LIBRARY OF THE University of California. GIFT Oi^ Class PRINCIPLES OF JUSTICE IN TAXATION BY STEPHEN E. WESTON, A. M. President of Antioeh College Sometime Univei'tity Fellow in Finance SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN THE Faculty of Political Science OF Columbia University \3 R A R')- UNI.' -:3ITY 0^■ 1903 PREFACE. The subject of this monograph was chosen in 1891 while I was taking post-graduate work at Columbia University. The first draft was nearly finished in the spring of 1894 when I was compelled to give up work for a time on account of ill health. Engaging in academic work in the fall of 1894 I was again obliged to set the monograph aside until the winter of 1900. Since then it has been completely rewritten and chapter VIII added. For his constant interest and encouragement I feel greatly indebted to Professor Seligman, for otherwise the monograph would not have been completed. I wish, also, to take this occasion to express my appreciation for the courtesy shown to me by the Faculty of Political Science of Columbia Uni- versity in giving so much extension of time for the comple- tion of my monograph. To Dr. Alvin S. Johnson, of Columbia University, I am indebted for verbal changes of text and for reading of proof, S. F. W. Antioch College, Yellow Springs, Ohio, May, igo^. TABLE OF CONTENTS VAGI CHAPTER 1 Introduction 1 1 CHAPTER II THE ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE STATE I. The Individual and Society 19 II. Origin of the State 24 III. The Nature of the State 26 IV. Characteristics of the State » • • . 28 I. Tht Voluntary and Involuntary Character of Political Organisa' tion 28 a. The Organic Theory of the State 32 3. The Nature of Sovereignty 36 CHAPTER III taxation, economics and kthics I. Taxation 43 1. The Nature of a Tax 43 2. Characteristics of a Tax 46- 3. The Limits of Taxation 5** II. Taxation and Economics 54 1. Taxation and Production 55 2. Taxation and Distribution -- - 60 3. Taxation and Consumption • 65 III. Taxation and Ethics * 68 CHAPTER IV THE political BASIS AND PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION I. The Social Contract and Taxation 76 1. The Political Philosophers 77 2. 7 he Protection Theory of Taxation 85 343] 7 8 CONTENTS [344 PAGB II. The Evolution Theory of the State and Taxation 90 III. The Utilitarian Theory of the State and Taxation 98 1. Tk£ Theory of Mill 99 2. The Utilitarian Theory of Sax and the Austrian School 102 IV. Social Theories and Taxation 106 1. Anarchism 106 2. Communism 107 3. Socialism 108 V. Conclusions as to the Political Basis and Principles iii CHAPTER Y the economic basis and principles of taxation I. The Physiocrats and the Single Taxers 116 1. The Fhysiocrats Il6 2. The Single Taxers : 119 H. The Classical School of Economists 125' I4 The Benefit Theory of Taxation 125 %4 The Exchange Theory, 129 3» The hisuratue Theory 132 HI. The Productive Theory of Taxation 134 IV. The Utility Theory of Sax 138 1. Its Originality ., 140 2. Simplicity and Truth 141 3. Individual arid Collective Psychology 143 {iy Individual Psychology 145 (a) Collective Psychology 146 4. Collective Needs empirically Considered , 149 (l). Differences in Character 149 (?) Political Factors 151 V. Conclusions as to True Economic Basis and Principles 155 CHAPl'ER VI the ethical basis of taxation I. The Benefit Theory of Taxation i6o 1. The Cost-of Service Theory 161 2. The Uahie-of- Service Theory 165 (a ) Expenditure 167 (2) Property 168 (3) Income 169 (4) Marginal Utility 1 70 345] CONTENTS 9 PAGE II. Ability as an Ethical Basis of Taxation 171 1. Ability and Property i-c 2. Ability and Income j -g ( 1 ) Meaning of Income i nn (2) Taxable Income 182 III. Ability and Sacrifice igy I- Mill ,87 2. Wagner and A^eumann 189 3. Meyer ,go 4- Sax ig^ 5. 7"^!? Dutch Economists iqy 6. Edgeworth 20 1 IV. Conclusion : Ability versus Sacrifice 206 CHAPTER VII ethical principles of taxation I. The Principle of Equality 212 1. Rate and Source of Income 21 ^ (i) Funded and Unfunded Incomes 213 (2) Inheritance and Gifts 216 (3) Monopoly and Quasi-Rent Income 217 (4) Income from Speculation 220 2. Rate and Character of Income 221 3. Rate and Amount of Income 224 (i) Proportional Taxation 226 (2) Progressive Taxation 2^1 II. The Principle of Universality 246 1 . The Justification of Exemptions 247 2. The Limitation of Exemptions 2c6 CHAPTER VIII practical justice in taxation I, Assessments * 266 1. Declaration vs. Doomage 266 2. Taxable Property ,68 3. Methods of Assessment 270 II. The True Tax System 276 I. Subjects and Methods of Taxation 277 ( 1 ) Taxes on Consumption 278 (2) Taxation of Real Estate 280 (3) Taxation of Personal Property 281 lO 2. CONTENTS [346 PAGB (4) Taxation of Mortgages 282 (5) Taxation of Corporations 283 (6) Taxation of Inheritances 287 Siate and Local Taxation 290 (i) National Taxes 291 (2) State Taxes 292 (3) Local Taxes 293 CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION A THEORY of taxation is necessarily bound up with funda- mental questions of political science, economics and ethics. By abstracting any one of these elements and making it alone the determining factor, or by giving it an undue im- portance, a theoretical solution of the problem may be made a comparatively easy task. But such a solution, like most schemes based upon one-sided or partial truths, is neces- sarily defective and not infrequently Utopian, The real difficulty arises when "these factors are comprehended in their full significance, or in their true relation to one an- other ; but only in this way can the problem be fully under- stood in its various bearings, or a solution be offered that is satisfactory alike to reason and to the requirements of jus- tice. This difficulty is two-fold. In the first place our views will necessarily be colored according to which of these factors we consider the foundation-idea of our theory and which we regard as incidental or supplementary ; and in the second place very much depends upon our interpretation of the fundamental idea and of the character of its relation to the other factors. Even if but one of these factors is con- sidered as having any importance, the question is not alto- gether a simple one, for there still remains the difficulty arising from the interpretation we may give to the chosen factor as the only one for consideration. It is such facts as these that account for the general disharmony in theories of taxation. An illustration of the difficulties referred to is found when 347] II 12 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [348 the political factor is made the only one or the fundamental one. For if, on the one hand, we regard the individual as the only important factor, and the state as merely an acci- dental but necessary evil, the tendency v^^ill be to an extreme of individualism; if, on the other hand, the individual be re- garded as a mere part of an organic whole, a cell of a living organism, we are in danger of the opposite extreme of socialism. The one extreme tends to the contract theory of Hobbs, Locke and Rousseau with its individual independence and its protective theory of taxation ; the other to a personi- fied social organism which directs the economic activities of its units and utilizes taxation to produce artificial equalities of wealth. Both of these extremes are false, although they involve the important truth that principles of taxation are intimately associated with a political philosophy. Not less are the difificulties, nor more satisfactory the re- sults, if the question be approached from a purely economic point of view. Different theories will be maintained and different conclusions reached according as production, dis- tribution, or consumption is made the basis of the economic theory. Moreover, different conclusions will result from different assumptions respecting economic principles, or from the importance attached to specific economic laws. If, for example, production under a laissez faire regime be regarded as the chief end of human activity, it will be con- cluded that taxation should interfere as little as possible with capital and its accumulation, while the relative productive powers of individuals should be the same after as before the payment of a tax. Or if there be implicit confidence in the doctrine of free competition there will be little concern about the tax system, the shifting and incidence of the tax through the action of competitive forces being relied upon to effect the ends of justice. Similarly we have only to exaggerate other economic elements to get other results. 349] INTRODUCTORY 13 So, too, the ethical factor may lead to equally divergent results according as Hedonistic or utilitarian principles, or the realization of the idea of man, is made the dominant feature of our ethical system. The difficulty is here further exaggerated by the fact that there is frequently a difference between theoretical and practical ethics. Harmony between these, whatever our ethical principles, is by no means easy to accomplish. Yet a substantial harmony must be estab- lished, or, on the one hand, we shall have only utopianism founded upon abstractions, and, on the other hand, expe- diency founded upon concrete facts without reference to ideas of justice. But a more fundamental difficulty than that which arises within the separate factors themselves is the determination of their relative importance. Each one must receive due con- sideration ; the political, because the relation of the state to ' the individual is primarily involved ; the economic, because/ matters of taxation are essentially of an economic character; the ethical, because the subject and the end of the whole proceeding is man, a spiritual and therefore an essentially ethical entity. But which is the ruling factor? The im- portance of this question, together with the full recognition of the separate factors, is so great that we shall treat this aspect of the subject somewhat 'at length before taking up the main question — that of justice in taxation. Indeed, this method of procedure is indispensable since the principles of justice can not be determined before the basis upon which they rest is established. It may be premised here, however, that the whole subject; of taxation revolves about man as its center — man in his relation to society, to his family and to himself; to the ends, that is, of his own existence. It has not, indeed, to do with the whole of man's activities and relations, but only with a small portion of them; in fact, with only a portion of those 14 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [350 involved in his political existence — the maintenance and support of the state, or what may be called the satisfaction of the collective needs of the individual. But because these needs and their satisfaction are common and involve human relations, an equitable distribution of the burden is de- manded. In brief, the question of taxation is a part of the larger question of distributive justice. But it is not with ideal men or ideal conditions with which we have to do, but / with actual men and conditions. Hence, the specific forms which the principles may take will depend upon the pre- vailing moral and intellectual, the political and economic development. But while the ultimate end is ethical, the means thereto are largely economic. Both a theoretical and a practical determination of what is justice in taxation presupposes a knowledge of economic laws and of their influence upon the efifects of any system of taxes. ^ It could not be other- wise, since all the phenomena concerned are economic. The end alone is ethical. But the ethical is not so far con- ditioned by the economic that it is only a consequence of economic laws. There are, however, certain fundamental principles in taxation (and it is these with which we shall have specially to do) that are not directly concerned with economic laws. They presuppose, indeed, certain economic conditions and certain economic forces, but their real justi- fication is to be found in a political philosophy and in the ethical end of man. It is more directly with the practical side of justice that economic forces have their importance ; although it is true that the theoretical principles of justice depend upon economic facts for their interpretation. Notwithstanding this close relation of the economic and the ethical, they are entirely distinct, being related as means to an end, or as proximate and ultimate ends. This fact is ^ Cf. Bastable, Public Finance, p. 9. 351] INTRODUCTORY 1 5 universally recognized in every financial doctrine ; for, con- sciously or unconsciously, the ultimate sanction of every theory is its conformity to what are assumed to be the ends of justice. Even those who, like Sax, deny that ethics has any place in finance, are forced to this standard, as we shall have occasion to see later. With all, the attainment of ? justice in the distribution of the tax burden, is the ruling ^ idea. Thus, in fact, as well as from the nature of the subject itself, the ethical element is made the predominating element in determining the principles of taxation. But unanimity of thought respecting the end does not guarantee unanimity of doctrine. Such agreement of doctrine depends upon the conceptions of ethical ideals, and in these the differences are as great as those already noted. Finally, the difficulties of the problem of taxation and of the attainment of a common agreement of doctrine do not consist alone in differences of fundamental presuppositions or of ideals. Not the least of the difficulties is a logical con- sistency in the development of a theory from its presupposi- tions. Too frequently prejudice, sentiment or expediency 3 usurp the place of logical thinking, which not unfrequently results in conclusions in no way related to the premises assumed, even if they are not in direct opposition to them. Without a further enumeration it must be evident that the problem that we have assumed to discuss is full of perplex- ing difficulties. That we shall be able wholly to avoid them cannot be presumed, for many of them are inseparable from the subject itself. We must necessarily start with assump- tions, and the merits of our treatment must be measured by the rationality of these assumptions and the logical con- sistency with which the idea contained in them is developed. A philosophical or scientific treatment must further be devoid of any personal bias. While it shall be my aim to attain this standard there will undoubtedly be some who l6 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [352 will consider my point of view, if not my reasoning, vitiated by an undue ethical emphasis. But apart from the fact that the real subject of my study is an ethical one, I believe that in emphasizing the ethical element of the problem I am only recognizing what is implied, if not expressed, in other theories. While we start out with the idea of ascertain- ing the principles of justice in taxation we endeavor to start without any presuppositions as to what those principles are. Our presuppositions are in the assumption of fundamental principles, not in the conclusions ; but without such assump- tion no rational treatment of the subject is possible. What, then, is the assumption with which we start out? It is the conception of man as a personality, and as such as an end in himself whose fullest realization is the purpose and end of his existence ; and that this realization takes place very largely in and through institutions, one of the most important of these being the political institution — the state. The assumption, however, is not a mere assumption. It has rational justification ; but the demonstration of this belongs to the field of metaphysics ' and for our purpose will be presumed. Of special and more immediate impor- tance to our thesis is the relation of the state to the individ- ual in this process of realization. Hence, a conception of the nature of the state and its relation to the individual will constitute the foundation of our thesis and form the basis of our argument. What the nature of the state is belongs to political philosophy to determine ; but since political philosophy afTords so many different conceptions of the state, and since our own argument must depend upon our own conception, it will be necessary to lay our own founda- tions by first discussing the origin and nature of the state before discussing the principles upon which the state should be maintained — or the principles of taxation. This we shall ^ See T. H. Green's Prolegomena to Ethics. 3531 INTRODUCTORY ' 17 attempt to do in the following chapter so far as is necessary to make clear our own point of view. We shall then discuss the nature of taxation and its relation to economics and ethics, after which we shall take up the subject of our thesis proper. Before beginning our discussion, however, it may be well to clear up an ambiguity suggested in the wording of our subject. "Justice in Taxation" maybe considered either! from a practical or from a theoretical point of view. Under I the former the subject would involve the setting forth of a detailed system of taxes that would realize justice to the individual taxpayer. A theoretical treatment, on the other hand, involves a discussion of principles rather than of kinds or systems of taxes. It is the latter view that forms the chief subject of our inquiry, although from neither point of view can a discussion of justice in taxation wholly ignore the efTects of taxation ; as, for example, the phenomena of shifting and incidence are closely related to the problem of rates and exemptions. Principles, however, must precede definite systems just as a fundamental assumption must pre- cede the determination of principles, for without a norm of judgment no definite conclusions are possible. The necessity of this norm must be our answer to the "practical man" who distrusts all theorizing not based upon empirical facts alone, and who seeks to determine justice inj' taxation by purely objective standards. Such a procedure is, to our mind, comparable to the attempt to obtain a knowledge of an object from mere sensations without refer- ence to a unifying and interpreting agency to give them meaning. Like sensations, mere facts are without signifi- cance. The so-called facts of the empiricist must be given a meaning by reference to fundamental concepts. The principles once established, it is for the practical statesman or financier to put them into operation. If the principles 1 8 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [354 are not practicable they must be considered as Utopian, at least under existing conditions. The ideal, however, has its place and importance, but the necessity of its modification in practice according to circumstances must be recognized. The nearest approximation to justice is always the ideal under any given conditions. CHAPTER II THE ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE STATE A STUDY of the origin and nature of the state is a neces sary preh'minary to a study of the nature of taxation and is indispensable as a foundation for the determination of the principles on which taxation should be based. It furnishes, moreover, an explanation of the reason why these principles should be based upon ideas of justice. That justice should be the aim in all taxation, is now universally admitted, and appears, indeed, so self-evident that proof is deemed un- necessary; but the proof is always implied, and is to be found in the nature of the state, or rather in the nature of the individual and his relation to the state. I. The Individual and Society The nature of the state is determined by the nature of society as the nature of society is determined by the nature of the individual. But the individual and society are so- intimately related that they mutually condition each other, and hence our study must begin with a study of the indi- vidual and society. Beginning, then, with man, the individual, it is possible to conceive of him in three dififerent aspects : As related to himself, that is, as a distinct personality ; as related to society, or as a complex personality; and as related to the Infinite, or as a permanent personality. These three aspects are expressive of the ethical, social and religious nature of man, and without their co-ordination we have only the im- perfect and undeveloped man. Our concern, however, is 355] 19 20 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [356 with only the first two of these aspects — man the individual and man in society. In respect to the former we assume, and without attempting a metaphysical proof, that man is a human spirit and, as such, a personality, and therefore exists as an end in himself; that it is the purpose of his life to realize that end — to develop his highest personality, to per- fect himself. Otherwise man would exist without any rational purpose. It is not the nature of the human spirit to be content with mere existence, except, perhaps, in its lowest form, where the animal predominates over the human. It is rather its nature to develop, to unfold itself, to manifest its possibilities, and in doing so it reveals and perfects its own personality. But the development of individual personality can not take place by itself. It is possible only in and through a society of similar personalities, a society oi persons. As a person in a society of persons the individual, in being conscious of his own end. as an end in itself, recognizes that every other in- dividual is likewise an end in himself, and therefore an end to be realized. In this reciprocal recognition of similar natures, effort towards the realization of others becomes a part of the realization of self. Thus, though an end in him- self, the individual does not exist solely for himself, but is at once his own end and a means to the ends of others. His development is conditioned by their development, as their development, in turn, is conditioned by his. The joint effort towards the realization of individual personality centers in the social nature of man and necessarily involves social re- lations. Only through the development of the social nature is the development of the individual nature made possible, as only by the co-ordination of the individual and social side of human nature can true personality exist. The development of the social, and therefore also of the individual, nature of man takes place in manifold ways, but 357] ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE STATE 21 more and more, with the progress of his development, through social relations that manifest themselves in social institutions, in whose complex phenomena we have what is called " society." To borrow Hegelian terminology, the human spirit in realizing itself objectifies itself in social insti- tutions — in society. Such a society being a manifestation of, and so constituted by, persons is something more than a mere aggregate of individuals, a mere numerical quanitcm. It is the result of social forces, and aggregation is not social- ization. The bond that transforms human aggregates into living societies is psychical. But at the same time that it is a uniting, it is also a differentiating force; thus, while giving unity to the social elements and to the social whole, it per- mits expression of the manifold human interests in social efTort. It is, furthermore, purposive in character, uniting common interests to common ends, and so re-enforcing the recognition by self-conscious spirits of persons as means to the ends of others, as ends to themselves. To the extent that this common interest and recognition do not exist the self-seeking spirit of man tends to the disintegration of so- ciety ; or to the assumption by a part of society that certain classes of individuals are only means to the ends of others, a practical denial of their existence as persons, as ends in themselves. The existence of such a negative force in so- ciety has far-reaching consequences, not only in matters of taxation but in the whole economic and social life; for to the failure to recognize individual personality as an end in itself are very largely due the antagonisms of social classes. Only in the complete recognition of the ethical nature and end of the human person can society fulfill its highest pur- pose, as expressing the objective realization of the individual — of personality; and the more this becomes a reality in life the more will justice between man and man be realized. And the more that society is recognized to be a society of persons the more will these ends be attained. 22 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [358 But if it is true that society is constituted of persons, and that without persons there is no society, it is not less true that without society there are no persons.' Persons and society are, in fact, correlative to each other. Each presupposes the other. In society personality and individuality unfold themselves; in society the human spirit seeks its realization. Without society the person has only potential capacity, while it is only in society, " only in the intercourse of men, each recognized by each as an end, not merely as a means, and thus as having reciprocal claims, that the capacity is actualized and that we really live as persons." ' If the evo- lution of social relations, indeed, is but the gradual tracing out of the evolution of the human spirit, these relations, as they at any time exist, are the embodiment of all past, and condition all future, social development. But although so- ciety and the individual mutually presuppose each other the end of social evolution is not in society, as such, but in the realization of the individual, to which end society is a con- dition and a means. And in the character of society as a society of persons, and as a condition of their development, we have indicated the ethical character of all social institu- tions, and the necessity of ethical considerations in all social relations. Related as subjective to objective the develop- ment of one implies the development of the other. And as the development of the ethical life takes on the form of a change in extent rather than in the fundamental ideas,^ em- bracing an ever larger circle of persons in the consciousness of the unity of purpose and ends, so in social evolution there is an ever increasing multiplicity in the numbers and variety of social institutions, an ever growing organization of com- mon interests and common ends, the complexity of the social relations being a reflex of the complex nature of the * Green, op. cit., p. 199. *Ibid., p. 192. » Cf. Green, p. 269. 359] ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE STATE 23 individual, a means of his giving expression of himself — of his being a person. The complexity of social relations is not a miscellaneous complexity. Every human interest, when it becomes suffi- ciently important and sufficiently general according to cir- cumstances, is focussed in an organized body of persons with the purpose of giving realization to the common interest. Thus, out of social relations are formed social groups, whose totality constitutes society. These groups tend to embrace every human interest of social importance — intellectual, moral, religious. They divide and subdivide, ever increasing in numbers and variety with intellectual, moral and religious progress. In content these groups tend to become more specialized, in extent more generalized; a condition due to scientific progress, as in means of communication, on the one hand ; and to a broader human fellowship, an enlarging consciousness of the unity of interests and ends, on the other hand. But the consciousness of a community of interests and ends that gives rise to social groupings is not a reflective consciousness of ultimate ends, except, perhaps, in certain religious groups. The determining consciousness is that of immediate interests and ends. Consciousness of ultimate ends has little direct influence upon social groupings. The ultimate end is revealed only by a reflective analysis of the philosophy of social life with reference to the life of the in- dividual. Yet it is only in and through the almost countless number of these groups, ever increasing in numbers and var- iety, that the human spirit finds its fullest realization. And the " unity in complexity " of these groups is typical of the highest form of social evolution.' The tendency towards social organization, however, is not without its opposing influences. The presence of self-seek- ing spirits as the dominant factor in human life is a dis- * Cf. Spencer, Principles of Sociology, Ft. v, chs. 2-4. 24 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [360 integrating social force and produces a retardation if not a negation of social organization. Social development is con- ditioned not only by the presence of positive social forces and favorable conditions, but by the absence of negative forces and conditions. Progressive realization of the human spirit is possible only where the conditions are favorable to its voluntary and spontaneous activity, both with respect to individual undertakings and with respect to associated effort such as is manifested in the social groups seeking a common purpose. That these positive and negative conditions should be maintained becomes, then, a matter of the first importance and of general interest. To this end a coercive power is a necessary requisite, and hence, in its main- tenance and support there is a universal interest. Such a power is realized in the political organization of society, the state — the all-comprehensive social group representing the universal common interest. In this group is centralized both the objective and the subjective complexity of society, in it social life reaches its highest culmination. II. Origin of the State With the actual historical origin or with the evolution of the stale we have no concern. Being in search of princi- ples our point of view is wholly that of a philosophy of the state, and is therefore an inquiry into its underlying princi- ple and cause, of which the historical state is a manifesta- tion, whatever may have been the course of its development. From this point of view the state's origin may be considered under two aspects, its objective necessity and its subjective necessity. By objective necessity I understand the necessity, pointed out above, of a coercive power to give unity to society and to make possible the conditions of social, and thereby in- dividual, development. For without such a dominating 36 I ] ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE STATE 25 social group society would at best be but an unorganized mass of social groups in perpetual and unrestrained conflict with anti-social forces, thus destroying the effectiveness of social organization and social effort in the work of the realization of man. The necessity, indeed, of this restrain- ing and controlling power has been recognized, however un- consciously, from the very dawn of society, though its earliest manifestation was in other social groups, such as the family and religious groups. In the course of time the ever increasing manifoldness of interests, by a process of social evolution, gave rise to a differentiation of the groups, a dis- tinct political group ultimately emerging with the specific function of maintaining the order and conditions necessary to the ends of individual and social life. Assuming the realization of the individual as the unrestrainable and impelling force, the necessity of the objective conditions may be considered as one of the unconscious forces that brought the state into being. In brief, its very indispensa- bleness is the cause of its being. With human nature as it is the state can not be conceived not to be. But the objective necessity is not the only cause of the state. Back of that and co-operating with it is a subjective necessity that springs from the nature of the individual. On the one hand it is the necessity of self-realization in the most effective manner; on the other hand, it springs from the social nature of man ' that impels him to associative effort for individual ends of a common interest. In this respect the state does not differ from other social groups. These differ among themselves chiefly in content and im- mediate end, but also in the form of organization and gov- ernment. Ncr is the social nature that binds men together in societies a mere instinct such as prevails in animal soci- eties. It is rather a partly conscious and partly unconscious * Aristotle, Folilics, i, 2. 26 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [362 recognition of common ends of immediate interest; and with the highest development, also, of ultimate ends. Philosoph- ically the social nature of man as distinct from the social nature of the animal, has its reason, if not its spring, in the conscious or unconscious recognition of man as an end in himself and as a means to the end of others. III. The Nature of the State The real nature of the state is revealed on the one side in its origin and on the other side in its end. Its origin, nature and end are, in fact, but different ways of viewing the funda- mental conception of the state as an indispensable instrument in human development. In determining its origin we have, therefore, determined in general its nature and end. But a more specific determination of its nature is necessary, and this may best be done by a more specific determination of its end, for, as Aristotle long ago pointed out, the nature of a thing is determined by its end.' What, then, is the end of the state? We must first of all distinguish between the end of the state and the functions of government. A government is only the agent of a state, an organization within the state for effecting its will — its pur- pose. A state is a body of people organized into a body politic to effect the purpose or ends of individuals. The functions of government, then, have reference to the organ- ized will of the people ; the end of the state to the end of the individual. We may, however, consider the end of the state as of a two-fold character: proximate and ultimate. Proximate with reference to the establishment of preliminary conditions; ultimate with reference to the final end. Ac- cordingly Professor Burgess calls the proximate end the establishment of government and liberty;'' but if we may ^ Aristotle, Politics i, 2, 8. ^ Burgess, Political Science and Constitutional Law, Vol. i, p. 86. 363] ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE STATE 27 consider government as inseparable from the state, though distinct from it, the proximate end might be more justly considered as the guaranteeing of rights and justice between man and man,' the direct maintenance of them being a function of government. What the specific functions may- be is a question that is determined at any time by the existing state of culture and civilization, by the prevailing conception of the relation of the state to the individual. But into this question we need not enter here. The ultimate end of the state is the ultimate end of its units — of the individuals of which the state is composed. The state by itself can have no end that is ultimate, since ultimate ends pertain only to entities that are ends in them- selves. The end is ultimate to the state only with reference to its supreme purpose — to the ultimate purpose of its exist- ence — not with reference io itself. This purpose, and there- fore the ultimate end of the state, is the completest realiza- tion of the individual — his capacities, his persotiality, the highest human development, the perfection of humanity." Considered with reference to itself the ultimate end of the state is the maintenance of the conditions that are essential to the self-realization of the individual. The state is a means ; man alone is the end. In brief, a state represents the organized efTort of a people to realize the fullest development of human personality; or it is the supreme conditioning instrument of that realization. And to be such a condition and instrument constitutes the real essence of the nature of the state. But all other human institutions are conditions as well as means to the develop- ment of the individual ; and since their existence and utility are conditioned by the existence of the state, we may char- acterize the state as the condition of conditions that are • Cf. Lilly, First Principles in Politics, p. 30. ' Cf. Burgess, op. cit., p. 85, and Lilly, op. cit., p. 51. 28 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [364 necessary for the realization of man. This supreme im- portance of the state to the individual makes it of universal interest, while the ethical character of its end, a consequence of the ethical character of its units, makes it an ethical institution. These characteristics of the state — the universal interest and the ethical character — may be called derivative characteristics of its nature. There are also other character- istics of the state that are essentially connected with the nature of the relation of the state to the individual. A definite conception of the most important of these is neces- sary to a clear understanding of the nature and principles of taxation. They are : The character of the relation of the individual to the state; the character of the state as an organization; and the character of the state as a supreme controlling power. We shall discuss these characteristics of the state briefly under the following heads : The voluntary and involuntary character of political organization; the organic theory of the state ; the nature of sovereignty. IV. Characteristics of the State I. The Voluntary and Involuntary Character of Political Organization. We have thus far seen that the state is the supreme and most important of social institutions ; that it originates on the one hand in the social side of human nature, and on the other hand in the effort of man to realize the possibilities of his nature ; that its origin dates from the very dawn of social life; that in its development in form and organization it has gradually become differentiated from other social groups, assuming the special function of estab- lishing the conditions that make their development, as well as all social evolution, possible, its ultimate purpose being the realization of human personality ; that, finally, it is an ethical institution in which there is a universal interest. Its dominant feature is its conditioning character, but while this 365"' ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE STATE 29 feature is prominent in every field of social life it has per- haps its greatest significance in the economic life ; not only because economic or industrial conditions are the best ob- jective indication of progressive enlightenment and civiliza- tion, but because the economic life is in a sense the founda- tion of both individual and social life, and so also of the state itself. In such a social body, whose existence is so impor- tant to the individual that without it he could not exist as a person, what is the character of the membership? In other social groups membership is limited, and is determined by choice based upon an idea of the Good for the self but with limitations imposed by each social group for itself. Choice and permission are both essential ; there is no compulsion either from within or from without, but only a subjective necessity. Is membership in the state of the same char- acter? Membership in this or that particular state is deter- mined by various influences, as language, custom, tradition, nationaUty; but with intellectual and economic enlighten- ment and growth in personal freedom, membership becomes more and more determined from choice, from an idea of a personal Good. But membership in a state is universal, there being no stateless persons in civilized society. It is also universally necessary, and this necessity is not only subjective but is also objective: subjective, because as we have seen, it is the inevitable expression of certain qualities in human nature; objective, because in civilized society there is no escape from membership in a state and subjec- tion to its laws. But is this membership voluntary and free, or involuntary and compulsory? Our answer must be that from different points of view it is both voluntary and compulsory. From the point of view of political science it is compulsory, but from the point of view of a philosophy of the state it is vol- untary. Objectively considered, that is from the point of 30 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [366 view of empirical political science, the state is undoubtedly founded upon force ; and membership in it, support for its maintenance and defense, is compulsory. Without the ex- ercise of force, or the possibility of its exercise, no state could endure. Without it there would be only individual and factional strife, the " war of all against all," barbarism, undeveloped humanity. But important as is the element of force in a state, force viewed as the foundation of the state expresses but a half-truth. Considered from the point of view of subjective political philosophy, the only point of view that reveals the true relation of the individual to the state, the foundation of the state is will.'' Or, if force is the foundation of the state, will is the foundation of force. In fact, the force which the state typifies is but the embodiment of the wills of its members, the objectified will of persons. Hence also membership in the state is both compulsory and voluntary. The state, as force, exacts support and obe- dience, but the state as the embodiment of will is created and maintained by the voluntary acts of free agents — of persons. This dual character of the state and of membership in it, a little reflection will make evident. The element of force and compulsion is too self-evident and too admittedly necessary to need special justification ; but that the force of the state can not be permanently effective, except as it is the ex- pression of will, reflection must make equally clear. The fact, indeed, is well illustrated in the practical impossibility of enforcing unpopular laws — of laws out of harmony with the general public sentiment. The fact that the state is a people organized into a political society, originating in a common interest to achieve a common purpose and common end — based upon an idea of a Common Good ^ — is likewise the clearest evidence of the implication of will as its source, *See Green, Political Obligations, pp. 12X-141. ^ Ibid., p. 126. 367] ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE STATE 31 and that there is not fundamentally any forced subjection to any external power. The purpose of realizing a common good can have no meaning except it be grounded upon con- sent; but consent is choice, choice is an act of will,' and will is based upon an idea of a Good. And, it may be added, in the willing of a common good, the pursuit of a common end, which implies a conscious presentation of the end to the subjects willing, is the final proof that the state is an ethical and not merely a natural institution." The real fact is that membership in a state — or the sup- port and obedience which it implies — is a result of compul- sion only in the case of this or that individual, where ignor- ance and selfishness has set up a personal good as opposed to the common good. Without such compulsory conformity to the idea of a common good, dissolution would set in and the state soon cease to be a state ; but this compulsion becomes less and less a factor in the life of a state, while voluntary participation in and support of the state, becomes more general, the more enlightened a people becomes — the more it rises to the idea of a common humanity possessed with common interests and like ends. Upon the state as a whole, indeed, there can be no compulsion, since the state is itself a body of people organized for the maintenance of rights. Compulsion must be by the whole upon the indi- viduals who contravene these rights. Compulsion is from without, and the state is not a body external to itself that can coerce itself. The people as a whole and individually will the enforcement of law for the maintenance of rights. Even the violator of law wills the enforcement of the law upon every member of society, and therefore upon himself. He merely takes his chances for a greater personal, temporary good for himself by evasion of it. ' Cf. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, iii, 2, I. * Cf. Green, Political Obligations, p. 132. 32 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [368 In brief, the case is this : By virtue of a recognition of persons as ends in themselves there arises the idea of the rig-Afs of persons, and therefore also a common interest in the maintenance of these rights by the combined force of all. To this end the state is organized — to centralize the force of the whole upon the individual. For the realization of rights, therefore, two conditions are essential : a concep- tion of persons as possessing rights because of their char- acter as persons, and the collective enforcement of these rights. Or, as Green says, force co-operates "with those ideas without which rights could not exist." ' 2, The Organic Theory of the State. What, now, is the character of the poHtical organization in which the citizen freely participates for the realization of himself? Is the state a mere aggregate of individuals, a social organism, or an as- sociation of individuals psychically united by a common interest in common ends? An answer to this question will throw light upon the nature of the state and also upon cer- tain principles of taxation, particularly respecting the basis of taxation and the exemption of the minimum of subsistence. Our own answer has practically been given in the preceding discussion, but we may re-enforce our argument by a brief consideration of the opposing theories. The theory that the state is a mere aggregate of individ- uals need not detain us long, as there are few, outside of the anarchist or the extreme individualist, who would maintain so irrational a doctrine. Clearly, a mere aggregate of indi- viduals cannot make a society, or a social group, any more than a mere sum of sensations can issue in knowledge. So- ciety, like knowledge, implies unity in multiplicity, but s»ich unity is possible only if there is a common principle that pervades the multiplicity — the individuals or sensations — * Cf. Green, Political Obligations, p. 140. 369] ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE STATE 33 and binds them together about a common idea, purpose or end. Without this uniting principle there can be no society. But is the unity that makes society an organic unity? Is society — the state — an organism? Such has been the ac- cepted doctrine of widely different schools of thought, as Spencer on the one side and German philosophers and econ- omists on the other side. The theory of the social organism is to-day one of the most widely accepted doctrines respect- ing society or the state.' That there is a striking analogy between the structure of the state and an animal organism there can be no doubt; and that this analogy is helpful to a clearer understanding of the nature of the state must also be admitted. But it is a poor logic that argues from an anal- ogy of structure to an identity of character or nature. In- deed, the analogy even with qualification is quite ?s harmful as helpful, since it is suggestive of an entirely erroneous con- ception of the relation of the individual to the state, and log- ically carried out would lead to strange conclusions in prin- ciples of taxation, as in political matters generally. Upon the whole I believe it to be in the interest of scientific truth, notwithstanding certain similarities, to abandon the analogy entirely, not only because of its misleading tendencies but because in its most important features the analogy is entirely false. Without attempting a detailed criticism I would men- tion three facts any one of which is sufficient to overthrow the doctrine that the state is a social organism. These are: I. Dififerences in the character of the units; 2. differences in sentiency of organism and society. 3. dififerences in the end of the units and the whole.' I. The units of an organism differ from those of a society ' It is interesting to note that there is a growing tendency among American authors lo reject the organic theory of society, as notably, Giddings, Willoughby and Fairbanks. *See Spencer, Principles of Sociology, Vol. I, pp. 478-9. 34 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [370 or state, in their discreteness, their mobility, their conscious- ness. («) The units of an organism are concrete, material things physically united, though endowed also with the phy- sical principle of life. The units that compose a state are materially discrete, though being essentially psychical in their nature are psychically united, {b) The physically united unit of the organism is immobile and performs a spe- cific function in a specific portion of the organism. The psycho-physical unit of the state being discrete has great mobility, and performs various functions in various portions of the body politic. (sential to state and government. The tax is and can be nothing else than a tax upon persons, at least upon our assumption of the true con- ception of the state. Nor, indeed, is the subjectivity of the tax, as a tax upon persons, any less apparent when viewed from its economic standpoint if only the subjective character of property be considered. For, subjectively considered, property is, as wc saw, the objectified self; and hence a tax upon property becomes indirectly a tax upon persons, upon personal productive capacity and ability, upon the economic means of satisfying personal wants, and thus upon the entire personality of the taxpayer. 48 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [384 Thus, whether we consider the tax with respect to its ne- cessity to the individual and to the corresponding individual responsibility and obligation (involving the relation of the individual to the state\ or with respect to its economic re- lation to the individual, it is equally evident that, while em- pirically and objectively viewed, a tax is upon property, ideally and subjectively viewed it is upon persons. And it may be added that this subjective character of the tax has far-reaching results. It supplies the key not only to the true philosophy of taxation but to the principles by which it should be governed. It also furnishes the key to the solution of many otherwise difficult problems in taxation, and consistently adhered to avoids much error and confusion of ideas. " The subjectivity of the tax." says Vocke, " is the Ariadne thread that must be firmly held if one would avoid a multitude of dangerous mistakes and escape from the laby- rinth of obscure (unklar), if also old views."' (2) Granting that a tax is a tax upon the person, is the tax contribution voluntary or compulsory? Again, it is necessary to distinguish between the objective and the sub- jective character of the tax, between the objective fact and the subjective idea. As objectively considered from the view-point of political science, or of the government, the payment of taxes is necessarily com.pulsory. Compulsion, in fact, is a necessary prerogative of objective sovereignty, and a necessarj'' consequence of the right of the state to be. So dominant, indeed, is this aspect of the tax that the idea of compulsion has become a central feature in all of the definitions of a tax by both the legist and the economist, the statesman and the financier. Yet, historically, the begin- nings of the tax, as occasional "aids," "grants" and " donations," were entirely voluntary ; and only gradually, with the change of society from status to contract, and the * Vocke, Die Abgaben, Auflagen und die Sieuer, p. 472. 3SS] TAXATION, ECONOMICS AND ETHICS 49 growing insufficiency of other sources of revenue, did these contributions become regular and compulsory.' And curiously enough, as the consciousness of the unity and universality of interest in a stable government has developed, and particularly with the rise of the democratic state, the compulsory character of tax contributions has become more universal and more rigid. But the compulsory feature of the tax represents only one side of the question, either historically or philosophically. For, correlated with the fact of an enlarged range, and the rigidity of compulsion, is the further fact that with the growth of a more definite consciousness of our citizenship, and of the vital relations that we sustain to the state and the state to us, there develops the conviction of an obligation to contribute towards the support of the government, and at the same time the right of the government to exact the con- tribution.' And, indeed, this conviction attests the voluntary character of the tax, at least where its true nature has been duly reflected upon. Nor is the voluntary character of the tax a mere subjective concept arising from conscious re- flection upon the nature of a tax. Taxes are in fact volun- tarily paid, even though the attempt is almost universally made to evade a part of them, or a protest is made against their amount. At least in all cases of pure democracy, or of representative governments elected by the people, the people voluntarily agree, directly or indirectly, to tax them- selves. As was pointed out when discussing the character of membership in a state, the people who voluntarily make up a state voluntarily agree to tax themselves for its support and maintenance ; and only here and there the self-seeking individual endeavors to make himself an exception to the general rule, and upon such it is agreed, individually and ^ See Seligman, Essays in Taxation, pp. 1-7. ' Cf. Cohn, The Science of Finance, sec. 192. JO JUSTICE IN TAXATION [386 collectively, that compulsion shall be applied, the voluntary and compulsory character of a tax thus implying each other. But not only is the idea of voluntary taxation implied in the voluntary character of membership in a state, it is a necessary consequence of the subjective idea of the tax and of the state. If, as we have maintained, the fundamental basis of the state is will, then the same will that creates the state must will to provide the means for its m.aintenance ; that is, contribution for the support of the state is a volun- tary act. Any other theory can rest only upon the pre- supposition that arbitrary force is the sole foundation of the state, thus failing to distinguish between the empirical state and the Concept state. Nevertheless, the subjective idea of taxation docs not exclude the idea of compulsion. On the contrary, compul- sion, we repeat, is in the voluntary conception of the tax ; a fact that must become apparent the moment that we reflect upon the distinction between the general will and the individual self seeking will, between the social will of the individual and his purely personal will, if we may be allowed the distinction. In any case, however, only the subjective idea of the state and the subjective idea of taxation can fur- nish a basis for ethical principles of taxation, for if force is the sole factor in the problem there can be no question of principles, but only of policy; still less a question of ethical principles. But, in fact, even the objective right of compul- sion, as in the enforcement of the law of universality, lests upon the subjective idea, or, perhaps better, the subjective fact. 3. The Limits of Taxation. Granting the power of the state to impose taxes as a sovereign ri^ht — a right, however, that has its source in the general will — are there any limits to the taxing power? If the question be made to refer to the state proper it must be said that no theoretical limits to 3S7] TAXATION, ECONOMICS AND ETHICS 51 taxation can be assigned ; for if the state is the people organized, and represents their collective will, there can be no limit to its power other than that which it determines for itself, that is, which is determined by the general will in view of common ideals. But in view of the fact that the government, as the agent of the stale, is the practical taxing power, it is wiih reference to the government that the ques- tion has its real hignincance. In discussing, then, the limits of the power of the govern- ment in taxation we shall pass over all specific reference to the individual, since this phase of the question constitutes the essence of the main burden of our thesis. Here we wish only to note a few general observations, particularly respect- ing the amount of the tax burden. And in the first place, it may be observed that the limits are relative, not absolute; and that while no a priori rule can be given for the limita- tion, there are, nevertheless, both theoretical and practical limitations. In a general way we may classify the limita- tions under the following heads: political, ethical, cconomicj (i) Politically speaking the power of a government in taxation is theoretically limited by its creator, the state ; and most commonly the limit finds objei.tive expression as a con- stitutional limitation, especially under con^titutional govern-' mcnts. That is, the will of the people is the final judge. More than this, in all representative governments the people theoretically exercise a direct control over the amount of the tax in the choice of their representatives. Unfortunately, however, owing to party machinery and political methods, the control of the people is very largely theoretical only. Where, indeed, the government falls into the hands of a "political aristocracy" — the politicians — the people retain only the semblance of power, while the government becomes practically absolute. And yet there are practical limitations, for if the burden 52 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [388 becomes too oppressive there is always danger of a revolu- tion, such, for example as the Revolution of 17S9; unless, perchance, the oppression successfully passes a point where resistance becomes hopeless, as is ap|)arently the present condition of Italy and Spain. In countries of greater en- lightenment and a larger freedom there is the restraint that the fear of being deprived of ofificc, through the ballot, con- stantly exercises. Such a limit is, however, very indefinite. It depends in part on the ability of the governing power to throw the burden on those who have practically the least political power; in part on the ability to use the more or less deceptive method of creating public debts.' Thus, po- litically a government has in practice a wide range of discre- tion in the use of its taxing power, even the constitutional restraint being very largely negatived in the fact that the government interprets the constitutional limitations put upon it. (2) But though a government has a large range in taxa- tion politically, there are certain ethical limitations that are incumbent upon it, for the government is, after all, consti- tuted of moral agents. Still, no definite moral rule of limi- tation can be assigned. All that can be said is, that since the government is the agent of the state in making condi- tions possible for the highest human development, it is morally bound to consider the effects of any taxation in retarding this development. But such a limit is relative. It depends, on the one side, on the functions that are assigned to the government, and, on the other side, on the national wealth, on the economic condition of the people. But the functions of government are themselves relative' — relative, * C/. Adams, Public Debts, ch. ii and pp. 41-2. *The theory of the relativity of the functions of government was warmly criti- cised by the Hegelian scholar, Dr. W. T. Hams, in a discussion following a paper by the writer on " The Functions of Government." 