1- EXCHANGE The Belief in Immortality BY SIMEON SPIDLE, B. D. Fellow in Psychology, Clark University A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF CLARK UNIVERSITY. WORCESTER. MASS.. IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY. AND ACCEPTED ON THE RECOMMENDATION OF G. STANLEY HALL N Reprinted from the Journal of Religious Psychology January, 1912, Vol. 5, No. i, pp. 5-51 Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2007 with funding from IVIicrosoft Corporation http://www.archive.org/details/beliefinimmortalOOspidrich The Belief in Immortality BY SIMEON SPIDLE, B. D. Fellow in Psychology, Clark University A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF CLARK UNIVERSITY. WORCESTER. MASS.. IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY. AND ACCEPTED ON THE RECOMMENDATION OF G. STANLEY HALL •V Reprinted from the Journal of Religious Psychology January, 1912, Vol. 5, No. i, pp. 5-51 S7 *..*'::♦: ^ THE BELIEF IN IMMORTALITY. By SIMEON SPIDLE, B. D., Fellow in PsycJiology, Clark University. Introductory. The present writer makes no claim to having any special light to shed upon the age-long question of immortality. He is rather an inquirer than an illuminator. Having been for a number of years interested in this subject, there has grown up in his mind a desire to make somewhat of a first-hand study of it. Others have worked in this same field and have given us, from time to time, the results of their investigations. All this is necessary in order to know how the current of thought concerning the belief in an after life is tending. No one cross-section of the belief can tell us this. We need several such cross^sections in order to indicate the direction of its flow. If the study made in this paper shall in any small degree contribute to this end, the writer's purpose will be abundantly fulfilled. The subject will be treated under four general heads. First of all we shall attempt an analysis of the concept of immortality with a view to determining the different senses in which that concept is used. Next we shall outline the different theories which have been advanced to account for the origin of the belief. Then we shall make a brief survey of the grounds upon which the belief rests. And, finally, we shall give the results of our own empirical study regarding the present status of the belief. The numbers included in brackets refer to the corresponding numbers in the bibliography at the end. Where the letter p is prefixed to the number, the reference is to the page of the book quoted. I. Types op Immortality Concepts. 1. Plasmic Immortality: No part of the furnishings of the human mind is endowed with greater plasticity than the concept of immortality. It is capable of being moulded into a great variety of forms. Not infrequently do we hear the word used with reference to the rejuvenating power of protoplasm. Not long since, while in 255770 6 JOURJSPAi, OJP RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY conversation wrtn a- proinment biologist, I made some inquiry- regarding the work being done in his class room. The reply that I received was that he was just then engaged in carrying his class through a course on the ''immortality of protoplasm." This may seem like a strange application of the term to one who is unacquainted with the facts of biology, but to one who is cognizant of those facts the application seems entirely justi- fiable. As every one knows, it is a truism of biology that "no protozoa have any dead ancestors." These creatures, lowest in the scale of animal life, and composed of one tiny cell of proto- plasm, never die under normal conditions. The whole mass of the cell is, in a sense, reproductive in its function, the mode of reproduction being that of cell-division. Taking the case of the amoeba, which is the lowest form of all, each parent cell divides, without loss or death of any of its material, into two equal parts. We have then two creatures instead of one, each having half of the protoplasm of the original cell from which they were pro- duced. Here no part of the original cell can be said to be the corpse of a being that has perished. No being has perished. It has simply transformed itself into two beings. The only pos- sible way of looking at such a process as this is to say that the substance and life of the original cell are continued on under changed conditions without loss or death. And this fact of plasmic immortality is not confined solely to the protozoan level of life. Modern embryology has revealed to us that, in a limited sense, this same principle obtains also on the higher levels of life, including man himself. Physical death, or "the birth of the corpse," took place in the animal series, as a normal experience, only when in the metazoans the cells began to divide themselves into two specialized groups, the somatic, or vegetative cells, and the reproductive cells. The vegetative cells then assumed the function of forming for the animal a body. In doing so, they lost their original power of perpetual rejuvena- tion and thus became subject to dissolution and death. Why they should have done so is still one of the unsolved problems of biology. Far different, however, was it with the reproduc- tive cells. They still retained their rejuvenating power. Both in the case of viviparous and oviparous reproduction, the off- spring is simply a fusion of two parent cells which have detached themselves from the reproductive cells of the parent bodies. The whole chain of animal life, therefore, from the amoeba up SMDLE; IMMORTALITY 7 to man, is simply the product of one continuous chain of death- less protoplasm which is "eternally young, eternally reproduc- tive, eternally forming new individuals to grow up and perish, while it remains in its progeny always youthful, always increas- ing, and always the same. Thousands upon thousands of gen- erations which have risen in the course of the ages were its pro- ducts, but it lives on in the youngest generations with the power of giving origin to coming millions. The individual organism itself is transient, but the embryonic substance which produces this transient organism preserves itself to all ages imperishable, everlasting, and constant." 2. Influential Immortality. But, rising to a somewhat higher level, we meet with an en- tirely different use of the term immortality. This time it is applied to the permanent character of human influence. If we designate the former use of the word as denoting a strictly biological conception, we may designate this latter use as denot- ing a strictly positivistic conception. Perhaps no better statement of this use of the term could be formulated than that given by Biichner, the famous exponent of German materialism during the last century. In speaking of death and immortality in his Man in the Past, Present and Future (p.225), he says: ** Great philosophers have called death the fundamental cause of all philosophy. If this be correct, the empirical or experimental philosophy of the present day has solved the greatest philosophical enigmas, and has shown (both logically and empirically) that there is no death, and the great mystery of existence consists in perpetual, uninterrupted change. Everything is immortal and indestructible — the smallest worm as well as the most enormous of celestial bodies; the sand-grain and the water-drop, as well as the highest being in creation, man and his thoughts. Only the forms in which being manifests itself are changing. Being itself remains eternally the same and imperishable. When we die, we do not lose our- selves, but only our personal consciousness or the causal form which our being, in itself eternal and imperishable, had assumed for a short time. We live on in nature, in our race, in our children, in our descendants, in our deeds, in our thoughts, in short, in the entire material and psychical contribution which, during our short personal existence, we have furnished to the subsistence of mankind and of nature in general.'* Comte taught the same doctrine. He held that the only im- mortality which any individual can reasonably expect to attain is the perpetuation of his memory and influence in the race. 8 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY This abiding influence he called ''subjective immortality," and held it up in true Thanatopsis fashion as the great incentive to noble living, the mighty motive to admission into the Company of the Saints made perfect by Positivism. A similar view is that of George Eliot, George Meredith, and numerous other writers of note. In his poems entitled Earth and Man, and A Faith on Trial, Meredith constantly exhorts men to live in their offspring and to dismiss forever from their minds the fictitious desire for a personal existence beyond this life. There is no such exist- ence. The only immortality to which any man shall ever attain is the immortal mark which his influence makes upon the race in which he has, for a time, lived and moved and had his being. 3. Cosmic Immortality. Leaving now these rather arbitrary uses of the word, we come next to a somewhat more consistent and more metaphysical ap- plication of the term. This time it is applied to the permanent character of the universe itself. This is the pantheistic notion of immortality, and as such may be designated as cosmic immor- tality. The whole universe, it is said, is one great being which is eternal and immortal. Out of this one unconscious cosmic being has come the whole train of individual things, including man himself. Each individual plays his part in his own day and generation and then sinks back again into this great uncon- scious world-soul out of which he originally sprang. In doing so, he loses his distinctive personal identity but not his essen- tial existence. Just as the drop of rain which falls into the sea loses its own particular individual form in the great indis- tinguishable mass of water, yet not its essential existence, so does man fall back at death, soul and body, intot the one imper- sonal essence of the universe, which is the great eternal God from whom all came and to whom all return. The great philosophic exponent of this view in modern times was Spinoza, although the view is as old as philosophy itself. Its first distinctive advocate was Xenophanes, the founder of the Eleatic School of pre-Socratic philosophy. Religiously, it may be said that the great exponent of this view is Buddha. The heaven, or Nirvana, of Buddhism has long since been a bone of contention, but for all practical purposes of thought it can be regarded as identical with the heaven of the pantheist. It is sometimes erroneously affirmed that Nirvana means annihilation. SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 9 But this is true only with reference to finite personality. Nir- vana, in the true Buddhistic sense, does not mean the annih ilation of existence itself. It means rather the annihilation of finite individuality through the infinite unfolding of individuality until it shall lose its finite limitations in becoming coexistent with the universe itself. It is the annihilation of personality through growth, just as the seed loses itself in the higher existence of the plant, or the ovum in the higher existence of the fuU grown man. Of course, the line of development toward this goal is by no means straight-forward. It is a singularly sinuous one, with numerous backward curvings of repeated reincarnations by means of which the soul is purged of its egoistic impulses and desires and thus made to take on the larger life of an impersonal, cosmic existence. A very clear and sjnnpathetic exposition of this view is given by W. S. Bigelow (7). For the ethical import of this conception of a future existence the reader is referred to C. L. Slattery's Life Beyond Life (61). While not accepting this view of the future as his own, Mr. Slat- tery is nevertheless forced to recognize in it a very lofty ethical principle, the principle of moral solidarity. According to this view the highest ethical effort of man consists in the elimination of all his purely personal and egoistic impulses and desires by merging them into the wider altruistic interests of the race. To quote his own words, Mr. Slattery says: "The selfishness of some forms of the Christian doctrine of immortality is little short of ghastly. The smug satisfaction of the mediaeval saint, leaving the world to its misery and sin that he might fit his own miserable and puny soul for heaven, is not edifying, is not Christian. We have grown to think the saint a truer saint if, with some little flecks from the naughty world, he has stayed in the world and helped to raise others with himself toward the heavenly vision. It is the great and growing sense of brotherhood, of mutual responsibility, that is making us feel that we must reach that other country with the rest of mankind, or it will after aU be a sad and mournful abode for our loving, unselfish hearts. That is the ideal toward which we strive. It is the kernel of vital truth hid within the Buddhist's doctrine of Nirvana.'* In passing, it may be said that we are here dealing with a view of immortality which is widely held today by minds of great refinement and culture. The reason for this we are told is noc far to seek. Besides the ethical charm of an ever-expanding altruism, already referred to, there is inherent in this view the philosophic charm of a monistic conception of the universe 10 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY which tends to satisfy the irresistible propensity of the human mind to mentally construct its material into a universe rather than a multiverse. There is, furthermore, inherent in this view, it is said, the religious charm of a monotheistic conception of the soul's relation to its God, and also the psychological charm of a unifying conception of life which tends mightily to the solidifying of personality, to the knitting together of psychic experiences against the inroads of abnormal dissociations. With all these features to commend it, we are not at all surprised to find this the cherished view of many highly cultivated minds. 