PHILO'S CONTRIBUTION TO 
 RELIGION 
 
PHILO'S CONTRIBUTION 
 TO RELIGION 
 
 BY 
 
 H. A. A. KENNEDY, D.D., D.Sc. 
 
 PROFESSOR OF NEW TESTAMENT EXEGESIS, 
 NEW COLLEGE, EDINBURGH 
 
 AUTHOR OF 
 
 "ST. PAUL AND THE MYSTERY RELIGIONS" 
 "ST. PAUL'S CONCEPTIONS OF THE LAST THINGS," ETC. 
 
 HODDER AND STOUGHTON 
 
 LONDON NEW YORK TORONTO 
 MCMXIX 
 
INSCRIBED WITH GRATITUDE 
 
 TO THE MEMORY OF 
 MY TWO GREAT TEACHERS 
 
 S. H. BUTCHER 
 
 AND 
 
 A. B. DAVIDSON 
 
 M605478 
 
PREFACE 
 
 NO ancient writer of such primary im- 
 portance for the environment and 
 presuppositions of early Christianity has 
 suffered the neglect which has fallen to the 
 lot of Philo. This is true both of British and 
 continental scholarship. I do not mean for 
 a moment to underrate such comprehensive 
 and valuable works as the late Principal 
 Drummond's Philo Judaeus, 2 vols. (London : 
 Williams & Norgate, 1888), and Dr. 
 Emile Br^hier's Les Idtes Philosophiques et 
 Religieuses de Philon d'Alexandrie (Paris : 
 A. Picard et Fils, 1908). 
 
 But Philo deserves to be made the subject 
 of many special monographs. Possibly the 
 sheer profusion of material has scared some 
 competent investigators. No one, it seems 
 
viii PREFACE 
 
 to me, can attempt to penetrate the back- 
 ground of early Christian thought without 
 realising the unique significance of Philo of 
 Alexandria. And this is just as true of the 
 practical as of the theoretical aspects of his 
 many-sided achievement. Indeed, the chief 
 impression made upon one by a careful 
 reading and re-reading of his works is the 
 extraordinary vitality of his religious interest, 
 the depth of his religious experience. This 
 seems to be of central value for under- 
 standing the man himself, and for estimating 
 his bearing on Christianity. 
 
 The only attempt to examine the facts 
 from this definite point of view, of which I 
 am aware, is Windisch's essay, Die From- 
 migkeit P kilos (Leipzig: J. C. Hinrichs, 
 1909). Apart from the fact of its not being 
 translated, the looseness and vagueness of 
 the plan according to which the material is 
 arranged, appeared to me likely rather to 
 suppress than to arouse interest in one of 
 the most remarkable figures in the history 
 of religion. So I was emboldened to 
 traverse the ground for myself, and to 
 
PREFACE ix 
 
 attempt to state the conclusions I had 
 reached with as little technicality as possible. 
 Accordingly my study is a completely in- 
 dependent piece of work, intended to 
 illuminate an unusually fascinating epoch in 
 the story of man's struggle to grasp and 
 understand God. I have made full use 
 of the work which has been done on Philo, 
 but I have refrained from loading my pages 
 either with discussions of minute details or 
 with references to the opinions and utterances 
 of other writers. One of my main objects 
 has been to let Philo speak for himself. 
 
 Several of these chapters have appeared 
 in the pages of the Expositor. These I 
 have carefully revised and, where it seemed 
 necessary, supplemented. I have cordially 
 to thank the Editor and the Publishers of 
 that journal for their kind permission to use 
 them. I am also under special obligation to 
 two friends: to Rev. J. H. Leckie, D.D., 
 who kindly read the MS., placing at my 
 disposal the fruits of his accurate knowledge 
 of Philo, and to my colleague, Professor 
 H. R. Mackintosh, D.D., D.Phil., who has 
 
x PREFACE 
 
 helped me to correct the proofs and favoured 
 me with valuable suggestions both as to form 
 and contents. 
 
 H. A. A. KENNEDY. 
 
 NEW COLLEGE, EDINBURGH, 
 1 2th September 1919. 
 
CONTENTS 
 
 CHAPTER I 
 
 PAGE 
 
 INTRODUCTION ..... i 
 
 CHAPTER II 
 PHILO'S RELATION TO THE OLD TESTAMENT . 29 
 
 CHAPTER III 
 
 FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS . . . .60 
 
 CHAPTER IV 
 MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD ..* . .96 
 
 CHAPTER V 
 GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN . . . 142 
 
 CHAPTER VI 
 
 UNION WITH GOD . . . .178 
 
 CHAPTER VII 
 THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO . . .211 
 
 INDEX ...... 239 
 
CHAPTER I 
 
 INTRODUCTION 
 
 THE contribution which Philo of Alex- 
 andria made to spiritual religion has 
 been largely overlooked, because attention 
 has been focused on the philosophical sig- 
 nificance of his thought. This was the 
 aspect of his writings which won for him the 
 interest of the Christian Fathers. At a time 
 when they were eagerly seeking to bridge the 
 gulf between the new religion and the old 
 philosophy, which for many of them formed 
 the chief content of their intellectual life, 
 they found in Philo, the Jew, a thinker who 
 had already attempted to reconcile the claims 
 of reason and revelation. His attitude to the 
 psychology, metaphysics and ethics of his 
 Hellenistic environment corresponded in 
 many respects to their own. He had not 
 shown himself a slavish adherent of any 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 single system. Probably he would have 
 called " the most sacred Plato," as he names 
 him, his supreme master, but he freely used 
 what attracted him in the Pythagorean tradi- 
 tion, in Aristotle, in the Earlier and Middle 
 Stoics, and in the popular Compendia, which 
 must have taken a prominent place in the 
 academic instruction of Alexandria. Philo's 
 eclecticism naturally appealed to the Christian 
 thinkers of the earlier centuries, for it was 
 characteristic of the milieu in which they 
 moved. They found his arguments apt for 
 their own task of refuting Paganism. 1 
 
 Equally acceptable in their eyes was his 
 chosen allegorical method. No doubt this 
 method had established itself in the Graeco- 
 Roman world apart altogether from Philo. 
 But he had employed it for a purpose parallel 
 to that which had engrossed the Christian 
 theologians. In his exposition of the great 
 text-book of Judaism, the Mosaic Law, taken 
 in its widest sense as including the patriarchal 
 history, he had set himself as a rule to show 
 that the details of ritual and biography were 
 
 1 Cf. Geffcken, Zwei Griechische Apologeten, pp. xxv-xxxii, 
 2 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 but a rich symbolism veiling the story of the 
 soul's progress from the sense- bound life of 
 earth to the vision of perfect reality in God. 
 He was thus able to establish lines of com- 
 munication between that ancestral religion 
 which he reverenced so profoundly and the 
 spiritual strivings of those Greek thinkers 
 who had meant so much for his inner life. 
 The great legislator of the Hebrew people 
 had, in Philo's view, larger ends in prospect 
 than the moral discipline of a single race. 
 He was concerned with the elemental prin- 
 ciples of the education of the soul for its 
 attainment of the highest wisdom, which 
 was nothing less than fellowship with the 
 Existent, the fountain of all being. But that 
 was also the goal of Hellenic philosophy. 
 The Jewish people, therefore, had a mission 
 to humanity. Moses was fitted to be the 
 teacher of all aspirants after truth. The 
 intellectual or moral difficulties of the Old 
 Testament vanished when the proper stand- 
 ard of interpretation was applied to them. 
 No material was left for the contemptuous 
 criticism of pagan philosophers. 
 
 3 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 The Fathers of the Church availed them- 
 selves of Philo's method for their own pur- 
 poses. The Old Testament had already 
 proved one of the most powerful instruments 
 in the Christian mission. It had to a large 
 extent provided the new faith with a religious 
 vocabulary. It formed the background of 
 those conceptions which, in writings like the 
 Epistles of St. Paul and the Fourth Gospel, 
 created the basis of a Christian theology. 
 The religious experience it recorded was 
 truly felt to be consummated in Jesus Christ. 
 But the inevitable controversy with Judaism 
 demanded something more. For the cham- 
 pions of the older religion also found their 
 weapons in the sacred book. From the 
 beginning, the early Church had searched 
 the Old Testament for anticipations of its 
 fundamental truths. By the use of Philo's 
 principles of interpretation, it became possible 
 to demonstrate that from Genesis to Malachi, 
 through history and ceremonial, the Scrip- 
 tures had exclusive reference to " the good 
 things to come." 
 
 For such reasons as these the study of 
 4 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 Philo has suffered from a lack of proportion. 
 He has been treated either as the most 
 important representative of a curious blend 
 of Jewish monotheism with later Greek 
 eclecticism, that is, as an interesting link in 
 the long chain of speculation on the philo- 
 sophy of religion in its widest sense, or as 
 the chief exponent of a fantastic method of 
 interpreting documents which can scarcely 
 excite even the archaeological interest of the 
 modern world. Abnormal attention has been 
 directed to his fluid and confused conceptions 
 of the Divine Logos and the Divine Powers. 
 His ethical positions have been mainly esti- 
 mated in the light of their relation to con- 
 temporary Stoicism. Serious attempts have 
 been made to force his often vague and 
 contradictory speculations into the rigid 
 framework of a system of metaphysics. 
 Ridicule has been poured upon his quaint 
 handling of patriarchal names and grammat- 
 ical details of the Greek Old Testament. 
 But these are not the things that count in 
 Philo. He is only to a slight extent import- 
 ant as the architect of a structure of doctrine, 
 
 5 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 philosophical or religious, if he ever aimed at 
 such an achievement. His speculative effort 
 to bring God into touch with the world of 
 men through \6yo$ or 8wd/j,et,s or dyye\oi is 
 no more successful than that of his revered 
 master, Plato, so vastly his superior in con- 
 structive intellecual power, to relate his Ideas 
 to the realm of actual experience. Many 
 of his dicta on the Divine essence, the con- 
 stitution of the cosmos, the soul of man and 
 its origin, the processes of life, and the nature 
 of society have become hopelessly antiquated. 
 
 Nevertheless Philo stands out as one of 
 the landmarks in the history of religion. 
 His career lies on the boundaries between 
 the old world and the new. Born not later, 
 in all probability, than 20 B.C., and dying 
 some time after 41 A.D., possibly not until 
 the fifth decade of our era, he was a con- 
 temporary both of Jesus and of Paul. These 
 facts alone mark his significance for students 
 of early Christianity. On the nature of that 
 significance we must briefly dwell. 
 
 Needless to say, there is no trace of 
 
 acquaintance on his part with Jesus or His 
 
 6 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 foremost apostle. We cannot tell whether 
 he ever came into contact with the Christian 
 faith. The tradition of his meeting Peter at 
 Rome (Eus. H.E. n. 17. i ; Photius, Biblioth. 
 Cod. 105 ; Suidas, s.v. $t\(0v) seems to be 
 purely legendary, based apparently on the 
 notion that the Therapeutae, whom he de- 
 scribes in the De Vita Contemplativa^ were 
 followers of Mark, the disciple of Peter. But 
 for the life and thought of that Graeco- 
 Roman world to which Christianity made its 
 appeal, he is in many respects a witness of 
 the first importance. The sidelights thrown 
 by his writings upon his Hellenistic environ- 
 ment have never been adequately estimated. 
 His references to mystery-religion, to pagan 
 festivals, to the widespread influence of 
 astrology, to the dominant ideas of fate, to 
 the current practices of " man tic" ; his com- 
 ments on Greek education, on the function 
 of rhetoric and dialectic, on current political 
 thought and existing scientific beliefs, are 
 invaluable for the reconstruction of an all- 
 important period. But far above this more 
 or less incidental interest is his position as a 
 
 7 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 Hellenistic Jewish thinker, whose life was 
 spent at Alexandria, probably at that time 
 the most remarkable centre of religious fer- 
 ment in the Eastern world. It has been 
 customary for scholars (e.g. Bousset) to treat 
 Philo as a completely isolated phenomenon. 
 This seems to us an abuse of the argument 
 from silence. Unquestionably his individu- 
 ality is unique. But, as Bousset himself 
 admits, Philo gives many hints that he stands 
 in a line of religious philosophers of Jewish 
 birth, who combined devotion to the sacred 
 tradition of their race with the wider outlook 
 opened to them by contemporary Hellenistic 
 speculation. 1 We naturally think in this 
 connection of the author or (as it is probably 
 a composite work) authors of the Wisdom of 
 Solomon, which most scholars assign to the 
 milieu of Alexandria. But this document is 
 a genuine product of the developed Wisdom- 
 literature of the Jews. It is philosophical 
 
 ^ Jiidisch'Christliche Schul-betrieb, pp. 153, 154. It seems 
 to us that Bousset's source-criticism of Leg. Alleg. ii. and iii. 
 (op. cit. p. 82 f.), and of De Congress. Erud. Gr. (p. 109 f.), 
 governed by this standpoint, is far too subjective to be 
 relied on. 
 
 8 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 only to a very limited degree. No doubt its 
 conception of Wisdom often coincides with 
 the Reason of the Stoics as the all-pervading 
 TTvev/jua of the universe. And the famous 
 description in chap. vii. 22 ff. would at many 
 points cohere with Philo's doctrine of the 
 Logos. But the thought of the book has 
 not been steeped in Greek metaphysics, as 
 Philo's has been, and what is perhaps the 
 most noteworthy element in it, the remark- 
 able stress laid on the hope of immortality, 
 belongs to a province not specially cultivated 
 by the later thinker. Hence it would be 
 illegitimate to group these authors, at any 
 rate, in a -single school. A large amount 
 of the material embodied in Philo's volumi- 
 nous writings is quite obviously inherited 
 tradition. 1 It appears often in the same 
 form, occasionally with slight variations, in 
 the compilers who abounded after the creative 
 epoch of Greek philosophy had spent its 
 force. 2 As incorporated in Compendia, it 
 was probably familiar to many of his fellow- 
 
 1 See Bousset, op. cit., e.g. pp. 14 ff., 23, 153. 
 
 2 See, e.g.) Schmekel, Die Mittlere Stoa> pp. 409-428. 
 
 9 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 countrymen who, like himself, had passed 
 through a curriculum of Greek education. 
 But in Philo's case the search for truth was 
 a consuming passion. His facile pen was 
 not daunted by any nice feeling for style. 
 His cumbrous and careless paragraphs are 
 indeed often left threadbare with repetition. 
 But when his spirit kindles, his language 
 takes fire, and the tedium of fine-spun 
 speculation is overshadowed by the glimpse 
 of a soul rapt up to the vision of God. 
 
 It may help us to a truer estimate of 
 Philo's thought and experience if we take a 
 brief glance at the personality of the man. 
 That is made comparatively easy by his self- 
 revealing tendency. There is a frankness 
 and artlessness about his attitude towards 
 men and things which give careful readers 
 of his books a sense of real acquaintance 
 with their author. This intimacy does not 
 mean the mere satisfying of curiosity as to 
 his tastes and pursuits, his prejudices or his 
 enthusiasms. It creates a feeling of affec- 
 tionate friendliness. Here is a man of lofty 
 
 ideals, of unwearying zeal in the quest for 
 
 10 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 goodness and truth : one who can turn his 
 back on the lower aspects of the life of 
 sense and keep himself " unspotted from the 
 world." Yet he assumes no airs. He takes 
 his readers into his confidence. If they are 
 willing to overlook a diffuseness which often 
 irritates, both in thought and style, and a 
 frequent cumbrousness of expression which 
 lays a burden on the attention, they may 
 dwell in a quiet, homely atmosphere with a 
 mind that is wholesome and refined, a spirit 
 which sends forth ennobling influences, and 
 leaves on sympathetic listeners the impression 
 that they have been in pure and stimulating 
 company. 
 
 In one of those notable glimpses which 
 Philo gives us of his own experience, he 
 describes with pathos his unmixed delight in 
 the contemplation of the world and God, a 
 condition in which he felt himself lifted high 
 above the worries of mortal life. But an evil 
 fate, jealous of his felicity, was lying in wait 
 to plunge him into the sea of turbulent 
 political anxieties. This hard lot was in- 
 evitable. All he can now do is to thank 
 
 ii 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 God that he is not completely engulfed in 
 the billows ; that he can still open the eyes 
 of his soul to the light of wisdom (De Spec. 
 Leg. iii. i ff.). The fervour of his utter- 
 ance is sufficient evidence of its sincerity. 
 Yet no responsive reader can think of Philo 
 as a recluse. A life of self-control and self- 
 dedication to the claims of religious contem- 
 plation is certainly his ideal. But no man 
 was ever more alive to the varied play and 
 colour of the world about him, and the society 
 of which he formed a part. His temperament 
 is keenly sensitive. He has followed with 
 absorbing interest the coming forth of bud 
 and leaf in spring (Quod Deus sit immut. 
 38 f.). He is fascinated by the beauty of 
 light (e.g. De Abr. 156 ff. ; De Ebriet. 44), 
 in which he finds a continual source of illus- 
 trations of spiritual processes. He has care- 
 fully watched the vicissitudes of ships both 
 in calm and stormy seas, and can make 
 effective use of his observations to delineate 
 the fortunes of the soul (e.g. De Cherub. 37 f. ; 
 De Migr. Abr. 6 ; De Post. Cain. 22). Music 
 appeals to him, and he has some knowledge 
 
 12 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 of harmony (e.g. De Post. Cain. 105 f. ; De 
 Cherub, no). He has an intimate acquaint- 
 ance with the athletic festivals of the Graeco- 
 Roman world, and has studied the efforts 
 and aims of the competitors (e.g. De Agric. 
 n iff.; De Cherub. 81 ff.). He has fre- 
 quented the theatre, and carried away clear, 
 shrewd impressions (De Ebriet. 49 ff.). He 
 is a man of general cultivation, who has felt 
 the charm of the great art of Pheidias (De 
 Ebriet. 89), and can make apt quotations 
 from Homer and Euripides when occasion 
 calls. He shows a thorough knowledge of 
 the ordinary curriculum of Greek education, 
 and is able to discuss its details with insight 
 (e.g. De Ebriet. 49 ff. ; De Congress. Erud. 
 I5ff; De Somn. i. 205). He reveals a 
 quite definite interest in medicine (e.g. Quod 
 Deus sit immut. 65 f. ; De Sacrif. Ab. 123), 
 and Breliier believes that he had taken a 
 medical course (Les Iddes phil. et relig. de 
 Philon, p. 286 and n. 6). 
 
 His outlook upon ordinary life is sane and 
 penetrating. He has reflected much on 
 politics, and his remarks on the statesman 
 
 13 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 (e.g. De Joseph. 32 ff., 54 ff.) are the well- 
 weighed product of ripe observation. He 
 gives vivid, caustic estimates of the familiar 
 figure of the sophist (e.g. De Congr. Erud. 
 67 f. ; Quod det. pot. 72 f. ; De Agric. 136). 
 He is aware of the vulgar extravagances of 
 the wealthy (De Fuga, 28 ff.), and of the 
 follies of reckless luxury (De Somn. ii. 
 48 ff.). And the pointed appeal which he 
 makes to money-lenders as a class lifts the 
 veil from a corner of the social life of the 
 time. But he is an observer also of the 
 more elusive aspects of human intercourse, 
 a fact indicated, for example, by the illumi- 
 nating things he has to say on the reflection 
 of a man's moods in his eyes (De Abr. 151). 
 It would take too long even barely to outline 
 his wide knowledge of the natural sciences 
 of his day, as exemplified, to mention only 
 one department, by his frequent references to 
 the laws which govern the movements of the 
 heavenly bodies. But perhaps enough has 
 been said to emphasise the mental alertness, 
 the moral balance, and the real lovableness 
 of this remarkable Jewish Hellenist who 
 
 H 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 stood on the threshold of a new and 
 wonderful epoch. 
 
 Yet before we leave this phase of our 
 subject, we feel compelled to illustrate by 
 one or two passages the poetic aspect of 
 Philo's temperament, so fundamental for his 
 thinking, and so strangely overlooked. 
 
 In the first which we shall quote, he is 
 making an impassioned protest against the 
 evil fortune which suddenly plunged him, in 
 the midst of his meditation on the highest 
 things, into the whirlpool of political life. 
 He has not been completely swept away. 
 " There are moments when I raise my head, 
 and with spiritual eyesight bedimmed (for 
 the keen glance of the soul has been clouded 
 by the haze of alien interests), gaze around, 
 with ardent yearning for a pure and untroubled 
 life. And then, if there be granted me, with- 
 out looking for it, a brief calm and respite 
 from political turmoil, I soar aloft in winged 
 flight, well-nigh treading the air, breathing 
 the breath of Knowledge, which ever urges 
 me to flee to her converse as from harsh 
 taskmasters, not men alone, but the torrent 
 
 15 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 of affairs that surges in upon me from every 
 side. Nevertheless it is meet to give thanks 
 to God that, despite my struggle with the 
 flood, I am not engulfed in its depths, but 
 may open the eyes of my soul which, in 
 despair of all bright hope, I deemed to be 
 fast closed, and am illumined by the radiance 
 of wisdom, not delivered over for ever to the 
 sway of darkness " (De Spec. Leg. iii. 46). 
 For Philo the heights of wisdom and know- 
 ledge are only to be attained in communion 
 with God. And it is when the sense of God 
 and His goodness to the soul breaks upon 
 him that his utterance is exalted to a poetic 
 strain, the expression of a high passion. " If 
 a yearning come upon thee, O soul, to possess 
 the good, which is Divine, forsake not only 
 thy 'country,' the body, and thy ' kindred,' 
 the sense-life, and thy * father's house,' the 
 reason, but flee from thyself, and depart out 
 of thyself, in a Divine madness of prophetic 
 inspiration, as those possessed with Corybantic 
 frenzy. For that high lot becomes thine 
 when the understanding is rapt in ecstasy, 
 
 feverishly agitated with a heavenly passion, 
 
 16 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 beside itself, driven by the power of him who 
 is True Being, drawn upwards towards him, 
 while truth leads the way " (Quis Rer. Div. 
 H. 69, 70). Notably does his wonder in pres- 
 ence of the Divine grace break out in hymns 
 of praise. " Bounteous, O Lover of giving, 
 are thy kindnesses, without limit or boundary 
 or end, as fountains which pour forth streams 
 too plentiful to be carried away " (op. cit. 3 1 ). 
 And again : " O mighty Lord, how shall we 
 praise thee, with what lips, with what tongue, 
 with what speech, with what governing power 
 of the spirit ? Can the stars, blended in single 
 chorus, chant thee a worthy anthem ? Can 
 the whole heaven, melted into sound, declare 
 even a portion of thine excellences?" (De 
 Vita Mas. ii. (iii.) 239). At times the rapture 
 of his spirit imparts a fresh glow to Nature. 
 " The soul anticipates its expectation of God," 
 he says, " with an early joy. We may liken 
 it to that which happens with plants. For 
 these, when they are to bear fruit, first bud 
 and blossom and put forth shoots. Look at 
 the vine, how wondrously Nature has decked 
 
 it out with slender twigs and tendrils, with 
 B 17 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 suckers and leaves, which all but utter in 
 living accent the joy of the tree over the fruit 
 that is to come. The day, too, laughs at 
 early dawn, as it waits for the sun-rising. 
 For there is a first heralding of the sun's 
 beams, and a dimmer radiance proclaims the 
 fuller blaze" (De Mut. Norn. 161 f.). This 
 poetic feeling gives us a truer clue to the 
 soul of the man than most of his favourite 
 speculations. It reveals his profound kinship, 
 on the one hand with the Psalmists of his race, 
 on the other with his Greek master, Plato, in 
 the deepest reaches of the inner life. It be- 
 longs indissolubly to that mystic "enthusiasm" 
 which was so dominant a force in all his aspira- 
 tions, and which pervades his religion at its 
 highest. His search for God glows with a 
 radiant ardour, the reflection of a spirit that 
 thrills to the finest issues. 
 
 Here, then, is a devout Jewish thinker, the 
 groundwork of whose spiritual life is the 
 religion of the Old Testament. Never for 
 a moment does he swerve from his allegiance 
 to that sacred tradition. Never does he grow 
 
 weary of extolling the Divine legislation of 
 
 18 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 which Moses has been the mouthpiece. 
 But he is a genuine product of the Diaspora. 
 We know that Egypt was not only one of the 
 earliest countries to admit Jews to its hospi- 
 tality, but that there special privileges were 
 accorded to them. That must have counted 
 for much in their attitude to the Hellenistic 
 environment created by Alexander's con- 
 quests, and the movements that followed 
 them. It was probably customary at Alex- 
 andria, with its famous schools of learning, 
 for Jews of intellectual bent to avail them- 
 selves of " the general education " (fj cy/cvicXux: 
 7rcuSeia) current in Greek society. In any 
 case Philo valued both the introductory 
 course, and the profounder study of philo- 
 sophy which came later. We have few data 
 from which to reconstruct his actual curri- 
 culum. Part of it he probably received within 
 his own community. But it is difficult to 
 avoid the conclusion that he had come into 
 personal touch with the philosophical schools 
 of the great " University " of the city in 
 which his life was spent. 
 
 What is of paramount interest for us is to 
 19 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 observe carefully the effect of the impact of 
 Greek ideas upon this sensitive religious 
 mind. Did they produce serious modifica- 
 tions in his inherited conceptions of God, of 
 God's relations to men, of human nature, of 
 the purpose of life ? How far could a loyal 
 Jew be affected by contemporary notions of 
 the fundamental elements of experience, such 
 as matter and spirit, reason, moral obligation 
 and the like ? To what extent were the 
 spiritual values of the Old Testament replaced 
 by others ? Does the process reveal a prepar- 
 ation for or approximation to the Christian 
 view of God and the world ? Such questions 
 form one aspect of our inquiry. And they 
 must come up again and again in our exami- 
 nation of the main subject before us, the con- 
 tribution of Philo to religion. But through- 
 out the discussion we wish deliberately to 
 reckon with the phenomena of the New 
 Testament. There we are confronted by 
 what is, in some important respects, a parallel 
 situation. The Letters of Paul, the Epistle to 
 the Hebrews, and the Fourth Gospel are also 
 
 the products of devout Jewish minds. They 
 
 20 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 all spring from an Old Testament soil. But 
 they all presuppose a Hellenistic environment. 
 Their authors have been more or less in touch 
 with the currents of contemporary thought, 
 and they have to meet the needs of Jews like 
 themselves who have burst the bonds of a rigid 
 Judaism, as well as of Gentiles, whom pagan 
 religion, even in its highest forms, has failed 
 to satisfy. How far has there been a reaction 
 to Greek thought on their part ? Has that 
 thought penetrated their central categories ? 
 Has it reshaped to any degree their working 
 conceptions of God and His contact with 
 human life ? Or, has their experience of 
 Jesus Christ so completely overshadowed 
 every other force in their religion as practi- 
 cally to neutralise the power of environment ? 
 We know that conflicting answers are being 
 given to these questions at the present time. 
 Perhaps a comparison at salient points with 
 the positions of Philo will help to illuminate 
 the situation. At least, it may clear away 
 some misconceptions and suggest a more 
 accurate perspective. 
 
 What has been said serves roughly to 
 21 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 determine the nature of our proposed investi- 
 gation. The works of Philo form a sort of 
 encyclopaedia of ancient philosophical ideas, 
 of results, often naive enough, attained by the 
 science of his day, of traditional lore, Hellen- 
 istic and Jewish, of spiritual experiences of 
 his own which have the perennial fascination 
 of real life. Much of this material we delib- 
 erately ignore. We have no intention of 
 examining the bearings of his philosophical 
 standpoint as a whole. Nor does it lie 
 within our scope to discuss systematically 
 even such central conceptions as that of God 
 or the Universe or the Logos or vow or the 
 Moral Ideal. Our chief aim is to sketch, how- 
 ever fragmentary, making constant use of his 
 own words, the contribution which this loyal, 
 earnest and highly cultivated Jewish thinker 
 made to religion at the very time when Jesus 
 appeared with His Gospel of the Fatherhood 
 of God and a Divine Kingdom not of this 
 world, won through suffering and death : 
 when the followers of Jesus Christ carried 
 through the Diaspora the message of a new 
 
 relation to God, made possible through 
 
 22 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 Christ crucified and risen. As has been in- 
 dicated, we desire to relate our discussion at 
 one point and another to the New Testament 
 material. That does not mean the endeavour 
 to search out groups of parallel ideas or 
 formulas in Philo and the great New Testa- 
 ment writers. 1 Such a task has frequently 
 been attempted in one form or other, and it is 
 doubtful whether it has led to important 
 results. So much depends on the contexts 
 of the passages singled out and the back- 
 ground against which they stand. And these 
 are features of the situation which have 
 usually been ignored. It would seem more 
 profitable to examine carefully certain in- 
 tegral elements in the fabric of Philo's religion 
 for their own sake, endeavouring with caution 
 to estimate the forces which have shaped 
 them, and then to try to discover in what 
 relation they stand to corresponding New 
 Testament conceptions. If the material be 
 properly selected, each ought to shed light 
 on its parallel. And there is the advantage 
 
 1 Cf. Jowett's essay on " St. Paul and Philo," in his Com- 
 mentary on ThessalonianS) Galatians and Romans^ vol. i. 
 
 23 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 in both cases that the Old Testament contri- 
 butes a common background. 
 
 The masterly edition of Philo's works by 
 Cohn, Wendland and Reiter (of which six 
 volumes have appeared, Berlin, 1896-1915), 
 one of the finest achievements of modern 
 scholarship, provides a thoroughly trust- 
 worthy basis of investigation, with the ad- 
 dition of the Quaestiones in Genesim and in 
 Exodum, translated from the Armenian into 
 Latin by J. B. Aucher. 1 The only treatise 
 in Cohn's edition of whose genuineness we 
 are not convinced is the De Aeternitate 
 Mundi y which has far more the appearance 
 of a somewhat superficial compilation than 
 any of the other documents. A vigorous 
 attack on its authenticity may be found in the 
 Quellenstudien zu Philo von Alexandria of so 
 highly equipped a scholar as H. von Arnim 
 (Philologische Untersuchungen,z&. by Kiessling 
 u. Wilamowitz, Berlin, 1888), pp. 1-52. But 
 this is not the place either to embark on source- 
 criticism or to investigate the development of 
 
 1 In the Quaestiones we have used the Leipzig ed. of Philo 
 (1829-30), vols. vi.-vii. 
 
 2 4 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 Philo's ideas by attempting a chronological 
 arrangement of his works. The most inter- 
 esting essay in that direction is Cohn's article, 
 " Einleitung u. Chronologic der Schriften 
 Philo's," in Philologus, Supplem. Bd. vii., 1899. 
 
 It seems advisable to begin by emphasising 
 the more characteristic features of Philo's re- 
 lation to the Old Testament. We do not 
 propose to spend time on the details of his 
 allegorical method, except in so far as these 
 may illuminate various corresponding features 
 in the Pauline Epistles and the Fourth Gospel 
 But his general attitude to the Law and the 
 Prophets is important for the entire discus- 
 sion, and his doctrine of verbal inspiration not 
 only raises some curious problem for his own 
 writings, but has a bearing on certain re- 
 markable phenomena in the New Testament. 
 
 Every large-minded religious thinker is 
 bound to relate his positions to various philo- 
 sophical assumptions more or less consciously 
 recognised. This is especially true of one like 
 Philo, for whom philosophy had opened up a 
 new universe. Contradictions may often be 
 traced among such assumptions, contradic- 
 
 2 5 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 tions which have scarcely been realised by 
 the philosophical theologian himself. In 
 ancient thought, moreover, which preserved 
 survivals of primitive religion and primitive 
 science, these discrepancies were bound to 
 remain for long undetected. The risk was in- 
 tensified in the case of a devout Jew, whose 
 enthusiasm for the efforts of Greek speculation 
 concealed from him the fact that he was con- 
 stantly attempting to fuse together incom- 
 patible magnitudes. But granting all this, it 
 ought to repay us to examine his attitude to 
 such fundamental problems as the relation 
 of God and the world and the constitution of 
 human nature, not merely for the purpose of 
 discovering how far Hellenistic thought influ- 
 enced his ultimate postulates, but also for the 
 purpose of ascertaining what points of contact, 
 if any, may emerge between him and his 
 Hellenistic- Jewish contemporary, Paul of 
 Tarsus, who had also seriously reflected on 
 these very questions. 
 
 Our supreme interest, however, attaches to 
 Philo's religion. That presupposes man's 
 
 yearning for God and God's approach to 
 
 26 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 man. Here it is above all else important to 
 investigate, on the one hand, his conception 
 of the Divine grace in the wide range of its 
 activities, and on the other, the obstacles 
 which thwart the human soul and deaden its 
 sensitiveness to higher influences, in a word, 
 the many-sided phenomena of the inner life 
 which may be grouped under such categories 
 as sin, conscience, repentance and faith. This, 
 further, is the sphere to which would belong 
 a consideration, however fragmentary, of 
 Philo's doctrine of the Logos. That doctrine, 
 as we have hinted, is riddled with contradic- 
 tions. But the idea of mediators between God 
 and the world is so central for Philo (as it 
 was for his pagan and Jewish contemporaries) 
 in one form or other, that we must briefly 
 touch upon a few of its salient aspects, keep- 
 ing in view at the same time the New 
 Testament parallels, and especially the all- 
 important Biblical conception of the Spirit of 
 God. 
 
 We shall then be in a position to deal with 
 the crowning-point of Philo's religious aspira- 
 tion, union with God. A wide vista is here 
 
 27 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 opened up. The content embraced in it is 
 far from being co-ordinated. It consists of 
 sudden flashes of insight and exaltation. In 
 these Philo reveals the depths of his religious 
 consciousness as nowhere else. But intuitions 
 defy analysis. The most sacred type of feel- 
 ing cannot be dissected. We must be content 
 with examining some presuppositions of this 
 high attainment. The pathway will thus be 
 prepared for approaching the author's crown- 
 ing doctrine of the Vision of God. Our 
 investigation will be rounded off by a brief 
 discussion of Philo's mysticism and the in- 
 spiration and ecstasy which are its conditions. 
 
 28 
 
CHAPTER II 
 
 PHILO'S RELATION TO THE OLD 
 TESTAMENT 
 
 NO more instructive summary could be 
 given of Philo's general attitude 
 towards the Old Testament than that which 
 appears in his own remarkable statement of 
 Moses' various functions as leader of Israel. 
 "We have already argued," he says, "that 
 the perfectly-equipped leader must have four 
 functions assigned to him, the kingly, the 
 legislative, the priestly, and the prophetic, 
 that as legislator he may enjoin what ought 
 to be done and forbid what ought not, that 
 as priest he may deal not only with human 
 but also with Divine matters, that as prophet 
 he may reveal what cannot be grasped by 
 reason. As I have discussed the first three 
 of these, and proved that Moses excelled as 
 king and legislator and high priest, I come 
 
 finally to show that he was also the most 
 
 29 
 
PHILO'S RELATION TO 
 
 notable of prophets. I thus recognise that 
 all that stands written in the sacred books 
 are Divine oracles, declared through him, 
 and I will go on to details, after making this 
 observation : of these sacred utterances some 
 were spoken by God in person, using His 
 marvellous prophet as interpreter, some were 
 revealed as the result of question and answer, 
 and some were announced by Moses in person, 
 in a state of inspiration and possession " (De 
 Vita Mas. ii. (iii.) 187 f.). 
 
