ool Addresses on of Social Work acCunn ^.^ ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK BY THE SAME AUTHOR. ETHICS OF CITIZENSHIP. Fourth Ed. 1907. James MacLehose & Son. THE MAKING OF CHARACTER. Fifth Ed. 1908. At the University Press, Cambridge. SIX RADICAL THINKERS. BENTHAM, J. S. MILL, COBDEN, CARLYLE, MAZZINI, T. H. GREEN. Second Impression, 1910. Edward Arnold, London. LIVERPOOL ADDRESSES ON ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK BY JOHN MAGGUNN, M.A., LL.D., Emeritus Professor of Philosophy in the University of Liverpool. LIVERPOOL THE UNIVERSITY PRESS: 57, ASHTON STREET LONDON CONSTABLE & COMPANY LTD. 1911 Printed at the DAILY POST AND MERCURY Printing Works, Fleet Street, Liverpool. To JAMES W. ALSOP, Esq. MY DEAR ALSOP, Will you allow me to inscribe this volume to you as a small tribute from a friend who has for many years watched your public life with respect and admiration, and who has had many opportunities of appreciating the magnitude of your services, and the sincerity of your devotion to the City of Liverpool and its University. Believe me, Sincerely yours, JOHN MAcCUNN. March 10, 1911. PREFACE. Addresses V. and VII. of the following have already been published by the Associations to which they were delivered. Some pages of VIII. have already appeared in " The Making of Character " ; and my thanks are due to the Syndics of the Cambridge Press for permission to reproduce them here. VI. and VII. were also printed for private circulation amongst their members by the Societies concerned. It is perhaps also desirable to say that Section III. includes two consecutive addresses, lest the reader should suspect the author of an over- estimate of the endurance of audiences. CONTENTS. I. MOTIVES TO SOCIAL WORK. II. SOCIAL MOTIVE AND DEMOCRATIC EDUCATION. III. JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES TO SOCIAL WORK. IV. CITIZENSHIP AND IDEAL INTERESTS. V. LOCAL PATRIOTISM AND EDUCATION. VI. POLITICAL PARTY AND POLITICAL CONVICTION. VII. THE TEACHING OF RELIGION AND THE ART OF EDUCATION. VIII. ETHICAL THEORY AND PRACTICE. I.-MOTIVES TO SOCIAL WORK.* It is not for a moment to be supposed that the only members of the community who render social service are those who of set purpose disinterestedly undertake it. Every man, whether he intend it or not, serves his generation by doing his own work, provided he does it well. With the vast majority indeed this is the main con- sideration. They do not often lift their thoughts to any end so large as the public good, or even the good of any considerable social group. They think first, and often enough they think last, of livelihood, of provision for those near and dear to them, of their good name, of the kind of work they are turning out, of well-earned rest when their working days are done. Nor are they, on this account, to be stigmatised as selfish. It is a perversion of fact, though some social censors and satirists and even some social analysts have been guilty of it, to vilify the ordinary battle of life as if it were a predatory "Addresses I. to III. were delivered to the Liverpool School of Social Science and Social Work. i ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK struggle, a " cut-purse and cut-throat scramble," in which each, regardless of each, fights fiercely for his own hand. On the contrary, it is the family rather than the isolated individual that is the true social unit. And most men work so habitually, so ungrudgingly, so patiently for kith and kin, or for friends and connections, that it would be a misnomer, not to say a libel, to brand their motives as " selfish." But though not selfish, these motives of the mass of men are nevertheless private. If society struggles and staggers forwards with an indomitable vitality, this is not because the average man makes the public good his conscious and direct aim. In a social system, still strongly- rooted in family life, in private property and inheritance, in industrial and professional com- petition, the vitality of the body politic, which is ever bearing us on towards ends greater than we know, comes from the many millions who go forth to their manifold toil till the evening, and who, in fulfilling that commonplace though honourable destiny, look little or not at all beyond the limited range of private interests. That stalwart individualist John Stuart Mill predicted the coming of a day when a common man would dig or weave consciously for his country's good as well as fight for it. And Ruskin eloquently prophesied that trade must have its heroisms and the market its sacrifices no less than war. But that day is not yet. The individualistic analysis, if not too atomistically MOTIVES TO SOCIAL WORK 3 interpreted, still holds true at any rate over wide tracts of our national life. Nor is it to be forgotten that there are many vocations in which deliberately unselfish motives are so inextricably interwoven with the push of private interests that it is often hard to say which are paramount. Our public officials, our doctors, nurses, teachers, ministers of religion, all work deliberately and of set purpose for the good of others. They serve the city and the State, they administer justice, they relieve suffering, they diffuse knowledge, they make character, they uplift the fallen, they console the sorrowful. Gratefully one renders tribute to their splendid and unobtrusive self-sacrifice. But we neither ask nor expect that their self-sacrifice should be selfless. Do they not love their vocation? Do they not value their reputation? Do they not work for and cherish their honourable independence? In truth, the very point that makes these callings enviable is that, in them, the passion for social work joins hands so happily with personal pride and absorption in a chosen vocation. And yet of course there is another kind of social work, and other motives than these. This lies upon the surface. For though the society we live in is fortunately not lacking in vigour and vitality, nothing can be more certain than that a given society can manifest much vigour and vitality, and yet be far from a satisfactory state of social health. This is a fact we are not suffered I, ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK to forget. For if there be one feature of the latter half of the igth century more conspicuous than another, is it not that, during that period, our reformers and moralists, our dispassionate social researchers, our satirists, and not least our socialists, have been busy with tongue and pen opening our eyes to the miseries, hardships, degradations, dangers, which mar and menace our social system, and which all its prodigious vitality and all its astonishing prosperity have hitherto proved unequal to throw off? With social vitality it is too true a tale comes social disease. The bane, however, has brought the antidote. It has at any rate brought one antidote in that rapid expansion of voluntary effort and agency for social betterment which has taken form and a body in our endlessly diversified charities, our conferences, congresses and leagues, our settlements and schools of social science and social work. Need it be added that the same clear call for remedy appears, ever increasingly, in our legislative programmes, and in that competition for remedy between State action and voluntary effort which, by its very rivalries, marks the collapse of the bygone fool's paradise that the health of the social organism can be left to take care of itself. The result is matter of common knowledge. In the camps of individualism, as well as those of socialism, we meet the settled conviction that it will never be well with our MOTIVES TO SOCIAL WORK i country until its citizens, and as many of them as possible, pass far beyond the narrow pale of private interests and make the public good, in one or other of its manifold departments, their deliberate, conscious, and direct aim. And with this conviction has come the emergence of motives to social work in the stricter and more definite sense of the words. Now these motives are many and diverse, and they are of course exceedingly unequal in depth, force, and steadiness in different individuals. But it seems possible to single out those which are salient, and may be found operating in the actual community of which we are members. It is no disparagement of human nature to say, to begin with, that of these motives one is Fear. This, indeed, is only what one might expect. For most movements for social better- ment have, as their shadow, an element of menace. In other words, they are commonly accompanied by pictures, sometimes highly rhetorical, sometimes conjured up by the un- adorned eloquence of facts, of the miseries, hardships, and wrongs that need redress, and forecasts, sometimes threatening enough, of what will happen if nothing is done. And these fore- bodings for society never lacks its Cassandras take many forms. Early in the iQth century the alarm was political revolution. Then, under Malthusian influence, it was over-population. Nowadays, when biology and physiology have had their say, it is rather physical and moral 6 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK degeneracy and the congested squalor of great cities. But there are, of course, many alarms besides these, alarms of industrial conflict, failure of employment, commercial defeat, pauperism, attacks on property, decay of the family, popular ignorance, intemperance, inordinate luxury, decline of national character, religious infidelity, and so on. Nor, in view of the grim catalogue, is it too much to say that in the igth century democracy has come into its kingdom to find that its kingdom is a damnosa hereditas of difficulties that seem likely to put it to the proof. It is a natural result that many persons, and by no means only those who are pessimists or alarmists, go about haunted by all manner of vague fears of impending catastrophes. Now it need not be suggested that these vague fears have ever of themselves done much to prompt social work. General alarms are singularly impotent to create concrete service. Did fear of national degeneracy ever yet produce an officer of health ? Did fear of pauperism ever yet inspire a single guardian of the poor? And yet fear has its place : indirectly, and in associa- tion with other things, it is certainly far from impotent. One may see this in politics and legislation. Fear for the future of one's country, it has been well said, is heroic virtue ; and so must it ever be, so long as it is no small part of the statesman's work to dissipate alarms and restore confidence. More potent still is the fear that attaches itself MOTIVES TO SOCIAL WORK j to some definite institution that is believed to be in danger. Conspicuously so when menaces rouse the strong resentful instincts of alarmed resistance. The instinct may be often enough unreasoning and obstructive; but that is no ground for denying it the title to be ranked as a motive to social work. Especially, of course, when the threatened institution is one that has enlisted time-honoured loyalties and affections. Let but a man's Church be assailed, or his trading Company, or his Trades Union, or his School or University does not indifference shake off its apathy and develop a militant energy that astonishes the world? It would be sheer blind- ness to overlook the volume of passion and effort that is poured into public questions by the conservative instincts of society; and in these conservative instincts fear is no small element. Let none withhold his tribute from even the champions of lost causes. They have not lived in vain, even if they have done no more than stir the stagnant waters of political apathy. And yet, when fear thus plays its part, it need not receive more than its due. For that part is after all but partial, because it is only the negative side of a positive loyalty and attachment to institutions. It is this that gives it substance,^ this that nerves it to effort and sustains it in work; this that makes all the difference between the mere political nervousness which fears it knows not what, and the fear which has become a just solicitude for the fate of something a man 8 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK believes worth having and living for. The truth is that human affairs are always sufficiently precarious to render it impossible to care much for anything without some dash of fears. Nor is the best citizen the man with the fewest fears for his country's institutions. But with him the fear is only the shadow; the loyalty, the attach- ment, is the substance. Fortunately this motive this positive loyalty and attachment to institutions is one upon which in most countries, and in. none more than our own, we can confidently reckon. Its object may vary. It may be a village club or a political party; a local school or a national church. But in one form or another the motive is widespread, persistent, and effective. This is only what one might expect. For, in an old and complex social system like ours, it early dawns upon the minds of its members (the lesson is begun even in school days) that he who would act with effect must act in association. Individual isolation is soon seen to be the straight path to individual impotence. Hence the institutions small and great, new and old, which diversify English society from end to end. And, then, an institution, be it remembered, is no mere bit of social fabric, no mere piece of social mechanism. If it be not decadent or dead, it is a meeting-point, a centre of convergence for human wills which have united in a living partnership for carrying out the ends, whatever they may be, for which the institution stands. MOTIVES TO SOCIAL WORK < For while of course every institution has its material and outward embodiment (buildings, offices, equipment, officials, balance-sheets, and so forth), these are not its essence. Its essence is that it is the vehicle of some plan, project, or purpose upon which its members unite, and into which they put a bit of their lives.* And just for that reason no institution with which men are in earnest can long exist without evoking those feelings of loyalty and even affection which prompt its members to spend and be spent in its service. We often talk of supporting institu- tions; and no one need quarrel with the phrase; but it sometimes hides the further fact that institutions support us. No one is likely to deny it who reflects what a Church or a Charity or a political Party does for its members, not only in opening up lines of action, nor yet in catching them up into a larger and more enduring life, which persists while generations come and go, but in furnishing a permanent object by which the motives to effort may be fed, steadied, and sustained. It is needless to labour the point. Few will deny that the men of most service to their generation are those who throw in their lot whole-heartedly with institutions. So true is this that it is only too possible to love institutions not wisely but too well. Nothing is easier than to find, in any large community, men and women to whom their particular church or chapel, or school or political club, or trades * See some luminous pages in Boe&nquet's " Philosophical Theory of the State," p. 170. B io ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK union or charity is the one thing beyond their private interests that fills their lives. So far good; nor could society spare the type. But such persons have the defects of their qualities. They lose the larger outlook. The many- sidedness and rich perspective of social life and effort escapes them. All's well with the world, if only the institution on which their hearts are set is prosperous; nothing is well, the very heavens are darkened, if its prosperity suffers even a passing eclipse. One can easily forgive the limitations of these single-minded folk for the sake of their devotion : but it is limitation none the less. But if experience tells us this, it also tells us where lie the antidotes. For the motive of loyalty to institutions can manifestly be intensified and enlarged in two directions. It can be broadened into civic patriotism; and it can be at once vitalised and humanised by a recognition of the worth and claims of the individual man. We must look at these in turn. The distinctive note of civic patriotism, as found in its best types, is that it lifts its eyes beyond particular and sectional interests to the well-being of the city, or the State, as a whole. Of this it habitually thinks; for this it habitually works. This does not mean that the best citizen is the man of most varied activities. Far from it. For the good citizen knows well that, as price of his efficiency, he must bend to the iron law of division of labour under which the MOTIVES TO SOCIAL WORK n world's work can alone be done. He soon discovers that he must choose his line, and concentrate his energies as his preferences, aptitudes, opportunities, may prescribe, be it public health, housing of the poor, education, finance, charity, or what not. But then this specialised activity need never obscure the comprehensive outlook that embraces many if not all the ends for which a great city, and still more a great nation, exists. And this is much. For in the light of this larger view, the one- sidedness and exaggerations, the narrowness and even the fanaticism of sectional effort are at an end, and in their place comes the sanity of purpose, the willingness to give and take in the furtherance of one's own pet projects, the readiness to recognise the work of fellow-citizens in other lines than our own all which are amongst the fruits of the genuine civic spirit. Nor need the larger outlook bring any abate- ment of that emotional fervour which particular institutions enlist, and which is sometimes supposed to evaporate as interests widen. Con- trariwise. For there is something in the very thought of a great city, with its struggling, suffering, transient yet on the whole victorious life, which touches the imagination and the heart. Who can doubt it who recalls Words- worth's sonnet on London from Westminster Bridge, or Carlyle's picture, seen as by flash of lightning, of W eissnichtwo at night, or Alexander Smith's noble invocation to Glasgow 12 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK " City ! I am true son of thine, Ne'er dwelt I where great mornings shine Around the bleating pens : Ne'er by the rivulets I strayed, And ne'er upon my childhood weighed The silence of the glens. Instead of shore where ocean beats I hear the ebb and flow of streets." It is sometimes said that local patriotism as an emotion is dying out. So it is, perhaps, as the mere habitual sentiment for locality. But so it is not, if it is the feeling, not unknown to those who have lived and worked in a great city, that is stirred by the sense of the magnitude and unwearying energy of that corporate life which sweeps into the central currents of its course so many ends for which men give their lives. This is not the furthest. In these days, when, both in idea and in fact, the spirit of nationality and empire is to the front, there is, of course, a patriotism which lifts its eyes beyond the city, and which, far from being the monopoly of political imperialists, is deeply-rooted in the ordinary citizen, who is quite ready unobtrusively to play his part, when some national catastrophe has made calls on his purse, or when war or menace of war has made proof of his courage. Yet the fact remains that it is in work done for and in the city that the social motives are mainly vitalised. For the service of the city has advantages which are peculiarly its own. Its problems are more forcibly and definitely before our eyes, they even stare us in the face, MOTIVES TO SOCIAL WORK 13 every day we live. And our local plans, experiments, and solutions are, to an extent impossible on the wider stage, our own to devise, to watch, to criticise, to control. And, however great the elation of the humble elector proudly conscious that he is playing his part in world- politics, it is, speaking broadly, in the smaller arena of city life and in the actual service of local institutions that he feels most and does most for the public good. Yet this civic spirit may easily stop short of its best. There is a type of citizen whose interest in local institutions is real and many-sided. He likes public work, he finds it absorbing, lively, even in its way amusing. What he wishes for is to see local institutions well administered. Efficiency, something of the efficiency he prides himself upon in his private business, is his dominant note. He wishes, in short, to carry into public work a business-like ideal ; and so long as he gets that, he does not think much, or at all (outside of his own small private circle) of individual lives. Possibly he has not the sympathy or the imagination to picture what is actually going on in the obscure courts and alleys and endless monotonous streets of mean brick tenements. Very likely his feet may never have crossed the threshold of one struggling or indigent home : very likely he might feel out-of- place and ill at ease if he went there. Not for a moment is he to be undervalued on that account. It is quite as common for men to be ill-fitted to 14 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK come into personal relations with the poor as with the world of rank and fashion. But what of that? These men do admirable work. Many an institution is deep in their debt. Nor is it in the least doubtful that they number amongst them not a few of the most energetic and effective benefactors of every great city. But there are others whose interest takes a different direction. These are the people whose thoughts run first of all to individual lives, to their struggles and sufferings, their toils obscure, their precarious fortunes, their unheeded failures and successes. Their prime interest, in short, centres in the drama of human life, and it is this intensely human interest in persons that really vitalises all the service they give to political or social or religious movements. The motive of persons of this kind may, however, assume various and fairly distinguish- able forms. Thus it may be, especially in its beginnings, almost purely emotional. It may be simple natural pity for suffering or sympathy with hardship, and nothing more nothing more except the impulse to rush to the rescue. So far, it is perhaps not not in these days of charity organisers held in much repute. And, of course, it has its obvious defects. It is precipitate, undis- criminating, sometimes sentimental, frequently gullible, and often highly mischievous so mischievous that social reformers spend much breath and ink in branding it as the sin that is not to be forgiven. MOTIVES TO SOCIAL WORK 15 But it is not the instinct of pity that is at fault, nor the sympathy with suffering. Will anyone contend that there is too much pity and sympathy in the world? Will anyone aver that the world is too tender-hearted? One wishes it were. For in that case there would be larger opportunities of dealing with this emotional motive in the right way. And the right way, one ventures to think, is not to set about to kill it, or even to discredit it, but to deepen it, and thereby to raise it to the rank of an incentive which society could ill afford to neglect, so long as feeling and who will deny it? lies close to the springs of action. Emotion without ideas may be blind and reckless, but ideas, however just and reasonable, without emotion are barren. How then is this emotional motive deepened? The answer is that it is deepened by a belief which may be truly said to lie at the roots of Western civilisation the belief in the worth, the potential worth at any rate, of the individual life. For this belief is no mere tenet of reformers, far less of visionaries. On the contrary, it has been wrought into the very texture of the consciousness of the community by some of the most potent agencies that can operate on human nature. Have not the churches been preaching it, and (within limits) acting upon it, since the Christian era? Have not jurists, legislators, and administrators been building it solidly into the massive fabric of Law and 16 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK Justice? Has not the cause of popular education been inspired by it, ever since Pestalozzi worked his wonders with his wretched waifs? Has not charitable effort, in all its many modes, been bearing witness to it by insisting, full in the face of appearances, upon finding worth even in the " worthless " ? Has not democracy recognised it as at once root and fruit of reforming energy? We may, of course, speculate and argue as to what this belief actually means. Members of different philosophical schools may seek out the grounds of its justification. But at any rate the belief is there, strongly held and powerful enough to have prompted the ascription to even the least among the sons of men, even to the slave and savage, of a value with which no serious thinker would dream of endowing even the highest of the animals. It is through this belief that the natural motive of pity has been deepened, and through alliance with it that the resulting motive has assumed a higher and, we may add, an intensified form. This becomes evident if we ask a quite simple question : Why is it that to any ordinary citizen of our day the sufferings of a fellow-man have an immeasurably stronger claim upon him than the sufferings of an animal ? The fact will not be disputed : if not, what is the explanation ? Not surely the contention, which might be difficult to make good, that the mere suffering of a man is greater than that of an animal; but the fact that the miseries of a man have a far MOTIVES TO SOCIAL WORK 17 deeper, and in truth a tragic significance, because, beyond the mere quantum of suffering, they may obstruct and even blight a life which might otherwise be decent, self-respecting, and worth living. It may be enough to ask about the animals, as Bentham said it was, " not can they reason, or can they talk, but can they suffer?" But this is precisely what it is not enough to ask about a man. For the sufferings of the human lot are never seen in their true light, and never sufficiently hated, till it is recognised that human suffering would not be the hateful thing it is if it did not so grievously obstruct and choke the capacities and struggles for a better life. Now this, it may be, is not a view that many people formulate. But mankind are actuated by motives long before they put them into formulae. So here. This conviction of the value of the individual life is too deeply rooted to have to plead for recognition. It has won recognition. Religion, Law, Education, political and social Democracy, Charitable effort are, as we have said, its sponsors. Nor is there any feature of our Western civilisation more striking than the tenacity with which this belief holds its ground in the best minds, not only in face of the cynics, satirists, and pessimists who decry the human species, but (a far greater thing) in face of the dreary array of ugly facts upon which these " devil's-advocates " of mankind subsist. There is a passage in the " Anthropology " of Kant in which that great philosopher quotes i8 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK a remark which Frederick the Great once made to the optimist, Sulzer : " My dear Sulzer ! you little " know to what an accursed race we belong." Is it not significant, and an uncommon tribute to the strength of the conviction of human worth, that it was the man who quoted those words who held and taught, more confidently than any thinker of either the ancient or the modern world, the doctrine of the dignity of every rational soul? Results upon motives follow. For wherever and in whatever form this conviction is held, it transforms the attitude to human hardship and suffering. And it does this by regarding them, no longer as mere afflictions, but as hindrances. It is not mere pity for suffering that is uppermost now : it is sympathy (and the more of it the better) not unmixed with respect for the kind of men and women who suffer that practical respect at any rate which goes to work in the belief that those who have claims upon our help are every one of them worth helping. Hence this motive readily becomes dis- criminating, as the merely emotional motive notoriously is not. For it is not of the mere amount of suffering, nor is it of the mere relief of misery, that the man who truly has this motive thinks first of all. He may even find room for the reflection that great suffering unrelieved has often enough been the rocky road to endurance and heroism. What really concerns him, and evokes his passionate sympathy is that kind of suffering whose relief is the removal of MOTIVES TO SOCIAL WORK 19 obstructions. Pitiful enough he may be, and tender-hearted to the verge of weakness; but when it comes to action, he is of like mind to a certain great surgeon, one of the most tender- hearted of men, who once said that with him pity as an emotion had to cease in order that pity as a rnotive might do its work. It is in this way that claims upon our compassion are transformed into claims upon our help, so that the deeply-rooted human instinct to rush to the relief of suffering or the righting of wrong becomes the settled resolve to emancipate fellow-citizens, whether by legislation or private effort, from the manifold obstructions of vice, disease, poverty, ignorance, thoughtless- ness, which in diabolical alliance baffle the forward-struggling strivings of the human spirit. Nor is this a result other than what one might, on reflection, expect to find. The motives that prompt a man to work for his fellows, whether in public life or otherwise, must sooner or later be vitally influenced by his ideas of what the people really are for whom his work is done. And so long as he holds to the belief that there is not one of his fellows, unless exceptionally brutalised by vice and crime, but has in him the making of a better man, he is not likely to flag for lack of motive. Indeed, it is precisely the wide acceptance of this doctrine that may be said to make the modern social problem difficult by a vast expansion of the area of recognised social obligations. For 30 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK though it must be admitted (it is a truism) that the civic patriotism of the ancient world, especially, of course, the Greek world, was more intense and highly developed in many ways than that of a modern Englishman, it is never to be forgotten that our inferiority is due to our aiming at a larger and far more difficult thing. For when all is said, the Greek civic spirit was narrow. It knew much of the rights of reason for the select minority : it knew nothing of the rights of man for the mass. " Like ours it looked in outward air, Its head was clear and true ; Sumptious its clothing, rich its fare, No pause its action knew ; Stout was its arm, each thew and bone Seemed puissant and alive But ah ! its heart, its heart was stone, And so it could not thrive." No; its heart was not stone. Who can doubt that it felt, and passionately enough, for kith and kin and friends and fellow-citizens? It was only that its heart was narrow, or at any rate not large enough to find a place for that vast misery and welter of servile life upon which the shining citizenship of Athens, like its glorious Parthenon on the unhewn native rock, was built. In the modern world we have at any rate tried {not always successfully) to improve upon that. For whatever be the cleavages of classes, the modern city and nation have certainly accepted responsibilities for the entire community without respect of classes or persons. It is even becoming MOTIVES TO SOCIAL WORK 21 trite to say that, in these days democratic, the community must stand altogether if it stand at all, and move altogether if it move at all. And in this respect we may claim, without vain-glory, that the public spirit of an Englishman of our day as far surpasses that of an ancient Greek in the comprehensiveness of its humanity as that of an ancient Greek no doubt surpassed his in the closeness of the bond which made the individual one with the State. It is the belief in the worth of the individual life that makes the difference. The contrast has become possible because the most insignificant and poverty- stricken day-labourer, not to say the most abject pauper and contemptible wastrel, is recognised as having claims not only on our compassion, but upon reasonable sympathy and practical effort claims which would, there is little doubt, have filled a Greek of the age of Pericles with incredulity and derision. The merit, amongst many a demerit, of our modern ideal of citizen- ship is that it tries to hold fast to what is best in both views, to emulate the intensity of that ancient civic spirit, and to widen it to multitudes who lay quite outside the close Athenian pale. Nor can one better describe the social problem of our day than by saying that it has accepted the task of uniting the patriotic civic spirit of the aristocratic Greek republic with the more inclusive, and more truly human, spirit of the democratic city and nation. II-SOCIAL MOTIVE AND DEMOCRATIC EDUCATION. If what has been said above be true, the motives to social work which may already be found in our midst are at their best when loyal attachment to institutions is, on the one hand, broadened into civic patriotism, and, on the other, intensified and humanised by sympathy. Not, however, by a mere emotional sympathy, but by natural compassion deepened and moralised by that belief in the worth of the individual man which has taken root, despite all discouragements, in the consciousness and institutions of Western peoples. With these motives before us, two problems emerge. The one, which is not only practical but urgent, is educational. How are these motives to be intensified where strong, strengthened where weak, and evoked where lacking this is the educational question. For it is not the business of the social reformer to discover, or invent, new motives. This must DEMOCRATIC EDUCATION 23 be left to the prophets and leaders of mankind who, at rare and incalculable epochs, confer upon the world the incomparable gift of a great new incentive. For the ordinary reformer it is enough to make the most of the materials he finds ready to his hand. Nor, if we pause to reflect how woefully the world falls short of what these available motives already are in the best types, is he likely soon to exhaust his task. The second problem is of a different kind. How are these motives to be justified, how are they to prove their sanity and reasonableness this, which may be called the philosophical question, though it greatly concerns many besides philosophers, is a no less important, though a less urgent, enquiry than the first. It will be dealt with in the sequel. The educational problem may, however, assume a lesser or a larger aspect. In its lesser aspect it concentrates all its energies upon a comparative few, those public- spirited folk, namely, who (be they professionals or voluntary workers) are already willing and even eager to make the public good, in one or other of its many aspects, their direct aim. Such persons are manifestly good material so good, in fact, that there is no doubt whatever that they can be made better. For the literature of social pathology, never nearly so copious as now, can effectually open their eyes to the maladies of society; and initiation into practical work, under organised expert guidance, can give to their 24 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK reading a reality such as the mere notional knowledge got from books can never impart. And with this may easily go it is part of the programme of this School and of other Schools like it a study of the methods whereby, in our own and other countries, social sympathy may best translate itself into good works, as well as of those economic and political facts and forces with which all genuine reform has inevitably to reckon. Nor is it Utopian to predict that, as these Schools of Social Training gain recruits, every great city like this will number amongst its citizens many men and women well qualified to grapple with those questions in which they already feel so keen an interest. Yet this is not enough. The larger, the far larger, educational problem lies behind, and it is one that cannot be ignored. In point of fact, it is forced upon our generation by two political movements of the first magnitude the one, the advent of democracy, the other, the change that has passed upon the spirit and aspirations of democracy during the past half-century. For it is a truism to say that democracy has come. ' The tramp of its myriad feet is on all " our thoroughfares," as Carlyle said years ago. And democracy, of course, means (amongst other things) democratic government. Nor is anyone likely to deny that democratic govern- ment is a fact that has to be reckoned with. But then, its significance depends. It depends on what democratic government aspires to do how DEMOCRATIC EDUCATION 25 much or how little. It was the ideal of the Radicals of the second and even of the third quarter of the nineteenth century that it should do little. The weapon, political power, was to be placed in the hands of the people, but care was to be taken that the people, unless for the safeguarding of their civil and religious liberties, were on no account to use it too often or too much. The youthful Demos was to be presented with a new rifle a lovely weapon with the strict injunction that, for all purposes beyond self-defence, he was never to load with more than blank cartridge. But the democracy we know in the twentieth century has changed all that. It wears a different guise. It has now for some time ceased to believe that the social system is a self- acting mechanism, or organism, that can best be left to go, or develop, in its own way. It has come to see that the health of the organism is not in proportion to its prodigious vigour and vitality. It has become aware of deep-seated social diseases which it seems signally impotent to throw off destitution, pauperism, squalor, epidemics, unemployment, commercial crises, and all the rest of the familiar dreary catalogue. And with this perception has come an altered view of government. The suspicion, dread, hatred even, of legislative intervention which fill the pages of Bright, Cobden, Spencer, and (though in less degree) of Mill, have wonderfully waned now that the men who obey the laws are the men who make them. " The State we are 26 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK " the State. Why should we fear ourselves ?" this is the thought that has begun to germinate. Nor are there lacking signs enough of a changed attitude on the part of multitudes who have heretofore been content to look to the voluntary good offices of the well-meaning leisured few for the relief of their hardships, miseries, and degradations. They dislike the dependence. They resent the patronage, how- ever well-intentioned. And so, when they fall on evil days, they look ever-increasingly to the public authority, the authority democratically dependent on their own votes, for that ameliora- tion of their lot which has been, in times past, the concern of voluntary benevolence and voluntary social effort. Democracy, in short, having got its weapon, seems minded to use it. And this change of attitude need one say it? is of pregnant significance, because our country seems manifestly about to plunge into a course of social, and possibly socialistic, legislation. Now it is manifest what all this involves. It means that both national and municipal problems of the utmost gravity are, to an extent undreamed of fifty years ago, being brought into the lives and thrust upon the decisions of the rank and file of the democratic electorate. The political problems which exercised our ancestors (parlia- mentary reform and such like) were not easy; but they were simplicity itself compared with these new questions (health and housing, tem- perance, pensions, poor-law reform, land-tenure, DEMOCRATIC EDUCATION 27 taxation), which send their roots deep down into social causation. They may well perplex the wits of the wisest, and now they are going to be dealt with by the rank and file of a democracy which seems determined to take its salvation into its own hands. Hence the need, urgent beyond all precedent, for the education of the democracy. " We "must educate our masters," said Lowe*, in characteristic words. But this dictum of distrust needs amendment. For the real problem is to educate the democracy to be their own masters. Now it is not to be supposed that a problem of this magnitude is to be solved by Schools of social science and social training for the few the admirable few who are already instinct with the spirit of social helpfulness. It has a vastly larger scope, nothing less indeed than the education of the whole democratic electorate by whose votes the future is to be made or marred. Nor is it difficult to see what this larger education must include. Manifestly it demands the nurture of the social conscience and the civic spirit, and not less manifestly the education of the political intelligence. What follows will naturally fall under these two simple and obvious heads. It is one of the greatest services which a School of social science and social training such as we have established in Liverpool has to render that it opens the eyes to the imperative need for the * Afterward* Lord Sherbrooke. 