»im*^i*^ vv w r /V ^//'/'/.'•■c<.y/:/'y>'//.':: 1^1.. \' £ LECTURES ON GEEMAN THOUGHT LONDON : PBINTED BY SP0TTI8W00DB AND CO., NEW-STRKET SQTIARH AND PAEIilAMKNT STEEET ir-iio ^"^ '■'■• SIX LECTUEES ON THE HISTORY OF GERMAN THOUGHT From the SEVEN YEARS' WAR to GOETHE'S DEATH DEUVERED AT THE ROYAL INSTITUTION OF GREAT BRITAIN May & June 1879 BY KARL HILLEBRAND LONDON LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO. 1880 All rights reserved rJ iLX ^"^ LIBRARY ^ / UNIVERSITY OF CATJFORNW SANTA BARBARA ^r PEEFACE. Readers acquainted with German, who may wish to follow up the necessarily brief indications of the present lectures, will find fm^ther information in the numerous histories of German civilisation, literature, and philosophy, more especially in the works of Biedermann and G. Frejrtag on the first subject, of Jos. Hillebrand and H. Hettner on the second, of E. Zeller on the third. In the following pages the lecturer has kept almost exclusively to the works of the great German writers themselves and to the follow- ing, amongst many hundred, special works : Dieterich on Kant, Haym on Herder, Helmholtz on Goethe as a naturalist, Dilthey on Schleiermacher, H. Hettner and Haym on the romantic school. No fault, the author hopes, will be found with him for having reproduced here and there the conclusions of his own earher essays on Winckelmann, Wieland, Lessing, Herder, W. von Humboldt, Caroline Schlegel, H. Heine, Gervinus, L. Hoensser, the Berlin Society from 1789 to 1815, the German Unity Question from 1815 to 1866, the history of classical philology in Germany, &c. &c. (published between 1865 and 1872 in the ' Revue moderne,' the VI PEEPACE. ' Revue des Deux Mondes,' the ' Journal des Debats ; ' the ' Nuova Antologia ; ' the ' Preussische Jahrblicher ; ' the ' Fortnightly Review,' and the ' North American Review.') They were so many preparatory studies for a general work on the subject, which has never been more than a project, the author having since abandoned this, for an entirely diffei-ent field of research, K. H. CONTENTS. LECTURE I. PAGE Inteodttction. — On the Part op the Fiye Great European Nations in the M^ork op Modern CDLTrEE (1450-1850) 1 LECTURE IL The Starting-point and First Stages of Modern Germany (1648-1760) 37 LECTURE III. The Seeds of German Thoitght (1760-1770) . . 79 LECTURE IV. The Reign of Herder (1770-1786) . . . .117 LECTURE V. The Triumtirate op Goethe, Kant, and Schtller (1787-1800) 173 viii CONTENTS. LECTURE VI. PAGE The Romantic School (1800-1825) . . . .228 EPILOGUE. ' Young Gekmany ' and ' Little Germany ' (1825- 1860) 264 LECTURES ON GEEMAN THOUGHT. LECTUEE I. INTRODUCTION — ON THE PART OF THE FIVE EURO- PEAN NATIONS IN THE WORK OF MODERN CULTURE. 1450-1850. Ladies and Gentlemen, — You will readily believe me, when I say that I begin these lectures with great apprehension. It is the first time that I am called upon to address an English public ; and I am to address it in its own language, the most precise and at the same time the supplest of instruments in the skilful hands of those who are used to it from their infancy, and have a complete mastery of it ; but a dangerous one for a foreigner, ever liable to miss the just measure and the right expression, weighing too much here, gliding too Z INTEODUCTION. lightly there, and becoming to a certain degree the slave of the enmne of -which he oug-ht to be the absolute ruler. I know that the audience I have the honour to address is, if not a, parterre de rois, at least a parterre of gentlemen, and that consequently it will be as lenient to a guest as it would have a right to be severe, if it were to assume the functions of an impartial judge. Nevertheless, I have thought it my duty not to rely too exclusively on your hospitable indulgence, or to overrate my strength in launching into these new waters without the swimming-apparatus of pen and ink. However alive I may be to the advantage of speaking over reading, I must forego that advan- tage and bring you my thoughts already made, as it were, and congealed, instead of letting them flow and expand naturally from the running spring of the spoken word. What renders the honour bestowed upon me of addressing so select a public more perilous still, is the consciousness that I have but an imperfect control, not only of the language of words, but also of the language of thought, pre- dominant in this country and in our days — an idiom, I am afraid, which I have still to learn. Every country and every time indeed has its own INTRODUCTION. 3 intellectual atmosphere ; and a Spaniard who in the sixteenth century might have spoken French as well as a Parisian, would have failed to un- derstand Voltaire or Diderot, if he had come to Paris a hundred years ago, as they in turn would have failed to understand him. Now, I am per- fectly aware that the intellectual atmosphere of the England of to-day — which is fast becom- ing the intellectual atmosphere of all Europe — is not the one in which my generation has been bred and reared. If I, for instance, have lived long and intimately with the English of the past, I know little of the English of to-day, or, to speak more precisely, I rather know about them than know them. In the whole tendency of my mind, in my entire way of looking at things — religious and moral, historical and scientific — I have remained a thorough Continental, nay, a thorough German, whereas the younger generation of Europe is entering more and more every day into the intellectual current which sprang up in this island towards 1860, and has since spread over the greater part of the Continent. But this will require an explanation which will lead us at once into the subject of these lectures. 4 INTRODUCTION. We may consider medieval Europe as one vast family, which, for a time, thought that it might Unity of remain for ever under the same roof, and Europe. -^qj.]j {^1 common at the great work of civilisation. One language, Latin — one Faith, the Catholic — one Law, the Eoman — one Sover- eign, the Emperor — were to rule supreme, and shelter all the members of the family. In reality this ideal was never completely attained. Yet it governed men's minds during the whole Middle Ages, and even in after-times haunted certain intellects, which were thirsting for unity and order, but were unable to find them in variety and liberty. The law of nature nevertheless was stronger than the laws of men : Europe outgrew the parental house, however spaciously it seemed constructed. 'No sooner had every hearth its own familiar language, than those who were assembled around it wished to give vent in that language to the thoughts and feelings of both their every day and their ideal life. From the day when a philosophical thought was expressed in a national language, that division of Europe had begun, which, during the fifteenth century, resulted in the national monarchies of England, France, and Spain, in UNITY OF EUROPE. 5 the Italian renaissance, and tlie reformation in Germany. The division, not the disunion. The work which Europe had done collectively and simulta- neously till then was henceforward to be done separately and successively, so that, as Algarotti said of his own nation, ' the one who had got up early before the others, and drudged a good deal, might rest somewhat in the day-time.' Neverthe- less the work done by modern Europe is truly one work, although the workmen have several times relieved each other, handing on to their successors the torch of intellectual hfe : Vitai lampada tradunt. It is one stock, one capital — the capital of humanity — which they have accumulated, each in turn contributing the fruit of his labour. I need scarcely warn you, gentlemen, that these and similar expressions must not be taken too strictly. Humanity is a living body, in which every part is intimately connected with the other, where every separation is felt like a sword-cut, painful at once and endangering life. Still, as the philosopher has a right to separate memory and imagination, will and sensation, understanding 5 INTEODUCTION. and reason, wliicli in reality form the living; individual, so the historian must claim permis- sion to divide mentally what in reality is closely united. When England exercised for the first time the intellectual hegemony over Europe, when Gilbert and Harvey, Bacon and Hobbes, Newton and Locke were writing and thinking, Italy had her Galileo, France her Pascal, Germany her Leibnitz. Still, for any impartial observer of the history of thought, the focus of the movement was in this island. Italy was the first of the European nations to come of age and grow impatient of the paternal jjjj]^, authority. As early as the beginning of 1450-1525. ^Yie fifteenth century she boasted of a poem in the national dialect, which summed up the whole intellectual life of the middle ages ; and, a century and a half later, she began to eman- cipate herself from this very system of thought to which Dante had given the most beautiful, as well as the most adequate, expression. The day- work of Italy may be reckoned from 1450 to 1525 ; but I must once more beg that such limits may be taken cum grano salts. Nobody can fix the exact line where one's arm ceases and one's shoulder begins ; still the anatomist must needs THE ITALIAN EENAISSANCE. 7 make the division somewhere. Everybody has present to his mind the events which, towards the middle of the fifteenth century, awoke Italy, as well as those more melancholy events which, seventy-five years later, laid her in the grave, or at least in a long and dull lethargy. You are all aware how Italy discovered, as it were, the treasures of Greek art and literature, how she cleansed, mended, and made them accessible, and rendered this purely lay and human civilisation the basis of all modern culture. The important point for us is to characterise in one word the nature of the intellectual work accomplished by her In those years of incessant and almost feverish labour. The Italian Renaissance was the re-habilitation of human nature ; and the instinct of history has not been mistaken when, up to this day, it calls the representative men of that age the Humanists, their culture the humanistic. The Middle Ages and Catholicism had subordinated the present to the future, liberty to authority, the human to the divine. They had declared flesh, i.e. the natural instincts of man, sinful, and preached the sup- pression or taming of them. The Italian Eenais- sance reversed things. For the naive scepticism of a Lorenzo and a Filelfo, an Angelo Poliziano 8 INTRODUCTION. and a Marsilio Ficino, the present alone had reality, and as such it was to be understood, de- scribed, enjoyed, as the Greeks of Pericles' time had tried to understand, describe, and enjoy it. All that was in nature was good and beautiful, in- stinct was the surest guide, natural forceand beauty were the truest signs of and titles to superiority. Let not the fact of their formal adherence to the Church mislead you any more than their enthu- siasm for Plato's lofty idealism. The Church was for them nothing more than an indifferent garment which a man would not needlessly ex- change for another, or lay down altogether. Platonism was a form of poetical dreaming, not a philosophical conviction. What they pursued was the knowledge of human nature, mental and physical, and of human society, not as they might be or ought to be, but as they were. Whether Machiavelli is describing political life as in his Prince, his Decades, his History of Florence, or is depicting the social life of his times as in his Comedies, he never enters into the question of good or bad; he is satisfied to understand things. So do the philo- sophers, the poets, the artists of the time. For them art is what Goethe proclaims it to be, what THE ITALIAN RENAISSANCE. 9 our century seems to have so utterly lost sight of — ' the interpreter of nature,' nothing more, nothing less. This might have been harmless, as it was right, if it had been limited to Art and Thought ; but it was the pretension of the Eenaissance to make of it the rule of life and action. Our temperament and our mental character frame our opinions, mostly without our knowing it ourselves. It was the sen- suousness of their temperament and mind which especially fitted the Italians for their historical mission; but it also led them to such lengths that they incurred the penalties attached to excessive indulgence in one's own thoughts and inclinations. They saw everything in the light of art, gave to everything an artistic form, regarded everything, public worship, the State, even private life, as within the province of art ; and the thought that they were living as the Greeks had done justified everything in their eyes. They forgot that in Greece ' the Muse accompanied life, and did not direct it.' What it came to, the names of the Sforza and the Borgia tell us forcibly enough. A strong reaction set in — a double reaction ; '^he one popular, appealing to the inward authority of conscience ; the other coming from above and 10 INTRODUCTION. endeavouring to restore the outward authority of tradition and collective force : the Reformation of Luther and the Society of Jesus. The former, although prior in time, had its full influence upon the strain of higher thought in Europe, only a century later in England, only two centuries later in Germany. The latter acted at once, and it Spain ^^^ Spain which gave rise to this move- 1525-1600. j^g^^^ When, ten years after the founda- tion of the Jesuit order by the Spaniard Ignatius Loyola, the famous Council was opened at Trent, it was Loyola's successor, the Spaniard Lainez, who became at once the directing genius of that great Assembly which renovated Catho- licism by giving it the form in which it has lived and prospered during the last three centuries. I find our time somewhat inclined to underrate the importance of the part played by SjDain in the history of Euroj^ean thought. Of course hers was above all a negative action ; but she acted also in a positive way. Not only was the reorganisation of the Church entirely her work ; the absolute Monarchy of Divine Eight, as it flourished during the seventeenth century, was equally of Spanish origin. Think of the difference between the medieval conception of sovereignty, and the one INFLUENCE OF SPAIN. 11 which was the soul of Louis XIY., nay, even of the Protestant James I. of England, and down to the smallest German and Italian princelings of that time ; between the variety of the feudal royalty of the Middle Ages with its almost inde- pendent vassals, and the uniformity of the modern monarchy with its passive obedience and its VEtat c'est moi. Now one might say, the mon- archy of Louis XIY. was simply the despotism of Philip II., tempered by the innate sense of the French for measure and taste, enlivened by their natural serenity and elegance. This, however, is only one side of the question, and, for our object, not the most important. At the same time that the principle of authority, both religious and political, received a new impulse from Spain, and conquered after an obstinate struggle the greater half of Europe, extirpating Protestantism in Italy and in France, in Belgium and in South Germany, in Bohemia and Austria, literature and philosophy underwent the same influence. At the very moment when Italy lost the monopoly of Fine Arts, and high schools of painting rose in Madrid, Seville, and the Spanish Netherlands, a new poetry and a new poetical style began to spread from Spain all over 12 INTRODUCTIOIT. Europe. Not only Italian and German Marinists were imitators of the Spanish Gongorists, even your English Euphuism of Shakspeare's times had its origin in the culteranismo of Spain ; and not the form and style alone, but the spirit also, and the subjects of literature during the first half of the seventeenth century, were in the main Spanish. Only think of Corneille's ' Cid,' written in 1636, of his ' Polyeucte,' which might figure among Calderon's Atitos sagramentales. Even in the second half of the century, Moliere takes the subjects of his ' Festin de Pierre,' his ' Princesse d'Elide,' his * Ecole de Maris,' from Moreto and Tirso. Grimmelshausen introduces into Germany, Scarron into Prance, the Roman 'picaresco of the Spaniards, of which Lesage and Smollett became the recognised masters in the following century. Much greater still is the influence exercised by Spain on the philosophical thought of Europe during the seventeenth century. The death of individuality which accompanied or followed the Spanish rule in State, Church and School, wherever it reached, threatened even speculative activity. Not that the philosophy of Molina and Suarez — if one may call philosophy what after all was only theology — ever really penetrated into the higher INFLUENCE OF SPAIN. 13 strata of intellectual life, even the elite of the clergy protesting against it, as they did in our days against the dogma of inftillibility ; but the principle of authority which Spain had restored all over the world was a powerful check on conti- nental thought, a check sometimes beneficial, more often most pernicious. There can be no doubt that no society could live in the long run with the principles, or rather the absence of principles, of the Italian Renaissance. The restoration of authority was the imposition of a salutary rein en daring minds for whom the licet quia libet had become a species of dogma. However, if you think how Malebranche, and even Descartes, were fettered in the movement of their thought by the reigning dogmatism of their time, you may well ask yourselves whether the benefit was not bought too dear. Je trouve hon qu^on n'approfondisse pas Fopinion de Copernic, says the great enemy of the Jesuits himself. It was because Catholic Europe did not dare to grapple with this opinion that the leadership of modern thought passed from it to the Protestant countries of England and Holland, where there was no Holy Inquisition to interrupt the researches of a Galileo, no unbending orthodoxy to stop the mighty thought of a Pascal. 14 INTEODUCTIOX. The Eeformation had been a popular move- ment, not an aristocratical one, as scientific Protestant- ^-ctivity must be everywhere and al- *^'"' ways. The great Protestant men of science of the preceding century, the Reuchlin and Erasmus, the Henry Estienne and Justus Scaliger, were sons of the Itahan Renaissance, not of the German Eeformation. Their inspiration was a thoroughly worldly one, they acted upon the aristocracy of culture, not on the masses. The Eeformation sprung more from a moral feeling of revolt, than from an intellectual want of liberty. This is the reason why I scarcely mention it here, where I look only for the formation of European thought, as it manifests itself in the higher sphere of select intelligence. For, whatever may be the character of moral life, in intellectual life the pa^tc^s vivit genus humanum will always remain a truth. If, however, the Eeformation was not a philosophical movement in its origin, it had the most momentous influence on the philosophical movement by its consequences. Modern Catholicism, indeed, such as it was shaped by the Jesuits during the sixteenth century, if it did not combat openly the classical civilisation and literature which the Eenaissance had un- PEOTESTANTISM. 15 covered, as it were, and given back to humanity, jet knew how to paralyse its action in the most effective way. Nowhere was the Greek and Latin literature more industriously studied than in the Jesuit schools ; but it was previously rendered innocuous. The poison of free thought which it contains was taken out of it, before it was served to the youthful mind. The freest and most living of all literatures became a collection of dead rhet- orical formulae to be learnt by heart and to be used as occasion demanded. The matter was repre- sented as of no value whatever ; the form only as a charming and clever play of the mind. Just so three centuries later, when it was no longer pos- sible to ignore the development of natural sciences, the Jesuits reduced all the results of long and universal research into manuals to be used and mechanically applied in practical life, or to be confided to memory for examination's sake, where it answers so well, indeed, that the rue des Pastes drills ten times more successful scholars for the ecole polytechnique than any lay establishment, although history does not say that it has produced one man of science. For they are prudent enough to teach the scientific data without awakening^ and stimu- lating that spirit of research which is the ideal 16 INTRODUCTION. value of natural science, as freedom of thought is the true ideal value of ancient literature. Not so Protestantism. That also had restored authority in place of the theory of unlimited liberty which in the times of Italian Eenaissance made caprice the supreme arbiter of life. But its authority was not an outward one ; it was the authority of individual conscience. Its main principle was free inquiry, first applied to the Bible ; but once allowed to exercise itself, there was no telling where it would stop, and in fact, it did not stop at the Bible. It was not the cradle of Protestantism, how- ever, which first saw these fruits of the new faith. German Protestantism was temporarily quenched, when the reaction against Spanish dogmatism set in in Europe ; and poor Kepler was almost stifled in his attempts to develope the system of Copernicus. Germany was engaged in the most disastrous and barbarous war that the history of mankind mentions in its annals, when the noble scientific movement of the seventeenth century En"-iand ^^^ ^^ ^^^ ^^^ vigour. It was reserved 1600-1700. ^^ England whose great Queen had saved for her the treasure of religious independence, to give the signal of the new march onward ; while ENGLAND IN THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY. 17 Holland, which had come out victorious from the long and manly struggle against Catholic Spain, associated herself with England in the glorious task. This self-given task was the knowledge of nature and its laws. The fifteenth century had, as it were, restored the broken links of time ; the seven- teenth unveiled space. The former had shown to man his place in history, the latter was to assign him his place in nature. The world was weary of rhetoric and words, as well as of abstract, bottom- less speculation. It thirsted for facts. It Lad long enough accepted hond fide the ready-made solutions of all questions oflPered to it by authority ; it was resolved to inquire for itself into the causes of things. The conclusions of an a priori philosophy would no longer satisfy it. Secretly and almost unconsciously it longed for a knowledge based on observation, which should also be a methodical knowledge. It was Bacon who gave words to the innermost desire of his generation, when he in- troduced and recommended the method of induc- tion. No doubt, Copernicus had observed before him and better than he did. Kepler was just then practising ' induction,' from observations with 18 INTEODUCTION. positive results, of which Bacon could not boast, whilst Galileo was at the same moment employing the experimental method which Bacon still used very awkwardly. Nevertheless it is Bacon, not Kepler or Galileo, who is rightly considered the father of modern thought. Kepler and Galileo indeed used the inductive and experimental method somewhat as M. Jourdain made prose — sans le savoir. Assuredly the progress of science was not the less furthered because Galileo's grand and simple nature, and Kepler's noble and unbend- ing mind, were occupied with the search for truth without being aware of the intellectual revolution they helped to bring about. Nevertheless, for the history of thought, the man who first spoke out and formulated the new method with the full consciousness of the momentous principle he expressed, remains the representative man of the age. It is the fashion nowadays, on the continent at least, to look down upon Bacon, because he was an indifferent observer and a sometimes puerile experimentalist ; a little also because he was a fine writer, and our time happens to be in a somewhat suspicious disposition of mind towards fine lan- guage. It is only just, however, to remember that Bacon's whole education still belonged to the ENGLAND IN THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY. 10 rlietorical period ; that his very nature was of an artistic turn ; and, above all, that, if he did not do much to further science by his discoveries, he advanced it immensely by the impulse which he gave to it by establishing- the new method. One might say that from that time only, the ground was won on which methodical empiricism could move freely. Not only did Hobbes take his start from Bacon ; but all that England dis- covered in natural philosophy from Harvey to Newton, all that it produced in psychological philosophy from Locke to Hume, would have been impossible, if the Novum Org anon had not laid down the laws of the exact method. It would have been equally impossible if the Protestant faith had not been maintained in England during that time. The melancholy lot of Kepler, G. Bruno, and G-alileo, would have been reserved for these daring hunters for truth, if they had not lived on Protestant ground. The three o-reatest continental thinkers of the mathematical age — Descartes, Spinosa, Leibnitz^ — could perform their work only because they passed the greater part of their lives in Protestant countries. One of them carried even there the invisible fetters imposed upon him by his first education. Nay, c 2 20 INTRODUCTION. Bayle himself, who forms the link between the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, between English and French thought, was obliged to in- voke the protection of the Protestant governments of the Hague and London. If English Empiricism ^ was a reaction against Spanish Dogmatism ; if Spanish Dogmatism had been a reaction against Italian Humanism, France, Erench Eationalism, which ruled su- ' " ■ preme during the following century, was a continuation of, not an opposition to, the intellectual current in England. It was a sort of contagion, indeed, which affected France, whose most distinguished geniuses, from Saint-Evremond to Montesquieu, from Yoltaire to Bufibn, and even down to Rousseau, came in turn to England, and even before crossing the Channel had put them- selves to the school of Newton and Locke. No sooner had France taken the lead than she gave to the movement that particular logical character of her own, which goes straight to the mark and never shrinks from the last conclusions. The great English thinkers of the preceding age con- ' By Empiricism I mean the spirit of the seventeenth cen- tury, i.e. the mechanical and mathematical explanation of Nature, as it was undertaken and to a great extent carried out. FEENCH RATIONALISM. 21 tented themselves with studying things and facts without trying to draw from them inferences which might be too dangerous, or applying them to religion and politics. Locke himself paused in deep reverence before revelation and the throne. Not so the French. Their rationalistic turn of mind and impatient temperament carried them at once to the extreme of submitting church and state to the same method of inquiry which had been so successfully applied to nature and mind. But logic and passion soon drove them further than they first intended, and made them often forget that patient observation and careful comparison of facts, which had yielded such extraordinary results in England. Already Des- cartes — a true Frenchman in that respect — had at once committed himself to the mechanical ex- planation of things, by making the animal a machine, and as he remained a spiritualist at heart, never could quite manage to reconcile the two worlds of matter and mind. The French of Bayle's school — I do not say Bayle himself — knew of no such impediments. They recognised no authority whatever. Their aim was simply abso- lute emancipation from all conventionality and authority. Without being aware of it, they fell 22 INTRODUCTION. again into the authoritative spirit, against which the English reaction was directed. Only it was no longer revelation, nor tradition which was the authority, but the senses and human reason, — human reason independent, if not of natural, at least of historical facts. They dreamed either of political constitutions (which were to be the result not of history, i.e. of conflicting interests, but of a general, abstract, preconceived idea of state and society) ; or of a natural law, which was to replace the codes of traditional laws and customs, just as they dreamed of a natural, or rather a rational, religion, which began with being a timid deism, very similar to that of Toland and Clarke, and ended with the enthronement of the goddess of reason, or with the complete denial of that spiritual world, from which Descartes had been unable to throw a bridge to the world of matter. Whatever may have been the fatal conse- quences of this method for France herself, though they are largely balanced by its salutary results, the method itself effected the liberation of Europe, nay of mankind. There existed an accumula- tion of traditional forms, prejudices, impediments of all sorts which disturbed the development of FRENCH RATION ALISM. 23 liumanity. It seems to have been the historical mission of France, it certainly was her merit, a merit which never can be sufficiently acknowledged, to have laid the axe unsparingly to this thicket of intellectual conventionalities, and levelled the road for us. Of course she could not remove all — it was not desirable that she should remove all ; and much of the brushwood which she re- moved, has grown up again. Still it was the first time in history that men dared to look at things and to order them by the light of reason alone. Many national qualities had singled France out for this task, many circumstances helped her to fulfil her mission with immediate success. The clearness of the French mind, as it reveals itself in the French language ; the geo- graphical position of the country between England, Spain, and Germany ; the political hegemony over Europe which she had won under Louis XTV. ; the vast influence gained already by her poetical litera- ture ; last, not least, the simplicity of the new creed, based upon the most general characteristics of humanity and common-sense, and carried out by the most seductive of instruments, logic — all contributed to facilitate her task. This explains also the instantaneousness with 24 INTRODUCTIO:^ which the French idea made its way in Europe. Generally, the- intellectual influence of a nation only begins to spread abroad when its work is nearly completed, Italy had already done her best, when towards the beginning of the sixteenth century her thoughts and works began to act upon the rest of Europe. For more than a century Europe still continued to go to Rome, Bologna, and Naples, although Velasquez and Murillo, Poussin and Claude, Rubens and Van Dyck, were capable of teaching- their teachers. It was the same with Spain and England. It is the same with Ger- many, whose original and creative work was done and well-nigh finished as early as 1850, although the world is looking upon her still as the great laboratory of thought for Europe. France is, perhaps, the only country which began to export her intellectual wares at once, even before the whole store was gathered and ready. The time of Voltaire and the Encyclopsedists was also the time of Hume and Gibbon. It was reserved for Germany to react against the too absolute thought of France, and to begin Germany, ^^^ work of restoration on a sounder 1.60-1825. ijg^gjg than that which Spain had tried to lay two centuries before. It would be interesting INFLUENCE OF GERMANY. 25 to show, at some length, how she prepared herself for her task, how she fulfilled it, and what were the results obtained from it. To do this properly, however, it would be necessary to prove how she owed part, at least, of her intellectual freedom to England and France, how from them she certainly received the impulse to her own work, how she renovated philosophy as well as history, how she created several new sciences which have since taken their place amongst the greatest achievements of the human mind. Suffice it to state that she in- troduced once for all the idea of Organism into European thought, just as French Rationalism, English Empiricism, Spanish Dogmatism, and Italian Humanism, have long become integral parts of the mental constitution of Europe. Is it not in fact as impossible now for us to read Homer in the same spirit in which our grand- fathers read him before Wolf had written his ' Prolegomena,' as it is for us to look at Nature as we might have done before Newton had published his ' Principia,' or at the State as we might have done before Montesquieu wrote his ' Esprit des Lois ' ? There is, indeed, a common stock of ideas on which we all live, in which we all move, often 26 INTEODUCTION. witliouL being quite conscious of it. Let even the most convinced of Roman Catholics ask him- self whether he could still look on the history of mankind as St. Thomas or St. Dominic looked on it before the Italian Renaissance had restored, as it were, the continuity of history, and filled up the abyss which cut humanity in two. Could any man consider public and private life with the unprincipledtiatue/e with which the contemporaries of Machiavelli considered them, before the prin- ciple of authority had been restored by Spain ? Again, who of us could ever forget, for a moment only, the physical discoveries of the seventeenth century, and think of the earth, like Dante, as the centre of creation ? And is it not the same with our political and philosophical views ? Has not the application of the French rationalistic method of the past century moulded our mind anew ? Could we still, if we wished, look on the divine right of monarchy or on revelation as Bossuet and Fenelon did ? Now something analogous has taken place since the death of Vol- taire and Rousseau. Another new thought has become an integral part of the European mind. It would be as impossible for Hume to write his essay on ' National Character ' to-day as INFLUENCE OF GERMANY. 27 it would have been for Augustin Thierry to write his 'Conquete d'Angleterre ' in the past centurj, or for anyone to compose Voltaire's ' Pucelle ' in ours. Why so ? Because not only have there been discoveries in philology and eth- nography which render it materially impossible to explain historical facts as a Hume or Gibbon explained them, but also because a new idea has been thrown into the world, which has profoundly modified our whole course of thought. Now this idea has been elaborated in Germany, and it is the history of this elaboration which is still to be written, and of which I venture to ofier something like a general programme, the outlines of a plan, which it would require volumes to fill in. In speaking of the intellectual movement of Germany, from the second half of the past century to the middle of the present, it will be in- Definition dispensable also to touch upon her poeti- pf the Sub- cal literature and her philosophy proj)er. This seems to be a sort of truism. Yet it is not so in my mind. What I am investigating now is neither the literary spirit, nor the meta- physical speculations, nor the scientific work of the nation, but the whole Weltanschauung, that is 28 JNTEODUCTION. to say, tlie general course of thought (or rather the general standing-point), which the German nation made for itself, and opened or added to European culture during those seventy or eighty years ; and such a general standing-point is but indirectly influenced by poetry and science proper. Poetry is an art, and as such it is not subject to the law of progress ; consequently it is, properly speaking, outside history, a thing absolute and eternal. The ' Iliad ' is as true to-day as it was three thousand years ago, the main object of poetry being the unchangeable part of man's nature. It is not so with science, with thought, with politics. These are subject to the law of development. When we read in Dante's poem of Francesca's love and Pia's death we are moved as Dante's contem- poraries may have been moved ; when he explains his cosmography to us, we smile, and perhaps shut il suo volume. Here, then, we speak of two different activities of the human mind, which sometimes are at work in a different, sometimes in the same, generation and country. Eng- land's philosophical labour began only after Shakespeare, that of France only after Pacine and Moliere ; whereas in Spain Calderon and Cer- vantes were the contemporaries of Suarez and DEFINITION OF THE SUBJECT. 29 Molina, while in Germany Goethe and Schiller lived at the same time with Kant and Wolf, Hum- boldt and Niebuhr. This apparently accidental fact has an important consequence. Poetry and philosophy penetrate each other, when they are simultaneous, to their mutual advantage in some respects, to their great disadvantage in others. The spirit of Calderon's poetry is also the spirit of Ignatius Loyola ; in Schiller you hear the echo of Kant's moral philosophy. The great literature of the French, on the contrary — the eloquence of a Bossuet and the enthusiasm of a Corneille — expresses a state of thought in some points directly opposed to that spirit of the eighteenth century which the world calls properly the French spirit. I might speak of Shakespeare, for whose clear, deep eye there is no yesterday nor to-morrow, no here nor there, without even mentioning that he was a contemporary of Bacon ; I could not speak of Goethe without reminding you that he was a friend of Herder, and a reader of W. von Humboldt. There is another fact of great importance which I could not pass over in silence if I had space to enter fully into the subject ; and this is the political state of Germany during the elabora- 30 INTRODUCTION. tion of her Thought {Weltanscliauung), and the effect which this thought has had on the ulterior transformation of the German State. This great period during which the intellectual culture of Germany was built up or at least accomplished, was the time when her old society was dissolved, and her political life was in complete decay. Is it possible to be at the same time great and fertile in public life, and in scientific and speculative activity ? When we think of Plato and Aristotle laying the foundation of all true and high philo- sophy in the period of decay which had followed the epoch of what might be called the civil war of Greece; when we contemplate the political dis- union and misery of Italy at the time of the Renaissance ; when we see England contribute most actively to the intellectual wealth of Europe during the not very glorious reigns of James I. and Charles II. ; when we observe France ruling the world by the pen of Voltaire and Rousseau, sending the missionaries of her thought to St. Petersburg and Naples, to Copenhagen and Lisbon, and at the same time defeated at Rossbach, obliged to sign the peace of Aix-la-Chapelle and that of Versailles, and driven out from India and her colonies ; when we think of Germany producing her Kant and Herder, DEFINITION OF THE SUBJECT. 31 ■while the Fatherland was utterly impotent and helpless, or even under foreign domination, we may be tempted to think that perhaps the two activities are incompatible, or at least oidy excep- tionally compatible. And why should it be otherwise ? Must not the different faculties of the human mind have their rest from time to time and relieve each other, if the sources are not to be exhausted before the time ? There have been religious ages, like the first centuries of our era and the sixteenth century, entirely bent upon the creation and definition of religious dogmas, passionate only for religious questions and interests ; and these have been followed by periods of comparative silence, when humanity, weary of theological dis- cussions, uninterested in religious subjects, quietly accepted the existing forms of religion and rested in them. There had been a great artistic age four centuries before Christ, slowly prepared during hundreds of years, slowly dying out during hundreds of years, after a short and brilliant blossom. Then the capacity of artistic intu- ition lay dormant for a long, long time, till it slowly awakened towards the end of the Middle Ages, and came to a short but splendid 32 INTEODUCTION. efflorescence in the fifteenth century only again to die a long death, which, I am afraid, is now well nigh consummated. But here again I must warn my hearers against taking my words too literally. There have been eminent statesmen like Richelieu in scientific ages, religious apostles like Savonarola in artistic centuries ; so there may be eminent artists in our time — but they act as isolated indi- viduals. The main efibrt of the human mind is bent in another direction, and there are but few eyes open to take in what is still left of artistic creation. Why should not the capacity for political and scientific life sometimes lie fallow, when the reli- gious and artistic faculties require such temporary repose? Why should they not have their rest in turn? Why, above all, should we discuss which grandeur is the better, that of Voltaire or that of Napoleon, that of Newton or that of Cromwell ? Men will never agree on that question, because it is not a difference of opinion, but a difference of temperament and character. Let us only admit this one point. When a nation, in- stinctively or consciously, feels that one day's work is done and sets herself to do the work of the next, leave her alone ; do not let us try to be wiser than DEFINITION OF THE SUBJECT. , 38 history and nature. If for a time a nation gives herself up to building, laboriously and awkwardly perhaps, a new house in which she may live un- molested and in conformity with her own history and nature, let her do so, and do not ask of man- hood the down of youth, nor of summer the mellow tints and ripe fruits of autumn. All these are at the bottom idle questions, which are much like reproaching the apple-tree for not bearing oranges. If the nation which has yielded the in- tellectual leadership of Europe to another nation, because it had more pressing work on hand — per- haps also because it was tired and wanted change — excludes itself from the intellectual life of Europe, as Spain did during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, it will pay a penalty heavy enough. If, on the contrary, it continues to participate in the spiritual movement of Europe, as this countr}^ has done during the eighteenth and nineteenth cen- turies, then it may be sure that one day or another the leadership will come back to it, and that sooner or later, it will reoccupy, even if it be only for a time, the first place in the intellectual laboratory of Europe. However this may be, the assigned limits of time force me to resist the temptation of giving D 34 INTRODUCTION. even a sketch of German literature and philosophy proper, still more of relating the history of state and religion in Germany, and I must content myself with simply tracing the outlines and the general character of German culture, such as it was shaped in the period I have mentioned. Even thus I shall be obliged to have recourse to somewhat superficial generalities in explaining the growth and the nature of the German standing- point in religion, literature, politics, and science. I need scarcely add that my remarks have not the slightest pretension to originality. I give you the results neither of special investigation, nor of j)ersonal thought ; but only what is the common property of every cultivated German, although I give it in the particular form which it has taken by passing through my individual mind. I speak only as an interpreter, not even as a commentator, still less as a critic, and least of all as a discoverer of new truth. One word more and I have finished. A sub- ject like the one which we propose to study, the contribution of one European nation to the common capital of European thought, can only be successfully treated if we endeavour to divest ourselves of all party spirit, national, political. NEED OF FKEEDOM FROM PREJUDICE. 35 and religious. Party spirit has its right place in practical life. When it is a question of defending one's faith, or one's country, of obtaining certain positive ends only to be obtained by collective and disciplined' forces, let us be of a party and stand by it usque ad mortem. But when we try to understand the history of mankind and to pene- trate its mysterious ways, nay, whenever we meet on a ground where those practical interests are not endangered or threatened, where there is no war and strife, where we are simply to live with each other, to know each other, at the utmost to judge each other — let us forget such unpleasant distinctions, and treat each other as if we were all of one nation, one party, one faith. Let us not approach peoples, or facts, or ideas with a precon- ceived judgment, nor ask them suspiciously for their passport, instead of trying to ascertain their intrinsic value. Let us not condemn or canonize people, facts or ideas, because they may be of Russian or Italian origin, bear a Catholic or Pro- testant label, come from the Conservative or Liberal camp. This would be true barbarism, — bar- barism, I am afraid, which will invade humanity more and more, in proportion as political democracy advances with superficial enlightenment I) 2 36 INTRODUCTION. and scientific lialf-culture. As tlie number of those who take part in public life increases, the more will passion — political, religious, national — overrule justice and equity and goodwill. Tor the man who puts himself under the thraldom of party bonds must needs sacrifice part of the truth which he knows, part of his moral and intellectual freedom, part of himself. On the other side, in proportion to the scantiness of their numbers will be the intensity of the love of truth in those who emancipate themselves from such passions in order to look at things and judge them by themselves. Let us all strive at least to be of those few ; for they are not only the lovers of truth, they are not only the sole free minds, they alone are also the really just. And whatever our effeminate age may say to the contrary, justice is still and will always be what Plato and Aristotle proclaimed it to be, the highest and manliest of virtues. 37 LECTUEE II. THE STARTING-POINT AND FIRST STAGES OP MODERN GERMANY. 1648-1760. Nobody can form a true estimate of the present state of Germany, social and political, religious and intellectual, who does not realise what was her starting-point. All European nations can boast of a continuous development from the Middle Ages to the nineteenth century. Even the great catastrophe which delivered Italy up to foreign rule towards the middle of the sixteenth century, even the Great Eebellion and the Glorious Revolution which gave birth to new England, nay, even the revolution of 1789 which destroyed the ancien regime in France, had not the power entirely to break the thread of national history in these three great civilised nations. From Dante and Giotto to 38 THE STAETING-POINT. Filijacaand Dominichino there is one uninterrupted line of growth and decay. The memory of Queen Bess was still living in the time of William III., and a Lamartine and a Victor Hugo have been lulled with the verse of Lafontaine and Racine, and reared on the ideas of Bossuet and Voltaire. Not so in German}^ The Thirty Tears' War which raged from 1618 to 1648 made a gap in her national development, such as we find nowhere else in history. It threw her back full two hundred years, materially and intellectually, and extinguished all remembrance of the past. If you walk through the cities of Augsburg a.nd Nuremberg, Liibeck and Eatisbon, you meet at Germany ©Very step vestigcs of a high civilisation. ^^Jith'^' Those churches, those town-halls, those centurj'. palaccs— Only think of the Heidelberg- Schloss — were mostlv built at the end of the six- teenth or the beginning of the seventeenth century ; and a hundred and fifty years before, ^neas Sylvius (Pope Pius TI.) had been so struck with the comfort of the German cities, that he declared the kings of Scotland might rejoice to be as well- housed as an ordinary burgher of Nuremberg. True, the relative poverty of the soil always ren- dered the accumulation of wealth difficult and GEEMANT IN THE SIXTEENTH CENTURY. 