 Various features here are significant. 
 Moses is the supreme figure in the history of 
 the chosen people. He has been used as 
 the special medium of the Divine revelation 
 to Israel. What he has written in the sacred 
 books possesses Divine authority. The 
 statement makes it clear that for Philo the 
 Pentateuch is the kernel of the Old Testa- 
 ment, and that it is in the most literal sense 
 inspired. We shall not discuss at this stage 
 Philo's conception of inspiration. But in 
 order to realise its scope, it must be observed 
 that he assigns the same infallibility to the 
 
 Septuagint translation as that which belongs 
 
 30 
 
THE OLD TESTAMENT 
 
 to the original. He accepts the Jewish legend 
 as to the miraculous agreement of all the 
 translators, working separately, in their 
 renderings, and observes that these men 
 must be called " not translators but hiero- 
 phants and prophets, inasmuch as it was 
 granted to them by unalloyed reasonings to 
 coincide with the wholly pure spirit of Moses " 
 (pp. cit. ii. 40). We may note in passing 
 that it is the translation of the laws which is 
 especially before his mind (op. cit. ii. 36). 
 
 Philo's chief aim in all his works, it need 
 scarcely be said, is to demonstrate the universal 
 validity of Jewish religion as enshrined in the 
 Old Testament, and, par excellence, in the 
 Pentateuch. Probably he devotes himself to 
 this task for his own sake, for that of his co- 
 religionists, and to win the attention of his 
 Hellenistic contemporaries. In his own case 
 the extraordinary fascination of Greek philo- 
 sophy for his mind perhaps compelled him to 
 adjust the powerful claims of reason to the 
 authority of what he regarded as a Divine 
 revelation. A similar adjustment would be 
 needful for many of his fellow-countrymen who 
 
 3 1 
 
PHILO'S RELATION TO 
 
 had passed through experiences like his own. 
 And it was natural for him to appeal along 
 these lines to fair-minded pagans, in whose 
 rich heritage of wisdom he shared, but who, he 
 felt, had lessons of incalculable value to learn 
 from the Divinely-taught philosophy of Moses. 
 But the work was beset by difficulties. 
 Although he never challenged the assumption 
 of verbal inspiration, he could no longer 
 approach the sacred text with the artlessness 
 of unquestioning submission. Thus when 
 he reads in Gen. ii. 8 that " God planted a 
 garden in Eden," he remarks : "To suppose 
 that vines and olive-trees or apple-trees . . . 
 were planted by God is utter and incurable 
 stupidity. . . . We must therefore have re- 
 course to allegory, the favourite method of 
 men of vision ". (De Plant. 32 ff.). There 
 can be little question that Philo stood in a 
 long succession of allegorical interpreters of 
 the Old Testament. The practice had been 
 reduced to a kind of science. 1 This he 
 
 1 At the same time, Siegfried's list of allegorical canons 
 (Philo von Alexandria als Ausleger d. A.T., pp. 168-197) 
 assumes a rigidity of practice for which we have no 
 adequate evidence. 
 
 32 
 
THE OLD TESTAMENT 
 
 assumes. " Do not be surprised," he says, 
 quite incidentally, " if, according to the rules 
 (Kavovas) of allegory, the sun is identified 
 [in Gen. xxviii. n] with the Father and 
 Governor of the universe " (De Somn. i. 73). 
 Numerous references of the same character 
 occur in his writings. A large variety of 
 competing interpretations is current and 
 familiar to Philo. In discussing, e.g., the 
 phrase used of Abraham (Gen. xv. 15), 
 "Thou shalt depart to thy fathers" he 
 mentions three differing explanations of 
 " thy fathers " : " Some say, the sun and 
 moon and the other stars. . . . Some think 
 of the archetypal Ideas. . . . Some have con- 
 jectured that the four elements are meant of 
 which the universe is composed " (Quis Rer. 
 Div. H. 280 ff.). Occasionally he speaks of 
 his predecessors in this art. as <f>vaiicol ai/fyes 
 (e.g. De Abr. 99; De Vita Mas. ii. (iii.) 
 103), sometimes, as in the quotation above, 
 as opaTiKol. Apparently, therefore, he was 
 in possession of an elaborately articulated 
 system of allegorical exegesis, although he 
 does not hesitate again and again to suggest 
 c 33 
 
PHILO'S RELATION TO 
 
 interpretations of his own (see esp. the 
 remarkable passage, De Cherub. 27 ff.). 
 Hence we need not be surprised to come 
 upon the statement : " Practically every- 
 thing, or at least most things, in our legisla- 
 tion must be taken allegorically " (De Joseph. 
 28). Philo acts consistently upon this 
 principle, and his theory of allegory is 
 worthy of a brief notice. It is essentially 
 esoteric in character, and this presupposes 
 a certain initiation, if its application is to 
 be grasped. In introducing a complicated 
 allegorical explanation of the sacrifice of 
 Isaac which Abraham was ready to carry 
 out, he says : " The story as a matter of fact 
 does not rest upon the literal and obvious 
 version, so that to the average reader its 
 nature seems rather obscure, but those who 
 have an understanding for the invisible things 
 of the mind rather than for the perceptions 
 of the senses and who possess the power of 
 vision, recognise it" (De Abr. 200). That 
 is the reason why once and again he appeals 
 to his readers in the language of the 
 Mysteries, e.g. Leg. All. iii. 209 : " Open 
 
 34 
 
THE OLD TESTAMENT 
 
 your ears, O ye initiates, and receive the 
 mystic ritual." 
 
 Plainly, his method enables Philo to remove 
 innumerable stumbling-blocks from the sacred 
 narratives : e.g. to take literally the statement 
 of Gen. xi. 5, that "the Lord came down to 
 view the city and the tower," is " monstrous 
 impiety." For " who is not aware that one 
 who comes down must leave one part of 
 space and occupy another. But the whole 
 universe is rilled by God " (De Con/us. Ling. 
 135 f. ). The startling character of the phrase 
 can only be explained, as in other cases, by 
 the legislator's need of using human speech 
 about a God who is not anthropomorphic, to 
 assist men's spiritual education (op. cit. 134 f.). 
 The real explanation lies beneath the sur- 
 face. An obstacle of a less serious type is 
 found in Jacob's command to Joseph to visit 
 his brethren in Sychem (Gen. xxxvii. 13). 
 " How could any one in his senses accept 
 such a situation ? Is it likely that a man 
 with such kingly resources as Jacob should 
 have such a scarcity of slaves or servants that 
 he must send his son abroad " on errands 
 
 35 
 
PHILO'S RELATION TO 
 
 of this kind? (Quod det. pot. insid. 13). 
 Here also trained insight is necessary. Yet 
 Philo's practice is by no means uniform. 
 Thus to a very large extent he treats the 
 story of Abraham's obedience in the sacrifice 
 of Isaac as a historical narrative, and gives an 
 elaborate exposition of it on that basis (De 
 Abr. 167-199). The early life of Joseph 
 is similarly handled as actual history (De 
 Joseph. 1-27), although its allegorical exegesis 
 follows. Indeed, in De Migr. Abr. 89, he 
 goes the length of saying : " There have 
 been some who, regarding the literal laws as 
 symbols of ideal realities, were excessively 
 scrupulous in some points, while in others 
 they were lazily negligent. For my own 
 part I must blame such people for their 
 laxity. For both elements demand attention, 
 the most diligent search for hidden meanings, 
 and the preservation of those on the surface 
 which cannot be challenged." The literal 
 sense he compares in this passage to the 
 body, the symbolic to the soul (op. cit. 93). 
 The comparison explains the well-known 
 statement of Clement of Alexandria regard- 
 
 36 
 
THE OLD TESTAMENT 
 
 ing the Fourth Gospel (Eus. H.E. vi. 14): 
 " John, last of all, having perceived that the 
 bodily things had been set forth in the 
 Gospels, being urged by his friends, inspired 
 by the Spirit, produced a spiritual Gospel " ; 
 and indirectly supplies the clue to much that 
 is enigmatic and baffling throughout that 
 book. In agreement with this frequently 
 close adherence to the literal narrative is the 
 emphasis Philo lays on minute verbal points. 
 He finds, e.g., in Ex. xxi. 12 the law: "If 
 a man strike another and he die, he must 
 certainly be put to death" (Oavdrw Oavarovo-Qat,). 
 " Being clearly aware," he proceeds, " that he 
 [Moses] never uses a superfluous word. . . . 
 I was puzzled by his saying of the volun- 
 tary slayer not Only BavarovaQat, but Qavdra 
 6avarova-6ai. . . . But when I consulted that 
 wise woman whose name is Enquiry, I was 
 relieved from my search : for she taught me 
 that some living people are really dead, while 
 some who have died are truly alive " (De Fuga, 
 54 f.). Similarly, in the opening paragraphs 
 of De Agricult. he urges the minute accuracy 
 of Moses in his use of terms, and presses the 
 
 37 
 
PHILO'S RELATION TO 
 
 distinction between yewpyta, husbandry, and 
 7/79 epyao-la, the working of land. 1 
 
 Yet there are other features of his usage 
 which seem directly to conflict with this 
 microscopic attention to detail. An extra- 
 ordinary example is his manner of quoting 
 from the LXX. We have seen that he held 
 the translation to be verbally inspired. Never- 
 theless he handles the infallible text with the 
 utmost freedom. Often, in citing a passage, 
 he gives part of it in his own words : e.g. 
 in Gen. xv. 6, for the clause, "it was 
 counted to him for righteousness," he sub- 
 stitutes, "he was considered righteous." 
 More daringly still, he sometimes without 
 warning replaces the very words he is 
 supposed to be interpreting by his own 
 allegorical explanation : e.g. in Num. v. 2 : 
 " Let them send away out of the camp 
 every leper," he substitutes for rf)$ 
 
 1 In the light of these and many parallel phenomena, it 
 seems by no means legitimate to draw the sharp distinction 
 which Bousset does between the Palestinian Rabbinic 
 exegesis and that of Alexandria, and to say that the one is 
 of the letter, while the other is of the spirit (Die Religion d. 
 Judenfums*, p. 185). The Rabbinic scrupulousness about 
 verbal minutiae has unquestionably influenced Philo. 
 
 38 ' 
 
THE OLD TESTAMENT 
 
 the phrase, rfy ayiov ^#779, "the consecrated 
 soul." Repeatedly he exchanges a less for 
 a more familiar word, and often omits un- 
 important expressions altogether. 1 Equally 
 remarkable, in view of his standpoint, are such 
 statements as that which he makes regarding 
 the creation of Eve. In expounding Gen. 
 ii. 21, " And he took a rib," etc., he remarks : 
 " The literal narrative in this case is mythical, 
 for, could anybody accept the story that 
 woman was made out of the rib of a man ? " 
 (Leg. Alleg. ii. 19). So also, in speaking 
 of Moses 1 fiery serpents, which call up the 
 story of the serpent's deception of Eve, he 
 describes them as prodigies, and adds : " But 
 in explanations based on the hidden sense, 
 the mythical element disappears, and the 
 truth is made evident" (De Agricult. 96 f.). 
 Here is a definite recognition of myth in the 
 patriarchal narratives. 
 
 How are we to relate these features of his 
 attitude towards the text to his doctrine of 
 verbal inspiration ? As a matter of fact, they 
 
 1 These instances are taken from Bishop Kyle's most useful 
 discussion, Philo and Holy Scripture^ pp. xxxv-xxxviii. 
 
 39 
 
PHILO'S RELATION TO 
 
 are wholly irreconcilable. Without realising 
 what had happened, Philo, by his adoption 
 of the allegorical method, had emptied his 
 basal doctrine of all genuine value. By 
 continuing to emphasise verbal details, he 
 presented, indeed, the appearance of loyalty 
 to his fundamental assumption, and probably 
 he concealed from himself the implications 
 of his normative system. Hence, whatever 
 language he might still use, in reality he 
 accepted as much of the literal text as suited 
 his scheme of thought, and had no hesitation 
 in explaining away what proved incompatible 
 with that. 
 
 A comparison with St. Paul's standpoint 
 at once presses itself on our attention. For 
 the same kind of difficulty confronts him in 
 a parallel situation. Very rarely, indeed, 
 does the Apostle have recourse to the alle- 
 gorical method, which was evidently familiar 
 to him. The most notable instance is, of 
 course, the allegory of the two Covenants, 
 under the names of Sarah and her handmaid, 
 Hagar (Gal. iv. 21-31), the mistress sym- 
 bolising the heavenly Jerusalem, the free 
 
 40 
 
THE OLD TESTAMENT 
 
 community of Christians, the slave repre- 
 senting the earthly centre of Judaism, which 
 remains in the bondage of legalism. Philo 
 more than once allegorises the same story, 
 but, as we should expect, on totally different 
 lines (De Congress. Erud. Grat., esp. 11-24). 
 Thus for him, Sarah stands for complete 
 virtue, with whom Abraham, the " learner," 
 cannot at first be fruitfully united. He must 
 first wed Hagar, i.e. preliminary instruction. 
 Later on, his marriage with virtue will bring 
 forth fruit. A precisely similar use of the 
 story is made by him in Quaestt. in Gen. iii. 
 pp. 190-191. So far as historical sense is 
 concerned, there is little difference between 
 the two writers. To say, as Lightfoot does 
 (Galatians, p. 199), that " Philo is, as usual, 
 wholly unhistorical," while with " St. Paul, 
 on the other hand, Hagar's career is an 
 allegory, because it is a history," is to 
 ignore the fact that Hagar's " history" has 
 no connection of any kind with existing 
 Judaism, and Paul's use of it is as arbitrary 
 on its own lines as Philo's. A remarkably 
 close correspondence of standpoint is ex- 
 
PHILO'S RELATION TO 
 
 hibited by a comparison of Paul's position 
 in i Cor. ix. 9-10 with that of Philo in 
 De Sacrific. 260. The Apostle, in defending 
 the right of missionaries to be supported by 
 the communities in which they labour, not 
 only refers to the words of Jesus (Luke x. 7), 
 but also quotes the precept of Deut. xxv. 
 4, " Thou shalt not muzzle the ox that 
 treads the corn," and applies it by asking : 
 " Does God care about oxen ? Or does he 
 speak thus with us exclusively in view ? Of 
 course it was written on our account." Simi- 
 larly, Philo, in discussing the regulations 
 regarding sacrificial animals, proceeds : " You 
 will discover that all this minuteness in 
 reference to the animal shadows forth by 
 means of symbols the improvement of your 
 character. For the law does not exist for 
 irrational creatures, but for those possessing 
 mind and reason, so that its concern is not 
 for sacrificial animals, to provide that they 
 be without blemish, but for those who offer 
 the sacrifices, that they be not disquieted by 
 reason of any passion." Philo also misses 
 
 the significance of one of those humane laws 
 
 42 
 
THE OLD TESTAMENT 
 
 which characterise the Old Testament code. 
 In Ex. xxii. 26 f. it is said : "If thou take 
 thy neighbour's upper garment as a pledge, 
 thou shalt give it back to him before sunset : 
 for it is his only covering. ... In what shall 
 he sleep? If he cry to me, I will listen to 
 him, for I am merciful." Philo's comment 
 runs thus : " Is it not meet, if not to reproach, 
 at least to suggest to, those who suppose that 
 the legislator has all this concern about a piece 
 of clothing, What do you mean, my friend, 
 does the Creator and Ruler of the universe 
 call himself merciful in connection with so 
 trifling a matter as the failure of a creditor 
 to return his upper garment to a debtor ? ' 
 (De Somn. i. 92 f.). Strangely enough, 
 Philo expresses his delight in the injunc- 
 tion about oxen, which Paul explains 
 symbolically, and speaks of it as " that 
 tender and gracious ordinance" (De Virtut. 
 
 145 f.)- 
 
 The Apostle, however, is extraordinarily 
 sparing in turning history into symbolism. 
 In his treatment of the Old Testament, he 
 often approaches a philosophy of history, as 
 
 43 
 
PHILO'S RELATION TO 
 
 in Gal. iii. 17 ff. But in his doctrine of 
 verbal inspiration he is confronted by the 
 same kind of problem as Philo. For Paul 
 also regards the text of the Old Testament 
 as the literal utterance of God. Like Philo, 
 nevertheless, he does not hesitate, when 
 quoting from the LXX, to omit or supply 
 words for the advantage of his argument : and 
 often, as in his case, Paul's quotations have 
 the inaccuracy which comes from trusting to 
 memory. But his crucial difficulty arises 
 from his attitude towards the Law. A 
 priori, the Law, as the revelation of the 
 Divine will, is " holy and righteous and 
 good." It presents an unassailable moral 
 standard. Why, then, has it not satisfied 
 Paul's religious aspirations? At one stage 
 in his career, represented by such passages 
 as Gal. iii. 19, Rom. vii. 13, and 
 Rom. v. 20, he adopts as a working 
 hypothesis the idea that the function of 
 the Law in the purpose of God was to 
 intensify the consciousness of sin, to make 
 the conscience more sensitive to all breaches 
 of the Divine order, and thus to humble 
 
 44 
 
THE OLD TESTAMENT 
 
 man as a sinner in presence of the All-holy. 
 But he could not rest there. And in the 
 light of his Christian experience, he feels 
 after a further explanation. Already in 
 Rom. viii. 2 f. he speaks of the Law as 
 baffled by the influence of sinful flesh, human 
 nature as Paul knows it in ordinary experi- 
 ence. Sin, therefore, is to blame for the 
 Law's failure. Yet the admission that 
 human sin so completely foiled what was a 
 Divine method that a new way of salvation 
 had to be brought in, makes clear that Paul 
 was occupying ground which he could not 
 permanently hold. Even in " Galatians," 
 under the pressure of controversy with 
 Judaising Christians, he had ventured to 
 detract from the dignity of the Law, as 
 contrasted with the revelation of grace in 
 Jesus Christ (iii. 19). In the same context, 
 the necessity of a human medium for the 
 legal dispensation, even Moses, constituted 
 for Paul's mind, in diametrical opposition, we 
 may note in passing, to Philo's standpoint, 
 a ground of disparagement. In Gal. iv. 4 
 and iv. 8-13, he had gone the length of 
 
 45 
 
PHILO'S RELATION TO 
 
 comparing Jewish legalism with pagan ritual- 
 ism. But in " Colossians," one of his latest 
 Epistles, he takes a more daring step. His 
 growing appreciation of Christ more com- 
 pletely overshadows everything in religion 
 that appears to compete with Him for 
 men's allegiance. And so, in Col. ii. 14 
 he sternly sweeps away the entire principle 
 of Legalism as something inherently value- 
 less, something whose existence is incom- 
 patible with the forgiveness of sin. Thus, 
 as in Philo's case, Paul is driven by the 
 inexorable logic of experience, probably 
 without any formal recognition of what was 
 happening, far away from his original 
 position. He still finds in the Old Testa- 
 ment the revelation of God's will and purpose, 
 but he finds it in such elements as the Divine 
 grace towards Abraham, and the faith of 
 Abraham which responded to it. The later 
 legal aspect of religion stood on a lower 
 plane. It was an ''interpolation " (Gal. iii. 
 19) in the true development. 
 
 Before leaving the subject of Philo's re- 
 lation to the Old Testament as history, let us 
 
 46 
 
THE OLD TESTAMENT 
 
 note one or two directions in which his 
 method sheds some light on the Fourth 
 Gospel. It is necessary, on the whole, to 
 distinguish between Philo's allegorising and 
 that symbolic element in the Fourth Gospel 
 which comes the more fully to light the 
 more exhaustively its material is investigated. 
 The Evangelist's descriptions of the typical 
 miracles which he selects as "signs," his 
 deliberate association of these with elaborate 
 discussions which aim at a spiritual inter- 
 pretation of them, his predilection for mys- 
 terious sayings which admit of divergent 
 explanations (e.g. ii. 19-21, iii. 14-15, iii. 29, 
 iv. 1 8, iv. 35, vi. 53 f., vii. 38, xii. 24, xiii. 
 8-10), his use of expressions which have a 
 twofold meaning (i. 30, iii. 3, 8, iii. 14, iv. 10, 
 v. 25, xi. u, xii. 32, etc.), his symbolic 
 explanations of localities (ix. 7), the inner 
 allusiveness of such passages as i. 46-51, 
 iv. 15-26, etc., his reticence regarding "the 
 disciple whom Jesus loved " all these phe- 
 nomena and others of the same kind impart 
 a certain esoteric flavour to the Gospel 
 throughout. That forms an essential element 
 
 47 
 
PHILO'S RELATION TO 
 
 in the author's symbolism. And it involves 
 an elusiveness which marks the contrast 
 with Philo. For in strict allegory, as Mr. 
 J. M. Thompson points out, "a particular" 
 stands for a " particular," whereas " in 
 symbolism proper it stands for something 
 more general than itself." * But, of course, 
 the vaguer method often passes into the 
 more detailed correspondence, and vice 
 versa. Hence, various points for com- 
 parison are obvious. Beside Philo's constant 
 emphasis on the significance of . numbers, 
 e.g., on the number 4 (De Opif. M. 45-52), 
 on 7 (ibid. 89-106), on io(De Decal. 18-31), 
 may be placed, with some reservation, the 
 six water-pots at Cana, the five husbands of 
 the Samaritan woman, and the five porches 
 at Bethesda. What may be called the 
 " esoteric" element in the vocabulary of the 
 Fourth Gospel, embracing such terms as 
 
 copa, dvorfev, vtlrcoOijvcu, vvfA^ios, vS&p wi>, ol 
 veicpoi, /C.T.X., has parallels in Philo's mystic 
 use of TO?? (De Somn. ii. 61-68), afavis 
 
 1 Proceedings of Oxford Society of Historical Theology, 
 Dec. 4, 1913, p. 25. 
 
 4 8 
 
THE OLD TESTAMENT 
 
 (De Migr. Abr. 32), and 71-17777 (De Fuga, 
 177 f.). Only, Philo expounds the meaning 
 of these words, while the Evangelist seems 
 to count upon an understanding of his terms 
 in the circle for which he writes. Specially 
 noteworthy in Philo is his elaborate symbol- 
 ism of names. Names and their component 
 parts, he says (De Mutat. Nom. 65), are 
 really " distinctive marks of capacities " 
 (xapa/crfpes wdpea)v), and, on this principle, 
 such proper names as Egypt, Joseph, Leah, 
 Rachel, etc., designate certain definite quali- 
 ties or characters. The interpretation of 
 Siloam by the Evangelist suggests an allied 
 standpoint, and possibly, if we had a clue to 
 the usage of his circle, the same might be 
 said of such names as Nathanael and Nico- 
 demus. Curiously enough, Philo shows the 
 same kind of reticence about Jacob's son, 
 Judah, whom he usually describes as "the 
 fourth in age" (e.g. De Joseph. 15, 189) 
 without mentioning him by name, as the 
 Fourth Evangelist with regard to "the 
 disciple whom Jesus loved." 
 
 We enter a less obscure region when we 
 D 49 
 
PHILO'S RELATION TO 
 
 try to estimate the discourses of the Fourth 
 Gospel in the light of Philo's practice. 
 Indeed, the latter gives us a most arresting 
 clue to the attitude of ancient thinkers 
 towards that which they reckoned to be 
 history. We know that for him the Penta- 
 teuch was inspired in every detail. Yet in 
 narrating, e.g., God's instructions to Moses 
 to warn Pharaoh, as reported in Ex. iv. 
 ii f., he expands the discourse on lines of his 
 own, simply making the original his starting- 
 point (De Vita M. i. 84). Even more 
 remarkable is his recasting and elaboration 
 of Moses' injunctions to the spies before 
 they left on their errand (ibid. 222-226). 
 Taking Num. xiii. 17-20 as his basis, he 
 constructs upon it a composition which em- 
 bodies some of its leading ideas, but supple- 
 ments them in every direction. 1 This process 
 illustrates the usage of the Fourth Evan- 
 gelist, for whom some saying or thought of 
 Jesus forms the text of a carefully articulated 
 
 1 Perhaps Philo was here indebted to the tradition of the 
 poi : see Vita M. i. 4, referred to by Schiirer, 
 .) Div. ii. vol. iii. p. 365. 
 
 50 
 
THE OLD TESTAMENT 
 
 discourse. It appears to him in no sense 
 arbitrary to draw out on these lines the 
 significance of a message which he regarded 
 as wholly Divine. 
 
 We have still to deal with Philo's relation 
 to the Law, as such, a subject which can only 
 be sketched in outline. The main task he 
 prescribed for himself was to expound the 
 Pentateuch in its most universal bearings. 
 For he regards Moses as the incomparable 
 legislator for humanity. "His laws alone, 
 stable, unshaken, undisturbed, bearing the 
 impress of the seal of Nature herself, remain 
 firm from the day when they were written 
 until now, and, we trust, will abide for all 
 time coming, endowed with immortality, as 
 long as sun and moon and the entire heavens 
 and universe endure " (De Vita M. ii. 14). 
 For this reason their scope reaches far 
 beyond national limits. And Philo's aim is 
 to show that they enshrine all that is of value 
 in pagan philosophy. His method, of course, 
 supplies the instrument for that purpose. 
 But over and above the results reached by 
 the use of allegory, Philo deliberately em- 
 
PHILO'S RELATION TO 
 
 phasises the complete harmony of the Mosaic 
 Law with the Law of Nature. He was deeply 
 imbued with that Stoic doctrine, and at the 
 very opening of his great allegorical com- 
 mentary on the Pentateuch he strikes this 
 note : " This beginning (i.e. this book of 
 Genesis) is ... worthy of the highest 
 admiration, as it contains a description of 
 the creation of the world, to show that the 
 world is in harmony with the law, as the law 
 is with the world, and that the man who 
 obeys the law is for that reason a citizen 
 of the world, since he guides his activities 
 according to the will of Nature (TT/JO? TO 
 povXrjpa T?}? ^vo-eo)?), by which the entire 
 universe is directed" (De Opif. Mund. 3). 
 Here is the famous Stoic maxim, "to live in 
 harmony with Nature," set in the forefront 
 of his enterprise. We are therefore not sur- 
 prised to find in his more detailed account 
 of the Mosaic legislation that Moses " began 
 with the creation of the universe, in order to 
 set forth his most necessary doctrines, first, 
 that the Father and Creator of the world is the 
 same as the real legislator ; and second, that 
 
 52 
 
THE OLD TESTAMENT 
 
 he who is willing to live by these laws will 
 gladly strive after harmony with Nature, and 
 will live in accordance with the ordinances of 
 the universe, bringing his words into agree- 
 ment with his deeds, and his deeds with his 
 words" (De Vita Mos. ii. 48). 1 But a 
 position like this has far-reaching implica- 
 tions. Hence Drummond is probably justi- 
 fied in saying that for Philo "the Pentateuch 
 was simply the Divine Logos resolved into 
 Logoi, statements of philosophical truth, and 
 precepts of the moral code" (Philo Judaeus, 
 ii. p. 308). 
 
 When such a point is reached, we are 
 prepared for the conception of Conscience, 
 the legislative Reason within us, which is 
 one of Philo's most remarkable contributions 
 to the content of ancient ethics. Also, we 
 
 1 Bre'hier points out an interesting affinity in this con- 
 nection between Philo and Cicero (De Republica and 
 De Legibus) : " They show a similar anxiety to champion 
 their respective laws by placing them under the aegis of 
 Natural Law" (Les Idtcs Philosophiques et Religieuses de 
 Philon^ p. 12). He does not mention that these works of 
 Cicero have as their main source the Stoic teacher Panaetius 
 (see Schmekel, Die Mittlere Stoa, pp. 47-63, 67-85). Philo 
 constantly reveals the influence of Posidonius, the pupil 
 of Panaetius. 
 
 53 
 
PHILO'S RELATION TO 
 
 are in no way surprised to find that Philo 
 transfers the emphasis from the ritual of the 
 Law to the condition of the soul before God. 
 " Let me tell you, my friend," he declares, 
 ''that God feels no joy when we bring him 
 hecatombs, for all things are his posses- 
 sion. . . . But he delights in pious disposi- 
 tions and in men who practise holiness, and 
 from them he gladly receives sacrificial cakes 
 and grains of barley and the most frugal 
 offerings as of highest worth. . . . And even 
 though they bring nothing else, in bringing 
 themselves, the most perfect completion of 
 noble character, they present the best sacri- 
 fice, honouring God their Benefactor and 
 Saviour with hymns and thanksgivings " (De 
 Spec. Leg. i. 271 f.). But, as Brdhier points 
 out, "this inward morality is not purely and 
 simply morality, it is morality accompanied by 
 the consciousness of its superhuman, Divine 
 origin " (op. cit. p. 228). Plainly, such a pro- 
 cess throws the door wide open for that 
 universal validity of the Law so dear to the 
 mind of Philo. He appears to be conscious of 
 occupying a unique position. " We instruct 
 
 54 
 
THE OLD TESTAMENT 
 
 in the Divine mysteries those initiates who 
 are worthy of the most sacred ritual : these 
 are the people who, without arrogance, 
 practise true and genuinely unadorned piety, 
 but we shall never be hierophants for those 
 in the grasp of an incurable disease, the 
 stupidity of set phrases, the paltry trifling 
 with names, the clap-trap of appointed cus- 
 toms" (De Cherub. 42). The statement 
 quoted earlier from De Migr. Abr. 89 as 
 emphasising adherence to the strict letter of 
 the law, though apparently a direct contra- 
 diction of this, is really modified by what 
 immediately follows it. " As it is," he says, 
 "like people living alone in isolation or 
 bodiless souls, having no communication 
 with city or village or family or any human 
 company, they look down upon the opinion 
 of the multitude, and search for bare truth 
 in itself: and yet the sacred word teaches 
 them to pay respect to estimable public 
 opinion and to abolish none of those usages 
 established by inspired men who surpassed 
 any of our time. . . . It is the part of the 
 mature soul to share both in being and in 
 
 55 
 
PHILO'S RELATION TO 
 
 seeming to be : it must aim not only at gaining 
 esteem in the men's quarters, but also at being 
 praised at the hearth where the women sit " 
 (ibid. 90, 96). Thus, one element, at least, 
 in Philo's concern for observance of the letter 
 of the law springs from the fear of wounding 
 the consciences of others, although in certain 
 moods he can speak of such " weak " brethren 
 in a tone of disparagement. 
 
 It is worth observing how, along a very 
 divergent line of development, Philo arrives 
 at a position regarding the Law which ap- 
 proximates to that of Paul. His religious 
 instinct, as well as the spiritual atmosphere in 
 which he moves, leads him away from the 
 region of ceremonial into that of obedience to 
 the Divine will, whose appeal he hears with- 
 in. The Christian Apostle, with surer spir- 
 itual vision, discovers through his crucial 
 experience of Christ a Divine Love which 
 seeks him out and to which his soul can make 
 answer with adoring gratitude. This heart- 
 felt devotion takes the place of legal obedi- 
 ence. But each, in his own manner, has 
 come to realise the accomplishment of Jere- 
 
 56 
 
THE OLD TESTAMENT 
 
 miah's epoch-making utterance : " I will put 
 my law in their inward parts, and write it in 
 their hearts " (xxxi. 33). 
 
 This quotation suggests a reference to 
 Philo's attitude towards the Prophets. We 
 have already seen that for him Moses stands 
 supreme above all the rest. And that is 
 borne out by the solitary level on which he 
 places the Pentateuch. Indeed, if we were 
 content to apply the rough and ready test of 
 quotation, this subject might be dismissed 
 without more ado. For in Dr. Ryle's classi- 
 fication of the material, six pages of extracts 
 represent the Old Testament prophets as 
 against two hundred and eighty-eight for the 
 Pentateuch. Windisch goes the length of say- 
 ing that Philo was scarcely influenced by them 
 at all (Die Frommigkeit P kilos, p. 93). We 
 are rather inclined to apply to them what 
 Windisch himself says, in the same connection, 
 of the Psalms, that they affected Philo more 
 powerfully than he acknowledges (op. cit. p. 
 94). It is true and surprising that he has not 
 attempted to allegorise the prophetic writings, 
 when we remember how current this practice 
 
 57 
 
PHILO'S RELATION TO 
 
 was among the Fathers of the early Church. 1 
 Possibly one reason may have been that his 
 interest did not lie in history, not even in the 
 historical experiences of his own nation. And 
 it would have been difficult to offer any kind 
 of exposition of these glowing utterances, 
 apart from an earnest participation in the 
 Hope which pervaded them, or at least in 
 the expectation of those great eschatological 
 events which loomed before their minds. We 
 know that Paul, as a Christian, rediscovered 
 the prophets, as Jesus had done, and carried 
 their lofty spiritual intuitions into the life and 
 thought of the new community. Philo, in 
 his own special environment, and on the path 
 of his own religious development, at least 
 reflects some of the most vital of the prophetic 
 achievements. The primacy which he assigns 
 to the inward worship of the spirit over all 
 sacrificial rites places us at the heart of the 
 religion of the prophets. It is quite possible, 
 as Br&iier suggests (pp. cit. p. 227), that his 
 distance from Jerusalem and its Temple, and 
 
 1 See, e.g.) Hatch, Influence of Greek Ideas on Christianity ', 
 PP. 72, 73- 
 
 58 
 
THE OLD TESTAMENT 
 
 his association of worship with the Syna- 
 gogue, in part account for this affinity. To 
 us it appears that the clue lies deeper. We 
 are not even inclined to lay strong emphasis 
 on his familiarity with an idealistic type of 
 philosophy which discountenanced anthro- 
 pomorphism. Must not his receptiveness 
 towards the spiritual have been one of the 
 main factors in creating his philosophic 
 interest ? Is it not rather his view of God, 
 and of the grace of God, and of God's 
 interest in man, which reminds us over and 
 over again of Hosea and Isaiah ? And does 
 not this go back to a personal religious ex- 
 perience, similar in kind to that in which the 
 prophets became profoundly aware of God ? 
 
 59 
 
CHAPTER III 
 
 FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 P*HE career of Philo belongs to a period 
 -L notable'for its philosophical syncretism, 
 and his own position in philosophy is one 
 of the most characteristic products of his 
 age. It is, as we shall have occasion to 
 note, a blending of theories belonging to 
 various schools, and probably for that reason 
 he found it easier to insert within its frame- 
 work much of his inherited Judaism. The 
 outcome of such a process could never take 
 shape as a coherent system, and Philo's 
 scheme of thought reveals ragged edges 
 on every side. 
 
 The question has been keenly discussed 
 whether Philo himself is directly responsible 
 for this remarkable synthesis of Platonic and 
 Stoic doctrine, powerfully coloured by Pytha- 
 
 gorean tradition, or whether, as Schmekel 
 
 60 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 (Die Mittlere Stoa, pp. 409 ff., 428 ff.) and 
 others believe, he was predominantly influ- 
 enced by Posidonius, and especially by the 
 famous commentary of the latter on Plato's 
 Timaeus, an exposition which left its mark 
 on numerous writers of that epoch. The 
 question is really secondary. For it is 
 universally admitted that Posidonius, to a 
 unique extent, summed up in himself the 
 eclectic tendencies of the time. There can 
 be little doubt that Philo was acquainted with 
 his works, but he must also have come into 
 contact with similar currents of thought 
 throughout his environment, and in all likeli- 
 hood he himself contributed more or less to 
 the syncretistic process. 1 
 
 At every turn his allegorical exposition of 
 the Law contains discussions of problems 
 which did not present themselves even to 
 serious Jewish thinkers. Yet in his attempts 
 to solve these problems, moulded as they 
 are by Platonic-Stoic speculations, we can 
 
 1 Cf. the important evidence for Philo's affinities with the 
 Hermetic documents in J. Kroll's Die Lehren d. Hermes 
 TrismegistoS) Minister i. W., 1914. 
 