4. Personal Immortality. There still remains another use of the term immortality to be considered. This time it is applied to the survival of person- ality itself. It is the theistic conception of the after life, and, as such, is known as ''personal immortality." According to theism, God is not the impersonal soul of the universe, as pan- theism affirms, but is a transcendent personal Being, existing independently of the universe and yet imminent in it as its upholder and providential Ruler. Neither is the human soul a part of the essence of deity, as pantheism affirms. It is rather a secondary essence, a thing derived from the creative activity of deity, which will ever retain its own essential, personal exist- ence apart from, yet in ethical relations with, deity. As to the exact nature of this personal identity there is a wide divergence of opinion among theists. Some hold that the after life will be a continuation of the present but under more favorable condi- tions. Others hold to a sort of cataclysmic conception of death by means of which the soul is to undergo at the moment of its departure from the body a sudden and radical transformation such as will purge out of it all traces of moral imperfection and thus enlarge and intensify its capacities and powers beyond the limit of anything which the most vivid imagination can now envisage. In general, it may be said that there are now held by theists two radically different conceptions of personal immortality. According to the one, the human soul is essentially immortal, immortality being an inherent quality of soul-essence. Accord- ing to the other, the human soul is not inherently immortal but immortable, that is, capable of being made immortal. Those who SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 11 hold to the former view are driven by the logic of the situation to postulate the personal survival of all human beings, good and bad alike, while those who hold to the latter view escape the per- plexing problem of caring for moral degenerates in the after life by affirming that through lack of moral and spiritual cultivation these souls never arrived at the state of actual immortality, the result being that at death they simply go out of existence. In- herent immortality, it may be said, is the orthodox view of pres- ent-day Christian theology. It is held universally in the Greek and Roman Catholic Churches and also by the great majority of Protestant denominations. Whether or not the New Testament teaches inherent immortality is a mooted question. Naturally enough, the advocates of this view say that it does, and adduce not a few passages in its support. On the other hand, the advo- cates of immortability, or ''conditional immortality" as it is com- monly called, say that it does not, and in like manner adduce a respectable array of passages in support of their view. They tell us that the New Testament holds out the hope of immor- tality only to those who receive eternal life through faith in Christ and devotion to that ideal of life by which he lived and for which he died. The idea of inherent immortality, it is said, crept into Christian theology during the Middle Ages at the time when the teachings of Plato played so large a role in the formation of Christian doctrine. The first outstanding voice in modern times to be raised against this so-called relic of mediaeval theology was Rev. Edward White of England. In 1846 he pub- lished a book entitled Life in Christ, in which the conception of attainable, as over against inherent, immortality was strongly advocated. The logic of White's arguments is not generally accepted today. But his book served to call attention to the subject aiid to crystallize certain vague stirrings which were then at work in the minds of men and which have since then, especially within the last few years, taken shape in the well- formed eschatological doctrine of conditional immortality. Scientifically considered, this view has much in its favor. It is the exact counterpart in the theological world of the doctrine of the "survival of the fittest" in the scientific world. As ap- plied to the question of immortality, the doctrine of the ** sur- vival of the fittest" affirms that only those survive death who are morally fit. The rest drop out of the race and become ex- 12 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY tinct. Seizing upon this scientific postulate in support of his view, the advocate of conditional immortality has only to tell us who the morally fit are, who shall survive. They are the spirit- ually renewed, he tells us, the recipients of the immortal life through filial relations with God. It will be observed, of course, that throughout this discussion the standpoint is religious and philosophical. The existence of a spiritual entity called the soul is taken for granted. The only question at stake is this, is this spiritual entity inherently immortal or is it not. One camp of theists says it is, while the other camp says it is not but that it may become immortal. To this latter view one serious objec- tion is raised. It is assumed by the advocates of immortability that the soul is essentially mortal or subject to dissolution and death, but that, by an ethical and spiritual readjustment of its relations to God, it may be made essentially immortal. How, it is asked, can any ethical and spiritual readjustment of relation- ship between God and man effect a change in the essential con- stitution of the human soul? Can love and obedience to God reorganize, so to speak, the constituent elements of the soul so as to ensure it against dissolution and death? What is this essential change which takes place in the soul when it passes from a state of mortality over into a state of immortality? Is it not a pure fiction of the imagination born of a superficial cast of metaphysical thinking ? Such is the objection offered by the advocates of inherent immortality to the doctrine of immorta- bility. And so the battle rages, each side holding its ground with dogmatic tenacity, yet both agreed that whatever of future survival there is, it must be of a personal character. Such then are the four chief uses of the word immortality, the biological, the positivistic, the pantheistic, and the theistic. The first two can hardly be classed under the head of beliefs. A be- lief is a conviction based upon considerations of greater or less probability but falling short of actual knowledge based upon experience. Plasmic and influential immortality are matters of every-day knowledge. We know from experience that these things are so. Cosmic and personal immortality, on the other hand, are matters of belief. They rest not upon experience, but upon presumptive evidence only. It is in these latter two senses, therefore, and especially in the sense of personal immor- tality, that we shall use the term in the remaining part of this paper. SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 13 II. Theories Concerning the Origin of the Belief. It is needless to say that in dealing with the matter of origin we lose ourselves in an exceedingly dense maze of prehistoric uncertainty. The precise point at which, in the unfolding of the human mind, the idea of an after life first dawned upon the threshold of human consciousness cannot be definitely deter- mined. There may be little evidence of its presence during the Palaeolithic age, but there is clear evidence of its presence during the Neolithic period. The ornaments, weapons, tools and food placed by the side of the dead, as well as the sacred drawings upon tombs, etc., all seem to indicate some conception of sur- vival. Especially true is this of the position of the body in the tomb. One of the peculiar features of Neolithic burial was the bent-up posture of the body to represent, apparently, the posi- tion of the foetus in the womb. This fact is now regarded by some ethnologists as a rather strong evidence of a Neolithic belief in human survival. The grave may have been looked upon as the womb of mother-earth from which the soul of the dead was to be born anew into an after life. Some such motive, it is thought, must have induced these early peoples to have placed their dead in such an unnatural position. The question now arises, whence came this belief? How did man ever come to have awakened within him this conviction of an after life? As already stated, we are here dealing with a question that lies entirely outside the sphere of demonstrable certainty. Our best knowledge is wholly a matter of conjecture, based, of course, upon considerations of greater or less proba- bility. Three such conjectures have been advanced. 1. Nativistic Hypothesis. The first theory purporting to explain the origin of the belief in immortality is that known as the ''nativistic" hypothesis. According to this view, man came upon the stage of his earthly existence with the idea of immortality ingrained into the very structure of his mental constitution. Plato, of course, is the classical exponent of this view. His theory is rather unique. He held to the pre-existence of the human soul. Man *s earthly life is a brief span, during which an eternal and immortal soul links itself up for a time with a temporal and perishable body. This spiritual voyager from the other world, in coming over into this tenement of clay, brought with it a full stock of knowledge 14 JOURNAL OP RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY acquired during its earlier existence. This epistemological outfit then furnished the basis of all earthly advancement. The acqui- sition of knowledge for Plato was simply and wholly a process of reminiscence, a lifting up into the focus of clear consciousness that which was previously known but which the process of rein- carnation had for a time obscured. How has man come to the idea of an after life? Plato answers, by calling to mind the fact of his former life. The fact that he has lived carries with it the necessary implication that he will live. And so, out of the depths of his own soul, man fishes up his belief in immortality. This, to be sure, is innateness with a vengeance, and, in the crass form in which Plato held it, is not popular today except among those who still believe in the doctrine of reincarnation, notably the theosophists. But there is a less drastic form of this hypothesis which has been and is held very widely by those who do not believe in reincarnation. Emerson may be cited as a good exponent of this type. In speaking of the origin of the belief in immortality he says: ^'I know not where we draw the assurance of prolonged life, of a life which shoots the gulf we call death and takes hold of what is real and abiding. Here is the wonderful thought. But whence came it? Who put it into the mind. It was not I, it was not you. It is elemental. It belongs to thought and virtue, and whenever we have either we see the bearers of this light. Whenever the Master of the universe has points to carry in his government, he impresses his will in the structure of minds." That expresses very clearly the essence of the nativistic hy- pothesis. Man believes in his own future existence because the idea of such an existence is imprinted upon each human soul by the hand of its Creator. The advocates of this hypothesis are very fond of quoting the experience of Huxley in support of their view. As is well known, Huxley was an avowed agnostic on the subject of immor- tality. He neither affirmed nor denied it. He simply lived a good life and wrought a good work in utter disregard of the future. But strange to say, while he disregarded the future, the future did not disregard him. In spite of all his agnosticism, the thought of an after-life forced itself in upon him with sin- gular persistency. In a letter written to Morley near the close of his life Huxley makes this frank confession. He says : ^ ' It is a curious thing that I find my dislike to the thought of extinction increasing as I get older and nearer the goal. It flashes across me at all SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 15 sorts of times and with a sort of horror that in 1900 I shall probably know no more of what is going on than I did in 1800. I had sooner be in hell a good deal — at any rate in one of the upper circles where the climate and company are not too trying. I wonder if you are plagued in this way." — {Life and Letters, Vol. II, p. 67.) Here, it is said triumphantly by the advocates of nativism, is a striking confirmation of our position. Why was Huxley un- able to shake ofi: this haunting idea of an after life? Simply because it was a part and parcel of the native stock of his soul- furniture. So far, all is plain sailing. Nothing could be more simple and self-evident. We believe we are immortal because the Creator has implanted the idea of immortality into the very texture of our natures. Such is the theory, and so it might stand were it not for the destructive weapons of the restless critic. As all must see, the whole theory rests upon the philo- sophic assumption of the validity of innate ideas, a philosophic bark that has had a stormy sea on which to sail ever since the days of Locke. As it is not within the scope of our present pur- pose to discuss this basal principle on which the theory rests, it must suffice to say that at best it is only an assumption, and, as such, any theory resting upon it can carry weight only in so far as the assumption itself is well grounded. 2. Revelatory theory. A second conjecture which attempts to explain the origin of the belief in an after life is that known as the "revelatory hy- pothesis." According to this theory, the human race did not come into existence with the idea of a future life imbedded within the texture of its psychical operations, but received this idea at a later date through the mediation of a divine revelation. This revelation, it is said, was not an isolated experience of the race, but was a part and parcel of a larger revelation which marks the origin of religion itself. Referring to this view, Dr. Brinton says, in his Religions of Primitive Peoples (p. 43) : **A strong school of Christian writers, led early in this century by Joseph de Maistre and Chateaubriand, and represented in our own tongue by Archbishop Trench, have asserted that all faiths, even the most savage, are fragments and reminiscences, distorted and broken indeed, of a primi- tive revelation vouchsafed by the Almighty to the human race everywhere at the beginning. These have occupied themselves in pointing out the analogies of savage and pagan creeds and rites with those of Christianity in proof of their theory." 