a UC-NRLF SEXTUS EMPIBICUS AND GREEK SCEPTICISM A Dissertation for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the University of Bern MARY MILLS PATRICK CAMBRIDGE DEIGHTON BELL & CO. 1899 fr~ PREFACE THE following treatise on Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism has been prepared to supply a need much felt in the English language by students of Greek philosophy. For, while other schools of Greek philosophy have been exhaust- ively and critically discussed by English scholars, there are few sources of information available to the student who wishes to make himself familiar with the teachings of Pyrrhonism. The aim has been, accordingly, to give a concise presentation of Pyrrhonism in relation to its historical develop- ment and the scepticism of the Academy, with critical references to the French and German works existing on the subject. The time and manner of the connection of Sextus Empiricus with the Pyrrhonean School has also been dis- cussed. In the study of the works of Sextus, the Greek text of Immanuel Bekker, Berlin, 1842, has been used, with frequent consultation of the text of J. A. Fabricius, 1718, which was taken directly from the existing manuscripts of the works of vi PREFACE. Sextus. Eeferences to Diogenes Laertius and other ancient works have been carefully verified. The principal modern authors consulted are the following: Ritter, Oeschichte der Philosophic, 11 Auf., Hamburg, 183638. Zeller, Philosophic der Gi^iechen, 111 Auf., Leipzig, 187989. Lewes, History of Philosophy, Vol. I., London, 1866. Ueberweg, History of Philosophy, IV. ed., tran.sl by Morris, 1871. Brochard, Les Sceptiques Grecs, Paris, 1877. Brochard, PyrrJion et le Scepticism Primitive, No. 5, Ribot's Revue Phil., Pai i Saisset, Le Scepticism Aentsidfait-Pascal-Kant, Paris, 1867. Chaignet, Histoire de la Psychologic des Grecs, Paris, 188790. Haas, Leben des Sextus Empiricus, Burghausen, 1882. Natorp, Forschungen zur d'^llckte des Erkenntnis- problems bei den Alien, Berlin, 1884. Hirzel, Untersuchungen zu Cicero's philos< / Schriften, Leipzig, 188793. Pappenheim, Erlduterung zu des Scxtu* Empiricus Pyrrhoneischen Grundzugen, 11 il< MX i-. 1882. Pappenheim, Die Tropen der Qreichiach* filter, Berlin, IcSS.V Pappenheim, LebensverhdU'n i*se des Sextus Empw*icus, Berlin, 1887. Pappenheim, Der angcblichc Heraclitismus des Skep- tikers Ainesidemos, Berlin, 1887. PREFACE. vii Pappenheim, Der Sitz der Schule der Griechischen Skeptiker, Archiv fur Geschichte der Philosophic, 1, 1. S. 47, 1887. Maccoll, The Greek Sceptics from Pyrrho to Sextus, London, 1869. My grateful acknowledgments are due to Professor Dr. Ludwig Stein, Professor of Philo- sophy in the University of Bern, for valuable assistance in relation to the plan of the work, advice in respect to the best authorities to be consulted, and for its final revision. BERN, November 5, 1897. CONTENTS CHAPTER I. PAOB THE HISTORICAL RELATIONS OF SEXTUS EMPIRICUS. . . 1 His profession. The time when he lived. The place where he taught. The character of his writings. CHAPTER II. THE POSITION AND AIM OF PYERHONIC SCEPTICISM . . 88 Its origin. Its nomenclature. The criterion of Pyr- rhonism. ^rrox'n and arupa^la. CHAPTER III. THE TROPES OF PYRRHONIC SCEPTICISM 31 The ten Tropes of ^rox^. The five Tropes of Agrippa. The two Tropes. The eight Tropes against aetiology. CHAPTER IV. AENESIDEMUS AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF HERACLITUS . . 63 The statement of the problem. The principal theories on the subject. Critical examination of the subject. CHAPTER V. AN ANALYSIS OF PYRRHONIC SCEPTICISM 81 Pyrrhonism and Pyrrho. Pyrrhonism and the Academy. The strength and weakness of Pyrrhonism. CHAPTER I. The Historical Relations of Sextus Empiricus. Interest has revived in the works of Sextus Empiri- cus in recent times, especially, one may say, since the date of Herbart. There is much in the writings of Sextus that finds a parallel in the methods of modern philosophy. There is a common starting-point in the study of the power and limitations of human thought. There is a common desire to investigate the phenomena of sense-perception, and the genetic relations of man to the lower animals, and a common interest in the theory of human knowledge. While, however, some of the pages of Sextus' works would form a possible introduction to certain lines of modern philosophical thought, we cannot carry the analogy farther, for Pyrrhonism as a whole lacked the essential element of all philosophical progress, which is a belief in the possibility of finding and establishing the truth in the subjects investigated. Before beginning a critical study of the writings of Sextus Empiricus, and the light which they throw on the development of Greek Scepticism, it is necessary to make ourselves somewhat familiar with the environ- ment in which he lived and wrote. We shall thus be able to comprehend more fully the standpoint from which he regarded philosophical questions. Let us accordingly attempt to give some details of his life, including his profession, the time when he lived, 1 '2 Sextua Empiricus and Oreek Scepticism. tin- place of liis birth, tin- country in which he taught, ;in--. -!i > c. msidered Sextus a physician of the Empirical Sclioul. ()tli.-r evidence also is not war that Sextos bore this surname I-'. '-ius, in his edition of the works of Sextus, quotes from the Tabetta de >rum of Lambecius the statement that US was called Kmpl, 16 of his pO>'. in nu.'dicine. 2 Pseudo-Galen also refers to him as one of the directors of the Empirical School, and calls him Se^ro^ 6 e/jLTreipifcos. 3 His name is often found in the manu- scripts written with the surname, as for example at the end of Loyic II. 4 In other places it is found written 1 Diog. Laert. ix. 12, 116. 2 Fabricius Testimonia, p. 2. 3 Pseudo-Galen Isag. 4 ; Fabriciua Testimonia, p. 2. 4 Bekker J/aM. vin. 481. Historical Relations of Sextus Empiricus. 3 without the surname, as Fabricius testifies, where Sextus is mentioned as a Sceptic in connection with Pyrrho. The Sceptical School was long closely connected with the Empirical School of medicine, and the later Pyrrhoneans, when they were physicians, as was often the case, belonged for the most part to this school. Menedotus of Nicomedia is the first Sceptic, however, who is formally spoken of as an Empirical physician, 1 and his contemporary Theodas of Laodicea was also an Empirical physician. The date of Menedotus and Theodas is difficult to fix, but Brochard and Hass agree that it was about 150 A.D. 2 After the time of these two physicians, who were also each in turn at the head of the Sceptical School, 3 there seems to have been a definite alliance between Pyrrhonism and Empiricism in medicine, and we have every reason to believe that this alliance existed until the time of Sextus. The difficulty in regard to the name arises from Sextus' own testimony. In the first book of the Hy- potyposes he takes strong ground against the identity of Pyrrhonism and Empiricism in medicine. Although he introduces his objections with the admission that " some say that they are the same," in recognition of the close union that had existed between them, he goes on to say that " Empiricism is neither Scepticism itself, nor would it suit the Sceptic to take that sect upon himself, 4 for the reason that Empiricism maintains dog- M matically the impossibility of knowledge, but he would 1 Diog. ix. 12, 115. 3 Diog. ix. 12, 116. 2 Brochard Op. cit. Livre iv. p. 311. 4 Hyp. I. 236. 4 Sextus Empiricu8 and Greek >m prefer io IM-I..II- t. tin- M<-tho.i'. only medical scliool worthy of the Sceptic. "For this alone of all tin medical sects, does not proceed ra>hly it seems to me, in regard to unknown things, and not presume to say whether they are comprehensible or not, but it is guided by phenomena. 1 It will thus hat (In- Methodical School of medicine has a in relationship to Scepticism which is closer than that of tin- oilier inediral 91 ' W. know from th uony of Sextus himself that li- wa.- a physician. In one case he uses the first person for himself as a physician, 3 and in another he sp.-aks of Asclepius as "the founder of our science/' 4 and all his illustrations >how a bn-adth and variety of medical kno\. iiat only a physician could possess. He published a im-dical work which he refers to once as la-Tpiica v7ro/jLvyjfj,aTaf and again as efnreipiKa vTro/jLvq- yLtara. Thrs.- paaBBgei probably refer to the same work, 7 which, unfortunately for the solution of the diffi- cult question that we have in hand, is lost, and nothing is known of its contents. In apparent contradiction to his statement in II j- potyposes I., that Scepticism and Empiricism are opposed to each other, in that Empiricism denies the possibility of knowledge, and Scepticism makes no dogmatic statements of any kind, Sextus classes the Sceptics and Empiricists together in another instance, as regarding knowledge as impossible 8 a\\' ol pev i >m. \\MiiId it Miit tin- Sc.-ptic !, it sect upon liitn- ine belonged to it. His other s to the Empirical School, of a more favorable r, can be easily ex on the ground of the long coiitinm --I connection which had existed between tin- two schools. It i .{ii it.- possible to suppose that us was an Empiricist a part of his life, and wards found the Methodical School more to his liking, .in 1 such a change would not in any way have affected his stand as a physician. In regard to the exact time when Sextus Empiri I'm .!, we gain very little knowledge from internal dence, and outside sources of information are eq UIK < Ttain. Diogenes Laertius must have been a gene- ration younger than Sextus, as he mention -ciple ot'S. ' 'iriiinus, as an Empii ^i. 1 Tlic tini.' of Diog usually i first half of the third century A.D., 2 therefore Sextus cannot be brought forward later than the beginning of the century. is, liowever, directs his writings entirely against the Dogmatics, by whom he distinctly states that he means the Stoics,' and the influence of the Stoics began to decline in the beginning of the third century A.D. A fact often used as a help in fixing the date of Sext his mention of Basilidcs the Stoic, 4 d\\a /cal oi OTGH*OI, ax? oi Trepl 7ov Bd(ri\iS7]v. This Basil supposed to be identical with one of the teachers of Marcus Aurelius. 5 This is accepted by Zeller in the second edition of his Histwy of Philosophy, but not in the 1 Diog. ix. 12, 116. 4 Adv. Math. vin. 258. Ueberweg Hist, of Phil. p. 21. 5 Fabriciua Vita Sexti. s Hyp. i. 65. Historical Relations of Sextus Empiricus. 9 third, for the reason that Sextus, in all the work from which this reference is taken, i.e. Math. vn. XL, men- tions no one besides Aenesidemus, who lived later than the middle of the last century B.C. 1 The Basilides- referred to by Sextus may be one mentioned in a list of twenty Stoics, in a fragment of Diogenes Laertius, recently published in Berlin by Val Rose. 2 Too much importance has, however, been given to the relation of the mention of Basilides the Stoic to the question of the date of Sextus. Even if the Basilides referred to by Sextus is granted to have been the teacher of Marcus Aurelius, it only serves to show that Sextus lived either at the same time with Marcus Aurelius or after him, which is a conclusion that we must in any case reach for other reasons. The fact that has caused the greatest uncertainty in regard to the date of Sextus is that Claudius Galen in his works mentions several Sceptics who were also physicians of the Empirical School, 3 and often speaks of Herodotus, supposed to be identical with the teacher of Sextus given by Diogenes Laertius, 4 but makes no reference whatever to Sextus. As Galen's time passes the limit of the second century A.D., we must either infer that Sextus was not the well-known physician that he was stated to be by Pseudo-Galen, and con- sequently not known to Galen, or that Galen wrote before Sextus became prominent as a Sceptic. This silence on the part of Galen in regard to Sextus increases the doubt, caused by Sextus 7 own criticism of the Empirical School of medicine, as to his having 1 Zeller Op. cit. in. 8. 3 Zeller, in. 7. 2 Brochard Op. cit. iv. 315. 4 Diog. xi. 12, 116. Jo SeXttu Kinjf'trlcua and Greek Scepticism. an KmpiriciM. The i' Bextaa early iii tip; third century, and that of Diogenes perhaps a little Inter than the middle, were it not that early in tin- third century the Stoics M to decline in influence, and could hardly have vxcitr.l tin- w.-umth of ai displayed by Se We must then suppose that Sextus wrote at the very i o{ tin- second a and either that Galen did not know him, or that Galen's books were pub- li>hed before Sextus became prominent either as a physician or as a Sceptic. The fact that he may heen better known as the latter than as the former does iifliciently account for (Jal.-n's >il-nce, as other tiofl are i 1 hy him of less importance than . nd the latter, even if not as great a phy> den asserts, was certainly both a Sc and a phy>irian, and must have belonged to one of the schools so thorou _ y Galen either the Knipiriral i the Methudic-al. Therefore, if Sextua were a contemporary of Galen, he was so far removed i'roin the eircle of Galen's acquaintances hare made DO impression upon him, rith- i Coptic 01 a physician, a supposition that is very improbable We must then fix the date of Sextus late in the second century, and conclude that the climax of his public Career was ivaehed after Galen had finished those of his writings which are still extant. 1 Pappenheim Lebetis. Ver. Sex. Em. 30. Zfllcr Urundriss der Get. der Phil. p. 260. Historical Relations of Sextus Empiricus. 11 Sextus has a Latin name, but he was a Greek ; we know this from his own statement. 1 We also know that lie must have been a Greek from the beauty and facility of his style, and from his acquaintance with Greek dialects. The place of his birth can only, however, be conjectured, from arguments indirectly derived from his writings. His constant references throughout his works to the minute customs of different nations ought to .give us a clue to the solution of this question, but strange to say they do not give us a decided one. Of these references a large number, however, relate to the customs of Libya, showing a minute knowledge in regard to the political and religious customs of this land that he displays in regard to no other country except Egypt. 2 Fabricius thinks Libya was not his birth place because of a reference which he makes to it in the Hypotyposes 0patc)v Se KOI TairovXwv (Aifivnv e edvos roOro). 