 61 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 frequently discern, from the points where he 
 places the emphasis or the directions in which 
 he leads the argument, the effect of his train- 
 ing in the Old Testament and the pressure of 
 certain inviolable religious postulates. 
 
 (a) God and the World 
 
 No more searching criterion can be applied 
 to the structure of Philo's philosophy, with a 
 view to discovering the relation of his adopted 
 metaphysics to his ancestral and still living 
 faith, than an examination of his attitude 
 towards the perennial crux for ancient thought, 
 the connection between Spirit and Matter, 
 between God and the World. This, it need 
 scarcely be said, was not a problem for Old 
 Testament religion. Even in the Wisdom- 
 sections of Proverbs there is no more than a 
 suggestion of the metaphysical. The precise 
 relations of the personified Wisdom to God 
 and the World are in no sense investigated. 
 We find little cogency in Siegfried's argu- 
 ments (Philo von Alexandria, p. 230 f.) for 
 his assertion that Philo's cosmogony was based 
 
 on current Jewish expositions of the work of 
 
 62 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 creation. Its main source, whether used 
 directly or through such a medium as Posi- 
 donius* commentary, seems to be Plato's 
 Timaeus? modified by an adaptation of the 
 Stoic conception of God and considerably 
 affected by Jewish presuppositions. 
 
 Let us briefly consider the facts. " Moses," 
 says Philo (De Opif. Mundi, 8 f.), " who had 
 reached the summit of philosophy and had 
 received instruction by Divine revelation 
 concerning the most important aspects of 
 Nature, recognised that among existing things 
 there must be, on the one hand, an active 
 Cause (Spao-riipiov amoz/), on the other a 
 passive (iraO^Tov), and that the active is the 
 mind (vofc) of the universe, perfectly pure and 
 unmixed, better than knowledge, better than 
 the good in itself and the beautiful in itself, 
 while the passive has no life (a^v^ov) and is 
 motionless of itself, but when moved and 
 shaped and quickened by mind becomes 
 transformed into the most perfect product, this 
 
 1 Mr. Barker points out (Greek Political Theory, p. 352, 
 note 2) that the Mediaeval period "drew its cosmology 
 largely" from the Timaeus^ "which . . . was practically 
 the only work of Plato known directly to the Middle Ages." 
 
 63 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 universe of ours." Here we are on familiar 
 Stoic ground, 1 and perhaps this group of ideas 
 has influenced Philo more powerfully than 
 scholars have usually imagined. Some pas- 
 sages which follow point in another direction. 
 " The great Moses," he proceeds, " regarding 
 that which had no becoming as alien to the 
 visible, ascribed to the invisible which can 
 only be conceived (vorjrov), as its most appro- 
 priate attribute, eternity, but to that which was 
 perceivable by the senses, as its befitting name 
 genesis " (becoming). This is, of course, the 
 Platonic distinction between the real and the 
 phenomenal. But how are these contrasted 
 magnitudes, the Active and the Passive, the 
 Eternal and that which comes into being, 
 related ? Philo grapples with the question as 
 follows : " Since God in virtue of his Deity 
 realised beforehand that a beautiful copy 
 (fiifjLtjfjLa) could not come into being apart from a 
 beautiful pattern (TrapaSe^aro?), and that none 
 of the things perceived by sense could be 
 flawless which was not made after the image 
 O'T)) of an Archetype and a spiritual 
 
 1 See esp. Diog. Laert. vii. 134 ; Seneca, Ep. Ixv. 2. 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 Idea, when he designed to create this 
 visible world, he first formed the ideal world, 
 so that he might produce the bodily by the use 
 of an incorporeal and most Godlike pattern, the 
 later modelled on the earlier, and intended to 
 contain as many classes of things (yevrj) ap- 
 prehensible by the senses as there were ideas 
 in the archetypal world" (op. cit. 16). This 
 is perhaps his clearest description of the 
 Divine plan in creation, and it reflects Plato's 
 argument in Timaeus, 28 A, B, 29 A. But 
 there is no mention in it of Matter. We 
 mainly gather from it the high value Philo 
 assigned to the notion of an archetypal world 
 in the process of creation. 
 
 Similarly, his conception of the motive of 
 creation closely follows Timaeus^ 29 E, 30 A, 
 B. " If any one should desire to investigate 
 the reason why this universe was created, I 
 should think he would not be far from the 
 mark in saying, as indeed one of the ancients 
 (i.e. Plato) has said, that the Father and 
 Maker of all things is gracious. On this 
 account he did not grudge his perfect nature 
 
 to matter (oiWa), which possesses nothing 
 E 65 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 beautiful of itself but has the capacity of be- 
 coming all things" (pp. cit. 21). In taking up 
 what is for the Plato of the Timaeus a semi- 
 mythical standpoint, Philo was really true to 
 his inherited and most real faith in a good and 
 gracious God, who was the Source of all 
 being and the Giver of nothing but benefits 
 to His creatures, and whose peculiar charac- 
 teristic is, he affirms, to create (Leg. All. \. 5). 
 But how did this plan, the outcome of a ben- 
 eficent purpose, actually work ? Did God 
 create out of nothing? What place and 
 meaning does Philo assign to the Matter 
 (ov<ria) of which he speaks ? "It was un- 
 ordered of itself, devoid of qualities, without 
 life, 1 abounding in difference, disagreement, 
 discord. But it received a change and trans- 
 formation into what was opposite and best, 
 order, quality, vitality, likeness, identity, con- 
 cord, harmony, all the attributes of the higher 
 Idea " (pp. cit. 22). Again, in commenting 
 on Gen. i. 31, "God saw all that he had 
 created, and behold it was very good," he ob- 
 serves: " God did not praise the matter (v\r)v) 
 
 1 Omitting dvcycotof, conjectured by Markland. 
 66 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 which he had used for creation, lifeless and 
 discordant and dissoluble and, moreover, per- 
 ishable of itself and irregular and unequal, but 
 he praised the products of his own skill, 
 finished according to a single equal and 
 regular power" (Quis Rer. Div. H. 160). 
 And once more : " That opinion which does 
 away with Ideas confuses everything and 
 refers it to the ultimate matter (ovaLa) of the 
 elements which is without form and quality. 
 But what could be more absurd ? for it was 
 out of that that God produced all things, not 
 touching it himself for it was not fitting that 
 the happy and blessed One should touch un- 
 defined and confused matter (v\^) but he 
 used those incorporeal forms, whose proper 
 name is the Ideas, in order that each class of 
 things should receive its suitable shape " (De 
 Spec. Leg. i. 328 f.). 
 
 In these passages he seems to use ova La 
 or v\rj without distinction for Matter, and to 
 regard it as in some sense existing indepen- 
 dently of God. It is there in its passivity, 
 awaiting the action of the Divine Artificer. It 
 is lifeless and without qualities, confused and 
 
 67 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 chaotic. It has to receive the impress of the 
 ideal Forms, which Philo seems to identify 
 with the Xoyot of the Stoics, and which proceed 
 from the Divine mind and are its expressed 
 thoughts, operating upon this undefined 
 material. Thus it becomes Cosmos, the 
 ordered universe. 
 
 Did Philo, then, regard Matter as eternally 
 there ? Such a position would, of course, be 
 in absolute conflict with Jewish conceptions. 
 And it is possible to quote a statement which 
 appears to contradict what has been said 
 above, De Somn. i. 76 : " As the sun, when 
 it has risen, reveals the hidden parts of bodies, 
 so also God, who begat all things, not only 
 brought them to light, but also created what 
 before was not in existence, since he was not 
 only artificer (fy/juovpyos) but also creator 
 (/trio-n^)." It is true that Matter is not dis- 
 tinctly mentioned, but surely the sharp 
 antithesis between bqiuavpyos, the word he 
 regularly uses for the shaping of chaos into 
 cosmos, and /c-uVn;?, Creator in the strict 
 sense, suggests that here he occupies the 
 
 position which appealed to a devout Jew, 
 
 68 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 that nothing came into being without God. 
 Further, his description of Matter in Quis 
 Rer. Div. H. 160, already quoted, as 
 " perishable of itself" seems to preclude a 
 distinct hypothesis of pre-existence. 1 The 
 discrepancy 2 between this and the statements 
 cited above is not surprising in so eclectic a 
 thin ker. We_jriaj^eyen_j^ 
 whether Philo ever faced the problem of the 
 eternity of matter. There is no direct hint 
 of it in his writings. What concerned him 
 was God's creative efficacy, and probably he 
 was content to assume a formles^, lifeless 
 substratum of things, somehow available to 
 receive the Divine impress. Possibly, in his 
 
 1 Drummond's attempt (Philo Judaeus, i. p. 301 f.) to 
 prove that here " it is not matter , but ' fabricated matter,' 
 which is said to be thus corruptible," seems to us to be based 
 on a misinterpretation of Philo's language, for the adjectives 
 he attaches to V\T)V, which are of precisely the same type as 
 he applies to v\rj or ova-la in the other quotations given 
 plainly qualify vXyv itself, and not the compound expression 
 dr)fjuovpyr)0iarav vXrjv. After it has been used for creation 
 (dTjfuovpyrjOf'io-a), i.e. according to Philo, " changed into what 
 was best " under the operation of the Divine Ideas, Matter 
 can no longer be called "lifeless, discordant, dissoluble 
 perishable of itself," as here. 
 
 2 Heinze, in his learned treatise, Die Lehre vom Logos 
 p. 210, note, takes the same view. 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 descriptions of v\rj or ovata he is influenced 
 by such statements as that of Timaeus, 5 1 A : 
 " The mother and recipient (VTTO^O^J) of 
 created things which are visible and by any 
 sense perceptible we must call neither earth 
 nor air nor fire nor water . . . but we shall 
 not err in affirming it to be a kind of invisible 
 and formless being (eZSo? ), all-receiving, in 
 some manner most bewildering and hard to 
 understand, partaking of the intelligible." This 
 vTroBo^ Plato identifies in Tim. 52 A, B with 
 empty Space (see Zeller, Plato, p. 304 ff.). 
 It is not a " substance" posited beside the 
 Ideas and the phenomenal world. It is for 
 him non-being. This modification of an 
 absolute Dualism is, we think, confirmed by 
 Philo's view of the character of Matter. We 
 have referred more than once to the epithets 
 he applies to it. These are practically all of 
 a negative kind, " unordered, devoid of 
 qualities, without life, abounding in differ- 
 ence," and the like. In other words, he 
 regards it as the formless substratum of cre- 
 ated things, in itself wholly " passive." Yet 
 
 it has " the capacity of becoming all things.' 1 
 
 70 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 Is it legitimate to say, as Siegfried (pp. 
 cit. p. 232) and other scholars do, that for 
 Philo Matter is evil ? Siegfried's argument 
 is quite unconvincing. It is derived from 
 the comment on Gen. i. 31, quoted above, 
 that " God did not praise the matter used by 
 him in creation . . . but praised the products 
 of his skill." The inference goes far beyond 
 the data. Matter as " devoid of qualities" 
 lies outside the realm of approval or dis- 
 approval. It is necessarily something in- 
 different, a mere potentiality, which attains 
 positive value only when it is transformed 
 through the influence of "the higher Idea" 
 into " quality, vitality, identity," i.e. into 
 "a product of the Divine skill." We can 
 find no trace in Philo of any active function 
 being ascribed to Matter, not even resistance 
 to the transforming energy of the Artificer as 
 mediated by His "powers." For the notion 
 of a restriction of God's creative operations 
 he does not associate with Matter, as 
 Drummond relevantly notes (pp. cit. i. p. 31 1), 
 but with that which has come into being 
 (761/60-45) in the strict sense. " Not according 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 to the magnitude of his gracious thoughts 
 for that is without limit or end does he 
 show forth his benefits, but according to the 
 capacities of those who are benefited. For 
 not according to God's power of conferring 
 good is that of the created thing (TO ^evo^evov) 
 to receive it. For God's capacities cannot be 
 measured ; but the created thing, being too 
 weak to receive the magnitude of them, would 
 have failed, had not God calculated and 
 fittingly measured out to each that which was 
 its portion" (Zte Op. M. 23). The concep- 
 tion appears in various passages, perhaps most 
 strikingly in Zte Vita Mos. ii. (iii.) 147, 
 where, in speaking of the calf offered as a 
 sin-offering, he finds in this a symbol that 
 " sin is innate in every one born (iravrl yevrjrw), 
 even if he be virtuous, by reason of his coming 
 to birth " (et<? yevea-w). Nothing like this is 
 ever said about Matter. Plato, we know, 
 regards the phenomenal as imperfect because 
 there belongs to it not only the existence im- 
 parted by the Idea, but that also which makes 
 it a phenomenon and to that extent limits the 
 
 Idea. Philo follows his master in recognising 
 
 72 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 that the phenomenon is separated by a vast 
 chasm from the Creator. One important 
 passage recalls Plato's belief that " the genera- 
 tion (yevevw) of this universe was a mixed 
 creation by a combination of necessity 
 (avayKtj) and reason "( Ti 'm. 48 A). 1 " God 
 alone," Philo says, " is most true and genuine 
 peace, but all matter (ov<ria) t as having come 
 into being (yevrjrrj) and perishable (<f)0apTi]), is 
 constant warfare. For God is free activity, 
 while matter is necessity. Whosoever, there- 
 fore, is able to leave behind warfare and 
 necessity and becoming and decay, and to 
 take refuge with that which has no becoming 
 or decay, free activity, peace, might rightly 
 be called the dwelling-place and city of God " 
 (Z?* Somn. ii. 353). Here he recognises, 
 without discussion, the fact of an inner 
 necessity in created things, which sets them 
 in contrast with the freedom of God. But 
 this necessity is not the mark of an absolute 
 dualism. It is inseparable, as in Plato, from 
 
 1 Archer Hind here interprets avaymr] as " the laws which 
 govern the existence of vovs in the form of plurality." This 
 exposition opens up a peculiarly fascinating vista of 
 speculation. 
 
 73 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 the entrance of Eternal Being, however 
 mediated, into the realm of the visible. Thus 
 the stamp of imperfection, from the nature of 
 the case, lies upon the phenomenon. But that 
 is far from the position that Matter is evil, 
 a position which to a thinker who conceived 
 God as Philo did would have seemed profane. 
 It may be said, then, that we find no 
 perfectly clear conception of Matter in Philo. 
 Sometimes he seems to approach Plato's 
 notion of Non- Being ; at others we are re- 
 minded of the Stoic conception of Active 
 and Passive as expressing modes of a single 
 substance, which can be separated in thought, 
 though not in fact, denoting at the one 
 extreme the highest Divine mind, at the 
 other the most indeterminate form of Matter : 
 while some passages cannot be fairly inter- 
 preted without ascribing Matter to the creative 
 energy of God. But there is nothing to show 
 that Philo regarded Matter per se as evil. 
 This fact is important for its bearing on the 
 significance of the Pauline antithesis between 
 Flesh and Spirit, which meets us in the next 
 phase of our discussion. 
 
 74 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 (b) The Constitution of Human Nature 
 
 Man is for Philo the crowning example of 
 the entrance of Spirit or Mind into a material 
 environment. And he describes both the 
 process and its consequences in an endless 
 variety of ways. Fundamentally, man con- 
 sists of soul (^1^77) and body (ar&fia). "There 
 are two elements," he says (Leg. Alleg. 
 iii. 161), "of which we are composed, 
 namely, soul and body : the body has been 
 fashioned of earth, but the soul belongs to 
 the ether, a fragment of the Divine : for 
 1 God breathed into his face the breath 
 (Trvevpa) of life, so that man became a living 
 soul' 15 (Gen. ii. 7). Or, stated more philo- 
 sophically : " Man is the noblest of animals, 
 by reason of the higher element among his 
 component parts, the soul, closely akin to 
 heaven, which is most pure in its essence, 
 and to the Father of the universe, as having 
 received mind (vow), of all things on earth 
 the most faithful image and copy of the 
 eternal and blessed Idea" (De Decal. 134). 
 Equally important for Philo is this religious 
 
 75 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 definition : "It is written in the book of 
 God that man alone is full of good hope. . . . 
 Hence the definition of us men as a compound 
 is a rational, mortal animal. But that of 
 man according to Moses is a condition of 
 soul which sets its hope on the truly existent 
 God" (Quod det. pot. 139). 
 
 Repeatedly Philo indulges in a speculation 
 which must have fascinated him, dealing 
 with a twofold creation of man, based upon 
 (i) Gen. i. 27 : "God made (eVow/o-ey) man, 
 after the image (ec<W) of God he made 
 him," and (2) Gen. ii. 7: " God formed 
 (eirXaa-ev) man of dust from the earth, and 
 breathed," etc. We refer to it here as a re- 
 markable instance of his attempt to combine 
 the influence of Greek metaphysics with that 
 of Hebrew tradition. Having quoted Gen. 
 ii. 7, he continues (De Op. Mund. 134 f.) : 
 " Most clearly does he show by this that 
 there is an immense difference between the 
 man now formed (TrXaa-Qevros) and him who 
 had earlier come into being (76701/0x05) accord- 
 ing to the image of God. For the man now 
 
 formed was perceptible by sense (a 
 
 76 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 already participating in quality, composed of 
 body and soul, man or woman, mortal by 
 nature ; while he who was made after the 
 Divine image was a sort of idea (ISea n<s) or 
 class or soul, apprehensible only by thought, 
 incorporeal, neither male nor female, immortal 
 by nature. Moreover, he says that the con- 
 stitution of the individual man, perceptible 
 by sense, was composed of earthly substance 
 and the Divine breath (irvev^aTo^). For what 
 he breathed into him was nothing else than a 
 Divine breath (or, spirit) which took its 
 departure hither from that blessed and 
 happy nature for the good of our race. So 
 that if it is mortal so far as its visible part is 
 concerned, as regards its invisible part at 
 least it possesses immortality." l 
 
 Bousset and others have tried to link on 
 
 1 Bre'hier (op. tit. p. 121 f.) seems to us completely mis- 
 taken in his interpretation of De Op. M. 69, in which he tries 
 to show that that passage refers to the Divine Man, but 
 contradicts the view in De Op. M. 134 f., and Leg. Alleg. 
 i. 31 ff. For in the first passage, although Philo refers to 
 Gen. i. 26, he has not before his mind the contrast between 
 the ideal and the earth-born man at all. He is thinking only 
 of the latter, as the statement, "for nothing earth-born is 
 more like to God than man," clearly indicates. And so he 
 explains the fl<a>v Oeov as referring to man's vovs, 
 
 77 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 Philo's ideal man to the early myth of an 
 Ur-Anthropos, of which they find traces in 
 various Gnostic documents. The hypothesis 
 is unnecessary, for the Ideal Man is postulated 
 by Philo's Platonic theory already described, 
 of God's method in the creation of the 
 visible world, according to which things 
 perceived by sense require a perfect pattern 
 of which they are copies. The slightest 
 examination of the data suffices to show the 
 irrelevance of the attempt made by some 
 scholars to explain from this notion of a 
 twofold creation Paul's statement as to the 
 "first man Adam " and the "last Adam," the 
 "earthly" (xot/eo?) and the "heavenly" 
 (Zirovpdvw). The very fact that Paul calls 
 the "earthly" the "first man," and the 
 "heavenly" the "second man," while the 
 whole point of Philo's argument turns on the 
 priority of the ideal man, is decisive. It is 
 true that the Apostle describes Christ as " the 
 image of the invisible God, the first-begotten 
 of all creation " (Col. i. 15) ; but the remark- 
 able words which follow : "for in him were 
 created all things in heaven and on earth, the 
 
 78 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 visible and the invisible, . . . and he is 
 before all things and in him all things 
 cohere " (i. 16 f.), have an immensely wider 
 scope than Philo's conception of the ideal 
 man. If we wish, therefore, to compare St. 
 Paul's cosmological doctrines with those of 
 Philo, this famous passage points in the 
 direction of the Logos, the central principle 
 which unifies the cosmos : e.g. De Somn. 
 ii. 45 : " God . . . sealed the universe with 
 an image and idea, his own Logos." 
 
 The speculation to which we have just 
 referred is, in a sense, typical of Philo's 
 views on the origin and constitution of 
 human nature. These often consist of an 
 attempted blend of Platonic, Stoic, and 
 Aristotelian conceptions. Often they re- 
 present Philo's theological bias, to a large 
 extent moulded by Old Testament ideas. 
 In the latter case, he does not hesitate to 
 assume an unmediated influence of God on 
 human nature, a position at variance with 
 his philosophical theories, which demand the 
 employment of mediating forces to bring 
 together the Infinite and the finite. The 
 
 79 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 influence of the Timaeus accounts for one 
 of his most discordant hypotheses, that of 
 the pre-existence of souls in the air. In 
 the semi-mythical tone characteristic of that 
 dialogue, Plato describes (Tim. 41 D-43 A, 
 69 A-7O A) how the Creator entrusted to 
 the " young gods " the confining of souls 
 who had previously formed part of the 
 universal Soul in mortal bodies. Philo 
 (esp. De Gig. 6-15) depicts in his fanciful 
 narrative the fortunes of these souls, who, 
 somehow, stooped from their pure dwelling 
 in the air to incarnation in mortal bodies, 
 leaving behind them an incorruptible group 
 of fellow-souls, whom God used as His 
 ministers for the supervision of mortals, 
 and whom Moses called " angels." Of those 
 incarnate, some were able to resist the current 
 of sensuous life and to return to their original 
 abode ; the others, surrendering themselves 
 to restless activities, were engulfed in the 
 illusory world of wealth, fame and similar 
 unreal things. Some scholars, e.g. Zeller 
 (Phil. d. Griechen\ 3te Theil, 2te Halfte, 
 
 p. 450 f.), refer Philo's entire conception 
 
 80 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 of human sin to this hypothesis. In 
 our judgment it seems to be largely a 
 side-issue. And it is far more rewarding 
 to follow the main trend of his ideas, re- 
 cognising throughout that these cannot be 
 adjusted in a coherent system. 
 
 No more comprehensive passage could be 
 selected for our purpose than Quod det. pot. 
 insid. sol. 82-90. "It follows," he says, 
 "from our recent analysis, that each of us 
 is numerically two, an animal and a man : to 
 each of these has been assigned its proper 
 spiritual potency, to the one that vital prin- 
 ciple (fj ZCOTIKT}) by which we live, to the other 
 the rational (n \oyiKij) in virtue of which we 
 are rational. In the vital principle mate- 
 rial things also share, but in the rational 
 God does not share : he is its source, the 
 fountain of the primal reason (\6yos). To 
 that potency, then, which we share with 
 irrational things, blood was assigned as its 
 substance (ozWa), but that derived from the 
 rational principle had for its essence spirit 
 (or, breath, 7n/e{5/*a), not air set in motion, but 
 
 a sort of stamp and impress of the Divine 
 F 81 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 power, which Moses calls by its proper name, 
 image (eitcwv), showing that God is the arche- 
 type of the rational nature, and man its copy 
 and facsimile, not the animal of twofold nature, 
 but the noblest aspect (eZSo?) 1 of the soul, which 
 is called mind (vofa) and reason (Xcfyos). On 
 this account he makes blood the soul of the 
 flesh, recognising that the fleshly nature 
 (17 <rapKos <u<n9) has no part in mind, but 
 partakes of life just like our whole body. 
 But the soul of man he names spirit (Trvevfta), 
 designating as man not the compound, as I 
 said, but that Godlike product of creation 
 by which we reason, whose roots he stretched 
 to heaven. . . . For alone of earthly creatures, 
 God made man a heavenly plant, bending the 
 head of the others towards the ground . . . 
 but making man look upwards. . . . Let us 
 therefore, who are disciples of Moses, be in 
 no doubt as to how man received his con- 
 ception (ewoiav) of the unseen God. . . . 
 Here are his (i.e. Moses') words : * The 
 
 1 It is impossible to find a thoroughly satisfactory render- 
 ing of eldos here. It means something more fundamental 
 than "aspect" in its ordinary sense. Perhaps "quality" 
 might serve. 
 
 82 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 Maker prepared for the body no soul suffi- 
 cient of itself to see its maker, but, considering 
 the great benefit of the creation, if it might 
 receive a conception of its Creator ... he 
 breathed into it from above of his own 
 divinity.' . . . How, then, is it likely that 
 so restricted a thing as the human mind . . . 
 should have room for the vastness of heaven 
 and the world if it were not an undivided 
 portion of that divine and blessed Spirit 
 C^xW? F r no P art f tne Divine is 
 separated by detachment, it is only an 
 extension of it." 
 
 Perhaps this statement may reflect the 
 theological more than the philosophical 
 aspect of Philo's thought, but that accords 
 with his bent, and reminds us that his Old 
 Testament training remained fundamental 
 for his entire speculation. The passage 
 reveals his essential view of human nature, 
 the supreme distinction between the rational 
 and the irrational in man. Before we ex- 
 amine these two elements more closely, let 
 us make clear a point which has only been 
 hinted at in the quotation. "For the con- 
 
 83 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 stituting of the soul," he observes, " God 
 seems to have used as pattern no created 
 thing, but only ... his own Logos. Of 
 this, therefore, . . . man was made the fac- 
 simile and copy, for his face was breathed 
 into, that part which is the seat of the senses 
 with which the Creator vitalised (tyvx&o-ev) 
 the body : but having implanted the reason 
 as ruler, he handed over the senses to this 
 governing element, so as to have them at 
 its service for the apprehension of colours, 
 sounds, tastes, odours and the like, which, 
 by itself alone, apart from sense-perception, 
 it would have been unable to grasp" (Zte 
 Op. M. 139). To realise the fluidity of 
 Philo's conceptions, we may compare with 
 this Leg. Alleg. i. 37 : God is the in- 
 breathing force, that which receives his 
 breath is the reason (or, mind, vovsi), that 
 which is inbreathed is the spirit (irvev^a). 
 . . . God breathes into this (i.e. vov<i) alone, 
 but the other parts he does not think worthy 
 of such action, I mean, the senses and the 
 faculties of speech and reproduction, for they 
 are secondary in their capacity. By what, 
 
 84 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 then, did these receive (vital) breath? 
 Plainly by reason (vovs), for that in which 
 God enabled reason to share, it imparted to 
 the irrational element of the soul, so that 
 reason was vitalised by God, and the 
 material element by reason." Here he pre- 
 supposes a human reason, which receives 
 Divine influence, and transmits it for the 
 establishing of sense-life ; whereas, in the 
 former passage, sense-life had already been 
 constituted by God, and awaited the in- 
 breaking of a higher energy, reason itself. 
 A similar oscillation of ideas is found re- 
 garding the function of the Logos in creation. 
 Commenting, as so frequently, on Gen. i. 
 26, he says : " The Father of the universe 
 converses with his own powers, to whom he 
 assigned the fashioning of the mortal part of 
 the soul, who copied his skill when he shaped 
 the rational element in us, judging it right 
 that the dominating principle in the soul 
 should be created by the Ruler, but the 
 subordinate by his subordinates " (De Fnga, 
 69 f.). The latter creation he calls in the 
 next sentence rrjv KdK&v yeveo-iv, the former, 
 
 85 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 T&V dyaOwv. Here is a curious parallel 
 to the " young gods" of the Timaeus ; but 
 the idea, of course, tallies both with Stoic 
 and even Jewish conceptions of mediation 
 between the Infinite and the finite. 
 
 In the passages quoted above we have a 
 rough summary of Philo's conception of the 
 Constitution of Human Nature. The body 
 (<rw/*a), which has been moulded by the 
 Divine power, 1 is animated by the soul 
 (^Xn\ which, however, has to be viewed 
 under two contrasted aspects. To it belongs 
 the vital energy (f) om*^ &W/u?, where f. = 
 Paul's adjective, ^/ru^/co?), the principle of life 
 in matter, irrational and common to us with 
 
 1 Curiously enough, there are exceeding few references 
 n Philo to the formation of the <ro5/ia by God, and these 
 are incidental : e.g. Quis Rer. Div. ff. 73 : #f<i> TG> KOI ri 
 o-co/ia <ra>fiaro{)im KOI irrjyvvvri ; Leg. Alleg. iii. 73 : iva eidys 
 on Kal ra afyvxa OVK (ov(riq irfrroirjKCv, aXX' dyaGorrjTi, i? KOI 
 ra f^vxa. Probably this is due to his fundamental notion 
 of the transiency of the body, and the inferiority which thus 
 characterises it. In a striking passage he represents the 
 elements, earth and water, as saying : " We are the matter 
 of your body : Nature having mixed us, shaped us by her 
 divine art into the semblance of the human form " (De Spec. 
 Leg. i. 266). The moulding of the body is here ascribed 
 to Qvais, almost as if he wished to avoid connecting the 
 process with God. 
 
 86 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 other animals. The essence of this vital 
 principle is blood. Here he is strictly loyal 
 to Hebrew ideas; e.g. Lev. xvii. n 
 (LXX): "for the soul (^i^) of all flesh 
 (a-apKos) is its blood." On the other hand, 
 it possesses a rational capacity which links it 
 to God, that being the image or impress of 
 the Divine reason. Pictorially, this higher 
 element is described as breathed into man 
 by God. As such it is called " spirit" or 
 " breath" (-Tri/eO^a). 1 But it may also be 
 named vow or \6yos, for it is really an un- 
 divided part of the Divine Reason (\6yo$). 
 As such it is the medium by which we reach 
 a conception of the unseen God. No doubt 
 Philo found it easier to conceive this ultimate 
 relation between the finite and the Infinite, 
 because he had already posited the Divine 
 Logos as God's instrument in creation, God's 
 reason operating in the cosmos almost as a 
 personal mediator. Occasionally he seems 
 to presuppose a human vovs, whose origin 
 he does not explain, which is the receptacle 
 
 1 See esp. De Spec. Leg. iv. 123, where blood = ova-la 
 -, while Divine Spirit = over/a tyvxrjs vofpa?, 
 
 87 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 of higher Divine influence, and in which the 
 senses, elsewhere ascribed to the direct action 
 of the Creator upon the body, find their vitality. 
 In any case, the life of sense (alo-^o-*?), accord- 
 ing to the Divine intention, is subordinated 
 to the dominant power (TO faqtofu**), a 
 synonym for reason in its highest capacity, 
 and is sometimes attributed to the action of 
 the subordinate " powers" (SiW/iet?) of God. 
 
 Let us briefly examine the chief elements 
 into which Philo analyses human nature, 
 keeping in view their relation to parallel 
 phenomena in the New Testament. The 
 body (o-/-ia) is regularly described as fashioned 
 from earth (e.g. Leg. Alleg. iii. 161), and as 
 such is, of course, inferior to the reason which 
 informs it. It is peculiarly the basis of the 
 sense-life (e.g. Quod det. pot. 109) and of the 
 passions (e.g. Quis Rer. Div. D. 268 : " Alien 
 to the understanding are the passions, which 
 belong truly to the body, springing out of the 
 flesh in which they have their roots "). Since 
 the desires which are fostered by the senses 
 and the force of the passions, as a matter of 
 
 experience, war against the higher aspirations 
 
 88 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 of the rational element in the soul, Philo con- 
 stantly identifies himself with the Neo-Pytha- 
 gorean position that the body is the source 
 of evil. " Away, my friend/' he exclaims, 
 " from that earthly vesture of yours, escape 
 from that accursed prison, the body, and from 
 its pleasures and lusts, which are your jailors " 
 (De. Migr. Abr. 9). The passage gives a 
 clue to Philo's standpoint. It is not the 
 body which is inherently bad. But the life 
 of the senses, which finds its material, so to 
 speak, in the physical organisation, is irra- 
 tional, and nothing but its subordination to 
 the Divine element of reason can preserve the 
 soul from going astray. Accordingly, Philo 
 anticipates St. Paul in using o-dpi;, " flesh," 
 to denote the lower side of human nature as 
 realised and felt in an ordinary experience. 1 
 Only here we come upon an important differ- 
 ence. In De Gigant. 40 this noteworthy 
 
 1 Lietzmann, Rbmerbrief^ p. 37, seems to us completely 
 astray when, in discussing the use of <ra/> by Philo and Paul, 
 he asserts that " in Philo it is viewed entirely from the intel- 
 lectual standpoint, in Paul from that of pure religion." In 
 our judgment Philo is here far more directly influenced by 
 religious experience than by any philosophical theory. 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 utterance occurs : " Contrast the good of the 
 flesh with that of the soul (^ux%) and that of 
 the whole. That of the flesh is irrational 
 pleasure, but that of the soul and of the 
 whole is the reason of the universe, even God." 
 Here <m/>f and ^x 7 ? are set in antithesis, 
 a usage never found in Paul. But in the 
 same treatise ( 29) he says : " The supreme 
 cause of lack of knowledge is the flesh and 
 intimate association with the flesh. Indeed 
 God himself acknowledges this when he 
 affirms that ' because they are flesh' (Gen. 
 vi. 3) the Divine Spirit (TTVCV^O) cannot abide 
 with them." This is a usage extraordinarily 
 akin to Paul's regular contrast between <ra/>f 
 and TTvev/jua. It seems highly probable that 
 Philo in using irvev^a for the Divine influence 
 or action upon men, a usage foreign to earlier 
 Greek thought, followed the LXX, which 
 regularly translates ruach, " spirit" (generally 
 of God), by irvev^a. We have little doubt 
 that Paul's employment of it in the same 
 sense also originated there. But Philo differs 
 from Paul in employing a-upa far more fre- 
 quently than crdpj; for the irrational part of 
 
 90 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 human nature, which is liable to temptations 
 to sin through its sense-life ; and Philo does 
 not seem to individualise irvevpa in Paul's 
 sense of man's higher, rational element (vow) 
 inspired by the Spirit of God. 
 
 From what has been said it is, further, 
 clear that Philo uses ^vyy in a sense for- 
 eign to Paul. That is to say, for him -^i^' 
 is often equivalent \ to vov? or -m/ei^a, the 
 highest element in human nature, an element 
 which can be distinguished from mere animal 
 life. Examples have been given above. Paul 
 rarely uses ^v^n except in the vague sense of 
 " person " or "personality," * for which nephesh 
 constantly stands in the Old Testament, and 
 is generally rendered in this connection by 
 i/rv%?7 in the LXX. Three or four times he 
 employs it, also following a usage of the 
 LXX, in the popular sense of "heart" or 
 "mind," with no emphasis on any psycho- 
 logical nuance. Probably the phrase, " your 
 spirit, soul, and body " (i Thess. v. 23), is 
 more colloquial than anything else, and 
 certainly it is quite unfit to prop up the 
 
 1 About eight instances. 
 91 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 theory of a trichotomy of human nature 
 which has been based upon it. There only 
 remains i Cor. xv. 45, where he care- 
 fully follows the LXX of Gen. ii. 7, which 
 translates n;n && by et<? \frvxnv waav. Here 
 he deliberately contrasts ^v^ with Trvevpa, and 
 it becomes clear that in his view ^vyy stands 
 for the life of man as untouched by the Holy 
 Spirit. Of course, this "life" for Paul as for 
 Philo was due to Divine operation, but under 
 the influence of his central conception of the 
 Trvevpa as God's special gift to the Christian 
 believer, it lay close to Paul's hand to em- 
 phasise ^v^r) as the " natural" element 
 common to every human being, as contrasted 
 with the " supernatural," which stood supreme. 
 Plainly the adjective ^V^LKO^ which he uses 
 in i Cor. xv., in direct connection with the 
 quotation from the LXX just discussed, 
 and once in i Cor. ii., where it also stands 
 in sharp antithesis to irvevfiaTLKo^ has its 
 meaning determined by this contrast with 
 TTvevpa. In this case, again, we note the 
 divergence in Philo. He employs i/ri^/w? 
 
 repeatedly, in all sorts of connections. In a 
 
 92 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 few instances it applies to the ordinary inner 
 life of men, whether viewed as physical, or as 
 the sphere of feeling and other forms of con- 
 sciousness. 1 More often it occurs in the 
 higher sense of " spiritual," which is, of course, 
 totally alien to Paul. 2 But it is easy to see 
 how readily his use of the term might glide 
 into that of Paul if he had occasion to employ 
 it in contrasting the irrational with the rational 
 part of the soul. 
 
