning of the contracting parties, whether they are A. and B., or happen to be two independent states. (Per Eyre, Ch. J., in Marryatt v. Wilson, 1 Bos. & Pul. 436 439. j The United States v. Arredondo et al., 6 Peters' S. C. Rep. 610.} With respect to the general rules for construing private contracts, and which equally apply to treaties, see cases collected, Chitty on Bills, 8 ed. 190194. Paley on Moral Phil. 126. The editor has purposely refrained from fortifying the excellent rules laid down in the context, by numerous instances, feeling that thatattemptmightratheren- cumber than improve this edition. C. OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. 244 this supposition, the art of interpretation would still not be BOOK n. useless. In concessions, conventions, and treaties, in all con- CHAP, xvn. tracts, as well as in the laws, it is impossible to foresee and point out all the particular cases that may arise ; we decree, we ordain, we agree upon certain things, and express them in general terms ; and, though all the expressions of a treaty should be perfectly clear, plain, and determinate, the true in- terpretation would still consist in making, in all the particular cases that present themselves, a just application of what has been decreed in a general manner. But this is not all : conjectures vary, and produce new kinds of cases, that can- not be brought within the terms of the treaty or the law, except by inferences drawn from the general views of the contracting parties, or of the legislature. Between different clauses, there will be found contradictions and inconsistencies, real or apparent ; and the question is, to reconcile such clauses, and point out the path to be pursued. But the case is much worse if we consider that fraud seeks to take advantage even of the imperfection of language, and that men designedly throw obscurity and ambiguity into their treaties, in order to be provided with a pretence for eluding them upon occasion. It is therefore necessary to establish rules founded on reason, and authorized by the law of nature, capable of diffusing light over what is obscure, of determining what is uncertain, and of frustrating the views of him who acts with duplicity in forming the compact. Let us begin with those that tend par- ticularly to this last end, with those maxims of justice and equity which are calculated to repress fraud, and to prevent the effect of its artifices. The first general maxim of interpretation is, that It is not 263. 1st allowable to interpret what has no need of interpretation. s eneral When a deed is worded in clear and precise terms, when "aiiow- its meaning is evident, and leads to no absurd conclusion, a bie to in- there can be no reason for refusing to admit the meaning terpret what which such deed naturally presents. To go elsewhere i n has . noneed search of conjectures, in order to restrict or extend it, is but t an attempt to elude it. If this dangerous method be once admitted, there will be no deed which it will not render use- less. However luminous each clause may be, however clear and precise the terms in which the deed is couched, all this [ 245 ] will be of no avail, if it be allowed to go in quest of extrane- ous arguments, to prove that it is not to be understood in the sense which it naturally presents.* Those cavillers who dispute the sense of a clear and deter- (131) See the same maxim, Paley's * Standum omnino est iis, quae verbis Moral Philos. 126 ; Chit, on Bills, 8 ed. expressis, quorum manifestus est sig- 190 to 194. There is another rule, (post, nificatus, indicata fuerunt, nisi omnem 443, 32), to construe against the party a negotiis humanis certitudinem re- prescribing the terms of treaty, or the movere volueris. WOLF. Jus Nat par superior. vii. n. 822. 343 245 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK n. minate article, are accustomed to seek their frivolous subter- fuges in the pretended intentions and views which they attri- CHAP. 264. 2d k u t e to its author. It would be very often dangerous to enter inaxim 1 - if "with them into the discussion of those supposed views that are he who not pointed out in the piece itself. The following rule is better could and calculated to foil such cavillers, and will at once cut short all ought to chicanery: If he who could, and ought to have explained ^hdiied*" himself clearly and fully has not done it, it is the worse for himself has him : he cannot be allowed to introduce subsequent restrictions not done it, which he has not expressed. This is a maxim of the Roman it is to his i aw : Pactionem obscurant Us nocere in quorum fuit potestate n^nt? 6 *"" leg em apertius conscribere.* The equity of this rule is glar- ingly obvious, and its necessity is not less evident. There will be no security in conventions, no stability in grants or concessions, if they may be rendered nugatory by subsequent limitations, which ought to have been originally specified in the deed, if they were in the contemplation of the contract- ing parties. f 265. 3d The third general maxim or principle on the subject of in- general terpretation is, that Neither the one nor the other of the parties maxim: interested in the contract has a riaht to interpret the deed or neither of j* * i* j? TT< /? *. vu the con- treaty according to his oivn fancy, lor if you are at liberty trading par- to affix whatever meaning you please to my promise, you will ties has a have the power of obliging me to do whatever you choose, nght to m- con t r ary to my intention, and beyond my real engagements : treatTac- an( ^> on * ne t ner hand, if I am allowed to explain my pro- cording to mises as I please, I may render them vain and illusory, by his own giving them a meaning quite different from that which they fancy. presented to you, and in which you must have understood them at the time of your accepting them. 266. 4th On every occasion when a person could and ought to have general made known his intention, we assume for true against him xim: what he has sufficiently declared. This is an incontestable e- principle, applied to treaties : for, if they are not a vain play tiared, is to of words, the contracting parties ought to express themselves be taken for in them with truth, and according to their real intentions. *" If the intention which is sufficiently declared were not to be taken of course as the true intention of him who speaks and enters into engagements, it would be perfectly useless to form contracts or treaties. \ 267. We But it is here asked, which of the contracting parties ought ought to at- to have his expressions considered as the more decisive, with tend rather regpect to tne true mean ing of the contract, whether we to the words , r . , , . , - , '. , , of the per- should lay a greater stress on the words of him who makes son promis- the promise, than on those of the party who stipulates for its ing, than to performance. As the force and obligation of every contract * Digest, lib. ii. tit xiv. de Pactis, nocere potius debere venditori qui id leg. 39. See likewise Digest, lib. xviii. dixerit, quam emptori ; quia potuit n tit i. de Contrahenda Emptione, leg. integra apertius dicere. 21. Labeo scripsit obscuritatem paoti 344 OF THE INTERPRETATION OP TREATIES. 246 arise from a perfect promise, and the person who makes BOOK n. the promise is no further engaged than his will is sufficiently CHAP - XY1I> declared, it is very certain, that, in order to discover the those of . the true meaning of the contract, attention ought principally to Jj^ 7 stlpu * be paid to the words of the promising party. For, he volun- tarily binds himself by his words ; and we take for true against him what he has sufficiently declared. This question seems to have originated from the manner in which conventions are sometimes made : the one party offers the conditions, and the other accepts them ; that is to say, the former proposes what he requires that the other shall oblige himself to perform, and the latter declares the obligations into which he really enters. If the words of him who accepts the conditions bear relation to the words of him who offers them, it is certainly true that we ought to lay our principal stress on the expres- sions of the latter : but this is because the person promising is considered as merely repeating them in order to form his promise. The capitulations of besieged towns may here serve us for an example. The besieged party proposes the condi- tions on which he is willing to surrender the place : the be- sieger accepts them : the expressions of the former lay no obligation on the latter, unless so far as he adopts them. He who accepts the conditions is in reality the promising party ; and it is in his words that we ought to seek for the true mean- ing of the articles, whether he has himself chosen and formed his expressions, or adopted those of the other party, by refer- ring to them in his promise. But still we must bear in mind the maxim above laid down, viz., that what he has sufficiently declared is to be taken as true against him. I proceed to explain myself more particularly on this subject. In the interpretation of a treaty, or of any other deed what- \ 268. 5th soever, the question is, to discover what the contracting parties general have agreed upon, to determine precisely, on any particular ^ i ^ e occasion, what has been promised and accepted, that is to^ on r ^jg ht say, not only what one of the parties intended to promise, to be made but also what the other must reasonably and candidly have according to supposed to be promised to him, what has been sufficiently ce j tein declared to him, and what must have influenced him in his ac- ru ceptance. Every deed, therefore, and every treaty, must be interpreted by certain fixed rules calculated to determine its meaning, as naturally understood by the parties concerned at the time when the deed was drawn up and accepted. This is a fifth principle. As these rules are founded on right reason, and are conse- quently approved and prescribed by the law of nature, every man, every sovereign, is obliged to admit and to follow them. Unless certain rules be admitted for determining the sense in which the expressions are to be taken, treaties will be only empty words ; nothing can be agreed upon with security, and 44 345 247 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK n. it will be almost ridiculous to place any dependence on the CHAP, xvii. e g- ect O f conventions. 269. The But, as sovereigns acknowledge no common judge, no su- faith of perior that can oblige them to adopt an interpretation founded treaties lays on j ug ru \ es ^ ^ ne f a ith of treaties constitutes in this respect tton'tofoi- a ^ * ne security of the contracting powers. That faith is no low these less violated by a refusal to admit an evidently fair interpre- ruies. tation, than by an open infraction. It is the same injustice, the same want of good faith ; nor is its turpitude rendered less odious by being choked up in the subtilties of fraud. 270. Ge- Let us now enter into the particular rules on which the rai rule of interpretation ought to be formed, in order to be just and interpreta- g^ gi nC e the sole object of the lawful interpretation of a deed ought to be the discovery of the thoughts of the author or authors of that deed, whenever we meet with any obscu- rity in it, we are to consider what probably ivere the ideas of those who drew up the deed, and to interpret it accordingly. This is the general rule for all interpretations. It particu- larly serves to ascertain the meaning of particular expressions whose signification is not sufficiently determinate. Pursuant to this rule, we should take those expressions in their utmost latitude when it seems probable that the person speaking had in contemplation every thing which, in that extensive sense, they are capable of designating : and, on the other hand, we ought to restrict their meaning, if the author appears to have confined his idea to what they comprehend in their more limited signification. Let us suppose that a husband has be- queathed to his wife all his money. It is required to know whether this expression means only his ready money, or whe- ther it extends also to that which is lent out, and is due on notes and other securities. If the wife is poor, if she was beloved by her husband, if the amount of the ready money be inconsiderable, and the value of the other property greatly superior to that of the money both in specie and in paper, there is every reason to presume that the husband meant to bequeath to her as well the money due to him as that actu- ally contained in his coffers. On the other hand, if the woman be rich, if the amount of the ready specie be very consider- able, and the money due greatly exceeds in value all the other property, the probability is, that the husband meant to bequeath to his wife his ready money only. By the same rule, we are to interpret a clause in the utmost latitude that the strict and appropriate meaning of the words will admit, if it appears that the author had in view every thing which that strict and appropriate meaning comprehends : but we must interpret it in a more limited sense when it ap- pears probable that the author of the clause did not mean to extend it to every thing which the strict propriety of the terms might be made to include. As, for instance, a father, who has an only son, bequeaths to the daughter of his friend 346 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. 248 all his jewels. He has a sword enriched with diamonds, BOOK n. given him by a sovereign prince. In this case it is certainly CHAP ' XYn * very improbable that the testator had any intention of making over that honorable badge of distinction to a family of aliens. That sword, therefore, together with the jewels with which it is ornamented, must be excepted from the legacy, and the meaning of the words be restricted to his other jewels. But, if the testator has neither son nor heir of his own name, and bequeaths his property to a stranger, there is no reason to limit the signification of the terms : they should be taken in their full import, it being probable that the testator used them in that sense. The contracting parties are obliged to express themselves g 271. The in such manner that they may mutually understand each tenns ar f to other. This is evident from the very nature of the transac- be e f xplai ? d m , , ' , . conformably tion. Those who form the contract concur m the same in- to comimm tentions ; they agree in desiring the same thing ; and how usage, shall they agree in this instance, if they do not perfectly understand each other ? Without this, their contract will be no better than a mockery or a snare. If, then, they ought to speak in such a manner as to be understood, it is necessary that they should employ the words in their proper signifi- cation, the signification which common usage has affixed to them, and that they annex an established meaning to every term, every expression they make use of. They must not, designedly and without mentioning it, deviate from the common usage and the appropriate meaning of words : and it is presumed that they have conformed to established custom in this particular, as long as no cogent reasons can be ad- duced to authorize a presumption to the contrary ; for, the presumption is, in general, that things have been done as they ought. From all these incontestable truths, results this rule : In the interpretation of treaties, compacts, and promises, we ought not to deviate from the common use of the language, unless we have very strong reasons for it. In all human affairs, where absolute certainty is not at hand to point out the way, we must take probability for our guide. In most cases, it is extremely probable that the parties have expressed themselves conformably to the established usage : and such probability ever affords a strong presumption, which cannot be overruled but by a still stronger presumption to the con- trary. Camden* gives us a treaty, in which it is expressly said that the treaty shall be precisely understood according to the force and appropriate signification of the terms. After such a clause, we cannot, under any pretence, deviate from the proper meaning which custom has affixed to the terms, the will of the contracting parties being thereby formally de- clared in the most unambiguous manner. * History of Queen Elizabeth. 347 284 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK n. The usage we here speak of is that of the time when the CHAP. xvn. .,.,. ^ or tne deed, of whatever kind, was drawn up and con- l 272. in- eluded. Languages incessantly vary, and the signification oTa^cient 11 an( ^ f rce f words change with time. When, therefore, an treaties. ancient deed is to be interpreted, we should be acquainted with the common use of the terms at the time when it was [ 249 ] written ; and that knowledge is to be acquired from deeds of the same period, and from contemporary writers, by dili- gently comparing them with each other. This is the only source from which to derive any information that can be de- pended on. The use of the vulgar languages being, as every one knows, very arbitrary, etymological and grammatical investigations, pursued with a view to discover the true im- port of a word in common usage, would furnish but a vain theory, equally useless and destitute of proof. g 273. Of Words are only designed to express the thoughts : thus, quibbles on the true signification of an expression in common use is the words. ^ Q& w hich custom has affixed to that expression. It is then a gross quibble to affix a particular sense to a word, in order to elude the true sense of the entire expression. Mahomet, emperor of the Turks, at the taking of Negropont, having promised a man to spare" his head, caused him to be cut in two through the middle of the body. Tamerlane, after having engaged the city of Sebastia to capitulate, under his promise of shedding no blood, caused all the soldiers of the garrison to be buried alive :* gross subterfuges which, as Cicero re- marks,t only serve to aggravate the guilt of the perfidious wretch who has recourse to them. To spare the head of any one, and to shed no blood, are expressions which, according to common custom, and especially on such an occasion, mani- festly imply to spare the lives of the parties. $ 274 A All these pitiful subtilties are overthrown by this unerring rule on this ru i e . When we evidently see what is the sense that agrees with subject. jj ie i n t en n on O f ih e contracting parties, it is not allowable to wrest their words to a contrary meaning. The intention, sufficiently known, furnishes the true matter of the conven- tion, what is promised and accepted, demanded and granted. A violation of the treaty is rather a deviation from the inten- tion which it sufficiently manifests, than from the terms in which it is worded : for the terms are nothing without the intention by which they must be dictated. g 275. Men- Is it necessary, in an enlightened age, to say that mental tai reserva- reservations cannot be admitted in treaties ? This is mani- tions. f eg ^ gince, by the very nature of the treaty, the parties are * See Puffendorf's Law of Nature thing of the perfidy which others and Nations, book v. chap. xii. g 3. attribute to him. La Croix, in his Hist, of Timurbec, f Fraus enim adstringit, non dis- book v. chap. xv. speaks of this cruelty solvit perjurium. Do Offic. lib. iii, of Timurbec, or Tamerlane, towards chap, xxxii. 4000 Armenian horsemen, but says no- OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. 249 bound to express themselves in such manner that they may BOOS n. mutually understand each other ( 271). There is scarcely CHAP X JL T - an individual now to be found who would not be ashamed of building upon a mental reservation. What can be the use of such an artifice, unless to lull the opposite party into a false security, under the vain appearance of a contract ? It is, then, a real piece of knavery. Technical terms, or terms peculiar to the arts and sciences, $ 276. In- ought commonly to be interpreted according to the definition terpretation given of them by masters of the art, or persons versed in the e ^ hnical knowledge of the art or science to which the terms belong. I r 250 "] say commonly, for this rule is not so absolute but that we may and even ought to deviate from it, when we have good rea- sons for such deviation; as, for instance, if it were proved that he who speaks in a treaty, or in any other deed, did not understand the art or science from which he borrowed the term, that he was unacquainted with its import as a techni- cal word, that he employed it in a vulgar acceptation, &c. If, however, the technical or other terms relate to things $ 277. Of that admit of different degrees, we ought not scrupulously to terms whose adhere to definitions, but rather to take the terms in a sense ^J^ on agreeable to the context ; for a regular definition describes a a eo . rees . thing in its most perfect state ; and yet it is certain that we do not always mean it in that state of its utmost perfection, whenever we speak of it. Now, the interpretation should only tend to the discovery of the will of the contracting parties ( 268) : to each term, therefore, we should affix that meaning which the party whose words we interpret probably had in contemplation. Thus, when the parties in a treaty have agreed to submit their pretensions to the decision of two or three able civilians, it would be ridiculous to endeavour to elude the compromise under the pretence that we can find no civilian accomplished in every point, or to strain the terms so far as to reject all who do not equal Cujas or Grotius. Would he who had stipulated for the assistance of ten thousand good troops, have any reason to insist upon soldiers of whom the very worst should be comparable to the veterans of Julius Csesar ? And if a prince had promised his ally a good gene- ral, must he send him none but a Marlborough or a Turenne ? There are figurative expressions that are become so familiar 278. Of in the common use of language, that, in numberless instances, figurative they supply the place of proper terms, so that we ought to ex P ressions - take them in a figurative sense, without paying any attention to their original, proper, and direct signification : the subject of the discourse sufficiently indicates the meaning that should be affixed to them. To hatch a plot, to carry fire and sword into a country,* are expressions of this sort; and there * The French expression, "oudir wie of a web,-" "fire and word," literally, trame," which is rendered " hatch a "fire and steel," (or iron). plot," literally signifies, " to lay the warp 2E 349 250 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK n. scarcely can occur an instance where it would not be absurd CHAP. XYII. tn ta j, e t j iein J Q tne - r Direct an( j literal sense. 279. Of There is not perhaps any language that does not also con- equivocal tain words which signify two or more different things, and expressions. ph rases w hich are susceptible of more than one sense. Thence arises ambiguity in discourse. The contracting parties ought carefully to avoid it. Designedly to use it with a view to elude their engagements in the sequel, is downright perfidy, since the faith of treaties obliges the contracting parties f 251 1 to express their intentions clearly ( 271). But, if an am- biguous expression has found its way into a deed, it is the part of the interpreter to clear up any doubt thereby occa- sioned. g 280. The The following is the rule that ought to direct the interpre- ruie for tation in this as well as in the preceding case : we ought these two always to affix such meanings to the expressions as is most suitable to the subject or matter in question. For, by a true interpretation, we endeavour to discover the thoughts of the persons speaking, or of the contracting parties in a treaty. Now, it ought to be presumed that he who has employed a word which is susceptible of many different significations, has taken it in that which agrees with his subject. In proportion as he employs his attention on the matter in question, the terms proper to express his thoughts present themselves to his mind ; this equivocal word could therefore only present itself in the sense proper to express the thoughts of him who makes use of it, that is, in the sense agreeable to the subject. It would be a feeble objection to this, to allege that a man sometimes designedly employs equivocal expressions, with a view of holding out ideas quite different from his real thoughts, and that, in such case, the sense which agrees with the sub- ject is not that which corresponds with the intention of the person speaking. We have already observed, that, whenever a man can and ought to make known his intention, we assume for true against him what he has sufficiently declared ( 266). And as good faith ought to preside in conventions, they are always interpreted on the supposition that it actually did pre- side in them. Let us illustrate this rule by examples. The word day is understood of the natural day, or the time dur- ing which the sun affords us his light, and of the civil day, or the space of twenty-four hours. When it is used in a con- vention to point out a space of time, the subject itself mani- festly shows that the parties mean the civil day, or the term of twenty-four hours. It was therefore a pitiful subterfuge, or rather a notorious perfidy, in Cleomenes, when, having concluded a truce of some days with the people of Argos, and finding them asleep on the third night, in reliance on the faith of the treaty, he killed a part of their number, and made the rest prisoners, alleging that the nights were not 350 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. 251 comprehended in the truce.* The word steel may be under- BOOK n. stood of the metal itself, or of certain instruments made of CHAP - XYn - it : in a convention which stipulates that the enemy shall lay down their steel, it evidently means their weapons: where- fore, Pericles, in the example related above ( 233), gave a fraudulent interpretation to those words, since it was con- trary to what the nature of the subject manifestly pointed out. Q. Fabius Labeo, of whom we made mention in the same section, showed equal dishonesty in the interpretation of his treaty with Antiochus ; for, a sovereign who stipulates that the half of his fleet or of his vessels shall be restored to [ 252 ] him, undoubtedly means that the other party shall restore to him vessels which he can make use of, and not the half of each vessel when sawed into two. Pericles and Fabius are also condemned by the rule established above ( 274), which forbids us to wrest the sense of the words contrary to the evident intention of the contracting parties. If any one of those expressions which are susceptible of dif- \ 281. Not ferent significations occurs more than once in the same piece, necessai r to ive cannot make it a rule to take it everywhere in the same ^aa. signification. For, we must, conformably to the preceding se nso every- rule, take such expression, in each article, according as the where in subject requires, pro substrata materia, as the masters of the the same art say. The word day, for instance, has two significations, ee as we have just observed ( 280). If therefore it be said in a convention, that there shall be a truce of fifty days, on con- dition that commissioners from both parties shall, during eight successive days, jointly endeavour to adjust the dispute, the fifty days of the truce are civil days of twenty-four hours ; but it would be absurd to understand them in the same sense in the second article, and to pretend that the commissioners should labour eight days and nights without intermission. Every interpretation that leads to an absurdity ought to be % 282. We rejected ; or, in other words, we should not give to any piece u & ht to re- a meaning from which any absurd consequences would follow, ^^retL but must interpret it in such a manner as to avoid absurdity. tionThat*" As it is not to be presumed that any one means what is a b- leads to an surd, it cannot be supposed that the person speaking intended ^urdUy. that his words should be understood in a manner from which an absurdity would follow. Neither is it allowable to pre- sume that he meant to indulge a sportive levity in a serious deed : for what is shameful and unlawful is not to be pre- sumed. We call absurd not only what is physically impossible, but what is morally so, that is to say, what is so contrary to reason that it cannot be attributed to a man in his right senses. Those fanatic Jews who scrupled to defend them- selves when the enemy attacked them on the Sabbath day, gave an absurd interpretation to the fourth commandment, * Puffendorf, lib. v. cap. xii. J 7. 351 252 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK n. Why did they not also abstain from dressing, walking, and CHAP, xvir. eat i n g v These also are "tvorks," if the term be strained to its utmost rigour. It is said that a man in England married three wives, in order that he might not be subject to the pe- nalty of the law which forbids marrying two. This is doubt- less a popular tale, invented with a view to ridicule the ex- treme circumspection of the English, who will not allow the smallest departure from the letter in the application of the law. That wise and free people have too often seen, by the experience of other nations, that the laws are no longer a firm barrier and secure defence, when once the executive power is allowed to interpret them at pleasure. But surely they do not mean that the letter of the law should on any occasion be strained to a sense that is manifestly absurd. The rule we have just mentioned is absolutely necessary, and ought to be followed, even when the text of the law 01 [ 253 ] treaty does not, considered in itself, present either obscurity or ambiguity in the language. For, it must be observed, that the uncertainty of the sense we are to give to a law or a treaty, does not solely proceed from the obscurity or other defect in the expression, but also from the limited nature of the human mind, which cannot foresee all cases and circumstances, nor take in at one view all the consequences of what is decreed or promised, and, finally, from the impossibility of entering into that immense detail. Laws and treaties can only be worded in a general manner ; and it is the interpreter's pro- vince to apply them to particular cases, conformably to the intention of the legislature, or of the contracting powers. Now, we are not in any case to presume that it was their in- tention to establish an absurdity : and therefore, when their expressions, taken in their proper and ordinary meaning, would lead to absurd consequences, it becomes necessary to deviate from that meaning, just so far as is sufficient to avoid absurdity. Let us suppose a captain has received orders to advance in a right line with his troops to a certain post : he finds a precipice in his way: surely his orders do not oblige him to leap headlong down : he must, therefore, deviate from the right line, so far as is necessary to avoid the precipice, but no further. The application of the rule is more easy, when the expres- sions of the law or of the treaty are susceptible of two differ- ent meanings. In this case we adopt without hesitation that meaning from which no absurdity follows. In the same manner, when the expression is such that we may give it a figurative sense, we ought doubtless to do this, when it becomes neces- sary, in order to avoid falling into an absurdity. \ 283. And It is not to be presumed that sensible persons, in treating that which together, or transacting any other serious business, meant ct Mil and *^ at t ^ ie result f t ^ e ^ r proceedings should prove a mere nul- lity. The interpretation, therefore, which would render a OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. 253 treaty null and inefficient, cannot be admitted. We may con- BOOK n. sider this rule as a branch of the preceding ; for, it is a kind CHAP - xyn - of absurdity to suppose that the very terms of a deed should void of ef * reduce it to mean nothing. It ought to be interpreted in such fect * a manner as that it may have its effect, and not prove vain and nugatory : and in this interpretation we proceed accord- ing to the mode pointed out in the foregoing section. In both cases, as in all interpretations, the question is, to give the words that sense which ought to be presumed most con- formable to the intention of the parties speaking. If many different interpretations present themselves, by which we can conveniently avoid construing the deed into a nullity or an absurdity, we are to prefer that which appears the most agree- able to the intention of those who framed the deed : the par- ticular circumstances of the case, aided by other rules of in- terpretation, will serve to point it out. Thucydides relates,* that the Athenians, after having promised to retire from the [ 254 ] territories of the Boeotians, claimed a right to remain in the country under pretence that the lands actually occupied by their army did not belong to the Boeotians ; a ridiculous quibble, since, by giving that sense to the treaty, they re- duced it to nothing, or rather to a puerile play. The terri- tories of the BoBotians should evidently have been construed to mean all that was comprised within their former boundaries, without excepting what the enemy had seized during the war. If he who has expressed himself in an obscure or equivocal 284. Ob- manner has spoken elsewhere more clearly on the same sub- scure . ex v ject, he is the best interpreter of his own words. We ought^ 6 ^^ ^" to interpret his obscure or equivocal expressions in such a b y others manner that they may agree with those clear and unequivocal clear terms which he has elsewhere used, either in the same deed, in the same or on some other similar occasion. In fact, while we have no aut or ' proof that a man has changed his mind or manner of think- ing, it is presumed that his thoughts have been the same on similar occasions ; so that, if he has anywhere clearly shown his intention with respect to a certain thing, we ought to affix the same meaning to what he has elsewhere obscurely said on the same subject. Let us suppose, for instance, that two allies have reciprocally promised each other, in case of ne- cessity, the assistance of ten thousand foot soldiers, who are to be supported at the expense of the party that sends them, and that, by a posterior treaty, they agree that the number of the auxiliary troops shall be fifteen thousand, without men- tioning their support : the obscurity or uncertainty which re- mains in this article of the new treaty, is dissipated by the clear and express stipulation contained in the former one. As the allies dp not give any indication that they have changed their minds with respect to the support of the auxi- * Lib. iv. cap. xcviii. 45 2 E 2 353 254 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK n. liary troops, we are not to presume any such change ; and CHAP. xvn. t nose fift een thousand men are to be supported as the ten thousand promised in the first treaty. The same holds good, and with much stronger reason, when there is question of two articles of the same treaty, when, for example, a prince promises to furnish ten thousand men, paid and maintained at his own expense, for the defence of the states of his ally, and in another article, only promises four thousand men, in case that ally be engaged in an offensive war. g 285. in- It frequently happens, that, with a view to conciseness, terpretation p e0 pj e express imperfectly, and with some degree of obscu- thTconne^. r ^ v > things which they suppose to be sufficiently elucidated tion of the by the preceding matter, or which they intend to explain in discourse, the sequel : and moreover, words and expressions have a different force, sometimes even a quite different signification, according to the occasion, their connection, and their rela- tion to other words. The connection and train of the dis- course is therefore another source of interpretation. We must consider the whole discourse together, in order perfectly to conceive the sense of it, and to give to each expression, not so much the signification which it may individually admit of, as that which it ought to have from the context and spirit [ 255 ] of the discourse. Such is the maxim of the Roman law, Incivile est, nisi totd lege perspectd, und aliqud particuld ejus propositd, judicare, vel respondere.* $ 286. in- The very connection and relation of the things in ques- terpretation tion help also to discover and establish the true sense of a drawn n f " treaty, or of any other piece. The interpretation ought to tioVand^e- ^ e ma ^ e * n 8UC ^ a manner, that all the parts may appear lation of consonant to each other, that what follows may agree with the things what preceded, unless it evidently appear, that, by the subse- themseives. q uen t clauses, the parties intended to make some alteration in the preceding ones. For it is to be presumed that the authors of a deed had a uniform and steady train of think- ing, that they did not aim at inconsistencies and contradic- tions, but rather that they intended to explain one thing by another, and, in a word, that one and the same spirit reigns throughout the same production or the same treaty. Let us render this more plain by an example. A treaty of alliance declares, that, in case one of the allies be attacked, each of the others shall assist him with a body of ten thou- sand foot, paid and supported; and in another article, it is said that the ally who is attacked shall be at liberty to de- mand the promised assistance in cavalry rather than in in- fantry. Here we see, that, in the first article, the allies have determined the quantum of the succour, and its value, that of ten thousand foot ; and, in the latter article, without ap- pearing to intend any variation in the value or number, they * Digest, lib. i. tit iii. De Legibus, leg. 24. 354 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. 255 the nature of the succours to the choice of the party BOOK . who may stand in need of them. If, therefore, the ally who CHAP - XYIT - is attacked calls upon the others for cavalry, they will give him, according to the established proportion, an equivalent to ten thousand foot. But if it appears that the intention of the latter article was, that the promised succours should in certain cases be augmented, if, for instance, it be said, that, in case one of the allies happen to be attacked by an enemy of considerably superior strength, and more powerful in cavalry, the succours should be furnished in cavalry, and not in infantry, it appears that, in this case, the promised assistance ought to be ten thousand horse. As two articles in one and the same treaty may bear rela- tion to each other, two different treaties may in like manner have a relative connection ; and, in this case, each serves to explain the other. For instance, one of the contracting par- ties has, in consideration of a certain object, promised to deliver to the other ten thousand sacks of wheat. By a sub- sequent agreement, it is determined, that, instead of wheat, he shall give him oats. The quantity of oats is not ex- pressed ; but it is determined by comparing the second con- vention with the first. If there be no circumstance to prove that it was the intention of the parties, in the second agree- ment, to diminish the value of what was to be delivered, we are to understand a quantity of oats proportioned to the price of ten thousand sacks of wheat ; but if it evidently [ 256 ] appears from the circumstances and motives of the second convention, that it was their intention to reduce the value of what was due under the former agreement, in this case, ten thousand sacks of oats are to be substituted in lieu of the ten thousand sacks of wheat. The reason of the law, or of the treaty, that is to say, g 287. in- the motive which led to the making of it, and the object in terpretation contemplation at the time, is the most certain clue to lead f <> unded on us to the discovery of its true meaning ; and great attention should be paid to this circumstance, whenever there is ques- tion either of explaining an obscure, ambiguous, indetermi- nate passage in a law or treaty, or of applying it to a parti- cular case. When once we certainly know the reason which alone has determined the will of the person speaking, we ought to interpret and apply his words in a manner suitable to that reason alone. Otherwise he will be made to speak and act contrary to his intention, and in opposition to his own views. Pursuant to this rule, a prince, who, on grant- ing his daughter in marriage, has promised to assist his in- tended son-in-law in all his wars, is not bound to give him any assistance if the marriage does not take place. But we ought to be very certain that we know the true and only reason of the law, the promise, or the treaty. In matters of this nature, it is not allowable to indulge in vague 256 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK n. CHAP. XYI and uncertain conjectures, and to suppose reasons and views YII. w j iere there are none certainly known. If the piece in ques- tion is in itself obscure, if, in order to discover its meaning, we have no other resource than the investigation of the au- thor's views, or the motives of the deed, we may then have recourse to conjecture, and, in default of absolute certainty, adopt as the true meaning, thut which has the greatest de- gree of probability on its side. But it is a dangerous abuse, to go, without necessity, in search of motives and uncertain views, in order to wrest, restrict, or extend the meaning of a deed which is of itself sufficiently clear, and carries no ab- surdity on the face of it. Such a procedure is a violation of that incontestable maxim, that it is not allowable to in- terpret what has no need of interpretation ( 263). Much less are we allowed, when the author of a piece has in the piece itself declared his reasons and motives, to attribute to him some secret reason, which may authorize us in giving an interpretation repugnant to the natural meaning of the expressions. Even though he should have entertained the views which we attribute to him, yet, if he has concealed them, and announced different ones, it is upon the latter alone that we must build our interpretation, and not upon those which the author has not expressed : we assume, % as true, against him, what he has sufficiently declared ( 266).' g 288. We ought to be the more circumspect in this kind of inter- Where pretation, as it frequently happens that several motives con- n y hlve~ cur to determine the will of the party who speaks in a law or concurred a promise. Perhaps the combined influence of all those to determine motives was necessary in order to determine his will ; per- the will. na p S each one O f them, taken individually, would have been [ 257 ] sufficient to produce that effect. In the former case, if ive are perfectly certain that it was only in consideration of several concurrent reasons and motives that the legislature or the con- tracting parties consented to the law or the contract, the inter- pretation and application ought to be made in a manner agreeable to all those concurrent reasons, and none of them must be overlooked. But in the latter case, when it is evi- dent that each of the reasons which have concurred in deter- mining the will was sufficient to produce that effect, so that the author of the piece in question would, by each of the rea- sons separately considered, have been induced to form the same determination which he has formed upon all the reasons taken in the aggregate, his words must be so interpreted and applied, as to make them accord with each of those reasons taken individually. Suppose a prince has promised certain advantages to all foreign Protestants and artisans who will come and settle in his estates : if that prince is in no want of subjects, but of artisans only, and if, on the other hand, it appears that he does not choose to have any other subjects than Protestants, his promise must be so interpreted, as to 356 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. 257 relate only to such foreigners as unite those two characters, BOOK n. of Protestants and artisans. But if it is evident that this CHAP. XVH. prince wants to people his country, and that, although he would prefer Protestant subjects to others, he has in particu- lar so great a want of artisans, that he would gladly receive them, of whatever religion they be, his words should be taken in a disjunctive sense, so that it will, be sufficient to be either a Protestant or an artisan, in order to enjoy the pro- mised advantages. To avoid tedious and complex circumlocution, we shall make 289. What use of the term, "sufficient reason for an act of the will," to constitutes express whatever has produced that act, whatever has de- reasorTfor termined the will on a particular occasion, whether the will an act of the has been determined by a single reason, or by many concur- will, rent reasons. That sufficient reason, then, will be sometimes found to consist in a combination of many different reasons, so that, where a single one of those reasons is wanting, the sufficient reason no longer exists : and in those cases where we say that many motives, many reasons, have concurred to determine the will, yet so as that each in particular would have been alone capable of producing the same effect, there will then be many sufficient reasons for producing one single act of the will. Of this we see daily instances. A prince, for example, declares war for three or four injuries received, each of which would have been sufficient to have produced the declaration of war. The consideration of the reason of a law or promise not 290. Ex- only serves to explain the obscure or ambiguous expressions tensive in- which occur in the piece, but also to exteod or restrict its torpretation several provisions independently of the expressions, and in the reason conformity to the intention and views of the legislature or the of the act. contracting parties, rather than to their words. For, accord- [ 258 ] ing to the remark of Cicero,* the language, invented to explain the will, ought not to hinder its effect. When the sufficient and only reason of a provision, either in a law or a promise, is perfectly certain and well understood, we extend that provision to cases to which the same reason is applicable, although they be not comprised within the signification of the terms. This is what is called extensive interpretation. It is commonly said, that we ought to adhere rather to the spirit than to the letter. Thus, the Mohammedans justly extend the prohibition of wine, in the Koran, to all intoxicating liquors ; that dangerous quality being the only reason that could in- duce their legislator to prohibit the use of wine. Thus, also, if, at the time when there were no other fortifications than walls, it was agreed not to enclose a certain town with walls, * Quid 1 verbis satis hoc cautum mur. Quia non potest, verba reperta erat 1 ? Minime. Qua res igitur valuit 7 sunt, non quae impedirent, sed qua in- Voluntas : quse si, tacitis nobis, intel- dicarent voluntatem. Cicer. Orat pro ligi posset, verbis omnino non utere- Csecina. 367 258 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK n. it would not be allowable to fortify it with fosses and ram- C.HAP. xvn ' parts, since the only view of the treaty evidently was, to prevent its being converted into a fortified place. But we should here observe the same caution above recom- mended ( 287), and even still greater, since the question re- lates to an application in no wise authorized by the terms of the deed. We ought to be thoroughly convinced that we know the true and only reason of the law or the promise, and that the author has taken it in the same latitude which must be given to it in order to make it reach the case to which we mean to extend the law or promise in question. As to the rest, I do not here forget what I have said above ( 268), that the true sense of a promise is not only that which the person promising had in his mind, but also that which has been sufficiently declared, that which both the contracting parties must reasonably have understood. In like manner, the true reason of a promise is that which the contract, the nature of the things in question, and other circumstances, sufficiently indicate : it would be useless and ridiculous to allege any by-views which the person might have secretly entertained in his own mind. g 291. The rule just laid down serves also to defeat the pretexts Frauds and pitiful evasions of those who endeavour to elude laws or *iud 1D f * * rea *^ es - Grood-faith adheres to the intention : fraud insists or promises. on ^ e terms, when it thinks that they can furnish a cloak for its prevarications. The isle of Pharos near Alexandria was, with other islands, tributary to the Rhodians. The latter having sent collectors to levy the tribute, the queen of Egypt amused them for some time at her court, using in the mean while every possible exertion to join Pharos to the main land by means of moles : after which she laughed at the Rhodians, and sent them a message, intimating that it was very unrea- t sonable in them to pretend to levy on the main land a tribute which they had no title to demand except from the islands.* [ 259 ] There existed a law which forbade the Corinthians to give ves- sels to the Athenians : they sold them a number at five drachmae each.f The following was an expedient worthy of Tiberius : custom not permitting him to cause a virgin to be strangled, he ordered the executioner first to deflower the young daughter of Sejanus, and then to strangle her.J To violate the spirit of the law while we pretend to respect the letter, is a fraud no less criminal than an open violation of it : it is equally repugnant to the intention of the law-maker, and only evinces a more artful and deliberate villany in the person who is guilty of it. Restrictive interpretation, which is the reverse of extensive * Puffendorf, lib. v.cap.xii. 18. He f Puffend. ibid. Herodotus, lib. ri. quotes Ammianus Marcellinus, lib. xxii. Five drachmae amounted to little more cap. xvi. than three shillings sterling. t Tacit. Annal. lib. v. 9. 358 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. 259 interpretation, is founded on the same principle. As we ex- BOOK ir. tend a clause to those cases, which, though not comprised CHAP - XYir - within the meaning of the terms, are nevertheless comprised 2 92. Re- in the intention of that clause, and included in the reasons strictive in- that produced it, in like manner, we restrict a law or a pro- terpretation. mise, contrary to the literal signification of the terms, our judgment being directed by the reason of that law or that promise : that is to say, if a case occurs, to which the well known reason of a law or promise is utterly inapplicable, that case ought to be excepted, although, if we were barely to con- sider the meaning of the terms, it should seem to fall within the purvieio of the law or promise. It is impossible to think of every thing, to foresee every thing, and to express every thing : it is sufficient to enounce certain things in such a manner as to make known our thoughts concerning things of which we do not speak : and, as Seneca the rhetorician says,* there are exceptions so clear, that it is unnecessary to express them. The law condemns to suffer death whoever strikes his father: shall we punish him who has shaken and struck his father, to recover him from a lethargic stupor? Shall we punish a young child, or a man in a delirium, who has lifted his hand against the author of his life ? In the former case the reason of the law does not hold good ; and to the two latter it is inapplicable. We are bound to restore what is intrusted to us : shall I restore what a robber has intrusted to me, at the time when the true proprietor makes himself known to me, and demands his property ? A man has left his sword with me : shall I restore it to him, when, in a trans- port of fury, he demands it for the purpose of killing an inno- cent person ? We have recourse to restrictive interpretation, in order to 293. Its avoid falling into absurdities (see 282). A man bequeaths use, in order his house to one, and to another his garden, the only entrance * a T ld *'" into which is through the house. It would be absurd to sup- s pose that he had bequeathed to the latter a garden into into what is which he could not enter : we must therefore restrict the unlawful. pure and simple donation of the house, and understand that it was given only upon condition of allowing a passage to the [ 260 ] garden. The same mode of interpretation is to be adopted, whenever a case occurs, in which the law or the treaty, if in- terpreted according to the strict meaning of the terms, would lead to something unlawful. On such an occasion, the case in question is to be excepted, since nobody can ordain or promise what is unlawful. For this reason, though assist- ance has been promised to an ally in all his wars, no assist- ance ought to be given him when he undertakes one that is manifestly unjust. When a case arises in which it would be too severe and too * lab. iv. Declam. xxvii. 359 260 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK ii. prejudicial to any one to interpret a law or a promise accord- CHAP. XYH. j n g to the rigour of the terms, a restrictive interpretation 294. Or is then also used, and we except the case in question, agree- what is too a bly to the intention of the legislature, or of him who made burden*"" 1 *^ e P rom ^ se : f r * ne legislature intends only what is just *om~ and equitable ; and, in contracts, no one can enter into such engagements in favour of another, as shall essentially super- sede the duty he owes to himself. It is then presumed with reason, that neither the legislature nor the contracting parties have intended to extend their regulations to cases of this nature, and that they themselves, if personally present, would except them. A prince is no longer obliged to send succours to his allies, when he himself is attacked, and has need of all his forces for his own defence. He may also, without the slightest imputation of perfidy, abandon an alliance, when, through the ill success of the war, he sees his state threatened with impending ruin if he does not immediately treat with the enemy. Thus, towards the end of the last century, Victor Amadeus, duke of Savoy, found himself under the necessity of separating from his allies, and of receiving law from France, to avoid losing his states. The king his son would have had good reasons to justify a separate peace in the year 1745 ; but upheld by his courage, and animated by just views of his true interest, he embraced the generous resolution to struggle against an extremity which might have dispensed with his persisting in his engagements. 295. How We have said above ( 280), that we should take the ex- it ought to preggiong j n the sense that agrees with the subject or the signification ma tter. Restrictive interpretation is also directed by this agreeably to rule. If the subject or the matter treated of will not allow the subject, that the terms of a clause should be taken in their full extent, we should limit the sense according as the subject requires. Let us suppose that the custom of a particular country con- fines the entail of fiefs to the male line properly so called : if an act of enfeoffment in that country declares that the fief is given to a person for himself and his male descendants, the sense of these last words must be restricted to the males descending from males ; for the subject will not admit of our understanding them also of males who are the issue of females, though they are reckoned among the male descendants of the first possessor. g 296. How The following question has been proposed and debated : & change Whether promises include a tacit condition of the state of fntheTtate a ^ rs continuing the same, or whether a change happen- of things i n g m the state of affairs can create an exception to the pro- may form mise, and even render it void ?" The principle derived from an excep- the reason of the promise must solve the question. If it be tion * certain and manifest that the consideration of the present state of things was one of the reasons which occasioned the promise, that the promise was made in consideration or in OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. 261 consequence of that state of things, it depends on the pre- BOOK n. servation of things in the same state. This is evident, since CHAr - xvn - the promise was made only upon that supposition. When therefore that state of things which was essential to the pro- mise, and without which it certainly would not have been made, happens to be changed, the promise falls to the ground when its foundation fails. And in particular cases, where things cease for a time to be in the state that has produced or concurred to produce the promise, an exception is to be made to it. An elective prince, being without issue, has pro- mised to an ally that he will procure his appointment to the succession. He has a son born : who can doubt that the pro- mise is made void by this event ? He who in a time of peace has promised succours to an ally, is not bound to give him any when he himself has need of all his forces for the de- fence of his own dominions. A prince, possessed of no very formidable power, has received from his allies a promise of faithful and constant assistance, in order to his aggran- dizement, in order to enable him to obtain a neighbouring state by election or by marriage : yet those allies will have just grounds for refusing him the smallest aid or support, and even forming an alliance against him, when they see him elevated to such a height of power as to threaten the liberties of all Europe. If the great Gustavus had not been killed at Lutzen, cardinal de Richelieu, who had concluded an alliance for his master with that prince, and who had invited him into Germany, and assisted him with money, would perhaps have found himself obliged to traverse the designs of that conqueror, when become formidable, to set bounds to his astonishing progress, and to support his humbled enemies. The states- general of the United Provinces conducted themselves on these principles in 1668. In favour of Spain, which before had been their mortal enemy, they formed the triple alliance against Louis XIV. their former ally. It was necessary to raise a barrier to check the progress of a power which threat- ened to inundate and overwhelm all before it. But we ought to be very cautious and moderate in the ap- plication of the present rule : it would be a shameful perver- sion of it, to take advantage of every change that happens in the state of affairs, in order to disengage ourselves from our promises : were such conduct adopted, there could be no dependence placed on any promise whatever. That state of things alone, in consideration of which the promise was made, is essential to the promise : and it is only by a change in that state, that the effect of the promise can be lawfully prevented [ 262 ] or suspended. Such is the sense in which we are to under- stand that maxim of the civilians, conventio omnis intelligitur rebus sic stantibus. What we say of promises, must also be understood as ex- tending to laws. A law which relates to a certain situation 43 2 F 361 262 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK ii. of affairs can only take place in that situation. We ought to CHAP. XYII. reason in the same manner with respect to a commission. Thus, Titus being sent by his father to pay his respects to the emperor, turned back on being informed of the death of Galba. 297. In- In unforeseen cases, that is to say, when the state of things terpretation happens to be such as the author of a deed has not foreseen, of a deed m an( j C0ll [ft not nave thought of\ we should rather be guided by unforeseen 7- .... ,7 IT- 7 i j. * 1 cases. nis intention than by his words, and interpret the instrument as he himself would interpret it if he were on the spot, or conformably to what he would have done if he had foreseen the circumstances which are at present known. This rule is of great use to judges, and to all those in society who are appointed to carry into effect the testamentary regulations of the citizens. A father appoints by will a guardian for his children, who are under age. After his death the magistrate finds that the guardian he has nominated is an extravagant profligate, without property or conduct : he therefore dis- misses him, and appoints another, according to the Roman laws,* adhering to the intention of the testator, and not to his words ; for it is but reasonable to suppose, and we are to presume it as a fact, that the father never intended to give his children a guardian who should ruin them, and that he would have nominated another, had he known the vices of the person he appointed. 298. Rea- When the things which constitute the reason of a law or sons arising convention are considered, not as actually existing^, but simply lossibHit as P 08S ible, or, in other words, when the fear of an event is ancTnot'the the reason of a law or a promise, no other cases can be ex- existence of cepted from it than those in which it can be proved to demon- a thing. stration that the event is really impossible. The bare possi- bility of the event is sufficient to preclude all exceptions. If, for instance, a treaty declares that no army or fleet shall be conducted to a certain place, it will not be allowable to conduct thither an army or a fleet, under pretence that no harm is in- tended by such a step : for the object of a clause of this nature is not only to prevent a real evil, but also to keep all danger at a distance, and to avoid even the slightest subject of un- easiness. It is the same with the law which forbids walking the streets by night with a lighted torch or candle. It would be an unavailing plea for the transgression of that law to allege that no mischief has ensued, and that he carried his torch with such circumspection that no ill consequence was to be apprehended. The bare possibility of causing a confla- [ 263 ] gration was sufficient to have rendered it his duty to obey the law ; and he has transgressed it by exciting fears which it was the intention of the legislature to prevent. 299. Ex- At the beginning of this chapter, we observed that men's * Digest, lib. xxvi. tit. iii. De Confirm. Tutor, leg. 10. 362 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. 263 ideas and language are not always perfectly determinate. BOOK n. There is, doubtless, no language in which there do not occur CHAP.XVII. expressions, words, or entire phrases, susceptible of a more or capable of less extensive signification. Many a word is equally appli- anexte . ns i ve cable to the genus or the species : the word fault implies ^J^ 1 1 *" intentional guilt or simple error : several species of animals have but one name common to both sexes, as partridge, lark, sparrow, &c. ; when we speak of horses, merely with a view to the services they render to mankind, mares also are com- prehended under that name. In technical language a word has sometimes a more and sometimes a less extensive sense, than in vulgar use : the word death, among civilians, signifies not only natural death, but also civil death : verbum, in the Latin grammar, signifies only that part of speech called the verb; but, in common use, it signifies any word in general. Frequently, also, the same phrase implies more things on one occasion, and fewer on another, according to the nature of the subject or matter: thus, when we talk of sending suc- cours, sometimes we understand a body of auxiliary troops maintained and paid by the party who sends them, at other times a body whose expenses are to be entirely defrayed by the party who receives them. It is therefore necessary to establish rules for the interpretation of those indeterminate expressions, in order to ascertain the cases in which they are to be understood in the more extensive sense, and those in which they are to be restricted to their more limited meaning. Many of the rules we have already given may serve for this purpose. But it is to this head that the famous distinction, between 300. Of things of & favourable and those of an odious nature, particu- tnin s s fe - larly belongs. Some writers have rejected the distinction,*^^' doubtless for want of properly understanding it. In fact, odious, the definitions that have been given of what is favourable and what is odious, are not fully satisfactory, nor easily applied. After having maturely considered what the most judicious authors have written on the subject, I conceive the whole of the question to be reducible to the following positions, which convey a just idea of that famous distinction. When the N provisions of a law or a convention are plain, clear, determi- nate, and attended with no doubt or difficulty in the applica- tion, there is no room for any interpretation or comment (263). The precise point of the will of the legislature or the con- tracting parties, is what we must adhere to. But if their ex- pressions are indeterminate, vague, or susceptible of a more or less extensive sense, if that precise point of their inten- tion cannot, in the particular case in question, be discovered and fixed by the other rules of interpretation, we must pre- sume it according to the laws of reason and equity : and, for * See Barbeyrac's remarks on Grotius and Puffendorf. 363 264 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK n. this purpose, it is necessary to pay attention to the nature of CHAP. XYII. th e things to which the question relates. There are certain things of which equity admits the extension, rather than the restriction ; that is to say, that, with respect to those things, the precise point of the will not being discovered in the ex- pressions of the law or the contract, it is safer atd more con- sistent with equity, to suppose and fix that point in the more extensive, than in the more limited sense of the terms ; to give a latitude to the meaning of the expressions, than to restrict it. These are the things called favourable. Odious things, on the other hand, are those, of which the restriction tends more certainly to equity than the extension. Let us figure to ourselves the intention or the will of the legislature or the contracting parties, as a fixed point. At that point precisely should we stop, if it be clearly known ; if uncer- tain, we should at least endeavour to approach it. In things favourable, it is better to pass beyond that point, than not tc reach it ; in things odious, it is better not to reach it, than to pass beyond it. 301. What it w in no t now be difficult to show, in general, what things common'ad- are f avoura ble, an( i what are odious. In the first place, evert/ vantage.and thing that tends to the common advantage in conventions, or to equality, that has a tendency to place the contracting parties on a foot- is favour- j n g O f equality, is favourable. The voice of equity, and the contra is g enera l ru ^ e f contracts, require that the conditions between odious. the parties should be equal. We are not to presume, without very strong reasons, that one of the contracting parties in- tended to favour the other to his own prejudice ; but there is no danger in extending what is for the common advantage. If, therefore, it happens that the contracting parties have not made known their will with sufficient clearness, and with all the necessary precision, it is certainly more conformable to equity to seek for that will in the sense most favourable to equality and the common advantage, than to suppose it in the contrary sense. For the same reason, every thing that is not for the common advantage, every thing that tends to destroy the equality of a contract, every thing that onerates only one of the parties, or that onerates the one more than the other, is odious. In a treaty of strict friendship, union, and alliance, every thing which, without being burdensome to any of the parties, tends to the common advantage of the confederacy, and to draw the bonds of union closer, is favourable. In unequal treaties, and especially in unequal alliances, all the clauses of inequality, and principally those that onerate the inferior ally, are odious. Upon this principle, that we ought in case of doubt to extend what leads to equality, and restrict what destroys it, is founded that well-known rule Incom- moda vitantis melior quam commoda petentis est causa,* * Quintilun, Instit. Orai. lib. vii. cap. iv. OF THE INTERPRETATION OP TREATIES. 264 the party who endeavours to avoid a loss has a better cause to BOOK u. support than he who aims at obtaining an advantage. CHAP, xvn. All those things which, without proving too burdensome to 302. What any one in particular, are useful and salutary to human so- is useful to ciety, are to be ranked in the class of favourable things : for a ^ ai j s 8 ^ nation is already under a natural obligation with respect to v^urabL *" things of this nature : so that if she has entered into any the contrary particular engagements of this kind, we run no risk in giving is odious, those engagements the most extensive meaning of which they [ 265 ] are susceptible. Can we be afraid of violating the rules of equity by following the law of nature, and giving the utmost extent to obligations that tend to the common advantage of mankind ? Besides, things which are useful to human society are, from that very circumstance, conducive to the common advantage of the contracting parties, and are consequently favourable (see the preceding section). On the other hand, let us consider as odious every thing that is, in its own nature, rather injurious than useful to mankind. Those things which have a tendency to promote peace are favourable ; those that lead to war are odious. Every thing that contains a penalty, is odious. With re- 303. What- spect to the laws, it is universally agreed, that, in case of ev . er con- doubt, the judge ought to incline to the merciful side, and ^" s ^J 6 " that it is indisputably better to suffer a guilty person to escape, odious! 8 than to punish one who is innocent. Penal clauses in trea- ties lay a burden upon one of the parties ; they are there- fore odious ( 301). Whatever tends to render a deed void and ineffectual, either 304. in the whole, or in part, and consequently, whatever introduces Whatever any change in things already agreed upon, is odious : for J^Jj^J is men treat together with a view to their common benefit ; and odious, if I enjoy any particular advantage acquired by a lawful con- tract, I must not be deprived of it except by my own renun- ciation. When, therefore, I consent to new clauses that seem to derogate from it, I can lose my right only so far as I have clearly given it up ; and consequently these new clauses are to be understood in the most limited sense they will admit of; as is the case in things of an odious nature ( 300). If that which tends to render a deed void and ineffectual is con- tained in the deed itself, it is evident that such passages ought to be construed in the most limited sense, in the sense best calculated to preserve the deed in force. We have al- ready seen, that we should reject every interpretation which tends to render a deed void and ineffectual ( 283). Whatever tends to change the present state of things is 305. also to be ranked in the class of odious things : for the pro- Whatever prietor cannot be deprived of his right, except so far, pre- H J ^ ft cisely, as he relinquishes it on his part ; and, in case of doubt, p rese nt state the presumption is in favour of the possessor. It is less re- of things, is pugnant to equity to withhold from the owner a possession odious ; the 2 F 2 365 265 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK ii. which he has lost through his own neglect, than to strip the CHAP. XTII. just possessor of what lawfully belongs to him. In the inter- contrary is pretation, therefore, we ought rather to hazard the former in- favourable, convenience than the latter. Here also may be applied, in many cases, the rule we have mentioned in 301, that the party who endeavours to avoid a loss, has a better cause to support than he who aims at obtaining an advantage. 306. Finally, there are things which are at once of a favourable Things of a or an odious nature, according to the point of view in which mixed na- they are considered. Whatever derogates from treaties, or t " re ' changes the state of things, is odious ; but if it is conducive L ^vv J ^ Q p eac6) j t j Sj j n that particular, favourable. A degree of odium always attaches to penalties : they may, however, be viewed in a favourable light on those occasions when they are particularly necessary for the safety of society. When there is question of interpreting things of this nature, we ought to consider whether what is favourable in them greatly exceeds what appears odious, whether the advantage that arises from their being extended to the utmost latitude of which the terms are susceptible, will materially outweigh the severe and odious circumstances attending them ; and if that is the case, they are to be ranked in the class of favourable things. Thus, an inconsiderable change in the state of things, or in conven- tions, is reckoned as nothing, when it procures the inesti- mable blessings of peace. In the same manner, penal laws may be interpreted in their most extensive meaning, on cri- tical occasions, when such an instance of severity becomes necessary to the safety of the state. Cicero caused the ac- complices of Catiline to be executed by virtue of a decree of the senate, the safety of the republic rendering it improper to wait till they should be condemned by the people. But where there is not so great a disproportion in the case, and where things are in other respects equal, favour inclines to that side of the question which presents nothing odious ; that is to say, we ought to abstain from things of an odious nature, unless the attendant advantage so far exceed the odi- ous part as in a manner to conceal it from view. If there be any appearance, however small, of an equilibrium between the odious and the favourable in one of those things of a mixed nature, it is ranked in the class of odious things, by a natural consequence drawn from the principle on which we have founded the distinction between things of a favourable and things of an odious nature ( 300), because, in case of doubt, we should, in preference, pursue that line of conduct by which we are least exposed to deviate from the principles of equity. In a doubtful case, we may reasonably refuse to give succours (though a thing favourable), when there is ques- tion of giving them against an ally, which would be odious. The following are the rules of interpretation, which flow from the principles we have just laid down. OP THE INTERPKETATION OF TREATIES. 266 1. When the question relates to things favourable, we ought BOOK n. to give the terms the utmost latitude of which they are suscep- CHAP, xvn. tible according to the common usage of the language ; and if a 307. Inter- term has more than one signification, the most extensive mean- pretation of ing is to be preferred : for equity ought to be the rule of con- fa y ourable duct with all mankind wherever a perfect right is not exactly * mgs ' determined and known in its precise extent. When the legis- lature or the contracting parties have not expressed their will in terms that are precise and perfectly determinate, it is to be presumed that they intended what is most equitable. Now, [ 267 ] when there is question of favourable things, the more exten- sive signification of the terms accords better with equity than the more confined signification. Thus Cicero, in pleading the cause of Caecina, justly maintains that the interlocutory decree, ordaining, " that the person expelled from his inhe- ritance be reinstated in the possession," should be understood as extending to the man who has been forcibly prevented from entering upon it :* and the Digest decides it in the same manner, f It is true that this decision is also founded on the rule taken from parity of reasoning ( 290). For it amounts to the same thing in effect, to drive a person from his inhe- ritance, or forcibly to prevent him from entering upon it; and, in both cases, the same reason exists for putting him in possession. 2. In questions relating to favourable things, all terms of art. are to be interpreted in the fullest latitude of which they are susceptible, not only in common usage, but also as tech- nical terms, if the person speaking understands the art to which those terms belong, or conducts himself by the advice of men who understand that art. 3. But we ought not, from the single reason that a thing is favourable, to take the terms in an improper signification : this is not allowable, except when necessary in order to avoid absurdity, injustice, or the nullity, of the instrument, as is practised on every subject ( 282, 283) : for we ought to take the terms of a deed in their proper sense, conformably to custom, unless we have very strong reasons for deviating from it ( 271). 4. Though a thing appears favourable when viewed in one particular light, yet, where the proper meaning of the terms would, if taken in its utmost latitude, lead to absurdity or injustice, their signification must be restricted according to the rules given above ( 293, 294). For here, in this par- ticular case, the thing becomes of a mixed nature, and even such as ought to be ranked in the class of odious things. 5. For the same reason, although neither absurdity nor injustice results from the proper meaning of the terms, if, * Orat. pro Csecina, cap. xxiii. t Digest, lib. xliii. tit. xvi. D e Vi, et Vi Armata, legg. 1 et 3. 367 267 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK ii. nevertheless, manifest equity or a great common advantage CHAP, xvn. re g u j res th e i r restriction, ive ought to adhere to the most li- mited sense which the proper signification will admit, even in an affair that appears favourable in its own nature, because here also the thing is of a mixed kind, and ought, in this particular case, to be esteemed odious. As to the rest, it is to be carefully remembered that all these rules relate only to doubtful cases ; since we are not allowed to go in quest of interpretations for what is already clear and determinate ( 263). If any one has clearly and formally bound him- self to burdensome conditions, he has knowingly and will- ingly done it, and cannot afterwards be admitted to appeal to equity. g 308. In- Since odious things are those whose restriction tends more terpretation cer tainly to equity than their extension, and since we ought thinS" 18 to P ursue tnat li ne which is most conformable to equity, when f 268 1 * ne will f the legislature or of the contracting parties is not exactly determined and precisely known, we should, when there is question of odious things, interpret the terms in the most limited sense: we may even to a certain degree adopt a figurative meaning, in order to avert the oppressive conse- quences of the proper and literal sense, or any thing of an odious nature, which it would involve : for we are to favour equity, and to do away every thing odious, as far as that can be accomplished, without going in direct opposition to the tenor of the instrument, or visibly wresting the text. Now, neither the limited nor even the figurative sense offers any violence to the text. If it is said in a treaty, that one of the allies shall assist the other with a certain number of troops at his own expense, and that the latter shall furnish the same number of auxiliary troops at the expense of the party to whom they are sent, there is something odious in the engage- ment of the former ally, since he is subject to a greater bur- den than the other : but the terms being clear and express, there is no room for any restrictive interpretation. But if it were stipulated in this treaty, that one of the allies shall fur- nish a body of ten thousand men, and the other only of five thousand, without mentioning the expense, it ought to be un- derstood that the auxiliary troops shall be supported at the expense of the ally to whose assistance they are sent ; this interpretation being necessary, in order that the inequality between the contracting powers may not be carried too far. Thus, the cession of a right, or of a province, made to a con- queror in order to obtain peace, is interpreted in its most confined sense. If it be true that the boundaries of Acadia have always been uncertain, and that the French were the lawful possessors of it, that nation will be justified in main- taining that their cession of Acadia to the English, by the treaty of Utrecht, did not extend beyond the narrowest limits of that province. 3G3 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. 268 In point of penalties, in particular, when they are really BOOK H. odious, we ought not only to restrict the terms of the law, or CHAP - * TU - of the contract, to their most limited signification, and even adopt a figurative meaning, according as the case may require or authorize it, but also to admit of reasonable excuses; which is a kind of restrictive interpretation, tending to exempt the party from the penalty. The same conduct must be observed with respect to what may render an act void and without effect. Thus, when it is agreed that the treaty shall be dissolved whenever one of the contracting parties fails in the observance of any article of it, it would be at once both unreasonable and contrary to the end proposed in making treaties, to extend that clause to the slightest faults, and to cases in which the defaulter can allege well-grounded excuses. Grotius proposes the following question " Whether in a 309. treaty which makes mention of allies, we are to understand Examples, those only who were in alliance at the time when the treaty [ 269 ] was made, or all the allies present and future ?"* And he gives, as an instance, that article of the treaty concluded be- tween the Romans and Carthaginians, after the war of Sicily, that, " neither of the two nations should do any injury to the allies of the other." In order to understand this part of the treaty, it is necessary to call to mind the barbarous law of nations observed by those ancient people. They thought themselves authorized to attack, and to treat as enemies, all with whom they were not united by any alliance. The article therefore signifies, that on both sides they should treat as friends the allies of their ally, and abstain from molesting or invading them : upon this footing it is in all respects so favour- able, so conformable to humanity, and to the sentiments which ought to unite two allies, that it should, without hesitation, be extended to all the allies, present and future. The clause cannot be said to involve any thing of an odious nature, as cramping the freedom of a sovereign state, or tending to dis- solve an alliance : for, by engaging not to injure the allies of another power, we do not deprive ourselves of the liberty to make war on them if they give us just case for hostilities ; and when a clause is just and reasonable, it does not become odious from the single circumstance that it may perhaps eventually occasion a rupture of the alliance. Were that to be the case, there could be no clause whatever that might not be deemed odious. This reason, which we have touched upon in the preceding section and in 304, holds good only in doubtful cases ; in the case before us, for instance, it ought to have prevented too hasty a decision that the Carthaginians had causelessly attacked an ally of the Romans. The Car- thaginians, therefore, might, without any violation of the * Lib. ii. cap. xvi. 13. 47 369 269 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK n. treaty, attack Saguntum, if they had lawful grounds for such CHAP. XYII. an attack, or (in virtue of the voluntary law of nations) even apparent or specious grounds (Prelim. 21). But they might have attacked in the same manner the most ancient ally of the Romans ; and the Romans might also, without breaking the treaty of peace, have confined themselves to the succouring of Saguntum. At present, treaties include the allies on both sides : but this does not imply that one of the contracting powers may not make war on the allies of the other if they give him cause for it but simply, that, in case of any quar- rel arising between them, each of the contracting parties re- serves to himself a power of assisting his more ancient ally : and, in this sense, the future allies are not included in the treaty. Another example mentioned by Grotius is also taken from a treaty concluded between Rome and Carthage. When the latter city was reduced to extremities by Scipio JEmilianus, and obliged to capitulate, the Romans promised "that Car- thage should remain free, or in possession of the privilege of governing herself by her own laws."* In the sequel, how- ever, these merciless conquerors pretended that the promised liberty regarded the inhabitants, and not the city : they in- sisted that Carthage should be demolished, and that the wretched inhabitants should settle in a place at a greater dis- tance from the sea. One cannot read the account of this per- fidious and cruel treatment, without being concerned that the great, the amiable Scipio was obliged to be the instrument [ 270 ] of it. To say nothing of the chicanery of the Romans respect- ing the meaning to be annexed to the word " Carthage," certainly, the "liberty" promised to the Carthaginians, though narrowly circumscribed by the existing state of affairs, should at least have extended to the privilege of remaining in their city. To find themselves obliged to abandon it and settle elsewhere, to lose their houses, their port, and the advan- tages of their situation, was a subjection incompatible with the smallest degree of liberty, and involved such considerable losses as they could not have bound themselves to submit to, unless by a positive engagement in the most express and formal terms. g 310. How Liberal promises, benefactions, and rewards naturally come we ought to under the class of favourable things,and receive an extensive in- interpret terpretation, unless they prove onerous or unreasonably charge- able to the benefactor, or that other circumstances evidently show they are to be taken in a limited sense. For kindness, benevolence, beneficence, and generosity are liberal virtues ; they do not act in a penurious manner, and know no other bounds than those set by reason. But if the benefaction falls too heavy upon him who grants it, in this respect it partakes AUTOVO//OJ. Appian. de Bello Punico. *70 Or THE INTERPKETATION OF TREATIES. 270 of the odious ; and, in case of doubt, equity will not admit BOOK n. the presumption that it has been granted or promised in the CHAP - XYIT - utmost extent of the terms : we ought therefore, in such case, to confine ourselves to the most limited signification which the words are capable of receiving, and thus reduce the bene- faction within the bounds of reason. The same mode should be adopted when other circumstances evidently point the more limited signification as the more equitable. Upon these principles, the bounties of a sovereign are usually taken in the fullest extent of the terms.* It is not presumed that he finds himself over-burdened by them ; it is a respect due to majesty, to suppose that he had good reasons to induce him to confer them. They are therefore, in their own nature, altogether favourable ; and, in order to restrict them, it must be proved that they are burdensome to the prince, or prejudicial to the state. On the whole, we ought to apply to deeds of pure liberality the general rule established above ( 270) ; if those instruments are not pre- cise and very determinate, they should be interpreted as meaning what the author probably had in his mind. [ 271 ] Let us conclude this subject of interpretation with what g 311. Coi- relates to the collision or opposition of laws or treaties. We 1 """"* 1 """ do not here speak of the collision of a treaty with the law of or treaties - nature : the latter is unquestionably paramount, as we have proved elsewhere ( 160, 161, 170, and 293). There is a collision or opposition between two laws, two promises, or two treaties, when a case occurs in which it is impossible to fulfil both at the same time, though otherwise the laws or treaties in question are not contradictory, and may be both fulfilled under different circumstances. They are considered as con- trary in this particular case ; and it is required to show which deserves the preference, or to which an exception ought to be made on the occasion. In order to guard against all mis- take in the business, and to make the exception conformably to reason and justice, we should observe the following rules : 1. In all cases where what is barely permitted is found in- $ 312. First compatible with what is positively prescribed, the latter claims rule in case a preference : for the mere permission imposes no obligatk to do or not to do : what is permitted is left to our own option we are at liberty either to do it or to forbear to do it. But we have not the same liberty with respect to what is pre- scribed : we are obliged to do that : nor can the bare per- mission in the former case interfere with the discharge of our obligation in the latter ; but, on the contrary, that which was before permitted in general, ceases to be so in this par- * Such is the decision of the Roman for it : " quod a divina ejus indulgentia law. Javolenus says : " Beneficium proficiscatur." Digest, lib. i. tit. iv. de imperatoris quam plenissime interpre- Constit. Princ. leg. 3. tari debemus ;" and he gives this reason 371 271 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK ii. ticular instance, where we cannot take advantage of the per- CHAP. XYII. m i ss j on -without violating a positive duty. I 313. 2d 2. In the same manner, the law or treaty which permits, Rule - ought to give way to the law or treaty which forbids : for the prohibition must be obeyed ; and what was, in its own nature, or in general, permitted, must not be attempted when it can- not be done without contravening a prohibition : the permis- sion, in that case, ceases to be available. g 314. 3d 3. All circumstances being otherwise equal, the law or the Rule. treaty which ordains, gives way to the law or the treaty which forbids. I say, "all circumstances being otherwise equal;" for many other reasons may occur, which will authorize the exception being made to the prohibitory law or treaty. The rules are general ; each relates to an abstract idea, and shows what follows from that idea, without derogation to the other rules. Upon this footing, it is evident that, in general, if we cannot obey an injunctive law without violating a prohibitory one, we should abstain from fulfilling the former : for the pro- hibition is absolute in itself, whereas every precept, every injunction, is in its own nature conditional, and supposes the power, or a favourable opportunity, of doing what is pre- scribed. Now when that cannot be accomplished without contravening a prohibition, the opportunity is wanting, and this collision of laws produces a moral impossibility of acting ; for what is prescribed in general, is no longer so in the case [ 272 ] where it cannot be done without committing an action .that is forbidden.* Upon this ground rests the generally received maxim that we are not justifiable in employing unlawful means to accomplish a laudable end, as, for instance, in stealing with a view to give alms. But it is evident that the question here regards an absolute prohibition, or those cases to which the general prohibition is truly applicable, and therefore equi- valent to an absolute one : there are, however, many prohi- bitions to which circumstances form an exception. Our mean- ing will be better explained by an example. It is expressly forbidden, for reasons to me unknown, to pass through a cer- tain place under any pretence whatsoever. I am ordered to carry a message ; I find every other avenue shut ; I there- fore turn back rather than take my passage over that ground which is so strictly forbidden. But if the prohibition - to pass be only a general one, with a view to prevent any injury being done to the productions of the soil, it is easy for me to judge that the orders with which I am charged ought to form an exception. As to what relates to treaties, we are not obliged to ac- complish what a treaty prescribes, any farther than we have * The prohibitory law creates, in that vetat, quasi exceptione quadam, cor- particular instance, an exception to the rigere videtur illam quse jubet." Ci- injunctive law. "Deinde utra lex cero, de Inventione, lib. ii. 145. iubeat, utra vetet. Nam ssepe ea quae 372 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. 272 the power. Now, we have not a power to do what another BOOK n. treaty forbids : wherefore, in case of collision, an exception CHAP - XYU - is made to the injunctive treaty, and the prohibitory treaty has a superior claim to our observance, provided, however, that all circumstances be in other respects equal ; for it will presently appear, for instance, that a subsequent treaty can- not derogate from a prior one concluded with another state, nor hinder its effect directly or indirectly. 4. The dates of laws or treaties furnish new reasons for g 315. 4th establishing the exception in cases of collision. If the c0Z- Rule - lision happen between two affirmative laws, or two affirmative * treaties concluded between the same persons or the same states, that which is of more recent date claims a preference over the older one : for it is evident, that since both laws or both treaties have emanated from the same power, the subsequent act was capable of derogating from the former. But still this is on the supposition of circumstances being in other respects equal. If there be a collision between two treaties made with tivo different powers, the more ancient claims the preference : for no engagement of a contrary tenor could be contracted in the subsequent treaty ; and if this latter be found, in any case, incompatible with that of more ancient date, its execu- tion is considered as impossible, because the person promis- ing had not the power of acting contrary to his antecedent engagements. 5. Of two laws or two conventions, we ought (all other cir- $ 316. 5th cumstances being equal) to prefer the one which is less general, Rie. and which approaches nearer to the point in question : be- cause special matter admits of fewer exceptions than that [ 273 ] which is general ; it is enjoined with greater precision, and appears to have been more pointedly intended. Let us make use of the following example from Puffendorf :* One law forbids us to appear in public with arms on holidays ; another law commands us to turn out under arms, and repair to our posts, as soon as we hear the sound of the alarm-bell. The alarm is rung on a holiday. In such case we must obey the latter of the two laws, which creates an exception to the former. 6. What will not admit of delay, is to be preferred to what $ 317. eth may be done at another time. For this is the mode to recon- Rule, cile every thing, and fulfil both obligations ; whereas, if we gave the preference to the one which might be fulfilled at an- other time, we would unnecessarily reduce ourselves to the alternative of failing in our observance of the other. 7. When two duties stand in competition, that one which is % 318. 7th the more considerable, the more praiseworthy, and productive Rule - of the greater utility, is entitled to the preference. This rule has no need of proof. But as it relates to duties that are * Jus Gent. lib. y. cap. xii. 23. 