3 This conclusion is, however, entirely unfounded, as the explanation of Sextus simply shows that the people whom he was then addressing were not familiar with the nations of Libya. Suidas speaks of two men called Sextus, one from Chseronea and one from Libya, both of whom he calls Sceptics, and to one of whom he attributes Sextus' books. All authorities -agree in asserting that great confusion exists in the works of Suidas ; and Fabricius, Zeller, and Pappenheim place no weight upon this testimony of Suidas. 4 Haas, 1 Adv. Math. A. 246; Hyp. i. 152; Hyp. in. 211, 214. 2 Haas Op. cit. p. 10. 3 Hyp. in. 213. 4 Pappenheim Lebens. Ver. Sex. Em. 5, 22 ; Zeller Op. cit. in. 39 ; JFabricius Vita de Sextus. 12 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. however, contends 1 that it is unreasonable to suppose tli;it tliis confusion could go as far as to attribute the writings of Sextus Kmpiricus to Sextus of Chaeronea, and also ni.iki the latt'-r a Sceptic, and he considers it f,n more reasonable to accept the testimony of Suidas, coincides so well with the internal evidence of Se\tu.>' writings in regard to his native land. ! in v< -rtheless evident, from his familiarity with the customs, language, and laws of Athens, Alexandria and Rome, that he must have resided at some time in each of these cities. Of all the problems connected with the historical Is of the life of Sextus, the one that is the most difficult <>l' solution, and also the most important for our iit purpose of making a critical study of his teach- ing, is to fix of tin- Sceptical School during the time that he was in charge of it. The Hypotyposes are lectures delivered in public in that period of his life. Where then were they delivered ? "NV that the Sceptical School must have had a long continued exis- tence as a definite philosophical movement, although some have contended otherwise. The fact of its exis- tence as an organized direction of thought, is demon- strated by its formulated teachings, and the list L by Diogenes Laertius of its principal leaders, 2 and by references from the writings of Sextus. In the first book of Hypotyposes he refers to Scepticism as a distinct system of philosophy, /cat Trjv Sidtcpio-iv r^ (T/eev/rea)? CLTTO TMV irapaKei^evayv avrfj rjyrjrij<; 6 6/10? SieXeyero, evravda eye* vvv SiaXeyofjiai. Therefore the school nn been re- moved from Alexandria, in or before tin- time of the xtus, to some otl re The Hypoty- poses are from beginning to end a direct attack on the Dogmatics; therefore must have taught ei in some city where th itic philosophy was strong, or in some rival philosophical cent! Ihipotyposes show also that the writer had access to some large library. Al >; an dri a. Rome and Athens are the three plaoefl the most probable for selection for such a purpose. For whatever reason the seat of the school was removed from Alexandria by the master of Sextus, or by himselt, IK. in the place \ had so long been united with the Knipirical School of medicine, Athens AvoiiM B6( OMMri suitable city mntinu in the land where Pyrrhonism first had its birth. Sextus, however, in one instance, in referring to things invisible because of their outward relations, says in illustration, "as the city of Athens is invisible to us at present." 1 In other p lao he contrasts the Athen- ians with the people whom he is addressing, equally with the Alexaiulrians, thus puttm- At liens as well as Alexandria out of the question. Of the ditiVivnt writers on Sextus Empiricus, those who have treated this part of the subject most critically are Haas and Pappenheim. We will therefore consider, somewhat at length, the results presented by the.s authors. Haas thinks that the Hypotyposes were delivered in Rome for the following reasons. Sextus" 1 Hyp. ii. 98. Historical Relations of Sextus Empiricus. 15 lectures must have been given in some centre of philo- sophical schools and of learning. He never opposes- Roman relations to those of the place where he is speaking, as he does in regard to Athens and Alexan- dria. He uses the name "Romans" only three times, 1 once comparing them to the Rhodians, once to the Persians, and once in general to other nations. 2 In the first two of these references, the expression " among the Romans" in the first part of the antithesis is followed by the expression, "among us," in the. second part, which Haas understands to be synonymous. The third reference is in regard to a Roman law, and the use of the word ' Roman ' does not at all show that Sextus was not then in Rome. The character of the laws referred to by Sextus as Trap' t]^lv shows that they were always Roman laws, and his definition of law 3 is especially a definition of Roman law. This argument might, it would seem, apply to any part of the Roman Empire,, but Haas claims that the whole relation of law to custom as treated of by Sextus, and all his statements of customs forbidden at that time by law, point to Rome as the place of his residence. Further, Haas considers the Herodotus mentioned by Galen 4 as a pro- minent physician in Rome, to have been the predecessor and master of Sextus, in whose place Sextus says that he is teaching. 5 Haas also thinks that Sextus' refuta- tion of the identity of Pyrrhonism with Empiricism evidently refers to a paragraph in Galen's Subfiguraiio 1 Haas Op. cit. p. 15. 2 Hyp. i. 149, 152; m. 211. 3 Hyp. i. 146. 4 Galen depuls. iv. 11 ; Bd. ym. 751. 5 Hyp. in. 120. 16 Sextus Empiricus a/nd <> ism. Empirl<:f t 'jp08e8, which would be more natural if rote in the same place. According to Haas, every thing in internal e and outward testimony, points to Rome as having been the city where S occupied his p.Mi ion as the head of the Sceptical School. Com in. 4 nuw to the position of Pappenheim on this subject, we find that he takes very decided ground at of the Sceptical School h, jn in Rome, even for a short time, in his latest publication ling it. 2 This opinion is the xesult of late Bi on the part of Pappenhe-im, for in his work on the Lcbensvcrhaltnisse des Sextus Empiiwus Berlin 1875, he says, "Dass Herodotus in Rom lebte sagt Galen. Vermuthlich auch Sextus." His reasons given in the later article for not connecting the Sceptical School at all with Rome are as follows. He finds no proof of the influence of Scepticism in Rome, as Cicero remarks that Pyrrhonism is extinct, 3 and he also gives weight to the well-known sarcastic saying of Seneca, Qc'ts est qui Iradat praecepta l\/rrhoni# ! 4 While Haas claims that Sextus would naturally seek one of the centres of dogmatism, in order most effectively to combat it, Pappenheim, on the contrary, contends that it would have been foolishness on the part of Sextus to think of 1 Galen Sub. Em. 123 B 126 D. (Basileae, 1542). 2 Pappenheim Sitz der Skeptischen Schule. Archiv fiir Getchichte der Phil. 1888. 3 Cicero De Oral. in. 17, 62. 4 Seneca nat. qu. vn. 32. Historical Relations of Sextus Empiricus. 17 starting the Sceptical School in Rome, where Stoicism was the favored philosophy of the Roman Emperors; and when either for the possible reason of strife between the Empirical and Methodical Schools, or for some other cause, the Pyrrhonean School was removed from Alex- andria, Pappenheim claims that all testimony points to the conclusion that it was founded in some city of the East. The name of Sextus is never known in Roman literature, but in the East, on the contrary, literature speaks for centuries of Sextus and Pyrrho. The Hy- poty poses, especially, were well-known in the East, and references to Sextus are found there in philosophical and religious dogmatic writings. The Emperor Julian makes use of the works of Sextus, and he is frequently quoted by the Church Fathers of the Eastern Church. 1 Pappenheim accordingly concludes that the seat of Pyrrhonism after the school was removed from Alex- andria, was in some unknown city of the East. In estimating the weight of these arguments, we must accept with Pappenheim the close connection of Pyrrhonism with Alexandria, and the subsequent influ- ence which it exerted upon the literature of the East. All historical relations tend to fix the permanent seat of Pyrrhonism, after its separation from the Academy, in Alexandria. There is nothing to point to its removal from Alexandria before the time of Menodotus, who is the teacher of Herodotus, 2 and for many reasons to be considered the real teacher of Sextus. It was Menodo- tus who perfected the Empirical doctrines, and who brought about an official union between Scepticism and 1 Fabricius de Sexto Empirico Testimonia. 2 Diog. ix. 12, 116. 1^ Sextus Empiincux and (Ireck Scepticism. Kmpiricism, arid who gave Pyrrhonism in -^reat measure, tlie f'dii.t that it enjoyed in Alexandria, and who appears to have been the most powerful influen- the school, from the time of Aenesidemus to that of Sextus. Furthermore, Sextus' familiaiity with Al- drian customs bears the imprint of original knowledge, and he cannot, as Zcller implies, be accepted as simply quoting. One could hardly agree with Zoller, 1 the familiarity sliown by Sextus with the customs of both Alexandria and Rome in the Hypotyposes does not necessarily show that he ever lived in either of those places, because a lar^v part of his works are com- pilations from other books; but on the contrary, the careful reader of Sextus' works must find in all of them much evidence <>f per-onal knowledge of Alexandria, Athens and Rom,-. A part of Sextus' books also may have been \vri in Alexandria. Tlpbs v(riKovs could have been written in Alexandria- If thei\oao<})oufjLevov<; avT(Z TOW \6ya)v, &v apicfroi ol IIvpp(t)veioi. } Suidas calls Favorinus a great author and learned in all science and philosophy, 1 aud Favorinus made Rome the centre of his teaching and writin-. j 1 '. -d by Zeller at MO- !.")<) A.D., therefore Pyrrhonism was known in Rome shortly before the time of Sextus. The whole tone of the Hypotyposes, with the constant references to the Stoics as living present opponents, shows thai tin >< ir.-tures must have been delivered in one of the centres of Stoic !ex- andria and Athens are out of the question, all testimony points to Rome as having been the seat of the Pyrrho- IH an School, for at least a part of the time that Sextus was at its head. We would then accept the teacher of Sextus, in v ace he says he taught, as the Hero- dotus so often referred to by Galen 3 who lived in Rome. <[uent references to Asdepiades, whom he mentions ten different times by name in his \\-orl. speak in favour of Rome in the matter under discussion, as Asdepiades made that city one of the centres of medical culture. On the other hand, the fact that there is no trace of the Hypotyposes in later Roman literature, with the one exception of the works of Hip- polytus, as opposed to the wide-spread knowledge of them shown in the East for centuries, is incontestable historical proof that the Sceptical School could not long have had its seat at Rome. From the two passages given above from Sextus' work against physics, he must 1 Zellor Op. cit. p. 67. 3 Galen vm. 751. 2 Brochard Op. cit. 329. 4 Bekker Index. Historical Relations of Sextus Empiricus. 21 either have written that book in Alexandria, it would seem, or have quoted those passages from some other work. May we not then conclude, that Sextus was at the head of the school in Home for a short time, where it may have been removed temporarily, on account of the difficulty with the Empiricists, implied in Hyp. I. 236-241, or in order to be better able to attack the Stoics, but that he also taught in Alexandria, where the real home of the school was certainly found ? There it probably came to an end about fifty years after the time of Sextus, and from that centre the Sceptical works of Sextus had their wide-spread influence in the East. The books of Sextus Empiricus furnish us with the best and fullest presentation of ancient Scepticism which has been preserved to modern times, and give Sextus the position of one of the greatest men of the Sceptical School. His works which are still extant are the Pyrrhonean Hypotyposes in three volumes, and the two works comprising eleven books which have been united in later times under the title of ?rpo9 ^aOri^an- KOVS, one of which is directed against the sciences in general, and the other against the dogmatic philoso- phers. The six books composing the first of these are written respectively against grammarians, rhetoricians, geometricians, arithmeticians, astronomers and music- ians. The five books of the latter consist of two against the logicians, two against physics, and one against systems of morals. If the last short work of the first book directed against the arithmeticians is com- bined with the one preceding against the geometricians, as it well could be, the two works together would be divided into ten different parts; there is evidence to -- Sextua Empiincua and Greek Scepticism. show that in ancient times such a division was in There were two other works of Sextus which are now lost, tin- medical work before referred to, and a book entitled Trepl yfrvxns. The character of the extant works of Sextus is similar, as they are all directed either against science or against the dogmatics, and they all present the negative side of Pyrrhonism. The nay of arguments comprising the subject-matter, often repeated in the same and different forms, are vidcntly taken largely from the Sceptical works which Sextus had resource to, and are, in fact, a summing up of all the wisdom of the S School. The style of books is fluent, and the Greek reminds one of Plutarch and Thucyd'uh's, and although Scxtus does not claim originality, l, u t j, n -< -nts in all cases the ; inents of the Sceptic, yet the illustrations and the form in which the argument* are presented, often bear the marks of his own thought, and are char and there by a wealth of humor that has not been sufficiently noticed in the critical works on Sextus. Of all the anthers who have reviewed Sextus, Brochard is the only one who seems to have understood and appre- ciated his humorous side. We shall now proceed to the consideration of the general position and aim of Pyrrhonism. 1 Diog. ix. 12, lie. CHAPTER II. The Position and Aim of Pyrrhonism. The first volume of the Pyrrhonean Hypotyposes gives the most complete statement found in any of the works of Sextus Empiricus of the teachings of Pyrrho- nism and its relation to other schools of philosophy. The chief source of the subject-matter presented is a work of the same name by Aenesidemus, 1 either directly used by Sextus, or ^through the writings of those who followed Aenesidemus. The comprehensive title Hvppdt- veioi vTTOTVTrdcKjeis was very probably used in general to designate courses of lectures given by the leaders of the Sceptical School. In the opening chapters of the Hypotyposes Sextus undertakes to define the position and aim of Pyrrho- nism. 2 In introducing his subject he treats briefly of the differences between philosophical schools, dividing them into three classes ; those which claim that they have found the truth, like the schools of Aristotle and Epicurus and the Stoics; those which deny the possibility of finding it, like that of the Academicians ; and those that still seek it, like the Sceptical School. The accu- sation against the Academicians, that they denied the possibility of finding the truth, was one that the Sceptics were very fond of making. We shall discuss the justice of it later, simply remarking here, that to affirm the 1 Diog. ix. 11, 78. 