389] TAXATION, ECONOMICS AND ETHICS 53 that is, to the habits and customs of a people, to their ideals, their intellectual and moral status, their industrial life, their political and economic freedom. The main ethical problem of a government in taxation, however, is the just distribution of the burden, a question we need not discuss here. (3) Economically, also, the limitations of taxation have the same relative character that they have ethically, the same indcfiniteness, the same want of definite rule." Neither a fixed percentage of the national wealth, nor a /^r capita average can furnish valid criteria for juilgment. Hardly more satisfactory is the rule that v/ould limit the amount of the tax upon ihe individual to a fixed proportion of his revenue.' No less indefinite is the rule that the amount of/|i taxes should be determined by the needs of the governmental (/ for not only are these needs relative to the functions of the government, but iheir salisfaction is conditioned by the national wealth and general economic circumstances. Of far greater importance, since it conforms both to the ethical ideal and to sound economic policy, is the rule of Stein, sanctioned by Professor Adams,^ that the amount of the tax should be so adjusted as to maintain a due proportion be- tween the satisfaction of the needs of the state and the needs of the individual. True, the difficulty of this rule is the prac- tical determination of a " due proportion," a problem that is very largely influenced by economic and ethical conditions. The solution of ihe problem, however, is made theoretically simi)le by the utilitarian economists by an application of the doctrine of marginal utility. But for reasons that will be given later, utilitarian economics has, to my mind, a very limited application in public finance, being subject to the delusions * Cf. Wagner, op. cit., s?cs. 104-106. C/. also Adams, Public Finance, pp. 26-33. ' See Vauban, La Dime Royale. "Adams, The :Science 0/ Finance, p. 28. 54 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [390 that are so common in reasoning from analogies. Still, the rule is economically and ethically sound as a rule for guid- ance. But, perhaps, the most practical economic rule is that taxes should not be so large as in any way to impair their source. That is, the economic limitation is determined by the efifects of taxes upon industries, and so upon the sources of revenue. This phase of the question we will discuss under the following head. II. Taxation and Economics The economic life of a people is intimately related to its social life, not only because it is itself a phase of the social life, but also because economic goods form the matcriiil basis of the existence and usefulness of all social groups, — religious, philanthropic, scientific, etc., — as well as of ihc political group itself. That is, social well-being is condi- tioned by economic well-being. Whatever, therefore, affects the economic life, or the economic conditions of a people, affects also its social and so its individual well-being. Hence it becomes of grave importance that a government in exer- cising its power of taxation, in collecting economic goods from individuals, should carefully observe any economic efifects that taxes may have, whether due to the methods of taxation, the amount of the taxes, or to other causes. These effects we cannot stop to discuss in any detail, but must confine ourselves to pointing out some of their more important features and tendencies, not only to indicate the character of the problem involved, but also to emphasize the fact that justice in taxation cannot be realized except by due observance of economic laws and principles. For while this aspect of the question is essentially one of the economics of taxation, rather than of the piinciples of taxation, a clear understanding of the character of the effects of a tax is an indispensable prerequisite to the determination of principles ; 39 1] TAXATION, ECONOMICS AND ETHICS 55 since the justification of principles must be found in tho effects resulting from their practical application, not in a priori formulae. Indeed, it is because of the influence that taxation has upon the production, distribution and consump- tion of wealth that it is of special economic and ethical im- portance to consider its efifccts, since these have an import- ant bearing upon principles of taxation, as no system can be just which unduly and unequally affects the opportunities, or material means of development. In the economic effects of a tax, therefore, and more particularly in the effects upon consumption, is to be found an important factor in determin- ing the justice of principles of taxation. I. Taxation and Production. The question specially in- volved here is not that of taxes as an element in the cost of production. It goes, indeed, without saying that taxes must constitute an essential elenient in the cost of production so long as government shall be necessary to guarantee the pro- tection, security and order that make production possible, and so long as taxes shall be necessary for the support of government. More strictly, taxes are a preliminary expense that make the conditions of production possible; but they are none the less a necessary part of the cost. Nor, again, is the question one of the possible use of taxes to further production by the government, as, for example, by the pur- chase of railroads or other industries. This is a question of policy and of the functions of government as well as an economic question, and is too large a subject to be consid- ered here. No, the question with which we are concerned, is the effect of taxes upon the production of individuals, and thus u|)on economic progress and the general material well- being of the individual and of society. Do, then, taxes encourage or discourage production? To this question different answers have been given. On the one. side there is the doctrine that taxes necessarily stimulate I 56 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [392 production, a theory successfully overthrown by Hume/ McCulloch accepts the reasoning of Hume but quaUfies his acceptance with the statement that, " it is undoubtedly true that the desire to maintain and improve their condition, stimulates most men to endeavor to discharge the burden of additional taxes by increased industry and economy, without allowing them to encroach on their means of subsistence, or on their fortunes."^ On the other hand, J. B. Say. who viewed the problem from a different aspect, thought it " a glaring absurdity to pretend that taxation contiibutcs to the national wealth," since " capital is but an accumulation of the very products that taxation takes from the subject;" 3 that is, since the source of a tax and of capital is one and the same, and to increase the one is to diminish the other. The fact of the case, however, is that general positive statements can not be safely made on either side of the ques- tion. The effects of taxation on production are relative to a great variety of circumstances and conditions, and these a government should, as far as possible, take into account in its tax systems and methods. What the efi'ects of a tax upon production are, depends, in fact, very largely upon the laws of shifting and incidence in taxation. But these laws are by no means simple in character; they depend upon many conditioning influences, and are specific rather than general in their nature. We cannot, however, stop to dis- cuss this aspect of the question further than to call attention to the evident fact that the efifect of a tax, and therefore its ' See Hume, Essay on Taxes. »McCuUoch, Taxation and Fundins;, p. 7 (ed- 1S52). For similar views of Petty and Temple see Seligman, Shifting and Incidence, p. 16. Cf. also Bear, r Avert e Phnposte, p. 126. Also Mill, Polit. Econ., sec. 3, bk. v, ch. iii. » Say, rolitical Economy, bk. iii, ch. viii, sec. i. For conditicns in which the tax may lower or raise the " n.arginal cost," cr influence the rate of remuneration, see Edgeworth, The Pure 1 lieory oj Taxation, in Economic Journal, Vol. vii, P-S7- 393 1 TAXATION. ECONOMICS AND ETHICS 57 incidence, is indissolubly linked with the problem of justice; ] and also to point out some of the more important conditions determining the shifting and incidence of taxation. I'hat is to say, the justice of a tax is largely conditioned by its effects, the effects are intimately connected with its incidence, and the incidence, as we have said, is determined by various conditions. Among the more important of such conditions arc the fol- lowing: Whether the industries taxed follow the law of con- stant, increasing or decreasing returns; whether or not they are monopolies ; whether or not there is mobility of capital and labor; whether the tax is based upon value or is a tax upon surplus ; whether the demand for the taxed commo- dity is elastic or inelastic; whether or not the " law of sub- stitution" is possible; whether the tax is high or low; whether special or general ; the condition iA the market for labor and capital; the economic condition of the industry taxed relatively to other industries; the form of the imposi- tion and the kind of taxes, as, for example, whether the tax is direct or indirect; and the kind of industry taxed .md the stage of the industrial process in which the industry is taxed. In brief, whatever conditions, arising from taxation, that have an influence upon price determine the mann.cr and degree of shifting and incidence, since these are essentially phenomena of price, the objective determination of which is the law of demand and supply, the subjective determination the law of marginal utility.' ' For the best statement of the history and theory of shifting and incidence, see Seligman, Shifting and Incidence of Taxation. See also Kaizl, Die I ehre vcn der Uberw Iziivg der Steiiem. For a theoretical stufly of the fir^t four *' condi- tions" mentioned in the text see the al:le article of Prof. Edgevvoith on "The I'ure 'theory of Taxation," Economic Join nal. Vol. vii. Thcsi conditions are net treated by Prof. Edgeworth singly but in groups of assumed combinations. He takfs into consideration also the effects of '"short" and "long peri ds," and whether the lax is on rival or coml'lementai-y industrits. 'Ihe artiJe is a splendid illustration of both the complexity and the difficulty of the proLlcm of "shilting and incidence." 58 ^.^ JUSTICE IN TAXATION- [394 It'is the influences of such individual or combined condi- tions as the above that help to determine the operation of a tax, and without a clear understanding of these influences it is impossible to determine the effect of a tax upon produc- tion. And yet they tell us but one side of the problem. By studying the effect of these influences we may learn the effect of a tax upon price and upon the demand and supply for the products taxed, but not necessarily the effect of a tax upon production. The question of the effect of a tax upon production is primarily and immediately a question of its effect upon the accumulation and employment of capital^ and upon the zeal and industry of labor. An important clement in the solution of this problem is undoubtedly the influence of demand and supply operating through price, itself largely determined by the above-mentioned conditions. But this is not the only element of the problem. It is necessary to know, not only the effect of a tax upon price and demand, but also the effect of a tax-deteimined price upon the profits of capital and labor. Nor even then can we say with any definiteness what effect these combined influences will have upon production. Positive statements concerning the effects can result only from an incomplete apprehension of the facts involved. Let us take, for example, the assumption of Say, that taxes always tend to cimini>h prcduction for the reason that what is spent as a tax would otherwise have been consumed as capital; or the opposite theory, that a tax tends to stimu- late productive activity, or to " create the ability to bear it," en the ground that the desire to maintain a certain standard of living stimulates to greater industry and labor whenever a tax curtails the means of maintaining the desired standard. The fact is that both assumptions aie only partial truths. In both also there is a Jion seqiiiltir. Not only is it clearly not a fact that what is spent as a tax would otherwise have beea 395] TAXATION, ECONOMICS AND ETHICS 59 employed as capital, but it by no means follows that, because both the tax and capital have the same source, to increase the one is to diminish the other, since all other expenditures have the same source. How that part of the income which is consumed as taxes would have been spent but for the tax depends in part, indeed, upon the possibility of profits, but also in part upon the character and habits of the individual taxpayer. And in like manner is determined whether a tax effects a greater utility of industry and labor. Influences are at work in both directions and the final efTect is a resultant of many opposing forces. But whatever the general tendencies, . there can be no doubt but that an excessive tax curtails pro- [ duction, while a moderate tax may, at least under certain; circumstances, afiford a stimulus to greater production or to' larger accumulations of capital.^ It is, indeed, in the fact that taxes may work both waya upon both capital and labor, may even have one efifect upon one class of producers and the opposite effect upon another class, that makes it of such importance that a government, in the determination of the amount and adjustment of taxes, should carefully consider their possible effects, and so the conditions under which those effects are likely to be pro- duced. Nor is this importance confined to the immediate effect of taxes upon production. It is shown as well in the logical results of our assumptions. To assume, for example, that taxes always encourage production is not only to assume a fallacious doctrine, but also a dangerous principle, since there would be no logical limit to the extent of taxation;, while the assumption that taxes always lessen production,, besides being false, tends to exaggerate the rights of the in- dividual as against the state and to cripple the necessary needs of the government. The possible indirect effects upon * C/. Marshall, Prhidp/es of F.coromtcs, p. 28S (2d ec'.). Also Pantaleoni Teoria dclla Fressioiie Tribtilaria, p. 41. 6o JUSTICE IN TAXATION [396 production would be far reaching. Thus, both because of its direct and its indirect effects, a government is morally bound to consider the effect of its tax impositions, both with respect to their amount and their adjustment. The constant /aim should be to interfere as little as possible with the pro- r cesses of production. Whether a government should encourage production by means of protective tariffs or otherwise — creating limited legal monopolies — is a different matter. This is a question of the functions of government and of governmental policy, not of public finance. But when a government by its tax system, or by the amount of its taxes, unnecessarily curtails production or produces unequal conditions of production, it does an injustice to the taxpayers affected by lessening their ability, absolutely or relatively, to satisfy their wants ; and /at the same time lessens its own efificiency by diminishing the source of its material means of usefulness ; thus con- stantly threatening stagnation, if not degeneracy, instead of promoting the highest development, intellectually, morally and spiritually — by promoting the material conditions of such development. That the task of the government in duly \ observing the efifects of its taxes and tax system upon pro- ; duction is a difificult one can not be denied. The complexity ; of the conditions that enter into the problem makes this in- 5 evitable. Nevertheless, consideration of these effects is nec- ; essary, both that production in general may not be unnec- essarily checked, and that the production of one class may not be promoted at the expense of another class, thus effect- ing inequalities and injustice, instead of the equality and \ justice for which a government stands. 2. Taxation and Distribution. The effect of taxation upon distribution is not less important than its effect upon production, not only because of the influence of the distribu- tion of wealth upon economic and social conditions, but 357] TAXATION, ECONOMICS AND ETHICS 6 1 because the distribution of wealth is a very large factor in the determination of the character, methods and amount of production. For instance, large industries and large-scale production are economic phenomena which have their eco- nomic basis in large accumulations of capital, which change the whole relation of capital to labor as well as relative social conditions. Both the economic and social importance of distribution, therefore, demand that careful consideration should be given to the possible efifects of taxation upon the distribution of wealth. The importance of the social and economic effects of the distribution of wealth must be as- sumed as self-evident. To adequately treat the question here would take us too far afield into a discussion of social and economic problems. I would, however, call attention to four different ways in which taxes do, or may, influence distribution ; and at the same time call attention to some of the more immediate effects. (i ) In the first place there is the inevitable change in the distribution of wealth consequent upon taxation and the expenditure of its proceeds. Wealth is taken from the pock- ets of the producing class and transferred to the pockets of those who perform the services of the government or pro- vide it with material goods. This is unavoidable in modern political societies where co-operative division of labor is so fully realized. But no hardship or injustice is thereby in- curred. Those who provide the revenue and those who con- sume it in performing the functions of government are equally supporters and maintainers of the government, and both are equally gainers by this division of labor. There is no injustice, therefore, in this effect of taxation upon distri- bution, so long, at least, as the effect is but the normal result of legitimate taxation to meet the essential needs of the government. (2) The second method by which taxation may (indeed 62 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [398 does) effect dis'iibution is by the tax system itself. This method is essentially indirect. Two illustrations will make this method sufficiently clear : Protective tariffs and per- sonal property taxes. Granting the legitimacy and justice of protective tariffs, their first and more direct effect is to divert wealth from em- ployment in natural channels of production to artificially created channels. This in itself may be an economic gain to the whole community as well as to those immediately concerned. But however this may be, protective tariffs have the further effect of establishing special privileges to certain classes, making possible the colossal fortunes of the Carne- •gies and Rockefellers. The same is true of any other monopoly-creating tax. The importance of these changes lies not only in their reactive effects upon the methods and amount of production, but also in widening social distinc- tions and creating social discontent. The distribution effected by the abominable system of per- sonal property taxes in the United States, while more indi- rect and less perceptible is not less certain, and at the same time results only in the most patent injustice. Such taxation is practically regressive ; the richer classes having larger ac- cumulations of personal property, more easily evade the tax assessor. The tendency of such a tax system is to foster the growth of large fortunes by relieving them of their just burdens, but at the expense of the smaller fortune. One ) class in society pays the taxes of the other class. The eco- nomic effect is precisely the same as if property was forcibly taken from the one class and transferred to the possession of the other. To this economic injustice there is added the political injustice of throwing the heaviest burden of taxa- tion upon those who have the least ability to bear it. Thus, again, instead of promoting justice and equality the govern- ment is made an instrument in fostering injustice and un- 399] TAXATION, ECONOMICS AND ETHICS 63 equal opportunities, with ths attendant social ncqualities. The same unjust influence upon distribution is eff^xted by any system of taxation that results in an unequal assessment and collection of the tax burden. (3) The influence of the rate of taxation upon distribu- tion involves chiefly the question of proT;rcssive taxation, for a strictly proportional tax leaves the same relative distribu- tion of wealth after as before the tax, effecting di>tribution only in such manner as is inseparable from the nature and use of taxation. The maintenance of the same relative economic conditions, or the equalizing of the burdens of tax- ation, may also be the special object of the progressive rate, and so far as this purpose is carried out the progressive rate simply corrects the defects of the proportional rate by ao compl'sh'ng in fact what it stands for in theory. The justice of the progressive rate from this point of view will come up for discussion in a future chapter. We need only to observe here that however just the progressive tax may be it e.Tects a different distribution from that entailed by a proportional tax, though only such as is incident to the system itself. It is a far more serious question where progressive Ir.xn- tion is used with the deliberate purpose of effecting an arti- ficial distribution of wealth, as in the social-political theory of Wagner.' Such a use of taxation is, however, a social use and does not strictly come within the province of public finance.'' Moreover, it rests upon the assumption that it is' a proper function of government to equalize the fortunes ofj individuals. This, however, is not an admitted fanction of government in the modern state, though it was practiced by the ancient Hebrews, ^ was attempted by some of the Spar- ^ Op. cit , ii, pj). 207, 3S5-6 and 455-9. Also i, p. 47. * Cf. Meyer op. cit., sac. 67 ; Vocke, vp.cii., p. 43, andMarzano, Compendia di Scienza delle finance, p. 116. ^ Levi/icus, x\v, ;o. I 64 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [400 tan kings,* and recommended by the agrarian reformers of ancient Romc,'^ At the present time this doctrine finds de- fenders only in the different schools of socialism. The weakness of the whole doctrine is excellently summed up by Professor S-ligman, when he says that " a legal equality which would attempt to force an equality of fortune in the face of inevitable inequalities of native ability would be a travesty of justice."^ Further comment is unnecessary. (4) A final use of the progressive rate is to effect a com- plete revolution in the distribution of wealth by converting private wealth into public wealth by a process of confisca- tion. This is advocated only by the extremes of socialism, and, with respect to land, by the disciples of Henry George. This use of the lax is so foreign to present ethical standards that it has no practical significance and needs not to be dis- cussed here. In the brief summary that we have attempted of the possi- ble influence of taxation upon distribution, inclusive of the effects upon social and economic conditions — upon spiritual as well as upon material development — sufficient, I think, has been said to emphasize the necessity of great care lest distribution be too arbitrarily and too unnecessarily affected by taxes. It illustrates also the truth of the statement of Professor Adams, that "the distribution of wealth within a country is of as much importance to its public economy as the possession of wealth. "•♦ But besides its social and economic importance, the use of taxation to effect a distribution of wealth other than is entailed in the system itself, has the further importance that it violates the " natural right" to property as understood in the preceding chapter. As was there indicated the claim of ^ See Plutarch's Lives of A^is and Cleomenet. *See Plutarch's Lives of the Gracchi. * Progressive Taxation, p. C9. * Adams, L'ul/hc Debts, p. 151. 40l] TAXATION, ECONOMICS AND ETHICS 65 the state, or government, is limited to its needs. To go farther than this, to appropriate the property of some to be- stow it upon others, however indirectly, is to transgress the " natural law," is to commit an injustice. 3. Taxation and Consumption. Only recently has con- sumption played any important part in either economics or public finance. With the classical economists the safe-guard- ing of production was regarded as a prime element in a sound theory of taxation ; while the ethical economists and the socialists have given special attention to distribution — both the distribution of the tax burden and the use of the tax in the distribution of wealth. It has remained for the subjec- tive economists — the Austrian school — to lay emphasis upon the relation of taxation to consumption. Of these several interests consumption is of most vital importance; for objectively and economically considered, consumption is the end of all production, and we may add also of distribution ; while subjectively and ethically con- sidered, consumption is the process by which the wants of the individual are satisfied, so far as they are materially de- termined — that is, the self-perfected, realized. Emphasis upon consumption, therefore, is a recognition of man as a compound of needs whose realization is the essence of his being. It changes the view-point from the thing to the per- son, the means to the end. Not the creation of wealth, but the use of it, is made the fact of most importance.' In the power of consumption is seen the best measure of material well-being; but material well-being, at least until a certain standard is attained, has a most important bearing upon the development of the whole spiritual life of man. In fact, consumption, both by its amount and by its char- acter, entails far-reaching results. It profoundly affects pro- duction by affecting the efficiency of labor ; for efficiency is * Cf. Walker, Political Economy^ p. 294, 66 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [402 determined more by what one consumes than by what he produces. The amount and character of consumption affect also distribution, as, for example, by their influence upon the standard of life, which, in turn, has its efTect upon effi- ciency. Whatever, therefore, affects consumption affects the whole economic life; but whatever afifects the economic life affects, directly or indirectly, man's complete development. For these reasons, and because private property is an ex- pression of human personality, of the effort to satisfy human wants, the government is in duty bound to observe the great- est care that its system of taxation does not unnecessarily interfere with individual consumption. But the practical determination of what part of individual wealth should go to the satisfaction of individual wants, and what part should be given to meet the needs of the govern- ment — to satisfy collective needs — is a problem of the most difficult character, involving as it does so many complicated conditions and circumstances. As worked out by the Austrian economists,' however, the theoretical solution of the problem is made simple enough, by placing the satisfac- tion of collective needs upon exactly the same footing as the satisfaction of private needs. That is to say, the same laws of subjective values, of marginal utility, that rule in private economy are made to rule in public economy.^ The doc- trine, however, contains no new principle, but applies to ^ Meyer, Sax and Wieser. This school has a strong following in Italy, Ricca- Salerno being one of its most able exponents. His Scienza delta Finanza is an excellent and lucid resume of the more pretentious work of Sax. ''■ The credit of first applying the economic theory of subjective values to finance is claimed by Sax for himself. His theory, however, is substantially the same as that of Robert Meyer, in spite of the effort to prove a difference. The Italian economists do not concede the credit to the Austrians. Mazzola, in a note to his I Dati Scientifici delta Finanza Pubtica, p. 24, claims the honor for Pantaleoni, referring to an article published by him in 1883 in the Kassegna liatiana, en- titled : Contributo alia Teoria delle Sped Publichi. 403] TAXATION, ECONOMICS AND ETHICS 67 finance as to economics a principle long familiar to utilitar- ian, or better Hedonistic, ethics — the obtainment of the greatest possible pleasure at the least possible sacrifice. We may for the present dismiss this theory with the re- mark, that while most extravagant claims are made for it (which will be considered more fully later) it correctly recognizes the fact that the satisfaction of collective and of private needs is, in a sense, mutually exclusive, or that taxes lessen the consuming power of the taxpayer. It is this fact that makes the problem such an important one. Yet it is quite as true to say that the satisfaction of collective and of private needs supplement each other, for the satisfac- tion of the former conditions, as we have seen, the satisfac- tion of the latter, thus adding to the complexity of the problem. We can not stop to discuss this aspect of the question further. We have succeeded in our purpose if we have made clear that taxation and economics are most intimately re- lated, and have made clear the importance, and, at the same time, the difficulty of the question involved. For it has been shown that, indispensable as they are, taxes may be so levied as to work most injurious and unjust results upon produc- tion, distribution and consumption through the operation of economic laws, thus materially afifecting human well-being. We have seen, also, that the whole question revolves about the problem of shifting and incidence in taxation, which, as we have seen, is determined by the operation of the phe- nomenon of price, which itself is objectively determined by the law of demand and supply and subjectively by the law of marginal utility. It is, then, to these economic influences and economic results that the statesman should give careful attention if justice is to be an aim in taxation. But while very definite conclusions may not be possible, Professor Seligman has shown that substantial results may be obtained 6S JUSTICE IN TAXATION [404 as a guidance in legislation.' Without such observance of economic laws, conditions and results the first requirements of ethical taxation are put to naught. III. Taxation and Ethics Important as is a knowledge of economic laws and forces in questions of taxation, this knowledge will not of itself de- termine the true principles on which taxes should be based. From such knowledge we may learn the economic results of kinds and systems of taxes, but nothing at all of principles, that is, of ethical principles. Actual results tell of condi- tions as they are ; ethical principles of conditions as they should be. Yet, without a knowledge of the former it would not be possible to prescribe the latter. Actual economic results have also the further significance that they indicate the extent to which the ideal, contained in the principle, is realized. They are at once, therefore, a manifestation and a guide. It is, however, the ethical principle that is of real primary importance ; for the ethical principle is the funda- mental principle of taxation, as the ethical basis (as we shall have occasion to see) is the ultimate basis. In thus insisting upon the paramountcy of ethical princi- ples in taxation, that the ends of justice can not be attained by the mere play of economic forces, I am aware of running counter to a theory, implied in the doctrines of the classical economists, and expressly championed by Sax and his school.' For according to Sax, at least, economic laws are but the expression of the process of the realization of justice ; or, justice is simply the realization of economic laws, par- ticularly of the subjective law of marginal utility. In eco- nomic laws are found the alpha and omega of justice in tax- ation. Yet justice is not to be directly aimed at, for, so we ' See, Shifting and Incidence of Taxation, ch. viji. * Cf. Sax, GrundUgungf 83, and Ricca-Salerno, op. cit., bk. ii, ch. vi. 405] TAXATION, ECONOMICS AND ETHICS 69 are told, ethics has no place in public finance. So far as public finance is concerned ethical ends are a consequence, not an aim.' To this doctrine two important objections may be opposed : It rests upon the false Hedonistic assumption that pleasure is the highest Good ; it assumes that economic motives and ends are one and the same as ethical motives and ends. That the highest Good, — the ethical end, — is not pleasure, it is not our place to demonstrate here;^ but it must be ad- mitted that it is not consonant with a theory that makes the ultimate end of the state the realization, or perfection of man. Pleasure (in the sense of satisfaction, happiness — Aristotle's Eudaemonia'^ — not Hedonistic pleasure) is an accompani- ment, a necessary incident, if you will, but is not itself the end.* Hence economic pleasure, as such, is by no means necessarily identical with 'ethical ends. Whether or not it is so, depends upon the idea of the Good whose realization is sought. However closely related, therefore, economics and ethics may be in certain phases of taxation, ethical motives and ends are entirely distinct from economic motives and ends. Purely economic motives are founded upon the idea of a selfish pleasure of a more or less material character, whose realization is the economic end. Ethical motives, on the contrary, are founded upon the idea of a Good of a spiritual character — the fulfilment of the possibilities of our nature. It is not a selfish Good, for it is recognized as the "good" of others as well as for the self. Its realization is the ethical ' This is also implied throughout by Sax in spite of his contention to the con- trary. *See Green, Prolegomena, bk. iii, ch. i. * Described by a German philosopher as " the culture, the all-sided develop- ment of all human faculties, and the satisfaction which is founded thereon." Cf. also Paulsen, System of Ethics, p. 49. * Cf. Green, Ibid., sees. 158 and 161. 70 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [406 end, which involves justice in the relations of man to man, individually and collectively. And because the ethical end is the highest end it is paramount over all other ends ; hence over economic ends, and thus, also, in matters of taxation. We can not, then, admit that in questions of taxation eco- nomic self-interest is the measure of the individually or the socially just, however dependent our notions of ethical justice may be upon economic results. For insisting upon an essential distinction between eco- nomics and ethics, and that the question of taxation is funda- mentally an ethical question, no apology is needed. The supremacy of the ethical element is the only logical deduc- tion from the theory of the state and the individual presented in the foregoing chapter. Indeed, from the ethical nature of man it follows of necessity, or as the old English moral- ists ' would say, it is "according to the reason of things," that the ethical element should be the ruling element in all social relations and social institutions. In fact, it is true of taxation, and of the thousand and one social questions that ■ are agitating the world to-day, that no satisfactory or per- manent solution is possible which does not conform to an ethical standard, though that standard pertains directly to economic conditions. That is, there should be an ethical standard of economic conditions, for as Mill well says : "The \first thing in every practical discussion should be to know what perfection is.''^" If we are at all correct in our conclusion, even more unten- able than the theory of Sax is the position maintained by ; McCulloch: That since perfect equality is unattainable, "in 1 laying down a practical rule that is to apply to all taxes, equality of contribution is of inferior consideration;" and that, " It is the business of the legislator to look at the prac- tical influence of different taxes, and to resort by preference ^ Cudworth, Clark and Price. ' Political Ecotiomy, v. 2, sec. 2. 407] TAXATION, ECONOMICS AND ETHICS 71 to those by which the revenue may be raised with the small- est inconvenience."' The error of this doctrine is not so much in the premise as in the conclusion. For the doctrine erroneously assumes that the sa/us populi, which is held to be of "prime consideration," may be permanently antagon- istic to ethical considerations ; that policy and justice may be permanently opposed to each other. No, the truth is with Madame Royer, who places both " utility and just ce above the narrow consideration of policy ; " but adds, that if "justice is at variance with utility, we say that justice is I preferable."' The fact is that there can be no true social policy, no true policy in any of the social relations of life, that is not based upon ideas of justice. Justice is the foun- dation of a permanent social order, and a permanent social peace. Only upon the grounds of a "policy" best known to the " politician," or through want of a wholesome influence at the ballot box of a powerful minority (unless, perchance, the masses are soothed by ignorance, lethargy, or hope- lessness) can a system of taxes long endure, that is recog- nized by all competent judges as full of injustice. 3 Our conclusion, then, is: That the problem of taxation is partly economic and partly (but also essentially) ethical, the two elements being inseparably related. It is an econ- - ' McCulloch, Taxation and Funding, p. 18 (2d Ed.)- Cf. also Schmoller, who opposes to the principle of BeitragsfShigkeit, the principle : " Nimrn wo es geht." Quoted by Meyer, Die Principien der gerechten Besieuerung, p. 128. The declar- ation of Held, that " the practice of using those taxes over which there is the least complaint is the wisest," is not an acquiescence with McCulloch ; for with Held justice is not sacrificed as end, or opposed to policy. On the contrary, it is policy to heed the " complaint" because it is the surest (negative) guide to the realization of justice, the surest measure " fiir die Grosse personlicher Opfer." (^Einkontfnensteuer, p. 115.) '■' Theorie de Plmpot, Introduction, pp. 14-5. 'As note the tax systems in many of the American Commonwealths (See Ely, Taxation in American States and Cities, and Seligman, " The General Property Tax," in Essays in Taxation). 72 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [408 cmic question in that it has to do with economic goods, con- ditions, and relations ; ethical, in that it has to do with man as a spiritual and ethical entity, at once an end in himself, and the end of all social life. Each supplements the other. As Bastable says: "The important problem of justice in taxation is indeed an ethical one, but until its economic effects are known it is impossible to say whether any given form of taxation is just or the reverse."' In insisting so strongly upon the ethical character of tax- ation no pretension is made that absolute justice is attain- able. In human affairs only relative justice is possible. But we can not reach the highest approximate to justice without first knowing, as Mill says, what perfection is, and the "high- est approximate" is all that can be desired. But the problem of taxation is something more than an economic and an ethical one ; it is also political. For our conception of the justice in taxation is quite as dependent upon our conception of the nature of the state and of the functions of government, as it is upon economic results.' But the political conceptions, like the desired economic re- sults, are relative to ideals of justice. We may therefore consider taxation as having three bases — political, economic, and ethical — which though distinct are inseparably related. Upon our conception of these bases, and of their relative importance, must our principles of taxation be determined. Sometimes the one and some- times the other is assumed as the only basis, with a conse- quent narrowness of views and one-sidedness of conclusions. They must be considered in their mutual relation and mutual dependence. We shall consider these bases somewhat his- torically and critically in the three following chapters. ' Public Finance, p. 9. Cf. also p. 273. * La justice dans 1' impot est une conception extr^mement difficile ^ formuler parce qu' elle depend de 1' idee qu' on se fait des droits et des devoirs des gouvernements. Leon Say, La question des impots, p. 66. CHAPTER IV. THE POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION As we have seen in the previous chapter, taxation is a contribution from the private property of the individual for the support of the government — for the satisfaction of a common need. It arises out of the nature of the state, the necessity of government, and the prevailing system of pri- vate economy. It was further shown that the tax may be regarded as voluntary or compulsory according to the point of view in question ; that it is influenced by economic con- ditions and involves economic results ; and that above all, taxation is a supremely ethical question which must be de- termined by ethical standards and in conformity to ethical ideals. Now these three phases —the political, the economic, and the ethical — are not separate, but are inseparable phases of the problem of taxation. They nevertheless afford distinct bases of taxation — bases, however, that lead to false results if taken in their isolation and not regarded in their in- terdependence and unity. The primary basis is the polit- ical basis, since the whole problem grows out of the relation of the individual to the state. But since economic goods are necessarily involved, and so the economic relations of the individual to the state, there is, following the political basis and inseparable from it, an economic basis. And finally, because of the ethical character of the taxable sub- ject, and of the ethical character of all social relations, there must be an ethical basis which must act as a guiding norm in the determination of the principles that should control 409] 73 74 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [410 taxation ; since because of the supremely ethical character of the problem, the highest demand is the attainment of justice. By the ' political basis ' of taxation is understood that basis which rests upon a definite theory of the state, and from which certain principles of taxation may be deduced ; or it is the determination of principles of taxation in accord- ance with an accepted theory of the state, or is the logical outcome of such a theory. Hence the possibility of a wide range of principles, varying from those of the extreme indi- vidualist to those of the extreme socialist. These we can not attempt to consider in any detail, but must confine our- selves to a few of the more important theories — those that have the greatest influence, either theoretical or practical. Such are : the contract theory, the evolution theory, the utilitarian theory, and the social theories (as anarchism, communism and socialism). Now in examining these views of the principles of tax- ation, as related to and dependent upon a theory of the state, two things must be constantly kept in mind : The deductions made by the advocates of a given theory, and the logical deductions of that theory. It is also important to note whether the question is viewed in its entirety, or whether the political basis is regarded as the only basis. Before, however, discussing the theories mentioned we may mention briefly previous conceptions of the state and taxation. In the time of Plato and Aristotle little was known or thought regarding principles of taxation, though both Plato and Aristotle elaborated a theory of the state. Had they attempted, however, to determine principles of taxation from their theories of the state, it is certain that they would have sought principles consistent with the highest development of the individual. The principles of Plato would have 411 POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 75 looked towards the attainment of ideal justice, while those of Aristotle would have been adjusted to a ' mean ' capable of realizing an approximation to justice. But with both, ethical results, as they saw them, would have stood in the fore- ground, since they saw in the state the proximate, and in the individual the ultimate, good.' And yet with neither Plato nor Aristotle would the laws of 'universality' and ' equality' apply to all members of the commonwealth. For with Plato the burdens of the industrial life, and so the burden of supporting the government, would fall upon the working classes, the " husbandmen ; " while with Aristotle the same burdens would fall upon those destined " by nature" to be slaves. The Roman idea of the state and government likewise precluded it from forming a basis for principles of taxation. The large dependence of the government upon boot y; and. tr^butefor^its ^U£pojtjJogether w ith the exemp doiLoL-the patrici an — the governing — class^frotn the tax burden^ pre- vented taxat[on from becoming a serious problem whose principles needed investigation and determination. Coming down to medieval society and to medieval thought, we find new conceptions of the state and more defi- nite ideas concerning taxation. The system by which indi- viduals gave up their persons and property to lesser lords fdr^grotection, and these, in turn, their persons and property to the h igher nobility, and "the hi gher nobility to roy^alty ; the system of sub-infeudation ; and, indeed, the whole feudal system, inculcated the idea of the dependence of the indi- vidual upon higher political power, and so made protection ' However true it may be that the Greek subordinated the individual to, the state, I do not beHeve that any such doctrine can be found, by any consistent in- terpretation, in the philosophy of Plato or Aristotle, as is so often assumed. With both, the State was only a means for the fullest development of the "golden nature " of the individual. -^^ JUSTICE IN TAXATION [412 a dominant idea of the social and political structure of society. For this protection personal service was performed. Hence, as the feudal society gradually gave way to the " status of contract," and personal service to taxation, it was only natural that taxation should have been looked upon as a payment for the protection re ceive d from the government. The tax was simply a payment to the government of the costs of its service of protection. It was the ' cojt-of-ser- vice ' theoryLof taxation. This theory, however, soon gave way, at least in part, to the ' value-of-service ' theory — a theory that measures taxation by the value of the service of protection, instead of the cost of that protection. The value of the protection was then conceived to be dependent upon the amount of the property protected, the protection of the person being apparently regarded as a negligible quantity. A tax, therefor e, pro portioned to_one's p rope rty would be pro portio nate to the value of th^service that he had rec^ii^ed. But amount of property protected was very early regarded as the measure of one's economic ability, or ' faculty,'' and so of one's ability to pay taxes. Though 'faculty' might be considered as only another as- pect of the ' value-of-service ' principle, the {diCn\\.y—facultas — of the individual to pay taxes was early laid down as a distinct measure, or canon, of taxation. = It was largely out of these conditions that grew the conception of the ' social contract ' and the theory of taxation that evolved from it. I. The Social Contract and Taxation At the same time that historical conditions were lending much force to the conception of society as founded upon a contract, there was gradually developing out of the old Stoic conception of a " law of nature," though with considerable ' Cicero somewhere identifies faculty with property. * Cf. Seligman, Progressive Taxation, p. 127. 413] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 77 transformation of ideas, a theory of a " social compact " as a complete explanation of the origin and nature of the state. Although this theory is now universally repudiated by econ- omists and political scientists, no theory of the state has exerted a wider or deeper influence, theoretical and practi- cal, in the fields of politics, economics and finance, partic- ularly in England, France and the United States. The contract theory had, for example, a great influence upon JefTerson and the founders of our Republic, and has also given color to much subsequent legislation,' while its as- sumptions are to-day among the most commonly accepted doctrines of lawyers, statesmen, and the general public, especially in matters of taxation.^ I. The Political Philosophers. The theory of the Social Contract has received its fullest development in the writings of Hobbes,3 Locke,* and Rousseau, ^ although the doctrine is older than the Leviathan.^ The theory is so generally understood that it is not necessary to enter into a detailed account of it. In brief it is this : Prior to the existence of civic society mankind lived in a " state of nature," accord- ing to Hobbes in an un-social, even anti-social, " state of war," but with Locke and Rousseau under more or less social conditions. In the course of time the individuals composing the non-civic society became, as it were, sud- denly conscious of the fact that their happiness and well- being would be furthered if they would organize themselves into a body politic and choose a common arbiter, or arbiters, ' Cf. for example, speech of Da\Wi, Annals of Congress, i4thC., istSes., p. 1681. * Cf. Cooley, Law of Taxation. Also second message of Gov. Black of New York (1896), and newspapers at the time of the Income Tax decisions in 1893. * Leviathan, De Ccrpore Politico and Philosophical Rudiments. * Civil Government. * Social Contract. •See Grotius, De Jure Belli et Pads. Also, Sidgwick, History of Ethics, pp. 157-160. 78 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [414 for settling all such disputes as are constantly arising in a state of nature, and for common defense against all attacks upon life and property; thus converting the ' natural right' of the self-defense of one's person and property into the right of a legal protection guaranteed by the people as an organized whole. As the theory is developed in detail there are considerable differences among the writers mentioned, though for our pur- pose most of them are unessential. We may mention, how- ever, that with Hobbes the purpose of the compact was to avoid a state of "waiijof all against a41 " that prevails in the state of nature ; that with Locke it was to avoid the " incQUr venjejices" that naturally arise in settling any disputes where there is not a common arbiter to decide differences; while with Rousseau the compact was rather a convenient hypoth- esis for picturing the conditions of an ideal society. Rous- seau, indeed, had little concern for the past, but believing man to be born free but everywhere in chains,' he sought, like Plato, to discover the nature of the ideal state where liberty and justice might be realized.^ And the basis of such a state he found in the idea of a 'contract.' There is also a difference with respect to the location of sovereignty, and to the character of the protection. H obbes emp has i ze d the protection of life, Lo cke the protection of pxaperty, and Rousseau the liberty that is conditioned by the protection of both. But the more important fact is, that with all alike the idea of a contract best expresses the nature of the state ; that, further, the state originated in the necessity of protec- tion, or, at least, has as its function the protection of the lives and property of its citizens. It is unnecessary to enter into a criticism of a theory now so universally repudiated by philosophers and political sci- entists, although the fiction is still kept up in much legal ' Cf. Social Contract, ch. I. ^ Ibid., Introduction. 415] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 79 writing. We would simply refer to the facts : That it rests upon no historical foundation; that it falsely assumes the relation of the individual to the state to be of the nature of a contract ; that it makes mechanical and statical what is spiritual and dynamic, formal what is vital, external what is internal. On the other hand, the criticism of Professor Burgess, that the theory assumes a logical contradiction, since the state must exist before there, could be a contrai;.t,' seems to us little more than a technical point of law, as by the 'contract' was evidently meant nothing more than a covenant, similar to that of the Scottish Covenanters, or of the Pilgrims in the Mayflower. Assuming, then, the theory as understood by its promul- gators, what is the theory of taxation based upon it? If its theory of taxation depended upon its theory of a contract we might dismiss it with the statement: That since no such contract ever existed, nor, in fact, expresses the true relation of the individual to the state, it can not form the basis of the rights and obligations of citizens in matters of taxation. But as a matter of fact the idea of a contract forms no part of the theory of taxation of the Contract theorists. With them the basis of both — of the state and of taxation — was found in the idea of protection. For this reason their theory of - taxation, most fully developed by Hobbes, deserves more careful consideration, since protection is unquestionably an \ important factor both in the conception of the state and in \ that of taxation. That the basis of taxation is found in the protection that the citizen receives from the state is most clearly brought out by Hobbes. Taxes, he says, " are nothing else but the wages due to them who hold the sword to defend private_ | men .Lg, tjie^exe rcise of their several t rades and ca llings^"/ Moreover, since the benefit that every one receives from this 1 Burgess, Op. cil.. Vol. I, p. 62. 8o JUSTICE IN TAXATION [416 protection " is the enjoyment of life, which is equally dear to poor and rich, the debt which a poor man oweth them that defend his life, is the same which a rich man oweth for the defense of his."' But this equality of taxation does not mean, however, an absolute equality, for the benefit of the protection is the "enjoyment of life" as measured by material consumption ; and hence taxes should be based upon what one " spendeth," or consumes, by which *' every man payeth equally for what he useth."' Similarly in the Politics : " The burdens of the commonwealth being the price that we pay for the benefits thereof, they ought to be measured thereby." And since this benefit is the equal enjoyment of the peace and liberty to use our industry to get our living, we should contribute equally to the common charge, not as measured by the results of our industry, but by our consumption. " That seemeth therefore to be the most equal way of dividing the burden of public charge, when every man shall contribute according to what he spendeth, and not according to what he gets." 3 Again in the Philosophical Rudiments it is declared, that taxes being " noth ing else^ut the price of bought_peac£,_it is good rea- son that they who equally shai:e_ln__the__p£ace, shjo uld als o^ pay in equal j)art." ♦ In brief, the position of Hobbes is this : The purpose of the state is the protection of the life of the individual that he may enjoy the peaceful pursuit of a living, and the indi- vidual should pay for the expense of this protection ; the tax, which is the price of this 'bought peace,' should there- fore be based upon the benefits derived from this protection ; » and since the value of this benefit is determined by the ^Leviathan, Part II, Ch. 30, p. 30. (All references to Hobbes are from Moleswortb's edition.) ' Ibid. ' De Corpore Politico, Part II, pp. 216-7. * PhiUiophical Rudiments, p. 1 73. 417] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 8 1 amount of the enjoyment, which is itself measured by the amount that one enjoys in the way of consumption under the protection of the state, the tax should be based upon the consumption of the individual; and since all equally enjoy the benefits of protection, as thus measured by con- sumption, all should bear equally the burden of taxation according to their enjoyment of consumptive goods, that is, in proportion to their consumption^ And that this principle should govern the distribution ~6i taxes is in accordance with the 'natural law.' "Rulers," says Hobbes, "are hy_ thejnatural_law_obHged_toJay the burden of the comnion- wealth equally on thejr subjects. Now in this place we understand an equality, not of money, but of burden, that is to say, an equality of reason [proportion] between the burdens and the benefits. For although all equally enjoy peace, yet the benefits springing from thence are not equal to all,"' because of differences in consumption, which is the true measure of benefits. That is, the cost of protection should be distributed among those receiving the protection in proportion to its value to them, or in proportion to the value of the benefits of protection, which is the quantity of consumption. Are these conclusions of Hobbes a logical consequence of his fundamental premise, or the logical outcome of his con- ception of the state? Or, again, does the theory of Hobbes j give us a satisfactory principle of taxation, grounded upon \ a sufficient and satisfactory basis? Both questions, we be- ! lieve, must be answered in the negative. Forj with regpect, to the first^ if protection is the sole.pjjrpose for which polit- ical^ s.ocjety exists, Jthen the cost of that protection is the logical basis ^oi taxation, but such a basis of tax distribution is a practically impossible basis. Or, if the tax be consid- ered to be paid for the benefits of the protection, not for the ' Philosophical Rudiments, p. 1 79. 82 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [418 protection itself, then the value of those benefits would seem to be the true basis for the distribution of the tax burden. But, again, this is an impossible basis, for the value of these benefits is an incalculable quantity, since the protection upon which they rest is the foundation of our whole civilization and of all the benefits derived therefrom. But since a tax can not equal the benefits let us concede that it should be in proportion to benefits ; that is, the share of each should be such a proportion of the total expense, as the benefits that he derives from the protection are to the total benefits. But this, again, is not a calculable quantity. Hobbes, how- ever, gets around the difficulty by first assuming that the benefits consist in the peaceful pursuit of " our trades and callings," and then illogically concluding that the benefits are measured by what we consume rather than by what we produce. In brief there is no logical connection between Hobbes' theory of protection and his theory of consumption as the basis of taxation. Nor is Hobbes more satisfactory in his assumption of benefits as the true principle of taxa- tion. Even if we concede that, in a sense, the theory of benefits is a logical deduction from the theory of protection we maintain, and shall presently show, that the theory of protection is wholly inadequate, as it expresses at best only a half truth. On the other hand the theory of benefits as understood by Hobbes is equally inadequate, since it ex- presses even less than a half truth. It is a grossly inade- quate conception of the state that conceives its benefits to be limited to the power of peaceful industry, or to the per- sonal consumption of economic goods. The benefits of government are manifold and are not to be limited to the enjoyments derived from the consumption of material goods. And the tax must include the whole range of enjoyments. Further, the theory of benefits is a false and impossible principle for taxation; false, because it assumes an erroneous 419] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 83 conception of the relation to the state as the basis of taxa- tion ; impossible, because the benefits that are supposed to form the basis of the distribution of taxes are in'no way> calculable quantity. Not only, therefore, does Hobbes commit the double error of assuming benefits as the true measure of taxation, and that these benefits are proportioned to our consumption of economic goods, but his theory altogether ignores the moral element that is involved in the relations of individuals to each other in society or the state, and hence he expressly repudiates the principle that proportions taxation to ability.' Hobbes finds the justice of his principle solely in the assump- tion that our benefits are proportioned to our individual economic consumption. And he finds corroboration for his principle in that it conforms to the most expedient. A tax proportioned to consumption, he says, " seemeth not only most equal, but also least sensible, and least to trouble the mind of them that bear it." ^ Turning from Hobbes to Locke and Rousseau, we find that they gave little attention to the problem of taxation. Yet Locke expressly bases taxation upon protection and intimates that it should be proportioned to its cost, though it must be admitted that his statement on the latter point is not very clear. " 'Tis true," he says, " government cannot be supported without great charge, and it is fit every one who enjoys a share of protection should pay out of his estate < his proportion for the maintenance of it." ^ This is practi- ' cally all that Locke has to say on the subject, so that we are left in doubt how the proportionate share of each in the tax burden is to be determined. But it suffices for our present purpose that the principle of taxation is based upon pro- tection, each sharing his proportion of the cost. It is interesting to note, however, that Locke emphasizes * Cf. De Cor pore Politico, p. 216. ' Ibid., p. 217. * Civil Government, sec. 140. 84 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [420 the importance of free consent in the payment of taxes, i. e., consent of the majority — since arbitrary taxation " invades the fundamental law of property, and subverts the end of government." This is not only an emphasis upon the moral obligation to pay our share of the cost of our protection, but it follows from Locke's theory of civil government and from his theory of property.' Yet Locke, himself, makes this moral obligation stand for naught by his theory that the ultimate incidence of all taxes is, by the inevitable workings of economic laws, upon land ; since the merchant will not and the laborer cannot pay the taxes. " It is in vain," says Locke, " in a country whose great fund is land, to hope to lay the pubUc charge of the government on any- thing else ; there at last it will terminate. The merchant (do what you can) will not bear it, the laborer cannot, and therefore the landlord must."' The merchant "will not," because he can shift it by raising the price ; the laborer " cannot," " for he just lives from hand to mouth. "3 Thus, the position of Locke amounts to this : We are all in duty bound to pay our share of the cost of the protection of gov- ernment, yet the large merchant class will not, since economic laws enable them to shift the burden, and the large laboring class cannot, because they are already at the minimum of subsistence. That is, economic laws and conditions stand in opposition to the moral law, thus compelling one class in society — the landlords — to bear the burdens of the rest. The theory as a whole, then, is inconsistent with itself, but the fault here is with the theory of incidence rather than with the theory of protection. Finally, in the case of Rousseau, we find no attempt to develop a theory of taxation based upon his theory of a * Civil Government, ch. 5. * Interest, p. 60 (Works, Vol. IV, Edition 1824). Cf. also p. 57. ■ Ibid., p. 57. 42 I ] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 85 social contract. Yet out of Rousseau's theory of * liberty and equality,' which he made the mainspring of the contract, theories of society and taxation were developed, mainly by the French communists at the end of the eighteenth century, such as Baboeuf and Morelly. But as these theories were communistic in character we shall postpone their considera- tion until we take up the question of Social Theories and Taxation. 2. The Protection Theory of Taxation. Our preceding dis- cussion has shown that the contract theorists based their principles of taxation solely upon the idea of protection. This doctrine we have also found to be contained in much legal thinking, as in the popular mind, and it is also found in a certain school of economists. Because, then, of its his- torical and practical importance it may be well to examine separately, though briefly, both the merits and the demerits of the doctrine, its truths and its limitations. In discussing the protection theory of taxation we should carefully distinguish it from the similar economic theory, better known as the give-and-take, or the quid pro quo, theory of taxation. The latter will come up for discussion in the following chapter. Here we are concerned only with the protection theory as forming the political foundation of taxation and of its principles. True, the kindred economic theory rests upon the assumption that protection constitutes the true political basis of taxation, but it views the relation- ship that necessitates taxation more from the economic point of view and deduces its principles wholly from eco- nomic considerations, or from economic laws. But although there is a clear theoretical distinction, it would be difficult to find any treatment of the subject wholly free from the one or the other point of view. Nevertheless we shall view them separately, though recognizing their practical inseparability. From the purely political point of view, then, I would 86 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [422 adduce as the most important criticisms of the protection theory: That its fundamental conception is inadequate; that the principles deduced are not consistent with its logical deductions ; that it sees no ethical consideration beyond the obligation of each to pay his share for the protection that he receives. I. We have already pointed out the fact that this theory is based upon an inadquate conception of the state, and from our point of view this statement finds sufficient proof in the theory of the state outlined in chapter II. If we are right in our conception of the state the protection theory is necessarily inadequate. It expresses, in fact, but a half- truth. For while the protection of persons and property is the fundamental basis of social order and social progress, the purpose of the state and the functions of government are altogether too large to be comprehended under the con- ception of protection. The true conception includes pro- tection and admits that it is fundamental, but it does not recognize protection as exhausting all that the state stands for. The state not only represents the highest culmination in the development of the social life of a people, but it is at the same time the conditioning instrument in the totality of their development, or in the development of the individual. To this end the protection of persons and property is a necessary incident but it is only one among many incidents, though we will grant that it is the most fundamental and most important. Hence the aim of taxation cannot be lim- ited to the one end of protection. Its range is necessarily as comprehensive as the functions of government acting as the agent of the state in the fulfilment of its purpose. This is practically conceded by defenders of the protection theory who, like Von Hock, make protection co-extensive with national well-being,^ or who, with Sismondi, make it include ' Von Hock, Die 'dffentlichen Abgaben und Schulden, §§ 1-4. 423] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 8/ all of the advantages that are derived from it, as roads, honor, justice, education, religion, etc' But if protection forms too narrow a conception for the political basis of taxa- tion, the principles deducible from this conception must like- wise be insufhcient, as we shall endeavor to show. 2, That the principles deducible from such a basis are insufficient is shown, among other reasons, in the fact that those who proceed upon its assumption are unable to carry the doctrine to its logical conclusions. For, logically, the theory involves the cost-of-service principle of taxation — the apportionment of taxes to the cost of the protection, whether of persons or of property. This position, however, is seldom maintained, it being usual to adopt in its place the principle that bases the tax upon the advantages, or the benefits, derived from the protection. But even if we assume that this principle is a logical consequence of its leading premise, as in a limited sense it, perhaps, is, it does not, any more than the cost theory, afTord a working principle for rules of taxation; for both individual costs and individual benefits are incalculable quantities. But this apart, accord- ing to the benefit principle the tax should be proportioned to the benefits received. But this is impracticable. For on the one hand the tax should equal the costs (else the protection must cease), whether or not the costs exceed the benefits; while on the other hand the tax for the most part cannot equal the benefits, otherwise the revenue would enor- mously exceed legitimate expenditure. Thus, neither the principle of individual costs, nor that of individual benefits, the only logical principles deducible from a purely protec- tion basis, are practically possible principles of taxation, since they have only a hypothetical existence. Nor do we wholly escape the difficulty by harmonizing the two principles, as is universally done, on the basis of the ' Sismondi, &conomie Politique, Vol. II, p. 165 (Ed. 1827). 88 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [424 totality of costs and the totality of benefits, assuming as the principle of taxation that the taxes of each should be such a proportion of the total costs as he shares of the total ben- efits. It is true that the total taxes must equal the total expenses of the government, but the protection basis of tax- ation does not afford in itself any ground for distributing the costs according to the benefits received, except upon the gratuitous assumption that the costs and benefits are in every case directly proportioned to each other. But even if this were true in theory no definite result would follow, since a proportion could not be established between two unknown quantities. The fact is that upon the political basis of protection the ■distribution of the costs of protection according to the theory of benefits can have validity only upon the assumptions : ( i ) that the idea of protection is confined strictly to the pro- tection of the person and of property; (2) that the value of the protection of the person is precisely the same for every individual; ' (3) that the value of the protection of property bears a direct, ascertainable ratio to the amount of property protected,^ a ratio that is most commonly assumed to be directly proportional. But this limitation of the function of government we have already seen to be too narrow even for the defenders of the protection theory. They assume that protection covers all of the advantages derived from the protection, and at the same time assume that these advan- tages have a definite money value that is proportioned to the amount of property of the individual. But these are assumptions only ; they are not logic. The failure of this school to arrive at logically deduced principles is emphasized still more in the fact that, not con- ^ C/. Von Hock, op. cit., same reference. * Examples are too numerous to mention. It is the almost universally accepted doctrine of those influenced by the conception of the state in question in the text. 42 5] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 89 tent with the theory of costs or of benefits, they make ability also the true norm of taxation, apparently regarding it as deducible from the theory of protection and in harmony with the theory of benefits, if not, indeed, synonymous with the latter.^ But, as will be shown later, ability is a principle quite distinct from that of benefits, and has a foundation quite distinct from that of the protection theory of the state. The ability principle implies an ethical basis that is not to be found in the protection theory, or the theory of benefits. And in fact the inconsequences in the conclusions of this school arise very largely from the assumption of principles, in the development of their theory, that are not involved in their fundamental premise — their theory of the state. 3. Not least important among these assumptions is the assumption of ethical relations that are not involved in the theory of the state upon which their principles are based. For if protection is the sole basis of the state, originating in an actual or implied contract to that end, the tax, as we have seen, must bear a definite relation to the cost, or at best to the benefits, of that protection. There can be no escape from the tax for the protection of the person, and no escape for the protection of property, by those who may possess even the smallest amount of it. Moreover, this theory of the state does not in itself involve principles from which exceptions may be logically derived. Hence the only ground for any exception to the above rule for taxation is that of absolute necessity. Many writers, indeed I think I may say most writers, consistently maintain this position, though some would justify exemptions on the principle of ability, which involves ethical considerations. Now it is my contention that any theory of the state is essentially defective from which practicable principles of ' C/. (or example Adam Smith's famous first canon of taxation, since widely ac- cepted without qualification. 90 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [42^ taxation cannot be logically derived, since a state implies as well as necessitates taxation. But such a theory the con- tract, or its counterpart the protection, theory does not afford. And this mainly because the ethical character of the state is ignored. The state is conceived of as static and as consisting of external, mechanical relations ; whereas it is dynamic and its relations are essentially internal, psychical. This means also that the relations are ethical, and that ethical precepts are involved in the rules that determine the manner of the state's support. It means further, that the ethical precepts should dominate more and more in the practical rules of taxation the more a people develops its ethical consciousness ; that principles and rules of taxation should not be derived from primitive conditions of society, but from the conditions prevailing in a society in the process of developing its internal relations, and with reference to its ultimate end. We may, indeed, seek to discover principles that controlled actions in the past, but in searching for prin- ciples for taxation we are searching for principles that should control the action of the future. Such principles are not mere records of past or actual experiences, but are the formulation of ideal norms for the guidance of conduct^, determined by the inner nature of society and the state. II. The Evolution Theory of the State and Taxation. The preceding discussion has shown us, at least by im- plication, that principles of taxation are not to be derived from specific functions of government, or from the historical origin of the state, but are to be derived from the nature and end of the state, which involves the nature and end of the individuals by whom the state is composed. Functions of government determine limits of taxation, and the actual origin of a state influences the character of its system of 42/] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 91. taxation, but in neither case do they afford a basis for the determination of ethical principles for the distribution of the tax burden. Important as these truths are, they are fre- quently ignored, not only by the school of writers just con- sidered, but among others, in part at least, by Mr. Spencer in the development of principles of taxation based upon his evolution theory of the state. Turning, then, to the evolution theory of the state (and we shall confine ourselves to the theory of Herbert Spencer), we shall not find it necessary to trace the evolution of the modern state from the primitive horde and tribe, for the course of this development has nothing to do with Mr. Spencer's theory of taxation. Besides, in this respect the theory does not differ essentially from the historical theory of the state, except that the evolution theory assumes to discover the underlying principle that guides the course of the development. It is' the principle that controls develop- ment that is the important thing in Mr. Spencer's theory of evolution, and the principle that controls social evolution is found to be precisely the same as that which determines all evolution in the plant and animal worlds — a principle that may be summarized as the survival of the fittest struggling in the direction of the least resistance, or, by co-operating forces, overcoming resistance. Hence the evolution of the social world, like that of all life, is mechanical, external ; the moving power as the determinant of the "fittest" being ultimately Force — the force to resist or to subdue, the force to destroy or to utilize. It is by the power of augmenting such forces through co- operation, that political society is made possible, and it is those peoples that possess this power in the greatest degree that are the fittest to survive and to develop. This suggests that social organization has not for its sole purpose mere survival, but has a larger, ultimate purpose in development 92 JUSTICE IN TAXATION 428 — the development of social organization and through it the development of the fullest life of the individual; for the development of the highest possibilities of life is the ultimate aim of all evolution. Now the all-essential to the highest development of the possibilities of individual life, that is, to the development of human nature, is the largest possible freedom of the individual in the exercise of his own powers as directed by his own nature, and so receiving "the good and evil results of his own nature and consequent results."' But if this rule were without restraint in its application there would be only individual conflicts without individual develop- ment. It needs, therefore, limitation, so that with the free- dom of the individual to develop himself, there must be recognized the like freedom of others. That is, " in the social state the conduct of each bringing to him these results must be restrained within the limits imposed by the presence of others similarly carrying on action and experiencing re- sults."'' Thus is developed the fullest life compatible with equal freedom, "the ultimate end being a higher develop- ment of human nature. "3 In short, while there should be full freedom and liberty for the individual in the exercise of his powers, since his development depends upon himself, it is true that his personal interests, when unrestrained, tend to come into conflict with the like interests of his fellows, who should possess the same freedom of development as himself. And since this conflict of interests will not cease until altru- ism dominates the world,'' such freedom and liberty of each must be guaranteed by a supreme power — that is, by the state. The sanction for this interference in the conduct of the individual would seem to lie in the power of force — co- operative force — and the fact that those peoples that enforce such restraint prove themselves the fittest to survive and to develop. ' Spencer, yusiice, p. 221. * Ibid. * Ibid., p. 226. • See Spencer, Data of Ethics, chs 11-13. 429] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 93 From this point of view of the state, and from what we may call its immediate and efficient cause, its chief purpose would seem to be to act as a protective agency, and hence it is that Mr, Spencer conceives of the state as a kind of a "joint-stock protection-society," ' whose function is to guar- antee to each the fullest freedom for the exercise of his facul- ^ ties compatible with the equal freedom of all others."^ But Mr. Spencer rightly regards protection as only a primary, immediate function of government — a means to an end. This end, as variously stated, is to "administer justice," "to maintain the conditions under which each may gain the fullest life compatible with the fullest lives of fellow-citi- zens. "3 Or, it is "to maintain the conditions under which individual life and its activities may be carried on,"* though ultimately it is " the formation of character."^ But notwithstanding this recognition of ultimate ends, it is the immediate function of government that is the important thing in Mr. Spencer's philosophy of the state. Indeed, when a government assumes to do more than protect the individual in the exercise of his faculties, that is, when it i assumes to participate positively in the development of { human nature, or of human capacities and characters, it defeats itself and retards rather than aids the development of the ' fullest life.'^ And this conclusion obtains from what- ever point of view we regard the state — from its immediate , or its ultimate end. The state (or with Mr. Spencer indiffer- ently, the government) must act simply as a restraining power, though the boundary line of this restraint is admit- tedly a difficult problem to determine. ^ From such a theory of the state, what principles of taxa- ' Spencer, Social Sialics (Abridg. Ed.), p. 122. * Hid., p. 123. • Spencer, Justice, pp. 213-4. * Jbid., p. 194. • Ibid., p. 251. • Cf. Social Statici, p. 127. Also Cb. 26, especially 372. • Ibid., p. 127 et seq. g^ JUSTICE IN TAXATION [430 \tion follow, according to the views of Mr. Spencer? In the ifirst place, it is to be observed that since the government .■must guarantee equal freedom of development, or negatively, fequal conditions " under which individual life and its activi- • ties may be carried on," it is bound not only to respect a '; principle of equality in the distribution of the tax, but to exact only the minimum necessary for its support; since to do otherwise would be to deprive us of our liberties, or of the freedom to exercise our faculties." ' Indeed, any tax is regarded as a curtailment of our liberty, yet necessary to the enjoyment of larger liberties, and so a necessary evil. Or, it is a necessary " sacrifice of a part to ensure the remainder of our property." ' But upon what principle is this equality to be realized and taxation confined to its proper limits? Upon Mr. Spencer's theory of a " joint-stock protection-society," the true meas- ure of taxation would seem to be the principle that controls an insurance premium, as the state exists to guarantee our lives and property against the attacks of others, and also their free exercise and use. But with Mr. Spencer the limit of taxation is found in the actual costs necessary to guarantee the desired protection, while the principle of distribution is that of " benefits " derived from the protection. " In the abstract," says Spencer, " the question does not appear to present any great difficulty. The amounts'individu- ally paid should be proportioned to the benefits individually received. So far as these are alike the burdens should be alike ; and so far as they are unlike the burdens should be unlike. Hence arises a distinction between the public expen- diture for the protection of persons and the public expendi- ture for the protection of property. As life and personal safety are, speaking generally, held equally valuable by all men, • Spencer, Social Siatics, p. 123. * yustice, 209. Cf. also Montesquieu, De /' esprit des his, bk. xiii, ch. I. 43 1 ] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 95 the implication appears to be that such public expenditure as is entailed on their account should fall equally upon all. On the other hand, as the amounts of property possessed at the one extreme by the wage worker, and at the other extreme by the millionaire, differ immensely, the implication is that the amounts contributed to the costs of maintaining property rights should vary immensely — should be propor- tionate to the amount of property owned, and vary to some extent according to its kind.' Not only should taxes be proportioned to benefits, but " state burdens, however proportioned among citizens, should be borne by all. Every one who receives the bene- fits which government gives, should pay some share of the costs of government, and should directly and not indirectly pay it." ' In the above quotations, we have substantially all that Mr. Spencer has to say respecting principles of taxation, although the same ideas are several times repeated in his different works. And the sum and substance of the principles that Mr. Spencer finds deducible from his theory of the state are, that the tax should be proportioned to benefits, and should be universal. But since Spencer, with Von Hock, distin- guishes between the protection of the person and of prop- erty, and consistently so, there must be one universality for persons and another for property We cannot stop here to enter into a criticism of Mr. Spen- cer's theory of the state which he assumes as the basis of his principles of taxation. For us the question is : Are these principles logically deduced, and are they consistent with the demands of justice? Or we may ask: Is this theory of the state itself capable of supplying principles that satisfy the highest demand of justice? I. Mr. Spencer deduced his principles from his theory of ' yustict, pp. 198-9. » Ibid., p. 194. 96 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [432 government as a " a joint-stock and protection-society" — from his theory of the functions of government; not from his his theory of the evolution of the state — not from the nature of the state itself. And assuming the same functions, he arrives at the same conclusions as those who hold to the contract theory, or to the protection theory of the state — the theory of benefits and universality. But we maintain that neither his theory of the functions of government, nor his princi- ples of taxation, are necessary deductions from the evolu- tion theory of the state. For if society is a " growth " and not a " manufacture," ' the same must be true of the state, for Mr. Spencer does not distinguish between the state and its government, and thus to assume that the state goes on developing while its functions remain constant, is to con- tradict himself, and to assume for the state dynamic, and for the government static conditions. It means, further, that while evolution is recognized as the all-controlling social force, yet arbitrary limits may be assigned to it ; that after all, it is the preconceived notion of what ought to be, and not the actual trend of evolution, that has formed the basis of conclusions. It is true that Mr. Spencer's individualism has given color to this theory of governmental functions, but it is not consistent with his theory of the ultimate end of the state to assign arbitrary limits to the functions of its govern- ment, the agency through which it must realize its end. The same criticism may be applied to the principles of taxation. For if there is any truth in this theory of evolu- tion, the principles of taxation must vary from time to time with the progress in social evolution, conforming to existing ideals and standards of society. Again, if we recall that all evolution, according to Mr. Spencer, is a product of exter- nal, material forces and laws, the non sequitur of his conclu- sions becomes even more apparent. Whether, on the theory * Cf, Justice, p. 247. 433] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 97 of evolution, a tax should conform to benefits and be univer- sal, must depend upon whether the evolution of the state is best promoted by an application of these principles. Nor does the theory of evolution, in itself, afford any a priori reasons in support of these principles. For a criticism of these principles as deductions from Mr. Spencer's theory of the functions of government we may refer to the preceding discussion.' But to this we may also add, that however true it may be that the protection of life has an equal value for all, it is by no means self-evident that the benefits derived from the protection of property are propor- tional to the amount of property protected. Indeed, the opposite conclusion has more reason. Still more, the pro- tection of property affords benefits to the propertyless as well as to the property holders, though in a less degree. 2. As to the ethical character of the principles, we may refer again to the preceding discussion,^ where it is shown that while the principle of universality is true as a general principle it nevertheless requires exceptions ; and that the principle of benefits is lacking in important ethical consider-^ ations. But more than this, we maintain that Mr. Spencer's theory of social evolution does not afford a sufficient basis for ethical principles of taxation. The conception of a state as composed of individuals who are little more than abstrac- tions of the individual as he is in actual life, and of relations that are little more than artificial and mechanical, are not conceptions to give a basis for ethical principles. No theory, indeed, can meet the requirements of ethical demands that does not conceive of the individual as a self-realizing spiritual entity — a person; as also having a social nature which is such a vital part of himself that apart from it he has no real- ity as a person. For only with such a conception can the relations of individuals to each other in society be rightly ' See ante, p. 73 et seq. * Ante, p. 75 et seq. gS JUSTICE IN TAXATION [434 understood, or ethical principles deduced. Material agencies may issue in conduct, but not in moral conduct. In brief, a philosophy of taxation, like a philosophy of the state, must, as we have before observed, take into consideration the whole man. But such is not the case with the theory of evolution in question. Principles of taxation that follow from it must result from the law of the " survival of the fittest," must be such as are best adapted to the conditions of social life, and to the economic conditions, as they at any time exist. It is true that such a result may be contained in the principle of uni- versality ; but it is equally true that those conditions might be met only by a modification of the law of universality — by means of exceptions; while under Mr. Spencer's assump- tion the law of universality admits of no exceptions. The benefit principle, however, cannot conform to such condi- tions, since it is not capable of practical realization, as there is no justification for the assumption that benefits are propor- tioned to the amount of property. Finally, it may be added that Mr. Spencer's theory of tax- ation is not consistent with his theory of a social organism. For if the state is an organism (as he maintains in spite of his own refutation of the doctrine), taxation should be based upon the economic ability of the individual, apart from any personal needs; other, at least, than those of the necessary minimum, since as a member of the organism he must exist and act to the extent of his capacity for the whole, and not for himself. III. The Utilitarian Theory of the State and Taxation. While almost any theory of the state possesses certain utilitarian characteristics, there is nevertheless a distinctively .utilitarian theory based upon utilitarian ideas; and while 435] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 99 utilitarian principles have been applied to taxation mainly from an ethical or an economic point of view, there is an underlying basis in a utilitarian political philosophy. It is this latter point of view, as furnishing a basis for principles of taxation, that I wish to consider here. In doing so I shall confine myself to Mill and to Sax, though the former considered the question more from an ethical, the latter from an economic point of view. I. The Theory of Mill. According to Mill mankind is of such a nature that every individual seeks the greatest pos- sible amount of pleasure and the avoidance of the greatest possible amount of pain, the ideal aim of life being " the great- est happiness of the greatest number." ' Now this ideal is most nearly realized when every individual is given the full- est liberty to act according to his own impulses and beliefs, subject only to the like liberty of others.* It is in the main- tenance of the conditions essential to this equal liberty that the utility of a government consists. That is, the utility and sanction of government consists in its usefulness to the ends of the individual, a utility, therefore, that is " grounded upon the permanent interests of man as a progressive being." And it is because these interests cannot be realized through an independent life that they " authorize the subjection of individual spontaneity to external control, but only in r-e- spect to those actions which concern the interests of other people." But such a common interest is limited to the maintenance of the conditions of the free activity of the in- dividual, in a word, to self-protection. Indeed, says Mill, *' the sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number, is self-protection," ^ With the functions of • Cf. Mill, Utilitarianism. ' Cf. Mill, On Liberty, ch, 3 and 4. * On Liberty, Introduction. lOO JUSTICE IN TAXATION {^436 government thus directed, but also thus restricted,' there is developed the highest individuality, and by implication the greatest happiness of the greatest number. It will be noted that Mill arrives at the same conclusion as Spencer respecting the functions of government; and we shall see that he also arrives at essentially the same princi- ples of taxation, derived, as with Spencer, from the relations of the individual to the functions of government, but also with the ethical ideal uppermost in mind. For with Mill the protection that guarantees equal liberty of performance, of the development of individuality, and so of the highest happiness of the individual and of mankind, is of interest to all since all are benefited by it. And hence, " every one who receives the protection of society owes a return for the benefit, and the fact of living in society renders it indis- pensable that each should be bound to observe a certain line of conduct towards the rest." And among other things, this " line of conduct " consists " in each person bearing his share (to be fixed on some equitable principle") of the labors and sacrifices incurred for defending the society or its mem- bers from injury and molestation." "^ But how, according to Mill, is the " share " of each to be determined? It must, he says, be upon some "equitable principle," and such a principle he finds contained in the idea of " equality." Equality is regarded as the basic prin- ciple of government, whose chief function it is to maintain equal liberty in the enjoyment of pleasures,^ and equal con- * In his later life Mill did not so restrict the functions of government, though he did not change his utilitatian ideas or his principles of taxation. Cf. for example, bis Autobiography and the later editions of his Political Economy, ' On Liberty, ch. 4. * With Mill " pleasure" is not merely Hedonistic, sensual, but it is a " happi» ness " that includes intellectual pleasures, and which, indeed, with doubtful con- siiiency, Mill makes the highest pleasure. Cf. Mill, Utilitarianism; and Green^ Prolegomena, p. 168 et seq. 437] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES loi ditions in the avoidance of pains. Therefore, for the labor and sacrifices incurred in maintaining these equal liberties and conditions there should be an " equality of sacrifice" on the part of those benefited; or "equality of sacrifice" should be the guiding principle of taxation. That is, the government should " apportion the contribution of each person towards the expenses of government so that he shall feel neither more nor less inconvenience from his share of the payment than every other person experiences from his." ' We shall postpone for future discussion the merits of this principle as an economic or an ethical principle and inquire here, as in the case of the preceding theory, whether the principle is consistent with the theory of the state upon which it is founded, and whether this theory of the state is adequate to the determination of satisfactory principles. I. The theory of Mill, at the outset, has the advantage over either of the preceding theories in that it assumes an ethical end in the purpose of the state, and involves ethical relations among individuals as they exist in society, what- ever may be said of the ethical end in itself. Granting, however, the ethical ideal, and also the assumption that the ideal is best attained by the maintenance of an equal liberty of individual action, of individual direction of one's activities — one's emotions and ideals — and equality would rightly seem to be the justly dominating principle of social life. Hence, also, it is that in the maintenance of the conditions of equal liberty there should be an equality of individual sacri- fice corresponding to the equal benefits derived from the equal liberty. As individuals share equally in the benefits, so also should they share equally in the sacrifices necessary to obtain them. It is further not only consistent with the theory of Mill, ^ Mill, Political Economy, bk. v., ch. 2, § 2. I02 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [438 but also its merit, that it fairly solves the problem of abso- lute and relative equality, the absolute equality being of a subjective, the relative equality of an objective character. For with respect to the property enjoyed under the protec- tion, or guaranteed liberty, of the government, there is only a relative equality of benefits, and so there is and should be only a relative equality in the goods given up for the sup- port of the government; but with respect to the conditions of liberty in the free use of our faculties, so far as the gov- ernment is concerned in them, there is an absolute equality of subjective interest, and hence there should be an absolute equality of subjective sacrifice for the maintenance of those conditions. Such an equality is found in Mill's subjective "equality of sacrifice" as the norm for the distribution of taxes. (2) But apart from the question whether equality of sac- rifice is the ideal norm of taxation — a question to be con- sidered later — the utilitarian theory of Mill is otherwise defective. True, he rightly considers the question from the point of view of the ultimate, and not the immediate, end of the state, and therefore escapes the criticisms passed upon the protective theory. But the faults of the theory arise mainly from the defectiveness of its ethical standard which we shall have occasion elsewhere to criticise. Besides, the theory is further defective in that its ideals and results are essentially of a subjective character, and so are incapable of the necessary quantitative determination. Nor would it be easy to find in the Greatest Happiness principle any definite standard for deviations from the rule of universality in the tax obligation for the maintenance of the conditions of equal liberty. And there would be the same difficulty in de- termining these exceptions on the principle of equality of subjective sacrifice. 2. T/te Utilitaria7i Theory of Sax and the Austrian School. 439] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 103 A far more elaborate attempt to place taxation upon utili- tarian principles is to be found in Sax and the Austrian school of economists.' But with them the theory loses its ethical character and assumes a distinctly economic form. Yet the theory is founded upon the utilitarian principle of pleasure and pain, a principle that it is assumed applies equally to the collective and to the individual life. That is to say, pleasure and pain are supposed to determine col- lective activity in precisely the same way that they determine individual activity. And, indeed, the collective life has the same end in view — the increase of the sum total of pleasure ; and, further, it exists to promote this end wherever it is more competent than individual action. As worked out by Sax the theory, in brief, is as follows: Man is a creature of wants — sensuous and intellectual, moral and religious, social and economic, etc., etc. — whose satis- faction with the least possible pain, or sacrifice, to himself is the aim of his life. Of these wants, infinite in their variety, some are satisfied by the individual directly, others by the associated or collective action of individuals. The former are called collective wants, the latter individual wants. Of the collective wants, which alone concern us, some are satis- fied by voluntary associations within the state, others by society as a collective whole, organized as a body politic. — by the state itself. But however satisfied, the ruling principle of all wants is : the greatest possible satisfaction with the least possible effort — with the least individual sacrifice. Now this principle not only determines all collective action but also what action shall become collective, that is, the func- »Sax, Grundlegung der theoretischen Staatswirthschafl ; z\%o. Die Frogressiv- steuer ; '^itstr, N'atural Value; Ricca-Salerno, Scienza della Finama ; Flora, Scienza delle Finanze. The work of Sax is profuse and difficult; that of Ricca- Salerno brief and clear. A very good statement of this theory is given by Flora in the Rassegna, for August, 1893, ii^ an article entitled, // Concetto della Economia Finanziaria. I04 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [440 tions of government. These functions extend to the satis- faction of all wants that could not be satisfied by individual effort, or if so only by a greater sum total of individual sac- rifice. These wants have no absolute restriction but are rel- ative to the conditions of a given civilization, to the convic- tions of a people. As Flora says, " The measure of the action of a state is a product of the wills of its members," ' but wills that are determined by ideals of pleasure and pain. That is to say, collective wants of whatever kind are de- termined by the law of satisfaction common to all wants, a condition thai follows from the nature of the individual and of society. For collective want, in its last analysis, like all want, necessarily pertains to psycho-physical organisms and not to a personified collective being that has only mythical existence. Hence, collective action, like individual action, must be determined by the law of greatest utility and of least disutility, in a word, by the law of " marginal " utility. Hence, also, the same law must determine principles, or more strictly laws of taxation. In this simple law of the satisfaction of want Sax thinks that he has found the key to the solution of the whole prob- lem of true principles of taxation, and, indeed, in its sim- plicity he finds a guarantee of its validity.'' But Sax does not discover any new principle from this law of utility, for his " equivalence of burdens," which he deduces from the law of marginal utility, is in reality nothing but Mill's " equality of sacrifice," in spite of the assumption to the contrary. Indeed, Sax sums up his principle in almost the exact words of Mill; for his principle of taxation is: that "every individual should value the goods taken from him as highly as every other individual values those taken from him." 3 In other words, the marginal utility of goods taken * op. cit., p. 8. * " Die Einfachkeit der Losung ist eine Biirgschaft ihrer Richtigkeit." Sax, op. iil., p. 308. ' Ibid., p. 514. See ante, p. 88. 441] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 105 as a tax should produce an equivalent sacrifice. Yet in his method of treatment Sax differs quite materially from Mill, particularly in relation to collective wants and in confining himself solely to the view-point of economics. For with Sax the political basis is put into the background, while the ethical is considered as having no place in determining prin- ciples of taxation, since taxation has to do with what is and not with what ought to be. A criticism of the theory of Sax must, therefore, be made in connection with the economic basis of taxation. But with respect to the political basis it may be observed, that if we grant the primary assumptions of Sax his conclusions would seem to follow. We cannot, however, concede that the economic law of marginal utility, based upon self-interest, determines collective action in precisely the same way that it determines the economic action of the individual; nor that economic laws take precedence over ethical considera- tions in the determination of principles of taxation ; or that ethical principles are nothing but the results of the action of economic laws, as is virtually assumed by Sax. And because of the faultiness of these assumptions the political basis fails as a basis for principles of taxation. The theory is, further, like Mill's too subjective, too abstract. We postpone further criticism. But whatever criticism may be passed upon the theory of Sax it must be admitted that his general views are not only suggestive but also contain much truth. The chief merits of his treatment are : Its conception of the state, as a social organization essential to the highest development of the individual, and yet not itself a social organism ; its recog- nition of the flexibility and the relativity of collective wants, and therefore of the functions of government; its rich sug- gestiveness in making the philosophy of taxation a part of the general philosophy of human wants ; its emphasis upon I06 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [442- the satisfaction of wants, rather than upon the benefits of gov- ernment, as the measure of taxation ; though by faiHng in a due recognition of the ethico-social nature of collective wants, and so of the implications involved therein, he fails to dis- cover the true norm that should determine their satisfaction. IV. Social Theories and Taxation We have thus far treated of theories that pertain to histor- ical or actual forms of state and government, and it may be well before closing the present chapter to say a word respect- ing the character of taxation involved in such ideal social theories as anarchism, communism and socialism. True, such theories may not be able to throw much light on prin- ciples of taxation that are consistent with prevailing notions of the political state, since the total abolition or the com- plete transformation of such states is a part of their scheme of taxation. And yet they are not wholly without their les- sons in their conceptions of the nature of individuals, their relations to each other in society, and their mutual obliga- tions in their associations with each other. I. Anaj'chism. Nominally under anarchism there is no state, but only voluntary associations. Force as a coercive, collective power, is completely wanting. All association, and therefore all political association, must be voluntary, else there would be a denial of individual liberty ; and for the same reason all support of these voluntary associations, of whatever sort, must likewise be a voluntary support. Membership in the association, and therefore support of it, is permanent or temporary according to the choice of the individual. Under such a social system the conscience, or the ethical standard, of the individual must be the sole determinant of the amount of individual contributions, as no force can be applied. Should an association forbid membership to any 443] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 107 individual, or enforce contributions as a condition of mem- bership, it would defeat its own purpose and repudiate its own notion of individual liberty. Yet, until the millennium appears, or so long as human nature remains as it is, en- forcement of contribution, and the determination of the pro- portionate share of each, is inevitable. The conscience of the individual can not, as yet, be trusted to determine his share of the necessary contributions. Nevertheless, the anarchist view has its lesson in its emphasis upon the volun- tary side of political society, and upon the ethical character (at least by implication) of the obligation to contribute for its support. And yet there is only a half-truth in this doctrine. There must be a social determination and a social enforcement, else the association must cease to exist. 2. Communism. Communism in its objective form is little more than the constructive side of philosophic an- archism,' As with anarthism political and industrial society are organized in one common Association, but while the association is voluntary, communistic ideals do not preclude the enforcement of its laws. Communism, further, finds a definite principle of association in the idea of the brother- hood of man, from which it deduces as a principle of col- lective activity : " From each according to his ability, to each according to his needs." This principle which should actuate all social effort must also control the contributions which it involves. True, technically speaking, there is no taxation in a communistic society, since the officers of the community share in the product on the same basis as the producers. But the support of the officers, and the provi- sion of the material wants of the government from the com- mon product is as much taxation as a direct levy upon the property or income of the individual ; for in either case the support of the government comes from individual labor and * See Benjamin F. Tucker, Instead of a Book. I08 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [444 effort, from the giving up of the results of one's own labor to the community. And since the common fund is the re- sult of the combined labor of the whole, each producing according to his ability, the burden of the support of the community is necessarily proportioned to the ability of its members. Here we virtually have " universality " and " ability " as the two cardinal principles of taxation, deduci- ble from the nature of the social organization and the ethical ideal upon which it is founded — the brotherhood of man. These principles are both consistent and sound. The error of communism lies in the assumptions which it bases upon the idea of a common brotherhood, particularly with respect to the nature and character of the collective life. It exaggerates the communal idea as anarchism does that of the individual. Its great merit is the emphasis it places upon the ethical side of social life, 3. Socialism. So many social ideals are included under this caption that I must confine myself to that type of social- ism that is known as Scientific Socialism, or Collectivism — the socialism that would abolish political states — the Polizei- Staat — and establish in their stead industrial states, which are to own all the means of production and to direct and control all industries. Under such a system, it is assumed, there will be no occasion for the exercise of police powers, and the state will have only economic functions to per- form. Yet every individual must be guaranteed an equal opportunity in the satisfaction of his economic wants. Such guarantee, however, is supposedly fulfilled by the system itself, which ofTers the same opportunity to all to make use of the means of production. That is to say, the equality, which it is assumed is the fundamental human right, and the basic principle of the state, is an "equality of opportunity," an equality of use, not an equality of possession. Hence the quantity of goods acquired by each individual for the 445] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 109 satisfaction of his wants should depend upon his ability and inclination to labor, as in the system of Rodbertus ; but in the less just system of Marx it depends upon the " average labor time" necessary for the production of commodities. And the same principle that determines the share of each in the common product, must determine, also, the contribu- tions of each to the common reservoir, the common fund, out of which the shares are distributed. But the government is also maintained out of the common fund. Upon what principle, then, is the burden of support- ing the government distributed? Necessarily, the share of the common burden must depend upon the portion that each contributes to the common product. In other words, the distribution of the expenses of the government will be rela- tive to the standard of private wants and the degree of their satisfaction ; or, in brief, upon the use that one makes of his opportunities. Nominally, then, the principle of sharing the common expense — for there is no taxation — is the ability to satisfy private wants, or rather to provide the means for their satisfaction. But more strictly, the principle is that of economic benefits, the contribution of each being propor- tioned to the actual use made of the economic opportunities afforded by the government. Upon the assumption of the sociaHstic conception of the state this conclusion cannot be gainsaid. It is logical and just. But there is not the same theoretical justice in the distribution of the burden upon the basis of the "labor- time" theory of Marx, since those having less than the average capacity of production are credited with more than they actually contribute, while those having a capacity above the average are credited with less than they actually con- tribute. The former receive benefits that are in excess of their power of production, and so of their contribution to the common fund ; the latter receive benefits that are less than ,10 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [446 their product, or their contribution. On the other hand, with no type of collectivism is there any exemption allowed for those who are capable of producing, but only for the incapables — the physical or mental incapables. Those who are able to produce must do so or starve, and must therefore contribute to the common burden in the same proportion that they satisfy their own economic wants, whether or not these wants are satisfied according to the ability of the individual, or the average ability of individuals. So that from this point of view the contribution may be regarded as based upon the abihty of the individual as measured by actual product, or by the average ability of individuals as measured by their average product. That is, the ability is determined by the power of production, and not by the necessities of consumption ; and therefore there can logically be no exemption based upon the needs of the individual, apart from his incapacity. If we consider this theory of public contributions from the point of view of benefits, we find that it is defective in that it confines benefits to the purely economic benefit of equal opportunities for production ; and if we regard it from the point of view of ability we find it defective in so far as it confines ability to the ability to produce. But the real defect of the socialistic system of taxation, if we may be per- mitted to use the term, lies in its fundamental conception of a purely economic state, and in its conception of justice as consisting solely in the economic equality of opportunity. Its important lesson is, perhaps, its emphasis upon the social character of production, upon the joint interest of the mem- bers and of the collective whole of society in the social pro- duct, and upon the joint responsibility in the maintenance of the government. But it views the relations of the individ- uals to each other and to the state too entirely from an eco- nomic point of view, and, indeed, from the point of view of production alone. 