2G 373 273 OF THE INTERPRETATION OF TREATIES. BOOK n. equally in our power, and, as it were, at our option, we should CHAP, xvn. care f u ii v guard against the erroneous application of it to two duties which do not really stand in competition, but of which the one absolutely precludes the other, our obligation to fulfil the former wholly depriving us of the liberty to perform the latter. For instance, it is a more praiseworthy deed to defend one nation against an ..unjust aggressor, than to assist another in an offensive war. But, if the latter be the more ancient ally, we are not at liberty to refuse her our assist- ance and give it to the former ; for we stand pre-engaged. There is not, strictly speaking, any competition between these two duties : they do not lie at our option : the prior engage- ment renders the second duty, for the present, impracticable. However, if there were question of preserving a new ally from certain ruin, and that the more ancient ally were not reduced to the same extremity, this would be the case to which the foregoing rule should be applied. As to what relates to laws in particular, the preference is undoubtedly to be given to the more important and necessary ones. This is the grand rule to be observed whenever they are found to clash with each other ; it is the rule which claims the greatest attention, and is therefore placed by Cicero at the head of all the rules he lays down on the subject.* It is counteracting the general aim of the legislature, and the great end of the laws, to neglect one of great importance, under [ 274 ] pretence of observing another which is less necessary, and of inferior consequence : in fact, such conduct is criminal ; for, a lesser good, if it exclude a greater, assumes the nature of an evil. f 319. 8th 8. If we cannot acquit ourselves at the same time of two R 1( >. things promised to the same person, it rests with him to choose which of the two we are to perform; for he may dispense with the other on this particular occasion ; in which case there will no longer be any collision of duties. But if we cannot obtain a knowledge of his will, we are to presume that the more im- portant one is his choice ; and we should of course give that the preference. And, in case of doubt, we should perform the one to which we are the more strongly bound; it being pre- sumable that he chose to bind us more strongly to that in which he is more deeply interested. $ 320. 9th 9. Since the stronger obligation claims a preference over Rule< the weaker, if a treaty that has been confirmed by an oath happens to clash with another treaty that has not been sworn to, all circumstances being in other respects equal, the prefer- ence is to be given to the former ; because the oath adds a * " Primum igitur leges oportet con- duae, aut si plures, aut quotquot erunt, tendere, considerando utra lex ad conservari non possint quia discrepant majores, hoc est, ad utiliorcs, ad ho- inter se, ea maxime conservanda puto- nestiores, ac magis necessarias res per- tur, quae ad masimas res pertinere vide- tineat. Ex quo conficitur ut, si leges atur." Cicero, ubi supra. 374 OF THE MODE OF TEKMINATING DISPUTES. 274 new force to the obligation. But as it makes no change in BOOK n. the nature of treaties ( 221, &c.), it cannot, for instance, CHAP ' XVIT> entitle a new ally to a preference over a more ancient ally, whose treaty has not been confirmed by an oath. 10. For the same reason, and, all circumstances being in$32i. 10th other respects equal, what is enjoined under a penalty claims Rule ' a preference over that which is not enforced by one, and what is enjoined under a greater penalty, over that which is enforced by a lesser ; for the penal sanction and convention give addi- tional force to the obligation : they prove that the object in question was more earnestly desired,* and the more so in pro- portion as the penalty is more or less severe. All the rules contained in this chapter ought to be com- g 322. Ge- bined together, and the interpretation be made in such manner neral re - as to accord with them all, so far as they are applicable to J^e^o? 8 the case. When these rules appear to clash, they reciprocally observinga u counterbalance and limit each other, according to their strength the preced- and importance, and according as they more particularly be- in e rules - long to the case in question. CHAP. XVIII. OF THE MODE OF TERMINATING DISPUTES BETWEEN NATIONS. CHAP, xvnr. THE disputes that arise between nations or their rulers, g 323. Ge- originate either from contested rights or from injuries received, neral direc- A nation ought to preserve the rights which belong to her ; tion . on thia and the care of her own safety and glory forbids her to sub- sub J eot mit to injuries. But in fulfilling the duty which she owes to herself, she must not forget her duties to others. These two [ 275 ] views, combined together, will furnish the maxims of the law of nations respecting the mode of terminating disputes be- tween different states. What we have said in Chap. I. IV. and V. of this book, 324. dispenses with our proving here, that a nation ought to do Evei r na - justice to all others with respect to their pretensions, and to* ioni f remove all their just subjects of complaint. She is therefore g^TsatL bound to render to each nation what is her due, to leave her faction re- in the peaceable enjoyment of her rights, to repair any spiting the damage that she herself may have caused, or any injury she jl ! s * com ' may have done, to give adequate satisfaction for such injtt- SotLr. ries as cannot be repaired, and reasonable security against any injury which she has given cause to apprehend. These are so many maxims evidently dictated by that justice which * This is also the reason which Cicero ea [lex] qua? diligentissime sancta est." gives : " Nam maxima conservanda est Cicero, ubi supra. 375 275 OF THE MODE OF TERMINATING BOOK ii. nations as well as individuals are, by the law of nature, bound cj^xvm. to observe. g 325. HOW Every one is at liberty to recede from his right, to relin- nations may q u i sn a j us ^ subject of complaint, and to forget an injury. thofrrihts ^ Ut t ^ ie ru ^ er f a nat i n * s not > i n this respect, so free as a and just private individual. The latter may attend solely to the voice complaints, of generosity ; and, in an affair which concerns none but him- self alone, he may indulge in the pleasure which he derives from doing good, and gratify his love of peace and quiet. The representative of a nation, the sovereign, must not con- sult his own gratification, or suffer himself to be guided by his private inclinations. All his actions must be directed to the greatest advantage of the state, combined with the ge- neral interests of mankind, from which it is inseparable. It behooves the prince, on every occasion, wisely to consider and firmly to execute, whatever is most salutary to the state, most conformable to the duties of the nation towards other states, and, at the same time, to consult justice, equity, humanity, sound policy, and prudence. The rights of the nation are a property of which the sovereign is only the trustee ; and he ought not to dispose of them in any other manner than he has reason to presume the nation herself would dispose of them. And, as to injuries, it is often laudable in a citizen generously to pardon them : he lives under the protection of the laws ; the magistrates are capable of defending or avenging him against those ungrateful or unprincipled wretches whom his indulgence might encourage to a repetition of the offence. A nation has not the same security : it is seldom safe for her to . overlook or forgive an injury, unless she evidently possess sufficient power to crush the rash aggressor who has dared to offend her. In such a case, indeed, it will reflect glory on her to pardon those who acknowledge their faults, f 276 1 Parcere subjectis, et debellare suporbos ; The duty an d she may do it with safety. But between powers that of a sove- are nearly equal, the endurance of an injury without insist- reign of an j n g on complete satisfaction for it, is almost always imputed independent^ wea k nesg or cowardice, a,nd seldom fails long to subject suite to in- '* / i / sist on com- the injured party to further wrongs of a more atrocious nature. pensation Why do we often see the very reverse of this conduct pursued for wrongs D y those who fancy themselves possessed of souls so highly ^cte" sub " exalted above the level of the rest of mankind ? Scarcely can they receive concessions sufficiently humble from weaker states who have had the misfortune to offend them ; but to those whom they would find it dangerous to punish, they be- have with greater moderation. ? 326. If neither of the nations who are engaged in a dispute, Means sug- Chinks proper to abandon her right or her pretensions, the the law of contending parties are, by the law of nature, which recom- nature, for mends peace, concord, and charity, bound to try the gentlest DISPUTES BETWEEN NATIONS. 276 methods of terminating their differences. These are first, BOOK n. an amicable accommodation. Let each party coolly and can- CHAP - * Ym - didly examine the subject of the dispute, and do justice to the J^ 1 * 1118 other ; or let him whose right is too uncertain, voluntarily pu te s . renounce it. There are even occasions when it may be pro- 1. Amica- per for him who has the clearer right, to renounce it, for the ble accom - sake of preserving peace, occasions, which it is the part of modatlon - prudence to discover. To renounce a right in this manner, is not abandoning or neglecting it. People are under no obligation to you for what you abandon : but you gain a friend in the party to whom you amicably yield up what was the subject of a dispute. Compromise is a second method of bringing disputes to a 327. 2. peaceable termination. It is an agreement, by which, with- Compro- out precisely deciding on the justice of the jarring preten- mise> sions, the parties recede on both sides, and determine what share each shall have of the thing in dispute, or agree to give it entirely to one of the claimants on condition of certain in- demnifications granted to the other. Mediation, in which a common friend interposes his good 328. 3. offices, frequently proves efficacious in engaging the contend- Mediation, ing parties to meet each other halfway, to come to a good understanding, to enter into an agreement or compromise respecting their rights, and, if the question relates to an in- jury, to offer and accept a reasonable satisfaction. The office of mediator requires as great a degree of integrity, as of pru- dence and address. He ought to observe a strict impar- tiality ; he should soften the reproaches of the disputants, calm their resentments, and dispose their minds to a reconcilia- tion. His duty is to favour well-founded claims, and to effect the restoration, to each party, of what belongs to him : but he ought not scrupulously to insist on rigid justice. He is a conciliator, and not a judge : his business is to procure peace ; and he ought to induce him who has right on his side to relax something of his pretensions, if necessary, with a view to so great a blessing. The mediator is not guarantee for the treaty which he has conducted, unless he has expressly undertaken to guarantee it. That is an engagement of too great consequence to be [ 277 ] imposed on any one, without his own consent clearly mani- fested. At present, when the affairs of the sovereigns of Europe are so connected, that each has an eye on what passes between those who are the most distant, mediation is a mode of conciliation much used. Does any dispute arise ? The friendly powers, those who are afraid of seeing the flames of war kindled, offer their mediation, and make overtures of peace and accommodation. When sovereigns cannot agree about their pretensions and f 329. 4. are nevertheless desirous of preserving or restoring peace, Arbitration, they sometimes submit the decision of their disputes to arbi- 48 2 o2 377 277 OF THE MODE OF TERMINATING CHAP. XVIII. trators chosen by common agreement. When once the con- tending parties have entered into articles of arbitration, they are bound to abide by the sentence of the arbitrators : they have engaged to do this ; and the faith of treaties should be religiously observed. If, however, the arbitrators, by pronouncing a sentence evidently unjust and unreasonable, should forfeit the cha- racter with which they were invested, their judgment would deserve no attention : the parties had appealed to it only with a view to the decision of doubtful questions. Suppose a board of arbitrators should, by way of reparation for some offence, condemn a sovereign state to become subject to the state she has offended, will any man of sense assert that she is bound to submit to such decision ? If the injustice is of small consequence, it should be borne for the sake of peace ; and if it is not absolutely evident, we ought to endure it, as an evil to which we have voluntarily exposed ourselves. For if it were necessary that we should be convinced of the jus- tice of a sentence before we would submit to it, it would be of very little use to appoint arbitrators. There is no reason to apprehend, that, by allowing the parties a liberty of refusing to submit to a manifestly unjust and unreasonable sentence, we should render arbitration use- less : our decision is by no means repugnant to the nature of recognisances or arbitration articles. There can be no difficulty in the affair, except in case of the parties having signed vague and unlimited articles, in which they have not precisely specified the subject of the dispute, or marked the bounds of their opposite pretensions. It may then happen, as in the example just alleged, that the arbitrators will ex- ceed their power, and pronounce on what has not been really submitted to their decision. Being called in to determine what satisfaction a state ought to make for an offence, they may condemn her to become subject to the state she has offended. But she certainly never gave them so extensive a power ; and their absurd sentence is not binding. In order to obviate all difficulty, and cut off every pretext of which fraud might make a handle, it is necessary that the arbitra- tion articles should precisely specify the subject in dispute, the restrictive and opposite pretensions of the parties, the demands of the one, and the objections of the other. These constitute the whole of what is submitted to the decision of the arbitrators ; and it is upon these points alone that the [ 278 ] parties promise to abide by their judgment. If, then, their sentence be confined within these precise bounds, the dispu- tants must acquiesce in it. They cannot say that it is mani- festly unjust, since it is pronounced on a question which they have themselves rendered doubtful by the disordance of their claims, and which has been referred, as such, to the decision of the arbitrators. Before they can pretend to evade such 378 DISPUTES BETWEEN NATIONS. 278 a sentence, they should prove, by incontestable facts, that it BOOK n. was the offspring of corruption or flagrant partiality. Arbitration is a very reasonable mode, and one that is per- fectly conformable to the law of nature, for the decisio?! of every dispute which does not directly interest the safety of the nation. Though the claim of justice may be mistaken by the arbitrators, it is still more to be feared that it will be overpowered in an appeal to the sword. The Swiss have had the precaution, in all their alliances among themselves, and even in those they have contracted with the neighbouring powers, to agree beforehand on the manner in which their disputes were to be submitted to arbitrators, in case they could not adjust them in an amicable manner. (132) This wise precaution has not a little contributed to maintain the Helvetic republic in that flourishing state which secures her liberty, and renders her respectable throughout Europe. In order to put in practice any of these methods, it is ne- g 330. Con- cessary to speak with each other, and to confer together. Con- ferences and ferences and congresses are therefore a mode of conciliation, congresses, which the law of nature recommends to nations, as well cal- culated to bring their differences to an amicable termination. Congresses are assemblies of plenipotentiaries appointed to find out means of conciliation, and to discuss and adjust the - reciprocal pretensions of the contending parties. To afford the prospect of a happy issue of their deliberations, such meetings should be formed and directed by a sincere desire of peace and concord. In the present century, Europe has witnessed two general congresses, that of Cambray,* and that of Soissons,f both tedious farces acted on the political theatre, in which the principal performers were less desirous of coming to an accommodation than of appearing to desire it. In order at present to ascertain in what manner and how 331. Dis- far a nation is bound ta resort or accede to these various tinction to modes of accommodation, and which of them she ought to j^**^ 6 " prefer, it becomes necessary, in the first place, to distinguish dlnt^nd 1 between cases that are evident, and those that are doubtful, doubtful Does the question relate to a right that is clear, certain, and cases, incontestable ? A sovereign, if he possesses sufficient strength, may peremptorily prosecute and defend that right, without ex- posing it to the doubtful issue of an arbitration. Shall he submit to negotiate and compound for a thing that evidently belongs to him, and which is disputed without the least shadow of jus- [ 279 ] tice ? Much less will he subject it to arbitration. But he ought not to neglect those methods of conciliation, which, (132) The stipulations between pri- parties as obligatory, in point of honour, vate partners and others in anticipation to endeavour to arbitrate the existing of mere possible disputes is analogous, dispute. C. and though not legally binding, yet, in * In 1724. practice, in case of differences, the mere -j- In 1728. Itipulation is usually considered by the 379 279 OF THE MODE OF TERMINATING K 11. without endangering his own right, may induce his opponent CHAP, xvm. ^ ij s t en to reason, such as mediation and conferences. Na- ture gives us no right to have recourse to forcible means, except where gentle and pacific methods prove ineffectual. It is not permitted to be so inflexible in uncertain and doubtful questions. Who will dare to insist that another shall imme- diately, and without examination, relinquish to him a dis- putable right? This would be a means of rendering wars perpetual and inevitable. Both the contending parties may be equally convinced of the justice of their claims : why, therefore, should either yield to the other ? In such a case, they can only demand an examination of the question, pro- pose a conference or an arbitration, or offer to settle the point by articles of agreement. I 332. Of In the disputes that arise between sovereigns, it is more- essential over necessary to make a proper distinction between essential rights, and r ight s and rights of inferior importance : for, according to importance 88 *k e difference in the two cases, a different line of conduct is to be pursued. A nation is under many obligations of duty towards herself, towards other nations, and towards the great society of mankind. We know that the duties we owe to ourselves are, generally speaking, paramount to those we owe to others ; but this is to be understood only of such duties as bear some proportion to each other. We cannot refuse, in some degree, to forget ourselves with respect to interests that are not essential, and to make some sacrifices, in order to assist other persons, and especially for the greater benefit of human society : and let us even remark, that we are invited by our own advantage, by our own safety, to make these ge- nerous sacrifices ; for the private good of each is intimately connected with the general happiness. What idea should we entertain of a prince or a nation who would refuse to give up the smallest advantage for the sake of procuring to the world the inestimable blessings of peace ? Every power therefore owes this respect to the happiness of human society, to show himself open to every mode of conciliation, in questions re- lating to interests which are neither essential nor of great importance. If he exposes himself to the loss of something by an accommodation, by a compromise, or by an arbitration, he ought to be sensible what are the dangers, the evils, the calamities of war, and to consider that peace is well worth a small sacrifice. But if any one would rob a nation of one of her essential rights, or a right without which she could not hope to support her national existence, if an ambitious neighbour threatens [ 280 ] the liberty of a republic, if he attempts to subjugate and enslave her, she will take counsel only from her own cou- rage. She will not even attempt the mode of conferences on so odious a pretension ; she will, in such a quarrel, exert her utmost efforts, exhaust every resource, and gloriously lavish DISPUTES BETWEEN NATIONS. 280 her blood to the last drop if necessary. To listen to the BOOK n. smallest proposition, is putting every thing to the risk. On CHAP - xvi p- such an occasion she may truly say Una salus nullam sperare salutem : and if fortune prove unfavourable, a free people will prefer death to servitude. What would have become of Rome, had she listened to timid counsels, when Hannibal was encamped before her walls ? The Swiss, ever so ready to embrace pacific measures or submit to legal decisions in disputes respecting less essential points, have uniformly spurned at all idea of compromise with those who harboured designs against their liberty. They even refused on such occasions to submit their disputes to arbitration, or to the judgment of the emperors.* In doubtful causes which do not involve essential points, ? 333. How if one of the parties will not accede either to a conference, we acquire an accommodation, a compromise, or an arbitration, the other *^? n * e has only the last resource for the defence of himself and his COU rse to rights, an appeal to the sword ; and he has justice on his force in a side in taking up arms against so untractable an adversary, doubtful For, in a doubtful cause, we can only demand all the reason- cause ' able methods of elucidating the question, and of deciding or accommodating the dispute ( 331). But let us never lose sight of what a nation owes to her $ 334. and own security, nor of that prudence by which she ought con- even with - stantly to be directed. To authorize her to have recourse to arms, it is not always necessary that every conciliatory mea- sure be first expressly rejected : it is sufficient that she have every reason to believe that the enemy would not enter into those measures with sincerity, that they could not be brought to terminate in a happy result, and that the intervening delay would only expose her to a greater danger of being over- powered. This maxim is incontestable; but its application in practice is very delicate. A sovereign who would not be considered as a disturber of the public peace, will not be in- duced abruptly to attack him who has not refused to accede to pacific measures, unless he be able to justify his conduct in the eyes of all mankind, by proving that he has reason to consider those peaceable appearances as an artifice employed for the purpose of amusing him, and taking him by surprise. To make his bare suspicions serve as sufficient authority for such a step, would be sapping every foundation on which rests the security of nations. The faith of one nation has ever been suspected by an- * When, in the year 1355, they sub- should not touch the liberty of those mitted their differences with the dukes countries, nor their alliance with the of Austria, in relation to the countries other cantons. Tschudi, p. 429, Ac. of Zug and Glaris, to the arbitration Stettler, p. 77. History of the Helvetic of Charles IV., it was not without this Confederacy, by De Watteville, book iv. preliminary condition, that the emperor at the beginning. 381 280 OF THE MODE OF TERMINATING BOOK n. other, and sad experience but too plainly proved that this dis- CHAP. xvin. f. rus f. i g no j. ill-founded. Independence and impunity are a ^ 335. Vo- touchstone that discovers the alloy of the human heart : the luntary law private individual assumes the character of candour and pro- on thhumb -T ' an< ^> * n Default ^ tne reality, his dependence frequently ject obliges him to exhibit in his conduct at least the appearance [ 281 ] f those virtues. The great man, who is independent, boasts still more of them in his discourse ; but as soon as he finds himself possessed of superior strength, he scarcely endeavours to save appearances, unless his heart be moulded of materials which, unfortunately, are very rare indeed : and, if powerful interest intervene, he will give himself a latitude in the pur- suit of measures that would cover a private person with shame and infamy. When, therefore, a nation pretends that it would be dangerous for her to attempt pacific measures, she can find abundance of pretexts to give a colour of justice to her pre- cipitation in having recourse to arms. And as, in virtue of the natural liberty of nations, each one is free to judge in her own conscience how she ought to act, and has a right to make her own judgment the sole guide of her conduct with respect to her duties in every thing that is not determined by the perfect rights of another (Prelim. 20), it belongs to each nation to judge whether her situation will admit of pacific measures, before she has recourse to arms. Now, as the vo- luntary law of nations ordains, that, for these reasons, we should esteem lawful whatever a nation thinks proper to do in virtue of her natural liberty (Prelim. 21), by that same voluntary law, nations are bound to consider as lawful the conduct of that power who suddenly takes up arms in a doubt- ful cause, and attempts to force his enemy to come to terms, without having previously tried pacific measures. Louis XIV. was in the heart of the Netherlands before it was known in Spain that he laid claim to the sovereignty of a part of those rich provinces in right of the queen his wife. The king of Prussia, in 1741, published his manifesto in Silesia, at the head of sixty thousand men. Those princes might have wise and just reasons for acting thus : and this is sufficient at the tribunal of the voluntary law of nations. But a thing which that law tolerates through necessity, may be found very un- just in itself: and a prince who puts it in practice may render himself very guilty in the sight of his own conscience, and very unjust towards him whom he attacks, though he is not accountable for it to other nations, as he cannot be accused of violating the general rules which they are bound to observe towards each other. But if he abuses this liberty, he gives all nations cause to hate and suspect him ; he authorizes them to confederate against him ; and thus, while he thinks he is pro- moting his interests, he sometimes irretrievably ruins them. A sovereign ought, in all his quarrels, to entertain a sin- cere desire of rendering justice and preserving peace. He 382 DISPUTES BETWEEN NATIONS. 281 is bound, before he take up arms, and also after having taken BOOK n. them up, to offer equitable conditions; and then alone he is justifiable in appealing to the sword against an obstinate ? 336 - enemy who refuses to listen to the voice of justice or equity, f^ 1 ^^ to It is the business of the appellant to prove his right ; for Coffered! he ought to show a good foundation for demanding a thing [ 282 ] which he does not possess. He must have a title : and peo- 337. PCS- pie are not obliged to respect that title any farther than he s f ssor ' s shows its validity. The possessor may therefore remain "^.^ in possession till proof be adduced to convince him that his casegt possession is unjust. As long as that remains undone, he has a right to maintain himself in it, and even to recover it by force, if he has been despoiled of it. Consequently it is not allowable to take up arms in order to obtain possession of a thing to which the claimant has but an uncertain or doubtful right. He is only justifiable in compelling the pos- sessor, by force of arms if necessary, to come to a discussion of the question, to accede to some reasonable mode of deci- sion or accommodation, or, finally, to settle the point by arti- cles of agreement upon an equitable footing ( 333). If the subject of the dispute be an injury received, the g 335. HOW offended party ought to follow the rules we have just esta- reparation of blished. His own advantage, and that of human society, ^ require, that, previous to taking up arms, he should try every pacific mode of obtaining either a reparation of the injury, or a just satisfaction, unless there be substantial reasons to dispense with his recurrence to such measures ( 334). This moderation, this circumspection, is the more becoming, and in general even indispensable, as the action which we look upon as an injury does not always proceed from a design to offend us, and is sometimes rather a mistake than an act of malice. It even frequently happens that the injury is done by inferior persons, without their sovereign having any share in it : and on these occasions it is natural to presume that he will not refuse us a just satisfaction. When some petty offi- cers, not long since, violated the territory of Savoy in order to carry off from thence a noted smuggling chief, the King of Sardinia caused his complaints to be laid before the court of France ; and Louis XV. thought it no derogation to his greatness to send an ambassador extraordinary to Turin to give satisfaction for that violence. Thus an affair of so deli- cate a nature was terminated in a manner equally honour- able to the two kings. When a nation cannot obtain justice, whether for a wrong I 339. Re- or an injury, she has a right to do herself- justice. But be- taiiation. fore she declares war (of which we shall treat in the follow- ing book), there are various methods practised among nations, which remain to be treated of here. Among those methods of obtaining satisfaction, has been reckoned what is called the law of retaliation, according to which we make another 282 OF THE MODE OF TERMINATING BOOK ii. suffer precisely as much evil as he has done. Many have CHAP, xvin. exto n e( i t } iat j aw? as being founded in the strictest justice: and can we be surprised at their having proposed it to princes, [ 283 ] since they have presumed to make it a rule even for the deity himself? The ancients called it the law of Rhadamanthus. The idea is wholly derived from the obscure and false notion which represents evil as essentially and in its own nature wor- thy of punishment. We have shown above (Book I. 169), what is the true origin of the right of punishing ;* whence we have deduced the true and just proportion of penalties (Book I. 171). Let us say, then, that a nation may punish another which has done her an injury, as we have shown above (see Chap. IV. and VI. of this book), if the latter re- fuses to give her a just satisfaction : but she has not a right to extend the penalty beyond what her own safety requires. Retaliation, which is unjust between private persons, would be much more so between nations, because it would, in the lat- ter case, be difficult to make the punishment fall on those who had done the injury. What right have you to cut off the nose and ears of the ambassador of a barbarian who had treated your ambassador in that manner ? As to those repri- sals in time of war which partake of the nature of retalia- tion, they are justified on other principles ; and we shall speak of them in their proper place. The only truth in this idea of retaliation is, that, all circumstances being in other respects equal, the punishment ought to bear some proportion to the evil for which we mean to inflict it, the very object and foundation of punishment requiring thus much. | 340. Va- It is not always necessary to have recourse to arms, in rious modes order to punish a nation. The offended party may, by way of punish- o f p un i s h men f deprive her of the privileges she enjoyed in ing, without ..*,.. \ ft '^il having re- nis dominions, seize on some ot her property, if he has an course to opportunity, and detain it till she has given him sufficient arms. satisfaction. g 341. Re- When a sovereign is not satisfied with the manner in which tortion. n i g subjects are treated by the laws and customs of another nation, he is at liberty to declare that he will treat the sub- jects of that nation in the same manner as his are treated. This is what is called retortion. There is nothing in this, but what is conformable to justice and sound policy. No one can complain on receiving the same treatment which he gives to others. Thus the king of Poland, elector of Saxony, en- forces the law of escheatage only against the subjects of those princes who make the Saxons liable to it. The retortion may also take place with respect to certain regulations, of which we have no right to complain, and which we are even obliged to approve, though it is proper to guard against their effect * " Nam, ut Plato ait, nemo prudena punit quia peccatum est, sed, ne pecce- tur." Seneca, de Ira. DISPUTES BETWEEN NATIONS. 288 by imitating them. Such are the orders relating to the im- BOOK n. portation or exportation of certain commodities or merchan- CHAP> XTm> dise. On the other hand, circumstances frequently forbid us to have recourse to retortion. In this respect, each nation may act according to the dictates of her own prudence. Reprisals are used between nation and nation in order to do 342. Re- themselves justice when they cannot otherwise obtain it. (133)P risal3 - If a nation has taken possession of what belongs to another, if she refuses to pay a debt, to repair an injury, or to give s adequate satisfaction for it, the latter may seize something [ 284 ] belonging to the former, and apply it to her own advantage till she obtains payment of what is due to her, together with interest and damages, or keep it as a pledge till she has re- ceived ample satisfaction. In the latter case, it is rather a stoppage or a seizure, than reprisals : but they are frequently confounded in common language. The effects thus seized on are preserved while there is any hope of obtaining satisfac- tion or justice. As soon as that hope disappears, they are confiscated, and then the reprisals are accomplished. If the two nations, upon this ground of quarrel, come to an open rupture, satisfaction is considered as refused from the mo- ment that war is declared or hostilities commenced ; and then also the effects seized may be confiscated. It is only upon evidently just grounds, or for a well-ascer- 343 - ^ a? tained and undeniable debt, that the law of nations allows usj^ ^^l to make reprisals. For he who advances a doubtful preten- tnem laj! ,_ sion, cannot in the first instance demand any thing more than ful. an equitable examination of his right. In the next place, before he proceed to such extremities, he should be able to show that he has ineffectually demanded justice, or at least that he has every reason to think it would be in vain for him to demand it. Then alone does it become lawful for him to take the matter into his own hands, and do himself justice. It would be too inconsistent with the peace, the repose, and the safety of nations, with their mutual commerce, and the duties which bind them to each other, that each one should be author- ized to have immediate recourse to violent measures, without knowing whether there exist on the other side a disposition to do her justice, or to refuse it. But, in order perfectly to understand this article, it must be observed, that if, in a disputable case, our adversary either refuses to pursue, or artfully evades the necessary steps for bringing the matter to the proof, if he does not candidly and sincerely accede to some pacific mode of terminating the dispute, especially if he is foremost in adopting violent mea- sures, he gives justice to our cause which before was proble- matical: we may then have recourse to reprisals, or the (133) See further, as to reprisals and thereon, 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, letters of marque, and English decisions 418 423. C. 49 2 H 385 284 OF THE MODE OF TERMINATING BOOK n. seizure of his effects, in order to compel him to embrace the PHAP. xvm - me thod8 of conciliation which the law of nature prescribes. This is the last remaining effort previous to a commencement of open hostilities. 344. Upon We have observed above ( 81), that the wealth of the citi- what effects zens constitutes a part of the aggregate wealth of a nation, ^eTi34) S tnat > between state and state, the private property of the members is considered as belonging to the body, and is an- swerable for the debts of that body ( 82): (134) whence it follows, that in reprisals we seize on the property of the sub- ject just as we would on that of the state or sovereign. Every thing that belongs to the nation is subject to reprisals, whenever it can be seized, provided it be not a deposit in- trusted to the public faith. As it is only in consequence of that confidence which the proprietor has placed in our good- [ 285 ] faith, that we happen to have such deposit in our hands, it ought to be respected, even in case of open war. Such is the conduct observed in France, England, and elsewhere, with respect to the money which foreigners have placed in the public funds. j 345. Tke He who makes reprisals against a nation on the property state ought o f fa members indiscriminately, cannot be taxed with seizing 8atethose ^ property of an innocent person for the debt of another : who suffer for, in this case, the sovereign is to compensate those of his by reprisals, subjects on whom the reprisals fall ; it is a debt of the state or nation, of which each citizen ought only to pay his quota.* g 34, The It is only between state and state that all the property ^ t " le individuals is considered as belonging to the nation. Sovereigns transact their affairs between themselves ; they (134!) The ancient law of nations payment la suspended during the war, perhaps was so; Attorney -General v. and revives again on the return of Weeden, Parko's Rep. 267; but see peace. 1 Rob. Rep. 196; 2 Rob. Rep. post, book fii. chap. v. 77, p. 323, as 200. Ex parte Bomsmaker, 13 Ves. J. to the change in practice. See fur- 71. Furlado v. Rodgen, 3 Bos. & Pul. ther, Chitty's Commercial Law, 421, 191. Antoine v. Morcsfand, 6 Taunt. 423, 425. $ The right is undoubted. 239. Brandon v. Curling, 4 East, 410. The Emulom, 1 scribed. Besides, this violent measure approaches very near to an open rupture, and is frequently followed by one. It is, therefore, an affair of too serious a nature to be left to the discretion of private individuals. And accordingly we see, that in every civilized state, a subject who thinks himself injured by a foreign nation, has recourse to his sovereign, in Letters of order to obtain permission to make reprisals. This is what marc i ae - the French call applying for letters of marque. (135) We may make reprisals against a nation not only for the 347. Re- actions of the sovereign, but also for those of his subjects : P"* als and this may take place when the state or the sovereign P ar ~ nf timffo ticipates in the act of his subject, and takes it upon himself, actions of which he may do in several ways, as we have shown in Chap, its subjects, VI. of this Book. and in fa- in the same manner the sovereign demands justice, or ^j^ the makes reprisals, not only for his own concerns, but also for gu bjects. those of his subjects, whom he is bound to protect, and whose cause is that of the nation. But to grant reprisals against a nation in favour of fo- 348. But reigners, is to set himself up as a judge between that nation not in and those foreigners ; which no sovereign has a right to do. The cause of reprisals ought to be just : they ought even to be grounded on a denial of justice, either an actual denial, or one which there is good reason to apprehend ( 343). Now, what right have we to judge whether the complaint of a stranger against an independent state is just, if he has really been denied justice ? If it be objected, that we may espouse the quarrel of another state in a war that appears to us to be just, to assist her, and even to unite with her, the case is different. In granting succours against a nation, we do not [ 286 ] detain her property or her people that happen to be within our territories under the public faith ; and in declaring war against her, we suffer her to withdraw her subjects and her effects, as will hereafter appear. In the case of reprisals granted to our own subjects, a nation cannot complain that we violate the public faith in seizing on her people or her property ; because we are under no other obligation to grant security to that property and those people, than what arises from a reasonable supposition that their nation will not, in the first instance, violate, with respect to us or our subjects, the rules of justice which nations ought to observe towards each other. If she violate them, we have a right to obtain satisfaction ; and the mode of reprisals is more easy, safe, and mild, than that of war. We cannot urge the same argu- (135) As to decisions on letters of Law, 418422. Chilly's L. N. 73 marque, see 1 Chitty's Commercial 86. C. 387 286 OF THE MODE OF TERMINATING BOOK ii. ments in justification of reprisals ordered in favour of foreign- CHAI>. xvni. erg> p or the security we owe to the subjects of a foreign power does not depend, as a condition, on the security which that power shall grant to all other nations, to people who do not belong to us, and are not under our protection. Eng- land having, in 1662, granted reprisals against the United Provinces in favour of the knights of Malta,* the states of Holland asserted, with good reason, that, according to the law of nations, reprisals can only be granted to maintain the rights of the state, and not for an affair in which the nation has no concern.f g 349. Those The individuals, who by their actions have given cause for who have just reprisals, are bound to indemnify those on whom they given cause faft . an( j ^g 80V ereign ought to compel them to do it. For oughuTL- we are un der an obligation to repair the damage we have oc- demnify casioned by our own fault. And, although the sovereign, by those who refusing justice to the offended party, has brought on the fer by reprisals against his subjects, those who were the first cause of them do not become the less guilty : the fault of the sove- reign does not exempt them from repairing the consequences of theirs. However, if they were ready to give satisfaction to the party whom they had injured or offended, and their sovereign has prevented their doing it, they are not bound to do any thing more in that case, than they would before have been obliged to do in order to prevent the reprisals ; and it is the sovereign's duty to repair the additional damage, which is the consequence of his own fault ( 345). I 350. What We have said ( 343) that we ought not to make reprisals, may be except when we are unable to obtain justice. Now, justice deemed a j g re f use( j j n several ways : First, by a denial of justice, 'us'tice * P ro P er ty so called, or by a refusal to hear your complaints or those of your subjects, or to admit them to establish their right before the ordinary tribunals. Secondly, by studied [ 287 ] delays, for which no good reasons can be given delays * On that subject, the grand pen- except in case of an open denial of jus- sionary De Witt wrote as follows: tice. Finally, it is also evident, that, " Nothing can be more absurd than even in case of a denial of justice, ho that grant of reprisals : for, to say no- cannot empower his subjects to make thing of its proceeding from a board reprisals, until he has repeatedly de- of admiralty, who have no power to manded justice for them, and added, grant it without infringing on the that, in the event of a refusal, he will sovereign authority of their prince, it be obliged to grant them letters of is evident that no sovereign can grant marque and reprisal." From the answers or make reprisals, except for the de- of M. Boreel, it appears that this con- fence or indemnification of his own duct of the British admiralty was subjects, whom he is, in the sight of strongly condemned by the court of God, bound to protect; but he never France. The king of England testified can grant reprisals in favour of any his disapprobation of it, and gave orders foreigner who is not under his protec- for the release of the Duteh vessels , tion, and with whose sovereign he has whose seizure had been permitted by not any engagement to that effect, ex way of reprisal. Edit. 1797. pacto vel fcedere. Besides, it is certain f See Bynckershoek's Competent that reprisals ought not to bo granted Judge of Embassadors, chap. xxii. 388 DISPUTES BETWEEN NATIONS. 287 equivalent to a refusal, or still more ruinous. Thirdly, by BOOK n. an evidently unjust and partial decision. But it is necessary cnAP - XVI ": that this injustice should be manifest and palpable. In all cases susceptible of doubt, a sovereign ought not to listen to the complaints of his subjects against a foreign tribunal, nor to attempt to screen them from the effects of a sentence passed in due form : for that would be the means of exciting continual troubles. The law of nations directs that states should re- ciprocally pay that kind of deference to each other's juris- diction, for the same reason as the civil law ordains, within the state, that every definitive sentence, passed in due form, shall be esteemed just. Between nation and nation the obli- gation is neither so express nor so extensive : but it cannot be denied, that it is highly conducive to their peace and con- formable to their duties towards human society, to oblige their subjects, in all doubtful cases, and, unless where there is a manifest wrong done to them, to submit to the sentences of the foreign tribunals before which their causes have been tried. (See above, 84). As we may seize the things which belong to a nation, in $ 351. Sub- order to compel her to do justice, we may equally, for the jects arrest- same reason, arrest some of her citizens, and not release ed by *** them till we have received full satisfaction. This is what the Greeks called Androlepsia.* At Athens the law permitted the relatives of him who had been assassinated in a foreign country, to seize three of the inhabitants of that country, and to detain them till the murderer was punished or delivered up.f But, in the practice of modern Europe, this method is seldom resorted to, except with a view to obtain satisfaction for an injury of the same nature that is to say, to compel a sovereign to release a person whom he detains unjustly. The persons, however, who are thus arrested, being detained only as a security, or pledge, in order to oblige a nation to do justice if their sovereign obstinately persists in refusing it, we cannot take away their lives, or inflict any corporal punishment upon them, for a refusal of which they are not guilty. Their property, their liberty itself, may be staked for the debts of the state ; but not their lives, of which man has not the power of disposing. A sovereign has no right to put to death the subjects of a state which has done him an injury, except when they are engaged in war ; and we shall see, elsewhere, what it is that gives him that right. But the sovereign is authorized to employ forcible means \ 352. Our against those who resist him in the exertion of his right, a nd r! g hta s ainst to pursue such means as far as is necessary to overcome their tho unjust resistance. It is therefore lawful to repel those who undertake to oppose the making of just reprisals : and if, for that purpose, it be necessary to proceed even so far as to * A*(5poAij^, seizure of men. f Demosthenes, Orat adv. Aristocrat H2 389 288 OF THE MODE OF TERMINATING BOOK n. put them to death, the whole blame of that misfortune is im- CHAP. xvur. p u t a ble to their unjust and inconsiderate resistance. In such a case, Grotius would have us rather abstain from making reprisals.* Between private persons, and for things that are not of the highest importance, it is certainly worthy, not only of a Christian, but, in general, of every man of principle, rather to abandon his right than to kill the person who un- justly resists him. But, between sovereigns, the case is other- wise. To suffer themselves to be bullied, would be attended with consequences of too serious a nature. The true and just welfare of the state is the grand rule : moderation is ever lau- dable in itself; but the conductors of nations ought to practise that virtue so far only as it is consistent with the happiness and safety of their people. g 353. Just After having demonstrated the lawfulness of making re- reprisals prisals when we can no otherwise obtain justice, we may donotaf- thence readily conclude that a sovereign is not justifiable in cause* roT ma king forcible opposition to, or waging war against, the war. party, who, by ordering or making reprisals in such a case, only exerts his just right. g 354. How And as the law of humanity directs nations as well as in- wo ought to dividuals ever to prefer the gentlest measures, when they are confine our- Su f5 c i en t to obtain justice whenever a sovereign can, by prilais^r * ne mo & e f reprisals, procure a just indemnification or a at length suitable satisfaction, he ought to confine himself to this method, proceed to which is less violent and less fatal than war. On this subject, hosiiiities. i cannot avoid noticing an error which is too general to be wholly disregarded. If it happens that a prince, having reason to complain of some injustice or some acts of hostility, and not finding his adversary disposed to give him satisfaction, determines to make reprisals with the view of endeavouring to compel him to listen to the voice of justice before he proceeds to an open rupture, if, without a declaration of war, he seizes on his effects, his shipping, and detains them as pledges, you hear certain men cry out that this is robbery. If that prince had at once declared war, they would not have said a word ; they would perhaps have praised his conduct. Strange for- getfulness of reason, and of every sound principle ! Would we not, at this rate, be tempted to suppose that nations were bound to observe the laws of chivalry, to challenge each other to the lists, and decide their quarrels like a pair of doughty champions engaged in regular duel ? It is the duty of sovereigns attentively to maintain the rights of their people, and to obtain justice by every lawful means still, however, [ 289 ] preferring the gentlest methods : and we again repeat the as- sertion it is evident that the mode of reprisals, of which we are speaking, is infinitely more gentle and less fatal than that of war. But since, between powers whose strength is nearly * Grotius De Jure Belli et Pacis, lib. iii. cap. ii. g 6. 390 DISPUTES BETWEEN NATIONS. 289 AP. xvin. equal, reprisals often lead to war, they ought not to be attempt- _ BO _ OK _ ed, except in the last extremity. In such circumstances, the - prince who has recourse to that expedient, instead of proceed- ing to an open rupture, is undoubtedly entitled to praise for his moderation and prudence. Those who run to arms without necessity, are the scourges of the human race, barbarians, enemies to society, and re- bellious violaters of the laws of nature, or rather, the laws of the common father of mankind. There are cases, however, in which reprisals would be justly condemnable, even when a declaration of war would not be so : and these are precisely those cases in which nations may with justice take up arms. When the question which con- stitutes the ground of a dispute, relates, not to an act of violence, or an injury received, but to a contested right, after an ineffectual endeavour to obtain justice by conciliatory and pacific measures, it is a declaration of war that ought to follow, and not pretended reprisals, which, in such a case, would only be real acts of hostility without a declaration of war, and would be contrary to public faith as well as to the mutual duties of nations. This will more evidently appear, when we shall have explained the reasons which establish the obligation of declaring war previous to a commencement of hostilities.* But if, from particular conjunctures, and from the obstinacy of an unjust adversary, neither reprisals, nor any of the methods of which we have been treating, should prove suffi- cient for our defence, and for the protection of our rights, there remains only the wretched and melancholy alternative of war, which will be the subject of the following book. * See Book in. chap. IT. 291 BOOK III. OF WAR. CHAP. I. CHA* ."i*.' o;p WAR 5 ITS DIFFERENT KINDS, AND THE RIGHT OF MAKING WAR. i. Defi- W AR is that state in which we prosecute our right by force. nition of "We also understand, by this term, the act itself, or the man- war, rise) ner O f p rosecu ting our right by force : but it is more con- formable to general usage, and more proper in a treatise on the law of war, to understand this term in the sense we have annexed to it. g 2. Public Public war is that which takes place between nations or war. (136) sovereigns, and which is carried on in the name of the public power, and by its order. This is the war we are here to con- sider : private war, or that which is carried on between pri- vate individuals, belongs to the law of nature properly so called. 3. Right In treating of the right to security (Book II. Chap. IV.), of making we have shown that nature gives men a right to employ force, war. (136) w h en ft j s necessary for their defence, and for the preserva- tion of their rights. This principle is generally acknowledged : reason demonstrates it ; and nature herself has engraved it on the heart of man. Some fanatics indeed, taking in a literal sense the moderation recommended in the gospel, have adopted the strange fancy of suffering themselves to be massacred or [ 292 ] plundered, rather than oppose force to violence. But we need not fear that this error will make any great progress. The generality of mankind will, of themselves, guard against its contagion happy, if they as well knew how to keep within the just bounds which nature has set to a right that is granted only through necessity ! To mark those just bounds, and, by the rules of justice, equity, and humanity, to moderate the exercise of that harsh, though too often necessary right, is the intention of this third book. (136) See definition of war and of 4 Rob. Rep. 252 ; Bro. Ab. tit. Deni- the king's sole right to declare it, as zen, pi. 20, and Chitty's L. N. 28, 29, regards England, per Sir Wm. Scott, 30. C. The Hoop, 1 Rob. R. 196; Nayade, 392 OF WAK, ETC. 292 As nature has given men no right to employ force, unless BOOK m. when it becomes necessary for self defence and the preserva- CHAP ' "' tion of their rights (Book II. 49, &c.), the inference is mani- 2 4 - II be - fest, that, since the establishment of political societies, a right, } ^ e ^ e so dangerous in its exercise, no longer remains with private re i gn pow er. persons except in those rencounters where society cannot pro- (137) tect or defend them. In the bosom of society, the public authority decides all the disputes of the citizens, represses violence, and checks every attempt to do ourselves justice with our own hands. If a private person intends to prosecute his right against the subject of a foreign power, he may apply to the sovereign of his adversary, or to the magistrates in- vested with the public authority : and if he is denied justice by them, he must have recourse to his own sovereign, who is obliged to protect him. It would be too dangerous to allow every citizen the liberty of doing himself justice against for- eigners ; as, in that case, there would not be a single member of the state who might not involve it in war. And how could peace be preserved between nations, if it were in the power of every private individual to disturb it ? A right of so momentous a nature, the right of judging whether the na- tion has real grounds of complaint, whether she is authorized to employ force, and justifiable in taking up arms, whether prudence will admit of such a step, and whether the welfare of the state requires it, that right, I say, can belong only to the body of the nation, or to the sovereign, her repre- sentative. It is doubtless one of those rights, without which there can be no salutary government, and which are therefore catted rights of majesty (Book I. 45). Thus the sovereign power alone is possessed of authority to make war. But, as the different rights which constitute this power, originally resident in the body of the nation, may be separated or limited according to the will of the nation (Book I. 31 and 45), it is from the particular constitution of each state, that we are to learn where the power resides, that is authorized to make war in the name of the society at large. The kings of England, whose power is in other re- [ 293 ~\ spects so limited, have the right of making war and peace.* Those of Sweden have lost it. The brilliant but ruinous ex- ploits of Charles XII. sufficiently warranted the states of that kingdom to reserve to themselves a right of such im- portance to their safety. (137) The right of declaring war is, in itself. But as a king of England by his prerogative, vested in the king cannot, without the concurrence of of the United Kingdom of Great Britain parliament, either raise money or com- and Ireland. Bro. Ab. tit. Denizen, pi. pel his subjects to take up arms, his 20. The ship Huop, per Sir W. Scott, 1 right of making war is, in fact, but a Rob. R. 196, post, 432. C. {And, by slender prerogative, unless the parlia- the Constitution of the United States, ment second him with supplies. Ed. in Congress. Art 1, 8.} 1797. * I here speak of the right considered 50 393 293 OF THE INSTRUMENTS OF WAR, ETC. BOOK in. War is either defensive or offensive. He who takes up CHAP - I- .arms to repel the attack of an enemy, carries on a defensive I 5. Defen- war. He who is foremost in taking up arms, and attacks a sive and of- nation that lived in peace with him, wages offensive war. fensive war. ^he object of a defensive war is very simple ; it is no other than self defence : in that of offensive war there is as great a variety as in the multifarious concerns of nations ; but, in general, it relates either to the prosecution of some rights, or to safety. We attack a nation with a view either to obtain something to which we lay claim, to punish her for an injury she has done us, or to prevent one which she is preparing to do, and thus avert a danger with which she seems to threaten us. I do not here speak of the justice of war : that shall make the subject of a particular chapter : all I here propose is to indicate, in general, the various objects for which a na- tion takes up arms objects which may furnish lawful reasons, or unjust pretences, but which are at least susceptible of a colour of right. I do not, therefore, among the objects of offensive war, set down conquest, or the desire of invading the property of others : views of that nature, destitute even of any reasonable pretext to countenance them, do not con- stitute the object of regular warfare, but of robbery, which we shall consider in its proper place. CHAP, n. CHAP. II. OF THE INSTRUMENTS OF WAR, THE RAISING OF TROOPS, &C., THEIR COMMANDERS, OR THE SUBORDINATE POWERS IN WAR. (138) 6. Instru- THE sovereign is the real author of war, which is carried monts of on in his name, and by his order. The troops, officers, war< soldiers, and, in general, all those by whose agency the sove- reign makes war, are only instruments in his hands. They execute his will and not their own. The arms, and all the apparatus of things used in war, are instruments of an in- ferior order. For the decision of questions that will occur in the sequel, it is of importance to determine precisely what are the things which belong to war. Without entering here into a minute detail, we shall only observe that whatever is peculiarly used in waging war, is to be classed among the (138) What are instruments of war, le croit yulgairement, 1'art do dctruire or contraband, and of the prohibitions mais 1'art de paralyaer dos forces de respecting them, as regards neutral com- 1'ennemi. Cours le Droit Public. merce, see Chilly's L. N. 119 to 128 ; 1 Paris, 1830 ; torn. 2, pages 85, 86, this question is no problem : it is more difficult of solution to [ 308 ] those who wish to see justice and prudence ever inseparably united. On the one hand, a state that increases her power by all the arts of good government, does no more than what is com- mendable she fulfils her duties towards herself without violating those which she owes to other nations. The sove- reign, who, by inheritance, by free election, or by any other just and honourable means, enlarges his dominions by the ad- dition of new provinces or entire kingdoms, only makes use of his right, without injuring any person. How then should it be lawful to attack a state which, for its aggrandizement, makes use only of lawful means ? We must either have actu- ally suffered an injury or be visibly threatened with one, before we are authorized to take up arms, or have just grounds for making war ( 26, 27). On the other hand, it is but too well known, from sad and uniform experience, that predominating powers seldom fail to molest their neighbours, to oppress them, and even totally subjugate them, whenever an opportunity occurs, and they can do it with impunity. Europe was on the point of falling into servitude for want of a timely opposition to the growing fortune of Charles V. Is the danger to be waited for ? Is the storm, which might be dispersed at its rising, to be permitted to increase ? Are we to allow of the aggrandizement of a neighbour, and quietly wait till he makes his preparations to enslave us ? Will it be a time to defend ourselves when we are deprived of the means ? Prudence is a duty incumbent on all men, and most pointedly so on the heads of nations, as being commissioned to watch over the safety of a whole people. Let us endea- vour to solve this momentous question, agreeably to the sacred principles of the law of nature and of nations. We shall find that they do not lead to weak scruples, and that it is an inva- riable truth that justice is inseparable from sound policy. \ 43. Alone, And first, let us observe, that prudence, which is, no doubt, and of itself, a virtue highly necessary in sovereigns, can never recommend ^iveTrf ht t ^ ie use ^ un l aw f u l means for the attainment of a just and toTttaci? laudable end. Let not the safety of the people, that supreme him. law of the state, be alleged here in objection ; for the very safety of the people itself, and the common safety of nations, prohibit the use of means which are repugnant to justice and 410 OF THE JUST CAUSES OF WAR, ETC. 308 probity. Why are certain means unlawful ? If we closely BOOK 1U - consider the point, if we trace it to its first principles, we shall CHAP ' m ' see that it is purely because the introduction of them would be pernicious to human society, and productive of fatal con- sequences to all nations. See particularly what we have said concerning the observance of justice (Book II. Chap. V.). For the interest, therefore, and even the safety of nations, we ought to hold it as a sacred maxim, that the end does not sanctify the means. And since war is not justifiable on any [ 309 ] other ground than that of avenging an injury received, or preserving ourselves from one with which we are threatened ( 26), it is a sacred principle of the law of nations, that an increase of power cannot, alone and of itself, give any one a right to take up arms in order to oppose it. No injury has been received from that power (so the question 2 44 - How supposes) ; we must, therefore, have good grounds to think the a PP* ar - ourselves threatened by him, before we can lawfully have re-^g S J give course to arms. Now power alone does not threaten an in- that right jury : it must be accompanied by the will. It is, indeed, very unfortunate for mankind, that the will and inclination to oppress may be almost always supposed, where there is a power of oppressing with impunity. But these two things are not necessarily inseparable : and the only right which we derive from the circumstance of their being generally or fre- quently united, is, that of taking the first appearances for a sufficient indication. When once a state has given proofs of injustice, rapacity, pride, ambition, or an imperious thirst of rule, she becomes an object of suspicion to her neighbours, whose duty it is to stand on their guard against her. They may come upon her at the moment when she is on the point of acquiring a formidable accession of power, may demand securities, and if she hesitates to give them, may prevent her designs by force of arms. The interests of nations are, in point of importance, widely different from those of indi- viduals : the sovereign must not be remiss in his attention to them, nor suffer his generosity and greatness of soul to super- sede his suspicions. A nation that has a neighbour at once powerful and ambitious has her all at stake. As men are under a necessity of regulating their conduct in most cases by probabilities, those probabilities claim their attention in proportion to the importance of the subject : and (to make use of a geometrical expression) their right to obviate a dan- ger is in a compound ratio of the degree of probability and the greatness of the evil threatened. If the evil in question be of a supportable nature, if it be only some slight loss, matters are not to be precipitated : there is no great danger in delaying our opposition to it till there be a certainty of our being threatened. But if the safety of the state lies at stake, our precaution and foresight cannot be extended too far. Must we delay to avert our ruin till it is become inevi- 411 309 OF THE JUST CAUSES OF WAR, ETC. BOOK in. table ? If the appearances are so easily credited, it is the .f.HAp. "" fault of that neighbour who has betrayed his ambition by several indications. If Charles the Second, King of Spain, instead of settling the succession on the Duke of Anjou, had appointed for his heir Louis XIV. himself to have tamely suffered the union of the monarchy of Spain with that of France, would, according to all the rules of human foresight, have been nothing less than delivering up all Europe to ser- vitude, or at least reducing it to the most critical and preca- rious situation. But then, if two independent nations think fit to unite, so as afterwards to form one joint empire, have they not a right to do it ? And who is authorized to oppose [ 810 ] them ? I answer, they have a right to form such a union, pro- vided the views by which they are actuated be not prejudicial to other states. Now, if each of the two nations in question be, separately and without assistance, able to govern and sup- port herself, and to defend herself from insult and oppression, it may be reasonably presumed that the object of their coali- tion is to domineer over their neighbours. And, on occasions where it is impossible or too dangerous to wait for an abso- lute certainty, we may justly act on a reasonable presumption. If a stranger levels a musket at me in the middle of a forest, I am not yet certain that he intends to kill me : but shall I, in order to be convinced of his design, allow him time to fire ? What reasonable casuist will deny me the right to anticipate him ? But presumption becomes nearly equivalent to certainty, if the prince who is on the point of rising to an enormous power has already given proofs of imperious pride and insa- tiable ambition. In the preceding supposition, who could have advised the powers of Europe to suffer such a formidable accession to the power of Louis the Fourteenth ? Too certain of the use he would have made of it, they would have joined in opposing it: and in this their safety warranted them. To say that they should have allowed him time to establish his dominion over Spain, and consolidate the union of the two monarchies, and that, for fear of doing him an injury, they should have quietly waited till he crushed them all, would not this be, in fact, depriving mankind of the right to regulate their conduct by the dictates of prudence, and to act on the ground of probability ? Would it not be robbing them of the liberty to provide for their own safety, as long as they have not mathematical demonstration of its being in danger ? It would have been in vain to have preached such a doctrine. The principal sovereigns of Europe, habituated, by the ad- ministration of Louvois, to dread the views and power of Louis XIV., carried their mistrust so far, that they would not even suffer a prince of the house of France to sit on the throne of Spain, though invited to it by the nation, whose approbation had sanctioned the will of her former sovereign. He ascend- ed it, however, notwithstanding the efforts of those who so 412 OF THE JUST CAUSES OF WAR, ETC. 310 strongly dreaded his elevation ; and it has since appeared that BOOK m. their policy was too suspicious. CHAP - m - It is still easier to prove, that, should that formidable pow- 45. An- er betray an unjust and ambitious disposition, by doing the other ca f e least injustice to another, all nations may avail themselves of e evi " the occasion, and, by joining the injured party, thus form a coalition of strength, in order to humble that ambitious poten- tate, and disable him from so easily oppressing his neighbours, or keeping them in continual awe and fear. For an injury gives us a right to provide for our future safety, by depriving the unjust aggressor of the means of injuring us ; and it is lawful and even praiseworthy to assist those who are op- pressed, or unjustly attacked. Enough has been said on this subject, to set the minds of politicians at ease, and relieve them from all apprehension that a strict and punctilious observance of justice in this par- [ 311 ] ticular would pave the way to slavery. It is perhaps wholly unprecedented that a state should receive any remarkable ac- cession of power, without giving other states just causes of complaint. Let the other nations be watchful and alert in repressing that growing power, and they will have nothing to fear. The emperor Charles V. laid hold on the pretext of religion, in order to oppress the princes of the empire, and subject them to his absolute authority. If, by following up his victory over the elector of Saxony, he had accomplished that vast design, the liberties of all Europe would have been endangered. It was therefore with good reason that France assisted the protestants of Germany : the care of her own safety authorized and urged her to the measure. When the same prince seized on the duchy of Milan, the sovereigns of Europe ought to have assisted France in contending with him for the possession of it, and to have taken advantage of the circumstance, in order to reduce his power within just bounds. Had they prudently availed themselves of the just causes which he soon gave them to form a league against him, they would have saved themselves the subsequent anxieties for their tottering liberty. But, suppose that powerful state, by the justice and circum- ? 46. Other spection of her conduct, affords us no room to take exception allowable to her proceedings, are we to view her progress with an eye e fe^ e f of indifference? Are we to remain quiet spectators of the^/ingta rapid increase of her power, and imprudently expose ourselves formidable to such designs as it may inspire her with : No, beyond all power, doubt. In a matter of so high importance, imprudent supine- ness would be unpardonable. The example of the Romans is a good lesson for all sovereigns. Had the potentates of those times concerted together to keep a watchful eye on the enterprises of Rome, and to check her incroachments, they would not have successively fallen into servitude. But force of arms is not the only expedient by which we may 2 K 2 413 ' OF THE JUST CAUSES OF WAR, ETC. 311 BOOK in. guard against a formidable power. There are other means, _CHAP. in. Q f a g en tl er nature, and which are at all times lawful. The most effectual is a confederacy of the less powerful sovereigns, who, by this coalition of strength, become able to hold the balance against that potentate whose power excites their alarms. Let them be firm and faithful in their alliance ; and their union will prove the safety of each. They may also mutually favour each other, to the exclusion of him whom they fear ; and by reciprocally allowing various advantages to the subjects of the allies, especially in trade, and refusing them to those of that dangerous potentate, they will augment their own strength, and diminish his, without affording him any just cause of complaint, since every one is at liberty to grant favours and indulgences at his own pleasure. 47. Poiiti- Europe forms a political system, an integral body, closely cai equiiibri- connected by the relations and different interests of the na- tions inhabiting this part of the world. It is not, as formerly, [ 312 ] a confused heap of detached pieces, each of which thought herself very little concerned in the fate of the others, and seldom regarded things which did not immediately concern her. The continual attention of sovereigns to every occur- rence, the constant residence of ministers, and the perpetual negotiations, make of modern Europe a kind of republic, of which the members each independent, but all linked together by the ties of common interest unite for the maintenance of order and liberty. Hence arose that famous scheme of the political balance, or the equilibrium of power ; by which is understood such a disposition of things, as that no one po- tentate be able absolutely to predominate, and prescribe laws to the others. 48. Ways The surest means of preserving that equilibrium would be, of main- ^hat no power should be much superior to the others, that all, taming it Qr a ^. ] eas ^g g rea ter part, should be nearly equal in force. Such a project has been attributed to Henry the Fourth:* but it would have been impossible to carry it into execution without injustice and violence. Besides, suppose such equality once established, how could it always be maintained by lawful means ? Commerce, industry, military pre-eminence, would soon put an end to it. The right of inheritance, vesting even in women and their descendants, a rule, which it was so absurd to establish in the case of sovereignties, but which nevertheless is established, would completely overturn the whole system. It is a more simple, an easier, and a more equitable plan, to have recourse to the method just mentioned, of forming confederacies in order to oppose the more powerful potentate, and prevent him from giving law to his neighbours. Such is the mode at present pursued by the sovereigns of Europe. * Of France. 414 OF THE JUST CAUSES OF WAE, ETC. 312 They consider the two principal powers, which, on that very BOOK m. account, are naturally rivals, as destined to be checks on each CHAP - m - other ; and they unite with the weaker, like so many weights thrown into the lighter scale, in order to keep it in equilibrium with the other. The house of Austria has long been the preponderating power : at present France is so in her turn. England, whose opulence and formidable fleets have a power- ful influence, without alarming any state on the score of its liberty, because that nation seems cured of the rage for con- quest, England, I say, has the glory of holding the political balance. She is attentive to preserve it in equilibrium : a system of policy, which is in itself highly just and wise, and will ever entitle her to praise, as long as she continues to pursue it only by means of alliances, confederacies, and other methods equally lawful. Confederacies would be a sure mode of preserving the equi- g 49. How librium, and thus maintaining the liberty of nations, did all he who de - princes thoroughly understand their true interests, and make ^JJ,^ the welfare of the state serve as the rule in all their proceed- may t, e re _ ings. Great potentates, however, are but too successful in strained, or gaining over partisans and allies, who blindly adopt all their even weak - views. Dazzled by the glare of a present advantage, seduced ened ' by their avarice, deceived by faithless ministers how many [ 313 ] princes become the tools of a power which will one day swallow up either themselves or their successors ! The safest plan, therefore, is to seize the first favourable opportunity, when we can, consistently with justice, weaken the potentate who destroys the equilibrium ( 45) or to employ every honourable means to prevent his acquiring too formidable a degree of power. For that purpose, all the other nations should be particularly attentive not to suffer him to aggrandize himself by arms : and this they may at all times do with jus- tice. For, if this prince makes an unjust war, every one has a right to succour the oppressed party. If he makes a just Avar, the neutral nations may interfere as mediators for an ac- commodation they may induce the weaker state to propose reasonable terms and offer a fair satisfaction, and may save her from falling under the yoke of a conqueror. On the offer of equitable conditions to the prince who wages even the most justifiable war, he has all that he can demand. The justice of his cause, as we shall soon sefc, never gives him a right to subju- gate his enemy, unless when that extremity becomes necessary to his own safety, or when he has no other mode of obtaining indemnification for the injury he has received. Now, that is not the case here, as the interposing nations can by other means procure him a just indemnification, and an assurance of safety. In fine, there cannot exist a doubt, that, if that formidable potentate certainly entertain designs of oppression and con quest, if he betray his views by his preparations and other 415 313 OF THE JUST CAUSES OF WAR, ETC. BOOK in. proceedings, the other states have a right to anticipate him ; CHAP " '" and if the fate of war declares in their favour, they are justi- fiable in taking advantage of this happy opportunity to weak- en and reduce a power too contrary to the equilibrium, and dangerous to the common liberty. This right of nations is still more evident against a sove- reign, who, from an habitual propensity to take up arms without reasons, or even so much as plausible pretexts, is con- tinually disturbing the public tranquillity. g 50. Be- This leads us to a particular question, nearly allied to the haviourai- preceding. When a neighbour, in the midst of a profound wards 1 ! t " peace, erects fortresses on our frontier, equips a fleet, aug- neighbour ments his troops, assembles a powerful army, fills his maga- preparing zincs, in a word when he makes preparations for war, are for war. we allowed to attack him, with a view to prevent the danger with which we think ourselves threatened ? The answer greatly depends on the manners and character of that neigh- bour. We must inquire into the reasons of those preparations, and bring him to an explanation : such is the mode of pro- ceeding in Europe : and if his sincerity be justly suspected, securities may be required of him. His refusal in this case, would furnish ample indication of sinister designs, and a suf- ficient reason to justify us in anticipating them. But if that [ 314 ] sovereign has never betrayed any symptoms of baseness and perfidy, and especially if at that time there is no dispute sub- sisting between him and us, why should we not quietly rest on his word, only taking such precautions as prudence ren- ders indispensable ? We ought not, without sufficient cause, to presume him capable of exposing himself to infamy by add- ing perfidy to violence. As long as he has not rendered his sincerity questionable, we have no right to require any other security from him. It is true, however, that, if a sovereign continues to keep up a powerful army in profound peace, his neighbours must not suffer their vigilance to be entirely lulled to sleep by his bare word; and prudence requires that they should keep themselves on their guard. However certain they may be of the good faith of that prince, unforeseen differences may in- tervene ; and shall they leave him the advantage of being pro- vided, at that juncture, with a numerous and well disciplined army, while they themselves will have only new levies to op- pose it ? Unquestionably no. This would be leaving them- selves almost wholly at his discretion. They are, therefore, under the necessity of following his example, and keeping, as he does, a numerous army on foot: and what a burden is this to a state ! Formerly, and without going any further back than the last century, it was pretty generally made an article in every treaty of peace, that the belligerent powers should disarm on both sides that they should disband their troops. If, in a time of profound peace, a prince was disposed to keep 416 OF THE DECLARATION OF WAR, ETC. 314 up any considerable number of forces, his neighbours took their BOOK m. measures accordingly, formed leagues against him, and obliged CHAP ' m ' him to disarm. Why has not that salutary custom been pre- served? The constant maintenance of numerous armies deprives the soil of its cultivators, checks the progress of population, and can only serve to destroy the liberties of the nation by whom they are maintained. Happy England ! whose situation exempts it from any considerable charge in supporting the instruments of despotism. Happy Switzer- land ! if, continuing carefully to exercise her militia, she keeps herself in a condition to repel any foreign enemies, without feeding a host of idle soldiers, who might one day crush the liberties of the people, and even bid defiance to the lawful authority of the sovereign. Of this the Roman legions furnish a signal instance. This happy method of a free republic, the custom of training up all her citizens to the art of war, renders the state respectable abroad, and saves it from a very pernicious defect at home. It would have been everywhere imitated, had the public good been everywhere the only object in view. Sufficient has now been said on the general principles for estimating the justice of a war. Those who are thoroughly acquainted with the principles, and have just ideas of the various rights of nations, will easily apply the rules to par- ticular cases. CHAP. IV. [ 315 ] OF THE DECLARATION OF WAR, AND OF WAR IN DUE CHAP, iv. FORM. (142) THE right of making war belongs to nations only as a 51. Da- remedy against injustice: it is the offspring of unhappy claration of necessity. This remedy is so dreadful in its effects, so war> destructive to mankind, so grievous even to the party who has recourse to it, that unquestionably the law of nature allows of it only in the last extremity, that is to say, when every other expedient proves ineffectual for the maintenance of justice. It is demonstrated in the foregoing chapter, that, in order to be justifiable in taking up arms, it is necessary 1. That we have a just cause of complaint. 2. That a rea- sonable satisfaction have been denied us. 3. The ruler of the nation, as we have observed, ought maturely to consider (142) See in general, Grotius, B. iii. c. iv. a. 8; and 1 Chitty's Com. Law, 378. C. 53 315 OF THE DECLARATION OF WAR, BOOK m. whether it be for the advantage of the state to prosecute his CHAP - Iy- right by force of arms. But all this is not sufficient. As it is possible that the present fear of our arms may make an thereof* 7 i m P ress i n on tne m ^ n d f our adversary, and induce him to do us justice, we owe this further regard to humanity, and especially to the lives and peace of the subjects, to declare to that unjust nation, or its chief, that we are at length going to have recourse to the last remedy, and make use of open force, for the purpose of bringing him to reason. This is called declaring war. All this is included in the Roman manner of proceeding, regulated in their fecial law. They first sent the chief of the feciales, or heralds, called pater pa- tratus, to demand satisfaction of the nation who had offended them ; and if, within the space of thirty-three days, that na- tion did not return a satisfactory answer, the herald called the gods to be witnesses of the injustice, and came away, say- ing that the Romans would consider what measures they should adopt. The king, and in after times the consul, here- upon asked the senate's opinion : and when war was resolved on, the herald was sent back to the frontier, where he de- clared it.* It is surprising to find among the Romans such jus- tice, such moderation and prudence, at a time too when, ap- parently, nothing but courage and ferocity was to be expected from them. By such scrupulous delicacy in the conduct of her wars, Rome laid a most solid foundation for her subsequent greatness. 52. What A declaration of war being necessary, as a further effort to it is to con- terminate the difference without the effusion of blood, by tam ' making use of the principle of fear, in order to bring the enemy to more equitable sentiments, it ought, at the same time that it announces our settled resolution of making war, T 316 ] to set forth the reasons which have induced us to take up arms. This is, at present, the constant practice among the powers of Europe. 53. it is After a fruitless application for justice, a nation may pro- simple or ceed to a declaration of war, which is then pure and simple. conditional. g u ^ ^ Q i nc j u( j e the whole business in a single act, instead of two separate ones, the demand of justice (called by the Ro- mans rerum repetitio) may, if we think proper, be accompa- nied by a conditional declaration of war, notifying that we will commence hostilities unless we obtain immediate satisfac- tion on such or such subject. In this case there is no neces- sity for adding a pure and simple declaration of war, the conditional one sufficing, if the enemy delays giving satis- faction. I 54. The If the enemy, on either declaration of war, offers equitable right to conditions of peace, we are bound to refrain from hostilities ; make war f or Ag soon ag justice is done to us, that immediately super- * Livy, lib. i. cap. 31. 413 AND OF WAR IN DUE FORM. 316 sedes all right to employ force, which we are not allowed to BOOK m. use unless for the necessary maintenance of our rights. To CHAP ' IY " these offers, however, are to be added securities; for we are the . off of under no obligation to suffer ourselves to be amused by empty Conditions proposals. The word of a sovereign is a sufficient security, as long as he has not disgraced his credit by any act of perfidy : and we should be contented with it. As to the conditions themselves, besides the principal subject, we have a right to demand a reimbursement of the expenses incurred in our pre- parations for war. It is necessary that the declaration of war be known to the ? 55. For- state against whom it is made. This is all which the natural mallties of a law of nations requires. Nevertheless, if custom has intro- J c ai duced certain formalities in the business, those nations who, by adopting the custom, have given their tacit consent to such formalities, are under an obligation of observing them, as long as they have not set them aside by a public renunciation (Prelim. 26). Formerly, the powers of Europe used to send heralds, or ambassadors to declare war ; at present, they con- tent themselves with publishing the declaration in the capital, in the principal towns, or on the frontiers : manifestoes are issued ; and, through the easy and expeditious channels of communication which the establishment of posts now affords, the intelligence is soon spread on every side. Besides the foregoing reasons, it is necessary for a nation 56. Otner to publish the declaration of war for the instruction and direc- reasons for tion of her own subjects, in order to fix the date of the rights * e o j ^ ssl " which belong to them from the moment of this declaration, pu biica- and in relation to certain effects which the voluntary law of tion.(i43) nations attributes to a war in form. Without such a public declaration of war, it would, in a treaty of peace, be too diffi- cult to determine those acts which are to be considered as the effects of war, and those that each nation may set down as in- juries of which she means to demand reparation. In the last treaty of Aix-la-Chapelle, between France and Spain on the one side, and England on the other, it was agreed that all the prizes taken before the declaration of war should be restored. He who is attacked and only wages defensive war, needs ? 57. D?- not to make any hostile declaration, the state of warfare be- fensi . vo v - ing sufficiently ascertained by the enemy's declaration, (HrJJStrSbl (143) But there seems to be no ab- was declared by Act of Congress, June eolute necessity for a formal declaration 18th, 1812. (Laws U. S. 1812, p. 227.) of war to render it legal. See obser- But war had existed, in fact, from March rations of Sir William Scott, in Nayede, 4th until May 13th, 1846, between 4 Rob. Rep. 252 ; Chitty's Law Nat. Mexico and the United States, without 29, 3. But, in England, the king must any formal declaration. The act of have assented to a war to render it Congress of 13th May, 1846, declares strictly legal. Brooke's Abrid. tit that, "by the act of the Republic of "Denizen," pi. 26; The Hoop, 1 Rob. Mexico," war existed between the coun- Rep. 196. C. { The late war between tries. (Laws U. States, 1846, p. 14.) { the United States and Great Britain 419 war. 317 OF THE DECLARATION OF WAR, BOOK in. open hostilities. In modern times, however, the sovereign CHAP. IY. w fr Q j s attacked, seldom omits to declare war in his turn, whether from an idea of dignity, or for the direction of his subjects. 58. When If the nation on whom we have determined to make war it may be w ifl no t admit any minister or herald to declare it, whatever omitted m ^e custom may otherwise be, we may content ourselves with publishing the declaration of hostilities within our own terri- tories, or on the frontier ; and if the declaration does not come to the knowledge of that nation before hostilities are commenced, she can only blame herself. The Turks imprison and maltreat even the ambassadors of those powers with whom they are determined to come to a rupture : it would be a perilous undertaking for a herald to go and declare war against them in their own country. Their savage disposition, therefore, supersedes the necessity of sending one. ?59. itisnot But no person being exempted from his duty for the sole to be omit- reason that another has been wanting in his, we are not to ted by way om ^ declaring war against a nation, previous to a commence- tfon 6talia men t f hostilities, because that nation has, on a former oc- casion, attacked us without any declaration. That nation, in so doing, has violated the law of nature ( 51) ; and her fault does not authorize us to commit a similar one. eo. Time The law of nations does not impose the obligation of declar- of the de- j n g war? w ith a view to give the enemy time to prepare for claration. an un j u g defence. The declaration, therefore, need not be made till the army has reached the frontiers ; it is even law- ful to delay it till we have entered the enemy's territories, and there possessed ourselves of an advantageous post : it must, however, necessarily precede the commission of any act of hostility. For thus we provide for our own safety, and equally attain the object of a declaration of war, which is, to give an unjust adversary the opportunity of seriously consi- dering his past conduct, and avoiding the horrors of war, by doing justice. Such was the conduct of that generous prince, Henry the Fourth, towards Charles Emanuel duke of Savoy ; who had wearied his patience by vain and fraudulent nego- tiations.* 61. Duty If he, who enters a country with an army kept under strict of the inha- discipline, declares to the inhabitants that he does not come as an enemy, that he will commit no violence, and will ac- quaint the sovereign with the cause of his coming, the in- tering a habitants are not to attack him ; and should they dare to at- country be- tempt it, he has a right to chastise them. But they are not to admit him into any strong-holds, nor can he demand ad- mission. It is not the business of subjects to commence hos- tilities without orders from their sovereign : but if they are brave and loyal, they will, in the mean time, seize on all the * See Sally's Memoirs. 420 AND OF WAR IN DUE FORM. 318 advantageous posts, and defend themselves against any at- BOOK m. tempt made to dislodge them. CHAP '. After a declaration of war on the part of the sovereign who g 62. Com- has thus invaded the country, if equitable conditions are not mencement offered him without delay, he may commence his operations ; of hostmties - for, I repeat it, he is under no obligation to suffer himself to be amused. But, at the same time, we are never to lose sight of the principles before laid down ( 26 and 51) concern- ing the only legitimate causes of war. To march an army into a neighbouring country by which we are not threatened, and without having endeavoured to obtain, by reason and jus- tice, an equitable reparation for the wrongs of which we com- plain, would be introducing a mode pregnant with evils to mankind, and sapping the foundations of the safety and tran- quillity of states. If this mode of proceeding be not exploded and proscribed by the public indignation and the concurrence of every civilized people, it will become necessary to continue always in a military posture, and to keep ourselves constantly on our guard, no less in times of profound peace, than during the existence of declared and open war. The sovereign declaring war can neither detain the persons \ 63. Con- nor the property of those subjects of the enemy who are duct to be within his dominions at the time of the declaration. They ^7^*' came into his country under the public faith. By permitting su bj ec ts of them to enter and reside in his territories, he tacitly promised an enemy, them full liberty and security for their return. He is there- who are in fore bound to allow them a reasonable time for withdrawing tl ^ OI ^ y with their effects ; and, if they stay beyond the term prescribed, * f th e e ^ he has a right to treat them as enemies, as unarmed enemies, ciaration of however. But, if they are detained by an insurmountable war - ( 144 ) impediment, as by sickness, he must necessarily, and for the same reasons, grant them a sufficient extension of the time. At present, so far from being wanting in this duty, sovereigns carry their attention to humanity still farther, so that foreign- ers, who are subjects of the state against which war is de- clared, are very frequently allowed full time for the settlement of their affairs. This is observed in a particular manner with regard to merchants ; and the case is moreover carefully pro- vided for in commercial treaties. The king of England has done more than this. In his last declaration of war against France, he ordained that all French subjects who were in his dominions should be at liberty to remain, and be perfectly secure in their persons and effects, "provided they demeaned themselves properly." We have said ( 56), that a sovereign is to make the de- ? 64. Pub- claration of war public within his dominions, for the informa- licat ^ a n r a f nd tion and direction of his subjects. He is also to make known his declaration of war to the neutral powers, in order to ac- (144) See in general 1 Chitty's Com. L. 414. C. 2L 421 318 OF THE DECLARATION OF WAR, BOOK m . quaint them with the justificatory reasons which authorize C1IAI> ' IV ' it, the cause which obliges him to take up arms, and to notify to them that such or such a nation is his enemy, that they may conduct themselves accordingly. We shall even see [ 319 ] that this is necessary in order to obviate all difficulty, when we come to treat of the right to seize certain things which neutral persons are carrying -,to the enemy, and of what is termed contraband, in time of war. This publication of the war may be called declaration, and that which is notified di- rectly to the enemy, denunciation ; and, indeed, the Latin term is denunciatio belli. War is at present published and declared by manifestoes. These pieces never fail to contain the justificatory reasons, good or bad, on which the party grounds his right to take up arms. The least scrupulous sovereign would wish to be thought just, equitable, and a lover of peace : he is sensible that a contrary reputation might be detrimental to him. The mani- festo implying a declaration of war, or the declaration itself, printed, published, and circulated throughout the whole state, contains also the sovereign's general orders to his subjects, re- lative to their conduct in the war.