2 Hyp. i. 3, 4. h'iit,iricw* tmd Gh incomprehensibility <>{ the uukn ..as a form of expression that, tin- Pyrrhonists them- tiinc.^ 1" into, notwithstanding their ca. avoidance of dogmatic itatementfc 1 After defining tin- three kind* ul' philosophy as KiatiCj ill*- Academic ami the Sceptic, Sextu minds his hearers tliat he does not speak dogmatically in anything that he says, but that he intends simply to Sceptical arguments historically, and as th -y appear to him. He characterizes his treatment of 'ihject as general rather than critical, including a statt niriit of the character of Scepticism, its idea, its principles, its manner of iva its criterion and aim, and a piv.M-ntation of thu Tropes, or aspects of doubt, and the Sceptical formulae and the distinction bet\\. schools of philo- sophy. 2 The result of all the gradual changes which I development of thought had brought about in the out- ward relations of the Sceptical School, was to increase the earnestness of the claim of the Sceptics to be simply followers of Pyrrho, the great founder of the movement. in discussing the names given to the Sceptics, Sex t us precedence very decidedly to the title " Pyrrho- nean," because Pyrrho appears the best representative of Scepticism, aud more prominent than all who before him occupied themselves with it. 3 It was a question much discussed among philoso- phers in ancient times, whether Pyrrhonism should be considered a philosophical sect or not. Thus we find 1 Adv. Math. viii. 191. 3 Hyp. i. 5, 6. 3 Eyp. i. 7. The Position and Aim of Pyrrhonism. 25 that Hippobotus in his work entitled Trepl aipevewv, written shortly before our era, does not include Pyrrho- nism among the other sects. 1 Diogenes himself, after some hesitation remarking that many do not consider it a sect, finally decides to call it so. 2 Sextus in discussing this subject calls Scepticism an aycoyrj, or a movement, rather than a a2pi>'ricu8 and Greek Scepticism. philosophical system without a do^ma, for tic Haims that h- has no dogma. 1 The Scept supposed to state a decided opinion, but only to say what appears to him. Even the Sceptical formulae, such as "Nothing more/' 2 or "I decide nothing/' 3 or ""All is false," include themselves with other things. The only statements that the Sceptic can make, are in regard to his own sensations. He cannot deny that he is warm or cold or hungry. ;tas n -plies to the charge that the Sceptics deny phenomena by refuting it. 4 Tli ic does not deny phenomena. beo*CI86 they are the only criteria by which he < an regulate his actions. "We call the criterion of the Sceptical Seh<>ol tli ]henomenon, meaning by this name tlie idea of it." 5 Phenoir, the only things which the Sceptic does not deny, and he guides his ] by them. They are, however, subjective. Sextus di>- tinctly affirms that sensations are the phenomena,* and that they lie in susceptibility and voluntary feeling, and that they constitute the appearances of obje< We see from this that Sextus makes the only reality to consist in subjective experience, but he does not follow this to its logical conclusion, and doubt the existence of anything outside of mind. He rather takes for granted that there is a something unknown outside, about which the Sceptic can make no assertions. Phenomena are the criteria according to which the Sceptic orders his daily life, as he cannot be entirely inactive, and they 1 Hyp. i. 12. 5 Hyp. i. 19. 2 Hyp. i. 14. 6 Hyp. i. 22; Diog. ix. 11, 105. * Hyp. i. 14. ' Hyp. i. 22. * Hyp. i. 19. The Position and Aim of Pyrrhonism. 27 affect life in four different ways. They constitute the guidance of nature, the impulse of feeling; they give rise to the traditions of customs and laws, and make the teaching of the arts important. 1 According to the tradition of laws and customs, piety is a good in daily life, but it is not in itself an abstract good. The Sceptic of Sextus' time also inculcated the teaching of the arts, as indeed must be the case with professing physicians, as most of the leading Sceptics were. Sextus says, "" We are not without energy in the arts which we undertake." 2 This was a positive tendency which no philosophy, however negative, could escape, and the Sceptic tried to avoid inconsistency in this respect, by separating his philosophy from his theory of life. His philosophy controlled his opinions, and his life was governed by phenomena. The aim of Pyrrhonism was ataraxia in those things which pertain to opinion, and moderation in the things which life imposes. 3 In other words, we find here the same natural desire of the human being to rise above and beyond the limitations which pain and passion impose, which is expressed in other forms, and under other names, in other schools of philosophy. The method, however, by which ataraxia or peace of mind could be reached, was peculiar to the Sceptic. It is a state of psychological equilibrium, which results from the equality of the weight of different arguments that are opposed to each other, and the consequent impossi- bility of affirming in regard to either one, that it is correct. 4 The discovery of ataraxia was, in the first 1 Hyp. i. 23. 2 Hyp. i. 24. 3 Hyp. i. 25. 4 Hyp. i. 26. 28 Sextus Empiricua and Greek & ],f'irlfim. instance, apparently accidental, for while the So withhold his opinion, unable to decide what things were true, and what things were false, ataraxia fortunately followed. 1 After he had begun to philosophize, with a < to discriminate in regard to ideas, and to separate the true from the false 2 during the time of eVo;^;, or suspension of judgement, ataraxia followed as if by chance, as the shadow follows the body. 3 The Sceptic in seeking ataraxia in the things of opinion, does not entirely escape from suffering from n-ations. He is not wholly undisturbed, for h is sometimes cold and hungry, and so on. 4 He claims, nevertheless:, that he suffers less than the dogmatist,, who is beset with two kinds of suffering, one from the feelings themselves, and also from the conviction that they are by nature an evil." To the Sceptic nothing is in itself either an evil or a good, and so he thinks that "he escapes from difficult r." 6 For instance, he who considers riches a good in themselves, is unhappy in the loss of them, and in possession of thom is in fear of losing them, while the Sceptic, remembering the Sceptical saying " No more," is untroubled in whatever condition he may be found, as the loss of riches is no more an evil than the possession of them is a good. 7 For he who considers anything good or bad by nature is always troubled, and when that which seemed good is not present with him, he thinks that he is tortured by that which is by nature bad, and follows after what he 1 Hyp. i. 26. Hyp. i. 30. 2 Diog. ix. 11, 107. 5 Hyp. i. 30. 3 Hyp. i. 29. Hpy. i. 30 ; Diog. ix. 11, 61. 7 Adv. Math. xi. 146160. The Position and Aim of Pyrrhonism. 29 thinks to be good. Having acquired it, however, he is not at rest, for his reason tells him that a sudden change may deprive him of this thing that he considers a good. 1 The Sceptic, however, endeavours neither to avoid nor seek anything eagerly. 2 Ataraxia came to the Sceptic as success in painting the foam on a horse's mouth came to Apelles the painter. After many attempts to do this, and many failures, he gave up in despair, and threw the sponge at the picture that he had used to wipe the colors from the painting with. As soon as it touched 'the picture it produced a representation of the foam. 3 Thus the Sceptics were never able to attain to ataraxia by examining the anomaly between the phenomena and the things of thought, but it came to them of its own accord just when they despaired of finding it. The intellectual preparation for producing ataraxia, consists in placing arguments in opposition to each other, both in regard to phenomena, and to things of the intellect. By placing the phenomenal in opposition to the phenomenal, the intellectual to the intellectual, and the phenomenal to the intellectual, and vice versa, the present to the present, past, and future, one will find that no argument exists that is incontrovertible. It is not necessary to accept any statement whatever as true, and consequently a state of eVo^r; may always be main- tained. 4 Although ataraxia concerns things of the opinion, and must be preceded by the intellectual pro- cess described above, it is not itself a function of the intellect, or any subtle kind of reasoning, but seems to 1 Hyp. i. 27. 2 Hyp. i. 28. 3 Hyp. i. 28, 29. * Hyp. i. 3235. 30 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. !) rather a unique form of moral perfection, leading to happiness, or is itse If happiness. It was the aim of Scepticism to know nothing, and to assert nothing in regard to any subject, but at the same time not to affirm that knowledge on all subjects is impossible, and consequently to have the attitude of still seeking. The standpoint of Pyrrhonism was ma- n nalistic. We find from the teachings of Sextus that he affirmed the non-existence of the soul, 1 or the ego, and denied absolute < tt altogether. 2 The intro- ductory statements of Diogenes regarding Pyrrhonism \\ould ai^ree with this standpo There is no criterion of truth in Scepticism. We cannot prove that the phenomena represent objects, or find out what the relation of phenomena to objects is. Tin -re is no criterion to tell us which one is true of all the different representations of the same object, and of all tL ties of sensation that arise through the many phases of relativity of the conditions which con- trol the character uf the phenomena. iy effort to find the truth can deal only with phenomena, and absolute reality can never be known. 1 .I'lr. Math. \ ,;>. ii. 32. * Adv. Math. xi. 140. 3 Diog. ix. 11,61. CHAPTER III. The Sceptical Tropes. The exposition of the Tropes of Pyrrhonism consti- tutes historically and philosophically the most important part of the writings of Sextus Empiricus. These Tropes represent the sum total of the wisdom of the older Sceptical School, and were held in high respect for centuries, not only by the Pyrrhoneans, but also by many outside the narrow limits of that School. In the first book of the Hypotyposes Sextus gives two classes of Tropes, those of eVo^ and the eight Tropes of Aeneside- mus against Aetiology. The Tropes of eVo^ are arranged in groups of ten, five and two, according to the period of the Sceptical School to which they belong ; the first of these groups is historically the most important, or the Ten Tropes of 67ro%?;, as these are far more closely connected with the general development of Scepticism, than the later ones. By the name T^OTTO? or Trope, the Sceptic understood a manner of thought, or form of argument, or standpoint of judgement. It was a term common in Greek philo- sophy, used in this sense, from the time of Aristotle. 1 The Stoics, however, used the word with a different meaning from that attributed to it by the Sceptics.' 2 Stephanus and Fabricius translate it by the Latin word modus, 3 and rpovro? also is often used interchangeably 1 Pappenheim Erlauterung Pyrrh. Grundzugen, p. 35. 2 Diog. i. 76 ; Adv. Math. vm. 227. 3 Fabricius, Cap. xiv. 7. 32 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. with the word \6yos by Sextus, ]) Laertius, ;in Empi/ricus "ud Greek Scepticism. also, ratify to ;i time of greater antiquity than tliat of A .us. The name Trope was well known in ancient thins, and the number ten reminds us of the ten opfH^m-j; principles of Pythagoras, and the ten IGS of Aristotle, the fourth of which was the same Tii- eighth Trope. The terminology, however, with very few exceptions, points to a later period than t of Pyrrho. Zeller points out a number of expressions in both Diogenes' and Sextus' exposition of the Tropes, which could not date back farther than the time of Aen> i i nuis. 1 One of the most striking features of tin- \\hole presentation of the Tropes, especially as given by Sextus, is their mosaic character, stamping them not as th \\ork of one person, but as a growth, and also an agglutinous growth, lacking very decidedly the sym- iii -try of thought that the work of one mind would ha shown. At the time of the separation of Pyrrhonism from the A'-adriny, no other force was as strong in giving life to the school as the systematic treatment by Aenesidemus of the Ten Tropes of eVo^r?. The reason of this is evident. It was not that the ideas of the Sceptical Trop - wore original with Aenesidemus, but because a > 1 . ti 1 1 n . >r atement of belief is always a far more powerful influence than principles which are vaguely understood and accepted. There is always, however, the danger to the Sceptic, in making a statement even of the prin- ciples of Scepticism, that the psychological result would be a dogmatic tendency of mind, as we shall see later the case, even with Aenesidemus himself. That 1 Zeller Op. tit. p. I The Sceptical Tropes. 35 the Sceptical School could not escape the accusation of dogmatizing, from the Dogmatics, even in stating the grounds of their Scepticism, we know from Diogenes. 1 To avoid this dogmatic tendency of the ten Tropes, Sextus makes the frequent assertion that he does not affirm things to be absolutely true, but states them as they appear to him, and that they may be otherwise from what he has said. 2 Sextus tells us that " Certain Tropes, ten in number, for producing the state of eVo^r; have been handed down from the older Sceptics." 3 He refers to them in another work as the "Tropes of Aenesidemus." 4 There is no evidence that the substance of these Tropes was changed after the time of Aenesidemus, although many of the illustrations given by Sextus must have been of a later date, added during the two centuries that elapsed between the time of Aenesidemus and Sextus. In giving these Tropes Sextus does not claim to offer a systematic methodical classification, and closes his list of them, in their original concise form, with the remark, " We make this order ourselves." 5 The order is given differently by Diogenes, and also by Favorinus. 