BF leas TRICHOTOMY IN ROMAN LAW BY HENRY GOTJDY IRLF 551 in LTD sD CO u OXFORD AT THE CLARENDON PRESS 1910 TRICHOTOMY IN ROMAN LAW BY HENRY GOUDY D.C.L. REGIUS PROFESSOR OF CIVIL LAW IN THE UNIVERSITY OF OXFORD OXFORD AT THE CLARENDON PRESS 1910 HENRY FROWDE, M.A. PUBLISHER TO THE UNIVERSITY OF OXFORD LONDON, EDINBURGH, NEW YORK TORONTO AND MELBOURNE TO HIS COLLEAGUES OF "THE SOCIETY OF PUBLIC TEACHERS OF LAW IN ENGLAND AND WALES" THIS LITTLE BOOK IS DEDICATED BY THE AUTHOR IN GRATEFUL RECOGNITION OF THE HONOUR CONFERRED ON HIM BY HIS ELECTION AS FIRST PRESIDENT OF THE SOCIETY 1908-10 M105768 PREFACE SOME years ago I contributed an article to a Festschrift in honour of Professor Carlo Fadda of Naples, in which I examined the classifications of obligations in Justinian's Institutes, and I endeavoured to show that the peculiar divisions into groups of four that we there meet with may be traced to a desire for artificial symmetry on the part of the Editors, and were neither based on any considerations of logic nor the result of mere coincidence. This article was published in the Studi Fadda in 1906 under the title ' Artifi- ciality in Eoman Juristic Classifications ', and its conclusions, though not generally accepted, have been received with favour by some eminent Romanists who have been good enough to write to me about it. In that article I stated that I was of opinion that many of the Roman lawyers were influenced by the symbolism of numbers, as regards both the external arrangement of their works and the classifications of the subject-matter contained in them, though I did not attribute the 4 PEEFACE particular fourfold classifications in the Institutes to symbolism but rather to a desire for artificial symmetry. I also said (Studi Fadda V, p. 212) that I should at a future date, if possible, com- ment on the symbolic influence of the number 3. The present monograph is the fulfilment of that undertaking. For the views expressed in the following pages I am solely responsible, but I desire to express here my thanks to my friends Professor Cook Wilson, Mr. Warde Fowler, Fellow of Lincoln College, and Emeritus Professor Strong, of Liver- pool University, for some valuable suggestions to which I have given effect. To Professor Cook Wilson in particular, who read over the whole of the proof prints of the work and made a number of acute criticisms, I am much indebted. ALL SOULS COLLEGE, OXFORD, 1910. TRICHOTOMY IN ROMAN LAW IN modern times, at any rate among European nations, one does not attach any particular signifi- cance to numbers as such, outside the realm of mathematics. One does not at all regard them as influencing actions or events either in public or private life. Least of all have modern writers, if we except perhaps Hegel, been consciously influenced by them in the composition of their writings. 1 What literary or scientific author nowadays, in dividing his treatise into parts, books, &c., or dividing his subject-matter into heads and categories or genera and species, would attach any special importance to what the number of these might be ? But in former times it was different: to the ancients certain numbers had a mystical value or fixed traditional force, and ancient writers frequently made the distributions of their subject-matter, as well as the external 1 But see Hofmann, Zeitschr. fur Rechtsgeschichte, xi, p. 344, n. 20 . Hegel's triads however are not properly classi- fications of genera into co-ordinate species, but rather a con- sequence of his method of philosophy. 6 TEICHOTOMY arfarigenient ,of their works, depend upon their ajgctiEdahoa -with one or other of these numbers. The influence of this symbolism, or whatever it be called, can be demonstrated to have existed, in greater or less degree, among all ancient nations with whose culture we are acquainted, especially the Hindus, Hebrews, Egyptians, Greeks, and Komans. 1 The numbers 3, 4, 7, and 12 seem to have been above all sacred, but 9 and 10 were also universally symbolic. By the vulgar they were generally regarded as lucky numbers, while philosophers sought a rational basis for them. It is in the last degree im- probable, for instance, that the Commandments given to Moses would ever have been published as, say, eight or eleven, or the decemviral code of the Eomans in, say, thirteen tables. 2 How far this mysticism of numbers continued to affect mediaeval writers or left its impress on mediaeval institutions it is not my purpose to inquire. That it still continued to exercise a certain, 1 See Usener, 'Dreiheit,' Rhein. Mus. f. Philol (N. P.), Iviii, pp. 32 sq. The Celtic races also showed great partiality for them. See K. Meyer, as in p. 7, n. 1 infra and p. 9, n. 3 . 2 Ausonius describes the law of the XII Tables as lus triplex, tabulae quod ter sanxere quaternae, Sacrum, privatum, et populi commune quod us- quam est. Edyll. xi, line 61. IN KOMAN LAW 7 though gradually decaying, influence is un- doubted. On this point it will suffice to quote a passage from our own Lord Coke, a dry but not wholly unimaginative writer. Speaking of the English jury, he says, ' It seemeth to me that the Law in this case delighteth herself in the number of twelve. For there must be not only 12 jurors for the trial of matters of fact, but 12 judges of ancient time for trial of matters of law in the Exchequer Chamber. . . . And that number of twelve is much respected in Holy Writ as 12 Apostles, 12 stones, 12 Tribes, etc.' 1 The Pythagorean school of philosophy was apparently the earliest to propound a system of symbolic numbers. Possibly they may have borrowed it from India, for, at all times in the philosophy and religion of the Hindus, such symbolism has been prominent. The Pytha- gorean views on the subject influenced Plato, as we see from the Timaeus, 2 and had an un- 1 Institutes, Part I, lib. 2, cap. xii 234. The Ancient Laws of Ireland, among others, afford unmistakable evi- dence of symbolic numbers, a whole book being composed in heptads. See vol. v, pp. 117 sq. of Ancient Laws of Ireland, Dublin, 1901, and K. Meyer, The Triads of Ireland, in Todd Lecture Series of Koyal Irish Academy (1906), p. xii. 8 See trans, by Jowett, pp. 463, 468, 474, &c. ; Proclus, 8 TKICHOTOMY doubted influence on Greek mythology. Perhaps strongest of all was the influence exercised upon the Neo-Platonists. The conquests of Alexander brought the Greeks into direct touch with the religion and philosophy of the East and affected powerfully, it is thought, the speculations of the later Greek Schools. It is not my purpose, and this is not the place, to enter upon a discussion of theories regarding the origin and meaning of the symbolic numbers above mentioned. My concern is with the number 3. That a special mystical value was attached by ancient writers to this number is of course familiar to scholars. 1 To quote what I said in the Festschrift for Carlo Fadda, referred to above in my Preface : l To many of the leading nations of antiquity it represented divine power. As evi- Commentary on Tim. iii. 181 ; cf. Plato, Legg. x. 888 E. Aristotle seems on the whole free from the same charge. But see De Caelo, i. 1 init. 268 a, where he discusses the completeness of the number 3 with reference to the line, plane, and solid in magnitude, and Ehet. i. 2, 3. 1 For an explanation of the origin of the mystic value of the number 3 see Diels, Archiv f. G-esch. d. Philos., x, pp. 232-3 ; Usener, op. cit., pp. 348-62. They trace it back to the earliest periods in the history of races, when 3 was the highest number that could be reckoned and signified many. Tylor, Primitive Culture, i, p. 220. Tribus, meaning a community, may perhaps be taken as an example of this. IN KOMAN LAW 9 dence of this it is enough to refer to the three Gods of Hindu mythology Vishnu, Siva, and Brahma, 1 and the Trinity of Christian doctrine. By some ancient philosophers, again, it was regarded as the most symbolic of numbers, because it repre- sented the beginning, middle, and end of all things, and also the dimensions of space.' 2 To this may be added that among the Welsh and Irish the influence of the number 3 was unbounded. The name triad was given in these countries to a species of literary composition in which the subject-matter was arranged in groups of three. K. Meyer observes, * I am not aware that this kind of composition has ever attained the same popularity elsewhere as in Wales and Ireland, where the manufacture of triads seems at times almost to have become a sport.' 3 He also gives one or two curious illustrations of modern triads, said to have been in current use among the 1 And the three goddesses Doorga, Lakshmi, and Saras- vati. Egyptian triads (e. g. Amon, Mut, and Khonsu) were also very common. See Maspero, Etudes de Mythologie jZgyptiennes, vol. ii, pp. 386 sq. 2 Studi Fadda, v, p. 210. See Usener, ' Dreiheit,' Rhein. Mus. f. Philologie (N. F.), Iviii. 1, pp. 31 sq. ; Lobeck, Aglao- phanus, pp. 384-9. For the further conception of trinity in unity see Usener, 1. c. ; cf. Martial, J^p. v. 24 l Hermes omnia solus, et ter unus.' 5 Todd Lecture Series, p. xv, cited supra. 1211 B 10 TKICHOTOMY common people within living memory. The two following are amusing and may be quoted : ' Three disagreeable things at home : a scolding wife, a squalling child, and a smoky chimney.' 1 1 The three finest sights in the world : a field of ripe wheat, a ship in full sail, and the wife of a MacDonnell with child/ But at any rate it is certain that anlong the Eomans from the earliest times the number 3 was by far the most significant. 3 As an odd 1 With this compare the old German couplet ' Drei ding im haus sind ungelegen : der rauch, ein bos weib und der regen.' 2 Ibid. p. ix. f ln England and Germany, also, as stated by me in the Studi Fadda, relics of the old superstition about the number 3 still linger. Thus in England one says * the third time is the lucky one ', and in Germany there are proverbs l aller guten Ding sollen drei sein ' and * dreimal ist Bubenrecht '. For other instances of the symbolism of the number in Germany see Grimm, Diet. v. ' Drei '. 3 The symbolism of the numbers 4 and 7 may just be noticed. The Pythagoreans regarded the 4 (the rerpaKTv?) as the perfect number, the root of all nature and ground of all things. See Themist. Phys., lib. iii, and other references in Koby, Introd. to Digest, p. xxix. Its importance in Holy Writ is also well known and needs no illustration. Not less symbolic was the number 7 (probably due to its being, as Philo says, a combination of 3 + 4, or, as some hold, 3 + 1+3, and not, as more commonly supposed, based on astrological reasons, just as the symbolism of the 9 and 12 may be due to their being 3x3 and 3x4 respectively). Thus in Holy Writ the whole book of Revelation is domi- IN KOMAN LAW 11 number it enjoyed of course the good omen which the Eomans attached to such numbers 1 numero deus impare gaudet V But the evidence of its influence meets us on every hand. The Roman mythology presents it to us unmistak- ably. 2 Thus we have the Capitoline triad of nated by the number 7 7 churches, spirits, golden candle- sticks, &c. while elsewhere we are given 7 days of the week and endless other examples. (See e.g. Ezekiel xlv. 23-5.) Among the Greeks the 7 was sacred to Apollo and Dionysus. Among the Komans we have also clear evidence of its influence, as in the 7 kings, hills, seals of testaments, &c. ; see Aulus Gellius, N. A. iii. 10, 17 ; Apuleius, Meta- morph. xi (238). Justinian himself, in his introduction to the Digest (Tanta, 1), tells us that he made the division of that work into 7 parts 'non perperam neque sine ratione sed in numerorum naturam et artem respicientes '. Consult especially Smith, Diet, of Bible, voce seven ; Hofmann, Z. fur Eechtsgeschichte, pp. 343 sq. ; Hadley, Essays Philological and Critical, pp. 325 sq. See also on the symbolism of the numbers 7 and 9 in Greek mythology, Eoscher, ' Sieben und Neunzahl' in Abhand. d. Konig. Sachs. G. d. W. (1904). 1 See Virg. Eclog. viii. 73-77. Numa's supposed enactment regarding the Calendar is given by Macrobius thus l Numa in honorem imparis, numeri adjecit diem '. See also Cen- sorinus, d. d. Nat. xx. 4. Cf. Plato, Laws, iv. 717. 2 Similarly among the Greeks. According to Usener's reckoning, the Theogony of Hesiod contains fifteen triads of Gods and lesser divinities ; see Bhein. Mus. f. Philologic (N. F.), Iviii. 1, p. 4. Tpn-oyeWa was a name for Athene and Tpwr/xeyto-Tos for Hermes. For the influence of the number 3 in the cult of mysteries, see Hildebrand's Prole- gomena to his edition of Apuleius, Metamorph., p. xxxvii. 12 TRICHOTOMY Jupiter, Juno, and Minerva, the three Furiae, the three Parcae, the three Gratiae, and others l most of them originally borrowed from the Greeks, but some of them native. But every department of Roman life, secular as well as sacred, private as well as public, was profoundly affected by it. In the singular poem of Ausonius, ' GripJius ternarii numeri/ 2 he has given, following in the steps of earlier writers from Pythagoras downwards, an immense number of instances of all kinds from which the nature and force of the number 3 among the Romans can be readily appreciated. In short, the number 3 seems to have repre- sented to the Romans periodicity, and hence by a natural transition completeness : it was to #iem the perfect number Tres numerus super omnia.* The traditional origin of the Romans 1 The Capitoline triad, as such, seems to have been Graeco-Etruscan. Another notable triad was Ceres, Liber, Libera ; corresponding to Demeter, Dionysus, Persephone. On the three Graces, see Seneca, de Beneficiis, i. 3. 3. He discusses why the number should be three as held by the Stoics (instead of two, as some held), and explains that they corresponded to the tria beneficiorum genera, viz. 'pro- nierentium, reddentium, simul accipientium reddentium- que.' Cf. note by Bouillet in Lemaire's ed. 2 Ausonius, Edyllia xi. 3 Ausonius, Edyll. xi, 1. 88 ; cf. ibid., 1. 