16 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY Here, then, we have a view which postulates the origin of the belief in immortality as an integral part of a larger revelation ''vouchsafed by the Almighty to the human race everywhere at the beginning." But what about this original revelation, asks the critic, both as to its historic validity as well as its psy- chological possibility? Here again, it is said, we are standing on the slippery ground of a great philosophic assumption, the assumption of the possibility and validity of a supernatural reve- lation, and with the credibility of this basal assumption, stands or falls the credibility of any theory that is built upon it. 3. Genetic hypothesis. A third conjecture purporting to explain the origin of the belief in a future life is that known as the ' ' genetic hypothesis. ' * According to this view, the belief originated not as the result of an innate idea nor yet as the result of a divine revelation, but rather as the product of man's whole mental reaction to his environment during the early, plastic stages of his psychic de- velopment. The factors involved in this early experience of the race which conspired to produce this belief are variously estimated by the different supporters of this hypothesis. It is generally con- ceded, however, that the tap root of the belief is to be found in the fact of death itself. The human race has never taken kindly to the idea of death. There seems to be a deep-seated desire in every normal human being to live. In fact, so irrepressible and universal is this desire in the whole gamut of life, that Darwin was led to postulate the "struggle for existence" as one of the bed-rocks on which to build his whole theory of evolution by natural selection. ' ' The-will-to-live, " as it has been called, and its counterpart, the dread of death, is regarded, according to the genetic hypothesis, as the basal motivation out of which the belief in immortality originated. In this process of belief -making, dreams are thought to have played an important role. The supposition is that at first primi- tive man looked upon death merely as a deep, prolonged sleep from which the slumberer would sooner or later awaken. Not finding this expectation fulfilled, naturally enough a psychic tension was produced, which issued in dreams concerning the dead. Visions of them were seen. These visions naturally led to the impression that these slumberers left their dwellings at SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 17 night and roamed abroad. Hence arose the idea of a double or second self, which lingered around and was in some way- dependent for its existence upon the same kind of nourishment which had supported the body previous to death. Consequently, food was taken at regular intervals to the tombs of the dead in order to nourish the soul of the departed. Haeckel emphasizes a somewhat different factor. In his Rid- dle of the Universe, he seeks to account for the idea of immor- tality in what he calls a "necessity of emotion." Taking his cue from Kant, that the conviction of immortality is not a postu- late of the pure or theoretical reason but of the practical or ethical reason, he demolishes, to his own dogmatic satisfaction, all the arguments hitherto advanced in support of a rational belief in an after-life, and then, having done so, raises the question, how did this transcendent delusion ever gain its grip upon the human mind. His answer is that it sprang up out of two fundamental emotional cravings of the human soul, the de- sire for a better condition of life than is here enjoyed, and the desire for a happy reunion with loved ones in this better land by and by. Being pressed on every hand by innumerable adversi- ties, and being denied a thousand delights which the heart most eagerly desires, the crucified emotions are said to have taken refuge in consoling dreams of a blissful existence beyond the grave. Others emphasize the element of aspiration as the fundamental motive in giving rise to the belief in an after life. Primitive man, it is said, launched out upon some great undertaking, but before completing his task he is brought face to face with the benumbing fact that he is about to die. Not being allowed to carry out his cherished plan, he commits the execution of it to the hands of another. This, however, fails to satisfy the lofty aspirations of his heart. Proxy attainment will not do. With- out himself his undertaking will be spoiled. No other mind can adequately conceive his ideal, and no other hand can adequately execute its attainment. He must complete the task himself. And so, the wish being father to the thought, as is always the case, there arises in his mind the settled conviction that he will complete his task, that the present life with all its golden possi- bilities is but an earnest of a future life in which all the broken efforts of to-day shall be brought to a successful issue in the larger attainments of to-morrow. 18 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY But, someone asks, how can such a theory of the origin of the belief in immortality explain the universality of this belief as it exists among primitive peoples 1 Granted that such an idea did by some happy accident strike its roots into the soil of some im- aginative soul which was especially favored by native endowment and local environment for the reception of it, how did it come to disseminate itself so universally and at so early a date as the Neolithic Age? The answer given by the genetic hypothesis is that the universality of this belief rests upon a broad psycho- logical principle, the unity of action in human intelligence. Upon this fact the whole science of psychology rests. Unless all normal minds functioned in a somewhat similar fashion, there could be no such a thing as a science of psychology. There could be psychologies of individuals, but no psychology of man as such. Speaking of this law of unitary mental activity, Dr. Brinton says, in his Religions of Primitive Peoples (p. 6) : ''And here I must mention a startling discovery, the most startling, it seems to me, of recent times. It is that these laws of human thought are frightfully rigid, are indeed automatic and inflexible. The human mind seems to be a machine. Give it the( same materials and it will unfailingly grind out the same product. So deeply impressed by this is an eminent modern writer that he lays it down as a fundamental maxim of ethnology that 'we do not think, thinking merely goes on within us.' " The bearing of this broad psychological principle upon the universality of the belief in immortality among primitive peo- ples is clear. The same fundamental laws of psychic activity operated everywhere, giving to all men a like reaction to the data of experience out of which the belief originated. In an article in Harper's Magazine (13), on ''The Survival of Human Personality," Dr. Alexander F. Chamberlain has given, from the genetic point of view, a very clear presentation of the supposed transmutations through which the idea of sur- vival passed > in its early development in the race. At first, primitive man had no conception of a personal immortality. The surviving spirit had little or nothing in common with the personality previous to death. Oftentimes it was looked upon, even, as an evil spirit full of malevolent restlessness. But as the idea and appreciation of personality became clearer in the minds of men, the tendency arose to postulate personal identity in the after life: SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 19 ''One great step was taken when man began to look upon himself as something more than a mere reproductive being. As von Negelein has pointed out, so long as man was regarded as a reproducer of offspring simply, personality and its high implications were impossible and unthought of. The perpetuation of the race having been assumed, the individual might drop out of sight without concern or damage. The birth of his son made the father a mere cipher in the community. The extent to which such a belief could be carried is seen in the ancient Hindu practice, in accordance with which the father who has repeated himself in his son, after imparting to the latter the sacred veda-knowledge, which constitutes him the very image of his parent, retreats soulless, as a beggar, into the forest. His personality has become extinct on earth, and its survival in another world would be a superfluity. At this stage of human thought self -repe- tition, not the evolution of personality, was the care of mankind. And woman fared much worse than man, whose appendage she was. She is con- ceived of at this period as soulless often and devoid of all personality, as also is her child until the soul and the personality of his father are trans- mitted to him.'' The writer then proceeds to show how this impersonal idea was transmuted by slow degrees so as to take on the idea of a personal survival. The first motivation to such a change he finds in hero-worship, and, according to some, the first class of heroes to be immortalized with personal survival was the warrior class. In an age when the dominant interest of man was physical prowess, naturally enough the warrior came to be regarded with special veneration. His worthship to the com- munity was supreme. Indeed, of such transcendent value was his personality to the life of the community, that when he died upon the battlefield fighting for his people it was an easy transition in thought to follow him on in imagination into the other world where he was supposed to survive in full posses- sion of his personal powers to complete the struggle which he had here begun. Having thus risen by slow degrees from the plain of a belief in a mere impersonal survival to the exalted plain of a belief in the personal immortality of the warrior, it was an easy movement in human thought to extend this honor to other great benefactors of the community. And so priests, doctors, poets, and artists all came at an early date to be can- didates for this glorious distinction of personal immortality. Once having started in this direction, there was no obstacle to impede progress until all men were included within its embrace, and thus by slow but sure degrees the race came to its noon-day conviction of a universal, personal survival. 20 JOURNAL OP RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY Such, in brief, are the three leading hypotheses set forth to account for the origin of the belief in an after life. Which of these views best accords with the facts of the case must be left for each individual to decide for himself. And this, we ar«? happy to say, is an entirely safe proposition, for no man's wel- fare either here or hereafter is in any way conditioned by thrr validity of the theory which he may hold with regard to the birth of humanity's idea of an after life. If the idea itself can bear the pragmatic test, the manner of its origin has, after all, only a theoretic interest. III. Grounds Upon Which the Belief Rests. In the interest of clearness we shall divide the arguments advanced in support of immortality into three groups, the phUo- sophicalj the scientific, and the religious. 1. Philosophical grounds. At what particular time in the psychic development of the race man began to philosophize concerning his belief in an after life, seeking to buttress his sentiments and convictions with more or less well-reasoned arguments, we do not know. So far as we do know, it remained for Plato to be the first to formulate arguments which carried with them the authority of a rational demonstration of an after life. The crucial thing in Plato's position was his belief in inherent immortalty. Primitive man, as we have seen, was long in coming to this conception. To him, personality was immortable rather than immortal. But with Plato the idea of inherent immortality stepped out from the shadows of primitive vagueness and once for all made itself felt as a determining factor in the relig- ious and philosophical thought of all succeedages. In a some- what recent work Dr. J. A. Beet (5) traces out the influence of Plato's views upon the formulation of the Christian doctrine of a future life. In a brief resume of the ground over which he has travelled he says : '*We have now traced the popular and traditional doctrine of the end- less permanence of all human souls to the teaching of Plato and to the school of philosophers of which he is the most illustrious representative; and have endeavored to prove that it was altogether alien from the phrase and thought of Christ and his apostles so far as his teachings and theirs are embodied in the New Testament; and that it entered into, and subse- quently became prevalent in, the church mainly through the influence of SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 21 Plato, apparently in the latter part of the second century. We have also considered the teaching of several modem theologians, but have not found any one who seriously endeavors to prove that the immortality of the soul is taught in the Bible" (p.88). With this background of Plato's importance in the field of philosophical argumentation for immortality, let us ask, what were the grounds on which Plato based his belief and whence did he derive it? It is commonly understood that Plato was in- debted for his views regarding an after life chiefly to Pytha- goreanism, the Greek religion, and the Greek mysteries which were essentially immortality cults. The nerve of his argiunent is contained in his **Phaedo.'' In this dialogue Plato has put into the mouth of Socrates his mature thought concerning a future life. In prison, on that fatal day when Socrates drank the poison hemlock, he tells those around him why it is that he can face death so cheerfully. It is because death has no power to destroy his soul. Analyzing the arguments advanced by Plato's Socrates, they are as follows: The soul is seen to be immortal from the fact of its capacity and desire for knowl- edge which it cannot attain in this life; from the law of con- traries which runs all through life and according to which rest prepares for labor and labor for rest, day ends in night and night disappears in day, and so life terminates in death and death in life; from the intuitive character of knowledge, all knowledge being a product of recollection ; from the simple and indivisible nature of the soul, only compound substances being capable of dissolution and death; and finally, from the immu- table goodness of God, God being too good to destroy so beau- tiful a thing as the human soul. These arguments carry little weight with them today. The second, third, and fourth, namely, those based upon the law of contraries, the reminiscent character of knowledge, and the indivisibility of the soul, are the merest ghosts of the human imagination. They rest upon the most arbitrary sort of assump- tions. Only the first and last, namely, that based upon the capacity and desire for unattainable knowledge, and that based upon God's appreciation of the aesthetic value of the human soul, carry any sort of weight for present-day thinking. From the time of Plato on, Greek philosophy ran a zig-zag course in its attitude toward the doctrine of immortality. Aris- totle was ambiguous on the subject, the Epicureans denied it. 22 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY the Stoics accepted it in the cosmic sense, and the Neo-Platonists virtually deified it. Throughout the Middle Ages, and up to our own day, numerous philosophical arguments have been ad- vanced in support of the belief in an after life, all more or less colored with Platonism. In a general way these can be grouped under six different rubrics. The first is the metaphysical argument. It assumes that mind and matter are two distinct entities, each capable of existing apart from the other. The second is the analogical argument. On the basis of numerous analogies drawTi from nature, such as the transforma- tion of energy, the metamorphosis of the chrysalis, and the winter slumber of certain hibernating animals, it