DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Honlion : C. J. CLAY and SOX, CAMBEIDGE UNIVERSITY TRESS WAREHOUSE, AVE :^rARIA LANE. CAMBRIDGE: I>i:i(;ilToN. lil'.l.l.. .\M> co. LEIPZIG: r. A. liKocKllArs. DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA A STUDY IN THE lIISToUV OF GREEK ALGEBRA BY -ClJUilM T. L. HEATH, B.A. SCHOLAR OF TRINITY COI.LKCiK, CAMHRIlxiK. EDITED FOR THE SYNDJC&^^^^XH^ UNIVEPiSITY PliESS. -^-V3 ^-'-- 3^"\S>. ((UHIVEP.'ITY QTambriligc : AT THE UNIVERSITY PKK.SS. 1885 [All Ei'jhts A'.^.Tc;./.] CTambritigr : rniNTF.ri dy c. j. clay, m.a. and sox, AT THK rXIVERSITY PRKSS. PREFACE. The scope of the prosont book is sufficiently indicatod Ity the title and the Table of Contents. In the chapter on " Dioijhantos' notation and definitions" several suggestions are made, which I believe to be new, with regard to the origin and significance of the symbols employed by Diophantos. A few words may be necessary to explain the purp(».se of the Appendix. This is the result of the compression of a large book into a very small space, and claims to have no inde- pendent value apart from the rest of my work. It is in- tended, first, as a convenient place of reference for mathe- maticians who may, after reading the account of Diophantos' methods, feel a desire to see them in actual operation, and, secondly, to exhibit the several instances of that variety of peculiar devices which is one of the most prominent of the characteristics of the Greek algebraist, but which cannot l)o brought under general rules and tabulated in the same way as the processes described in Chapter V. The Appendix, then, is a necessary part of the whole, in that there is much in Diophantos which could not be introduced elsewhere ; it must not, however, be considered as in any sense an alternative to the rest of the book: indeed, owing to its extremely con- densed form, I could hardly hope that, by itself, it would even be comprehensible to the mathematician. I will merely add that I have twice carefully worked out the .«;<.lution of H. D. ^ VI PREFACE. every problem from tlic proof-sheets, so that I hope and be- lieve that no mistakes will be found to have escaped me. It would be mere tautology to enter into further details here. One remark, however, as to what the work does not, and does not profess to, include may not be out of place. No treatment of Diophantos could be complete without a thorough revision of the text. I have, however, only cursorily inspected one MS. of my author, that in the Bodleian Library, which unfortunately contains no more than a small part of the first of the six Books. The best Mss, are in Paris and Rome, and I regret that I have had as yet no opportunity of consulting them. Though this would be a serious drawback were I editing the text, no collation of MSS. could afifect my exposition of Diophantos' methods, or the solutions of his problems, to any appreciable extent; and, further, it is more than doubtful, in view of the unsatisfactory results of the collation of three of the MSS, by three different scholars in the case of one, and that the most important, of the few ob- scure passages which need to be cleared up, whether the text in these places could ever be certainly settled. I should be ungrateful indeed if I did not gladly embrace this opportunity of acknowledging the encouragement which I have received from Mr J. W, L. Glaisher, Fellow and Tutor of Trinity College, to whose prospective interest in the work before it was begun, and unvarying kindness while it was proceeding, I can now thankfully look back as having been in a great degree the " moving cause " of the whole. And, finally, I wish to thank the Syndics of the University Press for their liberality in undertaking to publish the volume. T. L. HEATH. 11 May, 1885. LIST OF BOOKS OH PAl'KKS KKAD ()I{ KKKKlMtKI) 'K >. SO FAR AS THEY CON'CERN OK AUK ISKFIL TO THE SUBJECT. 1. Bookg directlif upon Dinphautois. Xylander, Diopliaiiti Alexambini Reruni Arithmetit-arum Libri sex Item Liber de Numcri.s Polygonis. Opus incoiupiirabile Latino redditum et Commeutariis explanatum Biusileae, 1575. Bachet, Diophanti Alexandrini Arithmeticoioim Libri sex, et de niuueri.s multaugulis liber uiiu.s. Lutetiae Parisiorimi, 1G21. Diophanti AJexandi-ini Ai-ithmeticorum libri sex, et de uumeris multaugu- lis liber unus. Cum commeutariis C. G. Bacheti V.C. et oWrua- tionibus D. P. de Fermat Senatoris Tolcsani. Tolosae, 1G70. ScHULZ, Diophantus von Alexandria arithmetische Aufgaben nebst desseu Schrift liber die Polygon-zahlen. Aus dem Griecbi-scheu iibersetzt und mit Anmerkungeu begleitet. Berlin, 18-22. PoSELGER, Diophantus von Alexandrien iiber die Polygon-Zahlen. Uebersetzt, mit Zusiitzen. Leipzig, 1810. Crivelli, Elementi di Fisica ed i Problemi aritlmietici di Diofanto Alessandrino analiticamente dimostrati. In Venczia, 1744. P. Glimstedt, Forsta Boken af Diophanti Arithmetica algebraisk Ocfvcr- sattning. Lund, 1855. Stevin and Girard, " Translation " in Les Oeuvres mathematiques de Simon Stevin. Leyde, 1684. 2. M'orha indirectly fluridati)i<j Diftj'lnmtitg. BoMBELLi, L' Algebra diuisa in tre Libri Bologna, 1579. F'ermat, Opera Varia mathematica. Tolixsai', H;7l>. Brassinne, Precis des Oeuvres mathematicpies de P. Fcrnuit et de I'Aritlj- metique de Diophante. P'""is l''*-'>3- CossALi, Origine, traspoi-to in Italia, prinii progre.s.si in e-ssa dell' Algebni Storia critica Parnm, 17U7. Nesselmanx, Die Algebra der Griechcn. Berlin, IM2. John Kersey, Elements of Algebra. London, 1674. Walms, Algebra (in Opera Mathematica. Ox.»iiittC, 161)5 9 . Saundek.son, N., Elements of Algebra. >"»'' Vlll LIST OF AUTIlulUTIKS. 3. Buuks ic/tich iiifiitivii or (/ice infurmation about Dio^laiiUof, including historiiis of mathematics. CuLEUHOOKE, AlgeVira with Arithmetic and ^Mensuration from the Sanscrit of Brahmaguptii and Bhiiscara. London, 1817. SriDAs, Lexicon (ed. G. Bernhardy). Ilalis et Brunsvigae, 1853. Fabricii.s, Bibliotheca Graeca (ed. Harless). AuCLEARAJ, History of the Dynasties (tr. Pococke). Oxon. 16C3. Ch. Th. v. Murr, Memorabilia Bibliothecarum publicarum Norimbergen- sium et Universitatis Altdorfinae. Norimbergae, 1786. DoPPELMAYR, Historische Nachricht von den Xiirnbergischen Mathema- ticis und Kiinstlern. (Nliruberg, 1730.) Vos.siis, De universae mathesius natiira et coustitutione Amstelaedami, 16G0. Hkilbronneh, Historia matheseos universae. Lipsiae, 1742. MuNTLCLA, Histoire des Math(5matiques. Paris, An 7. IviAEUEL, Matheniatisches "\Vorterl)uch. Leipzig, 1830. Kaestner, Geschiclite der Matheniatik. Giittingen, 1796. BussuT, Histoire G(5uerale des Mathematiques. Paris, 1810. Hankel, Zur Geschichte der Mathematik in Altertlium und Mittelalter. Leipzig, 1874. Cantor, Vorlesungen Uber Geschichte der Mathematik, Band L Leipzig, 1880. Dr Heinrich Slter, Gesch. d. :^Lathematischen Wisseuschaften, Zurich, 1873. Jame.s Gow, a short History of Greek Mathematics. Camb. Univ. Press, 1884. 4. Papers or Pamphlets read in connection with Diophantos. Poselger, Beitriige zur Unbestimmten Analysis. (Berlin xihhandhmgen, 1832.'i I.. RoDET, L'Algebre d'Al-Kharizmi et les methodes indienne et grecque. {Journal AHiatitjite, Janvier, 1878.) WoEPCKE, Extrait du Faklni, traitc^ d'Algebrc par Abou Bekr ^[ohammed ben Alhayan Alkarkhi, precede d'un memoiresurralgebre indeterminet; chez los Arabes. Paris, 1853 . WoEi'CKE, Mathematiques chez les Orientaux. 1. Journal Asiatique, Fdvrier-Mars, 1855. 2. Journal Asiatique, Avril, 1855. I'. Tanxehv, "A <iuelque epocpie vivait Dioi)hante /" {Bulletin des iSciences Mat/ufm. ct Astronom. 1879.) I'. Tax.nery, L'Arithm(5ti(iue dans Pajtpus {Bordeaux Memoirs, 1880.) lIusEN, Tiie Algel>ra of .Mohammed ben Musa. London, 1831. 1Ii:ii>er<;, Quacstiones Archimedeae. llauniae, 1879. CONTENTS. CHAPTER I. HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION'. PAGES § 1. Diophantos' name and particulars of his life .... i § 2. His date. Different views 3 («) Internal evidence considered 4_S {b) External evidence 8 — IG § 3. Results of the preceding investigation 16—17 CHAPTER II. THE WORKS OF DIOPHANTOS ; THEIR TITLES AND GENERAL CONTENTS; THE PORTIONS WHICH SURVIVE. § 1. Titles : no real evidence that 13 books of Aritliiiietics ever existed corresponding to the title IS — 23 No trace of lost books to be restored from Arabia. Corruption must have taken place before 11th cent, and probably before 950 A.D 23— "iC, Poiisms lost before 10th cent. a.d. 2<) § 2. What portion of the Arithmetics is lost? The contents of the lost books. The Polygonal Numbers and Porism.i may have formed part of the complete ArithmcticK. Objections to this theory 2(>— 3."> Other views of the contents of thf lost Books .... 3J — 37 Conclusion 37 CHAPTER III. THE WlllTEKS UPON J»lolMIA.\ T« ),s. § 1. (heck 38-39 § 2. Arabian 39 — 12 § 3. European gencially 42— 5('> CONTENTS. CHAPTER IV. \OT.\TI(»N AND DEFINITIONS (»F DlOPH.\NTOS. VAC.KS § 1. Introduction ,57 § 2. Sign for the unknown quantity discubsed 57 — 67 § 3. Notation for powers of the unknown G7— 09 § i. Objection that Diophantos loses generality by the want of more algebraic symbols answered 69 Other questions of notation : operations, fractions, dc. . . 69—76 § 5. General remarks on the historical development of algebraic notation : three stages exhibited 76—80 § 6. Ou the influence of Diophantos' notation on his work . . 80—82 CHAPTER V. §1. §3. SI. diophantos' METHODS OF SOLUTION. General remarks. Criticism of the positions of Hankcl and Ncsselmann Diophantos' treatment of equations ..... (A) Determinate equations of different degrees. (1) Pure equations of different degrees, i.e. equations con taining only one power of tlie unknown (2) Mixed quadratics (3) Cubic equation ....... Indeterminate equations. '.. Indeterminate equations of the first and second degrees. (li) (1) (2) Single equation (second degree) • 1. Those which can always be rationally solved 2. Those which can be rationally solved only under certain conditions II, Double equations. 1. First general method (first degree) . Second method (first degree) . 2. Double equation of the second degrei Indeterminate equations of liigher degrees. (1) Single ecjuations (first class) ,, (second class) (2) Double equations . Summary of the prerediiiji incestiijntioii Transition ..... Mitiiod of limits .... Method of appro.\imation to limits . 88—114 88- -90 90- -93 93- -94 95- -98 95 95—98 99—105 105—107 107 108—111 111—112 112—113 113—114 114—115 115—117 117—120 CONTKNTS. CHAPTER VI. PAOEH 1. The PonsHis of Diophantos 121 I2.'i 2. Other theorems assumed or implied 12.>— 132 ('/) Numbers as the sum of two squares 127— 1:<0 (h) Numbers as the sum of three squares l:{0 — l:{l (c) Numbers as the sum of four squares 131— 1H2 §1. §2. §3. §4. §5. §6. §7. CHAPTER VII. HOW FAR WAS DIOPHANTOS ORIGINAL? Preliminary 133—134 Diophantos' algebra not derived from Arabia .... 134—135 Reference to Hypsikles 13.") — 130 The evidence of his language 13G— 138 Wallis' theory of Greek Algebra 138 Comparison of Diophantos with his Greek predecessors . . 139—142 Discussion in this connection of the Cattle-prohlem . . . 142 — 147 CHAPTER VIII. DIOPHANTOS AND THE EARLY ARABIAN ALGEBRAISTS. § 1. Preliminary § 2. Comparison of Diophantos with Mohammed ibn Musfi . . 149- § 3. Diophantos and Abu'1-Wafa § 4. An anonymous Arabic ms. 155- § 5. Abu Ja'far Mohammed ibn Alhusain §G. Alkarkhi 156- 14S -155 155 -156 156 APPENDIX. ABSTRACT OF DIOPHANTOS. A rithmetics. Book I . 16.S— 171 Bookn . 172—181 Bookm . 181-189 Book IV . 189-208 BookV . 209-224 Book VI . 225-237 Polygonal Numbers . 238—244 EREATUM. On p. 78, last line but one of note, for " Targalia" read "Tartaglia" DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. CHAPTER I. Historical Introduction. § 1. The doubts about l^iophantos begin, as has been remarked by Cossali^ with his very name. It cannot be posi- tively decided whether his name was Diophanfos or Diophan^es. The preponderance, however, of authority is in favour of the view that he was called Diophantos. (1) The title of the work which has come down to us under his name gives us no clue. It is Aiocpdvrov 'A\€^avBp€Q}<i 'AptOfj,- rjTLKwv ^i/SXia ly. Now Atocjjdvrov may be the Genitive of either Ai6(f)avTo<i or A,io^dvrr]<;. We learn liowever from this title that he lived at Alexandria, (2) In Suidas under the article "TiraTia the name occurs in the Accusative and in old editions is given as Aio<f)dvTr}v ; but Bachet'^ in the Preface to his edition of Diophantos assures us that two excellent Paris MSS. have Aio^avrov. Besides this, Suidas has a separate article At6(})avTo<i, ovofia Kvpiov. More- over Fabricius mentions several persons of the same name Ai6<f)avTo<;, but the name /lio(f)dvTr]<i nowhere occurs. It is on this ground probable that the correct form is AiotpavTo^. We may compare it with "EK<f)avTo<;, but we cannot go so far as to say, with Bachet, that Aio<f)dvT'r]^ is not Greek ; for we have the analogous forms 'lepot^dvrrjt;, o-vK0(f)dvTr]<;. 1 "Su la desinenza del nome coniincia la divcisitii tni gli scrittori " (p. 61). - '-Ubi moueudus es imprimis, in editis Suidae libris male habori, <«j Ato- (pavT-qv, ut ex duobus probatissimis codicibus manu exaratis (lui extant in Bibliotheca Regia, depraehendi, qui veram exhibcut Icctionem d% Aw^ayrof." H. D. ^ 2 DIOPIIAXTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. (3) In the only quotation from Diophantos which we know Tlioon of Alexandria (fl. 3G5 — 390 A.D.) speaks of him as At6<f)avTo<i. (4) On the other hand Abu'lfaraj, the Arabian historian, in his History of the Dynasties, is thought to be an authority for the form Diophanfcs, and certainly in his Latin translation of the two passages in which D. is mentioned by Abu'lfaraj, Pococke writes Diophantes. But, while in the first of the two passages in the original the vowel is doubtful, in the second the name is certainly Diophantos. Hence Abu'lfaraj is really an authority for the form Diophantos. (5) Of more modern writers, Rafael Bombelli in his Algebra, published 1572, writes in Italian "Diofanie" corre- sponding to Aio(f)dvT7]<;. But Joannes Regiomontanus, Joachim Camerarius, James Peletarius, Xylander and Bachet all write Diophan^ws. We may safely conclude, then, that Diophanios was the name of our author. Far more perplexing than the doubt as to his name is the question of the time at which he lived. As no certainty can even now be said to have been reached on this point, it will be necessary to enumerate the indications which bear on the question. Before proceeding to consider in order the internal and external evidence, it will be well to give the only facts which are known of his personal history, and which can be gathered from an arithmetical epigram upon Diophantos. This epigram, the probable date of which it will be necessary to consider later along with the question of its authorship, is as follows : Ovt6<; tol ^t6(f>avToi> e'^et rd(f)o<;, d /jiiya Oavfia, Kal T«</)09 €K Te^i/779 fierpa ^10 to \i<y€L. "Ektt]v Kovpi^eiv ^toTou ^eo? cutraae fioipijv, AoyBeKUTrj S" iTriOeU firjXa Tropev '^(Xodetv. Tfj 8' ap' e'</)' e^BofuiTT} to yafirjXiov i'jyfraTO <f>iyyo<;, E/c 8e ydficov TrifMirrcp TralS' iirev^vaev eret. At ai r7]\vy€Tov BetXov Te«09, VjfXLav irarpo^, Tov 8e Kal 7; Kpvepo^ fierpov eXoov ^iotov. Iler'^o? 3' av iriavpecro'L Trapijyopecov eviavTOL<i Tj]8e TToaov ao(piT) repfx eTreprja-e /3iOV. HISTORICAL IXTUODUCTIOX. 3 The solution of this epigram-problem gives 84 as the age at Avhich Diophautos died. His boyhood lasted 14 years, his beard grew at 21, he married at 33/; a son was born to him 5 years later and died at the age of 42, when his father was 80 years old. Diophanto.s' own death followed 4 years later at the age of 84. Diophantos having lived to so great an age, an approximate date is all that we can expect to find for the production of his works, as we have no means of judg- ing at what time of life he would be likely to write his Aiithmetics. § 2. The most important statements upon the date of Diophantos which we possess are the following : (1) Abu'lfaraj, whom Cossali calls "the courageous compiler of a universal history from Adam to the 13th century," in his History of the Dynasties before mentioned, places Diophantos, without giving any reason, under the Emperor Julian (3G1 — 368 A.D.). This is the view which has been ordinarily held. It is that of Montucla. (2) We find in the preface to Rafael Bombclli's Algebra, published 1572, a dogmatic statement that Diophantos lived under Antoninus Pius (138 — 161 A.D.). This view too has met with considerable favour, being adopted by Jacobus de Billy, Blancanus, Vossius, Heilbronner, and others. Besides these views we may mention Bachet's conjecture, which identifies the Diophantos of the Arithmetics with an astrologer of the same name, who is ridiculed in an epigram attributed to Lucilius ; whence Bachet concludes that he lived about the time of Nero (54—68) (not under Tiberius, as Nesselmann supposes Bachet to say). The three views here mentioned will be discussed later in detail, as they are all worthy of consideration. The same cannot be said of a number of other theories on the subject, of which I will quote only one as an example. Simon Stevin* places Diophantos later than the Arabian algebraist Mohammed ibn Miisa 1 Les Oeuvrcs Mathcin. de Sim. Stevin, augm. par Alh. Girard, Loyden, 1634, "Quant h, Diophant, il semblc iiu'cn son temps los inventions de Mahomet ayent seulement tsto cognues, commc bo poult colligcr de sea six premiers livres." 1—2 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Al-Kliarizmi who lived in the first half of the 9th century, the absurdity of which view will appear. We must now consider in detail the (a) Internal evidence of the date of Diophantos. (1) It would be natural to hope to find, under this head, references to the works of earlier or contemporary mathema- ticians. Unfortunately there is only one such reference trace- able in Diophantos' extant writings. It occurs in the fragment upon Polygonal Numbers, and is a reference to a definition given by a certain Hypsikies\ Thus, if we knew the date of Hypsikles, it would enable us to fix with certainty an upper limit, before which Diophantos could not have lived. It is particularly unfortunate that we cannot determine accurately at what time Hypsikles himself lived. Now to Hypsikles is attributed the work on Regular Solids which forms Books XIV. and xv, of the Greek text of Euclid's Elements. In the introduction to this work the author relates'^ that his father knew a treatise of Apollonius only in an incorrect form, whereas he himself afterwards found it correctly worked out in another book of ApoUonios, which was easily accessible anywhere in his time. From this we may with justice conclude that Hypsikles' father was an elder contemporary of ApoUonios, and must have died before the corrected version of ApoUonios' treatise was given to the world. Hypsikles' work itself is dedicated to a friend of his father's, Protarchos by name. Now ApoUonios died about 200 B.C.; hence it follows that Hypsikles' treatise ' Polyg. Numbers, prop. 8. "Kal iirtdelxOri t6 waph. 'typiKkeX iv 8p(p Xeyd/J-evov.^' '^ <Tvvairob(ixOivTo% oZv koI tov 'T^iacX^ouj 8pov, k.t.X." ' "Kal TTOTf SteXoOfTfj (sc. Basileides of Tyre and Hypsikles' father) rb virb ' AwoWuviov ypa<p^u wepi ttjs (TvyKplaems roO SwStKaiSpov Kal tov tlKoffa^dpov tlov (U TT)v avTj]v <j<paipav iyypa<{>onivuv, rlva \oyov ix^i vpbs dWijXa, fSo^af raOra fMT] dpOQi ytypaipivai rbv 'ArroWwi/iof. aCrrol di ravra SiaKaddpavres fypa\j/av wj Tjj/ iKoveiv TOV naTpos. ^yCo Si vartpov irtpUtreaov iTlpi^ /3t/JA/v i"r6 ' AiroWuvlov iKbfhotxivtfi, Kal TTtpUxovTi anobuiiu ijyiwi (?) irepl tov i/iroKfifj^vov. Kal fieydXtji i\J/vxaywy^Or)v iirl Ty irpofiXi^fxaTos ^T-qati. Tb fj.iv viro ' AwoWwi'lov iKbodh (oiKf KOiff, OKOirdv. Kal yap irtpKpiptrai, k. t. X." HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION. 5 on Regular Solids was probably written about 180 B.C. It was clearly a youthful productiou. Besides this we have another work of Hypsikles, of astronomical content, entitled in Greek dva^opLK6<i. Now in this treatise we find for the first time the division of the circumference of a circle into 360 degrees, which Autolykos, an astronomer a short time anterior to Euclid, was not acquainted with, nor, apparently, Eratosthenes who died about 194 B.C. On the other hand Hypsikles used no trigonometrical methods : these latter are to some extent em- ployed by the astronomer Hipparchos, who made observations at Rhodes between the years 101 and 126. Thus the discovery of trigonometrical methods about 150 agrees well with the conclusion arrived at on other grounds, that Hypsikles flourished about 180 B.C. We must not, however, omit to notice that Nesselmann, an authority always to be mentioned with respect, takes an entirely different view. He concludes that we may with a fair approach to certainty place Hypsikles about the year 200 of our era, but upon insufficient grounds. Of the two arguments used by Nesselmann in support of his view one is grounded upon the identification of an Isidores whom Hypsikles mentions' as his instructor with the Isidores of an article in Suidas: 'lo-tSwpo? ^tXocro0O9 09 e^Ckocro^ae fiev vtto TOt«? dS€\<f)oi<;, eiirep rt? dWo<i, iv fiaOrjfiaaLv: and, further, upon a conjecture of Fabricius about it. Assuming that the two persons called Isidoros in the two places are identical we have still to deter- mine his date. The question to be answered is, what is the reference in viro roh dB€X(j)oi<; ? Now Fabricius makes a con- jecture, which seems hazardous, that the dBe\(f)ot are the brothers M. Aurelius Antoninus and L. Aurelius Verus, who were joint-Emperors from 160 to 169 A.D. This date being assigned to Isidoros, it would follow that Hypsikles should be placed about A. d. 200. In the second place Nesselmann observes that according to Diophantos Hypsikles is the discoverer of a proposition respect- ing polygonal numbers which we find in a rather less perfect ' Eucl. XV. 5. "77 5^ evpejii, u$'l<xl5wpos 6 Ti/x^Tepos vip-nyqaaTo fi^yat 5i6dcK- fiXos, ^x" ■'■0" '■poVoi/ TovTov," 6 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. form in Nikomachos and Theon of Smyrna ; from this he argues that Hypsikles must have been later than both these mathematicians, adducing as further evidence that Theon (who is much given to quoting) does not quote him. Doubtless, as Theon lived under Hadrian, about 130 A.D., this would give a date for Hypsikles which would agree with that drawn from Fabricius' conjecture ; but it is not possible to regard either piece of evidence as in any way trustworthy, even if it w^ere not contradicted by the evidence before adduced on the other side. We may say then with certainty that Hypsikles, and there- fore a fortiori Diophantos, cannot have written before 180 B.C!. (2) The only other name mentioned in Diophantos' writings is that of a contemporary to whom they are dedicated. This name, however, is Dionysios, which is of so common occurrence that we cannot derive any help from it whatever. (3) Diophantos' work is so UTiique among the Greek trea- tises which we possess, tliat he cannot be said to recal the style or subject-matter of any other author, except, indeed, in the fragment on Polygonal Numbers ; and even there the reference to Hypsikles is the only indication we can lay hold of. Tiie epigram-problem, which forms the last question of the 5th book of Diophantos, has been used in a way which is rather curious, as a means of determining the date of the Arithmetics, by M. Paul Tannery \ The enunciation of this problem, which is different from all the rest in that (a) it is in the form of an epigram, (6) it introduces numbers in the concrete, as applied to things, instead of abstract numbers (with which alone all the other problems of Diophantos are concerned), is doubtless borrowed by him from some other source. It is a question about wine of two different qualities at the price respectively of 8 and 5 drachmae the %o{;9. It appears also that it was wine of inferior quality as it was mixed by some one as drink for his servants. Now M. Tannery argues (a) tliat the numbers 8 and 5 were not hit upon to suit the metre, for, as these are the only numbers which occur in the epigram, and both are found in * lUilh'tin (ten Sciences mathnnntiqiiis et astronomif/ucs, 1879, p. 201. HISTORICAL INTRODrCTION. 7 the same line in the compounds 6KTa8pd^^f^ov<: and irein-eSpdx- fiov<i, some other numerals would serve the purposes of metre equally well, (b) Neither were they taken in view of the solu- tion of the problem, for each number of ;^6e? which it was required to find are found to contain fractions. Hence (c) the basis on which the author composed his problem must have been the price of wines at the time. Now, says M. Tannery*, it is evident that the prices mentioned for wines of poor quality are famine prices. But wine was not dear until after tlie time of the Antonines. Therefore the composer of the epi^-am, and hence Diophantos also, is later than the period of the Antonines. This argument, even if it is correct, does no more than give us a later date than we before arrived at as the upper limit. Nor can M. Tannery consistently assert that this determination necessarily brings us at all near to the date of Diophantos ; for in another place he maintains that Diophantos was no original genius, but a learned mathematician who made a collection of problems previously known ; thus, if so much had already been done in the domain which is represented for us exclusively by Diophantos, the composer of the epigram in question may well have lived a considerable time before Diojihantos. It may be mentioned here, also, that one of the examples which M. Tan- nery quotes as an evidence that problems similar to, and even more difficult than, those of Diophantos were in vogue before his time, is the famous Problem of the Cattle, which has been commonly called by the name of Archimedes ; and this very problem is fatal to the theory that arithmetical epigrams must necessarily be founded on ftict. These considerations, however, though proving M. Tannery to be inconsistent, do not neces- sarily preclude the possibility that the inference he draws from the epigram-problem solved by Diophantos is correct, for (a) the date of the Cattle-problem itself is not known, and may be later even than Diophantos, (6) it does not follow that, if M. Tannery's conclusion cannot be proved to be necessarily right, it must therefore be wrong. 1 "II est d'ailleurs facile de se rendre comptc que ccs prix n'ont pas 6t6 choisis en vue de la solution: on doit done supposcr qu'ils sent rt-els. Or ce sent evideininent, pour los vius de basse quality, do prix de famine." 8 DIOPHAXTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. On the vexed question as to how far Diophantos was original we shall have to speak later. Wo pass now to a consideration of the (b) External evidence as to the date of Diophantos. (1 ) We have first to consider the testimony of a passage of Suidas, which has been made much of by writers on the ques- tion of Diophantos, to an extent entirely disproportionate to its intrinsic importance. As however it does not bear solely upon the question of date, but upon another question also, it cannot be here passed over. The passage in question is Suidas' article 'TTTartaV The words which concern us apparently stood in the earliest texts thus, eypay^rev vTro/xvrj/jLa et? Aiocfxivrrjv Tov darpovofiiKov. Kavova et<? to. KOiVLKa' ^AiroWcovlov viro/jiVTjfia. With respect to the reading A.io(f)dvr'}]v, we have already remarked that Bachet asserts that two good Paris MSS. have A.i6(f>avTov. The words as found in the text cannot be right. Aiocfjdvrrjv TOV da-TpovofiiKov should (if the punctuation were right) be Aio(f>dvTr)v TOV d(TTpov6^ov, the former not being Greek. Ku.ster's conjecture '^ is that we should read vTrofivrjfia ek Aio(f)dvTov da-TpovofjLLKov Kavova' et? to, KwviKa ^ AttoWojvlov vTToiJ.vnp.a. If this is right the Diophantos here mentioned must have been an astronomer. In that case the person in question is not our Diophantos at all, for we have no ground whatever to imagine that he occupied himself with Astronomy. It is cer- tain that he was famous only as an arithmetician. Thus John of Jerusalem in his life of John of Damascus^ in speaking of some one's skill in Arithmetic compares him to Pythagoras and ' tiraTla rj O^wvos tov TtufUTpov Ovyarrip tov ' A\f^avSp^wi <pi\oa6^ov xal avTr] <f)iK6(To<poi, KoX woWoh yvwpifioi' yvvr] 'IcridiJopov tov <t>i.\oao<pov iJKnaafv iirl t^s PaaiXdai 'ApKailoV (ypayptv vir6fu/r)na th \io<p(xvTr)v tov dtXTpovopuKov. Kaxoi'a eh Ta KuviKa' ' AiroWwvlov v-ir6fj.injfia. ' Suidae Lexicon, Cantabiigiac, 1705. 3 Chapter xi. of the Life as Kiven in Sancti patris iiostri Joannis Damasceni, Monaclii, et rreshyteri Ilierusulymitani, Opera omnia quae exstant ft ejus nomine circumferuntur. Tonms primus. Parisiis, 1712. 'AvaXoyla^ di'ApidfxrjTiKii ovtu^ i^rfaKr/Kacif ti'^uwr, wi UvOayopai t} Ai6(pavToi, HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION. f) Diophantos, as representing that science. However, Baclict has proposed to identify our Diophantos with an astrologer of the same name, who is ridiculed in an epigram' supposed to he written by Lucilius. Now the ridicule of the epigram would be clearly out of place as applied to the subject of the epigram mentioned above, even supposing that Lucilius' ridiculous hero is not a fictitious personage, as it is not unreasonable to suppose. Bachet's reading of the passage is vTro/ivrjfia eh Aio^afToz/, t6i> darpovofiLKOv Kavova, etf ra koovlku AttoWcoviov vTro^vr,- fia'^. He then proceeds to remark that it shows that Hypatia wrote a Canon Astronomicus, so that she evidently was versed in Astronomy as well as Geometry (as shown by the Commen- tary on Apollonios), two of the three important branches of Mathematics. It is likely then, argues Bachet, that she was acquainted with the third. Arithmetic, and wrote a commentary on the AritJtmetics of Diophantos. But in the first place we know of no astronomical work after that of Claudius Ptolemy, and from the way in which 6 da-rpovo^iLKO'; Kavwv is mentioned it would be necessary to suppose that it had been universally known, and was still in common use at the time of Suidas, and yet was never mentioned by any one else whom we knjULUUi inexplicable hypothesis. ' 'ISipixoyivt) Tov larpov 6 affrpoXoyoi Ai6<f>ai'T(X Eln-e /xovovi ^wfjs ivvia pLrjvas ^X^'"- KcLKeivos ycXdaai, Ti /jl(v 6 KpSvos ivvia. /xrjvwy, ^■qal, \^y€L, (TV voef Ta/xa 5i ci'inofxa. aoc Elwe Kal ^KTslvas fwvov Tjxj/aro' Kal AiO(pain-os 'AWov dve\iri^u)v, avrbs awf (TKapKrev. "Ludit non innenustus poeta turn in Diopbantum AstroloRum, turn in niccli- cum Hermogenera, quem et alibi saepe false admodum perstringit, qniVl solo attactu non aegros modo, sed et ben(^ valentes, velut pestifero sidere afflntoa repente necaret. Itaque nisi Diopbantum nostrum Astrologiae iieritum fuissc negemus, nil prohibet, quo minus eum aetate Lucillij extitisse dicanius." Bacbet, Ad Urtorrm. - From tbis reading it is clear that Bachet did not rest his view of the identity of our Diophantos with the astrologer upon the i)as8age of Suidas. M. Tannery is therefore mistaken in supposing this to be the case, "Bachet, ayant lu dans Suidas qu'Hy^mtia avait commentu le Canon astronomique d© notre auteur..."; that is precisely what Bacbet did rmt read there. 10 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Next, the expression ek Aio^avrov has been objected to by Nesselmann as not being Greek. He maintains that the Greeks never speak of a book by the name of its author, and therefore we ought to have Atocfxivrov dpidfiijTiKa, if the reference were to Diophantos of the Arithmetics. M. Tannery, however, de- fends the use of the expression, on the ground that similar ones are common enough in Byzantine Greek. M. Tannery, accordingly, to avoid the difficulties which we have mentioned, supposes some words to have dropped out after ^lo^avrov, and thinks that we should read et? At6<f)avTov . . .rov aa-rpovofiiKov Kavova. et9 ra KwviKa WiroWcoviov virofivrjixa, suggesting that before tov acrrpovoiiiKov Kavova we might supply et? and under- stand TlroXe^iaiov. It will be seen that it is impossible to lay any stress upon this passage of Suidas. We cannot even make sure from this that Hypatia wrote a commentary upon Diophantos, though it has been very generally asserted by historians of mathematics as an undoubted fact, even by Cossali, who in speaking of the corrupt state into which the text of Diophantos has fallen remarks that Hypatia was the most fortunate of the commen- tators who have ever addressed themselves to his writings. (2) I have already mentioned the epigram which in the form of a problem gives us the only facts we know of Dio- phantos' life. If we only knew the exact date of the author of this epigram, our difficulties would be much lessened. It is commonly assigned to Metrodoros, but even then we are not sure whether Metrodoros of Skepsis or Metrodoros of Byzan- tium is meant. It is now generally supposed that the latter was the author ; and of him we know that he was a gram- marian and arithmetician who lived in the reign of Constantine the Great. (8) It is satisfactory in the midst of so much uncertainty to find a most certain reference to Diophantos in a work by Theon of Alexandria, the fatherof Hypatia, which gives us a loiuer limit for the date, more approximate than we could possibly have derived ironx the article of Suidas. The ftict that Theon quoted Diopiiantos was first noted by Peter Ramus* ; " Diophantus, ' Schold Mathnntitirii, Book i, p. Su. HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION. \\ cujus sex libros, cum tamcn author ipso tredccim poUiceatur, graecos habemus de arithmcticis admirandac subtilitatis artcm coniplexis, quae vulgo Algebra arabico nomine appellatur : cum tamen ex authore hoc antique (citatur enim a Theone) anti- quitas artis appareat. Scripserat et Diophantus harmonica." This quotation was known to Montucla, who however draws an absurd conchision from it* which is repeated by Klucrel in his Worterbuchl The words of Theon which refer to Diopliantos are koI Ai6(})avT6<i (f)r](riv on, rf]<; fxovdSo'i (iixeraderov ova-T]<: Kal earcoay]^ Trcivrore, to 7roWa7rXaaia^u/j,evov elSo'i eV avTTjf avTo TO ei8o9 earat. We have only to remark that these words are identically those of Diophantos' sixth definition, as given in Bachet's text, with the sole difference that iravTore stands in the place of the equivalent dei, in order to see that the refer- ence is certain beyond the possibility of a doubt. The name of Diophantos is again mentioned by Theon a few lines further on. Here then we undoubtedly have a lower limit to the time of Diophantos, supplied by the date of Theon uf Alexandria, and one which must obviously be more approximate than we could have arrived at from any information about his daughter Hypatia, however trustworthy. Theou's date, fortunately, we can determine with accuracy. Suidas^ tells us that he was con- temporary with Pappos and lived in the reign of Theodosius I. The statement that he was contemporary with Pappos is almost 1 "Theon cite une autre ouvrage de cet analyste, oil il ctoit question dc la pratique de I'arithm^tique. Je soupv'onnerois que c'etoit la qu'il expliquoit plus au long les regies de sa nouvelle arithnietique, sur quoi il ue s'ctoit pas assez ^tendu au commencement de ses questions." Montucla, Apparently translated word for word in Eosenthal's EncyclopUdie d. reinen Mathem. iii. 195. - I. 177, under Arithmetik: "Diophantus hab ausser seincm grossen arith- metischen Werke aucb ein Werk iiber die praktiscbe Arithmetik gescbriebcn, das aber verloren ist." To begin with, Montucla quotes the passage as occurring in the 5th Book of Theon's Commentary, instead of the first. The work of Diophantos which Theon quotes is not another work, but is identically the Arithmeticn vihich wo possess. ^ Qiuv 6 iK Tov ^lovjelov, Alyvirrioi, (pi\6(TO<f>oi, Ji'yxP°^°^ ^^ UdTririft ri^ <pi\oc6^ Kal avrc^ 'AXe^avdper irOyxavov di an<por{poi iirl Qfodoaiov fiaffi\^ws tov Tfxff^vri- poV iypafe 'MaOTj/xariKd, ' ApiO/xrjTtKo, k. t. \. 12 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. certainly incorrect .and due to a confusion on the part of Suidas, for Pappos probably flourished under Diocletian (a. D, 284 — 305) ; but the date of a certain Commentary of Theon has been definitely determined' as the year 372 A. D. and he undoubtedly flourished, as Suidas says, in the reign of Theodosius I. (379 — 395 A. D.). (4) The next authority who must be mentioned is the Arabian historian Abu'lfaraj, who places Diophantos without remark under the emperor Julian. This statement is important in that it gives the date which has been the most generally ac- cepted. The passage in Abu'lfaraj comes after an enumeration of distinguished men who lived in the reign of Julian, and is thus translated by Pococke : "Ex iis Diophantes, cuius liber A. B. quem Algebram vocat Celebris est." It is a difiicult question to decide how much weight is to be allowed to Abu'lfaraj's dogmatic statement. Some great autho- rities have unequivocally pronounced it to be valueless. Cossali attributes it to a confusion by Abu'lfaraj of our author with another Diophantos, a rhetorician, who is mentioned in another article'^ of Suidas as having been contemporary with the em- peror Julian (361 — 363); and assumes that Abu'lfaraj made the statement solely on the authority of Suidas, and confused two persons of the same name. Cossali remarks at the same time upon a statement of Abu'lfaraj's translator, Pococke, to the effect that the Arabian historian did not know Greek and Latin. Colebrooke too' {Algebra of the Hindus) takes the same view. Ncnv it certainly seems curious that Cossali should remark upon Abu'lfaraj's ignorance of Greek and yet suppose that he made a statement merely upon the authority of Suidas ; and the ques- tion suggests itself: had Abu'lfaraj no other authority? We 1 "On the date of Pappus," Ac., by Hermann Usener, Neues Rheinisches Museum, 1873, Bd. xxviii. 403. * Ai^dvios, (TO(piaTr)i AvTioxf'y. twv ivl toO 'lovXiavov toO Uapa^aTov xp<5»'w»'. Kal fJi^XP^ Qeo5offlov tov vpea^vripov, '^aayaviov Trarpoj, fiadrjrr]^ Aio(pdin-ov. * Note M. p. LXiii. "The Armenian Abu'lfaraj places the Algebraist Dio- phantus under the emperor Julian. Ihit it may be (luestioned whether he ha8 any authority for that date, besides the mention by Greek authors of a learned person of ihc name, the instructor of Libanius, who was contemporary with tht^t pmperor," HISTORICAL INTR()incTR)X. l.S must certainly, as was remarked by Schulz, admit that he must have had ; for he gives yet another statement about Diophaiitos, which certainly comes from another source, that his work was translated into Arabic, or commented upon, by Mohanuiicd Abu'1-Wafa. There would seem however to be but one possibility which would make Abu'lfaraj's statement trustworthy. Is it possible that the two persons, whom he is supposed to have confused, are identical ? Is it a sufficient objection that Liba- nius distinguished himself chiefly as a rhetor and not as a mathematician ? In fact, in the absence of any evidence to the contrary, why should the arithmetician Diophantos not have been a rhetorician also ? This question has given occasion to some jests on the compatibility of the two accomplishments. M. Tannery, for example, quotes Fermat, who was " Conseiller de Toulouse " ; and Nesselmann mentions Aristotle, arriving finally at the conclusion that the two may be identical, and so, while Abu'lfaraj's statement has nothing against it, it has a great deal in its favour. But M. Tannery thinks he has made the identification impossible by finding Suidas' authority, namely Eunapios in the Lives of the Sophists, who mentions this other Diophantos as an Arabian, not an Alexandrian, and professing at Athens \ Certainly if this supposition is correct, we cannot identify the two persons, and therefore cannot trust the state- ment of Abu'lfaraj. There is a further consideration — that the reign of Julian (361 — 363) could certainly only have been the end of Diophantos' life, as we see by comparing Theon's date, above mentioned, to whom Diophantos is certainly anterior; he may indeed have been much earlier, because (1) Theon quotes him as a classic, and (2) the absence of quotations before Theon does not necessarily show that the two were nearly contemporary, for of previous writers to Theon who would have been likely to quote Diophantos ? (5) In the preface to his Algebra, published A.D. 1572, Rafael Bombclli gives the bare statement that Diophantos lived ^ "II uous donne ce Diophante, qu'il a connu et dont il ne fait d'ailleure pas grand cas, comme nO, non pas a, Alexandrie, ainsi que le matht-maticien, mais en Arable (AiocpavTos 6 'Apd^ios), et, d'autre part, conime prolessant A Athenes." 14 DIOPIIANTOH OF ALEXANDRIA. in the reign of Antoninus Pins', giving no proof or evidence of it. From the demonstrated incorrectness of certain other state- ments of Bombelli concerning Diophantos we may infer that we ought not hastily to give credence to this ; on the other hand it is scarcely conceivable that he would have made the assertion without any ground whatever. The question accordingly arises, whether we can find any statement by an earlier writer, which might have been the origin of Bombelli 's assertion. M. Tannery thinks he has found the authority while engaged in another research into the evidence on which Peter Ramus ascribes to Diophantos a treatise on Harmonics '^ an assertion repeated by Gessner and Fabricius^. As I cannot follow M. Tannery in his conjectures — for they are nothing better, but are rather con- jectures of the wildest kind, — I will give the substance of his remarks without much comment, to be taken for what they are worth. According to M. Tannery Ramus' source of information was a Greek manuscript on music ; this there is no reason to doubt; and in the edition of Antiquae musicae auctores by Meibomius we read, in the treatise by Bacchios 6 <yepo)v, that there were five definitions of rhjjthm, attributed to Phaidros, Aristoxenos, Nikomachos, Ae6(f)avT0<; and Didymos. Now the name Aed<^ai/T09 is not Greek; the form Aea)(f)avTo<; however is, but M. Tannery argues that a confusion between Aeo and Atw is much less likely than a confusion between Aco and Aio. (I may be allowed to remark here that I cannot agree with this view. Of course A and A are extremely likely to be confounded, but that I should have been at the same tmie changed into € seems to me anything but probable. Besides, this involves two changes, whereas the change of Ae« into Aeo involves only one variation. This latter change then is the smaller one, and why should it 1 "Qucsti aniii passati, csscndosi ritrouato una opera greca di qucsta dis- ciplina nclla libraria di Nostra Siguore in Vaticano, coniposta da un certo Diofantc Alessandrino Autor Greco, il quale fh a tempo di Antonin Pio..." [I quote from the edition published in 1579, which is in the British Museum. I have not seen the original edition of 1572.] 2 "Scripserat et Diophantus harmonica." =* "Harmonica Diophanti, quae (icsiwrus et alii memorant, iuteUige de har- monicis numcris, uou dc scripto quoJam musici argumeuti," though what is meant by "harmonic numbers," as Nessclmann remarks, is not quite clear. HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION'. lo be less likely than the other ? I confess that it seems to mc hy far the more likely of the two ; for the long ami short vowx-ls o, M must have been closely associated, as is proved by the fact that in ancient inscriptions^ we find O written for both O and il indiscriminately, and in others H used for both sounds.) Tlicii, according to M. Tannery, Ramus probably took the name for Ai6(f)avTo<;, and was followed by other writers. Admitting that the identification with the arithmetician Diophantos is hypo- thetical enough, M. Tannery goes on to say that it is confirmed by finding the name of Nikomachos next to Ae6(f)avTo<i, and by observing that Euclid and Ptolemy also were writers on music, which formed part of the fiadrjixara. Now in enumerations of this sort the chronological order is generally followed, and the dates of many authors have been decided on grounds no more certain than this. (It is an obvious remark to make to M. Tannery that " two wrongs do not make a right " : it does not follow that, because other dates have been decided on insufficient grounds, we should determine Diophantos' date in the same manner ; wKfiught rather to take warning by such unsatisfactory determinations. But to proceed with M. Tannery's remarks) — In the present case we know that Aristoxenos was a disciple of Aristotle, and that Nikomachos was posterior to Thrasyllos who lived in the reign of Tiberius. Thus we can prove the chrono- logical order for two of the five names. Again, Nikomachos must be anterior to his commentator Apuleius who was con- temporary with Ptolemy, and Ptolemy speaks in his Harmonics of a tetrachord due to a neo-Pythagorean Didymos. Of Phaidros we know nothing. Hence if we admit that the names are given in chronological order, and remember that Diophantos lived to be 84 years of age, we might say that, coming between Niko- machos and Didymos, he lived in the reign of Antoninus Pius, as Bombelli states, i.e. 138 — IGl A.D. M. Tannery, however, is conscious of certain objections to this theory of Diophantos' date. This determination would, he says, have great weight if Bacchios 6 '^epoiv had been an author ' I mean, of course, inscrr. later than the introduction of Q, before which time one sign was necessarily used for both letters. Further, I lay no strcBH upon this fact except as an illustration. 16 DIOPHANTOS OV ALEXANDRIA. sufficiently near in point of" time to Diophantos and the rest in order to know their respective ages. Unfortuoately, however, that is far from certain, Bacchios' own date being very doubtful. He is generally supposed to have lived in the time of Constantine the Great ; this is however questioned by M. Tannery who thinks that the epigram given by Meibomius, in which Bacchios is associated with a certain Dionysios, refers to Constantine Porphyrogenetes, who belongs to the sixth century. Next, grave doubts may be raised concerning the determination by means of the supposed chronological order; for the definitions of rhythm given by Nikomachos and Diophantos (?) are very nearly alike, that of Diophantos being apparently a development of that of Nikomachos : kutu 8e NiKOfia^ov, '^povcou evTUKTO'i avvd€<TC<i' Kara 8e Ai6(f)avTov (?), -^povcov avvdeai<; kut dvaXo'^iav re Kol (TVfifierplav irpo'i eavTov<;. The similarity of the two definitions might itself account for their juxta-position, which might then after all be an inversion of chronological order. Again the age of Didymos must be fixed differently. By " Didymos " is meant the son of Herakleides Ponticus, gramma- rian and musician, whom Suidas places in the reign of Nero. Thus, if we assume Bacchios' order to be chronological, we must place Diophantos in the reign of Claudius, and Nikomachos in that of Caligula. § 3. Results of the preceding investigation. I have now reviewed all the evidence we have respecting the time at which Diophantos lived and wrote, and the conclusions arrived at, on the basis of this evidence, by the greatest autho- rities upon the subject. It must be admitted the result cannot be called in any sense satisfactory ; indeed the data arc not sufficient to determine indisputably the question at issue. The latest determination of Diophantos' date is that of M. Tannery, and there has been no theory propounded which seems on the whole preferable to his, though oven it cannot be said to have been positively established ; it has, however, the merit that, if it cannot be proved, it cannot be impugned ; as therefore it seems HISTORICAL INTROnrcTION. 17 open to no objection, it would seem best to accept it provisionally, as the least uusatistactory theory. We shall therefore be not improbably right in placing Diophantos in the second half of the third century of our era, making him thus a contemporary of Pappos, and anterior by a century to Theon of Alexandria and his daughter Hypatia, One thing is quite certain: that Diophantos lived in a period when the Greek mathematicians of great original power had been succeeded by a number of learned commentators, who confined their investigations within the limits already reached, without attempting to further the development of the science. To this general rule there are two most striking exceptions, in different branches of mathematics, Diophantos and Pappos. These two mathematicians, who would have been an ornament to any age, were destined by fate to live and labour at a time when their work could not check the decay of mathematical learning. There is scarcely a passage in any Greek writer where either of the two is so much as mentioned. The neglect of their works by their countrymen and contemporaries can be explained only by the fact that they were not appreciated or understood. The reason why Diophantos was the earliest of the Greek mathematicians to be forgotten is also probably the reason why he was the last to be re-discovered after the Revival of Learning. The oblivion, in fact, into which his writings and methods fell is due to the circumstance that they were not understood. That being so, we are able to understand why there is so much obscurity concerning his personality and the time at which he lived. Indeed, Avhen we consider how little he was understood, and in consequence how little esteemed, we can only congratulate ourselves that so much of his work has survived to the present day. CHAPTER II. THE WORKS OF DIOPHANTOS ; THEIR TITLES AND GENERAL CONTENTS; THE PORTIONS OF THEM WHICH SURVIVE. § 1. We know of three works of Diophantos, which bear the following titles. (1) Wpi6fxr]TtKci}v /Si/SXia ly. (2) Trep] TToXvyoovcov apidfioov. (3) TropiafMara. With respect to tlie first title we may observe that the meaning of "dpid/jbrjTiKa' is slightly different from that assigned to it by more ancient writers. The ancients drew a marked distinction between dpidfiijTiKT] and \ 0740- rt/c?;, both of which were concerned with numbers. Thus Plato in Gorgias 451 B* states that dpidfirjrtKy'] is concerned with the abstract properties of numbers, odd even, and so on, whereas XoytaTCKij deals with the same odd and even, but in relation to one anotlier. Geminos also gives us definitions of the two terms. According to him dpidfxrjTLKij deals with abstract properties of numbers, while XoyiariKi] gives solutions of problems about concrete numbers. From Geminos we see that enunciations were in ancient times concrete in such problems. But in Diophantos the calculations ' £1 tIs fjie fpoiTo..!'(l SwAcpares, tL^ eariv rj dptOfirjTiKr] t^x*''?> cI'toim' S** avTip, tSairep <ri> dpri, 6ti twv 5id \6you tis t6 Kvpoi ixovauv. Kal et /xe iwavip- ono Twf TTipl tL ; etiroifi' Av, 6ti twv vtpl rb Apribv tc koI irtpiTTov Sj dp (Kdrepa Ti^yx'**'^' ^"'■a- «' 5' av fpoiTO, Trjv 5^ XoyiariKriv rlva KoKds rix^riv ; ilvoiix &v 6ti Kal ai>T7) iarl tCiv \6yifi t6 trdv Kvpovp-ivuv. Kal el IwavipoiTo 'H iTfpl tI ; etiToifJ.^ hv wainp o\ iv rc^ StJ^v <iv-f^pa.<^6iXivoi, Sri ra fikv &\\a KaOdwep rj dpiOixrjTiKTi T} XoyuTTiKT] ^X"' ""fpi TO avTO yap icTL, to re dpTiov Kal to irepiTToV diatpitid Sk ToaovTov, oti Kal tt/jos aina Kal Trpos aX\i)\a ttuis ?x** irXridovi iiriffKOirei TO TTCpiTTOV Kal TO df>Tl0V 7] XoyKTTlKrj. (.tOnjlUg, 451 B,C. HIS WORKS. 10 take an abstract form, so that the distinction between XoyiaTiKij and apidfjiriTLKr] is lost. We thus have W.pid/xr}TiKd given as the title of his work, whereas in earlier times the term could only properly have been applied to his treatise on Polygonal Numbers. This broader use by Diophantos of the term arith- metic is not without its importance. Having made this preliminary remark it is next necessary to observe that of these works which we have mentioned some have been lost, while probably the form of parts of others has suffered considerably by the ravages of time. The Arithmetics should, according to the title and a distinct statement in the introduction to it, contain thirteen Books. But all the six known MSS.^ contain only six books, with the sole variation that in the Vatican MS. 200 the same text, which in the rest forms six books, is divided into seveii. Not only do the MSS. practically agree in the external division of the work ; they agree also in an equally remarkable manner — at least all of them which have up to the present been collated — in the lacunae and the mistakes which occur in the text. So much is this the case that Bachet, the sole editor of the Greek text of Diophantos, asserts his belief that they are all copied from one original ^ This can, however, scarcely be said to be established, ^ The six mss. are : 1—3. Vatican mss. No. 191, xiii. c, cbarta bombycina. No. 200, XIV. c, charta pergamena. No. 304, XV. c, charta. 4. MS. in Nat. Library at Paris, that used by Bachet for his text. 5. MS. in Palatine Library, collated for Bachet by Claudius Salmasius. 6. Xylander's ms. which belonged to Andreas Dudicius. Colebrooke considers that 5 and 6 are probably identical. - "Etenim neque codex Eegius, cuius ope banc editionem adornavimus; neque is quern prae manibus habuit Xilander; neque Palatinus, vt doctissimo viro ClauLlio Salmasio refcrente accepimus ; neque Vaticanus, quern vir suniniua lacobus Sirmondus mihi ex parte transcribendum curauit, quicquam amplius continent, quam sex hosce Arithmcticorum libros, et tractatum de iiumeris multangulis imperfectum. Sed et tarn infeUcitcr hi omnes codices inter ae consentiunt, vt ab vno fonte manasse et ab eodem exemplari dcscriptos fuisso non dubitem. Itaque parum auxilij ab his subministratum nobis esse, veris- simu allirmare possum," Epintola ad Lectorem. It will be seen that the learned Bachet spells here, as everywhere, Xylander's name wrongly, giving it as Xilander. O 9 20 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. for Bachet had no knowledge of two of the three Vatican MSS. and had only a few readings of the third, furnished to him by Jacobus Sirmondus. It is possible therefore that the collation of the two remaining mss. in the Vatican might even now lead to important results respecting the settling of the text. The evidence of the existence in earlier times of all the thirteen books is very doubtful, some of it absolutely incorrect. Bachet says * that Joannes Regiomontanus asserts that he saw the thirteen books somewhere, and that Cardinal Perron, who had recently died, had often told him that he possessed a MS. containing the thirteen books complete, but, having lent it to a fellow-citizen, who died before returning it, had never re- covered it. Respecting this latter MS. mentioned by Bachet we have not sufficient data to lead us to a definite conclusion as to whether it really corresponded to the title, or, like the MSS. which we knoAv, only announced thirteen books. If it really corresponded to the title, it is remarkable how (in the words of Nesselmann) every possible unfortunate circumstance and even the " pestis " mentioned by Bachet seem to have conspired to rob posterity of at least a part of Diophantos' works. Respecting the statement that Regiomontanus asserts that he saw a MS. containing the thirteen books, it is clear that it is founded on a misunderstanding. Xylander states in two passages of his preface " that he found that Regiomontanus 1 "loannes tamen Regiomontanus tredecini Diophanti libros se alicubi vidisse asseverat, et illustrissimus Cardinalis Perronius, quern nupei- ex- tinctum niagno Christianae et literariae Rcipublicae detrimeuto, conquerimur, mihi saepe testatus est, se codicem manuscriptum habuisse, qui tredeeim Dio- phanti libros integros contineret, quern cilm Gulielmo Gosselino conciui suo, qui in Diophantum Commentaiia meditabatur, perhumauiter more suo exhi- buisset, pauUo post accidit, ut Gossclinus peste correptus iuteriret, et Diophanti codex codem fato nobis criperetur. Cum enim prccibus meis motus Cardi- nalis amplissimus, nullisque sumptibus pai-cens, apud heredes Gosselini codicem ilium diligenter exquiri mandassct, et quouis pretio redimi, nusquam repertus est." Ad lectorcm. ■•* "Inueni deinde tanquam exstantis in bibliothecis Italicis, sibique uisi mentionem a Regiomontano (cuius etiam nominis memoriam ueneror) factam." Xylander, Epistola nuncupatoria. "Sane tredeeim libri Arithmeticae Diophanti ab aliis perhibentur exstare in bibliotheca Vaticana; quos Regiomontanus illo uiderit." Ibid. HIS WORKS. 21 mentioned a MS. of Diophantos which he liad seen in an Italian library; and that others said that the thirteen books were extant in the Vatican Library, " which Regiomontanus saw." Now as regards the latter statement, Xylander was obviously wrongly informed ; for not one of the Vatican Mss. contains the thirteen books. It is necessary therefore to inquire to what passage or passages in Regiomontanus' writings Xylander refers. Nesselmann finds only one place which can be meant, an Oratio habita Patavii in praelectione Alfragani^ in which Regiomon- tanus remarks that " no one has yet translated from the Greek into Latin the thirteen books of Diophantosl" Upon this Nesselmann observes that, even if Regiomontanus saw a MS., it does not follow that it had the thirteen books, except on the title-page ; and the remarks which Regiomontanus makes upon the contents show that he had not studied them thoroughly ; but it is not usually easy to see, by a superficial examination, into how many sections a Ms. is divided. However,- this passage is interesting as being the first mention of Diophantos by a European writer; the date of the Speech was probably about 1462. The only other passage, which Nesselmann was acquaint- ed with and might have formed some foundation for Xylatider's conclusion, is one in which Regiomontamis (in the same Oratio) describes a journey which he made to Italy for the purpose of learning Greek, with the particular (though not exclusive) 1 Printed in the work Eudimenta astronomica Alfrarfani. "Item Alba- tegnius astronomus peritissimus de motu stellarum, ex observationibus turn propriis turn Ptolemaei, omnia cum demonstrationibus Geometricis et Addi- tionibus Joannis de Eegiomonte. Item Oratio introductoria in omnen scientias Mathematicas Joannis de Reijiomonte, Patavii habita, cum Alfraganum pnblice praelegeret. Ejusdem utilissima introductio in elementa Euclidis. Item Epis- tola Philippi Melanthonis nuncupatoria, ad Senatum Noribergensem. Omnia jam recens prelis publicata. Norimbergae anno 1537. 4to." - The passage is: "Diofanti autem tredecim libros subtilissimos nemo osqne- hac ex Graecis Latinos fecit, in quibus flos ipse totius Arithmeticae latet, are videlicet rei et census, quam hodie vocant Algebram Arabico nomine." It does not follow from this, as Vossius maintains, that Kegiomontanus sup- posed Dioph. to be the inventor of algebra. The "ars rei et census," which is the solution of determinate quadratic equations, is not found in our Dioph. ; and even supposing that it was given in the MS. which liegiomontanus saw, this is not a point which would des4.•r^•o special mention. 22 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. object of turning into Latin certain Greek mathematical works\ But Diopliantos is not mentioned by name, and Nesselmann accordingly thinks that it is a mere conjecture on the part of Cossali and Xylander, that among tlie Greek writers mentioned in this passage Diophantos was included ; and that we have no ground for thinking, on the authority of these passages, that Regiomontanus saw the thirteen books in a complete form. But Nesselmann does not seem to have known of a passage in another place, which is later than the Oration at Padua, and shows to my mind most clearly that Regiomontanus never saw the complete work. It is in a letter to Joannes de Blan- chinis^ in which Regiomontanus states that he found at Venice " Diofantus," a Greek arithmetician who had not yet been translated into Latin ; that in the proemium he defined the several powers up to the sixth, but whether he followed out all the combinations of these Regiomontanus does not know ; '^ for not more than six books are found, though in the proemium he promises thirteen. If this book, a wonderful and difficult luork, could be found entire, I should like to translate it into Latin, for the knowledge of Greek I have lately acquired would suffice for thisV' &c. The date of this occurrence is stated 1 After the death of his teacher, Georg von Peurbach, he tells us he went to Eome &c. with Cardinal Bessaiion. "Quid igitur rehquum crat nisi ut orbitam viri clarissimi sectarer? coeptum felix tuum pro viribus exequerer? Duce itaquo patrono communi Romam profectus more meo Uteris exerceor, ubi scripta plurima Graecorum clarissimorum ad literas suas disceudas me invitant, quo Latinitas in studiis praesertim Mathematicis locupletior redderetur." Peurbach died 8 April, llGl, so that tlie journey must have taken place between 1-lGl and 1171, when he permanently took up his residence at Niim- berg. During this time he visited in order Eome, Ferrara, Padua (where he delivered the Oration), Venice, Rome (a second time) and Vienna. 