28 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK first of these two requirements. For our local School does not regard it as its business to convert the world to good works. It assumes, in those who come to it for instruction and training, that the social conscience is already awake, the social sympathies already strong, and the will to work for fellow-citizens already alive and resolute. On this assumption all its work proceeds. "With the object of providing an " opportunity of systematic study and training " for those already engaged or anxious to engage " in any of the many forms of social and charitable "work" so runs its prospectus. Destroy that assumption and its work is foredoomed to futility. Nor is this true only of practical training. It applies also to social research. For though a social researcher is not bound to be a philan- thropist, one may indulge the suspicion that there is no more indomitable researcher than the man who has his human side, and even it may be some far-off vision of the fruits of his labours. One recalls the address given in this place by Charles Booth on the foundation of the Economic Society. It breathed, as one might expect, the spirit of the researcher. But there was one memorable passage in which, just in a word, he spoke of the interest of the fascinating human drama that lies behind even the aridities of figures and statistics. But if this be true, if in the programme of this and other like Schools a social conscience is essential in all who mean, whether as workers or researchers, to grapple with social problems, DEMOCRATIC EDUCATION 29 what, we may well ask, are we to expect of the democratic electorate who seem so eager to solve those same problems for themselves? Can we expect to find in them that public spirit which prompts a man to work for social ends? Can we in their case reckon upon the social sympathies which leave nothing to be done except to open the eyes by instruction and to guide the feet by training? The answer to this question is incontrovertible. We cannot, or rather we cannot unless the democracy can be induced to take steps to create and to foster the needful motive. Herein lies the decisive difference between the lesser and the larger educational problem. The lesser takes the social conscience for granted; its concern is with instruction and training; the larger is vastly more comprehensive. Whatever it may do for the political intelligence, it has to lay the preparation for this in the nurture of that helpful spirit and civic conscience without which mere political knowledge, though it were cried upon the housetops, must remain barren and abortive. For a social conscience is not a congenital endowment. Men are not born with a ready-made perception of the gravity of public causes and the value of social ends. Except in those small beginnings which are great potentialities, a social conscience has a slow and gradual growth. It needs all the agencies of evolution, from the family onwards, to secure its development. If ethical analysis teaches us anything, it tells us 30 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK that. Easy and light, by comparison, would be the education of a people, if it were only a matter of popular enlightenment. The infinitely harder task is to capture the Will, especially the wayward and formidable Will of a great democracy to capture the will and to yoke it to the unselfish, resolute service of the public good. It used to be the fashion for the publicists of democracy, the philosophical Radicals and the Manchester School, to assure the world that social salvation lay along the lines of enlightened individual self-interest. And so within limits it does. We have already said* that, in the existing social system, the pursuit of private interest is one of the great driving wheels of the social machine. Who can doubt that it is to this pursuit of private interest that much, if not most, of the vitality of a city and a nation like our own is due? But when we come to social problems it is different. One can recall an occasion when Henry George (not an especially patient reformer) told an audience in this city that no one who put his hand to great social reforms need expect to reap in personal profit the full fruits of his labours. They were words of sanity. One cannot think so lightly of the problems that confront our generation as to suppose that they are likely to be solved in the short span of a life. Which of us, I wonder, would consent that Page 2. DEMOCRATIC EDUCATION 31 social problems should be hung up till social reformers are convinced that they will individually receive a quid pro quo for their work? As well hang them up for ever. And which of us here would father the imputation that the social work done in this city, say for the past half-century, has been motived by the masterful, but happily not all-masterful, appetite for private gain or glory? It is not in that spirit that great reforms have been carried through in the past; not, for example, the anti-slavery crusade or the factory acts. Nor have the philosophers of individualism Bentham, James Mill, and even the younger Mill ever been reduced to direr straits than when they set themselves to square their psychology of self-interest with their passion for the public good. For whatever a democratic electorate of self-seekers might do and it need not be denied that it could do many things it is safe to say it would hardly solve its social problems. Nor can it expect to solve them till it has developed a social conscience. Now it is not our present purpose to specify, far less to estimate the comparative value of the influences that go to the making of the social conscience. For there are many voices here. This one pleads for the Family as the nursery of the public affections ; that one for the churches as the one sure source of human brotherhood; a third for the religion of Humanity; a fourth for the humanising influences of ethical societies and leagues for moral and civic instruction; 32 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK others, again, for the socialising pressure upon the individual mind and conscience of that actual corporate life which, from parish council upwards, is an outstanding feature of our age and country. Nor is it the least hopeful of the signs of the times that these voices are so many and so confident. There is, however, still another influence to which it is not easy to set limits the influence of the schools which spread so wide a net and sweep into it the entire rising generation of democracy. For the immense advance which Elementary Education has made in the last forty years has led not a few to turn their eyes to the school, not only as the remedy for illiteracy and the place of preparation for artisan and clerk, but as the possible seed plot of the civic spirit. It is now some eighteen years since Mr. Acland, then at the Board of Education, introduced into the Code the new subject of ' The Life and Duties of the Citizen," and the step was prompted by a true perception. It recognised the need for fostering the civic spirit from childhood onwards amongst the citizens-to-be who throng the close- packed benches of our elementary schools. And few persons, I imagine, are likely to quarrel with the aim of that new departure. It is one thing, however, to accept the aim : another to be clear as to how it is best to be achieved. And here it is important to distinguish quite decisively between two ends which, though closely inter- related, are far from identical ; the one, instruction DEMOCRATIC EDUCATION 33 about citizenship, the other, the nurture of the civic spirit. For it is entirely possible to impart much information about citizenship without thereby doing much to make a citizen. There is a great gulf between knowing about citizenship, even all about it, and being a citizen in heart and conscience; just as there is between knowing about work among the poor and going to see the poor in their homes, or between knowing about missions and experiencing in heart and conscience the prompting that sends out the missionary with his life in his hands. The citizenship that addresses itself to social problems, at any rate, will not do much unless it is rooted in that loyalty to institutions and still more in that practical respect and even sympathy towards fellow-men which are as breath of life to all public causes. Not that instruction about citizenship is unimportant. It is vitally important. It must needs come some time. It makes all the difference between the mere law-abiding subject and the intelligent patriot. This goes without saying. Therefore let the School, and even the Elementary School, impart it so far as it can. But let it do this with the clear perception that it is doing little for citizenship unless it can succeed in planting and watering those human sympathies and corporate feelings which may in due season, by the experience and discipline of later years, be broadened into the truly civic spirit. 34 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK It is certainly not beyond the Schools to do this. Is it doubtful that they can do much to send out boys and girls into the world, not only self-reliant and courageous, able "to make their " way in the world," but also pitiful and human- hearted and with widening sympathies with other sorts and conditions of men besides those they have actually met in their own narrow circles? May no schoolmaster say that this is a dream. But a School can do more than this. By its discipline it can lay the foundations of that law- abiding spirit; and by its organisation develop in fruitful beginnings that sense of a corporate life both of which are amongst the greatest possessions of a civilised people. This is matter of common experience. For when one follows many a good citizen's record as schoolboy and as man, is it not the boy who plays his part in the corporate life of his own small world who in due season takes on his shoulders the burden of the city or the State; because, having felt there the force of the great twin influences of comradeship and leadership, he has learnt even thus early the secret of that loyalty to comrade and leader which is the cement of all collective action in the State. Burke has put this in words which are trite because they are so true : " To " be attached to the sub-division, to love the " little platoon we belong to in society, is the " first principle, the germ, as it were, of the public " affections." It is a sentence that hits the mark. To love the little platoon and not merely to know DEMOCRATIC EDUCATION 35 about the larger platoons (good though that may be) this is the beginning of all political education. There is, of course, much besides this that the School can do. It can prepare the clerk or artisan to earn his living. It can mould manners and confirm morals. Not least it can unfold, even before very youthful eyes, the memorable and enkindling record of the nation's and the city's history. And it can teach about the duties of citizenship. But not all these put together will suffice. Nothing will suffice which does not make sure work in weaving into the fibre of heart and conscience those actual ties to kith and kin, to friends and neighbours, and even to fellow-countrymen remoter than these, in which Burke, with unerring political insight, discerned the germ of the public affections. As to the precise methods and instruments of education by which this result is to be achieved let teachers say : it is perhaps the greatest of their responsibilities in these days when democracy is still new to its work. But it is not rash to hazard one remark. Be it in Family, School, or Church, the persons responsible must themselves be what they wish to create. For when the object of any teacher is to bring the rising generation truly to care for anything, it is never enough that he should know about that thing, however thoroughly : he must himself care for it whole-heartedly. This holds in literature, in science, in art, in religion. It holds every- 36 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK where. The lesson that comes home is not necessarily that which occupies the set times and seasons of education, but that which makes its appeal when young minds discern and they are quick to discern that those at whose feet they sit are in earnest about the matter, whatever it may be, of which they aspire, so to say, to be the ambassadors. This principle is fundamental, and its present application is obvious. For if the schools of a nation are indeed to be the seed- plots of those social sympathies and civic virtues which an energetic democracy needs, this will never be unless they are staffed by teachers who know, not merely in that notional way which is only knowing about, but who know really, and in experience, what these sympathies and virtues are. Surely it is the idlest of dreams to suppose that any teacher will do much to create sympathy with suffering, or respect for fellow-citizens, or loyalty to institutions, or pride in the city of our birth, or love of country, unless he himself possesses, or rather is possessed by, these things ? It is sometimes said that schoolmasters ought not to be too much of politicians. And if to be a politician means to convict rival politicians, the other half of the nation, in fact, of being wrong, there is doubtless truth in the remark. But the real danger is rather that our teachers may not be politicians enough. For if to be a politician is to realise the magnitude and the urgency of the tasks that confront our democracy, and to be alive to the local problems that lie at our DEMOCRATIC EDUCATION 37 feet, and to have learnt to respect fellow-citizens and to care for the future of our city and the destinies of our country these are surely the characteristics we must wish to find in the men, and women, who staff the schools of a democratic people. The School, however, even were it staffed by patriots and philanthropists, cannot do every- thing. It is at best but the place of beginnings, and what is begun in it, if it is not to be lost, must be confirmed and carried on by later influences. But it is just here we meet a well-known problem. For the life of the average citizen is not divisible into his school days, even when prolonged by continuation classes, and those later years when he takes his place in industrial or political associations those associations to which many look so hopefully for the practical education of the coming democracy. Un- fortunately there is a critical and often fatal gap in which the youth is more than schoolboy and less than citizen. Not that the gap is quite without its bridges. A fraction throw in their lot with the corporate life of church or chapel. A fraction accept the discipline and responsi- bilities of military service. A fraction unite themselves to societies, clubs, guilds, which so many well-wishers are making desperate efforts to establish. And all such associations, even those founded for trivial objects, provide a sort of training in public spirit, and become thereby 38 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK an undesigned preparation for the serious citizen- ship of later life. But for the vast majority, especially for the mass who quit school at 16 or 14, the gap is not bridged. No, they drift away from the " little platoons," the family and the school, in which they have heretofore lived; these earlier ties are relaxed, and the adolescent life, boyhood behind and manhood still in front, goes out to push its fortunes in a competitive and indifferent world. Is it wonderful if, as the years go on those momentous, adolescent years when the sympathies are still plastic and the habits still unconfirmed what happens in ten thousand cases is that the race for personal success, the scramble for livelihood, the natural appetite for pleasure, the allurements to frivolity give selfishly self-centred interests an ascendancy which they never afterwards lose. ' They forget u all they have learnt " how often have we heard that trite lamentation. But the more serious calamity by far is that the earlier ties are weakened, or even severed, and that no other socialising attachments (unless, indeed, the ties of private friendships) have come to take their place. This is universally deplored by all reformers. It is the weakest point in our social organisation. It is the ruin of many a life, the marring of many a citizen, the detriment of the State. What is to be done to counteract it? How is the youth of the nation, who in a few years will inherit the rights and responsibilities of political power, to DEMOCRATIC EDUCATION 39 be taught that the community needs and expects serious service and sacrifice at their hands ? " By " universal military service," say some. " By " anything rather than that," say others. And indeed the controversy runs high and hot. But meanwhile the need remains. Nor is there a more fruitful enterprise for a School of Social Science and Social Work than to go into the facts of this matter, and to suggest some way, or ways, by which this demoralising and desocialising interval between boyhood and manhood may effectually be bridged. For if this were done, the prospect would brighten. One might almost say that, if the preparation for them were securely laid, the later years of adult life could take care of themselves. For during the last sixty years, the growth of corporate life, and the sense of corporate life, has been going on apace. It is no longer an " anarchic " and atomistic individualism that alarmists dread. No writer now can re-echo the wild despairing cry of Carlyle in 1830 that " in the cut-throat and cut-purse scramble " of individual greed " there is no longer any social " idea extant." Labour, capital, politics, govern- ment, religion, charity, even amusement, have been moving steadily onwards to organisation, and the cry of our Cassandras now is that unions, leagues, syndicates, federations, caucuses, bureaucracies, and what not are rapidly organising England into a new slavery. Herein lies ground for hope. For though the artisan who faces the 40 anxieties and miseries entailed by strike or lock- out may or may not live to enjoy a rise of wages, he inevitably learns the lesson of public spirit in the iron disciplines and bitter sacrifices of collective action. The citizen who casts in his lot with a political party may or may not achieve the ends he has at heart, but he cannot miss the fact if he be more than a political camp- follower that public causes are not to be won but by sacrifice of leisure, money, and energy. This holds all along the line. There is no form of organised action for common ends, even when those ends may be wild and illusory, which may not become an education in civic spirit. It is thus that Democracy educates her sons in her own way, because it is thus that, by the call to organise and work for corporate ends, she evokes and fosters the social conscience. This, however, is but one requisite. I said, you will remember,* that there were two; and the other was political intelligence. It is far from me to suggest that political intelligence is to be acquired only in books, schools, or lecture-rooms. It is needful to say this because some of the bitterest assailants of democracy (Sir Henry Maine, for example, or Robert Lowe) have written as if it were. First these critics of popular government magnify political problems as enough to tax the wits of experts, which (especially when the problems See paga 27. DEMOCRATIC EDUCATION 41 are social) is entirely true; and then they turn round and ask if ignorant " roughs " and " clowns " (the words are Maine's) are likely to find solutions. And, if that were the sum of the whole matter, the case for democratic government would be as hopeless as these two distinguished publicists believed. But the matter stands quite otherwise. For political intelligence comes in other ways besides those that make direct appeal to intellect. It comes, one may suggest, from face-to-face personal experience of the hardships, miseries, and obstructions which it is ever-increasingly the concern of legislation and administration to extinguish. And in this connection, we may rejoice that no student of this School of Social Work need lack that personal contact with concrete cases which will give to his knowledge a reality which it will never afterwards lose a reality which mere hearsay knowledge can never possess. It comes, in greater measure still, of that practical experience of affairs, and that intercourse with men, which are to be found in the workshop, the friendly society, the trades union, the co-operative association, the political committee, not less surely than in middle-class business life or leisured-class immunity from business life. All those forms of corporate life are schools of political intelligence as well as nurseries of civic motive. Mill called them " education in the widest sense of the word." And, not least, political intelligence comes of 42 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK that sagacity, shrewdness, common-sense (call it what we may) which, though none too common in the world, is certainly not the monopoly of any class in the community, being as it is the distinctive quality of the practical man, however humble, in all ranks and conditions of life. These, or something like these, are among the elements which go to the making of the political intelligence. And the hope of the friends of Democracy is that these elements may be found, and more and more as the years go on, in sufficient measure to fit the rank and file of the electorate, whose business, after all, is not to find solutions for themselves so much as to choose the men they think can find them, to form a sound judgment upon broad political issues when these, having been well threshed-out in press and on platform, are from time to time submitted to them for decision. And yet nothing could be more fatuous and it is here Democracy may learn from its critics than to surfer these or any other pleas for democratic government to obscure the fact that, for the solution of those social problems which the democracy of our day is so eager to grapple with, nothing less is needed than expert knowledge of the highest quality. Think of the reform (or as some would have it the destruction) of the poor law, of the fiscal policy of the Empire, of sanitation and public health, of the perplexities of unemployment, of the almost mysterious cycles of commercial depression, of DEMOCRATIC EDUCATION 43 the intricacies of land valution and taxation who will say that these or any other large political problems can ever be solved except by minds with a wide and firm grasp of facts, principles, and methods? Majorities are not enough. There is nothing more essential for a democracy to realise, because there is nothing more certain, than that majorities, however overwhelming, can never really solve a single social problem. Majorities can make, or unmake, governments, push problems to the front, choose the men they think capable, reject the men they think incapable, and they can also, of course, approve or reprobate the solutions offered. But solutions are beyond them unless, somewhere available in elected or electorate, there exist that sound knowledge and firm grasp of conditions without which reforms must to the end of time remain superficial or fraudulent. For diagnosis and therapeutics, as scientific as they can be made, are as needful for the body politic as for the body physiological. Nor is it doubtful that, in the one case as the other, ignorant treatment will bring its nemesis. May I add, in conclusion, that it is these considerations that give all Schools like this a claim upon the public. Firstly, because this School aspires, in all modesty, to take its place amongst many other agencies for diffusing a knowledge of the facts, laws, and methods of social work. We make no great pretensions. We do not take our students very far. But at any rate we take them much further than 44 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK the average citizen cares as yet to go. And, secondly, because we desire to bear our testimony, by the mere fact of our existence, to the gravity and urgency of the need in this democratic country for a study of social problems immeasurably beyond these our small beginnings. We think that the day is past when the maladies of the social system can be left to those mere "good intentions," however benevolent, which are in truth not intentions at all because they do not take the trouble to forecast the results, and especially the more distant results, of social action and State intervention. We believe that those who aspire to meddle as meddle they must with the complex, delicately-balanced, vulnerable social organism should make sure that they know what they are doing, lest haply in " raw haste, half-sister to delay," they leave their country worse than they found it. We are, in short, convinced that social work must rest on social science; and, in that conviction, we stand for the reasonable demand that if clergy, teachers, doctors, engineers, soldiers need a special training for their professions, so also do the statesmen, the publicists, the leaders, and (in such measure as may be possible in a hard-driven world) the citizens of a democracy which, for better or worse, and with the fate of this great Empire at stake, has taken its destinies into its own hand. Ill -THE JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES TO SOCIAL WORK. If what has been said is true, if it is by belief in the worth of individual lives that the service of institutions is humanised and sympathy with suffering deepened and steadied, it is clearly of vital moment that this belief should be kept alive. This is the most reasonable of conclusions. For the quality of human motive inevitably depends upon its object, and with the stability and value of the object in this case the lives of men the motive must stand or fall. But unfortunately this belief is not left unassailed. For in all societies, great or small, there is a large crop of decriers of the species. Some of them are cynics, and some are satirists, and some again, without either the pungency of the cynic or the wit and indignation of the satirist, are simply those corrosive minds who delight in the belittlement of human nature. There are also Gallios to whom all generous estimates are an enigma, and " men of the world " to whose 46 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK matter-of-fact eyes the philanthropic, or demo- cratic, or religious faith in human worth is either incomprehensible, or at best the devout imagina- tion of enthusiasts. Nor are there lacking formidable theories about human nature, both pessimistic and naturalistic, which would render it flatly impossible and even absurd for their converts to hold fast to that conviction of the value and dignity of man of which Kant is so unfaltering a prophet. Add to these solvents of faith the disquieting array of facts the damnatory revelations of the criminal court, the prison, the workhouse, the asylum, the slum and altogether we have a collective indictment admirably fitted to remind us (to return to words already quoted) "to what an accursed race we "beloAg." There are more ways than one of meeting this indictment. One way is to set to work, after the fashion of practical men of heart and will without much appetite for theorising, and to prove against all comers that even the worst specimens of the race are worth helping by making them actually better through our help. Nor does it seem doubtful that many a quite humble worker in the holes and corners of city or country carries in his wallet experiences in this respect which might well put cynic, satirist, and pessimist to silence. None are more entitled to a hearing than those who have put their belief in the possibilities of human nature to the test of experiment. Yet this is not the only way. For JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 47 once misgivings have arisen as to those who are the objects of interest and effort, there is nothing for it, at least to such as wish to make their foundations sure, but to turn to the serious study of human nature, and to face the question whether a scrutiny of facts, as rigorous and searching as it can be made, deepens or dispels that faith in the worth of men which is the tap-root of social motive. Fortunately the question is anything but new. Since the dawn of history mankind has never been slow to recognise human worth; and since the dawn of ethical and religious reflection, this recognition of the unique value of human beings, even in the midst of dire misfortunes and disasters, has furnished a central problem to the thinkers. Hence two well-worn lines of enquiry. What is it that gives a human life its value in the best types, or (to be more concrete) what is it that redeems the life of Job amongst his potsherds or of Socrates when he put the cup of hemlock to his lips? This is the one question. And the second more characteristic of the modern than of the ancient world is but an extension of the first. For it does but press home the inquiry if this secret of human worth, whatever it may be, is the monopoly of the few or the birthright also of the weak, the obscure, and the neglected. Not that the answers to these questions are always reassuring. For it is not only against mere hostile opinions that the belief in human worth has to contend. As already suggested, it is also 48 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK against deliberate theories about human nature, and amongst these is pessimism. For, of course, pessimism is not merely a discourse on the miseries of life. If it be that, as indeed it is, it is only so because it is a philosophy of misery which claims to prove, by penetrating analysis, that by his very nature and by the constitution of the universe, man is born to misery as the sparks fly upward. Dowered, by the inscrutable force which operates throughout all Nature, with the instinct of self-preservation, man struggles on to find that the sorrows of life far exceed its joys. Pain is the lord of life. For what is life but one long pursuit of illusory satisfactions, which turn to ashes in the tasting. From this there is no escape. So has it been from the beginning : so will it be to the end. For the " Will to live," however bitter the experiences into which it precipitates the hapless human race, vitalises each fresh generation to struggle forward to the same harvest of miseries- miseries of unsatisfied desires, of unending toil, of broken illusions from which there is no refuge but death. And yet the darkness is not so unrelieved as might appear. For this " Will to live " which thrusts man onward irresistibly, breaks forth not only in bodily activities and in psychical cravings, but in intelligence. And intelligence can achieve at any rate three things for its possessor. It can furnish the solace and delights of Art, so that even the wretched such of them at any rate as JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 49 care for things of beauty can find at least a temporary anodyne in self-forgetful absorption in objects the sonata, the poem, the painting, the statue which charm us out of ourselves, and which never delude us, because they are created simply to be interesting in themselves and for no ulterior purpose whatever. 