is argued that the soul will certainly survive the changes involved in physical death. The classical exponent of this mode of argumentation is Bishop Butler, of whom Huxley said, '' Read Butler and see to what drivel even his great mind descends when he has to talk about the immortality of the soul." The third is the teleological argument, which regards man as purposefully endowed with capacities and powers which fit him for attainments far in advance of anything to which he can possibly achieve in this present life. Closely related to this is the moral argument. This world, it is said, is a scene of injustice. Not infrequently do the virtuous die unrewarded and the vicious unpunished. If death ended all, human life would be a tragedy. But death does not end all. It is the dropping of the curtain between the scenes of one continuous drama of soul-life. It will require the second scene to even up the moral situation to the complete satisfaction of man's deepest sense of injustice, and since justice demands such a scene, we are assured on the ground of the moral argument that such a scene is forthcoming. Kant's argument for the immortality of the soul falls under this same general rubric. To Kant, obedience to an inner sense of duty, the "Categorical Imperative," as he called it, is the supreme obligation resting upon man. Obedience to this inward moral monitor should always lead to happiness, and in a perfect state of existence always does lead to happiness. But man's present state, says Kant, is not one of perfection, and so, as a matter of fact, virtue and happiness do not always go hand in hand in this life. But thej^ are intended to do so, and since their perfect SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 23 unity is not attained here there must be another life in which this unity is attained. Such was the argument of Kant. The weakness of it is clear. On the ground of moral progress, sup- posing the day should ever come when in this present life vir- tue and happiness should always go together, what need then would there be, on the basis of Kant's argument, for an after- life? The goal of attainment for which that life was posited would be reached here and now, and Kant's heaven would be left dangling in mid-air with all of its logical underpinning knocked out from under it. The other argument set forth in support of the belief in immortality is the ethnological. Mankind the world over, holds the idea of an after life. This fact, it is thought, carries with it a very strong presumptive argument in favor of immortality. This mode of reasoning is, of course, as old as the Eleatics. It lies at the very roots of Parmenides' great philosophic assump- tion, an assumption which held its place in the foreground of philosophic thought all the way down to the time of Hegel, namely, that ' ' the thinkable is the real, ' ' But if this were true, says the critic of the ethnological argument, then my latch-key should always be in my pocket whenever I reach for it, for whenever I do reach for it I think it is there. But as a matter of fact it is quite often not there. In such a case the thinkable is certainly not the real. My latch-key is not in my pocket because I think it is there. Neither is my soul immortal, says the same critic, because I think it is or because all men may think it is. On the same ground, it is said, we should be able to prove the reality of ghosts and witches. So far, then, philosophical speculation has helped us but little in the laying of a solid foundation on which to build our hopes for an after life. If such a foundation can be found, it must evidently be sought for elsewhere. 2. Scie7itific grounds. Turning now from philosophy to science in search for light concerning the possible grounds on which to rest a rational belief in immortality, we are confronted with a great variety of personal attitudes. In a general way, scientists can be grouped into three classes on the basis of their attitude toward the subject of immortality. One is the unhelieving class. Re- flecting upon the particular group of scientific data with which 24 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY they are especially familiar, those who constitute this class have come to the settled conviction that there is no such thing as personal immortality. Science, for them, furnishes not only no suggestion of such a thing, but, what is more, it furnishes suggestions which are somewhat opposed to such a view. In the interests of intellectual honesty, therefore, they are obliged to affirm that they do not and can not accept the traditional teachings of religion which posit the personal survival of man beyond this life. Opposed to this group stands the believing class. For them the data of science are but a fragment of the sum-total of all the data upon which human beliefs are to rest. What and if sci- ence does not warrant a belief in personal immortality, it is said. Science is but a late comer upon the field of human his- tory. Its best findings in any department of knowledge are as yet very limited. To make all beliefs square to its present dis- closures would be a hasty step indeed. It has yet much to learn which may greatly modify its present findings. Besides, there are other interests than those of science which demand our serious attention. To cast them aside is to play the foolish part. We need to be progressive, but our progress should always be conservative, holding fast to all that is valuable in our inheri- tance from the past while we push ever onward into new fields of investigation. Religion, while it may not have had a stain- less career, is not altogether an unmixed evil. It has its claims, and these should be recognized. For the most part, the belief in immortality has been a great moral blessing to the race. It has comforted the sorrowing and guided the aspiring. And since there is as yet no positive disproof of the belief, eithei" scientific or otherwise, we do well, it is said, to hold fast to it, conserving it as one of the efficient agencies making for the highest moral development of the race. Midway between these two extremes stands the agnostic class. They neither affirm nor deny the fact of an after life. They simply say, we know nothing about it, it is an open question, it may be true and it may not. If there is such a thing, it is barely possible that some day we shall be fortunate enough to have clear evidence of it. That being so, let us possess our souls in patience, waiting the day of larger disclosures toward which our present age is rapidly advancing. And so we have, as already stated, these three attitudes among scientists, the nega- SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 25 tive believer who says there is no future life, the positive be- liever who says there is a future life, and the neutral believer who says there may and there may not be a future life, I know nothing about it, I stand on absolutely neutral ground and shall continue to stand there until more positive evidence is forth- coming. Clearly enough, to the first and last of these three classes, the negative and neutral believer, science in its present state has no suggestion whatever to offer in support of a rational belief in an after life. But to the second class the matter stands somewhat differently. While not accepting any of the data of science as furnishing a positive proof of immortality, yet they regard some of its findings as furnishing more or less presump- tive evidence in that direction. (a) The conservation of energy. Chief among the postulates of science which are looked upon as pointing toward the possibility of a future life is the doc- trine of the conservation of energy. As all know, it is one of the basal assumptions of science that the sum total of all energy in the universe is a constant factor. Amid the multitudinous changes of nature, energy, we are told, is constantly being changed from one form into another but without any increase or diminution of its quantity. Energy in the form of mechan- ical work may successively pass over into electricity, light, and heat, and in turn be reconverted again into mechanical work, and when the process is completed, we have exactly the same amount of energy with which we started, provided no loss has been sustained on the way. Working inductively on the basis of such experiments as these, the far-reaching inference has been drawn that no change in the whole great universal flux of things ever creates or destroys any energy. It simply converts energy from one form into another. And the same, we are told, is true of mass. As yet we know nothing that can effect the quantity of a given mass. We may subject it to all manner of changes, mechanical or chemical, and yet its quantitative value remains constant. It must be admitted, of course, that such a doctrine as this is nothing short of a far-reaching scientific assumption. As yet, no one has subjected all energy and all matter to the test. But so far as experimentation has been carried the assumption holds, and for all practical purposes it may be regarded as possessing universal validity. 26 JOUENALi OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY And now for the bearing of this fact upon the belief in immortality. Granting that mind is a form of energy, why, it is asked, should the human mind present an exception to this universal law of the conservation of energy which holds through- out the entire domain of the physical universe? If it is reason- able to believe that all the energy entering into the physiological processes of the body during the course of a life-time is con- served without loss, even after death has disintegrated the ele- ments of the body, is it not equally reasonable to believe that all the energy entering into the psychical processes of the mind, which ran their course parallel with the physiological processes of the body, is also conserved even after the dissolution of the body by death? Present day physiology, of course, forbids us assuming any such thing as an interchange of energy between body and mind. Carefully conducted experiments seem to have shown conclusively that the law of the conservation of energy holds within the realm of the human body. No process of thought nor act of will ever creates any energy in the nervous system. The only source of energy for that system is physical nourishment, and it has been clearly shown that the amount of energy expended by the different physiological processes is exactly proportionate to the amount of energy obtained through nourishment. This being so, we are at present obliged to con- ceive of a human being as constituted of two parallel streams of energy, which run side by side throughout the whole course of life, each keeping pace with the other yet neither overflowing its banks at any time to empty its waters into the other. If, now, we are justified in saying that one of these streams is conserved after death, and we know that it is, are we not justified in sup- posing that the other is conserved also ? This, we are told, is a much more scientific view of the case than the opposite, which affirms the conservation of the stream of physical energy and the annihilation of the stream of psychical energy. If one per- sists, and we know that it does, then why not the other ? So far, the advocates of the belief in immortality on the ground of the doctrine of the conservation of energy seem to have the logic of the situation on their side. But, says the opponent of this view, even though the logic of the situation be granted, at best it can argue only for an impersonal immortality. While it is true that the energy of the body does persist after death, yet it does so not as the formative principle of a distinct indi- SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 27 vidual, but in a disorganized condition. So for the psychical side, it is said. Even though the energy of the mind may per- sist after death, yet, on the basis of the analogy assumed, we are allowed to postulate at most its persistence only in a disorgan- ized, impersonal condition, for if these two streams of energy run their course in a perfectly parallel fashion all though the life of the individual what warrant have we for assuming that at death they enter upon divergent courses? Such a supposi- tion, we are told, begs the whole question and is at heart utterly unscientific. And so, there we are. On the basis of the doc- trine of the conservation of energy cosmic immortality, there- fore, seems highly probable, while personal immortality seems highly improbable. (h) The conservation of value. But there is another principle operative in the field of science which is sometimes quoted as favoring a belief in human sur- vival. It is the principle of the conservation of value. Science tells us that this earth on which we live came to its present con- dition through the operation of certain definite forces which worked by slow degrees through millenniums of ages. Beginning with a sort of undifferentiated ball of gaseous nebulae, it is assumed that accretions and condensations gradually took place giving rise to our solar system with its great network of revolv- ing planets. In the course of time the temperature lowered, a rocky core was formed, the surface of this core crumbled into soil, the waters collected into deep basins to form the seas which in turn become the cradle of life. This life, at first a mere uni- cellular speck of protoplasm, slowly evolved into multicellular forms of life, giving rise at last to the highly organized verte- brate, the fish. One day this daring Columbus of the sea in one of its bold innovations ventured out upon the land, took to breathing, developed lungs out of gills, legs and wings out of fins, and thus arose reptiles and birds. Some of these land creatures then improved their condition by becoming viviparous, and thus was ushered in the reign of mammals. Finally, out of mammalian development came the flower of the animal series, man himself. At first he was hardly distinguishable from his twin brothers, the apes, but very soon he began to show his dis- tinctively human qualities by his unique intellectual and moral advancement, until behold him in this twentieth century the 28 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY lord and master of creation. All through this process of devel- opment, we are told, there was present one very distinctive factor, namely the conservation of values. Wherever nature was fortunate enough to hit upon some quality that had in it special worth for the higher ends toward which the whole pro- cess was blindly moving, there attention, as it were, was focused until that quality became a fixed factor in the great evolving system. Labors in this direction were, of course, not always successful. Numerous species on which untold ages of patient toil had been expended, eventually retrograded and became extinct. Devolution as well as evolution