2 Given on p. 135 of Ch. Th. v. Murr's Memorabilia, Norimbergae, 1786, and partly in Doppelmayr, Ilistorischc Nachricht von der Kiirnbergischen Mathe- vuiticis uml Kiimtlcrn, p. 5. Note y (Niiruberg, 1730). 3 The whole passage is : " Hoc dico dominationi uestrae me reperisse nunc uenetiis Diofantum aritli- meticum graecum nondum in latinum traductura. Hie in prohemio diiliniendo terminos huius artis ascendit ad cubum cubi, primura cnim uocat uumcrum, quern numeri uocant rem, secundum uocat potentiam, ubi uumeri dieunt censum, deinde cubum, deinde potentiam poteutiae, uocant numerum censum de ceusu, item cubum de ccusu ct taudom cubi. Ncscio tamen si oumes com- HIS WORKS. 2li in a note to be 1463. Here then we have a distinct contradicti-.u to the statement that Regiomontanus speaks of having si-eu tliir- teen books ; so that Xylander's conchisions must be abandoned. No conclusion can be arrived at from the passage in F'ermat's letter to Digby (15 August 1G57) in which he says: The nanu' of this author (Diophantos) " me donne I'occasion de vous faire souvenir de la promesse, qu'il vous a pleu me faire de recouvrer quelque manuscrit de c^t Autheur, qui contienne tous les treize livres, et de m'en faire part, s'il vous pent tomber en main." This is clearly no evidence that a complete Diophantos existed at the time. Bombelli (1572) states the number of books to be seven\ showing that the MS. he used was Vatican No. 200. To go farther back still in time, Maximus Planudcs, who lived in the time of the Byzantine Emperors Andronicus I. and II. in the first half of the 14th century, and wrote Scholia to the two first books of the Arithmetics, given in Latin in Xylander's translation of Diophantos, knew the work in the same form in which we have it, so far as the first two books are concerned. From these facts Nesselmann concludes that the corruptions and lacunae in the text, as we have it, are due to a period anterior to the 14th or even the 13th century. There are yet other means by which lost portions of Diophan- tos might have been preserved, though not found in the original text as it has come down to us. We owe the recovery of some Greek mathematical works to the finding of Arabic translations of them, as for inststnce parts of Apollonios. Now we know binationes horum proseeutus fuerit. non enim reperiuntur nisi 6 eius libri qui nunc apud me sunt, in prohemio autem pollicetur se scripturum tredecim. Si liber hie qui reuera pulcerrimus est et diflicilimus, integer inueniretur [Doppel- mayr, inueHi'atur] curarem eum latiuum facere, ad hoc enim sufficereut mihi literae graecae quas in domo domini mei reuerendissimi didici. Curate et uos obsecro si apud uestros usquam inueniri possit liber ille integer, sunt enim in urbe uestra non nulli graecarum litterarum periti, quibus solent inter caetoros tuae facuitatis libros huiusmodi occurrere. Interim tamen, si suadebitis. Hex dictos libros traducere in latinum occipiam, quatenus latinitas hoc nouo et pretiosissimo munere non careat. " 1 "Egli e io, per arrichire il mondo di cosi fatta opera, ci dessimo i\ tradurlo e cinque libri {delU settc che sotio) tradutti ue abbiamo." Bombelli, pref. to Algebra. 24 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. that Diophantos was translated into Arabic, or at least studied and commented upon in Arabia. Why then should we not be as fortunate in respect of Diophantos as with others ? In the second part of a work by Alkarkhi called the Fakhrl^ (an algebraic treatise) is a collection of problems in deter- minate and indeterminate analysis which not only indicate that their author had deeply studied Diophantos, but are, many of them, directly taken from the Arithmetics with the change, occasionally, of some of the constants. The obliga- tions of Alkarkhi to Diophantos are discussed by Wopcke in his Notice sur le Fakhrl. In a marginal note to his MS. is a remark attributing the problems of section iv. and of section III. in part to Diophantos^. Now section IV. begins with pro- blems corresponding to the last 14 of Diophantos' Second Book, and ends with an exact reproduction of Book ill. Intervening between these two parts are twenty-five problems which are not found in our Diophantos. We might suppose then that we have here a lost Book of our author, and Wopcke says that he was so struck by the gloss in the MS, that he hoped he had dis- covered such a Book, but afterwards abandoned the idea for the reasons : (1) That the first twelve of the problems depend upon equations of the first or second degree which lead, with two exceptions, to irrational results, whereas such were not allowed by Diophantos. (2) The thirteen other problems which are indeterminate problems of the second degree are, some of them, quite unlike Diophantos ; others have remarks upon methods employed, and references to the author's commentaries, which we should not expect to find if the problems were taken from Diophantos. It does not seem possible, then, to identify any part of 1 The book which I have made use of on this subject is: "Extrait dn Fakhrl, traits d' Algl'bre par Abou liekr Mohammed ben Alhavan Alkarkhi (mauuscrit 1)52, supplement arabe de la bibliothequc Imperiale) pr^ced6 d'un m<?moire sur I'Algebre ind<5termiiiee chez les Arabes, par F. Woepckc, Paris, 1858." 2 Wopcke's translation of this gloss is: "J'ai vu en cet endroit une glose de I'dcriture d'Ibn Alsir&dj en ces termes : Je dis, les probli'mes de cette section et une partie de ceux de la section pr^c(5dente, scut pris dans les livres de Dio- phante, suivunt I'ordre. Ceci fut 6crit par Ahmed IJen Abi 13eqr Ben Ali Ben Alsiiiulj Alkclaueci." HIS WORKS. 2.'> the Fakhrl as having formed a part of Diophantos' work now lost. Thus it seems probable to suppose that the form in which Alkarkhi found and studied Diophantos was not different from the present. This view is very strongly supported by the follow- ing evidence. Bachet has already noticed tliat the solution of Dioph. II. 19 is really only another solution of ii. 18, and does not agree with its own enunciation. Now in the Faklu^l we have a problem (iv. 40) with the same enunciation as Dioph. II. 19, but a solution which is not in Diophantos' manner. It is remarkable to find this followed by a problem (iv, 41) which is the same as Dioph. ii. 20 (choice of constants always excepted). It is then sufficiently probable that il. 19 and 20 followed each other in the redaction of Diophantos known to Alkarkhi ; and the fact that he gives a non-Diophantine solution of II. 19 would show that he had observed that the enunciation and solution did not correspond, and therefore set himself to work out a solution of his own. In view of this evidence we may probably assume that Diophantos' work had already taken its present mutilated form when it came into the hands of the author of the Fakhrl. This work was written by Abu Bekr Mohammed ibu Alhasan Alkarkhi near the beginning of the 11th century of our era ; so that the cor- ruption of the text of Diophantos must have taken place before the 11th century. There is yet another Arabic work even earlier than this last, apparently lost, the discovery of which would be of the greatest historical interest and importance. It is a work upon Diophantos, consisting of a translation or a commentary by Mo- hammed Abu'1-Wafa, already mentioned incidentally. But it is doubtful whether the discovery of his work entire would enable us to restore any of the lost parts of Diophantos. There is no evidence to lead us to suppose so, but there is a piece of evidence noted by Wopcke* which may possibly lead to an opposite conclusion. Abu'1-Wafa does not satisfactorily deal with the possible division of any number whatever into four squares. Now the theorem of the possibility of such divi.siou 1 Journal Asiatique. Ciuqui^me s^rie, Tome v. p. 231. 2b DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. is assumed by Diophantos in several places, notably in iv. 31. We have then two alternatives. Either (1) the theorem was not distinctly enunciated by Diophantos at all, or (2) It was enunciated in a proposition of a lost Book. In either case Abu'1-Wafa cannot have seen the statement of the theorem ia Diophantos, and, if the latter alternative is right, we have an argument in favour of the view that the work had already been, mutilated before it reached the hands of Abu'1-Wafa. Now Abu'l-Wafa's date is 328—388 of the Hegira, or 940—988 of our Era. It would seem, therefore, clear that the parts of Diophantos' Arithmetics which are lost were lost at an early date, and that the present lacunae and imperfections in the text had their origin in all probability before the 10th century. It may be said also with the same amount of probability that the Porisms were lost before the 10th century a.d. We have perhaps an indication of this in the title of another work of Abu'1-Wafa, of which Wopcke's translation is " Demonstra- tions des thdoremes employes par Diophante dans son ouvrage, et de ceux employes par (Aboul-Wafa) lui-meme dans son com- mentaire." It is not possible to conclude with certainty from the title of this work what its contents may have been. Are the " theorems " those which Diophantos assumes, referring for proofs of them to his Porisms ? This seems a not unlikely sup- position ; and, if it is correct, it would follow that the proofs of these propositions, which Diophantos must have himself given, in fact, the Porisms, were no longer in existence in the time of Abu'I-Wafa, or at least were lor him as good as lost. It must be admitted then that we have no historical evidence of the existence at any time subsequent to Diophantos himself of the Porisms. Of the treatise on Polygonal Numhers we possess only a fragment. It breaks off' in the middle of the 8th proposition. It is not however probable that much is wanting; practically the treatise seems to be nearly complete. § 2. The next (juestion which naturally suggests itself is : As we have apparently six books only of the Arithmetics out of thirteen, where may we suppose the lost matter to have been HIS WORKS. 27 placed in the treatise? Was it at tlie beginning, micUHe, or end? This question can only be decided when we have come to a conclusion about the probable contents of the lost p<jrtion. It has, however, been dogmatically asserted by many who have written upon Diophantos — often without reading him at all, or reading him enough to enable them to form a judgment on the subject — that the Books, which we have, are the Jirst 9ix and that the loss has been at the end; and such have accordingly wondered what could have been the subject to which Diophantos afterwards proceeded. To this view, which has no ground save in the bare assertions of incompetent or negligent writers, Nesselmann opposes himself very strongly. He maintains on the contrary, with much reason, that in the sixth Book Diophantos' resources are at an end. If one reads carefully the last four Books, from the third to the sixth, the conclusion forces itself upon one that Diophantos moves in a rigidly defined and limited circle of methods and artifices, that any attempts which he makes to free himself are futile. But this fact can onl}^ be adequately appreciated after a perusal of his entire work. It may, however, be further added that the sixth Book forms a natural conclusion to the whole, in that it is made up of exemplifications of methods explained and used in the pre- ceding Books. The subject is the finding of right-angled triangles in rational numbers, such that the sides satisfy given conditions, Arithmetic being applied to Geometry in the geo- metrical notion of the right-angled triangle. As was said above, we have now to consider Avhat the contents of the lost Books of the Arithmetics may have been. Clearly we must first inquire what is actually wanting which we should have expected to find there, either as promised by the author himself in his own work, or as necessary for the elucidation or completion of the whole. We must therefore briefly indicate the general contents of the work as we have it. The first book contains problems leading to determinate equations of the first degree'; the remainder of the work being 1 As a specimen of the rash way in which even good writers speak of Dio- phantos, I may instance here a remark of Viucenzo Riccati, who says: "De problematibus determiuatis quae rcsulutis aequatiouibus dignoscuutur, nilill 28 DIOPH.\^TOS OF ALEXANDRIA. a collection of problems which, with scarcely an exception, lead to indeterminate equations of the second degree, beginning with simpler cases and advancing step by step to more complicated questions. These indeterminate or semideterminate problems form the main feature of the collection. Now it is a great step from determinate equations of the first degree to semideter- minate and indeterminate problems of the second; and we must recognise that there is here an enormous gap in the exposition. We ought surely to find here (1) determinate equations of the second degree and (2) indeterminate equations of the first. With regard to (2), it is quite true that we have no definite statement in the work itself that they formed part of the writer's plan; but that they were discussed here is an extremely probable supposition. With regard to (1) or determinate quadratic equations, on the other hand, we have certain evidence from the writer's own words, that the solution of the adfected or complete quadratic was given in the treatise as it originally stood ; for, in the first place, Diophantos promises a discussion of them in the introductory definitions (def. 11) where he gives rules for the reduction of equations of the second degree to their simplest forms; secondly, he uses his method for their solution in the later Books, in some cases simply giving the result of the solution without working it out, in others giving the irrational part of the root in order to find an approximate value in integers, without writing down the actual root\ We find examples of pure quadratic equations oninino Diophantus (!); agit duntaxat de eo problematum semidetenninatorum genere, quae respiciimt quadrata, aut cubos numerorum, quae problemata ut resolvantur, (juantitates radicales de industria sunt vitandae." Pref. to ana- litiche istituzioni. ^ These being tbe indications in the work itself, what are we to think of a recent writer of a History of Mathematics, who says: "Hieraus und aus dem Umstand, dass Diophant nirgends die von ihm versprochene Theorie dcr Auflosung der quadratiscben Gleichungen gibt, schloss man, er habe dieselbe nicht gekannt, und bat desshalb den Arabern stets den Ruhm dieser ErtinJuug zugctlieilt," and goes on to say that "nevertheless Nesselmann after a thorough study of the work is convinced that D. knew the solution of the quadratic"? It is almost impossible to imagine that these remarks are serious. The writer is Dr Heinricli Suter, (Jcschichte d. Mathetmitischen WissemchaJ'ten. Zweite Autliigf. Ziiricb, 1873. HIS Wol^KS. 29 even in the first Book : a fact which shows that Diophantos regarded them as in reality simple equations, taking, as he does, the positive value of the root only. Indeed it would seem that Diophantos adopted as his ground for the classification of these equations, not the index of the highest power of the unknown quantity contained in it, but the number of terms left in it when it is reduced to its simplest form. His words are': "If the same powers of the unknown occur on both sides but with different coefficients we must take like from like until we have one single expression equal to another. If there are on both sides, or on either side, terms with negative coefficients, the defects must be added on both sides, until there are the same powers on both sides with positive coefficients, when we must take like from like as before. We must contrive always, if possible, to reduce our equations so that they may contain one single term equated to one other. But afterwards we will explain to you also hoiu, luhen two terms are left equal to a - Diophantos' actual words (which I have trauslated freely) are: MtrA 5^ Tavra eav d-rrb irpo^Xr^^iaTos tlvos -yh-qrai virap^ii eldeffi rots avroh jurj ofioTrXTjBfj 5^ dirb eKar^puv twv fiepuiv, deriaa a.<paipe'it> to. ofxoia dir6 twu 6/xoiwv, ?a)S &v ^»'ds(!) elSoj €pI eidei tjov -yiv-qTaf eav de ttws if OTror^pu} ivvirapxTJ^^), ^ ^v dfKporipois iveWei^f/r] (?) rivk etSr), de-qaei irpoaBelvaL to, Xeivovra etOT) if dfjLcpor^poii roh fxipeaii', ews Slp eKarepij) tQv fxepQiv rd ei5r] ivvirdpxovra. y^vrjTai. Kal TraXi;' a'^e- Xelv Ta 6p.oi.a diro rwc onoiuf, ?ws &v eKarepij) tCiv fxepQ)V if eTooi KaTa\(i<p6rj. ne(pCKoTex''''i)<^6w S^ tovto eu rats vvoffrdaecn twv irpordaiwv, lav eVS^^'n'ot. ?wi hv if eldos €vl etdei tffov KaraKucpdrj. vcrrepov 5^ aoi del^o/xev Kal nUk dvo ddwv tcuv ivi KaraXeKpO^vTUV to toiovtov XvcTai. I give Bachet's text exactly, marking those places where it seems obviously WTong. KCLTaXeL^drj should of course be KaTaXeicpO^. It is worth observing that L. Kodet, in Journal Asiatique, Janvier, 1878, on "L'Algebre d'Al-Ivliarizmi et les muthodes indienne et grecque," quotes this passage, not from Bachet's text, but from the MS. which Bachet used. His readings show the following variations : Bachet. L. Rodet. ■yiv7)Tai yevq(T€TaL [?? How about the construc- tion with idv ?] virap^is Tiva icra if elSos iv X(L\l/ei. ivbs el8os ivtXXeixpri [I doubt the latter word very much, compounded as the verb is with the prep, iu twice repeated.] so DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. third, such a question is solved." That is to say, "reduce when possible the quadratic to one of the forms x = a, or x^ = b. I will give later a method of solution of the complete equation x^±ax=± b." Now this promised solution of the complete quadratic equation is nowhere to be found in the Arithmetics as we have them, though in the second and following Books there are obvious cases of its employment. We have to decide, then, where it might naturally have come; and the answer is that the suitable place is between the first and second Books. But besides the entire loss of an essential portion of Dio- phautos' work there is much confusion in the text even of that portion which remains. Thus clearly problems 6, 7, 18, 19 of the second Book, which contain determinate problems of the first degree, belong in reality to Book I, Again, as already re- marked above, the problem enunciated in ii. 19 is not solved at all, but the solution attached to it is a mere " dXKco^" of ii. 18. Moreover, problems 1 — 5 of Book il. recall problems already solved in i. Thus il. l = l. 34: ii. 2 = 1. 37: ii. 3 is similar to I. 33 : II. 4 = I. 35 : li. 5 = I. 36. The problem i. 29 seems also out of place in its present position. In the second Book a new type of problem is taken up at il. 20, and examples of it are continued through the third Book. There is no sign of a marked division between Books ii. and ill. In fact, expressed in modern notation, the last two problems of li. and the first of III. are the solutions of the following sets of equations : II. 35. x''+[x + y + z) = a^ y^+{x + y + z)=h'' :^ + [x -ir y -\- z) = c" II. 36. x^—{x + y-\-z)= a- \ y--{x + y + z) = lA z" -{x+y + z)=c- ] III. 1. (x + y + z) -.!■' = a" {x + y + z)~y' = U' {x + y + z)-2' = c' These follow perfectly naturally upon each other; and therefore it is quite likely that our division between the two HIS WORKS. 31 Books was not the original one. In fact tlie frequent occur- rence of more definite divisions in tlie middle of the Books, coupled with the variation in the Vatican Ms. which divides our six Books into seven, seems to show that the work may have been divided into even a larger number of Books originally. Besides the displacements of problems which have probably taken place there are many single problems which have been much corrupted, notably the fifth Book, which has, as Nesselmann expresses it\ been "treated by Mother Time in a very step- motherly fashion". It is probable, for instance, that between V. 21 and 22 three problems have been lost. In several other cases the solutions are confused or incomplete. How the im- perfections of the text were introduced into it we can only con- jecture. Nesselmann thinks they cannot be due merely to the carelessness of a copyist, but are rather due, at least in part, to the ignorance and inexpertness of one who wished to improve upon the original. The view, which was put forward by Bachet, that our six Books are a redaction or selection made from the complete thirteen by a later hand, seems certainly untenable. The treatise on Polygonal Numbers is in its subject related ' to the Arithmetics, but the mode of treatment is completely different. It is not an analytical work, but a synthetic one ; the author enunciates propositions and then gives their proofs ; in fact the treatise is quite in the manner of Books vil. — X. of Euclid's elements, the method of representing numbers by geometrical lines being used, which Cossali has called linear Arithmetic. This method of representation is only once used in the Arithmetics proper, namely in the proposition v. 13, where it is used to prove that if a; + 7/=l, and a; and y have to be so determined that aj + 2, ?/ + 6 are both squares, we have to divide the number 9 into two squares of which one must be > 2 and < 3. From the use of this linear method in this one case in the Anthmetics, and commonly in the treatise on Polygonal Numbers, we see that even in the time of Diophantos the geometrical representation of numbers was thought to have the advantage 1 "Namentlich ist in dicser Hinsicht daa fuufte Buch stiefmutterlich von dcr Mutter Zeit behandelt woiden." p. 2GB. 3.2 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. of greater clearness. It need scarcely be remarked how opposed this Greek method is to our modern ones, our tendency being the reverse, viz., to the representation of lines by numbers. The treatise on Polygonal Numbers is often, and probably rightly, held to be one of the thirteen original Books of the Arithmetics. There is absolutely no reason to doubt its genuineness ; which remark would have been unnecessary but for a statement by Bossut to the effect: "II avoit dcrit treize livres d' arithmetiques, les six premiers (?) sont arrives jusqu'a nous : tons les autres sont perdus, si, ndanmoins, un septieme, qu'on trouve dans quelques(!) editions de Diophante, n'estpas de lui"; upon which Reimer has made a note : " This Book on Polygonal Numbers is an independent work and cannot possibly belong to the Collection of Diophantos' Arithmetics^" This statement is totally un- founded. With respect to Bossut's own remark, we have seen that it is almost certain that the Books we possess are not the first six Books ; again, the treatise on Polygonal Numbei's does not only occur in some, but in all of the editions of Diophantos from Xylander to Schulz ; and, lastly, Bossut is the only person who has ever questioned its genuineness. We mentioned above the Porisms of Diophantos. Our knowledge of them is derived from his own words ; in three places in the Arithmetics he refers to them in the words exo/j-ev iv Tot<? iropiaixacnv : the places are V. 3, 5, 19. The references made to them are for proofs of propositions in the Theory of Numbers, which he assumes in these problems as known. It is probable therefore that the Porisms were a collection of propo- sitions concerning the properties of certain numbers, their divisibility into a certain number of squares, and so on ; and it is reasonable to suppose that from them he takes also the many other propositions which he assumes, either explicitly enunciating I them, or implicitly taking them for granted. May we not then reasonably suppose the Porisms to have formed an introduction to the indeterminate and semi-determinate analysis of the second degree which forms the main subject of the A 7'ithmetics? And may we not assume this introduction to have formed an ' "Dieses Buch de numeris multanguUn ist cine fiir sich bestehendc Schrift und gehort keinesweges in die Sammluug der Arithmeticorum Diophant'e." Ills WORKS. 3«? integral part, now lost, of the original thirteen books ? If this supposition is correct the Po7'isms also must have intervened be- tween Books I. and ll., where we have already said that probably Diophantos treated of indeterminate problems of the first degree and of the solution of the complete quadratic. The method of the Ponsms was probably synthetic, like the Poly- gonal iVwrnfters, not (like the six Books of the Anthmetics) analytical ; this however forms no sufficient reason for refusing to include all three treatises under the single title of thirteen Books of Arithmetics. These suppositions would account easily for the contents of the lost Books ; they would also, with the additional evidence of the division of our text of the Arithmetics into seven books by the Vatican MS., show that the lost portion probably does not bear such a large proportion to the whole as might be imagined. This view is adopted by Colebrooke \ and after him by Nesselmann, who, in support of his hypothesis that the Arithmetics, the Porisms and the treatise on Polygonal Numbers formed only one complete work under the general title of dptd/jLTjTLKa, points out the very significant fact that we never find mention of more than one work of Diophantos, and that the very use of the Plural Neuter term, dpid/xrjTiKa, would seem to imply that it was a collection of different treatises on arithmetical subjects and of different content. Nesselmann, how- ever, does not seem to have noticed an objection previously urged ^ Algebra of the Hindus, Note M. p. lxi. "In truth the division of manuscript books is very uncertain: and it is by no means improbable that the remains of Diophantus, as we possess tlicni, may be less incomplete and constitute a larger portion of the thirteen books an- nounced by him (Def. 11) than is commonly reckoned. His treatise on polygon numbers, which is surmised to be one (and that the last of the thirteen), follows, as it seems, the six (or seven) books in the exemi)lar8 of the work, as if the preceding portion were complete. It is itself imperfect: but the manner is essentially different from that of the foregoing books: and the solution of problems by equations is no longer the object, but rather the demonstration of propositions. There appears no gi-ouud, beyond bare surmise, to presume, that the author, in the rest of the tracts relative to numbers which fulfilled his promise of thirteen books, resumed the Algebraic manner: or in short, that the Algebraic part of his performance is at all mutilated in the copies extant, which are considered to be all transcripts of a single imperfect exemplar." H. D. 3 34 DIOPllANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. against the theory that the three treatises formed only one work, by Schulz, to the effect that Diophantos expressly says that his work treats of arithmetical problems^. This statement itself does not seem to me to be quite accurate, and I cannot think that it is at all a valid objection to Nesselmann's view. The passage to which Schulz refers must evidently be the opening words of the dedication by the author to Dionysios. Diophantos begins thus: "Knowing that you are anxious to become ac- quainted with the solution [or ' discovery,' eupecri?] of problems in numbers, I set myself to systematise the method, beginning from the foundations on which the science is built, the pre- liminary determination of the nature and properties in numbers^." Now these "foundations" may surely well mean more than is given in the eleven definitions with which the treatise begins, and why should not the "properties of numbers" refer to the Porisms and the treatise on Polygonal Numbers .? But there is another passage which might seem to countenance Schulz's objection, where (Def. 11) Diophantos says "let us now proceed to the propositions'... which we will deal with in thirteen Books\" The word used here is not problem {Trpo/SXTj/xa) but proposition (TrporaaL^;), although Bachet translates both words by the same Latin word " quaestio," inaccurately. Now the word irporaaL^; does not only apply to the analytical solution of a problem : it applies equally to the synthetic method. Thus the use of the word here might very well imply that the work was to contain 1 Schulz remarks on the Porisms (pref. xxi.): "Es ist daher nicht uuwahr- Bcheinlich dass diese Porismeu eine eigene Schrift uuseres Diophautus wareu, welche vorziiglich die Zusammensetzung dcr Zahlen aus gew-issen Bestaud- theilen zu ihrem Gegeustando hattc. Kunnte man diesc Schrift gar als eine Bestandtheil des grossen in dreizehn Biichern abgefassten arithmetischen Werkes anseheu, so wiire es sehr erkliirbar, dass gerade dieser Theil, der den blossen Liebhaber weniger anzog, verloren ging. Da indess Diophantus aus- driickiich sagt, sein Werk behandele arithmetische Probleme, so hat weuigstens die letztere Annahme nur einen geringen Grad von Wahrscheinhchkeit." * Diophantos' own words are: Tiju tvptcnv twv iv roh apid/ioTs Trpo^XijfidTuiv, TifU(l)TaT^ fiOL AiovOffie, -yivilKTKtiiv ae cnrovdalus ^xovra naOuv, opyavwcrai r^c /j^dodov iweipdOrji', dp^ofKifOS d(f>' uv avviarrjKe rd Trpaynara 0e(jif\lii)v, vTroaTTJffai Trjv iv tois dptOfioh tpvffiv T« Kal Swaniv. •* vvv 5^ iirl rds irpordans x^RV'^'^t^^"' '^- '''■ ^• * T^s irpay/xareiai avrQv kv TpiffKaldfKa fii^Xlois yiyivripiivr)s. HIS WORKS. ;i5 not only problems, but propositions on numbers, i.e. miglit include the Po7'isms and Polygonal Numbers as a part of the complete Arithmetics. These objections which I have made to Schulz's argument are, I think, enough to show that his objection to the view adopted by Nesselmaun has no weight. Schulz's own view as to the contents of the missing Books of Diophantos is that they contained new methods of solution in addition to those used in Books I. to vi., and that accordingly the lost portion came at the end of the existing six Books. In particular he thinks that Diophantos extended in the lost Books the method of solution by means of what he calls a double- equation {Bi7r\r] laorr]^ or in one word hi,Tr\ola6rr}<;). By means of this double-equation Diophantos shows how to find a value of the unknown, which will make two expressions containing it (linear or quadratic) simultaneously squares. Schulz accordingly thinks that he went on in the lost Books to show how to make three such expressions simultaneously squares, i.e. advanced to a triple-equation. This view, however, seems to have nothing to recommend it, inasmuch as, in the first place, we nowhere find the slightest hint in the extant Books of anything different or more advanced which is to come ; and, secondly, Diophantos' system and ideas seem so self-contained, and his methods to move always in the same well-defined circle that it seems certain that we come in our six Books to the limits of his art. There is yet another view of the probable contents of the lost Books, which must be mentioned, though we cannot believe that it is the riglit one. It is that of Bombelli, given by Cossali, to the effect that in the lost Books Diophantos went on to solve determinate equations of the third and fourth degree; Bombelli's reason for supposing this is that Diophantos gives so many problems the object of which is to make the sum of a square and any other number to be again a square number by finding a suitable value of the first square ; these methods, argues Bombelli, of Diophantos must have been given for the reason that the author intended to use them for the solution of the equation x*-\-px = q^. Now Bombelli had occupied himself 1 Cossali's words are (p. 75, 76):..."non tralascier<i di notarc 1' opinionc, di cui fu teutato Bombelli, chc nclli soi libri cioe diil tempo, di tutto distrufe'gitore, 3—2 36 DIOPHAXTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. much, almost during his whole life, with the then new methods of solution of equations of the third and fourth degree ; and, for the solution of the latter, the usual method of his time led to the making an expression of the form Ax^+ Bx + C a. square, where the coefficients involved a second unknown quantity. Nesselmann accordingly thinks it is no matter for surprise that in Diophantos' entirely independent investigations Bombelli should have seen, or fancied he saw, his own favourite idea. This solution of the equation of the fourth degree presupposes that of the cubic with the second term wanting ; hence Bombelli would naturally, in accordance with his view, imagine Diophantos to have given the solution of this cubic. It is possible also that he may have been influenced by the actual occurrence in the extant Books [vi. 19] of a cubic equation, namely the equation x^ + x = 4x^ + 4, of which Diophantos at once writes down the solution a; = 4, without explanation. It is obvious, however, that no conclusion can be drawn from this, which is a very easy particular case, and which Diophantos probably solved^ by simply dividing out by the factor x^+l. There are strong objections to Bombelli's view. (1) Diophantos himself states (Def. XI.) that the solution of the problems is the object in itself of the work. (2) If he used the method to lead up to the solution of equations of higher degrees, he certainly has not gone to work the shortest way. In support of the view it has been asked "What, on any other assumption, is the object of defining in Def ll. all powers of the unknown quantity up to the sixth ? rapitici, si avanzasse egli a sciogliere 1' equazionc x*+px-q, parendogli, die nei libri riinastici, con proporsi di trovar via via numeri quadrati, cammini una strada a qucU' intento. Egli e di fatto procedendo sn queste tracce di Diofanto, che Vieta deprime 1' esposta equazione di giado quarto ad una di secondo. Siccome pen"!* cio non si effettua che mediante una cubica mancante di secondo termine; cosi il pcnsiero sorto in auimo a Bombelli iniporterebbc, che Diofanto nei libri perduti costituito avesse la regola di sciogliere questa sorta di equa- zione cubicbe prima d' innoltrarsi alio scioglimento di quella equazione di quarto grado." ' This is certainly a simpler explanation than Bachet's, who derives the solution from the proportion ar* : .x-=x : 1. Therefore x' + x : x- + l = .r : 1. Therefore x^ + x : 4x^ + i = x : i. But the equation being .r''-)-.r = 4j-'-' + 4, it follows that x-i. HIS WORKS. 37 Surely Diophantos must have meant to use them." The answer to which is that he has occasion to use them in the work, but reduces all the equations which contain these higher powers by his regular and uniform method of analysis. In conclusion, I may repeat that the most probable view is that adopted by Nesselmann, that the works which we know under the three titles formed part of one arithmetical work, which was, according to the author's own words, to consist of thirteen Books. The proportion of the lost parts to tlie whole is probably less than it might be supposed to be. The Ponsnis form the part, the loss of which is most to be regretted, for from the references to them it is clear that they contained propositions in the Theory of Numbers most wonderful for the time. CHAPTER III. THE WRITERS UPON DIOPHANTOS. § 1. In this chapter I purpose to give a sketch of what has been done directly, and (where it is of sufficient importance) indirectly, for Dioph antes, enumerating and describing briefly (so far as possible) the works which have been written on the subject. We turn first, naturally, to Diophantos' own country- men ; and we find that, if we except the doubtful " commentary of Hypatia," spoken of above, there is only one Greek, who has written anything at all on Diophantos, namely the monk Maxi- mus Planudes, to whom are attributed the scholia attached to Books I. and ii. in some MSS., which are printed in Latin in Xylander's translation of Diophantos. The date of these scholia is the first half of the 14th century, and they represent all that we know to have been done for Diophantos by his own country- men. How different his fate would have been, had he lived a little earlier, when the scientific spirit of the Greeks was still active, what an enormous impression his work would then have created, we may judge by comparing the effect which it had with that of a far less important work, that of Nikomachos. Considering then that up to the time of Maximus Planudes nothing was written about Diophantos (beyond a single quota- tion by Theon of Alexandria, before mentioned, and an occa- sional mention of the name) by any Greek, one is simply astounded at finding in Bossut's history a remark like the following : " L'auteur a eu parmi les anciens une foule d'inter- prfetes (!), dont les ouvrages sont la plupart (!) perdus. Nous regrettons, dans ce nombre, le commentaire de la cdlebre Hipathia (sic)." Comment is unnecessary. With respect to THK WRITKHS UPON DK H'HANTc )S. :][) the work of Maximus Planudes itself, he has only commented upon the first two Books, the least important and most olomen- tary, nor can his scholia be said to have any importance. Bachet speaks contemptuously of them\ and even the modest Xylander has but a low opinion of their value^ § 2. I have, in first mentioning Maximus Planudes, de- parted a little from chronological order, for the greater con- venience of giving first the Greek writers upon Diophantos. But long before the time of Maximus Planudes, the work of Diophantos had found its way to Arabia, and there met with the respect it deserved. Unfortunately the actual works writ- ten in Arabia directly upon Diophantos are all lost, or at lea.st have not been discovered up to the present time. So far there- fore as these are concerned we have to be contented with the notices on the subject by Arabian historians or bibliographers. It is therefore necessary to collect from the earliest and best sources possible the scattered remarks about Diophantos and his works. The earliest and therefore presumably the best and most trustworthy authority on the subject of Diophantos in Arabia is the Kifab Alfihrist of al-Nadim', the date of which is as early as circa 990 a,d. The passages in this work which refer to Diophantos are : (a) p. 269, "Diophantos [the last vowel, however, being I = t; in one codex, in the rest undetermined] the Greek of 1 Bachet says: "Porro Graeci Sclioliastae in duos priores libros adnota- tiones edi non curauimus, vt quae nullius sint momenti, easque proinde Guilielmus Xilander(!) censura sua meritd perstrinxerit, si cut tamen oleum operamque perderc a(le7) leue est, vt miras GraecuU huius ineptias peruidcre cupiat, adeat Xilandrum." - Xylander says the Scholia are attributed to Maximus Planudes, and com- bats the view that they might be Hjiiatia's thus: "Sed profecto si ea tanta fuit, quantam Suidas et alij perhibent, istae annotationes cam autorcm non apnoscunt, de quibus quid senserim, raeo more liberfe dixi suis locis." Kpistola Nuncupatoria. 3 This work has been edited by Fliigel, 1871. The author himself dates it 987, and Wcipcke (Journal Asiatique, F^vrier-Mars, 18.55, p. 2.56) states that it was finished at that date. This is, however, not correct, for in his preface Fliigel shows that the work contains references to events which are certainly later than <)87, so that it seems best to say simply that the date is cir<-a 990 A.I). 40 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Alexandria. He wrote Kitab Sina'at al-jabr," i.e. "the book of the art of algebra." (h) p. 283, Among the works of Abii'1-Wafa is mentioned "An interpretation' (tafsir) of the book of Diophantos about algebra." (c) On the same page the title of another work of Abu'l- Wafa is given as " Demonstrations of the theorems employed by Diophantos in his work, and of those employed by (Abu'l- Wafa) himself in his commentary " (the word is as before tafsir). {d) p. 295, On Kosta ibn Luka of Ba'lbek it is mentioned that one of his books is tafsir on three-and-a-half divisions (Makalat) of the book of Diophantos on " questions of numbers." We have thus in the Fihrist mentions of three separate works upon Diophantos, which must accordingly have been written previously to the year 990 of our era. Concerning Abu'1-Wafa the evidence of his having studied and commented upon Diophantos is conclusive, not only because his other works which have survived show unmistakeable signs of the influence of Diophantos, but because the proximity of date of the Fihrist to that of Abu'1-Wafa makes all mistake impossible. As I have said the Fihrist was written circa 990 A.D. and the date of Abu'1-Wafa is 328—388 a.h. or 940—998 A.D. He was a native of Buzjan, a small town between Herat and Nishapur in Khorasan, and was evidently, from what is known of his works one of the most celebrated astronomers and geometers of his time^. Of later notices on this subject we may mention those ' There is a little doubt as to the exact meaning of tafsir — whether it means a translation or a commentary. The word is usually applied to the literal exe- gesis of the Koran ; how much it means in the present case may perhaps be ascertainable from the fact that Abu'1-Wafa also wrote a tafsir of the Algebra of Mohammed ibn Musa al-Khruizml. It certainly, according to the usual sense, means a commentary not a mere translation — e.g. at p. 249 al-Nadim clearly distinguishes translators of Aristotle from the mufassirln or makers of tafsir, i.e. commentators. For this information I am indebted to the kindness of Professor Robertson Smith. - Wcipcke, Journal Asiatiqne, Ft'vrier-Mars, 1855, p. 244 foil. Abu'l-Wafa's full name is Mohammed ibn Mohammed ibn Yahya ibn Ismail ibn Al'abbfis Abu'1-Wafa Al-Iiuzjani. THE WRITERS UPON DIOPHANTOS. 41 in the Tarlkh Ilokoma (Hajji-Khalifa, No. 2204), by tho Imam Mohammed ibn. 'Abd al-Karim al-Shahrastani wlio died A.ii. 548 or A.D. 1153\ Of course this work is not so trustworthy an authority as the Fihrist, which is about 160 years earlier, and the author of the Tarlkh HoJcoma stands to the Fihrist in the relation of a compiler to the original source. In the Tarikh Hokoma we are told {a) that Abu'1-Wafa " wrote a commen- tary on the work of Diophantos concerning Algebra," (6) that '• Diophantos, the Greek of Alexandria, conspicuous, perfect, famous in his time, wrote a famous work on the art of Algebra, which has gone over into Arabic," i. e. been trans- lated. We must obviously connect these two notices. Lastly the same work mentions (c) another work of Abu'1-Wafa, namely '• Proofs for the propositions given in his book by Diophantos." A later writer still, the author of the History of the Dynas- ties, Abu'lfaraj, mentions, among celebrated men who lived in the time of Julian, Diophantos, with the addition that " His book^..ou Algebra is celebrated," and again in another place he says upon Abu'1-Wafa, " He commented upon the work of Diophantos on Algebra." The notices from al-Shahrastani and Abu'lfaraj are, as I have ^ The work Bibliotheca arabico-hispana Escurialensis op. et studio Mich. Casiri, Matriti, 1760, gives many important notices about mathematicians from the Ta'rikh Hokoma, which Casiri denotes by the title Bibliotheca philo- sophorum. Cossali mentions the Ta'rikh Hokoma as having been written about a.d. 119^! by an anonymous person: "II hbro piti antico, che ci fornisca tratti relativi all' origine dell' analisi tra gli arabi e la Bihlioteca arabica de' jilosoji, scritta circa 1' anno 1198 da anonimo egiziano" (Cossali, i. p. 174). There is however now apparently no doubt that the author was al-Shahrastani, as I have said in the text. 2 After the word "book" in the text comes a word Ab-kismet which is un- intelligible. PocoQke, the Latin translator, simply puts A. B. for it: "cuius liber A. 13. quern Algebram vocat, Celebris est." The word or words are apparently a corruption of something ; Nesselmann conjectures that the original word was an Arabic translation of the Greek title, Arithmetics— a supposition which, if true, would give admirable sense. The passage would then mark the Arabian perception of the discrepancy (according to the accepted meaning of termn) between the title and the subject, which is obviously rather algebra than arith- metic in the strict sense. 42 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. said, for obvious reasons not so trustworthy as those in the Fihrist. They are, however, interesting as showing that Dio- phantos continued to be kno^vn and recognised for a consider- able period after his work found its way to Arabia, and was commented upon, though they add nothing to our information as to what was done for Diophantos in Arabia. It is clear that the work of Abu'1-Wafa was the most considerable that was written in Arabia upon Diophantos directly ; about the obliga- tions to Diophantos of other Arabian writers, as indirectly shown by similarity of matter or method, without direct refer- ence, I shall have to speak later. § 3. I now pass to the writers on Diophantos in Europe. From the time of Maximus Planudes to a period as late as about 1570 Diophantos remained practically a sealed book, and had to be rediscovered even after attention had been invited to it by Regiomontanus, who, as was said above, was the first European to mention it as extant. We have seen (pp. 21, 22) that Regiomontanus referred to Diophantos in the Oration at Padua, about 1462, and how in a very interesting letter to Joannes de Blanchinis he speaks of finding a MS. of Diophantos at Venice, of the pleasure he would have in translating it if he could only find a copy containing the whole of the thirteen books, and his readiness to translate even the incomplete work in six books, in case it were desired. But it does not appear that he ever began the work ; it seems, however, very extraordinary that the interest which Regiomontanus took in Diophantos and tried to arouse in others should not have incited some of his German countrymen to follow his leading, at least as early as 1537, when we know that his Oration at Padua was published. Hard to account for as the fact may appear, it was left for an Italian, Bombelli, to rediscover Diophantos about 1570; though the mentions by Regiomontanus may be said at last to have borne their fruit, in that about the same time Xylander was en- couraged by them to persevere in his intention of investigating Diophantos. Nevertheless between the time of Regiomontanus and that of Rafael Bombelli Diophantos was once more for- gotten, or rather unknown, for in the interval we find two mentions of tlie name, (a) b} Joachim Camerarius in a letter THE WRITERS UPON DIOPHANTOS. 43 published 1556\ in which he mentions that there is a MS. of Diophantos in the Vatican, which he is anxious to see, (6) by James Peletarius^ who merely mentions the name. Of the important mathematicians who preceded Bombelli, Fra Luca Pacioli towards the end of the loth century. Cardan and Tar- taglia in the 16th, not one so much as mentions Diophantos^ The first Italian to whom Diophantos seems to have been known, and who was the first to discover a MS. in the Vatican Library, and to conceive the idea of publishing the work, was Rafael Bombelli. Bachet falls into an anachronism when he says that Bombelli began his work upon Diophantos after the appearance of Xylander's translation*, which was published in 1575. The Algebra of Bombelli appeared in 1572, and in the ^ De Graecis Latinisque tiumerorum notis et praeterea Saracenis sett Indicts, etc. etc., studio Joachimi Camerarii, Papeberg, 1556. In a letter to Zasius : " Venit mihi in nientem eorum quae et de bac et aliis liberalibus artibus dicta fuere, in eo convivio cujus in tuis aedibus me et Peuce- rum nostrum participes esse, suavissima tua invitatio voluit. Cum autem de autoribus Logistices verba fierent, et a me Diophantus Graecus nominaretur, qui extaret in Bibliotbeca Vaticana, ostendebatur turn spes quaedam, posse nobis copiam libri illius. Ibi ego cupiditate videndi incensus, fortasse audacius non tamen iiifeliciter, te quasi procuratorem constitui negotii gerendi, mandate voluntario, cum quidem et tu libenter susciperes quod imponebatur, et fides solenni festivitate firmaretur, de illo tuo et poculo elegante ct vino optimo. Neque tu igitur oblivisceris ejus rei, cujus explicationem tua benignitas tibi commisit, neque ego non meminisse potero, non modo excelleutis \-irtuti8 ct sapientiae, sed singularis comitatis et incredibilis suavitatis tuae." - Arithmeticae practicae methodus facilis, per Gemmani Frisium, etc. Hue accedunt Jacobi Peletarii annotationes, Coloniae, 1571. (But pref. of Peletarius bears date 1558.) P. 72, Nota Peletarii: "Algebra autem dicta videtur a Gebro Arabe ut vox ipsa sonat ; hujus artis si non inventore, saltern excultore. Alii tribuunt Diophanto cuidam Graeco." '■' Cossali I. p. 59, "Cosa pero, che reca la somma maraviglia si 6, che largo in Italia non si spandesse la cognizionc del codice di Diofanto : che in fiore essendovi lo studio della greca lingua, non veuisse da qualche dotto a coman vantaggio tradotta; che per 1' opposto niuna menzione ne faccia Fra Luca verso il fine del secolo xv, e niuna Cardano, e Tartaglia intorno la metA del secolo XVI ; che nelle biblioteche rinianesse sepolto, ed andassc dimenticato per modo, che poco prima degli anni 70 del secolo xvi si riguardasse per una scoperta 1' averlo rinvonuto nella Vaticana liiblioteca." ■» "Non longo post Xilandrum interuallo llaphael Bombellius Bononiensis, Graecum e Vaticana Bibliotheca Diophanti codicem nactus, omnes priorum quattuor librorum quaestiones, et 6 libro quinto nonuuUas, probk-matibus uiub iuseruit, in Algebra sua quam Italico sermono conwcripsit." 44 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. preface to this work * the author tells us that he had recently discovered a Greek book on Algebra in the Vatican Library, written by a certain Diofantes, an Alexandrine Greek author who lived in the time of Antoninus Pius ; that, thinking highly of the contents of this work, he and Antonio Maria Pazzi de- termined to translate it ; that they actually translated five books out of the seven into wliich the MS. was divided ; but that, before the whole was finished, they were called away from it by other labours. The date of these occurrences must be a few years before 1572. Though Bombelli did not carry out his plan of publishing Diophantos in a translation, he has neverthe- less taken all the problems of Diophantos' first four Books and some of those of the fifth, and embodied them in his Algebra, interspersing them with his own problems. Though he has taken no pains to distinguish Diophantos' problems from his own, he has in the case of Diophantos' work adhered pretty closely to the original, so that Bachet admits his obligations to Bombelli, whose reproduction of the problems of Diophantos he maintains that he found in many points better than Xylander's translation'^ It may be interesting to mention a few points of 1 This book Nesselmann tells ns that he has never seen, but takes his infor- mation about it from Cossali. I was fortunate enough to find a copy of it published in 1579 (not the original edition) in the British Museum, the title being U Algebra, opera d'l Rafael BomheUi da Bolorjiia diiiisa in tre Libri In Bologna, Per Giovanni Rossi. MDLXXIX. I have thus been able to verify the quotations from the preface. The whole passage is : "Questi anni passati, essendosi ritrouato una opera greca di questa disciplina nella libraria di Nostro Signore in Vaticano, composta da un certo Diofante Alessandrino Autor Greco, il quale fCl a tempo di Antonin Pio, e havendo mela fatta vedere Messer Antonio Maria Pazzi Reggiano publico lettore delle Matema- tiche in Roma, e giu dicatolo con lui Autore assai intelligente de numeri (an- corche non tratti de numeri irrationali, ma solo in lui si vcde vn perfetto ordine di opcrare) egli, ed io, per arrichirc il mondo di cosi fatta opera, ci dessimo a tradurlo, e cinque libri (delli sette che souo) tradutti ne habbiamo ; lo restaute non haueudo potuto finire per gli trauagli aueuuti all' uno, e all' altro, e in detta opera habbiamo ritrouato, ch' egli assai volte cita gli Autori Indiani, col che mi ha fatto conoscere, che questa disciplina appo gl' indiani prima ih, che a gli Arabi." The parts of this quotation which refer to the personality of Diophantos, the form Diofante, &c., have already been commented upon ; the last clauses we shall have occasion to mention again. '^ Continuation of quotation in note 4, p. 43 : "Sed suas Diophanteis quaestionibus ita immiecuit, ut has ab illis distiu- THE WKITKKS UPON Dl< )1'|IANT()S. 45 notation in this work of Bombclli. At bef,dnning of Book ii he explains that he uses the word "tanto" to denote the unknown quantity, not "cosa" like his predecessors; and his symbol for it is i, the square of the unknown (x-) is c., the cube i; and so on. For plus and minus (pm and meno) he uses the initial letters p. and m. Thus corresponding to x + Q we should find in Bom- belli 11 p. 6, and for .r + ox-4<, 11 p. 5i m. 4. This notation shows, as will be seen later, some advance upon that of Dio- phantos in one important respect. The next writer upon Diophantos was ^Vilhelm Holznianu who published, under the Graecised form of his name Xylander by which he is generally known, a work bearing the title : Diophanti Alexandrini Rerum Arithmetical' um LibH sex, quo- rum primi duo adiecta hahent Scholia Maximi {ut coniectura est) Plamtdis. Item Liber de Numeris Polygonis seu Multan- gulis. Opus incomparahile, uerae Arithmeticae Logisticae per- fectionem continens, paucis adhuc uisum. A Guil. Xylandro Augustano incredihili lahore Latine redditum, et Commentariui explanatum, inque lucem editum ad Illustriss. Principem Ludo- vicum Vuirtemhergensem Basileae per Eusebium Episcopium, et Nicolai Fr. haeredes. mdlxxv. Xylander was according to his own statement a " public teacher of Aristotelian philosophy in the school at Heidelberg\" He was a man of almost universal culture ^ and was so thoroughly imbued with the classical litera- ture, that the extraordinary aptness of his quotations and his wealth of expression give exceptional charm to his writing whenever he is free from the shackles of mathematical formulae and technicalities. The Epistola Nuncupatoria is addressed to the Prince Ludwig, and Xylander neatly introduces it by the line "Offerimus numeros, numeri sunt principe digni." This preface is very quaint and interesting. He tells us how he first saw the name of Diophantos mentioned in Suida.s, and guere non sit in promptu, neque vefD se fidum satis interpretem pracbuit, cum passim verba Diophanti immutet, bisque pleraque addat, plcraque pro arbitrio detrahat. In multis nihilominus interprctationem Bombellii, Xilandriana prac- stare, et ad banc emendandam me adjuvisse iu(,'enue fateor." Ad Icctorem. ' " Publicus pbilosophiae Aristoteleae in schola Hcidolbergcnsi doctor." - Even Bachet, who, as wo shall see, was no favourable critic, calls him " Vir omnibus disciplinis excultus." 46 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. then found that mention had been made of his work by Regio- montanus as being extant in an Italian Library and having been seen by him. But, as the book had not been edited, he tried to reconcile himself to the want of it by making himself acquainted with the works on Arithmetic which were actually known and in use, and he apologises for what he considers to have been a disgrace to him\ With the help of books only he studied the subject of Algebra, so far as was possible from what men like Cardan had written and by his own reflection, with such success that not only did he fall into what Herakleitos called olrjo-Lv, lepav voaov, or the conceit of " being somebody " in the field of Arithmetic and " Logistic," but others too who were themselves learned men thought him (as he modestly tells us) an arithmetician of exceptional merit. But when he first became acquainted with the problems of Diophantos (he con- tinues) his pride had a fall so sudden and so humiliating that he might reasonably doubt whether he ought previously to have 1 I cannot refrain from quoting the whole of this passage : "Sed cum ederet nemo : cepi desideriimi hoc paulatim in animo consopire, et eorum quos consequi poteram Arithmeticorum librorum cognitions, et medita- tionibus nostris sepelire. Veritatis porro apud me est autoritas, ut ei con- iunctum etiam cum dedecore meo testimonium lubentissime perhibeam. Quod Cossica seu Algebrica (cum his enim reliqua comparata, id sunt quod umbrae Homeric^ in Necya ad aniniam Tiresiac) ca ergo quod nou assequebar modo, quanquam mutis duntaxat usus preceptoribus caetera ai)To5/5a/cTos, sed et augers, uariare, adeoque corrigere in loco didicissem, quae summi et fidelissimi in docendo uiri Christifer Eodolphus Silesius, Micaolus, Stifelius, Cardanus, No- nius, aliique litteris mandauerant : incidi in otrjaiv, lepav vbaov, ut scitfe appel- lauit Heraclitus sapientior multis aliis philosophis, hoc est, in Arithmetica, et uera Logistica, putaui me esse aliquid: itaque de me passim etiam a multis, iisque doctis uiris iuJicatum fuit, me non de grege Arithmeticum esse. Verum ubi primum in Diophantca incidi : ita me recta ratio circumegit, ut flenddsne mihi ipsi antca, an uero ridendus fuissem, haud iniuria dubitaucrim. Operas preciuni est hoc loco et meam inscitiam inuulgarc, et Diophantei operis, quod mihi ncbulosam istam caligincm ab oculis detcrsit, immo cos in coenum barbaricum defossos eleuauit et repurgauit, gustum aliquem exhibere. Surdorum ego uumerorum tractationem ita tenebam, ut etiam addere alioriun inuentis aliquid non poenitendum auderem, atque id quidem in rebus arithmeticis mag- num habetur, et difficultas istarum rerum multos a mathematibus deterret. Quanto autem hoc est praeclarius, in iis problematis, quae surdis etiam numsris uix posse uideutur explicari, rem eo deduccre, ut quasi solum arithmeticum ucrtere iussi obsurdescant illi plane, et ne mentio quidem eorum in tractatione inguniosissimarum quaustiouum admittatur." THE WRITERS I'PON DlOl'llANTOS. 47 bewailed, or laughed at himself. He considers it therefore worth while to confess publicly in how disgraceful a condition of ignorance he had previously been content to live, anil to do something to make known the work of Diophantos, which had so opened his eyes. Before this critical time he was so familiar with methods of dealing with surds that he actually had ventured to add something to the discoveries of others relating to them ; these were considered to be of great importance in questions of Arithmetic, and their difficulty was of itself sufficient to deter many from the study of Mathematics. " But how much more splendid " (says Xylander) " the methods which reduce the problems which seem to be hardly capable of solution even with the help of surds in such a way that, while the surds, when bidden (so to speak) to plough the arithmetic soil, become true to their name and deaf to entreaty, they are not so much as mentioned in these most ingenious solutions ! " He then de- scribes the enormous difficulties which beset his work owing to the coiTuptions in his text. In dealing, however, with the mistakes and carelessness of copyists he was, as he says, no novice; for proof of which he appeals to his editions of Plutarch, Stephanus and Strabo. This passage, which is delightful read- ing, but too long to reproduce here, I give in full in the note '. > " Id uero mihi accidit durum et uix superabile incommodum, quM mirificft deprauata omnia inueni, ctim neque problematum expositio interdum integra esset, ac passim numeri (iu quibus sita omnia esse in hoc arRumento, quia ignorat?) tarn problematum quam solutionum siue cxplicatiouum corruptissimi. Non pudebit me ingenue fateri, qualem me heic gesserim. Audacter, et summo cum feruore potius qusim alacritate auimi opus ipsum initio sum aggressus, laborque mihi omnis uoluptati fuit, tantus est meus rernm arithmoticarum amor, quin et gratiam magnam me apud omnes liberalium scientiarum amatores ac patronos initiirum, et praeclare de rep. litteraria nierituriim intclligebam, eamque rem mihi laudi (quam ii bonis profectam nemo prudens aspernatur) gloriaeque fortasse etiam emolumento fore sperabam. Progressus aliquantulum, in salebras incidi : quae tantum abest ut alacritatem meam retuderint, ut etiam animos milii addiderint, neque enim mihi novum aut insolons est aduersus librariorum incuriam certamen, et hac in re militaui, (ut Horatii nostri uerbis utar) non sine gloria, quod me non arroganter dicere, Dio, Plutarchu.