52. IN KOMAN LAW 13 from 3 races (Kamnes, Titles, and Luceres) and the consequent political division of the early people into tres tribus is a noticeable instance. 1 Evidence of the early symbolism of the num- ber is also clearly shown in the XII Tables. One of the most remarkable provisions of the decemviral code is expressed thus : ' Si pater filium ter venumduuit, films a patre liber esto.' 2 This means that if a paterfamilias sells his son three times his potestas over the son shall end. So fundamental was the power of a father over his son conceived to be involving the notion of imperium as well as dominium that the sale of the son to another person only suspended and did not destroy it. If such son were after- wards manumitted by the purchaser he fell back into patria potestas. Were he sold a second time and again manumitted, the result was the same. But if sold a third time the potestas was regarded as extinguished and, if now manumitted, the son became sui juris? Another rule of the XII 1 It also appears in the tripudium of the Carmen Arvale. On this see Warde Fowler in Classical Review, xvi, p. 211. 2 Tab. iv. 2 (Schoell). 3 Whether this rule was first laid down by the Decemvirs or was due to earlier custom it is impossible to say. Gaius (iv 79) speaks of it as if introduced by the Decemvirs for purposes of emancipation and adoption, but these applica- 14 TKICHOTOMY Tables was the so-called usurpatio trinoctialis. 1 1 Lege XII Tab. cautum erat,' says Gaius, * si qua nollet eo modo [usu] in manum mariti convenire, ut quotannis trinoctio abesset atqfue ita usum cuiusque anni interrumperet.' 2 That is to say, a wife who remained away from her husband's abode for three consecutive nights in each year prevented manus being acquired over her by prescription. 3 Another law of the XII Tables, illustrative of my point, was that relating to a judgement debtor arrested by manus injectio of his creditor. He had to be kept for 60 days in prison by the creditor, and produced during that period on three successive nundinae (ternis nundinis) before the praetor in the market-place. At the close of the third nundinde, failing settle- ment of the debt or intervention of a vindex, he was addicted to the creditor who might do what tions of it seem rather due to interpretatio, and it is more probable that it was originally intended to relieve sons from the hardship of being repeatedly sold for a price, or pledged by their patresfamilias. For another view see Girard, Manuel d. d. r., p. 183. 1 Tab. vi. 4 (Schoell). 2 Gai. i 111 ; cf. Gellius, Hi. 2. 13. 8 As the law speaks of trinoctium (and not triduum) it may be presumed that the wife might spend the day at the domestic hearth and attend to her duties, provided that she absented herself during the night. IN KOMAN LAW 15 he Jiked with him. 1 Another illustrative law of the Tables was in these words : l Cui testimonium defuerit, is tertiis diebus ob portum obvagulatum ito.' 2 Of this law various explanations have been given, of which one is that it refers to a plaintiff, in an action calling aloud upon his debtor outside the latter's house, to perform his obligation. If this were done for three consecu- tive days the recalcitrant or impecunious debtor (against whom ordinary in jus vocatio could not be made) could then be arrested by manus in- jectio even within the house itself. 3 Besides the instances just mentioned there are others in the XII Tables in which the number 3 figures. 4 In 1 Tab. iii. 5. Also 'tertiis nundinis partis secanto* in iii. 6 ; cf. Gellius, xx. 1. 49. 2 Tab. ii. 3 ; Festus, s. v. vagulatio (ed. Mueller), p. 375. 3 See Voigt, XII Tafeln, i, p. 535. If this be right, the Dharna of Hindu law offers an interesting analogy. Puchta, however (Inst. 160 a), and others think the obvagulatum relates to a recalcitrant witness who, after the third day, might be seized by manus injectio. 4 e. g. the dies comperendinus, the three kinds of delict, and the three forms of personal injury. It has been held by some writers that, prior to Justinian, three adjudications in separate liberates causae were required to fix the status of slavery on an alleged freeman. Such a rule may have been in the XII Tables, but the evidence on the subject is obscure and does not warrant the conclusion that there were then actually three actions ; see Cod. vii. 17. 1 pr. ; Buckland, Law of Slavery, p. 668. 16 TEICHOTOMY later times and among the classical jurists the notion of completeness or perfection involved in it is signified by numerous phrases, rules, and maxims. Such are, for example, the jus trium liberorum, tria onera tutelarum dant excusationem, the tria verba (do, dico, addico), tres faciunt colle- gium, the ex tribus maribus of the Senatusconsult Afinianum (or Sabinianum ?). That Eoman writers literary, philosophic, and juristic were alike profoundly influenced by the ternarius numerus, as indeed they were by other symbolic numbers, in the external arrangement and composition of their works, cannot be doubted. It has been frequently pointed out. 1 It continued down to Justinian, and even to mediaeval times, as already indicated. Thus Justinian, in his constitution ' Tanta ', says : ' Omni igitur Eomani juris dispositione composita, et in tribus volu- minibus, id est Institutionum, et Digestorum seu Pandectarum, necnon Constitutionum perfecta, et in tribus annis consummata.' 2 That a similar 1 See Koby, Introd. to Digest, pp. xxix-xxx; Hofmann, Zeitschrift fur R. G. xi, pp. 340 sq., and xii, pp. 180 sq. Hofmann calls it ' Zahlenspielerei '. He gives reasons for thinking that Justinian's partiality for mystic numbers was influenced by the Neo-Pythagorean philosophy. 2 Tanta, 12 ; cf. 23, and Omnem reipublicae, 7. As to what he says about the number seven see supra, p. 10, n. 3 . IN EOMAN LAW 17 influence affected the treatment of their subject- matter, particularly their divisions and classifi- cations, is to my mind equally clear, and it is this that I will attempt to prove, from juristic texts, in the following pages. This influence frequently led the jurists, or at least some of them, to sacrifice logic and proportion in dealing with legal topics, and thereby to produce unsatis- factory and sometimes even misleading doctrines. As I have elsewhere said, ' Almost necessarily classifications influence the treatment of subject- matter, and, if they are bad, the result is that subjects are placed in juxtaposition that are not truly co-ordinate, worthless distinctions are pro- duced, and otherwise the legal system is inju- riously affected.' 1 This influence of the ternarius numerus is best illustrated from the Institutional treatises of the jurists, as it is in them we naturally look for classifications and categories, but it appears in all their writings. Most of the jurists are, more or less, chargeable with it, but with Ulpian, infected as he was, apparently, by Stoic philosophy, it is On the possible symbolism of the mediaeval division of the Digest into three parts (vetus, infortiatum, novum), see Puchta, Inst. i, pp. 644 sq. 1 Studi Fadda, v, p. 209. C 18 TKICHOTOMY specially remarkable. It is perhaps not too much to say that wherever Ulpian gives a classification of an institution or doctrine into genera or species we may expect to find it tripartite, if the subject- matter admits of it or can be forced into it. 1 Keeping in view, then, the symbolism of per- fection attached by the Eomans to the number 3, illustrations may now be given of how it influenced the jurists in their classifications. By the term t classification ' I mean a division of the matters or topics, which constitute any doctrine or insti- tution, into classes that should be mutually exclu- sive or, in other words, a division into genera and species ; it does not apply to mere varieties or forms included in a species, which are of course generally indeterminate and may be infinite. 2 These latter, being incapable of classification, are generally introduced by such words as velut (veluti), sicut (sicuti), ut, utputa, quorum in numero, or the like, though no doubt some of these words were also 1 The same charge may he to a large extent made against Paul, who, if we may judge from his writings, was a Stoic of the Stoics. But, strictly speaking, the charges, as we shall see, are rather to be made against the earlier writers from whom Paul and Ulpian drew. 2 Distinctions however, in jurisprudence, between species and varieties are often as arbitrary and difficult to be made as in the field of natural science. See, as to the latter, Life and Letters of Charles Darwin, ii. 88. IN EOMAN LAW 19 occasionally used where an exhaustive enumera- tion was intended. 1 The partiality of the Koman jurists for the tripartite classification 2 has not been unobserved by modern writers, 3 but, so far as I know, no one has sought for a reason for it or attempted to give any explanation of it. I shall now arrange in juxtaposition some lead- ing tripartite classifications, confining myself to the primary divisions of law and the topics dealt with in the first books of the Institutes of Gaius and Justinian and the cognate texts in the Rules 1 See Gai. i 120, and iii 141 ; Cohn, Beitrage, Heft 2, p. 45. On partition and division of genera see Cicero, Top. 30-4. The jurists unfortunately use the terms genera and species without precision, e. g. species of obligations and genera of contracts in Gai. iii 88. Cf. Inst. iii. 13 2. We get genera instead of species furtorum in Inst. iv. 1 3. Cf. Gai. iii 182-3. 2 Tripertitus (or tripartitus), formed from the numeral and pars (partior), is quite classical (Cicero, de Off. iii. 2. 9 ; Top. 90). As is well known, the earliest treatise on Roman law, of which there is any distinct record, was the so-called Tripertita of Sextus Aelius, a work said by Pomponius (Dig. i. 1, 2 38) to have been composed of three parts, which he describes as harmonizing with his own threefold division of the sources of the law (Ibid. 6). Besides triper- titus there are numerous other Latin words meaning three- fold, similarly formed by composition with the numeral tres, as triplex, ternarius, trifarius, triplasius, triplusj triplaris. 3 See Savigny, Systenij i, p. 395 ; Mommsen, Bom. S.-R. iii. 1, p. 8n. 20 TRICHOTOMY of Ulpian and in the Digest ; afterwards I shall comment upon each of them separately. It will be observed that the great majority of these classi- fications are given by Ulpian ; several of them are given by him alone. 1. The precepts of law are honeste vivere, alte- rum non laedere, suum cuique tribuere. 1 2. Public law consists in sacra, in sacerdotibus, in magistratibus. 2 3. Private law is composed of jus naturale, jus gentium, and jus civile. 3 4. All law was either made by consent, or esta- blished by necessity, or settled by custom. 4 5. Praetorian law was introduced by the prae- tors for the purpose either of assisting, or supply- ing deficiencies in, or correcting the rigour of the jus civile, in the public interest. 5 6. Constitutions of the emperors, as a source of private law, are decreto vel edicto vel epistula. 6 7. The subject-matter of private law relates either to persons, or to things, or to actions. 7 1 Ulpian in Libro primo Eegularum, Dig. i. 1, 10 1 ; Inst. i. 1 3. 2 Ulp. in Lib. i Institutionum, Dig. i. 1, 1 2. 3 Ulp. in Lib. i Instit., Dig. i. 1, 1 2 ; Inst. i. 1 4. 4 Modestine in Lib. i Eeg., Dig. i. 3, 40. 5 Papinian in Lib. ii Definitionum, Dig. i. 1, 7. 6 Gai. i 5 ; Ulp. in Lib. i Inst., Dig. i. 4, 1 1 ; Inst. i. 2 6. 7 Gai. i 8 ; Inst. i. 3 pr. IN EOMAN LAW 21 8. All law is concerned with either the acquisi- tion, or conservation, or restriction of rights. 1 9. Persons are grouped into (I) liberi and servi, (2) cives, latini, and peregrini, and (3) sui juris and alieni juris. 2 10. Persons are divided into lib&ri, servi, and libertini. 3 11. Freedmen are divided into cives, latini, and dediticiorum numeral 12. The conditions upon which slaves might acquire civitas are three, and the modes of manu- mission under jus civile are also three, viz. vindicta, censUj and testamento. 5 13. Persons alieni juris are either in potestate, in manu, or in mancipio. 6 14. Marriages under jus civile are contracted farreo, coemptione and usu.* 1 15. Emancipation and adoption of filiifamilias 1 Ulp. in Lib. ii Inst., Dig. i. 3, 41. 8 Gai. i 9, 12, 48. 3 Inst. i. 5 pr. ; Ulpian in Lib. i Institutionum, Dig. i. 1, 4. 4 Gai. i 12 ; Ulp. Beg. i 5 ; cf. Inst. i. 5 3. 8 Gai. i 17 ; Ulp. Beg. i 6. 6 Gai. i 49 ; Ulp. Beg. xix 18. 7 Gai. i 110. Ulpian doubtless gave this also in Eeg. ix, but the MS. is here defective. It was also contained in his Institutes as cited by Boethius in Topica, 3, 4 ; see Girard, Textes, p. 467. 22 TKICHOTOMY is effected by three mancipations and three manu- missions. 1 16. Of persons sui juris it is said: 'quaedam vel in tutela sunt vel in curatione, quaedam neutro jure tenentur/ 2 17. Tutors are divided into ' legitimi aut senatus consultis constituti aut moribus introducti '. 3 18. Status consists of libertas, civitas, familial 19. Capitis deminutio is divided into maxima, media, and minima. 5 The above nineteen divisions form the large majority of the leading classifications of the subject-matter dealt with in the first books of the Institutes of Gaius and Justinian or cognate thereto. 6 I have so put them together for the sake of a clear conspectus. 1 Gai. i 132 ; Ulp. Eeg. x 1. Neither Gaius nor Justinian give the modes of creating patriapotest as formally ; but as described by them in their Institutes there were just three modes, viz. birth in lawful marriage, adoption, and legitimation the last of these having of course a widely different import with Gaius from what it had with Justinian. 2 Gai. i 142 ; Inst. i. 13 pr. It seems clear that a tri- partite division was here intended. 3 Ulp. Eeg. xi 2 ; cf. Ulp. in Dig. xxvi. 1, 6 2. Neither Gaius nor Justinian give formally any division, but see infra, p. 47, n. 2 . * Paul in Dig. iv. 5, 11. 5 Gai. i 159 ; Ulp. Eeg. xi 10 ; Inst. i. 16 pr. ; Paul in Dig. iv. 5, 11. 