39 slower than elsewhere in two-thirds of Germany ; true also, the discovery of America and the consequent change of the seat of commerce had in some measure checked the tide of German middle-class prosperity. Nevertheless the material and social civilisation of Germany was still in the sixteenth century on the whole rather superior than inferior to that of England and France. If we think of the high culture of city patricians like Pirckheimer and Peutinger, of bankers like Fugger and Welser, of lords and gentlemen like Philip of Hesse and TJlrich von Hutten ; if we think of their intimacy with artists such as Vischer and Diirer, with scholars such as Eeuchlin and Erasmus, with theologians such as Luther and Melanchthon, we at once feel that there exists an intellectual culture common to the whole nation, that wealth is not yet separated from learning, that Art is not yet the metier of a guild. Not only English and French courtiers, but also the highly refined Italians, who crossed the Alps, found in Germany a society quite on a par with that of Florence and Ferrara. True it is that politically, and even intellectually, the country made little progress after the religious peace of 1555. Ever since a foreigner, Charles V., had ascended the 40 THE STAETING-POINT. imperial throne in 1519, the German national state seemed doomed to death, and all patriotic minds felt it deeply. All towards the end of the century looked with eyes of melancholy envy on the national kingdoms of Queen Elizabeth and Henry IV. But this is not the place to relate the history of the sixteenth history. Suffice it to say that the political unity of Germany had declined more and more, that the Jesuits had won consider- able ground, not only over the Lutherans, but also over the National Catholics, as we might call all the representatives of the old religion, who in 3rermany as in Prance resisted the new cosmo- politan current of the Church. The whole of the second half of the century was employed in that double work of reaction, political and religious, and the work was successful. Still there remained the tradition of a German state, there remained some public life, there re- Germany rained abovc all a good deal of the seventeenth German religion. All this Ferdinand II. century. undertook to destroy, and, although he was conquered in the long run, he succeeded only too well. Germany came out of the Thirty Years' War almost expiring. It was as if a deadly illness had wiped out the memory of the nation in its / GEEMANT IN THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY. 41 cruel delirium. All the national forces, material as well as intellectual and moral, were destroyed when peace was concluded in 1648. There are fertile wars and sterile wars ; civil and religious wars belong mostly to the latter class. Still the religious wars in France, and the Great Eebellion in England, were light spring storms compared with that terrible Thirty Years' War which left Germany a desert. And what it destroyed in this way was not a barbarous country ; it was an old civilisation. Hundreds of Material flourishing cities were reduced to ashes ; ^*^*^' there were towns of 18,000 inhabitants which counted but 324 at the peace ; ground which had been tilled and ploughed for ten centuries had become a wilderness ; thousands of villages had disappeared. Trees grew in the abandoned houses. At Wiesbaden the market had grown into a brush- wood full of deer. The whole Palatinate had but- 200 freeholders; Wiirtemberg had but 48,000 inhabitants at the end of the war instead of the 400,000 which it had mustered at the beginning. We are told that a messenger going from Dresden to Berlin through a once flourishing country walked thirty miles without finding a house to rest in. The war had devoured, on an avera,ge, three quarters of 42 THE STARTING-POINT. the population, two thirds of the houses, nine tenths of the cattle of all sorts; nearly three quarters of the soil had been turned into heath. Commerce and industry were as utterly destroyed as agriculture ; the mighty Hanseatic League was dissolved ; the savings of the nation were entirely spent. I am therefore certainly not far from the truth when I say that Germany was thrown back two hundred years as compared with Holland, France, and England, Even in so prolific a nation, a century did not suffice to fill up the gaps in the population, nor could two centuries restore the lost capital. It is a proved fact, indeed, that Germany recovered only towards 1 850 the actual amount of capital and the material well-being with which she had entered the great war in 1618. Thus, so far as the number of homesteads, the heads of cattle, the returns of crops can be statistically ascertained, the amount in 1850 was, not relatively but absolutely, the same as in 1618 ; in some respects even inferior. The social and moral state corresponded with the material. Many schools and churches Moral and stood abandoned, for public instruction socia sta e. ^^^ public worship had nearly perished. The highly cultivated language of Luther was MOEAL STATE OF GERMANY. 43 utterly forgotten, together with the whole litera- ture of his time. The most vulgar vices had taken root in people who had been reared from their infancy in the horrors of war. Every higher aim and interest had been lost sight of; not a vestige of a national tradition remained. There was no middle class nor gentry left; the higher noblemen had become petty despotic pi'inces, with no hand over them, since the Emperor was but a name ; the lower went to their court to do lackey's service. A whole generation had grown up during the war, and considered its savage barbarism as a normal state of society. Only those who have read the '' Simplicissimus,' an admirable novel in Smollett's style, but anterior by more than a century, can have an idea of the state of things. Suicides became so frequent after the war, that an Imperial law ordered seK-murderers to be buried under the gallows. From houses and churches the old artistic furniture had disappeared, and was replaced by coarse and cheap utensils. The peasants' dwellings differed little from those of their animals. De- preciation of their products and taxation weighed heavily upon them ; the innumerable differences of weight and money, and the bad roads rendered 44 THE STAHTING-POINT. the sale of goods more difficult still. The adminis- tration of justice was detestable, slow, expensive, and corrupt. For all habits of self-government, even in the cities, had gone; the gentlemen had become courtiers instead of magistrates. An unprecedented coarseness of manners had invaded not only courts and cities, but also the universities and the clergy. There was servility everywhere. The theologians became in theory and practice the supporters of despotism ; a Leibnitz himself at times set a somewhat unworthy example of humility. Cowardice had become the common vice of the lower people and of what remained of the middle class, in a time when the free citizens were weaned from the use of arms through the numerous mercenary troops, which had become gangs of highwaymen. The prodigality, vanity, and luxury of the higher classes infected the lower; the con- tagion was general. Everybody wanted a title — for it was then that the great title-mania set in, of which Germany is not yet entirely cured. Theo- logy in its most rigid form, superstition of the rudest character, had replaced religion ; pedantry had taken the place of erudition. The study of the Greek language had almost disappeared from the universities and colleges, where the professors SOCIAL STATE OF GERMANY. 45 vied witL. tlie students in vulgar vices. Drink- ing- became a profession ; there were travelling drinkers; at the highest Court of the Empire at Wetzlar, an examination in drinking was exacted from the newly-appointed assessors by their col- leagues. Every baron had his mistresses, as well as an Augustus of Saxony, or a George of Hanover. ' At the Court of Dresden,' says a con- temporary, * there are numbers of people who, not being able to live from their own resources, sacri- fice their wives to maintain themselves in favour.' Gambling had become a general habit, and as nobody had money to gamble with, it was the public income which, through the channel of the princes, ran into the pockets of the courtiers and became the means of satisfying that passion. Venality and nepotism prevailed among the nume- rous ofiicials ; pauperism and mendicity among the lower people; ignorance and immorality every- where. The nobility and bourgeoisie, once so united, were henceforth separated, it seemed, for ever. Foreign manners and foreign language were adopted everywhere. Eead the letters of the Duchess of Orleans, read Lady M. Montague's reports of the beginning of the following century, or Pollnitz's and Casanova's memoirs, in order to 46 THE STARTING-POINT. form for yourselves an idea of the prevalent customs and language. The restoration of the Stuarts, and the splendour of the French court, acted as dangerous examples; every princeling wanted to imitate them. ' There is not a younger son of a side line,' said Frederick 11., even a century later, ' who does not imagine himself to be something like Louis XIV. He builds his Versailles, has his mistresses, and maintains his armies.' Now this splendour, without glory and taste, without refine- ment and art, without literature, without any redeeming point, in short, became general at the hundreds of German courts, and did not allow the exhausted country to rally. Never, perhaps, were things worse than towards 1700, when the court poet of Dresden, Besser, sang his well-known ode : Der Konig ist vergniigt ; Das Land erfreuet sich.' The political state was not better than the social. Ferdinand II. had not succeeded in his p ,.^ J plans ; he was conquered. The States state. became free ; religion also was free ; but one-third of Germany was virtually separated and * The king amuses himself : the country is delighted. POLITICAL STATE OP GERMANY. 47 estranged from tlie intellectual life of the nation. Austria and Bavaria liave only in this century begun again to take a part in it. All the wealthy, the learned, the industrious, who would not give up their faith, were exiled like Kepler ; those who remained were broken in spirit. National unity scarcely existed even in words and forms. The Empire was organised anarchy : confusio divinitus conservata, said Oxenstierna. Germany had really and truly become a geographical ex- pression. France and Austria governed her in turn ; the Germans themselves saw in Louis XI Y. the successor of Charlemagne, called to protect them against Spaniards and Turks. The small states, which the court-theologians called com- placently 'true gardens of God, cultivated by princely hands,' had in reality become hot-beds of debauch and tyranny. Never had despotism reigned so supreme and unchecked. And what despotism ! Not that of a Philip II. or a Louis XIV., which at least pursued high, if unjust, aims, and exercised itself in grand proportions ; but despotism of the meanest as well as the pettiest kind. In the interest of their faith men had stood by the Princes against the Emperor ; now the clergy had become instruments 48 THE STARTING-POINT. of the former against tlie people, preacliing everj- wliere the doctrine of passive obedience to the ' monarchs,' as they styled themselves. The ' monarchs ' in turn isolated themselves more and more from the nation, which they governed through the thousands of their servile and corrupt officials, whose business it was to find the money for their princely entertainments. Justice was as venal as administration was rapacious. The old parlia- ments had disappeared long ago, together with the jury, the Landesgemeinde, and all that recalled the old Teutonic uses and customs which, fortu- nately for yon, survived in this island. Eeligion itself, which had been the pretext of the war, had well-nigh vanished. True, the nation, in the misery of her political life, had thrown herself entirely into Church life, but a Church life of the narrowest kind, in which theology triumphed over religious feeling, as it had triumphed over science ; for science and theology again stood apart, as in the days of scholasticism. And as religion had united the classes, so theology separated them. Mean- while Catholic proselytism pursued its work, and princely conversions became of every-day occur- rence. It is easy from this to infer the intellectual INTELLECTUAL STATE. 49 state of the nation. Here also a gulf had opened between the learned and the people, as in intellectual religion between the clergy and the lay- " ^^'^' men. The German literature of the sixteenth century, the poetry and prose of a Hans Sachs, a Fischart, a Sebastian Brant, had been, essentially popular. A hundred years later there was as com- plete a separation between literature and the people as there was complete oblivion of what had existed before. There was no theatre, and no art ; for art did not survive the war. What remained of it was of the worst taste, more hric-a-hrac than art. It was at this time that the taste for collecting- curiosities arose : the grilne Gewolhe in Dresden dates from this period. In poetry there is the same utter want of originality. The whole litera- ture of the time is a servile imitation of the Neo- Latin. literatures. Opitz imitates Tasso, Ronsart, Ben Jonson ; the Silesian school imitates Marini, Mile. Scudery, Dryden ; Gottsched and Canitz imitate Boileau, Eacine, Pope. There was no- thing national either in the form, the language, the subjects, or the inspiration. Besides, the writers were without a j)ublic. The bourgeoisie lived in the narrowest social and intellectual circle. The gentry were too much given up to ' gambling E 50 THE STAETING-POINT. and drinking,' according to Leibnitz, * to be lovers of science like the English, or of wit and witty conversation like the' French.' The princes, who might be compared to your lords, 'thought it beneath their dignity to cultivate their mind.' So wrote Count Mannteufel to Wolff as late as 1738. Leibnitz himself ascribed to his countrymen one merit only, that of industry. The language fell into utter decay ; everybody in the higher classes spoke French as the Eussians did twenty years ago. ' Since the treaty of Miinster and the Pyrenees,' said Leibnitz, ' it is not only the French govern- ment, but also the French language which has got the best of us. Our princes have rendered Ger- many subject, if not to the French king— although there is little wanting for that either— at least to French fashion and language.' The official idiom was composed of Latin, French, and German words mixed together, and so awkwardly constructed, that even an English legal document would be easy reading compared with it. At the univer- sities teaching went on in Latin. If there was still some verse — whatever its worth might be — there was no prose left in the country of Luther. Nevertheless a quelque cJiose malheur est hon, and ogni male non viene per nuocere. However THE MISSION OP PRUSSIA. 51 great may have been the misery, the humiliation and the dismemberment of Germany, however radical her material, intellectual and moral ruin ; there yet remained for the nation at ... . . The work- least the possibility of a moral and politi- ins up, , 1648-1763. cal restoration. But she would have lost this if she had fallen under the Habsburg yoke, and if Jesuitism had invaded North and Central Germany as it invaded Austria and Bavaria, which were secluded from the intellectual and moral life of Germany for more than a century after. The two springs around which the new life gathered and grew up were the Prussian State and the Protestant Religion . Ever since Esau of Saxony had sold his primo- geniture for the lentil dish of the Polish crown, the task of reuniting Protestant Germany Political. had fallen to Prussia, and she did not shrink from her glorious mission. Scarcely was the Peace of Westphalia signed when the Great- Elector set about the task, as a disinterested servant of the people, and one conscious of his duty. Nor was it easy to do for Germany, in the broad daylight of modern history, what Egbert had done for England in the dim times of the early Middle Ages, what Louis XI. and Ferdinand the 52 THE STARTING-POINT. Catholic had accomplished for Spain and France in the fifteenth century, when means were still allowed which were no longer tolerated in the times of Cromwell and William III. This task was the unification of a great nation through the union and assimilation, or the submission, of all the minor states. Nor were the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries times in which public men could speak freely. The Continent was every- where under the sway of absolute monarchy. Absolute monarchy then guided the state with the instruments at its disposal. These were the army, the bureaucracy, the clergy, and the schools. When 'enlightened despotism' set to work, the first thing was to improve and furbish up these instru- ments, to enforce discipline, industry, honesty, and to awaken the sense of duty. They were rude masters, those kings of Prussia, who rose early, worked hard, went about themselves, stick in hand, to see that the schoolmasters held their classes, that the tax-gatherers kept their accounts rightly, that the contractors made no undue profits, that every judge had clean hands, and that every official was up to his task. When they began to set the example of economy at their courts in a time when extravagance and prodigality ENLIGHTENED DESPOTS. 53 seemed to be the necessary virtues of monarcliy, they were sneered at of course as undignified misers. When Frederick TI. received coldly ad- venturers like Pollnitz and Casanova, who were the delight of all the German courts, he was looked on as a sovereign who did not know what hon ton was. The nation, however, was not to be deceived, nor were the thinkers of the time. The friends of enlightenment, from Voltaire down to Diderot, and from Hume to Gibbon, had strong absolutist predilections. You all remember Vol- taire's delightful tale about Truth and Reason wandering about Europe after their long banish- ment, and finding everywhere, except in Poland, signs of a hopeful spring brought about by despotic reformers : it is Pombal in Lisbon, Aranda in Madrid, Tanucci in Naples, Ganganelli in Rome, Peter Leopold in Tuscany, Joseph 11. in Vienna, the great Catherine in St. Petersburg, Struensee in Copenhagen, and Gustavus III. in Stockholm. Even in the little capitals of Stuttgart and Darmstadt, Lippe-Detmold and Dessau, they find ' enlightened despots ' on a small footing. The one, however, who was the type and model of them all was Frederick. Not unjustly. Not only was he the only ruler, 54 THE STAETING-POINT. who was in full possession of the culture of his Frederick time, the One who had penetrated most deeply into the philosophy of the age, the one who proved the most completely disinterested personally; he was also the one who, from the outset, had the clearest conception of the duty which made him the first servant, ' le premier domestique,' of the nation. He was twenty-eight years old when he ascended the throne (1740), and wrote to his officials : ' Our intention is that you should not be allowed to enrich yourselves, and to oppress our poor subjects. You must watch over the welfare of the country as much as over our own ; for we will not recognise any distinction between our personal advantage and that of the country ; you must always have this in view as much as that — and even more. The advantage of the country should always have the preference over Our personal advantage, when both do not concur.' And he not only preached in words, he acted up to his precepts. When seven- teen years later he thought himself lost against the coalition of Europe, he wrote on the eve of Eossbach to Count Finck : ' If it happen that I should be killed, affairs must take their course without the slightest alteration, and without any FEEDERICK THE GKEAT. 55 body perceiving that they are in other hands. . , If I have the ill luck to be taken prisoner by the enemy, I forbid my subjects to show the slightest regard for my person, or to attach the least im- portance to vt^hat I may write from my captivity. If such a thing should happen, I wish to be sacrificed to the State ; and everybody shall obey my brother, who, as well as my ministers and generals, will answer on their heads that neither province nor ransom shall be offered for me, but the war shall be continued just as if I had never existed.' And what he had proclaimed on his accession and during his glorious reign, he still recommended on his death-bed and in his will to his successor ; i.e. 'if necessary, the sacrifice of his personal advantage to the well-being of the country and the good of the State.' It is this absence of per- sonal ambition, or avarice, or thirst of pleasure, this complete id© vilification of himself with the State, — i.e. with an impersonal but living ideal, which forms the moral grandeur of Frede- rick, whatever may be the means which he and all his contemporaries, without exception, used for the attainment of their ends. It is needless to speak of his intellectual grandeur: his deeds are too striking to allow of its being contested. 56 THE STARTING-POINT. Frederick's attitude towards religious opinion was one of absolute indifference, and ihe con- sequence thereof was absolute toleration. He made no attempt to unite the cburches as William III. had done, or as his own grandson tried to do. His policy was to let them alone. * All religions shall be tolerated in my States,' he wrote, ' and the ministers have only one thing to look to, and that is, that none should do any harm to others ; for here every one shall be free to seek his salvation after his own mind' {a sa fagon). He really was the first to emancipate Europe religiously, to create the purely secular State. ' A prince,' said Kant himself, *who avows it to be his duty not to prescribe anything to men about their religion, but to leave them complete liberty in that res^Dect, who consequently declines even the proud merit of toleration— such a prince is enlightened and deserves to be praised by his con- temporaries, and by a grateful posterity, as the one who first emancipated mankind, and left every man free to use his own reason in matters of con- science.' Similarly, as a civil legislator, he real- ised the dream of his age by putting natural law in the place of traditional law and custom. His Code (the Landrecht), in many of its articles. FREDEEICK THE GREAT. 57 reads like the 'Eights of Man' of the French Eevolution and the American Constitution. Well might Mirabeau say, tliat he was in advance of his age by a hundred years. Frederick has often been reproached with having shown no interest in German literature, nay, with having expressed something very like contempt for German intellectual life. This seems to me very unjust and unintelligent. When Frederick came of age towards 17-30, and again when, an ardent youth still, and thirsting for intel- lectual life, he became king, his country offered him little, and what it offered — Wolff's philosophy — ■ he certainly embraced with ardour. But naturally enough he sought his intellectual food chiefly in the country which produced most of it, and where literary activity was just then most intense — in France. Besides, if ' he was a Frenchman by education, he was a German by nature,' says Madame de Stael with great shrewdness ; and if he thought as a Frenchman, I might add, he acted as a German. There was nothing in the public life of Germany to inspire a poet or a writer, until by his deeds he gave a national subject to poetry, and above all a national inspiration. It is only after the Seven Years' War — a fertile war, because a necessary one 58 THE STAETING-POINT. — that the Germans began to feel themselves a nation again. Goethe in his own life has vividly de- scribed the effect of the v^raron the general marasmus of the time, and Gleim's poems, and Lessing's ' Minna,' remain as witnesses of the direct inspira- tion which the nation drew from Frederick's ex- ploits. Nay, his indifference to the literary life of his country was perhaps, I might say certainly, a good thing after all. He allowed it to grow natur- ally, spontaneously, without giving it a direction in an academical or other sense, contenting himself with levelling the ground for it, with making for it a wholesome atmosphere. If Frederick had not ensured absolute liberty of thought to Germany, her literature never would l^ave been what it became, one of the freest of all literatures since the Greek. Well might Schiller sing : Kein Augustisch Alter bliihte, Keines Medicaers Giite Lachelte der deutschen Kunst : * * * * Von dem grossten deutschen Sobne, Von des grossen Friedrichs Throne Ging sie schutzlos, ungeehrt.* ' No Augustan age flourished, the kindness of no Medicis smiled on German Art. From Germany's greatest son, from the throne of the great Frederick, she went unprotected, unhonoured. PEOTESTANTISM. 59 But instead of complaining- of this indifference, Germans ought to thank Frederick for it, in grateful remembrance of Kant's words : ' The age of enlightenment was the century of Frederick the Great/ More than that, the time of the resurrection of the German nation was the time of Frederick ; for it was he who inspired all that made the nation capable of self-assertion — hero- ism, national spirit, religious liberty, modern law ; it was he who gave life and strength to the nucleus which was to become, and deservedly to become, the German State. I said, that next to the Prussian State, it was Protestantism which allowed Germany to raise herself out of the state of intellectual protestant- and moral misery in which the Thirty ^^"^" Years' War had left her. Undoubtedly it was a petrified sort of Protestantism which had sur- vived ; but it was Protestantism, that is to say, relative liberty of religious thought. A revival which assumed the proportions of a new reforma- tion was slowly preparing as early as the second half of the seventeenth century. This reformation was not the work of Government, as that Pietism. of the -sixteenth century had been in England and partly even in Germany. It was 60 THE STARTING-POINT. worked out and spread by individuals. So was its influence an influence on tlie soul, on the inner life, not on the constitution of the Church, still less on government and public life. In both respects, in its origin and in its effects, it bears a close re- semblance to the Evangelical and Wesley an move- ment which took place a century later in this island. It sprang from a want of more intense religious feeling, and so renovated first religion and afterwards society. The old theology had for- gotten the struggle against sin in the struggle about dogma ; pietism left dogma alone, and appealed to the inner voice of revelation. Pietism, indeed, which we are so accustomed to look upon as a narrow or narrowing view of religion, was at first the exact contrary. It was a reaction against the dryness and stiffness of orthodox religion, where theology reigned supreme and dogmas and forms obstructed the direct and spon- taneous communication of the faithful with the Deity. * As Socrates, the new apostles said, had drawn down philosophy from heaven to earth, so they wished that theology should be turned from vain speculations and subtleties in order to show the way of the spirit and of saintliness in the pre- cepts necessary to salvation.' It was thus that PIETISM. 61 pietism brought warmth, and feeling, and life into religion, and, although mixed up with mysticism, acted as a liberating word. This is not the place to dwell on Spener's and Francke's doings, on the expulsion of the latter from Leipzig and his transfer to Halle, which afterwards became the seat of pietism ; nor can I enumerate the schools, the charitable institutions, the secularisa- tion of worship, the collective working establish- ments which owed their existence to Count Zin- zendorf and his Herrnhuter (Moravian bi'ethren). Suffice it to say that the mild charity, the demo- cratic simplicity of these men, won over hundreds and thousands of souls, and that the movement which spread from Halle became a general one in the first half of the past century. Goethe tells us indeed, that ' at this time a certain religious disposition of mind was rife in Germany. In many princely houses there was a genuine religious life ; noblemen were not rare who aimed at true holiness, and in the lower classes this feeling was widely spread.' So it came about that pietism grew into a real power in a very short time. Even the ' monarchs ' began to dread it. The Margrave of Bayreuth was admonished and rebuked for his vices by a pietist preacher in presence of the 62 THE STAETING-POINT. whole congregation, and publicly promised better conduct, and all that was required before he could obtain absolution. When Frederic William I., the king-corporal, was dying, his chaplain, a pietist also, reproached him severely with his accesses of wrath, his armies, the corvees he had inflicted on the peasants, and with his failure to do what he might have done for his poor subjects. However wholesome and fertile pietism might be, it was unable to make good the losses which Scientific ^^^ reformation of the sixteenth century revival. j^^^ sustained by not bringing about a political and national reorganisation. This work was reserved for others. Besides, pietism degene- rated but too soon and became in its turn inanimate and incapable of free action. The inner life, however, had been awakened, and it was not to fall asleep again, because those who stopped at the starting-point claimed the name and inherit- ance of the initiators. On the other hand the reigning philosophy was not without influence on religion ; but the reigning philosophy was not yet that of Locke and Shaftesbury ; it was the theistic philosophy of Descartes, Leibnitz, and WolfiP. The difference is great. The French and English amis des lumieres were Deists, that SCIENTIFIC REVIVAL. 63 is to saj, they arrived by the application of the law of causality in the outward world {i.e. by reasoning and mechanical explanation) at the First Cause or Deity. The German Theists started from Conscience and tried to prove the Deity by the inward revelation of the moral law as it speaks in the bosom of men ; and they invoked the authority of Cartesianism as developed by Leibnitz, and set forth and commented upon by Wolff, which appealed to the innate idea of a Deity as the strongest proof of its existence ; whereas Goethe rightly said of the French of the eighteenth century what he might also have said of the English Deists, — ' They do not understand that there can be anything in man which has not come into him from without.' The philosophy of Descartes, Leibnitz, and Wolff influenced science and moral life before it influenced religion. It was the sight of a superior foreign literature which first awoke the desire of a richer intellectual life in Germany. So the ad- miration of foreign culture became the impulse to the creation of a national one. For this, however, it was necessary to emancipate science from theology, as religion had been emancipated from it already. 64 THE STAETING-POINT. Tlie liberation of man from the yoke of authority, which was properly the idea of the eighteenth century had been aimed at everywhere as early as the end of the preceding century, even in Germany. Whilst Wolff's moral philosophy, which was only that of Leibnitz in a popularised form, emancij^ated morality from theology, it im- parted also a freer view of legislation. Puffendorf followed in the footsteps of Hugo G rotius. He drove the theologians out of political science and founded a purely lay theory of the state ; and although individually the German Lichtfreunde of that time were certainly inferior to a Locke and a Bayle, their immediate practical influence was perhaps greater. Thomasius not only revolutionised law by his teaching, putting it on a natural and rational basis ; he revolutionised teaching itself by the in- troduction of the German language into the uni- versities ; he founded the German Press by his weekly papers ; he j)ut a stop by his agitation to that shame of the age, the trials for sorcery and witchcraft ; he introduced a better tone amongst professors and students ; he dared to say to Frederick the Great's grandfather that the one thing wanting for an intellectual and moral revival in his states was liberty. ' If I must say it SCIENTIFIC REVIVAL. 65 in one word,' he wound up his address to King Frederick, prompting him already to take the lead of Germany by restoring liberty, ' if I must say it in one word it is liberty which gives to all spirit the right life ; and without it human understand- ing, whatever may be its advantages, is, as it were, dead and inanimate. . . . This is the one thing which has given to the Dutch and English so many learned men, whereas the want of this liberty has oppressed the inborn sagacity of the Italians, and the high-flowing mind of the Spaniards. Such liberty would justify the hope that in our Germany also noble minds might apply themselves to wash away that shamefiil spot — the belief in her own incapacity to invent and do anything good and great.' These words were spoken in 1705. The University of Halle had been founded under the protection of the first king of Prussia, Sophia Charlotte's husband, by the regenerators of religion, the pietists,who had been persecuted in Saxony. These, however, had soon fallen them- selves into the intolerance from which they had suffered so much, and waged a terrible war against Thomasius, to whom the king had offered an asylum in Halle when he in turn had been driven ¥ 66 THE STARTING-POINT. out of Leipzig. Did lie not dare together witli Wolff to preach rationalism in those halls which the unworthy followers of Spener and Francke con- sidered as their own realm ? Thomasius died opportunely; Wolff was obliged to leave, when the persecutors got the better of Frederick I.'s successor. Then it was that Miinchhausen founded the University of Gottingen, which henceforward became the stronghold of rationalistic science. It became also the hearth of that new philology which paved the way for a freer assimilation of profane antiquity. Gesner was the first to call the attention of his pupils to the beauty of ancient literature, which, till then, had been nothing more than a drilling instrument; Christ insisted upon the substance of it, the political, religious, above all the artistical life of the ancients, and thus became the creator of modern archseology ; whilst Michaelis through his more methodical study of the eastern languages, and Heine by his sesthetical commen- taries, widened the ground and enlivened the spirit of classical philology. Meanwhile the material and social life of the nation began to improve. The process, however, was very slow, for many of the old hindrances still re- mained. There was no national centre, no industry, THE LITERARY REVIVAL. 67 no commerce. The middle classes might be said to vegetate rather than to live, excluded from all participation in the State, shut up in the petty existence of their small towns, contented in their poverty, and unacquainted with the great currents of life which were flowing elsewhere. Out of their prose of every-day life they fled into the ideal world until they thought that this inner world alone had reality. As soon as the xheUterary wounds began to heal, the interest in ^^'""^^^• moral and intellectual things was at once re- awakened. First it was religion, soon science and poetry, which became the great aflPair of the nation, not a pastime for leisure-hours but the one serious thing, not an ornament of life but the national life itself. There were no courts to protect literature, as we have seen, or to guide it. The new literature sprang from the spontaneous activity of the nation. It freed the courts themselves from foreign manners and foreign culture, and forced the national tongue upon them. Ruhmend darfs der Deutsche sagen, Hoher darf das Herz ihm schlagen, Selbst erschuf er sich den Werth.' * The German has a right to boast of it, his heart may beat higher : for he gave to himself his riches. p 2 68 THE STAETIXG-POINT. There was no return, however, to the popular movement of the sixteenth century, the bridge which might have served for this purpose being irreparably broken. It was a new spirit which rose, individual, not national, but awakening at least, though late, the national spirit, instead of being awakened by it, as was the case elsewhere. Other nations indeed have had a national history and tradition, a centre and a society, wealth and comfort, before they possessed a literature ; in Germany it was the reverse. Literature came first, and gave its character to the slowly forming society instead of i^eceiving it from a society already formed. The impulse came from a concourse of isolated and individual forces and efforts which ran into the same bed. There was no political life, or, if there was any, it was beyond the reach of the middle classes ; but there arose a literary life, in which there was no division into states and provinces, governed and governing, upper and middle classes. Therein, at least, the nation was one ; therein everybody felt himself a German. What a man of talent wrote became at once the property of the nation, whether it was published in Strasburg or in Konigsberg, in Frankfort or in Dresden. All the THE LITEEART REVIVAL. 69 eminent writers of the age travelled from one end of the country to the other, and settled -where they pleased. Nobody thought of asking whether Lessing was a Saxon, Herder a Prussian, Schiller a Wiirtemberger. They all formed one nation. Thus national unity existed in literature long before its political existence was felt as a necessity; but it prepared and brought about political unity in the end. Moreover, and this specially concerns us here, this literature worked out an ensemble of views which became the lay creed of every cultivated German, whether Catholic or Protestant, a creed which is still held by many, I might say, by the whole elite, of the nation, if not outspokenly, at least as the tacitly accepted foundation ground of all their ideas. My object here is to explain what this creed was. At the beginning of the eighteenth century serious attempts had been made to endow Germany with a national literature ; but every- thing was wanting for original production, form as well as substance. The language was still, or rather had become, an unwieldy, awkward engine, composed of fragments of French, Italian, Latin, and legal phraseology. There was nothing 70 THE STARTING-POINT. in the common life of the nation to furnish the subject or the matter of a literature ; no original thought, no great action. The con- sequence was that the new literature continued to be what the literature of the preceding age had been — a stammering imitation of French, Italian, and English models; for Germany had gone through all the phases through which the western literatures had passed in the preceding centuries, following them closely, but without being able to give any life to its servile copies. Yet the writers had an instinctive feeling of the task which they had to fulfil, viz., the creation of a literature at once popular and refined, national and up to the mark of western culture. At the same time they differed as to the way by which this aim was -to be obtained, one side thinking Boileau's * Art Poetique ' the last word of literary legis- lation, the others invoking the authority of English examples. Their appeal, however, was not made so much to Addison and Pope, rational- ists fed with Locke and Shaftesbury, as to Milton, the poet of enthusiasm, and Richard- son the sentimentalist. No doubt they also were liberal Protestants, but they were not ration- alists in the English and French sense of the THE NEW LITEEATURE. 71 word; they were believers, not in tlie letter but in the spirit, and even the letter they com- bated with respect. And this was still the spirit even of the great literary generation which followed them, and began to enter the lists during and shortly after the Seven Years' War (1756 to 1763). In the first third of the eighteenth century, French models still ruled uncontested, and their advocate, Professor Gottsched, in Leipzig, Character was still the absolute sovereign of the of the new literatura German Parnassus. It was against his pedantic and despotic sway that the so-called English school arose in Zurich. A whole library might be filled, not only with the weekly papers, which for the last twenty years had been trying awkwardly enough to fill the place of German ' Tat- lers ' and ' Spectators,' but with the heavy volumes in which the conflicting schools expressed their theories and attacked those of their adversaries. Even when an original literature had begun to spring up, these literary and sesthetical discussions still continued ; in fact, they continued almost to our day. Modern German literature, you see, was not born in a simple, spontaneous, unconscious age, but in an age of criticism ; the war of theories 72 THE STAETHSTG-POINT. raged over its cradle, and with theories it was reared. No wonder that, even when it had reached manhood, it still retained something of these early habits of self-conscious, self-critical production, and appeared somewhat — Sicklied o'er with the pale cast of tliovight ; which does not mean that the German poet, bom in a library, was not to become capable of the fresh- est and most thrilling: utterances as often as he fled from the dust of his book-shelves into the forests and the fields of Franconia and Swabia. Yet you must not forget that this literature was the work of the learned middle-classes, not of idle and wealthy gentlemen, but of needy and hard-work- ing schoolmasters and clergymen. As there was no great national Court, so there was no rich no- bility and gentry to cultivate letters. Nor was there a noblesse de robe, as in France, or a class of well-to-do merchants, as in England, who might have filled up their leisure hours with literary pursuits. Germany boasts of no Montaigne or Montesquieu, no Shaftesbury or Bolingbroke. Men of the social position of Addison and Fielding, of Hume and Gibbon, did not exist, and, when they existed, did not think of literature. This, and the seclusion from political THE NEW LITEKATUEE. 73 life, and tlie absence of publicity, gave German literature its particular character, its wonderful freedom from all general fashion, form, style, con- ventionality, its unique individualism, its daring thought and imagination ; and also its somewhat abstract nature. It sometimes strikes one as a soul without a body. We at once feel that its writers have never known great life, whether social or po- litical. It betrays at the same time a general aver- sion to action and practical aims, as if the inner life alone had any worth and reality. It was only after the terrible blows which in the begin- ning of this century awoke them from their drea,my or ideal life, that the Germans began to compre- hend that their new intellectual liberty could live and last only in an independent and respected State. To revert, however, to the literary strifes of the first half of the past century, it was the English tendency which got the better TheEns- of the contest ; and Richardson was, per- haps, next to Thomson, the writer who contri- buted most to this result. Clumsy translations of Young's ' Night Thoughts,' followed the heavy metrical versions of ' Paradise Lost,' and the ' Seasons.' Their inspiration was, after all, more 74 THE STAETIXG-POIN'T. congenial to tlie G-emian nature, and more adapted to the social and moral state of the German middle-class than Eacine and Corneille, or even Moliere and Lesage. Under this influence — for it is a strange fact that the foundation of a national culture was stOl sought through imitation — and under the tutorship of theoretical criticism, arose a tame and modest, half-sentimental, half- moralising sort of literature, wliich reflected the petty, prosy, every-day life of the small cities of Germany, and which pleased because it reflected it. This humble, timid collection of satires, fables, and idyls, had, howerer, the one merit, till now wanting in all the literary productions of the country, the merit of depicting German life and giving expression to German feelings, instead of describing French and Italian manners, ideas, and characters. This literature was certainly as poor I dare not say poetically, but at least in rhyme and style as the life it depicted — the petty customs, defects, weaknesses, and interests of the poor tutored German middle-class. A host of Dr. Primroses came forward even before the English Dr. Primrose came to life ; but they were Primroses without the delightful irony, if not without the benevolence, of Olivia's father; and THE SETE^' TEAES' WAR. 75 who had never come into contact witli gentlemen like Sir William Thomliill. Few people read GeUert's novels, Eabener's satires, Zacharia's comic poems nowadays ; still the historian will find nowhere a tmer image of the modest conditions of the time than in these pale pictures, which resemble the bleached old photographs of 18-50, to which we still grant a place in onr sitting- room. The Seven Tears' "War soon roused the national spirit to new life after centuries of slumber. For the first time Germans might once more -j^g seyen feel proud of their deeds, and boast of a y^=^"^^- national hero ; and Gleim's ' Grenadiersongs ' (1758) gave vent to this feeling. The German 'Tvrtseus,' as he was ambitiouslv called, was a very mild Tyrtseus, if you like ; still his inspiration was a more visrorous one than that of the timid ^sdrsentimental friends of his vouth. Together with him, however, appeared on the field the somewhat younger generation of the great in- tellectual warriors who definitively freed the German mind from the foreign yoke and the bondage of narrow tradition, and who cleared the ground upon which those who followed were to build. 76 THE STARTING-POINT. Our new literature only began properly to- wards 1760. The hundred precedmg years were Recapituia- entirely filled with the slow and weari- some process of recovery from the material misery and the intellectual, as well as moral decay in which the Thirty Years' War had left us. It required these hundred years before people could attain even that modest degree of well-being which allowed them to give a thought to something else than the care for material existence. It required these hundred years to free German Religion, as well as German Science, from the thraldom of orthodox theology. It required these hundred years to create the beginnings only of a national State, and to reform some, at least, of the abuses of the Empire. It required yet a hundred years more of incessant toil, and four generations of men of genius and of talent, to bring about a really national literature and a really national State, looked up to and respected by the world. No doubt, as this our new State still bears the stamp of its origin — the bureaucratical and military monarchy of Frederick the Great, — so our new literature, very different in this respect from our literature of the Middle Ages, as well as from that of the sixteenth century, is a literature EECAPITULATION. 77 of scholars and officials. It reflects tlie intellectual and moral life of that class. It does not depict a large social and public life, which did not exist when it sprang up, and which has scarcely come even now, when all has been done that was neces- sary to clear the ground for it — perhaps because our history, our intellectual and moral aptitudes, make us less fit than other nations for such a life, and assign to us other and by no means lower fields of activity. Be this as it may, you will never under- stand our political and literary conditions if you forget the starting-point of modern Germany ; if you do not remember that, whereas the German of the sixteenth century was fully on a par with the Englishman, Frenchman, and Italian, in material and intellectual, as well as in moral and social, respects, the German of the seventeenth century was thrown back into utter barbarism by the Thirty Years' War. When our country, at the end of that cruel time, towards 1650, set out on a new career, she had everything to rebuild anew; state and religion, wealth and society, science and literature, language, even, and mo- rality. The start of two hundred years, which western Europe thus had over Germany, is still apparent in our society and manners, in our 78 THE STAETING-POINT. wealth and comfort. We have the presumption to believe that intellectually and morally — politi- cally, also, since 1866, if we do not cling to the prejudice that parliamentary government is the only one worthy of a civilised nation — we have again come up with our western neighbours in the great race of civilisation, in which men are not rivals but fellow-workers. 79 LECTUEB III. THE SEEDS OF GERMAN THOUGHT. (1760-1770.) It was during, and shortly after, the Seven Years' War (1756 to 1763) that the first generation of the great founders of our national culture made their appearance. There are three generations, indeed, which followed each other at twenty years' distance, and which almost entirely did the great work of German culture, of which I have genera- T • 1 tions. undertaken to trace the outlines in these short lectures. The first, born between 1715 and 1735, the generation of Klopstock, Wieland, Winc- kelmann, Kant, Mendelssohn, above all, Lessing, whose principal works were published between 1750 and 1770, when these men were from thirty to fifty years old. The second generation, born in the middle of the century, included Herder and Voss, Klinger and Biirger, Goethe and Schiller, 80 THE SEEDS OF GERMAN THOUGHT. whose greatest and most fertile activity displayed itself equally during tlieir'fuU manhood, from 1770 to 1800. Finally, in the third generation, born be- tween ] 760 and 1780, the most conspicuous names were those of the two Schlegels, the two Humboldts, Tieck, Rahel, Schleiermacher, Niebuhr, Savigny and Schelling, whose followers acted more parti- cularly in the first quarter of the present century. The two schools which, from 1825, to 1850, influenced the German mind most powerfully, the school of Hegel and that of Gervinus, only con- tinued, developed, summed up, applied, or contra- dicted the main ideas of the three preceding great generations ; they did not properly put forth and circulate new ideas. It was a manly and robust generation, the generation of Klopstock, Wieland, Lessing, which was also that of Frederick, Winckelmann, and Kant. They almost all were born in the humblest stations of life, and fought their way through direst privation ; but the struggle for life was not capable of stifling in them the sense of the ideal. You all know how Klopstock was formed by Kio stock English, Wieland by French models. bom 1724. "pjjgy -were, however, no servile imitators ; and they are thus distinguished from the Brookes KLOPSTOCK. 