^, Strabo, Stephanusque nostri testantur. Sed cum mox in ipsum pelagus nionstris scatons me cmsus abripuit: non dcspondi equidem animum, neque manus dedi, scd tamen saepius ad cram undo soluissem respeju, qujmi portum in quem csaet euadeudum cogitandu prospicerem, depracheudiquc non minus uerii quum ele- 48 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Next Xylander tells us how he came to get possession of a manu- script of Diophantos. In October of the year 1571 he made a journey to Wittenberg ; while there he had conversations on mathematical subjects with two professors, Sebastian Theodoric and Wolfgang Schuler by name, who showed him a few pages of a Greek manuscript of Diophantos and informed him that it belonged to Andreas Dudicius whom Xylander describes as " Andreas Dudicius Sbardellatus, hoc tempore Imperatoris Ro- manorum apud Polonos orator." On his departure from Witten- berg Xylander wrote out and took with him the solution of a single problem of Diophantos, to amuse himself with on his journey. This he showed at Leipzig to Simon Simonius Lucen- sis, a professor at that place, who wrote to Dudicius on his behalf. A few months afterwards Dudicius sent the MS. to Xylander and encouraged him to persevere in his undertaking to translate the Arithmetics into Latin. Accordingly Xylander insists that the glory of the whole achievement belongs in no less but rather in a greater degree to Dudicius than to himself. Finally he commends the work to the favour of the Prince Ludwig, extolling the pursuit of arithmetical and alge- braical science and dwelling in enthusiastic anticipation on the influence which the Prince's patronage would have in help- ing and advancing the study of Arithmetic \ This Epistola ganter ea cecinisse Alcaeum, quae (si possum) Latino in hac quasi uotiua mea tabula scribam. Qui uela uentis uult dare, dum licet, Cautus futuri praeuideat modum Cursus. mare ingressus, marine Nauigct arbitrio necesse est. Sand, quod de Echeueide pisce fertur, eum nauim cui se adplicet remorari, poenh credibile fecit mihi mea cymba tot mendorum remoris retardata. Expediui tamen me ita, ut facilS omnes mediocri de his rebus iudicio praediti, iutellecturi sint incredibilem me laborem et aerumnas difticilimas superasso : pudore etiam stimulatum oneris quod ultro milii imposuissem, non perferendi. Paucula quae- dam non plane explicata, studio et certis de causis in alium locum reiecimus. Opus quidem ipsum ita absoluimus ut ueque eius nos pudere debeat, et Arith- meticae Logisticesque studiosi nobis se plurimum debere sint baud dubie professuri." ' "Hoc non modo tibi Princeps Illustrissimc, honorificum erit, atque glori- osum ; sed tc labores nostros approbantc, arithmcticae studium cum alibi, tum in tua Academia et Gymuasiis, excilabitur, confirmabitur, prouebetur, et ad THE WRITERS UPON DIOPIIANTOS. 49 Nuncnpatoria boars the date 14th August, 1574'. Xylandcr (lied on the 10th of February in the year following that of the publication, 1576. Some have stated that Xy lander published the Greek text of Diophantos as well as the Latin translation. There appears to be no foundation for the statement, which probably rests on a misunderstanding of certain passages in which Xylander refers to the Greek text. It is possible that he intended to publish the Greek original but was prevented by his death which so soon followed the appearance of his trans- lation. It is a sufficient proof, how^ever, that if such was his purpose it was never carried out, that Bachet asserts that he himself had never seen or found any one who had ever seen such an edition of the Greek text ^ Concerning the merits of Xylander and his translation of Diophantos much has been written, and chiefly by authors who were not weW acquainted with the subject, but whose very ignorance seems to have been their chief incitement to startling statements. Indeed very few persons at all seem to have studied the book itself: a fact which may be partly accounted for by its rarity. Nesselmaun, whose book appeared in 1842, tells us honestly that he has never been able to find a copy, but has been obliged to take all information on the subject at second hand from Cossali and Bachet '. Even Cossali, so far as he gives any opinion at all upon the merits of the book, seems to do no more than reproduce what Bachet had said before him. Nor does Schulz seem to have studied Xylander' s work : at least all his statements about it are vague and may very well have been gathered at second hand. Both he and perfectam eiu.s scientiam multi tuis auspiciis, nostro labore pcrducti, niognam hac re tuis in remp. beneficiis accessionem factam esse gratissima commemora- tione praedicabunt." 1 "Heidelberga. postrid. Eidus Sextiles cio lo lxxiv." - "An vero et Graece a Xilandro editus sit Diophantus, nondum certti com- perire potui. Videtur sanb in multis suorum Commcntariorum locis, de Graeco Diopbanto tanquam a se cdito, vcl mox edendo, verba facere. Sed banc cditi- onem, neque mihi vidisse, neque aliquem qui viderit hactcnus audivisse contigit." Bachet, Epist. ad Led. 3 There is not, I believe, a copy even in the British Museum, but I had the rare good fortune to find the book in the Library of Trinity College, Cambridge. H. D. * 50 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Nesselmann confine themselves to saying that it was not so worthless as many writers had stated it to be (Nesselmann on his part confessing his inability to form an opinion for the reason that he had never seen the book), and that it was well received among savants of the period, while its effect on the growth of the study of Algebra was remarkable \ On the other hand, the great majority of writers on the subject may be said to shout in chorus a very different cry. One instance will suffice to show the quality of the statements that have been generally made : to enumerate more would be waste of space. Dr Heinrich Suter in a History of Mathematical Sciences (Zurich 1873) says^ " This translation is very poor, as Xylander was very little versed in Mathematics." If Dr Hein- rich Suter had taken the trouble to read a few words of Xylander's preface, he could hardly have made so astounding a statement as that contained in the second clause of this sentence. This is only a specimen of the kind of statements which have been made about Xylander's book ; indeed I have been able to find no one who seems to have adequately studied Xylander except Bachet ; and Bachet's statements about the work of his predecessor and his own obligations to the same have been unhesitatingly accepted by the great majority of later writers. The result has been that Bachet has been uni- versally considered the only writer who has done anything considerable for Diophantos, while the labours of his prede- cessor have been ignored or despised. This view of the relative merits of the two authors is, in my vieAv, completely erroneous. From a careful study and comparison of the two editions I have come to the conclusion that honour has not been paid where honour was due. It would be tedious to give here in 1 Schulz. "Wie uuvollkomiucn Xylanders Ai-beit auch ausfiel, wie oft cr auch den rcchten Sinn verfehlte, und wic oft auch seine Aumerkuugeii den Laser, der sich Eathes eiholen will, im Stichc lasseu, so gut war dock die Aufnalimc, welche sein Uuch bei den Gelehitcn damaligcr Zcit fand; dcnn in der That giog den Matlicmatikcru durch die Erscheinung dieses Werkes ein neues Licbt auf, und es ist mir schr wabrscbcinlicb, dass er viel dazu beigetrageu hat, die allgemeiue Arithmetik zu ihrer nachnialigen Hohe zu erheben." - "Dicse Uebersetzung aber ist sebr schwach, da Xylander in Mathematik sebr wenig bewaudcrt war." THE WIUTEUS UPON DluPlIANToS. ol detail the particular facts which led me to this conchision. I will only say in this place that my suspicions were first aroused by reading Bachet's work alone, before I had seen tlie earlier one. From perusing Bachet I received the impression that his repeated emphatic and almost violent repudiation of obligation to Xylander, and his disparagement of that author suggested the very thing which he disclaimed, that he was under too great obligation to his predecessor to acknowledge it duly. I must now pass to Bachet's work itself It was the first edition published which contained the Greek text, and appeared in 1621 bearing the title: Diophanti Alexandrini Anthmetico- 7-um libri sex, et de numeris nndtancjulis liber unus. JVtoic 2)riinuin Graece et Latine editi, atque absolidissimis Commentariis illitstrati. Auctore Claudio Gaspare Bacheto Mezinaco Sebusiano, V.G. Lidetiae Pansiorum, Surnptibus Hieronymi Drovart^, via Jacobaea, sub Scuto Solari. MDGXXI. (I should perhaps mention that we have a statement^ that in Carl von Montchall's Library there was a translation of Diophantos which the mathe- matician "Joseph Auria of Neapolis" made, but did not ap- parently publish, and which was entitled "Diophanti libri sex, cum scholiis graecis Maximi Planudae, atque liber de numeris polygonis, collati cum Vaticanis codicibus, et latine versi a Josepho Auria." Of this work we know nothing; neither Bachet nor Cossali mentions it. The date would presumably be about the same as that of Xylauder's translation, or a little later.) Bachet's Greek text is based, as he tells us, upon a MS. which he calls "codex Regius", now in the Bibliotheque Na- tionale at Paris; this MS. is his sole authority, except that Jacobus Sirmondus had part of a Vatican MS. transcribed for him. He professes to have produced a good Greek text, having spent incalculable labour upon its emendation, to have inserted 1 For "surnptibus Hierouymi Drovart" Nesselinann has "surnptibus Sebas- tiani Cramoisy, 1021 " which is found in some copies. The former (as given above) is taken from the title-page of the copy which I have used (from the Library of Trinity College, Cambridge). - Schulz, Vorr. xliii.: "Noch erwuhnen die Litteratorcn, dass eich in der Bibliothek eines Carl von Moutchall einc Bearbeitung des Diophantus von dem beruhmten Joseph Auria von Neapel (vermuthlich doch uur handschriftUoli) befuudeu habe, welche den Titel I'uhrte u. s. w." (see Text). 52 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. in brackets all additions which he made to it and to have given notice of all corrections, except those of an obvious or trifling nature; a few passages he has left asterisked, in cases where correction could not be safely ventured upon. In spite however of Bachet's assurance I cannot help doubting the quality of his text in many places, though I have not seen the MS. which he used. He is careful to tell us what pre- vious works relating to the subject he had been able to con- sult. First he mentions Xylander (whom he invariably quotes as Xilander), who had translated the whole of Diophantos, and commented upon him throughout, "except that he scarcely touched a considerable pai't of the fifth book, the whole of the sixth and the treatise on multangular numbers, and even the rest of his work was not very successful, as he himself admits that he did not thoroughly understand a number of points." Then he speaks of Bombelli (already mentioned) and the Zetetica of Vieta (in which the author treats in his own way a large number of Diophantos' problems : Bachet thinks that he so treated them because he despaired of restoring the book completely). Neither Bombelli nor Vieta (says Bachet) made any attempt to demonstrate the difficult porisms and abstruse theorems in numbers which Diophantos assumes as known in many places, or sufficiently explained the causes of his opera- tions and artifices. All these omissions on the part of his predecessors he thinks he has supplied in his notes to the various problems and in the three Books of "Porisms" which he prefixed to the work\ As regards bis Latin translation, he says that he gives us Diophantos in Latin from the version of Xylander most carefully corrected, in which he would have us know that he has done two things in particular, first, corrected ^ On the nature of some of Bacliet's proofs Nicholas Saunderson (formerly Lucasian Professor) remarks in Elements of Algebra, 1740, apropos of Dioph. III. 17. "M. Bachet indeed in the IGth and 17th props, of his second book of Porisms has given us demonstrations, such as they are, of the theorems in the problem: but in the first place he demonstrates but one single case of those theorems, and in the next place the demonstrations he gives are only synthetical, and so abominably perplexed withal, that in each demonstration he makes uso of all the letters in the alphabet except I and 0, singly to represent the quantities he has there occasion for." THE WRITERS UPON DIuPllANTOS. 53 what was wrong and supplied the numerous lacunae, secondly, explained more clearly what Xylander had given in obscure or ambiguous language: "I confess however", he says "that this made so much change necessary, that it is almost more fair to attribute the translation to me than to Xilander. But if anyone prefers to consider it as his, because I have held fast, tooth and nail, to his words when they do not misrepresent Diophantus, I do not care'". Such sentences as these, which are no rarity in Bachet's book, are certainly not calculated to increase our respect for the author. According to Montucla", "the historian of the French Academy tells us" that Bachet worked at this edition during the course of a quartan fever, and that he himself said that, disheartened as he was by the diffi- culty of the work, he would never have completed it, had it not been for the stubbornness which his malady generated iu him. As the first and only edition of the Greek text of Dio- phantos, this work, in spite of any imperfections we may find in it, does its author all honour. The same edition was reprinted and published with the addition of Fermat's notes in 1G70. Diophanti Alexandrini Arithmeticorwni lihri sex, et de numeris multangidis liher itmis. Cum commentariis G. G. Bacheti V. G. et ohseruationibus D. P. de Fermat Senatoris Tolosani. Accessit Doctrinae Amdyticae inuentum nouum, collectum ex variis eiusdem D. de Fermat Epistolis. Tolusae, Excudehat Bernardus Bosc, ^ Regione CuUegii Societatis Jesu, MDGLXX. This edition was not pubhshed by Fermat himself, as certain writers imply ^ but by his son '■"Deinde Latinum damus tibi Diophantum ex Xilandri versione accura- tissime castigata, in qua duo potissimum nos praestitisse scias velim, nam et deprauata correximus, hiantesque passim lacunas repleuimus : et quae sub- obscure, vel ambigue fuerat interpretatus Xilander, dilucidius exposuimus; fateor tamen, inde tantam inductam esse mutationem, vt propemodum aequius sit ver- sioneni istam nobis quam Xilandro tribuere. Si quis autem potius ad eum \^t- tinere contendat, qu5d eius verba, quatenus Diophanto fraudi non erant, niordicus retinuimus, per me licet." 2 I. 323. ' So Dr Hcinrich Suter: "Diese Am(fahe witrde 1G70 ditrch Fernuit ernnt^rt, der sie mit seinen eigenen algebraischep Untersuchungen und Erfindungen ^asstattete," 54 DIOPHANTOS OF AT.KXAXDRIA. after his death. S. Fermat tells us in the preface that this publication of Fermat's notes to Diophantos was part of an attempt to collect together from his letters and elsewhere his contributions to mathematics. The "Doctrinae Analj'ticae In- uentum nouum" is a collection made by Jacobus de Billy from various letters which Fermat sent to him at different times. The notes upon Diophantos' problems, which his son hopes will prove of value very much more than commensurate with their bulk, were (he says) collected from the margin of his copy of Diophantos, From their brevity they were obviously intended for the benefit of experts \ or even perhaps solely for Fermat's own, he being a man who preferred the pleasure which he had in the work itself to all considerations of the fame which might follow therefrom. Fermat never cared to publish his investiga- tions, but was always perfectly ready, as we see from his letters, to acquaint his friends and contemporaries with his results. Of the notes themselves this is not the place to speak in detail. This edition of Diophantos is rendered valuable only by the additions in it due to Fermat; for the rest it is a mere reprint of that of 1621. So far as the Greek text is concerned it is very much inferior to the first edition. There is a far greater number of misprints, omissions of words, confusions of numerals; and, most serious of all, the brackets which Bachet inserted in the edition of 1621 to mark the insertion of words in the text are in this later edition altogether omitted. These imperfec- tions have been already noticed by Nesselmannl Thus the reprinted edition of 1670 is untrustworthy as regards the text. ^ Lectori Beneuolo, p. iii. : "Doctis quibus tantum pauca sufficiunt, harum obseruationum auctor scribebat, vel potius ipse sibi scribens, his studiis exerceii malebat quam gloriari ; adco autem ille ab omni ostentationo alienus erat, vt nee lucubratioues suas ty]iie mandari curauerit, ct suonim qiiandoquc resjionsorum autographa nullo scruato exemplari pctentibus vitro miserit ; iiorunt scilicet ple- rique celeberrimorum huius saeculo Geomctrarum, quam libenter ille et quaut& bumanitate, sua iis inuenta patefecerit." 2 "Was dieser Abdruck an iiusserer Eleganz gewounen hat (denn die Ba- chet'sche Ausgcbe ist niit ausserst unangcnehmen, nanientlich Griechischeu Lettern gedruckt), das hat sie an inncrm Werthe in Bczug auf den Text ver- loren. Sie ist nicht bloss voller Diuckfchler in cinzelnen Worten und Zeichen (z. B. durchgehends ir statt "?>), 900) sondern audi ganze Zeilen sind ausgelassen Oder doppelt gedruckt, (z. B. iii. 12 cine Zeile doppelt, iv, 25 eine doppelt und THE WRITERS UPON DIOPHANTOS. 55 I omit here all mention of works which are not directly upon Diophantos (e.g. the so called "Translation" by Stevin and Alb. Girard). We have accordingly to pass from 1670 to 1810 before we find another extant work directly upon Diophantos. In 1810 was published an excellent translation (with additions) of the fragment upon Polygonal Numbers by Poselger : Dio- phantus von Alexandrien iiher die Polygonal-Zahlen. Uebersetzt mit Zusdtzen von F. Th. Poselger. Leipzig, 1810. Lastly, in 1822 Otto Schulz, professor in Berlin, published a very meritorious German translation with notes: Diupliantus von Alexandria arithmetische Aufgahen nebst dessen Schrift iiber die Pohjgon-Zahlen. Aus dem Griechischen ilbersetzt iind mit Anmerkungen begleitet von Otto Schulz, Professor am Berlinisch- Colnischen Gymnasium zum grauen Kloster. Berlin, 1822. In der Schlesingerschen Buck- und Musikhandlung. The former work of Poselger is with the consent of its author incorporated in Schulz's edition along with his own translation and notes upon the larger treatise, the Arithmetics. According to Nessel- mann Schulz was not a mathematician by profession: he pro- duced, however, a most excellent and painstaking edition, with notes chiefly upon the matter of Diophantos and not on the text (with the exception of a very few emendations) : notes which, almost invariably correct, help much to understand the author. Schulz's translation is based upon the edition of Bachet's text published in 1670; so that nothing has been done for the Greek text since the original edition of Bachet (1621). I have now mentioned all the extant books which have been written directly upon Diophantos. Of books here omitted which are concerned with Diophantos indirectly, i.e. those which reproduce the substance of his solutions or solve his gleich hinterher eine ausgelassen, rv. 52 eine doppclt, v. 11 eine aup^'clnpsen, desgleichen v. 14, 2.5, 33, vi. 8, 13 und so weiter), die Zalileu Verstiimmcit, was aber das Aergste ist, die Bacbet'schen kritischen Zeicheu sind fast iiberall, die Klammer durcbgtingig weggefallen, so dass diese Ausgabe als Text des Diophant vcillig unbrauchbar geworden ist," p. 283. Accordingly Cantor errs when he says "Die beste Textamijabe ist die von Bachet de Meziriac mit Anmerkungen von Format. Toulouse, 1G70." (Getch. p. 31)0.) 56 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. problems or the like of them by different methods a list has been given at the outset. As I have already mentioned a statement that Joseph Auria of Naples wrote circa 1580 a translation of Diophantos which was found (presumably in MS. form) in the library of one Carl von Montchall, it is necessary here to give the indications we have of lost works upon Dio- phantos. First, we find it asserted by Vossius (as some have understood him) that the Englishman John Pell wrote an un- published Commentary upon Diophantos. John Pell was at one time a professor of mathematics at Amsterdam and gave lectures there on Diophantos, but what Vossius says about his commentary may well be only a recommendation to undertake a commentary, rather than a historical assertion of its comple- tion. Secondly, Schulz states in his preface that he had lately found a note in Schmeisser's Orthodidaktih der Mathematik that Hofrath Kausler by command of the Russian Academy pre- pared an edition of Diophantos \ Of this nothing whatever is known; if ever written, this edition must have been only for private use at St Petersburg. I find a statement in the New American Cyclopaedia (New York, D. Appleton and Company), vol. VI. that "a complete translation of his (Diophantos') works into English was made by the late Miss Abigail Lousada, but has not been published." ^ The whole passage of Schmcisser is: "Die mechanische, geistlose Behand- lung der Algebra ist ins besondere von Herru Hofrath Kausler stark geriigt worden. In der Vorrede zu seiner Ausgabe des Vjlakerschen ExempcUmclis beginnt er so : ' Seit mehreren Jahren arbeitete ich fiir die Kussisch-Kaiserliche Akademie der Wissenschaften Diophants unsterbliches Werk iiber die Arithnietik aus, und fand darin einen solchen Schatz von den feinsten, scharfsinnigsten algebraischcn Auflosungen, dass mir die mechanische, geistlose Methode der neuen Algebra mit jedem Tage mehr ekelte u. s. w.' " (p. 33.) CHAPTER IV. NOTATION AND DEFINITIONS OF DIOPHANTOS. § 1. As it is my inteution, for the sake of brevity and perspicuity, to make use of the modern algebraical notation in giving my account of Diophantos' problems and general methods, it will be necessary to describe once for all the machinery which our author uses for working out the solutions of his problems, or the notation by which he expresses the relations which would be represented in our time by algebraical equations, the extent to which he is able to manipulate unknown quantities, and so on. Apart, however, from the necessity of such a description for the proper and adequate comprehension of Diophantos, the general question of the historical develop- ment of algebraical notation possesses great intrinsic interest. Into the general history of this subject I cannot enter in this essay, my object being the elucidation of Diophantos ; I shall accordingly in general confine myself to an account of his notation solely, except in so far as it is interesting to compare it with the corresponding notation of his editors and (in certain cases) that of other writers, as for example certain of the early Arabian algebraists. § 2. First, as to the representation of an unknown quantity. The unknown quantity, Avhich Diophantos calls ttXj/^o? fiovdBoiu aXoyov i.e. "a number of units of which no account is given, or undefined " is denoted throughout (def. 2) by what is uni- versally printed in the editions as the Greek letter ? with an accent, thus ?', or in the form s°'. This symbol in verbal description he calls u aptOfxo'^, "the number" i.e. by inipli- 58 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. cation, the number par excellence of the problem in question. (In the cases where the symbol is used to denote inflected forms, e.g. accusative singular or dative plural, the terminations which would have been added to the stem of the full word dpi6fi6<i are printed above the symbol 9 in the manner of an exponent, thus 9'' (for dpidfxov, as r' for t6v), <?°", the symbol being in addition doubled in the plural cases, thus 99°'', 99°"'^ 99"" 99°'« for dpidfjLOL K.T.X. When the symbol is used in practice, the coefficient is expressed by putting the required Greek numeral immediately after it, thus 99°' Td corresponds to 11a-, 9'a to sc and so on. Respecting the symbol 9 as printed in the editions it is clear that, if 9' represents dpiOixo^, this sign must be different in kind from all the others described in the same definition, for they are clearly mere contractions of the corresponding names\ The opinion which seems to have been universally held as to the nature of the symbol of the text by the best writers on Diophantos is that of Nesselmann and Cantor ^ Both authors tell us that the final sigma is used to denote the unknown quantity representing upi6p6<i, the complete word for it ; and they imply in the passages referred to that this final sigma corresponds exactly to the x of modern equations, and that we have here the beginning of algebraical notation in the strict sense of the term, notation, that is, which is purely conventional and shows in itself no necessary connection be- tween the symbol and the thing denoted by it. I must observe, however, that Nesselmann has in another place ' corrected the impression which the reader might have got from the first passage referred to, that he regarded the use of the sign for dpi6fji6<; as a step towards genuine algebraical notation. He makes the acute observation that, as the symbol occurs in many places where it represents dpidfio^ used in the ordinary untechnical sense, and is therefore not exclusively used to designate the unknown quantity, the technical dpi6fi6<i, it must after all be more of the nature of an abbreviation than ' Vide infra S", k", 55", &c. contractions for Suva/jLi^, kv^os, dwafioSufafxis, &c. •■! Nesselmann, pp. 290, 291. Cantor, p. 400. 3 pp. 300, 301, NOTATION AND DEFINITIONS OF DIOPHANTOS. 59 an algebraical symbol. This view is, I think, undoubtedly correct ; but the question now arises : bow can the final signia of the Greek alphabet be an abbreviation for dpiOfio^ ? The difficulty of answering this question suggests a doubt which, so far as I am aware, has been expressed by no writer upon Diophantos up to the present time. Is the sign, which Bachet'.s text gives as a final sigma, really the final sigma at all ? Nesselmann and Cantor seem never to have doubted it, for they both assign a reason why the final 9 was appropriated for the designation of the unknown quantity, namely that it was the only letter of the Greek alphabet which was not already in use as a numeral. The question was suggested to me princi- pally by the doubt whether the final sigma, 9, was developed as distinct from the form cr as early as the date of the MS. of Diophantos which Bachet used, or rather as early as the first copy of Diophantos, for the explanation of the sign is given by the author himself in the text of the second definition.\ This being extremely doubtful, if not absolutely impossible, in what way is its representation as a final sigma in Bachet's text to be accounted for ? The MS. from which Bachet edited his Greek text is in the Bibliotheque Natiouale, Paris, and I have not yet been able to consult it : but, fortunately, in a paper by M. Kodet in the Journal Asiatique (Janvier 1878), I found certain passages quoted by the author from Diophantos for the purpose of comparison with the algebra of Mohammed ibn Musti Al-Kharizmi. These passages M, Rodet tells us that he copied accurately from the identical MS. which Bachet used. On examination of these passages I found that in all but two cases of the occurrence of the sign for (ipi6/j.6<; it was given as the final sigma. In one of the other cases he writes for 6 dpiOfiof (in this instance untechnical) the abbreviation o d\ and in the other case we find ijTj"' for dpt6fj.oi In this last place Bachet reads 99°'. But the same symbol cji|" which M. Rodet gives is actually found in three places in Bachet's own edition. (1) In his note to iv. 3 he gives a reading from his MS. which he has corrected in his own text and in which thr signs i\d and qi|^ occur. They must here necessarily signify npidp.6<i d and dpidfiol 7) respectively because, although tlic sense rcciuire.s GO DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. 1 8 the notation corresponding to - , - , not x, 8x, we know, not only from Bachet's direct statement but also from the trans- lation of certain passages by Xylauder, that the sign for dpi6fjb6<; is in the MSS. very often carelessly written for dpid/MoaTov and its sign. (2) In the text of iv. 14 there is a sentence (marked by Bachet as interpolated) which has the expression l| ij? where again the context shows that i|L| is for dpcO/xoL (3) At the beginning of v. 12 there is a difficulty in the text; and Bachet notes that his MS. has o SfjrXaaifoi' avroO l|... where a Vatican MS. reads 6 hijfkaa-iwv avrov dpLdjjiov... Xylander also notes that his MS. had firjTe o hiir\.aaL(ov avrov ap.... It is thus clear that the MS. which Bachet used sometimes has the sign for dpiOfMo^; in a form which is at least sufficiently like q to be taken for it. This last very remarkable variation as com- pared with 9?°' seemed at first sight inexplicable ; but oq refe- rence to Gardthausen, Griechische Falaeur/raphie, I found under the head " hieroglyphisch-conventionell " an abbreviation 9, 9^ for dpidfio'^, dpiO^JbOL, which the author gives as occurring in the Bodleian MS. of Euclid '. The same statement is made by Lehmann'^ {Die tacky graphischen Ahkurzungen der grie- chischen Handscltriften, 1880) who names as a sign for dpcd^io^, found in the Oxford MS. of Euclid, a curved line similar to that used as an abbreviation for Kai He adds that the ending is placed above it, and the simple sign is doubled for the plural. Lehmann's facsimile of the sign is like the form given by Gardthausen, except that the angle in the latter is a little more rounded by Lehmann. The form ijq°' above mentioned as given by M. Rodet and Bachet is also given by Lehmann with a remark that it seems to be only a modification of the other. If we take the form as given by Gardthausen, the change necessary is the very slightest possible. Thus by assuming this conventional abbreviation for dpi,6/j.6<i it is easy to see 1 D'Orvillo MSH. X. 1 inf. 2, 30. " p. 107: "Von Sigeln, welchcn ich audi nnderwarts begegnet bin, sind zu uennen apiOixb^, das in der Oxfordcr Euclidhandsclirift niit eiucr der Note Kal ahnlichen Schlangenlinie bezeicbuet wird. Die Enduug wird dariiber gesetzt, zur Bezejchuung des Plurals wird das ejnfache Zeichen verdoppelt," NOTATION AND DEFINITIONS OF DIOrHANTOS. 01 how it was thought by Bachet to be a final sigma and Iwiw also it might be taken for the isolated form given by M. Rodet. As I have already implied, I cannot think that the symbol used by Diophantos is really a final sigma, 9. That the con- ventional abbreviation in the Euclid MS. and the sign in Diophantos are identical is, I think, certain; and that neither of the two is a final sigma must be clear if it can be proved that one of them is not. Having consulted the Ms. of the first ten problems of Diophantos in the Bodleian Library, I conclude that the symbol in this work cannot be a final sigma for the following reasons. (1) The sign in the Bodleian MS. is written thus, '<^° for dpcdfMO'i; and though the final sigma is used uni- versally in this MS. at the end of words there is, besides a slight difference in shape between the two, a very distinct difference in size, the sign for dpc6/ji6<: being always very much larger. There are some cases in which the two come close together, e.g. in the expression eh '<^° Tee, and the difference is very strongly marked. (2) As I have shown, the breathing is prefixed before the sign. This, I think, shows clearly that the symbol was regarded as an abbreviation of certain letters be- ginning with a the first letter of dpiO/xo^. It is interesting also to observe that in the Bodleian MS. there are certain cases in which dpcdfio^ in its untechnical, and dpt0fj,6<; in its technical sense follow each other as in era^a to tov Seurepov 'S^ dptdfiov et'o's, where (contrary to what might be expected) the sign is used for the untechnical dpidfjio'i and the other is written in full. This is a very remarkable piece of evidence to show that the sign is an abbreviation and in no sense an algebraical symbol. More remarkable still as evidence of this view is the fact that in the same MS. the luord dpi6fi6<; in the definition 6 Be firjBeu tovtcop toov ISicofjidTayv Kr'r}adfievo<;...e-)(Oiv he... dpidfjb6<; KaXeiTUL is itself denoted by the symbol, so that in the MS. there is absolutely no difference between the full name and the symbol. My conclusion therefore being (1) that the sign given as ? in Bachet's text of Diophantos is not really tlic final .sigma, (2) that it is an abbreviation of some kind for dpiOfMot, the question arises. How was this abbreviation arrived at ? If it is 62 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. uot a hieroglyph (and I have cot yet found any evidence of its hieroglyphic origin), I would suggest that it might very well be a corruption, after combination, of the two first letters of the word, Alpha and Rho. Before I go on to state when and how I conceive this contraction may liave come about, I may observe that, given its possibility, my supposition has, it seems to me, every- thing in its favour. (1) It would explain, and is countenanced by, the solitary occurrence in M. Kodet's transcription of the contraction a*. (2) It would also explain the remarkable variation in the few words quoted from Xylander's note on v. 12, fMT]T€ 6 hiTrKaaioiv avTov ap fio a... These words are important because in no other sentence which he quotes in the Greek does any abbreviation of dpt9iJL6<i occur. As his work is a Latin translation he rarely quotes the original Greek at all: hence we might have doubted whether the sign for dpi6fx6(; occurred in his MS. in the same form as in Bachet's. That it did occur in the same form is, however, clear from the note to III. 12\ That is to say, both ap and <h are used in one and the same MS. to signify apt^/xo?. This circumstance is easily explained on my hypothesis ; and I do not see how it can be explained on any other. But (3) the most important advantage that my theory would hav« is that it would establish uniformity between the different abbreviations used by Diophantos. It would show him to have proceeded on one invariable principle in fixing those abbreviations which we should naturally have expected to be parallel. Diophantos, in fact, appears to have proceeded thus. He took in all cases the first letter of the corresponding words i.e. a, B, k, fi. Then, as these could not be used alone for the reason that they all represented numbers, he added another letter to each. Now, as it happened, the second letter in each of the four words named occurred later in the 1 In tills problem it evidently occurred wrongly instead of the sign for the fraction apiOfioarbv (as was commonly the case in the mss.), for after stating that the context showed the reading apidfids to be wrong Xy lander says: "Est sane in Graeco nota senarii S". Sed locum habere non potest." Now s and r are so much alike that what was taken for one might easily be taken for the other. NOTATION AND DEFINITIONS OF Dl< )|'HANToS. Q:) alphabet than the respective first letters. Thus a with p addctl, B with V added, k with v added, and /i with o added gave abbre- viations luhich could not he confounded with particidar numbers. No doubt, if the two letters in each case were not written in the same line by Diophantos, but the second raised above the other, the signs might, unless they or the separate letters were dis- tinguished by some special marks, have been confused with numerical fractions. There would however be little danger of this ; such confusion would be very unlikely to arise, for (a) the context would nearly always render it impossible, as also would (6) the constant recurrence of the same sign for a constantly recurring term, coupled with the fact that, if on any particular occasion it denoted a numerical fraction, it could and would naturally be expressed in lower terms. Thus, if 8", /c", /i° were numerical fractions, they would be as unlikely to be written thus as we should be unlikely to write -^, ■^, ^. Indeed the only sign of the four which, written with the second letter placed as an exponent to the second, could reasonably be supposed to represent a numerical fraction is a", which miglit mean yi^. But, by a curious coincidence, confusion is avoided in this case ; and the contraction, which I suppose to have taken place, might very well be an expedient adopted for the purpose : thus we may have here an explanation why only one of the four signs ap, 3u, Kv, fio is contracted, j (4) Again, if we assume <^ to be a contraction of ap, we can explain the addition of terminations to mark cases and number in the place where the second letter of the other abbreviations is written. The sign '<^ having no letter superposed originally, this addition of terminations was rendered practicable without resulting in any confusion. On its convenience it is unnecessary to enlarge, because it is clear that the symbol could then be used instead of the full word far more frequently than the others. Thus oblique cases of Bvvafii'i are written in full where oblique cases of apidfi6<; would be abbreviated. For 8", /c", fi° did not admit of the addition of terminations without possible confusion and certain clumsiness. A few words will suffice to explain my views concerning the evolution of the sign for dpid^xo^. There are two alternatives possible. (1) Diophantos may not himself have made the con- 64 DTOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. traction at all ; he may have written the two letters in full. In that case I suppcse the sign to he a cursive contraction used by scribes. I conceive it would then have come about through a tolerably obvious intermediate form, 'p. The change from this to either of the two forms of the symbol used in MSS, for dpid/j-o^; is very slight, in one case being the loss of a stroke, in the other the loss of the loop of the p. (2) Diophantos may have used a sign approximately, if not exactl}^ like the form which we now find in the MSS. Now Gardthausen divides cursive writing into two kinds, which he calls " Majuskelcursive " and " Minuskelcursive." One or other of these terms would be applied to a type of writing according as the uncial or cursive element predominates. That in which the uncial element pre- dominates is the " Majuskelcursive," which is intermediate be- tween the uncial and the cursive as commonly understood. Gardthausen gives examples of MSS. which show the gradations through which writing passed from one to the other. Among the si^ecimens of the " Majuskelcursive " writing he mentions a Greek papyrus, the date of which is 154 A.D., i.e. earlier than the time of Diophantos. From this MS. he quotes a contraction for the two letters a and p, namely up. This may very well be the way in which Diophantos wrote the symbol ; and, after being copied by a number of scribes successively, it might very easily come into the MSS. which we know in the slightly simplified form in which we find it\ 1 Much of what I have written above concerning the symbol for dpi6/MS appeared in an article "On a point of notation in the Arithmetics of Dio- phantos," which I contributed to the Journal of Philolofjy (Vol. xin. No. 25, pp. 107 — 113). Since that was written I have considered the subject more thoroughly, and I have been able to profit by a short criticism of my theory, as propounded in the article alluded to, by Mr James Gow in his recent History of Greek Mathematics (Camb. Univ. Press, 1884). In the Addenda thereto Mr Gow states that he does not think my suggestion that the supposed final sigma is a contraction of the first two letters of apiOfi-os is true, for three reasons. It is right that I should answer these objections in this place. I will take them in order. 1. Mr Gow argues:— "The contraction must be supposed to be as old as the time of Diophantus, for he describes the symbol as tA s instead of to, or Tw ap. Yet Diophantus can hardly (as Mr Heath admits) have used cursive characters." Upon this objection I will remark that I do not think the descrip- NOTATION AND DEFINITIONS OV DMniANToS. C". In the following paq^es, as it is impossible to say for cort;iin what this sign really is, I shall not hesitate, where it is neces- tion of the symbol as to s proves that the supposed contraction must be ns oM as the time of Piophantos himself. I see no reason, even, why Diophnnfoi liimself shoiikl not have written Kal lanv avrov cnjfxe'ov to dp. For (a) it seems to me most natural tliat the article should be in the same number as ffrniuoy. Mr Gow might, I think, argae with equal force that the Greek should run, kcI ((TTiv wuTov ar]/M€7a ra dp. And yet o-nixeTov is not disputed. Saj)posing, then. that we have assumed on other grounds that Diophantos used the first two 1( tters, contracted or uncontracted, of apiOp.6i as his symbol for it, I do not seo that the use of the article in the singular constitutes any objection to our assumption. (Ji) Besides the censideration that to dp is perfectly possible grammatically, we have yet other evidence for its possibility in expressions which we actually find in the text. The symbol for the fifth power of the unknown, or for 5vvaiJ.6Kv^os, is described thus: Kal {<xtiv avrov arjftuov t6 ii twiarjixov /^cra v, ok". In this case much more than in the supposed case of dp should we have expected the plural article with 5k instead of the singular ; but 5k iTria-rjfiov ?xo»'to i* is in apposition with ok" and is looked upon as a single expression, and therefore preceded by the singular article to. If we give full weight to these considerations, it must, I think, be admitted that Mr Gow's conclusion that the contraction must be as old as the time of Diophantoa, whether true or not, is certainly not established by his argument from the description of the symbol as tA r. Hence, as one link in the reasoning em- bodied in Mr Gow's first objection fail=;, the olijection itself breaks down. Mr Gow appeai-s to have misunderstood me w^hen he attributes to me tlic inconsistency of supposing Diophantos to have used cursive characters, while in another place I had disclaimed such a supposition. It will be sufficiently clear from the explanation which I have given of the origin of the contraction that I am very far from assuming that Diophantos used cursive characters such as we now use in writing Greek. At the same time it is possible that Mr Gow's apparent mistake as to my meaning may be due to my own .inadvertence in saying (in the article above-mentioned) "If it [the symbol] is not a hiero- glyph (and I have not found any evidence of its hieroglyphic origin), I would suggest that it might very well be a corruption of the two letters dp" (printed thifs), where, however, I did not mean the cursive letters any more than uncials. 2. I now pass to Mr Gow's second objection to my theory. "The abbreviation s° for dpi.0p.6s in its ordinary sense is very rare indeed. It is not found in the mss. of Nicoraachus or Pappus, where it might most readily be expected. It may therefore be due only to a scribe who had some reminiscence of Diophantus." The meaning of this last sentence does not seem quite clear. I presume Mr Gow to mean "/h the rare cases where it does occur, it may be due, &c." I do not know that I am concerned to prove that to" for dpiOixos is of very frequent occurrence in mss. other than those of Diophanlon. Still the form (,, which I have no hesitation in stating to be the same as t-,. occurs often enough in the Oxford lis. of Euclid to make Gardthausen and H. D. J CG DIOPHAXTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. sary to designate it, to call it the final sigma for convenience' Lebmann notice it. And, even if its use in that ms. is due to a scribe wbo bad some reminiscence of Diophantos, I do not see that this consideration affects my tbeory in the least. In fact, it is not essential for my theory that tliis si^n should occur in a single instance elsewhere than in Diophantos. It is really quite sufficient for my purpose that o," occurs in Dioi>hantos for apiOfwi in its ordiiKn-y sense, which I hold that I have proved. 3. Mr Gow's tliird objection is stated thus: "If s is for dp. then, by analogy, the full symbol should be s' (like 5", k'") and not j°." (a) I must first remark that I consider that arguments from analogy are inapplicable in this case. The fact is that there are some points in which all the five signs of which I have been speaking are undoubtedly analogous, and others in which some are not; therefore to argue from analogy here is futile, because it would be equally easy to establish by that means either of two opposite conclusions. I might, with the same justice as Mr Gow, argue backwards that, since there is undoubtedly one point in which s° and 5" are not analogous, namely the superposition in one case of terminations, in the other case of the second letter of the word, therefore the signs must be differently explained : a result which, so far as it goes, would favour my view, (b) Besides, even if we admit the force of Mr Gow's argument by analogy, is it true that s' (on the supposition that s is for dp) is analogous to 5" at all? I think not; for s does not corres- pond to 5, but (on my supposition) to 8v, and I only partially corresponds to v, inasmuch as t is the tliinl letter of the complete word in one case, in the other i; is the second letter, (c) As a matter of fact, however, I maintain that my suggestion does satisfy analogy in one, and (I think) the most important respect, namely that (as I have above explained) Diophantos proceeded on one and the same system in making his abbreviations, taking in each case the two first letters of the word, the only difference being that in one case only are the two letters contracted into one sign. Let us now enquire whether my theory will remove the difficulties stated by Mr Gow on p. 108 of his work. As reasons for doubting whether the symbol for dpid/xoi is really a final sigma, he states the following. "It must be remembered : (1) that it is only cursive Greek which has a final siijma, and that the cursive form did not come into use till the 8th or 9th century : (2) that inflexions are appended to Diophantus' symbol s' (e.g. s°", ss°S etc.), and that his other symbols (except f) are initial letters or syllables. The objection (1) might be disposed of by the fact that the Greeks had two uncial sigmas C and 1, one of which might have been used by Dioi)hantus, but I do not see my way to dismissing objection (2)." First, with regard to objection (1) Mr Gow rightly says that, supposing the sign were really s, it would be possible to dismiss this objection. On my tlieory, however, it is not necessai-y even to dismiss it : it does not exist. Secondly, my theory will dismiss objection (2). "Diophantus' other symbols (except /;>) are inititil letters or syllables." I answer "So is to." "Inflexions are appended to Diophantus' symbol s'." I answer "True; but the nature of the sign itself made this convenient," as I have above explained. NOTATION AND DKriNITIoNS uV 1 )li .pll VNToS. CyJ sake, subject to the remarks which 1 have here ma^le on the subject. § 3. Next, as regards the notatiou Avhich Diupliaiitus used to express the different powers of the unknown quantity, i.e. corresponding to x^, x^ and so on. The square of tlie unknown is called by Diophantos SviafiK: and denoted by the abbrevia- tion* B". Now tiie word Bvvafiiq ("power") is commonly used in Greek to express a square number. The first occurrence of the word in its technical sense is probably as early as the second half of the fifth century B.C. Eudemos uses it in quoting from Hippokrates (no doubt word for word) who lived about that time. The dilBference iu use between the words Bvvafj.i<; and T€Tpnycovo<i corresponds, in Cantor's view^, to the difference l)etween our terms "second power" and "square" respectively, the first having an arithmetical signification as referring to a number, the second a geometrical reference to a plane surface- area. The difference which Diophantos makes in their use is, however, not of this kind, and Sui/a/i/.? in a geometrical sense, is not at all uncommon; hence the correctness of Cantor's suggestion is not at all certain. Both terms are used by Diophantos, but in very different senses. hvvafii<i, as we have said, or the contraction 8" stands for the second power of the unknown quantitt/. It is the square of the unknown, apidfio'i or '<h°, only and is never used to express the square of any other, i.e. any known number. For the square of any known number Diophantos uses TeTpdj(ovo<;. The higher powers of the un- known quantity which Diophantos makes use of he calls Kvfio<:, BvvafioSvva/jic<;, Bvva/j,6Kv^o<;, KVfS6Kv/3o<i, corresponding respec- tively to x^, X*, x\ a.". Beyond the sixth power he does not go, having no occasion for higher powers in the .solutions of his 1 I should observe with respect to the mark over the v that it is given in the Greek text of Bachet as a circumtiex accent printed in the form ~. By writers on Diophantos later than Bachet the sign has been variously printed as 3", a" or 5". I have generally denoted it by 5", except in a few special cases, when quoting or referring to writers who use either of the other forms. The same remark applies to /tt°, the abbreviation for ixovdSn, as well as to the circumflex written above the denominators of Cheek numerical fractions piven in this chapter as examples from the text of Diophantos. ' Gesrhichte der Mtitheiiuitik, p. 178. GS DIOPH\NTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. problems. For these powers he uses the abbreviations k^, ht'\ S/c", kkP respectively. There is a difference between Diophantos' use of the complete words for the third and higher powers and that of Bvvafit<;, namely that they are not always restricted like Bvvafxt<; to powers of the unknown, but may denote powers of ordinary known numbers as well. This is probably owing to the fact that, while there are two words hvvafii<i and TeTpdywvo^ which both signify "square", there is only one word for a third power, namely kv^o'?. It is important, however, to observe that the abbreviations «", 8S", 8/c", /c/c" are, like Bvva/j,i<i and S", onlij used to denote powers of the unknown. It is therefore ob- viously inaccurate to say that Diophantos "denotes the square of a number {hvvajxi^) by S", the cube by «", and so on", the only number of which this could be said being the 9' {dpi,6fM6<;) of the particular problem. The coefficients which the different powers of the unknown have are expressed by the addition of the Greek letters denoting numerals (as in the case of dpidfj.o'i itself), thus Sk^ kW corresponds to 26ir^ Thus in Diophantos' system of notation the signs 8" and the rest represent not merely the exponent of a power like the 2 in x^, but the whole ex- pression, x\ There is no obvious connection between the symbol S" and the symbol 9' of which it is the square, as there is be- tween x^ and X, and in this lies the great inconvenience of the notation. But upon this notation no advance was made by Xylander, or even by Bachet and Fermat. They wrote N (abbreviation of Numerus) for ?' of Diophantos, Q {Quadratas) for 8", C for «" (cubus) so that we find, for example, \Q■\■oN='l^f, corresponding to x^ -\- 5x= 24. Thus these writers do in fact no more than copy Diophantos. We do, however, find other symbols used even belore the publication of Xylander's Dioiiliantos, e g. in 1572, the date of Bombelli's Algebra. Bombelli denotes the unknown and its powers by the symbols i, t, ^, and so on. But it is certain that up to this time the common symbols had been Ji {Radix or Res), Z {Zensus i.e. square), C {Cuhvs). Apparently the first important step towards x'^, x^ &c. was taken by Vieta, who wrote Aq, Ac, Aqq, &c. (abbreviated fur A quadratus and so on) for the powers of A. This system, besides showing in itself the connection between the difforfut. NOTATION AND DEFINITIONS OF DIOI'HANTOS. GO powers, has the infinite advantage that by means of it we can use in one and the same solution any number of unknown quantities. This is absolutely impossible with the notati(.n used by Diophantos and the earlier algebraists. Diophantos does in fact never use more than one unknown quantity in the solution of a problem, namely the apLdfi6<i ur <;' . § 4. Diophantos has no symbol for the operation of multi- plication: it is rendered unnecessary by the fact tiiat his coefficients are all definite numerals, and the results are simply put down without any preliminary step wdiich would make a symbol essential. On the ground that Diophantos uses only numerical expressions for coefficients instead of general symbols, it would occur to a superficial observer that there must be a great want of generality in his methods, and consequently that these, being (as might appear) only applicable to the particular numbers which the author uses, are necessarily interesting only as clever puzzles, but not general enough to be valuable to the serious student. To this objection I reply that, in the first place, it was absolutely impossible that Diophantos should have used any other than numerical coefficients for the reason that the available symbols of notation were already employed, the letters of the Greek alphabet always doing duty as numerals, with the exception of the final <?, which Diophantos was supposed to have used to represent the unknown quantity. In the second place T do not admit that the use of numerical coefficients only makes his 'solutions any the less general. This will be clearly seen when I come to give an account of his problems ami methods. Next as to Diophantos' symbols for the operations of Addition and Subtraction. For the former no symbol at all is used: it is expressed by mere juxta-position, thus K^dh^ly^i corresponds to x^ + V^x" + ox. In this expression, however, there is no absolute term, and the addition of a simple numeral, as for instance /3, directly after e, the coefficient of vv, would cause confusion. This ."act makes it necessary to have some term to indicate an absolute term in contradistinction to the variable terms. For this purpose Diophantos uses the word ^ovdha, or units, and denotes them after his usual manner by the abbre- viation lA?. The number of monads is expressed as a c«<offiiipnf. DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Thus correspouding to the above expression x^ i-ISou^ + 5x+ 2 we should find in Diophantus «'' a 8" r-y 99 e fi° $. As Bachet uses the sign + for addition, he has no occasion for a distinct symbol to mark an absolute term. He would accordingly write IC +1'3Q + 5X+2. It is worth observing, however, that the Italians do use a symbol in this case, namely K (Xumero), the first power of the unknown being with them li (Rudice). Cossali* makes an interesting comparison between the terms used by Diophantos for the successive powers of the unknown and those employed by the Italians after their instructors, the Arabians. He observes that Fra Luca, Tartaglia, and Cardan begin their scale of powers from the power 0, not from the power 1, as does Diophantos, and compares the scales thus : Scala Diojantea. Sc((la Anibii. 1 . Numero. . .il Noto. X 1. Numero... riguoto. 2. Cosa, Radice, Lato. X- 2. Podesta. :?. Censo. .!■' '6. Ciibo. 4. Cubo. .T^ 4. Podesta-Podesta. 5. Censo di Censo. ^5 5. Podesta Cubo. C). Eelato V. x* 6. Cubo-Cubo. 7. Ccuso di Cubo, o Cubo di Censo. x7 7 S. Relato2«. .1-8 8 1). Censo di Censo di Ceuso. .1-9 [) 10. Cubo di Cujo. and so on. So far, however, as this is meant to be a comparison between Diophantos and the early Arabian algebraists them- selves (as the title Scala Araba would seem to in»ply), there appears to be no reason why Cossali should not have placed some term to express Diophantos fiovdBe<i iu the same line with Numero in the other scale, and moved tlie numbers 1, 2, 3, S:c. one place upwards in the first scale, or downwards ' Upon Wallis' comparison of the Diophantiue with the Arabian scale Cossali remarks: "ma egli non ha riflettuto a due altre diflerenze tra le scale medesime. La prima si e, che laddove Diofanto denomina con singolarita Numero 11 numero ignoto, denominanJo Monade il numero dato di compara- zione : gli antichi italiani degli arabi seguaci denominano questo il Numero ; e Radice, o IjuIo, o Cosa il numero sconosciuto. La scconda e, che Diofanto comincia la scala dal numero ignoto; e Fra Luca, Tartaglia, Cardano la in- coiiiinciano dal numero noto. Ecco le due scale di rincontro, onde meglio risaltino all" occhio le diffcrcnzc loro." i. p. I'.lo. i NOTATION AND DEFINITIONS <»K l)It>l'IfANT(»s. 71 in tlie secoiul. As Diopliantos does nut go "beyond the sixtli power, the hist three phices in the tirst scale are left blank. An examination of these two scales will show also that the generation of the successive powers dirt'ers in the two systems. The Diophantine terms for them are based on the addition of exponents, the Arabic on their multipliaition \ Thus the "cube- cube" means in ])iophantos of, in the Italian and Arabic system x". The first method of generation may (says Cossali) be described as the method by which each power is represented by the product of the two lesser powers which are nearest to it, the method of viidtiplication ; the second the method of elevation, i.e. the method which forms by raising to the second or third power all powers which can be so formed, or the ^ih, Cth, 8th, 9th, &c. The intermediate powers which cannot be so formed are called in Italian Relati. Thus the fifth power is Relato 1", x' is Relato 2", a-'" is Censo di Relato 1", .r" is Relato 3", and so on. Wall is calls these powers supevsolida, reproduced by Montucla as sursolides. For Subtraction Diophantos uses a symbol. His full terra for Negation is Xei-\\r.<;, corresponding to inrap^i<i, which denotes the opposite. Thus Xeiylrei (i.e. with the want of) stands for minus, and the symbol used to denote it in the MSS. is an inverted i/r or ^ (Def. 9 /cat t^? Xet>|re&)9 (njfietov yfr €X\nre<i Kara) vevov >>jt) with the top shortened. As Diophantos uses no distinct sign for +, it is clearly necessary, to avoid confusion, that all the negative terms in an expression should be placed together after all the positive terms. And so in fact he does place them^ Thus corresponding to x^ — ox' + Sx — 1, 1 This statement of Cossali's needs qualification however. There is at least one Arabian algebraist, Alkarkhi, the author of the Fakhri referred to above (pp. 24, 25), who uses the Diophantine system of powers of the unknown de- pending on the additioji of exponents. Alkarkhi, namely, expresses all powers of the unknown above the third by means of nUil, his term for tlie square, and ka% his term for the cube of the unknown, as follows. The fourth power is with hun mdl mdl, the fifth null Jca'b, the sixth ka'b ka'b, the seventh null mal ka'b, the eighth nial ka'b ka'h, the ninth ka'b ka'b ka'b, and bo on. » Dr Heinrich Suter however has the erroneous statement that Diopliantos would express j?