6 The Trope which Sextus gives as the tenth is the fifth given by Diogenes, the seventh by Sextus is the eighth given by Diogenes, the fifth by Sextus, the seventh by Diogenes, the tenth by Diogenes, the eighth by Sextus. Diogenes says that the one he gives as the ninth Favorinus calls the eighth, and Sextus and Aenesidemus the tenth. This statement does not 1 Diog. ix. 11, 102. 4 Adv. Math. vn. 345. 2 Hyp. i. 4, 24. 5 Hyp. i. 38. 3 Hyp. 1.36. * Diog. ix. 11. 87. 36 Sextiw Empiricus and QreA N //' correspond with the list of the Tropes which Sextus gives, proving that Diogenes took some other text that of Sextus as his authority. 1 The difference in the order of the Tropes shows, also, that the order was not considered a matter of gn-at importance. Then marked contrast in the spirit of the two presentations of the Tropes given by Sextus and Diogenes. The former gives them not only as an orator, but as one who feels that he is defending his own cause, and the school of which he is th- against mortal enemies, while Diogenes relates them as an historian. Pappenht im tries to pro ve 2 that Aenesidem us origin- ally gave only nine Tropes in his Pyrrhonean Hypoty- poses, as Aristocles mentions only nine in referring to the Tropes of Aenesidemus, and that the tenth was added later. Had this been the case, however, the fact would surely have been mentioned either by Diogenes or Sextus, who both refer to the ten Tropes of Aene- sidcinus. The Tropes claim to prove that the character of phenomena is so relative and changeable, that certain knowledge cannot be based upon them, and as we have shown, there is no other criterion of knowledge for the So-ptir than phenomena. 3 All of the Tropes, except the tenth, are connected with sense-perception, and re- late to the difference of the results obtained through tin senses under different circumstances. They may be divided into two classes, i.e., those based upon differ- ences of our physical organism, and those based upon 1 Diog. ix. 11, 87. 2 Pappenhcim, Die Tropen der Griechen, p. 23. s Hyp. i. 22. The Sceptical Tropes. 37 external differences. To the first class belong the first, second, third and fourth ; to the second class, th'e fifth, sixth, seventh and eighth, and also the ninth. The eighth, or that of relation, is applied objectively both by Sextus and Diogenes in their treatment of the Tropes, and is not used for objects of thought alone, but princi- pally to show the relation of outward objects to each other. The tenth is the only one which has a moral significance, and it has also a higher subjective value than the others ; it takes its arguments from an entirely different sphere of thought, and deals with metaphysical and religious contradictions in opinion, and with the question of good and evil. That this Trope is one of the oldest, we know from its distinct mention in connec- tion with the foundation theories of Pyrrho, by Dio- genes. 1 In treating of the subjective reasons for doubt as to the character of external reality, the Sceptics were very near the denial of all outward reality, a point, how- ever, which they never quite reached. There is evidently much of Sextus' own thought mixed with the illustrations of the Tropes, but it is impossible to separate the original parts from the material that was the common property of the Sceptical School. Many of these illustrations show, however, perfect famil- iarity with the scientific and medical teachings of the time. Before entering upon his exposition of the Tropes, Sextus gives them in the short concise form in which they must first have existed 2 (i) Based upon the variety of animals, (ii) Based upon the differences between men. 1 Diog. ix. 11, 61. 2 Hyp. i. 3638. 38 Sextua Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. (iii) Based upon differences in the constitution of the sense organs. (iv) Based upon circumstances. (v) Based upon position, distance and place. (vi) Based upon mixtures. (vii) Based upon the quantities and constitutions of objects. (viii) Relation. (ix) Based upon frequency or rarity of occurences. (x) Based upon systems, customs and laws, mythical beliefs, and dogmatic opinions. Although Sextus is careful not to dogmatise regard- ing the arrangement of the Tropes, yet there is in his clu-silication of them a regular gradation, from the argu- ments based upon differences in animals to those in man, first considering the latter in relation to the phy>i- cal constitution, and then to circumstances outside of us, and finally the treatment of metaphysical and moral differences. The First Trope. 1 That the same mental repre- sentations are not found in different animals, may be inferred from their differences in constitution resulting from their different origins, and from the variety in their organs of sense. Sextus takes up the five senses in order, giving illustrations to prove the relative results of the mental representations in all of them, as for example the subjectivity of color 2 and sound. 3 All knowledge of objects through the senses is relative an.l not absolute. Sextus does not, accordingly, confine the impossibility of certain knowledge to the qualities that 1 Hyp. I. 4061. 2 Hyp. i. 4446. 3 Hyp. i. 50. The Sceptical Tropes. 39 Locke regards as secondary, but includes also the prim- ary ones in this statement. 1 The form and shape of objects as they appear to us may be changed by pressure on the eyeball. Furthermore, the character of reflect- v ions in mirrors depend entirely on their shape, as the images in concave mirrors are very different from those in convex ones; and so in the same way as the eyes of animals are of different shapes, and supplied with y different fluids, the ideas of dogs, fishes, men and grass- hoppers must be very different. 2 In discussing the mental representations of animals of different grades of intelligence, Sextus shows a very good comprehension of the philogenetic development of the organs of sense, and draws the final conclusion that external objects are regarded differently by animals, according to their difference in constitution. 3 These differences in the ideas which different animals have of the same objects are demonstrated by their different tastes, as the things desired by some are fatal to others. 4 The practical illustrations given of this result show a familiarity with natural history, and cognizance of the tastes and habits of many animals, 5 but were probably few of them original with Sextus, unless perhaps in their application ; that this train of reasoning was the common property of the Sceptic School, we know from the fact that Diogenes begins his exposition of the first Trope in a way similar to that of Sextus. 6 His illustra- tions are, however, few and meagre compared with those , of Sextus, and the scientific facts used by both of them 1 Hyp. i. 47. 4 Hyp. T. 55. 2 Hyp. i. 49. 6 Hyp. i. 5559. 3 Hyp. i. 54. 6 Diog. ix. 11, 7980. 40 Sextu8 Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. may mostly be found in other authors of anti^' milar way. 1 Tin,- logical result of tin- r to explain the first Trope, is that we cannot com- bhe iv(Tt,oyva)/Jiovi,K7J croQia? as the authority for believing that the body is a type of the soul. As the bodies of men differ, so the souls also probably differ. The differ- ences of mind among men is not referred to by Diogenes, except in the general statement that they choose 1 Hyp. i. 8. 2 Hyp. i. 80. 3 Diog. ix. 11, 8081. 4 Compare Pyrrhon et le Scepticism primitive. Revue phil., Paris 1885, No. 5; Victor Brochard, p. 521. 5 Diog. ix. 11, 81. 6 Hyp. i. 85. The Sceptical Tropes. 43 different professions ; while Sextus elaborates this point, speaking of the great differences in opposing schools of philosophy, and in the objects of choice and avoidance, and sources of pleasure for different men. 1 The poets well understand this marked difference in human desires, as Homer says, " One man enjoys this, another enjoys that." Sextus also quotes the beautiful lines of Pindar, 2 " One delights in getting honours and crowns through stormfooted horses, Others in passing life in rooms rich in gold, Another safe travelling enjoys, in a swift ship, on a wave of the sea." The Third Trope. The third Trope limits the argu- ment to the sense-perceptions of one man, a Dogmatic, if preferred, or to one whom the Dogmatics consider wise, 3 and states that as the ideas given by the different sense organs differ radically in a way that does not admit of their being compared with each other, they furnish no reliable testimony regarding the nature of objects. 4 " Each of the phenomena perceived by us seems to pre- sent itself in many forms, as the apple, smooth, fragrant brown and sweet." The apple was evidently the ordin- ary example given for this Trope, for Diogenes uses the same, but in a much more condensed form, and not with equal understanding of the results to be deduced from it. 5 The consequence of the incompatibility of the men- tal representations produced through the several sense 1 Hyp. i. 8789. * Hyp. i. 86. 3 Hyp. i. 90. 4 Hyp. i. 94. 5 Diog. ix. 11, 81. 44 Sextua Empiricua and Greek Scepticism. US by the apple, may be the acceptance of either of the three following propositions: (i) That only those quail* t in the apple which we perceive, (ii) Th;it more than these exist, (iii) That even those per- ceived d<> not exist. 1 Accordingly, any experience which can give rise to such different views regarding outward objects, cannot be relied upon as a testimony concerning them. The non-homogeneous nature of the mental images connected with the different sense organs, as presented by Si-xtus, reminds us of the discussion of the same subject by Berkeley in his 7heoi*y of Vi#< Sextus says that a man born with less than the usual number of senses, would form altogether different ideas of the external world than those who have the usual number, and as our ideas of objects depend on our mental images, a greater number of sense organs would give us still different ideas of outward reality. 2 The strong argument of the Stoics against such reasoning as this, was their doctrine of pre-established harmony be- twren nature and the soul, so that when a representation is produced in us of a real object, a KaraXijTmicrj fyavraa-ia? by this representation the soul grasps a real existence. There is a \6yos in us which is of the same kind, o-vyyevos, or in relation to all nature. This argu- ment of pre-established harmony between the faculties of the soul and the objects of nature, is the one that has been used in all ages to combat philosophical teach- ing that denies that we apprehend the external world as it is. It was used against Kant by his opponents, 1 Hyp. i. 99. - Hyp. i. 9697. 3 Adv. Math. vn. 93. The Sceptical Tropes. 45 who thought in this way to refute his teachings. 1 The Sceptics could not, of course, accept a theory of nature that included the soul and the external world in one harmonious whole, but Sextus in his discussion of the third Trope does not refute this argument as fully as he does later in his work against logic. 2 He simply states here that philosophers themselves cannot agree as to what nature is, and furthermore, that a philosopher himself is a part of the discord, and to be judged, rather than being capable of judging, and that no conclusion can be reached by those who are themselves an element of the uncertainty. 3 The Fourth Trope. This Trope limits the argu- ment to each separate sense, and the effect is considered of the condition of body and mind upon sense-perception in relation to the several sense-organs. 4 The physical states which modify sense-perception are health and illness, sleeping and waking, youth and age, hunger and satiety, drunkenness and sobriety. All of these condi- tions of the body entirely change the character of the mental images, producing different judgments of the color, taste, and temperature of objects, and of the cha- racter of sounds. A man who is asleep is in a different world from one awake, the existence of both worlds being relative to the condition of waking and sleeping. 5 The subjective states which Sextus mentions here as modifying the character of the mental representations are hating or loving, courage or fear, sorrow or joy, and sanity or insanity. 6 No man is ever twice in exactly 1 Ueberweg Op. cit. 195. * Hyp. i. 100. 2 Adv. Math. vii. 354. 5 Hyp. i. 104. 3 Hyp. i. 9899. Hyp. i. 100. 4f> Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. urn- condition of body or mind, and never abl to v tin- diii ronces of his ideas as a sum total, for those of the present moment only are subject to careful inspection. 1 Furthermore, no one is free from tin/ in- fluence of all conditions of body or mind, so that he can be unbiassed to judge his ideas, and no criterion can be established that can be shown to be true, but on the ((.ntiary, whatever course is pursued on the subject, both the criterion and the proof will be thrown into the circulus in probando, for the truth of each rests on the other. 2 Diogenes gives in part the same illustrations of this Trope, but in a much more condensed form. The marked characteristic of this train of reasoning is the attempt to prove that abnormal conditions are also natural. In referring at first to the opposing states of body and mind, which so change the character of sense-perception, Sextus classifies them according to the popular usage as Kara vcriv and irapa (frvaiv. This distinction was an important one, even with Aristotle, and was especially developed by the Stoics 3 in a broader sense than referring merely to health and sickness. The Stoics, however, considered only normal conditions as being according to nature. Srxtus, on the contrary, declares that abnormal states are also conditions according to nature, 4 and just as those who are in health are in a state that is natural to those who are in health, so also those not in health are in a state that is natural to those not in health, and in some respects according to nature. Existence, then, and non-existence are not * Hyp. i. 112. * Hyp. 1.117. 3 Diog. vn. 1, 86. 4 Hyp. i. 103. The Sceptical Tropes. 47 absolute, but relative, and the world of sleep as really exists for those who are asleep as the things that exist in waking exist, although they do not exist in sleep. 1 One mental representation, therefore, cannot be judged by another, which is also in a state of relation to exist- ing physical and mental conditions. Diogenes states this principle even more decidedly in his exposition of this Trope. "The insane are not in a condition opposed to nature ; why they more than we ? For we also see the sun as if it were stationary." 2 Furthermore, in different periods of life ideas differ. Children are fond of balls and hoops, while those in their prime prefer other things, and the aged still others. 