 In Philo, vow is often interchangeable with 
 ^ V X^ although, of course, it usually stands 
 for the higher aspect of the soul. Here Paul 
 approximates to his older contemporary. For 
 he regards vow as an important element in the 
 natural equipment of man, his highest capacity 
 apart from the Divine gift of the 
 
 1 E.g. (a) De Op. M. 66 : (T(op.ariKfjs j) ^VXIKTJS ova-ias ; (b) 
 Leg. Alleg. ii. 85 : TOV ^vx^ov o^Xoi/ <TKe8d<ravTos 6cov, of the 
 tumult of the sense-life, but with no necessary suggestion 
 of evil ; (c) ibid. ii. 22, where the powers of the vovs are 
 described as exriK^i/, tfrvriKrjv, V/O^IKT;!/, \oyiKTjv, d(-avoijriKrjv. 
 
 2 E.g. Leg. Alleg. i. 97 : rpo<pijs ^VX<-KTJS ; ibid. iii. 171 : 
 ({KOTOS KOiva)VTJ(rai \^v^tKoi) ; ibid. 145 '. TO>V -v^u^tKcoi/ ayaOvv ; 
 Quod .det. pot. : rbv ^VXIKOV Bavarov ; De Spec. Leg. iv. 75 : 
 K\r]pov6p.ovs rov -^VXIKOV irXovTov. With this use agrees the 
 only example in the LXX, 4 Mace. i. 32, where desires are 
 divided into higher, ^UXIKCU, and lower, <ra>/*cmKat. 
 
 93 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 Thus in Rom. vii. 25 he contrasts i>o{5s with 
 o-apf, an antithesis in which from his stand- 
 point ^v^ could not have replaced it. On 
 the other hand, except in a quotation from 
 Isa. xl. 13 (LXX), he clearly distinguishes 
 voits from Trvevpa. For while vovs is the most 
 spiritual element in the " natural " man, it 
 has to be renewed (Rom. xii. 2). It still 
 belongs to the life of the <ra/>f (Col. ii. 18). 
 When renewed, it exercises a most important 
 function. It becomes the rational faculty in 
 the new life of the Spirit, and as such regu- 
 lates the exuberant enthusiasm of the pneu- 
 matic life ( i Cor. xiv. 14 f., 19). As passages 
 which we have quoted show, Philo uses 
 TTvevfjia in a much larger range of meanings 
 than Paul. In the former it is sometimes 
 equivalent to reason, e.g. Quod del. pot. 84, 
 where he describes it as the energy of the ^u^, 
 " that Godlike product by which we reason." 
 It also represents the activity of the senses 
 (e.g. De Fuga y 182), where it is associated 
 with sight, hearing, smell, etc. Finally, it 
 denotes the Divine Spirit in a unique sense, 
 manifested in men of notable wisdom (e.g. 
 
 94 
 
FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS 
 
 De Gig. 23) or prophetic power (e.g. Quis Rer. 
 Div.H. 255). This last usage, directly based 
 on the Old Testament, is closely akin to that 
 of Paul in the Christian sphere, which is 
 mainly the result of personal religious experi- 
 ence, and so irvev^a becomes the terminus 
 technicus for the Divine life in the believer. 
 
 95 
 
CHAPTER IV 
 
 MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 THE earnest longing of men for God is 
 recognised by Philo from various 
 standpoints. Sometimes it is viewed under a 
 more abstract aspect, rather as the satisfaction 
 of the intellect than of the whole nature. 
 "There is nothing better," he says, "than 
 to search after the true God, even if the 
 finding of him should escape human capacity, 
 seeing that even eagerness of desire to un- 
 derstand him in itself produces unspeakable 
 pleasures and delights" (De Spec. Leg. i. 
 36). Similarly, in De Con/us. Ling. 97 : 
 "It befits those who would company with 
 knowledge to strive after a vision of the 
 Existent, and if they cannot attain this, at 
 least of his image, the most sacred Logos, 
 and next in order of that most perfect of his 
 
 works, this universe of ours." But in other 
 
 96 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 passages we find a far more personal note. 
 "To what soul," he asks, "was it given to 
 put evil out of sight, save to that to which 
 God was revealed, the soul which he deemed 
 worthy of his unspeakable mysteries? For 
 he says, Shall I hide from Abraham, my 
 servant, the things I do ? True, O Saviour, 
 for thine own works thou dost show to the 
 soul that yearns for goodness, and hidest 
 none of them from her. For this reason she 
 is able to flee from evil . . . and unceasingly 
 to extirpate hurtful passions " (Leg. Alleg. iii. 
 27). Again, commenting on God's word 
 (Gen. xlvi. 4), " I will go down with thee," 
 he expands as follows : "This I do because 
 of my pity for thy rational nature, so that 
 by my guidance thou mayest be brought up 
 out of the Hades of passion to the Olympian 
 abode of virtue, for to all suppliant souls I 
 have made known the way that leads to 
 heaven, preparing for them a thoroughfare 
 that they might not grow weary of their 
 journey " (De Post. Cain. 31). Let us inquire 
 what he means by "the Hades of passion," 
 and how souls are to flee from evil. 
 G 97 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 (a) The Meaning of Sin 
 
 Philo's conception of sin is indissolubly 
 associated with his view of men's bodily 
 nature which we have just examined. Here, 
 as in the case of all his positions, we must 
 not be influenced by isolated passages, but by 
 the trend of his thought as a whole. Thus, 
 a statement like Leg. Alleg. iii. 71 : "The 
 body is evil by nature and plots against the 
 soul," is a bare summary which in no way 
 exhibits the processes of Philo's reflection. 
 Nor do we get upon the right track either by 
 pointing decisively to his theory of the descent 
 of souls into human bodies or by emphasising 
 the frequent descriptions of the Fall of man 
 in Paradise. The former, as already noted, 
 appears to us a side-issue for Philo. In 
 the latter he probably uses the figure of 
 Adam as a sort of inclusive personification 
 of humanity, much as Paul did in Rom. 
 v. 12 ff. Philo really starts from his ex- 
 perience of human nature in himself and 
 from his observation of his fellow-men, the 
 precise standpoint of Paul in all that [he 
 
 98 !.,i 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 affirms regarding "the flesh." Of course 
 Philo, from the texture of his mind, is com- 
 pelled to theorise on the subject. But that 
 is subsequent to his acquaintance with the 
 conflicts of the moral life. The personal 
 note, so poignant in some of his utterances, 
 gives the real key to his starting-point : e.g. 
 Leg. Alleg. iii. 211: " There is another kind of 
 groaning found in those who repent and are 
 distressed because of their past waywardness, 
 who exclaim, Wretched men that we are, 
 who have for so long been stricken, without 
 knowing it, by the disease of senselessness, 
 folly and wrong pursuits." We naturally 
 compare Paul's famous ejaculation (Rom. 
 vii. 24) : " Wretched man that I am, who shall 
 deliver me from the body of this death ? " 
 
 Bearing in mind, then, the point from 
 which he starts, we must further note that 
 there are certain presuppositions about which 
 he never argues. The body is, as we have 
 seen, for Philo as for Paul, a clog upon the 
 higher nature. He would have identified 
 himself whole-heartedly with the Apostle's 
 self-revelation : " I beat my body black and 
 
 99 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 blue and make it my slave" (i Cor. ix. 27). 
 This is not because its material is evil, but 
 because it is indissolubly bound up with the 
 life of sense. That life is largely at the 
 mercy of pleasure (f)ovrj), an irrational and 
 seductive passion. Pleasure is the serpent, 
 "an abominable thing in itself" (Leg. Alleg. 
 iii. 68), which " beguiles and leads astray 
 the reason" (ibid. 64). The "love of 
 pleasure" is "ungodly" (ibid. iii. 211). 
 So that when Philo speaks of sinning as 
 "innate in every man who has come into 
 being" (De Vita Mas. ii. (iii.) 147), when 
 he describes as "without limit" "the things 
 that stain the soul " (De Mut. Nom. 49), he 
 has above all else in view the appeal of 
 passion to man's nature. " Passion," he de- 
 clares, "is the fountain of sins" (Quod Deus 
 sit immut. 72). But there is nothing me- 
 chanical in the working of this appeal. The 
 allurements of passion present themselves 
 before the will. Philo assumes man's power 
 of choice. "Moses," he observes, "does 
 not follow the opinion of some impious men 
 
 who say that God is the cause of evils, but 
 100 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 he attributes them to our own hands, mean- 
 ing by that our own efforts and the voluntary 
 turning of the mind toward the worse " 
 (Quod det. pot. 122). Involuntary sin occu- 
 pies a position between right and wrong 
 (Quaestt. in Gen. iv. 64). Philo describes 
 his view of such sin with perfect clearness. 
 "As long," he says, "as we only form un- 
 worthy conceptions by mere imagination, we 
 are not responsible for our thoughts, for the 
 soul can have a direction given to it involun- 
 tarily. But when action follows deliberation 
 that deliberation may be put to our account, for 
 in this way especially voluntary error is re- 
 vealed " (Quod det. pot. 97). Accordingly he 
 can allege that "mind and reason are, as it were, 
 the home of vice and virtue, in which it is their 
 nature todwell" (De Op. M. 73). Man deliber- 
 ately subordinates the higher rational life 
 of the soul to the sway of irrational desire, 
 instead of following the counsel of Moses 
 that we "ought to cut out and root up 
 passion from the soul" (Leg. Alleg. iii. 129). 
 What is the bearing of this upon God ? 
 It is true, as Windisch (Die Frommrgkeit 
 
 ICI 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 Philos, p. 98) observes, that in Philo guilt 
 before God is overshadowed by the sense of 
 man's nothingness as a creature in the Divine 
 presence. Yet there are hints of something 
 more positive. " God was justly angry at 
 them," he says, speaking of the generation 
 described in Gen. vi., "seeing that the living 
 creature which seemed to be the noblest and 
 had been judged worthy of kinship with him- 
 self, because of sharing with him in reason, 
 eagerly followed evil and every kind of evil, 
 when it ought to have practised goodness " 
 (De Abr. 41). Man, that is to say, knew the 
 ideal and deliberately ignored it. God en- 
 trusted to him the gifts of soul, speech and 
 the sense-life. But by far the majority of 
 of men, under the influence of self-love 
 (<t>t,\avTia), appropriated these for themselves. 
 They had their just reward in souls defiled 
 by irrational passions and held in the grasp 
 of innumerable vices : in speech whetted 
 against the truth, hurtful to those who heard 
 it, disgraceful to those who uttered it : in a 
 sense-life insatiable, heedless of all control- 
 ling influence (Quis Rer. Div. H. 106 ff.). 
 102 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 This self-love, which prompts to the abuse 
 of men's God-given powers, reveals itself 
 flagrantly in the form of riJ<o9, overweening 
 vanity, which is again and again emphasised 
 by Philo. He asserts that " TV$O<; is the 
 artificer of many other evils, of false preten- 
 sion, of arrogance, of inequality. ... By 
 reason of rO^o? even Divine things are 
 utterly scorned " (De Decal. 5 ff.). This en- 
 tire attitude means defiance of God, and it 
 may become so hardened that doom is in- 
 evitable. Commenting on the subject of 
 vows and pledges by which maidens, wives, 
 widows, or divorced wives bind their souls, as 
 discussed in Num. xxx., he makes a psycho- 
 logical application of the law's prescriptions. 
 The understanding can bind itself down to 
 courses which are for ever incurable. It 
 will thus not only be widowed of knowledge 
 but divorced from it. " That is to say : the 
 soul which is bereft of good, but not yet 
 divorced from it, can by steadfastness find 
 terms of reconciliation with right reason, her 
 lawful husband ; but that which has been 
 
 once divorced and made to live apart as un- 
 103 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 faithful has lost her chance for ever and can 
 no more return to her old home" (Quod del. 
 pot. 148 f. Cf. the stern utterance of Qu. 
 in Gen. i. 70). Yet, though the only fitting 
 punishment for the human race was "that it 
 should be extirpated on account of its in- 
 gratitude towards God, its benefactor and 
 Saviour, God in his mercy took pity upon 
 men, and moderated their penalty " (De Op. 
 M. 169). Necessarily, however, the Divine 
 grace presupposes minds and hearts which 
 through repentance and humility can respond 
 to its workings. 
 
 In theory, Philo may at times be disposed 
 to associate wrong action with man's constitu- 
 tion as a transient being, just as there are 
 passages in St. Paul which appear, on the 
 surface, to connect sin with man's physical 
 heritage. But in reality, for both, sin means 
 an assent of the will to the lower, selfish 
 impulses, in opposition to those which point 
 God-wards. The actual human experience 
 which they both know presents the spectacle 
 of a practical rather than a theoretical dualism. 
 Wrong-doing in the strict sense is not in- 
 104 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 voluntary, the result of ignorance. It is the 
 turning away from God in favour of self, 
 which Philo calls T/OOTTT?. The situation is 
 that of a being akin to God, participating in 
 the Divine Logos or Thought, and yet ex- 
 posed to the assaults of pleasurable cravings, 
 with which his reason identifies itself and 
 makes them the ends of living. Men's inner 
 life, that is to say, is, " mingled of opposing 
 qualities, right and wrong, base and honour- 
 able, good and evil " (Qu. in. Gen. iv. 203). 
 Philo quotes with approval the saying of 
 Epicharmus : " Whosoever yields but slightly 
 to evil is a very good man : for no one is/ 
 guiltless, no one is exempt from reproach."/ 
 Hence the main task, if any spiritual progress) 
 is to be made, must be the attainment of 
 self-knowledge. " Hither, you who are 
 stuffed full of vanity and indiscipline and 
 braggart boasting, you pretenders to wisdom, 
 who claim not only to know clearly every- 
 thing that is, but also, in your hardihood, 
 venture to declare their causes, as if you had 
 been present at the creation of the world. . . . 
 
 Once for all, let alone these other concerns : 
 105 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 know yourselves, and declare plainly of what 
 nature you are" (De Migr. Abr. 136 f.). 
 
 (b) Conscience 
 
 At this point in his reflection Philo enunci- 
 ates with spiritual insight and power a truth 
 of the inner life which up till now had been 
 but dimly foreshadowed, viz. the existence of 
 the moral consciousness, a criterion of action 
 placed at men's disposal, with boundless 
 possibilities for the building up of human 
 character in accordance with the Divine 
 purpose. He has, indeed, no formal dis- 
 cussion of Conscience and its functions, but 
 his frequent references to its commanding 
 position within the soul reveal its importance 
 for his thought. Here, as invariably, his 
 utterances are found to fluctuate, but their 
 general drift is easy to grasp. 
 
 There are several important passages in 
 which his view of Conscience closely ap- 
 proaches Paul's conception of vovs, the higher 
 element in human nature which approves of 
 the good (e.g. Rom. vii. 23, 25). This Paul 
 
 occasionally designates o e<rw avdpwiros, "the 
 106 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 man within." It assents to the Divine 
 order (Rom. vii. 22); it is renewed in the 
 Christian (2 Cor. iv. 16); it is the recipient 
 of the power of the Spirit (Eph. iii. 16). In 
 other words, it is the connecting link between 
 the " natural " and the " supernatural." Now, 
 in De Agricult. 9, Philo asks: "What can 
 be the man in each of us but the vow which 
 is wont to reap the benefits of those things 
 which have been sown and planted ? " A 
 further stage in the working out of the idea 
 appears in De Fuga, 131 : "These are the 
 utterances of the genuine man, who is (read- 
 ing with Cohn, 09 eVrt) the testing power 
 (eXey^o?) of the soul, who, when he sees the 
 soul in perplexity making inquiry and search, 
 takes care that she may not go astray and 
 miss the right path." It should be noted 
 that eXey^o? is for Philo an almost technical 
 description of the function of Conscience. 
 The full-fledged conception is found in Quod 
 del. pot. 22 f . : "If the vision of their soul 
 had not been defective, they would have 
 recognised that the precise and characteristic 
 
 name of the genuine man is just ' man ' 
 
 107 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 , the proper designation of the well- 
 knit and rational understanding (Siavoias). 
 This man who dwells in the soul of each is 
 found to be, on the one hand, ruler and king, 
 on the other, judge and umpire in the contests 
 of life, and at times taking the place of 
 witness or accuser he tests us invisibly 
 within, not allowing us to open our mouth, 
 but laying hold of and bridling with the 
 reins of conscience the stubborn and rebellious 
 course of the tongue, and thus brings it to a 
 halt." Here Philo assigns to the rational 
 understanding the function of moral judg- 
 ment, regarding it no doubt in its unsullied 
 character as the commanding element in the 
 inner world of the soul. Hence it is not a 
 mere accommodation to popular usage, as 
 Breliier supposes (pp. cit. p. 302), when, in 
 De DecaL 87, Philo describes as innate 
 (</A7re(v/tft)9) to every soul the " testing 
 power" (o 6X67x09) that dwells with us, that 
 is always true to its character of hating evil 
 and loving good, that, as accuser, blames, 
 accuses, frowns upon us, and again as judge, 
 
 teaches, warns, exhorts us to change our 
 108 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 ways. That is surely one permanent aspect 
 of the situation. It entirely accords with the 
 well-known statement of De Op. M. 146 : 
 " Every man, so far as his understanding 
 (Sidvoia) is concerned, is intimately related to 
 the Divine Logos, an impress or particle or 
 effulgence of the blessed nature, while as 
 regards his bodily status he is closely akin 
 to the whole cosmos." This is what Paul 
 means when he speaks of man as the 
 "image" and " reflection" of God (i Cor. 
 xi. 7). Were this not true, man would be 
 in the position of the irrational creatures, 
 having no spiritual affinity to the Divine, 
 and finally excluded from fellowship with God. 
 But Philo, like Paul, recognises the 
 irrational tendency in human nature to follow 
 the worse, although it knows the better. 
 Therefore man's mind has to be reinforced 
 in its moral aspirations by the Divine energy 
 itself. And so, repeatedly, Philo identifies 
 Conscience with the Logos. Perhaps the 
 most notable passage is Quod Deus sit immut. 
 134 ff. : " So long as the Divine Logos has 
 
 not come into our soul as into its abode, the 
 109 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 deeds of the soul are blameless : for its 
 guardian or father or teacher or whatever we 
 ought to call that Priest by whom alone it 
 can be warned and controlled remains far 
 away from it : and those who sin through 
 ignorance, without knowledge of what things 
 they ought to do, receive pardon. For they 
 do not even apprehend their actions as sins. 
 Indeed they even suppose that they are 
 acting rightly in cases where they commit 
 great errors. But when the Priest who 
 genuinely tests us enters into us like a 
 perfectly pure ray of light, then we recognise 
 the unrighteous designs harboured in our 
 soul and our culpable . . . deeds. All these 
 the consecrated testing Power, having shown 
 their defilement, bids us pack away and 
 strip off, that he may behold the house 
 of the soul clean, and if any diseases have 
 arisen in it, may heal them." And later, in 
 the same context, having compared the Logos 
 to a prophet, on the basis of i Kings xvii. 18, 
 he continues : " For this inspired being, in 
 the grasp of an Olympian love, and goaded 
 
 by the irrestisible stings of his Divine frenzy, 
 no 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 entering into the soul, creates there the 
 remembrance of her old wrong-doings and 
 sins, not that she may again yield to them, 
 but that with loud lamentations and weeping 
 she may come back from her former wander- 
 ing, hating its issue, and may follow the 
 promptings of the Logos-prophet, who is the 
 interpreter of God." 
 
 Here the clearest emphasis is laid upon 
 Conscience as the Divine agent in the soul, 
 so illuminating its actions that their real 
 character cannot escape detection. Philo 
 never inquires whether this is a gradual 
 process, accompanying or constituting the 
 moral growth of the individual, or a sudden 
 experience, which might be compared to 
 Paul's remarkable account (Rom. vii. 7 ff.) 
 of his awakening to the real meaning of sin. 
 The opening sentences of the passage in- 
 evitably remind us, up to a certain point, of 
 what the Apostle says about sin not being 
 reckoned to a man so long as no moral 
 standard like the law confronts him. But 
 for Philo the activity of conscience is wholly 
 
 and permanently salutary, while by Paul the 
 1 1 1 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 religion of law comes to be regarded merely 
 as a makeshift. 
 
 Bre*hier (op. cit. p. 301) observes that the 
 function ascribed by the Stoics to the Wise 
 Man as a consultant on the subject of moral 
 health and progress is by Philo entrusted to 
 Conscience. This marks a real epoch in the 
 history of ethics. The Greek schools had 
 been chiefly concerned with the question of 
 the highest good for man. When, in their 
 later phases, they came to discuss the source 
 of moral obligation, the Stoics, who led the 
 way, found the authoritative norm in reason. 
 That doctrine is, as we have seen, recognised 
 by Philo, but in a very real sense he trans- 
 forms it on lines akin to, although not 
 immediately derived from, Old Testament 
 religion. For we may at least say that 
 Jeremiah's great conception of the Divine 
 law or teaching written in men's hearts 
 approximates to Philo's position. Essentially, 
 for Philo, Conscience involves the impact of 
 God upon the soul. It is the assessor in the 
 nature of the inner life (De Jos. 47 f.). It is 
 
 an angel who, while it questions the soul in 
 112 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 order to reveal to it the truth, has full know- 
 ledge of the situation (De Fuga, 203 f.). It 
 is identified with the vision of the good which 
 often hovers suddenly over the most worth- 
 less, but which they are unable to grasp or to 
 retain. And this vision is nothing else than 
 a visitation of the Spirit of God (De Gig. 
 210 f.). This last passage brings out clearly 
 what is suggested by Philo's entire conception 
 of conscience, its remarkable affinity to the 
 idea of the "advocate" (Tra/oa/cX^ro?) in such 
 places as John xvi. 8 : " When he has come, 
 he will convict (e'X<fyf) the world as regards 
 sin and righteousness and judgment " : and 
 xix. 17 : " He will give you another advocate 
 to be with you for ever, the spirit of truth." 
 There is a remarkable passage in Philo which 
 gives an almost startling corroboration of 
 this. When dealing (De Spec. Leg. i. 235 ff.) 
 with legal enactments bearing on the case of 
 those who have defrauded their neighbour 
 and afterwards confessed their sin, he says : 
 " After making atonement to the person he 
 has wronged, Moses enjoins that he should 
 
 go to the holy place, to ask for remission of 
 H 113 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 his sins, bringing with him an irreproachable 
 advocate (Trapd/cXrjTos), the power which has 
 searched his soul, 1 which delivered him from 
 a hopeless calamity, ridding him of a mortal 
 disease and transforming him into a condition 
 of perfect health." 
 
 We have seen that the main function of 
 Conscience in Philo is e'Xey^os, testing or 
 convicting. And for him its witness is in- 
 corruptible and absolutely true (De Post. 
 Cain. 59). Its activity at least points in the 
 direction of Paul's great doctrine of the Spirit 
 as the Divine life in the Christian, although, 
 of course, that presupposes a background of 
 experience which Philo would scarcely have 
 understood. Indeed, Philo seems to identify 
 Conscience with God himself. " If the 
 understanding, supposing that it can do 
 wrong without the knowledge of the Deity, 
 as if he were not able to see everything, 
 commits sin stealthily and in secret places, 
 and afterwards, whether of itself or at the 
 suggestion of some one, perceives that it is 
 impossible for anything to be concealed from 
 
 1 TOP Kara ^VXT 
 114 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 God, and thus unfolds itself and all its habits, 
 and bringing them forth as to the sunlight 
 shows them to the Overseer of all things, 
 asserting its penitence for these wrong 
 opinions which formerly it cherished through 
 lack of knowledge ... it is purified and 
 benefited and assuages the just wrath of 
 that testing, punitive Power which stands 
 over it " (De Somn. i. 9 1 ) 
 
 Reviewing, then, all the evidence we have 
 examined, it may be truly affirmed that Philo 
 regards Conscience as a real factor in 
 awakening man's aspirations after God. An 
 indispensable condition, therefore, of reaching 
 God is the lowliness of the man who is able 
 justly to estimate himself as in the Divine 
 presence. " I have learnt to measure my 
 own nothingness and to admire the exceeding 
 excellence of thy benefits. And when I 
 perceive myself to be but ' dust and ashes ' 
 and whatever can be more despicable, then I 
 have the courage to meet thee, having become 
 humble, cast down to the ground" (Quis 
 Rer. Div. H. 29). 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 (c) Repentance 
 
 If Conscience stimulates the soul to moral 
 progress, the fundamental step in such 
 progress is Repentance. Philo definitely 
 associates this change of mental and moral 
 direction with the action of conscience. 
 When discussing, on the basis of Lev. 
 vi. 2 ff, the case of a man who has sworn 
 falsely regarding a wrong he has done his 
 neighbour, he remarks that the man, having 
 imagined that he has escaped the charge 
 brought against him, " becomes his own 
 accuser, being convicted inwardly by con- 
 science, and reproaches himself for his false- 
 hood, and making open confession of his 
 wrong-doing, asks pardon." In such a case 
 he is bidden to prove the genuineness of his 
 repentance, not by words but by deeds. And 
 Philo points out that the sin-offering he has 
 to present is the same in kind as the peace- 
 offering (rov <ra)TrjpLov Ovvlcu), "for in a sense 
 the man who repents is saved, turning aside 
 from that disease of the soul which is more 
 
 serious than bodily passions " (De Spec. Leg. 
 116 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 i. 235 ff.). This instance shows his view of 
 the direct effect of conscience upon the will 
 in the matter of repentance. Probably that 
 remains a presupposition. But his delicate 
 moral observation plays on the subject from 
 varying standpoints, which suggests that he 
 is influenced not by theory but by practical 
 experience. 
 
 The main root of Repentance is the dis- 
 covery of the soul that it has been turning 
 aside from God after lower aims, such as 
 pleasure. At this discovery, "the man, 
 beholding God, laments over his own de- 
 sertion . . . and his soul cries out, imploring 
 the Almighty to save him from further 
 deviation and to accomplish his perfecting " 
 (Leg. All. iii. 211 ff.). Repentance therefore 
 begins in grief of spirit. " Those whogenuinely 
 repent are afflicted by reason of their former 
 course of life, and in their grief at its wretched- 
 ness they weep, they groan, they sigh " (Qu. 
 in Exod. i. 15). Sometimes the emphasis is 
 laid on the causality of the Divine Mercy, 
 which is no doubt assumed by Philo in all 
 the operations of conscience. " He resolved 
 117 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 on confession and pardon at an earlier time : 
 now ... he appoints repentance, not scoffing 
 at nor reproaching in any way those who are 
 thought to have sinned, making possible the 
 ascent of the soul from vice to goodness" 
 (Qu. in Gen. i. 82). Whatever be the 
 immediate stimulus, a primary stage in the 
 process of repenting consists in confession of 
 sins. "If ... in shame they turn with 
 their whole soul, reproaching themselves for 
 their waywardness, declaring and confessing 
 all their sins, in the first place with purified 
 mind before conscience . . . and then with 
 their lips . . . they shall obtain the favour 
 of the gracious God, the Saviour, who has 
 imparted to the race of men his choice and 
 chiefest gift, intimate kinship with his own 
 Logos" (De Exsecr. 163). But besides the 
 negative element of penitence, repentance 
 involves the positive longing for goodness. 
 11 Following upon the victory gained by hope, 
 there is a second contest in which the repent- 
 ing soul is the competitor, for though it has 
 not participated in the unchanging nature 
 
 . . . which always remains the same, yet 
 118 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 suddenly possessed by a passion ... for 
 the nobler, it hastens to abandon its habitual 
 greed and wrong-doing, and to make its abode 
 with self-control and righteousness and the 
 other virtues" (De Praem. et Poen. 15). 
 
 In the passage just quoted Repentance is 
 made to follow Hope. This is a favourite 
 position of Philo's. Hope he regards as the 
 supreme characteristic of the human soul 
 (De Abr. 8), in the sense of the expectation 
 of good things. Its precise relation to re- 
 pentance is described in a passage where 
 Philo groups them both with complete attain- 
 ment (reXeio-n;?). But to understand the 
 significance of this, we must turn to an 
 earlier statement. "It must be noted," he 
 says, "that repentance is ranked second to 
 complete attainment, as a change from sick- 
 ness to health ranks second to a perfectly 
 sound body. Thus uninterrupted complete- 
 ness in virtue stands closest to Divine power, 
 while the improvement that has gone on for 
 some time is the special blessing of a well- 
 ordered soul, refusing to continue among 
 childish things, but with full-grown and 
 119 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 manly bent, seeking a condition of poise, 
 and following the vision of the good " (De 
 Abr. 26). In the light of these words we 
 can appreciate the later utterance: "The 
 perfect man is complete from the beginning : 
 he who has repented is half-made, having 
 devoted the former period of his life to evil, 
 and the later to virtue, to which he ... 
 transformed his abode ; while he that hopes 
 ... is defective, aiming always at the good, 
 but having not yet been able to reach it, 
 resembling sailors who, though eager to put 
 into port, are still at sea, unable to get to 
 anchorage " (ibid. 47). Probably, as in the 
 case of the Wise Man of the Stoics, the 
 position of the T&ejo? is for Philo an ideal 
 rather than an attainment. For, in another 
 important passage where again he assigns to 
 Repentance the second rank, he remarks : 
 " To commit no sin at all is peculiar to God, 
 possibly also to a Divine man, but to turn 
 from sin to a blameless life is the part of a 
 discerning man who recognises what is wholly 
 profitable" (De Virtut. 177). In drawing 
 
 an ingenious distinction between the first 
 120 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 and the second return of the dove to TNJoah, 
 he uses the legend to emphasise the gradual 
 process of repentance. " To find repentance 
 is not easy, but an excessively difficult and 
 toilsome business " : and he proceeds to 
 illustrate the stages in the process by the 
 olive-leaf and the dry twig (LXX of Gen. 
 viii. n) in the dove's mouth (Qu. in Gen. ii. 
 42 f.). We do not touch on an interesting 
 feature of his longest discussion of repentance 
 (De Virtut. 175 ff.), in which he deals pri- 
 marily with the turning of idol-worshippers 
 to the one God, and shows that this involves 
 the exchange of folly for insight and of wrong- 
 doing for righteousness. The final result of 
 Repentance, which unifies the life of the soul, 
 is that its subject becomes at one and the 
 same time beloved of God and a lover of Him. 
 
 (d) Faith 
 
 If we were attempting to discuss the 
 genetic development of the Christian soul 
 on New Testament lines, it would be natural, 
 after estimating the significance of Repent- 
 ance, to deal with the fundamental religious 
 121 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 relationship of Faith. In a sense this is also 
 legitimate for the student of Philo. But that 
 sense must be made clear. Repentance, as 
 we have seen, means that conscience has 
 been at work, unveiling to the soul its own 
 unworthiness, and urging it on to a nobler 
 course. Faith, in Philo, seems to presuppose 
 this background. Whatever else it .may be, 
 it is at least "an amelioration of the soul at 
 all points," but "of the soul resting and 
 established on the Cause of all things, who 
 is able for anything, but who wills the best " 
 (De Abr. 268). The latter part of this de- 
 scription embodies much of Philo's doctrine 
 of Faith. 
 
 It is important to notice that he is largely 
 guided in his conception by the Old Testa- 
 ment report of Abraham's faith, and especi- 
 ally by Gen. xv. 6 : " Abraham believed 
 (eVwTTevae) God, and it was counted to him 
 for righteousness, "a passage which is equally 
 prominent in Paul, and seems to have taken 
 an outstanding place in Synagogue theology 
 (see, e.g., Mechilta, ed. Winter u. Wtinsche, 
 
 p. no). That fact, which has numerous 
 122 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 parallels throughout his works, reminds us 
 that some of his observations on Faith are 
 not necessarily typical of his thought, but due 
 rather to the details which happen to make 
 up some passage in the story of Abraham. 1 
 But in the main his own view accords with 
 the Old Testament account of the patriarch's 
 faith. And his description of it is most 
 significant for his entire outlook. " He first 
 is said to have believed God, since he was 
 the first to possess an unwavering and stable 
 notion (inroK^iv) that the sole Cause is the 
 highest, and that his providence is over the 
 universe and all that belongs to it. So 
 having come to possess faith, the most stable 
 of the virtues, he entered into possession of 
 all the others along with it" (De Virtut. 
 216). This, although expressed in different 
 terminology, is in remarkable agreement with 
 Paul's interpretation of the same story, that 
 
 1 This consideration takes from the force of Dr. Bigg's 
 remark (Christian Platonists of Alexandria, p. 26) that 
 in Quis Rer. Div. H. 21, Philo associates Faith with a 
 lower stage of spiritual life. Philo is attempting to do full 
 justice to all the details of the special passage he is 
 expounding (Gen. xv. 8). 
 
 123 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 Abraham staked everything on his Conviction 
 of the grace and truth and power of God 
 (Rom. iv. 1 6 ff. ; Gal. iii. 7 ff., 18). In both 
 cases there is far more than the mere un- 
 faltering expectation of good things to come. 
 The very foundation of religion is implied in 
 this relation of absolute trust in the unseen 
 God. The same may be said of the writer 
 to the Hebrews, who stands in line with Philo 
 at so many points. For him faith is "the 
 assurance of the things hoped for, the proof 
 (or, conviction, \eyx o< *) of the things not 
 seen" (xi. i). It means the realisation in 
 this present of that invisible realm in which 
 God can be fully known, or rather, the reali- 
 sation of the unseen God himself. " For 
 Moses . . . endured as seeing him who is 
 invisible " (xi. 27). The assurance of God is 
 primary for the writer to the Hebrews as for 
 Philo. All fulfilment of hopes and expecta- 
 tions is for both bound up with that. Indeed, 
 the New Testament teacher uses language 
 which might have been Philo's own, when 
 he declares : "He that draws near to God 
 
 must believe that he exists, and that he 
 124 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 rewards those who earnestly seek him " 
 (xi. 6). This conviction transforms life from 
 illusion into reality. 
 