-5x^ + 8.r - 1 by k" d /A «"« »• ij ^ M° «'. which is exactly what h« would not do. 72 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDKIA. Diophantos would write «" a s°"' ?; >//v S" e ^° d. With respect to this curious sign, given in the MSS. as ^ and described as an inverted truncated ■\\r, I must here observe tliat I do not believe it to be what it is represented as being. I do not believe that Diophantos used so fantastic a sign for minus as an inverted truncated -v/r. In the first place, an inverted -^^ seems too curious a sign, and too far-fetched. To one wlio was looking for a symbol to express mimis many others more natural and less fantastic than j/v must have suggested themselves. {Secondly, given that Diophantos used an inverted -x/r, why should he truncate it ? Surely that must have been unneces- sary ; Ave could hardly have expected it unless, without it, confusion was likely to arise; but ^ could hardly have been confused with anything. It seems to me that this very trunca- tion throws doubt on the symbol as we find it in the MS. Hence I believe that the conception of this symbol as an inverted truncated -^ is a mistake, and that the description of it as such is not Diophantos' description ; it appears to me to be an explanation by a scribe of a symbol which he did not under- stand*. It seems to me probable that the true explanation is the following : Diophantos proceeded in this case as in the others which we have discussed (the signs for apt^/xd?, ^vvaiJii<;, etc.). As in those cases he took for his abbreviation the first letter of the word with such an addition as would make confusion with numbers impossible (namely the second letter of the word, which in all happens to come later in the alphabet than the corresponding first letter), so, in seeking an abbreviation for \et>|rt9 and cognate inflected forms developed from Xtir, he first took the initial letter of the word. The uncial" form is A. Clearly A by itself would not serve his purpose, since it denotes a number. Therefore an addition is necessary. The second letter is E, but AE is equally a number. The second 1 I am not even sure that the description can be made to mean all that it is intended to mean. AXiWs scarcely seems to be sufliciently precise. Might it not be applied to ^ with any part cut off, and not only shortened at the top? * I adhere to the uncial form above for clearness' sake. If Diophantos used the "Majuskelcursive" form, the explanation will equally apply, the difference of form being for our purpose lU'Rlifiihle. NOTATION AND DEFINITIONS OF DIOl'llANTt )S. 7:{ letter of the stem Xnr is I, but Al is open to objectiuii \slnii so written. Hence Diophantos placed the I inside the A, thus, A. Of the possibility of this I entertain no doubt, because there are indubitable cases of combination, even in uncial writing, of two letters into one sign. I would refer in par- ticular to X, which is an uncial abbreviation for TAAANTON. Now this sign. A, is an inverted and truncated i/r (written in the uncial form, ^j; and we can, on this assumpti(tn, easily account for the explanation of the sign for minus which is given in the text. For Division it often happens that no symbol is necessary, i.e. in the cases where one number is to be divided by another which will divide it without a remainder. In other cases the division has to be expressed by a fraction, whether the divisor be an absolute number or contain the variable. Thus the case of Division comes under that of Fractions. To express nume- rical fractions Diophantos adopts a uniform system, which is also seen in other writers. The numerator he writes in the ordinary line like a number; then he places the denominator above the line to the right of the numerator, in the same place as we should write an exponent, usually placing a ciicumflex a-cent over the eud of it. Thus i| is represented by tf'^ , yJ^j^ is aP, -Win- is (v. 12) ^eTZT?""^", ^[\%' is (iv. 17) y.S'xicd^'^^'. Diophantos, however, often expresses fractions by simply putting iv fjLopiro or [lopiov between the numerator and the denominator, i.e. one number divided by another. Cf. IV, 29 pF-.^f ^ttS fiopiov HS^.fipixh, i.e. Vif/nV' ^^^'J "^'- -'^ /5-,^X ^^ p-opiw pK^.aKi, i.e. TyiC^o* There is a peculiarity in the way in which Diophan- tos expresses such complex fractions as ,.,,'• It will be best understood by giving a typical case. This jiarticular fraction Diopliantos writes thus, aoyXB^^^.u^, that is, it is as if he had written with our notation y^Y i. Instances of this - " - . fiH[)ii notation occur passim, cf. V. 2 T7r6i"'^.d^ is e(iuivalent to -p.f • Bachet reproduces Diophantos' notation by writing in the.se cases '/jY h ^^^^ iti h respectively. 74 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDHIA. But there is another kind of fraction, besides the purely numerical one, which is continually occurring in the Arith- metics, such fractions namely as involve the unknown quantity in some form or other in their denominators. The simplest case is that in which the denominator is simply a power of the unknown, 9'. Concerning fractions of this kind Diophantos says (Def. 3) "As fractions named after numbers have similar names to those of the numbers themselves (thus a third is named from three, a fourth from four), so the fractions ho- monymous with what are called dpiO/iot, or unknowns, are called after them, thus from dpi6fx6<; we name the fraction to dpiOfjioaTov [i.e. - from ;r], to Suvafioarov from BvvafiL<;, to Kv^oarov from Kv^o<i, to SwafjuoBwafioaTov from SuvafioBvva- /i.t<?, TO Bvva/xoKv/SoaTOv from Bwap-oKv^o^, and to kv^okv- ^oarov from Kv^oKv/So'i. And every such fraction shall have its symbol after the homonymous number with a line to indi- cate the species" (i.e. the order or power)*. Thus we find, for 8 . example, IV. 3, 77"*" corresponding to , or with the genitive termination of dpiOfioaTov, e.g., IV, 16, Xe''°^-^ or — . Cf. av^"-^ 250 or-V- ^iJe by side with the employment of the symbols to express fractions corresponding to -, —2, &c., we find the terms dpiOfioarov, Bwafioarov k.t.X. used in full : this is regularly the case when the numerator of the fraction itself contains a numerical fraction. Thus in v. 31 dptdfjioaTov d d^ corre- sponds to -^ and hwapLoarov T d^ to - ^ • Diophantos extends his use of fractions still further to more complicated ca.ses in which the numerator and denominator 1 The meaning of the last sentence is not quite clear. I am inclined to think there is something wrong with the text, which stands in Bachet as follows : ?$ft 5^ iKaarov avTwv iirl Toy< ofiuvi'ifiov dpiO/xov arjiii'iov ypdij.fj.r]v Ixo" SiaffT^Wovaav rb el5os. This he translates, "Habebit autem quaelibet pars a sibi cognomitie numero notarn et literam superscriptam quae speciem a specie distinguat."' Here apparently literam corresponds to ypdfifxr]v. XOTATIOX AND DKFIMTK t.NS OF UK )l'll ANTi )S. 7o may be compound expressions themselves, involving the un- known ([uantity. Thus, iv. 37, we liave /u." ^ ^ 9°'' «"''", i.e. ' — — . AVhen, however, tlie denominator is a compound ex- pression Diophantos uses the expedient which he adopts in the case of Large numbers occurring as numerator or denominator, namely, the insertion between the expressions denoting tlio numerator and denominator of the term iv fjLopi(p or fxoplov. Thus in VI. 13 we find, h" ^./u," j34>k iv fiopup B"6" a /x" "^ \ei\Jrei ., . . 60^-' + 2520 - .' ^, -'5 c>- c. - . ' sjc - - 5 s - r ^ 2j-' + ox- + ix + \ fiopiM o" a >i^ p /j.° a corresponding to ^ — ^^ . To connect the two sides of an equation Diophantos uses Avords (cro9 or i'ao9 iari, or the oblique cases of i<to<; when they are made necessary by grammatical construction. It would appear, at least from Bachet's edition of Diophantos, that the equations were put down in the ordinary course of writing, and that they were not placed in separate lines for each step in the process of simplification, being in fact written in the same way as the propositions of Euclid. We have, however, signs of a system by which the steps were tabulated in a manner very similar to that of modern algebraical work, s<^ that by means of a sort of skeleton of the procedure we get a kind of bird's-eye view of its course, in the manuscript of Dio- ])hantos which Bachet himself used. We have it on the authority of M. Rodet, who in an article in the Journal Asia- tique^ has occasion to quote certain passages from the text of J)iophantos, that to certain problems is attached a tabular view of the whole process, which Bachet has not in his editinn reproduced at all. M. Rodet gives from the MS. several in- iitances. In these we have equations set down in a form very like the modern, the two members being connected by the letter I (abbreviated for Xaoi) as the sign of e<iualit\'. Besides 1 Janvier, 1878. - Here again the abbreviation is explicable on the .same jirinciiik- as 11k»»c which I have previously discnssed. ( by itself means 10, but a distin^ishinp mark is ready to Land in the breathing' phmcd over it. 70 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. the equations written in this form there are on the left side words signifying the nature of tlie operation in passing from one particular step to the next. To illustrate this I will give the table after Rodet for the very simple problem i. 32. " To find two numbers whose sum, and the ditference of whose squares are given." (The sum is supposed to be 20, the dif- ference of squares is 80.) Diophantos assumes the difference of the two numbers themselves to be two dpidfioL I will put the Greek table on the left side, and on the right the modern equivalent. The operations will be easily understood. iKdeais s" /uoT : yuoif. set] virepox-f) si IX I ps>.^ Ixfpt(j/ji6i S a I p.o.-^ inrop^is ^Pp.oI? (^ po.q Put for the numbers x + 10, 10 - x. Squaring we have .r2+20x+ 100, x2 + 100-20x. Thediff., 40x = 80. Dividing, x = 2. Result, greater is 12, less is 8. The comparison of these two forms under which the same operations appear is most interesting. It is indeed obvious that if we take the skeletons of work given in the MS, the similarity is most striking. It is true that the Greek notation for the equations is very much inferior to the modern, but on the other hand the words indicating the operations make the whole very little less concise than the modern work. The omission of these tabular skeletons supplied in the MS. is a very grave defect in Bachet's edition, and thanks are due to M. Rodet for his interesting quotations from the original source. The same writer quotes two other such tables, which, however, for brevity's sake, we omit here. Though in the Ms. the sign I is used to denote equality, Bachet makes no use of any symbol for the purpose in his Latin translation. He uses throughout the full Latin word. It is interesting however to observe that in his earlier translation (1575) Xy lander does use a symbol to denote equalit3^ namely ||, two short vertical parallel lines, in his notes to Diophantos. Thus we find, for example (p. 7G) \Q -¥ 12 || \Q + 0^7 + 9, which we should ex- press by x' +12= x^ + Qx + ^d. § 5. Now that we have described in detail Diopliantos' method of expressing algebraical quantities and relations, we NOTATION AND DEFINITIONS OF DIOPIIANToS. 77 may remark on the general system which he uses that it is essentially different in its character from the modern notation. While in modern times signs and symbols have been developed which have no intrinsic relationship to the things which they syml)olise, but depend for their use upon convention, the case is quite different with Diophantos, where algebraic notation takes the form of mere abbreviation of words which are considered a.s pronounced or implied. This is partly proved by the symbols themselves, which in general consist of the first letter or letters of words (so written as to avoid confusion), the only possible exception being the supposed final sigma, 9, for dpiBfxof or the unknow^n quantit3^ Partly also it is proved by the fact that Diophantos uses the symbol and the complete word very often quite indifferently. Thus we find often in the same sentence 9 or 99 and dpt6fi6<;, dpiO/xol, S" and hvvaixi<;, ^ and \eiyjrei, and so on. The strongest proof, however, that Diophantos' algebraic notation >vas mere abbreviation is found in the fact that the abbreviations, which are his algebraical symbols, are used for the corresponding words even when those words have a quite different signification. So in particular the symbol 9 is used as an abbreviation for dpL6fi6<;, when the word is used, not in its technical Diophantine sense for the unknown, but in its ordinary meaning of a number, especially in enunciations ^\here dpi$fi6<; in its ordinary sense naturally occurs oftenest. Similarly ^ is not used only for Xelyjret but also for other inflexional forms of the stem of this word, e.g. for Xiiruv or \€Lyjra<; in ill. 3: Evpeh' Tpel<; dpiOfiov^ o7rco<; 6 diro tov avy/ceifievov iic rcov rpLiov JJ^ eKaarov nroifj rerpdycovoi'. Other indications are (1) the sepa- ration of the symbc.ls and coefficients by particles [cf. I. 4:J 99°"' dpa I] ; (2) the addition of terminations to the symbol to represent the different cases. Nesselmann gives a good instance in which many of these peculiarities are combined, 99°' dpa I fx° \ laot elalv 99°'* Td fiovdcrc Tt. I. ad Jin. In order to determine in what place, in respect of .systems of algebraic notation, Diophantos stands, Nesselmann observes that we can, as regards the form of exposition cf algebraic operations and equations, distinguish three historical stages of development, well marked and easily discernible. 1. Tho first <S DIorilANTOS OF ALKXANDlilA. Stage Nesselinann repiesonts by the name Rltetoric Algebra, or "reckoning by Complete words." The characteristic of this stage is the absolute want of all symbols, the ■svhole of the calculation being carried on by means of complete words, and forming in fact continuous prose. As representatives of this first stage Nesselmann mentions lamblichos (of whose algebrai- cal work he quotes a specimen in his fifth chapter) "and all Arabian and Persian algebraists who are at present known." In their works we find no vestige of algebraic symbols ; the same may be said of the oldest Italian algebraists and their followers, and among them Regiomontanus. 2. The second stage Nesselmann proposes to call the Syncopated Algebra. This stage is essentially rhetorical and therein like the first in its treatment of questions, but we now find for often-recurring operations and quantities certain abbreviational symbols. To this stage belongs Diophantos and after him all the later Europeans until about the middle of the seventeenth century (with the exception of the isolated case of Vieta, who, as we have seen, initiated certain changes which anticipated later notation to some extent; we must make an exception too, though Nesselmann does not mention these cases, in favour of certain symbols used by Xylandcr and Bachet, j| being used by the former to express equality, + and — by both, as also the ordinary way of representing a fraction by placing the numera- tor above the denominator separated by a Hue drawn horizon- tally'). 3. To the third stage Nesselmann gives the name Symbolic Algebra, which uses a complete system of notation by signs having no visible connection with the words or things which they represent, a complete language of symbols, which supplants entirely the rhetorical system, it being possible to work out a solution without using a single word of the ordinary written language, with the exception (for clearnes.s' sake) of 1 These are only a few scattered instances. Nesselmann, though he does not mention Xylauder's and Bachet's symbols, gives other instances of isolated or common uses of signs, as showing that the division between the dilTerent stages is not shfirphj marked. He instances the use of one operational algebraic symbol by Diophantos, namely ^, for which Lucas de Bnrgo uses m (and p for plKn), Targalia (p. Vieta has + and -, also = for ~. Oughtred uses x , and Harriot expresses multiplication by juxtaposition. NOTATION AND DKl'lMTK )NS (.F Llopll ANTuS. 70 a conjunction here ami there, and so on. Neither is it thr Europeans posterior to the middle of the seventeenth century who were the first to use Si/mbolic forms of Algebra, In this they were anticipated many centuries by the Indians. As examples of these three stages Nesselmann gives three instances quoting word for word the solution of a quadratic equation by Mohammed ibn Musa as an example of the first stage, and the solution of a problem from Diophantos to illus- trate the second. Thus : First Stage. Example from Molmmmed ibn Musa (ed. Rosen, p, 5). "A square and ten of its roots are equal to nine and thirty dirhems, that is, if you add ten roots to one square, the sum is equal to nine and thirty. The solution is as follows : halve the number of roots, that is in this case five ; then multiply this by itself, and the result is five and twenty. Add this to the nine and thirty, which gives sixty-four; take the square root, or eight, and subtract from it half the number of roots, namely five, and there remain three : this is the root of the square whicli was required and the square itself is nine^." Here we observe that not even are symbols used for num- bers, so that this example is even more "rhetorical" than the w^ork of larablichos who does use the Greek symbols for his numbers. Second stage. As an example of Diopliantos I give a trans- lation word for word ^ of II. 8, So as to make the symbols correspond exactly I use S {Square) for h" {8vvaf/.c<i), X (Xiun- her) for 9, U for Units {fiovdhe<i). " To divide the proposed square into two squares. Let it be proposed then to divide 16 into two squares. And let the first ' Thus Mohammed ilm Mfisfi states in words the solution x2+10j + 25 = C4, therefore x + 5 = 8, x = 3. ' I have used the full words whenever Diophantos does so, and to avoid con- fusion have written Siium-c and Xiimbfi- in the technical sense with a capital letter, and italicised tlicm. 80 DIOPHANTOS OF Al.EXANDIUA. be supposed to be Oue Square. Thus 16 miuus One Square must be equal to a square. I form the square from any number of iV's minus as many U's as there are in the side of 16 U's. Suppose this to be 2 K's miuus 4 U's. Thus the square itself will be 4 Squares, 16 U. minus 16 ^V.'s. These are equal to 16 Units minus Oue Square. Add to each the negative term (Xeti/ri?, deficiency) and take equals from equals. Thus 5 Squares are equal to 16 Numbers; and the Number is 16 fifths. One [square] will be 256 twenty-fifths, and the other 144 twenty-fifths, and the sura of the two makes up 400 twenty-fiftlis, or 16 Units, and each [of the two found] is a square. Of the third stage any exemplification is unnecessary. ^>^ § 6. To the form of Diophantos' notation is due the fact that he is unable to introduce into his questions more than one unknown quantity. This limitation has made his procedure often very different from our modern work. In the first place he performs eliminations, which we should leave to be done in the course of the work, before he prepares to work out the problem, by expressing everything which occurs in such a way as to contain only one unknown. This is the case in the great majority of questions of the first Book, which are cases of the solution of determinate simultaneous equations of the first order with two, three, or four variables; all these Diophantos ex- presses in terms of one unknown, and then proceeds to find it from a simple equation. In cases where the relations between these variables are complicated, Diophantos shows extraordinary acuteness in the selection of an unknown quantity. Secondly, however, this limitation affects much of Diophantos' work in- juriously, for while he handles problems which are by nature indeterminate and woukl lead with our notation to an inde- terminate equation containing two or three unknowns, he is compelled by limitation of notation to assign to one or other of these arbitrarily-chosen numbers which have the effect of making the problem a determinate one. However it is but fair to say that Diophantos in assigning an arbitrary value to a quantity is careful to tell us so, saying " for such and such a quantity we put any number wliatever, say such and such NOTATION AND DKFINITION'S (tF 1)F< )riIANT()S. Hi a one." Thus it can lianlly be said tliat there is (in LfiMieral) any loss of universality. We may say, then, that in general Diophantos is obliged to express all his unknowns in terms, or as functions, of one variable. There is something exce.ssively interesting in the clever devices by which he contrives .so to express them in terms of his single unknown, <?, as that by that very expression of them all conditions of the problem are satisfied except one, which serves to complete the solution by determining the value of 9. Another consequence of Diophan- tos' want of other symbols besides 9 to express more variables than one is that, when (as often happens) it is necessary in the course of a problem to work out a subsidiary problem in order to obtain the coefficients &c. of the functions of 9 which express the quantities to be found, in this case the required unknown which is used for the solution of the new subsidiary problem is denoted by the same symbol 9 ; hence we have often in the same problem the same variable 9 used with two diti'erent meanings. This is an obvious inconvenience and might lead to confusion in the mind of a careless reader. Again we find two cases, II. 29 and 30, where for the proper working-out of the problem two unknowns are imperatively necessary. We should of course use x and y ; but Diophantos calls the first 9 as u.sual ; the second, for want of a term, he agrees to call " one unit," i.e. 1. Then, later, having completed the part of the solution necessary to find 9 he substitutes its value, and uses 9 over again to denote what he had originally called " 1 " — the second variable — and so finds it. This is the most curious case I have met with, and the way in which Diophantos after having worked with this " 1 " along with other numerals is yet able to pounce upon the particular place where it has passed to, so as to substitute 9 for it, is very remarkable. This could only be pos- sible in particular cases such as those which I have mentioned : but, even here, it seems scarcely possible now to work out the problem using x and 1 for the variables as originally taken by Diophantos without falling into confusion. Perhaps, however,- it may not be impo.ssible that Diophantos in working out the problems before writing them down as we have them may have given the " 1 " which stood for a variable some mark by which H. D. ^ 82 DIOPHANTo.S OF ALKXANDl'JA. he could recognise it and distinguish it from otlier numbers. For the problems themselves see Appendix. It may be in some measure due to the defects of notation in his time that Diophantos will have in his solutions no numbers / whatever except rational numbers, in which, in addition to surds and imaginary quantities, he includes negative quantities. Of a negative quantity i^er se, i.e. without some positive quan- tity to subtract it from, Diophantos had apparently no con- ception. Such equations then as lead to surd, imaginary, or negative roots he regards as useless for his purpose : the solu- tion is in these cases dSvvaro'i, impossible. So we find him describing the equation 4 = 4.r + 20 as utotto^ because it would give ^ = — 4. Diophantos makes it throughout his object to obtain solutions in rational numbers, and we find him fre- quently giving, as a preliminary, conditions which must bo satisfied, which are the conditions of a result rational in Dio- phantos' sense. In the great majority of cases when Diophan- tos arrives in the course of a solution at an equation M'hich would give an irrational result he retraces his steps and finds out how his equation has arisen, and how he may by altering the previous work substitute for it another which shall give a rational result. This gives rise, in general, to a subsidiary problem the solution of which ensures a rational result for the problem itself. Though, however, Diophantos has no notation for a surd, and does not admit surd results, it is scarcely true to say that he makes no use of quadratic equations which lead to such results. Thu.s, for example, in v. 33 he solves such an equation so far as to be able to see to what integers the solution would approximate most nearly. CHAPTEIi V. DIOPHANTOS' METHODS OF SOLUTION. § 1. Before I give an accouut in detail of the differojit methods which Diophantos employs for the sohition of his pro- blems, so far as they can be classified, I must take exception to some remarks which Hankel has made in his account of Dio- phantos {Zur Geschichte der Mathematik in Alterthum vnd Mittelalter, Leipzig, 1874, pp. 164 — 5). This account does not only possess literary merit : it is the work of a man who has read Diophantos. His remarks therefore possess excep- tional value as those of a man particularly well qualified to speak on matters relating to the history of mathematics, and also from the contrast to the mass of writers who have thought themselves capable of pronouncing upon Diophantos and his merits, while they show unmistakeably that they have not studied his work. Hankel, who has read Diophantos with aj)- preciation, says in the place referred to, "The reader will now be desirous to become acquainted with the classes of inde- terminate problems which Diophantos treats of, and his methods of solution. As regards the first point, we must observe that in the 130 (or so) indeterminate questions, of which Diophantos treats in his great work, there are over 50 different classes of questions, which are arranged one after the other without any recognisable classification, except that the solution of earlier questions facilitates that of the later. The first Book only con- tains determinate algebraic equations; Books ir. to v. contain for the most part indeterminate questions, in which expressions which involve in the first or second degree two or more variables are to be made squares or cubes. Lastly, Book vi. is concerned G— 2 84 DIOPIIANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Avith riglit-augled triangles regarded purely arithmetically, in which some one linear or quadratic function of the sides is to be made a square or a cube. That is all that we can pronounce about this elegant series of questions vnthout exhibiting singhj each of the fifty classes. Almost more different in kind than the questions are their solutions, and we are completely unable to give an even tolerably exhaustive review of the different varieties in his procedure. Of more general comprehensive methods there is in our author no trace discoverable : every ques- tion requires an entirely different method, winch often, even in the problems most nearly related to the former, refuses its aid. It is on that account difficult for a more modern mathematician even after studying 100 Diophantine solutions to solve the lOlsi question ; and if we have made the attempt and after some vain endeavours read Diophantos' own solution, we shall be astonished to see how suddenly Diophantos leaves the broad high-road, dashes into a side-path and with a quiet turn reaches the goal : often enough a goal with reaching which we should not be content ; we expected to have to climb a difficult path, but to be rewarded at the end by an extensive view ; instead of which our guide leads by narrow, strange, but smooth ways to a small eminence ; he has finished ! He lacks the calm and concentrated energy for a deep plunge into a single important problem : and in this way the reader also hurries with inward unrest from problem -to problem, as in a succession of riddles, without being able to enjoy the individual one. Diophantos dazzles more than he delights. He is in a wonderful measure wise, clever, quick-sighted, indefatigable, but does not penetrate thoroughly or deeply into the root of the matter. As his ques- tions seem framed in obedience to no obvious scientific necessity, often only for the sake of the solution, the solution itself also lacks perfection and deeper signification. He is a brilliant performer in the art of indeterminate analysis invented by him, but the science has nevertheless been indebted, at least directly, to this brilliant genius for few methods, because he was deficient in speculative thought which sees in the True more than the Correct. That is the general impression, which I have gained from a thorough and repeated study of Diophantos' arithmetic." DIOPIIANTOS METHODS OF SOLUTION. S.") Now it will be at once obvious that, if Ilaiikcl's representa- tion is correct, any hope of giving a general account of Dio- phantos' methods such as I have shown in the heading of this chapter would be perfectly illusory. Hankel clearly asserts tliivt there are no general methods distinguishable in the Arith- metics. On the other hand we find Nesselmann saying (pp. 308 — 9) that the use of determinate numerals in Diophajitos' problems constitutes no loss of generality, for throughout he is continually showing how other numerals than those which he takes will satisfy the conditions of the problem, showinn- " that his whole attention is directed to the explanation of the method, for Avhich purjjose numerical examples only serve as means " ; this is proved by his frequently stopping short, when the method has been made sufficiently clear, and the remainder of the work is mere straightforward calculation. Cf. v. 14, IS, 19, 20 &c. It is true that this remark may only apply to the isolated " method " employed in one particular problem and in no other ; but Nesselmann goes on to observe that, though the Greeks and Arabians used only numerical examples, yet they had general rules and methods for the solution of equations, as we have, only expressed in words. "So also Diophantos, whose methods have, it is true, in the great majority of cases no such universal character, gives us a perfectly general rule for solving what he calls a double-equation." These remarks Nesselmann makes in the 7th chapter of his book ; the 8th chapter he entitles "Diophantos' treatment of equations'," in which he gives an account of Diophantos' solutions of (1) Deterniinato, (2) Indeterminate equations, classified according to their kind. Chapter 9 of his book Nesselmann calls "Diophantos' methods of solution^" These "methods" he gives as fcjlJows^ : (1) "The adroit assumption of unknowns." (2) "Metho<l of reckoning ^ "Diophant's BehandlunR der Gleichunt,'tn." 2 "Diophant's AuflosuriKsmethodeu." 3 (1) "Die gescbickte Annahme dcr Unbekannten." (2) '•Mflhode ilcr Zuriickrechming und Nebenaufgabe." (3) "Gebrauch dcs Symbols fiir dio Unbekannte in verschiedenen Bedeutungen." (4) "Metliodc der Gren/.fu." (5) "Auflosung durch blo.sse Reflexion." (G) "Autt.isung in ollKemeinPn Ausdriicken." (7) " Willkiihrliche Bestiniraungen und Annuhnien." (8) "tie- branch dcs rcchtwinkhu'cn Dipiecks." 86 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. backw artls and auxiliary questions." (3) " Use of the symbol for the unknown in different significations." (4) "Method of Limits." (5) " Solution by mere reflection." (G) " Solution in general expressions." (7) "Arbitrary determinations and assumptions." (8) " Use of the right-angled triangle." At the end of chapter 8 Nesselmann observes that it is not the solution of equations that we have to wonder at, but the per- fect art which enabled Diophantos to avoid such equations as he could not technically solve. We look (says Nesselmann) with astonishment at his operations, when he reduces the most difficult questions by some surprising turn to a simple equation. Then, when in the 9th chapter Nesselmann passes to the " methods," he prefaces it by saying : " To represent perfectly Diophantos' methods in all their completeness would mean nothing else than copying his book outright. The individual characteristics of almost every question give him occasion to try upon it a peculiar procedure or found upon it an artifice which cannot be applied to any other question Mean- while, though it may be impossible to exhibit all his methods in any short space, yet I will try to give some operations which occur more often or are by their elegance particularly notice- able, and (where possible) to make clear their scientific prin- ciple by a general exposition from common stand-points." Now the question whether Diophantos' methods can be exhibited briefly, and whether there can be said to be any methods in his work, must depend entirely upon the meaning we attach to the word "method." Nesselmann's arrangement seems to me to be faulty inasmuch as (1) he has treated Diophantos' solution of equations — which certainly proceeded on fixed rules, and there- fore by " method " — separately from what he calls " methods of solution," thereby making it appear as though he did not look upon the " treatment of equations " as " methods." Now cer- tainly the " treatment of equations " should, if anything, have come under the head of " methods of solution " ; and obviously the very fact that Diophantos solved equations of various kinds by fixed rules itself disproves the assertion that no metJwds ;nc discernible. (2) The classification under the head of " Mctliods of solution" seems unsatisfactory. In tlic first DIOPHANTOS METHODS UF SoLlTIoX. S7 place, some of the classes can hardly be said to be nu'thmls of solution at all; thus the third, "Use of the symbol for the unknown in different significations", might be more justly described as a "hindrance to the solution"; it is vlxx inconve- nience to which Diophantos was reduced owing to the want of notation. Secondly, on the assumption of the eight " methods" as Nesselmann describes them, it is really not surprising that " no complete account of them could be given without copying the whole book." To take the first, "the adroit assumption of unknowns." Supposing that a number of distinct, ditferent problems are proposed, the existence of such differences makes a different assumption of an unknown in each case absolutely necessary. That being so, how could it be possible to give a rule for all cases ? The best that can be done is an enumera- tion of typical instances. The assumption that the methods of Diophantos cannot be tabulated, on the evidence of this fact, i.e., because no rule can be given for the " adroit assump- tion of unknowns" which Nesselmann classes as a "method," is entirely unwarranted. Precisely the same may be said of "methods" (2), (5), (C), (7). For these, by the very nature of things, no rule can be given : they bear in their names so much of rule as can be assigned to them. The case of (4), "the Method of Limits", is different; here we have the only class which exemplifies a "method" in the true sense of the term, i.e. as an instrument for solution. And accordingly in this case the method can be exhibited, as I hope to show later on : (8) also deserves to some extent the name of a " method." I think, therefore, that neither Nesselmann nor Hanktl has treated satisfactorily the question of Diophantos' methods, the former through a faulty system of classification, the latter by denying that general methods are anywhere discernible in Diophantos. It is true that we cannot find in Diophanto.s' work statements of method put generally as book-work to be applied to examples. But it was not Diophantos' object to write a text- book of Algebra. For this reason we do not find the separate rules and limitations for the solution of different kinds of equa- tions systematically arranged, but we have to seek them out laboriously from the whole of his work, gathering .«5cattcred 88 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. indications here and there, and so formulate tlicni in the best way we can. Such being the case, I shall attempt in the follow- ing pages of this chapter to give a detailed account of what may be called general methods running through Diophantos. For the reasons which I have stated, my arrangement will be different from that of Nesselmann, who is the only author who has attempted to give a complete account of the methods. I shall not endeavour to describe as methods such classes of solutions as are some which are, by Nesselmann, called "methods of solution": and, in accordance with his remark that these " methods" can only be adequately described by a transcription of the entire work, I shall leave them to be gathered from a perusal of my reproduction of Diophantos' book which is given in my Appendix. § 2. I sluili begin my account with Diophantos' tueatmknt of equations. This subject falls naturally into two division.s : (A) Deter- minate equations of different degrees. (B) Indeterminate equations. (A.) Determinate equations. Diophantos was able without difficulty to solve determinate c( [nations of the first and second degree ; of a cubic equation we Hnd in his Arithmetics only one example, and that is a very special case. The solution of simple equations we may pass over; hence we must separately consider Diophantos' method of solution of (1) Pure equations, (2) Adfected, or mixed quadratics. (1) Pare determinate equations. By pure equations I mean those equations which contain oidy one power of the unknown, whatever the degree. The solution is effected in the .same way whatever the exponent of the term in the unknown ; and Diophantos regards pure eijuations of any degree as though thfy were simple C(iuations of the first DIOPHANTOS METHODS OF SOLLTION. M) degree'. He gives a general rule for this case without regard to the degree: "If we arrive at an equation containing on each side the same term but with different coefficients, we must take equals from equals, until we get one term equal to another term. But, if there are on one or on both sides negative terms, the deficiencies must be added on both sides until all tiie terms on both sides are positive. Then we must take equals from equals until one term is left on each side." After these opera- tions have been performed, the equation is reduced to the form Ax"* = B and is considered solved. The c^vses which occur in Diophantos are cases in which the value of x is fouud to be a rational number, integral or fractional. Diophantos only recognise one value of x which satisfies this equation ; thus if m is even, he gives only the positive value, a negative value jjer se being a thing of which he had no conception. In the same way, when an equation can be reduced in degree by dividing throughout by any power of x, the possible values, x=0, tlius arising are not taken into account. Thus an equation of the form x^ = ax, which is of common occurrence in the earlier part of the book, is taken to be merely equivaleut t'> the simj»Ie ecpiation x = a. It may be observed that the greater proportion of the pro- blems in Book l. are such that more than one unknown quantify is sought. Now% when there are two unknowns and two condi- tions, both unknowns can be easily expressed in terms of one symbol. But when there are three or four quantities to be found this reduction is much more difficult, and Diophanto-s manifests peculiar adroitness in effecting it : the result being that it is only necessary to solve a simple equation with one unknown quantity. With regard to pure eciuations, .some have asserted that pure quadratics were tlie only form «>f ([uailratic ' Dof. 11: MerA 5^ Tavra iav airb irpofi\r)naT6s rii'ot yivijTai Crapiit ilitai To?s aiiToh fir} bixoirX-qdr) Si dirb iKaripwv tCiv fitpCiv, Strati i^xupfiy rd Ofioia aw6 Twv ofioiwu, iws av ifbs (?) eZSos ivl etdfi toov y^vrrrai. 4cu> bl Twt (V oTOTifHfi im- irdpxv^^) V ^v diJ.<poT^poii ivtWei^f/ri TifiL etSr), Sc^ati ■Kp<(jOtlvai ri. Xiiworra itSif (i> dn(l>oT^pois Tois ixipeaiv, ?wj dv inaTtpip tu.'v nfpwv to. ttorj iwwdpxovTa finfrai. Kal trdXiv d^eXfiv rd cp.oia dirb rwf ofioluv tm ay cKor^/x^ twi' fitpif In tlSot Kara\ui>0^. Bachet's text (lO-il). p. 10. 90 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. solved in Diuplianto;;' : a statement entirely without foundation. We proceed to consider (2) Mixed quadratic equations. After the remarks in Def. 11 upon the reduction of pure equations until we have one term equal to another term, Diophantos adds*: "But we will show you afterwards how, in the case also when two terms are left equal to a single term, such an equation can be solved." That is to say, he promises to explain the solution of a mixed quadratic equation. In the Arithmetics, as we possess the book, this promise is not fulfilled. The first indications we have on the subject are a number of cases in which the equation is given, and the solution written down, or stated to be rational without any work being shown. Thus, IV. 23, "x = 4a; — 4, therefore cc = 2": vi. 7, "8-^x^ — lx = 7, hence a; = ^ " : vi. 9, " 630.^'^ — 73.r = 6, therefore x = f^": and, vi. 8, " G30j;*^ + 7Sx = G, and x is rational." These examples, though proving that somehow Diophantos had arrived at the result, are not a sufficient proof to satisfy us that he necessarily was acquainted with a regular method for the solution of quadratics ; these solutions might (though their variety makes it somewhat unlikely) have been obtained by mere ti'ial. That, however, Diophantos' solutions of mixed quadratics were not merely empirical, is shown by instances in v. 3.1 In this problem he shows pretty plainly that his method was scientific, in that he indicates that he could approximate to the root in cases where it is not rational. As this is an important point, I give the substance of the passage in question : "x has to be so determined •^■'-GO , x'-iJO . 2 ,.n - that it must be > — - — and < -^ , i.e. .x - 00 > o.r, and o O x' - GO < S.r. Therefore x" = Hx + some number > GO, therefore x must be not less than II, and x^ <8x + 60, therefore a; must be not greater than 12." 1 Cf. Iloimer, translation of Bossut's Ge.^rh. d. Math. i. 55. Kliigel's Dictionary. Also Dr Hcinrich Siitcr's doubts in Oesch. d. Math. Zurich, 1873. * vaTfpov hi (TOL Sci^ofxev Kal ttois 8i'o iidJiv lawv iv\ KaraXfifdivTwv t6 towvtov \vtTai. DIOrilAXTOS' MKTIloDS UF SOLUTION. 1»1 Now by examining the roots of these two equations we rtnJ x> ^, and .'•<4 + V<(), or .v> lO-G'-ldi and x< Il'TITN. It is clear therefore that x inai/ be < 1 1 or > 12, and there- fore Diophantos' limits are not strictly accurate. As however it was doubtless his object to find integral limits, the limits 11 and 12 are those wdiich are obviously adapted for his purpose, and are a fortiori right. Later in the same problem he makes an auxiliary determination of x, which must be such that x^+m>1±c, a,-' + GO < Sir, which give x>\l+J(ji, a;<12 + J^\. Here Diophantos says x must be > 10, <21, wliioli again are clearly the nearest integral limits. The occurrence of these two examples which we have given of equations whose roots are irrational, and therefore could not be hit upon by trial, show's that in such cases Diophantos must have liad a method by which he approximated to these roots. Thus it may be taken for granted that Diophantos had a definite rule for the solution of mixed quadratic equations. We are further able to make out the formula or rule by which Diophantos solved such equations. Take, for example, the equation ax^ ■\- hx -\- c = 0. In our modern method of solution we divide by a and write the result originally in tlic form 7 /~T^ x= — y~ + A / —J . It docs not appear that Diophantos divided throughout by a. Rather he first multiplied by a so as to bring the equation into the form aV + ahx + ac = ; tlicn solving he found ax= — \h ±J\i}^ — ac, and regarded the result in the' f..rm ,^_^ ^ ± ^'l ^'-«^, Whether the inter- a mediate procedure was as we have described it is n(H certain ; but it is certain that he used the result in the form given. One remark however must be made upon the form of the root. ' Nessi'luiann, p. :ilO. Also IJo.li-t, Jountdl A^iniiijiir. .Iiiiivi.r, I'-T-. 92 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Diophantos takes no account of tlie existence of two roots, according to the sign taken before the radical. Diophantos ignores always the negative sign, and takes the positive one as giving the value of the root. Though this perhaps might not surprise us in cases where one of the roots obtained is nega- tive, yet neither does Diophantos use both roots when both arc positive in sign. In contrast to this Nessehnann points out that the Arabians (as typified by Mohammed ibn Milsa) and the older Italians do in this latter case recognise both roots. M. llodet, however, remarks upon this comparison between Diophantos and the Arabians, so unfavourable to the former, as follows (a) Diophantos did not write a text-book on Algebra, and in the cases where the equation arrived at gives two positive solutions one of them is excluded a priori, as for ex- ample in the case quoted by him, v. 13. Here the inequality 72.r > llx'^ + 17 would give a; < f f or else x<-^. But the other inequality to be satisfied is *l^x<l^x^ + 19, which gives x>\% ov x> f^. As however -^j < /\j, the limits x<^\> fjj are impossible. Hence the roots of the equations corresponding to the negative sign of the radical must necessarily be rejected. (6) Mohammed ibn Mu^a, althougli recognising in theory two roots of the equation x^ + c = hx, in practice only uses one of the two, and, curiously enough, always takes the value cor- responding to the negative sign before the radical, whereas Diophantos uses the positive sign. But see Chapter viii. From the rule given in Def. 11 for compensating by addition any negative terms on either side of an equation and taking equals from equals (operations called by the Arabs aljahr and almulcahala) it is clear that as a preliminary to solution Diophantos so arranged his equation that all the terms were positive. Thus of the mixed quadratic equation we have three cases of which we may give instances : thus, -^,p + Jip' + m<i Case 1. YoYm mx^ -»rpx = q; the root is 1)1 according to Diophantos. An instance is afforded by VI. G. Diophantos arrives namely at the equation C./-I- 3u: = 7, which, if it is to be of any service to his solution, should give a rational value of X ; whereupon Diophantos says " the S(]uarc of half tlic DIOPHANTOS' MrnioDS OF SOLUTION. [):} coefficient' of a; togetlier with tlie pn.duot ul" the absohite term and the coefficient of x^ must be a square number; but it is not," i.e. ]/>"+ mq, or in tliis case (•^)'' + 42, must be a scjuare in onh-r that the root may be rational, which in tliis case it is not. Case 2. Form mx^ = px + q. Diopliantos takes i u + V i i)^ + tun X = - f^ iii 1 . An example is IV. 45, where 2x-* > Gx + 1 S. Diophantos says : " To solve this take the square of half the co- efficient of X, i.e. 9, and the product of the ftbsolute term and the coefficient of x', i.e. od. Adding, we have 45, the square root^ of which is not^ < 7. Add half the coefficient of x and divide by the coefficient of x"^ ; whence x < 5." Here the form of the root is given completely; and the whole operation by which Diopbantos found it is revealed. Case 3. Form mx^ + 3' = P'' '• Dioplianto.s' root is — M— - — /. Cf. in V. 13 the equation already mentioned, 17.6-^+ 17 <72x. Diophantos says: "Multiply half the coeffi- cient of X into itself and we have 1296 : subtract the i)roduct of the coefficient of x^ and the absolute term, or 2<S9. The remainder is 1007, the square root of which is not^ > 31. Achl half the coefficient of x, and the result is not > 07. Divide by the coefficient of x^, and x is not > f f ." Here again we have the complete solution given. (3) Cubic equation. There is no ground for supposing that Diophantos was acquainted with the solution of a cubic ct[uation. It is true there is one cubic e(piation which occurs in the Arithmetics, but it is only a very particular case. In vi. 19 the equation arises, a.'^ + 2^ + 3 = a;^ + 3a; - 3a;'^ - 1, and Diophantos says simply, "whence x is found to be 4." All that can be said of 1 For "coeflicient" Diophantos uses simply irX^t'os, luiinbcr: thus "number of apiOfiol " = coeff . of x. - Diophantos calls the "square root" irXei'pd or side. 2 7, though not accurate, is clearly the nearest integral limit which will servo the purpose. * As before, the nearest intajruJ limit. O-i DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. this is that if we write the equation in true Diophantine fashion, so that all terms are positive, x^ + oc = 4'X^+ 4. This equation being clearly equivalent to x{x^ + l) = 4(.r'^ + l), Diophantos probably detected the presence on both sides of the equation of a common factor. The result of dividing by it is a; = 4, which is Diophantos' solution. Of the two other roots X = ±J — 1 no account is taken, for reasons stated above. From this single example we have no means of judging how far Diophantos was acquainted with the solutions of equations of a degree higher than the second. I pass now to the second general division of equations. (B.) Indeterminate equations. As has been already stated, Diophantos does not in his Arithmetics, as we possess them, treat of indeterminate equa- tions of the first degree. Those examples in the First Book which would lead to such equations are, by the arbitrary assumption of one of the required numbers as if known, con- verted into determinate equations. It is possible that the treatment of indeterminate equations belonged to the missing portion which (we have reason to believe) has been lost between Books I. and II. But we cannot with certainty dispute the view that Diophantos never gave them at all. For (as Nessel- mann observes) as with indeterminate quadratic equations our object is to obtain a rational result, so in indeterminate simple equations we seek to find a result in ivhole numbers. But the exclusion of fractions as inadmissible results is entirely foreign to our author; indeed we do not find the slightest trace that he ever insisted on such a condition. We take therefore as our first division indeterminate equations of the second degree. I. Indeterminate equations of the second degree. The form in which these equations occur in Diophantos is universally this : one or two (and never more) functions of the uid<nown quantity of the form A.x^ ■{■ Bx + G are to be made rational s(|iiaro mnnbers by finding a suitable value for x. DIOPIIANTCJS MKTIloDS OF SOUTlnX. <).-, Tims we have to deal with one or two equations ol the fuini Ax^+Bx+ C = y\ (1) Single equation. The single equation of the form Ax" -\- Bx -\- C = if takes special forms when one or more of the coefficients vanish, «»r are subject to particular conditions. It will be well to give in order the different forms as they can be identified in Dio- phantos, and to premise that for "=/" Diophantos sim})l\' uses the formula laov rerpaycovcp. 1. Equations which can always be solved rationallv. This is the case when ^ or C or both vanish. Form Bx = f. Diophantos puts y^ = any arbitrary square number = nr, say therefore x= - . C'f iir. 5 : 2x = f, i/ = 1 (I, x=S. Form Bx + C = f. Diophantos puts for f any value m'', and x= — T-, — • He admits fractional values of x, onlv takin<f care that they are "rational," i.e. rational and positive. E.x. III. 7. Form Ax' + Bx = f. For i/ Diophantos puts any multiple of.r, -a:; whence Ax+B= .,x, the factor x disappearinf? n n tin and the root x=0 being neglected as usual. Therefore x= ,^"\ ,. Exx. II. 22, 34. Hi — A ir 2. Equations whose rational solution is only possible under certain condition.s. The cases occurring in Diophantos are Form Ax"^ + C = >/. This can be lationally solved accord- ing to Diophantos (a) When A is positive and a square, say a'. Thus oV -f C = _?/*, In this case ?/* is put = (ax ± in)* ; therefore a'x' + C = (ax ± m)^ a - m' 96 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. (m and the doubtful sign being always assumed so as to give £c a positive value). {/3) When C is positive and a square number, say c*. Tlius Aa;' + r = y^. Here Diophantos puts ?/ = (mx ± c) ; therefore Ax^ + c^ = (mx ± cf, A — lit'- (7) When one solution is known, any number of other solutions can be found. This is enunciated in vi. 16 tlms, though only for the case in which C is negative: "when two numbers are given such that when one is multiplied by some square, and the other is s\ibtracted from the product, the result is a square number; another square also can be found, greater than the first taken square, which will have the same effect," It is curious that Diophantos does not give a general enunciation of this proposition, inasmuch as not only is it applicable to the cases ± Ax^ ±C^ = if, but to the general form Ax^ -\- Bx -\- G = y"'. In the Lemma at vi. 12 Diophantos does prove that the equation Ax^ + C = y can be solved when ^ + C is a square, i.e. in the particular case when the value x = l satisfies the equation. But he does not always bear this in mind, for in III. 12 the equation o2x^ + 12 = y^ is pronounced to be impos- sible of solution, although 52 -f 12 = G4, a square, and a rational solution is therefore possible. So, ill. 13, 2(j(jx^ — 10 = 3/* is said to be impossible, though a; = 1 satisfies it. / It is clear that, if a; = satisfies the ciiuation, (7 is a square, and therefore this case (7) includes the previous case (/?). It is interesting to observe that in VI. 15 Diophantos states that a rational solution of the equation Ax' -€' = 7/ is impossible unless A is the sum of two squares^. ' Nesselmann compares Lpj,'cmlro, Tlirorie des Xomhrrs, p. GO. DIOPHANTOS MI-:TH01)S Ol' SOLI TloN. !)7 Lastly, we must consider the Form Ax^ + Bx+C = y\ This equation can be reduced by means of a change of variable to the previous form, wanting the second term. Thus if we put x = z — ^ . , the transformation gives ^- + ^A - y ■ Diophantos, however, treats this form of the equation quite separately from the other and less fully. According to him the rational solution is only possible in the following cases. (a) When A is positive and a square, or the equation is aV+ Bx + C=y"; and Diophantos puts if= {ax + mf, whence Exx. II. 20, 21 &c. 2am -B' (yQ) When C is positive and a square, or the ccjuation is Ax^ + Bx -\- c' = y-; and Diophantos writes y' = {mx + c)^ whence X = —J Y • Exx. IV. 0, 10 &c. A - m' (7) When \B'^ — AG is positive and a square number. Diophantos never expressly enunciates the possibility of this case: but it occurs, as it were unawares, in iv. 33. In this problem 3« + 18 — a;^ is to be made a square, and the ec|uation ^x-\-\^ — a? = y'^ comes under the present form. To solve this Diophantos assumes 3a;+ 18 — j;* = 4x* which leads to the quadratic 3a; + 18 — ox^ = 0, and " the equation is not rational". Hence the assumption 4a/' will not do : "and we must seek a square [to replace 4] such that 18 times (this square + 1) + (f)"'' may be a square". Diophantos then solves this auxiliary eciuation 18 {x" + 1) + ;,' = if, finding x = IS. TIr-u he assumes 3x+l8-a,'=(18)V, which gives 325a;^ - 3a; - 18 = 0, whence Jc = -^^. H. D. 7 98 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. It is interesting to observe that from this example of Dio- phantos we can obtain the reduction of this general case to the form At? + G^ = y^, wanting the middle term. Thus, assume with Diophantos that Ax^+Bx-^ C = m^x^, therefore by solution we have B ^ + and X is rational provided ~t- — AC+ Cnf is a square. This B'^ condition can be fulfilled if — - AC he a square by a previous case. Even if that is not the case, we have to solve (putting, for brevity, D for ~ — AG) the equation D + Cm' = f. Hence the reduction is effected, by the aid of Diophantos alone. (2) Double-equation. By the name "double-equation" Diophantos designates the problem of finding one value of the unknown quantity x which will make two functions of it simultaneously rational square numbers. The Greek term for the "double-equation" occurs variously as Bnr\ola-6T7](; or BtTrXi} caorij'i. We have then to solve the equations mx^ + ax + a= u'\ nx'-{- ^x + b = w') in rational numbers. The necessary preliminary condition is that each of the two expressions can severally be made squares. This is always possible when the first term (in x') is wanting. This is the simplest case, and wc shall accordingly take it first. y DIOPHANTOS MKTIKJDS OF SOLUTION. })0 1. Double equation of the first degree. Diophautos has one distinct method of solving the ociuations ax + a= II' ^x + b=w' taking slightly different forms according to the nature of the coefficients. (a) First method of solution of ^a; + b = wy This method depends upon the equation \ 2 ) '-^J-P<I. If the difference between the two functions can be separated into two factors p, q, the functions themselves are equated to ( — ~ ] . Diophantos himself states his rule thus, in ii. 12: " Observing the difference between the two expressions, seek two numbers whose product is equal to this ditfercncc ; then either equate the square of half the difterence of the factors to the smaller of the expressions, or the square of half the sum to the greater." We will take the general case, and investigate what particular cases the method is applicable to, from Dio- phantos' point of view, remembering that his cases are such that the final quadratic equation for w arising reduces always to a simple one. Take the equations ax + a= ii\ ' /S./; + i = n)\ and subtracting we have (a — /8) x + (a — 6) = i^ — w*. Let a— 13 = 8, a - 6 = e for brevity, thou 8x + e = «' - ui\ 7 •> Thus 100 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. We have then to separate B:c + e into two factors ; let these factors be «, — + - , and \vc accordins^ly write p p 8x € u + v = 1- , p p /hx e Y , ^ SV 2hxfe \ fe V ,, s therefore —5- -\ {- + p] + { +p] =4 (ax + a). p p \p / \p / Now in order that this equation may reduce to a simple one, either (1) the coefficient of x^ must vanish or 8 = 0, therefore a = ^, or (2) the absolute term must vanish. Therefore ( ~ + i^ ) = 4a, or p' + 2e/ + e' = 4ap% i. e. / +2{a-h-2a) pi' + (a - 6)" = 0. Therefore {p^ — a + hf = 4a6, whence ah must be a square number. Therefore either both a and h are squares, in which case we may substitute for them c' and d\ p being then equal to c ±d, or the ratio a : 6 is the ratio of a square to a square. With respect to (1) we observe that on one condition it is not necessary that S should vanish, i.e. provided we can, before solving the equations, make the coefficients of x' in both equal by multiplying either equation or both by a square number, an operation which does not affect the problem, for a square multi- plied by a square is still a square. DIOPHANTOS MI-yniODS OF SOLUTION. 101 Thus if =^ or aii^ = ^m^, the coudition 8 = will bo jo il satisfied by multiplying the equations respectively by n' and i/r ; and thus we can also solve the equations like the equations •'■ + « = '^^l ,v + b = w') in an infinite number of ways. Again the equations under (2), ax+ 6^= ^i^ ^x + d' = w\ can be solved in two different ways, according as we write them in this form or in the form ^c'x + c'd' = 2U" obtained by multiplying them respectively by (T, c* in order that the absolute terms may be equal. We now give those of the possible cases which are found solved in Diophantos' own work. These are equations (1) of the form ant'x + a= ii^] a case which includes the more common one, when tiie co- efficients of X in both are equal. (2) of the form ^x + cP = 2uy solved in two different ways according as they are thus written, or in the alternative form, ad\c + c'd^ = u' ^c'x + c"d' = w 102 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. General solution of Form (1), or, am an Multiplying respectively by if, nf, we have to solve the equations, am^n^x + an^ = il^\ amVic + hm^ = w'^) ' The difiFercnce = aif — hm^. Suppose this separated into two factors p, q. Put It' ± %d — p, n T w' = q, whence ..■^ ^ (P ±3)\ ^r- = (P-^)' , therefore am'^ifx + an^ = ( — 9- j , or a'm^n^x + hm'^= \—y^ Either equation will give the same value of x, and p^ + q^ arf + hmf i 2 X— — •xmSi^ since yq = arf — hnf. Any factors p, q may be chosen provided the value of x obtained is positive. Ex. from Diophantos. 65- G«=w') G5 - 24^ = to'} ' ,, . 2G() - 24.7- = w'-) therefore ... ^, . Oo — 24a; = w The difference = 195 = 15 . 13 say, therefore / 15 - 13 y ^ ^^^ _ ^^^^ 24a; = 64, or a; = §. C-^^) DIOPHANTOS MKTHODS OF SOLUTION. 1()3 General solution (first method) of Form (2), or, oc + c" = ii'^l ^x + d'' = 2o'y In order to solve by this method, we multiply by rf*, c* respectively and write (xd^x + c'dr = n") ^c'x + c\V = w") ' u being the greater. The diti: = {id' - /3r) x. Let the factors of this be px, 7, therefore ii^=(&i+lJ\\ Hence x is found from the equation This equation gives j9V + 2x (pq - 2a^) + q" - ^c'd' = 0, or, since pq = ad^ — y8c^ p'x' - 2x {ad' + /Sr ) + q' - ^c'd' = 0. In order that this may reduce to a simple equation, as Diophantos requires, the absolute term must vanish. Therefore q' - ^c\l' = 0, whence q = 2cd. Thus our method in this case furnishes us with only one solution of the double-equation, q being restricted to the value 2cd, and this solution is _ 2 {ad:" + I3c') _ Sc'ff (gff + )9 c') Ex. from Diophantos. This method is only used in one particular case, IV. 45, w^here c' = d' as the equations originally stand, namely 8x+-i = u'\ (jx+4> = iv'] ' 104- DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. the difference is 2x and q is necessarily taken = 2>/i = 4, and the factors are ^ , 4, therefore 8a; + 4 = r^ + 2 j and rr = 11 2. General solution (second method) of Form (2), or Here the difference ={ol - ^) x + (c^ - (T) = hx -\- € say, for brevity. Let the factors oi dx + e\iQ p, h . Then, as before proved (p. 100), p must be equal to (c + d). Therefore the factors are «-/3 - J 7 , oj + c + a, c + ft, c + fZ and we have finally \c±d J kC ± d. two. (^^)^'^+4.f<;;/>-fo, which equation gives two possible values for x. Thus in this case we can find by our method two values of x, since one of the factors, p, may be c + d. Ex. from Diophantos, III. 17 : to solve the equations 10a; + 9 = w'^) 5a; + 4 = 10^ } ' The difference is here 5x + 5, and Diophantos chooses as the factors 5, a; + l. This case therefore corresponds to the value c + d of jj. The solution is given by (i-y= lOx + !), whence x - 28. DIOPHANTOS METHODS OF SOLUTION. 