44?] POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES m With respect to the principles of taxation state and Kath- eder socialism are not essentially socialistic, as they would not wholly convert the political into the industrial state, nor equalize the burdens of government by equalizing the oppor- tunities of production. They are specially characterized by the emphasis they give to the ethical side of social life, from which they justly deduce as a principle of taxation the ability of the individual to pay ; and hence also are given a wider range in considering the problem of exemptions. The social side of their theory — the distribution of wealth — is a prob- lem of political policy, and not of taxation." V. Conclusions as to True Political Basis and Principles of Taxation. In the preceding discussion of political theories relative to a political basis of taxation, we have attempted to touch only upon such theories as have exercised the greatest influence, either theoretical or practical, in matters of taxation, together with a brief reference to social theories that antagonize the existing state. Of the latter class we found that while they contain important truths, they are but half-truths at the best ; and further, their lessons have little practical signifi- cance since they have not to do with actual conditions, but with ideals whose consummation must wait for the dawn of the millennium. Or again, they make false appHcations of principles that are true in themselves. In the theories of the first class many important truths were also found, but we were unable to find in any of them a consistent and logical development of principles directly deducible from the political basis that formed their primary assumptions. Besides a lack of logical development we found, also, an omission of important factors in the problem. But what to our mind constitutes their fundamental defect, is ^ Cf. Vocke, Die Ab^abtn, Auflagen und die Steuern, p. 476. 112 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [44^ their conception of the nature and purpose of the state in its relation to the individual ; together also with a deduction of principles from the immediate functions of government in- stead of from the ultimate ends of the state. The political basis of taxation is simply a conception, or theory, of the state in which is found the justification and character of taxation, and from which principles of taxation logically and naturally flow. Such a theory must compre- hend not only the nature and end of the state, but also the nature and end of the individual, as person, since each is the counterpart of the other and by itself is but an abstraction. / But man, as an end in himself, is essentially and fundamen- / tally ethical, and hence principles that govern taxation, as ; also all social relations, should conform to ethical standards ,i and ideals, and at the same time should conform to the political conception upon which they are based. The theory of the state outlined in the preceding chapter, it is believed, answers these requirements. It recognizes the obligation of the individual and the rights of the state, the voluntary and the compulsory character of taxation ; it recognizes the universal dependence upon the state for the highest individual development, and thereby inculcates the principle of " universality " in taxation ; it recognizes the ethical nature of the individual and the ethical nature of social relations, and thereby inculcates the principle of equity, or "equality" in taxation as its highest principle. These, Universality and Equality, are, in fact, the cardinal principles of taxation deducible from a political basis — from a true theory of the state — and may, therefore, be called the political principles of taxation. All other principles are but modifications of these. These two principles, indeed, are» with greater or less logic, found in all theories of taxation, but all theories do not find a sufficient basis in their concep- tion of the state for the modification, of these principles that 449 POLITICAL BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 113 are necessitated by economic and ethical considerations. A basis for the modification and limitation of these principles is, however, to be found in the theory of the state that we have upheld as the basis for all principles of taxation. The cardinal principles are in themselves abstract and general in character, and result from the viewpoint of the general rela- tion of the individual to the state. But in their concrete application the actual conditions of life, with reference to ethical aims and standards, must be considered, the neces- sity of this consideration resulting from the ethical nature of the individual and the state, such as we have conceived them to be. In brief, the modifications of the two primary principles, universality and equality, no less than the princi- ples themselves, are, as they must be in every consistent theory, the necessary implications of the conception of the state, and result naturally from the logical development of these implications. The main problem, now, is to deter- mine the basis and character of the equality, and the limita- tions that are to be put upon the principle of universality. These can not be determined by the purely political aspect of the question, but only by the economic and ethical aspects. These aspects we shall consider in the two follow- ing chapters. CHAPTER V THE ECONOMIC BASIS AND PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION As a theory of the state implies taxation, so taxation im- plies the economic relation of the individual to the state. A political basis and political principles of taxation imply, therefore, an economic basis and economic principles. By an economic basis, then, is understood the economic relation that the individual sustains to the state; and by economic principles the principles that should determine the portion of private wealth that each individual should contribute to the ends of the state, or the relative satisfaction of private and collective needs. The question is not directly con- cerned with the economic effects of taxation, although these effects are indirectly involved. The economic basis and principles of taxation are, in part, an interpretation, and, in part, a modification of the political basis and political principles. The economic aspect of the question is not, therefore, an independent problem, but simply one phase of the problem of taxation, though, indeed, a very important phase. In- deed, its importance has led some economists to consider the question of taxation as though it were wholly an econ- omic one, to be determined by the simple application of economic laws. Taxation is treated as though only the economic relations of individuals to the state were involved. In the political basis they see only an economic basis, and in the political principles only economic principles. Indeed, it is expressly or tacitly implied by them that the application of 114 [450 45 I ] ECONOMIC BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 115 economic principles and laws will in all cases best attain the ends of justice. Taken by itself, however, this is but a super- ficial view of the problem. For, in the taking of economic values for its support and maintenance — the execution of its functions — the state, through its government, enters into a most vital relation with the individual ; since the source of the economic values taken by the state is likewise the source of those values that go to the maintenance of life, and of the material conditions that are necessary to the development of human personality. This vital relation, then, is something more than an economic one. Because it relates to 2i person, and so to an ethical being, it has ethical as well as economic importance. However, there is an economic side to the question which may be abstracted from other relations, just as in a theory of knowledge sensation, perception, judgment, etc., may be abstracted from the unified process that alone makes knowl- edge possible. The state must ultimately determine, as it is ultimately responsible for, the amount of those values that are diverted from the satisfaction of private wants to the satisfaction of collective wants — the needs of the government. _ It is, therefore, important that there should be a definite un- derstanding of the economic basis and economic principles that should control this distribution. In the present chapter we shall attempt to consider this economic aspect of the question of taxation. In doing so we shall not only review such theories as would solve the prob- lem wholly along economic lines, but shall consider the economic side of other theories. As these theories differ, in the main, according to different conceptions of the char- acter and importance of different departments of economics — as Production, Distribution, Exchange and Consumption; or according to different conceptions of economic theory and economic laws, we shall consider the subject under these 1,6 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [452 several heads, using different economic theories as main divisions. I. The Physiocrats and the Single Takers. It was the theory of the first school of scientific economists — the Physiocrats — and is the theory of their modern repre- sentatives — the Single Taxers — that the whole expense of government should be met out of the proceeds from the land, from the proditit net or the "economic rent." Let us attempt to ascertain the economic basis and the economic principles underlying this theory. Although they reach practically the same result we shall find that the earlier and the later representatives of this theory employ somewhat dif- ferent lines of argument. I. The Physiocrats. According to the doctrine of the Physiocrats land alone produces 2. prodidt net, a net surplus above the expenses of production ; therefore upon whatever form of property or income a tax may be imposed its ulti- mate incidence must be upon this produit net, as otherwise production must cease and starvation follow. Hence, to avoid unnecessary expenses of collection and added costs due to the advancement of the taxes, all taxes should be imposed in the first instance upon the landed proprietors.* Moreover, as only the proprietors of land obtain a net pro- duct, they are the only class that has any interest in a stable government. Indeed, a net product and a stable govern- ment mutually condition each other. For "without good government and tranquility there will be no net product,, and without a net product no government and no society."" Security and tranquility increase the revenue of each. Because, therefore, of the mutual interest and mutual de- pendence of proprietors and the government they should share about equally in the net product.^ ^ Cf. Turgot, Works, vol. iv, p. 306. « Quesnay, Despotume de la Chine, ch. 8, sec. 20. ' Cf. Quesnay, Ibid. 453] ECONOMIC BASIS AND PRINCIPLES u; The doctrine of a produit net as applied to taxation is most fully developed by Turgot who assigns several reasons for a single tax on land. His argument we may summarize as follows : The object of a tax " is for the preservation of property, not to lose it, — and hence should be upon income, not upon property;"^ but "the proprietor of land is the only one who has a true income" — 2i produit net — and there- fore " he alone has an interest in preserving the permanent order of society," for to the industrial class any change of ownership would be but a change of employers.' The tax_ sho uld, the refore, be paid out of ^ the "true income. " and to force it from any other income, or to make it exceed this income, would check production 'and so dry up the source of the revenue of the state.3 Moreover, any other tax is always shifted to the proprietor by being added to the cost of production ;'• and to cause the laboring and industrial classes to advance the tax is to produce their ruin, since they have no disposable income.^ On the other hand, " it is impossible to make the consumers, who are not pro- prietors, pay a tax upon consumption, because from the moment it is established they are forced either to restrain their consumption or to diminish the price which they can offer for the production which they consume ; and because either method will throw the tax upon the producers, or sellers, of those productions."^ Finally, a single tax on the produce of land is demanded because an indirect tax — that is, any tax except that upon the produit net — leads to frauds, condemnation of goods, loss of the labor of the great num- ber of men who are necessary to collect it, a war of the government with its subjects, a disproportion between crime and punishment, and " attacks liberty in a thousand ways."' Thus we find that according to the doctrine of the Physio- ' Turgot, Works, vol. iv, p. 215. * Ibid., p. 216. * Ibid., p. 220. ♦ Ibid., p. 306. » Ibid., p. 313. » Ibid., p. 363. ^ Ibid., p. 208. Il8 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [454 crats the economic basis of taxation lies in the relation which a certain class of society sustains to the government. This class is that of the landed proprietors who alone can have any interest in the government, since land alone pro- duces a net product over and above that which is necessary in order that there may be any production at all. But as the net product that attaches to land would not exist but for the government, the landlord should share it with the government in the form of a tax. Not only has no other class any in- terest in the government, but the net product of land is the only fund out of which a tax can ultimately be paid. As the net product is equally conditioned by landlords and the gov- ernment we have, further, as the principle of its distribution, as the economic principle of taxation, that the net product should be distributed equally between landlords and the government. Or, as the basis of the tax is the economic interest which the proprietors of land have in the govern- ment, the principle of its distribution is the extent of the in- terest in the joint economic result — the produit net — which is assumed to be a half interest. Criticism of this theory may be brief. Not only is its theory of incidence utterly erroneous,' but so also is its theory of a net product^ upon which its theory of taxation rests. Other factors of production than land yield a net product upon which a tax may ultimately fall, and which is equally with the net product from land conditioned by the existence of government. It follows, therefore, even from the view-point of the Physiocrats, that other classes than land- lords have an interest in the government, and that the gov- ernment has interest in other products than the net product from land. Moreover, because a government is a condition of a net product, or for that matter of any product, it does * See, for example, Hume, Essay on Taxes. * See Adam Smith, Wealth of Nations, bk. iv, ch. 9. 455] ECONOMIC BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 119 not follow that the product must be distributed between the producer and the government on the basis of the share of each in its production. Indeed, if this were so the govern- ment might claim the whole product beyond the barest necessities of life. Because a government conditions pro- duction it is not therefore a factor in production in the sense that it should share in the product in proportion to its inter- est in it. The fact is that the income of government bears no relation whatever to its part in production. Its income, and therefore taxation, depends upon its character and upon the functions it assumes. And whether or not a tax should be determined according to the principle of interests, it cer- tainly is not to be determined by any joint interest in a» economic product. But above all, government does some- thing more than condition production. It is the condition of the satisfaction of all of our wants, and therefore interest in it is general and not special ; and for the maintenance of these general interests — the interests of civilized life — gov- ernment requires economic support from every citizen of the state. 2. The Single Taxers. — The doctrine that the whole ex- pense of government should be met by a single tax on land was revived in more recent years by Henry George ' whose doctrine is now known as that of the "single tax." By its modern advocates, however, the argument for a single tax takes on a somewhat different form from that of the Physio- crats. By George and his followers the justice of a single tax rests upon the Ricardian theory of rent ; only emphasis is given to the social factor as producing differential advan- tages that give rise to the phenomenon of rent, quite as much as do differences in natural advantages. This rent is akin to the prodiiit net and is called the nnearned increment of land. But land is the birthright of man, a " gratuitous • Henry Q&oxghtz.vaiaM\, Natural Taxation, pp. Ii8-g. 457] ECONOMIC BASIS AND PRINCIPLES i2l men according to the special advantages they receive from the community, thus putting all men on an equal plane."' This is the principle of taxation according to benefits, and is <:ommon to all " single taxers," who repudiate the principle of ability as unjust or as an appeal " to sentiments of benevo- lence and philanthropy."^ The principle is purely an eco- nomic one, as the " advantage" is measured by " the market value of the benefits conferred by government and by human society," 3 the market value of ground rent. As the benefit is measured by the extent of the ground rent, and is " con- ferred by government and by human society," the tax, according to George, should absorb the whole increment of Jajid^hatJsjioXdk:eJqJiumaj^^ but Shearman, assum- ing that such a tax would be in excess of the needs of govern- ment, less consistently holds that the government should take only such part of the ground rent as it needs, leaving the rest to the landlords.-* >If, indeed, it is true that the whole ground rent, the unearned increment, belongs of right to the government, it is difificult to see the justice of any part of it being retained by any class of society. The only just method of distributing the surplus would be to distribute it pro rata to every member of society. That the doctrine of the "single tax" has the merit of simplicity cannot be doubted, nor that it contains some de- sirable features.5 We must, however, discredit its claim as a panacea for all social ills, as the fanciful dream of an enthu- ^ George, Shigle Tax Discussion, p. 83. " There can be but one strictly just basis of taxation, and that is the basis of benefit received from the taxing power;" Shearman, op. cit.. p. 228. * George, Ibid., p. 82, and Shearman, Ibid., p. 227. 'Shearman, Ibid., p. 229. * Cf. Shearman, op. cit., pp. 132-135; and also ch. 10. * See Prof, J. B. Clark, Single Tax Discussion, p. 5. 122 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [458 siast.' Nor can we grant that the " single tax," as a theory of taxation, solves the problem of justice. Granting the validity of the theory of social values, aud assuming its suffi- ciency for purposes of public revenue, we would still have the following criticisms to offer to the theory, as a theory of taxation : (i) It assumes as an economic basis for taxation, that only one class in society bears such an economic relation to the state that there rests upon it the obligation to support the government, to pay taxes, to wit: the proprietors of land ; whereas, in point of fact, the economic relation and the consequent obligation rest upon every class of society, upon every citizen of the state. (2) Not only does the theory assume a limited economic relation, but it assumes as the basis of this relation that land alone yields an unearned increment, which, while it belongs to society, or to govern- ment, comes in the first instance into the hands of the pos- sessors of land ; whereas, land is not the only source of an unearned increment — a rent or a qitasi-rGini — that arises from social conditions, and therefore the rent of land is not the only wealth, or source of revenue, which comes into the hands of individuals, but which, according to the single tax doctrine, belongs to the government. Apart from the ques- tion of a quasi-r&nt in other factors of production than land,' there are legal and capitalistic monopolies that produce unearned increments quite as much as does the monopoly of land. Moreover, there is no form of industry that is not benefited by social growth. (3) It is further assumed that the advantages of government lie in the possession of the source of the unearned increment, and that this advantage ^See George, Progress and Poveriy, B. ix, ch. 4; also, Shearman, ./Va/«ra/ Taxation, ch. 13. * On this point, see Marshall, Principles, B. vi, ch. 7; and Hobson, Economics of Distribution, ch. 5. 459] ECONOMIC BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 123 is the only ground for the imposition of a tax ; and therefore, that a tax according to the benefits received from the gov- ernment is the true principle of taxation. But as other factors than land possess these advantages (which are made the basis of taxation) it is difficult to see by what justice the possessor of land alone should pay for the advantage of obtaining an unearned increment. Besides, there are other economic advantages produced by the state that equally demand a recompense — as the maintenance of the social conditions necessary to the pursuit of a livelihood. More- over, in assuming that the unearned increment is the price of a special advantage it is assumed that the advantage is proportioned to the amount of the increment, a position whose absurdity is at once seen when we reflect that the ultimate advantage is confined to the privilege of gaining a livelihood. Then, too, this privilege is common to all. More than this, there is fn reality no payment for any special advantages, as the government simply takes the unearned increment, and upon this the landholder has no claim. (4) In fact, it is a special feature of this theory that no individual should undergo any burden of sacrifice for the purpose of maintaining a government; that, indeed, the government has no right to touch any part of private wealth that results from one's own labor, but should support itself on the economic values that belong to society as a whole, which is to assert that there should be no taxation. But such an assumption is opposed to any rational conception of the nature of the state, and misconceives the nature of the " natural right" to the product of one's own labor, since the payment of a portion of this product to support the govern- ment is a condition of its own existence. Yet, in the first instance, a tax is imposed upon the present holders of land who are made to pay penalty for the sin of past governments in permitting private property in land — a species of confisca- 124 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [460 tion, in spite of all refinements upon the word,' that is re- pugnant to all sense of justice. Various other forms of a single tax have been promul- gated by different writers, though not so much from any peculiar notion respecting the relation of the state to the economic life of its members as from the conviction that a single tax best realizes the ideal of a tax according to ability. Such theories belong to the discussion of systems of taxation, and need not be dwelt upon here. There is one theory, however, that may be briefly touched upon, as it assumes a certain economic relation between the individual and the state as its economic basis. I refer to the theory of Menier,^ who would obtain public revenue by a single tax upon capital. The argument of Menier is as follows: Capital is a national product and therefore out of it alone should the state derive its income, " the tax representing the expense of giving value to, and the exploitation of, the national capital." Moreover, since the state exists to further in- dividual liberty and human personality — "the enfranchise- ment of the individual" 3 — it should not lay any tax burden upon the individual as such. " The tax," says Menier, " ought not to know man, but only the national fortune. But since this fortune is held by individuals they should pay a tax in proportion to what they hold." ^ The position is not wholly unlike that of George, since he would take the tax out of the national capital upon which the state has a claim because exploited by itself, the princi- ple of taxation being a proportion to the amount of the national capital individually possessed, no tax being im- posed upon the individual, as such. But does not Menier ' See Shearman, op. cit., p. 169. * Theorie et Application de Plmpdi sur le Capital. ' Op. cit., p. 192. * Ibid., p. 196. 46 1 ] ECONOMIC BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 125 confuse a nominal and a real tax on capital, thus leading to the untenable position that a tax on capital does not, while a tax on income or other form of wealth does, interfere with individual rights and individual liberty? Besides, income quite as much as capital is a national product, and quite as much as capital is given value by the government. Not the least error of Menier, however, is the assumption that a tax is upon property, not upon the person. Only persons can have a responsible relation to the state, or be under obliga- tions for its support. The state, it is true, demands prop- erty, that is, economic goods, but the demand is and can be only upon persons. Then, too, Menier falls into the error of supposing that one's interest in the government and obli- gation to it is directly proportional to the amount of capital that he possesses. II. The Classical School of Economists I, The Benefit Theory of Taxation. The economic basis of the classical economists rests upon their theory of the state as the protector of persons and property, while their principle of taxation is that the tax should be proportioned to the benefits derived from the protection. The economic aspect of taxation, in short, is simply the economic side of their political doctrine. Hence, a tax is regarded as an economic return for a presumably measurable benefit re- ceived from the government. This conception dififers from that of the Physiocrats only in the character and extent of the content contained in the idea of benefits. Here the idea is that the relation of the state to the individual is that of a protector and guarantor of liberty, and that the individual should compensate for the expense of this protection in pro- portion to the benefits derived from it. It is an economic relation that is the counterpart of the Contract theory of the state, and is very largely an outgrowth of it. 126 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [462 According to this view, then, a tax is considered as the expense of protection, while the value of the protection is measured by the amount of property protected. This is implied in the famous dictum of Montesquieu : that taxes are the payment of a part of one's property in order to enjoy the remainder in security.' It is expressed still more explicitly by Adam Smith, whose canon has become classic on principles of taxation. Subjects, he says, should con- tribute to the support of government " in proportion to the revenue which they respectively enjoy under the protection of the state. The expense of government to the individuals of a great nation, is like the expense of management to the joint tenants of a great estate, who are all obliged to con- tribute in proportion to their interests in the estate." ' True, this conception of taxation is given as an explanation of the meaning of " ability," which is regarded as the basic prin- ciple. But it is only by a confusion of ideas, or an incon- sistency of thought, that the principle of ability can be con- nected with the protection theory of the state. And yet this confusion or inconsistency is found in most of the classical economists. Its most extreme type is, perhaps, found in Murhard, who bases the tax upon the protection of property ,3 yet would proportion the tax to "ability,"* expressly re- pudiating a tax proportioned to the amount of income enjoying the protection. 5 Such, in the main, is the view of most writers of this school, some, like Murhard, emphasizing the protection of * Montesquieu, Esprit des Lois, ch. I. * Smith, Wealth 0/ Amotions, -p^.^i/^-^ (Rogers' edition). ' " Steuern werden bezahlt zum Schutze des Eigenthums. Darum, und nur darum gebe Ich Steuern." Murhard, Theorie und Polilik der Besteureung, p. 2P> * For taxes are " am gUicklicbsten gewahlt, wo jeder Staatsgenosse im Verhaltniss Seiner Krafte zu den Staats-Aufgaben beitragt." Ibid., p. 80. » Cf. ibid., p. 26. 463 J ECONOMIC BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 127 property, others, like Sismondi, emphasizing the protection of persons.' From the point of view of consistency, how- ever, Von Hock makes a distinct advance, since he not only recognizes the protection of both persons and property, but would have an equal tax for the former and a tax proportional to the benefits of protection for the latter.'-' Like Sismondi, too, he places the question squarely upon an economic ground, making the tax a compensation for the services received from the state.3 Yet in the hands of Von Hock the protection principle loses much of its character, as, indeed, it does also with Sismondi, since the term is made to include practically all that is contained in the idea of national well- being (das Wohl des Volkes). Protection, with such an extended conception of its content, loses, too, any signifi- cance that it might have as a basis of taxation, since it is incapable of giving a principle that is consistent with itself, for the distribution of the tax burden. We have had occasion to criticise the principle of benefits in the preceding chapter. As afTording an economic basis and principles it is even more defective than it is as a polit- ical principle. To have any validity from the view-point of economics the benefits of protection must have a definite assignable value, else the tax cannot be a compensation for a value received. From the point of view of the protection of persons it cannot be said that the benefit of the protection is equal, as Von Hock assumes, nor that the benefits from ' " L'impot doit etre considere par les citoyens comme une compensation de la protection que le gouvernement accorde k leurs personnes et k leurspropriet^s. II est juste que tous le supportent, en proportion des avantages que la societe leur garantit, et des depenses que la societe fait pour eux." Economie Politique, vol, II, p. 155. ' Cf. Von Hock, Die offenilichen Abgaben und Schulden, §§ 1-4. •" Jeder Abgabe ist eine Vergeltung der vom Staat geleisteten Dienste, und erscheint darum nur dann gerechtfertigt, wenn der Dienst des Lohns werth ist." Op, cie., p. 4. 128 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [464 the protection of property are proportional to the amount of property enjoying the protection, as most upholders of this theory maintain. Still less is it possible to apportion the tax to benefits when, as with Von Hock and Sismondi, bene- fits are made to include such immaterial qualities as honor^ glory, education, religion, national well-being, etc. But apart from the impossibihty of determining the value of the benefits, the economic relation between the individual and the state cannot be expressed by the idea of compensation for benefits received. Nor is this due simply to the fact that the benefits are not measurable quantities. The falsity of this conception rests chiefiy upon the fact that it is wholly out of harmony with the social relations that a tax involves. Indeed, the inadequacy of this conception would seem to be felt by most of its defenders, since they, following Adam Smith, interpret "benefits" as synonymous with " ability." But the two ideas are totally distinct and mutually exclude each other. As Bastable says : " So far as the ' benefits ' or ' service ' principle is applied, it excludes the rule of tax- ation according to ability." ' Most writers, however, who accept the benefit principle (whether or not they make it synonymous with ability) find a measure of benefits in the assumption that the benefits of government are proportional to the amount of property enjoyed or consumed. As ex- pressed by Sir William Petty : " Every man ought to con- tribute according to what he taketh to himself, and actually enjoyeth." = With Petty this means, as with Hobbes, that the benefit is proportional to what one consumes, and there- fore that the tax should be a proportional tax on consump- tion. This, too, is the tendency of the classical economists, who would throw every safeguard around capital and pro- * Bastable, Fut/ic Finance, p. 389. Gen. Walker and Mile. Royer, also of the classical school, likewise repudiate the " benefit " principle. * Petty, A Treatise of Taxes and Contributions, p. 83. 465] ECONOMIC BASIS AND PRINCIPLES 129 duction. But not the amount of property that one possesses, and still less what one consumes, nor any other portion of income, is an adequate measure of the benefits of govern- ment. Nor is the claim of government limited to any por- tion of income. As Gen. Walker has well said, " the reve- nue rights of the state attach equally to every portion of private revenue, irrespective of the consideration whether any such portion is to be spent or to be saved." ' But above all this view of the economic aspect of taxation is at fault, because it assumes a relation of economic equivalence where no such equivalence is possible, and because it falsely as- sumes that such an equivalence is the true basis and measure of the tax. 2. The Exchange Theory. The same in principle as the theory of " benefits," though different in point of view, is the " exchange theory" of Bastiat and Perry. Although this view of the tax was earlier expressed by Senior in his " Po- litical Economy," with Bastiat and Perry it was made a part of their economic theory, the collection and expenditure of public revenue being regarded as determined by the same principles of exchange that determine all economic ex- changes. The theory starts with the principle of the " division of labor." '^ In all departments of economic activities, so the argument runs, protection is required, and in the division of labor in social and economic life the function of protection is assigned to the government. For_tiie_iLsefviee-". that- the govern m ent^perlornis-ia-proeuriTig the protec+ion- every-.ecp- fiornic activity owes an^ '^equivalents -service 4a-ex£liaage.. That_JSr--in the "division of labor," go vernnjent^perfoMiis _one_sei:yice^— protection — in,exx:iiaTige for another^ervice — contribirtionofjtaxes. Or taxation, like all private economic 1 Francis Walker, "The Bases of Taxation," in Pol. Sci. Quart, iii, p. II. * Perry, Political Economy, p. 516. See also, Senior, Political Economy, p. 74. 130 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [466 activity, finds its basis and its principles in a theory of ex- change of equivalent economic services. As Perry puts it, taxation " finds a ready and solid justification in the com- mon principles of exchange." Indeed, " taxes demanded of citizens by a lawful government which tolerably performs its functions, are legitimate and just on principles of exchange alone." ' For " value resides in services exchanged ; but government is an essential prerequisite to any general and satisfactory exchanges, since it contributes by direct effort to the security of persons and property ; and justly claims, therefore, from each citizen a compensation in return for services thus rendered him.^"" The same thought is also expressed by Bastiat, who declares that when a state renders a service equal to the tax, there is only an exchange (il n'y a qu'un ^change) ;3 and that a good or a bad use is made of the tax according as the service of the state is, or is not, equivalent to what the public gives in exchange — the tax.^ In other words, according to the exchange theory of tax- ation the basis of the tax is an economic " exchange of ser- vices" betwen the government and the taxpayer. That is, the government being a participating factor in all private exchanges, it should find compensation for its " service " by participating in the gains from these exchanges. Or, the *' gains " accruing to individuals because of the service of the government in providing protection and security, the indi- viduals should share their gains with the government in ex- change for its service. And from these assumptions we get as a principle of taxation that individuals should contribute to the cost of the service of the government " in proportion to the gains of their exchanges." s * Perry, Political Economy, p. 516. * Ibid., p. 515. * Bastiat, Ce qu^ on voit et ce qu^ on ne voit pas, * Bastiat, Sophismes Aconomiques, Oeuvrcs, iv, p. 47 (Ed. 1863). •Perry, The Science of Finance, p. 297. * Cf. Adams, Public Finance, p. 330. 174 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [510 pointed out, that the tax obligation can rest only upon per- sons, since on\y persons can have a membership in and are capable of obligations to the state. True, a tax involves property, but property as incidental to a person. Property, we have said, is the person objectified, and a tax upon prop- erty is, therefore, a tax upon persons. But the obligation is not upon the property, but upon the person, as the term ability implies. The term " ability," moreover, has the merit of implying more than personal obligation. Its content is positive in character, and carries with it the idea of active participation in the support of the state, corresponding with active participation in the general ends of the state. But after all that is said, ability to pay is a relative con- ception. In the first place, it implies relativity to the ability of others; a relativity that follows from the recognition that the tax obligation that rests upon self, likewise rests upon others because it rests upon persons, and because others, equally with the self, are recognized as persons. In the second place, the term is relative to personal wants, for ability to pay taxes has no meaning, or at least lacks in significance, except with reference to the relative ability to satisfy collective and personal wants. For, unless the paramount personal wants are satisfied, there can be no tax for the satisfaction of collective wants. Besides, the person must be given first consideration, since the whole exists for the sake of the person — for the individual. Ethical considerations, in other words, re-enforce the economic' In the third place, since the tax and the satisfaction of private wants require economic goods, ability to pay is relative to some form of material wealth. In brief, " ability," as a basis of taxation, involves the relation of one's economic wealth to his personal and collective wants, compared with the similar relation of every other member of the state. ^ Cf. ante, p. 143 et seq. 5ii] THE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 175 It is around these relations involved in ability — relation to others, to self, and to economic goods — that the whole prob- lem of just distribution of the tax burden revolves. Only as the content of ability in these relations is gradually unfolded are we able to get at the full meaning of ability, as only in their development are we able to discover the just principles of taxation. For if ability be the true ethical basis of taxa- tion it must contain within itself the ethical principles of taxation, just as the acorn contains the oak ; so that in de- veloping its meaning we are developing the principles in- volved, or implied, in it. Principles of justice are, as it were, attributes of the basis of justice. It is in the development of these principles that consists the most important and the most difficult part of the prob- lem of justice in taxation. For although the principles must have their root in the basic idea — ability — and be developed logically from it, differences of point of view or of interpre- tation may lead to opposing or conflicting results. We shall, nevertheless, attempt to develop these principles as they appear to us as the logical consequences of the ideas most naturally connected in the term " ability." The re- mainder of the present chapter, however, will be devoted to a review of opinions respecting the relation of ability to property, to income, and to subjective sacrifice, at the same lime indicating the limitations of each. I. Ability and Property. — The most natural, as also the most obvious, test of economic ability is the amount of property possessed. Ability — faculty {facultas) — has throughout the centuries been associated with the idea of property — economic wealth. Cicero somewhere makes /rt:c- ultas synonymous with wealth, or possessions, and Coulanges points out that in the ninth century facultas signified one's entire property.' So again in the sixteenth century, Bodinus, ^ Coulanges, The Origin of Properly in Land, p. 72. 176 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [512 in opposing the privileges of the upper classes that then prevailed, declared that taxes should be universal, and should be borne equally by all classes of citizens according to their ability, or faculty {qicae in omnes orduies pro singulorum faciiliatibiis exaeqiiantur), which he explains to mean ac- cording to their wealth, or fortune {pro cujtisqiie opibus ac fortunis).^ Thus ability — faculty — and property had long been inter- changeable terms when ability was first made a basis of tax- ation ; so that it was one and the same thing whether the basis was considered to be property or ability. Still, the root idea was that the tax should be based upon ability to pay, but that this ability was measured by the amount of property or fortune possessed. Now there can be no doubt that fortune, or property, was a fair representation of ability, and so an approximately fair basis of taxation, under the primitive economic conditions that prevailed in early indus- trial society ; when there were no great inequalities of for- tune, industries were little diversified and wealth consisted almost wholly of property in land, social wants were few, and social conditions were upon an approximate equality. But under the conditions of modern industrial and social life, where these relations no longer hold, and where there is a growing class of propertyless producers, or, at least, produc- tive agents without capital, it must be clear that property alone affords a very inadequate test of ability ; for the ability to satisfy wants — the real test of ability — and, therefore, the ability to contribute to the support of the state, is not con- ditioned by the personal ownership of property. Besides, even where property is the source of the means of satisfying wants there is not necessarily the same proportionate power of satisfaction, since the means are not necessarily propor- tionate to the amount of property. For not only is some * Quoted by Meyer, op. cit., p. 4. 513] THE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 177 property unproductive of further means, but productive property is not always equally productive. Nevertheless, property is an index of ability, even " un- productive " or consumable property ; for the amount and character of the property that we possess indicates to a very large extent our power of satisfying our wants, and, there- fore, our tax ability. It is, indeed, as an " index," not as an absolute measure, that property is regarded by those who hold it to be synonymous with ability, though the index is necessitated more from practical than from theoretical grounds. Baer, for instance, would base all taxes upon property,' because property is a measure of ability. To get at a more accurate relation between property and ability, however, he divides property into three classes — productive property, unproductive property and property whose desti- nation is not yet determined upon." For each class there is an index, or indices, since the amount cannot be accurately determined directly. For example, the index for productive property is capitalized interest, while for unproductive prop- erty the indices are the articles of common consumption, the " ability " of this class of property being reached by con- sumption taxes — on wines, spirits, tobacco, etc. But even as an index the property test is wanting in im- portant particulars. It is true that property as a basis of taxation does not mean that the tax should be paid out of property, otherwise the property, and with it the ability, would soon be exhausted. The tax is presumed to be only nominally upon property ; in reality it is upon income. That is, the " index " is an index of income, and the real basis of ability is thereby assumed to be income, and not ^ " II criterio per giudicare della parita delle condizione o di loro rapporti in piu o in meno non puo essere altro che quello dell, importanza delle sostanze, dell' avere, dei beni che si possegono." L" Avere e V Imposta, p. 19. ' Ibid., p. 32 et seq. 178 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [514 property. But for practical reasons Baer and others would base the tax upon property as the best means of ascertain- ing income, it being a practical impossibility to determine real income by direct methods. This, too, is the common practice and is a necessity for many forms of income. But it is not less true that many forms of property are, in prac- tice, very imperfect indices of income, or ability; as note, for example, the universal failure of personal property taxes. For income not derived from property a more accurate test is consumption, and consumption taxes, such as those on spirits, tobacco and other luxuries, are a more accurate test of ability. However important, then, property may be as an index to income, and therefore of ability, it needs to be supple- mented by other tests to reach the full tax ability. It is theoretically defective because, being indirect, it affords only a proximate test of the power to satisfy wants ; it is practically defective because many forms of property cannot be discovered by the tax assessor. We cannot, therefore, subscribe to the contention of Menier, that the state has no right to inquire into what one makes or does, but only into the share of the national fortune that he possesses.' 2. Ability and Income. — Since Adam Smith first pub- Hshed his famous canons of taxation, property, as a measure of ability, has been commonly interpreted to mean revenue, or income. That there is, indeed, some doubt what was in the mind of Smith when, in explaining the term " abilities," he wrote : " That is, in proportion to the revenue which they respectively enjoy under the protection of the state," may be admitted.'^ But however this may be, it has generally been understood to mean that ability is measured by income, and it is with this meaning that the first canon has been so 1 Cf. Menier, op. cit., p. 196. « Op. cit., p. 414. 515] THE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 179 universally accepted, it being assumed that Smith stood for the principle of " ability " rather than that of " benefits." However true it may be that there are circumstances when it is necessary to use property as a measure or index, of income, there can be no doubt but that income is a truer measure of ability than is property. For in income is represented the actual earning power of the individual, the realized capacity of providing the material means for the satisfaction of wants. Moreover, income as a measure of ability is in harmony with the fact we have so often em- phasized, that the tax is a tax upon the person — upon his ability to satisfy his wants. But after all, income is a very vague and indefinite measure of ability. If we are to measure ability by income we must know what is meant by income ; also, the character of the income that determines the tax ability, that is, what portion of the total receipts of the individual constitutes his taxable income. (i) Meafiing of Income. — By income is generally un- derstood the returns that come in to the individual as the result of his economic activities, or from his control of the economic activities of others. It does not, however, include the total receipts of an industry. These are known as " gross incomes." Income, properly so called, is the "net income" that results after deducting from the gross income the costs of production and the maintenance of the plant. That part of the gross income that is absorbed in costs and maintenance is not a return that is at the disposal of the individual. The expenditure is essential that there may be any return, but it does not of itself add anything to that which was already possessed. Income, in an economic sense, implies an increase of wealth in addition to that which is already possessed, and which comes in within a definite period of time, giving an increased power of satisfying wants l8o JUSTICE IN TAXATION [516 within that period of time. Only net income is such an in- come. But the term "income " has been given a more extended meaning, and has been made to include the indirect income from enjoyment, or use, of so-called " unproductive" pro- perty, thus giving emphasis to periodic enjoyment rather than to periodic new acquisitions. All income, indeed, is valuable only as it affords means of enjoyment, to the satis- faction of wants. Income is a means, satisfaction the end. Hence possession of property is by some regarded as an addition to the money income derived from gainful occupa- tions, for its possession enables a given money income to satisfy the wants that otherwise remain unsatisfied. Such possessions are houses (occupied by the owner) and their furnishings. Take, for example, A and B, having equal money incomes, but A owning his house, while B rents a house of equal value, say at five hundred dollars per annum. Clearly, five hundred dollars represent the excess of A's income over B's, as measured in the satisfaction of wants. That is, A has five hundred dollars to spend for satisfactions that B cannot enjoy, has five hundred dollars more to dis- pose of than B has. His " ability," therefore, is greater than B's to the extent of five hundred dollars, other things being equal. That the same is true of household furnishings, paintings, or other" unproductive" property of this class, is not equally clear. True, if enjoyment is the test of income, such prop- erty is an advantage to income, just as is the ownership of a home. Yet the two cases appear to us to be quite dilTerent, particularly in the case of luxuries. The enjoyment of these is not income in the sense that house rent saved by owner- ship is income. They are enjoyments procured by means of income, but are not an addition to income — do not save income — in the sense that this is true of house rent saved. 517] THE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 181 As a rule (where not from gift or inheritance) they are an index of income, but not themselves income. They do not increase ability; on the contrary, they decrease it. Neces- sary household furniture should, perhaps, be excluded from this class, but from the practical impossibility of determin- ing where the necessity ends and the luxury begins, no dis- tinction should be made. If, however, with Cohn we regard luxuries as " income consumed in kind," ' we must admit with Meyer that its value " is impossible to reckon." ^ The mistake, we are inclined to think, lies in making en- joyment the sole criterion of income. Because income has value only as it is a means of enjoyment, it does not follow that all means of enjoyment are income. If such is the test of income, then there is little that is not income. All con- sumable goods would be income — food, clothing, shelter, etc, etc. Yet how small would be the income of the miser, however large his hoardings. 3 This is a needless confusion of ideas. For our purposes, at least, luxuries should not be regarded as income, but only as indices of income, and this is really the way in which Cohn regards them.* The income that we are seeking is the income that brings in annually positive acquisitions of material goods, disposable for the satisfaction of wants, and whether the acquisition is direct or indirect. Luxuries, we repeat, do not constitute such an income. They do not increase the sum of disposable goods in the sense that this is true of the ownership of a house. They represent satisfactions enjoyed — income expended — but they add nothing to ability, but only indicate its extent. * Cohn, op. cit., p. 359. * Meyer, op. ciL, pp. 327-8. * Cf. Rogers' criticism of Adam Smith's first canon in note to his edition of Wealth of Nations, p. 414. Much of this criticism is strained, particularly where Rogers concludes that if the emphasis of Smith is on " protection," then women and children should pay heavier taxes. The protection clearly refers to " revenue," not to persons. * Cf. for example, op. cit,, pp. 360-1. 1 82 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [518 (2) Taxable Income. — If we are right in our determination of the nature of income, we have next to inquire what is the character of taxable income, the income that determines tax ability. Evidently this cannot be gross income; for this would be, in effect, a tax upon the source of income, whose tendency would be the gradual extinction of income, of satis- factions, and thereby of ability. Costs and maintenance should, therefore, be rigidly excluded from taxable income.' (This is not saying that for practical reasons there should not be nominal taxes on gross income or capital.) What is left after these deductions is a net income. This, or some part of it, must then be the taxable income, the income that determines tax ability. Whether it is the whole or a part only of the net income that is the taxable income, economists do not agree. With the earlier economists, following the Enghsh school, the taxable income was held to be the "pure" income — the net income minus the necessary cost of subsistence. That is, there was assumed to be no ability to pay taxes until the income exceeded that required to supply the necessaries of life, since in the satisfaction of wants there is no " clear " income until the stage of enjoyments is reached.^ This view of income, it is true, is peculiar rather to the benefit than to the ability theory of taxation, it being assumed that there can be no benefits of government until after the means of subsistence are provided for. But it has its advocates also in those who accept the ability basis of taxation, and, as we shall see later, not without much show of reason. But largely through the influence of the German econo- mists, the net income is now far more generally accepted as the true taxable income ; at least nominally so. That is, it 1 " Man darf die Henne nicht schlachten welche goldene Eier legt." Schaffle, Grundsdtze, p. 57. ' Cj. Stein, op, cit., p. 230. 519] THE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 183 is considered as the theoretical ideal, but is negatived as an ideal by the admission of exemptions. According to Wag- ner, the "net" income theory is the logic of the financial view-point, while the ""clear" income theory is the logic of the social-political view-point.' The chief defense of the net income theory is found in the indispensableness of the state to the individual. Being a necessity, it should be placed upon an equality with other necessities in respect to satisfaction. This would seem to follow, too, from the nature of the state as we have regarded it; also from both the political and the economic basis of taxation. That is, from the universal obligations of citizenship, and from the seemingly relative importance of collective and private wants. When, however, the taxable income is viewed from the standpoint of ability it is not so self-evident that it is repre- sented by net income; unless, indeed, we assume that net income measures ability, in which case we have but a vicious circle. If, as we think Schafifle justly says: "Ability is an expression for how much a taxable unit can give up to the support of the state without injury to his own relative sup- port,"^ it is questionable if there is a taxable income — ability — until a "clear" income appears — an income over and above the necessities of life. Whether, however, the taxable income is a "net" or a "clear" income; whether, that is, ability is determined by net or clear income, is a question that involves political and ethical considerations that are inseparable from the problem of the exemption of the minimum of subsistence. In other words, it involves the problem of the justice of exemptions. We may, there- fore, postpone further discussion of this question until we take up the problem of exemptions in the following chapter. But it is a question, also, whether or not ability is affected by source, permanence, and size of income ; but this is a ' Op. cii.,'Tp. 330. * Grundsdize, p. 23. 