* g 65. Deco- In so civilized an age, it may be unnecessary to observe, mm and that, in those pieces which are published on the subject of war, tTbiTob- 011 ^ * 8 P r P er t abstain from every opprobrious expression in- served in dicative of hatred, animosity, and rage, and only calculated to the mani- excite similar sentiments in the bosom of the enemy. A prince festoes. ought to preserve the most dignified decorum, both in his words and in his writings. He ought to respect himself in the person of his equals : and, though it is his misfortune to be at variance with a nation, shall he inflame the quarrel by offen- sive expressions, and thus deprive himself even of the hopes of a sincere reconciliation ? Homer's heroes call each other " dog" and " drunkard:" but this was perfectly in character, since, in their enmity, they knew no bounds. Frederic Bar- barossa, and other emperors, and the popes their enemies, treated each other with as little delicacy. Let us congratu- late our age on the superior gentleness of its manners, and not give the name of unmeaning politeness to those attentions which are productive of real and substantial effects. 66. What Those formalities, of which the necessity is deducible from is a lawful the principles and the very nature of war, are the charac- teristics of a lawful war in due form (justum bellum.) Grotius says,f that, according to the law of nations, two things are requisite to constitute a solemn or formal war first, that it be * It is remarked as a very singular themselves properly," and, moreover, circumstance, that Charles the Se- his protection and favour to such of them cond, king of Great Britain, in his de- as might choose to 'emigrate to his do- claration of war against France, dated minions. February 9, 1668, promised security to f De Jure Belli et Pacis, lib. i. cap. French subjects who should " demean iii. Z 4. 422 AND OF WAR IN DUE FORM. 319 on both sides, made by tbe sovereign authority, secondly, BOOK m. that it be accompanied by certain formalities. These formali- CHAP - ** , ties consist in the demand of a just satisfaction (rerum repe- titio], and in the declaration of war, at least on the part of him who attacks ; for defensive war requires no declaration ( 57), nor even, on urgent occasions, an express order from the sovereign. In effect, these two conditions are necessarily [ 320 ] required in every war which shall, according to the law of nations, be a legitimate one, that is to say, such a war as nations have a right to wage. The right of making war be- longs only to the sovereign ( 4) ; and it is only after satis- faction has been refused to him ( 37), and even after he has made a declaration of war ( 51), that he has a right to take up arms. (145) A war in due form is also called a regular war, because cer- What a re- tain rules, either prescribed by the law of nature, or adopted S" 18 * war > by custom, are observed in it. noticed in Legitimate and formal warfare must be carefully distin- courts O f guished from those illegitimate and informal wars, or rather justice, Ac, predatory expeditions, undertaken either without lawful au- ( 146 -) thority or without apparent cause, as likewise without the J^Jj^" ** usual formalities, and solely with a view to plunder. Grotius gu i s hed relates several instances of the latter.* Such were the enter- from in- prises of the grandes compagnies which had assembled in formal and France during the wars with the English, armies of banditti, w ^ awful who ranged about Europe, purely for spoil and plunder : such were the cruises of the buccaneers, without commission, and in time of peace ; and such in general are the depredations of pirates. To the same class belong almost all the expeditions of the Barbary corsairs : though authorized by a sovereign, (145) Ante, the notes to the same sec- 62 ; Blackburne v. Thompson, 15 East, tions. C. 90, S. P.) observed, that, in order to as- (146) It has been laid down, that certain whether or not a war or state whenever the king's courts are open in of amity or neutrality subsists, it always a given country, it is time of peace in belongs to the Government of the coun- judgment of law ; but, when by hostile try to determine in what relation any measures such courts are shut up or in- other country stands towards it ; and terrupted, then it is said to be time of that is a point upon which courts of jus- war. Earl Lancaster's case, Bale's Pleas tice cannot decide ; (f. e. without evi- Crown, Part L c. 26, p. 344 ; Co. Litt. dence aliunde as to the declarations or 249, b. cited, and other points as to what resolutions of Government;) and the is war ; Elphinstone v. Bedreechund, most potent evidence upon such a sub- Knapp's Rep. 316. But at present, ject is the declaration of the state. And when in courts of justice, whether of if the state recognises any place as be- Common Law, Equity, Admiralty, or ing or as not being in the relation of Prize Court, it becomes necessary to hostility to this country, that is obliga- ascertain what is, or not, evidence of a tory on courts of justice. Per Lord El- war, or a peace, or neutrality, the same lenborough, 3 Camp. 66 ; and see other is now usually determined by distinct instances and authorities, 1 Chitty's acts of the state. Upon this question, Commercial Law, 393-4. C. { See, also, the following cases are material : Sir The U. States v. Palmer, 3 Wheat Rep. Wm. Grant (in case of Pelham Burke, 634, 635.} 1 Edward's Rep. Appendix D ; 3 Camp. * Lib. iii. cap. iv. 423 320 OF THE DECLARATION OF WAR, ETC. BOOK m. they are undertaken without any apparent cause, and from no CHAP. IY. Qtjjgj. mo tive than the lust of plunder. These two species of war, I say, the lawful and the illegitimate, are to be care- fully distinguished, as the effects and the rights arising from each are very different. 68. In order fully to conceive the grounds of this distinction, Grounds of ft [ s ne cessary to recollect the nature and object of lawful lc ~ war. It is only as the last remedy against obstinate injustice that the law of nature allows of war. Hence arise the rights which it gives, as we shall explain in the sequel : hence, like- wise, the rules to be observed in it. Since it is equally possi- ble that either of the parties may have right on his side, and since, in consequence of the independence of nations, that point is not to be decided by others ( 40), the condition of the two enemies is the same, while the war lasts. Thus, when a nation, or a sovereign, has declared war against another sovereign on account of a difference arisen between them, their war is what among nations is called a lawful and formal war ; and its effects are, by the voluntary law of nations, the same on both sides, independently of the justice of the cause, as we shall more fully show in the sequel.* Nothing of this kind is the case in an informal and illegitimate war, which is more properly called depredation. Undertaken without any right, without even an apparent cause, it can be productive of no lawful effect, nor give any right to the author of it. A nation attacked by such sort of enemies is not under any obligation to observe towards them the rules prescribed in formal war- [ 321 ] fare. She may treat them as robbers. (1) The inhabitants of Geneva, after defeating the famous attempt to take their city by escaladef, caused all the prisoners whom they took from the Savoyards on that occasion to be hanged up as robbers, who had come to attack them without cause and without a de- claration of war. Nor were the Genevese censured for this proceeding, which would have been detested in a formal war. * See chap. xii. of this book. are hastes humani generis. The 3fari- {(1) Pirates may be lawfully.^aptured anno Flora, 11 Wheat. Rep. l.{ by the public or private armed ships of -J- In the year 1602. any nation, in peace or war; for they 424 OF THE ENEMY, ETC. 321 CHAP. V. OF THE ENEMY, AND OF THINGS BELONGING TO THE ENEMY. THE enemy is he with whom a nation is at open war. The 69. wiio Latins had a particular term (Hostis) to denote a public enemy, is an en i f- and distinguished him from a private enemy (Inimicus). Our my ' ( language affords but one word for these two classes of per- sons, who ought, nevertheless, to be carefully distinguished. (147) As to the definition of an alien East, 489 ; Willan v. Patteson, 7 Taunt enemy, and of what is less than a gene- 439 ; Grotius, B. 3, c. 4, s. 8 ; Binker- ral enemy, and merely an hostile cha- shock, B. 1, c. 3 ; Chitty's L. Nat 1 to racier, or hostile residence, or hostile 27. The exceptions to that rule are trade, and of the modern decisions on the sometimes by express treaty ; (see 2 diversities ; see Boedes Lust, 5 Rob. Rep. Ward's Law of Nat. 358 ;) and in Great 233 ; 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, 394 Britain have been permitted by tempo- to 412, Id. Index, tit Hostile Character, rary acts, or by orders in council, author- and Chitty's L. Nat 30 to 64. izing the privy council to grant licenses. In some cases, the generous and be- (See Phillimore on Licenses, 5.) The neficial conduct of an enemy will obli- case of prisoners at war contracting for terate his hostile character, and preclude necessaries, constitutes an exception, his property from becoming subject to Antoine \. Morshead, 6 Taunt 237 seizure, as was beautifully illustrated 447 ; 1 Marsh. Rep. 558 ; Danby v. Mors- by Sir W. Scott's decision in Jonge J. head, 6 Taunt 332 ; Vattel, post, g 264, Baumann, where an English frigate, p. 414. with her officers and crew, having been Questions sometimes arise, whether saved from shipwreck by a foreign a commercial transaction between par- { neutral } vessel and crew, the former ties in different countries, afterwards ungratefully carried the latter into port at war with each other, as for instance, as prize; {asserting she had French Great Britain and America, pending property on board ; } but a restoration war, or on the eve of war, between was decreed, on the ground that such a these countries, was pactum illicitum, service had blotted out and obliterated If it be pending war, or in contempla- the character of an enemy, { if it had tion of it, and against its spirit, and not ever existed, which was not the fact. } expressly licensed by the Government, 1 Rob. Rep. 245 ; and see gg 178, post, then it is illegal. See the rule in the pp. 374-5. case of McGavon v. Stewart, in the Of the illegality of commerce between House of Lords, (14 July, 1830,) 4 Wils. subjects of belligerent states. Vattel is & Shaw, 193-4. An alien carrying on very succinct upon this, in modern trade in an enemy's country, though times, the most important consequence resident there also in the character of of war. In general it is illegal for the consul of a neutral state, has been con- private subjects of belligerents to have sidered an alien enemy, and as such any commercial transactions or deal- disabled to sue, and liable to confisca- ings between each other, in expecta- tion. Albrebtcht v. Sussmann, 2 Ves. it tion of or pending the war; for other- Beames, 323. wise assistance might be rendered to But these rules prohibiting com- the enemy, enabling them to protract merce between the subjects of bellige- the war, and, under colour of com- rent states, do not affect neutrals ; (ex- merce, secret communications might cepting, indeed, the liability to visitation be made injurious to the states of each and search;) and, therefore, actions country ; and therefore there is no such may be sustained in England by a neu- thing as a war for arms, and a peace tral on a promissory note given to him for commerce. The rule and the prin- by a British subject in an enemy's ciple upon which it is founded, are fully country, for goods sold by the neutral commented upon in the case of The to the latter there. Cowp. 363 ; Hour- Hoop, 1 Rob. Rep. 196; Potts v. Bell, 8 ret v. Morris, 3 Camp. 303. And it has Term Rep. 548; Mennett v. Bonham, 15 even been held, that an Englishman 54 2 L 2 435 321 OF THE ENEMY, AND OF THINGS BOOK in. A private enemy is one who seeks to hurt us, and takes plea- _CHAP. Y. gure j n ^ e ey -j t k a t k e fals us A public enemy forms claims against us, or rejects ours, and maintains his real or pretended rights by force of arms. The former is never innocent ; he fosters rancour and hatred in his heart. It is possible that the public enemy may be free from such odious sentiments, that he does not wish us ill, 1 and only seeks to maintain his rights. This observation is necessary in order to regulate the dispositions of our heart towards a public enemy. 70. AH When the sovereign or ruler of the state declares war the subjects against another sovereign, it is understood that the whole na- stote^aT ^ on declares war against another nation ; for the sovereign war are ene- represents the nation, and acts in the name of the whole so- mies, ciety (Book I. 40, 41 ;) and it is only in a body, and in her national character, that one nation has to do with another. Hence, these two nations are enemies, and all the subjects of the one are enemies to all the subjects of the other. In this particular, custom and principle are in accord. \ 71. and Enemies continue such wherever they happen to be. The continue to place of abode is of no consequence here. It is the political be enemies ^ies wn i cn determine the character. Whilst a man continues p aces ' a citizen of his own country, he is the enemy of all those with whom his nation is at war. But we must not hence conclude that these enemies may treat each other as such, wherever they happen to meet. Every one being master in his respect- ive country, a neutral prince will not allow them to use any violence in his territories. 5 72. Whe- Since women and children are subjects of the state, and ther women members of the nation, they are to be ranked in the class of and children enemies. But it does not thence follow that we are justifiable counted 6 *" * n treating them like men who bear arms, or are capable of enemies. bearing them. It will appear in the sequel, that we have not [ 322 ] the same rights against all classes of enemies. 73. Things When once we have precisely determined who our enemies belonging to are) j^ j s eag y ^o know what are the things belonging to the iemy enemy (res hostiles). We have shown that not only the sove- reign with whom we are at war is an enemy, but also his whole nation, even the very women and children. Every thing, therefore, which belongs to that nation, to the state, to the sovereign, to the subjects, of whatever age or sex, every thing of that kind, I say, falls under the description of things belonging to the enemy. domiciled in a foreign state fn amity commerce in a hostile country, is to be with this country may lawfully exer- considered as impressed with a hostile cise the privileges of a subject of the character, with reference at least to so place where he is resident, to trade with much of his commerce as may be con- a nation in hostility with England, 1 nected with that establishment; and Maule & Selwyn, 726, ted quaere. { See this, whether he maintains that esta- Livingtton v. The Maryland Int. Co. 7 blishment as a partner, or as a sole trade. Cranch, 506.} But, in general he who The Citto, 3 Rob. 38; The Portland, Id. maintains an establishment or house of 41 to 44. C. 426 OF THE ENEMY, ETC. 322 And, with respect to things, the case is the same as with BOOK m. respect to persons : things belonging to the enemy continue CHAP ~ v * . such, wherever they are. (1) But we are not hence to con- 74. con- clude, any more than in the case of persons ( 71), that we tinue sucn everywhere possess a right to treat those things as things be- ever y where - longing to the enemy. Since it is not the place where a thing is, which determines the nature of that thing, but the character of the person to whom it belongs, things belonging to neutral persons, which 75. Neu- happen to be in an enemy's country, or on board an enemy's tral ^ m .^f ships, are to be distinguished from those which belong to the ^ntzmy enemy. But it is the owner's business to adduce evident proof that they are his property: for, in default of such proof, a thing is naturally presumed to belong to the nation in whose possession it is found. (148) The preceding section relates to movable property: but the rule is different with respect to immovable possessions, such as landed estates. Since all these do in some measure 76. Lands belong to the nation, are part of its domain, of its territory, possessed by and under its government (Book I. 204, 235, Book ii. f n re ^ m rs ,g n 114) and since the owner is still a subject of the country country? as possessor of a landed estate, property of this kind does not cease to be enemy's property (res hostiles), though pos- sessed by a neutral foreigner. Nevertheless, war being now carried on with so much moderation and indulgence, protec- tions are granted for houses and lands possessed by foreigners in an enemy's country. For the same reason, he who declares war does not confiscate the immovable property possessed in his country by his enemy's subjects. By permitting them to purchase and possess such property, he has in that respect admitted them into the number of his subjects. But the in- come may be sequestrated, in order to prevent its being re- mitted to the enemy's country. Among the things belonging to the enemy, are likewise in- g 77. Things corporeal things, all his rights, claims, and debts, excepting, due to the however, those kind of rights granted by a third party, and in ^ y a ^ & which the grantor is so far concerned, that it is not a matter of indifference to him, in what hands they are vested. Such, [ 323 ~[ for instance, are the rights of commerce. But as debts are not of this number, war gives us the same rights over any sums of money due by neutral nations to our enemy, as it can give over his other property. (149) {(1) See Johnson et al. v. Twenty-one (149) This was the ancient law of Sales, Ac. Van Ness, Prize Causes, nations, Alt. Gen. v. Weedon, Parker p. 7.} Rep. 267, though certainly denied by (148) As to protection to neutrals' Rolle, J. At all events, it is now al- property and modern decisions, see 1 tered; see authorities, ante, 284, n. Chitty's Commercial Law, 385440; (134;) 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, Id. Index, tit. Neutrals; 1 Chitty's L. 423; 1 Chitty's L. Nat. 82 to 86. C. Nat 34, 54, 110113, 183; Id. Index, {But see Fairfax v. Hunter, 5 Cranch, tit. Neutrals. C. 19.} 427 823 OF THE ENEMY'S ALLIES, ETC. BOOK m. When Alexander, by conquest, became absolute master of CHAP ' Y ' Thebes, he remitted to the Thcssalians a hundred talents which they owed to the Thebans.* The sovereign has natu- rally the same right over what his subjects may owe to ene- mies, he may therefore confiscate debts of this nature, if the term of payment happen in the time of war ; or at least he may prohibit his subjects front paying while the war continues. But, at present, a regard to the advantage and safety of com- merce has induced all the sovereigns of Europe to act with less rigour in this point. (150) And as the custom has been generally received, he who should act contrary to it would violate the public faith ; for strangers trusted his subjects only from a firm persuasion that the general custom would be ob- served. The state does not so much as touch the sums which it owes to the enemy : money lent to the public is everywhere exempt from confiscation and seizure in case of war. CHAP. VI. CHAP, vr. OF THE ENEMY'S ALLIES OF WARLIKE ASSOCIATIONS OF AUXILIARIES AND SUBSIDIES. g 78. Trea- WE have sufficiently spoken of treaties in general, and ties relative shall here touch on this subject only in its particular relations to war. J.Q war> Treaties relating to war are of several kinds, and vary in their objects and clauses, according to the will of those who make them. Besides applying to them all that we have said of treaties in general (Book II. Ch. XII. &c.), they may also be divided into treaties real and personal, equal and un- equal, &c. But they have also their specific differences, viz. those which relate to their particular object, war. 79. Defen- Under this relation, alliances made for warlike purposes are ive and of- divided in general into defensive and offensive alliances. In fensive aih- ^ former, the nation engages only to defend her ally in case he be attacked : in the latter, she unites with him for the pur- pose of making an attack, of jointly waging war against another nation. Some alliances are both offensive and de- fensive ; and there seldom is an offensive alliance which is not also a defensive one. But- it is very usual for alliances to be I 324 ] purely defensive : and these are in general the most natural and lawful. It would be a tedious and even a useless task to enumerate in detail all the varieties incident to such alliances. 428 * Grotius, de Jure Belli & Pacis, lib. iii. cap. viii. \ 4. (150) See ivpra, n. (149). OF THE ENEMY'S ALLIES, ETC. 324 Some are made, without restriction, against all opponents : in BOOK m. others, certain states are excepted : others again are formed CHAP - TI - , against such or such a nation expressly mentioned by name. But a difference of great importance to be observed, espe- so. Dif- cially in defensive alliances, is that between an intimate and ference be- complete alliance, in which we agree to a union of interests, J^ associa- and another, in which we only promise a stated succour. The tions and alliance in which we agree to a union of interests is a warlike auxiliary association : each of the parties acts with his whole force ; all treaties, the allies become principals in the war ; they have the same friends and the same enemies. But an alliance of this nature is more particularly termed a warlike association, when it is offensive. When a sovereign, without directly taking part in the war g si. Auxi- made by another sovereign, only sends him succours of troops liai r troops, or ships, these are called auxiliaries. The auxiliary troops serve the prince to whom they are sent, according to their sovereign's orders. If they are purely and simply sent without restriction, they are to serve equally on the offensive and the defensive ; and for the particulars of their operations, they are to obey the directions of the prince to whose assistance they come. Yet this prince has not the free and entire disposal of them, as of his own subjects : they are granted to him only for his own wars ; and he has no right to transfer them, as auxiliaries, to a third power. Sometimes, this succour from a potentate who does not di- ? 82. Subsi- rectly take part in the war, consists in money : and then it is dies - called a subsidy. This term is now often taken in another sense, and signifies a sum of money annually paid by one sovereign to another, in return for a body of troops which the latter furnishes to the other to carry on his wars, or keeps in readiness for his service. The treaties for procuring such a resource are. called subsidiary treaties. France and England have at present such treaties existing with several of the northern powers and princes in Germany, and continue them even in times of peace. In order, now, to judge of the morality of these several trea- g 83. When ties or alliances, of their legitimacy according to the law of a nation ia nations, we must, in the first place, lay down this incontro- J^ .^ 8 ^* vertible principle, that It is lawful and commendable to sue- ^ T cour and assist, by all possible means, a nation engaged in a just war ; and it is even a duty incumbent on every nation, to give such assistance, when she can give it without injury to herself. But no assistance whatever is to be afforded to him who is engaged in an unjust war. There is nothing in this which is not demonstrated by what we have said of the common duties of nations towards each other. (Book II. Ch. I.) To support the cause of justice when we are able, is always commendable : but, in assisting the unjust, we partake of his crime, and become, like him, guilty of injustice. 324 OF THE ENEMY'S ALLIES, ETC. BOOK in. If, to the principle we have now laid down, you add the CHAP. TI. consideration of what a nation owes to her own safety, and g 84. and to of the care which it is so natural and so fit that she should make alii- take to put herself in a condition to resist her enemies, you w^j 68 f r w ^ *^e more rea >dily perceive how clear a right a nation has T*325 ~\ * ma ^ e warlike alliances, and especially defensive alliances, whose sole tendency is to maintain all parties in the quiet and secure possession of their property. But great circumspection is to be used in forming such alliances. Engagements by which a nation may be drawn into a war at a moment when she least expects it, ought not to be contracted without very important reasons, and a direct view to the welfare of the state. We here speak of alliances made in time of peace, and by way of precaution against future contingencies. 85. Alii- If there be question of contracting an alliance with a na- ances made tion already engaged in a war, or on the point of engaging tion'actaaii * n one ' * wo things are to be considered : 1. The justice of engaged in 7 that nation's quarrel. 2. The welfare of the state. If the war. war which a prince wages, or is preparing to wage, be un- just, it is not allowable to form an alliance with him ; for injustice is not to be supported. If he is justifiable in taking up arms, it still remains to be considered whether the welfare of the state allows or requires us to embark in his quarrel : for it is only with a view to the welfare of the state that the sovereign ought to use his authority : to that all his measures should tend, and especially those of the most important nature. What other consideration can authorize him to expose his people to the calamities of war? 86. Tacit x As it is only for the support of a just war that we are al- ciause in lowed to give assistance or contract alliances, every alliance, every war- ever y wa rlike association, every auxiliary treaty, contracted wee* l ' ky wa y f anticipation in time of peace, and with no view to any particular war, necessarily and of itself includes this tacit clause that the treaty shall not be obligatory except in case of a just war. On any other footing, the alliance could not be validly contracted. (Book II. 161, 168.) But care must be taken that treaties of alliance be not thereby reduced to empty and delusive formalities. The tacit restriction is to be understood only of a war which is evidently unjust ; for otherwise a pretence for eluding treaties would never be wanting. Is there question of contracting an alliance with a power actually at war ? It behooves you most religiously to weigh the justice of his cause : the judg- ment depends solely on you, since you owe him no assistance any further than as his quarrel is just, and your own circum- stances make it convenient for you to embark in it. But when once engaged, nothing less than the manifest injustice of his cause can excuse you from assisting him. In a doubt- OF THE ENEMY'S ALLIES, ETC. 325 ful case, you are to presume that your ally has justice on his BOOK m. Bide ; that being his concern. CHAP ' VI> But if you entertain strong doubts, you may very fairly and coromendably interpose to effect an accommodation. Thus you may bring the justice of the cause to the test of evidence, by discovering which of the contending parties re- [ 326 ] fuses to accede to equitable conditions. As every alliance implies the tacit clause above mentioned, g 87. To re- he who refuses to succour his ally in a war that is manifestly fse suc- unjust is not chargeable with a breach of alliance. ^-H,* When alliances have thus been contracted beforehand, the ^^breach question is, to determine, in the course of events, those cases O f alliance, in which our engagements come in force, and we are bound to act in consequence of the alliance. This is what is called \ 88. What cams fcederis, or case of the alliance, and is to be discovered *^ d ^J. in the concurrence of the circumstances for which the treaty has been made, whether those circumstances have been ex- pressly specified in it, or tacitly supposed. Whatever has been promised in the treaty of alliance is due in the casus foederis, and not otherwise. As the most solemn treaties cannot oblige any one to favour \ 89. It an unjust quarrel ( 86): the casus foederis never takes place never takes in a war that is manifestly unjust. SrJTst war In a defensive alliance, the casus foederis does not exist im- UDJUS mediately on our ally being attacked. It is still our duty to % 90. HOW examine whether he has not given his enemy just cause to itexis ^ ina make war against him : for we cannot have engaged to un- j^ ensi dertake his defence with the view of enabling him to insult others, or to refuse them justice. If he is in the wrong, we must induce him to offer a reasonable satisfaction ; and if his enemy will not be contented with it, then, and not till then, the obligation of defending him commences. But if the defensive alliance contains a guarantee of all I 91. and in the territories at that time possessed by the ally, the casus a treat y of foederis immediately takes place whenever those territories S"* 111 * 6 - are invaded or threatened with an invasion. If they are attacked for a just cause, we must prevail on our ally to give satisfaction ; but we may on good grounds oppose his being deprived of his possessions, as it is generally with a view to our own security that we undertake to guaranty them. On the whole, the rules of interpretation, which we have given in an express chapter,* are to be consulted, in order to de- termine, on particular occasions, the existence of the casus foederis. If the state that has promised succours finds herself un- g 92. The able to furnish them, her inability alone is sufficient to dis- succour is pense with the obligation ; and if she cannot give . her as- not due sistance without exposing herself to evident danger, thfal * Book II. chap. xvii. 431 826 OF THE ENEMY'S ALLIES, ETC. BOOK in. circumstance also dispenses with it. This would be one of thoge cageg j n w hi c k a treaty becomes pernicious to the furnish it, state? an( j therefore not obligatory (Book II. 160). But pubiitTaflty we ^ ere s P ea k f an imminent danger, threatening the very would be existence of the state. The case of such a danger is tacitly exposed. and necessarily reserved in every treaty. As to remote dangers, or those of no extraordinary magnitude, since [ 327 ] they are inseparable from every military alliance, it would be absurd to pretend that they should create an exception ; and the sovereign may expose the nation to them in consider- ation of the advantages which she reaps from the alliance. In virtue of these principles, we are absolved from the obligation of sending assistance to an ally while we are ourselves engaged in a war which requires our whole strength. If we are able to oppose our own enemies and to assist our ally at the same time, no reason can be pleaded for such dispensation. But, in such cases, it rests with our- selves to determine what our circumstances and strength will allow. It is the same with other things which may have been promised, as, for instance, provisions. There is no obligation to furnish an ally Avith them when we want them for our own use. f 93. Other We forbear to repeat in this place what we have said of cases. various other cases, in discoursing of treaties in general, as, for example, of the preference due to the more ancient ally (Book II. 167), and to a protector (ibid. 204), of the meaning to be annexed to the term "allies," in a treaty in which they are reserved (ibid. 309). Let us only add, on this last question, that, in a warlike alliance made against all opponents, the allies ezcepted, this exception is to be understood only of the present allies. Otherwise, it would afterwards be easy to elude the former treaty by new alliances ; and it would be impossible for us to know either what we are doing in concluding such a treaty, or what we gain by it. Two of the A case which we have not spoken of is this : Three parties in powers have entered into a treaty of defensive alliance : two co^n * to 6 a ^ tnem ( l uarre ^> an( * ma ke war on eacn otn er : how is the rupture. & third to act ? The treaty does not bind him to assist either the one or the other ; for it would be absurd to say that he has promised his assistance to each against the other, or to one of the two in prejudice of the other. The only obliga- tion, therefore, which the treaty imposes on him, is to en- deavour, by the interposition of his good offices, to effect a reconciliation between his allies ; and if his mediation proves unsuccessful, he remains at liberty to assist the party who appears to have justice on his side. g 94 Re- To refuse an ally the succours due to him, without having fusai of the any just cause to allege for such refusal, is doing him an in- cc rs . jury, since it is a violation of the perfect right which we gave him by a formal engagement. I speak of evident cases, it OP THE ENEMY S ALLIES, ETC. 6Z being then only that the right is perfect ; for, in those of a BOOK m. doubtful nature, it rests with each party to judge what he is CHAP ' "" able to do ( 92) : but he is to judge maturely and impartially, * of * n and to act with candour. And as it is an obligation naturally a iance " incumbent on us, to repair any damage caused by our fault, and especially by our injustice, we are bound to indemnify an ally for all the losses he may have sustained in consequence of our unjust refusal. How much circumspection, therefore, is to be used in forming engagements, which we cannot re- fuse to fulfil without material injury to our affairs or our [ 328 ] honour, and which, on the other hand, if complied with, may be productive of the most serious consequences. An engagement, which may draw us into a war, is of great g 95. The moment : in it the very existence of the state is at stake, enemy's He who in an alliance promises a subsidy or a body of auxilia- associates * ries, sometimes imagines that he only risks a sum of money or a certain number of soldiers ; whereas he often exposes himself to war and all its calamities. The nation against whom he furnishes assistance will look upon him as her enemy ; and should her arms prove successful, she will carry the war into his country. But it remains to be determined whether she can do this with justice, and on what occasions. Some authors* decide in general, that whoever joins our enemy, or assists him against us with money, troops, or in any other manner whatever, becomes thereby our enemy, and gives us a right to make war against him : a cruel decision, and highly inimical to the peace of nations ! It cannot be supported by principles ; and happily the practice of Europe stands in opposition to it. It is true, indeed, that every associate of my enemy is himself my enemy. It is of little consequence whether any one makes war on me directly, and in his own name, or under the auspices of another. Whatever rights war gives me against my principal enemy, the like it gives me against all his associates : for I derive those rights from the right t security, from the care of my own defence ; and I am equally attacked by the one and the other party. But the question is, to know whom I may lawfully account my ene- my's associate, united against me in war. First, in that class I shall rank all those who ar& really g 96. Those united in a warlike association with my enemy, and who who make a make a common cause with him, though it is- only in the common . name of that principal enemy that the war is carried on. inTe^Imy There is no need of proving this. In the ordinary and open are his asso- warlike associations, the war is carried on in the name of all ciates > the allies, who are all equally enemies ( 80). In the second place, I account as associates of my enemy, f 97. And" those who assist him in his war without being obliged to it those wh(v * See Wolf, Jus Gentium, 32 730 and 737. 55 2 M 433 328 OF THE ENEMY'S ALLIES, ETC. BOOK in. by any treaty. Since they freely and voluntarily declare CHAP. YI. a g a i ns t nu>j they, of their own accord, choose to become my assist him, enemies. If they go no farther than furnishing a determined without be- succour, allowing some troops to be raised, or advancing to g itb llged mone y> an d> in other respects, preserve towards me the ac- treaties; customed relations of friendship and neutrality, I may overlook that ground of complaint ; but still I have a right to call them to account for it. This prudent caution of not always coming to an open rupture with those who give such assistance to our enemy, that we may not force them to join him with all their strength, this forbearance, I say, has gradually introduced the custom of not looking on such as- sistance as an act of hostility, especially when it consists J_ 329 ] only in the permission to enlist volunteers. How often have the Switzers granted levies to France, at the same time that they refused such an indulgence to the house of Austria, though both powers were in alliance with them ! How often have they allowed one prince to levy troops in their country, and refused the same permission to his enemy, when they were not in alliance with either ! They granted or denied that favour according as they judged it most expedient for themselves ; and no power has ever dared to attack them on that account. But if prudence dissuades us from making use of all our right, it does not thereby destroy that right. A cautious nation chooses rather to overlook certain points, than unnecessarily to increase the number of her enemies. 98. Or Thirdly, those, who, being united with my enemy by an who are in offensive alliance, actively assist him in the war which he aTliance 81 Declares a g a "*st me, those, I say, concur in the injury in- with^im. tended against me. They show themselves my enemies, and I have a right to treat them as such. Accordingly, the Switzers, whose example we have above quoted, seldom grant troops except for defensive war. To those in the service of France, it has ever been a standing order from their sove- reigns, not to carry arms against the empire, or against the states of the house of Austria in Germany. In 1644, the captains of the Neufchatel regiment of Guy, on information that they were destined to serve under Marshal Turenne, in Germany, declared that they would rather die than disobey their sovereign and violate the alliances of the Helvetic body. Since France has been mistress of Alsace, the Swit- zers who serve in her armies never pass the Rhine to attack the empire. The gallant Daxelhoffer, captain of a Berne company in the French service, consisting of 200 men, and of which his four sons formed the first rank, seeing the gene- ral would oblige him to pass the Rhine, broke his espontoon, and marched back with his company to Berne. g 98, How Even a defensive alliance made expressly against me, or a defensive j(Vhich amounts to the same thing) concluded with my enemy alliance as- Curing the war, or on the certain prospect of its speedy de 434 OF THE ENEMY S ALLIES, ETC. 329 claration, is an act of association against me ; and if followed .BOOK m. by effects, I may look on the party who has contracted it as CHAF - YI - . my enemy. The case is here precisely the same as that of a sociates nation assisting my enemy without being under any obliga- with tho tion to do so, and choosing of her own accord to become my encmy- enemy. (See 97.) A defensive alliance, though of a general nature, and made 1 100. An- before any appearance of the present war, produces also the other case - same effect, if it stipulates the assistance of the whole strength of the allies : for in this case it is a real league, or warlike association ; and, besides, it were absurd that I should be debarred from making war on a nation who op- poses me with all her might, and thus exhausting the source of those succours with which she furnishes my enemy. In what light am I to consider an auxiliary who comes to make war on me at the head of all his forces ? It would be mock- ery on his part, to pretend that he is not my enemy. What [ 330 ] more could he do, were he openly to declare himself such ? He shows no tenderness for me on the occasion : he only wishes that a tender regard should be paid to himself. And shall I suffer him to preserve his provinces in peace, and secure from all danger, whilst he is doing me all the mischief in his power ? No ! the law of nature, the law of nations, obliges us to be just ; but does not condemn us to be dupes. But, if a defensive alliance has not been made against me 101. in in particular, nor concluded at the time when I was openly what cae it preparing for war, or had already begun it, and if the allies does ! not , , & . , ' , . . . , , , J , 6 ,, ' i n p -i produce the have only stipulated in it that each of them shall furnish a game effcct> stated succour to him who shall be attacked, I cannot require that they should neglect to fulfil a solemn treaty, which they had an unquestionable right to conclude without any injury to me. In furnishing my enemy with assistance, they only acquit themselves of a debt : they do me no wrong in dis- charging it; and, consequently, they afford me no just grounds for making war on them( 26). Neither can I say that my safety obliges me to attack them; for I should thereby only increase the number of my enemies, and, in- stead of a slender succour which they furnish against me, should draw on myself the whole power of those nations. It is, therefore, only the troops which they send as auxili- aries, that I am to consider as enemies. These are actually united with my enemies and fighting against me. The contrary principles would tend to multiply wars, and spread them beyond all bounds, to the common ruin of na- tions. It is happy for Europe, that, in this instance, the established custom is in accord with the true principles. A prince seldom presumes to complain of a nation's contributing to the defence of her ally by furnishing him with succours which were promised in former treaties, in treaties that were not made against that prince in particular. In the last 435 330 OF THE ENEMY'S ALLIES, ETC. BOOK in. war, the United Provinces long continued to supply the queen CHAP. YI. Q jj un g ar y w ith subsidies, and even with troops ; and France never complained of these proceedings till those troops marched into Alsace to attack the French frontier. Switzer- land, in virtue of her alliance with France, furnishes that crown with numerous bodies of troops, and, nevertheless, lives in peace with all Europe*. There is one case, however, which might form an exception to the general rule ; it is that of a defensive war which is evidently unjust. For in such case there no longer exists any obligation to assist an ally ( 86, 87, 89). If you under- take to do it without necessity, and in violation of your duty, you do an injury to the enemy, and declare against him out of mere wantonness. But this is a case that very rarely occurs between nations. There are few defensive wars with- out at least some apparent reason to warrant their justice or necessity. Now, on any dubious occasion, each state is sole judge of the justice of her own cause ; and the presumption is in favour of your ally ( 86). Besides, it belongs to you alone to determine what conduct on your part will be con- [ 331 ] formable to your duties and to your engagements ; and con- sequently nothing less than the most palpable evidence can authorize the enemy of your ally to charge you with sup- porting an unjust war, contrary to the conviction of your own conscience. In fine, the voluntary law of nations ordains, that, in every case susceptible of doubt, the arms of both parties shall, with regard to external effects, be accounted equally lawful (40). g 102. Whe- The real associates of my enemy being my enemies, I ther it be have against them the same rights as against the principal necessary to ene my ( 95). And as their own conduct proclaims them Gainst th" m y enem i es > an( * tne 7 ta ke up arms against me in the first enemy's as- instance, I may make war on them without any declaration : Bociatos. the war being sufficiently declared by their own act. This is especially the case of those who in any manner whatever concur to make an offensive war against me ; and it is like- wise the case of all those whom we have mentioned in 96, 97, 98, 99, 100. But it is not thus with those nations which assist my ene- my in a defensive war : I cannot consider them as his asso- ciates ( 101). If I am entitled to complain of their furnish- ing him with succours, this is a new ground of quarrel between me and them. I may expostulate with them, and, on not re- ceiving satisfaction, prosecute my right, and make war on them. But in this case there must be a previous declaration ( 51). The example of Manlius, who made war on the Galatians for having supplied Antiochus with troops, is not a case in point. Grotius* censures the Roman general for * De Jure Belli et Pacis, lib. iii. cap. iii. $ 10. OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. 331 having begun that war without a declaration. The Galatians, BOOK m. in furnishing troops for an offensive war against the Romans, CHAP - YT y had declared themselves enemies to Rome. It would appear, indeed, that, on peace being concluded with Antiochus, Man- lius ought to have waited for orders from Rome before he attacked the Galatians ; and then, if that expedition was con- sidered as a fresh war, he should have not only issued a de- claration, but also made a demand of satisfaction, previous to the commencement of hostilities ( 51). But the treaty with the king of Syria had not yet received its consummation : and it concerned that monarch alone, without making any mention of his adherents. Therefore Manlius undertook the expedition against the Galatians, as a consequence or a remnant of the war with Antiochus. This is what he himself very well observed in his speech to the senate ;* and he even added, that his first measure was to try whether he could bring the Galatians to reasonable terms. Grotius more appo- sitely quotes the example of Ulysses and his followers, blaming them for having, without any declaration of war, attacked the Ciconians, who had sent succours to Priam during the siege of Troy.f CHAP. VII. [ 332 ] OF NEUTRALITY AND THE PASSAGE OF TROOPS THROUGH A CHAP - Yn - NEUTRAL COUNTRY. (151) NEUTRAL nations are those who, in time of war, do not 2 103 - ^ eu - take any part in the contest, but remain common friends to tral nations * both parties, without favouring the arms of the one to the prejudice of the other. Here we are to consider the obliga- tions and rights flowing from neutrality. In order rightly to understand this question, we must avoid $ 104. Con- confounding what may lawfully be done by a nation that is duct to b free from all engagements, with what she may do if she e x- observed by pects to be treated as perfectly neutral in a war. As long as a neutral nation wishes securely to enjoy the advantages of her neutrality, she must in all things show a strict impartial- ity towards the belligerent power* : for, should she favour one of the parties to the prejudice of the other, she cannot com- * Livy, lib. xxxviii. mercial Law, 4364, 383 i90 ; Id. f Grotius, uli supra, not. 3. Index, tit Neutrals, and in Chitty's L. (151) The modern illustrating deci- Nat 14, 3454, 153; and Id. Index, sions upon neutrals, and neutrality, -will tit Neutrals. C. be found collected in 1 Chitty's Com- 2*2 437 382 OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. BOOK in. plain of being treated by him as an adherent and confederate CHAP. YII. Q f y g engj-Qy. jj er neutrality would be a fraudulent neu- trality, of which no nation will consent to be the dupe. It is sometimes suffered to pass unnoticed, merely for want of abi- lity to resent it ; we choose to connive at it, rather than excite a more powerful opposition against us. But the present ques- tion is, to determine what may lawfully be done, not what prudence may dictate according to circumstances. Let us therefore examine, in what consists that impartiality which a neutral nation ought to observe. It solely relates to war, and includes two articles, 1. To give no assistance when there is no obligation to give it, nor voluntarily to furnish troops, arms, ammunition, or any thing of direct use in war. I do not say, "to give assistance equally," but "to give no assistance:" for it would be absurd that a state should at one and the same time assist two nations at war with each other ; and, besides, it would be impossible to do it with equality. The same things, the like number of troops, the like quantity of arms, of stores, &c., furnished in different circumstances, are no longer equivalent succours. 2. In whatever does not relate to war, a neutral and impartial nation must not refuse to one of the parties, on account of his present quarrel, what she grants to the other. This does not deprive her of the liberty to make the advantage of the state still serve as her rule of conduct in her negotiations, her friendly connections, and her commerce. When this reason induces her to give preferences in things which are ever at the free disposal of the possessor, she only makes use of her right, and is not chargeable with partiality. But to refuse any of [ 333 ] those things to one of the parties purely because he is at war with the other, and because she wishes to favour the latter, would be departing from the line of strict neutrality, g 105. An I have said that a neutral state ought to give no assistance ally may to either of the parties, when "under no obligation to give it." Buecltrd'ue T1 " 8 restriction is necessary. We have already seen, that from him" wnen a sovereign furnishes the moderate succour due in virtue and remain of a former defensive alliance, he does not become an asso- neuter. ciate in the war( 101). He may, therefore, fulfil his en- gagement, and yet observe a strict neutrality. Of this, Europe affords frequent instances. g 106. Right When a war breaks out between two nations, all other states of remain- that are not bound by treaties are free to remain neuter ; and, ing neuter, jf e ither of the belligerent powers attempted to force them to a junction with him, he would do them an injury, inasmuch as he would be guilty of an infringement on their independ- ency in a very essential point. To themselves alone it be- longs to determine whether any reason exists to induce them to join in the contest ; and there are two points which claim their consideration : 1. The justice of the cause. If that be evident, injustice is not to be countenanced : on the contrary, 438 OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. it is generous and praiseworthy to succour oppressed inno- BOOK m. cence, when we possess the ability. If the case be dubious, CHAP - YIt - the other nations may suspend their judgment, and not engage in a foreign quarrel. 2. When convinced which party has justice on his side, they have still to consider whether it be for the advantage of the state to concern themselves in this affair, and to embark in the war. A nation making war, or preparing to make it, often pro- 2 10 ?- Tre a- poses a treaty of neutrality to a state of which she entertains iie{ neu " suspicions. It is prudent to learn betimes what she has to expect, and not to run the risk of a neighbour's suddenly join- ing with the enemy in the heat of the war. In every case where neutrality is allowable, it is also allowable to bind our- selves to it by treaty. Sometimes even necessity renders this justifiable. Thus, although it be the duty of all nations to assist oppressed inno- cence (Book II. 4), yet, if an unjust conqueror, ready to in- vade his neighbour's possessions, makes me an offer of neu- trality when he is able to crush me, what can I do better than to accept it ? I yield to necessity ; and my inability dis- charges me from a natural obligation. The same inability would even excuse me from a perfect obligation contracted by an alliance. The enemy of my ally threatens me with a vast superiority of force : my fate is in his hand : he requires me to renounce the liberty of furnishing any assistance against him. Necessity, and the care of my own safety, absolve me from my engagements. Thus it was that Louis the Four- teenth compelled Victor Amadeus, duke of Savoy, to quit the party of the allies. But, then, the necessity must be very urgent. It is only the cowardly, or the perfidious, who avail themselves of the slightest grounds of alarm, to violate their promises and desert their duty. In the late war, the king [ 334 ] of Poland, elector of Saxony, and the king of Sardinia, firmly held out against the unfortunate course of events, and, to their great honour, could not be brought to treat without the con- currence of their allies. Another reason renders these treaties of neutrality useful, ? 108 - Ad - and even necessary. A nation that wishes to secure her own dltlonal re *- peace, when the flames of war are kindling in her neighbour- ing these hood, cannot more successfully attain that object than by con- treaties. eluding treaties with both parties, expressly agreeing what each may do or require in virtue of the neutrality. This is a sure mode to preserve herself in peace, and to obviate all dis- putes and cavils. Without such treaties, it is to be feared that disputes will 109. Foun- often arise respecting what neutrality does or does not allow. dation of the This subject presents many questions which authors have dis- ~ cussed with great heat, and which have given rise to the most dangerous quarrels between nations. Yet the law of nature and of nations has its invariable principles, and affords rules 439 334 OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. BOOK m. on this head, as well as on the others. Some things also have CHAP, vir. g rown j nto cus tom among civilized nations, and are to be con- formed to by those who would not incur the reproach of un- justly breaking the peace.* As to the rules of the natural law of nations, they result from a just combination of the laws of war, with the liberty, the safety, the advantages, the com- merce, and the other rights of 1 neutral nations. It is on this principle that we shall lay down the following rules : \ no. How First, no act on the part of a nation, which falls within the bellowed exerc * se f her rights, and is done solely with a view to her moneylent own g 0( ^ without partiality, without a design of favouring and every ' one power to the prejudice of another, no act of that kind, kind of I say, can in general be considered as contrary to neutrality; things sold, nor does ft ec0 me such, except on particular occasions, when brealh'of ** cannot ta k e pl ace without injury to one of the parties, who neutrality, has then a particular right to oppose it. Thus, the besieger has a right to prohibit access to the place besieged (see 117 in the sequel). Except in cases of this nature, shall the quar- rels of others deprive me of the free exercise of my rights in the pursuit of measures which I judge advantageous to my people ? Therefore, when it is the custom of a nation, for the purpose of employing and training her subjects, to permit levies of troops in favour of a particular power to whom she thinks proper to intrust them, the enemy of that power can- not look upon such permissions as acts of hostility, unless they are given with a view to the invasion of his territories, or the [ 335 ] support of an odious and evidently unjust cause. He cannot even demand, as matter of right, that the like favour be granted to him, because that nation may have reasons for refusing him, which do not hold good with regard to his ad- versary ; and it belongs to that nation alone to judge of what best suits her circumstances. The Switzers, as we have al- ready observed, grant levies of troops to whom they please ; and no power has hitherto thought fit to quarrel with them on that head. It must, however, be owned, that, if those levies were considerable, and constituted the principal strength of my enemy, while, without any substantial reason being al- leged, I were absolutely refused all levies whatever, I should have just cause to consider that nation as leagued with my enemy ; and, in this case, the care of my own safety would authorize me to treat her as such. The case is the same with respect to money which a nation may have been accustomed to lend out at interest. If the sovereign, or his subjects, lend money to my enemy on that * The following is an instance : It at liberty, because they were then fallen was determined by the Dutch, that, on into the power of a nation that was in a vessel's entering a neutral port, after neutrality with the belligerent parties. having taken any of the enemies of her The same rule had been observed by nation prisoners on the high seas, she England in the war between Spain and should be obliged to set those prisoners the United Provinces. OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. 335 footing, and refuse it to me because they have not the same BOOK nr - confidence in me, this is no breach of neutrality. They lodge their property where they think it safest. If such preference be not founded on good reasons, I may impute it to ill-will against me, or to a predilection for my enemy. Yet if I should make it a pretence for declaring war, both the true , principles of the law of nations, and the general custom hap- pily established in Europe, would join in condemning me. While it appears that this nation lends out her money purely for the sake of gaining an interest upon it, she is at liberty to dispose of it according to her own discretion ; and I have no right to complain. But if the loan were evidently granted for the purpose of enabling an enemy to attack me, this would be concurring in the war against me. If the troops, above alluded to, were furnished to my enemy by the state herself, and at her own expense, or the money in like manner lent by the state, without interest, it would no longer be a doubtful question whether such assistance were incompatible with neutrality. Further, it may be affirmed on the same principles, that if a nation trades in arms, timber for ship-building, vessels, and warlike stores, I cannot take it amiss that she sells such things to my enemy, provided she does not refuse to sell them to me also at a reasonable price. She carries on her trade without any design to injure me ; and by continuing it in the same manner as if I were not engaged in war, she gives me no just cause of complaint. In what I have said above, it is supposed that my enemy ? in. Trad goes himself to a neutral country to make his purchases. Let of neutral us now discuss another case , that of neutral nations resort- ^se'which 1 ing to my enemy's country for commercial purposes. It is ar e at. war. certain, that, as they have no part in my quarrel, they are under no obligation to renounce their commerce for the sake of avoiding to supply my enemy with the means of carrying [ 336 ] on the war against me. Should they affect to refuse selling me a single article, while at the same time they take pains to convey an abundant supply to my enemy, with an evident in- tention to favour him, such partial conduct would exclude them from the neutrality they enjoyed. But if they only con- tinue their customary trade, they do not thereby declare them- selves against my interest : they only exercise a right which they are under no obligation of sacrificing to me. (152) (152) It must be a continuance only Deb. 935. It has even been holden that of such customary trade. See Home on a British-born subject, while domiciled Captures, 215233 ; De Tattet v. Tay- in a neutral country, may legally trade lor, 4 Taunt. 238 ; Sell v. Reid, 1 Maule from that country with a state at war & Selw. 727; and an able speech of with this country. Bell v. Reid, 1 Maule Lord Erskine, 8th March, 1808, upon A Selwyn, 727. C. the orders in Council ; 10 Cobbett's Parl. 56 441 336 OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. BOOK m. On the other hand, whenever I am at war with a nation, CHAP. YII. k |. n m y ga f e ty and welfare prompt me to deprive her, as far as possible, of every thing which may enable her to resist or injure me. In this instance, the law of necessity exerts its full force. If that law warrants me, on occasion, to seize what be- longs to other people, will it not likewise warrant me to inter- cept every thing belonging to'war, which neutral nations are carrying to my enemy ? Even if I should, by taking such mea- sures, render all those neutral nations my enemies, I had better run that hazard, than suffer him who is actually at war with me thus freely to receive supplies and collect additional strength to oppose me. It is, therefore, very proper, and perfectly conformable to the law of nations (which disapproves of mul- tiplying the causes of war), not to consider those seizures of the goods of neutral nations as acts of hostility. When I have notified to them my declaration of war against such or such a nation, if they will afterwards expose them- selves to risk in supplying her with things which serve to carry on war, they will have no reason to complain if their goods fall into my possession ; and I, on the other hand, do not declare war against them for having attempted to convey such goods. They suffer, indeed, by a war in which they have no concern ; but they suffer accidentally. I do not oppose their right : I only exert my own ; and if our rights clash with and reciprocally injure each other, that circumstance is the effect of inevitable necessity. Such collisions daily hap- pen in war. When, in pursuance of my rights, I exhaust a country from which you derive your subsistence, when I be- siege a city with which you carried on a profitable trade, I doubtless injure you ; I subject you to losses and inconve- niences ; but it is without any design of hurting you. I only make use of my rights, and consequently do you no injustice. But that limits may be set to these inconveniences, and that the commerce of neutral nations may subsist in as great a de- gree of freedom as is consistent with the laws of war, there are certain rules to be observed, on which Europe seems to be generally agreed. g 112. Con- The first is, carefully to distinguish ordinary goods which traband have no relation to war, from those that are peculiarly sub- goods, servient to it. Neutral nations should enjoy perfect liberty to trade in the former : the belligerent powers cannot with any rea- [ 337 ] * n refuse it, or prevent the importation of such goods into the enemy's country : the care of their own safety, the necessity of self-defence, does not authorize them to do it, since those things will not render the enemy more formidable. An attempt to interrupt or put a stop to this trade would be a violation of the rights of neutral nations, a flagrant injury to them ; necessity, as we have above observed, being the only reason which can authorize any restraint on their trade and navigation to the ports of the enemy. England and the United Provinces 442 OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. 337 having agreed, in the treaty of Whitehall, signed on the 22d of BOOK m. August, 1689, to notify to all states not at war with France, CHAP ' TU ' that they would attack every ship bound to or coming from any port of that kingdom, and that they beforehand declared every such ship to be a lawful prize, Sweden and Denmark, from whom some ships had been taken, entered into a coun- ter-treaty on the 17th of March, 1693, for the purpose of maintaining their rights and procuring just satisfaction. And the two maritime powers, being convinced that the complaints of the two crowns were well founded, did them justice.* Commodities particularly useful in war, atid the importation of which to an enemy is prohibited, are called contraband goods. Such are arms, ammunition, timber for ship-building, every kind of naval stores, horses, and even provisions, in cer- tain junctures, when we have hopes of reducing the enemy by famine.t(153) But, in order to hinder the transportation of contraband $ 113 - whe - goods to an enemy, are we only to stop and seize them, P a 7~ ^a^ma ing the value to the owner, or have we a right to confiscate beconfi8ca- them ? Barely to stop those goods would in general prove ted. an ineffectual mode, especially at sea, where there is no pos- sibility of entirely cutting off all access to the enemy's har- bours. Recourse is therefore had to the expedient of confis- cating all contraband goods that we can seize on, in order that the fear of loss may operate as a check on the avidity of gain, and deter the merchants of neutral countries from supplying the enemy with such commodities. And, indeed, it is an ob- ject of such high importance to a nation at war to prevent, as far as possible, the enemy's being supplied with such articles * See other instances in Grotius de sold both arms and provisions to the Jure Belli et Pacis, lib. iii. cap. i. 5, Spaniards, they could not with propri- not. 6. ety have attempted to forbid neutral f The Pensionary De Witt, in a let- nations to carry on a similar trade, ter of January 14, 1654, acknowledges (Grotius, Hist of the Disturbances in that it would be contrary to the law of the Low Countries, book vi.) Never- nations to prevent neutrals from carry- theless, in 1646, the United Provinces ing corn to an enemy's country; but published an edict prohibiting their he says that we may lawfully prevent own subjects in general, and even neu- them from supplying the enemy with tral nations, to carry either provisions cordage and other materials for the rig- or any other merchandise to Spain, be- ging and equipment of hip of war. cause the Spaniards, "after having, In 1597, queen Elizabeth would not under the appearance of commerce, al- allow the Poles and Danes to furnish lured foreign vessels to their ports, de- Spain with provisions, much less with tained them, and made use of them as arms, alleging that, "according to the ships of war." And for this reason, rules of war, it is lawful to reduce an the same edict declared that " the con- enemy even by famine, with the view federates, when blocking up their ene- of obliging him to sue for peace." The mies' ports, would seize upon every United Provinces, finding it necessary vessel they saw steering towards those to obsftrvo u greater degree of circum- places." Ibid, book xv. p. 572. Ed. spection, did not prevent neutral na- A.D. 1797. *ions from carrying on every kind of (153) What are contraband goods, commerce with Spain. It is true, in- see 1 Chitty's Comml. L. 444 449, doed, that, while their own subjects and Chitty's L. Nat. 119 128. C. 338 OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. BOOK in. as will add to his strength and render him more dangerous, . CHAP - TII- that necessity and the care of her own welfare and safety au- thorize her to take effectual methods for that purpose, and to declare that all commodities of that nature, destined for the enemy, shall be considered as lawful prize. On this account she notifies to the neutral states her declaration of war( 63;) whereupon, the letter usually 'give orders to their subjects to refrain from all contraband commerce with the nations at war, declaring, that if they are captured in carrying on such trade, the sovereign will not protect them. This rule is the point where the general* custom of Europe seems at present fixed, after a number of variations, as will appear from the note of Grotius, which we have just quoted, and particularly from the ordinances of the kings of France, in the years 1543 and 1584, which only allow the French to seize contraband goods, and to keep them on paying the value. The modern usage is cer- tainly the most agreeable to the mutual duties of nations, and the best calculated to reconcile their respective rights. The nation at war is highly interested in depriving the enemy of all foreign assistance ; and this circumstance gives her a right to consider all those, if not absolutely as enemies, at least as people that feel very little scruple to injure her, who carry to her enemy the articles of which he stands in need for the sup- port of the war. She, therefore, punishes them by the con- fiscation of their goods. Should their sovereign undertake to protect them, such conduct would be tantamount to his fur- nishing the enemy with those succours himself: a measure which were undoubtedly inconsistent with neutrality. When a nation, without any other motive than the prospect of gain, is employed in strengthening my enemy, and regardless of the irreparable evil which she may thereby entail upon me,* she is certainly not my friend, and gives me a right to consider and treat her as an associate of my enemy. In order, there- fore, to avoid perpetual subjects of complaint and rupture, it has, in perfect conformity to sound principles, been agreed that the belligerent powers may seize and confiscate all con- traband goods which neutral persons shall attempt to carry to their enemy, without any complaint from the sovereign of those merchants ; as, on the other hand, the power at war does not impute to the neutral sovereigns these practices of their subjects. Care is even taken to settle every particular of this kind in treaties of commerce and navigation. J 114. We cannot prevent the conveyance of contraband goods, Searching without searching neutral vessels that we meet at sea : we [ 339 ] have therefore a right to search them. Some powerful nations * In our time, the king of Spain pro- with military stores ; and thus he hibited all Hamburgh ships from en- obliged the Hamburghers to cancel their tering his harbours, because that city treaty with the Barbarians. Ed. A. D, had engaged to furnish the Algerines 1797. 441 OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. have indeed, at different times, refused to submit to this BOOK m. search. "After the peace of Vervins, Queen Elizabeth, con- CHAP ' YIT '. tinuing the war against Spain, requested permission of the neutral king of France to cause all French ships bound for Spain to shl P s -( 154 ) be searched, in order to discover whether they secretly car- ried any military stores to that country : but this was refused, as an injury to trade, and a favourable occasion for pillage."* At present, a neutral ship refusing to be searched, would from that proceeding alone be condemned as a lawful prize. (154) But, to avoid inconveniences, oppression, and every other abuse, the manner of the search is settled in the treaties of navigation and commerce. It is the established custom at present to give full credit to the certificates, bills of lading, &c., produced by the master of the ship, unless any fraud appear in them, or there be good reasons for suspecting it. (155) If we find an enemy's effects on board a neutral ship, we 115. Ene- seize them by the rights of war : (156) but we are naturally m y' s P r - J ^ ' J perty on (154) As to the right of visiting and searching neutral ships, see the cele- brated letter of the Duke of Newcastle to the Prussian Secretary, A. D. 1752 ; 1 Collect. Jurid. 138; and Halliday's Life of Lord Mansfield; Elements of General History, vol. iii. p. 222 ; Mar- shall on Insurance, book i. ch. 8, sect. 5 ; Garrets v. Kensington, 8 Term Rep. 230 ; Lord Erskine's Speech upon Or- ders in council, 8 March, 1808; 10 Cobbett's Parl. Deb. 955 ; Baring upon Orders in Council, p. 102. Clearly at this day the right of search exists prac- tically as well as theoretically. The right of search, and of the con- sequence of resistance, and of the pa- pers and documents that ought to be found on board the neutral vessels, are most clearly established by the best modern decisions ; see Barker v. Slakes, 9 East Rep. 283, and numerous other cases, collected in 1 Chitty's Commer- cial Law, 482489; Chitty's L. Nat 190 199. The international law upon the subject will be found admi- rably summed up by Sir \Vm. Scott, in his Judgment in the case of the Maria, 1 Rob. Rep. 346, and 1 Edwards's Rep. 208, confirming the authority of Vat- tel, and on which he thus concludes: " I stand with confidence upon all fair principles of reason, upon the distinct authority of Vattel, and upon the insti- tutes of other great maritime countries, as well as those of our own country, when I venture to lay it down that, by the law of nations, as now understood, a deliberate and continued resistance of search, on the part of a neutral ves- sel, to a lawful cruiser, is followed by the legal consequences of confiscation." And see Dispatch, 3 Rob. Rep. 278; Elsabc, 4 Rob. Rep. 408 ; Pennsylvania, 1 Acton's Rep. 33; Saint Juan Bap- tista, 5 Rob. Rep. 33 ; Maria, 1 Rob. Rep. 340; Mentor, 1 Edward, 268; Ca- therina Elizabeth, 5 Rob. Rep. 232. See the modern French view of the right of visitation and search, Cours de Droits Public, torn. i. p. 84. Paris : A. D. 1830. C. { And the American, The Eleanor, 2 Wheat. Rep. 345; The U. States v. La Jeune Eugenie, 2 Mass. Rep. 409 ; The Marianna Flora, 3 Mass. Rep. 116 ; Maley v. Shattuck, 3 Cranch, 458.} * Grotius, ubi supra. (155) As to papers and documents that ought to be on board, see 1 Chit- ty's Commercial Law, 487 489, and Chitty's L. Nat. 196199, and autho- rities there collected. The owner of the neutral vessel has no remedy for loss of voyage, or other injury occasioned by the reasonable exercise of the right of search (infra note), but he may in- sure against the risk ; Barker v. Slakes, 9 East, 283. C. {See Maley v. Shat- tuck, 3 Cranch, 458. } (15.6) Particular states have relaxed the rigour of this rule, and, by express treaty, granted immunity, by establish- ing a maxim, " Free ships, free goods ;" see instances, 5 Rob. Rep. 52; 6 Rob. Rep. 24, 41 358. C. 2N 445 339 OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. BOOK m. bound to pay the freight to the master of the vessel, who is CHAP - YII v not to suffer by such seizure.* (157) board a neu- The effects of neutrals, found in an enemy's ships, are to trai ship.^ |j e restored to the owners, against whom there is no right of j- ral '^y confiscation ; but without any allowance for detainer, decay, on board an & c - (158) The loss sustained by the neutrals on this occa- enemy's sion is an accident to which they exposed themselves by em- shi P- barking their property in an enemy's ship ; and the captor, in exercising the rights of war, is not responsible for the ac- cidents which may thence result, any more than if his cannon kills a neutral passenger who happens unfortunately to be on board an enemy's vessel. (158) 117. Trade Hitherto we have considered the commerce of neutral na- t * ns W ^ *^ e ter " tor ^ es f tne enemy in general. There is a P ar ti cu l ar case i n which the rights of war extend still farther. All commerce with a besieged town is absolutely prohibited. Blockade. If I lay siege to a place, or even simply blockade it, I have a right to hinder any one from entering, and to treat as an enemy whoever attempts to enter the place, or carry any thing to the besieged, without my leave ; for he opposes my undertaking, and may contribute to the miscarriage of it, and thus involve me in all the misfortunes of an unsuccessful war. [ 340 ] King Demetrius hanged up the master and pilot of a vessel carrying provisions to Athens at a time when he was on the point of reducing that city by famine.f In the long and bloody war carried on by the United Provinces against Spain * {See the rule as recognised by the 1 Molloy, 1 18 j and Twilling Ruet, 5 United States. The Nereide, 9 Cranch, Rob. Rep. 82. C. 110.} "I have obtained," said the am- (158) 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, bassador Boreel, in a letter to the Grand 440 ; Grotius, b. iii. c. vi. vi. ; Mar- Pensionary, De Witt, " the abrogation shall on Insurance, b. i. c. viii. v. Tho of that pretended French law, that ene- loss of voyage and damage may be in- mies' property involves in confiscation the sured against; Barker v. Slakes, 9 East, property of friends ; so that, if hence- Rep. 283. C. forward any effects belonging to the (159) As to violation of blockade in enemies of France be found in a free general, see the modern decisions, 1 Dutch vessel, those effects alone shall Chitty's Commercial Law, 449 and be liable to confiscation; and the vessel 460492; Chitty's L. Nat. 129 144, shall be released, together with all the and 259; and see, as to the distinction other property on board. But I find it between a military and commercial impossible to obtain the object of the blockade, and their effect, 1 Acton's Rep. twenty-fourth, article of my instructions, 128. On a question of violation of which gays, that the immunity of the vee- blockade, Sir W. Scott said, " Three set shall extend to the eargo, even if enc- things must be proved 1st, the exist- mies' property." De Witt's Letters and ence of an actual blockade ; 2dly, the Negotiations, vol. i. p. 80. Such a law knowledge of the party supposed to have as the latter would be more natural than offended ; and 3dly, some act of viola- the former. Edit A. D. 1797. tion, either by going in or coming out (157) [Schwartz v. The Int. Co. of with a cargo laden after the commence- North America, 3 Wash. C. C. Rep. ment of blockade." In case of Betsy, 117.J But, in these cases, the freight 1 Rob. Rep. 92, and Nancy, 1 Acton's to be paid is not necessarily to be mea- Rep. 59. C. \Fitzsimmons v. TheNew- sured by the terms of the charter-party, port Ins. Co., 4 Cranch, 185. } f Plutarch, in Demetrio. OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. 340 for the recovery of their liberties, they would not suffer the BOOK m. English to carry goods to Dunkirk, before which the Dutch CHAP - Yn - fleet lay.* A neutral nation preserves, towards both the belligerent us. im- powers, the several relations Avhich nature has instituted be- partial offi- tween nations. She ought to show herself ready to render ^ lg of neu ' them every office of humanity reciprocally due from one na- tion to another : she ought, in every thing not directly relat- ing to war, to give them all the assistance in her power, and of which they may stand in need. Such assistance, however, must be given with impartiality ; that is to say, she must not refuse any thing to one of the parties on account of his being at war with the other ( 104). But this is no reason why a neutral state, under particular connections of friendship and good neighbourhood with one of the belligerent powers, may not, in every thing that is unconnected with war, grant him all those preferences which are due to friends: much less does she afford any grounds of exception to her conduct, if, in commerce, for instance, she continues to allow him such indul- gences as have been stipulated in her treaties with him. She ought, therefore, as far as the public welfare will permit, equally to allow the subjects of both parties to visit her terri- tories on business, and there to purchase provisions, horses, and, in general, every thing they stand in need of, unless she has, by a treaty of neutrality, promised to refuse to both parties such articles as are used in war. Amidst all the wars which disturb Europe, the Switzers preserve their territories m a state of neutrality. Every nation indiscriminately is al- lowed free access for the purchase of provisions, if the coun- try has a surplus, and for that of horses, ammunition, and arms. An innocent passage is due to all nations with whom a state \ 119. Pas- is at peace (Book II. 123) ; and this duty extends to troops sa s e of as well as to individuals. But it rests with the sovereign of *P S h the country to judge whether the passage be innocent ; and it ne ntrfi is very difficult for that of an army to be entirely so. In the country, late wars of Italy the territories of the republic of Venice and those of the pope sustained very great damage by the passage of armies, and often became the theatre of the war. Since, therefore, the passage of troops, and especially that \ 120. Pas- of a whole army, is by no means a matter of indifference, he sa s e to be who desires to march his troops through a neutral country, asked - must apply for the sovereign's permission. To enter his ter- ritory without his consent, is a violation of his rights of sove- reignty and supreme dominion, by virtue of which, that coun- try is not to be disposed of for any use whatever, without his express or tacit permission. Now, a tacit permission for [ 341 ] the entrance of a body of troops is not to be presumed, since Grotius, ubi supra. 447 341 OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. BOOK in. their entrance may be productive of the most serious conse- CHAP - Tn - quences. 121. it ^ tne neutral sovereign has good reasons for refusing a may be re- passage, he is not obliged to grant it, the passage in that fused for case being no longer innocent. good rea- j n a jj d ou btful cases we must submit to the judgment of a 122. in *he proprietor respecting the' innocence of the use we desire what case it to make of things belonging to another (Book II. 128, 130), may be and must acquiesce in his refusal, even though we think it forced. unjust. If the refusal be evidently unjust, if the use, and, in the case now before us, the passage be unquestionably in- nocent, a nation may do herself justice, and take by force what is unjustly denied to her. But we have already observed, that it is very difficult for the passage of an army to be ab- solutely innocent, and much more so for the innocence to be very evident. So various are the evils it may occasion, and the dangers that may attend it, so complicated are they in their nature, and so numerous are the circumstances with which they are connected, that, to foresee and provide for every thing, is next to impossible. Besides, self-interest has so powerful an influence on the judgments of men, that if he who requires the passage is to be the judge of its innocence, he will admit none of the reasons brought against it ; and thus a door is opened to continual quarrels and hostilities. The tranquillity, therefore, and the common safety of nations require that each should be mistress of her own territory, and at liberty to refuse every foreign army an entrance, when she has not departed from her natural liberties in that respect, by treaties. From this rule, however, let us except those very uncommon cases which admit of the most evident demonstra- tion that the passage required is wholly unattended with in- convenience or danger. If, on such an occasion, a passage be forced, he who forces it will not be so much blamed as the na- tion that has indiscreetly subjected herself to this violence. Another case, which carries its own exception on the very face of it, and admits not of the smallest doubt, is that of ex- treme necessity. Urgent and absolute necessity suspends all the rights of property (Book II. 119, 123) : and if the pro- prietor be not under the same pressure of necessity as you, it is allowable for you, even against his will, to make use of what belongs to him. When, therefore, an army find themselves exposed to imminent destruction, or unable to return to their own country, unless they pass through neutral territories, they have a right to pass in spite of the sovereign, and to force their way, sword in hand. But they ought first to request a passage, to offer securities, and pay for whatever damages they may occasion. Such was the mode pursued by the Greeks on their return from Asia, under the conduct of Agesilaus.* * Plutarch's Life of Agesilaus. OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. 342 Extreme necessity may even authorize the temporary seizure BOOK m. of a neutral town, and the putting a garrison therein, with a CHAP - Tn - view to cover ourselves from the enemy, or to prevent the exe- cution of his designs against that town, when the sovereign is not able to defend it. But when the danger is over, we must immediately restore the place, arid pay all the charges, in- conveniences, and damages, which we have occasioned by seizing it. When the passage is not of absolute necessity, the bare 123. The danger which attends the admission of a powerful army into fear of dan - our territory, may authorize us to refuse them permission to^ a " t ^" enter. We may have reason to apprehend that they will be f usalj tempted to take possession of the country, or at least to act as masters while they are in it, and to live at discretion. Let it not be said, with Grotius,* that he who requires the passage is not to be deprived of his right on account of our unjust fears. A probable fear, founded on good reasons, gives us a right to avoid whatever may realize it ; and the conduct of nations affords but too just grounds for the fear in question. Besides, the right of passage is not a perfect right, unless in a case of urgent necessity, or when we have the most perfect evidence that the passage is innocent. But, in the preceding section, I suppose it impracticable to 124. or a obtain sufficient security which shall leave us no cause to ap- demand of prehend any hostile attempts or violent proceedings on the g^"!^ part of those who ask permission to pass. If any such secu- cur it y . rity can be obtained, (and the safest one is, to allow them to pass only in small bodies, and upon delivering up their arms, as has been sometimes required, f) the reason arising from fear no longer exists. But those who wish to pass should consent to give every reasonable security required of them, and con- sequently submit to pass by divisions and deliver up their arms, if the passage be denied them on any other terms. The choice of the security they are to give does not rest with them. Host- ages, or a bond, would often prove very slender securities. Of what advantage will it be to me to hold hostages from one who will render himself master over me ? And as to a bond, it is of very little avail against a priuce of much superior power. But, is it always incumbent on us to give every security a-g 125. Whe- nation may require, when we wish to pass through her terri- ther always tories ? In the first place, we are to make a distinction be- n f cessai 7 to tween the different reasons that may exist for our passing SndTS. through the country; and we are next to consider the man- curity re- ners of the people whose permission we ask. If the passage quired, be not essentially necessary, and can be obtained only on sus- picious or disagreeable conditions, we must relinquish all idea * Book ii. chap. ii. g 13, note 5. j- By the Eleans, and the ancient inhabitants of Cologne. See Grotius, ibid. W 2s2 449 342 OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. BOOK m. of it, as in the case of a refusal ( 122). But, if necessity au- JJHAP. TII. th or i zes me t p asSj the conditions on which the passage will be granted may be accepted or rejected, according to the man- ners of the people I am treating with. Suppose I am to cross [ 343 ] the country of a barbarous, savage, and perfidious nation, shall I leave myself at their discretion, by giving up my arms and causing my troops to march in divisions ? No one, I pre- sume, will condemn me to take so dangerous a step. Since necessity authorizes me to pass, a kind of new necessity arises for my passing in such a posture as will secure me from any ambuscade or violence. I will offer every security that can be given without foolishly exposing myself; and if the offer is rejected, I must be guided by necessity and prudence, and, let me add, by the most scrupulous moderation, in order to avoid exceeding the bounds of that right which I derive from necessity. g 126. E- If the neutral state grants or refuses a passage to one of the quality to be parties at war, she ought, in like manner, to grant or refuse observed to- ^ ^ ^ other, unless a change of circumstances affords her wards both , . , . , TT . parties as to substantial reasons for acting otherwise. Without such rea- the passage, sons, to grant to one party what she refuses to the other, would be a partial distinction, and a departure from the line of strict neutrality. g 107. No When I have no reason to refuse a passage, the party against complaint whom it is granted has no right to complain of my conduct, hes agamst muc j 1 } ess to ma k e jt the ground of a hostile attack upon me, etate for since I have done no more than what the law of nations en- granting a joins ( 119). Neither has he any right to require that I passage. should deny the passage ; for he must not pretend to hinder me from doing what I think agreeable to my duty. And even on those occasions when I might with justice refuse permission to pass, I am at liberty to abstain from the exertion of my right. But especially when I should be obliged to support my refusal by the sword, who will take upon him to complain of my having permitted the war to be carried into his country, rather than draw it on myself? No sovereign can require that I should take up arms in his favour, unless obliged to it by treaty. But nations, more attentive to their own interests than to the observance of strict justice, are often very loud on this pretended subject of complaint. In war, especially, they stick at no measures ; and if by their threats they can induce a neighbouring state to refuse a passage to their enemy, the generality of their rulers consider this conduct only as a stroke of good policy. state may " ^ powerful state will despise these unjust menaces : firm refuse it and unshaken in what she thinks due to justice and to her own from a fear reputation, she will not suffer herself to be diverted by the fear of the re- O f a groundless resentment : she will not even bear the menace. the^pMite But a wea ^ nation, unable to support her rights, will be under party; a necessity of consulting her own safety; and this important OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. 343 concern will authorize her to refuse a passage, which would BOOK expose her to dangers too powerful for her to repel. nr. AP. VII- Another fear may also warrant her in refusing a passage, 129. And namely, that of involving her country in the disorders and lest hcr calamities of war. For, even if the party against whom a c un .^ y , ..',, T_ j . . should be- passage is requested, should observe such moderation as not come the to employ menaces for the purpose of intimidating the neutral theatre of nation into a refusal, he will hardly fail to demand a passage war - for himself also : he will march to meet his enemy ; and thus [ 344 ] the neutral country will become the theatre of war. The in- finite evils of such a situation are an unexceptionable reason for refusing the passage. In all these cases, he who attempts to force a passage, does an injury to the neutral nation, and gives her most just cause to unite her arms with those of his adversary. The Switzers, in their alliances with France, have promised not to grant a passage to her enemies. They ever refuse it to all sovereigns at war, in order to secure their fron- tiers from that calamity ; and they take care that their terri- tory shall be respected. But they grant a passage, to recruits, who march in small bodies, and without arms. The grant of permission to pass includes a grant of every g 130. mat thing which is naturally connected with the passage of troops, is included and without which the passage would be impracticable ; such jj the rant as the liberty of carrying with them whatever may be neces- passa s e - sary for an army, that of exercising military discipline on the soldiers and officers, and of purchasing, at a fair price, every thing the army may want, unless, through fear of scar- city, a particular exception has been made, to oblige them to carry with them their own provisions. He who grants the passage is bound to render it safe, as far 131. Safe- as depends on him. Good faith requires this ; and to act ty of the otherwise would be ensnaring those to whom the passage is P assa s e - granted. For this reason, and because foreigners can do nothing in g 132, No a territory against the will of the sovereign, it is unlawful to hostility to attack an enemy in a neutral country, or to commit in it any ^ ^^j,. other act of hostility. The Dutch East- India fleet having pot tnd eonn- into Bergen, in Norway, in 1666, to avoid the English, the try. (ieo> British admiral had the temerity to attack them there. But the governor of Bergen fired on the assailants ; and the court of Denmark complained, though perhaps too faintly, of an at- tempt so injurious to her rights and dignity.* (160) * The author of the " Present State sea, within cannon-shot of the coast, is of Denmark," written in English, pre- considered as making a part of the ter- tends that the Danes had engaged to ritory; and, for that reason, a vessel deliver up the Dutch fleet, but that some taken under the cannon of a neutral seasonable presents, made to the court fortress, is not a lawful prize. Ante, of Copenhagen, saved it. Chap. x. book i. chap, xxiii. s. 289, p. 129 ; Mar- (160) At present, by the general ten's L. N. b. viii. chap. vi. s. 6 ; and uiw of nations, the whole space of the see 1 Molloy, b. i. chap. iii. s. 7 ; and 451 344 OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. BOOK. in. To conduct prisoners, to convey spoil to a place of safety, CHAP, vir^ are actg Q f war ^ conse q uen tly not to be done in a neutral coun- try ; and whoever should permit them, would depart from the line of neutrality, by favouring one of the parties. But I here speak of prisoners and spoil not yet perfectly in the enemy's power, and whose capture is, as it were, not yet fully com- pleted. A flying party, for instance, cannot make use of a neighbouring and neutral country as a place of deposit to se- cure their prisoners and spoil. To permit this, would be giving countenance and support to their hostilities. When the capture is completed, and the booty absolutely in the enemy's power, no inquiry is made how he came by such effects, and he may dispose of them in a neutral country. A privateer carries his prize into a neutral port, and there freely [ 345 ] sells it ; but he cannot land his prisoners there, for the pur- pose of keeping them in confinement, because the detention and custody of prisoners of war is a continuation of hostilities, g 133. Neu- On the other hand, it is certain that, if my neighbour af- trai country f or( } s a retreat to my enemies, when defeated and too much aretoeaf to* weakened to' escape me, and allows them time to recover, and troops, that watch a favourable opportunity of making a second attack on they may my territories, this conduct, so prejudicial to my safety and again attack interests, would be incompatible with neutrality. If, therefore, my enemies, on suffering a discomfiture, retreat into his coun- try, although charity will not allow him to refuse them permis- sion to pass in security, he is bound to make them continue their march beyond his frontiers as soon as possible, and not suffer them to remain in his territories on the watch for a con- venient opportunity to attack me anew ; otherwise he gives me a right to enter his country in pursuit of them. Such treat- ment is often experienced by nations that are unable to com- mand respect. Their territories soon become the theatre of war ; armies march, encamp, and fight in it, as in a country open to all comers. g 134. Con- Troops to whom a passage is granted are not to occasion d b * t0 d b *^ e ^ eas * damage in the country ; they are to keep to the pub- 7 lie roads, and not enter the possessions of private persons, chap. i. s. 16. { The Ann, 1 Gall. Rep. 62. } allowed to originate on neutral ground, And Professor Marten observes, that and explains and elucidates what pre- when two vessels, the enemies of eaofc paratory acts of warfare there ought, other, meet in a neutral port, or where or ought not, to be tolerated ; and see one pursues the other into such port, not 1 Chitty's Com. L. 441 to 444. So only must they refrain from all hostili- we have seen that even a sentence ties while they remain there, but should of condemnation of ship or goods as one set sail, the other must not sail in prize cannot legally take place in a less than twenty-four hours after. Mar- neutral country. Ante, and Flad Oyen, ten's L. Nat b. viii. c. vi. s. 6. Sir W. 1 Rob. Rep. 115; 8 T. R. 270; Atche- Scott, in the Twee Gcbroeders, 3 Rob. son's Rep. 8, note 9; and see Have- Hep. 162336 ; and the Anna, 5 Rob. loch v. Rockwood, Atcheson's Rep. 33, Rep. 373, observes, that no proximate 43. C. acts of war are in any manner to be 452 OF NEUTRALITY, ETC. 345 to observe the most exact discipline, and punctually pay for BOOK m. everything with which the inhabitants supply them. And if CHAF - Tn v the licentiousness of the soldiers, or the necessity of certain t ro P s P a8S - operations, as encamping or intrenching, has caused an j ^neutral^ damage, their commander or their sovereign is bound to make country . reparation. All this requires no proof. What right have an army to injure a country, when the most they could require was an innocent passage through it ? There can be no reason why the neutral state should not stipulate for a sum of money, as an indemnification for certain damages which it would be difficult to estimate, and for the inconveniences naturally resulting from the passage of an army. But it would be scandalous to sell the very grant of passage, nay, even unjust, if the passage be attended with no damage, since, in that case, the permission is due. As to the rest, the sovereign of the country is to take care that the compensation be paid to the parties who have suffered the damage ; for no right authorizes him to reserve for his own use what is given for their indemnification. It is, indeed, too often the case, that the weak sustain the loss, and the power- ful receive the compensation. Finally, as we are not bound to grant even an innocent ? 