 In emphasising the profoundly religious 
 significance of faith in Philo, as contrasted 
 with a more superficial aspect of it, namely, 
 belief in the fulfilment of God's promises 
 before there is any sign of its approach, 
 Brehier (op. cit. p. 222 f.) suggests that the 
 deeper view is due to the influence of Stoic 
 mysticism. 1 And he attempts to find a con- 
 firmation of this in such statements as Quis 
 Rer. Div. H. 101 : "That it would come to 
 pass, he of course firmly grasped in accord- 
 ance with the Divine promises," where he 
 associates the " firm grasp " with the Stoic 
 idea of faith as " powerful apprehension." 
 It is possible that some of his terms may have 
 been suggested by Stoic usage, although they 
 are such as might naturally present them- 
 selves. But Brevier's own admission (loc. cit.} 
 that, in distinction from the Stoics, who use 
 the conception in reference to all true repre- 
 sentations, Philo never applies the idea of 
 
 1 So also W. H. P. Hatch, The Pauline Idea of Faith, p. 47. 
 125 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 faith except to God, makes it far more 
 probable that he speaks fundamentally on 
 the ground of his own religious experience. 
 
 When we try to analyse Philo's view of 
 Faith more clearly, we are at once impressed 
 by its intellectual side. That has come out 
 above in the important passage where he 
 describes it as a stable V7r6\rj^ t and is corro- 
 borated by the quotations from Hebrews 
 which have so markedly Philonic a colour. 
 " To clear away each of these [earthly in- 
 fluences] and to distrust the world of 
 becoming which is of itself wholly unworthy 
 of confidence, and to have faith in God alone, 
 who alone is in truth trustworthy, requires a 
 large and Olympian understanding, one 
 which is no longer enticed by our worldly 
 interests " (Quis Rer. Div. H. 93). Hence 
 Schlatter is so far justified in saying that for 
 Philo, Faith is "the fruit of knowledge, and 
 the incompleteness of the latter is directly 
 transferred to it " (Der Glaube im NT. 
 p. 92). But obviously all Faith involves 
 intellectual elements. The question is 
 
 whether it gets beyond this intellectual 
 126 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 starting-point. And it is not difficult to 
 answer that question in Philo's case. 
 
 In one of his numerous comments on 
 Gen. xv. 6 he asks : " In what else can 
 we put our faith [save in God] ? Can we 
 put it in leadership or reputations and dis- 
 tinctions, or in abundance of riches and high 
 birth, or in health and quick sensibility, or in 
 vigour and bodily beauty ? " After estimating 
 these at their proper worth, which at best 
 is utterly transient, he concludes : " Faith 
 towards God alone is a true and stable good, 
 a consolation of life, a fulfilment of bright 
 hopes, a famine of evils, and a full crop of 
 blessings. . . . For, as those who walk by a 
 slippery path stumble and fall, while they 
 who tread the dry high road go forward 
 without tripping, so those who engross their 
 soul with bodily and external interests 
 accustom it to nothing but falls . . . while 
 they who through the contemplation of 
 virtue hasten towards God, follow a straight 
 course. ... So that one may truly say that 
 he who has put his faith in the former objects 
 
 refuses to trust God, while he who refuses to 
 127 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 trust them has put his faith in God " (De Abr. 
 263, 268 f.). It is plain that by genuine 
 Faith, Philo means that liberation of the soul 
 from the dominion of earthly good which has 
 as its obverse side the great venture of cast- 
 ing one's self upon God. This he describes 
 as a straining, testing experience. Referring 
 to Gen. xv. 6 as a eulogy of the trusting 
 soul, he meets a possible objection : " Perhaps 
 some one might say, Do you judge this 
 worthy of praise ? Who would refuse to 
 heed the word and promise of God, even if 
 he were the most lawless and impious of 
 men ? Our reply would be : Dear friend, do 
 not without careful inquiry deprive the wise 
 man of the eulogy which is his due, or ascribe 
 to the worthless the most perfect of virtues, 
 faith, or find fault with our discernment in 
 such matters. For if you choose to make a 
 profounder search and not merely a superficial 
 one, you will clearly discover that it is not 
 easy to put faith in God alone without drag- 
 ging in something else, on account of the close 
 kinship which binds us to mortal things, a 
 
 kinship which persuades us to confide in 
 128 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 money and fame, and power and friends and 
 vigour of body and many similar things. . . . 
 To fix our moorings firmly ... in the Existent 
 alone is a surprising thing among men, who 
 do not possess unadulterated good, but not 
 strange when truth is in control, rather the 
 pure product of righteousness " (Quis Rer. 
 Div. H. 90 ff.). Here he deliberately ex- 
 cludes everything but the immediate relation 
 of the soul to God. God fills the entire 
 spiritual horizon : and there is no other. 
 This is the true paradox of religious experi- 
 ence : to distrust and detach one's self from 
 all the forces that press in upon human life, 
 as deceptive and unreal, and to hazard every- 
 thing upon the Invisible, which cannot be 
 apprehended by the ordinary process of 
 knowledge. This implies a tremendous act 
 and perseverance of will. Philo is true to his 
 Old Testament lineage. There is nothing 
 to correspond to it in his Greek masters. 
 Knowledge could not achieve such a result. 
 And the issue is a glad fearlessness of bear- 
 ing (irappTja-ia). Philo delights to dwell upon 
 
 this. " The noble man " he is describing 
 I 129 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 Moses and his attitude towards God "can 
 behave with such glad fearlessness as not 
 merely to speak and shout, but he will 
 actually dare as the result of pure trust and 
 genuine feeling to cry out" (Quis Rer. 
 Div. H. 19). But such an attitude, the 
 high product of faith, is devoid of presump- 
 tion. It never crosses the boundary which 
 separates confidence in God from self- 
 confidence. " What am I " Philo represents 
 Abraham as saying "that thou shouldest 
 impart to me of thy speech ? Am not I an 
 exile from my country ? . . . Am not I an 
 alien from my father's house ? ... But thou, 
 O Lord, art to me my country, thou art my 
 kinsfolk, . . . thou art my reward, my glad 
 fearlessness. . . . Why then should not I dare 
 to utter my thoughts ? . . . Yet I who speak 
 of daring confess my awe and terror. . . . 
 Without ceasing, therefore, I find delight in 
 this blending, which has moved me neither 
 to speak boldly without godly fear, nor to 
 tremble before God without glad fearlessness " 
 (ibid. 26 ff.). Philo's descriptions of irapp^La 
 at once recall the prominence of the idea in 
 130 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 Hebrews and / John. In the former it 
 belongs distinctly, as in Philo, to the sphere 
 of faith. Indeed, chap. iii. 6 might have 
 come from the older author : " whose house 
 are we, if we keep our glad fearlessness and 
 our exultant hope stable unto the end." But 
 not less remarkable is the Johannine usage. 
 True, it is based on love rather than faith, 
 but it would be hard to distinguish in i John 
 between the two. At any rate, for the 
 writer, love is that which unites with God, 
 the very function which faith discharges, 
 according to Philo. 
 
 This reference to the New Testament 
 suggests a further one, which will serve to 
 bring out an additional element in Philo's 
 conception of Faith. We have mentioned 
 points in which St. Paul and Philo coincide. 
 And our last paragraph emphasises another, 
 faith's office of linking the soul to God. 
 From the nature of the case, Paul's con- 
 ception is far more concrete and personal, 
 for its medium is the living person of the 
 living Lord. But besides, for Paul, faith 
 marks especially the initiation of the Chris- 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 tian career. Undoubtedly he presupposes 
 faith at every stage, as so crucial a passage 
 as Gal. ii. 20 demonstrates. But above 
 all, in Paul's view, faith is that movement of 
 the whole being which, in response to the 
 revelation of the Divine love in Jesus Christ, 
 crucified and risen, carries it into union 
 with the living Lord, so that henceforth it 
 shares His attitude to sin and to God. 
 
 Some of the passages already cited hint 
 that at times Faith is viewed by Philo not 
 so much in relation to the beginning of a 
 higher life as to its consummation : not so 
 much as a starting-point, but rather as a 
 goal. Commenting on the expression, " which 
 I will show you " (Gen. xii. i), he observes 
 that here God " has carefully defined before- 
 hand for his promise, not the present but the 
 future, as a testimony to the faith which the 
 soul placed in God, not showing forth its 
 gratitude as the result of something accom- 
 plished for it, but as springing from its 
 expectation of what was to come. In 
 depending on and clinging to a bright hope, 
 and regarding as indubitably present that 
 132 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 which was not present, on account of the 
 steadfastness of him who had made the 
 promise, it has won as its prize, faith, a 
 perfect good" (De Migr. Abr. 43 f.) This 
 accords with his statement, quoted above, as 
 to the difficulty of attaining to faith. But 
 Philo's attitude is most clearly disclosed in 
 several estimates of Abraham, the typical 
 believer. " He who was the first to forsake 
 empty pride for truth, who used for his per- 
 fecting the virtue which could teach 1 him, 
 wins faith towards God as his prize. . . . 
 He to whom it has been granted to despise 
 and overstep all that is corporeal and all that 
 is not, and to rest and establish himself on 
 God alone with steadfast reason and un- 
 wavering . . . faith, he is truly fortunate 
 and thrice-blessed. We must also inquire 
 into the fact that each of the three [patriarchs] 
 had assigned to him the prize most befitting. 
 For to him who was perfected by instruction 
 [Abraham] faith was awarded, since the 
 learner must believe his teacher in the 
 lessons he has given : for it is difficult, 
 
 Reading didao-KaXiKfj, with Mangey. 
 133 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 nay, impossible, to train one who refuses 
 to trust you" (De Praem. et Poen. 27, 
 30, 49). In these passages, emphasis is 
 certainly laid upon faith as the climax of a 
 period of spiritual discipline. But perhaps 
 faith must always be viewed under these 
 two aspects : as the clue to spiritual progress 
 as well as its crown. That is implied in the 
 famous words of Heb. xii. if.: " Let us 
 by endurance run the race that is set before 
 us, looking away to Jesus, the leader and 
 the perfecter of our faith." And no less so 
 in Paul's ardent aspiration (Phil. iii. 8 f.) : 
 " Nay, I count all things as loss compared 
 to the surpassing worth of knowing Christ 
 Jesus my Lord . . . that I may win Christ, 
 and be found at the end in him." Faith, and 
 still more faith, is the goal of Paul's striving 
 to the close. It is the supreme issue for all 
 
 believers. 
 
 (e) Immortality 
 
 For Philo, the soul which is linked to God 
 
 by a real faith must possess eternal life. 
 
 From various passages it might be inferred 
 
 that Philo presupposed the immortality of 
 
 134 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 the soul. And this is possibly a necessary 
 corollary of his view of its nature, even 
 though we come upon such a passage as 
 De Abr. 55: "The nature of man is 
 mortal." This, in all likelihood, refers to 
 his nature as compound, although perhaps 
 our author has fundamentally in view rather 
 the immortality of the soul than that of 
 human beings as such. But it was not a 
 mere abstract conception which interested 
 Philo. It was the craving for life. His 
 attitude towards this perfection of being con- 
 ^tinually reminds us of the New Testament, 
 and he agrees with writers like St. Paul and 
 the author of the Fourth Gospel in regard- 
 ing the possession of Divine life as a present 
 possibility, and not something to be reached 
 only in a new order of being, though he fails 
 to reach their splendid vision of life eternal. 
 
 Nothing is more remarkable in this con- 
 nection than his descriptions of what he 
 conceives to be real death and real life, 
 for he employs similar phraseology to that 
 of St. Paul in similar discussions. " Natural 
 death," he says, " is that in which the soul 
 135 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 is separated from the body. But the death 
 which is penal is constituted when the soul 
 dies to the life of virtue, and lives only to 
 that of vice " (Leg. AIL i. 107). Cain's 
 punishment he describes as " living in a 
 continuous death, enduring, in a sense, a 
 death which is immortal and endless. For 
 there are two kinds of death. The one is the 
 state of being dead, which may be good, or 
 neither good nor bad (aSidfopov) ; the other 
 is the state of dying, which is altogether bad, 
 and the more grievous to bear the longer 
 it lasts " (De Praem. et Poen. 70). This 
 passage shows that Philo draws a sharper 
 distinction between physical and spiritual 
 death than Paul does. When the Apostle 
 speaks of death, he seems to regard the term 
 synthetically, ignoring the common analysis 
 into physical and spiritual, and regarding the 
 dissolution of an existence which is out of 
 touch with God as a single experience of 
 ruin. In Philo's case the lot of mortality is 
 overshadowed by the doom of the evil soul, 
 which appears to him independent of time 
 and space. An illuminating example of his 
 136 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 position is found in De Fuga, 55. There he 
 tells how reflection has taught him " that 
 the worthless, although they reach extreme 
 old age, are dead, for they are cut off from 
 the life of goodness ; while the good, even if 
 parted from their union with the body, live 
 for ever, sharing in a lot which is immortal." 
 Here he stands in line with the Pauline view, 
 that severance from the earthly body can 
 never quench the life that is rooted in God. 
 
 Hence, Philo emphasises the endowment 
 of the soul with eternal life, apart from the 
 division of experience into present and future. 
 " When the immortal type of being arises in 
 the soul, the mortal forthwith suffers destruc- 
 tion. For the origination of worthy pursuits 
 means the death of those that are base ; since, 
 when the light has once shone, the darkness 
 disappears" (Quod Deus sit immut. 123). This 
 is the counterpart in Philo of St. Paul's great 
 antithesis between " dying to sin " and " living 
 to righteousness," the first condition invari- 
 ably leading on to the second. It is worthy 
 of note that Philo attempts to define immor- 
 tality from this precise standpoint. "This," 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 he declares, "is the finest definition of 
 immortal life to be possessed with a [flesh- 
 less and bodiless] l passion and friendship for 
 God" (De Fuga, 58). Evidently it is such 
 a relationship which purifies the soul. For 
 in commenting on Gen. xv. 15, where it is 
 said of Abraham, " Thou shalt depart to thy 
 fathers in peace," he speaks of Scripture as 
 here indicating " that the good man does not 
 die, but departs, that it might declare the 
 inextinguishable and immortal nature of the 
 fully purified soul, which shall experience a 
 departure from this world to heaven, not 
 that dissolution and destruction which death 
 appears to bring" (Quis Rer. Div. H. 276). 
 
 This passage prepares us for a more 
 popular picture of immortality, again re- 
 minding us vividly of St. Paul, who also 
 combines the more pictorial with the pro- 
 founder idea, "When Abraham," he says, 
 "left the mortal state, ' he was gathered to the 
 people of God ' (Gen. xxv. 8 : Philo's own 
 adaptation of the text), reaping immortality, 
 made like unto the angels" (De Sacrif. Ab. 
 
 1 Omitted by Cohn. 
 138 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 et C. 5). It is almost needless to recall the 
 startling parallel to the last clause in Luke's 
 account of Jesus' answer to the Sadducees 
 (Luke xx. 36). Similarly , having described 
 the path of the soul towards goodness as 
 ending in life and immortality, while that 
 towards evil issues in the shunning of these 
 blessings and in death, he remarks that "the 
 God who loves to give, plants in the soul a 
 kind of paradise of virtues and of the deeds 
 which accord with them, which brings it to 
 perfect bliss " (De Plant. 37). Occasionally, 
 it is not easy to determine whether Philo's 
 language on the destinies of souls is to be 
 taken literally or metaphorically. Thus, in 
 a fine passage (De Somn. i. 151 f.), he tells 
 how "the wise have received an abode in 
 the Olympian and heavenly region, having 
 learned ever to sojourn above, while the 
 wicked dwell in the recesses of Hades, 
 having from first to last made it their aim 
 to die, and from childhood to old age being 
 accustomed to destruction." Possibly, how- 
 ever, the clause that follows regarding lives 
 of laborious effort (ao-KTjrai), " which go fre- 
 139 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 quently upwards and downwards as on a 
 ladder, either drawn upward by the worthier 
 lot, or pulled in the contrary direction by the 
 less worthy," indicates that the metaphorical 
 sense is uppermost in his mind. It is, how- 
 ever, noteworthy that Philo can deliberately 
 speak of the ideal (VOIJTOS) or spiritual world in 
 remarkably concrete terms terms which his 
 master, Plato, would have shrunk from using. 
 In conceiving it as the abode of immortality, 
 he sets it in sharp contrast with the visible 
 order as "a veritable world of intelligent 
 beings" (Bre*hier, op. cit. p. 240). Thus, in 
 a classification of men, the highest place is 
 taken by "men of God, priests and prophets, 
 who had no ambition ... to become citizens 
 of the world, but reaching beyond the entire 
 sensible universe, removed into the spiritual 
 and dwelt there, enrolled in the common- 
 wealth of immortal and incorporeal ideas" 
 (De Gig. 61). The closing words remind 
 us of his unfailing effort to fuse Hellenism 
 with Jewish conceptions. 
 
 We have in the foregoing paragraph sug- 
 gested various interesting comparisons with 
 140 
 
MAN'S YEARNING FOR GOD 
 
 St. Paul. Yet the fact cannot be ignored 
 that Philo's conception of immortality is far 
 less rich in content than that of the Apostle. 
 This is partly due to his failure to connect 
 the Hope in any definite fashion with the 
 consummation of the Kingdom of God and 
 those spacious moral processes of the Divine 
 government of the world which find their 
 climax there. It is surrounded by too rare- 
 fied an atmosphere, philosophical rather than 
 religious. And thus, while it strives to ex- 
 press, as we have seen, a genuine religious 
 need, its undue intellectualism narrows it 
 down to something less impressive even than 
 the Apocalyptic conception of immortality. 1 
 
 1 In these paragraphs I am specially indebted for valuable 
 hints to my friend Dr. J. H. Leckie. 
 
 141 
 
i 
 
 CHAPTER V 
 
 GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 (a) The Grace of God 
 
 N our discussion of Philo's view of Faith, 
 we found that it meant a complete 
 turning away from the life of sense and the 
 fixing of the soul's gaze upon God alone. 
 This he regards as a supreme achievement 
 of the spiritual life. But it presupposes an 
 experience of the Divine working which is 
 really the basis of its existence. Side by 
 side with those abstract descriptions of God, 
 which lay the emphasis on His incomprehen- 
 sibility, and deny to Him as pure Being the 
 possession of any qualities (a-Troio?), Philo 
 reveals his place in the true succession of 
 Old Testament piety by the prominence he 
 assigns in the history of the soul's progress 
 
 to the energies of the Divine Grace. Such 
 142 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 prominence is in no sense accidental. From 
 the readiness with which his conviction of 
 Grace is introduced as something self-evident 
 to the religious mind, and the feelings of 
 wonder and joy which it calls forth, it 
 obviously belongs to the inmost texture of his 
 devout experience. And it forms one of the 
 many testimonies which his works supply 
 that, in spite of his zeal for cosmological and 
 psychological speculations after the model of 
 his Greek masters, the crucial elements in 
 his view of God and man belong to the 
 spiritual heritage of his race. He does not 
 attempt in any theoretical fashion, not even 
 to the extent that Paul did, to divide the 
 ground in this mysterious realm between 
 God and man. He is content to accept as 
 one of the most inspiring factors in the 
 relation of God to His creatures the unceas- 
 ing outflow of a Divine purpose of mercy, 
 initiating all that is good in human life 
 and opening up the highest possibilities to 
 those who are conscious of nothing but 
 imperfection. 
 
 This fundamental idea comes out in one of 
 MS 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 those ingenious verbal distinctions to which 
 he is so strongly addicted. Again and again 
 he refers the difference between the two 
 leading names given in the Old Testament 
 to the Existent (TO oi>), namely, " God " (0eos) 
 and " Lord " (KU/HO?), to that between His two 
 chief powers, the power of showing grace 
 ii, e.g. De Somn. i. 163) or benefiting 
 fe, e.g. De Spec. Leg. i. 307), and that 
 of exercising rule, which includes punishing 
 (ftao-i\iKij t De Somn., loc. cit. : Ko\a<rnqpios, De 
 Spec. Leg., loc. cit.), often summed up in the 
 contrasted terms " beneficent goodness " and 
 "authority" (ayaOorw and efoiWa, e.g. De 
 Cherub. 27). The details in these discussions 
 are often far-fetched, but his essential view 
 emerges quite clearly. Each of these 
 aspects of the Divine Being, which are 
 combined in the Logos (De Cherub. 27), is 
 to be acknowledged with reverence, but the 
 "older" is that of beneficence. In speak- 
 ing of the sinners of the Patriarchal age, 
 he observes that, while many individuals 
 perished, God, " in order that the human race 
 
 might continue, mingles mercy [with judg- 
 144 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 ment], using it to benefit even the unworthy ; 
 and not only does he show mercy after 
 judging, but before judging he has mercy ; 
 for mercy is older with him [i.e. prior in his 
 thought] than penalty " (Quod Deus sit 
 immut. 76). How firmly rooted this concep- 
 tion is, appears from a fine passage (De Plant. 
 89), where he interprets the phrase "ever- 
 lasting God " (Gen. xxi. 33) as " him who does 
 not bestow grace at one time and withhold 
 it at another, but is always and continuously 
 the doer of kindness without interruption , . . 
 who omits no opportunity of benefiting, while 
 at the same time he is Lord, with the power 
 also to hurt." So inherent to God is the 
 bestowing of kindness, that even in the case 
 of those who have committed intolerable 
 wrongs, He desires to have intercession 
 made to Him on their behalf (De Mut. 
 Norn. 129). 
 
 The Divine Grace is conceived by our 
 author on the most spacious lines. Expand- 
 ing the words, " as for me, behold my covenant 
 is with them " (Gen. xvii. 4), he says : " There 
 
 are many different kinds of covenant which 
 K 145 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 bestow gracious benefits and gifts on those 
 worthy of them, but I myself am the highest 
 kind. ... I my self am the source and fountain 
 of all experiences of grace. For to some God 
 is wont to extend his benefits by means of 
 other channels, Dearth, water, air, sun, moon, 
 heaven, and other incorporeal powers, but 
 to others through himself alone, declaring 
 himself the portion of those who receive 
 him " (De Mut. Nom. 58 f.). All that exists, 
 in so far as it can benefit, is an expression of 
 the loving-kindness of God, imparted freely 
 to all His creatures. And so if one were to 
 ask, What is the principle (apxn) of the created 
 universe, the most accurate answer would be, 
 the kindness (ayaBorrj^ and grace of God 
 (Leg. Alleg. iii. 78). 
 
 But of supreme importance for human 
 beings is the recognition that their own highest 
 faculties are Divine gifts. Philo, as we 
 know, regards man's spiritual nature in its 
 supreme aspects as the in-breathing of the 
 breath of God, and, in a very real sense, 
 Conscience is, in his view, the energy of the 
 
 Divine Logos actually present in the soul. 
 146 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 " God," he declares, in a passage highly 
 relevant to our present discussion, " because 
 of his gentleness and love for men, desiring 
 to establish a shrine amongst us, found none 
 on earth more fitting than our reason " (De 
 Virtut. 1 88). But he is always sensitive to 
 the actual situation. Man, with his power of 
 self-determination, has misused his capacities. 
 In his shallowness of judgment he has been 
 allured by the superficial attractions of the 
 sense-life, especially by pleasure, which has 
 directed his strivings towards unworthy aims. 
 In this situation the grace of God shines forth 
 in all its splendour. " God, who is a lover of 
 giving ((/>tXo8o)/309, one of his favourite epithets 
 for God), bestows his blessings freely on all, 
 even on the imperfect, summoning them to 
 follow eagerly after virtue " (Leg. AIL i. 34). 
 Men's condition puts the loving-kindness of 
 God to a severe test. But God's grace and 
 mercy go far beyond the standard of mere 
 justice. His beneficent power is all-pervasive 
 (De Vita Mos. ii. (iii.) 238). The fitting 
 penalty for the human race, because of its 
 ingratitude towards Him, its Saviour and 
 147 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 Benefactor, would have been annihilation ; 
 but He, by reason of His gracious nature, 
 took pity and moderated their punishment 
 (De Op. M. 169). His purpose for men is 
 wholly good. He can, indeed, visit with 
 calamity, but it is His special property to 
 hold out blessings and to be beforehand with 
 His gifts. Nay, even when penalty is 
 deserved, God does not straightway visit it 
 upon the sinner, but gives time for repent- 
 ance and for the healing and amendment of 
 his fault (Leg. AIL iii. 105 f.). In a word, 
 His aim is nothing less than the redemption 
 of men. The Father, who has begotten the 
 soul, does not desire to leave it for ever 
 imprisoned, but, in His pity, to loose its 
 bonds and conduct it safely in its freedom 
 even to its mother-city, and not to cease until 
 the promises of His words are ratified by 
 actual deeds (De Somn. i. 181). 
 
 But at this point we are inevitably con- 
 fronted by the perennial problem of the 
 relation of the Divine Grace to human effort. 
 Philo has no systematic treatment of the 
 
 question, yet it is important to examine his 
 148 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 general attitude towards the facts. To begin 
 with, he is clear that all goodness in the soul 
 is due to the Divine operation. " It befits 
 God to plant and build up the virtues in the 
 soul : egoistic and impious is the mind which 
 imagines itself equal to God, and presumes 
 to be acting while it is really acted upon " 
 (Leg. All. i. 48 f.) ; "what soul ever suc- 
 ceeded in putting out of sight and annihilating 
 evil, save that to which God was revealed, 
 which he deemed worthy of his ineffable 
 mysteries?" (ibid. iii. 27). The progress of 
 the soul, from its beginnings, depends on 
 God's self-manifestation. In this whole 
 province there is a remarkable parallelism 
 between Philo and St. Paul. A most notable 
 example of the position which they may 
 almost be said to occupy in common appears 
 in De Migr. Abr. 30 ff. : "The fountain 
 from which blessings stream is our communion 
 (o-woSo?) with God who loves to give : this is 
 why he puts the seal upon his benefits by 
 saying, I will be with thee. What good 
 thing, then, could be lacking, when God who 
 
 never fails of achievement is present, with 
 149 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 the virgin-powers of his grace ? In that case 
 effort and toil and hard exertion are stilled, 
 and all that can benefit is imparted in abund- 
 ance. . . . The mind lets go its hold of those 
 energies which are at the command of its own 
 designs, and is, as it were, liberated from its 
 purposes by reason of the gifts rained upon 
 it in unceasing showers." The context, in- 
 deed, suggests that this description applies 
 primarily to the inward wrestling of the soul 
 with truth. But since in Philo no valid 
 distinction can be drawn between this search 
 and the personal yearning after God, it seems 
 legitimate to emphasise the striking resem- 
 blance to Paul as regards the cessation of 
 human effort and the complete dependence 
 of the soul on Divine aid. The position is 
 confirmed by such statements as De Mut. 
 Nom. 138: "There are few whose ears are 
 open to receive these sacred words which 
 teach that it belongs to God alone to sow and 
 to create (yewav) what is good." 
 
 Sufficient evidence has been adduced to 
 show that Paul's great watchword : " By 
 
 grace are ye saved, through faith, and that 
 150 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 not of yourselves, God's is the gift" (Eph. 
 ii. 8), can be rendered directly in terms of 
 Philo's thought, if we discount the Apostle's 
 definitely Christian background. Precisely 
 as in Paul's view, Philo regards man as hav- 
 ing nothing in which he can glory in God's 
 presence. Even anything good which he 
 achieves and Philo, like Paul, recognises 
 the importance of such achievement must 
 ultimately be ascribed to Divine influence. 
 For it is impossible for a human creature to 
 rid himself of his defilement. " What period 
 would suffice to wash away these stains ? 
 I cannot tell. . . . What eternity could 
 transform the impurity of a soul into a well- 
 ordered life ? Not even an eternity, but God 
 alone, to whom are possible the things which 
 with us are impossible " (De Spec. Leg. i. 
 281 f.). The words have an extraordinary 
 affinity with New Testament positions. If 
 we may regard them as expressing an under- 
 tone of religious feeling beginning to appear in 
 the more enlightened Judaism of the Diaspora, 
 we are indeed moving in an atmosphere in 
 which the way of the Lord is being prepared. 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 Now, the clause, "through faith," in Paul's 
 famous utterance, states the human condition 
 of the saving process. God's gift of grace 
 must not be mechanically conceived. The 
 manner of the Divine activity is not to force 
 an entrance into any heart. Apart from a 
 free and glad assent of the soul, that which 
 Paul calls Faith, there can be no real contact 
 between the grace of God and human need. 
 Philo, from his own standpoint, frankly 
 acknowledges this. He has various ways of 
 describing the condition of receptiveness to 
 which the Divine generosity can make its 
 appeal. Once and again he finds the condi- 
 tion fulfilled in the suppliant attitude of the 
 soul. " When pleasure," he says, "loses its 
 power, and the cause of our shocking and 
 wanton life has in a sense died, we weep 
 over and deplore our former career, because 
 we preferred pleasure to virtue and linked a 
 mortal to an immortal life. Then the only 
 Gracious, taking pity on our unbroken con- 
 fusion, draws near to our suppliant souls " 
 (Quod del. pot. 95). Similarly, "God will 
 
 perform the work which belongs to him, 
 152 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 having proclaimed release and freedom to the 
 souls which supplicate him " (Quis Rer. Div. 
 H. 273). Often, in this connection, it is the 
 reaction from an unworthy life, the recoil of 
 the soul, which affords its opportunity to the 
 grace of God. " When God is gracious," 
 says Philo, " he makes all things easy [read- 
 ing efevpapi&i with Cohn]. Now he becomes 
 gracious to those who feel shame and exchange 
 dissoluteness for self-control and reproach a 
 culpable life and loathe the base phantoms 
 which they impressed upon their souls, who 
 are eager for the quieting of passions and 
 haste after calm and peace of life " (De Praem. 
 et Poen. 116). So, too, in an important 
 passage (De Somn. i. 9), which we quoted 
 in discussing Repentance, he emphasises the 
 grace of Him, who alone is gracious, to 
 those who lay bare their hidden thoughts and 
 deeds, which are already exposed to the 
 glance of the Father of all. 
 
 There are certain aspects of the Divine 
 
 Grace which are singled out by Philo. That 
 
 which we first note has an arresting kinship 
 
 with the New Testament outlook. "Very 
 
 153 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 aptly [Moses says that] their supplication 
 reached God. Now it would not have 
 reached, if he who invited it had not been 
 gracious. But some souls he goes out to 
 meet : ' I will come to thee and will bless 
 thee ' (Ex. xx. 24). You see how large is the 
 grace of the Cause, who anticipates our hesita- 
 tion and goes out to bestow the completest 
 benefits upon the soul " (Leg. Alleg. iii. 215). 
 Here we are not merely reminded of Paul 
 but of Jesus Himself, and especially of the 
 marvellous delineation of the Father in the 
 parable of the Lost Son. Indeed, Philo 
 shows himself of the lineage of the great 
 prophet Hosea in his emphasis on the un- 
 wearying ardour of the Divine pity. God is 
 the Shepherd of the Soul. His " watchful 
 oversight is ... the first and only reason why 
 the parts of the soul are never left without 
 attendance but find a blameless and unfailing 
 good Shepherd " (De Agric. 49 f.). There 
 is, in short, in the nature of God no limit to 
 the outflow of His generosity towards men. 
 More than once this affluence of the Divine 
 bounty provokes in Philo an outburst of 
 154 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 praise. " O thou Lover of giving," he ex- 
 claims, " without stint are the gifts of thy 
 grace, having no limits or boundaries or end, 
 like fountains which pour forth streams too 
 plentiful to be borne away " (Quis Rer. 
 Div. H. 31). The only limit to the grace of 
 God lies in the narrowness of men's capacity 
 to receive it. Thus Philo lays down as the 
 normative principle for human beneficence 
 that which God imposes upon Himself 
 because of human limitations : " Freely give 
 not all that thou canst, but all that the needy 
 is able to receive " (De Post. Cain. 142). 
 "For that which has come into being," he 
 observes in the same passage (ibid. 145), 
 " is never without a share of God's gracious 
 gifts . . . but is unable to bear their abundant 
 and lavish current. Wherefore, desiring us 
 to be profited by his bounties, he measures 
 them according to the capacity of the 
 recipients." Philo enlarges on the theme in 
 dealing with Moses' prayer (Ex. xxxiii. 
 13 f.) for a vision of God, and the Divine 
 answer to his request. " I freely bestow that 
 which befits him who is to receive : for not 
 155 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 all that I might easily give is it possible for 
 man to take. Therefore I hold forth to him 
 who is worthy of my grace all the gifts he is 
 able to receive. But for a complete appre- 
 hension of me there is no room, not only 
 in human nature, but even in all earth and 
 heaven. Know thyself, then, and be not 
 carried away by impulses and desires be- 
 yond thy powers ... for in all attainable 
 good thou shalt have a share " (De Spec. Leg. 
 i. 43 f.). One further aspect of Philo's view 
 of Divine Grace may be pointed out before 
 we leave this phase of our discussion. It js 
 important, because it reminds us that Philo, so 
 far from being absorbed merely in theoretical 
 inquiries, has his gaze firmly fixed on the 
 higher claims of practical life. He is laying 
 stress on the proper use of the gifts, often 
 unexpected, which men receive from God. 
 "For," he says, "the generous bounties of 
 the Supreme Ruler, which he bestows on 
 individuals, are for the general well-being : 
 not that when they have received them they 
 may hide them or misuse them to the hurt of 
 
 others, but that, putting them into the 
 156 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 common stock, as at a public feast, they may 
 invite as many as they can to their use and 
 enjoyment" (De Virtut. 169). 
 
 (6) Mediation 
 
 The statments we have collected from 
 Philo to illustrate his conception of the Grace 
 of God are remarkable for their directness, 
 simplicity, and freedom from technical phrase- 
 ology. That is thoroughly characteristic of 
 the man. When he discloses the profoundest 
 realities of his religion, he usually lays aside 
 metaphysical and psychological arguments. 
 But recognising, as we must, the constant 
 emphasis he places upon the transcendence 
 of God, and his invariable assumption that 
 the Existent cannot come into direct contact 
 with the world of created things, we are not 
 surprised to find the idea of Mediation be- 
 tween God and man at the heart of his 
 thought. 
 
 The philosophical drift of his age, which 
 affected most of the serious thinkers on re- 
 ligion in the centuries immediately preceding 
 and following the birth of Jesus, favoured this 
 157 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 doctrine. The Ideas of Plato, and the \6yoi 
 o-TTepfjLarLKoi (generative rational forces) of the 
 Stoics, both of which played so prominent a 
 part in the later philosophy, were already con- 
 ceived, especially in the more popular philo- 
 sophical theology, as powers in a sense 
 mediating between the Absolute God or the 
 First Cause and the universe. Parallel move- 
 ments may be traced in every direction. The 
 Stoics themselves had, by means of allegory, 
 used the popular mythology to establish the 
 idea of subordinate spiritual powers which 
 were manifestations to men of the Divine. 
 The Hellenised theology of Egypt had, on 
 similar allegorical lines, attempted to com- 
 bine the myth of a creative Word with the 
 Divine Reason pervading all things. And 
 the Hermetic literature, also of Egyptian 
 origin, makes Hermes, who represents the 
 Egyptian Thoth the amanuensis of the gods, 
 the god of all wisdom, who has invented " the 
 words of God " (i.e. the written characters) 
 the bearer of a Divine revelation which he 
 communicates to disciples that they may 
 
 diffuse it abroad. 
 