3 The wisdom contained in this Trope in reference to the relative value of the things most sought after is not original with Sextus, but is found in the more earnest ethical teachings of older writers. Sextus does not, however, draw any moral conclusions from this reasoning, but only uses it as an argument for ITTO^TJ. The Fifth Trope. This Trope leaves the discussion of the dependence of the ideas upon the physical nature, and takes up the influence of the environment upon them. It makes the difference in ideas depend upon the position, distance, and place of objects, thus taking apparently their real existence for granted. Things change their form and shape according to the distance from which they are observed, and the position in which they stand. 4 The same light or tone alters decidedly in different surroundings. Perspective in paintings depends on the 1 H#p. i. 104. 2 Diog. ix. 11, 82. 3 Hyp. 1. 106. * Hyp. i. 118. 48 Sextus Empimcus and Greek Scepticism. angle at which the picture is suspended. 1 With Dio- genes this Trope is the seventh, 2 and his exposition of it is similar, but as usual, shorter. Both Sextus and Diogenes give the illustration 3 of the neck of the dove differing in color in different degrees of inclination, an illustration used by Protagoras also to prove the rela- tivity of perception by the senses. "The black neck of the dove in the shade appears black, but in the light sunny and purple/' 4 Since, then, all phenomena are regarded in a certain place, and from a certain distance, and according to a certain position, each of which rela- tions makes a great difference with the mental images, we shall be obliged also by this Trope to come to the reserving of the opinion. 5 The Sixth Trope. This Trope leads to eVo^/; re- garding the nature of objects, because no object can ever be presented to the organs of sense directly, but must always be perceived through some medium, or in some mixture. 6 This mixture may be an outward one, connected with the temperature, or the rarity of the air, or the water 7 surrounding an object, or it may be a mixture resulting from the different humors of the sense-organs. 8 A man with the jaundice, for example, sees colors differently from one who is in health. The illustration of the jaundice is a favorite one with the Sceptics. Diogenes uses it several times in his pre- sentation of Scepticism, and it occurs in Sextus' writings ^ Hyp. i. 120. - Diog. ix. 11, 85. s Hyp. i. 120; Diog. ix. 11, 56. 4 SchoL zu Arist. 60, 18, ed. Brandis ; Pappen. Er. Pyrr. Grundziige, p. 54. 6 Hyp. i. 121. * Hyp. i. 124. 7 Hyp. i. 125. 8 Hyp. i. 126. The Sceptical Tropes. 49 in all, as an illustration, in eight different places. 1 The condition of the organ of the rjyejAovucov, or the ruling faculty, may also cause mixtures. Pappenheim thinks that we have here Kant's idea of a priori, only on a materialistic foundation. 2 A careful consideration of the passage, however, shows us that Sextus' thought is more in harmony with the discoveries of modern psychiatry than with the philosophy of Kant. If the sentence, I'cro)? Se /cal avrrj (f) Stdvoia) eV^tu^/az; TLVCL IS lav TTOielrai, TT/DO? TO, VTTO rwv alcrOrjo'ecov dvao Sextua Empiricua and Greek Scepticism. The Seventh Trope. This Trope, based upon tin- quantities and compositions of objects, is illustrated by examples of different kinds of food, drink, and medicine, showing the different effects according to the quantity taken, as the harmfulness and the usefulness of i things depend on their quantity. Things act differently upon the senses if applied in small or large quant as filings of metal or horn, and separate grains of sand, have a different color and touch from the same taken in the form of a solid. 1 The result is that ideas vary according to the composition of the object, and this Trope also brings to confusion the existence of outward objects, and leads us to reserve our opinion in regard to them. 2 This Trope is illustrated by Diogenes with iig brevity. 3 The Elyhth Trope. The Trope based upon relation contain- afl Sextus rightly remarks, the substance of the other nine, 4 for the general statement of the rela- tivity of knowledge includes the other statements made. Thr prominence which Sextus gave this Trope in his introduction to the ten Tropes leads one to expect here new illustrations and added 5 arguments for eVo^. We find, however, neither of these, but simply a statement that all things are in relation in one of two ways, either directly, or as being a part of a difference. These two kinds of relation are given by Protagoras, and might have been used to good purpose in the introduction to the Tropes, or at the end, to prove that all the others were really subordinate to the eighth. The reasoning 1 Hyp. i. 129131. * Hyp. i. 39. 2 Hyp. i. 134. 5 Hyp. i. 135140. 3 Diog. ix. 11, 86. The Sceptical Tropes. 51 is, however, simply applied to the relation of objects to each other, and nothing is added that is not found else- where as an argument for eVo^. 1 This Trope is the tenth by Diogenes, and he strengthens his reasoning in regard to it, by a statement that Sextus does not directly make, i.e., that everything is in relation to the understanding. 2 The Ninth Trope. This is based upon the frequency and rarity of events, and refers to some of the phenomena of nature, such as the rising of the sun, and the sea, as no longer a source of astonishment, while a comet or an earthquake are wonders to those not accustomed to them. 3 The value of objects also depends on their rarity, as for example the value of gold. 4 Furthermore, things may be valuable at one time, and at another not so, according to the frequency and rarity of the occur- rence. 5 Therefore this Trope also leads to eVo%^. Dio- genes gives only two illustrations to this Trope, that of the sun and the earthquake. 6 The Tenth Trope. We have already remarked on the difference in the character of the tenth Trope, deal- ing as it does, not with the ideas of objects, like the other nine Tropes, but with philosophical and religious opinions, and questions of right and wrong. It was the well-known aim of the Sceptics to submit to the laws and customs of the land where they were found, and to conform to certain moral teachings and religious ceremonies; this they .did without either affirming or 1 Hyp. i. 135140. 4 Hyp. i. 143. 3 Diog. ix. 11, 88. s Hy pt T . 144. p. i. 141142. Diog. ix. 11, 87. ."I' Sextus Empiricu8 and Greek Scepticism. denying the truth of the principles upon which these teu< -1 lin^s were based, 1 and also without any passion or strong feeling in regard to them,- as nothing in it can be proved to be good or evil. The tenth Trope, accordingly, brings forward contradictions in customs, laws, and the beliefs of different lands, to show that ih.-y are also changeable and relative, and not of absolute worth. The foundation-thought of this Trope is gi twice by Diogenes, once as we have before stated in his introduction to the life of Pyrrlio, and also as on< the Trope.- it is apparently one of the oldest of the Tropes, it would naturally be much used in in- with the Stoics, whose philosophy had such a \v ethical significance, and must also have held an imj> ant place in the &c< -)iii -il School in all metaphysical and philosophical discussions. The definition 5 in the beumnini; of Sextus' exposition of this Trope Fabri< thinks waa taken from Aristotle, of schools, In ins, mythical lx li> t> and dogmatic opinions, 6 and the defini- tion which Diogenes gives of law in his life of Plat< similar. Pappenheim, however, thinks they were taken from i: ), perhape irom Chrysippus. 8 The argu- ( ment is based upon the ditterences in development of J thought, as affecting the nit of judgment in I philosophy, in morals, and religion, the results of which \ we find in the widely opposing schools of philosophy, in I the variety in religious belief, and in the laws and cus- toms of different countries. Therefore the decisions '.;?. 1.24. 5 llyp.i. 113-147. Hyp. in. 235. 6 Fabricius, Cap. iv. H. 3 Diog. ix. 11, 61. ' Diog. in. 86. 4 Diog. ix. 11, 83. & Pappenheim Gr. Pyrr. Grundzilge, p. 50. The Sceptical Tropes. 53 reached in the world of thought leave us equally -m\ doubt regarding the absolute value of any standards,/ with those obtained through sense-perception, and the\ universal conflict of opinion regarding all questions of '' philosophy and ethics leads us also according to this Trope to the reserving of the opinion. 1 This Trope is ; the fifth as given by Diogenes, who placed it directly after the first four which relate more especially to human development, 2 while Sextus uses it as the final one, perhaps thinking that an argument based upon the higher powers of man deserves the last place, or is the summation of the other arguments. Following the exposition of the ten Tropes of the older Sceptics, Sextus gives the five Tropes which he attributes to the " later Sceptics." 3 Sextus nowhere mentions the author of these Tropes. Diogenes, how- ever, attributes them to Agrippa, a man of whom we know nothing except his mention of him. He was evidently one of the followers of Aenesidemus, and a scholar of influence in the Sceptical School, who must have himself had disciples, as Diogenes says, ol rrrepl 'AypiTTTrav* add to these tropes other five tropes, using the plural verb. Another Sceptic, also mentioned by Diogenes, and a man unknown from other sources, named some of his books after Agrippa. 5 Agrippa is not given by Diogenes in the list of the leaders of the Sceptical School, but 6 his influence in the development of the thought of the School must have been great, as the transition from the ten Tropes of the "older 1 Hij2). I. 163. 4 Diog. ix. 11, 88. 2 Diog. ix. 11. 83. 5 Diog. ix. 11, 106. 3 Hyp. i. 164. 6 Diog. ix. 12, 115116. 54 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. Sceptics " to the five attributed to Agrippa is a marked one, and shows the entrance into the school of a logical power before unknown in it. The latter are not a re- duction of the Tropes of Aenesidemus, but are written from an entirely different standpoint. The ten Tropes are empirical, and aim to furnish objective proofs of the foundation theories of Pyrrhonism, while the five are /I "~ - ~ _!-- I rather rules of thought leading to logical proof, and are dialectic in their character. \Y<- find this distinction illustrated by the different way in which the Trope of relativity is treated in the two groups. In the first it points to an objective relativity, but with Agrippa to a general subjective logical principle. The originality of the Tropes of Agrippa does not lie in their substance matter, but in their formulation and use in the Sceptical School. These methods of proof were, of course, not new, but were well known to Aristotle, and were used by the Sceptical Academy, and probably also by Timon, 1 while the TT/HK TI goes back at least to Protagoras. The five Tropes are as follows. (i) The one based upon discord. (ii) The regressus in infinit (iii) Relation. (iv) The hypothetical, (v) The circulus in probando. Two of these are taken from the old list, the first and the third, and Sextus says that the five Tropes are intended to supplement the ten Tropes, and to show the audacity of the Dogmatics in a variety of ways. 2 The order of these Tropes is the same with Diogenes as Compare Natorp. Op. cit. p. 302. * Hyp. i. 177. I The Sceptical Tropes. 55 with Sextus, but the definitions of them differ sufficiently to show that the two authors took their material from different sources. According to the first one everything in question is either sensible or intellectual, and in at- tempting to judge it either in life, practically, or " among philosophers," a position is developed from which it is impossible to reach a conclusion. 1 According to the second, every proof requires another proof, and so on to * infinity, and there is no standpoint from which to begin the reasoning. 2 According to the third, all perceptions are relative, as the object is colored by the condition of the judge, and the influence of other things around it. 3 According to the fourth, it is impossible to escape from the regressus in infinitum by making a hypothesis the starting point, as the Dogmatics attempt to do. 4 And the fifth, or the circulus in probando, arises when that which should be the proof needs to be sustained by the thing to be proved. Sextus claims that all things can be included in these Tropes, whether sensible or intellectual. 5 For whether, as some say, only the things of sense are true, or as others claim, only those of the understanding, or as still others contend, some things both of sense and understanding are true, a discord must arise that is impossible to be judged, for it cannot be judged by the sensible, nor by the intellectual, for the things of the intellect themselves require a proof; accordingly, the result of all reasoning must be either hypothetical, or fall into the regressus in infinitum or the circulus in 1 Hyp. i. 165. 4 Hyp. i. 168. 2 Hyp. i. 166. 5 Hyp. i. 169. 3 Hyp. i. 167. Sextus l^i" i>> I'icus and Greek Scepticism. The reference above to some who B only tip tilings of sense are true, is to E] and Pr< ; to some that only the things of thoi; true, toDemocritusainl Plato; and to those that clain some of both to be true,to the Stoics arid thePeripateti The tin- < IK \\ Tropes added by Agrippa have notlr to do with sense-perception, but bear entirely upon ; possibility of reasoning, as demanded by the science of lo.i^ic, in contrast to the earlier ones which related almost / entin-ly, with the exception of the tenth, to mat- objects. Sextus claims that these five Tropes also 1 to the on of judgment, 3 but their logical result iie dogmatic denial of all possibility of know- ledge. showing as Hirzel has well demonstrated, more the influence of the New Academy than the spirit . of the Sceptical School. 4 It was the standpoint of the older Sceptics, that although the search for the truth had not yet succeeded, yet they were still seekers, and to be faithful to this old aim of Pynhoni-ts. He calls himself a seeker, 5 and in re- proaching the New Academy for affirming that know- ledge is impossible, Sextus says, " Moreover, we say that our ideas are equal as regards trustworthiness and un- trust\vorthiness." G The ten Tropes claim to establish doubt only in regard to a knowledge of the truth, but the five J]rjapej_oX_Agrippa aim to logically prove the impossibility of knowledge. It is very strange that Sextus does not see this decided contrast in the attitude 1 Hyp. i. 170171. 2 Adv. Math. vin. 185186; vm. 56; vn. 369. *lfyp.i. 177. 5 Eyp. i. 3, 7. 4 Hirzel Op. cit. p. 131. Hyp. i. - The Sceptical Tropes. 