1 84 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [5 20 question of rates, which like that of exemption, is a question of principles, and will, therefore, also be deferred to the fol- lowing chapter. Here, we wish only to emphasize the fact that a prime condition of " ability " is a net income. That it is not the only condition we shall see later. A somewhat dififerent criterion of ability-determining in- come was advocated by the late President Walker. Accord- ing to him ability is determined, not by actual income but by the capacity, or faculty, to produce income ; not by realized but by realizable income. Accordingly he defined ability (he used the term faculty) as the " native or acquired power of production," a tax on this basis being the " most equitable form of public contribution."' Property, expendi- ture, and revenue all come in for criticism as a basis of taxation. Property, because a tax on property " constitutes a penalty on saving (p. 3); expenditure, because "the revenue rights of the state attach equally to every portion of private revenue, irrespective of the consideration whether any such portion is to be spent or saved" (p. 11), and because any exemption of expenditure, "on the ground that it is to be used for the public good," involves the right, which may become a duty of the state, " to see that such wealth is, in fact, in all respects and at all times put to the best possible use;" and it is added: "If this is not social- ism of the rankest sort, 1 should be troubled to define socialism" (p. 12); revenue, because "the revenue tax lays the heavier burden upon him who most fully and dili- gently uses his abilities and opportunities. It even accepts indolence, shiftlessness and worthlessness as a sufficient ground for excuse from public contributions" (p. 14). In- deed, " to tax wealth instead of revenue is to put a premium upon self-indulgence, in the form of expenditure for present enjoyment," while " to tax revenue instead of faculty is to 1 Francis A. Walker, "The Basis of Taxation," in Polit. Set. Quart., vol. iii, p. 14. 52 1 ] THE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 185 put a premium upon self-indulgence in the form of indolence, the waste of opportunities, the abuse of natural powers." Hence, " a faculty tax constitutes the only theoretically just form of taxation, men being required to serve the state in the degree in which they have ability to serve themselves," ' any departure from this rule constituting a departure from justice. As a purely theoretical ideal this view of the tax basis is> perhaps, sound. It has the merit of emphasizing the necessity of positive effort ; it justly expresses the moral obligation resting upon every citizen to put forth his fullest energies and powers to the support of the state on whose maintenance depends his civilized existence; it justly empha- sizes, also, the moral obligation resting upon the individual because of his ethical relations to his fellow men, growing out of his and their natures as spiritual beings — as persons — and the identity of their mutual relations to the state. But if this is the ideal', it is an ideal to be realized only in the millenium. Under existing conditions of society it cannot be admitted that departure from it is departure from justice. From the practical viewpoint the chief objections to this theory of ability are : it is Utopian ; it necessitates most arbi- trary powers of government; it is too objective, {a) It is Utopian since there is no way of determining whether the " native or acquired powers of production" have been exer- cised to their utmost capacity, if material results are not be taken as the expression of the potential capacity under exist- ing social and economic conditions (as no doubt in many cases they cannot be), {b^ The only other alternative is the determination of these powers by the government. But this ''■Ibid. p. 15. To the same effect Mile. Royer writes: "Nous devpns contribuer de nos personnes, de nos facultfes intellectuelles et de nos forces physiques, comme de cette extension ext6rieure de notre etre que nous appelons nos biens, nos pro- pri6t6s." Thiorit de V Impdi, p. 24. 1 86 JUSTICE IN TAXATION 522 could not be except by most arbitrary methods and with most indifferent results. Besides, such a method of determi- tion would defeat itself, since the highest productive efficiency would not be obtained under such a sj^stem of governmental slavery. Moreover, when a government assumes the func- tion of seeing that every individual develops his latent power, and that no one be allowed to shift his burden upon others by "indolence, shiftlessness and worthlessness," logi- cally and justly it will be compelled to guarantee the condi- tions of their exercise, just as the logic of the Elizabethan Poor Laws was the public workhouse ; for these powers can- not be exercised where the means are wholly wanting, any more than the "vagabond" could work without tools and materials. Still more, with such functions it would "unmis- takably be the right, and it might even become the duty of the state to see that such powers are, in fact, in all respects and at all times put to the best possible use. But, " if this is not socialism of the rankest sort I should be troubled to define socialism." In fact, no action of the government could be more paternal or more arbitrary.' (c) Finally, this view of the ability is too subjective, too indeterminate, to be of practical value. In determining the ability of the tax- payer, the government is bound of necessity to measure his ability by objective, not by imaginary results. In short, we must, as Spinoza would say, deal with adequate ideas of the understanding, not with confused ideas of the imagination. Or actual income, not the theoretical possibilities of income, is the safest guide to real tax ability. Yet it must be admitted that the mere objective fact of income is but one factor in the determination of tax ability. ' Neumann opposes to the basing of the tax on the ability to produce the follow- ing objection : " Die Ermittelung dariiber wie viele Jemand nach seiner k5rper- lichen oder geistlichen Fahigkeiten noch erwerben konnte, diirften schwer zum Ziele fuhren und entsetzlichster Willkiir Thiir und Thor offnen." Die Progressive Einkommensteuer, p. 172. 523] THE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 187 Not only must we take account of income, but also of the legitimate demands upon that income. Or, from a different point of view, it is a question of the effect upon the tax- payer of the deprivation of a part of his income for the sup- port of the state — the effect of contributions for his collect- ive wants upon the satisfaction of his private wants. This suggests a negative and subjective determination of ability : That it is not income that determines it, but the sacrifices endured by the taxpayer in the way of the non-satisfaction of private wants, of the loss of personal enjoyments. This view has suggested the sacrifice theory of taxation, or ability. Ill Ability and Sacrifice I. Mill. — The first writer clearly to substitute subjective sacrifice for objective ability, as measured by revenue, as the basis of taxation, was John Stuart Mill' With Mill the basic idea in the distribution of taxes is sacrifice. The aim of justice in taxation is to effect an "equality of sacrifice;" not the giving up of equal shares of the means of enjoyment — revenue — but the giving up of equal enjoyments. " The true principle of taxation I conceive to be, not that it shall be equal in proportion to means, but that it shall, as far as pos- sible, demand an equal sacrifice from all," /. e., a " propor- tional sacrifice of enjoyments."^ This is Mill's substitute for taxation " according to ability." In a sense it is his explanation of the meaning of ability, though to Mill the idea of sacrifice is not so much an interpretation of ability, as it is a new principle of taxation. For with him the fundamental idea of justice is to be ex- plained, not in terms of ability, but in terms of sacrifice. The ideal is, "equality of sacrifice;" that each person ^ Political Economy, bk. v, ch. 2, § 2. * Report of the Tax Commission of 18^2, Mill's testimony, pp. 286, 312. 1 88 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [524 " shall feel neither more nor less inconvenience from his share of the payment than every other person experiences from his." ' This view of the basis of justice in taxation is the natural result of the reflections of a philosophic mind on the obliga- tions of the citizen to the state, and is no doubt influenced by a utilitarian ethics whose highest principle is the greatest possible sum of pleasure to each consistent with the like pleasure of others. It emphasizes the idea that the obliga- tion of the individual to the state calls for a sacrifice, a giving up, rather than an active, positive effort, and in this respect is directly opposite to the theory of Walker. From the viewpoint of Mill, " equality of sacrifice " is clearly the best expression we have of the theoretical ideal of the obli- gation resting upon the taxpayer; but, to our mind, this negative conception of our obligations does not bring out so clearly and fully our relations to the state as does the posi- tive conception that calls for efTort, activity, the fullest exer- cise of our faculties — taxation according to ability. We are inclined to think, too, that, theoretically at least, the two conceptions are quite distinct, representing distinct bases of taxation. Practically and objectively, however, there is no difference. For we find that Mill, in his testimony before the Tax Com- mission, is compelled to appeal to an objective standard — income or property — for the determination of the equal sacrifices. Ideally, he thinks, that equality of sacrifice is a proportion to what one is able to spend — his income ; but for practical reasons — the low state of morality — there should be an " equal sacrifice according to means," ^ which is just what Mill has said is not the true principle of taxa- tion. In short, viewed with respect to their objective ex- pression, ability and sacrifice are but two aspects of the 1 Political Economy, v. 2, § 2. ' See Testimony, p. 301 et seq. 52 5 THE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 189 same idea, the tertiiun qtcid being income, by which Mill means a "clear" income, including in the deduction not only the necessaries but also the lesser comforts, the taxable income being that part of income that is spent upon luxuries. So that equality of sacrifice comes to this : That each should "pay a fixed proportion, not of his whole means, but of his superfluities," ' just what taxation according to ability means to the advocate of the clear income theory. 2. Wagner and Neumaim. — Since the time of Mill "equality of sacrifice" has come to be very generally accepted as expressive of the basis of just principles of taxa- tion, but it is not considered as a distinct principle, but only as the subjective form of ability. Yet, while some, like Mill, find in the conception of sacrifice the true basis of jus- tice, others find that this basis is best expressed in the con- ception of ability. Wagner, for example, accepts the sacri- fice theory of Mill but thinks that the true norm of taxation is the economic ability to pay (wirthschaftliche Leistungs- fahigkeit), but that the sacrifice theory shows more defi- nitely how equality in taxation — taxation according to ability — is to be accomplished,^ or the meaning of ability. So likewise Neumann : " It is through a consideration of the sacrifice imposed that the measure of ability acquires defi- nite form and becomes useful for a system of taxation." 3 That is, both Wagner and Neumann find in the idea of " taxation according to ability " the real norm or demand of justice, but hold that the attainment of this norm is best accomplished in terms of sacrifice. This, I think, is the more usual form in which the ability and sacrifice theories ' Political Economy , v. 2, § 3. * «' Hier dient diese Theorie [OpfertheorieJ dazu, genauer den Weg zu weisen wie die Gleichmassigkeit der Besteuerung durchzufuhren ist." Wagner, Finamw. ". P- 349- •Neumann, Progressive Einkommensteuer, p. 62. I90 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [526 are held. And it has the merit of at once emphasizing the fact that in the positive idea of ability — effort — is the real basis of the tax obligation ; and at the same time, also, that every tax necessarily involves the sacrifice of personal satis- factions, the degree of the sacrifice marking the degree of ability, while the relative sacrifice of each to the sacrifice of others, marks the relative tax ability. Hence, accordingly, equal taxation according to ability is theoretically attained by effecting an equality of sacrifice. In determining the equality of sacrifice, however, Wagner, Neumann, and others are compelled, like Mill, to revert to objective standards. Indeed, with most the practical stand- ard is one rather of objective than of subjective sacrifice — the effect upon objective economic conditions, rather than upon subjective feelings. But Wagner and Neumann go even farther than does Mill in making allowances for the external circumstances that affect the sacrifice and thereby determine the ability; for they consider not only the source, size and character of the income, but also the circumstances and condition — health, indebtedness, etc. — of those de- pendent upon it. By considerations such as these, it is assumed, an equality of sacrifice may be attained, or, that " taxes will occasion equal efforts and sacrifices over against other needs." ' 3. Meyer. — Nominally opposed to the theory of Wagner and Neumann, and in form more nearly akin to the view of Mill, is the theory of Meyer, who insists that equality of sub- jective sacrifice is the true tax basis, but admits that this equality can be effected only through a consideration of the "ability to pay."' The difference, however, is more in seeming than in reality, except in the emphasis given to the central idea that lies at the basis of a just distribution of taxes, the emphasis being given in the one case to ability, * Neumann, ibid., p. 6j. ^ Cf. Meyer, op. (it., §§ 50 and 53. 527] THE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 191 and in the other to the idea of sacrifice. But there is no difference with respect to the objective and practical stand- ard of abihty, or sacrifice. The theory of Meyer, however, is not a mere restatement nor a mere expansion of the theory of Mill. It is peculiar to the theory of Meyer, as distinguished from the preceding views of sacrifice, that he gives greater definiteness to the meaning of the subjective sacrifice occasioned by the tax, by connecting it with the intensities of our " marginal wants," the intensity of the marginal wants occasioned by the tax, measuring the degree of the subjective sacrifice. But Meyer understands by the marginal want affected by the tax, not the last want unsatisfied because of the tax, but the last want attaining satisfaction.' In this view of the marginal want effected by the tax Meyer seems to think that he has discovered some new principle, but we fail to see what pos- sible difference it can make, in measuring the subjective effect of a tax, whether we consider the effect upon the intensity of the last need attaining satisfaction, or upon the intensity of the first want given up — unsatisfied — because of the tax. If equality of sacrifice is the aim, what possible difference can it make whether the equality is established between the last want attaining satisfaction, or the want unsatisfied because of the tax — the first want that would be satisfied if the tax were removed? If there is an " equality" in the first case, there is, of necessity, equality in the second case. The distinction is without a real difference. That Meyer has given us a more definite conception of the nature of the sacrifice occasioned by the tax, and a more ' " Das Opfer nicht in der Intensitat der in Folge der Steuer unbefriedigt blciben- den Bediirfnisse, sondern in dem Masse erblicken in welchem die durchscbnitt- liche Intensitat der letzen zur Befriedigung gelangenden Bediirfnisie in Folge der Steuer erhSht wird." Meyer, op. cii., p. 332. 192 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [528 definite standard for measuring the subjective equality, than did Mill, must be admitted, though in result there is no real difference. The equality in the intensity of the last need attaining satisfaction is precisely the equality of Mill — that one person should feel the tax no more than every other per- son feels it. In neither case is the equality thought of as an absolute equality, but only that the " feeling " or the " in- tensity " is for each person, under the circumstances in which he is placed, exactly what it is for every person other under the circumstances in which he is placed. That is, it is a purely relative equality. Has Meyer, then, added anything to the solution of the problem of justice in taxation by his reduction of " equality " to a comparison of " marginal wants," or rather of the in- tensities of m.arginal wants ? True, as a purely theoretical conception, it would be difficult to find a more exact, or more precise, conception of the idea of " equality of sacri- fice " than is to be found in the conception of a relative equality of intensities — i. e., of sacrifices — of marginal wants (of either margin) as occasioned by the tax. And true, also, that the conception of " ability " finds, perhaps, its most perfect subjective expression in the idea of a relation between the intensity of collective wants and the intensity of marginal per.f'Onal wants ; while relative ability finds its most perfect subjective expression in the idea that tax contributions should produce the same relative effects upon the satisfac- tion of the marginal, personal wants of every taxpayer. We cannot, therefore, agree with Leroy-Beaulieu that the sacri- fice theory is a piece of pure sentimentality.' On the other hand, it must be admitted that this subjective comparison of marginal wants is of little or no practical im- portance, -since in either case, as we have seen, they can be interpreted only by reference to objective facts — to economic ^ " Cette theorie est simplement sentimentale." Op. cit., i, p. 140. 529] THE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 193 conditions and personal circumstances. But if, however, we retain the idea of sacrifice along with that of ability, it can be of little consequence whether we consider " equality of sacrifice" as explaining " ability," or ability as explaining equality of sacrifice; although, as we have pointed out, the conception of " ability" best expresses the ideal of justice. Yet in either case or whether, with Professor Ely and others, we regard " equahty of sacrifice" and "ability to pay" as but different expressions of the same fundamental idea,' we are involved in a vicious circle. The solution of this circle, according to Sax, is to be found in his great discovery — the Theory of Equivalence. 4. Sax. — From the fact that Sax disclaims ethics in finance, and believes that the whole problem of taxation is a purely economic problem, it might seem, at first thought, that a discussion of his theory is out of place in a discussion of the ethical basis of taxation. But in spite of any dis- claimer, the fact is that Sax, equally with every other writer on the theory of taxation, has in mind as an ultimate end an ethical basis and ethical principles ; only with Sax, as we have previously seen, the fulfillment of the ethical end is to be attained by the free play of economic forces. It is proper, therefore, to examine his theory of justice and to inquire whether he has made any real contribution, in the solution of the problem, to the thought of his predecessors.' We have already sufficiently discussed the general features of the theory of Sax, and have found that his theory, like that of Meyer, is founded upon the intensity of marginal wants as resulting from the tax. It is, however, to the merit of Sax that he emphasizes rather the " satisfactions " than the " sacrifices," ^ thus calling attention to the positive, > Cf. Ely, Taxation in American Cities, pp. 80 and 237. ' Sax, " Die Progressivsteuer," in Zeitsckrift fiir Volkswirthschaft, Socialpolitik und Verwaltung, Erster Band, I Heft, p. 87. 194 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [530 instead of the negative, relations of the individual to the state. In the scale of wants, too, Sax brings out more clearly the inclusion of collective wants, the taxpayer, theo- retically at least, making his comparisons between his mar- ginal collective and marginal private wants ; whereas with Meyer the comparison is virtually between the marginal private wants before and after the tax ; or, when relatively considered, it is between the marginal want (as affected by the tax) of different taxpayers — a comparison impossible to make except through objective standards. In reality, however, with Sax, no less than with Meyer, the comparison is be- tween the intensities of marginal private wants as they are afifected by the tax, and he gives to these wants, also, the same objective reference. What, then, according to Sax, is the standard of justice? In the first place, Sax makes no effort to refute the ability and sacrifice theories, further than to maintain that in them- selves they explain nothing; just as, to the utilitarian econ- omist, the law of " demand and supply" is an explanation of economic facts that does not explain — the ultimate, efficient cause being wanting, and there being no third term of com- parison, other than that of " general feelings." What Sax seeks to do, then, is not to overthrow " ability " or " sacri- fice " as a basis of taxation, but to supply the tertium com- paratio7iis that gives them meaning, makes them intelligible. This " tertium,'' as we saw, Sax finds in " sensation." For the determination of ability or sacrifice lies in a comparison of the intensities of marginal needs, before and after the im- position of a tax; and "all needs have, without distinction of ends to which they are referred, a tertium comparationis in sensation."' Hence, therefore, the problem of tax distribution — taxa- tion according to ability, equality of sacrifice — revolves ' Grundlegung, p. 194. 53 l] THE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 195 about sensation, and when " reduced to a nutshell," we find it to be, " that our tax payments should be equivalent," ' i. e., should effect equivalent sensations. And when this is accomplished distributive justice will be attained, because it will be the fulfilment of economic laws.^" Moreover, it is in the "equivalence" of sensations resulting from the imposi- tion of a tax that ability and equality of sacrifice for the first time find a complete, ultimate explanation. But in what respect does this "equivalence of sensations" differ from "equality of sacrifice" as understood by Meyer — the equal sacrifice of enjoyments as measured by the intensity of feeling (of sensation) of the marginal wants attaining satisfaction after the payment of the tax? The great discovery of the tertium coniparationis is not, therefore, the discovery of Sax. In short, with Sax, equally with Meyer, the standard of justice in taxation is equahty of sacrifice — the production of an equal (= equivalent) in- crease in the intensity of" feeling of the marginal want satis- fied, or of the marginal want unsatisfied, because of the tax. Thus, that " equivalence of sensations " — i, e., of sacrifice — is only "equality of sacrifice" in a new dress is clear; also, from the fuller statement of the law of "equivalence: " that " every individual shall value the goods taken from him just as highly as every other individual values those taken from him, their respective stations in life being taken into con-' sideration,"3 a formula given by Mill forty years previously as expressing the meaning of " equality of sacrifice." Yet Sax. himself, does not admit that his theory of sacri- fice is at all in agreement with that of Meyer. He points out that Meyer regards the wants within each group of wants as having the same intensity, and insists, no doubt more correctly, that they have varying intensities. Accord- ingly, he accuses Meyer of making equality of sacrifice mean ^ Die Progressivsieuer, p. 90. *Ibid., p. 89. ' Grundlegung, p. 514. 196 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [532 a loss of equal utilities ; whereas, says Sax, " equal sacrifice is not the dispensing with equal enjoyments, but with equal parts of respective enjoyments [within the dififerent groups]. That is, by equal sacrifice is not meant absolutely equal, but relatively equal sacrifices;" or, "that the enjoyments that each person loses by means of the tax shall stand in the same relation to the total enjoyment made possible by means of his income."' But the difference is purely verbal so far as it has reference to the character of equality. Abso- lute equality is, no doubt, just as " unthinkable " to Meyer as it is to Sax. Nevertheless, we may agree with Sax that " equivalence " is a better term than " equality," as being less ambiguous; and that "equivalence of sensation" ex- presses with greater definiteness than "equality of sacrifice" the ideal of distributive justice. It is the further boast of Sax that equivalence of sensation for the first time also explains the meaning of justice in taxation. But it is rather a definition than an explanation. Still, the claim is not wholly without its reason. Not only because ability and sacrifice, subjectively considered, are ultimately resolvable into sensation — ability having reference more to the sensation of satisfaction, and sacrifice to the sensation of non-satisfaction ; but also, from the viewpoint of Hedonistic ethics and utilitarian economics, between which sensation — the ultimate fact of consciousness — con- stitutes a uniting bond ; a tertmm comparationis, pleasurable sensation — i.e., satisfaction — being the ultimate end of both. Still more, because of this reference of the economic and ethical to sensation, and because of the competition resulting from the fact that every individual is actuated by the same motives, the same sensations, it is assumed that each indi- vidual determines for himself the reahzation of the ethical * Die Progressivsteuer, p. 55. 533] THE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 197 ideal — equivalent sensations = equality of sacrifice = taxa- tion according to ability. But all this is ideal. The individual does not impose taxes upon himself, but through his representatives, and these representatives can interpret the sensations of their constituents only through objective signs, through the ob- jective conditions that produce the sensations. It is these objective signs, which are not a whit dififerent with Sax from what they are with Wagner or Meyer, that constitute the objective, practical tertium comparationis between ability and sacrifice and explain their meaning, that gives the practical solution to the riddle of the circle. However indefinite this solution may be, it is the only practical one. While, then, Sax may have added to the definiteness of the theory of subjective sacrifice, he has added nothing to the practical solution of the problem of justice. 5. The Dutch Economists ^ — Accepting " equality of sac- rifice " as the ideal of justice in taxation, the mathemati- cal economists of Holland have gone farther than any other economists in their attempt to give to the idea — equality of sacrifice — precision of meaning. They apparently start from the position of Meyer, that within every group of needs there is the same intensity throughout, together with the fact that the order of the satisfaction of needs varies in- versely with the means of their satisfaction — with income.' That is, only those with the larger incomes can satisfy the least intensive group of needs ; so that that group of needs affected by the tax is necessarily the most intensive of un- satisfied needs, or the least intensive of satisfied needs. Assuming, then, decreasing groups, or grades, of needs ' Pierson, Cohen-Steuart and Mees. I regret that my knowledge of this school of economists is only second hand, my acquaintance with them being limited to the exposition of Sax in Die Progressivsieuer, already referred to, and to Pro- fessor Seligman's account in his Progressive Taxation, pp. 137-144. igg JUSTICE IN TAXATION [534 with each decreasing grade satisfied by correspondingly increasing incomes, we have the fact that the marginal utility of incomes decreases as the incomes increase, since less intensive needs are satisfied by them. Again, with in- comes equally increasing the difference between the intensi- ties of the unsatisfied needs (or the last satisfied), on account of the tax, grows constantly less as the incomes increase ; or the difference between the intensities of unsatis- fied needs is less with the larger incomes than it is with the smaller incomes. Hence, every increment of tax, corre- sponding to an increment of income, has a less marginal utility than the next preceding increment. With these facts before us the problem of determining equality of sacrifice is apparently very simple. For all that is now necessary, is to assume a fixed gradation in the de- crease of the marginal utility of every increment of income, and a corresponding decrease in the marginal utility of every increment of tax. Then the sum of the marginal utilities of the different increments of income and of the tax will represent respectively the total utility of income and of the tax. If, now, we divide the total utility of the tax by the total utility of the corresponding income we shall ascer- tain the per cent, that the total tax is of the total income upon which it is assessed. In the same way percentages may be found for every grade of income. In every case this percentage will be the percentage that any given tax bears to the total utility of its corresponding income. The series of percentages thus obtained would measure the sacri- fice that a proportional tax would occasion for every grade of income. Now it must be very clear, as indeed Cohen-Steuart him- self points out,' that the gradation in the series of percent- ages must depend entirely upon the numbers assumed to ^ See Sax, Die Pro^essivsteuer, p. 76. 535] T^HE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 199 represent the marginal utilities of the increments of income and of the tax. Only, however, when the tax is exactly the same per cent, of the total utilities of the different grades of income can equality of sacrifice be attained. To produce this equality, therefore, all that is necessary is, to find such a tax rate as will yield a tax whose total utility divided by the total utility of the income paying the tax will be the same quota for every income. In brief, the tax should be such that the total utility of the tax of every individual will be the same per cent, of the total utility of his income as the total utility of the tax of every other individual is of the total utility of his income. Or, " Tax quota and income re- duced to units of utility must show the same relation to every tax-bearer, since herein consists the equality of sacrifice." ' The problem of effecting an equality of sacrifice is, then, the problem of finding such a tax rate for every income that the tax will take the same quota of the total utility of every income. Clearly everything depends upon the series of numbers taken to represent the marginal utilities of the in- crements of tax and of income. But whatever series we may choose, any other series, as Cohen-Steuart admits, would be equally legitimate. Hence, accordingly, it is pos- sible, by a clever manipulation of an arbitrary series of numbers representing utilities, to prove that almost any system of tax rates is necessary to produce an equality of sacrifice — as constant, increasing or decreasing rates. But this fact does not shake the faith of Cohen-Steuart in the possibility of a mathematical determination of equality of sacrifice. He therefore thinks to avoid the dilemma by assuming two, instead of one, series of decreasing marginal utilities with increasing incomes ; also that the truth lies somewhere between these two series, which are supposed to ^ Sax, Die Progressivsteuer, p. 57. 200 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [536 represent the two extremes of possible decreasing utilities. In the series that decreases more slowly the rate of increase is assumed to be inversely proportional to the cube root of the fourth power of the amount of the income ; while in the other series — that having the more rapid decrease — the de- crease is assumed to be inversely proportional to the second power of the amount of the income. From these two rules is deduced the following formula for equalizing the sacrifice of total utilities in the imposition of a tax: " An arithmetical increase of the tax rate with a geometrical increase of income." ' Here, indeed, we have the problem reduced to mathemat- ical exactness. But unfortunately Cohen-Steuart proceeds upon assumptions equally arbitrary and equally imaginary with those of the other Belgian economists, whose theories he rejects. All aHke, as Sax says, attempt to prove a truth by groundless assumptions. But, in fact, assumption lies at the basis of every theory of sacrifice, and we may, therefore, conclude with Sax that the sacrifice theory in itself is insol- uble.'' As to his own theory. Sax, of course, believes that he has avoided all assumption, and it must be admitted that his theory contains no such wild assumptions as are found in the Belgian economists. Indeed, his whole theory is based upon one of the most ultimate facts of conscious life- sensation. It is in the development of his thesis that what appears to us unwarranted assumptions make their appear- ance, particularly with reference to the assumed power of the individual over the satisfaction of his collective wants. At any rate, after all the elaborate development of his sub- jective theory. Sax is compelled to conclude that "justice merely forbids that a tax be imposed upon any one that is in contradiction with his economic relations;" 3 in other words, with his " ability." The prevention of this " contra- ' Quoted by Sax, Hid., p. 81. * Hid., p. 83. * Hid., p. 63. 537] THE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 201 diction " must be left to the officials of the government — to their " sensations " quite as much as to the " sensation " of the taxpayer. This conclusion is that of every sacrifice theory. 6. Edgeworth. Another interpretation of the sacrifice theory is given by Professor Edgeworth in his able article on " The Pure Theory of Taxation." ' Sacrifice is accepted as containing the true principle of taxation ; but it is main- tained that neither " equal " nor " proportional " sacrifice — as held respectively by Sidgwick and Cohen-Steuart — cor- rectly expresses the fundamental idea which the principle involves. The true notion of equity in taxation finds its more correct expression in the term like sacrifice, which constitutes the common genus of which "equal" and " pro- portional" sacrifice are but species.^ But " like sacrifice," otherwise expressed, is an equi-niarginal sacrifice, which we take to mean an absolute equality of the marginal utilities sacrificed — the marginal disutilities occasioned — on account of the tax. That these marginal sacrifices, or disutilities, should be at a minimum is an imperative demand of utili- tarian ethics. Hence, an " equi-marginal sacrifice " finds its most perfect expression in a minimum sacrifice, to which principle the true basis of taxation is ultimately reduced. It is not claimed, however, that there is any real opposition between this view and that of "equal" or " proportional" sacrifice. On the contrary, it is intimated that both equal and proportional sacrifice are notions that show a confusion in the minds of their advocates for equi-marginal sacrifice, itself leading to minimum sacrifice.^ Like other utilitarian economists Professor Edgeworth assumes as the basis of his argument " the greatest happi- ' Economic Journal, vol. vii. This article did not come to my notice until this and the following chapters were written. ' Ibid., p. 557. *Ibid., pp. 564-5. 202 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [538 ness principle," though in a " sHghtly modified " form. That is, in its application to social phenomena, which are not ^determined by competitive action, the principle must be interpreted to mean : not the greatest sum of happiness for each of the two or more parties concerned, taken individ- ually; but "that arrangement which conduces to the great- est sum-total welfare of both parties, subject to the condition that neither should lose by the contract." In other words, in its application to pohtical problems the greatest happiness principle must be understood to mean the greatest sum- total of utility for the community — i. e., of collective utility — not the greatest sum for each individual ; though " in the long run of various cases, the maximum sum-total of utility corresponds to the maximum individual utility." For, " of all principles of distribution which would afford him now a greater, now a smaller proportional sum-total utility obtain- able on each occasion, the principle that the collective utility should be on each occasion a maximum is most likely to afford the greatest utility in the long run to him individ- ually." ' Applied to taxation the principle means that taxes should be so distributed that the maximum total net utility will be realized, or the minimum of total disutility For " the con- dition that the total net utility procured by taxation should be a maximum reduces to the condition that the total dis- utility should be a minimum." Hence " it follows in general that the marginal disutility incurred by each taxpayer should be the same." But to produce such an equality would be to level all fortunes, which would produce the result: that " the richer should be taxed for the benefit of the poorer up to the point at which complete equality of fortune is attained." This is, indeed, the acme of socialism, " but it is immediately clouded over by doubts and reservations." * ^Economic Journal, vol. vii, p. 552. * Ibid., p. 553. 539] THE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 203 These " doubts and reservations " that stand in opposi- tion and modify the logical execution of the minimum prin- ciple, are such as have been noted by Mill, Sidgwick and others : That there would result a lessening of the amount to be distributed, since such a system would inculcate a ten- dency to leisure rather than to industry; that it would result in an increase of population, which would ultimately reduce the amount of wages, both by the increased competition of numbers and by a decrease of efficiency. But further (ex- cept upon the false assumption of an equality of natures), there are different capacities for happiness, which, on the principle of minimum disutility, involves an unequal distrib- ution of the tax. Still further, a progressive rate, which the unmodified principle implies, would produce a check to sav- ing, and so " would check the augmentation of the com- munity's wealth," though this loss is " to be set off against a probable increase of saving among the poorer classes," So likewise the principle of minimum sacrifice justifies dififer- ential rates on account of the size and permanence of incomes, the number of children, age, etc. But with such reservations as the above in the practical application of the principle, it still remains true that minimum sacrifice, the direct emana- tion of pure utilitarianism, "is the sovereign principle of taxation." ' And yet this principle affords us no definite data for the determination of rates. The rate must depend upon the relation existing between the decrease of utility and the increase of income. According to Cohen-Steuart the rate of the decrease of the utility is proportional to the increase of the income. Professor Edgeworth, on the other hand, main- tains that the decrease of the former is at a more rapid rate than the increase of the latter.^' But the exact ratio is theo- retically indeterminate. And hence from the view-point of ' Economic Journal, vol. vii, p, 556, * Ibid., p. 560. 204 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [540 pure theory it cannot be determined what rate of taxation would effect a minimum sacrifice. About all that can be said is that the tax rate should be progressive within the limits of the above reservations. Such, in brief, are the main points in Professor Edge- worth's interpretation of the " sacrifice theory" as a basis of taxation. And in this restatement important modifications of the theory are made. It is to us, indeed, of no little significance that we have the weight of Professor Edgeworth's authority — himself a utilitarian economist — in support of the contention of the preceding pages : that the principles of private economic activity are not, as supposed by Sax and others, applicable to the economic activity of political or col- lective life.' As Professor Edgeworth points out, the true analogy is not that of economic bargains governed by com- petition, but that of economic agreements between associa- tions of employers and employees ; " where the action of self-interest being suspended by mutual opposition, the more delicate force of amity, which even in economic man is not entirely wanting, may become felt." ^ Yet even in its modified form we are not convinced that the sacrifice theory affords a better statement of the basis of taxation than does the ability theory ; nor do we see any reasons for changing our previous criticism of the former theory. In fact. Prof. Edgeworth does not claim to do more than to bring out a little more definitely what was already impHed in Mill, Sidgwick, Meyer and others. At any rate, as we have understood these authors, the marginal sacrifice occasioned by the tax has meant an " equi-marginal " sacri- fice; one in which the tax imposes exactly the same sacri- fice upon every taxpayer, though not of absolutely equal amounts, viewed objectively. Yet " equi-marginal " has the merit of giving us a more definite expression of the idea in- 1 Economic Journal, vol. vii, p. 551. * Ibid., p. 552. 54l] THE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 205 volved. But whether viewed as " equal," " proportiQiial," or " equi-marginal," the conception of sacrifice affords but a most intangible basis for taxation — a basis, as Professor Edgeworth admits, that is hedged by " doubts and reserva- tions." Again, it may be admitted from a certain point of view that the procurement of the greatest amount of happiness — or the greatest sum-total of utility, or the minimum of dis- utility — is the true aim of all collective action ; but it is by no means self-evident that this "sum-total" or "minimum" pertains to the collectivity irrespective of the distribution of the "utility" or "disutility" among the individuals that constitute the collective whole. Such a principle is not wholly dissimilar from that which determines monopoly prices, the sum-total of a few utilities of large amounts off- setting a large number of utilities of individually small amounts. True, it is admitted that " in the long run " there is probably the greatest amount of individual happiness when there is the greatest sum-total of happiness ; and so in the long run it is of no practical moment which point of view is considered to be the correct one. Nevertheless, from the point of view of " pure theory" it is by no means clear that the largest sum-total of utility is the true aim of political action. Not only does such a view savor of a col- lective entity, but it assumes as a basis of action a principle that is quantitatively as indeterminable as anything that is to be found in the sacrifice theory of Mill, Sax, or Meyer. A sum-total of utilities has no meaning apart from individual utilities ; and to us a principle that looks merely to the sum of happiness and not to its extent, that permits the large total of the utilities of a few to be set ofif against the large total of the disutilities of many, is not the ideal of social justice. It is not sufficient that the largest sum-total may be consonant with the largest extent of individual happiness* 2o6 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [542 It may noi be so. For neither logically nor practically is what, is true of the whole necessarily true of the units. The ideal, then, would seem to be the minimum of sacrifice to the greatest number, which in the long run may produce the minimum of total sacrifice. No other supposition is con- sistent with the ideals of democratic institutions, or in har- mony with the conditions of social content. That the principle of equi-marginal, or minimum, sacri- fice does not, as we have seen, afford any definite rule for taxation is not perhaps of any importance in itself. But it seems a littie strange that one who is par excellence a mathematical economist should find satisfaction in a theory based upon a principle that does not permit of an exact mathematical expression, since " the reasoning from the principle of minimum sacrifice assumes no exact relation between utility and means." ' Nor is it without significance that he is compelled practically to abandon the subjective principle and to find the determinants of rules of taxation in objective standards — in the economic effects of the tax upon individuals and in the economic conditions of the taxpayers. But in this respect the position of Edgeworth is similar to that of Mill, Meyer and Sax. And finally, it is not without interest that in recognizing that there is no exact ratio between utility and means, Edgeworth has given the weight of his authority against the futile attempts of the Dutch economists to reduce taxation to an exact science. IV. Conclusion : Ability versus Sacrifice The preceding discussion on the basis of taxation has throughout implied the fact that the tax obligation rests upon persons, not upon property; that, therefore, the basis of taxation has specific reference to some fundamental princi- ple that attaches to the person, not to his property. Hence, * Economic yournal, vol. vii, p. 567. 543] T'HE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 207 therefore, the basis of the tax involves two fundamental ideas : the idea, or principle, that expresses the character of the tax obligation of the individual ; and, secondly, the prin- ciple of the universal apphcation of the basis, or the relative obligation of taxpayers. It is the first idea that has been the chief subject of our attention in the present chapter; the second will be the subject of the following chapter. The first of these principles — the basis of the idea that expresses the character of the tax obligation — we have found to be comprehended and expressed in two different ways — from the view-point of the ideas contained in the term " ability," and from the view-point of the ideas con- tained in the term " sacrifice." That there is significance in both of these conceptions of the tax basis is not to be denied ; but at the same time we have seen reasons for hold- ing that the idea connoted in the term " ability " more fully expresses the ethical basis for the imposition of taxes^ since it is the relation that most fully comprehends, not only the true relation of the individual to the state, but also the ethical relations of the individuals in the state ; is most ex- pressive, that is, of the fact that the obligation rests upon persons. Ability, as we saw, is expressive of the idea of positive, active participation in the expenses of the state^ corresponding to the positive, active participation in the ends of the state. It is expressive, too, of the voluntary character, or aspect, of tax contributions ; of the idea of duty, not of compulsion. On the other hand, we have seen that sacrifice is a nega- tive concept ; that it expresses a denial, a sacrifice of per- sonal satisfactions, though, it is true, for higher satisfactions that are common with self and others. It also contains more the idea of compulsion — the compulsory aspect of taxation. Undoubtedly there is truth in this view of the tax, for every tax necessarily involves a sacrifice — a conv- 2o8 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [544 pulsory sacrifice — of personal satisfactions for the sake of the realization of collective satisfactions. And it is true, too, that this idea of sacrifice is of a distinctly ethical char- acter; of a character, too, that is complementary of the ethical idea contained in " ability," But while all of this is true, the idea of sacrifice does not so clearly and fully represent the nature of the ethical basis — itself based upon the nature of the state — as does the idea of ability ; for while it is true that from the view-point of individual wants a sacrifice is involved, from the larger view- point of the complete whole of the individual there is no sacrifice in taxation, but only effort towards the fulfilment of the conditions of the more perfect realization of self. But, again, equality of sacrifice is a refinement of justice that it is inconceivable the state should ever realize ; for equality of sacrifice — relatively equal loss of enjoyments, = equivalent painful sensations — are conditioned not only by property conditions, but by individual character, habits, sensibilities, ideals, etc. Equivalence of sacrifice — of feel- ings, of sensations — is an ideal conceivable only from the view-point of individuals as a whole, in their ethical relations to each other. For ourselves, we cannot conceive it as an ideal which it is any part of the duty of the state to fulfil.^ The ends of justice are satisfied when the objective econ- omic conditions, or the objective effects, are made relatively the same by the tax. Or, again, when the tax is adjusted to the ability to support the state relatively to the ability to meet the demands of the wants of the self. Accepting, then, ability as the best expression of the ethical basis of taxation, though at the same time recogniz- ing the truth contained in the idea of equality of sacrifice, we have next to inquire what principles flow from this basis. ' " In framing an ideal," says Aristotle, " we may assume what we wish, but we should avoid impossibilities." Politics, ii, pp. 6, 7. 545] THE ETHICAL BASIS OF TAXATION 209 That is, since the primary element in the determination of ability (as, indeed, also, of sacrifice) is property, or more strictly, income, we have to inquire into the nature of the qualifications and limitations of the taxation of income that are demanded, in order to meet the requirements of taxation according to ability; or, again, what principles should con- trol the taxation of income so that the tax may meet the demands of justice. It is not simply or chiefly the ability of income to pay taxes relative to its ability to satisfy per- sonal wants, but it is a question of the relative ability of different incomes under different conditions and circum- stances ; hence, of the principles that should determine the taxation of income under these different conditions and cir- cumstances. Most important among the conditions deter- mining the ability of income, that is, the ability of its possessor, is the character, source, and size of income ; and, therefore, whether the income should be taxed at different rates according to these circumstances in order to meet the just requirements of taxation according to ability. Finally, whether under any circumstances consideration should be given to the needs of the individual as against the demands of the state. That is, whether there are circumstances in which exemptions may be allowed without infringing upon the principles of ability and universality. CHAPTER VII ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION By the ethical principles of taxation I have in mind those principles that are deducible from the ethical basis of taxa- tion ; the principles in accordance with which the tax burden must be distributed to meet the highest requirements of justice. It is the problem of determining the principles that will give realization to the ideal of taxation based upon ability. These principles should not be based upon mere sentiments, or upon mere abstractions. To have consistency and value they must be developments, not only of the impli- cations contained in the idea of " ability to pay," but must be developments, also, of the theory of the state, on which is based the whole theory of justice in taxation. Or these principles, again, should be developments of the meaning of " ability," whether they take the form of positive principles, or of exceptions to general rules. Exceptions to general rules there may be, but not exceptions to the fundamental idea — taxation according to ability. The exceptions, as well as the rules, or principles, must be logically contained in this idea. This distinction is important, but is almost universally overlooked, thereby leading to inconsistent con- clusions, as we shall have occasion to see. The development of these principles, which involves the development of the principles of a just distribution of the tax burden, is one of the most difficult problems within the whole field of taxation, and one upon which there is, per- haps, the most diverse opinion. But notwithstanding these differences of opinion, there is common agreement among all 2IO [546 547] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 211 schools of economic thought that justice demands that the tax should be distributed equally and universally. These two principles — Equality and Universality — , which are recognized as logical deductions of both the ethical and the economic basis of taxation, are regarded even more as the two cardinal principles of justice in taxation — of taxation based upon ability to pay. For, since the ends for which the state exists are common to all, justice requires that every member of the state, indeed every person that participates in its ends, should contribute to its support to the extent of his ability, relatively, of course, to the ability of others. The same conclusion is reached if the obligation to pay taxes is considered from the viewpoint of the ethical relations of the membership in the state, of the character of the members as persons. For this ethical view of the question demands above all "equality" of taxation, but equality implies uni- versality. These conclusions are not new. But what we wish to call attention to here is that the principles of Equality and Uni- versality as ethical principles, being viewed from a different standpoint from what they are as political or economic prin- ciples, lead to different, and, indeed, to more definite con- clusions. Politically, for example, the meaning of " equality " is vague, while the principle of universality stands unqual- ified. Ethically we find that both principles are conditioned' by " ability," and that, therefore, they may need qualifica- tion and limitation. In other words, the ethical contents of these principles supplement and complete their political and economic contents. Indeed, we might say that they are political and economic principles only because of the ethical implications involved in the political and economic bases of taxation. At any rate, it is in the development of the con- tent of these principles that we develop the content of the ethical basis of taxation — taxation according to ability. 212 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [548 I. The Principle of Equality That equality in taxation means a relative equality few will deny.' It means that there should be the same relative economic conditions after as before the tax. Viewed with respect to ability to pay it means that there should be the same relative economic ability after as before the tax for the satisfaction of personal wants. Subjectively considered — as equality of sacrifice — it means that there should be the same relative intensity of feeling of wants unsatisfied because of the tax; or, if you will, of the wants last attaining satisfac- tion. Or, again, since income is the primary factor in the determination of (objective) ability, equality in taxation means that the tax should take such portions of income as will leave the same relative amounts for the satisfaction of private needs, their objective importance, or their subjective intensity being considered ; or it means that income should be so distributed between the satisfaction of collective and private needs — between public and private expenditure — that there shall be the same proportional satisfaction, the same proportional expenditure, for each when viewed with reference to their relative importance, or their relative intensities. The problem of realizing equality m taxation, therefore, is a problem of the just distribution of taxes, or of the just distribution of income between collective and private wants. The question, then, resolves itself into this, What propor- tions of different incomes must be taken so that the tax may be proportioned to ability, and thereby a relative equality be established? In other words, in distributing the tax so as to ' Von Hock, as we have seen, makes exception of the tax for the protection of the person, which he thinks should be absolutely equal. The tendency of com- munism, too, is to make the burden of the government absolutely equal. And even such an individualist as the late Thomas Davidson once questioned, in conversa- tion with the writer, whether all taxes should not be absolutely equal. 549] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 213 realize a relative equality according to ability, Should there be the same rate, the same proportional tax, for all incomes? Or, Does the " equality " necessitate different rates accord- ing to the size, character, and amount of income? For if these affect the ability they must likewise affect the rate. I . Rate and Source of Income. It is the belief of many writers on taxation that the ability to pay taxes is very largely affected by the source of income, and that, therefore,, there should be differential rates according as the income is "funded" or "unfunded," is derived from inheritance, from monopoly, from " quasi-rents," or from speculation. In practice, however, but little consideration has been given to the source of income.' Let us examine briefly the grounds for such distinctions, that we may see to what extent ability is affected by the source of income, and thereby differential rates are justified. (i) Funded and Unfunded Incomes. According to Mill, « funded income, or income from property, has a greater tax-| ing ability than unfunded, or personal income, because of its greater permanence.