 158 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 It may be said without undue rashness 
 that Philo must have come into touch 
 with all these various currents of thought. 
 But he was exposed to others at least as 
 important proceeding from his ancestral 
 Jewish faith. The Alexandrian Wisdom 
 of Solomon, written not long before his time, 
 reveals the place given in cultivated Jewish 
 minds to Wisdom, conceived almost as a 
 Divine personality, subordinate to God, but 
 "a breath of the power of God/' "an image 
 of his goodness," which "has power to do all 
 things/' " renews all things," and " entering 
 consecrated souls makes them friends of God 
 and prophets, for God loves none but him who 
 isjn fellowship with wisdom" ( Wisd. vii. 256".). 
 But while we know this conception to have 
 been influential in Philo's immediate environ- 
 ment, the idea of mediation between God and 
 the world had taken further shape in Jewish 
 religion. A prominent figure in Old Testa- 
 ment tradition was that of the "angel" or 
 "messenger" of Jahweh, through whom the 
 Divine mind and purpose was disclosed to 
 men. Angelology had been developed to an 
 159 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 extraordinary extent within Judaism between 
 the Exile and Philo's time, perhaps chiefly 
 under the influence of Babylon and Persia ; 
 and the stress laid upon the Holiness of 
 God in the post-exilic community gave an 
 impetus to a large number of personifications 
 of the Divine. The actual evidence for some 
 of these belongs to a period later than Philo. 
 But when we take into account their Old 
 Testament basis, and remember that by his 
 time the transcendence of God was a dominat- 
 ing idea both in Palestinian and Alexandrian 
 Judaism, it is in no way improbable that he 
 was acquainted with them at some stage in 
 their evolution. Thus, the Rabbinic hypo- 
 stasis of Memra, the Creative Word of God, 
 has its roots in passages of Genesis (e.g. i. 3, 
 6, 9) and Psalms (e.g. cxlvii. 15) which de- 
 scribe the efficacy of the Divine utterance. 
 The Shekinah, which is a sort of concrete 
 embodiment of the Divine Presence, repre- 
 sents, of course, the " glory " of Jahweh, 
 described in the Old Testament as filling the 
 Tabernacle and the Temple. Ezekiel's com- 
 plex vision (chap, i.) became a favourite subject 
 1 60 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 of speculation in various circles of Judaism, 
 and the winged creatures which bore the 
 moving throne of the Almighty were ex- 
 plained as the powers of God. But from the 
 description of the vision, the living creatures 
 might be viewed as a unity, as well as in 
 their individuality. When so regarded, the 
 unified appearance, of which the several faces 
 were aspects, was named in esoteric Judaism 
 "the charioteer." It is impossible to avoid 
 the supposition that Philo was directly influ- 
 enced by this group of speculations, when he 
 designates the Logos "charioteer of the Divine 
 powers" (De Fuga, 101). Further, asSiegfried 
 has cogently pointed out (Philo von Alex- 
 andria, p. 221 f.), the dignity of the High 
 Priest had been immensely enhanced in the 
 post-exilic community, so that to a degree 
 never before conceived he stood as mediator 
 between God and the people. The efficacy 
 of his suppliant prayers is emphasised in 
 several Rabbinic treatises, and also his 
 intimacy with the All- Holy. A striking 
 comment on the fact is Philo's ascription of 
 
 the title "High Priest " to the Logos (e.g. De 
 L 161 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 Fuga, 108 ff. ; De Migr. Abr. 102). And 
 it is probably legitimate to regard this as one 
 of the factors which set the Priesthood of 
 Christ in the centre of the Epistle to the 
 Hebrews, a document whose Alexandrian 
 and Philonic associations are evident through- 
 out. 
 
 Philo's attempts to bridge the gulf which 
 he assumes between a God who is pure Being 
 and the world of Becoming circle round the 
 conception of the Logos, who is God's 
 Thought or Reason ; the powers (Svm/*a?) of 
 God, which are manifestations of His energy, 
 operating in the universe ; and angels, a 
 considerably vaguer category. It lies outside 
 our purpose to discuss these categories in 
 their metaphysical bearings. The Logos- 
 hypothesis itself, as it appears in Philo, is full 
 of confusion. This is no doubt partly due to 
 its composition from heterogeneous elements, 
 Platonic dualism, Stoic monism, and Jewish 
 monotheism, modified by the later belief in 
 hypostases of God, of which the most notable 
 was Wisdom. In part, it depends on the 
 
 fluctuating boundary in ancient thought 
 162 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 between personality and personification, and 
 on Philo's own tendency to glide from what 
 he conceived as truth to symbols of truth. 
 To some extent it results from his failure in 
 constructive power. 
 
 A few words on the cosmic significance of 
 these Divine energies will serve as an intro- 
 duction to their religious functions as sug- 
 gested by Philo. Probably his most inclusive 
 description of the Logos in this realm is that 
 of " the ideal world," " the image of God," the 
 pattern according to which the perceptible 
 universe has been fashioned (e.g. De Op. M. 
 24 f.). As the Logos is the " image " of God, 
 so par excellence is human reason the " image " 
 of the Logos (e.g. Leg. Alleg. iii. 96). Not 
 only has the Logos been God's instrument 
 (opyavov) in creation, but he is, so to speak, 
 the "helm" (omf) by which the Almighty 
 Steersman pilots the universe (De Migr. Abr. 
 6). A metaphor which he is fond of apply- 
 ing to the Logos is that of the Divine seal, 
 by which each created thing is stamped and 
 receives its permanent quality (De Fuga, 1 2 f.). 
 Varying the details of the comparison, he 
 163 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 speaks of the rational soul as stamped 
 by the seal of God, whose impression is 
 the eternal Logos (De Plant. 18). Roughly 
 speaking, these descriptions tally with the 
 conception of the Thought of God, more or 
 less abstracted from His pure Being, and 
 placed beside Him in a semi-personified form. 
 Philo usually conceives the powers as sub- 
 ordinate to the Logos. Thus he speaks of 
 God as having completely filled His Divine 
 Logos with incorporeal powers (De Somn. i. 
 62). But perhaps the clearest instance is 
 Qu. in Exod. ii. 68 (p. 515, Aucher), where in 
 discussing the relation of the two primary 
 Divine " powers," the gracious creative power 
 (#09) and the regal (/cu/no?), to the Logos, he 
 speaks of these as " flowing out from the 
 Logos as from a spring," and then proceeds 
 to show how other powers emanate from 
 them. These Powers, which he classifies 
 variously (e.g. Legal, ad Gaium, 6, 7), and of 
 which we have just mentioned the most rep- 
 resentative, he describes as stretched from 
 the roots of the earth to the confines of 
 
 heaven, holding together the entire universe 
 164 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 (De Migr. Abr. 181). As in the case of the 
 Logos, he so objectifies the Powers as over 
 against God, that their inferiority is clearly 
 manifest. Thus God uses them for the 
 punishment of sin, a function unseemly for 
 Himself. They were His instruments in 
 creating the mortal elements of the soul, as 
 contrasted with the rational. In some sense, 
 also, they are responsible for the presence of 
 conceptions of evil as well as of good in the 
 human soul (De Fiiga, 66 ff.). 
 
 Let us now turn to the more practical 
 aspects of these mediating agencies, which 
 give them an important place in the religious 
 and moral experiences of the soul. Br^hier 
 (op. cit. p. 100) is true to the facts when he 
 observes that in order to understand the real 
 position of the Logos in Philo, we must leave 
 on one side philosophical and cosmological 
 theories and consider God and the Logos as 
 objects of worship. In the progress of the 
 soul towards the Highest, the apprehension 
 of the Logos is an intermediate stage which 
 must be passed through. " It is a boon," Philo 
 says, " for perishable mortals to have medi- 
 165 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 ating and arbitrating Logoi (i.e. rational Divine 
 powers), because of their own awe and shrink- 
 ing before the Lord of all " (De Somn. i. 142). 
 This is no mere dread of punishment. It 
 means their incapacity to receive God's over- 
 powering and unmixed blessings, when these 
 are given by His own hand (ibid. 143). In 
 these paragraphs we are face to face with a 
 characteristic standpoint of post-exilic Juda- 
 ism. " God can only be grasped by means 
 of the powers which accompany and follow 
 him. For these do not present his essence 
 but only his existence, to be gathered from 
 what is accomplished by him " (De Post. Cain. 
 169). In distinguishing between the two 
 instances of the word " place " in Gen. xxii. 
 3 f., Philo remarks that "the man who is 
 under the guidance of wisdom arrives at the 
 first two places mentioned, having found the 
 Divine Logos who is the crown and goal of 
 satisfaction " (De Somn. \. 66), and a few sen- 
 tences later he speaks of the Logos as sent 
 forth to heal and completely cure the ailments 
 of the soul. Perhaps the most fundamental 
 
 passage for his general working conception is 
 166 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 Quis Rer. Div. H. 205: " The Father, who 
 has begotten all things, granted as his 
 choicest privilege to his chief messenger and 
 most august Logos, that he should stand in 
 the midst between the Creator and the created. 
 Now he is, on the one hand, always the sup- 
 pliant for transient mortals in presence of the 
 Immortal, and the ambassador of the Ruler 
 to his subject. Thus he rejoices because of 
 the privilege, and prides himself on it ... 
 being neither uncreated like God nor created 
 like you, but standing between the two ex- 
 tremes as a pledge to both, to him who 
 created as an assurance that created beings 
 will never wholly rebel or revolt, choosing 
 confusion rather than order, and in the case 
 of the creature to give him the bright hope 
 that the gracious God will never ignore his 
 own work." This remarkable utterance 
 reaches the heart of Philo's conception of 
 the Logos. What has further to be said is 
 simply an expansion of its ideas in various 
 directions. 
 
 It will not help us much to discuss, in the 
 
 light of such statements, how far Philo regards 
 167 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 the Logos as in some sense, a " personality," 
 distinct from God, whose Thought or Reason 
 or Utterance he is. We have already referred 
 to the vagueness of the boundary in ancient 
 thought between personality and personifica- 
 tion. In the New Testament precisely the 
 same problem arises ; as, e.g., in the Pauline 
 Epistles with reference to the relation 
 between the Spirit and the exalted Lord. 
 And it is needless to recall the numerous 
 controversies in the early Church which 
 sprang directly out of this region. Philo- 
 sophical or religious thinkers, in attempting 
 to make any affirmations at all within the 
 realm of spirit, are compelled to formulate 
 such distinctions, although reflection at once 
 reminds them that they are working with 
 anthropomorphic categories, and that this 
 picture-language must be recognised for 
 what it is, an inadequate effort to express the 
 inexpressible. Philo is no more and no less 
 successful in his efforts than Christian 
 theologies or idealistic philosophies. But it 
 can scarcely be doubted that his particular 
 
 differentiation of the Logos from the Supreme 
 168 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 God had an exceptional influence on the 
 subsequent Christology of the Church. 
 
 Philo gives prominence to the idea that 
 those mediators, whether Logos, 8iW/*et9, or 
 ayyeXoi, come to the soul's assistance in all its 
 higher aspirations. "He who follows after 
 God," he says, "has . . . as companions on 
 his journey those rational powers (\6yoi,) who 
 accompany God, who are commonly called 
 angels. . . . For as long as he is not per- 
 fected, he has the Divine Logos to show him 
 the way. . . . But when he has reached the 
 summit of knowledge, having run eagerly he 
 will equal in swiftness him who formerly led 
 the way. For both will become attendants 
 of the omnipotent God " (De Migr. Abr. 
 173 ff.). Indeed he implies that their very 
 function is to consider and aid the spiritual 
 needs of man, " For help," he observes, "a 
 succouring power waits in readiness in God's 
 presence, and the Ruler himself draws nearer 
 for the benefit of such as are worthy of 
 receiving benefits " (ibid. 57). In the passage 
 already quoted as specially typical, the Logos 
 
 is described as "a suppliant for transient 
 169 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 mortals." This is an aspect which occurs 
 more than once. 1 And we cannot help find- 
 ing traces of its influence in the primary 
 place assigned in " Hebrews " to the work of 
 intercession in the priesthood of Christ. 
 
 In one important place (De Con/us. Ling. 
 146) God's " first-born Logos " is described as 
 "a being of many names." We shall glance 
 at some of these, from the point of view 
 of religious significance. Commenting on 
 Gen. xliii. n (LXX). Philo asks: "How 
 could you hesitate, my friends, to hate war 
 and love peace, you who are called by the 
 name of the same father, not a mortal but an 
 immortal, a Divine man, who, being the 
 Logos of the Eternal, is himself necessarily 
 imperishable?" (De. Con/. Ling. 41). Now, 
 whatever shade of meaning may have been 
 here attached to the term Logos in Philo's 
 
 1 We entirely disagree with Drummond's position, that 
 " in all these passages we are concerned only with certain 
 functions of human reason and speech," and that the term 
 iKfTTis excludes any idea of intercession (Philo Judaeus, ii. 
 236, 235). The latter statement seems quite arbitrary when 
 viewed in the light of the context of these passages. And 
 to us it appears that no statements in Philo more clearly 
 suggest the idea of personality than those in question. 
 170 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 mind : whether the idea of the Divine 
 Reason in man predominates, or that of a 
 vicegerent of the Eternal, who bridges the 
 chasm between the seen and the unseen, it is 
 plain that such a usage must lead even 
 unconsciously to the personalising of the 
 conception. We can never determine what 
 point in the process has been reached, but 
 the more powerfully the notion of religious 
 value is present, the more concrete will be 
 the shape which the Logos idea assumes. 
 An illuminating instance of how the various 
 nuances of the term shade off into each other 
 appears in De Somn. i. 103 ff. Philo begins 
 by observing that Logos, obviously in the 
 sense of " reason," but sometimes gliding into 
 that of " speech," is God's choicest gift to 
 man, his "bulwark," his "bodyguard," his 
 "protagonist," the power that "furthers his 
 aspirations." He is the "saving remedy for 
 the passions of the soul," a "counsellor and 
 champion " whose presence gives joy and 
 rest. But at the close of the passage, all 
 that has been affirmed is merged in the 
 
 figure of the " Divine Logos," whom the 
 171 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 ascetic soul, renouncing itself, " awaits as a 
 visitant coming invisibly from without." All 
 through the paragraph we are inevitably 
 reminded of the New Testament conception 
 of the indwelling Spirit, which often can 
 scarcely be distinguished from the renewed 
 nature of the Christian, but at other times is 
 viewed quite separately. Such a distinction 
 appears plainly in De Somn. i. 86 : " The 
 Logos of God when he visits our earthly 
 system of things helps and succours those 
 who have kinship with goodness and tend 
 in that direction (cf. John iii. 21), so as to 
 provide for them a complete refuge and 
 salvation, but on the enemies of good he 
 launches ruin and incurable destruction.^ 
 Here the Logos is set over against God and 
 men as the representative of the Eternal, 
 acting for men's highest well-being. Once, 
 in a discussion of the incomprehensibility of 
 the Divine Nature, the " Logos-interpreter" 
 (cf. John i. 1 8) receives the remarkable appel- 
 lation " God of the imperfect," as opposed 
 to the Eternal, who is God " of the wise and 
 
 perfect " (Leg. Alleg. iii. 207), a class which, 
 172 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 probably for Philo as for the Stoics, remained 
 no more than an ideal. Perhaps nowhere is 
 the religious colour of the Logos-conception 
 more visible than when he describes it, quite 
 incidentally, as " the heavenly, incorruptible 
 food of the soul that longs for the vision of 
 God " (Quis Rer. Div. H. 79), or when he 
 compares it to a river. " As from the fountain 
 of wisdom, the Divine Logos flows down to 
 refresh and water the Olympian and heavenly 
 plants of souls that love goodness, a kind of 
 Paradise." This is " the river of God, full 
 of water," referred to in Ps. Ixv. 9, "a 
 stream of wisdom, which makes glad the 
 city of God " (Ps. xlvi. 5), "the soul of the 
 wise, in which God is said to walk to and fro 
 as in a city" (De Somn. ii. 242 ff.). 
 
 We have barely mentioned the important 
 fact that Philo sometimes identifies the Logos 
 with Wisdom. Referring, e.g., to " goodness " 
 as the genuine virtue, he declares that its 
 source is the wisdom of God. "That," he 
 adds, " is the Logos of God " (Leg. Alleg. i. 
 65). This identification cannot surprise us, 
 as Philo was, of course, familiar with the 
 173 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 commanding place occupied by the hypostasis 
 of " Wisdom" in the deeper thought of his 
 Jewish contemporaries. It is possibly true 
 that Greek influence accounts for the over- 
 shadowing of the latter conception by the 
 former in his writings. But this influence 
 may have been indirect rather than im- 
 mediate in his case, inasmuch as the term 
 Logos, as a mediating idea, covered a far 
 wider range of relations than Sophia, and 
 thus more adequately met the needs of his 
 thinking. So far as their range is the same, 
 the parallelism could scarcely be closer, and 
 we cannot help believing that Philo's own 
 extension of the application of Logos in 
 certain directions was made possible by his 
 acquaintance with the mediating function of 
 Sophia in the Wisdom-literature of the Jews. 
 One special use of Logos, although possess- 
 ing affinities with that of Wisdom, may per- 
 haps be traced more directly to his Egyptian 
 environment, in which Divine " words " were 
 endowed with unique potency. In a few 
 passages he uses it to describe the all-effica- 
 cious utterance of God. Thus, in referring 
 J74 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 to the account of Moses' death in Deut. 
 xxxiv., where it is ascribed (ver. 5) to 
 the "word of the Lord," he says by that 
 4 'word the whole universe was created, that 
 you may learn that God counts the wise man 
 of equal value with the world, by the same 
 Logos both producing the totality of things, 
 and leading the perfect man from his earthly 
 environment to himself" (De Sacr. Ab. et C. 
 8). This and other instances are, however, 
 isolated from the main trend of his usage, 
 and he goes out of his way to assert that the 
 Divine utterance has no point of comparison 
 with the human (Quod Deus sit immut. 82 f.), 
 thus preserving for it its fundamental signifi- 
 cance of the ideal form which brings coherence 
 into the universe. Yet we can easily under- 
 stand how, in spite of this, a Jewish mind, 
 accustomed from the Old Testament to the 
 idea of God's all-powerful Word, might find in 
 Philo's usage a significance which the author 
 himself had barely suggested. That would 
 be all the more likely if he were already 
 sensitive to those personifications of the 
 Divine Wisdom which represented her as 
 175 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 pleading with men and offering them instruc- 
 tion in the name of God (e.g. Prov. viii. 
 and ix.). 
 
 We must bear all these considerations in 
 mind when we place beside Philo's conception 
 of the Logos that which belongs to the Pro- 
 logue of the Fourth Gospel Dr. Rendel 
 Harris, with remarkable skill and contagious 
 enthusiasm, has tried to prove that the writer 
 is entirely dependent on the Sophia of the 
 Wisdom-literature, and he works out the 
 influence of this conception through one and 
 another of the Early Christian Fathers, as 
 well as in St. Paul. No doubt he has suc- 
 ceeded in unravelling one strand of a varie- 
 gated pattern. But the other threads must 
 not be ignored. The demonstration of many 
 remarkable parallels to Sophia in the famous 
 Prologue by no means excludes Alexandrian 
 features, for these parallels certainly came 
 within Philo's horizon. No conclusive argu- 
 ment has been as yet produced to account 
 for the Fourth Evangelist's choice of Logos 
 in preference to Sophia. And that choice, in 
 
 the light of Philo's employment of the term, 
 176 
 
GOD'S APPROACH TO MAN 
 
 affords a strong presumption in favour of 
 Alexandrian affinities. The progress of 
 research in Hellenistic thought, whether 
 Jewish, Pagan, or Christian, continually puts 
 us on our guard against the tendency to 
 trace kinship along a single line. Syn- 
 cretism is the sign-manual of the period. 
 And Ephesus, the home of Heraclitus, with 
 his conception of Logos as the "compre- 
 hensive principle of order in the unified 
 world-process," was not likely to remain in- 
 different to the far-reaching developments 
 of the idea, whether among the Stoics or in 
 Philo. But one aspect of the question is not 
 open to dispute. To Philo, as to any of his 
 pagan contemporaries, it would have ap- 
 peared an inversion of all values, whether 
 religious or metaphysical, that the Evan- 
 gelist should have dared the tremendous 
 assertion: "The Logos became flesh, and 
 dwelt among us." 
 
 M 177 
 
CHAPTER VI 
 UNION WITH GOD 
 
 ALL careful readers of Philo must agree 
 with the statement of Windisch, that 
 11 Religion is for him an inward impetus of 
 the soul, a quest for and delight in Divine 
 revelations, a craving after fellowship with 
 God, an experience of God" (Die Frommig- 
 keit P kilos, p. 80). How to attain com- 
 munion with the Unseen is the question 
 which absorbs his spirit. Now the very 
 presuppositions of his thinking about human 
 nature encourage him to press towards his 
 goal. For if anything can be called funda- 
 mental in his view of the constitution of 
 things, it is the conviction which he assigns 
 to " those who have gone deep into the 
 meaning of the laws" that "God gave man 
 as the best of his gifts a share with himself 
 in his rational nature" (De Op. M. 77). 
 178 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 Man starts, therefore, with a real kinship 
 to God. It is inevitable that, in proportion 
 as the Divine element asserts itself, he will 
 strive after more complete union with the 
 Fount of his being. 
 
 (a) Fatherhood and Sonship 
 
 In this connection it is worth while briefly 
 to examine Philo's application of the cate- 
 gories of Fatherhood and Sonship to the 
 relation between God and men, as that may 
 shed some light on the background of the 
 New Testament. He is fond of ascribing 
 to God the name of " Father," and this 
 under various aspects. By far the most 
 fundamental of these is that of Creator. 
 "The mind of the unseen," he says, "has 
 begotten the whole : but the Creator is 
 superior to the created. Hence he cannot 
 be borne along in the inferior, apart from 
 the unfitness of a father being contained in 
 his son : rather must the son grow through 
 the care of his father" (De Migr. Abr. 193). 
 Similarly, in De Cherub. 49, God is named 
 " Father of all" as " having begotten them." 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 We do not need to look for the origin of this 
 conception, as some scholars have done, to 
 the Platonic notion of "God" as Father of 
 the universe. It is, of course, familiar from 
 the Old Testament, e.g., Deut. xxxii. 6 : 
 " Do ye thus requite the Lord. ... Is not 
 he thy father that formed thee ? Hath 
 he not made thee and established thee " ; 
 Mai. ii. 10 : " Have we not all one father ? 
 Hath not God created us ? " Isa. Ixiv. 8 : 
 " But now, O Lord, thou art our father ; 
 we are the clay, and thou our potter ; and 
 we are all the work of thy hand." 
 
 We do not clearly understand what 
 Principal Drummond means by saying that 
 when Philo represents man as a " son " of 
 God, he gives it an explanation " which 
 reduces it to an ordinary figure of speech," 
 and that "the term is used as a designation 
 of spiritual worth, and is not connected with 
 the ontological relations of man" (Philo 
 Judaeus, ii. 281-282). Can it ever be fruit- 
 fully used in the province of religious thought 
 except as "a designation of spiritual worth " ? 
 
 If we attempt to regard it under the category 
 1 80 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 of "ontological relations," can we arrive any- 
 where ? Even Jesus, for whom the conception 
 is so central, has no interest in " ontological 
 relations." " Love your enemies," He enjoins 
 upon His followers, "and pray for them that 
 persecute you, that you may become sons 
 of your Father who is in heaven " (Matt, 
 v. 44 f.). This, surely, must be called "a 
 designation of spiritual worth." Indeed, 
 one of the most interesting passages in 
 Philo bearing upon the subject has some 
 affinities with that famous utterance. 
 "Those," he says, "who act upon their 
 knowledge of the One," a phrase explained 
 in what follows as "estimating the noble 
 alone to be good," "are fittingly called sons 
 of God, as Moses also acknowledges in the 
 words, ' ye are sons of the Lord God ' 
 (Deut. xiv. i), and 'God who begat them' 
 (Deut. xxxii. 18), and 'Is not this thy 
 Father'" (ibid.) (De Conf. Ling. 145). But 
 this he regards as a difficult achievement, 
 to be reached by stages. Therefore he adds : 
 " But even if a man be not yet actually worthy 
 
 of being called a son of God, let him aim at 
 181 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 being ranked in that relation to the Logos, 
 God's first-born son, the oldest of angelic 
 beings" (ibid. 146). Like Jesus, Philo seeks 
 to raise the mind from earthly to heavenly 
 relationships. "Why should we remember 
 only our human father? We have the un- 
 created, immortal, Eternal " (De Jos. 265). 
 " The law," he says, "confirms my sugges- 
 tion when it declares that those who do what 
 is acceptable . . . and noble are sons of God, 
 for it declares, Ye are sons of the Lord your 
 God, obviously indicating that they are to be 
 deemed worthy of such providence and solici- 
 tude as a father bestows. Now this care will 
 differ as greatly from human care, I believe, 
 as he who cares differs [from a human father]" 
 (De Spec. Leg. i. 318). A very illuminating 
 utterance, in view of the matter we have been 
 discussing, is Quaest. in Gen. i. 92 (p. 66, 
 Aucher): "Sometimes, indeed, he[Moses] calls 
 the angels sons of God, seeing that they were 
 not made incorporeal by any mortal man, for 
 they are spirits without bodies. But with 
 preference that great teacher names sons of 
 
 God the noblest of men, those endowed with 
 182 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 virtue." Here Philo makes his position plain, 
 and it certainly approaches the standpoint of 
 the New Testament. Recognising, then, 
 that we can only interpret such a relation- 
 ship ethically and spiritually, we find real 
 religious significance in his comment on the 
 well-known words of Gen. xviii. 17, " Shall 
 I hide from Abraham my friend (TOO QiXov pov, 
 not in known MSS of LXX) ?" " He who 
 possesses this portion has passed beyond the 
 limits of human well-being : for he alone is 
 high-born who can inscribe God as his 
 Father and has become his only adopted 
 son" (De Sobr. 56). It would be easy to 
 trace the parallel between such an utterance 
 and some of those in which St. Paul sets 
 forth the unique privileges which belong to 
 " adoption" in the Christian sense. We 
 cannot describe a relation of this kind by 
 any other term than " personal," and so, 
 mainly in virtue of his Old Testament con- 
 ception of God, Philo has something more 
 intimate in view than the Stoics when they 
 designated the " wise man " as a son of God. 
 It is from this standpoint that he can speak 
 
 183 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 of "the Father and Saviour" as " having 
 pity" on the soul that yearns to behold Him 
 (De Praem. et Poen. 39). But while we have 
 pointed out affinities in this realm of thought 
 between Philo and the New Testament, we 
 fully recognise that his tendency to resolve 
 God into hypostases has detracted from the 
 unity and power of an otherwise most impres- 
 sive Theistic conception. 1 
 
 (b) The Spirit of God 
 
 It comes natural to those who approach 
 the great Jewish thinker from a New Testa- 
 ment point of view to ask what place he assigns 
 to the Spirit of God in his analysis of the 
 process by which the human soul strives to 
 attain fellowship with the Divine. We have 
 seen that he does recognise, although far less 
 prominently than the New Testament writers 
 who have caught the inspiration of Jesus, the 
 possibility of a filial relation between man 
 and God. Is this in any way associated, as 
 in the New Testament, with a doctrine of 
 
 1 See Windisch, op. cit. pp. 97, 98. On the background of 
 in Philo, see esp. J. Kroll, op. cit. pp. 30-32. 
 184 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 the Spirit ? Or, does the conception of the 
 Spirit exercise any important influence on 
 Philo's idea of communion between the finite 
 and the Infinite ? We certainly cannot accept 
 off-hand Dr. Bigg's unqualified statement that 
 " the doc trine of the Holy Spirit . . . has no 
 place in his system" (Christian Platonists of 
 Alexandria, p. 25). The evidence fails to 
 justify it. But an examination of the facts 
 may bring out some interesting features of 
 Philo's view. 
 
 One of his fundamental positions is that 
 man could have formed no conception of 
 God, had God not breathed into that part of 
 his nature which was endowed with higher 
 potentialities His own " breath "or " spirit" 
 (rrvevpa). Thus, he says, " there comes about 
 a union (ei/ox?) of the three," i.e. of God, the 
 human vow, and the Divine Trvevpa (Leg. 
 Alleg. i. 37 f.). This, of course, represents 
 man's highest capacity, whether or not it 
 be afterwards developed. It cannot be 
 compared with the specifically Pauline use 
 of TTvevpa, but seems closely akin to what the 
 Apostle calls vow or o eW avOp^iro^. Its pre- 
 
 \ 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 dominant characteristics appear to be rational. 
 It is the essence of the " governing element" 
 in human nature, and he identifies it with 
 \oyiar/ji6<}, reason (Quis Rer. Div. //. 55 ff.). 
 In another place he speaks in notable terms 
 of the " rational soul " of man as " the 
 genuine coinage of that Divine and invisible 
 spirit, marked and stamped by the seal of 
 God, whose impress is the eternal Logos " 
 (De Plant. 18). That is to say, the rational 
 element in the soul is the stamp on human 
 nature of the Divine Spirit, the impress of 
 the Logos, which cannot here be distinguished 
 from the Trvev^a of God. On the same lines, 
 the Divine part of man, " the noblest aspect 
 of the soul which is called vovs and XOYO?, 
 mind and reason," he designates by the 
 general description of TO irvev^a (Quod del. 
 pot. 83). In these instances we are not 
 dealing with an attainment in the religious 
 life, but with an original endowment. But 
 in the most interesting and elaborate of all 
 the passages in which he discusses the 
 Divine Spirit, he reveals a wider outlook. 
 
 Discussing the statement of Gen. vi. 3 
 186 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 (LXX) : " My spirit shall not dwell with 
 men for ever, because they are flesh," he 
 comments : " He does remain sometimes, but 
 he does not dwell always with most of us. 
 Who indeed is so irrational ... as never 
 either voluntarily or involuntarily to receive 
 a notion (evvoiav) of the Highest ? Nay, even 
 over the reprobate there often hovers the 
 impression (<f>avTacria) of the good, but they 
 cannot grasp it and keep it by them. For 
 it vanishes at once, turning away from 
 those . . . who have abandoned law and 
 right. Indeed, it would never have visited 
 them, except to convict them sharply of 
 preferring the base to the noble. Now, 
 according to one usage, the air that rises 
 from the earth is called Divine irvev^a . . . 
 but according to another it means that pure 
 (a/cr)pa,Tos) knowledge in which every wise 
 man fully shares." He proceeds to illustrate 
 this aspect of the Divine Spirit by the special 
 equipment of wisdom and understanding 
 bestowed upon Bezaleel for the construction 
 of the Tabernacle, and by the imparting to 
 
 the seventy elders of the spirit of Moses, 
 187 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 which he describes as " wise, Divine, in- 
 divisible, noble, without any defect " (De 
 Gig. 20 ffi). 
 
 Here he recognises a physical sense of 
 rn/eO/Lta, equivalent to "air," which recalls 
 Stoic descriptions of God as the " aery 
 essence " (ovaia ae/joetSrfc) which permeates all 
 existence (e.g. Diog. L. vii. 148). Indeed, 
 his language throughout this paragraph has 
 various echoes of Stoicism, as when he 
 speaks of " receiving a notion " (evvoiav 
 \a/3e2v) of God, and refers to the " impres- 
 sion " (<f>avTaa-La) of the good. And the 
 influence of Platonic terminology is evident 
 when he calls the Divine Spirit in its highest 
 aspect "that pure knowledge in which every 
 wise man shares." 1 But the passage shows 
 that he is fully sensitive to the Old 
 Testament conception of the Spirit as a 
 Divine equipment, a Divine gift, an experi- 
 ence not to be identified with that natural 
 endowment which he also calls the inbreathing 
 of the irvevfia. Obviously it will be as a rule 
 
 1 See Phaedrus, 247 D : didvoia v& re KOI eiricrrfjfjirj 
 (so Bekker) 
 
 188 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 impossible to distinguish the Divine Spirit in 
 this sense from the Logos. And in all 
 likelihood the reason why the conception is 
 not more prominent is just that the Logos 
 absorbs its functions. But it is straining the 
 evidence to say, as Zeller (followed by 
 Drummond) does, that Philo only speaks of 
 the Divine Spirit when the idea is presented 
 to him by some text of Scripture (Phil. d. 
 Griechen^, iii. 2. 2, p. 432, note 2). There 
 is nothing artificial or awkward in his em- 
 ployment of the category. His most arresting 
 references occur quite incidentally, and their 
 basis is not theory but experience. " The 
 invisible Spirit which is wont to commune 
 with me unseen whispers to me and says " 
 (De Somn. ii. 252). Here is an instance 
 from his own life of fellowship with God. 
 In another place he appears to include 
 himself when he recounts what happens to 
 " prophetic " natures : " The mind (1/01)9) in 
 us departs at the coming of the Divine Spirit, 
 and when it leaves, returns to its abode. 
 For it is not fitting that mortal should dwell 
 
 with immortal. Thus the sinking of reason 
 189 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 and the darkness which encompasses it beget 
 ecstasy and God-inspired frenzy " (Quis Rer. 
 Div. H. 265). In these passages, in which 
 he speaks most intimately of the Divine 
 Spirit, he is in no sense influenced by some 
 direct reference in Scripture. 
 
 Further light is shed upon his conception 
 by the references he makes to the conditions 
 of the Spirit's indwelling. " Let us keep 
 still from wrong-doing," he says, "in order 
 that the Divine Spirit of wisdom may not 
 easily remove and depart, but may abide 
 with us for a long, long time, as with Moses 
 the wise man" (De Gig. 47). It may be 
 noted that in the context the " Spirit " is 
 identified with 6p0o$ Xtfyo?, an identification 
 common in Philo. In the same treatise (53) 
 he declares that " among the majority," i.e. 
 those who set before them many ends in life, 
 the Divine Spirit does not abide, even if for 
 a short time he may sojourn, but only with 
 one type of men does he dwell, that which 
 has stripped off all that belongs to the world 
 of becoming, " and the inmost veil and curtain 
 
 of opinion, and with unrestricted and open 
 190 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 mind reaches God." Moses is adduced as 
 an example of this type, one "who enters 
 into the darkness, the unseen place, and 
 abides there while he is initiated into the 
 most sacred mysteries. Indeed, not only 
 does he become an initiate, but also a 
 hierophant of mystic rites, a teacher of 
 Divine things, in which he gives instruction 
 to those whose ears have been purified. 
 With such a man the Divine Spirit is ever 
 present, showing him the way in every straight 
 path " (ibid. 54 f.). 
 
 But while there is a real approximation in 
 Philo's use of the conception of the Spirit of 
 God to that in the New Testament, we not 
 only feel that in his thought it is secondary, 
 but also that as an energising power it is 
 grasped with far less vigour and discerned in 
 a dimmer light than, e.g., by St. Paul. We 
 have no doubt that for Philo also it represents 
 the formulation of an experience, but that 
 experience lacks the sureness and depth and 
 permanence which characterise the Apostle's 
 endowment. And the reason surely is that 
 
 in Philo the Divine Spirit is one special de- 
 191 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 scription of a fluctuating and elusive category 
 like the Logos, while St. * Paul indissolubly 
 associates it with that which has the most 
 concrete reality for his spiritual life, the 
 person and activity of the living Lord. 
 