57 of the two s'ets of Tropes, and expresses his approval of those of Agrippa, and makes more frequent use of the fifth of these, 6 &c-ptical one, then Sc. i is n< more a path to tip- philosophy of Heraclitus th to other schools of philosophy, or to life, as all use common subject matter. " But we are afraid that the Sceptical School not only does not help towards the knowledge of the philosophy of Heraclitus, but even hinders that result. Since the Sceptic accuses Heraclitus of having ra>ldy dogmatised, presenting on the one hand the doe-trine of ' conflagration ' and on the other that 'contradictory predicates are in reality applicable to the same thing.' " 2 " It is absurd, then, to say that this conflicting school is a path to the sect with which it conflicts. It is therefore absurd to say that the Scepti School is a path to the philosophy of Heraclitus." 3 This is not the only place in the writings of Sextus which states that Aenesidemus at some time of his life was an advocate of the doctrines of Heraclitus. In no instance, however, where Sextus refers to this remark- able fact, does he offer any explanation of it, or express any bitterness against Aenesidemus, whom he always speaks of with respect as a leader of the Sceptical School. We are thus furnished with one of the most difficult problems of ancient Scepticism, the problem 1 Hyp. i. 211. a Hyp. i. 212. 3 Hyp. i. 212. \Aenesidemus and the Philosophy of Heraclitus. 65 of reconciling the apparent advocacy of Aenesidemus of the teachings of Heraclitus with his position in the Sceptical School. A comparison with eadh other of the references made by Sextus and other writers to the teachings of Aenesidemus, and a consideration of the result, gives us two pictures of Aenesidemus which conflict most de- cidedly with each other. We have on the one hand, the man who was the first to give Pyrrhonism a position as an influential school, and the first to collect and pre- sent to the world the results of preceding Sceptical thought. He was the compiler of the ten Tropes of eVo^, and perhaps in part their author, and the author of the eight Tropes against aetiology. 1 He develops his Scepticism from the standpoint that neither the senses nor the intellect can give us any certain knowledge of reality. 2 He denied the possibility of studying pheno- mena as signs of the unknown. 3 He denied all possi- bility of truth, and the reality of motion, origin and decay. There was according to his teaching no plea- sure or happiness, and no wisdom or supreme good. He denied the possibility of finding out the nature of things, or of proving the existence of the gods, and finally he declared that no ethical aim is possible. The picture on the other hand, presented to us by Sextus and Tertullian, is that of a man with a system of beliefs and dogmas, which lead, he says, to the philosophy of Heraclitus. In strange contradiction to his assertion of the impossibility of all knowledge, he advocates a theory 1 Hyp. i. 180. 2 Photius 170, B. 12. * Adv. Math. via. 40. (ii; Sextns Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. that, the original substance is air, 1 which is most tainly a dogma, although indeed a deviation from the teachings of Heraclitus, of which Sex t us seemed uncon- scious, as he says, TO re ov Kara -rov 'HpdicKeiTov arjp ecrriV) co? (fryvlv 6 Aivfjfft&fjfAOV, Aenesidemu i also regarding number and time and unity of the ori<_rinal world-^tuff. 2 He fteemfl to have d<> further about motion, 3 and about the soul. 4 It S xtus' language is taken according to it> a meal find ourselves here in tl -nee of a which would be naturally held by a follower of the Stoic-Heraclitan physics, 6 and absol inexplicable from the nan who advocated ! a Scepticism as Aenesidemus. Sextus in thf irition against the Idea that Scepticism could form th- path to the j)hilo>o|)hy of ir-r;clitus, but he does not ex} surprise or indignation against Aenesidemus persoi or orVer any explanation of the apparent contradic 1 and while his wrr -und in references to him as a ted leader of tlte Sceptical School, he sometimes srenis to include him with the Dogmatic-, n, him with the Soypart/cwv (piXocrofav. 7 In fact, the task of presenting any consistent hi>try of the develop] of thought through which Aenesidemus }> a puzzling one, that Brochard brilliantly remarks that ly the best attitud. towards it would be to follow the advice of Aenesidemus himself -pend 1 Adv. Math. x. 233. 6 Compare Zellor Op. cit. in. p. 33. Vath. ix. 337; x. 216. 6 Hyp. I. 210 J 3 Adv. Mitti. x. 38. V. Math. vm. 8; x. 215. * Atlr. Math. vn. 349. Aenesidemus and the Philosophy of Heraclitus. 67 one's judgment altogether regarding it. Is it possible to suppose that so sharp and subtle a thinker as Aene- sidemus held at the same time such opposing opinions ? The conjecture that he was first a Heraclitan Stoic, and later a Sceptic, which might be possible, does not offer any explanation of Sextus' statement, that he regarded Scepticism as a path to the philosophy of Heraclitus. Nor would it be logical to think that after establishing the Sceptical School in renewed influence arid power, he reverted to the Heraclitan theories as they were modified by the Stoics. These same theories were the cause of his separation from the Academy, for his chief accusation against the Academy was that it was adopting the dogmatism of the Stoics. 1 The matter is complicated by the fact that Tertullian also attributes to Aenesidemus anthropological and physical teachings that agree with the Stoical Heraclitan doctrines. It is not strange that in view of these contradictory assertions in regard to the same man, some have suggested the possibility that they referred to two different men of the same name, a supposition, however, that no one has been able to authoritatively vindicate. Let us consider briefly some of the explanations which have been attempted of the apparent heresy of Aenesidemus towards the Sceptical School. We will begin with the most ingenious, that of Pappenheim. 2 Pappenheim claims that Sextus was not referring to Aenesidemus himself in these statements which he joins with his name. In the most important of these, 1 Compare Zeller Op. cit. in. p. 16. 2 Die angebliche Heraclitismus des Skeptikers Ainesidemos, Berlin 1889. 68 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. the one quoted from the Hypotyposes, 1 which repr AeneademtUI as daimin^ that Scepticism is the path to the philosophy of Hcraclitus, the expression used is ol Trepl -rov Alvrjo'io'rj/jLov, and in many of the other places where Sextus refers to the dogmatic statements of Aenesidemus, the expression is either ol Trepl rov Alirq- aiSrjfjLov, or Alvrja-iSrjfjLo^ tca0' *H pdfc\en ov, while when us quotes Aenesidemus to sustain Scepticism, he his nairn- alone. Pappenhrim thinks that S -onflict was not with the dead Aenesinm<, who had lived two cen- turies before him, but with his own contempor He also seeks to prove that Sextus could not have gained his knowledge of these sayings of Aenesidemus from any of AeiHsidi mus' own writings, as neither by the ancients, nor by later writers, was any book spoken of which could well have contained them. Neither Aristocles nor Dio- genes mentions any such book. Papponheim also makes much of the arinmu-nt that Sextus in no instance seems conscious of inconsistency on the part of Aenesidemus, even when most earnestly combating his alleged teachings, but in referring to him personally he always speaks of him with great respect. Pappenheim suggests, accordingly, that the polemic of Sext us was against contemporaries, those who accepted the philosophy of Heraclitus in consequence of, or in some connection with, the teachings of Aenesidemus. He entirely ignores the fact that there is no trace of any such school or sect in history, calling themselves Hyp. i. 210212. Aenesidemus and the Philosophy of Heraclitus. 69 followers of " Aenesidemus according to Heraclitus," but still thinks it possible that such a movement existed in Alexandria at the time of Sextus, where so many dif- ferent sects were found. Sextus uses Aenesidemus' name in four different ways: alone, ol irepl TOP Aivei H BeztUl naturally warmly combats this tendency, as he \vishe< to preserve Pyrrhonism pure. Brochard advocates a change of opinion on f of Aenesidemus as an explanation of tlie difficulty in 'ion. 1 He starts from the Disposition, the reason- ableness of which we shall consider later, that Aene- sidemus had pa.-srd through one change of opinion already when he severed his connection with the New Academy; and to the two phases of hit life, which such a ( hange has already made us familiar with, he adds a third. Aenesidemus would not be the first who has accepted different !> -li< -f> at different periods of his life, and Hrnrhard claims that such a development in the opinions of Aenesidemus is logical. He does not accuse Aenesidemus of having, as might seem from the pern>al of Sextus, suddenly changed his basis, but rather of having gradually come to accept much in the teachings of Heraclitns. Aenesidemus modifies his Scepticism only to the extent of pretending to know something of absolute reality. The Sceptic says, "Contradi predicates are apparently applicable to the same ti and Aenesidemus accepts the Heraclitan result " Con- tradictory predicates are in reality applicable to the same thing." From Sextus' report, Aenesidemus would seem to have renounced his position as a Sceptic in saying that Scepticism is the path to the philosophy of Heraclitus. He does not, however, renounce Sceptici>m, but he finds it incomplete. In deliberating concerning the appearance of contradictory predicate! in regard to 1 Hrochard Op. cit. 272. Aenesidemus and the Philosophy of Heraclitus. 71 the same object, he would naturally ask, " Whence come these contradictory appearances ? " After having doubted all things, he wished to know wherefore he doubts. The system of Heraclitus offers a solution, and he accepts it. Contradictory predicates produce equilibrium in the soul because they are an expression of reality. As a Sceptic he claims that knowledge is impossible, and he does not find that the statement of Heraclitus disproves this, but rather that it supports his theory. He had denied the existence of science. He still does so, but now he knows why he denies it. Brochard asks why it is any more impossible that Aenesidemus should have been a follower of Heraclitus than that Protagoras was so, as Protagoras was after all a Sceptic. In con- clusion, Brochard claims that the dogmatic theories attributed to Aenesidemus relate to the doctrine of the truth of contradictory predicates, which seemed to him a logical explanation of the foundation theories of Scepticism. It is right to call him a Sceptic, for he was so, and that sincerely ; and he deserves his rank as one of the chiefs of the Sceptical School. Coming now to the opinion of Zeller, 1 we find that he advocates a misconception of Aenesidemus on the part of Sextus. The whole difficulty is removed, Zeller thinks, by the simple fact that Sextus had not under- stood Aenesidemus ; and as Tertullian and Sextus agree in this misconception of the views of Aenesidemus, they must have been misled by consulting a common author in regard to Aenesidemus, who confused what Aene- sidemus said of Heraclitus with his own opinion. Zeller 1 Zeller Op. cit. Ill, pp. 31 35; Grundriss der Geschichteder Griechis- chen Phil. p. 263. 7 '2 tieztux Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. maintains that the expression so often repeated by Suxtus Aivr)(rib7)iJLOS naff 'HpatcKeirov shows that some one of Aenesidemus' books contained a report of Heraclitus 1 doctrines, as Aenesidemus was in the habit of quoting as many authorities as possible to sustain his Scepticism. To justify his quotations from Herac- litus, he had possibly given a short abstract of Heraclitus' teachings ; and the misconception advocated by Zeller, and found both in Tertullian and Sextus, refers rather to the spirit than to the words quoted from Aeneside- ii) ns. and is a misconception due to some earlier author, who had given a false impression of the meaning of Aenesidemus in quoting what Aenesidemus wrote about Heraclitus. That is to say, Heraclitus was classed by Aenesidemua only among those who prepared th- for Scepticism, just as Diogenes 1 mentions many philo- sophers in that way ; and that Soranus 2 and Sextus both ha.l the same misunderstanding can only be explained by a mistake on the part of the authority whom they consulted. This explanation, however, makes Sextus a very stupid man. Aenesidemus' books were well known, and Sextus would most certainly take the trouble to read them. His reputation as an historian would not sustain such an accusation, as Diogenes calls his books TO, Setca TWV cnceTTTiicwv KOI a\\a tcd\\iid -mus, for it is exactly the opposite of what Sextus has reported. Strange to say, Saisset him.-elf remarks in another place that we owe religious respect to any text, and tl should he tin- first Irnv of criticism to render this. 1 Such 't to the text of Sextus, as he him<-lt' fcdvo puts Saisset's explanation of the subject under dis- cussion out of the question. Hirzel and Natorp do not find such a marked contradiction in the two views presented of the theories of Aenesidemus, nor do they think that Sextus has misrepresented them* They rather maintain, that in declaring the coexistence of contradictory predicates regarding the same object, Aenesidemus does not cease to be a Sceptic, for he did not believe that the predicates are applicable in a dogmatic sense of the word, but are only applicable in appearance, that is, applicable to phenomena. The Heraclitism of Aenesidemus would be then only in appearance, as he understood the statement, that " Contradictory predicates are in reality applicable to the same thing," only in the phenomenal sense. 2 Hirzel says in addition, that contradictory predicates are in reality applicable to those phenomena which are the same for all, and consequently true, for Aenesidemus considered those phenomena true that are the same for all:' 1 As Protagoras, the disciple of 1 Saisset Op. cit. p. 206. * Natorp Op. cit. 115. 122. 3 Adv. Math. vin. 8 ; Hirzel Op. cit. p. 96. Aenesidemus and the Philosophy of Heraclitus. 