11 When you get simple beauty and nought else, You get about the best thing God invents." from this consolation mankind is not shut out. But intelligence can do more than this. For it can open the eyes at any rate of those who think to the fact that they and their fellow-sufferers (for are not all born to suffer) are all alike kin, inasmuch as all alike are the products, shall we say the victims, of one and the same " Will to live " which drives on the sons of men to the common destiny of disillusionment. Hence room for the growth of sympathy, the reflective sympathy of the man in whom the experience of dissatisfied desire and disillusioned egoism has given birth to the wish to alleviate in others the sufferings he is impotent to remove either from his own life or from theirs. And, not least, intelligence can teach the lesson that, after all, the "Will to live," however masterful, has left one way of escape. For cannot intelligence suggest that, as the miseries of life come of the vain pursuit of illusions, these miseries will end if only passion-driven man has strength of mind enough to cease to care for 50 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK what life has to give, and to acquiesce in that inevitable passage from life to death in which lies the one effective escape from suffering? It will be easy enough to shew that this estimate of human life strikes at the heart of social effort. Any theory which declares life to be irremediably a poor thing at best must needs dishearten those who wish to make it better. But it does not follow that pessimism has not its message even for them. For at very least it furnishes an antidote to that facile optimism which exasperates by the proffer of all too easy remedies for miseries the depths of which it has never plumbed. It is good that those who stand forward to make life better should realise the depths of the sea of human misery. The experienced social worker may not need the lesson : he probably sees enough for himself. But for one who knows the facts there is a multitude who do but skirt the fringe of the woes of the world, and have little notion of the magnitude of the evils they set out to encounter. To them pessimism has a salutary message. It at any rate tries to go to the root of the matter. Be its diagnosis right or wrong, it at least tries to track the sorrows of men up to their ultimate causes. It is easy to say that pessimism paints the world in drab, and to set it down as morbid, or cynical, or sentimental. It is not so easy to accept its challenge, and to prove as well as assert that life can be made something better than the death in life it makes it out to be. JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 51 Nor can it be doubted that there is much in pessimism to evoke that compassionate sympathy which is at any rate an element in social motive. If those sufferings that are the Nemesis of folly, vice, and crime can touch the heart to pity, how much more the sorrows which are the inevitable fruit of that forlorn struggle to live which condemns all alike, saint and sinner, strong and weak, rich and poor, master and servant, to take their assigned positions in the universal partner- ship of wretchedness. " Poor wandering, way- " ward man !" cries Carlyle. "Art thou not tried "and beaten with stripes, even as I am? Ever " whether thou bear the Royal mantle or the "beggar's gabardine, art thou not so weary, so- " heavy-laden ; and thy Bed of Rest is but a " Grave. O my Brother, my Brother, why cannot " I shelter thee in my bosom, and wipe away all "tears from thy eyes!" How infinitely more pathetic, one may well ask, if that which is here described is the common irreversible doom of all that live? Small wonder that Schopenhauer should find in sympathy the ground phenomenon of ethics. And yet it is precisely here that pessimism begins to disclose its inadequacy. Sympathy with suffering, if our previous analysis be sound,* will never be of the deepest, nor will it be discriminating, so long as it is only sympathy with suffering, however acute. It is the belief * See page 15 et seq. 52 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK in the value of the being who suffers that makes all the difference between our compassion for a saint and a scoundrel, or for a man and an animal. And when sympathy passes into action, the very nerve of effort lies in the conviction that we can not only alleviate suffering, but alleviate suffering which mars and obstructs a life which is worth living. There is no room in pessimism for this belief. The miseries of mankind mar that which, according to its creed, has at best but little value. Nor could the alleviation of their miseries be more than an illusory and passing respite. Hence the paralysing doubt, Is it worth while? Nay, better the grief that kills than grief assuaged only to encounter new cause for grief. Better the hope that is unwilling to be fed and is never fed, than that which is fed only to live in one more fools' paradise. For as the sting of suffering is only understood when the onlooker realises that the miseries of the object of his compassion are robbing him of a life of positive worth and happiness, so does the triumph of sympathy lie in the perception that the relief of the wretched is the emancipation of obstructed powers whose exercise points the way to a self- respecting and self-satisfying life. For this kind of suffering, and for this kind of sympathy, there is no room in pessimism. A similar line of remark applies to the pessimist's doctrine of Renunciation. This is unquestionably its loftiest mood. It brings it into closest affinity to two of the greatest religions JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 53 of sacrifice. "In my i/th year," says Schopen- hauer, " without any but the most elementary " school education, I was as possessed by the " sorrow of the world as was Buddha in his youth '' at the sight of illness, old age, pain, and death." And if thus with Buddha he saw the problem, with Buddha also as he is himself aware he finds the solution. " His books at their best," says Wallace in his brilliant little Life of Schopen- hauer, " give the picture of a soul . . . which ' holds the best life to be that of one who has ' pierced through the illusions dividing one ' conscious personality from another, into that ' heart of divine rest where we are each members ' one of another, essentially united in the great ' ocean of Being in which and by which we alone ' live." These sentences are a sympathetic rendering of that pessimistic self-sacrifice that passes into glad acquiescence in personal annihilation. The affinity to Christianity is hardly less obvious. For iwhen the Christian moralist tells mankind that he who would save his life must lose it, and when the emphasis is made to lie as not seldom it is on the losing of self in the service of man, we are not far from the renunciation of the pessimistic creed, especially if we bear in mind that pessimism is an ethics of sympathy as well as of renunciation. It may no doubt be a problem for the student and one may suspect it is a problem pessimists never solve to understand by what process " the Will to live," so masterful and unquenchable, so 54 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK deeply rooted in the very fibre of life, is brought thus to humble itself and acquiesce in its own suppression. But so it is. This self-renunciation, this total surrender of the very last shred of egoism and self-seeking, is so pronounced that one is tempted to say of pessimism that having belittled all the ends of life as vain, illusory, and worthless, it makes amends by exalting life to a superhuman elevation just for that moment when the last rush of annihilating darkness is descending on the soul. Now all this is so lofty, and so much in harmony with the spirit in which the best work of the world is done, that it might appear unjust and even outrageous to say that, despite its doctrine of renunciation, pessimism remains the most fatal of all philosophies to social motive. But so it is. It is the most deadlv of all theoretic j solvents of social effort. It is so because it belittles human nature. For no gospel of renunciation can confirm, far less elevate, the estimate of man, unless it includes either a recognition of the value of the ends for which the sacrifice of self is made, or of the value of the person, the self, who makes the sacrifice. Pessimism gives us neither. For if the lives even of the so-called fortunate and happy, how much more those of the ill-starred and wretched, be so honey-combed with misery that the best thing that could befall a man would be not to be born, and the second best that, seeing by no choice of his own he has been thrust into the JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 55 world, he should set himself to care not a whit, nay, to despise, everything that life has to offer, is it wonderful if his fellows should doubt if it be worth while lifting so much as a little finger in his service? It may be that as matter of fact they do, driven on by instincts of compassion. But why should they? Why work so devotedly to restore the sick to health, the indigent to livelihood, the wastrel to industry, the sorrowful to joy, the despairing to new hope, if this new life to which we strive to bring them back is to be a new lease of misery to end only with the end of life? Nothing cuts the sinews of social effort more completely than the paralysing conviction that the lives of those who are its objects are despicable. The two things are irreconcilable. Even the temporary alleviation of suffering must repel, if it be translated into prolongation of agony. The one thing left for pessimism, as for Buddhism, is to preach the glad tidings of the gospel of acquiescence in personal annihilation. And this, of course, is, in a sense, effective. "The right ear that is filled with dust Hears little that is false or just." There is no further disillusionment. But this is not the renunciation that sheds dignity and heroism on human nature. It is poles asunder from the renunciation which in the moment of self-surrender realises the value of what is surrendered, and even in the hour of death is most profoundly convinced of the value of 56 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK life. Compared with this, such peace as the pessimist's gospel can bring is but the sense of relief begotten by the knowledge of coming escape from a hopeless life-long struggle, disillusionment, thraldom, and unhappiness. Pessimistic renunciation is but the last impenitent protest against the value of human life, the last Parthian shaft against all resolute, hopeful, and unselfish effort. It is therefore fortunate that pessimism finds an antidote in naturalism. For naturalism is at all events a cheerful creed. Like pessimism it recognises to the full the strength and pertinacity of " the Will to live." Awake to the indomitable persistence with which Life struggles forwards, at all costs, in the vegetable and animal worlds, it recognises in the highest animal, man, the same principle of self- preservation. Unlike pessimism, it discerns in this process the emergence of higher, that is, more fully-developed and more richly-integrated forms of life. It has much to say of " the fit " ; in the light of evolution it prophesies the advent of the fitter, and even of the "fittest" who, having put all rivals under their feet, shall victoriously in the latter day stand upon the earth. There is no misgiving here that life is not worth living. On the contrary, the legend inscribed on the gateway of the Academy of naturalism might well be " More life and fuller." This appears with convincing clearness in some of its extremest types. Nietzsche is, to JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 57 say the least, no philanthropist : had his power been equal to the ferocity of his rhetoric, he would have swept the world clean of all the Christian virtues and all the Christian graces. But why? Because, reverting to that deification of successful Power which is as old as the Greek Sophists, he would have the world peopled by strong, self-assertive, self-seeking egoists who are so entirely convinced that life is worth living, at any rate in their own persons, that they are quite prepared to sacrifice their fellows in whole battalions, and to glory in so doing, if only they could thereby make the utmost of themselves. It is a ruthless creed, but it does but transfer to human affairs that struggle for existence and survival of " the fittest " which is the law of nature; and it has at all events the redeeming feature that it affirms the value of life. In the very phrenzy of its egoism it is a protest against the pessimistic message that a human life even at its best is worthless. To assert the will to live at all costs ; to denounce individual sacrifice and renunciation as the false and contemptible morality of slaves what is this but a way of saying that fulness of life is to be coveted and struggled for at any price? Hence it may be said that, even in its most pitiless form, and in despite of all the scoffs of Nietzsche at philanthropy, naturalism does not a little to reinforce the philanthropic spirit. By its laudations of human nature in its strong and victorious types, and in its firm faith that the 58 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK best that is is but first-fruits of something better to come, it leaves no place for the doubt that the elevation of man may not be an end worth living for. It affirms the very contrary. So much therefore may be set down to the credit of naturalism. It sees in the struggle of life, which fills the pessimist with despair, the necessary ordeal by which human nature proves its mettle : it foresees the coming of a time when by evolutionary process, the best that is will have given place to a better. And by doing these things, it certainly is well fitted to bring encouragement and hope to all who wish and work for the betterment of man. Unfortunately, however, what this type of naturalism gives with the one hand it withdraws with the other. For when we look closer, the aristocracy of naturalism, " the fittest to survive," as has often been pointed out (and not least by Huxley),* cannot be said as such to possess any moral worth whatever. " Fittest " is an epithet that, naturalistically, must be construed rigorously in relation to environment. If the environment be good, the fittest will have qualities accordingly; but if the environment be bad, the fittest would be anything but worthy of our admiration. In Gomorrah, for example, the fittest were those who were ultimately deemed fit to be destroved by fire from Heaven. It follows that the "fit" In hia "Evolution and Ethics." JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 59 or "fittest" of which evolution speaks are not necessarily such as to kindle the wish that the species should inherit the earth. Nor does Huxley shrink from the statement that moral effort is so far from finding inspiration in this idea of " the fittest " that its prime function is to resist and counteract the " cosmic process " of which "the fittest" are the fruit. Clearly social effort must work up to other values than those which, so far, naturalism is able to furnish. This becomes evident if we remember that one of the attributes of the fittest to survive is ability to prevent others from surviving. The "fittest" of the evolutionist, like the merciless " superman " of Nietzsche, rises on stepping stones of the dead selves of his neighbours and rivals. For the emergence of the fit is to the last degree costly. In the process of natural selection (to borrow Huxley's metaphor) for every bullet that hits the mark a thousand fly wide and are wasted. Of the individual life Nature is not only careless but contemptuously lavish. The drift of this is obvious. How is it possible to familiarise the mind with this profligate wastage of human material without lowering our estimate of the value of individual lives? Nietzsche tells us that the poor are good for nothing but statistics; statistics, we may add, that are swelled by the multitudes whose extinction is the price of the advent of the small minority who, if the strict law of natural selection has free play, prove their worth, such as it is, 60 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK by practically disproving the worth of their weaker competitors in life's race. Thus regarded, naturalism becomes almost as fatal to social effort as pessimism. It sets us wondering if the weak, the unfortunate, the obscure and neglected, not to say the physically and mentally and morally defective, are worth even a tithe of the thought and labour that is bestowed upon them. Nietzsche's vituperative assaults on Christian ethics are but one indication of many that pity, mercy, long-suffering, refusal to despair even of the worst and weakest, are not the ways of naturalism if naturalism stands or falls with the struggle for existence between individuals as the law of human as it admittedly is the law of animal life. This, however, is happily not the case. For there is a broader and a more human naturalism. It is more human because it is more social In its conception. For this creed enlarges its idea of " cosmic process " so as to include within it the conflict of social groups. These groups, having come into existence through the natural sociality of man and other influences, fulfil the evolutionary law of struggle for existence and survival of the fittest. They fulfil it indeed so effectively, group against group, that they rear within them individuals who are so thoroughly socialised that they have risen far above that selfish struggle of man against man of which we have already said enough. The group may be small or large a clan, a tribe, a nation; but the JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 61 essential features are always alike. For in order that the group may hold its own and stand strong against its rival groups, individual rivalries within the group are greatly softened and humanised, and in their place come those self- suppressions and that sense of common interest which are essential to the pursuit of a common good. Without these even a gang of banditti would dissolve. Nor need the evolutionist, if he thinks he has sufficient data, deny himself the vision of the coming of a time when the combative qualities fostered by conflicts between races or nations may be further softened or even extinguished by the evolution of an organised humanity (far enough off at present), in the service of which that reciprocal hatred between nation and nation which deluges the world with blood might be dissolved in the pursuit of cosmopolitan ends. Now a theory like this manifestly modifies and corrects the cruder and more individualistic naturalism. For the price of the emergence of the fit is no longer the wholesale destruction of the weaker individuals by the stronger; and, consequently, the wastage, so appalling in the sub-human world, need no longer so much disquiet us. Wastage, no doubt, there is. It comes when group encounters group in the sanguinary wars that devastate the world. But, within the several groups, hatreds and hostilities are conspicuously softened (though in societies where competition prevails they are far from 62 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK abolished). This follows because, if a group (let us say a nation) is to present an invulnerable front to its rivals, it will take care that conflicts between its members are, at all events in their more disturbing and destructive forms, suppressed. Hence the type of human being which now comes to the front is conspicuously more in harmony with a faith in the value of the individual man. For he is no longer the self- assertive human animal, but the loyal citizen who has been so effectually socialised, and who responds so naturally to the demands his country makes upon him, that he does his utmost to make and keep the commonwealth strong against all comers. A type of this kind has many valuable qualities : it is intrinsically worth having and worth working for. But this is not all. For the value which comes to be ascribed to the group reflects itself in the lives of its members. From the days of the village community or clan onwards, men always regard the group to which they belong as having value value so great that they are ready on occasion to sacrifice even their lives for its sake. And this tendency so essentially human rises to high-water mark when the object of loyalty is the modern nation (or empire). It is not too much to say that, in practice at any rate (for the average citizen does not trouble himself much with theory), the life of the nation is regarded by every citizen as if it had an absolute value. And whatever JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 63 hesitancies on this point may arise, as in some cases they do, when the larger idea of Humanity emerges, bringing in its train possible conflicts between patriotic and cosmopolitan ends, the fact substantially remains that the citizen of France, England, Germany, Switzerland acts on the conviction, tacit or avowed, that the conservation of his country's life and power, not to say the fulfilment of his country's destinies, is essential to civilisation. He will not even think of national self-effacement. So indomitable is the value set upon the group. Small wonder therefore if we also come to value every man who either is, or can be made, a good citizen. It is one of the commonest of experiences that the recognised value of any institution imparts a value to its members such as they might not otherwise possess. Even its humblest supporters gain an enhanced importance in our eyes. How much more when the valued object is that organism of institutions, the nation, which has victoriously proved its strength in the evolutionary struggle for existence ? Now it may be admitted that this takes us some considerable way. To the question, Why ascribe to our fellow-men that value which makes them the objects of social effort? we have now an answer. We have the conception of a nation, well-organised, able to hold its own against all comers, of acknowledged value, and with citizens reared and disciplined to promote its efficiency in all modes. Is not this an object 64 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK worth working for? And if so, what more do we need to justify the energies of legislators, administrators, and philanthropists ? And yet we do need something more. The justification is incomplete. i. For, in the first place, we must never forget that social motive and effort are not limited to fellow-citizens. Cosmopolitan sympathies and cosmopolitan effort exist in great strength and vitality. Be the official attitude of group to group what it may, and be international rivalries never so keen, the fact remains that the sympathies pass far beyond the frontiers of the group and extend to other peoples, tribes, and races. What, then, is the justification of this? Wliy should an Englishman, for example, interest himself, through the mission field or otherwise, in savage races, or it may be in Jews or Armenians, whom he believes to be persecuted, or possibly in the citizens of some foreign nation menaced by invasion ? One can hardly say it is because of a sense of the value of the group to which these aliens belong. It sometimes is, but by no means always. Cosmopolitan sympathies go out to men oftener than to nations or groups. And the nations or tribes to which these men belong may be far from admirable, and even politically worthless, without drying up our interest in their members. As matter of fact many of the objects of mis- sionary and civilising effort belong to no organism which has any value whatever in the eyes of their JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 65 sympathisers. Nor does it help much to say as is often said that they belong at any rate to the great family of Humanity, for as " Humanity ' is not not yet, at any rate an organised unity of recognised value (as the nation is) this reference to " Humanity " is only a way of saying that these objects of our interest and effort have value because they are human beings. And this may possibly be the fact : but it is not a fact that naturalism, so far as we have gone, has succeeded in explaining. For the distinctive note of naturalism is that it derives the value of the individual from the recognised value of the group to which he belongs. 2. It is even harder to follow the naturalistic justification when we turn our eyes to what goes on within the nation itself. One has only to pass in melancholy review the incurably diseased, the insane, the vicious, the paupers, the criminals, and then to put the question if the pitiful and patient care and tendance of these social failures can be justified as making the nation strong in the international struggle for existence. Grant that the thought, time, and money spent on them does something to enhance the sense of national solidarity, it is doubtful in the extreme if this does much to counterweigh the fact that they are an impoverishment, a burden, if not a curse to the society to which they owe so much. So far at national strength goes, it might seem better that they should be drowned in the depths of the sea. 66 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK Nor can we escape the difficulty by following such stalwarts of naturalism as think that our humanitarianism has gone too far, and that the time has come to make less of the worth of the worthless, and to give a freer hand to natural selection. For in doing this we should not merely be outraging our instincts of pity and mercy (which it might be our duty to repress), but running straight in the teeth of that obstinate, deep-seated belief in the " worth " even of the weakest and worst which, as we have seen, has entrenched itself in religion, law, philanthropy, education, and democratic politics.* In other words, we should be confessing the failure of naturalism to justify existing facts. Put the blunt question : which course makes for the strength of a nation; is it that its weaklings, waifs, and wastrels should be kept alive through ineffectual lives far on into old age, or that (were such a thing possible) they should be despatched quam primumt The answer does not seem doubtful. Nor is it easier to justify, on naturalistic grounds, our preferences for some of the best of mankind than to justify our interest in the worst. Naturalism, if we have interpreted it aright, builds upon the recognised value of the social organism, on the ground that it has proved its strength in the conflict of groups. And it would seem to follow that our preferences should go out towards the citizens of the strongest Page 15. JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 67 States. But this is not the case. "A generous " spirit," says Lord Acton, " prefers that his " country should be poor and weak, and of " no account, but free, rather than powerful, " prosperous, and enslaved. It is better to be "the citizen of a humble commonwealth in the "Alps, without a prospect of influence beyond " the narrow frontier, than a subject of the " superb autocracy that overshadows half of "Asia and of Europe."* Now if a preference of this kind (for we need not enter into the specific comparison suggested) is a fact; if we do affirm that the life of the member of the weaker State may have more genuine value than that of the citizen of a great and powerful Empire, one of the great world- powers, then it would seem to follow that the worth assigned to the individual cannot be dependent on, or derived from, the value ascribed to a group because that group is even irresistibly strong and victorious in the inter- national struggle. From whatever sources the citizenship of the small, weak, and even insignificant State may derive the quality of life which constrains us to give it the decisive preference, this source is not to be found in the mere fact that, by the vis a tergo of social evolution, the community to which he belongs has become strong and formidable. Yet that would seem to be the source to which, on naturalistic grounds, we ought to go. * " History of Freedom," p. 23. 68 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK The conclusion from all this is obvious. The reality of cosmopolitan sympathies, the philanthropic care for many who can only be regarded as a burden to society, the fact that we do not believe that the best kind of life is necessarily to be found in the strongest State these are considerations which bid us look beyond naturalism, even in its most socialised forms, for adequate justification of that belief in the worth of the individual which lies so close to the source of social motive. We may accept this result with the more confidence because, of course, pessimism and naturalism do not exhaust the resources of philosophy. There are other creeds, and one of them, by no means obsolete, is utilitarianism. No one can justly tax utilitarianism with failure to recognise the value of the individual man. In the pages of J. S. Mill, it is not only a defence of individualism, democratic in the breadth of its sympathies : it is also a passionate incitement to foster individuality, even to or across the verge of eccentricity, in all members of the community. Few writers have had so firm a faith in what human nature has it in it to become. Nor can any reader, not only of the ever-memorable Essay on Liberty but of all his writings, rise from Mill's pages without an enhanced conception of human life. Mill has been twitted by critics with a low and niggardly estimate of men, " the herd, the " common uncultivated herd," as he sometimes JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 69 calls them; yes, but it is just this candid dis- paragement of men as they are that throws into stronger relief the glowing anticipations, optimistic in the highest degree, of what (given liberty and favouring environment) they have it in them to become. Assuredly no doubt ever crossed Mill's mind that his fellow-men were worth the utmost that could be done for them. Nay, the very reproach that has been levelled against utilitarianism becomes, in this connection, a tribute. The reproach is that utilitarianism has been slow to assimilate biology; that it has failed to recognise that society is " an organism " ; that it has viewed the community arithmetically as an aggregate of units and not biologically as a wonderfully integrated organic whole which has its own life to live, its own function to fulfil, in the inevitable conflict with other organic groups of like kind to itself. Be it so. The reproach has its truth. It is undeniable that even Mill, though living in days Darwinian, fought singularly shy of biological formulae. But why? Not of a surety because he failed to recognise the reality of social ties, but because he could never forget the claims of the individual. Happiness that Greatest Happiness which was the watchword of his School meant for him always the happiness .of actual men and women. This comes out in many ways. We have it in the emphasis laid on individual rights as the sine qua non of all social well-being; in the significant addendum " each to count for one '* 70 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK which, following Bentham, he tacks on to the Greatest Happiness principle; in the insistence, again and again renewed, that the value of any social system is to be measured by the fullness of life within reach of its members. Nor is it doubtful that utilitarianism has left its indelible mark on English thought by its glowing, and at times all but fanatical, pleas for the claims, possibilities, and worth of the individual life. Nor are the grounds of this estimate far to seek. Men have value in utilitarian eyes because it is their nature to possess the capacity for happiness. Many and various as are the ends and objects whose pursuit gives substance and reality to the individual life, these are all ultimately valuable for no other reason than that they satisfy this deep-seated capacity and craving for happiness. In this capacity therefore lies the root of human worth. There is much to be said for such a view. It is indubitable that men desire a happy life for themselves; quite as indubitable as that they hate and recoil from the very thought of the 'opposite ; and in proportion as experience teaches them that the satisfaction of these capacities for happiness are many and great, in like proportion do they consider their lives to be worth living. To desire and value one's own happiness, to be sure, is one thing, and to value and desire that of other persons is another. But it is not beyond JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 71 the power of sympathy and sympathy plays a vital part in utilitarian ethics to transfer to the lives of others what is matter of familiar experience to ourselves. Hence that attractive and inspiring utilitarian picture of a community of men and women living unobstructed and happy lives, and satisfying their varied capacities with the best things, small and great, which a civilised society has in its gift. Best of all, of course were such a millennium possible a community in which every one was happy. But, seeing that, in the imperfect state of human affairs, failure, misfortune, disease, and death still bring their blight, the next best is that at any rate the majority should be happy. Such, in brief, is the doctrine of the utilitarians. It stands written in their formula, " Greatest " Happiness of the Greatest Number " ; it stands written still more eloquently in their devoted and public-spirited lives. The conception filled them with enthusiasm. Jeremy Bentham, " the " most philanthropic of the philanthropic," as he once styled himself, gloried in it. And John Stuart Mill embraced it, so he tells us, as " a religion " a religion which prompted him, (to use his own words) to " take up his cross " in the service of his generation. Call it religion or call it philosophy, it evidently offered to its votaries an object worth living for. One cannot wonder that Green, that searching critic of the utilitarian philosophy, should nevertheless freely 72 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK acknowledge its supreme value as a doctrine of public spirit and social service.