 (c) The Vision of God 
 
 For Philo, the crowning achievement of the 
 pious spirit is the Vision of God. " What 
 lovelier or more fitting garland could be 
 woven for the victorious soul than the power, 
 with clear vision, to gaze upon Him who is ? 
 Truly splendid is the prize held out to the 
 wrestling soul to be equipped with eyesight 
 so as to perceive without dimness Him who 
 is alone worthy of contemplation " (De Mut. 
 Nom. 82). That man has reached the heights 
 of blessedness to whom it is granted not 
 merely by knowledge to apprehend all that 
 belongs to the natural order, but to behold 
 the Father and Maker of the universe. For 
 there is nothing higher than God : he that 
 has succeeded in stretching his soul's vision 
 as far as Him may well pray to abide there 
 
 without change (De A dr. 58). For such 
 192 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 vision is no mere passing rapture. It must 
 prove a singular aid in the good life. "If 
 the sight of elders or instructors or rulers or 
 parents move the beholders to reverence and 
 orderly conduct and the desire for a self- 
 controlled life, how great a bulwark of virtue 
 and honourable living may we expect to find 
 in souls which, reaching beyond all that is 
 created, have been trained to behold the 
 Uncreated and Divine " (Leg. ad Gaium, 5). 
 This fundamental conviction lets us see into 
 the heart of Philo's religious aspiration. 
 
 It is a good thing, he holds, for the soul to 
 seek God. For even the striving after good- 
 ness brings a sort of preliminary satisfaction. 
 But it is a matter of uncertainty whether the 
 search will reach its goal. Many failed 
 to attain. God did not reveal Himself to 
 them (Leg. All. iii. 47). Here is the crux. 
 The highest stage of religion, the only 
 fully satisfying attainment, means revelation. 
 Philo does not so much discuss the idea of 
 revelation in itself as presuppose it in what 
 he affirms concerning the spiritual vision of 
 
 God. But in speaking of some whose 
 N 193 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 search is not fruitless, he describes God as 
 " Himself, by reason of his gracious nature, 
 going forth to meet them with his virgin- 
 graces, and revealing himself to those who 
 crave to behold him, not as he is for that is 
 impossible . . . but in so far as it was 
 possible for a created nature to approach his 
 incomprehensible power " (De Fuga, 141). 
 
 What, then, are the conditions in which the 
 spirit can attain the Vision of God ? Philo 
 has much to say on this problem. We shall 
 try to select some crucial examples of the 
 position which he occupies. In a set of 
 reflections on Gen. xv. 5, where he takes 
 the words, " He [God] led him [Abraham] 
 forth," in a spiritual sense, he proceeds : 
 " The mind that is to be led forth and set at 
 liberty must withdraw from all things, from 
 bodily necessities, from the instruments of the 
 senses, from sophistical reasonings, from 
 plausible arguments, finally from itself. . . . 
 For it is not possible for one who dwells in 
 the body and among mortal men to have 
 communion with God, but only for him whom 
 God delivers out of his prison " (Leg. All. 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 iii. 41 f.). This conception appears in a 
 specially impressive form in Quod del. pot. 
 158 f . : "Will you then assert, O senseless 
 man, that if you are deprived of bodily and 
 external advantages you cannot reach the 
 vision of God ? I tell you that in that event 
 you will surely attain to it : for you must be 
 released from the iron fetters of the body and 
 from bodily concerns if you are to receive the 
 vision of the Uncreated. . . . For it was when 
 [Abraham] left his whole house that the Law 
 says, ' God appeared to him ' (Gen. xii. 7), 
 showing that God distinctly appears to him 
 who escapes from material things and retires 
 into the incorporeal soul of this body of ours." 
 Philo sheds light upon his position in distin- 
 guishing between God's manner of revealing 
 Himself to corporeal souls and those which 
 are bodiless. " To these souls which are 
 incorporeal and worship him it is natural that 
 he should appear as he is, talking as a friend 
 with friends. But to those still in the body 
 he resembles angels, not indeed altering his 
 proper nature, for he cannot suffer change, 
 but impressing upon them who behold him 
 195 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 the notion of a different shape, so that they 
 suppose that this image is not a copy, but 
 that what they see is the original itself." 
 (De Somn. i. 232). Philo goes on to say 
 that for the benefit of dull natures God has 
 to be represented in Scripture by anthropo- 
 morphic descriptions, for in this way alone can 
 they be disciplined. But the more accurate 
 statement is that of Num. xxiii. 17 : "God 
 is not as a man." Hence, to mortals, He 
 must reveal Himself in angelic guise. And 
 His angel, as found in Scripture, is really 
 His "image," the Logos (ibid. 236 ff.). But 
 while life in the thraldom of the body is an 
 insuperable barrier to the undimmed vision 
 of God, he does regard it as possible, as 
 passages quoted above plainly indicate, for 
 a soul which has completely detached itself 
 from the hampering conditions of mortal 
 existence (and this he also assumes as a 
 possibility) even now to attain the goal of its 
 yearnings. He can speak of minds so 
 M completely purified " that the Lord of all, 
 "silently, unseen, alone, sojourns with them," 
 
 while " with the spirits of those who are still 
 196 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 being cleansed and have not yet completely 
 washed away the stained and defiled life they 
 have lived in burdensome bodies, angels may 
 dwell, Divine Logoi, making them bright 
 and pure by the doctrines of high virtue " 
 (ibid. 148). Abraham, the wise man, the stable 
 soul, is the true pattern for those who would 
 commune with God. " For in very deed 
 only the unchanging soul can draw near to 
 the unchanging God, and the soul in such a 
 condition veritably stands beside the Divine 
 power" (De Post. Cain. 27). 
 
 Now the purified soul has a certain dlan or 
 urge towards the beatific vision. " When the 
 eyes formed of corruptible material reach so 
 far as from the region of earth to scan remote 
 heaven and touch its limits, how spacious 
 must we suppose to be the sweep of the eyes 
 of the soul ! For these, winged by an eager 
 longing to behold the Existent in his radiance, 
 not only stretch to the utmost ether, but, pass- 
 ing beyond the bounds of the entire universe, 
 hasten to the Uncreated." These are the 
 souls which cannot be satiated with wisdom 
 
 and knowledge. They are said to be "sum- 
 197 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 moned up" to God. " For it is meet that 
 these should be called up to the Divine, who 
 have been inspired by him." Thus it is by 
 the Divine Spirit that the vow is lightened 
 and lifted up to the highest heights (De 
 Plant. 22 ff. : cf. the fine description of a 
 similar experience in De Spec. Leg. i. 207). 
 
 Let us try to ascertain how Philo conceives 
 the Vision of God to be attained. We have 
 seen that a presupposition of the achieve- 
 ment is the liberation of the mind or spirit 
 from bodily entanglements and all material 
 complications. It has, in a sense, to with- 
 draw from the body in order to reach the 
 Uncreated. Further, as a matter of experi- 
 ence it is only a few who reach the goal. 
 But this small number are "so mighty in 
 energy that not even the whole round of 
 earth can contain them, and they reach 
 heaven ; for, possessed by an unquenchable 
 longing to behold and to be ever in fellow- 
 ship with the Divine, when they have closely 
 investigated and scrutinised the whole of 
 visible nature, they go at once in quest of 
 
 the incorporeal, ideal world, taking none of 
 198 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 the senses with them, but leaving behind all 
 that is irrational in the soul, and only making 
 use of that which is called mind and reason " 
 (De Praem. et Poen. 26). It is important 
 to note that in all that Philo says of what 
 is plainly an "ecstatic" experience, he makes 
 the "rational" capacity of man the chief 
 human factor. But even the purified human 
 spirit is unfit to pursue this arduous quest 
 alone. " There is danger for the soul in 
 ascending to the vision of the Existent by 
 itself, for it knows not the way, and may be 
 puffed up by ignorance and rashness. ... 
 Wherefore Moses prays that he may have 
 the guidance of God himself for the path 
 that leads to him, for he says, Unless Thou 
 go with me, take me not up hence " (De 
 Migr. Abr. 170 f.). God Himself, there- 
 fore, comes to the aid of the yearning soul. 
 He will assist its pursuit of Him. This is 
 exemplified in the experience of Abraham. 
 When his understanding had dispelled the 
 mists of sense which confused it, he was 
 scarcely able to grasp, as in clear air, the 
 
 impression of the Unseen. But God, "by 
 199 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 reason of his philanthropy, did not turn away 
 from the soul as it came to him, but going 
 forth to meet it, revealed his own nature, in 
 so far as it was possible for the beholder to 
 see it. Hence it is said, not that the wise 
 man saw God, but that God appeared to the 
 wise man. For it was impossible that any 
 one should grasp by himself the truly Existent, 
 unless he had manifested and revealed him- 
 self " (De Abr. 79 f.). 
 
 What, then, is Philo's conception of the 
 Vision ? It need scarcely be said, in view 
 of statements already discussed, that contra- 
 dictory utterances are to be found. " When 
 the soul that loves God searches into the 
 nature of the Existent, according to his 
 essence, it enters into an unseen and in- 
 visible search, from which the chief benefit 
 that accrues to it is to comprehend that God 
 is incomprehensible and to see that he is 
 invisible " (De Post. Cain. 15). The classical 
 instance is the experience of Moses as 
 narrated in Ex. xxxiii. 13 ff. All that is 
 vouchsafed to him is a vision of the environ- 
 ment of the Divinity. "His nature does 
 200 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 not admit of being seen : and what wonder 
 that the Existent cannot be grasped by man, 
 since even the mind in each of us is unknow- 
 able by us. For who ever beheld the essence 
 of his soul ? " (De Mut. Norn. 9 f.). Yet very 
 important statements occur of an opposite 
 drift. And these probably bring us as near 
 as we can reach to an analysis of a mystical 
 experience which is really beyond analysis. 
 " There is," he says, "a more perfect and more 
 completely purified type of spirit [again ex- 
 emplified by Moses], initiated into the Divine 
 mysteries, which does not reach a knowledge 
 of the First Cause from created things, of the 
 substance, as it were, from the shadow, but 
 overleaping the created, receives a clear 
 manifestation of the Uncreated, so as to 
 grasp Him from Himself (Leg. All. iii. 
 100). Some light is shed upon the meaning 
 of this vague phrase by several remarkable 
 utterances. Describing the discipline of the 
 wrestling soul, Philo speaks of a point at 
 which "a bright incorporeal ray, purer than 
 ether, suddenly shining upon it, revealed the 
 
 ideal world as under guidance. But the 
 201 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 Guide, encompassed by unstained light, was 
 hard to behold or to divine, for the soul's 
 vision was obscured by the splendour of the 
 rays. Yet she, despite the streaming to- 
 wards her of intense radiance, endured, 
 through her extraordinary craving for a 
 vision. Then the Father and Saviour, 
 seeing her genuine longing and yearning, 
 pitied her, and imparting power to the 
 approach of her sight, did not withhold the 
 vision of himself, in so far as it was possible 
 for a created and mortal nature to contain 
 it" (De Praem. et Poen. 37 ff.). He seems 
 to feel, however, that his description is quite 
 inadequate. And so he returns to the ex- 
 perience. " How this approach [i.e. of the 
 eyes of the soul to God] has taken place, it 
 is worth while observing by means of a simile. 
 Can we behold this sense-perceived sun by 
 any other means than the sun itself? Or, 
 can we behold the stars by any other means 
 than the stars? In a word, is not light seen 
 by means of light? In the same fashion 
 God also, who is his own radiance, is seen 
 
 through himself alone, no other co-operating, 
 202 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 or being able to co-operate towards the pure 
 apprehension of his existence " (ibid. 45 ). We 
 may connect with this a noteworthy state- 
 ment in Qu. in Gen. iv. i (p. 238, Aucher) : 
 " Since God is incomprehensible, not only to 
 the race of men, but also to all the parts 
 of heaven which surpass men in purity, he 
 caused a certain radiance to flash forth from 
 himself, which we may rightly call his form, 
 scattering incorporeal rays about the mind 
 and filling it with super-celestial light. 
 Under this guidance the mind is led, 
 through the mediating form, to the 
 Prototype." 
 
 Some further clues to the meaning of 
 what he conceives as the most intimate 
 experience of union with God may be found 
 in certain descriptions of moments of spiritual 
 rapture. And first let us recall his famous 
 account of his own spiritual illumination as 
 a thinker. " I am not ashamed," he says, 
 "to recount my own experience. ... At 
 times, when I proposed to enter upon my 
 wonted task of writing on philosophical 
 
 doctrines, with an exact knowledge of the 
 203 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 materials which were to be put together, I 
 have had to leave off without any work 
 accomplished, finding my mind barren and 
 fruitless,; and upbraiding it for its self- 
 complacency, while startled at the might 
 of the Existent, in whose power it lies to 
 open and close the wombs of the soul. 
 But at other times, when I had come 
 empty, all of a sudden I was filled 
 with thoughts showered down and sown 
 upon me unseen from above, so that by 
 Divine possession I fell into a rapture and 
 became ignorant of everything, the place, 
 those present, myself, what was spoken or 
 written. For I received a stream of inter- 
 pretation [reading, with Markland, e<rx ov 
 yap epfjLrjveias pevaiv], a fruition of light, the 
 most clear-cut sharpness of vision, the 
 most vividly distinct view of the matter 
 before me, such as might be received 
 through the eyes from the most luminous 
 presentation" (Zte Migr. Abr. 34 f.). 
 Such illumining of his spirit means for 
 him the direct impact of the Divine. And 
 
 no doubt it has contributed materials 
 204 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 to his attempt, acknowledged by himself as 
 inadequate, to delineate the soul's vision of 
 God. Of similar import is his remarkable 
 appeal to the soul in Quis Rer. Div. H. 
 69 f.: "If a yearning come upon thee, O 
 soul, to possess Divine blessings, forsake 
 not only thy 'land/ the body, and thy 
 'kindred,' the life of sense, and thy 'father's 
 house' (Gen. xii. i), the [uttered] word, 1 but 
 escape from thyself also, and go forth from 
 (eWT7?&) thyself, filled with a Divine frenzy 
 like those possessed in the mystic rites of the 
 Corybantes, and holden by the Deity after 
 the manner of prophetic inspiration. For 
 when the mind is filled with God and is no 
 longer self-contained, but rapt and frenzied 
 with a heavenly passion and driven by the 
 Truly Existent and drawn upwards to him, 
 while truth goes in front and removes 
 obstacles that it may tread the highway, 
 this is thy [Divine] inheritance." Here is 
 an impressive description of spiritual ecstasy, 
 and perhaps it delineates with as much de- 
 
 1 See De Migr. Abr. 2 : \6yov rov Kara npofopdv, a 
 passage which explains the symbolism here. 
 205 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 finiteness as Philo could reach what for him, 
 on the basis of real experience, was the 
 content of his most intimate union with 
 God. He makes a like appeal in Quaestt. 
 in Exod. ii. 51 (pp. 505-506, Aucher), in 
 which, after laying down certain conditions, 
 the cutting off of desires, pleasures, despon- 
 dencies, fears, and the casting aside of folly, 
 wrong-doing, and cognate evils, he shows 
 the soul how it may be consecrated to God 
 a living temple. " Then he may appear to 
 thee visibly, causing incorporeal rays to shine 
 upon thee, granting visions of his nature 
 undreamed of and ineffable, which are the 
 overflowing sources of all other blessings." 
 In such experiences it is plain, as Br^hier 
 fitly expresses it, that " Philo's contemplation 
 [of God] is ... an inward rapture in which 
 all precise knowledge disappears in the feeling 
 of the existence of a Being incomprehensible 
 and without limitations" (op. cit. p. 296). 
 Here we inevitably recall the parallel ex- 
 perience of a nature at various points so 
 closely akin to that of Philo, although so 
 
 immeasurably his superior in creative power. 
 206 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 St. Paul also has entered into the mystic 
 ecstasy : "I knew a man in Christ who four- 
 teen years ago was caught up to the third 
 heaven. In the body or out of the body ? 
 That I do not know : God knows. I simply 
 know that, in the body or out of the body 
 (God knows which), this man was caught 
 up to paradise and heard sacred secrets, 
 which no human lips can repeat. Of an 
 experience like that I am prepared to boast, 
 but not of myself personally not except as 
 regards my weaknesses!" (2 Cor. xii 3 ff. : 
 Moffatt's tr.). The smallest reflection will 
 show that, like Philo, Paul feels himself 
 rapt by the Divine power, his soul perfectly 
 passive, and thus laid open for the reception 
 of ineffable Divine revelations. 
 
 Attention has been already called to Philo's 
 opposing statements regarding the possibility 
 of an immediate apprehension of God, state- 
 ments which have their parallels in thewritings 
 of many mystics. Possibly he is quite aware 
 of these apparently contradictory standpoints. 
 And some important utterances on the more 
 
 and the less direct vision of the Existent 
 207 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 may be an attempt to suggest a via media. 
 Of special significance is that in De Abr. 
 1 19 ff., a section in which he explains the sym- 
 bolic meaning of Abraham's three heavenly 
 visitants (Gen. xvii. i ff.). " When the soul, 
 as at broad noon, is encompassed by the 
 Divine radiance, and, being wholly filled with 
 spiritual light, welcomes [reading avya? 
 aa-Trdffrjrai, with Wendland] the rays poured 
 forth around, it receives a threefold impres- 
 sion of the one essence, the first as of One 
 who is three, the other two as of shadows 
 cast by him. . . . Let no one, however, 
 suppose that we can properly speak of 
 shadows in the case of God. We only use 
 this expression to bring out more clearly 
 what has to be explained. . . . But, as one 
 might say in close accord with the truth, the 
 Father of all stands in the midst, who in 
 Holy Scripture is called by his proper name, 
 the Existent, while on either side are his 
 highest Powers, those closest to the Existent, 
 the creative and the ruling. . . . With these, 
 then, as his attendants, He in the midst pre- 
 sents to the spirit that has vision at one time 
 208 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 the impression of one, at another of three ; of 
 one, when the mind is in the highest state of 
 purification and not only passing beyond the 
 multitude of numbers, but also beyond the 
 Two which is the neighbour of the One, 
 hastens to the unmixed and uncompounded 
 Idea, which needs no other than itself; of 
 three, when the mind has not yet been initi- 
 ated into the Great Mysteries, but still only 
 knows the lower grades, and cannot grasp the 
 Existent from himself alone without the help 
 of another, but only through what he does, 
 either as creating or ruling." This paragraph 
 is full of interest as indicating how Philo at- 
 tempted to satisfy his own mind as to the 
 relation of the mediate to the immediate 
 vision of God. The spirit which is "in the 
 highest state of purification " is that which is 
 able fully to renounce itself and to yield 
 wholly to the Divine influence. Not that 
 Philo appears ever to adopt the conception, 
 characteristic of mysticism, of a complete 
 fusion of the individual soul with God. But 
 its self-consciousness is suppressed, and, as 
 
 in prophetic inspiration, which seems power- 
 o 209 
 
UNION WITH GOD 
 
 fully to have influenced his conception, it 
 becomes simply the receptacle or the instru- 
 ment of the Divine Spirit. 
 
 Thus the two poles of thought stand over 
 against each other. On the one hand, the 
 transcendent God cannot be grasped by 
 finite creatures. Yet no other goal will 
 satisfy. Perhaps, as Zeller suggests (Philos. 
 d. Griechcn*, iii. 2. 2, p. 463), "the very 
 transcendence of Philo's conception of God 
 arose, not from the attempt to cut off all 
 relations between men and God, but rather 
 from the very opposite effort, to reach the 
 Deity, whom he could not find in himself or 
 in the world, beyond the bounds of all finite 
 existence." That could only be realised in a 
 Divinely inspired ecstasy, in which the finite, 
 for the moment, transcended mortal limits, 
 and was virtually endowed with infinity. 
 
 210 
 
CHAPTER VII 
 
 THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 WE have attempted in the preceding 
 chapter to give a brief description 
 of what Philo means by the soul's Vision of 
 God, that which he conceives to be the su- 
 preme spiritual attainment. This attainment, 
 we found, is realised in an ecstatic condition 
 in which the restrictions of sense are for the 
 moment left behind, and the purified soul is 
 alone with the Alone. But Philo's Mysti- 
 cism, which reaches its crowning point in 
 this high experience, has so large a bearing 
 upon his whole religious outlook and aspi- 
 rations that it calls for a more detailed 
 examination. 
 
 It has already been noted that success in 
 the quest after union with God is regarded 
 by Philo as the meed only of a few. This 
 conviction colours both his thought and his 
 
 21 I 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 language. Again and again when he deals 
 with the ineffable discoveries of the soul in 
 God which he seeks to elucidate allegorically, 
 he speaks as if to an esoteric circle, and 
 employs the terminology of the Mystery-cults 
 of paganism. " This," he exclaims, "receive 
 in your souls, ye initiates, purified of hearing, 
 as veritably sacred mysteries, and divulge it 
 not to any of the uninitiated, but keep it in 
 the storehouse of your mind as a treasure 
 not composed of silver and gold, substances 
 which perish, but as the fairest of existing 
 possessions " (De Cherub. 48). The same awe 
 in declaring the deeper secrets of the Divine 
 appears in De Sacr. Ab. et Cain. 60, where 
 he speaks of the necessity of hiding "the 
 sacred revelation concerning the Uncreated 
 and his Powers, since not every one can guard 
 the deposit of the Divine ritual." Moses' 
 action in pitching the tabernacle (which the 
 LXX of Ex. xxx. 7 calls " his tent," and Philo 
 " his own tent ") outside and away from the 
 camp, means that "having established his 
 mind firmly, he begins to worship God, and 
 
 having entered into the cloud abides there, 
 212 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 receiving initiation into the Divine Mysteries. 
 Indeed he becomes not only an initiate but 
 also a hierophant of ritual and a teacher of 
 Divine things, in which he guides those 
 whose hearing is purified " (De Gig. 54). The 
 full force of this mystic terminology is made 
 clear by Leg. All. iii. 100 : " There is a more 
 perfect and purified type of spirit which has 
 been initiated into the Great Mysteries, which 
 does not discover the Cause from created 
 things, the abiding, as it were, from the 
 shadow, but overleaping the created, receives 
 a clear vision of the Uncreated so as to ap- 
 prehend him from himself" 1 Possibly this 
 usage requires no further explanation. In 
 every period, those whose spiritual affinities are 
 mystical draw together through the attraction 
 of a common experience and cultivate on its 
 basis a common speech. Yet there is some- 
 thing to be said for Reitzenstein's hypothesis 
 (Poimandres, p. 204, note i) that Philo was 
 here influenced by his Egyptian environment 
 in which there had grown up as the result of 
 
 1 See the interesting collection of mystery-terms from Philo 
 in Bousset, Religion d. Judentums*, p. 519, note 3. 
 213 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 mystery-cults (< an elaborated literary form and 
 manner" of this type. That is, however, 
 something very different from the theory 
 which accompanies it, that Philo's doctrine 
 of ecstasy is itself the product of Hellenistic 
 religion, a question to which we must return. 
 Before we go further, let us try to form 
 some more or less clear notion of the terms we 
 have to use. Mysticism, it need scarcely be 
 said, is one of the most question-begging 
 descriptions of certain elusive because very 
 personal spiritual conditions. Some power- 
 ful minds regard such states as a kind of nar- 
 cotic indulgence of the sensibilities, fostered 
 by turbid thought and unethical feeling. 
 Some at the opposite extreme would embrace 
 under the name those experiences which are 
 supremely life-enhancing. Others associate 
 it with individualities of a religious bent 
 whose intellectual nature is completely over- 
 shadowed by the emotional. And further 
 interpretations of " Mysticism " have been 
 current. Hence there has come into vogue a 
 use of the term as lax as that of such words 
 
 as "evolution," " realism," "socialism." 
 214 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 It is surely true, as Dr. Bigg suggests, 
 that " in one sense all believers in the unseen 
 are mystics" (Christian Platonists of Alex- 
 andria, p. 99, note i) That is to say, a stage 
 may be reached in the experience of com- 
 munion with God which is so intimate as to 
 be indescribable in terms of normal states of 
 consciousness. Various degrees of intensity 
 may be discovered in the attitude of the 
 spirit which, to use Plotinus' phrase, is "in 
 love with " God. Probably some spiritual 
 minds which delight in exercising a strong 
 control over the processes of their Godward 
 aspiration discredit the circle of ideas usually 
 called "mystic," because to them it seems to 
 imply spheres of being that are nebulous 
 or morally unproductive. Yet many such 
 persons would willingly admit that St. Paul 
 stands on the summit of religious experience 
 when he exclaims : "I have been crucified with 
 Christ : nevertheless I live ; yet not I, but Christ 
 lives in me : indeed the life which I now live 
 as a man I live by faith faith in the Son of 
 God, who loved me, and gave himself for me " 
 
 (Gal. ii. 19, 20). But faith in Paul's profound 
 215 
 

 THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 sense of the term undoubtedly involves a 
 mystical element, a factor or condition which 
 eludes psychological analysis, although it is 
 far removed from many of the typical formu- 
 lations of what may be called technical mysti- 
 cism. On the other hand, there have been 
 yearning souls throughout the ages whose 
 dominant aim has been to get beyond the 
 limits of self and to be merged in Him who 
 is the All. This probably represents the 
 most intensified degree of the mystical ex- 
 perience in the strictest sense. It is, however, 
 in reality no more than the exaggeration of 
 an element which is discernible everywhere 
 in religious experience, by whatever designa- 
 tion it may be named, the longing for union 
 with the Divine. This is described from the 
 standpoint of his own special experience by 
 St. Paul as being " in Christ " : and from a 
 totally divergent angle of vision by an entirely 
 different type of thinker, Spinoza, as amor 
 intellectualis Dei. * The goal in all cases is 
 
 1 But, as Mr. C. C. J. Webb cogently points out, "there is 
 in this amor intellectualis Dei no question of reciprocation " 
 {God and Personality, p. 70). 
 
 216 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 complete unification of life. For some this 
 means individuality raised to its highest power, 
 for others entire absorption in Perfect or 
 Absolute Being. 
 
 There can be little doubt that the direction 
 which this mystical element in human nature 
 is trained to take, depends largely on the 
 temperament of the individual. Many will 
 be content to satisfy its needs in the relation 
 which Faith in its deep Pauline sense estab- 
 lishes between the soul and God. For such, 
 no abandonment of personality is involved. 
 Rather does personality reach for the first 
 time its full realisation. Others, however, 
 are led to discipline their spiritual natures so 
 resolutely by patient concentration on the 
 goal of their desires that they enter upon 
 abnormal spiritual conditions of greater or 
 less intensity which assume the nature of a 
 trance. This state also may vary in- 
 definitely. Its most common form is ecstasy. 
 "Taken alone," says Miss Underbill, "and 
 apart from its content, ecstasy carries no 
 guarantee of spiritual value. It merely 
 
 indicates the presence of certain abnormal 
 217 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 psycho-physical conditions, an alteration 
 of the normal equilibrium. . . . Ecstasy, 
 physically considered, may occur in any 
 person in whom (i) the threshold of con- 
 sciousness is exceptionally mobile, and (2) 
 there is a tendency to dwell upon one 
 governing idea or intuition. Its worth 
 depends entirely on the objective worth of 
 that idea or intuition." (Mysticism, p. 430). 
 It need scarcely be said that the governing 
 idea in the case of all truly mystical natures 
 is that of God. 
 
 The excellent summary of the facts just 
 quoted will serve as an introduction to an 
 examination of Philo's mysticism. And it 
 also puts us on our guard against a miscon- 
 ception which has recently gained currency 
 through the dogmatic assertions of prominent 
 scholars. Thus Reitzenstein declares that 
 Philo's doctrine of ecstasy is "to be fully 
 explained from Hellenism," and, quoting 
 certain commonplaces of mystical technique, 
 remarks that " Philo has taken over these 
 Hellenistic theories" (op. cit. p. 204, note i, 
 
 238, note 3). Similarly Brdhier attempts to 
 218 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 show that various mystical doctrines in Philo 
 have their origin in traditions of Egyptian 
 mystical theology such as are to be found in 
 Plutarch's treatise, On his? and the Hermetic 
 Tractates (see esp. op. cit. pp. 245-248). 
 Apart altogether from the fact that these 
 tractates are of much later date than Philo, 
 and must have been as directly exposed to 
 his influence as we know Plotinus to have 
 been, the material he adduces is in no sense 
 the special property of Egyptian theology. 
 Still less are the mystic conceptions which 
 Reitzenstein (followed as usual by Bousset) 
 finds him to have borrowed from his environ- 
 ment in any degree characteristically Hellen- 
 istic. They bear the familiar stamp of 
 Mysticism as it appears in every quarter of 
 the world where spiritual or even unspiritual 
 religion is cultivated. To describe the in- 
 variable phenomena of the mystic quest for 
 God as the peculiar product of Hellenistic 
 religious activity, is to ignore a realm of facts 
 
 1 It is plain to the careful reader of such texts as De Cherub. 
 42 if. and Leg. All. iii. 3, 139, quoted by Brehier in support 
 of his view, that Philo's use of earlier ideas in these passages 
 is purely metaphorical and illustrative. 
 219 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 of which no one who writes on the history 
 of religion has any business to be ignorant. 
 
 We have recognised how frequently Philo 
 uses the terminology of the Mystery-cults of 
 paganism for his own purposes. His actual 
 estimate of these cults is made sufficiently 
 plain by such passages as De Spec. Leg. 
 i. 319: " Further, he (Moses) removes from 
 the sacred legislation rites and mysteries and 
 all such clap-trap and buffoonery, considering 
 that people brought up in such a common- 
 wealth as Israel are above cultivating ritual 
 and despising truth and running after 
 ceremonies belonging to the darkness of 
 night, while they cling to mystic fictions and 
 ignore what can stand the light of day. 
 Therefore let none of Moses' disciples and 
 friends either initiate or be initiated. For 
 either of the two, the teaching or learning of 
 mystic rites is no small profanation. . . . 
 Let those whose activities are hurtful be 
 ashamed and search for holes and recesses 
 in the earth and deep darkness, and let them 
 hide and cast a shadow over their own un- 
 righteousness. . . . Ought we not openly to 
 220 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 offer whatever is needful and profitable to all 
 who are worthy of it for their benefit? But 
 the fact is that seldom is a good man 
 initiated, but you do find robbers and pirates 
 and bands of wretched, unbridled women, 
 because they pay fees to the hierophants who 
 initiate them." 
 
 Let us more minutely scrutinise that 
 condition of ecstasy or inspiration in which 
 Philo, like most mystics, attains his most 
 satisfying apprehension of the living reality 
 of God. How completely his thought is 
 saturated with ecstatic experiences appears 
 from his constant use of the vocabulary of 
 Divine possession. Terms like IvOovviaGpo*;, 
 "Divine inspiration," evOova-idfav, "to be 
 Divinely inspired," eWtaa0>w>9, "Divine 
 rapture," eTriQudfav, "to be in a condition 
 of Divine rapture," /copvpavnav, "to be filled 
 with supernatural frenzy," paKffveiv, "to be 
 seized with Divine madness," 
 "to be possessed by Deity," 
 "Divine possession," deo^oprjro^ "possessed 
 by God," and its corresponding verb, 
 , e/39 ovpdvios, " heavenly passion," 
 
 221 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 and <Wracrt9, " ecstasy," are of frequent occur- 
 rence. 1 It is unnecessary to enlarge on the 
 fact established in our last chapter that the 
 literal meaning of the word " ecstasy " is 
 fundamental for Philo. We there quoted a 
 passage of marked significance (Quis Rer. 
 Div. H. 69 f.) in which he adjures the soul 
 that craves the summum bonum of the Beatific 
 Vision to " escape from" (airbbpaOi) itself, to 
 "go forth from" (eWr^t) itself, "filled with 
 a Divine frenzy like those possessed in the 
 mystic rites of the Corybantes." This associa- 
 tion of ecstasy with an inward rapture is 
 found repeatedly in Philo. A very important 
 instance is Leg. All. i. 82 ff. "When the 
 spirit (which allegorically represents Judah, 
 o efoyitoXo??;/?, the man given to praising 
 God ") goes out of itself and offers itself 
 to God ... it there and then surrenders 
 (6fjLo\oy[av TToieiTcu, possibly, ' comes to terms 
 with ') to the Existent. . . . And truly it 
 must be observed that this act of praise 
 (TO egofio\oyei<T0ai) is not the doing of the soul 
 
 1 See the useful list in Bousset, Religion d. Judentums 2 , 
 p. 517, note 2, which might be considerably extended. 
 222 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 but of God, who reveals to it his beneficence." 
 The passage occurs in a paragraph in which 
 he compares the various tribes of Israel to 
 the jewels in the high priest's breastplate. 
 Judah, the symbol of the man who praises 
 God, has as his gem the carbuncle (avOpat;). 
 For the spirit which he represents, the spirit 
 which goes out of itself, "is kindled into a 
 flame of thanksgiving to God and becomes 
 drunken with that drunkenness which does 
 not intoxicate." Again, in an interpretation 
 of the story of Hannah who was rebuked for 
 drunkenness (i Sam. i. 14) as she prayed 
 before the Lord, Philo remarks : "In the 
 case of the God-possessed not only is the 
 soul wont to be stirred and driven into frenzy, 
 but to be flushed and inflamed, since the joy 
 which wells up within and makes the spirit 
 glow transmits the experience to the outward 
 parts" (De Ebriet. 147). Very suggestive is 
 an actual description of ecstasy (Leg. All. 
 ii. 31). Taking as his basis Gen. ii. 21 
 (LXX), " God put Adam into a trance 
 (e/co-rao-t?) and caused him to sleep," Philo 
 
 says that "the going-forth (e/co-rao-^) and 
 223 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 turning (rpoirrj) of the spirit is a sleep which 
 falls upon it. It goes forth when it ceases 
 to busy itself with the ideas which impinge 
 upon it, and when it does not exercise 
 activity upon them it slumbers. Its going 
 forth is an apt account of what happens, that 
 is, its turning in the direction not of itself but 
 of God who . . . imparts to it this new 
 direction." In this definition of ecstasy the 
 emphasis is placed not on the rousing of 
 the spirit to a Divine madness, but on its 
 quiescence. And this aspect of the condition 
 appears to be as familiar to Philo as the 
 other. We have referred in a former chapter 
 to that experience of the soul which he calls 
 " intercourse with the God who loves to 
 give," in which there is a cessation of all effort, 
 and the soul simply receives the Divine 
 bounties (De Migr. Abr. 30 f.). He de- 
 lineates the beginnings of the Quietist type 
 of ecstasy with real vividness in Quaestt. in 
 Gen. iv. 140 (Aucher, pp. 350-351), where 
 he is discussing Isaac's solitary meditation in 
 the fields at the close of the day. " The 
 
 man," he says, " who highly values the 
 224 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 removal and absence of all thought of the 
 visible, begins to lead a solitary life alone 
 with the sole invisible God. . . . Hence, 
 nominally, they go forth from their city or 
 home ; really, the meaning is that the spirit, 
 apart from the body (per se), begins to be 
 inwardly so inspired and initiated in Divine 
 things as to be possessed almost wholly by 
 God." Some other utterances are sharper in 
 outline. " The most secure method of con- 
 templating (Oecopelv) the Existent is with the 
 soul alone, apart from all utterance " (De 
 Gig. 52). Dean Inge, who points out that 
 the ecstasy of Plotinus was of this calm type 
 which is experienced in solitude, remarks that 
 "the vision of the One is only the highest 
 and deepest kind of prayer, which is the 
 mystical art par excellence " (Philosophy of 
 Plotinus, ii. p. 143). In the light of his 
 statement it is worthy of note that Philo gives 
 no prominence to the conception of prayer as 
 the request for blessings from God. Indeed, 
 he contrasts such request with what he calls 
 "great prayer" (basing the expression on 
 
 Num. vi. 2), namely, the conviction that 
 p 225 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 " God is of himself the cause of blessings, 
 without the co-operation of any one else " 
 (Quod Deus sit immut. 87). 
 