marked the whole course of the movement. As one has aptly put it, "The privi- lege of going to hell has ever existed throughout the whole pro- cess of organic evolution." And yet, in spite of all these blind alleys of partial retrogression, the general trend of the whole movement was ever onward and upward, so that the forces of the universe have not labored in vain but have attained sublime success in the conservation and reinforcement of their best productions. Such has been the course of events so far. Each new age has been a distinct advance upon the preceding one, reaching, as we have, the present age with highly refined moral personality as the ripest product of the whole process. And now comes the question as to the ultimate goal of all this. Is the process to stop here? Is moral personality, with all of its marvellous pos- sibilities, and for the production of which all the creative energy of the universe has worked with infinite patience through mil- lenniums upon millenniums, a mere transient bubble to be burst by the hand of physical death ? Is this supreme value of the uni- verse, for the creation of which all other values have been merely auxiliary, a mere will-o-the-wisp which the forces of nature have been vainly chasing through all the ages ? Was Heraclitus right ? Is the universe nothing more than a grinding mill with an empty hopper? Is no grist ever ground out? Does nothing of per- manent value ever emerge out of thic gigantic process of ** be- coming '^ with all of its sacrifice and suffering? Where in all the universe have we ever yet seen this developing process turn back upon itself, and what grounds have we for assuming that it ever will do so ? Is it not far more reasonable to suppose that death, instead of being the annihilation of personality, is but an incident in a great cosmic process of evolution, and that this SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 29 highest value so far attained, instead of becoming extinct, is conserved and made the nexus of union with another order of existence which is as much in advance of the present as the human is in advance of the animal? Unless this be so, then the universe is indeed a ' ' riddle ' ' as Haeckel has denominated it. And so, the belief in personal immortality, we are told, is the necessary correlate of the scientific doctrine of the conservation of value which lies at the very basis of the whole evolutionary hypotheses. As T. H. Green has expressed it, "it is impossible to believe without intellectual confusion that a system whose visible goal is the evolution of personality ends in the extinction of personality." To be sure, strenuous opposition has been offered to this idea of personal immortality, as supported by the conception of the conservation of values. The principal point of attack has been the fact of the correlation between mind and brain. Physiolog- ical psychology has shown us that all mental processes, so far as we know anything about them, are intimately correlated with corresponding brain processes. What the exact nature of this correlation is no one as yet knows. But whatever its exact nature may be, it is there. Destroy those centers in the brain that function for speech or sight or hearing and you render at once the subject mute or blind or deaf, as the case may be. The evident conclusion seems to be that if you destroy all the centers of the brain, as is the case in death, you thereby destroy all the psychical operations which have been correlated with those cen- ters. In his little book on Human Immortality (38), the late Professor William James has sought to clear the ground of this objection. He recognizes two kinds of functional dependence, a productive and a transmissive function, and in his judgment the functional dependence of the mind upon the brain is not a productive but a transmissive function. Thought is not a pro- duct of brain activity in the sense that bile is a secretion of the liver. If it were, then, of course the destruction of the brain would involve the annihilation of the mind. But thought, he holds, is rather transmissively dependent upon brain activity. It may exist quite independent of all neural processes and yet without those processes be utterly unable to make itself known. In such a case the destruction of the brain would in no wise involve the annihilation of the mind. In the thought of Pro- fessor James, the nervous system stands related to the physical 30 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY world on the one hand, and to the mental world on the other hand somewhat as the Atlantic cable stands related to Europe and America. You may destroy the cable, but in so doing you do not destroy either Europe or America. You simply cut off their means of inter-communication. So for the nervous sys- tem. Destroy it and the line of communication between mind and the external world is gone, but mind itself is in no sense destroyed thereby. A less scientific, but somewhat ingenious, attempt has been made by various other writers to solve this problem attempted by Professor James. The view assumes that there is encased within the visible body a semi-material body of like shape and size, which serves as the connecting link between the physical and the mental. At death this transparent duplicate takes its departure from the body with the soul, and serves thereafter as the material basis of the soul's activity. If the reader is interested in this solution of the problem, he will find a good discussion of it in D'Albe (17), Bjorklund (8), and Frank (22). (c) Spiritism. In recent years science has interested itself in seeking to establish objective demonstration of the validity or invalidity of the belief in immortality. Assuming that there are surviving spirits, the aim has been to get into speaking communication with them. To this end, certain individuals are chosen as ' ' me- diums" through whom these spirits communicate their thoughts to certain inhabitants of earth. The supposition is that in some way, quite unknown to us of course, the soul of the medium vacates the body for a time during which period some spirit from the other world takes its place as the "control" of the medium, making use of the physiological mechanism of the body as a means of communicating its thought either by vocal utter- ance or by written language. Claims to performances of this sort have been in existence for a long time, but no scientific attention was given to them until within recent years. The first systematic effort to study them was made by the British Society for Psychical Research. When this Society was organ- ized in 1882, one of its aims was the investigation of the claims of spiritism. This aim it has pursued with much diligence. Its findings, not only in this field but also in the fields of tele- SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 31 pathy, crystal-gazing, hypnotism, clairvoyance etc. are simply enormous. Out of all that has been done by this Society, both in England and America, have evolved three distinct attitudes with refer- ence to the subject of spiritism. One is the attitude of implicit faith in an objective demonstration of the existence of spirits. It is believed by not a few that clear evidence has been estab- lished of actual communication with departed spirits through the agency of mediums. A second attitude is that of suspended judgment. To the members of this class, much of the evidence collected by the Society seems to warrant a belief in the validity of spirit-communication, and yet the possibilities of error are sufficiently great to act as a counter-balance, leaving the mind in a state of suspended judgment. A third attitude is that of radical scepticism. It is held by the members of this class that all the data of the Society bearing upon the subject of spiritism can be adequately explained on the basis of multiple person- ality. The exit of a medium's soul out of the body and the entrance of a departed spirit in its place is said to be nothing other than the splitting off for the time being of a fragment of the medium's normal personality and causing it to function in an abnormal way. This role it very soon learns to play with singular skill. Clues of knowledge suitable for its purposes which are carried over from the normal state, suggestions re- ceived from those present at the time of the seance, and venture- some guesses some of which fit while many do not, these form the stock in trade of the split-off personality or assumed "Con- trol." Of all the mediums studied by the Society, none has been more baffling than Mrs. Piper of Boston. Professor James called her his "white crow," with reference to the whole sub- ject of spiritism. While fraud has been repeatedly discovered in other mediums, no fraud has as yet been made out in connec- tion with the seances of Mrs, Piper. A careful study of her case has been made of late by Dr. G. Stanley Hall and Dr. Amy E. Tanner. The results of their investigations have appeared in a recent book by Dr. Tanner (64). The book is a wholesale slaughter of the spiritistic hypothesis. It seeks to explain not only Mrs. Piper 's case but also the whole body of spiritistic data gathered by the Society for Psychical Research on the basis of multiple personality. Naturally enough, the book has called 32 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY down upon its authors a volley of criticism from certain mem- bers of the Society. What effect the book will ultimately have upon this whole movement yet remains to be seen. It is hoped, however, by many who agree with its interpretation of the facts, that it will serve, at least, to counter-balance certain extrava- gances which have manifested themselves in connection with this study of spiritistic phenomena. Taken as a whole, what has the study of spiritism done by way of confirming the belief in immortality? Its chief service has been to call attention to the subject, and in an age of mate- rialistic tendencies this has had its value, no doubt. But so far as furnishing positive evidence of immortality is concerned, its results are of a doubtful character to say the least. And what else could be expected? The world of disincarnate spirits is rather an awkward sphere for science to investigate. It is a sufficiently difficult task to gather valid scientific data on this mundane world of ours, but to collect valid scientific data from a super-mundane world, and have it transmitted to earth through the channel of a pathological personality, seems like a hopeless task indeed. And further, supposing that a considerable body of trustworthy scientists should succeed in gaining what to them would be incontrovertible evidence of communication with spirits, and supposing they should couch their findings in a permanent literary form, how much weight would their testimony have for the generations following them, by way of settling once for all the fact of immortality? Would it have any more weight than the evidence for the resurrection of Christ, contained in the New Testament, has for the average scientist to-day ? He snaps his finger at such evidence. To him it is a case of establishing miracle on the basis of human testimony, a task which Hume convinced most of the scientific world years ago can not be accomplished. Strange conceit this is of the scientist that he should regard his own word as of so much more value than that of a company of honest fishermen two thousand years ago. Free communication with disembodied spirits can never be a common- place of human experience. If such a thing is possible, and possible only through certain select mediums, then it must ever remain a sweet luxury for the few, and, as such, an extraordi- nary and rather miraculous occurrence. That being so, it can never carry with it the weight of a universally convincing proof of human survival, according to the verdict of science itself. We SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 33 would not under any consideration put a handicap upon scien- tific investigation in any field, but it does seem as though there must be a better way for a noble soul to build up its assurance of immortality than by raking among the pathological abnor- malities of multiple personalities. So far, then, the scientific grounds for a belief in immortality are on about the same footing with those of philosophy. Neither one is conclusive. While there are certain phenomena which seem to point in the direction of personal survival, there are others which seem to point just as definitely in the opposite direction, leaving us, from a scientific point of view, in a state of suspended judgment. 3. Religious grounds. But philosophy and science are not the only points of view from which the belief in an after life may be considered. In fact, they are not the primary standpoints from which to view this subject. In the last analysis the question of immortality is a religious question. As John Fiske has said, "it must ever remain an affair of religion rather than of science." Scien- tifically we may never be able to demonstrate the fact of an after life, assuming that there is such a life. And yet, the rank and file of humanity ever has believed, still does believe, and for aught we now know will continue to believe in a future life, notwithstanding the negative testimony of science. The reason for this is to be found in the fact that the belief is fundamentally motivated by considerations which are essentially religious. And this is legitimate. As has already been stated, religion has its rightful place in the general scheme of human affairs. And when religion is pressed to its ultimate psychological analysis it is found to concern itself chiefly with the emotional aspect of man's mental life. We may not wholly agree with Schleier- macher's definition of religion as a ''feeling of dependence,** and yet Schleiermacher put his finger on the right place when he found in feeling the essence of religion. Other elements enter into it of necessity, but here we are at the center. As one has said, ''Religion is the meeting of spirit with spirit, the flush of happiness, the thrill of satisfaction, the sense of peace, the glad realization that now at last a hunger, keener than physical hunger, has been appeased by the heavenly bread. God and the soul have met, and in the shock of that meeting there 34 JOURNAL OP RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY has come to the soul an emotion of loving fellowship which is the very heart of religion." Of course, it must be understood that religion has to do with cognition as well as with emotion. The preacher struck a wrong note, when, in the course of his sermon, he said: "Few things have done more harm in this world than thought. Don't put me down, my dear friends, as a thinker, put me down as a believer." The audience is said to have remarked afterward that the preacher had placed before them a very unnecessary precaution. Such