* But, though this is the truth about utili- tarianism, and nothing but the truth, it is, unfortunately, not the whole truth. For, in an evil hour (as some may think) utilitarianism wedded itself to hedonism; and on the strength of psychological analysis, resolved the capacity for happiness into the capacity for pleasurable satisfaction. This makes a difference. When we say that we value a human life because it can be rendered "happy" the word may pass, because it can be made as it often has been made to cover so much. It is quite another thing when it is narrowed down to mean no more than pleasurable satisfaction or escape from pain. We are at once conscious then of a swift descent to a less inspiring level. Easy enough to regard our fellow-men as worth caring for and working for on the ground that they have great capacities for " happiness " : not so easy when we think of them as simply dowered with capacities to welcome pleasure and abhor pain. Not that increase of pleasures and diminution of pains is a small matter. These count for much in most men's plan of life; and so long as this is fact, it is reasonable that they should also count for much in the sympathetic recognition that the lives of our neighbours are similar to * See " Political Obligation," page 23, and " Prolegomena to Ethics," Sections 213 and 356. JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 73 our own. Nay, when we realise how many and how varied, how pure, elevated, and satisfying, are the pleasures of which human nature is capable, which of us will deny that the thought of bringing pleasures into the lives of fellow- men supplies a powerful incentive? Not least in cases where these lives, despite all their capacities for happiness, have been starved, cheerless, and wretched. For if many persons think it worth their while, and even accept it as a duty, to make the lives of their four-footed dependents comfortable and happy, it can hardly be unreasonable to be moved to do the same for fellow-men who are so infinitely more capable of pleasurable satisfactions than even the aristocracy of the animal world. It is therefore by no means necessary to suggest that utilitarian hedonism is a failure as a gospel of good works, least of all when the motive it supplies is relief of pain. And, of course, if the hedonistic version of human nature be the true one, we must needs be content with it and justify our motives accordingly. We need not, however, be too easily content. For two reasons, the first of which is that hedonism has never lacked its assailants. Need one recall the long array of ascetic philosophers who, from the ancient Cynics onwards, have derisively denied the value of pleasure in toto. Need one suggest the still larger companv of austere moralists who have never been weary of descanting on the notorious fragility and 74 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK evanescence of all pleasures, even the best and noblest ? And, if we shrink from these extremists, we have still to reckon with the more convincing verdict of the soberer thinkers who tell us that, though pleasures and pains have their value, they drop into quite a secondary place in the economy of human nature, being indeed no more than the concomitants of life and by no means its essence. All this must needs have weight. It needs some courage, with the analysis of Aristotle, Butler, Kant, Green on the other side, to single out the capacity for pleasure as the root of human worth. The second reason is that there is another alternative to utilitarian hedonism besides naturalism or pessimism the alternative of idealism. As a doctrine of human worth idealism is by no means at war with naturalism all along the line. On the contrary, it welcomes every word that naturalism has to say about the value of the social organism. It agrees that a nation, like every other group, has come to be what it is by the long road of historical evolution. It agrees that it has a unique value in the eyes of its citizens. It agrees that it is in it that the individual finds the nurture and the opportunity without which his life, however great its capacities, would remain poor, meagre, stunted, and incomplete. Nothing is more characteristic of idealism than the zeal with which it has adopted, and translated into terms of modern life, the JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 75 old Aristotelian dicta that man is "a political " animal " and " by nature a citizen." It is therefore entirely at one with naturalism in insisting that we must always estimate the value of the individual in the light of the station he occupies and the function he fulfils, in the larger organism of which he is a member. So far there is no quarrel. Divergence arises and it is decisive only when we begin to scrutinise the credentials of the value of the organism. For the distinctive note of naturalism is to identify value with strength. A group has value because it has proved its value by coming out victorious in the evolutionary struggle between group and group. On this as an accomplished fact naturalism takes its stand, and proceeds to derive the value of the individual from the proved value of the community to which he belongs. From this idealism dissents. It looks beyond the value of the group, however strong and compact : it refuses to derive the value of the individual from the value of the group, even though that group be a great and all-powerful nation : it insists that the value of the nation must ultimately be estimated in one way, and in one way alone, and that is in the light of the concrete lives of the men and women who, in organic union, are the nation. ' The life of the nation," says T. H. Green, " has no real existence except as the life "of the individuals composing the nation." Or in still more sweeping words : " To speak of "any progress or improvement or development 76 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK "of a nation or society or mankind except as "relative to some greater worth of persons is "to use words without meaning."* Hence a certain affinity between idealism and utilitarianism. Both recognise the value of the individual life. Both insist that the happiness of the community, if it mean anything, must mean the happiness of human beings. Both regard the nation, or any other group, as possessing value and both accord to. it an indisputable value precisely in so far as human capacity finds fullness of life and abiding satisfaction in and through it. To both therefore the seat and centre of worth is the human soul. But idealism is, of course, not utilitarianism. It rejects its hedonism. It refuses to find the ultimate ground of worth in the capacity for pleasure. If affirms that, on that conception of human nature, the belief in the worth of the individual would remain for ever inexplicable. And so it does its best to furnish a better. Why then should idealism, any more than naturalism or utilitarianism, succeed in finding grounds for the ascription to the individual of value, worth, and dignity? It was with this problem we set out, and it is with the idealist's answer to it we must end. The answer is comparatively easy, so long as we limit our view to the aristocracy of the moral life. In the best men we know, and still more in the shining examples which the vast range of * " Prolegomena to Ethics," Section 184. JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 77 recorded experience furnishes, we seem to find a dutiful spirit and a devotion to ideals which irresistibly compel our respect and often evoke our reverence. Who can deny it? At first, and to the last, this respect or reverence is an emotion. But even from the first, and ever-increasingly as experience deepens, it is far more. For it goes with the ever-clearer perception that, in the best types, this dutiful devotion, this devotion to ideals, permeates and vitalises the individual life through and through. The large interests of public life and the small details of private inter- course, the patriotic service of country and the unobtrusive fidelity to the claims of business, home, and friendship they are all alike pene- trated by the one spirit. It is a spirit variously described by analysts. Some would call it a constraining consciousness of a law of Duty, others would prefer to describe it as devotion to a supreme Good. But, however described, it is manifestly there. We seem to be clearly conscious of it as the best thing in our own lives, even when we are far from having lived up to it; and we are confirmed in that estimate by the knowledge of what it can be and do in the lives of the men who have made and maintained the moral traditions of our race. But perhaps we need not labour this point. Few would have the hardihood to deny that, if this be a true transcript of human nature, if all men were such as these, they would be worth all and more than all the service that man can render to man. 78 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK But, of course, the vast majority of our " accursed race " can make small claim to stand on this exalted level. Long and diversified is the scale of moral value which descends from the best to the worst. And the difficulty, of course, is to justify the ascription of worth, not to those who manifestly merit our help, but to those who manifestly need it. Can the idealistic conception of human nature justify this? Can it justify that recognition of the claims and worth of all men, even the waifs and failures? Now we need not here commit ourselves to the assertion that even the worst specimens of our race have " worth " : it may be granted that the pathology of morals can find, in the ranks of the incurably vicious and desperately criminal, individuals with reference to whom " worth " is a word not so much as to be mentioned. Society, it is true, and especially Christian societies, have not despaired even of them. But even Christian societies have long been convinced that some of them are not fit to live. And yet these cases must not be allowed to depress unduly our estimate of human nature. For we need not despise the consolation such as it is that many a life, even when it fills us with disgust and despair is the baleful result of the perversion of capacities and desires which, under better influences, might have had a vastly different history. Such perversion is doubtless deplorable : vice, crime, and insanity are among its products. But it is not wholly discouraging. At very least it suggests JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 79 that human nature is modifiable. And with that fact may come the hope that, if modifiable for the worse, then peradventure modifiable for the better, if only it can find direction, care, and treatment. Lamentable though the tragedy of moral lapse must necessarily be, it is not a spectacle that fills one with blank despair, so long as we can see in ft the misdirection and waste of human powers which might have had a better ending. One need not press this point unduly : it remains too much of a paradox to find grounds for hope in the hideous vices and crimes of mankind. And yet these ghastly facts are not altogether without their hopeful side. It is more to the point that idealism can draw encouragement from the belief in evolution. For it is amongst the happy results of this belief that it opens the eyes to the extent to which small and even unpromising beginnings may lead on to notable endings. By habituating our minds to the idea of continuity of growth, it forbids us to set up those dividing barriers between the less-developed and the more-developed barriers which parted the serf and even the artisan by a great gulf from the citizen in the ancient world.* On the contrary, it helps us to see the makings of a law-abiding citizen in a savage, of a freeman in a slave, of a civilised human being in a barbarian. The process upwards may be slow; and it would be blindness to overlook the fact that there is such a thing as arrested development, * See page 20. 8o ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK not to say degeneration. Yet, despite all qualifi- cations, the belief in evolution remains a cheerful faith cheerful not only because of the results to which it points forwards, but because of the light it throws backwards upon all the earlier stages from actually achieved advance. Even glaring inferiorities of man to man wear a new and more hopeful aspect in the scale of value from the moment when they come to be regarded as containing even the far-off promise of the sterling qualities of character from which we never dream of withholding our tribute of respect when we meet them in their more highly- developed forms. It is thus that the belief in evolution enables us to use our estimates of the higher in uplifting and humanising our valuations of the lower through all the many degrees of human inequality. Nor do we fail to find in experience what the belief in evolution thus suggests. We find it, idealism at any rate claims to find it, as result of ethical analysis. For one of the most certain of all the results of an examination of human faculty is the discovery that the natural desires of man are in their very nature progressive. In human experience the satisfaction of a desire is not simply an event that happens, to be again and again repeated as the days or years go round; it becomes the occasion for discovering, or inventing, some new end or object which may satisfy some fresh desire. Well might the Greeks call desire " insatiable," and Carlyle call it JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 81 " infinite." For nothing could be harder than to set limits to the possible objects of satisfaction which human eagerness can discover and human resourcefulness invent, except to set limits to the capacities of response which such objects evoke as soon as they shape themselves before the mind's eye of a lacing in whom the hunger for satiety is forever shadowed by unrest, and who can no more cease to crave, to hope, to seek than he can cease to wish to live. So it is now, and so will it remain in sazcula s&culorum, so long as, by the very constitution of man, the sanguine forward-struggling cravings of the human spirit emerge in inseparable fusion with the dawnings of imagination and forward-looking thoughts. The veriest savage, serf, or drudge, unless by prolonged degradation he be brutalised, has still some power of picturing, and craving for, some better future than the daily life of hand-to-mouth. Nor is it by any means the men of affluence, of station, or of ideas who are oftenest visited by these longings for a better life than has fallen to their lot. Grant that the ideal may be homely and unambitious, though it need be neither. Grant even that it may be mistaken and illusory in many a case. The fact nevertheless remains unshaken that human nature discloses the presence of progressive capacities and powers which, however they may be obstructed, can never be quenched, not even by the long array of hostile influences which frustrate in ten thousand ways the inherent potencies and promise of life. 82 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK It is these capacities and powers that lie before the social worker as the material with which he has to deal. Can he doubt that the material is of value sufficient to justify ten times over the best he can do for it? Can he doubt it when he remembers what it can become in those shining examples of moral achievement which compel his admiration and reverence? And far short of that, can he doubt it when he simply thinks of the multitude of decent and self-respecting lives who, though far enough from claiming to be examples, have yet, in face of all obstructions, borne their unobtrusive witness to the worth of life by the lives they have lived. Add to this the consciousness of available resources, never nearly so many or so great as now. The salutary pressure of social institutions from the family onwards, the moralising and enlightening influences of education in its widest sense, the uplift of religion, the eager effort of voluntary associations, the far-reaching possibilities of democratic legislation and admini- stration when we think of what these instruments of civilisation are, and may become, what can be more reasonable than the sober optimism which ventures the hope that, in the long path a nation has to travel, social effort will be abundantly justified by its fruits, because it is already justified by the value, actual and potential, of those who are its objects. Nor ought we to fall into the illusion all too common in a philanthropic age like ours that JUSTIFICATION OF MOTIVES 83 social motive is mainly concerned with the failures, laggards, and wastrels of our civilisation. Social effort has an infinitely wider scope. Its objects are none other than our fellow-workmen in all classes of work, and our fellow-citizens in all ranks, classes, and degrees. Not compassion, but respect, is the fit word to describe our right attitude to them and their right attitude to us. For these motives to social work at their best and highest are not the peculiar possession of any class or section in a truly democratic state. They are the common property of all good citizens united in the pursuit of that public good which finds its gradual realisation in the lives of men of every rank and class. rv.-cmzENSHiP AND IDEAL INTERESTS.* The life of every citizen may be written in two chapters. The one records what his city does for him; the other what he does for his city. Many and diverse as are the aspects in which we may view our city's many-coloured life, these two stand out : it is the place of preparation and equipment for the serious work of life, and it is the place where the serious work of life is done. When we think of all that an average good citizen gets from his city, it is manifest at a glance that he by no means gets everything. In these days of mobility, when citizenship comes to so many by naturalisation and not by birth, the springs of life may rise in other places, in other cities, perhaps, or in quiet corners of the country which may long continue to feed our lives through memories which are the strength and solace of solitary hours. Others again may, of course, bring back from travel, or occasional residence in other surroundings, impressions and ideas which vitally An Address to the Liverpool and Krkenbead Raskin Society. CITIZENSHIP & IDEAL INTERESTS 85 mould their characters and pursuits. Others, still, may travel with their minds, and on these far journeys of the spirit absorb influences from Greece, Rome, Judaea which may penetrate their lives to the core. So to be able to live, in fruitful imaginative contact with what is distant or remote, is, in fact, one of the marks of civilisation. It was the dream of Aristotle that the city-state which, following Plato, he idealised in his " Politics," could be so organised as to be the source and vehicle of all the influences which, from cradle to grave, inspire and mould the individual life. But we may grant at once that no such conception is possible for us. To the modern spirit there has come a consciousness of wider personal relations to Nature and to God which opens the way to influences which cannot be said to need the city or even the nation as indispensable intermediary. And there has also come, in the broad wake of Stoicism and Christianity, that larger outlook upon civilisation and that knowledge of many other forms of social life besides our own, which has begotten a cosmopolitan attitude for which we search in vain in the ideal State of Aristotle. This being so, even the most civic of citizens, if he be not blind, must acknowledge that he may find within him experiences and incentives which cannot, with substantial justice, be credited to even the most paternal of modern nations, far less of modern cities. This, however, is not a line of thought we 86 need at present further pursue. Broadly it remains true that most which a man gets comes to him through the city where his lot is cast. It is the home of his own people, the place of his schooling, the corner of the world's workshop in which he by and by finds his vocation. It is there his eyes are gradually opened to the larger life, so overwhelming in its magnitude, so irresistible in its force, which rushes on around him. Even from early years he sees his seniors caught up into the torrents of commercial and political and religious life, and his own calling, even though obscure and humble, begins to open out large vistas. By and by he is caught up into these currents himself. It is then he begins to realise the mixed blessings of becoming ratepayer and taxpayer; not, however, without the compensating satisfactions of enjoying not only those civil rights whereby his person, property, and reputa- tion are safeguarded, but likewise those political rights which are the peculiar heritage and pride of the citizen of democracy. Institutions of many kinds cease to be the mere names or notions which is all they were to the unawakened con- sciousness of his youth : in the form of the religious organisation, the friendly or co-operative society, the trades union, the political party (not to mention many a lesser group) they become realities which exist for serious, permanent, and far-distant ends. Nor, if he be wide awake, can he miss the fact that through these and other local institutions the local press, for example, or the CITIZENSHIP & IDEAL INTERESTS 87 local college or university many of the influences of the outside world are focussed and brought to bear upon his life with decisive effect. Now in all these ways the citizen manifestly gets much. He has not made these institutions which so masterfully shape his destiny : he finds them already made. They are the work of many minds and many hands, through whose energies, sometimes commemorated but for the most part forgotten, they have been woven together into the many-coloured fabric, or rather (one ought to say) organised into the richly-integrated life of the city. Into this as his inheritance, the magnitude of which is hidden from most by its familiarity, the citizen comes. It will not, I imagine, be denied that it is a goodly heritage. It binds the individual to the city by many ties. It unites him to fellow- citizens in the partnership of common interests. It links on his personal lot, otherwise so fleeting and insignificant, to that corporate life of the community which is neither insignificant nor fleeting. And it brings the assurance, which most men need, that the causes in which they have been enlisted will be carried forward long after they are gone. All this and it would be easy to enlarge upon it is certainly a substantial instal- ment of what we mean by citizenship. Yet it is only an instalment. For it is not what a man takes from his city that makes him citizen : it is rather what he gives. Nor will anyone ever get what the city of his birth or adoption has in 88 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK its gift unless, on his part, he gives it of his best. We can see this conclusively if we glance at what many seem most to value, and to regard as especially distinctive of civic status, their rights. Often enough we speak of our rights as if they were gifts, boons, or privileges bestowed upon us by the community. Not without reason. Have we not just been calling them an inheritance? But let it never be supposed that the mere having or holding of rights makes the citizen : it is the using of them. For that end are rights given. This is, to be sure, a truism, yet it is a truism which some reformers seem to have to learn. For it is just the reformer who has been passionately absorbed in the struggle for rights who is apt at times to look no further than the day when he could rest in the knowledge that rights had been won. But the value of a right is never proved by the winning of it, nor yet by the arguments advanced in winning it. It depends upon what it enables its possessor to do and to be after he has won it. This holds of every right. Good, of course, that a man's property should be secure; but for appreciation of the value of that fundamental right, we must surely look to those who are able as well as willing to earn and to keep property to secure ? So with the right of free speech : we are not likely to undervalue it, being (as of course it is) of the essence of our liberties. But its value depends. It depends upon whether it becomes in its possessor the condition of words of truth and CITIZENSHIP & IDEAL INTERESTS 89 soberness or words of falsehood and folly. Similarly with political rights. Small indeed, and it may be less than nothing, is the value of the " gift " of the franchise, if the men or women who have received it either never use it at all through indifference, or use it with an irresponsible levity infinitely worse than total abstention. The same principle holds of everything the city (or the nation) has in its gift. For it is a law of life, and there is none more inexorable, that it is those who give most who get most. It is so from our early years. The home gives us much who will deny it? but what is it more than a convenient lodging-house, if there be in the youthful heart no response to the family affections ? The school gives us much : but what schoolmaster has not felt the barrenness of his work if the stirrings of intellectual life do not come half-way to meet his efforts ? Similarly with all that friends and advisers may do to plan our lives and smooth the path to success. Little that will profit in those who fail to rise to their opportunities. So throughout. The most admirable institutions, the best appliances the city has to offer, will not suffice to make a single citizen worthy of the name. For the truth is that citizen- ship cannot be given : it has to be earned. The citizen cannot be made, because he 'must be self- made. For it is never by passive citizenship that character and will are developed. "Activity is the lord of life," as Aristotle told the world long ago, and it is but an application of the dictum to 90 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK add that no one need hope to bring into his life the stuff and substance which the life of the city has in its gift unless he is prepared to give sympathy, money, energy, and patience to club, friendly society, trades union, political party, church, chapel, or what not. There are writers in these days who discern and lament the blight of civic indifference. They lament that institutions lack support, that there are all too many willing enough and eager to take all the advantages of their position except their share of public work. It is lamentably true. But it is not the city that suffers most. The city can and will go forward in spite of its laggards ; it can carry a deal of dead weight. The real sufferers are the laggards themselves, who miss their opportunities. For the lukewarm citizen is by that very fact a lesser man. He may have his private virtues. One hopes he has them in abundant measure, for he will need them all to compensate for his fatal poverty of public interests. But in order that this active citizenship may yield its fruits, it manifestly postulates conditions, and indeed nothing less than a sufficiently rich and varied environment. This lies on the threshold, because it is only when this is forthcoming that justice can be done, not only to the diverse instincts and aptitudes of different men, but to the varied capacities of many-sided men. The community must, in short, gather up into its CITIZENSHIP & IDEAL INTERESTS 91 organised life many, and, so far as possible, all the great and valued ends by the pursuit of which characters are enriched and wills invigorated and developed. Suppose the opposite. Imagine this city and district were what some say all England is coming to be, " the coalpit and workshop of the world." How great a boon and what matter of rejoicing to those whose aptitudes and interests lie to coalpits and foundries ! Without doubt there would be activity enough, and enterprise enough, the prodigious enterprise and activity of the Black Country or the Clyde Shipbuilding Yards. But meanwhile, how would it fare with the men whose instincts were political, or scientific, or literary, or artistic, or religious? Would they not be conscious of a spiritual starvation? Would they not live in a perpetual spirit of revolt against the bleakness and barrenness of their environment? Would there be no risk that the artisans and men of business would be dehumanised by the intolerable monotony and limitation of their sordidly specialised lives ? Not certainly because coalpits, yards, and foundries are other than desirable not to say indispensable things, but for quite other reasons which in their cumulative force are convincing. Because even a very ordinary human being is sufficiently aware of the existence of cravings and capacities in himself and in his fellows to make it natural to long for surroundings in which there are many other things to live for beyond a coalpit and workshop 2 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK millennium. Because students of human nature have long been opening our eyes to the amazing fertility, persistence, insatiability, and progressiveness of man's desires and aspirations. Because the history of civilisation is one long record of the endless resourcefulness of the human spirit in discovering or inventing new and ever-new objects of desire and effort upon which those desires and aspirations are fed. Because it stands upon record how, when human faculty has grasped the skirts of happy chance, as in the glorious heyday of the Athenian State, the civic spirit has responded to favouring environment in a fashion which has ever since been the wonder of the world. And, may we add, because even in the less joyous and more obstructed cities of our modern world, the latent capacities of the community have been undeniably evoked by every fresh advance in industrial or hygienic or political or educational conditions. With these facts in mind, who will say that it is unreasonable to cherish the hope that the city of our birth or adoption may gather up into a many-sided life, in measure worthy of its greatness, all the main ends and interests which make for the strength and development of the lives of its sons ? It is true that, from one point of view, this may seem Utopian. For these modern cities, unlike the self-centred, self-sufficing, self-complete little city-states of the Greek world, are of course but parts of a larger whole; and, as such, are, even when highly organised, called each to its special CITIZENSHIP & IDEAL INTERESTS 93 function and destiny in that larger organism, the nation. Nor is it to be disputed that it is just by this differentiation of city from city that the massive life of the nation is broadened and enriched. And this is certainly a good reason why we should be content that every city should develop along its own lines, and that we, here in this haven of the world, should be not only content but eager that Liverpool should be pre-eminent amongst the cities of the world for its commerce. But it is not a good reason, it is not a reason at all, for acquiescing in this specialised destiny to all lengths. The right inference points in quite the opposite direction. If our city be in the van in commerce, this is one of the best of reasons for wishing, and working, that it should not lag ingloriously in the rear in these other not less precious things which give substance and worth to human life. For this, though not the dictate of industrial specialisation, is the condition of individual development and the path, the only path, to a satisfying citizenship. This holds of all specialised forms of city life. The dominant note may be manufacture or commerce or politics or religion or war or art or science or amusement. And each centre is bound to fulfil its destiny in the national economy. Yet never in such a way as to forget that there are other ends and interests besides those which are conspicuously its own, by neglect of which the lives of its citizens will be irretrievably impoverished. Therefore the entire reason- 94 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK ableness of that ambition, which so happily inspires not a few in our midst, to plant and water in this city all the most valued products of civilisation which lie within its reach. For this is so far from being a mere " devout imagination " that it is the plain dictate of the fundamental law that all individual development is inevitably relative to the quality of the environment, and that it is by living interaction between the little life of the individual and the larger life of the city that the citizen is made. But this it once creates a problem the difficult problem of comparative values. It is easy to see that the main elements of a full and complete life have value, taken separately. For if some of them do not sufficiently impress us by what we see, or fail to see, in our own city, we can easily supplement our experience by what we see elsewhere. In this way Liverpool can learn from Oxford, and Oxford from Liverpool ; Portsmouth from Canterbury, and Canterbury from Ports- mouth; Birmingham from Edinburgh, and Edinburgh from Birmingham. What is not so easy is to make up our minds as to the comparative prominence we wish to assign to this element or that to commerce, public health, politics, religion, soldiering, art, learning, beautiful surroundings, and so on within the life of our own city. A really great city, a city that aspires to vitalise and socialise and humanise the lives of its inhabitants, must, I have been suggesting, try to recognise them all. But, then, CITIZENSHIP & IDEAL INTERESTS 95 as we have just admitted, no two cities need expect to absorb them in the same proportions. They cannot so long as city differs from city in geographical position, in access to natural products, in history and traditions, in actual work, in destiny. This being so, there devolves upon every active citizen the problem we have mentioned the inevitable problem of making up his mind what the comparative values ought to be in the local civic ideal. And this problem is accentuated because current popular estimates seem so haphazard and conflicting; this valuator insisting that a city without a University or an Art Gallery is not worthy of the name, that valuator declaring that a city has not so much as the right to build a Cathedral till all its poor are decently housed and fed. Now, to help us to solve this problem of comparative values, there is no lack of social ideals. Men of genius have been delineating ideal communities since the days of Plato; and such ideals, under the dominating influence of ideas of unity and proportion inseparable from all true imaginative construction, necessarily select the elements of human well-being and exhibit them in perspective. And, when this perspective is the result of careful valuations, it would be rash and ungrateful to suggest that our own valuations either can or ought to remain unaffected thereby. For that reason a course of reading about Utopias is certainly no bad preparation for the social reformer. But of 96 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK course these ideals can never solve for us our own particular problem. For the most part they are Utopias or " nowheres." However rich in detail, they are abstract in the sense that they are divorced from actual concrete situations; and however the student 'may steep himself in their valuations, the actual problem which concerns us here is still unsolved when we pass from the mere " pattern in the heavens " to the exceedingly concrete situation of our own actual city. To the citizen of Liverpool hesitating, let us say, between the claims of Housing of the poor and a Cathedral, or between the urgencies of Public Health and the cause of Higher Education, or between the regulation of the traffic in drink and the purchase of Old Masters, it is not enough to point him to an abstract " nowhere." Because of course Liverpool is but one amongst a number of actual cities whose practical comparative valuations must be expected to diverge. And it is precisely these concrete local valuations which are so peculiarly puzzling. And yet few things are more important. For, in the rush and scramble of a city's life, the comparative valuations are only too apt to be forgotten. This one presses for Housing, that one for Education, a third for Finance, a fourth for Art, and so on they are all admirable because their ends are all good. But under this municipal division of labour, each one pursuing his own particular concernment, each one striving with his neighbour in this honourable rivalry of ends, the just CITIZENSHIP & IDEAL INTERESTS 97 perspective, the sane and judicious balance of the civic ideal is forgotten or ignored. Nor was this risk ever so great as now, when so many civic ends and schemes are clamouring for money and service. Hence the peculiar need for well- considered and firm comparative valuations, or, in simpler words, the need of a clear notion of what we wish our city to be. Now there appear to be some quite simple principles on which all such valuations should be made, and amongst these the fundamental principle that, in all our estimates of ends and institutions, the scale of civic value is not to be confused with the scale of civic urgency. Thus nothing can well be more urgent than public health : it involves the lives of men. Nor than industrial and commercial prosperity, which, needless to say, holds in its hands the happiness and even the bare livelihood of thousands of struggling families. Nor need it be disputed that a city, however splendid its achievements in other directions, is a disastrous failure if these great material props of its life be rotten. Therefore it is easy to understand why so many persons seem to think that the only sound civic policy is to make solid work (as they regard it) by beginning from below and moving upwards ; in other words, by concentrating sympathy, effort and expenditure upon sanitation, law and order, elementary education, industrial organisation, and such-like, and by refusing to lift a finger to organise and equip higher education or to found museums and 98 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK art galleries, or to rear stately public buildings, and so forth, till every honest citizen is well-fed, well-housed, and decently clad. Nor is this an ideal of which anyone need be ashamed; for it is often motived by a depth of sympathy with hardship and suffering, which commands respect. But it is a mistaken ideal none the less. It views the growth of a city mechanically as if it were the building of a house, of which the foundations must be complete before any superstructure can be reared thereon. But the fact stands otherwise. A city is an organism. And this being so, its friends and administrators can no more afford to neglect the less urgent, but not less valuable, elements of civic life than the father of a family can - postpone the moral and