 A careful reader of Philo can scarcely avoid 
 the conclusion that, so far from conceiving 
 ecstasy in terms of Hellenistic religion, the 
 thought in which he endeavours to express 
 the mystic experience is determined by the 
 phenomena of prophetic vision in the Old 
 Testament. The prophet is above all else 
 a man of piercing glance, " having within 
 himself a spiritual sun and unshadowed rays 
 so as to grasp with perfect clearness those 
 things invisible to the senses and only to be 
 apprehended by the mind " (De Spec. Leg. 
 iv. 192). These prophetic functions, indeed, 
 may be caricatured. And here, no doubt, 
 he has in view the "prophets" who are in- 
 fluential among his pagan contemporaries. 
 Those who deal in divination parody the 
 Divine possession of the genuine seer. 
 " Each by his guesses and conjectures sets 
 forth an order of things out of harmony with 
 truth : and easily cajoling the unstable in 
 
 character, like a stiff blast blowing against 
 226 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 ships without ballast, retards and capsizes 
 them and prevents them from reaching the 
 sacred havens of piety. For he deems it his 
 duty to proclaim his divinations not as in- 
 ventions of his own, but as Divine oracles 
 imparted to him alone in secret, in order to 
 gain a surer confidence for his deceit from 
 large companies of people. Such a man he 
 [Moses] designates by the accurate name of 
 false prophet " (De Spec. Leg. iv. 50). In 
 contrast with him the genuine prophet 
 " declares nothing at all of his own, but is 
 an interpreter of the promptings of another in 
 all that he proclaims, continuing in a state of 
 ignorance all the time he is Divinely possessed: 
 for his reason has removed and withdrawn 
 from the citadel of the soul, where has 
 come to dwell the Divine Spirit, stimu- 
 lating and producing sound in the entire 
 mechanism of the voice so as clearly to 
 reveal that which he predicts" (ibid. 49 : cf. the 
 exact parallel, ibid. i. 66). We may note in 
 passing the further light shed by the contrast 
 on Philo's estimate of the Hellenistic idea of 
 
 possession. And the account of the true 
 227 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 prophetic state reminds us of the material 
 which this Jew of Alexandria contributed to 
 the formation in the early Church of a rigid 
 doctrine of inspiration. More than once he 
 singles out as central for the prophetic state 
 the falling into abeyance of reason (vow) 
 which is confined within definite limits of 
 comprehension, and its replacement by the 
 Divine influence which opens up for the 
 prophet a new realm of vision (e.g. De Vita 
 M. ii. 6). 
 
 But perhaps the clearest exposition of his 
 conception is to be found in Quis Rer. Div. 
 H. 249 ff., a passage which shows that he 
 has reflected carefully on these abnormal 
 phenomena. Here he distinguishes four 
 types of ecstasy. The first he describes 
 as " a mad frenzy which produces derange- 
 ment in old age or melancholia or some such 
 symptom." The second is "the intense 
 stupor caused by events happening suddenly 
 and unexpectedly." The third is "the 
 quiescence of the understanding when at any 
 time it comes to be still." The fourth, "the 
 
 noblest type of all, is that Divine possession 
 228 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 and frenzy characteristic of prophetic natures." 
 This experience is typical of the inspired 
 man. But Philo has a wider view of the 
 possibilities. " Holy Scripture," he says, 
 "allows prophecy to every fine and noble 
 nature. For the prophet sets forth nothing 
 of his own but what lies beyond his range, 
 at the prompting of another. Now it is not 
 right for a worthless person to become the 
 interpreter of God. Therefore, properly 
 speaking, no rascal is divinely possessed. 
 This befits the wise alone : for he only is the 
 echoing instrument of God, invisibly struck 
 by him. Hence all whom he [Moses] 
 recorded as righteous he introduced as 
 possessed and exercising prophetic functions." 
 He proceeds minutely to analyse the ecstatic 
 state of the prophet, taking as his starting- 
 point the words of Gen. xv. 12: "About 
 the setting of the sun, ecstasy fell upon him." 
 " As long as our own reason encompasses us 
 with brightness . . . filling our whole soul, 
 as it were, with noonday light, we remain in 
 ourselves and do not experience possession. 
 
 But when the light of reason sets . . . ecstasy 
 229 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 and Divine possession and frenzy fall upon 
 us. For when the Divine light blazes forth, 
 the human sets, and when that sets, this 
 rises. That is what is wont to happen to 
 prophetic natures. For the reason within 
 us leaves its abode at the arrival of the 
 Divine Spirit, but when the Spirit departs 
 the reason returns to its place. For it is not 
 fitting that the mortal should dwell with the 
 immortal. On this account the setting of the 
 rational power and its obscuration produces 
 ecstasy and inspired frenzy. And what 
 accompanies this he weaves into the text 
 of Scripture, saying (Gen. xv. 13), 'it was 
 said to Abraham.' For truly the prophet, 
 even when he appears to speak, is really 
 silent, while another uses his organs ot 
 speech, his mouth and tongue, to declare 
 his will." 
 
 The fundamental element, therefore, in 
 ecstasy as conceived by Philo, is the replac- 
 ing of the human reason (vov? or X^o/to?) by 
 the Divine Spirit, which takes complete 
 possession of the personality and uses it for 
 
 its own high ends. An interesting passage 
 230 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 (Quaestt. in Gen. iii. 9) adds one or two 
 features to his main conception. Ecstasy 
 is there described as a " Divine excess 
 made tranquil," and emphasis is laid on the 
 fact that it does not come on gradually, 
 but with a sudden inrush of the Spirit. 
 Possibly, however, this latter statement must 
 be estimated in the light of his view as a 
 whole. For, as we pointed out in an earlier 
 chapter, Philo is often influenced in the precise 
 formulation of his thought at any given time 
 by the actual words of the text on which he 
 is commenting. And here the text (Gen. xv. 
 12) reads : " An ecstasy y*?// upon Abraham." 
 The earlier part of the description recalls the 
 existence of ecstatic states in which frenzy 
 has no part. One specially pregnant instance 
 of this negative aspect of the condition ought 
 not to be omitted. In a symbolic interpre- 
 tation of Ex. xxxii. 27, where Moses com- 
 mands the members of the tribe of Levi, 
 who have remained loyal to God, to attack 
 the worshippers of the golden calf, and to 
 slay " each man his brother and his neighbour, 
 and him who is nearest to him," Philo takes 
 231 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 the first class mentioned as representing the 
 body, which is the brother of the soul ; the 
 second, as standing for the material element, 
 which is the neighbour of the rational ; and 
 the third, as signifying the "uttered Word," 
 which stands nearest to the mind. " For 
 only thus," he says, "could the noblest 
 element in us worship the noblest of all 
 existences if, in the first place, the man were 
 reduced to soul, its brother the body with all 
 its ineffectual desires being disjoined and 
 separated from it : if, secondly, the soul, as 
 I remarked, should cast aside the irrational 
 element, the neighbour of the rational 
 for that, like a torrent divided into five 
 parts among the five senses . . . stirs up the 
 current of the passions if, in the next place, 
 the reason should divorce and separate from 
 itself the uttered word, so that the rational 
 should be left alone, parted from the body, 
 parted from the sense-life, parted from the 
 sound of the uttered word. For when thus 
 left to live a life of solitude, it can cleave to 
 the only Existent in purity and without 
 
 being drawn aside " (De Fuga, 90 ff.). This 
 232 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 remarkable passage lays bare the bed-rock of 
 Philo's conception of ecstasy as that unin- 
 terrupted stillness of the soul, that complete 
 unity of being in which no discordant element 
 exists, and God can reveal Himself without let 
 or hindrance. It prepares us directly for what 
 is perhaps the highest description in his writ- 
 ings of the issue of prophetic inspiration, 
 expressed in his answer to the question : 
 " Why does Scripture say, Moses alone shall 
 draw near unto God ? " (Quaestt. in Exod. 
 ii. 29). "This," he observes, "is said 
 perfectly naturally. For the prophetic mind, 
 when it has been initiated in Divine things 
 and is inspired, resembles unity. 1 . . . Now he 
 who cleaves to the nature of unity is said to 
 have approached God with the intimacy as it 
 were of a kinsman. For, abandoning all 
 mortal types, he is transferred into the 
 Divine type so that he becomes akin to God 
 and truly Divine.' 
 
 1 This has reference to certain numerical speculations on 
 Moses and his companions, Aaron, Nadab and Abihu ( 27), 
 in which Moses is represented by the first numeral I, 
 symbolising the purest intelligence, the prophetic, while the 
 other three are adornments of that. 
 
 233 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 In ecstasy, therefore, the spirit reaches the 
 true end of its being, the pure apprehension 
 of God. " For the goal of bliss is the advent 
 of God who draws near, bountifully filling the 
 entire soul with all his incorporeal and eternal 
 light " (Quaestt. in Gen. iv. 4 ; Aucher, p. 246). 
 In this condition it desires to remain. For 
 if the visitation of God be only transient, the 
 soul is left forlorn and empty : in a moment 
 thick darkness comes upon it (ibid., loc. cit.\ 
 And yet the passing of this blissful experience 
 is inevitable. It is not possible for a created 
 being uninterruptedly to sustain the Divine 
 presence (deum in segerere : ibid. 29; Aucher, 
 p. 268). " When the spirit, possessed by 
 the love of God, reaching to the very holy 
 of holies, advances with all eagerness and 
 ardour, it forgets all else in its Divine 
 rapture : it forgets even itself, and remembers 
 and cleaves to Him alone whom it attends 
 and worships, to whom it solemnly dedicates 
 its sacred and untainted virtues. But when 
 its Divine passion is stilled and its ardent 
 yearning slackens, it retraces its course from 
 the realm of the Divine and becomes man, 
 234 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 lighting upon those human interests which lie 
 in wait for it at the entrance of the sanctuary " 
 (De Somn. ii. 232 ff.). This means that the 
 spirit is too frail to keep itself so firmly con- 
 centrated on God and so completely alienated 
 from material concerns as to be able to retain 
 its full Divine illumination. 
 
 Hence we are not surprised to find 
 repeated hints in Philo that the grasp of the 
 Existent in ecstasy is a rare attainment. No 
 doubt he has frequent descriptions of the 
 T6\e*o9, the man who has reached the goal and 
 may be called " completely a man of God." 
 But when we look deeper we can discern 
 that he reserves this high designation for a 
 favoured few. It holds good without reser- 
 vation of Abraham and Moses. But in the 
 main it stands for an ideal which towers high 
 above the aspirations of humanity. 
 
 At this point, as at so many, the position 
 of Philo is strikingly elucidated by the 
 mystical experience of Plottnus. Apparently 
 by this famous mystic the estatic state was 
 rarely enjoyed. Dean Inge, in drawing a 
 most illuminating contrast between Plotinus 
 235 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 and later mystics such as Bohme and Blake, 
 points out that while Bohme, for example, 
 used to hypnotise himself to induce abnormal 
 spiritual conditions, Plotinus always insisted 
 that the Divine vision must be waited for 
 (Philosophy of Plotinus, ii. 152 f.). This 
 meant a patient quieting of the soul, of which 
 but few are capable. 
 
 Philo's outlook is, in essentials, the same. 
 We might almost venture to say that the 
 catena of extracts so skilfully linked together 
 by Dr. Inge (pp. cit. ii. pp. 132-142) to 
 illustrate the fundamental character of the 
 mysticism of Plotinus, except for modifica- 
 tions here and there in the interest of Jewish 
 monotheism, unfolds to us the very essence 
 of Philo's mystic ecstasy. 
 
 That ecstasy is the crowning-point of a 
 religious experience which may well create in 
 the unprejudiced student of Philo a willing 
 and affectionate reverence. He will carry 
 away from his acquaintance with the 
 Alexandrian sage a feeling like that which 
 Dr. Rendel Harris so sympathetically de- 
 scribes when speaking of his own work on 
 236 
 
THE MYSTICISM OF PHILO 
 
 the Fragments. " To us," he says (Fragments 
 of Philo, p. i f.), " his fragments are no mere 
 chaff and draff, but such blessed brokenness 
 of truth just dawning on the world that one 
 would imagine him to be holding out to us 
 what had previously passed through the 
 hands of the Master Himself." To these 
 words the present writer can whole-heartedly 
 say, Amen. 
 
 237 
 
INDEX 
 
 (i) AUTHORS AND SUBJECTS 
 
 Abraham, 33, 34, 41, 46, 122, 
 123, 124, 133, 138, 199, 231, 
 
 235. 
 Advocate (irapAK^ros), 113, 
 
 114. 
 Alexandria, 8, 19, 38, 159, 176, 
 
 177. 
 Allegory, 2, 25, 32, 33, 34, 35, 
 
 36, 38, 40, 48. 
 Angels, 6, 80, 159, 162. 
 Archer Hind, 73. 
 Arnim, Von, 24. 
 Aucher, 24, 164, 182, 224. 
 
 Barker, E., 63. 
 
 Bigg, 123, 185, 215. 
 
 Blake, W., 236. 
 
 Body, 75, 86, 88, 98, 99. 
 
 Bohme, 236. 
 
 Bousset, 8, 38, 78, 213, 219, 
 
 222. 
 
 Brehier, 53, 54, 58, 77, 108, 
 112, 125, 140, 165, 218, 
 219. 
 
 Cicero, 53. 
 
 Clement of Alexandria, 36. 
 
 Cohn, 24, 25, 138, 153. 
 
 Compendia, 2, 9. 
 
 Conscience, 27, 53, lo6ff., Ill, 
 
 114, 115, Ii6f., 146. 
 Creation, 64, 65, 76. 
 
 Diaspora, 19, 21, 151. 
 
 Diogenes Laertius, 64, 188. 
 Drummond, J., 53, 69, 71, 170, 
 
 1 80, 189. 
 Dualism, 70, 73. 
 
 Ecstasy, 199, 205, 210, 214, 
 217 f., 221, 223 ff., 229, 230, 
 231, 233. 
 
 Education (Greek), 7, 10, 13, 
 
 19- 
 
 Egyptian theology, 219. 
 Ephesus, 177. 
 Epicharmus, 105. 
 Epistles^ Pauline), 2O. 
 Ezekiel, 160. 
 
 I0 7> IO 8| 114- 
 
 Faith, 27, 122, 125, 126, 127, 
 
 131-134, 215 f., 217. 
 Fathers (Christian), I, 58. 
 Flesh (<rdp), 74, 89, 90, 94. 
 Fourth Gospel, 20, 37, 47-50, 
 
 176. 
 
 Geffcken, 2. 
 
 God, relation of, to world, 62 f. ; 
 
 as Creator, 64 f., 67, 84 f. ; 
 
 and necessity, 73; man's 
 
 longing for, 96 ff., 193; 
 
 relation of, to Lord, 144 ; 
 
 generosity of, 154, 155; 
 
 transcendence of, 160 ; Spirit 
 
 of, 27, 172, 184, 187, 190; 
 
 239 
 
INDEX 
 
 as Father, 1 79 ft., 184; 
 immediate apprehension of, 
 207, 209, 235. 
 
 Grace (Divine), 17, 27, 59, 
 117, 142, 143, 145, 147, 
 148 f., 152, 153, 156. 
 
 Harris, Rendel, 176, 236. 
 Hatch, E., 58. 
 Hatch, W. H. P., 125. 
 Hebrews (Epistle to), 20, 124, 
 
 134, 162, 170. 
 Heinze, 69. 
 Hellenism, 7, 8,' 13, 19, 21, 26, 
 
 31, 76, 140, 214, 218, 219, 
 
 226. 
 
 Heraclitus, 177. 
 Hermetic documents, 61, 158, 
 
 219. 
 Hope, 119. 
 
 Ideas (Platonic), 64, 67, 158. 
 Immortality, 9, 134, 137, 138, 
 
 140, 141. 
 
 Inge, W. R., 225, 235, 236. 
 Inspiration (verbal), 32, 37, 
 
 3 8 39. 40 44 prophetic, 
 
 226, 227, 233. 
 
 Jeremiah, 56, 112. 
 
 Jesus, 6, 22, 154, 181, 182. 
 
 Jowett, 23. 
 
 Kroll, J., 61, 184. 
 
 Law, (Mosaic), 2, 30, 31, 44, 
 
 45. 5 1 . 54, 56. 
 Leckie.J. H., 141. 
 Lietzmann, H., 89. 
 Life, 135, 137. 
 Lightfoot, 41. 
 Logos, 5, 6, 27, 79, 84, 85, 87, 
 
 109, 161, 162, 163, 167-169, 
 
 170, 172 f., 176 f., 186, 189, 
 
 192. 
 \6yot, 67, 158, 166, 169. 
 
 Man, Ideal, in Philo, 76, 78; 
 
 in Paul, 78, 79. 
 Mangey, 133. 
 Markland, 66, 204. 
 Matter, 62, 64, 65, 66, 67, 68, 
 
 70, 71, 72, 74. 
 Mechilta, 122. 
 Mediators, 27, I57ff. 
 Memra, 160. 
 Moses, 2, 3, 29, 30, 51, 57, 63, 
 
 64, 155, 200, 212, 220, 231, 
 
 235. 
 
 Mystery-terminology, 34, 212, 
 
 213, 220. 
 
 Mysticism, 211 ff., 214. 
 Myth, 39. 
 
 Neo-Pythagoreanism, 60, 89. 
 New Testament, 20, 184, 191. 
 
 Old Testament, in Christian 
 theology, 4 ; in Philo, i8f., 
 25, 46, 62, 83, 122, 1 80, 1 88. 
 
 otffla, relation of, to f/X?;, 67, 
 69. 
 
 Panaetius, 53- 
 
 Passions, 100, 101. 
 
 Paul, 26, 40, 41. 42, 43. 56, 
 58, 131 f., 134, 135, 136, 138, 
 141, 149, i$of., 183, 191, 
 206 f., 215. 
 
 Peter, 7. 
 
 PhatdruS) 1 88. 
 
 Philo, use of, by Fathers, 1,2; 
 date of, 6; traditions regard- 
 ing, 7 ; and Hellenism, 7 ; 
 style of, 10 ; personality of, 
 10-15 ; culture of, 12, 13, 14 ; 
 poetic strain in, 15 ff. ; relig- 
 ion of, i, 6, 22, 23; verbal 
 minutiae in, 37 ; and Posi- 
 donius, 6 1 ; syncretism of, 61, 
 79 j his experiences of 
 spiritual illumination, 203 ff. ; 
 opposition of, to mystic 
 initiation, 220. 
 
 240 
 
INDEX 
 
 Philosophy of Philo, I, 5, 19, 
 
 22, 25, 60. 
 Plato, 2, 1 8, 60, 62, 64, 65, 70, 
 
 72, 73, 74, 80, 158, 1 80. 
 Pleasure, 100. 
 Plotinus, 215, 219, 225, 235, 
 
 236. 
 
 Plutarch, 219. 
 Posidonius, 53, 61. 
 Powers (Divine), 5, 6, 162, 164, 
 
 165, 166, 169, 208. 
 Prayer, 225, 226. 
 Pre-existence (of Souls), 80. 
 Prophets, 57, 58, 226, 227, 
 
 228. 
 
 , 129, I3of. 
 
 92. 
 s, 92, 93. 
 
 Reason (i>ous), 81, 83, 84, 85, 
 87, 9i, 93, 94, io6f., 147, 
 1 86. 
 
 Redemption, 89, 148. 
 
 Reitzenstein, 213, 218, 219. 
 
 Repentance, 27, ii6ff., 121. 
 
 Revelation, I, 193. 
 
 Ritual, 54, 55. 
 
 Ryle, 39, 57- 
 
 Schlatter, 126. 
 Schmekel, 9, 53, 60. 
 Schiirer, 50. 
 Self-love, 102. 
 Seneca, 64. 
 
 Septuagint, 31, 32, 38. 
 Shekinah, 160. 
 
 Siegfried, 32, 62, 70, 71, 161. 
 Sin, 27, 72, 8 1, 98, 101, 104. 
 Sonship, 179, i8of. 
 Soul (turf), 75. 86, 87, 90, 
 91, 92. 
 
 Spinoza, 216. 
 
 Spirit (WKVIM), 75, 84, 87, 90, 
 
 91, 92, 94, 95, 185. 
 Stoics, 2, 5, 9, 52, 60, 63, 67, 
 
 74, 86, 112, 125, 158, 183, 
 
 1 88. 
 Supplication, 152, 153, 169, 
 
 170. 
 
 Symbolism, 48, 49. 
 Synagogue, 59. 
 Syncretism, 60, 79. 
 
 Thompson, J. M., 48. 
 
 Thoth, 158. 
 
 Timaeus, 61, 63, 65, 69, 70, 73, 
 
 80, 86. 
 
 rAetos, 120, 235. 
 rpoirf), 105. 
 
 Underhill, E., 217. 
 Union (with God), 27, 28, 
 I78ff. 
 
 Ur-Anthropos, 78. 
 i, 69, 70. 
 
 lS, 126. 
 
 Vanity (rO^os), 103, 105. 
 
 Vision of God, 192 ff. ; condi- 
 tions of, I94ff. ; Philo's 
 conception of, 198-202. 
 
 Webb, C. C. J., 216. 
 Wendland, P., 24, 208. 
 Windisch, H., 57, 101, 178. 
 Wisdom, 9, 62, 159, 162, 173, 
 
 174. 
 Wisdom of Solomon > 8, 159. 
 
 Zeller, 70, 80, 189, 210. 
 
 2 4 I 
 
INDEX 
 
 (2) REFERENCES IN PHILO 
 
 (Paragraphs numbered as in Cohn and Wendland's ed.) 
 
 De Opificio 
 
 Mundi 
 
 PAGE 
 
 Leg. Alleg. iii. contd. PAGE 
 
 j 
 
 
 t2 
 
 100 
 
 2OI, 213 
 
 8f 
 
 . 
 
 3 
 
 105 f. . 
 
 I 4 8 
 
 16 . 
 
 . 
 
 . 65 
 
 129 . 
 
 101 
 
 21 
 
 . 
 
 . 66 
 
 139 
 
 2I 9 
 
 23 ' 
 
 . 
 
 . 72 
 
 145 
 
 93 
 
 24 - 
 
 . . 
 
 . 163 
 
 161 . 
 
 75 
 
 45-52, 89-106 . 
 
 . 48 
 
 171 . 
 
 93 
 
 66 . 
 
 . 
 
 93 
 
 207 . 
 
 172 
 
 73 
 
 . 
 
 . 101 
 
 209 
 
 34 
 
 77 
 
 . 
 
 . 178 
 
 211 
 
 99, 100, 117 
 
 134 
 
 . 
 
 76 
 
 215 . 
 
 154 
 
 139 
 
 . 
 
 84 
 
 De Cherubim 
 
 
 146 . 
 169 . 
 
 
 
 . 109 
 104, 148 
 
 2 7 ff. . . 
 
 37 f- 
 
 34, M4 
 
 12 
 
 Legum Allegoriarum 
 
 Librii. 
 
 42 ff. . 
 
 55, 219 
 
 5 
 
 . . 
 
 . 66 
 
 48 . 
 
 . 212 
 
 22 
 
 
 . 66 
 
 49 
 
 . 179 
 
 34 
 
 , , 
 
 147 
 
 8iff. . 
 
 13 
 
 37 
 
 . 
 
 84, 185 
 
 130 . 
 
 13 
 
 48 f. . 
 65 . 
 
 
 
 . 149 
 173 
 
 De Sacrificiis Abelis et Caini 
 
 82 ff. . 
 
 
 . 222 
 
 3 
 
 J 
 
 
 
 
 o . 
 
 *75 
 
 97 
 
 
 
 93 
 
 60 . 
 
 . 212 
 
 107 . 
 
 
 . 136 
 
 123 . 
 
 
 Leg. Alleg. 
 
 ii. 
 
 
 Quod Deter ius Potiori in- 
 
 19 . 
 
 
 
 39 
 
 sidiari soleat 
 
 
 22 
 
 
 
 93 
 
 13 
 
 36 
 
 3 1 
 
 . 
 
 . 223 
 
 22 f. . 
 
 . 107 
 
 85 
 
 
 
 93 
 
 70 . 
 
 - 93 
 
 Leg. Alleg. 
 
 iii. 
 
 
 72 f. . 
 
 
 3 
 
 . 
 
 . 219 
 
 82-90 
 
 '. 81 
 
 27 . 
 
 . . 
 
 . 97 
 
 83 - 
 
 . 186 
 
 41 f. . 
 
 . 
 
 . 194 
 
 8 4 . 
 
 . 94 
 
 47 - 
 
 . 
 
 193 
 
 95 
 
 . 152 
 
 64 . 
 
 . 
 
 . 100 
 
 97 
 
 . 101 
 
 68 . 
 
 . 
 
 . 100 
 
 109 . 
 
 . 88 
 
 7i 
 
 . . 
 
 98 
 
 122 
 
 . 101 
 
 
 . . 
 
 86 
 
 139 
 
 . 76 
 
 78 
 
 . . 
 
 146 
 
 148 f. . 
 
 . 104 
 
 96 
 
 . 
 
 . 163 
 
 158 f. . 
 
 '95 
 
 242 
 
INDEX 
 
 De Posteritate Caini 
 
 PAGE 
 
 De Ebrietate 
 
 PAGfc 
 
 !5 
 
 . 200 
 
 44 
 
 12 
 
 22 
 
 12 
 
 49 ff. . 
 
 13 
 
 27 
 
 . 197 
 
 89 . . 
 
 13 
 
 31 
 
 97 
 
 147 . 
 
 . 22 3 
 
 59 . 
 
 . 114 
 
 De Sobrietate 
 
 
 105 f. 
 
 13 
 
 56 . 
 
 183 
 
 142 
 
 . 155 
 
 
 
 145 
 
 155 
 
 De Confusione 
 
 Lingu- 
 
 169 . . 
 
 . 166 
 
 arum 
 
 
 
 
 41 
 
 . 170 
 
 De Gigantibtis 
 
 
 97 
 
 . 96 
 
 6-15 . . 
 
 20ff. . 
 
 . 80 
 
 . 188 
 
 134 f. . 
 
 135 ^ 
 
 35 
 35 
 
 23 ... 
 29 ... 
 
 95 
 
 90 
 
 145 
 146 . 
 
 . 181 
 
 170, 182 
 
 40 ... 
 
 47 ... 
 
 . 90 
 . 190 
 
 De Migratione Abrahami 
 
 52 ... 
 
 . 225 
 
 2 
 
 . 205 
 
 53 ... 
 
 . 190 
 
 . 
 
 . . 12 
 
 
 
 54 ... 
 
 U : : : 
 
 . 213 
 . 191 
 
 140 
 
 9 
 3off. . 
 32 . 
 
 89 
 . 149, 224 
 . 49 
 
 210 f. . 
 
 . 113 
 
 34 f. - - 
 
 . 204 
 
 
 
 43 f- - 
 
 133 
 
 Quod Deus sit immutabilis 
 
 38 f. . . . . 12 
 
 g : : 
 
 . 169 
 
 65 ... 
 
 13 
 
 90 . 
 
 56 
 
 72 . .* . 
 
 . 100 
 
 96 . 
 
 . 56 
 
 76 ... 
 
 J 45 
 
 102 
 
 . 162 
 
 82 f. . 
 
 175 
 
 136 f. . 
 
 . 106 
 
 87 ... 
 
 . 226 
 
 I6 9 
 
 . 179 
 
 123 . 
 
 137 
 
 170 f. . 
 
 . 199 
 
 I34ff. . 
 
 . 109 
 
 173 ff 
 
 . . 169 
 
 
 
 181 . 
 
 . 165 
 
 De Agricultura 
 
 
 193 
 
 . 179 
 
 i ff. 
 
 37 
 
 
 
 
 31 
 
 IO7 
 
 Qiiis Rerum Divinarum 
 
 49 f. 
 
 **/ 
 
 IS4 
 
 Heres sit 
 
 
 96 f. .' ! 
 
 39 
 
 19 . 
 
 130 
 
 mff. . 
 
 13 
 
 21 
 
 . 123 
 
 136 ... 
 
 
 26 ff. . 
 
 . 130 
 
 
 
 29 
 
 ^ 1 5 
 
 De Plantatione 
 
 
 3 1 
 
 17, 155 
 
 18 . 
 
 164, 1 86 
 
 55* 
 
 . 1 86 
 
 22 ff. . 
 
 . 198 
 
 69 f. . 
 
 17, 205, 222 
 
 3 2ff. . . . 
 
 32 
 
 73 
 
 . 86 
 
 37 
 
 139 
 
 79 
 
 . 173 
 
 89 ... 
 
 145 
 
 90 ff. . 
 
 . 129 
 
 243 
 
INDEX 
 
 Quis Rerum Di-vinarum 
 
 
 De Somniis i. continued 
 
 PACK 
 
 Heres sit continued \ 
 93 
 
 'AGE 
 126 
 
 M : : : : 
 
 68 
 
 IOI 
 
 125 
 
 86 .... 
 
 172 
 
 io6ff. 
 
 102 
 
 91 .... 
 
 
 160 . 67 
 
 ,68 
 
 92 f 
 
 43 
 
 205 
 
 167 
 
 103 ff. . 
 
 171 
 
 255 
 
 95 
 
 142 . 
 
 1 66 
 
 265 . 
 
 190 
 
 143 .... 
 
 1 66 
 
 268 
 
 88 
 
 148 .... 
 
 197 
 
 273 
 
 153 
 
 151 f. .... 
 
 139 
 
 276 . . 
 
 138 
 
 163 .... 
 
 144 
 
 De Congressu Eruditionis 
 Gratia 
 11-24 
 
 4i 
 J 3 
 
 181 . 
 232 .... 
 236 .... 
 
 De Somniis ii. 
 
 148 
 196 
 196 
 
 67 i '. ' ! '. 
 
 14 
 
 45 .... 
 48 ff. . 
 
 79 
 14 
 
 De Fuga et Inventione 
 
 
 *T W *** * * * 
 
 61-68 
 
 48 
 
 12 f. . 
 
 28 ff. .... 
 54 f- .... 
 
 163 
 14 
 
 37 
 
 232 ff. . 
 242 ff. .... 
 252 .... 
 
 235 
 173 
 189 
 
 55 
 
 '37 
 
 353 
 
 73 
 
 58 .... 
 66ff. .... 
 
 138 
 
 165 
 
 De Abrahamo 
 
 
 69 f. .... 
 90 ff. . 
 
 85 
 232 
 
 8 .... 
 26 .... 
 
 119 
 
 120 
 
 IOI .... 
 
 161 
 
 41 .... 
 
 102 
 
 io8ff. . 
 
 162 
 
 47 .... 
 
 120 
 
 131 .... 
 
 107 
 
 55 
 
 *35 
 
 141 .... 
 
 194 
 
 79 f ! 
 
 200 
 
 203 f. . 
 
 49 
 94 
 
 99 .... 
 119 ff. . 
 151 
 
 208 
 14 
 
 De Mutatione Nominum 
 
 
 I56ft .... 
 
 12 
 
 9 f. . . . . 
 
 201 
 
 167-199 . 
 
 36 
 
 49 .... 
 
 100 
 
 200 .... 
 
 34 
 
 58 f. .... 
 65 .... 
 
 146 
 
 49 
 
 263 .... 
 268 f. . . .122 
 
 128 
 , 128 
 
 82 .... 
 129 .... 
 
 192 
 145 
 
 De Josepho 
 1-27 
 
 36 
 
 138 . 
 
 15 
 
 15 . 
 
 49 
 
 161 f. . 
 
 18 
 
 3 2ft. . . . 
 
 14 
 
 De Somniis i. 
 
 
 47 f. . . . . 
 
 112 
 
 9 .... 
 62 .... 
 66 .... 
 
 153 
 164 
 166 
 
 54ft .... 
 189 . 
 265 . . . . 
 
 :l 
 
 244 
 
INDEX 
 
 De Vita Mosis i. 
 
 PAGE 
 
 De Virtutibus 
 
 PAGE 
 
 4 .... 
 
 5O 
 
 145 f. 
 
 43 
 
 84, 222-226 
 
 50 
 
 169 . . . . 
 
 157 
 
 De Vita Mosis ii. (iii.) 
 6 .... 
 
 228 
 
 175 ff. 
 177 
 
 121 
 120 
 
 
 
 188 . 
 
 147 
 
 14 .... 
 36 .... 
 
 51 
 
 3 1 
 
 216 . 
 
 123 
 
 40 .... 
 
 
 De Praemiis et Poenis 
 
 
 48 .... 
 
 53 
 
 15 
 
 119 
 
 103 .... 
 
 33 
 
 26 
 
 199 
 
 147 . . . 72, 
 
 100 
 
 27, 30, 49 
 
 134 
 
 187 f 
 
 30 
 
 37ff . . . . 
 
 2O2 
 
 238 .... 
 
 147 
 
 39 
 
 I8 4 
 
 239 .... 
 
 17 
 
 70 . 
 
 136 
 
 De Decalogo 
 
 sff. . . . . 
 
 18-31 
 
 "3 
 
 116 . 
 
 De Exsecrationibus 
 163 . . . 
 
 153 
 
 118 
 
 87 .... 
 
 1 08 
 
 Legatio ad Gaium 
 
 
 134 .... 
 
 75 
 
 5 
 
 193 
 
 De Specialibus Legibus i. 
 36 .... 
 
 96 
 
 6f. . 
 
 Quaestiones in Genesim i.- 
 
 164 
 
 43 
 
 156 
 
 82 . 
 
 118 
 
 207 . 
 
 198 
 
 92 . 
 
 182 
 
 235 ff. "3> 
 260 ( = De Sacrific. ) 
 
 116 
 
 42 
 
 Quaestiones in Genesim ii. 
 42 f. . 
 
 121 
 
 266 .... 
 
 86 
 
 
 
 271 .... 
 
 54 
 
 Quaestiones in Genesim iii. 
 
 
 
 281 f. . 
 
 
 9 
 
 231 
 
 307 .... 
 
 144 
 
 190 f. . 
 
 41 
 
 318 .... 
 
 182 
 
 Quaestiones in Genesim iv. 
 
 
 
 319 .... 
 
 220 
 
 i 
 
 203 
 
 328 f. . 
 
 67 
 
 4 . 
 
 234 
 
 De Spec. Leg. iii. 
 
 
 64 . 
 
 101 
 
 I ff. . 
 
 12 
 
 140 . . . . 
 
 22 4 
 
 4-6 . . . . 
 
 16 
 
 203 .... 
 
 105 
 
 161 . 
 
 88 
 
 Quaestiones in Exodtim i.- 
 
 
 De Spec. Leg. iv. 
 
 
 15 
 
 117 
 
 49 f. .... 
 
 227 
 
 Quaestiones in Exodum ii. 
 
 
 
 75 .... 
 
 93 
 
 29 . 
 
 233 
 
 123 .... 
 
 87 
 
 Si 
 
 206 
 
 192 . 
 
 226 
 
 68 .... 
 
 I6 4 
 
 245 
 
PRINTED IN GREAT BRITAIN IQ 
 
 BY MORRISON AND GIBB LTD. 
 
 EDINBURGH 
 

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY 
 BERKELEY 
 
 Return to desk from which borrowed. 
 This book is DUE on the last date stamped below. 
 
 31952LU 
 
 
 JAN 1 
 
 REC'D L 
 
 APRS 1977 
 
 LD 21-100m-9 > '481B399sl6)476 
 
2361