an attitude is, of course, a travesty on religion. And yet, it serves to show by way of exaggeration where the primary interests in religion lie. They lie not in the rational processes of cognition, but in the affective processes of the emotions. And this being so, we shall find on close investigation that the belief in immortality, which is primarily a religious belief, finds its strongest support, not in the intellect where philosophy and science move and have their being, but in the affections where religion moves and has its being. Taking the Christian religion, which is pre-eminently the religion of personal immortality, there are two fundamental motivations to the belief in a future life. One is the attitude of Jesus himself toward the future, and the other is the doc- trine of his resurrection. Which of these two has had the greater influence in the past it would be difficult to say. Pos- sibly the balance has held a fairly horizontal position. But to-day there is a slight inclination on the side of the former. The deeper men's lives become rooted in the conviction of a personal God, to whom they are related in a vital and filial way, the less do they look for objective proofs of immortality, and the more do they come to rest the whole burden of their faith upon that inner sense of assurance which results from a loving and trustful attitude toward God. And this, we are told, is the true Christian ground on which the belief in immortality should ever rest. It was the one ground on which Jesus' belief in immortality rested. While it is true that he did at one time argue for immortality with the unbelieving Sadducees on the ground of the teachings of the old Testament, yet he did so for their sakes and not for his own. His own belief had its roots not in any book but in a great experience, the sense of Sonship. The fact of an eternal and immortal God to whom he was related by an indissoluble tie of filial affection was one of the most real SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 35 factors in the consciousness of Jesus. His whole life may be looked upon as the unfolding of this conviction, and his whole attitude toward the future was the blossom of this conviction. When he spoke of the future, it was his "Father's house" to which he was going and to which he would ultimately lead his people. He had no long drawn out arguments, based upon logical deductions, to offer in support of his belief. The future life was to him as real as the present life, and all because he was the Son of an immortal Father, whose immortal life he shared. And ultimately, it is said, here is where the Chris- tian 's faith in immortality should ever rest, not so much in the objective evidence of the resurrection of Christ, valuable as that may be, but in the subjective evidence of God's life in the soul. We are to take our stand where Jesus took his stand, not upon logic, but upon the experience of the heart in its relation to God. Am I God's child, have I the divine life in me? If so, I am the immortal child of an immortal Father, and in the sweet consciousness of this fact my heart should rest. IV. Present Status of the Belief. Having thus outlined the different forms which the belief in immortality has assumed, the different theories which have been advanced to account for its origin, and the different grounds on which it has rested, we are now ready to consider the present status of the belief as determined by our own empirical study. No sweeping deductions can be made from our limited survey. The results obtained are suggestive rather than exhaustive. In order to ascertain approximately how this subject of an after life is lying to-day in the minds of intelligent, thinking people, the following list of questions was drawn up and distributed over a wide area both in America and Canada. 1. Do you believe in man's immortality I If not possessed of a belief in immortality, do you hold it as a hope? 2. What kind of immortality do you believe in, personal or cosmic or merely influential? 3. Are all men immortal? If not, who are? 4. What are your reasons for believing in, or not believing in, man's immortality? 5. What is your conception of the state of the after life? Is it a mere continuation of the present state or is it different? 6. Did the question of immortality in any way lead to your ''conver- iion" or acceptance of the Christian faith, in case you have accepted it? 36 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY 7. Have your views on immortality undergone any radical change with the lapse of years? If so, when, and in what respects? 8. If given your preference, which would you choose, immortality or annihilation? Why? 9. What influence has your belief in immortality upon your own con- duct, character, and life? 10. In your judgment, how did the belief in immortality originate in the race? 11. In your judgment, has the race been profited or not by its belief in immortality? If profited, how? If not, why? 12. In your judgment, is the belief in immortality increasing or decreas- ing in the race? If either, why and among what particular class or classes? 13. In your judgment, has the belief in immortality acted in any way as a cause of or as a preventive against suicide? 14. In your judgment, what effect would a complete annihilation of the belief in immortality have upon the race, directly and ultimately? 15. Has the modern pulpit changed its message regarding immortality? If so, how, and with what effect? 16. What weight do you attach to the general belief in immortality as an evidence for immortality? 17. What was the attitude of Jesus toward immortality, and what weight do you give to his attitude? 18. What value do you attach to the doctrine of the resurrection of Christ as an evidence for immortality? 19. Is science to-day in conflict with a rational belief in personal im- mortality? If so, how? 20. In your judgment, can the fact of immortality, if it is a fact, ever be established on scientific grounds? If not, why not? 21. Is a belief in immortality necessitated by the doctrine of evolution? If so, why? If not, why? 22. Is a belief in immortality necessitated by the doctrine of the conser- vation of energy? Why? 23. In your judgment, has ''THE SOCIETY FOR PSYCHICAL EE- SEARCH^' in England and America made any contribution toward a solution of the problem of immortality? If so, what? 24. Should children be taught adult views of the after life or be left to frame their own views of it? 25. Does the desire to be reunited again with loved ones act in any way as a spur to your belief or hope in immortality? 26. Has the thought of "helP* in any way influenced your life? 27. What is your age? 28. Is your sex male or female? 29. What is your occupation? 30. Any remarks or suggestions. The parties to whom copies of these questions were sent were in most cases the writer's own personal acquaintances from whom he had every reason to expect serious and honest answers. One hundred and seventy such answers were secured. Of these, SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 37 forty-six belonged to the High School level, twenty to the college level, and one hundred and four to the professional level which included lawyers, physicians, teachers, preachers, etc. We shall deal with the professional class first. Of this group seventy-five believed in personal and seven in cosmic immor- tality. Thirteen rejected the idea of a future life altogether. The only immortality for man, they held, is that of influence. Nine were uncertain as to the kind of future life they believed in, but vaguely hoped for a continued existence of some sort. Fifty believed that all human beings are immortal. Fifteen affirmed that only a part of humanity will survive death, that part being "the good" and "believers in Christ." Twenty-six were in doubt in regard to the matter, and thirteen affirmed that none are immortal. As to the reasons given for the belief in a future life, the teaching of the Bible was named fifty-three times, the general belief in immortality thirty-four times, the incompleteness of this life eleven times, the doctrine of the conservation of energy as applied to personality five times, the doctrine of evolution or of the conservation of values three times, the influence of early training seven times, the influence of the dead twice, the law of the fitness of things twice, boundless aspiration, dread of ex- tinction, and simple faith were each named once. Fifty reported themselves as having experienced no impor- tant change of view, while fifty-four reported radical changes of view. The character of the changes indicated were a turn- ing away from a belief in inherent to a belief in conditional immortality; a turning away from a gross material conception of an after life to a more refined spiritual conception of unfet- tered psychical activity; a turning away from a belief in only human survival to a belief in the survival of all animal life ; a turning away from the conception of a heaven of mere song to a heaven of service ; a turning away from a definite belief to a rather vague hope ; and a turning away from all belief and hope to a state of utter disbelief. The particular time in life at which these changes occurred were : * ' After reading the Origin of Species and the Descent of Man ; * ' ' * after my second year in College as the result of my philosophical and psycholog- ical studies ; * ' < < after my graduate work in science ; ' ' ' ' after my theolog- ical and psychological studies; '* *' during early adolescence;*' ''at the age of twenty-five;" and ''after a careful study of the Scriptures.'* 38 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY One said the doctrine of immortality had been an important factor in helping to upset his faith in Christianity as a whole. His case is so extraordinary that I feel constrained to note it somewhat in detail. He is an eminent physician, fifty-one years of age. I quote his own words: '^I believed in immortality up to the age of fifteen. By twenty-three I had become somewhat doubtful, as my belief in the Bible as the 'Word of God' was fading out, but, as I had never looked closely into the matter, I kept my judgment in suspense. At a later age, I developed consumption of the lungs and became fully persuaded that I had only a few months to live. I then resolved to attempt to settle the matter, and, as I felt that the belief in immortality was bound up with that of the inspiration of the Bible, I began my investigation at the first chapter of Genesis in connec- tion with Adam Clarke's Commentaries. With every chapter my belief in inspiration faded. I did, for a short time, try to persuade myself that Jesus was really divine and was sent by a beneficent Deity to teach the human race, but further study forced me to give up the New Testament also. With the belief in Christianity as a divine system went the doctrine of immortality. Nearly thirty years more of reading science, old theology and new theology, together with such casual thought as I have been able to employ, have only confirmed the conclusions framed then. I would, how- ever, if given my choice prefer immortality to annihilation, provided I could be assured against excessive pain and monotony. My reason is that there Is so much more that I want to know. I would like to spend — not eternity perhaps — but a very, very long time examining into the mysteries of the universe. ' ' There were other returns in which the changes in belief indi- cated were just as radical as this, but the case of this man seemed especially significant in view of the fact that the read- justment of his belief took place as a result of a careful inves- tigation of the Scriptures and that at a time when death seemed near at hand. Ninety-five preferred immortality. The reasons given were: ''For the joy of loving and serving; " "for the sake of the improved con- ditions expected ; " < ' for the sake of a life of harmony with God ; " "be- cause of my repugnance of the idea of annihilation;" "because life is sweet ; " * < from a desire to solve life 's enigmas ; " "in order to complete this incomplete life ; ^ ' ' ' for the opportunity of progress ; ' ' and ' ' for the joy of living and working without tiring." Two preferred annihilation, one giving as his reason the fact that "annihilation is nature's order to which I cordially submit." Twelve had no preference, except to prefer such as should be, whether annihilation or immortality. SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 39 As to the influence which this belief has upon character and life, eighty-two said that it has a beneficial influence. The ex- pressions used were : **It inspires me to altruistic service;'* **it makes life worth living;'* * * it makes me desire to grow like God in character ; " * ' it restrains me from evil ;" "it inspires progress in personal holiness ; ' ' * * it holds me to the right ;'* "it gives dignity and range to my life and character ;" "it stimulates fidelity to duty;" and "it gives my life hope and purpose.*' Seventeen said the belief had no influence upon their life. Five were unable to tell whether it had or had not an influ- ence upon them. As to its racial influence ninety-three affirmed that the race has been profited by the belief. Nine were in doubt in this respect. One expressed the opinion that the belief has been a positive hindrance to the race in that it has diverted man's attention from the proper business of life, which is the material and moral improvement of this present world, and has focused his attention upon another world which he knows nothing about and will never reach. One said the belief was both a help and a hindrance to humanity. In the case of some it inspired hope and progress, while in the case of others it fostered depression and even insanity by holding up before the mind the gruesome picture of loved ones roasting in a hell of endless torment. Twenty-seven held that the belief is decreasing. There was pretty general agreement that this decrease is found principally among the educated classes. One, however, was of the opinion that the decrease is confined chiefly to the religiously liberal classes of Northern Europe who are temperamentally shallow and cynical in their mental characteristics. As to the causes of this decline, it was thought to be brought about : "As the result of scientific study, which demands the evidence of the senses as over against that of mere faith ; " "as the result of the doctrine of evolution;" "as the result of the psychological fact of the correlation betwen mind and brain ; " "as a result of the teachings of pagan reli- gions ; ' ' and " as a result of the present-day greed for gold. ' * Thirty, on the other hand, said that the belief is increasing. Some distributed this increase among all classes, others confined it to the educated, others said it is increasing wherever Christianity is being taught, and one made bold to af&rm that "'It is increasing among all classes, except a few college men and a few fool preachers." Eleven were of the opinion that the belief is relatively stationary. 