81 and Gottsclieds of the preceding age. TLey filled their works with a spirit of their own, and modified even the forms which they borrowed, so as to accommodate them to the genius of their own language. The tendency of their age was still that of the beginning of the century : a deeply religious spirit, but one which believed more in the continuous revelation of God throuorh con- science than in the historical revelation of the Orthodox, or the argumentation of the Deists, rejDresenting God as the great architect of this material machine. It was partly because Klopstock gave a poetical expression to this feeling that his poem acted so powerfully ; and partly also because its form seemed an entirely German one, although the verse was the classical hexameter of the ancients, now for the first time quite assimilated and mastered, as that generation believed. Ger- many imagined that she too possessed a * Paradise Lost,' and welcomed in the bard of the * Messiah ' the interpreter of its innermost thought. Then at last Germany had a German poem, both in sub- stance and form ; and neither substance nor form was of the mediocre, prosy, and humble kind to which German genius seemed till then condemned. Thought and language soai'ed high — too high, G 82 THE SEEDS OP GERMAN THOUGHT. perhaps, for us to follow it still with our clipped wings — yet it proved to the nation that she might attempt what other nations had successfully at- tempted before her. Whilst Klopstock's inspiration was Christian and Teutonic, that of Wieland was more ration- Wieiand alistic and cosmopolitan. If Klopstock born 1733. -j^g^^gi^^ ^j^g German language strength and flight, Wieland gave it fluency and elegance. He became, indeed, the very creator of a simple, easy, and natural prose, the most necessary instru- ment of culture. German prose before Wieland was pedantic, stiff, intricate : with some writers it is so still. Wieland gave it the tone of polite society ; taught it how to handle iron}^ how to be witty with grace and decorum. He him- self had belonged entirely to the school of the French, particularly to that of Yoltaire, and among the English, Shaftesbury, the virtuoso, had been the chief object of his study and predilection. When he wrote his philosophical novels and minor poems in Voltaire's manner, Germany seemed at first astonished to see that her heavy language could be capable of such charming, jDrattling talk. Wieland won over to it the higher classes, then exclusively bred in French ; he made German Ian- WIELAND. 83 guage and literature 7iq^d7% (admissible at Court). At the same time lie popularised the English and French philosophy of the time. The popular philosophers of Berlin, such as Mendelssohn and Nicolai, the friends of Lessing, would have been impossible without Wieland ; and their influence was great. As Klopstock and his followers had given a poetical expression to the religious feeling of the nation, independent of, and superior to, dogma and outward w^orship, so Wieland directed the war of the century against sacerdotalism and theology with the somewhat blunted, but not less effective, arms, which German free-thought has ever since used against Church and dogma ; for Germany seemed to have found at least the proper vehicle to enable her to join in the movement of Western culture, instead of following it at a dis- tance. Now, only, she seemed to have made that culture completely her own. This was necessary ; but it was not suffi- cient. She wanted also to be able to go on alone and without anybody's help. She was no longer the province of a foreign civilisation, but she was still a tributary. And she had to be freed from this allegiance also, and to be received on an equal foot- ing in the intellectual society of Europe, before she G 2 84 THE REEDS OF GERMAN THOUGHT. could work on lier own account. More than this : after having obtained an entire command over foreign culture, after having not only accepted but digested and assimilated it, it became neces- sary that she should react against it : for all life- brinoingf movement is action and reaction. Lessing undertook the task. It was he who founded the literary independence of Germany Lessinff ^J rebelling against the foreign laws, bora 1729. ^yj^j^^j^ j^g^^j remained even after the foreign rulers had yielded the place to home-born leaders ; and he freed, not Germany alone, but the whole world, when he gave the deadly blow to the con- ventional classicism of the French. For it is hard to believe that Byron, Manzoni, Victor Hugo himself could have written what they wrote, without Lessing's ' Dramaturgic ' ? When Lessing attacked the French poetical laws and rules, they were still universally acknowledged. Addison had written his ' Cato ' in conformity with them, and Pope recognised no higher authority ; and, long after them, Moratin preferred Racine to his own Cal- deron, as they had placed Corneille over Shake- speare. Nay, even after Lessing, but before his influence could be felt on the other side of the Alps, Alfieri, the Misogallo, cast his impetuous LESSING. 85 thought in the French mould. Lessing was the first revolt against that law, and to show that it was entirely conventional and arbitrai'j, adhering to outward and accidental forms, instead of to the essence of ancient poetry. From Boileau's theories he appealed to Aristotle, from Corneille's practice to that of Shakespeare, whom he proved to be a truer, although unconscious, follower of Sophocles than Corneille. But Aristotle himself and Shake- speare he treated as a true Protestant treats the Bible : with the spirit of free inquiry. He did not submit to Aristotle because he was Aristotle, but because he discovered in him ' truth as sure as that of Euclid. ' At the same time, adding example to theory, he gave to Germany literary works of his own at once popular and refined, such as she had yearned for so long. He united Wieland's realism with Klopstock's idealism in works which have survived, whilst those of Klopstock and Wieland can scarcely be said to be still living. He gave a model of the free dramatic form, which he wanted to substitute for the French pattern, in his ' Emilia Galotti.' He gave words to the first national enthusiasm felt by modern Germany at Frederick's deeds in his ' Minna von Barnhelm.' Nay, the whole re- 86 THE SEEDS OF GERMAN THOUGHT. ligious and pliilosopliieal creed of his generation he expressed in his ' Nathan,' for which his friend Mendelssohn sat as model, and which he left as a legacy to the nation, to the world. The spirit of toleration, together with a firm belief in a good and just Deity, breathes in every page of that wonderful work, in which the best ideas of the age are summed up. For what he had done for litera- ture he did for religion ; what he had done for Aristotle he did for Luther. ' The true Lu- theran,' he exclaimed, ' does not want to be protected by Luther's writings, but by Luther's spirit, and Luther's spirit exacts absolutely that no man should be prevented from communicating his progress in knowledge to others.' He would not allow the Protestant clergy to assume an authority which the spirit of Protestantism for- bids them to claim, and declared loudly that he would be ' the first to take back the Pope for the pox^elings ' if they should put a stop to free inquiry. And as his * Nathan ' showed religious feeling to be independent of, and superior to, established forms of religion, so in his ' Education of Mankind ' he showed that morality is indepen- dent even of religious belief; and that the good done for the satisfaction of one's own conscience is "WIXCKELMANN". 87 superior to that wliicli is done with a hope of re- compense in a future life, the preoccupation of such a life being rather an impediment than a furtherance towards making the best use of this existence. 'Why not quietly wait for a future life, as one waits for the morrow ? ' without wish- ing to investigate what cannot be investigated, the things which it will bring? Who knows whether there will not come ' a new eternal gospel,' promised in the New Testament, and which will be to Christianity what Christianity was to Juda- ism, a third stage in the long education of man- kind by God, for whom ' the shortest line is not always a straight line ' ? In such ideas, however, Lessing was far in advance of his generation, for he not only gave the last expression to the past, but he also opened the door for the coming age. He, as well as Kant and Winckelmann, stood with his feet in the eighteenth century ; with his head he already reached the nineteenth. Winckelmann had published his ' History of Art ' in 1764 ; so had Kant his ' Observations on the Sublime.' In 1766, just a hundred years before the auspicious birthday of the German State, appeared his ' Dreams of a Visionary,' W^inckelmann's ' Allegory,' Lessing's ' Laocoon,' 88 THE SEEDS OF GERMAN THOUGHT. and the most suggestive book perhaps ever written, Herder's ' Fragments,' They announced to the world that the years of apprenticeship were over for Germany, and that she had begun to work on her own account. The medium through which the modern classicaj writers of the Italian and French type View of looked at antiquity was Roman civilisa- antiquity. ^j^j^^ Ever since the Jesuits had become masters of public education in the neo-Latin coun- tries, they had seen how easy it would be in nations, whose Church, whose language, and whose legal traditions were Roman, to put the Latin literature in the foreground. They felt at the same time how important for their aim it would be to mould men's minds by Roman antiquity, the spirit of which is discipline, instead of feeding them with Greek antiquity, the essence of which is freedom. While the contemporaries of Angelo Poliziano and Marsilio Ficino still lived under the charm of the Hellenic civilisation, those of Bembo and Alamanni were already under the spell of Latin Alexandrinism. Lessing had been as attentive a reader of Sophocles as of Shakespeare ; and when he pro- posed the latter instead of Corneille as a model to the future dramatic poets of Germany, it was WINCEELMANN'S ' HISTORY OF ART.' 89 because he saw in him, in spite of his irregular form, a more faithful, if not a more systematic fol- lower of the ancients, than in Racine and Corneille. Here also it was not the letter which he preached, but the spirit. He protested against the whole way of looking at the ancients, which had reigned ever since Trissino and Tasso, as against a sort of third Alexandrinism. For, according to him, they saw the importance of ancient literature where it was not, in accidental outward forms ; and sacri- ficed to these that which had really inspired the ancients — natural beauty. He wished his age and his nation to do what the great artists of the Renaissance had done, before academical classicism had set in, viz., to look on Nature and Man directly with clear, sound, unprejudiced eyes, such as the Greeks had brought to the contemplation of things ; and to create, if necessary, new forms for new thoughts and feelings. It is highly important to notice that a new view of antiquity, entirely opposed to the academical one, was the basis of the literary edifice which Germany was about to build. Hence also the importance of Winckel- niann's ' History of Art,' which, as I have said, appeared in 1764, and of his ' Allegory ' which was published in 1766, 90 THE SEEDS OF GERMAN THOUGHT. Winckelmann's ' History of Art ' is at once a system of aesthetics and a history. There may be, and there are, many points on which we Winckel- mann, born are at variance with Winckelmann, and 1717. the fundamental idea even of his sreat book — that the aim of art is the creation of ideal forms — is no longer, I hope, admitted by SBsthetic criticism. Nevertheless, his book acted as if it was a revelation of the Hellenic world. Winckel- mann had himself something of the s^^irit of the Greeks, and so became naturally their most elo- quent interpreter. It was as if he had brushed away the dust from the ancients, and revealed to view the purity of their outlines, buried as they were under a dense layer of rubbish. He en- deavoured to show in language hitherto unparal- leled — a prose lofty and noble, nay, majestic, with- out affectation, and correct without purism — in a language worthy of the ancients, that the Greek art of the time of Pericles rested on the same basis as the Platonic philosophy ; the basis of idealism, contemplating the real world as a reflection of the world of ideas, and trying to reconstruct for the senses, as Plato tried to do for the intellect, those ideas which were like the lost types of the created world. Against the unquiet, overladen style of his own time, he invoked the calm and sim^^Hcity INFLUENCE OF WINCKELMANN". 91 of Greek art, even introducing into painting the rules of sculpture. Although this reaction against rococo degenerated soon — as all reactions will do — and degenerated into the cold and dry school of a new Academy, almost worse than the Berninesque school which it superseded, yet it was a necessary reaction, and one which, if it has done no good in the domain of the fine arts, has had most fertile re- sults for poetry. Goethe's ' Iphigenia,' and ' Alexis and Dora,' would never have been written, if Winckelmann had not first unveiled the ideal beauty of Greek antiquity. The powdered and patched Greek heroines of Voltaire's tragedy be- came henceforward as impossible as the senti- mental or raging heroes of Crebillon. For they were totally devoid of that ' noble simplicity and calm grandeur' which Winckelmann had estab- lished as the first principle of Greek art. If men like David and Ingres, Canova and Thorwaldsen, who were directly or indirectly disciples of Winckelmann, proved themselves unable to create an Iphigenia, at once Greek and modern, ideal and real, full of life and full of measure, it was because the generation to which they belonged entirely lacked the natural disposition which makes great artists, that spontaneous, direct intuition, which is unbiassed by abstract thought 92 THE SEEDS OP GEHMAN THOUGHT. and abstract systems. It was also — I will not deny it — because the new theory could not be ac- cepted throughout. Sculpture had tried to produce the effects of painting. Winckelmann went into the other extreme by introducing into painting the rules of sculpture. But, we have not to ask ourselves here whether the action of Winckel- mann was beneficial or not ; only what it was, and how far it reached. But Winckelmann did even more in his History than reveal the principle of Greek Art. He gave the first example of modern historical method. All histories of Art, like those of literature, had been till then collections of biogra- phies, lists of titles, and analyses or descriptions of difi'erent works, with an account of their vicissi- tudes. Winckelmann was not only the first to dis- tinguish the difi'erent periods of Art as coinciding with the different styles; he also described its growth and decay as if it were a natural vegetation, showed the causes of this growth and decay — climate, national character and national manners, political history, religion, race — and thus restored the unity of History. Thus Winckelmann first introduced, not in theory, but in practice, the idea of organic and historical development, which is pro- FEENCH CULTURE. 93 perly the German idea. In his hands the history of the infancy, adolescence, youth, maturity, and old age of Art became a system of the different styles, and vice versa. He expelled the concep- tion of arbitrary creation by intellects independent of circumstances from the domain of Art-history ; and it was only after Winckelmann had shown Fine Arts to be the result of the general condition of a given civilisation, that other writers began to apply the same idea to Poetry, Philosophy, Religion and the State. The first seed of the German idea was thrown into the world. But althouo-h Winckelmann had awakened the sense for the ' noble simplicity and calm grandeur * of ancient Art, he had not been able to Lessin^-g divest himself of certain intellectual '-^^ocoon.' habits of his time. As he had proposed ideal forms as the highest aim of Art, ix. forms which do not exist in nature, but are the product of the idealising mind, and had combined the fruits of his various observations into one patchwork called ideal beauty, so he had raised no objection against abstract thought becoming the object of Art, in other words, against allegory. This was the legacy of the French rationalistic culture of the first half of the century against which Lessing 9.4 THE SEEDS OP GEEMAN THOUGHT. Avas to lead the reaction. The French of that time approached Poetry as they approached Re- ligion, as they approached the State, with the conviction that the organ of understanding was able to produce intentionally and consciously what in reality has always been the joroduct of other human faculties acting almost unconsciously ; they believed in inventors of religion as in inventors of constitutions. Hence a confusion of all the activities of the human mind. People believed that the Fine Arts could serve to explain abstract thought, which is allegory, and again that words might paint objects, which produced descriptive poetry. The simple explanation that words, sounds, forms, and colours are different languages for different orders of mental activity had been entirely lost sight of. Experience taught that none of these mental faculties could work when isolated, without the aid of the others ; the inference was drawn that each might do the work of the other. People wanted to express in forms and colours, that is, in the language of the Fine Arts, what can only be expressed in words ; and they wanted to express in words what can only be expressed in sounds, i.e. music. The great historical importance of Les- sing's ' Laocoon ' lies in the fact that it put a stop rUKCTIONS OF THE ARTS. 95 once for all to that confusion — once foi' all, if eveiy- body had known how to read it, or had consented to read it as it was written. We should not have musicians who are content to interpret words, or painters who condescend to illustrate novels and poems, if the necessary consequences had been drawn from Lessing's premises. For in his com- parison between Virgil's description of Laocoon's death and the famous group in the Vatican, he traced the impassable boundary which sepa- rates Fine Arts and Poetry. The Fine Arts have to show things in space and to the eyes. Poetry in time and through the ears to the in- tellect : the inference is that the subjects of the Fine Arts must be circumscribed objects, or, at least, lasting situations as extended in space and capable of being embraced in one glance, whereas the subjects of poetry must be actions accomplished in time, and conveyed to the intellect in their successive stages. When, con- sequently, the poet wants to treat the same subject as the artist, he must first transform it into action, as Homer did with Achilles' shield and Helen's beauty (her appearance before and impression on the old men of Troy) ; or Goethe, when he describes the gardens of Hermann's father, by following 96 THE SEEDS OF GERMAN THOUGHT. the steps of his mother from one part to the other. If, on the contrary, the artist wishes to treat a poetical subject, he must first transform the action into a situation of some duration. As a rule it would be better still to avoid such a subject altogether ; but if he does take it he must first modify it, choosing in the action that moment which is most lasting and at the same time most pregnant, i.e. in which there is contained most of the past and of the coming moment. There is much to object to in this theory which would condemn altogether such masterpieces as Eubens' Lionhunt or Gericault's Hussars, and is not only, as it seems to me, a most insufficient defi- nition of the artistic object, but also leaves un- touched the far more important side of the question, viz., the subjective origin of a work of art. On the whole we should be justified in saying that Lessing's artistic education was very incomplete, his artistic organisation, if he had any, hardly at all developed. This, in fact, is somcAvhat the fault of all the German aesthetic theories which have been brought forward during the last hundred years ; nay, Lessing, who saw the point in poetry so ad- mirably, still harboured the false and hollow con- ception of the ideal which was the principal mis- LESSING ON POETRY. 97 take of Winckelmann. Be this, however, as it may, I am not here to criticise, but to explain, and I turn again to Lessing's proper field, litera- ture, where his thought was to bear fruit a hun- dredfold. The essence of poetry, Lessing taught, is action ; but action which reveals the complete- ness of human nature, and which must therefore show man in the free movement of passion. The aim of poetry, then, is to reproduce human passions, and to inspire sympathy with them, but a sympathy purely human, free from all personal interest ; and, as poetry is not to produce in us real, material fear and hope, so it does not pursue either moral or religious or political aims : it has its aim in itself. ' True Art' [Darstellung), says Goethe, 'has no aim; it neither approves nor disapproves ; it develops the feelings and actions as they follow each other and out of each other, and by this, and this alone, it enlightens and teaches.' With this the didactic poem was banished from literature, as the descrip- tive had been banished from it by the former theory. And this was the second seed sown be- tween 1760 and 1770. If Winckelmann and Lessing reacted against the sesthetic views of the French, Kant and H 98 THE SEEDS OF GERMAN THOUGHT. Herder received their first impulse from them : Kant born ^°^ from Voltaire, it is true, nor from the ^''^'^' Encyclopaedists (with the exception of Diderot, who diflfered from them in many- respects, and had immense influence on German thought), but principally from Buffon and Rousseau. In his metaphysical thought Kant rests entirely on Newton. He started from Locke and Hume in his psychology, which overthrew all metaphysics as they had been taught till then. In his views of history and humanity, with which we are more especially concerned here, he owed as much to Rousseau, although he reacted partly against him, as he did against Hume's psychology. This he only developed twenty years later, thereby producing in philosophical science a revolution only to be compared with that effected by Newton in the natural sciences ; but they belong to the periods which we shall have to consider in our fifth lecture. To-day we must fix our attention on the Kant of 1766, not tlie Kant of 1787. Till then, as he shows in his ' Natural History of the Heavens,' which was inspired by Newton, Kant considered the history of mankind, somewhat like that of nature, in the light of a deadly struggle for life. Just as our planet through terrible cata- Rousseau's ethics. 90 stroplies and cataclysms had shaped itself into a dwelling for reasonable beings, so humanity ad- vances through wars and revolutions towards per- fection ; and just as nature emerges more and more out of chaos into organisation, so the human mind frees itself more and more from the tumult of blind passions, and through perfecting of the intellect forms a pure image of the eternal har- mony of the universe. Few individuals, however, attain this lofty aim ; the great majority vege- tate like plants; millions of germs perish; the progress of humanity takes place only in the high spheres of a privileged few. This aristocratic belief was deeply shaken by the reading of Eousseau's works towards 1760. Rousseau, as you all remember, saw in the progress of art and science the cause of immorality as well as of inequality among men. He represented the natural state of man as good, and contended that his superiority over animals was not in his intelli- gence, but in his heart. Now, as feeling is not, like intelligence, the privilege of a few, as it is the common possession of men, the whole demo- cratic view of Eousseau results from this deceptive paradox. Kant adopted this theory, though in a modified form, in his * Considerations on the Senti- E 2 100 THE SEEDS OF GERMAN THOUGHT. ment of tlie Beautiful and the Sublime,' whicli appeared in 1764, eight years after Burke's ■work on the same subject, with which, however, it has much less in common than with Lessino-'s ^Laocoon.' According to Kant's correction of Eousseau's views, it is no longer the intellectual culture of privileged classes or individuals which is the aim of history, but the culture of the masses through the education of their feelings. In this respect he allows that a retrograde move- ment has taken place, which is also a progres- sive one — retrograde compared with Greek anti- quity ; progressive compared with the savage state of primitive tribes. For he holds that the per- fection of human nature was realised in the simple civilisation of the ancients, and by no means shares Eousseau's enthusiasm for savasres. He preaches a return to nature, but finds nature, not in the primitive times which knew no art and no thought, but, like Winckelmann, in the Hellenic civilisation which had remained faithful to nature. There, indeed, was a union of true nature and true culture, and Kant hoped that humanity might come again to such a state through a simpler education ; nay, he believed that it will be the final result of all the warfare and movement kant's idea op civilisation. 101 of history. No doubt, man only acts witliin the given limits of nationality, epoch, and climate ; but he must strive, and will strive with success, to de- velop more and more the purely human in him- self. National distinctions will not, therefore, disappear ; only they will be no longer contrasts, but merely varieties and gradations of character — a view which was entirely accepted by Lessing and Herder, Goethe and SchiUer, and has re- mained the German view of cosmopolitanism and nationality. Kant goes a step farther on the way to which Eousseau had directed him. The motive power in Nature is pleasure and pain, the sensation of what furthers and what im- pedes the development of life. But in man a whole series of more delicate sensations is added to those of pleasure and pain : the sensations of ideal worth, sensations which are less strong but more durable than the material ones. Such is the feeling of honour — an inferior feeling still, because it depends upon the judgment of others and implies a selfish personal interest. Such is sympathy, which is above all selfish personal interest — nay, is the contradiction of it — but lacks duration and con- sistency. Such is above all the feeling of duty, which makes us sacrifice our personal interest, not 102 THE SEEDS OF GERMAN THOUGHT. according to momentary impulse, but to a fixed and durable rule of conduct. It has its origin in the feeling of one's own dignity, which dignity we grant to every other human being, and which we respect in him ; for man, who lives in conformity with nature, both esteems himself and considers every human being as a fellow-creature deserving esteem. This feeling once awakened, the beauty of the soul becomes the highest eesthetic and moral ideal. Among the moderns, the Italians through fine art, the French through elegance and taste, the English through earnestness and depth, have come nearest to this ideal. 'By their feeling of duty, by their unbending fidelity to principles, by their enthusiasm for the rights and dignity of man, the English set an example to all nations.' The Germans follow slowly in the cultivation of sesthetic and moral feeling. Once freed and cured of their present vices, leading a free and national life, they will perhaps unite the virtues of the French and English, delicacy of taste and a strong sense of duty ; and a new Hellenic life will blossom once more. This hope, this ideal, animated the whole of this and the next generation. Ger- many was to become a new Greece ; humanism in the highest sense, intellectual, moral, and herder's first appearance. 103 social, was to be realised by Ler. But none at that time, except Kant and Herder, saw clearly what was the preliminary condition for such a second Renaissance. 'What is wanting to our country,' said Herder, almost at the same moment as Kant, ' is public feeling, a noble pride, which is not to be organised according to foreign patter us, but will organise itself according to its own nature, as other nations have always done : to be Germans on our own well-defended soil.' So spoke the fourth of the German prophets, Herder. He was the first to draw out the con- sequences involved in the teaching of his master, Kant, that the purely human was the aim of history and culture, a teaching which we ought to consider as the seed which, next to Winckelmann's and Lessing's, worked most powerfully on the German mind. True, Kant's earlier writings (although composed in a style of such eloquence that the reader sometimes wonders how the same hand could have written in the dry and abstract style of the ' Critic of Judgment ') did not waken so loud an echo as the contemporary works of Winckelmann, Lessing, and Herder. Still they fell on good ground, and proved in the long run as fertile as, perhaps more fertile than, the seeds sown by his contemporaries. 104 THE SEEDS OF GERMAN THOUGHT. I have pronouncecl the name of Herder, and I have called him a prophet. Such a name he indeed Herder dcserves more, perhaps, than any man of born 1744. ^^^ ^^^^ centnrj. He had the soul and he had the language of a seer, and it was as a seer that he worked upon his contemporaries. In reality he belongs to the next generation, although his first Avork appeared at the same moment as the writ- ings, which I have noticed, of Winckelmann, Lessing, and Kant. He was only twenty-two, and an obscure teacher in the distant Baltic provinces under Eussian rule, when his Tragmente' ap- peared in 1766, and ran through Germany with the quickness of a train of gunpowder. With him, then, the new generation made its entrance. Older than Goethe, Biirger, Jacobi, Yoss, by four or five years only, he became their master at once, the preacher of the new literary gospel, to whom they listened as if he had been inspired. It is perhaps — nay, it is certainly — a great dis- advantage that I should have chosen a subject and adopted a plan of treating it, which obliges me to pass by the men and their lives, their moral character, their living persons, and to present to you only their ideas, detached from life like fruits from the tree : their ideas, moreover, in an INFLUENCE OP HERDER. 105 abstract form and condensed in a few words. Still the subject is so vast, and our time so sliort, that I must needs thus confine myself, however dry and unattractive my subject must consequently become. I regret it often, however, and never can I regret it more than when I speak of Herder, who was neither a great writer, nor a great in- vestigator and discoverer, nor an accomplished poet, but who was a mighty personality and whose doctrine itself was, so to speak, the doctrine of personality. No one, Kant perhaps alone excepted, has con- tributed more to the stock of German thought, or has ever exercised greater or more lasting influence over an age, a nation, or the world at large than Herder. Like the genuine rebel he was, he began by turning upside down the science and literature which then reigned, as Kant was to do with the philosophical speculation of his time. He was a revolutionist indeed. Lessing would fain have paused after having freed the laws of composition from the hoary over- growth of time, false interpretation, and erroneous application. He never had the slightest intention of attacking the laws themselves. But, however great a man's genius may be, he cannot stem at 106 THE SEEDS OP GERMAN" THOUGHT. Lis will the current whicli carries away a wliole generation witli it — particularly when lie has himself cleared the road for it by removing the obstacles which stood in its way. Every Mirabeau finds a Danton to outstep him. Lessing had claimed the right of individual genius to modify rule, and five years had hardly elapsed after the publication of his * Dramaturgic ' when .the literary montagne already urged a radical abo- lition of all literary legislation and proclaimed the right of genius to absolute self-government. Reform had drifted into revolution ; and Herder was marching at the head of the insurgents. Before showing the influence exercised by Herder over his contemporaries, let us see what was the nature of the new principle applied by him to theology, history, and poetry. It was the superiority of nature over civilisation, and of in- tuition over reason. The essence of Herder's ideas lay in continually opposing synthesis to analysis, the individual to rule, spontaneous im- pulse to conscious action, organism to mechan- ism, development and growth to legislation and creation — in a word, in placing the Jieri above the facere. This was the basis of the creed professed by that school of ' original geniuses ' IDEAS OF NATURE. 107 •which he was leading to battle against the religious, literary, and scientific rationalism of the age. No man finds his starting-point within himself. The starting-point of German thought was in France, as that of French thought had been in England. It was more particularly from Rousseau that Herder received his first impulse. Rousseau's The reaction against the exclusive wor- " ^*^"^^' ship of reason had begun precisely in those countries which had been foremost in establishing it. It was the land of Pope and Hume which gave birth to Burns and Burke; and the writings of Lowth and Wood, of Young and Macpherson had struck out in literature and criticism that path on which Eousseau was to lead the latter half of the century in political and social matters. Mankind was to return to nature, to that good parent whose works had become disfigured by the manners and customs of a polished, refined society. It is difficult for us in our days to form any ade- quate conception of the effect produced by Eous- seau's ' Discourse on Inequality ' at the time when it appeared. ' It is impossible to speak otherwise than v«^ith secret veneration of these lofty ideas and sublime thoughts,' exclaimed Lessing, then 108 THE SEEDS OP GEEMAN THOUGHT. a young man, but already very little disposed to be sentimental. Kant actually forgot bis daily walk while be perused * Emile.' Even ten years later, Scbiller compared Eousseau to Socrates — * Rousseau, wbo perisbed by tbe bands of Cbris- tians ; Eousseau, wbo would fain make buman beings out of Cbristians.' Herder, wbile yet a student, addressed entbusiastic verses to Rousseau, in wbicb be cbose bim for * bis guide tbrougb life.' One must read tbe description wbicb Goetbe bas left of tbe impression made on tbe youth of Ger- many by Rousseau's works. What it was in France is well known. We smile at those diminutive English parks which replaced Le Notre's stately avenues, at tbe farmyards established in royal de- mesnes, and at tbe queens wbo turned themselves into dairymaids. When we read of tbe great ladies of the eighteenth century suckling their infants amidst a group of elegants, we are often tempted to see more affectation in it than there really was. Everything in that powdered and hooped company bad become so artificial that any symptom of naturalism appeared as a deliverance, passed for a protest against unnatural refinement, and really was a thoroughly justified reaction against the opposite extreme. Nothing, indeed. POETRY AND COMMON SENSE. 109 could be more justifiable than Rousseau's oppo- sition to Voltaire and tbe Encjclopeedists ; far wliat was it but tlie rebellion of feeling against reason which till then had restrained and en- thralled it — of feeling which burst the tight ligatures bj which men had sought to confine their hearts, in the effort to shake off reason's yoke and obtain breathing room for itself? In Germany too, the spirit of the * Encyclo- psedia' was then reigning, or at least threaten- ing to reign. The great Frederick, Nicolai and his followers in Berlin, Wieland himself, were con- firmed rationalists at heart, although the rational- ism of the latter was draped in Shaftesbury's sesthetical epicurism. We find common sense, not sentiment, ruling all things. Even in Mendelssohn and Lessing, although their in- spira,tion is so different from that of the French and English rationalists, light is the characteristic quality. How should such minds, in which everything was clearness, precision, and accuracy, have any room left for vague twi- light ? Now, that same precise, matter of fact, uncompromising thing which we denominate common sense never did engender poetry, and chiaroscuri will exist in the depths of man's 110 THE SEEDS OP GERMAN THOUGHT. nature. Such things as dim apprehensions, pre- sentiments, reverie, lie dormant within the in- nermost recesses of the human soul — nay, form, mayhap, the most precious of its treasures. If we seek to light up these dark corners, not by the mild and unfailing light of inward revelation or intuition, but by the dazzling and often mis- leading lantern of reason, we may chase from their haunts the spirits which have taken up their abode there. Then, as often happens, we may only suc- ceed in driving them to seek refuge in mystery elsewhere, and to assume the form of a grosser superstition, while, if wholly cast out, they leave behind them a blank void together with a painful longing to fill it up again. An Aene- sidemus provokes an Apollonius of Tjana ; and the d'Holbachs and Helvetiuses are followed by the Cagliostros and Mesmers. Herein lay Herder's right of protest against the prose of common sense, as against the moralising didacti- cism of German poetry, from which even Lessing was unable entirely to free his contemporaries, and against the petrified forms of citizen life, religion and science in Germany ; for Herder's protest against one-sided rationalism never de- generated into a defence of superstition or mys- ticism. HERDER AND ROUSSEAU. Ill Whereas Eousseau had chiefly sought to re- establish nature's rights in social matters, Herder wished to establish them in things of the Herder's intellect. In that lies his originality. It i^^^^ipies. was by this he developed and continued what Kous- seau had begun, and it was by this that he was finally induced to turn round upon Rousseau and react against him. While searching for nature's unconscious proceeding in her intellectual creation of what we call language, religion, and poetry, he ended by discovering the secret of her process in creating society and the state, and found this pro- cess to be the antipodes of the Contrat Social. You will find in Herder's earliest writings the ideas developed twenty-five years later in Burke's ' Re- flections.' ' But it was not Rousseau alone who acted upon Herder and his master Haraann, ' the Magi- cian of the North,' as they used to call him. Herder's mind was stirred by the English works on Homer, by the poetry of the Bible, by Shake- speare, by Percy's ballads ; as he was also im- ' Mr. Leslie Stephen and Mr. John Morley have abundantly proved that Burke expressed this fundamental belief of his life as early as 1756 in his Vindication of Natural Socii'tij ; but he expressed it en jMissant without developing it, and without finding an echo, as he did thirty-live years later, and as Herder did from the outset. 112 THE SEEDS OF GERMAN THOUGHT. pressed by Buffon's profound views of nature and the cohesion of intellectual and physical life. Still it was Eousseau's idea, that the condition of human development lay in the enlightenment and perfecting, not of our reasoning faculty, but of our feelings, which led him to investigate the elementary operations of the soul. These operations soon assumed in his eyes the character of infallible powers. Instinctive, intuitive man, with all the energies of body and mind unimpaired, became the ideal man. Everybody and every- thing was to be looked at, not dissolved, as abstract philosophy had dissolved it, into its parts by analysis, nor detached from the natural cir- cumstances, but in the combination of the parts in an indivisible whole. So everybody was to act. Coherence, cohesion became the watch- word. Not isolated faculties, but only all the faculties combined, could grasp the outward as well as the inner world. Intuition is all. Es- thetic rules as well as moral laws ought to be put aside. Even in science sight is to replace analysis. Here we have the germ of that contrast between Herder and Kant which was to break out so much later. Indeed, both Kant and Herder gave definitive and systematic shape to their ideas only HERDER AND KANT. 113 twenty years later, and, although starting from the same point, reached very different conclusions. So did Goethe and Schiller, whose poetical pro- duction began under the powerful influence of Herder's views, but was afterwards deeply modi- fied through Kant and a more methodical study of nature. To-day we only contemplate their spring, which was the sj)ring also of German in- tellectual life — a spring full, of course, like all springs, of promises which were not kept ; full of terrible storms also, which, however, proved to be salutary in the end ; full, above all, of a charming freshness Avhich the literature of summer did not find again. Herder himself, the mighty representative of this age — he in whose work all the new ideas which have animated the intellectual world during fifty years are in germ — Herder himself remained always a youth, ever unable to give a definite and artistically measured form to his thought. Her- der's very universality was injurious to him. His range was too vast to allow of his grasping any- thing firmly : il embrassa trop pour hien etreindre. His ever-wandering eye never could restrict itself to one narrow spot, and his enthusiasm reminds us more of a burning steppe than the concen- I 114 THE SEEDS OF GERMAN THOUGHT. trated, persistent g-low of a furnace. He caught glimpses — 1 might almost say he had the visions of a genius, upon all subjects, mastering none completely; and thus, while able to give the architect the most valuable suggestions, he was himself utterly at a loss to construct the smallest edifice. !No man ever scattered abroad a greater quantity of fruitful seeds than he ; yet at the close of his career he found that he had not tilled a single corner of his own field according to rule. It is undeniable that his works are more remarkable for the variety than for the profundity of the learning they contain, as he himself was endowed with more imagination than good sense, with more ardour than thoroughness. It was precisely these defects, nevertheless, which determined his immense and immediate Herder's influence. He was certainly one of the action, greatest incentive powers the world has ever known. * Who is this modern Pindar who has just made his appearance amongst you ? ' wrote Winckelmann from Eome in 1767, when Herder's ' Fragments ' had just appeared. ' This, to be sure, is a madman or a genius,' exclaimed Wieland. * Whoever maybe the author,' Lessiug said to Mcolai, ' he is at any rate the only one for herder's fundamental idea. 115 "wliom it is worth my while to publish mj ideas.' If the mature generation spoke thus, what must have been the effect of the youthful prophet upon the unripe one ? Nor is the fact astonishing. Bj dint of analysing- human nature, and introducing into history the division of labour, people had come to such a point that, as Mephistopheles has it, ' they held the parts in their hands, the intel- lectual link alone being wanting.' It was Herder's unmethodical visionary imagination which dis- covered the failing link, and reunited what analysis had severed. * Everything that man undertakes to produce, whether by action, word, or in whatsoever way, ought to spring from the union of all his faculties. All that is isolated is condemnable.' These are the words in which Goethe sums up the fundamental idea which inspired Herder's master Hamann and Herder himself. Nothing, he would say, is in reality isolated, and just as each individual sense is assisted by the four others in the perception of any object which absorbs our attention, so do memory and imagination likewise co-operate with judgment and perception in enabling us to acquire our knowledge of things. This union of all the faculties, this primitive entireness of the individual, I 2 116 THE SEEDS OP GERMAN THOUGHT. is what we must endeavour to recover, sucli as it was in the early ages, ere abstract rules had been thoug-ht of — times when each individual acted, thought, and spoke according to inspiration and direct view. And what is true of individuals is true of nations. What thej produce — laws, con- stitutions, religions, poetry — always is, in a way, a collective work, the result of a union of all faculties and forces. This was the fourth great mother-idea, if I may so call it, that gave birth to the German view of mind and nature, man and history, which we have proposed to examine. We have now to see what became of the seeds of thought sown in Germany between 1760 and 1770 by the hands of the four great geniuses who are to be con- sidered as the real architects of our culture. We shall try to form to ourselves an idea of Herder's own view on mankind and history in his maturer age, of Goethe's view on mankind and nature, Kant's view on mankind and morality, Schiller's view on mankind and art. 117 LECTUEE IV. THE EEIGN OF HERDER. 1770-1786. We liave seen that the principal ideas which Germany had to develop and illustrate in her national literature and in her scientific work were almost all thrown on the intellectual market of Europe shortly after the conclusion of the Seven Years' War. Winckelmann gave new life to an- tiquity by applying to it a new historical method. LessinsT traced the limits between the fine arts and poetry, assigning to each of them a domain not to be overstepped. Kant, correcting Eousseau'a view of the history of mankind, contended that the ideal aim of mankind was not the natural state of the savage as Eousseau held, but a state of nature combined with intellectual, moral, sesthetic, and political development, such as was realised in Greece. Herder, finally, starting likewise from 118 THE REIGN OF HERDEE. Rcusseau, believed all great creations of Immanitj to be the work of spontaneous action, either indi- vidual or collective and national, not the inten- tional result of self-conscious activity. The three first of these four great men still belong to the generation of 1760, as we should call the men born in the second and third decade of the century ; the last, Herder, born in 1744, already belongs to the foUoAving generation, that of Goethe. His marvellous precocity alone permitted him to fight at the side of Lessing, his elder by fifteen years. It seems natural that the j^oungest of the prophets should also be the one most eagerly listened to by the youth of his country; it becomes more natural when we take into account the inspired and inspiring personality of the man who at twenty- two stirred the German world by his apparent paradoxes, who at twenty-six was the Mentor, the initiator, the guiding genius of Goethe, his junior only by five years. And not of Goethe alone, although his personal relations with him were more intimate than with others, but of tlie whole generation of 1775. It is not too much to say that he inspired all the writers of this period of literary history — and Germany had then scarcely any but literary history — the Sturm- und Drang- herder's mature works. 119 periode, which lasted from about 1770 till about 1786. Herder, it is true, gave to his thoughts their lasting and determined form only in 1784, when he published his principal work, the * Ideas on a Philosophy of the History of Mankind.' This great book, however, only develops the con- ceptions which were in the germ in the * Frag- ments,' the 'Critical Sylvffi,' and the 'Origin of Language,' just as in the ' Letters on the Study of Theology ' and the ' Spirit of Hebrew Poetry ' (1781-1782) we find the very thoughts which he had laid before the public ten years earlier in his ' Most Ancient Document of Humanity ' — thoughts which opened quite a new insight into the secret laboratory of language, poetry, and religion. Even the memorable book, which has been father to all the histories of poetry, religion, language and law of our century — even the ' Ideas ' — are unfinished, diffusely written in a loose disconnected style, the style of a seer rather than of a thinker, and still less that of an historian ; very in- sufficient if we look upon them as a collec- tion of researches, nay, totally antiquated as far as form and materials are concerned. But as for the thoughts contained in it, the book seems written but yesterday ; it might easily 120 THE EEIGN OF HERDER. be taken for a sketch from the pen of M. Taine. The one chief conception, we have seen, which Herder sought to impress on his age, was that of Herder's evolution, growth, fieri, which he had viewb. borrowed from the vegetable kingdom in order to apply it to political, religious, and literary history ; nay, to the natural history of man and to that of his language. He, and Hamann before him, had been struck by the little help obtained from isolated observation towards arriving at the truth. They saw that almost all our knowledge is acquired by synthetic and unconscious observation, or, to use a more accu- rate term, reception; while intuition — i.e. the sj^ark which suddenly shoAvs the link and coherence of such synthetic knowledge, and which is after all only the result of long unconscious reception and unconscious maturation of what has been received — seemed to them infinitely superior to consciously generalising and arguing reason, which had been so exclusively used in their century. Hence their two leading ideas, which gradually acquired depth, width, and strength, became the two leading ideas of German culture: the first being that of the totality of individual or collective forces as opposed herder's views. 