135. A passage, except for just causes, we may refuse it to him who P assa s e & y requires it for a war that is evidently unjust, as, for instance, for 7 wa r to invade a country without any reason, or even colourable evidently pretext. Thus Julius Caesar denied a passage to the Helvetii, unjust, who were quitting their country in order to conquer a better. I conceive, indeed, that policy had a greater share in his re- fusal than the love of justice ; but, in short, justice authorized him on that occasion to obey the dictates of prudence. A sovereign who is in a condition to refuse without fear, should doubtless refuse in the case we now speak of. But if it would be dangerous for him to give a refusal, he is not obliged to [ 346 ] draw down the impending evil on his own head for the sake of averting it from that of his neighbour : nay, rashly to hazard the quiet and welfare of his people, would be a very great breach of his duty. 453 346 OF THE RIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. BOOK III. CHAP. Till. CHAP VIII. OF THE RIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAK, AND, FIRST, OF WHAT WE HAVE A RIGHT TO DO, AND WHAT WE ARE ALLOWED TO DO TO THE ENEMY'S PERSON, IN A JUST WAR. (161) f 136. Ge- WHAT we have hitherto said, concerns the right of making norai prin- war : ] e t us now proceed to those rights which are to be re- cipies of the g p ec t e d during the war itself, and to the rules -which nations ajainst an should reciprocally observe, even when deciding their differ- enemy in a cnces by arms. Let us begin by laying down the rights of a just war. nation engaged in a just war : let us see what she is allowed to do to her enemy. The whole is to be deduced from one single principle, from the object of a just war : for, when the end is lawful, he who has a right to pursue that end has, of course, a right to employ all the means which are necessary for its attainment. The end of a just war is to avenge or pre- vent injury ( 28) that is to say, to obtain justice by force, when not obtainable by any other method, to compel an un- just adversary to repair an injury already done, or give us securities against any wrong with which we are threatened by him. As soon, therefore, as we have declared war, we have a right to do against the enemy whatever we find necessary for the attainment of that end, for the purpose of bring- ing him to reason, and obtaining justice and security from him. $ 137. Dif- The lawfulness of the end does not give us a real right to ference be- any thing further than barely the means necessary for the at- w7ha h a at tainment of that end - Whatever we do beyond that, is repro- right to do Da ^ed by the law of nature, is faulty, and condemnable at the and what is tribunal of conscience. Hence it is that the right to such or barely ai- such acts of hostility varies according to circumstances. What lowed to be j s j us j. an( j p er f ec tly innocent in war, in one particular situa- impunity ^ on > * s no * a l wa y s so on other occasions. Right goes hand done with between in hand with necessity and the exigency of the case, but never enemies. exceeds them. But as it is very difficult always to form a precise judgment of what the present case requires, and as, moreover, it belongs to each nation to judge of what her own particular situation authorizes her to do (Prelim. 16) it becomes absolutely necessary that nations should reciprocally conform to general [ 347 ] rules on this subject. Accordingly, whenever it is certain and evident that such a measure, such an act of hostility, is necessary, in general, for overpowering the enemy's resist- (161) See, in general, the Rights of Commercial Law, 377 to 437; and Chit- War ; Grotius, ch. vi. ; and 1 Chitty's ty's Law of Nations, per tot. C. 454 OF THE EIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAK. 347 ance, and attaining the end of a lawful war, that measure, BOOK m. thus viewed in a general light, is, by the law of nations, CHAP - Ym - deemed lawful in war, and consistent with propriety, although he who unnecessarily adopts it, when he might attain his end by gentler methods, is not innocent before God and his own conscience. In this lies the difference between what is just, equitable, irreprehensible in war, and what is only allowed between nations, and suffered to pass with impunity. The sovereign who would preserve a pure conscience, and punctu- ally discharge the duties of humanity, ought never to lose sight of what we already have more than once observed, that nature gives him no right to make war on his fellow-men, except in cases of necessity, and as a remedy, ever disagree- able, though often necessary, against obstinate injustice or violence. If his mind is duly impressed with this great truth, he will never extend the application of the remedy beyond its due limits, and will be very careful not to render it more harsh in its operation, and more fatal to mankind, than is requisite for his own security and the defence of his rights. Since the object of a just war is to repress injustice and g 138. The violence, and forcibly to compel him who is deaf to the voice ri g ht to of justice, we have a right to put in practice, against the ^^ en b an enemy, every measure that is necessary in order to weaken everyjustifi- him, and disable him from resisting us and supporting his able me- injustice ; and we may choose such methods as are the most ^od. efficacious and best culculated to attain the end in view, pro- vided they be not of an odious kind, nor unjustifiable in them- selves, and prohibited by the law of nature. The enemy who attacks me unjustly, gives me an undoubted g 139. The right to repel his violence; and he who takes up arms to ri g htover oppose me when I demand only my right, becomes himself the enem J' 8 the real aggressor by his unjust resistance : he is the first per author of the violence, and obliges me to employ forcible means in order to secure myself against the wrong which he intends to do me either in my person or my property. If the forcible means I employ produce such effect as even to take away his life, he alone must bear the whole blame of that misfortune : for, if I were obliged to submit to the wrong rather than hurt him, good men would soon become the prey of the wicked. Such is the origin of the right to kill our enemies in a just war. When we find gentler methods insuf- ficient to conquer their resistance and bring them to terms, we have a right to put them to death. Under the name of enemies, as we have already shown, are to be comprehended, not only the first author of the war, but likewise all those who join him, and who fight in support of his cause. But the very manner in which the right to kill our enemies \ HO. is proved, points out the limits of that right. On an enemy's Li . mit f of submitting and laying down his arms, we cannot with justice this right take away his life. Thus, in a battle, quarter is to be given 455 348 OF THE RIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. wi. A particular case, in refused. \ 142. prisais. to those who lay down their arms ; and, in a siege, a garrison O flf er i n g t capitulate are never to be refused their lives. The humanity with which most nations in Europe carry on their , , i JJTI- wars a * P resen ^ cannot be too much commended. If, some- times, in the heat of action, the soldier refuses to give quarter, it is always contrary to the inclination of the officers, who eagerly interpose to save the* lives of such enemies as have laid down their arms.* There is, however, one case in which we may refuse to spare the life of an enemy who surrenders, or to allow any capitulation to a town reduced to the last extremity. It is, wnen * na * enemy has been guilty of some enormous breach of the law of nations, and particularly when he has violated the laws of war. This refusal of quarter is no natural con- sequence of the war, but a punishment for his crime, a pu- nishment which the injured party has a right to inflict. But, in order that it be justly inflicted, it must fall on the guilty. When we are at war with a savage nation, who observe no rules, and never give quarter, we may punish them in the persons of any of their people whom we take, (these belonging to the number of the guilty,) and endeavour, by this rigorous proceeding, to force them to respect the laws of humanity. But, wherever severity is not absolutely necessary, clemency becomes a duty. Corinth was utterly destroyed for having violated the law of nations in the person of the Roman am- bassadors. That severity, however, was reprobated by Cicero and other great men. He who has even the most just cause to punish a sovereign with whom he is in enmity, will ever incur the reproach of cruelty, if he causes the punishment to fall on his innocent subjects. There are other methods of chastising the sovereign, such as depriving him of some of his rights, taking from him towns and provinces. The evil which thence results to the nation at large, is the consequence of that participation which cannot possibly be avoided by those who unite in political society. This leads us to speak of a kind of retaliation sometimes practised in war, under the name of reprisals. If the hostile general has, without any just reason, caused some prisoners to be hanged, we hang an equal number of his people, and of the same rank, notifying to him that we will continue thus * From several passages of Grotius's History of the Disturbances in the Low Countries, it appears that the war between the Dutch and Spaniards was carried on with unrelenting cruelty at sea, although the parties had agreed to observe the usual rules of moderation on land. Intelligence being received by the confederate states, that the Spa- niards had, by the advice of Spinola, embarked at Lisbon a body of troops destined for Flanders, they despatched a squadron to wait for them in the strait of Calais, with orders to drown without mercy every soldier that was taken; and the order was punctually executed. Book xiv. p. 550. Edit. A.D. 3797. (162) As to reprisals and letters of marque in general, see ante, b. ii. ch. xviii. 334. C. OF THE EIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. 483 to retaliate, for the purpose of obliging him to observe the BOOK m. laws of war. It is a dreadful extremity thus to condemn a , CHAP - YI ?-. prisoner to atone, by a miserable death, for his general's crime : and if we had previously promised to spare the life of that prisoner, we cannot, without injustice, make him the [ 349 ] subject of our reprisals.* Nevertheless, as a prince, or his general, has a right to sacrifice his enemy's lives to his own safety and that of his men, it appears, that, if he has to do with an inhuman enemy, who frequently commits such enor- mities, he is authorized to refuse quarter to some of the pri- soners he takes, and to treat them as his people have been treated.f But Scipio's generosity is rather to be imitated : that great man, having reduced some Spanish princes, who had revolted against the Romans, declared to them that, on a breach of their faith, he would not call the innocent hostages to an account, but themselves : and that he would not avenge it on an unarmed enemy, but on those who should be found in arms.! Alexander the Great, having cause of complaint against Darius for some malpractices, sent him word, that if he continued to make war in such a manner, he would proceed to every extremity against him, and give him no quarter. It is thus an enemy who violates the laws of war is to be checked, and not by causing the penalty due to his crime to fall on innocent victims. How could it be conceived, in an enlightened age, that it is 143. Whe- lawful to punish with death a governor who has defended his ther a go ~ town to the last extremity, or who, in a weak place, has had t^ ^ the courage to hold out against a royal army ? In the last be punished century, this notion still prevailed ; it was looked upon as one with death of the laws of war, and is not, even at present, totally exploded. fo f an k- What an idea ! to punish a brave man for having performed f*^ his duty ! Very different were the principles of Alexander the Great, when he gave orders for sparing some Milesians, on account of their courage and fidelity. \\ "As Phyton was led to execution, by order of Dionysius the tyrant, for having obstinately defended the town of Rhegium, of which he was governor, he cried out, that he was unjustly condemned to die for having refused to betray the town, and that heaven would * In the French, we here find (ap- prisoner, in case of victory declaring on parently very much out of place) a ver- their side. He spared Adeimantus alone, batim repetition of the long note which who had opposed that infamous reso- has already appeared in page 286. lution. Xenoph. Hist. Graec. lib. ii. cap. Edit. A. D. 1797. i. Edit A. D. 1797. f Lysander, having captured the J Neque se in obsides innoxios, sed Athenian fleet, put the prisoners to in ipsos, si defecerint, saeviturum ; nee death, on account of various cruelties ab inermi, sed ab armato hoste, poenas practised by the Athenians during the expetiturum. Tit. Liv. lib. xxviii. course of the war, but principally on \ Quint Curt. lib. iv. cap. i. and ii. account of the barbarous resolution || Arrian. de Exped. Alexand. lib. L which they were known to have adopt- cap. xx. ed, of cutting off the right hand of every 53 20 457 349 OF THE RIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. BOOK in. soon avenge his death." Diodorus Siculus terms this " an CHAP. YIII. un j ust punishment."* It is vain to object, that an ohstinate defence, especially in a weak place, against a royal army, only causes a fruitless effusion of blood. Such a defence may save the state, by delaying the enemy some days longer ; and, be- sides, courage supplies the defects of the fortifications. f The [ 350 ] chevalier Bayard having thrown himself into Mezieres, de- fended it with his usual intrepidity,! and proved that a brave man is sometimes capable of saving a place which another would not think tenable. The history of the famous siege of Malta is another instance how far men of spirit may defend themselves, when thoroughly determined. How many places have surrendered, which might still have arrested the enemy's progress for a considerable time, obliged him to consume his strength and waste the remainder of the campaign, and even finally saved themselves, by a better-supported and more vigor- ous defence ! In the last war, whilst the strongest places in the Netherlands opened their gates in a few days, the va- liant general Leutrum was seen to defend Coni against the utmost efforts of two powerful armies, to hold out, in so in- different a post, forty days from the opening of the trenches, and, finally, to save the town, and, together with it, all Piemont. If it be urged, that, by threatening a commandant with death, you may shorten a bloody siege, spare your troops, and make a valuable saving of time, my answer is, that a brave man will despise your menace, or, incensed by such ig- nominious treatment, will sell his life as dearly as he can, will bury himself under the ruins of his fort, and make you pay for your injustice. But, whatever advantage you might promise yourself from an unlawful proceeding, that will not warrant you in the use of it. The menace of an unjust pun- ishment is unjust in itself: it is an insult and an injury. But, above all, it would be horrible and barbarous to put it in execu- tion ; and, if you allow that the threatened consequences must not be realized, the threat is vain and ridiculous. Just and * Lib. xiv. cap. cxiii., quoted by Gro- ill-fortified place against a royal army, tins, lib. iii. cap. ii. g xvi. n. v. and when, refusing to accept of reason- j- The false maxim which formerly able conditions offered to them, they prevailed on this subject, is noticed in undertake to arrest the progress of a the relation of the battle of Mussel- power which they are unable to resist." burgh (De Thou, vol. i. p. 287). " The Pursuant to that maxim, Caesar an- general (the duke of Somerset), the re- swered the Aduatici that he would gent of England, was on this occasion spare their town, if they surrendered much admired for his clemency, which before the battering-ram touched their induced him to spare the lives of the walls ; and the duke of Alva strongly besieged (the garrison of a castle in blamed prosper Colonna for having Scotland,) notwithstanding that ancient granted terms of capitulation to the maxim in war, which declares that a garrison of a castle, who had refused weak garrison forfeit all claim to mercy to treat of a surrender until the cannon on the part of the conqueror, when, had been employed against them. Edit, with more courage than prudence, they A. D. 1797. obstinately persevere in defending an { See his life. OF THE RIGHTS OP NATIONS IN WAR. 350 honourable means may be employed to dissuade a governor BOOK m. from ineffectually persevering to the last extremity ; and such CHAP, ym. is the present practice of all prudent and humane generals. At a proper stage of the business, they summon a governor to surrender ; they offer him honourable and advantageous terms of capitulation, accompanied by a threat, that, if he delays too long, he will only be admitted to surrender as a prisoner of war, and at discretion. If he persists, and is at length [ 351 ] forced to surrender at discretion, they may then treat both himself and his troops with all the severity of the law of war. But that law can never extend so far as to give a right to take away the life of an enemy who lays down his arms ( 140), unless he has been guilty of some crime against the con- , queror ( 141). Resistance carried to extremity does not become punishable in a subaltern, except on those occasions only when it is evi- dently fruitless. It is then obstinacy, and not firmness or valour : true valour has always a reasonable object in view. Let us, for, instance, suppose that a state has entirely sub- mitted to the conqueror's arms, except one single fortress, that no succour is to be expected from without, no neighbour, no ally, concerns himself about saving the remainder of that conquered state : on such an occasion, the governor is to be made acquainted with the situation of affairs, and summoned to surrender ; and he may be threatened with death in case of his persisting in a defence which is absolutely fruitless, and which can only tend to the effusion of human blood.* Should this make no impression on him, he deserves to suffer the pu- nishment with which he has been justly threatened. I suppose the justice of the war to be problematical, and that it is not an insupportable oppression which he opposes : for if this gover- nor maintains a cause that is evidently just r if he fights to save his country from slavery, his misfortune will be pitied ; and every man of spirit will applaud him for gallantly perse- vering to the last extremity, and determining to die free. Fugitives and deserters, found by the victor among his ene- % 144. Fn- mies, are guilty of a crime against him ; and he has undoubt- gitives and edly a right to put them to death. But they are not properly desertors - considered as enemies: they are rather perfidious citizens * But it is not lawful to employ in Louis's hands) should be put to menaces of every kind in order to in- death in his sight. Philip replied that duee the governor or commandant of a he would feel the most poignant regret town to surrender. There are some, to lose his father, but that his honour against which nature revolts with hor- was still dearer to him, and that ho ror. Louis the Eleventh, being en- was too well acquainted with the gaged in the siege of St. Omer, and king's disposition, to apprehend that incensed at the long resistance he ex- he would disgrace himself by the per- perienced, informed the governor, Phi- petration of so barbarous a deed. lip, son of Antony, the Bastard of Bur- Hist, of Louis XL book viii. Edit, gundy, that if he did not surrender the A.D. 1797. place, his father (who was a prisoner 459 351 OF THE RIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. BOOK in. traitors to their country ; and their enlistment with the enemy CHAP. Tin. cannot obliterate that character, or exempt them from the punishment they have deserved. At present, however, deser- tion being unhappily too common, the number of the delin- quents renders it in some measure necessary to show clemency ; and, in capitulations, it is usual to indulge the evacuating garrison with a certain nuritber of covered wagons, in which they save the deserters. \ 145. Wo- Women, children, feeble old men, and sick persons, come men, chil- un der the description of enemies ( 70 72) ; and we have ^ed' and cei> t a in rights over them, inasmuch as they belong to the sfck.' ^ nation with whom we are at war, and as, between nation and [ 352 ] nation, all rights and pretensions affect the body of the society, together with all its members (Book II. 81, 82344). But these are enemies who make no resistance ; and consequently we have no right to maltreat their persons or use any violence against them, much less to take away their lives ( 140). This is so plain a maxim of justice and humanity, that at present every nation in the least degree civilized, acquiesces in it. If, sometimes, the furious and ungovernable soldier carries his brutality so far as to violate female chastity, or to massacre women, children, and old men, the officers lament those ex- cesses ; they exert their utmost efforts to put a stop to them ; and a prudent and humane general even punishes them when- ever he can. But, if the women wish to be spared altogether, they must confine themselves to the occupations peculiar to their own sex, and not meddle with those of men, by taking up arms. Accordingly, the military law of the Switzers, which forbids the soldier to maltreat women, formally excepts those females who have committed any acts of hostility.* g 146. cier- The like may be said of the public ministers of religion, of gy, men of men of letters, and other persons whose mode of life is very letters, Ac. remo t e from military affairs : not that these people, nor even the ministers of the altar, are, necessarily, and by virtue of their functions, invested with any character of inviolability, or that the civil law can confer it on them with respect to the enemy : but, as they do not use force or violence to oppose him, they do not give him a right to use it against them. Among the ancient Romans, the priests carried arms : Julius Caesar himself was sovereign pontiff: and among the Chris- tians, it has been no rare thing to see prelates, bishops, and cardinals buckle on their armor, and take the command of armies. From the instant of their doing so, they subjected themselves to the common fate of military men. While deal- ing out their blows in the field of battle, they did not, it is to be presumed, lay claim to inviolability. g 147. Pea- Formerly, every one capable of carrying arms became a ants, and, so ldier when his nation was at war, and especially when it * See Simler, de Repub. Helvet. 460 OF THE EIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. 352 was attacked. Grotius, however,* produces instances of BOOK m. several nations and eminent commanders, f who spared the CHAP ' ^~ peasantry, in consideration of the immediate usefulness of in general, their labours.^ At present, war is carried on by regular a11 who do troops : the people, the peasants, the citizens, take no part ] ^g arry in it, and generally have nothing to fear from the sword of a " the enemy. Provided the inhabitants submit to him who is master of the country, pay the contributions imposed, and [ 353 ] refrain from all hostilities, they live in as perfect safety as if they were friends : they even continue in possession of what belongs to them : the country people come freely to the camp to sell their provisions, and are protected, as far as possible, from the calamities of war. A laudable custom, truly worthy of those nations who value themselves on their humanity, and advantageous even to the enemy who acts with such moderation. By protecting the unarmed inhabitants, keeping the soldiery under strict discipline, and preserving the coun- try, a general procures an easy subsistence for his army, and avoids many evils and dangers. If he has any reason to mis- trust the peasantry and the inhabitants of the towns, he has a right to disarm them, and to require hostages from them : and those who wish to avoid the calamities of war, must sub- mit to the laws which the enemy thinks proper to impose on them. But all those enemies thus subdued or disarmed, whom the ? 148. The principles of humanity oblige him to spare, all those persons ri s h * ' belonging to the opposite party, (even the women and chil- n e ^ s f "" dren,) he may lawfully secure and make prisoners, either with war . a view to prevent them from taking up arms again, or for the purpose of weakening the enemy ( 138), or, finally, in hopes that, by getting into his power some woman or child for whom the sovereign has an affection, he may induce him to accede to equitable conditions of peace, for the sake of redeeming those valuable pledges. At present, indeed, this last-men- tioned expedient is seldom put in practice by the polished nations of Europe : women and children are suffered to enjoy perfect security, and allowed permission to withdraw wherever they please. But this moderation, this politeness, though undoubtedly commendable, is not in itself absolutely obliga- tory ; and if a general thinks fit to supersede it, he cannot be justly accused of violating the laws of war. He is at liberty to adopt such measures, in this respect, as he thinks most conducive to the success of his affairs. If without reason, and from mere caprice, he refuses to indulge women with this liberty, he will be taxed with harshness and brutality, he * Book iii. ch. xi. g xi. and make war only against those who T Cyrus, Belisarius, &c. appeared in arms : and the proposal f Cyrus proposed to the king of As- was agreed to. Xenoph. Cyrop. lib. v. Syria, that both parties should recipro- cap. 4. cally spare the cultivators of the soil, 2 o 2 461 353 OF THE RIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. BOOK in. will be censured for not conforming to a custom established CHAP. Tin. ky humanity : but he may have good reasons for disregarding, in this particular, the rules of politeness, and even the sug- gestions of pity. If there are hopes of reducing by famine a strong place, of which it is very important to gain possession, the useless mouths are not permitted to come out. And in this there is nothing which is not authorized by the laws of war. Some great men, however, have, on occasions of this nature, carried their compassion so far as to postpone their interests to the motions of humanity. We have already men- tioned, in another place, how Henry the Great acted during the siege of Paris. To such a noble example let us add that of Titus at the siege of Jerusalem : at first he was inclined to drive back into the city great numbers of starving wretches, [ 354 ] wno came out of it ; but he could not withstand the compas- sion which such a sight raised in him ; and he suffered the sentiments of humanity and generosity to prevail over the maxims of war. . g 149. A As soon as your enemy has laid down his arms and sur- prisoner of rendered his person, you have no longer any right over his be^oTto* life (140), unless he should give you such right by some death. new attempt, or had before committed against you a crime deserving death ( 141). It was therefore a dreadful error of antiquity, a most unjust and savage claim, to assume a right of putting prisoners of war to death, and even by the hand of the executioner. More just and humane principles, however, have long since been adopted. Charles I., king of Naples, having defeated and taken prisoner Conradin, his competitor, caused him to be publicly beheaded at Naples, together with Frederic of Austria, his fellow-prisoner. This barbarity raised a universal horror ; and Peter III., king of Arragon, reproached Charles with it as a detestable crime, and till then unheard of among Christian princes.* The case, however, was that of a dangerous rival, who contended with him for the throne. But supposing even the claims of that rival were unjust, Charles might have kept him in prison till he had renounced them, and given security for his future behaviour. \ 150. How Prisoners may be secured ; and for this purpose they may prisoners of k e p u ^ j n t confinement, and even fettered, if there be reason to a PP r ehend that they will rise on their captors, or make their escape. But they are not to be treated harshly, unless personally guilty of some crime against him who has them in his power. In this case, he is at liberty to punish them : otherwise, he should remember that they are men, and unfor- tunate, f A man of exalted soul no longer feels any emotions * Epist Pet. Arrag. apud Petr. de therlands, at the persuasion of the Vineis. count de Fuentes, resolved no longer f In 1593, the council of the Ne- to observe towards the United Pro- 462 OF THE RIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. 354 but those of compassion towards a conquered enemy who has BOOK HI. submitted to his arms. Let us, in this particular, bestow on , CHAP - YI _"' the European nations the praise to which they are justly entitled. Prisoners of war are seldom ill-treated among them. We extol the English and French ; we feel our bosoms glow with love for them, when we hear the accounts of the treatment which prisoners of war, on both sides, have experi- enced from those generous nations. And what is more, by a custom which equally displays the honour and humanity of the Europeans, an officer, taken prisoner in war, is released on his parole, and enjoys the comfort of passing the time of [ 355 ] his captivity in his own country, in the midst of his family ; and the party who have thus released him rest as perfectly sure of him as if they had him confined in irons. Formerly, a question of an embarrassing nature might have g 151. Who. been proposed. When we have so great a number of pri- ther P rison - soners that we find it impossible to feed them, or to keep them ^ n *t be with safety, have we a right to put them to death ? or shall we kept or fed, send them back to the enemy, thus increasing his strength, may be put and exposing ourselves to the hazard of being overpowered to death - by him on a subsequent occasion? At present, the case is attended with no difficulty. Such prisoners are dismissed on their parole, bound by promise not to carry arms for a cer- tain time, or during the continuance of the war. And as every commander necessarily has a power of agreeing to the condi- tions on which the enemy admits his surrender, the engage- ments entered into by him for saving his life or his liberty, with that of his men, are valid, as being made within the limits of his powers ( 19, &c.); and his sovereign cannot annul them. Of this, many instances occurred during the last war : several Dutch garrisons submitted to the condition of not serving against France or her allies for one or two years: a body of French troops being invested in Lintz, were by capitulation sent back across the Rhine, under a restriction not to carry arms against the queen of Hungary for a stated time : and the sovereigns of those troops re- spected the engagements formed by them. But conventions of this kind have their limits, which consist in not infringing the rights of the sovereign over his subjects. Thus the enemy, in releasing prisoners, may impose on them the con- vinces that moderation which humanity hands, obliged the Spaniards to re-es- rcnders so necessary in war. They tablish those indispensable usages, gave orders for putting to death every which, in the words of Virgil [JEn. x. man who should be made prisoner, 532], are called belli eomiercia, the and, under the same penalty, prohi- ransom or exchange of prisoners, and bited the payment of any contributions the payment of contributions to avert to the enemy. But the complaints of pillage and devastation. The ransom the nobility and clergy, and still more of each prisoner was then settled at a the murmurs of the military, who saw month's pay. Grotius, Hist, of Ne- themsclves exposed to an infamous therlands, book iii. death in case of falling into the enemy's 463 355 OF THE RIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. BOOK in. dition of not carrying arms against him till the conclusion of - HAP- YII _ the war ; since he might justly keep them in confinement till that period : but he cannot require that they shall for ever renounce the liberty of fighting for their country ; because, on the termination of the war, he has no longer any reason for detaining them ; and they, on their part, cannot enter into an engagement absolutely inconsistent with their cha- racter of citizens or subjects. If their country abandons them, they become free in that respect, and have in their turn a right to renounce their country. But if we have to do with a nation that is at once savage, perfidious, and formidable, shall we send her back a number of soldiers who will perhaps enable her to destroy us ? When our own safety is incompatible with that of an enemy even of an enemy who has submitted the question admits not of a doubt. But to justify us in coolly and deliberately putting to death a great number of prisoners, the following conditions are indispensably necessary : 1. That no promise have been made to spare their lives ; and, 2. That we be perfectly assured that our own safety demands such a sacrifice. If it is at all consistent with prudence either to trust to their parole, or to disregard their perfidy, a generous enemy will rather listen to the voice of humanity than to that of a timid circumspec- [ 356 ] tion. Charles XII., being encumbered with his prisoners after the battle of Narva, only disarmed them and set them at liberty : but his enemy, still impressed with the apprehen- sions which his warlike and formidable opponents had excited in his mind, sent into Siberia all the prisoners he took at Pultowa. The Swedish hero confided too much in his own generosity : the sagacious monarch of Russia united, perhaps, too great a degree of severity with his prudence : but neces- sity furnishes an apology for severity, or rather throws a veil over it altogether. When Admiral Anson took the rich Aca- pulco galleon, near Manilla, he found that the prisoners out- numbered his whole ship's company: he was therefore under a necessity of confining them in the hold, where they suffered cruel distress.* But had he exposed himself to the risk of being carried away a prisoner, with his prize and his own ship together, would the humanity of his conduct have justified the imprudence of it ? Henry V., king of England, after his victory in the battle of Agincourt, was reduced, or thought himself reduced, to the cruel necessity of sacrificing the pri- soners to his own safety. "In this universal rout," says Father Daniel, " a fresh misfortune happened, which cost the lives of a great number of French. A remainder of their van was retreating in some order, and many of the stragglers rallied and joined it. The king of England, observing their See Anaon's Voyage round the World. {P. 382, 383. Lond. Ed. 4to. 1756.} OF THE RIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. 356 motions from an eminence, supposed it was their intention to BOOK m. return to the charge. At the same moment, he received in- CHAP> Tm : formation of an attack being made on his camp, where the baggage was deposited. In fact, some noblemen of Picardy, having armed about six hundred peasants, had fallen upon the English camp. Thus circumstanced, that prince, appre- hensive of some disastrous reverse, despatched his aides-de- camp to the different divisions of the army, with orders for putting all the prisoners to the sword, lest, in case of a re- newal of the battle, the care of guarding them should prove an impediment to his soldiers, or the prisoners should escape and join their countrymen. The order was immediately car- ried into execution, and all the prisoners were put to the sword."* Nothing short of the greatest necessity can justify so terrible an execution ; and the general whose situation requires it, is greatly to be pitied. Is it lawful to condemn prisoners of war to slavery ? Yes, 152. Whe- in cases which give a right to kill them, when they have ther P ris n - rendered themselves personally guilty of some crime deserv-^ ^" ing of death. The ancients used to sell their prisoners of made slave*, war for slaves. They, indeed, thought they had a right to put them to death. In every circumstance, when I cannot innocently take away my prisoner's life, I have no right to make him a slave. If I spare his life, and condemn him to [ 357 ] a state so contrary to the nature of man, I still continue with him the state of war. He lies under no obligation to me: for, what is life without freedom ? If any one counts life a favour when the grant of it is attended with chains, be it so : let him accept the kindness, submit to the destiny which awaits him, and fulfil the duties annexed to it. But he must apply to some other writer to teach him those duties : there have been authors enough who have amply treated of them. I shall dwell no longer on the subject ; and, indeed, that dis- grace to humanity is happily banished from Europe. Prisoners of war, then, are detained, either to prevent their g 153. Ex- returning to join the enemy again, or with a view to obtain ch ange and from their sovereign a just satisfaction, as the price of their ra ? som of liberty. There is no obligation to release those who are de- pn tained with the latter view, till after satisfaction is obtained. As to the former, whoever makes a just war has a right, if he thinks proper, to detain his prisoners till the end of the war : and whenever he releases them, he may justly require a ran- som, either as a compensation at the conclusion of a peace, or, if during the continuance of the war, for the purpose of at least weakening his enemy's finances at the same time that he restores him a number of soldiers. The European nations, who are ever to be commended for their care in alleviating the * Hist, of France, Reign of Charles VL 59 465 357 OF THE RIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. BOOK in. evils of war, have, with regard to prisoners, introduced humane CHAP. Tin. an( j gajutary customs. They are exchanged or ransomed, even during the war : and this point is generally settled beforehand by cartel. However, if a nation finds a considerable advan- tage in leaving her soldiers prisoners with the enemy during the war rather than exchanging them, she may certainly, unless bound by cartel, act in that respect as is most conducive to her interest. Such would be the case of a state abound- ing in men, and at war with a nation more formidable by the courage than the number of her soldiers. It would have ill suited the interests of the czar, Peter the Great, to restore his prisoners to the Swedes for an equal number of Russians. 154. The But the state is bound to procure, at her own expense, the state is release of her citizens and soldiers who are prisoners of war, rocure as soon as s ^ e ^ as *^ e means f accomplishing it, and can do their re- it without danger. It was only by acting in her service and lease. supporting her cause that they were involved in their present misfortune. For the same reason, it is her duty to provide for their support during the time of their captivity. For- merly, prisoners of war were obliged to redeem themselves : but then the ransom of all those whom the officers or soldiers might take, was the perquisite of the individual captors. The modern custom is more agreeable to reason and justice. If prisoners cannot be delivered during the course of the war, at least their liberty must, if possible, make an article in the treaty of peace. This is a care which the state owes to those who have exposed themselves in her defence. It must, ne- vertheless, be allowed, that a nation may, after the example of the Romans, and for the purpose of stimulating her soldiers to the most vigorous resistance, enact a law to prohibit pri- [ 358 ] soners of war from ever being ransomed. When this is agreed to by the whole society, nobody can complain. But such a law is very severe, and could scarce suit any but those am- bitious heroes who were determined on sacrificing every thing in order to make themselves masters of the world, g 155. Who- Since the present chapter treats of the rights which war ther an ene- gives us over the person of the enemy, this is the proper my may place to discuss a celebrated question, on which authors have wTaSate'd ^ een muc h divided, and that is, whether we may lawfully r poisoned, employ all sorts of means to take away an enemy's life ? whether we be justifiable in procuring his death by assassina- tion or poison ? Some writers have asserted, that, where we have a right to take away life, the manner is indifferent. A strange maxim ! but happily exploded by the bare ideas of honour, confused and indefinite as they are. In civil society, I have a right to punish a slanderer, to cause my property to be restored by him who unjustly detains it : but shall the manner be indifferent ? Nations may do themselves justice sword in hand, when otherwise refused to them : shall it be indifferent to human society that they employ odious means, 400 OF THE RIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. 358 capable of spreading desolation over the whole face of the BOOK m. earth, and against which the most just and equitable of sove- CHAP - YIU - reigns, even though supported by the majority of other princes, cannot guard himself? But, in order to discuss this question on solid grounds, as- sassination is by all means to be distinguished from surprises, which are, doubtless, very allowable in war. Should a re- solute soldier steal into the enemy's camp by night, should he penetrate to the general's tent, and stab him, in such conduct there is nothing contrary to the natural laws of war, nothing even but what is perfectly commendable in a just and necessary war. Mutius Scaevola has been praised by all the great men of antiquity ; and Porsenna himself, whom he intended to kill, could not but commend his courage.* Pepin, father of Charlemagne, having crossed the Rhine with one of his guards, went and killed his enemy in his chamber, f If any one has absolutely condemned such bold strokes, his cen- sure only proceeded from a desire to flatter those among the great, who would wish to leave all the dangerous part of war to the soldiery and inferior officers. It is true, indeed, that the agents in such attempts are usually punished with some painful death. But that is, because the prince or general who is thus attacked exercises his own rights in turn, has an eye to his own safety, and endeavours, by the dread of a cruel punishment, to deter his enemies from attacking him other- wise than by open force. He may proportion his severity towards an enemy according as his own safety requires. In- deed, it would be more commendable on both sides to renounce every kind of hostility which lays the enemy under a neces- r 3f/J 1 sity of employing cruel punishments, in order to secure him- self against it. This might be made an established custom, a conventional law of war. The generous warriors of the present age dislike such attempts, and would never willingly undertake them, except on those extraordinary occasions, when they become necessary to the very safety and being of their country. As to the six hundred Lacedaemonians, who, under the conduct of Leonidas, broke into the enemy's camp, and made their way directly to the Persian monarch's tent,| their expedition was justifiable by the common rules of war, and did not authorize the king to treat them more rigorously than any other enemies. In order to defeat all such attempts, it is sufficient to keep a strict watch ; and it would be unjust to have recourse to cruel punishments for that purpose : ac- cordingly, such punishments are reserved for those only who gain admittance by stealth alone, or in very small number, and especially if under cover of a disguise. * See Livy, lib. ii. cap. xii. Cicero, f Grotius, lib. iii. cap. 4, g xviii. n. L pro P. Sextio. Valer. Max. lib. iii. cap. j Justin, lib. ii. cap. xi. iii. Plutarch, in Poplicol. 467 359 OF THE RIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. BOOK m. I give, then, the name of assassination to a treacherous CHAP. Tin. mur( j er) -whether the perpetrators of the deed be subjects of the party whom we cause to be assassinated, or of our own sovereign, or that it be executed by the hand of any other emissary, introducing himself as a supplicant, a refugee, a deserter, or, in fine, as a stranger ; and such an attempt, I say, is infamous and execrable, 'both in him who executes and in him who commands it. Why do we judge an act to be criminal, and contrary to the law of nature, but because such act is pernicious to human society, and that the practice of it would be destructive to mankind ? Now, what could be more terrible than the custom of hiring a traitor to assassinate our enemy? Besides, were such a liberty once introduced, the purest virtue, the friendship of the majority of the reigning sovereigns, would no longer be sufficient to insure a prince's safety. Had Titus lived in the time of the old man of the mountain, though the happiness of mankind centred in him, though punctual in the observance of peace and equity, he was respected and adored by all potentates, yet, the very first time that the prince of the Assassins might have thought proper to quarrel with him, that universal aifection would have proved insufficient to save him ; and mankind would have lost their "darling." Let it not here be replied, that it is only in favour of the cause of justice that such extraordinary measures are allowable : for all parties, in their wars, main- tain that they have justice on their side. Whoever, by setting the example, contributes to the introduction of so destructive a practice, declares himself the enemy of mankind, and de- serves the execration of all ages.* The assassination of [ 360 ] William, prince of Orange, was regarded with universal detest- ation, though the Spaniards had declared that prince a rebel. And the same nation denied, as an atrocious calumny, the charge of having had the least concern in that of Henry the Great, who was preparing for a war against them, which might have shaken their monarchy to its very foundations. In treacherously administering poison there is something * See the dialogue between Julius on the traitor's own head," he ordered Caesar and Cicero, in the Melanges de him to bo despatched with the same Litte'rature et Po6sies. Farrudge, sul- poniard with which he had intended to tan of Egypt, sent to Timur-bec an perpetrate the abominable deed. The ambassador, accompanied by two vil- body of the traitor was then committed lains, who were to assassinate that to the flames, as an example to others, conqueror during the audience. This The two assassins were only condemned infamous plot being discovered, " It is to suffer the amputation of their noses not," said Timur, " the maxim of kings and ears ; Timur contenting himself to put ambassadors to death : but as to with this punishment, and forbearing this wretch, who, under the sacred garb to put them to death, because he wished of religion, is a monster of perfidy and to send them back with a letter to the corruption, it would be a crime to suffer sultan. {Petis de la Croix.} Hist, of him and his accomplices to live." Pur- Timur-bec, book v. chap. xxiv. {p. 313. suant, therefore, to that passage of the Ed. Delf. 1723.} Koran which says that "treachery falls OF THE RIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. 360 still more odious than in assassination : it would be more BOOK m. difficult to guard against the consequences of such an attempt ; CHAP - Tm - and the practice would be more dreadful ; accordingly, it has been more generally detested. Of this Grotius has ac- cumulated many instances.* The consuls Caius Fabricius and Quintus ^Emilius rejected with horror the proposal of Pyrrhus's physician, who made an offer of poisoning his master ; they even cautioned that prince to be on his guard against the traitor, haughtily adding : " It is not to ingra- tiate ourselves with you that we give this information, but to avoid the obloquy to which your death would expose us."f And they justly observe, in the same letter, that it is for the common interest of all nations not to set such examples.^ It was a maxim of the Roman Senate, that war was to be carried on with arms, and not with poison. Even under Tiberius, the proposal of the prince of the Catti was rejected, who offered to destroy Arminius, if poison were sent him for that purpose: and he received for answer, that "it was the practice of the Romans to take vengeance on their enemies by open force, and not by treachery and secret machinations ;"|| Tiberius thus making it his glory to imitate the virtue of the ancient Roman commanders. This instance is the more re- markable, as Arminius had treacherously cut off Varus, to- gether with three Roman legions. The senate, and even Tiberius himself, thought it unlawful to adopt the use of poison, even against a perfidious enemy, and as a kind of re- taliation or reprisals. Assassination and poisoning are therefore contrary to the laws of war, and equally condemned by the law of nature and the consent of all civilized nations. The sovereign who [ 361 ] has recourse to such execrable means should be regarded as the enemy of the human race ; and the common safety of mankind calls on all nations to unite against him, and join their forces to punish him. His conduct particularly au- thorizes the enemy, whom he has attacked by such odious means, to refuse him any quarter. Alexander declared, that "he was determined to proceed to the utmost extremities against Darius, and no longer to consider him as a fair enemy, + but as a poisoner and an assassin."^" The interest and safety of men in high command require, that, so far from countenancing the introduction of such prac- * Book iii. chap. iv. \ xv. g Armis bella, non venenig, geri de- f Oob yap raura a 3 X apir< jupwyuy, bere. Valer. Maxim, lib. vi. ch. v. oXX' em-uf ftij ro ttov iraBo; TI/KV <5iaoAijK num. i. fi*y*j. Plut in Pyrr. j| Non fraude, neque occultis, sed pa- J Sed communis exempli et fidei ergo lam, et armatum, populum Romanum visum est, uti te ealvum velimus ; ut hostes sues ulcisci. Tacit Annal. lib. ii. esset, quern armis vincere possemus. cap. Ixxxviii. AuL Gell. Noct Attic, lib. iiL cap. f Quint Curt lib. iv. cap. xi. num. T iii- xviii. 2P 469 361 OF THE RIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. BOOK m. tices, they should use all possible care to prevent it. It was CHAP, via. w isely said by Eumenes, that "he did not think any general wished to obtain a victory in such manner as should set a pernicious example which might recoil on himself."* And it was on the same principle that Alexander formed his judg- ment of Bessus, who had assassinated Darius, f 156. Whe- The use of poisoned weapons may be excused or defended tW poison- w jth a little more plausibility. At least, there is no treachery ;d weapons m the case, no clandestine machination. But the practice is iiTwar! USe nevertheless prohibited by the law of nature, which does not allow us to multiply the evils of war beyond all bounds. You must of course strike your enemy in order to get the better of his efforts : but if he is once disabled, is it necessary that he should inevitably die of his wounds ? Besides, if you poi- son your weapons, the enemy will follow your example ; and thus, without gaining any advantage on your side for the decision of the contest, you have only added to the cruelty and calamities of war. It is necessity alone that can at all justify nations in making war: they ought universally to abstain from every thing that has a tendency to render it more destructive : it is even a duty incumbent on them to oppose such practices. It is therefore with good reason, and in conformity to their duty, that civilized nations have classed among the laws of war the maxim which prohibits the poison- ing of weapons ;J and they are all warranted by their com- mon safety to repress and punish the first who should offer to break through that law. 157. Whe- A still more general unanimity prevails in condemning the ther springs p rac ti ce of poisoning waters, wells, and springs, because (say m ^' y e , some authors) we may thereby destroy innocent persons, poisoned. / .1 i 11 rrn we may destroy other people as well as our enemies. This is indeed an additional reason : but it is not the only nor even [ 362 ] the true one ; for we do not scruple to fire on an enemy's ship, although there be neutral passengers on board. But though poison is not to be used, it is very allowable to divert the water, to cut off the springs, or by any other means to render them useless, that the enemy may be reduced to sur- render^ This is a milder way than that of arms. (163) 158. Dis- I cannot conclude this subject, of what we have a right to positions to do against the person of the enemy, without speaking a few * Nee Antigonum, nee quemquam (163) But, in modern warfare, what- ducum, sic velle vincere, ut ipse in so ever may be the necessary practice in exemplum pessimum statuat. Justin, starving the besieged fortress into a lib. xiv. cap. i. num. xii. surrender, we have instanced the Eng- ) Quern quidem [J5em] cruci ad- lish supplying the French army with fixum videre festino, omnibus regibus medicine, to prevent the progress of a gentibusque fidei, quam violavit, me- destructive disorder, although, if a petty ritas poenas solventum. Q. Curt. lib. policy were allowed to prevail, such an vi. ch. iii. num. xiv. indulgence of humane feeling might ap- J Grotius, book iii. ch. iv. xvi. pear injudicious (ante). C. g Grotius, ibid. xvii. 470 OP THE RIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. words concerning the dispositions we ought to preserve to- BOOK m. wards him. They may already be deduced from what I have OHAP ' vnr ' hitherto said, and especially in the first chapter of the second be P reserve d book. Let us never forget that our enemies are men. Though ^ w " w reduced to the disagreeable necessity of prosecuting our right by force of arms, let us not divest ourselves of that charity which connects us with all mankind. Thus shall we courageously defend our country's rights without violating those of human nature.* Let our valour preserve itself from every stain of cruelty, and the lustre of victory will not be tarnished by inhuman and brutal actions. Marius and Attila are now detested ; whereas we cannot forbear admiring and loving Caesar ; his generosity and clemency almost tempt us to overlook the injustice of his undertaking. Moderation and generosity redound more to the glory of a victor than his courage ; they are more certain marks of an exalted soul. Besides the honour which infallibly accompanies those virtues, humanity towards an enemy has been often attended with immediate and real advantages. Leopold, duke of Austria, besieging Soleure, in the year 1318, threw a bridge over the Aar, and posted on it a large body of troops. Soon after, the river having, by an extraordinary swell of its waters, car- ried away the bridge together with those who were stationed on it, the besieged hastened to the relief of those unfortunate men, and saved the greatest part of them. Leopold, relent- ing at this act of generosity, raised the siege and made peace with the city.f The duke of Cumberland, after his victory at Dettingen,^ appears to me still greater than in the heat of battle. As he was under the surgeon's hands, a French [ 363 ] officer, much more dangerously wounded than himself, being brought that way, the duke immediately ordered his surgeon to quit him, and assist that wounded enemy. If men in ex- alted stations did but conceive how great a degree of affec- tion and respect attends such actions, they would study to * The laws of justice and equity are of a bribe, but with a view to save the not to be less respected even in time women and children, whom he saw of war. The following I quote as a perishing with famine; for Clearchus, remarkable instance : Alcibiades, at who commanded the garrison, had given the head of an Athenian army, was to the soldiers all the corn that was engaged in the siege of Byzantium, found in the city. The Lacedsemoni- then occupied by a Lacedaemonian gar- ans, with a noble regard to justice, and rison ; and finding that he could not such as seldom prevails on similar oc- reduce the city by force, he gained casions, acquitted the culprit, observing over some of the inhabitants, who put that he had not betrayed, but saved him in possession of it. One of the the city, and particularly attending to persons concerned in this transaction the circumstance of his being a was Anaxilaus, a citizen of Byzantium, Byzantine, not a Lacedaemonian. who, being afterwards brought to trial Xenoph. Hist. Graec. lib. i. cap. iii. for it at Lacedaemon, pleaded in his Edit. A. D. 1797. defence, that, in surrendering the city, f Watteville's Hist, of the Helvetic he had not acted through ill-will to the Confederacy, vol. i. p. 126. Lacedaemonians, or under the influence J In the year 1743. 471 363 OP THE RIGHTS OF NATIONS IN WAR. BOOK m. imitate them, even when not prompted to the practice by CHAP. Tin. na tj ve elevation of sentiment. At present, the European nations generally carry on their wars with great moderation and generosity. These dispositions have given rise to several customs which are highly commendable, and frequently car- ried to the extreme of politeness.* Sometimes refreshments are sent to the governor of a besieged town ; and it is usual to avoid firing on the king's or the general's quarters. We are sure to gain by this moderation, when we have to do with a generous enemy : but we are not bound to observe it any further than can be done without injuring the cause we de- fend; and it is clear that a prudent general will, in this respect, regulate his conduct by the circumstances of the case, by an attention to the safety of the army and of the state, by the magnitude of the danger, and by the character and behaviour of the enemy. Should a weak nation or town be attacked by a furious conqueror who threatens to destroy it, are the defenders to forbear firing on his quarters ? Far from it : that is the very place to which, if possible, every shot should be directed. 2 159. Ten- Formerly, he who killed the king or general of the enemy derness for was commended and greatly rewarded : the honours annexed the person t ne S p n a opima are well known. Nothing was more natural : w^oU^n in former times, the belligerent nations had, almost in every arms against instance, their safety and very existence at stake ; and the ua. death of the leader often put an end to the war. In our days, a soldier would not dare to boast of having killed the enemy's king. Thus sovereigns tacitly agree to secure their own persons. It must be owned, that, in a war which is car- ried on with no great animosity, and where the safety and existence of the state are not involved in the issue, this regard for regal majesty is perfectly commendable, and even consonant to the reciprocal duties of nations. In such a war, to take away the life of the enemy's sovereign, when it might be spared, is perhaps doing that nation a greater degree of harm than is necessary for bringing the contest to a happy issue. But it is not one of the laws of war that we should on * Timur-bec made war on Joseph share those new fruits with that prince Sofy, king of Carezem, and subdued when so near him : and accordingly he his kingdom. During the course of ordered them to be put into a gold the war, that great man proved him- basin, and carried to him. The king self to be possessed of all that modera- of Carezem received this instance of tion and politeness which is thought politeness in a brutal manner; he or- peculiar to our modern warriors. Some dered the melons to be thrown into melons being brought to him whilst he the fosse, and gave the basin to the was besieging Joseph in the city of city gate-keeper. La Croix, Hist, of Eskiskus, ho resolved to send a part Timur-bec, book v. ch. xxvii. Edit, of them to his enemy, thinking it A.D. 1797. would be a breach of civility not to 472 OF THE RIGHT OVER ENEMIES' PROPERTY. 363 every occasion spare the person of the hostile king : we are BOOK. m. not bound to observe that moderation except where we have CHAP. Tin. a fair opportunity of making him prisoner.* CHAP. IX. [364] OF THE RIGHT OF WAR, WITH REGARD TO THINGS BELONGING CHAP, ix. TO THE ENEMY. (164) A STATE taking up arms in a just cause has a double ieo. Prin- right against her enemy, 1. a right to obtain possession of ci P les of tne her property withheld by the enemy; to which must be added jjjj*^" the expenses incurred in the pursuit of that object, the lon gfn g to charges of the war, and the reparation of damages : for, were the enemy, she obliged to bear those expenses and losses, she would not fully recover her property, or obtain her due. 2. She has a right to weaken her enemy, in order to render him incapable of supporting his unjust violence ( 138) a right to deprive him of the means of resistance. Hence, as from their source, originate all the rights which war gives us over things belong- ing to the enemy. I speak of ordinary cases, and of what * On this subject, let us notice a trait of Charles XII. of Sweden, in which sound reason and the most ex- alted courage are equally conspicuous. That prince, being engaged in the siege of Thorn in Poland, and frequently walking round the city, was easily dis- tinguished by the cannoneers, who regularly fired upon him as soon as they saw him make his appearance. The principal officers of his army, great- ly alarmed at their sovereign's danger, wished to have information sent to the governor, that, if the practice was con- tinued, no quarter should bo granted either to him or to the garrison. But the Swedish monarch would never per- mit such a step to be taken, telling his officers that the governor and the Saxon cannoneers were perfectly right in act- ing as they did, that it was himself who made the attack upon them, and that the war would be at an end if they could kill him; whereas they would reap very little advantage even from killing the principal officers of his army. Histoire du Nord, p. 26. Edit A. D. 1797. (164) See, in general, Grotius, ch. 6 ; Home on Captures 5 Marten's L. Nat. 287 ; and the modern decisions, 1 Chit- ty's Commercial Law, 377 i37; and Chitty's Law of Nations, per tot. And as to the legal right of embargo and capture, as it affects commerce, and ex- ceptions, as respects small fishing vessels, 1 Chitty's C. L. 426. But, that exemp- tion is matter of forbearance, rather than of right, and seems analogous to hus- bandmen and cultivators of land being usually spared, see Vattel, 147, ante, 352 ; and see Young, Jacob, and Johorca, 1 Rob. Rep. 19, as to fishing-boats and fishermen, per Sir Wm. Scott. Questions respecting captures and prizes, or even imprisonment of the person incident to the seizure as prize, cannot in general become the subject of litigation, directly, in any of the mu- nicipal courts of this country, but must be investigated in a prize court, which, in this country, is holden under a dis- tinct authority from that of the court of Admiralty, viz. under a special com- mission from the king, who would otherwise preside in person over prize questions: and from such commission there is usually an appeal to the king in council; see cases in note (165), posit 365. C. 60 2p2 473 364 OF THE RIGHT OVER ENEMIES' PROPERTY. BOOK in. particularly relates to the enemy's property. On certain oc- CHAP. ix. cas i ons> the right of punishing him produces new rights over the things which belong to him, as it also does over his person. These we shall presently consider. 161. The We have a right to deprive our enemy of his possessions, right of O f every thing which may augment his strength and enable them^ U h* m * ma ^ e war * This every one endeavours to accomplish in the manner most suitable to him. Whenever we have an opportunity, we seize on the enemy's property, and convert it to our own use : and thus, besides diminishing the enemy's power, we augment our own, and obtain at least a partial in- demnification or equivalent, either for what constitutes the subject of the war, or for the expenses and losses incurred in its prosecution : in a word, we do ourselves justice. \ 162. What The right to security often authorizes us to punish injustice is taken or violence. It is an additional plea for depriving an enemy ^iTm^b ^ some P ar t f his possessions. This manner of chastising a way m of pe _ nation is more humane than making the penalty to fall on the naity. persons of the citizens. With that view, things of value may [ 365 ] be taken from her, such as rights, cities, provinces. But all wars do not afford just grounds for inflicting punishment. A nation that has with upright intentions supported a bad cause, and observed moderation in the prosecution of it, is entitled rather to compassion than resentment from a generous con- queror : and in a doubtful cause we are to suppose that the enemy sincerely thinks himself in the right. (Prelim. 21 ; Book III. 40.) The only circumstance, therefore, which gives an enemy the right to punish his adversaries, is their evident injustice, unsupported even by any plausible pretext, or some heinous outrage in their proceedings : and, on every occasion, he ought to confine the punishment to what his own security and the safety of nations require. As far as consistent with prudence, it is glorious to obey the voice of clemency : that amiable virtue seldom fails of being more useful to the party who exerts it, than inflexible rigour. The clemency of Henry the Great was of singular advantage in co-operating with his valour, when thaj good prince found himself com- pelled to conquer his ovn kingdom. Those who would have continued his enemies if only subdued by arms, were won by his goodness, and became affectionate subjects. \ 163. What In fine, we seize on the enemy's property, his towns, his is withheld provinces, in order to bring him to reasonable conditions, and from him, compe i him to accept of an equitable and solid peace. Thus in order to i f i_* At: i. 1.1. oblige him mucn more is taken from him than he owes, more than is to give just claimed of him : but this is done with a design of restoring atisfaction. the surplus by a treaty of peace. The king of France* was, in the last war, known to declare that he aimed at nothing for * The peace was become absolutely with all its dependencies, which were necessary to him ; and he had, in re- of more importance to him. [Note by turn fr his few conquests, Louisbourg, the former translator.] 474 OF THE RIGHT OVER ENEMIES* PROPERTY. 365 himself: and by the treaty of Aix-la-Chapelle, he actually BOOK m. restored all his conquests. CHAP, ix. As the towns and lands taken from the enemy are called ? 164. conquests, all movable property taken from him comes under Booty.(i65) the denomination of booty. This booty naturally belongs to the sovereign making war, no less than the conquests ; for he alone has such claims against the hostile nation as warrant him to seize on her property and convert it to his own use. (165) His soldiers, and even his auxiliaries, are only instruments which he employs in asserting his right. He maintains and pays them. Whatever they do is in his name, and for him. Thus, there is no difficulty, even with regard to the auxiliaries. If they are not associates in the war, it is not carried on for their benefit ; and they have no more right to the booty than to the conquests. But the sovereign may grant the troops what share of the booty he pleases. At present most nations allow them whatever they can make on certain occasions when [ 366 ] the general allows of plundering, such as the spoil of ene- mies fallen in the field of battle, the pillage of a camp which (165) That they belong to the king, unless delegated to a subject, see fur- ther, post, 202, page 391. But to the king for the benefit of the community, and not as his own private property. Id. ibid. In case a territory of a fo- reign sovereign, or a part of it, be cap- tured, the sovereign of the conquering state is entitled to all the property there of the conquered sovereign ; Advocate General v. Amerchund, Knapp's Rep. of Cases before the Privy Council, 329 ; and the same case establishes that there is no distinction, in this respect, between the public and private property of an absolute monarch; and that, therefore, money in the hands of the banker of a prince, whose territories have been conquered by the British, may be recovered on an information by the English attorney-general from the banker. Decided in Privy Council, reversing the judgment of the court be- low at Bombay. See Holt's case, Ni. Pri. 113; Undo v. Rodney, Douglas, 313 ; Caux v. Eden, Douglas, 594 ; El- phinstone v. Bedreechund, Knapp's Rep. 316; Chitty's Gen. Practice, 2 n. (6), 16 n. (e), Id. 818. But to this rule there is an exception, as regards any trust which may be enforced in a court of equity ; Pearton v. Belcher, 4 Ves. 827 ; Chaloner v. Samson, 1 Bro. pi. 149 ; and see Hill v. Reardon, 2 Russell's Rep. 608, qualifying 2 Sim. A Stu. Rep. 437451; Chitty's Gen. Practice, 818. When the property seized is under 100, the claim may be settled in the prize court, summarily, and without a formal suit ; but not so, if it be even a trifle above that amount. The Mercurius, 5 Rob. 127. In the case of Elphinstone v. Bedree- chund, Knapp's Rep. 316, where the members of the provisional government of a recently conquered country had seized the property of a native, who had been refused the benefit of the ar- ticles of capitulation of a fortress, of which he was the governor, but who had been permitted to reside under military surveillance in his own house in the city, in which the seizure was made, and which was at a distance from the scene of actual hostilities, it was held that such seizure must be re- garded in the light of a hostile seizure, and that, therefore, a municipal court had no jurisdiction on the subject. And it was further considered, in the same case, that the circumstance that, at the time of the seizure, the city where it was made had been, for some months previously, in the undisturbed possession of the provisional govern- ment, and that courts of justice, under the authority of that government, were sitting in it for the administration of justice, did not alter the character of the transaction ; and that, consequently, whatever might be the legality of the capture, or hostile seizure, still the party had mistaken his remedy in prosecuting it in the supreme court of Bombay. C. 475 366 OF THE RIGHT OVER ENEMIES PROPERTY. BOOK in. has been forced, and sometimes that of a town taken by as- _CHAP. ix. gau ik j n se veral services, the soldier has also the property of what he can take from the enemy's troops when he is out on a party, or in a detachment, excepting artillery, military stores, magazines, and convoys of provisions and forage, which are applied to the wants and use of the army. This custom being once admitted in an army, it would be injustice to ex- clude the auxiliaries from the right allowed to the national troops. Among the Romans, the soldier was obliged to bring in to the public stock all the booty he had taken. This the general caused to be sold ; and, after distributing a part of the produce among the soldiers, according to rank, he con- signed the residue to the public treasury. g 165. Con- Instead of the custom of pillaging the open country and tributions. defenceless places, another mode has been substituted, which is at once more humane, and more advantageous to the bel- ligerent sovereign I mean that of contributions. Whoever carries on a just war has a right to make the enemy's country contribute to the support of his army, and towards defraying all the charges of the war. Thus, he obtains a part of what is due to him ; and the enemy's subjects, by consenting to pay the sum demanded, have their property secured from pil- lage, and the country is preserved. But a general who wishes to enjoy an unsullied reputation, must be moderate in his de- mand of contributions, and proportion them to the abilities of those on whom they are imposed. An excess in this point does not escape the reproach of cruelty and inhumanity : al- though there is not so great an appearance of ferocity in it as in ravage and destruction, it displays a greater degree of avarice or greediness. Instances of humanity and moderation cannot be too often quoted. A very commendable one oc- curred during those long wars which France carried on in the reign of Louis XIV. The sovereigns, seeing it was their mu- tual interest as well as duty to prevent ravage, made it a practice, on the commencement of hostilities, to enter into treaties for regulating the contributions on a supportable foot- ing : they determined the extent of hostile territory in which each might demand contributions, the amount of them, and the manner in which the parties sent to levy them were to be- have. In these treaties it was expressed, that no body of men under a certain number should advance into the enemy's country beyond th limits agreed on, under the penalty of be- ing treated as freebooters. By such steps they prevented a multitude of disorders and enormities, which entail ruin on the people, and generally without the least advantage to the belligerent sovereigns. Whence comes it that so noble an ex- ample is not universally imitated ? 166. Waste If it is lawful to take away the property of an unjust enemy and destruc- j n or ^ he sovereign, therefore, whose arms are not sanctioned by justice, is not the less unjust, or less guilty of violating the sacred law of nature, although that law itself (with a view to avoid aggravating the evils of human society by an attempt to prevent them) requires that he be allowed to enjoy the same external rights as justly belong to his enemy. In the same manner, the civil law authorizes a debtor to refuse payment of his debts in a case of prescription : but he then violates his duty : he takes advantage of a law which was enacted with a view to prevent the endless increase of lawsuits ; but his conduct is not justifiable upon any grounds of genuine right. From the unanimity that in fact prevails between states in observing the rules which we refer to the voluntary law of nations, Grotius assumes for their foundation an actual con- sent on the part of mankind, and refers them to the arbitrary law of nations. But, exclusive of the difficulty which would often occur in proving such agreement, it would be of no validity except against those who had formerly entered into it. If such an engagement existed, it would belong to the conventional law of nations, which must be proved by history, not by argument, and is founded on facts, not on principles. In this work we lay down the natural principles of the law of nations. We deduce them from nature itself; and what we call the voluntary law of nations consists in rules of conduct and of external right, to which nations are, by the law of nature, bound to consent ; so that we are authorized to pre- sume their consent, without seeking for a record of it in the [ 384 ] annals of the world ; because, even if they had not given it, the law of nature supplies their omission, and gives it for them. In this particular, nations have not the option of giving or withholding their consent at pleasure : the refusal to give it would be an infringement of the common rights of nations (Prelim. 21). This voluntary law of nations, thus established, is of very extensive use, and is far from being a chimera, an arbitrary or groundless fiction. It flows from the same source, and is founded on the same principles, with the natural and neces- sary law. For what other reason does nature prescribe such and such rules of conduct to men, except because those rules are necessary to the safety and welfare of mankind ? But the maxims of the necessary law of nations are founded imme- diately on the nature of things, and particularly on that of man, and of political society. The voluntary law of nations supposes an additional principle, the nature of the great society of nations, and of their mutual intercourse. The 494 OP ACQUISITIONS BY WAR, ETC. 384 necessary law enjoins to nations what is absolutely indispen- BOOK m sable, and what naturally tends to their perfection and common CHAP, xir. happiness. The voluntary law tolerates what cannot be avoided without introducing greater evils. CHAP. XIII. OF ACQUISITIONS BY WAR, AND PARTICULARLY OF CON- CHAP, xm. QUESTS. IF it be lawful to carry off things belonging to an enemy, 193. How with a view of weakening him ( 160), and sometimes of pu- war " a nishing him ( 162), it is no less lawful in a just war to appro- ^^f^ priate them to our own use, by way of compensation, which the civilians term expletio juris ( 161). They are retained as an equivalent for what is due by the enemy, for the expenses and damages which he has occasioned, and even (when there is cause to punish him) as a commutation for the punishment he has deserved. For, when I cannot obtain the individual thing which belongs or is due to me, I have a right to an equivalent, which, by the rules of expletive justice, and in moral estimation, is considered as the thing itself. Thus, according to the law of nature, which constitutes the neces- sary law of nations, war, founded on justice, is a lawful mode of acquisition. But that sacred law does not authorize even the acquisitions 194. Mea- ns ade in a just war, any farther than as they are approved by s y re of tte justice, that is to say, no farther than is requisite to obtain n .^ ht u complete satisfaction in the degree necessary for accomplish- glv ing the lawful ends we have just mentioned. An equitable conqueror, deaf to the suggestions of ambition and avarice, will make a just estimate of what is due to him, that is to say, of the thing which has been the subject of the war (if the thing itself is no longer recoverable), and of the damages and [ 385 ] expenses of the war, and will retain no more of the enemy's property than what is precisely sufficient to furnish the equiva- lent. But if he has to do with a perfidious, restless, and dangerous enemy, he will, by way of punishment, deprive him of some of his towns or provinces, and keep them to serve as a barrier to his own dominions. Nothing is more allowable than to weaken an enemy who has rendered himself suspected and formidable. The lawful end of punishment is future secu- rity. The conditions necessary for rendering an acquisition, made by arms, just and irreproachable before God and our own conscience, are these, justice in the cause, and equity in the measure of the satisfaction. 495 385 OP ACQUISITIONS BY WAR, ETC. BOOK in. But nations cannot, in their dealings with each other, insist CHAP, xin. on this rigid justice. By the rules of the voluntary law of 195. Rules nations, every regular war is on both sides accounted just, as of the vo- to its effects ( 190) ; and no one has a right to judge a nation luntary law respecting the unreasonableness of her claims, or what she o nations. Chinks necessary for her own safety (Prelim. 21). Every acquisition, therefore, which has been made in regular war- fare, is valid according to the voluntary law of nations, inde- pendently of the justice of the cause and the reasons which may have induced the conqueror to assume the property of what he has taken. Accordingly, nations have ever esteemed conquest a lawful title ; and that title has seldom been dis- puted, unless where it was derived from a war not only unjust in itself, but even destitute of any plausible pretext. 196. Ac- The property of movable effects is vested in the enemy quisition of f rom the moment they come into his power ; and if he sells property t ^ iem to neutra l nations, the former proprietor is not entitled (168) to claim them. But such things must be actually and truly (168) See further, as to the effect of capture, as to movables and immovables, and the doctrine of postliminium, and the principle on which it is in general founded, post, 392, 204, 205 ; and the other authorities and modern deci- sions, Marten's L. N. 290293; 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, 414 435; and Id. Index, tit. Postliminium. As to movables captured in a land war, some writers on the law of nations state it to be merely requisite that the property shall have been twenty-four hours in the enemy's power, after which they contend, that the right of postli- minium is completely divested, so that immediately after the expiration of that time, they may be alienated to neutrals, as indefeasible property. Others con- tend, that the property must have been brought infra prcesidia, that is, within the camps, towns, ports, or fleets of the enemy : and others have drawn lines of an arbitrary nature. Marten's L. N. 290-1 ; 2 Wooddeson's Vin. L. 444, 34. With respect to maritime captures, a more absolute and certain species of possession has been required. In the case of Flad Oyen, 1 Rob. Rep. 134; Atcheson's Rep. 8, n. 9 ; and 8 Term Rep. 270, in notes, Sir Wm. Scott said, " By the general practice of the law of nations, a sentence of condemnation is at present deemed generally necessary; and a neutral purchaser in Europe, during war, does look to the legal sen- tence of condemnation as one of the title-deeds of the ship, if he buys a prize- vessel. I believe there is no instance in which a man, having purchased a prize- vessel of a belligerent, has thought himself secure in making that purchase, merely because that ship had been in the enemy's possession twenty-four hours, or carried infra pr&sidia. At any rate, the rule of condemnation is the general rule applied by England." So that, by the general law of nations, if a vessel be retaken before condemna- tion, by any ship of the nation of which the original owner is a subject, although even four years after the capture, he has a right to have the same restored to him, subject to his paying certain salvage to the re-captor. See Goss and Withers, 2 Burr. 683 ; Constant Mary, 3 Rob. Rep. 97 ; The Huldah, Id. 235 ; jlssievedo v. Cambridge, 10 Mod. 79. And such sentence of condemnation must also have been pronounced by a court of competent jurisdiction, and in the country either of the enemy him- self, or of some ally, and not in a neu- tral country. Flad Oyen, 1 Rob. Rep. 134; Havelock \. Rockwood, Atcheson's Rep. 8, n. 9. But if, after the time of the enemy's transferring his prize to a neutral, a peace be concluded between that enemy and the state from whose subject the prize was taken, then the transfer to the neutral becomes valid and perfect, even though there was no legal con demnation, for, as observed by Vattel the right of postliminium no longei OF ACQUISITIONS BY WAR, ETC. 385 in the enemy's power, and carried to a place of safety. Sup- BOOK m. pose a foreigner, coming into our country, buys a-portion of CHAP, xm. the booty which a party of enemies have just taken from us : our men, who are in pursuit of this party, may very justly seize on the booty which that foreigner was over precipitate in buying. On this head, Grotius quotes from De Thou the instance of the town of Lierre in Brabant, which having been captured and recaptured on the same day, the booty taken from the inhabitants was restored to them, because it had not been twenty-four hours in the enemy's hands.* This space of twenty-four hours, together with the practice observed at sea,f is an institution of the law of nations established by agreement or custom, and is even a civil law in some states. The natural reason of the conduct adopted towards the in- habitants of Lierre is, that the enemy being taken as it were in the fact, and before they had carried off the booty, it was not looked upon as having absolutely become their property, or been lost to the inhabitants. Thus, at sea, a ship taken [ 386 ] by the enemy may be retaken and delivered by other ships of her own party, as long as she has not been carried into some port, or into the midst of a fleet : her fate is not decided, nor is the owner's property irrecoverably lost, until the ship be in a place of safety with regard to the enemy who has taken her, and entirely in his power. But the ordinances of every state may make different regulations on this head between the citizens,! with a view either to prevent disputes, exists after the conclusion of peace, salvage to the re-captor. 1 Chitty's And see Sir W. Scott's decision on that Com. L. 434 6 ; and see Franklin, point, in Schooner Sop/tie, 6 Rob. Rep. 4 Rob. Rep. 147; 1 Edward's Rep. 68; 142. San Francisco, 1 Edward's Rep. 279 ; In cases arising between British sub- the Two Friends, 1 Rob. Rep. 271 ; jects with one another, and also in Cornu v. Blackburne, Dougl. 648. {Lu- cases arising between such subjects ler v. The Resolution, 2 Ball. Rep. 1.} and those of her allies, peculiar modifi- In the absence of express stipulations cations of the general law of nations with allies, Sir Wm. Scott observed, " I were introduced or acknowledged by understand that the actual rule of the Great Britain. Thus, it was established English maritime law is this : viz., that by several acts of parliament (13 Geo. the maritime law of England having 2, c. 4; 17 Geo. 2, c. 34; 19 Geo. 2, adopted a most liberal rule of restitu- c. 34; 43 Geo. 3, c. 160; and see tion with respect to the re-captured Hamilton v. Mendes, 2 Burr. 1198; property of its own subjects, gives the 1 Bla. Rep. 27), that the maritime right benefit of that rule to its allies, till it of postliminium shall subsist even to appears that they act towards British the end of the war ; and, therefore, the property on a less liberal principle. In ships or goods of the subjects of this such a case it adopts their rule, and country, taken at sea by an enemy, treats them according to their own and afterwards retaken, even at any measure of justice." Santa Cruz, indefinite period of time, and whether 1 Rob. Rep. 49. C. before or after sentence of condemna- * Grotius, de Jure Belli et Pacis, tion, are in general to be restored to lib. iii. cap. vi. iii. n. vii. the original proprietors, but subject to f See Grotius, ibid, and in the text, certain specified exceptions, and, in j Grotius, ibid, general, also subject to the payment of 63 2 R 2 497 386 OP ACQUISITIONS BY WAR, ETC. BOOK in. or to encourage armed vessels to retake merchant ships that CHAP, xiii. have fallen, into the enemy's hands. The justice or injustice of the cause does not here become an object of consideration. There would be no stability in the affairs of mankind, no safety in trading with nations engaged in war, if we were allowed to draw a distinction between a just and an unjust war, so as to attribute lawful effects to the one which we denied to the other. It would be opening a door to endless discussions and quarrels. This reason is of such weight, that, on account of it, the effects of a public war, at least with regard to movables, have been allowed to expeditions which deserved no other name than that of predatory enterprises, though carried on by regular armies. When, after the wars of the English in France, the grandes compagnies ranged about Europe, sacking and pillaging wher- ever they came, none of the sufferers was ever known to claim the booty which those plunderers had carried off and sold. At present, it would be in vain to claim a ship taken by the Barbary corsairs, and sold to a third party, or retaken from the captors ; though it is very improperly that the piracies of those barbarians can be considered as acts of regular war. We here speak of the external right : the internal right and the obligations of conscience undoubtedly require, that we should restore to a third party the property we recover from an enemy who had despoiled him of it in an unjust war, provided he can recognise that property, and will defray the expenses we have incurred in recovering it. Grotius quotes many instances of sovereigns and commanders who have generously restored such booty, even without requiring any thing for their trouble or expense.* But such conduct is Pursued only in cases where the booty has been recently taken, t would be an impracticable task, scrupulously to seek out the proprietors of what has been captured a long time back ; and moreover they have, no doubt, relinquished all their right to things which they had no longer any hope of recovering. Such is the usual mode of thinking with respect to captures in war, which are soon given up as irrecoverably lost. 197. Ac- Immovable possessions, lands, towns, provinces, &c., become quisition of the property of the enemy who makes himself master of them : ^orcon- CS ' k u t ^ ^ s on ty kj the treaty of peace, or the entire submission quest. (169) an( l extinction of the state to which those towns and provinces belonged, that the acquisition is completed, and the property becomes stable and perfect. 198. How Thus, a third party cannot safely purchase a conquered to transfer town or province, till the sovereign from whom it was taken i^em va- ^as renounced it by a treaty of peace, or has been irretrievably subdued, and has lost his sovereignty : for, while the war con- * Grotius, lib. iii. cap. xvi. post, chap. xiv. ; and the case of Breda (169) See further as to postliminium, Lust, 5 Bob. Rep. 233 251. C. 498 OF ACQUISITIONS BY WAR, ETC. 387 tinues, while the sovereign h$ s still hopes of recovering his BOOK m. possessions by arms, is a neutral prince to come and deprive CHAP, xm. him of the opportunity by purchasing that town or province from the conqueror ? The original proprietor cannot forfeit his rights by the act of a third person ; and if the purchaser be determined to maintain his purchase, he will find himself involved in the war. Thus, the king of Prussia became a party with the enemies of Sweden, by receiving Stettin from the hands of the king of Poland and the czar, under the title of sequestration.* But, when a sovereign has, by a definitive treaty of peace, ceded a country to the conqueror, he has relinquished all the right he had to it ; and it were absurd that he should be allowed to demand the restitution of that country by a subsequent conqueror, who wrests it from the former, or by any other prince, who has purchased it, or re- ceived it in exchange, or acquired it by any title whatever. The conqueror, who takes a town or province from his 199. Con- enemy, cannot justly acquire over it any other rights than dit i ns on such as belonged to the sovereign against whom he has taken up arms. War authorizes him to possess himself of what belongs to his enemy : if he deprives him of the sovereignty of that town or province, he acquires it such as it is, with all its limitations and modifications. Accordingly, care is usually taken to stipulate, both in particular capitulations and in treaties of peace, that the towns and countries ceded shall retain all their liberties, privileges, and immunities. And why should they be deprived of them by the conqueror, on account of his quarrel with their sovereign ? Nevertheless, if the inhabitants have been personally guilty of any crime against him, he may, by way of punishment, deprive them of their rights and privileges. This he may also do if the inhabitants have taken up arms against him, and have thus directly become his enemies. In that case, he owes them no more than what is due from a humane and equitable conqueror to his vanquished foes. Should he purely and simply incor- porate them with his former states, they will have no cause of complaint. Hitherto I evidently speak of a city or a country which is not simply an integrant part of a nation, or which does not fully belong to a sovereign, but over which that nation or that sovereign has certain rights. If the conquered town or pro- vince fully and perfectly constituted a part of the domain of a nation or sovereign, it passes on the same footing into the power of the conqueror. Thenceforward united with the new state to which it belongs, if it be a loser by the change, that is a misfortune which it must wholly impute to the chance of war. Thus, if a town which made part of a republic or a [ 388 ] limited monarchy, and enjoyed a right of sending 'deputies to * By the treaty of Schwedt, October 6, 1713. 499 388 OF ACQUISITIONS BY WAR, ETC. BOOK in. the supreme council or the general assembly of the states, be CHAP, xin. justly conquered by an absolute monarch, she must never more think of such privileges : they are what the constitution of the new state to which she is annexed does not permit. 200. Lands In the conquests of ancient times, even individuals lost their of private lands. Nor is it matter of surprise that in the first ages of persons. Rome such a custom should have prevailed. The wars of that era were carried on between popular republics and commu- nities. The state possessed very little, and the quarrel was in reality the common cause of all the citizens. But at pre- sent war is less dreadful in its consequences to the subject : matters are conducted with more humanity : one sovereign makes war against another sovereign, and not against the unarmed citizens. The conqueror seizes on the possessions of the state, the public property, while private individuals are permitted to retain theirs. They suffer but indirectly by the war ; and the conquest only subjects them to a new master. 