75 Heraclitus, declared the relative character of sensations, that things exist only for us, and that their nature depends on our perception of them ; so, in the pheno- menal sense, Aenesidemus accepts the apparent fact that contradictory predicates in reality apply to the same thing. This explanation entirely overlooks the fact that we have to do with the word vTrdpxew, in the statement that contradictory predicates in reality apply to the same thing ; while in the passage quoted where Aenesidemus declares common phenomena to be true ones, we have the word aXrjdrj, so that this explanation of the diffi- culty would advocate a very strange use of the word All of these different views of the possible solution of this perplexing problem are worthy of respect, as the opinion of men who have given much thought to this and other closely related subjects. While we may not altogether agree with any one of them, they neverthe- less furnish many suggestions, which are very valuable in helping to construct a theory on the subject that shall satisfactorily explain the difficulties, and present a consistent view of the attitude of Aenesidemus. First, in regard to the Greek expression ol irepl in connection with proper names, upon which Pappenheim bases so much of his argument. All Greek scholars would agree that the expression does not apply usually only to the disciples of any teacher, but ol irepl rbv AlvrjatSTj/juov, for instance, includes Aenesidemus with his followers, and is literally translated, "Aenesidemus and his followers." It is noticeable, however, in the writings of Sextus that he uses the expression ol irepl often for 7(> Sextm Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. the name of the founder of a school alone, as Pappen- heim himself admits. 1 We find examples of this in th- mention of Plato and Democritus and Arcesilaus, as 01 Trepl TOV TIXaTtova Kai A^jjuoKpiTov 2 and ol Trepl TOP 'Apx the spirit of his time to seek to sustain all philosophical teaching 1 Diog. ix. n. TO. Aenesidemus and the Philosophy of Heraclitus. 79 by the authority of as many as possible of the older philosophers, and he could hardly escape the tendency which his training in the Academy had unconsciously given him. Therefore we find him trying to prove that the philosophy of Heraclitus follows from Scepticism. It is not necessary either to explain the matter, as both Hirzel and Natorp so ingeniously attempt to do, by claiming that the truth of contradictory predicates which Aenesidemus accepted from Heraclitus referred only to phenomena. The history of philosophy gives us abun- dant proof of the impossibility of absolute Scepticism, and Aenesidemus furnishes us with one example of many of this impossibility, and of the dogmatism that must exist in connection with all thought. In the case of Aenesidemus, who evidently gave the best efforts of his life to establish the Sceptical School, the dogmatism was probably unconscious. That he remained to the end a Sceptic is shown by the fact that he was known as such to posterity. Nowhere do we find a change of basis referred to in regard to him, and Sextus, in refuting the mistakes which he attributes to Aene- sidemus, does it, as it were, to point out something of which Aenesidemus had been unconscious. Let us consider here the second cause of Aeneside- mus' Dogmatism, the psychological effect upon himself of formulating Sceptical beliefs. The work that he did for the Sceptical School was a positive one. It occupied years of his life, and stamped itself upon his mental development. In formulating Scepticism, and in ad- vocating it against the many enemies of the School, and amidst all the excitement of the disruption from the Academy, and of establishing a new School, it was so Seotfus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. inevitable that, liis mind .should take a dogmatic denry. He remained a Sceptic as IK.' had always been, but must liave grown dogmatic in his attitude tov. the Sceptical formulae, and was thus able to adopt some <>!' the teachings of Ileraclitus, unconscious of their inconsistency. Where should we find a modern writer who is c it in all his statements? Could we read the works of Aenesidemus, we might better understand the con- nection between the apparently contradictory ideas in his teaching, but the incn: Q statement i probably remain. It is necessary to remember the position of Aenesidemus in breaking away from the Academy and in founding a new school, the full ficance of which he could not foresee. There must iarily be some crudenen in pioneer \v some failure to see the bearing of all its parts, and a compiler like Sextus could point out the inconsistencies which the two centuries since the time of Aenesidemu- made plain. Aenesidemus was too positive a char dmit of absolute Sceptical consistency. He was nevertheless the greatest thinker the Sceptical School had known since the age of Pyrrho, its founder. In claiming a union between Pyrrhonism and the philo- sophy of Heraclitus, he recognised also the pre-Socnatic tendency of the Sceptical School. The name of Soc was all powerful in the Academy, but Aenesidemus com- prehended the fact that the true spirit of Pyrrhonism was of earlier origin than the Academic Scepsis. CHAPTER V. Critical Examination of Pyrrhonism. The distinct philosophical movement of which Pyrrho was the author bore his name for five centuries after his death. It had an acknowledged existence as a philo- sophical tendency, if indeed not a sect, for a great part of that time. Yet, when we carefully analyse the relation of Pyrrhonism, as presented to us by Sextus, to the teachings of Pyrrho himself, in so far as they can be known, we find many things in Pyrrhonism for which Pyrrho was not responsible. The foundation elements of the movement, the spirit of Empirical doubt that lay underneath and caused its development in certain directions rather than others, are due to Pyrrho. The methods of the school, however, were very foreign to anything found in the life or teach- ings of Pyriho. Pyrrho was eminently a moralist. He was also to a great degree an ascetic, and he lived his philosophy, giving it thus a positive side wanting in the Pyrrhonism presented to us by Sextus. Timon represents him as desiring to escape from the tedious philosophical discussions of his time & yepov & Ilvppwv, TTW? r) Trb6ev etcSvcnv evpes Bo^&v re /cepo^poavvrj^ re O- M* Sextua Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. ,'ind a^ain be of his modest and tranquil life TOVTO pot,, (!) TIvppwv, ipelperai rj-rop dfcovcrac 7TW9 TTOT' avrjp eV ayets Travra f fjiovvo? SavQptoTTOicri deov rpojrov rj alel apovTio-Ta)<; fcal iutivfaw* Kara ravra i]Sv\6jov Pyri-li.) wished more than anything rl>: to live in peace, and his dislike of the Sophists 2 may well hav/ made him try to avoid dialectic; while, on the contrary, in tli<- Pyrrhonean School of InU-r timrs discussion was one of the principal ni-thuds of contest, at I the time of Agrippa. Pyrrhonism seems to have been nriiiinally a theory of life, like the philosophy of Socrates, to whom Pyrrho is often compared;' and Pyrrho, like ites, lived his philosophy. Our knowledge of Pyrrho is gained from Aristocles, Sextus Empiricus, and Diogeoes, and from the Academic traditions L: 1)\ ( iioera Diogenes gives us details of his lite which he attributes to Antigonus of Carystius, who lived about tin- time of Pyrrho. 4 Pyrrho was a disciple and adi of Democritus, 5 some of whose teachings bore a lasting influence over the subsequent development of Pyrrho- nism. He accompanied Alexander the Great to India, where he remained as a member of his suite for time, and the philosophical ideas of India were not without influence on his teachings. Oriental philosophy 1 Diog. ix. 11, 65. Given from Mullach's edition of Timon by m primitive, p. .52"). Diog. ix. 11, 69. * Diog. ix. 11, 02. 3 Lewes Op. cit. p. 460. Diog. ix. 11. Critical Examination of Pyrrhonism. 83 was not unknown in Greece long before the time of Pyrrho, but his personal contact with the Magi and the Gymnosophists of the far East, apparently impressed upon his mind teachings for which he was not unpre- pared by his previous study and natural disposition. In his indifference to worldly goods we find a strong trace of the Buddhistic teaching regarding the vanity of human life. He showed also a similar hopelessness in regard to the possibility of finding a satisfactory philosophy, or absolute truth. He evidently returned from India with the conviction that truth was not to be attained. 1 After the death of Alexander and Pyrrho's return to Greece, he lived quietly with his sister at Elis, and Diogenes says that he was consistent in his life, asserting and denying nothing, but in everything withholding his opinion, as nothing in itself is good or shameful, just or unjust. 2 He was not a victim of false pride, but sold animals in the market place, and, if necessary, washed the utensils himself. 3 He lived in equality of spirit, and practised his teachings with serenity. If one went out while he was talking he paid no attention, but went calmly on with his remarks. 4 He liked to live alone, and to travel alone, and on one occasion, being knocked about in a vessel by a storm at sea, he did not lose his imperturbability, but pointed to a swine calmly eating on board, and said that the wise man should have as much calmness of soul as that. He endured difficult surgical operations with indifference, 5 and when his 1 Compare Maccoll Op. cit. 4 Diog. ix. 11, 63. 2 Diog. ix. 11, 61, 62. 5 Diog. ix. 11, 67. 3 Diog. ix. 11, 66 84 Sextua Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. friend Anaxarchus was once unfortunate enough to fall into a morass, he went calmly by without stopping to help him, for which consistency of conduct Anaxarchus afterwards praised him. There are two instances given by Diogenes when he lost control of himself; once in getting angry with his sister, and once in trying to save himself when chased by a dog. When accused of incon- sistency, he said it was difficult to entirely give up one's Imm.'inity. 1 He was greatly venerated by the people among whom he lived, who made him high priest, and on his account exempted all philosophers from taxation, 2 and after his death erected a statue to his memory. These facts testify to his moral character, and also to fulfil the functions of high priest a certain amount of dogmatism must liav. been necessary. According to Diogenes, " We cannot know," said Pyr- l rho, " what things are in themselves, either by sensation 1 or by judgment, and, as we cannot distinguish the true / from the false, therefore we should live impassively, and without an opinion/' The term eVo^?;, so characteristic / of Pyrrhonism, goes back, according to Diogenes, to the I time of Pyrrho. 3 Nothing is, in itself, one thing more than another, but all experience is related to pheno- mena, and no knowledge is possible through the senses. 4 Pyrrho's aim was arapagta and his life furnished a marked example of the spirit of indifference, for which the expression cnrdOeia is better suited than the later one, arapa^ia. The description of his life with his sister confirms this, where the term aSiafopla is used to 1 Diog. ix. 11, 66. 3 Diog. ix. 11, 61. 2 Diog. ix. 11, 64. Diog. ix. 11, 6162. Critical Examination of Pyrrhonism. 85 describe his conduct. 1 He founded his Scepticism on the equivalence of opposing arguments. 2 The picture given of Pyrrho by Cicero is entirely different from that of Diogenes, and contrasts decidedly with it. 3 Cicero knows Pyrrho as a severe moralist, not as a Sceptic. Both authors attribute to Pyrrho the doctrine of indifference and apathy, but, according to Cicero, Pyrrho taught of virtue, honesty, and the summum bonum, while Diogenes plainly tells us that he considered nothing as good in itself, "and of all things nothing as true." 4 Cicero does not once allude to Pyrrho- nean doubt. We see on the one hand, in Cicero's idea of Pyrrho, the influence of the Academy, perhaps even of Antiochus himself, 5 which probably colored the representations given of Pyrrho ; but, on the other hand, there is much in Diogenes' account of Pyrrho's life and teachings, and in the writings of Timon, which shows us the positive side of Pyrrho. Pyrrho, in denying the possibility of all knowledge, made that rather a motive for indifference in the relations of life, than the founda- tion thought of a philosophical system. His teaching has a decided ethical side, showing in that respect the strong influence of Democritus over him, who, like Pyrrho, made happiness to consist in a state of feeling. 6 The one motive of all of Pyrrho's teaching is a positive one, the desire for happiness. The essence of Pyrrhonism as given by Tiruon is as follows : 7 Man desires to be happy. To realise his 1 Diog. ix. 11. 66. 5 Compare Natorp Op. cit. p. 71. 2 Diog. IJL. 11. 106. 6 Zeller Grundriss der Griechischen Phil. p. 70. 3 De oral. Ill, 62. 7 Aristocles ap. Eusebium Praep. Ev. xiv. 18. 4 Diog. ix. 11, 61. S(i SeoctUB tiiHi/n'icua and Greek Scepticism. desire he must consider three things: (i) What is the nature of thing (ii) How should man conduct himself in relation to them? (iii) What is the result to him of this relation ? The nature of things is unknown. Our relation to them must be one of suspension of judgment, without activity, desire, or belief, that is, an entirely negative relation. The result is that state of having no opi; called tVo^//, which is followed in turn by arapagia. lr fhe problem of philosophy is here proposed very nearly in the terms of Kant, but not with the positive motive, like that of the great philosopher of Germany, of evolving a system to present the truth. Yet the im- portance of these questions shows the originality of Pyrrho. The earnestness of Pyrrho is further >ho\vn by an example given by Diogenes. Once on being found talking to himself alone, he said, when asked the reason, that he was meditating how to become a good man (XPT/O-TO?), 2 thus showing an entirely different spirit from anything found in Sextus' books. The explanation of his life and teachings is to be found largely in his own disposition. Such an attitude of indifference must belong to a placid nature, and cannot be entirely the result of a philosophical system, and, while it can be aimed at, it can never be perfectly imitated. One of his disciples recognised this, and said that it was neces- sary to have the disposition of Pyrrho in order to hold his doctrines. 3 Diogenes tells us that he was the first to advance any formulae of Scepticism, 4 but they must 1 Compare Maccoll Op.cit. p. 21. 3 Diog. ix. 11, 70, 64. 2 Diog. ix. 11, 64. 4 Dio-. ix. 11, 69; ix. 11, 61. Critical Examination of Pyrrhonism. 87 have been very elementary, as Pyrrho himself wrote nothing. We find no trace of formulated Tropes in Pyrrho's teachings, yet it is probable that he indicated some of the contradictions in sensation, and possibly the Tropes in some rudimentary form. Of the large number of sceptical formulae, or (fxovai, the three which seem to have the oldest connection with Scepticism are the avri- \o7/a, the ovBev dp/a>, and the ov pa\\ov. 1 We know from Diogenes that Protagoras is the authority for saying that in regard to everything there are two opposing arguments. 