121 to the division of labour ; tlie second, that of the unintentional origin of all great individual and collective creations. Now the unconscious creative power, working in man and nature, manifests itself nowhere so strikingly as in genius — the genius not only of the great legislator, captain, philosopher, poet, but also the genius of naivete, i.e. of any single human being, or collection of human beings, not yet affected by our abstract and analytical habits. Our minds to day are differently framed fi'om those of primitive men, owing to the education of our youth for so many past generations. We are accustomed to reflect and analyse so much that we hardly see or feel any more. We no longer poetise in or on the living world; our poetry is not the result of the contact of objects with our soul ; we manufacture artificially both the subjects and the modes of ti-eating them ; and we have practised this so long and so frequently, and we begin to do so at so early an age, that a free education would have small chance of success with us ; for how should the lame learn to walk upright 1 The starting-point, then, of Herder's whole philosophy is the conception of genius as the one acting force of the intellectual world. ' What is it in Homer that compensates for his ignorance of the rules, deduced from the study of his works by 122 THE REIGN OF HERDER. Aristotle ? What in Shakespeare that makes up for his direct violation even of these laws of criti- cism ? The unanimous answer to the question will be : Genius.' These words of Hamann may be considered as the theme of all Herder's varia- tions. Now, the nature of genius consists in the elementary operations of the mind before habits of analvsis and abstraction have severed the differ- ent mental faculties and have accustomed man to form general conceptions and to influence his will by them. Its essence is direct sensation and in- tuition, unconscious production. It lives prin- cij^ally in popular poetry, legislation, and religion, not yet influenced by rationalistic culture. Even nowadays it cannot survive unless it keeps itself free from all rationalistic rules, and obeys only its inspiration. We shall see by and by to what errors this principle led as soon as it was applied to science, which rests entirely oii the combination of observation and reasoning; and to morals, the very essence of which is connected in our own minds with the idea of duty. Let us confine our- selves for the moment to poetry and history in the widest sense, comprising theology, philology, &c., where this point of view was exceedingly fertile and salutary. herder's VIET7S OK" POETRY. 123 Indeed, the much vaunted originality not being of frequent occurrence in the eminently artificial society of the eighteenth century, it be- q^ came necessary, in order to find it in all °® ^•- * its purity, either to ascend to epochs which preceded civilisation — in other words, to primitive nations, — or to descend to those popular strata of the existing age which had as yet escaped the contagion of corrupt culture. Herder, you see, was a kind of literary Eousseau. He may be said to have renovated and regenerated the poetry of his time by immersing it in the true sources of all great poetry : nature and popular life. He it was who first established the fact, subsequently confirmed by historical discovery, that poetry always pre- ceded prose in the annals of mankind ; he it was who first proclaimed the poetical superiority of ages in which the entireness of individuality was not yet broken. In the floiu'ishing periods of elegant prose, lie would say, nothing but art can prosper in poetry. Later on we find even mere versified philosophy and half-way poetry. On the other hand, the language of those times, when words had not yet been divided into nobles, middle-class, and plebeians, nor had prose been sifted, was the richest for poetical purposes. Our tongue compared with the idiom of the savage seems adapted rather for reflection 124 THE REIGN OF HERDEE. than for the senses or imagination. The rhythm of popular verse is so deHcate, so rapid, so precise, that it is no easy matter for us hookworms to detect it with our eyes ; but do not imagine it to have been equally difficult for those living populations who listened to, instead of reading it ; who were accustomed to the sound of it from their infancy ; who themselves sang it, and whose ear had been formed by its cadence. And here Herder enters into one of tlie topics wliicli he has made so wonderfully his own — that of the organ of the ear — but it would lead me too far if I were to quote in extefiso. Suffice it to say that his essentially musical nature made him par- ticularly apt to listen to that innermost life of the soul, which can be expressed only by tone and rhythm. If he so continually and persistently contemplates primitive ages, and incessantly op- poses them to his own conventional age, it is chiefly because that innermost life was more intense then, because thoughts, facts, images even of primitive man had not yet been severed from tliis innermost life, and consequently still wanted the help of music, as the only adequate language of it, in order to give them expression. Poetry in those happy days lived in the ears of the peoj)le, on the lips and in the harps of living hards ; it heedee's theoet on poetet. 125 sang of history, of the events of the day, of mysteries, miracles, and signs. It was the flower of a nation's cha- ractei', language, and country; of its occupations, its prejudices, its passions, its aspirations, and its soul. The whole modern theory concerning epic poetry is contained in embryo in these words. Yet Herder goes still further, and formulates it so distinctly that F. A. Wolf had scarcely anything to do but to develop and establish it more firmly by means of that detailed and solid system of argumentation, which made him the true father of the Homeric idea, as comprehended by our age. The greatest among Greek bards was also the gi'eatest among popular poets. His sublime work is no epopoeia ; it is the epos, the story, the legend, the living history of the people. He did not sit down on velvet cushions to compose a poem in twice twenty-four cantos according to the rules of Aristotle. Words like these naturally fell like thunder- bolts on that eighteenth century, so self-satisfied, so vain of the great progress it had achieved and of the hiofh culture it had attained. Yersificaticn as an art had been brought to such perfection, the criterion by which the merits and demerits of poetry were to be measured had been so accurately defined, poetry itself was so easily learnt and 126 THE REIGX OF HERDEE. tauglit, that the world was completely dumb- foundered at this strange enthusiasm for miserable, despised savages. Moreover, Herder added practice to theory. During his stay at Strassburg, he had already begun with Goethe to search for popular songs, and great was his delight when he was able to send one to his affianced bride, which he had gathered from the mouth of the people. No book, since the appearance of Percy's ' Relics,* had met with such success in Germany as the ' Voices of Nations,' a series of volumes containinsr popular poems in masterly translations, and pub- lished by Herder in 1778. It became indeed the model for all the numerous collections of the kind which have come out during the nineteenth century. But Herder not only discovered true living poetry in the distant ages of Homer and the cloudy isles of Ossian ; he found it out in modern times, in his own nation, lending a ready ear to the simple ditties of the woodcutter and the peasant, of the journeyman and the soldier, of the hunter and the shepherd. Germany owes the revival of the lied or song entirely to Herder and to his ' Stimmen der Volker.' When we read the verses which Goethe wrote at Leipzig, before THE BALLAD AND THE LIED. 127 meeting with Herder, we may well be permitted to doubt whether Germany would have ever possessed those unrivalled pearls, his little songs of love, ad- dressed to Friederike and Lili, if he had not known him. It is, at any rate, very doubtful whether it would have had the ' Erlkoiiig ' or the * Fisherman.' Of these, however, England possesses beautiful examples in her own ballads ; not so of the lied, with which even Burns's poems have little in common, and of which we find only the -pendant in Shakespeare's little songs, such as — Blow, blow, thou winter wind ! and others. It is difficult indeed to define the lied. "What is the lied ? Herder asked. It is neither a sonnet nor a madrigal, poems for the study and the salon ; it is no composition for painting with harmonious colour- ing ; light and brilliancy are not its merits. . . . The essence of the lied is song, not painting. Its perfection resides in the melodious course of a passion or a sentiment, ... If this melody be wanting in a lied, if it have not the poetical modulation, the right tone, it may contain ever so many images, it may be graceful, it may have colouring ; it never can be a lied. And as with the epic poem, the ballad, and the lied, so with the fable. Lafontaine had made 128 THE REIGN OP HERDER. delicious tableaux de genre of the fable of the ancients ; Lessing concise, epigrammatic satires. Nay, Lessing had still defined the fable in the spirit of the eighteenth century as an intentional form of moral teaching : ' If we reduce a general proposition to a particular case, lending it reality and making a story out of it, in which the general proposition may be recognised by means of in- tuition, we call this a fable.' How much deeper is Herder's view. In his eyes fables originally were, and would again become, were we to live less artificially, the ' poetical illustration of a lesson of experience by means of a characteristic trait, drawn from animal life and developed by analogy.' In ancient fables (he says) animals act, because what- ever in nature produces effects ap2)eai-s to primitive humanity to act. ... It is analogy which is the parent of poetry in fables, not abstraction, still less a dry deduc- tion from the general to the particular. . , , The feble rests on Nature's eternal consistency and constancy. . . . Its characters are types. . . . The more natural the state m which a nation hved, the more it hkcd fables. Now, Herder made this refutation of the mechanical theories, then reigning throughout Europe, from his point of view, i.e. that of spon- VIEW OF THE ANCIENT WORLD. 129 taneous creation without special conscious aim, not only in the domain of the fable, but in that of every kind of poetry. He carefully studied the nature of the epigram in its earliest form, and of q^^ ^^^^j the national drama, as he had studied ^"^'^'^ that of the lied and the epic poem, chiefly illus- trating his theories from Greek examples. The whole of the ancient world has been looked upon with different eyes since Herder. Viewing the ancients as an historian alone could view them, he oi^posed his own less refined conception of antiquity, not only to the Alexandrian, rather than the Athe- nian, conventional antiquity which found favour with the French and Wieland, but also indirectl}- and half-unconsciously to Winckelmann's some- what cothurnic idealism. For him the first, Achilles and Ajax became chiefs of clans, instead of princes of the blood, or lords of a royal court a la Versailles, as Apollo and Diana became living mythical figures instead of cold allegories. It was Herder who taught young Goethe to laugh at Wieland's jjowdered and patched Alcestis in his charming satire, ' Gods, heroes, and Wieland' (1774), as it was Herder who made him understand the beauty of the Strassburg Cathedral, then considered as a work of barbarism, and express in his Essay on K 130 THE EEIGN OF HERDER. ' German Architecture ' those simple and profound thoughts on art, which ought to have put a stop to all our systematic imitations of past and foreign styles which correspond to nothing in our life. Herder's views, however, failed unfortunately to prevail within the province of plastic art. On His owing to the powerful and yet too recent ^°'"'^- influence and authority exercised by Winckelmann. But they penetrated rapidly into all other branches of intellectual activity in Germany; into historical studies particularly, for Herder himself applied his main conception of poetry to the history of states, civil law, and religions. It is true he placed the history of civilisation far above political history. Still he included political history in that of civilisation, and thereby he made a real revolution in historical science, or I had perhaps better say in the art of history. Up to his time the most mechanical teleology had reigned in the philosophy of history. Providence was represented to have created ' cork- trees that men should have wherewithal to stop their bottles ; ' as also, of course, to have prevented Cromwell from setting out for America in order that an instrument might not be wanting to ac- herder's views on history. 131 complisli the Eevolution in England. Bossuet's ' Discours sur Vhistoire universelle ' is still entirely based upon the programme-idea ; and Montesquieu, in his ' Grandeur et decadence,^ if he does not bring in the Divine regisseur, lends to the mortal actors of history plans and intentions, and ascribes to laws and institutions an influence which they never had. Herder was the first who ventured to leave the alleged aims of Providence as well as those of theo- retical legislation in historical events out of the question, and opposing himself alike to the idea of a preconceived plan, and that of mere chance, refused to see p.nything in history beyond the development of given germs. This has undoubtedly proved the most fertile of modern ideas. ' Each nation contains its centre within itself, as a bullet its centre of gravity. There is nothing within the whole kingdom of God which is a mere means ; everything is at once means and end.' He was the first also to banish the conscious legislators out of primitive history. For him Lycurgus was already what Otfried Miiller proved him to be fifty years later, the legendary judge who, according to tra- dition, codified the secular uses and customs of his tribe, not the inventor of a brand new constitution planned ad hoc like that of the Abbe Sieyes. The •K 2 132 THE ESIQN OF HEEDER. pervading spirit of his great book is a sort of warfare against mechanical causes or abstract ideas, intro- duced as realities into history, and above all against teleology, which looks for an end or purpose in every event. The historian, he says, ' will never attempt to explain a thing which is by a thing which is not. And with this severe principle all ideals, all phantasmas of a dream-world disappear.' Consequently we must beware of referring the phenomena of history to a design or plan which is unknown to us. To the question, ' Why did Alexander go to India ? ' there is only one answer, ' Because he was Alexander, Philip's son.' In giving up this investigation into a plan of history we are recompensed by getting an insight into the high and beautiful laws of nature. Indeed, * ... if there is a God in nature, he is also in history ; for man is also part of the creation, and must, even in his "wildest excesses and passions, obey laws, which are no less beautiful and excellent than those according to which all the celestial bodies move.' ... * The God I look for in history must be the same as the God of natiu'e ; for man is but a tiny particle of the whole, and the history of mankind resembles that of the worm, closely connected loith the tissue it inhabits ; therefore the natural laws by which the Deity reveals itself must reign in man Hkewise.' And elsewhere : * . . . The whole history of humanity is herder's views oisr the law of history. 133 pure natural history of human forces, actions, and instincts, according to place and time.' This is the view of human history which we shall afterwards see Goethe applying to nature, nor can the resemblance surprise any one who knows how intimately the two men lived together. Herder has not only a wonderful insight into the early periods of history — one must read his diary during his journey from Riga to Nantes to see how the mystery of the formation of States, and of the migration and settlements of nations, revealed itself to him — he has even profound views on the prehistoric state of mankind which belongs still, up to a certain point, to natural history. And a great naturalist of our days (Baer) could say of him that he * had drawn with the divination of a seer the outlines of comparative anatomy of which the works of Cuvier and our time give only the commentary.' Now, Herder's principle as ap- plied to historic as well as prehistoric times, is that everywhere on earth all beings become what they can become according to the situation and necessities of place, according to the circumstances and opportunities of time, and according to the inborn or acquired physical and intellectual character of the race ; in other words, M. Taine's 134 THE EEIGN OP HEEDEE. ' milieu, moment, et race.' No doubt, Montes- quieu in his famous seventeenth and eighteenth books had already given great importance to the influence of climate and soil on the destinies of nations ; but he, wisely enough, made of them only contributing elements, and although his views on this matter taken in themselves may be sounder than those of Herder, it is certain that they have not acted on the general current of thought as Herder's did, perhaps also because he exposed them less persistently and less enthusiasti- cally. The plan w^hich Herder proposed to the future historian was to take his start from the Universum, marking the position of the earth in it, and to show the condition of life on earth, resulting from this position ; then to describe the typical forms of plants and animals ' until the physiognomy of the earth as a whole should be entirely grasped with all the conditions it offers for human history.' The great geographical work of K. Ritter, who wrote these words, as well as those of A. von Hum- boldt, are the fruit of this method recommended by Herder. All this, however, was for him only the basis of a History of Man. Man is the last and highest link in the develop- VIEW OF THE DEVELOPMENT OF MAN". 133 ment of tlie creating power, which lives in the earth. He shows how the progress of nature pro- duced a more and more refined brain until it arrived at man. The same organic evolution which gave him the most developed brain gave him also language. Indeed, whilst one-half of the cul- tivated world still saw in language a gift or reve- lation of God, the other an intentional, human invention. Herder already saw in it, what we all nowadays see in it, a potential instrument for the development of reason, a natural product of the soul's vital forces, an ever self-creating process. For it is through language that we must under- stand the birth of abstract reason, i.e. the faculty of forming general conceptions, which is not a primi- tive faculty, common to all men from the begin- ning, but one acquired by the co-operation of language and intellig-ence. According to Herder's conception of organic development, therefore, the human alone can be the ideal aim of mankind. A morality, which affects anything higher, would be a delusion. If we examine mankind — if we look on mankind, as we know it to be, i.e. according to the laws which are within it — we know nothing higher than humanity in man. Even when we imagine angels and gods, we imagine tJiem as ideal, higher men. 136 THE REIGN OF HERDER. The Deity has limited man's possibilities onlj by time, place, and innate faculties. The one active force is the creative power of man's nature, which the environment hinders or furthers more or less. Now, the law of this progress and develop- ment is, that all destructive forces must, in the long run, not only succumb to the conservative forces, but also serve to the development of the whole. This the history of the animal kingdom shows as well as the history of mankind.' Though Herder is continually appealing to God, all this sounds singularly like pantheism, On Reii- ^^^^ ^^® words which I have quoted are ^'°"" not such as he would have penned at Biickeburg at the time he made the first rough sketch of his philosophy of history. But, since then, he, like Lessing, Goethe, and nearly all the eminent minds of the age, had tasted of Spinoza and relished him extremely. In spite of the scandal produced among believers by this change, Herder never renounced his new faith, even after having attained the highest ecclesiastical dignities. He sought to conceal it, more certainly from him- self than from others, and in order to do this he ' See the ' Ideas ' pasnm-, and particularly Book xv. 1 and 2, Cf. Book xiii. 7, on Greek history in general. heeder's views on religion. 137 was obliged to put mucla into Christianity wliich does not really belong to it, as many others before and since have done. The pearl is found (he says) ; no one can build upon any other foundation than that of Christ. As this Gospel needs no extei'nal signs, being its own proof, neither can it be overthrown by theological or other doubts. , , , In all the things which occur in the world, it is its kingdom which is coming ; for this is the business of Providence, and it is the aim and character, the very essence of the human race to accomplish the work of Providence, Pttt no trust in phantoms. The kingdom of God is within you. This religion, you see, was a very wide one, and this species of Christianity very closely re- sembled the doctrines of Spinoza. But it was precisely in virtue of the peculiar wideness of his Christianity that Herder exercised so great an influence over his country. If the German people has been — till lately, at least — the only one which has remained deeply religious without paying any great attention to external worship, religious observance and dogmas, it has merely followed the example which Herder gave it. Tlie question has been raised whether a man can be moral independently of religion — independently of re- ligious dogma is undoubtedly what is meant, for other- 138 THE EEIGN OF HERDEE. "wise this question would be resolved by itself. True religion cannot exist without morality, and true morality is religion under whatever form it may show itself. This, translated into Lutlier's language, means that faith goes before works : the man who lives in the ideal cannot be immoral, the modern German would say, in accordance therein with the unconscious belief of all his forefathers. As far from orthodoxy as from rationalism, Herder constantly appeals from dogma and reasoning to religious feeling : ' Flee religious controversy as you would the plague,' he used to say, ' for it is impossible to dispute about what religion is. It is as impossible either to deny or affirm it by dis- cussion as to paint the mind or hear light.' It is precisely because Christianity is an especially human reli^fion that Herder feels himself a Chris- tian ; for the development of the human was the ideal of his life. The natural nobility of man was great enough in his eyes without claiming a supra- natural one for him. Herder's religious development is very charac- teristic of Germany in the past century. The Bible was for him the earliest source of intellectual culture, as it was for Klopstock, Lessing, and above all Goethe. At an early age, however, he rebels HEEDER'S ' MOST ANCIENT DOCUMENT.' 139 against the idea of its being a revealed book. Genesis became in his eyes only a kind of theo- gony, like that of Hesiod, nor conld he see anything beyond a collection of national chronicles, poems and proverbs, in the rest of the Old Testament. What he discovers in it above all is poetry ; and we find him defending the Song of Solomon as energetically against mystics as against moralising rationalists. It is necessary to read his eloquent pages on the Mosaic epopoeia in order to under- stand the effect which they produced in their apparently profane treatment of the subject. For Herder, of course, and his countrymen it was only another form of admiration, ' Burn all rational- istic metaphysics ! ' he exclaims. ' The living commentary on the Mosaic monument blows with the morning air.' Herder it was who first taught the world to understand the Oriental way of thinking, who first showed it what Oriental poetry was, and opposed the primitive simplicity of the Bible to the dogmatic interpretation of theologians. And he finds beautiful words to praise the beauty of this Oriental poetry of the Bible. These ideas Herder brought forward for the first time in his ' Most Ancient Document,' which 140 THE REIGN OF HERDER. lie ' had cherished in his heart from his tenderest infancy.' They were taken up again and de- veloped still further eight and ten years later in his ' Letters on the Study of Theology,' and in the ' Spirit of Hebrew Poetry.' He never tires of telling the world that the Bible is not only the basis of our own religion, but also contains that which is the most elevated and ancient in the world. (At that time the Yedas had not yet been discovered.) It was he above all who opened the world's eyes ancvv to tuat poetry which had been hidden from its sight by the mass of allegory, morals, dogmas, philosophical ideas, and law texts with which it had been stifled. For he had the boldness to treat the Bible like any other human document ; and by doing so, he rendered possible the history of religion which belongs essentially and exclusively to our age. For nothing less than the example of Herder's deep and sincere religious feeling would have sufficed to enable men of those times to study religion itself without placing them- selves at the point of view of any given religion. The various forms under which mankind have successively or simultaneously tried to satisfy their craving for the infinite and the supernatural, had to be duly respected and loved ; but it was herder's, influence on later schools. 141 needful also to reach the jjoint at which the believer no longer requires that the infinite and superuatui'al should have a definite and conven- tional form, in order to adore and dread it. An enthusiastic nature was needed, like that of Her- der, capable of understanding a mystical glow, and yet free-thinking enough not to attribute to himself and his sect alone the privilege of such mystical glow and the immediate conception of the Deity. The Tiibingen school would have been an impossibility without Herder, and we may say exactly the same thing with regard to its adver- saries. Ewald would never have written his * History of the People of Israel ; ' Bunsen would never have composed his great * Bible- work,' nor his * God in History,' if Herder had not opened out fresh horizons to theology and history. Even E. Eenan finds himself still upon ground which Herder has conquered for religious history. Re- spect and sympathy for religion are here allied to an independence of view which regards all religions as issuing from the same religious want, and which substitutes internal for external revelation. Herder no longer explains the origin of posi- tive religion, as it was customary to do in the philosophical camj), by the imposture of priests. 142 THE REIGN OP HERDER. but liistoricallj. First lie sees fear and super- stition ; then curiosity, creating cosmogonies, and, with the aid of poetical imagination, mythology. He shows that reUgious ideas become simplified, generalised, and purified only by degrees. In the beginning they could only be instinctive, intuitive, sensuous, and consequently local and definite. It was natural that these traditions should be more national than anything else in the world. Everyone spoke through the mouth of his forefathers, saw by the standard of the world which surrounded him ; gave him- self solutions concerning the problems which interested him most, such as were best adapted to his climate, nationality, and traditions. . . . Scandinavia built a world of giants ; the Iroquois made the turtle the machine which explained to him the existence of the earth. The whole of modern religious criticism, its fertility as well as its perils, is contained in these words. For how should a grosser mind, or simply a less poetical, less respectful soul than Herder's, translate all this otherwise than by the well-known words of the arch-scofi'er : ' God created man after his own image and man gave it him back ? ' Nor are gross minds, cold and irreverent souls less common among the defenders than among the VIEW OF THE FUTUEE OF MANKIND. 143 detractors of positive religion. Warburton wonld not have understood Herder better than he was understood by Paine. Hence the great unpopu- larity of Herder and his disciples in both camps. It is usual to call Herder the apostle of humanitarian ideas, and not without reason, pro- vided a contempt for nationalities be not q^^ implied. Herder, like Lessing, who de- humanity. clared patriotism to be a virtue of doubtful worth, like Goethe, like Schiller above all, placed human- ity higher than nationality. In his eyes the title ' man ' was the noblest which could be imairined, and he still belongs entirelj^ to his essentially optimistic century by this very exalted idea of man. In his eyes national prejudices were as contempt- ible as were religious and caste prejudices. He thought that a day would come when a single bond would unite all peoples, when a single, un- written religion, a single civilisation, a single morality would bring men together in a common brotherhood. He protested vehemently against national exclusiveness, as he protested against every other species of exclusiveness. He did not wish that any people, not even his own, should be trumpeted forth as the elect ; but he was not the less full of love and reverence for his countiy on 144 THE REIGN OF HEEDEE. that account, and I may anticipate what I shall have to say later, by stating that this spirit of temperate patriotism, which desires for our native country an equal, but never a predominant, place among nations, has given the main impulse to the national revival of Germany in this century, and still moves and sways the mass as well as the elite of the nation. National pride (said Herder) is absurd, ridiculous, and dangerous ; but it is everybody's duty to love his country, and it cannot be loved if it is not honoured, or if it is allowed to be disparaged. It must be defended, and each of \is must contribute the utmost in his power to its honour and welfare. Far from being a despiser of his own country. Herder was perhaps the most patriotic German writer of the last century, although he had not continuously ' Hermann, the Cherusk,' and the * Roman tyrants ' in his mouth like Klopstock and the Stolbergs. He was undoubtedly the one who best understood the degradation and who most deplored the fragmentary condition, the slavery and political decadence of the Empire. He laments that Germany was but ' a thing of the imagination,' that she had no ' common voice,' that there was no Frederick II. seated upon the worm-eaten herder's views on humanity. 145 throne of the German Csesars. And as, in oj^po- sition to Schiller, he desired that poetry should seek her inspiration in real life and not in the ideal world, he likewise wished, in opposition to Goethe, that this reality should be that of public, not for ever that of private, life. In particular his * Letters on' Humanity,' especially the first, are full of these patriotic and political ideas. But it would convey a false impression if I did not add that in his eyes the nation was but ' a member of humankind.' His demand was that nations should exercise a mutual influence over each other by means of their moral and intellectual qualities only, and he saw in a ' free competition of activity among- the different nationalities the fundamental condition of the civilisation of mankind.' Certainly it seems to have been his mission to preach the Human, but also to show it in all its manifold forms. For he contended even ag-ainst Lessinsr that human development is conditioned by nationality and natural surrouu dings, that in the vicissitudes of history the ideal of the Human never appears nor ever will appear in one universal form. This man it is who, thanks to some ill- comprehended sentence of a speech made in his youth, has become the ' apostle of cosmopolitism ' L 146 THE REIGN OF HEEDEE. in tlie eyes of posterity. One ought far rather to say that, after having been the standard-bearer in the revolt of the Teutonic against the Latin spirit by his literary criticism, he was at once the first and the most eloquent defender of that principle of nationalities which has agitated our own century so deeply. By restoring national poetry to its place of honour he contributed indirectly to the revival of patriotic sentiments ; by formulating the German idea he became the forerunner of those who, long after, created the German State. As for himself. Herder was a citizen of all coun- tries and ages, as he was a reader of all literatures. He deemed it necessary to know and appreciate the poetry of other countries as well as of his own ; and to be able to do this properly it was in- dispensa,ble that he should place himself amongst the surroundings which had produced it. Now, nature had endowed him for this purpose with a pliability of intelligence, an acuteness of percep- tion, a keenness of sight and hearing, a refined delicacy of taste totally unrivalled. This faculty of appreciating and entering into the spirit of the •most divers countries and periods constitutes his chief and true grandeur, and he bequeathed a good part of it to the culture of Germany. This was in reality his cosmopolitism, which has been so often herder's views on humanity. 147 misrepresented, and about which, a legion of his- torians have been content to repeat stereotyped judgments, without attempting to subject them to the slightest criticism. This cosmopolitism never for a moment prevented him from being the most German of all German writers in the general tone of his inspiration, still less from heralding the German idea to the world with that exaggeration which is always to be found in reactions, and which it is the task of our time to moderate. In fact, as we have seen, Herder not only put an end to the remnants of reasoning, didactics, and moralising which even Lessing had still admitted into the domain of poetry ; he combated them also in the field of religion, politics, and historical science, as he also rose up against the idea of rule which Lessing defended, for the essen- tially German conception of individual right. He restored originality, if I may say so, to German poetry and thought by setting limits for a while to the imitation of the ancients ; and the form and spirit of his teaching were eminently German. For, although Germany has had more than one matter-of-fact and sober genius since Luther, still Herder's rather musical than plastic genius, his high-flown, enthusiastic nature, his want of measure L 2 148 THE EEIGN OP HERDEE. and of definiteness, his wonderful intuitive power, his rather unmethodical reasoning, and his faculty of assimilation are, after all, more characteristic of the German nature than the practical sense and the energy of a Frederick and a Bismarck, the dialectical prowess of a Lessing, or the plastic power of a Goethe. There was one quality besides, almost lost, it seemed, since the days of Leibnitz, which Herder restored to his nation and bequeathed to its civili- sation and thought : universality and breadth of horizon. Understanding nationality as few per- sons of his time understood it, he subordinated it to humanity. Brought up in reverence for Hellenism, and the first to point out its true character, he discovered the East by intuition. In heart a Christian, he knew how to assimilate all the * pagan' humanism of the Renaissance. Full of admiration for the classical authors, he found the secret of primitive and religious j)oetry. Liberal in his political sympathies, he demonstrated the laws and consistency of history. No mani- festation of mankind, whatever its form, had a secret for the apostle of humanity. GENERALITY OF THE MOVEMENT. 149 Tlie movement initiated bj Herder was a general one, and it extended from Konigsberg to Zurich, from Strassburg to Dresden, Sturm- un every town of Germany taking part in it, J)ranff- periode. more or less. Not only universities and republics, like Gottingen and Frankfort, but small capitals also, such as Darmstadt, Weimar, Stutt- gart, saw the ' geniuses ' hurl their clamorous challenge and defy the heaven in their desire to renew and regenerate the world by a return to Nature ; for the young disciples, as disciples will do, began forthwith to out-Herder Herder. The preceding generation had been concentrating its powers for action, and Berlin had been Lessing's headquarters. Young Germany of 1775 overflowed the entire country, finding voluntary agents and apostles in all quarters. The same ideas which Hamann had instilled into Herder, when on the shores of the Baltic, were to strike his ear as soon as he approached Switzerland, where Lavater was preaching them with still greater zeal and in more whimsical language than the ' Magician of the North.' When a student at Konigsberg, indeed. Herder had undergone not only Kant's influence, Kgnjo-g. but also, and still more, Hamann's. He ^"^' 150 THE EEIQN OF HEEDEE. owed to Kant — not yet the man who wrote the Critic of Pure Reason, and opened new horizons to man's intelligence — the awakening of his philo- sophical thought. I once had the happiness of knowing a philosopher ; he was my teacher. He had the joyous cheerfulness of youth at that happy time ; his open forehead, created ex- pressly for thought, was the seat of imperturbable serenity ; his speech, redundant with ideas, flowed from his lips ; he always had some humorous trait, some witty sally at his disposal, . . . He would constantly bring us back to the siniple, unaffected study of nature. . . . He gave me self- confidence, and obhged me to think for myself, for tyranny was foreign to his soul. And Kant himself, on reading some verses of the enthusiastic boy, said: 'When this boiling genius has done fermenting, he will be a very useful man.' Who could then have predicted the desperate warfare which was to break out between these two great men thirty years later? Even then, however, it was Hamann's more than Kant's merit to have shown Herder the road he was to follow. Hamanu is not to be counted among the German classical writers, although he left several volumes ; for all he produced was of a fragmen- tary nature. He abounded in new and original ideas, but there were as many ' nebulous spots as GOTTINGEN. 151 stars on that firmament ' (Jean Paul), and the dis- order of his brain was as clearly reflected in his * grasshopper-style ' as it was in his odd person. This singularly active power — Goethe called him *the indispensable, but indigestible leaven' of the time — must in a great measure, of course, escape the scrutiny of history ; nor is it easy to explain it otherwise than by the persistency with which Hamann harped upon that fundamental theme then about to become the leading principle of the generation : the theme of absolute individual liberty. He excited Herder against the dead letter of poetical rule, as well as against the narrow- minded morality of the middle classes. He was as rebellious against the 'modern State' of the Philosopher King, as against ' enlightenment ' and rationalism in religion ; but it was reserved to the disciple to set the ' unstrung pearls ' of the Konigsberg ' Magus.' The University of Gottingen was a still more agitated centre of movement than that of Konigs- berof. There Biiro^er had iust written his ^ » J GSttingen. ' Lenore,' and those other early ballads which at once took Germany by storm ; there some young students had formed among themselves a poetical league, which assembled around the secu- 152 THE EEIGN OP HERDEE. ]ar oaks of the neisrlibonrinGf forest, invokincf the memory of Hermann, the liberator, and the Teu- tonic bards, worshipping Klopstock, and burning Wieland's woi-ks. The famous 'Hainbund' num- bered among its associates many celebrated names. There were the two impetuous Counts Stolberg, the ' enemies of tyrants ' — dead tyrants, of course — Voss, the peasant-boy and future poet of ' Louise,' he who gave Germany what Heine called the Vul- gate of Homer, and who, forty years later, declared war upon Fritz Stolberg, when this friend of his youth fled into the arms of Rome ; his brother-in- law, Boie, who published the first poetical alma- nack, the ' Moniteur ' of the League ; melancholy Holty, doomed to early death, and many other poets who afterwards got a high reputation, but the eldest of whom at that time was hardly tAventy-two years of age ; sincere and pure and high-minded youths all of them, but somewhat in- tentional in their enthusiasm, not without uncon- scious affectation beneath the surface of their mag- niloquent vehemence; more bent upon looking for the poetical in abstract thought and vague feelings than in sensuous reality and its definite forms. In the South, especially in Wlirtemberg, a soil which has alwa^^s been productive of revolutionary wiJETEMBEEG. 153 radicalism, it was no loiisrer rebellion airainst literary authority alone which armed the wurtem- poets. lliey did not limit themselves '^*^'"^' to ridiculing, like Blirger, ' Mam'zell la Regie, nursery-governess and duenna, half French, half Greek, ever ready to watch over the children of the German Muse, preventing them from straying on to the flower-beds and admonishing them to hold up their heads, turn out their toes, and stretch their arms.' Here it was not only against the yoke of scholastic pedantry in science and thought that protest was made, as in the North ; here was not only a platonic hatred vowed against religious and political 0]3pression, as in the plains of Gottingen ; here there was rebellion ag'ainst the established authorities as well. Despotism had put such a strain upon the springs in the little country of Suabia that at last they threatened to snap asunder. The worship of Eousseau nowhere found more numerous and more fervent ad- herents than in the native land of Schiller. The young writer of the ' Brigands ' had himself much to bear from the intolerable yoke of ' Denys turned into a schoolmaster.' It is well known how he escaped from the Duke's College by flight, and what eloquent, clamorous protest he hurled 154 THE REIGN" OF HEEDEE. from that time ao^ainst despotism in ' Fiesco,' in * Cabal and Love,' in ' Don Carlos.' His gipsy- like countryman Weckherlin, who protested in his newspapers, divided his life between prison and exile. Before him Schubart, the journalist, scholar, musician and poet, the model and ideal of Schiller's early days, had raised his voice in impetuous stanzas, and expiated the temerity of his ' Fiirsten- gruft ' by ten years of solitary captivity in the famous castle of Hohenasperg, which received within its walls many other high-minded men, determined to resist absolute rule. More to the South still, in the old Swiss re- publics, ' preserved in spirits of wine,' as Goethe used to say, the new ideas also worked Zurich. against the antiquated and petrified forms of state, society, religion. There it was that Pestalozzi, inflamed by Rousseau's * Emile,' at- tempted to elevate the lower classes by a more natural education, without falling into the ex- tremes of the other great school reformer of the day, Basedow, who had also waged war against all the traditional systems. Basedow, however, who was one of Goethe's odd travelling companions on the Rhine, ^ preached and worked mostly in the • Propliete rechts, Prophete links, Das Weltkind in der Mitten. ZUEICH. loo north of Germany. The other 'prophet,' Lavater (born 1741), the famous physiognomist, taught the new religion in Ziirich, which ever since the beginning of the century had been an active focus of literary life. Reviving pietism in a way by giving it a sort of poetical colour and combining with it a high culture, little familiar to the humble brethren, he pretended to regenerate Christianity by the inner light, by the revelation every day re- peated. With the tone of an inspired seer he boasted of having found again the Divine word, which had been lost. In his heart he felt Christ born anew. This tone and these ideas he brought also into the poetical domain, where he would re- cognise genius alone. Young Goethe was content to proclaim the autocracy of Genius, which ' school could but fetter,' and to which ' principles were more noxious even than examples ; ' Lavater went the length of actual worship : Geniuses (he would exclaim), lights of the world, salt of the earth, nouns in the grammar of humanity, images of Deity, human Gods, creators, destroyers, revealers of the secrets of God and man, drogmans of nature, prophets, priests, kings of the world — it is of you I speak, it is you 1 ask, How did the Deity call you 1 There you have something of the reigning 156 THE EEIGX OF HEEDEE. liercH-svorsliip in its absti-usest form ; and, of course, among the worsliipped heroes was the prophet himself and even his disciples. Xothing could give a better idea of the wars and spirit of this strange young generation than these bizaiTe efPu- sions. However tedious may be the tortured style of the enthusiast, one must endure it if we wotild understand the time. The character of genius is apparition, which, Kke that of an angel, does not come, but is there, which, like that, strikes the innermost maiTow . . . and disappears and continues acting after having disappeared, and leaves behind itself sweet shudders and teai-s of tenx)r and paleness of joy which are the work and effect of genius. Call it as thou hkest — call it fecundity of mind, inexhausti- bility, unequalled sti-ength, piimitive force, elasticity of soul, call it central spirit, central fire, or simply inven- tion, instinct, the not-learned, the not-borrowed, the un- leamable, the unborrowable, etc., etc. And thus it goes on for pages ; but in spite of the absurd form the idea appears clearly. Nothing but spontaneousness is worth anything ; and the form itself is contempt for aU that is orderly, correct, and svstematic. The manners also which shocked not a little the pedantic and economical inhabitants of the Alps corresponded to these forms of style, when the young enthusiasts of STEAS5BUEG. 1-57 the Xorth came as on a pilgrimage to tlie Zurich apostle, foremost among them the two Stolbergs, displaying their long fair locks in the midst of those carefallj powdered heads, and dividing *the crreen waves of the lake ' in full davlight. Who does not think of old Horace? Ingenium mbera quia, fortunatius arte Credit et excludit sanos HeUcone poetas Demociitus, bona pars non ungues ponere curat, etc. Still the true field of battle, that of literary principles, which at that time had alone the power of exciting a passionate interest in Ger- Strassburg. many, after Frederick's heroic period had been succeeded by his more prosaic administrative activit}', the true battle-field was the valley of the Ehine, where historical ideas and interests at all times were wont to meet and join in conflict. It was in Strassburg that Goethe met with unfortunate Lenz, the most gifted perhaps of his friends, a morbid and misunderstood genius, "who, like many of his generation, was to sink, while still voting, into the night of insanity ; with honest Lerse, whom he immortahsed in his ' Gotz ; ' with that strange and kind-hearted dreamer, Jung- Stilling, the tailor-doctor, a sweet and touching physiog- nomy, an ardent and mystical soul, whom Goethe 158 THE REIGN OP HEEDEE. revealed to the Avorld by publisliini^ the manuscript of his diary ; with Herder above all, who was then suffering from an operation on his eyes, and with whom he kept company in the long winter evenings of 1770-71. Here took place those conversations, and that interchange of thought, awakened by their reading which made that year a memorable date, and the city of Strassburg, still entirely German in spite of ninety years of French government, a hallowed spot to the German people. Here it was that young Goethe — then twenty-one years old — who had recently arrived from Leipzig with some- what academical or rather arcadian views and habits of mind, was initiated into the beauties of Shakespeare by Herder. Here it was that they read and re-read the ' Vicar of Wakefield,' 'Tristram Shandy,' Percy's ' Reliques,' and of course Ossian ; and here, also, that Goethe, while under the charm of the most poetical romance of his life, composed his finest lyric poems, sketched his ' Gotz,' and conceived the idea of ' Faust.' The account he has left in his memoirs of the time he spent in Alsace, the portraits he has traced of the companions of his generous freaks there, the de- scription we owe to him of the movement of ideas which animated this sparkling, stirring young FRANKFURT. 