105 The other value c — (Z of jj is in this case excluded, because it would lead to a negative value of x. The possibility of deriving any number of solutions of a double-equation when one solution is known does not seem to have been noticed by Diophantos, though he uses the prin- ciple in certain special cases of the single equation. Fermat was the first, apparently, to discover that this might always be done, if one value a of x were known, by substituting in the equations x+ a for .v. By this means it is possible to find a positive solution even if a is negative, by successive appli- cations of the principle. But nevertheless Diophantos had certain peculiar artifices by which he could arrive at a second value. One of these artifices (which is made necessary in one case by the unsuit- ableness of the value found for x by the ordinary method), employed in iv. 45, gives a different way of solving a double- equation from that which has been explained, used only in a special case. (/S) Second method of solution of a double-equation of the first degree. Consider only the special case hx + if = u^, {h+f)x + n^ = iu\ Take these expressions, and ?^^ and write them in order uf magnitude, denoting them for convenience by A, B, C. A = {h+f)x + n\ B = hx + n\ G = n\ ,, „ A-B f , A-B=fx therefore F^ = ^ ^^^ 5- (7 = 1... Suppose now hx + if = {}j + nf, therefore hx = y~ + 2ny, therefore A-B = ^(if + ^nij), f or ^=(2/+«)' + ^(2/'+2ny), thus it is only necessary to make this expression a s(|uarc. 106 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Write therefore (l + {) / + 2'^ ({ + 1)2/ + '^' = (Vy - '')"' whence any number of values for y, and therefore for x, can be found, by varying p. Ex. The only example in the Arithmetics is in iv. 45. There is the additional condition in this case of a limit to the value of X. The double-equation 8a; + 4 = u^^ Qx + 4! = vf has to be solved in such a manner that x<1. A— B Here ^ — ^ ~ 3 > ^^^ ^ ^^ taken ' to be {y + 2)^ therefore ^-5=^^^, therefore ^ = 2^!+^^^ + ^^ + 4 1/ + 4 = ^|-V -|^ + 4 which must be made a square, or, multiplying by f , 3^/^ -I- 12t/ + 9 = a square, where y must be < 2. Diophantos assumes 32/^+123/ + 9 = (m2/-3r, 6w + 12 whence ?/ = -^ ., , and the value of m is then determined so that ?/ < 2. As we find only a special case in Diophantos solved by this method, it woidd be out of place to investigate the con- 1 Of course Diophantos uses the same variable .r where I have for clearness used y. Then, to express what I have called in later, he says: "I form a square from 3 minus some number of x's and .r becomes some number multiplied by 6 together with 12 and divided by the dillerence by which the square of the number exceeds three," DIOPHANTOS METHODS OF SOLUTION. 1()7 ditions under which more general cases might be solved in this manner \ 2. Double equation of the second degree, or the general form Ace' + Bx + C = 2i\ A'x'' + B'x + C' = w\ These equations are much less thoroughly treated in Diophan- tos than those of the first degree. Only such special instances occur as can be easily solved by the methods which we have described for those of the first degree. One separate case must be mentioned, which cannot be solved, from Diophantos' standpoint, by the preceding method, but which sometimes occurs and is solved by a peculiar method. The form of double-equation being ax' + ax = u'] (1), ^x'+bx = w'\ (2), Diophantos assumes whence from (1) a X = -2 m — a and by substitution in (2) a \~ ha , , + a must be a square, m —aj 7n —a a'^ + ha{m'-a) IS a square. Therefore we have to solve the equation abm^ + a (/9a — ah) = if, and this form can or cannot be solved by processes already given according to the nature of the coefficients^ , . OJ+bi • Bachet and after him Cossali proved the pos.Kibility of solving ^^^ j\ "V this method under two conditions. - Diophantos did not apparently observe that this form of e<iualion could be 108 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. II. Indeterminate equations of a degree liigher than the second. (1) Single Equations. These are properly divided by Nesselmann into two classes ; the first of which comprises those questions in which it is re- quired to make a function of a; of a higher degree than the second a square ; the second comprises those in which a rational value of X has to be found which will make any function of cc, not a square, but a higher power of some number. The first class of problems is the solution in rational numbers of Aar + Bx""' + + Kx + L = f, the second the solution of Ax'' + Bx"-' + 4-Kx + L = y\ for Diophantos does not go beyond making a function of j; a cube. Also in no instance of the first class does the index n exceed 6, nor in the second class (except in a special case or two) exceed 3. First class. Equation Ax'' + 5a;""' + + Kx + L = y\ We give now the forms found in Diophantos. 1. Equation Ax"" + Bx^ + Cx + d"- = y\ Here we might (the absolute term being a square) put for y the expression mx + d, and determine ni so that the coefficient of X in the resulting equation vanishes, in which case Q %nd = G, m = ^ , and we obtain in Diophantos' manner a simple equation for x, giving ^ ^ _ G'-U'B reduced to one of tbe first degree by dividing by x- and putting ?/ for , iu wbich case it becomes a + ay = u''- ) p + by^w'^S' Tbis reduction was given by Lagrange. DIOPHANTOS METHODS OF SOLUTION. l(j!) Or we might put for y an expression mV + H.r + (/, and (k-ter- inine m, n so that the coefficients of x, x'' in the resultiin' equation both vanish, whence we should again have a simple equation for x. Diophantos, in the only example of this furm of equation which occurs, makes the first supposition. Thus in VI. 20 the equation occurs, x'-Sx' + Sx + l = i/, and Diophantos assumes ?/ = i] x- + 1, whence x=^K 2. Equation Ax* + Bx^ + Cx" + Dx + E=tf. In order that this equation may be solved by Diophantos' method, either A ox E must be a square. If A is a square and equal to a^ we may assume y = ax^ + — x-\- n, determining n so that the term in x' vanishes. If ^ is a square (e^ we may write y — Tm?+ ^x + e, determining m so that the term in a-' may vanish in the resulting equation. We shall then in either case obtain a simple equation for x, in Diophantos' manner. The examples of this form in Diophantos are of the kind, a V + Bx^ + 6V + Dx + e' = y; where we can assume y = ± ax^ + kx ± e, determining k so that in the resulting equation (in addition to the coefficient of x*, and the absolute term) the coefficient of a;', or that of a;, may vanish, after which we again have a simple equation. Ex. IV. 29 : 9x' - 4a;' + 6a;' - 12a; + 1 = y'. Here Diophantos assumes y = ox" — Ga; + 1, and the equation reduces to 32a-' - 3Ga;' = anda; = U. Diophantos is guided in his choice of signs in the ex- pression ± aaf+kx±ehy the necessity for obtaining a "rational" result. But far more difficult to solve are those e<[uations in which (the left expression being bi-quadratic) the odd powers of x arc wanting, i.e. the eciuations Ax* + Cx' + E= y', and Ax* + A* = y*, 110 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. even when -<4 or ^ is a square, or both are so. These cases Diophantos treats more imperfectly. 3. Equation Ace* + Ccc'' + E = if. Of this form we find only very special cases. The type is which is written aV-cV + e'=2/', X Here ii is assumed to be ax or - , and in either case we ^ X have a rational value of x. 25 Exx. V. 30 : 25*^ - 9 + — = 2/^ This is assumed to be equal to 25a;^ V. 31 : -^ c^ - 25 + 2 = y"- f assumed to be = -7-^ . 4. Equation Ax''^E = if. The case occurring in Diophantos is a;'* + 97 = if. Diophantos tries one assumption, _y = a;^ — 10, and finds that this gives ^ = -i^, which leads to no rational result. Instead however of investigating in what cases this equation can be solved, he simply shirks the equation and seeks by altering his original assumptions to obtain an equation in the place of the one first found, which can be solved in rational numbers. The result is that by altering his assumptions and working out the question by their aid he replaces the refractory equation, a;* + 97 = y^, by the equatioQ x* + 337 = f, and is able to find a suitable sub- stitution for y, namely o^ — 25. This gives as the required solution cc = '^. For this case of Diophantos' characteristic artifice of retracing his steps' — "back-reckoning," as Ncsscl- mann calls it, see Appendix v. 32. 5. Equation of sixth degree in the special form a;« _ Ax" + Bx + c' = f. 1 "Methode der Zuriickrccbnung und Ncbcnaufgabe. " DIOPHANTOS METHODS OF SOLUTION. Ill It is only necessary to put y = .7/ + c, whence — A.r' + B= 2cx* and ^^'^ = 7", 9 • This gives Diophantos a rational solution if . IS a square. G. If however this last condition does not hold, as in the case occurring IV. 19, x'^ - 16^' + a; + 64 = ?/^ Diophantos employs his usual artifice of " back-reckoning," by which he is enabled to replace this equation by .«*' — 128a;' + a; + 409G = y*, which satisfies the condition, and (assuming y = x^-\- 04) x is found to be -j^r. Second Class. Equation of the form Ax'' + Bx''~^ + +Kx + L = y^. Except for such simple cases as Ax^='if, Ax* = if, where it is only necessary to assume y = mx, the only cases which occur in Diophantos are Ax^ -^ Bx-\- C= y^, Ax^ + Ba? + Cx+D = if. 1. Equation Ax' + Bx + C = y\ There are of this form only two examples. First, in vi. 1 a;* — 4a: + 4 is to be made a cube, being at the same time already a square. Diophantos therefore naturally assumes ;c — 2 = a cube number, say 8, whence x= 10. Secondly, in vi. 19 a peculiar case occurs. A cube is to be found which exceeds a square by 2. Diophantos a.ssumes (a;-l)^ for the cube, and (a^ + l)^ for the square, obtaining a;' - 3a;" + 3x - 1 = a;^ + 2a; + 3, or the equation a;' + a; = 4a;* + 4, previously mentioned (pp. 36, 93), which is satisfied by x = 4. The question here arises: Was it accidentally or not that this cubic took so special and easy a form? Were a;— l,a; + l assumed with the knowledge and intention of finding such an equation ? Since 27 and 25 are so near each otlier and are, as Fermat observes \ the only integral numbers which satisfy the 1 Note to VI. I'J. Fermatii Opera Math. p. I'.i'i. 112 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. conditions, it seems most likely that it was in view of these numbers that Diophantos hit upon-the assumptions x + 1, x—1, and employed them to lead back to a known result with all the air of a general proof. Had this not been so, we should probably have found, as elsewhere in the work, Diophantos first leading us on a false tack and then showing us how we can in all cases correct our assumptions. The very fact that he takes the right assumptions to begin witli makes us suspect that the solution is not based upon a general principle, but is empirical merely. 2. The equation Ax^+Bx-' + Gx + D^f. If -4 or D is a cube number this equation is easy of solution. For, first, if A = a^ we have only to write y = ax+ -^ , and we arrive in Diophantos' manner at a simple equation. C Secondly, if D = d?, we put y = ^^ x + d. If the equation is a^x^ + Bx^ + Cx + d^ = y^, we can use either assumption, or put y=ax + d, obtaining as before a simple equation. Apparently Diophantos only used the last assumption ; for he rejects as impossible the equation y^=8x' — x^+8x—l because y = 2x — l gives a negative value a; = — ^y, whereas either of the other assumptions give rational values \ (2) Double-equation. There are a few examples in which of two functions of x one is to be made a square, the other a cube, by one and the same rational value of x. The cases arc for the most part very simple, e.g. in vi. 21 we have to solve 4x + 2=y'' 2x + l=z'' therefore ?/' = ^z^, and z is assumed to be 2. 1 There is a special case in which C aud 1) vanish, Ax'^ + Bx- = y'K Here y is put —mx and x- ., , . Cl'. iv. 0, 30. »«•* - A DIOPHANTOS' METHODS OF SOLUTION. \l:\ A rather more complicated case is vi. 23, where we have the double equation of + 2x- + X = 2^\' 2 Diophantos assumes )j = moc, wheuce x= —^ , and we have to solve the single equation / 2 Y .^/^^_y 2 W-2) ^■^\m^-2) "^ nT^l ^ = ^. (m«-2f To make 2m* a cube, we need only make 2in a cube, or put m =■ 4. This gives for x the value f . The general case Ax' + Bx^+ Cx = z\ hx^ + ex =y^> would, of course, be much more difficult ; for, putting i/ = nix, we find X = —, — r . and we have to solve or Ccm* + c(Bc- 2b C) m" + hc{hC-Bc) + A c' = u\ of which equation the above corresponding one is a very parti- cular case. § 3. Summari/ of the preceding investigation. We may sum up briefly the results of our investigation of Diophantos' methods of dealing with equations tiius. 1. Diophantos solves completely equations of the first degree, but takes pains beforehand to secure that the solution shall be positive. He shows remarkable address in reducing a number of simultaneous equations of the first degree to a single equation in one variable. H. D. 8 114 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. 2. For determinate equations of the second degree Dio- phantos has a general method or rule of solution. He takes however in the Arithmetics no account of more than 07ie root, even when both roots are positive rational numbers. But his object is always to secure a solution in rational numbers, and therefore we need not be surprised at his ignoring one root of a quadratic, even though he knew of its existence. 3. No equations of a higher degree than the second are found in the book except a particular case of a cubic. 4. Indeterminate equations of the first degree are not treated in the work as we have it, and indeterminate equations of the second degree, e.g. Aaf + Bx -\-G = y', are only fully treated in the case where ^ or C vanishes, in the more general cases more imperfectly. 5. For " double-equations " of the second degree he has a definite method when the coefficient of x^ in both expressions vanishes ; this however is not of quite general application, and is supplemented in one or two cases by another artifice of particular application. Of more complicated cases we have only a few examples under conditions favourable for solution by his method. 6. Diophantos' treatment of indeterminate equations of higher degrees than the second depends upon the particular conditions of the problems, and his methods lack generality. 7. After all, more wonderful than his actual treatment of equations are the extraordinary artifices by which he contrives to avoid such equations as he cannot theoretically solve, e.g. by his device of " Back-reckoning," instances of which, however, would have been out of place in this chapter, and can only be studied in the problems themselves. § 4. I shall, as I said before, not attempt to class as methods what Nesselmann has tried so to describe, e.g. "Solution by mere reflection," "solution in general expressions," of which there are few instances definitely described as such by Diophantos, and " arbitrary determinations and assumptions." It is clear that the most that can be done to formulate these " methods " is the DIOPHANTOS METHODS OF SOLUTION. 1 1 .') enumeration of a few instances. This is what Ncssclmann has done, and he himself regrets at the end of his chapter on "Methods of solution" that it must of necessity be so incomplete. To understand and appreciate these artifices of Diophantos it is necessary to read the problems themselves singly, and for these I refer to the abstract of them in the Appendix. As for the " Use of the right-angled triangle," all that can be said of a general character is that rational right-angled triangles (whose sides are all rational numbers) are alone used in Diophantos, and that accordingly the introduction of such a right-angled triangle is merely a convenient device to express the problem of finding two square numbers whose sum is also a square number. The general forms for the sides of a right-angled triangle are c^ -f h^, a^ — 1>\ 2ab, which clearly satisfy the condition {a' + by={a'-b'f + {2abY. The expression of the sides in this form Diophantos calls "form- ing a right-angled triangle from the numbers a and b." It is by this time unnecessary to observe that Diophantos does not use general numbers such as a, b but particular ones. " Forming a right-angled triangle from 7, 2 " means taking a right-angled triangle whose sides are 7'^ + 2', 7" — 2'^ 2 . 7 . 2, or o3, 4o, 28. § 5. Method of Limits. As Diophantos often has to find a series of numbers in ascending or descending order of magnitude : as also he does not admit negative solutions, it is often necessary for him to reject a solution which he has found by a straightforward method, in order to satisfy such conditions ; he is then very frequently obliged to find solutions of problems which lie within certain limits in order to replace the ones rejected. 1. A very simple case is the following: Required to find a value of X such that some power of it, x", shall lie between two assigned limits, given numbers. Let the given numbers bo a, b. Then Diophantos' method is : Multiply a and 6 both succes.sively by 2", 3", and so on until some (nf' power is seen which lies be- tween the two products. Thu.s suppose c" lith between up' and /*// ; 6—2 Il6 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. then we can put « = - , in which case the condition is satisfied, P for(-| lies between a and 6. & Exx. In IV. 34 Diopbantos finds a square between f and 2 thus : he multiplies by a square, 64 ; thus we have the limits 80 and 128; 100 is clearly a square lying between these limits ; hence (lo)'^ or f| satisfies the condition of lying between | and 2. Here of course Diophantos might have multiplied by any other square, as 16, and the limits would then have become 20 and 82, between which there lies the square 25, and so we should have f§ again as the square required. In VI. 23 a sixth power (a " cube-cube ") is required which lies between 8 and 16. Now the sixth powers of the first natural numbers are 1, 64, 729, 409 6... Multiply 8 and 16 (as in rule) by 2° or 64 and we have as limits 512 and 1024, and 729 lies between them ; therefore "^^-^^ is a sixth power such as was required. To multiply by 729 in this case would not give us a result. 2. Other problems of finding values of x agreeably to certain limits cannot be reduced to a general rule. By giving, however, a few instances, we may give an idea of Diophantos' methods in general. Q Ex. 1, In IV, 26 it is necessary to find x so that , x' + x lies between x and x+l. The first condition gives 8 > a;'' + a;^ Diophantos accordingly assumes 8 = {x+lY = x' + x' + '^^ + Jj, which is >x'' + .c\ Thus x = ^ satisfies one condition. It also Q is seen to satisfy the second, or -5-— < a; -f- 1 : but Diophantos X + X '■ practically neglects this condition, though it turns out to be satisfied. The method is, therefore, hero imperfect. Ex. 2. Find a value of x such that x>y^x''-C)0)<l-(x'-(y()), or x^ — 60 > ox, x^ - 60 < 'Sx. DIOPIIANTOS' MKTIIODS ()F SOLrTIuX. II7 Hence, says Diophantos, rr is <(: 11 nor > 12. Wi- liave already spoken (pp. 00, 91) of the reasoning by which h.- arrives at this result (by taking only one root of the quadratic, and taking the nearest integral limits). It is also required that a? — 60 shall be a square. Assuming then a;^ - 60 = {x - mf, x = — ^ — , 2m which must be > 11 < 12, Avhence m' + 60 > 22m, m" + 60 < 2hn, and (says Diophantos) in must therefore lie between 10 and 21. Accordingly he writes x'' - 60 = (x - 20)^ and x = llh, which is a value of x satisfying the conditions. § 6. Method of Approximation to Limits. We come now to a very distinctive method called by Dio- phantos 7rapia6T7]<i or irapiaorrjro'; dywyjj. The object of this is to find two or three square numbers whose sum is a given number, and each of which approximates as closely as possible to one and the same number and therefore to each other. This method can be best explained by giving Diophantos' two instances, in the first of which two such squares, and in the second three are required. In cases like this the principles cannot be so well described with general symbols as with con- crete numbers, whose properties are immediately obvious, and render separate expression of conditions unnecessary. Ex. 1. Divide 18 into two squares each of which > 6. Take \^ or 6i and find what small fraction -^ added to it makes it a square : thus 6^ + -^ must be a square, or 26 4- -, X y is a square. Diophantos puts 26 + \_ = [^+l)\ or 26/ + 1 =(5^+ 1)', whence ?/ = 10 and „ = t.W. •»!" - = in,' •""' *'' *" i^>'> ~ ^ J y' '"" J- 118 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. square = (f l)^ [The assumption of {oy + 1)^ is not arbitrary, for assume 26?/^ + 1 = {py + l)^ therefore y = ^ ^ ^ , and, since - should be a small proper fraction, therefore 5 is the most y suitable and the smallest possible value for ^^, 26 — p- being < Ip or p^ + 2jj + 1 > 27.] It is now necessary (says Diophantos) to divide 13 into two squares whose sides are each as near as possible to |^. Now the sides of the two squares of which 18 is by nature compounded are 3 and 2, and 3 is > fi by ^1 2 is < f^ by l^i ■ Now if 3 — -g^, 2 + ^ were taken as the sides of two squares their sum would be 2^^601 ^^^ 400 ' which is > 13. Accordingly Diophantos puts 3 - 9a;, 2 + ll.r, for the sides of the required squares, where x is therefore not exactly ^ but near it. Thus, assuming (3 -9a:)' + (2 + 11a;)' = 13, Diophantos obtains x = y^. Thus the sides of the required squares are \^\, f^. Ex. 2. Divide 10 into three squares such that each square is >3. Take ^o or 3^ and find what fraction of the form ^ added 9 to it will make it a square, i.e. make 30 + -^ a square or Wy'^ + 1, I 3 1 where - = - . X y DIOPHANTdS' METHODS OF SOLUTION. Ill) Diophautos writes 30/ + 1 = (r)y + 1)-, whence y = 2 and ^*- And 3^ + ^V = a square = '^' . [As before, if we assume 30//^ + 1 = {py + 1)*, 7 = , Z"' ^ , and since - must be a small proper fraction, 30 —;:>'' should < 2y; or p^+ 2jj + 1 > 81, and 5 is the smallest possible value of p. For this reason Diophantos chooses it.] We have now (says Diophantos) to make the sides of the required squares as near as may be to y. Now 10=9+l = 3^+(f)^+(|)^ and 3, f, 4 are the sides of three squares whose sum = 10. Bringing (3, f , 4) and y to a common denominator, wo have (f^, ^, M) and M. Now 3is>ffbyf§, f is<M by M. f is<Mby M- If then we took 3 - f^, f + f§, f + fi for the sides, the sum of their squares would be 3 (y )* or ^{f, which is > 10. Diophantos accordingly assumes as the sides of the three required squares 3 - Zox, f + 37a-, I + 31a-, where x must therefore be not exactly ^'^, but near it. Solving (3 - rox)' + (f + 37a,f + (4 + 3U-)^ = 10, or 10-llG.t-+3555a;'=10, we have x = ^-^ ; the required sides are therefore found to be sw. w. sw> and the squares 'UM^^> VW^'. "Mi^- The two instances here given, though only instiinces, serve perfectly to illustrate the method of Diophantos. To have put them generally with the use of algebniical symbols, nistead <»f 120 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. concrete numbers, would have rendered necessary the intro- duction of a large number of such symbols, and the number of conditions (e.g. that such and such an expression shall be a square) which it would have been necessary to express would have nullified all the advantages of this general treatment. As it only lies within my scope to explain what we actually find in Diophantos' work, I shall not here introduce certain investigations embodied by Poselger in his article " Beitrage zur TJnbestimmten Analysis," published in the Ahhandlungen der Koniglichen Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin Aus dem Jahre 1832, Berlin, 1834. One section of this paper Poselger entitles "Annaherungs-methoden nach Diophantus," and obtains in it, upon Diophantos' principles \ a method of approximation to the value of a surd which will furnish the same results as the method by means of continued fractions, except that the approxi- mation by what he calls the " Diophantine method " is quicker than the method of continued fractions, so that it may serve to expedite the latter ^ ^ "Wenn wir den Weg des Diophantos verfolgen." 2 "Die Diopliantisehe Mctbode kann also dazii diencn, die Convergcnz der Partialbriiche des Kettenbruchs zu beschlcunigen." K^r.r^. CHAPTER VI. § 1. THE PORISMS OF DIOPIIANTOS. We have already spoken (in the Historical Introduction) of the Porisms of Diophantos as having probably foiined a distinct part of the work of our author. We also riiscussed the question as to whether the Porisms now lost formed an integral portion of the Arithmetics or whether it was a com- pletely separate treatise. What remains for us to do under the head of Diophantos' Porisms is to collect such references to them and such enunciations of definite porisms as are directly given by Diophantos. If we confine our list of Porisms to those given under that name by Diophantos, it docs not therefore follow that many other theorems enunciated, assumed or implied in the extant work, but not distinctly called Porisms, may not with equal propriety be supposed to have been actually pro- pounded in the Ponsm^. For distinctness, however, and in order to make our assumptions perfectly safe, it will be better to separate what are actually called porisms from other theorems implied and assumed in Diophantos' problems. First then with regard to the actual Porisms. I shall not attempt to discuss here the nature of the proposition which was called a porism, for such a discussion would be irrelevant to my purpose. The Porisms themselves too have been well enumerated and explained by Nesselmann in his tenth chapter; he has also given, mth few omissions, the chief of the other theorems assumed by Diophantos as known. Of necessity, therefore, in this section and the next I shall have to cover very much the same ground, anil shall acconliugly bo a.s brief us may be. 122 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Porism 1. The first porism enunciated by Diopbantos occurs in v. 3. He says " We bave from tbe Porisms tbat if eacb of two numbers and tbeir product wben severally added to tbe same number produce squares, the numbers are the squares of two consecutive numbers \" This theorem is not correctly enunciated, for two consecutive squares are not the only two numbers which will satisfy the condition. For suppose x + a = m\ y + a = n^, xy+a= p^. Now by help of the first two equations we find xy + a= m^n^ — a {m^ + n^ — \)+ a^ and this is equal to ]f. In order that m\^ — a {m^ + n^ — l)-\-d^ may be a square certain conditions must be satisfied. One sufficient condition is m^ + ?i" — 1 = 2inn, or m — n = + 1, and this is Diopbantos* condition. But we may also regard 2«,8 rrrn a {m? + 71" - 1) + a'' = p^ as an indeterminate equation in m of which we know one solution, namely m = n ± 1. Other solutions are then found by substituting z + {ii ±1) for m, whence we have the equation {re -a)z' + 2 {n' (n ±l)-a{n±l)}z + {ii' - a) {n ± If - a(?r— 1) + a'^ = p^, or {7i' - a) / + 2 {n' - a) (w ± 1) ^ + {n (n ± 1) - af = p\ which is easy to solve in Diopbantos' manner, the absolute term being a square. But in the problem V. 3 tlwee numbers are required such that each of them, and the product of each pair, severally added ^ Kal iirel ^xoM*" ^'' '''O'S irophixaffiv, on (of hvo dpiO/Jiol iKarepds re Kai 6 vir^ avTuiv /nerd rod avTov SoOivTos ttoltj Tfrpdycovov, ■yt-ybvaaiv dwb Svo reTpayuvuv rwv KOLTk Tb ^f ijs. THE PORISMS OF DIOPHANTOS. 123 to a given number produce squares. Thus, if the third number be z, three more conditions must be added, namely, z + «, zx-\-a, yz + a should be squares. The two last conditions are satisfied, if m + 1 = n, by putting z = 2{a; + y) — 1 = 4/m" + 4??i + 1 — 4a, when xz + a= {m {2m + 1) - Sa}", yz + a= {m {2m + 3) - (2a - l)f , and this means of satisfying the conditions may have affected the formulating of the Porism. V. 4 gives another case of the Porism with — a for + a. Porism 2. In V. 5 Diophantos says* , " We have in the Porisms that in addition to any two consecutive squares we can find another number which, being double of the sum of both and increased by 2, makes up three numbers, the product of any pair of which ^lus the sum of that pair or the third number produces a square," i.e. m\ m^ + 2??i + 1 , 4 ( 7?i' + m + l), are three numbers which satisfy the conditions. The same porism is assumed and made use of in the follow- ing problem, v. 6. Porism 3 occurs in v. 19. Unfortunately the text of the enunciation is corrupt, but there can be no doubt that the correct statement of the porism is " The difference of two cubes can be transformed into the sum of two cubes." Diophantos contents himself with the mere enunciation and does not pro- ceed to effect the actual transformation. Thus we do not know his method, or how far he was able to prove the porism as a perfectly general theorem. The theorems upon the trans- formation of sums and differences of cubes were investigated by Vieta, Bachet and Format. 1 Kal txoiJ^o irdXi;/ (v toZs wopifffMacriv on iraai 56o Ttrpaywvoif toTj (tori t6 iint irpo<TevplaK€Tai irepos dptOubs 8i a)c divXaaiuv <jvv<ifj.<t>oripov Kal SvUt. fxtiiuiv, t/xji apidfiodi TTOtei tSv 6 vwd 6iroiu}vo!}i> idvTe irpoffXdiir] avvan<p!)Ttpov, iatnt Xoiw-di- «■<>•« TeTpd-ywvov. 124 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Vieta gives three problems on the subject ^ (Zetetica iv.). 1. Given two cubes, to find in rational numbers two others whose sum equals the difference of the two given ones. As a solution of a^-I/ = x^ H- y^, he finds _ a{a'-^h') _ hj^a'j- If) ^- a' + h' ' y~ a' + b' ' 2. Given two cubes, to find in rational numbers two others, a +0 -X y, X- ^3_^, , y ^,_^, . 3. Given two cubes, to find in rational numbers two others, whose difference equals the difference of the given ones; a -u -X y, X- ^3_^^3 , y- ^^,_^^, . In 1 clearly x is negative if 2b^>a^', therefore, to secure a "rational" result, (v-j > 2. But for a "rational" result in 8 we must have exactly the opposite condition, t5 < 2. Fermat, who apparently was the first to notice this, remarked that in con- sequence the processes 1 and 3 exactly supplement each other, 1 Poselger {Berlin Abhandhuigcn, 1832) has obtained tlicse results. He gets, e.g. the first as follows: Assume two cubes {a-xf, (mx-j3f, which are to be taken so that their sum = a3 - /33. Now (a-x)^ = a^-3a-x + 3ax--x\ (fftx - /3)3 = - /33 + 3?»/3-x - 3»i''/3x2 + m^a?. If then G)' and 3(TO2/3-a) Sap' ^~ m3-l a3 + /33' (a-x)3 + (mx-/3)8 = a3-/3», a(a3-2^)l THB PORlSMS OP DIOPHANTOS. 125 SO that by employing them successively we can effect the trans- formation of 1, even when Process 2 is always possible, therefore by the suitable com- bination of processes the transformation of a sum of two cubes into a difference, or a difference of two cubes into a sum of two others, is always practicable. Besides the Po)nsins, there are many other propositions assumed or implied by Diophautos which are not definitely called porisms, though some of them are very similar to the porisms just described. § 2. Theorems assumed or implied by Diophantos. Of these Nesselmann rightly distinguishes two classes, the first being of the nature of identical formulae, the second theorems relating to the sums of two or more square num- bers, &c. 1. The first class do not require enumeration in detail. We may mention one or two examples, e.g. that the expressions C^-) - ah and a" (a -h 1)' + a' + (a + 1)" are squares, and that a {a^ — a) -\- a + (a^ — a) is always a cube. Again, Nesselmann thinks that Diophantos made use of the separation of a' — 1/ into factors in the solution of v. 8, in which he gives the result without clearly showing his mode of procedure in obtaining it ; though its separability into factors is nowhere expressly mentioned, and is not made use of in certain places where we should most naturally expect to find it, e.g. in iv. 12. 2. But ftxr more important than these identical formulae are the numerous propositions in the Theory of Numbers which we find stated or assumed as known in the Arithmetics. It is, in general, in explanation or extension of these that Fermat wrote his famous notes. So far as Diophantos is concerned it is extremely difficult, (jr rather impossible, to .say how far these 126 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. propositions rested for him upon rigorous mathematical demon- stration, and how far, on the other hand, his knowledge of them was merely empirical and derived only from trial in particular cases, whereas he enunciates them or assumes them to hold in all possible cases. But the objection to assuming that Diophantos had a completely scientific system of investigating these propositions, as opposed to a merely empirical knowledge of them, on the ground that he does not prove them in the present treatise, would seem to apply equally to Fermat's o-svn theorems set forth in these notes, except in so far as we might be inclined to argue that Diophantos could not, in the period to which he belongs, have possessed such machinery of demon- stration as Format. Even supposing this to be true, we should be very careful in making assertions as to what the ancients could or could not prove, when we consider how much they did actually accomplish. And, secondly, as regards machinery of proof, we have seen that up to Fermat's time there had been very little advance upon Diophantos in the matter of notation. It will be best to enumerate here in order the principal propositions of this kind which we find in Diophantos, observing in each case any indication, which is perceptible, of the extent which we may suppose Diophantos' knowledge of the Theory of Numbers to have reached. It will be necessary and useful to refer to Fermat's notes occasionally. The question of the merits of Fermat's notes themselves this is not the place to inquire into. It is well known that he almost universally enunciates the theorems contained in these notes without proof, and gives as his reason for not inserting the proofs that his margin was too small, and so on. It is considered, however, that as his theorems are always true, he must necessarily have proved them rigorously. Concerning this statement I will only remark that in the note to v. 25 Format addresses himself to the solution of a problem which was " most difficult and had troubled him a long time," and says that he has at last found a general solution. Of this he gives a demonstration wliich is hopelessly wrong, and which vitiates the solution completely. THE PORISMS OF DIOPHANTOS. ] 27 (a) Theorems in Diophantos respecting the comjyosition of numbers as the sum of two squares. 1. Any square number can be resolved into two squares in any number of ivays, li. 8, 9. 2. Any number luhich is the sum of two squares can be resolved into two other squares in any number of ways, u. 10. N.B. It is implied throughout that the squares may be fractional, as well as integral. 3. If there are two whole numbers each of tuhich is the sum of tiuo squares, their product can be resolved into the sum of two squares in two ways, iii. 22. The object of ill. 22 is to find four rational right-angled triangles having the same hypotenuse. The method is this. Form two right-angled triangles from (a, b), (c, d) respectively, viz. a== + b\ a' - b\ 2ab, c' + d', c'-cr, 2cd. Multiplying all the sides of each by the hypotenuse of the other, we have two triangles having the same hypotenuse, {a' + h'){c'+d^), {a'-b'){c' + d?l 2ab{c' + d'), (a' + b') (c'+ cf), (a' + b') {& - d'), 2cd (a^ + b'). Two other triangles having the same hypotenuse are got by using the theorem enunciated, viz. (a' + ¥) (c' + d') = (ac ± bdf + (ad + be)', and the triangles are formed from ac ± bd, acl + be, being (a' + b') (c* + d'), 4abcd + (rr - b') (c' - d"), 2 (ac + bd) {ad - be), {a' + 6") {c' + d'), ^abcd - {a' - b') (c' - d'), 2 {ac - bd) {ad + be). In Diophantos' case a' + b' = V + 2"- = 5, d' + d'=2' + :i'=U; and the triangles are (65, 52, 39), (65, 60, 2o), (65, 63. 16), (65, c>i>, 33). 128 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. [If certain relations hold between a, h, c, d this method fails. Diophantos has provided against them by taking two right- angled triangles viro iXax^o-Toov dptOfiwv (3, 4, 5), (5, 12, 13)]. Upon this problem Fermat remarks that (1) a prime number of the form ^n + 1 can only be the hypotenuse of a right-angled triangle in one way, the square of it in two ways, «&;c. (2) If a prime number made up of two squares be multiplied by another prime also made up of two squares, the product can be divided into two squares in two ways ; if the first is mul- tiplied by the square of the second, in three ways, &c. Now we observe that Diophantos has taken for the hypotenuse of the first two right-angled triangles the first tiuo prime numbers of the form 4n + 1, viz. 5 and 13, both of which numbers are the sum of two squares, and, in accordance with Format's remark, they can each be the hypotenuse of one single right-angled triangle only. It does not, of course, follow from this selection of 5 and 13 that Diophantos was acquainted with the theorem that every prime number of the form 4?i + 1 is the sum of two squares. But, when we remark that he multiplies 5 and 13 together and observes that the product can form the hypotenuse of a right-angled triangle in four ways, it is very hard to resist the conclusion that he was acquainted with the mathematical facts stated in Format's second remark on this problem. For clearly 65 is the smallest number which can be the hypotenuse of four rational right-angled triangles ; also Diophantos did not find out this fact simply by trijing all numbers up to G5 ; on the contrary he obtained it by multiplying together the first two prime numbers of the form 4?j-f- 1, in a perfectly scientific manner. This remarkable problem, then, serves to show pretty con- clusively that Diophantos bad considerable knowledge of the properties of numbers which arc the sum of two squares. 4. Still more remarkable is a condition of possibility of solution prefixed to the problem v. 12. The object of this problem is "to divide 1 into two parts such that, if a given number is added to either part, the result will be a square." Unfortunately the text of the added condition is very much THE PDKISMS (^F Dlnl'HANTOS. 1l>!» corrupted. There is no doubt, however, about the first few words, " The given number must not be odd." i.e. No number of the form 4/i-|- 3 [or 4« - 1] can be the sum of two squares. The text, however, of the latter half of the condition is, in Bachet's edition, in a hopeless state, and the point cannot be settled without a fresh consultation of the Mss.^ The true con- dition is given by Fermat thus. " The given number mu.st not be odd, and the double of it increased by one, when, divided by the greatest square which measures it, mu^st not be divisible by a pnme number of the form 4h— 1." (Note upon v. 12; also in a letter to Roberval). There is, of course, room for any number of conjectures as to what may have been Diophantos' words'. There would seem to be no doubt that in Diophantos' condition there was something about "double the number" (i.e. a number of the form 4n), also about "greater by unity" and "a prime number." From our data, then, it would appear that, if Dio- phantos did not succeed in giving the complete sufficient and necessary condition stated by Fermat, he must at all events have made a close approximation to it. 1 Bachet's test has bel 8r] tov diS6iJLevoi> n-qn irepiaaov iXvai, firire 6 BiirXafflui' avTov q fi^a. fjceL^ova ^r) fxipos 5 . fj fxerpdrai viro rot a°". s°". He also says that a Vatican ms. reads /nTjre 6 diirXajlujv avrov api9iJ.ov fioudSa d. fiell^ova ^XV M^pos Tiraprov, fj neTpelrai viro tov irpwrov apiO/j-ov. Neither does Xylander help us much. He frankly tells us that he cannot understand the jmssage. ' ' Imitari statueram bonos grammaticos hoc loco, quorum (ut aiunt) est multa nescirc. Ego vcru noscio hoic non multa, scd pacnc omnia. Quid enim (ut reliqua taccam) est /xrjTe 6 onrXaalijsv avrov ap no a, &c. quae causae liuius irpocoi.opi.dfiov, quae processus ? immo qui processus, quae operatic, quae solutio?" * Nesselmann discusses an attempt made by Schulz to correct the text, and himself suggests nrfre rbv 8nr\affiova avrov apiOnov /xovdSi fitl^ova fx^iv, 6s fie- rpeirai vir6 rivoi irpurov api.6y.ov. But this ignores /i^pos riraprov and is not satisfactory. Haukel, however (Gesch.d. Math. p. 169), says: "Ich zweifele nicht, dass die von den Msscr. arg entstellte Determination so zu lesen ist: Sei Si) rbv 5iW/i*ror Urire ntpicabv ehai, /J-rire rov dnrXacrlova ai/Tou apiOnbv fjLovdSi a fitl^ova fitrptiadcu iino TOV irpil)Tov apid/iov, 8s aj' /louadi d ixd^uv IxV t'-^po^ TirapTov." Now this cor- rection, which exactly gives Fermat's condition, seems a decidedly probable one. Here the words p.ipos rirapTov find a place; and, secondly, the rept'tition of liovaSi d nd^uv might well confuse a copyist, tov for tov is of course natural enough ; Nesselmann reads nvos for tov. H. I). i» 130 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. We thus see (a) that Diophantos certainly knew that no number of the form 4??. + 3 could be the sum of two squares, and (b) that he had, at least, advanced a considerable way to- wards the discovery of the true condition of this problem, as quoted above from Fermat. (6) On numbers luhich are the sum of three squares. In the problem v. 14 a condition is stated by Diophantos respecting the form of a number which added to three parts of unity makes each of them a square. If a be this number, clearly 3a + 1 must be divisible into three squares. Respecting the number a Diophantos says "It must not be 2 or any multiple of 8 increased by 2." i. e. a number of the form 24>i + 7 cannot be the sum of three squares. Now the factor 3 of 24 is irrelevant here, for with respect to three this number is of the form 3w + 1, and this so far as 3 is concerned might be a square or the sum of two or three squares. Hence we may neglect the factor 3 in 24/i. We must therefore credit Diophantos with the knowledge of the fact that no number of the form 8n + 7 can be the sum of three squares. This condition is true, but does not include all the numbers which cannot be the sum of three squares, for it is not true that all numbers which are not of the form 871 + 7 are made up of three squares. Even Bachet remarked that the number a might not be of the form 32?i -)- 9, or a number of the form 9G>i+ 28 cannot be the sum of three squares. Fermat gives the conditions to which a must be subject thus: Write down two geometrical series (common ratio of each 4), the hrst and second series beginning respectively with 1, 8, 14 16 C4 256 1024 4096 8 32 128 512 2048 8192 32768 then a must not bo (1) any number obtained by taking twice liny term of tlu' ii[)per scries ami adding all the preceding terms, THE PORISMS OF DIOPHAN'TOS. l.'H or (2) the number found by adding to the numbers so obtained any multiple of the correspondino: term of the second series. Thus (a) must not be, 8?i + 2.1 = 8" + 2, 32/1 + 2.4 + 1 = 32« + 9, 128n + 2.1G + 4<+ 1 =128n + 87, ol2n + 2.64 + 16 + 4 + 1 = 512n + 149, &c. Again there are other problems, e.g. v. 22, in which, though conditions are necessary for the possibility of solution, none are mentioned; but suitable assumptions are tacitly made, without rules by which they must be guided. It does not follow from the omission to state such rules that Diophantos was ignorant of even the minutest points connected with them ; as however we have no definite statements, it is best to desist from specula- tion in cases of doubt. (c) Goinposition of naniberti an the sum of four squares. Every number is either a square or the sum of two, three or four squares. This Avell-known theorem, enunciated by Format in his note to Diophantos iv. 31, shows at once that any number can be divided into four squares either integral or fractional, since any square number can be divided into two other squares, integral or fractional. We have now to look for indications in the Arithmetics as to how far Diophantos was acquainted with the properties of numbers as the sum of four squares. Un- fortunately it is impossible to decide this question with any- thing like certainty. There are three problems [iv. 31, 32 and V. 17] in which it is required to divide a number into four squares, and from the absence of mention of any condition to which the number must conform, considering that in both cases where a number is to be divided into three or two Sipiares [v. 14 and 12] he does state a condition, we should probably be right in inferring that Diophantos was aware, at least empirically, if not scientifically, that any number could be divided into four squares. That he was able to prove the theorem scientifically it would be rash to assert, though it i.s not impossible. But wc 9—2 132 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. may at least be certain that Diophantos came as near to the proof of it as did Bachet, who takes all the natural numbers up to 120 and finds by trial that all of them can actually be ex- pressed as squares, or as the sum of two, three or four squares in whole numbers. So much we may be sure that Diophantos could do, and hence he might have empirically satisfied himself that in any case occurring in practice it is possible to divide any number into four squares, integral or fractional, even if he could not give a rigorous mathematical demonstration of the general theorem. Here again we must be content, at least in our present state of knowledge of Greek mathematics, to remain in doubt. CHAPTER VII. HOW FAR WAS DIOPHANTOS ORIGINAL ? § 1. Of the many vexed questions relating to Diophantos none is more difficult to pronounce upon than that which we propose to discuss in the present chapter. Here, as in so many other cases, diametrically opposite views have been taken by au- thorities equally capable of judging as to the merits of the ca.se. Thus Bachet calls Diophantos "optimum praeclarissiniumque Lo- gisticae parentem," though possibly he means no more by this than what he afterwards says, "that he was the first algebraist of whom we know." Cossali quotes "T abate Andres" as the most thoroughgoing upholder of the originality of Diophantos. M. Tannery, however, whom we have before had occasion to men- tion, takes a completely opposite view, being entirely unwilling to credit Diophantos with being anything more than a learned compiler. Views intermediate between these extremes are those of Nicholas Saunderson, Cossali, Colebrooke and Nessel- mann; and we shall find that, so far as we are able to judge from the data before us, Saunderson's estimate is singularly good. He says in his Elements of Algebra (1740), "Diophantos is the first writer on Algebra we meet with among the ancients ; not that the invention of the art is particularly to be ascribed to him, for he has nowhere taught the fundamental rules and principles of Algebra; he treats it everywhere as an art already known, and seems to intend, not so much to teach, as to culti- vate and improve it, by applying it to certain indeterminate problems concerning square and cube numbers, right-angled triangles, &c., which till that time seemed to have been either not at all considered, or at least not regularly treateil c»f. These 134 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. problems are very curious and ratertaining; but j^et in the resolution of them there frequently occur difficulties, which nothing less than the nicest and moc^ refined Algebra, applied with the utmost skill and judgment, could ever surmount: and most certain it is that, in this way, no man ever extended the limits of analytic art further than Diophantos has done, or dis- covered greater penetration and judgment; whether we consider his wonderful sagacity and peculiar artifice in forming such proper positions as the nature of the questions under considera- tion required, or the more than ordinary subtilty of his reason- ing upon them. Every particular problem puts us upon a new way of thinking, and furnishes a fresh vein of analytical treasure, which, considering the vast variety there is of them, cannot but be very instructive to the mind in conducting itself through almost all difficulties of this kind, wherever they occur." § 2. We will now, without anticipating our results further, proceed to consider the arguments for and against Diophantos' originality. But first we may dispose of the supposition that Greek algebra may have been derived from Arabia. This is rendered inconceivable by what we know of the state of learning in Ai'abia at different periods. Algebra cannot have been developed in Arabia at the time when Diophantos wrote ; the claim of Mohammed ibn Musa to be considered the first important Arabian algebraist, if not actually the first, is ap- parently not disputed. On the other hand Rodet has shown that M(jhammed ibn Musii was largely indebted to Greece. There is moreover great dissimilarity between Greek and Indian algebra ; this would seem to indicate that the two were evolved independently. We may also here dispose of Bombelli's strange statement that he found that Diophantos very often quoted Indian authors \ We do not find in Diophantos, as we have him, a single reference to any Indian author whatever. There is therefore some difficulty in understanding Bombelli's positive statement. It is at first sight a tempting hypothesis to suppose that the "frequent quotations" occurred in parts of Diophantos' ^ "Ed in detta opera abbiamo ritrovato, ch' egli assai volte cita gli autori indiani, col cho rui lia fatto conoscere, che questa disciplina appo gl' indiani prima lu che agli arabi." HOW FAR WAS DIOPHANTOS ORIGINAL? 135 work contained only in the MS. which Bombclli used. But wo know that not a single Indian author is mentioned in that MS. We can only explain the remark by supposing that Bombelli confused the text and the scholia of Maximus Planudes ; for in the latter mention is made of an " Indian method of multiplica- tion." Such must be considered the meagre foundation for Bombelli's statement. There is not, then, mucli doubt that, if we are to find any writers on algebra earlier than Diophantos to whom he was indebted, we must seek for them among his own countrymen. § 3. Let us now consider the indications bearing upon the present question which are to be found in Diophantos' own work. Distinct allusions to previous writers there are none with the sole exception of the two references to Hypsikles which occur in the fragment on Polygonal Numbers. These references, how- ever, are of little or no importance as affecting the question of Diophantos' originality; for, so far as they show anything, they show that Diophantos was far in advance of Hypsikles in his treatment of polygonal numbers. And, so far as we can judge of the progress which had been made in their theoretical treat- ment by writers anterior to Diophantos from what we know of such arithmeticians as Nikomachos and Theon of Smyrna, we must conclude that (even if we assume that the missing part of Diophantos' tract on this subject was insignificant as compared with the portion which has survived) Diophantos made a great step in advance of his predecessors. His method of dealing with polygonal numbers is new ; and we look in vain among his precursors for equally general propositions with regard to such numbers or for equally scientific proofs of known pro- perties. Not that previous arithmeticians were uuaccjuaiuted with Diophantos' propositions as applied to particular jwlygonal numbers, and even as applicable generally ; but of their general application they convinced themselves only empirically, and by the successive evolution of higher and higher orders of sucli numbers. We may here remark, with respect to the term "arithmetic" which Diophantos applies to his whole work, that he is making a new use of the term. According to the previously ucc.-j»t.-<l 136 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. distinction of apLdfiijriKi] and XoytariKT] the former treats of the abstract properties of numbers, considered apart from their mutual relations, XoyiaTCKi] of problems involving the relations of concrete numbers. XoyiartKi], then, includes algebra. Ac- cording to the distinction previously in vogue the term dpid- fiTjTiKi] would properly apply only to Diophantos' tract on Polygonal Numbers ; but, as in the six books of Diophantos the numbers are treated as abstract, he drops the distinction. § 4. Next to direct references to the names of predecessors, we must look to the language of Diophantos, in order to see whether there is any implication that anything which he teaches is new. And in this regard we might naturally expect that the preface or dedication to Dionysios would be important. It is as follows : Trjv evpeaiv rwv iv Toh dpi6p.ol<i irpo^X'qiicnoiv, TifiicoTari fioL Aiovvcrte, jivooaKcov ere a7rovSai(o<; e')(0VTa ixadeiv, opyavajcrat rrjv fieOoSov €7reipd6r)v, dp^(i/ji€po<i d(f wv crvi'iaTrjKe rd Trpdy/jiaTa Oefxekicov, v7roar7]aai Tt)v iv Tol<i dpi6fioL<; <pvaiv re Kol hvvafJiLV. Laa)<i fiev ovv hoKel to Trpdyfjba Sva-^^^epearepov, eVeiS?) iMrjTTW yvwptyiov iari, hvaekinaTOL yap et? KaropOuxxLV elaiv al rwv dp'^^ofjiiicov -v^up^ai, o/iw? 8' evKardXTjTrrov aoc jevt]- aerat Btd rrjv arjv irpodvp.Cav koI Tr)v e^rjv dirohet^Lv' ra^eta fydp et9 fx,d6r](rLV eTriOufiia irpoaXa^ovaa ScSa^yjv. The first expression which would seem to carry with it an indication of the nature of the work as conceived by Diophantos himself is opyavwxrat rrjv fiedoSov. The word opyavwaat has of itself been enough to convince some that the whole matter and method of the Arithmetics were originaP. Cossali and Colebrooke are of opinion that the language of the preface implies that some part of what Diophantos is about to teach is new". But Montucla 1 Cf. the view of " 1' abate Andres " as stated by Cossali: "Diofanto stesso parla in guisa, che sembra mostrare assai cLiaramente d' essere stata sua iuven- zione la dottrina da lui proposta, e spiegata nulla sua opera." " "A me par troppo il dire, che da quelle cspressioni non ne esca alcuu lume; mi pare troppo il restingcre la novita, che annunziano, al metodo, che nell' opera di Diofanto regnas si mira ; ma parmi anche troppo il dedurne essere state Diofanto in assoluto sonso inventor dell' analisi." Cossali. "He certainly intimates that some part of what he proposes to teach is new: Tffwj fxh oiV doKel rd irpayfia 5v<TXf p^<rTepoi' iireiSri firiiru) yvdpi/xoi' iari: while in other places (Def. 10) he expects the student to be previously exercised in the HOW FAR WAS DIOPHANTOS ORIGINAL ? 137 does not go too far when he says that the preface does not give us any chie. The word op-^avwaai is translated by Bachet as " fabricari," but this can hardly be right. It means " to set forth in order", to "systematise"; and such an expression may per- fectly well apply if there were absolutely nothing new in the work, and Di(iphantos were merely writing a text-book simply giving in a compact and systematic form the sum and substance of previous labours. The words eVetS?} /u,7;7r&) ^vwpiixov iariv have also been made use of by advocates of Diophantos' claim to originality; but, looked at closely, they clearly imply no more than that the methods were unknown to Dionysios. The phrase is subjective, as is shown by the following words, SuaiX- TTicTTOC yap eh Karopdcocriv eicriv al twv dp^^^ofievav ylrv^ai. The language of the definitions also has been variously understood. "L' abate Andres" concluded from their very presence at the beginning of the book that Diophantos is minutely explaining preliminary matter as if he were speaking of a new science as yet unknown to others. But the fact is that he does not minutely explain preliminary matter ; he gives an extremely curt summary of the necessary preliminaries. Moreover he makes no stipulations as to what he will choose to call by a certain name. Thus a square KaXelrai 8vvafii<i : the unknown quantity is called dpidfio'i, and its sign is ?•*. Again, he says Xeiyfri^ iirt Xel^jrtv TroXXaTrXaaiaadelcra Troiei virap^iv, Minus multiplied hij minus (jives j)lus^. In the 10th algorithm of Algebra. The seeming contradiction is reconciled by conceiving tlic principles to have been known, but the application of thorn to a certain class of problems concerning numbers to have been new." Ci'lebrooke. • I adhere to this translation of the Greek because, tiiough not quite literal, it serves to convey the meaning intended better than any other version. It is not easy to translate it literally. Mr James Gow (History of Creek Mnthemntict, p. 108), says that it should properly be translated "A difference multiplied by a difference makes an addition." This translation seems unfortunate, because (1) it is difficult, if not impossible, to attach any meaning to it, (2) Xc^jj and vvap^is are correlatives, whereas "difference" and "addition" are not. If either of these words are used at all, we shoidd surely say either "A dillerenco multiplied by a diffirence makes a sum", or "A subtraction multiplietl by a subtraction makes an addition." The true meaning of Xer^ii must be " a falling- short" or "a wanting", and that of i-Vapfis "a presence" or "a forthcoming". If, therefore, a literal translation is desired, I would suggest " A wanting multi- 138 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Definition he says how important it is that the beginner should be familiar with the operations of Addition, Subtraction, &c.; and in the 11th Definition the rules for reducing a quadratic to its simplest form are given in a dogmatic authoritative manner which would only be appropriate if the operation were generally known : in fine, the definitions, in so far as they have any bear- ing on the present question, seem to show that Diophantos does not wish it to be understood that they contain anything new. He gives them as a short but necessary resume of known prin- ciples, more for the puriDose of a reminder than as laying any new foundation. To assert, then, that Diophantos invented algebra is, to say the least, an exaggeration, as we can even now see from the indications above mentioned. His notation, so far as it is a nota- tion, is apparently new ; but, as it is merely in the nature of abbreviations for complete words, it cannot be said to constitute any great advance in algebra. § 5. I may here mention a curious theory propounded by Wallis, that algebra was not a late invention at all, but that it was in common use by the Greeks from the time of their earliest discoveries in the field of geometry, that in fact they disco- vered their geometrical theorems by algebra, but were extremely careful to conceal the fact. But to believe that the gi'eat Greek geometers were capable of this sj^stematic imposition is scarcely possible\ plied by a wanting makes a forthcoming". But, thongb this would be correct, it loses by obscurity more than it gains by accuracy. 1 "De Algebra, prout apud Euclideu Pappum Diophantum et scriptores habetur. Mihi quidem extra omne dubium est, veteribus cognitam fuisse et usu comprobatam istiusmodi artcm aliquam Investigaudi, qualis est ea quam nos Algebram dicinius : Indequc derivatas esse quae apud cos conspiciuntur prolixiores et intricatae Demonstrationcs. Aliosque ex recentioribus mecum bae in re sen tire comperio. ...Hanc autem artem Investigaudi Veteres occu- luerunt sedulo: contenti, per demonstrationes Ajjagogicas (ad absurdum seu impossibile ducentcs si quod assorunt negetur) asscnsum cogere; potins quam directum methodum indicare, qua fuerint inventae propositiones illae quas ipsi aliter et per ambages demonstrant." (Wallis, Opera, Vol. ii.) Bossut is certainly right in bis criticism of this theory. "Si cette opinion 6tait vraic, elle inculperait cch grands hommes d'unc charlatancrie systc^matique et traditionolle, ce qui est invraiscmblable en soi-nieme et ne pourrait Stre admis sans les preuves les plus rvidentes. Or, sur quoi une telle opinion cst-elle HOW FAR WAS DIOPHANTOS ORIGINAL? 