40 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY With regard to suicide, fifty-seven held that the belief in immortality has acted as a preventive. As evidence of this, it was cited that there are few suicides among Roman Catholics, who as a body hold firmly to the doctrine of immortality; that the greatest number of suicides are found in non-religious com- munities where the belief in an after life is not held, as is shown by a study of French and German suicides; and that religious workers among persons of suicidal tendencies are at one in their testimony to the great restraining power which this belief has over persons contemplating the act of suicide. One teacher was very emphatic on this point. He said: ''It is indeed a powerful preventive, as I know from personal experience in dealing with persons of suicidal tendencies. '' One called atten- tion to the fact that among primitive peoples this belief has acted as a cause of suicide. Firmly believing in the reality of a future life, these people rushed on by self-inflicted death to enter into that life. Twelve said that the belief acted both as a cause and a preventive, citing examples like those given above. Twelve expressed the opinion that the belief has had no influence either for or against suicide, suicide being the result of a pathological condition of mind with which the belief in a future life has no connection whatever. Eighty-five were of the opinion that an annihilation of the belief would work untold harm to the race, both immediately and ultimately. The particular lines of harm indicated were : ''It would lower the value now set upon human life and thus cause a reversion to the animal state;" *'it would dull aspiration;" ''it would take away hope and destroy man's peace of mind; " "it would check spirit- ual development;" "it would usher in the reign of unrestrained immor- ality;" "it would increase suicide amazingly;" "it would destroy the moral and religious sanctions that now sustain the race;" and "it would obliterate all altruism and spiritual aspiration." \ One replied with the following quotation from the late Senator Hoar: "No race or nation will ever be great or will long maintain greatness unless it holds fast to the faith in a living God, in a beneficent Providence, and in a personal immortality. To man as to nation, every gift of noblest origin is breathed upon by this hope's perpetual breath. "Where this faith lives are found courage, manhood, power. Where this faith dies, courage, manhood, and power die with it." Two expressed the opinion that an annihilation of the belief in a future life would prove a blessing to humanity in that it SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 41 would give greater emphasis to the worth of this present life and thus elevate the general moral tone of society. Both, how- ever, were of the opinion that the belief should be destroyed gradually rather than suddenly. Three said that an annihi- lation of this belief would have no important effect, either immediately or ultimately. The relation of the modern pulpit to the belief in an after life was variously estimated. Sixty-two were agreed that the pulpit has changed its message concerning the future. The lines of change indicated were varied. Some held that the present-day pulpit has turned very generally from a belief in personal to a belief in cosmic immortality. Others, that it has turned from personal to influential immortality. And still others held that it is rapidly moving toward an acceptance of the doctrine of reincarnation. There was pretty general agree- ment, however, that the pulpit of today is saying less about an after life than the pulpit of earlier days had to say about it, and that, when it is spoken of, the idea of hell is almost, if not quite, ignored. Most of this class of respondents were of the impression that this change is for the better in that it leads to the acceptance and formation of a good life from higher motives than that of fear. A few, however, said that this change is for the worse in that the pulpit is failing to use the motive of fear which, they said, has been the great moral educator of the race. One of this class expressed the belief that the reason why the pulpit of to-day is either silent altogether or else exceedingly cautious in its utterances about the future is because both preacher and people alike are at the present time utterly at sea on the whole subject. Twelve were of the opinion that the modern pulpit has not changed. Seventy-seven said that Jesus assumed the fact of immor- tality, and that his attitude carries with it the greatest weight possible as an evidence for the reality of an after life in view of the fact that he was the most spiritually minded teacher that the world has ever known. Fifteen, however, took the opposite view and said that the attitude of Jesus carried no more weight than that of any other good man. Two, in fact, said that his attitude carried less weight than that of an intel- ligent scholar of to-day. To quote their own words: "The testimony of Jesus to an after life is of no more value than that of any other man of his day, and is not to be compared with that of a 42 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY modern scientist of good standing •'' ^' Jesus imbibed the belief in immor- tality from his environment and was not in as good a position as we are today to judge of its truth.'' Twelve said they had no idea whatever what Jesus' attitude was toward the belief in an after life. In regard to the doctrine of Christ's resurrection, seventy- six held it to be the crowning evidence of a future life. A few others were inclined to attach less evidential value to the story of the resurrection, regarding it merely as a co-ordinate factor in the general group of evidences for an after life. All of these seventy-six respondents, however, were at one in their belief that the resurrection of Christ is a well authenticated fact of history. Fifteen, on the other hand, said that the story of the resurrection is not an established fact of history, and, therefore, carries no weight as an evidence for immortality. Two physicians replied in substantially the same terms, the exact words of one being, ''The teaching concerning the resur- rection of Christ is by no means an established fact. It is utterly lacking in historical confirmation." One man said, ''Even if a physical resurrection did take place, it would by no means prove immortality." One scientist of wide repute said, "While I believe in personal immortality yet I do not base my belief upon the doctrine of the resurrection of Christ. I regard Hume's argument as never having been answered." Hume's argument, as we all know, was that "Nothing that is of less frequent occurrence than the falsity of human testi- mony can be proved by testimony." Thirteen said that they had never given the story of the resurrection any thought, and were not in a position, therefore, to say what bearing it had upon the belief in an after life. Fifty-five were of the opinion that science is not in conflict with a rational belief in personal immortality. Fifteen took the opposite view. One psychologist, of international reputa- tion, said, "It is, I believe, impossible to disprove personal immortality by scientific reasoning, because of the lack of data one way or the other. I think, however, that science makes it extremely improbable." An eminent physician says: "Science, so far as I am aware, finds no evidence upon which to found a rational belief in personal immortality. Since the scientific spirit teaches us to believe only those things which are proved, to disbelieve those which SPiDLE: IMMORTALITY 43 are disproved, and to hold our judgment in suspense in regard to other matters, we must be content to leave, at least, the doctrine of personal immortality in doubt." Thirty-four had no idea how science stands related to the belief in personal immortality. As to the possibility of science proving the reality of an after life, granted that there is such a life, fifteen believed such a thing possible. One scientist of note said, *'No man can foretell what science will be able to do." Another scien- tist said, "Science has already so far outstripped in its dis- coveries the expectations of a generation ago that it would not be at all surprising if in this matter of an after life it should also outstrip our present expectations and lay bare to us facts which now seem utterly beyond the limit of its apparent sphere. ' ' Sixty, on the other hand, were of the opinion that science can never establish the fact of an after life, granting the reality of such a life. The grounds upon which their convictions were based can all be summed up in one sentence, namely, science can never prove the existence of a future life because it has no data upon which to work and can obtain no data, for the reason that science deals only with the experiential facts of man's present life while immortality lies entirely outside the sphere of such experience. Forty-one regarded the doctrine of evolution as lending no support whatever to the belief in an after life. To quote the words of one, ''The doctrine of evolution argues more for mor- tality than it does for immortality, for if the lower species are mortal, as we know they are, why not the higher species, includ- ing man himself." A prominent physician says: **The doctrine of evolution appears to me to oppose a belief in personal immortality. Individual plants and animals, species, races, nations, planets, stars, systems, and now it seems perhaps even the chemical elements, arise, grow old, and die. The elements of which they are composed live on and are reincarnated in other forms, but that which distinguished them — their individuality — disappears. Why should we expect an exception to be made in favor of one, even the highest, species of animals?" With minor variations, this was the line of reasoning followed by all of those indicated above. Opposed to them stood twenty- eight who regarded the doctrine of evolution as furnishing rather strong presumptive evidence in favor of personal immor- tality. The gist of their position has already been given under 44 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY the head of 'Hhe conservatism of values" in discussing the scientific grounds of the belief. In like manner did opinions differ as to the evidential value of the doctrine of the conservation of energy. Thirty affirmed that it has no value as an evidence for personal immortality but that it does favor the idea of cosmic survival. Says one, **Is my mind 'energy' or some manifestation of it? If so, I would expect it to live on after death but not in the form of my personality. As a matter of fact I believe that mind is as inde- structible as energy or matter." Another says, "Only the imagination of a protagonist could detect any analogy here." Another says, "If the doctrine of the conservation of energy furnished any support to the idea of personal immortality then every living creature from time immemorial to time immemorial must be immortal." Another says, "Life and energy are not in the same category, so that the conservation of the one by no means argues for the conservation of the other." Twenty-nine took the opposite view and said that the doctrine of the con- servation of energy does support a belief in personal immor- tality. In fact, one prominent scientist gave this as the only ground of her belief in personal immortality, "the doctrine of the conservation of energy as applied to personality." Forty-eight were of the opinion that "The Society for Psy- chical Research" has made no contribution whatever toward a solution of the problem of immortality. Two believed that it has done something for the belief by calling general attention to the subject. Eight took the opposite ground and said that this Society has made a most invaluable contribution in that it has established beyond all reasonable doubt the validity of spirit-communication. Sixty-one favored the idea of children being taught adult views of immortality. Thirty-one objected to this. The rea- sons given were that: * ' Children are shrewd enough to frame their own views, which they do ; * ' '*it is wrong to inculcate views into a child's mind which may later have to be repudiated. Teach only those things to a child which are known to be true and which the child will never have occasion to repudiate, and let all debatable matters like that of a future life take care of themselves ; ' ' *^ children should not have adult views of religious matters thrust upon them but should be given the Bible and allowed to frame their own views therefrom ;" ' ' it is better for the child not to force into its mind adult views upon any subject but rather to guide its processes in the framing of SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 45 its own views ; ' ' and "it is of much greater importance to teach the child how to obtain immortality than to attempt to teach it about immortality. ' ' Twelve were in doubt as to whether children should or should not be taught adult views of an after life. It was acknowledged by fifty-nine that the desire to be reunited to loved ones acted as a spur to their belief in a future life. Two couched their sentiments in the following phrases: ' ' I long for the touch of a vanished hand ; " * ' I would like to see my mother, God grant that I may go to her." Here I should add the case of a young lawyer from whom I obtained the following statement. I had given him a copy of our ques- tionnaire some months before this, with a promise on his part to fill it out and return it to me. Months passed by and the syllabus was not returned. One day he came to me with this statement : "1 am sorry to say I have never been able to fill out your syllabus. I took it home, laid it on the shelf in the dining room, and every day took it down and looked over the questions and talked them over with my wife while engaged in the noon meal. Honestly, I have worn out that sheet of paper handling it over and looking at the questions, but I have not an- swered one of them and I cannot answer them. When I try to reason this matter out on the basis of logic I say to myself, of course there is no future life. But, on the other hand, my father died a few years ago and I cannot but believe that I shall see him again. That is how I think and feel, and, if you can reconcile that contradiction you know what my belief in immortality is.'