^ Wagner assigns two reasons — because funded income leaves the entire labor power wholly, or for the most part, free for other acquisitions ; and because per- sonal income has more necessary expenses to meet, such as provisions against sickness, old age, etc.3 With Meyer the only basis of distinction is, that " property is not only and not always a source of income, but it may be immediately applied for the satisfaction of needs " * in emergency cases. As to the argument of Mill, it contains only a partial truth. For, as far as life incomes are concerned, the economic necessities of the business world and the growing. 1 The Italian income tax is a partial exception. Cf. L. Say, op. cit., ii, p. 152. ^ Mill, Polit. Econ., v. 2, § 4. ' Op. cit.y ii, p. 56. Cf. also Neumann, Die Progressivsteuer, p. 178. * Op. cit., p. 326. 214 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [550 Civil Service provisions of governments tend to a per- manency of salaried positions that makes unfunded incomes not a whit less permanent than funded incomes. In fact, many personal incomes are more permanent than property incomes ; and besides, there are degrees of permanence in both.' So far, then, as the difiference is due to a difference in the permanence of income it is a question pertaining to the character, not to the source, of income. The second argument of Wagner is but a fuller statement of the argument of Mill, for it is the assumed temporary character of personal income that necessitates a larger out- lay to provide against future needs.^ So far as this argu- ment relates to perpetual family income it contains, indeed, much force of reason ; for of two equal incomes there is un- doubtedly greater tax ability in the perpetual, than in a life, and still more than in a temporary, income. But this, again, is a question of the character, not of the source of income. As to the first argument of Wagner, the primary conten- tion is true, but the conclusion unwarranted. If, for example, A and B have each a personal income of $1000, and A has in addition a funded income of $1000, it is no reason in itself why A should pay a higher rate on his funded income. He simply has twice the income that B has, and if his ability is more than proportionately increased thereby, it is due to the size of his income relatively to his needs, as compared with the size of the income of B relatively to his needs. In determining A's ability it is of no impor- tance that he is free to earn a personal income in addition to his property income, unless, indeed, we accept Walker's theory of potential ability. So far as this particular argu- ^ Cf. Meyer, ibid., p. 327. * To Sax this is theonly ground for a differential tax on funded incomes. Cf. Grundie^unft'p. $14. 5 5 I ] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAX A TION 2 I 5 ment is concerned — i. e., leaving aside other characteristics of funded incomes — the question is simply one of the size of A's income as compared with B's, and consequently of his relative ability. This question will be considered presently. The position of Meyer is equally untenable, and, besides, if it is not inconsistent with the declaration of the preceding page, that as there is practically no difference in the per- manency of funded and unfunded incomes there is in this respect no difference in ability, it represents, at least, a con- fusion of ideas. For the real comparison is between differ- ent sources of income, whereas with Meyer it is virtually between income and property. Or, more strictly, his com- parison is between those who have property but no income, and those who have neither property nor income. Be this as it may, it is quite true that as between the possessor of a funded and the possessor of an unfunded income, the former can continue satisfying his needs, presumably also his collec- tive needs, after income ceases, while the latter can not. But this advantage is in the possession of property, not in a par- ticular kind of income ; since the incomes being assumed to have equal permanence represent, as incomes, equal ability. But if the mere possession of property gives greater ability to pay taxes, it must exist whether or not the property is yielding an income, and must exist so long as there is private prop- erty ; and at the same time differ in degree among different - property holders according to the amount of property pos- sessed. But this "ability" could be reached only by a real tax on property, and by such dififerential rates that it is difificult to see where they would stop short of confiscating all private property, or equalizing its possession — as com- pared, of course, with the non-income receiver. Upon the whole, then, we must agree with Sax, that the only reason that a funded income gives a greater ability than an unfunded income is, because it does not necessitate the 2i6 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [552 same saving to provide against future needs.' The posses- sion of property may, indeed, have this same advantage, but only in a very Hmited way, since in most cases it would soon be exhausted. It is not a taxable advantage. Property itself gives a tax ability not because it may be used to satisfy future wants, but because it has the power of yielding a future income to satisfy future wants. This advantage, how- ever, is limited in scope, and has special application only to perpetual incomes, for reasons previously given. (2) Inheritance and Gifts. That inheritance of property (including bequests) and gifts tend to increase the tax ability of the recipient no one can safely deny. At the same .time it must be admitted also, that there are many cases where an inheritance, or a bequest, carries with it a de- crease of ability, if we consider the family as the taxable unit ; for with the inheritance or bequest there is a loss of the salary of the head of the family.'^ But so far as there is a real addition to the tax ability of the recipient it is not to be measured by the amount of the inheritance as in itself an additional income, for I cannot regard an inheritance as a true income. It may be a source of new income to the inheritor, but it is not itself income. The ability, therefore, is increased only to the extent of the income-producing power of the property inherited. This ability is not con- fined to the year of the inheritance, but lasts as long as the income from it lasts. In fine, the increased ability resulting from an inheritance is confined solely to the effects of the inheritance upon the income of the inheritor, either with respect to its annual increase in size or to its funded, or perpetual, character. The same holds true of gifts, particularly of productive property. In the case of money gifts for defraying living ^ Cf. also Cohn, op. cit., p. 359. " Cf. West, The Inheritance Tax, p. 1 18. 553] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 217 expenses, whether occasional or continuous, the gift is justly a part of the annual income. This is true, also, of inheritances or bequests in the form of annuities, or life incomes. If B receives from A $100,000, his ability is increased just to the extent that A's decreases — to the extent of the income-pro- ducing power of the $100,000, no more, no less. , The ability that centered in the personality of A now centers in the personality of B. That the increased ability comes gratuitiously is not a matter that can have any weight, so long as the present property relations are sanctioned by the law of the land.' All that justice requires is that the government should ascer- tain the existing tax ability of every taxpayer. To tax the inheritance or gift, other than as specified, is to put a tax upon capital, though not, it is true, upon the national capi- tal.' The tax should be on the income, not on the property, if it is to be a tax on ability. That an inheritance tax may be justified for other reasons, as compensatory for evaded taxes, payment for special services, etc.,3 we would not deny, but we cannot agree with Meyer that a tax on inheritance is justified on the ground of greater tax ability ,♦ for this ability is amply reached, to the ends of justice, by taxing the income from the inheritance, the income being the only ground of the increased ability. (3) Monopoly and Quasi-rent Income. At first thought it might appear that a differential tax rate would be justified on monopoly incomes on the ground that such incomes have a special tax ability, relatively to other incomes, since they result from special advantages in income-earning power. * Cf. Wagner, per contra, ii, p. 588. ' As clearly demonstrated by Mill. Cj. Polit, Econ., v, 2, 7. ' For a good summary of arguments for special tax on gifts and inheritances see Max West, op, cit., ch. v. * Meyer, op. eit., p. 359. 2l8 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [554 On account of these advantages, whatever their source, the tendency is to give the holder of the monopoly an additional income above the average of non-monopoly incomes, and so to increase his ability to the extent of the monopoly incre- ment of his income. All this may be true. But this does not give A, with a monopoly income, a greater ability than B has with an equal but non-monopoly income, their condi- tions being otherwise the same. Both A and B, with respect to C with his smaller income, have the same relative advan- tage, the same relative increase of ability. It is simply a question of the size of the income. On the mere ground of abiHty, therefore, the tax rate on A's income should be the same as that on B's income. The fact that it is a monopoly income does not in itself give it greater tax paying ability. However, a special tax on monopoly incomes may be justified on other grounds. All monopolies, whether natural or capitalistic,' are at bottom legal or social creations, and society has, therefore, a peculiar claim upon the increased ability resulting from the monopoly increment of income. Particularly is this the case where the monopoly utilizes public property, such as streets, or is in any sense a legal creation (which includes capitalistic monopolies)." It is only justice that incomes due to special privileges of govern- ment should compensate the government for them. That society should absorb the full monopoly increment of income cannot be granted, for it receives back indirectly many advantages from the monopoly, as, for example, from the private ownership of land, or, in the case of capitalistic monopolies, from the concentration of productive wealth * Such we understand to be those huge corporations where the concentration of enormous wealth under one management makes possible a control over prices. Examples: The Standard Oil Company, the United States Steel Corporation, though both are partly, also, natural monopolies. * Which, by their incorporation, become, in a sense, legal monopolies. 5551 ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 219 under the management of the most efficient and competent entrepreneurs. The case is very similar where the income is due to social conditions more than to personal effort, as is the case with " unearned increments." Of this class " ground rent" is the best example. Here the " unearned increment " — rent — is peculiarly a social product, and society has, therefore, a peculiar claim upon it. We are not prepared, however, to concede that society should claim the whole of the unearned income — the " ground rent;" both because society indirectly receives many advantages from this private " monopoly," and because it would tend, in many cases, to discourage the most efficient use of the land. But, in any case, society cannot justly absorb the " unearned increment" of the past, or its capitalized value ; for in most cases the rent, to the present holders, is not an "unearned increment," but inter- est on capital invested. Still, it must be admitted that society has a special claim to this class of income, not only because largely a social product, but because society, as Henry George rightly claims,' has a just claim upon the soil. But a differential tax is not justified on the ground of a peculiar ability, other than that which comes from the size of the income. Much the same conclusions follow with respect to " quasi- rent " — to ^«^^/-monopoly income. To the extent that income is increased by means of these " rents " there is an increase in tax ability, but the ability to pay taxes is not increased by the mere fact that any part of the income has its source in a " guast-rent." But on the other hand, there is not the same ground for a differential rate, or a special tax, upon the income of " qi^asi-rents" as there is upon pure monopoly income, both because it results more from per- * C/. Progress and Poverty, B. vii, ch. i. 220 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [556 sonal efficiency than from social causes,' and because such a tax would have a more immediate and more direct effect upon production and consumption. As Professor Ross holds, a tax on the "consumer's rent" would tend to lessen consumption and thereby work injuriously. But the con- tention of Professor Ross that the "producer's rent" is a specially good subject for taxation, since such a tax would curtail production least,' can be accepted only with qualifica- tion. It may be true with respect (to monopoly rent, but a special tax upon the "producer's rent," as "profits "3 of the entrepreneur, would be in effect a penalty upon individual capacity and efficiency in production, and would tend to cur- tail production. (4) Income from Speculation. We need not stop to dwell on the income from speculation. It does not differ from other income in its abihty-giving power. It involves large risks and may result in large returns, and it is the size of these returns that determines the tax ability, so far as this is effected by income. But there are different kinds of specu- lation, and the question whether there should be a differen- tial tax upon speculative profits must be decided in each case according to circumstances. In some cases, as in illegitimate speculation, a special tax may be demanded for police purposes, but in no case does speculative income carry with it any special tax ability. On the contrary, such income tends to give less ability on account of the possibility of its loss in the immediate future. Upon the whole, then, we find no reason for holding that the ability of any person to pay taxes is affected by the source of his income. The mistake of those who hold to the contrary is due, we think, to their attaching ability to the * The "quasi-rent " of capital would be a partial exception. •Ross, "A New Canon of Taxation," in Polit. Set. Quart., vol. vii. • See Walker, Political Economy, bk. iv, ch. 4. 557] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 221 object of the tax — the income — rather than to its subject — the person. As Vocke says, " The tax on the basis of real abiHty knows no object, but only a subject and a measure. The subject is constantly changing, let the source of the income be where it will."' In other words, income deter- mines ability only so far as it relates to the satisfaction of wants — future as well as present. This satisfaction is not influenced by the source of income, but only by its character and size, or by source only as character and size of income are reflected in the source. 2. Rate and Character of Income. By the character of income is understood, whether it is permanent and secure, or temporary and precarious. Do, now, these character- istics of income produce differences in tax paying ability that justify differential rates? Not, it may be answered, the characteristics per se. From the viewpoint of income alone it is of no consequence to ability whether the income be permanent or temporary. If permanent it pays taxes permanently, if temporary it pays taxes temporarily.' These characteristics assume importance only because of their in- fluence upon the satisfaction of future wants. Mill, for example, held that permanent incomes should be taxed more highly than temporary incomes, and temporary more highly than precarious, for the reason that temporary, and still more precarious, incomes have to make larger outlays to provide against future wants — sickness, old age, etc.' This is a very commonly accepted doctrine, and is, as we have seen, the only ground for the assumption that funded incomes give a greater ability than unfunded incomes.* This position we believe to be theoretically sound, for since the taxpayer is a person it is necessary and just that his future needs be taken into consideration in relation to » op. cU., p. 465. » Cf. Vocke, ibid. ' Mill, Political Economy, v. 2, § 4. * See also Vocke, p. 466. 222 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [558 the probabilities of this future means for their satisfaction. Practically, however, allowance for future demands on present incomes leads to grave difificulties. To begin with, the theory assumes that every person who receives a tem- porary or precarious income saves a part of his income and invests it in insurance, or otherwise, to provide for future wants. Or, if actual saving does not take take place, it is presumed that it ought to take place. But admitting that a part of the income is saved to provide for future wants, it follows that there is proportionately less income to satisfy present wants, and therefore less tax ability. This is too self-evident to need illustration. If, then, such ' savings ' are justified it follows, on the ground of tax ability alone, that they should be exempted from taxation ; or, what amounts to the same thing, that temporary incomes, from which savings are made for the future, should be favored by differ- ential rates. But it is believed, that not only is such saving justified from the viewpoint of the individual, but that it is sound political policy to encourage it, lest the receivers of temporary incomes (still more of precarious incomes) may become future public charges. But upon what basis of savings should such differential rates be established? To base them upon actual savings would admittedly be a most difificult problem in practice. Accordingly, Mill thinks that " the next best thing in point of justice" is "to take into account in assessing the tax, what the different classes ought to save." ' This we believe to be a very questionable solution of the difficulty. It opens up at once most perplexing problems. Unless what is exempted is actually saved there results the injustice of what is virtually regressive taxation, equal incomes being taxed at different rates. But above all, it raises the query, How much "ought" one to save from a temporary and a * Political Economy, v, 2, § 4. 559] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 223 precarious income for future needs? It must, of course, bear some relation to the amount of the income and to the accepted standard of life. But whatever the amount pre- sumed to be saved, no government could consistently, or justly, exempt from taxation what " ought " to be saved unless the saving was enforced by compulsory insurance, or in some other manner. To exempt any portion of a tem- porary income, on the assumption that it is saved to provide for future needs, would be grossly unjust if the exempted income is squandered on present pleasures. No ! To accept what ought to be saved as the standard makes it obligatory upon the government to see that the actual corresponds to the ideal. Nevertheless, admitting the justice and right of " savings" from temporary incomes, we believe that the theory of eco- nomic ability requires that there should be difTerential rates in favor of those incomes from which savings are actually effected. But we cannbt agree with Mill, that the basis of such rates should be what one " ought to save." Not that we fear any bugbear of " paternal socialism," nor because we think the government would thereby overstep the limits of its functions (for these we have seen to be relative') ; but because consideration of the actual savings is not only all that is required by theoretical justice, but because, in spite of the practical difificulties, rates based upon actual savings, we believe, would approximate most nearly to the ideals of justice. Nor is it any argument against differential rates on temporary incomes that they pay taxes only temporarily, while permanent incomes pay taxes permanently."" The argument rests upon the old fallacy that a tax is upon the income, or property, not upon the person, and that mere income is the measure of ability — a fallacy that is at the ' See ante, pp. 26, 27 and 52. ' See, for example, Perry, op. cit., p. 519. 224 JUSTICE IN TAXATION L560 root of many false solutions of tax problems. Once com- prehend that only the individual, the person, can be the subject of a tax and the way is cleared to a more easy solu- tion of many tax problems. But dififerential rates, or exemptions, on account of the savings from temporary incomes for future needs, involves or implies an important consequence : That it is the right of the individual to provide for his future, and therefore, also, of necessity, his present, necessary needs before he is under obligation to contribute to the support of the state. Though a debatable question I believe the conclusion to be sound, but we may best discuss this phase of the question when we come to tax exemptions. 3. Rate and Amount of Income. Of far greater import- ance than the source or the character of income, in the de- termination of the ability of the taxpayer, is the amount of the individual income received. Normally income is both 'i the means by which we satisfy our economic wants and the source of our tax contributions. The ability to pay taxes is, therefore, conditioned by the ability to satisfy our personal .wants, but this latter ability in turn is necessarily conditioned ' by the amount of income at our disposal. Clearly, then, the i amount of taxes that one can pay is conditioned by the amount of his income, other conditions remaining equal. «This no one will deny. But we have found that justice re- quires that taxes should be based upon relative ability, that the burden should be equal; or that such portion of each income should be taken for taxes as will leave the same relative ability to satisfy wants after as before the tax. Hence the first principle of justice in the distribution of the tax is that taxes should be imposed in proportion to the ability to pay. But ability, we have said, is relative to the amount of income. The question before us, therefore, comes to this : In what ratio must incomes be taxed, with respect 56 1] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 225 to their size, in order that the tax may be proportional to ability — that a relative equality in taxation may be estab- lished? The answer to this question is by no means a simple one Indeed, to determine what portions of incomes of different sizes must be taken as a tax, in order to effect a true pro- portion according to ability, is perhaps the most difficult problem within the whole field of tax distribution. It is certainly a crucial problem, and its answer supplies the basic principle of just taxation — the just rate of taxation on in- come. This has no reference to an income tax. By income we mean the total income of the individual, whatever may be its source. There may without any injustice be different rates on different species of income, or property, either for administrative purposes or otherwise. The question, how- ever, is: What should be the average rate for the total income if taxation is to be according to ability? In other words, In what measure does ability vary with the size of the income? The idea of absolute equality in taxation being excluded, except in communistic or socialistic societies, we have left the possibilities that ability varies regressively, proportion- ally, progressively, or degressively with income. But re- gressive taxation — an increasing rate with a decreasing income — is not less absurd than the idea of absolute equality, and, in fact, is contended for by no one ; though particular forms of regressive taxes are found in all countries, and are not necessarily inconsistent with justice. Degressive taxa- tion — proportional on all income above a fixed limit, pro- gressive backwards from the same limit — is, in effect, a mild form of progression, being a decreasing progression on the total income until the rate becomes practically, though never theoretically, proportional. It rests, however, upon somewhat different grounds from the progressive tax and arises from exemptions, and may, therefore, better be con- sidered in connection with universality in taxation. 226 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [562 We have left, therefore, proportional and progressive tax- ation, and the problem is to determine which of these plans most fully realizes equality in taxation — taxation propor- tional to ability. It will not be necessary, for our purpose, to go into an extended discussion of every phase of pro- portional and progressive taxation, but we may say in general, that conclusions respecting either system de- pends upon our theory of the state, our conception of the ethical basis of taxation, and not less upon consistent and logical deductions.' In general, those who uphold the pro- tective theory of the state and the benefit theory of taxation advocate proportional taxation, while supporters of what has here been called the ethical theory of the state, and of the abil- ity theory of taxation, tend to the advocacy of progressive tax- ation.'' To the former class belong the English, the French and the earlier German economists; to the latter, the later German economists and those who have come under their influence, (i) Proportional Taxation. Proportional taxation is, I think, the logical tendency of the protective theory of the state and of the benefit theory of taxation, for these theories put a property value upon the protection and assume that the benefit of the protection is proportional to the property, or revenue, " enjoyed under the protection of the state." At the same time the conclusion is little more than tauto- logical. If, however, we assume as would seem to be quite as true, that the benefit of the protection has a proportion- ately greater value for the poor than for the rich, relatively to their incomes, regressive taxation would be the logical * For a careful review of the relation of tax rates to the basis of taxation, see Seligman, Progressive Taxation. ' Exceptions are, in the main, due to a confusion, or to an unconscious identi- fication of the ability and benefit theories, or to considering the tax from the view- point of income instead of the person. 563] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 227 consequence.' If, on the other hand, we regard the benefits of government as measured by the subjective sacrifice occasioned by the loss of satisfactions on account of the tax, progressive taxation would seem to be the logical result, since the intensity of the unsatisfied wants would decrease as incomes increase. If cost of service, instead of value of service were considered as the basis of the tax, I am inclined to believe that regressive taxation would be logically de- manded.^ But the fact is that the benefit theory affords no fixed basis for determining the rate of taxation. The ad- vantages of government are qualitative, and therefore, as Professor Seligman says, " quantitatively immeasurable." 3 But we have already discarded the benefit theory of taxa- tion, and have, therefore, to consider proportional rates only in their bearing upon the relative " ability " of taxpayers. The question, therefore, is, Is ability proportional to in- come? But few economists of note answer the question in the affirmative.4 With 'those who do, either the benefit theory is lurking in the background, or else ability and in- come (or property) are assumed to be equivalents 5 — income, not the person, being regarded as the subject of the tax. Marzano, for example, writes : "I firmly maintain that the proportional tax is consonant with justice, for the simple reason that the contributive faculty, of which income is the concrete and actual expression, does not increase otherwise, than in proportion" {i.e.,io income).^ This, indeed, is ' Cf. Roscher, op. cit., p. 191; Mill, Polit. Econ., v, 2, § 2; Parieu, TraiU des Impots, i, p. 87; Menier, op. cit., p. 215. » Cf. Madam Royer, op. cit., pp. 36-7. Per contra, Sismondi, op. cit., p. 155. ^Progressive Taxation, p. 85. * Cf. Seligman. ibid., pp. 150-3. 'See, for example, Parieu, Traite des Impots, vol. i, p. 134, for both defects. The same errors, 1 think, are also found in L6on Say and Leroy-Beaulieu. * Marzano, Compendia di Scienza delle Finanze,"^. 122. So, likewise Baer: " II criterio per giudicare della parita delle condizione, o di loro rapporto in piu o meno, non puo essere altro che quello dell' importan.'^a delle sostanze, dell' avere, di beni che si posseggono." Op. cit., p. 19. 228 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [564 really the only logical argument for a proportional tax, from the view-point of ability. But it is either a petitio principii, or it is tautological. Income and ability are made inter- changeable. No consideration is given to the personality of the taxpayer, to the relation between income and wants. This criticism is seemingly forestalled by Marzano in the further argument, that, since the demand of advancing civilization increases wants in the same proportion that in- come increases, the tax should be proportional.' By impli- cation the satisfaction of wants measures ability, but the wants are assumed to increase proportionately with income, and so, also, is ability. The argument is specious, but not sound. It is far truer, I believe, that with advancing civiH- zation wants increase at a more rapid rate than income or wealth increases. Wants increase directly with education and culture, with moral and spiritual growth, but while it is true that the development of these is very largely condi- tioned by the growth of wealth (and so of income), it is not true that their development is necessarily directly propor- tional to the growth of wealth. Rather do they develop progressively. Hence, wants thus viewed in their relation to income would seem to demand regressive rather than proportional taxation. But if by " wants" Marzano means " efficient wants" his argument is not less ineffective. It is true, in that case, that the power of satisfying our personal wants increases propor- tionately with income, but ability is not merely a question of the relation of income to the satisfaction of personal wants. Ability to pay taxes has reference to the relative ability to satisfy personal and collective wants, as compared with the like ability of others. Because, then, if there were no taxes our abihty to satisfy our increasing personal wants would be proportional to our increasing income, it does not ^ Cf. Marzano, pp. 124-5. 565I ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 229 follow that our ability to pay taxes maintains the same pro- portion. For, while wants increase with advancing civiliza- tion, and " efficient wants " with increasing income, collective wants — the demand for efficient government — increase in even greater proportion, become of their relatively greater importance. Hence, from this point of view the tendency would be towards a progressive, rather than a proportional tax. However, the question of ability is not a question of increasing wants with growth in civiHzation, and consequent increase of incomes, but whether, under existing conditions, ability increases proportionately with income. This can be maintained only by the first argument of Marzano, the inval- idity of which we have pointed out above. Besides, though our individual wants increase with the increase of our individual incomes, or our wealth, our collective wants increase in an even greater ratio. Or, apart from the question of the value of life, which may be assumed to be the same for all, our wants, deprived of satisfaction on account of the tax, become of relatively less importance as our wealth increases, as com- pared with the wants of government. Hence, from this view-point the relative ability of large and small incomes is evident. We shall, however, consider this phase of the question more fully in connection with progressive taxation. The weakness of the argument for proportional taxation, as a logical deduction of the theory of ability, is brought out very clearly in the fact that the most influential, and to their advocates the most decisive, arguments result from inconse- quential reasoning, or specters of the imagination. For the most part these arguments take the form of objections to a progressive tax; on the ground that it is, " inquisitorial," is " robbery," is " socialistic," is " inhuman," is "sentimental," is " arbitrary," etc., etc. With such an abandonment of reason argument is impossible. There is, however, one argument that perhaps deserves 230 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [566 more consideration. It is not the result of fright at a " specter," but is nevertheless a clear type of the incon- sequences of reasoning by a complete shifting of premises. I refer to the leave-them-as-you-find-them argument for pro- portional taxation — noli me tangere. This is one of the most common, and has been, perhaps, the most telling, argument for proportional taxation, but it has nothing whatever to do with the theory of ability. If the argument has any applica- tion at all it is, as Neumann says, in the give-and-take theory of taxation,' and only in the persistence of the benefit theory does it find any place in the theory of ability. The argu- ment, too, presumes that property, not income, is the source of the tax, and is closely allied with the economic doctrine of laissez-faire. Moreover, the primary premise is itself false. Noli me tangere is no more a function of government in taxation than it is to level all fortunes. A tax necessarily affects the distribution of wealth through its influence upon the savings from income, and the cessation of taxes (assum- ing that government would still exist) would favorably affect, upon the whole, the accumulations of the rich more than of the poor. A government, then, has done its duty when it distributes the tax according to the ability to bear it, although it incidentally and indirectly affects the distribution of wealth even though this end is not directly aimed at.^' Still, a government may not overlook the economic effects of a tax, for when these become ruinous it is evidence that the tax is not based upon ability to bear it, and is therefore unjust.3 But proportional taxes may affect the distribution of wealth in the same manner as progressive taxes, though by no means in the same degree. Passing over these irrelevant arguments for proportional taxation, the question whether a tax proportional to income * Neumann, Die Progressivsteuer, p. loi. » Cf. Neumann, ibid. ' See chapter iii. ^%,^^''^>' 567] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION " 231 is a tax proportional to ability may be considered from two points of view — objectively and subjectively. Objectively, it is a question of the relative importance of public and private needs satisfied by increasing incomes ; subjectively, it is a question of the relative sacrifice endured by the posses- sors of large and small incomes through the payment of the tax. In the former case, relative ability is determined by the relative importance, objectively considered, of the needs unsatisfied because of the tax ; in the latter case, relative ability is determined by the subjective intensity of the same marginal, unsatisfied wants. As the question leads at once to progressive taxation, it will be considered in that connec- tion. The disproof of proportional taxation based oa ability is the proof of progression. (2) Progressive Taxation. That the principle of taxation according to ability leads logically and inevitably to a pro- gressive rate is recognized by most economists who accept ability, or its assumed equivalent — equality of sacrifice — as the just basis of taxation. Some, however, like Mill and Vocke, accept the principle of progression only in its modi* fied form of degression — a proportional rate on the "clear" income.' Others, like Seligman, Pescatore and Walker, while accepting the principle of progression theoretically, as the only logical outcome of the ability basis of taxation, question whether it can be justly applied in practice on account of the practical difficulties in the way of its execu- tion.^ Upon what, then, does this consensus of opinion rest? In brief, upon the conviction that ability to pay taxes increases faster than income increases. But what is the ground of this conviction, if it is anything more than a mere sentiment, or an ^ Mill, Polit. Econ., v, 2, 3; Vocke, op. cit., pp. 472-9. * St\\gxad.x\, Progressive Taxaiion,^. 199; Pescatore, Za Logica delle Impost, pp. 23-5 ; Walker, Political ^Economy, p. 500. 232 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [568 ipse dixit ? It rests upon both objective and subjective con- siderations. Let us note the latter first. Subjectively, then, a tax is assumed to be proportioned to ability when it effects an equality — "equivalence" — of sacri- fice ; when the holder of a small income feels the sacrifice occasioned by his tax just as much, but no more, than the holder of a large income feels the sacrifice occasioned by his tax. But, so it is maintained, such an " equality of sacri- fice " is not obtained by the giving up of proportional parts of incomes of different sizes. For, in satisfying our wants the most intensive wants are always the first to be satisfied, and with increasing incomes wants will be satisfied of ever decreasing intensity ; so that the marginal utility of the want satisfied with the last increment of a large income has a less intensity than the marginal utility of the want satisfied with the last increment of a small income. Or, what amounts to the same thing, the wants sacrificed on account of the tax are always the least intensive wants, but the marginal wants sacri- ficed on account of the tax increase in intensity as incomes decrease in size — the obverse of the fact that with increasing incomes wants of decreasing intensity are satisfied. Hence, the taking of proportional parts of unequal incomes neces- sarily does not effect a proportional sacrifice. Therefore, a progressive rate is essential to realize a true proportion, the rate gradually increasing as incomes increase. As put by Meyer the argument is, that " the proportional tax (Der gleiche Steuerbetrag) occasions a so much larger sacrifice the smaller the income from which it is borne, because the smaller the income the more intensive are the needs which are deprived of the means of satisfaction, and the average intensity of the needs attaining satisfaction is put off to an ever greater distance." ' Hence to equalize * Meyer, op. cit., p. 331. Meyer advances another argument for progressive taxation that is closely allied with his argument for diSerential rates on funded 569] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 233 the intensities there must be a progressive rate. So, Hke- wise, it is held by Wagner: "That it is statistically probable that ability increases faster than income, because with in- creasing income there is an ever larger quota of free income left over, which is not held for the satisfaction of subsistence needs, therefore for needs satisfied with much greater diffi- culty," ' larger portions of small incomes and smaller portions of large incomes being used to provide for the necessities — food, clothing, shelter. Hence the necessity of a progressive rate. So, too, Neumann reaches the same conclusion from a slightly different point of view. In the first place ability is identified with sacrifice, since, like sacrifice, it increases either as one imposes labor upon himself or as he denies himself enjoyments and satisfactions — "the sacrifice of toil and of renunciation." ^^ Such sacrifices are imposed by taxes. Nevertheless, ability to pay taxes is not propor- tioned to income, as there are other sacrifices that must be taken into consideration — expenses for food, clothing, cul- ture, care and support of the family, etc., etc. These latter sacrifices increase progressively as incomes decrease. Hence, a progressive rate with increasing incomes is neces- sary in order that the tax may " occasion equal efforts and sacrifices over against other needs." ^ In spite of the weight of authority in its behalf and the dictum of Neumann, " that it is only through a consideration of the sacrifice imposed that the measure of ability first con- tains definite form and becomes useful for a tax system," * incomes. It is, that with larger incomes there is greater power of accumulation of property; that, therefore, they should be taxed more highly, the property adding to the ability as in the case of funded property. The argument contains the same fallacy as that for a differential rate on funded incomes. {Anie, pp. 213-216.) Or, if it be presumed that the accumulation of a large property increases the income, the argument is not to the point. 1 Wagner, op. cit., p. 457. * Die Progressive Eitikommensteuer, p. 62. * Ibid., p. 63. * Ibid., p. 62, 234 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [570 the sacrifice theory of progression is not to us, we confess, altogether convincing. Indeed, the argument appears to be a non sequitur. Because we satisfy our wants in the order of their decreasing intensity, or with large incomes satisfy less intensive wants than with small incomes, and in the case of a tax sacrifice the least intensive of our wants, it does not follow that proportional parts of incomes of different sizes will not effect equivalent sacrifices ; that, for example, a 3 per cent, tax on A's income of $10,000 is not felt by him exactly the same as a 3 per cent, tax on B's income of $i,coo is felt by him. If the income of A were suddenly reduced from $10,000 to $1,000 and the income of B raised from $1,000 to $10,000, then A would feel a 3 per cent, tax on $1,000 proportionately more, and B a 3 per cent, tax on $10,000 proportionately less than they felt the 3 per cent, tax on their former incomes. But this does not follow when the state of mind of A is compared with that of B, for what is to A a necessity is to B a luxury. Really, comparison between them is impossible. Above all is our contention true if, with Mill and Vocke, we exempt the necessities — the minimum of subsistence — and apply the rate only to the clear income ; an exemption, as we shall show later, is the logical consequence of the ability theory. Moreover, necessities are in a class by them- selves. Comparison between them and other wants is on a par with a comparison between the indefinite and the definite, or in their extremes, between the infinite and the infinitesimal.' Apart, then, from the question, whether the ideal aim of taxation is the production of equivalent in- tensities of feeling on account of the tax (a somewhat ques- tionable ideal), there can be no subjective proof of the realization of this equivalence. Subjectively, we cannot tell whether it would be attained by a proportional, a progres- * Cf. Sax, Die Frogressivsteuer, p. 85. 5/1 ] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 235 sive, or a degressive rate. We are dealing with the " quan- titatively immeasurable." In spite of this difficulty both Wagner and Neumann, while accepting ability as the true basis of taxation, find their proof for progression only by interpreting ability in tei-ms of subjective sacrifice. On the other hand, Meyer, who makes sacrifice the basis of the tax, determines the rate (which he finds should be progressive) by interpreting the sacrifice in terms of objective economic conditions — of objective ability. So, likewise, Sax declares that no definite results can be attained by the sacrifice theory, as all we can say of feelings is that one is greater or less than another, but not how much greater or less.' But Sax does not him- self escape the difficulty as easily as he imagines. He prides himself, as we have seen, upon escaping the dilemmas of the sacrifice theory (and also of the ability theory) by his theory of marginal utility, applicable alike to collective and to private wants. From the fact that as incomes increase there is both a decreasing utility — a decreasing intensiveness — in the wants satisfied, and at the same time an increasing utility, with respect to their extensiveness, it is concluded that finally the extensiveness of the utilities becomes so great that their decreasing intensiveness is practically in inverse proportion to the increase of income ; and that, but for their extensiveness it would be more than an inverse proportion.^ But in changing from the conception of sacri- fice to that of marginal utilities, Sax has not changed the principle in the least. He is still dealing with subjective states of feeling. These marginal utilities are precisely what the sacrifice consists of. To effect an "equivalence" of these utilities — these subjective feelings — is not a whit differ- ent from effecting an " equivalence" of sacrifice. Hence, in the determination of the question of rates, the ' Cf. Sax, Die Prop-essivsteuer, p. 83. ' Sax, ibid., p. 86. 236 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [572 theory of Sax has to meet with practically the same diffi- culties that are to be met with in the sacrifice theory, and he solves the problem exactly as Meyer solved it — by an appeal to objective standards, to the general agreement among men, and to the observation of the effects of feelings in economic exchange.' True, the objective conditions are supposed to be the expression of the subjective feelings, or subjective feelings to be induced by objective conditions ; so that in determining the tax rate the government has but to observe the effect upon feelings of objective conditions and relations, and then so arrange the rate that these relations will produce the desired subjective efTect — equivalence of feelings = equivalence of sacrifice. But with all of the " observation " of the effect of feelings upon economic exchange, no government can tell whether a tax proportional to income will produce equivalent feelings ; not only for the reason already given, to wit: that the fact that with increasing incomes the marginal utilities satisfied are of constantly decreasing intensity — of constantly de- creasing utility — is no proof that the loss of a portion of these utilities to A, with a large income, would not be the same to him as the loss of the same proportion would be to B, with a small income ; but also from the fact, as well pointed out by Sax, that we must take account of the extensiveness as well as the intensiveness of the marginal utilities sacrificed. Even if a " more or less " could be determined, the theory affords no way of determining how much more or less, or the rate of the progression ; for I cannot agree that collective wants are determined in exactly the same way as are the private wants.'^ It has remained for the Dutch economists, firmly adhering to the sacrifice theory, and to progression as its logical con- * Sax, Die Progressivsteuer, p. 85. * CJ. Neumann, Die Steuern und das offentliche Inter esse, pp. 190-200. 573] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 237 sequence, to reduce the rate of progression to a fixed rule to a mathematical formula— but their scientific exactness is purely an affair of the imagination. As we have seen, they attempt to solve the problem by the ingenious but deceptive device of taking two series of numbers and assuming that they correspond respectively to the decreasing utility of in- creasing increments of income, and the decreasing utility of increasing increments of the tax, such as would result from proportional taxation. This, it is assumed, would show an unequal, or a disproportionate, sacrifice. All that there is to do then is to so change the series as to produce a rate that will equalize the marginal utilities of the tax on differ- ent incomes, or equalize the sacrifice occasioned by the tax. But as there is absolutely no reason for choosing one series rather than another, any result, any rate of taxation, is theoretically possible according to this theory. This Cohen- Steuart admits, but .his own attempted refinement of the theory by assuming that the truth lies in the mean between two extremes, is, as both Professors Sax and Seligman have shown,' equally groundless, equally imaginary. It is all guess work, all groundless hypothesis. Hence the rule for progression : " Arithmetical increase of the rate with geomet- rical increase of the income up to a definite point when pro- gression is replaced by proportion," » is purely chimerical, and therefore wholly without value. Upon the whole, then, the sacrifice principle does not appear to throw much light upon the theory of rates. In- evitably appeal must be made to objective standards, to ob- jective economic conditions and relations. Even if " equiv- alence of feeling " is the ideal of justice in taxation, it is a purely abstract ideal. A government has fulfilled its obliga- ' Sax, Die ProgressivsUuer, p. 59 et seq.; Seligman. Progressive Taxation, pp. 184-5. * Quoted from Seligman, Ibid., p. 188. 238 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [574 tions in the just distribution of the tax burden when it has proportioned the tax according to the abiHty of the tax- payer, as this abiHty is determined by objective facts, objec- tive economic conditions of the taxpayers. We may grant that such a tax may, and in a very general way will, produce an equivalence of subjective feelings. But the fact remains that the point of view of the government is that of relative objective ability; that is, ability as determined by the econ- omic means for the satisfaction of public and private needs, their relative importance being taken into consideration. Such a conception of ability and our obligation to pay taxes is founded upon the nature of the state. It is, as we have seen, of a distinctively ethical connotation. This granted, What rate of taxation follows as a logical consequence? That is, A and B having incomes of different sizes, what portions of their incomes ought each to contribute to the support of the state, on which their social and civilized ex- istence depends? If A has ten times the income of B, ought he to contribute ten times as much? Is his ability ten times as great? To me the question is essentially, at least funda- mentally, ethical. But it is a question of practical ethics. It involves, nay it cannot escape, consideration of the rela- \ tive economic conditions of A and B ; nor, again, the effect J of a tax upon their relative economic conditions. Imme- / diately the problem has an objective reference ; ultimately, a subjective reference. That is to say, immediately it is a question of the true relation between economic means and objective economic conditions ; while ultimately it is a ques- tion of the relative importance, or character, of the wants satisfied by the economic means, or the relative importance of the needs of which the economic conditions are the expression. Immediately and objectively it has to do with economic conditions ; ultimately and subjectively with the importance of these relations in their bearing upon the pur- 575] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 239 poses of life. A government, however, must find its rules for guidance in the objective conditions, in accordance with a standard that represents the consensus of opinion as moulded by the moral sense of mankind ; by the habit, customs, and ideals as reflected in social institutions; by the degree of culture and civilization attained and by the econ- omic status of the society in question. Now by common consent wants are divided, in a very general way, into necessities, comforts and luxuries, and by common observation we learn that there is a certain corres- pondence between the satisfaction of each of these grades of wants and the amount of disposable income ; or, that with different amounts of income we provide ourselves with dif- ferent classes of economic goods, and thereby with the cor- respondingly different grades of enjoyment, of which the economic goods afford the means. By common consent, too, the necessities are deemed of the most, the luxuries of the least relative importance, not alone from the viewpoint of the subjective value to the individual, but also from the viewpoint of the progress and development of mankind. The comforts stand between the two. Therefore, the exten- sion of the scope of the necessities is of more importance than the extension of the comforts, while the extension of the latter is of more importance than the extension of the luxuries, and this importance could be shown to extend both to our economic and our spiritual well-being. Hence, considered from the viewpoint of the realization of the ends of man, in which is found the ultimate end of the state, it is of more importance that those who are confined to the necessities of life extend the scope of their satisfactions, than that those who enjoy the luxuries should extend theirs. At the same time it must be admitted that the comforts and luxuries are as positive factors in human development as are the necessities. Indeed, in a sense they are much 240 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [576 more significant. Necessities, when confined to absolute necessities, are a pre-condition to any development. De- velopment begins only when the stage of necessities is passed, when the stage of comforts, or of "culture" begins. And progress is marked by the gradual merging of comforts into culture necessities, and the conversion into luxuries of what has been regarded as superfluous. But the order of their importance remains unchanged. From the ethical standpoint, both of man and of the state, it would seem, then, to be a logical deduction, that the deprivation of a portion of the luxuries would be of relatively less importance than the deprivation of a similar portion of comforts, and, still more, than that of necessities. Or, what amounts to the same thing, it is of more importance that there should be the means of satisfying the latter than either of the former. Briefly, then, we are forced to the conclusion that ethically considered, that is, from the viewpoint of the ethical con- ception of man and of the state, wants of relatively decreas- ing importance are satisfied with increasing incomes, so that the taking away of a part of a small income (as by a tax) necessitates the giving up of wants of relatively greater im- portance than would the taking away of equivalent parts of large incomes. In other words, considered with respect to the importance of wants there is proportionately more dis- posable for taxes in large, than in small, incomes — propor- tionately greater ability. But there is no difiference in the importance of the state to the person, as such. The dififer- ence of interest is indistinguishable. Yet regarded from the point of view of the totality of satisfactions, and, therefore, of the means of these satisfactions, the importance of the state to the individual would seem to increase with the in- crease of income ; and because of the indispensableness of the state to this increase of income, its importance might well be regarded as increasing in greater proportion than 577] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 24 1 the increase of income. Hence, also, the obligation for a more than proportionate share of the tax burden as meas- ured by income. But this view merges into the benefit theory ; it does not directly determine ability, or the obliga- tion resting upon it. Confining ourselves, then, to the view of the equal importance of the state, the above argument leads inevitably to the conclusion that ability increases in a greater ratio than income, thus necessitating a higher rate on large than on small incomes in order that the tax may be proportional to ability. In brief, a progressive rate on increasing incomes is essential to a proportional tax on ability, if by ability is understood the relative satisfaction of wants with respect to their importance. This view of progression is not, I think, altogether dif- ferent from that of SchafBe, who conceives of ability as determined by the amount which one can contribute in taxes without crippling the same relative support of himself; and who concludes that this principle leads to progression, on the ground that as incomes increase in size relatively larger portions may be contributed to the state without detriment to a relative satisfaction of personal wants. But Schaffle also thinks that the idea of progression is itself "instinctively correct," "it being only the manner of carry- ing it out that is false in the theory of progressive taxation."' This is specially true if we give emphasis to the difference in the importance of wants, which appears to be implied in the theory of Schafifle. It is questionable if based on the sacrifice theory. But progression is "instinctively correct" only because it is based upon ideas that conform to the common judgment of mankind, with respect to the relativity of wants and their comparative importance to individual and social well-being. That there is an indefiniteness in this theory of progres- * Schaffle, Mensch und Gut, p. 49. C/. also, Die Grutidsatze, p. 23. 242 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [578 sion, and that it affords no definite ratio, or rate, of pro- gression, is not to be denied.' But this is inevitable in any theory of progression, and it does not prove that the prin- ciple itself is not correct. It has, at least, the merit of con- forming to the sound principle of Vocke (though differently applied by him), that the principle of progression must proceed from its own fundamental thought,'^ which we take to be the principle of relative ability as determined by in- come and by the relative importance of wants. But though vague and indefinite, must it be admitted that this theory of progression affords absolutely no principle for determining the rate and the limit of the progression? We think not. Vocke solves this question easily by assuming that the "fundamental thought" is the primary right to the needs of subsistence, and therefore the right to the exemp- tion of the minimum of subsistence, by which both the rate and its limit is fixed by the amount of the exemption, the only indefiniteness being in the amount of the exemption. That is, the limit of progression is dcgression.3 The diffi- culty with this view, as it appears to me, is this: What Vocke considers to be the " fundamental thought " of pro- gression — that is, of the principle of equality — is in reality, the fundamental thought of exemption — that is, of the prin- ciple of universality. The degressive principle is, indeed, incidental to exemption, but it has no direct bearing upon the question of progression, except upon the questionable assumption that ability is proportional to " clear" income. Schaffle, without reference to any "fundamental thought" of progression, but upon mere grounds of policy, would have the rate and limit of the progression indirectly deter- ^ See Seligman, Progressive Taxatiou, for criticism of Schaffle. * See Vocke, op. cit., p. 477. ' Vocke, ibid., pp. 477-9. 579] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 243 mined by the taxpayers themselves, through a tax upon consumption.' But this would be very uncertain in its effects on account of the shifting and incidence of taxes. Still, we may admit that the tendency of such a system would be to impose the tax "according to one's dynamic ability;" also to tax the " economic personality," and at the same time put a limit upon the progression.^ So likewise, Held would also indirectly attain the same result by impos- ing taxes so that they will occasion the least complaint, this complaint being considered as the best index, or measure, of sacrifice, or ability.^ This view has much in common with the theory of Sax, already sufficiently discussed, that the "equivalence" of the burden, and therefore, also, the just tax rate, is determined by the people through their representatives in the government. But while these views contain much truth, I believe that we can find in the principle of progression rules that deter- mine and limit its rate. Theoretically, if the principle of progression is based upon comparative ability, as we have understood it, there must be the same relative means of satisfying wants, according to their importance, after as be- fore the tax. This is a mere truism. But it follows, also, that there should be the same relative ability to exercise one's faculties, to the end of larger satisfactions, as existed prior to the tax. Otherwise progressive human develop- ment will be checked, and the purpose for which the state exists be negatived. Nor is this mere abstract theory. The same objective signs, by which the principle of progression is objectively determined, will aid, also, in determining the rate and limit of the progression — the effects of a tax upon the relative economic means of satisfaction. Above all is * Schaifle, Mensch und Gut, pp. 168-9. ^ Ibid., p. 168. * Einkommensteuer, p. 115. 244 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [580 the limit reached when the rate is such as to prevent that ' saving' that provides for future production." ' That this whole view of progression — of equality in taxa- tion — is vague and arbitrary, must again be admitted. But so is every other theory of progression. Here everything depends upon the determination of the relative importance of needs, which is a purely relative conception. But it must be borne in mind that our viewpoint is ethical — the ethical ideal in taxation. Nevertheless, this conception of progres- sion is not altogether impracticable. It is capable of prac- tical application within certain limits, and, therefore, of realizing an approximation to justice, which is all that any theory of progression can claim. And the higher the moral standard of mankind the more nearly will the approximation attain to the ideal. But in spite of the justice of the principle of progression, there are practical objections of another character that de- serve, perhaps, some consideration. That progressive tax- ation would prevent the growth of capital, or cause it to emigrate, is true only if the rate of progression be excessive. It would not follow moderation, or a wise conservatism, in the application of the principle. This is attested by the results of its practical application in Switzerland, Saxony, or wherever else applied. The same is true of the objection that, logically carried out, a progressive tax would confiscate wealth and equalize fortunes. Besides, logically carried out progressive taxation does not lead to confiscation. Progres- sion may lead to infinity, but progressive taxation is limited in its application by the principle by which it is itself deter- mined, as we have already seen. Hence, Wagner's social- political theory of progressive taxation is in direct conflict with his theory of taxation according to ability. Again, that ' The theory that a progressive tax necessarily prevents " saving " is based upon the erroneous assumption that what is paid as a tax would otherwise be " saved." 58 1 ] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 245 progressive taxation would stimulate money lenders to en- courage the increase of public debts is no truer than in the case of proportional taxation.' Nor would it necessarily imply undue interference with personal rights and liberties. This results more from the kind than from the rate of taxation. Upon the whole, then, I believe that if progression is just in principle it should be applied in practice ; but moderately applied. Even a conservative attempt to realize a principle of justice that is felt to be "instinctively correct" would go far towards mitigating the social discontent of the masses, and would tend to their rise by peaceful, instead of by revolutionary, methods. Or, as Held says: progressive taxation ** is a social need and a means of peaceful pro- gress."' "A social need," I take it, in the sense that I have understood the principle of progression, as largely con- ditioned by the relative importance of the intellectual and social development of the poorer classes, upon which in great measure depends the progressive development of man- kind;" peaceful progress," since every recognition of justice towards the masses, on the part of the government, tends to kill the revolutionary impulse. "If that organization of society and political life which we call aristocratic in the best sense of the term," says Cohn, "is to survive (and it is indispensable for the progress of civilization that it should survive), the corresponding aristo- cratic attitude of the upper classes must come up to the demand made upon it. They will, among other things, have to fulfil this requirement also in the way of accepting an adequately developed system of taxation. Their degree of readiness will make up in quality for what the democratic masses would otherwise demand, some day, in quantity. The voluntary acceptance of an increasing burden will serve * Cf. Adams, Public Debts, pp. 39-41. 'Held, op. cit., p. 172. 246 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [582 to strengthen their traditional influence and is indispensable to the best civilization, as well as to the existence of the higher classes themselves. On the other hand, the more an increasing progression comes as the result of the importunate demands of a discontented populace, the more reckless will it be, both in the new demands which it embodies and in its changes of the old order of things."' In brief, if the prac- tice of progression by those upon whom it would apply creates a possible danger, it averts the possibility of a far greater danger. II. The Principle of Universality That the principle of " universality," like the principle of " equality," follows from the nature of the state, the nature of the individual, and from the relation of the individual to the state, we have already seen. Thus viewed there would seem to be no ground for any exception to the rule. Uni- versality would seem to be an unconditional principle of taxation. This, in fact, is the view of most writers on the theory of taxation. It is the common idea that because of the indispensableness of the state to the individual, the universality of interest in the state, there is no exception, in principle, to the obligation to contribute to the state's sup- port. If exception is allowed, it can be only upon the ground of absolute necessity — the non-existence of means above the necessary minimum of subsistence. For to tax this " minimum" would necessitate an equal return from the taxes, which would occasion a net loss to the government, because of the increased cost of the collection and dispensa- tion of this part of its revenue without any net return to itself. But this view of exemption from taxation appears to me to be entirely wrong. It overlooks important factors in the ^ Cohn, o/>. cit., pp. 324-5. 583] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 247 problem. It is consistent only with the protective theory of the state and the benefit principle of taxation.' For since every individual receives protection, and thereby derives a benefit, every individual, without exception, should con- tribute to the cost of that protection. In the case of prop- erty there could be no tax for protection if there was no property to protect.'^ But for the protection of the person there could be no exception, other than that of absolute necessity. For every "benefit" there must be a correspond- ing tax. If we consider the benefit to consist in the gains from " exchange " there could be no tax where such " gains " did not exist, but there are certain benefits that are imma- terial gains, common to every member of the state, and for these gains every citizen should contribute a tax in exchange.3 Again, we may regard the benefit as consisting in the ser- vice performed by the state in production. In this case, if we look at results only, there could be no tax if the " ser- vice " was not utilized — if there was no production. But, on the other hand, if, more properly, we regard the state as the condition precedent to all production, in which every one is privileged to participate, there would seem to be no ground for exemption. "» At any rate, Stein considers it to be just to tax labor on the ground that it is only by the administra- tion of the state that its acquisitions are made possible.^ In reality, however, the problem of exemption is not consistent with Stein's theory of " diffusion," since, according to this theory, the burden of the tax is, in the main, justly dis- tributed through the influence of price.^ Or, again, if the benefit consists in the possession of a portion of the " na- tional capital," and the tax is distributed in proportion to the amount of this capital held, then there can be no ^ Cf. Murhard, op.cit., p. 90. ' CJ. Sismondi, op. cit., p. 164. ' Cf. Perry, op. cit., p. 515-8. * Cf. Stein, op. cit., p. 496. * Ibid., ii, p. 251. ^ Ibid., i, p. 494. 248 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [584 exemption except where there is no possession of the national capital. " The minimum of needs is spared by force of necessity, not by virtue of a false principle." ' Much the same conclusion results when exemption is con- sidered from the viewpoint of " equality of sacrifice;" for if " equality of sacrifice " is the true principle of taxation any exemption must appear as a contradiction of the principle, and is to be justified only on grounds of absolute necessity.* For where there is no tax there can be no sacrifice, and hence no " equality " in taxation. Exemption is an excep- tion to the principle, not a logical consequence of it.3 Nevertheless, Sax attempts to deduce exemption as a conse- quence of the principle of subjective sacrifice, and his ex- planation is, perhaps, the best that has been given from this standpoint. The thought is, as with Mill,'^ that the physical necessities are incomparable in their intensity with all other classes of needs, comparison being possible only between those needs that are satisfied after the physical minimum is passed, the comparison including all collective needs. But no needs above the physical minimum (which includes the collective needs) can be satisfied until the needs below the minimum are fully satisfied. Hence, sharing in the expense for the satisfaction of collective needs can take place only where the means exceed the requirements of the minimum of subsistence. 5 The exemption is a matter of necessity, not of principle. " On grounds of absolute necessity the pure minimum must be exempted, but justice does not demand any exemption so long as there is an income equal to the minimum plus the tax."* But exemption on the ground of necessity is confined to the bare physical necessities of life. If exemption is to be > Menier, op. cit., p. 221. * See, for example, Wagner, op. cit. * Cf. Meyer, op. cit., p. 294. * Mill, Political Economy, v, 2, 3. * See Sax, GrundUgung, pp. 509-13. • Sax, Die Progressivsteuer, p. 69. 585] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 249 justified on income that exceeds the requirements of these bare necessities, it must be justified upon some fundamental principle, be the logical outcome of the " fundamental thought " that lies at the basis of the ethical idea of taxa- tion. Such I believe to be in accordance with the real facts of the case. We have, then, two problems before us — the justification of exemptions and the limitations of exemption. I . The Justification of Exemptions. Accepting the ability basis of taxation, exemption of the minimum of subsistence follows as a necessary consequence. For if taxation accord- ing to ability is the true principle of taxation, it is a mere truism to say that where there is no ability there can be no obligation. It is not merely that there can be no tax if there is no ability, but where the ability does not exist the tax obligation does not exist. The obligation begins the moment that the ability is manifest. To tax where there is no ability would be a violation of the principle that taxes should be proportioned to ability. Exemption, where there is no ability, is but the fulfilment of the impHcations of the principle which is assumed to be the just basis for the dis- tribution of the tax burden. It is not, as in the preceding theories, a necessary exception in contradiction with the principle that is assumed as the basis of taxation. It is true that the exemption of any person from the pay- ment of taxes is in contradiction with the principle of uni-. versality. But this principle is a relative, not an absolute, principle of taxation. Or, if politically and economically it is absolute, ethically the principle of universality extends only so far as there is ability. Within this limit only is it a universal principle. Hence, while exemption is an excep- tion to the general principle of universality, it is in harmony with the qualified form of the principle — the form in which it is a true principle of taxation. True, exemption of the min- imum of subsistence is a necessity, but this is not its only justification. It follows, as we have seen, from principle. 2^0 JUSTICE m TAXATION [586 But the real justification of exemption rests upon a basis that is more fundamental than the idea of taxation according to ability. It rests, indeed, upon the same " fundamental thought" as does the idea of ability itself. Both are devel- opments of the same fundamental idea — human personality in its relation to the state. It involves both the relations of the individuals to the state and their relations to each other, and not simply, as Meyer holds, their relation to the state ; nor, as Wagner seems to hold, simply their relations to each other.' Particularly is this true if the exemption is to extend beyond the bare necessities for physical existence. What, then, is the fundamental ground of exemption, or of exceptions to the principle of universality in taxation? The more common idea is that since every individual parti- cipates in the ends for which a state exists, every individual, without exception, should contribute to its support. But this we have found to be conditioned by the further prin- ciple, that the support should be proportioned to ability ; by implication there being no obligation where there is no economic ability. But we have now to inquire why this obligation does not exist when the importance of the state to every individual is admitted. Those, for example, who hold that the obligation never ceases base their conviction upon the idea that the state, if not of first importance, is, at least, of equal importance with physical subsistence, to every member of civilized society. This is the view of both Held and Cohn. Held, for example, in declaring against the exemption of the wages of labor, says : "The state is for all a need ; its existence for the whole is more necessary than the life of the individual."' So likewise Cohn: "Plainly, as viewed from the standpoint of the latest theory of the state, there is no room for the doctrine which admits the state and its demands only as second to the necessaries of life. The » See Meyer, cp. cit., pp. 293-4. * Held, op. cit., p. 105. 587] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 2$ I State, above all things, is part of these necessaries and its demands are therefore part and parcel of the demands of subsistence."' Hence, theoretically, or in principle, there is, according to this view, no justification for exemption. But the view of Held and Cohn appears to me to be a mistaken one. It is based upon, or at least it implies, the erroneous conception of the state as a "social organism," the individual being a means, the state the end. But ac- cording to the view that the state exists for the highest development of human personality — the individual being the end, the state a means — " the latest theory of the state," the effect of the tax upon the person becomes of first import- ance. If the state is a necessity to this development, it is quite as true that there must first be the existence of the person. Moreover, the right to provide the means of sub- sistence is a fundamental right, and is prior to every other right. Even Held admits this. He goes even farther, and, in spite of his theoretical objection to exemptions, would exempt not only what is necessary for the physical needs of self and family, but also what is necessary for their spiritual life.'' Vocke, too, recognizes the right to the necessary needs of subsistence as prior to any claims of the state, but he limits this right to the bare minimum of subsistence.3 It must be admitted, however, that with Held the exemption which he ^Cohn, op. cit., p. 331. Cf. also, p. 354. ' " Den Jeder hat vor AUem das Recht zu leben, und es ist wohl die schreiendste Ungerechtigkeit von dem zum nothdiirftigen Unterhalte erforderlichen Einkom- men noch offentliche Abgaben fiir den Staat zu fordern." Held, op. cit., p. 451. " So wahr aber der Mensch ein Vernunftwesen ist, muss einem Jedem nicht bless as verlassen werden, was ihm zum sinnlichen, sondern auch Das, was ihm zum geistlichen Leben unentbehrlich ist." Ibid., p. 452. "" Der Staat nur solche Anspriiche als seinen eigenen vorgehend anerkennen darf und kann, welche alter und naturgemiss noch berechtiger sind als er selbst, nSmlich das Recht auf die Selbsterhaltung und auf die Erhaltung der Familie, bzw. in diesen auf die Erhaltung des Menschengeschlechts. Ein altereres, unbe- dingteres Recht gibt es nicht." Vocke, 0/. cit., p. 480. See also pp. 463-4. 252 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [588 would allow is not a right, but only a social need that is necessary to the highest efficiency of labor.' That exemption of the minimum of subsistence is a neces- sity, as is so universally emphasized, goes without saying; but the above considerations show, I think, that the exemp- tion is also justified in principle, and is not, as Von Hock claims, " a simple act of benevolence." ^ I do not see how any other conclusion is possible when we reflect that the ultimate end of the state is the developed personality of the individual. For the first condition of this development is an economic personality, an economic freedom, which involves above all the necessary means of subsistence. And, there- ■ fore, to tax the " minimum " is to nullify or retard the very development which it is the purpose of the state to promote. This is even more patent if the tax necessitates a public charity. The economic and social importance of an " economic personality" was clearly recognized by Held, who deemed it a sufficient ground for the exemption, not only of a bare minimum, but of a sufficient minimum to enable the poor to rise to a higher economic order.3 Stein goes even farther and justifies exemption because of its bearing upon the total personality of the individual. True, Stein regards the state as an " organism " whose personality is to be realized, the tax being a necessary means to this end. But this " or- ganic " view adds nothing to the theory. For the fully realized personality of the state is marked by the realized personality of the individual, or the highest form of personal life — " personal freedom." Indeed, the realization of " per- sonal freedom " is regarded as the ultimate end of the state, and this realization is efifected by the realization of its own personality. But the first requisite is " economic freedom." ^Held, p. 118. » Von Hock, op. cit., p. 173. ^ Held, op. cit., p. 1 1 8. 589] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 253 Hence, the exemption of the minimum of subsistence.' The same conclusion is reached by Schaf^le, though from a diflfer- ent point of view. Emphasizing the fact that the tax obli- gation rests upon personality — upon the person — it is justly held that there can be no obligation where the personality has not realized itself in property, in an economic personal- ity (eine Vermogenspersonlichkeit), since what the state re- quires is economic goods.' That is, while the tax obligation rests upon personality it is only potential until there is realized an " economic personality." While there is much truth in these different views of the relation of exemption to personality, the question of real importance is the effect of a tax (upon the minimum) or of an exemption, upon the personality of the taxpayer.3 Where this is endangered there can be no obligation ; and it is endangered when it has not so far developed as to have realized itself in objective goods sufficient to meet the needs of subsistence ; to have realized itself, that is, in economic freedom, in economic personality. In brief, the obligation begins when "economic" or "personal" freedom begins. The first claim upon property, which we have seen to be the objectified self, and therefore, in a sense, a " natural right," is subsistence of the self, of the physical person ; but since the state is a condition of the development of the person- ality of self, the obligation to use the property to support the state, and the right of the state to demand this support, begins after the needs of physical subsistence are met. But this right to exemption, on the part of those who have incomes at or below the minimum of subsistence, involves a corresponding obligation, on the part of those who have in- comes above the minimum, to meet the full demands of the * Stein, op. cit., section, Die Steuer. 'See Schaffle, Grundsdtze,^^. 14 and 169. 2 Cf. Schaffle, ibid., p. 170. 254 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [590 state for economic goods. Nor docs this obligation rest simply upon the nature of their relation to the state as alone possessing economic ability, but it has its basis also in the nature of the ethical relation of man to man, of man as a spiritual being — an end in himself. Indeed, from no other point of view is exemption to be justified in principle, whether considered with respect to the relation of the in- dividual to the state, or with respect to the relation of individuals to each other as persons. Directly and imme- diately, however, the basis of exemption is the principle that the burden of taxation should be proportioned to ability. Even the social-political argument of Wagner assumes to be based upon this principle. But in making social-political ends the only justification of exemptions,' Wagner diverts his argument from the main point at issue. For the real social-political end of exemption, like that of progression, is not to distribute the tax according to ability, but by equal- izing property to equalize ability. But the attainment of such a result is not a problem of taxation. There are, however, various other arguments for the ex- emption, which do not involve the question of principle, but are of a practical nature. Such, for example, is the argu- ment based upon an assumed analogy between capital and labor and the necessity of maintaining their highest effi- ciency. As developed by Luigi Rameri it is, that income consumed for subsistence is a species of recuperation of capital, " being spent to maintain the productive force of labor; " that, therefore, such income should be exempt from taxation for the same reason that the taxable income from any industry excludes that part of the product that goes to pay current expenses and to keep up the plant." Hence, only the clear income is a taxable income. This is the same ' See Wagner, op. cit., ii, § 167. * Luigi Rameri, "Per la Proportionalita delle Imposte," in Rassegna for Oct. 1891. I> ,.- 591] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 2$$ economic argument as that used by Held who justifies exemption on the ground that to tax the " minimum would lessen the efficiency of labor.' While the argument has directly only an economic bearing it is nevertheless of considerable importance, since to curtail labor efficiency is to check economic progress and thereby to lessen the means and with it also the efficiency of the state. It is given an added weight when we reflect that the evil influences would be cumulative in their effects. But indirectly the argument bears also upon the principles previously discussed. For in- lessening labor efficiency by a tax upon the " minimum " we check the development of " economic personality," and witfv it also that social development that leads to the development of the larger personality of man. Passing over the ''compensatory" argument^ which is a question of special and not of general exemption, we may note the argument based upon Adam Smith's fourth canon of taxation :' the argument that there should be an exemp- tion of small incomes on the ground that the cost of collec- tion of the tax would be in excess of the receipts. The effect of such a tax would be, not only to work economic injury to those having small incomes, but also to those hav- ing large incomes, by unnecessarily and unjustly increasing their tax burden. From this point of view exemptions would be justified even though they were not justified in principle. Nor would the exemption necessarily be limited to the minimum of subsistence, but should extend to the point where the receipts from the tax would just exceed the cost of its collection ; just as in the preceding economic argument the exemption should extend to the point where the tax would not cripple the efficiency of labor. 'See Held, op. cit., p. 118. '' For this argument see, for example, Mile. Royer, op. cit.^ pp. 23-7, ' Adam Smith, op. cit,, p. 416. 256 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [592 But while such arguments as these have their weight, and should be considered in any practical application of the principle of exemption, the real justification of exemption must be found, as we have seen, in the nature of man, the nature of the state, and the relation of man to the state. The importance of the state to the individual cannot be ignored, but at the same time the supreme importance of the individual should be recognized. This is brought out very well by Vocke, who of all writers has most clearly stated the true principle of taxation. His statement is a good summary of the whole argument. " Man," he says, " lives and moves in the state and for the state, but not alone that, for he is an end in himself ; if he exists for the state the state exists for him. And if man lives through the state he does not live alone through the state, but also, and indeed in the first instance through himself. Man, generally speaking, is before the state, and if the state takes from him his existence it puts itself in contradiction with its function and its purpose," ' for the first duty of the state is not to endanger the existence and the support of man.^ And it is claimed with much truth, that if we remember that the sub- ject of the tax is persons, not things, the problem solves itself.3 2. The Limitation of Exemptions. The argument has thus far assumed that the exemption should be confined to the " minimum of subsistence." But is this " minimum " limited to the absolute necessities of life, or should it extend to a ' " Der Mensch lebt unci webt zwar im Staat und fur den Staat, aber das alles nicht allein, sondern er ist auch Selbstzweck ; er ist nicht nur um des Staats willen, sondern auch der Staat ist um des Menscben willen. Ebenso lebt der Mensch durch den Staat, aber das ebenfalls nicht allein, sondern auch, und zwar in erster Reihe, durch sich selbst. Der Mensch ist iiberhaupt vor dem Staat, und wenn hiernach der Staat den Menschen in seiner Existenz angreift, so setzt er sich in Widerspruch mit seiner Aufgabe und seiner Bestimmung." Op. cit., p. 459. *IHd. ^ /iid., TpY>. 471-2. 593] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 257 "culture minimum"? In other words, Does the obligation to contribute to the support of the state begin the moment that income exceeds the necessary means of physical sub- sistence, or is the obHgation relative to an arbitrary standard of life? In the first place the " minimum " must be sufficient, not only for the subsistence of the person but also for the main- tenance and support of the family. Without such an exten- sion of the " minimum" the race could not be perpetuated, at least under the conditions that promote the highest civilization, the highest development of individual person- ality. Moreover, the family is the natural economic unit — the unit of economic personality, of economic freedom. And without the economic freedom of the family the first important step towards realized personality must remain untaken, the first important step towards the fulfilment of the ends of the state unattained. The family as much as the individual precedes the state — conditions the state. Provi- sion for its subsistence is, therefore, not only a right, but is a "natural right," that the state is in duty bound to respect. To quote Vocke, "The state has the same obligation to recognize the necessary care of the family as a duty prior to its own claims, as it has to recognize that of self- main- tenance." ' In the second place, there can be no permanent economic freedom — requisite to permanent economic personality — until the income is sufficient to provide not only the absolute necessities of physical existence, but also to provide for the maintenance of labor power and for times of sickness,* for the family as well as for the self. For a state to levy a tax that would be prejudicial to either of these conditions would be to weaken the source of its own support; and besides, it would be as much a contradiction of its own purpose as to ' Op. cit., p. 467. ' Cf. Vocke, ibid., p. 460. 258 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [594 tax the absolute necessities of physical existence, differing only in degree. On the other hand, until the "minimum" is sufficient to meet these requirements there is no real tax ability, and therefore no tax obligation.' But when these requirements have been met, when, that is, there is a " clear" income above the minimum of subsist- ence as above understood, the obligation to aid in the sup- port of the state begins. Or the obligation that was before potential, because of the importance of the state to the indi- vidual, now for the first time becomes actual. If exemption is extended beyond this limit it cannot be as a right, but only on grounds of policy — political, social, or economic. It is true that the limit is somewhat arbitrary, for it is difficult to determine exactly how much should be set aside as necessary for the support of the family or to maintain the labor power of the taxpayer. In fact, the limit is a purely relative one, the standard for exemption necessarily depend- ing upon the accepted standard of life, which is itself con- ditioned by the customs, habits, social ideals and degree of culture attained ; and, above all, by the conditions of indi- vidual and national wealth. Practically the standard must be determined by the same principles that determine the rate of progression. Still, it should be remembered that purely on grounds of theoretical justice only provision for normal support, and normal efficiency, should be allowed. For example, allow- ance cannot, or should not, be made for abnormally large famihes,^ since this would be to put a premium upon thrift- lessness and irresponsibility, and thus to encourage an increase of population where most detrimental to society, and to the highest individual development. On the other ^ " Die Leistungsfahigkeit aber ist das notwendige Korrelat der Leistungspflicht, welche ohne jene nicht denkbar ist." Vocke, p. 284. * See, per contra, Wagner, op. cit., ii, 447. 595] ETHICAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION 259 hand, if more than the normal efficiency of labor is allowed for in the exemption, it must be because of the retroactive effects of the exemption, or because of the disproportionate cost of the collection of the tax. But with advancing wealth, advancing culture, and advancing civilization the standard of exemption should be raised in conformity with the ends for which the state exists — the progressive develop- ment of mankind. CHAPTER VIII PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION In the preceding study of the principles of justice in tax- ation, we have not wholly lost sight of the fact that theoret- ical ideals are not always, nay are seldom, fully realizable in practice. Nor have we been unmindful of the fact that economic and social conditions must enter largely into our determination of the ideal. For since the ideal in taxation must necessarily have as its objective point the effects, or results, of this or that system or method of taxation, the nature of the effect must be a controlling influence in deter- mining the character, or the justice, of our ideal. But while we have recognized the relative nature of the ideal of justice in taxation it must be admitted that we have not developed this aspect of the question, but have given our attention almost entirely to theoretical principles. And yet, we insist, not to theoretical principles that are purely vision- ary in the sense that they are applicable only to ideal beings, but principles that are founded upon the ethical nature of man and upon moral and social facts and forces. Neverthe* less, the fact that the dominant thought has been that of the morally right — of justice — has led us to ignore for the most part the possibility of the practical realization of our ideal. So true is this, indeed, that there will be a seeming justice for the critic who urges that our theoretical principles afford no solution to the apparently insoluble problem of practical justice in taxation. Moreover, since the theoretical prin- ciples are unrealizable in practice, the critic may further 260 [596 597] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 261 urge that there can be no value in these theoretical discus- sions. But before we concede the truth of these criticisms let us consider for a moment whether theoretical principles that cannot be fully realized in practice may not after all have some practical value ; indeed, whether the principles them- selves are not to some extent, at least, practicable. In the first place, there is always a practical value in determining a norm for the guidance of real life, or for the guidance of action in the actual happenings of life. Human action un- guided by an ideal can be but irrational, purposeless, and without significance or achievement. This is as true in matters of taxation as in the purely moral life. Indeed, since human action is necessarily social action, a norm of conduct becomes indispensable, for otherwise there could be only the self-seeking of the individual which would be destructive of social life, and so ultimately also of any truly human life. But again, Is there nothing practicable in the theoretical principles we have discussed ? The answer to the question must depend upon the meaning we give to the " prac- ticable." But the practicable must mean one of two things : Either a system which is so in harmony with prevailing sentiments and convictions that there is a possibility of its immediate adoption ; or a system of which there is a reason- able hope of adoption by a change in the prevailing thoughts and ideals. Now we maintain that there is some- thing practical in our principles from both points of view. In fact, there is no principle that we have advocated that cannot be found in actual practice in one country or an- other, so that the problem is not so much one of a practical application of new principles as an extension, or fuller application, of accepted principles. But though there may be some principles not in harmony with the sentiments of a 262 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [598 particular people, there may yet be some practical value in their discussion ; for a nation, like an individual, can pro- gress only as its thought and ideals move ever upward to higher and truer standards. But there is yet another point of view from which we may consider the practicability of theoretical principles of just taxation — that of their implications. That is to say, if the principles involve consequences that are impossible to be realized in practice it would seem to be a just charge that the principles are themselves impracticable. What, then, are the implications involved in our principles, if these prin- ciples are to be fully realized? Undoubtedly the student of finance will say : A single tax on incomes. Nay, more, an income tax with progressive and differential rates together with a broad application of the principle of exemptions. Nor can one deny the justice of this judgment. More than this, however, is true ; for there are not a few economists and students of finance who will grant that under ideal con- ditions of human life and human relations — when a sound social ethics dominates human affairs — such a system of taxes would most nearly realize the ideal of justice. But we are not dealing with such ideal conditions, and taking the facts as we find them — the sentiments, prejudices and con- victions of the people — there can be no doubt but that a single progressive tax on incomes is one of the most vision- ary of all possible forms of taxation, particularly with re- spect to the people of the United States. But after all, is such an implication, or such a consequence, involved in our theory? The main burden of our whole thesis has been to show not only that the tax burden should be distributed according to the ability to bear it, but to show the grounds upon which such a principle rests. True, it was found that the ability is determined in part by income and in part by the needs which that income must satisfy, and 599] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 263 that, therefore, a tax in proportion to ability is necessarily based upon income, though it may be with progressive and differential rates. Yet the fact is recognized (if not before,' it is now) that the tax could not be assessed directly upon income for the reason that only under ideal conditions could the income be ascertained. Nay, to attempt to do so under existing standards of social ethics would be to defeat the end sought by imposing, in many cases, regressive burdens. We have before insisted that the principles of justice are relative, in the sense that they must be tested by results. In the same way must we determine their implications. Because under ideal conditions the implications involve certain results it by no means follows that under actual conditions the same re- sults must occur. In other words, because under ideal con- ditions our principles involve a single tax on incomes, it does not follow that they involve such a tax under the social con- ditions as we actually find them to be. The main thing is to tax ability by taxing income, which is the only ultimate source of ability; but if this income can be reached and ascertained by the indirect method, this method is the one demanded by our principles. Or if the sentiment of the people is against the direct ascertainment of ability the same conclusion follows. In fact, if we could reach the full income by either method it would matter little which one was em- ployed. We must then employ the one that will give us the most accurate results, the one that will most nearly ascertain the true income. Under present conditions this is believed to be that of the indirect method. Indeed, with a proper system it is believed that ability, so far as it is determined by income, can be ascertained with a fair approximation to justice, and such an approximation is all that can be hoped for in human afifairs. And yet the ideal — a tax on income — is not without its value, since it serves as the goal for every indirect system of reaching the income ability of the tax- 264 fUSTICE IN TAXATION [6oo payer, for every tax, however assessed, is ultimately a tax on income. Assuming, then, the above conditions, it remains to indi- cate the character of a practicable tax system that will most nearly realize the principles for which we have contended. Nor can I do more than to " indicate " such a system. I cannot stop either to elaborate or to defend it. It is beheved, however, that the system which we shall propose is not only perfectly consistent with our principles, but is one of which there is hope for its gradual adoption ; and when adopted will give a realization to justice in taxation such as has never yet been realized in this country, if, indeed, in any country. It is not maintained that all of the principles would be fully realized, as, for example, the principle of progressive taxa- tion, but that we should attain the nearest attainable approx- imation of those principles, and at the same time go a long way towards removing the gross inequalities in the tax systems of our several States.' Our present thesis, then, is to outline a scheme of taxa- tion that will most nearly reach the full income of the tax- payer and most equitably distribute the tax burden — most nearly and most equitably, I mean, under existing condi- tions. And this method is believed to be that of the indi- rect one of reaching income through some index, or through indices, of income. Such an index is to be found in prop- erty which, as we have seen, may be regarded either as the source or the consequence of income. And by taking differ- ent forms of property we may get several indices, which if wisely selected will constitute a fair basis for the determina- tion of income. But the problem of an equitable system of taxation is something more than this. It is necessary not only to select such indices as shall be fairly representative of in- 1 For an outline of a rational system of taxation, see Adams, FudUc Finatice. 6oi] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 265 come, but such as may be most easily and most fairly assessed — perhaps the most difficult problem in the whole field of practical taxation. For if property is to be made the basis, or measure, of income„an honest assessment be- comes fundamental to an equality of taxation. And, there- fore, very much depends both upon the character of the property taxed and the method by which it is taxed. More- over, much depends also upon the character of the political unit that taxes the different forms of property. Or in other words, the problem is also one of a distribution of the tax system among the different political units in such a way as to realize the best economic and ethical results. In brief, then, the problem before us is one of the assess- ment of property, of the methods of taxation, of the kinds of property to be selected for taxation, and the proper spheres of state and local taxation. We cannot stop to dis- cuss the question of rates or of exemptions. Not the ques- tion of rates, because it is admitted that only the propor- tional rate is feasible for the present; not exemption, because the principle is universally adopted in practice, and we do not feel it necessary to add to what has already been said on the subject. And yet we must acknowledge, that the principle of exemption is not carried out in practice to the extent that our principles would demand, not to the extent that we believe to be justified. Still, as previously pointed out, it must be admitted that the limit, or rather the extension of exemption, is relative to the prevailing econ- omic and social conditions of the people and to the econ- omic needs of the state. But assuming the question of exemptions to be on the whole fairly settled, and the ques- tion of rates to be for the present outside of the field of practical discussion, let us attempt to portray in some detail, though briefly, the system of taxation indicated above. 266 JUSTICE IN TAXATION ; 6o2 I. Assessments That equitable assessment is one of the most difficult problems in practical taxation is admitted on all hands. It is the crucial point in the investigations of all tax commis- sions and in all practical plans for the reform of our present methods and systems of taxation. And yet if property is to be made the measure of income — the index of ability — equal assessment is indispensable to justice. Indeed, given an honest assessment of property and the battle for justice in taxation is as well as won. Whether such an assessment maybe approximated will depend very largely upon the char- acter of the property taxed and the method by which it is assessed. What, then, are the conditions that are essential for the equal assessment of property? I. Declaration versus Doomage. — Much has been written concerning the relative merits of a declaration by the tax- payer, and doomage by the government. Theoretically the principle of declaration is no doubt the correct one. This follows inevitably from the voluntary character which we found in the relation of the citizen to the state. Yet we found at the same time that there is also a compulsory feature in this relation, which is founded upon the necessity of the state's existence. From the character of this com- pulsion, founded upon a political necessity, it follows that the declaration should be supplemented by the doomage power of the government. This double feature — declaration and doomage — is the prevailing system of our several Com- monwealths, though with some the " declaration," with others the "doomage" is made the key-note of the system. But however much the principle of declaration may conform to the highest ideals of taxation, experience shows that it is not a principle that can be relied upon to attain justice until there prevails a higher standard of social ethics. No system can be just, either in theory or in practice, that 603] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 267 puts a premium upon perjury by ignoring facts of human nature; that induces perjury on the part of some because of the well-known fact of the perjury of others, perchance with the connivance of officials; that induces perjury because honesty would invite upon one's self a penalty in the form of an assumption of a part of the tax burden that rightfully devolves upon those who have escaped by an act of perjury. It is, for example, within our personal knowledge that an aged widow whose sole means of support is the income from nine thousand dollars loaned on mortgages at five per cent, (a small part at six per cent.), pays a tax of three per cent, because she insists upon an honest declaration ; thus paying in taxes more than fifty per cent, of her small income ! And this is but one of hundreds of similar instances fostered by the perjury systems of taxation in our various Common- wealths. The iniquity and injustice of such a system cannot be too strongly emphasized. These iniquities should be removed by the adoption of some system that will reach the income and distribute the burden according to the income ability of the taxpayer, and not according to the conscience of the individual. Such a system, however, is not to be found in the way of a premium upon honest declarations in the form of a lower tax rate on certain forms of intangible property, such as mortgages — a method practiced in Pennsylvania and par-' tially approved by the Massachusetts Tax Commission.^ For such a method of evoking honest declarations is a species of class legislation that purposely relieves a part of the taxpayers from their proper and just share of the tax burden, only to impose it upon those whose visible property prevents their evasion. True, such a method may evoke a ' Tax Commission Report, 1897, PP- 88-9. Connecticut has adopted a similar device which the Michigan Tax Commission deems "worthy of most serious con- sideration." Report, 1900, pp. 18-9. 268 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [604 larger sum of taxes upon a given form of property — intan- gible personalty — than would result from the normal rate upon the declaration (with implied oath') of the individual. But such a concession, or purchased honesty, is quite as un- necessary as it is unjust. For if such property must be taxed there are simpler and more rational methods of reach- ing it. What these mothods are we shall presently consider. Here we wish simply to emphasize the fact that equal assessment is the foundation of justice in matters of taxation, and that that system is inherently wrong and unjust that seeks honest declaration by a veiled method of bribery. 2. Taxable Property. Before discussing the proper methods of assessments it will be well to consider the kinds of property that should be taxed as most nearly and most adequately representing income, the ascertainment of which is the real aim of the government and the real purpose of the assessment. It follows, therefore, that in the selection of property for taxation two conditions are essential : First, the property selected should be fairly indicative of income, and, secondly, it should be such that its value may be easily ascertained with some degree of truth; for while income is not always proportionate to the value of property, it never- theless remains true that upon the whole the value is a fair index of income. At any rate the value of property is about the only standard, or measure, of income that we have, so long as it is not feasible to ascertain the amount Of income directly. But the justice of such a standard of income depends more than all else upon the equality of the assessment. And this equality, again, depends both upon the kind of property taxed and upon the method by which it is assessed. As to the kind of property that best measures tax ability, it is the common theory and practice of our several States ' The actual taking of an oath is, I believe, rarely required. 605] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 269 that every variety of property is equally indicative, and that, therefore, no form of property should escape assessment. Wagner's devices for reaching every form of property give sanction to this theory. In practice, Ohio has carried the doctrine to very near its extreme limit. The experience, however, in all of our States is a clear demonstration of the utter failure of the attempt to reach ability by any such method. This, indeed, is recognized by most Tax Commis- sions ^ as one of the most patent evils of our tax systems. The fact is that no form of property can be considered as indicative of income, or ability, of which it is morally cer- tain that only a small fraction can be reached. Hence, for purposes of taxation, only such forms of property should be assessed whose value can be determined with some de- gree of accuracy; or, better, perhaps, property should be assessed only in such form as lends itself to the determina- tion of its value. This leads us to remark that we believe the principle of multipficity of taxes to be entirely erron- eous, both in theory and in practice. For apart from the impossibility of determining all forms of property, as men- tioned above, there are certain types of property that are more accurate measures of income than other types, and tax systems should seek such types if such property can be found and its value can be ascertained. Without stopping to develop this feature, it may be remarked that a " habitation' tax," or a tax on house rent, affords an excellent example of what is meant. Such a tax, too, has the advantage that it can be easily ascertained. That, within certain limits, such a tax is a fair measure of income will be generally con- ceded, since the amount paid for house rent is, in general, proportionate to income. So true is this, that it is recom- mended by many French writers and by the Italian econo- ' As Massachusetts, Ohio, Wisconsin and Michigan. For the opposite view see minority report of Geo. E. McNeill in Mass. Tax Cora., 1897. 270 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [606 mist Baer.' It is also recommended in the majority report of the Massachusetts Tax Commission.' Still, it must be admitted that house rent as a measure of incomes must be confined to moderate incomes. For the income of the multi- millionaire house rent would be no measure whatever. Such a tax must, therefore, be used with caution. As a single tax, except upon small incomes, such a tax would be most unjust. Indeed, any form of a single tax must work injust- ice, largely in consequence of the differing effects of shifting and incidence, but partly because of the differing opportuni- ties for evasion. The multiple tax is also objectionable because of the cost of assessment and collection, thus violating one of the car- dinal principles laid down by Adam Smith, and since accepted by all students of taxation. Because, then, of their double injustice — evasions and unnecessary costs — multiple systems of taxation should be avoided. But we have seen that the single tax is also objectionable. Hence a wise sys- tem will consist of such a selection of plural taxes as can be based upon forms of property at once indicative of income and of easily ascertainable value. What these forms are will appear a little more in detail as we proceed. But after all, it is, perhaps, not so much the form of the property to be assessed as the method of its assessment that is important. 3. Methods of Assessment. The problem of equitable as- sessment involves two difficult tasks: The discovery of property, and uniformity of valuation. Though a constitu- tional requirement of most of our states, it is a notorious fact that, with the comparatively few exceptions of " widow's mites," there is not only no pretense at a full valuation, but hardly a pretense at a valuation at a uniform rate. But ' Baer, Vavere e V Ifnposta, p. 32. * Report, 1897, PP- 104-9. Id opposition see minority report of McNeill, pp. 153-4. 6o7] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 27 1 whatever the " pretense," it is the universal verdict of Tax Commissions, tax ofificials, and of students of our taxing systems that uniformity of assessments is an unrealized dream, an ideal of the imagination, to say nothing of the total escape of certain forms of property from all taxation. Lack of uniformity of assessment applies to all forms of property, though to some more than to others, depend- ing in part upon the successful intrigue and deception of owners, in part upon the intelligence and honesty of ofificials; but the complete escape from assessment pertains essentially to intangible property. Let us consider, briefly, each of these problems — the discovery of property and the uniform- ity of its assessment. Concerning the discovery of real estate and tangible per- sonal property little or no difficulty arises. The problem, as we have seen, attaches to the discovery of intangible per- sonal property. How, then, is this to be reached? Two methods are possible; Either the compulsory recording of all possessions of intangible property — of mortgages, bonds, stocks, etc. — similarly to the recording of deeds, in order that they may have legal validity; or the taxing of such forms of property by taxing their visible representatives — lands, corporations, etc. With respect to mortgages either method is applicable ; only care should be taken to avoid the injustice of double taxation by taxing both the land and . the mortgage. If the land is taxed to its full value the mortgage is indirectly taxed and should not, therefore, be taxed directly. But if it is deemed best to tax the land at its full value, less the value of the mortgage, and to tax the mortgage directly, then the mortgage should be recorded that its full value may be ascertained without difficulty, and with only a nominal expense. Other credits could be treated in the same manner, though some forms of personal notes it would seem to be advisable to exempt from taxation and to use other indices of income. 272 - JUSTICE IN TAXATION [6o8 For the taxation of stocks and bonds the only rational and effective method is that which taxes them by taxing the corporation or other property which they represent. Viewed as a tax upon income, as in effect it is, it is the principle of taxing income at its source — a principle extensively practised in the English Income Tax. The extent to which such forms of pro-perty escape assessment is too notorious to need specific proof, there being, as a rule, from 80 per cent, to 90 per cent, that wholly escapes taxation.' Nor has any effective method yet been adopted, other than the English method, by which the income from such property can be reached for purposes of taxation. The compulsory record- ing of stocks and bonds would be a decidedly objectionable method, both on account of the expense attending the re- cording, assessment and collection (the stocks and bonds constantly changing hands), and on account of the practical difficulties of the enforcement of such a method ; as where the owner of the stock or bond resides in a State other than that where the corporation is situated, or the stock or bond recorded. On the other hand, it is a simple matter to ob- tain from corporations the amount of their earnings, of their capital, or of stocks and bonds ; and the collection of the tax directly from the corporation has the merit of involving the minimum of expense. It is the absence of a rational system for the taxation of this form of property — the mere pretense of its taxation — that has given to the tax systems of the American States their well-earned opprobrium — begetters of perjury, fraud and injustice. But by the simple expedient of taxing at the source, order and justice may come out of the present chaos and injustice. We shall return to this subject later in another connection. 