159 generation, is simply a masterpiece of literary history in the modest frame of a personal memoir. From Strassburg Goethe returned to his native town, Frankfurt, where he at first settled under the paternal roof — the casa santa, as the Frankfurt. poet s friends used to call it— and after- wards took up his residence at Wetzlar as a clerk to the Imperial Court of Justice. There, assisted by his friend Merck — a shrewd and deep mind of severe literary taste, with whom he was always to be seen, * like Faust and Mephistopheles ' — he edited the chief paper of the party, the ' Frankfurter Gelehrte Anzeigen,' and published stroke upon stroke ' Gotz,' ' Werther,' ' Clavigo.' Here ' Socrates-Addison,' as they called Merck, replaced the ' Irish dean with his whip ' — so they styled Herder — in the tutorship of Goethe, the ' young lord with scraping cock-spurs.' Literary congresses were soon organised everywhere in the valleys of the Lahn, Mein, and Ehine. Jacobi, the philosopher of sentiment, opened his hospitable villa of Pempelfort to his numerous friends ; Sophie de la Eoche — the authoress of ' Fraulein von Sternheim,' the first love of Wieland's youth, the mother of Maximiliane Brentano, who furnished more than one feature to Goethe's ' Lotte,' the 160 THE EEIGN OF HERDER. grandmother of Clemens Brentano, tlie roman- ticist, and Bettina, ' the child ' — Sophie de la Roche received them often in her seat near Co- blentz. The little University of Giessen, where proud Klinger, the dramatist, who has given the name to the whole period, was then studying, and already shaping out that wonderful career which he began as a poor workman's apprentice and ended as a Russian lieutenant-general ; the old imperial city of Wetzlar, where the scene of Goethe's ' Werther ' is laid, as it was the real scene of the poet's and Lotte's love ; the small residence of Darmstadt, where Merck received the visits of all the literary celebrities of the day — saw in turn the meetings where the new creed was enthusiastically preached. It was under Merck's guidance that Goethe, together with his brother-in-law, Schlosser, and Herder, set to work so vigorously and mercilessly to attack the old literary routine in his periodical, upon which Goze, Lessing's old theological enemy, invoked the rigour of the secular arm ; and when we see Merck ' knock the powder out of the wigs ' in his young friend's journal, it is not difficult to understand how Wieland conld say of him : ' Merck is among critics what Klopstock is among WEIMAR. 16] poets, Herder among tlie learned, Lavater among Cliristians, and Goethe among all human beings.' But with, all his impatience for conventional literature, and in spite of his appreciation of that simple, unaffected popular poetry which Herder had brought into fashion, Merck never suffered himself to be deceived bj counterfeit nature a la Macpherson. True, he ridiculed the tight-laced poetry of the times, and had no mercy for classical buskin ; but he was quite as severe upon, the two impetuous Stolbergs' strained enthusiasm, upon whimsical Lenz's intentional eccentricity, and tender-hearted Jacobi's mystic languor. In the midst of all these young folks giving themselves the airs of tribunes or seers — more than one of them had indeed a deceptive likeness to genius — he did not hesitate a moment in distinguishing the only real genius, Wolfgang Apollo. It was Merck also who made him known to the young Duke of Saxe-Weimar, henceforth his protector and friend for life. Goethe was twenty-six years old when he ac- cepted (1775) the invitation of Charles Weimar. Augustus, and transported to Weimar the tone and the allures of the literary Bohemia of Strassburg. There, to the terror of the good M 162 THE REIGN OF HERDER. burghers of that small residence, to the still greater terror of the microscopic courtiers, began that ' genial ' and wild life, which he and his august companion led during several years. Hunting, riding on horseback, masquerades, private theatricals, satirical verse, improvisation of all sorts, flirtation particularly, filled up day and night, to the scandal of all worthy folks, who were utterly at a loss to account for His Serene Highness saying ' Du ' to this Frankfurt roturier. The gay Dowager Duchess, Wieland's firm friend, looked upon these juvenile freaks with a more lenient eye ; for she well knew that the fermen- tation once over, a noble, generous wine would remain. ' We are playing the devil here,' writes Goethe to Merck ; ' we hold together, the Duke and I, and go our own way. Of course, in doing so we knock against the wicked, and also against the good ; but we shall succeed ; for the gods are evidently on our side.' Soon Herder was to join them there, unfortunately not always satisfied with the results of his teaching about absolute liberty of genius. The whole generation bore with impatience, as we have seen, the yoke of the established order, of authority under whatever form, whether GENERAL ATTITUDE OF THE GENERATION. 163 the fetters were tliose of litei^ary convention or social prejudice, of the State or the Church. The er/o affirmed its absolute, inalienable right; ^j^^ ^^^_ it strove to manifest itself according to '^^ the^'S its caprices, and refused to acknow- °'^^'^'^^'"^- ledge any check. Individual inspiration vy;^as a sacred thing, which reality with its rules and prejudices could only spoil and deflower. Now, according to the temperament of each, they rose violently against society and its laws, or resigned themselves silently to a dire necessity. The one in Titanic eflPort climbed Olympus, heaving Pelion on Ossa ; the other wiped a furtive tear out of his eye, and, aspiring to deliverance, dreamed of an ideal happiness. Sometimes in the same poet the two dispositions succeed each other. Cover thy sky with vapour and clouds, Zeus, ex- claims Goethe's Promethevis, and practise thy strength on tops of oaks and summits of mountains like the child who beheads thistles. Thou must, nevertheless, leave me my earth and my hut, which thou hast not built, and my hearth, whose flame thou enviest. Is it not my heart, burning with a sacred ardour, which alone has accom- plished all 1 And should I thank thee, who wast sleeping whilst I worked ] The samjg young man, who had put into the mouth M 2 164 THE EEIGN OF HERDER. of the rebellious Titan this haugiity and defiant outburst, at other moments, when he was dis- couraged and weary of the struggle, toolr refuge within himself. Like Werther, ' finding his world within himself, he spoils and caresses his tender heart, like a sickly child, all whose caprices we in- dulo-e.' One or the other of those attitudes towards reality, the active and the passive, were soon taken by the whole youth of the time ; and just as Schiller's ' Brigands ' gave birth to a whole series of wild dramas, ' Werther ' left in the novels of the time a long line of tears. More than that, even in reality Karl Moor found imitators who engaged in an open struggle against society, and one met at every corner languishing 8iegwarts, whose delicate soul was hurt by the cruel contact of the world. What strikes us most in this morbid sen- timentality, is the eternal melancholy sighing after nature. Ossian's cloudy sadness and Young's dark Nights veil every brow. They fl}' into the solitudes of the forests in order to dream freely of a less brutal world. They must, indeed, have been very far from nature to seek for it with such avidity. Many, in fact, of these ardent, feverish young men became in the end a prey. GENERAL ATTITUDE OF THE GENERATION. 105 some to madness, others to suicide. A species of moral epidemic, like that whicli followed upon the apparent failure of the Ee volution in 1799, had broken out. The germ of Byronism may be clearly detected already in the Wertherism of those times. Exaggerated and overstrained imaginations found insufficient breathing-room in the world, and met on all sides with boundaries to their unlimited demands. Hearts, accustomed to follow the dictates of their own inspiration alone, bruised themselves against the sharp angles of reality. The thirst for action which consumed their ardent youth could not be quenched, in fact, in the narrow limits of domestic life ; and public life did not exist. Frederick had done great things, but only, like the three hundred other German governments, to exclude the youth of the middle classes from active life. Thence the general uneasiness. ' Werther ' was as much an effect as a cause of this endemic disease ; above all, it was the expression of a general state of mind. It is this which constitutes its historical importance, while the secret of its lasting value is to be found in its artistic form. Besides, if I may say so without paradox, the disease was but an excess of health, a juvenile 166 THE REIGN OF HERDER. crisis through which Herder, young Goethe, Schil- ler, and indeed the whole generation, had to pass. Oh (exclaimed old Goethe fifty years later in a conver- sation with young Felix Mendelssohn) — oh, if I could but write a fourth volume of my life. ... It should be a history of the year 177.5, which no one knows or can write better than I. How the nobility, feeling itself outrun by the middle classes, began to do all it could not to be left behind in the race ; how liberalism, jacobinism, and all that devilry awoke : how a new life began ; how we studied, and poetised, made love and wasted our time ; how we young folks, full of life and acti^dty, but awk- ward as we could be, scoffed at the aristocratic proijensities of Messrs. Nicolai and Co. in Berlin, who at that time reigned supreme. . . . Ah, yes, that was a spring, when everything was budding and shooting, when more than one tree was yet bare, while others were already full of leaves. All that in the year 1775 ! Old pedantic Nicolai, at whom he scoffed thus, foresaw, with his prosy common* sense, what would happen ' with all those confounded striplings,' as Wieland called them, ' who gave themselves airs as if they were accustomed to play at blind -man's buff with Shakespeare.' ' In four or five years,' said he in 1776, *this fine enthusiasm will have passed away like smoke ; a few drops of sj>irit will be found in the empty helmet, and a big cajjut LATER PHILOSOPHY OF HIS DISCIPLES. 167 mortuum in the crucible.' This proved true cer- tainly for the great majority, but not so as regards the two coursers which then broke loose, and for him who had cut their traces and released them. Of the latter I have spoken to-day ; of tlie former two I shall say something the next time we meet. Not of their youth, however, but of their maturer age ; not of their vie ws when they were twenty, but of the philosophy which they had come to twenty years later. Goethe, indeed, modified, or at least cleared up, his early views under the influence of a deeper study of nature and the sight of ancient and Eenaissance Art in Italy (1786-1788) ; Schil- ler put himself to school under Kant (1790), and went out of it with a completely altered philosophy ; Kant himself became another after, if not in consequence of, the great King's death (1786); Herder alone remained faithful throughout to the creed he had himself preached. I have dwelt so long on Herder not only because, till lately, his influence has not been sufficiently acknowledged, but also because the way Conclusion. opened by mm, although partly and temporarily abandoned during the classical period of which I shall have to speak to you the next time, was followed again by the third generation 168 THE EEIGN OF HERDER. of the founders of German culture, the so-called Eomanticists, and by all the great scholars, who, in the first half of this century, revived the his- torical sciences in Germany. Herder's ideas have, indeed, penetrated our whole thought to such a degree, whilst his works are so unfinished and disconnected, that it is hardly possible for us to account for the extraordinary effect these ideas and works produced in their day, except by marking the contrast which they present with the then reigning methods and habits, as well as the surprising in- flaeiice exercised by Herder personally. From his twenty-fifth year, indeed, he was a sovereign. His actual and uncontested sway was not, it is true, prolonged beyond a period of about sixteen years, albeit his name figured to a much later time on the list of living potentates. It is also true, that when the seeds thrown by him had grown luxuri- antly, and were bearing fruit, the sower was almost entirely forgotten or wilfully ignored. The gene- ration, however, of the ' Stiirmer und Drang er,' or, as they were pleased to denominate themselves, the 'original geniuses,' looked up to Herder as their leader and prophet. Some of them turned from him later on and went back to the exclusive worship of classical antiquity ; but their very HIS INDIRECT I-NTLUENCE. 169 manner of doing homage to it bore witness to Herder's influence. The following generation threw itself no less exclusively into the middle ages ; but what, after all, was it doing if not fol- lowing Herder's example, when it raked up Dantes and Calderons out of the dust in order to confront them with and oj)pose them to Virgils and Racines ? HoAvever they might repudiate, nay even forget, their teacher, his doctrines already pervaded the whole intellectual atmosphere of Germany, and men's minds breathed them in with the very air they inhaled. To-day they belong to Europe. Herder, I repeat, is certainly neither a classical nor a finished writer. He has no doubt gone out of fashion, because his style is pompous and diffuse, his composition loose or fragmentary ; because his reasoning lacks firmness and his erudi- tion solidity. Still, no other German writer of note exercised the imjDortant indirect influence which was exercised by Herder. In this I do not allude to Schelling and his philosophy, which received more than one impulse from Herder's ideas ; nor to Hegel, who reduced them to a metaphysical system and defended them with his wonderful dialectics. But F. A. Wolf, when he points out to us in Homer the process of epic poetry ; Niebuhr, 170 THE REIGN OF HERDER. in revealing to us the growth of Eome, the birth of her religious and national legends, the slow, gradual formation of her marvellous constitution; Savigny, when he proves that the Roman Civil Law, that masterpiece of human ingenuity, was not the work of a wise legislator, but rather the wisdom of generations and of centuries ; Eichhorn, when he wrote the history of German law and created thereby a new branch of historical science which has proved one of the most fertile ; A. W. Schlegel and his school, when they trans- planted all the poetry of other nations to Germany by means of imitations which are real Avonders of assimilation ; Frederick Schlegel, when, in the * Wisdom of the Hindoos,' he opened out that vast field of comparative linguistic science, which Bopp and so many others have since cultivated with such success ; Alexander von Humboldt and Karl Eitter, when they gave a new life to geo- graphy by showing the earth in its growth and development and coherence ; W. von Humboldt, when he established the laws of language as well as those of self-government ; Jacob Grimm, when he brought German philology into existence, while his brother Wilhelm made a science of Northern myth- ology; still later on, D. F. Strauss, when, in the days FERTILITY OF HIS IDEAS. 171 of our own youth, he placed the myth and the legend, with their unconscious origin and growth, not alone in opposition to the idea of Deity intervening to interrupt established order, but also to that of imposture and conscious fraud ; Otfr. Miiller, when he j)roved that Greek mythology, far from con- taining moral abstractions or historical facts, is the involuntary personification of surrounding nature, subsequently developed by imagination ; Max Miiller even, when he creates the new science of comparative mythology — what else are they doing but applying and working out Herder's ideas ? And if we turn our eyes to other nations, what else were Burke and Coleridge, B. Constant and A. Thierry, Guizot and A. de Tocqueville — what are Eenan and Taine, Carlyle and Darwin doing, each in his own branch, but applying and developing Herder's two fundamental principles, that of or- ganic evolution and that of the entireness of the individual? For it was Herder who discovered the true spirit of history, and in this sense it is that Goethe was justified in saying of him : A noble mind, desirous of fathoming man's soul in whatever direction it may shoot forth, searcheth through- out the universe for sovmd and word which flow through the lands in a thousand sources and brooks ; wanders 172 THE EEIGN OF HERDEE. tbrough the oldest as the newest regions and listens in every zone. . . . He knew how to find this soul wher- ever it lay hid, whether robed in grave disguise, or lightly clothed in the garb of play, in order to found for the future this lofty rule : Humanity be our eternal aim !j 173 LECTURE Y. THE TRIUMVIRATE OF GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLER. 1787- 1800. Among the young literary rebels who, under Herder's guidance, attempted, towards and after 1775, to overthrow all conventionalism, all autho- rity, even all law and rule, in order to put in their stead the absolute self-government of genius, freed from all tutorship — the foremost were the two greatest German poets, Goethe and Schiller. Goethe's 'Gotz' and ' Werther,' Schiller's 'Bri- gands,' and ' Cabal and Love,' were greeted as the promising forerunners of the national literature to come. Their subjects were German and modern, not French or classic ; in their plan they affected Shakespearean liberty ; in their language they were at once familiar, strong, and original; in 174 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLER. their inspiration they were protests against the social prejudices and political abuses of the time, vehement outbursts of individuality against con- vention. Not twenty years had passed away, when both the revolutionists had become calm and resig^ned liberal conservatives, who understood and taught that liberty is possible only under the empire of law ; that the real world with all its limits had a rio-lit as well as the inner world, which knows no frontiers ; that to be completely free man must fly into the ideal sphere of Art, Science, or formless Religion. Not that they abjured ' the dreams of their youth.' The nucleus of their new creed was contained in their first belief; but it had been developed into a system of social views more in harmony with society and its exigencies, of aesthe- tic opinions more independent of reality and its accidents, of philosophical ideas more speculative and methodical. In other words, Goethe and Schiller never ceased to believe as they had done at twenty, that all vital creations in nature as in society are the result of growth and organic development, not of intentional, self-conscious planning, and that individuals on their part act powerfully only through their nature in its en- GENERAL VIEW ON NATURE AND MAN. 175 tiretj, not through one faculty alone, such as reason or will, separated from instinct, imagina- tion, temperament, passion, etc. Only they came to the conviction that there existed general laws which presided over organic development, and that there was a means of furthering in the individual the harmony between temperament, character, understanding, and imagination, with- out sacrificing one to the others. Hence they shaped for themselves a general view of Nature and Mankind, Society and History, which may not have become the permanent view of the whole nation ; but which for a time was predominant, which even now is still held by many, and which in some respects will always be the ideal of the best men in Germany, even when circumstances have wrought a change in the intellectual and social conditions of their country, so as to necessi- tate a total transformation and accommodation of those views. We cannot regard it merely as the natural effect of advancing years, if Goethe and Schiller modified and cleared their views ; if Kant, whose great emancipating act, the ' Critic of Pure Reason,' falls chronologically in the preceding period (1781), corrected what seemed to him too absolute in his 176 GOETHEj KANT, AND SCHILLER. system, and reconstructed from the basis of the conscience that metaphysical world which he had destroyed by his analysis of the intellect. The world just then was undergoing profound changes. The great ' Philosopher King ' had descended to the tomb (178G), and with him the absolute libertj"^ of thought, which had reigned for forty- six years. The French Eevolution, after having exalted all generous souls, and seemingly con- firmed the triumph of liberty and justice which the generation had witnessed in America, took a direction and drifted into excesses which unde- ceived, sobered, and saddened even the most hopeful believers. As regards personal circum- stances, the Italian journey of Goethe (1786-1788) and his scientific investigations into nature, the study of Kant's new philosophy to which Schiller submitted his undisciplined mind (1790 and 1791), were the high-schools out of which their genius came strengthened and purified, although their aesthetic and moral doctrines did not remain quite unimpaired by them. I shall endeavour to give an idea of this double process and its results at the risk of being still more abstract and dry than before.' ' For the following pages on Goethe, see his 'Wilhelm Meister,' especially the sixth book, and ' Bildung und Umbildung ART AND NATURE. 177 Man is the last and liighest linlc in Nature ; Lis task is to understand what she aims Q^gthe's at in liim and then to fulfil her inten- moral ^ tions. This view of Herder's was Goethe's '"""^'P ***• starting-point in the formation of his Weltan- schauung or general view of things. All the woi-ld (says one of the characters in ' Wilhelm Meister ' ) lies before us, like a vast quarry before the architect. He does not deserve the name, if he does not compose with these accidental natural materials an image whose soux'ce is in his mind, and if he does not do it with the greatest possible economy, solidity, and perfection. All that we find outside of us, nay, within us, is object-matter ; but deep within us lives also a power capable of giving an ideal form to this matter. This creative power allows U3 no rest till we have produced that ideal form in one or the other way, either without us in finished woi-ks, or in our own life. Here we already have in germ Schiller's idea that life ought to be a work of art. But how do we achieve this task, continually impeded as we are by circumstances and by our fellow-creatures, who will not always leave us in peace to develop our individual characters in perfect conformity with organischer Naturen,' particularly 'Gescliichte meines Botan- ischeu btudiams ' (vol. xxxvi. of the ' Works '). 178 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLER. nature? In our relations with our neighbour, Goethe (like Lessing and Wieland, Kant and Herder, and all the great men of his and the pre- ceding age, in England and France as well as in Germany) recommended absolute toleration not only of opinions, but also of individualities, par- ticularly those in which Nature manifests herself ' undefiled.' As to circumstances, which is only another name for Fate, he preached and practised resignation. At every turn of our life, in fact, we meet with limits ; our intelligence has its frontiers which bar its way ; our senses are limited, and can only embrace an infinitely small part of nature ; few of our wishes can be fulfilled ; pri- vation and sufferings await us at every moment. ' Privation is thy lot, privation ! That is the eternal song which resounds at every moment, which, our whole life through, each hour sings hoarsely to our ears ! ' laments Faust. What remains then for man ? ' Everything cries to us that we must resign ourselves.' 'There are few men, however, who, conscious of the privations and sufferings in store for them in life, and desirous to avoid the necessity of resigning themselves anew in each particular case, have the courage to perform the act of resignation once for all ; ' who Goethe's moral principles. 179 say to themselves that there are eternal and neces- sary laws to which we must submit, and that we had better do it without grumbling ; who ' en- deavour to form principles which are not liable to be destroyed, but are rather confirmed by contact with reality.' In other words, when man has discovered the laws of nature, both moral and physical, he must accept them as the limits of his actions and desires ; he must not wish for eternity of life or inexhaustible capacities of enjoyment, understanding, and acting, any more than he wishes for the moon. For rebellion against these laws must needs be an act of impotency as well as of deceptive folly. By resignation, on the contrary, serene resignation, the human soul is purified ; for thereby it becomes free of selfish passions and arrives at that intellectual superiority in which the contemplation and understanding of things give sufficient contentment, without making it needful for man to stretch out his hands to take possession of them : a thought which Goethe's friend, Schiller, has magnificently developed in his grand philosophical poems. Optimism and pessimism disappear at once as well as fatalism ; the highest and most refined intellect again accepts the world, as children and ignorant toilers do, as N 2 180 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLER. a given necessity. He does not even think the world could be otherwise, and within its limits he not only enjoys and suffers, but also works gaily, trying, like Horace, to subject things to himself, but resiofned to submit to them, when thev are invincible. Thus the simple Hellenic existence which, contrary to Christianity, but according to nature, accepted the present without ceaselessly thinking of death and another world, and acted in that precent and in the circumstances allotted to each by fate, without wanting to overstep the boundaries of nature, would revive again in our modern world and free us for ever from the torment of unaccomplished wishes and of vain terrors. The sojourn in Italy, during which Goethe lived outside the struggle for life, outside the competition and contact of practical Goethe's . . . view of activity, m the contemplation or nature Nature. ^ , . . and art, developed this view — the spec- tator's view, which will always be that of the artist and of the thinker, strongly opposed to that of the actor on the stage of human life. ' Iphi- genia,' ' Torquato Tasso,' * Wilhelm Meister ' are the fruits and the interpreters of this conception of the moral world. What ripened and perfected it, 30 as to raise it into a general view, not only of Goethe's method. 181 morality, but also of the great philosopliical questions which man is called upon to answer, was his study of nature, greatly furthered during his stay in Italy. The problem which lay at the bottom of all the vague longing of his generation for nature he was to solve. It became his inces- sant endeavour to understand the coherence and unity oi nature. You are for ever searching for what is necessary in nature (Schiller wrote to him once), but you search for it by the most difficult way. You take the whole of natui'e in oider to obtain light on the particular case ; you look into the totality for the explanation of the individual existence. From the simplest organism (in nature), you ascend step by step to the more complicated, and finally construct the most complicated of all, man, out of the materials of the whole of nature. In thus creatmg man anew under the guidance of nature, you penetrate into his mysterious organism. And, indeed, as there is a wonderful harmony with nature in Goethe, the poet and the man, so there is the same harmony in Goethe, the savant and the thinker ; nay, even science he practised as a poet. As one of the greatest physicists of our days, Helmholtz, has said of him : * He did not try to translate nature into abstract concep- tions, but takes it as a complete work ot art, which 182 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLER. must reveal its contents spontaneouslj to an intelligent observer.' Goethe never became a thorough experimentalist ; he did not want ' to extort the secret from nature by pumps and re- torts.' He waited patiently for a voluntary revela- tion, i.e. until he could surprise that secret by an intuitive glance ; for it Avas his conviction that if you live intimatel}^ with Nature, she will sooner or later disclose her mysteries to you. If you read his ' Songs,' his ' Werther,' his ' Wahlverwandt- schaften,' jo\i feel that extraordinary intimacy — I had almost said identification — with nature, pre- sent everywhere. Werther's love springs up with the blossom of all nature ; he begins to sink and iiears his self-made tomb, while autumn, the death of nature, is in the fields and woods. So does the moon spread her mellow light over his garden, as 'the mild eye of a true friend over his destiny.' Kever was there a poet who humanised nature or naturalised hnman feeling, if I might say so, to the same degree as Goethe. Now, this same love of nature he brought into his scientific researches. He began his studies of nature early, and he began them as he was to fi.nisn them, with geology. BufFon's great views on the revolutions of the earth had made a deep impression upon him, although Goethe's view of a'ature. 183 lie was to end as tlie declared adversai-y of that vulcanisni which we can trace already at the bottom ofBuffon's theory — naturally enough, when we thiuk how uncongenial all violence in society' and nature was to him, how he looked everywhere for slow, uninterrupted evolution. From theo- retical study he had early turned to direct obser- vation ; and when his administrative functions obliged him to survey the mines of the little Dukedom, ample opportunit}- was offered for positive studies. As early as 1778, in a paper on Granite, he wrote : ' I do not fear the reproach that a spirit of contradiction draws me from the contemplation of the human heart — this most mobile, most mutable and fickle part of the creation — to the observation of (granite) the oldest, firmest, deepest, most immovable son of Nature. For all natural things are in connexion with each other.' It was his life's task to search for the links of this coherence in order to find that unity, which he knew to be in the moral as well as material uni- verse. From those ' first and most solid beginnings of our existence,' he turned to the history of plants and to the anatomy of the animals which cover this crust of the earth. The study of Spinoza 184 GOETHE, KANT, AKD SCHILLEE. confirmed liim in the direction thus taken. * There I am on and under the mountains, seeking the divine in herhis et laindibus,' says he, in Spinoza's own words ; and again : ' Pardon me, if I like to remain silent, when people speak of a divine being which I can know only in rehus singularibvs.' This pantheistic view grew stronger and stronger with years ; but it became a pantheism very different from that of Parmenides, for whom being and thinking are one, or from that of Giordano Bruno, which rests on the analog-y of a universal soul with the human soul, or even from that of Spinoza himself, which takes its start from the relations of the physical world witli the conceptive world, and of both with the divine one. Goethe's pantheism always tends to discover the cohesion of the members of nature, of which man is one : if once he has discovered this universal unity, where there are no gaps in space, nor leaps in time, lie need not search further for the divine. Nature ! We live in it and remain strangers to it. It continvially talks to us and does not betray its secret. It seems to have planned everything with a view to indi- viduality, and does not care for individuals. It lives only by continual birth, and the mother is indiscernible. Nature has thought, and does not cease to think ; but it Goethe's view of nature. 1S5 thinks, not as man does, but as Nature. It loves itself and is ever centred on itself with innumerable eyes and hearts. It has multiplied itself in order to enjoy itself a hundredfold. It is ever creating new enjoyers, never tired of communicating itself. Life is its most beautiful invention, and death its artifice for having much life. This idea it was which was afterwards meta- physically developed by Schelling and Hegel ; but metaphysics are not what we are now studying-. Even when I shall have to speak by and by of Kant, who entirely changed the basis of all specu- lative thought, I shall leave aside his philosophy proper as much as possible, and try only to speak of his way of looking at life and history. Goethe's view of life, which he won through the study of nature, and which consists in trying to seize the unity of nature in the constant climax of its phenomena up to the highest, the intellectual phenomenon, man, — differs from all former similar views in this, that it considers the coherence of the universe as a process in time, a history in which or through which nature becomes conscious of itself, not as a connection by links in space only. This is the point where Herder's influence is most percej)tible, and which was to be brought into a system by the methodical and dialectical specula- 186 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLEE. tions of Hegel, whom we may consider as the great summariser of all the intellectual work done by Germany during the sixty or seventy years with which we are occupied. By what means was this process, this history, which Goethe discerned in the coherence of nature, to be discovered and understood ? By the means of the very same organ of intuition which the whole generation of Herder and Goethe had recog- nised in their youth as the highest of poetical faculties, and which Kant himself had admitted to be the distinctive quality of the poet. Others, we have seen and shall further see, applied this faculty to history. Goethe applied it to nature. His poet's eye revealed to him the mystery of nature's laws ; but he was not content with such divination. He became a patient and conscien- tious observer, and did not rest until he had, as it were, proved his sum. Now, this method has re- mained the dominant one in Germany, and has misled thinkers more than once, when they applied it without controlling it by the inductive method. The aberrations and excrescences of Schelling's philosophy of Nature are in everybody's memory ; and the best things done in natural science, even in Germany, have been done by adversaries of Goethe's view of nature. 187 Scbelling's school and adherents of the mechanical principle of explanation. Nevertheless the in- tuitive method has been wonderfully fertile even for natural science, and I remember how often Liebig himself told mo that all his discoveries had been the result of lightning-like intuition and divination, ascertained afterwards by observation and experiment. As for historical sciences, the conquests made by the intuitive method are nncontested. It has taught the world that the knowledge of laws — that is to say, the most ab- stract and unreal kind of knowledge — is by no means alone valuable ; that causality, to which the savants of our dav would again limit all science, is not its sole object; that the intuitive knowledge of typical forms — in other words, of platonic ideas — which we acquire by the careful observation of individual and particular phenomena, has equally its value; for it allows us to form ideas of things, which always remain the same through all the changes of the phenomena, and neverthe- less do not exist in reality. It is analogy which helps us to form these intuitive or platonic ideas. It was through analogy that Goethe arrived at his great dis- coveries in natural science, and I only repeat ]88 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLER. what swch men as Johannes Miiller, Baer, and Hehnholtz have been willing to acknowledge, when I say that the poet's eye has been as keen as that of any naturalist. Kant had contended that there might be a superior Intelligence, which, contrary to human intelligence, goes from the general to the particular ; and Goethe thought — he proved, I might say — that in man too some of this divine intelligence can operate and shine, if only in isolated sparks. It was a spark of this kind which, first at Padua on the sight of a fan- palm tree, then again, on the eve of his departure from Palermo, during a walk in the public garden amidst the southern vegetation, revealed to him the law of the metamorphosis of plants. He found an analogy between the difierent parts of the same plant which seemed to repeat themselves : unity and evolution were revealed to him at once. Three years later the sight of a half-broken sheep-skull, which he found by chance on the sand of the Venetian Lido, taught him that the same law, as he had suspected, applied also to vertebrate animals, and that the skull might be considered as a series of strongly modified ver- tebrae. He had, in fact, already hinted at the principle, shortly after put forward by Lamarck, Goethe's view op nature. 189 and long afterwards developed and firmly established by Darwin. He considered the difference in the anatomical structure of animal species as modi- fications of a type or planned structure, modi- fications brought about by the difference of life, food, and dwellings. He had discovered as early as 1 786 the intermaxillary bone in man, i.e. the remnant of a part which had had to be adapted to the exigencies of the changed structure ; and proved thereby that there had been a primitive similarity of structure, which had been trans- formed by development of some parts, and atrophy of others. Goethe's sketch of an ' In- troduction into Comparative Anatomy,' which he wrote in 1795, urged by A. von Humboldt, has remained, if I may believe those competent to judge, a fundamental stone of modern science. And, I may be allowed, as I am unversed in such matters, to invoke the authority of one of the most eminent living physiologists, Helmholtz, who says of Goethe's anatomical essay, that in it the poet .... teaclies, with the greatest clearness and decision, that all differences in the structure of animal species are to be considered as changes of one fundamental type, which have been brought about by fusion, transformation, ag- grandiiiement, diminution, or total annihilation of several 190 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLER. parts. This has, indeed, become, in the present state of comparative anatomy, the leading idea of this science. It has never since been expressed better or more clearly than by Goethe : and after-times have made few essential modifications.' Now, the same may be said, I am told, in spite of some differences as to details, of Ms metamor- phosis of plants. I do not mean by this to say that Goethe is the real author of the theory of evolution. There is between him and Mr. Darwin the difference which there is between Vico and Niebuhr, Herder and F. A. Wolf. In the one case we have a fertile hint, in the other a well- established system, worked out by proofs and convincing arguments. Nevertheless, when a man like Johannes Miiller sees in Goethe's views ' the presentiment of a distant ideal of natural history,' we may be allowed to see in Goethe one of the fathers of the doctrine of evolution, which, after all, is only an application of Herder's prin- ciple oi fieri to the material world. After having thus gone through the whole series of organisms, from the simplest to the most complicated, Goethe finds that he has laid, as it were, the last crowning stone of the universal 1 Written in 1853, five years before the appearance of Mr, Darwin's great work. Goethe's philosophic views. 191 pyramid, raised from the materials of the whole quarry of nature ; that he has reconstructed man. And here begins a new domain ; for after Goethe's all for mankind the highest study must be philosophic views. man himself. The social problems of property, education, marriage, occupied Goethe's mind all his life through, although more parti- cularly in the last thirty years. The relations of man with nature, the question how far he is free from the laws of necessity, how far subject to them, are always haunting him. If you read the ' Wahl- verwandtschaften,' the ' Wanderjahre,' the second ' Faust,' you will find those grave questions ap- proached from all sides. I shall not, however, enter here into an exposition of Goethe's political, social, and educational views, not only because they mostly belong to a later period, but especially because they have never found a wide echo, nor determined the opinions of an important portion of the nation, nor entered as integrating principles into its lay creed. Not so with the metaphysical conclusion which he reached by this path, and which is somewhat different from the pantheism of his youth, inasmuch as he combines with it some- what of the fundamental ideas of Leibnitz, which were also Lessing's, and which, after all, form a » 192 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLER. sort of return to Christianity, as understood in its widest sense, in the sense in which it harmonises with Plato's idealism. ' Tliiuking is not to be severed from what is thought, nor will from move- ment.' Nature consequently is God, and God is nature, but in this God-Nature man lives as an imperishable monad, capable of going through thousands of metamorphoses, but destined to rest on each stage of this unlimited existence, in full possession of the present, in which he has to ex- pand his whole being by action or enjoyment. This conception of life was not, as you will see, the creation of an imagination longing to pass beyond the conditions of human existence — which is the idealism of the ' general '— but the highest result of the poet's insight into the order of nature. Here we mark the great contrast with the later Kant, the contrast between a view which sees in man one link in the chain of nature, and the view which takes man out of the order of nature and makes him a member of a higher invisible order. This contrast has filled up the intellectual history of Germany ever since Herder opened hostilities against the master of his youth. In vain Fichte, Scheiling, Hegel gave themselves out to be the disciples of Kant ; in reality they Goethe's philosophic Views. 193 ■were only the sophists, who, with the weapons of Kant's dialecticism, carried ad ahsurdum the main idea of Herder and Goethe, the German idea, Kar^ s^o-^rjv, according to which nature is immanent in the human mind, and develops itself by the de- veloping of the conceptions of this mind. For mind is nothing* else hut nature come to the con- sciousness of itself : its essence being the essence of nature, its contents the contents of nature. The task of the student is to discover this identity, and the most powerful vehicle for its discovery is intuition. Now, as long as in these matters in- tuition let itself be controlled by observation and induction, it had wonderful results, particularly in the historical sciences and even in the natural sciences, although, as I just said, the best part of Germany's work in the latter was done by ad- versaries of this method. Still, A. von Humboldt, when he declared his aim to be 'the consideration of physical things as a whole, moved and animated by inner forces,' and K. Ritter, when he defined 'the earth as a cosmic individual with a particular organisation, an ens sui generis, with progressive development,' both stood on common ground with Goethe and Herder ; on common ground even with Schelling, whose influence has been so de- o \ 10 J) GOET^ter :^ANT, AND SCHILLER. plorable on natural science in Germany, leading- to the most dangerous consequences through the desire to understand and grasp the parts, their distribution and ordination, by starting from the whole — a sort of deductive system of intuition as the old deductive system was one of abstract conceptions. What, on the contrary, the intui- tive method, supported by severe and sagacious criticism of detail, has produced in the historical sciences, which can only be grasped by intuition, I need not say. The names of F. A. Wolf and Niebuhr, W. von Humboldt and Bopp, the Grimms and Boeckh, Savigny and Eichhorn, tell us clearly enough. Philology and archaeology, theology and mythology, jurisprudence and history j)roper, have been entirely renewed by it ; whilst linguistic and literary history may be said to have been created by it. (I am here only explaining the views of the creators of German culture : I do not defend them, where I share them, as I did not criticise them when I found myseK at variance with them. Else, I should certainly pause here, and in all courtesy break a lance with those men of the younger generation and of this island, who would treat the historical sciences by the same method as the natm-al or mathematical.) THE TWO CURRENTS. 195 I have said that there was an antagonism between Kant's views and those of Herder and Goethe, and that this antagonism has rj,,^g ,p^^ been ever since sensibly felt in the intel- ^^"®°^^- lectual history of Germany. Some efforts were made to reconcile them, as for instance by Schiller. Sometimes a sort of alliance took place, as in 1813, when the romanticists, who were quite under the spell of the Herder-Goethe ideas, invoked the aid of the moral energy, which was a special characteristic of Kant's disciples ; but the antagonism lives on not the less even now in the German nation, as the antagonism between Hume and Burke, Locke and Berkeley, Fielding and Richardson, Shakespeare and Milton, nay, between Renaissance and Puritan- ism in spite of their apparent death, is still living in the English nation. This difference is, as will happen in this world, much jnore the difference between two dispositions of mind, character, and temperament, than between two opposite theories ; or at least the conflicting opinions are much more the result of our moral and intellectual dispositions than of objective observation and abstract argu- mentation. Germany owes much to the stern unflinching moral principles of Kant ; she owes still more, however, to tlie serene and large views o 2 196 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLER. of Goethe. The misfortune of both ideals is that they cannot and will never be accessible save to a small elite, that of Kant to a moral, that of Goethe to an intellectual elite. But are not all ideals of an essentially aristocratic nature ? The German ideals, however, are so more than others, and the consequence has been a wide gap between the mass of the nation and the minority which has been true to those ideals. The numerical majority, indeed, of the German nation has either remained faithful to the Church, though without fanatic- ism, or has become materialistic and rationalistic. It is a great misfortune for a nation when its greatest writer in his greatest works is only understood by the happy few, and when its greatest moralist preaches a moral which is above the common force of human nature. The only means of union between the nation and the in- tellectual and moral aristocracy, which has kept and guarded that treasure, as well as the only link between these two aristocratic views of life themselves, would be furnished by religion, a religion such as Lessing, Mendelssohn, and above all Schleiermacher, propounded, such as reigned all over Germany forty or fifty years ago, before party spirit had set to work, and the flattest of THE TWO CURRENTS. 