* With regard to the belief in "Hell," fifty-five said that it never had any influence over their life. Forty affirmed that it had. A few specified as to the exact nature- of this influence. One said, "the thought of hell has had an influence for good over my life ever since I can remember." Another said, "the thought of hell hindered me from joining the church for a year or two." A third said, "for a time the thought of hell upset my faith in everything and caused me much misery." And another said, "only as a child did the thought of hell have any influence over my life, and then it introduced into my experience an element of tragedy which was entirely needless and which interfered for a time with both my mental and moral development." Some of the "Remarks" appended to our returns were of considerable significance. One psychologist of wide repute says : 46 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY ''If I should try to sum up my views in general, I should say that the whole question is one that has become a side issue in my life, — one on which I do not hold any very vital opinions, such as I do have being rather in the negative. I hold them lightly and in a way to be somewhat easily changed, I suppose, by scientific evidence if any were forthcoming, or by those funda- mental emotional determinants (which I think are at the root of the belief in those that hold it strongly) if any should rise in my own life. ' ' Another says: ''My impression is that all these questions refer to reason, omitting the great field of feeling, which may be just as meaningful as that which our poor intellects can comprehend. The only incontestable argument for im- mortality, incontestable because unanswerable, is the argument of the heart. When I see injustice, suffering, sorrows of parting, and incompleteness in this life, my heart longs to give those who desire it another life where all may be righted. This is best expressed in Browning's Saul. But, as I said above, my reason works otherwise, and to it the immortality of influence, as set forth in George Eliot's Choir Invisible, seems most desirable." Another says: ' ' I regret to say that in my present state of mind I cannot give a very satisfactory response to the questions set. If I were to reply now, it would be from the standpoint of a pretty rank agnostic, and you know very well what the character of such a reply would be. It may be that this is only a temporary state with me. I hope it is, for I am getting very little com- fort out of it." The Mayor of a large city writes : "Your circular was duly received and I have read it over several times. I did not realize before how limited my knowledge was along the lines you suggest. There are so few items in the list of questions that I could answer with satisfaction to myself that I do not feel justified in answering even the more simple questions. Candidly, if I could satisfactorily answer those questions, I ought to be able to write after my name all the letters that Clark University gives for degrees." Turning now to our College and High School returns, we find only one in each of these two groups expressing doubt in the reality of an after life. All the rest believed in immortality, and all, except one, in personal immortality. With the excep- tion of one other thing which will be noted below, this was the only feature of special importance to be observed in these two groups. From all the above returns, it will be seen that the belief in personal immortality far outstrips that of any other form of survival. Seventy-two per cent, of all our respondents hold to a belief in the preservation of personality in a future life. The idea of an impersonal survival does not seem to fascinate SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY the imagination of most people. If they are to survive, imy want to know it and to consciously participate in whatever the future may have for them. Another disclosure of importance is that relating to the time and cause of changes in belief. Fifty-two per cent, of our respondents reported themselves as having passed through a period of radical change regarding their belief in a future life. The time at which these changes took place were almost invari- ably that of later adolescence. This, as we know, is the college period, and the causes assigned for these changes indicated were said to be, in almost every case, the effect of the study of science and philosophy during the college course. An inter- esting side-light upon this aspect of the subject is furnished by our college and High School returns. Out of the forty-six copies of our syllabus which were distributed among High School pupils, forty-six copies were returned, all answered. Out of the one hundred copies which were distributed among college students, only twenty were returned. The distribution of these latter copies was placed in the hands of four college professors, one in each of four different colleges. One of these colleges returned fourteen copies, another six, and the other two none. Of the forty-six respondents from the High School level, only four reported changes of view regarding the future. Of the twenty respondents from the college level, on the other hand, fourteen reported changes of belief. It would seem from all this, then, that the time of radical readjustment of belief in immortality is during the college period or the time of later adolescence. And the intensity of this process of readjustment seems to be pretty accurately measured by the small number of those who are willing to commit their views to paper, and also by the large percentage of changes in belief found among those who are willing thus to commit themselves. All this, of course, comports with what we have long since known, namely, that the age of adolescence is the age of psychical upheaval and of radical readjustment of beliefs, a fact which carries with it a tremendous pedagogical significance, as all must admit. One other important fact should not be overlooked. While it is true that, for various reasons, many are now questioning the validity of the belief in a future life, yet the almost unani- mous verdict of our returns is that an annihilation of this belief would work untold harm, both immediately and ultimately. 48 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY Only seven venture a contrary judgment. And the reason for this solicitude is placed wholly on the ground of its practical moral value. It is held that this belief has been one of the most potent incentives to a good life that has motivated human con- duct. In Pragmatic phraseology it has "worked," and, hence, according to Pragmatic logic, it is " true. ' ' But does it ' ' work ? ' ' Does the belief in a future life put man in more helpful and healthful relations with his environment? I am inclined to think that it does. No doubt life would still have worth even though the belief in immortality were destroyed. But with the destruction of this belief, life would certainly lose a large percentage of its worth for most people. It is by no means a cheap belief. Its power to enrich life is great. It is at once both humanizing and expanding. Nothing can more effectively kill out the brute in man and spur him on to the attainment of high moral manhood than the thought of immortality. What else can strip a human soul so utterly bare naked of everything but itself as this thought of the future? And, surely, if any- thing should induce a man to be good, it is the contemplation of one day having nothing to fall back upon but himself. "What a hell such an experience is for some people. They dread to be alone. They are such poor company to themselves that unless they have a book or a friend or some exciting pleasure to divert their attention from themselves they are utterly wretched. There is a Book that asks this question: "Where- withal shall a young man cleanse his way ? ' ' and the same Book answers, "By taking heed thereto according to thy Word." For a man to take heed to his way in the light of his immortal destiny is a most powerful cleanser from all brutal defilement. And not only that. The belief in a future life is not only humanizing but it is also expanding in its effects upon char- acter. It gives to human endeavor its most enhancing orienta- tion. It says to every laborer, do your best, you are not carv- ing a statue of ice to be melted down by the hot rays of anni- hilation, you are carving a figure out of materials that are inde- structible, do your best therefore. Such has ever been the appeal of the belief in immortality to the human heart. And wherever this appeal has been responded to, there do we find our noblest character and our highest service. A belief, there- fore, that has blessed the race with such results as these we can ill-afford to abandon. And we are pleased to say that as SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 49 rational beings we are not obliged to abandon it. So far as the writer is aware, no field of human research has as yet demon- strated the denial of immortality. The burden of proof is not with the man who affirms, but with the man who denies, a future life. He has the instincts of the whole race against him. Are these instincts false ? They may be, but it remains to be shown. In my inner heart of hearts I have the conviction, however I may have received it, that my life is destined to unfold into a higher order than the present. This conviction rules and mo- tivates all the activities of my life. Who will say that it is a delusion? It may be, but I await a positive demonstration of it. Till otherwise proved, I shall cling to my belief in a per- sonal immortality as one of the most precious boons, not only of my own life, but of the life of the race. BIBLIOGRAPHY. / 1. Algek, W. R. a Critical History of the Doctrine of a Future Life. ^ Philadelphia, 1864. 661p. 2. Andersen, K. Die Unsterblichkeitsfrage. Leipzig, 1906. 3. Atkinson, W. W. Reincarnation and the Law of Karma. Chicago, 1908. 249p. 4. AvELiNG, Fr. -Immortality of the Soul. St. Louis, 1905. 67p. 5. Beet, J. A. The Immortality of the Soul; a Protest. New York, 1901. 115p. 6. Bernier, V. L. Spirituality et immortality. La ChapeUe-Montligeon, 1910. 7. Bigelow, W. S. Buddhism and Immortality. Boston, 1908. 75p. 8. Bjorklund, G. J. Death and Resurrection from the Point of view of the Cell-Theory. London, 1910. 198p. 9. Brooks, H. S. Progression to Immortality. New York, 1902. 79p. 10. BucKNER, E. D.- Immortality of Animals and the Relation of Man as Guardian. Philadelphia, 1903. 291p. \^) Budge, E. A. W. Egyptian Ideas of the Future Life. London, 1899. 198p. 12. BuRNEY, C. F. Israel's Hope of Immortality. London, 1909. 106p. 13. Chamberlain, A. F, *'The Survival of Human Personality. ' ' Har- per's Magazine, vol. 107, 1903, pp. 277-282. ^4?^ Charles, R. H. A Critical History of the Doctrine of a Future Life, in Israel, in Judaism, and in Christianity. London, 1899. ( Jowett lectures, 1898- '99.) 15. Chester, W. -Immortality a Rational Faith; the Predictions of Sci- ence, Philosophy, and Religion on a Future Life. New York, 1903. 207p. 16. Cremer, H. Ueber den Zustand nach dem Tode. Giitersloh, 1901. 17. D 'Albe, E. E. F. New Light on Immortality. London, 1908. 327p. 18. Delanne, G. Evidence for a Future Life. New York, 1904. 264p. 50 JOURNAL OF RELIGIOUS PSYCHOLOGY 19. Denis, L. Here and Hereafter; a Treatise on Spiritual Philosophy, offering a Scientific and Rational Solution of the Problem of Life and Death. New York, 1909. 352p. 20. Dickinson, G. L. Is Immortality Desirable? Boston, 1909. 63p. 21. Elbe, L. Future Life in the Light of Ancient Wisdom and Modem Science. Chicago, 1906. 382p. 22. Frank, H. Modern Light on Immortality. Boston, 1909. 467p. 23. Fechner, G. T. The Little Book of Life after Death. Boston, 1904. 108p. 24. Fell, G. Immortality of the Human Soul Philosophically Explained. London, 1906. 25. FiSKE, J. Destiny of Man, Viewed in the Light of His Origin. Bos- ton, 1899. 121p. 26. Life Everlasting. Boston, 1901. 87p. 27. Fox, L. A. Evidence of Future Life. Philadelphia, 1890. 378p. (^^^ Frey, J. .Tod, Seelenglaube und Seelenkult im Alten Israel. Leipzig, 1898. 29. Fullerton, G. S. On Spinozistic Immortality. Philadelphia, 1899. 154p. 30. Gate, R. K. The Platonic Conception of Immortality and its Connec- tion with the Theory of Ideas. London, 1904. 257p. 31. Gilbert, L.- Sidelights on Immortality. Chicago, 1903. 233p. 32. Gordon, G. A. Witness to Immortality in Literature, Philosophy, and Life. Boston, 1900. 310p. 33. . Immortality and the New Theodicy. Boston, 1897. 130p. 34. Hall, C. C. Redeemed Life after Death. New York, 1905. 58p. 35. Holmes, E. E. -Immortality. New York, 1909. 320p. 36. How ATT, J. R. ,Next Life; Light on the World's Beyond. Chicago, 1910. 207p. 37. Hudson, T. J.- A Scientific Demonstration of the Future Life. Chi- cago, 1907. 326p. 38. James, W. Human Immortality. Boston, 1900. 70p. 39. Kempson, F. C. -The Future Life and Modern Difficulties. London, 1907. 394p. 40. Kennedy, H. A. A. St. PauPs Conceptions of the Last Things. Lon- don, 1904. 390p. 41. Keyserling, H. G. Unsterblichkeit. Munchen, 1907. 42. Leadbeater, C. W. The Otherside of Death Scientifically Examined and Carefully Described. Chicago, 1903. 502p. 43. Lodge, Sir Oliver. The Immortality of the Soul. Boston, 1908. lOlp. 44. . Life and Matter. New York, 1909. 175p. 45. MuiRHEAD, L. A. The Terms ''Life'' and "Death" in the Old and New Testament. Glasgow, 1908. 162p. 46. McConnell, S. D. The Evolution of Immortality. New York, 1901. 204p. 47. Munsterberg, H. The Eternal Life. Boston, 1905. 72p. 48. Myers, F. W. H. Science and a Future Life. London, 1893. 243p. SPIDLE: IMMORTALITY 51 49. . Human Personality. New York, 1903. 2 Vols. (Psychic Besearch Findings.) 50. OsLER, W. Science and Immortality. Boston, 1904. 54p. 51. OsTWALD, W. Individuality and Immortality. Boston, 1906. 74p. 52. Palmek, F. The Winning of Immortality. New York, 1910. 235p. jtaL:\PETAVEL-OLLiF, E.- The Problem of Immortality. New York, 1893. ^-^ 2 Vols. 54. Plato. Phaedo, or the Immortality of the Soul. 55. EOHDE, E. Psyche; Seeleneult und Unsterblichkeitsglaube der Grie- chen. 2 Vols in 1. Tubingen, 1903. 56. BoYCE, J. The Conception of Immortality. Boston, 1900. 91p. 57. Salmond, S. D. F. The Christian Doctrine of Immortality. Edin- burg, 1901. 565p. (58. Savage, M. J. Life Beyond Death. New York, 1901. 329p. 57. Schneider, W. Das Andere Leben. Paderbom, 1902. 60. ScHWALLY, F. Das Leben nach dem Tode nach den Vorstellungen des alten Israels und des Judenthums. Giessen, 1892. 61. Slattery, C. L. Life Beyond Life. New York, 1907. 133p. 62. Smyth, N. Modern Belief in Immortality. New York, 1910. 9op. 63. Stockwell, C. T. The Evolution of Immortality. Boston, 1906. 190p. 64. Tanner, Amy E. Studies in Spiritism. New York, 1910. 408p. 65. Thompson, R. J. Proofs of Life after Death. Boston, 1908. 359p. 66. Wallace, A. R. The World of Life; a Manifestation of Creative Power, Directive Mind, and Ultimate Purpose. London, 1910. 400p. 67. Wheeler, B. I.- Dionysos and Immortality. Boston, 1899. 67p. UNIVERSITY OP CALIFORNIA LIBRARV si'-! - i THIS BOOK IS DUE ON THE LAST DATE STAMPED BELOW AUG 6 1916 ^-16 1920 MAY 6 1921 DEC 2 8 1988 30ot-1,'15 J t U.C. BERKELEY LIBRARIES CQ0b74b1M5