139 § 6. What remains to be said may, perhaps, be best arranged under the principal of Diophantos' methods as headings ; and it will be advisable to take them in order, and consider in each case whether anything is anticipated by Greek authors whose works we know. For it would seem useless to speculate on what they might have written. If we once leave the safe ground of positive proveable fact, such an investigation as the present could lead to no useful result. It is this fact which makes so much of what M. Tannery has written on this stibject seem unsatisfactory. He states that Diophantos was no more than a learned compiler, like Pappos : though it may be ob- served that this is a comparison by no means discreditable to the former ; he does not think it necessary to explain the com- plete want of any other works on the same subject previous to Diophantos. The scarcity of information respecting similar previous labours, says M. Tannery, is easily explicable on other grounds which do not concern us here\ The nature of the work joined to what we know of Diophantos would seem to prove his statement, thinks M. Tannery ; thus the work is very unequal, some operations being even clumsy*. But we are not likely to admit that inequality in a work is any evidence against originality ; for what great genius always equalled himself? Certainly, if we cannot find any certain traces of anticipation of Diuphantos by his predecessors, he is entitled to the benefit of any doubt. Besides, given that Diophantos was not the in- ventor of any considerable portion of his science, the merit of having made it known and arranged it scientifically is little less than that of the discoverer of the whole, and very much greater than that of the discoverer of a small fraction of it. First with regard to the use of the unknown quantity by fondce? Sur quelques anciennes propositions, tirc^es principaleraent du trei- ziiSme livre d'Euclide, oti Ton a cru reconnaitre I'alK^bre, mais qui ne siipposont r^ellement que I'analyse gtom^trique, dans laquelle les anciens C-taient fort exer- ccs, commc je I'ai d6ja marqu6. II parait certain que Ics (Jroca n'ont commcuc<5 a connaitre I'alt^ubre qu'au temps de Diophante." (Ilistoire Gin(rale tUn Math/- viatiques par Charles Bossut, Paris, 1810.) The truth of the last sentence is not so clear. ' lluUrtin (ipx Srifiirfx miithi'mnl'ujnex ct dgtronomiqnt's, 1870, p. 261. 2 Ibid. 140 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Diophaiitos. There is apparently no indication that dpidfi6<i, in the restricted sense appropriated to it by Diophantos, was em- ployed by any other extant writer without an epithet to mark the use, and certainly Bvvafii<; as restricted to the square of the unknown is Diophautine. But the employment of an unknown quantity and calculations in terms of it are found before Dio- phantos' time. To find a thing in general expressions is, with Diophantos, to find it iv dopiaro). Cf. the problem IV. 20. But the same word is used in the same sense by Thymaridas in his Epanthema. We know of him only through lamblichos, but he probably belongs to the same period as Theon of Smyrna. Not only does Thymaridas distinguish between numbers which are wpiafMevoL (known) and doptaroc (unknown), but the Epan- thema gives a rule for solving a particular set of simultaneous equations of the first degree with any number of variables. The artifice employed is the same as in i. 16, 17, of Diophantos. This account which lamblichos gives of the Epanthema of Thy- maridas is important for the history of algebra. For the essence of algebra is present here as much as in Diophantos, the " nota- tion" employed by him showing only a very slight advance. Thus we have here another proof, if one were needed, that Diophantos did not invent algebra. Diophantos was acquainted with the solution of a mixed or complete quadratic. This solution he promises in the 11th Definition to explain later on. But, as we have before remarked, the promised exposition never comes, at least in the part of his work which we pos.se.ss. He shows, however, sufficiently plainly in a number of problems the exact rule which he followed in the solution of such equations. The question therefore arises : Did Diophantos himself discover and formulate his purely arithmetical rule for solving complete determinate quadratics, or was the method in use before his time ? Cossali points out that the propositions 58, 59, 84 and 85 of Euclid's BeSofieva give in a geometrical form the solution of the equations ax — x^= b, ax -i x' = b, and of " A . xy = b) It was only necessary to transform the geometry into algebra, in HOW FAR WAS DIOPHANTOS ORIGINAL? 141 order to obtain Diophantos' rule ; and this might have been done by some mathematician intermediate between Euclid and Diophantos, or by Diophantos himself. It is quite possible that it may have been in this manner that the rule arose; and, if that is the case, it is probable that the transformatii^n referred to was accomplished by some matliematician not much later than Euclid himself; for Heron of Alexandria {circa 100 R.C.) already used a similar rule\ We hear moreover of a work on quadratic equations by Hipparchos (probably ciixa IGl — 126 B.C.)*. Thus we may conclude that Diophantos' rule for solving complete quadratics was not his discovery. § 7. But it is not upon Diophantos' solution of determinate equations that the supporters of his claim to originality rely ; it is rather that part of his work which forms its main subject, ^ namely, Indeterminate or Semi-determinate Analysis. Accord- / ingly it is to that that the term Diophantine analysis is applied. We should therefore look more especially for anticipations of Diophantine analysis, if we would be in a position to judge as to Diophantos' originality. The foundation of semi-determinate analysis was laid by Pythagoras. Not only did he propound the geometrical theorem that in a right-angled triangle the square on the hypotenuse is equal to the sum of the squares on the other two sides, but he applied it to numbers and gave a rule — of somewhat narrow application, it is true — for finding an infinite number of right- angled triangles whose sides are all rational numbers. His rule, expressed in algebraical form, asserts that if there are three numbers of the form 2m'^ - 2wi -t- 1, 2m^ — 2/n, and 1m — 1, they form a right-angled triangle. This rule applies clearly to that particular case only in which two of the numbers differ by unity, i.e. that particular case of Diophantos' general form for a right-angled triangle (m* -^-n^ w' - n"", 2mn) in which in-ii = l. But Pythagoras' rule is an attempt to deal with the general problem of Diophantos, II. 8, 9. Plato gives another form f.ir a » Cf. Cantor, pp. 341, 342. The solution of a quailratio \va.>< for Heron no more than a matter of arithmetical calcnlation. He solved such e<iuationH by making both sides complete squares. 2 Cf. Cantor, p. 313. 142 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. rational right-angled triangle, namely (w^ + 1, m^—l, 2;/i), which is that particular case of the form used by Diophantos in which 71=1. Euclid, Book x. prop. 29 is the same problem as Dioph. II. 8, 9, Diophantos improving upon Euclid's solution. In compar- ing, however, Euclid's arithmetic with that of Diophantos we should remember that with Euclid arithmetic is still geometry: a fact which accounts for his marvellously-developed doctrine of irrational and incommensurable numbers. In Diophantos the connection with arithmetic and geometry is severed, and irrational numbers are studiously avoided throughout his work. There is another certain case of the solution of an indeter- minate equation of the second degree in rational numbers before Diophantos. Theon of Smyrna, in his work Twv Kara fiaOrjfia- TLKTjv '^(^p'rjcrl/xcov et9 r})v rov TI\dTcovo<i dvayvcoaLv [sc. expositio, say the editors], gives a theorem Trepl irXsvpiKoov Kal Sia/xerpiKcov dpLd/xoov. From this theorem we derive immediately any number of solutions of the equations provided that we can find, by trial or otherwise, one solution of either. Theon does not make this application of his theorem : he solved a somewhat important problem of the second degree in indeterminate analysis without knowing it. There is an allusion to the doctrine of Side- and Diagonal-numbers in Proclus, Comment, on Euclid iv. p. 111. § 8. Such are the data upon which Nesselmann founded his view as to the originality of our author. But M. Tannery has tried to show, by reference to a famous problem, that still more difficult questions in indeterminate analysis had been propounded before the time of Diophantos. This problem is known by the name of the " Cattle-problem " ; it is an epigram, and is com- monly attributed to Archimedes. It was discovered by Lessing, and his discussion of it may be found in Zur Geschichte und Litteratur (Braunschweig, 1773), p. 421 seqq. I have quoted it below according to the text given by Lessing'. The title does 1 I have unfortunately not been able to consult llic critical Wdik on this epigram by Dr J. Struvc anil Dr K. L. Stiuvc, father and son (Altona, 1H21). s HOW FAR WAS DIOPHANTOS ORIGINAL? 143 not actually imply that Archimetles was the author. Of the two divisions into which it falls the second leads to an induter- My information about it is derived at second-hand from Nesselmann. LessinR's text can hardly be perfect, but it seems better to give it as it is without emen- dation. nPOBAHMA oirep 'APXIMHAH2 iv ^Trtypd/jL/j.affiv fvpwv TOiS iv 'AXe^avdpeigi wepl ravra Trpayp-aTov/idfoi^ t'tfTeiv aTricTciXtv if TTJ TTpbs "RpaToaOivrjv rhv Kvprivaiov eTn(7To\fj. nXijdiii' ijeXloio (SoCoi>, u ^eive, pArp-qffov, <f>povTlb' eiricrTrjcras, el /xer^x^'J ffO(pir]s, iroffffij dp' iv ireStois HiKeXrjs ttot' (^6ffKeTo vrjffov Qpivad-qs, rerpaxv (rri^ea Saffffafi^v-q Xpo^V" oXXaaaovra' t6 iih XevKoio yaXaKTos, Kvav4(i> 8' irepov xpw/toTt Xa/iirdfievov, dXXoye /xiv ^avObf, t6 di iroiKlXoy. 'Ev 5e eKaartf) aricpet i<rav ravpoi Tr\i}de<yL ^pidbiievoL, av/x/jLeTpi-qs TOLTJade TerenxoTer dpydrpixas fxiv Kvaviuv Taupojv r]/j.icr€L rjdi rplrif), Kal ^av^ots (T6/jLTra(Tiv taovs, w ^eive, vb-qaov. Avrdp Kvaviovs t^ rerpdrip fiipei /MiKTOXpbuv Kal ir^/XTTTif), ?Tt ^avdo'ial re iraji. Toys 5' viroXeiiro/xifOis iroiKiXbxjx^o.^ adpei dpyfvvCiv ravpwv ^KTip p-epei, f^So/udrtf. re Kal ^avOoh avrous irdcriv laa^op.ivovs. OrfXeiaiai Si j3ov<Ti rdo' ^TrXero" XevKorpixfS p-fv r)(Tav ffvpLirdffrjs Kvavirfs dyeXtjs rtfi TpiTdT(f re fiipei Kal T€TpdT(f} drptKis Iffat. A&rip Kvdveai t<J) Tirpdri^j re waXiv /UKTOXpowu Kal irifiirrifi 6/j.ov pJpei Iffd^ovro <Ti>v TaipoLS irda'r)% eh vofiov ipxop^vris. Savdorpix^^y dyeXijs W/urrT(f> fi^pei rjoi Kai <\T<f) iroiKiXai ia-dpiOp-of ttXtjOos Ix^"- '^^'''P^-XTI ^avdal o' 7]pid/xiOvTo p-ipovi rpiTov rjpxaei. laon dpyevprjs dyiXrjs e^oonaTi^ re fxipei. SeTve, tri) 5' ijeXioio /So'ej iroaai drpeKh elirwv X^^pls M^f raijpuv ^aTpe(piui> dpiOp-bv, Xwpis 5' oB drjXeiai Saai Kari xpoidv iKacTai, oiiK d'idpb Ke Xiyoi, oi)5' dpi0p.Qv dSa^i, oil pirjv iribye <TO<po7s iv dpiOfioiV ctW tdi (ppd^ev Kal TaSe irdvra ^bwv ijeXloio iradij, 'Apyorpixes ravpoi fiiv iirel m^alaro wXijOC'v Kvav^ois taravT ffiireSov laofxerpoi eh ^dOoi eh evpo^ re' rd 5' av irepifxriKea xdyryj wl/jLirXavTO tXivOov QpivaKt-qt TreSi'o. ^afdoi o' av r' eh ff Kai Troi/nXoi dOpoiaOimtf 144 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. minate equation of the second degree. In view of this fact it is important for us to discuss briefly the matter and probable date of this epigram. Struve does not admit that it can pretend to that antiquity which is claimed for it in the title. This we may allow without going so far as Kliigel, who makes it as late as the introduction of the present decimal system of numeration. Nesselmann's view is that the heterogeneous conditions, which are thrown together to render the problem difficult, show that the author (if the whole is due to one author) could have had no idea how to solve it. Nesselmann is of opinion that the editors of the anthology were justified in refusing a place to this epigram, that the most one could do would be to admit the first part and condemn the latter part as corrupt, and that we might fairly regard the whole as unauthentic because even the first part could not belong to the age of Archimedes. The first part, which falls into two divisions, gives seven equations of the first degree for determining eight unknown quantities, namely the number of bulls and cows of each of four colours. The solution of the first part gives, if {X YZW) are the numbers of the bulls, {xyziu) the corresponding numbers of cows, X = 10366482 n, x = 7206360 n, Y= 7460514 w, 2/ = 4893246 ?i, Z= 7358060 w, 2=3515820??, W= 4149387 w, «<; = 54.39213 w, where n is an integer. If we take the smallest possible value the number of cattle is sufficiently enormous. The Scholiast's solution corresponds to the value 80 of n, the result being " truly," as Lessing observes, " a tolerably large herd for Sicily." The same might be said of the solution arising from putting w = 1 above. This is surely a curious commentary on M. Tannery's theory above alluded to (pp. 6, 7), that the price of the wine in vi. 33 of Diophantos is a sufficient evidence of the i(xravT' afx^o\aZr)v i^ ivbi apxa/J-efOi ffxvM-o- reXtiovvTes t6 rpiKpacnredov oUre irpoaovruu aSXoxpouv ravpwv, oUt^ iTriXenro/JL^vuv. TaOra cvvf^fvpilji' Kal ivi TrpairiSfcrcriv ddpolaas Kal ir\t)Oi.o}v diro5ous, u) ^^i>(, iravra fiirpa. ^PX^o Kv5i6o}v inKri(p6po%' taOi Tf iravTUii KCKpifi^fot rairrxi uinrvLO% cp ffocply. now FAR WAS DIOl'HANTOS OHKMNAL? U.', date of the epigram. If the " Cattle-problem " of which we arc now speaking were really due to Archimedes, we should, sup- posing M. 'i'aunery's theory to hold good, scarcely have found the result in such glaring contradiction to what cannot but have been the facts of the case, Nesselmann further argues in ftivour of his view by pointing out (1) that the problem is clearly at an end, when it is said that he who solves the problem must be not unskilled in numbers, i.e. where I have shown the division ; and the addition of two new conditions with the preface "And yet he could not pretend to proficiency in wise calculations" unless he could solve the rest, shows the marks of the interpolator on the face of it, and, moreover, of a clumsy interpolator who could neither solve the complete problem itself, nor even conceal his patchwork. (2) The lan- guage and versification are against the authenticity. (3) The Scholiast's solution does not, as it claims, satisfy the whole problem, but only the first part. (4) The impossibility of solution with the Greek numeral notation and the absurdly large numbers show that the author, or authors, could not have seen what the effect of the many heterogeneous conditions would be. Nesselmann draws the conclusion above stated ; and we may safely assume, as he says, that this ej)igram is from the historical point of view worthless, and could not, even if it were shown to be earlier than the date of Diophantos, be held to prove anything against his originality. M. Tannery takes the opposite view and uses the epigram for the express purpose of proving his assumption that Dio- phantos was not an original writer. M. Tannery takes a passage attributed to Geminos in which he is describing the distinction between XoytariKi] and apLOfirjTiKt'j. XoyiariKi] according to Geminos dewpet to /zef KXijOki' vtt \\pxiM^ov<i ^oIkov trpu- l3Xi]/j.a, toOto' he p-ifKira^i fcuL (jjiaXLTu^i ctpiO/xovs'- Ul the two 1 I do not read rovs as M. Tannery does. He alters tovto, the original reading, into rods, simply remarking that tovto is an "inadmissible reading." TovTo Si is certainly a reading which needs no defence, being exactly what we should expect to have. The passage appears to be taken from the Scholia to Plato's Cluinnideii, where, however, Stallbaum and Heiberg read Otupti o^ roOro Hkv rb K\r}6iv i'lr" 'A/ixtM')'Joi'S (ioeiuoi' wij6ft\)ina, touto bi li'iMrai «o» 0ioXirat H. D. 10 146 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. kinds of problems which are here distinguished as falling within the province of Xoyca-TiK/j M. Tannery understands the first to be indeterminate problems, the type taken {kXvO^v vir 'Apxi-M^ovi ^o'Ckou Trpo^Xiifia) being nothing more or less than the very problem we have been speaking of. He states that Nesselmanu has not appreciated the problem properly, and finally that we have here an indubitable reference to an indeterminate problem of the second degree (viz. the equation 8Ax^ + l=if, where yl is a very large number) more difficult than those of Diophantos. But this statement would seem simply to beg the question. For, if the expression of Geminos refers to the problem which we are speaking of, it may even then only refer to the first part, that is, an indeterminate problem of the first degree : M. Tannery has still to show that the whole problem is one, and a genuine product of antiquity. But I have not found that M. Tannery makes any attempt to answer Nesselmann's arguments ; and, unless they are an- swered, the conclusion which the latter draws from them cannot be said to be invalidated. But Nesselmann's view is also opposed by Heiberg {Quae- stiones Archimedeae, 1879). I do not think, however, that his arguments in favour of the authenticity are conclusive ; and, though answering some, he does not answer all of Nesselmann's objections. With regard to the language Heiberg observes that the dialect need not surprise us, for the use by Archimedes of the Ionic instead of the Doric dialect for this epigram would easily be explained by the common use of the Ionic dialect for epic and elegiac poetry \ And he further suggests that, even if dpidfiovs, which Beems better than the reading quoted by M. Tanuery from Hultsch, Ileronis Reliquiae, and given above. ^ Heiberg admits that the language of the title is not satisfactory. He points out that tV iiriypd/xfxaaii' shoukl go, not with eipuv, but with airiffreiXe, though so far separated from it, and that the use of the plm-al i -my pd/ifiaaLv is unsatisfactory. Upon the reading noiKlXai iaapUlixov ttXtjOos ^x"" '''^''^po-XV (1- 21) he observes that by symmetry z should not be equal to four times (l + l){1V+w), but to (j + i) (W+ic) itself, and, even if that were the case, we should require TerpdKis. Hence he suggests for this lino iroiKlXai ladpiOfiov nX^Ooi ?xo*'<^' ^<pdvrj. (Apparently, to judge from his punctuation, Lessing understood Terpaxij in the sense of "fourthly.") Heiberg explains irXivOov (1. 36) as " quadraugulum sohdum," by which is mtaut dimply " a square," as is clearly indicated by 1. 34. now FAR WAS DlOrilANTdS OUICINAL ^ 147 the difficulties as to the hmguagc arc considered too great, we may suppose the problem itself to have been the work of Archimedes, the language of it that of some later author. But, if Heiberg will go so far as to admit that the language may be the work of a later author than Archimedes, it would be no more unnatural to suppose that the matter itself of the latter part of the problem was also of later date. The suggestion that Archimedes could not have solved the whole problem (as com- pleted by the two last conditions) Heiberg meets with argu- ments which appear to be extremely unsafe. He says that Archimedes' approximations to the value of J^, although we cannot see by what process he arrived at them, show plainly that his arithmetic was little behind our modern arithmetic, and that, e.g., he possessed means of approximation little in- ferior to the modern method by continued fractions. Heiberg further observes that Archimedes possessed machinery for deal- ing with very large numbers. But we are not justified in assuming on these two grounds that Archimedes could solve the indeterminate equation 8Ax^+l=y^, where (Nesselmann, p. 488) A = 51285802909803, for the solution of which we should use continued fractions. I do not think, therefore, that Heiberg has made out his case. Hence I should hesitate to assume that the problem before us is an indubitable case, }n-evious to Diophantos, of an indeterminate equation of the second degree more difficult than those treated by him. The discussion of the " Cattle-problem " as possibly throwing some light on the present question would seem to have adiled nothing to the arguments previously stated ; and the (juestiou of Diophantos' originality may be considered to be uuaftectod by anything that has been said about the epigram. We may therefore adopt, with little or no variation, Ncssel- mann's final result, that he is far from believing that Diophantos merely worked up the materials of others. On the contrary he is convinced that the greater part of his propositions and his ingenious methods are his own. There is moreover an " ludivi- duum" running through the whole work which strongly confirms this conclusion. lU-2 CHAPTER VIII. DIOPHANTOS AND THE EARLY ARABIAN ALGEBRAISTS. § 1. I propose in this chapter to examine briefly the indica- tions which are to be found in certain Arabian algebraists of in- debtedness to, or points of contact with, Diophantos. And in doing so I shall leave out of consideration the Arabic translations of his work or commentaries tiiereupou. These are, so far as we know, all lost, and such notices ot them as we have I have given in Chapter ill. of this Essay (pp. 39 — 42). Our histori- cal knowledge of the time and manner in which Diophantos became known to the Arabs is so very scanty as to amount almost to nothing: hence the importance of careful comparison of the matter, methods, and mode of expression of Diophantos with those of the important representatives of early Arabian algebra. Now it has been argued that, since the first transla- tion of Diophantos into Arabic that we know of was made by Abu'i-Wafa, who lived A.D. 940 — 998, while Mohammed ibn Musa's algebraical work belongs to the beginning of the 9th century, Arabian algebra must have been developed inde- pendently of that of the Greeks. This conclusion, however, is not warranted by this evidence. It does not follow from the want of historical proof of connection between Greek and Arabian algebra that there was no such connection; and it is to internal evidence that we must look for the correction of this misconception. I shall accordingly enumerate a number of points of similarity between the Arabian algebraists and Dio- phantos which would seem to indicate that the Arabs were ac(|uainted with Diophantos and Greek algebra before the time of Mohammed ibn Musu, and that in Arabian algebra generally, DIOPHANTOS AND THE EARLY AllAHIAN AMJKHUAISTS. 14;) at least iu its beginnings, the Greek element greatly j.rr.lomi- nated, though other elements were not wanting. §2. The first Arabian who concerns us liere is Mohammed ibn Musa Al-Kharizmi. He wrote a work which he callfd Aljahr wahnukUhala, and which is, so far as we know, not only the first book which bore such a title, but (if we can trust Arabian notices) was the first book which dealt with the subject indi- cated thereby. Mohammed ibn Musa uses the words aljahr ami almukiihala without explanation, and, curiously enough, there is no application of the processes indicated by the words in the theoretical part of the treatise: facts which must be held to show that these processes were known, to some extent at least, even before his time, and were known by those names. A mere translation of the two terras jabr and mukdbala does not of itself give us any light as to their significance. Jabr has been trans- lated in Latin by the words restauratio and restitutio, and in German by "Wiederherstellung"; mukabala by oppusitio, or "comparison," and in German by "Gegeniiberstellung." Fortu- nately, however, we have explanations of the two terms given by later Arabians, who all agree as to the meaning conveyed by them\ When we have an algebraical equation in which terms affected with a negative sign occur on either side or on both sides, the process by which we make all the terms positive, i.e. adding to both sides of the equation such positive terms as will make up the deficiencies, or absorb the negative ones, is jabr or restauratio. When, again, we have by jabr transformed our equation into one in which all the terms are positive, the process by which we strike out such terms as occur on both sides, with the result that there is, finally, only one term con- 1 Rosen gives, in his edition of The Algebra of Mohammed ben Miua, a number of passages from various authors explaining aljabr and almukabala. I shall give only one, as an examijle. Itosen says " In the Kholaset iil Hisub, a compendium of arithmetic and geometry by Baha-Eddiu Mohammed ben Al Hosain, who died A.n. 1031, i.e. 1575 a.i>., the Arabic text of which, together with a Persian commentary by Roshan Ali, was printed at Calcutta (IHTi, Svo), the following explanation is given : ' The side (of the e<iuation) on which bouic- thing is to be subtracted, is made complete, and as much is to be added to the other side; this is jebr; again those cognate (luautitiea which are equal on both sides are removed, and this is iW)kdbalah\" 150 DIOPIIANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. taining each power of tlie unknown, i.e. subtracting equals from equals, is mukdhala, oppositio or "comparison." Such was the meaning of the terms ja6?* and mukdhala) and the use of these words together as the title of Mohammed ibn Musa's treatise is due to the continual occurrence in the science there expounded of the processes so named. It is tiTie that in the theoretical part of it he assumes that the operations have been already completed, and accordingly divides quadratic equations at once into six classes, viz. aa? = hx, ax^ = c, hx = c, x^ + hx = c, x^ + c = hx, x^ = bx-{-c, but the operations are nevertheless an essential preliminary. Now what does Diophantos say of the necessary preliminaries in dealing with an equation? "If the same powers of the un- known with positive but different coefficients occur on both sides, we must take like from like until we have one single ex- pression equal to another. If there are on both sides, or on either side, negative terms, the defects must be added on both sides, until the different powers occur on both sides with posi- tive coefficients, when we must take like from like as before. We must contrive always, if possible, to reduce our equations so that they may contain one single term equated to one other. But afterwards we will explain to you how, when two terms are left equal to a third, such an equation is solved." (Def. 11.) Here we have an exact description of the operations called by the Arabian algebraists aljahr and almukahala. And, as we said, these operations must have been familiar in Arabia before the date of Mohammed ibn Musa's treatise. This comparison would, therefore, seem to suggest that Diophantos was well known in Arabia at an early date. Next, with regard to the names used by Mohammed ibn Musa for the unknown quantity and its powers, we observe that the known quantity is called the "Number"; hence it is no matter for surprise that he has not used the word corresponding to npi6fx6<i for his unknown quantity. He uses shai ("thing") for this purpose or jidr ("root"). This last word may be a translation of the Indian mfda, or it may be a recollection of the DIOPIIANTOS AND THE EARLY ARAIUAN ALGEBRAISTS. 151 pl^t] of Nikomachos. But avg can say nothing with certainty as to the connection of the three words. For the square of the unknown he uses mal (translated by Cantor as "Vcrmogen," " Besitz," equivalent to "power"), which may very well be a translation of the Svvafii'i of Diophantos. M. Bodet comments in his article Ualgehre (VAl-Khh'izmi (Journal Asiatique, 1878) upon the expression used by Moham- med ibn Musa for minus, with the view of proving that it is as likely to be a reminiscence of Diophantos as a term derived from India \ The most important point, however, for us to examine here is the solution of the complete (juadratic equation as given by Diophantos and as given by Mohammed ibn Miisa, The latter gives rules for the solution of each of the forms of the quadratic according to his distinction ; and each of these forms we find in Diophantos. After the rules for the three forms of the complete quadratic Mohammed ibn Miisa gives geometrical proofs of them. Now in Greece it was the practice to work out theorems 1 He says (pp. 31, 32) "Le mot dont il se sert pour dtisigner lestermcs d'une equation affectes du signe -est naqis, qui signifie, comme on le sait, ' manquant de, prive de ' : un ampute, par exemple, est iwqis de son bras ou de sa jambc ; c'est done tres-improprement qu'Al-Kharizmi cmploie cette expression ^wur designer ' la partie eulevec'...Aussi le mot en question n'a-t-il plus c'te cmployo par ses successeurs, et Behri ed-Din qui, au moment d'cxposer la regie dcs siijncs dans la multiplication algebriquc, avait dit : ' s'il y a soustraction, on appcllo CO dont on soustrait zaid (additif), et ce que Ton soustrait naqis (manquant de), ne nomme plus dans la suite les termes n^gatifs que ' les s^par^s, mis H part, retranches.' D'oti vient ce mot 7iaqis? II repond, si Ton vcut, au Sanscrit ii;i<M oa au pr6fixe vi- au moyen desquels on iudique la soustraction : njekas ou ckoiias veut dire 'dont on a retranchc,' niais I'adjectif viias se rapportc ici au ' ce dont on a retranche ' de Beba ed-Din, et non a la quautito rctrancbil-e. Or, lo groc possede et emploie en langage algebriquc une expression tout A fait ana- logue, c'est I'adjectif AXi7rr)s, dont Diopbant se sert, par excmplo, pour definir le signe de la soustraction 71 : xj/ tWtir^i Kdru vtvoy, ' un \f/ iiicomplct incline vers le bas.' L'arabe, j'en prcnds a temoin tous les arabisauts, tra- duirait iWinrji par en-m'iqis. Dans I'indication dcs operations algubriquca Diopbant lit, li la place de son signe -71, if \d^pu : fjiowdSft /3 if \d4^u dpiOfxou iv6i, dit-il; mot-amot : "2 unites manquant d'une inconune,' pour cxprinier 2-x. Done, s'il est possible qu'Al-Kbarizmi ait emprunt6, sauf I'emploi qu'il en fait, son HtJ<//.s- au sauscrit uiias, il pourrait tout aussi bicu so fairo iju'il I'eAt pris au grec iv Xti^et." 152 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. concerned witli numbers by the aid of geometry; even in Dio- phantos we find the geometrical method employed for the treatise on Polygonal Numbers and a trace of it even in the Arith- metics, although the separation between geometry and algebra is there complete. On the other hand, the Indian method was to employ algebra for working out geometrical propositions, and algebra reached a far higher degree of development in India than in Greece, though it is probable that even India was in- debted to Greece for the first principles. Hence we should naturally consider the geometrical basis of early Arabian algebra as a sign of obligation to Greece. This supposition is supported by a very remarkable piece of evidence adduced by Cantor. It is based on the letters used by Mohammed ibn Miisa to mark the points in the geometrical figures used to prove his rules. The very use of letters in a geometrical figure is Greek, not Indian ; and the letters which are used are chosen in what appears to be, at first sight, a strange manner. The Arabic letters here used do not follow the order of the later Arabian alphabet, an order depending on the form of the letters and the mode of writing them, nor is their order quite explained by the original arrangement of the Arabian alphabet which corresponds to the order in the other Semitic languages. If however we take the Arabic letters used in the figures and change them respectively into those Greek letters which have the same nu- merical value, the series follows the Greek order exactly, and not only so, but agrees with it in excluding 5" and t. But what reason could an Arab have had for refusing to use the particular letters which denoted 6 and 10 for geometrical figures? None, so far as we can see. The Greek, however, had a reason for omitting the two letters 5" and i, the former because it was really no longer regarded as a letter, the latter because it was a mere stroke, I, which might have led to confusion. We can hardly refuse to admit Cantor's conclusion from this evidence that Mohammed ibn Musa's geometrical proofs of his rules for solving the different forms of the complete quadratic are Greek. And it is, moreover, a reasonable iufereuce that the Greeks themselves discovered the rules for the solution of a complete quadratic by means of geometry. We thus have a confirmation Vi DIOPIIANTOS AND THE EARLY ARABIAN ALfJEBRAlSTS. l.'>3 of the supposition as to the origin of the rules used by Diophan- tos, which was mentioned above (pp. 140, 141), and we may pro- perly conclude that algebra, as we find it in Diophantos, was the result of a continuous development which extended from the time of Euclid to that of Heron and of Diophantos, and was independent of external influences. I now pass to the consideration of the actual rules which Mohammed ibn Mfisii gives for the solution of the complete quadratic, as compared with those of Diophantos. We remarked above (p. 91) that Diophantos would appear, when solving the equation ax' -\- bx = c, to have first multiplied by a throughout, so as to make the first term a square, and that he would, with b our notation, have given the root in the form — — . Mohammed ibn Musa, however, first divides by a throughout : " The solution is the same when two squares or three, or more or less, be specified ; you reduce them to one single square and in the same proportion you reduce also the roots and simple numbers which are connected therewith \" This discrepancy between the Greek and the Arabian algebraist is not a very striking or important one; but it is worth while to observe that Mohammed ibn Musa's rule is not the early Indian one ; for Brahmagupta (born 598) sometimes multiplies throughout by a like Diophantos, sometimes by 4a, which was also the regular practice of (^'rldhara, who thus obtained the root in the form . This rule of Crldhara's is quoted and followed 2a ' by Bhaskara. Another apparent discrepancy between Moham- med ibn Musa and Diophantos lies in the fact that Diophantos never shows any sign, in his book as we have it, of recognising two roots of a quadratic, even where both roots are positive and real, and not only when one of them is negative: a negative or irrational value he would, of course, not recognise ; unless an equation has a real positive root it is for Diophantos "impossible." Negative and irrational roots appear to be tacitly ])ut aside by ' Rosen, The Al<jtl>r<i of Muluimtiu-U bfii Miisu, p. '.». 164 DIOPHAIITOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Mohammed ibn Musa and the earliest Indian algebraists, though both Mohammed ibn Musii and the Indians recognise the exist- ence of two roots. The former undoubtedly recognises two roots, at least in the case where both are real and positive. His most definite statement on this subject is given in his rule for the solution of the equation x^ + c = hx, or the case of the quadratic in which we have "Squares and Numbers equal to Roots; for instance, ' a square and twenty-one in numbers are equal to ten roots of the same square.' That is to say, what must be the amount of a square, which when twenty-one dirhems are added to it, becomes equal to the equivalent of ten roots of that square? Solution : Halve the number of the roots ; the moiety is five. Multiply this by itself; the product is twenty-five. Subtract from this the twenty-one which are connected with the square ; the remainder is four. Extract its root; it is two. Subtract this from the moiety of the roots, which is five ; the remainder is three. This is the root of the square which you required, and the square is nine. Or you may add the root to the moiety of the roots; the sum is seven; this is the root of the square which you sought for, and the square itself is forty-nine. When you meet with an instance lohich refers you to this case, try its solu- tion by addition, and if that do not serve, then subtraction cer- tainly will. For in this case both addition and subtraction may be employed, which will not answer in any other of the three cases in which the number of the roots must be halved. And know that, when in a question belonging to this case you have halved the number of roots and multiplied the moiety by itself, if the product be less than the number of dirhems connected with the s(piare, then the instance is impossible; but if the pro- duct be equal to the dirhems by themselves, then the root of the square is equal to the moiety of the roots alone, without either addition or subtraction. In every instance where you have two squares, or more or less, reduce them to one entire square, as I have explained under the first case\" This defi- nite recognition of the existence of two roots, if Diophantos could be proved not to have known of it, would seem to show ' Quoted from The Algebra of Mohavimed ben Musa (ed. Rosen), pp. 11, 12. DTOPIIANTOS AND THE EARLY ARABIAN ALGEBRAISTS. 155 that Mohammed ibu Musii could here have been indebted to India only. Rodet, however, remarks that we are not justified in concluding from the evidence that Diophantos did not know of the existence of two roots: in the cases where one is negative we should not expect him to mention it, for a negative root is for him "impossible," and in certain cases mentioned above (p. 92) one of the positive roots is irrelevant. Rudet further ob- serves that Mohammed ibn Musa, while recognising in theory two roots of the equation ,v^+c = bx, uses in practice only one, and that (curiously enough) in all instances the root correspond- ing to the sign minus of the radical. This statement however is not quite accurate, for in some examples of the rule which we quoted above he gives two possible values \ Mohammed ibn Milsa, being the first writer of a treatise on algebra, so far as we know, is for obvious reasons the most important for the purposes of this chapter. If the influence of Diophantos and Greek algebra upon the earliest Arabian algebra is once established, it is clearly unnecessary to search so carefully in the works of later Arabians for points of connection with our author. For, his influence having once for all exerted itself, the later developments would naturally be the result of other and later influences, and direct reminiscences of Diophantos would disappear or be obscured. I shall, therefore, mention only a few other Arabian authors, and those with greater brevity. § 3. Abu'1-Wafa Al-Buzjani wc have already had occasion to mention (pp. 40, 41) as a translator of Diophantos and a commentator on his work. As then he studied our author so thoroughly it would be only natural to expect that his works would abound in reminiscences of Diophantos. On Abu'1-Wafa perhaps the most important authority is Wopcke. It must suftice to refer for details to his articles '^ § 4. An Arabic MS. bearing the date 972 is concerned with the theory of numbers throughout and particularly with the formation of rational right-angled triangles. Unfortunately the • Cf. Rosen's edition, p. 42. 2 Cf. in particular the articles on MalMmntiqucs chez let Arabt-» {Journal Asiatique for LS.'}")). 156 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. beginning of it is lost, and with the beginning the name of the author. In the fragment we find the problem To find a square which, when increased or diminished by a given number, is again a square proposed and solved. Tlie author of the fragment was undoubtedly an Arabian, and it would probably not be rash to say that much of it was based on Diopliautos. § 5. Again, Abu Ja'far Mohammed ibn Alhusain wrote a treatise on rational right-angled triangles at a date probably not much later than 992. He gives as the object of the whole the investigation of the problem just mentioned. It is note- worthy (says Cantor) that a geometrical explanation of the solution of this problem makes use of similar principles to those which we could trace in Mohammed ibn Musa's geometrical proofs of the solution of the complete quadratic, and he further definitely alludes to Euclid II. 7. If we consider the use of right-angled triangles as a means of finding solutions of this problem, and c^, c^ be the two sides of a right-angled triangle which contain the right angle, then c^' + c^ is the square of the hypotenuse, and c'^ + c^ + '^c^c^ is a square. Hence, says Ibn Al- husain, c^ -f c'^ is a square which, when increased or diminished by the same number 'Ic^c^, is still a square. Diophantos says similarly that " in every right-angled triangle the square of the hypotenuse remains a square when double the product of the other two sides is added to, or subtracted from, it." (ill. 22.) § 6. Lastly, we must consider in this connection the work of Alkarkhi, already mentioned (pp. 24, 25). We possess two treatises of his, of which the second is a continuation of the first. The first is called Al-Kafi fll hisUb and is arithmetical, the second is the Fakhrl, an algebraic treatise. Cantor points out that, when we compare Alkarkhi's arithmetic with that of certain Arabian contemporaries and predecessors of his, we see a marked contrast, in that, while others used Indian numeral signs and methods of calculation, Alkarkhi writes out all his numbers as words, and draws generally from Greek sources rather than Indian. The advantages of the Indian notation as compared with Greek in securing clearness and compactness of work were so great that we might naturally be surprised to see Alkarkiii ignoring them, and might wonder that he could have DIOPHANTOS AND THE EARLY ARABIAN ALGEBRAISTS. 157 been unaware of them or have undervalued them so much. Cantor, however, thinks that the true explanation is, not that he was ignorant of the Indian arithmetical methods and notation or underestimated their advantages, but that Alkarkh! was a repre- sentative of one of two mathematical schools in Arabia, the Greek and the Indian. Alkarklii was not the solitary repre- sentative of the Greek arithmetic; he was not merely an excep- tion to an otherwise universal acceptation of the Indian method. He was rather, as we said, a representative of one of two schools standing in contrast to each other. Another representative of the Greek school was Abu'1-Wafa, who also makes no use of ciphers in his arithmetic. Even in Alkarkhi's arithmetical treatise, as in the works of Abu'1-Wafa, there are not wanting certain Indian elements. These could hardly by any means have been avoided, at any rate as regards the matter of their treatises; but the Greek element was so predominant that, prac- tically, the other may be neglected. But the real importance of Alkarkhi in this connection centres in his second treatise, the Fakhri. Here again he appears as an admiring pupil of the Greeks, and especially of Diophantos, whom he often mentions by name in his book. The Fakhri consists of two parts, the first of which may be said to contain the theory of algebra, the second the practice of it, or the application to particular problems. In both parts we find Diophantos largely made use of Alkarkhi solves in this treatise not only determinate but indeterminate equations, so that he may be taken as the representative of the Arabian indeter- minate analysi.s. In his solutions of indeterminate ccjuations of the first and second degrees we find no trace of Indian methods. Diophantos is the basis upon which he builds, but he has also extended the Greek algebraist. If we refer to the account which the Italian algebraists give of the evolution of the successive powers of the unknown quantity in the Arabian system, we shall see (as already remarked, p. 71, n. 1) that Alkarkhi is an exception to the adoption of the Indian .system of generation of powers by the vviltiplicution of indices. He uses the additive .system, like Diophantos. The square of the un- ku.iwu bein^ mal, and the cube ka'b, the succeeding powers are 158 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. mal mrd, null ha'h, ka'b ka'h, iiuil mal ha'h, rncil ka'h Jca'b, ka.h ka'b ka'b, &c. Alkarklii speaks of the six forms of the quadratic which Mohammed ibn MusJi distinguished and explains at the same time what he understands hy jab?' and mukabala. He appears to include both processes under jabr, understanding rather by mukdbala the resulting equation written in one of the six forms. Among the examples given by Alkarkhi are .r^+10a;=39, and 0;'^+ 21 = 10a;, both of which occur in Mohammed ibn Miisa. Alkarkhi has two solutions of both, the first geometrical, the second (as he expresses it) "after Diophantos' manner." The second of the two equations which we have mentioned he reduces to x^ — 10a; + 25 = 4, and then, remarking that the first member may be either (x — 5f or (5 — xf, he gives the two solutions x = 7, and x = 2. The remarkable point about his treatment of this equation is his use of the expression " after Diophantos' manner" applied to it. We spoke above (p. 92) of the doubt as to whether Diophantos knew or did not know of the existence of two roots of a quadratic. But Alkarkhi's expression " after Diophantos' manner " would seem to settle this question beyond the possibility of a doubt; and perhaps it would not be going too far to take his words quite literally and to suppose that the two examples of the quadratic of which we are speaking were taken directly from Diophantos. If so, we should have still more du'ect proof of the Greek origin of Mohammed ibn Miisa's algebra. On the other hand, however, it must be mentioned that of two geometrical explanations of the equation a;'^ + 10^=39 which Alkarkhi gives one cannot be Greek. In the first of the two he derives the solution directly from Euclid, ii. 6 ; and this method is therefore solely Greek. But in the second geometrical solution he employs one line to represent x'^, another to represent 10j7, and a third to represent 100. This confusion of dimensions is alien from the Greek manner ; we must therefore suppose that this geometrical solution is an Arabian product, and probably a discovery of Alkarkhi himself As an instance of an indeterminate ecpiation treated by Alkarkhi we may give the equation mx^ + nx + p = y\ He gives as a cuudition for the solution that either m or p must ])o DIOPHANTOS AND THE EARLY ARABIAN ALGEBRAISTS. 150 a square. He then puts for y a binomial expression, of which one term is either Jlna? or JJ). This is, as we have seen, exactly Diophantos' procedure. With regard to the collection of problems, whicli forms the second part of the Fakhrl, we observe that Alkarklii only admits rational and positive solutions, excluding even the value 0. In other cases the solution is for Alkarkhi as for Diophantos " impossible." Many of the problems in indeterminate analysis are taken directly from Diophantos, and are placed in the order in which they are there found. Of a marginal note by Alsiraj at the end of the fourth section of the second part of the treatise we have already spoken (p. 25). ADDENDUM. In the note beginning on p. 6i I discussed three objections urged by Mr James Gow in his History of Greek Mathematics against my suggestion as to the origin of the symbol <>) for dpi0/x6s. The second of these objections asserted that it is of very rare occurrence, and is not found in the >iss. of Nikomachos and Pappos, where it might most naturally be expected. In reply to this, I pointed out that it was not in the least necessary for my theory that it should occur anywhere except in Diophantos ; and accordingly I did not raise the question whether the symbol was found in mss. so rarely as Mr Gow appears to suppose. Since then I have thought that it would be interesting to inquire into this point a little further, without, however, going too far afield. ■\;\liile reading Heiberg's Quaestiones Archimeikae in connection with the Cattle- problem discussed in chapter viii. it occurred to me that the symbol for apiOnos would be likely to be found, if anywhere, in the mss. of the De areiiae mimero Ubclhts of Archimedes, which Heiberg gives at the end of the book, and that, if it did so occur, Heiberg's textual criticisms would i^lace the matter beyond doubt, without the necessity of actually collating the mss. My expectation proved to be fully justified ; for it is quite clear that the symbol occun-cd in the MSS. of this work of Archimedes rather frequently, and that its form had given rise to exactly the same confusion and doubt as in the case of Diophantos. I will here give references to the places where it undoubtedly occurred. See the following pages in Heiberg's book, p. 172. p. 174. Heiberg reads dpL6fwv, with the remark "/cat omnes." But the similarity of the signs for api6fi6s and Kai is well known, and it could hardly be anything else than this similarity which could cause such a difference of readings. p. 187. Heiberg's remark " apiOfxiov om. codd. Bas. E ; excidit ante s (Kai)" speaks for itself. Also on the same page "dpiOnwu] si FBC." p. 188. js three times for dpiBixuv. p. 191. Here there is a confusion between 5" (six) and dpiOfxis, where Heiberg remarks, "Error ortus est ex compendio illo uevhi dpiOfios, de quo dixi ad I, 3." p. 192. iXaTTuv and dpid/xos given as alternative readings, with the obser- vation, " Confusa sunt compendia." Thus it is clear that the symbol in question occurs tolerably often in the mss. of another arithmetical treatise, and that the only one which I have investigated in this connection : a fact whicli certainly does not support Mr Gow's statement that it is veiy rarely found. APPENDIX. ABSTRACT OF THE ARITHMETICS AND THE TRACT ON POLYGONAL NUMBERS. H. D. u J DIOPHANTOS. ARITHMETICS. BOOK I. Introduction addressed to Dionjjsios. Definitions. 1. "Square" and "side," "cube," "square-square," etc. 2. " Power." Notation 8", k", 88", Sk", kk", /a", c^. 3. Corresponding fractions, the reciprocals of the foi-mer ; names used corresponding to the " nimibers." 4. "]S'umber"x"Number"= square. Square x square = "squarc- squai-e," &c. 5. " Number " x corresponding fraction = unit (/xoi-ds). 6. "Species" not changed by multiplication with monads. * I Reciprocal x reciprocal - reciprocal scpiare, etc. 9. Minus multiplied by minus gives j^lus. Notation for minus, /p. 10. Division. Remark on familiarity with processes. 11. Simplification of equations. Frohlenis. 1. Divide a given number into two having a given difference. Given nund)er 100, given difference 10. Lesser number required x. Therefore 2.«+ 40-100, X - 30. The required numbers an- 70, 30. 2. To divide a given number into two having a given nitio. Given number GO, given ratio ."3 : 1. Two numbers x, 2>x. Therefore ./j- ir». Till" numbers arc 45, 15. 11—2 164 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA, 3. To divide a given number into two having a given ratio and diffei-ence '. Given number 80 ; ratio 3:1; diflference 4. Smaller number x. Therefore the larger is 3x + 4, x = 1 9. The numbers are 61, 19. 4. Find two numbers in a given ratio, their difference also being given. Given ratio 5:1. Diffei'ence 20. Numbers 5x, x. Therefore x-6, and the numbers are 25, 5. 5. To divide a given number into two such tliat the sum of given fractions (not the same) of each is a given number. Necessary condition. The latter given number must lie between the numbers arising when the given fractions are taken of the first given number. First given number 100, given fractions ;^ and -, given sura 30. Second part 5a-. Therefore first part = 3 (30 - x). Therefore 90 + 2a; = 100, x = 5. The required parts are 75, 25. 6. To divide a given number into two parts, such that a given fraction of one exceeds a given fraction of the other by a given difierence. Necessary condition. The latter number must be less than that which arises when that fraction of the first number is taken which exceeds the other fraction. Given number 100 ; fractions - and -respectively : excess 20. 4 G Second part Gx Therefore 10.v+80=100, x = 2, and the parts are 88, 12. 7. From the same (rcqiiired) number to take away two given numbers, so that the remainders are in a given ratio. Given numbers 100, 20; ratio 3:1. X required number. Therefore a;- 100 : a- 20 = 1 : 3, .«;^ 140. 8. To two given numbers to add tlie same (required) number, so that the sums ai-e in a given ratio. 1 By thiH Diojihantos means " such that one is so many times the other ylm a given number." ARITHMETICS. BOOK I. 165 Cotulilion. This ratio must bo less tlmu that of the greater given number to tlie smaller. Given numbers 100, 20, given ratio 3:1. X required number. Therefore 3a; + 60 = a: +100, and x=20, 9. From two given numbers to subtract the same (required) one so that the two remainders are in a given ratio. Condition. This ratio must be greater than that uf the greater given number to the smallei'. Given numbers 20, 100, ratio 6 : 1. X required number. Therefore 1 20 - 6x- = 100 - X, and a; - 4. 10. Given two numbers, to add the same (required) number to the smaller, and subtract it from the lai-ger, so that the sum in the first case may have to the difference in the second a given ratio. Given numbers 20, 100, given ratio 4:1. X required number. Therefore 20 + x- : 100-cc = 4 : 1, and a; = 76. 11. Of two given numbers to add the first to, and subtract the second from, the same (required) number, so that the numbers which arise may have a given ratio. Given numbers 20, 100 respectively, ratio 3:1. X required number. Therefore 3a; - 300 = a; + 20, and x = 160. 12. To divide a given number twice into two parts, such that the fii-st of the first pair may have to the first of the second a given ratio, and also the second of the first pnir to the second of the second another given ratio. Given number 100, ratio of greater of fii-st parts to less of second 2:1, ratio of greater of second parts to less of first 3:1. X smaller of second parts. The parts then are , J"" . 1 'int^ ^^^ ~ ^■" [ • Therefore 300 - 5x- = 1 00, x - 40, 100- 2a; j X J and the parts are (80, 20), (60, 40). 13. To divide a given number thrice into two parts, such that one of the first parts and one of the second pai-ts, the other of the second 166 DIOPUANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. parts and one of the third parts, the other of the tliird parts and the remaining one of the first parts, are respectively in given ratios. Given number 100, ratio of gi-eater of first parts to less of second 3 : 1, of greater of second to less of third 2:1, and of greater of third to less of first 4:1. X smaller of third parts. Therefore greater of second = 2x, less of second = 100 - 2x, greater of first = 300 - Gx. Therefore less of first = Gx- 200. Hence greater of third = 2ix - 800. Therefore 25^-800 = 100, a; =36, and the respective divisions are (84, 16), (72, 28), (64, 36). li. To find two numbers such that their product has to their sum a given ratio. [One is arbitrarily assumed subject to the] Condition. The assumed value of one of the two must be greater than the numerator of the ratio [the denominator being 1]. Ratio 3:1. x one number, the other 12 ( > 3). Therefore 12a; = 3a; +30, a; = 4, and the numbers are 4, 12. 15. To find two numbers such that each after receiving from the other a given number may bear to the remainder a given ratio. Let the first receive 30 from the second, ratio being then 2:1, and the second 50 from the first, ratio being then 3:1. cc 4- 30 the second. Therefore the first = 2x - 30, and a; + 80 : 2a;- 80=3 : 1. Therefore x = 64, and the numbers arc 98, 94. 16. To find three numbers such that the sums of each pair are given numbers. Condition. Half the sum of all must be greater than any one singly. Let (1) + (2) = 20, (2) + (3) = 30, (3) + (l) = 40. x the sum of the three. Therefore the numbers are X - 30, X - 40, X - 20. Hence the sum x = 3x' - 90. Therefore a; = 45, and the numbers ai-e 15, 5, 25. 17. To find four numbers such that the sums of all sets of three are given. Condition. One third of the sum of all must be greater than any one singly. Sums of threes 22, 24, 27, 20. J ARITHMETICS. HOOK I. 107 X the sum of all four. Therefore the mimhera uro .T-22, a; -24, a; -27, a; -20. Therefore 4x- - 93 = x, .r = 31 , and the numbers are 9, 7, 4, 11. 18. To find three numbers such that the sum of any puir exceeds the third by a given number. Given excesses 20, 30, 40. 2x sum of all, x = 45. The numbers arc 25, 35, 30. 19. [A different solution of the foregoing problem.] 20. To find four numbers such that the sum of any three exceeds the fourth by a given number. Condition. Half the sum of the four given dilterences must be greater than any one of them. Given differences 20, 30, 40, 50. 2a; the sum of the four required numbers. Tlierefoi-c the numbers are a;- 10, a;- 15, x-20, x-2b. Therefore 4x- 70 = 2.f, and .^•= 35. Therefore the numbers are 25, 20, 15, 10. 21. [Another solution of the foregoing.] 22. To divide a given number into three, such that the sum of each extreme and the mean has to the remaining extreme a given ratio. Given number 100 i (1) + (2) = 3 . (3), (2) + (3) 4.(1). X the third. Hence the sum of first and second = 3a-. There- fore 4a; =100. X = 25, and the sum of the first two = 75. y the first '. Therefore (2) + (3) = 4v/. Therefore by = 100, y = 20. The required parts are 20, 55, 25. 23. To find three numbers such that the greatest exceeds the middle number by a given fraction of the least, the middle exceeds the least by the same given fraction of the greatest, but the least exceeds the same given fraction of the middle number by a given number. 1 As already remarked on pp. 80, 81, Diophantos docs not uso a second syllable for the uuknowu, but uses dpiO/xos for the second oiHiratiou as well ob for the lirtit. 168 TJlOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Condition. The middle number must exceed the least by such a fraction of the greatest, that if its denomiuator be multiplied into the excess of the middle number over the least, the result is gi-eater than the middle number. Greatest exceeds middle by ^ of least, middle exceeds least by o of greatest, least exceeds ^ of middle by 10. aj + 10 the least. Therefore middle = 3aj, greatest = 6a; -30. Therefore x- 12^, and the numbers are 45, 37^, 22|^. 24. [Another solution of the foregoing.] 25. To find three numbers such that, if each give to the next following a given fraction of itself, in order, the results after each has given and taken may be equal. Let first give ^ of itself to second, second . of itself to third, third - of itself to first. 5 Assume the second to be a number divisible by 4, say 4. 3a; the first, and x = '2. The numbers are 6, 4, 5. 26. Find four numbers such that, if each give to the next following a given fraction of itself, the results may all be equal. Let first give ^ of itself to second, - , -, ^ being the other fractions. Assume the second to be a multiple of 4, say 4. 3a; the first. The second after giving and taking becomes a; + 3. Therefore first after giving x to second and receiving of fourth = a; + 3. Therefore fourth =18- 6a;. And fourth after giving 3 - a; to first and receiving r^ of third = a; + 3. Therefore third = 30a; - 60. Lastly the third after giving 6.x- - 1 2 to fourth and receiving 1 from second = a; + 3. Therefore 50 24a; - 47 - a; + 3, a; - ^o • ARITHMETICS. ]J0OK I. 100 m, I- *i 1 1^0 , 120 111 Therefore the numbers are ^ , 4, -^ * ~ok ' or, multiplying by the common denominator, 150, 92, 120, 114. 27. To find three numbers such that, if each receives a given fraction of the sum of the other two, the results are all equal. The fractions being , -r, _ , the sum of the second and third is assiimed to be 3, and x put for the first. The numbers are, after multiplying by a common denominator, 13, 17, 19. 28. To find four numbers such that, if each receives a given fraction of the sum of the remaining three, the four results are eqiial. The e;iven fractions being 77 , 7 , ^ , ;r , we a^suvie the sum of ° ° 3 4 6 the last three numbers to be 3. Putting X for the first, Diophantos finds in like manner that numbers are 47, 77, 92, 101. 29. Given two numbers, to find a third which, when multiplied by each successively, makes one product a square and the other the side of that square. Given numbers 200, 5. X required number, 200a; = (oxY, a; = 8. 