197 rationalisms liad again invaded the nation — a religion, corresponding, for the mass, to what Goethe's and Kant's philosophy, which is neither materialism nor spiritualism, is for the few — a religion based on feeling and intuition, on con- science and reverence, but a religion Avithout dogmas, without ritual, without forms, above all without exclusiveness, and without intolerance. I doubt whether this mild and noble spirit, which is bj no means indifferentism, will soon revive, as I doubt whether Germany will quickly get over the conflict between the traditional and the rationalistic spirit, which mars her public life, whether too she will soon reach that political ideal which England realised most fully in the first half of this century and which consists in a perfect equilibrium between the spirit of tradi- tion and that of rationalism. However, although Kant's lofty and Goethe's deep philosophy of life is now the treasure of a small minority only, it has none the less pervaded all the great scientific and literary work done up to the middle of this century. It has presided over the birth of our new State ; and the day will certainly come when public opinion in Germany will turn away from the tendency of her present literature, science, and 198 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLEE. politics — a somewhat nan'ow patriotism, a rather shallow materialism, and a thoroughly false parlia- mentary regime — and come back to the spirit of the generations to whom, after all, she owes her intellectual, though not perhaps her political and material, civilisation. But I have wandered away from our immediate subject, and it is time that I should come back to it, and especially to Kant, who, at the period we speak of, wielded, with Groethe and Schiller, the sceptre of intellectual life. Whoever has studied the history of German philosophy, knows that there are two Kants ; nay, Kant ^ might even say, three Kants. The first h. 1/24. j^^jj-t^ i]^Q young Kant of thirty, started, as we have seen, from Newton and Rousseau, and came to a view of the world and of mankind very much akin to that of Lessing. He was little noticed then, however, and acted little upon his contemporaries at large, in spite of the animated, sometimes even elegant and ornamented, style of his youthful essays. The second Kant, if I might be allowed to say so, wrote when he was fifty and published in 1781 the ' Critic of Pure Eeason,' the most wonderful effort of abstract thought which the world has seen. By this extraordinaiy per- formance Kant effected for the intellectual world, KANT. 199 as lie said himself, what Copernicus had effected for the physical world : an entire change of the basis of all philosophical study. Before him the only paths tried in metaphysics were dogmatism and scepticism. He had himself followed first the one with L eibnitz- Wolff ; then the other with Hume ; but coming to no satisfactory conclusion with either, he at last chose a third way, the critical, and made this ' footpath a highroad ' to the knowledge of speculative truth. Till now it was taken for gi'anted that onr under- standing must accommodate itself to the objects ; but all attempts to learn anything which might widen our know- ledge by a priori conceptions were without result in consequence of that supposition. Let us try, therefore, whether we do not come nearer to the solution of meta- physical problems, by supposing that objects must accom- modate themselves to our understanding. ... It is with this as with the fii'st thought of Copernicus. Not suc- ceeding with the explanation of the celestial movements as long as he supposed that all the host of stars turned round the observer, he tried whether he would not succeed better if he left the stars quiet, and made the observer turn round. There can be no doubt that the hypothesis proved true in both cases. Kant's philosophy is to the metaphysics before him what astronomy 200 GOETHE, KANT, AND SGHILLEE. is to astrology, "vvliat chemistry is to alcliymy. As lie proclaimed, lie acliieved the momentous revolution by submitting to examination the in- stniment itself of philosophising, i.e. human reason, for, according to him, philosophy is a science which treats ' of the limits of reason,' and he showed why it is incapable of grasping the infi- nite in space and time, as well as the idea of a first cause. Space, indeed, as well as time, and in- directly causality, are not qualities of the outer world, but laws of our mind, or rather ' forms of our representation,' which have nothing to do with the things themselves. In fact, objects of the senses can never be known, but as they a^jpear to us (through the subjective medium of space and time) not as they are in themselves; and objects which our senses do not perceive are no objects for our theoretical knowledge. (Remark the theo- retical, because on it the later evolution of Kant hinges.) Kant never denied the existence of the sensual world, as Berkeley did ; he only con- tended that we see it not as it is, but as the forms of our intellect make it appear. Teleology is therefore a ' regulative ' principle of our under- standing, which supplies a motive for the world of phenomena, not a ' constitutive ' principle of this objective world. It is true that Kant added in the KANT. 201 first edition of his book a passage which he left out in the second, and in which he said, quite in pass- ing, that the ' thing in itself ' and the perceiving ego might be one and the same thinking substance, and it is on this passing hypothesis that 'the three great impostors,' as Schopenhauer most unjustly calls Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, constructed their whole idealism. Kant himself says plainly enouo-h : — "»' The proposition of all the true idealists, from the Eleatic school down to Bishop Berkeley, is contained in the formula : all knowledge through the senses and ex- perience is mere appearance ; truth is only in the ideas of pure intelligence and pure reason. The principle which governs and pervades all my idealism is, on the contrary : all knowledge of things through pure intelli- gence and pure reason is nothing but appearance ; truth is only in experience. All psychology, cosmology, and theology based on pure reason fall with that principle ; for they are attempts to apply the forms or categories of the understanding to the 'thing in itself,' which those very categories prevent it from perceiving, consequently they must mislead. Psychology, which treats the soul as a thinking substance, must lead to paralogisms, such as liberty Avithout motives ', theology, with its famous three proofs 202 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLER. of the Deity, deals witli empty conceptions ; cos- mology, wliich considers the world as it appears to us, to be the world as it really is, can only end in contradiction or antiDomies {e.g. the world has a beginning and is limited in space, and the antithesis, the world is eternal and infinite). The ' Critic of Pure Reason ' made a great stir : but the salutary influence which it Kant's . . -, 1 . moral phi- might have exercised at once on the phi- losophy. losophical movement of the country ,^ as it begins to do just now only, was marred to a cer- tain extent by the second great book of Kant, the ' Critic of Practical Peason,' which virtually was a retractation of the first book. Indeed, Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, the so-called continuators of Kant, meant to be true Kantians, when with one foot they stood on the ' Pure Eeason,' with the other on the ' Practical Eeason.' We all know what was the result of their acrobatic efforts at equilibrium. Scho]3enhauer, the only thinker who held fast by Kant's great discovery, and took his starting- point from it, combining it at the same time with the Herder-Goethe idea of the ever-working creative power in nature, remained ignored for forty years. Since then there has been a revival of Kant's philosophy, which will, I trust. kakt's mokal philosophy. 203 prove permanent; and it is particularly remark- able that, as Kant started from tlie natural sciences to arrive at the criticism of the mind, so his critical method has in our days penetrated into, and pervades, all the natural sciences. Almost all the really great men of science in Germany are neither materialists nor spiritualists, nor sceptics, but critics, if I may say so, of the Kantian school. This, however, is not the place to enter further into an exposition of Kant's ' Pure Reason ; ' for here, I repeat, we are not studying the history of philosophy any more than that of literature and the State, but the history of the general thought of the German nation. Now a book like Kant's ' Pure Eeason ' cannot exercise any direct in- fluence on the general thought of a nation ; it is too special for that, too difficult, too abstract; it remains the esoteric property of the philo- sophers. Even the indirect influence which it must exercise, the exoteric doctrine, which belongs to the domain of these lectures, begins only to be felt in our days, as I said just now, and we are speaking here of the end of the past century, Not so with what I venture to call the third Kant. Kant published his 'Critic of Practical Eeason' in 1 788, his ' Critic of Judgment ' in 1790, 204 GOETHE, KAXT, AND SCHILLEE. and these two books liad a deep and immediate effect on general thought. Schiller modified his fiesthetic views under the influence of the latter, and the best of a whole generation lived and acted in the lofty — for us too loftj — moral ideas of the former. Kant's ' Critic of Pure Eeason ' had been the scientific analysis of the human intellect. His ' Critic of Practical Eeason ' may be regarded as the scientific analysis of human will (or, more exactly, desire), together vdth a reconstruction of the metaphysical world through moral feeling. Kant, indeed, contended that there were only three psychological faculties : understanding, volition, and feeling. Understanding contains its own principles and those of the other two. Considered with regard to its own principles, it is ' Pure Eeason ; ' considered with regard to volition, it is 'Practical Eeason;' considered with regard to the feeling of pleasure and pain, it is ' Judgment.' Now, Kant contends that there is a sentiment of morahty inborn in us, and he calls it, in opposition to all conditional morality, the ' categoric impera- tive,' which orders us to act so or so. We have it, he contends, without and before experience, and it tells us what is right and wrong independently of kant's moral philosophy. 205 all tlie dictates of a given social law in a given j)eriod or nation. Liberty consists in our obeying this inner law. He had himself stated that this is an idea which cannot be proved, that for reason liberty does not and cannot exist ; but it exists, he now urges, for feeling ; and as he had shown in his ' Pure Reason ' that behind this experimental and phenomenal world there might be a different world superior to, or rather exterior to, the laws of our understanding and senses, so this undoubted feeling of a moral law within us proves that this possible higher world really exists. This is the raonstrum, to use Schopenhauer's words, to which Kant found his way : ' a theoretical doctrine ' which is theoretically indefensible, and which has only practical value ! From this postulate, then, Kant reconstructs the immortality of the soul, as the necessary con- dition for realising our inborn ideal of virtue, and the personal Deity as being a consequence of our inborn desire of happiness ; in other words, the very things which in his ' Pure Eeason ' he had proved to be unprovable. ' We can imagine,' he then said of the Deity plausibly enough, ' an intelligence which, not being discursive like ours, but intuitive, might go from the general to the 206 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLER. particular . . . ; ' but for its, men, there is no knowledge except tlirougli the combination of sensation with the forms and categories of the intelligence. There is no faculty within us to create anything without materials furnished by the senses. Consequently the particiilars furnished by the senses on one side, and the unity which we impart to them by our combining intellect on the other side, would remain independent of each other. If they correspond, it might be mere chance ; it is only by supposing a divine mind really intuitive that this casual, accidental cor- respondence would become a necessary identity. But this, he surmises (and with him all thinkers who wish to remain within the limits assigned by Kant himself to human intelligence), would always remain an hypothesis. Now, in his ' Practical Eeason,' this hypothesis suddenly becomes a reality, through the inner sense of the moral law. Once more, in his third great work, to which we shall revert by and by, in the ' Critic of Judgment,' Kant destroys the old onto- logical, cosmological, and physico-theological proofs of the existence of a personal God, only to admit the moral proof — not before the tribunal of Reason, of course, but on the eant's moral philosophy. 207 ground of sentiment, and before that of practical necessity. Kant's whole religion, however, is always founded upon the moral law alone, not upon reason and argument like that of the rationalists and Deists ; still less upon individual revelation, like that of the mystics and pietists ; least of all on the Bible or tradition, like that of the orthodox and theologians. Men xoill not understand (he says) that when they fulfil their duties to men, they fulfil thereby God's com- mandments ; that they are consequently always in the service of God, as long as their actions are moral, and that it is absolutely impossible to serve God otherwise. And again : As everybody likes to be honoured, so people imagine that God also wants to be honoured. They forget that the fulfilment of duty towards men is the only honour adequate to him. Thus is formed the conception of a re- ligion of worship, instead of a merely moral religion. . . . Apart from moral conduct, all that man thinks himself able to do in order to become acceptable to God is mere superstition and religious folly. If once a man has come to the idea of a service which is not purely moral, but is supposed to be agreeable to God himself, or capable of propitiating him, there is little difference between the several ways of serving him. For all these ways are of 208 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLER. equal value. . . . Whether the devotee accomplishes his statutory walk to the church, or whether he undertakes a pilgrimage to the sanctuaries of Loretto and Palestine, whether he repeats his prayer-formulas with his lips, or like the Tibetan, uses a prayer-wheel ... is quite indifferent. As the illusion of thinking that a man can justify himself before God in any way by acts of worship is religious superstition, so the illusion that he can obtain this justification by the so-called intercourse with God is religious mysticism {Schwdrmerei). Such super- stition leads inevitably to sacerdotahsm [Pfaffenthum) which will always be found where the essence is sought not in principles of morality, but in statutory command- ments, rules of faith and observances. The last consequence of Kant's principle is that religion should be .... successively freed from all statutes based on history, and one purely moral religion rule over all, in order that God might be all in all. The veil must fall. The leading- string of sacred tradition with all its appendices . . . becomes by degrees useless, and at last a fetter . . . The humiliating difference between laymen and clergymen must disappear, and equality spring from true hberty. All this, however, must not be expected fi'om an exterior revolution, wloich acts violently, and depends upon fortune. In the principle of pure moral religion, which is a sort of divine revelation constantly taking place in the soul of man, must be sought the ground for a passage to the new order of things, which will be accomplished by slow and successive reforms. eaxt's political views. 209 And as in religion so in the State ; with the dif- ference that he not only wanted to break with all tradition, but wished also to see the new Kant's State founded on purely rational prin- political views. ciples. Hence his enthusiasm for the North-American Eepublic and for the French Revolution, in spite of his previous conviction that ' a revolution might bring about the downfall of personal despotism and avaricious oppression, but never a true reform . . . for new prejudices would serve as well as the old for leading-strings for the thoughtless mass' (1785). When, in 1792, the Republic was proclaimed, he said with tears in his eyes : ' Now, I can say like Simeon, Lord, now lettest Thou Thy servant depart in peace, for mine eyes have seen Thy salvation.' He was somewhat shaken by the death of Louis XVL, some months later, and wrote once more (1798) against the right of rebellion ; but soon after the reign of terror was over, and even during the Directory, when everybody turned away in disgust, he remained faithful to his belief, that the French Revolution was the dawn of a new day for mankind, the first great attempt to found a State on reason alone. We must not allow ourselves to be misled by his polemic against Rousseau's ' Contrat social.' p 210 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLEE. Here, as in his metaphysics, he drew the distinc- tion between theoretical and practical truth, contending that in fact there was nothing like a contract, either between all the members of a nation, or between the citizens and the king. His political views remained nevertheless in their essence those of the constitution-mongers of the century, from Montesquieu to Hamilton. In this he remained isolated in Germany. The incredible and universal enthusiasm which the Eevolution had excited there gave way to very different feel- ings after the execution of the King; and even the principle of a rational constitution was soon abandoned for the more congenial idea of pro- gress through a reform of the traditional institu- tions. It was Burke, the English Herder, who became the prophet of the rising generation in Germany. Not so with Kant's religious and moral ideas. The former found a most eloquent interpreter in Schleiermacher, and it was, I might say, the national religion during almost haK a century. The moral principle, on which Kant based his religion, j^g„(^,g made, indeed, an immediate impression in lu uence. gpj^g ^f ^^g almost Superhuman severity. When Kant proclaimed this stem idea of inexor- kant's influence. 211 able duty, tlie German world was practically and tlieoretically worslLipping- selfishness, be it under tlie form of indulgence to caprice, or under that of meek sentimentality, while Courts vied with literary circles in * genial ' license. Kant's was a morality not of passion or disposition, but of firm principles and severe commandments. Love and affection are in his eyes no more moral motives than utility and ambition. The one motive is : ' thou shalt ' ; fulfilment of duty for duty's sake, respect for the unbendiDg moral law. When he preached absolute political liberty, equality, and self-government, the German nation still lived under the most arbitrary despotism of three hun- dred absolute rulers ; it was divided into narrow castes, and no public life existed. When he called for a peaceful federation of all civilised nations, (1795) a war which seemed destined never to end was still raging almost throughout Europe. It was, perhaps, this contrast of his ideas with the suiTounding world which gave them such power over men's minds. There can be no doubt that the generation of Stein and Scharnhorst, of Fichte and Arndt, was fed and inspired with Kant's moral views, that they obeyed his ' categoric imperative,' when they withstood violence and injustice, when p 2 212 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLER. they chose exile and privation rather than wrong their conscience, when the j rose at last against the foreign oppressor, but only after having given to their own countrymen liberty, equality and, as far as the times would allow, self-government. You all know that Stein abolished the last remnants of serfdom, made the soil free, and gave the cities their autonomy, whilst Scharnhorst introduced that palladium of our revived nation, equal military service for every citizen whether rich or poor, nobleman or peasant, and created that army, which, even should it ever become superfluous for the defence of national independence, should it ever cost us twice as much as it does, will be maintained as that national high school of unselfishness, reverence, manliness, and true idealism which it has been for the last seventy years, in the silent times of universal peace, still more than in the stirring moments of glorious warfare. ' » In general, there is a good deal of exaggeration in the way the English Press speaks of the financial burdens onr army imposes upon us. The sum total of the German taxation, direct and indirect, amounts to 15«. 2d. per head, whereas that of England is not less than 21. Os. Sd. Germany spends 17|-. millions annually for mihtary purposes on a total budget of 84 millions, i.e. about one lifth ; Great Britain spends 32| millions on a total budget of 128 millions, i.e. about one fourth. kant's influence. 213 Still, I must be allowed to say tliat Want's moral creed was no more the German one tlian his political credo. Even the men of whom I jnst spoke were obliged practically to bend its rigid rules and to adapt them to the exigencies of circumstance and of character. No, the idea of free will is no more a German idea than radicalism or rationalism. The pretension of basing morality on the conception of duty alone, and without taking into account either the inborn nobility or meanness of character or pity and emotion is no more German than is the attempt to create religion and State, without and in contra- diction to the given historical circumstances and traditions, according to reason and by means of a conscious will. These are no German ideas, and, as I am addressing an English audience, I may say they are not Teutonic ideas. Our culture — yours still more than ours — has been strongly, and on the whole healthily, influenced by Pelagianism and rationalism; still, at the root it has remained faithful to Augustinianism as to the belief in the unconsciously working powers of history and nature, and in the rights of these powers. A true Teutonic mind will certainly never admit that his- tory is only a long series of unmeaning accidents ; but still less will it admit that the traditional 214 GOETHE, KANT, AXD SCHILLEE. state which we have inherited from our fore- fathers is only a heap of abuses and absurdities wil- fully introduced, and to be done away with entirely in order to make room for constitutions, framed by abstract reason and for abstract men. It will never admit that religion is only an imposture of priests and a tissue of superstitions, to be replaced by an enlightened system of morality, and that the poor in spirit should be denied the right to satisfy his craving for an ideal by giving to this, his ideal, a palpable, or at least a sentimental form. It will never admit that morality is to be sought only in obedience to the commandment of duty, that such a thing as life for high dis- interested pursuits, like science and art, such a thing as generous and even unwise impulse, such a thing as pity, above all, and instinctive self-sacrifice, should not constitute morality as well as the obedience to duty. It will never admit that men are free and equal morally. When, at the great revolt of the Teutonic spirit against the Latin, which we call the Eeformation, Luther placed faith above works and claimed the privilege of salvation for the elect, was he not ex- pressing in his language the same thought which, two centuries later, was put into words by the SCHILLER. 215 second great Teutonic rebel against the Latin spirit, Herder, when he said that the man living in the ideal could not be immoral ; or by his disciple malgre lui, Fr. Schlegel, when he spoke of the moral aristocracy of ' noble natures ' {Edel- gehornen) ; or by Schleiermacher, when he gave a new form to the doctrine of St. Augustin ? Did he not give the form of his time, i.e. the theo- logical, to the fundamental conception of a Shake- speare, a Fielding, and a Goethe, when they showed us their Prince Hal, their Tom Jones, their Egmont, as noble, sympathetic, and elect natures, in spite of their freaks, their follies, and their sins ? Besides, it was not Herder alone who remon- strated against Kant's ideas of morality, gehiiier, b. politics, and religion, as against his whole ' way of analysing what in nature is united. Schiller himself, Kant's greatest disciple, has lent to his ' Wallenstein ' the finest words in which ever the true Teutonic idea, from Luther down to Schopen- hauer, the negation of absolute free will, was formulated : Hab' ich des Menschen Kern erst untersucht, So kenn' ich auch sein WoUen und sein Handeln, &c. Schiller, it is true, does not speak these words in 216 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLER. liis own name ; be puts tliem into tlie moutli of Ms fatalistic hero. Nay, lie always insists upon freedom as the distinctive quality of man in oppo- sition to necessity, which is the law of nature ; but he always means by it the co-operation of intellectual and moral motives in the formation of our actions, not the absolute rule of those motives. In this, as in all the rest, he extenuated the rigidity of Kant's doctrines, and largely modified at last what he had taken from Kant. Was it not Schiller himself who wrote the famous epigram against Kant's categoric imperative ? Willingly I serve my friends ; unfortunately I do it with pleasure, and so I am often angry with myself for not being virtuous. There is only one remedy : try to despise your fi-iends, and then do with horror what duty commands. Already before studying Kant's great works, Schiller had arrived at the same conclusions as Kant with regard to history. Starting from Eousseau, as Herder, and Kant himself in his earlier works, had done, he had contended that the state of nature, so much vaunted by Jean Jacques, was reconcilable with civilisation, pro- vided this civilisation was a simple one like that of the Greeks, which, far from stifling natural SCHILLER. 217 spontaneousness as ours does, develops it. The aim of Humanity was to be Nature purified by- culture. Tbe prototype of this renovated and ennobled nature was the Hellenic world. Here you have almost literally Kant's earlier ideas of 1764. Nevertheless, Schiller already goes his own way even here, when he sees in Art the first civilising power which prepares moral and scientific culture, as well as the crowning of all civilisation, the highest development of man. The ideal of mankind, in his eyes, will be attained only when moral and scientific culture is placed again under the principle of beauty, in other words, when life itself becomes again a work of art, as it was in Greece. When, after having put forth this view in 1789, in his great poem, ' The Artists,' he made the acquaintance of Kant's works, Schiller was exceedingly struck and even conquered by them; but soon a reaction took place, and he tried to com- plete and modify Kant's moral doctrine, in order to bring it into harmony with his own artistic pro- pensities and predilections. Kant's condemnation of the senses, his rigid conception of duty, hurt the artistic nature of Schiller, who endeavoured to show that moral beauty, not moral actions, ought 218 GOETHE, KAXT, AND SCHILLEK. to be tlie ideal aim of man, because perfection could oulj be attained wlien duty liad become a second nature to mau. Already, in his restlietic treatises, Schiller had contended against Kant that beauty was not only a subjecti^ sensation, but that it existed objectively in things. As often as an object is, what it is, by itself and for itself, it is beautiful, according to him — an idea already con- tained, however, in Kant's ' teleologic ' or objec- tive judgment, as opposed to the * aesthetic ' or subjective judgment, although Schiller corrected Kant's conception of a higher teleology by that of autonomy. This objective beauty — a most doubtful conception — Schiller called architectural beauty, and he opposed to it the moveable beauty or grace, which belongs only to free beings, and which is the expression of the beautiful soul regu- lating all the movements of the body. Archi- tectural beauty, he says, does honour to the Author of nature, moveable beauty to the possessor, who is at the same time its creator. Now, what is the state of the soul which pro- duces this moveable beauty or grace '? It cannot be the absolute empire of reason over the senses, because the liberty of natm-e is impaired thereby ; it cannot be the absolute rule of the senses, which SCHILLER. 219 are always tinder the yoke of necessity. Hence, beauty of soul exists, wlien both come to a kind of mixed constitution and compromise, in which reason and sense, duty and inclination, coincide. Man is designed not for the performance of par- ticular moral actions, but to be a moral being. His perfection lies not in virtues, but virtue; and virtue is only inclination for duty. ' We call a soul beautiful, when the moral feeling: has become so thoroughly master of all the sensations of man that he can without fear abandon to impulse the direction of the will.' Thence, in a beautiful soul, it is not the particular actions which are moral ; the whole character is moral. This, you see, is a reconciliation of the Herderian and Kantian ideas by the evocation of the Hellenic ideal ; it is the serene KaloTcagathia of the Greeks, not Kant's rigid law of the categoric imperative, which treats the senses like slaves. This ideal of the beautiful soul, however, is practically almost unattainable. There are mo- ments when the assaults of the senses must be conquered ; and these moments will be the test whether the moral beauty is really an acquired possession which will resist, or only an inborn dis- position to kindness and a goodness of tempera- 220 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLEE. ment wliicli will give way. If it is the former, tlie victory will be dignity, wliicli is not the opposition, but the completion of grace ; for ' grace lies in the freedom of our voluntary movements, dignity in the rule over involuntary movements.' I need scarcely say that I am here simply stating the ideas of the great German thinkers and poets. I do not discuss them. I also adopt their terminology, even when it seems to me objectionable, as that of Schiller when he uses the words dignity, grace, beauty. The means, according to Schiller, to acquire beauty of soul, are art and science, because they are the only things in which our personal interest does not come into question, and in which con- sequently we are, philosophically speaking, really free. The contemplation of nature and its forms, and the study thereof, without a wish to possess, utilise, or enjoy the objects of such contemplation or study for our personal advantage, constitute art and science. The ideal of a human society would in con- sequence be a sort of aesthetic community, which Schiller, however, was quite resigned not to see ever realised, except in some select sphere. Nevertheless, he thinks that the example of Greece shows that the thing is possible. Whilst with us SCHILLEE. 221 there is nothing but barbarism on one side, cor- ruption on the other, and a division of labour everywhere, with the Greeks there was nature and culture ; their work was not divided, nor were their souls. Thucydides was, at the same time, a philosopher, a physician, an admiral, a statesman, and an historian ; and Xenophon, the naturalist, showed himself a great general when circumstances required it. Something analogous must be done for the modem world. All political amendment, however, must proceed from an amendment of character. For this we want an instrument inde- pendent of the State, an instrument which the general corruption will not touch ; and this instru- ment is art. Each of us must, somewhat in the spirit of Goethe's Wilhelm Meister, try to educate himself, to make of himself a beautiful soul, to develop all the germs of his individuality to an harmonious unity. Thus Schiller, by the philo- sophical way, reaches the same goal which Herder had reached by the study of history, and Goethe by the study of nature — I mean, the ideal of human- ism. The completion of Schiller's ideas his friend, W. von Humboldt, gave in his strange book on the ' Limits of the Action of the State,' which reads like a chapter of J. S. Mill's 'Essay on 222 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLER. Liberty ' from an idealistic, instead of from an utilitarian, point of view : for W. von Humboldt vrants to see the power and interference of tlie State limited to tlie utmost, only in order that the freest and most harmonious development of individuality ma-y not be impeded. Thus the emancipative tendencies of the cen- tury, which elsewhere had led to the democratic conclusion of the superior rights of individual reason over collective wisdom as represented by tradition, of common sense over genius, and thence to affirming the equal value of all individuals, led in Germany to the aristocratic view of the recognition of superior individualities and their rights, and thence to considering the education of these individualities (not the satisfaction of the interests, passions, and wishes of the greater number) as the means and aim of civilisation. It is but natural that the former view should favour the development of utilitarianism and of positive science, and that the latter should generate the artistic and the historical treatment of things. There is no doubt that Schiller definitively determined the province of art, when he said that it consisted not in dreaming of an unreal, fantastic world, but in discerning the ideal in the real world, SCHILLER. 223 in seeing in the accidental tlie manifestation of the eternal. The question is whether he and his time were right in seeing the dignity of man preserved in art alone, because in art alone man was free and active, his own master, and yet working npon the outer world. A second and secondary question is whether they did not en- tirely misunderstand Greece, where State and City formed the basis of the whole national existence and by no means only a disagreeable necessity. Finally, there is always the Mephistophelian objection : what, if you had seen Greece near ? would you not have found things somewhat differ- ent from what they seem to you in the haze of distance ? One thing, however, is certain : the standpoint of Schiller remained that of the whole age in its greatest representatives. The weak side of it is obvious ; and cruel reality stirred up Germany, proving to her harshly enough that the much despised State was the necessary ground upon which alone man could devote himself with dignity and security to his sesthetic perfection. Things have been reversed since then in Germany. The idea of the State, so utterly obliterated in Schiller's time, has become exceed- ingly active and poweriul ; and the nation is eager 224 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLER. to sacrifice everytliing to it. Scliiller's idea is not extinct for all that. As long as the national State, the lack of which had been so painfully- Present views on felt in the moment of need, is being con- State. , , * . structed, it is natural that the nation should show a certain onesidedness and exclusive- ness in this direction. For the time being, indi- vidualism, as preached by the great pathfinders of German culture, seems almost vanished. The nation in which Madame de Stael did not find two minds thinking alike on any subject, has become singularly gregarious, nay, uniform ; the great producer and consumer of original ideas is content nowadays to feed on some few watchwords mechanically repeated. Individualism indeed, humanism, absence of prejudice and of social con- ventionality, when pushed so far as they were by the generation of Schiller and Goethe, are absolute hindrances to public life, which subsists only by the sacrifice of individual interests and convic- tions to party principles or national interests. A nation, or a class, or a party in a nation, is irre- sistible only when it has a whole set of common thoughts, interests, feelings, and forms. As long as each unit goes its own way, nation, class, party exist only in words, and cannot resist the slightest PRESENT VIEWS ON STATE. 225 shock. Modern German history proves it on every page. And not only has individualism made room for uniformity, humanism for patriotism, but Schiller's conception itself that art was the highest form of human activity, that accidental practical life must be subordinated to a higher ideal life, has, as it were, disappeared, for the time being at least. For I feel confident that, as soon as the long- yeamed-for national State is complete and insured against inner and outer enemies, Germany will come back to the creed of the real founders of her civilisation. But she will only accept it with quali- fications. She will never again profess that un- spoken contempt for the State, which lay at the root of all the thought of Schiller's generation ; but neither will she any longer see in the State an end, as she does now, instead of a means, a necessary means, a noble means even, but a means, nevertheless, not an end. It seems im- possible, indeed, that the nation of Lessing and Herder, Goethe and Kant, should not weary of politics as she wearied, long ago, of theology, and, leaving politics to the politicians as she left theo- logy to the theologians, should not set to work Q 226 GOETHE, KANT, AND SCHILLEE. again at the ideal content of life, instead of at tlie containing forms. There is no contradiction in this, as might at first sight appear. If there are domains of human activity, where absolute individualism is an evil, and a sign of selfishness, there are others where it is as fertile as it is noble. And so it is with collectivism, if I may use that term. A blessing in one department of life, it is a curse in the other. But is it really impossible to confine each of them within limits which will render it salutary? The Germany of 1800 knew only indi- vidualism ; the Germany of 1879 seems to know only collectivism. The Germany of the future, let us hope, will submit to collectivism, and will be ready to sacrifice individual thought and feeling where it is necessary to do so, i.e. in State and society. She will claim full liberty of personal thought and feeling, where individualism alone i^an bear fruit, i.e. in art and science; and in doino- so she will feel that she has chosen the better part : for he, who tries to penetrate the world — humanity and nature — and to interpret it faithfully and lovingly, be it by the artist's intui- tion and second creation, be it by the intellect and learning of the scholar, has chosen a higher PEESENT VIEWS ON STATE. t227 activity than the man who lives only in and for the State and its passing interests. We shall see, however, in the next and last of these lectures, how the contrary conviction was brought about in Germany, and what is its justifi- cation. 228 LECTURE VI. THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL. 1800-1825. We have seen that the great task of giving to Germany the foundations of a new and national culture fell to three generations, that of Winckel- mann, Kant, and Lessing ; that of Herder, Goethe, and Schiller ; that of the two Schlegels and the two Humboldts, which was also that of Hardenberg and Tieck, of Eahel and Gentz, of Schelling and Hegel, of Arndt and Kleist, of Schleiermacher and Holderlin, not to speak of many other less cele- brated writers and thinkers who were all bom towards the year 1770. It is of this generation, whose principal works were published from 1800 to 1815, that I have to speak to you to-day. My remarks must be, if possible, of a character still more summary and, I am afraid, more superficial than those I have presented to you thus far, as THE STAETING-POINT. 229 this is our last meeting, and I wisli also to notice rapidly, as in an epilogue, tlie different currents of thought which have agitated Germany during the quarter of a century succeeding the palmy days of the romantic school, which forms the main subject of the present lecture. The romanticists were by no means from the first day such as they appear to us now, and such as they will figure for ever in the history of rpj^g g^^^^. thought. They also, like the two preced- '""S-pomt. ing generations, fought their battle on the literary field, the only one then open to Germany ; and they began only later to act upon the public life of their country. When they first began to attract attention, they gave themselves out as staunch admirers of Goethe, and adhered strictly to Schiller's principles. It was only in their second phase of development that they turned round against the reigning classicism. Two things are necessary for the poet and artist (says Schiller) ; he must rise above reality, and he must remain within the sensuous. Where both those exigencies are fulfilled equally, there is aesthetic art. But in an un- favourable and shapeless nature (and society), he too easily abandons the sensuous along with the real, and be- comes idealistic, and, if his understanding be feeble, even 230 THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL. fantastic ; or when he wishes, and is obliged by his nature, to remain in the sensuous, he obstinately cHngs to the real, and becomes realistic in the narrow sense of the word, and even servile and vulgar if he wholly lacks imagination. In both cases he is not aesthetic. These golden words, whicli the artist and poet can never meditate upon sufficiently, or keep too steadily before his mind, found a notable commen- tary in the German literature of the time. Whilst Goethe and Schiller were on the limit, and often even overstepped the limit, which separates artistic truth — or what they called sesthetic beauty — from abstract idealism, there were many writers who were pleased to dwell within the most vulgar, everyday reality, because they were either afraid or unable to rise into ideal regions. And these writers had a far more numerous public than our classics. The Ifflands, Schroders, Kotzebues, Aug. Lafontaines, and others were in possession of the stage, and made the fortune of the circulating libraries. The prosiest philistine-life became the object of literature, and the inartistic forms of this life were reproduced in poetry, if not yet by plastic art. Schiller and Goethe declared pitiless war against this vulgarity ; and it was no wonder if they exaggerated on their side, not only by the BATTLE WITH THE REALISTS. 231 occasional misuse of tlie weapon of satire, but also bj the example of their works. In tbe beginning of their classical period, which is that of their maturity, they had still taken their subjects and their inspiration from real life and national history. * Hermann and Dorothea ' and ' Wallenstein * -are in the highest degree what Schiller required works of art to be, 'within the limits of the sensuous, but raised above accidental reality.' So in spite of the foreign costume were ' Tasso ' and *Iphigenia,' 'Egmont' and the ' Eoman Elegies.' They showed reality, i.e. concrete feelings and passions, personages and situations, reduced to their eternal, artistic element, and thereby interpreted reality by art. More than this, ' Wilhelm Meister ' had shown that the task of life, the task of the time particularly in which Goethe lived, was to recognise the rights of reality, and to reconcile idealism with this reality. When once the battle had begun against the vulgar realists, who thought a button-hole an object as worthy of art as a human face, and a wart on that face as important as the lines of the forehead, Goethe and Schiller were led to the same extreme to which the Fine Arts had already been drifting. In their horror of prosy reality they fled into the 232 THE EOMANTIC SCHOOL. classic world of antiquity and even into abstract idealism ; and just as Carstens and David looked for ideal types, and thought to find them in the art of the ancients alone, so they began to give classic names and forms to mental abstractions, turned the old gods which Herder had shown to be living mythical individualities once more into lifeless symbols of general concejptions, and fell again into full allegory. If they were not entirely lost in it, it was because the ideas they allegorised were of real depth, and because their artistic genius was so powerful that even allegory lost something of its inanimate coldness under their hands. ' Pandora ' and ' Paleophron and Euterpe ' are still read, in spite, not because, of the sesthetic theory which was godmother to them. The pre- text for thus abandoning the ' sensuous ' was not even plausible. The German life of their time, they said, offered no fit objects for poetry. ' Her- mann and Dorothea ' is the most eloquent refuta- tion of that paradox, if it wanted refutation. Men's costume may sometimes be inartistic ; their body and soul is never entirely devoid of interest for the artist, although it may offer to him a more or less fertile object. The young romanticists went a step further VIEWS OF SCHILLER AND GOETHE. 233 still than Schiller and Goethe, who had become — for the time being, at least — one-sided idealists; ' they became dreamers because their understand- ing was feeble.' Goethe and Schiller, indeed, even when they went so far as to seek their subjects beyond the bounds of reality, in abstract thought or a so-called ideal world, at least treated them with the wisdom of artistic understanding and in an objective way. Their young disciples and allies deemed their caprice and inspiration sufficient guides, and treated their imaginary themes in a quite subjective manner. So, strangely enough, it came to pass that they took from Goethe and Schiller just the shortcomings of their youthful as well as of their mature age, and disdained the superior qualities which distinguished them in both periods. In their youth the two great poets had sought in reality and personal experience the materials of their poetry, treating them, however, with a ' subjectivity ' which did not recognise the authority of artistic understanding as the regulat- ing power. Fifteen years later they came to the conviction that no great work of art can be pro- duced without that regulating power, but, disgusted with the realistic literature of the time, they sought their objects outside reality. In this the young 234 THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL. romanticists followed them, but remained in the other respect at the point where their masters had been in the ' Sturm- und Drangperiode ' ; they recognised no right of control by the under- standing. The only controlling power they ad- mitted was irony, i.e. reason, liovering over and smiling at the work done by unfettered fancy. The consequence was that they, without the guidance of artistic understanding, soon went still farther astray than their models, and not only fled from the surrounding reality, like Goethe and Schiller, but from all reality, into the world of mere imasrination. Even to such creations, how- ever, they did not know how to give plastic, sen- suous, palpable form ; all remains musical, lyrical, vague, subjective, like their inspiration. They pride themselves on this personal character of both object and form in their poetry. They transferred to art the philosophic system of Fichte, for whom the whole universe was only the production of the Ego ; and the one activity of this Ego, which they recognised as the supreme, was Imagination, fantasy. They soon felt the complete contra- diction between themselves and the classical Hellenic world, evoked by Schiller and Goethe, and opposed to it the world of the middle ages, whose THE MEDIEVALISTS. 235 chiaroscuro is infinitely more favourable to their dreamy, fantastic art ; and they ended with trying practically to restore the middle ages in order to get a poetical reality. The apostles of unlimited personal liberty in art and life became the mis- sionaries of a religious and political conservatism, which would erase from history three centuries of progressive enlightenment, because the preachers of such conservatism feel more comfortable in the dark than in daylight. German romanticism, you see, is totally differ- ent from that which the French have since called by this name, and which bears infinitely Definition more resemblance to the principles of of roman- ticism. the German ' Sturm- und Drangperiode,' viz., the emancipation from all aesthetic rules. For the French, for instance, Shakespeare's ' Corio- lanus ' would be a romantic drama, Corneille's ' Cid ' a classical one. It is just the reverse with the Germans. The form of the ' Cid,' of ' Poly- eucte,'maybe classical, the inspiration is modern, i.e. subjective, and the process of creation is modern, i.e. conscious. The form of ' Julius Csesar ' ' may be ever so different from Sophocles,* the inspiration is objective, the process of creation navf, as with the ancients. Now German roman- 236 THE EOMANTIC SCHOOL. ticisni was, above all, a reaction in favour of imagination and faith against the enlightenment and rationalism of the preceding age, but also a reaction in favour of Christianity and the middle ages against the Hellenic heathendom of the end of the century. The theorist of the school, the younger Schlegel, defined it in these words : Romanticism rests solely on Christianity and the feel- ing of charity and love which, thanks to this religion, reigns also in poetry. In this feeling, suffering itself appears as a means of glorification and transfiguration. The traditions of the Greek, Germanic, and Scandmavian mythology become in it graceful and serene plays of the imagination. Even among the external forms of style and language, the romantic poet chooses those which answer best to this intimate feeUng of love, and those plays of the imagination. Love then, sentimental love, fancy, faith, chivalry, honour, were to be the inspiration of romantic poetry. And as unity reigned in the middle ages, so it was to reign again, unity between head and heart, between poetry, life, philosophy and religion. 'Romanticism,' said Fred. Schlegel, *is the aspiration after an in- finite poem, which includes the germs of all other poems.' And young Novalis : ' Should the funda- DEFINITION OF ROMANTICISM. 