201. Con- But if the entire state be conquered, if the nation be sub- quest of the dued, in what manner can the victor treat it, without trans- (170) StatC ' S ress ^ n S ^ e bounds of justice ? What are his rights over the conquered country ? Some have dared to advance this mon- strous principle, that the conqueror is absolute master of his conquest, that he may dispose of it as his property, that he may treat it as he pleases, according to the common expres- sion of treating a state as a conquered country ; and hence they derive one of the sources of despotic government. But, disregarding such writers, who reduce men to the state of transferable goods or beasts of burthen, who deliver them up as the property or patrimony of another man, let us argue on principles countenanced by reason and conformable to humanity. The whole right of the conqueror is derived from justifiable self-defence ( 3, 26, 28), which comprehends the support and prosecution of his rights. When, therefore, he has totally subdued a hostile nation, he undoubtedly may, in the first place, do himself justice respecting the object which had given rise to the war, and indemnify himself for the expenses and damages he has sustained by it : he may, according to the exigency of the case, subject the nation to punishment, by way of example : he may even, if prudence so require, render (170) When a country has been Trials, p. 322 ; and Cowper, 205 ; and conquered by the British, or any other Fabrigas v. Moslyn, Cowp. Rep. 165. arms, and having become a dominion But statutes previously passed do not of the king in right of his crown, the in general extend to a conquered coun- conquered inhabitants, once received try; see 2 Merivale's Rep. 156; 4 Mo- by the conqueror, become his subjects, dern Rep. 222 ; 1 Chitty's Com. L. and are universally to be regarded in 639, 640; 1 Bla. Com. 102 3. As that light, and not as enemies or aliens, to the application of the laws of Eng- Elphinttone v. Bedreechwid, Knapp's land to her foreign possessions, see Rep. 338 ; Campbell v. Hall, 23 State Gardiner v. Fell, 1 Jac. & Walk. 27 ; and Id. 30, n. (a). -C. 500 OP ACQUISITIONS BY WAR, ETC. 388 "her incapable of doing mischief with the same ease in future. BOOK m. But, for the attainment of these different objects, he is to CHAP, xm. prefer the gentlest methods, still bearing in mind that the doing of harm to an enemy is no further authorized by the law of nature, than in the precise degree which is necessary for justifiable self-defence, and reasonable security for the time to come. Some princes have contented themselves with imposing a tribute on the conquered nation, others, with depriving her of some of her rights, taking from her a pro- vince, or erecting fortresses to keep her in awe : others, again, confining their quarrel to the sovereign alone, have left the [ 389 ] nation in the full enjoyment of all their rights, only setting over her a new sovereign of their own appointment. But if the conqueror thinks proper to retain the sovereignty of the conquered state, and has a right to retain it, the same principles must also determine the manner in which he is to treat that state. If it is against the sovereign alone that he has just cause of complaint, reason plainly evinces that he acquires no other rights by his conquest than such as belonged to the sovereign whom he has dispossessed : and, on the sub- mission of the people, he is bound to govern them according to the laws of the state. If the people do not voluntarily submit, the state of war still subsists. A conqueror who has taken up arms, not only against the sovereign, but against the nation herself, and whose intention it was to subdue a fierce and savage people, and once for all to reduce an obstinate enemy, such a conqueror may with justice lay burthens on the conquered nation, both as a com- pensation for the expenses of the war, and as a punishment. He may, according to the degree of indocility apparent in their disposition, govern them with a tighter rein, so as to curb and subdue their impetuous spirit : he may even, if necessary, keep them for some time in a kind of slavery. But this forced condition ought to cease from the moment the danger is over, the moment the conquered people are become citi- zens : for then the right of conquest is at an end, so far as relates to the pursuit of those rigorous measures, since the conqueror no longer finds it necessary to use extraordinary precautions for his own defence and safety. Then at length every thing is to be rendered conformable to the rules of a wise government and the duties of a good prince. When a sovereign, arrogating to himself the absolute dis- posal of a people whom he has conquered, attempts to reduce them to slavery, he perpetuates the state of warfare between that nation and himself. The Scythians said to Alexander the Great, " There is never any friendship between the master and slave : in the midst of peace the rights of war still subsist."* * Inter dominum et servum nulla amicitia est ; etiam in pace, belli tamen jura servantur. Q. Curt. lib. vii. cap. viii. 501 389 OF ACQUISITIONS BY WAR, ETC. BOOK in. Should it be said, that in such a case there may be peace, and CHAP, sin. a ki nc l of compact by which the conqueror consents to spare the lives of the vanquished, on condition that they acknow- ledge themselves his slaves, he who makes such an assertion is ignorant that war gives no right to take away the life of an enemy who has laid down his arms and submitted ( 140). But let us not dispute the point : let the man who holds such principles of jurisprudence, keep them for his own use and benefit : he well deserves to be subject to such a law. But men of spirit, to whom life is nothing, less than nothing, unless sweetened with liberty, will always conceive themselves at war [ 390 ] with that oppressor, though actual hostilities are suspended on their part through want of ability. We may, therefore, safely venture to add, that if the conquered country is to be really subject to the conqueror as to its lawful sovereign, he must rule it according to the ends for which civil government has been established. It is generally the prince alone who occasions the war, and consequently the conquest. Surely it is enough that an innocent people suffer the calamities of war : must even peace itself become fatal to them ? A generous conqueror will study to relieve his new subjects, and mitigate their condition : he will think it his indispensable duty. " Con- quest (says an excellent man) ever leaves behind it an im- mense debt, the discharge of which is absolutely necessary to acquit the conqueror in the eye of humanity."* It fortunately happens, that, in this particular as in every thing else, sound policy and humanity are in perfect accord. What fidelity, what assistance, can you expect from an op- pressed people ? Do you wish that your conquest may prove a real addition to your strength, and be well affected to you ? treat it as a father, as a true sovereign. I am charmed with the generous answer recorded of an ambassador from Priver- num. Being introduced to the Roman senate, he was asked by the consul " If we show you clemency, what dependence can we have on the peace you are come to sue for?" "If (replied the ambassador) you grant it on reasonable condi- tions, it will be safe and permanent : otherwise, it will not last long." Some took offence at the boldness of this speech ; but the more sensible part of the senate approved of the Priver- nian's answer, deeming it the proper language of a man and a freeman. " Can it be imagined (said those wise senators) that any nation, or even any individual, will longer continue in an irksome and disagreeable condition, than while com- pelled to submit to it ? If those to whom you give peace receive it voluntarily, it may be relied on : what fidelity can you expect from those whom you wish to reduce to slavery ?"f * Montesquieu, in his Spirit of remittimus vobis, qualem nos pacem Laws. vobiscum habituros speremus ? Si bo- f Quid, si poenam (inquit consul) nam dederitis, inquit, et fidam et per- OF ACQUISITIONS BY WAR, ETC. 390 "The most secure dominion," said Camillus, "is that which BOOKHI. is acceptable to those over whom it is exercised."* CHAP, xm. Such are the rights which the law of nature gives to the conqueror, and the duties which it imposes on him. The manner of exerting the one, and fulfilling the other, varies according to circumstances. In general, he ought to consult the true interests of his own state, and by sound policy to [ 391 ] reconcile them, as far as possible, with those of the conquered country. He may, in imitation of the kings of France, unite and incorporate it with his own dominions. Such was the practice of the Romans : but they did this in different modes according to cases and conjunctures. At a time when Rome stood in need of an increase of population, she destroyed the town of Alba, which she feared to have as a rival : but she received all its inhabitants within her walls, and thereby gained so many new citizens. In after times the conquered cities were left standing, and the freedom of Rome was given to the vanquished inhabitants. Victory could not have proved so advantageous to those people as their defeat. The conqueror may likewise simply put himself in the place of the sovereign whom he has dispossessed. Thus the Tartars have acted in China : the empire was suffered to subsist in its former condition, except that it fell under the dominion of a new race of sovereigns. Lastly, the conqueror may rule his conquest as a separate state, and permit it to retain its own form of government. But this method is dangerous : it produces no real union of strength ; it weakens the conquered country, without making any considerable addition to the power of the victorious state. It is asked, to whom the conquest belongs, to the prince 202. To who has made it, or to the state ? This question ought never whom the to have been heard of. Can the prince, in his character of sovereign, act for any other end than the good of the state ? Whose are the forces which he employs in his wars ? Even if he made the conquest at his own expense, out of his own revenue or his private and patrimonial estates, does he not make use of the personal exertions of his subjects in achieving it ? Does he not shed their blood in the contest ? But, supposing even that he were to employ foreign or mer- cenary troops, does he not expose his nation to the enemy's petuam; si malam, haud diuturnam. esse fidam, ubi voluntarii pacati sint; Turn vero minari, nee id ambigue Pri- neque eo loco, ubi servitutem esse velint, vernatem, quidam, et illis vocibus ad fidem sperandam esse. Tit. Liv. lib. rebellandum incitari pacatos populos, viii. cap. xxi. Pars melior senatus ad meliora re- * Certe id firmissimum longe impe- sponsa trahere, et dicere viri et liberi rium est, quo obedientes gaudent. Tit. vocem auditam : an credi posse ullum Liv. lib. viii. cap. xiii. populum, aut hominem denique, in ea (171) Ante, 365, s. 164, and note conditione cujus eum pceniteat, diutius (165). quam necesse sit, mansurum ? ibi pacem 391 OF ACQUISITIONS BY WAK, ETC. BOOK m. resentment ? Does he not involve her in the war ? And CHAP, xnr. shall he alone reap all the advantages of it ? Is it not for the cause of the state, and of the nation, that he takes up arms ? The nation, therefore, has a just claim to all the rights to which such war gives birth. If the sovereign embarks in a war, of which his own per- sonal interests are the sole ground, as, for instance, to assert his right of succession to a foreign sovereignty, the question then assumes a new face. In this affair the state is wholly unconcerned : but then the nation should be at liberty either to refuse engaging in it, or to assist her prince, at her own option. If he is empowered to employ the national force in support of his personal rights, he should, in such case, make no distinction between these rights and those of the state. The French law, which annexes to the crown all acquisitions made by the king, should be the law of all nations.(lTl) 203. Whe- It has been observed ( 196) that we maybe obliged, if not ther we are externally, yet in conscience, and by the laws of equity, to bert* f U " restore to a tn i r( * P art J tne booty we have recovered out of people** * ne hands of an enemy who had taken it from him in an unjust whom the war. The obligation is more certain and more extensive, with enemy had regard to a people whom our enemy had unjustly oppressed, unjustly p or a p e0 pi e thus spoiled of their liberty, never renounce the hope of recovering it. If they have not voluntarily incorpo- [ 392 ] rated themselves with the state by which they have been sub- dued, if they have not freely aided her in the war against us, we certainly ought so to use our victory, as not merely to give them a new master, but to break their chains. To deliver an oppressed people is a noble fruit of victory : it is a valuable advantage gained, thus to acquire a faithful friend. The canton of Schweitz, having wrested the country of Glaris from the house of Austria, restored the inhabitants to their former liberties ; and Glaris, admitted into the Helvetic con- federacy, formed the sixth canton. *(172) (171) dnte, 365, s. 164, and note tion; and this is the principle of just (165). war. So, there is no regular inter- * Histoire de la Confederation Hel- national or even municipal court to ve'tique, par M. de Watteville, liv. iii. adjudicate upon questions of lawful under the year 1351. capture or prize. And in Great Britain, (172) As nations are independent of no municipal court, whether of common each other, and acknowledge no supe- law or equity, can take cognizance of rior (ante, in several places), there is, any questions arising out of hostile seiz- unfortunately, no sovereign power we; nor can any question respecting among nations to uphold or enforce the infraction of treaties be directly agi- the international kw; no tribunal to tated before courts of law, any more which the oppressed can appeal, as of than questions respecting booty ac- right, against the oppressor ; and, con- quired in a continental inland war. sequently, if either nation refuse to In general, in all states, this is a juris- give effect to the established principles diction assumed only by the sovereign, of international law, the only redress in whom the right or power of declaring is by resorting to arms, and enforcing war and peace, and modifying their the performance of the national obliga- terms, is vested, excepting in some cases 604 OF THE RIGHT OF POSTLIMINIUM. 392 BOOK III. CHAP. XIV. CHAP. XIV. OF THE RIGHT OF POSTLIMINIUM. (173) THE right of postliminium is that in virtue of which per- 204. De- sons and things taken by the enemy are restored to their finition of . the right of of particular facts, where the king has thought fit to act with the concurrence of his nation at large, instead of pro- ceeding only upon his prerogative. In Great Britain, the king usually, by a special commission, delegates his power to decide upon questions of capture and prize to the chief judge of the Admi- ralty Court, but quite separate from his ordinary jurisdiction, with an appeal to the Privy Council ; and before that tri- bunal alone can any question of capture or prize be discussed ; (Elphinstone v. Bedreechund, Knapp's Rep. Privy Coun- cil, 316 to 361; Le Caux v. Eden, Dougl. 594 ; Hill v. Reardon, 2 Rus- sell's Rep. 608 ;) and not in an action at law or court of equity, excepting in the case of a trust. Id. ibid. ; and Faith v. Pearson, Holt's Cas. Ni. Pri. 113. Therefore, where the members of the provisional government of a recent- ly conquered country seized the property of a native of it, who had been refused the benefit of the articles of capitula- tion of a fortress of which he had been the governor, but had been permitted to reside, under military surveillance, in his own house in the city in which the seizure was made, and which was at a considerable distance from the scene of actual hostilities ; it was held by the House of Lords, hi England, that the seizure having been made fiagrante et nondum cessante hello, must be regarded in the light of a hostile seizure, and that a municipal court had no jurisdiction on the sub- ject ; (Elphinstone v. Bedreechund, Knapp's Rep. 316 to 361 ; and see Hill v. Reardon, 2 Sim. & Stu. 431 ; but which on one point, respecting a trust, was afterwards overruled in Chancery ; Id. 2 Russ. 608 ;) and per Lord Tenterden" We think the proper character of the transaction was that of a hostile seizure, made, if not flagrante, yet nondum cessante ^ Oi hello, regard being had both to the UI1 time, the place, and the person ; and, consequently, that the municipal court had no jurisdiction to adjudge upon the subject : but that, if any thing was done amiss, recourse could only be had to the government for redress. We shall therefore re- commend it to his majesty to reverse the judgment of the Su- preme Court of Bombay." Id. page 360-1. 'Again, it has been held that the circumstances that a recently conquered city, where a seizure of the property of a native is made by the members of a provisional government during time of war, had been some months previously in the undisturbed possession of that government, and that courts for the administration of justice were then sitting in it, under the authority of that government, do not alter the character of the transac- tion, so as to make it a subject of cognizance by a municipal court." Id. 316. And there is no distinction, in this respect, between the public and private property of an absolute monarch ; and, therefore, money in the hands of the banker of an absolute monarch, whose territory has been conquered by the British, may be recovered from the banker, on an information, on behalf of the crown. Mvocate-General of Bombay v. Jlmtr- chund, Knapp's Rep. 329, note ; El- phinstone v. Bedreechund, Knapp's Rep. 357. As the capture, in general, belongs to the sovereign of the state (although, by municipal regulations, the actual captors may acquire some subordinate rights), it also follows that no British subject can maintain an action against the captor. Caux v. Eden, 2 Dougl. 573. In a state resulting from a state (173) See, in general, 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, 430 to 435; Id. Index, tit. Postliminium. C. 64 28 506 392 OF THE RIGHT OF POSTLIMINITTM. BOOK in. former state, on coming again into the power of the nation CHAP, xiv. to which they belonged. (174) 205. Foun- ^ e sovereign is bound to protect the persons and dationof property of his subjects, and to defend them against the this right, enemy. When, therefore, a subject, or any part of his property, has fallen into thevenemy's possession, should any fortunate event bring them again into the sovereign's power, it is undoubtedly his duty to restore them to their former condition, to re-establish the persons in all their rights and obligations, to give back the effects to the owners, of war, if property be seized under an erroneous supposition that it belongs to the enemy, it may be liberated by the proper authorities ; but no action can be maintained against the party who has taken it, in a court of law. Caux v. Eden, 2 Dougl. 573 ; Elphin- stone v. Bedreechund, Knapp's Rep. 357. If an English naval commander seize any movable as enemies' pro- perty, that turns out clearly to be British property, he forfeits his prize to the Prize Court (sometimes con- founded with the Court of Admiralty), and that court awards the return of it to the party from whom it was taken. The Court of Admiralty is the proper tribunal for the trial of questions of prize or no prize, and it exercises this jurisdiction as a court of prize, under a commission from his majesty ; and if it makes an unsatisfactory deter- mination, an appeal lies to his ma- jesty in council ; for, the king reserves the ultimate right to decide on such questions by his own authority, and does not commit their determination to any municipal court of justice. Booty taken under the colour of military authority, falls under the same rule. If property be taken by an officer under the supposition that it is the property of a hostile state, or of individuals, which ought to be con- fiscated, no municipal court can judge of the propriety or impropriety of the seizure : it can be judged of only by an authority delegated by his majesty, and by his majesty, ultimately, as- sisted by the lords in council. There are no direct decisions on such ques- tions, because, as was stated by Lord Mansfield, in Lindo v. Rodney, they are cases of rare occurrence. Elphinstone v. Bedreechund, Knapp's Rep. 340, 357-8; Caux v. Eden, Dougl. 592 ; Lindo v. Rodney, Id. 313. 506 For these reasons, it is usual, when questions of importance between two sovereigns, or their subjects, arise, by particular treaty, to constitute a tri- bunal for that special purpose; and municipal statutes have been passed in England in aid of such treaty. Thus, by additional articles of the definitive treaty of peace between Great Britain and France, of the 30th May 1814, certain conventions were made for indemnifying British sub- jects for the confiscation of their pro- perty by the French revolutionary government, and certain commission- ers were appointed between the two countries, to examine and decide upon such British claims ; and the statute 59 Geo. 3, c. 51, was passed with the same object ; and such claims were adjudicated upon between the two countries. It was held, however, that these conventions and treaties, and the act for carrying the same into effect, did not exclude the jurisdiction of a court of equity to examine and enforce equities attaching upon the compensation in the hands of the person in whose favour the award of the commissioners had been made; (Hill v. Reardon, 2 Russell's Rep. 609, overruling S. C. in 2 Sim. & Stu. 437;) and it was holden that, where a person, in whose favour an adjudication under such conven- tions has been made by the com- missioners or by the Privy Council, is affected by a trust or by fraud, a court of equity has jurisdiction to enforce the trust or relieve against the fraud (id. ibid.) ; and the same prin- ciple would, no doubt, be extended to cases of capture or prize. C. (174) See ante, s. 196, page 385, note (168), as to movables and ships. C. OF THE EIGHT OF POSTLIMINIUM. 392 in a word, to replace every thing on the same footing on BOOK m. which it stood previous to the enemy's capture. CHAP. XIT. The justice or injustice of the war makes no difference in this case, not only because, according to the voluntary law of nations, the war, as to its effects, is reputed just on both sides, but likewise because war, whether just or not, is a national concern ; and, if the subjects who fight or suffer in the national cause, should, after they have, either in their persons or their property, fallen into the enemy's power, be, by some fortunate incident, restored to the hands of their own people, there is no reason why they should not be restored to their former condition. It is the same as if they had never been taken. If the war be just on the part of their nation, they were unjustly captured by the enemy ; and thus nothing is more natural than to restore them as soon as it becomes possible. If the war be unjust, they are under no greater obligation to suffer in atonement for its injustice than the rest of the nation. Fortune brings down the evil on their heads when they are taken : she delivers them from it when they escape. Here, again, it is the same as if they never had been captured. Neither their own sovereign, nor the enemy, has any particular right over [ 393 "] them. The enemy has lost by one accident what he had gained by another. Persons return, and things are recovered, by the right of 206. How postliminium, when, after having been taken by the enemy, it; takes ef - they come again into the power of their own nation ( 204). ' This right, therefore, takes effect as soon as such persons or things captured by the enemy fall into the hands of sol- diers belonging to their own nation, or are brought back to the army, the camp, the territories of their sovereign, or the places under his command. Those who unite with us to carry on a war are joint par- 207. Whe- ties with us : we are engaged in a common cause ; our ther it takes right is one and the same ; and they are considered as effect among making but one body with us. Therefore, when persons or ^^ ies things captured by the enemy are retaken by our allies or auxiliaries, or in any other manner fall into their hands, this, so far as relates to the effect of the right, is precisely the same thing as if they were come again into our own power ; since, in the cause in which we are jointly embark- ed, our power and that of our allies is but one and the same. The right of postliminium therefore takes effect among those who carry on the war in conjunction with us ; and the persons and things recovered by them from the enemy are to be restored to their former condition. (175) (175) As to the general rule in the But, in general, the precise rule is absence of treaty, see Santa Cruz, fixed by treaty between allies. Id. I Rob. Rep. 49 ; ante, 385, n. (168). ibid. C. 507 393 OF THE RIGHT OF POSTLIMINIUM. BOOK in. But, does this right take place in the territories of our CHAP, xiv. allies ? Here a distinction arises. If those allies make a common cause with us, if they are associates in the war, we are necessarily entitled to the right of postliminium in their territories as well as in our own : for, their state is united with ours, and, together with it, continues but one party in the war we carry on. But if, as in our times is frequently the practice, an ally only gives us a stated suc- cour stipulated by treaty, and does not himself come to a rupture with our enemy, between whose state and his own, in their immediate relations, peace continues to be observed, in this case, only the auxiliaries whom he sends to our assistance are partakers and associates in the war ; and his dominions remain in a state of neutrality. 208. Of no Now, the right of postliminium does not take effect in validity in ne utral countries : for, when a nation chooses to remain neuter in a war, she is bound to consider it as equally just on both sides, so far as relates to its effects, and, conse- quently, to look upon every capture made by either party as a lawful acquisition. To allow one of the parties, in prejudice to the other, to enjoy in her dominions the right [ 394 ] of claiming things taken by the latter, or the right of post- liminium, would be declaring in favour of the former, and departing from the line of neutrality. 209. What Naturally, every kind of property might be recovered by things are fa e r ight of postliminium ; and there is no intrinsic reason by^thtr e wn y movables should be excepted in this case, provided right (176) they can be certainly recognised and identified. Accord- ingly, the ancients, on recovering such things from the enemy, frequently restored them to their former owners.* But the difficulty of recognising things of this nature, and the endless disputes which would arise from the prosecu- tion of the owners' claims to them, have been deemed mo- tives of sufficient weight for the general establishment of a contrary practice. To these considerations we may add, that, from the little hope entertained of recovering effects taken by the enemy and once carried to a place of safety, a reasonable presumption arises that the former owners have relinquished their property. It is therefore with reason that movables or booty are excepted from the right of postliminium, unless retaken from the enemy immediately after his capture of them ; in which case, the proprietor neither finds a difficulty in recognising his effects, nor is presumed to have relinquished them. And, as the custom has once been admitted, and is now well established, there would be an injustice in violating it (Prelim. 26). Among (176) As to movables and ships, * See several instances in Grotius, ante, 384, n. C. book iii. ch. xvi. 2. OF THE RIGHT OF POSTLIMINIUM. 394 the Romans, indeed, slaves were not treated like other BOOK m. movable property : they, by the right of postliminium, CHAP, xiv. were restored to their masters, even when the rest of the booty was detained. The reason of this is evident : for, as it was at all times easy to recognise a slave, and ascertain to whom he belonged, the owner, still entertaining hopes of recovering him, was not supposed to have relinquished his right. Prisoners of war, who have given their parole, territories 210. Of and towns which have submitted to the enemy, and kave^ e J- sworn or promised allegiance to him, cannot of themselves *^ n ^ t r _ return to their former condition by the right of postlimi- turn by the nium : for, faith is to be kept even with enemies (174). rightofpost- But if the sovereign retakes those towns, countries, or limmmm - prisoners, who had surrendered to the enemy, he recovers ( ' all his former rights over them, and is bound to re-establish 2 . x l 7" he y them in their pristine condition ( 205). In this case, they^^en enjoy the right of postliminium without any breach of their retaken, word, any violation of their plighted faith. The enemy loses by the chance of war a right which the chance of war had before given him. But, concerning prisoners of war, a distinction is to be made. If they were entirely free on their parole, the single circumstance of their coming again into the power of their own nation does not release them, since, even if they had returned home, they would still have continued prisoners. The consent of the enemy who had captured them, or his total subjugation, can alone dis- charge" them. But, if they have only promised not to effect their escape, a promise which prisoners frequently make [ 395 ] in order to avoid the inconveniences of a jail, the only obligation incumbent on them is, that they shall not, of themselves, quit the enemy's country, or the place assigned for their residence. And if the troops of their party should gain possession of the place where they reside, the consequence is, that, by the right of war, they recover their liberty, are restored to their own nation, and reinstated in their former condition. (178) (177) In general, as regards coun- absolutely new. Upon this principle tries or persons taken by a belligerent was decided an important question state, who were not the subjects of in the case of Boedes Lust, 5 Rob. that state during any preceding part Rep. 233 ; and on the same principle of the same war, a different rule pre- it was established, that, if a neutral vails than that laid down by Vattel, have but just set his foot on the sect. 211 ; for, the law of postliminium colony of an enemy for a few hours implies that the party claiming it before its capture ; but if it be proved returns to his previous character, that he went there for the purpose of And he who, during the whole war, settling, then his property will be has been the subject of the enemy subject to condemnation, as if he alone, must be considered, when he were a native enemy. And see the falls into the hands of the rival state, Diana, 5 Rob. Rep. 60. C. not as returning to a previous cha- (178) See note (177), ante. racter, but as acquiring a character 2s 2 509 395 OF THE RIGHT OF POSTLIMINIUM. BOOK in. When a town, reduced by the enemy's arms, is retaken by CHAP, xiv. those of her own sovereign, she is, as we have above seen, 2 12. Whe- restored to her former condition, and reinstated in the pos- ther this session of all her rights. It is asked whether she thus re- tflMjs T" covers such P ar t f ner property as had been alienated by tne'ir pro- *k e enemy while he kept her in subjection. In the first place, perty alien- we are to make a distinction between movable property not ated by recoverable by the right of postliminium ( 202), and im- the enemy, movables. The former belongs to the enemy who gets it into his hands, and he may irrecoverably alienate it. As to immovables, let it be remembered that the acquisition of a town taken in war is "not fully consummated till confirmed by a treaty of peace, or by the entire submission or destruction of the state to which it belonged ( 197). Till then, the sove- reign of that town has hopes of retaking it, or of recovering it by a peace. And from the moment it returns into his power, he restores it to all its rights ( 205), and consequently it recovers all its possessions, as far as in their nature they are recoverable. It therefore resumes its immovable possessions from the hands of those persons who have been so prematurely forward to purchase them. In buying them of one who had not an absolute right to dispose of them, the purchasers made a hazardous bargain ; and if they prove losers by the transac- tion, it is a consequence to which they deliberately exposed themselves. But if that town had been ceded to the enemy by a treaty of peace, or was completely fallen into his power by the submission of the whole state, she has no longer any claim to the right of postliminium ; and the alienation of any of her possessions by the conqueror is valid and irreversible ; nor can she lay claim to them, if, in the sequel, some fortunate revolution should liberate her from the yoke of the conqueror. When Alexander made a present to the Thessalians of the sum due from them to the Thebans (see 77), he was so abso- lutely master of the republic of Thebes, that he destroyed the city and sold the inhabitants. The same decisions hold good with regard to the immov- able property of individuals, prisoners or not, which has been alienated by the enemy while he was master of the country. Grotius proposes the question with respect to immovable pro- perty possessed in a neutral country by a prisoner of war.* [ 396 ] But, according to the principles we have laid down, this question is groundless : for, the sovereign who makes a pri- soner in war, has no other right over him than that of detain- ing his person until the conclusion of the war, or until he be ransomed ( 148, &c.) ; but he acquires no right to the pri- soner's property, unless he can seize on it. It is impossible to produce any natural reason why the captor should have a right , * Lib. iii. cap. ix. vL 510 OF THE EIGHT OF POSTLIMINIUM. 396 to dispose of his prisoner's property, unless the prisoner has BOOK m. it about him. CHAP. XIY. When a nation, a people, a state, has been entirely sub- 2 i3.Whe- dued, it is asked whether a revolution can entitle them to the ther a na- right of postliminium. In order justly to answer this ques- tion that has tion, there must again be a distinction of cases. If that j^Jjj 1 e ^_ conquered state has not yet acquiesced in her new subjection, due Jean en- fa as not voluntarily submitted, and has only ceased to resist j oy the right from inability, if her victor has not laid aside the sword of of postlimi- conquest and taken up the sceptre of peace and equity, mum * such a people are not really subdued : they are only defeated and oppressed ; and, on being delivered by the arms of an ally, they doubtless return to their former situation ( 207). Their ally cannot become their conqueror ; he is their deli- verer ; and all the obligation of the party delivered is to re- ward him. If the subsequent conqueror, not being an ally to the state of which we speak, intends to keep it under his own jurisdiction as the reward of his victory, he puts him- self in the place of the former conqueror, and becomes the enemy of the state which the other had oppressed: that state may lawfully resist him, and avail herself of a favour- able opportunity to recover her liberty. If she had been unjustly oppressed, he who rescues her from the yoke of the oppressor ought generously to reinstate her in the possession of all her rights ( 203). The question changes with regard to a state which haa voluntarily submitted to the conqueror. If the people, no longer treated as enemies, but as actual subjects, have sub- mitted to a lawful government, they are thenceforward de- pendent on a new sovereign; or, being incorporated with the victorious nation, they become a part of it, and share its fate. Their former state is absolutely destroyed; all its relations, all its alliances are extinguished (Book II. 203). Whoever, then, the new conqueror may be, that afterwards subdues the state to which these people are united, they share the destiny of that state, as a part shares the fate of the whole. This has been the practice of nations in all ages, I say, even of just and equitable nations, especially with regard to an ancient conquest. The most moderate conqueror confines his generosity in this particular to the restoration of the liberties of a people who have been but recently sub- dued, and whom he does not consider as perfectly incorporated, or well cemented by inclination, with the state which he has conquered. If the people in question shake off the yoke and recover their liberty by their own exertions, they regain all their rights ; they return to their former situation ; and foreign nations have no right to determine whether they have shaken off the yoke of lawful authority, or burst the chains of slavery. Thus, the kingdom of Portugal, which had been seized on 511 397 OF THE RIGHT OF POSTLIMINIUM. BOOK in. by Philip II. king of Spain, under pretence of an hereditary CHAP, xiv. right, but in reality by force and the terror of his arms, re-established the independency of her crown, and recovered her former rights, when she drove out the Spaniards, and placed the duke of Braganza on the throne. 214. Right Provinces, towns, and lands, which the enemy restores by niuTfS 1 "" the treat y of P eace > are certainly entitled to the right of post- what is re- i"*"Wttl : for, the sovereign, in whatever manner he reco- stored at the vers them, is bound to restore them to their former condition, peace, as soon as he regains possession of them ( 205). The enemy, in giving back a town at the peace, renounces the right he had acquired by arms. It is just the same as if he had never taken it ; and the transaction furnishes no reason which can justify the sovereign in refusing to reinstate such town in the possession of all her rights, and restore her to her former condition. 215. and But whatever is ceded to the enemy by a treaty of peace, ceded't^th 18 t ru ty an( ^ completely alienated. It has no longer any enemy. 6 c l a i m to the right of postliminium, unless the treaty of peace be broken and cancelled. 216. The And as things not mentioned in the treaty of peace re- r'm^niu 1 * 081 " ma ^ n * n the condition in which they happen to be at the does not er- ^ me when the treaty is concluded, and are, on both sides, ist after a tacitly ceded to the present possessor, it may be said, in ge- peace. neral, that the right of postliminium no longer exists after the conclusion of the peace. That right entirely relates to the states of war. 217. Why Nevertheless, and for this very reason, there is an excep- always m ^ion to be made here in favour of prisoners of war. Their sonere Pn ~ sovere ig n is bound to release them at the peace ( 154). But, if he cannot accomplish this, if the fate of war compels him to accept of hard and unjust conditions, the enemy, who ought to set the prisoners at liberty when the war is termi- nated, and he has no longer any thing to fear from them ( 150, 153), continues the state of war with respect to them, if he still detains them in captivity, and especially if he reduces them to slavery ( 152). They have therefore a right to effect their escape from him, if they have an oppor- tunity, and to return to their own country, equally as in war time ; since, with regard to them, the war still continues. And in that case, the sovereign, from his obligation to pro- tect them, is bound to restore them to their former condi- tion ( 205). 218. They Further, those prisoners who are, without any lawful rea- are free even gonj detained after the conclusion of peace, become imme- hLTne^ di^ 61 ? fr ee, when, once escaped from captivity, they have t r ai country. even reached a neutral country : for, enemies are not to be pursued and seized on neutral ground ( 132) ; and whoever detains an innocent prisoner after the peace, continues to be his enemy. This rule should and actually does obtain 512 OF THE RIGHT OF POSTLIMINIUM. 397 among nations who do not admit and authorize the practice BOOK m. of enslaving prisoners of war. It is sufficiently evident from the premises, that prisoners 219. HOW are to be considered as citizens who may one day return to the ri ^ te their country : and, when they do return, it is the duty of tionsof lg ri the sovereign to re-establish them in their former condition, soners sub- Hence it clearly follows, that the rights of every one of sist those prisoners, together with his obligations (or the rights of others over him), still subsist undiminished, only the [ 398 ] exertion of them is, for the most part, suspended during the time of his captivity. The prisoner of war therefore retains a right to dispose of 220. Tes- his property, particularly in case of death : and, as there is tament of a ,,\ r . *V , ***. -L- i. 0.1. i ii prisoner of nothing m the state of captivity which can in this latter re-^ ar spect deprive him of the exercise of his right, the testament of a prisoner of war ought to be valid in his own country, unless rendered void by some inherent defect. With nations which have established the indissolubility of ? 221. Mar- the marriage ties, or have ordained that they should continue nage * for life unless dissolved by the judgment of a court, those ties still subsist, notwithstanding the captivity of one of the parties, who, on his return home, is, by postliminium, again entitled to all his matrimonial rights. We do not here enter into a detail of what the civil laws of ? 222. Re- particular nations have ordained with respect to the right of postliminium : we content ourselves with observing that such - local regulations are obligatory on the subjects of the state n i u m, esta- alone, and do not affect foreigners. Neither do we here ex- blished by amine what has been settled on that head by treaties : those treaty or particular compacts establish merely a conventional right, CU which relates only to the contracting parties. Customs con- firmed by long and constant use are obligatory on those na- tions who have given a tacit consent to them ; and they are to be respected, when not contrary to the law of nature : but those which involve an infringement of that sacred law are faulty and invalid ; and, instead of conforming to such customs, every nation is bound to use her endeavours, to effect their abolition. Among the Romans the right of postliminium was in force, even in times of profound peace, with respect to nations with which Rome had neither connections of friend- ship, rights of hospitality, nor alliance.* This was because those nations were, as we have already observed, considered in some measure as enemies. The prevalence of milder man- ners has almost everywhere abolished that remnant of bar- barism. * Digest, lib. xlix. de Capt et Postlim. leg. v. 3 ii. 65 513 399 OF THE RIGHT OF BOOK III. CHAP. XV. CHAP. XV. OF THE RIGHT OF PRIVATE PERSONS IN WAR. 223. Sub- THE right of making war, as we have shown in the first jects cannot chapter of this book, solely belongs to the sovereign power, commit hos- wn j cn no t on }y decides whether it be proper to undertake the oiuLYso?" war > an( * to Declare it, but likewise directs all its operations, vereign's as circumstances of the utmost importance to the safety of order. the state. Subjects, therefore, cannot of themselves take any steps in this aifair ; nor are they allowed to commit any act of hostility without orders from their sovereign. Be it understood, however, that, under the head of "hostilities," we do not here mean to include self-defence. A subject may repel the violence of a fellow-citizen when the magistrate's assistance is not at hand ; and with much greater reason may he defend himself against the unexpected attacks of foreigners. 224. That The sovereign's order, which commands acts of hostility, order may an d gives a right to commit them, is either general or parti- be general cu i ar> ^Q declaration of war, which enjoins the subjects at larf" large to attack the enemy's subjects, implies a general order. The generals, officers, soldiers, privateers-men, and partisans, being all commissioned by the sovereign, make war by virtue of a particular order. g 225. But, though an order from the sovereign be necessary to Source of authorize the subjects to make war, that necessity wholly re- the neces- 8u lts from the laws essential to every political society, and sity of such no ^. f rom an y obligation relative to the enemy. For, when one nation takes up arms against another, she from that mo- ment declares herself an enemy to all the individuals of the latter, and authorizes them to treat her as such. What right could she have in that case to complain of any acts of hos- tility committed against her by private persons without orders from their superiors ? The rule, therefore, of which we here speak, relates rather to public law in general, than to the law of nations properly so called, or to the principles of the re- ciprocal obligations of nations. ? 226. Why 1^ we confine our views to the law of nations, considered in the law of itself, when once two nations are engaged in war, all the nations subjects of the one may commit hostilities against those of s the other ' and do them a11 the mischief authorized by the s state of war. But, should two nations thus encounter each other with the collective weight of their whole force, the war would become much more bloody and destructive, and could hardly be terminated otherwise than by the utter extinction of one of the parties. The examples of ancient wars abun- dantly prove the truth of this assertion to any man who will for a moment recall to mind the first wars waged by Home 514 PRIVATE PERSONS IN WAR. 400 against the popular republics by which she was surrounded. BOOK m. It is therefore with good reason that the contrary practice . CHA p- * v -.. has grown into a custom with the nations of Europe, at least with those that keep up regular standing armies or bodies of militia. The troops alone carry on the war, while the rest of the nation remain in peace. And the necessity of a special order to act is so thoroughly established, that, even after a declaration of war between two nations, if the peasants of themselves commit any hostilities, the enemy shows them no mercy, but hangs them up as he would so many robbers or banditti. The crews of private ships of war stand in the same predicament : a commission from their sovereign or admiral can alone, in case they are captured, insure them such treat- ment as is given to prisoners taken in regular warfare. In declarations of war, however, the ancient form is still 225". Pre- retained, by which the subjects in general are ordered, not cise mean - only to break off all intercourse with the enemy, (179) but ^ e f th also to attack him. Custom interprets this general order. It authorizes, indeed, and even obliges every subject, of what- ever rank, to secure the persons and things belonging to the enemy, when they fall into his hands (179); but it does not invite the subjects to undertake any offensive expedition with- out a commission or particular order. There are occasions, however, when the subjects may reason- g 228. What ably suppose the sovereign's will; and act in consequence of private per- his tacit command. Thus, although the operations of war are ^ n d s e ^ e by custom generally confined to the troops, if the inhabitants p res uming of a strong place, taken by the enemy, have not promised or on the sove- sworn submission to him, and should find a favourable oppor- reign's will, tunity of surprising the garrison, and recovering the place for their sovereign, they may confidently presume that the prince will approve of this spirited enterprise. And where is the man that shall dare to censure it ? It is true, indeed, that, if the townsmen miscarry in the attempt, they will experience very severe treatment from the enemy. But this does not prove the enterprise to be unjust, or contrary to the laws of war. The enemy makes use of his right, of the right of arms, which authorizes him to call in the aid of terror to a certain degree, in order that the subjects of the sovereign with whom (179) Hence it is illegal to have any State* v. Barker, Paine's C. C. Rep. commercial intercourse with an enemy, 157.} Thus, Great Britain permitted or even to pay him a just debt, during commercial intercourse with some of war. Grotlus, b. iii. c. iv. | 8; Byn- her plantations, whilst under capture kershoek, b. L c. iii.; Dr. Phillimore by the French, because she expected on Licenses, 5; The Hoop, 1 Rob. Rep. to recover them back. See observa- 198; Potts v. Bell, 8 Term Rep. 548; tions in The Hoop, 1 Rob. Rep. 209; Willson v. Patteson, 7 Taunt 439 j but these exceptions are in general 3 Meriv. R. 469 ; 2 Ves. not to act at tne i r own discretion : they are only instruments in the hands of their commanders. Let it be 516 PRIVATE PERSONS IN WAR. 401 remembered here, that, by a tacit order, I mean one which is BOOK m. necessarily included in an express order, or in the functions CHAP - XY - with which a person is intrusted by his superior. What is said of soldiers must also in a proper degree be understood of officers, and of all who have any subordinate command. Wherefore, with respect to things which are not intrusted to their charge, they may both be considered as private indi- viduals, who are not to undertake any thing without orders. The obligation of the military is even more strict, as the martial law expressly forbids acting without orders ; and this discipline is so necessary that it scarcely leaves any room for presumption. In war, an enterprise which wears a very advantageous appearance, and promises almost certain success, may nevertheless be attended with fatal consequences. It [ 402 ] would be dangerous, in such a case, to leave the decision to the judgment of men in subordinate stations, who are not acquainted with all the views of their general, and who do not possess an equal degree of knowledge and experience : it is therefore not to be presumed that he intends to let them act at their own discretion. Fighting without orders is almost always considered, in a military man, as fighting contrary to orders, or contrary to prohibition. There is, therefore, hardly any case, except that of self-defence, in which the soldiers and inferior officers may act without orders. In that one case, the orders may safely be presumed ; or rather, the right of self-defence naturally belongs to every one, and requires no permission. During the siege of Prague, in the last war, a party of French grenadiers made a sally without orders and without officers, possessed themselves of a battery, spiked a part of the cannon, and brought away the remainder into the city. The Roman severity would have punished those men with death. The famous example of the consul Manlius is well known, who, notwithstanding the victory gained by his son, caused capital punishment to be inflicted on him for having engaged the enemy without orders.* But the differ- ence of times and manners obliges a general to moderate such severity. The mareschal Bellisle publicly reprimanded those brave grenadiers, but secretly caused money to be distributed ,, among them, as a reward for their courage and alacrity. At another famous siege in the same war, that of Coni, the private men of some battalions that were stationed in the fosses, made, of their own accord, during the absence of their officers, a vigorous sortie, which was attended with success. Baron Leutrum was obliged to pardon their transgression, lest he should damp an ardour on which the safety of the place en- tirely depended. Such inordinate impetuosity should never- theless be checked as far as possible ; since it may eventually be productive of fatal consequences. Avidius Cassius inflicted * Tit Liv. lib. viii. cap. vii. 2T 517 402 OF THE EIGHT OF PRIVATE PERSONS IN WAR. BOOK in. capital punishment on some officers of his army, -who had, CHAP, xv. w j t h out orders, marched forth at the head of a handful of men, to surprise a body of three thousand enemies, and had succeeded in cutting them to pieces. This rigour he justified, by saying that there might have been an ambuscade, dicens, evenire potuisse ut essent insidice, of the hostile armies. If the agreement be for a more considerable length of time, and especially if general, it is more particularly distinguished by the appellation of a truce. Many people use both expressions indiscriminately. g 234. Does The truce or suspension of arms does not terminate the not tenni- war . ft only suspends its operations. nate th ^ truce is either partial or general. By the former, hos- . 23 '. A tilities are suspended only in certain places, as between a truce is town and the army besieging it. By the latter, they are to either par- cease generally, and in all places, between the belligerent tial or gene- powers. Partial truces may also admit of a distinction with respect to acts of hostility, or to persons ; that is to say, the parties may agree to abstain from certain acts of hostility during a limited time, or two armies may mutually conclude a truce or suspension of arms without regard to any particu- lar place. g 236. Ge- A general truce, made for many years, differs from a peace nerai truce j n little else than in leaving the question which was the ori- for many g} na } ground of the war still undecided. When two nations are weary of hostilities, and yet cannot agree on the point which constitutes the subject of their dispute, they generally have recourse to this kind of agreement. Thus, instead of peace, long truces only have usually been made between the [ 405 ] Christains and the Turks, sometimes from a false spirit of religion ; at other times, because neither party were willing to acknowledge the other as lawful owners of their respective possessions. g 237. By It is necessary to the validity of an agreement, that it be whom these made by one who possesses competent powers. Every thing ma^he^on ^ one * n war IS done by the authority of the sovereign, who eluded! C0n ~ a ^ one nas the right both of undertaking the war, and direct- ing its operations. ( 4) But, from the impossibility of exe- cuting every thing by himself, he must necessarily communi- cate part of his power to his ministers and officers. The question, therefore, is, to determine what are the things of which the sovereign reserves the management in his own hands, and what those are which he is naturally presumed to intrust to the ministers of his will, to the generals and other officers employed in military operations. We have above (Book II. 207) laid down and explained the principle which is to serve as a general rule on this subject. If the sovereign has not given any special mandate, the person commanding in his name is held to be invested with all the powers neces- 520 OF VARIOUS CONVENTIONS, ETC. 405 sary for the reasonable and salutary exercise of his functions, BOOK m. for every thing which naturally follows from his commission. . CHAP - XYr - Every thing beyond that is reserved to the sovereign, who is not supposed to have delegated a greater portion of his power than is necessary for the good of his affairs. According to this rule, a general truce can only be concluded by the sove- reign himself, or by some person on whom he has expressly conferred a power for that purpose. For, it is by no means necessary to the success of the war, that a general should be invested with such an extensive authority : it would exceed the limits of his functions, which consist in directing the mili- tary operations in the place where he has the command, and not in regulating the general interests of the state. The conclusion of a general truce is a matter of so high import- ance, that the sovereign is always presumed to have reserved it in his own hands. So extensive a power suits only the viceroy or governor of a distant country, for the territories under him ; and even in this case, if the truce be for a num- ber of years, it is natural to suppose the sovereign's ratifica- tion necessary. The Roman consuls, and other commanders, had a power to grant general truces for the term of their commission ; but, if that term was considerable, or the truce made for a longer time, it required the ratification of the senate and people. Even a partial truce, when for a long time, seems also to exceed the ordinary powers of a general ; and he can only conclude it under a reservation of its being ratified by the sovereign authority. But, as to partial truces for a short period, it is often ne- cessary, and almost always proper, that the general should have a power to conclude them : it is necessary, when he can- not wait for the sovereign's consent ; it is proper on those occasions when the truce can only tend to spare the effusion of blood, and to promote the mutual advantage of the con- tracting parties. With such a power, therefore, the general or commander in chief is naturally supposed to be invested. [ 406 ] Thus, the governor of a town, and the general besieging it, may agree on a cessation of arms, for the purpose of burying the dead, or of coming to a parley: they may even settle a truce for some months, on condition that the town, if not relieved within that time, shall surrender, &c. Conventions of this kind only tend to mitigate the evils of war, and are not likely to prove detrimental to any one. All these truces and suspensions of arms are concluded by g 238. The the authority of the sovereign, who consents to some of them sovereign's in his own person, and to others through the ministry of Ws^/in generals and officers. His faith is pledged by such agree- them> ments, and he is bound to enforce their observance. The truce binds the contracting parties from the moment f 239. When of its being concluded, but cannot have the force of a law, with regard to the subjects on both sides, till it has been so- 66 2i2 521 406 OF VARIOUS CONVENTIONS, ETC. BOOK m. lemnly proclaimed : and, as an unknown law imposes no obh- CHAP. XVI - g a tion, the truce does not become binding on the subjects begins to be Qn ^{\ tnat > during the truce, each party may, within his ing its con- own territories, and in the places where he is master, do tinuance. whatever he would have a right to do in time of profound 1st Rule : p eace . Thus, a truce does not deprive a sovereign of the ma, dcTat 7 li Der ty of levying soldiers, assembling an army in his own home what dominions, marching troops within the country, and even they hare a calling in auxiliaries, or repairing the fortifications of a town 524 OF VARIOUS CONVENTIONS, ETC. 409 which is not actually besieged. As he has a right to do all BOOK m. these things in time of peace, the truce does not tie up his cnAP - XYI i hands. Can it be supposed that, by such a compact, he meant fight to do to debar himself from executing things which the continuation in time of of hostilities could not prevent him from doing ? But to take advantage of the cessation of arms in order to 246. 2d execute without danger certain things which are prejudicial Rule = Not to the enemy, and which could not have been safely under- to take ad ~ taken during the continuance of hostilities, is circum venting ^truce^n and deceiving the enemy with whom the compact has been doing what made : it is a breach of the truce. By this second general hostilities rule we may solve several particular cases. The truce concluded between the governor of a town and f^ n ^ the general besieging it, deprives both of the liberty of con-j nstance tinuing their works. With regard to the latter, this is mani- continuing fest, his works being acts of hostility. But neither can the the works governor, on his part, avail himself of the armistice, for the of a sie . s f f purpose of repairing the breaches or erecting new fortifica- J^che* tions. The artillery of the besiegers does not allow him to carry on such works with impunity during the continuance of hostilities : it would therefore be detrimental to them that he should employ the truce in this manner : and they are under no obligation of submitting to be so far imposed upon : they will with good reason consider such an attempt as an infrac- tion of the truce. But the suspension of arms does not hinder the governor from continuing within his town such works as were not liable to be impeded by the attacks or fire of the enemy. At the last siege of Tournay, after the surrender of the town, an armistice was agreed on ; during the continuance of which, the governor permitted the French to make all the necessary preparations for attacking the citadel, to carry on their works, and erect their batteries, because the governor, on his part, was in the mean time busily employed within, in clearing away the rubbish with which the blowing up of a ma- gazine had filled the citadel, and was erecting batteries on the ramparts. But all this he might have performed with little or no danger, even if the operations of the siege had com- menced ; whereas the French could not have carried on their works with such expedition, or made their approaches and erected their batteries without losing a great number of men. There was therefore no equality in the case ; and, on that footing, the truce was entirely in favour of the besiegers : and, in consequence of it, the capture of the citadel took place sooner, probably, by a fortnight, than it would otherwise have happened. If the truce be concluded either for the purpose of settling g 248. or the terms of the capitulation or of waiting for the orders of introducing the respective sovereigns, the besieged governor cannot make succours ' use of it as a convenient opportunity to introduce succours or ammunition into the town : for, this would be taking an undue 525 410 OF VARIOUS CONVENTIONS, ETC. BOOK in. advantage of the armistice for the purpose of deceiving the CHAP, xvi. enem y a conduct which is inconsistent with candour and honesty. The spirit of such a compact evidently imports that all things shall remain as they were at the moment of its conclusion. 249. Dis- But this is not to be extended to a suspension of arms tinction of a a g ree ^ on f or S0 me particular 'circumstance, as, for instance, case! burying the dead. In this case, the truce is to be interpreted, with a view to its immediate object. Accordingly, the firing ceases, either in all quarters, or only in a single point of attack, pursuant to agreement, that each party may freely carry off their dead : and during this intermission of the can- nonade, it is not allowable to carry on any works which the firing would have impeded. This would be taking an undue advantage of the armistice, and consequently a violation of it. But it is perfectly justifiable in the governor, during such a cessation of hostilities, silently to introduce a reinforce- ment in some quarter remote from the point of attack. If the besieger, lulled by such an armistice, abates in his vigilance, he must abide the consequences. The armistice of itself does not facilitate the entrance of that reinforcement. g 250. Re- Likewise, if an army in a bad position proposes and con- treat of an c i u( j es an armistice for the purpose of burying the dead after iTsus en" 03 a Da *^ e j it cannot pretend, during the suspension of arms, to sion of hos- extricate itself from its disadvantageous situation, and to tilities. march off unmolested, in sight of the enemy. This would be availing itself of the compact in order to effect a purpose which it could not otherwise have accomplished. This would be laying a snare : and conventions must not be converted into snares. The enemy, therefore, may justly obstruct the motions of that army the moment it attempts to quit its sta- tion : but, if it silently files off in the rear, and thus reaches a safer position, it will not be guilty of a breach of faith ; since nothing more is implied by a suspension of arms for the burial of the dead, than that neither party shall attack the other whilst this office of humanity is performing. The enemy, therefore, can only blame his own remissness : he ought to have stipulated, that, during the cessation of hosti- lities, neither party should quit their post: or it was his bu- siness vigilantly to watch the motions of the hostile army : and on perceiving their design, he was at liberty to oppose it. It is a very justifiable stratagem to propose a cessation of arms for a particular object, with a view of lulling the enemy's vigilance, and covering a design of retreating. But, if the truce be not made for any particular object alone, we cannot honourably avail ourselves of it in order to gain an advantage, as, for instance, to secure an important post, or to advance into the enemy's country. The latter step would indeed be a violation of the truce ; for, every advance into the enemy's country is an act of hostility. 526 OF VARIOUS CONVENTIONS, ETC. 411 Now, as a truce suspends hostilities without putting an end BOOK m. to the war, every thing must, during the continuance of the , CHA truce, be suffered to remain in its existing state, in all places g 251. 3d of which the possession is contested : nor is it lawful, in such Rule ^No- places, to attempt any thing to the prejudice of the enemy. thing to be This is a third general rule. T C ^L When the enemy withdraws his troops from a place, and places, but absolutely quits it, his conduct sufficiently shows that he does every thing not intend to occupy it any longer: and in this case we may^^ieftas lawfully take possession of it during the truce. But if, by J ^ any indication, it appears that a post, an open town, or a 252 - Places village, is not relinquished by the enemy, and that, though n" 1 "^^ he neglects to keep it guarded, he still maintains his rights ^f enemy/ and claims to it, the truce forbids us to seize upon it. To take away from the enemy what he is disposed to retain, is an act of hostility. It is also an undoubted act of hostility to receive towns or g 253. Sub- provinces inclined to withdraw from the sovereignty of the jects in- enemy, and give themselves up to us. We therefore cannot clined io . re ~ receive them during the continuance of the truce, which wholly thei/prince suspends all hostile proceedings. not to be re- Far more unlawful it is, during that period, to instigate the ceived dur- subjects of the enemy to revolt, or to tamper with the fidelity ing the of his governors and garrisons. These are not only hostile truce ' proceedings, but odious acts of hostility ( 180). As to de- | e 2 g 5 *; uch serters and fugitives, they may be received during the truce, solicited to since they are received even in time of peace, when there is treason. no treaty to the contrary. And, even if such a treaty did exist, its effect is annulled, or at least suspended, by the war which has since taken place. To seize persons or things belonging to the enemy, when 255. Per- he has not, by any particular fault on his side, afforded us sons or ef - grounds for such seizure, is an act of hostility, and conse- ^f n ^ t e e " quently not allowable during a truce. be geized Since the right of postliminium is founded only on the during the state of war (Chap. XIV. of this Book), it cannot take effect t 06 - during the truce, which suspends all the acts of war, and ? 256. Right leaves every thing in its existing state ( 251). Even pri- f P stlimi - soners cannot during that season withdraw from the power ^ m c truce. of the enemy, in order to recover their former condition : for the enemy has a right to detain them while the war continues ; and it is only on its conclusion that his right over their liberty expires ( 148). During the truce, especially if made for a long period, it ? 257. in- is naturally allowable for enemies to pass and repass to and tercourse from each other's country, in the same manner as it is allowed J^g a in time of peace, since all hostilities are now suspended. But truce, each of the sovereigns is at liberty, as he would be in time of peace, to adopt every precaution which may be necessary to pi event this intercourse from becoming prejudicial to him. 527 412 OF VARIOUS CONVENTIONS, ETC. BOOK ni. He has just grounds of suspicion against people with whom CHAP, xvr. ^ j g goon to recommence hostilities. He may even declare, at the time of making the truce, that he will admit none of the enemy into any place under his jurisdiction. 3 258. Per- Those who, having entered the enemy's territories during sons de- the truce, are detained there by sickness or any other unsur- tained by mountable obstacle, and thus Happen to remain in the country a ^ ter the expiration of the armistice, may in strict justice be , kept prisoners : it is an accident which they might have fore- after the ex- seen, and to which they have of their own accord exposed piration of themselves ; but humanity and generosity commonly require the truce. ^^ ^gy s h ou ld be allowed a sufficient term for their de- parture. g 259. Par- If the articles of truce contain any conditions either more ticuiar con- extensive or more narrowly restrictive than what we have rttotonMa ^ ere ^ a ^ down, *he transaction becomes a particular conven- es * tion. It is obligatory on the contracting parties, who are bound to observe what they have promised in due form : and the obligations thence resulting constitute a conventional right, the detail of which is foreign to the plan of this work. 260. At As the truce only suspends the effects of war ( 233), the the expira- moment it expires, hostilities may be renewed without any tion of the f resn declaration of war : for every one previously knows that war Is M! fr m tliat i nstant tne war w iU resume its course ; and the newed with- reasons for the necessity of a declaration are not applicable out any to this Case ( 51). fresh decia- jj u t a truce of many years very much resembles a peace, ration. an( j on j^ ^g^g f rom ft [ n leaving the subject of the war still undecided. Now, as a considerable lapse of time may have effected a material alteration in the circumstances and dis- positions of both the parties, the love of peace, so becoming in sovereigns, the care they should take to spare their sub- jects' blood, and even that of her enemies, these dispositions, I say, seem to require that princes should not take up arms again at the expiration of a truce in which all military pre- paratives had been totally laid aside and forgotten, without making some declaration which may invite the enemy to pre- vent the effusion of blood. The Romans have given us an example of this commendable moderation. They had only made a truce with the city of Veii ; and the enemy even renewed hostilities before the stipulated time was elapsed. Nevertheless, at the expiration of the term, the college of the feciales gave it as their opinion that the Romans should send to make a formal demand of satisfaction, previous to their taking up arms again.* 261. Ca- The capitulations on the surrender of towns are among .ituiations; ^ p r i nc }p a j conventions made between enemies during the whon/they co urse f war - They are usually settled between the general may be con- ' eluded. * Tit. Liv. lib. ir. cap. 30. 528 c p K OP VAKIOUS CONVENTIONS, ETC. 412 of the besieging army and the governor of the besieged town, both acting in virtue of the authority annexed to their respec- tive posts or commissions. We have elsewhere (Book II. Ch. XIV.) laid down the principles of that authority which is vested in the subordinate powers, together with general rules to aid in forming a deci- [ 413 ] sion respecting it. All this has recently been recapitulated in a few words, and particularly applied to generals and other military commanders in chief ( 237). Since the general of an army, and the governor of a town, must naturally be invested with all the powers necessary for the exercise of their respective functions, we have a right to presume that they possess those powe^sj and that of concluding a capitulation is certainly one or tlie number, especially when they cannot wait for the sovereign's order. A treaty made by them on that subject is therefore valid, and binds the sovereigns in whose name and by whose authority the respective com- manders have acted. But let it be observed, that, if those officers do not mean I 262. to exceed their powers, they should scrupulously confine Clau8es themselves within the limits of their functions, and forbear to ^^ m meddle with things which have not been committed to their charge. In the attack and the defence, in the capture or the surrender of a town, the possession alone is the point in ques- tion, and not the property and right : the fate of the garrison is also involved in the transaction. Accordingly, the com- manders may come to an agreement respecting the manner in which the capitulating town shall be possessed : the besieg- ing general may promise that the inhabitants shall be spared, and permitted to enjoy their religion, franchises, and privi- leges : and, as to the garrison, he may allow them to march out with their arms and baggage, with all the honours of war, to be escorted and conducted to a place of safety, &c. The governor of the town may deliver it up at discretion, if reduced to that extremity by the situation of affairs : he may surrender himself and his garrison prisoners of war, or engage, that, for a stipulated time, or even to the end of the war, they shall not carry arms against the same enemy, or against his allies : and the governor's promise is valid and obligatory on all under his command, who are bound to obey him while he keeps within the limits of his functions ( 23). But, should the besieging general take on him to promise that his sovereign shall never annex the conquered town to his own dominions, or shall, after a certain time, be obliged to restore it, he would exceed the bounds of his authority, in entering into a contract respecting matters which are not intrusted to his management. And the like may be said of a governor who in the capitulation should proceed to such lengths as for ever to alienate the town which he commands, and to deprive his sovereign of the right to retake it, 67 2 U 529 413 OF VAKIOUS CONVENTIONS, ETC. BOOK m. who should promise that his garrison shall never carry arms, jgAp. xvr. not even - m ano ther war. His functions do not give him so extensive a power. If, therefore, in the conferences for a capitulation, either of the hostile commanders should insist on conditions which the other does not think himself em- powered to grant, they have still one expedient left, which is, to agree to an armistice, during which every thing shall con- [ 414 ] tinue in its present state, until they have received orders from higher authority. 263. Ob- At the beginning of this chapter we have given the reasons servanco of wn y we thought it unnecessary to prove in this place that all tfons^and * nese conventions made during the course of the war, are to its utility, he inviolably adhered to. We shall therefore only observe, with respect to capitulations in particular, that, as it is unjust and scandalous to violate them, so the consequences of such an act of perfidy often prove detrimental to the party who has been guilty of it. What confidence can thenceforward be placed in him ? The towns which he attacks will endure the most dreadful extremities, rather than place any depend- ence on his word. He strengthens his enemies by compelling them to make a desperate defence ; and every siege that he is obliged to undertake will become terrible. On the con- trary, fidelity attracts confidence and affection ; it facilitates enterprises, removes obstacles, and paves the way to glorious successes. Of this, history furnishes us a fine example in the conduct of George Baste, general of the imperialists in 1602, against Battory and the Turks. The insurgents of Battory's party having gained possession of Bistrith, other- wise called Nissa, Baste recovered the town by a capitulation, which in his absence was violated by some German soldiers : but, being informed of the transaction on his return, he imme diately hanged up all the soldiers concerned, and out of his own purse paid the inhabitants all the damages they had sus- tained. This action had so powerful an influence on the minds of the rebels, that they all submitted to the emperor, without demanding any other surety than the word of General Baste.* ? 264. Pro- Individuals, whether belonging to the army or not, who mises made happen singly to fall in with the enemy, are, by the urgent to the one- necess ^y of the circumstance, left to their own discretion, and dividual. ma ji so f ar as concerns their own persons, do every thing which a commander might do with respect to himself and the troops under his command. If, therefore, in consequence of the situation in which they are involved, they make any pro- mise, such promise (provided it do not extend to matters which can never lie within the sphere of a private individual) is valid and obligatory, as being made with competent powers. For, when a subject can neither receive his sovereign's orders nor * SvOlj's MtsmoiM, by M. de 1'Eclmse, voL iv. p. 179. OF VARIOUS CONVENTIONS, ETC. 414 enjoy his protection, he assumes his natural rights, and is to BOOK m. provide for his own safety by any just and honourable means CHAP- XY1 ' in his power. (184) Hence, if that individual has promised a sum for his ransom, the sovereign, so far from having a power to discharge him from his promise, should oblige him to fulfil it. The good of the state requires that faith should be kept on such occasions, and that subjects should have this mode of saving their lives or recovering their liberty. (185) Thus, a prisoner who is released on his parole, is bound to [ 415 ] observe it with scrupulous punctuality ; nor has the sovereign a right to oppose such observance of his engagement : for, had not the prisoner thus given his parole, he would not have been released. Thus, also, the country people, the inhabitants of villages or defenceless towns, are bound to pay the contributions (184) In general, all contracts in fa- vour of alien enemies are, in Great Britain, void, both at law and in equity ; ( Williamson v. Patterson, 7 Taunton's Rep. 439, 1 J. B. Moore, 333, S. C.j 2 Ves. & B. 332; ante, 321, n. (a), ); unless the enemy come into this coun- try sub salvo conductu, or live here by the king's license; (Cowp. 163; 6 Term Rep. 23; 2 Ves. & Beam. 332.) And a bill drawn abroad by an alien enemy on a British subject here, and endorsed during war to a British subject volun- tarily resident in the hostile country, cannot bo enforced by the latter after peace has been restored, because it was illegal in its concoction ; ( Williamson v. Patterson, ubi supra; 3 Bos. & Pul. 113 ; 3 Maule & Sel. 533.) But, upon the principle above laid down by Vat- tel, it was decided that where two British subjects were declared prisoners in France, and one of them drew a bill in favour of the other on a third British subject, resident in England, and such payee endorsed the same in France to an alien enemy it was held that the transaction was legal, and that the alien's right of action was only sus- pended during the war; and that, on the return of peace, he might recover the amount from the acceptor; for, otherwise, such persons would sustain great privations during their detention : and, for the same reason, it is no ob- jection to an action on such bill, that it is brought as to part in trust for an alien enemy. Antoine v. Moorshead, 6 Taunt. 237, 447, 1 Marsh. Rep. 558, S. C. Danbitg v. Moorshead, 6 Taunt. 332. 0. (185) See the same principle and reasoning, ante, g 174, p. 371-2. This doctrine, as to ransom, and ransom-bills, is recognised as part of the law of na- tions, in 4 Bla. Com. 67; 1 Chitty's Com. L., 32, 428. But the ransoming of any ships, or merchandise on board the same, and taken by an enemy of Great Britain, is absolutely prohibited by the English statutes, (22 Geo. 3, c. 25; 43 Geo. 3, c. 150; 45 Geo. 3, c. 72 ;) except in cases of extreme neces- sity, continuing to be allowed by the Court of Admiralty; and all contracts for ransom, contrary to those statutes, are declared void, and subjected to a penalty of 500. See Marshall on In- surances, 431. These ransom acts are to be considered as remedial laws, and must be construed liberally to meet the mischief. Havelock v. Rockwood, 8 Term Rep. 277 : Anthon v. Fisher, 2 Dougl. 649, n. ; Woodward v. Larkins, 3 Esp. R. 266. And see decisions, Corme v. Blackburne, 2 Dougl. 641; Webb v. Brooke, 3 Taunt. 6 ; Teats v. Hall, and Kelly v. Grant, 1 Term Rep. 73, 76. And where the master of a British ship, captured by an American, induced the latter to release the vessel, on the for- mer drawing a bill on England for 1000, by way of ransom, and the pay- ment of which he countermanded in time, he was even allowed to recover from his owners compensation, in the nature of salvage, for his services morally speaking, constituting a per- fidious breach of faith. Ship London, 2 Dodson's Rep. 74. C. 415 OF SAFE-CONDUCTS BOOK m. which they have promised in order to save themselves from CHAP - XVI - pillage. (186) Nay, more, a subject would even have a right to renounce his country, if the enemy, being master of his person, refused to spare his life on any other condition: for, when once the society to which he belongs is unable to protect and defend him, he resumes his natural rights. And besides, should he obstinately refuse compliance, what advantage would the state derive from his death ? Undoubtedly, while any hope remains, while we have yet any means of serving our country, it is our duty to expose ourselves and to brave every danger for her sake. I here suppose that we have no alternative but that of renouncing our country, or perishing without any ad- vantage to her. If by our death we can serve her, it is noble to imitate the heroic generosity of the Decii. But an engage- ment to serve against our country, were it the only means of saving our life, is dishonourable ; and a man of spirit would submit to a thousand deaths, rather than make so disgraceful a promise. If a soldier, meeting an enemy in a by-place, makes him prisoner, but promises him his life or liberty on condition of his paying a certain ransom, this agreement is to be respected by the superiors : for, it does not appear that the soldier, left entirely to himself on that occasion, has in any particular exceeded his powers. He might, on the other hand, have thought it imprudent to attack that enemy, and, under that idea, have suffered him to escape. Under the direction of his superiors, he is bound to obey : when alone, he is left to his own discretion. Procopius relates the adventure of two sol- diers, the one a Goth and the other a Roman, who, being fallen together into a pit, mutually promised each other that their lives should be spared : and this agreement was approved by the Goths.* [ 416 ] CHAP. XVII. CHAP. XYH. OF SAFE-CONDUCTS AND PASSPORTS, WITH QUESTIONS ON THE KANSOM OF PRISONERS OF WAR. (187) 265. Na- SAFE-CONDUCTS and passports are a kind of privilege ture of safe- insuring safety to persons in passing and repassing, or to cer- and^ass * a * n things during their conveyance from one place to another. port*. (186) Same point, ante, 403, in note. (187) As to these, and Meditorra- C. nean passes and licenses in general, * Hist. Goth. lib. ii. cap. i. quoted by see 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, 492 Puffendorf, book viii. chap. vii. 14. 513. C. 532 AND PASSPORTS, ETC. 416 From the usage and genius of the (French] language, it ap- BOOK m. pears that the term "passport" is used, on ordinary occasions, CIIAP - xvn - when speaking of persons who lie under no particular excep- tion as to passing and repassing in safety, and to whom it is only granted for greater security, and in order to prevent all debate, or to exempt them from some general prohibition. A safe-conduct is given to those who otherwise could not safely pass through the places where he who grants it is master, as, for instance, to a person charged with some misdemeanour, or to an enemy. It is of the latter that we are here to treat. All safe-conducts, like every other act of supreme com- 266. From mand, emanate from the sovereign authority : but the prince wha * au - may delegate to his officers the power of granting safe-con- ^nate* 167 ducts ; and they are invested with that power either by an express commission, or by a natural consequence of the na- ture of their functions. A general of an army, from the very nature of his post, can grant safe-conducts : and, as they are derived, though mediately, from the sovereign authority, the other generals or officers of the same prince are bound to respect them. The person named in the safe-conduct cannot transfer his 267. Not privilege to another : for he does not know whether it be a transferable matter of indifference to the grantor of the safe-conduct that from one another person should use it in his stead : and, so far from an^tiTer. presuming that to be the case, he is even bound to presume the contrary, on account of the abuses which might thence result ; and he cannot assume to himself any further privilege than was intended for him. If the safe-conduct is granted, not for persons, but for certain effects, those effects may be removed by others besides the owner. The choice of those who remove them is indifferent, provided there do not lie against them any personal exception sufficient to render them objects of just suspicion in the eye of him who grants the safe-conduct, or to exclude them from the privilege of enter- ing his territories. He who promises security by a safe-conduct, promises to $ 268. Ex- afford it wherever he has the command, not only in his own tent of the territories, but likewise in every place where any of his prom ! sed * troops may happen to be : and he is bound, not only to for- soc bear violating that security either by himself or his people, but also to protect and defend the person to whom he has [ 417 ] promised it, to punish any of his subjects who have offered him violence, and oblige them to make good the damage.* * At the famous interview at Pe- and negotiated their defection while he ronne, Charles duke of Burgundy, ex- was at Peronne, Charles would have asperated to find that Louis XI. had been justifiable in disregarding a safe- engaged the people of Liege to take up conduct of which an improper use had arms against him, paid no respect fo been made. But the French monarch the safe-conduct which he had granted had despatched agents to Ghent for that to that prince. If Louis had plotted purpose, before there was any question 2c2 533 417 OF SAFE-CONDUCTS BOOK III. CHAP. XVII. As the right arising from a safe-conduct proceeds entirely from the will of him who grants it, that will is the standard extent of the right is to be measured ; and the u-eo the right de- w ^ * s discoverable in the object for which the safe-conduct rived from was granted. Consequently, a person who has barely ob- a safo-cou- tained permission to go away, does not thence derive a right duct. ^0 come back again ; and a safe-conduct, granted for the simple passage through a country, does not entitle the bearer to repass through it on his return. When the safe-conduct is granted for a particular business, it must continue in force until that business is concluded, and the person has had time to depart: if it is specified to be granted for a journey, it will also serve for the person's return, since both passage and return are included in a journey. As this privilege consists in the liberty of going and coming in safety, it differs from a permission to settle in any particular place, and consequently cannot give a right to stop anywhere for a length of time, unless on some special business, in consideration of which the safe-conduct was asked and granted. g 270. Whe- A safe-conduct given to a traveller, naturally includes his theritin- baggage, or his clothes, and other things necessary for his g^and 3 j urne y> w ^ n even one or two domestics, or more, according domestics, to the rank of the person. But, in all these respects, as well as in the others which we have just noticed above, the safest mode, especially when we have to do with enemies or other suspected persons, is, to specify and distinctly enumerate the particulars, in order to obviate every difficulty. Accordingly, such is the practice which at present prevails ; and, in grant- ing safe-conducts, it is the custom expressly to include the baggage and domestics. g 271. Safe- Though a permission to settle anywhere, granted to the conduct father of a family, naturally includes his wife and children, granted to it is otherwise with a safe-conduct; because it seldom hap- does notTn- P ens * na * a man se ^les in a place without having his family elude his fa- with him; whereas, on a journey, it is more usual to travel nuly. without them. g 272. Safe- A safe-conduct, granted to a person for himself and his conduct retinue, cannot give him a right of bringing with him persons SlV6 \'totiu~ J us ^y suspected by the state, or who have been banished, or one and his 7 nave fled from the country on account of any crime ; nor can retinue. it serve as a protection to such men : for, the sovereign who grants a safe-conduct in those general terms, does not sup- pose that it will be presumptuously abused for the purpose of [ 418 ] bringing persons into his territories who have been guilty of crimes, or have particularly offended him. g 273. Term A safe-conduct, given for a stated term, expires at the end of the safe- _ _ _ _ conduct of ^Q mee ti n g a t Peronne ; and Charles, pected intelligence, committed a fla- in the transports of blind resentment, grant breach of the law of nations. excited by the disagreeable and uuex- 534 AND PASSPORTS, ETC. 418 of the term specified therein ; and the bearer, if he does not BOOK m. retire before that time, may be arrested, and even punished, CHAP - xyn - according to circumstances, especially if he has given room for suspicion by an affected delay. But, if forcibly detained, as by sickness, so as to be un- 274. A per- able to depart in time, a proper respite should be allowed son forcibly him; for a promise of security has been made to him: and, ^dtife^" though it was made only for a limited time, it is not by any term> fault of his own that he has been prevented from departing within the term. The case is different from that of an enemy coming into our country during a truce : to the latter we have made no particular promise : he, at his own peril, takes advantage of a general liberty allowed by the suspension of hostilities. All we have promised to the enemy is to forbear hostilities for a certain time ; and, at the expiration of that term, it is a matter of importance to us that we be at liberty to let the war freely take its course, without being impeded by a variety of excuses and pretexts. The safe-conduct does not expire at the decease or depo- 275. The sition of him who granted it ; for it was given in virtue of safe - conduct the sovereign authority, which never dies, and whose efficacy^ 3 *^*" exists independent of the person intrusted with the exercise death of him of it. It is with this act as with other ordinances of the who gave it. public power ; their validity or duration does not depend on the life of him who enacted them, unless, by their very na- ture, or by express declaration, they are personally confined to him. The successor, nevertheless, may revoke a safe-conduct, if 2 276. How he has good reasons for the revocation. Even he who has lt a j be re " granted it may, in like case, revoke it : nor is he always v obliged to make known his reasons. Every privilege, when it becomes detrimental to the state, may be revoked, a gra- tuitous privilege, purely and simply, a purchased privilege, on giving an indemnification to the parties concerned. Sup- pose a prince or his general is preparing for a secret expe- dition, must he suffer any person, under cover of a safe- conduct, antecedently obtained, to come and pry into his preparatives, and give the enemy intelligence of them ? But a safe-conduct is not to be converted into a snare : if it be revoked, the bearer must be allowed time and liberty to depart in safety ._ If he, like any other traveller, be detained for some time, in order to prevent his carrying intelligence to the enemy, no ill-treatment is to be offered him ; nor is he to be kept longer than while the reasons for his detainder subsist. If a safe-conduct contains this clause " For such time as $ 277. Safe- we shall think fit," it gives only a precarious right, and is conduct revocable every moment : but, until it has been expressly J 1 ^J he /br revoked, it remains valid. It expires on the death of him LTLeL who gave it, who, from that moment, ceases to will the con- 535 419 OF SAFE CONDUCTS BOOK in. tinuation of the privilege. But it must always be under- CHAP. XYII. 8too j t k at> w ken a safe-conduct expires in this manner, we shall the bearer is to be allowed a proper time for his safe de- tunk ^ parture. 278. Con- After having discussed the right of making prisoners of Mn""^ the war ' *ke obligation of the qaptor to release them at the ransfm of peace, by exchange or ransom,' and that of their sovereign prisoners, to obtain their liberty, it remains to consider the nature of those conventions whose object is the deliverance of these unfortunate sufferers. If the belligerent sovereigns have agreed on a cartel for the exchange or ransom of prisoners, they are bound to observe it with equal fidelity as any other convention. But if (as was frequently the practice in former times) the state leaves to each prisoner, at least during the continuance of the war, the care of redeeming himself such private conventions present a number of questions, of which we shall only touch on the principal ones. 279. The He who has acquired a lawful right to demand a ransom from right of de- j^g prisoner, may transfer his right to a third person. This ransom may was P rac tised in the last ages. It was frequent for military be trans- men to resign their prisoners, and transfer all the rights they ferred. had over them into other hands. But as the person who takes a prisoner is bound to treat him with justice and hu- manity ( 150), he must not, if he wishes that his conduct should be free from censure, transfer his right, in an unli- mited manner, to one who might make an improper use of it : when he has agreed with his prisoner concerning the price of his ransom, he may transfer to whom he pleases the right to demand the stipulated sum. ? 280. What When once the agreement is made with a prisoner for the tJufconvem P" ce ^ ^is ransom, it becomes a perfect contract, and can- tion made n t ^ e rescinded under pretence that the prisoner is disco- for the rate vered to be richer than was imagined : for it is by no means of the ran- necessary that the rate should be proportioned to the wealth B0m< of the prisoner, since that is not the scale by which we mea- sure the right to detain a prisoner of war ( 148, 153). But it is natural to proportion the price of the ransom to the prisoner's rank in the hostile army, because the liberty of an officer of distinction is of greater consequence than that of a private soldier or an inferior officer. If the pri- soner has not only concealed, but disguised his rank, it is a fraud on his part, which gives the captor a right to annul the compact. \ 281. A pri- If a prisoner, having agreed on the price of his ransom, soner dying ^j eg before payment, it is asked whether the stipulated sum ment e ofSn- be due and whether the heirs are bound to pay it? They aom. undoubtedly are, if the prisoner died in the possession of his liberty : for, from the moment of his release, in consideration of which he had promised a sum, that sum becomes due, and does not at all belong to his heirs. But, if he had not yet 536 AND PASSPORTS, ETC. 420 obtained his liberty, the price which was to have been paid CHAP. m. for it is not a debt on him or his heirs, unless he had made CHAP- XTI V his agreement in a different manner ; and he is not reputed to have received his liberty until the moment when he is per- fectly free to depart at pleasure, when neither the person who held him prisoner, nor that person's sovereign, opposes his release and departure. If he has only been permitted to take a journey, for the purpose of prevailing on his friends or his sovereign to fur- nish him with the means of ransoming himself, and dies be- fore he is possessed of his full liberty, before he is finally discharged from his parole, nothing is due for his ransom. If, after having agreed on the price, he is detained in pri- son till the time of payment, and there dies in the interim, his heirs are not bound to pay the ransom such an agree- ment being, on the part of the person who held him prisoner, no more than a promise of giving him his liberty on the actual payment of a certain sum. A promise of buying and selling does not bind the supposed purchaser to pay the price of the article in question, if it happens to perish before the completion of the purchase. But if the contract of sale be perfect, the purchaser must pay the price of the thing sold, though it should happen to perish before delivery, provided there was no fault or delay on the part of the vendor. For this reason, if the prisoner -has absolutely concluded the agreement for his ransom, acknowledging himself, from that moment, debtor for the stipulated sum, and is, nevertheless, * still detained, no longer indeed as a prisoner, but a surety for the payment, the price of the ransom is due, notwith- standing the circumstance of his dying in the interim. If the agreement says that the ransom shall be paid on a certain day, and the prisoner happens to die before that day, the heirs are bound to pay the sum agreed on : for the ran- som was due ; and the appointed day was assigned merely as the term of payment. From a rigid application of the same principles, it follows ? 