30. To find two numbers ivhose sum and whose product are given. Condition. The square of ludf the sum 7nust exceed tlie product by a square number, Iuti Se tovto irXaaixaTiKov '. Given sum 20, product 9G. 2x the difierence of the required numbers. Therefore numbers are 10 + x, 10 -x. Hence 100-aj'=96. Therefore x ^ 2, and the difierence = 4. The required numbei-s are 12, 8. 1 There has been much controversy as to the moaninR of this diflicult phrase. Xylancler, the author of the Schoha, Bachct, Cossali, Schulz, NcbhoI- mann, all discuss it. As I do not profess here to bo commcntinR on the text I shall uot criticise their respective views, hut ouly remark tliat I think it is best to take TrXaff/xariKov in a passive sense. "And this condition can (easily) be formed," i.e. can be investigated (and shown to bo tnu), or </i.«. covered. 170 DIOPIIANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. 31. 2^0 find two numbers, luiving given their sum and the sian of their squares. Condition. Double the sum of the squares must exceed the square of their sum by a sqxiare, Icrri Se KaX tovto irXaa-fxaiLKov. Sum 20, sum of squares 208. 2x the difference. Therefore the numbers arc 10 + .r, 10 - cc. Thus 200 + 2x- = 208. Hence x = 2, and the numbers are 12, 8. 32. To find two numbers, having given their sum and the difference of their squares. Sum 20, difference of squares 80. 2x difference of the numbers, and we find the numbers 12, 8. 33. I'ofind two munbcrs whose difference and product are given. Condition. Four times the 2)roduct together with square of differ- ence must produce a complete square, Icttl Se koI tovto TrXao-ynariKo'v. Difference 4, product 96. 2x the sum. Therefore the numbers are found to bo 12, 8. 31. Find two numbers in a given ratio sucli that the sum of their squares is to their sum also in a given ratio. Ratios 3 : 1 and 5 : 1 respectively. X lesser number, x—1] the numbers are 2, 6. 35. Find two numbers in a given ratio such that the sum of their squares is to then- difference in a given ratio, Ratios being 3 : 1, 10 : 1, the numbers are 2, 6. 36. Find two numbers in a given ratio such that the difference of their squares is to their sum in a given i*atio. Ratios being 3 : 1 and 6:1, the numbers arc 3, 9. 37. Find two numbers in a given i\atio such that the difference of their squares is to their difference in a given ratio. Ratios being 3 : 1 and 12 : 1, the numbers are 3, 9. Similarly by this method can be found two numbers in a given ratio (1) such tliat their product is to their sum in a given ratio, or (2) such that their product is to their diflerence in a given ratio. 38. To find two numbers in a given ratio such that the square of the smaller is to the larger in a given ratio. Ratios 3 : 1 and 6:1. Numbers 54, 18. ARITHMETICS. BOOK I. 171 39. To find two numbers in a given ratio such that tliu square of the smaller is to the smaller itself in a given ratio. Ratios 3 : 1 and G : 1. Numbers 18, 6. 40. To find two numbers in a given ratio such that the sf^uaro of the less has a given ratio to the sum of both. Ratios 3:1,2:1. Numbers 24, 8. 41. To find two numbers in a given ratio such that the square of the smaller has a given ratio to their diUcrcncc. Ratios 3 : 1 and G : 1. Numbers 36, 12. 42. Similarly can be found two numbei-s in a given ratio, (1) such that square of larger has a given ratio to the smaller. (2) such that square of larger has to larger itself a given i-atio, (3) such that squai'e of larger has a given ratio to the sum or difference of the two. 43. Given two numbers, to find a tliird such that the sums of the several paii's multiplied by the corresponding third give three numbers in A. p. Given numbers 3, 5. X the required number. Therefore the three expressions are 3a; +15, 5a; +15, 8a;. Now 3a; + 15 must be either the middle or the least of the three, 5a; + 15 cither the greatest or the middle. 15 (1) 5a;+ 15 greatest, 3x+ lo least. Therefore x=- -^ • 15 (2) 5x+ 15 greatest, 3a;+ 15 middle. Therefore x^ ^ . (3) 8a; greatest, 3a; + 15 least. Therefore x = 15. 172 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. BOOK 11. [The first five questions of this Book arc identical with questions in Book I. In each case the ratio of one required number to the other is assumed to be 2 : 1. The enunciations only are here given.] 1. To find two numbers whose sum is to the sum of their squares in a given ratio. 2. Find two numbers whose difference is to the difference of their squares in a given ratio. 3. Find two numbers whose product is to their sum or difference in a given ratio. 4. Find two numbers such that the sum of their squares is to the diffei'ence of the numbers in a given ratio. 5. Find two numbers such that the difference of their squares is to the sum of the numbers in a given ratio. 6. Find two numbers having a given difference, and such that the difference of their squares exceeds the difference of the numbers themselves by a given number. Condition. The square of their difference must be less than the sum of the two given differences. Difference of numbers 2, the other given number 20. X the smaller number. Therefore x + '2 is the larger and 4a; + 4 = 22. a; = 4|, and the numbers ai*e 4|, 6 J. 7. Find two numbers such that the diflTerence of their squares may be greater than their diflTerence by a given number and in a given ratio (to it)'. [Difference asswned.] Coiulition. The ratio being 3:1, the square of tlie difference of the numbers must be < sum of three times that difference and the given number. ui. ' By this Diophautos mcaiiK "may exceed a given proportion or fractio f it by a given number. " ARITHMETICS. BOOK II. 17:^ Given number 10, difference of nunibei-s required 2. X the smaller number. Therefore the hirger x + 2, and 4a; + 4 = 3 . 2+10. Therefore a; = 3, and the niimbei-s are 3, 5. 8. To divide a square mnnber into two squares. Let the square number be IG. x^ one of the required squares. Therefore IG-.r* must be equal to a square. Take a square of the form' {nix - 4)-, 4 being taken as the absolute term because the square of 4 = 1 G. i.e. take (say) (2a; -4)* and equate it to 16 -a;'. Therefore 4.'c- - 1 Gx = - x'. Therefore a^ = "5" , 5 ' ^.v 'A 256 144 and the squares required are -^ , -^ . 9. [Another solution of the foregoing, practically equivalent.] 10. I'o divide a number which is the sum of two squares into two other squares. Given number 13 = 3'+2^ As the roots of these squares are 2, 3, take [x + 2)* a.<? the first square and {mx - 3)" as tlie second required, say (2x- - 3)*. Therefore (x + 2 )^' + (2a; - 3)^' = 1 3 . 324 1 Therefore the required squares are -^^ > 05 " 11. To find two square numbers diflWing by a t/iven ntimber. Given difference GO. Side of one number x, side of the other x phis any number whose square < GO, say 3. Therefore (x- + 3)^' - a;' = 60, and the required .squares are 72], 132 j. » Diophantos' words are: "I form the s(iuare from any number of apiBnol minus as many units as are contained in the side of U)." The prt-eftution im- plied throuRhout in the choice of m is that we must assume it so tli-ii tli. r. suli may be rational in Diophantos' sense, i.e. rational and positive. 174 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. 12. To add such a number to each of two given numbers that the results shall both be squares. (1) Given numbers 2, 3, required number x. x + 2) Therefore ^M^^^^st each be squares. x+ o) ^ This is called a double-equation. To solve it, take the difference between them, and resolve it into tioo factors^ : in this case say 4 and -. . Then take either (a) the square of half the difference bettveen these factors and equate it to the smaller expression, or (b) the sqriare of half the sum and equate it to tlie larger. 225 In this case (a) the square of half the diflference = -^ . m r o 225 - 97 Iheretorc x+ ^= yrr > ^^^ ^ — wr, o4 d4 ... ^. 225 289 Avhilc the squares are -rr- , -ttt • (2) In order to avoid a double-equation, First find a number which added to 2 gives a square, say x^ — 2. Therefore, since the same number added to 3 gives a square, x' + 1= square = {x- 4y say, the absolute term (in this case 4) being so chosen that the solution may give x^>2. 15 Therefore x=-^ , 97 and the required number is ^ , as before. 13. Fro77i two given numbers to take the same (required) number so tluit both the remainders are squares. Given numbers 9, 21. Assuming 9 - x^ as the required number we satisfy one condi- tion, and it remains that 12 + a;" = a square. Assume as the side of this square x minus some number whose square > 12, say 4. 1 Wc must, as usual, choose suitable factors, i.e. such as will give a "ra- tioual" result. This must always be premised. ARITHMETICS. HOOK II. 175 Therefore (x - 4)^ = 1 2 + x\ 1 ^ = 2' and the required number is 8|. 14. Fro7n the same {required) number to subtract sui-cessiv:/;/ two given munbers so that the remainders may both be squares. 6, 7 the given numbers. Tlien (1) let cc be required number. Tlierefore cb - G~| , , ^ \ are both squares. The difference = 1, which is the product of 2 and .^ ; and, l)y the rule for solving a double-equation, 121 (2) To avoid a double-equation seek a number which exceeds a square by 6, i. e. let a;" + G be the required number. Therefore also x- - 1 : square = {x- 2)' say. Hence ^ ~ I ' and the number required = tr • 15. To divide a given number into tioo ])arts, and tojind a square number tohich when added to either of the two parts gives a square number. Given number 20. Take two numbci-s the sum of whose squares < 20, say 2, 3. Add x to each and square. "We then have x^ + 4a; + 41 X' + Gx + 'd) ' and if 4.x- + 4]^ 6a; + 9j are respectively subtracted the remaindei-s are the same s<|uiire. Let then x- be the square required, and therefore 4a; + 4"| Gx + Oj the required parts of 20. Then 10X-+13-20, and X ^ iV, . 176 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. (68 132\ iTi ' ~i7r ) ' 49 and the required square rrrrr . 16. To divide a given number into two parts and find a square which exceeds either part by a square. Given number 20. Take (x + rtif for the required square, where m' < 20, i.e. let (x + 2Y be the required sqi;are (say). This leaves a square if either 4a; + 4) . , ^ ^ , ^ ^ „ ?■ 1*5 subtracted, or 2.r + 3J Let these be the parts of 20, and x=-7, . b /76 44\ Therefore the parts required are (-w, /. ) > .625 and the required square is -^^ . ob 17. Find two numbers in a given ratio such that cither together with an assigned square produces a square. Assigned square 9, ratio 3:1. If we take a square whose side is mx + 3 and subtract 9 from it, the remainder will be one of the numbers required. Take e. g. (x + 3)^ - 9 = cc^ + 6a; for the smaller number. Therefore 3a;* + 18a; = the larger number, and 3x* + 18a; + 9 must be made a square - (2.x-- 3)" say. Therefore x = 30, and the required numbers are 1080, 3240. 18. To find three numbers such that, if each give to the next following a given fraction of itself and a given number besides, the results after each has given and taken may be equal. First gives to second - of itself + 6, second to third ^ of itself i> b + 7, third to first = of itself + 8. Assume that the first two are 5x, Gx [equivalent to one con- ,.,. -, , ,. , ,, , ^ - 90 108 105 ditionj, aiul we find the numbei"s to be - , - , -=- . ARITHMETICS. BOOK H. 177 19. Divide a number into throe parts .sati-sfyinfj tlio conditions of tlie preceding problem. Given number 80. First gives to second p of itself + G ic, and results are equal. [Diophantos a.ssumes 5x, 12 for tlie first two nunilM-rs, and his ,^ . 170 228 217 , result IS -y^- , — , — ; but the solution does not cor- respond to the question.] (See p. 2.5.) 20. To find three squares such that the difference of the great- est and the second is to the diffei-ence of the .second and the lea.st in a given ratio. Given ratio 3:1. Assume the least square ^- .r^, the middle = .r* -I- 2x -f 1. Therefore the greatest = x° + 8x + 4 = square = {x + SYsay. Therefore x ^ '■ , and the squares are 30|, 12^, 6;^. 21. To find two numbers such that the square of either added to the other number is a square. X, 2a; -1- 1 are assumed, which by their form satisfy one con- dition. The other condition gives 4x- + 5x + \ ^ square = (2.c - 2)" say. 3 Therefore ,-« = --, 3 19 and the numbers are :^ , ^^ . Id lo 22. To find two numbers such that the square of eitlier utitntu the other number is a square. a; -f- 1 , 2.r -f- 1 are assumed, satisfying one condition. Therefore 4.7;^ -i- 3x - square - 9,r* say. 3 Therefore -^ = ? > and the numbers are ^ . c • 5 23. To find two numbers such that the sum of the square of either and the sum of both is a square. Assume x, x+l for the numbers. These satisfy one condi- tion. H. D. 12 178 DIOPnANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Also a;* + ix + 2 must be a square = {x - 2)* say. Therefore x = -, . 4 1 5 Hence the numbers are t , ^ . 4 4 24. To find two numbers such that the clifTerence of the square of either and the sum of both is a square. Assume x + 1, x for the numbers, and we must have a;^ - 2a; - 1 a square = {x- 3)- say. Therefore x=^, and the nvimbei's are 3|, 2^. 25. To find two numbers such that the sum of either and the square of their sura is a square. Since 03" + 3x^, x^ + 8x' are squares, let the numbers be 3x-, Sx- and their sum x. Therefore 1 Icc^ = a; and a; = yy . 3 8 Therefore the numbers are y^ , ynT • 26. To find two nunibers such that the difference of the square of the sum of both and either number is a square. If we subtract 7, 12 from 16 we get squares. Assume then 12a;', 7x^ for the numbers, 1 6a;" = square of sum. 4 Therefore Idoif = ix, x = ^1) f 192 112 and the numbers are ^„^ , ^r^^ . obi obi 27. To find two numbers such that the sum of either and their product is a square, and the sum of the sides of the two squan s so arising equal to a given number, 6 suppose. Since x (4a; - 1) + a; = square, let a;, 4a; - 1 be the numbers. Therefore 4a;* + 3a; - 1 is a square, whose side is 6 - 2a;. 37 Therefore x = --, in 1 37 121 and the numbers are - , . ^1 til 28. To find two numbers sndi that tlu; difference of their pro- duct and either is a square, and the sum of the sides of the two squares so arising equal to a number, 5. ARITIIMKTICS. ROOK II. 17!» Assume 4a; + 1, x for tlie nuinheis, wliicli tlicit.'foie satisfy on*- condition. Also 4.V* - 3x- - 1 - {') - 2,<f . Thoivforc .r : "'' 17' 26 121 and the numbers are - , 29. To find two square numhrrs such that the sum of the product and either is a square. Let the numbers ' be x", y". Therefore o „ ..\ are both snuares. a;V + .r-j ' To make the first a square we make x" + 1 a square, putting x^ + 1 = (x - 1)-. Therefore x = '-. 4 We have now to make y— (_j/^ + 1) a square [and y must be different from x\. Put 9/ + 9 = (3^ - 4)' sav. Therefore y=-^-:. 9 49 Therefore the numbers are .— , ^^ . lb 0/b 30. To find two square numbers such that the difference of their pi*oduct and either is a square. Let a;', y' be the numbers. Therefore aJ*2/^ — '/) , ,, 2 2 zf ^^^ ^^<^Vi\ squares. X y — X ) , 2;") A solution of x? -\ ^ square is re ^ .^ , and a solution of y- - 1 = square is _?/= — . m, . , 1 25 289 Therefore the numbers are , „ , -^ . • lb 04 31. To find two numbers such that their product ± their sum gives a square. 1 DIophantos docs not use two unknowns, but assumes the numl)crs to bo x"- and 1 until ho has found x. Then he uses the same unknown to find wliat be had first called unity, as explained above, p. 81. The same remark applies to tho next problem. 12-2 180 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. a' + ^= ± 2ab is a square. Put 2, 3 for a, b, and 2- + 3' ± 2 . 2 . 3 is a square. Assume then product = (2' + 3") .x*^ = 13a;", the numbers being x, 1 3x, and the sum 2 . 2 . 3aj° or 1 2x-°. 7 Thei-efore 14a; = 1 2x^, and x= ^. 7 91 Therefore the numbers are ^ , -^ . b 32. To find two numbers whose sum is a square and ha\dng the same property as the numbers in the preceding problem. 2 . 2m . m = square, and 2m\^ + «i|^ ± 2 . 2m. in = square. Ifw-2, 4'+2'±2.4.2 = 36or 4. Let then the product of numbers be (4' + 2') x^ or 20a;' and their sum 2 . 4 . 2x- or 16a;*, and let the numbers be 2a;, lOx. 3 Therefore 1 2a; = 1 Qx', x = -, 6 30 and the numbers are ^ , -t-. 4 4 33. To find three numbers such that the sum of the square of any one and the succeeding number is a square. Let the first be x, the second 2a; + 1, the third 2 (2a'+ 1) + 1 or 4a; + 3, so that two conditions are satisfied. Lastly (4a; + 3)' + x = square = (4a; - 4)" say. 7 Therefore a; - ^^ , 57 7 71 199 and the numbers are _^ , ^ , -^ . 34. To find three numbers such that the difieronce of the square of any one and the succeeding number is a square. Assume first a; + l, second 2a: +1, third 4a; + 1. Therefore two conditions are satisfied, and the third gives 1 Ga;' +7x = square = 25a;* say. 7 Therefore "^ ^ n > 16 23 37 and the numbers are n , -q- , -q • 35. To find three numbers such that, if the square of any one be added to the sum of all, the result is a square. /7>i-n\ ^ ^^^^ .^ ^ square. Take a number soparublo into ARITHMETICS. BOOK 111. IM two factors (m, u) in three ways, say 12, whicli is tlio pro duct of (1, 12), (2, 6), (3, 4). The values then of — ^ — are 5.\, 2, - . Let now o\x, 2x, ^x be the numbers. Their sum is 12.r'. Therefore So; = 1 2.t*, a: = !^ , and the numbei-s are - , ^ , q • O ij <J 30. To find three numbers such that, if the sum of all be sub- tracted from the square of auy one, the result is a square. — ^r— J —mn is a square. Take 12 as before, and let G.^x, Ax, Zlx be the numbers, their sum being \'2x*. Therefore x = - , G , ,, , 91 28 49 and the numbers are vt, , - , ,^^ . 12' 6 ' 12 BOOK III. 1. To find three numbers such that, if the square of any one be subtracted from the sum of all, the remainder is a square. Take two squares af, 4a;* whose sum = 5x". Let the sum of all three numbers be 5.*;^, and two of the numbers X, 2x. These assumptions satisfy two couditions. 4 121 Next divide 5 into the sum of two squares [ii. 10] ^-^, -^, 2 and assume that the third nuuiber is t x. 2 17 Therefore x+2x+ ^x = 5x^ Therefore a; = ,, . , 17 34 34 and the numbers are — , , ^-^ • 2. To find three numbers such that, if the scjuare of the sum be added to any one of them, the suui is a s(|uan'. L^^ = ix,x = l7' 28 289 48 ' 289 60 ' 289 182 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Let the square of the sum be x', aud the numbers 3x', Sx", 15a;'. Hence 2Gx^ - x, sc = ^ , and the numbers are ^^ , g^g , ^. 3. To find three numbers such that, if any one be subtracted from the square of their sum, the result is a square. Sum of all 4a;, its square 16a;", the numbers 7x^, 12.v*, \5x'. Therefore and the numbers are 4. To find three numbers such that, if the square of their sum be subtracted from any one, the result is a square. Sum X, the three numbers 2a;'', 5x^, lO.f'^. Therefore x = ^r^ , It and the numbers are ir^r^ , r-r^ , ^r—z^ . 289' 289' 289 5. To find three numbers such that the sum of any pair exceeds the third by a square, and the sum of all is a square. Let the sum of the three be (x+l)"; let first + second=third+ 1, x^ so that third .- '^ + a; ; let second + third - first + x", 1 a;* 1 so that first = a; + ^ . Therefore second ='^ + ^ . But first + third = second + square, therefore 2.*; = square = 16, suppose. Therefore x = S, and (8^, 32^, 40) is a solution. 6. [The same otherwise.] First find three squares whose sum is a square. Find e.g. what square number + 4 + 9 gives a square, i.e. 36. Therefore (4, 36, 9) are such squares. Next find three numbers such that sum of a pair = third + given number, say, first + second- third = 4, second + third - first = 9, third + first - second = 36, by the previous problem. 7. To find three numbers whose sum is a square, and such that the sum of any pair is a square. ARITHMETICS. BOOK III. 183 Let the sum be a;* + 2.«+l, sum of fh-st and sccoml x*, and therefore the third 2a; + 1 ; let second + third = (x- 1)*. Therefore the first is 4a:, and therefore the secontl x* - 4x. But first + third = square, or G.t- + 1 = square -Vl\ say. Therefore s; = 20, and t]ie numbers are (80, 320, 41). 8. [The same otherwise.] 9. To find three numbers in A. p. such that the sum of any pair is a square. First find three square numbers in A. p. any two of which are together > the third. Let x^, {x + 1 )* be two of these ; therefore the tliird is a;* + 4a; + 2 = (a; - 8)* say. 31 Therefoi-e x - ..., or we may take as the squares 961, 1G81, 2401. We have now to find three numbers, the sum.s of pairs being these numbers. Suin of the three = ^-^ = 252 U-, and we have all the three numbers. 10. Given one number, to find three others such that the sura of any pair of them and the given number is a square, and also the sura of the three and the given number is a square. Given number 3. Suppose first + second = x* + 4a; + 1, second + third - x" + G.f + 6, sum of all three = x* + 8x + 13. Therefore third = 4.« + 1 2, second = x-° + 2x - 6, first = 2x + 7. Also third + first + 3 = square, or 6x+22 = squai-e=K)0sui)i)Ose. Therefore o: = 1 3, and the numbers are 33, 189, 64 11. Given one number, to find three othci-s such that, if the given number be subtracted from the sum of any pair of them or from the sum, the results are all squares. Given number 3. Sum of first two x* + 3, of next pair x' + 2x + 4, and sum of the three x* + 4x + 7. Therefore third = 4x + 4, second = x* - 2x, first = 2x + 3. Therefore, lastly, 6x + 4 = square -- 64 say. Therefore x=10, and (23, 80, 44) is a solution. 184 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. 12. To find three numbers such that the sum of the product of any two and a given nmnher is a square. Let the given number be 12. Take a square (say 25) and sub- tract 12. Take the difference (13) for the product of the first and second numbers, and let these numbers be ISrc, - . X Again, subtract 1 2 from another square, say 1 6, and let the diffei-ence 4 be the product of the second and third numbers. Therefore the third number = ix. Hence the third condition gives 52.7;^+ 12 = square, but 52 = 4. 13, and 13 is not a square, therefore this equa- tion cannot be solved by our method. Thus we must find two numbers to replace 13 and 4 whose product is a square, and such that either +12 = square. Now the product is a square if both are squares. Hence we must find two squares such that either + 12 = square. The squares 4 and ^ satisfy this condition. Retracing our steps we put 4.r, - , - for the numbers, and we have to solve the equation X' +12 = square = (as + 3)^ say. Therefore « = n , and (2, 2, ^) is a solution. o 13. To find three numbers sui;h that, if a given number is sub- tracted from the product of any pair, the result is a square. Given number 10. Put product of first and second =a square + 10=4 + 10 say, and let first = 14.r, second = - . Also let product of second andthird=19. Therefore third = 19a;. Whence 2G6x-'- 10 must be a square; but 266 is not a square. Hence, as in the preceding problem, we must find two squares each of which exceeds a square by 10. Now ( — - — 1 -10-[--^-], therefore 30| is one sucli square. If vi' be another, ta'-XO must be a square = (m - 2)" say, therefore in = 3^. AUITHMETICS. BOOK III. 185 Thus, putting 30 jr, -, 12;iu; for the uumbei-s, we have, from the third coudition, [)929x-^- 1 GO ^square =^(7 7a;- 2)* say. Therefore x = ^r= , 1 1 1 ,1 , 1240] 77 5021 and the numbers arc „„ , ., , ■ 77 '41' 77 U. To find three numbers such that the product of any two added to tlie third gives a square. Take a square and subtract part of it for tlie tliinl number. Let x^ +6x+d be one of the sums, and let the third number be 9. Therefore product of fii-st and second = x* + 6x. Let the fii'st = x, therefore the second = a; + G. From the two remaining conditions 10a: + 54) . . 10a; + 6/ are both squares. Therefore we have to find two squares differing l)y 48, wliich are found to be IG, G4. and (1, 7, 9) is a solution. 15. To tind three numbers such that the product of any two exceeds the third by a square. First X, second x + 4, therefoi-e their product is x- + Ix, and we suppose the third to be 4a;. Therefore by the other conditions 4x- + 15a; ) , ^, -2 a\ ^^'^ **^ squares. The difference = IGa; + 4 = 4 (4a; + 1), and f -^-TT — ) = 4 a;' + 15a;. / 4.r + 5 Y 25 Therefore ^'' = ^,^, 'ind the numbers are found. IG. To find throe numbers such that tlie product of any two added to the square of the third gives a square. Let first be x, second 4x + 4, third 1. Two conditions arc thus satisfied, and the remaining one gives a; + (4a; + 4)^ ^ a square - (4a; - 5)' say. 9 Tlierefore a^ = ;r:t > and the numbers are 9, 328, 73. i^^)'- 186 DIOPIIANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. 17. To find three numbers such that the product of any two added to the sum of those two gives a square. Leimna. The squares of two consecutive numbers liave this property. Let 4, 9 be two of the numbers, x the third. Therefore 10a; + 9) , , , , I must both be squares, 5a; + 4 j ^ and tlie difference = 5a; + 5 = 5 (a; + 1). Therefore by Book ii., 10a: + 9 and a; =28, and (4, 9, 28) is a solution. 18. \_Another solution of the foo'egoinff problem.] Assume the first to be x, the second 3. Therefore 4a; + 3 = square = 2-5 say, whence a; = 5^, and 5^, 3 satisfy one condition. Let the third be a;, 5^ and 3 being the first two. Therefore 4a; + 3 ) , , ., , -, _, > must both be squares, C^a; + 5iJ ^ bid, since the copfficients in one expression are both greater than those in the other, but neither of the ratios of corre- sponding ones is that of a square to a square, our method will not solve them. Hence (to replace 51, 3) we must find two numbers such that their product + their sum = square, and the ratio of the numbers each increased by 1 is the ratio of a square to a square. Let them be y and 4?/ + 3, which satisfy the latter con- dition ; and so that product + sum = square we must have 4y^ + 81/ + 3 - square = (2^ - 3)'', say. 3 Therefore y = -- 3 Assume now ^tt, 45, a; for the numbers. Therefore oja; + 4M 13x 3 \- ave both squares. To" "^ 10) or 130a; +1051 , . 130X+ 30J -- 1-^1-^"--^' ARITHMETICS. BOOK III. 187 the ditlerence = 75, -wliicli has two factors 3 ami 2"), 7 and X - :^A gives a solution, 3 7 the numbers being , 4J, . 19. To fniil three numbers siu-li tliat the iiroduct of any two exceeds the sum of those two by a square. Put first = X, second any number, and we fall into the same difficulty as in the preceding. We have to find two numbers such that their product minus their sum = square, and when each is diminished by one they have the ratio of squares. 4?/+l, y+l satisfy the latter condition, and it/- - 1 - square -{2i/ — 2)' say. 5 Therefore !/ = :>• c 13 28 Assume then as the numbers -^- , ~, x. b b Therefore 2}^x-3U 5 , _ ^ /• are both squares, 8 ''*'' ~ 8 ) or lOx-U] . ^. 10a;-2Gj "'"^ 'l"'^'"^^' the difterence = 12 = 2 .G, and x =^ 3 is a solution. 13 The numbers are -^ , 3h, 3. o 20. To find two numbers such that their product added to both or to cither gives a square. Assume x, ix - 1 , since x{ix- 1) + x = ix^ = square. Therefore also 4a,-' + 3.x- - 1 ) , ^, , > arc both squares, 4x^ + ix-l) the diflference = x = 4a; , 7 , 4 and X = ,j^ gives a solution. 21. To find two numbers such that the product exceeds tho sum of both, and also cither severally, V)y a stjuare. Assume x + 1, ix, since 4a; (x- + 1 ) - 4a; = scpiare. 188 DIOPIIANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Therefore also 4a;* + 3.« - 1 ~) , , 2 'j- are both squares, the difference = ix = 4x. 1. Therefore a;=l], and (2|, 5) is a solution. 22. To find four numbers such that, if we take the square of the sum ± any one singly, all the resulting numbers are squares. Since in a rational right-angled triangle square on hypotenuse = squares on sides, square on hypotenuse =*= twice product of sides = square. Therefore we must find a square which will admit of division into two squares in four ways. Take the right-angled triangles (3, 4, 5), (5, 12, 13). Multiply the sides of the first by the hypotenuse of the second and vice versa. Therefore we have the triangles (39, 52, 65), (25, 60, 65). Thus 65^ is split up into two squares in two ways. Also G5 = 7' + 4' = 8^-hP. Therefore 65^ = {T - ^J + 4 . 7^ 4" = (8^ - 1')^ + 4 . 8M* . = 33'' + 56^= 63* +16', which gives two more ways. Thus 65* is split into two squares in four ways. Assume now as the sum of the numbers 65a;, first number = 2 .39 . 52a;* = 4056a;*^ second „ =2 25 . 60x* = 3000a;* third „ =2.33. 56a;* = 3696a;* i fourth „ =2.16.63.«*=2016a;*j 65 Therefore 12768x-* = 65a; and x=i21Q9>' and the numbers arc found, viz. 17136600 12675000 15615600 8517600 163021824' 163021824' 163021824' 163021824" 23. To divide a given number into two j)arts, and to find a sijuare which exceeds either of the parts by a scpiare. Let the given number be 10, and the square x" + 1x + 1. Put one of the parts 2.'b+1, the other 4a;. Therefore the conditions are satisfied if fix- -I- 1 = 10. and the sum = 12768x* Tlierefore ARITHMETICS. HOOK IV. 189 3 X- and the parts are 6, 4, the square 6]. 24. To divide a given number into two parts, and to find ii square which added to either of the parts produces a square. Given number 20. Let the square be x^ + 2x+\. Tliis is a square if we add 2a; + 3 or 4a; + 8. Therefore, if these ai'e the parts, the conditions are .satisfied when 6a; + 1 1 = 20, or a; ~ H. Therefore the numbers into which 20 is divided an- (6, 14) and the required square is 6^. BOOK IV. 1. To divide a given number into two cubes, such that the sum of their sides is a given number. Given number 370, sum of sides 10. Sides of cubes 5 + x,5-x. Therefore 30x' 4 250 = 370, x = 2, and the cubes are 7^, 3^. 2. To find two numbers whose difference is given, and also the difference of their cubes. Difference 6. Difference of cubes 504. Let the numbcra be- a; + 3, a; - 3. Therefore 1 8a;* + 54 = 504. Tlierefore a;' = 25, a; = 5, and the sides of the cubes are 8, 2. 3. A number multiplied into a square and its side makes the latter product a cube of which the foi-mer product is the side; to find the square. Let the square be a;". Therefore its side is x, and let tho Q number be - . Hence the products are 8a;, 8, and {Sxy = rr,, . . 1 1 Therefore a; = ^ , ^ = 7- 190 DIOPnANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. 4. To add the same number to a square and its side and make them the same, [i.e. make the first product a square of which the second product is side]'. Square cc^, whose side is x. Let the number added to x' be such as to make a square, say 3a;". Therefore Zx" + x = side of 4x° = 2x and x = ^. The square is 3 and the number is - . 5. To add the same number to a square and its side and make them the opposite. Square x^, the number ix° - x. Hence 5a;^ -x = side of 4a;" = 2.r, and x--=. 6. To add the same square number to a square and a cube and make them the same. Let the cube be o;^ and the square any square number of x^'s,, say Ox--. Add to the square 16a;^ (The 16 is arrived at by taking two factors of 9, say 1 and 9, subtracting them, halving the remainder and squaring.) 1 o Therefore x^ + 16.«" = cube = S.c'' suppose and a; = — . Whence the numbers are known. 7. Add to a cube and a square the same square and make them the opposite. [Call the cube (1), first square (2), and the added square (3)]. Now suppose (2) + (3) = (1) [since (2) + (3) = a cube\. Now a' + y^2ah is a square. Suppose then {\) =a- + 1/, (3) = 2ah. But (3) must be a square. Therefoi-e 2ab must be a square ; hence we put « = 1, & = 2. Tlius suppose (1) = 5x^, (3) = 4,r-, (2) = x^. Now (1) is a cube. Therefore a? - 5, and (1)- 125, (2) = 25, (3) = 100. ' 111 this aud the following enunciations I have kept closely to the Greek, partly for the purpose of showing Diophautos' mode of expression, and partly for the brevity gained thereby. "To make them the same" means in the case of -1 what I have put in brackets; "to make them the opposite" means to make the first product a side of which the second product is the square. ARITHMETICS. BOOK IV. 191 8. [Another solution of the foregoing.] Since (2) + (3) = (l), a cube, and (1) + (3) = .square, I havn to find two squares whose .sum + one of thoni - a S(iuan', and whose sum = (l). Let the fii-st square be ar*, the second 4. Therefore 2.r + 4 = a square = (2^; - 2)' say. Therefore x = i, and the squares are IG, 4. Assume now (2) = ix\ (3) = IGx'. Therefore 20a;' = a cube, and x = 20, thus (8000, 1600, 6400) is a solution. 9. To add the same number to a cidje and its side, and make them the same. Added number x, cube 8x-^, say. Therefore second sum = 3a;, and this must be the side of cube Sx^ + x, or 8a;^ + a; = 27x'. Therefore 19x' = a;. But 19 is not a square. Hence we must find a square to replace it. Kow the side 3a; comes fx-om the assumed 2j;. Hence we must find two consecutive numbers whose cubes differ by a square. Let them he y, y+\. Therefore 3v/" + 3v/ + 1 =square = (l — 2?/)* say, and y = l. Thus instead of 2 and 3 we must take 7 and 8. Assuming now added number = x, side of cul)e = Ix, side of new cube — 8a;, we find 343.<;' + x = 512x''\ Therefore a;^ = ^J^, a; = l. (343 7 1 \ 2197'T3'13;^'^'"^"^^""- 10. To add the same number to a cube and its sid'! and i/uikc them the opjwsite. Suppose tlie cube 8x-^, its side 2x, the number 27x-' - 2a;. Therefore 35x' - 2a; = side of cube 27j;', therefore 3r)x*-5 = 0. This gives no rational value. Now 35 = 27 + 8, 5 = 3 + 2. '^ Therefore we must find two numbers the sum of wlioso cubes bears to the sum of the numbers tlie ratio of a square to a square. Let sum of sides = anything, 2 say, and side of first cul>c = :. Therefore 8 - 12^3 + 6s' = twice a square. Therefore i-(jz + 3z^ = a .square = (2 - 45)* sjiy, and : = on- 192 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. of the sides = ^ ^ , and the other side = j^ . Take for them 5 and 8. Assuming now as the cube \'25x^, and as the number 5 1 2^' - 5x, we get 637a;^ -5x = 8x, and a; = - , , /125 5 267\ . 11. To find two cubes whose sum equals the sum of their sides. Let the sides be 2x, Sx. This gives 35a;' = 5x. This equation gives no rational result. Finding as in the preceding problem an equation to replace it, 637a;' = 1 Sx, a; = = , 1.1 1 125 512 and the cubes are ^^ , -^^^ . 12. To find two cubes whose difference equals the difference of their sides. Assume as sides 2x, 3x. This gives Idx^ = x. Irrational; and their difference we have to find two cubes such that difference of sides = ratio of squares. Let them be (z + 1)*, z\ Therefore Sz' + 3;^ + 1 = square = (1 - 2z)- say. Therefore z = 7. Now assume as sides 7a;, Sx. Therefore 169a;* = a;, and .'c=t^. 1 o Therefore the two cubes (i^> a 13. To find two numbers such that the cube of the greater + the less = the cube of the less + the greater. Assume 2a;, 3a;. Therefore 27a;' + 2a; = Sa;' + 3a;. Therefore 19.x' = a;, which gives an irrational result. Hence, as in 12th problem, we must assume 7a;, 8a;, 7 8 and the numbers are as there v:^ , ^g • 1 4. To find two numbers such that either, or their sum, or their difference increased by 1 gives a square. Take unity from any square for the first number ; let it be, say, 9a;" + 6.r. ARITHMETICS. BOOK IV. 19:^ But the second + 1 =a square. Therefore wc must Cnd a squar.- such that the square found + 9x* + 6x = a square. Taku factors of 9j;* + 6.r, nz, (9x+6, x). Square of half dif ference -16xf + 24a; + 9. Therefore, if we put the second number IG.c" + 24.C + 8, threo conditions are satisfied, and the remaining condition gives difference + 1 = square. Hence 7a;* + 1 Sx + 9 = square = (3 - 3x-)- say. Therefore x = 18, and (3024, 5624) is a solution. 15. To find three square numbers such that their sum equals the sum of their differences. 8umo{diSerences=A-B+B-C+A-C = 2{A-C) = A+B+C, by the question. Let least (C) = 1, greatest = a;' + 2.x- + 1. Therefore sum of the three squares = 2x^ + ix = x^ + 2a; + 2 + the middle one. Therefore the middle one (JB) = a;' + 2a; - 2. This is a 9 square, = (x - 4)" say. Therefore a; = - , and the squares are (s^, ~nr ? 1 ) '^'' (196, 121, 25). 16. To find three numbers such that the sum of any two multi- plied by the third is a given number. Let (fii-st + second) . third = 35, (second + third) . first = 27, and (third + first) . second = 32, and let the third = x. 3.3 Therefore first + second = Assume first = 1*^ — , second X 250 Therefore ^^^ If + 10 = 27~ + 25 = 32 These equatians are inconsistent, but if 25 - 10 u-ere t^ual to 32 - 27 or 5 they would be right. Therefore we have t<» divide 35 into two parts differing by 5, i.e. 15 and 20. Thus first number = — , second = — . Therefore . +15-27, r*^ X * II. 1). X--5, and (3, 4. 5) is a solution. 13 194 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. 17. To fiiid three numbers whose sum is a square, and such th<(t the sum 0/ the square of each and the succeeding number is a square. Let the middle number be 4a;. Therefore I must find what square + ^x gives a square. Take two numbers whose product is ix, say 2ic and 2. Therefore {x-\y is the square. Thus the first number = £c- 1. Again 16x-* + third = square. Therefore third = a square - 1 6a;* = (4a; + Vf—YQtx? say, = 8a;+ 1 . Now the three together = square, therefore 13a;=square=1697/- say. Therefore x=\ 3^. Hence the numbers are ISy^'-l, 52/, 104/ +1. Lastly, (third)* + first = square. Therefore 10816/ + 221/ = a square or 10816/ + 221= a 220 55 square = (104y/ +1)° say. Therefore y = -"- = — , , /36621 157300 317304\ . , . 18. To find three numbers whose sum is a square, and such that the difference of the square of any one and the succeeding number is a square. The solution is exactly similar to the last, the numbers being in this case 13/ +1, 52/, 104/ -1. The resulting equation is 10816/ - 221 = square = (104^ - 1)-, whence 2/ =-^^-^, , /170989 640692 1270568\ . ^^^ (T08I6-' T0816 ' 10816 ; ^^ " ^^^"*^°'^- 19. To find two numbers such that the cube of the first + thr second - a cube, the square of the second + the first = a square. Let the first be x, the second 8-a;'', therefore a;''-16.r''+64 + a' = a square = (x* + 8)* say, whence 32a;^ = x. This gives an irrational result since 32 is not a square. Now 32 = 4. 8. Therefore we must put in our assumptions 4 . 64 insteail. Then the second number is 64 -a;^, and we get, as an equation for x, 256a;» = 1 . Therefore x = — , lb 1 262143 and tlu. numbers are jg, ^^gg . ARITHMETICS. UOOK IV. 10.", 20. To jlud three numbers imfffinite/i/^ s?/<7( (/uU the ]>ro<liict «/ ani/ two increased by 1 is a square. Let the product of first and second be x* + 2x, whence on»i condition is satisfied, if second = x, first = x + 2. Now th« product of second and third + 1 =a square ; let this pro- duct be Ox* + 6a;, so that third number =^x + G. Also lh(? product of third and first + 1 = square, i.e. 9x* + 24j; + 13 ^ a square. Nov.\ if 13 ivere a square, and tfie coefficient of X v}ere 6 times the side of this square, the problem icoubl be solved indefinitelij as required. Now 13 comes from 6.2 + 1, the 6 from 2 . 3, and the 2 from 2.1. Therefore we want a number to replace 3 . 1 such that four times it + 1 = a square ; therefore we need only take two numbers whose difierence is 1, say 1 and 2 [and 4. 2.1+ (2 — 1)- = square]. Then, beginning again, we put product of first and second = x-* + 2a-, second x, first x+2, pi'oduct of second and third = 4x* + 4.r, and third = ix + 4. [Then first x third + 1 = 4«- + 1 2x + 0. ] And (x + 2, X, 4x + 4) is a solution. 21. To find four numbers sicch that the product of ani/ two, ina'eased by 1, becomes a square. Assume that the product of first and second = a;* + '2x, fii-st = x, second = x + 2, and similarly third = 4x + 4, fourth =9a:+ G, but (4a; + 4)(9a; + 6) + 1 = square = 36a;- + 60x + 2;3. Also for second and fourth, 9x-' + 24x + 1 3 = square = (O.v- - 24..- + 1 6), say. Therefore x = -r-^. lb All the conditions are now satisfied*, 68 105\ ^ /J^ 33 ^° V16' 16' the solution bein^ i ^t, > t^ > -i « > if. 22. Find three numbers which are proportional and such that the difference of any two is a square. Assume a; to be the least, x + 4 the midiUe, x + 1 3 the greatoist. therefore if 13 were a square we shoidd have an indefi- nite solution satisfying three of the conditions. We muHt 1 I.e. in general expressions. 2 Product of second and third + 1 = (a: + 2) (ix + 4) + 1 - i-c' ♦ l'^-^ + 9. ^hidi i« a square. 1.1—2 196 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. therefore replace 13 l)y a squai-e wliich is tlie sura of two squares. Thus if \vc assume x, x + 9, x+ 25, three conditions are satisfied, and the fourth gives x (x + 25) = {x + 9)", there- fore x = -;^ , I . ,81 144 256\ . . ^. I i IT , „- . r,- IS a solution. /«i 144 ZDt)\ [j ' T ' 7') 23. To find three numhers such that the sum of their solid content^ and any one of them is a square. Let the product be x' + 2x, and the first number 1, the second £C*+ 2x ix + 9 ; therefore the third = :, — -^ . This cannot be divided out generally unless x^: 4:X=2x : 9 or a;" : 2.^'=4a; : 9, and it could be done if 4 were half of 9. Now ix comes from (jx - 2x, and 9 from 3^, therefore we have to find a number m to replace 3 such that 2»i-2 = -^, therefore m^ = 4w - 4 or m = 2. ^ We put therefore for the second number 2x + 4, and the third then becomes Ix. Therefore also [third condition] 5 x^ + 2x + \x - square = ix^ say, whence x= , . (. 34 1\\ . solution. 24. To find three numbers such that tJie difference of their solid content and any one of them is a square. Fii'st x, solid content x^.+ x; therefore the product of second and third = 03 + 1 ; let the second = 1 . Therefore the two remaining conditions give a i both squares [Double equation.] Difference = cc = ^ . 2a;, aay ; therefore (.t + :^)' = vX-*+k-1, x- .™.(^;,i, 8 -— ) is a .solution. I.e. the continued product of all three. Observe the solution of a mixed quadratic. X- 27' 26 27 136 ARITHMETICS. UooK IV. l!l7 25. Divide a givou number into two jiarts wljose prcKluct i.s a cube mltius its side. Given number 6. First part x ; therefore second = 6 - x, and 6a; - a;* = a cube minus its side = {^x-lf- (2x - 1 ) say, so that 8x^ - 1 2.t' + ix = Gx - x'. This wouUl reduce to a simple equation if the coefficient of x were the same on both sides. To make tliis so, since G is lixcd, we must put m for 2 in our assumption, where 3m - )n = G, or m = 3. Therefore, altering the assumption, (3x•-l)^-(3x•-l)=6x•-.t•^ , 26 whence and the parts are 2G. To divide a rjiven number into three parts sii.<7i that their con- firmed 2)roduct equals a cube lohose skle is the sum oj' their differencen. Given number 4. Let the product be 8a;' : now the sum of differences = twice difference between third and firat; therefore difference between third and first parts = x. Let the first be a multiple of a;, say 2a;. Therefore the third = 3a;. Hence the second = r. ^, ii"d, if the second had lain between o the first and third, the problem would have been solved. Now the second came from dividing 8 by 2 . 3,- so that we have S to find two consecutive numbers such that ^, . , ^ their product lies between them. Assume m, m + 1 ; therefore -, 7/t + m lies between m and m + 1. g Therefore —5 + 1 > ?« + L m + m Therefore m* + m + 8 > 7?i' + 2«t' + m, or 8 > m" i in\ 1\' Take (IN ' "i + ., ) ) which is > m"" + m, and p.|u:itc it t< Therefore m + ;^ - 2, and m = \^ 27 cube. 198 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Hence we assume for the numbers 5 9 8 3^' 5'^'' 3^' or (25x, 27a;, -iOx), multiplying throughout by 15. Therefore the sum = d2x= 4, and •'k = oo j and f -^ , , „ j are the three parts required. o [N.B. The condition —^ <m+l is ignored in the work, and is incidentally satisfied.] To find two numbers whose product added to either gives a Suppose the first number equals a cube number of a;'s, say 8a;. Second a;^ - 1, (so that 8a;^ - 8a; + 8a; = cube); also 8a;' - 8a; + a;^ - 1 must be a cube = (2a; — 1)^ say. 14 Therefore 1 2>x* = 1 4,x-, x = yoi 1 o ^"^ (13-' res) i« ^ soi^^ti^"- 28. To find two numbers such that the difference between the product and either is a cube. Let the first be 8a;, the second a;^ + 1 (since 8a;'+8a; - 8a;= cube) ; also 8if^ + 8a; - a;* - 1 must be a cube, which is "im- possible " [for to get rid of the third power and the abso- lute term we can only put this equal to (2a;- 1)^ which gives an " irrational " result]. Assume then the first = 8a; + 1, the second = a;* (since 8a;^ + a;^ - x^ = cube). Therefore 8a;' + a;" - 8.r - 1 = a cube = {2x - If say. 14 Therefore x = y^ , wi ^ 125 196 and the nunilx'rs are „- , . Id 169 29. To find two numbers such that their product =t their sum - a cube. Let the first cube be G4, the second 8. Therefore twice the sum of the numbers = 64 - 8 = 56, and the sum of the numbers = 28, but thi-ii- product + their sum = 64. Therefore their product - 36. ARITHMETICS. BOOK IV. 199 Therefore we have to tind two numbers whose sum -• 28, and whose product = 36. Assuming 14 +a;, 14 -x for these numbers, 196 -x':::^ 36 and x* = 160, and if 160 were a a square we could solve it rationally. Now 160 arises from 1 4'' -36, and 14= J. 28 --.56 2 4 = T (diflference of cubes) ; 36 = ^ sum of cubes. Therefore we have to find two cubes sucli that ( - of their difiereuce ) - ^^ their sum = a square. Let the sides of these cubes be s + 1 , s - 1 . 1 3 1 Therefore - of their difference = r> ~' + ;j> '^^^^ the square of this 9,3,1 =r ^2^'^4- Hence ( - . differer cc ) ^ .^ • sum = t ~ + ;> =' + a~~) v"^ "*" "')• Therefore dz' + Gz' + 1 - 4^' - 1 2s = a square = (3;:' + 1 - 6c)» say, 9 whence 32s^ ■= 36s*, and ~ ^ o • Therefore sides of cubes are 17 1 , , ^ 4913 1 -, g, and the cubes .^,,-- 4913 Now put product of numbers + their sum = -,- product - sum = ^y^ therefore their sum 2456 ~ 512 ' their product 2457 ~ 512 ■ Then let the first number = 1228 X + half sum = x + — - - , second 1228 = 512 -"• -ru r 1507984 Therefore -j^-^^-^-^ -x* '•*" ""- 512- Therefore 2621 4 4x •- 250000. 200 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. „ 500 Hence x = ^—- , 512 , /1728 728\ . ""'"^ V^12 ' 512 j '' ^ '"^"*'°''- 30. To find two numbers such that their product ± their sum = a cube [same problem as the foregoing]. Every square divided into two parts, one of tohich is its side, makes the 2)roduct of these ])arts + their sum a cube. [i.e. x(x^ - x) + x' — x + x= a cube.] Let the square be x^ ; the parts are x, x^ — x, and fi-om the second part of the condition x^ -x^ -X- = x^ - 2x^ = a cube = [7,] say. Therefore 5 *^ = 2a;'', x = -^ , o < , /16 144\ . and ( -^ , -jq 1 IS a solution. 31. 7'o find four square numbers such that their sum + the su?n of their sides - a yiven number. Given number 1 2. Now x* + a; + j = a square. Therefore the sum of four squares + the sum of their sides + 1 = 13. Thus we have to divide 13 into 4 squares, and if from eacli of their sides we subtract ^ we shall have the sides of the required squares. 10 . n G4 36 144 81 Now l3 = 44-9 = --f25+-25+05' and the sides of the required squares are 11 ^ 19 13 10' lO' 10' 10" 32. To find four squares such that their sum ininus the sum of their sides equals a given number. Given number 4, Then similarly f side of first - - j + ... = 5. -,.,..,-. 9 IG G4 36 and 5 is divided into ^-^ , ^rz , ^^ . ?,- > 2y 25 25 2;) and the sides of the squares arc ( . - 13 21 17^ 10 ' 10 ' lOy ARITHMETICS. BOOK IV. 201 33. To divide unity into two parts snch that, if given numbers be added to each, the j)roduct of the resulting expressions may be a square. Let 3, 5 be the numbers to be added, aud let the parts be , 1 -xj Therefore (a; + 3) (6 - a;) = 18 + 3x — a;' - a square = ■l.c* say. Hence 18 + 3a; = 5a;*; but 5 comes from a S([uare+1, and the roots cannot be rational unless (this square +l)18 + [7jj =a square. Put (m- +l)18 + f^j =a square, or 72/?r + 81 = a square = (8ni + 9)* say. Therefore «i = 1 8. Hence we must put (x + 3) (6 - a;) = 18 + 3a; - a;' - 3•24a;^ Therefore 325x'' - 3a; - 18 = 0. 78 6 Therefore sohition. 31. [Another solution of the foregoing.] Suppose the first a; - 3, the second i -x; therefore a; (9 - a;) = square = 4a;* say, 9 and 5a;- = 9a;, whence a;=p, but I cannot take 2 from 9 - , and X must be > 3 < 4. 9 Now the value of a; comes from - — r . Therefore, since a square + 1 a; > 3, this S(piare + 1 < 3, therefore the square < 2. It is 5 also > -. . 4 Therefore I mustfind a square between -and 2, or ^^ and — . And -TT-r- or ^ will satisfy the conditions. 64 16 Put now x(9-x)- j^, .c. 202 DIOPIIANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Therefore U4 IT 21 20^ /21 20\ . , ^. and ( .,- , . 1 IS a solution, 35. To divide a given number into three j)arts such that the pro- duct of the first and second, with the third added or subtracted, may be a square. Given number G, tlie third part x, the second any niimher less than G, say 2, Therefore the first — ^ - x. Hence 8 - 2x' ± a; = a square. \^Doid)le-equation.^ And it cannot be solved by our method since the ratio of tlie coefficients of X is not a ratio of squares. Therefore we must find a number y to replace 2, such that ?/ + 1 , r = a squai-e = 4 say. 2/-1 5 Therefore 2/ + 1 = -iy — 4, and y = q • 5 13 Put now the second part = - , therefore the first - ~ —x. o o G5 5 Therefore -^ -^x^x^^s. square. Thus „„ o . }• are both squares, or „„^ ~ i^ .^l- are both squares : difference =195 = 15. 13. 2G0-24:x) Hence (^^^ ~ Y = 65 - 24a;, and 24a; = 64, a; = | . /5 5 8\ Therefore the parts arc ( ^ , ^ , ^ j . 36. To find two numbers such that the first with a ce^-tain fraction of the second is to the remainder of the second, and the second with the same fraction of the first is to the remainder of the first, each in given ratios. Let the first with the fraction of the second = 3 times the remainder of the second, and the second with the same fraction of tlie first = 5 times the remainder of the first. Let the second = x + 1, and let the part of it received by the first be 1. Therefore the first - 3.c - 1 [for 3.f - 1 + 1 - 3.c]. ARITHMETICS. 1U)0K IV. 203 Also fii-st + second - ix, uiul first + second = sum of tlie numbers after interchange, therefore J^I$±^^S^l_ ^ q remainder of tiret 2 Therefore the remainder of the first = ^x, and hence the second receives from the first 3.0 - 1 - ^ x- = r a; - 1 . o o Hence l^^^^, = r, tlierefore r,x^ + tx~\ = 3.c - 1 , 6x-\ x+\ 3 3 and x = ^ . 8 12 Therefore the first number = -;; , and the second = -''- : and 1 is < t rr- of the second. Multiply by 7 and the numbers are 8, 12; and the fraction is ^ ; but 8 is not divisible by 12, so multijily by 3, and (24, 36) is a solution. 37. To find two numbers indefinitely such their product + their sum = a given number. Given number 8. Assume the first to be x, the second 3, Therefore 3a; + a; + 3 = given number = 8. Therefore x-'j, and the numbers are ( . , 3 j . 5 8 — 3 Now - arises from -. — !r . Therefore we may put mx + n for 4 3+1 "^ ^ 1 1 1 1 1 z' 8 ~ ("*•*-' + '" ) the second number, and tiie nrst = r- . mx + n+l 38. To find three numbers such that (the product + the sum) of any two equals a given number. Condition. Each number must be 1 less than some squai-o. Let product + sum of first and second = 8, of second and tbinl - 15, of third and first = 24. Thi-n , — , = the first: let the second = x- 1. second + 1 Therefore ^-"•^- first --1. Similarly third — -1. X X •'-■ 204 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Therefore (^^ - 1 V^ - l) + ^ - 2 = 24, and ^.^ - 1 = 24, 12 therefore aj = -. , o , /33 7 68\ . , ^. and I _ , ^ , 1 IS a solution, 39. To find two numbei-s indefinitely such that their product exceeds their sum by a given number. Let the first number be x, the second 3. Therefore product - sum = 3.V - a; - 3 = 2a; - 3 = 8 (say). Therefore x = -- . Thus the first = — , tlie second = 3. But — = — :r . x + d Hence, putting the second = a; + 1 , the first = — — . 40. To find three numbers such that the product of any two exceeds their sum by a given number. Condition. Each of the given numbers must be 1 less than some square. Let them be 8, 15, 24. Therefore first number = :; — =- = , say. Therefore second - 1 a; 9 IG the first = - + 1 , the second = a; + 1 , and the third = — + 1 . X X Therefore ('^ + 1 V^ + l) - ^ - 2 = 24. Orl4i-ll24, Ij', X- 5 md ( q-s ,,.,,_) is a solution. /57 17 9Z\ . (l2' 5'12;^^^ 41. To find two numbers indefinitely whose product has to their sum a given ratio. Let the ratio be 3 : li the first number x, the second 5. 15 Therefore 5x = 3 (5 + x), and x = — . r,ut -^ = r~~:^ , and, putting x for 5, the indefinite solution is: first = -^_ , second =x. X — o ARITUMETICS. BOOK IV. 205 42. To find three numbers such that for any two their product bears to theii- sum a given ratio. _ first and second multiplied . , , , Let 5 — 7 , — = 6, and let the other ratios be nrst + st^cond 4 and 5, the second number .r. Therefore first = — , third X — 3 4a; ~ x-i' 3x ix . 3x 4a; \ , ^ , Also -. j = 5 { —5+ r) or 12x- x-Z a;-4 \a;-3 a;- 4/ 35.0-' - 1 20.r. \a; — o x — -±/ 120 Therefore x = -^, , , /360 120 480\ . . , . ""n^' 23' 28;"''^'''"^^'^""- 43. To find three numbers such that the product of any two h«s to the sum of the three a given ratio. Let the ratios be 3, 4, 5. First seek three numbers such that the product of any two has to an arbitrary number (say 5) the given ratio. Of these, let the product of the first and the second =15. 15 Therefore if x = the second, the first = ■ — . X But the second multiplied by the third = 20. 20 20 15 Therefore the third - — , and "^—^^ — = 25. x or Therefore 25.v'=20.15. And, if 20 . 15 were a square, what is required would be done. Now 15 = 3.5 and 20 = 4 . 5, and 15 is made up of the ratio 3 ; 1 and the arhilrary number 5. 12»r Therefore we must find a number m such that — = ratio of a square to a square. Thus 1 2/?r . 5»i = GOm' - square = 900/»', say. Tliereforo m = 15. Let then the sum of the three =15, and the product of the first and sccon<l = 15, therefore tli«» first = — . X GO , , 45. GO _. , (. Simihirlv tlio third = — ; therefore , ^ < •> and x ^ G. X X 206 DIOPUANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. 45 Therefore the first number =- , the third = 10, 47 and the sum of the three = 23| =— . Now, if this loere 15, the j)rohlevi loould he solved. Put therefore 15a;° for the sum of the tlirce, and for the numbers l^x, Qx, \0x. 47 Therefore 2^x = 15a;-, and x=---, /705 282 470\ whence fgQ-,3Q,3QJ is a sohition. 44. To find three numbers such that the product of their sum and the first is a triangular number, that of their sn7n and the secoml a square, and that of their su7h and the third a cube. Let the sum be x', and the first —, , the second -, , the third — ^ , X X .r which will satisfy the three conditions. 1 8 But the sum =—3 = .r* or 18 = x\ X Therefore loe must rejilace IS by a fourth iiower. But 18 = sum of a triangular number, a square and a cube; let the fourth power be x^, which must be made up in the same way, and let the square be x* -1o? + 1. Therefore the triangular number + the cube = 2a;*— 1; let the cube be 8, therefore the triangular number = 2a;^ - 9. But 8 limes a triangular number + 1 = a square. Therefore IG.x'^ - 71 = a square = (4a;- 1)^ say; therefore x = 9, and the triangular number = 153, the square =6400 and the cube = 8. Assume tlien as the first number -^-, as the second — „ , x' ' a' as the third -3 . Therefore — „- = a;* and x = 9. a; ,,,, /153 6400 8\ . , ^. ARITHMETICS. BOOK IV. 207 45. To find three numbers such that the dijj'crence of the greatest and the middle has to tlie difference of the middle and the least a given ratio, and also the sinn of any pair is a square. Ratio 3. Since middle number + lea.st = a square, let them = l. Therefore middle > 2 ; let it be x + 2, so that least = 2 - x. Therefore the interval of the greatest and the middle = 6a-, whence the greatest = Tx + 2. Therefore ' > are both squares [Donble equation] : take two numbers Avhose product = 2x, say - and 4, and pro- ceed by the rule. Therefore x= 112, biit I cannot take \\2 from 2; therefore x must be found to be < 2, so that 6.f+4<lG. Thus there are to be three squai-es 8a; + 4, Gx + 4, 4 ; ami difference of greatest and middle = ^ of difference between middle and least. Therefore we must find three squares having this proi)erty, such that the least = 4 and the middle one < 1 6. Let side of middle one be s + 2, wlience the gi'eatest is equal to 2^ + 42 „ , , 4 2 16, _3- + .^ + 4. + 4^-- + -3-c--.4. Therefore this is a square, or 3^* + 1 2s; + 9 = a square; but the middle of the required squares < 1 6, therefore z <'2. Put now 3i' + 1 2s + 9 = {mz - 3)» = mV - (jmz + 9. Therefore z ^ „ — " , which must be < 2. m — o Hence 6m + 12 < 2m- - 6, or 2m» > 6m + 18, and 18 . 2 + 3- = 4.5 ; therefore we may put in-'- + ^. Thus we have 3;:- + 12^ + 9 = (3 - bz)'. Hence s = yi , -'^'i^l the side of the middle square ■--■ ... aii«l the square itselr - . Turning to the original problem, wo i>ut y^j'^ ^•'-" + ^• Therefore x = , ' , which is < 2. <26 208 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Hence the greatest of the required numbers = 7x + 2 - - 11007 726 ' 2817 and the second of them = as + 2 = - , lab 87 and the thii'd = 2-x = ^^z . 46. To find three numbers such that the difference of the squares of the f/reatcst and the middle numbers has to the difference of the middle and the least a given ratio, and the sums of all 2}airs are severally squares. Ratio 3. Let greatest + middle = the square 1 (Sx^. Therefore greatest is > 8a;^, say 8a;" + 2, Hence middle = Bx* - 2, and greatest + middle > greatest + least, therefore great- est + least < 1 6a;* > Sx^ = 9a;-, say; therefore the least number = a;® - 2. Now difference of squares of greatest and middle = 64a;*, and difference of middle and least = 7a;", but 64 ^ 21. Now 64 comes from 32 . 2, so that I must find a number m 21 such that 32m = 21. Therefore ««. = ^ . Assume now that the gi'eatest of the numbers sought 21 ,21 „ 21 = 8a;* + -^ , the middle = 8a; - — , the least = a; - — . [Therefore difference of squares of greatest and middle = 21a;* = 3. 7a;*.] The only condition left is 21 21 8a;* - p + a;* - -gT, ^ a square 9.1; — = a square = {S.r - 6)" say. r,., r 597 Therefore x = yr:^ . 5/6 /3069000 2633544 138681\ . , ^. "^'"^^ (331776' 331776 ' 331776;^^''^ ^°^^^^^'^"- AIUTILMETICS. BOOK V. BOOK V. 1. To find three numbers in c. p. such that each exceeds a given number by a square. Given number 12. Find a square which exceeds 12 by a square [by ii. 11], say 42^. Let the first number be 42^, the third x^, so that the middle one = 6i.r. a;2_ 12") Therefore „. ,_> are both squai-es : their diflference therefore as usual we find the value of x, viz. — - , A^, 2346 i 130321\ . ^^ (^21,^^, -10816 j-^ solution. 2. To find three numbers in g. p. such that each together icith the same given number equals a square. Given number 20. Take a square whicli exceeds 20 by a square, say 36, so that IG + 20 - 3G = a square. Put then one of the extremes 16, the other x*, so that the middle term = \x. ^ + 20 "i Therefore , ^^> are both squares : their difference \x + 20j = y? -ix^x{x- 4), whence we have 4a; + 20 = 4, which gives an irrational result, but the 4^1(16), and we should have in i)lace of 4 some number > 20. Therefore to replace 16 we must find some square > 4 . 20, and such that with the addition of 20 it becomes a square. Now 81>80; therefore, putting for the nijuired square {m + 9)-, (»4 + 9)' + 20 = square -{m-U)' .siiy. Therefore m = .i, and the square = (9A)'' OOj. H.D. " " 1* 210 DIOPIIANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Assuming now for the numbers 90^, O^x, a?, we have, ^^ > are both squares : and the difference =a;(a;-9i), 9^a;+20j whence we derive x = -r— - , 152 ' /nm 389.1 1681 \ . ^^ V ^^' T52 ' 23I04J ^^ ^ '°^^^^^"^- 3. Givoi one numhei; to find three others such that any one of them or the product of any two, when added to the given number, pro- duces a square. Given number 5. Porism. If of two numbers each and their pi'oduct together with the same number make squares, the two numbers arise from two consecutive squares. Assume then {x + 3)-, {x + 4)-, and put for the first number a;^+6cc + 4, and for the second a;° + 8x+ll, and let the third equal twice their sum minus 1, or ix^ + 28a; + 29. Therefore 4a;' + 28a; + 34 = a square = (2x - 6)^ say. Hence a; = ^r^; , 26 /2861 7645 20336\ . , ,. and I -;r=-;r , -sv^/T . Wr,,^ IS a solution. V676 ' 676 ' 676 / 4. Given one number, to find three others such that each, and the product of any two exceed the given number by some square. Given number 6. Take two consecutive squares x", a;* + 2a; + 1, add 6 to each, and let the first number = a;* + 6, the second number = a;^ + 2a; + 7, the third being equal to twice the sum of first and second mhiics 1, or 4a;^ + 4a; + 25. Therefore third minus 6 =4a;' + 4a; + 19 = square =(2a; -6)* say. 17 Therefore a; = — : , /4993 6729 22660\ . *^^ (-784' T84' -78r)-^-'^<^l"*^°^^- [Observe in this problem the assumption of the Porism numbered (1) above (pp. 122, 123).] 