intellectual education of his sons until their bodies have reached maturity. Even as, in the growing boy, the tiny shoots of intellectual promise must, on penalty of the impoverishment of a lifetime, be vigilantly fostered, so in the larger organism, the less urgent, less immediately necessary ends and interests, which may by and by render it famous, must be recognised and encouraged long before the city has become great in industry and commerce. Indeed, if the analogy may be pressed, it dips in favour of the social organism. For in the life history of the city there is little corresponding to precocity in individual development. Seldom indeed, if ever, is the culture of the more ideal products premature in it. The besetting danger lies in the opposite CITIZENSHIP & IDEAL INTERESTS 99 direction. It is so easy for the utilities which are obvious, tangible, necessary, urgent, to be pushed to the front, and for the spiritualities, the " goods of the soul," as the Greeks used to call them, to be ignored or thrust into the background. Yet this is precisely the result which, in the name of a sound ideal an ideal reflecting right valuations must not be allowed to happen. And for the following reasons. In the first place if you will forgive the repetition, however brief, of an overworn educational commonplace the affairs of a great city have become so complex that the conduct of them demands the developed intelligence, the well-informed mind, the disciplined will, the sound judgment of the leaders of men in all walks of life. This holds of the conduct of industry and commerce in its vast and complicated operations : it holds of municipal administration which seems so steadfastly bent upon annexing^ new provinces : it holds of the whole network of private charities and voluntary associations. Hence the exhortations, reiterated till we are weary of them, to bestir ourselves in the Higher and Technical Education. We may safely, however, take all this as read, and pass, as a second reason, from a platitude to- a paradox. The paradox is that, in order to value at their true worth the more urgent, necessary, and material energies of civic life, it is never enough that a man should know these well : he must also have learnt to value the more ioo ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK ideal products. For it is a grievous error to think that those who are most exclusively absorbed in material pursuits appreciate them most highly. The truth is that these pursuits will never be estimated at their genuine worth, or invested with their true significance and dignity, except by those whose eyes have been opened to the extent to which, in every highly-organised civilisation, the less material elements of our lives are reared upon industrial prosperity, commercial enterprise, and adequate finance. What, one may well ask, would become of our hospitals and charities with their elaborate equipment, or of our schools, universities, churches, with their endowments and organisation, or of the costly treasures of museums and art galleries, were it not for the strenuous work of workshop and office? Hence the folly, and ignorant ingratitude, of men of the study or men of ideas when they belittle the business life, or satirise it as vulgar, or denounce it as materialistic. Surely their valuations are all awry. For it is to them we might reasonably look to magnify the value even of the hewing of wood and drawing of water, because, presumably, they live in the light of the knowledge that the more ideal ends and interests for which they stand would quickly shrink into an impoverished insignificance were they not so firmly under- propped by industrial and commercial enterprise. The true message of the man of ideas to the business world is not absurdly to exalt his own vocation above that of men whose virtues and CITIZENSHIP & IDEAL INTERESTS 101 abilities may possibly surpass his own, but to point out that the full significance and value of the material substratum of life can only be understood in the light of the more spiritual superstructure which may be reared on that secure and honour- able foundation. It is a small and occasional part of an idealist's task, if, indeed, it be part of it at all, to vituperate material progress : his better course is to try to spiritualise it by pointing out that, by the very laws of social growth and structure, it is organically bound up with other, and, as we sometimes call them, higher things. This however, I hasten to admit, must not be taken for granted. It involves the large assumption that the more ideal interests, the " spiritual superstructure," not only have value for few, I imagine, would deny them all value- but that they have social value so great as to justify those who believe in them as you in this Ruskin Society do in setting them in the fore- front of a civic ideal. This, of course, is just what may be disputed. For we must here face facts : and facts compel the suspicion -one hopes it may not be true- that in the eyes of the majority, some of the ideal products at all events literature and learning, art and science, stately buildings, dignified streets,, beautiful parks, are still no more than embellishments, decorations, " extras," and therefore not for a moment to be put on the same level of value in the scale of civic enterprise as the more urgent ends and interests 102 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK of civic life. Nor is it to be denied that there is reason in this. We are bound to face the fact that, in proportion as ends and interests are ideal, they are not enjoyable, or at any rate not -enjoyed in anything approaching to equal measure, by all. Quite naturally, therefore, it seems doubtful to not a few (and some of ihem far from ignorant or uneducated) if collective effort is justified in working for ends which only a minority seem able to enjoy. Whence this widespread conviction that (whatever private enterprise may please to do) it is hardly in the name of citizenship that public expenditure and -effort upon these " extras " can ever be justified at all. I have put this point of view strongly though not, I think, too strongly because it appears to me that in the name of a civic ideal worthy of our city it is quite untenable. For, in the first place, it is to be borne in mind that nothing could be more fatal to the future of a great city than that civic effort should limit itself to the provision of things which can be enjoyed in equal measure by all its inhabitants. For as a matter of fact there is nothing a city can do for its inhabitants which is not unequally enjoyed. Two heads of families become, shall we say, tenants of a Corporation tenement : the one finds in his couple of rooms a clean and 'decent family life : the other, with help of wife and children, does his best to reduce his to the level of the pig-sty from which he has emerged. CITIZENSHIP & IDEAL INTERESTS 103 Two men send their children to the same spacious Elementary School, splendidly equipped at the ratepayers' expense : the one invests the remission of fees in improving the family budget : the other increases his budget of beer and tobacco. This is so always, nor can it be evaded. So long as men's instincts and capacities and characters, and powers of appreciation and enjoyment, are unequal, that city which limited its efforts narrowly to what could be equally enjoyed would find its occupation gone. This much one may say, to prevent ourselves from being impressed overmuch by abstract ideas of equality. But of course these considerations take us but a little way towards the solution of our problem. Even the commonest things are unequally shared true, but that does not dispose of the fact that some things are substantially enjoyable by multitudes (however diverse their degrees of appreciation as individuals), and that other things are directly and fully enjoyable only by a comparative handful. No one is likely to deny that sanitary homes, clean streets, cheap locomotion, elementary education, good municipal government, can be enjoyed by multitudes. But what are we to say of the rare treasures of a Museum, the costly walls of an Art Gallery, a great public Library with many thousand volumes that comparatively few ever read, a High School that draws upon the rates, or a University distinguished by municipal support. Directly, these institutions are utilised only by a section of io 4 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK our vast population : the harvest they offer is reaped in anything like full measure only by a minority. And if this be so, we are still face to face with our problem : Is it justifiably a civic obligation to provide for them? It is a question we need not fear to face : it admits of answers. 1. One of these answers is that the ends, objects, or causes for which the institutions just mentioned stand are recognised, and have long been recognised, as having an immeasurable national, not to say universal value in the valuations alike of the great prophets and teachers of our race, and of the multitudes who have called them masters. Therefore it devolves upon the city, as an organic part of the nation to which it rejoices to belong, to take its share, to play its part, by furthering them up to the limits of its powers and resources. Never will the arts and sciences flourish in a manner worthy of the mission of a great nation to civilisation if they are left to look for support only to great seats of learning or other specialised centres of spiritual life. No : they must enlist the immense favouring forces of local civic patriotism. 2. A second answer is that in every great city there arise from time to time minds of such rare natural endowment that they repay a thousand-fold the best that can be done for them. Such minds and powers and they may emerge from very humble homes have in them incontrovertibly the seeds of greatness. Beyond CITIZENSHIP & IDEAL INTERESTS 105 doubt they are amongst the greatest gifts and boons which Nature gives to a nation. And many of them still spiritually survive in full career of influence even though the cities that reared them have long ago been levelled with the dust. Surely such are worth watching for, and when they arise, worth caring for? Is public money wasted, is civic effort misdirected, if it can help in from time to time nurturing into the plenitude of his marvellous powers even one great scholar, artist, musician, architect, engineer, surgeon, statesman? Cities are always proud of their great men : they rejoice to catch the reflection of their glory : they are quick to claim a borrowed credit from their achievements. No one would grudge them this. It is admirable. But we should all concede it more readily to the city that has done most to make its great men possible. 3. But, then, the population of a city is happily not divided into the geniuses who come but rarely and an indistinguishable mob of nonentities. There are gradations, and amongst these two classes are distinguishable. The one consists of the men, some rising to the level of distinction, but most falling below it, whose is the congenial task sometimes simply to work out in detail the ideas and discoveries of the great originative minds, and sometimes to make their own small contributions to research, or artistic creation, or literature, or reflective thought. Individually their work may be insignificant, but it is by their 106 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK collective contribution, which is immense, that the world of literature, science, art, philosophy, is won. The other class stands on another plane. They have no pretensions to distinction : they make no contributions to the things of the mind. But in one point they may, if they will, challenge comparison even with the man of genius : they can enter, with a joy and appreciation as genuine and sincere, though not so penetrating and exalted, into the intellectual and spiritual wealth of their country. There are the men and one sometimes thinks their lot is the happiest of all who, whatever be their avocation, can contentedly and whole-heartedly enjoy a good book, an interesting discovery, a great picture, a noble building. In that respect they need be second to none, not even to the genius. And in regard to them there are two truths which must, I think, be borne in upon the mind of everyone who has spent his life in a great city like ours with his eyes open : the one, that there already exists within it a great multitude of such men, the other that, given opportunities and encouragement, their number can be vastly, and indeed indefinitely, increased. Do you say that these men these two classes of men may well be left to take care of them- selves? Yes, happily and up to a point they can. They have books and friends, and teachers and preachers, and societies like this, to which they can go to feed their minds and keep their souls alive. But it is just in doing this that they CITIZENSHIP & IDEAL INTERESTS 107 furnish evidence that they have claims on the city of their birth or adoption. For these hungers and thirsts of the human spirit far more truly human than the homely appetite for meat and drink cannot in these days be adequately appeased on what the individual man can be left to forage and find unaided. With every forward step in national advance, they call for increased facilities and equipment such as no private man, or group of private men, can adequately procure. They call for public libraries, laboratories, museums, art galleries, high schools, universities, buildings, gardens, parks : and, some would add, for municipal theatres and orchestras. To what extent is of course dependent on the demands of other less ideal and more urgent interests upon the city's resources. Hence the problem of comparative values perpetually recurs, and each generation must do its best to solve it by looking broadly and fairly at the good of the city as a whole. For this is of the essence of the civic spirit. But whatever that solution may be, it is not too much to say that all that has as yet been done for the more ideal interests in great commercial centres like our own, though munificent when compared with the past, is after all but a beginning, in proportion to the strength and potentialities of the needs and cravings which such provision is designed to satisfy. Nor is there the slightest violation of a true democratic equality in the expenditure of effort and resources on these ideal ends, though those io8 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK who can reap the full harvest remain a minority. The real contradiction of social equality is monopoly the enjoyment of anything by a class to the exclusion of another class. And with monopoly the democratic spirit can make no terms. But it is not monopoly that one citizen should make more use of a public library than his neighbour, if the opportunities are alike for both ; or that an art gallery should be as it must for ever remain the peculiar delight and privilege of the lover of pictures, provided the like opportunity is open to all ; or that a university should do more for the capable and clever than for the less gifted brethren, so long as the path to degrees and distinctions lies open, by free student- ships and scholarships, to the scholars who may come from the humblest of homes. In such things as these there is nothing at variance with the democratic spirit. On the contrary there is only a realisation, which does one good to think of, of the democratic watchword, " Tools to the man who can use them." Nor ought it ever to be forgotten that the great ideal interests of life cannot, under any circumstances, become the exclusive concern of the few. For it is the glory of literature, science, and art that, in our modern world, they can never be monopolised by a class. Self-absorbed and self-centred in his subject the scholar, or the man of science, may be. It is right that he should; for it is the condition of work and achievement. But that is no proof that he monopolises his LOCAL PATRIOTISM & EDUCATION. 109 subject; it is only proof that his subject has monopolised him. For all these ideal interests have this much in common with religion they are too profoundly human to suffer themselves to be appropriated by any learned or other caste. Let them once have taken firm root in a city, and nothing can stop them from diffusing, through many channels, their permeative and proselytising influence. And most of all, of course, where the members of the community are knit together in the bonds of genuine fellow-citizenship. One need but think of the inexhaustible applications of the arts and sciences to Health, Industry, Commerce, Invention, Medicine, Law, War, Politics. And then, these ideal interests can subserve other ends than these practicalities. They become, and ever-increasingly as education does its work, the meeting-points of many minds, thereby drawing men together in cheerful and fruitful comradeship such as you in this Society enjoy. They may become the basis of enduring friendships which kindred spirits often form when associated in the love and study of great books, great men, great causes. And far beyond the limits of lesser groups like this, they may become a rallying point, and a source of mutual respect and sympathy, between all these like-minded dwellers in our city, to whatsoever class they may belong, who stand, as you in this Ruskin Society do, for " the goods of the soul." V.-LOGAL PATRIOTISM AND EDUCATION.* There are undoubtedly certain aspects in which education is no friend, but rather the foe, of local patriotism. Education, we may assume, brings an enlarged horizon. Does it not put into the hands of the schoolboy, be he in Cornwall or in Caithness, the same cosmopolitan primers, the same far-circulating story books? Is it not its peculiar privilege, through the daily newspapers, to drop the same ideas, the same items of news, at the same moment, into the minds of east and west, of north and south? And of course it fails of its purpose altogether if it does not introduce the reading and studious world to that common heritage of educated men the great books that are classical, the great ideas that are universal. What, then, can seem more evident than that, in so far as the tide of education sets in this direction, it must sweep away that type of man, sometimes so attractive, whose little world is bounded by his country town or natal village, and * An Address to the Arts Students' Association in 1901. LOCAL PATRIOTISM & EDUCATION in whose public affections narrow, intense, satisfy- ing have never learned to stray beyond the local traditions, the local society, the local gossip, the local industries, the local politics? I do not forget that, in these latter days, Philology and Folk-lore, Anthropology, History, Fiction, have come to find in dialects, customs, place-names, antiquities, costumes, and indeed in most things local, a fresh significance. These ardent and admirable developments do, however, but reinforce our contention. For, in the first place, they seldom discover the value of these survivals of local life till they are just on the point of disappearing for ever, and in the second, discovery does but little towards their perpetua- tion. On the contrary, when the philologist or lover of folk-lore, or novelist in search of local colouring, enters at the door, local characteristics seem to fly out at the window. Not unnaturally. For what is the entrance of these admirable men but one of many signs that local language, customs, ideas, feelings, and so forth, are open at last to the dissolving influences of the outside world ? Let us, therefore, admit that this kind of patriotism of locality is going, and let us, if we will, deplore it. For is it not " the ending of an " auld sang " ? Yet when we find ourselves in the presence of any great idea that lays its grasp upon the human soul, the decay or dissolution of the forms it has assumed may be anything rather than a reason for lament. For it may be but a ii2 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK sign that the idea, in its unexhausted vitality, is passing on to new, it may be to higher phases. It is emphatically so with the idea of local patriotism. You will not require me here, in Liverpool, to prove that local patriotism still exists. The men of Liverpool have settled that by their lives. I refuse to argue the point, and pass on at once to assert that this spirit of local patriotism, so fully alive in our midst, may find in education one of its surest and strongest props and preservatives. For, in the first place, education enriches the ideal of local life. This is true of all local life. When a good school is for the first time opened in a village, or when a library or a learned society is founded in a country town, an element comes into the life of that place which makes it more worth a man's while to live in that corner of the world, and to work for it. But it is true most of all of a city. There are, of course, many ways in which men regard the city in which they live. It may be as the place where their fathers before them worked and found their rest, or as their own birthplace and well-remembered home, or as the scene of cherished friendships and social intercourse, or as workshop and place of business, or as arena of local politics, or as the accepted sphere for social or spiritual work. But not only is the city far more than any of these things singly, it is more than all of them added together; being, indeed, nothing less than a marvellously evolved organism, instinct with a LOCAL PATRIOTISM & EDUCATION 113 victorious life, which persists while generations come and go, in which, and through which, its citizens can redeem the span men call life by living for ends that are great and enduring. So regarded, our city need fear comparison with none. Other cities may be richer in tradition, or they may have been more fruitful of men of genius and renown, or they may be more favoured in the charm of natural surroundings. One thinks of Scott's invocation to his own romantic town, or of the lines in which Arnold pays his tribute to beautiful and storied Oxford. And though it is far from me to suggest that there is not that in Liverpool which may find its poet (Glasgow has found her poet,* why not Liverpool?), our city, of course, has had to work out a very different destiny from Oxford or Edinburgh. Yet with the result, the great and satisfying result, that she can to-day offer her sons, as few cities can, intensity and fulness of local life. This will not be doubted in respect of industry and commerce, or of law and medicine, or of politics and religion, or of social intercourse and social work in many modes. Nor, up to a certain point, is it doubtful in respect of education. In all the history of Liverpool there is nothing more honourable than the place that has come to be assigned to elementary education in our civic ideal during the past thirty years. It can never now become a subordinate end. Its claims have * Alexander Smith. ii 4 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK been sealed and for all the future accredited by the devotion of the lives that have been given to it. We are, perhaps, too apt to estimate the value of our boards and committees of school management or our training colleges simply by what they do for the schools and the children. But, when we think of lives like those of S. G. Rathbone, of the Bushells, father and sons, and of many another I need not name, nothing can be more evident than that these lives were enriched by finding in education a thing worth living for. They did much for education. Yes, and education did much for them; and for us, in enriching through them our traditions of civic patriotism. But, it is not by elementary education alone, even if this were perfect, that our civic ideal can be adequately enriched. To that end education in all its stages must enter into the very tissue of our local life. May I illustrate this by a supposition. Suppose for a moment that, for all education above the elementary school, it became possible that the young people of this city could be sent out of Liverpool to the best preparatory, the best secondary schools, the best colleges or universities to be found in the kingdom, or even in the world. And suppose that as a result there was no necessity to set up either a secondary school or a university within our borders : would this be a gain to Liverpool? Now, I do not say that these boys and girls, or young men and women, might not return with a LOCAL PATRIOTISM & EDUCATION 115 better education than they could hope to find at a local school, or a local University; though I also think they might easily find a worse. But we must also bear in mind that when they came back to settle down amongst us, they would, with their education, bring back another thing and it would never leave them all their lives a bitter and a just sense of shame that their own city the city with which they were about to cast in their lot in life with all its enterprise, its energy, its riches, its reputation, its destinies, its men, was doing nothing within its own borders for one of the greatest ends that can fill the minds and hearts of the leaders of mankind. And, indeed, I think that these school-boys, these University students of our supposition, would never rest they could not rest if they were really educated men till they had reared and endowed great local schools, and a great local University, reared them and wrought them into the organic life of the community. Nor is this supposition merely. For such has been the spirit that has inspired the founders and the friends of this institution. They have founded this University College, and, with the enterprise of masters in industry and commerce, they have decided to transform it into the University of Liverpool.* But they have done this, be sure, not merely to equip Liverpool with an institution to which it may be convenient for our citizens to- send their sons and daughters, when they cannot * This Address was given in 1901. u6 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK afford to send them away to a better. No, they have begun this work, and they will complete it, in the conviction that when a city has become as great, as rich, as famous, as manifestly called to future destinies as ours, it is bound, in education as in other things, to aim at nothing short of the best. There is an adjective that is sometimes applied to our College, and to other similar Colleges. ' The provincial Colleges," men say; not using the epithet as a geographical expression simply, but infusing into it that flavour of disparagement which is commonly suggested by the people who talk of provincial ideas, provincial manners, provincial dialect, provincial society, provincial politics, and so forth. The implication all along the line is that we of the provinces may well be content with what is second rate, and, indeed, that perhaps we are not fit to appreciate anything better. When a man is truly provincial this is precisely what he is not. It is one of the fortunate political characteristics of our country, and one of its greatest blessings, that much of the most energetic, enterprising, sane, and fruitful life of the commonwealth goes on in the provinces. Wiser words have not, in our time, fallen from the lips of politician than those in which, some years ago, Lord Rosebery dwelt upon the splendid opportunities of local and municipal life. And, indeed, the service of the city has that to offer which the larger politics can never give. It has the inspiration that comes of the nearness, the LOCAL PATRIOTISM & EDUCATION 117 urgency, the defmiteness of its problems : it has the comradeship of co-workers : it has the prospect of comparatively quick and definite results; and the worker has the advantage in seeing, every day he lives, the fruits of his labours, be it in public health, or improved housing, or the embellishment of the city, or education, or any of the great ends of civic life. Therefore, I say, let us here be what men say we are. Let us be provincial, provincial to the core, being well assured that this means that in our College that is, or in our University that is to be, we are determined in teaching, in research, in student life, in academic loyalty and comradeship, to stand second to none. What we want here, as I imagine and I think it may well content us is a university which shall be, in its spiritual fabric, as massive and well compacted as our provincial dock-walls, and as hospitable in the commerce of ideas as are our provincial harbours to the flags of all nations. But, if our civic ideal is to include all this, then it devolves on us here to play our part. Our paramount duty I am speaking not of our duty to ourselves but of our duty to the city is, up to the limits of our powers, to live the scholar's life. For the supreme law of all healthy civic life is none other than the Platonic TO TO, avrov irpdrrciv each citizen to the work he is fit for. Therefore, as the shipowner is first of all a shipowner, the merchant a merchant, the clergyman a clergyman, so is the student first of all a student. And, in n8 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK truth, if you will pardon the paradox, I would say that, as students, we may be serving Liverpool most when we are thinking of Liverpool least, when our thoughts are, it may be, far away in Athens or in Rome, or in mediae val Europe, or in the England of Elizabeth, or in one or other corner of that larger experience, into which it is our prerogative as students to enter. What Liverpool asks of you and me first is that we should represent her, if we can, as worthily in the world of letters, or science, or teaching, as did an Ismay in the world of commerce; as a Rathbone happily still does in the eventide of a long and glorious day, in the large domain of social service.* It goes closely with this that we as students are peculiarly bound, here in a great city, to stand shoulder to shoulder for the things of the mind. For it behoves us to remember that our net is not cast like that of our brethren in the older Universities of England in the sheltered waters of an academic society. It is cast in the rushing tideways of practical commercial, political, and religious life; and we may be pardoned the fear that, in face of these tremendous currents, our comparatively small ship may be swept away whither we would not. Therefore the need for association; not only for association which, like that of the Art students, * Since these words were spoken Mr. William Rathbone has passed away. It is not too much to say that simply to hare known him is of itself a kind of civic education. LOCAL PATRIOTISM & EDUCATION 119 may strengthen the connection between past and present students of Arts, nor yet only association, strong and true, between all students of all faculties, but also alliance with all friends of ideas, all lovers of books, all votaries of science or of art, whether these be within our own walls or without. I remember the remark of a friend who has had opportunities of knowing Liverpool better than most.* He was convinced, he said, that scattered up and down our city there were, in far greater number than might be supposed, men who were unostentatiously lovers of books, or in one way or another believers in the things of the mind. Be it ours to recognise all such and to establish comradeship with them, and, by the cultivation of friendly relations with the learned societies of the city, or by any other means, to uphold the ideal of the scholar. Such fellowship of all true students is the more important because the growth of local colleges has led to a confusion between two things which are entirely separable. One is the notion that a local College, even a local University, must needs take the complexion of its locality. Nothing is more reasonable. All Universities cannot be equally distinguished in all directions; and here, in Liverpool, we may well lay stress on such studies as Modern History and Modern Languages, Economic and Political Philosophy, Engineering, Architectures, Medicine, Public Health. But there must be no confusion between * Dr. John Watson. 120 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK this and that other thing, that fatal fallacy that, in our study of these or other subjects, we must clip our wings, and limit ourselves to the meagre utilitarianism that can never rise beyond quick results and direct applications. For, if we yield to that spirit, then is the scholar's life robbed for us of its very charter of freedom freedom to range unchecked that many-provinced land that is ours by right freedom to seek unfettered the truth that makes men free. There is a passage in Darwin where, discoursing of certain winged beetles which inhabit oceanic islands, he points out that the loss of wings may be of much advantage. For (so runs the explanation) the individuals with imperfectly developed or atrophied wings, are, just by reason of this deprivation, no longer liable to be carried out to sea by the wandering winds. May the students of the University of Liverpool be delivered from similar advantages ! When the winds of the spirit, that are the breath of God, arise, may we still have wings to spread to their benign constraining influences, and therewith to voyage, with Homer and Plato, with Shakespeare and Newton, over the strange, and not shoreless, seas of phantasy and thought. For this is what, as Liverpool students, we owe to Liverpool. You will not, however, suppose that in thus magnifying our vocation and we can never magnify it enough I am suggesting that we in University College sit loose, or ought to sit loose, to the life of the city. Far otherwise. Among LOCAL PATRIOTISM & EDUCATION 121 the hopes that group themselves round the project of a University for Liverpool, none is more reasonable than the confident anticipation that the students of a local University would, as the years go on, become bound to the community by ties that are increasingly strong, intimate, and enduring. This will come, in one way, through attachment to the University itself. Everyone who has had a genuine experience of it, knows that a man looks back upon his University with feelings that are unique. It is the place, perhaps, where he was first caught up into the great currents of the world's intellectual life the place of that day- break of ideas that knows no night, and of the glad confident morning of the spirit the place of frank comradeships and varied acquaintance where we form the friendship that last with life the place, too, of debates (those unending debates that need start from no premises and end in no conclusion) the place of keen, generous rivalries, of dawning ambitions, of academic vicissitudes, of honourable successes. Memorable days ! that were so good that we could not know how good they were till they were past ! To most these memories stand out as a thing apart. They are not, I mean, associated with the scenes of home and boyhood, or with the place where our work in life comes to lie. Nor is this wholly a disadvantage; it is, perhaps, the reason why this oasis rises so distinctly before the eye of memory in the dusty days of after-life. But, be this as 122 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK it may, it will certainly enrich a man's local patriotism, enrich it by a whole province, when the city of his hearth and altar, of his honourable toil, of his friendships, of his political enthusiasms and his social work, is likewise the city that gives to him these glorious crowded hours of memorable student life. I think, too, that we may claim that our studies here will give us an enhanced respect for our city. We are fond of saying, here on the Arts side of the College, that the proper object of our study is Man. This is our privilege and pride. And of course, in the prosecution of this study, we must expect as I have already said to wander far enough from Liverpool and all its ways. What then is likely to be the result of this upon our habitual estimates of Liverpool pursuits and Liverpool men? It will depend. If our studies do not take us beyond the outsides of things if we dwell simply on the material glories of the cities that have risen and crumbled, and the civilisations that have had their day and ceased to be, when the Mersey was as yet but a silent sea-swept estuary, then we may come to think that Liverpool with all its noisy life is but a little thing after all. Will it stand the contrast with Athens or Rome, with Venice or Florence? Hence the suspicion, deeply rooted in many minds, and quite natural, that the student, and especially the student of Arts subjects, must needs have his estimates of value revolutionised, and under the illusions of the past and the 123 distant fail signally to appreciate the life that is before his eyes. I do not think that it can be denied that there is truth in this. The genuine student, whose eyes have been opened by History, or Literature, or Art to see the past and the distant, cannot look out upon the world about him with the same perceptions as before. No. But it does not follow that he will appreciate and value this the less. Far from it. It is the glory of liberal studies that they give a deeper interest in all that lives. They fail of their purpose if they leave us learned, clever, critical, fastidious. Their best gifts are of quite another sort the imagination that penetrates, the insight that discerns the life under all its disguises, the human sympathy that stretches out hands of recognition across the ages. And when any man among us has these things, it will, of a certainty, be his experience that the life of this great city, however familiar, prosaic, rough, unlovely, soiled with the dust of passing circumstance, will wear in his eyes a new significance, an enhanced interest and worth; because it will be recognised as one in substance with that larger unquenchable life of Man, whose strange eventful history is the object of all our studies. Is it not the fact that our interest in our own familiar friends is never keener than when we see them the men we know so well acting under some new conjunction of circumstances? So on in the larger scale. It is the man who has really entered into the beautiful and versatile 124 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK vitality of the men of Athens, or into the austere, practical genius of the men of Rome, who will best know how to do justice to the resourceful enterprise of the men of Liverpool. There is no perversion of the student's life more lamentable than that which uses the knowledge of what is great to belittle what is at our feet. And of him whose " liberal studies " have ended thus, we can but say with Wordsworth, that he Hath faculties Which he has never used; that thought with him Is in its infancy. Need I add that this appreciation of the life of Liverpool ought to carry with it an increased respect for Liverpool men. It is necessary to say this because I am sure that practical men, some practical men at all events, believe that the student thinks himself superior. Even great students have courted this suspicion. It was Mill who said that a person of high intellect should never go into unintellectual society unless he could enter it as an apostle. And I fancy that the average citizen, if he reads Culture and Anarchy, will rise from its perusal with the conviction that the apostle of culture believes himself well qualified to try, condemn, and castigate (in the interest of sweetness and light, of course) the average man. "Culture says:" (so runs one characteristic sentence) " ' Consider these people, then, their " ' way of life, their habits, their manners, the very LOCAL PATRIOTISM & EDUCATION 125 ' tones of their voice ; look at them attentively ; ' observe the literature they read, the things ' which give them pleasure, the words which ' come forth out of their mouths, the thoughts ' which make the furniture of their minds ; would ' any amount of wealth be worth having with the ' condition that one was to become just like these ' people by having it ?' And thus culture begets " a dissatisfaction which is of the highest possible " value in stemming the common tide of men's " thoughts in a wealthy and industrial community, " and which save the future, as one may hope, " from being vulgarised, even if it cannot save the " present."