237 mental laws of imagination really be in opposi- tion to those of logic ? ' And out-Herdering Herder : * Poetical sentiment has something akin to the sense of divination, to religious sense, even to madness.' Again, poetry was to be philosophy without ceasing to be religion for these mystical minds. Philosophy is the hero of poetry (said NovaHs). It elevates poetry, and shows that it is all in all. . . . The separation of poet and philosopher is only apparent and injures both; it is the symptom of an illness or of a sickly constitution. All ought to centre in the philo- sopher who is always omniscient, who is the real world in nuce. But not philosophy alone, all existence was to be poetry. Life was to become again poetical, as they imagined it to have been in the dark ages, and poetry was to be lived : both poetry and life under the guidance of religion — not of stern, prosaic, Protestant, but of warm, coloured, sen- suous, Catholic religion. Thus they overthrew all limits, not only those which the strong artistic sense of the ancients had drawn between epic, dramatic, and lyrica poetry, those which Lessing had laboriously erected between plastic art and poetry, those which Kan 238 THE ItOMANTIC SCHOOL. had sagaciously traced between theoretical and practical knowledge, but also the limits between prose and verse, art and life, morality and intellect, science and religion, imagination and understand- ing. It was the exaggeration, or rather the caricature, of Herder's profound principle of unity — unity and simultaneousness of individual forces in individual action, of national forces in national action, of human forces in the pursuit of human aims. Herder had remonstrated against division of labour, but only in the sense that a general basis was required for every special work, that individual, nation, humanity must be entirely absorbed in the special work in which they are enofa^ed. For the romanticists there was no longer any special work : State, Religion, Science, Poetry were all one in their eyes. This came in fact to a denial of all civilisation, whose very action is specialisation, not indeed of the subjec- tive forces acting, but of the objective mass which it is its task to master. No wonder if they saw their ideal in the dark ages. Where indeed could they find such unity, poetical life and ' lived ' poetry, political religion and religious politics, as in the middle ages ? Novalis went so far as to declare it a misfortune DEFINITION OF ROMANTICISM. - 239 that the Papacy should no longer have the power to stop such dangerous theories as those of Coper- nicus, which made mankind believe itself no longer the centre and aim of creation. ' The spirit of all art and sciences,' said Fred. Schlegel, ' must again be united in one centre, similar to that which humanity has lost since the middle ages and to the restoration of which it must aspire.' In the words of his more sober brother, A. William : Europe was one in those gi-eat times. One chivalry made friends of all warriors. All vied in fighting for one faith. Hearts were open to one love. Then also poetry arose, one in feeling, although different in lan- guage. Now the power of the olden times is gone, and we dare to speak of them as barbarous ! People have invented for themselves a narrow wisdom, and what, in their impotence, they do not understand, they call di-eams ; but nothing which is of a divine nature can thrive any longer in a time when work is done by unholy hands. Alas ! This age has neither Faith nor Charity ; how should it have retained Hope 1 Hence also their antipathy for the Hellenic world where all is clearness, light and health. They had begun with masterly studies on Greek poetry, in F. A. Wolfs sense ; had shown great admiration for Goethe ; had developed Schiller's 240 THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL. theories on sentimental poetry ; but in proportion as they formulated their own principles more distinctly, they turned against Greek classicism, as Goethe and Schiller understood it. In their yearning for twilight, they turned away from a period when that longed-for unity of life and poetry was realised in full sunshine, and under the control of healthy reason. How much more congenial to them were the dark ages in which they saw the reign of uncontrolled fantasy, the outward realisation of their own inner life ! If only they could restore that time, would they not become the Dantes and Wolframs of their time, as Goethe and Schiller were the Homers and Sophocles of theirs ? Now, it was particularly the religion of the Middle Ages which they con- sidered the one higher region, in which all classes, all cultures and all nations might meet again. 'Art and religion were synonymous ' in Z. Werner's eyes, as poetry and science in Hardenberg's. *They made piety,* Goethe says, ' the one foundation of art, because some monks had been artists, and consequently all artists ought to be monks ; ' and elsewhere he compares them to * children, who, to imitate a bell, fasten a rope to a tree and sing ding-dong, whilst they are moving it.' A NEW MYTHOLOGY. 241 To give new life, then, to this bleak, rational- istic age, the spark of imagination was to be rekindled. Fancy was to become once ^ j^^^ more the queen of the world, as they Mythology, imagined she had been in the Middle Ages ; and this sullen, bleak atmosphere was to shine once more in rich colours and in varied forms. What was wanting in modern religion as in modern poetry was a mythology. A mythology then was to be created anew out of all the frasfments of pagan and German myths, Indian and Christian legends blent together ; the elves and nixes, who dwelt in the forests and on the rivers, the dwarfs and kobolds who peopled the mediaeval world, were evoked anew. The fairy tale was to become the highest form of poetical production, as it was at once the most simple, and the most composite — the most simple because it was created by childlike minds for children ; the most composite, as in it lay united as in a germ, religion and imagination, poetry and thought, wisdom and folly, legend and history, in that unity in which they presented themselves to primitive minds. Even so with the great geniuses of the Christian era. ' Shake- speare's and Calderon's artistic confusion, the delightful harmony of contradictions, the wonder- B 242 THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL. ful alternations of enthusiasm and irony, which show themselves in the smallest fragment, seem a new peculiar kind of mythology ; for the beginning of all poetry is to suspend the processes and laws of speculative reason, and to take us back into the beautiful confusion of imagination, into the primi- tive chaos of nature.' Heine, a romanticist himself in his earlier days, to whom it was given to realise in his poems, if not in his life, the poetical ideal which lay at the root of all the aspirations and vague definitions of the romanticists, has wonderfully satirised this mixed mythology and poetical chaos of irony and enthusiasm, of fancy and wit, in his ' Atta Troll,' and in what I cannot help considering his finest work, ' the Exiled Gods.' Yon will not wonder when I say that this apotheosis of imagination, ' Jupiter's spoiled child,' as the higliest intellectual power, degenerated naturally into a species of mysticism. They were for ever seeking after the ' blue flower,' like Heinrich von Ofterdingen, the hero of Hardenberg's novel, the ' Wilhelm Meister ' of the school. ' What there is highest in the world,' Fred. Schlegel would say, ' can be told only in sym- bols, precisely because it is unspeakable.' And CHARACTER OF THE ROMANTICISTS. 243 Novalis (Hardenberg), alluding to his beloved Middle Ages as the golden age of mankind, says : It had then become quite a natural thing to consider the most ordinary and the nearest things as miraculous, and what was strange and supernatural as ordinary. In this way daily life itself surrounded man like a wonderful fairy tale, and that region which most men do but guess at — or question — as a distant incomprehensible thing, became his home. It seemed unnatiu-al that the poets should form a separate class of men. To be a poet was in their eyes the proper activity of the human mind. Nor otherwise Gorres, the tribune of the party, when he speaks of the dark ages : ' Faith, love, heroism, were then mingled in one large stream. Then it was that the new garden of poetry blos- somed, the Eden of romanticism.' Unfortunately there was no genuine simplicity in all this, no spontaneousness, nor that sort of second sight which illuminated for Character Herder all the darkness of early ages, of the Ro- manticists. It was the studied simplicity of pedants and bookworms, who tried laboriously by the effort of understanding and will to arrive at the simple, but rich, direct and concrete conceptions which intuition revealed spontaneously and easily to the K 2 244 'the eomantic school. original and healthy minds of primitive nations, or to robust and undefiled genius in modern times. Their ^^ ^^ ^^ even with their religion. EeUgion. jjardenberg excepted, they had all been sceptics in their first youth. It is possible that in England the Evangelical movement may have awakened, at least indirectly, what might, in one sense, be called the English romanticism of this century, in other words, the Tractarian movement and what followed. In Grermany it was from the beginning rather in opposition to pietism, than in accordance with it. Schleiermacher himself, who had been brought up in a school of Moravian Brethren, was intellectually emancipated even be- fore he left it. No, Catholicism was to them all only a question of aesthetics, as A. W. Schlegel himself confessed, and as it was in fact also to Chateaubriand. Most of them remained Protest- ants, even after they had denounced Protestantism as the sin against the Holy Ghost. Hardenberg himself, the St. John of the mission, a sickly over- strained nature — Hardenberg who had declared that ' Christianity was finished with the Reform- ation,' who had called Protestantism 'a sacrilegious revolt against Christianity, which exists only in the unity of the visible and universal Church ' — Hard- THEIR RELIGION AND ETHIOS. 245 enberg-Novalis himself, never left, perhaps had not the time to leave, the Lutheran Church in which he was born. True, there were many among them, who, following Fred. Schlegel's and Zacharias Werner's example, actually embraced Catholicism ; but their new religion did not prevent them from enjoying life and its most worldly pleasures just as before. They took from Catholicism only what suited their tastes, its outward plastic forms, its deep historical value, some dogmas which might be interpreted as the symbolical expression of their philosophic convictions, the uncontested authority which it represented ; but they submitted in no wise to what was in the least severe, or even only inconvenient to them in the old faith ; for they ex- hibited a marvellous ingenuity in choosing and appropriating to themselves in every theory, political, religious, philosophical or aesthetic, just what was congenial to their tastes and wants, and in ignoring the rest as if it did not exist. As their religious, so was their poetical and moral attitude. In whatever they do and say there is something voulu and tendu as -pj^gjj. the French would say, and there is no affectation more insupportable than the affectation of simplicity. There was an utter want of healthy 246 THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL. and vigorous sensuousness as well as of natural genius in most of those men who made such a pretence of having strong impulses where there was only a perverted imagination, or, at least, a self-indulgence, which was content to consider every caprice as an unconquerable passion. The doctrines of ' Lucinde,' Fred. Schlegel's youthful novel, a rehabilitation of the flesh and its rights, were commented upon by his friend Schleiermacher, a clergyman, not with Rabelais' or Sterne's jovial sensuousness, which makes us almost forget their ecclesiastical robes, but with a sort of unctuous devotion, as if he spoke of a new religion ; and these doctrines were put into practice during their whole lifetime by such men as Fr. Schlegel, Gentz, and Zacharias Werner, who carried epicurism to a kind of maestria. Divorce was no longer that respectable institution which allows a fetter to fall off, when it has become intolerable, and brings to an end the long expiation of a youth- ful mistake. Divorce in their circle had become an every-day occurrence. There is an actual chassez-croisez among them. Tieck's sister is divorced from her brother's best friend Bernhardi ; Mendelssohn's daughter is divorced from Yeit and marries Fred. Schlegel ; A. W. Schlegel's THEIR ETHICS. 247 wife — tlie most remarkable among the women of the generation after Rahel — Caroline Schlegel, is divorced and marries Schelliug, who is ten years younger than she. There is something unhealthy even in those who do not break deliberately through the barriers of society : Holderlin be- comes an early prey to insanity, through his hopeless passion for the mother of his pupils ; Hardenberg cherishes a sentimiental love for a girl of twelve years, and dies an early death, at the age of twenty-nine, when this child is taken from him ; Schleiermacher has a romantic re- lation with another clergyman's wife, and ends by marrying a third friend's widow, for whom he had entertained an apparently hopeless love ; Kleist commits suicide, together with a not less morbidly excited lady friend ; Tieck, Clemens Brentano, and Hoffmann made hizarrerie a system, and lived according to that system. Their moral indifference itself varied widely from that of a Diderot and his friends. There was a consciousness about it, which deprived it of the only excuse to be pleaded for it. When they contended that ' to have understood a thing was to have justified it;' when they pleaded that * noble creatures pay with what they are, not 248 THE EOMANTIC SCHOOL. with what they do ' ; when they thus brought the doctrines of election and grace into a worldly system which had no other aim than to justify their own loose morals ; when these refined Epicureans of Culture, these impotent dilettanti, who have not produced a single lasting poem, were for ever talking of spontaneousness and imagination and popular simplicity — they were certainly theoreti- cally in the right. But it was plain to everyone that the thing most wanting in them was the one they most recommended and praised, whilst, on the contrary, they most depreciated the faculty they possessed in the highest degree, that of criticism. It was by this faculty nevertheless that they acted principally on their time and on the follow- Their ing generation. For they acted power- action in Germany, fully upou it, not Only in the domain of poetry and art, but also in that of science and politics. It was the romanticists, indeed, who created modern literary history, of which Herder had only Their in- sketched the outlines. They collected Literary" ^^^ popular songs and fairy tales of Old 18 ory. Q^eriiia,ny ; they republished, and com- mented upon, the poems of Wolfram and Gott- ITS INFLUENCE ON LITEEART HISTOEY. 249 fried, the ' Nibelungen ' and the ' Gudrun ; ' and they did it with a delicacy, and a poetical tact, which have been completely lost, since the literary history of the Middle Ages has been treated only from a grammatical point of view. Nor was it only the literary history of the German Middle-Age which the romanticists created; they brought Dante again to honour and with him all the minor medieval poets of the South as well as of their own country. Their translations of the Eenaissance poets, of Shakespeare particularly, of Bojardo, Ariosto, Calderon, Camoens, Cervantes, have, it may be said, made the master- works of the world the property of the German nation. It is their merit if, after such a total change of atmosphere, and when the worship of foreign things, which characterised the old Germany, has long subsided, these masterworks still keep their place on the German stage and in German libraries beside those of Goethe, Schiller, and Lessing. Germany owes to them not only the naturalisation of the poets of all latitudes and times ; but also that of the poetical forms of all nations and periods. It was they who introduced and acclimatised the Italian terzina and canzona, the Spanish redondilla, the Persian gasela, as their predecessors had introduced 250 THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL. and acclimatised in German poetry the hexameter and the alcaic strophe of the Greeks. It was Fr. Schlegel, who first sought and found in India the highest expression of romanticism, i.e. *the deepest and most intimate life of the imagination. When once we are able to draw from the original sources, perhaps the appearance of southern glow, which now attracts us so much in Spanish poetry, will appear to us but pale and occidental.' Then, again, their reaction against the exclu- sive Hellenism of Goethe and Schiller gave impulse to the new poetry of the national and Christian type, of which Uhland has remained and will remain the most charming representative ; to the great national dramas of a Kleist, which after all are the most effective that Germany has produced for the stage, if we except those of Lessing and Schiller; to the patriotic songs of 1813 (the Schenkendorffs and Arndts, Korners and Riic- kerts, all belonged, more or less, to the romantic school) to the new fantastic novel-literature of the Arnims, Brentanos, Hoffmanns, Chamissos, Fouques ; above all, to what there is best and most imperishable in Heine's wonderful productions. I am not giving you here a literary history of Germany ; otherwise I should have to show you the AET. 251 different ramifications of the romantic school; the crroup of the fatalists, that of the patriots, that of the pure fantasts, that of the sentimentalists, who have all retained in German poetrj a place which the preachers of the new Gospel themselves never succeeded in attaining. A similar impulse was given bj the romanticists to architecture and painting. That mediaeval tendency, which still prevailed in these arts in the days of our youth, was their work. France, England, Italy themselves received that impulse from the German romanticists, although they were not quite conscious by what channels it reached them. Bonald had lived in Germany ; B. Constant was as intimate with A. W. Schlegel as Coleridge was with Tieck ; and as the whole atmosphere was pregnant with similar tendencies, as the ground seemed only to wait for the seed in the country of Chateaubriand and in that of Walter Scott, it is natural enough that the slightest germs should bear fruit. The roman- ticists had the merit of freeing the world from Winckelmann's new academical theories, in which Goethe was still entirely wrapt up, of having drawn attention to the beauty of Gothic cathedrals, so de- spised in those days as barbarous monstra, of having 252 THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL. shown the vahie of a Giotto and a Fra Angelico, of having made the first collections of Van Eycks and Memlings, as they were also the first to revive the old Catholic church music. Whatever may have been the shortcomings of that school in Art, it was a necessary reaction against the academical classicism of the school of David and Canova. However false and perilous may have been their views about Art as an instrument for conveying religious or other impressions, the very fact that people began again to appreciate works of art, which were fruits of a simple and genuine study of nature, furthered the interests of modern Art. The revival and exaggeration 6ven of Herder's ideas of unconscious growth in history and their On History application to language, poetry, and law, proper. acted most powerfully and beneficially on the historical, if not on the natural, sciences. The romanticists themselves self-complacently dated a new age from their apostolic mission. ' Several of my friends and I,' said A. W. Schlegel, candidly, ' have proclaimed in all forms, in poetry and prose, seriously and playfully, the beginning of a new era.' And it would be unjust not to confess that there is some truth in this pretension. It was only now and under their care that the HISTORY PEOPEE. 253 .seeds sown by Herder, thirty years before, bore all their fruits. The whole history of medieval literature and language dates from them. The troubadours and the trouveres, the Minnesingers and the Meistersangers, the minstrels and jongleurs, were revived ; more than that, German j»hilology was created by their disciples, the two Grimms. Soon neo- Latin philology was to follow ; nay, even Oriental philology owes its first impulse to Fr. Schlegel's important work on the ' Wisdom of the Hindoos,' as the comparative science of languages was created by one of their generation, if not of their school, W. von Humboldt. But we must go a step further. If their prin- ciple, applied to politics, to philosophy and natural science, has done little more than mischief; if it has led to the monstrous hypotheses of a Schelling and to his arbitrary a priori constructions, uncon- trolled by observation of facts ; if it produced a mysticism which considered Nature as the dark mystery which the senses and understanding could never unveil, and has thus led to Oken's, Schubert's, and Steffens's scientific aberrations — it yet exer- cised an important influence for good in the history of philosophy, religion, legislation, the State, and even in that of science. Not only the Grimms, but 254 THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL. Eicliliorii, Savign J, Niebuhr, Creuzer were personal friends of the romanticists, in the main adherents to their principles, and fed with their ideas. Ton know the revolution effected by Creuzer's ' Sjm- bolik,' and how, in spite of all its extravagances, it created indirectly the science of comparative mythology. You also know the importance of the so-called historical school of Niebuhr and Eichhorn, Otfried Miiller and Bockh, which re- novated history. Even on religion their influence has been, partially at least, a salutary. If they favoured and furthered the Catholic reaction which took place after 1830 in Germany as well as in France, they have also propagated in a whole generation (from 1800 to 1830) the conviction that religion can exist without dogmas, that all inner life, all higher feeling is religion, as Schleiermacher had argued in his ' Discourses ; ' and in propa- gating this wide religion they also pleaded and furthered the cause of real, inner toleration. But their influence was most perceptible and most favourable, after all, in the awakening of national sentiment, of patriotism. In fact, the principle according to which Art and Poetry have their roots in national life, the study of old German history, poetry, and Ian- NATIONAL FEELING. 255 guage at the moment when the deepest humilia- tion was inflicted upon the nation, the lofty humanitarianisrn and idealism of a Herder, q^ National a Goethe, a Schiller, which seemed to have ^^^^^^s- led to the ruin of the German State on the battle- field of Jena, indirectly awakened the national feel- ing, while the persistency with which the roman- ticists dwelt upon the importance of nationality, contributed not a little to the great patriotic effort of the nation in 1813 to free itself from foreign yoke. Nay, that peculiar national pride of a lite- rary and scientific character, which ever since has been proper to Germany, and which ultimately has kindled also the national pride in things political, can be traced to the influence of the Romanticists. With them also began, alas, that sort of methodical reaction in favour of feudal and ecclesiastical institutions, which was caused by their hatred for the radicalism and Jacobinism of the French Eevolution, its spirit of levelling uniformity, its rationalistic spirit. It is remarkable that the German Burke, young Gentz, made, as early as 1796, the first German translation of Burke's ' Eeflections.' Unfortunately they did not stop where the great interpreter of the British Constitution stopped. They wanted to go back 256 THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL. not only beyond 1688, but beyond 1520; nay, further back still, to the glorious time when the holy Roman crown rested on the anointed head of the German Emperor, and his half princely, half sacerdotal sway extended over the whole of middle Europe, when the State was still entirely imbued with an ecclesiastical spirit. The whole movement was, in fact, like that of Herder's times, a reaction against the rationalistic tendency of the eighteenth century, and The Political the romanticists might be called the real executors of Herder's bequest, were it not that Herder contented himself with emanci- pating the mind from rationalistic conventionalism, whereas the romanticists, after having most effec- tually worked in the same direction, wanted to enthral it in the fetters of a worse conventionalism — that of a dead tradition, galvanised by artificial means. Herder strove to awaken the mind by appealing to all its active forces ; the romanticists tried to lull it into a dreamy sleep by mesmerising as it were all those forces. Herder was of opinion that the historical principle consisted in progress ; the romanticists held that it meant retrogression. Herder wished his own time to make history ; the romanticists thought that they could show respect THE POLITICAL REACTION. 257 for history only by stopping its course. This they believed might be done most effectually by preaching the cause of ' throne and altar,' of authority, both secular and spiritual, in writings worthy of J. de Maistre. Almost all of them became instruments of the despotic governments of the Restoration after 1815; many of them, we have seen, were even consistent enough to throw themselves into the arms of Rome, the securest citadel, they thought, against the spirit of ex- amination which had bred revolt and resulted in the overthrow of all the creations of history. 'The spirit of enlightenment,' said A. W. Schlegel, * which has no respect whatever for darkness, is the most decided and most dangerous adversary of poetry.' Now, as poetry was supposed to penetrate the whole life, public and private, the consequence was that enlightenment in the eyes of the romanticists was an enemy to be combated also in the domains of Religion and the State. Hence their strong antipathy for the French Revolution, which Klopstock, Kant, Schiller, and even Herder had saluted as the beginning of a new era. They saw in it nothing but Voltaireanism and the worship of the goddess Reason ; the presumptuous attempt to create mechanically a s 258 THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL. social order according to rationalistic principles ; the negation, in a word, of History. Unfortu- nately their medieval tastes were not so inno- cent as the children's play with the bells spoken of by Goethe. The literary and philosophical ten- dencies of earlier times soon developed into poli- tical and ecclesiastical tendencies. Alexander of Russia was deeply imbued with their ideas when he formed the ' Holy Alliance,' more even against the spirit of the past century than against revolu- tionary France. In Austria and in Italy the governments made themselves the chamj^ions of the Roman Church ; in France ' throne and altar ' formed an alliance against scepticism and liberal- ism ; the petty nobility of Germany already dreamed of a restoration of its feudal rights ; Prussian professors and statesmen began to vie with each other in theorising on the ' Christo- Teutonic State. It was reserved for the most exalted disciple of the romanticists to realise their ideal — so far as the good old Protestant State of Prussia allowed him to realise it — when he at last ascended the throne in 1840 : for Germany's favourable star had granted a long life to his wise and good father. Romanticism, indeed, was long dead, when Fre- derick William IV., the ' Romanticist on the J RECENT GERMAN WORK. 259 tlirone,' as Strauss called him by innuendo in a celebrated pamphlet, delivered up to the Catholic Church the rights of the State, so strenuously defended by his father, catholicised Protestant- ism as much as it lay in his power, and tried to create artificially a medieval constitution. He did not succeed ; but Germany still pays the penalty of these dangerous poetical experiments. We have arrived at the end of our task. Germany has not since been idle. She has pro- duced one poet of genius and many of talent since 1825. She has given to the world some Conclusion. great scientific and historical works, which are unequalled even in the period we have been studying together. Some great discoveries have been made in natural science ; but no new and fruitful ideas, such as had come forth from Germany during the sixty or seventy years we have been contemplating, have been produced. No new science has been created. The German intellect has been busy, ever since' Goethe's death, in developing or contradicting, in modifying or applying the ideas propounded and insisted on by the three generations to which Germany owes her intellectual Renaissance, the generation of 1760, that of 1780, and that of 1800. We have s 2 260 THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL. examined together these ideas, and I need not dwell upon them longer — or if I were to do so, I should be obliged to ask you for fifty meetings more — but I must beg you to bear in mind (what is indeed the purport of all these lectures), that the point of view, which was the general one in Europe during the last fifty years, was really opened by Germany. Let us not be misled by the universality of certain currents of thought as to their origin. When all Europe seemed bent on the mechanical explanation of nature, when Galileo, Kepler, Des- cartes, devoted their lives to this task, it was England which, through Harvey, Gilbert, Bacon, gave the impulse, which, through Hobbes, Newton, Locke, kept the lead in the movement which had sprung up in this island. It was the same with the French thought of the past century. No sooner had the Montes- quieus and Yoltaires, the Rousseaus and Diderots, expressed their ideas, than these ideas passed into European currency and were changed into foreign coin. The same phenomenon may be seen in the successive phases of the period dur- ing which Germany was acquiring the intellectual hegemony, i.e. from about 1763 to about 1830. ITS INFLUENCE IN ENGLAND AND EUROPE. 261 Scarcely had Winckelmann declared war against the reigning rococo, than all over Europe sculpture, painting, and architecture took the new classical turn. When, fifty years later, a reaction set in against the style empire, which had but been an exaggeration of Winckelmann's theories, when Chateaubriand in France, and Walter Scott in England, brought the Middle Ages into fashion, they only followed — unconsciously of course — the impulse given by the German romanticists. It was the same with the more important movement which took place all over Europe in historical and natural science. Not only would Augustin Thierry and Thomas Carlyle have been impossible without the German revolution of thought ; but the way in which our century looks upon antiquity, so widely difierent from that in which Pope or Voltaire looked upon it, was opened by Winckelmann and Lessing. The point of view, if not the method, which is generally accepted now in natural science, was first held by Goethe. The historical sciences — under which name we comprise not only political and literary history, but also theology, philology, archaeology, and jurisprudence — have been, during the whole century, and have scarcely even now ceased to be, 262 THE EOMANTIC SCHOOL. under the empire of Herder's ideas of evolution. Comparative philology, whether we consider it a branch of natural or of historical science, has not yet abandoned the roads opened by W. von Humboldt and Bopp, nor have the neo- Latin studies repudiated the paternity of Diez, or the Ger- manistic that of Grrimm. A new basis for philo- sophy has been laid by Kant. Schiller's concep- tion of art has been more and more generally adopted. The science of religion, and the inde- pendent spirit in which our time treats the history of Christianity, so different from the aggressive tone of the last century, are mainly due to Herder's German disciples. Above all, the con- sciousness with which individualism — a conserva- tive principle, when understood in the German sense — still resists here and there the overwhelm- ing tide of the levelling tendencies of our days, is of German origin. So also is the conscious- ness with which the right of intuitive genius — an aristocratic principle — is as yet maintained against the all- invading method of analysis and rationalism, a method which, in its ultimate re- sults, must always further the democratic interest, as it applies to the most general of human faculties. The fact of this struggle would suffice to prove CONCLUSION. 263 that the main principles of German thought have not triumphed without contest in Europe. They can hardly be said to have triumphed even in Germany, where they have been deeply modified and corrected by new currents, just as they had themselves deeply modified and corrected the English French currents of the past. 264 EPILOGUE. * TOUNG GERMANY ' AND ' LITTLE GERMANY.' 1825-1860. The romanticists were men ' who, with the weapons forged by the age of enlightenment, combated enlightenment itself, in the domains of science, art, morality, and politics.' With these words one of the most gifted Young Hegelians, who rose against romanticism towards 1830, Arnold Ruge, characterised his opponents. The exaggera- tion, in fact, of the romantic movement produced, as will always be the case, a strong reaction. This reaction took place in every department of intellectual life, just as the romantic movement had pervaded every branch of activity. The his- torical idea had been carried so far that it had led to the justification of every abuse and of every crime of the good old time, nay, to plans and efforts for bringing the world back to that good old time. HEGEL. 265 Hegel himself did not go to sucli lengths. He remained throughout faithful to the ideal of the modern State and the Protestant ^^^^^^ religion. Feudality and Catholicism re- ^''^-^^^i- mained always for him things of the past, which no effort could recall to life ; but he saw in the bureaucratical State of Frederick William III. the crowning result of all the historical evolutions, the end to which all the political history of Germany had tended. He regarded the ' Evan- gehcal Alliance' of Frederick William III. as destined to bring together Calvinists and Luthe- rans, as the ultimate expression of the religious development of his country. Now this evolution was, according to the philosophy of identity, which he had modified, but not abandoned, nothing but the evolution of universal reason itself, as developed in time and space ; and he gave to this view its philosophical formula, when he declared that ' whatever is, is reasonable, and whatever is reasonable, is ' — a proposition quite defensible if only Hegel's premiss were accepted, that his dialectic method was a thinking process identical with the process of things which in its turn was but the process of eternal thought thinking itself. For Hegel had given to the fieri idea of Herder 266 'young Germany' and 'little Germany.' dialectic and metaphysical form : the ' immanent negativity ' of things — everything is alv^^ays chang- ing, consequently denies itself unceasingly — is the form of a thought, w^hich is identical with the process of fieri in the world of phenomena. In the same way he had undertaken to prove that Christianity had given expression to the con- sciousness of the absolute in its purest form — as far as imagination and feeling were concerned — that it was consequently the absolute religion, as his philosophy was of course the absolute philo- sophy. At last he had gone so far as to interpret all the diflPerent dogmas of Christianity so as to make of them symbols of his own philosophy. This provoked the rebellion of his most eminent disciples. Strauss and Feuerbach, B. Bauer and Ruge, separated from him, and formed the left wing of Hegelianism, or, as they called themselves, the Young-Hegelians. Strauss attacked super- naturalism as well as theological rationalism with the weapons of historical investigation in his ' Life of Jesus,' which appeared in 1835. Faith- ful to Hegel's earlier ideas he presented in this memorable book the origin of Christianity as growing naturally out of the thoughts, feelings, and circumstances of the time, not as created by YOUNG HEGELIANS. 267 one stroke of a magic wand. He showed how far legend, myth, and the popular imagination had aided in the birth of Christianity, combating the supernatural as well as the rationalistic ex- planation of the miracles ; but combating quite as warmly the irreverent theories of the eighteenth century, which saw only wonder-workers and im- postors in all founders of religions. He thus be- came, together with F. 0. Baur, who had begun before him and who continued his work, the father of the new theological school, known as the Tiibin- gen school, whilst Feuerbach subjected more fully the theoretical side of Hegel's doctrine to the dialectical process which he had learned from his master, investigating the essence of religion in general ; and soon a numerous school of young thinkers followed in his steps. A return to common- sense in philosophy, to criticism in theology, was the consequence of these attacks against the high- priest of ' official ' philosophy. Even in the field of pagan mythology the spirit of enlightenment rose once more against the spirit of dusky divination ; and Voss and Lobeck threw down the gauntlet to Creuzer in the name of common-sense and reason. Something similar took place in jurisprudence and history proper. Savigny as well as Eichhorn 268 ' YOUNG GERMANY ' AND ' LITTLE GERMANY.' had taught that our time had neither vocation nor aptitude for law-giving ; that all fertile legislation There- ^^^ ^^^ work of generations; that the orrationaf- Roman law, which still lived in all the countries of the Continent, the German law, which still j^revailed in England, were only the expression of national spirit, custom, tradi- tion, and local necessities. Already in Hegel's life- time his most eloquent disciple, Gans, had defended against the historical school the rights of the living, and with these the rights also of reason. At the same time the wonderful development of the Frederician and Napoleonic legislation seemed the living refutation of the historic theory, pushed as far as it was pushed by the romanticists. Not a generation had passed away since the great work of Bonaparte ; and the Code Napoleon seemed already ineradicably rooted in France. Nay, with an eye of envy non- Prussian Germany regarded this simple rational legislation as contrasted with her own various complicated and antiquated laws. Napoleon, after all, had made his Code civil as well as his Code penal and his Code de procedure — as Frederick II. had, thirty years before, constructed his less comprehensive Landrecht — out of the frag- ments of former historical legislation, just as his HISTORY. 269 new administration was only that of the old mon- archy in disguise. This, however, was not yet well recognised by the generation of 1830, which was still persuaded that all this new organisation had sprung out of the Emperor's head, like Minerva from that of Jupiter, and that he had shaped it exclusively according to abstract principles of justice and utility. In all German universities ' natural law,' i.e. the rationalistic theory of law, as the eighteenth century had preached it ever since Thorn asius, again mounted the pro- fessors' chairs and revindicated the rights of reason against the absolutism of the historic school, which Goethe had so wittily parodied by anticipation. Like an inveterate disease, law and rights descend trailing from generation to generation, and gently move from place to place. Reason becomes non-sense ; what was a blessing is a curse. Woe to thee that thou art a grandson ! Of those rights, alas ! with which we are born, there is ne'er a question. A large body of historians followed the road of the new rationalistic school of jurisprudence. Germany was inundated with histories History. which treated all the past with reference to the present, which were not content to tell the facts, but commented upon them from the point 270 'young Germany' and 'little geemany.' of view of the Frencli liberals or the French re- publicans of the day. Eotteck's and Welcker's great ' Dictionary of Political Science,' entirely written under the influence of formal French constitutionalism, was the Bible of the new liberal doctrinaires, who sprang up everywhere in Germany and repeated in the small Chambers of Carlsruhe and Darmstadt the great oratorical tournaments of Paris under the Restoration and Louis Philippe. If the most practical of English statesmen, Lord Palmerston, naively believed that the recipe of a parliamentary constitution, neatly written on white paper, would work in Spain and Greece, as that growth of centuries, the British constitution, worked in England, the German professors of 1830 were certainly excus- able in thinking that they might introduce that most delicate and most abnormal form of govern- ment into their tiny bureaucratical States. Had not the French constitution-mongers, with Ben- jamin Constant at their head, adapted it to Con- tinental use ? There was, however, a party which went further than the constitutionalists. ' Young Germany' — so we call the group of youthful writers, bom about 1810, who, towards 1830, trod THE MODERN MINDS. 271 in the footsteps of Borne and Heine— Young Ger- many did not stop at representative monarchy, as it did not stop at Deism in philosophy, youno- although Heine himself remained ever ^'''"•'^"J'- faithful to the theory of a limited monarchy, and came back at the end of his life to ' the simple belief in the personal God of the common man,' as he used to say. Laube and Gutzkow, Wienbarg and Euge attacked Christianity and even Hegelian - ism, in which they had been bred, with the violence of the French revolutionists of 1 7 9 2 . They showed a determined predilection for atheism and material- ism in philosophy, for Jacobinism in politics ; they even preached, with the Saint- Simonians, the emancipation of woman and the abolition of indi- vidual property. They called themselves proudly ' modern ' minds. They protested against all forms of aristocracy, social as well as intellectual. The State was to become the one all-resfulatins power ; not the historical State, as it had grown up in the course of centuries — but the modem State built up according to the dictates of Eeason — or of Jean-Jacques ; not even the State of 1 790, but the democratical State of 1793. The place held till now by the great — kings, aristocrats, ge- niuses — was to be held henceforward by the people, 272 'young Germany' and 'little Germany.' wliicli was to become the hero of history and public life. At the same time they claimed, not only for the people, but for themselves, the right to material enjoyment, even to luxury ; not an equality in misery, but an equality in v^ealth was their un- attainable ideal. Their religion was the rehabilita- tion of the flesh ; science and poetry were means for preaching and propagating their new gospel. Their last and most dangerous disciple, Ferdinand Lassalle, died only fifteen years ago, not without having left his fatal legacy to Germany. Borne and Heine, who had given the first siernal for this reaction in favour of rationalism Borne and ^g^iiiist history, and of French ideas Heme. against German, did not, as I said, go so far. Heine was too much of an artist not to be shocked by such excesses ; Borne too much of a Stoic to go such lengths — his ideal was the in- corruptible Robespierre, not the epicurean Danton. For Heine, politics, as well as religion, history, philosophy, never ceased to be themes for poetical variations. In reality they were as indifferent to him as the religious subjects of the great works of the Italian Renaissance were indifferent to the artists who produced them. It was Borne and Heine, nevertheless, who set the example. Heine BORNE AND HEINE. 273 himself had belonged, as I have said, to the romantic school, and was the personal pupil of A. W. Schlegel. He had begun with two romantic tra- gedies which exhibit only too visibly the traces of the master's influence ; and he was destined to give in ' Atta Troll ' and the ' Romanzero ' what the romanticists themselves had never been able to give, the ideal romantic poem. There was not even wanting in them the much recommended irony of Fred. Schlegel. But Heine had always been a somewhat unruly disciple. As early as at the age of sixteen he had sung his song of the Napoleonic grenadiers, which was in opposition to the whole tendency of his masters ; and you know how he developed the theme of the Napoleon- worship in the incomparable prose-poem of ' Tambour Legrand.' Now, for a while Germany neglected Heine the immortal poet for Heine the ephemeral politician and philosopher —there are many foreigners who do so still — and was led to accept the most meagre of doctrines by the irresistible fascination of a prose and a verse which she had not heard since the great days of Goethe and Schiller ; whilst Borne's incomparable wit made her forget for a time that his political ideal was still more shallow than that of Heine. T 274 ' YOUNG GEEMANT ' AND ' LITTLE GERMANY.' We have seen that the liberating movement of 1813, the rising of the whole nation against the foreign yoke, had taken place under the inspira- tion of romanticism. It had taken the form of a crusade, not only against Napoleon and the French, but against the rationalism, the demo- cracy, and the cosmopolitan pretences of the eigh- teenth century and the great Revolution. It had invoked the Christian and religious spirit, Teutonic patriotism, feudal loyalty towards the hereditary princes ; and these feelings were still very strong when Heine and Borne, towards 1825, gave ex- pression to the aspirations of the rising genera- tion which had not felt the hardship of foreign oppression and to which the political reality which had followed the enthusiastic rise of 1813, had proved a source of the bitterest disappoint- ment. The shameless despotism of the fathers of the fatherland, most of them of Napoleon's own creation, or at least promotion, the petty tyranny of their instruments, and the religious fanaticism or hypocrisy which already began to spring up in the official spheres of South Germany, were quite sufficient to alienate the young from the romantic cause. It was the time when Grabbe wrote his tragedy of ' The Himdred Days,' when Zedlitz LITTLE GERMANY. 275 composed his poem of the dead Caesar's ' JMidnight Review,' when W. Miiller's ' Griechenlieder,' and Mosen's Polish songs resounded in the streets of every German town. The reaction in favour of cosmopolitism and humanitarianism against pa- triotic one-sidedness, and of French sympathies against German national prejudices, was at the same time a partial return to the ideas which had predominated in Germany in the times of Schiller and Goethe, and the exposition of which has been the main object of these lectures. A partial return, I say; for in opposing democracy to aris- tocracy, the masses to individualism, the mechani- cal making of states and laws to the ideas of growth and evolution, it was in contradiction with the creed of Herder and of Goethe. In its cosmopolitism and in its paganism it was quite under the sway of the great Humanitarian and the great Heathen. The Francophil, democratical, and rationalistic current, initiated by Borne, Heine, and Young Germany, prevailed for nearly a quarter ^ittie of a century, from 1825 to 1850. Then G*^"^'^"^'- again u^nder the influence of the disenchantment which the failures of 1848 had caused, and still more under the impressions produced by the T 2 276 'young Germany' and ' little geemany.' bankruptcy of the French democracy in 1849, a contrary current arose in Germany. Already towards 1840 this new current had set in : the current of German national spirit Its national ^gaiust foreign influence, and above character, ^^l against France. From 1840 to 1848 the 'Germanistenversammlungen ' or meetings of Teutonic philologists, jurisconsults and historians, were for Germany what the scientific congresses were for Italy, the pretext and opportunity for asserting and preparing the unity of Germany. For it was written that our political ideas should be framed by professors, as professors had framed our literary and artistic, our religious and philosophical ideas. The two men, however, who gave us, the one a national poetry, the other a national state, were not professors : but could they have done their work if the professors had not prepared the ground for them ? Would they not have done it in a still more satisfactory way if the professors had not continued to interfere in it ? The outbreak of French Chauvinism — the ugly word seems to have established itself in all our languages — and the thirst for conquest betrayed in 1840, the cries for the Ehine which resounded in Paris, as soon as Europe was threatened with ITS NATIONAL CHARACTER. 