6 There are no doubt a considerable number of classifica- IN KOMAN LAW 23 It would, of course, be rash to predicate that all of them are due to the mystic influence of the number 3, but I cannot resist the conclusion that the great majority of them are due to that cause. They are mostly, if not altogether, traditional. A critical examination of them, which I now pro- ceed to make, will show that with few exceptions they are neither logical nor suitable to the treat- ment of the topics that they severally represent. tions to be found in the Institutes both of Gaiusand of Justi- nian that are not tripartite. The influence of the ternarius numems in fact in these works, apart from traditional classifications, is not so marked as it is in the writings of Ulpian, and possibly neither Gaius nor Justinian's editors were consciously affected by it. Gaius's fundamental divi- sion of law into jus gentium and jus civile is noticed below (p. 27). Another primary division of law into jus publicum and jus privatum (perhaps taken originally from Aristotle, Hhet. i. 13. 2 Xcyw 8e v6p.ov TOV fJiV tSiov TOV of. KOLVOV ) is also noted below (p. 25). Another dual division into jus scriptum and jus non scriptum was, as Ulpian indicates (Dig. i. 1, fr. 6 and Inst. i. 2 3), taken from the Greeks and perhaps from Aristotle (Ehet. i. 13. 2). See Schrader, Com- mentary on the Institutes, hoc loco. Gaius further makes logical twofold divisions of men into liberi et servi and of freemen into ingenui et libertini, while Ulpian, as above noted, has a trichotomy (see infra, p. 39, n. 2 ). Of adoption it is said by Gaius, i 98, ' duobus modis fit ', while Ulpian, Reg. viii. 2, describes it as created ' aut per populum aut per praetorem velpraesidem provinciae ', where, though the con- trast of aut and vel shows perhaps that he does not intend a tripartite division, he seems almost as if constrained by his usual habit. 24 TKICHOTOMY 1. The praecepta juris are said to be three honeste vivere, alterum non laedere, suum cuique tri- lucre. That this text was originally borrowed from some writer on philosophy can hardly be doubted. It was familiar to the Greeks. 1 It is obvious that none of the three precepts is a rule of positive law. To live honestly, for instance, is a good moral maxim, but the law does not insist on it. The police constable is not called upon till the dishonesty or immorality discloses itself in the infraction of some rule prescribed by the law of the land. ' Non omne quod licet honestum est,' says Paulus. 2 The other two precepts are open to similar criticism. The second would seem to be logically included in the third. Or the honeste vivere, if it is to be taken in a wide sense as in- cluding both negative and positive duties, would alone have sufficiently included the other two. 3 1 See references in Schrader, Inst. hoc loco. The precepts are rightly, I think, connected with the three cardinal virtues of the Stoics by Thomasius, Not. ad Inst. In. I. cited by Schrader. 2 Dig. 1. 17, fr. 144 pr. Cf. Dig. xxiii. 2, fr. 42 pr. ; and 1. 17, fr. 197 where it is said of marriage ' semper in conjunc- tionibus non solum quid liceat considerandum est, sed et quid honestum sit '. 3 See the criticism by Savigny, System, i, p. 409, who regards the precepta not as rules of law but as the basis on which rules of law rest. Puchta, Inst. 102 n. c , thinks IN EOMAN LAW 25 It would have been more logical still for Justinian to have said that the universal precept of law is to do justice justitia having been already defined as ' constans et perpetua voluntas jus suum cuique tribuendi'. 1 On the other hand, if each of the three precepts was intended to be taken in a re- stricted sense, they seem incomplete, and might have been added to appropriately. Thus Ulpian might have borrowed from Gaius and added ' male nostro jure non uti '. 2 2. Public law is tripartite, consisting in sacris, in sacerdotibus, in magistratibus. 3 This strange classi- fication is also taken from Ulpian, and is a sub- division of his primary dual division of law into jus publicum and jus privatum. It is interesting to notice that a tripartite division of law into jus sacrum, publicum and privatum was current among writers before Ulpian and is given by Quintilian, 4 the precept honeste vivere may be a ' Eeminiscenz aus den Stoikern (Cic. de Fin. ii. 11) ', and adds 'Es wiirde dann eine Bestatigung davon sein, dass dergleichen Entlehnungen so gut wie gar keinen Einfluss auf den eigentlichen recht- lichen Gehalt der Thatigkeit der Juristen hatten, denn wir finden nicht dass aus jenen praecepta juris das Kecht wirk- lich abgeleitet worden ware*. On this view see infra, p. 71, n. 1 . 1 Inst. i. 1 1. . 2 Gai. i 53. 3 Supra, p. 20, n. 2 . 4 Orat. ii. 4. 33. It is also given by Ausonius, Edyll. xi, 1. 62 ; supra, p. 6, n. 2 . 1211 D 26 TEICHOTOMY and also appears (though in a somewhat different sense) in the Code. 1 For Ulpian to have adopted this would, of course, have prevented his tricho- tomy of jus publicum. Under magistratibus we must apparently place the vast subjects of the legis- lature, the magistracy, imperial administration and taxation, in short the whole of constitutional and administrative law. But is there any real distinction between sacris and sacerdotibus so as to justify the jurist in placing each of them separately on the same plane with magistratibus ? Either term alone would quite as well have represented all public matters of the jus divinum, as magistratibus represented those relating to the jus humanum. But for any practical consequence the classification was worthless and seems to have been ignored. A twofold division into jus divinum and humanum , 2 corresponding to matters of Church and State in modern law, the jus humanum being subdivided into publicum and 'privatum, would have been the natural and logical one. The division into jus divinum and jus humanum was, in fact, quite well known to Ulpian and was adopted by him in dealing with interdicts. 3 3. Private law is tripartite, viz. law (1) common 1 Cod. i. 2, 23. 2 See Cic. de Legibus ii and iii. 3 Dig. xliii. 1. 1 pr. IN ROMAN LAW 27 to men with the lower animals (jus naturale), (2) common to all peoples (jus gentium), and (3) binding upon Roman citizens alone (jus civile}, 1 This division of private law is from a different point of view to that of public law but is scarcely less objectionable. It can hardly have originated with Ulpian (in his Institutions), but much more probably is due to some unknown Stoic philo- sopher from whom he drew ; and, if we except perhaps two unimportant writers, Hermogenianus and Tryphoninus, 2 it was not adopted by any other jurist. The twofold division of Gaius into jus gentium and jus civile* was of course per- fectly well known to Ulpian, and, so far as the Corpus Juris shows, this was the only one which the jurists distinctly recognized. 4 We can say at 1 Supra, p. 20. 2 Savigny (System, Beilage i, p. 415) thinks that these two jurists adopted the trichotomy, but the passages in the Digest bearing on the point are not conclusive, viz. Dig. xii. 6, fr. 64 ; xvi. 3, fr. 31 ; and i. 1, fr. 5. It has been suggested that the first two of these, and a passage from Paul, Dig. xviii. i. 34 1, have suffered interpolation ; see Mitteis, Privatrecht, p. 63 n. This seems improbable. 3 Gai. i. 1. Cicero, de Off. iu. 5, 23, had said 'jus naturae id est gentium.' 4 E.g. Marcian in Dig. i. 8, fr. 2 and 4 ; Florentine in Dig. i. 8, fr. 3 ; Paul in Dig. i. 1, fr. 11, and xxiii. 2, fr. 14 2, and 1. 17, fr. 84 1 ; Modestine in Dig. xxxviii. 10, fr. 4 2. The term j. g. is used by them sometimes in a wide, sometimes in 28 TKICHOTOMY any rate that no jurist recognized a distinction between jus naturale and jus gentium so far as practical effects were concerned. Jus naturale is defined by Ulpian as ' quod natura omnia animalia docuit ', such as ' conjunctio maris atque feminae, liberorum procreatio, educatio V This definition elevates the instinctive actions of birds, beasts, and fishes to the domain of law, and astonishment has been often expressed by modern writers that a scientific lawyer like Ulpian should have adopted it. At the same time attempts have been some- times made to defend or explain it on philosophi- cal grounds (e. g. on the Stoic doctrine of living according to nature), but none of these can be admitted by jurisprudence. 2 Law is not con- cerned with instincts that are common to man and the lower animals. 3 The only theoretic con- sequence which Ulpian himself deduced from it was that slavery was contrary to the law of nature but sanctioned by jus gentium 4 , as regards prac- a narrow sense. Cf. Mitteis, I. c. and authorities there cited. 1 Dig. i. 1, 1 3. 2 See Savigny, System i, p. 416 ; Vinnius, Com. ad Inst. i. 2 pr. Ulpian himself says (D. ix. 1, 1 3) ' nee enim potest animal iniuria fecisse quod sensu caret '. 3 Cic. de Fin. iii. 20. 67. 4 This conception was undoubtedly borrowed from the Stoics. Even as regards slavery it is hard to suppose that IN KOMAN LAW 29 tical consequences he really did not adhere to or make any use of it, but on the contrary posi- tively identified jus naturale and jus gentium in various passages in his writings other than the one above cited. 1 Justinian in his Institutes, while so far adopt- ing the tripartite division of Ulpian, makes at the same time a variation from it which Savigny rightly describes as senseless (gedankenlos). 2 He first gives Ulpian's definition of jus naturale, and then proceeds to define jus gentium in the words of Gaius as ' quod naturalis ratio inter omnes homines constituit '. 3 He then further somewhat modifies his definition of jus gentium by applying it to the settled usages of mankind and the require- ments of social life ( l usu exigente et humanis ne- cessitatibus '), 4 as shown by the consensual and Ulpian can have had in view his own definition. Mediaeval lawyers following Ulpian fell into similar difficulties on the subject. See Odofredus in Digestum Vetus i. 1 6, citing a gloss of Irnerius (lucerna juris). This gloss is given by Savigny, GescMchte des rom. Eechts im Mittelalter iv, p. 387. See also Carlyle, Mediaeval Political Theory in the West, vol. ii, pp. 28-33. 1 E. g. Dig. ix. 2, fr. 50 ; x. 4, fr. 3 15 ; xvi. 2, fr. 6 ; xliii. 16, fr. 1 9 ; xliv. 7, fr. 14 ; 1. 16, fr. 10. 2 Inst. i. 1 4 ; i. 2 pr. See Savigny, System i, p. 419. 3 Inst. i. 2 1. 4 Inst. i. 2 2. 30 TKICHOTOMY other contracts, 1 and then finally, as every tyro knows, altogether ignores in the rest of the work (save as regards the origin of slavery) the tripartite division, and even in one passage expressly iden- tifies jus naturale with jus gentium. 2 There was indeed a sense in which, in the time of the classical jurists, jus naturale was distinguishable from jus gentium and might have justified a tripartite divi- sion. The law based on 'naturalis ratio inter omnes homines' (called jus gentium in Gaius i. 1, and Inst. i. 2 1) truly represented the jus naturae or naturale of the philosophers and philo- sophizing lawyers of the early empire. 3 It was essentially theoretical and based on speculation, and in this sense was distinguishable from jus gentium historically considered, which formed from an early period part of the jus Romanum.* That dominium might be acquired by occupatio and traditio and that civil contracts might be created by mere consent were illustrations of jus gentium in this latter sense, and to it the name might well have been confined ; while upon the jus naturale^ in 1 Following in this Ulpian and Hermogenian Dig. 1. fr. 1 5 and frs. 4 et 5. 2 See Inst. i. 2 11, and ii, 1 11. 3 Of. Cicero, de Off. iii. 5. 23. 4 This is vaguely contemplated in Inst i. 2 2, but the definition there is too wide for the historic jus gentium. IN EOMAN LAW 31 its wide speculative conception, depended inter alia such dogmas (the product mainly of Stoic philo- sophy operating upon the jurists), as the per- sonality of slaves, naturalis cognatio and naturalis oUigatio. 1 Unhappily, however, the jurists, as already indicated, failed to make any precise distinction between the two. However this be, it noways justifies Ulpian's tripartite division, which must ever remain what Savigny calls a Curiositat, and seems only explicable on the hypothesis for which I am contending. 4. The statement of Modestine regarding the sources of law that ' omne jus aut consensus fecit aut necessitas constituit aut firmavit consuetudo ' 2 is very different in its point of view from that of Papinian in Dig. i. 1, fr. 7 (who divides the sources of the written law into five parts), and from the well-known divisions given by Gaius and Justinian in their Institutes. Modestine's classification is obviously traditional, and Cujacius thinks it was taken from the Greek of Menander. Modestine was not the kind of man to originate it. It is 1 See on this Voigt, Jus naturale, etc., i, pp. 286 sq. ; Krttger, G. d. Quellen, 17. Early writers on International Law, e. g. Grotius and Puffendorf, lay stress on this distinc- tion. For Greek law see Schulin, GescMchte d. rom. Rechts, pp. 85-6. 2 Supra, p. 20. 32 TKICHOTOMY both scientifically and practically worthless, though Cujacius makes an ingenious, if futile, attempt to explain it. 1 No use was ever made of it. 5. 'Jus praetorium est quod praetores intro- duxerant adjuvandi, vel supplendi vel corrigendi juris civilis gratia.' 2 This, in some respects admirable, definition of Papinian has been much commented upon by modern writers on Eoman law, and treated as if it represented (which it hardly does) an exhaustive summary of the prae- tors' reforms. 3 Yet its three parts what Cujas calls the 'tres virtutes juris praetorii' awaken suspicion, and I cannot resist the supposition that it was borrowed from some quasi-philosophic writer. With it may be compared the definition in Justinian's Institutes, where the expressions confirmandi, emendandi, and impugnandi, juris civilis gratia are used. 4 1 Cujac. Obs. xiv, c. 16. He thinks that ' omne jus ' must be limited to leges, senatus consulta, and constietudo, to which threefold division of topics the rubric of the Title (Dig. i. 3) is confined. His comments are very strained and uncon- vincing. He also endeavours to explain the text alter- natively on the assumption that it applies to the whole body of law. If he had thought of a Stoic trichotomy he would have saved himself the trouble. See also Otto, TJiesaur. iii, p. 695. 