* It is easy to follow the advice of Culture. We are admirably placed for following it. We can " consider these people." Yes, we can consider them in their public meetings, their committees, their educational and charitable associations, their counting-houses, their factories, their churches, their homes, with all the hopes, the struggles, the aspirations, the sorrows, the achievements that these things carry with them. And when we have done considering them, I hardly think we shall feel disposed to put the question with which " Culture " concludes the sentence I have quoted. For when we seriously consider the sterling qualities, and in many cases the supreme qualities, which the ordinary good citizen possesses industry, thrift, integrity, courage, self-reliance, enterprise, kindliness, hospitality, generosity, * " Culture and Anarchy," Popular Edition, p. 13. 126 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK munificence, sound judgment, decision, public spirit then we must see it is an idle, if not a vulgar question to ask what amount of wealth we would take to become just like these people by having it; because the qualities of " these people " are such as wealth can neither give nor buy. Truth is, that in the diverse distribution of human virtues, all fancied superiorities of class over class or calling over calling are absurd. Or, if there be one superiority which it is worth our while as students to claim, it is that of knowing how to value our fellow citizens not of the University more highly than we may hope that they may learn to value us. For of all the ties that grapple citizen to citizen, there is none more enduring, none more honourable, than the strong bond of respect for one another's work and worth. Need I, in conclusion, express the obvious and confident hope, that our institution may, besides, prove itself the nursery of active citizens. It can do this in quite specific ways. It can impart the needful knowledge. I have spoken of the tides and currents of our city's life how can we best control and make them tributary to the common good ? And where they may be, as in many ways they are, so vast as to be uncontrollable, how best secure the needful adaptation of ourselves to them? In either case the prime pre-requisite is that these forces should be understood. This is what a school of commerce, and perhaps still more a school of political science, have to do. I do not mean that these will turn out citizens ready made. LOCAL PATRIOTISM & EDUCATION 127 Impossible. It is action alone that can make the citizen, whether it be in commerce or politics. But they can at least lay that foundation of sound knowledge and trained faculty, without which the most vigorous common-sense will be blind in presence of that experience for which it rightly professes so deep a respect. For local patriotism, however ardent, loses more than half its value, it is a stream severed from its source, the moment it ceases to be intelligent. It is not enough to love our city and work for it : it is necessary to understand it. To live in memory through its history; to grasp the economics of its commerce, industry, and charity; to realise the significance of its varied races, ranks, denominations, parties; to comprehend the machinery of its government and the meaning of its manifold institutions; to do justice to its achievement and its destinies in the larger life of the Empire these are some of the things which a local University has in its gift for the citizens of this city of strenuous politics. Nor would I have our friends in the city who give so much of their lives to the larger politics forget that the students of this institution have a politics of their own. One wonders sometimes if they realise that, in the exercise of your own self-government, you have your organisations, your leaders, your parties, your constitutional experiments, your debates, elections, policies. These things have a value of their own. They need no justification beyond the purposes for which they are designed to transact your affairs, 128 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK to vitalise and enrich academic life. But it stands without saying that, just for these reasons, they feed those political instincts which are the strength of our race, and point onwards with a sure promise to the later and larger loyalties of local and imperial patriotism. VI.-PARTY AND POLITICAL CONVICTION.* There is a paradoxical passage in the Republic of Plato in which he first declares that the State in which the rulers are most reluctant to govern is best and most quietly governed, and the State in which they are least reluctant, the worst ; and then proceeds to add that the politician after his heart " will take office as a stern necessity, and " not like our present Ministers of State." It is Plato's way of saying (and there was nothing he more firmly believed) that the true politician must feed his soul on something beyond politics. If a man is to care for politics, he must not care for politics only. For only then will he attain two things which, to this great thinker, seemed indispensable; the one, an unworldly superiority to what Bentham used to call " sinister," i.e., selfish or factious interests; the other, that apprehension of enduring and inspiring ends which it behoves the politician to set himself to enact in the imperfect under-world of human affairs. *An Address to the New Century Society at the Liverpool Reform Club. i3o ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK Thus backed by Plato, might we not venture to suggest that the same thing holds on the narrower scale, and declare that no one will ever be in heart and mind a party politician unless he is convinced that party politics are not everything ; that no one, in short, will care for his party enough till he has learnt to put party in its right place as the instrument for realising ends and ideas of which no party can ever have the monopoly. :< No " monopoly ! '' may the echoes of that great Radical watchword never die ! but it would ill befit the foe of monopoly to set up the ancient idol on its base again in that least of all tolerable shapes the monopoly of political ends and political ideas. Great is party, and large is its life, even to those who can never see beyond it. But greater and larger will it become for him who can realise the magnitude of the ends the municipal ends, the national ends, the imperial ends that are greater and larger than it. This, at any rate, is the burden of my song. I suppose there is no one here who is so radical that he wishes to get rid of Party. It is part of our unwritten Constitution. It has become a condition of our political life. It has so grown not only into our constitutional organisation, but into our political habits and sentiments, that we could not shake it off even if we tried. If we disbanded our parties to-day into the anarchy of individualism pure and simple, they would begin to group themselves afresh to-morrow around new PARTY & POLITCAL CONVICTION 131 sentiments, around fresh interests. They might not group themselves to-morrow just as they are grouped to-day. For, sometimes, the traditional lines of cleavage are not the only possible lines of cleavage, or even the most natural. But parties there would be, as surely as the sun rises; and however various the species, or sub-species, might be, there would be the inevitable gravitation to those two great parties which will always exist so long as representative democratic government remains instinct with life the party of the " ins,' r and the party of the " outs." If it were an affair of opinion only, or sentiment only, it might be different; quot homines, tot sententice\ but with political parties it is more ; it is an affair of power. And so long as those who have power love it and cling to it, and those who have it not, covet it, so long will the political forces, at any rate of democratic countries, tend to range themselves in two opposing camps. I do not suggest that this is to be deplored. Even in our times of deepest disgust with the diseases of the party system (one may read them in Mr. Bryce's chapter in his American Common- wealth on the Boss and all his works) there comes the question, What would you have instead? Not despotism surely? How could it be, when even the most benevolent despotism (of the other kind be perfect silence) would at best only kill us with kindness, kill the political part of us, at any rate ; which, I take it, none of us here assembled are prepared to sacrifice, even by euthanasia. 132 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK Nor could we seriously think of entrusting ourselves to Bureaucracy, for that would only be the old doctrine of Whig trusteeship over again, with the substitution of the official for the Whig. For what does Democracy mean if not that the Democracy is minded, for better or for worse, to manage its own affairs ? And we need not despair of Democracy yet. Or is it to be representative democracy without parties'? (For there are some who cherish that aspiration.) Nor need it be denied that there are times when we might, at any rate, wish for that : at those times, namely, when we contemplate the promise and the performance, " the petty done, " the undone vast " of some particularly eloquent Parliamentary session ; or, shall we say, when we consider the result of taking all politicians at the valuation of their adversaries; or, when we see some strong and safe Foreign Secretary dislodged and compelled to go, because of the muddling of some other Minister who is neither; or, when in cool blood, we sit down and read the unchastened rhetoric of a contested election; or, simply, when in a quiet hour we ask ourselves if, after all, it can be good economy that one-half of the best men in our midst should be systematically engaged in nullifying and sterilising the efforts of the other half. And yet when all, even the very worst, is said, there always remains the misgiving that under representative democracy without the party system could such a thing exist there would probably be much more of Babel, and so PARTY & POLITICAL CONVICTION 133 much less of business in our Legislature that we might soon find ourselves longing for the good old days of Party Government. Nor need one strike the note so low. When all is said, a great party is a great instrument. It is of the rudiments of politics that if men would act with effect, they must act in alliance; and if alliance is to yield its fruit, it must be more than an ephemeral compact or a transitory understanding. It must rest secure upon the trust of comrade in comrade, and the loyality that is begotten of long and tried fidelity. And when we have Party at its best when to substantial agreement in opinion we add a long and glorious tradition of common work and common achievement, and to a memorable tradition the sentiment of comrade- ship, and to comradeship leadership, and to leadership the organisation that utilises effective strength to the uttermost, and finds a place for every willing worker what is it but folly to reject an instrument like this? Shall we cease to dig the ground because people have fought with picks and shovels? Therefore, we do well in this country " in the way men call party : ' to worship the constitution of our fathers." In this we may all be proud to be deeply-dyed Conservatives. Here in the home of Reform, I venture to declare that there is one Reform Bill that would never pass a Bill for the dissolution of parties. You will not, therefore, number me among the assailants of Party. Not only does Party exist; in a democratic country it inevitably exists. And not only does it inevitably exist, it is good that it should exist. I assume this henceforth, and go on to ask what is the right attitude of the citizen towards it? Now, there can be little doubt that Party does much to broaden and to quicken the life of the average citizen. A great Party links generations together, and gathers within itself many sentiments, interests, projects. It is the product of many hands, and many minds. So far it is larger, often far larger, than any or all of its individual members. And if sometimes one member eyes another askance, as if he had strayed somehow into the wrong fold, he would usually be better occupied if, instead of troubling himself with his neighbour's orthodoxy, he gave thanks to Heaven that his Party was so roomy. Who can doubt that many a life, otherwise isolated, narrow, ineffectual, has gained much, much in seriousness, practicality, and breadth of out- look, because it has been caught up into that larger life of Party which persists whilst individuals and even generations come and go? Away, therefore, with the unsocial impotence of the fanatics and faddists ! An end to the sectarian dissidence of factions, coteries, and caves ! What we want and need is. the many- chambered mansion of a great and comprehensive Party. " Make up your mind to be somebody," said a venerable statesman to a youthful and ambitious fellow countryman. Good advice ! PARTY & POLITICAL CONVICTION 135 But, in politics at any rate, a man is not likely " to " be somebody " he is fairly certain to be nobody, or (in Burke's strong words) to " fall an !< unpitied sacrifice in a contemptible struggle " unless he learns to act in concert with his fellows, and to grapple himself to one or other of the great parties in the State. But then it is just because the citizen does well to give himself to Party that another result happens. The party absorbs him, and in absorbing him it concentrates his mind over- whelmingly upon the present, and is only too apt to shut his eyes to the more distant ends. Mr. Rhodes once said that it is the curse of our politics that statesmen will not look ahead. But the fault lies not wholly with the statesmen. It lies at the door of Party, which by its very nature runs a risk of making the present everything, and the future, the more distant future, nothing. There are many influences that make for this. There is the fighting spirit, whose dominant motive becomes the longing to see the enemy routed at the polls, or in the House a most human and natural sentiment. There is the organising spirit to which it is enough to live for to see the machine working working like a well- oiled engine that is the heart's delight of the officiating engineer. There is the spirit of loyalty, which prompts the soldier of party to march in unhesitating, and, at times, blind faith behind the party leader. " Their's not to reason why." There is the practical business spirit 136 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK which claims to know just what is here and now to be done, and to do it. There is the deeply rooted deference to party oracles, whose pleasure it is to represent every passing issue as an earth- quake. There is the aversion, natural enough to all who have to act in highly organised association, to indulge ideas or schemes which might develop inconvenient differences. Not least there is the excitement, the bustle, the glow, the urgency of current affairs, the oratory, the strategy, the hopes and fears, not to add the necessity of watching narrowly the tactics of the enemy and of instantly rushing to his discomfiture. One cannot say that Party gives its members little to think about. It gives them much. But it gives them this in such a way as to limit their thoughts overwhelmingly to the present, and so to bring them to lose sight of the more distant ends. Parties, in short, by their very nature as instruments for fighting and acting, tend to bring their members to live more or less from hand to mouth, and so to lose sight of the large and permanent interests of national well- being. This is the worst I have to say against them, and I believe it to be incontrovertibly true. In saying this, you are not to suppose that wish to animadvert, or to be censorious. Far from it. There are distinguished writers, Sir Henry Maine for example, who have gone so far as to depict party politics as a game, or as a pro- longed cricket match between blue and yellow.* * Sec Maine's "Popular Government." PARTY & POLITICAL CONVICTION 137 We need not follow them. Such analogies do little justice to the fact that the stakes for which the game is played are the happiness, it may be the lives, of men and nations. Yet these analogies, however frivolous, serve a purpose. They point to the familiar fact that party politics is an endless struggle, struggle in the House, struggle in the constituencies, struggle in the Press, struggle on the platform. And where there is struggle, it is natural, it is human, that the immediate result should be all-engrossing. The Opposition thinks day and night of dislodging the Government; the Government, day and night, of demolishing the Opposition. The constituencies compass heaven and earth to carry their candidate ; and the candidate earth and heaven to justify their support by a sweeping majority. What they all wish for, and work for, not cynically or recklessly, but very earnestly, is Victory, and this dazzling hope and darling wish for victory who can deny it ? are pre-eminently calculated to withdraw the mind from the more distant ends for which political, like other battles, are fought or won. Party immerses us all in the current politics of the hour. Now, I fully recognise that in all this there is much that is altogether manly, honest, and invigorating. It keeps politics and parties alive. Is a community ever more alive than when a general election is upon us? But there is a fact in the presence of which it goes on, and it is a fact of the first magnitude. I mean the fact that 138 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK party politics, as we have it in this country, is, almost more than any other department of human life more even than religion or commerce saturated with the casuistry of compromise. There is a passage in which Lecky declares crede experto that, to a new member of the House, what goes on in that Mother of Parliaments is at first very painful, especially if the new member be one who has been accustomed to treat the formation and expression of opinion as a matter of serious duty. ;< He finds that he is required again and again " to give an effective voice in the great council of " the nation, on questions of grave importance, " with a levity of conviction upon which he would " not act in the most trivial affairs of private life. " No doctor would prescribe for the slightest " malady; no lawyer would advise in the easiest " case; no wise man would act in the simplest " transactions of private business or would even " give an opinion to his neighbour at a dinner ' party, without more knowledge of the subject " than that on which a Member of Parliament is " often obliged to vote. But he soon finds that " for good or evil this system is absolutely " indispensable to the working of the machine. " If no one voted except on matters he really " understood and cared for, four-fifths of the " questions that are determined by the House of " Commons would be determined by mere " fractions of its members, and in that case PARTY & POLITICAL CONVICTION 139 ' Parliamentary Government under the Party " system would be impossible."* Thus it is that the chosen champion of freedom, the democratic Member of Parliament, finds himself constrained, by this categorical imperative of Party, to support measures he detests, and to oppose measures he desires, to vote when he does not want to, and to refrain from voting when he does want to, to give a vote sorely against the grain here in order that he may be conciliated by his party there, to be silent when he fain would speak, and possibly have to speak when he had rather be dumb. He may salve his conscience, no doubt, by abstention, truancy, or even by rebellion, if the Ark be not in danger. But for the rest, except on occasions of very extraordinary gravity, he must often those who have been through it alone know, I fancy, how often swallow his pride, his judgment, and even some of his conscience, and obey the Whip. And what shall we say of the self-suppressions, to call them by the mildest name, that are supposed to go on within a Cabinet? It is wrapped in obscurity. It is a Cabinet secret. Eye hath not seen, nor ear heard, what goes on in this secret Council of a free nation. But tales transpire, significant of much. Here is one. A Cabinet meeting had agreed to propose a fixed duty on corn. As the Ministers were rising to go, the Premier (Lord Melbourne, one should perhaps hasten to say) put his back to the door. "The Map of Life," p. 124. 140 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK " Now," he said, " is it to lower the price of corn, " or is it not? It doesn't much matter which we " say, but, mind ! we must all say the same."* ' This is a hard case, an indefensible case," once said an experienced Secretary of the Treasury. ' We must apply our majority to this question."! This might suggest that Parliamentary, not to say Cabinet Government needs reforming. No ! not at all, if we accept the sum of the whole matter according to Lecky (surely one of the most conscientious politicians of his day). ' Those " who refuse to accept the conditions of " Parliamentary life should abstain from entering " into it." The same thing reappears, though in less acute degree, in the relation of member to constituency. The party or the caucus that stands behind member or candidate is for the most part composed of too extensive a colluvies of opinions and interests to render it at all possible for him to see eye to eye with them all. The same sort of thing recurs. There is silence here, and there the evasion that brings down the meeting by its dexterity; a little more emphasis on this point, a diminished emphasis on that; the soft answer that turneth away wrath, or the wrathful answer that is not to be trifled with, and so on, and all so necessary that the party may " go solid " for their man. Even the humble elector is not exempt. And, indeed, many of us may have had to cast * Bagehot, " English Constitution," p. 14, note t Bagehot, ibid., p. 141. PARTY & POLITICAL CONVICTION 141 our votes for candidates whom on some points we consent with difficulty to leave unmuzzled only because there are others on which we more desire to muzzle their opponents. The casuistries of politics are not limited to candidates. Now, much of this is inevitable. Compromise, casuistical compromise must come. Collective action is on no other condition possible. The serious matter is, not that these compromises exist, but that they exist side by side with the hand-to-mouth politics which (as I have contended) the party system so indubitably fosters. Here lies the danger. Here comes the crux. For of all persons the hand-to-mouth politician, the man whose eyes are fixed on current politics alone, is least fitted to deal satisfactorily with the casuistries of compromise. I do not suggest that he will be paralyised. This is not his weakness. He will vote, he will act, he will speak, he will decide with energetic confidence. He may do this on more grounds than one. Because his party bids him ; because his interests prompt him ; because the other side opposes him; because he follows his leader; because he trusts comrades who are expert where he is ignorant; because he must implement his pledges ; because he must do something; because he dare not do nothing. It is not for me to try to enumerate his motives, or to deny that some of them may do him credit. The point is that these ways are not the best ways ; not the most effective and most hopeful ways; 142 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK not the ways in which a man may best hold fast both to his party (which is much) and to his integrity (which is more). For when a politician is face to face with one of these cases of compromise, not one of the paltry issues not worth stickling about, but one of the serious issues that make him uncomfortable, what is it that we ought most earnestly to wish for him ? A conscience? Undoubtedly. Nothing can cut casuistical knots like a conscience. It is the supreme instrument. We need it. But a conscience, a mere conscience, is not enough. Oh, conscience ! what things have been done in thy name ! What is needed is a conscience enlightened by an ideal of the public good. And by an " ideal," I mean nothing pretentious or up in the clouds, but simply a firmly-grasped, well- grouped, strongly-held body of convictions about the political ends which really matter for our country, and (if we are able to rise to that larger outlook) for the world. For it is thus, by convictions about our ends, that casuistical difficulties can alone be effectually disposed of in any domain of life; and politics is no exception. So long as politics lasts, these casuistical questions will come in crowds. None of us can escape them. And none of us will be armed against them, none of us will be fit to meet them, till he has made up his mind what are the essentials of the public good for which he means to take his stand. Nothing less will suffice. Without it the most vigorous of hand-to-mouth PARTY & POLITICAL CONVICTION 143 politicians will drift into the lamentable tortuosities of opportunism. With it the man who does not wish to leave his conscience on the shore when he goes to sea on the troubled ocean of politics, will have a criterion which, though neither infallible nor easy of application, will help him mightily to decide when to put down his foot, even if need be, in defiance of his Party; and when, on the other hand, to make those concessions and compromises from which no politician can escape any more than he can jump off his own shadow. For to the man with an ideal these compromises, concessions, abatements, that are painfully wrung from him in public life, and that are even abhorrent at first sight to the inexperienced, are not really the surrender of his ends, but the means whereby, in the difficult medium of party struggle, the realisation of these ends alone becomes possible. People sometimes speak and write as if the reign of compromise and casuistry in politics justified a despair of all fidelity to political ideals. It is precisely the other way. It is the necessity for compromise in politics; it is the reality of casuistry in politics which compels us if we do not wish to see our judgment overwhelmed, our integrity sapped, and our consciences frittered away to do our best to cling to our ideal as the sheet-anchor of straightforwardness and consistency. This being so, it is not too much, is it? to expect of our politicians, especially, of course, of i 4 4 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK all who aspire to lead, that they should come to their work with convictions with coherent convictions. What meaning do we put on those basal principles of Liberty and Equality that run from end to end of all our politics? Do we believe in the expansion and unification of the British Empire? Do we wish the Colonies to go, or to be drawn closer to the Mother of Nations? Are we, with Cobden, non-interventionists in foreign policy, or are we, with Mazzini, believers in the international mission of nations? Do we lean to State-action, not to say socialistic State- action, in home affairs, or are we disciples of laissez-faire and voluntary effort? Are we Free Traders or not ? Do we revere or do we reprobate Church Establishments? Do we wish to see religious teaching in our schools, or do we wish them secularised to the uttermost? Have we definite opinions upon the just incidence of Taxation ? In short, what are we really working for what are the ends in regard to the social betterment of the whole People ? These are the things that matter. These are some of the ends which must enter, not in desultory juxtaposition, but in well-compacted unity, into a citizen's ideal of the public good. I am far from suggesting that convictions on such weighty matters come easy ; and still further from supposing it easy when the ends are so multifarious to determine which take priority. Let no one say that Politics are easy. Nor am I arguing not for a moment that even our leaders PARTY & POLITICAL CONVICTION 145 should be expected to have come to a cut-and- dried finality about any of them. But is it extravagant to expect is it asking too much of them that they should, at any rate, definitely know where they are in such problems, and still more, that they should know whither they are going, and inviting us to follow them? I have no desire to invite politicians to formulate dogmatic Creeds. We do not want a Thirty-nine Articles in politics, or a political Westminster Confession. All we ask of them is intelligent and coherent conviction as to the ends upon which they are moving. If you say : " They have this " already," I stand corrected, I have been crying Fire ! in Noah's Flood. If you say : " It is too " much to expect," then must they flounder on in the great Serbonian bog of casuistical compromise, world without end. Of this, however, we may be certain that the plan or ideal in question is not one that any single party can be expected to furnish. It is not the function of Party to impart ultimate political convictions. It can, of course, help; especially if our lot should fall in days when party leaders, or party organs, or party pamphleteers have a comprehensive and far- reaching grasp of policy. Party is often the way of approach to political convictions. Men do not perfect their convictions first and then join their party. They sometimes join their party first and find their convictions afterwards. Nor can anyone reasonably blame us if, in the faith of our i 4 6 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK fidelity, we attach something more than its value to the party tradition, the party manifesto, the party organ, the party policy, the party programme. But Party can never here suffice. It is essentially an instrument of action and combat, not of thought and conviction. It is devised, organised, and worked to enact our convictions, not to form them. If we read history and study economics if we even take a larger view of current events if we dip into the political writers of all parties if we even respectfully regard the utterances of the other side above all, if we give just heed to experience of life and what it has to tell us of hardships, abuses, grievances, struggles, aspirations we must know that our convictions are fed, nay, it is shameful if they are not fed, from many a source that lies beyond our party. It is no real tribute to our party to prostrate our minds before it least of all if we aspire to be the champions of freedom. The signal for fight, the watchword, the plan of campaign, the strategy, the tactics, the immediate programme yes, our Party may dictate these. But our convictions, our ideal of what we would have our country become and of what we would have the lives of our fellow citizens be when it comes to these, we are getting into the region of what I would call the spiritual power. And no party can be suffered to usurp the spiritual power. And if it tries to do so, by constituting itself sole source and repository of our political convictions, we must flatly deny its competence. PARTY & POLITICAL CONVICTION 147 It is the policy of both great parties in the State to catch their followers young. I do not quarrel with them for that. By all means let every citizen begin betimes to learn the long lesson of discipline, organisation, and co-operation. Politics needs apprenticeship. Yes, but therein lies the very reason why the partisan should keep his eyes wide open to the fact that a party, just because it is a party, and not least when it is a strong party, is no sufficient school for any man's political convictions. I do not think so lightly of political convictions as to be able to think it is. For political convictions send their roots deep and far. They grow on a wider and a deeper soil than the Party seed-plot. They are built on that rock of all freedom freedom to think. ; ' Depend upon it," once said Burke, " the lovers " of freedom will be free." He said it of Parliamentary representatives in his vehement protest against the servility of a delegative democracy. We say it of party loyalty. For a party is not only an association of politicans. Whatever else it be, and most of all when it is a party of Reform, it must be a league of freemen. I may seem to be waxing over-emphatic. If so- il is because I not only honour convictions, but because I believe in Party. But I follow Plato. I hold that it is the man who has risen above Party, gone beyond Party, in the formation of his convictions, who will alone do justice to Party as an instrument of action. Not only will he have larger and more enduring ends on which to- 148 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK feed his political passions and energies; not only will he have a clue the only clue worth having to lead him out of that tortuous and maddening labyrinth of political casuistry; not only will he gain that influence unknown to the waverers, trimmers, and opportunists which surely waits upon coherent convictions; he will turn to Party with an eagerness all his own because he will regard it in the light of the ends it can achieve. Nor is this experience peculiar to politics. It is what we find all through life in all the arts. Think of the manufacturer, the master in commerce, the engineer, the soldier well they know the value of the instruments with which they work. They know it because they realise the magnitude and worth of the ends which these instruments subserve. So in the art of Politics. Your true political craftsmen will welcome party organisation because he can see, beyond all the mere machinery of party, the ends the concrete realities of human betterment and happiness for the achievement of which nations have been gathered together by the " Divine tactic." Nay, even a single great end of national well-being Public Health, Education, Commercial Policy, Defence carefully thought out and laid to heart, will suffice to make a man, conscious of the impotence of isolated effort, greedy of the strength and effectiveness which a compact party with convictions can never fail to give. Nor need those who are zealous for the Party system fear lest party loyalty might be impaired PARTY & POLITICAL CONVICTION 149 by thus relegating Party to its proper place as an instrument for the enactment of convictions drawn from sources far beyond those that lie within our party's boundaries. It is true, no doubt there is no need to disguise the fact that there come times when a citizen, just in proportion as he has personal convictions, must face a parting of the ways, and, if need be, change sides. It was so when Burke broke from Fox and the Whigs when Peel gave up the Conservative Protectionists when Robert Lowe fought against extension of the franchise when Harrington parted from Gladstone and the Liberals on Home Rule when, in these latter days, Fiscal Policy seems to be pregnant of leavetakings on both sides. Such things are not to be deplored. They are to be welcomed as a sign of political health, being, as they are, a proof that there exists a loyalty to convictions about ends that is stronger than the loyalty to Party, the instrument for the realisation of ends. And though one cannot but sympathise with the loyal spirit that clings to a party, even when it has been borne in upon a man's mind that his party has ceased to be the most effective organ for expressing his convictions, our respect is infinitely more due to him who has nerve to face the rupture of old ties and the bitter severance from old comrades for conviction's sake. Both are, at any rate, preferable beyond comparison to the type who is never tempted to leave his party because he has never seen beyond it. It is well to remember 150 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK especially in this land where Party is of the very fibre and tissue of our political system that strong political parties are apt to produce limited political creeds. Leave-takings that may serve as a reminder that a political creed ought always to be wider than a political party are not unwhole- some. Yet, happily, these ruptures are not our daily diet. And it would be a depressing error to suppose that honest convictions need be at all incompatible with entire and lifelong devotion to a party. Except at times when parties seem to have outlived their programmes, and when the lines of party cleavage have become blurred, our two great parties in the State divide with such decisiveness, that it is not difficult for the citizen to decide which of them puts the best instrument into his hands. And as both parties having each its traditions and its settled trend of policy move on more or less consistent lines, the citizen who wears the Liberal or Conservative colours may probably enough march loyally for a life- time with the army he has chosen. The vital matter is that he should (sooner or later) choose and march with his eyes open. Not merely because such choice is the right nay, it is the very breath of life of free citizenship, but also because, if there be any truth in my contention, it is in this way that a man can best bring to his party that ardour of loyal service that sees in association with tried comrades under trusted leaders the supreme instrument for the PARTY & POLITICAL CONVICTION 151 realisation of convictions, for which, if need be, he would go to the stake. I have no wish, however, to see such persons going to the stake. I would prefer to see them going, in increasing numbers, to the House of Commons. VIL-THE TEACHING OF RELIGION AND THE ART OF EDUCATION.