5. To find three sqiiares such thai the procbict of any tivo, added to the sum of those two, or to the remaining one, gives a square. Porism. If any two consecutive squares be taken, and a third number which exceeds twice their sum by 2, tliese three ARITHMETICS. BOOK V. 211 numbers have the property of the numbers recpiired by the problem. Assume as the first a;^ + '2a; + 1 , and as the second x" + 4x + 4. Therefore the third = Ax^ + 1 2x- + 1 2. Hence x- + 3.v + 3 = a square -{x- 'df say, and a; = ^ . m c /25 64 196\ . iherefore ( ^ > 'K ■> ~q~ ) ^^ '^ solution. C. To find three numbers such that each exceeds 2 by a square, and the product of any two minus both, or minus the remaining one = a square. Add 2 to numbers found as in 5th problem. Let the first be x^ + 2, the second x^ +'2x+ 3, the third ■^if + -ix + 6, and all the conditions are satisfied, except 4x^ + 4a; + 6 - 2 = a square = 4 (a; - 2)* say. 3 Therefore x = -^ , o /59 114 246\ . ^^^ (,25' 25' 25 J '' ^' '°^"^^""- 7. To find two numbers such that the sum of their product and the squares of both is a square. [^Lemma to the following j)roblem.^ First number x, second any number {m), say 1. 3 Hence a;' + a; + 1 = a square = {x — 2)- say, and -c = r . Therefore K , 1] is a sokitiou, or (3, 5). 8. To find three right-angled triangles ' whose areas are equal. First find two numbers such that their product + sum of their squares = a square, i.e. 3, 5, as in the preceding problem [15 + 3' + 5^'= 7']. Now form three right-angled triangles from (7, 3), (7, 5), (7, 3 + 5), respectively, i,e. the triangles (7« + 3S 7*- 3', 2.7.3), Ac. ^ I.e. rational right-angled triangles. Ax <tll the triangles ichich Diophantos treats of are of this kind, I shall sometime.'^ use mimphj the tcord "triannU" to represent "rational right-angled triangle," for the purposes of brevity, where the latter expression is of very frequent occurrence. 14-2 212 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. and we have the triangles (40, 42, 58), (24, 70, 74), (15, 112, 113) and the area of each = 840. [7^ - 3=) 7 . 3 - (7' - 5^) 7 . 5 = (8= - 7') 8 . 7]. ['For if ah + 0?-^ 1)^=0% (c- - a') ca = {c' - 6=) cb = {{a + bf - c'] (a + b) c, since each = abc (a + 6)]. 9. To find three numbers such that the square of any one =t the sum of the three = a square. Since, in a right-angled triangle, (hypotenuse)^ ± twice product of sides = a square, we make the three numbers hypotenuses, and the sum of the three four times the area. Therefore I must find three triangles having the same area, i.e. as in the preceding problem, (40, 42, 58), (24, 70, 74), (15, 112, 113). Therefore, putting for the numbers 5 803, 74a;, 113£C, their sum = 245a; = four times the area of any one of the triangles = 33G0a;^anda; = Qg. Therefore [-^ , W WJ ^' ^ '°^^^^^°"- 10. Given three squares, it is possible to find three numbers such that the products of the three pairs are respectively equal to those squares. 4 9 Squares 4, 9, IG. One number x, the second - , the third - , a; X and -^=16, and a; = li. x^ ' ^ 1 Ncsselmann suggests that Diophantos discovered this as follows. Let the triangles formed from (n m), (q in), (r m) have their areas equal, therefore n (m^ - 11^) = q {vi^ - q'') = ?• (r" — //(-), therefore m-n - Jt-' — m-q - q^, m^=- — i =,r- + nq + q^. n-q Again, given [q m ?i). to find r; q [m"- - q'^) = r(r- - m"), and in- -q'' — n- + nq from above, therefore q (n- + nq) = r (;•- - n^ - nq - q"), or q {n'^ + nr) + q'^(n + r) = r{r^-}i-). Dividing by r + n, qn + q- = r^ - rn, therefore {q + r)n = r-- q-, and r = q + n. ARITHMETICS. BOOK V. 213 Therefore the niuiibers are (l.l, „, 6). We observe that 'C = -, where G = product of 2, 3, and 4 = side of 1 G. Hence rule. Take the product of the sides, 2, 3, divide by tlio side of the third square, and divide 4, 9 again by the result. 11. To find three numbers such that tlie product of any two the sum of the three = a square. As in 9th problem, find three riglit-anglcd triangles having equal areas : the squares of the hypotenuses are 3364, 5476, 127G9. Now find as in 10th problem three num- bers, the products of paii-s of which equal these squares, which we take because each ± (4. area) or 3360 = a square; the three numbers then are 4292 3277 4181 "113 '^' 37 ""' ^ ^' It only remains that the sum = 3360a;". m f 32824806 ._. , Therefore -^t^t-^-t?^ x- 3360x". 121249 ^, , 32824806 Therefore 407396640' whence the numbers are known. 12. To divide unity into two parts such tJvat if the same given number he added to eitlier part the result will be a square. Condition. The added number must not be odd [the text of this condition is discussed on p. 129 and note.] Given number 6. Therefore 13 must be divided into two two squares so that each > 6. Thus if I divide 13 into squares whose difference < 1, this condition is satistied. 13 Take -^ = 6|, and I wish to add to 6i a small fraction which will make it a square, or, multiplying by 4, I wish to make ;, + 2G a square, or 26x* + 1 = a square = {5x+\ )' Siiy, whence x = 10. 214 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Therefore to make 2G into a square I must add y^, or to make 6^ into a square I must add 400^ 1 13 /51\' ^^^ 4o-o-'-2=Uo;- Tlierefore I must divide 1 3 into two squares such tluit their sides 51 Tnay be as nearly as possible equal to ^ . [TrapicronjTos dywyrj, above described, pp. 117 — 120.] Now 13 = 2^ + 3^ Therefore I seek two numbers such that 51 9 3 minus the first = ^ , or the first = — , and 2 plus 51 11 the second = ^ , so that the second = — . I write accordingly (11a +2)°, (3 - 9a;)° for the required squares substituting x for -— . Therefore the sum = 202a;- - lO-i; + 13 = 13. 5 ,^, ., 257 258 Hence x = y^ , and the sides are y^. ' Tni » and, subtracting 6 from the squares of each, we find as the pai-ts of unity / 4843 ^358- V10201 ' 10201, 13. To divide unity into two jyarts such that, if we add given numbers to each, the results are both squares. Let the numbers be 2, G, and let them be represented in the figure. Suppose DA = 2, AB = l, BE=G, G a point in A£ so chosen that DG, GE may both be squares. Now Tlierefore I have to divide 9 into tioo squares such that one of them lies between 2 and 3. Let the hitter square be x^. Therefore the second square = 9 - a;', wliere x-" > 2 < 3. Take two squares, one > 2, tlie other < 3, [the former square ARITHMETICS. BOOK V. 21') being the smaller], say ^ ■ , -^^ . Therefore, if we can make x" lie between these, what wtis required is done We must have ^^^,<\l Hence, in making 9 - x^ a square, we must find 17 19 67)1 ^?Tl 17 19 >12"I2- Thus 72w>17m'' + 17, and 36*- 17. 17 = 1007 which' is '^ Sl°, hence m is :}► — . Similarly ?« is -j; tt; • Let m = 3i Therefore 9 -x' = h - '-x\ , and x = =Ti • 53 TT » 7056 ,^, ^ „, /1438 1371\ Hence ar ^ ^^^^ , and the segments of 1 are (^^gog ' 2809J " 14. To divide unity into three pm-ts such that, if we add the same number to the three parts severally/, the results are all squares. Comlition. Given number must not be 2 [Condition remarked upon above, pp. 130, 131.] Given number 3. Thus 10 is to be divided into three squares such that each > 3. Take ^ of 10, or 3^, and find x so that ^^7,+ 3J may be a square, or 30x° + 1 = a square = {6x +\f say. Therefore a; = 2, 1 121 and 36 '*' ^^ " "36" " ^ s^^''^^"^- Therefore we have to divide 10 into three squares each near to — . , [7rapio-OT7;T09 aywyr;']. 00 1 I.e. the integral part of the root is ^31. The limits taken arc .1 fortiori limits as explained on p. 93, n. 3 and 4. Strictly speaking, wc could only say, taking integral limits, that x/Iu07<32, but this limit is not narrow enough to secure a correct result in the work which follows. 21 G DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. 9 16 Now 10 = 3^ + 1' = the sum of the three squares 9, ^, ^ . 3 4 11 Comparing the sides 3, -, p with -^, or (multiplying by 30) 90, 18, 24 with 55, we must make each side approach 55. Put therefore for the sides 3-35CC, 31a; + g, S7x+-^ [35 = 90-55, 31 = 55-24, 37 = 55-18], we have the sum of the squares = 35550;^- 116rK+ 10 = 10. Therefore x = ^rv^- , 3555 and this solves the problem. 15. To divide unity into three parts such that, if three given numbers be added, each to one of the parts, tlie results are all squares. Given numbers 2, 3, 4. Then I have to divide 10 into three squares such that the first > 2, the second > 3, the third > 4. Let us add - unity to each, and find three squares whose sum is 10, the first lying between 2, 2^, the second between 3, 3i, and the third between 4, 4|. Divide 10 into two squares, one of which lies between 2 and 2^. Then this square minus 1 will give one of the parts of unity. Next divide the other square into two, one lying between 3, 3J ; this gives the second part, and therefore the third. 16. To divide a given number into three parts such that the sums of all pairs are squares. Number 10. Then since the greatest + the middle jmrt = a square, &c., the sum of any pair is a square < 10, but twice the sum of the three = 20, There/ore 20 is to he divided into three squares each of lohich < 10. Now 20=16 + 4. Therefore we must divide 16 into two squares, one of which lies between 6 and 10; we then have three squares each of which is < 10, and whose sum = 20, and by subtracting each of these squares from 10 we get the parts required; [16 must be divided into the two squares by v. 13.] ARITHMETICS. ROOK V. 217 17. To divide a given number into four parts such that the sum of any three is a square. Number 10. Then three times the sum = the sum of four squai'es. Hence 30 must be divided into four squares, eacli of wliich < 10. If we use the method of Tra^icro'-nj? and make each near 7|, and then subtract each square found from 10, wc have the required i)arts. But, observing that 30-1G + 9 + 4+1, I take i, 9 and divide 17 into two squares each of which < 10 > 7. Then sub- tract each of the four squares from 10 and we have the required parts. 18. To find three numbers S2ich that, if we add any one of them to the cube of their sum, the result is a cube. Let the sum be x, the numbers 7x^, 26a;', G3x^. Hence, for the last condition, 9Ga;^ = x. But 9G is not a square. There- fore it must be replaced. Now it arises from 7 + 2G + G3. Therefore I have to find three numbers, each 1 less than a cube, whose sum is a square. Let the sides of the cubes be wi+ 1, 2-m, 2, whence the numbers are m^ + 3'w' + 3m, 7- 12ni+ Gnr-m'', 7, aud the sum = ^m" - dm + 14 = a square = (3?« - 4)-. 2 Therefore 7n = -r-. , 15 1538 18577 ^ and the numbers are qq^t- > qqtF ' '• Therefore, putting the sum - x, and the numbers of the problem 3375^' 3375 '"'''*'' 15 we find X = ^ : therefore, «fec. 54 1 9. To find tloree numbers such t/uif, if we subtract any one of them from t/ie cube of the sum, the result is a cube. Let the sum be x, the numbex"8 - x', " x', . x'. rr. r 4877 a / Therefore ^r^;-- x" ^ x ; |( n .io \ 4877 but irz^TT-, ^ 3 - the sum of three cubes. 1728 218 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Therefore we must find three cubes, each < 1, such that (3 -their sum) = a square =2,^ say. Tlierefore we liavetofind three 3 162 cuhes whose sum is -=^, or we have to divide 162 into three cubes. But 162 = 125 + 64 - 27. Now (Porism) the difference of two cuhes can be transformed into the sum, of two cuhes. Having then found the three cubes we start again, 2 and x = 1\x^, so that x = -^, which, with the three cubes, determines the result. 20. To find three numbers such that, if we subtract the cube of tlieir sum from any one of them, the result is a cube. Sum =x, and let the numbers be 2x', 9a;^, 28a;^. Therefore 39 x^ = 1, and we must replace 39, which = sum of three cubes + 3. Therefore we must find three cubes whose sum + 3 = a square. Let their sides be m, 3 -m, and any number, say 1. Therefore 9m^ + 31 - 277/2- = square = (3m - 7)" say, so that 6 , , .. ^.1 , 6 9 m- - , and the sides of the cubes are ■= , - , 1. Starting again, let the sum be x, and the numbers 341 3 854 3 250 3 Wb^' 125*' 125*' 25 5 so that 1445a;' =^ 125, ^''=289' ^ " 17 ^ thus the numbers are known. 21. To find three numbers, whose sum is a square, such that the cube of their sum added to any one of them gives a square. Let the sum be x^, the numbers 303', Bx", IS.'c". Therefore 26a;* = 1 ; and, if 26 were a fourth power, this would give the result. To replace it by a fourth power, wc must find three squares whose sum diminished by 3 = a fourth power, or thi-ee numbers such that each increased by 1 - a square, and the sum of the three - a fourth power. Let these he ARITHMETICS. ROOK V. 219 m* - 2ni^, m^ + 2m, m^ - 2m [sura ^ m*] ; then if we put m anything, say 3, the numbers are 63, 15, 3. Thus, putting for the sum x^, and for the numbers 3j;', 15x', GSx", a; = 5 , and the problem is solved. 22. To find three numbei-s whose sum equals a square, and such that tlie cube of the sum exceeds any one of them by a square. [Incomplete in the text.] 23. To divide a given fraction into three parts, such that each exceeds the cube of the sum by a square. Given fraction - . Therefore each = — + a square. Therefore 3 the sum of the three = sum of three squares + — . 13 Therefore we have simply to divide — into three squares. 24. To find three squares such that tJieir contimced product added to any one of them gives a square. Let the "solid content" = x", and we want three squares such that each increased by 1 gives a square. They can be got from right-angled triangles by dividing the square of one of the sides about the right angle by the square of the other. Let the squares then be 9 , _25 , ^ 16 '^' 144*' 225 '*^- 14400 Therefore the solid content = x". This = x'. Olo'iUU 120 Therefore " oq ** ~ ^ ' 120 . but _g, IS not a square. Thus we must find three right-angled triangle.s such that, if 6's are their bases, ;/s arc tlieir p<'q)endicular8, p H/9^6,6, 6^ == square, or assuming one tnangle arbitrarily 3»,6, (3, 4, 5), we have to make l2pj)J>J'j ^ square, or 220 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. a square. " This is easy" (Diophantos ') and the triangles (3, 4, 5), (8, 15, 17), (9, 40, 41), satisfy the condition, and 03 = -^ ; 25 256 .1 .1 /25 256 9\ the squares then are ( -7- , -5, , Vr / • 25. To find three squares such that their continued product exceeds any one of them hy a square. Let the " solid content " = a;*, and let the numbers be got fx'om right-angled triangles, being namely 16 ^ 2 _64 , 25^^' 169 '^' 289^' m r 4.5.8 , , Therefore — r^ a; = 1, and the first side ought to be a square. As before, find three triangles, assuming one (3, 4, 5) such that hjiji^2^^pj>^= Q. square^, [letters denoting hypotenuses and bases], or such that 20 v^-^ — a square. [For the rest the text is in a very unsatisfactory state.] 1 Diophantos does not give the work here, but merely the results. Moreover there is a mistake in the text of (5, 12, 13) for (H, 15, 17), and the problem is not finished. Schulz works out this part of the problem thus : Find two right-angled triangles whoso areas are in the ratio vi : 1. Let the Bides of the first be formed from {2m + 1, m - 1), and of the second from (m -f- 2, 7K-1), BO that two sides of the first are Am" -2m -2, ^m- + (im and the area =6m'» + 9Hi3-9,/i2-6m. Two sides of the second are 2m'^ + 2m-i, G?;! + 3, and m times the area = Cm'* + 9m' - 9m- - Om. Now jmt e.g. jft = 3, therefore the first k-ianglc is formed from 7, 2, viz. (28, 4,5, ,'53) ; second from 5, '2, viz. (20, 21, 29). 2 Cossali remarks: "Construct the triangles (/, h,p) [i = ipotenusa], [-b ' —b ' ir=^^j' /ib^' + iip^ bAbp-p(b^-ip^) p Abp + b {b^ - ip-) ,,\ ^""^ [^b—' b ' b ^^)' ARITHMETICS. HOOK V. 221 26. To find three squares such that each exceeds tlicir continued product by a square. Let the "solid content " = a;', and the squares have to be found by means of the same triangles as before. We put 25x*, 625a;-, 1 4784a;- for them, ic. [Text again corrupt.] 27. To find three squares such that the product of any two increased by 1 is a square. Product of fii-st and second + 1 = a square, and the third is a square. Therefore solid content + each = a square ; and the pnjblem reduces to the 24th above. 28. To find three squares such that the product of any two diminished by 1 is a square. [Same as 25th problem.] or the solid content of the three hypotenuses has to that of the three perpen- diculars the ratio of a square to a square. It is in his note on this imperfect problem that Fermat makes the error which I referred to above. He says on the problem of finding tico triiuujks such that the products of hij2)otcnuse and one t<ide of each have a given ratio "This question troubled me for a long time, and any one on trying it will find it very difficult : but I have at last discovered a general method of sohing it. "Let e.g. ratio be 2. Form triangles from (ab) and (a d). The rectangles under the hypotenuses and the perpendiculars are respectively 2ba^ + 2lPa, 2da^ + d^a, therefore since the ratio is 2, ba^ + b^a = 2(da' + d^a), therefore by 2(P _ Ij3 transposition 2<P -P = ba^ - 2da^ ; therefore, if - — — y- be made a square, tho problem will be solved. Therefore I have to find two cubes <P, IP such that 2(P-h^ divided or multiplied by b-2d-a. square. Let x + 1, 1 be the sides, therefore 2d3-63 = 2x3 + Cx= + Cx + l, 2b-d^l-x^ therefore (l-a;)(l + 6a; + 6x' + 2x3) = l + 5x-4x3-2r«-square=^|x + l-^V) , and everything is clear." [Now Fermat makes the mistake of taking 2b - d instead o{ h- 2d, and thus he fails to solve tho problem. Brassinnc (author of a Pr<Jci3 of DiophantoH and Fermat) thinks to mend the matter by milking (1 +Gx + 6x» + 2r>)(l +2x) a square, whereas, the quantity to be made a square is (1 + 6x + Ox' + 2x^1 { - 1 - 2x). The solution is thus incurably wTong.] Fermat seems afterwards to have discovered that his solution did not help to solve this particular problem of Diophantos, but docs not seem to have seen that the solution is inconsistent with his own problem itself. 222 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. 29. To find three squares such that unity diminished by the product of any two = a square, [Same as (26).] 30. Given a number, find three squares such that the sum of any two together with the given number jyroduces a square. Given number 15. Let one of the required squares =9. Therefore I must find two other squares, such that each + 24 = a square, and their sum + 15 = a square. Take two pairs of numbers whose product = 24, and let them be the sides of a right-angled triangle' which contain 4 the right angle, say - , Gx ; let the side of one square be 2 half the difierence, or - - 3a;. X 3 Again, take other factoi'S - , 8x, and half the difierence 3 = 4:X = side of the other square, say. 2x / 3 \^ /2 \" Therefore (^ — 4ccj +( — 3a; j +15 = a square, or -f + 25a;^ - 9 = a square = 25a;^ say. g Therefore x = ^ , and the problem is solved. 31. Given a number, to find three squares such that the sum of any pair exceeds the given number by a square. Given number 13. Let one of the squares be 25. Therefore we must seek two more such that each + 12 = a square, and (sum of both) - 13 ^ a square. Divide 12 into products (3a;, -) and (4a;, -J, and let the squares /3 2\" / 3 \" Therefore (^ a; - - j + ( 2a; - .^ j - 13 = a square, or ^ + 61 a;" - 25 = a square = -| say. a;" * '^ XT Therefore x = 2, and the problem is solved. 1 I. c. corrcspoudiug factors in the two pairs, in this case G.r, Sj. be AllITHMETICS. BOOK V. 223 32. To find three squares such that the sum of thdr squares is a mare. Let one be x", the second 4, the third 9. Therefore a;* + 97 = a square = (x' - 10)* say. 3 Therefore ^'' = 2o> ^"* *^--^ ^^ ^^ot a square and must be replaced. Hence I have to find p*, q* and m such that "^~ ^ ^^ = a 2m square. Let ;r = s-, q' = \, and //t = ;:' + 4. Therefore m''-;/-5' = («* + 4)*-s--16 = 8c'. Hence we must , 8«' 4;:^ ^ave, ggT^g = ^ square, or - — - = a square. Put s' + 4 = (;s+l)«say. Therefore s = ^ , and the squares are i^" = t , q^ = 4, and 25 m= -Y, or, taking 4 times each, ^r = 9, (7' = IG, 7?i =: 25. Starting again, put the first square = :<r, the second ^ 9, the third = 16, whence the sum of the squares =- x* + 337 = {x' - 25)^ 12 Therefore '144 /144 \ and f -^ ,9, 16 j is a sol ution. 33. [Fpigra7n-problem]. 'OKTaSpd^ov; Koi. TrevraSpa^ovs ^oeas tis ffii^f. Toi? TrpoTToXolcn ttuIv XPV^"^' a^rora^a/xcvos. Kat Tifxrjv airihoiKcv vwlp iravruiv jiTpaymvov, Tas iTTLTaxOeLcra^ Be^d/Jievov /iovaSas, Kat TToiovvTa ttuXiv erepoV (re (f)ipiiv TtTpdywvov KT7]adfj.evov nkivpdv crvvdeixa twv ;(0£'a)v. 'flare StacrreiXov toOs OKTaSpd^fiov^ ttoVoi ^crav, Kai TrdXc tovs Irepovs irai kiye irevTiSpaxfiovi. Let the given number {iinTaxOela-ai. fiovaScs) be 60. The meaning is : A man buys a certain number of ;^dc? of wine, some at 8 draclnnas, the rest at 5 eacli. He pays for them a square number of drachmas. And if we add 60 to this number the result is a stjuare whose side = the 224 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. whole number of xo'es. Required how many ho bought at each price. Let X = the whole number of xo'es. Therefore a" - 60 = the price paid, wliich is a square, (x - m)" say. Now - of the price of the five-drachma xoes + o of the price of the eight- drachma xo'es = X. We cannot have a rational solution unless ic > Q (x" - GO) < g {x^ - 60). Therefore a;' > 5a; + 60 < 8x + 60. Hence x" = 5a; + a number > 60, or x is' -^ 11. Also a;- -f: 8a; + 60. Therefore a; is :|» 12, so that x must lie between 11 and 12. But a;'-60=(a;-«^)^ therefore a;= —^ — , which > 11, < 12, whence vf + 60 > 22m < 24??t. From these we find, m is not > 21, and not < 19. Hence we put x' - 60 = {x - 20)', and a; = 11^. Thus a;^-132i, a;^- 60 = 721, and 72^ has to be divided into two numbers such that - of the first + Q of the second = 11 A. Let the first = z. o Therefore |.^(72i-.) = lH, or and 5. 79 "' ~ 1 o 79 Therefore the number of xocs at five-drachmas = j^ - 59 eight „ -j2- [At the end of Book v. Bachet adds 45 Greek arithmetical epi- grams collected by Salmasius, which however have nothing to do with Diophantos.J 1 See pp. 'JO, *J1 for uu uxijlaualiuu of thusu liiuils. 225 BOOK VI. 1. To find a rational right-anfjkd triamjle such that the hypote- nuse exceeds each side by a cube. Suppose a triangle formed from tlie two numbei-s x, 3. Therefore hypotenuse =.x--+ 9, perpendicular = G.r, base=x'-9. Therefore by the question x^ + 9 - (x* - 9) should l)e a culx?, or 18 should be a cube, which it is not. Now 18 = 2. 3*, therefore we must replace the number 3 by m, where 2»r = a cube ; i. e. m = 2, Thus, forming the triangle from .r, 2, viz. (x" + 4, \x, x^ - 4), we must have a;" - 4a; + 4 a cube. Therefore {x - 2)- = a cube, or x-2 - a cube - 8 say. Hence x =10, and the triangle is (40, 96, 104). 2. To find a right-angled triangle such that the sum of the hypotenuse and either side is a cube. Form a triangle as before from two numbers, and one of them must be a number twice whose square - a cube, i.e. 2. Therefore, forming a triangle from x, 2, or (x' + 4, 4x, 4 - x*) we must have a;* + 4x + 4 a cube, and x^ < 4. ■ " 27 Hence a; + 2 = a cube, which must be < 4 > 2 -^ — say. o Therefore ^ "^ "s" ' . , . /135 352 377\ and the triangle is (^_ , -^ - , — j . 3. To find a right-angled triangle such that the sum of the area and a given number is a square. Let 5 be the given number, (3a;, 4a;, o.^) the triangle. Therefore 6 1* + 5 = square = 9x' say. 5 Hence 3x-^ = 5, and ^ is not a square ratio. Hence I must find a triangle and a iuiml)er such that the difference of the square of the number and the area of the triangle has to 5 a square ratio, L e. - ^ of a square. .. .. 13 226 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Form a triangle from x, - : then the area = a;* — 5, and let the ° ' «' a;' 1 2.5 ^. _ . 101 1 - number =x-i , so that i . 5 -\ — j- = - of a square, or, 4 . 2o + — 15- = a square = (10 + - j 24 Whence cc = -^ . o 24 5 The triangle must therefore bo formed from -^ j ni > and the number is -7:7; . oU Put now for the original triangle (Jix, 2>x, bx), where (hj^b) is 24 5 pbx' 170569 , and we have the solution. 4. To find a right-angled triangle such that its area exceeds a given number by a square. Number 6, triangle {3x, ix, 5x). Therefore Gx^ - 6 = square = 4aj* say. Hence, as before, we must find a triangle and a number such that the area of the triangle - (number)^ = -^ of a square. Form the triangle from ?», — . ° 7)1 1 fi 1 Therefore its area = ju' :,, and let the number he m--^. — . 1)1, z m Hence G (G s \ m. or, 36;>i" - GO = a square = (6»i - 2)*. Therefore vi = .. , and the triangle must be formed from (-^, -A, the number being ^ . 5. To find a riglit-anglcd tri;nigle such that a given number exceeds the area by a S(juare. Number 10, triangle (3x', ix, 5x). Therefore lO-Gx-'-a square, ARITHMETICS. BOOK VI. 227 and a triangle and a number must be found sudi tli:it (nund.fr)* + area of triangle = -- of a square. Form a triangle frum m, - , and let the number be - + 5m. Dt m Therefore 260«i' + 100 = a square, or 65»i* + 25 ^- a square = (8ni + 5)^ say. Therefore m - 80. The rest is obvious. 6. To find a right-angled triangle such that th'' sum of the area and one side* about the right angle is a given number. Given number 7. Triangle {3x, 4x, 5x), therefore 6x"+3£c=7. ■^j +6.7 not being a square, is not possible. Hence we must siibstitute for (3, 4, 5) a right-angled triangle , , /onesideX* ^ . , sucli that ( — ^ j + I times the area = a square. Let one side be x, the other 1. 7 1 Therefore ^x + j = a. square, or lix + 1 = a square) Also, since the triangle is rational, x'+l = a squarei ' Now the difference — x^ — lix = x(x~ 14). Therefore, putting 24 7^ = 14a; + 1, we have x- -=-. Therefore the triangle is /24 25\ (-^ , 1, -;^ ), or we may make it (24, 7, 25). Going back, we take as the triangle (24.c, 7x, 25x). Therefore 84a;" + lx-l, and x^ - . 4 . / 7 25 Hence the triangle is ( 6, t , . 7. To find a right-angled triangle sucii that its area exceeds ouo of its sides by a given number. 1 N.B. For brevity and distinctness I slmll in future call llic flidcs about the ri«ht angle simply "sides," and not apply the term to the hyiwUjnuMC. which will always be called "hypotenuse." 1 .;— 2 228 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Given number 7. Therefore, as before, we have to find a right-angled triangle such that ( ~ ) + ^ times area = a square, i.e. the triangle (7, 24, 25). Let the triangle of the problem be (7a;, 24a;, 25a;). Therefore 84a;^ - 7a; = 7, and x= ^. 8. To find a right-angled triangle such that the sum of its area and both sides = a given number. Number 6. Again I have to find a right-angled triangle such /sum of sidesX' that ( ~ J -f times area = a square. Let «i, 1 1 .1 -1 ..1 p fm+l\- „ m" 7m 1 1 be the sides; therefore ( -— j +3m = ^ +-^ + - = a square, and m" -f- 1 = a square. Therefore vi' + 1 im + 1) , , , , V are both squares, m- + 1 J ^ ' and the difierence = 2«i . 7. 45 Therefore "'' ^ 28 ' (45 53\ Assume now for the triangle of the problem (45a;, 28a;, 53a;). Therefore G30a;' + 73a; = 6, and X is rational, 9. To find a right-angled triangle such that its area exceeds the sum of both sides by a given number. Number 6. As before we find subsidiary triangle (28, 45, 53). Therefore, taking for the required triangle (28a;, 45a;, 53a;), we find 6S0x- - 73a; = 6, and x= ^ . 65 10. To find a right-angled triangle such that the sian of its area, hypotenuse, and one side is a given number. Given number 4. Assuming hx, px, bx, ,-, - + hx ^-bx=i, and in order that this equation may have a rational solu- tion I must find a triangle such that /hypotenuse -f one sideV -f- 4 times area = a square. I AlUl'lI MIOTICS. BOOK VI. 229 ^[ake a right- angled triangle from ;«, m+ 1. Therefore /hyiJOtenuse + one sicle\ * /2«t* + 2//i + 1 + '2m + 1\* V 2 ; =v 2 ) = Hi* + im' + Gin' + 4//t + 1 and 4 times area = im {/a + 1) (2m + 1) which = Sm^ + 12/«- + im. Therefore m* + I2iu^ + ISm- + Sm + 1 ^ a square = (7/4- + Gm - 1)^ say. Hence m=,, 4 and the triangle must be formed from ( , - j, or (5, 9). Thus we must assume for the triangle of the problem the similar triangle {2Sx, 45.f, ~^3.c), and G30.C* + 81a-= 4. 4 Therefore x = — — . lOo 11. To find a right-angled triangle such that its area exceeds the sum of the hypotenuse and one side by a given number. Number 4. As before, Vjy means of the triangle (28, 45, 53) we get G30a;" — 81.'; = 4. Therefore x = ^ . 6 12. To find a right-angled triangle such that the difference of its sides is a square, and also the greater alone is a square, and, thirdly, its area -1- the less side - a square. Let the triangle be formed from two numbei-s, the gi-eater side being twice their product. Hence I must find two numbers such Uiat twice their product is a square and also exceeds the difference of their squares by a square. This is true for any two numbers of which the gi-eater - twice the less. Form then the triangle from x, 2x, and two conditions are fulfilled. The third condition gives Gx* + 3x* - a wjuarc, or 6x^ -I- 3 = a square. Therefore we must seek a number such that six times its square with 3 produces a square, i.e. 1, and an infinite number of others. Hence the triangle required is formed from 1, 2. Lemma. Given two numbers whose sum is a s(iuai-o, an infinite number of squares can be found which by multiplication with one of 230 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. the given ones and the addition of the other to this product give squares. Given numbers 3, G. Let x" + 2a; + 1 be the square required, which will satisfy 3 (x^ + 2a; + 1) + 6 = a square, or 2>x- + G.r + 9 = a square. This indeterminate equation has an infinite number of solutions. 1 3. To find a right-angled triangle such that the sum of its area and either of its sides = a square. Let the triangle be (5a;, 12a;, 13x). Therefore 30.«' + 1 2a; = a square = 36a;^ say. Therefore 6a; = 12, and a; = 2. But SOx^ + 5x is not a square when x = 2. Therefoi'e I must find a square m^a;^ to replace 36a;" such that the value 12 —5 — :ryr of X IS veol and satisfies 30a;- + 5a; = a square, m - 30 rru- • 1 1 .-. .• 60m^+2520 This gives by substitution -, — z^^ ,, . . = a square. *' ^ m* - 60m + 1)00 ^ Therefore 60??r + 2520=a square. If then [by Lemma'] we had 60 m' + 2520 equal to a square, the equation could he solved. Now 60 arises from 5, 12, i.e. from the product of the sides of (5, 12, 13); 2520 is the continued product of the area, the greater side and the difference of the sides [30. 12.1235]. Hence we must find a subsidiary triangle such that the pro- duct of the sides + the continued product of greater side, difierence of sides and area - a square. Or, if we make the greater side a square, we must have [dividing by it], less side + product of difference of sides and area = a square. Therefore we must, given two numbers (area and less side), find some square such that if we multiply it by the area and add the less side, the result is a square. 2'his is done hy the Lemmas^ and the auxiliary triangle is (3, 4, 5). 1 Diophantos has expressed this rather curtly. If (h p b) bo the triangle (b>p), we have to make hp + ^bp . (b -p) b a Kquarc, or if b is a square, 2' + i ^'P U'-p) must be a square. ARITHMETICS. I50<)K VI. liSl Thus, if the original triangle is {Zx, ix', 5x), we have Gx-* + 4a;) , . 4 Let !»= — a —„ be the solution of the first equation. 9G 12 Therefore the second gives — ; — q-^; — 7. — Trr. + . " ^ = a S(iuarc. " 7Ji'-12//i' + 30 m'-G ' Hence 12 m^ + 24 = a square, and we must find a square such that twelve times it + 24 = a square [as in Lemma], Therefore m^ = 25, and a; = Tj-jT . ^. . , . , . , . /12 16 20\ Therefore the triangle required isLq, jq, -.q)- 14. To find a right-angled triangle such that its area exceeds either side by a square. The triangle found as before to l)c similar to (3, 1, 0), i.e. (3a;, ix, 5x). Therefore 6.r - 4a; = square ^ m" {< G). 4 Hence x = Q-m" 96 12 '''''^ (6 - my 6 - wr a square, or 24 + 12»t- a stjuaiv Let m = 1 say. Therefore 4 X ~ ^ , /12 16 A and the triangle i« v g . 5 ' - / • Or, putting m = z+l, we tiiid 3r + 6c+9 a square, ami 13 22 .1 z^^, 3+1^0 , SO that X- is rational. This relation can be satisfied in an infinite number of ways it b- pin a «,uaro, and also ;; + i />i). ., ,._ Therefore wo liave to find a triant^le such that Krcatcr side ^^luore. difference of sides = s(iuare, less side + area = square. Form the triangle from (u, h), therefore greater side =2.1,. which ib a Hqimro. if a -26, difference of sides =16^-36^= a square, less side + area -3&> + 0fc»= a square. 232 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. 15. To find a right-angled triangle such that its area exceeds either the liypotenuse or one side by a square. Let the triangle be (3a;, ix, 5x). Therefore 6a;* -5a;) , ^, V are both squai-es. \)X — ox\ 3 Making the latter a square, we find x = ;, Cm? < 6). Therefore from the first ,^ ^, - t, ; = a square, or (G - m)- - m 15wt* - 36 = a square. This equation we cannot solve, since 15 is not the sum of two squares. Now 15??i^=the product of a squai-e less than the ai-ea, the hy})0teuuse, and one side ; 36 = the continued product of the area, one side, and the difference between the hypote- nuse and that side. Hence we must find a right-angled triangle and a square such that tlie square is < 6, a^id the continued pi'oduct of the square, the hyj)otenuse of the triangle, and one side of it exceeds the continued product of the area, the said side and the difference hetioeen the hypotenuse and that side by a square. [Lacuna and coiTuption in text']. Foi*m the triangle from two "similar plane numbers" [numbers of the form ah, oir], say 4, 1. This will satisfy the con- ditions, and let the square be 36. (< area.) The triangle is then (8*, \bx, 17a;). Therefore GO.r- - 8a; = 360;^^ say. 1 Thus x = y^, and the triangle ^^ (3' ^' y ) 1 Schulz works out the subsidiary part of this problem thus, or rather only proves the result given by Diophantos that the triangle must be formed from two "similar plane numbers'' a, aU- [i.e. a. 1 and ah. h.] ; and hyp. h = a-h^^-a-. greater side ij = a-b* - «-, less side k = 2a-b'\ area /= ^ kg. Now h-k = a^b* - 2a-b'^ + a" = {ab"^ - ay, ft square ; and hkz'^ - Jcfih - ft) is a square i{ z-=k (h - k) k, for, if we then divide by the square h - k and twice by the square kk, we get 2 (k-(i)^ia\ which is a square. AUlTilMETlCS. I'.uolv VI. 233 16. Given two numbers, if some square be multiplictl by one of them, and the other be subtracted, the result being u square, then another square can be found greater than the tii-st square wliich han the same property. [Leitwia to the following problem.] Numbei-s 3, 11, side of square 5, so that 3. 25 -11= 64 = a square. Let the required square be (.« + 5)*. Therefore 3 (a; + 5)- - 1 1 = 3.v" + 30x + 64 = a square = (8 - 2.r)» say. Hence x = 62. The side of the square = 67, and the square it.self = 4489. 17. 2h find a riyht-amjled triamjle such that the sum vf the area ami either the hypotenuse or one side = a square. We must first seek a triangle {h, k, (j) and a square s' such that hkz- - ka {h -k) = a, squai-e, and z' > «, the area. Let the triangle be formed from 4, 1, and the square be 36, but, the triangle being (8, 15, 17), the square is not > area. Therefore we must find another square to replace 36 by the Lemma in the preceding. But hk = 136, ka {h - i) = 480 . 9 = 4320. Thus 36 . 136 - 4320 = a square, and we want to find a larger square {m') than 36 such that 136?«' - 4320 - a square. Putting m = z+ 6, (s- + 122 + 36) 136 - 4320 = square, or, 136^' + 16322 + 576 = a square = (»z - 24)* say. This equation has any number of solutions, of which one gives 676 for the value of {z + 6)' [putting n = 16]. Hence, putting for the triangle (8x, 15.i-, 17x), we get 60x* + 8a; = 676x-*, Therefore ^ ^ 77 " 18. To find a right-anfied triangle such that the Hue hiscctiw/ nti acute angle is rational. Let the bisector (A D) = 5a; and one .section of tlu- has,- ( Itli) .ij, so that the perpendicular \x. 234 DIOPIIANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Let the whole base be some multiple of 3, say 3. Then CD = 3-3x. But, since AD bisects the i BAC, the hypotenuse = - (3 - 3a;), therefoi-e the hypotenuse = 4 - 4a;. Hence IGa;' - 32a; + 16 = 16a;= + 9, and a; = ^ . Multiplying throughout by 32, the perpendicular = 28, the base = 96, the hypotenuse = 100, the bisector =: 35. 19. To find a right-angled triangle such that the sum of its area and hypotenuse = a square, and its perimeter = a cube. Let the area = x, the hypotenuse = some square minus x, say 16 -a;; the product of the sides = 2x. Therefore, if one of the sides be 2, the other is x, and the perimeter = 18, which is not a cube. Therefore we must find a square which by the addition of 2 becomes a cube. Let the side of the square be {x+ 1), and the side of the cube (a:-l). Thei-efore a;^ - 3a;^ + 3a; - 1 = a;^ + 2a; + 3, from which a; = 4. Hence the side of the square is 5, and of the cube 3. Again, assuming area = x, hypotenuse = 25 - a?, we find that the perimeter = a cube (sides of triangle being x, 2). But (hypotenuse)'' = sum of squares of sides. Therefore of - 50a; + 625 = a;- + 4, 621 and x=-^. 20. To find a right-angled triangle such that the sum of its area and hg2>otenuse = a cube, and the perimeter = a square. Area x, hypotenuse some cube mimis x, sides x, 2. Therefore we have to find a cube which by the addition of 2 becomes a square. Let the side of the cube = m-1. (3 \* ^m + lj say. <¥)'• ' Put then the area a;, the sides x and 2, the hypotenuse ^y^ -x. (4913 \* —rrr xj = a;^ + 4 gives a;. 21 Thus wi = -J-, and the cube ■■ 4913 AlUTIIMETICS. ROOK VI. 235 21. To find a right-angled triancjle mch that thf sum of its area and one side is a square and its perimeter is a cube. Make a riglit-angk'il triangle from .r, x + 1. Therefore the i)erpendicular -2x+\, the base = 2x* + 2x, the hypotenuse = 2x* + 2x* + 1 . First, Ax- + Ga; + 2 = a cube, or (4a; ■(- 2) {x + 1 ) = a cube. If wo divide all tlie sides by x + 1 we have to make 4x + 2 a cube. Secondly, area + perpendicular = a square. ^, - 2x^ + 3xVx 2x+l Ihereiore — ; r-r^ — + -^ = a square. (x + 1)* X + 1 ^ 2x' + 5x* + 4x+l „ , Hence ^39" i " ^ 2x+ 1 =a square. But 4x+ 2 = a cube. Therefore we must find a cuU- which is double of a square. 3 Tlierefore 2x + 1 = 4, x = - , and .1 . ■ 1 • /8 15 17\ the triangle IS (^g, ^ , -j 22. To find a right-angled triangle such that tlie sum of its area and one side is a cube, while its perimeter is a square. Proceeding as before, we have to make 4x + 2 a squarej 2x + 1 a cube / ' Therefore the cube = 8, the square = IG, »-• = .,, and the triani , . /16 63 65\ 23. To fiml a right-angled triangle such that its perimeter is a square, and the sum of its perimet^ and area is a cube. Form a right-angled triangle from x, 1. Therefore the sides are 2.7;, x-*- 1, and the hypotenuse x* + 1. Hence 2x* + 2x should be a square, and x' -I- 2x* -f x a cul>c. It is easy to make 2x'' + 2x a square : let it ^ 7«V. 2 Therefore x- ^"' ^ , and from the second condition m* -2 8 8 _2^ {m' - 2)' "^ {m' - 2)' "^ m' - 2 must be a cube, i.e. 7-^ — rr-3 = a culto. (w -J) 236 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Therefox'e 2m* = a cube, or 2m = a cube = 8 say. 2 1 I Thus ??i = 4, .X' = r7 = - . ^^^ *" ^ 7a • 14 7 49 But foi* one side of the triangle we have to subtract 1 from this, which is impossible. Therefore I must find another value of a; > 1 : so that m" > 2 < 4. And I must find a cube such that \ of the square of it > 2 < 4. Let it be n^, so that ?i" > 8 < 1 G, This is satisfied by , 729 3 27 -"=G4''^==T- 97 729 512 Therefore m=^^, nr = . _ _ , x = ^^^ , and the square of this 16 25G 21/ > 1. Thus the triangle is known. 24. 7'o Jiiid a right-angled triangle such that its 2)erimeter is a cube and the sum of its perimeter and area = a square. (1) We must first see how, given two numbers, a triangle may be formed whose perimeter = one of the numbers, and whose area - the other. Let 12, 7 be the numbers, 12 being the perimeter, 7 the area. Therefore the product of the sides = 14 = - . 14.u Thus the hypotenuse = 12 — ; — 1 4x'. Therefore from the right-angled triangle 1 24 1 172 + 4 + 19Ga;'' - 336x - — = -^ + 196a;^ a;- X X or, 172 - 336a;- ^- = 0. ' X This equation gives no rational solution, unless 86"- 24. 336 IS a square. But 172 :^ (perimeter)- + 4 times area, 24 . 336 = 8 times area multiplied by (perimeter)". (2) Let now the area = x, the perimeter = any number which is both a square and a cube, say 64. Therefore ( — a ] - 8 . 64" . a; must be a square, or, 4a;' - 2 4 5 7 6a; + 4 1 9 4 3 4 ^ a square. AUITMMETICS. I500K VI. li.ST Therefore x' - GlU.c + 1048570 is a square.) Also X + 04 is a square./ To solve this double equation, multiply the second equation by such a square as will make the absolute t<.'rm the same as in the first. Then, taking the difference and factors, itc, the equations are solved. [In the text we find i$i(Tw(r$o} aoi ol dpiO/JLoi, which, besides being ungrammatical, would seem to be wrong, in that dpiOfjiOL is used in an unprecedented manner for /loraoe?.] 25. To find a right-angled triangle such that the square of its hypotenuse = the sum of a square and its side, <and the quotient obtained by dividing the (hypotenuse)^ by one side of the triangle = the sum of a cube and its side. Let one of the sides be x, the other x'. Therefore (hypotenuse)" = the sum of a square and its side, and = a cube + its side, X Lastly, X* + x' must be a square. Therefore of + 1 = a square = {x - 2)' say. 3 Therefore a; = -j , and the triangle is found. 26. To find a right-angled triangle such that one side is a cube, the other = the diflerence between a cube and its side, the hypotenuse = the sum of a cube and its side. Let the hypotenuse = a;' + x, one side = x^-x. Therefore the other side = 2x* = a cube. Therefore x = 2, and the triangle is (6, 8, 10). TRACT ON TOLYGONAL NUMBERS. 1. All numbers, from 3 onwards in order, are polygonal, con- taining as many sides as units, e.g. 3, 4, 5, &c. " As a square is formed from the multiplication of a number by itself, so it was proved that any polygonal multiplied by a number in proportion to the number of its sides, with the addition to the product of a square also in pro- portion to the number of the sides, became a square. This we shall prove, first showing how a polygonal num- ber may be found from its side or the side from a given polygonal number." 2. If there are three numbers equally distant from each other, then 8 times the 2>i'odicct of the greatest and the middle + tlie square of the least = a square whose side is (greatest + twice middle number). Let the numbei-s be AB, BG, BD (in fig.) we have to prove 8 {AB){BG) + {BDy- = [AB + 2BGy. E A B..D...G Now AB = BG+GI). Therefore SAB . BG - 8 (BG' + BG . GD) = iAB . BG + iBG' + 4BG . GD. and iBG . GD +DB'^ AB' [for AB=BG + GD, DB = BG-GD\ and we have to seek how AB" + iAB. BG -\- iBG^ can be made a square. Take AE^ BG. Therefore iAB . BG = iAB . AE. This together witli ABG' or iAE' makes iBE.EA, and this together with AB' = [BE+EA)- = (AB + 2BGy. 3. If there are any numbers in A. p. the difference of the greatest and the least > the common difference in the ratio of the number of terms dimiuiahcd by 1. POLYGONAL NUMBERS. 239 Let AB, BG, BD, BE... he in a. p. B.A..G..D.. E Therefore we must have, difference of AB, BE^ (difference of AB, BG) X (number of terms- 1). AG, GD, DE arc all equal. Therefore EA = AG >i (number of the terms AG, GD, DE) ^ AG x (number of term.s in series- 1). Therefore (kc. 4. If there are any numbers in a.p. {greatest + least) x number of terms = double the sum of all. [2s = 7i{l + a).] Let the numbers be ^, 2^, C, D, E, F. (A +F) X the number of them shall be twice the sum. A.B.C.D.E.F H.L.M.K...G The number of terms is either even or odd ; and let their number be the number of units in IIG. First, let the number be even. Divide IIG into two equal parts at A'. Now the difference of i^, Z) = the difference of C, A. Therefore F+ A =C + I),h\it F + A = {F+ A) HL. Hence C + D = {F+A)LM, E+B = {F+A)MK. Therefore A + B + ... = (F+A) UK. And {F + A) IIG ^twice (A +B +...). 5. Secondly, let the number of terms be odd, A, B, C, D, E, and let there be as many units in FU as there are terms, «J:c. A.B.C.D.E F.G.K.II 6. If titer e are a series of numbers beginning loilh 1 and increas- ing in A. p., then the sicm of all x eight times the common difference + the square of {common difference - 2) = a square, whose side dimin- ished by 2^ the common difference multijilied by a number, which increased by 1 is double of the number of terms. [Let the a.p. be 1, \ + a, ... 1 + n - 1 . a. Therefore we have to prove s.8a + {a-2y = {a{2n-\) + 2y, i, e. 8as = 4a V - 4 (a - 2) na, or 2» - an' - (o - 2) « = n (2 + n- la)]. 240 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Proof. Let AB, GD, EZ be numbers in A. p. starting from 1. A.K..N...B G D E.L Z H.M X—T Let HT contain as many units as there are terms including \. Difference between EZ and 1 = (difference between -4 5 and 1) X a number 1 less than IIT [Prop. 3]. Put AK, EL, HM each equal to unity. Therefore LZ=MT.KB. Take KN = 2 and inquire whether the sum of all x eight times KB + square on NB makes a square whose side diminished by 2 = KB X sura of HT, TM. Sum of all = I product {ZE + EL) .IIT=\ {LZ + 2EL) HT, and LZ= AIT . KB from above. Therefore the sum = \ (KB . iVT . TH+ 2TH), or, bisecting MT at X, the sum = KB . TH . TX+ HT. Thus we inquire lohether KB. TH. TX. SKB + 8KB . HT + square on KB is a square. Now SHT . TX . KB' = iHT . TM . KB', and SKB . HT = AHM. KB + i (HT + TM) KB. Therefore toe must see lohether i.HT. TM. KB' + iHM. KB + 4 (HT + TM) KB + NB"- is a square. But 4/7.1/ . KB = 2KB . NK, and 2KB.NK+NB-=KB- + KN% and again /JA'^ = HM' . BK\ and HM\BK"- + UlT . TM . BK'= {HT+ TMf BK\ Hence our expression becomes {HT+ TMf Bid + 4 {HT + TM) KB + A'iV^^ A.K..N ...B R H.M A'— T or, putting {HT + TM) BK= NR, NR' + iNR + KN' and 4.NR ^ 2NR . NK. Therefore the given expression is a square whose side is RK, and RK -2 = NR, which is KB {HT + TM), and HT+ TM+ 1 = twice the number of terms. Thus th(! proposition is proved. 7. Let POLYGONAL NUMBERS. HT+TM^A, KB=B. K 1j 241 Therefore square on .1 x square on B = square ou G, where G = {HT+TM)KB. Let DE = A, EZ =^ B, in a straight line. Complete squares DT, EL, and complete TZ. Then DE : EZ^DT : TZ, and TE ■ EK=TZ : EL. Therefore TZ is a mean proportional between the two squares. Hence the product of the squares = the square of TZ, and DT^ {IIT -h TMf, ZK = square on KB. Thus the product (HT + T2If. KB' = NB^. 8. If there are any number of terms heginning from 1 in a. p. the svm is a jiolygonal number, for it has as many angles as the common difference increased by 2 contains units, ami its side = the number of terms inclibding the term 1. The numbers being represented in the figure, (sum of series multiplied by ^KB) + NB- - RK\ O.A.K..N...B RG- II . M A'- -D /•; . L- -T Therefore, taking another unit AO, KO - 2, KN -- 2, and OB, BK, BN are in arithmetical progression, so that S.OB.BK + BN' = {OB + 2BKy, [Prop. 2], and OB + 2BK- OK - ZKB an.l 3+12.2, or 3 is one less than the double of the common difference of OB, BK, BN. Now as the sum of the terms of the j)rogressiou, including unity, It; H. D. 242 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. is subject to the same laws as Oi? ', while OB is any number and OB always a polygonal (the first term being AO [1] and AB the term next after it) whose side is 2, it follows that the sum of all terms in the progression is a polygonal equiangular to OB, and having as many angles as there are units in the number which exceeds by OK, or 2, the difference KB, and the side of it is HT which = number of terms, including 1. And thus is demonstrated what is said in Hypsikles^ definition. If there are any numbers increasing from unity by equal intervals, when the interval is 1, the sum of all is a tri- angular number : wlien 2, a square: when 3, aj)entagon and so on. And the number of angles = 2 + common difference, the side = number of terms including 1. So that, since we have triangles when the diffei'ence = 1, the sides of them will be the greatest term in each case, and the product of the greatest term and the greatest term increased by 1 - twice the triangle. And, since OB is a polygonal and has as many angles as units, and when multiplied by 8 times (itself - 2) and increased after multiplication by the square of (itself — 4) [i.e. NB-] it becomes a square, the definition of polygonal numbers will be : Every polygonal multiplied 8 times into (number of angles — 2) + square of (number of angles — 4) = a squax'e. The Hypsiklean definition being proved, it remains to show how, given the sides, we may find the numbers. Now having the side HT and the number of angles we know also KB, therefore we have {IIT + TM) KB = NR. Hence KR is given [NK^1\ * This result Nesselmann exhibits thus. Take the aiithmetical progression 1, 6 + 1, 2& + l...(K-l)t + l. If s is the sum, Qsh + (l) - 2)'^=[h (2k - 1) + 2p, If now we take the three terms 6-2, h, h + 2, also in a. p., 8b(?;+2) + (?i-2)' = [(6 + 2) + 26]' = (3!> + 2)2, Now 6 + 2 is the sum of the first two terms of first series; and 3 = 2.2-1, therefore 3 corresponds to 2h - 1. Hence s and h + 2 are subject to the same law. POLYGONAL NUMBERS. 243 Therefore we know also the square of KR. Subtracting from it the square of NB, we have tlie remaining term which = number x '^KB. Similarly given the number we can find the side. 9. Rule. To Jhid the number from the side. Take the side, double it, subtract 1, and multiply the remamder by (number of angles - 2). Add 2 to the product, and from the square of the number subtract the square of (number of angles — 4). Dividing the remainder by 8 times (number of angles - 2), we find the required polygonal. To filed the side from the numher. Multiply it l>y 8 times (number of angles - 2), add to the product the square of (number of angles - 4). We thus get a square. Subtract 2 from the side of this square and divide remainder by (number of angles - 2). Add 1 to quotient and half the result is the side required. 10. [A fragment.] Given a numher, to find in how viany loays it can he a polygcmal. Let AB be the given number, BG the number of angles, and in BG take GD = 2, GU - 4. A . T B E..D..G K Z H Therefore, since the polygonal AB has BG angles, %AB . BD + BE- = a square = ZIP say. Take in AB the length AT=\. Therefore MB . BI)= iAT . BD + i (AB + TB) BD. Take DK=i{AB+TB), and for AAT.BD put 2BD . DE. Therefore ZIP = KD . BD + 1BD .DE + BE*, but 2BD . DE + BE' = BD' + DE\ Hence ZU ' ^ KD . BD + BD* + DE\ and KD . BD + BD^ - KB . BD. Thus Zir=KB.BD+DE\ and, since DK = 4 {AB + TB), DK> 4 J T > 4, and half 4 - DG, GK>GD. 244 DIOPHANTOS OF ALEXANDRIA. Therefore, if DK is bisected at L, L will fall between G and K, and the sqiiare on LB = LD' + KB . BD. A . T B E..D..G L K Z H N M Therefore ZE' = BU - LD' + DE\ or ZH' + DL' = BU- + DE\ and LD"-~DE' = LB'~ZH\ Again since ED = DG and DG is produced to L, EL.LG + GD'=DL\ Therefore DL' - DG' = DL' - DE' = EL . LG. Hence EL . LG = LB' ~ ZIP. Put ZM = BL {BL being > ZII). Therefore ZM' - ZH' = EL . LG ; but DK is bisected in L, so that DL = 2 (AB + BT) ; and DG = 2 AT. Therefore GL = iB T, and BT-^^GL, but also AT {ov l) = ^^6-'(or 4). Therefore AB = \ EL, but TB also = \ GL. 4 4 Hence AB.TB=^EL. LG, or EL.LG=1(JAB.BT. Thus UAB.BT = MZ' - ZII ' = 21 H ' + 2ZH . II M. Therefore IIM is eve^i. Let it be bisected in JV [Here the fragment ends.] INDEX [The references are to pages.] Ab-kismet, 41 u. Abu'lfaraj, 2, 3, 12, 13, 41 Abu'l-Waffi Al-Biizjfmi, 13, 25—20, 40—42, 148, 155, 157 Abu Ja'far Mohammed ibn AUiusain, 156 Addition, how expressed by Diophantos, 69 ; Bombelli's sign for, 45 ; Vieta's, 78 «. Algebraic notation, three stages of, 77 —SO aljabr, 40, 92, 149—150, 158 Alkarkhi, 24—25, 71 ?;., 156—159 Al-Kharizmi, see Mohammed ibn Mfisfi almuktibahi, 92, 149—150, 158 Al-Nadim, 39, 40 ii. Al-Shahrastani, 41 Alsirfij, 24 u., 159 avaipopiKos of Hj-psikles, 5 6x)pl(TTu%, iv doplarcf), 140 ApoUonios, 4, 8, 9, 23 Approximations, 117—120, 147 Apukius, 15 Arabian scale of powers compared with that of Diophantos, 70—71, 150— 151 Arabic translations, Ac, 23, 24, 25, 39—42, 148—159 Archimedes, 7, 142, 143, 144, 146, 147 Aristoxenos, 14, 15 Arithmetic and Geometry, 31, 141— 142 'ApiOfiriTLKo. of Diophantos, 33 and pas- sim apidfiijriKri and XoyiaTiK-f), IH, 136, 145 dpidfioi, 6 ; Diophantos' technical use of the word, 57, 150; his sj-mbol for it, 57- 66, 137—138, 160 apidfiOffTov, 74 Ars rei et census, 21 h. Auria, Joseph, 51, 56 Autolykos, 5 Bacchios 6 y^pwv, 14, 15, 16 Bachet, 49 — 53 and passim "Back-reckoning," H5 — 86, 114; ex- amples of, 110, 111, and in the ap- pendix passim Bhaskara, 153 Billy, Jacobus de, 3, 54 Blancauus, 3 Bombelli, 13, 14, 15, 23, 35, 36. 42— 45, 52, 134—135; his algebraic no- tation, 45, 68 Bossut, 32, 38, 90 n., 138—139 n. Brahmagupta, 153 Brassinne, 221 n. Camcrarius, Joachim, 2, 42 Cantor, 55 h., 58, 59. 67, 141 n., 151. 152, 156, 157 Cardan, 43, 46, 70 Casiri, 41 n. Cattle-problem, the, 7, 142—117 Censo, 70 Coefficient, 93 «. Colebrooke, 12, 19 n., 33, 133. 136. 137 n. Cosa, 45, 70 Cossali, 1, 3, 10, 12, 31, 36, 41 n., 43 n.. 49, 51, 70, 71. 107 n.. 133. 136. HO. 169 ;i.. 220 ;i. Tridhara, 153 Cubes : transformation of a Bom of two cube-s into the difference of two others, and vice rer$ii, 123—125 Cubic equation. 30, 93—91. 114 246 Data of Euclid, 140 Dedication to Dionysios, 136 Definitions of Diophantos, 28, 29, 57, 67, 7-4, 137, 138, 163 Determinate equations : see contents ; reduction of, 29, 149—150 Diagonal numbers, 142 Didymos, 14, 15, 16 Digby, 23 Dioi^hautos, see contents s , . - J 35, 98 Division, how represented by Diophan- tos, 73 Double-equations of the first and second degrees, 98 — 107 ; of higher degrees, 112—113 Svva/jLis and the sign for it, 58 n., 62, 63, 66 7i., 67, 68, 140, 151 ; dvfa/xis and Terpaywvoi, 67 — 68 dwa/xoduva/jus and the sign for it, 67 — 68 dvvainoOvvafJ.oa'Toi', 74 dvva/jMKv^os and the sign for it, 65 ii., 67—68 Swa/JLOKV^offTov, 74 dwafioarov, 74 er5os = power, 29 7i. Elements of EucUd, 4, 5, 142, 158 Epanthema of Thymaridas, 140 Epigrams, 2, 6, 7, 9, 142—147, 223 Equality, Diophantos' expression of, 75—76 ; Xylander's sign for, 76 Equations, classes of, see contents; reduction of determinate equations, 29, 149-150 Eratosthenes, 5 Euclid, Elements, 4, 5, 142, 158; Data, 140 Eudemos, 67 Eunapios, 13 Fabricius, 1, 5, 14 Fakhn, the, 24—25, 71 n., 156—159 Fermat, 13, 23, 53, 54, 68, 123, 124, 125, 126, 128, 129, 130, 131, 221 n. Fihrist, the, 39, 40, 41, 42 Fractious, representation of, 73 — 75 Gardthausen, 60, 64 Geminos, 18, 145—146 Geometry and algebra, 140 — 141, 151 —153, 156, 158 Geometry and arithmetic, 31, 141 — 142 Girard, Albert, 3 n., 55 Gow on Diophantos, 64 — 66 7i., 137 n., 160 Hankel, 83—85, 129 n. Harmonics of Diophantos, 14 ; of Pto- lemy, 15 Harriot, 78 n. Heiberg, 146—147, 160 Heilbronner, 3 Herakleides Ponticus, 16 Heron of Alexandria, 141, 153 Hipparchos, 5, 141 Hippokrates, 67 History of the Dynasties, see Abu'Ifaraj Holzmann, Wilhelm, see Xylander Hultsch, 146 n. Hypatia, 1, 8, 9, 10, 11, 17, 38, 39 n. Hypsikles, 4, 5, 6, 135, 242 Z for tffos, 75 lambHchos, 78, 79, 140 Identical formulae, 125 Indeterminate equations, 94 — 113, 144, 146, 147, 157, 158, 159 Irrationality, Diophantos' view of, 82 Isidoros, 5 Italian scale of powers, 70, 71 jabr, 40, 92, 149—150, 158 jiclr, 150 John of Damascus, 8 John of Jerusalem, 8 ka'b, 71 n., 157, 158 Kitab AljUtrist, 39 Kliigel, 11, 90 n., 144 Kostfi ibn Luk:l, 40 KvfioKvpos and the sign for it, 67—68 KvjBos and the sign for it, 58 n., 62, 63, 66h., 67— 68 Kuster, 8 INDEX. 247 Lato, 70 Lehmann, 60 Xfr^ty, and the symbol for it, 66 ;i., TI- TS, 137, 163 Xei^tj iirl \e'i\pLv ■jroWairXaffiaffOuaa TTOtet virap^LV, 13T n. \i6((>avTos or Aew^aj'Tos, 14 Lessing, 142, 143, 144, 146 h. Limits, jnethod of, 86, 8T, 115— IIT ; approximation to, IIT — 120 \(yyi.<jTLKr] and apidfiy^TiKT], 18, 136, 145 — 146 Lousada, Miss Abigail, 56 Lnca Pacioli, 43, TO n. Lucilius, 9 " Majuskelcursive " writing, 64, T2 71. mal, Tin., 157, 158 Manuscripts of Diophantos, 19, 61 Maximus Planudes, 23, 38, 39, 51, 135 Meibomius, 14 Metrodoros, 10 7n(n!«, Diophantos' sign for, 66 /;., 71 — 73 ; Bombelli's, 45 ; Tartaglia'6,78 h.; Mohammed ibn Miisfi's expression for, 151 Minus vniltipUed bij minus gives plus, 137, 163 " Minuskclcursive " writing, 64 Mohammed ibn Miisa Al-Kliarizmi, 3, 40 n., 59, 92, 134, 148, 149—155, 156, 158 fxovaSis, 69 ; the symbol for, 69 Montucla, 3, 11, 53, 71, 136 imtfasxirln, 40 u. mukdbala, 92, 149—150, 158 vifda, 150 Multiplication, modern signs for, 78 ;i. lutqis, 151 n. Nessehnann, 5, 10, 20, 21, 22, 23, 27, 81, 33, 34, 35, 36, 37, 44 n., 49, 51 h., 54, 55, 58, 59, TT, T8, T9, 85, 8s, 91 h., 92, lOS, 110, 114, 121, 125, 129 «., 133, 142, 143 n., 144, 145, 140, 147, 169 n., 212 7!., 242 71. Nikomachos, 6, 14, 15, 10, 38, 05 «., 135, 151 Notation, algebraic: three stages, 77 — 80 ; drawbacks of Diophantos' nota- tion, 80—82 Numbers which are the sum of two squares, 127—130 Numbers wliich are the sum of three squares, 130—131 Numbers as the sum of four squares, 131—132 dpyavQaai, 136 — 137 wpiafiivoi apidfjLol, 140 Oughtred, 78 77. Pappos, 11, 12, 17, 65 71., 139 Trapio-OTTji or irapiffOTrrros ayoyy-ri, 117 — 120 Pcletarius, James, 2, 43 Pell, John, 56 Perron, Cardinal, 20 Phaidros, 14, 15 TrXaffficLTiKOv, 169 n. Plato, 18, 141—142, 145 TrXij^os, coefficient, 93 71. 2)lus, Diophantos' expression of, 71, 137 71. ; Bombelli's s^-mbol for, 45 ; Vieta's, 78 n. Pococke, 2, 12, 41 ;i. Polygonal Numbers, {31 — 35 and pas- sim Porisms, 18, 32—35, 37, 121—125, 210, 218 Poselger, 55, 120, 124 71. Powers, additive and multiplicative evolution of, 70—71, 150—161 Proclus, 142 Progression, arithmetical, summation of, 239—240 irporacris and xp6fi\rjfi.a, 34 Ptolemy, Claudius, 9 Pythagoras, 141 Quadratic equation, solution of, 90— 93, 140—141, 151—155; tbo two roots of, 92, 153—155 Radix, 68 Uumu-s, Peter, 10. \\, 15 248 INDEX. Reduction of determinate equations, 29, 149—150 Eegiomontanus, Joannes, 2, 20, 21, 22, 23, 42, 46, 78 Eeimer, 32 Eelati, 71 Res, 68 Eiccati, Vincenzo, 27 n. Eight-angled triangle: formation of, in rational numbers, 115, 141, 142 ; use of, 115, 127, 128, 155, 156 ; ex- amples, APPENDIX, especially Book VI. pi^rj of Nikomachos, 151 Eodet, L., 29 n., 59, 60, 61, 62, 75—76, 91 n., 92, 134, 151, 155 Rosen, editor of Mohammed ibn Musa, q. V. Sursolides, 71 Suter, Dr Heinrich, 28 n., 50, 53 h. Symbols, algebraic : see plus, minus, &c. tafsir on Diophantos, 40 Tannery, Paul, 6, 7, 9 n., 10, 13, 14, 15, 16, 133, 139, 142—146 tanto, Bombelli's use of, 45 Ta'rlkh Hokoma, 41 Tartaglia, 43, 78 n. Theon of Alexandria, 8 n., 10, 11, 12, 13,38 Theon of Smyrna, 6, 135, 142 Thrasyllos, 15 Thymaridas, 140 Translations of Diophantos, see Chap- ter III. Salmasius, Claudius, 19 n., 224 Saunderson, Nicholas, 52 n., 133 Scholia on Diophantos, 38, 39, 135 Schulz, 55 and iwssiMi Series, arithmetical; summation of, 239—240 shai, 150 " Side-numbers," 142 Simultaneous equations, how treated by Diophantos, 80, 89, 113, 140 Sirmondus, Jacobus, 19 n., 20 Square root, how expressed by Dio- phantos, 93 n. Stevin, 3, 55 Struve, Dr J. and Dr K L., 142 n. Subsidiary problems, 81, 86 ; examples of, 97, 110, 111 Subtraction, Diophantos' symbol for, 66 71., 71—73; TartagUa's, 78 n.; Bombelli's, 45 Suidas, 1, 8, 9, 10, 11, 12, 13, 45 Supersolida, 71 Unknown quantity and its powers in Diophantos, 57—69, 139—140; in other writers, 45, 68, 70, 71 n., 150, 151, 157, 158 ; Dioi^hantos' devices for remedying the want of more than one sign for, 80—82, 89, 179 ilnap^is, 29 n., 71, 137 n. Usener, Hermann, 12 n. Variable, devices for remedying the want of more than one symbol for a, 80—82, 89, 179 Vieta, 52, 68, 78 n., 123—124 Vossius, 3, 21 71., 56 Wallis, 70 »„ 71, 138 Wopcke, 24, 25, 26, 155 Xylander, 45 — 51 and passim Zcmus, 68 Zetetica of Victa, 52 CAMBRIlJdK : ritlNTEI) 1)Y ,AY, M.A. AND SON, AT THK VNIVERSITY PRESS. rrrrr' -psnoK I? RETURN CIRCULATION DEPARTMENT jO^B^ 202 Main Library LOAN PERIOD 1 HOME USE ' V BE RECALLED AFTER 7 DAYS -Qr.cs MAY BE MADE 4 DAYS PRIOR TO DUE DATE. "'"-■' 3-MONTHS. AND 1-YEAR. "^FLOW %. ■A 27]ur»':;\ ^-^ fACKS 73 -'J Au LD2lA-50m-4'00 (A956'2sl0)47CB UniTemcy pt Berkeley OOifalr^ .ELEY GENERAL LIBRARY U.C. BERKPIF^ ' 5:* THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA UBRARY Uff^Jj