2 Supra, p. 20. 3 See e. g. Sohm, Inst, pp. 540 and 547. 4 Inst iii. 9, pr. 1. IN EOMAN LAW 33 6. The imperial constitutions as a source of law are divided into three kinds, viz. decreta, edicta, and epistulae. 1 This purely legal classification does not seem open to serious objection. It may have originated with Gaius and at any rate cannot be much earlier than his time. Nevertheless it is incomplete, as it omits mandata. 2 These mandata though sometimes contrasted with constitutiones (e.g. Dig. xlvii. 11. 6) cannot be sensibly dis- tinguished from, but were a species of, them. Eeasons have been suggested for this omission by modern writers, but none of them satisfactory. Thus it has been said by some that, as they are of the nature of edicta, they may have been intended to be included in that category; by others that they were intended to be included under epistulae, and by others that they were deliberately excluded because they related mainly to matters not of private but of public law. 3 But these views cannot be maintained, it is thought, in face of the texts. 4 1 Supra, p. 20 ; Krttger, Quelkn, p. 99. 2 How far leges datae (e. g. lex Salpensana) should also be included may be a question. See Schulin, Gesch. d. rom. Eechts, p. 102. 3 See Schrader, Inst. i. 2 6 ; Puchta, Inst. as in next note. 4 See Dig. iv. 1, 1 pr. ; xxix. 1, fr. 1, pr., fr. 2 ; xxxiv. 9. 2 1 ; Pernice rev. Wlassak, Z. d. Sav. Stift. vi, pp. 297-8. On the possibility of an interpolation in Dig. i. 4. 1 1, see Puchta, Inst. i ex, note g. 1211 E 34 TEICHOTOMY 7. The subject-matter of private law relates to persons, things, and actions. 1 Personae, res, and actiones represent respectively the subjects, objects, and sanctions of rights. I will not enter upon an exhaustive criticism of this famous classification, upon which so much has been already written, and which has so largely domi- nated the method of mediaeval and modern writers upon law. It has its conveniences but it is quite illogical. Apart from the illogicality of co-ordinating the law of actions with that relating to persons and things, to which it stands properly as adjective, the classification forced Gaius to treat property as a res corporalis, and succession and obligations as res incorporates* rights to things being thereby confounded with things themselves. 3 1 Supra, p. 20. 2 As is well known, it has been doubted whether obliga- tions were intended in the classification in Justinian's Institutes to fall under the head of res or actiones. Theo- philus in his Paraphrase treated them as falling under actions. 3 See Austin, Jurisprudence, ii, pp. 764-6. Austin remarks on the Gaian method 'In pursuance of that well-founded distinction between Law of Persons and Law of Things, which Gaius . . . has adopted, the main division (according to Ends and Subjects) should not have been threefold (still less fourfold) but twofold ; the matter of the Law of Actions (i. e. civil procedure), as unmodified by status, . . . being IN EOMAN LAW 35 Here also it, is a question whether Gaius borrowed his tripartite division direct from some earlier writer, and the probabilities are all in favour of his having done so. It had already, at any rate, been foreshadowed in non- legal works as, for instance, in Varro's Anti- quitateSj where, in connexion with the doctrine of res divinae, he treats first of persons in rela- tion to things, then of loca sacra vel religiosa, and finally of the Calendar and days of festival. 1 All attempts to explain the classification on grounds of abstract jurisprudence seem to me quite vain, 2 as, for example, the old theory of Duarenus that Gaius did not intend the three parts to be mutually exclusive, but used them rather to indicate that the whole law may be included under the Law of Things, and the several modifica- tions, under the several status out of which they arise/ 1 See Girard, Textes, 3rd ed., p. 203 ; Karlowa, E. E. G. i, p. 725. For the view that it was more probably due to Gaius than traditional, see Savigny, Syst., i, pp. 395-7, where he refers to Hugo, Civil Mag. 5, p. 403, and 6, p. 286. Hugo's view that it was taken from some early non-juristic writer seems to me most probable. Karlowa, 1. c., remarks ' diese Eintheilung ist aller Wahrscheinlichkeit nach ein altes Gemeingut der romischen Eechtsgelehrten, auf sie vererbt von der alten pontifizischen Jurisprudenz ', and refers to Booking, Pandekten, i 2 , Anhang vi. 2 See Austin, Jurisprudence, ii, pp. 764-66. 36 TEICHOTOMY studied in relation to any one of them. 1 The author of the division (whether Gaius or another) wanted a tripertita, and the doctrines had to be fitted into it somehow. One may, however, well attribute the division to the traditional influence of the Stoa 2 a view which seems to me to be supported by the fact that Ulpian in his Institu- tions makes, or rather borrows, another scholastic trichotomy of the omne jus, which, as we will see under next head, is without any scientific value whatever. 8. In his Institutions, as cited in the Digest, Ulpian says : i Totum autem jus consistit aut in adquirendo aut in conservando aut in minuendo : aut enim hoc agitur quemadmodum quid cujusque fiat, aut quemadmodum quis rem vel jus suum 1 The passage of Duarenus is quoted by Booking in an appendix to his edition of Gaius and by Emerton, The Three- fold Division of Roman Law, p. 19 (London, 1888). Einerton founds on the use by Gaius of vel instead of aut in the division, as confirming the view of Duarenus, but his argu- ments are to my mind quite unconvincing. Cf. Savigny, Syst. , ut sup. 2 Compare the division of Philosophy by the Stoics into Logic, Natural Science, and Ethics. See Zeller, Stoics, Epi- cureans and Sceptics, chap. iv. (Reichel's Trans.), pp. 62-7; August, de Civ. Dei, xi, c. 25. But for my thesis it is immaterial whether it was taken from a Stoic writer on jurisprudence or was an inheritance from old pontifical traditions. IN KOMAN LAW 37 conservet, aut quomodo alienet aut amittat/ ! This is a rather strange limitation of the totum jus, but we may perhaps assume that Ulpian is here referring to the jits privatum alone. Can any one doubt that it represents one of Ulpian's borrowings from some philosophic or pseudo- philosophic treatise ? Apparently he attached no significance or importance to it whatever. Com- mentators have as a rule, so far as I have ob- served, left the passage severely alone, but Savigny makes some observations about it. After stating the proposition that every legal relation has its own special rules according to which in respect of any specific person it comes into existence and again is extinguished, and that these rules are of such importance that in many legal relations they form the sole ground of inquiry, he cites the above passage in a note and remarks : ' Hier wird noch ein neues Moment in die Mitte jener bei- den [i.e. Entstehung and Untergang] gestellt, das conservare. Nimmt man dieses im eigentlichen Sinn fur die Bewirkung der Fortdauer des Kechts selbst, so fallt es mit dem dritten zusammen, indem es dann als die Negation des dritten (oder umgekehrt) aufgefasst werden kann ; dann sagt aber auch das totum ius consistit viel zu viel. 1st 1 Supra, p. 21, n. 1 . 38 TEICHOTOMY dagegen das conservare als Erhaltung der Aus- iibung, oder als Kechtsverfolgung, gedacht, so um- fassen allerdings jene drei Momente den grossten Theil aller Bechtsregeln iiberhaupt : dann aber sind die drei Momente nicht so gleichartig dass diese Zusammenstellung derselben gerechtfertigt werden konnte. 5 1 All this may be admitted, but the ineptitude of the text and its worthlessness to Ulpian himself remain to my mind perfectly clear. No use is made of it. 2 9. The grouping of persons into three classes, viz. (1) liberi and servi, (2) cives, latini, and pere- grinij and (3) sui juris and alieni juris, is not formally given by Gaius, but it appears to have been before his mind quite distinctly nevertheless. Whether it was borrowed by him is unknown. In terms, however, the second class is confined by him to liberti, whom he divides into cives, latini, and pere- grini dediticiorum numero. 3 The reason why a similar division of the second class was not made specifically by him for the ingenui is not easy to say. It may have been that he regarded the dis- cussion of civitas and peregrinitas as falling under 1 System, iii, p. 2, note (b). 2 Except perhaps the triad of interdicts ? See infra, p. 53. 8 Gai. i 12 ; see supra, p. 21, n. 2 ; infra, p. 41 ; Mommsen, Staatsrecht, iii. 1, p. 8 2 . IN EOMAN LAW 39 public rather than private law. Whatever the reason, he only notices freeborn citizens, latins and peregrins incidentally, and in so far as it enables him to discuss by analogy the three classes of libertini. It is an obvious defect of the above classification that slaves fall under both (1) and (3). 1 10. Persons are again treated by Ulpian as divisible jure gentium into three classes, ' liberi et his contrarium servi et tertium genus liberti.' 2 This is apparently an illogical division, as liberti are not co-ordinate with the other two but form a subordinate class of liberi. It is moreover in- consistent with Ulpian's own definition of manu- mission as ' datio libertatis ' (Dig. i. 1, 4). Gaius avoids the illogicality and rightly divides persons into servi and liberi, subdividing the latter into ingenui and libertini. 5 Some commentators have suggested that by liberi Ulpian meant ingenm,* but this would also make a bad classification and is merely an attempt to save his logic. 1 For a logical classification of persons see Savigny, System, ii, pp. 58-9. 2 Swpra, p. 21, n. s . His language seems to indicate a tradi- tional division. 3 Gai. i 9. Justinian's editors give first the Gaian classification (Inst. i. 3 pr. 5), and then carelessly that of Ulpian (Inst. i. 5 pr.). * See Schrader, Inst. i. 5 pr. 40 TKICHOTOMY Moreover, a classical jurist would not have used ingenuitas in this way in contrast with servitus. It is hard to suppose that Ulpian, to whom the dual classification of Gaius must have been familiar, should have been unconscious that he was making a cross division. Whether he borrowed it or not, I see no explanation but the desire for a tripartite division. 11. Gaius (i J 17) says, regarding acquisition of civitas by a manumitted slave, ' in cujus per- sona tria haec concurrunt, ut major sit annorum triginta, et ex jure Quiritium domini, et justa ac legitima manumissione liberetur, id est vindicta aut censu aut testamento, is civis Eomanus erit ; sin vero aliquid eorum deerit, Latinus erit.' Here we are given, first, three conditions for, and second, three modes of, manumission. As regards the conditions, it was only the second and third that were required by the old jus civile to make a Eoman citizen ; the first was due to the lex Aelia Sentia. Apparently the three con- ditions are intended to be exhaustive, but, if so, they are wanting in accuracy. The age of the master, for instance (he must be over twenty years), had by the Aelia-Sentian law as much to be considered as that of the slave. 1 But this 1 Gai. i 18, 38 ; cf. Ulp. Reg. i 12, 13. In the IN KOMAN LAW 41 may perhaps be a mere oversight of Gaius or due to his mode of exposition. Besides the three forms of manumission men- tioned (which Ausonius apparently gives as an illustration of the ternarius numerus, under the name * triplex libertas ' *), there were other modes of a slave being legally manumitted and obtain- ing civitas, e. g. grant by the State under various enactments. 2 In any case the trichotomy is an old one and purely Koman. 12. The classification above mentioned of freedmen into cives, latini, and dediticiorum nvr mero* is obviously the symmetrical counterpart of the division of freemen into cives, latini, and peregrini, and is, as we have seen, one of the three groups under whicli Gaius discusses persons West Gothic Gaius the regular modes of manumission are different but are kept tripartite, viz. ' testamento, aut in ecclesia, aut ante consulem.' Gai. Epit. i. 1. 1 EdyU. xi, 1. 65, but see infra, p. 42, n. 1 . 2 See also Inst. i. 11 12, adoption by a master of one of his own slaves. The irregular modes of manumission by which Junian latinity was obtained were also classified as threefold in the West Gothic Gaius, where it is said ' Latini sunt qui aut per epistolam aut inter amicos aut convivii adhi- bitione manumittuntur '. As to the magistrates before whom manumission could take place cf. Ulp. Reg. i 7 apparently consul, praetor, proconsul with Inst. i. 5 2, and Schrader's note hoc loco. 3 Supra, p. 21. See also Gai. Epit. i. 1. 1211 42 TEICHOTOMY in the first book of his Commentaries. In the Institutes of Justinian this classification of freed- men is called tripertitus status. 1 It cannot of course be earlier than the Empire, as it was based on the lex Aelia Sentia and lex Junia. As we learn from Gaius (iii 74-6) these dediticii were, in the matter of succession to their states, treated sometimes as citizens and some- times as latins, this depending on the nature of their manumission. 2 The only criticism one can make upon the classification is that it is not exhaustive. There were other freedmen who were peregrini, though not in the number of dedi- ticii, viz. those manumitted by peregrin owners in accordance with the laws of the latter's own civitos.* 13. Persons alieni juris were said to be either in potestate, or in manu, or in mancipio.* In the early period of Eome the only word to express the powers of a paterfamilias over the familia was 1 Inst. i. 5 3. It is not certain whether the term 1 triplex libertas' in Ausonius, Edyll. xi, 1. 