282. Pn- that a prisoner, who has been released on condition of pro- soner re- curing the release of another, should return to prison, in ^* s j d ti of case the latter happens to die before he has been able to^cni-ing procure him his liberty. But certainly such an unfortunate the release case is entitled to lenity ; and equity seems to require that of another, this prisoner should be allowed to continue in the enjoyment of that liberty which has been granted to him, provided he pays a fair equivalent for it, since he is now unable to pur- chase it precisely at the price agreed on. If a prisoner, who has been fully set at liberty, after hav- 283. Pri- ing promised but not paid his ransom, happens to be taken a soner - second time, it is evident that, without being exempted from ! ake , n befo r? ,1 /!/ * he has paid the payment of his former ransom, he will have to pay a his fom ;, r second, if he wishes to recover his liberty. ransom. 68 537 420 OF SAFE-CONDUCTS, ETC. BOOK in. On the other hand, though the prisoner has agreed for the CHAP, xvn. p r j ce O f n ig ransom , if ? before the execution of the com- 284. Pri- p ac t ? before he is set at liberty in virtue of it, he be re- cued'before ta ^ en an ^ delivered by his own party, he owes nothing. I he has re- here evidently suppose that the contract for his ransom was ceived his li- not completed, and that the prisoner had not acknowledged berty. himself debtor for the sum agreed on. The person who held [ 421 ] him prisoner had, as it were, only made him a promise of selling, and he had promised to purchase : but the purchase and sale had not actually passed into effect; the property was not actually transferred. 285. Who- The property of a prisoner's effects is not vested in the thfauHwliifih ca P tor ' ex 66 ?* so f ar as ne seizes on those effects at the time a prisoner* 5 ^ ^ s ca pture. Of this there is no doubt, in these modern has found times, when prisoners of war are not reduced to slavery, means to And, even by the law of nature, the property of a slave's conceal, be- g 00( j s (j oes no ^ without some other reason, pass to the mas- im ' ter of the slave. There is nothing in the nature of slavery which can of itself produce that effect. Though a man obtains certain rights over the liberty of another, does it thence follow that he shall have a right over his property also ? When, therefore, the enemy has not plundered his prisoner, or when the latter has found means to conceal something from the captor's search, whatever he has thus saved still continues to be his own property, and he may em- ploy it towards the payment of his ransom. At present, even the plundering of prisoners is not always practised : the greedy soldier sometimes proceeds to such lengths ; but an officer would think it an indelible stain on his character, to have deprived them of the smallest article. A party of private French troopers, who had captured a British general at the battle of Rocoux, claimed no right to anything be- longing to their prisoner, except his arms alone. g 286. Hos- The death of the prisoner extinguishes the captor's right. tages given "Wherefore, if any person is given as a hostage in order to leL^ofT P rocure a prisoner's enlargement, he ought to be released the prisoner. moment the prisoner dies ; and, on the other hand, if the hostage dies, his death does not reinstate the prisoner in the possession of his liberty. The reverse of this is true, if the one, instead of being simply a hostage for the other, had been substituted in his stead. 538 OF CIVIL WAR. 421 BOOK. m. CHAP. xvm. CHAP. XVIII. OF CIVIL LAW. IT is a question very much debated, whether a sovereign 287. Foun- is bound to observe the common laws of war towards rebel- Cation of the lious subjects who have openly taken up arms against him ? JjJJJJ 18 *'" A flatterer, or a prince of a cruel and arbitrary disposition, aga i ns t the will immediately pronounce that the laws of war were not rebels, made for rebels, for whom no punishment can be too severe. [ 422 ] Let us proceed more soberly, and reason from the incon- testable principles above laid down. In order clearly to dis- cover what conduct the sovereign ought to pursue towards revolted subjects, we must, in the first place, recollect that all the sovereign's rights are derived from those of the state or of civil society, from the trust reposed in him, from the obligation he lies under of watching over the welfare of the nation, of procuring her greatest happiness, of maintaining order, justice, and peace within her boundaries (Book I. Chap. IV). Secondly, we must distinguish the nature and degree of the different disorders which may disturb the state, and oblige the sovereign to take up arms, or substitute forci- ble measures instead of the milder influence of authority. The name of rebels is given to all subjects who unjustly g 288. Who take up arms against the ruler of the society, whether their ^e rebels, view be to deprive him of the supreme authority, or to resist his commands in some particular instance, and to impose con ditions on him. A popular commotion is a concourse of people who as- 2 289. Popu- semble in a tumultuous manner, and refuse to listen to the ] * r comm - voice of their superiors, whether the design of the assembled ^io 8 ^ multitude be levelled against the superiors themselves, or duion? " only against some private individuals. Violent commotions of this kind take place when the people think themselves aggrieved ; and there is no order of men who so frequently give rise to them as the tax-gatherers. If the rage of the malecontents be particularly levelled at the magistrates, or others vested with the public authority, and they proceed to a formal disobedience or acts of open violence, this is called a sedition. When the evil spreads, when it infects the ma- jority of the inhabitants of a city or province, and gains such strength that even the sovereign himself is no longer obeyed, it is usual more particularly to distinguish such a disorder by the name of insurrection. All these violences disturb the public order, and are state g 290. HOW crimes, even when arising from just causes of complaint. ^ s0 - 539 422 OF CIVIL WAR. BOOK m. For violent measures are forbidden in civil society : the in- CHAP. xvin. j ure( j individuals should apply to the magistrate for redress ;^ reign is to and if they do not obtain justice from that quarter, they may suppress j a y their complaints at the foot of the throne. Every citi- em> zen should even patiently endure evils, which are not insup- portable, rather than disturb t]ie public peace. A denial of justice on the part of the sovereign, or affected delays, can alone excuse the furious transports of a people whose pa- tience has been exhausted, and even justify them, if the evils be intolerable, and the oppression great and manifest. But what conduct shall the sovereign observe towards the in- surgents ? I answer, in general, such conduct as shall at the same time be the most consonant to justice, and the most salutary to the state. Although it be his duty to repress those who unnecessarily disturb the public peace, he is bound to show clemency towards unfortunate persons, to whom just causes of complaint have been given, and whose sole crime consists in the attempt to do themselves justice : they have been deficient in patience rather than fidelity. Subjects who [ 423 ] rise against their prince without cause deserve severe punish- ment : yet, even in this case, on account of the number of the delinquents, clemency becomes a duty in the sovereign. Shall he depopulate a city, or desolate a province, in order to punish her rebellion ? Any punishment, however just in itself, which embraces too great a number of persons, becomes an act of downright cruelty. Had the insurrection of the Netherlands against Spain been totally unwarrantable, univer- sal detestation would still attend the memory of the duke of Alva, who made it his boast that he had caused twenty thou- sand heads to be struck off by the hands of the common exe- cutioner. Let not his sanguinary imitators expect to justify their enormities by the plea of necessity. What prince ever suffered more outrageous indignities from his subjects than Henry the Great, of France ? Yet, his victories were ever accompanied by a uniform clemency; and that excellent prince at length obtained the success he deserved : he gained a nation of faithful subjects ; whereas the duke of Alva caused his master to lose the United Provinces. Crimes, in which a number of persons are involved, are to be punished by penalties which shall equally fall on all the parties con- cerned : the sovereign may deprive a town of her privileges, at least, till she has fully acknowledged her fault : as to cor- poral punishment, let that be reserved for the authors of the disturbances, for those incendiaries who incite the people to revolt. But tyrants alone will treat, as seditious, those brave and resolute citizens who exhort the people to preserve themselves from oppression, and to vindicate their rights and privileges : a good prince will commend such virtuous pa- triots, provided their zeal be tempered with moderation and prudence. If he has justice and his duty at heart, if he 540 OF CIVIL WAR. 423 aspires to that immortal and unsullied glory of being the OOK m. father of his people, let him mistrust the selfish suggestions CHAP - XVIir _- of that minister who represents to him as rebels all those citizens who do not stretch out their necks to the yoke of slavery, who refuse tamely to crouch under the rod of arbi- trary power. In many cases, the safest, and at the same time the most 291. He is just method of appeasing seditions, is to give the people satis- bound to faction. And if there existed no reasons to justify the insur- JJ^J g *J rection (a circumstance which, perhaps, never happens), even has made to in such case, it becomes necessary, as we have above observed, the rebels, to grant an amnesty where the offenders are numerous. When the amnesty is once published and accepted, all the past must be buried in oblivion; nor must any one be called to account for what has been done during the disturbances : and, in general, the sovereign, whose word ought ever to be sacred, is bound to the faithful observance of every promise he has made, even to rebels, I mean, to such of his subjects as have revolted without reason or necessity. If his promises are not inviolable, the rebels will have no security in treating with him : when they have once drawn the sword, they must [ 424 ] throw away the scabbard, as one of the ancients expresses it ; and the prince, destitute of the more gentle and salutary means of appeasing the revolt, will have no other remaining expedient than that of utterly exterminating the insurgents. These will become formidable through despair ; compassion will bestow succours on them ; their party will increase, and the state will be in danger. What would have become of France, if the leaguers had thought it unsafe to rely on the promises of Henry the Great? The same reasons which should render the faith of promises inviolable and sacred be- tween individual and individual, between sovereign and sove- reign, between enemy and enemy (Book II. 163, 218, &c., and Book III. 174), subsist in all their force between the sovereign and his insurgent or rebellious subjects. However, if they have extorted from him odious conditions, which are inimical to the happiness of the nation, or the welfare of the state, as he has no right to do or grant any thing contrary to that grand rule of his conduct, which is at the same time the measure of his power, he may justly revoke any perni- cious concessions which he has been obliged to make, pro- vided the revocation be sanctioned by the consent of the nation, whose opinion he must take on the subject, in the manner and forms pointed out to him by the constitution of the state. But this remedy is to be used with great reserve, and only in matters of high importance, lest the faith of pro- mises should be weakened and brought into disrepute.* * An instance of this occurs in the insurrection at Madrid, in 1766. At transactions which took place after the the requisition of the cortes, the king 2V 541 424 OF CIVIL WAR. BOOK HI. When a party is formed in a state, who no longer obey the IAP. xvm. S0 vereign, and are possessed of sufficient strength to oppose 2 292. civil hj m) or wnen) i n a republic, the nation is divided into two opposite factions, and both sides take up arms, this is called a civil war. Some writers confine this term to a just insur- rection of the subjects against their sovereign, to distinguish that lawful resistance from rebellion, which is an open and unjust resistance. But what appellation will they give to a war which arises in a republic torn by two factions, or in a monarchy, between two competitors for the crown ? Custom appropriates the term of " civil war" to every war between the members of one and the same political society. If it be between part of the citizens on the one side, and the sove- reign, with those who continue in obedience to him, on the other, provided the malecontents have any reason for taking up arms, nothing further is required to entitle such disturb- ance to the name of civil war, and not that of rebellion. This latter term is applied only to such an insurrection against lawful authority as is void of all appearance of justice. The [ 425 ] sovereign, indeed, never fails to bestow the appellation of rebels on all such of his subjects as openly resist him : but, when the latter have acquired sufficient strength to give him effectual opposition, and to oblige him to carry on the war against them according to the established rules, he must ne- cessarily submit to the use of the term " civil war." g 293. A It is foreign to our purpose in this place to weigh the civil war reasons which may authorize and justify a civil war : we have fwo^nde e ^ sewnere treated of the cases wherein subjects may resist plndent" * ne sovereign (Book I. Chap. IV). Setting, therefore, the parties. justice of the cause wholly out of the question, it only remains for us to consider the maxims which ought to be observed in a civil war, and to examine whether the sovereign in parti- cular is, on such an occasion, bound to conform to the esta- blished laws of war. A civil war breaks the bands of society and government, or, at least, suspends their force and effect : it produces in the nation two independent parties, who consider each other as enemies, and acknowledge no common judge. Those two parties, therefore, must necessarily be considered as thence- forward constituting, at least for a time, two separate bodies, two distinct societies. Though one of the parties may have been to blame in breaking the unity of the state and resisting the lawful authority, they are not the less divided in fact. Besides, who shall judge them ? who shall pronounce on which side the right or the wrong lies? On earth they have no common superior. They stand therefore in precisely the same predicament as two nations, who engage in a contest, revoked the concessions which he had populace, but he suffered the amnesty been obliged to make to the insurgent to remain in force. MB OF CIVIL WAK. 425 and, being unable to come to an agreement, have recourse to BOOK m. arms. CHAP ' XYIIT - This being the case, it is very evident that the common I 294. They laws of war, those maxims of humanity, moderation, and are to ob - honour, which we have already detailed in the course of this *^ m * e work, ought to be observed by both parties in every civil i aws O f war . war. For the same reasons which render the observance of those maxims a matter of obligation between state and state, it becomes equally and even more necessary in the unhappy circumstance of two incensed parties lacerating their common country. Should the sovereign conceive he has a right to hang up his prisoners as rebels, the opposite party will make reprisals :* if he does not religiously observe the capitula- tions, and all other conventions made with his enemies, they will no longer rely on his word : should he burn and ravage, they will follow his example ; the war will become cruel, hor- rible, and every day more destructive to the nation. The [ 426 ] duke de Montpensier's infamous and barbarous excesses against the reformed party in France are too well known: the men were delivered up to the executioner, and the women to the brutality of the soldiers. What was the consequence ? the Protestants became exasperated; they took vengeance of such inhuman practices ; and the war, before sufficiently cruel as a civil and religious war, became more bloody and destructive. Who could without horror read of the savage cruelties committed by the Baron Des Adrets ? By turns a Catholic and a Protestant, he distinguished himself by his barbarity on both sides. At length it became necessary to relinquish those pretensions to judicial authority over men who proved themselves capable of supporting their cause by force of arms, and to treat them, not as criminals but as enemies. Even the troops have often refused to serve in a war wherein the prince exposed them to cruel reprisals. Officers who had the highest sense of honour, though ready to shed their blood in the field of battle for his service, have not thought it any part of their duty to run the hazard of an ignominious death. Whenever, therefore, a numerous body of men think they have a right to resist the sovereign, and feel themselves in a condition to appeal to the sword, the war ought to be carried on by the contending parties in the * The prince of Conde, commander The duko of Alva made it a practice of Louis XIII.'s farces against the re- to condemn to death every prisoner he formed party, having hanged sixty-four took from the confederates in the Ne- officers whom he had made prisoners therlands. They, on their part, retali- during the civil war, the Protestants re- ated, and at length compelled him to solved upon retaliation ; and the duke respect the law of nations and the rules de Rohan, who commanded them, caused of war in his conduct toward them, an equal number of Catholic officers to Grotius, Ann. lib. ii. be hanged. See Memoires de Rohan. 426 OF CIVIL WAR. BOOK in. manner as by two different nations : and they ought to leave cHA.p-_xym. O p en t j ie same means for preventing its being carried to out- rageous extremities, and for the restoration of peace. When the sovereign has subdued the opposite party, and reduced them to submit and sue for peace, he may except from the amnesty the authors of the disturbances, the heads of the party: he may bring -them to a legal trial, and punish them, if they be found guilty. He may act in this manner particularly on occasion of those disturbances in which the interests of the people are not so much the object in view as the private aims of some powerful individuals, and which rather deserve the appellation of revolt than of civil ivar. Such was the case of the unfortunate duke of Montmorency : he took up arms against the king, in support of the duke of Orleans ; and, being defeated and taken prisoner at the bat- tle of Castelnaudari, he lost his life on a scaffold, by the sen- tence of the parliament of Toulouse. If he was generally pitied by all men of worth and sentiment, it was because they viewed him rather as an opponent to the exorbitant power of an imperious minister, than as a rebel against his sovereign, and that his heroic virtues seemed to warrant the purity of his intentions.* \ 295. The When subjects take up arms without ceasing to acknow- effects of ledge the sovereign, and only for the purpose of obtaining a tiTuished 13 re( ^ ress f their grievances, there are two reasons for observ- according to i n g the common laws of war towards them : First, an appre- cases. hension lest the civil war should become more cruel and de- structive by the insurgents making retaliation, which, as we [ 427 ] have already observed, they will not fail to do, in return for the severities exercised by the sovereign. 2. The danger of committing great injustice by hastily punishing those who are accounted rebels. The flames of discord and civil war are not favourable to the proceedings of pure and sacred jus- tice : more quiet times are to be waited for. It will be wise in the prince to keep his prisoners, till, having restored tran- quillity, he is able to bring them to a legal trial. As to the other effects which the law of nations attributes to public war, see Chap. XII. of this Book, and particularly the acquisition of things taken in war, subjects who take up arms against their sovereign without ceasing to acknowledge him, cannot lay claim to the benefit of those effects. The booty alone, the movable property carried off by the enemy, is considered as lost to the owners ; but this is only on ac- count of the difficulty of recognising it, and the numberless inconveniences which would arise from the attempt to recover it. All this is usually settled in the edict of pacification, or the act of amnesty. * See the historians of the reign of Louis XIIL OF CIVIL WAR. 427 But, when a nation becomes divided into two parties ab- BOOK m. feolutely independent, and no longer acknowledging a common CHAP - * TIIL superior, the state is dissolved, and the war between the two parties stands on the same ground, in every respect, as a public war between two different nations. Whether a republic be split into two factions, each maintaining that it alone con- stitutes the body of the state, or a kingdom be divided between two competitors for the crown, the nation is severed into two parties, who will mutually term each other rebels. Thus there exist in the state two separate bodies, who pre- tend to absolute independence, and between whom there is no judge ( 293). They decide their quarrel by arms, as two different nations would do. The obligation to observe the common laws of war towards each other is therefore absolute, indispensably binding on both parties, and the same which the law of nature imposes on all nations in transactions be- tween state and state. Foreign nations are not to interfere in the internal govern- $ 296. Con. ment of an independent state. (Book II. 54, &c.) It be- duct to be longs not to them to judge between the citizens whom discord J b r s j v n e ^ y has roused to arms, nor between the prince and his subjects : t^naf " both parties are equally foreigners to them, and equally in- dependent of their authority. They may, however, interpose their good offices for the restoration of peace ; and this the law of nature prescibes to them. (Book II. Ch. I.) But, if their mediation proves fruitless, such of them as are not bound by any treaty, may, with the view of regulating their own conduct, take the merits of the cause into consideration, and assist the party which they shall judge to have right on its side, in case that party requests their assistance or accepts the offer of it : they are equally at liberty, I say, to do this, as [ 428 ] to espouse the quarrel of one nation embarking in a war against another. As to the allies of the state thus distracted by civil war, they will find a rule for their conduct in the na- ture of their engagements, combined with the existing cir- cumstances. Of this we have treated elsewhere. (See Book II. Chap. XII. and particularly 196 and 19T.) 645 BOOK IV. OF THE RESTORATION OF PEACE; AND OF EMBASSIES. CHAP. I. CHAP. I. OF PEACE, AND THE OBLIGATION TO CULTIVATE IT. g 1. What -t EACE is the reverse of war : it is that desirable state peace is. in which every one quietly enjoys his rights, or, if contro- verted, amicably discusses them by force of argument. Hobbs has had the boldness to assert, that war is the natural state of man. But if, by "the natural state of man," we under- stand (as reason requires that we should) that state to which he is destined and called by his nature, peace should rather be termed his natural state. For, it is the part of a rational being to terminate his differences by rational methods ; whereas, it is the characteristic of the brute creation to de- cide theirs by force.* Man, as we have already observed (Prelim. 10), alone and destitute of succours, would neces- sarily be a very wretched creature. He stands in need of the intercourse and assistance of his species, in order to enjoy the sweets of life, to develope his faculties, and live in a man- ner suitable to his nature. Now, it is in peace alone that all these advantages are to be found : it is in peace that men respect, assist, and love each other : nor would they ever de- [ 430 ] part from that happy state, if they were not hurried on by the impetuosity of their passions, and blinded by the gross deceptions of self-love. What little we have said of the effects will be sufficient to give some idea of its various calami- ties ; and it is an unfortunate circumstance for the human race, that the injustice of unprincipled men should so often render it inevitable. $ 2. Obiiga- Nations who are really impressed with sentiments of hu- tion of cuiti- man ity, who seriously attend to their duty, and are ac- tmg it q ua i n ted with their true and substantial interests, will never * Nam cum sint duo genera decer- endum est ad posterius, si uti non licet tandi, unum per disceptationem, alte- superiore. Cicero, de Offic. lib. i. cap. rum per vim, cumquo illud proprium 11. Bit hominis, hoc belluarum, confugi- 546 OF PEACE, AND THE OBLIGATION TO CULTIVATE IT. 430 seek to promote their own advantage at the expense and de- BOOK IT. triment of other nations: however intent they may be on CHAP ' r ' their own happiness, they will ever be careful to combine it with that of others, and with justice and equity. Thus dis- posed, they will necessarily cultivate peace. If they do not live together in peace, how can they perform those mutual and sacred duties which nature enjoins them? And this state is found to be no less necessary to their happiness than to the discharge of their duties. Thus, the law of nature every way obliges them to seek and cultivate peace. That divine law has no other end in view than the welfare of man- kind : to that object all its rules and all its precepts tend : they are all deducible from this principle, that men should seek their own felicity ; and morality is no more than the art of acquiring happiness. As this is true of individuals, it is equally so of nations, as must appear evident to any one who will but take the trouble of reflecting on what we have said of their common and reciprocal duties, in the first chapter of the second book. This obligation of cultivating peace binds the sovereign by 3 - The s - a double tie. He owes this attention to his people, on whom verei s n ' s war would pour a torrent of evils ; and he owes it in the a * most strict and indispensable manner, since it is solely for the advantage and welfare of the nation that he is intrusted with the government. (Book I. 39.) He owes the same attention to foreign nations, whose happiness likewise is disturbed by war. The nation's duty in this respect has been shown in the preceding chapter ; and the sovereign, being invested with the public authority, is at the same time charged with all the duties of the society, or body of the nation. (Book I. 41.) The nation or the sovereign ought not only to refrain, on ? 4. Extent their own part, from disturbing that peace which is so salu- of thls duty> tary to mankind : they are, moreover, bound to promote it as far as lies in their power, to prevent others from breaking it without necessity, and to inspire them with the love of jus- tice, equity, and public tranquillity, in a word, with the love of peace. It is one of the best offices a sovereign can render to nations, and to the whole universe. What a glorious and amiable character is that of peace-maker ! Were a powerful prince thoroughly acquainted with the advantages attending it, were he to conceive what pure and effulgent glory he may derive from that endearing character, together with the gratitude, the love, the veneration, and the confidence of na- tions, did he know what it is to reign over the hearts of men, he would wish thus to become the benefactor, the [ 431 ] friend, the father of mankind ; and in being so, he would find infinitely more delight than in the most splendid conquests. Augustus, shutting the temple of Janus, giving peace to the universe, and adjusting the disputes of kings and nations, 547 431 OF PEACE, AND THE OBLIGATION TO CULTIVATE IT. BOOK iv. Augustus, at that moment, appears the greatest of mortals, IAP ' r ' -and, as it were, a god upon earth. g 5. Of the But those disturbers of the public peace, those scourges oflie^ub f the earth > w ^' fired kj a lawless thirst of power, or ina- ne peace 1 P e ^ e d by the pride and ferocity of their disposition, snatch up arms without justice or reason, and sport with the quiet of mankind and the blood of their subjects, those monstrous heroes, though almost deified by the foolish admiration of the vulgar, are in effect the most cruel enemies of the human race, and ought to be treated as such. Experience shows what a train of calamities war entails even upon nations that are not immediately engaged in it. War disturbs commerce, destroys the subsistence of mankind, raises the price of all the most necessary articles, spreads just alarms, and obliges all nations to be upon their guard, and to keep up an armed force. He, therefore, who without just cause breaks the ge- neral peace, unavoidably does an injury even to those nations which are not the objects of his arms ; and by his pernicious example he essentially attacks the happiness and safety of every nation upon earth. He gives them a right to join in a general confederacy for the purpose of repressing and chas- tising him, and depriving him of a power which he so enor- mously abuses. What evils does he not bring on his own nation, lavishing her blood to gratify his inordinate passions, and exposing her to the resentment of a host of enemies ! A famous minister of the last century has justly merited the indignation of his country, by involving her in unjust or un- necessary wars. If by his abilities and indefatigable appli- cation, he procured her distinguished successes in the field of battle, he drew on her, at least for a time, the execration of all Europe. g 6. How The love of peace should equally prevent us from embark- far war may j n g j n & war y^houfc necessity, and from persevering in it after the necessity has ceased to exist. When a sovereign has been compelled to take up arms for just and important rea- sons, he may carry on the operations of war till he has at- tained its lawful end, which is, to procure justice and safety. (Book III. 28.) If the cause be dubious, the just end of war can only be to bring the enemy to an equitable compromise (Book III. 38) ; and consequently the war must not be continued beyond that point. The moment our enemy proposes or consents to such compromise, it is our duty to desist from hostilities. But if we have to do with a perfidious enemy, it would be [ 432 ] imprudent to trust either his words or his oaths. In such case, justice allows and prudence requires that we should avail ourselves of a successful war, and follow up our advan- tages, till we have humbled a dangerous and excessive power, or compelled the enemy to give us sufficient security for the time to come. 548 OF TREATIES OF PEACE. 432 Finally, if the enemy obstinately rejects equitable condi- BOOK iv. tions, he himself forces us to continue our progress till we. , CHAP - T - have obtained a complete and decisive victory, by which he is absolutely reduced and subjected. The use to be made of victory has been shown above. (Book III. Chap. VIII. IX. XIII.) When one of the parties is reduced to sue for peace, or 7. Peace both are weary of the war, then thoughts of an accommoda- the end of tion are entertained, and the conditions are agreed on. Thus wa peace steps in and puts a period to the war. The general and necessary effects of peace are the reconci- 1 8. Gene- liation of enemies and the cessation of hostilities on both r ^ effects sides. It restores the two nations to their natural state. peace- CHAP. II. CHAP, n. TREATIES OF PEACE. (188) WHEN the belligerent powers have agreed to lay down g 9. Defim- their arms, the agreement or contract in which they stipulate tion of a the conditions of peace, and regulate the manner in which it tre8lty of is to be restored and supported, is called the treaty of peace. pec The same power who has the right of making war, of de- g 10. By termining on it, of declaring it, and of directing its opera- whom it tions, has naturally that likewise of making and concluding may be con the treaty of peace. (189) These two powers are connected c u e ' together, and the latter naturally follows from the former. If the ruler of the state is empowered to judge of the causes and reasons for which war 1 is to be undertaken, of the time and circumstances proper for commencing it, of the manner in which it is to be supported and carried on, it is therefore his province also to set bounds to its progress, to point out the time when it shall be discontinued, and to conclude a peace. But this power does not necessarily include that of granting or accepting whatever conditions he pleases, with a view to peace. Though the state has intrusted to the prudence of her ruler the general care of determining on war and peace, yet she may have limited his power in many particulars by the funda- mental laws. Thus, Francis the First, king of France, had the absolute disposal of war and peace : and yet the assembly of Cognac declared that he had no authority to alienate any (188) Upon the subject of treaties in are collected in Chitt/s Commercial general, and their construction, see ante, Law, latter part of vol. 2. C. book ii. ch. xii. p. 192274. Whilst (189) Ante, 291-2 ; and see Hoop, 1 examining the sections of Vattel rela- Rob. Rep. 196, Id.; 1 Chitty's Com. L. tive to treaties, it will be found advis- 378. C. able to read the modern treaties, which 549 432 OF TREATIES OF PEACE. BOOK iv. part of the kingdom by a treaty of peace. (See Book I. A nation that has the free disposal of her domestic affairs, and of the form of her government, may intrust a single person, or an assembly, with the power of making peace, al- though she has not given them that of making war. Of this we have an instance in Sweden, where, since the death of [ 433 ] Charles XII., the king cannot declare war without the consent of the states assembled in diet ; but he may make peace in conjunction with the senate. It is less dangerous for a nation to intrust her rulers with this latter power, than with the former. She may reasonably expect that they will not make peace till it suits with the interest of the state. But their passions, their own interest, their private views, too often in- fluence their resolutions where there is question of undertaking a war. Besides, it must be a very disadvantageous peace, in- deed, that is not preferable to war, whereas, on the other hand, to exchange peace for war is always very hazardous. When a prince, who is possessed only of limited authority, has a power to make peace, as he cannot of himself grant whatever conditions he pleases, it is incumbent on those who wish to treat with him on sure grounds, to require that the treaty of peace be ratified by the nation, or by those who are empowered to perform the stipulations contained in it. If, for instance, any potentate, in negotiating a treaty of peace with Sweden, requires a defensive alliance or guarantee as the condition, this stipulation will not be valid, unless approved and accepted by the diet, who alone have the power of carry- ing it into effect. The kings of England are authorized to conclude treaties of peace and alliance ; but they cannot, by those treaties, alienate any of the possessions of the crown without the consent of parliament. Neither can they, without the concurrence of that body, raise any money in the kingdom ; wherefore, whenever they conclude any subsidiary treaty, it is their constant rule to lay it before the parliament, in order that they may be certain of the concurrence of that assembly to enable them to make good their engagements. When the emperor Charles V. required of Francis the First, his prisoner, such conditions as that king could not grant without the con- sent of the nation, he should have detained him till the states-general of France had ratified the treaty of Madrid, and Burgundy had acquiesced in it : thus he would not have lost the fruits of his victory by an oversight which appears very surprising in a prince of his abilities. 11. Alien- We shall not repeat here what we have said on a former ations made occasion concerning the alienation of a part of the state ( B k L 268 ' &C ')' F f the Wh le State ' ( Ibi(L . 68 ' &C ') We shall therefore content ourselves with observing, that, in case of a pressing necessity, such as is produced by the events of an unfortunate war, the alienations made by the 550 OF TREATIES OF PEACE. 433 prince, in order to save the remainder of the state, are consi- BOOK IT. dered as approved and ratified by the mere silence of the na- CHAP " " tion, when she has not, in the form of her government, retained some easy and ordinary method of giving her express con- sent, and has lodged an absolute power in the prince's hands. The states-general are abolished in France by disuse and by the tacit consent of the nation. Whenever, therefore, that kingdom is reduced to any calamitous exigency, it belongs to the king alone to determine by what sacrifices he may pur- [ 434 ] chase peace : and his enemies will treat with him on a sure footing. It would be a vain plea on the part of the people, to say that it was only through fear they acquiesced in the abo- lition of the states-general. The fact is, that they did acqui- esce, and thereby suffered the king to acquire all the powers necessary for contracting with foreign states in the name of the nation. In every state there must necessarily be some power with which other nations may treat on secure grounds. A certain historian* says, that, " by the fundamental laws, the kings of France cannot, to the prejudice of their suc- cessors, renounce any of their rights, by any treaty, whether voluntary or compulsory." The fundamental laws may indeed withhold from the king the power of alienating, without the nation's consent, what belongs to the state ; but they cannot invalidate an alienation or renunciation made with that con- sent.f And if the nation has permitted matters to proceed to such lengths that she now has no longer any means of ex- pressly declaring her consent, her silence alone, on such occa sions, is in reality a tacit consent. Otherwise there would be no possibility of treating on sure grounds with such a state ; and her pretending thus beforehand to invalidate all future treaties would be an infringement of the law of nations, which ordains that all states should retain the means of treat- ing with each other (Book I. 262), and should observe their treaties. (Book II. 163, 269, &c.) It is to be observed, however, that in our examination whether the consent of the nation be requisite for alienating any part of the state, we mean such parts as are still in the nation's possession, and not those which have fallen into the enemy's hands during the course of the war : for, as these latter are no longer possessed by the nation, it is the sovereign * The abbe de Choisi, Hist, de Charles national approbation, and the character V. p. 492. of a law of the state. The cardinals f The renunciation made by Anne who examined this affair by order of of Austria, consort of Louis the Thir- the pope, whom Charles II. had con- teenth, was good and valid, because it suited, paid no regard to Maria The- was confirmed by the general assembly resa's renunciation, as not deeming it of the cortes, and registered in all the of sufficient force to invalidate the laws offices. The case was otherwise with of the country, and to supersede tho that made by Anna Theresa, which established custom. Memoirs of M. was not sanctioned by those formalities, de St. Philippe, vol. i. p. 29. Ed. consequently, not stamped with the A. D. 1797. 551 434 OF TREATIES OF PEACE. BOOK iv. alone, if invested with the full and absolute administration of CHAP - " the government, and with the power of making war and peace, it is he alone, I say, who is to judge whether it be expedient to relinquish those parts of the state, or to continue the war for the recovery of them. And even though it should be pretended that he cannot by his own single authority make any valid alienation of them, he has, nevertheless, according to our supposition, that is, if invested with full and absolute power, he has, I say, a right to promise that the nation shall never again take up arms for the recovery of those lands, towns, or provinces, which he relinquishes : and this suffices for securing the quiet possession of them to the enemy into [ 435 ] whose hands they are fallen. g 12. How The necessity of making peace authorizes the sovereign to the sove- dispose of the property of individuals ; and the eminent do- main gives him a right to do li ( Book L 244 )' He may even, to a certain degree, dispose of their persons, by virtue what con- of the power which he has over all his subjects. But as it is cems indi- f or the public advantage that he thus disposes of them, the viduais. state is bound to indemnify the citizens who are sufferers by the transaction. (Ibid.) 13. Whe- Every impediment by which the prince is disabled from ther a king, administering the affairs of government, undoubtedly deprives bemg a pn- ^ m Q ^e power of making peace. Thus a king cannot make sonerofwar, ,,* , i? -^ I_M e can make a treaty of peace during his minority, or while in a state of peace. mental derangement : this assertion does not stand in need of any proof: but the question is, whether a king can con- elude a peace while he is a prisoner of war, and whether the treaty thus made be valid ? Some celebrated authors* here draw a distinction between a monarch whose kingdom is pa- trimonial, and another who has only the usufructus of his do- minions. We think we have overthrown that false and dan- gerous idea of a patrimonial kingdom (Book L 68, &c.), and evidently shown that the notion ought not to be extended beyond the bare power with which a sovereign is sometimes intrusted, of nominating his successor, of appointing a new prince to rule over the state, and dismembering some parts of it, if he thinks it expedient ; the whole, however, to be uni- formly done for the good of the nation, and with a view to her greater advantage. Every legitimate government, whatever it be, is established solely for the good and welfare of the state. This incontestable principle being onee laid down, the making of peace is no longer the peculiar province of the king; it belongs to the nation. Now it is certain that a captive prince cannot administer the government, or attend to the management of public affairs. How shall he who is not free command a nation ? How can he govern it in such manner as best to promote the advantage of the people, and * See Wolf. Jus Gent 2 .982. 552 OF TREATIES OF PEACE. 435 the public welfare? He does not, indeed, forfeit his rights; BCOK IT. but his captivity deprives him of the power of exercising CEAP - "-. them, as he is not in a condition to direct the use of them to its proper and legitimate end. He stands in the same predi- cament as a king in his minority, or labouring under a de- rangement of his mental faculties. In such circumstances, it is necessary that the person or persons whom the laws of the state designate for the regency should assume the reins of government. To them it belongs to treat of peace, to settle the terms on which it shall be made, and to bring it to a con- clusion, in conformity to the laws. The captive sovereign may himself negotiate the peace, and promise what personally depends on him : but the treaty does not become obligatory on the nation till ratified by her- self, or by those who are invested with the public authority during the prince's captivity, or, finally, by the sovereign [ 436 ] himself after his release. But, if it is a duty incumbent on the state to use her best efforts for procuring the release of the most inconsiderable of her citizens who has lost his liberty in the public cause, the obligation is much stronger in the case of her sovereign, whose cares, attention, and labours are devoted to the common safety and welfare. It was in fighting for his people that the prince, who has been made prisoner, fell into that situation, which, to a person of his exalted rank, must be wretched in the extreme : and shall that very people hesitate to deliver him at the expense of the greatest sacrifices ? On so melancholy an occasion, they should not demur at any thing short of the very existence of the state. But, in every exigency, the safety of the people is the supreme law ; and, in so severe an extre- mity, a generous prince will imitate the example of Regulus. That heroic citizen, being sent back to Rome on his parole, dissuaded the Romans from purchasing his release by an in- glorious treaty, though he was not ignorant of the tortures prepared for him by the cruelty of the Carthaginians.* When an unjust conqueror, or any other usurper, has in- 14 Whe- vaded the kingdom, he becomes possessed of all the powers ther peace of government when once the people have submitted to him, can be mado and, by a voluntary homage, acknowledged him as their y s ^ rp * sovereign. Other states, as having no right to intermeddle with the domestic concerns of that nation, or to interfere in her government, are bound to abide by her decision, and to look no farther than the circumstances of actual possession. They may, therefore, broach and conclude a treaty of peace with the usurper. They do not thereby infringe the right of the lawful sovereign : it is not their business to examine and judge of that right : they leave it as it is, and only look to the possession, in all the affairs they have to transact with * See Tit Lir. Epitom. lib. xviii. and .other historians. 7 2W 553 436 OP TREATIES OP PEACE. BOOK iv. that kingdom, pursuant to their own rights and those of the CHAP, it. na tion whose sovereignty is contested. But this rule does not preclude them from espousing the quarrel of the dethroned monarch, and assisting him, if he appears to have justice on his side : they then declare themselves enemies of the nation which has acknowledged his rival, as, when two different states are at war, they are at liberty to assist either party whose pre- tensions appear to be best founded. g 15. Allies The principal in the war, the sovereign in whose name it included in j^g ^ een carried on, cannot justly make a peace without in- ofVeaTe? eluding his allies, I mean those who have given him assist- ance without directly taking part in the war. This precaution is necessary, in order to secure them from the resentment of the enemy : for though the latter has no right to take offence against his adversary's allies, whose engagements were purely of a defensive nature, and who have done nothing more than [ 437 ] faithfully execute their treaties (Book III. 101) yet it too frequently happens that the conduct of men is influenced by their passions rather than by justice and reason. If the alli- ance was not of prior date to the commencement of the war, and was formed with a view to that very war, although these new allies do not engage in the contest with all their force, nor directly as principals, they nevertheless give to the prince against whom they have joined, just cause to treat them as enemies. The sovereign, therefore, whom they have assisted, must not omit including them in the peace. But the treaty concluded by the principal is no farther obligatory on his allies than as they are willing to accede to it, unless they have given him full power to treat for them. By including them in his treaty, he only acquires a right, with respect to his reconciled enemy, of insisting that he shall not attack those allies on account of the succours they have fur- nished against him, that he shall not molest them, but shall live in peace with them as if nothing had happened. \ 16. Asso- Sovereigns who have associated in a war, all those who ciates to h ave di re ctly taken part in it, are respectively to make their * rea *i es f peace, each for himself. Such was the mode adopted at Nimeguen, at Ryswick, and at Utrecht. But the alliance obliges them to treat in concert. To determine in what cases an associate may detach himself from the alliance, and make a separate peace, is a question which we have ex- amined in treating of associations in war (Book III. Chap. VI.), and of alliances in general (Book II. Chap. XII. and XV). g 17. Medi- It frequently happens that two nations, though equally ntion. tired of the war, do nevertheless continue it merely from a fear of making the first advances to an accommodation, as these may be imputed to weakness ; or they persist in it from animosity, and contrary to their real interests. On such occasions, some common friends of the parties effectually interpose, by offering themselves as mediators. There cannot $54 OF TREATIES OF PEACE. 437 be a more beneficent office, and more becoming a great prince, ROOK iv. than that of reconciling two nations at war, and thus putting CHAP - n - a stop to the effusion of human blood : it is the indispensable duty of those who have the means of performing it with suc- cess. This is the only reflection we shall here make on a subject we have already discussed (Book II. 328). A treaty of peace can be no more than a compromise, g is. On Were the rules of strict and rigid justice to be observed in it, what footing so that each party should precisely receive every thing to which peace may he has a just title, it would be impossible ever to make a peace. cl e u ^" First, with regard to the very subject which occasioned the war, one of the parties would be under a necessity of acknow- ledging himself in the wrong, and condemning his own just pretensions : which he will hardly do, unless reduced to the last extremity. But if he owns the injustice of his cause, he must at the same time condemn every measure he has pur- sued in support of it : he must restore what he has unjustly taken, must reimburse the expenses of the war, and repair the damages. And how can a just estimate of all the damages be formed ? What price can be set on all the blood that has [ 438 ] been shed, the loss of such a number of citizens, and the ruin of families ! Nor is this all. Strict justice would further demand, that the author of an unjust war should suffer a pe- nalty proportioned to the injuries for which he owes satisfac- tion, and such as might insure the future safety of him whom he attacked. How shall the nature of that penalty be deter- mined, and the degree of it be precisely regulated ? In fine, even he who had justice on his side may have transgressed the bounds of justifiable self-defence, and been guilty of im- proper excesses in the prosecution of a war whose object was originally lawful : here then are so many wrongs, of which strict justice would demand reparation. He may have made conquests and taken booty beyond the value of his claim. Who shall make an exact calculation, a just estimate of this ? Since, therefore, it would be dreadful to perpetuate the war, or to pursue it to the utter ruin of one of the parties, and since, however just the cause in which we are engaged, we must at length turn our thoughts towards the restoration of peace, and ought to direct all our measures to the attainment of that salutary object, no other expedient remains than that of coming to a compromise respecting all claims and grievances on both sides, and putting an end to all disputes by a convention as fair and equitable as circumstances will admit of. In such conventions, no decision is pronounced on the original cause of the war, or on those controversies to which the various acts of hostility might give rise ; nor is either of the parties condemned as unjust, a condemnation to which few princes would submit ; but, a simple agreement is formed, which determines what equivalent each party shall receive in extinction of all his pretensions. 555 438 OF TREATIES OF PEACE. BOOK iv. The effect of the treaty of peace is to put an end to the CHAP- "' war, and to abolish the subject of it. It leaves the contract- 1 19. Gene- j n g p ar tjes no right to commit any acts of hostility on account thelfeat of e ^ tner f tne subject itself which had given rise to the war, or, peace. of any thing that was done during its continuance : wherefore they cannot lawfully take up arms again for the same subject. Accordingly, in such treaties, ' the contracting parties reci- procally engage to preserve perpetual peace : which is not to be understood as if they promised never to make war on each other for any cause whatever. The peace in question relates to the war which it terminates : and it is in reality perpetual, inasmuch as it does not allow them to revive the same war, by taking up arms again for the same subject which had origin- ally given birth to it. A special compromise, however, only extinguishes the par- ticular means to which it relates, and does not preclude any subsequent pretensions to the object itself, on other grounds. Care is therefore usually taken to require a general compro- mise, which shall embrace not only the existing controversy, but the very thing itself which is the subject of that contro- versy : stipulation is made for a general renunciation of all pretensions whatever to the thing in question : and thus, although the party renouncing might in the sequel be able to [ 439 ] demonstrate by new reasons that the thing did really belong to him, his claim would not be admitted. f 20. Am- An amnesty is a perfect oblivion of the past ; and the end nesty. O f peace being to extinguish all subjects of discord, this should be the leading article of the treaty : and accordingly, such is at present the constant practice. But though the treaty should be wholly silent on this head, the amnesty, by the very nature of the peace, is necessarily implied in it. g 21. Things As each of the belligerent powers maintains that he has not men- justice on his side, and as their pretensions are not liable to be J ud g ed b 7 others ( Book IIL 188), whatever state things happen to be in at the time of the treaty is to be considered as their legitimate state ; and if the parties intend to make any change in it, they must expressly specify it in the treaty. Consequently all things not mentioned in the treaty are to remain on the same footing on which they stand at the period when it is concluded. This is also a consequence of the pro- mised amnesty. All damages caused during the war are likewise buried in oblivion ; and no action can be brought for those of which the treaty does not stipulate the reparation : they are considered as having never happened. \ 22. Things But the effect of the compromise or amnesty cannot be ex- not included tended to things which have no relation to the war that is n the com- terminated by the treaty. Thus, claims founded on a debt, amnesty ' or on an ^ n j ur j which had been done prior to the war, but which made no part of the reasons for undertaking it, still stand on their former footing, and are not abolished by 556 OF EXECUTION OF THE TREATY OF PEACE. 439 the treaty, unless it be expressly extended to the extinction BOOK IT. of every claim -whatever. The case is the same with debts CHAP " "' contracted during the war, but for causes which have no re- lation to it, or with injuries done during its continuance, but which have no connection with the state of warfare. Debts contracted with individuals, or injuries which they may have received from any other quarter, without relation to the war, are likewise not abolished by the compromise and amnesty, as these solely relate to their own particular object, that is to say, to the war, its causes, and its effects. Thus, if two subjects of the belligerent powers make a contract to- gether in a neutral country, or if the one there receives an injury from the other, the performance of the contract, or the reparation of the injury and damage, may be prosecuted after the conclusion of the treaty of peace. Finally, if the treaty expresses that all things shall be re- stored to the state in which they were before the war, this clause is understood to relate only to immovable possessions, and cannot be extended to movables, or booty, which imme- diately becomes the property of the captors, and is looked on as relinquished by the former owners on account of the diffi- [ 440 ] culty of recognising it, and the little hope they entertain of ever recovering it. When the last-made treaty mentions and confirms other ? 23. Former treaties of prior date, these constitute a part of the new one, J^*^ d no less than if they were literally transcribed and included in^ 1 ""* it : and any new articles relating to former conventions are to firmed in be interpreted according to the rules which we have laid down the new, are in a preceding part of this work (Book II. Chap. XVII. and a P art of i4 - particularly 286). CHAP. III. CHAP, in. OF THE EXECUTION OF THE TREATY OF PEACE. A TREATY of peace becomes obligatory on the contract- $ 24. when ing parties from the moment of its conclusion, the moment it the obiiga- has passed through all the necessary forms : and they are bound to have it carried into execution without delay.* From that instant all hostilities must cease, unless a particular day * It is an essential point to neglect to the Grand Pensionary De Witt, in none of the formalities which can in- 1662, thus observes " The articles sure the execution of the treaty, and and conditions of this alliance con- prevent new disputes. Accordingly, tain various matters of different na- care must be taken to have it duly tures, the majority of which fall under recorded in all the proper offices and the cognisance of the privy council, courts. M. Van Beuningen, writing several, under that of the admiralty, 2 w 2 557 440 OF EXECUTION OF THE BOOK iv. has been specified for the commencement of the peace. But CHAP " '"' this treaty does not bind the subjects until it is duly notified to them. The case is the same in this instance as in that of a truce (Book II. 239). If it should happen that military men, acting within the extent of their functions and pursuant to the rules of their duty, commit any acts of hostility before they have authentic information of the treaty of peace, it is a misfortune, for which they are not punishable : but the sove- reign, on whom the treaty of peace is already obligatory, is bound to order and enforce the restitution of all captures made subsequent to its conclusion : he has no right whatever to retain them. ? 25. Pubii- And in order to prevent those unhappy accidents, by which ^ man y i nnocen * persons may lose their lives, public notice of the peace is to be given without delay, at least to the troops. But at present, as the body of the people cannot of themselves undertake any act of hostility, and do not personally engage in the war, the solemn proclamation of the peace may be de- ferred, provided that care be taken to put a stop to all hosti- lities : which is easily done by means of the generals who direct the operations, or by proclaiming an armistice at the head of the armies. The peace of 1735, between the emperor and France, was not proclaimed till long after. The procla- [ 441 ] mation was postponed till the treaty was digested at leisure, the most important points having been already adjusted in the preliminaries. The publication of the peace replaces the two nations in the state they were in before the war. It again opens a free intercourse between them, and reinstates the sub- jects on both sides in the enjoyment of those mutual privileges which the state of war had suspended. On the publication, the treaty becomes a law to the subjects : and they are thence- forward bound to conform to the regulations stipulated therein. If, for instance, the treaty imports that one of the two nations shall abstain from a particular branch of commerce, every subject of that nation, from the time of the treaty's being made public, is obliged to renounce that commerce. g 26. Time When no particular time has been assigned for the execu- of the exe- ^ on O f ^ ne treaty, and the performance of the several articles, common sense dictates that every point should be carried into effect as soon as possible : and it was, no doubt, in this light that the contracting parties understood the matter. The faith of treaties equally forbids all neglect, tardiness, and studied delays, in the execution of them. others, under that of the civil tri- followed; and the states-general rc- bunals, the parliaments, Ac. es- quired that the treaty concluded the cheatage, for instance, which comes same year should be recorded in all the under the cognisance of the chambre parliaments of the kingdom. See the des comptes [exchequer]. Thus, the king's reply on this subject, in his letter treaty must be recorded in all those to the Count D'Estrades, page 399. different places." This advice was Edit A.D. 1797. 558 TEEATY OF PEACE. 441 But in this affair, as in every other, a legitimate excuse, BOOK iv. founded on a real and insurmountable obstacle, is to be ad- CHAI>< III- mitted ; for nobody is bound to perform impossibilities. The 27 - A law ~ obstacle, when it does not arise from any fault on the side of ^^JJJJ? the promising party, vacates a promise which cannot be made ted. good by an equivalent, and of which the performance cannot be deferred to another time. If the promise can be fulfilled on another occasion, a suitable prolongation of the time must be allowed. Suppose one of the contracting nations has, by the treaty of peace, promised the other a body of auxiliary troops : she will not be bound to furnish them, if she happen to stand in urgent need of them for her own defence. Suppose she has promised a certain yearly quantity of corn : it cannot be demanded at a time when she herself labours under a scarcity of provisions ; but, on the return of plenty, she is bound to make good the quantity in arrear, if required. It is further held as a maxim, that the promiser is absolved 28. The from his promise, when, after he has made his preparations P r mise is for performing it according to the tenor of his engagement, he ^ e ^^to is prevented from fulfilling it, by the party himself to whom w hom it was it was made. The promisee is deemed to dispense with the made has fulfilment of a promise of which he himself obstructs the exe- himself hin - cution. Let us therefore add, that if he who had promised JUJj^Jj^, a thing by a treaty of peace was ready to perform it at the O f it. time agreed on, or immediately and at a proper time if there was no fixed term, and the other party would not admit of it, the promiser is discharged from his promise : for the pro- misee, not having reserved to himself a right to regulate the performance of it at his own pleasure, is accounted to re- nounce it by not accepting of it in proper season and at the time for which the promise was made. Should he desire that the performance be deferred till another time, the promiser [ 442 ] is in honour bound to consent to the prolongation, unless he can show by very good reasons that the promise would then become more inconvenient to him. To levy contributions is an act of hostility which ought to \ 29. Ces- cease as soon as peace is concluded ( 24). Those which are sation of already promised, but not yet paid, are a debt actually due ; J^" 1311 ' and, as such, the payment may be insisted on. But, in order to obviate all difficulty, it is proper that the contracting parties should clearly and minutely explain their intentions respecting matters of this nature ; and they are generally careful to do so. The fruits and profits of those things which are restored | so. Pro- by a treaty of peace are due from the instant appointed for du . cts of the carrying it into execution : and if no particular period has *^Jf d ^ been assigned, they are due from the moment when the re- ceded . stitution of the things themselves was agreed to : but those which were already received or become payable before the conclusion of the peace, are not comprised in the restitution ; 559 442 OF EXECUTION OF THE BOOK iv. for the fruits and profits belong to the owner of the soil ; and, CHAP - In - in the case in question, possession is accounted a lawful title. For the same reason, in making a cession of the soil, we do not include in that cession the rents and profits antecedently due. This Augustus justly maintained against Sextus Pom- pey, who, on receiving a grant of the Peloponnesus, claimed the imposts of the preceding years.* 31. in Those things, of which the restitution is, without further what condi- explanation, simply stipulated in the treaty of peace, are to tion things k e restored in the same state in which they were when taken : stored b **' f T ^ e wor( ^ "restitution" naturally implies that every thing should be replaced in its former condition. Thus, the resti- tution of a thing is to be accompanied with that of all the rights which were annexed to it when taken. But this rule must not be extended to comprise those changes which may have been the natural consequences and effects of the war itself and of its operations. A town is to be restored in the condition it was in when taken, as far as it still remains in that condition at the conclusion of the peace. But if the town has been razed or dismantled during the war, that da- mage was done by the right of arms, and is buried in oblivion by the act of amnesty. We are under no obligation to repair the ravages that have been committed in a country which we restore at the peace ; we restore it in its existing state. But, as it would be a flagrant perfidy to ravage that country after the conclusion of the peace, the case is the same with respect to a town whose fortifications have escaped the devastation of war : to dismantle it previous to the restoration would be a viola- tion of good faith and honour. If the captor has repaired the breaches, and put the place in the same state it was in before the siege, he is bound to restore it in that state. If he [ 443 ] has added any new works, he may indeed demolish these : but if he has razed the ancient fortifications, and constructed others on a new plan, it will be necessary to come to a parti- cular agreement respecting this improvement, or accurately to define in what condition the place shall be restored. In- deed this last precaution should in every case be adopted, in order to obviate all dispute and difficulty. In drawing up an instrument solely intended for the restoration of peace, it should be the object of the parties to leave, if possible, no ambiguity whatever, nothing which may have a tendency to rekindle the flames of war. I am well aware, however, that this is not the practice of those who value themselves now-a- days on their superior abilities in negotiation : on the con- trary, they study to introduce obscure or ambiguous clauses into a treaty of peace, in order to furnish their sovereign with a pretext for broaching a new quarrel and taking up arms again on the first favourable opportunity. How contrary * Appian. de Bell. Civ. lib. v., quoted by Grotius, lib. ii. cap. 20, 22. TREATY OF PEACE. 443 such pitiful finesse is to the faith of treaties, we have already BOOK rv. observed (Book II. 231) : it is a disparagement of that can- CHAP ' Iir ', dour and magnanimity which should beam forth in all the actions of a great prince. But, as it is extremely difficult wholly to avoid ambiguity 32 - Th in a treaty, though worded with the greatest care and the i terpreta " most honourable intentions, and to obviate every doubt t *" t of which may arise in the application of its several clauses to peace is to particular cases, recourse must often be had to the rules of t>e against interpretation. We have already devoted an entire chapter the su ^j^f to the exposition of those important rules :* wherefore, instead par y ' of entering at present into tedious repetitions, we shall con- fine ourselves to a few rules more particularly adapted to the special case before us, the interpretation of treaties of peace. 1. In case of doubt, the interpretation goes against him who prescribed the terms of the treaty : for as it was in some measure dictated by him, it was his own fault if he neglected to express himself more clearly : and by extending or restricting the signification of the expressions to that meaning which is least favourable to him, we either do him no injury, or we only do him that to which he has wilfully ex- posed himself; whereas, by adopting a contrary mode of in- terpretation, we would incur the risk of converting vague or ambiguous terms into so many snares to entrap the weaker party in the contract, who has been obliged to subscribe to what the stronger had dictated. 2. The names of countries ceded by treaty are to be under- ? 33 - Names stood according to the usage prevailing at the time among of ced ? d skilful and intelligent men : for it is not to be presumed that COIJ weak or ignorant persons should be intrusted with so import- ant a concern as that of concluding a treaty of peace ; and the articles of a contract are to be understood of what the contracting parties most probably had in contemplation, since the object in contemplation is the motive and ground of every contract. 444 J 3. The treaty of peace naturally and of itself relates only g 34. Resto- to the war which it terminates. It is, therefore, in such re- rntionnott<) lation only, that its vague clauses are to be understood. ^"j^" Thus, the simple stipulation of restoring things to their those wno - former condition does not relate to changes which have not have voiun- been occasioned by the war itself: consequently, this general tarfiy given clause cannot oblige either of the parties to set at liberty a ^ hcmBelTes free people who have voluntarily given themselves up to him up ' during the war. And as a people, when abandoned by their sovereign, become free, and may provide for their own safety in whatever manner they think most advisable (Book I. (190) As to the construction of treaties in general, see Book II. Chap. XVII. 262, ante, 244. C. * Book II. Chap. XVII. ante, 244274. 71 561 444 OF OBSERVANCE AND BREACH BOOK iv. 202) if such people, during the course of the war, have CHAP, m.^ voluntarily, and without military compulsion, submitted and given themselves up to the enemy of their former sovereign, the general promise of restoring conquests shall not extend to them. It were an unavailing plea, to allege that the party who requires all things to be replaced on their former footing may have an interest in the independence of the former of those people, and that he evidently has a very great one in the restoration of the latter. If he wished to obtain things which the general clause does not of itself comprise, he should have clearly and specifically expressed his intentions relative to them. Stipulations of every kind may be inserted in a treaty of peace ; but if they bear no relation to the war which it is the view of the contracting parties to bring to a conclusion, they must be very expressly specified ; for the treaty is naturally understood to relate only to its own parti- cular object. ?*>- ** CHAP. IV. OF THE OBSERVANCE AND BREACH OF THE TREATY OF PEACE. g 35. The THE treaty of peace concluded by a lawful power is un- treaty of doubtedly a public treaty, and obligatory on the whole na- thTnluon taon'(Book II. 154). It is likewise, by its nature, a real and socces- treaty ; for if its duration had been limited to the life of the sore. sovereign, it would be only a truce, and not a treaty of peace. Besides, every treaty which, like this, is made with a view to the public good, is a real treaty (Book II. 198). It is therefore as strongly binding on the successors as on the prince himself who signed it, since it binds the state itself, and the successors can never have, in this respect, any other rights than those of the state. ? 36. It is After all we have said on the faith of treaties and the in- to be faith- demn each other without appeal, and, finally, that they [ 447 ] are bound to act in their quarrels as if each was equally in the right. On this footing, whether the new cause which gives birth to hostilities be just or not, neither he who makes it a handle for taking up arms, nor he who refuses satisfac- tion, is reputed to break the treaty of peace, provided the cause of complaint on the one hand, and the refusal of satis- faction on the other, have at least some colour of reason, so as to render the question doubtful. When nations cannot come to any agreement on questions of this kind, their only remaining resource is an appeal to the sword. In such case the war is absolutely a new one, and does not involve any in- fraction of the existing treaty. And as a nation, in making a peace, does not thereby give? 41 - A sub- up her right of contracting alliances and assisting her friends, se< i uent f 1 - it is likewise no breach of the treaty of peace to form a sub- anTnemy is sequent alliance with the enemies of the party with whom she likewise no has concluded such treaty, to join them, to espouse their breach of quarrel, and unite her arms with theirs, unless the treaty the ^^y- expressly prohibits such connections. At most, she can only be said to embark in a fresh war in defence of another people's cause. But I here suppose these new allies to have some plausible grounds for taking up arms, and that the nation in question has just and substantial reasons for supporting them in the contest. Otherwise, to unite with them just as they are en- tering on the war, or when they have already commenced hostilities, would be evidently seeking a pretext to elude the treaty of peace, and no better, in fact, than an artful and perfidious violation of it. It is of great importance to draw a proper distinction be- ? * 2 - wh y a tween a new war and the breach of an existing treaty of Distinction peace, because the rights acquired by such treaty still subsist, ^ a ^ e ^ e , notwithstanding the new war : whereas they are annulled by tween a new the rupture of the treaty on which they were founded. It is w &r and a true, indeed, that the party who had granted those rights does not fail to obstruct the exercise of them during the course of the war, as far as lies in his power, and even may, by the right of arms, wholly deprive his enemy of them, as well as he may wrest from him his other possessions. But in that case he withholds those rights as things taken from the enemy, who, on a new treaty of peace, may urge the restitu- tion of them. In negotiations of that kind, there is a ma- terial difference between demanding the restitution of what we were possessed of before the war, and requiring new con- 2X 565 448 OF OBSERVANCE AND BREACH )K IV. cessions : a little equality in our successes entitles us to in- CHAP - IV - sist on the former, whereas nothing less than a decided supe- riority can give us a claim to the latter, it often happens, when nearly equal success has attended the arms of both par- ties, that the belligerent powers agree mutually to restore their conquests, and to replace every thing in its former state. When this is the case, if the war in which they were en- gaged was a new one, the former treaties still subsist ; but if those treaties were broken by taking up arms a second time for the same subject, and an old war was revived, they remain void ; so that, if the parties wish they should again take effect, they must expressly specify and confirm them in their new treaty. The question before us is highly important in another view also, that is, in its relation to other nations who may be interested in the treaty, inasmuch as their own affairs require them to maintain and enforce the observance of it. It is of the utmost consequence to the guarantees of the treaty, if there are any, and also to the allies, who have to discover and ascertain the cases in which they are bound to furnish assistance. Finally, he who breaks a solemn treaty is much more odious than the other, who, after making an ill-grounded demand, supports it by arms. The former adds perfidy to injustice : he strikes at the foundation of public tranquillity ; and as he thereby injures all nations, he affords them just grounds for entering into a confederacy in order to curb and repress him. Wherefore, as we ought to be cautious of im- puting the more odious charge, Grotius justly observes, that, in a case of doubt, and where the recurrence to arms may be vindicated by some specious pretext resting on a new ground, "it is better that we should, in the conduct of him who takes up arms anew, presume simple injustice, unaccompanied by perfidy, than account him at once guilty both of perfidy and injustice."* g 43. Justi- Justifiable self-defence is no breach of the treaty of peace. Cable self- It is a natural right which we cannot renounce : and, in pro- defence is nriging to live in peace, we only promise not to attack without of the^trea cause an( ^ * abstain from injuries and violence. But there ty . are two modes of defending our persons or our property : sometimes the violence offered to us will admit of no other remedy than the exertion of open force ; and under such cir- cumstances, we may lawfully have recourse to it. On other occasions, we may obtain redress for the damage and injury by gentler methods ; and to these we ought of course to give the preference. Such is the rule of conduct which ought to be observed by two nations that are desirous of maintaining peace, whenever the subjects of either have happened to break out into any act of violence. Present force is checked and * Lib. iii. cap. 20, 28. OF THE TREATY OF PEACE. 448 repelled by force. But, if there is question of obtaining BOOK rv. reparation of the damage done, together with adequate satis- CHAP ' w ' faction for the offence, we must apply to -the sovereign of the delinquents : we must not pursue them into his dominions, or have recourse to arms, unless he has refused to do us justice. If we have reason to fear that the offenders will escape, as, r 449 1 for instance, if a band of unknown persons from a neighbour- ing country have made an irruption into our territory, we are authorized to pursue them with an armed force into their own country, until they be seized : and their sovereign can- not consider our conduct in any other light than that of just and lawful self-defence, provided we commit no hostilities against innocent persons. When the principal contracting party has included his al- 44- Causes lies in the treaty, their cause becomes in this respect insepa- of rable from his ; and they are entitled, equally with him, to enjoy all the conditions essential to a treaty of peace ; so that any act, which, if committed against himself, would be a breach of the treaty, is no less a breach of it, if committed against the allies whom he has caused to be included in his treaty. If the injury be done to a new ally, or to one who is not included in the treaty, it may, indeed, furnish a new ground for war, but is no infringement of the treaty of peace. The second way of breaking a treaty of peace is by doing ? 45. 2. The any thing contrary to what the particular nature of the treaty treaty is requires. Thus, every procedure that is inconsistent with w ^ at e ^ C o n _ the rules of friendship is a violation of a treaty of peace trary to its which has been concluded under the express condition of particular thenceforward living in amity and good understanding. To nature - favour a nation's enemies, to give harsh treatment to her ' subjects, to lay unnecessary restrictions on her commerce, or give another nation a preference over her without reason, to refuse assisting her with provisions, which she is willing to pay for, and we ourselves can well spare, to protect her factious or rebellious subjects, to afford them an asylum, all such proceedings are evidently inconsistent with the laws of friendship. To this list, may, according to circumstances, be also added the building of fortresses on the frontiers of a state, expressing distrust against her, levying troops, and refusing to acquaint her with the motives of such step, &c. (191) But, in affording a retreat to exiles, in har- bouring subjects who chose to quit their country, without an intention of injuring it by their departure, and solely for the advantage of their private affairs, in charitably receiving emigrants who depart from their country with a view to en- joy liberty of conscience elsewhere, there is nothing incon- sistent with the character of a friend. The private laws of friendship do not, according to the caprice of our friends, dis- (191) And see, ante, Book in. c. 3, as to what are just causes of war. C. 567 449 OF OBSERVANCE AND BREACH BOOK iv. CHAP. iv. pense with our observance of the common duties of humanity which we owe to the rest of our species. 46. 3. By Lastly, the peace is broken by the violation of any of the the violation express articles of the treaty. This third way of breaking it of^any arti- j g ^ Q mos t decisive, the least susceptible of quibble or evasion. Whoever fails in his engagements annuls the contract as far as depends on him : this cannot admit of a doubt, g 47. The But it is asked whether the violation of a single article of violation of the treaty can operate a total rupture of it ? Some writers,* tide breiSw ^ ere drawing a distinction between the articles that are con- the whole nected together (connexi) and those that stand detached and treaty. separate (diversi], maintain, that, although the treaty be vio- lated in the detached articles, the peace nevertheless still [ 450 ] subsists with respect to the others. But, to me, the opinion of Grotius appears evidently founded on the nature and spirit of treaties of peace. That great man says that all the arti- cles of one and the same treaty are conditionally included in each other, as if each of the contracting parties had formally said, "I will do such or such thing, provided that, on your part, you do so and so;"f an ^ he justly adds, that, when it is designed that the engagement shall not be thereby rendered ineffectual, this express clause is inserted, that, "though any one of the articles of the treaty may happen to be vio- lated, the others shall subsist in full force." Such an agree- ment may unquestionably be made. It may likewise be agreed that the violation of one article shall only annul those corresponding to it, and which, as it were, constitute the equivalent to it. But, if this clause be not expressly inserted in the treaty of peace, the violation of a single article over- throws the whole treaty, as we have proved above, in speak- ing of treaties in general (Book II. 202). 2 48. Whe- It is equally nugatory to attempt making a distinction in t'her a dis- this instance between the articles of greater and those of tinction may ] esser importance. According to strict justice, the violation hCr > "* cap. xix. 14. 568 OF THE TREATY OF PEACE. 450 In like manner, there may, to the violation of each individual BOOK rv. article, be annexed a penalty proportionate to its importance. We have treated of this subject in our remarks on truces violation of (Book III. 243), to which we refer the reader. an article - Studied delays are equivalent to an express denial, and % 50. Stu- differ from it only by the artifice with which he who practises died delays, them seeks to palliate his want of faith : he adds fraud to per- fidy, and actually violates the article which he should fulfil. But, if a real impediment stand in the way, time must be \ 51. Insur- allowed ; for no one is bound to perform impossibilities. And mountabie for the same reason, if any insurmountable obstacle should ^^g 1 " render the execution of an article not only impracticable for the present, but for ever impossible, no blame is imputable to him who had engaged for the performance of it; nor can his inability furnish the other party with a handle for annulling [ 451 ] the treaty : but the latter should accept of an indemnification, if the case will admit of it, and the indemnification be prac- ticable. However, if the thing which was to have been per- formed in pursuance of the article in question be of such a nature that the treaty evidently appears to have been con- cluded with a sole view to that particular thing, and not to any equivalent, the intervening impossibility undoubtedly cancels the treaty. Thus, a treaty of protection becomes void when the protector is unable to afford the promised protection, although his inability does not arise from any fault on his part. In the same manner, also, whatever promises a sove- reign may have made on condition that the other party should procure him the restoration of an important town, he is re- leased from the performance of every thing which he had pro- mised as the purchase of the recovery, if he cannot be put in possession. Such is the invariable rule of justice. But rigid justice is not always to be insisted on : peace is so essential to the welfare of mankind, and nations are so strictly bound to cultivate it, to procure it, and to re-establish it when inter- rupted, that, whenever any such obstacles impede the exe- cution of a treaty of peace, we ought ingenuously to accede to every reasonable expedient, and accept of equivalents or indemnifications, rather than cancel a treaty of peace already concluded, and again have recourse to arms. We have already, in an express chapter (Book II. Chap. 1 52. infrae- VI.), examined how and on what occasions the actions of tions of the subjects may be imputed to the sovereign and the nation. It ^ is by that circumstance we must be guided in determining how far the proceedings of the subjects may be capable of annul- ling a treaty of peace. They cannot produce such effect un- less so far as they are imputable to the sovereign. He who is injured by the subjects of another nation takes satisfaction for the offence, himself, when he meets with the delinquents in his own territories, or in a free place, as, for instance, on the open sea ; or if it be more agreeable to him, he demands 72 2x2 569 451 OF OBSERVANCE AND BREACH OF TREATY, ETC. BOOK iv. justice of their sovereign. If the offenders are refractory CHAP ' 1V- subjects, no demand can be made on their sovereign ; but whoever can seize them, even in a free place, executes sum- mary justice on them himself. Such is the mode observed towards pirates : and, in order to obviate all misunderstand- ings, it is generally agreed that the same treatment be given to all private individuals who c6mmit acts of hostility without being able to produce a commission from their sovereign. 53. Or by The actions of our allies are still less imputable to us than allies. those of our subjects. The infractions of a treaty of peace by allies, even by those who have been included in it, or who joined in it as principals, can therefore produce no rupture of it except with regard to themselves, and do not affect it in [ 452 ] what concerns their ally, who, on his part, religiously ob- serves his engagements. With respect to him, the treaty sub- sists in full force, provided he do not undertake to support the cause of those perfidious allies. If he furnishes them with such assistance as he cannot be bound to give them on an oc- casion of this nature, he espouses their quarrel, and becomes an accomplice in their breach of faith. But, if he has an in- terest in preventing their ruin, he may interpose, and, by obliging them to make every suitable reparation, save them from an oppression of which he would himself collaterally feel the effects. It even becomes an act of justice to undertake their defence against an implacable enemy, who will not be contented with an adequate satisfaction. \ 54. Right When the treaty of peace is violated by one of the con- of the tracting parties, the other has the option of either declaring art nded the treat J nul1 ant * v id> or allowing it still to subsist : for a against him contract which contains reciprocal engagements, cannot be who has vio- binding on him with respect to the party who on his side lated the pays no regard to the same contract. But, if he chooses not treaty. ^ Q come ^ a ru pture, the treaty remains valid and obligatory. It would be absurd that he who had been guilty of the vio- lation should pretend that the agreement was annulled by his own breach of faith : this would, indeed, be an easy way of shaking off engagements, and would reduce all treaties to empty formalities. If the injured party be willing to let the treaty subsist, he may either pardon the infringement, insist on an indemnification or adequate satisfaction, or discharge himself, on his part, from those engagements cor- responding with the violated article, those promises he had made in consideration of a thing which has not been performed. But, if he determines on demanding a just indemnification, and the party in fault refuses it, then the treaty is necessa- rily broken, and the injured party has a very just cause for taking up arms again. And indeed this is generally the case ; for it seldom happens that the infractor will submit to make reparation, and thereby acknowledge himself in fault. 570 OF THE RIGHT OF EMBASSY. 452 BOOK IV. CHAP. T. CHAP. V. OF THE RIGHT OF EMBASSY, OR THE RIGHT OF SENDING AND RECEIVING PUBLIC MINISTERS. IT is necessary that nations should treat and hold inter- \ 55. it is course together, in order to promote their interests, to avoid necessary injuring each other, and to adiust and terminate their dis- * hat n t*, lo r 8 > . , 11 i 11 IT be enabled putes. And as they all lie under the indispensable obligation to treat and of giving their consent and concurrence to whatever conduces communi- to the general advantage and welfare (Prelim. 13) of cate to s e - procuring the means of accommodating and terminating their tben differences (Book II. 323, &c.) and as each has a right to every thing which her preservation requires (Book I. 18) r 453 ] to every thing which can promote her perfection without in- juring others (Ib. 23), as also to the necessary means of ful- filling her duties, it results from the premises, that each na- tion is at once possessed of the right to treat and communicate with others, and bound by reciprocal obligation to consent to such communication as far as the situation of her affairs will permit her. But nations or sovereign states do not treat together im- g 56. They mediately : and their rulers or sovereigns cannot well come do this b y to a personal conference in order to treat of their affairs. ^ e *^ 7 Such interviews would often be impracticable; and, exclu- ministers, sive of delays, trouble, expense, and so many other inconve- niences, it is rarely, according to the observation of Philip de Commines, that any good effect could be expected from them. The only expedient, therefore, which remains for na- tions and sovereigns, is to communicate and treat with each other by the agency of procurators or mandatories, of dele- gates charged with their commands, and vested with their powers, that is to say, public ministers. This term, in its more extensive and general sense, denotes any person intrust- ed with the management of public affairs, but is more par- ticularly understood to designate one who acts in such capa- city at a foreign court. At present there are several orders of public ministers, and in the sequel we shall speak of them ; but whatever dif- ference custom has introduced between them, the essential character is common to them all ; I mean that of minister, and, in some sort, representative of a foreign power, a per- son charged with the commands of that power, and delegated to manage his affairs : and that quality is sufficient for our present purpose. Every sovereign state then has a right to send and to re- \ 57. Every ceive public ministers; for they are necessary instruments sovereign 571 453 OF THE RIGHT OF EMBASSY. BOOK iv. in the management of those affairs -which sovereigns have to CHAP. j^ transact with each other, and the channels of that correspond- state has a ence which they have a right to carry on. In the first chapter right to send O f this work may be seen who are those sovereigns, and what a ubiic C m? 6 those independent states, that are entitled to rank in the great nisters. * society of nations. They are the powers to whom belongs the right of embassy. 58. An un- An unequal alliance, or even a treaty of protection, not equal alii- b e mg incompatible with sovereignty (Book I. 5, 6), such treat "of* treaties do not of themselves deprive a state of the right of protection, sending and receiving public ministers. If the inferior ally does not ' or the party protected has not expressly renounced the right take away O f entertaining connections and treating with other powers, this right ne necessar iiy retains that of sending ministers to them, and of receiving their ministers in turn. The same rule applies to such vassals and tributaries as are not subjects (Book I. 7, 8). 1 59. Right Nay more, this right may even belong to princes or commu- of the nities not possessed of sovereign power : for the rights whose pn cos f a ^ assemblage constitutes the plenitude of sovereignty, are not empirein indivisible : and if, by the constitution of the state, by the this respect, concession of the sovereign, or by reservations which the subjects have made with him, a prince or community remains [ 454 ] possessed of any one of those rights which usually belong to the sovereign alone, such prince or community may exercise it, and avail themselves of it in all its effects and all its natu- ral or necessary consequences, unless they have been for- mally excepted. Though the princes and states of the empire are dependent on the emperor and the empire, yet they are sovereign in many respects ; and as the constitutions of the empire secure to them the right of treating with foreign powers and contracting alliances with them, they incontest- ably have also that of sending and receiving public ministers. The emperors, indeed, when they felt themselves able to carry their pretensions very high, have sometimes disputed that right, or at least attempted to render the exercise of it subject to the control of their supreme authority, insisting that their permission was necessary to give it a sanction. But since the peace of Westphalia, and by means of the imperial capi- tulations, the princes and states of Germany have been able to maintain themselves in the possession of that right ; and they have secured to themselves so many other rights, that the empire is now considered as a republic of sovereigns. 1 60. Cities There are even cities which are and which acknowledge that have themselves to be in a state of subjection, that have never- the right of t ne i esg a right to receive the ministers of foreign powers, and iner ' to send them deputies, since they have a right to treat with them. This latter circumstance is the main point upon which the whole question turns : for whosoever has a right to the end, has a right to the means. It would be absurd to ac- 572 OF THE EIGHT OF EMBASSY. 