2 The saying " to determine nothing " is quoted from Timon's Python by Diogenes, 3 and the other two mentioned are also attributed to him by Aristocles. 4 We have also in the ov paXkov a direct connection with Democritus, although the difference in the meaning which he attributed to it is shown by Sextus. 5 So while the expression is the same, the explanation of it given by Pyrrho must have been different. It would seem probable that Pyrrho used all of these three sayings, from the account of Diogenes, and that even then they gave rise to the accusation of the Dogmatics, that simply by possessing such sayings the Sceptics dogmatised, 6 for the refutation of this used by Sextus occurs in the old account of the sayings, namely, that these formulae include also themselves in the meaning, as a cathartic removes itself together with other harmful objects. 7 In comparing the later Pyrrhonism with the teach- ings of Pyrrho, we would sharply contrast the moral 1 Hyp. i. 202 ; Diog. ix. 8, 51 ; Photius Bekker's ed. 280 H. 2 Photius Bekker's ed. 280 H. 3 Hyp. i. 197; Diog. ix. 11. 76. 4 Aristocles ap. Eusebium, Praep. Ev. xiv.18. 5 Hyp. i. 213. 6 Diog. ix. 11, 6876. 7 Diog. ix. 11, 76; Hyp. i. 206. 88 Sextua Empii-icus and Greek Scepticism. attitude of the two. With Pyrrho equilibrium of soul a means to be applied to his positive theory of life; with tin- later Pyrrhoneans it was the end to be attained. We would attribute, however, the empirical tendency shown during the whole history of Pyrrhonism to Pyrrho M ita "rininator. He WfU) an empirical philosopher, and the result of his influence in this respect, as seen in the subsequent development of the school, stands in m;i contrast to tin- dialrti<- spirit of the Academic Scepsis. The empirieism of the school is shown in its scientific lore, in the fact that so many of the Sceptics were physicians, and in the character of the ten Tropes of eVo^?;. We may safely affirm that tin- foundation principles of Pyrrhonism are due to Pyrrho, and the originality which gave the school its power. The elaborated arguments, however, and the details of its formulae belong to later times. Con ii n_; now to the relation of Pyrrhonism to the Academy, the connection between the two is difficult to exactly determine, between the time of Pyrrho and that of Aenesidemus. Scepticism in the Academy however, never absolutely identical with Pyrrhonism, although at certain periods of the history of the Aca- demy the difference was slight. We can trace throughout the evolution of doubt, as shown to us in Pyrrhonism., and in Academic Scepticism, the different results which followed the difference in origin of the two movements, and these differences followed according to general laws of development of thought. Arcesilaus, who introduced doubt into the Academy, claimed to return to the dia- lectic of Socrates, and suppressing the lectures, 1 which 1 Compare Maccoll Op. tit. p. 36. Critical Examination of Pyrrhonism. 89 were the method of teaching in the later schools of philosophy, introduced discussions instead, as being more decidedly a Socratic method. Although, accord- ing to Sextus, he was the one leader of the Academy whose Scepticism most nearly approached that of -^Pyrrhonism, 1 yet underneath his whole teaching lay that dialectic principle so thoroughly in opposition to the empiricism of Pyrrho. The belief of Socrates and Plato in the existence of absolute truth never entirely lost its influence over the Academy, but was like a hidden germ, destined to reappear after Scepticism had passed away. It finally led the Academy back to Dog- matism, and prepared the way for the Eclecticism with which it disappeared from history. The history of Pyrrhonism and that of Academic Scepticism were for a time contemporaneous. The im- mediate follower of Pyrrho, Timon, called by Sextus the " prophet of Pyrrho," 2 was a contemporary of Arcesilaus. That he did not consider the Scepticism of the Academy identical with Pyrrhonism is proved from the fact that he did not himself join the Academy, but was, on the contrary, far from doing so. That he regarded Arcesilaus as a Dogmatic is evident from his writings. 3 One day, on seeing the chief of the Academy approaching, he cried out, " What are you doing here among us who are free?" 4 After the death of Timon, the Pyrrhonean School had no representative till the time of Ptolemy of Gyrene, 5 and Greek Scepticism was represented by the Academy. That Pyrrho had a strong influence over Arcesilaus, the founder of the Middle Academy, 1 Hyp. i. 232. 2 Adv. Math. I. 53. 3 Diog. iv. 6, 33, 34. 4 Diog. ix. 12, 114. 5 Diog. ix. 12, 115. DO >^SV./-///..s EmpirlcuH and Greek Scepticism. coi idem us the Academy because of the theory that good and evil exist, or if this cannot be decidedlv proved, yet that it is more probable that what is railed good < than the contrary. 1 The whole Academic teaching of probabilities con- tradicted the standpoint of the Sceptics that our ideas are equal as regards trustworthiness and untrustworthi- ness, 2 for the Academicians declared that some ideas are probable and some improbable, and they make a difference even in those ideas that they call probable. Sextus claims that there are three fundamental grounds of difference between Pyrrhonism and the Academy. The first is the doctrine of probability which the Academicians accept in regard to the supe- rior trust worth in- me ideas over others. 8 The second is the different way in which the two schools follow their teachers. The Pyrrhoneans follow without striving or strong effort, or even strong inclination, as a child follows his teacher, while the Academicians follow with sympathy and assent, as Carneades and Clito- machus affirm. 4 The third difference is in the aim, for the Academicians follow what is probable in life. The Sceptics follow nothing, but live according to laws, customs, and natural feelings undogmatu -ally. 5 The difference between the later teaching of the Academy and Pyrrhonism is evident, and Sextus treats of it briefly, as not requiring discussion, 6 as Philo taught that the nature of facts is incomprehensible, and Antio- chus transferred the Stoa to the Academy. It is therefore 1 Hyp. i. 226. * Hyp. i. 230. 2 Hyp. i. 227. 5 Hyp. i. 231. 3 Hyp. i. 229. Hyp. i. 235. Critical Examination of Pyrrhonism. 93 evident, from the comparison which we have made, that we do not find in the Academy, with which Scep- ticism after the death of Timon was so long united, the exact continuance of Pyrrhonism. The philosophical enmity of the two contemporaries, Timon and Arcesilaus, the Academician who had most in common with Pyr- rhonism, is an expression of the fundamental incom- patibility between the two schools. During all the chequered history of the Academy the dormant idealism was there, underlying the outward development. Although during the time of Arcesilaus and Carneades the difference was so slight as to seem a mere matter of form of expression, yet the different foundations on which the two schools stood was always recognisable. On the one hand there was the germ of idealism which was destined to awake to a new life, and on the other, the attempt at absolute negation which was to result in the final extinction of Pyrrho- nism. We find in both, it is true, especially in the time of Arcesilaus, the aim of eVo^. 1 Both placed great weight on IcroaOeveia^ or the equal value of opposing arguments. 2 The foundation of the GTro^rj was, however, different in the two cases. Arcesilaus founded his on dialectic, while Pyrrho's was empirical. The Pyrrhonean believed that ideas give us no knowledge of the outer world ; the Academic Sceptic believed that we cannot distinguish between true and false ideas, so such knowledge is impossible. The Pyrrhonean denied that truth could exist in ideas because of their contradictory nature, and consequently 1 Hyp. i. 232. 2 Diog. ix. 73; Hyp. n. 130; in, 65. 91 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. the existence of all truth, fjirj&ev elvat, rfj aXr^Bela eVl TrdvTcav^sThe Academic Sceptic granted that the _truth was possibly contained in ideas, but affirn _that it could never be known to us. The Pyrrhonean__ prided themselves on still being seekers for although^ ordinary ideas are too contradictory knowle of the outer world, they did not deny that >ueh know- ledge might be possible, but simply susp-nd-d the j i \ dgment regarding it. To the Pyrrhonean the re- correspond <-ti uctive element. In the Academic Scepsis such an element was found throughout all its hi.Mory in tin- theory of Probability. Arcesilaus himself laid great stress upon this doctrine, ich Sextus caret ull\ !y inconsist- ent with Pyrrhonism. Arcesilaus plainly teaches that, having suspended one's judgment in regard to m;r of knowledge, one should control his choices, his refu and his actions by the probable. 3 After Antiochus introduced Eclecticism into the Academy, Pyrrhonism was the only representative of (Jreek Scepticism, and it flourished for over two cen- turies after our era, and then also disappeared, no more ;lar philosophical school. 1 Diog. ix. 11, 61. -Hyp. 1.229. - Ma, , Critical Examination of Pyrrhonism. 95 Having considered at length the essence of Pyrrho- nism as presented by Sextus Empiricus, it now remains to briefly note the characteristics that formed its strength and weakness, and the causes of its final downfall. Herbart says that every philosopher is a Sceptic in the beginning, bat every Sceptic remains always in the beginning. This remark may well be applied to Pyr- rhonism. We find in its teachings many fundamental philosophical truths which might have formed the be- ginning of great philosophical progress, but wh^ch^were never developed to any positive results. The teachings of Pyrrhonism were some of them well fitted to prepare the way to idealism. The great idea of the relativity of Vorstellungen is made very prominent by the ten Tropes of eVo^r/. Aenesidemus, in his eight Tropes against aetiology, shows the absurdity of the doctrine of causality when upheld on materialistic grounds. That was to him final, errel OVK ecrrai ainov. He could not divine that although the result which he presented was logical, it only led to a higher truth. It was reserved for the greatest of modern philosophers to reveal to the world that causality is a condition, and a necessary condition, of thought. When Aenesidemus proved by his seventh Trope that causality is subjective, he regarded it as fatal to the doctrine ; yet this conclusion was a marked step in advance in critical philosophy, although Aesesidemus- could not himself see it in all its bearings. The great difference between Aenesidemus and Kant is the differ- ence between the materialist and the believer in sub- jective reality. Both agreed in the unknown nature of the Ding an sich, but this was to the Pyrrhonist the end of all his philosophy ; to Kant, however, the beginning. !H> Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. Pyrrhonism has rendered, notwithstandii . ats of fatal weakness, marked service to the world in science, philosophy, ethics, and religion. It quickened scientific thought by emphasising empirical methods of invc % gation, and 1>\ all results i'ound'-d without sufficient data upon false hypotheses. If, instea denying the possibility of all sciei of the .want of a criterion of the truth of phenomena, the" Fyrrhonists had comprehended the possibility of a science of phenomena, they mi^ht have l.-d the world"" in scientific progress. 1 jn th IS to thought that t: y j)n dogmatic beliefs occasioned. Pyrrhonism brought together all the must prominent theories of the old schools of philosophy to test tin their contradictious, and this very process of critici-m often d< uioii.xti -ated the power oTthe truth which they stained. Sextus Empiricus was often charged by the Church Fathers with corrupting religious belief, and yet the st service which Pyrrhonism has rendered the world was in religious and ethical lines. This sen did not, naturally, consist in destroying belief in al. lute truth, as the Sceptic professed to do, but in preparing the way to find it. The bold attacks of Scepticism on all truth led men to investigate ethical and religious teachings, to examine the grounds of their belief, and to put in practical use the right of reason and free discussion. Scepticism was the antecedent of freedom of con- science and rational criticism, 2 and the absolute right of 1 Compare Lewes Op. cit. p. 463. 2 Compare Cbaignet Op. cit. p. 460. Critical Examination of Pyrrhonism. 97 scientific thought. The Sceptics, however, reaped none of the benefits of their own system. They remained, as it were, always on the threshold of possible progress. With the keys to great discoveries in their hands, the doors of philosophical and scientific advancement were for ever closed to them by the limitations of their own system. The inherent weakness of Pyrrhonism lay in its . ; psychological inconsistency and in its negative character. I think that weTmay safely say that Pyrrhonism was the most consistent system of Scepticism ever offered to the world, and yet it proves most decidedly that complete Scepticism is psychologically impossible. A man may give up his belief in one set of ideas, and, if they are ideas that are popularly accepted, he will be called a Sceptic, as was the case with Hume. He must, however, replace these ideas by others equally positive, and then he is no longer a Sceptic, but a Dogmatic, for he believes in something. We have shown that the greatest thinkers of Pyrrho- nism, Pyrrho, Aenesidemus, and Agrippa, were not examples of absolute Scepticism, and although Sextus Empiricus realised what consistency demanded in this respect, and affirmed on almost every page that he was asserting nothing, yet there is not a paragraph of his books in which he does not, after all, dogmatise on some subject. Complete Scepticism is contrary to the funda- mental laws of language, as all use of verbs involves some affirmation. The Pyrrhonists realised this, and therefore some of them wrote nothing, like Pyrrho, their leader, and others advocated afyacria 1 as one of the doctrines of their system. 1 Hyp. i. 192. TO' I RETURN TO the circulation desk of any University of California Library or to the NORTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY Bldg. 400, Richmond Field Station University of California Richmond, CA 94804-4698 ALL BOOKS MAY BE RECALLED AFTER 7 DAYS 2-month loans may be renewed by calling (510)642-6753 1-year loans may be recharged by bringing books to NRLF Renewals and recharges may be made 4 days prior to due date DUE AS STAMPED BELOW 2 5 2003 DD20 15M 4-02 ' VB 24729 U.C. BERKELEY LIBRARIES