65, applies to this or to the three modes of manumission. Probably the latter. 2 Cf. Gai. i 17. 3 Pliny, Ep. x. 4 ; Frag. Dosith. 12. See Girard, Manuel d. d. r., 4th ed., p. 126. 4 Supra, p. 21, n. 6 . IN EOMAN LAW 43 probably manus ; potestas was a word of later origin. But in time manus, though still occasion- ally used in a general sense to express power, 1 became technically restricted to power over a wife. Mancipium was also a term of early law used in a variety of senses, but in time came to mean (in the expressions 'in mancipio' or 'in causa mancipii ') power of a paterfamilias over free persons mancipated to him, not being liberi or loco liberorum. Potestas was, like mantis in early times, a general term for power of the head of the house, but was more specially applied to power over slaves and children. This tripartite division, however, as given by Gaius and Ulpian, is quite artificial and without solid basis. Con- sidering the fundamental difference in the time of the classical jurists between slaves and chil- dren, one would naturally expect a fourfold division of persons alieni juris, viz. those in domi- nica potestate, those in patria potestate, those in manUj and those in mancipio and in fact Gaius does discuss them as if so classified. 2 It has been 1 e. g. Inst. i. 5 pr. ; Dig. i. 1, 4 and i. 2, 2 1 ; Cod. viii. 48. 6. 2 Gai. i 49 sq. The classification is doubtless older than Gaius. In Justinian's Institutes, as manus and manci- pium were in desuetude, there is a twofold division into 44 TEICHOTOMY justly observed by Poste, * The powers of the head of the family were nominally three, potestas, manuSj mancipium -, potestaSj however, was either potestas dominica ... or potestas patria . . ., which at the period when Koman law is known were different in kind ; so that the rights of a pater- familias were really fourfold.' l The differences between patria and dominica potestas were at all times much greater than those between manus or mancipium and patria potestas. 14. On Gaius's (and presumably Ulpian's) divi- sion of marriages cum manu into confarreatio, coemptio, and usus, 2 there is only this remark to be made that Gaius gives it as traditional, and, though possibly correct at one time, it was out of date at the time he wrote. It is a purely Eoman trichotomy. Hand marriages were still in the second century of our era contracted by coemp- tion, though rare, and even for certain purposes by confarreation, 3 but usus as creative of manus, as Gaius tells us, had been abolished partly by persons in dominica, and persons in patria potestate. Potestas was also applied to the power of guardians over wards. XII Tab. v. 7 ; Inst. i. 13 1 . ; Dig. xxvi. 1, 1 pr. ; Aul. Gell. v. 19. 10. See also Dig. 1. 16, 215. 1 Poste, Gaius (3rd ed.), p. 40. 2 Supra, p. 21, note 7 . 3 Gai. i 112, 113, 136. IN EOMAN LAW 45 statute and partly by desuetude before his time. 1 Gaius apparently says not a word about the con- stitution of marriage by simple consent, which was the ordinary mode in his time. 2 15. Extinction of patria potestas over sons was effected by three sales and three corresponding manumissions. I have already sufficiently dis- cussed the symbolism of this. 3 It is probable, and it seems to be the view generally accepted, that originally this rule applied to all descendants, and that it was by casuistical interpretation of the word * filium ' in the law of the XII Tables, that a single mancipation and manumission was subsequently held to be sufficient in the case of daughters and grandchildren. 4 16. Persons sui juris are distributed by Gaius and Justinian in their Institutes into those in tutory, those in curatory, and those who are in neither the one nor the other. 5 The Eomans had no technical term equivalent to our English 1 Gai. i 111. 2 Had this traditional tripartite division anything to do with Justinian's treatment of marriage in the Digest ? See Const. Tanta, 5 ; Hofmann, Ztsch. f. R. G. xi, p. 350, who says, 'Die Zahl drei bedeutet unter anderem auch die Ehe.' 3 Supra, p. 13 and p. 22, n. 1 . 4 See Jhering, Geist des rom. Eechts, ii, p. 104. 5 Supra, p. 22, n. a . 46 TEICHOTOMY ' infant ' signifying a person under majority, or to our English 'ward' signifying any person under guardianship, nor had they any general term equivalent to guardianship. Pupilarity and mi- nority were with them fundamentally distinct and had different effects, and it was proper for them to treat tutory and curatory separately. But we have here a strange tripartite division, of which the third class is wholly uncalled for, save in order to be symmetrical with the division of persons alieni juris. The way in which the classification is made shows that it was intended to be three- fold: 'Videamus igitur quae in tutela, quae in curatione sint ; ita enim intellegemus ceteras per- sonas quae neutro jure tenentur.' x It would have been as reasonable for Gaius to have treated of marriage by dividing persons into those married cum manu, those married sine manUj and those who are neither. But a threefold classification, of which one of the heads does not, ex necessitate, admit of discussion in relation to the other two, is worthless. 17. In the Institutes of Justinian and also in the Digest tutors are treated (without any formal 1 Gai. i 142 ; cf. Gai. i 50, 51. These divisions rest on the principle of Aristotelian logic ' contrariorum cognito uno, cognoscitur et alterum.' IN KOMAN LAW 47. classification being given) as divisible into testa- mentarii, legitimi, and a magistratibus dati, 1 and this is not objectionable. It was familiar to Ulpian and doubtless used by him. But in his Eules he gives formally a separate tripartite division, viz. legitimi, senatusconsultis constitute and moribus introducti, and this seems highly arti- ficial. 2 It seems to be conceived from the point of view of the sources from which the office of tutor is derived. But the first class (the legitimi) is altogether out of proportion to the other two, embracing as it does each of the three kinds in the above-mentioned Justinianian treatment, i.e. tutory- at-law (agnatic and patronal) as well as testamen- tary and ordinary magisterial tutory. 3 The second 1 Inst. i, tits. 13-20 ; Dig. xxvi, tits. 2-5. 2 Ulpian, Eeg. xi 2-24. Ulpian seems at times to lose sight of it. See 5, 6, where he distinguishes apparently tutor fiduciarius from tutor legitimus. As Gaius tells us (i 172), the former was thought to be unable to cede injure his tutory while the latter could do so. See Ulp. Eeg. 17. Like his tripartite division of the totum jus (supra, p. 36), Ulpian evidently attaches no importance to this division. 3 While Gaius, i 168, subdivides tutors-at-law into three, viz. agnati, patroni, and liberorum capitum manumissores, Justinian in the Institutes subdivides them into agnati, patroni, parentes, and fiduciarii. Ulpian, on the other hand, in a passage in the Digest (xxvi. 4, 1 pr.), ascribes to the XII Tables three species, viz. agnati, consanguine^ and patroni a 48 TRICHOTOMY and third classes represent merely such magisterial tutors as were appointed in special cases either by virtue of a senatusconsult or by custom. The senatorial tutors were appointed by magistrates only in a few exceptional cases, as, e.g. where a legitimus patronal tutor of a woman was dumb or insane and auctoritas was required to constitute her dowry, 1 while the tutors by customary law were likewise appointed by magistrates excep- tionally, as, for instance, where a pupil or adult woman was desirous of raising an action against his or her proper tutor. 2 In any proper classifica- tion it is obvious that these special cases would have been treated simply as exceptions in discuss- ing the magisterial tutors, as in fact is done by Gaius. 3 Could Ulpian have had before his mind the Ciceronian 'si partiri velis tutelas, inscienter facias si ullam praetermittas ' ? 4 Gaius, speaking of the species tutelarum, as he calls them, viz. plainly objectionable division. See Gothofredus, edition of Corpus Juris (1663), notes on this .passage. 1 Ulp. xi 21 ; cf. Gai. i 177, 180-3. By the lex Julia de marit. ord. the same course was followed where the patronal tutor was a p.upil. Gai. i 178-9 ; Ulp. xi 20. 2 Ulp. xi 24 ; cf. Gai. i 184. Such tutor was technically called praetorius. 3 Gai. i 176-84 ; cf. Inst. i. 21 3. 4 Cic. Top. 33. IN EOMAN LAW 49 the testamentary, agnatic and others, says this (i 188) : ' Si vero quaeramus in quot genera hae species diducantur, longa erit disputatio ; nam de ea re valde veteres dubitaverunt, nosque diligen- tius-hunc tractatum executi sumus et in edicti interpretatione et in his libris quos ex Q. Mucio fecimus. Hoc tantisper sufficit admonuisse quod quidam quinque genera esse dixerunt ut Q. Mucius; alii tria ut Ser. Sulpicius ; alii duo, ut Labeo ; alii tot genera esse crediderunt, quot etiam species essent.' This passage seems to show rather an odd lack of capacity for systematic arrangement among the earlier jurists. 18. Paulus says, i Tria sunt quae habemus, libertatem, civitatem, familiam.' 1 But obviously, as Savigny points out, there were many other things in private law quae kabemus, such as property, obligations, marriage, &c. What Paul probably however meant was that status, in the sense of caput or civic personality, is composed of three elements, viz. liberty, citizenship, and family. These made up a man's caput under jus civile. The classical jurists seem to have im- properly invented the triad, holding that no one enjoyed full public and private rights who did 1 Supra, p. 22. Dig. iv. 5, 11. See Savigny, System, ii. Beilage vi. 9 (pp. 508-10). 1211 50 TRICHOTOMY not possess all three. But civitas included fa- milia. On the other hand, it is clear that in early times the distinction between libertas and civitas was unknown; if a person was not a citizen he was de jure a slave, he had no caput. 1 19. Capitis deminutio is either the greatest, the middle, or the least. 2 There are various passages in the texts proving that originally there were only two kinds of cap. dem., viz. the greater and the less (magna or major and minor), and that the division into three classes was due to the jurists of the last century of the Republic. 3 The magna cap. dem. meant loss of citizenship and with it all public and private civil rights ; the minor cap. dem. meant loss of caput within the sphere of the private law alone, i.e. loss of existing family rights. This was sufficient to meet all cases. But the jurists, 1 The word liber signifying both free and a child points to this. See as to liber and libertus, Mommsen, Eom. Staatsr. iii. pp. 8, 62, 421. Commenting on Capitis deminutio, Savigny (1. c. p. 511) says: 'die ganze Stelle des Paulus erscheint demnach nur als ein mislungener Versuch die dreifache Cap. dem. auf eine rationelle Weise zu begrtinden. 2 Supra, p. 22. Ausonius gives this as an illustration of ternarius numerus Edyll. xi, line 65. 3 Thus Ulp. in Dig. xxxviii, 16. 1 4, speaks of only magna and minor, but he is not there making any division. For the varying terminology in the texts see Savigny, System, ii 68 d. Cf. Kuntze, Inst. ii. p. 368. IN EOMAN LAW 51 founding on the distinction, which gradually grew up, between that loss of citizenship which carried with it loss of liberty, and that which did not, but reduced merely to the status of peregrin, divided the magna cap. dem. into maxima and media or minor, and gave the name minima to cap. dem. within the private law. Thus they got a triad. In both the maxima and media there was loss of citizenship ; but the former, it was said, reduced to slavery, the latter did not. 2 We have thus an attractive but somewhat irrational symmetry maxima includes the other two, media includes minima to which the three elements of status above considered, viz. libertas, civitas, familia, were made to correspond. 3 This view of the origin of the threefold division is, indeed, only conjectural, 1 Could a non civis be said to undergo cap. dem. maxima? There is no sufficient evidence of it, though it has been maintained by some writers. See Cohn, Beitrage, Heft ii. pp. 46 sq. 2 Mommsen observes, E. S.-R. iii. 1, p. 8 The Koman jurists, in order to support their threefold division into (1) liberi et servi, (2) ewes, L., p., and (3) sui et alieni juris, have obscured the meaning of cap. dem. by setting up three degrees of it, * obwohl sie selbst diese mehrfach auf zwei zuruckfuhren und zuruckfiihren mtissen, weil dem spateren Privatrecht Freiheit und Burgerrecht zusammenfallt. In der That sind es nicht zwei Grade, sondern zwei verschiedene, obwohl correlate Kechtsbegriffe.' 52 TKICHOTOMY but it has received incidentally a good deal of support from the inquiries of recent writers. 1 If the foregoing critical remarks be sound, it must be admitted that the great bulk of the classifications in the department of the law dealt with are traditional tripertita resting on no logical basis and only explicable on the theory for which I am contending. In the other departments of the law discussed in the three remaining books of the Institutes of Gaius and Justinian the tri- partite division, though it frequently occurs, is' apparently not so prominent as in the first books, while in the department of obligations in Justinian's Institutes it wholly gives place, as I have shown in the Studi Fadda, to artificial quadripartite classifications. However, I will now notice a few threefold divisions in the departments of the law relating to things and actions that have given rise to difficulties and seem to me to support my thesis. (a) There are two well-known tripartite classifi- cations of interdicts. By the first, which is called summa divisio, they are divided into exhilitory, resti- tutory, and prohibitory. 2 On this I will content 1 See Mommsen, Staatsrecht, 1. c. ; H. Krttger, Cap. Dem. vol. i. 2 Gai. iv, 142; Inst. iv. 15 1 ; Paul in Dig. xliii. 