454 knowledge the right of negotiating and treating, and to con- BOOK IT. test the necessary means of doing it. Those cities of Swit- CHAP -, T - . zerland, such as Neufchatel and Bienne, which have the right of banner, have, by natural consequence, a right to treat with foreign powers, although the cities in question be subject to the dominion of a prince : for the right of banner, or of arms, comprehends that of granting succours of troops,* provided such grants be not inconsistent with the service of the prince. Now, if those cities are entitled to grant troops, they must necessarily be at liberty to listen to the applications made to them on the subject by a foreign power, and to treat respect- ing the conditions. Hence it follows that they may also depute an agent to him for that purpose, or receive his mi- nisters. And as they are at the same time vested with the administration of their own internal police, they have it in their power to insure respect to such foreign ministers as come to them. "What is here said of the rights of those cities is confirmed by ancient and constant practice. However ex- alted and extraordinary such rights may appear, they will not be thought strange, if it be considered that those very cities were already possessed of extensive privileges at the time when their princes were themselves dependent on the emperors, or on other liege lords who were immediate vassals [ 455 ] of the empire. When the princes shook off the yoke of vas- salage, and established themselves in a state of perfect inde- pendence, the considerable cities in their territories made their own conditions ; and instead of rendering their situation worse, it was very natural that they should take hold of ex- isting circumstances, in order to secure to themselves a greater portion of freedom and happiness. Their sovereigns cannot now advance any plea in objection to the terms on which those cities consented to follow their fortunes and to acknowledge them as their only superiors. Viceroys and chief governors of a sovereignty or remote 61. Minis- province have frequently the right of sending and receiving ters of vice- public ministers ; but, in that particular, they act in the roys- name and by the authority of the sovereign whom they re- present, and whose rights they exercise. That entirely depends on the will of the master by whom they are delegated. The viceroy of Naples, the governors of Milan, and the governors- general of the Netherlands for Spain, were invested with such power. The right of embassy, like all the other rights of sove- 62 - Minis- reignty, originally resides in the nation as its principal and ^"^ * e of primitive subject. During an interregnum, the exercise of thTgents that right reverts to the nation, or devolves on those whom during an the laws have invested with the regency of the state. They interreg- may send ministers in the same manner as the sovereign num - * See the History of the Helvetic Confederacy, by M. de Watteville. 573 455 OF THE RIGHT OF EMBASSY. BOOK rv. used to do ; and these ministers possess the same rights as CHAP ' Y ' were enjoyed by those of the sovereign. The republic of Po- land sends ambassadors while her throne is vacant : nor would she suffer that they should be treated with less respect and consideration than those who are sent while she has a king. Cromwell effectually maintained the ambassadors of England in the same rank and respeetability which they possessed under the regal authority. 63. Of him Such being the rights of nations, a sovereign who attempts who molests hi n( j er another from sending and receiving public ministers, ttw exereue ^ oes n an i n J UI 75 an( * offends against the law of nations. It of the right is attacking a nation in one of her most valuable rights, and of embassy, disputing her title to that which nature herself gives to every independent society: it is offering an insult to nations in general, and tearing asunder the ties by which they are united. jf 64. What But this is to be understood only of a time of peace : war in this? 1 * 16 " ltroc * uces Ot ^ er r igh ts - & allows us to cut off from an speet'inu'me enem 7 a ^ his resources, and to hinder him from sending mi- of war. nisters to solicit assistance. There are even occasions when we may refuse a passage to the ministers of neutral nations, who are going to our enemy. We are under no obligation to allow them an opportunity of perhaps conveying him intelli- gence of a momentous nature, and concerting with him the means of giving him assistance, &e. This admits of no doubt, for instance, in the case of a besieged town. No right can [ 456 ] authorize the minister of a neutral power, or any other person whatsoever, to enter the place without the besieger's consent. But, in order to avoid giving offence to sovereigns, good reasons rnnst be alleged for refusing to let their minis- ters pass ; and with such reasons they must rest satisfied, if they are disposed to remain neuter. Sometimes even a pas- sage is refused to suspected ministers in critical and dubious junctures, although there do not exist any open war. But this is a delicate proceeding, which, if not justified by reasons that are perfectly satisfactory, produces an acrimony that easily degenerates into an open rupture. \ 65. The As nations are obliged to correspond together, to attend to m " nsterc)f the proposals and demands made to them, to keep open a poweTis to f ree an ^ pa ^ e channel of communication for the purpose of be received, mutually understanding each other's views and bringing their disputes to an accommodation, a sovereign cannot, without very particular reasons, refuse admitting and hearing the minister of a friendly power, or of one with whom he is at peace. But in case there be reasons for not admitting him into the heart of the country, he may notify to him that he will send proper persons to meet him at an appointed place on the frontier, there to hear his proposals. It then becomes the foreign minister's duty to stop at the place assigned : it 574 OF THE RIGHT OF EMBASSY. 456 is sufficient that he obtains a hearing; that being the utmost BOOK TV. that he has a right to expect. The obligation, however, does not extend so far as to in- 66. Of re- elude that of suffering at all times the residence of perpetual sident mi - ministers, who are desirous of remaining at the sovereign's mster8 ' court, although they have no business to transact with him. It is natural, indeed, and perfectly conformable to the senti- ments which nations ought mutually to entertain for each other, that a friendly reception should be given to those resi- dent ministers, when there is no inconvenience to be appre- hended from their stay. But if there exist any substantial reason to the contrary, the advantage of the state undoubt- edly claims a preference ; and the foreign sovereign cannot take it amiss if his minister be requested to withdraw, when he has fulfilled the object of his commission, or when he has not any business to transact. The custom of keeping every where ministers constantly resident is now so firmly esta- blished, that whoever should refuse to conform to it, must allege very good reasons for his conduct, if he wishes to avoid giving offence. These reasons may arise from particular con- junctures : but there are also ordinary reasons ever subsist- ing, and such as relate to the constitution of a government and the state of a nation. Republics would' often have very good reasons of the latter kind, to excuse themselves from continually suffering the residence of foreign ministers, who corrupt the citizens, gain them over to their masters, to the great detriment of the republic, and excite and foment par- ties in the state, &c. And even though no other evil should arise from their presence than that of inspiring a nation, ori- ginally plain, frugal, and virtuous, with a taste for luxury, the thirst of gain, and the manners of courts, that alone would be more than sufficient to justify the conduct of wise and provident rulers in dismissing them. The Polish govern- [ 457 J ment is not fond of resident ministers ; and indeed their in- trigues with the members of the diet have furnished but too many reasons for keeping them at a distance. In the war of 1666, a nuncio publicly complained, in the open diet, of the French ambassador's unnecessarily prolonging his stay in Poland, and declared that he ought to be considered as a spy. In 1668, other members of that body moved for a law to regulate the length of time that an ambassador should be allowed to remain in the kingdom.* The greater the calamities of war are, the more it is in cum- 67. How bent on nations to preserve means for putting an end to it. the minis - Hence it becomes necessary, that, even in the midst of hosti- * r e s m f * e lities, they be at liberty to send ministers to each other, for to be a^. the purpose of making overtures of peace, or proposals tend-mittd. ing to moderate the transports of hostile rage. It is true, * Wickefort's Ambassador, b. L 3 1. 575 457 OF THE RIGHT OF EMBASSY. BOOK iv. indeed, that the minister of an enemy cannot come without -^ -^ permission ; accordingly, a passport, or safe-conduct, is asked for him, either through the intervention of some common friend, or hy one of those messengers who are protected by the laws of war, and of whom we shall speak in the sequel I mean a trumpeter or drummer. It is true, also, that, for substantial reasons, the safe-conduct may be refused, and ad- mission denied to the minister. But this liberty, which is authorized by the care that every nation is bound to bestow on her own safety, is no bar to our laying it down as a gene- ral maxim, that we are not to refuse admitting and hearing an enemy's minister ; that is to say, that war alone, and of itself, is not a sufficient reason for refusing to hear any pro- posal coming from an enemy ; but that, to warrant such re- fusal, there must exist some reason of a particular nature, and which rests upon very good grounds, as, for instance, when an artful and designing enemy has, by his own conduct, given us just cause to apprehend that his only intention, in sending his ministers and making proposals, is to disunite the members of a confederacy, to lull them into security by hold- ing out false appearances of peace, and then to overpower them by surprise., \ 68. Whe- Before we conclude this chapter, it will be proper to dis- ther minis- cusg a celebrated question, which has been often debated. It received ' 1S as ^ e( ^ whether foreign nations may receive the ambassa- from or sent dors and other ministers of an usurper, and send their minis- to an usurp- ters to him ? In this particular, foreign powers take for their er - rule the circumstance of actual possession, if the interest of their affairs so require : and, indeed, there cannot be a more certain rule, or one that is more agreeable to the law of na- tions and the independency of states. As foreigners have no right to interfere in the domestic concerns of a nation, they are not obliged to canvass and scrutinize her conduct in the management of them, in order to determine how far it is either just or unjust. They may, if they think proper, sup- L *5o J p 0ge the r ight to be annexed to the possession. When a na- tion has expelled her sovereign, other powers, who do not choose to declare against her, and to risk the consequences of her enmity or open hostility, consider her thenceforward as a free and sovereign state, without taking on themselves to determine whether she has acted justly in withdraAving from her allegiance to the prince by whom she was governed. Car- dinal Mazarin received Lockhart, whom Cromwell had sent as ambassador from the republic of England, and refused to see either King Charles the Second, or his ministers. If a people, after having expelled their prince, submit to another if they change the order of succession, and acknowledge a sovereign to the prejudice of the natural and appointed heir foreign powers may, in this instance also, consider what has been done as lawful : it is no quarrel or business of theirs. At 576 OF THE SEVERAL ORDERS OF PUBLIC MINISTERS. 458 the beginning of the last century, Charles, Duke of Suder- BOOK iv. mania, having obtained the crown of Sweden, to the preju- CHAl> - T - . dice of his nephew Sigismumd, king of Poland, was soon acknowledged by most sovereigns. Villeroy, minister of the French monarch, Henry the Fourth, in his despatches of the 8th of April, 1608, plainly said to the president, Jeannin, " All these reasons and considerations shall not prevent the king from treating with Charles, if he finds it to be his in- terest, and that of his kingdom." This remark was sensible and judicious. The king of France was neither the judge nor the guardian of the Swedish nation, that he should, contrary to the interests of his own kingdom, refuse to acknowledge the king whom Sweden had chosen, under pretence that a competitor had termed Charles an usurper. Had the charge been even founded in justice, it was an affair which did not fall under the cognizance of foreigners. Therefore, when foreign powers have received the minis- ters of an usurper, and sent theirs to him, the lawful prince, on recovering the throne, cannot complain of these measures as an injury, nor justly make them the ground of a war, pro- vided those powers have not proceeded to greater lengths, nor furnished any assistance against him. But to acknow- ledge the dethroned prince or his heir, after the state has solemnly acknowledged the person to whom the sceptre has been transferred, is an injury done to the latter, and a pro- fession of enmity to the nation that has chosen him. Such a step, hazarded in favour of James the Second's son, was, by William the Third and the British nation, alleged as one of the principal reasons of the war which England soon after declared against France. Notwithstanding all the caution,, and all the protestations of Louis the Fourteenth, his acknow- ledgment of young Stuart, as king of England, Scotland, and Ireland, under the title of James the Third, was considered by the English as an injury done both to the king and to the nation. CHAP. VI. E 459 J OF THE SEVERAL ORDERS OF PUBLIC MINISTERS OF THE RT8-- CHAP - TI - PRESENTATIVE CHARACTER AND OF THE HONOURS DUE TO MINISTERS. IN former days, people were scarcely acquainted with more ? 69. Origin than one order of public ministers, iii Latin termed legati, of the seve- which appellation has been rendered by that of " ambassa- dors." But, when courts were become more proud, and, at the same time, more punctilious in the article of ceremony, and especially when they had introduced the idea of extend- 73 2 Y 577 459 OF THE SEVERAL ORDERS BOOK nr. ing the minister's representation even to that of his master's CHAP, vi. dignity, jt wag thought expedient to employ commissioners of less exalted rank on certain occasions, in order to avoid trouble, expense, and disputes. Louis the Eleventh of France was, perhaps, the first who set the example. Thus, several orders of ministers being established, more or less dignity was annexed to their character, and proportionate honours were required for them. 70. Repre- Every minister, in some measure, represents his master, as sentative every agent or delegate represents his constituent. But this B ** t> representation relates to the affairs of his office : the minister represents the subject in whom reside the rights which he is to exercise, preserve, and assert the rights respecting which he is to treat in his master's stead. Although such repre- sentation is admitted in a general view, and so far as respects the essence of affairs, it is with an abstraction of the dignity of the constituent. In process of time, however, princes would have ministers to represent them, not only in their rights and in the transaction of their affairs, but also in their dignity, their greatness, and their pre-eminence. It was, no doubt, to those signal occasions of state, those ceremonies for which ambassadors are sent, as, for instance, marriages, that this custom owes its origin. But so exalted a degree of dig- nity in the minister is attended with considerable inconve- nience in conducting business, and, besides occasioning trouble and embarrassment, is often productive of difficulties and disputes. This circumstance has given birth to different orders of public ministers, and various degrees of representa- tion. Custom has established three principal degrees. What is, by way of pre-eminence, called the representative character, is the faculty possessed by the minister, of representing his master even in his very person and dignity. 11. Am- The representative character, so termed by way of pre- rmt* ' em i nence > or m contradistinction to other kinds of represen- tation, constitutes the minister of the first rank the ambas- sador. It places him above all other ministers who are not invested with the same character, and precludes their enter- ing into competition with the ambassador. At present there are ambassadors ordinary and extraordinary : but this is no more than an accidental distinction, merely relative to the subject of their mission. Yet almost everywhere some dif- ference is made in the treatment of these different ambas- [ 460 J sadors. That, however, is purely matter of custom, g 72. En- Envoys are not invested with the representative character, voys. properly so called, or in the first degree. They are ministers of the second rank, on whom their master was willing to con- (192) An ambaMador may annul a the event of his nation rejecting a treaty, see authorities collected in person sent by the friendly nation as 1 Chitty's Commercial Law, 46. la consul, he is to assign the reasons, 57S OF PUBLIC MINISTERS. 460 fer a degree of dignity and respectability, which, without BOOK iv. being on a level with the character of an ambassador, im- CHAP - Yr - mediately follows it, and yields the pre-eminence to it alone. There are also envoys ordinary and extraordinary ; and it appears to be the intention of princes that the latter should be held in greater consideration. This likewise depends on custom. The word resident formerly related only to the continu- \ 73. Resi- ance of the minister's stay ; and it is frequent, in history, dents - for ambassadors in ordinary to be designated by the simple title of residents. But, since the practice of employing dif- ferent orders of ministers has been generally established, the name of residents has been confined to ministers of a third order, to whose character general custom has annexed a lesser degree of respectability. The resident does not represent the prince's person in his dignity, but only in his affairs. His representation is in reality of the same nature as that of the envoy: wherefore we often term him, as well as the envoy, a minister of the second order, thus, distinguishing only two classes of public ministers, the former consisting of ambas- sadors who are invested with the representative character in pre-eminence, the latter comprising all other ministers who do not possess that exalted character. This is the most neces- sary distinction, and, indeed, the only essential one. Lastly, a custom of still more recent origin has introduced g 74. Minis- a new kind of ministers without any particular determination ters ' of character. These are called simply ministers, to indicate that they are invested with the general quality of a sove- reign's mandatories, without any particular assignment of rank and character. It was likewise the punctilio of cere- mony which gave rise to this innovation. Use had esta- and request the appointment of ano- tions. Id. 461-2 ; The Caroline, 6 Rob. ther consul. Id. 55. In his absence a Rep. 461 ; The Madison, 1 Edw. R. 224. consul of his nation may demand an As respects an ambassador or mi- Ambassa- audience with the minister of the nister in Great Britain, this is de- dor's privi- friendly state, (Id. 63,) although a clared and enforced by 7 Anne, c. 12 ; lege from consul has not the same privileges as see the decisions thereon, Chitty's CoL arrest. an ambassador in other respects, Id. Stat. 13 ; Novella v. Togwood, 1 Barn. 70. The children of an ambassador & Ores. 554, 2 Dowl. & Ryl. 833, S. C. ; and of his attendants, though born in and 13 Price Rep. 805. And a ser- a foreign state, are considered natural- vant of a foreign minister, though born subjects. Id. 110, 112. An am- not lodging in his house, is protected bassador from a foreign court, for- by that act In re Count Haslang, merly, could not come into England Dick. 274. But a plaintiff xmcler such without a license and safe-conduct, protection of a foreign ambassador Id. 131. He is the proper person to has been compelled to give security grant a passport. Id. 492. The am- for costs before he will be allowed to bassador of an enemy at a neutral court proceed. Adderly v. Smith, Dick, 355. may recover and insist on having re- But that act does not extend to consult, stored despatches sent by a neutral who are, therefore, liable to arrest. vessel, and captured by an enemy ; and Vivearu v. Belcher, 3 Maule & Selwyn, he is peculiarly an object of the pro- 284. C. tection and favour of the law of na- 579 460 OF THE SEVERAL ORDERS BOOK IT. Wished particular modes of treatment for the ambassador, the CHAP. TI. m enyo^ an{ j t h e res ident. Disputes between ministers of the several princes often arose on this head, and especially about rank. In order to avoid all contest on certain occasions when there might be room to apprehend it, the expedient was adopted of sending ministers not invested with any one of the three known characters. Hence, they are not subjected to any settled ceremonial, and can pretend to no particular treatment. The minister represents his master in a vague and indeterminate manner, which cannot be equal to the first degree ; consequently he makes no demur in yielding pre- eminence to the ambassador. He is entitled to the general [ 461 ] regard due to a confidential person intrusted by a sovereign with the management of his affairs ; and he possesses all the rights essential to the character of a public minister. This indeterminate quality is such that the sovereign may confer it on one of his servants whom he would not choose to invest with the character of ambassador ; and, on the other hand, it may be accepted by men of rank, who would be unwilling to undertake the office of resident, and to acquiesce in the treat- ment at present allotted to men in that station. There are also ministers plenipotentiary, and of much greater distinction than simple ministers. These also are without any particular attribution of rank and character, but, by custom, are now placed immediately after the ambassador, or on a level with the envoy extraordinary. g 75. Con- We have spoken of consuls in treating of commerce (? ook IL 3 f) Formerly, agents were a kind of public mi- Bisters : but in the present increase and profusion of titles, sioners, Ac. this is given to persons simply appointed by princes to trans- (193) act their private affairs, and who not unfrequently are sub- jects of the country where they reside. They are not public ministers, and consequently not under the protection of the law of nations. But a more particular protection is due to them than to other foreigners or citizens, and likewise some attention in consideration of the prince whom they serve. If that prince sends an agent with credentials and on public bu- siness, the agent thenceforward becomes a public minister ; his title making no difference in the case. The same remark is also applicable to deputies, commissioners, and others in- trusted with the management of public affairs. g 76. Ore- Among the several characters established by custom, it dentiais. rests with the sovereign to determine with what particular one he chooses to invest his minister ; and he makes known the minister's character in the credentials which he gives him for the sovereign to whom he sends him. Credentials are the instrument which authorizes and establishes the minister in his character with the prince to whom they are addressed. (193) Ante, 147 and 459. 530 OF PUBLIC MINISTERS. 461 If that prince receives the minister, he can receive him only BOOK iv. in the quality attributed to him in his credentials. They are, CHAP< VI ' as it were, his general letter of attorney, his mandate patent, mandatum The instructions given to the minister contain his master's g 77. i n - secret mandate, the orders to which the minister must carefully structions. conform, and which limit his powers. Here we might apply all the rules of the law of nature respecting procurations and mandates, whether open or secret. But exclusive of their being more particularly applicable to the subject of treaties, we may with the less impropriety dispense with such details in this work, as the custom has wisely been established, that no engagements into which a minister may enter, shall have any validity between sovereigns, unless ratified by his principal. We have seen above that every sovereign, every commu- 1 78. Right nity, and even every individual, who has a right to treat with of sendin s foreign powers, has also that of sending ambassadors. the preceding chapter.) The question admits of no difficulty, so far as respects simple ministers or mandatories, considered in general as persons intrusted with the affairs, and vested [ 462 ] with the powers, of those who have a right to treat. Further, the ministers of every sovereign are, without hesitation, allowed to enjoy all the rights and prerogatives belonging to ministers of the second order. Powerful monarchs, indeed, deny to some petty states the right of sending ambassadors : but let us see with what reason. According to the generally established custom, the ambassador is a public minister, re- presenting the person and dignity of a sovereign; and, as this representative character procures him particular honours, great princes are therefore unwilling to admit the ambas- sador of an inconsiderable state, from a repugnance to pay- ing him honours of so distinguished a kind. But it is mani- fest that every sovereign has an equal right of causing himself to be represented in the first as well as in the second or the third degree : and the sovereign dignity is entitled to dis- tinguished respect in the great society of nations. We have shown (Book II. Ch. III.) that the dignity of independent na- tions is essentially the same : that a sovereign prince, how- ever low he may rank in the scale of power, is as completely sovereign and independent as the greatest monarch, in the same manner as a dwarf is a man equally with a giant: although, indeed, the political giant makes a more conspicu- ous figure in the general society than the dwarf, and has, on that account, a greater portion of respect and more signal honours paid to him. It is evident, then, that every prince, every state, truly possessed of sovereignty, has a right to send ambassadors, and that to contest their right in this in- stance is doing them a very great injury ; it is, in fact, con- testing their sovereign dignity. And if they have that right, 2r2 581 462 OF THE SEVERAL ORDERS BOOK iv. their ambassadors cannot be refused those regards and ho- CHAP. vi. nourg w hi c h custom particularly assigns to the representative of a sovereign. The king of France admits no ambassadors from the princes of Germany, as refusing to their ministers the honours annexed to the first degree of representation ; yet he receives ambassadors from the princes of Italy. The reason alleged for this conduct>is that he considers the latter to be more perfectly sovereign princes than the former, be- cause, though equally vassals of the emperor' and the empire, they are not equally dependent on the imperial authority. The emperors, nevertheless, claim the same rights over the princes of Italy, as over those of Germany. But France, seeing that the former do not actually constitute a part of the Germanic body, nor assist at the diets, countenances their absolute independence, in order as much as possible to detach them from the empire. I shall not here enter into a detail of the honours due and actually paid to ambassadors : these are matters which alto- gether depend on institution and custom : I shall only observe, in general, that they are entitled to those civilities and distinctions which usage, and the prevailing manners of the time, have pointed out as proper expressions of the re- spect due to the representative of a sovereign. And it must be observed here, with regard to things, of institution and [ 463 ] custom, that, when a practice is so established, as to impart, according to the usages and manners of the age, a real value and a settled signification to things which are in their own nature indifferent, the natural and necessary laAV of nations requires that we should pay deference to such institution, and act, with respect to such things, in the same manner as if they really possessed all that value which the opinion of mankind has annexed to them. For instance, according to the general usage of all Europe, it is the peculiar prerogative of an ambassador to wear his hat in presence of the prince to whom he is sent. This right expresses that he is acknow- ledged as the representative of a sovereign : to refuse it, therefore, to the ambassador of a state which is truly inde- pendent, would be doing an injury to that state, and, in some measure, degrading it. The Switzers, who formerly were much deeper adepts in the art of war than in the etiquette of courts, and far from being punctilious on the score of mere ceremony, have, on some occasions, submitted to be treated in a manner unbecoming the dignity of their nation. In 1663, their ambassadors suffered the king of France, and the nobles of his court, to refuse them those honours which cus- tom has rendered essential to the ambassadors of sovereigns, and particularly that of being covered before the king at their audience.* Some of their number, who knew better what * In Wicquefort, may be seen a particular account of tho whole trans- 582 OF PUBLIC MINISTERS. 463 they owed to the glory of their republic, strongly insisted on BOOK IT. that essential and distinctive honour ; but the opinion of the CHAP ' YI ' majority prevailed, and at length they all yielded, on being assured that the ambassadors of their nation had not worn their hats in presence of Henry the Fourth. Allowing the fact to have been true, the argument was not unanswerable. The Switzers might have replied, that in Henry's time their nation was not yet solemnly acknowledged free and inde- pendent of the empire, as it had lately been by the treaty of Westphalia in 1648. They might have said, that, although their predecessors had not been duly attentive to support the dignity of their sovereigns, that gross error could not impose on their successors any obligation to commit a similar one. At present, as the nation is more enlightened, and more attentive to points of that nature, she will not fail to support her dignity in a more becoming manner. Whatever extra- ordinary honours may, in other respects, be paid to her ambassadors, she will not, in future, suffer herself to be so far blinded by those empty marks of distinction, as to overlook that peculiar prerogative which custom has rendered essential. When Louis the Fifteenth visited Alsace, in 1744, the Helvetic body declined sending ambassadors to compliment him accord- ing to custom, until informed whether they would be allowed to wear their hats : and on the refusal of that just demand, [ 464 ] none were sent. Switzerland may reasonably hope that his most Christian majesty will no longer insist on a claim which does not enhance the lustre of his crown, and can only serve to degrade an ancient and faithful ally. CHAP. VII. OF THE BIGHTS, PRIVILEGES, AND IMMUNITIES OF AMBAS- CHAP. TII. SADORS AND OTHER PUBLIC MINISTERS. (194) THE respect which is due to sovereigns should redound to ? 80 - Re - their representatives, and especially their ambassadors, as spec * due ! to representing their master's person in the first degree. Who-^ 1 ^ 1111 " ever offends and insults a public minister commits a crime the (195) ' . more deserving of severe punishment, as he might thereby involve his country and his sovereign in very serious diffi- culties and trouble. It is just that he should be punished for his fault, and that the state should, at the expense of the de- action. That writer is justifiable in nation by coarsely asserting that expressing a degree of indignation "they prefer money to honour." against the Swiss ambassadors ; but he Ambassador, book i. g 19. See also ought not to have insulted the whole 18. (194) See Wicquefort's Ambassadors, (195) Ante, p. 459, n. per tot. C. 583 464 OF RIGHTS, PRIVILEGES, AND BOOK iv. linquent, give full satisfaction to the sovereign who has been CHAP, vn. O ff en( j ec i j n the person of his minister. If the foreign minis- ter is himself the aggressor, and offends a citizen, the latter may oppose him without ^departing from the respect due to the character which the offender bears, and give him a lesson which shall both efface the stain of the outrage, and make the author of it blush for his misqonduct. The person offended may further prefer a complaint to his own sovereign, who will demand for him an adequate satisfaction for the minister's master. The great concerns of the state forbid a citizen, on such occasions, to entertain those thoughts of revenge which the point of honour might suggest, although they should in other respects be deemed allowable. Even according to the maxims of the world, a gentleman is not disgraced by an affront for which it is not in his own power to procure satis- faction. g 81. Their The necessity and right of embassies being established persons sa- (g e e Chap. V. of this Book), the perfect security and inviola- cred and foUtj O f ambassadors, and other ministers, is a certain con- inviolable. ,, . ,, .,, , . , . j * (196) sequence of it : for, if their persons be not protected from violence of every kind, the right of embassy becomes preca- rious, and the success very uncertain. A right to the end inseparably involves a right to the necessary means. Embas- sies, then, being of such great importance in the universal society of nations, and so necessary to their common well- being, the persons of ministers charged with those embassies are to be held sacred and inviolable among all nations. (See Book II. 218.) Whoever offers violence to an ambassador, or to any other public minister, not only injures the sovereign whom that minister represents, but also attacks the common [ 465 ] safety and well-being of nations: he becomes guilty of an atrocious crime against mankind in general. (196) Ante, p. 459, n. C. the sultan for this barbarous massacre; * An enormous infraction of the and, finding him backward to give it, law of nations caused the ruin of the he took up arms. The conquest of powerful empire of Khovarezm, or the whole empire of Khovarezm soon Kakesm, and opened a door to the followed; and Mohammed himself, re- Tartars for the subjugation of almost duced to the condition of a wretched all Asia. The famous Gengis-khan, fugitive, died of a broken heart in a wishing to establish a commercial in- desert island of the Caspian Sea. tercourse hetween his states and those Canson, the last sultan of the Mam- of Persia, and the other provinces sub- melucs, having put to death the am- ject to Mohammed Cotheddin, sultan bassadors of the Turkish emperor, of Khovarezm, sent to that prince an Selim the First, the injured monarch ambassador, accompanied by a caravan took a signal vengeance for the atro- of merchants. On the arrival of that cious deed. He conquered all the do- caravan at Otraw, the governor caused minions of Canson, and, having de- them to be arrested, together with the feated and captured that prince near ambassador, and wrote word to the Cairo, he caused him to be hanged Sultan that they were a company of at one of the gates of the city. Ma- spies. Mohammed thereupon ordered rigny, History of the Arabs, vol. ii. p. him to have the prisoners put to death. 105, 427. Gengis-khan demanded satisfaction of IMMUNITIES OF AMBASSADORS, ETC. 465 This safety is particularly due to the minister, from the BOOK IT. sovereign to whom he is sent. To admit a minister, to an- CHAP - * TU knowledge him in such character, is engaging to grant him I 82 - Parti- the most particular protection, and that he shall enjoy all cula . r pr ' 11 f T j j a.1- j. J.-L J . J . tection due possible safety. It is true, indeed, that the sovereign is to them> bound to protect every person within his dominions, whether (197) native or foreigner, and to shelter him from violence : but this attention is in a higher degree due to a foreign minister. An act of violence done to a private person is an ordinary transgression, which, according to circumstances, the prince may pardon : but if done to a public minister, it is a crime of state, an offence against the law of nations ; and the power of pardoning, in such case, does not rest with the prince in whose dominions the crime has been committed, but with him who has been offended in the person of his representative. However, if the minister has been insulted by persons who were ignorant of his character, the offence is wholly uncon- nected with the law of nations, and falls within the class of ordinary transgressions. A company of young rakes, in a town of Switzerland, having, in the night-time, insulted the British minister's house, without knowing who lived in it, the magistracy sent a message to the minister to know what satis- faction he required. He prudently answered, that it was the magistrates' concern to provide for the public safety by such means as they thought best ; but that, as to his own part, he required nothing, not thinking himself affronted by persons who could have had no design against him, as not knowing his house. Another particular circumstance, in the protec- tion due to foreign ministers, is this : according to the de- structive maxims introduced by a false point of honour, a sove- reign is under a necessity of showing indulgence to a person wearing a sword, who instantly revenges an affront done to him by a private individual : but violent proceedings against a public minister can never be allowed or excused, unless [ 466 ] where the latter has himself been the aggressor, and, by using violence in the first instance, has reduced his opponent to the necessity of self-defence. Though the minister's character is not displayed in its full 83. when extent, and does not thus insure him the enjoyment of all his it coin- rights, till he is acknowledged and admitted by the sovereign, mences - to whom he delivers his credentials, yet, on his entering the country to which he is sent, and making himself known, he is under the protection of the law of nations; otherwise, it would not be safe for him to come. Until he has had his audience of the prince, he is, on his own word, to be considered as a minister ; and besides, exclusive of the notice of his mission, (197) See also the case of the arrest 12. See recital in act, and 1 Bla. Com. of the Russian ambassador, which oc- 250, and ante, 459, note. C. casioned the passing of the 7 Anne, c. 74 585 466 OF RIGHTS, PRIVILEGES, AND BOOK iv. usually given by letter, the minister has, in case of doubt, his CHAP, vii. p a ggp 0r t s to produce, which will sufficiently certify his cha- racter. % 84. What These passports sometimes become necessary to him in the is due to countries through which he passes on his way to the place of countries n * s destination ; and, in case of need, he shows them, in order through to obtain the privileges to which he is entitled. It is true, which they indeed, that the prince alone to whom the minister is sent, is paas. under any obligation, or particular engagement to insure him the enjoyment of all the rights annexed to his character. Yet the others through whose dominions he passes are not to deny him those regards to which the minister of a sovereign is en- titled, and which nations reciprocally owe to each other. In particular they are bound to afford him perfect security. To insult him would be injuring his master, and the whole nation to which he belongs : to arrest him, and offer him violence, would be infringing the right of embassy, which belongs to all sovereigns ( 57 63). The French monarch, Francis the First, had therefore very good reason to complain of the murder of his ambassadors, Rincon and Fregose, as an atro- cious violation of public faith and the law of nations. Those two ministers, the one destined for Constantinople, the other for Venice, having embarked on the Po, were stopped and murdered ; and, according to all appearances, the deed had been perpetrated by order of the governor of Milan.* The emperor Charles the Fifth, having taken no pains to discover the persons concerned in the murder, authorized a belief that he had himself ordered it, or at least that he tacitly approved of the act after its commission. And, as he did not give any suitable satisfaction for it, Francis had a very just cause for declaring war against him, and even calling for the assistance of all other nations : for an affair of this nature is not a pri- vate dispute, a doubtful question, in which each party pre- tends to have justice on his side : it is a quarrel which in- volves the concern of all nations, since they are all equally interested in maintaining the sacred inviolability of that right, and of those means which enable them to hold com- [ 467 ] munication with each other, and to treat of their affairs. If an innocent passage, and even perfect security are due to a private individual, much more are they due to the minister of a sovereign, who is going to execute his master's orders, and who travels on the affairs of a nation. I say, " an in- nocent passage ;" for the minister's journey is justly sus- pected, if a sovereign has reason to apprehend that he will make an improper use of the liberty granted him of entering his territories, by plotting against his interests while in the country, or that he is going to convey intelligence to his ene- mies, or to stir up others against him. We have already * Memoires de Martin du Bellay, liv. ix. 586 IMMUNITIES OF AMBASSADORS, ETC. 467 said ( 64) that he may in such case refuse him a passage : BOOK iv. but he is not to maltreat him, nor suffer any violence to be , CHAP - Tu -. offered to his person. If he has not reason sufficient for de- nying him a passage, he may take precautions against the abuse which the minister might make of it. These maxims the Spaniards found established in Mexico and the neigh- bouring provinces. In those countries, ambassadors were respected throughout their whole journey : but they could not deviate from the high road without forfeiting their rights :* a prudent and judicious reservation, introduced as a guard against the admission of spies under the name of ambassadors. Thus, while the negotiations for peace were carried on at the famous congress of Westphalia, amid the dangers of war and the din of arms, the several couriers sent or received by the plenipotentiaries had each his particu- lar route designated; and, out of the prescribed tract, his passport could afford him no protection, f What we have here observed relates to nations that are | 85. Am- at peace with each other. On the breaking out of a war, we bassadors cease to be under any obligation of leaving the enemy in the going ^ an free enjoyment of his rights: on the contrary, we are justi- Country. fiable in depriving him of them, for the purpose of weakening him, and reducing him to accept of equitable conditions. His people may also be attacked and seized wherever we have a right to commit acts of hostility. Not only, there- fore, may we justly refuse a passage to the ministers whom our enemy sends to other sovereigns ; we may even arrest them if they attempt to pass privately, and without permis- sion, through places belonging to our jurisdiction. Of such proceeding the last war furnishes a signal instance. A French ambassador, on his route to Berlin, touched, through the imprudence of his guides, at a village within the electo- rate of Hanover, whose sovereign, the king of England, was at war with France. The minister was there arrested and afterwards sent over to England. As his Britannic ma- jesty had in that instance only exerted the rights of war, neither the court of France nor that of Prussia complained of his conduct. The reasons which render embassies necessary, and am- 86 - bassadors sacred and inviolable, are not less cogent in time bas ,, , f j s\ i t twe oi Avar, than in prolound peace. On the contrary, the ne- miea- cessity and indispensable duty of preserving some resource by which the minds of the belligerent parties may be brought [ 468 ] to a mutual understanding, and peace be restored, is a fresh reason why the persons of ministers, as instruments in the preliminary conferences and final reconciliation, should be still more sacred and inviolable. Nomen legati, says Cicero, * Solis's history of the Conquest of Mexico. 17. | Wicquefort's Ambassador, book i. g 1. 537 bassies be ~ en ene- 468 BOOK IV. CHAP. VII. \ 87. He- ralds, trum- peters, and drummers. 88. Mi- nisters, trumpeters, Ac., to b respected, even in a civil war. [469] OF RIGHTS, PRIVILEGES, AND ejusmodi esse debet, quod, non modo, inter sociorum jura, sed etiam inter hostium tela, incolume versetur.* Accordingly, one of the most sacred laws of war is that which insures per- fect security to persons who bring messages or proposals from the enemy. It is true, indeed, that the ambassador of an enemy must not approach without permission : and as there does not always exist a convenient opportunity of ob- taining such permission through the medium of neutral per- sons, the defect has been supplied by the establishment of certain privileged messengers for carrying proposals from enemy to enemy, in perfect safety. The privileged messengers I allude to are heralds, trum- peters, and drummers, who, from the moment they make themselves known, and as long as they confine themselves within the terms of their commission, are, by the laws of war and those of nations, considered as sacred and inviolable. This regulation is absolutely necessary ; for, exclusive of the duty incumbent on us to reserve the means of restoring peace (as above mentioned), there occur, even during the course of the war, a thousand occasions, when the common safety and advantage of both parties require that they should be able to send messages and proposals to each other. The insti- tution of heralds succeeded that of the Roman feciales : at present, however, they are seldom employed : drummers or trumpeters are sent, and after them, according to the exi- gence of the occasion, ministers, or officers furnished with powers. Those drummers and trumpeters are held sacred and inviolable ; but they are to make themselves known by the marks peculiar to them. (198) Maurice, prince of Orange, highly resented the conduct of the garrison of Ysendick, who had fired at his trumpeter :f on which occa- sion the prince observed that no punishment can be too severe for those who violate the law of nations. Other in- stances may be seen in Wicquefort, and particularly the repa- ration which the duke of Savoy, as general of Charles the Fifth's army, caused to be made to a French trumpeter, who had been dismounted and despoiled by some German soldiers, f In the wars of the Netherlands the duke of Alva hanged up a trumpeter belonging to the prince of Orange, saying that he was not obliged to allow safety to a trumpeter sent him by the chief of the rebels, f On this, as on many other occasions, that sanguinary general was undoubtedly guilty of a flagrant violation of the laws of war, which, as we have proved above (Book III. Chap. XVIII.), ought to be ob- served even in civil wars : for, unless both parties can with perfect safety interchange messages, and reciprocally send * In Verrero, orat. L ( 198) But see Msop'a Fables. C. | Wicquefort, book L 3. . IMMUNITIES OF AMBASSADORS, ETC. 469 confidential persons to each other, how can they, on those BOOK IT. unfortunate occasions, ever come to talk of peace ? What CHAP - Y "-, channel remains open for negotiating a salutary accommo- dation ? The same duke of Alva, in the war which the Spaniards afterwards made on the Portuguese, whom they also termed rebels, caused the governor of Cascais to be hanged for having given orders to fire on a trumpeter sent to demand a surrender of the town.* In a civil war, or when a prince takes up arms for the purpose of subduing a body of people who think themselves absolved from their allegiance to him, an attempt to compel the enemies to respect the laws of war, while he himself does not observe them on his own part, is in fact equal to a determined resolution of carrying those wars to the extreme of cruelty, and converting them into a scene of inordinate and endless murder, by the long series of mutual retaliations which will naturally ensue. But, as a prince, when influenced by substantial reasons, 89. Some- may refuse to admit and listen to ambassadors, in like man- times they ner the general of an army, or any other commander, is not aay d be d ^- t always obliged to permit the approach of a trumpeter or t * e */w9) drummer, and to give him a hearing. If, for instance, the governor of a besieged town is apprehensive that a summons to surrender may intimidate the garrison, and excite prema- ture ideas of capitulation, he undoubtedly may, on seeing the trumpeter advance, send him orders to retire, informing him that if he comes a second time on the same errand and without permission, he shall be fired upon. This conduct is no violation of the laws of war : but such a mode of proceed- ing ought not to be adopted without very cogent reasons, because, by irritating the besiegers, it exposes the garrison to be treated by them with the extreme of rigour, untem- pered with mercy or moderation. To refuse to hear a trum- peter's message without alleging a substantial reason for the refusal, is equivalent to a declaration that the party is determined to presevere in irreconcilable hostility. Whether we admit or refuse to hear a herald or a trum- ? 90. Every peter, we ought carefully to avoid every thing which might thin s which wear the appearance of an insult offered to him. Not only p^rlnc^ o~f does the law of nations claim that respect, but prudence i nsu it to moreover recommends such caution and delicacy. In 1744, them must the Bailly de Givry sent a trumpeter, with an officer, to sum- be avoided, mon the redoubt of Pierrelonge in Piedmont. The Savoyard [ 470 ] officer who commanded in the redoubt, a brave man, but of a blunt and fiery disposition, feeling his indignation roused by a summons to surrender a post which he deemed tenable and secure, returned an insulting answer to the French gene- ral. The officer to whom the answer was given, judiciously * Wicquefort, book i. 21 b.; 4 Inst 155; 2 Inst 57; 1 Chit- (199) See also Calvin's case, 7 Coke, ty's Com. L. 131. C. 2Z 589 470 OF RIGHTS, PRIVILEGES, AND BOOK iv. took advantage of the circumstance, and delivered it to the CHAP - Yir - Bailly de Givry in the hearing of the French troops. It set them in a flame ; and their native valour being stimulated by the eager desire of avenging an affront, their impetuosity was irresistible : though the attack was attended with con- siderable carnage, the losses they sustained only added fresh fuel to their courage, till at length they carried the redoubt : and thus the imprudent commandant was accessary to his own death, the slaughter of his men, and the loss of his post. 91. By and The prince, the general of the army, and every corn- to whom mander-in-chief within his department, have alone the right ^ sending a trumpeter or drummer ; and, on the other hand, it is only to the commander-in-chief that they can send such messengers. Should a general, besieging a town, at- tempt to send a trumpeter to any subaltern, to the magis- tracy, or the townsmen, the governor might justly treat that trumpeter as a spy. The French monarch, Francis the First, while engaged in war with Charles the Fifth, sent a trumpeter to the diet of the empire, then assembled at Spires. The trumpeter was seized by order of the emperor, who threatened to hang him, because he was not sent to him.* But he did not dare to put his threat in execution; for, loudly as he complained on the subject, he was nevertheless convinced, in his own mind, that the diet had a right, even without his consent, to listen to the proposals brought by a trumpeter. On the other hand, a drummer or trumpeter from a subaltern is seldom received, unless for some particu- lar object depending on the present authority of that subal- tern acting in his function. At the siege of Rynberg in 1598, a colonel of a Spanish regiment having taken upon him to summon the town, the governor sent the drummer orders to withdraw, informing him at the same time, that, if any other drummer or trumpeter had the audacity to come on the same errand from a subaltern, he would cause the messenger to be hanged.f 92. inde- The inviolability of a public minister, or the protection to pendence of which he has a more sacred and particular claim than any foreign mi- o j ner person, whether native or foreigner, is not the only nisters. . ., r , ' . . . . & . ' . ,, J (200) privilege he enjoys : the universal practice of nations allows him, moreover, an entire independence on the jurisdiction and authority of the state in which he resides. Some au- thors;}; maintain that this independence is merely a matter of institution between different states, and will have it refer- red to the arbitrary law of nations, which owes its origin to manners, customs, or particular conventions : in a word, they deny it to be grounded on the natural law of nations. It is true, indeed, that the law of nature gives men a right to * Wiequefort, ubi supra. f Idem, ibid. (200) See ante, pp. 459, 464. j See Wolf. Jus Gent, 1059. 590 IMMUNITIES OF AMBASSADOKS, ETC. 470 punish those who injure them : consequently, it empowers BOOK iv. sovereigns to punish any foreigner who disturbs the public CHAP ' Y "' tranquillity, who offends them, or maltreats their subjects : it authorizes them to compel such foreigner to conform to the laws, and to behave properly towards the citizens. But it is no less true, that the natural law at the same time im- [ 471 ] poses on all sovereigns the obligation of consenting to those things, without which it would be impossible for nations to cultivate the society that nature has established among them, to keep up a mutual correspondence, to treat of their aifairs, or to adjust their differences. Now, ambassadors, and other public ministers, are necessary instruments for the main- tenance of that general society, of that mutual correspond- ence between nations. But their ministry cannot effect the intended purpose, unless it be invested with all the preroga- tives which are capable of insuring its legitimate success, and of enabling the minister freely and faithfully to discharge his duty in perfect security. The law of nations, therefore, while it obliges us to grant admission to foreign ministers, does also evidently oblige us to receive those ministers in full possession of all the rights which necessarily attach to their character all the privileges requisite for the due per- formance of their functions. It is easy to conceive that in- dependence must be one of those privileges; since, without it, that security which is so necessary to a public minister, would be enjoyed on a very precarious footing. He might be molested, persecuted, maltreated, under a thousand pre- tences. A minister is often charged with commissions that are disagreeable to the prince to whom he is sent. If that prince has any power over him, and especially a sovereign authority, how is it to be expected that the minister can exe- cute his master's orders with due fidelity, firmness, and free- dom of mind ? It is a matter of no small importance that he have no snares to apprehend that he be not liable to be diverted from his functions by any chicanery that he have nothing to hope, nothing to fear, from the sovereign to whom he is sent. In order, therefore, to the success of his minis- try, he must be independent of the sovereign authority and of the jurisdiction of the country, both in civil and criminal matters. To this may be added, that the nobility and other persons of eminence would be averse to undertaking an em- bassy, if such commission were to subject them to a foreign authority not unfrequently in countries where they have little friendship to expect for their own nation, and where they must support disagreeable claims, and enter into dis- cussions naturally productive of acrimony. In a word, if an ambassador may be indicted for ordinary offences, be cri- minally prosecuted, taken into custody, punished if he may be sued in civil cases the consequence will often be, that he will neither possess the power, the leisure, nor the freedom 591 471 OF RIGHTS, PRIVILEGES, AND BOOK iv. of mind which his master's affairs require. And how shall CHAP, vii. ne jj e jjj^g to g U pp 0r t; the dignity of representation in such a state of subjection ? On the whole, therefore, it is impossible to conceive that the prince who sends an ambassador, or any other minister, can have any intention of subjecting him to the authority of a foreign power : and this consideration fur- nishes an additional argument which completely establishes [ 472 ] the independency of a public minister. If it cannot be rea- sonably presumed that his sovereign means to subject him to the authority of the prince to whom he is sent, the latter, in receiving the minister, consents to admit him on the footing of independency : and thus there exists between the two princes a tacit convention, which gives a new force to the natural obligation. The established practice is perfectly conformable to the principles here laid down. All sovereigns claim a perfect in- dependency for their ambassadors and ministers. If it be true that there was a king of Spain, who from a desire of arrogating to himself a jurisdiction over the foreign ministers resident at his court, wrote to all the Christian princes, in- forming them that if his ambassadors should commit any crime in the places of their respective residence, it Avas his pleasure that they should forfeit all their privileges, and be tried according to the laws of the country,* one solitary in- stance is of no weight in an affair of this nature ; nor have his successors on the Spanish throne adopted a similar mode of thinking. \ 93. How This independency of the foreign minister is not to be the foreign converted into licentiousness : it does not excuse him from toTehave 8 conforming to the customs and laws of the country in all his external actions, so far as they are unconnected with the object of his mission and character : he is independent ; but he has not a right to do whatever he pleases. Thus, for instance, if there exist a general prohibition against pass- ing in a carriage near a powder-magazine, or over a bridge against walking round, and examining the fortifications of a town, &c. the ambassador is bound to respect such prohibi- tions, f Should he forget his duty should he grow insolent, * The fact is advanced by Antony respective claims to precedency, mado de Vera, in his "Idea of a Perfect a general request to all the foreign Ambassador :" but Wicquefort sus- ministers not to send their carriages pects the authenticity of the anecdote, to attend the public entry of the Ve- not having, as he says, met with it netian ambassador. The count d'Es- in any other writer. Ambassad. book i. trades, at that time minister from tho 29. court of France, having complied with f The king of England having re- his majesty's desire, Louis XIV. tes- ceived information that the French tified his dissatisfaction at the dcfe- and Spanish ambassadors had seve- rence paid by the count to the British rally collected considerable numbers monarch's message, "which was no of armed men, for the purpose of sup- more than a simple request not to porting, on a solemn occasion, their send carriages; whereas, even if he 592 IMMUNITIES OF AMBASSADOKS, ETC. 472 and be guilty of irregularities and crimes there are, accord- BOOK rr. ing to the nature and importance of his offences, various CHAP - YII -_ modes of repressing him : and these we shall speak of, after \ve have said a few words concerning the line of conduct to be pursued by a public minister in the place of his residence. He must not avail himself of his independency for the pur- [ 473 ] pose of violating the laws and customs; he should rather punctually conform to them, as far as they may concern him, although the magistrate has no compulsive power over him ; and he is especially bound to a religious observance of the rules of justice towards all who have any dealings with him. As to what concerns the prince to whom he is sent, the am- bassador should remember that his ministry is a ministry of peace, and that it is on that footing only he is received. This reason forbids his engaging in any evil machinations : let him serve his master without injuring the prince who re- ceives him. It is a base treachery to take advantage of the inviolability of the ambassadorial character, for the purpose of plotting in security the ruin of those who respect that character of laying snares for them of clandestinely in- juring them of embroiling and ruining their affairs. What would be infamous and abominable in a private guest, shall that be allowable and becoming in the representative of a sovereign ? Here arises an interesting question. It is but too common for ambassadors to tamper with the fidelity of the ministers of the court to which they are sent, and of the secretaries and other persons employed in the public offices. What ideas are we to entertain of this practice? To corrupt a person to seduce him to engage him by the powerful al- lurement of gold to betray his prince and violate his duty, is, according to all the established principles of morality, undoubtedly a wicked action. How comes it then that so little scruple is made of it in public affairs ? A wise and virtuous politician* sufficiently gives us to understand that he absolutely condemns that scandalous resource : but, fear- ful of provoking the whole tribe of politicians to assail him at once, like a nest of hornets, he proceeds no further than barely advising them not to practise such manoeuvres except when every other resource fails. As to me, whose pen is employed in developing the sacred and immutable principles- had issued an express order (as being subject; since every sovereign must at liberty to give what orders he pleases surely have a right to prohibit all fo- in his own kingdom,) you should have reign ministers doing any thing in his replied that you receive no commands dominions which may tend to produce but from me: and if, after that, he disorder, and which, moreover, is not had attempted to use violence, the necessary to the exercise of their mi- part which remained for you to act, nisterial functions, was that of withdrawing from his * Mons. Pequet, Discours sur 1'Art court." I think the French monarch de Negocier, p. 91. entertained erroneous ideas on the 75 2 z 2 593 473 OF RIGHTS, PRIVILEGES, AND BOOK iv. of justice, I must, in duty to the moral world, openly aver CHAP. YII. ^at ^ mo( j e O f corruption is directly repugnant to all the rules of virtue and probity, and a flagrant violation of the law of nature. It is impossible to conceive an act of a more flagitious nature, or more glaringly militant against the re- ciprocal duties of men, than that of inducing any one to do evil. The corruptor is undoubtedly guilty of a crime against the wretch whom he seduces ; and as to the sovereign whose secrets are thus treacherously explored, is it not both an offence and an injury committed against him, to abuse the friendly reception given at his court, and to take advantage of it for the purpose of corrupting the fidelity of his servants ? He has a right to banish the eorruptor from his dominions, and to demand justice of his employer. If ever bribery be excusable, it is when it happens to be the only possible mode by which we can completely discover [ 474 ] and defeat a heinous plot, capable of ruining, or materially endangering the state in whose service we are employed. In the conduct of him who betrays such a secret, there may, according to circumstances, be no criminality. The great and lawful advantage accruing from the action which we induce him to perform, together with the urgent necessity of having recourse to it, may dispense with our paying too scru- pulous an attention to the questionable complexion of the deed on his part. To gain him over is no more than an act of simple and justifiable self-defence. It every day happens, that, in order to foil the machinations of wicked men, we find ourselves under a necessity of turning to our account the vicious dispositions of men of similar stamp. On this footing it was that Henry the Fourth said to the Spanish minister, that " it is justifiable conduct in an ambassador to have recourse to bribery for the purpose of detecting the intrigues that are carried on against his sovereign's interest ;"* adding, that the affair of Marseilles, that of Metz, and seve- ral others, sufficiently showed that he had good reason for endeavouring to penetrate the schemes which his enemies were plotting at Brussels against the tranquillity of his kingdom. That great prince, it is to be presumed, did not consider bribery and seduction as on all occasions excusable in a foreign minister, since he himself gave orders for the arrest of Bru- neau, the Spanish ambassador's secretary, who had tampered with Mairargues for the clandestine surrender of Marseilles to the Spaniards. In "barely taking advantage of the offers made to us by a traitor, whom we have not seduced, our conduct is less in- consistent with justice and honour. But the examples of the Romans, which we have already quoted (Book III. 155, 181), and in which there was question of declared enemies, * See Solly's Memoirs, and the French historians. IMMUNITIES OF AMBASSADOKS, ETC. 474 those examples, I say, sufficiently show that true greatness BOOK iv. of soul disdains even that resource, lest the adoption of it CHAP - YI1 -. should hold out an encouragement to infamous treachery. A prince or a minister, whose ideas of honour are not inferior to those of the ancient Romans above noticed, will never stoop to embrace the proposals of a traitor, except when com- pelled by some dire, uncontrollable necessity : and even then he will regret the degrading circumstance of owing his pre- servation to so unworthy an expedient. But I do not here mean to condemn an ambassador for employing civilities and polite attentions, and even presents and promises, with a view to gain friends for his sovereign. To conciliate men's affections and good-will is not seducing them, or impelling them to the perpetration of criminal deeds : and, as to those new friends, it is their business to keep a strict Avatch over their own hearts, lest their attach- ment to a foreign prince should ever warp them from the fidelity which they owe to their lawful sovereign. [ 475 ] Should an ambassador forget the duties of his station $ 94. How should he render himself disagreeable and dangerous should he he form cabals and schemes prejudicial to the peace of the citizens, or to the state or prince to whom he is sent there are various modes of punishing him, proportionate to the nature and degree of his offence. If he maltreats the sub- 1. for ordi- jects of the state if he commits any acts of injustice or nar y. traus - violence against them the injured subjects are not to seek grts: redress from the ordinary magistrates, since the ambassador is wholly independent of their jurisdiction : and, for the same reason, those magistrates cannot proceed directly against him. On such occasions, therefore, the plaintiffs are to make application to their sovereign, who demands justice from the ambassador's master, and, in case of a refusal, may order the insolent minister to quit his dominions. Should a foreign minister offend the prince himself g 95. 2. for should he fail in the respect which he owes him, or, by his fa j llts com - intrigues, embroil the state and the court the offended 1 ^ t the prince, from a wish to keep measures with the offender's pX^. sovereign, sometimes contents himself with simply requiring that the minister be recalled ; or if the transgression be of a more serious nature, he forbids his appearance at court in the interval while his master's answer is expected ; and, in cases of a heinous complexion, he even proceeds so far as to expel him from his territories. Every sovereign has an unquestionable right to proceed in 3 95. Right this manner ; for, being master in his own dominions, no of ordering foreigner can stay at his court, or in his territories, without awa >' an his permission. And though sovereigns are generally "'^y^ obliged to listen to the overtures of foreign powers, and to ty, or justly admit their ministers, this obligation entirely ceases with re- suspected. gard to a minister, who, being himself deficient in the duties 595 475 OF RIGHTS, PRIVILEGES, AND BOOK iv. attached to this station, becomes dangerous to, or justly sus- CHAP. vii. p ecte( j by the sovereign, to whom he can come in no other character than that of a minister of peace. Can a prince be obliged to suffer that a secret enemy, who is raising dis- turbances in the state and plotting its ruin, shall remain in his dominions and appear at his court ? Ridiculous was the answer of Philip the Second td queen Elizabeth, on her re- quest that he would recall his ambassador, who was carrying on dangerous plots against her. The Spanish monarch re- fused to recall him, saying, that "the condition of princes would be very wretched indeed, if they were obliged to recall a minister whenever his conduct did not suit the humour or the interest of those with whom he was negotiating."* Much more wretched would be the condition of princes, if they were bound to suffer in their states, and at their court, a mi- nister who was disagreeable or justly suspected, an incendiary, an enemy disguised under the character of an ambassador, who should avail himself of his inviolability for the purpose of boldly plotting schemes of a pernicious tendency. The queen, justly offended at Philip's refusal, put a guard on the [ 476 ] ambassador. f 97. Right But is a prince on every occasion bound to confine his re- of repressing sentment to the simple expulsion of an ambassador, however force^f he ^^ *^ e enorm ^ es ^ which the latter may have been guilty ? behaves as* Such is the doctrine maintained by some authors, who ground an enemy, their opinion on the absolute independency of a public minis- ter. I own he is independent of the jurisdiction of the coun- try : and I have already said, that, on this account, the com- mon magistrate cannot proceed against him. I further admit, that, in all cases of ordinary transgression, all instances of offensive or disorderly behaviour, which, though injurious to individuals, or to society, do not endanger the safety of the state or of the sovereign, there is that degree of respect due to the ambassadorial character which is so necessary for the correspondence of nations, and to the dignity of the prince represented, that a complaint be first made to him of the conduct of his minister, together with a demand of repara- tion ; and that, if no satisfaction is obtained, the offended sovereign be then content with simply ordering the ambassa- dor to quit his dominions, in case the serious nature of the offences absolutely require that a stop be put to them. But shall an ambassador be suffered with impunity to cabal against the state where he resides, to plot its ruin, to stir up the sub- jects to revolt, and boldly to foment the most dangerous con- spiracies, under the assurance of being supported by his master ? If he behaves as an enemy, shall it not be allowable to treat him as such ? The question admits not of a doubt with re- gard to an ambassador who proceeds to overt acts, who takes * Wicquefort, book L 29. t Idem, ibid. 596 IMMUNITIES OF AMBASSADORS, ETC. 476 up arms, and uses violence. In such case, those whom he BOOK iv. attacks may repel him : self-defence being authorized by the CHAP - Tn - law of nature. Those Roman ambassadors, who, being sent to the Gauls, fought against them with the people of Clusium, divested themselves of the ambassadorial character.* Can any one therefore imagine that the Gauls were bound to spare them in the hour of battle ? The question is more difficult with respect to an ambassa- 98. Am- dor who, without proceeding to overt acts, broaches plots of bassador a dangerous tendency, who, by his occult machinations, ex- *j^ cites the subjects to revolt, and who forms and encourages p^^nT conspiracies against the sovereign or the state. Shall it be conspira- deemed unlawful to repress and inflict exemplary punishment cies. on a traitor who abuses the sacred character with which he is invested, and who is himself the first to set the example of violating the law of nations ? That sacred law provides no less for the safety of the prince who receives an ambassador, than for that of the ambassador himself. But, on the other hand, if we allow the offended prince a right to punish a foreign minister in such cases, the subjects of contest and rupture [ 47 7 ] between sovereigns will become very frequent; and it is much to be feared that the ambassadorial character will cease to enjoy that protection and inviolability which are so essen- tial to it. There are certain practices connived at in foreign ministers, though not always strictly consistent with the rules of rectitude: there are others, again, which are not to be corrected by actual punishment, but simply by ordering the minister to depart. How shall we, in every case, be able to ascertain the precise boundaries of those different degrees of transgression ? When there exists a premeditated design of persecuting a minister, an odious colouring will be given to his intrigues : his intentions and proceedings will be calum- niated by sinister constructions ; even false accusations will be raised against him. Finally, sucti plots as we here allude to are generally conducted with caution : they are carried on so secretly, that, to obtain full proof of them, is a matter of extreme difficulty, and indeed hardly possible, without the formalities of justice, formalities to which we cannot sub- ject a minister who is independent of the jurisdiction of the country. In laying down the grounds of the voluntary law of na- tions (Prelim. 21), we have seen that, in particular con- junctures, nations must, with a view to the general advan- tage, necessarily recede from certain rights, which, taken in themselves and abstracted from every other consideration, should naturally belong to them. Thus, although the sove- * Livy, book v. chap. 26, where the " Legati, contra jus gentium, arma capi- historian peremptorily decides that those unt." ambassadors violated the law of nations : 597 477 OF RIGHTS, PRIVILEGES, AND BOOK iv. reign who has justice on his side be alone really entitled to CHAP - Yn - all the rights of war (Book III. 188), he is nevertheless obliged to look upon his enemy as enjoying equal rights with himself, and to treat him accordingly (Ibid. 190, 191). The same principles must be our rule in the present case. We may therefore venture to affirm, that, in consideration of the extensive utility, nay, tne absolute necessity of em- bassies, sovereigns are bound to respect the inviolability of an ambassador as long as it is not incompatible with their own safety and the welfare of their state. Consequently, when the intrigues of the ambassador have transpired, and his plots are discovered, when the danger is passed, so that there no longer exists a necessity of laying hands on him in order to guard against it, the offended sovereign ought, in consideration of the ambassadorial character, to renounce his general right of punishing a traitor and a secret enemy who conspires against the safety of the state, and to con- tent himself with dismissing the guilty minister, and requir- ing that punishment to be inflicted on him by the sovereign to whose authority he is subject. Such, in fact, is the mode of proceeding established by common consent among the generality of nations, especially those of Europe. Wicquefort* gives us several instances of some of the principal European sovereigns, who, on discover- [ 478 ] ing ambassadors to be guilty of odious machinations, have limited their resentment to the expulsion of the offenders, without even making application to have them punished by their masters, of whom they did not expect to obtain a com- pliance with such a demand. To these instances let us add that of the duke of Orleans, regent of France. That prince, having detected a dangerous conspiracy which had been formed against him by the prince de Cellamare, ambassador from Spain, behaved with great moderation on the occasion, not adopting any severer measures than those of setting a guard over the guilty minister, seizing his papers, and caus- ing him to be conducted out of the kingdom. Another re- markable instance, of very ancient date, stands recorded by the Roman historians, that in which Tarquin's ambassadors were concerned. Having repaired to Rome under pretence of claiming the private property belonging to their master, who had been expelled from his kingdom, they tampered with the profligate young nobility, and engaged them in a black and infamous conspiracy against the liberties of their coun- try. Although such conduct would have authorized the rulers of the Roman state to treat them as enemies, the con- suls and senate nevertheless respected the law of nations in the persons of those ambassadors, f The offenders were sent * Ambassad. book i. g 27, 28, 29. tamen gentium valuit Tit Liv. lib. ii. j- Et quamquam visi aunt (legati) cap. 4. commisisse ut hostium loco essent, jus 593 IMMUNITIES OF AMBASSADORS, ETC. 478 back to their employer, without having received any personal BOOK iv. injury : but, from Livy's account of the transaction, it ap- CHAP - YII pears that the letters which they had from the conspirators to Tarquin were taken from them. This example leads us to the true rule of the law of na- ? 99. What tions, in the cases now in question. An ambassador cannot ma y be be punished because he is independent : and, for the reasons a * we have alleged, it is not proper to treat him as an enemy, the till he himself proceeds to overt acts of violence : but we are cy of the justifiable in adopting against him every measure which the case< circumstances of the case may reasonably require for the purpose of defeating his machinations and averting the evil which he has plotted. If, in order to disconcert and prevent a conspiracy, it were necessary to arrest or even put to death an ambassador who animates and conducts it, I do not see why we should for a moment hesitate to take either of those steps, not only because the safety of the state is the su- preme law, but also because, independent of that maxim, the ambassador's own deeds give us a perfect and particular right to proceed to such extremities. A public minister, I grant, is independent, and his person is sacred : but it is un- questionably lawful to repel his attacks, whether of a secret or of an open nature, and to defend ourselves against him, whenever he acts either as an enemy or a traitor. And if we cannot accomplish our own preservation without harm thence resulting to him, it is he himself who has laid us un- der a necessity of not sparing him. On such an occasion, it may with great truth be asserted, that the minister has, by his own act, excluded himself from the protection of the law of nations. Suppose the Venetian senate, though ap- prised of the marquis of Bedamar's conspiracy, and impressed with a thorough conviction of that minister's being the prime [ 479 ] mover and director of the whole business, had nevertheless been, in other particulars, destitute of sufficient information to enable them to crush the detestable plot, suppose they had been uncertain with respect to the number and rank of the conspirators, the designs they had in agitation, and the particular quarter where the meditated mischief was to burst forth, whether an intention was entertained of exciting a revolt among the marine or the land forces, or effecting the clandestine capture of some important fortress, would they, under such circumstances, have been bound to suffer the ambassador to depart unmolested, and thus afford him an opportunity of joining and heading his accomplices, and of bringing his designs to a successful issue ! No man will seriously answer in the affirmative : the senate, therefore, would have had a right to arrest the marquis and all his household, and even to extort from them their detestable secret. But those prudent republicans, seeing the danger was removed, and the conspiracy totally suppressed, chose 599 479 .OF EIGHTS, PRIVILEGES, AND BOOK iv. to keep measures with Spain : wherefore they prohibited all CHAP " VIL accusation of the Spaniards as concerned in the plot, and contented themselves with simply requesting the ambassador to withdraw, in order to screen himself from the rage of the populace. 100. Am- In this case the same rule is to be followed which we have alrea( ty laid down ( Book IIL J 36 ') in treatin g of what may lawfully be done to an enemy. Whenever an ambassador sovereign's acts as an enemy, we are justifiable in adopting against him life. every measure that is necessary for the purpose of defeating his evil designs and insuring our own safety. It is on the same principle, and under the idea which represents the am- bassador as a public enemy when he behaves as such, that we proceed to determine the treatment he ought to receive in case he pursues his criminal career to the last stage of enor- mity. If an ambassador commit any of those atrocious crimes which sap the very foundations of the general safety of mankind, if he attempt to assassinate or poison the prince who has received him at his court, he unquestionably deserves to be punished as a treacherous enemy guilty of poisoning or assassination (See Book III. 155). The am- bassadorial character, which he has so basely prostituted, cannot shield him from the sword of justice. Is the law of nations to protect such a criminal, when the personal secu- rity of all sovereigns and the general safety of mankind loudly demand that his crime should be expiated by the sacri- fice of his forfeit life ? It is true, indeed, that we have little room to apprehend that a public minister will proceed to such dreadful enormities : for it is generally men of honour who are invested with the character of ambassadors ; and even if there should, among the number, be some whose con- sciences are callous to every scruple, the difficulties, never- theless, and the magnitude of the danger, are sufficient to deter them from the attempt. Yet such crimes are not [ 480 ] wholly unexampled in history. Monsieur Barbeyrac* in- stances the assassination of the lord of Sirmium by an am- bassador of Constantinus Diogenes, governor of the neigh- bouring province for Basilius II., emperor of Constantinople; and for his authority he quotes the historian Cedrenus. The following fact is likewise to the purpose. In the year 1382, Charles III., king of Naples, having sent to his competitor, Louis duke of Anjou, a knight named Matthew Sauvage, in the character of a herald, to challenge him to single combat, the herald was suspected of carrying a demi-lance whose point was tinged with a poison of so subtle a nature, that who- ever should look steadfastly on it, or even suffer it to touch his clothes, would instantly drop down dead. The duke, * In his notes on Bynkershoek's treatise on the Competent Judge of Am- bassadors, ch. xxiv. 5, note 2. 600 IMMUNITIES OF AMBASSADORS, ETC. 480 being apprized of the danger, refused to admit the herald BOOK rv. into his presence, and ordered him to be taken into custody. CHAP - ""*-. The culprit was interrogated, and, upon his own confession, suffered the punishment of decapitation. Charles complained of the execution of his herald, as an infraction of the laws and usages of war : but Louis, in his reply, maintained that he had not violated those laws in his treatment of Sauvage, who had been convicted by his own confession.* Had the crime imputed to the herald been clearly substantiated, he was an assassin, whom no law could protect. But the very nature of the accusation sufficiently proves that it was a false and groundless charge. The question of which we have been treating has been g 101. Two debated in England and France on two famous occasions, remarkable In the former of those countries, the question arose in the case of John Leslie, bishop of Ross, ambassador from Mary, queen of Scots. That minister was continually intriguing ties of public against queen Elizabeth, plotting against the tranquillity of ministers, the state, forming conspiracies, and exciting the subjects to rebellion. Five of the most able civilians, being consulted by the privy council, gave it as their opinion, that " an am- bassador raising a rebellion against the prince at whose court he resides, forfeits the privileges annexed to his character, and is subject to the punishment of the law." They should rather have said, that he may be treated as an enemy. But the council contented themselves with causing the bishop to be arrested, and after having detained him a prisoner in the Tower for two years, set him at liberty when there was no longer any danger to be apprehended from his intrigues, and obliged him to depart from the kingdom.f This instance may serve to confirm the principles which we have laid down ; and the like may be said of the following. Bruneau, secre- tary to the Spanish ambassador in France, was detected in the very act of treating with Mairargues, in a time of pro- found peace, for the surrender of Marseilles to the Spaniards. The secretary was thereupon committed to prison, and was [ 481 ] subjected to a judicial examination by the parliament before whom Mairargues was tried. That body, however, did not pronounce sentence of condemnation on Bruneau, but referred his case to the king, who restored him to his master, on con- dition that the latter should order him to depart immediately from the kingdom. The ambassador warmly complained of the imprisonment of his secretary : but Henry IV. very judi- ciously answered, that "the law of nations does not forbid putting a public minister under an arrest, in order to hinder him from doing mischief." The king might have added, that a nation has even a right to adopt, against a public minister, * History of the Kings of the Two Sicilies, by Monsieur D'Egly. f Cambden's Annal. Angl. ad ann. 1571, 1573. 76 3 A 601 481 OF BIGHTS, PRIVILEGES, AND BOOK iv. every measure which may be necessary for the purpose of CHAP. YII. war( ij n g O ff the mischief he meditates against her, of defeat- ing his projects, and preventing their evil consequences. It was on this principle that the parliament were authorized to interrogate Bruneau, for the purpose of discovering all the parties concerned in so dangerous a conspiracy. The ques- tion, whether foreign ministers who violate the law of nations do thereby forfeit their privileges, was warmly debated at Paris, but, without waiting to have the point decided, the king restored Bruneau to his master.* 102. Whe- It is not lawful to maltreat an ambassador by way of reta- therrepri- liation: for the prince who uses violence against a public madron an mil " ster * s guilty of a crime ; and we are not to take ven- ambassador. geance for his misconduct by copying his example. We never can, under pretence of retaliation, be authorized to commit actions which are in their own nature unjustifiable : and such undoubtedly would be any instance of ill treatment inflicted on an unoffending minister as a punishment for his master's faults. If it be an indispensable duty to pay a general regard to this rule in cases of retaliation, it is more particularly obligatory with regard to an ambassador, on account of the respect due to his character. The Cartha- ginians having violated the law of nations in the persons of the Roman ambassadors, the ambassadors of that perfidious nation were brought to Scipio, who, being asked how he would have them to be treated, replied, " Not in the manner that the Carthaginians have treated ours." Accordingly he [ 482 ] dismissed them in safety :f but at the same time he made preparations for chastising, by force of arms, the state which had violated the law of nations.J There cannot be a better * See the discussion of the question, with common decency." La Croix, and the discourse which Henry IV. held Hist, of Timur-Bec, book ii. chap. 26. on this subject to the Spanish ambassa- The same historian, in his account of dor, in the Memoires de Nevers, vol. ii. Barcouc, sultan of Egypt, who put p. 858, et seq., in Matthieu, vol. ii. book Timur's ambassador to death, observes, iii. and other historians. " that it was an infamous action ; Joseph Sofi, king of Carezem, having that to insult an ambassador is a vio- iinprisoned an ambassador of Timur- lation of the law of nations, and a Bee, Timur's secretary of state wrote deed at which nature herself shudders." him a letter couched in strong terms Ibid, book v. chap. 17. Edit A.D. of expostulation on the subject of that 1797. infraction of the law of nations, in- f Appian, quoted by Grotius, lib. ii. forming him that " it is a maxim with cap. 28, g 7. According to Diodorus kings to consider the person of an am- Siculus, Scipio said to the Romans, bassador as sacred : for which reason " Do not imitate that conduct with he is always held exempt from the which you reproach the Carthagi- punishment of death or imprisonment, mans." EKITTKJI/ owe E^IJ 6ctv Trparrav 5 if the sovereign to whom he is sent rot; Kapxrfoviois /rtyaXouo-j. Diod. Sic. has even the slightest knowledge of Excerpt. Peiresc. p. 290. the law of nations, or the ambassador J Livy, book xxx. chap. 28, 7. himself does but possess sufficient pru- That historian makes Scipio say, dence to refrain from the commission "Though the Carthaginians have of any heinous offence, and to behave violated the faith of the truce, and the IMMUNITIES OF AMBASSADORS, ETC. 482 pattern for sovereigns to follow on such an occasion. If the BOOK IT. injury for which we would make retaliation does not concern CHAP - *" a public minister, there exists a still stronger certainty that we must not retaliate on the ambassador of the sovereign against whom our complaint lies. The safety of public ministers would be very precarious, if it were liable to be affected by every casual difference that might arise. But there is one particular case in which it appears perfectly justifiable to arrest an ambassador, provided no ill treatment be given to him in other respects. When, for instance, a prince has, in open violation of the law of nations, caused our ambassador to be arrested, we may arrest and detain his, as a pledge for the life and liberty of ours. But should this expedient prove unsuccessful, it would become our duty to liberate the unoffending minister, and to seek redress by more efficacious measures. Charles the Fifth caused the French ambassador, who had made him a declaration of war, to be put under an arrest ; whereupon Francis the First caused Granvelle, the emperor's ambassador, to be arrested in like manner. At length, however, it was agreed that both those ministers should be conducted to the frontier, and re- leased at the same time.* We have derived the independence and inviolability of the \ 103. ambassadorial character from the natural and necessary prin- A s ree en * ciples of the law of nations. These prerogatives are further on g^ning confirmed by the uniform practice and general consent of the privi- mankind. We have seen above ( 84), that the Spaniards leges of found the right of embassies established and respected in^ assa - Mexico. The same principle also prevails even among the savage tribes of North America : and if we thence turn our eye to the other extremity of the globe, we find that ambas- sadors are highly respected in China. In India also the same rule is observed, though with less scrupulous punctuality :f the king of Ceylon, for instance, has sometimes imprisoned the ambassadors of the Dutch East-India company. Being master of the places which produce cinnamon, he knows that the Dutch, in consideration of a profitable commerce, will overlook many irregularities in his conduct ; and, with the true disposition of a barbarian, he takes an undue advantage of that circumstance. The Koran enjoins the moslems to re- spect public ministers : and if the Turks have not in all in- stances uniformly observed that precept, their violations of [ 483 ] it are rather imputable to the ferocity of particular princes than to the principles of the nation at large. The rights of ambassadors were formerly very well known among the law of nations, in the person of our * Mezeray's Hist of France, vol. ii. ambassadors, I will do nothing against p. 470. theirs that is unworthy of the maxims f General Hist of Voyages, art of the Roman people, and of my own China, and Indies. principles." 603 483 OF RIGHTS, PRIVILEGES, AND BOOK iv. Arabs. A writer of that nation* relates the following inci- CHAP. vii. ^ en ^. . Khaled, an Arabian chief, having come, in the cha- racter of ambassador, to the army of the emperor Heraclius, used insolent language to the general : whereupon the latter observed to him, that " ambassadors were protected from all kind of violence by the law which universally prevailed among nations : and it was probably that consideration which had emboldened the Arab to speak to him in so indecent a manner, "f It would be quite unnecessary, in this place, to accumulate the various examples with which the history of the European nations presents us : the enumeration would be endless ; and the established customs of Europe on this subject are sufficiently known. Saint Louis, when at Acra in Palestine, gave a remarkable instance of the protection due to public ministers : an ambassador from the Old Man of the Mountain, or prince of the Assassins, speaking inso- lently to the French monarch, the grand-masters of the orders of the Temple and the Hospital informed that minis- ter, that, " were it not for the respect paid to the character with which he was invested, they would cause him to be thrown into the sea."$ The king, however, dismissed him without suffering the slightest injury to be done him. Never- theless, as the prince of the Assassins was on his own part guilty of grossly violating the most sacred rights of nations, it would have been reasonable to suppose that his ambassa- dor had no claim to protection, except indeed on this single consideration, that, as the privilege of inviolability is founded on the necessity of keeping open a safe channel of commu- nication, through which sovereigns may reciprocally make proposals to each other, and carry on negotiations both in peace and in war, the protection should therefore extend even to the envoys of those princes, who, guilty themselves of violating the law of nations, would otherwise have no title to our respect. gi04. Free There are rights of another nature, which, though not exercise of necessarily annexed to the character of a public minister, religion. are nevertheless allowed to him by established custom in almost every country. One of the principal of these is the free exercise of his religion. It is, indeed, highly proper that a minister, and especially a resident minister, should enjoy the free exercise of his religion within his own house, for himself and his retinue. But it cannot be said that this right, like those of independence and inviolability, is abso- lutely necessary to the success of his commission, particu- larly in the case of a non-resident minister, the only one whom nations are bound to admit ( 66). The minister may ) * Alvakedi's History of the Conquest of Syria, t Ockley's History of the Saracens, vol. i. j Choisy's History of St. Louis. 604 CHAP. VII. IMMUNITIES OF AMBASSADORS, ETC. 484 in this respect, do what he pleases in his own house, into BOOK iv. which nobody has a right to pry or to enter. But, if the sovereign of the country where he resides should, for sub- stantial reasons, refuse him permission to practise his reli- gion in any manner which might render it an object of pub- lic notice, we must not presume to condemn the conduct of that sovereign, much less to accuse him of violating the law of nations. At present, ambassadors are not debarred the free exercise of their religion in any civilized country : for a privilege which is founded on reason cannot be refused when it is attended with no ill consequence. Among those rights that are not necessary to the success 105. Whe- of embassies, there are, on the other hand, some which are ther an a ~ not founded on a general consent of nations, but which are e^pted nevertheless, by the custom of several countries, annexed to f rom all im- the ambassadorial character. Of this number is the ex emp- posts, tion of things brought into or sent out of the country by a foreign minister from the customary duties on importation and exportation. There is no necessity that he should be favoured with any distinction in that respect, since his pay- ment of those duties will not render him the less capable of discharging his functions. If the sovereign is pleased to exempt him from them, it is an instance of civility which the minister could not claim as matter of right, any more than that his baggage, or any chests or packages which he imports from abroad, shall not be searched at the custom-house. Thomas Chaloner, the English ambassador in Spain, sent home a bitter complaint to Queen Elizabeth, his mistress, that the custom-house officers had opened his trunks in order to search them. But the queen returned him for answer, that it was "the duty of an ambassador to wink at every thing which did not directly offend the dignity of his sove- reign."