'See, for example, Ely, Taxation in Amencan Ciiies ; Seligman, " The Per- sonal Property Tax" (in Essays) ; and the Reports of the Tax Commissions of Massachusetts, Pennsylvania, Ohio, Michigan, Wisconsin and Colorado. 6o9] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 273 We have said that the assessment of tangible personal property and of real estate affords but little difficulty. This, however, is true only theoretically. Being tangible, it is true, indeed, that it is theoretically, nay, in a sense, practically possible to discover these forms of property; yet it is a notorious fact that both forms are very unequally assessed. Particularly is this true of tangible personal property in the form of household goods, but a small fraction of which is reached by the tax assessor. The chief difficulty of reach- ing this form of property hes in the fact that every home is felt to be sacred from the intrusions of government officials, a sentiment respected by the officials themselves. The result is that the official assessor must rely upon the tax- payer's declaration, a very unsafe criterion as we have seen. Only injustice can result from such a method. The only feasible solution would seem to be the total exemption of this form of property from taxation. And this suggestion will appear all the more rational when we consider that the purpose of taxing any form of property is to reach the in- come of which the property is but a symbol. True, house- hold goods constitute such a symbol, or index, but only in a very general way, and then only for moderate incomes. But there are other and more certain indices of income which will serve the purpose far more satisfactorily. To obtain substantial justice it is not necessary to seize upon every possible index of income ; but, as we have seen, only such as are at the same time most indicative and most easily applied. The case is quite different with real estate. This is upon the whole (though there are exceptions) a just index of in- come, and there are neither sentimental nor technical reasons against its assessment. The problem here is essentially one of the intelligence and honesty of the assessor, his ability to estimate the value of property and to withstand the 274 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [6lO temptations of bribery. Nor is this difficulty confined to real estate. Precisely the same difficulties are to be met with in the assessment of corporations, particularly railroad corporations.' In the case of real estate, it is the require- ment of most of our States that it shall be assessed to the full extent of its value, though it is not uncommon to find it assessed, even within the same city, anywhere from 40 per cent, to 75 per cent, of its value.^ Such an inequality of assessment is most unjust in its effects, being equivalent, in extreme cases, to the imposition of a tax upon some greater by 100 per cent, than the tax upon others. And, by the way, we need only to call attention to this intentional under- valuation of real estate to emphasize the gross injustice of taxing the poor widow's mortgage or bond to the full amount of her honest declaration. And yet there is a rational ground for the sixty per cent, valuation — that by decreasing the amount of the tax valuation, with a conse- quent increasing of the tax rate, there will result a tendency to check extravagant appropriations and squandering of the public funds. But whatever the basis of the assessment it should be uniform. The real difficulty, however, is to obtain an equal assessment of all property on any accepted basis, of real estate as well as of other forms of property. Yet the taxation of real estate is demanded on poHtical, economic, and ethical grounds. ' In the decennial appraisement of Ohio in 1900 the railroad property in many counties was assessed at about 12 per cent, of its value. Notably was this so in Cuyahoga county (Cleveland). This condition was made possible by a vicious system of appraisement (by county auditors) which lent itself to a system of indi- rect bribery through the grant of railroad passes to the assessors — the auditors. * Such was the fact in the appraisement of real estate in Cleveland in 1900, as the writer was reliably informed by a real estate owner who made personal inqui- ries of the different assessors. It was within the personal knowledge of the same authority that in the assessment of 1890 large owners of real estate got low assess- ments by bribing the assessors through a third party. 6ii] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 275 What, then, is the solution of the problem — i. e., of uni- form and honest assessments? The remedy lies very largely with the taxpayers themselves. For first and fore- most is the necessity of honest and efficient assessors,' with- out which any system of taxation may be made to work injustice, while with them any systems in themselves defec- tive may be made to realize substantial justice.^ But while very much depends upon the character of the assessors, the methods of assessment are also of much importance. For however honest and intelligent the assessors, there can be only a chance equality of assessment, unless there is some common basis for the determination of values and some common agreement for the percentage of valuation. What method will best accomplish the desired result we cannot stop to discuss. We may note, however, that it lies in the direction of a more centralized control of assessments, the degree of centralization being determined by the character of the property assessed : the taxing area for real estate being the township, county or city ; that for railroads and other corporations the state. There should also be fixed and uniform rules for determining values and a rigid enforce- ment of some fixed percentage of valuation. But so long as the matter rests very largely upon the judgment of in- dividual, local assessors, the pretense of justice becomes a farce. With some such system as suggested, and with. intelligent and honest assessors, a fair approximation of jus- tice may be attained. But the methods of assessment are closely allied with a system of taxation, to which let us next turn our attention. ^ See last note. ' Cf. Report of Professor Bolles in Report of Pennsylvania Revenue Commis- sion 0/1887, P' ^57- 276 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [6i2 II. The True Tax System In the preceding discussion it has been pointed out that a just system of assessment involves a direct assessment by the taxing authorities, a consequent wise selection of the kinds of properties to be taxed, and methods of assessment that shall reach all assessable property equally. Without stopping to discuss these methods in any detail it was indi- cated that they should be such as to eliminate, as far as possible, any personal factor within the same taxing political unit — eliminate, that is, the individual judgments of different assessors as well as the personal declarations of the assessed ; thus diminishing, on the one hand, bribery and corruption, and, on the other hand, deception and perjury. It was also pointed out that in the choice of taxable property three things must be considered : The indicativeness of the prop- erty as a measure of income — the ultimate source of all taxes; and the readiness with which the taxed property lends itself to equitable assessment ; and finally, that this readiness, or equality of assessment (and, we may add, of taxation), depends very largely upon the tax system; or, in other words, upon the kind of taxes and the methods of tax- ation, and the distribution of the different taxes among the different political taxing units. With, then, a wise system of taxation — a proper choice of subjects and methods, and a proper distribution — it is be- lieved that much would be accomplished in the way of re- moving the glaring absurdities and inequalities of present methods, and for the practical introduction of the principle of " equality of burden " as based upon " ability," so far, at least, as ability is measured by income. A brief considera- tion of such a system, which we must confine to the barest outline, will supplement our remarks upon assessment, and at the same time point out what be believe to be a rational system of taxation that will at once realize substantial jus- • 6i3] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 277 tice in taxation and come within the realm of the practicable — essentially conform to the ideals of justice and to the re- quirements of practical application. Let us consider, then, the outline of such a system. I . Subjects and Methods of Taxation. We have already indicated the principles that should determine the choice of subjects — i. e., of property — for taxation, and also the rela- tion which this choice bears to equitable assessments, which will appear further as we proceed. Our present purpose is to give an outline of the more important subjects for tax- ation that will realize the requirements of these principles. No attempt will be made to weigh the pros and contras of dififerent kinds of taxes. Our aim shall be positive and con- structive, rather than negative and by elimination. Yet we may again emphasize the fact that no rational system of tax- ation can contain a "general property tax" which treats alike taxes on real estate, on tangible, and on intangible property. Nor is it necessary to add to what has already been said in justification of this conviction. We shall, therefore, assume the abandonment of the " general property tax," as such, in compliance with the logic of experience and the all but universal opinion of expert testimony.' This, however, does not imply that some forms of property are to escape taxation altogether. On the contrary, so far as they are proper subjects for taxation they will be taxed equally- (at least more equally), and will be taxed in fact and not merely in name, but under a different name and by dififerent methods than those now in vogue. The system of taxes which we have in mind may, perhaps, best be outlined by a consideration of taxes on consumption, on real estate, on personal property (tangible only), on mortgages, on corporations and on inheritances; though special assessments, fees and fines should have their place * As Dunbar, Taussig, Seligman, Adams and Ely. 278 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [6 1 4 in the system. These, however, have for their purpose local improvements, special benefits, or penalties and must, there- fore, be passed over in a scheme for general taxation based upon ability.' ( I ) Taxe^ on Consumption. If it were true that all in- comes are spent in personal satisfactions and enjoyments there would be much to be said for the contention of Sir WilHam Petty: that "a man is actually and truly rich according to what he eateth, drinketh, weareth, or in any other way really and actually enjoyeth ;" and that, therefore, •' every man ought to contribute according to what he taketh to himself, and actually enjoyeth." = But such a condition of things would be true only under the circumstance that the total income was spent in this manner, a circumstance that, as a rule, would happen only with moderate incomes. Indeed, with the enormous development of savings banks and other means for making small investm.ents — stocks, bonds, etc. — it does not apply universally to even moderate incomes. And yet with moderate incomes (especially with the more moderate incomes) expenditure is a very fair index of income, and a tax on expenditure a very fair approxima- tion to justice. But such a tax would reach only a fragment of the larger incomes, and hence is objectionable as a single tax; and, besides, has the further objection that there are many technical difficulties in the way of its execution, so far as there should be an attempt to reach every possible form of consumption. But while there should be other forms of taxes to reach the parts of income that do not find their way to personal "enjoyments," a tax on consumption is a legitimate and ' For a full report of these sources of revenue see Seligman, Essays, ch. ix. For criticism of Prof. Seligman's " special assessments " and " fees," see Bastable, Public Finance, "p^. 153-6. ' letty, A Treatise of Taxes and Contributions, p. 83. 6i5] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 279 necessary part of every tax system that seeks to reach income by the indirect method, since in all cases consump- tion does afford some index of income ; in many cases a fairly perfect index. But such a tax should be applied indi- rectly, as by customs duties, taxes on manufactures and cor- porations, and taxes on real estate — lands and houses — not only to realize economy in assessments and collections and the Smithian canon of "convenience" in time of payment; but also to avoid any possible antagonisms that might arise on account of the strong popular sentiment against personal inquisitions on the part of the government, as a violation of individual liberties. Such a tax, too, lends itself very fittingly to the higher taxation of larger incomes by means of heavy taxes on articles of luxury. To carry out this pur- pose, however, would require the non-taxation of articles of necessity with a constantly increasing rate for articles of decreasing necessity. But it must be admitted that no such scientific system is possible with protective tariffs. But though it may not be possible to realize the ideal system of consumptive taxes, they should form an essential feature in any tax system ; not only for the reasons given above, but also for political reasons. For though a direct tax is important as tending to stimulate an active interest in the government, and to check extravagance in expenditures, an attempt to raise all public revenue from direct taxation would result in social revolution, or a niggardliness that would effectively cripple the government in the performance of its functions. For, however much we may philosophize about taxes, there is much truth in the statement made by Mr. Buck, of Kentucky, in the early debates in Congress on the subject of taxation: That "taxes are always disagree- able, and it is with reluctance that people consented to .pay any, except they saw advantage arising from the pay- ment of them greater than to counterbalance the evil of pay- 280 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [6i6 ing." ^ Hence the importance of supplementing direct taxes with indirect taxes, particularly in the taxing system of a na- tional government. It is not less true that the indirect tax should be supplemented by direct taxes ; in part to offset the uncertainty of the incidence of indirect taxes, in part because of their greater certainty and economy, and in part because of their direct relation to the government. Most important among these are property taxes and taxes on inheritances. We omit the income tax because of its admitted impractica- bility. Let us briefly consider the property and inheritance taxes viewed as essential parts of a good tax system. (2) Taxation of Real Estate. The taxation of real estate is theoretically simple enough. It is one of the oldest, as well as the most universal, of all taxes. Indeed, the fact that real estate is a source of income, cannot be hidden from the assessor, and has an immediate relation to and dependence upon the expenditures of government, makes it a peculiarly fitting subject for taxation. And yet, as we have seen, under present systems there is no guaranty of an equality of assess- ments and of burdens, either between individuals or between different political units. Nor, for the former inequality, is there any effective remedy other than the adoption of a uniform basis for assessments, a larger use of ofificial records — deeds, bequests, mortgages, etc. — and the choice of men of char- acter and intelligence for assessors ; while the remedy for the latter inequality — that between different political units — is to be found very largely in an entire rearrangement and readjustment of the tax system, on the basis of greater fiscal independence of the different political divisions within the same system of government — a question which will come up for consideration later. Upon the justice of levying upon real estate for purposes ^Annals of Conp'ess, 4th Cong., 2d Sess., p. 1862. Cf. also speech of Mr. Richardson, of Tennessee, 14th Cong., ist Sess., p. 84. 6l7] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 281 of public revenue there is" no difference of opinion. It con- forms to the ideal of taxation according to ability, since the value of real estate is determined very largely by its income- producing power, if we omit the exceptional cases of the speculative holding of land. With this exception, it is in the main true that land, buildings and machinery, and dwelling houses have their value fairly represented in the capitalized amount of the income derived from them. Hence, omitting as we do in the present discussion the question of progres- sive and differential rates, a tax based upon the valuation of such forms of property is a fair approximation of a tax based upon the derived income, and so likewise a fair approxima- tion of justice. That such taxes may and do become, in part at least, taxes upon consumption does not lessen their effectiveness or their justice. With a rational and stable system of taxation, the burden will adjust itself fairly in the long run. To this end, however, it is important that other forms of property should be reached. (3) Taxation of Personal Property. A sound and just system of taxation must include taxes whose ultimate inci- dence shall bear upon productive personalty, as well as those that bear upon productive realty. To reach personal in- comes it may be necessary, also, to tax some forms of un- productive personalty ; unproductive, that is, to the con- sumer in the sense that Adam Smith used the term. In- deed, such taxes are taxes upon consumption, which have already been sufficiently considered. Yet we may perhaps add, that to us there is some question whether household goods should not be exempted from taxation ; not only be- cause they are at best but very roughly indicative of income, but because such a tax must always be upon but a nominal part of the total amount, and that, too, in very unequal por- tions ; must, that is, so long as public sentiment remains as it is concerning the sacredness and privacy of the home. 282 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [6i8 Moreover, there is little of a scientific character in a system of taxation that places unproductive personalty, which is only roughly indicative of income, upon exactly the same basis as productive property. On the other hand, such forms of tangible personalty as farming implements and live stock may well be included in the tax system, not only as indicative of income but as also productive of income; while they are at the same time easily assessable ; in fact, for the reasons just given, tangible person- alty in general should be included in any well rounded sys- tem of taxation, and taxed in the same direct manner as realty. The same cannot be said of intangible personalty. As already sufficiently shown, every attempt of this nature leads to the grossest inequalities (to say nothing of perjur- ies), while its enforcement is a practical impossibility; this impossibility, indeed, being the occasion of the inequalities. Some other method than the direct one must, therefore, be found for reaching the income that has its source in this form of property ; or, rather in the forms of property that stand back of and are represented by the intangible forms — mortgages, stocks, bonds, etc. Such a method, and indeed the only practicable method, is to be found in the taxation of this class of income at its source. In this way alone can evasion be avoided and the burden equitably distributed. As the form of property under consideration is most largely represented by mortgages and by stocks and bonds, we may consider briefly the best method of taxing these at their source, which will indicate the true method of taxing the in- come from all forms of intangible personal property. (4) Taxatio7i of Mortgages. The proper method of tax- ing mortgages has, perhaps, been sufficiently indicated in our discussion of methods of assessment. Either the real estate, which is represented by the mortgage and is the source of its income, should alone be taxed, leaving mort- 6l9] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 283 gagor and mortgagee to make the proper adjustment of interest; or, if the mortgage is taxed, the tax should be based upon a compulsory court record, similar to the re- cording of deeds. At the same time, the amount of the mortgage should be deducted from the value of the real estate that is back of it, according to some such methods as those in vogue in Massachusetts and California/ There is but one source of income, and therefore but one source of ability. Hence, to tax both the land and the mortgage is to inflict the patent injustice of a double taxation on that part of the income from land that goes to pay the interest of the mortgage. The better method would seem to be to tax the land and exempt the mortgage, since the land is the direct source of the tax-paying power. Certain it is, at any rate, that the present methods of taxing mortgages are open to so many possibilities of evasion that only the most flagrant inequalities can result, the amount of the mortgages taxed being directly proportional to the sensitiveness of the con- sciences of the mortgage holders. (5) Taxation of Corporations. A still more important form of intangible personalty is to be found in corporate stocks and bonds, whose income-producing power is to be found in the corporation. In fact, the net earnings of cor- porations are, in the main, distributed to the holders of these stocks and bonds. If, then, we levy a tax upon the net earnings of a corporation, we thereby impose a tax upon the incomes of its stocks and bonds at their source. The ease with which the imposition of such a tax may be effected, and the unquestioned impossibility of reaching this class of income by the direct method, make the method of taxing at the source the only rational and scientific method of taxing income of this character. 'See Report of Massachusetts Tax Commission, 1897, P- 7> ^nd Plehn, The General Properly Tax in California (Economic Studies of Am, Econ. Ass.), pp. 126-7 ^^^ *48' 284 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [620 The principle of taxing incomes at their source is now very generally recognized by economists to be the only sound principle of public finance. This is done in the case of real estate, and it is believed that the same principle should be applied in the taxation of intangible personalty. Not only is this the most practicable and most effective method, but it is the most economic, entails the least incon- veniences, and is the most equitable in its results. By elimin- ating the intangible forms of property and the personal equation in assessments, evasions would become practically impossible; while by reaching the whole income there is secured a uniformity in the distribution of the tax burden. And since such a tax necessarily bears upon individual in- comes, it meets the ethical requirement of the imposition of a tax upon the source of ability. Granted, then, the principle of taxing the incomes from stocks and bonds at their soujce, and that individual tax ability — so far as conditioned by such holdings — is reflected in the corporate ability — i. e., in the corporate net income — the question arises : How, or in what manner, may this cor- porate ability be most effectively and most efificiently reached? Our answer to this question must be very brief, and somewhat dogmatic. The problem of the taxation of corporations is too large and too complex to be treated with any fulness in the closing chapter of a treatise on the prin- ciples of justice in taxation.' Thirteen different methods are given by Professor Selig- man for taxing corporations.' These are reduced to three by Professor Adams : as based upon property, upon the volume of business, or upon earnings.^ Both, however, ^ For a thorough treatment of the subject see Seligman, " Taxation of Corpora- tions," Essays, ch. 6, 7 and 8. For an excellent brief statement see H. C. Adams, Public Fifiatice, pp, 446-466. * Seligman, op, cit., pp. 177-9. ' Adams, op. cit., p. 454. 62l] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 285 agree that the true measure of corporate ability is to be found in the net income of the corporation ; and it must be evident that there can be no other standard. The limitation made by Professor Adams in the case of railroads : that the tax should be based upon the net "income from operation," is important only in calling attention to the fact that double taxation should be avoided in the case of leased corpora- tions.' Undoubtedly, if the leased corporation is taxed, the basis of a corporation tax should be the " earnings from operation; " but if only the operating companies are taxed, the basis of the tax should be based upon the total net in- come. In any case the taxable net income should include the gross earnings, minus operating expenses ; but not deducting the outlay for interest, rent, taxes, or improve- ments.^ Accepting, then, corporate net income — not the net in- come to stockholders and bondholders — as the true basis of corporation taxes, it ddes not follow that the desired end can be reached best, in all cases, by imposing the tax directly upon the net income. Whether or not this is the best method must depend upon the practical possibility of uniform and fixed rules of accounting. But according to Professor Adams,^ such a system of accounting is prac- ticable. We may, therefore, accept the net income basis as, upon the whole, afTording both the best theoretical and best practical basis for corporate taxation. But if in any parti- cular case such a method is not practicable, we must agree with Professor Seligman that a tax based upon the market value of stocks and bonds will most nearly realize the ends of justice, being, besides, " certain and simple of enforce- ment."'* It is only, or chiefly, because the market values of stocks and bonds are not always determined by their net ' Adams, ii>id., pp. 460-1. C/. Seligman, Essays, p. 199. « C/. ibid., p. 461. ' Ibid. * Essays, p. 212. 286 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [622 incomes, that this method of taxing corporations is not al- ways the most just, as it is the most simple. The correct determination of the basis of assessment, however, is by no means the least difficult problem in the taxation of corporations. There would, indeed, be little difficulty if the tax were aimed at the corporation per se, or if stockholders and bondholders lived wholly within the tax area of the corporation. But from our present view-point, the subject of the tax is not the corporation, but its indi- vidual stockholders and bondholders ; who, moreover, are scattered throughout various areas of taxation. Yet theoret- ically, at least, the problem is easy of solution. For all that is necessary is that there should be, among the different commonwealths concerned, a uniformity in the methods of taxation, based upon a common agreement respecting the taxation of resident holders of stocks and bonds of foreign corporations, and of foreign holders of the stocks and bonds of domestic corporations. The only ethical or logical basis for such agreement is, that each commonwealth should tax only such portion of the net profits as are earned within its borders ; this portion being determined, for practical reasons, on the basis of mile- age, gross earnings, amount of business, or capital within the commonwealth, according to the nature of the industry. In other words, the net income taxed within a given com- monwealth should bear the same proportion to the total net income that the mileage, gross earnings, etc., within the commonwealth bears to the total mileage, or gross earnings, etc. The assumption here is, that the net income within any area is proportional to the mileage, earnings, business or capital within the same area; and if the choice of these methods is wisely made, according to the character of the corporation, substantial justice will be attained, though only if there is uniformity throughout all of the commonwealths. 623] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 287 Such, in brief, is the ideal of corporate taxation, as a means of reaching the individual abilities of stockholders and bondholders. Practical obstacles in the way of state consti- tutions, and the uncertainties of " politics," do not, however, promise a speedy realization. Nor does this doubt grow less when we contemplate the fact that not one of the American States has ever adopted the recommendations of its various expert Tax Commissions. Nevertheless, the practice in some of the states is evidence of a tendency in the right direction.' But for some time, at least, we shall have to put up with the injustice of double taxation; an injustice that is, perhaps, very largely nullified in the fact of extensive eva- sions under present methods of taxing stocks and bonds. (6) Taxation of Inheritances. Concerning the inherit- ance tax we may be very brief. It is now very generally justified and very generally adopted. We may consider it from two points of view : That of the decedent and that of the heir. Viewed with respect to the ability of the former, a taSnipon the inheritance must find its justification in the assumption that past taxes have been evaded, but have held a permanent lien upon the property. While there is much ground for this theory,^ it applies only to personal property, and even then is but the crudest approximation to justice, since the amount of the evasion is an incalculable quantity .3 The more correct point of view, however, is undoubtedly that of the heir, or legatee. And from this viewpoint the justice of the tax is to be found in the increased ability aris- ing from the inheritance, or legacy. According to both 1 For examples and a fuller discussion of the interstate taxation of corporations, see Seligman, Essays, pp. 223-254. * A lady in New York, the sole heir to her father's estate, told the writer that her father never paid a personal property tax, though at the time of his death he held stock in ten different banks. ' Cf. Seligman, Essays, p. 131. 288 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [624 Professor Seligman and Doctor West, this ability arises from the fact that the inheritance should be regarded as an " acci- dental income " — measuring ability like other incomes — and the tax as an "accidental income" tax.^ This is no doubt the true attitude to take in the case of small inheritances that are spent in the manner of regular incomes. But to us the argument is not so evident with respect to the inheritance of productive property, from which there is the enjoyment of only the annual income. From the viewpoint of income, the ability of the heir is increased, practically at least, only by the amount of the increase of his annual income ; and, theo- retically, this increased ability should be reached by pro- gressive rates, if not also with differential rates on account of the source. Certainly, from the viewpoint of the govern- ment, there has been no increase of social ability, because no increase of social income ; but only a transference from decedent to heir. True, there is a sense in which the whole inheritance may be regarded as a gratuitous and "accidental" income, there- fore increasing by its full amount the ability of the heir. If this is the correct view, then, logically and justly, this income should be treated like other incomes of the same class. If this is the only basis and justification of the tax, there should be the same principle of rates that is applied to other incomes, no allowance being made for degrees of relation- ship. But this is seldom advocated in theory, and is nowhere applied in practice. If, indeed, this theory be true, then are the existing arbitrary rates and distinctions of relationship both illogical and unjust. The fact that they are both justi- fied and practiced is evidence that the " accidental income " theory is, at least, not the only consideration in the inherit- ance tax. The theory at least assumes that the true tax prin- ciple should here be deviated from on grounds of policy or * Seligman, Essays, p. 132, and West, Tke Inheritance Tax, p. 118. 62 5] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 289 sentiment. Whatever truth, therefore, there may be in this theory of the inheritance tax, it is not a theory that permits of logical application in practice. It needs, too, to be sup- plemented by other considerations. We shall not attempt, however, to discuss the various theories of the inheritance tax — cost of service, value of ser- vice, co-heirship, escheat, etc. All of them, as Dr. West says, contain some element of truth, and therefore to that extent afford some justification for the tax. Not only is this tax justified on theoretical grounds, but it has also the prac- tical merit of being difficult to evade, and of occasioning little disturbance of industry ; besides being less oppressive and less reluctantly paid than most other taxes. Viewed in all of its aspects it forms a necessary adjunct to any scientific system of taxation. We cannot, indeed, quite agree with the implication in the statement of Dr. West that " no tax is better adapted to replace the antiquated personal property tax," ' since this implies substitution. The true substitute for these antiquated taxes lies, as we have seen, in the direction of a tax on corporations, though the inheritance tax (on per- sonal property) may well be used as supplementary to the corporation taxes. In the above outline of a system of taxation no attempt has been made to exhaust every legitimate source of public revenue, but only to indicate the main features of a scientific system that will most nearly conform to the theoretical prin- ciples of justice — a tax based upon ability, so far as this ability is measured by income. We have omitted a discus- sion of rates, because, as we have said, we believe that undfer the prevailing sentiment on this subject this is not, in this country at least, a practical question, though without the progressive rates the highest ideals of justice in taxation must remain unattainable. Of the principle of exemptions 'West, op.cit.,^. 132. 290 JUSTICE IN TAXATION 626 we need only to say that it is fairly well realized in practice, though, as previously pointed out, we beheve that there should be further extensions of the principle, at least in some cases, in order to correspond to the progressively higher standards of living. There is, however, another question of great practical importance, which, because of its immediate bearing upon the execution of such a system as that outlined above, is, indeed, an essential requisite to such a system, and therefore should constitute a vital part of it. I refer to the separation of state and local taxes, which let us in conclusion briefly consider. 2. State and Local Taxation. The importance of the separation of national, state, and local taxation is another of those financial questions upon which there is now very gen- eral agreement.' This granted, the question arises: On what basis should the distribution of taxes be made? Ac- cording to Professor Bastable it cannot be made on the ground of a difTerence of governmental duties, since there is no correlation between these duties and tax systems. Hence the distribution must be made on financial and economic grounds." This is, no doubt, in part true. But in this country, at least, it should be modified by the more correct view of Professor Adams : That " a government should select for purposes of taxation those industries with which it holds some fundamental or constitutional relations." 3 In other words, while financial and economic conditions are im- portant factors in determining the political distribution of taxes, the governmental relation to the industry taxed is, perhaps, of prime consideration. Indeed, it is this relation that very largely determines the financial conditions. The principle may be best illustrated by calling attention to the ' For a very good treatment of this question see Adams, Public Finance, ch. 7. Cf. also Bastable, Public Finance, iii, 6. * Bastable, op. cit.. pp. 367-8. 3 Adams, op. cil., p. 493. 627] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 29 1 more important taxes that should be assigned to national, State and local revenue. [i) Natio7ial Taxes. The revenue system of our national government is so thoroughly established that there could be only a speculative interest in a discussion of possible reforms. At the very outset the policy was adopted of relying solely upon indirect taxes, leaving all direct taxes for the States. At first it was thought that sufficient revenue could be ob- tained from customs duties, but it was very soon learned that they would be inadequate, and so excise duties were added. Only twice have direct taxes been resorted to, and with the exception of war periods customs and excises (on spirits, malt liquors and tobacco) have been, and promise long to remain, the chief source of national revenue. Nor is this without much reason. For, as Professor Adams shows, not only do they meet his requirement in the governmental selection of taxes, but they also give realization to the im- portant fiscal principle of permanence of government revenue. To realize the other important principle — that of elasticity — Professor Adams would have a national tax on interstate commerce. However desirable such a tax may be, there would seem to be little chance of its adoption in the near future. The national system of indirect taxes is not without other important merits. For, however desirable it may be, from a theoretical point of view, .that the citizen should pay a direct tax, in order to emphasize his responsibility to the government and make him watchful over expenditures, there can be no doubt, as we have seen, but that a dependency upon a direct tax would greatly cripple the efficiency of the government. Moreover, the rather indirect relation of the citizen to the national government, at least his remoteness from its opera- tions, goes far to justify the indirect tax for national pur- poses. Again, if we suppose the tax to retain anything of 292 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [628 permanency it will be found, in the long run, fairly to dis- tribute the burden according to ability; so far, at least, as ability is determined by consumption. (2) State Taxes. For the same reason that customs duties and excise taxes were assigned to national revenue — that of the peculiar relations of the industry taxed to the government — there should be assigned to State revenue the taxation of corporations and quasi-public monopolies. Be- ing dependent upon, and under the regulations of, the State governments, there is a peculiar fitness in their taxation for the purposes of State revenue. Such a tax would be diffi- cult to evade, and would have the fiscal importance of being easily and economically collected. At the same time it would meet the requirements of permanence and elasticity. Moreover, under conditions similar to those assumed in the case of customs and excises, there would be a fair distribu- tion of the burden. To these taxes might also be added the inheritance tax. Certainly, upon the principles set forth above, the inheritance tax does not properly belong to the system of national taxes. So far as the inheritance tax is regarded as a fee for cost or value of service in the transference of property, it belongs more properly to county taxes ; but so far as regarded on the principle of escheat, of co-heirship, or of guaranteeing the right of inheritance, it is very properly a State tax. As grounded upon the idea of compensation or of ability, it should be distributed between State and local governments. On the ground of the dependence of the inheritance upon, and its control and protection by, the government, the in- heritance tax belongs, again, more properly to the system of State taxes. On fiscal and economic grounds there is also reason for this disposition of the inheritance tax. Upon the whole, the inheritance tax should go into the State revenue, except, perhaps, such portion as might be necessary for the 629] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 293 probate fees, or other expenses incidental to the conveyance. But we fail to see any good reason why this tax should be assigned to any specific purpose, such as State education, as suggested by Professor Adams.' With these two sources it is beheved that ample revenue would be supplied for all of the necessary expenses of the State governments. As Dr. West says: "The experience of New York with the inheritance tax and the experience of a number of States with corporate taxes show that by these two methods of taxation alone most, if not all of the State governments, could pay all of their expenses, leaving all taxes on property to local political divisions." =" (3) Local Taxes. We have left, then, for local taxation, land, houses, manufacturing plants and real estate generally ; also tangible personal property and municipal licenses and franchises. Since county expenses are mainly devoted to the improvement of roads and bridges, which add materially to the value of the surrounding lands, it is very fitting that a land tax should constitute the chief source of county revenue. For township purposes there is the tangible per- sonalty and real estate, including the real estate of corpora- tions. While for municipal expenses we have, in addition to the property taxes of townships, municipal licenses and franchises— such as those of street railways, water works, lighting plants, etc. A special justification for this assign- ment of local taxes is not needed, since it is directly in- volved in the principles of distribution of national and state taxes. If further justification were needed it might, perhaps, be found in the fact that in local taxation, as distinct from national or state taxation, there is some justi- fication in the application of the benefit principle as a basis of taxation. It may be added, too, that with such a system of local taxes, where each political unit is fiscally inde- 1 o/. a/., p. 505. ^C?/.«V.,p. 132. 294 JUSTICE IN TAXATION [630 pendent, there will be an end to the evil of political units shifting their burdens upon each other by undervaluations. The above outline of what is conceived to be a rational system for the political distribution of taxes, it must be admitted, is not wholly free from arbitrariness. For in spite of the more or less clearly marked political divisions, the parts of our federal system are so intimately connected, and so closely interdependent, that the relationship of the citizen to one of the units involves his relationship to each higher and lower unit in the system. There is, nevertheless, a difiference that is substantial enough for forming a legitimate basis for a political division of taxes. If our division is in contradiction with any of our previous principles, it is with that principle which declares that ability is the only true basis of taxation, for the division is apparently very largely based upon the principle of benefits. As to local taxation, it is admitted that there is some validity in the benefit prin- ciple. But carefully examined it will be seen that the con- tradiction is little more than an apparent one. There can be no doubt but that it is the fundamental thought in taxation that every individual should contribute towards the support of the political units with which he stands in some direct relation, and should contribute accord- ing to his ability. That such a result would follow from such a system of taxation as that outlined in the present chapter, taken in connection with its political distribution, we believe that a careful analysis of probable results would make sufficiently clear. But even though it may not give realization to theoretical principles in every particular, it offers so many practical advantages — realizing uniformity and equality, as well as having political, economic and fiscal advantages — that it may well be considered as offering the highest form of the practical ideal; at the same time that it conforms substantially to the theoretical ideal. The effect 631] PRACTICAL JUSTICE IN TAXATION 295 of such a system upon the ehmination of those personal and political factors that are the source of so much inequality — fraud, corruption, undervaluations, evasions, etc. — would go far to promote the conditions of an ideal equality, the ends of a complete justice. Finally, there are hopeful signs that such a system is not always to remain a mere fiscal ideal. The abuses and in- equalities of present methods are becoming so flagrant that political parties are being forced to take cognizance of them and to consider remedies for the solution of the evil.' normal schools in the United States and other countries. The second group hold that the most effective results are Nevertheless, the ideal is far from attainment. This is made inevitable on account of the great number of our states, their varied economic conditions, and the natural conserva- tism of political parties. But until some such system as that outlined in the present chapter is put into practice, we can hope for only makeshift Teforms. With such a system once in operation we shall, at least, have taken a long step toward realizing the ideal ends of justice in taxation, and shall have attained a close approximation to justice, which is all that can be hoped for in human affairs. ^ In the State campaign in Ohio, in the fall of 1901, Mr. Tom L. Johnson, in behalf of the Democratic party, made the issue upon the equalization of taxes. The present writer took occasion to write a letter for a Cleveland paper, briefly advocating the system set forth in this chapter. In reply, letters were received from the leader of the Republican party and from Mr. Johnson, while a Demo- cratic candidate for the legislature made a public reply. In every case it was con- tended that the system advocated in my letter was essentially the same as that for which they stood committed. In the next legislature the Democratic party did attempt to carry out some tax reforms along these lines, but their efforts were negatived by the Republican majority. BIBLIOGi^APHY Adams, II. C. Public Finance. New York, 1898. Adams, H. C. Public Debts. New York, 1892. Aristotle. Politics. Aristotle. Nichomachean Ethics. Baer, C. Z' Avere e V Impost a. Roma, 1872. Bastable, C. F. Public Finance. London, 1895. Bastiat, F. Ce qu' on voit et ce qu' on ne voit pas. Oeuvres. Paris, 1863, Bastiat, F. Sophismes ilconomiques. Oeuvres, 4th ed. Paris, 1863. Block, M. Les Progres de la Science iconomique. 2 vols. Paris, 1890. Bluntschli, J. K. Theory of the State. Tr. London, 1895. Bockh, A. The Public Economy 0/ Athens. Tr., 2 vols. Boston, 1857. Burgess, W. Political Science and Constitutional Law. Boston and London, 1898. Cherbuliez, A. E. Precis de la Science Aconomique. Paris, 1862. Cohn, G. The Science of Finance. Tr. Chicago, 1895. Cooley, T. Law of Taxation. 2d ed. Chicago, 1886. Cossa, L. Primi Elementi di Scienza delle Finanzt. 4th ed. Milan, 1887. Courcelle-Seneuil, J. G. Traite d' Aconomie Politique. 2 vols., 2d ed. Paris, 1867. Coulanges, F. The Origin of Property in Land. Tr. London, 1891. Davenant, C. Essay on the Ways and Means of Supplying the War. 1695. Denis, H. Z' Impot. Bruxelles, 1889. De Parieu, F. E. Traite des Ittip&ts. 4 vols., 2d ed. Paris, 1866-67. Edgeworth, F. Y. " The Pure Theory of Taxation." Economic Journal. Vol. 7. Ely, R. T. Taxation in American States and Cities. New York, 1888. Fairbanks, A. Introduction to Sociology. New York, 1896. Flora, F. Manuale di Scienza delle Finanze. Livorno, 1893. Flora, F. " II Concetto della Economia Finanziaria." Rassegna di Scienti Sod' alee Politiche. Aug., 1889. Gamier, J. Traite des Finances. Paris, 1885. George, H. Progress and Poverty. New York, 1879. Giddings, F. 11. The Principles of Sociology. New York, 1896. Giovanelli, G. Della Scienza Finanziaria, Roma, 1877. Girardin, E. de. De P Impot. Paris, 1852. Green, T. H. Prolegomena to Ethics, Oxford, 1884. 296 [632 633] BIBLIOGRAPHY 297 Green, T. H. Political Obligations. London, 1895. Grotius. De Jure Belli ac Pads. 1625. Held, A. Die Einkommensteuer. Bonn, 1872. Helferich, I. A. R. " Allgemeine Steuerlehre." In Schonberg's Handbuch der Politischen Oekonomie. Tubingen, 1885. Hobbes, T, The Leviathan. Molesworth's edition. London, 1841. Hobbes, T. De Corpore Politico. Hobbes, T. Philosophical Rudiments concerning Government and Society. Hobson, J. Economics of Distribution. New York, 1900. Hock, C. von. Die bffentlichen Abgaben und Schulden. Stuttgart, 1863. Hume, D. Essay on Taxation. Kaizl, T. Die Lehre von der Ueberwahung der Steuern. Leipzig, 1882. Konig, G. Un Nouvel Impot sur le Revenu. 2d ed. Paris, 1887. Leroy-Beaulieu, P. Traite de la Science des Pmances, 2 vols. Paris, 1892. Lilly, W. S. First Principles in Politics. New York, 1899. Locke, J. Civil Government. Locke, J. Interest. Works, vol. iv, ed. 1824. , Marshall, A. Principles of Political Economy. London, 1 89 1. Marzano, F. Compendia di Scienza delle Finanze. Torino, 1887. Mazzola, U. I Dati Scientifici delta Finanta Publico. Roma, 1890. McCuUoch, J. R. Taxation and Funding. 2d ed. London, 1852. McLane, W. M. " The Ethical ^asis of Taxation." Andover Review. Dec, 1892. Menier, A. Z' Impot sur le Capital. Paris, 1874. Meyer, R. Die Principien der gerechten Besteuerung. Berlin, 1884. Mill, J. S. Political Economy. London, 1848. Mill, J. S. Utilitarianism. London, 1862. Mill, J. S. On Liberty. London, 1859. Mirabeau, V. de R. Theorie de V Impot. Paris, 1761. Mirabeau, H. G. " Sur 1' Egalite des Contributions." Speech in National Assembly, Oct. 7, 1 789. Mirabeau, H. G. Addresse aux Franfais sur la Contribution Patriotique. 1789. Montesquieu, M . de S. Esprit des Lois. 1 748. Murhard, K. Theorie und Politik der Besteuerung. Gottingen, 1834. Neumann, F. J. Progressive Einkommensteuer. Leipzig, 1874. Neumann, F. J. Die Steuern und das bffentliche Inter esse. Leipzig, 1887. Nevvcomb, S. Principles of Political Economy. New York, 1886. Pantaleoni, M. Teoria delta Pressione Tributario. Roma, 1882. Pareto, V. " Parliamentary Government in Italy." Political Science Quarterly. Vol. viii, 1893. Perry, A. L. Political Economy. New York, 1 874. Pescatore, M. La Logica delle Imposte. Torino, 1867. Petty, Sir Wm. A Treatise of Taxes and Contributions. 1667. Plehn, C. C. Public Finance. New York, 1896. 298 BIBLIOGRAPHY [634 Plehn, C. C. "The General Property Tax in California" (Am, Econ. Assoc, Economic Studies, Vol, II, No, 3). Plato. Republic. Post, L. F, The Single Tax. Proudhon, P. J. Theorie de V ImpSt, Oeuvres, v. 15. Bruxelles, 1845, Proudhon, P. J. Les Contradictions Economiques. 1845, Quesnay, F. Maximes Generales. Paris, 1758. Quesnay, F. Dest>otisme de la Chine. Paris, 1767, Quesnay, F. Le Revenu Piiblique, Oeuvres. Francfort S. M., 1888. Rameri, L. " Per la Proportionalita delle Imposte," Rassegna di Scienzi Sociali e Politiche, Oct., 1891. Ricardo, D, Works. McCuUoch's Edition, London, 1888, Ricca-Salerno, J, Mantiale di Scienza delle Finanze. Firenze, 1888, Ritchie, D. G, Principles of State Interference. London, 1897, Roscher, Wm, System der Finanzwissenschaft. Stuttgart, 1894. Ross, E. A, " A New Canon of Taxation." Political Science Quarterly, Vol. 7, Rousseau, J. J. Contrat Social. 1762, Royer, C, A, Theorie de /' Impbl. 2 vols, Paris, 1 864, Say, J, B. Political Economy. American Edition. Philadelphia, 1836, Say, L. La Question des Impots. 2 vols, 1 886, Sax, E. Grundlegung der theoretischen Staatswirthschaft. Wien, 1887, Sax, E. " Die Progressivsteuer," Zeitschrift filr Volkswirthsckaft, Socialpolitik und Verwaltung. Erster Band: i Heft., 1892. Schaffle, A, E, F. Grundsatze der Steuerpolitik. Tiibingen, 1880. Schaffle, A. E. F, " Mensch und Gut," Deutsche Vierteljahrschrift, 1 861, 4 Heft. Seligman, E, R. A, Essays in Taxation. New York, 1895, Seligman, E, R. A, Progressive Taxation. Baltimore, 1894, Seligman, E, R, A, Shifting and Incidence of Taxation. Baltimore, 1892, Seligman, E, R, A, " Social Elements in the Theory of Value." Quarterly jfournal of Economics, vol. xv. Senior, N. W. Political Economy. Shearman, T. G. Natural Taxation. New York, 1898. Sidgwick, H, Principles of Political Economy. London, 1887, Sidgwick, H. History of Ethics. London, 1886, Sismondi, S, de. Nouveaux Principes d^ Aconomie Politique. Paris, 1819, Single Tax Discussion. Social Science Association, Saratoga, 1894. Smith, A, Wealth of Nations (Rogers' Edition), 2 vols. 1880. Smith, E, P, Political Economy. Spencer, H, Principles of Sociology. Vol. I. New York, 1884. Spencer, H, Social Statics (Abridged and Revised), New York, 1897. Spencer, H. Data of Ethics. New York, 1884. Spencer, H. Justice. New York, 1895. Taylor, F. M. Right oj the State to Be, Thiers, A, De la Proprieti. Paris, 1848, 635] BIBLIOGRAPHY 299 Thiers, A. Impai sur le Luxe et le Revenu. Tucker, B.R. Instead of a Book. 2d ed. New York, 1897. Turgot, A. R. J. Travaux Divers concernant les Impositions. Works, vol. iv. Paris, 1808. Umpfenbach, K. Lehrbuch der Finanzwissenschaft. 2d ed. Stuttgart, 1887. Vauban, M. de. Le Dime Royal. 1707. Vocke, W. Die Abgaben, Auflagen und die Steuern. Stuttgart, 1887. Volta.'R. dalla. " L' Imposta Progressiva dal Punti di Vista Teorica." Ras- segna di Scienzi Sociali e Politiche. Oct. and Nov., 1893. Wagner, A. Finanzwissenschaft. 3 vols. Leipzig, 1 883-1 898. Walker, F. A. Political Economy. New York, 1888. Walker, F. A. " The Bases of Taxation." Political Science Quarterly, vol. 3. Walras, L. Theorie de V Impot. Paris, 1861. West, M. The Inheritance Tax. New York, 1893. Wieser, F. von. Natural Value. Tr. London, 1893. Zorh, A. La Scienza dei Tributi. Bologna, 1889. REPORTS. Report of English Income Tax Commission. 1852. Report of Special Committee on Taxation of Boston Executive Business Asso- ciation. 1889. Report of Tax Commission of Pennsylvania. 1890. Report of Tax Commission of Ohio. 1893. Report of Tax Commissio7t of Massachtisetts. 1897. Report of Revenue Commission of Colorado. 1901. Report of State Tax Commission of Michigan. 1901. Report of Tax Comtnission of Wisconsin. 1901. ERRATA. Page 97, Note i, for 73 read 86. Note 2, for 75 read Page 104, Note 3, for 88 read loi. Page 134, Note i, for 43 read 56. Page 140, Note 2, for 92 read 104. Page 141, Note 2, for 53 read 66, note 2. Page 160, Note i, for 63 read 77. Page 161, Note i, for 109 read 121. Page 174, Note I, for 143 read 155. VITA The writer of the following monograph received his pre- paratory and collegiate education at Antioch College, from which institution he was graduated in 1879. From the same college he received the degree A. M. in 1884. In 1885 he went to the University of Michigan, taking two years of post- graduate work at that institution. The major work consisted of Philosophy and Ethics, and was taken under Professors Morris and Dewey. The two minors were Economics and Pedagogy, the former being under Professor Adams and the latter under Professor Payne, In the fall of 1890 the writer entered the School of Political Science in Columbia University and pursued two years of post- graduate work in that department of the University. The major study at Columbia was Finance, and the two minors Social Science and Administrative Law. The major work was under the direction of Professor Seligman, the minors under the direction of Professors Mayo-Smith, Giddings, and Goodnow. During the second year at Columbia the writer held. a Seligman Scholarship in Economics, and at the end of the second year was given a University Fellowship in Finance for the year 1892-3. In the fall of 1892 he received the appoint- ment of Assistant in Economics and thereupon resigned the University Fellowship. The position of Assistant in Eco- nomics was held for two years. In 1894 the writer went to Western Reserve University, Cleveland, Ohio, as Associate Professor of Political and Social Science. In 1902 he was elected as acting executive of Antioch College, Yellow Springs, 301 302 VITA Ohio, under the title of Dean of Antioch College, having also the Professorship of Philosophy and of Political and Social Science. The previous publications of the author of this Monograph are the following : "The Significance of the Individual," published in Seed Time, Oct., 1893 — a publication of the London Fabian Society. Two articles on "Tax Reform " pubhshed in the Cleveland Plain Dealer, Oct., 1901. Reviews in the Political Science Quarterly, viz. : Vol. VI, No. 2 : Crime and Its Causes, by William D. Morrison ; The Elmira Re- formatory, by Alexander Winter; The Death Penalty, by Andrew J. Palm. Vol. VII, No. 2 : Trade Unionism, New and Old, by George Howells ; Problems of Poverty, by John Hobson. Vol. VIII, No. 4 : La Riduzione delle Ore di Lavoro e i suoi Effetti Economici, by Riccardo dalla Volta ; La Legislation Internationale du Travail, by Paul Boilley ; Guide Pratique pour I'Application de la Participation aux Benefices, by Charles Robert. Vol. IX, No. I : Teoria della Trasformazione dei Capitali, by Camillo Supino. Vol. XIII, No. 2 : La Questione dei Negri, by Gennaro Mondaini. Vol. XIV, No. 2 : Saggi di Economia e Finanze, by A. de Viti de Marco. Vol. XV, No. 4 : La Teoria del Salario, by G. Ricca-Salerno. ^ J /> Lij*.^! UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY This book is DUE on the last date stamped below. Fine schedule: 25 cents on first day overdue 50 cents on fourth day overdue One dollar on seventh day overdue. JoH 7 H'^t LD 21-100m-12,'46(A2012sl6)4120 YC ?3'^F^4 / HJS305 We-s'toK