1. IN KOMAN LAW 53 myself with quoting the following significant passage from Ulpian : ' Interdictorum autem tres species sunt; exhibitoria, prohibitoria, restitutoria; sunt tamen quaedam interdicta et mixta, quae et prohibitoria sunt et exhibitoria/ l Here Ulpian mentions four classes and yet says 'tres species sunt'. 2 The second classification is that of the so-called possessory interdicts, they being divided into adi- piscendae, retinendae and recuperandae possessions causa ; 3 Ausonius, in his Griphus above mentioned, gives this as an illustration of the ternarius numerus. He says : 1 Interdictorum trinum genus ; unde repulsus Vi fuero, aut utrobi fuerit, quorumve bonorum.' 4 As is well known, this classification of posses- sory interdicts has largely governed the doctrine on the subject. Yet it has often been objected to as illogical, and various attempts have been 1 1. Gaius specifies, in all, three divisions (tria genera) of interdicts (iv. 142, 143, 156), of which, however, the third, simplicia and duplicia, is bipartite. There were in fact numerous other categories (e. g. Gai. iv. 170). 1 Dig. xliii. 1, fr. 1 1. See also Dig. xliii. 4, 3 2 and Karlowa, Eom. E.-G. iii. p. 1009. 2 Of. Dig. ii. 14. 5 cited infra, p. 55. See also Cic. Brutus, 43 and 54, where Cicero does much the same thing. 3 Gai. iv. 143 ; Inst. iv. 15 2 ; Paul in Dig. xliii. 1. 2 3. 4 Edyll. xi, lines 63-4. 54: TKICHOTOMY made, from the time of Donellus onwards, to find a ratio for it. The interdicts adipiscendae posses- sionis, such as the quorum bonorum and the Salvianum, being destined for the obtaining of possession of things by one who makes no claim to having had previous possession of them, are, it is thought, distinct in their character from the retinendae and recuperandae possessionis interdicts, which were intended for the protection of pre- viously existing possession. They are treated apart from the latter in the Digest. Savigny, in the earlier editions of his famous treatise, did not hesitate to exclude the adipiscendae possessionis interdicts altogether from the class of possessory, and charged the Koman jurists with inaccuracy in making the classification, but the idea that the co-ordination of the three was due to the influence of the ternarius numerus does not seem to have impressed him. 1 There existed also, as we learn from Paulus in the Digest xliii. 1. 2 3, and the Vienna fragments of Ulpian's Institutes, interdicts 'tarn adipiscendae quam reciperandae possessionis' 1 Sav. Poss. 37. He slightly modifies his view in later editions. To defend the classification on the ground of its having in each case & jus possessionis i.e. the external object of the suit as its basis would, Savigny holds, be quite unscientific. For a contrary view see Cornil, Possession (Paris, 1905), pp. 307 sq. IN EOMAN LAW 55 (such as the quern fundum) ; but these, instead of being given by Paul and Ulpian as a fourth class with the three above named, are classified by them merely as in a sense interdicta duplicia. 1 As Paulus says : ' Sunt interdicta, ut diximus, duplicia tarn reciperandae quam apiscendae possessionis.' 2 (&) The exception of vitious possession in the possessory interdicts is also a tripertita, viz. vi aut clam aut precario.* This appeared in all interdicts retinendae possessionis, and is of Early Eoman origin. Excluding, as it does, dolus, and for "other reasons it can only be explained on my theory. Against the vitious possessor there seem also to have been three independent recuperatory interdicts, viz. de vi, de dandestina possessione, and de precario, but the nature of the second of these is unknown. 4 (c) In Digest ii. 14. 5 (de Pactis) we get the following extract from Ulpian's Commentary on the Edict: ' Conventionum autem tres sunt species. Aut enim ex publica causa fiunt aut ex privata : privata aut legitima aut juris gentium.' Here there is apparent disregard of logic ; species is improperly 1 See Girard, Textes, p. 467. Cf. supra, p. 53, n. 1 2 Dig. xliii. 1. 2 3. 3 Gai. iv 150-1 ; c-f. Terence, Eunuch, ii. 3, 28. See Cuq, Nouv. Eev. Hist. 1894, pp. 24 sq., who remarks: ' On tenterait vainement de la justifier.' 4 Dig. x. 3. 7 5. See Puchta, Inst. ii 225. 56 TKICHOTOMY co-ordinated with genus. This is similar to what occurs, as we have already seen, in Ulpian's classi- fication of persons into liberi, servi, and liberti^ and any emendation of the passage, as has been suggested, would be improper. 2 What one would have expected here (and it would have been in accordance substantially with the way in which Ulpian goes on to treat the subject) was a state- ment that there are two kinds of conventions, viz. ex publica causa and ex privata causa, and that, of the latter, there are two species, viz. legitimae and juris gentium. But Ulpian cannot refrain from his tripartite division. 3 (d) The division of heirs into necessarii, sui et necessarii, and extranei 4 is open to objection. Gaius 1 Supra, p. 39. Of. the classification of interdicts, supra, p. 53. 2 See Cujacius, Olservat. lib. xv, c. 33 ; Otto, Thesaur. i, p. 570 and iii, pp. 270, 445. For an independent classifica- tion in accordance with Ulpian's presumed meaning, though not an explanation of the trichotomy, see Voigt, Horn. R.-Gr. ii, pp. 852-3. Cf. Gliick, Erldut. d. PandeJc. iv, p. 278, who describes the action of the Digest editors in connecting the legitima conventio of fr. 5 with that of fr. 6 as ' sehr unschick- lich'. 3 Cujac. I.e., where it is remarked 'Tres [species] sunt sane, si universas ita numeres, hoc est et genera et species simul, alias duae. Sunt enim generatim pacta, % S^/xoo-ia, 17 t&a, aut publica, aut privata.' 4 Gai. ii 152 ; Inst. ii. 19 pr. ; Ulp. Eeg. xxii 24-5. IN ROMAN LAW 57 says : ' Heredes autem aut necessarii dicuntur aut sui et necessarii aut extranei.' A grandson in potestate, whose father was also in that position, was, if instituted (the father being disinherited), heres necessarius but not suns', and yet the definition of the heredes necessarii does not include him. 1 Persons in causa mancipii, again, instituted heirs cum libertate, though classed as necessarii, had, like sui, the abstinendi potestas which slaves had not. 2 The true generic division is into necessarii and voluntarii or into domestici and extranei. Schrader remarks (Inst. hoc loco) : t Abit haec trimembris divisio, ut aliae pleraeque, in bimembrem necessa- riorum voluntariorumque.' (e) A division of obligations made by Paulus from a processual point of view is into ' ad dandum aliquid vel faciendum vel praestandum'. He says 4 obligationum substantia non in eo consistit, ut aliquod corpus nostrum aut servitutem nostram faciat, sed ut alium nobis obstringat ad dandum aliquid vel faciendum vel praestandum.' 3 This obviously has reference to the formulae for en- forcing them. The meaning of praestare is not 1 Gai. ii 153 ; Inst. ii. 19 1, 2. Only by a fiction can he be regarded as suus et necessarius. 2 Gai. ii 160. 3 Paul in Dig. xliv. 7. 3 pr. ; Gai. iv 2. 1211 58 TEICHOTOMY certain, but it is certain that it only appeared in a formula (if at all) in a few special cases and ought not to have been co-ordinated with the other two. From this point of view Paul might almost as well have said l damnum decidendum ' as 'praestandum'. 1 Praestare was, in any case, comprehended by the generic facere. 2 Com- menting on this Pauline division, Savigny says : ' In diesem Zusammenhang ware das faciendum oder das praestandum (neben dem dandum) allein vollig hinreichend gewesen ; die an sich iiber- fliissige Zusammenstellung der drei moglichen Gegenstande enthalt eine augenscheinliche Anspie- lung auf die drei gleichnamigen Arten der Intentio in den Klagformeln. 5 3 (/) The frequent trichotomy of actio, petitio, persecutio in the texts creates difficulties which modern writers have in vain attempted to resolve. It is in fact meaningless, and Ulpian and other jurists who adopt it only fall into inexactitude in 1 Praestare was really a general term embracing dare and facere. See e.g. Gaius, iii 155 and iv 61. For different views as to praestare see Savigny, Syst. vol. v. App. xiv, pp. 599 sq. Of. Lenel, Edict Perpet. 2nd ed. p. 287, n. 12 , and p. 318. 2 Dig. 1..16, fr. 175, fr. 189, fr. 218. 3 System, 1. c. p. 602. See also Puchta, Inst. ii 165, note aa . for various explanations by different writers. IN KOMAN LAW 59 attempting to explain it. What is the distinction between actio and petitio ? Ulpian x and Papinian 2 say that specifically actio is used where the action is based on a personal, while petitio is used where based on a real right. Thus Ulpian says : ' " Actionis " verbum et speciale est et generale. Nam omnis actio dicitur, sive in personam, sive in rem sit petitio; sed plerumque "actiones" personales solemus dicere. " Petitionis " autem verbo in rem actiones significari videntur. " Per- secutionis " verbo extraordinarias persecutiones puto contineri, ut puta fideicommissorum et si quae aliae sunt, quae non habent juris prdinarii exsecutionem.' It is indisputable, however, that petitio and petere are constantly used as general expressions to indicate any kind of action, per- sonal (e. g. in the expression i si certum petetur ') as well as real. In Paul's Sentences we have petitio actually put in contrast with vindication Persecution on the other hand, which Ulpian sup- poses to have applied to the actiones extraordinariae, was used quite indefinitely, 4 and Ulpian is here not supported but rather contradicted by Papinian. 5 1 Dig. 1. 16, fr. 178 2. In a general sense he makes actio and petitio synonymous. 2 Dig. xliv. 7 fr. 28. 3 iv. 1. 18. 4 e. g. Dig. xxxii. 41 9, 11. Cf. references in notes 2 and 4 supra. 60 TKICHOTOMY Mitteis, who is the most recent writer to dis- cuss this trichotomy, gives all the principal authorities, and I may refer to what he says. 1 After showing the impossibility of making any satisfactory distinction between the three terms, and the consequent inaccuracy of Ulpian's view, he concludes thus : ' Bestimmte Bedeutungen lassen sich hier iiberall nicht erkennen,und so kann man es denn schwer vermeiden, mit Bruns in " actio petitio persecutio " eine sinnlose Haufung der Ausdrucke zu finden' (Bruns, Ztsch. f. E. Gesch. xii. 118). What Bruns and Mitteis have called a ' sinnlose Haufung der Ausdrucke ' it is preferable to call an example of persistent ten- dency to trichotomy. (g) Heirs by the jus civile are classified by Ul- pian as sui, consanguine^ and agnati : 2 t Intesta- torum ingenuorum hereditates pertinent primum ad suos heredes . . . ; si sui heredes non sunt, ad consanguineos, id est fratres et sorores ex eodem patre ; si nee hi sunt, ad reliquos agnatos proxi- mos.' Here the introduction of consanguinei is unnecessary, 3 and is not supported apparently 1 Privatrecht, 1908, p. 39, n. 1 and pp. 89-91. The tricho- tomy, as he points out, was traditional, for it appears in older laws as the lex Salpen. 26, lex Malacit. 58, 62, lex Urson, 129. 2 Ulp. Eeg. xxvi. 1 ; cf. Collat. xvi. 4 1, 2. 8 He makes a similar distinction as regards tutors-at-law IN EOMAN LAW 61 by any other jurist. The consanguinei are em- braced by the term agnati in Gaius * and all other writers ; in Ulpian's time there were only two classes of heredeSj the sui and agnati. Neither is Ulpian's division in accordance with that of the XII Tables, which Gaius correctly gives as sui, agnati, and gentiles. 2 Is it not in order to avoid a fourfold division that Ulpian refers to the suc- cession of the gentiles as merely matter of history ? 3 (h) Ulpian makes a tripartite division of the law into civil, praetorian, and imperial. 4 He is the only jurist who does so, but he is followed by Justinian in the Institutes. 5 This division is in- consistent with the general theory of the classical jurists that the emperors' Constitutions were but in Dig. xxvi. 4, 1 pr. (where he also apparently intends a threefold division of tutores legitimi). See Gltick, Pandekt. xxix, p. 325 ; supra, p. 47, note 3 . 1 Gai. iii 1, 9, 17. 2 Says Paul (Collat. iii. 3) ' Sane consanguinei, quos lex non adprehenderat, interpretatione prudentium primum inter agnatos locum acceperunt.' 8 Collat. xvi. 4 2. This reference to the gentiles was also doubtless in the Liber Regularum, but was omitted by the copyist of the MS. 4 Dig. 1. 16 10 ' Creditores accipiendos esse constat eos quibus debetur ex quacunque actione vel persecutione, vel jure civili ... vel honorario, vel extraordinario/ 5 Inst. ii. 10 3, where it is said of the imperial testament 1 hoc jus tripertitum esse', meaning its sources were threefold. 62 TRICHOTOMY the continuation of the jus praetorium in the wider sense. The emperors, prior to Diocletian, were theoretically regarded as but higher magistrates, acting like the consuls and praetors of the Re- public. It has been suggested that the passage of Ulpian may possibly be a Tribonianism, 1 but there is, I submit, no ground for this. On the contrary, the very fact that we have a tripartite classification makes it in my judgement all the more probable that there is no interpolation. (i) In Ulpian's Book of Rules it is said, * Actio- num autem quaedam ex contractu, quaedam ex facto, quaedam in factum sunt.' This most illo- gical division has much exercised the commenta- tors, many of whom are disposed to trace in it the interpolating hand of Tribonian. But it is not worse than several of the Ulpianic trichoto- mies above considered. As explained in the Digest text, it places actions in factum conceptae as a species along with actions based on contract and delict. 2 But actions in jus are the proper 1 Mitteis, Privatrecht, p. 39 n \ Mitteis also observes, ' Es 1st moglich class diese nachklassische Eintheilung an die Trichotomie actio, petitio und persecutio in unklarer Weise angeknupft hat.' 2 1%. xliv. 7, 25 1. In fr. 42 1 h. t. Ulpian makes a similar tripartite division which is almost equally open to objection ' qui aliquam actionem vel civilem habent . . . vel honorariam actionem, vel in factum/ IN BOMAN LAW 63 antithesis, as Gaius makes clear, of actions in factum conceptae. The text has been discussed at length by Erman, 1 with characteristic ability, and he arrives at the conclusion that the classification at least is due to Ulpian. He says, with reference to the arguments for interpolation by the Digest compilers, l Wir konnen also die, iibrigens durch nichts beglaubigte, Moglichkeit einer so tief- greifenden Umarbeitung von Ulpian's Eegulae ftir unsere Stelle als durchaus unwahrscheinlich bezeichnen und Ulpian's Autorschaft als sicher.' 