* The independency of the ambassador exempts him indeed from every personal imposition, capitation, or other duty of that nature, and in general from every tax relating to the character of a subject of the state. But as for duties laid on any kind of goods or provisions, the most absolute inde- pendency does not exempt him from the payment of them : + even sovereigns themselves are subject to them. In Holland, the following rule is observed: ambassadors are exempt from the taxes on consumption, doubtless, because those taxes are more directly of a personal nature : but they pay the duties on importation and exportation. However extensive their exemption may be, it is manifest that it solely relates to things intended for their own use. Should they abuse and make a shameful traffic of it by lend- ing their name to merchants, the sovereign has unquestionably * Wicquefort's Ambass. book i. g 28, towards the end. 3A2 605 485 OF RIGHTS, PRIVILEGES, AND BOOK iv. a right to put a stop to the fraud, even by suppressing the CHAP, vii. privilege. Such things have been known in several places; and the sordid avarice of some ministers, who made a trade of their exemption, has obliged the sovereign to deprive them of it. At present, the foreign ministers at Peters- burgh are subject to the duties on importation ; but the empress has the generosity to indemnify them for the loss of a privilege which they had no right to claim, and which, from the frequency of its abuse, she had been obliged to abolish. 106. Obii- But, here it is asked, whether a nation may abolish what gation general custom has established with respect to foreign minis- use^nd n ters ' ^ et ^ ^^ cons ^ er wnat obligation custom and custom received usage can impose on nations, not only in what con- cerns ministers, but also in any other instance, in general. The usages and customs of other nations are no further obli- gatory on an independent state, than as she has expressly or tacitly given her consent to them. But when once a custom, indifferent in itself, has been generally established and re- ceived, it carries the force of an obligation on the states which have tacitly or expressly adopted it. Nevertheless, if, in process of time, any nation perceives that such custom is attended with inconveniences, she is at liberty to declare that she no longer chooses to conform to it : and when once she has made this explicit declaration, no cause of complaint lies against her for refusing thenceforward to observe the custom in question. But such a declaration should be made before- hand, and at the time when it does not affect any particular nation : it is too late to make it when the case actually exists : for it is a maxim universally received, that a law must never be changed at the moment of the actual existence of the particular case to which we would apply it. Thus, on the subject before us, a sovereign who has previously notified his intentions, and received an ambassador only on that footing, is not obliged to allow him the enjoyment of all the privi- leges, or to pay him all the honours, which custom had before annexed to the ambassadorial character, provided that the privileges and honours which are withheld be not essential to the nature of the embassy, and necessary to insure its legiti- mate success. To refuse privileges of this latter kind, would be the same thing in effect as refusing the embassy itself, a conduct which a state is not at liberty to pursue generally and on every occasion ( 65), but in those instances only where the refusal is founded on some very substantial reason To withhold honours which are consecrated by custom and become in a manner essential,, is an expression of contempt, and an actual injury. Here it must be further observed, that, when a sovereign intends to break through an established custom, the rule should be general. To refuse certain customary honours or 606 IMMUNITIES OF AMBASSADORS, ETC. 485 privileges to the ambassador of one nation, and to continue BOOK iv. the enjoyment of them to others, is an affront to that nation, CHAP - Tn - a mark of contempt, or at least of ill-will. Sometimes princes send to each other secret ministers, g ior. A whose character is not public. If a minister of this kind be mmlster insulted by a person unacquainted with his character, such J^" ^ t insult is no violation of the law of nations : but the prince public, who receives this ambassador and knows him to be a public minister, is bound by the same ties of duty towards him as [ 486 ] towards a publicly acknowledged ambassador, and under equal obligation to protect him, and as far as in his power, to insure him the full enjoyment of that inviolability and independence which the law of nations annexes to the am- bassadorial character. No excuse, therefore, can be offered for the conduct of Francis Sforza, duke of Milan, in putting to death Maraviglia, secret minister of Francis the First. Sforza had often treated with that secret agent, and had acknowledged him as the French monarch's minister.* We cannot introduce in any more proper place an im- g 108. A portant question of the law of nations, which is nearly allied sovereign in to the right of embassies. It is asked, what are the rights ^^ n of a sovereign, who happens to be in a foreign country, and c un ry- how the master of the country is to treat him ? If that prince be come to negotiate, or to treat about some public affair, he is doubtless entitled in a more eminent degree to enjoy all the rights of ambassadors. If he be come as a traveller, his dignity alone, and the regard due to the nation which he re- presents and governs, shelters him from all insult, gives him a claim to respect and attention of every kind, and exempts him from all jurisdiction. On his making himself known, he cannot be treated as subject to the common laws ; for it is not to be presumed that he has consented to such a subjec- tion : and if a prince will not suffer him in his dominions on that footing, he should give him notice of his intentions. But, if the foreign prince forms any plot against the safety and welfare of the state, in a word, if he acts as an enemy, he may very justly be treated as such. In every other case he is entitled to full security, since even a private indi- vidual of a foreign nation has a right to expect it. A ridiculous notion has possessed the minds even of per- sons who deem themselves superior in understanding to the common herd of mankind. They think that a sovereign who enters a foreign country without permission, may be arrested there. f But on what reason can such an act of violence be * See the Memoirs of Martin Du Gramond's Hist. Gall. lib. xii. The Bellay, book iv., and Father Daniel's Cardinal De Richelieu also alleged History of France, vol. v. p. 300, this trifling reason, when he gave at * east * n suc ^ cases as ^ ave ar ^ sen during the time ciu juris- f his embassy ; and, in support of their opinion, they allege diction of that this subjection is by no means derogatory to the am- the country bassadorial character: "for," say they, "however sacred a w ^ e be person may be, his inviolability is not affected by suing him in a civil action." But it is not on account of the sacred- ness of their person that ambassadors cannot be sued : it is because they are independent of the jurisdiction of the coun- try to which they are sent ; and the substantial reasons on which that independency is grounded may be seen in a pre- ceding part of this work ( 92). Let us here add, that it is in every respect highly proper, and even necessary, that an ambassador should be exempt from judicial prosecution even in civil causes, in order that he may be free from molestation in the exercise of his functions. For a similar reason, it was not allowed, among the Romans, to summon a priest while [ 489 ] he was employed in his sacred offices :* but at other times he was open to the law. The reason which we have here alleged for the exemption is also assigned in the Roman law : "Ideo enim non datur actio (adversus legatum) ne ab officio suscepto legationis avocetur^ ne impediatur legatio^" But there was an exception as to those transactions which had taken place during the embassy. This was reasonable with regard to those legati, or ministers, of whom the Roman law here speaks, who, being sent only by nations subject to the empire, could not lay claim to the independency enjoyed by a foreign minister. As they were subjects of the state, the legislature was at liberty to establish whatever regulations it thought most proper respecting them: but a sovereign has not the like power of obliging the minister of another sove- reign to submit to his jurisdiction : and even if such power was vested in him by convention, or otherwise, the exercise of it would be highly improper : because, under that pretext, the ambassador might be often molested in his ministry, and the state involved in very disagreeable quarrels, for the tri- fling concerns of some private individuals, who might and ought to have taken better precautions for their own security. It is, therefore, only in conformity to the mutual duties * Nee pontificem (in jus vocari f Digest lib. v. tit 1, de Judiciia, oportet) dum sacra facit Digest, lib. Ac. leg. 24, 2. ii. tit 4. De in Jus vocando, leg. 2. \ Ibid. leg. xxvi. 010 IN CIVIL CASES. 489 which states owe to each other, and in accordance with the BOOK nr. grand principles of the law of nations, that an ambassador CHAP - YIir -_ or public minister is at present, by the universal custom and consent of nations, independent of all jurisdiction in the country where he resides, either in civil or criminal cases. I know there have occurred some instances to the contrary ; but a few facts do not establish a custom : on the contrary, those to which I allude, only contribute, by the censure passed on them, to prove the custom such as I have asserted it to be. In the year 1668, the Portuguese resident at the Hague was, by an order of the court of justice, arrested and imprisoned for debt. But an illustrious member of the same court* very justly thinks that the procedure was unjustifiable, and contrary to the law of nations. In the year 1657, a resident of the elector of Brandenburg was also arrested for debt in England. But he was set at liberty, as having been illegally arrested ; and even the creditors and officers of jus- tice who had offered him that insult were punished, f But if an ambassador chooses to renounce a part of his m. How independency, and to subject himself in civil affairs to the hema 7 vo ~ jurisdiction of the country, he is undoubtedly at Wberty to do so, provided it be done with his master's consent. g e if to it Without such consent, the ambassador has no right to re- nounce privileges in which the dignity and service of his sovereign are concerned, which are founded on the master's rights, and instituted for his advantage, not for that of the [ 490 ] minister. It is true, indeed, that the ambassador, without waiting for his sovereign's permission, acknowledges the jurisdiction of the country when he commences a suit as plaintiff in a court of justice. But the consequence, in that case, is inevitable ; and besides, in a civil cause, on a point of private interest, no inconvenience attends it ; since the ambassador has it at all times in his power to avoid com- mencing a suit, or may, if such a step be necessary, intrust the prosecution of his cause to an attorney or lawyer. Let us here add, by the way, that an ambassador ought never to institute a prosecution on a criminal charge. If he has been insulted, he should make his complaint to the sovereign ; and the delinquent is to be prosecuted by the public. It may happen that the minister of a foreign power is at 112. A the same time a subject of the state where he is employed ; "j^J 6 * and in this case, as a subject, he is unquestionably under ^ject'of the jurisdiction of the country in every thing which does not the state directly relate to his ministry. But the question is, to de- where ho is . employed. * M. de Bynkershoek's Competent his creditors, and refused a passport by Judge of Ambassadors, chap. xiii. 1. the French court. See Journal Poli- f Ibid. It is not long since the world tique de Bouillon, Feb. 1, 1771, p. 54, witnessed the circumstance of a foreign and Jan. 15, p. 57. minister in France being pursued by 611 490 OF THE JUDGE OF AMBASSADORS BOOK iv. termine in what cases those two characters, of subject and CHA *;, VI11 -,. foreign minister, are united in the same person. To produce such union, it is not sufficient that the minister was born a subject of the state to which he is sent ; for unless the laws expressly prohibit every citizen to leave his country, he may legally have renounced his country, and placed himself in subjection to a new master. He may, likewise, without re- nouncing his country for ever, become independent of it during the whole time that he spends in the service of a foreign prince ; and the presumption is certainly in favour of such independency : for the state and functions of a pub- lic minister naturally require that he should depend only on his master ( 92), on the prince who has intrusted him with the management of his affairs. Whenever, therefore, there does not exist any circumstance which furnishes a proof or indication to the contrary, a foreign minister, though ante- cedently a subject of the state, is reputed to be absolutely independent of it during the whole time of his commission. If his former sovereign does not choose to allow him such independency in his dominions, he may refuse to admit him in the character of a foreign minister, as is the practice in France, where, according to Monsieur De Callieres, "the king no longer receives any of his own subjects as ministers of foreign princes."* But a subject of the state may still continue its subject, notwithstanding his acceptance of a commission from a fo- reign prince. His subjection is expressly established when the sovereign acknowledges him as minister only, with a reserve that he shall remain a subject of the state. The states-general of the United Provinces, in a decree of the [ 491 ] 19th of June, 1681, declare, " That no subject of the state shall be received as ambassador or minister of another power, but on condition that he shall not divest himself of his cha- racter of subject, even with regard to jurisdiction both in civil and criminal affairs, and that whoever, in making himself known as ambassador or minister, has not mentioned his quality of subject of the state, shall not enjoy those rights or privileges which peculiarly belong to the ministers of foreign power s."f Such a minister may likewise retain his former subjection tacitly ; and then, by a natural consequence, drawn from his actions, state, and whole behaviour, it is known that he con- tinues a subject. Thus, independent of the declaration above mentioned, those Dutch merchants who obtain the title of residents of certain foreign princes, and nevertheless continue to carry on their commerce, thereby sufficiently denote that they remain subjects. Whatever inconveniences may attend * Manner of Negotiating with Sovereigns, chap. vi. t Bynkershoek, ubi supra, chap. x ; 612 IN CIVIL CASES. 491 the subjection of a minister to the sovereign with whom he BOOK iv. resides, if the foreign prince chooses to acquiesce in such a cnAP ' Ym '. state of things, and is content to have a minister on that footing, it is his own concern ; and should his minister, on any ignominious occasion, be treated as a subject, he has no cause of complaint. It may likewise happen that a foreign minister shall become a subject of the sovereign to whom he is sent, by accepting of a post under him : and in this case he cannot lay claim to independence, except in such things alone as directly re- late to his ministry. The prince by whom he is delegated, in allowing of this voluntary subjection, agrees to risk the inconveniences that attend it. Thus, in the last century, the baron De Charnace' and the count D'Estrades were ambas- sadors from France to the States General, and at the same time officers in their high mightinesses' army. The independency of a public minister is the true reason us. Im- of his exemption from the jurisdiction of the country in munit 7 f which he resides. No legal process can be directly issued th< ; mini f er , , . , , . e , r ,. . ,, ,. ..* f , extends to against him, because he is not subject to the authority of the Ua pro . prince or the magistrates. But it is asked whether thatperty. exemption of his person extends indiscriminately to all his property ? In order to solve this question, we must consider by what circumstances property may be subjected to, and by what others it may be exempted from, the jurisdiction of a country. In general, whatever lies within the extent of a country, is subject to the authority and jurisdiction of the sovereign (Book I. 205, and Book II. 83, 84). If any dispute arises concerning effects or goods within or passing through the country, it is to be decided by the judge of the place. In virtue of this dependence, the mode of stoppage or seizure has been established in many countries, for the purpose of compelling a foreigner to repair to the spot where the seizure has been made, and there to answer questions that are to be put to him, though not directly relating to the [ 492 ] effects seized. But a foreign minister, as we have already shown, is independent of the jurisdiction of the country ; and his personal independence in civil cases would be of little avail, unless it extended te every thing which he finds necessary in order to enable him to live with dignity, and quietly to attend to the discharge of his functions. Besides, whatever he has brought with him, or purchased for his own use as minister, is so connected with his person as to partake of the same fate with it. Since the minister entered the territory on the footing of independence, he could not have it in contemplation to subject his retinue, his baggage, or his necessaries, to the jurisdiction of the country. Every thing, therefore, which directly belongs to his person in the character of a public minister, every thing which is intend- ed for his use, or which serves for his own maintenance and SB 613 492 OF THE JUDGE OF AMBASSADORS. BOOK iv. that of his household, every thing of that kind, I say, CHAP, vnr. p ar takes of the minister's independency, and is absolutely exempt from all jurisdiction in the country. Those things, together with the person to whom they belong, are consi- dered as being out of the country. 114. The But this exemption cannot e v xtend to such property as QnofcT ev *dently belongs to the ambassador under any other rela- tendtoef- ^ on ^ &n that of minister. What has no affinity with his fectsbe- functions and character cannot partake of the privileges longing to which are solely derived from his functions and character. the 7 Sister Should a minister, therefore, (as it has often been the case,) may carry embark in any branch of commerce, all the effects, goods, on; money, and debts, active and passive, which are connected with his mercantile concerns, and likewise all contests and lawsuits to which they may give rise, fall under the juris- diction of the country. And although, in consequence of the minister's independency, no legal process can, in those lawsuits, be directly issued against his person, he is, never- theless, by the seizure of the effects belonging to his com- merce, indirectly compelled to plead in his own defence. The abuses which would arise from a contrary practice are evident. What could be expected from a merchant vested with a privilege to commit every kind of injustice in a foreign country ? There exists not a shadow of reason for extend- ing the ministerial immunity to things of that nature. If the sovereign who sends a minister is apprehensive of any inconvenience from the indirect dependency in which his servant thus becomes involved, he has only to lay on him his injunctions against engaging in commerce, an occupation, indeed, which ill accords with the dignity of the ministerial character. To what we have said, let us add two illustrations : 1. In doubtful cases, the respect due to the ministerial cha- racter requires that things should always be explained to the advantage of that character. I mean that, when there is room for doubt whether a thing be really intended for the use of the minister and his household, or whether it belongs to his commerce, the decision must be given in favour of the minister: otherwise there would be a risk of violating his privileges. 2. When I say that we may seize such of the [ 493 ] minister's effects as have no relation to his public character, particularly those that belong to his commercial concerns, this is to be understood only on the supposition that the seizure be not made for any cause arising from his transac- tions in quality of minister, as, for instance, articles supplied for the use of his family, house-rent, etc., because any claims which may lie against him in that relation cannot be decided in the country, and consequently cannot be subjected to its jurisdiction by the indirect mode of seizure. 614 IN CIVIL CASES. 493 All landed estates, all immovable property, by whomsoever BOOK iv. possessed, are subject to the jurisdiction of the country CHAF " Tm - (Book I. 205, and Book II. 83, 84). Are they to be $ us. nor exempted from it on the single ground that their owner has * i 1111110 ^- been appointed ambassador by a foreign power? There can able , p . p ! r ~ rr *., -i T . ty which he exist no reason for the exemption in such case. It is not in possesses in his public character that the ambassador possesses that pro- the country, perty ; nor is it attached to his person, so as, like himself, to ( 201 ) be reputed out of the territory. If the foreign prince appre- hends any ill consequences from that state of dependency in which his minister may stand on account of some of his pos- sessions, he may make choice of another person to fill the office. Let us conclude, therefore, that immovable property possessed by a foreign minister does not change its nature in consequence of the character conferred on the owner, but con- tinues subject to the jurisdiction of the state in which it lies. All contests and lawsuits concerning that property are to be carried before the tribunals of the country ; and those same tribunals may decree its seizure in order to satisfy any legal claim. It is, however, easily conceived, that, if the ambas- sador lives in a house of his own, that house is excepted from the rule, as actually serving for his immediate use ; it is excepted, I mean, in whatever may affect the present use which the ambassador makes of it. (201) It may be seen, in Monsieur de Bynkershoek's treatise,* that custom coincides with the principles laid down in this and the preceding sections. In suing an ambassador in either of the two cases just mentioned, that is to say, on the subject of any immovable property lying in the country, or of movable effects which have no connection with the embassy, the ambassador is to be summoned in the same manner as an absent person, since he is reputed to be out of the country, and his independency does not permit any im- mediate address to his person in an authoritative manner, such as sending an officer of a court of justice to him. By what mode, then, may satisfaction be obtained of an g lie. How ambassador who refuses to do justice to those who have deal- justice may ings with him ? It is asserted by many that he must be be btamed sued before the tribunal to whose jurisdiction he was subject ambassador, antecedently to his appointment as ambassador. In this there appears to me an impropriety. If the necessity and importance of his functions set him above all prosecution in the foreign country where he resides, shall any man be allowed to molest him in the performance of his ministerial [ 494 ] duties by summoning him to appear before the tribunals of his own country ? The interest of the public service forbids (201) As to this point, and the exemption from a distress, see Novella v. Toogood, 1 Barn. A Cress. 554-2 ; Dowl. & Ry. 833, S. C. C. * On the competent Judge of Ambassadors, chap. xvi. 6. 615 494 OF THE AMBASSADOR'S HOUSE. BOOK IT. such a procedure. It is absolutely necessary that the minis- CHAP. YIII. j. er ghoui^ solely depend on his sovereign, to whom he be- longs in a peculiar manner. He is an instrument in the hand of the conductor of the nation ; and no circumstance whatever ought to be permitted to divert or obstruct his ser- vices. Neither would it be just that the absence of a person who is intrusted with the interests of the sovereign and the nation should prove detrimental to him in his private con- cerns. In all countries, those who are absent on the service of the state enjoy privileges which secure them from the in- conveniences attendant on the state of absentees. But these privileges of the ministers of the state should, as far as pos- sible, be so modelled and tempered as not to be unreasonably burdensome or injurious to private persons who have dealings with them. How then arc those different interests the ser- vice of the state and the administration of justice to be re- conciled ? All private persons, whether citizens or foreign- ers, who have any demands against a minister if they can- not obtain satisfaction from himself should apply to his master, who is obliged to do them justice in such manner as may be most consistent with the public service. It rests with the prince to determine whether it be most proper to recall his minister, to appoint a tribunal before which he may be sued, or to order an adjournment of the cause, &c. In a word, the good of the state does not allow that any person whatever should have it in his power to disturb the minister in his functions, or to divert his attention from them without the sovereign's permission; and the sovereign, whose duty it is to distribute impartial and universal justice, ought not to countenance his minister in refusing it or wearying out his adversaries by unjust delays. CHAP. IX. CHAP. IX OF THE AMBASSADOR'S HOUSE AND DOMESTICS. g 117. The THE independency of the ambassador would be very im- ambasaa- perfect, and his security very precarious, if the house in (202* h e ' w ^ c ^ ke lives were not to enjoy a perfect immunity, and to be inaccessible to the ordinary officers of justice. The am- bassador might be molested under a thousand pretexts ; his secrets might be discovered by searching his papers, and his (262) How far exempt from a dis- lord of a house tenanted by an am- tress, see Novello y. Toogood, 1 Barn, bassador to tho payment of poor-rates A Cres. 554, 2 Dowl. & R. 833, S. C. and taxes. a Modern acts usually subject the laad- 616 AND DOMESTICS. 494 person exposed to insults. Thus, all the reasons which es- BOOK IT. tablish his independence and inviolability, concur likewise in CHAP - " . securing the freedom of his house. In all civilized nations, this right is acknowledged as annexed to the ambassadorial character ; and an ambassador's house, at least in all the ordinary affairs of life, is, equally with his person, considered as being out of the country. Of this, a remarkable instance occurred, not many years ago, at Petersburgh. On the 3d of April, 1752, thirty soldiers, with an officer at their head, entered the house of baron Greiffenheim, the Swedish minis- [ 495 ] ter, and carried off two of his domestics, whom they con- ducted to prison, under a pretence that those two men had clandestinely sold liquors, which the imperial farm alone has the privilege of selling. The court, incensed at such a pro- ceeding, caused the authors of this act of violence to be im- mediately taken into custody, and the empress ordered satis- faction to be made to the offended minister; she likewise sent to him and to all the other foreign ministers, a declara- tion, in which she expressed her concern and resentment at what had happened, and communicated the orders which she had given to the senate to institute a prosecution against the commissioner of the office established for the prevention of the clandestine sale of liquors, he being the chief delin- quent. The house of an ambassador ought to be safe from all out- rage, being under the particular protection of the law of nations, and that of the country ; to insult it, is a crime both against the state and against all other nations. But the immunity and freedom of the ambassador's house us. Right is established only in favour of the minister and his house- of asylum, hold ; as is evident from the very reasons upon which it is grounded. Can he take advantage of the privilege, in order to convert his house into an asylum, to afford shelter and protection to the enemies of the prince, and to malefactors of every kind, and thus screen them from the punishments which they have deserved ? Such proceedings would be con- trary to all the duties of an ambassador, to the spirit by which he ought to be animated, and to the lawful purposes for which he has been admitted into the country. This is what nobody will presume to deny. But I proceed further, and lay it down as a certain truth, that a sovereign is not obliged to tolerate an abuse so pernicious to his state, and so detrimental to society. I grant, indeed, that when there is question only of certain ordinary transgressions, and these committed by persons who often prove to be rather unfortu- nate than criminal, or whose punishment is of no great im- portance to the peace of society, the house of an ambassador may well serve as an asylum for such offenders ; and it is better that the sovereign should suffer them to escape, than expose the ambassador to frequent molestation under pre- ?S 3 B 2 617 495 OF THE AMBASSADORS' HOUSE. BOOK iv. tence of a search after them, and thus involve the state in CHAP, ix. anv difficulty which might arise from such proceedings. And as the house of an ambassador is independent of the ordinary jurisdiction, no magistrate, justice of the peace, or other subordinate officer, is in any case entitled to enter it by his own authority, or to send any of his people to enter it, unless on occasions of urgent necessity, when the public welfare is threatened with imminent danger which admits of no delay. Whatever concerns a point of such weight and delicacy, whatever affects the rights and the dignity of a foreign power, whatever may embroil the state with that power, is to be laid immediately before the sovereign, and to be determined either by himself in person, or, under his f 496] direction, by the privy council. Thus, it belongs to the sove- reign to decide, on occasion, how far the right of asylum, which an ambassador claims as belonging to his house, is to be respected : and if the question relates to an offender whose arrest or punishment is of great importance to the state, the prince is not to be withheld by the consideration of a privi- lege which was never granted for the detriment and ruin of states. In the year 1726, the famous duke de Ripperda having sheltered himself in the house of lord Harrington, am- bassador from England, the council of Castile decided "that he might be taken out of it, even by force ; since, otherwise, those regulations which had been made for the purpose of maintaining a more regular and intimate correspondence be- tween sovereigns would, on the contrary, operate to the sub- version and utter ruin of their authority ; and that, if per- sons who had been intrusted with the finances, the power, and the secrets of the state, were, when guilty of violating the duties of their office, allowed to take shelter under a pri- vilege which had been granted to the houses of ambassadors in favour only of ordinary offenders, such an extension of the right of asylum would be productive of consequences the most pernicious and detrimental to all the powers on earth, who, if the practice once became established, would be re- duced to the necessity, not only of enduring the presence of every man who was plotting their destruction, but even of seeing him supported in their own court."* Nothing could be said on this head with greater truth and judgment. The abuse of the privilege has nowhere been carried to a greater extent than at Rome, where the ambassadors of crowned heads claim it for the whole ward in which their house is situated. The popes, once so formidable to sove- reigns, have for above two centuries been in their turn under a necessity of observing the most delicate and cautious cir- cumspection in their conduct towards them. It is in vain that they have endeavoured to suppress, or at least to reduce * Memoirs of the Abb6 De Montgon, vol. 1. 618 AND DOMESTICS. 496 within proper bounds, an abusive privilege, for which, pre- BOOK rv. scription, however great its antiquity, ought not to be CHAP ' IX< allowed as a sufficient plea in opposition to justice and reason. An ambassador's carriages and equipages are equally pri- g 119. Ex- vileged with his house, and for the same reasons : to insult emption of them is an attack on the ambassador himself, and on the *" ambassa - sovereign whom he represents. They are independent of all &&* subordinate authority of guards, custom-house officers, ma- gistrates and their agents, and must not be stopped or searched without a superior order. But in this instance, as in that of the ambassador's house, the abuse is not to be con- founded with the right. It would be absurd that a foreign minister should have the power of conveying off in his coach a criminal of consequence, a man, in the seizure of whose person the state were highly interested ; and that he should do this under the very eyes of the sovereign, who thus would see himself defied in his own kingdom and court. Where is the sovereign who would suffer this ? The marquis de Fon- tenay, the French ambassador at Rome, sheltered the Neapo- litan exiles and rebels, and at last undertook to convey them out of Rome in his own carriages : but the carriages were stopped at the city gates by some Corsicans of the pope's [ 497 ] guard, and the Neapolitans committed to prison. The am- bassador warmly complained of the procedure : but the pope answered " that his motive had only been that of arresting men whom the ambassador had assisted in escaping from con- finement ; and that, since the ambassador took the liberty of harbouring villains, and affording protection to every criminal in the papal territory, at least he, who was sovereign of the state, ought to be allowed to have them retaken wherever they could be found ; as the rights and privileges of ambas- sadors were not to be carried to such lengths." The ambas- sador replied, "that it would not appear, on examination, that he had granted an asylum to any subjects of the pope, but solely to some Neapolitans, whom he might very lawfully shelter from the persecutions of the Spaniards."* By this answer, the minister tacitly conceded that he would not have been authorized to complain of the stoppage of his carriages, if he had employed them for the purpose of favouring the escape of any of the pope's subjects, and aiding criminals to elude the pursuit of justice. The persons in an ambassador's retinue partake of his ? 120. of inviolability ; his independency extends to every individual his retinn of his household: so intimate a connection exists between ( 203 )' him and all those persons, that they share the same fate with * See Wicquefort's Ambassador, book Anne, c. 12 ; and see cases, Chitty's Col. i. g 28, towards the end. Stat 13; 13 Price Rep. 805. C. (203) Privileged from an arrest, 7 619 497 OF THE AMBASSADOR'S HOUSE BOOK iv. him ; they immediately depend on him alone, and are exempt CHAP, ix. f rom ^g jurisdiction of the country, into which they would not have come without such reservation in their favour. The ambassador is bound to protect them ; and no insult can be offered to them, which is not at the same time an insult to himself. If the domestics and household of a foreign minis- ter were not solely dependent "on him, it is evident at first sight, how easily he might be harassed, molested, and dis- turbed in the exercise of his functions. These maxims are at present everywhere adopted and confirmed by custom, g 121. of his The ambassador's wife is intimately united with him, and wife and m0 re particularly belongs to him than any other person of his household. Accordingly, she participates in his inde- pendence and inviolability; she even receives distinguished honours, which, in a certain degree, cannot be refused to her without affronting the ambassador; and for which there exists, in the generality of courts, an established ceremonial. The respect due to the ambassador extends likewise to his children, who also partake of his immunities. $ 122. of the The ambassador's secretary is one of his domestics : but secretary of the secretary of the embassy holds his commission from the bass* 3 sovereign himself; which makes him a kind of public minis- ter, enjoying in his own right the protection of the law of [ 498 ] nations, and the immunities annexed to his office, independ- ently of the ambassador, to whose orders he is indeed but imperfectly subjected, sometimes not at all, and always in such degree only as their common master has been pleased to ordain. 123. of Couriers sent or received by an ambassador, his papers, the ambas- letters, and despatches, all essentially belong to the embassy, sador's cou- an( j are consequently to be held sacred ; since, if they were despatches no * res P ec ted, the legitimate objects of the embassy could not be attained, nor would the ambassador be able to dis- charge his functions with the necessary degree of security. The states-general of the United Provinces decided, while the president Jeannin resided with them as ambassador from France, that, to open the letters of a public minister is a breach of the law of nations.* Other instances may be seen in Wicquefort. That privilege, however, does not on cer- tain momentous occasions, when the ambassador himself has violated the law of nations, by forming or countenancing plots or conspiracies against the state deprive us of the liberty to seize his papers for the purpose of discovering the whole secret, and detecting his accomplices ; since, in such an emergency, the ambassador himself may lawfully be arrested and interrogated ( 99). An example is furnished us in the conduct of the Roman government, who seized the letters * Wicquefort, book L \ 27. 620 AND DOMESTICS. 498 which a treasonable junto had committed to the hands of BOOK rv. Tarquin's ambassadors ( The persons in a foreign minister's retinue, being inde- \ 124. The pendent of the jurisdiction of the country, cannot be taken J^* 8 * 1 ^ into custody or punished without his consent. It would, ri y s ov e r " nevertheless, be highly improper that they should enjoy an bis retinue, absolute independence, and be at liberty to indulge in every kind of licentious disorder, without control or apprehension. The ambassador must necessarily be supposed to possess whatever degree of authority is requisite for keeping them in order :* and some writers will have that authority to include even a power over life and death. When the marquis de R6ny, afterwards duke De Sully, was in England as ambas- sador extraordinary from France, a gentleman of his retinue committed a murder, which caused a great noise among the people of London. The ambassador assembled some French noblemen who had accompanied him on his mission, tried the murderer, and sentenced him to lose his head. He then ac- quainted the lord mayor of London that he had pronounced sentence on the criminal, desiring that magistrate to furnish him with an executioner and proper attendants to have the punishment inflicted. But he afterwards consented to de- liver up the criminal to the English, in order that they might [ 499 ] execute justice on him as they thought proper : and Monsieur De Beaumont, the French ambassador in ordinary, prevailed on the British monarch to pardon the young man, who was related to that minister by the ties of consanguinity, f It rests entirely at the option of the sovereign to invest his am- bassador with such an extensive power over the persons of his suite : and the marquis de Kony was confidently certain of having his conduct approved by his master, who did, in fact, express his approbation of the whole transaction. In gene- ral, however, it is to be presumed that the ambassador is possessed only of a coercive power sufficient to restrain his dependants, by other punishments which are not of a capital or infamous nature. He may punish the faults committed against himself and against his master's service, or send the delinquents to their sovereign, in order to their being pun- ished. But should any of his people commit crimes against society, which deserve a severe punishment, the ambassador * It is his duty to watch over their mediate an accommodation between conduct, and to exert his authority in Charles I. and his parliament, several order to prevent them from transgress- gentlemen of that minister's suite re- ing the bounds of their station, and paired to the royal army, and fought committing actions which may give against the parliamentarians ; on which just offence to the sovereign at whose account the parliament immediately court he resides, an event which may declined all further negotiation with sometimes be productive of very se- the count De Harcourt. Duport's Hist. rious and disagreeable consequences, of Conspir. vol. iv. p. 261. Edit. A. D. The French court having sent the 1729. count De Harcourt to England to ( Bully's Memoirs, vol. vi. chap. i. 621 499 OF THE AMBASSADOR'S HOUSE BOOK iv. ought to make a distinction between such of his domestics as CHAP> IX> belong to his own nation, and others who are subjects of the country where he resides. The shortest and most natural way with the latter, is to dismiss them from his service, and deliver them up to justice. As to those of his own nation, if they have offended the sovereign of the country, or committed any of those atrocious crimes in whose punishment all nations are interested, and whose perpetrators are, for that reason, usually surrendered by one state when demanded by an- other, why should he not give them up to the nation which calls for their punishment ? If the transgression be of a dif- ferent kind, he is to send them to his sovereign. Finally, if the case be of a doubtful nature, it is the ambassador's duty to keep the offender in irons till he receives orders from his court. But if he passes a capital sentence on the criminal, I do not think he can have it executed in his own house; an execution of that nature being an act of territorial superiority which belongs only to the sovereign of the country. And although the ambassador, together with his house and house- hold, be reputed out of the country, that is nothing more than a figurative mode of speech intended to express his in- dependency, and all the rights necessary to the lawful suc- cess of the embassy : nor can that fiction involve privileges which are reserved to the sovereign alone, which are of too delicate and important a nature to be communicated to a fo- reigner, and, moreover, not necessary to the ambassador for the due discharge of his functions. If the offence has been committed against the ambassador or against the service of his master, the ambassador may send the delinquent to his sovereign. If the crime concerns the state where the minis- ter resides, he may try the criminal, and, if he finds him [ 500 ] worthy of death, deliver him up to the justice of the country, as did the marquis de R6ny. 1 125. When When the commission of an ambassador is at an end, the rights wnen ne has concluded the business for which he came into bLsadoi- 1 ' ^6 coun t r y > when he is recalled or dismissed, in a word, expire. when he is obliged to depart on any account whatever, his functions cease : but his privileges and rights do not imme- diately expire : he retains them till his return to his sove- reign, to whom he is to make a report of his embassy.* His safety, his independence, and his inviolability are not less necessary to the success of the embassy in his return, than at his coming. Accordingly, when an ambassador departs on account of a war arising between his master and the sove- reign at whose court he was employed, he is allowed a suffi- * " It was at that time," says Join- them happened to die, the ambassadors Tille, "an established custom, as well in whom they had mutually sent to each pagan as in Christian countries, that, other remained prisoners and slaves." when two princes were at war, if one of p. 72, edit. A. D. 1797. 622 AND DOMESTICS. 500 cient time to quit the country in perfect security : and, BOOK iv. moreover, if he was returning home by sea, and happened to CHAP - "_ be taken on his passage, he would be released without a mo- ment's hesitation, as not being subject to lawful capture. For the same reasons, the ambassador's privileges still 126. Cases exist at those times when the activity of his ministry happens when n f w to be suspended, and he stands in need of fresh powers. credentials Such a case occurs in consequence of the death of the prince l^ whom the minister represents, or of the sovereign at whose court he resides. On either occasion it becomes necessary that the minister should be furnished with new credentials. The necessity, however, is less cogent in the latter than in the former case, especially if the successor of the deceased prince be the natural and necessary successor; because, while the authority whence the minister's power emanated still subsists, it is fairly presumable that he retains his for- mer character at the court of the new sovereign. But if his own master is no more, the minister's powers are at an end ; and he must necessarily receive fresh credentials from the new prince, before he can be authorized to speak and act in his name. In the interim, however, he still continues to be the minister of his nation, and, as such, is entitled to enjoy all the rights and honours annexed to that character. At length, I have reached the end of my proposed career, g 127. Con- I do not flatter myself with the idea of having given a per- elusion, feet, full, and complete treatise of the law of nations ; nor was that, indeed, my design ; for it would have been too great a degree of confidence in my own abilities to have made such an attempt on a subject so extensive and so co- pious. I shall think I have done a great deal, if my princi- ples are approved as solid, luminous, and sufficient to enable intelligent persons to give a proper solution on any minute questions that may arise in particular cases ; and shall be happy if the result of my labours proves in anywise service- able to those men in power who love mankind and respect justice, and furnishes them with weapons for the purpose of defending the cause of right, and compelling the unjust to observe at least some measures, and to keep within the bounds of decency. 623 INDEX. ABSENCE. See COUNTRY. of the right of individuals to quit their country, 103, f things not included therein, ib. does not extend to things having no re- lation to the war, ib. as debts contracted with individuals, ib. or to movables, Ac., ib. former treaties, mentioned and confirmed in the new, are part of it, 440. Of the execution of those treaties, 440 to 443. when the obligation of the treaty com- mences, 440. publication of peace, ib. should bo without delay, ib. when may be postponed, 440, 441. time of the execution thereof, 441. lawful excuse for delay, ib. promise void when party has hindered the performance of it, ib. cessation of contributions, 442. products of the things ceded or restored, ib. in what condition to be restored, ib. import of word restitution, ib. instances, 442, 443. Interpretation of treaty of peace, 443. 1. where doubtful, against the pre- scriber thereof, ib. 2. names of ceded countries, ib. how to be understood, ib. 3. restoration not to be understood of those who have voluntarily given themselves up, 444. Of the observance and breach thereof, ib. binds the nation and successors, ib. to be faithfully observed, ib. plea of fear or force does not dispense with its observance, ib. breach of what, 446. 1 ways in which it may be broken, ib. may be violated in three ways, 446 to 450. 1. by conduct contrary to the nature thereof, 446. to take up arms for a fresh cause, no breach, ib. nor is a subsequent alliance with an enemy a breach, 447. distinction to be made between a new war and a breach of treaty, ib. JHstiflable defence no breach of treaty, 44S. causes of rupture on account of allies, 449. 2. by conduct contrary to its par- ticular nature, ib. instances herein, ib. 3. by violation of any article, ib. violation of a single article breaks the whole treaty, 450. no distinction between more and less important articles, 449. PEACE (continued). of penalty annexed to the violation of an article, 450. studied delays, their effect, ib. of insurmountable difficulties, ib. when time must be allowed, 450, 451. or indemnity given, 451. preferable to recourse to arms, ib. instruction of treaty by subjects, ib. distinction, if not imputable to sovereign, ib. the treaty not broken by, ib. of infraction by allies, ib. right of offended party against violator of treaty, 452. optional to declare treaty null, or allow it to subsist, ib. PIETY. See RELIGION. meaning of, 55. its influence on happiness of nation, ib. nation ought therefore to be pious, ib. should be attended with knowledge, ib. consequences of want of, 55, 56. POISON, use of, in warfare condemned as odious, 360. not to be adopted by way of reprisal, ib. of poisoning prisoners, 358, 360, 361. use of poisoned weapons condemned, 361. so, of poisoning springs, ib. POLICE. See JUSTICE AND POLITY. POLITICAL EQUILIBRIUM. See WAR. what, 312. POPE. See POPERY. POPERY, Abuses of, particularized, 66. 1. power of the popes, ib. extent thereof, 66, 67. whence it arises, 67. effect of, in a foreign court, ib. instances, 65 to 67. 2. important employments conferred by a foreign power, 68. disposal of ecclesiastical dignities, ib. practice hereof a violation of nation's right, ib. nations submitting to, condemned, ib. 3. powerful subjects depending on a foreign court, 68, 69. abuse in this respect, 69. 4. the celibacy of the priests, ib. for what cause invented, ib. practice of, condemned, 69, 70. of convents, ib. marriage advocated, 70. 5. enormous pretensions of the clergy, ib. their pre-eminency, ib. its prejudice on good order, ib. INDEX. 643 POPERY (continued). 6. independence of, 71. immunities, ib. their attempt to escape from political authority, t'6. claim their immunities from God, ib. 7. immunities of church possessions, 72, 73. same immunity claimed for pos- sessions of the church, 72. when state may exempt them, ib. should be first taken for the use and safety of the state, 73. limit of exemption, 72. 8. excommunication of men in office, 73. 9. and of sovereigns themselves, 74. instances of abuse, ib. but abuses not confined to popes, ib. instance, 74, 75, in note. 10. the clergy drawing every thing to themselves, and disturbing the order of justice, 75, 76. 11. money drawn to Rome, 76. their rapacity herein, ruinous to the court of Rome, ib. 12. laws and customs contrary to the welfare of states, t'6. consequence of trusting same to the clergy, t6. its pernicious effect on the state, ib. POPULAR GOVERNMENT. See GO- VERNMENT. what, 2. empire kept by state in its own hands, 2. also called a democracy, ib. PORTS. See SEA. to whom belonging, 129. enemy pursuing ship into neutral port must refrain from hostilities there, 344, n. POSITIVE LAW, what, Ixiv., Ixvi., Ixvii., and notes, proceeds from the will of nations, 66. is of three kinds, Ixvi. 1. voluntary, what, t'6. 2. customary, what, t'6. 3. conventional, what, t'6. the two latter called the arbitrary law of nations, Ixvi. POSTLIMINIUM. See Jus POSTLIMINIUH. PREROGATIVES OF THE CROWN, what, 15. with respect to coin, 46. See COIN. in matters of religion, 62. See RELIGION. with regard to public property, 112. See PROPERTY. as to pardoning offenders, 83. See PARDON. PRESCRIPTION, of usucaption and prescription, 187, and note. definition of, 187, &c. is derived from the law of nature, 187. what foundation required for ordinary prescription, 189. of immemorial prescription, t'6. claimant alleging reasons for his silence, 190. proprietor showing he does not intend to abandon his right, t'6. prescription founded on the actions of the proprietor, 16. usucaption and prescription take place between nations, t'6. more difficult between nations to found them on a presumptive desertion, 190, 191. other principles that enforce prescription, 191. effects of voluntary law of nations on this subject, 191, 192. law of treaties or customs herein, 192. nations should adopt rules on this sub- ject, ib. exclusive right to, not acquired by pre- scription, 127. right may be acquired by treaty, 126. PRETEXTS, what, 304, 306. See WAR. PRISONERS OF WAR. See WAR. right of making, 353. are not to be put to death, 348, 354. how to be treated, 354. may be confined and fettered, t'6. but not to be treated harshly, t'6. unless guilty of crime, t6. are seldom ill-treated by European na- tions, t'6. of releasing them on parole, 355. whether prisoners who cannot be fed, &c., may be put to death, t6. should be dismissed on parole, ib. whether may be made slaves, 356. in what cases lawful, ib. exchange and ransom of, 357. object of detention of, t'6. time of exchange or ransom, ib. when proper, t'6. state bound to procure release of, ib. its duty to provide for support, ib. formerly obliged to redeem themselves, ib. of assassination and poisoning of, 353, 360, 361. practice of, condemned, t'6. of the jus postliminium with respect to, 398. in force for prisoners, 397. how rights of, subsist, 398. may dispose of and will property, t'6 644 INDEX. PRIZE COURT, how constituted, 364, 392, in notes, questions of capture or prize determined in, 364, 392, in notes, rules respecting, 166, note. 1. must belong to belligerent country ti, 344, note. 2. must have actually sat in country to which it belonged, ib. 3. properly condemned must be, at time of condemnation, in country where sentence pronounced, ib. PRIVATEER. SeeWAK. PROPERTY, Different kinds of, 109. is public, common, or private, ib. Of public property, 109, 113. what, 109. called by Romans res communes, ib. of what it consists, ib. how acquired, 110. of the revenues of the public pro- perty, ib. naturally at the sovereign's disposal, ib. nation may grant him the use and property of its common posses- sions, ib. may allow him the domain, ib. and reserve to itself the use of them, ib. of taxes, 111. See TAXES. nation may reserve to itself the right of imposing, ib, of the sovereign who has this power, 16. his duties with respect to, 112. of eminent domain annexed to sove- reignty, ib. his right thereto, ib. may dispose thereof, ib. government of private property, 113. Of common properly, 113, 115. what, 109, 110. sovereign may make laws respecting, 113. but not abuse such power, ib. of alienation of property of a corpo- ration, ib. corporation has a right to do so, ib. how that right should be exercised, ib. whose consent requisite therein, ib. of the several kinds of corporate pro- perty, 114. use of common property, ib. how each member is to enjoy it, ib. must not injure the common use, ib. right of anticipation in the use of it, 16. instances of the exercise of this right, ffc in drawing water from a well, ib. or felling tree in a forest, 114. PROPERTY (continued). preservation and repairs of common, possessions, 115. expenses hereof, and how raised, ib. duty and right of sovereign herein, ib. Of private property, 115, 116. rights of proprietors of, 115. when sovereign may interfere there- ' with, ib. may subject it to regulations of police, ib. may compel sale of, in cases of neces- sity, 115, 116. power over, in other instances, ib. should hinder monopolies, 116. of inheritances thereto, ib. right of persons to bequeath it, ib. when limited, ib. Of the alienation of public property, ib. right of nation herein, ib. duties of nation in this respect, ib. in cases of necessity, ib. duties of the prince as to, 117. cannot alienate it, ib. though nation may give him a right to it, ib. but right not to be presumed, ib. rules respecting alienation between nations, ib. of treaties thereon, ib. of alienation of a part of the state, 1 18. should only be in cases of extreme necessity, ib. rights of dismembered party, 118, 119. not obliged to receive new master, 119. whether prince has power to dismem- ber the state, ib. PROTECTION. See NATION. of protection sought by a nation, 93. simple treaty of, what, 93, 94. how annulled, 95. PUBLIC GRANARIES, propriety of establishing, 36. PUBLIC WAYS, utility of highways, canals, &c., 43, and note. duty of government in respect of, 43. should render them safe and commo- dious, ib. its rights in this respect, 16. nation should contribute to expenses of, ib. may compel people to labour at, 44. or contribute to the expense, 44, and see note. foundation of the rights of toll, ib. abuses of, ib., and notes, how far tolerated by arbitrary law of nations, ib. now generally settled by treaties, ib. INDEX. 645 PUNISHMENT. See JUSTICE. Of transgressors, 81. foundation of right of punishing, \b. founded on right of personal safety, ib. to whom it belongs, ib. of the laws, and their execution, ib. of the criminal laws, ib. necessity of these laws, ib. their choice, and establishment, 81, 82. Of the degree of punishment, 82. not to be beyond what safety of state requires, ib. what to be considered in proportion- ing of it, ib. as nature of crime itself, ib. opportunities of committing it, ib. degree of injury done to the public, ib. consequences of unnecessary severity, ib. importance of enforcing the laws, ib. RANSOM, of prisoners, 357. right to detain till ransomed, ib. time of ransom, ib. generally settled by treaty, ib. right of sovereign to enforce payment of ransom, 414. conventions relating to the ransom, 419. right to demand, may be transferred, 16. should not be in an unlimited manner, ib. what may annul the convention made for the rate of the ransom, ib. ransom proportionate to rank of officer, ib. concealment of rank, compact may be annulled, ib. prisoner dying before payment of ran- som, ib. ransom when, or not due, 419, 420. instances, ib. prisoner released on condition of pro- curing the release of another, 420. when bound to return, ib. where prisoner is retaken before pay- ment of ransom, ib. his liability to pay second ransom, tA. otherwise, if rescued before he has ob- tained his liberty, 421. of ships, &c., 414, notes. prohibited by English laws, 414, note. RANSOM BILLS, doctrine of, recognised as a part of the law of nations, 414, note. REBEL. See CIVIL LAW. who are rebels, 422, 424. sovereign's right against, 422. obligatory on him to perform promises to, 423. REGENT, when to be appointed, 23. his authority, 27. RELIGION. See PIETY. Of religion external and internal, 56. denned, ib. as an affair of conscience, ib. or an affair of state, ib. Rights of individuals as to, ib. should acquire knowledge of God and his laws, ib. love and respect due to God, ib. liberty of conscience, ib. right to exercise choice in matters of re- ligion, 56, 60. importance of this right, 56, 61. is natural and inviolable, ib. should be limited within just bounds, 56. Public establishment of religion, ib. is a matter of state, 57. and under jurisdiction of political au- thority, ib. of a nation how established, ib. When as yet no established religion, ib. choice of, how made, ib. duty of nation herein, ib. majority to have choice of, ib. but minority to have liberty to follow their own religion, ib. or separate from society of majority, ib. when may sell their property, and re- tire, ib., 106. When there is an established religion, 58. nation bound to protect and support, ib. when may make changes therein, ib. of the danger of innovations, ib. who to determine on changes, ib. in case of a new religion spreading, ib. Duties and rights of sovereign with respect to religion, ib. When no religion established, ib. should establish one by mild and suitable means, ib. should not use authority or restraint, ib. should prevent introduction of one pernicious to morality, &c., ib. When there is an established religion, 59. duty of sovereign to watch over it, ib. should restrain attempts to disturb it, ib. his right to interfere in such case, ib. how right to be exercised, ib. objects of his care, and the means he ought to employ, 60. interior as well as external religion should be, ib. Of toleration, ib. of all tenets advisable, ib. unless dangerous to morality, 16. Of prince's duty, when nation resolved to change its religion, ib. cannot constrain them therein, 61. but may exercise his own religion, ib. 646 INDEX. RELIGION (continued). difference of, does not deprive him of his crown, 61. duties and rights of the sovereign recon- ciled with those of the subjects, ib. Right of sovereign to have inspection over matters of religion, 62. should have inspection of all relating thereto, ib. also over those who teach it, ib. its exercise advantageous to the state, ib. a prerogative of majesty, ib. right of nation to delegate this power, *" sovereign's duty to prevent abuse of received religion, 63. i his authority over ministers of religion, ib. this authority described, 63, 64. cannot compel ecclesiastic to preach against his conscience, 64. duty of ecclesiastic herein, ib. rule to be observed with respect to eccle- siastics, ib. should enjoy a large portion of es- teem, ib. should have no authority, ib. or claim independence, ib. should be subject to the public powers, ib. and amenable to sovereign for their conduct, ib. duty of sovereign towards, 16. should cause them to be respected, ib. and invest them with authority suffi- cient to discharge their functions, ib. but should prevent abuse of that au- thority, ib. clergy when formidable as a separate body, 16. Recapitulation of reasons establishing sove- reign's rights in matters of religion, 64, 65. authorities and examples, 65. Pernicious consequences of denying sovereign to be head of the church, ib. abases particularized, ib. 1. Power of the popes, 66. See POPE- RY. extent thereof, 66, 67. pernicious effect of, in a foreign court, 67. instances, ib. 2. Of important employments conferred by a foreign power, '68. disposal of dignities, ib. a violation of a nation's right, ib. submission thereto condemned, ib. RELIGION (continued) 3. Powerful subjects depending on fo- reign court, 68, 69. abuse in this respect, 69.^ 4. The celibacy of their priests, ib. for what cause invented, ib. practice of, condemned, 70. of convents, 69, 70. marriage advocated, 70. 5. Enormous pretensions of the clergy, ib. of their assumed pre-eminence, ib. its prejudice on good order, ib. 6. Independence of, 71. immunities of, t'6. attempt of, to escape from political authority, ib. claim their immunities from God, ib. 7. Immunities of church possessions, 72, 73. when state may exempt them, 72. limit of exemption, t'6. 8. Excommunication of men in office, 73. 9. And of sovereigns themselves, 74. instances of this abuse, 74, 75, in note. 10. The clergy drawing every thing to themselves, and disturbing the order of justice, 75, 76 11. Money drawn to Rome, 76 12. Laws and customs contrary to the welfare ot states, Hi. consequences of trusting same to the clergy, ib. pernicious effects thereof on the state, ib. Right of nations to interfere with religion of each other, 157, 158. no nation can be restrained with re- spect to, 158. with respect to missionaries, ib, what a sovereign may do in favour of those professing his religion in an- other country, 159. RENUNCIATION, what, 25. validity and effect of, 25, 26. REPRISALS, what, 283. their nature, 283, 284. accomplishment of, 284. what required to render them lawful, ib. must be on just grounds before allowed, ib. upon what effects reprisals made, t'6. and note. general reprisals, what, 285, note, state should compensate those who puffer by, 285. sovereign alone can order reprisals, ib. INDEX. 647 REPRISALS (continued). termed by the French letters of marque, 285. against a nation for the actions of its subjects, ib. but not in favour of foreigners, 16. those who have given cause for, ought to indemnify the sufferers, 286. what deemed a refusal to do justice, 286, 287. arrest of subjects by way of, 287, 481. instances of, ib. our right against those who oppose re- prisals, 287. just reprisals do not afford a just cause of war, 288. how we ought to confine ourselves to reprisals, or proceed to extremities, 288, 289. wnen latter course preferable, 289. of reprisals during war, 348. whether may be made on ambassadors, Ac., 481, 482. use of poison not to be adopted by way of reprisal, 360. REPUBLIC. See GOVERNMENT. what, 2. empire intrusted by nation to a certain number of citizens, 2. RESIDENTS, who, 460. RETALIATION OF INJURIES, 282, 283, 317. RETORTION, 283. REVENUE. See PROPERTY. of the public revenues, 110. at whose disposal, ib. application of, ib. RIGHTS. See OBLIGATIONS AND RIGHTS. RIVERS, STREAMS, AND LAKES, right of nation thereto, 120. of river separating two territories, 76. rules respecting, ib. 1. where nation takes possession of country bounded by, t'6. priority of possession gives right, ib. 2. and appropriates to itself the use thereof, 76. 3. where possession doubtful, t'6. 4. where possession long and undis- puted, 120, and note. 5. where settled by treaty, 120. of the bed of a river dried up, or taking another course, 121. the bed of, belongs to owner of river, t'6. of the right of alluvion, t"6. distinction between, and avulsion, t'6. whether it produces any change in the right to the river, t'6. where bed of changed, 122. RIVERS, &c. (continued). right of soil of abandoned course, in whom, 122. of works tending to turn the current of, ib. when, or not lawful, ib. or in prejudice of right of others, ib. rules in relation to interfering rights, ib. where right of fishery exists, ib. in cases of navigation, ib. of lakes, 123, 124. See LAKES. proprietors of, who, 123. of the increase of lakes, ib. of land formed on banks of lakes, 125. where bed of lake dried up, ib. jurisdiction over lakes and rivers, ib. SAFE CONDUCT, what, 416. distinction between, and passport, ib. right of sovereign to grant, ib. when may delegate right, ib. is not transferable, ib. of safe conduct granted for certain effects, ib. when those effects may be removed by others, ib. extent of the promised security, ib. duty of party granting it, 417. of the right derived thereby, ib. whether includes baggage and domestics, ib. practice to specify particulars, ib. granted to father does not include his family, ib. when to party and his retinue, ib. term of safe conduct, 418. of person forcibly detained beyond the term, ib. of respite in case of forcible detainer or sickness, ib. does not expire at death of him who gave it, ib. how may ba revoked, ib. time allowed in case of revocation, ib. SAFE-GUARD. See ENEMY. what, and when granted, 369. SEA, its use, 125. dominion over, 125, in note. whether it can be possessed, 125. no one can appropriate to himself the use of, ib. attempt to exclude another does it an injury, 126. attempt an injury to all nations, t'6. exclusive right may be acquired by treaties, ib. but not by prescription, or long usage, 127. unless by virtue of a tacit agreement, t'6. but sea near the coasts may become a property, t'6. 648 INDEX. 8EA (continued). reason for appropriating the sea near the coast, 128. how far this possession may extend, 128, 129. of shores and ports, 129. of bays and straits, 129, 130. of straits in particular, 130. of tax in right of passage, ib. of the right to wrecks, ib. when allowed, ib. to whom belonging, ib. of a sea included within the territories of a nation, 130, 131. of the jurisdiction over the sea, 131. empire and domain over, not insepara- ble, ib. of children born at, 102. See COUNTRY. SEARCH. See NEUTRALITY. right of, in neutral ships, 338, 339. consequences of refusal, ib. usually settled by treaty, ib. SEPARATION, of a nation from the state of which it is a member, 96. when allowed, 96, 97. when conquered or abandoned, 97. mere failure of protection not sufficient, 96, 97. SETTLEMENT. Sec COUNTRY. what, 103. when may be changed, ib. distinction between, and habitation, ib. of natural or original settlement, ib. acquired settlement, what, ib. SHORE, 129. Sec SEA. SLAVERY, of the right to condemn prisoners to, 356, 357. See PRISONER. SOCIETY. See LAW OF NATIONS. of the establishment of natural society, lix. its necessity, ib. its duties and obligations, Ix. IxL its object, Ixi. general laws deduced therefrom, Ir. Ixi. IxiL benefit of others, without prejudice to ourselves, Ixi. Ixii. the liberty of nations, Ixii. effect of this liberty, ib. the right of judging for herself, Ixii. 346. importance of this law, Ixiv. violation of, a ground of war, ib. extent of right, ib. must not affect the liberty of nations, ib. SOLDIERS. See WAR. right of raising, 293. f enlistment of, 294. SOLDIERS (continued) their pay and quarters, 296. of mercenary soldiers, 297. SOVEREIGN, obligations and rights of, 12. who is a sovereign, 1, 12. established for the advantage of society, 13. representative character of, 14. origin of, 16. is intrusted with the obligations of the nation, ib. and invested with its rights, 14. rights of in this respect, 14, 15. ought to know the nation, 15. extent of his power, i&. his prerogatives, ib. to respect and support the laws funda- mental, ib. may change those not fundamental, ib. ought to maintain the existing laws, 16. in what sense subject to the laws, ib. person of, sacred and inviolable, 17. nation may curb a tyrant, 17, 18. may withdraw itself from his obedience, ib. arbitration between, and his subjects, 20. obedience which subjects owe to, 21. when may resist him, ib. appointment of ministers by, 23. duty of, in establishing glory of the na- tion, 91. of pardoning offenders. See PARDON. right of, to grant privilege of safe con- duct, 416. duty of state to procure release of, when a prisoner, 436. right of, over property of subject. See PROPERTY. SOVEREIGN STATE, what, 2. is such, though bound by an unequal alliance, ib. or by treaty of protection, ib. or to pay tribute, ib. or to do homage, ib. two states subject to the same prince, may be, 3. so of states forming a federal republic, ib. when it ceases to be such, 4. when under dominion of another, ib. SOVEREIGNTY. See alo SOVEREIGN STATE. what, 3. indivisibility of, 21. is inalienable, 31. SPY, of the employment of, 375, 376, 358. STATE. See NATION, LAW OP NATION, SOVEREIGNTY. INDEX. 649 STATE (continued). Its constitution, 8. duties and rights of the nation in re- spect to, ib. of the public authority of, ib. nation should choose the best constitu- tion, 9. of the political, fundamental, and civil laws of, ib. of the support of the constitution, and obedience to the laws, 9, 10. rights of nation with respect to its con- stitution and government, 10. may reform its government, ib. and change its constitution, ib. of the legislative power of, 11. right of, to change the constitution, ib. of the caution necessary herein, 12. is the judge of all disputes relating to the government, ib. no foreign power has a right to interfere, ib. several kinds of states, 23. STRAIT. See SEA. of refusing passage through, 130. of levying tax on vessels passing through, ib. STREAM, 120, 121. See RIVEE, STREAMS, AND LAKES. SUBMISSION. See NATION. of one nation to another, 94. different kinds of, ib. right of citizens on, ib. how treaty of, annulled, 95. distinction between, and incorpora- tion, 96. SUBSIDY. See ENEMY. what, 324. SUCCESSIVE OR HEREDITARY STATE, what, 24. origin of, ib. when may be changed, 25. ought to be kept, 26. of renunciation, 25. when, or not binding, ib. of regents, 27. indivisibility of sovereigns, ib. who to decide disputes respecting suc- cession, ib. ought not to depend on judgment of a foreign power, 29. SUPPLICANT. See COUNTRY. who are, 107. such as implore protection of a sove- reign against nation they have quitted, ib. SURETY. "ie GUARANTY. for observance of treaties, 237. See TREATY. 82 TAXES, imposition and regulation of, 111. each citizen to contribute according to his ability, ib. nature of the obligation, ib. nation may reserve to itself the right of imposing them, ib. of money bills, 111, in note. of the sovereign who has this power, ib. duties of sovereign with respect to, ib. application of, 112. TERRITORY. See COUNTRY. TESTAMENTS, validity of, how decided, 167. how construed in England, 167, note. prisoner of war may make, 398. TOLERATION. See RELIGION AND PIETY. when universal toleration advisable, 60. is so, unless tenets dangerous to mo- rality, ib. TOLL. See PUBLIC WAYS. foundation of right to, 44, 115. nature and object of imposition of, 44. on whom imposed, 44, and note. TRADE, 37 to 43. See COMMERCE. TREATIES, Of alliance and other public treaties, 192. nature of treaties, 192, and note. of pactions, agreements, and conven- tions, 192. by whom treaties are to be made, ib. state under protection may make, 193. limitation of right, ib. of treaties concluded by proxies and plenipotentiaries, ib. by whom ratified, ib. validity of treaties, 194. injury does not render them void, ib. duty of nations herein, ib. if injurious to state, a nullity, ib. so, if made for unjust or dishonest pur- poses, 195. contraction of, with those who do not profess the true religion, ib. obligation of observing treaties, 196. necessity of, acknowledged by all na- tions, ib. glory to nation resulting therefrom, ib. instances, 196. violation of, an act of injustice, ib. cannot be made contrary to those pre- viously existing, ib. how concluded with several nations with same view, 197. the more ancient ally entitled to pre- ference, ib. no assistance in an unjust war, ib. General division of the subject, 198. 1. those relating to things already due by the law of nature, ib. 650 INDEX. TREATIES (continued). 2. those relating to further engagements, 189. the former described, ib. collision of these treaties with duty we owe ourselves, ib. treaties by which we barely promise to do no injury, ib. utility thereof, ib. treaties concerning things not na- turally due, ib. these treaties described, ib. are equal or unequal, 198, 199. of equal treaties, 199. obligation of preserving equality in treaties, 199. difference between equal and unequal treaties, 200. of unequal treaties and alliances, ib. are divided into two classes, ib. 1. where inequality on side of stronger power, ib. 2. where on side of inferior, ib. of unequal alliances, 201. either impair the sovereignty, or they do not, 16. how alliance with diminution of sove- reignty may annul preceding treaties. 202, 203. should be avoided as much as possible, 203. mutual duty of nations with respect to unequal alliances, ib. of those where inequality on the side of the more powerful party, 203, 204. how inequality may be conformable to the law of nature, 204. when imposed by way of punishment, 205. of personal and real treaties, ib. personal alliance, what, ib. expires with him who makes it, ib. real alliance, what, ib. always attaches to the state, ib. unless limited, ib. distinctions between, to be observed, ib. general rules respecting, ib. naming contracting parties in, does not make it personal, ib. alliance by a republic is real, ib. subsists, though form of government changed, 206. of treaties concluded by kings or other monarchs, ib, of perpetual treaties, ib. of those for a certain time, ib. of treaties for king and his successors, ib. treaties for the good of the kingdom, 207. TREATIES (continued). presumption, how to be founded in doubtful cases, 207. instances in illustration, 207, 208. obligations and rights resulting from a real treaty pass to the suc- cessor, 208. hut -general custom for successor to renew them, ib. of treaties accomplished once for all and perfected, 208, 209. of those accomplished in part, 209,210. personal alliance expires if one of parties ceases to reign, 211. of those in their own nature personal, 211. where concluded for defence of king and royal family, ib. when binding where king deprived of his crown, ib. distinction when dethroned by rebels, ib. and lawfully dethroned, ib. instances of Louis 4th and king William, 212. obligation of a real alliance where the king is dethroned, ib. Of the dissolution and renewal of treaties, ib. expiration of alliances made for a limited time, 213. of the renewal of treaties, ib. of the tacit renewal of, 213, 214. how dissolved when violated by one of contracting parties, 214. violation of one treaty does not cancel another, ib. when violation of part cancels the whole, 215. is void by the destruction of one of the contracting parties, 216. but not by state placing itself under pro- tection of another, ib. of treaties dissolved by mutual consent, 217. Of public conventions in nature of, 218. Sec CONVENTION. when made by sovereigns, ib. of those by subordinate powers, ib. of treaties concluded by public person not having sufficient power, 219. of the agreement called Sponsio, ib. state not bound thereby, 220. effect of, on promiser, ib. sovereign, how far bound by, 223. Of the faith of treaties, 229. what is sacred among nations, ib. treaties are held sacred between nations, ib. faith of treaties is sacred, ib, and he who violates them violates the law of nations, ib. right of nations against violator, 230. INDEX. 651 TREATIES (continued). violation of, by the popes, 230. this abuse authorized by princes, 231. use of an oath in treaties, 232. does not constitute the obligation, t'6. or produce new obligations, ib. or change the nature of them, ib. it gives no pre-eminence to one treaty above another, ib. cannot give force to a treaty invalid, 233. of asseverations, 232. violation of, disgraceful, ib. faith of treaties does not depend on the difference of religion, 233. precautions to be observed in wording of, 233. of subterfuges in treaties, 234. an evidently false interpretation incon- sistent with faith of treaties, ib. faith tacitly pledged, ib. Of securities given for observance of, 235. guaranty, what, ib. gives the guarantee no right to interfere, ib. nature of the obligation it imposes, 236. cannot impair the rights of a third party, ib. duration of the guaranty, ib. of treaties with surety, 237. of pawns, securities, and mortgages, ib. right of nation over what she holds as a pledge, 237, 238. how obliged to restore it, 238. how she may appropriate it, ib. of hostages, 238, 239. See HOST- AGE. Of the interpretation of treaties, 244. necessity of establishing rules of, ib. general observations herein, 244, and notes, maxims respecting, ib. 1st, not allowable to interpret what has no need of interpretation, ib. 2d, if he who could and ought to have explained himself, and has not done it, it is to his own detriment, 245. 3d, neither of contracting parties to interpret according to his own fancy, ib. 4th, what is sufficiently declared is to be taken for true, 245, 246. 6th, interpretation ought to be made according to certain rules, 246. faith of treaties lays an obligation to follow these rules, 247. general rule of interpretation, ib. TREATIES (continued). should be conformable to common usage, 248. how ancient treaties to be interpreted, ib. of quibbles on words, 249. rule for avoiding of, ib. mental reservations not allowed, 16. technical terms, how interpreted, 250. of terms whose signification admits of degrees, ib. of figurative expressions, ib. of equivocal expressions, 251. rule for latter cases, ib. not necessary to give a term the same sense everywhere in the same deed, 252. absurd interpretations should be re- jected, ib. absurdity described, and instances, ib. interpretation rendering treaty void not to be admitted, 253. obscure expressions, how interpreted, 254. interpretation founded on the connection of the discourse, ib. or drawn from the connection, &c. of the things themselves, 255. to be founded on the reason of the deed, 256. how, where many reasons have con- curred to determine the will, 257. what constitutes a sufficient reason for an act of the will, ib. extensive interpretation founded on the reason of the act, ib. of frauds tending to elude laws and promises, 258. of restrictive interpretations, 259. use of, to avoid falling into absurdities, ib. or into what is unlawful, ib. or into what is too severe and burthen- some, 260. how it ought to restrict the signification agreeably to the subject, ib. when change happening in the state of things forms an exception, 261. interpretation of, in unforeseen cases, 262. reasons arising from the possibility and not the existence of the thing, t'6. where expressions capable of an ex- tensive and a limited sense, 263. of things favourable and things odious, ib. favourable, when tending to the common advantage, 264. odious, when to the contrary, ib. so, of things useful to human society, 265. whatever contains a penalty is odious, ib. 652 INDEX. TREATIES (continued). so, whatever renders a deed void odious, 265. all tending to change the present stat of things is favourable, ib. the contrary is odious, ib. of things of a mixed nature, 266. interpretation of favourable things, ib. rules respecting, ib. 1. utmost latitude to be given to term used according to common usage ib. 2. terms of art to receive the fulles interpretation, 267. 3. but not in an improper signification unless from necessity, 267. 4. signification to be restricted, where leading to absurdity, ib. 6. to be restricted where equity or great common advantage requires it, ib. interpretation of things odious, ib. should be limited, 267, 268. examples, 268, 269. how deeds of liberality should be inter preted, 270. where a collision of laws and treaties ib. General rules respecting interpretation of, ib. 1. where bare permission incompatible with prescription latter preferred, 271. 2. treaty permitting, to give way to that forbidding, ib. 3. so, that which ordains, to give way to that which forbids, ib. 4. where collision between two affirma- tive treaties, latter to be preferred. ib. when otherwise, 16. 5. of two laws or conventions, the less general preferred, 272. 6. treaty not admitting of delay, to be preferred to that to be done at another time, 273. 7. of two competing duties, the most important, &c., preferred, ib. 8. of two promises, the party promised to elect, 274. but in case of doubt, promiser to perform that in which most strongly bound, Hi. 9. treaty confirmed on oath to be preferred to one not sworn to, ib. 10. treaty enjoined under a penalty, to be preferred to that not enforced by one, ib. no, of that enjoined under a greater penalty to that enforced by a lesser, TREATIES OF PEACE, 432. See PEAC*. TRIBUTARY STATE. See STATE. what, 3. is a sovereign state, 3. TROOPS, right of levying, 294. enlistment of, 294, 298. TRUCE. V &eWAR. what, 404. does not terminate the war, ib. is partial or general, ib. general truce for many years, ib. how concluded, ib. sovereign's faith engaged in, 406. when truce begins to be obligatory, ib. publication of, ib. subjects contravening the truce, 16. violation of, 407. stipulation of penalty against infractor of, ib. time of the truce, ib. effects of a truce, 408. what or not allowed during continuance of, t6. rules respecting, 408, 409. 1. each party may do at home what they have a right to do in time of peace, 409. 2. not to take advantage of the truce in doing what hostilities would have prevented, ib. as continuing the works of a siege, 16. or repairing breaches, &c., ib. or introducing succours, 410. distinctions herein, ib. as army retreating during a sus- pension of hostilities, ib. 3. nothing to be attempted in con- tested places, but every thing to be left as it was, 411. but places quitted, &c., by enemy may be possessed, ib. subjects inclined to revolt not to be received during the truce, 16. much less to be solicited to treason, Ik persons or effects of enemy not to be seized during truce, t'6. right of postliminium during a truce, ib. intercourse allowed during, ib. of persons detained by insurmounta- ble difficulties after expiration of, 412. of adding particular conditions to truces, ib. at expiration of, war renewed without fresh declaration, ib. TRUTH, when bound to speak it to an enemy, 373. INDEX. 653 USUCAPTION. See PRESCRIPTION. what, 187, and note. VAGRANT. See COUNTRY. who are vagrants, 103. those who have no settlements, ib. children of, have therefore no country, ib. when country of vagrant that of child, ib. as where vagrant has not renounced his natural settlement, ib. VOLUNTARY LAW, what, Ixiv., and note. founded on a presumed consent, Iriv. maxim concerning use of, Ixvi. VOLUNTEERS, 401. See WAR. WAR, Definition of, 291. is public or private, ib. defensive or offensive, 293. right of making, 291. belongs only to the sovereign power, 292, 293. though sometimes otherwise, 292. right of kings of England to make, 292, 293, and note. Of the instruments of war, 293. what deemed such, ib. troops, officers, &c., ib. arms, artillery, &c., ib. right of levying troops, 294. belongs to the sovereign power, ib. is one of the prerogatives of majesty, ib. though right sometimes limited, ib. obligations of citizens to serve and de- fend the state, ib. of the enlistment or raising of troops, ib. of the exemptions from carrying arms, 295. who exempt, as magistrates, clergy, &c., 295, 296. of soldiers' pay and quarters, 296. of hospitals for invalids, ib. of mercenary soldiers, 297. who are such, ib. possession of, how far lawful, ib. what observed in their enlistment, 298. service of, voluntary, ib. must not be by stratagem or force, ib. of enlistment in foreign countries, ib. permission of sovereign requisite, 298. none but volunteers to be enlisted, i&. of enticing away subjects, ib. nature of crime and punishment, ib. when a cause for declaring war, ib. of the obligation of soldiers, 299. to take oath of fidelity, ib. are not to desert the service, ib. punishment of deserters, ib. WAR, (continued). of solicitations to desert, 373. of military laws, ib. necessity of, in army, ib. military code of, what, ib. of military discipline, ib. importance of, considered, ib. of subordinate powers in war, ib, their authority, ib. extent and limit thereof, ib. promises of, how far binding on sove- reign, 300. when binding only on themselves, i&. of the assumption of power by, ib. their responsibility, ib. how they bind their inferiors, 301. Of the just causes of war, ib. should not be undertaken without very cogent reasons, ib. justificatory reasons and motives for making, 302. explanation hereof, ib. what in general a just cause of war, ib. what unjust, 16. of the object of war, ib. what motives requisite in undertaking war, 303. proper motives, what, ib. vicious motives, what, ib. of war undertaken upon just grounds, though motives vicious, ib. pretexts, what, 304. of war undertaken merely for advantage. * of nations making war without reason or apparent motives, 305. are considered enemies to mankind, ib. right of nations to punish them, ib. how defensive war is just or unjust, ib. nation has no right to defend an unjust war, 305, 307. her duty under such circumstances, 305, 313. how defence may become just, 305, 313, 316. > offensive war, how far just in an evident cause, 305. requisites to be considered, 306. 1. a right to demand something of another nation, 306, 315. 2. the inability to obtain it otherwise than by force of arms, 306, 315, 320. in a doubtful cause, 306. when to be resorted to, ib. war cannot be just on both sides, i6. though sometimes reputed lawful, 306, 320. of war undertaken to punish a nation, 307. should be founded on right and necessity, ib. duty of nation at fault, ib. SB* 654 INDEX. WAR (continued). aggrandizement of a neighbouring power, 308. when no right to make war, ib. when appearance of danger gives the right, 309. when other nations may check aggrand- izement of a state, 310, 311. other allowable means of defence against a formidable power, 311. political equilibrium, what, 311, 312. ways of maintaining it, 312. how he who destroys it may be re- strained, 312, 313. behaviour allowable towards a neighbour preparing for war, 313. Of the declaration of war, 315. of the necessity thereof, ib, what it should contain, ib. is simple or conditional, 316. right to make, ceases on offer of equi- table conditions, ib, formalities of, ib. publication of, ib. necessity hereof, ib. defensive war requires no declaration, ib. when may be omitted in an offensive war, i&. or against enemies' associates, 331. not to be omitted by way of retaliation, 317. unnecessary at expiration of a truce, 412. should be made where truce of long duration, ib. Time of declaration of war, 317. need not be till army has reached the frontiers, ib. or has entered the enemy's territories, ib. must precede acts of hostility, ib. Duty of inhabitants on entry of foreign army before declaration, ib. commencement of hostilities, ib. conduct to be pursued towards subjects of enemy in country at time of declaration, 318. freedom of persons and property, ib. time allowed for departure, ib. extension of that time, when, ib. when to be treated as enemies, ib. Publication of the war and manifestoes, ib. necessity for, among neutrals, ib. how published, 319. manifestoes, what, ib. what they should contain, ib. decorum and moderation to be observed in, ib. Of lawful war in due form, ib. requisites of, ib. by whom to be made, ib. also termed a regular war, 320. WAR (continued). how far noticed in courts of justice, 320, in note. distinctions between lawful and un- lawful war, 320. between unlawful and informal, ib. grounds of distinction, 320, 321. Of the enemy, and things belonging to him, ib. See ENEMY. Of neutrality, 332. See NEUTRALITY. Of the rights of nations in war, 346, and note. general principles of, 346. difference between what may be done of right, and what merely allowed, 346. the right to weaken an enemy by every justifiable method, 347, 353, 364. the right over the enemy's person, 347. origin and limitation of this right, ib. of giving quarter, and the offer to ca- pitulate, 348. enemy not to be killed after ceasing to resist, 348, 350, 354. case when quarter may be refused, 348, 361. enemy violating the laws of war, 348, 350, 354, 361. of the governor of a town making an obstinate defence, 349, 350. Reprisals, what, 348. See REPRISAL. a system of retaliation, 348. examples of, 349, and note, what prisoners not to be the subject of, 349, 350. Fugitives and deserters, 351. when may be put to death, ib. of the clemency to be shown to them, ib. capitulation with respect to, ib. Women, children, aged, and the sick, ib. not to be put to death, ib, unless guilty of acts of hostility, 352. Clergymen, men of letters, l;c., ib. also exempted from death, ib. when not, ib. peasants and those not carrying arms, 352, 353. likewise exempt, ib. their freedom in general, 16. when may have restraints imposed on them, 353. Of prisoners of tear, ib. See PIV>ONEB. right of making, ib. its object, ib. not to be put to death, 348, 354, 355. treatment of, 354, and note, of prisoners who cannot be fed, 355. of condemning them to slavery, 356. INDEX. 655 WAR (continued). exchange and ransom of, 357. See RAN- SOM. object of, 357. when it takes place, ib. how regulated in general, ib. when exchange may be refused, ib. of providing liberty of, in treaty, ib. right of nation to prohibit ransom of, 357, 358. of assassinating and poisoning of, 358 to 360. meaning of assassination, 359. is contrary to the law of nature, 360, 361. guilt of sovereign resorting thereto, 361. how punished, ib. use of poison not to be adopted by way of reprisal, 360. Of the right of war with regard to things belonging to the enemy, 364. See ENEMY. Of the sovereign who wages an unjust war, 378. an unjust war gives no right, ib. guilt of him who undertakes it, 378, 379. his obligations, 379. Of the effects of a regular war, 381. is bound to make reparation, ib. nations not rigidly to enforce the law of nature against each other, ib. should observe the voluntary law of, 382. reason for this, ib. regular war, its effects, ib. whatever permitted to one party, is so to the other, 382, 383. effect of the voluntary law in an unjust war, 383. Of acquisitions by war, 384. war, when a lawful mode ofacquisition,t'6. conditions necessary to render it just, 384, 385. every acquisition in regular, valid, 385. and this though war unjust, ib. exception in case of war destitute of any plausible pretext, 385. acquisition of movable property, 385, in note. of maritime captures, ib. title to, when complete, ib. law as to, in England, ib. acquisition of immovables on conquest, 386. to whom they belong, ib. when title thereto complete, ib. how to transfer them validly, 387, 395. conditions on which a conquered town is acquired, 387. such rights only acquired as belonged to the conquered sovereign, & WAR (continued). lands of private persons, 388. formerly subject to the right of conquest, ib. such right now confined to public pro- perty, ib. conquest of the whole state, ib. treatment of the conquered state, 388, &c., and note, to whom the conquest belongs, 391, 365, and note. the nation entitled thereto, 391. nature of the sovereign's right thereto, 391, 365, and note, of liberating a people whom the enemy have unjustly conquered, 391. when under an obligation to do so, 339, and note. Of the right of postliminium, 392. See Jus POSTLIMINIUM. Of the rights of private persons in war, 399. subjects cannot commit hostilities with- out the sovereign's order, ib. nature of that order, ib. necessity for, and why adopted, 399, 400. precise meaning of order, 400, and note. how interpreted, 400. what private persons may undertake, presuming on the sovereign's will, ib. of privateers, ib. nature of their rights, 400, 401. of volunteers, 401. their treatment, ib. what soldiers and subalterns may do, 401, 402. obligation of state to indemnify subjects for damages sustained in war, 402, 403, and note. distinction herein, ib. duty of state in this respect, 403, and note. Of conventions made during war, 404. See TKUCE. of truce and suspension of arms, ib, distinction between, ib. does not terminate the war, ib. a truce is either partial or general, ib. of a general truce for many years, ib. how concluded, 16. sovereign's faith engaged in, 406. when truce begins to be obligatory, ib. publication of, i6. subjects contravening of, ib. truce not .thereby broken, ib. punishment of delinquents, 406, 407. violation of, 407. its dissolution by breach of one of con- tracting parties, ib. 656 INDEX. WAR (continued). stipulation of penalty against infractor of, 407. time of the truce, ib. necessity of specifying, 407, 408. how construed in the absence of such specification, 408. general effects of a truce, ib. what, or not allowed during continu- ance of it, ib. rules respecting, 409. See TRUCE. Of capitulations, 412. by whom to be concluded, 412,413. clauses thereof, 413. necessity for their observance, 414. promises made to the enemy by in- dividuals are binding, 414, 371, 372. instances, 415. duty of sovereign to see them fulfilled, 414. as to contracts in favour of alien ene- mies, 414, note. as to promises of ransom, 414. See RANSOM. WAR (continued). of conventions relating to ransom, 419, 420. See RANSOM. WAYS, 43. See PUBLIC WATS. WHALE FISHERY. customary law respecting, Ixiv. note. WILLS,' validity of, how decided, 167. how construed in England, 167, note. prisoner of war may make, 398. WORSHIP. See RELIGION. what, 46. is either public or private, 61. of the establishment of, 56, 59, 60. how destroyed, 61. of attendance at public worship, ib. how far enjoined by religion, ib. WRECKS, of the right thereto, 130, and note. in what cases allowed, ib, only where owner cannot be found, ib. to whom they belong, ib. THE END. E. B. HEARS, STEREOTYPED CQ o II if *. Q S= I 3 g -& fS **- ?3

S fe I 1 I g ? ^ ^F-CAUFO^ P I* -.rJB %BWJ^ - 3 : -CAllf L 007 824 602 2 ~ n ^^ ^W- ^- I 33 "T 3 V I I i-n University of California Library Los Angeles This book is DUE on the last date stamped below. lOSAHCflEf,, :- ' UCLA URU REC'DYRL JAN 19 1 HW Ur * MM Ll AR 1 9 2005 F-CAIIFOJ? ^ 9 .jclOS-ANCnfj.> ft 1