277 a general war through the complication in the East, contributed not a Kttle to strengthen this current, particularly in the menaced provinces of the left bank, which had been the special centre of the romantic movement. This current is, neverthe- less, very distinct from that of 1813, and it became still more so after 1848, when the romantic dreams of a resurrection of Frederick Barbarossa's Empire, under the form of a Seventy- Millions Germany, prevented the foundation of the national State. It was, in the main, undoubtedly directed against what was un-German in the political rationalism of ' Young Germany ' — whose best men, from Borne, Gans, and Heine, down to F. Lassalle, were, curious to say, really not of German blood, being Israelites by birth, if not by creed. The declara- tion of war itself was a violent pamphlet against Borne from the pen of Gervinus. Nevertheless, the reaction of 1850 did not affect a picturesque and poetical costume like that of 1813. The new patriots deemed it unnecessary and childish to show the love of their country by their white collars, bare necks, and long hair. On the contrary, they affected rather a sort of bourgeois common-place exterior. They dreaded to be considered as unpractical dreamers j their 278 'young GERMANY ' AND ' LITTLE GERMANY.' higliest ambition was to be taken for ' positive ' people. Tbeir ideal in history was the honest, stedfast, prosy Burger of the sixteenth century, not the romantic knight of the Middle Ages, or the Germanic chieftain of barbarous times. They saw the strength of the nation in the middle- class, and turned against the Jmiker nobility, as well as against the democratic masses. They did not dream of a traditional royalty, but of a monarchy resting on contract like that of England since 1688. They showed no sympathy for the Church or for any religious mysticism, such as had inspired the poets of 1813 ; on the contrary, they wished to impress upon men's minds that they were Protestants — sober, unpoetical Protestants — and at the same time the heirs of Kant, whose purely moral religion, without dogmas and forms of worship, was to be the German religion far excellence, i.e. the final form of Protestantism, as for the English Deists of the past century Uni- tarianism was the final form of English Pro- testantism. But if they were disciples of Kant the moralist, they pointedly ignored Kant the metaphysician. 'Young Germany' had still been strongly imbued with the speculative spirit ; it had grown up under THE GERMAN METHOD. 279 Hpgel's, as yet, uncontested rule. The new school deliberately turned their backs on all metaphysics : duringr their reisrn over public opinion, if ° Oil. Its Positive not over State and Church — i.e. from Character in Science. 1850 to about 1866— a sort of indiffer- entism, nay, of aversion, for philosophical specula- tion seemed to have taken hold of the nation, awakened, as she was, and sobered down from her metaphysical excesses. Even in their way of treat- ing science they went to the opposite extreme. The great advantage of Kant's influence was, that science during the first half of this century was always handled in a philosophical spirit. There was certainly an excess both in the so-called 'philo- sophy of nature ' and in the ' philosophy of history,' which interfered too often with the sober and exact observation and verification of facts. The new school assumed to be more positive. General ideas had nothing to do with science ; and they even went so far as to treat history as a sort of exact science. The famous ' German method ' dates from this time. Imagination, and even intuition, were banished from historical studies, as well as from natural science. Facts alone were to be sought for, sifted, and assembled ; the only combination of the facts which was allowed was connexion 280 ' YOUNG GEEMANT ' AND ' LITTLE GERMANY.' through cause and effect ; and the disciples were so well drilled that they succeeded at last not only in finding the facts they wanted, and in mak- ing them take the appearance which they desired, but in driving life itself out of history, which is but the evolution of life. Even the present genera- tion, which has come back to long neglected philo- sophy, is animated in its researches by a spirit entirely different from that which j)redominated in the times of Hegel. It is, indeed, Kant's criticism of reason with its strictly experimental character and its opposition to all a priori speculation, which our matter-of-fact juniors have taken up again. In other words they have returned to the point whence their fathers started on their strange Odysse}^ and they are favoured in their new vojsige by all the light which the progress of natural science, accomplished in the interval, throws on their road. And not the professional philosophers alone, but the men of science them- selves, the physiologists especially, tread now with a surer foot in the steps of the great renovator of modern thought. If, however, the men of 1850 repudiated all philosophical ideas, they did not reject political ideas ; nay, history soon became in their hands a GEEMAN LIBERALISM. 281 storehouse of arguments for political views. The ' men of Gotha ' — so they were called in consequence of the Gotha Parliament of 1849, in which thej formed the majorit}" — thought, if thej did not say, that politics alone really deserved to la Politics. occupy a nation which had come of age. They were staunch Liberals of the constitutional school ; but their ideal was the old English Con- stitution, not the French one of 1830. In general their leaders, from Dahlmann and Gervinus, down to Gneist and Waitz, Sybel and Hausser, were decidedly English in their sympathies, until — well, until a period which lies beyond the limits of the subject which I have to treat here. Like the English Liberals of the old school they had arrived at a species of compromise between political rationalism and ' historicism.' They still adhered to the German idea of evolution — the only great German idea to which they remained faithful — but they corrected it consciously, as the English had done and do almost unconsciously, by adaptation of the past to the exigencies of the present. They saw the historical spirit, not in a return to the past, or in a stopping of history at a given moment, but in continuous progress. Moreover, as, although mostly professors, they 282 ' YOUNG GEEMANY ' AND ' LITTLE GEEMANY.' claimed to be practical politicians, not dreamers and theorists, tliey did not want to awaken Fre- derick Barbarossa in bis Kjffbaiiser, and call to life the ' Holy Eoman Empire of tbe German Nation,' witb its seventy millions of souls and its sway over Hungary and Italy, Poland and Burgundy. Tbey wanted to have a national State strong enough to defend itself against foreign aggression, not so mighty as to arouse the fears or suspicion of the neighbouring nations; a State similar to those founded, or at least perfected, by Louis XI. of France, Henry YII. of England, Ferdinand the Catholic of Spain. In consequence they raised a characteristic protest against the Othos and Fredericks of the Middle Ages, who, instead of following the sensible and moderate national policy of Henry I., went to assume in Eome the crown of the Csesars. And as Austria was still con- sidered, and considered herself as the natural heir of the Holy Empire, as her possessions lay to a great extent outside the frontiers of the German language and German interests ; as she was Catho- lic throughout, the exclusion of Austria became an article, and indeed the chief article of the new political faith. Thence the name of the party, ' Little Germany,' as opposed to those successors THE PRUSSIAN STATE. 283 of the romantic school still numerous in 1848, who wanted to defend the German interests ' on the Mincio,' and saw in Austria the champion of German grandeur, and were usually called the party of ' Great Germany.' The ' Little Germans,' indeed, saw clearly from the beginning, in Protestant Prussia, the power which was to realise the longed-for national State, powerful enough to defend its integrity, but with- out any hankering after political hegemony in Europe such as Charles Y. and Louis XIY. had aspired to, and such as had always haunted the patriots of 1813, when they dreamed of avenging the death of young Conradin and restoring the Empire of his grandfather. Their aim, I said, was to be eminently matter-of-fact, and they affected a contempt for high-flown or sentimental ideas, which was often taken abroad for less of a fanfaronnade de vice than it really was. They were so anxious to show that they were no longer modest, shy, dreamy sentimentalists that they sometimes overdid it ; for they strove not only against the looseness of moral principles, the Bohemian life, the Jacobinism and the Frenchified ways of ' Young Germany,' to whose Gallic frivolity they opposed their Teutonic earnestness ; 284 ' YOUNG GERMANY ' AND ' LITTLE GERMANY.' not only against tlie mania for poetical fancy- costumes, and the unpractical enthusiasm of the patriots of 1813. They strove also against the idealism of Goethe's and Schiller's time, against its exaggerated individualism, against the eternal seK-education, against the Avhole worship of beautiful souls, against its humanitarian cosmo- politism, and absence of prejudice ; but above all against its alienation from public life, and its exclusive admiration of art and thought as the highest activity of man. Gervinus, at the end of his history of German poetry, which appeared from 1835 to 1842, and was a species of patriotic pamphlet in five huge volumes, breaks out into these words, which give vent to the suppressed idea, that pervades his whole book, as it was the undercurrent of the feelings of his whole generation : Is it not time to use the forces hidden in the nation 1 to ask the governments to appreciate those forces, and give them free course 1 to wish that the nation, which forms the centre and nucleus of Eiu-ope, should come out of the despised position which it occupies ? that it should enter at last on its majority 1 . . . But, by whatever means that aim is to be attained, it is not by the ways which our poetry has taken. . . . We want a man of Luther's stamp. He himself was tempted to undertake the task ; but he THE GERMAN STATE. 285 despaired for the ever alleged reason that he did not believe in the political intelligence and capacity of his nation. If it were in the nature of the people, he was of opinion, it would show itself without laws. . . . But we will not despair of this people. . . , We cannot believe that a nation can have achieved so great results in poetry, religion, art, and science, and yet should be absolutely incapable of any political achievement. , , . Our duty is to understand the signs of the times, to give up scattering our strength as we do, to direct our activity towards the point which is the object of the most ardent desires of all. The fight on the field of art is over ; now we ought to aim steadily at the other object, which nobody as yet amongst us has attained. Perhaps Apollo will there also grant us the prize, which he has not refused us elsewhere ! The ' man of Luther's stamp ' came, and the first to turn his back upon him was the man w^ho had yearned for him ; and the man of Luther's stamp saw what Luther had seen, that political capacity was not in the nature of the nation, and so, having vainly tried to build the national State with the help of the nation, he at last did it without the nation. As soon as he had done his work, the ' Little Germans,' who had not understood him, and had opposed him, loaded him with praise, for they saw that it was their dream which he had realised. So he called them 286 * YOUNG GEEMANT ' AND '^LITTLE GERMANY.' again to work with him to fit up the new building, and they put their hand to the work, and again proved that political capacity was not in their nature, and thus they separated again, perhaps for ever. Nevertheless, they have been, and are, trying hard to become a political nation. To arrive at Its infla- "^^i^ result, Germany, freed for the last ^g*fjjj°°Q fifty years from all social, religious, and °^^ ' national prejudices, had to acquire them again artificially, or at least to form a new ' cake of custom,' or ensemble of such prejudices as were necessary for the practical purposes of a national and political life. A man who sees all sides of a question, whom the passions of the patriot and the party-man do not move, who thinks more of being let alone than of acting upon others, a man without prejudices — in a word, the ideal man of Goethe's time — was scarcely fit for the new task. For this work, good, solid, narrow, social and other prejudices were a necessity. The con- solidation then of prejudices, above all, of the national prejudice, was the chief, though uncon- scious aim of the German intellectual movement since 1850 ; and as regards national prejudice, they certainly succeeded. Whenever national interests MODERN GERMAN PATRIOTISM. 287 are at stake, we all liold together, as our fathers never did, and show a public spirit utterly un- known to them. I cannot say the same as yet in cases where the interests of liberty, of good admin- istration, of free trade, and so forth, are concerned. It is a great thing that at least in national ques- tions, we should be united and unanimous even to excess. As I said in my last lecture, the death of individualism, which we have witnessed since 1850, seems a contradiction of tke German idea. Still, it was necessary to a certain degree, because excessive individualism unfits man for public life. One of the first means of creating those pre- judices, and one of its last consequences, was the creation of national pride, a virtue or a vice, utterly unknown to the great period of 1790. This new patriotism had not the simplicity of the French or Greek patriotism, which regards all other nations as barbarians ; nor the humble and sentimental tenderness of Italian patriotism, which clings to the redeemed country as a mother does to a child saved from death but still delicate and ailing, and scarcely able to face the hard- ships of life in a public school with hardy com- rades. It had not the robust vigour of the Roman and old-English patriotism, which simply ignored 288 ' YOUNG GERMANY ' AND * LITTLE GERMANY.' the legal existence of all who were not Eoman citizens or British subjects. The new German patriotism, which is not to be confounded with the old Prussian, was not, and is not na'if. It is conscious ; it is intentional ; it has a tincture of pedantry because it has been made by scholars and literary men. It has sprung up from a feel- ing of want of patriotism, such as had reigned before, and against which reaction was necessary. It resembles in that respect the religion of the German romanticists, who had all been free- thinkers, and resolved one fine day to become believers because belief was a necessary basis of all poetical excellence. Hence the exaggerations of German patriotism. It was not bom naturally, or spontaneously, it was the fruit of reflection. It was not the less justified for all that ; for it was really necessary for the creation of a na- tional State. Now, next to a just and righteous order, which is the very raison d'etre of the State, national independence and national strength, which guarantees this independence, are the most in- dispensable conditions for the welfare of a nation. When a nation does not possess these, it must sacrifice everything to attain them, even liberty. The Spaniards gave the example of it in the STRUGGLE FOR INTERNAL LIBERTY. 289 beginning- of this century, because they had at least this superiority over Germany, that they possessed a national State — worse, certainly, than the one which the French wanted to force upon them — but still a national State. This goal once attained, the struggle for internal liberty ought to begin, with its various vicissitudes of victory and defeat, as England carried it on from the destruction of the Armada to the reisrn of George IV. ; and it is only when this conquest has been achieved, that the nation can allow herself again the luxury of such liberal ideas and feelings as those which animated the great founders of German culture. Meanwhile those ideas bear fruit a thousand- fold throughout the world, and spring up even in distant fields, whither the seed has been . T 1 T . ^ c T • Conclusion. carried by the winds of history. But at home there still remains, and will ever remain a quiet, unobserved community of the faithful, who guard devotedly the treasure bequeathed to their country by the great heroes of thought and art. They live outside the strife of public life, looking on it sometimes with regret, sometimes with anger — but always with hope. They will not allow that Germany, which has given to the world the u 290 ' YOUNG GERMANY ' AND ' LITTLE GERMANY.' ideas of Lessing and Herder, of Goethe and Schiller, should for ever exclude them from their national creed. They will take care that, when the day is come, Germany shall restore those wide ideas to their place of honour at the hearth from which they went forth over the world. When that moment is come, Germany, which now seems chiefly occupied with the selfish, though necessary, task of strengthening her house against the storms which might threaten it, and of rendering it more habitable than it has been before, will, I for one am confident, resume with undivided heart her share in that common work of Europe which, under whatever national form it may be produced, is the civilisation of mankind. LONDON : PRINTED BY SPOTTISTVOODE AND CO., KEW-STBEET SQCTABB AXD PAKHAilEXT STUEET OCTOBIEI?, 1879. GENERAL LISTS OF NEW WORKS PUBLISHED BY Messes. LONGMANS, GEEEN & CO. PATERNOSTER ROW, LONDON. »o>fKo« HISTORY, POLITICS, HISTORICAL MEMOIRS &.C. Armitage's ChUdhood of the English Nation. Pep. 8vo. 2*. M. Arnold's Lectures on Modern History. 8vo. 7s. 6d. Bagehot's Literary Studies. 2 vols. 8vo. 28s. Buckle's History of Civilisation. 3 vols, crown Svo. 245. Chesney's Indian Polity. Svo. 21^. — Waterloo Lectures. Svo. 10^. 6(7. Digby's Famine Campaign in India. 2 vols. Svo. 32*. Durand's First Afghan "War. Svo. Frontispiece, 16*. Epochs of Ancient History : — Beesly's Gracchi, Marius, and Sulla, 2s. 6d. Capes's Age of the Antonines, 2s. Gd. — Early Eoman Empire, 2s. 6d. Cox's Athenian Empire, 2s. 6d. — Greeks and Persians, 2s. Gd. Curteis's Bise of the Macedonian Empire, 2*. Gd. Ihne's Eome to its Captm-e by the Gauls, 2s. Gd. Merivale's Roman Triumvirates, 2*. Gd. Sankey's Spartan and Thebau Supremacies, 2*. Gd. Epochs of English History, complete in One Volume. Fcp. 8vo.-5s. Creighton's Shilling History of England (Introductory Volume). Fcp. Svo. Is. Browning's Modem England, 1820-1875, 9d. Cordery's Struggle against Absolute Monarchy, 1603-1688, dd. Creighton's (Mrs.) England a Continental Power, 1066-1216, 9d. Creighton's (Eev. M.) Tudors and the Reformation, 14S5-1603, Sd. Rowley's Rise of the People, 1215-1485, Sd. Rowley's Settlement of the Constitution, 1688-1778, dd. Tancock's England during the American & European Wars, 1778-1820, 9d. York-Powell's Early England to the Conquest, Is. Epochs of Modern History : — Church's Beginning of the Middle Ages, 2*. Gd. Cox's Crusades, 2*. Gd. Creighton's Age of Elizabeth, 2s. Gd. Gau-dner's Houses of Lancaster and York, 2s. Gd. Gardiner's Puritan Revolution, 2s. Gd. — Thirty Years' War, 2*. Gd. Hale's Fall of the Stuarts, 2*. Gd. Johnson's Normans in Europe, 2*. Gd. Loudon, LONGMANS & CO. General Lists of New Works. Epochs of Modem History— continued. Ludlow's War of American Independence, 2s. Gd. MoitIs's Age of Queen Anne, 2s. 6d. Seebohm's Protestant Revolution, 2s. 6d. Stubbs's Early Plantagenets, 2s. 6d. Warbui-ton's Edward III., 2s. 6d. Froude's English in Ireland in the 18th Centm-y. 3 vols. 8vo. iSs. — History of England. 12 vols. Svo. £8. 18*. 12 vols, crown 8vo. 72s. — Julius Cffisar, a Sketch. Svo. IGs. Gairdner's Richard III. and Perkin Warbeck. Cro^vn Svo. 10^. Gd. Gardiner's England undar Buckingham and Charles I., 1G24-1628. 2 vols. Svo. 2is. — Personal Government of Charles I., 1628-1637. 2 vols. Svo. 2is. Greville's Journal of the Reigns of George IV. & William IV. 3 vols. Svo. 36j. Hayward's Selected Essays, 2 vols, crown Svo. I2s. Hearn's Aryan Household. Svo. 16^. Ihne's History of Rome. 8 vols. Svo. 45s. Lecky's History of England. Vols. I. & II. 1700-1760. Svo. 3Gs. — — — European Morals. 2 vols, crown Svo. 16s. — Spirit of Rationalism in Europe. 2 vols, crown Svo. 16s. Lewes's Histoiy of Philosophy. 2 vols. Svo. 32.s. Longman's Lectures on the History of England. Svo. 15s. — Life and Times of Edward III. 2 vols. Svo. 28s. Macaulay's Complete Works. S vols. Svo. £5, 5s. — History of England : — Student's Edition. 2 vols. or. Svo. 12s. | Cabinet Edition. S vols, post Svo. 48*. People's Edition. 4 vols. or. Svo. 16*. | Library Edition. 5 vols. Svo. £4. Macaulay's Critical and Historical Essays. Cheap Edition. Crown Svo. 3*. Gd. Student's Edition. 1 vol. cr. Svo. 6s. [ Cabinet Edition. 4 vols, post Svo. 24.S. People's Edition. 2 vols. cr. Svo. Ss. \ Library Edition. 3 vols. Svo. Z6s. May's Constitutional History of England. 3 vols, crown Svo. 18s. — Democracy in Eirrope. 2 vols. Svo. 32s. Merivale's FaU of the Roman Republic. 12mo. 7s. 6d. — General History of Rome, B.C. 753— a.d. 476. Crown Svo. 7s. 6d. — History of the Romans under the Empire. 8 vols, post Svo. 48.S. Phillips's Civil War in Wales and the Marches, 1642-1649. Svo. 16s. Rawlinson's Seventh Great Oriental Monsu-chy — The Sassanians. Svo. 28s, Sixth Oriental Monarchy — Parthia. Svo. 16.S. Seebohm's Oxford Reformers — Colet, Erasmus, & More. Svo. 14*. Sewell's Popular History of France. Crown Svo. 7.s. 6d. Short's History of the Church of England. Crovra Svo. 7s. 6d. Smith's Carthage and the Carthaginians. Crown Svo. 10*. 6d. Taylor's Manual of the History of India. Crown Svo. 7*. 6d. Todd's Parliamentary Government in England. 2 vols. Svo. 37s. Trench's Realities of Irish Life. Cro\vn Svo. 2*. Gd. Walpole's History of England. Vols. I. & II. Svo. 36*. Webb's Civil War in Herefordshire. 2 vols. Svo. Illustrations, 42*. BIOGRAPHICAL WORKS. Burke's Vicissitudes of Families. 2 vols, crown Svo. 21*. Gleig's Life of the Duke of Wellington. Crown Svo. 6*. London, LONGMANS & CO. Jerrold's Life of Napoleon III. Vols. I. to III. 8vo. price 18*. each. Jones's Life of Admiral Frobisher. Crown 8vo. 6s. Lecky's Leaders of Public Opinion in Ireland. Crowii 8vo. 7s. Gd. Life (The) and Letters of Lord Macaiilay. By his Nephew, G. Otto Trevelyan, M.P. Cabinet Edition, 2 vols, post 8vo. 12s. Library Edition, 2 vols. Svo. 26s. Marshman's Memoirs of Havelock. Crown Svo. 3s. Gd. Memoirs of Anna Jameson, by Gerardine Macpherson. Svo. 12*. 6d. Memorials of Charlotte Williams- Wynn. Crown Svo. 10*. Gd. Mendelssohn's Lettei-s. Translated by Lady Wallace. 2 vols, cr, Svo. 5*. each. Mill's (John Stuart) Autobiography. Svo. 7*. Gd. Newman's Apologia pro Vita Sua. Crown Svo. 6*. Nohl's Life of Mozart. Translated by Lady Wallace. 2 vols, crown Svo. 21*. Pattison's Life of Casaubon. Svo. 18*. Spedding's Letters and Life of Francis Bacon. 7 vols. Svo. £4. 4*. Stephen's Essays in Ecclesiastical Biography. Crown Svo. 7*. Gd. Stigand's life. Works &c. of Heinrich Heine. 2 vols. Svo. 28*. MENTAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. Amos's View of the Science of Jm-isprudence. Svo. 18*. — Fifty Years of the English Constitution. Svo. — Primer of the EngUsh Constitution. Crown Svo. 6*. Bacon's Essays, with Annotations by Whately. Svo. 10*. Gd. — Works, edited by Spedding. 7 vols. Svo. 73*. Gd. Bain's Logic, Deductive and Inductive. Crown Svo. 10*. Gd. Part I. Deduction, 4*. | Pakt II. Induction, 6*. Gd. BoUand & Lang's Aristotle's Politics. Crown Svo. 7*. Gd. Brassey's Foreign Work and English Wages. Svo. 10*. Gd. Comte's Sj'stem of Positive Polity, or Treatise upon Sociology, translated : — Vol. I. General View of Positivism and its Introductory Principles. Svo. 21*. Vol. II. Social Statics, or tlie Abstract Laws of Human Order. 14*. Vol. in. Social Dynamics, or General Laws of Human Progress. 21*. Vol. IV. Theoi-y of the Futm-e of Man ; with Early Essays. 24*. Congreve's Politics of Aristotle ; Greek Text, English Notes. Svo. IS*. Grant's Ethics of Ai-istotle, Greek Text, English Notes. 2 vols. Svo. 32*. Hillebrand's Lectures on German Thought. Svo. Hodgson's Philosophy of Reflection. 2 vols. Svo. 21*. Lewis on Authority in Mattera of Opinion. Svo. 14*. Leslie's Essays in Political and Jloral Philosophy. Svo. 10*. Gd. Macaulay's Speeches cprrected by Himself. Crown Svo. 3*. Gd. Macleod's Economical Philosophy. Vol. I. Svo. 15*. Vol. II. Part 1. 12*. Mill on Representative Government. Crown Svo. 2*. — — Liberty. Post Svo. 7*. Gd. Crown Svo. 1*. id. Mill's Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind. 2 vols. Svo. 28*. — Dissertations and Discussions. 4 vols. Svo. 46*. Gd. — Essays on Unsettled Questions of Political Economy. Svo. 6*. Gd. — Examination of Hamilton's Philosophy. Svo. 16*. — Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive. 2 vols. Svo. 25*. — Phenomena of the Human Mind. 2 vols. Svo. 28*. — Principles of Political Economy. 2 vols. Svo. 30*. 1 vol. cr. Svo. 5*. London, LONGMANS & CO. 4 General Lists of New "Works. Mill's Subjection of Women. Crown 8vo. 6s, — Utilitarianism. 8vo. 5*. MoreU's Philosophical Fragments. Crown 8vo. 5*. MUller's (Max) Chips from a G-ermau Workshop. 4 vols. Svo. 5Ss. — Hibbert Lectures on Origin and Growth of Religion. Svo. 10s. Gd. Mullinger's Schools of Charles the Great. Svo. 7^. dd. Sandars's Institutes of Justinian, with English Notes. Svo. 18*. Swinboume's Picture Logic. Post Svo. 5s. Thomson's Outline of Necessary Laws of Thought. Crown Svo. 6s. TocqueviUe's Democracy in America, translated by Reeve. 2 vols, crown Svo. 16*. Twiss's Law of Nations, Svo. in Time of Peace, 12.S. in Time of War, 21*. Whately's Elements of Logic. Svo. 10s. 6d. Crown Svo. is. 6d. — — — Rhetoric. 8vo. 10s. Gd. Crown Svo. is. 6d. — English Synonymes. Fcp. Svo. 3s. Williams's Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle translated. Crown Svo. 7s. Gd ZeUer's Socrates and the Socratlc Schools. Crown Svo. 10s. 6d. — Stoics, Epicureans, and Sceptics. Crown Svo. 14*. — Plato and the Older Academy. Crown Svo. ISs. MISCELLANEOUS AND CRITICAL WORKS. Arnold's (Dr. Thomas) Miscellaneous Works. Svo. 7^. 6d. — (T.) Manual of EugUsh Literature. Crown Svo. 7s. 6d. — English Authors, Poetry and Prose Specimens. Bain's Emotions and the Wai. Svo. 15s. — Mental and Moral Science. Crown Svo. 10*. 6d. — Senses and the Intellect. Svo. 15s. Blackley's German and English Dictionary. Post Svo. 7s. 6d. Buckle's Miscellaneous and Posthumous Works. 3 vols. Svo. 52s. 6d. BuUinger's Lexicon and Concordance to the New Testament. Medium Svo. 30*. Conington's Miscellaneous Writings. 2 vols. Svo. 28*. Contanseau's Practical French & English Dictionary. Post Svo. 7s. Gd. — Pocket French and English Dictionary. Square ISmo. 3*. Gd. Edwards's Specimens of English Prose. 16mo. 2*. 6d. Farrar's Language and Languages. Crown Svo. 6*. Froude's Short Studies on Great Subjects. 3 vols, crown Svo. 18*. German Home Life, reprinted from Fraser's Magazine. Crown Svo. 6*. Hume's Essays, edited by Green & Grose, 2 vols. Svo. 28*. — Treatise of Human Nature, edited by Green & Grose. 2 vols. Svo. 28*. Latham's Handbook of the EugUsh Language. Crown Svo. 6*. — English Dictionary. 1 vol. medium Svo. 24*. 4 vols. 4to. £,7. LiddeU & Scott's Greek-English Lexicon. Crown 4to. 86*. — — — Abridged Greek-English Lexicon. Square 12mo. 7*. 6d. Longman's Pocket Gennan and English Dictionary. ISmo. 5*. Macaulay's Miscellaneous Writings. 2 vols. Svo. 21*. 1 vol. crown Svo. 4*. Gd, — Writings and Speeches. Crown Svo. 6*. MiiUer's (Max) Lectm-es on the Science of Language. 2 vols, crown Svo. 16*. Noird on Max MUller's Philosophy of Language. Svo. 6*. Rich's Dictionary of Roman and Greek Antiquities. Crown Svo. 7s. Gd, London, LONGMANS & CO. General Lists of New Works, Rogers's Eclip-c of Faith. Fcp. 8vo. 5s. — Defence of the Eclipse of Faith Fcp. 8vo. 3s. 6(7. Koget's Thesaurus of English Words and Phrases. Crown 8vo. 10.!. 6d, Selections from the "Writings of Lord Macaulay. Crown 8vo. 6s. The Essays and Contributions of A. K. H. B. Crown 8vo. Autumn Holidays of a Country Pai-son. Zs. 6d. Changed Aspects of Unchanged Tiiiths. 3.s. Gd. Common-place Philosopher in To^vn and Country. Ss. 6d. Coimsel and Comfort spoken from a City Pulpit. 3s. 6d. Critical Essays of a Counti-y Parson. 3s. Gd. Graver Thoughts of a Country Parson. Thi-ee Series, 3*. Gd, each. Landscapes, Churches, and Moralities. 3*. 6d. Leisure Hom-s in Town. 3s. 6d. Lessons of Middle Age. 3s. 6d. Present-day Thoughts. 3s. 6d. Recreations of a Country Parson. Three Series, 3s. Gd. each. Seaside Musings on Sundays and Wee]5:-Days. 3s. 6d. Sunday Afternoons in the Parish Chmch of a University City. Zs. Gd. White & Riddle's Large Latin-English Dictionary. 4to. 21*. White's College Latin-EngUsh Dictionary. Medium 8vo. 12s. — Junior Student's Lat.-Eng. and Eng.-Lat. Dictionary. Square 12mo. I2s. <^nflrntPlv i '^^^ EngUsh-Latin Dictionary, 5s. Gd. cjepaxateiy -| ,pj^g Latin-English Dictionary, 7s. Gd. White's Middle-Class Latin-EngUsh Dictionary. Fcp. 8vo. 3s. Wit and Wisdom of the Rev. Sydney Smith 16mo. 3s. Gd. Tonge's Abridged English-Greek Lexicon. Square 12mo. 8s. Gd. — Large English-Greek Lexicon. 4to. 2ls. ASTRONOMY, METEOROLOGY, POPULAR GEOGRAPHY 8cc. Dove's Law of Storms, translated by Scott. 8vo. 10s. Gd. Herschel's Outlines of Astronomy. Square crown 8vo. 12s. Keith Johnston's Dictionary of Geography, or General Gazetteer. 8vo. 42s. Nelson's Work on the Moon. Medium 8vo. 31s. Gd. Proctor's Essays on Astronomy. 8vo. 12s. — Larger Star Atlas. Folio, 15s. or Maps only, 12s. Gd. — Moon. Crown 8vo. 10s. Gd. — New Star Atlas. Crown 8vo. 5s. — Orbs Around Us. Crown 8vo. 7s. Gd. — Other Worlds than Om-s. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6f7. — Satm-n and its System. 8vo. 14s. — Sun. Crown Svo. 14s. — Transits of Venus, Past and Coming. Crown Svo. 8s. Gd. — Treatise on the Cycloid and Cycloidal Curves. Crown Svo. 10s. Gd. — Universe of Stars. Svo. 10s. Gd. ScheUen's Spectrum Analysis. Svo. 28s. Smith's Air and Rain. Svo. 24s. The Public Schools Atlas of Ancient Geography. Imperial Svo. 7s. 6d. — — — Atlas of Modern Geography. Imperial Svo. 5s. Webb's Celestial Objects for Common Telescopes. New Edition in preparation. NATURAL HISTORY &c POPULAR SCIENCE. Amott's Elements of Physics or Natm-al Philosophy. Crown Svo. 12s. Gd. Brande's Dictionary of Science, Literature, and Art. 3 vols, medium Svo. 63s. London, LONGMANS & CO. General Lists of New Works. Buckton's Town and "Window Gardening. Crown 8vo. 3*. Cox's Mechanism of IMan. 2 vols, crown 8vo. 23«. Decaisne and Le Maont's General System of Botany. Imperial 8vo. 31s. 6d. Dixon's Rural Bird Life. Crown 8vo. illustrations. Ganot's Elementary Treatise on Physics, by Atkinson. Large crown 8vo. 15s. — Natiu-al Philosophy, by Atkinson. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d. Gore's Art of Scientific Discovery. Crown 8vo. 15s. Grove's Correlation of Physical Forces. 8vo. 15s. Hartwig's Aerial World. 8vo. 10.s. Gd. — Polar World. 8vo. 10*. 6d. — Sea and its Living Wonders. 8vo. 10s. Bd. — Subterranean World. 8vo. 10s. 6d. — Tropical World. 8vo. 10s. Gd. Haughton's Principles of Animal Mechanics. 8vo. 21s. Heer's Primaeval World of Switzerland. 2 vols. 8vo. IGs. Hehnholtz's Lectures on Scientific Subjects. 8vo. 12^. Gd. Hfllmholtz on the Sensations of Tone, by EUis. 8vo. SGs. HuUah's Lectures on the History of Modern Music. 8vo. 8^. Gd. — Transition Period of Musical History. 8vo. 10*. Gd. Keller's Lake Dwellings of Switzerland, by Lee. 2 vols, royal 8vo. 42*. Kirby and Spence's Introduction to Entomology. Crown 8vo. 5s. Lloyd's Treatise on Magnetism. 8vo. 105. Gd. — — on the Wave-Theory of Light. 870. lOi. 6^. Loudon's Encyclopsedia of Plants. 8vo. i2s. Lubbock on the Origin of Civilisation & Primitive Condition of Man. 8vo. 18*. Macalister's Zoology and Morphology of Vertebrate Animals. 8vo. 10s. Gd. Nicols' Puzzle of Life. Crown 8vo. 3*. Gd. Owen's Comparative Anatomy and Physiology of the Vertebrate Animals. 3 vols . 8vo. 73*. Gd. Proctor's Light Science for Leisure Hours. 2 vols, crown Svo. 7*. Gd. each, Eivers's Orchard House. Sixteenth Edition. Crown 8vo. 5s. — Rose Amateur's Guide. Fcp. 8vo. 4*. Gd. Stanley's Familiar History of Birds. Fcp. 8vo. 3*. Gd. Text-Books of Science, Mechanical and Physical. Abney's Photography, 3*. Gd. Anderson's (Sir John) Strength of Materials, 3*. Gd. Armstrong's Organic Chemistiy, 3*. Gd. Barry's Railway Appliances, 3*. Gd. Bloxam's Metals, 3*. Gd. Goodeve's Elements of Mechanism, 3*. Gd. — Principles of Mechanics, 3*. Gd. Gore's Electro-Metallurgy, 6*. Grifan's Algebra and Trigonometry, 3*. Gd. Jenkin's Electricity and Magnetism, 3*. Gd. Maxwell's Theory of Heat, 3*. Gd. Merrifield's Technical Arithmetic and Mensuration, 3*. 6d. Miller's Inorganic Chemistry, 3*. Gd. Preece & Sivewright's Telegraphy, 3*. Gd. Rutley's Study of Rocks, 4*. Gd. Shelley's Workshop Appliances, 3*. Gd. Thomg's Structural and Physiological Botany, 6*. Thorpe's Quantitative Chemical Analysis, 4*. Gd, London, LONGMANS & CO. General Lists of New Works. Text-Books of Science— continued. Thoi-pe &, Muir's Qualitative Analysi3,'3*. 6d. Tildeu's Chemical Philosopliy, 3^. Gd. Unwin's Machine Design, Ss. Gd. Watson's Plane and Solid Geometry, Ss. 6d. Tyndall on Sound. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6(7. — Contributions to Molecular Physics. 8vo. IGs. — Fragments of Science. 2 vols, post 8vo. lG,s. — Heat a Mode of Motion. Crown 8vo. — Lectmes on Electrical Phenomena. Crown 8vo. Is. sewed, 1*. 6rf. cloth. — Lectures on Light. Crown 8vo. Is. sewed, 1*. 6d. cloth. — Lectui'es on Light delivered in America. Crown 8vo. 7s. Gd. — Lessons in Electricity. Crown 8vo. 2«. Gd. Von Cotta on Eocks, by Lawrence. Post 8vo. lis. Woodward's Geology of England and Wales. Crown 8vo. lis. Wood's Bible Animals. With 112 Vignettes. 8vo. 14i. — Homes Without Hands. Svo. 14s. — Insects Abroad. Svo. lis. — Insects at Home. With 700 Illustrations. Svo. lis. — Out of Doors, or Articles on Natural History. Cro-mi Svo. 7s. Gd. — Strange Dwellings. With 60 Woodcuts. Crown Svo. 7s. Gd. CHEMISTRY &. PHYSIOLOGY. Auerbach's Anthracen, translated by W. Ci-ookes, E.E.S. Svo. 12s. Buckton's Health in the House ; Lectm-es on Elementary Physiology. Cr. Svo. 2s. Crookes's Handbook of Dyeing and Calico Printing. Svo. i2s. — Select Methods in Chemical Analysis. Crown Svo. 12s. Gd. Kingzett's Animal Chemistry. Svo. 18s. — History, Products and Processes of the Alkali Trade. Svo. 12s. Miller's Elements of Chemistry, Theoretical and Practical. 3 vols. Svo. Part I. .Chemical Physics, 16s. Part II. Inorganic Chemistry, 24s. Part III. Organic Chemistry, New Edition in the press. Thudichum's Annals of Chemical Medicine. Vol. I. Svo. Watts's Dictionary of Chemistry. 7 vols, medium Svo. £10. 16s. Gd. — Third Supplementary Volume, in Two Parts. Part I. 36s. THE FINE ARTS & ILLUSTRATED EDITIONS. Bewick's Select Fables of .ffisop and others. Crown Svo. 7s. Gd. demy Svo. 18s. Doyle's Fau-yland ; Pictm-es from the EU- World. Folio, 15s. Dresser's Arts and Art Industries of Japan. [In preparation. Ingelow's Poems. Illustrated Edition. Fcp. 4to. Woodcuts, 21s. Jameson's Sacred and Legendary Art. 6 vols, square crown Svo. Legends of the Madonna. 1 vol. 21s. — — — Monastic Orders. 1 vol. 21s. — — — Saints and Martyrs. 2 vols. 31s. Gd. — — — Saviom-. Completed by Lady Eastlake. 2 vols. 42s. Longman's Three Cathedrals Dedicated to St. Paul. Square crovm Svo. 21s. Macaulay's Lays of Ancient Rome. With 90 Illustrations. Fcp. 4to. 21s. Macfarren's Lectures on Harmony. Svo. 12s. Miniature Edition of Macaulay's Lays of Ancient Eome. Imp. 16mo. 10s. Gd. Moore's Irish Melodies. With 161 Plates by D. Maclise, R.A. Super-royal Svo. 21s. — LaUa Rookh. Tenniel's Edition. With 68 Illustrations. Fcp. 4to. 10s. 6(7. London, LONGMANS & CO. ° General Lists of New Works. Northcote and Brownlow's Roma Sotterranea. 3 vols. 8vo. 58s. Perry on Greek and Roman Sculpture. 8vo. [In preparation. Redgrave's Dictionary of Artists of the English School. 8vo. ISs. THE USEFUL ARTS, MANUFACTURES &c. Bourne's Catechism of the Steam Engine. Fcp. 8vo. 6s. — Examples of Steam, Air, and Gas Engines. 4to. 70s. — Handbook of the Steam Engine. Fcp. 8vo. 9s. — Recent Improvements in the Steam Engine. Fcp. 8vo. Gs. — Treatise on the Steam Engine. 4to. 42s. Cresy's Encyclopaedia of Civil Engineering. 8vo. 42s. Cnlley's Handbook of Practical Telegraphy. 8vo. IGs. Eastlake's Household Taste in Fm-niture, &c. Square crown 8vo. 14.s. Fairbairn's Useful lufoiTuation for Engineers. 3 vols, crown 8vo. Zls. 6d. — Applications of Cast and Wrought Iron. 8vo. IGs. — Mills and Millwork, 1 vol. 8vo. 25*. Gwilt's Encyclopedia of Architecture. 8vo. 52s. Gd. Hobson's Amatem- Mechanics Practical Handbook. Crown Svo. is. Gd. Hoskold's Engineer's Valumg Assistant. Svo. 31s. Gd. Kerl's Metallurgy, adapted by Crookes and Rbhi-ig. 3 vols. 8vo. £i. 19s. Loudon's Encyclopeedia of Agriculture. Svo. 21s. — — — Gardening. Svo. 21s. Mitchell's Manual of Practical Assaying. Svo. 31s. Gd. Northcott's Lathes and Turning. Svo. 18s. Payen's Industrial Chemistiy, translated fi-om Stohmann and Engler's (Jennan Edition, by Dr. J. D. Bany. Edited by B. H. Paul, Ph.D. Svo. 42s. Piesse's Art of Perfumery. Fom-th Edition. Svo. Stoney's Theory of Strains in Girders. Roy. Svo. 36s. Thomas on Coal, Mine-Gases and Ventilation. Crown Svo. 10s. 6c/. Ure's Dictionary of Ai-ts, Manufactures, & Jlines. 4 vols, medium Svo. £7. 7s. VOle on Artificial Manures. By Crookes. Svo. 21s. RELIGIOUS 8c MORAL WORKS. Abbey & Overton's English Cbiirch in the Eighteenth Century. 2 vols. Svo. 36s. Arnold's (Rev. Dr. Thomas) Sermons. 6 vols, crown Svo. 5s. each. Bishop Jeremy Taylor's Entu-e Works. With Life by Bishop Heber. Edited by the Rev. C. P. Eden. 10 vols. Svo. £5. 6s. Boultbee's Commentary on the 39 Articles. Crown Svo. 6s. — History of the Church of England, Pre-Reformation Period. Svo. 15s. Browne's (Bishop) Exposition of the 39 Ai-ticles. Svo. 16s. Colenso's Lectures on the Pentateuch and the Moabite Stone. Svo. 12s. Colenso on the Pentateuch and Book of Joshua. Crown Svo. 6s. — — Part VII. completion of the larger Work. Svo. 24.$. Conder's Handbook of the Bible. Post Svo. 7s. Gd. Conybeaxe & Howson'sLife and Letters of St. Paiil : — Library Edition, with all the Original Illustrations, Maps, Landscapes on Steel, Woodcuts, &c. 2 vols. 4to. 42s. Intermediate Edition, -nith a Selection of Maps, Plates, and Woodcuts. 2 vols, square crown Svo. 21s. Student's Edition, revised and condensed, with 46 Illustrations and Maps. 1 vol. crown Svo. 9s. London, LONGMANS & CO. General Lists of New Works. 9 Drew's Hulsean Lectures on the Human Life of Christ. 8vo. 8s. Dmmmond's Jewish Messiah. 8vo. 15^. BUicott's (Bishop) Commentary on St. Paul's Epistles. 8vo. Galatians, Ss. Gd. Ephesians, 8s. Sd. Pastoral Epistles, 10^. 6d. Philippians, Colossians, and Philemon, 10*. 6d. Thessalonians, 7*. Gd. EUicott's Lectures on the Life of our Lord. 8vo. 12s. Ewald's History of Israel, translated by Carpenter. 5 vols. 8vo. 63*. — Antiquities of Israel, translated by Solly. 8vo. 12s. Gd. Hopkins's Christ the Consoler. Fcp. Svo. 2s. Gd. Jukes's Types of Genesis. Crown Svo, 7*. Gd. — Second Death and the Restitution of all Things. Crown Svo. 3*. Gd. Kalisch's Bible Studies. Part I. the Prophecies of Balaam. Svo. 10*. Gd. — — — Part II. the Book of Jonah. Svo. 10*. 6d, — Historical and Ci-itical Commentary on the Old Testament; with a New Translation. Vol. I. Genesis, Svo. 18*. or adapted for the Grcneral Header, 12*. Vol. II. Exodus, 15*. or adapted for the General Reader, 12*. Vol. III. Leviticus, Part I. 15*. or adapted for the General Reader, 8*. Vol. IV. Leviticus, Part II. 15*. or adapted for the General Reader, 8*. Keith's Evidence of the Truth of the Christian Religion derived from the Fulfil- ment of Prophecy. Square Svo. 12*. Gd. Post Svo. 6*. Kuenen on the Prophets and Prophecy in Israel. Svo. 21*. Lyra Germanica : Hymns translated by Miss "Winkworth. Fcp. Svo. 5*. Manning's Temporal Mission of the Holy Ghost. Svo. 8*. Gd. Martineau's Endeavours after the Christian Life. Crown Svo. 7*. Gd. — Hymns of Praise and Prayer. Crown Svo. 4*. Gd. 32mo. 1*. Gd. — Sermons ; Hours of Thought on Sacred Things. Crown Svo. 7*. Gd. Merivale's (Dean) Lectures on Early Church History. Crown Svo. 5*. MOl's Three Essays on Redigion. Svo. 10*. Gd. Monsell's Spiritual Songs for Sundays and Holidays. Fcp. Svo. 5*. 18mo. 2*. MuUer's (Max) Lectures on the Science of Religion. Crown Svo. 10*. Gd. Newman's Apologia pro Vita Sua. Crown Svo. 6*. O'Conor's New Testament Commentaries. Crown Svo. Epistle to the Romans, 3*. Gd. Epistle to the Hebrews, 4*. Gd. St. John's Gospel, 10*. Gd. One Hundred Holy Songs, &c. Square fcp. Svo. 2*. Gd. Passing Thoughts on Religion. By Miss Sewell. Fcp. Svo. 3*. Gd. SeweU's (Miss) Prepai-ation for the Holy Communion. 32mo. 3*. Supernatural Religion. Complete Edition. 3 vols. Svo. 36*. Thoughts for the Age. By Miss Sewell. Fcp. Svo. 3*. Gd. Vaughan's Trident, Crescent, and Cross ; the Religious History of India. 8vo.9*.6rf. Whately's Lessons on the Christian Evidences. ISmo. Gd. White's Four Gospels in Greek, with Greek-English Lexicon. 32mo. 5*. TRAVELS, VOYAGES &c. Baker's Rifle and the Hound in Ceylon. Crown Svo. 7s. Gd. — Eight Years in Ceylon. Crown Svo. 7*. Gd. Ball's Alpine Guide. 3 vols, post Svo. with Maps and Illustrations :— I. "Western Alps, 6*. Gd. II. Central Alps, 7*. Gd. III. Eastern Alps, 10*. Gd. BaU on Alpme Travelling, and on the Geology of the Alps, 1*. Bent's Freak of Freedom, or the Republic of San Mai-ino. Crown Svo. 7*. Gd. Brassey's Sunshine and Storm in the East. Svo. — Voyage in the Yacht ' Sunbeam.' Crown Svo. 7*. Gd. London, LONGMANS & CO. 10 General Lists of New Works. ^ Edwaxds's (A. B.) Thousand Miles up the Nile. Imperial 8vo. 42«. Hassall's San Remo and tUe Western Riviera. Crown 8vo. 10^. Gd. Indian Alps (The). By a Lady Pioneer. Imperial 8vo. 42«. Lefroy's Discovei-y and Early Settlement of the Bermuda Islands. 2 vols, royal 8vo. 60s. Mi'ller and Skertchley's Fenland Past and Present. Royal 8vo. 31,j. 6d. Large Paper, 50.S. Miller's Wintering in the Riviera. Post 8vo. Illustrations, 12*. Gd. Noble's Cape and South Africa. Fcp. 8vo. 3*. Gd. Packe's Guide to the Pyrenees, for Mountaineers. Crown 3vo. 7s. Gd. The Alpine Club Map of Switzerland. In Four Sheets. 42^. Wood's Discoveries at Ephesus. Imperial 8vo. 63s. WORKS OF FICTION. Becker's Charicles ; Private Life among the Ancient Greeks. Post 8vo. 7s. Gd. — Gallus ; Roman Scenes of the Time of Augustus. Post 8vo. 7*. 6d. Cabinet Edition of Stories and Tales by Miss Sewell :— Ivors, 2s. Gd. Katharine Ashton, 2s. Gd. Laneton Parsonage, 3s. Gd. Margai-et Percival, 3s. Gd. Ursula, 3s. Gd. the Earl of Beaconsfield, E.G. Cabinet crown 8vo. price £3. Hem-ietta Temple, Gs. Contarini Fleming, Gs. Ali-oy, Ixion, &c. Gs, The Young Duke, &c. Gs. Vivian Grey, Gs. Amy Herbert, 2s. Gd. Cleve Hall, 2s. Gd. The Earl's Daughter, 2s. Gd. Experience of Life, 2s. Gd. Gertrude, 2s. Gd. Novels and Tales by the Right Hon. Edition, complete in Ten Volumes, Lothair, Gs. Coningsby, Gs, Sybil, Gs. Tancred, 6*. Venetia, Gs. Klein's Pastor's Narrative. Translated by Marshall. Crown 8vo. Map. The Modern Novelist's Library. Each Work in crown 8vo. A Single Volume, oi-2s.Gd. cloth : — By Major Whyte-MelviUe. Digby Grand. General Bounce. Kate Coventry. The Gladiators. Good for Nothing. Holmby House. The Intei-preter. The Queen's Maries. By the Author of ' the Atelier du Lys.' Mademoiselle Mori. The Atelier du Lys. By Various Writers. Atherstone Priory. The Bm-gomaster's Family. Elsa and her Vulture. / complete in itself, price 2^. boards, By the Earl of Beaconsfield, K.G. Lothair. Coningsby. Sybil. Tancred. Venetia. Hemrietta Temple. Contarini Fleming. Alroy, Ixion, &c. The Young Duke, &c. Vivian Grey. By Anthony TroUope. Barchester Towers. The Warden. By the Author of ' the Rose Garden.' Unawares. The Six Sisters of the Valleys. Lord Beaconsfield's Novels and Tales. 10 vols, cloth extra, gUt edges, 30s. Whispers from Fairy Land. By the Right Hon. E. H. KnatchbuU-Hugessen M.P. With Nine lUustrations. Crown 8vo. 3.J. Gd. Higgledy-Piggledy ; or, Stories for Everybody and Everybody's Children. By the Right Hon. E. H. KnatchbuU-Hugessen, M.P. With Nine Illustrations from Designs by R. Doyle. Crown 8vo. 3s. Gd. London, LONGMANS & CO. General Lists of New Works. 11 POETRY 8c THE DRAMA. Bailey's Festus, a Poem. Crown 8vo. 12«. 6d. Bowdler's Family Shakspeare. Medium 8vo. lis, 6 vols. fcp. 8vo. 21*. Cayley's Iliad of Homer, Homometrically translated. 8vo. 12s, Gd. Conington's ^neid of Virgil, translated into English Verse. Crown 8vo. 9*. Cooper's Tales from Euripides. Fcp. 8vo. 3s, Gd. Edwards's Poetry-Book of Elder Poets. 16mo. 2*. Gd. — Poetry-Book of Modern Poets. 16mo. 2s. 6d. Ingelow's Poems. New Edition. 2 toIs. fcp. 8vo. 12s. Macaulay's Lays of Ancient Rome, with Ivry and the Armada. 16mo. 3^. 6d. Ormsby's Poem of the Cid. Translated. Post 8vo. 5s. Petrarch's Sonnets and Stanzas,translated by C. B. Cayley, B. A. Crown Svo.lOs.Gd. Southey's Poetical Works. Medium 8vo. 14.!. Yonge's Horatii Opera, Library Edition. 8vo. 21*. RURAL SPORTS, HORSE & CATTLE MANAGEMENT &c. Blaine's Encyclopsedia of Rural Sports. 8vo. 21s, Dobson on the Ox, his Diseases and their Treatment. Crown 8vo. 7*. 6d. Francis's Book on Angling, or Treatise on Fishing. Post 8vo. 15^ Malet's Annals of the Road, and Nimrod's Essays on the Road. Medium 8vo. 21s. Miles's Horse's Foot, and How to Keep it Sound. Imperial 8vo. 12s. 6d, — Plain Treatise on Horse-Shoeing. Post 8vo. 2s. Gd, — Stables and Stable-Fittings. Imperial 8vo. 15s, — Remarks on Horses' Teeth. Post 8vo. Is. 6d, Nevile's Horses and Riding. Crown 8vo. 6*. Reynardson's Down the Road. Medium 8vo. 21.S. Ronalds's Fly-Fisher's Entomology. Bvo. 14.?. Stonehenge's Dog in Health and Disease. Square crown 8vo. 7s. 6d. — Greyhound. Square crown 8vo. 15.S. Yonatt's Work on the Dog. 8vo. Gs. — _ _ _ Horse. 8vo. 12*. Gd. Wilcocks's Sea-Fisherman. Post 8vo. 12*. Gd. WORKS OF UTILITY & GENERAL INFORMATION. Acton's Modern Cookery for Private Families. Fcp. 8vo. 6s. Black's Practical Treatise on Brewing. 8vo. 10*. Gd. Buckton's Food and Home Cookery. Crown 8vo. 2*. Bull on the Maternal Management of Children. Fcp. 8vo. 2*. Gd. Bull's Hints to Mothers on the Management of their Health during the Period of Pregnancy and in the Lying-in Room. Fcp. 8vo. 2*. Gd. Campbell- Walker's Con-ect Card, or How to Play at Whist. Fcp. Svo. 2*. Gd. Crump's EugUsh Manual of Banking. Svo. 15*. Cunningham's Conditions of Social Well-Being. Svo. 10*. Gd. Handbook of Gold and Silver, by an Indian Official. Svo. 12*. Gd. Johnson's (W. & J. H.) Patentee's Manual. Fourth Edition. Svo. 10*. Gd. Longman's Chess Openings. Fcp. Svo. 2*. Gd. Macleod's Economics for Beginners. Small crown Svo. 2*. Gd. London, LONGMANS & CO. 12 General Lists of New Works. Macleod's Theory and Practice of Banking. 2 vols. 8vo. 26*. — Elements of Banking. Fourth Edition. Crown 8vo. 5s. M'CuUoch's Bictiouary of Commerce and Commercial Navigation. 8vo. 63«. Maunder's Biogi-aphical Treasnry. Fop. Svo. 6s. — Historical Ti-easiiry. Fcp, Svo. 6*. — Scientific and Literary Treasury. Fcp. Svo. 6*. — Treasury of Bible Knowledge. Edited by the Rev. J. Ayre, M.A. Fcp. Svo. 6i. — Treasury of Botany. Edited by J. Lindley, F.R.S. and T. Moore, F.L.S. Two Parts, fcp. Svo. 12s. — Treasury of Geography. Fcp. Svo. 6s. — Treasury of Knowledge and Library of Eeference. Fcp. Svo. Gs. — Treasuiy of Natiu-al History. Fcp. Svo. 6s. Pereira's Materia Medica, by Bentley and Redwood. Svo. 25$. Pewtuer's Comprehensive Specifier ; Building-Artificers' Work. Conditions and Agreements. Crown Svo. 6s. Pierce's Three Hundred Chess Problems and Studies. Fcp. Svo. 7s. 6d. Pole's Theory of the Modern Scientific Game of Whist. Fcp. Svo. 2^. 6d. Scott's Farm Valuer. Crown Svo. 5s. — Rents and Purchases. Crown Svo. 6.s. Smith's Handbook for Mid wives. Crown Svo. 5^. The Cabinet La^vyer, a Popular Digest of the Laws of England. Fcp. Svo. 9*. West on the Diseases of Infancy and Childhood. Svo. 1S«. WiUich's Popular Tables for ascertaining the Value of Property. Post Svo. 10«. Wilson on Banking Reform. Svo. Is. 6d. — on the Resources of Modern Countries 2 vols. Svo. 24^. MUSICAL WORKS BY JOHN HULLAH, LL.D. Chromatic Scale, with the Inflected Syllables, on Large Sheet. 1^. 6d. Card of Chromatic Scale. Id. Exercises for the Cultivation of the Voice. For Soprano or Tenor, 2^. 6d. Grammar of Musical Harmony. Royal Svo. 2 Parts, each Is. 6d. Exercises to Grammar of Musical Harmony. \s. Grammar of Coimterpoint. Part I. super-royal Svo. 2s. 6d. Hullah's Manual of Singing. Parts I. & II. 2^. 6d. ; or together, 5s. Exercises and Figures contained in Parts I. and II. of the Manual. Books I. & n. each SfZ. Large Sheets, containing the Figures in Part I. of the Manual. Nos. 1 to 8 in a Parcel. 6^. Large Sheets, containing the Exercises in Part I. of the Manual. Noa. 9 to 40, in Fom- Parcels of Eight Nos. each, per Parcel. 6s. Large Sheets, the Figures in Part II. Nos. 41 to 52 in a Parcel, 9j. Hymns for the Young, set to Music. Royal Svo. %d. Infant School Songs. 6d. Notation, the Musical Alphabet. Crown Svo. 6d. Old English Songs for Schools, Harmonised. 6d. Rudiments of Musical Grammar. Royal Svo. 3*. School Songs for 2 and 3 Voices. 2 Books, Svo. each 6d. Time and Tune in the Elementary School. Crown Svo. 2s. 6rf. Exercises and Figures in the same. Crown Svo. 1*. or 2 Parts, 6d each. London, LONGMANS & CO. SjpottisKiude <& Co., Printers, New-street Square, Loudon.. (pi THE LIBRARY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Santa Barbara STACK COLLECTION THIS BOOK IS DUE ON THE LAST DATE STAMPED BELOW. 10w-5,'65(F4458s4)476D vHifi^iilii^^^i'^miiii:,