* When those of us who are senior look back across our lives, there is one educational principle of the first importance which we can single out, with unerring vision, from the tangle of hopes and struggles, advances and rebuffs, successes and failures, which make up the complex web of life. It is the principle that it is what we have truly cared for that has made our characters what they are. It may be for better or for worse. This one may thankfully see how his whole career has been shaped and inspired by strengthening and uplifting pursuits, interests, ends, or it may be persons, all of which he has come to value the more the longer he lives. They have become the very stuff and substance of his life. That one, on the other hand, may bitterly discern that the promise of his youth has been squandered on paltry ambitions and delusive passions and poor trivialities, all so tenaciously clung to that they * An Address to Sunday School Teachers in training, delivered in the Arts Theatre of the University of Liverpool. THE TEACHING OF RELIGION 153 have left him a moral bankrupt. But both alike, if they be honest with themselves, will acknowledge the same principle. In that confessional of the soul, in which there are no reserves, because in it a man meets himself face to face, both will be constrained to own that it is what they have really cared for that has made them what they are. This is only what we might expect to find from what we know of human nature. For it follows from two facts about human nature which you, will, I imagine, be hardly inclined to dispute. The one is that every human soul, from the very dawn of existence, struggles forward towards increasing fullness of life. As a great thinker put it, it persists, or perseveres, in its own being. And it strives ever onwards with a pertinacity so indomitable that it still values life, it still clings to life, or at very least shrinks from death, even long after life has, as sometimes happens, lost its charms or its hopes of happiness. So deeply rooted in man is the will to live. Thus struggling forwards, the soul feeds itself on the thousand varied interests and satisfactions which the world has to offer; and if the world as it is cannot yield enough to satisfy it, it is not daunted. It calls the constructive* imagination, and a marvellous fertility of invention to its aid, and devises new, and ever again new forms of satisfaction. It does this with a resourcefulness to which the whole course of civilisation is a witness a resourcefulness to which it is quite impossible to set a limit. It goes further. It projects its 154 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK aspirations beyond the span of mortality, and from the far-off days of the fabled transmigration of souls to the personal immortality of the Christian creeds, forecasts the fuller realisation of the will to live in a further phase of existence. This then the strength and vitality of the will to live is the one fact to which I invite assent. The second is that in this hungry and indeed insatiable quest of satisfactions, in this eager pursuit of what men think worth living for, a human being can only gain much by rejecting much. We sometimes, to be sure, fall into the way of saying of the favourites of fortune that they were able to satisfy every desire of their hearts. It is not true. The thing is impossible. Life is not built on that plan. No man can enjoy everything he wants. On the contrary, for every considerable end he attains, and especially if the end be of pre-eminent value, he has to pay a price. If he aspires to be a public man, he must sacrifice the leisure of private life. If he means to be a scholar, he must forego many an amusement and many a recreation. If he intends to be a business man, he must see that the office or the workshop have the first charge upon his time, and let go many a rival attraction. For, in this sense, there comes to all ordinary mortals an inevitable parting and choice of the ways. It is not that choice of the ways, famous in fable, that is supposed to be made once for all and done with. How easy were life if that were all ! No, the real choice of the ways is an ever- THE TEACHING OF RELIGION 155 recurrent choice of the ways. It has to be made again and again all through life. Nor is it a choice that can ever be evaded. It cannot, because it is of the very rudiments of a true economy of life that to set one's heart or mind upon one range of satisfaction, is perforce to turn one's back, in greater or lesser degree, upon other satisfactions. Perhaps these statements may seem truisms. It may sound a truism to say that, all our lives through, we are craving and seeking for food to feed our souls just as certainly as for food to feed our bodies. It may also sound a truism to say that, seeing we cannot have everything we want, we must choose choose for ourselves, or find other persons to choose for us. If you think these are truisms, I shall rejoice, because that, I suppose, is a sign that they are true. And this being so, what I now go on to ask is, supposing them true, what follows ? It follows that what we ought most earnestly to wish for everyone whose interests we have at heart is that, with this inevitable choice of the ways before him, he should be so guided as to come to care most for those things in life that are most worth caring for, and to care least for those that are least worth caring for, or (it may be) not worth caring for at all. That is the most fundamental principle in education I can think of. For to repeat what I said at the outset it is what a man really cares for that shapes his life and makes its character. Let me now add 156 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK that it makes his character in two ways : It feeds it, and it disciplines it. It feeds the character because it enriches a man's life with ends or interests that are worth living for sometimes worth dying for. These ends and interests may of course be of many kinds the love of home, the ties of affection to friends, the respect of our neighbours, the helping of our fellow-citizens, the public service in many modes, the mastery of books, the knowledge of nature, the love of God. They all feed the character, because they all furnish, in inexhaustible profusion, ends and interests to think about, to feel about, and to strive for. They are the nutriment of the soul. And they discipline the character, because, though this word " discipline " often enough, and up to a certain point rightly enough, suggests repression and chastening, that is not the only kind of discipline. There is another kind, and it comes in a very different guise. It comes of implanting in man or boy in his heart, mind, conscience- positive interests, that love of the things worth caring for of which I have spoken, in the sure hope that the discipline by repression will then largely take care of itself. For the one sure way to make man or boy incapable of evil is to make him capable of good. Give him persons or causes worth living for, enlist his thoughts and his passions in the service of these, and you have the strongest of all securities a stronger security far than the too often impotent " Thou shalt not " of direct repression against idleness, folly, THE TEACHING OF RELIGION 157 triviality, and vice in all its insidious forms. For no truth is truer than that all genuine development of character is likewise discipline of character. And it is for that reason I venture to lay it down as fundamental that it is the things we care for the persons, the causes, the ends, the interests we care for that both nurture and discipline the character. Now, as the world is fashioned, there are things enough to care for. If there be cynics who imply, and pessimists who say, that life is not worth living, the responsibility for their cynicism and pessimism rests not with the world. It rests with themselves. Having eyes they see not; having ears they hear not. Does not great Nature spread before us, as the revolving year goes round, her inexhaustible apocalypse ? To make this earth, our heritage, A cheerful and a changing page, God's bright and intricate device Of day and season doth suffice. Does not Literature speak with her thousand voices ? Heard are the voices, Heard are the sages, The world and the ages. Has not Science revelations of its own- revelations not only of wonders seen and heard (for that of course is only a part of Science), but of that impalpable material world which eye has not seen nor ear heard, because it lies beyond sight or hearing, conjured into being by the 158 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK constructive scientific imagination? And, then, there are the arts the great arts which in music sweep the secret strings of emotion, and in painting, sculpture, architecture, give form and a body to mystic meanings and messages which, without their interpretation, had remained for ever hidden and unknown. They are things which have all their own intrinsic and undying charm. And (it is this concerns us now) they are also, all of them, things which may have, must have their penetrating and decisive influence on character. Many of us must have known men who were lovers of nature, or books, or research, or votaries of one or other of the arts not necessarily poets, or artists, or men of science, but much less distinguished folk, who had simply a heart-felt, life-long delight in their ruling passion. Do you think that such people have reaped nothing more from it, whatever it might be, than an intellectual or aesthetic harvest? Did the influence stop there? On the contrary, it is matter of common observation that pursuits of that kind can decisively influence a man's whole life. Why, even a hobby or a sport, trivial though they are, may actually become the centre of gravity round which a grown man's whole life may revolve, and upon which his thoughts, desires, ambitions, time, expenditure, may converge. It is not otherwise with those greater things of which I have spoken. Never yet did man or boy come seriously under the influence of any one of them without becoming a quite THE TEACHING OF RELIGION 159 different creature from what otherwise he would have been. But there are still some other things which more especially concern us here. They have brought us together in this meeting. They are the basis of our partnership in this educational adventure,* and I am not sure but that they lie still closer to character than even those other influences of which I have spoken. I mean, of course, those sacred things, those things in a peculiar sense of the spirit, which are distinctively the province of the Sunday School. It is your high prerogative, as it is your grave responsibility, as Sunday School teachers, to claim these things as peculiarly your own. You aspire to become the ambassadors of sacred things to young, receptive, plastic minds. And upon your handling of these things, in the spirit of it and in the methods of it, it depends whether religion is to become as real and decisive an influence in the lives entrusted to your care as nature and literature and science and art already are in the hands of their avowed and highly-trained representatives and exponents. I am not rash, I imagine, in assuming that you believe religion to be the greatest influence in life. You believe it is to be the source of aspiration, energy, endurance, consolation. You recognise it as the fountain-head of all our being. You stand for it as the most powerful and penetrating of all * The occasion of this Address was the inauguration of courses of instruction on theory and art of education. The audience consisted of Sunday School teachers. 160 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK the influences which transform and transfigure human nature. And it is for that reason it makes such demands upon teachers, and expects so much at their hands. Those of us whose business it is to teach literature, or science, or philosophy, know well how hard a task that is. We know how much we have to go through before we learn how to do it, and how not to do it. And our greatest difficulty is and every teacher will bear me out in this to discover, not only how to teach about literature and about science and about philosophy, but to teach about them in such a way as to bring our pupils genuinely to love literature and to love science and to love philosophy. Till we have done that, we know we have not succeeded. Hence there has come into existence that great science (as some call it, but which I should prefer to call that great art) of education. It counts among its craftsmen some of the great names of the world Plato, Aristotle, Quintilian, Comenius, Erasmus, Locke, Rousseau, Pestalozzi, Froebel, Herbart, Arnold, and many others. It has produced a vast literature. It has had innumerable practitioners of all sorts and descriptions, planning, executing, experimenting, in an infinite variety of ways. And yet all alike be it the head of a great public school, be it the obscure " dominie " of a country village striving after the one thing, the discovery of the secret, which some seem to have wonder- fully found, how to bring the youthful mind not only to learn the allotted task, not only to THE TEACHING OF RELIGION 161 " get up " so much history, or literature, or mathematics, or whatever may be the matter in hand, not only (as I have said) to acquire knowledge about these or other things, but to do this in such a fashion as whole-heartedly to care for them. So that when school is past, and the days of leading-strings are ended, the young life may go out into the world with substantial acquisitions, with definite likings, with settled interests, with habitual proclivities, possibly (though alas ! it is all too infrequent) with a genuine passion for the things of the mind. It is for you, as Sunday School teachers, to become craftsmen in this great art. It is for you to fit yourselves to teach the Bible not less effectively than the teacher of the week-day school equips himself to teach Virgil or Shakespeare or mathematics or chemistry. And it is for you a more difficult task still to train the boys and girls who sit on the benches of the Sunday School, to care for, to love sacred things, even as it is the ambition of the so-called " secular " teacher to train them to love the things of the mind. Only, I am bound to add, yours is the greater responsibility. A man may come through his schooling it is only too possible and care little for the things of the mind. It is lamentable enough. He will remain a mutilated specimen at best. He will be poor in his soul. Yet the misfortune is not fatal. But if a man, through lack of early training, goes out into the world apathetic to sacred things, it is different. His deprivation is more lamentable. For we must not fall into the habit it is perhaps a tendency of our times to look upon religion as if it were only one subject among other subjects, an item in a curriculum. That might perhaps be said of Biblical instruction, for which, of course, just as for other subjects, there are times and seasons. But religion, the actual valuing of sacred things, the caring for them, is a different thing. It is of its very essence to be permeative and pervasive. If a man have it, it will be with him in all he thinks and does. Its influence will not be limited to times and seasons, to places and occasions. It will determine his whole outlook on life. It will decisively affect all his valuations of persons and things. It will quicken his conscience. It will vitalise his conduct. And he who has it not will be irretrievably impoverished. Not that we need strain this contrast between religion and other things over much. I have said that every serious pursuit moulds the character, and there are some though I daresay they are not common to whom nature or literature or research is such a life-long passion that one or other of these has even become a kind of religion. People, at any rate, sometimes say that. But there is something about what we more usually call religion which distinguishes it from these other things; and part of the distinction is that, when it comes to the actual conduct of life, whether it be in the great crises of life that try THE TEACHING OF RELIGION 163 our fortitude, or in the daily round that perhaps proves our mettle no less effectually, it certainly matters more that a man be religious than that he be a lover of nature or books or research, how- ever enthusiastic. It is this that makes religious education so responsible a task, for we can say of it not only what can be said of education in general (and that is not a little), but something- more. It is a part of education with claims claims on our thought, our study, our service- that are nothing short of paramount. But if this be so, the inference is obvious. When any man believes with heart and soul in the importance of an end, he cannot stop there. Instantly the thought comes up : How is this end to be won ? Nor is there any plight more miserable than to believe whole-heartedly in some end, and to feel oneself impotent, through lack of knowledge, lack of skill, lack of training, to attain it. It is this thought that creates the sense of the value of method, and the deeper the conviction of the value of the end, the more urgent and eager the search for the means. Every parent, teacher, minister of religion, states- man, every practical man knows this to be the fact. He knows it in the confidence and satis- faction and success of having found the right methods; he knows it too in the perplexity, the ineffectually, the misspent time and service vain, the deplorable defeat of having failed to find them. It is, however, not my purpose to speak in 164 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK detail of the methods of religious education. I have not the claim to do so, because I have not the experience. I leave that in the capable hands of the expert. I will, therefore, under this head of method, confine myself to a few generalities; because there are some generalities on the subject which are within the knowledge of all of us. Thus it is manifest enough that people differ, and differ widely, as to the avenues, the modes of approach, by which the young may best be led into the presence of sacred things. There are, for example, some who lay the stress on the dogmatic teaching of catechisms and creeds, so much so that, like our friend Sir Oliver Lodge, in whom scientific genius and religious sympathies have so conspicuously joined hands, they essay the formidable task of supplementing the older catechisms by writing new ones. It is a method, one may say, which at any rate no Scotsman is likely to forget. I am old enough to remember how, on the passing of the Scottish Education Act, the whole country, in every school-board and every city, was in a ferment over the burning question as to whether the Shorter Catechism was to be taught in the schools, and how the all but unanimous pronouncement was that it should. Partly it was, no doubt, that that masterly and venerable document had become a religious symbol, rich in associations with the old days when children had learned their " Questions " (as we used to call THE TEACHING OF RELIGION 165 them) from parents and teachers to whom they looked up with affection not unmixed with awe. But partly also, and I dare say mainly, it was because the Scottish people has always had a suspicion of a merely emotional religion. It was not enough for them to arouse the feelings. The feelings were, in their somewhat hard-headed estimates, too apt to be vague, fitful, evanescent, untrustworthy. And so they set themselves, by their Catechism with its clear-cut definitions, to set before the youthful mind great and august theological conceptions upon which the feelings, otherwise vague and amorphous, might take hold. They did this, one may add, so strenuously that it sometimes happened that the intellectual element altogether swamped the emotional, and that the definitions, so admirably compact and condensed, gave so much for the head to do that the heart, and even the conscience, had hard work to keep up with it. That is one method. You will be able from your own experience of other catechisms to find analogous instances. I have given you that one because it is with it that my own upbringing made me memorably familiar. There is a second method which goes to an opposite extreme. The idea which underlies it is that, by the very laws of mental growth as psychologists from the days of Plato and Aristotle till the twentieth century have seen the youthful heart lies open to emotional influences long before the youthful mind has risen to the level at which it can grasp formulae or handle definitions. 166 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK Hence it is only natural that those who are of this way of thinking should cast about to find, and to magnify, those influences which seem to make their appeal to the feelings feelings of awe, of reverence, of mystery, of aspiration, of hope, of love. Not that such people believe that to be enough. Not necessarily at any rate. For they may be of opinion that though we ought to begin with appeal to the feelings, we need not end there. Yet their distinctive characteristic remains. Whatever we may do, we must (such is their conviction) do justice, in our scheme of education, to the religious emotions. We must do it even in the later education of men and women, but we must do it most of all in the education of the young while their hearts are still tender and their spirits responsive to all the heavenly and all the earthly influences. This is the idei which seems to work in the minds of those who lay especial stress upon devotional services and religious ceremonial. They may be thinking of widely different things. To this one it may be the "Cottar's Saturday Night," to that one the homely ritual of some puritanical mountain chapel, to a third the simple hymn and prayer of an elementary school, to a fourth the habitual services of a school or college chapel, to still another the majesty and glory of a Cathedral service to which all the arts have been made tributary. But amidst diversities of form there is one spirit. What they have all alike at heart is to enkindle, to uplift, to sustain those religious THE TEACHING OF RELIGION 167 emotions to which the human soul is as surely responsive as the whispering pines to the music of the winds, as the sounding seashore to the voices of the ocean. There is a third method, and the keynote of it is neither appeal to the intellect nor to the emotions though it is very far from dispensing with either but rather to the imagination and the conscience. And it is this which perhaps most of all concerns you here, because there lies ready to your hand, if you only can learn to use it, so powerful and so well tried an instrument in the teaching of the Bible. It is not for me to say how the Bible should be taught. I cannot answer that question. I content myself with saying that the difficulty in answering it is due to the same cause which makes it important to find its answer. The difficulty comes of the fact that the Bible is not a book or a subject, but (as has a thousand times been said) a literature. It is history, biography, story, poetry, prophecy, sermon, theology. Yes, and just for that reason it becomes possible to find in it so many varied ways in which its spiritual message can be simply and rationally and convincingly conveyed to all sorts of minds, and not least to minds at a stage when the love of a story is strong, and the imagination hungry and eager, and the conscience plastic, and the instinct to find a picture or a type far in excess of the appetite for a definition or a formula. And it is for that reason that so many feel such confidence in what i68 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK can be done by the great eventful story of Jewish history, by the heroic individualities and winged words of the Prophets, by the gladdening and strengthening and consolatory music of the Psalms, by the memorable utterances, the familiar parables, the shining examples of Old and New Testament. There is no teacher of any subject who has such opportunities as the teacher of the Bible, none certainly whose matter is more varied and naturally interesting, and none who is better placed to instil that spiritual message which lies so very close to the thoughts and intents of the heart, and to the vitalisation of the character. One hears in these days often enough the alarm that the Bible is being crushed out of the schools of the nation, and it is I suppose true that some people seem to wish to minimise it or even to get rid of it altogether. But there are at any rate two considerations -per contra. One is that it is not credible that those who care for education (and it is from the educational aspect I am speaking) would be content to live on under the soul- denying ordinanace of leaving to rust upon the shelf one of the most effective of all educational instruments. The other is that, if such a thing were credible, it would force upon the Sunday School the high distinction of preserving, I do not say for churches or creeds, but for the education of the human race, a book of which it may, in all sobriety, be said that more than any other ever printed it has both been found inexhaustible by scholars, and been welcomed, through all the THE TEACHING OF RELIGION 169 centuries, by unlearned and even unlettered millions an an unfailing source of spiritual strength and consolation. Such are the three great educational avenues to sacred things the way of catechism and creed ; the way of devotion and ceremonial; the way of study of the Bible. They are not exclusive of each other, though doubtless some will prefer one and some another. Nor do I presume to sit in judgment on their comparative value. I had rather learn to do justice to them all. For, diverse though they be, they all unite in one purpose, they all converge upon one end none other than that of leading the human spirit into the presence of realities upon which the eye that is once opened will never close. But there is still another method, or rather another aspect of all methods, and I am not sure but that, in the guidance of young lives, it is the most effectual of them all. I do not know how many of you may be familiar with Carlyle's " Sartor Resartus." Those who are will remember how Carlyle describes the first introduction of the hero of that strange spiritual biography to spiritual things. It comes when this hero of the story, looking back on his childhood, tells how, as a little lad, he was taken to church by his foster-parents. " The highest whom I knew on earth," so runs the reminiscence, " I here saw bowed down with " awe unspeakable, before a Higher in Heaven : " such things, especially in infancy, reach inwards 1 70 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK " to the very core of your being : mysteriously " does a Holy of Holies build itself into visibility " in the mysterious deeps, and reverence, the " divinest in man, springs forth undying from its " mean envelopment of fear." And Carlyle adds a sentence to suggest, I suppose, how experiences like this may profoundly influence a man's valuations of persons and things all through his life : 1 Would'st thou rather be a peasant's son that ;< knew, were it never so rudely, there was a God " in Heaven and in Man ; or a duke's son that " only knew there were two and thirty quarterings " on the family coach? " Nor is this other than a quite common experience. It holds, indeed, of many other things besides religion. It holds, one may say, of all the less tangible influences that operate in life. Is there not many an one who can trace the dawn of an interest in literature back to the far-off day when he first realised how profound was the veneration of those he loved and looked-up to a father, a friend, a teacher for one or other of the great books or great writers of the world? Are there not others who can remember how they first formed some dim notion of the seriousness of social or political movements, on the day when they saw a father, or an elder brother, or simply some acquaintance absorbed and excited by some political crisis, or some burning social question? This was their first lesson in citizenship. Are there not others still, to whom the heretofore somewhat mysterious words " business " and " the office " begin to gain a new significance from occasions in which even very young eyes have not failed to mark the pre-occupied and care-worn face of the bread- winner of the household? It is so that most of us come to have our first lessons in the reality of things. It is not telling that does it. It is not teaching about literature, or about politics, or about business life, that does it. It is personal experience, and actual daily observation by young eyes of those we most look up to, when they are deeply moved by the realities of life. For it is in this way that those we love and respect become to us, in our receptive and open-hearted youth, the missionaries of that greater unexplored world that lies beyond our childish horizon. It is not otherwise when the experiences are religious. You will not suppose that I under- estimate the value of catechisms and creeds, or of the thoughts that breathe and the words that burn on the sacred page, or of the penetrating influences of devotional services. I have done my best at any rate, in some imperfect fashion, to do them justice. They are all so important that one cannot wonder if controversies rage, in the educational as well as the religious world, as to their comparative value. But behind the noise of the controversies there keeps sounding in one's ears that notable saying of one of our wisest :* " If you would teach religion, the first thing is * Thomas Carlyle. i;2 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK " to find a man who has religion." It is a principle that is the bed-rock of all education. If you wish to make a boy a scholar well, it is not easy but the first thing is to place him in the hands of a scholar in whom he may see scholar- ship incarnate. If you would make a lad a man of business, send him into a great commercial house in which he can see, daily and hourly, a man of enterprise, and integrity, and practical wisdom at work. If you would make a good citizen, then bring the citizen-that-is-to-be under the habitual influence of men and women to whom civic patriotism is a serious and sacrificing passion. Nothing is more certain than that, for all effective and permanent influence, a man must be the thing he wishes to impart. That is the root of the matter. The application to our subject is obvious. You aspire, in your Sunday Schools, to teach and to train boys and girls to be Christian men and women. I congratulate you on your high calling. There is none higher. It demands knowledge, reverence, skill, sympathy, devotion, patience. Yes, and it also demands most of all that you yourself should have drank of spiritual life at those same unfailing sources to which you aspire to lead the lives entrusted to your care. For it is only then you can hope truly to feed and to discipline their character by bringing them to care, above all things else, for those things that are most worth caring for in life. VIIL-ETHICAL THEORY AND PRACTICE.