2 He subsequently to some extent departs from this as regards the text as a whole, but, if I understand him aright, he adheres to his view that the trichotomy is Ulpian's. 3 In any case I hold, in accordance with my thesis, that it is undoubtedly his. There are numerous other tripartite divisions in the texts, to which one might refer as resting on no rational basis and creative of embarrass- ment by their inappropriateness or illogicality. 1 Ztsch. d. Sav.-Stift. xix, pp. 299; but cf. xxiii, pp. 447-9. Erman describes Ulpian's use of the expression ex facto for the usual ex delicto or ex maleficio as a ' Wortspiel '. 2 Ztsch. d. Sav.-Stift. xix, p. 301. 3 Ibid, xxiii, pp. 447-9. There is the greatest probability that the last sentence of fr. 25 1 has been altered by the compilers. 64: TKICHOTOMY But enough illustrations have probably been given. 1 Are then these constantly recurring categories of three, which as we have seen are but rarely logical or natural, explicable on no general hypo- 1 The following may be considered : Tripartite division of (1) praetorian stipulations by Ulp. in ig. xlvi. 5. 1 pr. See explanation by Puchta (Inst. ii. 268 i.) with note by Kudorff. In Van Leeuwen's edition of the Corpus Juris, h. I., it is remarked 'Species recte dixit. Puritas enim, dies, con- ditio, formae sunt stipulationum, non species/ (2) * tribus modis insula in flumine fit ' in Dig. xli. 1. 30 2 ; (3) atrox injuria is ex facto, ex loco, ex persona in Gai. iii 225, cf. Paul, Sent. v. 4 10 and Dig. xlvii. 10. 7, 8 : locus vulneris is added to them in Dig. fr. 8 h. t., Inst. iv. 4 9. (4) 'Edi autem est vel dictare, vel tradere libellum vel codicem proferre' Ulp. in Dig. ii. 13. 6 7. (5) Urere, frangere, and rumpere in the Lex Aquilia which necessitated an extension to corrumpere ; (6) i Inpensarum species sunt tres ' in Ulp. Eeg. vi 14 ; cf. Paul in Dig. 1. 16. 79 ; (7) of obligations it is said (Dig. 1. 16, fr. 19) that quaedam agantur, quaedam gerantur, quaedam contrahantur. This last is attributed by Ulpian to Labeo's Commentary on the Edict and as explained in the Digest is quite illogical and indefinite. See Otto, Thesaurus, i. 672, ii. 403 ; Voigt, Rom. R.-G. ii. 853. (8) Pulsare, verberare, vi domum introire in the lex Cornelia de injuriis. Dig. xxxxvii. 10, 5 pr. See Ehetor. ad Herenn. iv. 25, 35, and Girard in Melanges Gerardin, p. 258. (9) Three kinds of receptum, viz. arbitri, nautarum cauponum stalula- riorum, and argentariorum. See Lenel, Ed. Perpet, 48-50. (10) 'Munus tribus modis dieitur' Dig. 1. 16, 18; 'Tres fere causae sunt ex quibus in possessionem mitti solent * Dig. xlii. 4, 1. There are also aliae divisiones trifariae innumerabiles. IN ROMAN LAW 65 thesis ? Commentators on the Roman law have for the most part contented themselves with remarking on this or that classification that it is strange or inexplicable or a playing with words, or heaping-up of terms, 1 or else sometimes they have given the most far-fetched and unsatisfactory explanations, as we have seen in relation to the trichotomies of jus naturale, gentium, and civile, and jus personarum, rerum, and actionum. But are they not all attributable to a tendency of the jurists (especially of Ulpian), more or less conscious, to adopt traditional symbolic tripartite divisions (whether handed down from remote times or invented in the later philosophic schools), or, influenced by tradition, to invent them ? I have a conviction that they are due to each of these causes. There is nothing improbable in this. I have shown that the tendency to choose triper- tita was inherent in Roman thinking about law from very early times. I have also indicated here and there that this tendency was increased by the influence of the philosophic schools. The tendency is, I think, to be largely found among non-juristic writings of the late Republic and early Empire. In the writings of the philosophers, both prior to and during the period of classical jurisprudence, 1 See supra, p. 60. 1211 I 66 TRICHOTOMY especially of the Stoics and the Neo-Platonists, but even to some extent of the Peripatetic School, abundant evidence of proneness to trifariae dim- siones exists. It undoubtedly appears in the wri- tings of Cicero, who, though he cannot strictly be described as an adherent of any of these Schools, was, in his later years at least, much influenced by Stoicism. 1 Thus in the Topics he considers the division of law in general (jus) into ' legem, morem, aequitatem *, 2 and he subsequently, with apparent inconsistency, says of aequitas, t institutio aequitatis tripertita est, una pars legitima est, altera con'veniens, tertia moris vetustate firmata. Atque etiam rursus aequitas tripertita dicitur esse : una ad superos Deos, altera ad manes, tertia ad homines pertinere. Prima pietas, secunda san- ctitas, tertia justitia aut aequitas nomiriatur.' 3 Permce, in commenting on the first sentence of this passage, of which the meaning is, to my mind (as it probably was to that of Cicero), 1 Cicero is usually described as an Academic. 2 Top. 81. Of. de Invent, ii. 22 65 sq. and 53 161 sq., where the sources of law are natura, consuetude, lex. 3 Top. 90. Cf. ibid. 28, where aequitas has a different meaning. The Topica is a work based on Aristotelianism, and therefore the influence of symbolism on it, and particu- larly of the number 3, is not on the whole very great. See supra, p. 7, n. 2 . IN EOMAN LAW 67 wholly vague, suspects it to be due to Greek influence and refers to Aristotle (Ehet. i. 13). 1 Other illustrations of this kind of trichotomy, most probably borrowed from the Greek philo- sophers, will be found in most of Cicero's writings, other than his letters and orations, in immense abundance. 2 It would, of course, be too much to charge Cicero, who, as I said, was not an adherent of any of the Schools, with being consciously domi- nated by the influence of trichotomies. All that can be said is that he shows a strange partiality for them. Take, for instance, the Ad Brutum Orator. A great part of the scheme of the book rests on trifariae divisiones. Thus the perfect orator is he who has these * tria dicendi genera ' in his power, viz. 'humilia subtiliter, modica temperate, magna graviter dicere.' 3 Then he 1 Ztschr. d. Sav.-Stift. xxii, p. 62, note \ It is to be re- gretted that no attempt has hitherto been made to examine the trifariae divisions of Cicero, to trace their source and to estimate their value. I commend the subject to our younger scholars. 8 See e. g. Cic. de Nat. Deor. ii. 30. 75 ; de Off. i. 3. 10 and ii. 9. 31 ; de Orat. i 48. Even the orations are not wholly free from the charge. See e. g. pro Murena 9, with which cf. de Orat. 1. c. The comparison of these two last-cited passages, in so far as they characterize the functions of a jurist, is instructive. 3 Cic. Orat. ad Brut. 20, 100 ; cf. Rhetor, ad Herenn. iv. 8-11 'Sunt igitur tria genera, quae genera nos figuras 68 TEICHOTOMY points out that there are three things that must be looked to by the orator, viz. ' quid, quo loco, et quomodo dicat,' of which the first depends on inventiOj the second on dispositio, and the third on elocutio. 1 Then he makes a tripartite division (tripartUa varietas) of the objects of perfect elo- quence, viz. ' ad probandum, delectandum, flecten- dum,' 2 and then further treating of the ' forma et character orationis ', he makes the ' collocatio verborum in eloquentia' of three different kinds. 3 Leaving Cicero I will take Seneca. Seneca was an out-and-out Stoic, 4 and supplies us with good illustrations of the habit I am discussing. Thus, in the Second Book of his Naturales appellamus, in quibus omiiis oratio non vitiosa consumitur ; unam gravem, alteram mediocrem, tertiam extenuatam vocamus.' 1 Orat. ad Brut. 43-57. Despite his tripartite division ( 43) Cicero, ignoring it, actually makes four parts, 54, 55. Cf. de Off. i. 3. 10. 2 Ibid. 69. 3 Ibid. 149, 175 ; cf. Rhetor, ad Herenn. iv. 12 sq., 27. Other trichotomies that I have noticed in the Rhetor, are i. 8. 12 (' narrationum tria sunt genera ', &c.) ; i. 9. 14 (' tres res convenit habere narrationem ', &c.) ; i. 11. 18 ('constitu- tiones itaque . . . tres sunt conjecturalis, legitima, juridi- cialis ') ; i. 2. 2 ; iv. 25. 35 (cf. ii. 26, 41). * On Seneca's relation to Stoicism see Dill, Roman Society from Nero to M. Aureliits, pp. 306-9, and authorities there cited. IN KOMAN LAW 69 Quaestiones, he deals with a topic which readily lends itself to divisions and subdivisions. He professes to treat of lightning and thunder, and he begins ( 1) by saying of the universe, 'Omnis de universo quaestio in coelestia, sub- limia, terrena dividitur' (meaning astronomy, meteorology, and geography), and he then proceeds to make, in his subsequent chapters, almost every classification of his subject-matter tripartite. This may be seen, for instance, in sections 10, 12, 33, 39, 40, 47, 50. Probably all of them are tradi- tional. Once or twice he expresses himself as dubious about the propriety of a particular divi- sion, but not with much confidence. 1 Most, if not all, of the trichotomies are in any view open to criticism as strained and unscientific. 2 Another writer whose writings seem to show the influence of the ternarius numerus, both as re- gards words and ideas, is Apuleius. As is well known, he was a Phoenician who flourished during the reigns of Antonius Pius and Marcus Aurelius, and was thoroughly imbued with the current ideas of philosophy both of Greece (where 1 See especially Nat. Quaest. ii. 39, 47, 48. 2 See also Seneca, Epist. 75, 9-15, where he says of 'pro- ficientes in philosophia et studio sapientiae ' that * in tres partes, ut quibusdam placet, dividuntur ', &c. 70 TEICHOTOMY he studied as a young man) and of Kome, and borrowed from his predecessors freely. 1 It is needless to insist here upon the influence exercised upon the jurists by the Stoic School (not to speak of other schools) of philosophy; it has been often and abundantly discussed. 2 Such philo- sophers as Panaetius and Posidonius were espe- cially influential. At the present day lawyers are not much influenced, either in theory or practice, by the doctrines of psychology or metaphysics. On the contrary, they as a rule regard abstract speculation in relation to law with suspicion if not dislike. We are living in an age of intense commercial competition, both individual and in- 1 The following passages may be referred to: Apul. de dogm. Plat. i. 584 (' deorum trinas species '), i. 591, ii. 597 (' tria genera ingeniorum '), 606 (' justitiam vero, quod trinis animae regionibus sparsa sit '), iii. 638 ; de Deo Socrat. 664, 684 ; de Mundo, 755 ('tria fata sunt ') ; Apolog. 461, 484; Florid, ad init. ; Metam. iii. 55, iv. 82. 2 Several illustrations of this have been given in the pre- ceding pages. See also Dig. 1. 16. 124, attributed by Cujas (viii, p. 622) to the Stoics, and Dig. xli. 3. 30, where the influence of Stoic principles of realism on the division of things and the law of usucapio is well shown in the tripartite division given by Pomponius. Cf. Seneca, Epist. 102. 6 ; Sokolowski, Philosophie im Privatrecht, i, pp. 48 sq. and 119. Pomponius's three illustrations df corpus ex distantibus, viz. grex, populus, legio, may be compared with Seneca's exercitus, populus, senatus, which Sokolowski apparently overlooks (p. 119, I.e.). IN EOMAN LAW 71 ternational, and empirical rules of practical con- venience govern the development of the law. But far otherwise was it at the close of the Eoman Eepublic and the early period of the Empire. Graecia capta, having no longer any national life and few commercial interests, exerted her still keen intellectual forces in the fields of philosophy and speculation. And with these she dominated the Koman intellect not only in art and philosophy but to a large extent in jurisprudence, which, after the establishment of the pax Romano, under Augustus, became the favourite study of the Eomans and the securest avenue to fame. That Ulpian and Paul, among others, did not escape this influence is not open to doubt. 1 Savigny, in dealing with the tripartite division of pupils into infantes, wfantiae proximi and pubertati proximi (see Inst. iii. 19 $ 9, 10), the infantes being those who have not completed seven years, makes the 1 On the influence of the schools of philosophy generally on the jurists see Pernice, Labeo, i, pp. 30 sq. ; Voigt, Jus Naturak, &c. i, pp. 250 sq. On their influence on the doctrines of property and possession in particular, see Soko- lowski, Philosophic im Privatrecht, vols. i and ii. Puchta (Inst. 102) seems to quite underestimate the Stoic in- fluence, though before his time there was perhaps a tendency to exaggerate it. Marcus Aurelius subsidised chairs at Athens for the four principal schools Platonists, Peripatetics, Stoics, and Epicureans. Dio Cass. Ixxxi. 31. 