* It is no wonder that the gulf between ethical theory and practice yawns so wide. It is seemingly so hard to bridge it from either side. For, on the one hand, it is quite certain that the practical world cares little for theories. It does not seem so much as to miss their absence. Driven on by the relentless urgencies of life urgencies of livelihood, of ambition, of passion, of impatience it has not the time, even if it had the appetite or the faculty for theorising. It has so much to do to make itself more moral that it is not minded to think about morality. Nor are many things more remarkable than the easy consciences with which even the salt of the earth, though they would wince under the faintest aspersion of moral backsliding, can sit supine under the imputation that they will not think. In truth they are too seldom encouraged to try. All too seldom do their teachers and preachers, their priests and pastors espouse the neglected cause of * A Paper read before the Literary and Philosophical Society of Liverpool. 174 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK theory unless, indeed, it be the cause of the comprehensive theory that theory is a superfluity. For their very prophets are at times /iwrdXoyoi, to whom the theorist, especially the ethical theorist, is a perversion, and theory a sacrilege : The moral sense, thank God ! is a thing you will never account for. By no greatest Happiness principle, greatest Noble- ness principle, or any principle whatever, will you make that the least clearer than it already is : forbear, I say, or you may darken it away from you altogether. Strong words ! But do we really need them in a world in which, too manifestly, as Plato puts it, philosophers are useless because mankind will not use them? When, on the other hand, we turn to the theorists, it would be rash to say that they reciprocate this indifference. Let the truth be told at once. The philosopher the ethical philosopher at any rate has a weakness. It is a secret longing to preach. And though when caught ftagrante delicto, especially by other philosophers, he is ashamed of himself, and almost over prompt to admit that it is not the philosopher's business to preach (which indeed is true), his human sympathies are too much for him, and in his own despite his thoughts begin to breathe and his words to burn. It has happened before now that moral philosophers have been likewise moral reformers. It happened in Greece. From Socrates right on to the Stoics, and some- times, as in Plato, with passionate aspiration, the thoughts of the thinkers, even when deeply ETHICAL THEORY & PRACTICE 175 plunged in analysis and definition, have been eager to turn to the betterment of men's lives. So likewise in the modern world. Theory and practice may have sundered. But the battles of rival ethical schools of ascetics and hedonists, of Kantians and utilitarians have not been fought solely for the calm empire of thought, but also for the sway of the human soul and human destiny. There are invocations to Duty even in the cold analytic page of Kant. Nor can all the formal rigour of demonstration, and all the repudiation of tears and laughter that freeze the sentences of Spinoza, quench the surmise that the writer of the Ethics sustained his vast and solitary labours by the conviction that he was revealing to passion-tossed man the peace that cometh of understanding. Such aspirations are happily far from illusory, as perhaps tne sequel may prove. Yet they do not justify the expectation that the philosopher can do much to leaven the world by his own direct influence upon it. The philosopher has his mission, and his mission is, of course, to be a philosopher. His chief end is not to alter the world, but to understand it. It is not the physiologist's chief end to be a doctor; n9r the economist's to be a Chancellor of the Exchequer; nor the logician's to be a master of argumentation. No more is it the moral philosopher's calling to make men moral. Not better men, but better theories, this is his main concern. Therefore is he sometimes misunderstood. " There is nothing " harder," once said Burke in his usual vein, " than the heart of a thorough-bred meta- 14 physician " (i.e., abstract thinker). But it is not that the heart of the theorist is harder than those of his neighbours. He may be pitiful of men like the philosopher of the New Atlantis. He may play his part as citizen, as Fichte did in the hour of his country's need, or as Green of Oxford did when, in unobtrusive devotion, he led the life of the honest citizen and good neighbour, to which in his writings he never failed to do honour. And many a thinker besides Mill has found incentive in the thought that the best work done for the world is often that of those who have lived remote. The point is that even the most sympathetic of theorists can make but little way by himself directly leavening the world with theories. It is not his vocation, and probably enough he has neither the gifts nor the time nor the rhetoric the glowing ideal, the telling metaphor, the vivid instance, the impassioned appeal without which theory will knock long and in vain for entrance into the popular mind. " Philosophy," says Mark Pattison, '" perishes " the moment you would teach it." It perishes at any rate the moment you would preach it- perishes to live in other forms which must needs sacrifice the rigour of philosophical statement if they are ever to gain the ear of the world, and mould its life. The inference is obvious. If theory can power- fully influence the world, it will be because the ETHICAL THEORY & PRACTICE 177 philosopher finds those better qualified in this respect than himself to whom he can entrust his message. For such allies he need not look in vain. There is a figure well known to us in this great centre of commerce. He produces nothing, and though we may not say he consumes nothing, yet what he consumes is but a fraction of what passes through his hands. For is it not through him, as middleman, that the produce passes which feeds the factories of our myriad-handed industrial life ? There are middlemen, too, of the spiritual world, all them preachers, teachers, moralists, essayists, orators, poets. By gifts, by vocation, by sympathy, they belong not strictly to the world of theory, nor yet definitely to the world of practice. Yet they are, or may be, in intimate relation to both; and the hope is that, at their hands, theory will receive that interpretation and expression which it cannot receive from the theorist himself and which yet it must receive if it is really to pass into the mind and life of a people. No one can doubt that, in one aspect at least, these " middlemen " are fitted for this task. They gain the ear of the world. For the world needs, and it knows it needs them. It needs them as satirists to lash its vices, cynics to probe its weaknesses, moralists to uplift its standard of valuation, preachers to steady its fluctuating faiths, prophets to feed its aspirations, spiritual leaders of all kinds to quicken and to strengthen i;8 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK its soul. Nor will it be otherwise so long as the world, with all its conventionalities, sensualities, apathies, is haunted by the sense of shortcoming, and visited, however fitfully, by the cloud-skirted dreams of a better life. Therefore the world gives heed to the penetrating earnestness of Robertson, to the high discourse of Ruskin, to the aggressive honesty of Huxley, to the ethical reasonableness of Arnold, to the prophecies of Carlyle, the music of Tennyson, the optimism of Browning, and to the whole many-coloured host who follow in their train. They are not men of action, these middlemen : a long road lies between their words, however moving, and men's deeds. Yet they have their allies Church, School, Home, Press, Platform. Nor is there one of these that is not leavened to its core by the great rhetoricians who never fail to arise as generation follows generation. This, in a word, is not our difficulty. The world listens to ideas, if clothed in rhetoric. The world acts on ideas, when ideas fire the imagination. The difficulty comes when we ask if these men who give the world its ideas these middlemen of the spiritual world will them- selves in turn listen to the theorist. This is the central point. Now, once this question is raised, it becomes evident in a moment that theory has rivals rivals so powerful that against them theory has to struggle for its life. One of these is authority, and the other is intuition. ETHICAL THEORY & PRACTICE 179 We do not here discuss the influence of authority and intuition upon the ordinary life. Our concern is with " the middlemen " with those who aspire to be, by pen or tongue, the moral leaders of their generation : and what in particular we wish to discover is the claim which ethical theory may reasonably have upon them. No one can doubt that many of these teachers of the world may become the servants, and some the slaves of authority. As little can one doubt that many others rest content with intuitions whose subjective strength is taken all too readily as warrant for their objective truth. Church and world manifestly teem, therefore, with men who accept the role of moral leadership, and yet ignore, or even (like Carlyle) flout the claims of ethical theory. There is no call to quarrel with either authority or intuition on that account. Authority is so vast a principle, and the forms through which it speaks are often so august and so venerable, that minds may still remain remark- able, if not great, even when they have accepted the attitude of credo quia impossibile. And insight, however incoherent its intuitions may be, is sometimes so penetrating that it may put to shame the work of lesser minds who " love to " spin the ostentatious continuity." There need, therefore, be no quarrel with either except when the grateful admission that they can do much, is perverted into the obscurantist claim that between them they can do everything. For then it becomes the task of those who believe in theory i8o ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK to insist that there are certain definite services which theory can render to our middlemen of the intellectual world, for which they will look in vain to authority, however consecrated, or to intuition, however piercing. i. In the first place, it is theory, and theory alone, that can enable our moral prophets to meet theory by theory. It would be too much to say that every leader of thought is bound to meet theory by theory. He may prefer to meet it by rhetorical projectiles, and, in Johnsonian fashion, when his pistol misses fire to knock down his adversary with the butt end. Or he may prefer to meet it by a dogma, to dispute which involves an indictment of a sacred book, a " universal " church, or of one or other of the traditions of the elders. Or he may prefer to meet it by appeal, couched in burning words, to conscience. They are all effective methods, and we need not, in this so combative world, disparage even the first. Only be it well under- stood that he who limits himself to one or all of the three, even though he should speak with the tongue of men and of angels, must be prepared to run a risk the grave risk of losing hold of the more rational minds of his generation. As a matter of fact it is the perception of the gravity of the risk that has prompted some of the greatest efforts of ethical speculation that the world has seen. One may not say perhaps that had the Sophists never arisen in Greece, Socrates would have lived and died unknown. But it is ETHICAL THEORY & PRACTICE i8r beyond doubting that neither Socrates nor Plato nor Aristotle would be numbered among the conscript fathers of philosophy had they not dedicated their lives to deliver the better minds of their generation from the sophistic theories that Might is Right, and individual hedonistic self- interest the measure of morality. They felt the need in the public interest of meeting theory by theory. The situation repeats itself. In every community such as ours there are men born and bred with the rationalising instinct. Dogma, even when it takes the hybrid form of dogmatic theory, cannot satisfy their craving, nor intuitions, how- ever glowing and prophetic, appease their appetite to understand. They hunger still for something more coherent, more intelligible, more rational. Followers afar off of Hume, they will not envy even the angels who hide their eyes with their wings. No; they will enquire, question, discuss, and doubt; and especially will they discuss and doubt the foundations of morality. And if the preachers and teachers of their generation these " middlemen " to whom they look for light have no reasons to give, then we shall have the spectacle of minds drifting rudder- less from creeds in which they can find no rest, and from gospels in which they can find no- coherence. Every teacher of his generation must face the fact that he has minds like this to reckon with. The ethical insight in Robertson's sermons, the 182 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK subtle persuasiveness of Newman's argument, the heart-moving music of In Memoriam, the wild prophetic fire of Sartor Resartus even these will not win them. Nothing will win them but to give them more of what they want, to appease this so reasonable longing for more light, to lead them on by every resource of rhetorical exposition to the pages of the masters who know because they think. Hence the pity and the disaster of it, when our men of genius become /uo-dAoyoi. They betray their trust. Does the officer of health refuse the light of the pathologist? or the doctor of the physiologist? or the engineer of the mathe- matician? or the statesman of the economist? Even our manufacturers in days when practice is turning with a feverish anxiety to science believe that the chemist or the electrician has something to tell them. Why then should our leaders of the world's thought flatter themselves that they can afford to ignore the systematised reflection of the great philosophers upon man's life and destiny? It is no sufficient answer to say that philosophers are at variance. They are at variance, they have ever been at variance among themselves, and this would be in point if we asked our prophets and teachers to go to them for dogmas. But it is not for dogmas that we ask to go. It is for the rationalising spirit, the methods of analysis, above all it is for that passion and effort after coherency and consistency of conviction, in absence of which the thoughtful ETHICAL THEORY & PRACTICE 183 minds of any generation will turn away even from the genius with abiding dissatisfaction. 2. Akin to this is the further service that ethical theory may do much to sustain belief in the essential reality of the moral ideal in days of transition and doubt. For there is a weakness to which, at such times, the non-theorising person, however gifted, is prone; and it is never greater than when his unreasoned convictions are blindly strong. He is too apt to think that morality itself is staked upon the finality of the precise form in which the moral ideal has shaped itself in his imagination. The time comes when this this version of the ideal is subjected to an inevitable criticism. It may be simply the criticism to which all ideals are subjected by life, or it may be the subtle sap of the casuist, or it may be the direct assault of the sceptic. The result is that, in proportion as this combined attack begins to prevail, he is apt to be panic-stricken, and to think that his moral world is tottering to its fall. He has more ways than one of reassuring him- self. Have we not said that he can find shelter and retreat under some authority which may silence, though it cannot solve, his doubts? Have we not said that he may trust to his intuitions, or perhaps follow in the train of some great ethical prophet? For, of course, it is the glory of the ethical prophet that he has an eye that can divide asunder form and substance, and intuitively discern the eternally true behind, or 1 84 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK through, its perishable embodiments. But there is a third way the way of ethical theory. In its results, this is not unlike the last. For it, too, brings its message that the particular forms of moral ideal to which man's allegiance is given are, to the larger view, finite and transitory. It, too, discerns behind this flux of forms one and the same principle of never-dying moral life, persistently striving to realise itself anew under the endlessly varied and everchanging conditions of actual and imagined experience. It, too, in a word, discriminates between the forms that decay and the function that never dies; between the ideals which are but perishable textures of human imagination, and that imperishable fore-felt and in part foreseen moral end, for which from age to age and from place to place, the human spirit has been for ever labouring to weave a worthier vesture. And, indeed, the results are so much the same, that philosophy has been denounced for vexing itself, and vexing its votaries, by trying to do laboriously what prophetic insight can do by the swifter, easier way of intuition. Away, haunt thou not me Thou vain philosophy ! Little hast thou bestead, Save to perplex the head, And leave the spirit dead. * ****** Why labour at the dull mechanic oar When the fresh breeze is blowing, And the strong current flowing, Right onward to the Eternal Shore ! ETHICAL THEORY & PRACTICE 185 The answer is that, though the results be the same, the process is different. It is the ethical thinker's task to analyse experience, not simply his own (which may be a small thing), but also that larger experience of mankind which is written in the moral institutions of society, and not least in the lives of the reformers, teachers, saints, heroes, prophets of our race. From such analysis he does not return empty-handed. He brings two convictions. One is the knowledge that it is the fate 'of all particular forms of the moral ideal (from which nothing can save them) to yield to the slow sap of the criticism of the morrow; and the other the complementary conviction that the moral life of w r hich man is capable, and which he knows he is imperatively bound to realise, remains a far richer and loftier thing than has ever yet found its reflection in the imperfect mirror of human heart and conscience. Only be it noted that when we call these the convictions of an ethical philosopher, we mean that they rest, not on the fitful revelations of prophetic insight, which may so easily mistake the light that leads astray for light from Heaven, but on the firm ground of observation, analysis, and proof. It is for this reason that the genuine student of philosophy will, even in days of disintegration and doubt, look on without misgiving at the contradictions of moral standards, the conflict of duties, the dilemmas of casuistry, the whisperings of the spirit of negation. For he will know, if he knows anything, that such things needs must come. 186 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK He will have discounted them by anticipation. If he have the full courage of his convictions, he will take a further step still. For in those very contradictions and collisions, which are the terror of the dogmatist, and the despair of the unreasoning mind, and in the spectacle, always tragical enough, of some cherished ideal crumbling before mordant criticism, he will see but one more proof of the exhaustless vitality of that moral law which, for ever on the march, does but " strike its tent in order to begin a new ' journey." It is here the moral philosopher can help the moral prophet. Inspiration and utterance he cannot give; these are the gifts of nature and of art and of the spirit that bloweth where it listeth. But he can give what even the greatest of prophets and teachers may lack, the assurance that the beliefs they offer to the world stand firm because they are rooted in reason. Do they not themselves know the need of this? How many, one sometimes wonders, are the teachers of the world who have had to give their message " in " the light of yesterday's faith hoping it may " come back to-morrow " ? How many have striven, not disingeniously, but from motives far from unworthy, to cover up even from themselves, by confident words and impassioned appeal, the secret misgivings which it would seem like treason to reveal to the world ? This is the situation that philosophy faces ; this is the need it tries to meet. Not, be it granted, by any promise of finality (for ETHICAL THEORY & PRACTICE 187 none knows better than the philosopher that his constructions may be incomplete), yet not without an unwavering confidence that it is only when reason has done the work that the structure of conviction can stand coherent and secure. 3. Ethical theory, then, can sustain the belief in the moral ideal. We may add now that it can powerfully affect the form which the moral ideal may from time to time assume. There is a popular error here which needs correcting. It comes of the illusion that it devolves upon the philosopher to create his ideals, so to say, out of his own head. It would be truer (though not wholly true) to say that the philosopher creates nothing. For the duties and the virtues, which give substance, body, " content " to the philosopher's ideal, are not the creations of philosophy. They are the gradual discoveries of human experience of the god- fearing reverence of the Hebrew, of the self- controlled confidence of the Greek, of the domestic purity and civic devotion of the Roman, of the pitifulness and aspiration of the Christian, of the chivalry of the knight, of the integrity and justice of the modern world of industry and commerce. Not only do the virtues thus, by their own exhaustless life, spring up in profusion long before theory and theorists could be there to plant them; the same holds true of ideals. What can be more incontrovertible than that ideals existed ages before theory had come upon the scene at all? 1 88 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK Yet, though philosophy cannot, in this sense, create, it can remedy the grave imperfections in what is otherwise created. For it is the bane of non-philosophical morality that one-half of its ideals are apt to be one-sided for lack of breadth ; and the other-half, incoherent and fragmentary for lack of unity. Nor are these imperfections easily avoided. For, on the one hand, whenever an ideal takes the form (as it so often does) of a type a typical man, a typical society it is apt to lose in breath. Just in proportion as the type is vividly and faithfully imaged, it surrenders its claim to comprehensiveness by becoming simply one type among others. On the other hand, if we begin to see that our moral ideal must be a wider and more many-sided thing than any single type can embody, we run an opposite risk. The unity of the ideal of type breaks up, and falls asunder before the recognition of many elements aggregated without regard to unity and proportion. Hence the multitude of ideals alike of poet of prophet and of moralist that have unity without breadth, and breadth without unity. This is what philosophy can help to remedy. For, on the one side, it takes that wider survey of experience which brings home the conviction that the rightly nurtured human soul is too rich in possibilities to be everywhere moulded after any single concrete type, even the greatest. And, on the other hand, it has learnt by many an instance how the inculcation of virtues, however shining, will stiffen into a lifeless catalogue of ETHICAL THEORY & PRACTICE 189 qualities, if it be not saved from this by a vitalising conception of the supreme end be it greatest happiness, duty, perfection, or what you will in the light of which all the cardinal human virtues can be seen to cohere as diverse modes of approach towards what man has it in him to become. Such a conception is precisely what philosophy can give. Nor need philosophy be overmuch disquieted by the obvious tu quoque that its own ideals have often enough been limited and one-sided. This is so true that it would be unanswerable were moral philosophy identifiable with the mere succession of ethical ideals which have seen the light in the long history of ethical theory. But philosophy is more than these. It lies deeper, being in its essence a spirit of synthesis. As such, it is as inherently intolerant, in the long run, of unity without comprehensiveness as of compre- hensiveness without unity. Grant that some of the ideals of character it has held up to the world, with the Cynic, Stoic, Epicurean in the ancient world, as with Hobbes, Kant, and Bentham in modern times, have been so one-sided as to have mutilated human nature and repelled the world by their contractedness. Little that matters, so long as we bear in mind that philosophy invites no man to accept these or any other ideals as a gospel. It invites to nothing except to surrender to that spirit of synthesis which if, in the passion for unity and consistency, it has constructed ideals that are narrow, has likewise, as the history of ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK ethical thought testifies, been swift to subject them to criticism and to go forward to new constructions such as will better do justice to the facts of many- sided experience. It is the same in the history of the individual so long as he keeps mentally alive. He may for a season be content with this ideal or with that, and perhaps be jealous to defend it against all comers with all the ardour of convinced discipleship. But if the spirit of philosophy be in him, he will not sit down satisfied till he has striven to gather up into his ideal every element of conspicuous value which experience has disclosed. And it is precisely because, and so far as, this spirit is in him that he can help to awaken even great and inspired teachers if they would but listen from that unconsciousness of the limitations of their ideals which is itself one of the greatest of limitations. 4. It is a still greater service that ethical theory can bring its students one step nearer that reasonable service that alone is perfect freedom. It is this that enables us to meet what is perhaps the most forcible of all the pleas for the disparagement of theory. Theory, it is said, does not really come to a man till his life is, in large measure, already determined, for good or for evil. He has chosen his vocation. He has formed his habits and built them into the fabric of character. He has wrought his moral ideal, what- ever it be, into the texture of his life. As against all this, what can the belated gospel of ethical theory do? Are we to suppose it will work a ETHICAL THEORY & PRACTICE 191 miracle ? Slow is the process and long is the way by which any bit of theory passes into the life. Is it not likely to be slower still, and longer, for those whose whole moral being has already taken set and shape under the great twin-influences of habituation and authority. ; ' Surely it is " impossible, or at least the hardest of tasks," and it is Aristotle who speaks, " to remove by " argument (Adyw) what has been from of old " engrained in the character." The force of this must be acknowledged. It is undeniably true that, if men are in character good, ethical theory will not forthwith pervert them to vice. It is no less true that if they be bad, ethical theory will not forthwith convert them to virtue. Character is too stable a structure to rise, like the walls of Thebes, to the music of theories however persuasive, or to fall like the walls of Jericho to the blowing of all the trumpets of theorists, however aggressive. Can one wonder, therefore, if theory is ignored, if not derided, not only by the disciples but by the leaders, not only by the average man but by those middlemen of the spiritual world, as we have called them, to whom the disciples look for light. But it is precisely here that the claims of theory- are upon strong ground. It does not follow that because ethical theory makes no pretension to work sudden miracles upon character, it can do nothing. On the contrary it is not too much to say that it, and it alone, can carry to completeness the moral emancipation of man. 192 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK There is a morality that never asks the reason why for the life of duty it nobly exemplifies. And when we meet the men who live it we call them, with Wordsworth, the ;< bondsmen " of duty, not stumbling at the servile word because the service is so high. The word is better chosen than we may think. For bondsmen and no better they still are, and bondsmen they will remain (however glorious their service), so long as the grounds upon which service is rendered are unexamined and unintelligible. Even the service of a god is but a loftier slavery, if it leaves the reason of the servant darkened. It is here that philosophy brings its message of emancipation. All ethical schools (unless we except intuitionism, which is a kind of despair of explanation) attempt to explain the problem of moral obligation. Their solutions are different : their aim is one. Refusing to regard the duties of life, however fundamental or cherished or sacred, as facts that defy analysis, they ask the reason Why for one and all of them. Up to their light they give their answers, and even when their answers fail to satisfy, be it never said that they leave us no better than we were. For even then they at least bring us nearer that reasonable service, without which the bondsmen of duty still wear the livery of moral servitude. You will not suppose me to be saying that even a perfect theory of moral obligation were such attainable would of itself make its possessor morally free. This would be absurd. Men have ETHICAL THEORY & PRACTICE 193 painfully to work out their moral freedom in their lives. They must become freemen in habitual thought, feeling, desire, deed. Many an un- lettered man who has been far enough from theories of any kind, has in this way wrought out r in sweat of soul, a substantial freedom, even under iron limitations, which he could neither alter nor understand. '' Servitude," says Carlyle, " is a blessing and a great liberty, the greatest that " can be given a man. So the shrewd little de Stael, on reconsidering and computing it, found :c that the place of all places even known to her " she had enjoyed the most freedom in was the ' Bastille." Need it be said that, in default of this this actual achievement of the moral life a knowledge of all the theories of moral obligation put together would profit us little. The point is that, be this practical moral achievement never so splendid, philosophy has something to superadd. It can speak the last word of emancipation; not the spurious " emancipation " born of caprice, that would shake allegiance to our habitual duties, but that far other emancipation that rivets allegiance the closer, because it makes it open-eyed, intelligent, and reasonable. For this is the one service that, for a rational being, is perfect freedom. 5. It remains to urge one further point. Theory can enable moral teachers to meet theory by theory ; it can sustain their belief in the reality of the moral ideal ; it can help to give to that ideal unity and breadth ; and it can crown the struggle 194 ETHICS OF SOCIAL WORK for moral freedom. Is it too much to claim that, beyond all this, it can quicken the moral life ? One suspects that philosophers are here too modest. They claim too little. Realising beyond all others how wide is the gulf between Theory and Practice, and well aware that it is not for philosophy to create, so much as to systematise what is otherwise created, they come to underrate the quickening influences of the study of ethical fact. " It is not to be supposed," says T. H. Green, " that .... anyone for !< being a theoretic utilitarian has been a better " man." When one studies the lives of the great utilitarians of Bentham, the founder, of James Mill, the propagandist, of John Mill, the apostle it is difficult to believe it. These men lived for the public good as few have done; and though they might have done this without their philosophy, as many other lesser men have done, one is driven to think, if there be truth in biography, that as the idea of human happiness rose before their eyes in ever widening comprehensiveness, in ever increasing detail, it kindled within them a zeal for public good which would not otherwise, in measure so abounding, have entered into their lives. So with ideals other than the utilitarian. Readers of Green's Prolegomena to Ethics cannot fail to feel the indomitable repressed fervour of its pages ; and those who knew the man can never forget the unobtrusive passion for righteousness that shone through a character which shrank from ETHICAL THEORY & PRACTICE 195 expression of the deeper emotions. It was ethical temperament. It was strength of character. It was habitual moral aspiration. Doubtless. But was it not likewise the fruit of a life-long reasoning reflection upon the moral possibilities of the soul, and of speculation resolute to the end upon the problem of human destiny. For it is false to say that the deeper ethical analysis, how- ever scientific, blights the enthusiasm and freezes the feelings. It seems to do so only because feeling must be sternly held in check whilst analysis proceeds, lest we fall under the temptation of believing what we wish, not what we know, to be true. As we labour at " the dull mechanic oar," our backs must needs be to that goodly land whither all the while we are voyaging. Yet, be it never forgotten that ethical analysis brings us, by its own path, into the presence of august and enduring objects into the habitual presence of moral law, of public good, of the far off half-revealed and half-concealed possibilities of the individual life. The man who has looked upon these facts with what Plato called " the eye " of the soul," will be other than that cold- blooded analyst in whom the world too often travesties the philosopher. For, after his own fashion, he will have been led to see the vision, and as he muses in his silent and solitary hours, the fire will burn within him. SOME PUBLICATIONS OF THE LIVERPOOL UNIVERSITY PRESS. FRANK BATE. The Declaration of Indulgence, 1672 : A Study in the rise of organised dissent. Based upon original documents. With an Introduction by C. H. Firth, Regius Professor of Modern History in the University of Oxford. Demy 8vo. 55. nett. RAMSAY Mum. A History of Liverpool. With numerous maps and illustrations. Second Edition. Large crown 8vo. 6s. nett. Some Press Opinions regarding this work are as follows : Athenceum " A luminous essay on the life-history of a great community an essay which shows wide vision and great insight expressed with unusual charm of style." Manchester Guardian. ;< It approaches much nearer to the ideal of its kind than anything we have yet seen." Liverpool Daily Post. " By far the most interesting and by far the most trust- worthy account of the origin and growth of this city hitherto published." RAMSAY MUIR and EDITH M. PLATT. A History of Municipal Government in Liverpool. In two parts : Part I., A Narrative Introduction by Ramsay Muir; Part II., A Collection of Charters and other documents transcribed, translated, and edited by Edith M. Platt. 4to. 2 is. nett. AMY HARRISON. Women's Industries in Liver- pool : An enquiry into the Economic Effects of Legislation regulating the Labour of Women. Demy 8vo. 33. nett. JANE WEIGHTMAN. The Language and Dialect of the later Old English Poetry. Demy 8vo. 45. 6d. nett. N. ANNANDALE and H. C. ROBINSON. Fasciculi Malayenses. Anthropological and Zoologi- cal Results of an Expedition to Perak and the Siamese Malay States, 1901-2, under- taken by N. Annandale and H. C. Robinson. In 8 sections, 4to. Zoology : Pt. I. 305. nett; Pt. II. 2os. nett (appendix to Pt. II. is. nett); Pt. III. 305. nett; Pt. IV. is. nett. Anthro- pology : Pt. I. 155. nett; Pt. II. los. nett. Supplement containing map and itinerary, 55. nett. THE FOLLOWING JOURNALS ARE ALSO PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS : Annals of Archaeology and Anthropology. Published quarterly. Annual subscription, i os. 6d. Sets of Vols. I. and II. (now completed) will be supplied at i is. each. The Bio-Chemical Journal. Devoted to the publication of original research in Bio- Chemistry. Edited by Benjamin Moore and E. Whitley. Published periodically. Subscription 2 is. per volume. Vols. I.-IV. can be supplied at 15$. each, unbound. Liverpool Committee for Excavation and Research in Wales and the Marches. First Annual Report of Excavations iq,o8-g. 4to. 1909. Published for annual subscribers at two guineas. The Town- Planning Review : Journal of the Department of Civic Design. Published quarterly. 2s. 6d. per number. Annual subscription IDS. post free. Annals of Tropical Medicine and Parisitology. Published quarterly. Edited by Ronald Ross. Annual subscription i is. od. Sets of Vols. I. and II. can be supplied. 14 Nl 3*5 Haf 50i-3,'68 (H9242s8) 9482 A 000