72 TRICHOTOMY following observations : ; Nun wurde den Bomern eine uralte Lehre griechischer Philosophie be- kannt, welche der Zahl Sieben geheimnissvolle Krafte, und den siebenjahrigen Lebensperioden eine besondere Wichtigkeit beilegte. Diese Lehre kam jenem praktischen Bediirfniss auf die will- kommenste Weise entgegen, und so geschah es, dass die Granze der Kindheit gerade auf das Ende des siebenten Jahres allgemein angesetzt wurde, anstatt dass wohl auch Sechs oder Acht Jahre dafiir angenommen werden konnten.' * On the influence of Greek speculations generally on the jurists of the early Empire, Sokolowski, with much truth and cogency in my opinion, remarks : ' Sicher ist der elementare, produktive Eechtsinstinkt in der Kaiserzeit gesunken, zu- gleich aber uiiter dem Einfluss der griechischen Geistesbildung die Neigung fiir allgemeine Speku- lationen ganz bedeutend gestiegen. Das Kecht tritt aus dem Gebiet der praktischen Bedurfniss- befriedigung eines politisch eminent geschulten Volks in die Welt wissenschaftlicher Gedanken. . . . Der griechische, spekulative Genius unter warf sich im zweiten und dritten Jahrhundert nach Christo das gesamte Geistes- und Sitten- 1 System, iii, p. 32. See also Quinctil, i. 1, 18, and Dig. xxvi. 7, 1 2, commented on by Savigny (1. c.). IN KOMAN-LAW 73 leben, er umspann die einfachen und elemen- taren Lehren Christi mit einer Ftille schon friiher ausgereifter, philosophischer Gedanken, er dureh- drang vielfach auch die schlichten, praktischen Kechtsbegriffe des alien Komertums.' l The Greek Schools of Philosophy also exercised an undoubted influence upon the works of the early Christian writers, similar to what they exercised upon those of the jurists. From the influence of numbers, and of the number 8 in particular, they did not emancipate themselves. It will be found in the works of Augustine, Ter- tullian, and others. 2 Nor can it well be doubted that the tripartite divisions both of the Deity into Father, Son, and Holy Ghost and of man into body, soul, and spirit the soul or psyche being further subdivided by Philo, following Aristotle, into three principles (nutritive, emotional, and 1 Philosophic im Privatrecht, ii, p. 126. 2 See Augustin. Civ. xi, c. 25 (' de tripertita totius philoso- phiae disciplina '), where he says : ' Tria sunt quae in uno quoque homine artifice spectantur . . . natura, doctrina. usus ' ; Augustin. Epist. ad Januarium, ii. 18. 33, where he says : ' Tenarius numerus in multis sacramentis maxime excellit.' Cf. Cassiodor. as cited by Teuffel, Gesch. d. rom. Litt. 483, notes 6, 7, 9, 10, 11 ; Tertull. de Baptismo, VI in fine ; Usener, Ehein. Mus. f. Phil. Iviii, pp. 41 sq. Curious illustrations of the mystic value of the number 3 in theological writings are given by Hugo de Palma, Theo- logia Mystica, ed. de Montes, Amsterdam, 1647. 1211 K 74 TRICHOTOMY rational) 1 were due to that influence. 2 Many other illustrations might easily be given. 3 It may be objected to the foregoing thesis that tripartite classifications of subjects are in them- selves natural and convenient and very common (the latter part of the proposition no one who has been accustomed to listen to sermons will dis- pute), and that there are in the Roman texts many duads and quadrads and other classifi- cations, of which fact also there is abundant evidence. In every system of law, moreover, including our own, there are plenty of tripartite divisions. 4 They assist the memory and are thus an aid to composition. Such objectors must then, 1 Eth. Nic. i. 13. 2 Cf. Plato's division of man's nature into intellectual, appetitive, and passionate (TO flv/xoaSc's), which however is perhaps a natural consequence of his view of his subject- matter. To what confusion of thought and extent of con- troversy the trichotomy of body, soul, and spirit may lead, see J. B. Heard, Tripartite Nature of Man, Edinburgh, 1870. 3 On the Pauline triad of virtues Faith, Hope and Charity see Lobeck, Aglaophanus, p. 388 note ; Epist. St. John, i. 7, 8. 4 Some of them traditional and illogical, e. g. in English law the old divisions of Crimes into (1) treasons, (2) felonies, and (3) misdemeanours (treason being just a felony, though with special rules of procedure), and of Contracts into (1) contracts of record, (2) contracts by specialty, and (3) simple contracts. See Broom, Com. Law, 9th ed., pp. 255-6 ; Blackstone, Commentaries, ii, p. 465 ; Kenny, Outlines of IN KOMAN LAW 75 however, hold that the Koman trichotomies above criticized are either defensible in themselves on grounds of simplicity, convenience, logic, or the like, or that they were made casually, not to say ' perperam et sine ratione '. But this I have shown cannot be maintained. Nor can it be disputed that the traditional dominance of the number 3 was potent at the time of the classical jurists. It is not necessary for me to hold, nor, as I have said, do I hold, that all the various trichotomies of Paul, Ulpian, and others that I have given were deliberately invented by them under the influence of symbolism or the traditional force of numbers. On the contrary it is almost certain that many of them were tralatitious, and it is probable that when the jurists ventured to make divisions of their own they were often less illogical. 1 Gaius, at least, who was not apparently much influenced by Stoic or other philosophy, seems entitled to this credit. And the same credit may doubtless be given to some other jurists. But Ulpian and Paul cannot be acquitted in my opinion of the charge of adopting, and to some extent inventing, more or less con- sciously, symbolic tripartite categories, with the Criminal Law, p. 83 ; Stephen, Hist, of Crim. Law, ii, p. 187. Of. Kussell on Crimes, 6th ed., p. 192. 1 See, e. g., Gai. iv 1. 76 TKICHOTOMY result of obscuring the subject and producing fre- quently fanciful and misleading doctrines. Trichotomy, unlike dichotomy (e.g. A and not A), has no apparent universality. It depends on the subject-matter which is being discussed whether it can in any given case be justified. There is no principle in logic which should, for instance, lead to a given genus being divided into three species rather than any other number ; the special subject-matter must in each case decide what the number of co-ordinate species should be. If my theory be accepted, it will perhaps put an end to the vain attempts that have been made, and are still being made, by commentators on the Eoman law to find reasons to justify classifi- cations which their authors themselves could not have attempted to justify as logical or natural, and to which they, in fact, attached no practical importance. How much labour would have been saved, and may yet be saved, to jurists, philo- sophers, and theologians by a little attention to anthropological research ! Of course, nothing that I have said can materially detract from the merits of the Eoman jurists from their lucidity and logical acumen and power of philosophic analysis to which all who have studied them must ever pay profound reverence. IN EOMAN LAW 77 It merely shows that classification and definition of legal doctrines and rules were not their strong points. 1 They were in fact in these matters the children of their age, and were unable to emanci- pate themselves from the traditional influences of their predecessors and of the schools of philosophy. 1 Savigny, System, ii, Beilage vi, p. 508, observes : l . . . die allermeisten Definitionen der alten Juristen tiberaus mangel- haft sind.' Oxford : Printed at the Clarendon Press by Horace Hart, M.A. CLARENDON PRESS BOOKS LAW Jurisprudence Bentham's Fragment on Government. Edited by F. C. MONTAGUE. 8vo. 7s. 6d. Bentham's Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legisla- tion. Second edition. Crown 8vo. 6s. 6d. Studies in History and Jurisprudence. By the Right Hon. JAMES BRYCE. 1901. Two volumes. 8vo. 1 5s. net. The Elements of Jurisprudence. By T. E. HOLLAND. Eleventh edition. 1910. 8vo. 10s. 6d. net. Elements of Law, considered with reference to Principles of General Jurisprudence. By Sir W. MARKBY, K.C.I.E. Sixth edition revised, 1905. 8vo. 12s. 6d. Roman Law Imperatoris lustiniani Institutionum Libri Quattuor ; with introductions, commentary, and translation, by J. B. MOYLE. Two volumes. 8vo. Vol. I (fourth edition, 1903), 16s. ; Vol. II, Translation (fourth edition, 1906), 6s. The Institutes of Justinian, edited as a recension of the Institutes of Gaius. By T. E. HOLLAND. Second edition. Extra fcap. 8vo. 5s. Select Titles from the Digest of Justinian. By T. E. HOLLAND and C. L. SHADWELL. 8vo. 14s. Also, sold in parts, in paper covers : Part I. Introductory Titles. 2s. 6d. Part II. Family Law. Is. Part III. Property Law. 2s. 6d. Part IV. Law of Obligations. No. 1. 3s. 6d. No. 2. 4s. 6d. Gai Institutionum luris Civilis Commentarii Quattuor: with a translation and commentary by the late E. POSTE. Fourth edition. Revised and enlarged by E. A. WHITTUCK, with an historical introduction by A. H. J. GREENIDGE. 8vo. 16s. net. Institutes of Roman Law, by R. SOHM. Translated by J. C. LEDLIE : with an introductory essay by E. GRUEBER. Third edition. 1907. 8vo. 16s. net. Infamia : its place in Roman Public and Private Law. By A. H. J. GREENIDGE. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Legal Procedure in Cicero's Time. By A. H. J. GREENIDGE. 8vo. 25s. net. The Roman Law of Damage to Property : being a commentatory on the title of the Digest ' Ad Legem Aquiliam ' (ix. 2), with an introduction to the study of the Corpus luris Civilis. By E. GRUEBER. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Contract of Sale in the Civil Law. By J. B. MOYL.E. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Trichotomy in Roman Law. By H. GOUDY. 8vo. 4s. net, The Principles of German Civil Law. By ERNEST J. SCHUSTER. 1907. 8vo. 12s. 6d. net. CLARENDON PRESS BOOKS English Law Principles of the English Law of Contract, and of Agency in its relation to Contract. By Sir W. R. ANSON. Twelfth edition, 1910, revised by M. L. GWYER. 8vo. 10s. net. Law and Custom of the Constitution. By Sir W. R. ANSON. In two volumes. 8vo. Vol. I. Parliament. Fourth edition. 1909. 12s. 6d. net. Vol. II. The Crown. Third edition. Part 1, 1907. 10s.6d.net. Part II, 1908. 8s. 6d. net. Introduction to the History of the Law of Real Property. By Sir K. E. DIGBY. Fifth edition. 8vo. 12s. 6d. Legislative Methods and Forms. By Sir C. P. ILBERT, K.C.S.I. 1901. 8vo. 16s. Modern Land Law. By E. JENKS. 8vo. 15s. Essay on Possession in the Common Law. By Sir F. POLLOCK and Sir R. S. WRIGHT. 8vo. 8s. 6d. Outline of the Law of Property. By T. RALEIGH. 8vo. 7s. 6d. Law in Daily Life. By RUD. VON JHERING. Translated with Notes and Additions by H. GOUDY. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d. net. Cases illustrating the Principles of the Law of Torts, with table of all Cases cited. By F. R. Y. RADCLIFFE and J. C. MILES. 8vo. 1904. 12s. 6d. net. The Management of Private Affairs. By JOSEPH KING, F. T. R. BIGHAM, M. L. GWYER, EDWIN CANNAN, J. S. C. BRIDGE, A. M. LATTER. Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d. net. Calendar of Charters and Rolls, containing those preserved in the Bodleian Library. 8vo. 1 11s. 6d. net. Handbook to the Land- Charters, and other Saxonic Documents. By J. EARLE. Crown 8vo. 16s. Fortescue's Difference between an Absolute and a Limited Monarchy. Text revised and edited, with introduction, etc., by C. PLUMMER. 8vo, leather back. 12s. 6d. net. Villainage in England. By P. VINOGRADOFF. 8vo. 16s. net. Welsh Mediaeval Law : the Laws of Howel the Good. Text, trans- lation, etc., by A. W. WADE EVANS. Crown 8vo. 8s. 6d. net. Constitutional Documents Select Charters and other Illustrations of English Constitutional History, from the earliest times to Edward I. Arranged and edited by W. STUBBS. Eighth edition. 1900. Crown 8vo. 8s. 6d. Select Statutes and other Constitutional Documents, illustrative of the reigns of Elizabeth and James I. Edited by G. W. PROTHERO. Third edition. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. Constitutional Documents of the Puritan Revolution, selected and edited by S. R. GARDINER. Third edition. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. CLARENDON PRESS BOOKS International Law International Law. By W. E. HALL. Sixth edition by J. B. ATLAY. 1909. 8vo. 1 Is. net. Treatise on the Foreign Powers and Jurisdiction of the British Crown. By W. E. HALL. 8vo. 10s. 6d. The European Concert in the Eastern Question, a collection of treaties and other public acts. Edited, with introductions and notes, by T. E. HOLLAND. 1885. 8vo. 12s. 6d. Studies in International Law. ByT. E. HOLLAND. 1898. 8vo. 10s. 6d. The Laws of War on Land. By T. E. HOLLAND. 1908. 8vo. 6s. net. Gentilis Alberici de lure Belli Libri Tres edidit T. E. HOLLAND. 1877. Small quarto, half -morocco. 1 Is. The Law of Nations. By Sir T. Twiss. Part I. In time of peace. New edition, revised and enlarged. 8vo. 15s. Pacific Blockade. By A. E. HOGAN. 1908. 8vo. 6s. net. Colonial and Indian Law The Government of India, being a Digest of the Statute Law relating thereto, with historical introduction and illustrative documents. By Sir C. P. ILBERT, K. C.S.I. Second edition. 1907. 8vo, cloth. 10s. 6d. net. British Rule and Jurisdiction beyond the Sea. By the late Sir H. JENKYNS, K.C.B., with a preface by Sir C. P. ILBERT, and a portrait of the author. 1902. 8vo, leather back. 15s. net. Cornewall-Lewis's Essay on the Government of Dependencies. Edited by Sir C. P. LUCAS, K.C.M.G. 8vo, leather back. 14s. An Introduction to Hindu and Mahommedan Law for the use of students. 1906. By Sir W. MARKBY, K.C.I.E. 6s. net. Land-Revenue and Tenure in British India. By B. H. BADEN- POWELL, C.I.E. With map. Second edition, revised by T. W. HOLDER- NESS, C.S.I. (1907). Crown 8vo. 5s. net. Land-Systems of British India, being a manual of the Land-Tenures, and of the systems of Land-Revenue administration. By the same. Three volumes. 8vo, with map. 3 3s. Anglo-Indian Codes, by WHITLEY STOKES. 8vo. Vol. I. Substantive Law. 1 10s. Vol. II. Adjective Law. 1 15s. 1st supplement, 2s. 6d. 2nd supplement, to 1891, 4s. 6d. In one vol., 6s. 6d. The Indian Evidence Act, with notes by Sir W. MAHKBY, K.C.I.E. 8vo. 3s. 6d. net (published by Mr. Frowde). Corps de Droit Ottoman : un Recueil des Codes, Lois, Reglements, Ordonnances et Actes les plus importants du Droit Inte"rieur, et deludes sur le Droit Coutumier de 1'Empire Ottoman. Par GEORGE YOUNG. 1905. Seven vols. 8vo. Cloth, 4 14s. 6d. net; paper covers, 4 4s. net. Parts I (Vols. I- III) and II (Vols. IV to VII) can be obtained separately; price per part, in cloth, 2 17s. 6d. net, in paper covers, 2 12s. 6d. net. YC 36554 M105768 THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY