'*? UCSB LIBRARY CHRISTIAN ETHICS. BY DB. ADOLF WUTTKE, LATE PBOFESSOB OF THEOLOGY AT HALLE. WITH A SPECIAL PREFACE, BY DR. RIEHM, EDITOR OF THE "STUDIEN UND KBITIKEN." TKANSLATED BY JOHN P. LACROIX. VOLUME I- HISTORY OF ETHICS. EDINBURGH : T. & T. CLARK, GEORGE STREET. MDCCCLXXIII. Entered according to Act of Congress, in the year 1873, by NELSON & PHILLIPS, In the Office of the Librarian of Congress at Washington. LETTER OF AUTHORIZATION. DECLARATION. WE, the representatives of the family of the late Dr. Adolf WuttJce, Professor of Theology at Halle on the Saale, have thankfully accepted the proposition of Professor JOHN P. LACROI^: to translate into English the deceased author's Christliche Bittenlehre (Wiegandt & Grieben, Berlin, 1864-5), and we gladly second the wish of the esteemed translator by expressly and formally authorizing him, on our part, to publish the work in the English language. MRS. PROFESSOR WUTTKE, DR. EDTJARD RIEHM, (as Guardian of the children). HALLE, March 8, 1872. NOTE OF TKANSLATOB. IN my labor upon this translation I have aimed at the truest practical reproduction, sentence by sentence, of the thoughts of the author. This method I deliberately preferred, rather than incur the risk of impairing the clearness of thought by entirely recasting the forms of speech. In a few cases I have employed unusual compounds, rather than resort to para- phrases or to an undue multiplication of subordinate clauses. On the whole, I am persuaded that those who are best ac- quainted with the difficulties of the original will be most indulgent toward the style of the version. This first volume, although only the Introduction to the entire work, is yet a complete whole in itself, viz., a survey of the whole current of the ethical thought of humanity from the earliest dawn of scientific reflection down to the latest results in Christian theology. The motives that led me to undertake the translation have been various. Esteemed teachers exhorted me thereto, as soon as notices of the work began to appear. German scholars spoke to me enthusiastically of its unparalleled excellence. My chief motive, however, has been a com- pound of gratitude and hope, gratitude to the devout thinker whose work had been, to me, the medium of so much spiritual good, and a hope of helping others to the same good. For, in fact, no other human production has lifted, for me, so many vails from shadowy places in Revela- tion and Providence; none has worked so effectually in defin- itively directing my mind and heart toward that Light which stands, serene and ever-brightening, over against the comfortless spectacle of the successive and rapid extinguish- ment of every effort at social reform which does not kindle its torch at the central Source of all light. And no labor VI NOTE OF TRANSLATOR. that I have ever performed has been attended with such a joy- ous consciousness that the very toil itself was self -rewarding. As to the specific merits of the work, I am happy to refer the reader to the considerate words of the distinguished the- ologian of Halle, Dr. Riehm, in the special preface which he has prepared for this translation. I could also, were it desir- able, fill many pages with words of highest praise from the most respectable and the most diverse sources. And the praise is bestowed not only upon its scientific worth, but largely also upon the spirit of its author. All critics accord in testifying that we have to do here with a man singularly endowed with keenness of philosophic insight and with devoutness of Christian faith. Whether, however, there is need here in America where there is so strong a proclivity to run away after every glitter- ing theological or social novelty, and where there are so many evidences that the general consciousness both of preachers and of people is not thoroughly enough grounded upon the central truths of the Gospel of a work such as this (a work which, in so masterly a manner, brings the whole moral life into vital relation to its only possible Source, and which sweeps away so thoroughly every social or religious theory which does not stand the touch-stone of plain Bible-truth), it is for others to judge. We have been led to augur favorably, how- ever, both from our own studies in the field and also" from the expressed views of many of our most progressive teachers of ethics, viz., that there is a loud call for something more solidly philosophical and more thoroughly evangelical than is afforded by our common text-books on Moral Science ;* and we feel pretty confident that few who once drink of the fresh thought- stream here opened will be disposed to dissent from the well- known utterance t of Dr. Hengstenberg, that Wuttke's Ethics ought to have its place in every pastor's library. J. P. L. * See Dr. Warren's Introduction to Vol. II. t See Evangelhche Kirchenzettung, (Berlin), Sept. 4, 1861. SPECIAL PREFACE TO THIS TRANSLATION.' THE author of the work which here appears in English, Dr. Carl Friedrich Adolf Wuttke, has won for himself a disl^n- guished place in the evangelical Church and theology of Ger- many. A few items as to his life and activity, and as to the spirit and character of his endeavors, may serve to call atten- tion to a work which is widely circulated and much read throughout Germany. Born in Breslau, November 10, 1819, in humble life, the young Wuttke obtained his preparatory education under cir- cumstances of great difficulty and self-denial. In 1840 he entered the University of Breslau in view of studying the- ology, but he found very little satisfaction in the theology that was there taught. The superficial Rationalism which then pre- vailed in Breslau violently repelled him, and drove him at once and forever to a position of 'antagonism to this stand-point. As neither his religious nor his scientific wants found satisfaction in his theological teachers, he endeavored to satisfy the latter, at least, by turning- his attention primarily and chit- fly to phi- losophy. To this end he possessed dialectic talents of unu- sual excellence, and he received from the celebrated and, then, fully mature Braniss fruitful inspiration. His academic career he bega.ii in 1848, in Breslau, as Doctor and pritat- docent of philosophy. His preferred field was the Philosophy of Religion. This led him to thorough studies in the history of religions. A fruit of his studies he has embodied in his ''History of Heathenism in respect to religion, knowledge, art, * Dr. Riehm, who has kindly famished me this general preface, and to whom I am indebted for many valuable suggestions in regard to my undertaking, is one of the professors of theology at Halle, and also editor-in-chief of the Studien itnd Kritiken. TR. via SPECIAL PREFACE TO THIS TRANSLATION. Morals and Politics, (Breslau, 1852-53), a work which estab- lished his reputation as a scholar. Utilizing his extensive acquaintance with the historical material, his chief endeavor was to give here a faithful objective presentation of the sub- ject-matter, and to avoid doing it violence by forcing it into harmony with preconceived theories, and his success was so great as to obtain for him the warm recognition, among others, of that master of Indian antiquities, Dr. A. Weber of Berlin. At the same time, however,, he was also able to present the religiose-historical matter in a clear synoptical order, and to elucidate it from higher religioso-philosophical stand-points. The more he pursued his studies in the history and phi- losophy of religions, so much the more fully and renewedly he became convinced that the highest and the only soul-satis- fying knowledge of the truth is to be found only by merging one's self into the Holy Scriptures and into the therein-wit- nessed revelations of the living God; hence he felt himself more and more attracted back to the field of theology. In 1853 he obtained the degree of Licentiate in Theology, and changed his field of instruction from philosophy to that of theology; having been called to Berlin, in November, 1854, to an extraordinary professorship of theology, he found an en- larged and appreciative sphere for the exercise of his gifts. In virtue of his firm and independent nature partly inborn and partly developed in the severe school of experience he felt also a pressing need of a firmly-based construction of his theo- logical views, and of a clear, distinct, and unambiguous ex- pression of the same. This need was in part met by the Lutheran form of doctrine. It is true, he saw very clearly the defects and imperfections which a scientific construction and demonstration of this doctrinal formula bring to light ; taking into consideration, however, its essential features, he found in it the purest and truest didactic presentation of evangelical truth.* To preserve this form of the truth in its main features, * As a Gennan Protestant, Dr. Wuttke had practically only two choices in his Church-relations, namely, between the Lutheran Church and the Reformed or Calvinistic Church. The so-called "United" Church of Prussia has little more than a legal existence, the individual societies having mostly remained essentially Lutheran or Reformed, as before the union. TB. SPECIAL PEEFAGE TO THIS TRANSLATION. IX and by his own deeper study of the Scriptures as well as by earnest systematic thought so to raise it to a new scientific construction that it should express the truth of the Bible in a still richer degree, and that in its form and demonstration it should answer the requirements made upon it by the present stand-point of theology and philosophy, and that it might be raised to a more full development also in fields wherein it had as yet attained only to an imperfect and very inadequate ex- pression, such was the life-task to which Dr. Wuttke felt himself, with ever- deepening conviction, called by God. And this life-task'he endeavored, in the greatest conscientiousness and in the most unwearied and exhausting labor, to fulfill* And the animating spring of his labor was the consciousness so repeatedly expressed by him, that theology is intrusted with the preservation of sacred treasures. Fidelity in preserving the intrusted truth-treasure, such is the animating spirit of his theologico-scieutific labor ; and with this fidelity are connected the limits and imperfections of the same. In this fidelity he was earnestly resolute, even in the face of the coryphei of theological and philosophical speculation, in rejecting all views and thought-constructions which seemed to him foreign to the spirit of the Holy Scriptures, however much they might seem to be characterized by profundity or by loftiness of thought, and however much they might bedazzle by brilliant ingenuity and by their artful application to Biblical ideas. This fidelity made him a decided opponent of all efforts which he regarded as bent on seeking an accommodation between faith and unbelief. In this fidelity he deliberately consented to sacrifice the favor and approbation of the majority of his con- temporaries ; and he neglected no opportunity, where he felt the duty of champidning the pure evangelical truth and of assailing perversions and misrepresentations of the same, man- fully and with open visor to enter the lists, and to fight it out with keen weapons and without respect of persons. It is true he has, in his earnestness-, not always awarded due honor to the views of the ideally-inclined theologians, , nor to the results of historical and critical Scripture-examination. For his own person, however, he was, in this work, never concerned, nor for the interests of any party, but solely and simply for Christian truth and for the kingdom of God. X SPECIAL PREFACE TO THIS TRANSLATION. In this sense and spirit he exercised his office of theological teacher in Berlin. One can well imagine how glad the late Dr. Hengstenberg was to have found in him so able a co- laborer, and also that he became warmly and intimately at- tached to his younger colleague.* But also the other mem- bers of the Berlin faculty, though in part of different churchly and theological tendencies, fully appreciated his scientific ability and his faithful and fruitful academic activity; and they expressed their esteem publicly by conferring upon him, in 1860, the doctorate of theology. In the autumn of 1861 he accepted a call to an ordinary professorship of systematic theology in our university at Halle. Although, as the representative of a strictly churchly theology, he stood here somewhat isolated, still the positive evangelical tendency (a tendency based on faith in the reve- lations and redemptive acts of God as witnessed in the Script- ures) of the other members of .the faculty (and among them the universally known and revered Dr. Tholuck} afforded a broad and firm basis for a richly productive official co-opera- tion. Highly esteemed by his colleagues for his straight-for- wardness, reliableness, punctuality, and conscientious fidel- ity in all his official duties, he ^xercised, here, his calling as teacher in a circle of hearers, at first relatively narrow, but which soon grew visibly larger, especially in the case of his lectures on Christian^ ethics ; and he had the joy of seeing the seed, he had sown, spring up and bear fruit in many youth- ful hearts, until on the 12th of April, 1870, after a brief sickness, it pleased the Lord whom he served- to permit him, unexpectedly early, to pass from faith to sight. Along-side of his more specific professional activity, Dr. Wuttke was always ready to serve the church by special ad- dresses, in ecclesiastical and other assemblies, on weighty questions of the day. Quite a number of these addresses have been published in Hengstenberg's ' ' Evangelical Church Journal." To one of them, which was delivered in 1858, at a church-diet at Hamburg,- is due the preparation of his widely-popular and excellent work, "The German Popular * Dr. Wuttke, however, was free from the ultra-confessionalism of Hengstenberg ; he even favored the " Union." See Neue evangelischt Kirchenzeitung of May 7, 1870. TR. SPECIAL PREFACE TO THIS TRANSLATION. XI Superstition of the Present," which appeared in 1860 in its first, and in 1869 in a new and enlarged second, edition. This work combines laborious selection with a lucid grouping of the abundant material, and is inspired by a vital interest for the health of the German national life and for the healing of its defects by the divine power of the Gospel. For the judgment and appreciation of some portions of the work here presented to the public, it will not be out of place to observe that the author took a lively and active part also in the political life of the nation. As early as during the revolutionary storm of 1848 he defended for a while, as editor of a conservative journal in KSnigsberg, the cause of legal order and of the government. And during his activity among us, though in other respects living in the greatest seclu- sion, he frequently appeared publicly, in political meetings in Halle and in other towns of the province of Saxony, as the spokesman of the constitutional party ; and once he took part also in the labors of the national diet, to which the confidence of his fellow-citizens had called him. The work here given to the English-reading public, Chris~ tian Ethics, which appeared in 1861-'62 in its first, and in 1864-'65 in its second, revised and enlarged, edition, is Dr. Wuttke's only considerable theological work. He has here entered upon a field, the cultivation of which, his special life- task as above indicated, must have, pressed upon him with very great urgency. Upon no other field had the scientific treatment of the theology he represented, remained to such a degree imperfect and unsatisfactory. Although Christian ethics, after the precedent of Danoeus on the Calvinistic side, had been raised by Calixtus to the dignity of an independent theological science, nevertheless the prevalent one-sidedly dogmatic interest hindered and prevented its thorough de- velopment. And when finally, sinfce the last decade of the last century, a more lively scientific interest was turned to the subject, then, unfortunately, Christian ethics became in- volved in an almost slavish dependence. upon the philosophic- al systems of a Kant, a Fichte, a Fries, a Hegel, and a Herbart, as they successively rose and followed each other. From this cramping pupilage, ethics was indeed emancipated by the Reconstructor of the collective body of German theology, Xli SPECIAL PREFACE TO THIS TRANSLATION. Schleiermacher, and also radically renovated from the basis of the specifically Christiarily-etliical principle. But in Schleier- macher, as well as in Rothe, Christian ethics appeared rather in the garb of theologico-philosophical speculation ; it was not based directly upon the Holy Scriptures ; on the contrary, these highly deserving men endeavored to be just to the positive Biblical basis of evangelical Protestantism by undertaking to reconstruct the contents of the Holy Scriptures directly out of the Christian consciousness^ in a word, these ethical systems stood in no manner of close connection with ecclesiastical dogmatics. On the other hand, Harless had produced an ethics based directly upon, and derived from, the Scriptures ; but in his method he had disdained the learned structure and the dialectical procedure of modern science. WuttTce was the first theologian who made the attempt, upon the foundation* of the Lutheran dogmatical ground-views as enriched and vitalized by personal self-immersion in the study of the Scriptures, to carry out, by means of the dialec-^ tical method, (which theology had assumed at the time of the supremacy of philosophy), a strictly scientific, organic struct- ure of Christian ethics, which should embody in itself the fruits of precedent labors upon this field, and also polemic- ally elucidate its relation to the various other ethical sys- tems. In this work, however, he makes no other use of this dialectical method than simply to purify theological ethics from all elements foreign or hostile to the Biblico-ecclesias- tical ground-thoughts, and to bring these ground-thoughts to more complete expression by process of inner self-develop- ment. Hence the great majority of churchly-minded theolo- gians could, with great reason, welcome in Wuttke the, until then, lacking scientific standard-bearer upon the field of * That in the construction of his ethical system, Dr. Wuttke did not allow the Lutheran symbols to construe the Bible, but on the contrary measured them by the Bible, and freely criticized them where found defective, we have both his own reiterated avowal (as where, 80, he declares it his purpose to write, not on ethics of this or that Church, but a Christian Ethics ; and where, in his preface, p. 4, he declares the governing principles of his labors to be ''honest loyalty to the Gos- pel ") ; and also his actual contrasting of the Lutheran and the Reformed ground-views (see 87), and his ample admission that the Lutheran view needs to be complemented. TB. SPECIAL PREFACE TO THIS TRANSLATION. Xlll ethics ; and consequently his work met with an astonishingly rapid circulation and a thankful reception. But also those who as the writer of this preface * stand in many respects upon the ground of other theological convictions, and who do not fully agree with many views and judgments expressed in the work, have every reason highly to prize tfiis system of Ethics, and for the following reasons: because of its firm Biblical foundation, because of its sharp and clear vindica- tion and presentation of the ethical ground-thoughts of the Holy Scriptures against, and in the face of, various wide- spread errors and prevalent thought-currents of the day, because of its thoroughly carried-out aim, in connection with all the rigor of a scientific method, to present in broad and clear light the sublime directness and simplicity of the truth of the Gospel, because of the richness of the subject-matter which it presents, and to mention especially one single feature because of the exceedingly valuable, and hitherto almost entirely lacking, history both of the science of ethics and also of the ethical consciousness itself. I doubt not, therefore, that this work, will meet with a heai-ty welome also in America and in England, and that too in theological circles which, while not sharing the special ecclesiastical views of the author, will yet not fail worthily to appreciate his conscientious fidelity to Scripture-truth and the scientific significancy of his labors ; and I feel confident that the work will prove serviceable in the promotion of a healthy and practically-fruitful theological knowledge. DK. EDUAKB RIEHM:, Professor, in ordinary, of Theology at Halle. HALLE, March 1A, 1872. * I am indebted to Dr. P. Schafffor the following: " Dr. Riehm is a liberal Unionist of the critical school of Hupfeld, his predecessor." TB. AUTHOR'S PREFACE TO THE FIEST EDITION THE theology of the nineteenth century has aimed at giving special prominence to the ethical phase of Christianity ; and yet, strangely enough, the scientific treatment of Christian ethics has shown, as com- pared to the other branches of theology, a far infe- rior productiveness, and in fact a degree of barren- ness. This phenomenon is not explainable from any precedent over-fruitfulness. nor from any un- questioning satisfaction with any already-attained relatively- definitive perfection of the science, nor from the imposing pre-eminence of any exceptionally great author; on the contrary, every competent theologian knows perfectly well that no other branch of theology is so far from having reached any, even relatively, settled completeness and generally-ac- cepted form and contents, as precisely the science of ethics. Even the very idea, contents, and bounda- ries of ethics, are as yet in many respects so unsettled that the different presentations of the science have often only very remote resemblances to each other; 2 A.UTHOK'S PEEFACE TO FIKST EDITION. and there are some recent theologians who look upon the ethical field as something like an ownerless pri- meval forest wherein they are at liberty to roam at simple discretion and to give free scope to all sorts of pet speculations. We would of course not wish to shut the field of theology against philosophical thought; on the contrary, we regard its scientific completion as possible only on condition of its per- meation with mature philosophical thought-labor. In view, however, of the not only manifold, but also (in very deep-reaching and essential ground-princi- ples) self-contradicting philosophical systems of the time, we could not advise Theology that guardian of sacred treasures to cast itself away, in character- less self-forgetfulness, into the arms of the first tran- siently-shining philosophical system, and to seek its glory only in a pliable self-conformity to the rapidly- passing Protean forms of the philosophies of the day. Remarkable indeed, though not precisely very praise- worthy, is the metamorphic capability of those theo- logians who have kept pace in their theology with the entire history of philosophy from Kant down to Hegel, afad have furnished the public at each decade with an entirely different form of theology. It is not scientific truthfulness to attempt violently to force together irreconcilable elements ; and it is high time that the day were past when men presume to introduce Spinozistic and other kindred Hegelian AUTHOR'S PREFACE TO FIRST EDITION. 3 conceptions into Christian ethics as its own contents proper. We fully recognize the high services of precisely the latest forms of philosophy, for the sci- ence of ethics ; but we must guard against allowing theological ethics, as conscious of its divinely re- vealed contents, and as basing itself upon the holy Scriptures, to be cramped and thrown into the back- ground by these philosophical systems. Precisely the most recent developments in this field justify us in entertaining, at this point, a prudent distrust. The manner in which some have introduced philosoph- ical, or a so-called " theological, speculation " into the field of Christian ethics, reminds one only too much of the feats of the suitors of Penelope in the house of Ulysses, who presume to cast their footstools at the head of the returning master, and yet prove incapable even of bending the bow of the hero, to say nothing of shooting through the twelvefold target. What we attempt in the present work is neither speculative ethics nor yet Biblical ethics in the sense of a purely exegetico-historical science, but, in fact, a system of theological ethics based on the substance and spirit of the Bible, and con- structed into a scientific form, not by the help of a philosophy foreign to that spirit, but by the inner self-development of the spirit itself. Whether we have properly comprehended this spirit, and whether we have faithfully learned from the general 2 4 AUTHOR'S PREFACE TO FIRST EDITION". history of science, including also philosophy, others will have to judge; this much, however, we know, that we have endeavored to acquire such learning only in honest loyalty to the Gospel. And the fact that we have omitted to employ many technical forms that have been imposed upon this science by ingenious authors, will, we hope, be regarded, by those who have grown familiar with said forms, as at least an indication of a sincere endeavor on our part to avoid breaking the impression of simple evan- gelical truth by any element foreign to the spirit of the Scriptures, however much it may enjoy the pres- tige of profundity, and however artfully it may have been fitted upon Christian ideas. BERLIN, Dec. 31, 1860. AUTHOR'S PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION. WITHIN" a surprisingly brief period a new edition of this System of Ethics has become necessary. To many critics of the work we feel ourselves thankfully indebted ; of others, however, we regret to have to say that, instead of scientific earnestness, they have manifested only passionate hostility. It is true, we have gone at our work with honesty aad plainness of speech, and have touched somewhat ungently upon certain sore places in the more recent forms of theology ; and the tone of ill-will in which the opposers have indulged would seem to indicate that the right spot has been probed ; and we are in fact cheerfully ready to be subjected to the most searching criticism. There is an immense difference, however, between actual confutation and unworthy abuse. Some critics have charged this work with being an "attentat" against the "inalienable" con- 6 AUTHOR'S PREFACE TO SECOND EDITION. quests of modern science ; this sounds almost as badly as when, in times past, a certain class of the- ologians spoke of "attentats" against the teachings of the Church and against the symbolical books. There is, in- fact, in the field of contemporary un- belief both an "orthodoxy" which does not stand a whit behind the intolerance of former and much- despised ages in its hereticating of dissenters, and an authority-faith in the so-called " heroes " of con- temporary science, which exalts the preventions of the said science to infallibility in exact proportion as it is zealous against a real faith in the Scriptures, and tramples their claims into the dust. Just such a .deference to writers who let only their own light shine, (a light kindled not at the divine light, but only at the faintly-shining wisdom of the anti-Chris- tian world,) still weighs down like an Alp upon the theology of the present day, and especially upon ethics ; and to do battle against a spiritual despotism of this character, must be to take a step in the direction of true progress. Incredulity constitutes, in fact, in our day no slight recommendation ; will the public, therefore, not let us enjoy the advantage of a little incredulity as to the Apostolical calling AUTHOR'S PREFACE TO SECOND EDITION. 7 of certain recent authors who have forced the Pan- theism of Spinoza into the doctrines of Christianity? We are not unaware, however, that only that one can hope for favor and popularity with the multitude of to-day, who makes amends for his faith in the living Christ by strewing incense upon the altars of the divinities of recent literature, who fuses to- gether the Apostolical doctrines with the unqaestion- ingly infallible-assumed " results of modern culture," in a word, who selects the golden middle-way between simple evangelical faith and God-denying unbelief: the tints just now in vogue are indefinite and indesignable. We frankly confess that, in scien- tific respects, we can less readily come to an under- standing with this nondescript olla-podrida theology than with those who make a clean sweep of Chris- tianity at once. Upon firm earth one can walk erect, in water one can swim ; but in a miry marsh, which mingles earth and water together, one can neither walk nor swim. We must submit to let those who imagine that they stand or swim upon the heights of " modern " culture look disdainfully down upon us, and reproach us with not being abreast with the times ; let them do that to which they are called ; 8 AUTHOR'S PREFACE TO SECOND EDITION. we, however, have a sure prophetic word, and we think we do well to give heed to it as to a light that shines in a dark place, until the day dawn and the morning-star arise in the hearts of all, [2 Peter i, 19] ; and we feel confident that in so doing we have chosen the "good part, which will not be taken from us" when the specious fruits of the un-Christian culture of the day shall be swept away, without leaving a trace, by the streams of still newer progress. To those to whom appreciation for recent science is synonymous with an unconditional homage to every pretentiously-rising system, we must be content to appear as non-appreciative; meantime, however, may we not suggest that these gentlemen would do well to come to an understanding among themselves as to precisely which of the more recent and vio- lently inter-contradictory systems represents the real progress proper, and as to how long it will do so, before we be peremptorily required to disregard the exhortation of the Holy One, to "hold that fast which thou hast, that no man take thy crown " [Rev. iii, 11]. We regard it as the first scientific duty of a true truth-seeker not to suffer himself to be captivated by the flickering glare of great names AUTHOR'S PREFACE TO SECOND EDITION. 9 and by the sham-gold of pretended latest discoveries, and not to let himself be intoxicated and carried away by the indiscriminate applause of the multi- tude. We greatly rejoice to see that precisely the most recent productions upon the field of ethics (Harless, Schmid, Palmer) give proof of evangelical soundness, and we shall anxiously await to see whether the rapidly-erring and deteriorating "the- ology of progress " will not, in its turn, enter upon this field, whether Rothe, who (encouraged and urged on by the well-calculated applause of this party) shows as yet no signs of hesitation to do service in the ranks of the sympathizers with Strauss and Renan, will not make up his mind to turn to the service of sound words, or whether in the interest of an erroneous system he will drive even still deeper the wounds which he has already inflicted upon evangelical faith, to which at bottom his heart belongs. . HALLE, August, 1864. CONTENTS. PAOK INTRODUCTION. I. THE IDEA OF ETHICS, AND THE POSITION OF THIS SCIENCE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE IN GENERAL 13 1. THE IDEA 13 2. PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS 16 3. THEOLOGICAL ETHICS 21 II. THE SCIENTIFIC TREATMENT OF ETHICS, 4 27 III. THE HISTORY OF ETHICS AND OF THE MORAL CONSCIOUSNESS IN GENERAL, 5 35 A. THE MORAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND THE ETHICS OF HEA- THEN NATIONS, 6 37 7. THE UNHISTORICAL NATIONS; THE CHINESE 43 8. THE INDIANS 47 9. THE EGYPTIANS AND THE SEMITIC NATIONS 54 10. THE PERSIANS 58 1 1. THE GREEKS 62 1 2. SOCRATES 69 13. THE CYNICS AND THE CYRENAICS 72 14-15. PLATO 75 16-21. ARISTOTLE ' 02 22-25. THE EPICUREANS AND THE STOICS 126 26. THE SKEPTICS AND THE NEO-PLATONISTS ; THE ROMANS 144 B. OLD TESTAMENT AND JEWISH ETHICS. 27. THE CANON OF THE OLD^TESTAMENT 151 28. THE APOCRYPHAL BOOKS, THE TALMUD. 169 [ISLAMISM] 171 C. CHRISTIAN ETHICS, 29 173 12 CONTENTS. PAQB 1. THE ANCIENT CHURCH, 30, 31 180 2. THE MIDDLE AGES. 32 199 33, 34. SCHOLASTICS AND CASUISTICS. 200 35. THE MYSTICS AND THE PHOTO- REFORMERS 223 3. THE EPOCH OP REFORM, 36 233 37. THE EVANGELICAL ETHICS OF THE SIXTEENTH AND SEVENTEENTH CENTURIES 2i:5 38, 39. ROMISH ETHICS 255, OT3 40. PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS BEFORE KANT 217 41. DEISTIC AND NATURALISTIC ETHICS 301 42. THE EVANGELICAL ETHICS OF THE EIGHTEENTH CEV- TDRY 324 43. KANT ,. 327 44. FICHTE 338 45. SCHELLING ; JACOBI 341 46. HEGEL AND HIS SCHOOL 345 47. THE MOST RECENT PHILOSOPHY 355 48. THE EVANGELICAL ETHICS OF THE NINETEENTH CEN- TURY 359 49. ROMISH ETHICS . .375 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. HSTTKODUCTIOlsr. I. IDEA OF ETHICS, AND THE POSITION OF THIS SCIENCE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE IN GENERAL. SECTION I. ETHICS, as belonging to the sphere both of philoso- phy and of theology, is the science of the moral, and hence Christian ethics is the science of Christian mor- als. But the moral lies in the sphere of the freedom of rational creatures, as in contrast to mere nature- objects. Man, as a rational being, has the end of his life, not as one realizing itself in him spontaneously and with unconditional necessity, but, on the contrary, he has it primarily only ideally, in his rational con- sciousness, so that he cannot attain to it by a mere unconscious letting himself alone, but only by a per- sonally and freely-willed life-activity ; but also, for that very reason, he can fail of it by his own fault ; and the essence of this life-development of man, as relating to the realizing of his rational life-purpose, is the moral / that is, when normal, the morally-good, and when guiltily-perverted, the morally-<5w7. So much merely preliminarily ; the more complete demonstra- tion can be given only further on. The sphere of freedom is that of the moral ; whatever is moral is essentially free, and whatever is free is moral. There is, indeed, an immorally- 14 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 1. incurred unfreeclom, but even this unfreedom is essentially different from the unfreedom of nature. He who, in contradic- tion to the Christian as well as to the universally-human con- sciousness, denies moral freedom in general, and places even man's moral activity into the sphere of unconditional necessity, may indeed give a description of the seemingly-moral, but he cannot place upon man a moral requirement; in the presence of the "must" the "should" disappears. Such a denier would at least have to regard the contradictory and almost universal con- sciousness of freedom as also posited by unconditional necessity thus surrendering all right to assail the same. We may there- fore here preliminarily presuppose it as the utterance of the general human consciousness when not perverted by one-sided theories, that the moral lies neither in the sphere of cognition nor of natural necessity, but in the sphere of the freedom of the rational will. Where there is no freedom of will, there we speak neither of the morally-good nor of the morally-evil. Moral willing, however, is not of a blind, fortuitous, but of a rational, character; that is, it wills a rational something, something willed by God, and that too in a rational manner or, indeed, it wills it not ; but also this non- willing, that is, the morally- evil, relates, though negatively, to a rational end. In the Scriptures, the ethical phase of Christian doctrine is designated as " the knowledge of God's will in all wisdom and spiritual understanding " (Col. i, 9) ; that is, of that which God "requires" of us (Deut. x, 12; comp. Phil, iv, 8). Of other definitions of ethics we will mention but the more important. Unquestionably all such are to be rejected as express merely an outward collection of single moral thoughts, as, e. g., "an ordered digest of rules by which man, and, more specifically, a Chris- tian, is to shape his life;" this would not be a science, but only a collection of material for a science ; moreover, rules are only one phase of the moral thought, for rules must have a basis, an end, and an inner logical unity, all of which lies outside of this definition. Many writers designate ethics as the description of a morally normal development. But, properly speaking, only that can be described which is real ; not, however, that which simply ought, but is not necessitated, to become real. Even the describing of the person of Christ as the ideal of the moral, gives only a part of Christian ethics, inasmuch as Christ could 1.] DEFINITIONS OF ETHICS. 15 not, in his actual life, represent all the phases of the moral. And besides, ethics has not merely to do with the morally- normal, but it has also to treat of sin and the contest with it as an actual power ; and, moreover, it has not merely to describe, but also to prove and to establish. The majority of theological moralists present at once the def- inition of Christian ethics ; but this more restricted notion can- not be understood without the more comprehensive notion of ethics in general. The declaration (Harless and others) that ethics is the theoretical presentation of the Christianly-normal life-course, or the development-history of man as redeemed by Christ, is both too narrow and too broad at the same time: too narrow, inasmuch as ethics must unquestionably speak also of the non-normal life-course, and that, too, not merely incidentally and introductorily, but as of one of its essential elements; and too broad, because, in fact, many things belong to such a life-course which belong not to the sphere of the moral, but to the objective workings of divine grace upon the moral subject. Such a def- inition is rather that of the order of Christian salvation, which, however, is not wholly embraced in the notion of the moral. It is true, Christian ethics must take into consideration the work- ings of divine grace, but only, however, as its presupposition ; the becoming seized upon by the influence of divine grace leads, indeed, to morality, but lies not itself in the moral sphere. Ac- cording to Schleierm acker, Christian ethics is " the presentation of communion With God as conditioned by communion with Christ, the Redeemer, in so far as this communion with God is the motive of all the actions of the Christian, or the description of that manner of action which springs from the domination of the Christianly-determined self-consciousness;"* this, however, is "two mutually complementing definitions, each of which ex- presses by itself only one phase of ethics. As to the name applied to the science, the German expression " Sittenlehre," usual since the time of Mosheim, is ambiguous, being capable of being understood as the doctrine of customs instead of the doctrine of the moral. The term ethics is the most ancient, as dating from Aristotle himself; r)6of- radically related to edof, from the root ew, "to set" and "to sit," signifies in Homer the seat, the dwelling-place, the home, and hence, at * Christl. Sitte, pp. 32, 33. 16 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 2. a later period, that which has become the fixed definite home of the spirit that wherein the spirit feels itself at home as in its own peculiar element, and hence manner, primarily in the sense of habit ; that is, a manner of action as having become second nature. In this sense the word f/dij occurs also in the New Testament (1 Cor. xv, 33.) But the signification of the word advances, further, to that of the moral proper, as objective- grown custom, which presents itself to the individual with the authority of law ; i)6of is therefore a spiritual power to which the individual subordinates himself, as in contradistinction to the rude lawlessness of man as uncultured and savage, and which, in so far as it is no longer a power foreign and opposed to man, appears as character.* The Romans used generally, for this idea, the term mores, and hence Cicero and Seneca speak of a philosophia moralis. In Germany this science was formerly called " Moral " theologia s. philosophia moralis and frequently also theologia s. philosophia practica. But after the word " Mor- al " had been appropriated by the advocates of deistic illumin- ism, and degraded into the most spiritless superficiality, the term became involved in such prejudicial associations that later writers preferred to avoid it, and resorted again to the German term used by Mosheim, or to the one originally used by Aristotle. SECTION II. As a philosophical science, ethics forms a part of the philosophy of the spirit, has as presuppositions speculative theology and psychology, and stands in the closest relation to the science of history as the objective realization of the moral life. As standing within the science of spirit, it presents, as in contrast to knowledge, the active phase of the rational spirit-life, whereby man, as having come to rational self-con- sciousness, makes into reality that which exists in him primarily only as an idea,- makes his spiritually- rational nature as existing objectively to him into a nature freely-willed and posited by himself. *Aristot., Eth. Nic., i, 13. 2.] SCOPE OF ETHICS. 17 A.11 philosophy has to do essentially with three objects : the thoughts of God, of nature, and of the human spirit. Ethics, as belonging to the third sphere, has, co-ordinate to itself within this sphere, the science of psychology as treating of the nature of the individual mind and of its development, and the science of history as portraying the development of the collective spirit ; it is in some sense the unity of the two ; it is psychology, in that it presents, in fact, the highest form of the soul-life, the ration- ally-free life ; and it is history, in that it embraces man not as isolated, but as an organic member of the whole, and considers his activity as directed toward the rational shaping of collective humanity. Ethics gives to history its rational goal; and all morality has the perfect shaping of universal history as its ulti- mate end. A real understanding of history is not possible with- out ethics ; universal history is the realization of the moral the good and also the evil within humanity ; hence history, the actual contents of which lie of course outside of the sphere of purely philosophical knowledge, is an important teacher of morality teaching by example in sacred history, and by cau- tion and warning in profane. The position here assigned to philosophical ethics takes the definition of that science in its widest sense, and embraces also right and art. While the view which merges morality essen- tially into either right or art is very one-sided and a mistaking of the nature of the moral in general, it would not be less erro- neous entirely to shut out the moral from these two spheres, and to place it simply along-side of them ; the moral is rather, as the superior element, above them, and right and art have truth only in so far as they are special realization-forms of the moral ; there is, in truth, no immoral right and no immoral beauty, al- though by sinful man the wrong is often regarded as right, and the un-beautiful as beautiful. Schleiermacher, in his Philosophical Ethics, gives a definition of philosophical ethics, based on the views of Fichte and Schel- ling, which entirely differs from the usual one. In assuming two chief sciences, that of nature and that of reason, whereof each may be treated either empirically or speculatively, according as the reality or the essence of the object is more directly taken into view, he obtains four sciences in all. The empirical science of nature is natural history; the speculative science of nature is 18 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 2. physics; the empirical science of reason is history; the specu- lative science of reason is ethics. Hence ethics "is the knowl- edge of the essence of reason," and stands in the same relation to history as speculation to experience, and is hence essentially the philosophy of history. Under such conditions it would be more correct to call ethics the philosophy of the spirit; but Schleiermacher evades this, no less manifest than necessary, consequence ; logic and psychology belong, according to him, not to ethics, for psychology corresponds to natural history, and hence is " the empirical knowledge of the activity of the spirit- ual ;" and logic belongs, empirically-treated, to psychology, and, speculatively-treated, to physics.* Though, by means of this strange conception of logic and psychology, the immeasurable sphere of ethics as fixed by the first definition is somewhat re- duced, still there yet remains for it a very unusually wide field, and it embraces, with the exception of physics, the whole of philosophical theology and of the philosophy of history ; and as natural history and physics have like extent of field, differing only in point of view taken, so the fields of empirical history and of ethics are also co-extensive, and ethics is nothing other than the speculative consideration of history. " History is the example-book of ethics, and ethics is the form-book of history ;" but history is, when so viewed, every thing which is not mere nature ; and as, in the highest instance, nature and reason are es- sentially identical, nature being reason, and reason nature, hence " in the highest view of the matter ethics is physics and physics ethics," whereas in a lower view of the matter ethics is condi- tioned, as to contents and form, by physics, and physics by ethics. It is evident at once that according to these definitions ethics is something entirely other than what is usually understood there- by in the scientific world; and it involves not a little courage to undertake to justify the applying of the term ethics to this extensive field. This scientifically-unjustifiable extension of the field of ethics has occasioned much confusion ; and Rothe's "Theological Ethics" suffers also from this lack of limitation, whereas Schleiermacher himself carefully avoided applying to theological ethics this philosophical conception, which in fact sprang more from an ingenious thought-play than from an inner consequential development of the ground-principle. Indeed, * System der EtJMc, edited by Schweizer, 1835, 55, tqq., 60, 61, 87. 2.] SCHLEIERMACHER'S VIEW. 19 even in his philosophical ethics, Schleiermacher very soon intro- duces a much narrower notion, without any logical justification thereto in his system. Thus ethics is, presently, made to ap- pear as " the scientific presentation of human action" which manifestly cannot be regarded as identical with the notion of the " speculative knowledge of the essence of reason." But also this new declaration is much too indefinite ; it is not action in general, but moral action, that belongs to ethics. Should we thus find this narrower definition too comprehensive still, then we are relieved by the declaration that ethics is the " specula- tive knowledge of the collective activity of reason upon nature," and are at once thrown into a field so narrow as to be obliged to exclude from ethics a very essential, nay, the most essential, part of this science. For all morality is not embraced in an activity of reason upon nature; in however wide a sense "na- ture " be taken, still it always stands over against reason as of a different character, is that which, in empirical respects, consti- tutes the field of natural science, natural history, etc. The moral cultivation of the heart humility, truthfulness, the moral disposition in general, the whole sphere of the purely spiritual life belongs not at all to this activity upon nature. On the other hand, this definition is also much too comprehensive, in- asmuch as there may be also an extra-moral and an immoral interpenetration of reason and nature, and an immoral activity of reason upon nature ; but should it be said that this, now, would not be the true moral reason, then this would vir- tually imply that the moral is to be sought elsewhere than in this activity of reason upon nature, would place it in reason as such. As, in the view of Schleiermacher, ethics is only the speculative reverse-side of history, hence he requires, consequen- tially enough, that it be presented essentially historically. " The style of ethics is the historical; for only where manifestation and law are given as the same is the view taken a scientific one. Hence the style can be neither imperative nor consultative. The form of ethics is the development of a theoretical view. The formula of the ' should ' is entirely inadmissible, as this formula rests upon an antagonism to the law, whereas it is the part of science to present this antagonism as a mere appearance." This position, (harmonizing with the view expressed in his " Dis- courses on Religion,") which, from the stand-point of Panthe- 3 20 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 2. istic determinism, is quite consequential, we simply mention in passing, in order to explain, in some manner, this position of ethics in Schleiermacher. Even as the other speculative science, namely, physics, does not present what should be, but what really is and must be, so also Pantheistic ethics has to do only with the " is" and the "must be," but not with the " should ;" all reality is here rational ; all disagreement with the law is mere appearance ; there exists nothing else than what must be ; hence ethics has simply to present for the reason-life the laws, even as physics, for the nature-life, and is just as certain of the agree- ment of reality with these laws as astronomy is certain of the occurrence of a calculated eclipse of the moon. On the con- trary, so soon as by the admission of moral will-freedom, even the possibility of an antagonism of moral reality to the moral law is conceded, ethics presents itself at once with the should; for the moral law has unconditional validity, whether man really fulfills it or not. Ethics is only in so far purely historical as perfect morality is also personal reality ; hence Christian ethics bears, indeed, essentially also a historical character, because Christ is, for it, the moral ideal ; for others, however, it bears the form of the " should." Pantheistic ethics makes collective humanity the real expression of the moral idea, makes human- ity its Christ. And that Schleiermacher's philosophical ethics is by no means free of a Pantheistic character, is undeniable. Hegel conceives of ethics as one of the phases of the Philoso- phy of the Spirit, and more specifically as the sphere of the objective spirit in contradistinction to that of the subjective, which embraces anthropology, the phenomenology of the spirit, and psychology. The spirit, as having come to itself and be- come free, realizes itself, in that, as free rational will, it posits itself outwardly, forms for itself a world corresponding to itself, which i*the expression of the spirit. This objective reality of the free spirit, which becomes for the individual subject an objective power whereby the subject is determined in his free- dom, and which consequently is to be recognized by the indi- vidual, is, as of a universal character, for the individual, law. Hence this will of objective rationality is right, which becomes for the individual, duty. But in that right does not remain a merely objective power, but makes itself immanent in the indi- vidual subject, so that the individual will becomes an expres- 3.] HEGEL'S VIEW. 21 sion of the general will, and right finds in the subject free recognition becomes subjective disposition so the notion of right transforms itself into that of morality, which in its turn by not remaining merely subjective, but by forming for itself in the spheres of the family, of civil society, and of the state, a complete rational reality, wherein the free spirit finds its self- created and perfectly self-answering home exalts itself to eus- tomariness* Hegel styles this development of the objective spirit, not ethics to which he surely had a higher right than Schleiermacher for his much more comprehensive notion, (inas- much as the ethical is the highest phase of this development,) but the philosophy of right. The entire contents of this phi- losophy of right fall indeed into the sphere of ethics in the wider sense of the term, though the entire contents of Christian ethics do not fall into the sphere of this philosophy of right. Ethics has, according to the Christian view, not merely to create an objective world of rationality, but also to make the moral per- sonality itself a perfect expression of rationality ; hence many things which Hegel treats of in the philosophy of the subjective spirit belong to ethics ; and this is doubtless the principal reason why Hegel (much more cautious and less arbitrary in his notions and their definitions than Schleiermacher) designates the science of the objective spirit, not ethics, but the doctrine of right. SECTION III. As a theological science ethics forms a part of systematic theology, in which it stands in closest connection with dogmatics, and has dogmatics as its immediate presupposition. The two sciences belong together in organic unity, and cannot be entirely separated from each other. Dogmatics presents the essence, the contents, and the object of the religious consciousness ; ethics presents this consciousness as a power determining the human will. Dogmatics em- braces the good as reality, that is, as it, through God, is, or becomes, or, by the fault of moral creatures, is *PMlosophie des Geistet, 481, sqq. ; RecTitsphilosophie, p. 22, sqq. 22 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 3. not ; ethics, on the contrary, embraces this good as a task for the free, and hence moral, activity of man ; that is, as, on the basis of the religious consciousness, it should become in reality. Dogmatics presents real- ity, in the sphere of the divine and religious, for man, as an object of the religious consciousness ; on the contrary, ethics presents the religions consciousness as a power creating a. spiritual reality ; that is, it pre- sents a reality as going out from man as a religious subject. Hence dogmatics bears predominantly an ob- jective character relates toknowledge; and ethics pre- dominantly a subjective character relates to loilling. Theoretical theology in contradistinction to practical theol- ogy, -which presents the ecclesiastico-pastoral application of the subject-matter given in theoretical theology is partly historical and partly systematic. Ethics has indeed a historical founda- tion, and stands in constant relation to history, but in itself it is no more history than is dogmatics ; exegesis and Church his- tory furnish only the material for ethics. The separating of ethics from dogmatics, with which it was formerly, and up to the time of Danseus and (^alixtus, intimately involved, is diffi- cult, and, in fact, not without violence, entirely practicable; both sciences reach over into each other like two intersecting circles, and have, under all circumstances, some territory in com- mon ; the general foundations of ethics are based in the corre- sponding thoughts of dogmatics. The usual and quite natural statement, that dogmatics shows what we should believe, and ethics what we should do, is only proximatively correct, and is inadequate ; for also the moral laws and maxims are an object of faith ; and " what we should be- lieve " bears, even in the correct expression itself, the character of a moral requirement. Believing, itself, is of a moral character; ethics cannot confine itself to the mere outward action, but must have to do also with the inward, with the disposition. Accord- ing to Harless, dogmatics presents the essence of the objective ground of salvation, and of the objective mediation of salvation, whereas ethics presents the subjective realization of the life-goal 3.] RELATION TO DOGMATICS- 23 as established by Christ; dogmatics presents the objective sal- vation-power as determining the Christian ; ethics presents the personal life-movement of the Christian toward his highest life- goal ; ethics gives answer to the question, What thinkest thou of Christ ? dogmatics to the question, What thinkest thou of the right manner of the Christian's life in the world ? This declaration limits the two sciences quite too much : dogmatics must in fact speak also of man and of the order of salvation ; and ethics must speak also of the objective law and of sin. According to Schleiermacher's theological ethics, ethics pre- sents the Christian self-consciousness in its relative motion, while dogmatics presents the same in its relative rest ; dogmatics an- swers the question, What must fo, because the religious heart- state it? ethics the question, What must become out of the religious self-consciousness and through the same, because the religious self-consciousness is? This antithesis is not entirely to the point, for, on the one hand, dogmatics treats not merely of what is, but also of what becomes, as, e. g., in the doctrines of regeneration and of eschatology ; as, on the other hand, ethics treats not only of what becomes, but necessarily also of what morally is, as well normally as abnormally. Virtue is not a mere becoming, but an ens, as Schleiermacher himself admits ; the good when attained, certainly does not for that reason cease to be an object of ethics. The antithesis of motion and rest is in this sphere utterly unapt. Schleiermacher presents the mat- ter also thus : the dogmatical propositions are those which express the relation of man to God as an interest, namely, as, under its manifold modifications, it passes over into conceptions; whereas the ethical propositions express the same thing, but as an inner impetus, op/z^, an impulse, which goes out into a cycle of actions. But also this is not quite correct; for also ethics expresses a relation of man to God in conceptions or thoughts, which do not per se include in themselves an inner impetus, as, e. g., in the questions as to the moral essence of man, as to the moral idea per se, and in the entire doctrine of goods. The difficulty in defining the difference lies less in the general antithesis than rather in those points where both sciences must treat of the same topics. The doctrines of the moral essence of man, of the divine law, of sin, of sanctification, of the Church, belong strictly to dogmatics ; but ethics must necessarily treat 24 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 3. also of all these things, so that it might after all seem advisable, in order to avoid repetitions, to unite both into one science again, as was formerly the case, and as has been done recently by Nitzsch, and in part also by Sartorius. But the separate treatment of ethics rests in fact, aside from weighty practical reasons, upon a wide-reaching inner difference ; and those points which fall within the scope of both sciences, are nevertheless treated, in each, from a different stand-point, and in a very dif- ferent manner. Both of them present a life of the spirit of God or of man but dogmatics views this life as an objective fact, while ethics views it as a task for the free activity of the rational subject; hence dogmatics has essentially an objective and real character, while ethics has a subjective and ideal one. Dog- matics has constantly to do with an object transcending the individual, with God, with Christ, with man in general; ethics has to do primarily always with the individual moral person, and with the totality only in so far as it rests upon the moral action of the individual personality. What dogmatics teaches relates not to me as this single person, but as a human being in general ; - what ethics teaches concerns me precisely as a person. Dogmatics treats of sin per se, as an objective something and as an historical fact ; ethics treats of the same as a personal malady and as guilt. Dogmatics treats of the kingdom of God as an objective organism ; ethics treats of the same in so far as the moral subject is an organic member thereof. Dogmatics treats of sanctification as a manifestation-form of the kingdom of God ; ethics treats of the same as a subjective life-manifestation of the person. "The kingdom of God comes indeed without our prayer" that is dogmatical; "but we ask in this prayer that it come also to us" this is ethical. Dogmatics sketches the physical chart of the kingdom of God ; ethics sketches the ways and dwelling-places therein. The object of dogmatics is abso- lutely independent of the freedom of the individual subject is either eternal or an historical fact is in nowise within the power of man ; the object of ethics is, in its reality, absolutely depend- ent on the free resolution of the subject is per se a pure idea, the realization of which is a requirement upon the free activity of man. Dogmatics presents that which is, or was, or will be; ethics presents that which should be or should not be ; hence dogmatics presents always an unconditionally-secured result, 3.] ROTHE'S VIEW. 25 either of an accomplished or of a destined movement ; ethics, however, presents a task, the accomplishing of which is condi- tioned on the free assent of man. The contents of dogmatics relate essentially to knowledge and faith; those of ethics to volition. Dogmatics wills that man accept the truth ; ethics wills that he do it. Hence man's relation to dogmatics is rather passive womanly ; and to ethics rather active manly. In the sphere of dogmatics there is a revelation of the divine for man ; in that of ethics a revelation of the divine through man, who has received this element into himself. In dogmatics the move- ment of the divine goes out from the divine middle-point toward the created periphery ; in ethics, on the contrary, it goes back from the periphery toward God as the middle-point. In dog- matics God is conceived of as the ground, as the point of departure ; in ethics as the goal of the life-movement ; in dog- matics man's relation is more epic; in ethics more dramatic. Dogmatics is predominantly ontological and historical ; ethics is predominantly teleological. Both sciences treat of man and his activity dogmatics, however, in so far as man is an object for God ; ethics, in so far as God is an aimed-at object for man. Dogmatics is related to ethics, as psychology to pedagogy, as physiology to dietetics, as botany to horticulture, as animal sensation to motion.* From all this it is apparent that ethics has dogmatics neces- sarily as its presupposition that it is the second and not the first. Ethics is faith as having become a subjective life-power faith in so far as it is an operative force. The popular in- struction in the Scriptures implies, throughout, this relative position of dogmatics and ethics, in that it presents the moral command after the subject-matter of faith, and bases it thereon; thus already in the Mosaic legislation (Exod. xx, 2, sqq.), and thus again in most of the New Testament epistles. (Comp. also Matt, vii, 21, 24, sqq. ; John xiii, 17 ; xv, 1, sqq. ; 1 Cor. xiii, 2 ; Col. i, 4-10 ; 2 Tim. iii, 14, sqq. ; Titus i, 1 ; James i, 22, sqq. ; ii, 14, sqq. ; 1 John ii, 4.) Deviating entirely from this view, BotJie places ethics in a wholly different field from dogmatics. In his view ethics be- longs to speculative, and dogmatics to historical, theology ; they do not stand along-side of each other, do not run parallel to each * Comp. Palmer: Moral, 1864, p. 21, sqq. 26 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 3. other, but belong to entirely different forms of theology. The difference of the two sciences lies not in their respective objects, for these objects are in fact essentially the same, but in the manner of their scientific treatment. Dogmatics is the science of dogmas, that is, of the ecclesiastically-authorized articles of faith, and hence has an empirically-given historical object, and is therefore essentially historical, and not at all speculative; speculative theology is, on the contrary, the presupposition of dogmatics. But ethics has nothing whatever to do with eccle- siastical doctrines, but must be treated purely speculatively, and is, as a speculative science, a presupposition of dogmatics. The theology of the evangelical Church has had from the very be- ginning, in the introduction of moral theology, no intention of creating a second science along-side of dogmatics, but has tended, though without being clearly conscious of it, toward a specula- tive theology ; and this science would necessarily lead out beyond the hitherto-observed ecclesiastical rut would progressively metamorphose the dogmas.* This view, constituting one of the many eccentricities of the Rothean theology, is utterly without sufficient ground. It is entirely arbitrary to place speculative theology along-side of dogmatics, and to declare ethics as be- longing exclusively to the former. Both sciences admit of being treated purely theologically or purely specnlatively, though in- deed all their contents cannot be embraced speculatively ; and with the same right whereby the speculative doctrine of God and of the world is excluded from dogmatics, may also the speculative portions of ethics be excluded from this science, and ethics be, then, declared as a purely empirical science. A large portion of ethics proper lies without the scope of a purely spec- ulative treatment, as is in fact sufficiently evinced by the third part of Rothe's ethics. It may indeed be questioned whether speculation is admissible at all in theology ; if it is, however, once admitted, then it is quite as much in place in dogmatics as in ethics as indeed not an insignificant portion of the Rothean ethics is nothing other than speculative dogmatics ; and there is no manner of justification for degrading dogmatics, as in con- trast to the historical development of the science, into a merely dogmatico-historical statement of the doctrines of the Church. . * Ethik, i, 88, tqg. All references to Rothe are to the first edition of his Ethik. 4.] THREE FORMS OF ETHICS. 27 And in that Rothe regards the dogmatical field as not at all bordering upon the ethical, he obtains full liberty to extend im- measurably the boundaries of ethics, so that this science thus receives a compass elsewhere unparalleled, even in Schleier- macher's philosophical system. Not merely does Rothe preface his ethics with a thorough presentation of the whole of specula- tive theology by way of introduction (in which connection he reaches far over, and not any too aptly, into the field of natural philosophy), but also he receives into ethics itself many entirely foreign subjects, e. g., eschatology. Moreover, also the facts of redemption through Christ are presupposed in this ethics, as a Christian one, not however as furnished by dogmatics, but by the immediate religious consciousness. Under such circum- stances it seems more than arbitrary to declare the scientific presentation of this consciousness, not as the scientific presup- position, but as a sequence of ethics. H. SCIENTIFIC TREATMENT OF ETHICS. SECTION IV, OF the three possible methods of presenting ethics, the empirical, the philosophical, and the theological, the first and most ancient is to be regarded as the mere fore'-court to the science itself. And philosoph- ical ethics, as resting upon the inner necessity of rational thinking, can never, even when it is inspired by a Christian spirit, entirely assume the place of theological ethics, and displace the latter as a lower stage of the science ; rather can it only be the scien- tific presupposition and support of the same, without, however, taking up into itself its actual collective .contents; for theological ethics bears in its founda- tion and essence predominantly an historical character < has for its source the historical revelation, and for 28 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [4. its essential contents the (not philosophically neces- sary) thoughts of the actual existence of sin and of the collective history of salvation, whereof the cen- tral point is the historical Christ (who is at the same time the perfect ideal of the moral), and it treats also of the circumstances of humanity and of individual man, as having become real within the scope of Chris- tian history, which also, as the results of free action, are not to be regarded as philosophically necessary. A merely empirical ethics, furnishing only a series of observa- tions and rules, as with the Chinese, the Indians, the older Grecian sages, and also to a large extent inside of the scope of Christian history, is only a collection of material for scientific ethics, but not ethics itself. In the sphere of science we have to do only with the antithesis of philosophical and theological ethics, in the place of which, however, we may not, as Schleier- macher does,* substitute the antithesis of Christian and philo- sophical ethics. Over against Christian ethics stands, not philosophical, but non-Christian ethics; also a philosophical ethics may be Christian, and a Christian ethics philosophical ; a believing Christian will in fact never otherwise philosophize than in a Christian spirit. The antithesis between philosophical and theological ethics is in itself simple and clear ; for philosophical ethics, only that is valid which is developed from the per se necessary thought, with inner necessity ; it presents the moral as a pure revelation of reason ; theological ethics, on the contrary, conceives it as a revelation of faith in the personal God and in the historical Christ as an expression of obedience to the revealed will of God ; hence between the two methods of presentation there is in fact not merely an antithesis of method and source, but also of compass. Theological ethics, embracing also the sphere of the historical facts of free will-determination, transcends the limits of philosophical ethics. The two could only then be per- fectly co-extensive when the sphere of moral freedom should be merged into that of unconditional necessity ; that is, when the * Christl. Sitte, p. 24. 4.] THEOLOGICAL ETHICS. 29 rational ground and presupposition of the ethical itself should be denied. The ethical thoughts which relate to the realized free acts of man and of Christ can be treated of in philosophical ethics only hypothetically, so that philosophy shall apply the results obtained in the sphere of pure thought to the, not phil- osophically, but historico-empirically ascertained conditions; that is, not as pure but, in some sense, as mixed philosophy. But if also the historical facts of Christianity are to be taken up into philosophical ethics, as Palmer assumes,* then its difference from theological ethics is at least, not to be placed in the fact that the latter bases itself upon Scripture ; for indeed philosophy cannot come at these facts otherwise than from the Scriptures, and is then in fact no longer purely philosophical. While purely philosophical ethics can develop only the general moral ideas, but not their application to definite historically- arisen relations, on the other hand, a purely theological ethics, as absolutely excluding all philosophical treatment, is defective, at least, in scientific respects. Theological ethics can appropri- ate to itself philosophy, and it is all the more scientific the more it does this ; but it cannot take philosophy as its exclusive ground and source without ceasing to be theological. Hence theolog- ical ethics is, in respect to extent of contents and to the means at its disposal, richer than purely philosophical ethics. The highest perfection of Christian ethics is a vital union of the phil- osophical and the theological manner of treatment, namely, in that the ideas given in the moral reason itself are treated and speculatively developed as such, and receive from Christian rev- elation their religious confirmation ; while, on the other hand, the actual truths lying in the sphere of the free activity of man himself are taken up from revelation and from historical expe- rience. Such a presentation of ethics preserves its Christianly- theological character by the fact that, in view of the constantly- renewed alternation of philosophical systems, and of their not unfrequently weighty and essential mutual contradictions, it does not make the validity of the firmly-established truths of revelation dependent on their agreement with a particular phil- osophical system, but, on the contrary, makes the acceptance of philosophical thoughts and of their sequences dependent on their harmonizing with the certain truths of revelation. If this * Moral, p. 19. 30 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 4. relation is otherwise understood, then it is in fact no longer a theological, but a philosophical, system. This antithesis between philosophical and theological ethics is entirely rejected by Rothe, in that he presents a theological ethics which is essentially speculative, and in that he definitely distinguishes theological speculation from philosophical, and re- quires of theological ethics that it must, as a science, be also speculative, whereas dogmatics cannot in the nature of things be such. Every speculation begins with a proto-datum, philo- sophical speculation with the self-consciousness. But this self- consciousness is not mere self-consciousness, but is at the same time in some manner a determined one, is also a God-conscious- ness; the religious subject recognizes his self-consciousness not as an absolutely pure one, but as always at the same time affect- ed by an objective determinateness, namely, the religious. Man is never otherwise conscious of himself than as being conscious at the same time also of his relation to God. This point may, says Rothe, be in itself controverted, but in the sphere of piety, , that is, in the theological sphere, it is not controverted : " we deny to no one the right to question the reality of piety itself, but with impiety we have, as a matter of principle, nothing to do ; there can be a system of theology only on the presupposi- tion of piety ; for all who are impious our system of speculation has no validity, and, as related to them, we must continue in error." According to this, there are two kinds of speculation, a religious and a philosophical ; the latter has its point of de- parture in simple self-consciousness, the former in the pious self- consciousness ; philosophical speculation conceives the "All" through the idea of the ego, theological speculation through the idea of God, but both are d priori ; hence theological specula- tion is theosophy ; it begins with the idea of God, with which idea philosophical speculation ends; the evidence is the same in both. Speculative theology must be essentially different for every peculiar form of piety, inasmuch as the starting-point, namely, the peculiarly-determined pious consciousness, is differ- ent. Hence there is also a peculiarly Chnstianly- speculative theology, and likewise for every Church a special one, and hence also a special evangelico-Christi&n theology; and this special speculative theology has in fact validity only for this particular Church is for the others without significancy. This theolog- 4,] ROTHE'S METHOD. 31 ical speculation, however, is not in any way bound by the dog- mas of the Church in which it originates, but is independent of them knows itself as co-etaneous with them ; nay, it must in its every nature be Jieterodax ; its purpose is in fact to develop the consciousness of the Church still further, and to reconstruct the existing dogmatical definition?. In the circle of theological sciences speculation occupies the first and highest place. The difference between theological and philosophical ethics becomes, now, perfectly plain. Both are speculative ; but philosophical ethics proceeds from the moral consciousness purely as such ; whereas theological ethics proceeds from the same as it exists in the Christian individual belonging to a particular Christian Church, that is, as a peculiarly-determined religious conscious- ness, and from the historically-given ideal of morality in the person of Christ. This view appears to us entirely erroneous. We cannot possi- bly admit any other than a purely philosophical speculation, at least as of a scientific character. In the first place it is incor- rect, in point of fact, that philosophical speculation always proceeds from self-consciousness as in contradistinction to theo- logical speculation, which is made to proceed from the God- consciousness. Spinoza starts directly from the idea of God, and his philosophy will surely not be called a theological spec- ulation; in like manner also Schelling. Hegel begins with the idea of pure being; and this is certainly also not identical with self-consciousness. Theological speculation, Rothe holds, differs only in its beginning, from philosophical, in that this beginning is, in it, somewhat more determined and more rich in contents, namely, as being already a religiously-determined self-conscious- ness. This is the view of Schleiermacher, who also proceeds from the religiously-determined self-consciousness; however, Schleiermacher does not undertake to base thereon a system of speculation, but simply a theological description of the pious conditions of the soul, and to argue toward their presupposi- tions, which in fact cannot, in any sense, be called speculation. Rothe herein less consequential than Schleiermacher goes beyond him in two respects : first, in that he carries the relig- ious detenninateness, the self-consciousness, even into the con- fessional phase ; and, secondly, in that he undertakes to make this purely empirical fact the foundation of a system of specu- 32 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 4. lation. The original self-consciousness upon which Rothe bases speculative theology, and more specifically ethics, is not merely religiously determined in general (as, e. g., with Schleiermacher, a feeling of absolute dependence), but also Christianly-relig- iously, nay, even evangelically-Christianly, etc., and only on the basis of such a quite specific determinedness is, in his view, a theological speculation possible. This, however, is, properly speaking, not a theological speculation, but a Christian, a Prot- estant, a Lutheran, or a Reformed speculation, and has in fact validity only for this special ecclesiastical circle ; others, belong- ing to another Church, may construct their own peculiar specu- lations with the speculations of others they have no concern, nor others with theirs ; and yet all this is assumed to be not merely science, but in fact speculative science. We can find in it, however, only arbitrary assumption, and can recognize such products neither as speculative nor as scientific, neither as Chris- tian nor as evangelical. In the first place, a real science, and hence above all a true speculation, cannot rest upon a merely fortuitous ground, but only upon an absolutely certain one. A speculation which concerns itself not as to whether its starting- point, its foundation, is certain and true, is manifestly worthless. Now the pretended theological speculation of Rothe bases itself upon an entirely fortuitously-determined religious consciousness, without inquiring as to its legitimacy, and then speculates there- upon unsuspectingly, further. Again, as the starting-point of this speculation is of a fortuitously-determined character, hence it can never have any validity save for the definite and limited circle of persons who in fact chance to recognize this starting- point, has, in fact, no general significancy, as indeed Rothe him- self expressly admits ; and hence there is absolutely no possibility of harmony between the speculative theologians of different Churches ; they must simply let each other alone, and deliver themselves in monologues; and he who speculates from the Protestant consciousness must renounce all hope that a Roman Catholic Christian may understand him, and in any degree enter, into his line of thought for he cannot do so. But this is a positive contradiction not merely to all speculation, but in fact to all science ; nay, to the very nature of truth in general, and to morality itself. Truth and every science claims to be its expression can never be particular, but necessarily claims vnir 4.] ROT11E CRITICISED. 33 versal validity ; every real science purposes to convince all men who are rational and at all capable of scientific thought; hence to renounce all hope of convincing other men, for the reason that they chance to find themselves otherwise confessionally- determined, would be positively immoral. No real science in general is at liberty to construct itself upon a fortuitously-given basis, and to regard other equally fortuitous bases as equally valid and unassailable. I cannot, without treason to the truth, speculate evangelically-Cliristiauly simply because I find myself in my earlier religious self-consciousness evangelically-Chris- tianly determined, but only for the reason that, for convincing grounds, I have recognized this evangelically-Christian conscious- ness as per se true, as universally valid truth, and which there- fore excludes, as erroneous, every contradictory view. And for the simple reason that the truth, in its very idea and essence, can and may never be merely subjective, but must have objective and universal validity, and because all men should come to a knowledge of the truth (1 Tim. ii, 4), I absolutely dare not con- struct a system of speculation which, on principle, excludes the hope of persuading other persons of different confessions, which purposes to have for such no convincing power, and does not regard them as called equally with me to recognize the truth, which as truth must be absolutely valid for them also. Without a firm and absolutely verified basis there can be no science. A speculation upon a chance, fortuitous basis is idle play without purpose and without worth. There would, in fact, be as m:my mutually-excluding and equally-entitled speculations as there are such chance presuppositions; and what would be the sig- nificancy of a science which aims not at convincing those in error, but only at furnishing an interesting entertainment for the already convinced ? If the assumed foundation is not to be itself an object of a preliminary scientific examination, then in fact any and every one would be fully entitled to say : I find myself not merely so or so religiously, but also so or so morally, determined, I find in my moral self-consciousness this particu- lar desire and this particular aversion, and on the basis of this determinedness I propose to construct a system of speculative ethics! The distinction between philosophical and theological speculation in Rothe's sense would in fact be simply the dis- tinction between science and unscientific arbitrariness. We 34 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 4. fully admit that only a moral spirit caji truly speculate upon the moral, and only a Christianly-pious spirit upon religion ; but that a person is moral or pious is only an individual fact, but not a scientific basis of a system, is a moral presupposition, but not a material principle of the speculation itself; piety is only the subjective condition, the impulse toward and the power for speculation, but not the scientific foundation thereof. The strange contradiction, that this speculation, though proceeding from a determined ecclesiastical consciousness as the unassaila- ble and unquestionable basis, yet at the same time claims to be entitled to pass out beyond the ecclesiastical consciousness, and even sets up heterodoxy as one of its requirements (a require- ment which Rothe himself meets in a high degree), we need not here further elucidate. Rothe presents theological speculation as co-etaneous, along- side of philosophical. Now, however, if, as he expressly affirms, philosophical speculation in proceeding in its development nec- essarily arrives at the idea of God, and there ends, that is, pre- cisely at the point where theological speculation begins, then, in fact, speculation may, from this idea of God as obtained in a purely scientific manner, simply advance further, so that conse- quently we now have a theological speculation resting not upon a fortuitous and empirical presupposition, but upon a scientific result, to which the one assumed by Rothe bears only a rela- tion of premature over-haste. The entire distinction between theological and philosophical speculation, we must consequently declare as scientifically unfounded ; and we cannot, with Rothe, look upon the difference between philosophical and theological ethics as the 1 difference between a speculation without presup- positions and a speculation with presuppositions, but only as the difference between a speculative and a non-speculative ethics, or an ethics resting essentially on history. Purely philosophical ethics knows nothing of Christ, of redemption, nor even of sin as a reality, and hence cannot possibly answer the full idea of a Christian ethics, although it may and should, in that which it is competent to embrace, be of a very Christian character: and as the entire moral life of the Christian rests upon redemption and spiritual regeneration, hence there is not a single point in this life, where a purely philosophical ethics could suffice. Hence the view of Schleiermucher, that Christian and philosophical 5.] METHOD OF THE AUTHOR. 35 ethics are of exactly of the same compass, we must regard as incorrect.* In his Philosophical Ethics he himself expressly de- clares that the notion of evil has no place in it, but is only obtained from the experience of real life ; but in Christian ethics this notion is an essentially co-deter mining element of the whole.! Theological and philosophical ethics do not mutually exclude each other, but stand in intimate connection, and may go hand in hand ; we must admit both of them, each in its own field, and each with the task of combining the other as much as pos- sible in itself. But for each of the two manners of treatment, we must lay claim to universal validity. Whether we have recognized a truth philosophically or theologically, we regard this much as settled, that it is a truth not merely for us Protest- ant or Roman Christians, but for all men who seek truth at all ; and those who do not admit it, we can regard only as in error. This is not intolerance, but simple fidelity to the truth ; every truth is, in this sense, intolerant, claims the right to be accepted of all men. Ethics is frequently so treated that philosophical ethics, as pure, precedes, and Christian ethics as applied ethics, follows. This is not correct ; Christian ethics is not a mere application of philosophical, but has, in so far as it rests on history, an essentially other character, and other ground-thoughts peculiar to itself. We purpose here to present a System of Christian ethics, which, for the reason that it is to embrace all the phases of the Christianly-moral, must be essentially theological; but in the inner organizing and in the developing of the ground- thoughts, philosophical considerations must furnish the deeper scientific foundation. HI. HISTORY OF ETHICS AND OF THE MORAL CON- SCIOUSNESS IN GENERAL, SECTION V. CHRISTIAN ethics cannot be understood without its history, nor the latter without the history of the sys- tems lying anterior to and outside of Christianity. * Christl. Sitte, JSeil, p. 4. t Ibid., pp. 35, 36. 4 36 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 5. But the history of ethics presupposes a knowledge of the historical development of the moral consciousness in general, whereof ethics proper is simply the scien- tific fruit. The mistakes committed in a large portion of the field of more recent ethics, spring largely from non-attention to the his- tory of this science ; and yet no other theological science has so long and rich a history, and so many relations to the history of the human mind anterior to and outside of Christianity, as, in fact, this very one ; Greek philosophy has had, upon the devel- opment of Christian ethics, a wide-reaching influence. But the history of ethics cannot be separated from the history of the moral spirit in general, out of which ethics sprang, and of which it is simply the scientific form ; also the moral consciousness it- self has a history, the knowledge of which is of much higher importance than that of the history of mere ethics. Not every moral consciousness has produced an ethical system, for only the more gifted nations have risen to science at all, and ethics is one of the most difficult ; but the moral consciousness of a people, even though not developed into a scientific form, is to be looked upon as the historical basis for another higher and ultimately scientific national consciousness. Even as botany considers the germination and foliation no less than the blos- soms and fruit, as the history of religious doctrines presupposes the history of the religious^ life, as the history of philosophy pre- supposes and develops further the history of civilization, so also the history of ethics cannot be given without, at the same time, taking into consideration the history of the moral consciousness itself; the ethical thoughts of Plato and Aristotle are not to be understood merely from themselves, but largely only in the light of the moral spirit of the Greeks in general. The history of ethics itself,, though frequently touched upon, has not as yet been sufficiently presented. The most complete work is that of Stdudlin .* u History of the Ethics of Jesus," 1799-1823, 4 vols., of which the work, "History of Christian Morals since the Revival of the Sciences," which appeared as early as 1808, is to be regarded as a continuation; and to it is to be added the same author's " History of Moral Philosophy," 1822 (and, as a short compendium, the "History of Philosoph- 6.] HISTORIES OF ETHICS. 37 ical, Hebrew, and Christian Ethics," 1816). The rich body of matter scattered through these works, is much diluted and not always reliable, and is constructed into no vital unity. The superficial Rationalistic stand-point precludes a proper under- standing whether of philosophical or of theological ethics. It is stated as a high merit of the ethics of Jesus, that, in it, are combined the " better elements of the Platonic and Stoic sys- tems;" the portraiture of the "wise Teacher" of morals, Jesus, is about as insipid as well possible. Rousseau's " excellent " moral discussions are lauded to the skies, while Luther is treated as a person of narrow prejudice; the doctrine of the inspiration of the Scriptures is repeatedly declared as dangerous to moral- ity. The "History of Moral Philosophy" and several minor treatises on the history of special ethical subjects (the oath, marriage, the conscience) are very superficial and inaccurate. De Wette wrote a " Christian Ethics," 1819 ; (more briefly pre- sented in his " Compendium of Christian Ethics," 1833, in which the history of ethics constitutes far more than half of the whole book ; the first work, because of the negligent printing, is almost useless for unprofessional persons, and is very dependent on Staudlin, even to his typographical errors, though in particular parts surpassing him). (Meiner's "History of Ethics," 1800, utterly worthless. Marheineke's " History of Christian Ethics," etc., 1806, only a fragment.) E. Feuerlein's " Ethics of Chris- tianity in its Historical Chief-Forms," 1855, furnishes only un- equal and often unclear or inadequate outlines ; the same author published a " Philosophical Ethics in its Historical Chief- Forms," 1856-59. Neander's "History of Christian Ethics," 1864, enters also upon Greek ethics, though here from a some- what antiquated stand-point, and is somewhat ununiform, break- ing off the historical development by an unhappy classification, and furnishing rather single points than a connected pres- entation. A. MORAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND ETHICS OF HEA- THEN NATIONS. SECTION VI. The most of historical heathen nations have indeed collections of ethical life-rules, based almost always 38 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 6. upon religion, but before the golden age of Greek philosophy they had no ethics proper. The ground- character of all heathen ethical consciousness and of heathen ethics is, that the starting-point and the goal of the moral is not an infinite spirit, but either the impersonal nature-entity, or a merely individually- personal being. The starting-point is not the infinite God, and the goal is not the perfection of the moral personality in a kingdom of God as resting upon the moral perfection of the individual person, and in the communion of the person with the infinite personality of God, but it is always merely a limited something, either a merely earthly civic perfection with the rejec- tion of a trans-mundane goal (the Chinese), or the giving-up of personal existence altogether (the In- dians), or a merely individual perfection irrespective of the idea of a kingdom of God embracing the indi- vidual personality as a vital member (the Egyptians, Persians, Greeks, and Germans). There is through- out a lack of the knowledge of true moral freedom; either it is rejected on principle, or it is ascribed only to a few specially-gifted ones, while the rest of man- kind are, as barbarians, incapable of any moral free- dom and perfection. Hence there is, further, a general lack of a knowledge of humanity as called, in its total- ity, to the accomplishing of a moral task. It is uni- formly only one people, or an aristocratic class of a people, that is morally active ; the slave is incapable of true morality. But where humanity itself is regarded as called to morality with the Buddhists there the moral task is an essentially negating one, is directed to the annihilating of personal existence. There is throughout a lack of the knowledge of the moral depravity of the natural man, and hence of the 6.] ESSENCE OF HEATHENISM. 39 necessity of a spiritual new-birth ; morality is not so much a struggle, as rather a simple development. There is indeed a consciousness of immoral conditions of humanity, yea, of a natural unaptness for the good ; but these conditions are almost always attributed to mere civic and individual degeneracy, and this unapt- ness is confined to barbarians and slaves. And the idea of the highest good is embraced either merely negatively, or is referred to earthly weal, or is left entirely in doubt, at best is sought in merely indi- vidual perfection. The heathen moral consciousness can be understood, evidently, only in the light of the religious consciousness upon which it always rests. That, of the majority of heathen nations, we possess only loosely-connected moral precepts and observations, moral adages and practical life-rules, but not ethical systems proper, is no obstacle to our knowledge of their moral conscious- ness, inasmuch as systems always bear in fact traces of the sub- jective character of their authors, whereas, the popular collec- tions in question, based, for the most part, on divine authority, are an objective unclouded expression of the consciousness dominant in a people. It is the essence of heathenism to possess the idea of God only under some form of limitation, to conceive of God as a being in some degree limited ;* and to this corresponds also the moral consciousness. Where God is conceived of as an unspiritual nature-being, there morality bears essentially the character of un-freedom, as it were of impersonality, is either a mechanical adapting of self to universal nature, an absolutely goal-less passive subordinating of self to the ever-uniform unchangeable order of the world (China), or a subordinating of the personal human spirit to the divine being conceived of as nature, with which the free personality is in essential contradiction (India). Wliere God, however, is conceived of as a limited individual spirit, and then consequentially as plurality, there the personal human spirit stands not in perfect moral dependence upon Him, * See the author's OescTi. d. Heidentums, i, 11 sqq. 40 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 6. but is relatively co-ordinate with Him, has not God's will as its unconditional law ; the foundation of the moral becomes predominantly subjective and unsettled ; the self-love and the self-seeking pride of the strong subject appears as the legitimate chief-motive of the moral life (West-Asia and Europe). With the prevalence of such views the goal of moral effort, the highest good, can also be embraced only as a limited some- thing. Among the naturalistic nations, the Chinese and the Indians, this goal has no positive contents at all, for the personal spirit as placed under the dominion of an impersonal nature- power cannot aim to attain to any thing positive which did not already exist; its goal can only be the greatest possible self- denial of the personal spirit as over against nature. In China the moral spirit can attain to nothing which has not already always existed by nature and hence with necessity ; it behooves not to create a spiritual, moral kingdom, but to uphold the eternal kingdom of necessarily-determined order as already ex- isting by nature without any personal act, to subordinate to, and keep in passive harmony with, it, one's own worthless indi- vidual existence. In India, with the Brahmins as well as with the Buddhists, where the consciousness of the personal spirit has awakened to a much higher validity, moral effort assumes a truly tragic character, in that the total, violent contradiction of the personal spirit to the personality-overwhelming divine nature-entity comes to consciousness. The ultimate goal of the moral spirit is here not only not a positive entity, nor indeed even the upholding of an eternally-uniform world-order, but the passing away of personal existence into the general indetermi- nate nature-existence ; the highest good is complete self-annihi- lation through moral effort. With the Occidental Indo-Germanic nations the personal spirit is indeed no longer merged into the impersonal nature-existence, for the divine is itself conceived of as personality. But because of the merely limited individuality of the divine, which rises to the height of an infinite personal spirit only ifl the last results of philosophy, not recognized by the masses of the people, the certainty of the moral goal falls away also. The personal spirit looks not to cease to be, to vanish in the mechanical whirl-din of the great world-machine, as in China, nor to melt away into the incomprehensible and ineffable proto-Brahnia or nirvana as in India, on the contrary, 6.] IDEA OF HUMANITY OBSCURED. 41 it looks to attain to a positive result, but it finds therefor no assured, firm footing ; and, as in this life the moral hero sinks tragically under the envious disfavor of the gods or of fate, so also is the lot he has earned in the next world of an entirely doubtful character ; Achilles would fain exchange his lot in the lower world for the position of a servant upon earlh, and Soc- rates is not fully confident whether for his philosophical virtue he will attain to the enjoyment of converse with the great dead. At best, doubting hope looks only to a merely individual well- being, and the idea of a real kingdom of God, which has its roots in the earthly life of moral man, and its crown in a trans- mundane perfection, and of which the essence is the history of humanity, remains unknown even to the most highly enlight- ened heathendom. The moral freedom of the person is indeed actually denied only by a few of the more consequential philosophers of India, but yet it ia nowhere recognized in its full truth. With the Chinese, it is smothered under the weight of all-dictating State- law ; with the Brahminic Indians a radical Pantheism admits , only for the less-clearly and less-logically thinking classes of the masses, a very limited form of freedom ; but to the more edu- cated consciousness all initiatorily-active freedom appears as ille- gitimate, as per se sinful, or, more consequentially still, as mere appearance. Impersonal Brahma is the solely real existence, and all individuality is but an absolutely dependent, immediate manifestation-form of this One, utterly devoid of free self- determination. The Greek even in the highest philosophy, far beyond the limits of the national consciousness, concedes free moral self-determination not to man as man, but only to the free Greek ; the barbarian has only a half-humanity, is utterly incapable of true virtue, and is not called to free service under the moral idea, but' only to an unfree service under the free Greek. Even Aristotle knows nothing of a general morality for all men. One of the most hampering limits of heathen morality, is its total lack of the idea of humanity. The religion of the Bud- dhists, the sole one which transcends the limits of nationality, and even in many respects approximates Christian views, has indeed conceived the thought of humanity as equally called in all its representatives to truth and morality, and has sent out 42 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 6. missions beyond its national boundaries, but it has done this only because, religiously and morally, it bears a predominantly negating character ; in the consciousness of the nullity of all being, fall away also, as null, the limits between nations; but this morality aims not to build up a spiritual kingdom of moral reality, but, on the contrary, to liberate the moral spirit from all reality as being per se null, even from its own personal exist- ence. The consciousness of a guiltily-incurred moral depravity of unredeemed humanity, which gives to Christian morality a so deeply earnest back-ground, finds in heathendom but faint and even delusory echoes. To the Chinese all reality is good; the sea of life is mirror-smooth, at worst, is but superficially disturbed by light waves \vhich the shortest calm suffices to settle again. To the Indian all existence is equally good and equally evil, equally good, in that all reality is the divine existence itself, equally evil, in that it is at the same time an untrue and an illegitimate self-alienation of the solely-existing Brahma, or, with the Buddhists, an expression of absolute, nullity. The guilt lies not on man, but on God and on existence in general ; man suffers from the untruthfulness of reality, but has not him- self guiltily occasioned it. The Persian conceives of evil in the world much more earnestly and with higher moral truthfulness. Humanity is really morally corrupted, and is so because of a moral guilt, because of a fall from the good ; and man has the task of morally battling against the evil and for the good. But this fall lies yon-side of human action and of human guilt, lies in the sphere of the divine itself. Not the rational creature, not man, has guiltily fallen, but a god ; the divine is itself hostilely dualistic, the good god is from the beginning opposed by the guilty evil one, and the real world not merely the moral one, but also nature is the work of two mutually morally-opposing divine creative powers. In this no longer naturalistic, but moral dualism there lies a much higher truth than in the Indian doctrine of unity, according to which the distinction of the world from God is explained away into a mere appearance, into a self-deception, either of Brahma, or, and more consequen- tially, of man; and man has, in the Persian view, a much higher personal moral task. But in that this view throws the weight of the guilt from man and upon the divinity, the moral struggle 7.] IDEA OF THE MORAL OBSCURED. 43 lacks, after all, its true ground and truth. With the Greek even this (in its principal nerve paralyzed) earnestness of the Persian is thrown into the shade by the, in other respects, higher theory of an inner harmony of existence. That which in the Christian world-view is the moral goal, is conceived here as the essence indestructibly inherent in reality, so that the moral activity has only to develop the per se essentially faultless germ of the spir- itual essence of man, in order to attain to the highest good. Of a positive struggle against a potent reality of evil in man, even the most enlightened philosophers have no consciousness ; and whatever reality of such an evil in existence forces itself upon the sound feelings and judgment, is sought for, by the in- tensified self-complacence of the most highly-cultivated Greeks, not in the moral essence proper of man, but yon-side of man in the world of the gods, which world appears itself in the morally better-feeling poets as morally tarnished, as an object ot just censure, or yon-side of the god-world in irrationally dom- inating fate, or in the extra-Greek world of mankind, which, as barbarous, is also involved in moral degradation. By far the highest view of the moral and of guilt, appears among the an- cient Germanic nations, the world-view of whom was indeed more fully developed only in Christian times, and not unaffected by Christian influences. SECTION VII. The obscured and only very partially developed moral consciousness of savage nations lies outside of the field of history ; * the more tender consciousness of the half-civilized nations, especially of the Peruvi- ans and Mexicans the former of whom especially developed social morality to a degree of one-sided maturity,! appears rather as potent custom than as a clearly self-conscious consciousness. The very defi- nitely and detailedly developed moral consciousness of the Chinese, as expressed in numerous and in part sacred-esteemed writings, is devoid of higher ideas, * Gesch. des ffeident., i, p. 40 sgq., p. 163 sqq. t Ibid., 251 sqq., 303 sqq. 44 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 7. and .is rather merely soberly empirical, purely polit- ical, and directed predominantly onl} r to outward pur- poses. The essence of this morality is an effortless conformance to an eternally-changeless world-order, a remaining in the just middle-course ; there is no consciousness of a forfeited perfection of the human race, nor of a perfection yet morally to be attained to. There is pre-supposed the unclouded goodness of human nature, the entire agreement of the ideal and of reality. There is no call for a sanctifying of an unholy reality, there needs only that the individual existence of man be modeled upon pure human pat- terns, and conformed to never entirely erroneous, arid always uniform common custom. The bright point in Chinese morality is obedience, in the family and in the State; its ground-character is passive persistence in the constantly homogeneous, goal-less movement of the universe, a steady pulse-beat the significance of which lies not in the goal, but in the movement itself. The Chinese, whose religious views constitute a barren and tame, but clear and consequential Naturalism, have special in- terest for moral life-rules ; the ancient books of their religion, the Kings, which were collected and digested by Confucius in the sixth century before Christ, contain in the main simply a very detailed system of morals ; so also nearly all their later re- ligious, philosophical, and historical writings. The life of the All bears every-where, even in its spiritual phase, a nature-character; there is no history with a spiritual goal to be attained to by moral activity, but only a nature- course with a constantly uniform character manifesting itself in constant, unvaried repetition ; morality looks not forward, but simply backward to that which has been and will always remain as it is, and all reformatory action upon an occasionally some- what deteriorated present is but a mere return to the previous better. Instead of progress the goal of moral effort is uniformly simply a conserving, or a return to the past. There is no ideal 7.] CHINESE MORALITY. 45 yet to be reached, but the ideal has already always existed, and has never suffered but slight becloudings ; humanity is already perfect from the very beginning, without history and without development ; morality never looks to the creating of something which has not already been, at best aims only at remedying a slight but never deeply seated disorder. Good is not that which in the nature of things ought first to become, but that which already is from the beginning ; the highest good is not a goal and end, but it is that itself which eternally is ; man has and enjoys it as already given from the start ; it is the Paradise into which he is placed by nature herself, and which he has never really lost, at the worst, only a few thorns and thistles have insinuated themselves into it, which however can only render the Paradisaical life of the " Celestial Kingdom " only a little more incommodious for man, but not by any means banish him out of it, and in fact are very readily to be got rid of. The stream of world-history flows on of itself without the co-opera- tion of man ; man has simply to yield himself to it, to adapt himself unresistingly to the eternally-unvarying order of the world, to join himself, as a passively revolved wheel, into the constantly uniform-moving clock-work. Hence morality has no high goal, but requires only repose and order, and a passive submission to the minutely-tutorial civil law and to the equally valid laws of custom ; there is no violent struggle, but only a quiet persisting and laboring. The highest symbol of morality is the natural sky, with its eternally-unvarying orderly revolu- tion. As the real world is the mutual interpenetration of the two primitive principles, heaven and earth, and the equilibrium and mean between the two, so consists ajso morality in the pre- serving of equilibrium, in the observing of the just mean; the middle way is always the best. Hence ethics is by no means rigid and severe, aims not at high reality-transcending ideals, is of a mild gentle nature, sober, practical, temperate, without high inspiration ; it requires of man scarcely any thing which could be difficult to him, or which would involve much self- denial; he is not required to divest himself of his natural char- acter, but has only to observe measure in all things. Man, that is, of course, only the Chinaman, is consequently already capac- itated by nature to fulfill perfectly all the requirements of morality, and there are in fact also absolutely perfect, sinless 46 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 7. men. Virtue is of easy practice, for it is the natural expression of the soul-life, and has not to contend against any evil rooted in the heart, and it meets in fact with no actual hostility to it- self in the world ; it awakens not displeasure, but always love, esteem, and honor; for mankind is in fact generally and, as a whole, good ; actual evil is always a mere exception ; the gate is wide, and the way is broad which leads to life, and many are those who walk upon it. As being a mere expression of general, natural world-order, morality stands in direct connection with the course of nature. The observance of the just mean preserves equilibrium in the All, and every disturbance of this equilibrium by sin re-echoes through the whole, and effects, directly, disturbances in nature, especially when the offending one is the vicegerent of heaven, the emperor, who is called by his very office to the presenting of a moral ideal, of a pattern of virtue. Drought, famine, inun- dations, pestilence, and the like, are not so much positively in- flicted punishments of a personally-ruling God, as rather direct natural consequences of the sins of the emperor, and of the peo- ple as imitating him. Instead of an historical connection and an historical working of sin upon coming generations, as in the Christian world-theory, there is here a natural connection and a natural working of sin upon contemporary nature and the con- temporary generation. This naturalistic parallel to the Chris- tian doctrine of inherited sin, has a deeply earnest significancy. Man in his moral activity has to do not merely with himself, but with the totality of the universe ; by sinning, he disturbs the order and the harmony of existence in general ; every sin is an outrage against the All, and consequently also against the highest manifestation thereof, namely, the Middle Kingdom ; all sins are crimes, all are hurtful to the public weal ; in the Chinese view nature suffers by sin ; in the Christian, history. The focus of the moral life is the family; in it manifests it- self directly the divine life, which consists in the antithesis of the male or active and of the female or passive, in heaven-force and earth-material, and in the union of the two. The family life is a living worship of God, and the family duties are the highest, and have the unconditional precedence of all others ; to the obedience of children to parents all other obedience must give way. What heaven is for the world, that the father is for 8.] THE CHINESE STATE. 47 the children, and reverence toward parents is a religious virtue. Hence marriage is a moral duty from which no virtuous man can excuse himself; the celibate interrupts the ranks of the family and commits an outrage on his ancestors. But the full realization of morality appears in the state, which is simply the all-sidedly developed family. The emperor, as the son and vicegerent of heaven not governing arbitrarily but by eternally valid heavenly laws, is the father and teacher of the people, not merely protecting right, but also, as a pattern of virtue, guiding and conserving the morality of the people. In China every thing is the State, and the State is everything ; it is the great ocean into which all the streams of the spirit-life ulti- .raate, and morality itself stands absolutely under the guardian- ship of the State. Not as man, but only as a citizen of the State and a member of the family, has the Chinaman a moral life ; all morality is accomplished by obedience to the laws of the State ; and between civil and moral law there is no distinction. SECTION VIII. The Indians, the Brahminic as also the Buddhistic, conceived morality, on the basis of their consequen- tially developed Pantheism, essentially negatively. All finite reality, and above all, that of the human personality, is null, untrue, and illegitimate, either because, with the Brahmins, it is only the self- estranged divinity, or because, with the Buddhists, the essence of all existence in general is nihility; hence the ground-character of morality is self-denial, world-renunciation, a passive endurance instead of creative activity. The moral goal, the highest good, is not a personal possession, but a surrendering of personality to the impersonal divine essence or to nihility. There is no realizing and no shaping of a moral kingdom based on personality, nor even a pre- serving of existing reality, but a dissolving of the same. All reality, in so far as it is a finite formation, 48 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 8. is evil, not, however, through the guilt of man, but in virtue of its very essence from the beginning ; and there is no other redemption than its annihilation. But while, in the purely Pantheistic doctrine of the Brahmins, the thought of the development of the world out of God recognizes in fact in existence a divine and hence relatively good substratum, and re- gards mankind as emanated from God, as participant in this divine substance in different degrees, accord- ing as they stand at different distances from the divine pro to-foun tain, the distinctions of caste, on the other hand, the doctrine of the Buddhists annihilates, to- gether with the divine proto-Brahma, also these con- centric circles around the ungodded middle-point, and requires equal, absolutely world-renouncing mo- rality of all men, even irrespective of the limits of nationality, and changes the positive self-torture, which appears among the Brahmins as the acme of pious morality, into a quietistic, self-denying patience resting upon hopeless grief at the nihility of all existence. s The Brahminic Indians have, in their books of law, ancient and rich collections of moral doctrines. Almost equally esteemed with the Vedas, and attributed to a divine origin, is the book of the Laws of Manu, the parts of which belong to very differ- ent ages, though the most recent belong certainly anterior to the fourth century before Christ ; the moral precepts proper are as yet unseparated from the religious and civil. Also the Vedas and the later philosophical and legal writings contain much moral matter. Basing himself, in contrast to the nature-dualism of the Chi- nese, upon the unity of the universe as divine, the Brahmin regards the real world merely as a, neither necessary nor strictly legitimate, but rather mere dream-like self-alienation of primi- tive Brahma, which is destined, after an essentially purposeless 8.] BEAHMINIC MORALITY. 49 continuance, to be absorbed back into its source. Hence moral- ity has no positive aim, but rather simply looks to an escaping from individual existence, a dissolving of personality into the impersonal. The continuance of personality through metemp- sychosis is punishment, not reward. Existing reality is not, as in China, good as such, but, as separate existence, is evil, and is good only in its general divine substance ; only the latter, but not the former, may be held fast to. The moral subject is not man as such ; there is in fact no unitary humanity, but only dif- ferent, narrower or wider, circles around the divine middle- point, classes of men differing essentially by nature both spirit- ually and morally, and of whom the lowest stand even below many brutes, and are absolutely incapable of the moral life ; to teach to these latter the Vedas or the Laws, is a crime worthy of the deepest damnation. Only the three highest castes are capable of a knowledge of the truth, and hence also of morality. But also with these the moral duties and capacities are very different, and the Indian speaks not of the moral duties of man, but always only of the duties of the castes. The vaifja's highest good is riches ; his virtue, industrious acquiring ; the xatrija's highest good is power, and his highest virtue, courage; and onlv the Brahmin is capable of the highest morality ; but this morality directs itself, not transformingly and productively, upon reality, but only, disdainingly and renouncingly, away from the same, not, however, in order to virtualize a free, self- conscious personality as over against nature, but in order to merge back the personal spirit, as illegitimate, into the imper- sonal essence of the universe. The highest virtue is renuncia- tion, not indeed merely of sensuous enjoyment, of earthly weal, but of one's own self-conscious personality ; and the acme of this morality is, consequently, self-annihilation as sought through persistent self-torture, to the end that Brahma alone may exist. The highest good of the true man, that is, of the Brahmin, is to become at one with Brahma, not in the sense of a moral life- communion of the personal spirit with a personal God, but as a dissolving of the per se illegitimate personal spirit into the general, the impersonal. That which is in the present state the sum and substance of all wisdom, namely, to know that "-I am Brahma," attains to full truth by the dissolving of the ego into Brahma ; the goal of morality is, " Brahma alone is, not I ;" 50 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 8. and as man, even now, while in deepest sleep, wherein he knows nothing of the world and of himself, is nearer to divin- ity than when in his waking hours, so the goal of virtue is the total falling to sleep of the personal spirit, the exhaling of the dew-drop that trembles on the lotus-leaf. The holding fast to personality is the essence of all evil. Nothing can nor should permanently endure but the divine essence alone, which tolerates nothing other than itself, and for which all reality of the world is, at best, only a dream-phantom, a transient hallucination ; even in the eyes of the deeper instructed of men, the world in general is only a false imagination of the foolish, and does not really exist at all. The Chinese aim, in morality, simply to con- serve the already-existing ; the higher nations aim at transform- ing it into a more spiritual reality ; the Indians aim at dissolving it into nonentity. The West-Asiatic nations see the truth in the future, and long, hopefully, and through moral effort, for a bet- ter reality than is offered by the present ; the Indians look sadly into the present, with indifference into the future, and with sat- isfaction only into the past, when as yet nothing else existed but unitary Brahma, and into that future which simply returns to the condition of this past. The Chinese work for the present ; the higher nations, for the future ; the Indians work not at all, but simply endure and perish ; they aim not at implanting the free moral spirit into reality, but at tearing it away from the same, not at transfiguring reality by the spirit, but at emanci- pating the spirit from the same. Indian morality is less a crea- tive working than a sacrificing, and hence is essentially identical with the practice of religion, of which the highest phase is self- mortification aiming at a total annihilation of personal exist- ence. The way which the world has traveled out from primitive Brahma, this way it must travel back again; nature herself accomplishes this by death; man accomplishes it by morally- pious self-annihilation. That which is with nature the natural goal, is with man a moral end. Even as Brahma developed himself out of his pure transparent unity into the world of plurality, so must man fold himself back out of his isolated existence again into unity ; man, the highest fruit of mundane existence, must gather himself out of the dispersion of Brahma in the world, back into unity, must give up his separate exist- ence. Man must die away, not indeed to sin, or merely to 8.] MORTIFICATION ASCETICISM. 51 sensuousness, but to himself, must cease to be a real person- ality, must renounce every feeling, every volition, every thought, which contains any thing whatever other than Brahma alone. The fearful self-tortures of the Indians are not penance for sins, but the highest virtue-exercises of saints. A vital consciousness of guilt, the Indian is utterly devoid of; the evil of existence is not his own, is not the fault of man in general. Whatever is and transpires, is directly Brahma's act. It is true, evil inheres by nature in all existence, but it is not to be imputed to man, and there is no other redemption from the same than the de- struction of the finite, even of one's own being. The entire scope of morality bears a negating character ; the truly know- ing one needs not merely not to do any positive works, but he avoids them from principle, because they belong simply to the realm of folly. For man, even in so far as he is an object of the moral activity, the Indian has no concern ; he has a higher love for nature, which stands nearer related to the nature-divinity, and consti- tutes the narrowest circle around the divine center-point. In nature he beholds his mother, and he loves it reverently as the most direct and most unclouded revelation of Brahma. The same Indian who can heartlessly see a pariah famish without so much as stretching out to him a helping hand, reverently avoids, as a severe sin, the breaking of a grass-blade, or the swallowing of a gnat ; a Brahmin allows himself not, without ground, to break even an earth-clod. Marriage and the family-life in gen- eral can only be a transition-stage for the, as yet, morally imma- ture. The Brahmin who has risen to true knowledge must leave father and mother, wife and child, and, dead to the world and to himself, live henceforth only in solitary contemplation of Brahma, standing for years, in the forest, upon the same spot, emotionless as a tree-trunk, and seeking or accepting only the scantiest food ; every thing finite must have become abso- lutely indifferent to him, until, vegetating on like a plant, and fading away, he attains to the long-sought death. For society and politics, only those who belong to the inferior castes can have any further interest, for the Brahmin himself these things have no attraction, and, higher than the warrior-hero and than the zealously-ruling prince, is he who exchanges a crown for the life of the hermit. 52 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 8. More remarkable still is the moral consciousness of the Bud- dhists, whose world-historical and influential religion an off-shoot of the Brahminic was founded by the Indian prince Sakya- Mvni in the sixth century before Christ, the sole heathen religion which sent out missions beyond the national limits, so that within a few centuries it extended itself throughout all middle, southern, and eastern Asia, as far as into Japan. The sacred books of the Buddhists are chiefly of moral contents, for here religion passes over almost entirely into morality. While in Brahminisni the ground and essence of all existence is the one absolutely indeterminate and un-positive proto- Brahma, Buddhism goes a step further, and declares this inde- terminate, empty substratum to be nonentity itself. All things are sprung of nonentity ; hence nonentity is the contents of all being, hence all reality is per se null, and finds its truth only in that it returns to nothing. As the beginning, so is also the end of all being, and hence also that of man and of his moral efforts, nonentity. Every thing is vain, in heaven and upon earth ; heaven and earth themselves are vain, and upon the ruins of a crumbling world sits, eternally enthroned, empty Naught. The moral element of this atheistical religion lies in the fact that the Buddhist is really and truly in earnest with the comfortless thought, and, in striking contrast to the lust- ful, pleasure-seeking atheism of modern times, presents to man the God-forsaken world as in fact really such, and forbids to him all enjoyment of the same, that he has no joy in it, but makes deep grief at all existence the foundation of all morality. The Buddhist is fully conscious of what it signifies to place na- ture above spirit, to seek God only in nature and in the world in general. Not being able to rise to the- conception of a per- sonal God, he disdains the impersonal nature-God, and chooses rather to live without God in the world, only, however, as one who has no hope at all. Buddhism in its pure form is a religion of despair, and its ethics answers to this character, and is essen- tially different from the Brahminic. Here no divine proto- Brahma unfolds himself into a world ; and hence the different castes of mankind have no longer any essential meaning ; no one man stands, by nature, nearer to the divinity than another, but all men are equal ; there is no plant-like branching-out of a divine proto-germ, but only a homogeneous sea of equally- 8.] BUDDHISTIC MORALITY. 53 worthless sand-grains. With the Brahmin moral freedom is essentially trammeled, and in fact, consequentially regarded, annihilated, by the fact that Brahma alone works all and in all ; but for the Buddhist no such limitation exists. No divinity forcibly interferes with human action. Moral effort, however, has no reality, as a highest good, for its goal; the ultimate goal is annihilation ; and this thought is here much more deeply and sadly embraced than with the Brahmins. While with the Brah- mins, man and the entire world sink back into the divine essence, with the Buddhists they fall into utter annihilation ; and the goal of all life and effort is a traceless extinguishment nirvana. The Buddhist strives not ; he only patiently endures the pain of inner nothingness, that falls to the lot of all living existence. The entire history of the world is but one grand tragedy ; in deep pain worries on all that lives, until it succumbs to death, and the consciousness of this pain is the beginning and the end of all wisdom. In comparison with this acme of all wisdom, namely, the knowledge of the four-fold misery in- herent in the world, that is, birth, old age, disease, and death, all other questions lose their importance. All reality is vain and irrational; this is the basis of all morality. Hence, man should break loose from all love to real existence, should re- nounce all earthly pleasure ; the only feeling that beseems the sage is that of pain and compassion. For a positive moral -act- ing, aiming at the production of a reality, there is here no place ; man strives only to urge his way out of this world of pain, for misery is the essence of the world, and all moral wisdom con- sists in the greatest possible breaking away from all liking for the same. In the God-void world, man feels homeless, finds therein no rest and no satisfaction ; his future is annihilation ; his present, the renouncing of all joy. The world-renunciation of the Brahmin is rather active and manly, for by the throwing off of his finite existence he returns into Brahma. The world- renunciation of the Buddhist is rather passive and womanly, does not rise to positive self-torture and to real self-destruction ; on the contrary, the Buddhist waits, still and patient, supports the misery of life in unmurmuring pain, until his existence falls away ; the characteristic of this world-theory is a quiet, gentle grief, for the thought of the empty nothingness of all things cannot inspire to manly action ; and the pain of existence should 54 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 9. not be additionally heightened by voluntary act. Man is simply to disdain the world, not because he compares it with a better sinless one, but because evil and misery are inseparable from it. Separated from all the world, and as a homeless wanderer, or as a hermit in forest or desert, the pious man should live in beggar- garb, devoid of adornment, utterly possessionless, entirely isolat- ed, indifferent to joy and grief, and dead to all emotions. Mar- riage, as productive of new existence, is per se of evil, and is absolutely forbidden to the saint; the family bonds have no significancy for him, and sensuous enjoyment is in his eyes a pure folly. The most ancient and pure doctrine of Buddhism requires such renunciation of all men, and it is only a deteriorated form of later times that conceded that all did not need to lead this spiritual life, but that a portion of the people might con- tent themselves with an inferior severity. Buddhistic ethics contains but few positive precepts ; almost all of them are negative ; virtue consists essentially in omitting ; " thou shalt not," is the almost unvarying beginning of the pre- cepts; all of them aim simply at preventing the spirit from taking delight in existence, forbid worldly pleasure, but do not create a moral reality ; and, as relating to other living crea- tures, beast as well as man, they guard against all multiplication of the already so widely-prevalent misery. Hence there goes here, hand in hand, with the intensest world-despising, the greatest gentleness toward all living beings; no creature may be tormented, nor even slaughtered; in order to alleviate the pain of another creature, man should rather himself endure it. Hence the Buddhists have been, in fact, the gentlest of heathen nations; but their gentleness is not so much an expression of active love as rather merely of compassion, is simply a non- interfering, a sparing, but not a positive helping. The dumb, patient enduring of pain, a complete indifference to joy and sor- row, is not the heroic pride of a deeply self-conscious personal- ity, but the womanly, submissive patience of a heart broken with pain. SECTION IX. The moral consciousness of the Egyptians and of the Semitic nations, especially of the Assyrians and Rulnjlonians, is, as yet, only very imperfectly and par- 9.] EGYPTIAN THEOLOGY. 55 tially known, so that a very definite characterizing of it is not yet possible. So much appears to be reliably ascertained, that among these nations (which consti- tute the transition from naturalistic East- Asia to the Occidental nations among whom the divine is con- ceived of as a personal spirit) both the moral bases and the essence of the moral subject and of the moral task, are conceived in a higher and more spiritual manner than was the case among the earlier nations, in a manner which brings personality to a greater validity. The Pantheistico-naturalistic character of the religious and moral world-theory is overcome, and a morally dualistic one struggles more definitely into the fore-ground. Morality passes over from the mere preserving and persisting of the Chinese, and .from the self-renouncing of the Indians, into a struggle against evil, as super-humanly originated, though not exclusively dominant, and as in fact ultimately to be overcome. Egypt stands on the dividing-line between the naturalistic and the personally-spiritual world-theory ; the divine is indeed primarily and originally, as yet, a pure nature-power, but it struggles up into spiritual personality, and such a personality is recognized also in man ; among the Semitic nations this con- sciousness comes into the fore-ground more prominently still. The presupposition of the moral is no longer the perfect and uniform goodness of existence, as -with the Chinese, nor the essential evilness of the same, as with the Indians, but an inner moral antagonism of existence. Over against the personal- become good divinities, stands evil as a divine entity different from them, and which is primarily less spiritual, and expressive rather of mere nature-character; and man in his moral struggle stands in the midst of this antagonism, has to determine him- self for the divine good, and against the not less divine evil. Thus, in virtue of the contest of the antagonism dominant in the world, the moral subject becomes more nearly independent. 56 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 9. and free, than among the purely naturalistic nations ; his moral task becomes, by far, more earnest and arduous, calls far more emphatically for personal self-determination. Hence these na- tions have produced grander world-historical characters than the earlier ones, have become world-historically militant na- tions. And the goal of the militant struggle is the ultimate victory of the good over the evil ~by the personal spirit, which is also itself not destined to be dissolved back into a general im- personal nature-existence, but, triumphing over mere nature, preserves its own personality. But this breaking-forth of the rational spirit and of its moral task into greater distinctness, manifests itself otherwise among the Egyptians than among the Semitic nations. It is among the Egyptians that the personal nature of the moral spirit comes first to full self-consciousness. The spirit is a something other than nature and higher than it, is not destined to servitude under it, but to personal, free moral self-determination and to personal immortality, over against death-dominated nature. But this antithesis of the moral personal spirit to nature does not as yet rise, in the earthly life, to complete victory. Even as Osiris succumbs to the evil divinity, Typhon, so must man ulti- mately succumb in the struggle with unspiritual nature, only, however, in order to attain in the yon-side to. the full enjoyment of spiritual personality. The morning-twilight of the freedom of the rational spirit dawns in Egypt, but it is not as yet day. It is only through struggle, through suffering and dying, that the spirit becomes free, in the world of the gods as well as in the world of man. Osiris becomes a true ruler only in the next world, and so with man also ; only out of death spring forth life and victory. Also over the Egyptian's moral life a dusky vail is thrown, a melancholy breath poured out, as with the Indi- ans, though relieved by a brighter hope. To the Indian all moral life is but a rapidly passing meteor, vanishing away with- out trace ; to the Egyptian it is a conflict, painful indeed, but resulting in an ultimate permanent victory of the moral person. Man has not as yet complete freedom and complete personal validity, but he will have them after death if lie only struggles manfully here below ; and he is conscious of entire personal re- sponsibility for his life and his fortune after death. His per- sonally-moral life falls not a prey to a universally-dominating 9.] EGYPTIAN MORALITY. 57 nature-necessity, but to the personal decision of the first personal victor (Osiris) over nature and over death. By Osiris, the king of the yon-side world, where alone true life first begins, man's moral life is judged weighed in the scales of righteous- ness. In personal communion with Osiris, the just man lives, happy thenceforth. Osiris, the highest representative of spirit- ual divinity, the forerunner and pledge of immortality, the first- born among those who have died and are now living after death, is also the highest representative of Egyptian morality, the ground-character of which is, a persistent battling for righteous- ness. The ostrich-feather, the symbol of truth and righteous- ness, is one of the highest badges of honor. But it is only in the next world that true righteousness is realized ; here upon earth rule as yet, invincibly, the powers of evil. Hence the Egyptian, in contrast to the Chinese, turns all his love and his interest to the yon-side life. The dwellings of the living were for the most part paltry huts ; the dwellings of the dead are monuments of the highest art and of an unparalleled zeal for labor; the tombs hewn out the rocks, and the pyramids intended for the sepulchers of kings, belong among the wonders of the ancient world, and bid defiance to the ravages of time. The present life is, as with the Indians, lightly esteemed, not, how- ever, because of the nullity of all existence in general, but be- cause it is contrasted with a higher life, which, as the highest good, is a richly promising moral goal. Reminders of death attend the Egyptian wherever he turns, and the mummies and the images of the dead were an eloquent memento mori even at his most convivial banquets). " The Egyptians," says Diodorus (i, 51), "regard the time of this life with very little esteem ; the dwellings of life they designate as inns, but the graves as ever- lasting mansions." The heathen Semitic nations, especially the Assyrians and Babylonians, base themselves, in religion and morality, entirely on the ground of the subjective spirit, of the individual person- ality. The general unity of naturalism they have given up, but they have not as yet risen to that of the infinite spirit. The spirit appears only in the multiplicity of single forms ; hence these nations never appear in history as a unity, but always as a plurality. In religion as well as in morality there is manifested the reckless independence of the (now, for the first time, vigor- 58 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 10. ously and mightily self-conscious) subjective spirit, from any and all unconditional objective authority, whether of nature or of spirit, an untaniedness and intractableness of the strong in- dividual will, daring deeds, but also a violent wildness of the unbent will and of the passions, a highly excited turmoil with- out goal or purpose. Man, as a personal individual, comes into the fore-ground as possessed of paramount rights. Morality is devoid of any certain basis and rule ; the strong individual will breaks through all barriers. It is the era of great heroes, and of great tyrants and God-despisers, from Nimrod who began to be a mighty one upon earth, a mighty hunter before Jehovah (Gen. x, 8), to Nebuchadnezzar, who daringly exalted himself against God. The moral consciousness, as bewildered by an over-intense self-consciousness, manifests predominantly a defi- ance on the part of this strongly egotistical subject against all objective power, even against God; cruelty and coarse sensu- ousness characterize even the rites of religion, and hence much more also the moral life. Nineveh and Babylon attained, in ante-Christian times, to the culminating-point of the godless, pleasure-seeking, luxurious life. Eeligion and morality stand here in the most violent contrast to those of India ; the rude, the violent, the tumultuous, tolerates no law, no regulated order. SECTION X. To a higher stand-point, though not to a higher development thereof, than the earlier nations, rise the merely transitorily world-historical Persians. The violent dualism of two mutually morally-opposed per- sonal gods, calls also morality to an earnest moral struggle against ante-mundane, god-sprung evil ; the moral personality comes much more emphatically into the fore-ground than ever before ; the moral task be- comes more difficult, but it has the certain promise of ultimate victory over evil, not merely in a yon-side life, but within the scope of history itself. Morality has here, for the first time in heathendom, a positive goal inside of the field of history, namely, the realiz- ]Q.] PERSIAN THEOLOGY. 59 ing of a kingdom of the good upon earth ; and the Persians are the sole heathen people who make a definite prophecy the foundation of their religiously- moral striving. Hence the essence of Persian moral- ity consists in a definitely hope-inspired conscious struggle against evil as potent in the world, as well as in, and upon, man himself, and which, both in its guilty origin and in its effects, appears as a not nat- ural but moral and utterly illegitimate corruption, in a progressive purification of man from every thing which springs from all-invading and all-infecting evil, in a word, in struggling against the world of Angra- mainyus. Man stands forth with his moral will, legit- imated and victorious, over against a potently ruling divinity. The Persians, whose world-historical sigriificancy proper ex- tends from Cyrus to Alexander the Great, have not been able within this short period to develop their religiously-moral con- sciousness into a scientifically matured form. The chief source for the same the Avesta is far inferior in contents and devel- opment of thought to the so-rich and deeply-suggestive sacred writings of the Indians ; and yet the moral view, as a whole, is a higher one. The real world, in which man has morally to work, is here no longer the immediate divine essence itself, but it has come into existence essentially by a personal, divine act. The spirit, in its personal reality, is no longer a mere moment- ary phenomenon upon the alone-eternal nature-ground, as in China and India, nor is it fettered and hemmed by nature, as over-potent in this life, as is the case in Egypt ; but it is already the higher creative power over nature, although not as yet a perfectly free and omnipotent Creator. Hence the world, in its relation to the moral spirit, is no longer a foreign and hetero- geneous element, but as a spirit product, is unhostile and even congenial to the spirit ; man begins to feel at home in the world, and hence he places no longer the goal of his moral striving merely in the yon-side, but he conceives it as to-be-attained-to 60 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 10. within the field of history. This goal of moral effort is, however, not to be reached by a mere simple, natural development of man, but by a constant and earnest struggle against positively extant evil. Evil is no longer, as with the Buddhists and, in part already, with the Brahmins, the substance of the world, inheres not in the essence of existence as inseparable therefrom, but has in fact become, through the moral fault of the personal spirit, is a guilty fall from the originally good. This is a thought more strongly approximative of the Christian world- theory than we have as yet met with in our development of the history of the moral consciousness. Wherever evil is regarded as naturally necessary, there the vitality of the morally evil is paralyzed ; the Chinese entertain not this view, simply because they conceive of evil in general only very superficially ; the In- dians conceive of it far more profoundly and earnestly, but they recognize not the moral root of the same ; the Persians regard all evil as springing exclusively from personal act. This act, however, is not an historical one, but a pre-historical one ; not a human act, but a divine one. The unitary divinity per se, how- ever, cannot do evil, as is attributed to the Indian Brahma, but the good God, Ahura-Mazda, remains free of all evil ; it is an- other no less personal god, that by free self-determination, chose the evil and now thrusts his world into the world of Ahura- Mazda, and is involved in all real evil whose proto-source he is, namely, Angra-mainyua, that is, "the evilly disposed," the author of death, of falsehood, of all impurity, and of all hurtful creatures, the spirit which constantly denies the good. Although, according to this, man has thrown off the guilt of evil reality from himself upon the world of the gods, still he conceives of his moral nature and life-task, in regard to this evil, more highly thap did the earlier nations. Man, as created good by the good god, is placed, with complete personal free- dom, in the midst of the moral antagonism of the world, and has now actually to accomplish in his own person the moral task of coming constantly into closer communion with Ahura- Mazda, and to contend against Angra-mainyus and all his works. Morality is a struggle, and rests not upon mere natural feelings and impulses, but upon the distinct consciousness of the holy will of the good god, upon the Word expressly re- vealed to men. By this view, morality is made to throw off all 10.] PERSIAN MORALITY. 61 nature-character, and is placed in the purely spiritual sphere, and at the same time the subjective caprice of the Semitic na- tions is overcome, and, for the moral, an objective law obtained, a law that is to be received purely spiritually. The revealed holy Word is the mightiest weapon against Angra-mainyus. This moral struggle is a much more vigorous one than in Egypt, for it is joyously and hopefully conscious of final victory, even within the sphere of history. The Egyptian regards his god who is at the same time his moral example as defeated for the present world, and driven to the future world ; the Persian feels himself called even here to a courageous co-militancy with Ahura-Mazda, who persistently struggles against evil, and does not succumb to it, not even in the present world. The Persian regards himself as a co-worker with God, and does not mourn- fully long for the next world; for his moral effort, he has a high object, namely, to combat against a god and the evil crea- tion of that god, also a high goal, namely, the redemption of a world from evil, and also a high confidence in victory, for there will ultimately come the Rescuer, aoschyan9, that is, the Helper, who will accomplish the victory. It is not by mere chance that the Persians who usually showed themselves hos- tile to foreign religions, and especially to all sensuous idolatry manifested constantly a high regard for the Jews, in whose higher idea of God they met in fact with a somewhat related element. In correspondence to its religious presupposition, Persian morality bears primarily a negating character, though in a wholly different manner than among the Indians. While the system of the latter is directed against existence, and especially against the personal nature of man, Persian morality on the con- trary directs itself, with the most complete consciousness of the validity of the personality, negatingly against every thing which belongs to the world of Angra-mainyus. Self-purification from every thing which stands really, or even merely symbolically, in relation with evil, death, or corruption, the killing of poison- ous and hurtful animals, and the like, are not merely moral requirements, but even acts of worship, and the Avesta gives, on these points, very precise and detailed directions. But also the positive phase of the moral life is much more highly developed in the moral consciousness of the Persians than in that of the earlier nations. The Persians acquired 62 CHRISTIAN ETHICS.* [11. among their contemporaries the reputation of high moral ear- nestness as in contrast to the luxuriousness of the Semitic nations. They were, in their prime, a very vivacious and vigor- ously active people ; indolence springs of Angra-rnainyus ; labor, especially agriculture, internal improvements, etc., are required by the good god, and are sacred duties ; this is somewhat as it is in Chinese morality, but from a different reason ; the Chinese labor for the present, the Persians for the future. The moral relation to other men is here kindly and noble ; a high esteem for the personality, in every respect, forms the basis of social virtue. Honesty, strict truthfulness, and a high feeling of per- sonal honor, distinguish Persian morality very widely from East-Asiatic. It is a morality of vigor and manliness. Where evil is no longer regarded as a merely abstract some- thing, as a quality of existence in general, but as a concrete guilt reality, not a mere neutrum, but as borne by personality, there only can the moral struggle against the same be really earnest. The Chinaman labors quietly and busily in mechan- ical persistence; the Indian patiently endures; the Egyptian mourns, and longs to pass out of this world ; the Shemite riots and enjoys ; but the Persian battles with a manfully-moral ear- nestness. The defective phase of his moral consciousness is essentially this, that he throws evil off from himself upon the sphere of the gods, that he has not recognized the evil of his own heart. SECTION XI. The moral consciousness of the Greeks is very dif- ferent from that of the Persians ; though rising above it, it yet seems to throw the approximation to the Christian view, that lay in the Persian consciousness, farther again into the back-ground. The heathen mind could not remain stationary at Persian dualism ; the Greeks endeavor to bring about a reconciliation of the antagonism of the universe, by throwing this antagonism into the past, and by regarding the pres- ent ae an expression of the harmony of existence as effected at the very beginning of history by a victory 11.] GREEK VIEWS. 63 of the persona] spirit over the nature-powers that op- posed it; the dualism of hostile antagonism gives place to a dualism of love. No evil god and no nature-power hostile to the personal spirit, offer ob- struction to the moral activity. Morality is not a struggle, but a progressive development of man as per se good and pure ; by following his own inwardly harmonious nature, by enjoying the intrinsically beau- tiful existence of the world, and by exalting sensu- ous enjoyment by means of spiritual culture, and by equally developing all the phases both of his sensuous and of his spiritual life, man arrives at the harmoni- ous perfection of his personality, at the highest goal of moral effort. The beautiful is per se the good ; in enjoying and creating the beautiful, man is moral. The battle is not against a world of evil that is to be destroyed, nor in championship of a moral idea that is to be realized ; but its end is simply to develop the full personality of the hero. The Greek battles for the sake of battling ; the battle is even enjoyment, is heroic play. The Greek ideal is the vigorous, youth- ful personality, in the world of gods, the youthful Apollo, in the world of heroes, Achilles, until, at the close of Grecian history, it assumes a world-historical form in Alexander the Great. But the entire ideal element inheres in the person of the hero ; a perma- nent moral world-historical reality, the Greeks could not create; they lacked the positively world-historical purpose; Alexander's world-conquering deeds aimed at, and were able to effect, only an exaltation of the person of the hero, and necessarily ended in anarchy at his death, and the Greeks became an easy prey to that nation which aimed with iron-persistency at the positive purpose of a unitary historical reality, and 64 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 11. absolutely subordinated the person to the same. The moral idea is, with the Greeks, more an object of artistic enjoyment than of moral realization. For the positive basis of the higher moral life, the family, their moral consciousness is extremely defective, and the idea of man as man, has not as yet come to con- sciousness ; only the Hellene, but not the barbarian, is regarded as a truly moral personality. Slavery is the indispensable foundation of the free state. The precedent antagonism of existence, which conies to con- sciousness in all heathen religions, primarily as an antithesis of nature and spirit, which rises with the Persians to a moral character, is, with the Greeks, not indeed entirely overcome (heathenism in fact never rises beyond it), but in fact reduced to harmony, a harmony, however, which, as viewed from a Chris- tian stand-point, must be regarded as delusive. The conscious- ness of this antagonism comes to expression in myths concerning ancient combats between the spiritual gods and Titanic nature- powers; the gods came off victorious, and the present world expresses the peaceful reconciliation of the earlier antagonisms ; every-where, both in the world of gods and of men, spirit and nature are in harmonious union ; there is nowhere mere spirit, and nowhere mere nature. What appears as a hostile power over the personal spirit, was already vanquished anterior to human history; no inimical, evil god disturbs the beautiful harmony of existence ; the Titans have been thrust into Tar- tarus. The foundation of Greek morality is therefore joy in existence, love as enjoyment ; man has not to sacrifice his ex- istence and his wishes, but only to heighten the former, and to fulfill the latter, in so far as they express the character of har- mony, of the beautiful; he has not, as with the Indians, to renounce the world, but on the contrary to enjoy it, as bearing every-where the stamp of the beautiful, and to remain in genial peace therewith, has not, as the Persian, to battle against its reality as permeated with evil, but simply to pluck from it the fruits of happiness. Greek morality is the morality of him who is complacently self-satisfied, without any severe inner struggle. The Hellene has, in his consciousness of the harmony of ex- 11.] IDEAL VERSUS REAL. 65 istence, on the one hand a powerful stimulus to virtue; he endeavors to preserve this harmony, and hence is in general amiable, frank, and honorable ; to a certain degree he shows also magnanimity toward his enemies, respects the moral personal- ity ; but, on the other hand, he has in this consciousness also the tendency to make light with the moral ; he believes himself already to have attained to the good, and not to need to under- go a severe struggle for its possession, believes himself to have already, in his natural proclivities, also the right. Hence he is inclined to take life unseriously ; even unnatural lusts pass for allowed, if they only appear under the form of the beautiful. The beauty of the manner beautifies the sin, and the worship of Aphrodite lends to sensuality itself a religious sanction. Greek effeminacy and luxuriousness despised only by the Spar- tans became even a by-word among the Romans ; and even the dark passions of hate and revenge found in the Greek con- sciousness little condemnation ; no Greek took offense at the barbarous mistreatment of the hero Hector. The most virtuous citizens were not respected, but banished; sycophants were honored, and the friends of truth hated or killed. A high sense for beauty raises indeed the moral consciousness to a high and harmonious conception of moral beauty, and the poets sketch moral ideals with master-hand; but these ideals are more for esthetic enjoyment than for moral imitation. Even morality becomes to the Hellene a matter of mere spectacle, and in no heathen nation is the contrast between the ideal and the real life so great, as in that one which conceived the ideal the highest. For the practical life the requirements of the moral consciousness were other than for poetry;, the same people which admired female ideals, such as Penelope, Antigone, and Electra, as presented in song and upon the stage, placed woman- hood and marriage, and the family-life in general, much lower in real life than did the Chinese or the ancient Germans ; and it was not merely in the censured license of the frivolous world, but also in the moral views of the most highly cultured, that talented concubines (especially after the example of Aspasia, notorious for her connection with Pericles, and also honored by Socrates) stood higher than house-wives proper, and became the real representatives of female culture, and ideals of female grace. Sparta, by its legislation, overthrew on principle the proper life 66 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 1L of the family ; the penal laws against bachelors which finally became a necessity, furnish proof, how popular this anti-family legislation was.* Solon found it necessary in the interest of the State to protect by penal enactments the merest natural duties of the marriage-state, at least within the bounds of a minimum requirement ; t so great was already in his day the general dis- inclination to wedlock, which, though forming the foundation of all true morality, was regarded in the Golden Age of Greece as little better than a necessary evil. The bringing about of abortion and the exposing of new-born children, was a right of parents, which was not only protected by laws, but even defend- ed by the most esteemed philosophers. The perverseness not only of frivolous practice, but of the general moral conscious- ness, is manifested most strikingly in the prevalence of unnatural vice, as apologized for even by philosophers themselves ; and the dark picture of St. Paul not merely of Greek morality it- self, but also of the moral consciousness of the Greeks (Rom. i, 21 tqq.~), is perfectly corroborated by historical reality. In cer- tain efforts of recent date to clarify the Christian world-view by the help of the "classical" one, these facts ought not to be left out of sight. The heathen Germans stand in this respect very much higher than the Greeks. However fully the moral consciousness of the worth and dig- nity of the personality is developed, still the dignity of true manhood is conceded only to the free Hellenes, who constituted by far the smallest number of the Greek population. (In Attica at its highest prosperity there were 400,000 slaves, in Corinth 460,000). The barbarian and the slave have no right to the full dignity of personality. Freedom without slavery is, in the eyes of a Greek, an absurdity. The generally prevalent mild treat- ment of their slaves was more an expression of natural kind- heartedness and of personal interest than of conceded right ; the Spartan slave-massacres were the expression of an undisputed right of the State and of the free citizens ; even Plato and Aris- totle are unable to conceive of a State and of political freedom without the personal unfreedom of slavery. The so-called no- tion of " humanitarianism " limits the practice of this virtue to the possessors of slaves ; and the higher the right and the might of the free citizens are placed, so much the more complete and * Plato: Symp., p. 192. f Plutarch: Solon, c. 20. 11.] IDEAL ADVANCE. 67 striking becomes also the rightlessness of the slaves. That slaves are but domestic animals possessed of intelligence was a. general maxim, recognized even by philosophers. Though the reality of the moral consciousness and of the moral life of the Greek is in many respects far below that of other heathen nations, still the moral idea that underlies this reality is a higher one. That which, in the Christian world- view, forms the presupposition of all truly moral life, namely, the reconciliation of the contradiction and of the antagonism in the world of reality, the higher right and the higher power of the personal spirit over unfree nature, this is recognized by the Greeks, though indeed with heathen perversions, in a higher manner than is the case among the earlier heathen nations. Only man as redeemed by the historical redemption-act from the power of his sinful naturalness, and as now for the first having risen to a truly free moral personality, is capable, accord- ing to the Christian view, of accomplishing true morality; also the Hellene makes the reconciliation of the antagonism, the actual harmony of human nature and of existence in general, the presupposition of morality, and conceives this reconciliation as one that falls indeed before human history, but yet is accom- plished by the free act of the personal spirit; whereas with the earlier nations (where the consciousness of the inner antagonism and contradiction is also recognized) the right of the personal spirit is either rejected, or else thrown for its realization into the far future, either into the life after death, or at least toward the close of the world's history. It is true, this thought of a reconciliation is made possible only by the fact that the con- sciousness of moral guilt is kept away from the antagonism that is to be reconciled, and that this antagonism is conceived rather as of a primitive cosmical character, and moreover that not man but the personal gods enter into the sphere thereof, and, bat- tling, overcome, so that there is left for man nothing further than the enjoyable repetition of the same in artistic pl5 sqq. ; Phaed., p. 237 sqq. Gorgias, 470 sqq., 504-509 ; Menon, p. 87 sqq./ Rep., pp. 352, 444, 563, 585; Phil., pp. 40, 64. | Gorgias, pp. 4'>9 sqq., 477, 527. If PMl., p. 11 sqq. ; Gorgias, p. 494 sqq. * Gorgias, pp. 464, 500 ; Menon, p. 87 sqq. 78 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 14. a direct reason-knowledge, and the highest of all that can be known is the foundation and presupposition of virtue; with- out knowledge there is no virtue ; virtue is not a natural quality of man, but is learned and appropriated by learning.* And the knowledge of the good leads with inner necessity to the prac- ticing of that which is recognized as good ; evil rests essentially upon error, and is never committed with consciousness and in- tentionally ;t herein Plato perfectly harmonizes with Socrates. The will has, over against knowledge, no discretion whatever, but is the direct and necessary expression thereof. The lower, sensuous desires can indeed withstand reason, but the will of the spirit itself cannot do so. That also the heart the spirit- ual essence of man himself may have a natural tendency to evil, Plato has not the least conscious suspicion. Nevertheless an obscure presentiment of the entrance of corruption into the universe does find expression in his notion, that the present en- chainment of the spirit to a body is not an original and normal, but a guiltily-incurred state of things. In fact, according to Plato, the soul existed as a rational personality once before in a bodiless state, and only in consequence of a moral transgression was it joined to a trammeling corporeality, so that it is now, as^ it were, fettered in a cell or a dark cavern.J Also for still an- other reason, the good, though indeed the highest end, is yet never fully attainable in the earthly life. For inasmuch as the real world is not solely and purely the work of the absolute God-will, but, on the contrary, a product of two factors, whereof the one is the formless proto-material which is in fact a relative nonentity (jaj 6v), and the other the ideal God-will, and as the former, because not posited by God himself, does not perfectly yield to the formative working of God when impress- ing his ideas upon it (even as the impress of a seal never reflects perfectly clearly every feature of the same), so the world is not an absolutely perfect one, but only the best possible one, is not the pure and mere expression of the rational spirit, but there lingers in it a never entirely-overcomable irrational resid- . unm, an evil . lying in the essence of the world itself, which though not sprung from the fault of moral creatures, is yet the * Menon, p. 87 qq. t/Vxtf., pp. 345, 352 sqq., 358; Menon,p. 95; Gory., p. 468. $ Timaeus, p. 41 ; Phaedrus, p. 246 sqq. ; Rep., p. 514 sqq. 14.] PLATONIC LOVE. 79 ground and source of all moral guilt, a proto-evil.* So also is there in man himself a primitive antagonism never entirely overcomable in the present life, namely, between reason and the lower animal desires, which latter should in fact be morally dominated by reason.f In Plato, therefore, there is lacking to the moral consciousness that joyous confidence which character- izes Christian morality. "Evil can never be annihilated, for there must always be something over against the good; it can- not, however, have its seat among the gods, but it inheres in mortal nature ; therefore man should strive as soon as possible to flee hence and to escape thither." f " True philosophers are minded to strive after nothing other than to decease and be dead, seeing 'that, so long as we still have the body, and our soul is united with this evil [the body], we can never attain to that whereafter we aspire ;" and they lay not violent hands upon themselves simply because they are placed by God in this life as upon a watch, which they are not at liberty to abandon at will.|| Hence morality consists primarily in this, that man turns himself to the ideal, the spiritual, and away from the merely sensuous. This is, however, only one phase of morality, the ideal ; the other phase is the real one. Even as God, in im- pressing his ideas upon matter, shaped the world into an object of beauty, so must also man actively merge and imprint himself into the actual world-existence, and shape it into beauty. Hence virtuousness is delight in the beautiful. And the beautiful is harmony, not merely sensuous but also spiritual. The essence of virtue is, as this delight in the beautiful, love, or eras, a thought that is developed by Plato with very great emphasis (especially in his Phaedrus, Lysis, and Symposium). This is, however, by no means the Christian idea of love that love in which man knows himself at one with another in virtue of com- munion with God, but it is a love to the manifestation, to the beautiful. Not the divine per se is loved, but the concrete, and even essentially sensuous manifestation. It is not a love of soul to soul, but one that clings- to the sensuous form. Hence it has in Plato's state no significancy for the family. It is true, eras exalts itself from the sensuous to the spiritual, to soul-beauty ;T * Tim., p. 46 sqg., 54; PoUt., 269; Rep.> 611 sqq. ; PAaedrus, 246 sqq. t Rep., 436 sqq., 589 ; Gorg., 505. J Theaet., p. 176. Phaedo, p. 63 sqq. \ Ibid., p. 62. Tf Symp., 209 sqq. 80 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ H. the sensuous element, however, remains the basis, and does not receive its worth simply from the spiritual. The beautiful is per se, and in all of its manifestations, a revelation of the divine, and the divine is accessible to us only under the form of the beautiful ; where beauty is, there is also the divine. This is the characteristically Greek stand-point ; beauty and grace excuse all sin ; even the frivolous is recognized as good, provided it is only beautiful. The recognition of love under every form, even under that of unnatural vice, is so characteristic of the Greek, that even Plato attempts a philosophical justification thereof, which is far from complimentary to Greek ethics.* In love, here, predominates by no means self-denial, as is the case with Chris- tian love, but simply pleasure; I love another not for his sake, but for my own sake. This love knows nothing of a self-sacri- ficing suffering, but only a self-enjoying, at farthest only a suf- fering of longing and jealousy. It is true, mere sensuous love as directed to merely fleshly enjoyment, is blamed :f but where a higher spiritual love, not merely to the body but also to the soul, exists, and in the beautiful the divine element is recog- nized, there sensuous love, even when it assumes the form of a misuse of sex, finds its justification, and becomes a virtue, and even a religious enthusiasm.! " Beautifully enacted, it is beau- tiful; otherwise, however, shameful." The very circumstance that Plato speaks so repeatedly and so extensively and with visible approval of this absolutely vicious love [Rom. i, 27], while at the same time he scarcely touches upon the morally close-related mere sexual love, and, in his long discourses on eros, honors wedlock love with not a single word, and further that he attempts to repress | the feeling that instinctively im- presses itself upon him, that there is something shameful there- in, by the help of strangely ingenious turns of thought and disguises and enthusiastically poetical expressions, which can- not but make upon the modern reader a truly distressful impression, all this is a notable and significant index of the moral bewilderment of the Greek spirit. Plato's development of the idea of the moral is as follows : * Symp., p. 181 sqq., 216 sqq. ; Phaedrus, p. 250 sqq. t Gorg., p. 494; Pkaedrus, p. 250; Symj>., p. 180 gqq. J Phaedrm, p. 251 sqq. Symp., p. 183. | PAaedrus, p. 237 sqq. ; comp. 230, 242 ; Symp., p. 183. 14.] THE PLATONIC VIRTUES. 81 Virtue, as essentially constituting a unity, appears primarily as wisdom, aoittia, consisting in a knowledge of the truth and of the good ; upon wisdom as the chief virtue, depend all the othei virtues. Now, in that wisdom brings to the consciousness what really is, and what is not, to be feared in our moral efforts and in our struggle against hostile powers, it develops our natural zeal in acting into the virtue of manliness or courage, avSpeia. And in that it teaches us what is the inner harmony of the soul, and what is the proper subordination of sensuous and irrational desires to reason, it develops the virtue of temperateness or prn- dence, autypcxrvvri, which preserves the right inner order of the soul through the domination of reason over all lower life-forces and pleasure-desires ; these lower desires are not crushed out, but simply kept within proper limits, and placed in the service of reason. In that wisdom guides to outward activity the har- mony of the inner soul-life in its relation to other men, it develops the virtue of justness, which preserves harmony with and among men, in that it respects the rights of each individ- ual; it presupposes the other three virtues, and indeed gives them their proper force and significancy.* To justness belongs also piety or holiness, OGIOTW, which preserves man in his proper relation to the gods; Plato uses here, constantly, the plural.f A more full development of the virtues Plato has not given ; and the necessity of precisely the four ones actually given is based more on the nature of the State than on that of the moral person. A special treatise on duties is not given ; and, in con- sideration of the notion that an inwardly harmonious and hence virtuous soul finds, of itself, the proper course in each particular conjuncture,! such a treatise appears indeed as superfluous. That morality is not conceived of as of a merely individual character, but, on the contrary, as realizing itself essentially in moral communion, is a great advance of the moral con- sciousness; but in that this thought is carried out in the most rigid one-sidedness, and, as it were, with a theoretical passionateness, and in that it lacks the proper historical and re- ligious bases, Plato has arrived, in his enthusiastically and per- sistently pursued ideal of a State, at a positive caricature, which has brought upon the great philosopher, in the .eyes of those * Protag., pp. 332, 349 ; Sep., p. 428 qq., 442 sqq., 591. t Euthyphron, p. 6 sqq. ; Gorg., pp. 507, 522. J Potit., pp. 294, 297. 82 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 14. who look upon the real world with practical sobriety, the ap- pearance of ridiculousness, or at least the reproach of an utterly unpractical theorizing ;* and it has often been undertaken to rescue the reputation of the great man by simply holding his state-theory as a mere ideal not in the least designed for realiza- tion. But both this reproach, and also this attempt at vindi- cating his honor, do injustice to the philosopher. Unquestion- ably his work on the -State is the most mature and the most fully perfected of his writings, one upon which he wrought with the highest and most enthusiastic preference. (His work on the Laws has greater reference to the real world, which as yet was very different from his ideal State, and expresses rather a preliminary expedient, until the true state finds a bold crea- tor.) That his ideal of a state was not intended by him for realization, has no good evidence in its favor, and is on the whole incredible; on the contrary, it cannot be doubted but that Plato made repeated attempts, and with well-grounded hopes, at realizing his state-theory by the help of Dionysius the Younger in Syracuse ;t and his own declarations as to the prac- ticability of his state-theory confirm thi^.J From our own social views these theories differ very widely, it is true; but to a Greek, and especially to the state-institutions of the Doric tribes, which were regarded by Plato with great admiration, they were by no means foreign, and they have already in the laws of Sparta an actual prototype in very essential points. Precisely in its con- trasts to the Christian view of moral communion, to the idea of the Christian Church and of the Christian state, the Platonic state is very instructive. Not individual man, but the state, is the moral person proper, by which all the morality of the individuals is conditioned, pro- duced, and sustained. Not the moral individual persons mak'e the state, but the state makes the moral persons. Without the state, and outside of it, there is no morality proper, but only unculture. Hence the task of the state is to make its citizens into morally good persons, to undertake the cure of souls. The state, which in its inner constitution as a harmonious * Made as early as by Aristophanes, and even by Aristotle : FblM. ii, 1-5, 12. t See K. F. Hermann: Gesch. u. Syst. d.plat. Phil, 1S39, i, 67. 1 Hep., p. 471 tqq. ; 499, 502, 540; Legg., 709. Gorg., p. 464. 14.] STATE-ABSOLUTISM. 83 moral organism, answers to the three phases of the soul-life of man, and represents (1) reason or thought and knowledge, and (2) courage or zeal, 6v/j.og, and (8) sensuousness, in the three classes of society, namely, (1) the savans, who therefore rule, (2) the warriors, and (3) the producers, that is, the instructing, the protecting, and the providing classes,* realizes inner har- mony, and hence at the same time justness and happiness, in that it does not permit each individual to act and work at his personal discretion, and to select his own life-calling, but on the contrary in that it assigns to each his special and appropriate position in the whole, a position which the individual must unquestioningly accept and fulfill, without intermeddling in any manner in any other form of activity. A rigorous separation of ranks and of professions by the state itself, is the uncondi- tional presupposition of a healthy state-life. The rulers have the task of assigning the individuals to the particular classes, according to their capabilities.! The productive class, which corresponds to sensuous desire, has as its special virtue, temper- ateness or modesty, which it realizes by keeping itself within its proper bounds. Courage and wisdom belong to the two higher classes; these two are the gold and silver, while the pro- ductive class is but ignoble brass. The producer is not to con- cern himself, with state matters, but simply to attend to handi- craft and agriculture.^ Slavery is presupposed as a mere matter of course ; however, where practicable, only non-Greeks are to be sold as slaves. The rulers have wisdom as their essential virtue ; there can never be in the state but a few of them, and it is best when there is but one, and this one a philosopher. The good of the whole requires the exclusive dominion of the best, an absolute aristocracy or a monarchy. | And as wisdom can find the right course in each particular case, whereas laws must always be merely general, and often do not apply to particular conjunc- tures, hence the power of those who rule should not be cramped by many laws, but must have scope for free movement, and must decide in each particular case with entire discretion ; and the wise ruler will often, without law and against the will of the * Sep., p. 369 sqq., 412 sqq., 435. t Ibid., pp. 412-415. \Polit., p. -289 sqq. ; Sep., pp. 374, 397. Rep., p. 469. | Polit., p. 292 sqq., 297 ; Rep., pp. 473, 540. 7 84 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 14. citizens, and hence with force, realize the weal of the state, and force the citizens to let themselves be made happy.* The truly free personality is conceded accordingly only to the sage, who is at the same time the ruler ; all the other citizens of the state are, in their entire life, absolutely subject to the state, the spiritual essence of which finds its expression not so much in abstract law as in the perfected personality of the rul- ing sage. Though the members of the third class are left more free, still this is done only out of contempt ; u even if shoe- cobblers are bad, still they bring little danger to the state."! The true citizen, the one possessing the virtue of wisdom and manliness, is under the absolute guidance of the state ; the ab- solutism of the state is without limitation. The two higher classes, as the proper and complete representatives of the spirit- ual essence of the state, the sentinels of the same, are reared and educated, and determined in their collective life by the state. In their education first importance is given to music and gym- nastics, in order that they may learn to love and practice har- mony; the education of the future rulers who can become rulers only at the age of fifty years, after having passed the test of severe trials requires, additionally, special acquaintance with mathematics and philosophy.^ To any other religious culture than that given by philosophy, Plato, who clearly saw the worthlessness of the popular religion, could not refer. The state as including in itself and guiding all morality, and as realizing justness, has all and every right; the individual citizen of the state has rights only in so far as the state concedes them to him ; even to his life he has no right, so soon as he is no longer capable of benefiting the state; the physicians are charged with the duty of letting the incurably sick perish with- out help.] The state alone is entitled to property; private property is not to be allowed. The producing class labors not for itself, but solely for the state. IT With this principle Plato supposes himself to have quenched at once all the sources of contention and disquiet. Even the act of poesy stands under the rigid censorship of the state ; and dramatic poetry is not to be tolerated at all.** The appropriate meters to be used in *Pblit., pp. 293-296; Sep., pp. 473, 540. i Ibid., p. 421. J Ibid., p. 402 sqq., 424, 519 sqq., 535. Ibid., p. 386 sqq. d; P- 405 qq. t 409. U Ibid., pp. 416, 464. ** Ibid., p. 391 sqq. , 568. 14.] PLATONIC SEX-RELATIONS. 85 poetry are carefully prescribed, and of musical instruments only the cithara and the lyre are allowed.* The family is not the foundation, but only a branch of the state, and merges itself into it. Personality has here no right of its own. No one consort belongs to the other, but both be- long exclusively to the state. Wedlock proper is consequently inadmissible, on the contrary the citizen is obligated to the be- getting of children in the interest of the state ; in this connec- tion personal love to the sex has no validity, but only civic duty. The citizen is not permitted to choose for himself the wife (who is conceded to him only temporarily), but the state gives her to him, ostensibly by lot, but in reality the rulers are to "make use of falsehood and deception," and cunningly to guide the lot according to their own judgment, so as always to bring together the most suitable pairs. Men are under obliga- tion to beget from their thirtieth to their fifty-fifth year ; women to bear from their twentieth to their fortieth year. This of it- self implies that there is to be no permanent marriage relation ; on the contrary a change of wives is expressly required ; no one is permitted to regard any woman as his own exclusive posses- sion.f It is laid down as a principle for the free and active citizens proper, " that all the women should be in common to all the men, and that no woman should live solely with one man, and that also the children are to be in common, so that no father shall know the child begotten by him, and no child its own father."! Hence the children are, immediately after their birth, to be taken away from their mothers, and to be reared in common on the part of the state, and the greatest possible care is to be taken that the mother shall never again recognize her child. The children are nursed by the women in common and interchangeably ; feeble and physically imperfect children arc to be exposed. After the lapse of the determined period of life, the procreation with the persons specifically assigned by the state, and as having taken place at the order of the state, is to cease, and, from this time on, both the men and the women may fqrm temporary connections with each other on the princi- ple of elective affinity, with the one proviso that births must be prevented, or, where this cannot be done, the child must be left * Rep., pp. 398, 399. t Ibid., 449 sqq. t Ibid. ,457. Ibid. , 457 sq q. 86 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 14 to perish without food.* The woman is not a family-mother, but only a state-citizen, and she has political duties, in real and even magisterial state-offices, to fulfill. The women must per- form the same work as the men, must even take part, entirely nude, in the gymnastic exercises, must march out in war, though in battle they are to occupy only the rear-ranks ; for in- deed between men and women there is no other difference than simply that the former beget, and the latter bear, and that the former are stronger than the latter.f This family-undermining absolutism of the state has to do, however, only with the first two classes, while the producing class are less affected by this care of the state for them, and may act with greater freedom. The great task toward which all moral community-life is directed, namely, to realize the idea of the body politic, by means of the moral freedom of the indi- vidual, Plato was unable to accomplish otherwise than by an unconditional and unquestioning non-permission of the free personal self-determination of the individual. Objective moral- ity entirely swallows up the subjective. This is, however, not peculiar to the view of Plato, but is the Greek tendency in gen- eral. Plato manifests rather a decided progress toward the development of the free moral personality. While in the legis- lation of Sparta, somewhat as in that of the Chinese, the imper- sonal law held ruthless domination, and disallowed of the personal self-determination of the individual in very essential things, and while in the democracy of Athens the irrational caprice of the masses was the predominant power over the in- dividual, in the Platonic state the personal spirit of the wisely taught and tested regent attains to domination. From -the stand-point of heathen antiquity, which knows of no right of the person over against the state, but concedes the absolute right of the state over the individual, this is a progress; and that, which appears therein as unnatural and as a harsh one-sidedness indicates not so much the untruthfulness of the consequential pr< >gress, as rather the untruthfulness of the fundamental view common to all the Greeks. That the spirit of wisdom and power can be and is to be poured out upon all flesh [Joel iii, 1], and that there is no dif- ference before God, but that all are equally called to be children *.%>., 461. Mbid., 451 sqq., 471, 540. 15.] PLATONIC CASTE. 87 of the truth and of wisdom, this thought is unknown to entire heathendom, and therefore also to the greatest of heathen phi- losophers. Of a morality absolutely valid for all men and with- out exception, Plato knows nothing ; without slavery, society does not appear to the Greek as possible ; but the slave is not called to, nor capable of, free self-determination, and hence also not of true morality; and even of the free, only a relatively small number are accessible to true wisdom and virtue. Capa- bility and incapability for the good are transmitted through natural generation from parents to children.* The reason for this dividing of humanity into a minority who represent reason, and into an irrational, passive multitude who require absolute guidance, lies not exclusively in the general Greek national con- sciousness, but also in the philosophical world-theory of Plato in general. The primitive dualism of existence manifests itself also in humanity. Even as the world is not an absolutely pure and perfect expression of the spirit, and as the rational spirit is not an absolute power, but has simply to shape a formless proto- material not created by it, and to impress itself upon it, without however being able entirely to master and spiritually transfigure it, so also in humanity the men of the rational spirit, namely, the philosophers, stand over against the spiritually dependent and relatively unspiritual multitude, whose destination it is to be absolutely guided and shaped by the former. SECTION XV. The essential advance of the ethical view of Plato beyond earlier theories consists in this, that he eman- cipated the idea of the good from all dependence on the individual pleasure-feeling, that he conceived it as unconditionally valid and lying in God himself, and that consequently he regarded morality as God-like- ness, as an image of God in man, and hence as a phase of the ^spiritual life constituting an essential part of rationality itself, and that in consequence thereof he conceived morality as a per se perfectly unitary life, and reduced the plurality of moral forms of action to *Rep., 459 ^., 546. 88 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 15. a single principle, namely wisdom. But the charac- teristically heathen dualism, which (though reduced by him to its minimum) is yet not entirely overcome, rendered it impossible for him to rise to the full free- dom of the personal spirit in God and in man, and hence to the full knowledge of the moral idea. The real personality is recognized neither in its rights and power, nor in its guilt. There remains in all exist- ence, even in the most highly developed moral life, a never entirely overcomable residuum of an unfree, un- spiritual, and morally spirit-trammeling matter, over which God himself is not absolutely master. But the limitation of the moral lies not in the guilt of the per- sonal spirit, but in the unspiritual (and not by it entirely controllable) nature-ground of things. The possibility, and therefore also the requirements, of the moral are different for the different classes of men, but even the most free is not entirely free. The moral freedom of the freest, namely, the philosophers, is tram- meled by the fetters of a corporeality not in harmony with the moral task, that of the rest of men by lack of knowledge and of moral capacity, and that of the free Greek citizens, additionally, by the power of the rulers as extending beyond the expressed laws, and that of the unfree Greek citizens, still additionally, by the weight of the entire mass that presses upon them from above. From this progressively and descend- ingly increasing unfreedom there is no redemption within the sphere of historical reality, but only yon- side of history, through death. Morality bears, neither in its progressive realization nor in its guilty perver- sion, the character of historicalness, is in no respect a power essentially modificatory of universal history, and consciously aiming at such modification as its 15.] PLATONISM AND CHRISTIANITY. 89 end ; and even the ideal state is and remains simply the very limited activity-sphere of a special moral virtuosity of the governing individual spirit, without a higher world-historical purpose in relation to the totality of humanity. Also the moral consciousness itself rises not entirely above the character of the merely individual ; the connection of the same with the God-consciousness is only of a loose character, is not really based in the same. The gain accruing to moral knowledge through the labors of Plato is not to be lightly estimated. Light and order are given to the previously dark and confused mass. There is henceforth no more question of merely isolated and not deeper-grounded moral rules, but morality has acquired a firmer basis, has come here for the first to serious self-examination. In fact, Plato oc- cupies himself so predominantly with the foundation-laying thoughts that he does not reach the task of carrying out a special doctrine of virtue or duty. In these ground-thoughts there are, in so far as is possible from a heathen stand-point, some approximations to a Christianly-moral consciousness; and they would have been more marked still, had the philosopher only succeeded in severing the chain which still held the already floating ship fast anchored to the soil of naturalism, namely, by overcoming the thought of an unspiritual pro to-material as oflering a hinderance to the personal God, in a word, had he succeeded in changing the fttj w which lies at the basis of the real world, into an OVK bv. But neither Plato nor the heathen spirit in general was able to do this. Even Aristotle was able only silently to vail the, also to him, troublesome thought of dualism, but not scientifically to master it. But wherever the rational spirit is not absolutely the ground and life of every thing, there also the full idea of morality is not possible ; for only the thought of the complete mastery of the spirit over every thing unspiritual, and the confidence of untrnmineled lib- erty, assure to'morality foundation-ground and courage. Though in the recognition of the limits of freedom there lies an approximation to the Christian thought of the natural de- 90 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 15. pravity of the human race, yet there lies in it, on the other hand, also an all the greater departure from the same ; for these limits are not placed in the sphere of moral guilt, and hence of moral freedom, but yon-side of morality in the sphere of a nature-substratum not to be overcome by the moral spirit. The hampering of morality has not sprung from an historical act, and hence is not to be overcome by an historical act. The con- sciousness of the moral imperfection of the world, which despite all the idealism of the Platonic world- view comes often to pain- ful expression, leads not to the thought of a needed redemption. The sage emancipates himself, so far as, in view of the imper- fection inherent in the essence of all existence, it is possible, from the limitations of his moral life, and he emancipates others only through philosophical instruction and through absolutistic state-guidance, but not through a sanctifying communion- grounding historical act. In the idea of the state there lies indeed the presentiment, that morality, in its true character, is not a merely individual quality, but, on the contrary, has an historical signiflcancy and task, but Plato does not rise beyond the mere presentiment; and when he is on the very point of passing beyond the limits of a merely individual morality, and into the sphere of an his- torical one, he hesitatingly checks his step^nd turns back. His State forms no link in history, and has no history as its goal. As it is not sprung of history, but only of the ingenious intellect of a theoretical philosopher, so it is designed to be nothing other than the platform upon which the geniality of the indi- vidual personality of the philosophic regent may find scope for itself. Neither people nor ruler are to be the representatives of an historical idea; on the contrary, the people is only the passive material for the formative hand of the state-artist, and the ruler only the executor of a philosophic theory. The state itself is to be only an individual organism along-side of many other state-organisms, likewise ruled by individual geniality. Hence it must also be only very small ; even a thousand citizens suffice. The thought of regarding the state as a vital member in an historical collective organism, lies very far from Plato. Hence, though his state is a moral organic system, yet it has no world-historical character ; it has neither behind it an historical presupposition, nor before itself an historical goal. That hu- 15.] RELIGIOUS DEFECTIVENESS. 91 inanity in general is a goal of the moral striving, that it may be brought together into a moral unity, that a state of peace among all nations is to be aimed at of all this Plato has not the remot- est presentiment; rather does war appear, even for his ideal state, as in accordance with order, and as a necessary matter of course ; for in fact Greeks and non-Greeks are enemies by na- ture.* Let this state-ideal of the profoundest Greek philoso- pher, as presented without any trammeling from a resisting real world, be compared with the Old Testament theocratic state as brought to realization among a stubbornly resisting people, and which had, from the very beginning, a world-his- torical goal, and which kept in view, and had as the basis of its entire organization, the thought of the salvation, and hence also of the peace'and unity, of entire humanity, and the result will be very suggestive. Most manifestly appears the weakness of Platonic ethics in its relation to the religious consciousness. The beautiful con- ception of the God-likeness of the moral man, Plato is not able to carry out ; the founding of the moral upon the divine will is foreign to him, and must have been so, for the Greek knows nothing of a revelation of this will, and the philosopher could not invent one ; he was only able to refer to the rational con- sciousness of man himself; but to raise this consciousness to a universally-extant and valid one Plato did not venture to hope, and hence he placed simply the authority and even the strong dictatorial power of the philosophers, in the stead of the author- ity of a divine revelation. Also his profoundly-conceived God- idea, which far surpassed all previous results of heathenism, Plato did not venture to carry out in its entire ethical signifi- cancy, and to make it consequentially the basis of the moral. It is true he is far removed from the folly of certain modern theories, which present morality as entirely independent of piety ; he in fact makes piety a very essential element of all moral life, and derives even from the idea of a divine judgment after death, a very potent motive for morality ;f still, piety is with him not the foundation of all the virtues, but only a single one of the same, and that too not the first one, but only a form of justness ; and even such as it is he ventures not to refer it djrectly to the philosophically-recognized God-idea, but only to * Rep., p. 373, 469 seq. t Gorg., p. 523 sgq. 92 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 16. the gods of the popular religion. But as he himself exposes the immoral character of the Greek mythology with a noble indig- nation, and on that account, bitterly censures the so highly and universally-revered Homer, nay, even would have his poems, for moral reasons, banished from his ideal state,* it is consequently difficult to say how he could justify and require piety toward these gods. There remains here a wide-reaching and unbridged chasm in his ethical teachings. SECTION XVI. The completer of the Platonic philosophy, and of Greek philosophy in general, namely, Aristotle, who in many respects passed independently beyond Plato, and who was less idealistic than he, and more devoted to the study of sober reality, presented ethics for the first time as a special systematically carried-out science, in connection with Physics on the one hand, and with Politics on the other. The greatest possible repres- sion of the dualism of the primitive elements of exist- ence, as still yet admitted by Plato, leads Aristotle not to a deriving of the moral idea from his more fully developed God-idea, but to a still more confident grounding of the same in the rational self-conscious- ness, which appears here less clogged than in Plato. A sound psychology affords for ethics a scientifically firm basis, but the repression of the Platonic antith- esis of the ideal and of reality gives it a morally feebler character. Of the three different presentations of Aristotelian ethics, only the Ethica NicomacTieia (that is, ad Nicomachum) is, in the eyes of the trustworthy results of criticism,t to be regarded as * Sep., p. 377 tqq., 386 tqq., 598 sgq., 605. t Spengel, in his Abhandl. d. Kgl. Baierschen Akad., philos.-philol. lK ?* and by Marcus Aurelius Antoninus.^ On the dualistic antithesis of matter and spirit rests the cor- responding ethical antithesis between merely sensuously-natu- ral objective existence and the rational spirit in the individual free subject. Not the mere nature-entity, but the spirit, is the true entity, and it is such in full, freely self-legislating self-sufficiency ; its destination is to manifest itself as inde- pendent in relation to nature, and to base itself entirely upon itself. Not the passive, but the active entity is the solely true one, not enjoyment but activity; it is only as active that the spirit is in its true reality, whereas, as merely enjoy- ing, it sinks below spirituality. Man, as related to objective existence, is a self-poised absolutely freely self-determining being, is, as a rational spirit, perfectly self-sufficient, needs nothing outside of himself in order to be a spirit, to be free, to be happy; he should not let himself be determined by any thing whatever external to himself. Whatever is to have worth for man, and hence is to form a part of, and to con- tribute to, his perfection and happiness, must proceed from and depend upon himself alone ; every thing else, whatever it may be, concerns him not, is indifferent to him, can, and may, neither hinder nor promote his perfection and happi- ness. It is in being self-dependent that the wise man is truly free. The essence of man, in distinction from the brute, is not enjoying and feeling, but thinking ; it is not in enjoy- ing, but in thinking, that he is free, that he is a rational spirit; and the more he seeks to enjoy external objects and finds pleasure therein, so much the more is he dependent and unfree, so much the more is he irrational, and hence so much the less a true man. Thinking and not feeling is, therefore, the decisive criterion of the truth and of the good ; hence there should be first judging and then acting. All rational, and hence moral, activity must rest on knowledge ; to act * His lectures, for the most part merely popular moral exhortations, are preserved in Arrian ; besides these we have the Enchiridion Epic- teti, Which has lieen much used even in Christian times. t From him we have Tu etf eavrov , (moral meditations) disconnect- ed, and, in many cases, merely suggested thoughts and life rules, with much repetition and without regular development. 134 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [24: from mere feeling is irrational ; there is no virtue without knowledge. Philosophy itself is a practice of virtue, and knowledge is the first and highest virtue. Out of the knowl- edge of the good springs, of itself and from inner necessity, pleasure in the good and a striving after it, just as from a knowledge of the evil springs an abhorrence of the same. But these movements of the sensibilities are not the ground, but only the attendants of the moral activity ; the ground thereof is knowledge alone. From erroneous knowledge, however, spring irrational sensibility-movements and striv- ings of the soul, that is, the passions, which are consequent- ly to be regarded as a soul-disease. Now, though all evil springs from error, yet is man nevertheless responsible there- for, for the error itself is guiltily incurred. It is by the knowledge of the good, that is, by perfect consciousness, that volition is distinguished from impulse or instinct. The will aims at the truly-known good, impulse at the merely seemingly good. Knowledge, as an essential manifestation of rationality, is, like the latter itself, germinally innate in man, and hence it is in all men essentially the same ; simply the further development and the particular application of the same is left to one's own judgment. The essence and the fundamental thought of the good is conformity to nature (6/zoAoym, convenientia, TO Kara Qvatv, conven- ienter natures vivere). Nature is taken here, not as outer sensuous nature in contradistinction to the self-conscious spirit, but as the general order of the world, as the natura rerum, the inner conformity-to-law of the All, and, above all, the rational nature and conformity-to-law of one's oVn spir- itual existence and life. Hence conformity to nature is agree- ment with one's self the inner order and spiritual health of the life. Even the brute puts forth effort primarily not from pleasure and for pleasure, but for natural self-preservation and self-development. The true nature of man, however, is not the sensuous nature but the reason. To live right signi- fies, therefore, to live according to reason. Hence evil is a contradiction to the rational nature of man, and the direct opposite of the good, differs from the good not merely quantitatively, but also qualitatively and essentially, is the anti-natural and anti-rational. (24. STOIC VIRTUE. 135 Virtue is, therefore, in its very essence, a "being well ;" hence it has a feeling of happiness as its immediate and necessary consequence, and thus it is itself per se the highest good. He who is truly virtuous is happy in the same man- ner as God ; he who is vicious is necessarily wretched. Not this happiness-feeling, however, but the good as such, is the rational end of the moral activity ; virtue is to be sought for its own sake without reference to the happiness-feeling ; the pleasure-sensation is indeed the consequence, but not the end of moral action. There are, in fact, other pleasure-sensations than those which flow from virtue, and other pain-sensations than those which follow from vice ; also external things, things not dependent on us and our free determination, such as health, riches, etc., may excite pleasure-sensations, and hence contribute to our external happiness. Now, if the end of our striving were not the good per se, but happiness, then our effort would be directed toward a something that is not fully within our power ; but nothing can be truly good, and hence truly to be sought after, which is not dependent upon us and within the scope of our will. The pleasure which arises independently of us from external things may be agreeable, and hence these things may be useful, but real goods they are not. Hence the antithesis of the honestum (TO KaOfjKov, TO naAov) and the utile. Thus the happiness and per- fection of the sage rests entirely upon himself ; he is the free creator of his well-being; all that is really* good depends solely upon himself ; all that is not dependent upon him af- fects and disturbs him not. Every wise man is a rich man, a king. \s the good differs from the evil, not in degree but in essence, hence all the virtues are essentially equal to and homogeneous with each other ; for* a virtue inferior to another could be possible only by its being somewhat participant in evil ; but this is impossible from its very idea. Hence who- ever has one virtue has them all ; and they are all intimately involved in each other. Likewise, all vices are essentially equal to each other, and, e. g., to kill a cock needlessly is just as bad as to commit parricide. From the Stoic notion of the self-based freedom of the sage, as well as from their view of the essence of virtue, it follows that there may be entirely perfect men, men who are 136 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [24. free of all error and of all immorality, fully possessed of all knowledge and virtue and happiness. That there really are such is taken for granted ; and delineations of this self- acquired glory are given in the most glowing colors, and form a favorite topic of Stoic philosophy. On the other hand, we find not the least trace of the notion of a natural corruption of mankind ; there is admitted (as was the case in Aristotle's system) simply a difference between the rude mul- titude little inclined to, and little capable of, the good, and the more happily-gifted ones, the latter being of course the Stoics themselves ; and it is given as an essential character- istic of a sage, never to repent of any thing.* In consequence of the diametrical antagonism between good and evil, there is no mean moral sphere between the two, no sphere of moral indifference. There are indeed things that are per se indiffer- ent to man, and which can hence per se neither increase nor diminish his worth and happiness, but their 'actual applica- tion is in each particular case either good or bad. In classi- fying the virtues, the Stoics, for the most part, follow Plato. Zeno himself based the moral on religion; also some of his disciples understand by the "nature" with which man is to be in harmony, the divine contents and the 'divine con- formity-to-law of nature, and hence that which harmo- nizes with the divine will ; and they conceive of reason as a manifestation of the divine activity in things. But the later Stoics, for the iHost part, lost sight of this religious character of the moral, and presented it as quite independent of re- ligion, as a spiritual life-sphere resting strictly and inde- pendently upon itself. In Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius the religious element comes again more into the fore-ground ; they recognize reverence fo"r the gods, or for God, as a virtue and as a ground of the moral, conceive of virtuousness as God-likeness, and viciousness as godlessness, and even at- tribute high worth to prayer, though here, of course, there is no trace of penitential prayer, but for the most part, only the spirit qf the Pharisee's prayer : "God, I thank thee that -I am not as other men."t It is' in fact not impossible that in * Cic. : Pro Murcena, 29. 1 Arrian : Dissert. Epict., iii, 24, 96 tqq. ; iv, 10, 14 sqq., (ed. Schweigh.) ; M. Aurel. Ant. : f iavrov, ix, 40. 24.] STOIC PRACTICE. 137 the more religious tendency of later Stoicism there is a de- gree of influence from Christianity. This view of the moral produced in fact among the Stoics an earnest moral striving, though without enthusiasm or heart, and only in the manner of a cold logical calculating. Feeling amounts to nothing at all ; of the potency of love there is not a trace ; thought passes directly over into action, and feeling merely accompanies the act as a something en- tirely indifferent. The love of neighbor is regarded only as a mode of action, but not as an aifair of the heart. The sage ought indeed to help the wretched according to his means and according to their worthiness, but to feel compas- sion, or even to act as if one felt it, would be unworthy of a wise man ; for the truly wise man is above all suffering ; and the wretched suffer only from lack of knowledge, because they regard external things, which are not within their own control, as reai goods.* The friendliness to man which is so earnestly recommended by the Stoics flows not from love, and their patience under received injustice springs only from contemptuous pride. Hence, while, on the one hand, wrath, revenge, envy, slander, etc., are condemned as unworthy of the sage, partly because every passive feeling-movement is immoral, and in part because the sage is too proud to allow himself to be disturbed by the acts and manners of others, yet, on the other hand, it is held as an unworthy weakness to forgive others for their injustice, for that jvould be equiva- lent to declaring the injustice as indifferent, and to lightly" esteeming justice. f The Christian principle, "Forgive and ye shall be forgiven," has no force for a Stoic, because he believes himself never to be in circumstances to need forgiveness. The morality of the Stoics is a constant contest of the spirit against sensuous nature and against the unspiritual and irra- tional in the objective world in general ; but as this contest is directed against a primordial and never entirely-overcome- able antagonism in existence itself, and hence can never lead *Epict. : EncJiir., 16; M. Anton., v, 36; vii, 43 ; Diog. L., vii, 123; Cicero : Pro MuranM, c. 29 ; Seneca : De dementia, ii, 5, 6. t Stobsous : Echffce etkicce, ii, 7, p. 190 (Heeren) ; Diog. L., vii, 123 ; Cic. : Pro Mur., 23. 138 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [24. to an objective victory, it assumes consequently not so much an actively outward-working character, as rather that of a passive resistance against irrational reality. The sage does not undertake to produce a real world of the moral spirit ; on the contrary, he retreats within himself in proud contempt of the actual world ; only himself, but not the outer world, can he make perfect ; the real struggle is carried on not by a victory-confident assaulting of immoral reality, but by a con- temptuous turning away from the same, by an indifference to pleasure and pain, the depicting of which is given again and again in endless reiteration. This blunt, indifferent en- during of pain is not the fruit of a pious faith in a divine world-government or of love toward mankind, but it is the proud defiance of the absolutely self-relying subject as against a world imbued with a primitive and essential irrationality. This indifference toward all that excites the sensibilities re- strains indeed the Stoic from Epicurean senguality, but is very far from leading to a true resistance of one's self ; the sensuous is only despised, but not positively assailed. Stoic ethics requires no severe self-denial, no fasting, no jenuncia- tion of sensual enjoyment ; it only requires that one be mod- erate and that one place no value on the enjoyment ; but after all, this restraint was, for the most part, but a mere flourish- ing of rhetoric ; Seneca accepted, with the greatest suavity, riches upon riches, which his pupil Nero conferred upon him. The lightly esteeming of the non-spiritual extends also to 'the physical life. The Stoics indeed regard the instinct of self-preservation as a fundamental impulse of human nature, and as a strictly normal expression of the law which requires harmony with one's self and with nature, but it is not incon- sistent therewith that they should regard life itself as an object of indifference seeing that it is not within man's own control. Death must not be feared, but must as a power not within our control be despised ; and in so far as it is a nature-law, and one that liberates us from a painful bodily life, it is to be regarded even with pleasure. The thought of immortality is, in this connection, regarded merely as a possibility ; if the life of the soul continues on, then the wise man is happy ; but if it ceases, then ceases for him also all pain; in neither case is there the least ground for fear. But 24.] CHAMPIONSHIP OF SUICIDE. 139 the Stoic goes still further. The wise roan is a free lord over himself ; but in death he is overcome by an external power. It does not become the sage, therefore, to let the close of his life depend merely on any such extraneous power ; it is but a visualization of his own self-dependent freedom, that he should close his life when it pleases himself, that is, when he has satisfactory reasons therefor. To the Stoic, suicide is, under certain circumstances, not only allowed, but even a duty, a heroic virtue. Among the circumstances that justify suicide, irrespective of self-sacrifice for country or friends, are the following: great distress, poverty, incurable disease, physical maiming, and other oppressive afflictions, depriva- tion of liberty, and in general, any essential hinderance to living freely and in conformity to reason, such as infirmity from age ; all these are divine hints that it is time to take one's voluntary departure; "The door is open," is a saying which the Stoic fondly reiterates as an expression of his per- fect liberty, even in regard to the ending of his life.* Sui- cide is defended with great zeal, and almost with enthusiasm, by Seneca, on the ground that it is an assertion of the true self-dependence and freedom of man ; for this reason man may and should proceed to suicide even when the above freedom-hindering evils are merely in threatening prospect, inasmuch as, if he does not, he may in the end be hindered from the accomplishment of this self-liberation. Only a single way leads into life, but thousands lead out of it. No one is wretched save through his own fault ; for if misfor- tune falls upon him, he is at liberty to depart; life keeps none back. The wise man lives only so long as life pleases him ; the lancing of an artery opens to him the way to free- dom. Death is, after all, unavoidable, why then adjourn it till the evil day ? The foulest death is better than the clean- est slavery ; the prudent man seeks the easiest death ; yet if it cannot be otherwise, he does not shun even a painful suicide. t And the practice corresponded to the theory. Zeno himself is said to have hanged himself at an advanced age, because he had broken one of his fingers ; his disciple Cleanthes * Diog. L. , vii, 130 ; Arrian, i, 9, 20 ; i, 24, 20 ; i, 25, 18 tqq. ; ii, 1, 20 ; $A. Anton.,v, 29 ; Cic. : De Finibus, iii, 18. t Epiat. ii, 5 (17) ; vi, 6 (58) ; viii, 1 (70) ; De ira, iii, 15, (ed. Fickert). 140 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [24 starved himself to death because his gums became sore. The frequent suicides among the Roman Stoics are a matter of notoriety. This doctrine and this practice are often regarded as in conflict with the general view of the Stoics, which, in fact, denies that pain is a real evil. The inconsistency is only apparent, and contains, at all events, a very true con- fession. If man has no higher consolation against the mis- eries of existence than the pride of the self-centered, self- satisfied individual spirit, then it is simply mere truthfulness when he confesses that he is not equal to the misery of real life, that he has not the moral power entirely to overcome it by morality, and to say with joy, "We glory also in tribu- lations." The Stoic knows nothing of an almighty father- love of God, and less still of any personal guilt ; he lacks the entire basis upon which the courage of a Christian heart can even grow stronger amid all the buffetings of life ; he rises only to a defiance of the miseries of reality ; but this defiance, seeing that it is not exalted to moral courage by the pious confidence of a God-thirsting heart, is not equal to the task of humbly bowing itself under suffering, but only to that of destroying itself in bitter accusation against the moral order of the world, and in the consciousness that the real world is not worthy longer to contain such a sage. Stoic morality is of a purely individual character, aims only at virtualizing the free self-dependence and self-sufficiency of the individual subject. For an objective reality of the moral thought, and for a moral community-life, the Stoic has no ap- preciation, and hence also none for the naturally-moral basis of society, namely, marriage, which, in fact, as requiring self- submission to an objective moral reality, appears as a trammel- ing fetter for the individual subject; and it is doubtless only from the striving after the maintenance of the complete self- sufficiency of the wise subject in the face of all objective moral reality, that are to be explained the strangely perverted views of the sexual relations that prevailed among the Stoics. By them marriage itself was lightly esteemed, and, while passion- ate love and lustfulness were condemned, sexual communion outside of marriage was expressly defended against all crit- icism ; * and of Zeno and Chrysippus, it is made out with a * Epict. : Enchir. 33. 24.] DISESTEEM OF MARRIAGE. 141 good degree of certainty, that they required community of wives among the wise, and that they declared allowable, sexual communion between nearest blood-relatives (even between par- ents and children), and also whoredom, self-pollution and ped- erasty.* It must not be forgotten that in these opinions with the exception of incest, which is readily explainable from their one-sided, calculating spirit, the Stoics had the moral con- sciousness of the Greeks on their side, and that for their com- munity of wives they were countenanced by the teachings of Plato. Also in other respects their moral relations to other men are neither frank nor pure. The lofty contempt which the sage indulges in toward all non-sages, disengages him also from many moral duties toward them; thus he is not under obliga- tion always to tell them the truth, ; falsehood is allowable not only in war, to the enemy, but also in many other cases, especially in view of attaining an advantage.! The morality of the Stoic is the pride of the natural man who is conscious of being a moral creature, but who has no suspicion of a morality higher than and transcending the indi- vidual subject, nor of a personal moral depravity. His oft- repeated high-sounding descriptions of self-complacency make any thing but an agreeable impression. This pride restrains him, it is true, from many unworthy acts; in consequence, how- ever, of his total lack of an objective standard, it did not guard him from grave moral errors, nor from an almost fanatical hate against a higher world-theory, which, at a later period, offered itself to him in Christianity ; and Marcus Aurelius was not in the least deterred by his so high-sounding discourses on kind- ness, tolerance, and charity, from letting loose a fearful perse- cution upon the Christians, in whose martyr-courage he could discover only criminal obstinacy. Though Stoic ethics was distinguished from the essentially-related ethics of the Cynics by the fact that it discarded the unspiritual and unre- fined form of the latter, and that it respected the spiritual under every phase, and hence also in art, and placed a high estimate upon the worthy appearance of the body and upon cleanliness, nevertheless at bottom it does not really transcend * Diog. L., vii, 13, 33, 131, 188; Sext. Emp. : 'TCirorvTruofif, iii, 24. fStob. : Ed. eth., ii, 7, p. 230 (Heeren). 142 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 25 - the same. It does not rise beyond the mere formal notion of the moral as a conformity to nature ; the material constructions to be put upon the contents of the moral idea are left to the subjective discretion of the individual; and though it really stands higher than Epicurean ethics, still it did not spiritually vanquish the same. Instead of an absolutely and objectively valid moral idea, and of the expression of a divine will, we find only man's subjective knowledge of his own nature ; the contents of the moral law, the Stoic discovers only by the observation of his own personal peculiarities ; and the possi- bility that this self of his might be a morally perverted one he does not even remotely suspect. SECTION XXV. Epicureanism and Stoicism are two diametrically opposed but also mutually requiring and complement- ing phases of the Greek spirit ; both are equally one- sided, both are equally remote from the Christian ethical idea ; both refer all moral truth back to the individual subject. In the place of Christian moral- ity, the Epicureans offer joyous voluptuousness; the Stoics offer the high-minded pride of complete self- righteousness ; neither party feels the least need of redemption, of divine grace ; "for the Epicureans regard the per se sinful as right, while the Stoics im- agine themselves to have overcome the same through their per se pure individual will. Epicurean ethics emphasizes the nature-phase in man ; Stoic the spirit- phase ; the former teaches an unresisting, voluptuous giving-over of self to sensuous nature, the latter an earnest but only partially successful resisting of the same; the former is absolutely indiifeient as to moral knowledge, natural instinct supplies the place of knowledge ; the latter manifests a busy seeking after knowledge, and esteems it as a virtue ; the former is a crude realism, in all essential features a materialistic naturalism ; the latter is a one-sided idealism, in all essential 25.] EPICUREANISM VERSUS STOICISM. 143 features a ploddingly-calculating spiritualism; the former bears a feminine character, is passive, yielding, lax ; the latter bears a masculine character, is active, earnest, rigorous; the former suited better the effeminate Ionic tribe and the Orient, the latter rather the stern Doric tribe and the Romans. The Epicurean seemingly gives sway to the universal, namely, to nature, to which the individual subordinates himself; in reality, however, the individual subject is set free from the bonds of the universal, of the spiritual, of rationality; the Stoic also seemingly subordinates the individual subject to a general thought, namely, the moral idea; in reality, however, also here the universal is made to yield to the individual subject; in the place of a general moral idea we find, strictly speaking, only the calculating opinion of the individual ; it is the self-will of the subject in the face of the spiritual objective world, namely, history, that asserts itself as rational freedom; According to both systems, therefore, the truth is found only within the sub- ject ; nature and existence in general have value for the Epicu- rean only in so far as they can be enjoyed, that is, in so far as they are for the individual subject, in every other respect existence is indifferent ; in the eyes of the Stoic, existence is truth only in so far as it appears in the subject ; the sage is the embodiment of the moral order of the universe, which, apart from him, exists but very imperfectly. In both systems the higher thought of Plato, namely, that, by the moral, the real harmony of existence, the harmony between nature and spirit, is realized, is one-sidedly perverted ; the Epicurean effects this harmony only by sacrificing the rationally-personal spirit to nature, the Stoic by sacrificing nature to the individual per- sonal spirit ; it is no longer a harmonizing, but a giving up, of one of the two phases of existence. Though Stoic ethics is in many respects graver and more worthy of man than Epicurean, nevertheless both systems are equally remote from the Christian view. The Epicurean does not recognize the spiritual personality as the highest factor ; the Stoic does not recognize the rights of objective reality; but Christianity recognizes both as absolutely belonging to each other. In both systems, the natural man, the individual sub- ject, thrusts himself in his fortuitous reality into the fore- ground, as having the highest claims ; in both the subject is of 144 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [26. himself perfectly competent to attain to all perfection, has no need, in this work, either of God or of history ; neither -has even the faintest presentiment of the moral signifieancy of his- tory, of humanity as a unity. In both, therefore, there is abso- lutely no humility of moral self-denial, but either a mere lustful devotion to world-enjoyment, or a haughty contempt of the external world, and hence in neither of them is there the least felt need of redemption ; the sole redemption from the burden, not of guilt but of an evil world of reality, is, suicide with the Stoic, and sensuous intoxication with the Epicurean. In neither system is there manifest the least approximation to the Christian principle, no progress beyond Plato and Aristotle, but rather simply the moral consciousness of hea- thenism in its incipient dissolution, which is consummated in Skepticism. SECTION XXVI. The subjectivism that predominated in Epicurean and Stoic ethics finds its consequential and scientific- ally-rigorous carrying-out, and at the same time Greek and heathen ethics in general, its dissolution and honorable self-destruction, in Skepticism, which declares all judging of good and evil as futile, and all modes of action as indifferent. Neo-Platonic philosophy, which seeks to rescue heathenism as against Christianity, and which perverts Christian ideas to heathen purposes, presents in its but par- tially developed ethics little more than a dreamy mysticism a quietistic self-merging into the one uni- versal divine essence ; and it is only for non-philoso- phers that there is need of a, not scientific but, practical code of morals. Roman philosophy made no original contributions to ethics. Apart from a but slightly independent adoption of the doctrines of Stoicism, it presents nothing more than a feebly eclectic character, and 26.] SKEPTICISM. 145 does not rise beyond superficial calculating observa- tions and opinions. Skepticism lias often been misunderstood not only in its scientific, but also in its world-historical significancy ; it arose gradually and, as it were, spontaneously, without any one spe- cially prominent founder, as a protest of the general rational consciousness against the self-sufficiency and presumption of the previously existing philosophies, and, in the sphere of ethics, as the scientific conscience of heathenism. Subjectivism, when consequentially carried out, leads inevitably to skepticism. Socrates had contended with moral earnestness against the subjectivism of the Sophists, and had attempted to find a solid basis also for ethical philosophy ; in this commendable effort, however, he succeeded as little as did, after him, Plato and Aristotle and the Stoics. In these efforts they did not rise be- yond mere formal definitions of the moral, and were obliged to derive the material contents of the same from the primarily merely fortuitously-determined essence of the individual sub- ject. The sole thought that leads to a true basing of the moral consciousness, namely, that the moral is the will of God, was only dimly caught sight of, and could not in fact, from the heathen stand-point, be carried out with any degree of cer- tainty. That, now, the vail was torn off from the false method of taking the finite subject as the criterion and the infallible source of universally-valid and objective truth, and of attrib- uting to subjective opinion an absolutely valid objective sig- nificancy, and that subjectivism was exposed in all its naked- ness and invalidity, this was the scientific service of Skepti- cism, which, having shown traces of itself as early as in the age of Aristotle (Pyrrhd), attained to greater prevalence in the century before Christ (^ffinesidemus of Alexandria), and fully developed itself in the second century after Christ (Sextus Em- piricus), and thus like a devouring rust gradually undermined the last self-confidence of heathen philosophy, save in so far as it did not seek refuge behind the mystical nebula? of Neo- Platonicism. Skepticism is in fact simply the product of the antithesis between Epicureanism and Stoicism. The former said: the feeling of pleasure and displeasure alone decide as to the 146 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 26. morally-good ; the latter said : not feeling but thinking decides ; Skepticism lets the two cancel each other, and says: neither feeling nor thinking is capable of any real decision as to what is good. Man cannot at all know what is per se good ; all our feelings, experiences and thoughts have merely and exclusively a subjective significancy, furnish no truth in regard to things per se. This is not a mere feeble courting of doubt, not a mere, *' I know not whether this or that is good," but a decisive, " I know positively that I cannot know it, and I know also that there is nothing that is per se good ; " and this knowledge of the lack of knowledge is the true wisdom and the true virtue. What is good or not good is determined solely by civil law and by adopted custom, and there is no occasion for seeking for an- other or higher basis therefor. Nothing is per se, and in its essence good or evil. This consideration furnishes the basis for true soul-repose and happiness, seeing that we then need no longer be disturbed by feelings of desire or of disgust, but that we look upon every thing with calm indifference. The true and highest good consists therefore in this, that we be ab- solutely indifferent toward all things that are usually regarded as goods. As, on one occasion, during a storm, Pyrrho saw some swine very unconsciously devouring their food, he is said to have exclaimed: "The wise man must also be equally imper- turbable I" If there were any thing that is good or evil per se, all men would be found to see it ; whereas in fact the judgments of men differ in all things, and the opposing philosophic schools proclaim the most opposite things as good or evil. The truth is, that in every case, the judgment as to good or evil is de- termined by the spiritual or bodily peculiarity of the person judging, and hence gives no certainty as to the essence of the thing per se, but is always simply indicative as to what chances to seem good or evil to him. Hence a science of the moral, a sys- tem of ethics, is absolutely impossible, and all teaching as to the moral is futile. But, as now, notwithstanding this, it is necessary to live and act in some manner, so it is most advisable to act according to the existing laws and customs, not, how- ever, because they are good, but because this course is most ad- vantageous. Though Sextus Empiricus, who has said most on this head, does not show his best powers on the field of ethics, yet it is not to be denied that liis attacks against the re- 26.] NEO-PLATONISM. 147 suits of all previous ethics contain much truth, and that from the heathen stand-point the Skeptics were, on the whole, justi- fied in their doubts. Their skepticism gives evidence of a sig- nificant self-consciousness in heathen science ; and even though its results were unsatisfactory, still there was need of just such a radical sifting and exposure in order to bring to sober reflec- tion the falsely-secure and self-deluding spirit of heathenism, and to render it more receptive for a better-founded world- theory. Neo-Platonic ethics can hardly be regarded as a genuine phase of Greek thought proper. Entering the lists in antagonism to the new world-power of Christianity for the purpose of rescuing heathenism, mingling together into a nebulous conglomerate all the fragmentary notions of Oriental and Occidental religions and philosophies, and supplementing them with Christian thoughts, Neo-Platonic philosophy manifests also in its but crudely-formed ethics little more than the distressful features of a spirit slowly and painfully dying of the mere senility of age, a spirit which, without considerate choice of its means, is feverishly possessed with the one desire of arousing up by arti- ficial nerve-stimuli its already half-dead life-forces to one last desperate up-flickering into life, a tragically-grand desperation- effort of a mortally-wounded combatant, the titanic rebound- ing of the spirit of antiquity when pierced through the heart by the arrow of a higher form of truth ; (Plotinus, the greater disciple of Ammonius Saccas, the founder of the school, living mostly in Rome, ob. A. D. 270 ; his disciple Porphyry, ob, A. D. 304 ; Proclus, who lived mostly at Athens, ob. A. D. 485, the last philosopher of Occidental heathenism.) Deviating from all previous Greek philosophy, the Neo-Pla- tonists place the idea of God in the fore-ground, and deduce from it, and bring in relation to it, all principles of morality. But this God-idea itself is further remote from the Biblical idea of God than is even that of Plato and Aristotle. God is no longer the infinite "personal Reason, but the absolutely unde- termined abstract Unity, which unfolds itself, in Pantheistic em- anation, into the world of multiplicity, which world is conse- quently not a separate reality different from God, but simply the shadow of God himself, the reverse-side of the divine, the fading-away of the pure divine light, and hence of essentially 11 148 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [26. negative essence. Now as all knowledge must aim at behold- ing all things in God and God in all things, hence also all moral activity is directed exclusively to this one end, namely, to unite one's self with God, to press one's self out of the world of plu- rality, to renounce one's self as an individual being, to wish to be and actually to be nothing more than a transient phase of the alone truly-existing unitary divine essence. The moral activity aims not at the producing of a real world of the good different from God, aims not at realizing any thing which is not already real and perfect from eternity, but, on the contrary, aims at reducing back the soul from its immersion in the world of reality into the solely and the alone-existing good, that is, into God. God is not merely the highest good, but in fact the ab- solutely sole good ; and whatever is different from God is, in so far as it is so, not truly good. Hence the sole path of salvation is the return from plurality to unity, and the first and most es- sential condition thereto is the beholding of God, an indulging in a mystical speculation, which is possible only in that one for- gets one's self, spiritually dies away, so as to permit God alone to prevail. The more I am a particular self-hood claim- ing personality, so much the more remote am I from God. Morality consists, therefore, not in a developing of this person- ality, but in a suppressing of it, not in a becoming like God, but in fact in becoming God himself. The self-conscious per- sonality is not the God-like, but the God-foreign ; for God him- self is not a personality is not this or that has no manner of determinateness, but is that which is sublime above all cleter- minateness, all quality, and hence also above spiritual person- ality ; whatever is in any manner determined is not God, but has gone out from God, and' hence is, in so far, extra-divine ; and the same path which reality has traversed in passing from undetermined unity to manifoldly-determined plurality, moral- ity traverses again in the opposite direction, passes back from plurality and determinateness to the unitary and undetermined. In all these phases of thought, an Indian influence is unmistak- able. As true cognizing is not dialectical but contemplative, name- ly, a spiritual beholding of God, so also true morality is not an outward-going activity, but rather a non-acting, a restraining of active volition, a dissolving of all particular personal voli- 26.] ROMAN ETHICS. 149 tionating into the one divine essence. Whoever has the high- est good needs and wishes for no other good. But the highest good exists in no sense whatever apart from God, in the world, but solely in the reality-transcending and indeterminate God. For such an outward working, such a creating of a real king- dom of the good, there is no occasion whatever; for all that really exists is good already in so far as it is the divine essence, and hence cannot be an object of change or resistance ; and in so far as it is the divine essence as self-estranged, it is evil, and hence should not be loved and confirmed ; there remains, there- fore, for the moral activity no other work than simply to with- draw itself from the world and, not so much int > itself as much rather, into God. Hence there is no need of striving, of combatting, and of laboring, but only of reposing ; to the eter- nal keeping-silence, the eternal repose, of God, corresponds the silent repose of the sage and moral man. Active virtue is not the highest form of morality, but is only a praiseworthy moral quality of such as have not yet risen to the stage of true wis- dom. Such are the chief fundamental thoughts of this Keo- Platonic philosophy, the influence of which made itself felt as late as in the Christian mysticism of the Middle Ages. On the whole, we could not properly expect from this last attempt of heathen philosophy at self-preservation, any rigorous conse- quential carrying-out of fundamental principles ; and hence we in fact often find thoughts in it which hut imperfec ly harmo- nize with it as a system. Still, the most of these seemingly irrec- oncilable views are doubtless to be accounted for in the light of the distinction which it made between wisdom proper (which is attainable only for the elect few) and the moral instruction of the populace at large. For the latter there is in fact need of other moral precepts, seeing that men at large are not yet in such a condition as to be able, through beholding and yielding, to merge themselves into the absolutely One. Roman philosophy, though enjoying high repute in the Mid- dle Ages, and even as late as in the last century, has, however, for the philosophical development of the science of ethics scarce- ly any significance. The Stoic Romans did little more than in- dulge in general popular discussions on the philosophy they had adopted from the Greeks ; the Epicurean Romans simply applied their views practically. Cicero is simply a discreet 150 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 26. Eclectic, though without speculative genius. He discusses moral questions in clear but superficial processes of reasoning, without finding for them a firm philosophical ground, or a real- ly, scientific solution. The rhetorical form of his ethico- philo- sophical writings does not redeem them from that tediousness which inheres in any verbose display of unprofound observa- tions. Zealously opposing Epicureanism, Cicero holds fast in general to the Stoic system, modifying it with Platonic, Aris- totelian and other elements, and this too not without many in- stances of misunderstanding. His most important ethical work is his De officiis, which is based mostly on the Stoic Panaetius. In this work he examines, first, the notion of the morally-good (honestum), then that of the useful (utile), and the mutual rela- tion of these so often conflicting principles. The ' useful " he finds to be only seemingly different from the good ; the fact is, whatever is good is also useful, and whatever is truly useful is also good, not, however, for the reason that it is useful, but the converse ; hence to strive after the good renders necessarily at the same time also happy. Of the other writings of Cicero, be- long also here the Quaestion.es academ., the Disputationes Tus- culante, and his essays: De senectute, De amicitia, De legibus, De finibus. Cicero blames, in the Stoics, that they conceive of the good only partially, that they regard not the entire man, but only his spiritual phase, and lightly esteem the corporeal, so that in fact while professing to follow nature they do not do her justice, that they place on an equal footing all the virtues as well as all the vices, and admit no intermediate gradations, and also that because of their one-sidedness they involve them- selves in many contradictions. Though finding the source of the moral consciousness in reason, which is an efflux from the divine reason, and by which therefore we become like God, he yet derives ethics only in a very slight degree from the es- sence of reason itself, but rather from the experience of life. From this lack of a firm philosophical foundation, we can un- derstand why Cicero placed an especially high value on his dis- cussion upon the collision of duties. On the condition of a real deduction of the various forms of duty from one fundamental principle, there would be no possible place for such a discus- sion ; but to the moralist who takes his starting-point from em- pirical observation, this field appears as of especial difficulty and 27.] OLD TESTAMENT ETHICS. 151 importance. The question: Which of several morally good actions which cannot be reconciled with each other is to be chosen as the better? Cicero answers very unsatisfactorily and unphilosophically, on the mere ground of the social comfort- ableness resulting therefrom (De off., i, 43 sqq.) Nor does he succeed in all his sonorous periods on universal benevolence, etc., in rising beyond the narrow views characteristic of heathen ethics. Plutarch, a Greek with Roman education (about A. D. 100,) furnishes in his numerous moral writings many good observations on the moral life, and gives evidence of a noble disposition of soul, though he does not rise be- yond popular essays and observations, relating for the most part to particular moral topics, gives neither a system, nor rigorous, clear principles. In general he follows Plato, *and rejects the extremes both of Epicureanism and Stoicism. B. OLD-TESTAMENT AND JEWISH ETHICS. SECTION XXVII. The ethics of the Old Testament presents, in its entire essence, a direct contrast to all heathen ethics. Without systematic form and without scientific de- velopment, it is yet perfectly self-consistent in its ground, its essence, and its end. In harmony with the idea of God as a spirit absolutely independent of nature, and himself omnipotently conditioning the whole sphere of nature, the ground of all morality is absolutely and exclusively God's holy will as revealed to the free personal creature ; the essence of the moral is free, loving obedience to the revealed divine will ; the ultimate end of morality is the realizing of per- fect God-likeness, and hence also of perfect God-son- ship and bliss, not merely for the individual, not merely for the people Israel, but for all humanity, and hence the realization of a humanity-embracing kingdom of God ; the most immediate historical end, 152 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 2T. however, is to impart a knowledge of the need of redemption from depravity as incurred by the sin of man himself. Hence the law appears in fact pre- dominantly, not as an inner natural one, but as a purely positive, objective, historically-revealed one, in order that man may become conscious of his natu- ral estrangement from the truth. In this form it does not have an ultimately definitive, but a transitory and essentially disciplinary end ; and the realization of the kingdom of God can only be prepared for, but not fully accomplished, by the Israelitic people ; it is a morality of hope. As in the presentation of Christian ethics, further on, we shall have to glance in considerable detail also at its historical ante- cedent, namely, Old Testament ethics, hence we need here give only the general characteristics of the latter.* The antagonism of the moral idea of the Old Testament to the views of collective heathenism, is radical and fundamental ; there is here no shadow of a transition from the latter to the former. Pre-Christian revealed ethics did not, however, have a scientific, systematic form, and indeed could not have it, inas- much as the key to its correct understanding was to be given only in the days of the Messiah, and as the Hebrews were not to be a perfect, independently-developed nation, but to find their full truth only in Christianity. The Hebrews do not un- dertake to find the ground of the moral consciousness in the human spirit itself, for the man whom they know as real is no longer the pure image of God, has no longer the unobscured natural consciousness of God and of the moral. and even un- fallen man needed to be awakened to this consciousness by the revelation of God. The entire ground of the moral conscious- ness is therefore sought in God's positive revelation to man, as *In addition to general works on Old Testament theology, which treat mostly of the ethical phase only incidentally, and to the works mentioned in 5, may be cited, G. L. Bauer: Bibl. Moral des A. T., 1803, 2 vols., extremely Rationalistic; (Imm. Berger : Prakt. Einl. ins A. 7*., continued by Augiitti, 1799-1808, 4 vols.) 27.] NORM OF RIGHT. 153 indeed the ground of the moral on the whole is absolutely the holy will of God, not as "an abstract law immanent in, though partially hidden from, human reason, but as an express com- mand of the personal God and made known to man by a his- torical act of revelation. God speaks and man hearkens ; and the moral activity is in its entire essence a child-like obeying of the divine command made upon man. Here there is no longer any room for a doubt, unless it be. a sinful one, no need of a philosophical analysis. In case there is need in particular conjunctures for a more definite decision, then God gives it him- self, either directly, as with the patriarchs and the divinely- called and enlightened prophets, or, mediately, through the same, or indeed also through specific signs, such as the lot [Num. xxvi, 55, 56; xxxiii, 54; xxxiv, 13; Josh, vii, 14 sqq. ; xiii, 6; xiv, 2; xviii, 6 sqq.; xix, 1 sqq.; xxi, 4 sqq.; 1 Sam. x, 20 sqq.; Prov. xvi, 33; xviii, 18], the high-priestly Urim and Thummim [Ex. xxviii, 30 ; Num. xxvii, 21 ; 1 Sam. xxiii, 6 sqq.; xxviii, 6; xxx, 7, 8; comp. 2 Sam. ii, 1; v, 19, 23 sqq.], and others [1 Sam. xiv, 8 sqq., cornp. Gen. xxiv, 12 sqq.]. The command of God to man presents itself in a strictly positive definite form: "thou shalt," "thou shalt not," "thou mayest." For any other reason than God's will, man has no right to ask ; he is simply to believe the word of God this alone leads him to righteousness. To personal free self-determination and ma- turity, man is to attain simply and solely through child-like faith-obedience to the word of the Father. He who questions and hesitates where God speaks, cannot possibly be moral, since he is lacking in faith. Unhesitating, unreluctant, joyous submission to God's definite command, is the beginning, the end and the essence of all morality. Types of such faith-obedi- ence are Noah [Gen. vi, 22 ; vii, 5], Abraham [xii, 4], Jacob, Moses, Samuel. David, and others. The simple fact that God wills it, is the absolutely sufficient reason ; the fear of God is the beginning of wisdom. The antecedent condition of the moral, as lying in the bosom of man himself, is, however, the image of God the pure knowledge and the untrammeled will of moral freedom. Man should, but he is not compelled ; his salvation is placed within his own hand ; the thought, "If thou hearkenest to my word, it shall go well with thee," pervades the entire Old Testament from beginning to end., 154 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 27. Between God and man there subsists an absolutely person- ally-moral relation. Even as God, 'as the true and perfect personality, is the holy prototype of all morality, and as the simple thought of this God is directly presented as the per- fectly sufficient ground for all moral life : "Ye shall be holy, for /the Lord your God am holy" [Lev. xi, 45; xix, 2], "I am the almighty God, walk before me and be thou perfect " [Gen. xvii, 1], so also is man's complete personality recog- nized and respected by God even in the already sin-corrupted race. God does not himself immediately work all willing and acting in man, does not force him to obedience, but He makes a cocenant with man, with his people, comes as a holy personality into moral relation to man as a free moral person- ality. The fulfillment of the covenant-promise is conditioned on the covenant-fidelity of man. The purpose, the goal of the moral is not the merely indi- vidual perfection of the moral subject, but it is, on the one hand, the salvation and perfection of the whole human race, a thought entirely unknown to heathendom and, on the other, the full and blissful life-communion of the person with God; "I will be your God, and ye shall be my people" [Lev. xxvi, 12; Jer. vii, 23]; not merely the individual subject but the moral community, the people of God (entire humanity is to become this people), is to be received into this com- munion with God. Immediately upon the creation of man the thought of the moral presents itself clearly and definitely [Gen. i, 26-ii, 24]. (1.) The objective presupposition of the moral is presented, namely, the living personal God as the prototype of man and of his life, and nature as good and normal and as existing independently over against man, and, then, the subjective presupposition, namely, man as a personal spirit like unto his Creator. (2.) The goal of morality as a task, a duty, namely, the realizing and completing of the divine image, is expressed under one of its phases, as the dominion of man over nature; this implies the realization of free personal spirituality in likeness to God the legitimate "being as God." In the strong emphasizing of this dominion over nature, (so utterly in contrast to all actual experience,) there is plainly indicated the ideal essence of the moral task ; its 27.] CONDITIONS OF MORALITY. 155 full realization however is not to be attained to at once, but is the final goal, and lies in the future. In striking contrast to all heathen views, according to which man is either abso- lutely subject to nature, or at least has nature before him as a cramping, and never-entirely-to-be-overcome power, we have here the true relation of the rational spirit to nature, namely, his complete freedom, his destination to entire mastery over it, that is, we have the full personality of man as the key-stone of the collective morally-religious world- theory. That this dominion of the spirit over nature is not to be a childish magical interfering with nature, is evident from the simple fact that man is called to it only as being un image of the nature-dominating God, and that immediately before and after his call thereto the God-established perma- nent regularity of nature is alluded to as in some sense a right of nature, and that man is at once directed to the orderly and conserving culture of nature [ii, 15]. The dominion o /er nature is not the entire goal of the moral striving, it is, however, a very expressive suggestion of the same, and is within the comprehension of the child-like and as yet imma- ture spirit. (3.) The legitimate freedom of choice and its en- joyment are guaranteed to man. as a right, in the sphere of the discretionary [i, 28-30; ii, 16]. (4.) The unambiguous dec- laration is made that morality is not a something belonging merely to the individual person, but that on the contrary man can accomplish his task only as a member of a moral community ; it is not good that man should be alone ; he ought not to remain in isolation, but should form a part of a family, should enter into association with moral humanity, and it is only on this condition that the good is truly realizable for the subject. (5.) In the anticipatory allusion to the observance of the Sabbath as based on the divine example [ii, 2, 3] is presented the ideal phase of human activity, the re-collect- ing of the personal spirit from the distractions of the outer life into the calm of meditation ; man is not at liberty com- pletely to merge himself into earthly temporal cares, should constantly have before him, in all his temporal activity, also the eternal as the true and highest good. The heathen either buries himself up in temporal activity and enjoyment, or con- temptuously turns himself entirely away from the same ; .the 156 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 2T. saint of the Old Testament lives and acts in God's good- created world, but does not merge himself into it, with- draws himself from it into the Sabbath repose of a heart in communion with its God. In the simple feature of Sab- bath observance itself, Old Testament morality presents itself in sharp and definite contrast to all heathen ethics, and places the moral task of man higher than the latter. Hebrew ethics, however, does not linger, as was almost exclusively the case with heathen ethics, in the purely ideal sphere, in the consideration of the good per se, does not conceive of evil as a mere possibility or as a merely excep- tional or isolated reality, or as a nature-necessity back of all human guilt (which are all, in fact, heathen views) but looks evil earnestly and squarely in the face, and regards it as a sad, all-prevalent reality, the guilt of which lies in the free act of man, and is participated in by all without exception. The morality of the chosen people of God looks, therefore, not merely to a warding off and an avoiding of evil as a something as yet external to our heart, and merely threaten- ing us, but to a zealous, constant combating of the same, not outside of us in an originally defective world, but within in the inmost guilt-laden heart of the subject himself. Sin is of historical origin, an historical reality and power; and morality, the nature of which presents itself now quite pre- dominantly as a vigorous combating against sin, appears , also itself in a uniformly historical character, is promoted and guided by a divine history-chain of ever richer-unfolding gracious guidances, and gives rise to a moral history, to a redemption-history, to a kingdom of God here upon earth inside of humanity, at first, in faith and hope, and after- wards (after it has reached the goal promised by God from the very start, and embraced by the people with pious confidence, and kept constantly in view) in full, blissful reality. Hea- thenism knows indeed evil, knows vice, but it does not know *t/i, for sin is of a morally-historical character ; hence it knows also of no historical overcoming of the same, no expecting, no preparing for, nor realization of, a kingdom of God in humanity; the Persians alone have an obscure presentiment thereof, perhaps not without a ray of light received from the people of God, with whom they were in contact, and whom, 27.] WORLD-HISTORICAL GOAL. 157 from their residence among them, they learned highly to esteem. On the entrance of sin into the world there arises at once a separation among men between those who permit them- selves to be fettered by sin and those who retain God and his salvation in view, between the children of the world and the children of God ; God, however, looks in compassionate love also upon the former and plans for them a redemption, the world-historical preparation of which is confided to that peo- ple which He separates out from among the men of sin, and paternally guides ; God separates to himself the man of faith, him who trusts in God with rock-like firmness and cheerfully and unconditionally obeys his word even where he is unable to comprehend it and where it diametrically contradicts his own natural consciousness. God places be- fore Abraham, from the very start, not a merely personal, but a world-historical goal: "In thee shall all the families of the earth be blessed" [Gen. xii, 3], and he repeats this promise again and again in progressively more definite feat- ures ; as in Adam all die, so in Abraham are all nations to be blessed and to be brought to the Acconiplisher of Salvation. For the first time in the history of humanity we find here, and in contrast to all heathendom, a definite world-historical goal of the moral life ; not man, but God has established it in compassionating grace, and has sealed it in successive and progressively richer promises ; and an individual man is elected to co-operate in the fulfilling of this promise, which is not given to him as an individual but to humanity, to co- operate in such a sense as that this man, that this people itself, may become capable of really participating in the fruit of the redemption accomplished by the act of grace, by be- coming the maternal womb which is to bear and give birth to the Saviour. But the individual has part in this moral work only when he accepts the promise in faith, and it is only when he accepts the promise in faith, and only on the basis of this faith, that he is able to attain to true obedience of life. This people, so strictly cut off from all the rest of the race, this people hated, oppressed, down-trodden by the rest of mankind, becomes thus, from the very beginning, of world- 158 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 27. hixtorical significance, in a much higher sense than any other pre-Christian people. The heathen nations which actively entered into and shaped history sought only themselves but not humanity; the Israelitic people, shut up exclusively to the promise and to faith, a people already spiritually de- veloped and molded into a moral organism before it had as yet where to lay its head, and which was as yet seeking its earthly home, a spiritual people without any nature-basis, and which received its earthly home only as a gracious gift of God, conferred on moral conditions [Lev. xxv, 23], this people, in its God-willed and commanded separation from all heathen nations, in its so often, even up to the present day, reproached "particularism," was, after all, absolutely the only people which had in view, from the beginning, the true " universalism, " (namely, the salvation of collective hu- manity), as its highest goal, and which sought to do nothing else than to prepare the way for this salvation of humanity [Gen. xii, 3; ^viii, 18; xxii, 18; xxvi, 4; Deut. xxxii, 43; 1 Chron. xvi, 23, 28; Isa. ii, 2 sqq.; xi, 10 sqq.; xxv, 6 sqq.; xlii, 1, 6; xlv, 20, 22, 23; xlix, 6; lii, 15; liv, 3; Iv, 5; Ix; Ixi, 11; Ixii, 2; Ixv, 1; Ixvi, 18 sqq.; Jer. iv, 2; xvi, 19; Amos ix, 11, 12 ; Hag. ii, 7 (8) ; Zech.ii, 11 ; vi, 15 ; viii, 20 sqq.; xiv, 16 ; Micah iv, 1 sqq.; Mai. i, 11 ; Psa. ii, 8 ; xviii, 49 ; Ixvii, 2; Ixxii, 8 sqq.; lxxxvi,9,10; xcvi,7,10; cii, 15; cxvii, 1]. The Israelites had therefore, from the very beginning, the deepest interest for history, and for the goal of history as clearly presented by prophetic promise ; the divine prophetic bene- dictions upon the patriarchs relate much less to their own person than to the history of humanity as proceeding from them; the Hebrew is clearly conscious that all his moral striving contributes to conduct the God-guided current of history to the God-promised realization of salvation ; instead of the gloomy, despairing tragic consciousness of the most highly cultured of all the heathen nations, we find here a full confidence in the ultimate fulfillment of the redemption longed-for by man and promised by God. The Israelites have and could have this high world-his- torical mission only because they were made to conceive of themselves from the very beginning as, not a nature-people, but as a spiritual people which obtained for itself its natural 27.] A SPIRITUAL PEOPLE. 159 prosperity only through moral fidelity. As the people of God, they name themselves not Hebrews, from their natural descent, nor yet from Abraham, nor from Isaac, nor indeed from Jacob's first name, but from his later God-given name, Israel, which he received after he had wrestled with the angel [Gen. xxx, 24 sqq]. From Abraham and Isaac descend also other tribes, which do not belong to the people of God ; only Jacob's descendants belong all thereto. Nor is Jacob the progenitor of the people of God in his earlier self-willed and self-confiding life, but solely in his spiritually-transformed life, after that, praying and beseeching, he had wrestled, in bitter repentance, with Jehovah as offended at his many sins and deceits, and after that, in self-denying humility having put off all self-righteousness, he had thrown himself child-like at the feet of God and confided all his well-being to His blessing. It becomes the people of Israel, as a spiritual peo- ple, to have also a spiritual and not a merely natural man as their father, and the true bearing of this father to God is ex- pressed in the words : "I will not let thee go unless thou bless me." Whoever would belong to this spiritual people of God must divest himself of all his mere naturalness ; this is sym- bolized by the covenant-token of the people with God, cir- cumcision. The Israelite, in his moral strivings, has the highest good hopefully and confidently in view, and not for the individual person 'alone, but for humanity. The idea of the highest good, the fundamental thought of all morality, has, in the Old Testament history, a very distinct development. It ap- pears in God's promises, on the one hand, as a grace, and, on the other, as a reward for trusting fidelity, neither of which is by any means to be separated from, or regarded as contra- dictory to, the other. In the first blessing after the creation, as we have already seen, the thought of the highest good is already indicated ; by sin, however, the blessing is changed into a curse, the highest good is thrown into the far distant, and is only obscurely alluded to in the promise of the ulti- mate victory of the seed of the woman over the seed of the serpent [Gen. iii, 15], and henceforth the thought of the highest good is associated with the victory over evil-, with redemption. And though mankind, originally destined to 160 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 2f . possess the whole earth [Gen. i, 28; Matt, v, 5], receive now merely in small numbers, as members of the people of God, only a very small space of the earth for their possession, yet is also this typical foretaste of the possession of the highest good associated at the same time with promises of victory over the sin-symbolizing heathen inhabitants thereof; the highest good even in its feeblest foretastes is conditioned on trustful struggle and victory. In the blessing upon Noah [Gen. ix] there are indicated as the highest good, in the first place, the multiplication of the human race through Noah, and the dominion over nature (now, after the fall into sin, under a somewhat changed form), and, then, in the express covenant of God with Noah, the full personal communion of believing man with God. To Abraham, the prophetic bene- diction is essentially enlarged, including the multiplication of his family under God's guidance, the guaranteeing of an earthly father-land as a gift of God, and the blessing of en- tire humanity through the people of God as springing from him. God had expressly called Abraham away from his natural father-land ; he is to receive another one in its stead, one that is morally acquired from God's hand through be- lieving submission to God ; all earthly good is to bear also a spiritual character, is to be an outgrowth from spiritual good ; even the most natural earthly good, the home, is to be obtained as a grace in reward of faith. Homeless upon earth for several centuries, the people Israel are to find, first, their eternal home, so as, then, after having been trained by God's hand, and ripened for his service through sufferings and submission, to receive an earthly one as a gift of grace ; and this home is to be for them a symbol of the eternal one, a shadow of the highest good. Even in the first promise to Abraham, there beams out through this earthly good a faint gleam of the heavenly one : " in thee shall all families of the earth be blessed ; " Abraham is to be, not merely by his ex- ample of faith, but also really, by his family, the beginning of a kingdom of God for entire humanity ; to be himself in this kingdom of blessing, and this kingdom in him, this is, for him, the highest good. Exactly similar promises of tem- poral and likewise spiritual goods, God gives to Isaac and to Jacob [Gen. xxvi, 3-5; xxviii, 13-15; comp. xxxv, 9-11; 27.] LIFE AFTER DEATH. 161 xlviii, 4] ; Isaac's blessing upon his son Jacob relates, it is true, primarily only to temporal good [xxvii, 28,29]; xxviii, 3, 4], but nevertheless with allusion to the higher good. It is true, temporal well-being [Gen. xxxix, 2, 3, 5, 23; Lev. xxvi, 3 sqq.; Deut. v, 29; vi, 3, 18, 24; vii, 13 sqq.; viii, 6 sqq.; xi, 9 sqq., 21 sqq.; xii, 28; xv, 4-6, 10; xxviii, I sqq., comp. Psa. Ixxxi, 13, 14], and a continuance in the land, and long life [Exod. xx, 12 ; xxiii, 26 ; Deut. iv, 40 ; v, 33 ; vi, 2 ; xxx, 2 sqq.; xxxii, 47], are very often presented, not indeed with reference merely to the individual, but also to the na- tion, as a divine blessing for pious fidelity, as a high good and end ; but as early as at the time of the actual conclusion of the covenant of God with the people on Sinai, the highest good appears as of a spiritual character: "If ye will obey my voice indeed and keep my covenant, then ye shall be a peculiar treasure unto me above all people ; for all the earth is mine ; and ye shall be unto me a kingdom of priests and a holy nation " [Exod. xix, 5, 6] ; the highest blessing is the peace of God [Num. vi, 26 ; Psa. xxix, 11], the love of God, the com- passion of God, and his covenant with men [Deut. vii, 9, 12, 13; xiii, 17, 18], so that they "may live long" [Deut. v, 33] and that God might be their "righteousness" [vi, 25] ; and in the first commandment : " I am the Lord thy God, thou shalt have no other gods before me " [Exod. xx, 2, 3], the ob- jective phase of the highest good is definitely expressed ; any thing else, save God, that man might regard as the highest good, is in fact but a worthless idol ; and hence the rejection of the covenant of grace works an everlasting rejection of him who rejects it [1 Chron. xxviii, 9]. In view of this high spiritual conception of the highest good, it appears as in the highest degrge a surprising fact that the thought of a life after death is not directly brought to bear upon the moral life, is not presented as a motive of action, or as a phase of the highest good, a peculiarity that is all the more striking when we consider that the children of Israel had lived for four centuries in Egypt, and that Moses had been edu- cated in the wisdom of this country, where precisely this thought of immortality very powerfully shaped the entire moral and religious life, and when we further consider that this thought itself was most unquestionably recognized among the 162 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 27. children of Israel [Gen. v, 24 ; xv, 15 ; xxv, 8 ; xxxvii, 35 ; xlix, 26, 29,33; Deut. xxxi, 16; xxxii, 50; 1 Sam. xxviii; Job xxvi, 5; 2 Kings ii; Psa. xvi, 10; xlix, 15; Prov. xv, 24], as it would also be naturally presumable that a people which places so high a value upon the personality, could not be igno- rant of this thought, which so largely prevailed throughout heathendom. This manifestly intentional placing in the back-ground of the thought of immortality as bearing upon the moral life, is to be explained from the peculiarity of the purpose which God had with this nation, in view of the salva- tion of mankind. (1.) The people of Israel is a world-historical one as no other ante-Christian people was; the entire hopes and striving of the nation are directed toward the ultimate salva- tion of the human race as the highest goal ; the primarily feeble, but constantly more definite-growing Messianic thought throws temporarily into the back-ground the interest in future life of the individual person. The entire hope of Israel looks forward to the highest good, the true salvation, but this high- est good consists, even for the pious Israelite, only in the future redemption that is to be accomplished by a world-historical divine act ; the Redeemer had first to spring from the line of David before the life after death could have real worth for the saint, or be his highest good ; before this event, the transmun- dane life was a beclouded one, not only for the consciousness, Ttmt also per se, was not as yet a truly blissful life in the pres- ence of God [Psa. vi, 5; xlix, 15 sqq . ; Ixxxviii, 10-13; cxv, 17; Isa. xxxviii, 18]. As Abraham rejoiced that he should see the day of the Lord [John viii, 56], so also longed Abraham's seed for this day, from which time forth, only, the life after death could be a truly blessed one. The saints of the Old Covenant did not pass their lives as having no hope, but their hope was primarily an historical one, was fixed upon the his- torical fulfillment of the promises, and aspired toward a heav- enly home only from, and on the basis of, this fulfillment. (2.) Though for the redeemed Christian the thought of a future life is a very important element of his moral conscious- ness, nevertheless for the as yet not truly regenerated man there lies in the same no inconsiderable danger, namely, the danger of selfish reward-seeking, of a narrow-hearted directing of his moral striving exclusively toward his personal well-being 27.] ANTI-HERO -WORSHIP. 163 instead of toward the salvation of humanity. Though the saints of the Old Covenant participated in many gracious gifts, so that they cannot be regarded as merely natural men, still, they were not as yet in the highest sense spiritually regenerated ; and, in fact, in the necessary redemption-prepar- ing requirement of strict obedience to the objectively-given law, they stood all the more exposed Jo this danger of regard- ing their future salvation as a reward for good works, as is actually evinced by the rise of Pharisaism. From this danger God preserved the Hebrews, in that while He indeed promised them a gracious reward for their fidelity, He yet presented as such reward, on the one hand, only such goods as most evi- dently could not be, for the pious, the highest good, and, on the other hand, the fulfillment of the divine promises within the sphere of history, namely, redemption, so that they were necessarily brought to the consciousness that the highest good was not the reward of their own works, but the fruit of a future divine act of grace. Although the law had essentially also the purpose of awak- ening the consciousness of the antagonism of the sinful nature of man against the holy will of God, thus implying that the full consciousness of the sinful perversion of human nature was a state that had as yet to be attained to, nevertheless this con- sciousness exists from the very beginning, and that too very vividly, as we shall hereafter see ; and it is especially note- worthy that notwithstanding the high reverence which the Israelites had for their patriarchs and for the prophets of God, still they were very far from regarding them as moral ideals. It is true, there are mentioned pious and just men, such as Enoch and Noah; and the faithfulness of Abraham shines forth typically even into the New Covenant ; but they are never pre- sented as real holy types of morality, (not even in Gen. xxvi, 4, 5 ; 2 Chron. vii, 17 ; Mai. ii, 15) ; on the contrary, the his- torical records relate, even of the most revered characters, manifold sins, and sins which the Israelites unquestionably regarded as such; thus, for example, of Abraham [Gen. xii, 11 sqq. ; xx, 2 sqg.], and of Jacob [xxvii, 14 sqq. ; xxxi, 20], and of Reuben, of Simeon and Levi [xxxiv, 14 sqq. ; xxxv, 22; xlix, 14 sqq.] ; and of the other sons of Jacob [xxxvii] ; and of Judah, the ancestor of the kings, there is recorded scarcely 12 164 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 27. any thing but evil ; he even begets Pharez from whom David, and hence also the Messiah, were to descend in unconscious incest and conscious whoredom [xxxviii] ; Moses slays the Egyptian and buries him secretly, and this was also certainly regarded as a crime [Exod. ii, 11 sqq.] ; he resists faint-heartedly the divine call, [Exod. iii and iv] and subsequently wavers in his faith, and is, for that reason, shut out from the Land of Prom- ise [Num. xx, 7 sqq. ; Deut. xxxii, 49 sqq.] ; and that which is said to him holds good in another sense of all the saints of the Old Covenant, namely : " thou shalt see the land before thee, but thou shalt not enter into it ; " and however pre-eminent David and Solomon are in courageous faith and in wisdom, still they were not pure examples even for the Israelites ; the Israelites knew of only one Servant of God who was perfect and pure and holy, namely, the longed-for Anointed of the Lord. And accordingly the saints of the Old Covenant kept them- selves far from all self-glorification, and aspired to a higher goal. The undevout self-righteousness and work -holiness of the later Pharisaism is totally repugnant to the spirit of the Old Covenant ; for the law requires most certainly not merely the outward work, but above all and essentially also a morally-pious disposition, bears, in contradistinction to the later Jewish out- ward legality, a very positive character of inwardliness. The basis and essence of all morality are the requirement, that man " should love God with all his heart, with all his soul, and with all his might " [Deut. vi, 5 ; x, 12 ; xiii, 3] ; he is to take the divine law to his heart, and to observe it with his whole heart and his whole soul [Deut. v, 29; vi, 6; xi, 13; 18 sqq. ; xxvi, 16 ; xxx, 2 ; Josh, xxii, 5] ; God desires not merely the external works, he requires our heart [1 Chron. xxii, 19 ; Prov. xxiii, 26] ; the saint not only fulfills the law, but " his delight is in the law of the Lord " [Psa. i, 2 ; cxii, 1 ; cxix, 24, 35, 70 ; Job xxii, 22, 26 ; Deut. xxviii, 47] ; and all obedience is simply joyous thankful- ness for God's gracious guidance [Exod. xx, 2 sqq. ; Deut. iv and v; vi, 20 s^.; viii, 3 sqq. ; x, 19 sqq. ; xi, 1; xv, 15; xvi, 12 ; 1 Chron. xxix, 9 and others] ; and therefore not merely the sinful act, but equally also the lust to evil, is sinful and damna- ble [Exod. xx, 17 ; Prov. vi, 25]. Old Testament morality has essentially a preparatory charac- ter, refers forward to a higher and as yet to be acquired 27.] "CLEAN" AND "UNCLEAN." 165 morality ; hence it bears in part a symbolical form, expressing by external signs, that, the full realization of which, was pos- sible only after the time of the accomplishment of redemption, and thereby constantly keeping before the eyes of the people what the ultimate moral purpose of the divine economy with Israel was, although this purpose could not as yet be fully realized. In order to keep constantly awake and to intensify the moral consciousness of the antagonism of the divine will to the sinful nature which had now become natural to actual man, the antagonism of the " clean " and the " unclean " is rigor- ously insisted upon and carried out, and that too not merely in the sphere of the purely spiritual and moral, but also in that of nature, where the moral is only symbolically prefigured. Man is required to learn, in free obedience, to distinguish and choose between the godly and the ungodly, and that too not according to his natural impulses and feelings, nor by the merely reflective observation and examination of things, but solely by the minutely-particularizing positive divine law. To man, as not yet actually redeemed and sanctifiecl, but as yet involved and entangled in the bonds of sinfulness, the law presents itself, and properly so, as of an objectively-revealed character, as foreign to his natural state, and to which there is nothing correspondent in his inner nature unless it be a loving willing- ness to unconditional obedience. Educative disciplining to obedience is the essential end of many of the positive laws, which must consequently appear to the truly emancipated and redeemed as a yoke, whereas, for him who is only as yet struggling toward freedom, they are a wholesome discipline. Old Testament morality presents a moral task not only to the individual person, but it also keeps in view, from the very start, the necessity of moral communion. It conceives of the moral significance of the family more highly than any of the heathen systems ; in giving to reverence for parents a religious ground, it guarantees at the same time the moral rights of children as against sinful parents ; and if it is not as yet able to raise marriage to the height of the Christian view, inasmuch as only the truly spiritually-regenerated are in a condition to appre- ciate and fulfill its full significance [Matt, v, 31 ; xix, 8], nev- ertheless it does give to it the truly religious and moral basis. It changes the slavery of Israelites into a very mild service-rela- 166 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 27. tion, and protects, by extremely humane regulations, that o non-Israelites from arbitrary and severe oppressiveness. The differences among mankind are no longer natural, but spirit- ually -moral ; even foreign slaves have part in the worship and in the blessings of the people of God. The moral organization of society into the state is presented in the Old Testament, from the very start, in its highest moral significancy, as a unity of church and state as a theocracy in which the entire moral community-life of the people rests on a religious basis, in which Jehovah alone is Jdng, and the God-called and enlight- ened prophets the organs of his will, organs to whom the peo- ple submit themselves in believingly joyous obedience. But here also, as well as in the case of marriage, God gives simply the unambiguous idea, and, because of the hardness of the hearts, concedes another state-organization more correspondent to the sinful circumstances of the people, namely, the purely human institution of an earthly monarchy, reserving the full realiza- tion of the higher idea, for the future. But even this earthly kingdom is to be an image of the divine kingdom, and the kings, the faithful instruments of the holy will of God kings "after God's own heart;" the Old Testament recognizes neither despotic nor democratic caprice-domination as morally admissi- ble. Of all this we must speak again further on. As Old Testament redemption-history presents essentially an educative preparation for the historical accomplishing of the redemption-act, hence it is clearly manifest that this prepara- tion must be a historically-progressive one, and that conse- quently Old Testament ethics itself must have an historical devel- opment. This, as yet, very unsatisfactorily-treated portion of Biblical theology cannot, however, be fully presented in the brief space to which the plan of our historical Introduction confines us ; we therefore remark here only two points, (1), that the essential character of the moral view (and the question is here simply as to essential features) is contradictory to the heathen view, and different from the Christian, and, throughout all the writings of the Old Testament, self-consistent and the same : and, (2), that the prophetic redemption-history is closely connected with the legislative, seeing that Moses himself was the greatest among the prophets. The prophets, in the nar- rower sense of the word, do not give an essentially new moral 27.] ETHICS OF THE PROPHETS. 167 revelation, but, on the contrary, uniformly proceed on the basis of that of Moses, referring, on the one hand, exhortingly to its requirements, and rebuking the unfaithfulness of the people to its spirit, but, on the other, directing attention with constantly greater distinctness to the goal of this moral development- process of the people of Israel, that is, to their world historical destination, and, above all, they seek to ward against the danger of legal holiness and self-sufficiency, the danger of the selfish contentment of the single moral subject with his own individual development, which lies in every strictly-developed system of laws, that is, against the danger of a merely external performing of the works of the law, as was at a later period actually presented in Pharisaism ; they earnestly urged to the inner purity of the heart, and bring to an increasingly clearer consciousness, the morality that transcends that of the mere in- dividual, namely, the general moral task of the totality, of the people of God. While the earlier ethics has more the character of a doctrine of laws and duties, the ethics of the prophets bears rather that of a doctrine of goods. The Proverbs of Sol- omon, in contrast to the Mosaic Laws which present themselves as direct revelations from God, consist predominantly in rules of practical life-wisdom and life-prudence, drawn from the rich life-experience of a heart pious, though indeed often erring, and strengthened and ripened in the true fear of God ; they appeal therefore less to a believing submission to an express divine command than rather to the free spontaneous assent, natural to a pious God-consciousness ; they aim not at the disciplining of a, as yet, morally immature spirit by a legal yoke, but at the purifying, ripening and moral strengthening of the spirit as al- ready consciously dwelling in God; they are not the sternly demanding voice of a prophet, but the witness of a preacher; it is not directly Jehovah, but it is the pious servant of God, who speaks to the pious. In Moses the question is every-where as to obedience ; with Solomon the constant theme is wisdom, a quality which is scarcely mentioned by Moses, and for the sim- ple reason that the discipline of the law needed to precede and prepare the way, before the free subjectivity of wisdom could come to realization. This coming into the fore-ground of the thought of wisdom evinces the progress of the moral conscious- ness out of the child-like condition of subjection to an objective 168 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 27. law, to the riper manhood of a freer self-determination on the basis of personal moral knowledge. Wisdom is here by no means mere worldly prudence, but its beginning and essence is the "fear of the Lord" [Prov. i, 7], and complete, hearty, God- confiding is its life-spring [iii, 5; xvi], and soul-repose and God's approbation its fruit [iii, 12, 18, 22 sqq.; viii, 17, 35 ; xv, 24; xxviii] ; and hence for individual man it is the highest good [iii, 13 sqq]. This wisdom is very far removed from the "magnanimous" wisdom of the Greeks; it takes cognizance above all things of the sinfulness of the natural heart, and re- quires watchfulness over the same [iv, 23] and humility before God and man [iii, 34 ; xi, 2 ; xvi, 18 ; xviii, 12 ; xxvii, 2 ; xxix, 23]. While in the Solomonic Proverbs there is a manifest ele- vating of Mosaic legality toward the personal freedom of the pious sage, still it is not to be overlooked that there lies in the stand-point they assume, as in contrast to the Mosaic, also the danger that the subjective presumption of the individual per- son may rise to an unwarranted height, and work detriment to the true heart-humility that springs from a consciousness of one's own want of conformity to the law. And it is not unworthy of note that the Christian consciousness of the Apos- tles found much less occasion to appeal to the wisdom of man ; they discourse far preferably of self-denying, humbly loving faith. The Ecclesiastes of Solomon, after referring to the com- fortless experience of a heart temporarily immersed in world- enjoyment, totally overthrows all world-pleasure and the vain hope of finding in the finite any real good ; the mere negative knowledge that " all is vanity " prepares the way for a seeking after the true, the highest good, which, however, is but remotely suggested [Eccles. xii, 7, 13] but not fully presented ; the skepti- cism, at first sight so seemingly wide-reaching and so entirely despairing of satisfaction, has a back-ground of very profound educative wisdom. In the fact that the moral is not derived from the natural conscience of man, seeing that the conscience is no longer the pure expression of the original God-consciousness, but that, on the contrary, the historically-revealed will of God is the exclusive source of the moral command, there lies an es- sential reason why Hebrew ethics did not develop itself into a philosophy ; the very thought of such a philosophy conflicts 28.] ETHICS OF THE APOCRYPHA. 169 with the fundamental presuppositions of the Old Testament consciousness. The time had not yet come when the con- science, and human knowledge in general, had so far become free as to derive truth also from within themselves. As yet man was called simply believingly to obey, but not freely and philosophically to create. SECTION XXVIII. The Old Testament Apocryphal Books* abandon- ed by the fire of the prophetic spirit, and in part affect- ed by foreign philosophical influences, treat predomi- nantly of morality. The moral law, in the Old Testament canon an essential element of the educa- tive divine revelation as a whole, is here considered rather in itself and as unconnected with the world- historical goal of the Theocracy, and is thereby de- graded into a merely individual, empirically-grounded moral system. In the Talmud the law appears aa entirely unspiritualized, as fallen into complete life- less externality, dissolved into its ultimate atoms. The moral thoughts of the Apocrypha give clear evidence of some degree of obscuration of the consciousness of re- demption-history, both in respect to its presupposition, namely, the fall and its consequences, and in regard to its true nature in the Ancient Covenant, and also in regard to its historical goal the expected redemption-act by Christ. With the obscuration of this thought go naturally enough hand in hand a manifest coming into the fore-ground of a certain holiness by works, in the manner of the heathen mor- alists [comp. Sirach iii, 16, 17 (14, 15), 33 (30) ; xxix, 15-17 (12, 13); xvii, 18 (22) sqq.], a one-sided laudation of wisdom and righteousness in obliviousness of the question whether * Comp. Staudlin : Gesch. der Sittenl. Jesu, i, 358 ; Cramer : Moral der Apokr., 1814; (also in Keil and Tzschirner's Analekten, 1814, 5i, 1, 2,); Babiger: Ethica libe apocr., 1838 ; Kcerl : Die Apokr. d. A. T., 1852, somewhat unfair ; comp. Heugstenberg : Fur BeHtehaltung der Apokr. 170 CHKISTIAN ETHICS. [28. indeed there are any such wise and righteous persons to be found, and also in many respects a proud self-satisfaction with one's own wisdom and virtue, together with a censori- ous and contemptuous looking-down upon the unwise and unrighteous many, a certain coldly-rational self-complacent tone, especially in Sirach, a suspicious complaining and an almost bigoted abstaining from true love -communion with others [comp. Sirach xi, 30 (29) sqq.; xii; xiii; xxv, 10 (7); xxx, 6; xxxiii, 25; sqq.], a zealous cautioning against the wickedness and falseness of others instead of a warning against the wickedness and deceptiveness of one's own heart ; and there is frequently a manifest lack of the proper humil- ity of the truly self-understanding conscience ; and the ob- taining of personal happiness is often presented too one- sidedly as a direct motive to virtue, so that the ethical view is sometimes tinged with a shallow utilitarianism [comp. Sirach xiv, 14 tqq.]. The book of Wisdom, showing traces of Alexandrine-Platonic influences, and accordingly containing the four Greek virtues [viii, 7], does not keep far clear of work-holy boasting [e. g. vii and viii] ; and though it admits the sinful corruption and weakness of all men [ix; xii, 10 sqq.; xiii, 1 sqq.; ii, 24], it yet brings them into a false con- nection with theories from other sources [viii, 19, 20 ; ix, 15 ; e. g., pre-existence of the soul, and dualistic relation of the body as an essential trammeling of the soul]. The book of Sirach gives expression both to a deep piety and to a rich practical life-experience, and though in the eyes of Rational- ism it is the most valuable book of j;he Old Testament, it is still very far superior to modern Rationalistic shallowness [comp. xxv, 32 (24) ; xl, 15,16 ; xii, 8 (5), sqq. ; viii, 6 (5)] ; it manifests, however, on the other hand, also a want of depth in its view of sinfulness and of the need of redemption [comp. xv, 15-17; xxxii, 27 (Septuagint, xxxv, 23) ; xxx vii, 17 (13) ; li, 18 (13) sqq.], and often places the outward ungenerous prudence- rules of a distrustful understanding in the stead of higher moral ideas [e. g. viii, 1 sqq.; xiii, 6, 7], and, as differing from the book of Wisdom, alludes to no supernatural goal of morality in a transmundane life; it may indeed teach the spiritually regenerated much moral life-wisdom and prudent rational foresight, but it cannot bring the natural man to 28.] TALMUDISM, ISLAMISM. 171 self-acquaintance and humility. From the stand-point of Christian ethics, this book is very far remote ; the essence of love is unknown to it. The book of Judith presents in narra- tive form a highly questionable morality [ix, 2 sqq.; comp. Gen. xxxiv; xlix, 5-7]. As in Sirach the vigorously-growing tree of Old Testament ethics begins to show signs of failing vitality, so in the Talmud (A. D. 200-600) We find the dead and decayed or petrified trunk.* Abandoned by the spirit of faith and hope, the Jews, in their faithlessness to their Redeemer, lost also the spirit of love; and human ingenuity changed the law which was readily enough borne by hoping faith, into an unspiritual yoke utterly subversive of moral freedom. The strictly objective character of the Old Testament law, so necessary for disciplinary purposes, had its vital complement in an expectant faith. This latter ele- ment becomes in the Talmud deceptive and wavering, and gives place almost entirely to the doctrine of the law ; and the lifeless, idealess law, multiplied thousaudfoldly by the ingenuity of human exegesis and inference, takes even the most insignifi- cant and external actions into a dictatorially-regulative tutelage. Man acts no longer as prompted by his inner consciousness, for his inner life-source is dried up, but according to the outward law as multiplying its branches through all the channels of human life. The Talmud contains, besides its more spiritual elements, which are mostly taken from the Old Testament, a system of casuistry unparalleled for its trivial and childish en- tering into minutiae, such as was possible in fact only on just such a soil, namely, matured Pharisaism. For the Jew, the authority of the Scribes takes the place of the moral conscience ; to him who honestly holds fast to the law, the multiplicity of precepts becomes a yoke subversive of true morality, while to those who are less sincere the manifold contradictions in the same give pretext for a disingenuous relaxation of duty. Observation. Islami&m, which finds its place in the history of the religious and moral spirit not as a vital organic member, but as violently interrupting the course of this history, and * Mishna translated by Rabe, "1760, 6 vote. Talmud Eabli, the Baby- lonian Talmud, by Pinner, 1842. Schulchan Arueh by Lowe, 1836, 4 vols. Fassel: Die mosaisch-rabbin. Tugend-u. Iflichtenl., 2 ed., 1842. 172 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 28. which is to be regarded as an attempt of heathenism to main- tain itself erect, under an outward monotheistic form, against Christianity, and to arm the entire unbroken essence of the nat- ural man against the spirit of an inner new-birth, has indeed given rise to a peculiar ethical system, though one which has so little of deptli peculiar to itself, that we need here only allude to it in passing.* The ethics of Islam bears the character of an outwardly and crudely conceived doctrine of righteousness ; conscientiousness in the sphere of the social relations, faithful- ness to conviction and to one's word, and the bringing of all action into relation to God, are its bright points ; but there is a lack of heart-depth, of a basing of the moral in love. The highest good is the very outwardly and very sensuously conceived happiness of the individual. The potency of sin is not recog- nized ; evil is only an individual, not an historical power ; hence there is no need of redemption, but only of personal works on the basis of prophetic instruction ; Mohammed is only a teacher, not an atoner. God and man remain strictly external to, and separate from, each other ; God no less in- dividually conceived of than man comes into no real com- munion with man ; and man, as moral, acts not as influenced by such a communion, but only as an isolated individual. The ideal basis of the moral is faith in God and in his Prophet ; the moral life, conceived as mainly consisting in external works, is not a fruit of received salvation, but a means for the attainment of the same; pious works, and particularly prayer, fasting and almsgiving, and pilgrimaging to Mecca, work salvation directly of themselves. Man has nothing to receive from God but the Word, and nothing to do for God but good works ; of inner sanctification there is no thought ; the essential point is simply to let the per se good nature of man manifest itself in works ; there is no inner struggle in order to attain to the true life, no penitence-struggle against inner sinfulness ; and instead of true humility we find only proud work-righteousness. To the nat- ural propensions of man there is consequently but little refused, nothing but the enjoyment of wine, of swine-flesh, of blood, of strangled animals, and of games of chance, and this, too, for * Imm. Berger : Ueber die Moral des Koran in Staudlin's Beitrage zur PMl., v, 250, (1799), superficial. Weil: Mohammed, 1843. Sprenger : Ltben u. Lehre des Moh., 1862. 29.] MARRIAGE AND POLYGAMY. 173 insufficient (assigned) reasons. The merely individual character of the morality manifests itself especially in the low conception that is formed of marriage, in which polygamy is expressly conceded, woman degraded to a very low position, and the dis- solution of the marriage bond placed in the unlimited discretion of the man ; there hence results a very superficial view of the family in general; the moral community-life is conceived of throughout in a very crude manner. Unquestionably this form of ethics is not an advancing on the part of humanity, but a guilty retrograding from that which had already been attained. C. CHRISTIAN ETHICS. SECTION XXIX. In Christianity alone morality and ethics are en- abled to reach their perfection, the former being perfected in the person of Christ himself, the latter being in process of self-perfection in the progressive intellectual activity of the church. The subjective and the objective grounds of morality are given, in Christianity, in full sufficiency. On the one hand, the moral subject has attained to a full consciousness of sin, of its general sway, of its historical significancy, and of its guilt ; on the other, he has, by redemption, become free from his bondage under sin. and risen again to moral freedom, has again attained to the possibility of accomplishing his moral task. On the one hand, the objective ground of the moral God is now for the first, perfectly, personally and historic- ally revealed to man. and God's will not merely man- ifested in unclouded clearness in his Word and through the historical appearance of the Redeemer himself, but also, by the holy, divine Spirit as im- parted to the redeemed, written into their hearts ; on the other, this God stands no longer in violent antith- 174 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [29. esis to the sin-estranged creature, but is in Christ rec- onciled with him, and, as a graciously loving Father, is present to him and in constant sanctifying and strengthening lite-communion with him. The goal of morality has become an other, has risen from the state of hope to a constantly-growing reality. God-sonship is not placed simply at the remote termination of the moral career, but is from the very beginning already present ; the Christian strives not merely in moral aspiration toward it, but lives and acts in it and as inspired by it ; he cannot possibly live or act morally if he is not already God's child ; he has his goal already from the very begin- ning as a blessed reality, and his further goal is in fact simply fidelity in this God-sonship, a sinking deeper into it, a strengthening and purifying of it by a constantly greater triumphing over the sinful nature which yet clings to the Christian, namely, the "flesh" which lusts against the spirit ; and for collective humanity the moral goal is and has been realizing itself from the beginning in ever increasing fullness, namely, in the fact that all nation-separating barriers progressively fall away, arid that the Word of life in- creasingly assumes form in the God-fearing of all nationalities, constituting the kingdom of God in its gradual rising to full historical reality in a universal Christian church. The essence of morality has risen from the stage of the obedience of a faithful servant to that of the lov- ing, confiding freedom of the children of God. Man has the command no longer as a merely outward, purely objective one, uncongenial to his subjective nature, but as an inward one dwelling within him, and as become his personal possession, and hence as 29.] CHRISTIANITY A PROGRESS. 175 no longer a yoke, a burden, but as an inner power at one with his personality itself. Man lives and acts no longer as a mere individual subject, but he lives and acts in full life-communion with the Redeemer, and through him with God, by virtue, on the one hand, of the love of faith, and, on the other, of the gift of the Spirit : I live, and yet not I, but Christ lives iu me. The moral idea is not a mere revealed Word, it is the Son of God as become man, the personal Re- deemer himself, not merely in his truth-unvailing doctrine, not merely in his truth-revealing Spirit, but pre-eminently in his person itself, both as the histor- ical, pure example of all holiness, as also as the One who is with us always even to the end of the world. Love to that God who is manifested in redemption as himself the highest love, is the motive of the moral life its essence and its power ; it is a life of holy com- munion in every respect, a life in and with God, a life with the children of God and in the communion of the redeemed. The morality of hope has passed over into a morality of the joyous victory-conscious- ness, i s rather an actual manifestation of the already- attained, grace-awarded highest good, than a mere longing, aspiring after it. The ideal goal of morality is not in the least of a doubtful character, but is ab- solutely assured. While the fundamental feeling of the heathen virtue-sage is that of a proud self-con- sciousness of personal merit, the fundamental feeling of the Christian is the feeling of grace-accepting, thankful, loving humility / while the fundamental virtue of the Greeks is self - acquired wisdom, that of Christian morality is child-like faith in God's loving revelation both in Word and in histor- ical act. 176 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [29. There is no need here of detailed developments or proofs ; we desire simply to present the ground-character of Christian ethics as in contrast to heathen ethics. This much is clear from what we have already said, that morality must assume here an entirely other form than in heathendom, and even in many respects a different one from that in the Old Testa- ment. No heathen ethical system looks to the formation of a kingdom of God embracing all mankind ; the freedom of the will is either denied or restricted to a very few favored ones, and with these it is regarded as unaffected by the his- torical power of sin ; heathenism knows nothing of personal love to God as a moral motive, and of the personal love of God to all men as its antecedent condition. Christianity takes it just as earnestly with the reality, the power and the guilt of sin, as with the real, historical, overcoming of the same through Christ. Man, as not from nature free, but as become free by historical redemption-act and by the personal appropriation of the same, is the true subject, capable of all true morality ; and hence the realization of this morality de- pends no longer on a mere nature-conditionment, but solely on man's free self-determination for or against his redemp- tion. That which is presumptuously presupposed by the Greek philosophers as already possessed by the elect few who are capable of true morality, namely, true will-freedom and a personal moral consciousness springing from the inner es- sence of the soul, all this has attained to its full truth only in Christianity, namely, in that the false security of a merely natural freedom and power is overcome and remedied. Both freedom and power are procured for all who wish them, and that not by self-deception, but by a real moral redemption- act of the alone holy One. That the highest good is not a something to be attained to exclusively by moral action, but, on the contrary, in its es- sence a power graciously conferred on the willing heart, a power which has true morality simply as its fruit and sub- jective perfection, and which manifests this morality essen- tially as faithfulness, as a preserving and virtualizing of the received grace, this is a thought utterly foreign to all heathendom, and which is placed, even in the Old Testa- ment, only in the promised future ; and upon this thought, 29.] LOVE AND PRAYER. 177 as upon the consciousness of personal guilt and divine grace, rests the so distinctively Christian virtue of humility, as that of a pardoned sinner. There is scarcely anywhere to be found so violent an ethical antithesis as that between the high-esteemed virtue of magnanimity in Aristotle (which corresponds to the pride of the Pharisee in the parable of Christ,) and the Christian humility of that Publican who ven- tures no other prayer than this : "God be merciful to me a sinner." Such magnanimity appears to the Christian as mere self-blinding pride, while this humility appears to the Greek as servile-mindedness. Heathen ethics is always simply of a purely individual character, or, if it relates to a moral community-life, then only of a merely civil character, as consisting in obedience to laws purely human, and valid only for a particular people ; or where, as in China, the state is regarded as of divine ori- gin and essence, there individual morality becomes essential- ly a mere mechanical self-conforming to an eternally on-re- volving unspiritual world-order ; Christian morality is, on the contrary, never of a merely individual character, but abso- lutely and always an expression of moral communion on the one hand, with the personal Saviour and God, and, on the other, with the Christian society ; its essential nature is there- fore love in the fullest sense of the word, and it is never of a merely civil character but belongs to a purely moral commun- ity-life, a life that rests in no respect on nature -limits or on unfreedom, namely, that of the Church as the historical king- dom of God. In contradistinction to worldward-turned heathenism, Christians make the foundation and essence of all moral life to consist in the constant direction of the heart to God ; and especially in prayer (which, as exalted by the communion of devotion, becomes the principal phase of the entire religious life, and conditions and preserves a direct personal life-communion with God) the entire moral life shapes itself into an expression of the religious consciousness as certain of its reconciliation with God. The Christian stands not alone in his moral life, nor is he merely a member of a moral society, but he stands in constant vital personal life-communion with God, and derives therefrom constantly new moral power. And precisely because Christian morality 178 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [g 29. is not of a merely individual character, but is rooted in and grows out of the holiest of communions, is it truly free ; the law stands no longer simply over against man, so that his re- lation to it becomes one of mere service, but, as in contrast to the self-sufficiency of the heathen mind (which finds in the natural man the pure fountain of the moral consciousness), it has become a perfectly inward personal law, one that con- stantly generates itself anew out of the sanctified heart of the spiritually regenerated. But prayer, wherein man enters into communion with God, is, as also the example of the ancient church shows, essentially in- tercession, implies moral communion. The development of morality into a collective life of the moral society, into a col- lective morality, is an essentially new phenomenon. Heathen- dom knew indeed the indefinite and merely impersonal, abstract power of national custom, as well as the very definite but un- free-working power of the civil law and of political rulers, but it knew nothing of a free moral power of the truly moral com- munity. The Christian community itself is the clearly duty- conscious ^upholder, promoter and conservator of the morality of the individuals ; it has the duty of the moral overseeing, furthering and guiding of all its members, and hence also of moral discipline, and, as involved hi this, also the power of in- flicting moral discipline upon the unfaithful, consisting essen- tially in the withdrawing of communion with them, in the excluding of them from the moral whole as being non-tolerant of any immoral element. The community-life is of so purely moral, so intensely unitary, a character, that the unfaithfulness of a single member thrills through the moral whole, and, because of the intimate love of the whole for all the individuals, is pain- fully felt and reproved and rejected by the society. The total- ity stands surety for the morality of the individual, and the in- dividual for that of totality ; the moral life of the spiritual organism has attained to its truth. The thought of church- discipline, which raises morality above the sphere of mere individuality, without, however, giving to the community- life the power of outward coercion, such as that of the state, but on the contrary preserves and gives effect to this life as a purely spiritual power, is an essentially Christian thought, and is only there practical where the moral idea 29.] TASK OF THE CHURCH. 179 and its realization in the community-life are taken really in earnest. In the emancipation of the human spirit by redemption, in the'taking up of the moral idea into the inner heart of the con- sciousness, there lie, now, the possibility of, and the incentive to, a scientific development of the moral consciousness. Hea- thendom developed an ethical science only on the basis of a presumed freedom and autonomy of the spirit of the natural man ; the Old Testament religion developed none at all, because in it the divine law was as yet an absolutely objective and merely passively-given one, to v which man could stand only in an obeying relation. But Christianity regains for the human spirit its true freedom, makes the merely objective law into an also perfectly subjective one, into one that lives in the heart of the regenerated as his real property, one that enlightens the reason and becomes thereby truly rational ; and hence there is here given the possibility of shaping this pure moral subject- matter as embraced in the divinely enlightened conscience, into free scientific self-development. But Cliristian ethics, naturally enough, developed itself as a science only after its presupposi- tions, namely, the dogmatical questions in regard to God, to Christ and to man had attained to some degree of ripeness in the dogmatic consciousness of the church, and hence it appears for a long while predominantly only in closest involution with dogmatics, and in popular ecclesiastical instruction in the form of rules and exhortations, and hi part also hi ecclesiastically- defined life-regulations enforced by ecclesiastical discipline. The notion that the ancient church could and should have passed over the great dogmatic questions and devoted itself pri- marily and predominantly, or hi fact exclusively, to the devel- opment of a system of morals as the essence proper of Chris- tianity, is very erroneous. If we once perceive and admit that the Christian world-theory in general, in respect to God, to the creature, and especially to the nature of man, is of a character diametrically opposed to the heathen view, and if we admit that morality cannot be of an unconscious and merely instinct- ive character, but must rest on a rational consciousness, then it is perfectly clear that the consciousness must first be scientific- ally informed in regard to the reality of existence, before that the consciousness of that which, in virtue of the character of 13 180 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 30. this reality, becomes moral duty, can be further developed The religious consciousness of" the moral was indeed given in high perfection in the first form of Christianity, but the scien- tific development of the moral could realize itself only very gradually and subsequently to the development of dogmatics. The three natural chief epochs of church history constitute also those of the history of Christian ethics. I. THE ANCIENT CHURCH UP TO THE SEVENTH CENTURY. SECTION XXX. Morality, as never separated from piety, and as uniformly based on loving faith in the Redeemer, and as upheld, fostered and watched over by the church- communion, appears in its inner phase as essentially love to God, and to Christ and to his disciples as brethren, and in its outer phase as a strict rejection of heathen customs, which latter feature, both in con- sequence of the persecutions suffered and because of the deep corruption of the extra-Christian world, as- sumes the form not unfrequently of a painfully-anx- ious self-seclusion from the same ; and when, with the victory of Christianity over heathenism, from the time of Constantine on, worldliness pressed into the church itself, then, as a natural counterpoise against this worldliness, world-renunciation was made to apply, among the more pious-minded Christians, even to the sensuously-worldly phase of the Christian life, and was intensified, in the hermit-life, even to morbidness ; and in consequence of the distinction which gradually sprang up in the church itself out of this antithesis in the Christian life, namely, between the moral com- 30.] INCIPIENT MONASTICISM. 181 mands, on the one hand, and the evangelical counsels on the other (which latter were thought to condition a superior degree of holiness), the moral consciousness was essentially beclouded. The moral views of the early Church are at once distin- guishable from those of later Judaism by their profound grasping into the pious heart as the living fountain of a true and free morality, and from those of heathenism by the pu- rity and rigor of the fundamental principles involved ; and the unavoidable militant resistance against the demoralized heathen world naturally enough heightened this rigor to a de- gree which, but for this, seems no longer required. The es- sential difference of the Christian moral law from that of the Old Testament is fully recognized as early as from the time of Barnabas (Ep. c. 19). The rigorous element shows itself especially in respect to all sensuous pleasure and all worldly diversion, to marriage, to temporal possessions, and to polit- ical power, and to whatever is in any manner implicated with heathenism. In contrast to heathen laxity, the ancient Chris- tians were all the more anxiously watchful against all domin- ion of sensuous desire, esteeming fasting very highly, though not as a commanded duty, and eschewing the demoralizing and religion-periling influence of the heathen stage and of other amusements ; and the severity of their sufferings under the hatred of the world naturally enough made all worldly pleasure appear as in diametrical antagonism to Christian- mindedness. In a well-grounded persuasion of the dangers involved, the Christians declined to accept official positions in the heathen State. Chasteness even in thought was rigor- ously insisted upon ; marriage was held more sacred than had ever been done before, and the sensuous element of the same was guarded within strict limits ; and in view of the troubles of the times, and of the expectation of a near second-coming of Christ (which pretty generally prevailed in the first two centuries), very many inclined to a preference of celibacy, without, however, regarding it as a specially-meritorious course of conduct; second marriages, however, were general- ly viewed as an infidelity to the first consort. Riches were 182 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [30. mostly looked on as of questionable desirableness ; the tak- ing of interest was regarded (in harmony with the Old Testa- ment view) as not permissible ; beneficence and generosity to the brethren on a wide-reaching scale, was held as one. of the most essential virtues ; fidelity to truth, especially in con- fessing the faith, even in the face of threatening death, was a sacred duty, and its faithful fulfillment was the Christian's brightest testimony before his heathen persecutors. The oath was generally regarded as not allowable. Tender love toward each other, and a noble love of enemies, were the Christian's honor. The moral and warmly-fraternal com- munity-life of the believers was a matter of astonishment even to the passionate enemies of Christianity. Slavery was at once essentially done away with by being transformed into a fraternally-affectionate service-relation ; and when the State and laws became Christian, it was also greatly mitigated legally. Notwithstanding the rigor of the moral view of the Chris- tians, it nevertheless differs essentially from that of the Stoics, because of its fundamental character of joyous faith and love ; it is in no respect a harsh, stiff or dismal, but, on the con- trary, a thoroughly vigorous, youthful and joyous self-sacri- ficing life, in the full enjoyment of inner peace and of a con- scious blessedness. These features were measurably lost only when the Christian Church itself ceased to be the pure moral antithesis of the un-Christian world, and when, having be- come a State-Church, it admitted into itself even worldly, and in so far, also, heathen elements. And it was now an es- sentially correct consciousness which inspired the more pious of the believers with a disinclination to the life and pursuits of the great mass of Christians, and drove them into separat- ing themselves from them. The error, however, was this, that instead of separating the unpiousfrom the Church itself, they chose the separation, within the Church, of the pious from communion with the mass of the Church, and thereby ren- dered the exclusion of the immoral from the Church more impracticable than ever, in other words, that, instead of morally purifying the natural elements that inhered both in' themselves and in the society, they despisingly withdrew the spiritual from all contact with the natural. 30.] ASCETICISM. 183 The first theoretical as well as practical separation of the ascetes (as imitated from the distinction, prevalent in the heathen world, between philosophers and the unphilosophical multitude, and as extending even to their costume), who thought by extreme world-renunciation to attain to an es- pecially high moral perfection, and, as consequent thereon, also the distinguishing of a general Christian morality from a higher (and in some sense voluntary) ascetic morality, man- ifests itself in the third century in the currents of Alexan- drian thought which had been so largely influenced by heathen philosophy, as yet but feebly in Clemens Alexan- drinus,* but already very damagingly in Origen.f The vic- tory of Christianity over the heathen state in the fourth cen- tury, and the in-rushing both of the great and also of the populace into the Church, occasioned, on the one hand, a progressively growing relaxation of ecclesiastical discipline and a darkening of the moral consciousness in the great masses, and, on the other, in natural antithesis thereto, an increasingly radical exalting of the monastic life, in which the Christian conscience of the multitude found, as it were, an atoning complementing of their own imperfect secularized life. The ordinary requirements made upon the life of the or- dinary Christian became less deep-reaching ; but all the more rigorous were those made upon the ascetic life wherein Christian morality was now thought to exist in its highest perfection. The distinguishing of mere ordinary moral duty, as the inferior, from moral perfection, became increasingly more familiar to the general Christian consciousness. The two true elements of Christian morality, namely, the turning away from the sinful world, and the aggressive living and working in and for the same, fell apart into two different channels, which respectively served, for the sum total of moral merit, as complements to each other; the superabun- dant merit of the sanctity of the ascetes fell to the good of the little-meriting world-Christians. In the sphere of moral- ity a division of labor, so to speak, took place, and, in conse- quence thereof, t .there was subsequently developed in the sphere of moral merits a system of labor and traffic so artfully * Strom., p. 775, 825 (Potter). t Comm. in Ep. ad Bom., 507 (De la Rue). 184 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [31. organized that it required all the boldly initiatory vigor of the Eeformation to bring again to the light of day the plain fundamental principles of evangelical morality. To the pres- ent period of the history of Christian ethics belong, however, only the feebler beginnings of this corruption. The development of monasticism introduced a dualism into Christian morality, in that it proposed for the ascetes a mo- rality essentially different from that of the rest of the Chris- tian world, the latter being based upon the divine command, and the former \npf>n pretended divine counsels ; with this error were more or less affected Lactantius, Ambrose, Chrysostom, Jerome, and Augustine. In consequence of this, general Christian morality was degraded to a mere minimum ; the truly good was made to be different from the divine com- mand, and this good was considered no longer as the imper- ative will of God, but only, as it were, a divine wish, the ful- filling of which procures for man a special extraordinary merit, but the non-fulfilling of which awakens no divine dis- pleasure. The more general prevalence of this view involved the overthrow of purely evangelical ethics, and the begin- ning of the perversion of the moral life of the Chnrch in practical respects. By far the greatest portion even of the dogmatic and ecclesiastical errors of the Romish and Greek Churches has sprung from this very notion of a special sanc- tity in monasticism. SECTION XXXI. Ethics itself appears not as yet in scientific form and apart from the presentation of the subject-matter of dogmatics ; it appears more in the popular edifi- catory than in the scientific writings, and approaches more nearly a scientific form in the works written in self-defense against the heathen. The first connected and somewhat comprehensive presentation of ethics by Ambrose in the manner of Cicero, is scientifically of little value; while the brilliant, penetrative, and ingenious moral thoughts of Augustine, (which, along with Aristotle, formed the foundation of Mediaeval 31.] THE EARLIER FATHERS. 185 ethics), deviate sometimes in daring originality from the earlier ecclesiastical view, and also bring some confusion into purely evangelical ethics by an over- valuing of monkish asceticism. After the time of Augustine, ethics is for the most part limited to the mere collecting of the views of earlier writers, and to popular instruction. The mystical thoughts of the pseudo-Dionyaius the Areopagite became influential onty in the Middle Ages.* The strict moral life of the early Christians furnished in- deed in its inner experiences weighty matter for ethics; ethics proper, however, confined itself at first to the framing of life-rules, which, resting on the fundamental thought of faith and love, were enforced and supported by Scripture texts and by apostolical tradition, by the example of Christ and of the saints of sacred history, and by spiritual experi- ence, and, at a later period, also by the example and authority of the martyrs, and by the definitions [canones] qf the synods, but they were not as yet digested into a scientific whole. From the moral philosophy of the heathen the Church Fathers kept themselves substantially clear, though they adopted from the Platonic and Stoic, and from the later pop- ular philosophy of the Eclectics, many forms and thoughts. The earlier Fathers, also Irenaeus, involved themselves in perplexities by the fact that, basing themselves primarily on the Old Testament writings, they often presented the moral life of the Patriarchs too fully as a pattern for Christians, al- though they recognized, throughout, the merely preparatory purpose of the Old Testament law. In their genuine writings the apostolical Fathers confine themselves to simple evangelically-earnest exhortations, t * The ethical views of the Ebionites and Gnostics offer many interest- ing phases, but they have too little influence in the shaping of the ethics of the church, and are, without a fuller examination, too obscure to justify us in entering upon the subject here at all : comp. Neander : Geseh. d. christl. Sittenl., pp. Ill, 137. t Heyns: Depatrum op. doctrina morali, 1833; Van Gilse, the same subject, 1833. 186 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 31. At a very early date there was manifested an antithesis of such on the one hand, as with full fidelity to the Christian faith yet used in the service of Christianity the best results of heathen culture, and, of such on the other, as regarded it as the primary duty of the Church to emphasize and insist on the total contrariety of Christianity to heathenism, and, above all things, also in the morally-practical life, to break off all yet-existing relations with the heathen world, and to present the holy society as, in itself, a totally new worid. Both tendencies the former prevailing more among Greek, the latter more among Latin Christians were equally legiti- mate, but both in equal danger of one-sidedness ; the former with the aid of Greek philosophy laid rather the foundation for a scientific construction of the moral consciousness, the latter developed rather a rigorous, and even harsh, legality of the moral life ; Origen and Tertullian respectively, are prom- inent representatives of this antithesis. The philosophically educated Justin the Martyr gives spe- cial emphasis, in defense of Christianity, to its high moral (and by him very earnestly conceived) views and practical workings, and to its difference from the merely preparatory Old Testament law ; he insists very strongly on the freedom of the will as a condition of the moral ; but he manifests al- ready a preference for celibacy as a higher perfection, doubt- less not without being somewhat influenced thereto by the Platonic notion of the nature of matter. Clemens Alex- andrinus enters more direct upon the nature of the moral. In his Exhortation to the Heathen (Logos protreptikos, cohorta- tio), he exposes the defectiveness of heathen ethics, and in single characterizing strokes contrasts with it Christian ethics as the higher; in his Paedagogos, designed for beginners in Christianity, he gives a more specific but at the same time more popular presentation of the subject ; but in his Stromctta he raises the Christian faith-consciousness and morality-con- sciousness to a much higher scientific form, evidencing truly philosophic ability. The divine Logos, who manifests him- self in fact in all true philosophy of the heathen, but in a still higher degree in the Old Testament, and most fully and purely in the New Testament, is also the pure fountain of the moral consciousness ; with the Hebrews the divine law 31.] CLEMENS ORIGEN. 187 was essentially objective ; but in Christianity it is, by virtue of the activity of the divine Logos, written into the hearts of all believers. The highest law is love to God, and, as based thereon, love to our neighbor ; the highest goal is like- ness to, and life-communion with, God ; the condition of the moral is will-freedom, which, although hampered, yet not destroyed, by the fall, is now restored in Christianity ; the Logos, that is, Christ, is the pattern of salvation and the leader thereto. In his very detailed inquiries in the sphere of the moral life, Clemens shows himself both earnest and judicious ; he esteems marriage very highly, and manifests no preference for celibacy. A visible fondness for the rational contemplation of the divine, as in contrast to the lower sphere of mere faith (corresponding to the prevalent Greek distinguishing between philosophers and ordinary men), in- terferes somewhat, however, with his interest in active out- ward life. On the use of earthly goods, he treats in detail in his work : Quiz dives salvetur. Origen has rich thoughts on the moral, scattered through his many writings, but especially in his Homilies and Com- mentaries and in his work against Celsus. His Scripture- exegesis is always pregnant with thought, though often venturesomely interpreting and allegorizing, especially in the Old Testament. Freedom of will he insists on fully as strongly as does Clemens, with whom in other respects he essentially harmonizes. His moral views are rigid, but not harsh ; the moral disposition alone constitutes, in his view, the worth of the deed ; but his over-estimation of the monk- ish life and of martyrdom, and his doctrine that man can do more of the good and meritorious than is commanded of him, becloud somewhat the otherwise evangelical character of his ethics. His well-known dogmatical tendency to un-churchly opinion shows itself less prominently in the sphere of ethics, and even his notion of the pre-existence of souls does not essentially interfere with his moral ideas. In striking contrast to the freer idealistic tendency of the Alexandrians, and in harshest Occidental realism, stands the African theologian Tertullian. Greatly delighting in spiritual eccentricities, and inclined to daring exaggerations of per se true ^oughts, this writer presents Christian ethics in his 188 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 31. numerous moral writings on special topics (especially in his De idololatria, De pudicitia, Ad uxorem, De monogamia, De ex- hortatione castitatis, De spectaculis, De oratwne, etc.), in a very rigorously legal spirit, especially insisting upon its self-deny- ing, world-renouncing, ascetic phase, already far leaning toward the monkish view, and exerting a wide-spread influ- ence on the Occident. And this juristic-minded man, with his strong inclination to rigorous formulae, is true to himself also in the sphere of morality. His passing over to Montan- ist views does not essentially modify his previous moral views, as they were in fact from the first not inconsistent therewith. While, on the one hand, he emphasizes more strongly than the Greek Fathers the natural corruption of all men as resulting from the fall, without, however, doing away with moral freedom, on the other hand, he raises (though not without having the precedent of the church in his favor) the requirement of holiness in Christians so high that he re- gards as admissible, at farthest, only a single repentance after baptism, and, for reiterated severe sins, such as defection from the faith, adultery, whoredom, murder, knows of no forgiveness whatever ; * the distinction here appearing more strongly than ever before between venial and mortal sins, received subsequently a somewhat different significancy. The greatest sin is defection from the true faith idolatry ; t hence the Christian must avoid in word and deed every thing which is connected with heathenism, e. g., he may not crown himself, may not visit theatrical spectacles, etc. Ter- tullian insists also, and with almost painful anxiety, on at- tention to all outward actions and manners, e. g., he gives long and detailed disquisitions on the clothing and decoration of women, whom he would like to see attired in a natural and modest simplicity, not without many theoretical whims (De halitu, muliebri, De cultu foeminarum, De velandis vi/rgini- bu8). Marriage he regards indeed as a divine institution, al- though, in view of the expectation of a speedy second coming of Christ, he prefers celibacy as the more perfect and pure state ; and second marriages he unconditionally forbids as a heavy sin, in the face of the utterances of Paul. Fasting * Depoenit., c. 2, 6 ; Depudicitia, c. 2, 19 ; comp. Adv. Marc,, 4, 9. f- De idolol. , c. 1 sqq. 31.] TERTULLIAN CYPRIAN. 189 he requires -not merely as a penance, but as a protective means of virtue, conducive to a higher perfection, namely, in that it turns the soul away from the earthly and toward the heav- enly ; and he attempts to reduce it to definite rigorous rules (De jejunio). To accept political offices and to wear the in- signa thereof, conflicts per se with Christian humility, seeing that because of their connection with heathen religion they are inconsistent with Christian sincerity, as also, because of the function of officers to execute and to torture, inconsistent with Christian gentleness ; * military service, the Christian must unconditionally refuse.! The notion of a Christian state is utterly foreign to Tertullian; he knows only of the heathen state. The enduring of martyrdom may, as the highest victory of Christian virtue, by no means be evaded by flight or otherwise ; all shrinking is here unworthy coward- ice (Defuga in persecutione ; Scorpiacum). Unshaken patience in all manner of suffering in general, he describes and dis- cusses with great ability (De patientia). Cyprian, a great admirer of Tertullian, but more churchly than he, and in his moral judgments more mild, developed, one-sidedly, still further, the ascetic phase of Christian morality; abstinence from enjoyment, steadfastness in suffer- ing, martyrdom, and beneficence to the poor, appear, to him, as the highest virtues ; strict churchliness, obedient submis- sion to the visible church and its episcopal guides, as the foundation of all Christian morality ; heretical opinions and schismatic separation, as the ground of all moral corruption. While in Tertullian morality appears more as an individual manifestation of the religious personality, in Cyprian it is rather an expression of the community-life of the church. As to marriage and celibacy, he judges as Tertullian. (De unitate eeclesm; Exhort, ad martyrium ; De tono patientice De opere et eleemosynis ; De zelo et liwre; De oratione dominica; and many letters). The severe dogmatic conflicts of the fourth century which so deeply rent the Oriental church, turned the current of thought somewhat away from ethics, so that we here find scarcely any thing but merely popular and not scientific presentations of the * De idol., c. 17, 18, 21. t De corona miUtis, c. 11 ; De idol., e. 19. 190 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 31. ethical, and that too for the most part simply in homilies and practical elucidations of Scripture. Basil the Great :is yet largely devoted to ethical questions gives (besides his homi- lies and several other writings of kindred nature) in his Ethica a short, popular, little-digested, but plain and Gospel-inspired synopsis of New Testament ethics, comprised in eighty rules expressed in strictly Biblical forms. In other respects he man- ifests indeed an over-estimation of monasticism and of outward works in general, as well as an under-estimation of the natural corruption of man. His brother, Gregory of Nyssa, likewise emphasized moral freedom quite strongly, even in man while as yet unregenerate, and applied many of the ideas of Greek phi- losophy to Christian ethics, and moreover found also the moral ideal in the monkish life. This life was still more exalted by Gregory of Nasiamus, who also presents already quite definitely the doctrine of the evangelical counsels as distinguished from the universally-binding moral laws,* although in other respects he gives expression to many excellent thoughts on Christian ethics. The liberally-cultured, John Chrysostom, who was no less profound in feeling than rich in thoughts and in acquaint- ance with man, and who was inspired with high moral earnest- ness and moral love, presents in his masterly Homilies an es- sentially pure, evangelical and deep-reaching moral view, in a striking, warm and clear style, to such an extent as no other Church Father has done ; and even where, in the delineation of the natural conscience and of its freedom, he presents, by the help of philosophical examples, the favorable phases rather too prominently, and where he treats over-fondly of monasticism and the monkish life, and ascribes, in repentance, too high a value to outward works, especially to fasting and alms-giving, still the evangelical ground-thought is by no means pushed into the back-ground. Love to God is, with him, the ground, the beginning, the essence of all morality. His somewhat ideal- istic turn of mind betrays him sometimes into unpractical views, e. g., into the wish (born of his love to monasticism) for the introduction of a community of goods. t Imitating Chrys- ostom also in his weaker points, the likewise philosophically * Orat. Ill, invect. in JuL, p. 94 sqq. (ed. Col.); Orat. iv, c. 97 sqq. (ed. Bened.) t HomiL in Act., opp. (ed. Montf.) ix, 93. 31.] LACTANTIUS AMBROSE. 191 educated abbot, Isidore of Pelmium, treated, in numerous epis- tles, largely of special topics in ethics, and sometimes bordered on Pelagian views. In the more practically-inclined and less dogmatically-rent Occident, we find, already in the fourth century, more compre- hensive treatises on the moral subject-matter of Christianity, but as differing from the more idealistic and philosophic Greek doctors in a rather realistic, legal, juridical manner; and it is characteristic that precisely the most excellent of the ethical writers among the Latin Fathers were originally jurists and rhetoricians. Lactantius, in his Institutiones divirue (III- VI), treats of the ethical quite largely, critically assailing hea- then ethics, and defending spiritedly the ethics of Christianity. The highest good, as the ground-question of ethics, he finds in the blissful communion of the immortal spirit with God, a com- munion which is to be attained to only in the Christian religion, and of which, in heathendom, not even the conception is to be found. Christianity alone, but not heathen philosophy, affords a knowledge of the moral goal, and of the moral way, and fur- nishes also in Christ the moral example, and moral strength, and lastly, in pure unselfish love, the true moral motive. The unchurchly and dualistically-iuclining notion entertained by Lactantius, of a certain primitively-ordained necessity of evil (ii, 8, 9, 12; vi, 15; De ira Dei, 55) has not much interfered with his other moral thoughts. Ethics attains, in a feeble and ill-adapted outward imitation of Cicero, to a scientific form, though without really scientific development, through the labors of Ambrose, whose work De affici.s ministrorum, though for a long time highly prized, is yet rhetorical in style, and feeble in scientific contents ; and yet, notwithstanding that it introduces, undigested, many foreign thoughts and forms into the field of Christian thought in order to conceal a manifest lack of theo- logical culture, it still commends itself by the warmth of a sincere heart, by its enthusiasm for active piety and by ingen- ious trains of thought. Though treating in this work primarily of the duties of clergymen, Ambrose yet considers also pretty extensively those of Christians in general ; as a whole, however, it has little order and consecutiveness, and, notwithstanding its frequent prolixity and repetitions, leaves many points but slightly touched. He cites many Biblical examples, especially 192 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 31. from the Old Testament ; in his exegetical method he is quite faulty ; that which is not expressly taught in Scripture either by word or example, he regards as unallowed, e. g., jesting. The four virtutes pr'mcipales (the expression virtutes cardinalea occurs only in the manifestly unauthentic work, De sacramentis), he adopts from Plato ; he gives them, however, a much higher significancy ; and, by finding for them a greater unity in piety and love, as also by penetrating deeper into the subjectivity of the love-inspired and morally-acting heart, he demonstrates, despite all his defectiveness in scientific construction, the great superiority of Christian ethics over heathen. He places the highest good in the bliss resulting from a knowledge of God, and in moral perfection, the two being inseparably connected with each other. A preference for celibacy he shares with his contemporaries, but in enthusiastic laudations thereof he even outdoes most of them. The" duty of beneficence he pushes so far that, like Chrysostom, he passes over into advocacy of a vol- untary community of goods (i, 28) ; and he regards self-defense, even in case of murderous assault, as unallowable. The scien- tifically-insignificant exegetical writings of Ambrose deal also very largely with ethical questions. St. Jerome, in such of his writings as treat of the moral, is, for the most part, intent on exalting the, by him, fanatically espoused monastic life, but rather rhetorically than scientifically, and with frequent incon- sistencies ; treating marriage disdainfully, and in fact hostilely, he finds any good in it at all only because it produces children who may devote themselves to the unmarried life (Ep. 22, 20, ad Eustoch., ed Veron., t. i) ; his passionately violent assailing of Jovinian (in Rome) who contested the meritoriousness of the monastic life and of ascetic works, found in the spirit of the age great applause. Much higher in spirit and penetration than the views of the other Latin Fathers, stand St. Augustine's ethical disquisi- tions, De doctrina Christiana, De civitate dei, De moribus ec- clexice catholicce, De libero arbitrio, and other works without, however, presenting a connected ethical system. In Augus- tine the Occidental church not only manifests her radical antithesis to the fundamental and dangerous errors of the Pelagian school, but she further develops at the same time the ethically-significant and healthful antithesis to the more 31.] ST. AUGUSTINE. 193 dogmatically and theosophico-speculatively inclined Greek church, namely, in that this Father emphasized much more strongly than did the Greek church the antagonism of the natural man to God as well as man's moral impotency, and hence his need of redemption, and also in that he conceived the Christianly-moral life as the expression of a complete spiritual transformation, whereas the Greek Fathers tended to regard it rather as a bettering of the, in his moral essence, but slightly-disordered natural man. Occidental ethics makes more reference to the Saviour ; Oriental, more to the Creator ; the former has therefore conceived more deeply, than the latter, the moral consciousness of Christianity, and has de- veloped it more fully. And from this time on, the history of Christian ethics finds but little that is worthy of attention outside of the current of Occidental thought. As it was the special task of the Greek church to ward off from the Chris- tian doctrine of God and of Christ, all heathen and Judaistic notions, and definitively to refute them, so was it the task of the Latin church to confute and overcome these same ele- ments in the field of ethics; and this task was in the main accomplished by St. Augustine. The freedom of the will as it appears in the Greek church, and especially also in Chrys- ostooi, is by no means identical with the freedom of the regenerated Christian as insisted upon by the evangelical church, and the confidence which many of the Greek Fathers place in the moral inclination of the piously-stirred heart, is not yet free from every trace of that over-estimation of the purity of human nature so characteristic of heathenism ; also moral action is as yet obscured by the thought of the meri- toriousness of the same. These remaining traces of heathen and Jewish views were, in their ground-thought at least, eradicated by Augustine ; the thought of unmerited grace whereby man attained to the capability of a moral life, and to the highest good, was placed by him in the foreground, and thus the foundation was laid for a true evangelical ethical system. His doctrine (far exceeding Scripture warrant) of the total unfreedom, for good, of the natural will and of an unconditional election of grace, has a less misleading influ- ence on his moral views than might have been expected, it simply gives to them the character of deep earnestness, but 194 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 31. does not dampen the power of moral admonition. Man in his enslavement under sin to moral unfreedom is raised to real moral freedom only on the basis of a divine election of grace, by means of a spiritual regeneration through faith in Christ. Natural man is not able to will and to accomplish the truly good ; the virtues of heathen and of unbelievers, though indeed often very admirable, have yet no real merit, no truly moral worth. Between virtue and vice there lies no medium ground ; whatever is not virtue, and hence whatever springs not from faith, from the right intentio, is necessarily sinful ; natural man is free only to evil ; even the desire for redemption is lacking to him, and is purely a work of gra- cious influence. Still there are among sin-dominated hu- manity great differences of personal guilt, and even the heathen have yet a free choice between the more, and the less, evil ; to true righteousness, however, they cannot attain. The destination of man, and hence his moral goal and the highest good, is to return to God from whom he has fallen away, to become reunited with Him by God-likeness. This is possible only through love to God, which is consequently the ground and essence of all good. The world and what- ever belongs to it, is not the goal of moral effort, is not the highest good itself, but only a means to this end. Lve to the world in itself is therefore not true moral love, but is only lust ; spirit never has true love save to spirit. But man is not to himself the highest end, because he is not per se capa- ble of blessedness ; the highest end, and hence the highest object of love, is God, upon whom all -blessedness rests. All true love rests on love to God, and to love men otherwise than in God, is sinful ; also self-love is only then moral when it flows from love to God. Hence love to God is the first and highest command, and the one from which all others spring ; this love works obedience to God's command, wherein alone rests all the moral worth of an action ; love is the sole true motive to the good, fear is only a feeble incipiency of wisdom. Hence virtue is in its essence simply love to God, is nothing other than ordo amoris* and therefore obedience to the divine will, which will is the eternal law of all morality. * De civ. dei, xv, 22. 31.J SEVEN VIRTUES. 195 Love to God as the ground-virtue unfolds itself into the four cardinal virtues : TEMPERANTIA, amor integrum se prac- lens ei, quod amatur ; FORTITUDO, amor facile tolerans omnia propter quod amatur; JUSTITIA, amor soli amato serciens et proptcrea recte dominant; PRUDENTIA, amor ea, quibus adju- vatur, db eis, quibus impeditur, sagaciter seligens* It is with great ingenuity that the Greek classification of virtue is thus embraced and presented in higher unity, as an unfolding of love under four forms, but the violence of the process is too mani- fest not to make felt at once the unadaptedness of the Greek classification for the Christian idea ; it is new wine in old ves- sels. To these virtues, borrowed from Greek philosophy, Augustine adds, as superordinate thereto, the three virtues subsequently known as the theological virtues : faith, love and hope, without succeeding in placing them into a clear relation to the other four; t and this unclear and clumsy twofold classification prevails from now henceforth and until the close of the Middle Ages. Faith springs from the merely germinal love to God ; but only from faith springs the true all-dominating love to God, and from faith and love springs hope, namely, a longing for the highest good, for the blissful enjoyment of God in union with Him, in the vision of Him, in perfected love ; objectively therefore the highest good is God himself as the perfect truth, the infinite eternal life itself. Evil or sin is in essence and origin a lack of true love, that is, a love not to God but to the world and its lusts, and primarily a love to self that does not rest on love to God, that is self-seeking. From self-seeking springs evil desire (concupiscentia) which becomes a power over the spirit. Evil become real in no sense whatever from God, but through the free choice, through the guilt, of free creatures, is a guilty ruining of the originally good. The distinction (referring primarily to the administration and practice of penance) be- tween venial and mortal sins (peccata venalia et mortifera 8. mortulia), Augustine defines in the thenceforth prevailing sense, thus, that the latter include all sins consciously and * De moribus eccl., c. 15 (25) sqq., 25 (46) ; De lib. arl., 1, 13 ; 2, 10. t Enchiridion, s. deflde, spe et cMritate / de doctr. christ., 1, 37 ; 3, 10, ft al. 14 196 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 31. voluntarily committed against the Decalogue, and particu- larly idolatry, adultery, and murder, which, unless atoned for by ecclesiastical penance, involve damnation, whereas the former may be atoned for, or gotten rid of, by the repentant person himself, without special church-penance, through prayer, alms-giving and fasting.* As to the requirements of morality in detail, Augustine is no less earnest than judicious, forming quite a contrast to the manifold laxities of the age, and to many errors and ex- treme views of earlier Church Fathers, and, on the whole, he conceived of Christian morality much more profoundly than had yet been done by church writers ; but his more especial merit consists in this, that he brought clearly and definitely into prominence the foundation of all morality, namely, faith and the essence of faith, to wit, love to God, and that he referred the validity of outward works more definitely than had been done before to the inner disposition of the actor. A truly evangelical spirit breathes through the greater part of his moral views ; and even where, in harmony with" the spirit of the times, he laudingly emphasizes outward good works, and particularly fasting, alms-giving and monastic asceticism, he still always lays greater stress on the state of the heart than on the work itself. His greatest departure from a purely evangelical consciousness is the recognition of the, then, already long-prevalent distinction between the di- vine commands and the divine counsels; the latter refer es- sentially to the giving up of allowed enjoyments, and espe- cially to the abstaining from marriage. The man who leaves the counsels unobserved, sins not ; he who fulfills them, ac- quires for himself higher virtue ; wedlock-virtue is merely human virtue, but virginal chastity is angelic virtue. Mar- riage is indeed per se holy and pure, and prevailed also in the state of sinlessness,t but for the state of sinfulness, from which in fact the redeemed are not as yet totally free, celib- acy is higher than marriage ; and if all men would but live unmarried, there would thereby be straightway brought about the end of the world and the perfection of the king- * Sermo, 351 ; EncTiir.^ 70, 11 ; comp. Defideet op., c. 19 (34) ; He civ. dei, 21, 27. t D Geneti ad litt., 9, 3 iqg. t 1. 31.] ST. AUGUSTINE BOETHIUS. 197 dom of God.* But Augustine wisely avoids the self-contra- dictory extremes of Jerome, and tolerates even second mar- riages. In contrast to heathen ethics, which looks, for all salvation, to the State and to its unlimited sway, Christians, even in the days of Augustine, placed (not without very good reasons) very little confidence in the worldly State. The Christian state to the realization of which the Germanic na- tions were more especially called had not yet become real ; and the nominally-Christian Roman State lingered as yet es- sentially in heathen forms. In his ingenious work De civitate dei, Augustine contrasts with the earthly State the purely spiritual divine State, deriving the former from the self-seek- ing of God-forsaking man, as prevailing since the brother- murder of Cain, since which time the earthly and heavenly State have been in a condition of divorce (xv, 5). "The two kinds of love produced two kinds of state : the earthly state springs from self-love which ripens into contempt of God ; the heavenly, from love to God which ripens into contempt of self." (xiv, 28). The divine State develops itself inde- pendently of the sinful earthly one, until it attains to its true manifestation in Christ ; this state is not an outwardly force- exercising one, but a spiritual kingdom, and is indeed des- tined to sanctify and transfigure the earthly State, to change it from a merely world-state into an organ of the divine state, but not to merge itself into it. The great decline of the scientific life in the Occident from and after the close of the fifth century, manifested its effects also in the field of ethics. Little more was done than to make collections of the opinions (sententice) of the Fathers, and to apply them to purposes of Church-discipline and of popular instruction. But there was no further creative pro- duction. In reducing to greater system the discipline of penance, the interest was turned rather to the discriminating, defining and classifying of sins than to the scientific exami- nation of the moral in general. The knowledge of Greek ethics disappeared almost entirely, and the work of Boethius, De consolatione philosophies (about A.D. 542) t, which is but feebly touched with Christian influence, and which for the * De Sancta mrginitate ; De bono conjugali ; De nuptiis et con&ipis. t Fr. Mtzsch : System des Soeth., 1860, p. 42 sqq. 198 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 31. most part expresses, eclectively, mere Graeco-Roman philos- ophy, passed in the earlier Middle Ages for an excellent work of Christian philosophy. Gregory the Great, basing himself on Augustine, wrote moral expositions (Mornlid) of the Book of Job, of Solomon's Song, etc., and other rather edificatory than scientific works of the same class ; most in- fluential was his Regula pastoralis, which treated of the cler- ical calling more especially under its moral phase. Isidore of Hispalis (Seville) (ob. 636) treats, especially in his Sententice, on many moral points, mostly, however, by way of judicious digesting from preceding Fathers, especially from Augus- tine and Gregory the Great, furnishing for the early Mid- dle Ages a principal help in ethical study. In the Greek Church Maximus the Confessor (ob. 622) gives in his " Chapters on Love " * a tolerably complete presentation of ethics ; John Damascenus (ob. 754) furnishes, in his chief work, the ground thoughts for an ethical treatise, and in his "Holy Parallels " a rich collection of patristic sentences. Standing entirely apart, and of influence only in the Middle Ages, is the pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite (fifth century) .who introduced Neo-Platonic mysticism into Christianity, and whose Pantheistically-inclined world-theory invades here and there also the moral sphere, f God is all in all, is the being in all being, the life in all that lives, is the good absolutely. Hence evil cannot exist by itself, but must always be a negating something on the good, is not an existing something, but es- sentially only a lack and more an appearance than a reality, and it turns again into the good. The goal of all life, and hence also of the moral, is the returning into God, the changing into God, of whatever is as yet distinct from God ; the highest wis- dom is therefore the turning-away of the spirit from whatever is not God, the unclouded beholding of the one, the nameless, the pure divine light, in which God directly imparts himself to man. An outwardly active morality is, according to this view, the opposite of true wisdom. * Kftydhaia irepi aydirrjf. t Especially in De divinis nominibus ; De ccelesti hierarchia ; D mygt. theol. 32.] CASUISTIC ETHICS. 199 II. THE MIDDLE AGES. SECTION XXXH. The ecclesiastical consciousness, as having arrived now at greater repose, but as also in a state of spirit- ual paralysis, limits itself primarily to the preserving and digesting of the views already-attained to, and to the constructing of systems of life-rules on the basis of the decisions of the Fathers and of church councils, at best elucidated anew by examples from the Scriptures or from the legends of the saints. The practical decisions on the subject of church penance gave rise gradually, in connection with these collec- tions of rules, to a very minutely-specifying system of casuistry, which, however, related primarily chiefly to transgressions. The moral views themselves were already largely estranged from evangelical purity, and an ascetic monk-morality, not binding upon all, passed as the ideal of Christian virtue, while the general morality, binding upon all, .was to a large degree neglected. The libri pcenitentiales, for the use of confessors, are based for the most part on the decisions of synods and on ancient practice, but are also in some degree complemented by their respective authors; they give for the most part little more than imper- fectly classified and illogically connected registers of single sins and of the church-penances and penalties imposed therefor, the latter of course without established and certain norms (Theodore of Canterbury, Bede, Halitgarius and others). These books form the beginning of a casuistical treatment of ethics, which was subsequently extended to other questions than sins, especially to cases of conscience. Attempts at a more inde- pendent and more connected, but yet, on the whole, purely 200 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [32. practical treatment of ethics mostly simply on single points, were made by Alcuin (De mrtutibus et vitiis ; De ratione ani- mce), largely borrowing from Augustine; also by Rhdbanua Maurus, by Jonas, Bishop of Orleans (about 828), by the earnest- ly sin-rebuking Ratherius of Verona (ol. 974), by Damiani (ob. 1072), the excessive eulogist of self-castigation, and by the learned FuTbert of Chartres (ob. 1029). In proportion as the zeal of love abated, and worldly- mindedness increased in the church at large, in the same proportion arose, as in antithesis to this secularism of the church, a zeal for a special holiness transcending the general morality required of all. Directions for the monkish life form a favorite topic for ecclesiastical moralists ; the merits of the ascetic life are more warmly lauded than the practical Christian life in the civil or domestic spheres, and wedlock is progressively more deeply disparaged as in contrast to en- tire renunciation ; consorts are loaded with praise, who divorce themselves in order to practice such renunciation ; and accord- ing to Damiani's assertion, even St. Peter had to undergo the martyr-death in order to wash away the stains of hia wedlock-life (De perfect ione monach, c. 6). SECTION XXXIII. The philosophy of the Middle Ages, and especially Scholasticism, was occupied for a long while almost exclusively with speculations on dogmatical and metaphysical questions, leaving ethics almost un- touched ; wherever, however, it brought ethics within the sphere of its intellectual activity, there it treated the same merely in connection with dogmatics, and for the most part in the light of the opinions of Augustine, and, later, of those of Plato and Aristotle, often buuglingly combining the latter with the former. The brilliant but idealistico-Pantheistieally inclined mystical philosophy of John Scotus Erigena, which threw its lights, as well as its shades, into the 33.] ERIGENA'S PANTHEISM. 201 field of morality, seems as not understood to have had little influence on subsequent ethics, save in the mystical school. The spiritualistico-idealistic tendency of the Schoolmen could primarily treat of the moral only collaterally, at least until the dogmatical and metaphysical fields had attained to some degree of philosophical maturity and self-consciousness. The potent influence of Augustine made itself felt also in the ethical field, and his ground-thoughts re-appear in almost all the Schoolmen. The freedom of the will is, however, dis- tinctly recognized, although, in man after the fall, as in a trammeled condition ; but also Greek philosophy was power- fully influential on ethics, not merely as to the form, but also as to the subject-matter. The Platonic classification of the virtues was already early combined with the three theological virtues, notwithstanding the inconsistency and impractica- bility of such a uniting of two entirely different stand-points. In how far John Scotus' attempted translation of Aristotle's Ethics into Latin was of influence, is doubtful ; the applica- tion of Aristotle to Christian ethics appears in a more direct ' form, first, in the thirteenth century. The deep-thinking John Scotus Erigena (at the court of Charles the Bald, then at Oxford, ob. 886), who was not un- derstood by his own age, and who had but little connection with it even in his errors, touches in his chief work, De di- visione natures, also upon the more general ethical topics, and molds them to his idealistico-Pantheistical system, a system based on the Neo-Platonic views of Dionysius the Areopagite, and which very different from recent natural- istic Pantheism denies not the absolute personal God, but on the contrary the independent reality of the world. The world is only another existence-form of the eternal God him- self ; God alone is real ; the creature, in so far as it is con- ceived as distinct from God, is nothing ; it exists only in so far as it is wholly identical with God. God is whatever truly exists, because He himself does all and is in all; G. d in not merely the most excellent part of the creature, but He is its beginning, its middle and its end the essence and true being in all things. The coming into being of the world is 202 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 33. a self-outpouring of God, a theophany. God is manifest not only in Christ, but also in the entire universe, in the highest degree in the rational creature, and here indeed most purely in the saints. The believing and cognizing of the saints take place solely through God ; God cognizes himself in man as cognizing Him. Man is therefore God's image, because God himself conies to manifestation in him. As now every thing ideal, and hence the ideal world, precedes, in the mind of God, its outward realization, so is also the spirit of man earlier than his body, which latter is but the shadow of the spirit, and is in fact by it created, and that too as a perfect and immortal one (ii, 24). Man, however, is now no longer in the condition in which he originally was ; the body is frail and subject to death; this condition can have been brought about only by sin. But how is sin possible if God is in fact all in all ? Answer: every thing is real only in so far as it is good ; but in so far as it is not good, it exists not. Hence evil is a mere non-being, a merely negative something, but in no sense a real entity. God can cognize only that which is, not that which is not, hence He cognizes and knows not evil ; for if He knew it, then it would be real, and hence would not be evil (ii, 28). This normal Dei igno- rantia banishes evil from the sphere of being into that of mere appearance. All evil is merely the shadow of the good, and is accordingly only upon the good, is essentially only a lack, a non-being, not a positive entity. Sin consists in this, that man, as on the one hand identical with, and, on the other, distinct from God, fixes his attention solely upon this distinctness from God, directs himself toward himself and toward nature, and not toward God (i, 68; ii, 12, 25). Only by this confessedly per se inexplicable (v. 36) fall into sin, is it that the body of man became material and mortal and a clog to the spiritual life (ii, 25, 26; comp. iv, 12, 14, 15, 20); man thereby ceased to be truly a spirit, became subject to natural desires ; previously the lord of nature, he now became a slave to it. The ultimate goal of all life, and hence also of the moral, is the return into God (ii, 2, 11), namely, so that this differentness from God, all corporeality and individuality, ceases and passes over into God himself, is transformed into Him (i, 10 ; v, 20, 27, 37, 38). Hence all 34.] SCHOLASTICISM. 203 moral effort is directed toward this uniting of one's self with God, toward the breaking down of the hampering limits of individual naturality, and realizes itself in a gradually pro- gressive development (v, 8, 39). Morality must accordingly bear a predominantly spiritualistic and ascetic, negating character, must disdainfully turn itself away from finite reality (iv, 5). Into details Erigena enters but little. It is perfectly consequential in him that he regards marriage, which rests on the difference of the sexes, as having origi- nated solely in consequence of sin, whereas sinless man was sexless (ii, 6; iv, 12, 28). And yet marriage is now allow- able, only, however, in view of the propagation of the race, irrespective of sensuous pleasure. Though the mystico- speculative bases of these ethical thoughts were of a very unchurchly character, still the thoughts themselves answered very well to the ascetic spirit of the then prevalent morality. SECTION XXXIV. It is only in the twelfth century that ethics is seriously treated of by scholastic science; first by ffildebert of Tours (ob. 1134), for the most part in the light of the Roman Eclectic and Stoic philoso- phies ; then by Abelard, who, however, treats, mostly in a mere preliminary manner, of the more general questions, giving proof of great acumen, but also sometimes enfeebling the significancy of sin ; very fruitfully by Peter Lombard, who presents, in the light of Augustinian thoughts, and with the help of ancient philosophy, a very clear and well-arranged total of Christian doctrine, of which ethics, though but briefly presented, constitutes an essential part ; but with greatest thoroughness and fullness by Thomas Aquinas, who made large use of the Aristo- telian philosophy in perfecting a system of Christian speculation, and that, too, without thereby working serious detriment to the Christian idea. In Duns 204 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 34. Sootus a sophistico-skeptical treatment of ethics began already to effect, in many respects, an enfeebling of the moral idea, and to prepare the way for the double- dealing morality of the Jesuits. Through almost all the scholastic presentations of ethics there prevails a pretty great uniformity of spirit and manner of treat- ment, springing mostly from Augustine and Aristotle, and subsequently from Peter Lombard and Thomas Aquinas ; evangelico-theological and ethnico-philo- sophical elements are often brought together, without that the latter element is always successfully mastered and molded into a Christian character. Ingenious arid often truly speculative processes of thought, but frequently also trivial and fruitless hair-splittings, also a pedantic carrying out of particular schemata, and a preference for certain typical numbers in the distribution of the subject-matter, such are the gen- eral characteristics of scholastic ethics. Contemporaneously with scholasticism prevailed also the science of casuistry, which had also to do with practical life ; this science was in fact influenced by scholasticism to a higher development, and it attained to its highest perfection in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries. Hildeb&rt of Tours (about 1100) treated ethics for the first time in a special work : Philosophia inoralis de honesto et utili (Opp. Par. 1708, p. 961 sqq). In philosophical contents it is as yet feeble and dependent, and belongs rather to the sphere of Roman popular philosophy, especially that of Cicero and Sen- eca, than to speculative science proper; and the Christian ele- ment is thrown largely into the shade by that which is borrowed from heathen moralists ; the four Greek virtues are servilely car- ried out ; the relation of the honestum and utile is extensively discussed ; and as a whole the work is immature and superficial. Nearly cotemporaneously appears Abelard^ Ethica, s. Scito te 34.] ABELARD. 205 ipsum, not a comprehensive system, but properly only a phil- osopliico-theological introduction to ethics ; it treats somewhat un-uniformly of general questions, and particularly of the essence of sin and of its imputation. The toning-down of Christian thoughts, elsewhere observable in Abelard, in his over-estimat- ing the natural capability of man, shows itself also here. He distinguishes between a natural tendency to evil (called by him a " will ") and the freely-resolved approving of the same ; the former is not per se sinful and forbidden of God, for it has its seat in the sensuous and fragile nature of man, and it is not even yet a sin when it overcomes the reason ; it becomes sin only by a real approving of sin ; and it is for the simple reason that there is a natural tendency to evil in us, that the virtuous opposing of it becomes a moral desert. From this it follows, on the one hand, that man, in virtue of his very nature, cannot avoid all evil, though indeed this unavoidable evil is not im- puted to him as guilt, and, on the other, that the essence of sin consists wholly and alone in the conscious choosing of it, and neither in the evil tendency preceding it, nor in the act pro- ceeding therefrom. By the carrying-out of an evil intention the guilt of that intention becomes not greater, and by the omitting of its carrying-out, not less. Moral merit and guilt lie consequently entirely and alone in the disposition ; actions themselves, per se considered, are morally indifferent. Hence he who does a bad act without a bad intention, does not sin. True, there is necessary also in order to the truly good not merely a well-meaning, but also a correctly-cognizing intention. Therefore it is that, while, because of the heathens' lack of a correct knowledge of the law and the truth, their unbelief and even their persecuting of the Christian martyrs cannot be im- puted to them as real sins, yet, on the other hand, they cannot without faith become really saved ; and the prayer of Christ on the cross for his persecutors shows that they did wrong in ignorance, and were in need of forgiveness. There are thoughts here in Abelard which, while per se true, are yet one-sidedly pushed into the extreme, and thereby become erroneous. Thus, he explains the distinction, prevalent in the ethics of the Middle Ages, between mortal and venial sins, to mean this, that under the latter we are to understand those the immorality of which is indeed known to us in general, but is not clearly conscious 206 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 34. and present to our mind at the moment of our consenting to them, and which are consequently committed rather in a state of forgetfulness. The ethics of Abelard was, not without rea- son, severely assailed by Bernard of Clairvaux, and is in many respects a fore-runner of the system of the Jesuits ; but in his own day the conscience of the church' was as yet somewhat quick and tender, and the synod of Sens (1140) expressly con- demned the more questionable features of the same. The subject of ethics was treated with great skill, but rather ingeniously than profoundly, by Peter Lombard (ob. 1160), more especially in the third book of his Libri sententiarum, a work which was for later schoolmen a very influential model and a high authority, though the relatively brief manner of treatment touches only upon the principal points. With a fully-developed system we are not as yet furnished ; it is rather a dialectical analysis and examination of ideas than a profound speculative development from a fundamental principle. The ethical notions are presented first in definitions, then proved and illustrated by texts from Scripture and from the Fathers, and thereupon fol- low dialectical inquiries, comparisons of opposed views, and a definitive judgment. The notion "good" has both an objective and a subjective significancy. The good as object is the goal of the subjective good, the good will ; this good object is blessedness, eternal life in God, and hence God himself in so far as he comes into communion with man (II, Dftt. 38, 40). The presupposition of all morally good is will-freedom. This freedom is primarily a threefold one : freedom from necessity, freedom from sin as a dominating power, and freedom from misery. The first is un- forfeitable, exists also in sinful man ; the second is enjoyed by the redeemed, the third by the saved. Before the fall man had perfect freedom, could, by his own strength, keep free from sin, though not attain to perfection save as aided by divine grace, as, on the other hand, he could in his own strength also turn to sin. Hence will-freedom is that capacity of the rational will whereby it, by the assistance of divine grace (gracia assist- ente), chooses the good, or, by not sharing in the same (eadcm de- sistente), the evil. In the rational will there is a natural striving, though but feeble (licet tenuiter el exiliter), to choose the good ; but, by the assistance of grace, it becomes powerful and effica- 34.] PETER LOMBARD. 207 cious (efficaciter), whereas man per se can effectually turn to evil. By the possibility of choice in the two directions, human liberty differs from divine liberty, which latter can eternally choose only the good. After the fall into sin, the truth : poterat peecare et not peccare, was changed into, potest peccare et non potest non peccare; that is, into a freedom very much tram- meled indeed, though not yet sunk to necessity ; the inwardly enfeebled and corrupted nature of man impels him constantly to sin, and allows him not to will and to accomplish the truly good. The redeemed, however, is free from this predominancy of evil desire, has indeed as yet moral weakness, but also the assistance of divine grace ; hence he can also yet sin, in fact it is still true of him : non posse non peccare, but only as to venial sins, not as to mortal sins. In his ultimate perfection, however, the redeemed attains to a condition transcending the condition of unfallen man, namely : non posse peccare, where all weakness is overcome, and man has risen to a moral impossibility of choosing evil; thus the threefold freedom becomes a fourfold one (II, Dist. 24, 25). Virtue is the right quality of the human will as turned toward the good. The ground-virtue is, therefore, love to Gorl, as the substance of all good ; and all virtues are closely involved in each other, so that he who truly possesses one, possesses them all, and he to whom one is lacking, lacks them all ; no one can have simply one virtue, for love is the mother of all the virtues, and he who has the mother has* also the children (III, Dist. 36). In agreement with Augustine, Peter Lombard presents three chief-virtues, which, however, are only different phases of the one love to God, namely : faith, hope, love (fides, spes, charitas). (1) FIDES est virtus, qua creduntur, qua non videntur, namely, in the sphere of the religious ; this faith is threefold : (a) credere DEO, to believe the word of God ; (&) credere DEUM, to believe in the existence of God ; both these forms of faith are possible to the evil ; (<) credere IN DETTM, to love God in faith, and to unite one's self with him ; this is true faith, which leads also to truly good works (III, Dist. 23). (2) SPES est virtus, qua, spiritualia et ceterna *bona sperantur, i. e., cum fiducia exspectantur. This virtue is only briefly and insufficiently developed, and is not clearly enough distinguished from the first; for the statement that hope refers only to future good, while faith refers also to 208 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 34. evil and to the past and to the present (III, Dist., 26), gives, after all, only the difference of a part from the whole. (3) CHAR- IT AS eat dilectio, qua diligitur deus propter se, et proximus prop- ter deum Tel in deo; God must be loved for his own sake, but our neighbor (and every human being is such) only for God's sake (III, Dist. 27 sqq.). From another point of view, and which is not properly brought into harmony with the first, but only joined to it four other virtues (virtutes principals vel cardinales) are adopted, after the example of Plato and Augus- tine, and presented, namely: just itia, fortitudo (which manifests itself in suffering), prudentia, and temperantia (III, 33) ; after which, without any further development of these four virtues, are given the seven gifts of the Holy Spirit (taken from Isa. xi, 2, 3, in the Vulgate version, namely : wisdom, understanding, counsel, strength, knowledge, piety, God-fearing), as the condi- tions of the practice of virtue, and as spiritual virtues. Some further discussion of special points is given in connection with a presentation of the ten commandments and of the sacraments. In the steps of Peter Lombard follows, in all essential points, Alexander Hales (ob. 1245), though he develops some points more fully, and contributes thereto original matter, especially is this the case in his discussion of the moral law, which he distinguishes into the natural, the Mosaic, and the evangelical (Summa univ. theol., pars III). He separates the moral part of theology more distinctly than had yet been done from the dog- matical, as the "doctrine of manners," and distributes it into the doctrine, first, of the divine law, second, of grace and the virtues, and, third, of the fruit of virtue. (William of Paris [ob. 1249] discussed the more important points of morality in separate treatises grounded on Augustine and Aristotle). More learned, and especially distinguished by extensive use of Aris- totle, are the ethical portions of the writings of Albertus Magnus (ob. 1280), though in other respects they do not con- tain very much original speculation, and in some respects they show already a strong casuistical tendency. It is through Thomas Aquinas that scholastic ethics was most highly perfected both in form and in substance, and raised to a system of profound speculation. His great work, Summa theologies, prima et secunda secunda, combines, in com- prehensive thoroughness, a clear intellectual insight with 34.] THOMAS AQUINAS. 209 deep religious knowledge and moral life experience. The style of presentation is indeed somewhat discursive, especially in the citing and refuting of opposite opinions, and runs often into unprofitable distinctions and splittings of ideas, but the substantial contents are in the main so sound and excellent, that the almost autocratical authority enjoyed by Thomas Aquinas, especially in the field of ethics (an authority which has maintained itself unabated in the Romish Church up to the present day) is essentially a well-merited one ; the later ethics of the Romish Church could indeed fall below this model, but it has not surpassed it ; and also for Protestant ethics have the works of this author been of great influence, and they are even yet of weighty import. The ethics of Thomas Aquinas, which is directly connected with his dogmatics, is distributed into a general and a special part, of which the former treats of the virtues and vices in general, and the latter of the same in detail, so that the whole is made to appear predominantly, though not exclu- sively, as the doctrine of virtue. Man is the image of God principally in virtue of his reason ; but an essential element of reason is the freedom of the will, namely, the free deter- mining of our own activity. All activity, and hence also that of irrational creatures, has an end ; hence human activ- ity must have a rational end, and one which man knows as such, and which is aimed at by free will-determination, whereas irrational creatures seek their end unconsciously and from natural instinct. But rational ends are such only in so far as they do not constitute a mere interminable plurality, but converge and terminate in one last and highest good, upon which consequently all rational activity is directed. This one highest end, and hence the highest good, which the rational creature seeks to attain to, cannot consist in outward, perishable, and hence unessential things, but only in the one absolutely imperishable, the divine, namely, in communion with God, and hence in the absolutely perfect life of the rational creature, in blessedness. God is the objective, bless- edness the subjective, phase of the highest good. The human soul per se, and without being united with God, cannot be happy ; hence the highest good is not a something belonging to the soul per se, has its ground not in the soul but in God; 210 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 34. the highest good in its objective phase, considered as an ob- ject, is not a created, but an uncreated and divine entity, which, however, is appropriated to himself by man. But this uncreated entity cannot be appropriated by sensuous perception, but solely through a spiritual grasping, through cognizing, through spiritual beholding or intuiting. Hence blessedness rests on an. intuiting of God, and toward this, therefore, the rational activity of the soul is directed. This blessedness, as resting on the highest activity of the reason, cannot be wholly reached in this earthly, manifoldly-limited and dependent life, and, moreover, as being of an unending nature, it cannot be merited by finite actions, it can only be appropriated by religious intuition, by contemplation, namely, in jthat God lovingly imparts himself, and therewith at the same time blessedness, to man. This appropriating is, how- ever, not a merely passive bearing, not a will-less beholding, but a willing, loving, and love-enjoying embracing of the divine. In that the rational striving attains to perfect satis- faction and rest in God as the highest good, blessedness is enjoyment, the feeling of delight; this is, however, but one of the phases of blessedness, the other is the visional cog- nizing. The will of man, ever directed toward a good, is indeed free, can be forced neither through an outward nor through an inward power to a given choice, nor is it so forced by God, for God leaves every created being to act according to its inborn nature ; and hence the will can direct itself as well to a false and merely seeming good, as to the true good, but this true good itself stands not within the free determination of man, but is absolutely determined by God and by the inner necessity of the case itself ; man can, freely-willing, strive for it or fail of it, but he cannot posit any other good than the true one. There is no other highest good than God. The will is good when it hearkens to the reason ; but the reason is truthful only when it hearkens to God and accepts illumination from him. Hence every action is evil which deviates from reason, and is evil also when this reason is in error (II, 1, 19) ; whatever does not spring from the conscience is sin ; but the will that follows an erring rea- son is also not good, but evil, in so far as the error was avoid- able. Hence only that action is truly good which follows, 34.] THOMAS AQUINAS. 211 not merely reason in general as fortuitously determined in this or that particular person, but true reason, which is con- scious of the divine will, and determines itself thereafter. The readiness of the soul for well-acting is virtue, which is consequently to be conceived of not as mere action, but as a permanent power and tendency for acting, as a habitus, as a power of the rational will. The virtues are primarily of a nat- ural character; that is, such as belong to man as such, to his natural rational being, and are developed by exercise and ha- bituation, although they cannot in themselves attain to perfec- tion (ii, 1, qu. 55-59, 63). They are distinguished as knowledge- virtues and moral virtues (comp. 17, 18) ; the former are wis- dom, science, understanding and, connected therewith, prudence, and, in a somewhat peculiar sense, also art-skill. The moral virtues relate to desire; they fall into four cardinal virtues (ii, 1, qu. 60. 61 ; ii, 2, 47 sqq). (1) Virtue considered as a good of the reason, and as expressing the essence of the same, is prudence ; this virtue is, as distinguished from wisdom, not the lord, but the servant of morality, gives not the end proper, but only the means to the end of the practical reason. (2) The virtue which expresses the practical will-direction of the reason toward moral actions, is justness or righteousness ; it re- lates to the realizing of the right, is the constant and fixed will to give to each his right, and hence has to do with what we owe to others. It is true, man can in a certain sense be just also toward himself, namely, when reason holds in proper con- trol the passions. Justness is the highest of the moral virtues, and includes in itself also piety, thankfulness, etc. (3) The vir- tue which expresses the practical will-direction of the reason toward the checking of all reason-resisting desires and passions, is temperateness. It holds within rational bounds all desires and pleasure-feelings which relate to sensuous goods, and all dis- pleasure-feelings which spring from the lack of such goods. Modifications of this virtue are shame, reverentiality, abstinence, gentleness, modesty, humility, etc. (4) The virtue which ex- presses the practical will-direction of the reason toward the car- rying-out of rational purposes as against opposing natural inclinations and affections, especially against fear in the face of dangers, is courage. It wards off whatever would hinder the ac- tivity of the reason, and thus preserves man, as against all 15 212 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. C 34 - sensuous and irrational impulses, within the limits of rational- ity ; it is, on the one hand, defensive, a firm calm enduring of hostile influences, and, on the other, offensive, in that it actually assaults the dangers ; the first phase, however, is, for Christian morality, the predominant. The highest stage of Christian courage is martyrdom, wherein the main element is love. The several chief virtues are subdivided by Thomas Aquinas in a very far-reaching and excessively detailed manner, into very nu- merous special manifestation-forms. Above all the moral virtues, stand (not as co-ordinate there- with, but as in fact exalting them into a Christian character) the theological virtues, that is, the supernatural ones those which have for their object the divine, the supernatural, and are not grounded in us by nature, but given (infusce) to us by God (ii, 1, 62 sqq.; ii, 2, 1-46); through these alone is per- fection possible to man, even in the other or moral virtues. (1) Faith; this virtae relates not to the finite, but to God, and has as its presupposition, divine revelation. It is'a think- ing with an inner assent of the will, and must manifest itself also outwardly in confession. The object of faith is, in part, purely supernatural, transcending our knowledge and reason, and in part it can be discovered even through natural reason ; but also that which is discoverable through reason has in fact been revealed by God out of love, and for purposes of culture. Faith is raised to a vital form only by the incre- ment of love (fides formata) ; without love it is crude (in- formis). As faith is the foundation of all morality, so is un- belief the greatest sin ; but as faith is a virtue, hence it is not allowable to bring a non-Christian to faith by force. The matter is, however, very different with heretics and apos- tates, for these have broken their vow, and hence fall under punishment ; heresy deserves capital punishment (ii, 2, 10, art. 8, 9) ; and when a prince falls from faith and in conse- quence thereof, incurs the ban of the Church, then are his subjects ipso facto free and absolved from his dominions and from their oath of fealty (ii, 2, 12, art. 2). (2) Hope has for its object eternal blessedness, that is, the subjective phase of the highest good ; it pre-supposes faith inasmuch as it is only by faith that eternal blessedness becomes known to us. With hope must be associated God-fearing, inasmuch as God 34.] THOMAS AQUINAS. m 213 is the executor of just punishments. (3) Love is the most perfect of the virtues, and its presupposition is faith and hope. It is an intimate union of man with God, a possessing of God, and the shaping-form of all the other virtues, inas- much as man is to do all good out of love to God ; it endures forever, whereas faith ultimately passes over into sight, and hope into the possession of blessedness. This love, which is primarily love to God, and as such is not in us by nature, but ia a divine grace-gift, enlarges itself spontaneously into love to men and to all creatures, as also into a love of man for him- self and for his own body as created by God. But all love to the created must spring exclusively from our love to God, and it cannot relate approvingly to the evil that is in crea- tures, but rathej seeks to eradicate it. Our enemies and bad men in general we are to love, not as bad, but as men, and for the sake of their rational nature. The degree of our love to creatures is to be in proportion to the union of the same with God. God himself is to be loved above all things, above even ourselves. This double classification of the virtues is doubtless the weakest side of the ethics of Thomas Aquinas and of the schoolmen in general. The theological and the natural vir- tues do not possibly admit of being brought into any clear relation to each other ; they are based upon two utterly foreign and heterogeneous stand-points, and can be reduced neither to a condition of co-ordinatiun nor of subordination, but on the contrary, they constantly cross and cramp each other, and lead, on the one hand, to many repetitions, and, on the other, to an arbitrary distribution of the special virtue-manifestations. That love, even love to the creature, should appear solely as a theological virtue, is entirely unnatural. The separating of faith from wisdom is no less erroneous, inasmuch as Chris- tian wisdom rests essentially on faith in God. The distinc- tion made between knowledge-virtues and moral virtues suf- fers not only under all the defects of its prototype in Aris- totle, but becomes more perplexed still by the distinguishing of both these classes from the theological virtues, inasmuch as a very essential part of that which Aristotle ascribes to wisdom must here be transferred to faith. And the matter is made still worse by the fact that the moral virtues are not 214 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 34. presented strictly according to Aristotle, but according to the four chief virtues of Plato, who does not find any place for special knowledge-virtues, so that while, now, wisdom does not, yet prudence does, appear as a moral cardinal viV- tue, whereas in fact prudence belongs unquestionably along with wisdom to the knowledge-virtues, as is the case in Aris- totle ( 17). The fact is, the entire Greek schema is totally inadequate for the expression of the Christian virtues, and the violence of the process is felt at every step of the attempt. Even the utterly untenable position of Aristotle, that virtue always lies in the middle between two opposite aberrations ( 17), is adopted by Thomas Aquinas, and applied even to the knowledge-virtues ; to the theological virtues he applies it only in this respect, that, in them, we are* to reach a defi- nite measure corresponding to our nature (ii, 1, 64), to say the least, a strange application of the middle-way of Aris- totle. On the virtues in general, Thomas Aquinas makes also the following observations, mostly in the spirit of Aristotle : every virtue is heightened in its power by exercise ; all of them stand in connection with each other, and when they ap- pear in their perfection, no one of them is without all the others. The virtues, according as they are viewed under dif- ferent aspects, are, as to worth, in part equal and in part un- equal ; the knowledge-virtues are per se nobler than the moral virtues, inasmuch as reason is nobler than desire ; but in re- spect to their activity, the moral virtues stand higher, as they are more fruitful in results. The perfect practice of virtue depends on the directly God-conferred seven gifts of the Spirit (ii, 1, 68), which make the person willing to follow the promptings of the Holy Spirit, a thought which occurs al- ready in Ambrose and in Gregory I. , but in respect to which, even the intellectual acumen of a Thomas Aquinas does not succeed in making clear the relation of these gifts to the cor- responding virtdes, especially the theological. The moral activity determines itself according to a law ; this law belongs to the sphere of reason. The eternal law is the universe-ruling divine reason, not the fortuitous reason of the individual. The laws of nature, and also those of the practical reason (ratio practica) are an efflux from the eternal 34.] THOMAS AQUINAS. 215 law, and the human laws of the state and of society are in turn an efflux from both. The laws which lie merely in the natural reason do not suffice for morality ; but there is needed, in order to the supernatural end of blessedness, also a positive divine law, which is made known and evidenced to all bv revelation, and which at the same time also preserves the natural consciousness from all doubt (ii, 1, 90 sgq). In the field of Christian morality the law proper, which is absolutely binding on all Christians, is to be distinguished from the counsels, which are left to free choice, though the following of them works a higher perfection and leads more speedily to the goal of salvation. The Old Testament law, as a law of servitude, had no such counsels ; but the Gospel as a law of freedom has them, in order to bring men rightly to a con- sciousness of their freedom. The clinging to the earthly hinders our arriving at the heavenly; hence the counsels hasten this arriving, in that they free man as far as possible from earthly enjoyments which are otherwise not forbidden to him; they therefore require poverty, perpetual chastity (that is, non-marriage), and the yoke of obedience (obedientice servitus), the latter very erroneously based on Matt, xix, 21 ("follow me,") and on John x, 27 (ii, 1, 108, art. 4; comp. ii, 2, 186). The Christian law as distinguished from the nat- ural law cannot be fulfilled by our own natural power, but only in virtue of the grace-gifts infused into the hearts of be- lievers ; and in so far man acquires for himself, by his virtue, no merit before God. Without grace no one can acquire the life of blessedness ; on the presupposition of grace, however, man can in fact acquire a merit before God, and thereby an increase of grace and of the love of God, and hence also a heightening of his blessedness (meritum condigni) (ii, 1, 114). Opposed to the morally-good stands evil; to the virtuous act, sin; and to virtue as a habit, vice (ii, 1, 71 sqq.); sin and vice are in contradiction to true reason, and hence in general to the essence or nature of man. In reference to the kind of pleasure felt or sought in sin, sins are divided into spiritual and fleshly sins. In reference to their guilt and punishable- ness, they are classed into venial and mortal (peccata venalia et mortalid) ; the former consist in the turning to the finite without a conscious and designed turning-away from God, 216 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 34 and they involve finite punishments, either here upon earth or in purgatory; mortal sins consist in a conscious and de- signed turning-away from, and hence in a conscious rebell- ing against, God and his will, are contrary to the order of love, and hence involve eternal punishment. The gravity of the guilt is measured by the importance of the object, by the motives, by the degree of consciousness and of freedom, and by the spiritual character and position of the subject in so- ciety. In reference to the positive or negative contents of the action, sins fall into sins of commission and of omission (peccata commissionis et omissi&nis). In reference to their man- ner of commission, sins are sins of the heart, of the mouth, and of act {peccata cardis, oris, operis). In sin there is to be distinguished a twofold consent of the rational will, namely, to the pleasure in the sin, and to the sinful deed itself, the latter being the more criminal. The causes of sin, as act, are in part direct, namely, erring cognition and volition the re- garding a seeming good as a real one, and the willing it, and, in part, indirect, namely, first, inner ones, such as im- agination, sensuousness, ignorance,, passion, and other al- ready committed sins; and, second, outward or tempting ones, such as evil spirits and bad men ; temptation, however, presupposes, in order to its effectualness, a sinful welcoming of it. God is not the cause of sin, though indeed, in virtue of his righteousness, He is the mediate cause of the conse- quences of sin, e. f themselves as conclusive proofs ; texts from the Scriptures fall rather into * Quastt. in Ubr. Sentent. ii, dist. 25, ed. Lugd., 1639, t. 6, p. 873 sqq. t Ibid. Hi, dist. 37, t. 7, p. 857. \ Ibid, ii, dist. 41. Ibid, iii, dist. 38, p. 917. | Ibid, iii, dist. 39, p. 980. 34.] SPIRIT OF SCHOLASTICISM. 219 the back-ground. Despite the undeniable acumen shown by the schoolmen in the development of processes of reason- ing, there is yet manifest also a lack of the courage to derive their philosophical systems purely and simply from the Chris- tian consciousness. Graeco-Roman ethics was in fact, to the schoolmen, not a merely preliminary and preparatory study, but it was with them of quite too determining an influence, also in respect to the subject-matter" of their science. They endeavor, indeed, with great earnestness to exalt extra-Chris- tian philosophy into the sphere of Christian thought; it proves, however, an element too mighty for them, and they do not wholly escape entangling the Christian consciousness in the heathen, and thus robbing it of its peculiarity. They felt indeed the antagonism, but did not overcome it, and the prevalent lifeless juxtaposing of the two elements shows only their embarrassment, but not their ability to dominate the foreign material. The almost universal resorting to certain favorite numbers in the division and classification of the subject-thatter, particularly to three and seven, and also to four and twelve, is indeed based on an obscure consciousness of an inner order of the spiritual life ; but this order does not come to a scientific consciousness, and the real reason for its observance is, after all, the typical significance of these num- bers as sacred. That there should be presented precisely seven beatitudes, seven (diversely-stated) mortal sins, etc., seems without inner ground ; and frequently this using of numbers sinks to jejune play, as, e. g., when a certain writer introduces every-where the number twelve, in the dividing of his subject, in assigning reasons, in citing objections, etc. The ethical subject-matter treated of by the schoolmen was subsequently wrought over in large, though but little system- etized summaries in connection with appropriate citations from the Fathers, and placed within reach of the wider cir- cles of the ecclesiastical world. To the period of Thomas Aquinas himself belongs the Summa of William Peraldus,* an essentially casuistical and pretty well digested appreciation of scholastic science ; after which we may mention the Spee- * Summa s. tractatus de mrtictibus et vitiis, from the fifteenth century, (without date or place of printing, then at Col. Agr., 1479 fol. ; Basle, 1497, 8vo.) often reprinted. 220 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 34. ulum morale, attributed to Vincent of Beauvais (ob. 1264), but originating in the fourteenth century ;* and also the much used and very complete and erudite Summa of Antony of Florence (ob. 1459). t John of Salisbury (ob. 1180, as Bishop of Chartres), who op- posed scholasticism proper with brilliant ability, but was rather empirical in regard to the source of knowledge, though in other respects of rich philosophical culture, undertook to give to the moral views of the Church a scientific expression ; in his efforts he based himself most largely on Gregory the Great. To be perfect is God's essence, to become perfect is the task of man as God's image ; man becomes perfect, and hence happy only by moral activity, which activity rests, on the one hand, on the knowledge of the truth, and, on the other, on love to God. Since the fall into sin man can know the truth only in virtue of divine revelation and illumination, and he can realize the good only by the assistance of divine grace. Because of the evil desire inborn in all men, there is no virtue without a constant struggle of our love tf> right- eousness, as strengthened by redemption, against our innate evil desires. Even as the essence and source of all sins is the natural desire as developed into pride and presumption (so that consequently all virtuous effort directs itself prima- rily against the pride of the heart), so the essence of all Chris- tian virtue is that humility which springs from love to God, and which seeks to lay aside all self-will and to give God the glory in all things. Hence the moral worth of actions lies not in the work, but in the disposition ; but from the right disposition there follows with moral necessity also the right work. Morality is not, however, a merely individual task, it finds its full truth only in the moral community-life, which comes to expression in the church and in the closely therewith-connected Christian state. The State has, as a real moral organism, also a moral task, namely, to execute righteousness according to the divine will, and not only to protect the morality of the people, but also to foster and guide it. Hence the law which governs the state is to be * Not in his Opp., 1431, but separately printed as a part of the great Speculum naturale, etc., 1473, and subsequently. t Summa, theol., 1477, 1476, 1480, 1496; 1740, 4 vols. 34.] JOHN OF SALISBURY. 221 an expression, not of human discretion, but only of the di- vine will, to which even the prince must absolutely subordin- ate himself ; hence it must rest on God's revealed Word, and the vicegerents of God, that is, the representatives of the religious community-life the Church, must be also the ani- mating soul of the Christian state ; for, in fact, in its moral task, the Christian state is identical with the church. God- fearing is the life-power of the Christian state, and this state must therefore above all things recognize and honor both the moral right of the church and also the priests as the higher and, so to speak, divine element in worldly society. The priests indeed should not and may not themselves guide and administer the state ; they are rather simply by their moral example, by doctrine, by exhortation, and by reproof, to in- fluence the same, but the princes to whom by divine ordi- nance the guidance of the state belongs, have received the sword only from the higher moral community, the church, in order to execute justice in the name of the Christian idea ; and so likewise stands the military order, knighthood, not merely in the service of the prince, but quite as fully, and in fact primarily, in the service of God, and hence of the church. A prince who breaks away from divine law, who rebels against the divine ordinances, and hence also against the church, has, as a tyrant, forfeited his moral right to the crown, and it is not merely legitimate to offer resistance to him, but also in any manner whatever, even by treachery or assassination, to get rid of him [Policraticus iv, 2]. The political doctrine of John of Salisbury is a Mediaeval Christian counterpart to Plato's doctrine of the state, with which he was not acquaint- ed, and is in fact an attempt to introduce Augustine's Civitas Dei into the worldly state.* The fondness of Schoolmen for proposing difficult contro- versial questions led them inevitably into the province of casuistry; and this science which had sustained itself along- side of scholasticism subsequently borrowed from scholastic science much congenial material, and in part also a scientific form. Hence at the decline of scholasticism in the fourteenth century, casuistry entered in fact upon its brightest days. * Especially in his Policraticus. (Reuter : Joh. v. S., 1842). Schaar- Bchmidt: Joh. Saresb., 1862. 222 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 34. The works entitled Summce casuum conscientice, were very much used in connection with confession and penance, and, as they generally contained also much matter relative to church law, also in ecclesiastical administration. In them we find a very imperfectly digested, and often merely alpha- betical, summary of specific single moral questions, which relate in the main to what is allowed or disallowed, and the decision of which is given less from general principles than on the basis of the utterances of the more highly esteemed Fathers. The questions are often not taken from -life at all, but are simply invented in order to exercise ingenuity, as in riddle-solving ; and in some of these works there is manifest- ed a peculiarly fond lingering over extremely impure sub- jects. In the presence of the too exclusively considered individual case, the general principles involved in it are often wholly lost sight of, and ethics is in danger of degen- erating into a sophistry of special-pleading, into a treating of the moral merely empirically and skeptically ; thus we find questions often extensively discussed, as doubtful, which cannot be in the least practically doubtful for the unsophis- ticated moral consciousness. The best known of these works are the Summce of Raymund of Pennaforti in the thirteenth century,* and of Astesanus in the fourteenth! (the Astesana, is cautious and judicious, contains also many general consid- erations, and is pretty systematic and comprehensive) ; Angelus of Clavasio in the fifteenth century J (the Angelica, perhaps the most extensively used ; alphabetical, with much worth- less matter, and often treating of indelicate questions) ; Syl- vester Prierias, General of the Dominicans, the well-known opponent of Luther, gave in his Summa moralis, generally called Summa summarum, an alphabetical compilation from others. (The Pisanella [1470 and often], revised by Nicolas of Ausmo, 1471, '73, '74, '75, '78; Galensis, 1475; Rosella, 1516; Pacifica, 1574. The BiUia aurea, 1475, '81, also in * Summa de casibue panitentice, Verona, 1744; upon this is based the work of John of Freiburg, Augsb., 1472, and frequently. t form, and differing equal- ly from scholasticism and from mysticism, are the moral views of Raymund de Sabunde (of Toulouse, about 1430).* Appropriating to himself the results of preceding theological and philosophical thought, he undertook, rather from the stand-point of experience, of the observation of nature, and of the common sense of mankind, to place these results with- in reach of the understanding of the masses. The freedom of the will as directed toward the good is the highest posses- sion of reason ; called to the highest place in the scale of created beings, man should, by free conduct, show himself worthy of this calling, should establish and preserve the harmony of the created. As man has received nothing from himself, but every thing from God alone, hence his first duty is thankful love to God who first loved him (tit. 96 sqq., 109 sqq.}; love to self becomes moral only through love to God. Other creatures give us good only in so far as God works through them, and hence our love to them must be subordi- nated to our love to God ; but out of this love to God follows also a love to that which He has created, and hence, first of all, to man as God's image ; hence the requirement to love one's neighbor as one's self (120 sqq). Through love to God, man constantly grows in God -likeness, for amor convertit amdntem in rem amatam (129 sqq.), though this is not to be taken in the sweeping sense of the Mystics. Evil consists in this, that we honor and love the creature not in God but for itself, and is consequently idolatry ; the root of all evil is this impious love to self, that is, it is self-seeking and self- will; the devil seeks nothing but himself. As in consequence of sin a general corruption of man's nature has been brought about, and as the power of sin over man is paralyzed only by redemption, hence Christian morality rests entirely on loving thankfulness to Christ, and involves a constant struggle against the remains of sin that still infect us. The evangelical tendency which during the time of the * Theologia naturalis, Solisb., 1852. Matzke : B. t>. S., 1846. 35.] PRE-REFORMERS. 231 universal domination of the Romish church had never entire- ly disappeared, and which, especially since the appearance of the Waldenses, had been growing more positive in its opposition to the corrupted church, directed its efforts from the very first against the anti-scriptural and arbitrary ordi- nances of said church, especially against the work -holiness of monastic morality, in order to vindicate the moral free- dom of the Christian personality, and also against the sophis- tical laxity of the more recent period ; this tendency insists above all upon faith-born love as the source and essence of all true morality, and rejects the notion of supererogatory merit as arising from the observance of the so-called evan- gelical counsels. So taught Wickliffe in his Trialogus, but rather as assailing than as positively building up ; all sin, he refers to a lack in true faith ; a correct knowledge of faith precludes sin ; true virtue is not possible without true faith ; a correct knowledge of faith precludes sin ; true virtue is not possible without true faith ; hence by a man's virtue one can judge of his faith. Wickliffe's over-rigid and almost de- terministic predestinarianism simply stands, unmediated, along-side of his moral views, and merely impedes their freer scope. Also Huss combats, in the ethical field, chiefly only against the errors of Romish dogmas and morals, without himself establishing any thing essentially new. Violent and keen, and generally, though not always, purely evangelical are also the assaults of Nicolas de Clamengis [Clemangis] in France ob. about 1440 against the corruption of the moral consciousness of the church).* John of Goch, of Malines (pb. 1475) assailed, from an Augustinian stand-point, the com- mingling of the evangelical with the Mosaic law, also the sys- tem of vows, and outward work-holiness in general ; faith as working by love is the essence of Christian freedom and moral- ity.f The influence of Savonarola in Florence lay more in his fiery zeal for pure evangelical morality than in fruits of scientific thought ; in his mode of thinking, the phase of the God-pos- sessed affections stands forth with most prominence ; a mysti- cal subjectiveness is combined with a fervent work-activity. J * De corrupto eccl. statu, and in briefer essays and letters, Opp. t 1613. t Ullmann : Bef&rmatoren vor d. Ref., 1841, i. JRudelbach: Sav., 1835; F. C. Meier, 1836. 232 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [35. If we leave out of view these teachers of the church who were forerunners of the Reformation, we find in general in the ecclesiastical ethics prevailing before the opening of this Refor- mation a threefold character : a casuistical, a scholastic, and a mystical one, corresponding to the three phases of the soul-life, namely, to the empirical understanding, to the speculative rea- son and to the loving heart. The mystical form of ethics is the pure antithesis to the casuistical ; the former rests on heart- union with God, the latter on the analyzing understanding ; the former, upon an inward ineffable vision, the latter, upon out- ward calculating observation ; the former strays at times into the borders of Pantheism, and hence has some points of con- tact with the cosmic theory of India ; the latter is rather in danger of repeating, in the Christian sphere, the Jewish ex- ternality and chicanery of Pharisaism and Talmudisin ; the former reduces all plurality, all heterogeneousness, to a homo- geneous unity, endangers the practically moral working-life in the world ; the latter dissolves the moral idea into an atom- istic plurality of single cases devoid of uniting bond ; mysti- cism turns itself away disdainfully from all objective reality even of the moral life ; casuistry threatens to bind up and to smother the moral in narrow legal forms ; mysticism turns away from the circumference toward the center, but does not return again from the center to the circumference ; casuistry proceeds and stumbles by a reverse course ; the former tends to a lightly- esteeming of the active life, the latter to a hypocritical and ex- ternal work-holiness. Speculative ethics, especially in Thomas Aquinas, stands higher than in either of the other two forms, but lacks too much in evangelical directness and simplicity; and because of its double dependence on Greek ethics, on the one hand, and on the evangelical church-creed, on the other, it has not only compromised its legitimate and essential freedom, but, at the same time, also its truth. Notwithstanding this, how- ever, it stands (especially in its highest perfection in Thomas Aquinas) far more closely to the evangelical consciousness than the later form of Roman Catholic ethics as presented by the zealous champion of the Romish church, the Jesuits. 36.] PROTESTANT ETHICS. 233 IIL THE EPOCH OP REFORM. SECTION XXXVI. The antagonism of the evangelical ground-thought to that of Romanism manifested itself also in ethics. In the evangelical or Protestant church the sinful corruption of the natural man was conceived much more deeply, and consequently the moral task of the Christian much more earnestly ; and, as a consequence of the impossibility of meriting salvation by our works, Christian virtue was conceived, in much greater freedom from self-seeking, as the simple fruit of faith ; and the notion of supererogatory works be- came impossible in view of the decided recognition, that the life even of the most holy always falls short of moral perfection. The Scriptural view excludes a very essential portion of Romish ethics from that of the evangelical church.* The semi-Pelagian enfeebling of the effects of sin that pre- vailed in the Romish church, deprived ethics of its proper deep-reaching foundation. The more deeply the moral corrup- tion of man is conceived of, so much the greater becomes also the significancy of redemption, and likewise also of the moral struggle of the regenerated Christian against sin. Hence the, at first thought, surprising phenomenon that the rigid predes- tinarianism of Calvin did not lead to a decline in moral effort, but on the contrary to a very vigorous moral life. In the deep earnestness- of their conception of the moral task, both evan- gelical churches, the Lutheran and the Reformed, stand alike. The Holy Scriptures are the sole fountain of Christian ethics, just as, living faith in Christ as the sole cause of salvation, is * Comp. H. Merz : System der christl. Sittenlehre in seiner Gestaltung nach den Orundsetzen des Protestantismus im Gegensatze zum KatJioUcis- mtw, Tub., 1841, ingenious, but prepossessed by speculative theories, arid doing inj ustice to both sides. 234 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 36. also the subjective ground and the living fountain of morality. All blessedness is imparted to us without our meriting it, and solely of grace ; but good works, as the necessary effects of true faith, are the certain verification of the same. The moral law is not. as in the Romish church, predominantly objective, but is of a strictly inward character. No one can do more than what God requires of him, for man is called to perfection ; all that is truly good is a requirement of the divine law and not of any mere counsels, which, without the forfeiture of a God- pleasing life, might in so far be left undone, all the good that we can do, we are also under obligation to do. The so-called counsels of the Romish church are rather a hindering than a furthering of the good, for they stand in the way of active love, and nourish the delusion of personal merit. Monastic vows are not consistent with vital faith. As man is saved only in virtue of redemption through Christ, hence his salvation rests solely on the worthiness of Christ, and not on personal merit ; all true virtue must be simply a fruit of faith, and hence of an already- acquired divine sonship, and consequently, though it may verify this sonship, it cannot first acquire or heighten it. Evangelical ethics is therefore apparently much less compre- hensive in its subject-matter than that of the Romish church, treats a not inconsiderable portion of the latter merely con- demnatorily, as, e. g., the entire subject of asceticism, and of opera supererogatoria as fulfilling the counsels; on the other hand, however, it has a deeper ground and a higher earnest- ness. Romish asceticism simply hides from view the inner lack of a truly evangelically moral depth. He who has under- stood the entire and profound earnestness of the moral life-task, and is conscious, how far the reality still falls below the moral prototype, can never come upon the thought of attempting, in addition to the moral task proposed to us by God, to per- form still other additional works, in order to attain to a still higher degree of sanctity. All these self-imposed works are really an implication that God placed the moral goal of man too low, and that He is thankfully pleased to accept the voluntary and non-owed over-payment of those who feel them- selves superior to the ordinary assessment. 37.] LUTHER. 235 SECTION XXXVII. The Reformers themselves treat the moral con- tents of the Christian consciousness for the most part only practically ; Melanchthon develops in his Loci merely the ground-thoughts, though he also attempts, on the basis of Aristotle, a philosophical establishing of the foundations of ethics ; Calvin gives only brief outlines, independently of the earlier scholastic method. The antithesis of the two evangelical churches manifested itself also in wide-reaching dif- ferences of ethical views. As an independent theo- logical science, ethics was somewhat earlier treated in the Reformed than in the Lutheran church. In the latter, it was at first either combined, in its mere ground-principles, with dogmatics, or treated merely practically and popularly ; G. Calixtus, however, treated it as a science distinctly separate from dog- matics, though only in its scanty beginnings. From this time forward it was frequently treated independ- ently, though for the most part, even as late as into the eighteenth century, only as casuistry; and Pietism, which embraced so earnestly the ethical contents of Christianity, although with some formal narrowness, prepared the way for a profounder scientific treat- ment of ethics. Luther himself, who embraced the evangelical ground-truths so clearly and distinctly, was not called by the general scope of his activity to the preparing of a system of scientific ethics proper. His warfare against Romish work-holiness, and against the formal, subtle and freedom-hampering casuistry of the Ro- manists, must have awakened in him a certain disinclination to a rigidly-scientific development of ethics, and an anxiety lest such a work might sink the free moral activity of the Christian 236 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [37. from the sphere of faith-communion with Christ into unfree and juridical forms. He expressed it repeatedly, that the true believer needs no law at all, because faith itself is both law and power, and spontaneously works the God-pleasing out of free love without being hampered by an objective law. As the apple-tree bears its fruit not in virtue of a law given to it, but out of its own proper nature, so are all Christians so tempered by faith that they spontaneously do well and righteously better than all laws could teach them to do. Even as the tree must exist antecedently to its fruit, and as the fruit does not make a tree good or bad, but the tree makes the fruit, so must man be good or bad before he does good or bad works. The Christian's love is to be an outward-gushing love, flowing from within out of the heart, out of his own little fountain ; the spring and the stream are themselves to be good, are not to derive their waters from without. Christ was a Redeemer, not a Lawgiver, and the Gospel is not to be turned into a book of laws. With such views, so directly antagonistic to the common Romish teach- ing, if we except the Mystics, it was natural that a rigidly- drawn-up system of ethics might seem a hampering to faith- born freedom, might seem like an adulterating of the teachings of the Gospel with the doctrine of the law. This period of agitated contest was therefore little adapted to the scientific development of a system of ethics ; this science was in fact the fruit of the evangelical life as having come to inner peace and stability, and as grown ripe through long experience in faith. Of the chief Reformers, only Melanchthon, who was of solid classic culture, and who gave proof, at the time of his scientific maturity, both of decided fondness for, and of a thorough un- derstanding of, Aristotle, indicated, in his theological writings not only the ground- thoughts of 'evangelical ethics, but gave even the outlines of a system of philosophical ethics. Besides his valuable comments on the Ethics and Politics of Aristotle,* he wrote, on -the basis of Aristotelian principles, Philosophies * InEthica Arist. comment., 1529, treating only the 1st and 2d books ; in 1532 were added the 3d and 5th ; re-written in 1545 as Enarratio aliquot tibrorum Efh. Ar., etc., in the Corpus Reformatorum of Bret- schneider and Bindseil, t. xvi, p. 277-41 H. Comment, in aliquot polU- icos Ubros Aristot., 1530, in Corp. Ref., ib., p. 417 sqq. 37.J MELANCHTHON. 237 moralis epitome, 1538.* In this work Melanchthon keeps phil- osophical ethics and the Christian knowledge of the moral strictly separate. The former is capable of comprehending and presenting only a part of the divine law ; it gives only the nat- ural law ; but this is also a true divine law, which is implanted in human reason ; and the philosophical knowledge of the same is a legitimate requirement and is an education toward the higher truth, as also the true foundation of all civil legislation, and is consequently by no means to be despised ; moral reason is the mirror from which the wisdom of God is reflected forth [Corp. Be/., pp. 21-27 ; comp. 277]. The method of the work follows the plan of the ethics of Aristotle, but presents far more solid principles. Man is the image of God, and his goal is the true development and manifestation of this image. Hence the end of man is to know and to recognize God, his prototype, and to manifest, in and through himself, the glory of God, by willing and complete obedience [28 sqq~\. Of the virtues that fall within the scope of philosophical ethics, righteousness or justness takes first rank, and this virtue is pretty fully discussed [63 sqq.~], especially in its civic significancy ; more briefly are treated the virtues of truthfulness, beneficence, thankfulness, and friendship. His philosophical ethics appeared, in 1550, entirely re-written and more independent of Aristotle, as Ethicm doctrines elementa et enarratio libri quinti Ethicorum, and afterward in 1554, '57, '60, and frequently after Melanchthon's death. f This excellent work, though not comprehensive, shorter even than the previous work, and presenting only the general bases of the moral, and examining more fully only certain special and, in part, civic questions, is written in a clear, concise, and beauti- ful style, and is a worthy commencement toward a system of evangelical and, in fact, essentially philosophical ethics, since the seventeenth century undeservedly laid aside, and also in more recent times almost forgotten. A knowledge of the vir- tues is necessary, because it shows that God is ; for the eternal and immutable distinction of the moral and the immoral in our reason cannot be fortuitous, but must proceed from the eternal, prescribing reason itself; it shows also how God is, namely, * Corp. Ref., xvi, pp. 21-164. The following editions, 1539, '40, are largely changed ; three later ones, 1542-'46, are like that of 1540. t Corp. Ref., xvi, pp. 165-276 ; not printed in the earlier Opp. 238 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 37. wise, free, truthful, just, beneficent, merciful, etc. ; it is a witness of God's justly retributing judgments, and is a life-norm for men in outward (not spiritual) actions and in discipline. Nat- ural reason, however, can discover neither the ground of the enfeehleinent which has resulted from sin, nor the means of sal- vation therefrom ; hence philosophy, without the Gospel, does not suffice [Corp. Ref., 165-167]. Moral philosophy is the sci- entific presentation of the moral law of nature in the sphere of external morals and discipline, and is, in this field, in harmony with the Decalogue, and in so far also with the Gospel ; for the moral law is the eternal and immutable wisdom and measure of the justice of God, obligating all rational creatures, and con- demning those who come into conflict with it ; but the Gospel preaches repentance, and promises forgiveness of sins on the ground of redemption by grace. Now, though moral philoso- phy knows nothing of this promise, yet, as being a part of the law, it also, on its part, leads toward the Gospel, and is there- fore not to be despised [C. JR., 167-170]. Ethics inquires first of all after the goal of the moral course. This goal or end is God himself, who lovingly communicates himself to us, and hence the true knowledge and reverencing of God. God created man unto his image, hence He wills that He should himself be manifested in and through man, namely, in that man becomes morally like unto Him ; only in a derived sense can it be said that virtue is the end of man, as the highest good. The good is that which harmonizes with the God-set goal ; hence evil is a disturbing of the divine plan ; and evil is primarily a malum culpee, in pure antagonism to the divine will, and then, second- arily, a malum poence, which by the divine, righteous will is madeT to follow upon the guilty malum culpce; God is in no sense whatever the author or accomplice of sin, to affirm this would be blasphemy, though He is indeed the author of the punishment [C. R., 170-183].' Virtue, as an acquired tendency to obey right reason, is conditioned on the fact that, on the one hand, reason guides the will by a right judgment, and that on the other the will freely, persistently and firmly lays hold upon this judgment, and has pleasure in so doing. A knowledge of the law and a free-will are the characteristics of the divine image as created in man by divine love; virtue is the moral realization of this image, is thankful, answering love for re- 37.] MELA1STCHTHON. 239 ceivecl love. In reason, as darkened by sin, this knowledge and freedom are indeed enfeebled, but not annihilated, and there remained in man a moral consciousness of right and wrong, and some degree of freedom to act conformably to this conscious- ness. Hence, the will is then truly good when it corresponds to the moral consciousness in so far as this consciousness har- monizes with the divine will. Hence virtue more definitely stated is the tendency of the will constantly to hearken to the moral consciousness for God's sake and out of thankfulness toward him [183 sqq\. The thought of the moral freedom of the will is, now, thoroughly, carefully, and very emphatically developed by Melanchthon, and an attempt made to establish it by Scripture (in harmony with Loci, iv, edition of 1559). Man as man, and hence even unredeemed man, has in the moral sphere a free discretion to prefer morality to crime, to perform outward moral works and to preserve discipline, and it is God's will that such discipline and order be freely preserved not merely from fear, but also for conscience' sake. Indeed, genuine God-fearing, right trust and right love to God, steadfastness in confession, and hence, in fact, all the truly God-pleasing spiritual virtues, are impossible without the assistance of the Holy Spirit ; in this assistance, however, man is not purely inactive like a statue, but reason must attentively lay hold on the Word of God, and the will must not resist, but must yield to the gracious workings of the Holy Spirit, and aspire after divine support. Absolute predestination and Stoic fatality are equally to be rejected. The passions by which Melanchthon understands both the impulses of feeling and the desires are not to be sup- pressed as irrational, as the Stoics teach, but are to be taken into the service of the moral reason, and those that have become evil by sin are to be resisted [201-207]. The distribution of the virtues is best made according to the Decalogue. But the commands of the first table cannot be adequately known in a purely philosophical manner; nevertheless, some points may be made. Every effect is dependent on its cause, and must remain in harmony therewith ; man is an effect of God, consequently he ought to remain in harmony with God, and not break off the bond that unites him with God. Moreover, as the image of God, man has the duty of remaining in likeness and harmony with God [214, 215]. In the commandments of the second 240 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 37. table appears, first, the virtue of justness, and in fact primarily in a general character, in the relation of those who guide and those who are guided, in which relation obedience to parents and to the magistracy, and piety in general, appear as a moral law of nature. Justness in its special form that which gives to every one his dues appears in the three following command- ments, which require the preserving of every one in his rights, in respect to life, to wedlock-fidelity and to property. The second chief virtue, as expressed in the eighth commandment, is truthfulness, which is a necessary requirement of the rational nature of man ; for in fact reason consists essentially in a knowl- edge of the truth, and consequently it also requires the truth. The two last commandments enjoin temperateness, but they are not developed in detail. To these three chief virtues the others are joined as branches, namely, steadfastness to truthfulness, and thankfulness, beneficence, diligence, etc., to justness, espe- cially justness toward God [215-222]. In his second book, Melanchthon gives a development of the virtue of justness in detail, with the omission of the other virtues. Justness, of righteousness in the evangelical sense the virtue which acquires for man eternal salvation cannot be attained to by mere human effort because of the prevalence of sin, but is imparted to man by grace in virtue of redemption; in moral philosophy the question is therefore only as to the justness which consists in the outward fulfilling of positive laws. This justness is, in part, of a general character, consisting in obedience to law both human and divine [as in Rom. ii, 13; Psa. cxix, 121], and in part of a special character; the latter is, in its turn, of a dis- tributive and of an exchanging character ; as distributive it relates to social order, as well to social superordination and subordination as to the calling of the proper persons to par- ticular offices, and to rewarding and punishing, and hence, in general, to the upholding of proper discipline, as exchang- ing it relates to the moral intercourse and commerce of men among each other as equals. The practice of justness, and hence also obedience toward those holding oflice and author- ity, takes place not merely in virtue of human laws, but also in the fulfilling of the divine will ; the proper human ordi- nances of society are God's ordinances. A violation of the law of nature, and hence also disobedience toward the legit- 37.] MELANCHTHON'S LOCI. 241 imate ordinances of civil authority, is consequently not merely a civil misdemeanor, but also a sin against God, a mortal sin. The ordinances of the natural law are in part unconditional, and hence divine and perpetually-valid commands, such as obedience toward God, parental duties, the virtue of truth- fulness ; and, in part, only conditionally-valid, such as the keeping of peace and the communistic use of property ; the latter feature, in fact, would be obligatory only on condition that mankind were not corrupted by sin ; in consequence of sin, however, the forcible protection and distinct separation of property become necessary [223-234] . The guilt of trans- gressions of the law is different according as the person does or does not act with a clear consciousness of the law and of the deed ; guiltily-incurred error excuses not the deed, but rather heightens the guilt, inasmuch as it is our duty to seek after the truth. Also violent passions do not make the un- lawful action an involuntary one, for man may and ought to control his passions [237-240]. Hereupon, and apropos to the assumption of power on the part of the Pope over sec- ular governments, Melanchthon treats of the nature of, and the difference between, the spiritual and the temporal pow- ers, in essential agreement with what he had said in his Loci [20, 21] ; this is followed by disquisitions on questions of civil right, on taxes and contracts. In his Loci Melanchthon gives the general bases of the moral consciousness in strictly Biblical form [Loci 3-6; 8-11]. The Old Testament law is not identical with the eternal moral law, but contains besides this law (which is indeed not fully included in the Decalogue, but only indicated in its chief features) also the ceremonial and the civil law, both of which had validity only until the advent of Christianity. The moral law is the immediate and pure expression of the divine wisdom and just- ness themselves, and hence was not first given by Moses, but was always valid from the very beginning. Melanchthon's some- what extensive examination of the several divine laws in the order of the Decalogue, may serve in many respects to comple- ment his philosophical ethics. He writes, here, free from the cramping fetters of the long-observed schemata, and reckons among the " works " of the first commandment : a proper knowl- edge of God, God-fearing, faith, love, hope, patience, and hu- 242 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 37. mility. The Romish doctrine of the counsels he refutes and rejects. The distinction between mortal and venial sins he indeed retains, but he conceives it much more deeply, under- standing under the latter such sins as are committed by Chris- tians without evil intention and with inner resistance to the evil, and are followed by honest repentance, and under the latter those which are committed premeditatedly and against con- science [Loc., 11]. In addition to this, Melanchthon examines in special treaties and letters many particular, and especially practico-moral, questions,* in a very judicious manner. In his scientific conception of the ethical task, Melanchthon furnishes an essential complement to that of Luther, who fixed his attention simply on the fact of the moral life of the regener- ated as such, without shaping the development of this fact out of the inner heart of the Christian life, into an ethical science. Melanchthon himself, however, did not complete this task, but simply began it ; and although we find in him frequently a slight over-estimation of Aristotle, still we perceive in the vigorous manner in which, in his last ethical writings, he breaks loose from all cramping and foreign forms and thoughts, and lays an entirely new, purely Christian foundation, how clearly he com- prehended his task, the carrying-out of which was delayed by the soon-following inner struggles of the evangelical church ; only a few writers Chytrwus, Victorin Strigel and Nicholas Hemming followed, in, as yet, feeble attempts, upon the path marked out by Melanchthon.f The rigid predestinarianism of Calvin seems at first thought still more unfavorable for the development of ethics than the stand-point of Luther ; in reality, however, the Reformed church developed an independent system of ethics earlier than the Lutheran. The juridically-dialectic ground-character of the Calvinistic world-conception necessarily led sooner than the more mystically-inclined subjective Lutheran view, to a rigor- ous development of the practical phase of religion. In his In- stitutio [iii, 6-10] Calvin gives a short, plainly- biblical pres- entation of the bases of Christian morality, which, of course, can be actually practiced only by the predestinated, but which * De conjugio ; quaestiones aliquot ethic(e,dejuramentis, etc., 1552; in Corp. lief., xvi, 453 sqq. Consilia 8. judicia theol., ed. Pezellii. 1(360. t J. C. E. Schwarz in Stud. u. Krit., 1853 ; Pelt., ib., 1848. 37.] CALVIN'S ETHICS. 243 is however for them, as being called to purity, an unconditional duty. That virtue cannot actually obtain for us salvation communion with God but is simply the necessary fruit of the salvation already obtained by grace, and the constant bond of this communion as established by grace, Calvin affirms very definitely. Therein, precisely, consists, in his view, the essential superiority of Christian to philosophical ethics, namely, that the former gives much deeper-reaching motives for the good than the latter, to wit, thankful love in return for God's love as re- vealed in redemption, and confiding love to the Redeemer, in whom we have at the same time the perfect personal pattern of the moral life. Out of this love to God in Christ flows a love of justness or righteousness (in the Biblical sense of the word) as the basis of the entire religious life. But the essence of Christian righteousness consists in perfect self-denial, that is, in the renunciation of all self-will and self-reason as opposed to God, in an unreserved surrender to God and his will ; it draws us away from love to the world, but must not sink into self- mortification and false asceticism. Man must not, by arbitrary non- Scriptural ordinances, impose upon himself a yoke. The moral life manifests itself [according to Titus ii, 12] in three chief virtues : soberness, righteousness and piety*; to the .first (sobrietas), which relates to the subject himself, belong also chastity, temperateness and the enduring of privation; the second relates to other men, and gives to each his dues ; the third separates us from the impurity of the world and unites us with God. Calvin gives expression, on the whole, also in his other numerous moral essays, especially in his exegetical writings, to a moral view which is no less earnest than sound, and generally keeps clear of all un-Biblical austerity. To the Romish seeking of holiness by abnegation, he opposes the thought, that the goods of this world are designed not merely for our absolute wants, but also for our moral delight; their enjoyment is not forbidden, but it should be made to contribute to the glory of God. The strict church discipline established and exercised by Calvin was indeed an offense to a gainsaying world, but was morally perfectly justifiable. His unevangelical view of the right of capital punishment against heretics, belongs less to the sphere of ethics proper than to that of civil right. In all essential points the ethical systems of the Reformed 17 244 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 37. and of the Lutheran churches are in harmony; there is manifest throughout, however, a general characterizing difference in the coloring given to the otherwise essentially harmonizing forms ; this difference we cannot here follow into its finer shades;* a few of the more general traits will suffice. The ethics of the Lutheran church bears predominantly an anthropologico-sub- jective character, that of the Reformed a theologico-objective character ; the former proceeds from the inner life-source of the regenerated heart, and constructs, therefore, only hesitatingly an ethical system proper, as, in some degree, superfluous; the latter sets out from the unconditional will of God to man, and hence felt much earlier the need of a scientific expression of the moral law, objective to the consciousness; the former wears rather a Paulino-free stamp, the latter rather an Old Testament stamp ; in the Reformed church sermons on morals have a much more prominent place than in the Lutheran. Lutheran ethics expresses, also in its christology, the transfiguration of the hu- man through indwelling grace, Reformed ethics, rather the glorifying of God in and through the elect. With both, the goal of morality is the glory of God, in the Lutheran church, however, more through the witness of the salvation-experience of the redeemed, in the Reformed, more through the offering of willing obedience under the law ; in the former predominates rather the manifestation of the filial relation, in the latter, rather that of submissive service ; in the former there is greater freedom in the self-determination of the believing subject, even to the danger of Antinoniianism, in the latter greater rigor of outward discipline, incurring danger of Puritanic rigorism and pedantic externality. The moral life of the Lutheran church bears, so to speak, a lyric character, that of the Reformed a practice-juridical one; hence the former expressed itself, natu- rally enough, in the sublimest soaring of church hymnology, the latter crystallized itself into a sharply-defined and regular church discipline; in the former predominates the mystical heart-element of union with God, in the latter predominates a rational contrasting of God and man. In the former all that is natural is ethically exalted and taken into the service of the * Comp. Schneckenburger: Vergleichende Darstellung des luth. u. ref. Lehrbegriffs, 1855; Tholuck: Das Hrchl Leben des 17 Jahrh., i, 199 sqq., 218 sqq., 301 sqq. ; ii, 140 sqq., 239 sqq. 37.] LUTHERAN TEBSUS REFORMED. 245 holy ; whereas, in the latter, the spiritual is exalted by being divested of the natural. The morality of the Lutheran church develops itself rather from the fullness of inner life toward knowledge, that of the Reformed rather from knowl- edge toward life-fullness ; the former is more immediate, natural and unconscious, the latter is more mediate, calcu- lating, doctrinary ; the former is directed more inwardly, the latter more outwardly ; the former is more an outgush out of the deep and overflowing feeling of love and bliss, the latter, more an intentional act of the earnest but calm will, as also, in the Lutheran view of salvation, the attention is fixed more upon the all-embracing love of God, and in the Reformed more upon the decrees of the will of God ; Mary and Martha are types of the respective ethical tendencies. The Lutheran Christian does good works because he is certain of his salva- tion through faith ; the Reformed does them in order that he may become certain of his saving faith, and hence of his election, good works are to him necessary unto salvation, though not its cause. The Lutheran needs the law and its discipline, strictly speaking, only in so far as he has as yet in himself sinful elements which need to be taken into disci- pline ; but to the Reformed, the law is a real and necessary guide for the regenerated heart itself. Hence, to the Re- formed, the Gospel wears essentially also the character of law in the Old Testament sense, and the Old Testament law is taken literally as yet binding, hence the rigid observance of the Sabbath and the prohibition of statues and pictures. In the Lutheran catechism the ten commandments precede the confession of faith ; in most of the Reformed churches they stand after the same, and constitute, in the French and English service, an essential part of the liturgy. This seem- ingly insignificant circumstance is in fact very significant ; in the Lutheran view the law has essentially the purpose of edu- cating toward the true freedom of the children of God, which freedom itself, when once attained to, has no longer any need of an outward law; in the Reformed view the law is an essential part of the Christian faith-life itself, but an objec- tive, purely-divine element still external to the regenerated subject. The Lutheran is fearful rather of work-holiness, the Reformed rather of non-conformity to the law ; the former 246 CHEISTIAN ETHICS. [ 37. has the law rather as his inward personal property, the latter rather as a categorical imperative external to his own sub- jective will. To the Lutheran, Moses and Christ stand in sharp contrast to each other ; to the Reformed they are most intimately united; "one must live as if there were no Gospel, and die as if there were no law," says, very significantly, the Reformed divine Baile (Praxis pietatis, 1635). To the Lu- theran, Christ is, in ethical respects, rather the beloved Saviour, out of love to whom and in communion with whom he lives in holiness ; to the Reformed he is more the moral pattern by which man is constantly learning, and which he endeavors to imitate. Hence Lutheran ethics appears predominantly as the doctrine of virtue and of goods, Re- formed ethics as the doctrine of the law. The Lutheran Christian conceives the good essentially as the morally-feaw- tiful, and hence he has also appreciation and love for the beautiful in general, gives expression to art, and makes it even a moral agency ; the Reformed conceives the good essen- tially as the right, and hence he has little taste or love for art as a moral power, but all the higher an appreciation for the legally-disciplined development of the church and of moral society ; to the former the highest virtue is believing love ; to the latter, righteousness. The moral consciousness of the Lutheran conceives the highest good rather as a power directly given by grace and reflecting from itself the moral life; the Reformed consciousness makes the moral life an essential factor in the obtaining of the highest good. Hence, in the ethical sphere, the antithesis of the Lutheran doctrine to the Romish is more violent than that of the Reformed ; hence also the Reformed church, but not the Lutheran, de- veloped a theocratical form of the church, and placed in general much greater emphasis on the legal and govern- mental development of the purely moral community of the church as in contrast to the state, and as a determining power for and over the same, whereas the subjective inward- liness of Lutheran Christians manifested little interest for such development. Such are the differences which, while they indeed manifest a general ethical antithesis of the two forms of doctrine, yet in fact constitute only two correspond- ing and manifoldly-complementing, but not rnutually-ex- 37.] DANAEUS, ETC. 247 eluding phases of the same unitary evangelical conscious- ness. The theological ethics of the evangelical church was treated as a separate science,* first by the learned Reformed divine Dancem (Daneau, ob. 1596) in his Ethica Christiana (1577, '79, '88 and 1601), in a rigidly Calrtnistic sense, with a large using of Augustine, Aristotle, and the Schoolmen, in strong opposition, however, sometimes to the two latter sources, resulting in a learned and thoughtful work, though as yet somewhat immature. He endeavors especially to solve the apparent contradiction between the doctrine of predesti- nation and the requirements of the moral consciousness, though not with very happy results; the special treatment of duties he bases on the Decalogue ; in respect to Church-dis- cipline he requires the greatest rigor, for heretics, capital punishment. (In connection with this ethics stands his Politico, Christiana, 1596-1606). The antithesis which Danaeus makes between Christian ethics and Aristotelian philosophi- cal ethics, was rejected by JZeckermann (ob. 1609 in Heidel- berg), who considered ethics as essentially a philosophical science, and Aristotle as its true founder ; t while the severely Puritanical Amesius (in Holland, ob. 1634) emphasized again very strongly the distinction of Christian from philosophical ethics, placing Christian ethics along-side of dogmatics, f (The distinguishing pf ethics and dogmatics as the two parts of the body of Christian doctrine, appears also in the Re- formed divine, Polanus of Basle. ) Walceus (in Holland, ob. 1639) attempted in his compendium of the ethics of Aristotle (1620) to imbue this work with a Christian spirit. More im- portant, despite its rather popular style, is the peculiar work of the moderate Calvinist Amyraud (Amyraldus, at Saumur, ob. 1664). I He distributes ethics historically, into the ethics of the pure unfallen state, into that of heathenism, and of * On the history of the earlier Reformed ethics, see Schweizer in Stud. u. Krit., 1850. t Systema etMcce, in his Opp., 1614. J Medulla theolagia, 1630, and frequently, a brief compendium; De conscientice et ej.jure vel casibvs, 1630, and subsequently, casuistical. Syntagma theol., 1610. J La morale chrestienne, 1652 sqq., 6 1., rare in Germany ; see Staudlin v, 404 qq.; Schweizer in Stud. u. Krit., 1683. 248 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [37. Judaism and of Christianity ; the first part contains the gen- eral philosophical considerations. The historical treatment of the subject gives a just appreciation also of heathen ethics, -without intermingling Christian ethics therewith. The ethics of the Reformed church was casuistically treated by the Puritan Perkins (of Cambridge, 1611), also by the above-mentioned Amesius, and by the German Alsted (1621, 1630), who distributed the subject-matter according to the chief heads of the Catechism. A.lsoJForbesius d Corse treated the subject in the order of the Decalogue, in his learned though quite practically-written work on moral theology, considered as the special doctrine of duties.* Ethics was treated in a popular, edifying manner by La Placette, Pictet, Basnage, and by the Englishman Richard Baxter. The sci- entific and purely theological form of Reformed ethics was still further developed, in the eighteenth century, by Hoorn- beek (1663), by Peter of Mastricht (1699), who follows Ame- sius, by Heidegger (1711), by Lampe (1727), and by others. In the middle of the eighteenth century the rigid form of Calvinistic ethics begins to give way, and the influence of the philosophy of Wolf commences to break down the confes- sional antithesis in the field of morals. In the Lutheran church there was at first but little done beyond the already-mentioned further developments of the philosophical ethics of Melanchthon, with the exception of a single, though not purely theological, attempt of the Me- lanchthonian Hamburger, Von Eitzen;\ theology is so in- volved in dogmatical controversies as to have in general but little inclination toward a scientific development of ethics ; it treated the weightier and more general questions only briefly, in dogmatics, in connection with the doctrines of free-will, of sin, of the law, and of sanctification, leaving the more detailed treatment of the subject rather for such practical writers as worked toward the Christian edification of the masses, writers who were in some respects related to the Mystics, and among whom two deserve especial attention. The first of these, John Valentine Andreas, of Wurtemberg (ob. 1654), is a very morally-earnest spirit, thoroughly do- voted to practical Christianity, of slightly mystical tenden- * Opp., Amst., 1703. t Comp. Pelt in Stud. u. Krit., 1848. 37.] ANDREAE AARNDT. 249 cies, of thorough scientific culture, and of deep acquaintance with human nature. Strongly impressed with the Calvinistic church discipline in Geneva, Andreae devoted his unwearying efforts to the bringing about of moral discipline also in the German church, though he found a rather unreceptive age, and was much deceived in his, at times, somewhat idealistic hopes. His numerous moral writings, often clothed in poet- ical and especially allegorical forms, and sometimes satirical, though always hiding, even in hilarity, a very deep and often melancholy earnestness, are always directed to definite special objects, and hence present no connected whole. Holding fast to the faith of the church, he yet rebuked in- dignantly the unfruitful hair-splitting spirit of dogmatic con- troversy, and insisted on the one thing needful ; at the same time, it is true, he occasionally too lightly esteemed man's scientific right to a clear knowledge of the contents of faith, as well as the significancy of the doctrinal differences between the churches ; and, in his desire for a moral reformation of the church, he too little considered the importance of pure doctrine, and was too indulgent toward many opposers of the same. The second, John Arndt, (ob. 1621), was spiritually kindred to Andreae and held him in high esteem ; Arndt was an evangelical Thomas a Kempis, and combined evangelical fidelity of faith with mystical subjectivity and practical zeal for morality, and exerted a deep-reaching, beneficent influ- ence on the evangelical churches. His work entitled Four Books of True Christianity (at first in 1605-10) with the ex- ception of the Imitation of Christ, the most widespread of German books of devotion bears indeed sometimes a rather strong mystical coloring (in this respect following somewhat in the path of Tauler and of the "German Theology"), and under-estimates, in many respects, the significancy of the objective means of grace, and lays chief emphasis on the mystical, direct union of the soul with God ; nevertheless it constituted so essential and so salutary a complementing of the somewhat one-sidedly theorizing theological spirit of the age, and so powerfully stirred up the partially-dormant moral consciousness, that Arndt will always occupy an eminent place in the history of morality and of practical ethics. A per se unimportant and yet fruitful attempt at a purely 250 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [37. theological system of ethics, unconnected with dogmatics, was made by George Calixt of Helmstadt ; his Epitome theol- ogicB moralis (p. I, 1634; 1662,) is only a short, incomplete outline, giving in fact only an introduction. The purpose of ethics is, to describe the way to blessedness, the life of the already spiritually-regenerated Christian ; regeneration itself is presupposed ; the foundation, even of Christian morality, is the ten commandments, which are a revealed re-establish- ment of the original law of nature ; but the difference of Chris- tian ethics from Old Testament ethics is not made prominent enough. In the footsteps of Calixt followed J. C. Diirr of Alt- dorf, who, for the first, gave a tolerably complete and learned treatise on ethics ; * he distinguishes between virtues toward God, toward others, and toward ourselves; in regard to theatrical spectacles, to jesting, etc., he shows a less rigid severity than the ethical writers of the Reformed church ; and this difference of view is manifest also among the other Lutheran moralists, if we except the Pietists. Of the same tendency was also G. T. Meier, of Helmstadt, whose erudite and profound introduction to ethics t examines, for the first time, with critical discrimination the presuppositions of this science. (H. Rixner, in a briefer work in 1690.) Aristotle is used- also in these theological treatises on ethics, without, however, damagingly influencing their theological character. The ethics of the Lutheran church was treated more fre- quently casuistically than in a systematic form ; it bore this character even as late as into the eighteenth century, and forms, properly speaking, only an amassment of material for a subsequent scientific development. As occasioned by the casuistry of the Romish church, the casuistry of the evan- gelical church, in express antithesis thereto, manifests, on the basis of Scripture and of spiritual experience, a greater certainty and simplicity, and preserves a middle-ground be- tween the sophistical laxity of the Jesuitical view and the rigid severity of the Calvinistic. Many of these works con- tain also many dogmatic questions together with their decis- ions. The distribution of the subject-matter follows, for the * Enchiridion theol. mor., 1662 ; later as : Compend., 1675-98 4to. t Introd. in univ. theol. mor. studium, 1671. And as the beginning of a development of ethics itself: Bisputt. theol., 1679. 37.] OLEARUS OSIANDER. 251 most part, the order of the catechism ; the answer is given on the basis of the Scriptures, and then confirmed by the decis- ions of the Fathers and of later writers, especially of Luther and of the other Reformers. The first work of this kind, after the already-mentioned Gonsilia of Melanchthon, is by Baldwin of Wittenberg,* and obtained great popularity; it treats chiefly of the casus conscientia, that is, of such moral questions as the common conscience cannot immediately and satisfactorily decide, but in regard to which it may fall into doubt, and which consequently can be decided only by a careful weighing of the word of God. He classifies these cases according to the moral objects : God, angels, the sub- ject himself, and other men. (L. Dunte of Reval, gave a thousand and six decisions on conscience-questions of a moral and dogmatical character, in 1643.) Olearius of Leipzig, who had already previously presented ethics in tabular form, examined thoroughly, and with the most minute and dis- criminating exactness, the purpose and the nature of casu- istry ; f casuistry was more fully carried out by Dannhauer, J by G. Kb'nig, but especially circumstantially by John Adam Osiander, \ who introduces into the subject almost the entire body of dogmatics ; he classifies the cases in the order of the Decalogue; under the sixth commandment, e. g., he proposes the question whether in a case of extreme necessity it is al- lowable to eat human flesh, and, in opposition to the Jesuits, negatives it (ii, p. 1367). The work of Mmgering (superin- tendent in Halle) Scrutinium conscientias catecheticum, that is, a "Reproving of Sin and Searching of the Conscience," etc. (3 ed. 1686, 4to.), more especially intended for moral self- examination, is classified minutely and circumstantially ac- cording to the Decalogue, and is morally earnest and judi- cious, though it presents also a few peculiarities (e. (7., p. 752, as to the inadmissibility of tobacco-smoking, then called tobacco-drinking). Only in part, belongs in this place the voluminous work: ConsUia theologica Witebergensia, that is, * Tractatus luculentus, etc., 1628, '35, and later. t Introd. brevis in theol. casuisticam, 1694. J Liber conscientice, 2 ed. 1679, 2 t., and Theologia casualit, 1706. Cams consc., Altdorf, 1676, 4to. |j Theol, casualu, 1680, 6 t., 4to. 252 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 3T. "Wittenberg's Spiritual Counsels," etc. (Frankfort on the Main, 1664) which contains, in an immense folio, judg- ments of Luther and of his co-laborers, and decisions of the Wittenberg faculty on doctrinal points, moral and ecclesi- astico-legal questions (also matrimonial questions). Of a similar character is the Opus novum qucestionum Practico-Theo- logicum (Frankfort, 1667, fol.), which treats, in the order of the common Loci, sixteen hundred and sixty-seven questions, also that of Dedekenn : Thesaurus consiliorum theol. etjurid. (1623), revised by John C. Gerhard (Jena, 1671, 4 vols. fol.). Also the theological " Bedenken " of the eighteenth century belong to the sphere of this casuistical ethics. Among these works those of Spener occupy a peculiar and significant place, and constitute, together with his other more or less ethical writings, a turning-point in the development of the evangelical moral consciousness. Their significancy rests less in their sin- gle judgments than in their peculiar ground-thoughts. Spener, who was imbued with the spirit of Thomas & Kempis/of Andreae and of Arndt, and in part, even of Tauler, and who restlessly labored in the path trod by these men for a moral bettering of the Christian church, called forth by the Pietism which proceeded from him, a deep-reaching, beneficent move- ment in the moral life and in the moral views of the evangelical church, although indeed in consequence of his one-sided em- phasizing of the practical, he treated science itself somewhat too lightly, and set too high an estimate on certain outward forms of devout morality, and thus needlessly limited the legiti- mate liberty of a regenerated Christian. Spener's Pia desideria * are directed essentially to an improving of the ecclesiastical life, to a stronger emphasizing of holiness in the spiritual ac- tivity of the church, to a stirring-up of the church-member- ship to churchly spontaneity, to the bringing about of a more edifying manner of doctrinal preaching, and, on the other hand, against the misuse of the doctrine of justification by faith. His ethical works proper, though only bearing on par- ticular cases, especially of the inner life, are found in his Theo- * Appearing first in 1675 as a preface to Arndt' s Pastille, afterward separately, often printed. 37.] SPENER AND PIETISM. 253 logical Considerations* which exercised a wide-reaching and wholesome influence on the church. Spener insisted with much more earnestness on the significancy of spiritual regeneration for the moral life than did the orthodoxy of the day, in its one- sided emphasizing of theoretical faith. The man of the Holy Spirit has nothing in common with the sinful world and its lusts; his total life-stream flows from a new and absolutely holy fountain ; worldly pleasure is foreign and uncongenial to him, and therefore to be avoided. The morality of the Pietists was distinguished primarily by an especial rigor in regard to the sphere of the allowed, inasmuch as it viewed as absolutely unallowable many worldly enjoyments which in the Evangelical Lutheran church had, thus far, been regarded (too unsuspi- ciously, it is true) as adiaphora, and consequently as not strictly unallowable, especially such as dancing, card-playing, theater- visiting, banqueting, gayness of dress, and the like; it denied altogether that there are any morally indifferent things; what- ever is not done to the glory of God, and springs not of faith, is sin ; and these amusements cannot consist with a pious frame of the heart, cannot take place in faith, and to the glory of God. This is. however, only an outer manifestation of a very deep-reaching antithesis of Pietism to the hitherto prevalent views of the Lutheran church. The high evangelical thought of Gospel-freedom and of justification by faith alone, had in fact, in the time of the declining church-life, led, in many respects, to erroneous courses, and had often allowed the moral earnestness of holiness to give place to mere formal orthodoxy, and also sometimes occasioned, in contrast to the severe earn- estness of the discipline of the Reformed church, too careless a regard for the outward forms of the moral life, and had en- larged beyond measure the sphere of morally-indifferent things. The notion had obtained for itself vogue, that whatever is not forbidden in Scripture is allowable. It was the reaction of a truly. Christian conscience, which caused Pietism to discard this somewhat presuming maxim, and, in any case, the thought which it opposed thereto was strictly legitimate, namely, that there is nothing indifferent in the entire life-sphere of a regen- * Theologische Bedenken, 1700, 1712, 4 vols. ; Letzte theol. Btdenken, 1711, 3 vols. ; Consilia etjudicia theol., 1709, 3 vols., and many other smaller works. \ 254 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 37. erated person, but that every thing without exception must stand in living relation to the new spiritual life-principle, and that whatever does not admit of a true association with the same is not simply indifferent, but is un-Christian. Pietism may have made many mistakes in the application of this thought, but the thought itself had, as in contrast to the one-sided orthodoxy then prevalent, its own good right. Fur- thermore, Spener brought again into the fore-ground the thought which, while indeed dogmatically admitted, had yet never been sufficiently emphasized morally, namely, that faith without works is dead ; the sanctification of the heart and life does not simply follow upon, and stand in connection with, true faith, but is in such faith already itself directly contained; there are not two spiritual life- streams, but only one ; the moral personality itself as justified by faith admits of no falling apart of faith and morality ; all religious life is immediately and necessarily at the same time moral, is not simply followed by the moral as a second collateral element. In the eyes of declining ortho- doxy, religion had become too much a mere objective something by which the religious subject is simply embraced and influ- enced, but not thoroughly permeated ; Pietism brought religion and its divine spirit-principle again entirely within the Chris- tian subject, and caused the subject, as now transformed, to create a new Spirit-witnessing, objective morality. The Chris- tian conscience is quickened and made more vigorously active by Pietism ; the views thus far prevalent in the Lutheran church are, in the eyes of Pietism, not strictly conscientious, seeing that they tolerate many manners of action which do not flow from the Christian conscience, and are not consistent with it. The morality of Pietism is by no means of a predominantly outwardly-active working character, is in fact very different from the more recent activity of the " inner mission," but is predominantly subjective, is one-sidedly directed toward the morally-pions heart-condition of the subject, and sustains to the outer world rather a rejecting, negating and uninterested relation ; the ascetic tendency which constantly grew more prominent, especially among Spener's followers, rose even to a manifest preference of celibacy to marriage, and to an avoid- ance of political offices (in the spirit of Tertullian), and to a refusing of military service. When its orthodox opponents re- 38.] EOMISH ETHICS. 255 proached Pietism with an unevai.gelical seeking of sanctiflca- tion by works, with a tendency to the monkish spirit and the like, they did not do it full justice ; and it was in vain that they undertook to check the historically-justified movement, and, notwithstanding all their hostile exaggerations, they saw very clearly the questionable narrownesses of the movement they opposed more clearly than they saw their own ; and it is not exclusively through Pietism, but also in virtue of the oppo- sition which it awoke, that the religiously-moral consciousness of the church was stimulated to a higher life. The Pietistic tendency proper, because of its disinclination to abstract sci- ence, produced no ethical works of importance ; most im- portant are: Breithaupt: Theol. moralis (1732, 4to. ; Institt theol., 3 parts, 1716), and the moral parts of Joachin Lange's (Economia salutis (1728.) But the popular Pietistic works, written for the masses of the church, were more influential. SECTION XXXVIII. The ethics of the Roman Catholic church, after the Reformation, was treated for the most part as a constantly increasing and more minute-growing body of casuistry. The highest development of the same, and at the same time the greatest perversion of Chris- tian ethics, also in regard to its moral contents, ap- peared in the semi-Pelagianizing ethics of the Jesuits. The place of the unconditional validity of the moral idea is here largely usurped by outward adaptability to the weal of the visible church, as the highest end ; the place of the unshaken authority of the Scriptures and of early Christian tradition, by the authority of certain special Doctors ; the place of moral convic- tion, by probabilisni; the place of moral honesty, by a sophistical construing of the moral law to the present fortuitous advantage of the church and of the individual, and by the falsehood of reservationes mentales ; and the place of the moral conscience, by 256 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 38. rational and cunning calculation ; thus the essence of the moral law becomes entirely unsettled; and the practical application of moral principles, an un- serious exercise of sophistry. At first thought we are surprised at the exceeding fruitfulness of the Romish theology of the sixteenth and seventeenth cen- turies in ethical writings, in comparison with which the evan- gelical church, and especially the Lutheran, is very barren. Opposition to the faith-principle of the Evangelical church, led the Romish church to an especial development of the prac- tical phase of religion, as in fact, in the order of the Jesuits, a vigor of activity hitherto unknown in the Romish church makes at this time its appearance ; and precisely this order was the chief representative of Romish ethics. The more purely scien- fic form of ethics lingered in general strictly within the limits of the scholastico- Aristotelian rut. Francis Piccolomini, a much- lauded Aristotelian, in Italy (ob. 1604) produced a comprehen- sive and discursive moral philosophy * based on Aristotle and Plato ; but his writings do not give proof of any independence, and fail to satisfy the Christian consciousness. The Order of the Jesuits, as calculated in its very nature for action, for the championship of the endangered Romish church, was called by its fundamental principle to the development of a special system of morality, a system the highest end of which is the glory of God through the exaltation of the visible church. The majority of the Jesuitical presentations of ethics treat, for the most part, enly of the more or less classified circle of single cases, while the more rare systematic works follow very closely the traditions of scholasticism.! Very soon after the Reforma- tion the Jesuits appeared in the field of ethics ; we will men- tion only the more important. Among the Spaniards were: Francis Tolet (a cardinal, ob. 1596, Summa casuum comcientim, often printed) ; Azorio (Institutiones morales, 1600, 3t. ; 1625, 2t.) ; Vtisquez (Opuso. mor., 1617); Henriquez (Summa, 1613fol.); * Uhiver8aphilogop7iiamoribv8,Venct.l5SS; Frkf., 1595, 1627. tPerrault: Morale des Jes., 1667, 3t. ; Ellendorf: Die Moral und Politik der Jcsuiten, 1840-^-not sufficiently scientific ; Pragm. Gesch. d. Monschsorden, 1770, vols. 9 and 10. 38.] JESUIT MORALISTS. * 257 Thomas Sanchez, whose learned work, De matrimonio* was highly esteemed, (but which, in the invention and discussion of indelicate questions, transgresses the bounds of all propriety), and who by his sweeping doctrine of probabilism deeply un- settles the foundations of all morality; (of him are further: Opus morale s. Summa casuum, Col. 1614, 2t. ; Consilia s. opu- scula mor., Lugd. 1635, 2 fol.) ; Francis Suarez, in numerous very ingenious works ; Alphonso Rodriguez (Exercitium perfec- tionis, etc., 1641); Antonio de Escobar, one of the most impor- tant of the casuists (Liber tlieol. moral., etc., Ludg., 1646; Uniterm theol. moral, problemata, Ludg., 1663, 7 fol.); and Gonzalez (Fundamentum theol. moralis., 1694, 4to.) Among the Italians were: Tamburini, and Filliucci (Moral, qucest., 1622, 2 fol.) Among the French : Bauny, and Raynauld. Among the Germans: Layman (Theol. mor., 1625, 3 4to.); Busenbaum, of Munster, whose Medulla casuum consc. has had, since 1645, more than fifty editions,t an able, clear, compact manual in tolerably systematic order, and authoritative almost throughout the whole Order, although in many respects assailed, even by popes, and in some countries proscribed. Among the Nether- landers : Leonard Less (in several works), and Besser (De con- scientia, 1638, 4to.) The contents and manner of treatment of most of these work.s are very similar. The peculiar character of Jesuitical ethics rests on the funda- mental purpose of the order as a whole, namely, the rescuing of the Church, the bride of Christ, as endangered by the Ref- ormation in its very foundations, and hence the rescuing of the honor of God from a most pressing danger. In a struggle of life and death one is not very careful in the choice of means, and in all warfare the sentiment holds good, though involving manifold violations of ordinary right, that the end sanctifies the means. The rescuing of the Romish church at any price is the task, even should it involve an entering into alliance with the dark powers of this sinful world, and with the passions and sinful proclivities of the unsanctified multitude. The one * Genuse, 1592? 1602; Antv. 1607, 1612, 1614, 1617, 3 fol. ; Norimb. 1706 ; the first edition has become rare ; in the later editions, after 1612, the smuttiest passages are omitted or modified. t Eewritten and enlarged by Lacroix, 1710, 9t., Col. 1729, 2 fol., and frequently. 258 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 38. exclusively aimed-at end makes use of the systematized totality of moral ends as mere means, and the morally-contracted view taken of this one end leads naturally and of itself to morally unallowable means. The real, visible church is not measured by the idea of the true or ideal church, but all moral ideas are measured by the visible church. The Jesuits were well aware that they were an essentially new phenomenon of the churchly life, that they stood upon purely human invention and power; we need not be surprised therefore to find that in their moral system human invention and human authority stand in the fore- ground. The expressed opinion of a church doctor forms a sufficient basis for a legitimate moral decision. The eternal and objective foundations of the moral are exchanged for the subjective view of individual persons of eminence. The con- tradictions thereby resulting render the single subject all the less trammeled, enable him to follow the decision which he most prefers. Another of their peculiarities is their discipline ; the required unconditional obedience to the commands of superi- ors takes the place of the personal conscience, and paralyzes its power; it becomes a duty of the members of the order to have no personal conscience whatever, and to subordinate the indi- vidual conscience unconditionally and blindly to the general conscience of the order ; a collective conscience, however, is a poor one, and poorest of all when it is represented by one single person. Thus the Jesuit accustoms himself from the very start, blindly to follow the authority of a single eminent man, and Probabilism is, in his moral theory, an inevitable matter of course. This, then, is the distinguishing characteristic of Jesuitical ethics, that in the place of the eternal objective ground and criterion of the moral, it substitutes subjective opinion, and in the place of an unconditional eternal end, a merely condi- tionally valid one, namely, the defending of the actual, visible church against all forms of opposition, that in the place of the moral conscience, it substitutes the human calculating of circumstantial and fortuitous adaptation to the promotion of this its highest end, that it attempts to realize that which is per se and absolutely valid by a wide-reaching isolating of the means, but in so doing subordinates morality to the discretion of the single subject. While the ethics of the Jesuits appears 38.] SPIRIT OF JESUITISM. 259 as lax and quite too indulgent toward worldly, sinful proclivi- ties and fashions, yet this is only one phase of the matter. A merely worldly-lax moral system, in the usual sense, seems but little applicable to the members of a brotherhood the first rule of which is a perfect renunciation of personal will and personal opinion and self-determination, in a word, unconditional obe- dience to every command of superiors, and which has actually accomplished in the missionary field the grandest of deeds, and numbers, among its members, multitudes of heroic martyrs. This lack of strictness in one direction rests by no means on mere world- 15 ness, on pleasure in the delights of this life, but follows, on the one hand, of necessity (as well as does also the rigor of obedience) from the subjectively-arbitrary presupposition of the entire or- der, from the lack of an objective, unshaken foundation, and rests, on the other hand, strictly on calculation, is itself a cunningly-devised means to the end, is intended to awaken, especially in the great and mighty of the earth (and the masses of the people are such under some circumstances), a love to the church, to the mild, friendly, indulgent mother ; and these con- cessions to the world formed a contrast to the severer moral views of the evangelical church, and especially to the over-rigid discipline of the Reformed church ; and the contrast was tempt- ing. The purpose zealously pursued by the Jesuits in the interest of Romish domination of becoming soul-guarding fathers and conscience-counselors, especially for men and women of eminence, required, on the one hand, that the Jesuits themselves should acquire for themselves the highest possible repute in ethics, and hence it was requisite that they should become the literary representatives thereof, and, on the other, that this ethics should bft molded in adaptation to this end, should make itself not disagreeable and burdensome, but should become as elastic as possible in view of different wants, should be a " golden net for catching souls," as the Jesuits themselves were wont to call their own pliableness. The more ramified and complex the net-work of casuistic ethics became, so much the more indispensable were the practiced conscience- counselors, or more properly, conscience-advocates; the more stairways and back doors they were able to turn attention to in conscience affairs, so much the more prized and influential they became. This explains the great compass and the peculiar 18 260 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [38. character of Jesuitical ethics. The becoming accustomed to slippery and precipitous ways, and the pleasure in the ready- finding of sophistical authority for morally novel positions, led of itself unconsciously into still deeper error. ' ' Accommoda- tion " was the magic word which opened the way for a surpris- ingly-rich storehouse of moral rules. Confession, where made to Jesuits, lost much of its seriousness, and nowhere else was absolution so easily obtainable for those who were to be won over, nowhere penance and satisfaction so readily done with, and this not merely in fact, but also from principle. Penance is to be chosen as light as possible ; the confessor may impose as penance, on the confessing one, the good or evil which he can do or suffer on the same day or in the same week ; the penance may, when there exists a sufficient reason, be even per- formed for oue person by another, etc.* Also in most cases it is not a very serious matter even if the absolved one neglects en- tirely the imposed penance. The development of Jesuitical ethics is by no means a phe- nomenon essentially new ; the bases therefor were already long extant ; it is only a further building upon the same foundations. The Pelagianizing view of the moral ability of the human will and of the meritoriousness of outward works lay already at the basis of the entire system of monkish holiness, and the Jesuits went only one step further when they, in contradiction to Thomas Aquinas, taught often almost entirely as Pelagius. The earlier casuistry in its lack of fixed principles had already shaken the moral foundation ; and the too great indulgence in sophistry on particular, and, in part, entirely imaginary, cases, had beclouded the unsophisticated moral consciousness; the doctrine of probabilism had been already sanctioned at Con- stance, and in many respects practically applied. The entan- glement of the church with the then so manifoldly-complicated state of European politics, with worldly passions and rancors, and its very worldly struggles against the worldly state, had already long since undermined the purity of the ecclesiastical conscience, and the maxim, that the end sanctifies the means, had already been long practiced and approved by the church before it was, by the Jesuits (if not sanctioned in express words, * Filliucci : Moral, quast., 7, tract. 6 c. 7 ; Escobar: Liber th., VII, 4 c. 7 (especially n. 181,182), comp. Ellendorf, 263 sqq., 312 sqq. 38.] PROBABILISM. 261 yet in fact on the largest scale) put into practice ; the per se not incorrect distinguishing of venial from mortal sins offered easy opportunity of indefinitely enlarging the sphere of the former by a limitation or a ready transforming of the sphere of the latter, while at the same time the ever-growing readiness in granting indulgences was making the sphere even of mortal sins of a less terrifying character, especially for those at whose command stood the keys to the treasure-chambers of indul- gence ; and in fact it was these especially, namely, the rich and noble, who enjoyed the advantages of the generosity of Jesuitic ethics. Jesuitic ethics did not indeed harmonize with the moral consciousness of the ancient church ; its representatives were also well aware of this, and they hesitated not to admit that they did not recognize ancient church tradition as a crite- rion for morality, but wished rather to lay the foundations for a new tradition. The chief means used for the purpose of lightening moral duty was the so-called moral probabilism, namely, the principle that in morally-doubtful cases the authority of a few eminent church-teachers, or also even of a single one (if he is a doctor grams et probus), suffices to furnish a sententia probaMlis as to a moral course of action, and hence to justify the performing of it, even if the opinion followed were per se false ; nay, accord- ing to some, even if this teacher himself had declared it as only morally possible, without really approving of it. Hence, as soon as I can hunt up for an action which seems to me of doubtful propriety, or even positively wrong, a consenting opin- ion of an ecclesiastical authority (and of course it is best if I find it among the Jesuit doctors themselves), then am I perfectly screened by the same ;* in which connection it is to be taken into account that there is scarcely any one moral question which is not answered by different doctors in an entirely contrary sense. That thus the most opposite manners of action may be equally readily justified, the Jesuits knew very well ; and Esco- bar even found, in the actual variety of views as to the moral, an amazing trace of Divine Providence, inasmuch as thereby the yoke of Christ is in so agreeable a manner rendered *Laymann: TJieol. mor. 1625, i, p. 9; Escobar: Liber th., proceem., exam. 3; Bresser: De consc. iii, c. 1 $$., and in almost all the others. 262 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 38. easy.* Although probabilism was not so immoderately extended by all the Jesuits, nevertheless it was the decidedly dominant teaching; and when the general of the order, Gonzales, in 1694, disapproved of it, many were minded to regard him as thereby deposed because of heresy, and only the protection of the Pope saved him.f Probabilism is not a merely fortuitously discovered expe- dient, but it is in fact an almost inevitable consequence of the historical essence of Jesuitism. As the order itself arose neither on the basis of Scripture nor of ancient church-tradi- tion, but sprang absolutely from the daring inventive power of a single man breaking through the limits of ecclesiastical actuality, hence it is not at all unnatural that it should make the authority of a single spiritually preeminent man its highest determining power, and subordinate to this the historical, objective form of the moral consciousness. "When the learned moralists came to be regarded as the determining authority in morals, then the Jesuits were the masters of the world, for they were themselves the most excellent doctors. Though they absolved the inquirer from so many burdensome chains of commanding duty, though they led him in the selection between opposed authorities to a subjective discretion of de- cision, yet at least this point was reached, that he recognized the Jesuit priests as his liberating masters. The doctrine of probabilism can by no means be explained as a simple sequence of the Roniish tradition-principle ; for here the deciding ele- ment is not the authority of the church, but simply individual teachers and in fact not, the majority of authorities, but it is expressly permitted to follow f the lesser authority in face of the greater, and to select among several authorities the one which best pleases, even if it be the less probable one. Hence also the father-confessor is not at liberty, as against the probable opinions of those who confess to him, to appeal to other and higher authorities, but he must admit the former * Quia ex opinionum varietatejugum Christi suavita sustinetur ( Univ. theol. mor., t. i, lib. 2, 1, c. 2 in Crome, x, 182.) t Wolf: Gesch. d. Jesuit., 1, 173. J Escobar: Th. mor., proceem., iii, n. 9, and many others. Sanchez: Of. mor., i, 9, n. 12 sqq., n. 24. 38.] PROBABILISM. 263 even should he hold them for entirely false,* and a doctor, when asked for moral advice needs not to impart the same exclusively according to his own judgment, but may also suggest the judgment of another though contradictory to his own, in case it is more favorable to, or more desired by, the inquirer (si forte hoc illi favorcibilior sen exoptatior sit); hence he may give to different persons a directly contrary answer to the same question, "only he must in this matter use discre- tion and prudence."! Many go so far as to maintain that I not only need not follow the opinion most probable to me, but that I may even follow that one of which I hold only that it is probable that it may be probable (Tamburini). But how is the doctrine of probability to be reconciled with the Cath- olic doctrine that the assent of the church is necessary in order that any course of action may be ecclesiastically valid? Bauny gives the answer: All that doctors teach in printed books has, in fact, the assent and approval of the church, provided that the church has not expressly declared it as invalid. Though probabilism per se, as a mere formal principle, en- dangers morality in a high degree, substituting in the place of the moral conscience individual and arbitrary authority, and rocking the soul into false security, still it were possible that the danger of this principle should not actually realize itself, in that it might be presupposed that the theological authorities would, in all essential moral thoughts, harmonize with each other and with the Scriptures, and would show some difference only in regard to more external, unimportant questions. In this case the erroneousness of the formal prin- ciple would in some measure be remedied by the correctness of the material contents. The question rises therefore : What do the doctors who are presented as moral oracles, positively teach as to the moral? One would be largely deceived were one to expect to find in the moral writings in question merely the loose world- morality of moral indifference, selfishness, and pleasure-seek- ing; on the contrary, they often present anxiously, minute Escobar: TJi. mor. proaem., iii, n. 27; Laymann, i, p. 12; so also Diana : Besol. mor., ii, tract., 13,11 tqq., Antv., 1637 ; Summa, 1652, p. 210. t Laymann, i, p. 11. 264 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 38. and strict prescriptions, especially in churchly relations, so that the evangelical liberty of a Christian man would feel itself thereby in many respects largely cramped. One must here distinguish, however, between the ordinary popular morality as it were, for home use, and indeed also for show and the higher morality which relates to the fundamental purposes of the Jesuit order, that is, to the furtherance of the Romish church, and which is chiefly practiced by the great, in church and state, and hence also by the Jesuits them- selves. To the semi-Pelagianizing explaining-away of the sinful corruption of human nature, corresponds, on the other hand, a lowering of the moral requirements made of man ; for the natural man, downy cushions are spread. We are not obligated to love God throughout our whole life, in the full sense of the word, nor even every five years, but more especially only toward the close of life.* In fact, the French Jesuit Sirmond denies the obligation of love to God on the whole ; it is sufficient if we fulfill the other commandments and do not hate God ; t and he found in his Order warm con- currence. So also is the love of neighbor, and especially of enemies, lowered to a degree corresponding to anti-Christian, heathen ways of thinking. And even the duties of children are placed lower than is the case among the Chinese. The fourth commandment is fulfilled by the fact that one shows due honor to his parents, though without loving them ; for love is not required in the commandment. To be ashamed of one's parents, to banish them from one's presence, to treat them as strangers and the like, is not a severe sin ; but, on the contrary, it is allowable for the son to accuse his father of heresy before the Inquisition (Busenbaum), and according to a majority of the Jesuits, as also in the opinion of Diana, he is obligated thereto ; and the same holds true of brothers and sisters, and of consorts. J Some of them declare it even as allowable that a son should wish his father's death, or should rejoice at the occurrence of his death, because he has now the happiness of coming into his inheritance (Tam- burini, Vasquez), or that a mother should wish the death of her daughter, in case the latter is ugly (Azorius). Malignant * Escobar : i, 2, n. 7 sqq. ; v, 4, n. 1 sqq. t Defensio virtutis, i, 1. J Diana : Resol. mor. i, tract., 4, 4, 5, 38.] JESUITIC DEPRAVITY. 265 revenge is indeed forbidden, but not the taking revenge in vindication of one's honor. In respect to moral imputation and condemnation, most of the teachers make in view of rendering moral desert easy the remarkable distinction, that the action answering to the divine law is good and meritorious as such, without it being requisite thereto that the intention should be good ; and that, on the contrary, sin exists only where there is really an intention of sinning. Hence if the intention is a good one, that is, pro- motive of the weal of the church, then the act which serves to its carrying-out cannot be sinful ; and there can be a mortal sin only where the person in the moment of the act had the definite intention of doing evil, and a perfect knowledge of the same. But passion and evil habit becloud one's knowl- edge and hence render the sin venial, as does also weighty evil example ; * and a probable opinion entirely excuses even a mortal sin. In an unimportant matter even the transgres- sion of a divine law is not a mortal sin. Ignorance of the law excuses the mortal sin ; and inveterate ignorance, the father- confessor may overlook in silence. Repentance over a com- mitted sin is indeed necessary to the forgiveness of the same, but a very slight degree of repentance suffices, or even a de- sire to have repentance, or the fear of eternal punishment ; and, in case of repeated sins, it is enough to feel repentance for only one of them, provided that all are confessed ; nay, it even suffices that I should feel pained, not because of the sin, but because of its bad consequences, e. g,, disease, dishonor ; t it is therefore not to be wondered at when some of the doctors assert, in contradiction to others, that it is suf- ficient in order to the obtaining of absolution that we feel a regret at our lack of repentance (Sa, Navarra). An actual bettering of one's life needs not to follow immediately upon repentance, as in fact the habit of sinning renders the sin itself venial. Venial sins (and in the eyes of the Jesuits this field is uncommonly large) need not to be confessed, and it is not even necessary, in connection with the sacrament of penance, to repent of them, and to form a resolution to avoid them. * E. g., Laymann : i, 2, c. 3 ; i, 9, 3 ; Escob. : i, 3, n. 28 ; Conseuetudo dbsque advertentia letale peccatum non,facit. t Escobar : Tr. V, 4, c. 7. 266 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [38. Not undeserved is the notoriety of the chapters in Jesuitical ethics on falsehood, on the sexual sin, and on murder. One may intentionally use ambiguous words in one sense though knowing that the hearer understands him otherwise; and one may for a legitimate end, e. g., for self-defense, or to protect one's family, or to practice a virtue, utter words, which, as uttered, are entirely false, and which express the true sense (which may be the opposite to the sense really expressed) only through mental additions restrictio s. reservatio mentalis) ; of such cases the moralists abound in remarkable illustrations;* e. g., when some one wishes to borrow something of me which I do not like to let him have, I am at liberty to say, "I have it not," namely, by adding mentally, "in order to give it to thee;" if some one asks of me something which I do not wish to tell, I am at liberty to answer, "I know it not, "namely, as obligated to communicate it ; if I am asked as to a crime of which I am the sole witness, I am at liberty to say, ' ' I know it not, " mentally adding, "as a thing publicly known;" if I have hidden away a quantity of provision of which I have need, then I may swear before the court, "I have nothing," men- tally adding, "which I am bound to disclose." A priest threatened with death may, without real intentio, that is, merely in appearance, pronounce absolution, administer sac- raments, etc. An adulterous wife, when questioned by her husband, may swear that she did not commit adultery, adding mentally: "on this or that day," or "in order to reveal it to thee." He who conies from a scene of pestilence, but is con- vinced that he is not infected, may swear that he does not come from such a place. When a poor debtor is pressed by a hard creditor, he may swear before the court that he owes nothing to the other, in that he adds mentally, "in order to pay it right away." I may deny, before the court, every trespass or crime which has any manner of excuse, namely, by adding mentally, "as a crime." Is, qui ex necessitate vel aliqua utilitate offert se ad jurandum nemine petente, pote&t uti amphibologiis, nam habet justam causam Us utendi (Sanchez, * Sanchez: Opusmor., iii, 6, 12 sqq. / Summa : i, 3, 6 ; Diana: ii, tr. 15, 25 sqq.,' iii, tr. 6, 30, where many cases are cited and approved ; El- lendorf: pp. 42 sqq., 52 sqq., 124 sqq., 157 sqq.; Crome: x, 142 sqq. 38.] SEXUAL LAXITY. 267 Diana). In general, all such untruths are allowed EX JUSTA CAUSA, namely, quando id necessario est, vel utile ad salutem corporis, honoris aut rerum familiarum, or when an improper question is addressed to us ; on the contrary, to swear falsely without a good reason is a mortal sin (Diana) ; this is though not in express words yet certainly in sense the maxim which is disavowed by the more recent Jesuits, namely, that the end sanctifies the means. A promise obli- gates to its fulfillment only when one actually had, at the time of promising, the intention of fulfilling it.* Hence an oath is binding only when one meant it earnestly ; otherwise it is to be regarded as a mere blame-worthy indeed, though not obligating, piece of trifling (Sanchez, Busenbaum, Es- cobar, Less, Diana), and it obligates only in the sense in which, by mental reservations, it was intended, and not in that in which, by its form of expression, it would have to be understood by the other ; and knowingly to mislead any one into a false oath, who, however, acts in good faith, is no sin, since in fact he who unknowingly swears falsely does no evil thereby ; f to swear falsely from bad habit, is only a venial sin. If any one swears that he will never drink wine, then he seriously sins only when he drinks much, but not when he drinks but little (Escobar). He who swears before a court that he will tell all that he knows, is not bound to tell that which he alone knows (Less).f The sexual relations are discussed by the Jesuits in a so im- morally-detailed circumstantiality that the laxity of moral judgment (elsewhere without parallel) is rendered thereby all the more pernicious and condemnable. A maiden who has committed unchastity for the first time is not required, even when she is, as yet, unfjer the oversight of her parents, to give, in making her confession, this circumstance, namely, that it ia the first and hence more serious case, for the freely consenting virgin does a wrong neither to herself nor to her parents, inas- much as she has discretionary power over her virginal purity. * Escobar : iii, 3, n. 48. t Ibid., i, 3, n. 81. J Compare Diana : iii, t. 5, 100 sqq. Escobar : i, 8 ; v, 2 ; Busenbaum : iii, 4 ; especially Sanchez ; D matrim.; so also Diana; comp. Ellendorf: 30 sqq., 95 sqq., 28$. sqq., 331 sqq. 268 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 38. (Quum sit domina suce integritatis mrginalis)* For all possible kinds of unchastity, apologies and excuses are invented ; t and Tamburini even fixes with great exactness the taxes for public women. The discussions of the moralists on these subjects are, in many respects, of so indelicate a character, that the judg- ment of the Episcopal censor, printed in the work of Sanchez, (t. 2.), namely, summa voluptate perlegi, sounds almost too naive. Under the head of murder, the Jesuits had the task of accommodating themselves to the then prevalent moral notions of the South-European nations, and the result of their labors was an ingeniously constructed code of murder.J The murder- ing of a person, even of an innocent one, may under circum- stances be allowable, not indeed simply in case of self-defense, but also in other cases, for example, in case of severe insult, inasmuch as the insulted one would otherwise pass as dishon- ored ; and even when the insulted one is a monk or priest, he may, according to some authorities, kill his opposer (Escobar i, c. 3, Less, and others) ; and several Jesuits directly maintained that any one, even a priest or monk, is entitled to anticipate an intended slander or false accusation by secret murder ; for this would not amount to murder, but simply to self-defense ; and this was expressly applied to the case where a monk should have reason to fear the disclosures of his mistress. When a knight, in fleeing from the enemy, cannot otherwise rescue himself than by riding over an infant child or a beggar, then is the killing of these innocent persons allowable, save only in case that the child is not as yet baptized (Escobar, c. 3, 52), which would apparently be rather difficult for the knight to know. Killing in self-defense is allowable even where the self-defender is caught in a crime, and that, too, where the kill- ing is beforehand intended, e. g., whpn he who is caught in- adultery kills the injured husband (Escobar i, 7, c. 2, 5, 13 ; 3, 35 ; i, 8, n. 61). A woman may stiletto her husband when she knows definitely that this same fate threatens her from him, and when she knows no other escape (Less). He who has secretly * Escobar: Liber, etc., princ. ii, n. 41 ; so also Bauny. ^ E.g., Diana : ii, 1. 16, 54 ; 17, 62 sqq. ; iii, 5, 87 sqq. ; iv, 4, 36, 37, in the spirit of many of the Jesuits. \ Especially Escobar : i, 7 ; comp. Ellendorf : 72 sqq. Sanchez : Summa, t. i, 2, 39, 7 ; Amicus : Dejure etjustitia, v, sec. 7, 118 ; comp. Diana: iii, tr. 5, 97, ed. Antv. 1637. 38.] CODE OF MURDER. 269 committed adultery may kill the single witness thereof who is on the point of accusing him, for this witness is not under ob- ligation to make this accusation ; however, adds the Jesuit, civil law has unfortunately not assented to this probable opin- ion (Escobar i, 7, n. 39). He who without his own fault is re- quired to accept, or to challenge to, a duel, does wisely to put his opponent out of the way by secret murder, for thereby he protects himself from the assault, and his opponent from a serious sin.* Escobar is unwilling to see him who murders his enemy secretly shut out, just like a common murderer, from the right of asylum (6, 4, n. 26). According to some teachers the majority, however, think otherwise a pregnant maiden may procure an abortion in order to escape the shame, t According to Azor, a physician may administer a less certainly effectual medicine although he has with him a more certain one, and even, when it is more probable that the less effectual one may do harm ; for he has after all some probability on his side.}: Tamburini justifies the castration of singers for the service of the church. The doctrine notorious in church-his- tory of the justifiableness of tyrant-murder, we need only mention in passing, as well as also the almost demagogic doc- trine of the merely-relatively valid and purely human right of princes, and of the right to disobey law on the part of the people, as being themselves sovereign. In this political respect is especially notorious the work of the Spanish Jesuit, Mariana, (De rege. 1598, 1605), according to which, a king who oppresses religion or violates the laws of the state may be killed by any of his subjects, openly or by poison ; the murderer, even if his attempt fails, renders himself meritori- ous in the eyes of God and man, and wins immortal renown (cornp. the view of John of Salisbury, 34). It is chiefly these revolutionary doctrines that brought the order to its fall ; with its other moral views the secular world could have put up with much better grace. The maxims of the Jesuits disseminated themselves like * Sanchez : Opus mor. ii, 39, 7. t Crome, x, 229 ; Escobar, i, Y, n. 59, 64. Jin Escobar: Princ. iii, n. 25, who, however, himself disapproves thereof. Perrault, ii, 804 tqq.; Staudlin, 503 ; Ellendorf, 360 sqq. 270 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 38. an infectious disease far beyond the circle of their own Order, as is shown by the comprehensive works of the already men- tioned Sicilian, Antony Diana (clericus regular is),* who taught, under the express approbatio of his ecclesiastical su- periors, and also of the Jesuits, the doctrine of probabilism in its worst forms. One may act according to a probable opinion and disregard the more probable one ; man is not under obligation to follow the more perfect and the more certain, but it suffices to .follow simply the certain and per- fect ; it would be an unendurable burden were one required to hunt out the more probable opinions ; t the most of the Jesuits taught the same thing. In relation to murder, he teaches like Escobar ; I am at liberty to kill even him who assails my honor, if my honor cannot otherwise be rescued. J When some one has resolved upon a great sin, then one is at liberty to recommend to him a lesser one, because such ad- vice does not relate absolutely to an evil, but to a good, namely, the avoiding of the worse ; for example, if I cannot otherwise dissuade a person from an intended adultery than recommending to him fornication instead thereof, then it is allowable to recommend this to him, not, however, in so far as it is a sin, but in so far as it prevents the sin of adultery; Diana appeals in this connection to many like-judging Jesuit doctors. If a priest commissions Peter to kill Caius, who is weaker than Peter, but nevertheless Peter comes out second best and gets killed himself, still the priest incurs no guilt, and may continue in the administration of his office. | He who resolves upon committing all possible venial sins, does not thereby involve himself in any mortal sin. IT He who ex aliqua justa causa rents a house to another for purposes of prostitu- tion, commits no sin.** To eat human flesh, in case of neces- sity, he holds with the majority of the Jesuits, as allowable, ft He who in virtue of a promise of marriage induces a maiden to yield to him, is not bound by his promise, in case he is of higher rank or richer than she, or in case he can persuade himself that she will not take his promise in serious ear- * Resolutions morales, Antv., 1629-37, 4 fol., Lugd. 1667, Venet., 1728. t Res. mor., Antv., 1637, ii, tract. 13 ; iv, tr. 3 ; Summa, 1652, p. 214. I Ibid., iii, 5, 90 ; Summa, pp. 210, 212. Res. mor., Antv., 1637, iii, tract. 5, 37. || Ibid., ii, t-act. 15, 17. 1 Ibid., iii, tr. 6, 24. ** Ibid., iii, tr. 6, 45. ft Ibid., 6, 48. 38.] JESUITISM AND TALMUDISM. 271 nest. * Marriage between brother and sister can be made legit- imate by Papal dispensation.! In such moral perversity of view Diana seems only to have been surpassed by the Spanish Netherlander Cistercian, Lobkowitz,l who, in his skepticism, entirely breaks down the moral consciousness, and declares that nothing is evil per se, but only because it is positively forbidden; hence God can dispense even from all the com- mandments (comp. the views of Duns Scotus, 34), can, e. <7., allow whoredom and other like sins, for none of these are evil per se. Monks and priests are at liberty to kill the female misused by them, when they fear, on her account, for their honor. This writer declares himself expressly and de- cidedly in favor of the views of the Jesuits. Also the Fran- ciscan order became infected with the maxims of the Jesuits, as is proved by the very voluminous work of Barthol. Mastrius de Mandida,^ which was published under the express sanction of the officers of the order, and who justifies restrictiones men- tales even in oaths, || and also the murder of tyrants, IT the murders of the slanderers of an important person, castration and similar things,** as well as also probabilism. The moral system of the Jesuits is not, strictly speaking, that of the Romish church; many of their more extreme maxims the church has condemned, and the more recent Jesuits themselves find it advisable no longer fully to avow their former principles. Nevertheless Jesuitism, together with its system of morals, is the ultimate consequential goal of the -church in its turning-aside from the Gospel, just as (though in other respects widely different therefrom) Tal- mudism was the necessary goal of Judaism in its rejection of the Saviour. The error consists in the placing of human discretion and authority in the stead of the unconditionally valid, revealed will of God. Even as earlier Catholicism had intensified the divine command by self-invented, ascetic work-holiness into a seemingly greater severity, had aimed * Besol. mor., Antv., iii, 6, 81 ; in the spirit of Sanchez and Less, t Ibid., iv, tr., 4, 94; sanctioned by several Jesuits. J Theol. mor., 1645, 1652 ; the work itself 1 have not been able to find ; comp. Perrault : i, 331 sqq. Ibid., 1626. | Disp., xi, 5-2, 171, 172, 183, (ed. Ven. 1723.) H Ibid., viii, 27. ** Ibid., viii, 25, 28 ; xi, 110 sqq. 272 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 38. at a higher moral perfection than that required by God, so Jesuitism with like presumption lowered the moral law, out of consideration to temporal relations, to a merest minimum requirement, contented itself with a much lower moral per- fection than the divine law calls for, and sought out cunning means for lightening even this minimum. Jesuitical ethics is the opposite pole of monastic ethics ; what the latter requires too much, the former requires too little. Monastic morality sought to win God for the sinful world ; Jesuitical morality seeks to win the sinful world, not indeed for God, but at least for the church. Monasticism said to God, though not in an evangelical sense : " if I have only thee, then I ask for nothing else in heaven or earth ; " Jesuitism says about the same thing, but says it to the world, and particularly to the distinguished and powerful. The former turns away in in- dignant contempt from the worldly life, because the world is immersed in sin ; the latter generously receives the same into itself, and turns attention away from guilt, by denying it. It is true, the Jesuits represent also a monastic Order, but this order is only a means to an end, and resembles the other nobler orders about as much as wily Renard resem- bles the pious Pilgrim ; and the well-known hostility of the older orders to this brilliantly rising new one, Avas not mere jealousy, but a very natural, and, for the most part, moral protest against the spirit of the same. Other casuists are: Jacobus h Graffiis, a Benedictine (Con- siliorum s. respons. cas. consc. 1610, 2, 4to.) ; Pontas of Paris (Examen general de conscience, 1728; Latin, 1731, 3 fol., alpha- betical) ; the French bishop Qenettus (ob. 1702, Theologie mo- rale ; also in Latin, 1706, 2, 4to., earnest and rigid); the Dominican Perazzo, in his Thomisticus ecdesiastes (1700, 3 fol.), digested the ethics of Thomas Aquinas into an alphabetical register; Malder of Antwerp treated it more systematically (De virtutibus theologicis, 1616). In a more systematic form, a purer Christian spirit, and, in many respects, opposed to Jesuitical views, and correspond- ing rather to Mediaeval ethics, is the moral treatise of the French bishop Godeau (1709) ; Natalis Alexander (1693) treated the same subject in a similar spirit, in connection with dog- matics. 39.] JANSENISM. 273 SECTION XXXIX. In striking antithesis to the morals of the Jesuits, stand the teachings of the Augustine-inspired Jansen- ists, who, in opposition to the subjectively-individual character of the Jesuitical system, hold fast to the immutable objectivity of the moral law, and teach the latter in a very rigid manner, much resembling that of Calvinists; but yet because of their leaning upon the earlier mysticism of the church they come short of carrying fully out the Reformatory principle. The mystical theology present in Jansenism only as a co-ordinate element perpetuated itself in the Romish church, in natural antagonism to the cold casu- istic morality of the Jesuits, but rather in a popularly devotional than in a scientific form, and rose, in the Quietism of Molinos, to a one-sided turning-aside from all vigorous moral activity, while F'anelon shaped a modified and moderated mysticism into a noble, moral system of devout contemplation. Jansen of Louvain (afterward bishop of Ypres)j presses, in his Augustinus (1640), the doctrine of Augustine against the semi-Pelagian system of the Jesuits, and occasioned thereby a powerful theological movement which led almost to schism, and which demonstrated again by historical results that even the most rigid teaching of predestination brings about higher moral views than the doctrine of Pelagianism and semi-Pela- gianism, and for this simple reason, that, in the former sys- tem God is brought absolutely into the fore-ground, while, in the latter, the individual subject is put forward into a false position. Love to God and to his will is the essence of all morality ; where God is not loved in an action, there the action is not moral ; mere love to created things is sinful ; but our love to God is poured out into our hearts by God him- self, and hence stands in need of grace, which inclines the will directly and irresistibly to the working of the good. 274 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 39. The four chief virtues and the three theological virtues, as adopted from Augustine, are only different manners of loving God ; God is their ultimate goal, as also their source ; his gracious working and our love, both inseparably united, con- stitute their impelling power ; fear does indeed bring about order, but not virtue. Although the book of Jansen was burned at Rome, and forbidden by Papal bulls, still his opinions continued to disseminate themselves in the Nether- lands and in France, and bade defiance to Jesuitism. The writings of Arnauld, Pascal, Nicole, Quesnel, developed the moral principles of Jansen still further, and though they in fact remained far remote from evangelical purity of faith, and even defended as a high virtue the afflicting of the body by fasting and other severe acts of penance, even to self- mortification, still they were thoroughly in earnest for moral purity, required complete moral self-denial out of love of God, and placed the moral worth of all actions, and even of their ascetic practices, essentially in the disposition of the heart ; and their ground-principles were definite and clear, and proof against all sophistry.* Arnauld assailed effectu- ally the ethics of the Jesuits. Pascal's (ob. 1662) "Pensees" (1669 and later), consisting of thoughts on religion without any very close connection, attained to a very wide circula- tion. That the presentation of these quite plain thoughts could produce so great an impression, is evidence of how deeply had sunk the Christian life, and of how great was the necessity of reformation. Peter Nicole (ob. 1695) worked ef- fectually, through his numerous popular and essentially Scrip- ture-inspired writings on special moral topics, toward a purer form of ethics ; t and this was done in still wider circles by QuesneVs "Moral Reflections" (at first in 1671, on the Pour Gospels, afterward on the entire New Testament) which were affected with a slight tinge of mysticism ; (Sainte-Beuve : "Resolutions," etc., 1689, 3, 4to.). The open or under- handed opposition of the Jesuits to these writings simply awakened the attention of the people all the more to the great difference between the parties, and that, too, not to the * Comp. Reuchlin: Geschichte von Portrayal, 1839, and the same au- thor's Pascals Leben, 1840, neither work entirely unprejudiced, t Rirchenhistor. Archiv. v. Stiiudlin, etc., 1824, 1, 127. 39.] QUIETISM. 275 advantage of the Jesuits. The chief strength of Jansenism lay in its opposition to the Jesuits ; its own positive contents, as an emphasizing of the practical phase of Augustinianism, was not consequentially carried out ; it was not able to disen- thrall itself from the unevangelical ground-thoughts of the corrupted church, but halted at half- ways ; and hence though it had a wide-reaching, it did not have a permanent and pro- found, influence. Discarding the system of external work- holiness and insisting on the inner element of the moral life, it yet did not clearly and purely embrace the evangelical thought of faith, which first lays hold on grace and then freely carries out the life of grace ; but it regarded morality not merely as an evidence of salvation, but also, though without merit in itself, as a means of salvation ; hence its in- sisting on painfully-anxious ascetic practices. The mystical current of ethics, with which the Jansenists always manifested a sympathy, was represented by Francis de Sales (bishop of Geneva, ob. 1622, and subsequently canon- ized) in several works;* \>yVergier (abbot of St. Cyr, ob. 1643) a Jansenist, who was already powerfully working in the direc- tion of Quietism, and who encouraged the severest, and even cruel, self-mortifications; t and by Cardinal Bona (ob. 1674.) J Most remarkable, however, though quite consequential, was the manner in which mysticism was transformed into Quiet- ism by the Spaniard, Michael Molinos (afterward in Rome,) whose work entitled "Spiritual Guide," originally (1675) in Spanish, soon disseminated itself throughout Romish Europe. As the goal of morality is union with God through an entire turning away from the creature, hence true morality must manifest itself, not in acting in the outer world, but in turn- ing away from it. Such is the doctrine which Molinos de- rives from his favorites among the earlier mystics, from Dionysius the Areopagite down. In contemplation, in the path of faith, in immediate spiritual vision of God, without the intervention of an inferential process of thought, the soul already possesses eternal truth. True vision, inward * (Euvres, Paris, 1821, 16 t., 1834. t Opp. theol., 1642, 1653. J Manuductio ad calum, 1664, and frequently ; Opp. Antv., 1673,1789. Walch : Einl. in d. Bd. ttreit. ausser. d. ev. K; 1^24, ii, p. 982 ; Staudlin u. Tschirner : ArcMv., i, 2, 175. 19 276 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 39. rest and inward composure, the remaining silent in the presence of God, the beholding of God without figure or form, and without distinguishing between his attributes, as the absolutely One, all this is not a self-acquired active state, but a passive one imparted by God himself to the soul, so that consequently God alone works in man, and the soul itself remains motionless and inactive, yields itself entirely to the solely-working divine activity, is entirely united with God ; this is the true, pure manner of prayer, which cannot be uttered in words, but is a holy, keeping-silence of the soul. Satiated in this union with God the soul is entire- ly filled with the divine, and hates all worldly things, feels a repugnance to every thing earthly, forgets every thing created, is divested, in its inner solitude, of all affections and thoughts, of all inclinations and all creature-will, with- draws itself into its most innermost depths, and enjoys, in its total self-forgetfulness (entirely merged into God), perfect inner rest, and holy peace ; self-mortification and self-denial are but disciplinary helps for beginners in the acquiring of salvation, but do not themselves lead to perfection ; this is attained only through sinking into one's own nothingness, through "self-annihilation," through the putting on of, and becoming united with, God. Molinos, though at first favored by the Pope, was afterward delivered over, by the influence of the Jesuits, to the Inquisition, and was required to disa- vow his doctrines (1687), and died in prison. Many of the propositions condemned were only inferences drawn from his writings, though not expressly taught by himself. In spite of this and other persecutions, mysticism still continued to exist, also in its quietistic form, in the Latin nations. (Madam Bouvier de la Mothe Guion ob. 1717 represented it in numerous writings, mostly published by Poiret, in which she sometimes goes in fervent mystical depth of love, even beyond Molinos, the out-gush of a glowingly enthusiastic womanly heart.) Fenelon, archbishop of Cambray, favored the doctrine of Madame Guion, and endeavoreti by moderating her quietistic views to conjure the opposition; and his writ- ings, which portray in simple, noble eloquence the pious life of the Christian, and keep free from the extremes of one- sided mysticism, and uniformly place love to God in the fore- 40.] HUMANISM. 277 ground as the essence of the moral, offer and propose, in op- position to the pettifogging dialectics of Jesuitical morality, the Christian spirituality of the heart. His mystical master- piece (Explication des Maxims des Saintes, 1697, and often sub- sequently) was condemned by the Pope and proscribed; Fenelon yielded. SECTION XL. Independently pf the Reformation, because averse to Christianity itself, and standing rather in connec- tion with the already previously existing breaking- loose from the evangelically-moral consciousness which showed itself, as godlessness on the one hand, and as humanism on the other, there was developed, in antithesis to the Christian religion and to Mediaeval philosophy (as also in antithesis to the riper Greek philosophy, and consequently to the historical spirit in general) an essentially new philosophical movement, which, while moving forward under manifold modi- h'cations of form, gradually won a progressively greater influence on theology, and in fact chiefly also on theological ethics, leading the same astray, on the one hand, into deep-reaching errors, but also, on the other (and in fact because of these errors) bringing it to a riper self-examination and to a clearer self-con- sciousness. Showing a preference, in contrast to the precedent of the better form of scholasticism, to those ancient moralists who already represented the decadence of Greek thought, namely, to the Epi- cureans, the Stoics, and the Skeptics, or indeed also, merely in a general way, to the so-called humanistic spirit of antiquity, this movement (which found favor especially in Italy and France, because of the there-increasing demoralization of the higher classes), shows itself at first, for the most part, simply in the 278 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 40. form of general maxims and sentiments, and attained only rarely to a more scientific shape. Scarcely any- where save in Germany did this current of thought rise to scientific earnestness and philosophical devel- opment, and thereby to a more substantial moral character. Spinoza broke off all connection with ancient and Mediaeval philosophy, and developed a consequential Pantheistic system, in which ethics assumes the form of an objective describing of the absolutely unfree, purely mechanically-conceived moral life, as determined with unconditional nature- necessity by the life of the universe, although, be- cause of the unhistorical originality of his manner of thinking, he exerted but little influence upon his (for this element, yet unreceptive) age. All the greater, however, became the influence of the philosophy of Leibnitz, representing as it did a world-theory the opposite of that of Spinoza, and placing itself rigidly on monotheistic ground, and standing in a much ^closer connection with history; especially was this influence extended through the labors of his some- what independent disciple, Christian Wolf, who cre- ated a very detailed and morally earnest system of ethics, essentially under the form of the doctrine of duties, which, as a purely philosophical opposition- movement to the above-mentioned non-Christian and anti-Christian current, attained to a not undeserved in- fluence on Christian ethics in Germany, and gave rise in Crusius to an evangelically deeper, though not phil- osophically carried-out, development of moral science. It is utterly incorrect and -anti-historical to deduce the collective, and (as some have done) even the anti-Christian philosophy of modern times from the Reformation, or even to regard it as standing in any close connection therewith. 40.] ERASMUS. 279 The essence of the Reformation is not the freeing of the in- dividual subject from all objective authority. Historically, we are forced to hold fast to the fact that both before, and during, and after, the time of the Reformation, there were prevailing still other entirely different spiritual influences than the religiously-evangelical one, influences which were in part entirely independent of the Reformation and of its spirit, nay, even utterly opposed thereto, and in part, though occasioned in their development by the movement of thought going out from the Reformation, were yet not caused thereby. The renewed cultivation of ancient classical literature, espe- cially of the belletristic as distinguished from the philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, played, in the Reformation-move- ment, only a very subordinate and essentially negative role, namely, in that it undermined the credit of scholasticism. The deep earnestness of the religious life in the evangelical church, the required inward purity, and the repentance of regeneration, consisted but illy with a love for the exaltation of the natural man, as exhibited in Greek literature ; and it was much easier for humanism to find an undisturbed patron- age within the Romish church, which, though indeed not theoretically approving of the movement, had yet practically already long since accorded it favor. Humanism was the name self-assumed by this movement, which in antithesis to the Christian world-theory placed man, in his natural devel- opment, into the fore-ground even of its moral world-the- ory, and threw as far as possible into the back-ground his need of redemption, and which had consequently in Chris- tianity only a scientific and aesthetic interest. The unbeliev- ing impiety which prevailed widely in the Romish church of that age, and which found its way even into the Papal chair, had a much more lively sympathy for heathen literature than the evangelical church, The Pelagian character of hu- manism stood in fact nearer to the view of the Romish church than to that of the evangelical. Luther turned the un- evangelical Erasmus indignantly away ; Rome offered him a cardinals hat. It was quite natural, although it had nothing at all to do with the evangelical Reformation, that there should now rise in opposition to the one-sided idealism and spiritualism of 280 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [40. scholasticism, an equally one-sided realism and naturalism, which would naturally enough find encouragement in the spirit of the age as weaned off from the Mediaeval ideals of chivalry and poetry, and as immersed in material interests and in the prose of politics. This thoroughly non-Christian naturalistic tendency, which attained to a more spiritual content only in the sphere of German thought, manifested from the very start a decided aversion to all history, an aver- sion which constantly grew more marked and positive. This anti-historical spirit began already to show itself in the at- tempt to call again into life, in disregard to the entire his- tory of Christian thought, an ante-Christian world-theory, namely, to effect a rehabilitation of the spirit of the heathen thought of Greece and Rome. At a later period the move- ment went still further, broke even with the history of phi- losophy, pushing it entirely aside even in its ancient form, and the "philosophical" century thought to display its strength in speaking disdainfully of the spiritual products of a Plato and an Aristotle, and in regarding as philosophers only third and fourth rate minds, such as Cicero, and in basing itself, in boundless self-sufficiency, purely and simply upon itself. It required all the pretension of the so-called philosophical century to accept men, such as Rousseau and Voltaire (who had in fact scarcely the faintest conception of solid philosophical thought-work), as the greatest philoso- phers of the world's history. From the history of thought, these men were unwilling to learn any thing, but solely from nature ; every one wanted to philosophize on his own responsibility ; every thing had to be entirely new ; the new era wished to owe nothing to the past, but contemptuously to tread it under foot ; and the reaction from this anti-historical, and hence unspiritual tendency, begins only quite late with Schelling. Now as the Christianly-moral world-theory has a thoroughly historical character, hence the history of this es- sentially naturalistic form of ethics admits of no possible organic incorporation into the history of Christian ethics ; it simply moves side by side with the Christian current, breaks, especially at a later period, disturbing, confusing, and perverting, into it, but is with only slight exception not a furthering element of its development. 40.] ERASMUS SPINOZA. 281 Erasmus, who enters the ethical field in several treatises,* does not as yet himself directly assail the Christianly-inoral consciousness, but only presents with prudent reserve the ethics of Plato and Cicero as very closely related to Christian ethics, and mingles faint Christian views with Grecian, and thereby reduces them to the level of Pelagianism. His as- saults on the moral abuses of the church are devoid of Chris- tian depth. Pomponatiw (of Padua and Bologna, ob. about 1525), f who, under the patronage of the Papal court, assailed the doctrine of personal immortality, professed, in point of ethics, to belong to the Stoic school, taught absolute deter- minism, and presented the Christian view only ambiguously along-side of the heathen. Lipsius, in the Netherlands (ob. > 1606) went still further in the exaltation of Stoicism, \ though his opinions received no very favorable commendation from his unbridled life and from his threefold change of faith Romish, Lutheran, Eeformed, and then Romish again. In all essential features belongs here also the Socinian ethics of Crell, which is in many respects kindred to the later Ration- alistic system, and presents (in a spirit of pure Pelagianism) Christian ethics simply as improved Aristotelian ethics, and prefers the latter to the ethics of the Old Testament. Agrippa of Nettesheim (of Cologne, ob. 1535), undermined, by a far-reaching skepticism, the certainty of all moral con- sciousness, and explained this consciousness simply by mere fortuitous habit and by fortuitously-adopted public man- ners ; I his magico-alchemistic superstitiousness forms the back-ground thereto. (Giordano Bruno, the forerunner of Spinoza, produced no system of ethics.) Less influential upon his own age than upon recent times, was the philosophy of Spinoza. His chief work, Ethica (1677), which appeared only after his death, constitutes al- most an entire philosophical, system, of which the ethical * Enchiridion militia christ. ; Motrimonii chrigt. institt. ; Institt. prin- cipis christ. ; and others. t Opp., Bas. 1567, 3 t. I ManuHuctio ad Stoicam philosophiam, 2d ed., 1610. Ethica Arietotelica, etc., Selenoburgi, s. a., 4to., later : Cosmopoli, 1681, 4to. ij De incertitudine et vanitate scientiarum, 1527 (?) then in Col., 1531. 282 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [40. part proper forms indeed the largest but not the most philo- sophical and important. This perspicuous arid mathemati- cally-exact treatise presents not so strictly a speculative devel- opment of the subject-matter as, rather, rational elucidations and proofs of assumed propositions, among which, however, some very important ones, which needed to be demonstrated, are presented merely as axioms not needing proof, or are dis- guised in definitions. That the Jewish, but also Judaism- rejecting, philosopher should feel himself obliged also to ignore the history of the human spirit in general, was nat- urally to be expected ; his system (if we except the philosophy of Descartes, which had likewise but little connection with earlier philosophy, and whose monotheistical character Spi- noza assails) has no historical antecedents proper, but in fact begins anew the philosophical thought-work from the very beginning, and develops the Pantheistic world-theory so consequentially and undisguisedly as is nowhere else to be found. God, as the solely existing substance whose two at- tributes are thought and extension, has not a world different from and outside of himself, but is this world himself, as considered simply under a particular aspect. All particular being is only a mode of the existence of God ; and all these modes are conditioned by the absolute necessity of the divine life, and cannot be otherwise than as they really are ; all that is, is what, and as, it is, from necessity ; of every thing which is or takes place the principle holds absolutely good : omnia sunt ex necessitate natures divines determinata. Hence tins holds good equally also of man, who is likewise a particular mode of the being of God. When we say : " the human soul thinks something," this is the same as to say: "God thinks," not however in so far as God is infinite, but in so far as he con- stitutes the essence of the human spirit. Hence human thought is just as necessarily determined as is all being in general, and hence knows per se, and necessarily, the truth. Now, thinking has two phases : knowing and willing. Of willing the same holds good as of knowing, namely, it is ab- solutely determined in all its activity. Every will-act has a definite cause, by which it is absolutely determined. Will- ing can never contradict knowing, but is the immediate and necessary product of the same, an.d is, strictly speaking, 40.] SPINOZA. 283 identical therewith ; willing is affirming, and non-willing is denying. He who believes that he speaks, or keeps silent, or does any thing else, by free choice, dreams with open eyes. Men delude themselves into thinking that they are free in their volitions, only because they are not conscious of the cause which absolutely determines them ; all that takes place through the activity of the will is necessary, and therefore good. This doctrine renders the heart calm and makes us happy ; with it we have no longer any occasion for fear, for we know that every thing takes place according to the ever- lasting decree of God, with the same necessity as it follows from the idea of a triangle, that its three angles are equal to two right angles, teaches us to hate, to despise, to mock no one, teaches us unlimited contentment (ii, prop. 48, 49). All this is clear and consequential ; but how can the exist- ence of a moral consciousness be reconciled therewith ? How can any thing be morally required or done, if every thing takes place with unconditional necessity, and if will-freedom is only a false appearance ? That there can be no question of a moral command proper, of an "ought," Spinoza himself virtually admits, inasmuch as he declares it his purpose to speak of human actions just as if the matter in question were lines, surfaces, and solids (iii. prowm.) We are active in so far as any thing takes place within or without us, of which we are the perfect cause ; and the more we are act- ive, and the less we are passive, so much the more perfect are we. Even as all other things, so also the spirit strives to retain and to enlarge its reality ; its striving is its willing ; the end is not different from the cause from the unf ree- acting impulse of nature ; the passing-over to a higher real- ity awakens the feeling of pleasure ; the opposite, that of displeasure. Pleasure in connection with the consciousness of its cause, is love; the opposite is hate. For a real differ- ence between good and evil there is, in this world-theory, no place whatever. Neither good nor evil is a reality in things themselves, but both are simply subjective conceptions and notions, which we form by a comparison of things, and are hence only relative relations having their basis not in things but in ourselves, are only modes of oar thinking; for exam- ple, a particular piece of music is good for a melancholic CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 40. person, not good for a different one, and is of no significancy at all for a deaf one ; hence it is per se neither good nor bad, (iv, prcef.) Hence we cannot say in general that any thing at all is good per se ; it is only by comparing one thing with another higher entity, or with a notion formed by ourselves, that we find any thing to be good ; good and evil are only expressions of our subjective judgment as to that for or against which we have a desire or an aversion. Per se, how- ever, every thing is good, because necessary ; nothing is or transpires without God or against his will ; every thing is just as, according to eternal, divine destination and necessi- ty, it ought to be ; hence the notion of evil is only a limited and ungrounded manner of thinking on the part of our own understanding, is nothing on the part of God. Evil is in fact, even in our own conception, only a negative something, a privation ; but God knows no mere negative something, hence God knows absolutely nothing of evil (comp. the view of Erigena, 83), and hence there is in reality no such thing as evil ; for what God does not know does not exist, and outside of God's thinking there is no other thinking. Moreover, were evil or sin a real something, God would necessarily not only know it, but also be the cause of it, for God is the sub- stance and the cause of all that is ; and what is of God can- not be evil. Hence it is- only a false manner of looking at things, an imagination, when we find anything evil in the real world, false, in that we bring things into relation to ourselves, to our fortuitous feelings of pleasure and displeas- ure, instead of contemplating them in their own nature ; in and of itself, and hence in truth, every thing real is good and perfect. In all seemingly free action nothing else can take place than what results with necessity from the existing cir- cumstances of the acting subject. Even the stings of con- science are a self-deception, and are nothing other than a sadness or chagrin which we feel over some kind of a failure. Let it not be objected to this, that if men do every thing from necessity, and hence, also, sin from necessity, they can- not consequently be blamed therefor, but that all men would then be necessarily happy. On the contrary, man can be without guilt, and, notwithstanding that, be also devoid of happiness. The horse is not guilty for its not being man, 40.] SPINOZA. 285 and nevertheless it still remains a horse ; and he who is bitten by a mad-dog is also not guilty therefor, and yet he goes mad ; he who is blind was in fact destined in the concatena- tion of beings to be blind and not seeing (Ep., 32, 34.) This is surely the most wonderful justification of the moral order of the universe which one could possibly fall upon ; for, in fact, whence can mad-dogs originate in an absolutely neces- sary and good world ? If every thing is necessary, and the entirely innocent can be made mad by mad-dogs, this is evi- dently a very bad sort of world-order. And we must ask : if all human thinking is the thinking of God himself, and is absolutely necessary, how is there in fact possible any man- ner of false thinking and imagining ? If men really regard evil as real, then this is, in fact, an error on the part of God himself, which our philosopher should endeavor to account for; but if there is no evil, then there is also no error, and the system thus entangles itself in its own meshes. And when Spinoza makes error to be just as necessary as truth (ii, prop., 35, 36), he still cannot evade this contradiction by declaring error to be merely relative, for a merely seeming error would yet in reality be the truth, and hence would not admit of the turn here taken by Spinoza. Hence so infers Spinoza all is good which is useful; and all is evil which hinders from a good (iv, def., 1, 2.) Hence virtue is the power or capacity of acting in conformity to our own nature ; virtus nihil aliud est, quam ex legibus proprice natures agere; hence every one must follow the necessity of his nature, and by it judge of good and evil. Hence sin is avoided for the simple reason that it is contrary to our nature ; but why sin is yet in fact committed, Spinoza needs not to answer, because sin in the proper sense of the word cannot be committed at all ; of sin there can be any question only in the State, and, there, it is disobedience to civil law (iv, 37, schol. 2). As reason can require nothing which would be against nature, hence it requires that each should strive for that which is useful to himself ; and useful is that which brings each to a higher reality. Hence morali- ty requires that each should love himself, should seek to preserve as much as possible his existence, and to bring it to higher perfection and reality ; and man is all the more 286 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [40. virtuous the more he seeks after that which is useful to him, (iv, prop. 18). As the essence of reason is knowledge, hence knowledge is the most useful of things, and the rational man holds nothing for truly useful save that which contributes to knowledge. Hence the highest good is the knowledge of God, and the highest virtue is the striving thereafter; and every man has the strength necessary thereto ; and as the body is directly connected with the spirit, and as the spirit is all the more vigorous the more vigorous the body is, hence it is useful and virtuou^ to make the body skillful. The good always awakens delight ; hence delight is per se necessarily good, and sadness necessarily evil, as well as whatever leads to sadness. Hence compassion is, for the rational man, evil and irrational ; true, it often inclines us to beneficence, but this we should do at any rate even without compassion, (this is the virtue of generositas) ; and the truly wise man knows indeed that nothing is or takes place in the world over which we could grieve ; moreover compassion easily leads astray to false acting (Efh. iv, 50). Also humility as including a feeling of sadness is not a virtue, and springs not from reason, but from error, inasmuch as in it man recog- nizes himself as, in some respect, powerless, whereas, in vir- tue of the prevalence of universal necessity, he has all the power necessary to his destination (iv, 53). Repentance over committed sin is not only not virtuous, but it is irrational, be- cause it rests on the delusion of having done a free and, that too, evil action, whereas the action was in reality necessary, and hence good ; he who feels repentance is consequently doubly miserable. However, our moralist appears to shrink back from the practical consequences of this doctrine ; he declares it as very dangerous when the great masses are not kept in bounds by humility, repentance and fear (iii, 59, def. 27; iv, prop. 54), an apprehension which is, of course, en- tirely inexplicable from the ground-principle of his system, and must be banished, as a mere "imagination," into the sphere of unreason ; for how can there be, in Spinoza's world, a dangerous populace to be curbed only by false no- tions, seeing that indeed every thing that takes place is abso- lutely a necessary divine act ? The notion that any thing is bad or evil is, according to Spinoza, per se already an evil ; 40.] SPINOZA. 287 if man is truly rational and has only correct ideas, then he can have no notion of evil at all, for it in fact does not exist ; whatever affects us as pain or suffering, is such only in vir- tue of an erroneous, confused conception, an "imagination;" if we have correct knowledge, then are we free from all pain ; the more we recognize all things as necessary, so much the less are we subject to suffering ; every painful state of the emotions disappears so soon as we form to ourselves a clear notion thereof. Hence, according to Spinoza, the sole evil is false conceptions, but how these could arise we are not in- formed. He who truly knows himself and his circumstances, has necessarily joy ; and as in all true knowing he also knows God, and as this knowing is attended with joy, hence he also loves God ; hence in the knowledge and love of God consists the highest joy. God himself, however, (conceived as the universe) is without states of emotion, without love or aver- sion. God can neither love nor hate, save in the love or hate of man himself ; and when any one who loves God de- sires to be loved in turn by God, he desires in fact that God should cease to be God. True, we may indeed speak of God's love, but not in such a manner as that God as a per- sonal spirit should love man, but only that God loves in our love ; God loves not me but God loves himself, namely, in that I love Him. Spinoza's ethics appears at once as very widely different from all preceding ethics ; its essential characteristic is, un- historicalness. Greek philosophy, and also scholasticism, are the fruit of a long and vigorous development of an historical current of human thought, presuppose an already historical moral consciousness, for which they aim to create a scientific form. Spinoza's ethics sprang, in no sense whatever, from the spirit of an historical people, has no historical antece- dents, no historical consecration, and hence wears in its lofty, reality-spurning bearing, also the character of historical im- possibility. Plato's idealistic state is historically possible on a Greek basis ; Spinoza's ethics can absolutely never and nowhere be the expression of the moral consciousness of a people, can be appropriated only as their isolated moral consciousness by single persons, who in proud selfishness imagine themselves far above the morally-religious conscious- 288 -CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [40. ness of the masses, whereas in fact they owe the very possi- bility of their moral existence in society simply to this con- sciousness of the masses. Spinoza has learned nothing, whether from the philosophers of Greece, from the Middle Ages, from the religion of the Old Testament, or from Chris- tianity ; his ethical speculations are devoid of preparatory antecedents, are an absolutely revolutionary breaking-off from all historical spirit-development, base themselves purely upon individual thinking. His unimportant depend- ence on Descartes^is not in conflict therewith. If he had had even the slightest appreciation for the significance and the rights of history, he would have been required, on the very ground of his own system, to recognize the Christian world-theory as a highly important revelation of the alone- ruling God, and to regard history in general as a normal and necessary life-manifestation of God. Whereas in fact he turns himself contemptuously away from all history- of thought, as if God had come to true self-consciousness alone and sole- ly in himself. He does not free himself in any sense from the contradiction of declaring, on the one hand, all reality as necessary and good, and all evil as mere appearance, and of regarding on the other hand, all previously-existing spiritual reality as absolutely wrong, senseless, and irrational. Plato and Aristotle, for the reason that they stand more within the current of histo'ry, stand also far nearer the Chris- tian consciousness than Spinoza. In his wide-reaching antith- esis to the real essence of spirit, which is in fact necessarily history, he is the father of the Naturalism of more recent times. Only the unf ree, the nature-entity, is real ; the free, the spiritual, and hence also the moral, in general has no ex- istence whatever. Though indeed he contrasts thought and extension in space, as being of different nature, yet this thinking is in fact not free and spiritual, but bears absolute- ly a nature-character, has not ends before it, but simply presents manifestations of a necessary ground ; so in the case of God, so in the case of man. Ethics is therefore degraded to a mere describing of necessary nature-phenomena; and where it falls into the tone of moral exhortation in view of rational ends, then this is to be understood either in a mere- ly improper sense, and is indulged in simply in view of the 40.] SPINOZA. 289 unwise multitude, or it comes into irreconcilable contradic- tion with the ground-thought of the system. The Jew contin- ues a Jew, in this Christian age, only through hatred against history, which has in fact pronounced his condemnation ; he is either the petrified guest in the midst of living society, or the insolently mocking despiser of all historical reality, utterly devoid of reverence and respect for the historical spirit, a champion of the wildest radicalism. Spinoza, breaking loose from the petrified form of Talmudic Juda- ism, stands entirely isolated in the worle^ of the historical spirit; he can find for himself no proper place in this world, makes only an attempt to build up an entirely new world out of himself. The same self-delusion which prevails throughout post-Christian Judaism, namely, in that it dreams of still having an historical character, whereas it has in fact sunk utterly into mere lifeless matter, is also potent in Spi- noza. He dreams of creating a system of ethics, whereas it proves to be really nothing else than the theoretical describ- ing of a moral instinct devoid of a rational end. Where the "must" dominates, there all "should" and "would" cease. In sharp contrast to the pure idealistic Pantheism of Erigena, who really recognizes only God and not the world, and who, like the Indians, finds evil only in the distinguishing of the worldly and finite from God, Spinoza holds in fact fast to the reality and divinity of the finite, merges God into the world, and regards the real, simply as it is, in its isolated separateness, as good and perfect. The Pantheism of Erige- na leads to an ascetic turning-away from the world ; that of Spinoza, to a contented and absolutely satisfied merging of self into the world; and the "akosmism" which Hegel thinks he discovers in Spinoza is not to be found in him, but rather in the nobler and far more spiritual John Scotus Erigena. Spinoza exerted in his own age but little influence. Not- withstanding the deep spiritually-moral declension of that 'dark period, the religious God-consciousness was as yet too vital to fall in with this naturalistic Pantheism ; and the re- quirement to recognize all reality as necessary and good, could find little response at a time of profound disorganiza- tion and far-reaching material, misfortune in Germany. It 290 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [40. was reserved for a later age, when a wide-spread irreligious sentiment was attempting to create for itself a scientific jus- tification, to emphasize the doctrine of Spinoza not merely in its undeniable (though yet not to be overestimated) philo- sophical significancy, but also to attempt to exalt it to a religious character, nay, even to a pretended transfiguration of Christianity, and "to offer a lock to the manes of the holy Spinoza" (Schleierni., Reden; 2 ed.. p. 68). That from this doctrine there could arise for the moral life itself only a perverting influence, needs for the unpreju- diced mind no proof. The letting of one's self alone in his immediate naturalness and reality, is here even lauded as wisdom ; repentance and sanctification within, and sanctify- ing activity without, become folly, because no one has either the right or the ability initiatively to interfere with the eternally necessary course of things. That Spinoza him- self was an upright man, proves nothing in favor of his system; the weight of custom and the natural moral senti- ments are often stronger than a perverse theory ; nor is, in fact, mere uprightness in our social relations the full mani- festation of the moral. Leibnitz, though also stimulated by Descartes, but op- posed to Spinoza in his fundamental thoughts, and more imbued with an historical spirit, and standing in closer con- nection with the results of precedent spiritual development, did not produce a system of ethics proper, though he broke the way for the development of such. Though highly re- specting the Christian consciousness, he yet had no very deep appreciation for the same, and hence his thoughts in relation to religion and morality are of a somewhat external character. He is unable to comprehend evil in the purely spiritual sphere, but seeks for its roots, beyond this sphere, in the essence of the creature as such. God as the absolutely per- fect rational spirit has indeed realized, among all possible conceptions of a world, the best one ; but as the world does not contain the fullness of all perfection, which in fact exists in God alone, nor yet all possible perfections, as in fact all that is possible has not become real, hence there lies in the conception even of the best world still at the same time the necessity of a certain imperfection, without which a World is 40.] LEIBNITZ. 291 in fact not conceivable, and which consequently belongs to the essence of the world as such, and is a malum metaphysi- cum ; this is, however, not per se a reality, but only a non- being, a limit. The reality of the morally evil is fortuitous, is the fault of man ; only the possibility of it is necessary. In his popularly- written work " Theodicee" (1710), he further develops this thought, although elucidatorily rather than scientifically. Though Leibnitz recognizes the freedom of the will and the guilt of man in relation to sin, still he does not sufficiently deeply conceive of this guilt, and above all of the significancy and workings of sin as an historical world- power, otherwise he would have constructed his theory quite differently. He constantly seeks the roots of evil elsewhere than in committed sin. The naturalistic determinism of Spinoza, however, he utterly rejects; to the free personal God, corresponds the freedom of the rational creature. The rational man never acts from mere fortuitous fancies, but only from rational grounds. But this moral necessity does not interfere with liberty, because the possibility of irrational determinations still remains. Leibnitz conceives of ethics essentially as the doctrine of right, inasmuch as moral duty is a right of God upon us. Right, in the wide sense of the word, has three stages : mere right, which requires that we injure no one ; equitableness, which leaves and imparts to every one his own ; and piety, which fulfills the will of God and thereby preserves the harmony of the world. Hence faith in the personal, almighty and all- wise God is the found- ation of all right ; and the essence of piety is love to God, from which all other forms of love, constituting the essence of justness, receive their power. To love signifies to be re- joiced by the happiness of another, or to make that happi- ness one's own. The proper object of love is the beautiful, that is, that, the contemplation of which delights ; but God is the highest beautiful. Piety as the highest stage of right, creates also the highest moral communion the church which is destined to embrace entire humanity. The three forms of society, corresponding to the three stages of right, have also a threefold uniting-bond : mere power, and reverence, and conscience ; but also the first two receive their real character of right, only through the latter. Love to God leads us into 20 292 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 40. the way of the highest happiness, is in itself already the beginning of the same in the "this-side," and works a con- stant progress in perfection also in the "yon-side." * In an original spirit, and, in the moral sphere, almost in- dependently of Leibnitz, wrote Christian Wolf. He created a complete ethical systern.f His great reputation, and the authoritative character which he enjoyed with his contem- poraries, were, however, almost entirely overthrown in the Kantian period ; that over-estimation, as also the subsequent under-estimation, were equally unjust. A many-sided boldly- exploring spirit, and, though in many respects deceiving himself as to the scientific value of propositions which he uttered with the greatest confidence, and attempted to dem- onstrate in a not unfrequently stiff mathematical form, he yet attained to an extraordinary influence, because of the clearness and precision of his ideas, and of their manner of presentation, and gave rise, also in the sphere of ethics, to a very vigorous scientific movement ; and though his com- mendable effort to remain in harmony with Christian revela- tion was not by any means always realized, yet it helped to preserve for a long while in Germany, as in contrast to the frivolous hatred of Revelation prevalent in France and in England, a more earnest Christian and scientific spirit. Precisely in the field of morals Wolf was greatly influential toward the independent shaping of German science; and he broke off the excessive dependence, also of theological ethics, on Aristotle. While Wolf, in his decided, scientifi- cally-grounded recognition of the personal God whom he conceives of indeed rather merely, in his relation to the world, as Creator and Governor, and less, in relation to him- self, in his inner essence holds fast to the objectively- religious basis of ethics-, he yet at first view seems to en- *In various essays, especially fn the preface to Cod. juris diplom., 1693; Gubrauer: Leibnitz, 1842, i, p. 226 sqq. t Verniinft. Gedanken v. d. Metischen Tfvun n. Lassen (1720) ; more elaborate is : PMlosopMa moralis s. EtMca, methodo scientifico pertractata (1750), both works forming the first part of a whole which he presented in his PMlos. prac. univ. (1738), the second part of which embraces the doctrine of society or politics ; also in his Jus natures (1740) there is much ethical matter. 40.] WOLF. 293 danger the subjective foundation thereof, namely, the moral freedom of the will, by his determinism. Whatever takes place, also the seemingly fortuitous, has a sufficient ground, either in itself or in its connection with other things, and is in so far determined ; there takes place no change whatever which is not conditioned in the pecul- iarity of the concatenation of the universe, and determined by the antecedent circumstances thereof, just as a clock, set in motion for a whole year, is determined in each moment of its movement by this its first starting ; the world is just such an absolutely, determined clock-work, is a machine. Also in the freedom of the human will, every real determination has its sufficient ground, and is not arbitrary. This freedom consists in the possibility of choosing and doing the opposite of what we really do, but that the opposite possible should become real pre-supposes motives, and in so far as the motive is sufficient, this determination to realization is also condi- tioned by the motive. It is impossible that a person who knows something as better, should prefer to it the worse, and hence in such a case it is necessary that he should choose the better ; but the will is free in this nevertheless, as in fact man has the ground of his determination of will in himself. This sounds at once very questionable, and, as is well known, Wolf was, because of this doctrine, driven from the Prussian states, as politically dangerous. However, it is not to be overlooked that when man is considered as a rational creature per se irrespective of the already-existing depravity, his freedom is in faet not a groundless and irrational caprice, but is determined by rational knowledge, and that, for the really moral man in possession of correct' knowledge, there does in fact exist a moral necessity of following the rational. Hence Wolf's thought is not per se incorrect, but only too unguarded, and therefore liable to misunderstanding. As, however, Wolf expressly declares himself against determin- ism as held by Spinoza, and as he distinctly and repeatedly asserts the real, free will -determination of man, though in- deed not as irrational caprice,* we are consequently not at liberty to attribute to him the full determinism of Spinoza. The question as to whether, and in how far, our knowledge is * Introduction to the 2d ed. of his Moral. 294 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 40. conditioned by and dependent on our moral nature, and hence as to whether this knowledge is freely, or absolutely unfree- ly, determined, Wolf does not answer, but simply holds, that our willing is conditioned and determined by our knowl- edge ; and with him, as with Socrates, the essential point is simply to correct and disseminate knowledge, and then the corresponding moral action follows of itself with inner necessity. Hence we can explain the almost unbounded pretensions which the Wolfian ethics makes, and hence also the per se correct, but (in view of the actual condition of humanity) erroneous thought that ethics is not simply a sci- entific consciousness of the moral life, but also an essential motive to the moral life itself, that, properly understood, ethics is the source of virtue. This thought stands forth more or less clearly throughout Wolf's writings; practice follows theory of necessity. The moral life is like a mathe- matical question proposed for solution ; it is only necessary to have clear notions of virtue and vice and of duty, and then evil disappears of itself, and man becomes virtuous. "I have," says Wolf, (in the preface to his second edition), "not a little lightened the entire practice of the good and the avoidance of the evil, by the fact that I have shown that when one wishes to turn the will, it is just the same as when one disputes, namely, in that one has at all times in the one case, as in the other, simply to answer to one of the prem- ises of an inference; " and later (in the preface to the third edition) he says: "When my writings on world-wisdom and, among them, the present one on what men are to do and what not to do, appeared, those who are able to understand and judge of the matter for themselves, and who were not prepossessed by unfavorable prejudices, judged that thence- forth reason and virtue would become universal, and that every tody would strive, by this means, to attain to happiness of life." Wolf, however, expressly deprecates the miscon- ception, that in his ethics he ' ' ascribes too much to nature and leaves no room for grace; the doctrines taught by me," says he, "serve much rather to make clearly understood the difference between nature and grace, and especially the great help which the latter is to the former, so that consequently they are guides to grace ; " the Christian religion offers more 40.] WOLF. 295 than world-wisdom can do ; rather does man learn by this rational morality, that his natural powers do not suffice, and hence he perceives all the better the necessity and excellency of the grace which is offered to us in the Christian religion, and which supplies that which nature lacks. How it can be that the natural powers do not suffice, and how, on the pre- sumption of such a lack of strength, the philosophical ethics of "Wolf can yet be, independently, effectual in itself, we are not informed. Ethics has to do with the free actions of men as distin- guished from the necessary ones ; and freedom consists in the possibility of choice between several possible things. The condition of a man is perfect when his earlier and later conditions agree with each other, and all of them with the essence and nature of man. The free actions of man pro- mote or diminish this perfection, that is, they are either good or lad. When, therefore, actions are to be judged according to their moral worth, then we must inquire what change they bring about in the condition of our body or soul. Hence free actions become good or evil in virtue of their effect ; and as the effect follows from them necessarily and cannot fail, hence actions are good or evil in and of themselves, and are not made so simply by God's will ; hence if it were possible that there were no God, and that the present inter-depend- ence of things could exist without him, still the free actions of men would nevertheless remain good or evil. Here the per so correct ground-thought of the moral receives an ex- ternal and therefore misleading application, inasmuch as the result of our actions is dependent on other powers than these actions themselves ; only in an ideal and as yet not sin-per- verted condition of humanity, would such a judging of the moral worth of actions from their result, hold good, though even then it would be certainly more appropriate to deter- mine this worth from the essence of the action itself and not simply from its result. In this respect Wolf clings so fast to the merely-outward that he says : "Thus, he who is tempted to steal learns that stealing is wrong, because it is followed by the gallows." Equally one-sided is the con- trasting of the goodness per se of an action and of the will of God. The general maxim of ethics is therefore this: "Do 296 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [40. that which renders thee and thy condition, or that of others, more perfect ; avoid that which makes it more imperfect ; " this is a universal rule of nature. [This "or that of o'thers" is only thrust in, and is not at all derived from the ground- thought ; the dualism involved therein, and the possible con- tradiction, are in no manner reconciled.] The sufficient motive of the will is the knowledge of the good ; and it is impossible that one should not will a per se good action, when one only clearly comprehends it ; hence when we do not will it, it is for no other reason than that we do not comprehend it." Likewise is the knowledge of evil the motive of non- willing or aversion, and hence it is likewise impossible that one should will a per se evil action when one clearly under- stands it. Hence all moral willing and doing of the good or of the evil rests absolutely on our knowing or non-knowing. True, man can indeed act contrary to his conscience, but this takes place only when, because of special circumstances, he regards the good as evil, or the 'fevil as good, and hence, after all, from error. The ultimate end of all moral actions, and hence of our entire life, is the perfection of ourselves and of our condition, or happiness, which is consequently the highest good for man. Ethics proper, Wolf treats as the doctrine of duties. Duty is an action which conforms to law. Law is a rule to which we are bound to conform our free actions ; it is either a nat- ural, a divine, or a human law. Reason is the teacher of the law of nature ; this law fully embraces the whole moral life, and is, for this life, sufficient and absolutely valid and un- changeable, for it rests on the harmonizing of our actions with our nature. But as this our nature is established by the divine creative will, hence the law of nature is at the same time also a divine law, an expression of the divine will, though this will is not to be conceived of as an arbitrary one, so that, for example, God's will might declare the per se good for evil, and the per te evil for good. The duties are : (1) duties of man toward himself, and more specifically, toward his understanding, toward his will, toward his body, and the duty in regard to our outward condition (that is, our social position) ; (2) duties toward God, and more specifically, love to God, fear and reverence, trust, 40.] WOLF. . 297 prayer and thankfulness, and outward worship; (3) duties toward other men, and more specifically, toward friends and enemies, duties in regard to property, and duties in speech and in contracts. This general classification of duties became subsequently very usual. Upon ethics is based natural right, which treats of the allowable, as ethics proper treats of the obligatory; all rights rest on duties. The ground-thought of right is : thou mayest do whatever sustains and promotes the perfection of thy own condition and that of the condition of others, and, thou mayest do nothing which is contrary thereto. In- the further application of right to society, and hence as politics, the welfare of society is the norm of action. Wolfian ethics has manifestly, both in form and in contents, great defects. In respect to form, it may be reproached with a manifold commingling of empirical maxims with specula- tion ; notions derived from experience are often simply ana- lyzed and then used as bases for further inferences, and that, too, with the pretension of philosophical validity ; also there is abundant philosophical dogmatism, inasmuch as the thoughts are very frequently not really developed in regular process from the ground-thought, but are only associated and joined with it. In respect to matter, there prevails through- out this ethics, despite all its monotheistic presuppositions, a naturalistic tendency; Wolf knows only the immediate natural existence of the moral spirit, but not the history thereof, that is, the life proper of the same. His ethics has a history of the spirit neither as its presupposition nor as its goal ; there is created by the moral activity not a moral his- tory of humanity, but only a state of the individual. Hence the question as to whether indeed the actual nature of man is not already in some respects a product of such a moral history of humanity, whether or not it is a pure unchanged original nature, falls outside of this circle of thought, and in fact remained unheeded by philosophical ethics, and hence also to a large degree by theological ethics, throughout the eighteenth and a part of the nineteenth century ; and in this respect Wolf was, in fact, the forerunner of the modern Rationalistic school. And what he says of sinfulness, of divine grace and of Christianity, by way of guarding against this naturalistic ground-tendency, is rather mere personal 298 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 40. good-will than a consequential result of his system. All real interest is directed here to the sufficient reason, and not to the end ; there is lacking to morality and to history the vital heart-blood of free spiritual productive creation. Chris- tianity can be, to this world-theory, at best only a higher revelation of the truth, a furthering of knowledge, but not an historical history-creating fact. Hence in the further theological development of this stand-point, Christianity constantly sunk more and more to a mere revealed system of morals, which, however, contained and could contain nothing other than the Wolfian doctrine itself. Positive contents proper, Wolf does not really give to the moral law ; he does not rise beyond mere formal definitions. What the good is, in and of itself, we are not informed ; we learn only that it stands in harmony with reason and makes us happy ; hence it is embraced only in its relations to something else, but not in its inner contents. In the spirit of Wolf, though with some independence, Cans labored further, in Tubingen ; his Discipline morales omnes, 1739, is an able survey of the entire ethical field as then known ; more theological is his Instruction in the Duties of Christians, (1745, 4to., presenting ethics as "duty-impos- ing God-acquaintance " and prefacing the doctrine of duties simply by an essay on the four chief springs of all human action and omission, namely, the flesh, nature, reason, and the gracious workings of the Holy Spirit). Alexander Baum- garten (a brother of the noted theologian) perfected, in his PhilosopTiia ethica (1740, 1751), the Wolfian ethics, especially in formal respects ; he places our duties toward Ged (as those which condition all the others) at the head. G. F. Meier of Halle wrote, on the basis of Baumgarten's book, a fuller and more popular work : Philosophical Ethics (1753). (The volu- minous and superficial Eberhard appears in his Ethics of Rea- fnn (1781) merely as a feeble, barren imitator of Wolf.) Nearly contemporaneously with Wolf, had Thomasius (of Leipzig and Halle) presented ethics from the stand-point of u. ere common sense in a very popular form,* offering indeed * Von der Kunst verniinftig. u. tugenhaft zu LIEBBN, etc., 1710 ; Von der Artzenei wider die unvernunftige Liebe, 1704 ; comp. Fiilleborn : Betir. z. Gesch. d. "Phil, 1791, iv. 40.] CRUSIUS. 299 many good observations, but containing neither precision of thought nor a really scientific development. He places Christian ethics higher than philosophical, but conceives of the former very superficially; Aristotle and the schoolmen he despises and combats without understanding them. The essence of virtue is love, or the desire naturally inherent in man to unite himself to, and to remain in union with, that which the understanding recognizes as good ; in this love lies blessedness, that is, repose of soul and absence of pain, as the highest good ; love is irrational when it aims at vain, transitory, and hurtful things, or when it is too violent, or wills the impossible ; from such love spring all the vices. General love to man, as the essence of morality, embraces five chief virtues: sociableness, truthfulness, modesty, forbear- ance, patience ; self-love should rest only on love to man. The necessity of revelation, Thomasius recognizes ; philoso- phy does not supply its place, but leads to it, in that it leads to self-acquaintance. Clear-headedly and with deep Christian knowledge, Chris- tian August Crusius (of Leipzig, ob. 1776) opposed the Wolfian philosophy, but was abler in criticizing than in creating, and hence of more limited influence than Wolf, ("Directions for Living Rationally,"* etc., 1744; third edition, 1767). He declares himself very definitely against the determinism of Wolf ; the human will is not absolutely determined by its knowledge, but remains, in relation thereto, free, and can act contrarily thereto ; he appeals in proof thereof to the per- fectly unambiguous evidence of consciousness, and to the full responsibility of man for his sins. The determinations of the will are indeed, as rational, not arbitrary and fortuitous, but have, on the contrary, a sufficient reason ; but this reason ifl by no means a necessarily-determining one, but the will has always the possibility of acting contrarily even to a suffi- cient reason ; and Crusius goes, in this respect, so far as to find perfect freedom only in holding that the will can deter- mine itself as easily for the one course as for the other. All duties he considers as contained in our duty toward God, and hence he does not co-ordinate, but subordinates, them to this duty. Moral effort has indeed happiness and perfection for * Anweisutig vernilnftig zu leben. 800 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [40. its goal, but it has its law in the divine will, which likewise aims thereat. Man's relation of dependence to his Creator directs him to make his entire life dependent on the holy will of God; our striving toward the rational God-willed goal, becomes truly moral only when it is the expression of loving obedience to the revealed divine will. Hence it is incorrect that the good is good per se even without reference to God's will ; rather is it good simply because God wills it, though this divine willing is not irrational caprice, but a morally necessary act of his holy essence. Hence morality rests in its very essence on religion ; and the moral law may not, as in Wolf's system, stand apart from the religious conscious- ness, but requires a free God-obeying course of acting answer- ing to the divine will, and therefore also to the end of the perfection of the creature. A natural, though not absolutely sufficing manifestation of the divine will, is given in the con- science, which, however, does not, as with Wolf, simply form a theoretical judgment, but contains also at the same time a feeling of joy or anguish, and hence an impulse. Crusius separates prudence from the doctrine of morality proper, .as the ability of finding, for rational ends, also the special ap- propriate means. A more popular presentation of this view is contained in the so-long-esteemed, widely-read, and influ- ential "Moral Lectures"* of Gellert (1770), which, however, are estimable more for their noble sentiments and warmth of feeling than for depth of thought; and which, in their rhetorically verbose and often dull and tedious manner could have made so great an impression only in an age which had lost all taste for strong food ; discursive discussions on "the utility of health," etc., were then regarded as interesting reading. Gellert addresses himself more to the feelings than to the cognizing understanding, but the former are not embraced in Christian depth, but rather as mere feeble senti- mentality. Since the middle of this century the taste for really philo- sophical thinking had been declining in Germany, in the pre- cise measure in which the pretension to the name of ' ' philo- sophical century " was put forward ; instead of a spiritually- vigorous, constantly-progressing development of thought, we * Moralische V&rleaungen. 41.] ENGLISH ETHICS. 301 find, for the most part, only a self-complacent superficial criticising tendency and arbitrarily-brought-together, un- grounded assertions and observations, derived more from outward experience than from reason, and often delighting in rhetorical bombast. The voluminous Feder of Gottingen (Pralct. Philos., 1776; Unters. ub. d. menschlichen Willen, 1779-85), reminds indeed often of Wolf by his pedantic minuteness, but not by depth of thought ; and he bases him- self in the main on the empiricism of Locke. Game, who Avas highly esteemed by his contemporaries, derived the most of his matter from the English moralists, and limited his own moral thoughts to annotations on other writers (Cicero), and to disconnected but clear and elegantly written, though neither profound nor ingenious, dissertations. SECTION XLI. In England and France an anti-Christian tendency gave rise to a progressively-degenerating moralism, which, resting on an idealess empiricism, and, though vigorously resisted, yet maintaining a rising influence for a long time, based itself in part on a superficial deism, but also in part, and more consequentially, advanced to pure atheism and materialism, and ex- alted into a moral law the lowest form of Epicurean self-seeking. But it was especially reserved to the French mind to draw the ultimate consequences of these premises, and to seek in the wildest demoral- ization the highest civilization and "philosophy," and, through a destruction-loving dissolution of all moral consciousness in the higher classes (a dissolu- tion which swept over devastatingly into the un- German circles of the German literary world) to prepare the way for that general convulsion in Europe which at length attained, only through horrors and anarchy, to some presence of mind and to some degree of calm. English moralism lingered 302 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [41. iD general in a state of capricious wavering between the principle of happiness and the principle of spirit- ual perfection, between the principle of subjective eudemonism arid the principle of objective spiritual- ism. The reaction of this freethinking on Germany shows itself mostly in the superficial utilitarian morality of the period of self-styled " illuminisrn" Quite otherwise than in Germany was philosophical ethics shaped in England and France. While in Germany, notwith- standing the deep spiritual and moral disorder consequent upon the Thirty Years' war, there prevailed, for a long while still, a predominantly Christian spirit, (which remained proof against the Spinozistic Pantheism, and sought to de- velop philosophy in harmony with Christianity, and only gradually and at a late hour was enervated by French free- thinking through the un-German culture of the higher classes), in England the religious contests had resulted in a deep spiritual laxity and in a growing aversion to Christianity and to the spiritual in general. The unspiritual empiricism of Bacon and Locke seconded this superficial empirical turn- ing-away to the immediately visible and prosaic reality of the world. At first it was regarded as a progress to disregard the doctrinal contents of Christianity and to insist only on its morals; then it followed very naturally that this morality, as divorced from its doctrinal basis, should be divorced also from its historical presuppositions in general, and be derived only from the consciousness of the natural man, and that re- ligion in general, as in contrast to the Christian religion, should be conceived simply as a system of moralism, over which then, not as a foundation but as a protecting super- structure, a superficial deism was constructed; or, indeed, this tendency was followed out further, and men rejected also this deism, and contented themselves with the superficial morality of individual self-love ; and it must be regarded as a real progress (as in contrast to this spiritual superficiality), when clearer thinkers skeptically undermined also this pre- tended natural religion and natural morality, and insisted on the vanity of all human knowledge. 41.] BACON LOCKE. 303 Bacon of Verulam, though not himself constructing an ethical system, opened, by his empiricism (which opposed all previous philosophy, and according to which, there is abso- lutely no knowledge h priori, but only such as springs from immediate and primarily sensuous experience), a current of thought which was dangerous to the Christian world-theory, although he himself did not in the least oppose the Chris- tian consciousness, but rather placed Christian faith above all philosophical knowledge. However, he was not clearly conscious of the tendency of his fundamental thoughts. On this basis, Locke (ob. 1704) subsequently developed a system of philosophy which attained, especially in England, to a wide-reaching influence, but which is in fact, properly speak- ing, the very opposite of all speculation. True knowledge arises only from the experience of our sensuous existence ; general notions are not the first but the last ; the human mind per se has and produces neither notions nor ideas, but is rather a tabula rasa upon which the experience of the object- ive world first writes its characters ; and it is only through impressions from objective existence that the spirit attains, through abstraction, comparison, and analysis, to ideas. Out of this empiricism, however harmless and pretentionless it might seem at first examination, was destined logically to result a system of religion and morality essentially different from the Christian world-theory ; and historical facts realized this logical sequence. It sweeps away, in fact, at a single blow all ideal contents of the scientific and religious con- sciousness, in so far as these lie outside of sensuous experi- ence. But experience furnishes not ideas, but only impres- sions ; and at furthest one attains only to abstracted notions, which, however, have no general and unconditional validity ; for the ideas of the divine and eternal, there is no place. But man must have something ideal ; if he has it not in and above himself, so that he has simply to accept it in his ra- tional self-consciousness and in religious faith, then he must have it before himself, must practically and productively create it, in action ; the ideal is indeed not yet real, but it is to become so. It is consequently, at least, a presentiment of reason which turned this idealess empiricism toward ethics. But precisely this one-sided moralism shows most evidently, 304: CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [41. the incorrectness of the ground-principles ; an idealess mo- rality sinks at once to a morality of the most ignoble self- seeking and materialism. A moral consciousness is, accord- ing to this system, derived only from direct experience ; what is good I know only from the fact that it makes upon me a pleasant impression, affects me, as a particular individual, with the feeling of pleasure ; individual happiness becomes the measure of the moral, and thus Epicureanism has again attained to validity. Already before "the more complete development of the Baconian empiricism by Locke, Thomas Hobbes had drawn the natural and clear consequences of the same.* Only what we experience is true ; but we can experience only through the senses, and hence only the sensuous ; only this is true and real, even in man himself. Human action has not a purpose, for a purpose is a mere idea without reality, but only a ground, namely, in his sensuously-material reality, and, in virtue of this ground, it is also fully determined ; hence the moral law -is in no respect different from the law of nature. Good or evil is the agreeable or disagreeable state of the individual person, and hence is determined by our immediate feelings, and has in no sense a general significancy beyond the indi- vidual being; what is good for me is not so for another; hence, in regard to the good there can be no general decision ; every one determines this according to his feelings and ex- perience ; every one strives, and rightly too, to have the most possible feelings of pleasure, and in this he is rational and moral. Self-love in this sense, namely, of referring every thing to one's own enjoyment of the agreeable, is the highest moral law ; each has a right to all. From this it follows, in- deed, that through mere morality no harmonious life of men in common is possible, but that, on the contrary, all strive against each other, a war of all against all; but this leads not to a proof of the unreality of the moral law, but only to the necessity of the State; but also the state, because of the lack of a universally-valid objective norm of morality, can rest only on the individual will of the strong. The unlimited despotism of a single person is alone capable of bringing * Especially in Ms Leviathan, 1651, and in his De cive. 1647; comp. Lechler : Gesch. de engl. Deismw, 1841, p. 67 sqq. , 41.] HOBBES CUMBERLAND. 305 order and harmony into the chaos of individual strivings; and all individuals must submit themselves unconditionally to the will of this ruler, a will which knows no other law than its own pleasure, and which consequently is alwaya right, let the ruler decree what he will, and which is for all the citizens of that state the unassailable law and conscience, aud which has consequently to determine what shall consti- tute right and morality. Also all religion in the state de- pends exclusively on the will of the ruler ; and he alone has to determine what shall be believed and not believed ; no one has a right, in the state, to hold any thing else for good and true in the moral and religious sphere, than what the king declares as good and true ; sin is only a contradiction to the king's will. Whatever is not by him prescribed or forbidden, is morally indifferent. We cannot deny to this system full consequentiality, and the unabashed nakedness of the same is at least more honest than those more recent views, which seek to bemantle the very same ground-thoughts with more moral forms and disguises. In express antagonism to this materialism, Cumberland made general benevolence the principle of morality ; * but he rendered it difficult for himself to refute the consequential Hobbes, by the fact that he placed himself essentially upon the stand-point of sensuous experience, and undertook there- from to rise to higher religious and moral ideas. He attains thus to the principle which he makes the foundation of all morality, namely, that the striving for the common good of the entire system of rational creatures leads to the good of all the single parts of the same, whereof our own happiness constitutes a portion. Hence the chief end of moral effort is not one's own but the general good, although the former is contained in the latter. This moral law, to the observ- ance of which man is obligated by nature itself, is especially seconded by religion, and sanctified by the will of pod, as Lawgiver, who associates with the law rewards and punish- ments. But the idea of God is not already pre-supposed in the moral consciousness, but this idea pre-supposes this con- sciousness. Hobbes was opposed from a stand-point diamet- rically opposed to this, and related to that of Plato, and * D6 legibus naturae, 1672, 83, 94. 306 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 41. hence also more effectually and consequentially, by Citdicorth,* who entirely rejected the empirical basis of the moral, and appealed to original moral ideas given in reason itself. He assails materialism and atheism in a learned and ingenious manner, and declares the moral ideas which transcend all experience, and which can never be adequately explained by experience, as a seH-revelation of God himself, impressed upon finite reason; and in his opposition to empiricism, he goes so far as to hold that the moral idea stands even above the will of God, so that this will does not determine the good, but is determined by the per se valid idea of the good as existing in God. A complete moral system Cudworth did not carry out ; and his influence was less extensive, because of the prevalent tendency of the English mind toward empirical reality, than it deserved to be. Basing himself upon Cud- worth's theory, Henry More presented a brief but compre- hensive treatise on philosophical ethics, t (The end of mo- rality is the perfection, and therefore the happiness, of man, which rests essentially on virtue ; sensuousness has no right in itself, but stands under the dominion of moral reason ; the antecedent condition of morality is the freedom of the will, as itself not determined by any thing, not even by knowl- edge.) In a similar spirit, Samuel Clarice (1708) insisted on the view, that creatures are for each other. Morality con- sists in conducting one's self, by virtue of free rationality, in harmony with the universe, and in the proper relation to one's self and to the rest of the world, even as irrational creatures do from inner impulse. This relation cannot be arbitrarily fixed by man, but is fixed by the nature itself of things, and man is morally to conform himself to this rela- tion ; thereby he realizes his happiness. Locke endeavored to avoid the inferences which Hobbes had drawn from the ground-thought of empiricism, at least in the moral sphere. J Inborn moral ideas, or ideas that lie in the essence of reason itself and in the conscience, do not exist ; all moral laws are derived simply from the observation of real life, are inferred from the benefit which certain * Sygtema intelleetvale, etc., in English in 1678. f Enchiridion ethicvm, in his Opp. omn., 1670, 2 fol. J Essay on the Human Understanding, 1690. 41.] LOCKE. 307 modes of action have for the well-being of the actor or of others, and hence may, under different circumstances, be very different ; and the actual differences, nay, even contra- dictions, of moral views that do exist, prove that these views do not lie in reason itself. It is only through education and dominant custom that moral opinions rise into pretended fixed moral principles, into laws of conscience ; there is no innate primitive conscience ; the approval or disapproval of a particular organized society is the sole sufficient measure of virtue and vice. Here, however, it is natural that such modes of action as are useful not merely to the subject him- self, but also to others and to the community, should also be regarded in general as praiseworthy, and hence virtuous, so that for a certain circle of actions, there may indeed be found an essential agreement of moral judgment, and hence a cer- tain natural law lying in the nature of the thing, which is to be regarded as also God's law. However, Locke derives this law not from the nature of the moral thought itself, but in fact, simply from public opinion, and hence from experience, and he rises only through inferences from facts of experience to more general notions, which, however, have by no means a validity absolutely and per se. Hence the moral idea does not transcend reality, does not so much say what should be, as rather what already is; a moral judgment upon the actual moral consciousness of a society is, according to Locke's theory, impossible ; for not the idea is the measure for reality, but reality is the measure for the ide-i. The question whether indeed the condition and the moral consciousness of society themselves might not be perverted and untrue, is entirely out of place, is indeed absurd, as it would assume to measure moral reality by an idea independent thereof ; the moral consciousness of society is always right. The limiting of these far-reaching assertions by the interposing of a super- ficially-conceived divine revelation is without any sufficient foundation in Locke's system. The Lockian view has in- deed, as compared with that of Hobbes, a somewhat more respectable tone, but it has on the other hand less inner con- sequentially. The thought of self-love, or, more properly, self-seeking, is at least intelligible and clear ; but the taking, as a basis, the judgment of society must be regarded as en- 21 308 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [41. tirely ungrounded, and is in reality utterly meaningless, in- asmuch as, in every society, moral views the very opposite of each other are represented, so that consequently the indi- vidual is, after all, referred to his own private judgment, which, as it rests upon no per se valid idea, can in fact be based only on the feeling of pleasure or displeasure. The consequences of this unspiritual ethics showed them- selves very soon. The position of Wollaston * is as yet moder- ate, but for that reason all the more indefinite and unclear. He reduces all religion to morality ; religion is only the obliga- tion to do the good and avoid the evil. The good is identical with the true ; every action is good which gives expression to a true proposition, that is, which actually recognizes that a thing is as it really is, and which hence corresponds to the na- ture or end of a thing ; things should be treated as being what they are. The destination of man himself is happiness ; but happiness is pleasure, the consciousness of something agree- able, of that which is in harmony with the nature of man ; hence true pleasure springs only from that which corresponds to the destination of man, and consequently to reason. Moral- ity or religion is, therefore, the seeking of happiness through the realizing of truth and of reason. The next advancement of this tendency consisted in this, that the thought of happi- ness was fixed more definitely in view. Man wills by his very nature to be happy, that is, he has inclinations the fulfillment of which renders him happy. These inclinations man does not give to himself, but he has them from nature, finds them in a definite form existing within himself ; they are the norms of man's actions, that is, he is good when he follows his natural inclinations. This advance to Epicurean ethics is made by the plausible and fashionable writer, Lord 8haftebury.^ Every action springs from an inner determinateness of the actor, from a proclivity or propensity ; hence the moral worth of an action lies essentially in this propensity ; the propensity aims at that which gives pleasure, and avoids that which gives displeasure ; that which by its presence gives pleasure, and by its absence displeasure, is good ; the opposite thereof is evil; as objects of effort, the former is the good, the latter the evil ; between these * The Religion of Nature Delineated, 1724. t Characteristic^, (1711), 1714; comp. Lechler, p. 240 aqq. 41.] LOCKE. 309 there lies the sphere of the indifferent. The decision as to good and evil is not arbitrary ; but that is good which corre- sponds to the peculiarity of a being, and, for that very reason, gives pleasure to the being experiencing it. Happiness is the greatest possible sum of satisfactions or experiences of pleas- ure ; spiritual pleasure-impressions stand higher, however, than the merely sensuous; and the generally-useful or benevolent propensities are, in turn, the better among the spiritual ones, for they duplicate the enjoyment by the participation of others ; and they do not stand in contradiction to our own personal good, because they relate to the whole of which we ourselves form a part. Hence true morality consists in the striving after the proper relation and harmony of the individual and of the whole ; the one is not to be merged into the other, for man is just as much an individual as he is a member of the whole, and self-love is per se just as legitimate as the propensity of general benevolence. Hence virtue consists in a rationally- calculated weighing out of the measure of the reciprocally lim- iting propensities, that is, in preserving a proper equilibrium. The decision in this case is given primarily by our innate feel- ing for good and evil, by the moral sense or instinct, not taken in the sense of a conscious thought, but of a feeling, a feeling of pleasure in the presence of the good, and of displeasure in the presence of the evil. This moral sense is developed by ex- ercise and reflection into a moral judgment. Virtue is indeed independent of religion, and even atheism does not directly endanger it ; but yet it receives its proper force and life only in the belief in a good, all-wise and justly-governing God. Shaftesbury endeavors to rise above the fortuitousness of the determination of the moral in Hobbes and Locke, and to attain to a per se valid determination of the same ; but after all, he also finds the deciding voice only in the fortuitous feeling of pleasure or displeasure ; his empiricism is essentially subjective. That, as differing from Locke, he regards the moral feeling as innate, does not yet guarantee its objective truth, and, at all events, the objection of Locke holds good against it, namely, the actually- existing diversity of moral views. But this moral feeling is not a moral idea ; it has no contents, but utters itself only in each separate case, when it is stimulated by an action or an ob- ject, even as a piano gives a note only when it is struck , other- 310 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [41. wise this feeling is silent and dead, whereas an idea is living and conscious even in the absence of any reality affecting it ; this subjective feeling itself is moreover incapable of being tested by a per se and absolutely valid idea. While Collins, the eulogist of Epicurus, a disciple and friend of Locke, and the first who called himself Freethinker, denied the freedom of the will and regarded human action as abso- lutely determined by the influences surrounding us, Hutcheson (of Glasgow) endeavored to rectify the moral system of Shnftes- bury by assuming good-will toAvard others, in contradistinction to self-love, as the contents proper of the innate moral sense. To the purely empirical foundation of ethics, however, he held fast in his " System of Moral Philosophy " (1755). We find that certain actions in men, even when these men are not affected by the consequences of the same, meet with approbation or disap- probation; from this it follows that the ground of this judg- ment is not personal advantage or disadvantage, but a natural moral sense, which perceives the moral irrespective of personal interest, and has therein pleasure, and which therefore also, equal- ly disinterestedly, impels to moral action. This inborn moral sense is not a conscious idea, but an immediate feeling which differs from the interested self-feeling, just as we have an im- mediate pleasure in a beautiful, regular form, without being conscious of the mathematical laws thereof, or having any benefit therefrom. The moral approbation and striving are con- sequently also all the purer the less our personal interest is in- volved in the case. The selfish and the benevolent propensi- ties mutually exclude each other, for benevolence begins only where personal interest ceases. Therefore we have to make our choice between the two propensities, and as the benevolent one is the purer, hence the moral proper consists exclusively in it. Virtue is not practiced for the sake of a benefit or an en- joyment, but purely out of inner pleasure in it; our nature lias an inner innate tendency to promote the welfare of others with- out having any regard therein to personal benefit. This benev- olence toward others is the essence of all the virtues ; for even our care for our own welfare is exercised in order to pre- serve ourselves for the good of others ; the degree of virtue rises in proportion to the happiness procured for others, and to the number of persons benefited by us. The preliminarily- 41.] SMITH HUME. 311 ignored moral relation of man to God, Hutcheson afterward brings not without violence into his system, by holding that the moral sense leads also to the union of the moral creature with the Author of all perfection. The fundamental thoughts of this ethical system are indeed well meant, but they are sci- entifically weak and arbitrary ; from the Christian view they are far remote, for the self-complacent mirroring of self in the pretendedly pure virtuousness of one's own benevolent heart, and the easy contenting of self in a certain circle of benevolent outward actions, are, in one direction, quite as dangerous for correct self-knowledge, as is the system of pure self-seeking in the other. A related system, but one manifoldly complicated in unclear originality, was developed by Adam Smith (1759, and later). He emphasized, more strongly still, the element of feeling for others in the innate moral sense, and conceived of it as the feeling of sympathy, in virtue of which we share in nat- ural participation in the joy and in the pains of others, and strive for the participation and harmony of others with our own feelings and actions ; in this harmony we find the good, and in the opposite the evil. The morality of our action we recognize by the fact that it is adapted to awaken the sympa- thies of others; a perfectly isolated man could not possibly have a moral judgment as to himself, because he would lack the criterion, the mirror. Hence man must always so act that others not standing in the same fortuitous relations, that is, impartial persons, can sympathize with him. The obscure con- viction that the moral consciousness must rest on a per se valid idea, brings the empiric to this strange and certainly very diffi- cult and inadequate procedure, which, however, though ex- pressly intended to throw off the accidentality of individual being, yet cannot, after all, get rid of it. Also David Hume treats of the subject of ethics, thovjgh with less acumen than that wherewith, in the sphere of religion and of theoretical philosophy, he skeptically undermines the certainty of all knowledge.* While, in the field of philosophy, he ingeniously exposed the feeble superficiality of the preva- lent empiricism, he yet hesitated to- introduce his skepticism, with like consequentiality into the practical sphere of morals. A real science of the moral there cannot, be, in the opinion of * Treatise of Human Nature, 1730 ; Essays, etc., 1742. 312 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [41. Hume, seeing that the moral is not an object of the cognizing understanding, but only of mere feeling or sensation. The ultimate end of all action is happiness ; but that which renders happy can be determined only by sensation ; hence a sense, or tact, or feeling innate in all men, decides as to good a,nd evil, in that the good excites a pleasant, and the evil an unpleasant feeling. Hence we must learn by way of pure observation what actions violate, or answer to, the moral feeling ; and we find, now, that the useful excites moral approbation, and more particularly, that which is useful to the community. General and necessary moral ideas there are none ; and even the moral feeling is veiy different in different nations ; hence moral con- ceptions have always only a varying worth and rest essentially upon custom. The obligation to virtue rests on the fact that in virtue there is furnished the greatest guarantee for actual hap- piness ; and also the working for the good of others reacts in the end upon our own good. Thus Hume coincides essentially with Locke. That he regards suicide as allowable is easily explainable from his ground-thoughts. By means of a feeble and unfounded eclecticism, Adam Ferguson (of Edinburgh)* endeavors to avoid the one-sidedness of other moralists, but only involves himself in worse confusion. To the moral he gives three fundamental laws : the law of self-preservation, the law of community or society, and the " law of estimation," (the latter relating to the per se excellent), without reducing this threefoldness to any kind of clear unity, He attains to an unpredjudiced consideration of the moral in detail only at the expense of the consequentially of his system. The ultimate consequences of empiricism were not drawn by the systematic moralists, but by other so-called Freethinkers who wrote more for the general public. Such was the case especially with the most influential among them, Lord Boling- ~broke, the chief representative of deism (ob. lT51),t who de- clared Plato to be half crazy, and all philosophy proper to be mere narrow-mindedness. The moral law is, as the law of na- ture, clearly revealed to all men through the observation of existence. All morality rests on self-love ; this law incites 'to marriage, to the family, and to society, and to" the duties that result therefrom. The end of all effort is the greatest possible * Institutes of Moral Philosophy, 1769. t Works, 1754. 41.] BOLINGBROKE. 313 happiness, that is, the greatest possible number of pleasure- sensations. But this natural law teaches Bolingbroke some very strange things ; shamefulness, e. g., is only an aspiration of man to be something better than the brute, or it is a mere social prejudice; polygamy is not immoral; on the contrary, it harmonizes with the law of nature, because it effects a greater increase of the race ; wedlock-communion is disallowable only between parents and children ; all other degrees of relationship admit of it, for the highest law and end of marriage is propa- gation. The pretentious superficiality of this writer obtained for him in the " cultured " world the highest repute. English moralism checked itself, for the m< st part, at half- ways; it found as yet too much moral consciousness alive among the masses, not to feel bound in general to hold fast still to a respectable code of morality, even though at the cost of the consequentially of the system. In France, on the con- trary, the demoralization had made sufficient progress among the cultivated classes to be enabled to throw off all reserve, also in the sphere of theory. The scanty remnants of religious and moral contents still retained in the freethinking ethics of Englishmen, had to be thrown out, in the further fermenting process, as discoloring dregs, in order that the unmingled wisdom-beverage of the natural man might attain to its life- giving purity; deistic moralism had to pass over into atheistic materialism. The French ethics of frivolity became, also for German ears, a sweet-sounding music ; and French parasites at the little German ducal courts charged themselves with the task of distilling the decoction of trans-Rhenane moral notions also into the lower strata of the German population. Shaftesbury and Hutcheson had endeavored to secure the innate moral feeling- against the threatening overthrow of all morality, by placing over against the feeling for self, a feeling for the social whole, either as of 'like worth, or as of a still higher validity. This course was arbitrary, and not grounded in their fundamental principle ; for every man is, as an individ- ual, the nearest to himself. And a feeling inborn in me relates, after all, first and last, always to myself ; as a merely natural being inspired by no higher idea, I feel for others only in so far as I am myself interested in them. Feeling clings absolutely to the subject, and egotism is the inner essence of any natural 314 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [41. moral feeling which is not willing to be dominated by an idea. In order to this further development of ethics, there was need of a still further carrying out of empiricism as a theory. This we meet with in Condittac, a French, nobleman, an abbot and prince-educator, one of the most superficial and, therefore, most preferred authors of the middle of the eighteenth cen- tury. All knowledge rests on sensuous impressions; man is acted upon and filled with spiritual contents, simply as a ma- chine, through outward impressions ; of all the senses the sense of touch is the highest ; it alone gives us certainty as to the objective reality of things, and raises man above the brute. with whom in other respects he is essentially identical. The pleasure and displeasure of impressions work desire and repug- nance, and hence awaken and determine the will. It is incred- ible what stupid absurdities Condillac offers in the name of metaphysics ; and it is a significant index of the spirit of the age, that he was one of the most influential and feted writers of France. The ethics of this world-theory was easily inferred, and was pronounced with open boldness. Long previously Gassendi (of Paris, ob. 1655) had presented the satisfaction of desire as the end of human life ; this satisfying is rational when it is orderly, natural, and not excessive ; and it effects peace of heart and painlessness of bpdy. He recommended, consequen- tially enough, the doctrine of Epicurus as the highest wisdom. The full and clear consequence of empiricism, however, was drawn by Helvetius, who expressly based his doctrine on the, by him, highly esteemed theory of Locke. As an affluent gen- tleman of leisure, and living only for his pleasures, he became greatly renowned by his work, De Pesprit (1758), throughout the luxurious fashionable circles of Europe. His book was proscribed in France, but all the more circulated throughout Europe ; and the author, in his gravels to different courts, espe- cially the German ones, was feted as a great philosopher. His second more important work, (a further development of the first one,) De rhomme, appeared only after his death (1772). The highly-colored and daring tone of his writings, with their rich setting of wit, and of indelicate anecdotes, furnishes a clear image of the then prevalent spirit of the higher classes of cul- tivated Europe. All thoughts, according to Helvetius, spring from sensuous perceptions, and our knowledge extends only so 41.] FRENCH SENSUALISM. 315 far as the senses extend ; of any thing super-sensuous, and hence also of God, we know nothing. The motives to activity are essentially the passions, which spring from our inclination to pleasure and our aversion to displeasure. The fundamental stimulus of all moral activity is self-love, the expression of which is, in fact, the passions ; nothing great is accomplished without great passion ; he who is not passionate is stupid. As, now, all thoughts rest on sensuous impressions, so rest also all self-love and all passion, and hence all morality, on the impulses of sensuous pleasure ; and even the decision as to truth is en- tirely dependent on the interest of the self-loving subject. Should the case arise, says Helvetius, that it would be more ad- vantageous for me to regard the part as greater than the whole, then I would in fact assume this to be the case. The good, or the moral, is neither an absolutely valid idea, nor is it any thing arbitrarily assumed, but the determination as to it rests in the experience of the individual ; but experience teaches that each regards as good that which is useful to him ; and consequently each judges of the morality of actions simply according to his own interest ; hence the best actions would be such as corre- sponded to the interest of all men ; but there are no such ac- tions. Hence we must limit our view ; and, on closer exami- nation, we find to be truly good that which promotes the inter- est not merely of the individual but of our nation ; the political virtue is the highest, and the 'political transgression, the high- est sin ; that which does not contribute to the public good of the nation, as, for example, the so-called religious virtues, is not a virtue, and what does not conflict therewith is not a sin ; virtues which profit nothing must be regarded as virtues of delusion, and be discarded. Hence, true ethics has its norm essentially in the civil law-book and in public utility ; that which lies outside of these is, for the most part, morally indif- ferent ; when it is useful to the public weal, even inhumanity is just. The motive to moral activity remains, even in this^so narrowly limited sphere, self-love ; the thought of doing the good for the good's sake, is antiquated and exploded. To sacrifice my own private advantage to that of the public, I am under no obligation ; rather must I seek in the best manner pos- sible to combine the two. When any one helps an unfortunate, out of compassion, this is only self-love, for he simply aims to 316 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 41. rid himself of the sight of misery, which is unpleasant to him. Ethics is utterly fruitless and vain so long as it does not defi- nitely regard personal interest, and hence sensuous pleasure and the avoidance of sensuous pain, as the highest principle of morality ; nothing is forbidden but what causes us pain ; with religion, ethics has nothing whatever to do. Morality is there- fore also, at different times and under different relations, essen- tially different ; there is no crime which under some circum- stances (when it should be useful) would not also be right. True, the vicious man seeks also his own advantage, and the only trouble in the matter is that he deceives himself as to the means thereto ; hence, he is to be pitied because of his error, but not to be despised. The fact that among all nations, some actions are regarded as virtuous which offer no profit whatever for this life, is simply a hurtful delusion. As self-interest is the ground of all virtue, hence it is also entirely legitimate that the state should stimulate its citizens to obedience by rewards and punishments ; in fact, it thereby hits upon the solely cor- rect moral motives to the good ; rewards and punishments are the gods which create virtue. All statesmanship consists in awakening the self-love and self-interest of men, and in thereby stimulating them to virtue. The intellectual revolution represented by great names made sweeping advances in France and also in the fashion- able world servilely dependent on France, at the courts of the rest of Europe, and especially of Germany, and had al- ready long since reached its ultimate results, before the political revolution enabled also the lower classes to speak their word in the same sense. It was fashionable at this period to designate by the word "esprit" (as the privilege of the giddy, freethinking world) that which was subse- quently called "revolution" among the great masses, and which was, in fact, simply the consequence of the former. Every thing which hitherto had passed as philosophy, (with the exception of the Epicurean), was regarded as nonsense ; the most stupid superficiality, provided only that it ridiculed sacred things, passed as philosophy ; wit and frivolous fan- cies took the place of earnest science. The " philosophical " century sank, in the appreciation of really philosophical thought, deeper than even the earlier and as yet barbarous 41.] ROUSSEAU'S ETHICS. 317 Middle Ages had sunk. The higher the encomiums they heaped upon what they called "spirit," so much the more utter became the spiritual vacuity ; men extolled reason more pretentiously than ever, and yet they placed in her temple, as goddess, a public woman. Rousseau and Voltaire passed as the profoundest thinkers of all ages ; their spiritual tri- umphs and attainments were unparalleled, and Voltaire's re- nown transcended in glory all renown ever heaped upon an author. The history of the human mind has no second century to refer to in which un-reason dominated with such complete omnipotence. Jean Jacques Rousseau produced indeed no system of ethics, but he exerted in the sphere of moral opinion an influence such as no author before or after him ever exerted, and felt even up to the present day, not indeed because he uttered deep thoughts, but because he gave expression to what lay in the spirit of the age, himself an utterly un- genuine character under the form of a severe moralist undermining all morality, under the form of earnest thought bidding defiance to all philosophy and science, under the form of a censorious sage, in hermit-like seclusion from the world, preparing soft cushions for the vices of the "cultured " great. And precisely in this his peculiar character he chimed in with the tastes and desires of the age ; he simply made, in the dike of the as yet somewhat cramped current of the age, the little breach through which its pent-up waters dispersed themselves over the low-lands so as subsequently, as morasses, to exhale the pestilential miasma of revolution. Of scientific ground-thoughts there can in Rousseau be no question ; bold assertions and rhetorical phrases take almost every -where the place of scientific demonstration. The writings of Locke exerted upon him the greatest influence ; sensuous experience is also for him the source of all ideas. His moral views re- ceive their proper commentary in his utterly immoral life. His Ccmtrat social (1761) became the theoretical basis of the French Revolution; his narrow-minded sophistical work, Emile (1762) had an immeasurable and bewildering influence on education, and is yet to-day the catechism of all un-Chris- tian schemes of education. Rousseau's religion of nature, as he called it, is a shallow idealess deism grouped around the 318 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 41. three thoughts : God, virtue, and immortality, in high sound- ing rhetorical phrase. He bases morality upon the natural conscience, which, as a direct feeling for the moral, renders unnecessary all instruction and all science as to the moral, and guides man with unerring certainty. All immorality springs simply from "civilization," and from perverted edu- cation ; true education consists in non-educating. Let -the child be simply let alone in its naturalness ; let it be guarded against perverting influences, and then it will spontaneously develop, itself as normally as a tree in a good soil. In the nature of man there lies nothing evil whatever; all natural impulses are good; every child is by nature still just as good as the first man was in coming from the hands of the Creator. The sole inborn passion is self-love, and this is good. The child should learn every thing through per- sunal experience, and nothing through obedience ; the words "obey" and "command" must be erased from its diction- ary, as also the words- "duty" and obligation;" the child must by all means be kept in the belief that it is its own lord, and that its educator is subordinate to it. Make the child strong, and it will be good ; for all defects, the edu- cator alone is to blame. The sole moral instruction for the child is: "Do wrong to no one ; " of love and religion there should, in education, be no question whatever. Instruction should by no means be imparted before the twelfth year, and even after this period only at the desire of the pupil; at twelve years it should yet be incapable of distinguishing its right hand from its left. It should never believe or do any thing on the mere word of another, but must always do simply what it has found to be good from personal experi- ence. The end of this "inactive" method of education, as Rousseau himself designates it, is the end of human life, namely, freedom ; but true freedom consists in this, that we wish nothing other than what we can do or obtain ; and in this case we will also do nothing other than what pleases us ; and this is always the right. Hence the essence of .all mo- rality is the giving free scope to our natural propensities. The highest moral law is; "seek thine own highest welfare with the least possible detriment to others." Christianity is the natural enemy of true morality and of human society, for 41.] VOLTAIRE DIDEROT. 319 it desires the absolute purity of human nature, directs man away from the earthly, and preaches only servitude and tyranny. These were sweet words for the ears of the great multitude, and they did not die away unheeded, but found enthusiastic welcome. Although the almost apotheosized prince of the "philosophical" century, Voltaire, whose pre- tended philosophy rests almost exclusively on Locke, wrote both moral phrases and un-nioral poems, yet in neither case has he produced any thing peculiar or original, much less philosophical, notwithstanding his frequent allusion to his "metaphysics." Morality, he repeats time and again in the strongest affirmations, is entirely independent of religious faith, rests upon a natural innate impulse, and is conse- quently in all men and in all ages, so soon as they use t*heir reason, uniform and the same.* Virtue or vice, the morally good or evil, is always and every-where that which is either useful or hurtful to society; incest between father and daughter may, under circumstances, be allowable, and even a duty, as, for example, when a single family constitutes an isolated colony ; falsehoods uttered out of a good purpose are legitimate, and the same holds good of almost every thing that is in ordinary cases unallowable. Divinely-re- vealed moral laws there are none ; but a certain benevolence toward others is inborn in man, at the same time with self- love. To the objection, that with so uncertain a basis, one might seek his own welfare by stealing, robbing, etc., Vol- taire has the ready answer: then he would get hanged.f And all this he calls metaphysics. What little of a superficial religious consciousness had yet remained with Rousseau and Voltaire, entirely vanished with the Encyclopedists, and especially with Diderot (ob. 1784). Diderot endeavored, above all things, entirely to divorce morality from religion ; the latter is for the former rather a hindrance than a help. In morality itself he wavers, unde- cided, between naturalistic determinism and a very super- ficial society-morality. The Epicurean view he regards as the most true. All the vices spring from covetousness, and hence they can all be got rid of by the abolition of property, * (Euvres, Paris, 1830, t. 31, p. 262 ; t. 12, p. 160 ; t. 42, p. 583. t Ibid., t 37, p. 336 ; t. 38, p. 4.0. 320 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [41. by a community of goods ; for the discovery of this universal panacea of human ills, he- takes to himself great credit. Naturalistic morality appears in its most gross form and in shameless nakedness in La Mettrie (ob. 1751),* whom even Voltaire despised, but whom Frederick the Great, from some incomprehensible caprice, made his reader and daily com- panion (from 1748 on), and even nominated him, ignoramus that he was, to membership in the Academy of Sciences. Religion and morality stand in irreconcilable antagonism to philosophy ; they rest only in politics, and serve for the bridling of the masses who are yet unable to rise to philosophy, just as, for a similar reason, there is as yet need also of hang- man and death-penalties. But humanity as a whole cannot be happy until all the world embraces atheism. Religion has poisoned nature and cheated her out of her rights. Where the truth, that is, atheism, prevails, there man follows no other law than that of his particular natural propensity. And thus alone can he be happy. Man is not essentially dif- ferent from the brute, not even by any peculiar moral con- sciousness ; he stands in many respects below the brute, and has only this advantage, that he has a greater number of wants, whereby a greater culture becomes possible. Man as sprung from the mingling of different races of animals, and as formed from matter of the same kind as that constituting the brute, save only that it has simply gone through a higher fermentation-process, and as being of a merely material or- ganism (for the soul is only the brain, which is itself only a slightly organized piece of dirt), is simply a mere machine, and is set into motion by outward impressions, and hence he is necessarily determined in all his volitions, and is not re- sponsible for any of his actions. Repentance is folly; for individual man is not at fault for his being a poorly con- structed machine. Hence also we should not despise the seemingly vicious, nor judge them severely. As, at death, all is over, hence we should enjoy the present as much as we possibly can. To defer an enjoyment when it offers itself, is the same as waiting at a banquet without eating, until all are done ; enjoyment, and indeed primarily and principally, sen- suous enjoyment, is our highest and sole destination. It was * IShomme machine; Dart dejouir., 1751. 41.] LA METTRIE D'HOLBACH. 321 precisely during his stay in Potsdam that La Mettrie wrote his most audacious glorification of the wildest and even unnatural wantonness. His writings were very much sought after in the higher circles of society. The total result of materialistic ethics is summed up in a work written very probably by Baron Holbach with the co- operation of Diderot and other Encyclopedists : System de la nature, par Mirabaud (1770), constituting the gospel proper of atheism, and presenting nakedly and undisguisedly, in a dull and spiritless form, the results of the philosophy of Locke, Hobbes, and Condillac, who are in fact expressly cited as sources. As man is only a material machine, hence there is between the physical and the moral life no difference ; all thinking and willing consist simply in modifications of the brain. All propensities and passions are purely corporeal states are either hatred or love, that is " repulsion or attrac- tion ; " the absurd doctrine of the freedom of the will has been invented simply to justify the equally absurd one of divine providence. Man is only a part of the great world- machine, determined in all his movements, a blind instru- ment in the hands of necessity; the concession of freedom even to a single creature would bring the whole universe into confusion'; hence whatever takes place takes place neces- sarily. Religion and its ethics are the greatest enemies of man, and occasion him only torment. The system of nature alone makes man truly happy, teaches him to enjoy the present as fully as possible, and gives him, in relation to every thing which is not an object of enjoyment, the indiffer- ence that is essential to his happiness. Hence there is no need of a special moral system. Its fundamental principle would necessarily be : "enjoy life as much as thou canst;" but every man does this already of himself without instruc- tion. Self-love, one of the manifestations of the law of grav- itation, is the highest moral law. The chief condition of happiness is bodily health ; the true key of the human heart is medicine ; the most effectual moralists are the physicians ; he who makes the body sound, makes the man moral. Every man follows by nature and necessarily his own special in- terest, a course of conduct which in fact follows immediately and necessarily from his bodily organization ; vice and crime 322 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [41. are but consequences of morbid corporeality, are not guilt but necessity. Hence only the unwise can repent; in any case repentance is only a pain arising from the fact that an act has had bad consequences for us. Now as the instincts and passions are the sole motive of human action, hence we can influence other men only by working upon their passions. Each is obligated only to that which procures him an advan- tage. Hence a good man is he who satisfies his passions in such a manner that other persons must contribute to this satisfaction so as that they also thereby satisfy their own pas- sions and interests. Hence the atheist is necessarily a good man, whereas religion makes men bad in that it embitters to them the passions. That suicide is held as legitimate for those who are weary of life, is a matter of course. This godless world-theory disseminated itself in rapid develop- ment deeper and deeper among the masses; and the ten years of the French Revolution are the practical realization of this ethics as a social power. It is characteristic of the difference of national spirit that the naturalistic tendency could not, in its stark crudity, take hold upon the German people, but came to expression only in association with other higher principles, with Christ ianly-moral elements, namely, in the Rationalistic " illuminism " of the eighteenth century. Open unbelief proper and materialistic morals spoke, in Germany, almost exclusively French ; and the sycophant court-atheists were too much despised to find hearty favor with the masses. The demoralizing revolution which pro- ceeded from the upper classes, met with a powerful opposition in the German national spirit. Even while a popular gchool of poetry divorced itself from the Christian consciousness, still this school held fast to the antithesis of the spiritual and the naturalistic world-theories, recognizing the former as the high- er ; l% let him who cannot believe, enjoy ; let him who can be- lieve, deny himself.''' The superficial deistic ethics attains to greater influence in Germany than the materialistic, though without giving rise to any important scientific works. On the basis of the uncorrupted purity of human nature there was developed a superficial utilitarian morality without deeper con- tents;- and this morality was looked upon as the essence proper of Christianity. Basedoic's demagogic attempt at world-reno- 41.] BASEDOW STEINBART. 323 vation by a new system of education based on Rousseau, became very soon too ridiculous to exert any enduring influence, Steinbart * (professor of theology at Frankfort on the Oder) in his utterly superficial but greatly lauded System of Pure Philos- ophy or Christian Doctrine of Happiness (1778, '80, '86, '94), regarded the chief contents'of the Christian religion and of Christian ethics as simply the answering of the question : " What have I to learn, and to do, in order to have the great- est possible sum of pleasure ? " " Happiness is the end of the entire human life, and consists in the heart-state of a continuous contentment and of frequently recurring enjoyment." Every man is by nature perfectly good and pure, though indeed not as a spirit but as an animal, and he rises only gradually from the animal to the man. Self-love is the ground of all morality, and morality is the infallible way to a state of enjoyment ; of a checking of self-love there can be no occasion ; hence Christian virtue is " nothing else than a preparedness to enjoy one's exist- ence to the highest degree, under all circumstances " ; the high- est state of enjoyment is of course only in the life after death, where alone we can really survey the consequences of our benefi- cent, meritorious actions ; " but our glimpses into that life en- courage us to a better using of the present one, and the fullest enjoyment of this life enlarges our receptivity for higher degrees of happiness in the future world." This is the pure doctrine of Jesus, which unfortunately has, for eighteen centuries, been lost sight of. Steinbart was favored in the highest degree by the Prussian government, and aided in his plan of founding a " general normal school in which teachers might be educated for the true enlightenment of the nations." It was only the revival of the Pantheism of Spinoza in the nineteenth century that gave rise, in Germany, to a scientific form of ethics ; but also this system, though of a far higher character than the freethinking of France, yet, in its later un- scientific offshoots, ultimated in like results ; and the fact that in our own day a resuscitated materialism, resting, however, more on natural science than on philosophy, presents us again with the ethics of the " System of Nature," is certainly no indi- cation of progress in spiritual development, though indeed an * System der reinen Phil, oder GliickseliglceUslehre dee CJtristen- t&ums. 22 324 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 42 evidence of a progress of the intellectual blight consequent on the too great stagnation of the religious and philosophical spirit in the present age. SECTION XLII. * The theological ethics of the evangelical church of the eighteenth century made but a quite temperate use of German philosophy before the time of Kant, and insisted but little (not without some influence from Pietism) on the antithesis of the two evan- gelical churches in the sphere of ethics. JBuddceus furnished the first scientific system of ethics, though in its philosophical elements it is rather eclectic. Stapfer, Bauingarten and others, applied the Wolfian philosophy in pedantic minuteness to Christian ethics ; while Mosheim constructed it more upon a purely Biblical basis, and upon that of practical life-experi- ence. Toward'the close of the century the superfic- iality of Rationalism began already to make itself felt. Francis Buddceus of Jena, one of the most learned and sound theologians of the eighteenth century, a man of comprehensive philosophical culture and who wrote also a thoughtful, evangel- ically-inspired system of practical philosophy (Elementa phi- losophic practices, 1697, and often), prepared the way, with his Institut. theologies moralis (1712, '23, 4to. ; in German as "In- troduction to Moral Theology," 1719), for a more thorough, systematic treatment of ethics. The rich, carefully and some times rather lengthily treated subject-matter rests upon sound Scripture exegesis and careful observation of human life. Influ- enced somewhat by Spener, this writer combines practical sense with a scientific spirit. He begins at once with the thought of the corruption of human nature and with that of divine grace, and hence gives not a general philosophical, but only a specifically-Christian system of ethics, in view of man as regen- erated. The ground-thought of morality is : man must do every thing which is essential to a constant union with God 42.] BUDD^US BAUMGARTON. 325 and to the restoration of God's image, and must avoid the contrary thereof. The whole subject-matter is distributed, (1), into moral theology (in the narrower sense of the word),which treats of the nature of regeneration and sanctification in their collective development, (2) into jurisprudentia dimna, which treats of the divine laws and of the duties resting thereupon, and (3) into the doctrine of Christian prudence, which presents the practical carrying out of the moral in detail, and especially by clergymen. For the future development of evangelical ethics, the thorough treatment of the first part is especially valuable ; Buddseus finds in Christian ethics not merely the manifestation, but also the progressive development of the spiritual life of the regenerated. He presents as chief virtues : piety, ternperatenesfc and justness. (Budda3us has been much used by other writers, also by J. J. Rambach, 1739, and by J. G. Walch, 1747). The Reformed* divine, John F. Stapfer of Bern made, in his rather comprehensive than scientifically-important system of ethics (1757), a very moderate use of the Wolfian philosophy. The earlier Calvinistically-rigorous spirit is here already very much modified. Sigismund Jacob Baumgarten (of Halle, a brother of the philosopher) follows, in his discursive " Theolog- ical Ethics " (1767, 4to.), the painfully-minute manner of Wolf, which is applied also in his numerous other writings, and which leaves absolutely nothing unsaid, not even that which every reader could supply for himself; and this pedantic discursive- ness detracts considerably from the otherwise real thoroughness of the treatment. (The "Wolfian philosophy was applied to theological ethics by Cam ( 40), by Bertling [1753], and by Reusch [1760] ; J. C. Schubert [1759, '60, '62] is more indepen- dent.) The not sufficiently prized P. Hanssen (of Schleswig- Holstein) gave in his " Christian Ethics " (1739, '49) a very clear and sound presentation of the evangelical doctrine, a work which gives evidence of a truly philosophical spirit, and protests against the one-sidedness of Wolf; in the first general part, he develops the threefold form of the moral life in the state of innocence or perfection, in the state of sin, and in that of regeneration. T. Criiger (of Chemnitz) develops, in his Apparatus theol. moral. Ohristi et renatorum (1747, 4to.), the thought of the moral pattern as found in Christ, and hence of 326 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 42. an ethical Christology and of its application to the life of Chris- tians, with great profoundness and uncommon erudition, though in a somewhat stiff, over-carefully-classified, scholastic form. Mosheim's comprehensive " Ethics of the Holy Scriptures," * though in its sometimes almost hortatory discursiveness, often unnecessarily detailed, yet differs from works of the Wolfian and the earlier schools by a beautiful, animated and popular form, free of all stiff scholastic-elements, and gives evidence of a close observation of life, of impartial and profound study of the Scriptures, of a simple, mild, evangelical spirit, and of a thorough and careful attention to details ; but the scientific demonstration and development are frequently feeble, and, despite all his insisting on the rationality of Christian morality, the philosophical element is almost entirely overlooked ; the antitheses of view, as developed in the two churches, are not made prominent. The whole subject is distributed into the consideration of the inner holiness of the soul, and into that of the outer holiness of the walk. Miller's continuation of the work, though furnished with more learned apparatus, is less mature and also less inviting in form. Crusius, whom we have already mentioned as a philosophical moralist, wrote also a " Moral Theology " (1772) which is inspired with a philosophic- al spirit, and gives evidence of deeply Christian knowledge. Ttillner, 1762, wrote rather on the treatment of ethics than on ethics itself, already quite Rationalistic; Reuss, 1767, uncom- pleted ; the work of G. Less, (1777, and subsequently), is not important; H. C. Tittmann, 1783, '94, endeavors to be strictly Biblical but is without depth ; 'Morns' work, 1794, is imper- fectly edited from his lectures, partially based on Crusius, frequently rationalistic. The Englishman, Thomas Stackhouse, wrote on Christian ethics in a plain and Biblical spirit, treating mainly only of general questions. The Reformed divine, End&- mann of Marburg, closes the series of Reformed moralists (1780), but he bears the distinctively Reformed character only in very feeble traits. * 1735-70 ; continued by Miller, 1762; Miller -wrote also a special Einleit, in die theol. Moral, 1772, and a short Lehrbuch, i?7S. 43.] KANT. 327 SECTION XLIH. In the system of Kant philosophical ethics put off the naturalistic or subjectivistic character; the moral idea attained, on the basis of the freedom of the will, to an objective significancy, and became an end per se, and not simply a means to the end of in- dividual happiness. Independently of the theoretical reason and of the God-consciousness, the moral idea became the presupposition and basis of all specula- tion on the supersensuous, and hence also of rational religion. The universal validity of the moral law became the formal, and, pretendedly also, the mate- rial principaf of morality. But the one-sided rational character of this morality left essential phases of the moral unaccounted for ; and the merely formal char- acter of the moral law admitted of no consequential carrying-out in detail. The application of Kantian ground-thoughts to theological ethics was of two-fold effect, raising it indeed above the utilitarian ethics of the "illuministic " current, but robbing it, in its divorce from religion, of a part of its Christian char- acter. Previous philosophical ethics had gone astray in two respects. The two equally true and necessary thoughts, that, on the one hand, the moral idea has a universally valid significancy, that it cannot be dependent in its obligating character on the chance caprice of the individual subject, and that yet, on the other, it has in fact for its end the perfection of the person, and hence also his happiness, had been one-sidedly held fast to, each for it- self. Naturalistic Pantheism gave validity simply to the objec- tive significancy of the moral, absolutely annihilated the free- dom of the will, and conceived by the moral law as a mere fatal- ism unalterably determining every individual ; and when, with the champions of materialistic atheism, this notion of the unfree 328 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 43. determination of the individual, ultimated practically in an entire letting-loose of the passions, it was not without the countenance of strict consistency with the ground principle. The opposite tendency proceeded from the subject, emphasizing his free will, and hence looking less to the ground than to the end of the moral activity ; man was to be determined by noth- ing which does not leave him absolutely free, which does not contribute to his own individual advantage, in other words, by the thought of individual happiness. While the first ten- dency undermined morality by the fact that it annihilated the moral subject, sinking him into a mere unfree member of the great world-machine, the other tendency imperiled morality in its innermost essence, in a no less degree, by the fact that it required no self-subordination of the subject under a per se valid idea,, but emphasized the absolute claims of the individ- ual personality, so that in fact in their ultimate consequences the two opposite tendencies resulted, equally, in the letting- loose of the individual in his unbridled naturalness. Christian ethics could not, save by letting itself be led astray by philos- ophy, fall into either of these errors. That the moral idea is valid per se, that it has an unconditional, universally-obligating significancy, is here a point settled from the very start, inas- much as it conceives this idea as the holy will of God. He who inquires first as to himself, and only afterward as to the will of God, has absolutely reversed the moral relation. On the other hand, it is, in Christian ethics, not in the least doubtful, that this will of God has in view the perfection of man, and hence also his perfect happiness, that man, in fulfilling God's will becomes also truly happy, and does not lose his freedom but brings it to perfection. It was high time, toward the end of the eighteenth century, to set bounds to the decline of philosophical ethics ; the two opposed currents had attained to their last corrupt consequences, subversive of all morality. The " eudemonistic " tendency could oppose nothing else to the frivolous enjoyment-seeking and conscienceless self-seeking of the materialistic tendency, than an insipid utilitarian moral- ity essentially identical at bottom with the other, and which differed from it only by an air of external decency, but not by profundity of th'ought or moral worthiness. It was a great forward-step of philosophical thought-development when 43.] KANTIAN ETHICS. 329 Kant, with mighty hand, dashed to atoms both these moral structures, and built up a new firmer-based system ; although his own age, in its enthusiasm for him, no less than he himself, sadly deceived themselves as to the perfection and durability of the same. His first and by no means unimportant service consists in the fact that basing himself primarily on the skepticism of Hume, he annihilated, at a single stroke, all confidence in pre- vious methods of philosophizing, whether speculative or em- pirical, and deprived both empiricism and the pure theoretical reason, in so far as it had thus far been developed, of all right to pretend to establish, in respect to the supersensuous, or the ideal, any thing whatever as philosophical knowledge. Though in his "Critique of the Pure Reason" (1781) Kant had ascribed to the speculative reason, in the sphere of theoretical knowledge, really only the function of formal thought or logic, he yet attained in fact to a positive knowl-- edge of reality in the sphere of the practical reason, that is, in that of morality.* Reason is not merely a cognizing, but also a volitionating power; hence there is not merely a ra- tional knowledge of that which is, namely, theoretical or pure reason, but also of that which, through rational volition, ought to be, namely, practical reason; the former seeks in every given reality for the rational beginning, the ground ; the practical reason seeks for the rational goal, the end. This end can, as a rational one, not be fortuitous, arbitrary, or doubtful, but must have an unconditional absolutely-valid character. The office of reason is here entirely other than in the sphere of pure theoretical cognition ; the practical reason directs itself toward something which is not yet real, but which should through reason become real, and which, conse- quently depends upon reason; hence reason is here, as in contrast to the other sphere, in its own sphere proper, where it itself actively creates its own object, is free and responsi- ble. Man, as a spirit, can choose whatever object of action he pleases, but as a rational spirit he should set before hiin- * Qrundlegung sur Metaphysik der Sitten, 1785; Krittie der prakti- scTien Vernunft, 1788, the chief work of the Kantian form of ethics ; Metaph. Anfangtgrilttde der RecTitslehre, 1797; Metaph. Anf. der Tit- gendlehre, 1797. 330 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [43. self only a rational, and hence absolutely valid object. As he acts here in a sphere determined by himself, hence he is dependent only upon himself ; in willing and acting, man is free. A rational end is such a one as must be recognized by every rational man, as his own end ; for reason is not a merely individual quality, but is in all men the same ; hence the ra- tionality of the end consists in its universal validity. Hence the highest principle of all rational moral action is the law : "act in such a manner that the maxim of thy conduct is adapted to become a universal law for all men." (Maxim is here taken as the subjective principle of moral action in con- tradistinction to the objectively-valid law.) The obligatori- ness of such action lies exclusively in my rationality, and is hence entirely unconditional ; should I act otherwise I would not be rational; hence this law of the reason is the "cate- gorical imperative.'" 1 I am here to inquire not after my own happiness, but only after that which is rational ; I ought to be rational ; to this end I need no other motive than my own ra- tional nature itself. To make my own happiness the end of my moral activity eudemonism is irrational and immoral ; for, because of the fortuity of the outward conditions of hap- piness, and of the heterogeneousness of claims upon happi- ness, the moral would be rendered dependent upon accident and caprice. The moral reason is absolutely free only when it has absolutely within itself the law and the motive of ac- tion, and where it makes itself dependent on no other con- ditions not given within itself. kl Autonomy" constitutes the essence of reason and the dignity of human nature. Reason, in a practical law, determines the will directly, and not by means of an intervening feeling of pleasure or dis- pleasure. To be happy is indeed the legitimate and naturally- necessary striving of every rational being, but such a ground for action can be known and recognized only empirically, whereas the moral law must necessarily have objective un- conditional validity. What is good or evil cannot be known through any thing outside of reason, but only through reason itself ; but feelings of pleasure and displeasure belong not to reason, but to the lower'sphere of the spirit-life. Though morality as resting exclusively upon the categori- cal imperative of the reason has not happiness for its motive, 43.] KANTIAN ETHICS. 331 yet it earns a right to happiness ; virtue is the subjective fit- ness for and worthiness of happiness, that is, for that condi- tion of a rational being to whom, in its entire existence, every thing goes according to wish and will, and where consequently also the outward relations, including those of nature, harmonize with the spiritual and moral reality of the person. Neither virtue per se, nor happiness per se, but hap- piness as attendant upon virtue, constitutes the true, perfect life-condition of man his highest good. The moral law per sc is the sole true motive of the will, while the idea of the highest good is an object of reason. Happiness depends not merely upon our rational will, but also upon outer conditions which lie not within our power. Hence happiness and virtue are not identical (as the Greek moralists taught), but have primarily nothing whatever to do with each other ; the virtu- ous man may possibly be very unhappy, namely, in so far as his condition is not dependent upon himself, which is in fact another proof that the striving after virtue and the striving after happiness are not one and the same thing, and that the striving after happiness per se is neither moral nor leads to morality. In this distinction lies the dialectics of the practical reason; happiness is not already included in virtue itself, stands therewith not in analytical but in syn- thetic connection ; and hence we are brought to the important question : how is the highest good practically possible f that is, how can the two essentially different elements of this good be brought into perfect harmony? The highest good is a demand of the practical reason; the demand of happiness for the virtuous is just as rational as that of virtue itself ; but its realization rests not (as that of virtue) within our free power, but is rather a morally necessary demand upon the moral gov- ernment of the world, a " postulate of the practical reason." The demand, the postulate, of a perfect morality which is not fully to be attained to in this temporal, sensuously-limited life, and of a correspondent happiness, that is, the demand of the highest good, finds its fulfillment only in the assump- tion of an immortality of the rational personality, and of a universal government of an all-wise, just and almighty Q-od. These postulates have, in virtue of the moral nature of man, entire moral certainty, because it is only on the assumption 332 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 43. of their truth that the morally-rational life can attain to its goal. Thus the moral law leads, through the idea of the highest good as the object and end of the practical reason, to religion, that is, to the conceiving of all duties as divine commands, not indeed as arbitrary prescriptions of an ex- ternal will, but as essential and morally-necessary laws of every free rational will per se, which, however, must be looked upon as divine commands, because it is only on the supposition of a moral Infinite Will that we can attain to the highest good. Thus the moral striving is preserved from becoming selfish, and the thought of happiness is not made the motive of morality, but this motive is and remains abso- lutely nothing else but the moral law; but, through the religious consciousness, our reason attains to certainty and confidence in its moral aspirations. Ethics will never be- come a doctrine of happiness, an art of becoming happy ; it becomes simply the doctrine as to how we may make our- selves worthy of happiness. Hence the moral idea rests not upon religion, but, conversely, religion rests upon the pe>' se certain and necessary moral idea, follows by moral neces- sity from this idea. Man is not moral because he is pious, but he is pious because he is moral. Morality in so far as it 'rests upon the idea of a free and rational creature, has no need, per se, of religion, because it has no end nor motive outside of itself, but it leads necessarily to religion, and thus gives rise to the idea of an almighty moral Lawgiver and world-Governor. A special carrying-out of philosophical ethics, Kant has not really given ; we find only a scanty ap- proach thereto in his "Doctrine of Virtue," a work of no great importance, and which already betrays marks of intel- lectual senility. He contents himself mostly with the mere general foundation-laying, whereas in fact, the chief question is : in how far the general thoughts admit also of being car- ried out in detail? Duties toward God belong, according to Kant, not to ethics proper, but to the doctrine of religion.* Unquestionably there lies in the ethics of Kant a decided advance beyond antecedent philosophical ethics, and espe- cially beyond the empirical and naturalistic. He raised it from the low region of a self-seeking or external utilitarian . * * Met. d. Sitten, ed. 1838, p. 355 sqq. 43.] KANT CRITICIZED. 333 morality into the dignity of the science of a purely rational idea transcending all mere reality, rejected all inferior self- seeking motives to morality, and insisted on the unconditional validity and obligatoriness of the moral law. While there lies in this a decided approximation to the Christian concep- tion of the moral, still the great difference of this from the Christian view, and the inner weakness of the Kantian system as a whole, are unmistakable. The independence of morality on religion which follows from Kant's theory of rational knowledge, makes it impossible for the moral principle to ob- tain positive contents ; his much admired moral law, and for which he puts forth such high claims, says in fact absolutely nothing, and does not lead, save by arbitrarily calling in aid from without, a single step further ; and it is manifestly not without good reason, that Kant developed no system of ethics proper. The above-mentioned formula expresses not, properly speaking, the moral law itself, but only the universal validity of the law which is yet to be discovered, says, in fact, noth- ing else than: "act according to rational, and hence univer- sally-valid law ; " but if we now ask, what then is this law, we are left entirely without answer. The application of this formal principle becomes in each particular case an experi- ment, an examination of the question : can I will that all men should act according to the same maxim by which I act? But we have absolutely no clue or criterion as to whence and on what basis the answer is to be given, inasmuch as the moral law is utterly destitute of positive contents ; we could at best only start the inquiry as to what the result would be in case all men acted as we ; but this, as a judging of morality by the result, would be in contradiction to the other moral views of Kant, and would be the worst of all empiricism, as in fact not the real, but only the possible or probable result could be taken into consideration. But in case, now, some one should, in view of some per se immoral action, come to the manifestly possible, though erroneous conviction, that such action is adapted to be practiced universally, then such a person would be entirely unassailable and unreformable from the stand-point of Kant, and thus an error in the calculating understanding would jeopardize the entire moral conduct of the person. And in fact Helvetius and La Mettrie affirmed CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 43. without hesitation, that their own maxim was adapted to be a universally valid law ; what could Kant then object to them, seeing that they recognized his formal principle ? The Kantian moral law, which he himself declared to be purely formal, is moreover incorrect even in formal respects. Inasmuch as, according to Kant, a maxim is the subjective rule which lies at the basis of my conduct, hence it is for that very reason per se utterly unadapted to be made into a universal law for all men ; a maxim is the law as subjectively conditioned and shaped, and has in fact, in its subjective form, validity only for this particular subject. The moral maxim of an educator and guide is not adapted to be also the maxim of him who is to be guided and led, that of a warrior cannot be that of a clergyman. Although it is true that the law which forms the basis of my maxim must be universally valid, yet I cannot derive the law from the maxim, but only the maxim from the law. Kant gives not the contents of the law, but only the way in which the contents may be found ; this way, however, is in contradiction to his entire system, and is not merely a purely empirical or rather experimental one, but also an en- tirely false one. In the very attempt at rejecting every merely individual element as determinative, Kant exalts it in fact to the solely determining one. Kant undertakes, now, actually to advance further by the aid of this formal principle, and infers from it, as a second formula, the principle: "act in such a manner as to consider and use rational nature, that is, humanity in general, both in thy own person and also in the person of every other one, always, at the same time, as an end, and never merely as a means," namely, because rational nature is personality, and personality is an end in itself. Kant himself admits that this formula is merely formal ; but precisely in this fact lies its defectiveness, for it is just as impossible to attain to posi- tive contents from merely formal principles as to obtain a real value from a purely algebraic equation. When the prin- ciple is only a mere empty space which is first to be filled from without, and not the fountain which unfolds itself into a stream, there is no possibility of advancing a step further. And hence, the above formula may be applied equally well morally and immorally ; the whole question depends on, what 43.] KANT CRITICIZED. 335 the end is, for which I consider the person ; it might in fact ' be an end of Satanic malice. This second principle is, in its arbitrarily-determined form (and which in fact embraces only a limited part of morality) still less adapted to its purpose than the first, with which in fact it stands in no logical con- nection. Another wide-reaching defect of Kantian ethics is this, that morality appears as a mere one-sided affair of the understand- ing, while the heart entirely disappears, and is left utterly unexplained. This one-sidedness results of course from the divorce of morality from religion. It sounds plausibly, and is likewise very easily said, that the good must be done for its own sake, that the law of the reason must be per se the direct motive to moral action ; but as Kant positively admits elsewhere the possibility that man can act also against his better knowledge, and consequently against his conscience, hence this undenjable fact proves that rational knowledge is not per se a sufficient motive to moral action. The thought of love is wanting ; man can indeed act against his knowledge, but not against his love. It is only in a love of the good that a sufficient motive for moral action is found; but in this God- ignoring morality of the understanding, love has no ground and no place. The love of the living God can enkindle love, but an abstract thought cannot. Kant demands simply un- conditional obedience, but not love ; he expressly declares that the law must often be fulfilled even against our inclina- tions, yea, in the face of decided repugnance ; but this would amount only to an outward fulfilling of duty. Kant's mo- rality is possible only for beings who have in themselves no manner of sin and no germ of sin ; but so soon as even the mere possibility of an already-existing sinfulness is admitted, this ethical system loses all foundation ; for both the certainty and also the potency of the rational law as a motive, are there- by undermined. And now Kant in fact admits, in his re- ma'rkable work: " Religion within the Limits of Pure Rea- son " (1792, '94) (which, with the exception of the one point here in question, became the catechism of Rationalism) the indwelling of an evil principle in man along-side of the good one, a " radical evil in human nature," existing there already anterior to any exercise of freedom, a tendency to evil in- 336 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 43. hering in all men without exception, as a subjective motive- power antecedent to all action, apeccatum originarium, which he describes with such dark colors that even the strongest presentations of the orthodox doctrine of hereditary sin would fail to depict the natural man so unfavorably ; but by this admis- sion, Kant undermines his entire moral system, for he thereby renders it entirely incomprehensible, how the mere knowledge of the moral law (if indeed, under such circumstances, such a knowledge could in fact be certain and unclouded) could be the motive to a willing fulfillment of the same, seeing that, in fact, the love of man is turned in the direction of evil. And though it is true that often precisely in the contradic- tions of a system, the deeper presentiment of the truth is in fact contained, still the system itself is thereby overturned and proven untrue. And in general the antithesis of reason and sensuousness, which extends through Kant's entire world- theory, is in no respect rendered comprehensible, nor concili- ated; it appears simply as a fact, broadly prominent and defying all comprehension. Another peculiarity of Kantian ethics is its utter lack of appreciation for history, although this was in fact characteristic of the entire epoch ; his ethics has history neither as its presupposition, nor as its end, nor as its contents. Each man stands unconnected with the his- torical development of the spirit, is considered only as a rational unity, and acts only as such ; and there is also a lack of all appreciation for an historical goal of the moral, for a morality of humanity, for the rational moral significancy of universal history. The Kantian ground-principles of ethics were further carried out and applied, with partial modifications, by Kiesewetter (1789), by K. C. E. Schmid (1790), by the Roman Catholic Mutschelle (1788, '94), by Snell (1805) in smooth, popular style, by L. H. Jacob (1794), by Heydenreich (1794), by Tief trunk (1789 and later), and by others. Kant's moral system was, in its general character, very poorly adapted to be applied to Christian ethics. Its absolutely un- historical character, its merely formal principle the application of which rests simply on reflective calculation, its lack of any other moral motive than the authority of an abstract law, and above all the reversing of the Christian relation between mor- 43.] KANT AND CHRIST. 337 ality and religion, all this could not, on its application to theological ethics, fail to endanger the Christian character thereof, notwithstanding the fact that it opposed with moral earnestness the insipid utilitarian morality of deistical " illu- minism." Precisely this divorcing of morality from religion a direct contradiction to the Christian view was very much in harmony with the dominant spirit of the age ; and this in fact accounts in part for the warm welcome which Kant's moral system met with also within the sphere of the already deeply sunken theological world ; and upon this adoption of Kantian views rests the general development of the system of Rationalism. The dogmatic element of the Christian religion, reduced now to the ideas of God, of immortality and of Christ as the ideal of virtue, sank into secondary im- portance into dependence on the morality given with full certainty in reason itself; the historical phase of Christianity was without worth ; Christ himself was admired only in so far as he had realized in himself the moral law given already in reason, only as a teacher of " illuministic " morality, and as a living exemplification of the same. It was not evangelical faith that could lean with confidence upon Kant, but rather only the anti-Christian tendency, which had thus far been represented in " illuminism, " and which now, in fact, received from Kant a more earnestly-ethical and scientific character. We have no wish to deny this scientific impulse given to the- ology ; but when (as is done by Daniel Schenkel in his Dog- matics) Kant is exalted into an essential and necessary reformer of the whole field of evangelical theology, through whom there has been wrought " a deep-reaching reaction on the part of the ethical factor against the fanatical-grown doctrinism of the dogmatics of the seventeenth century " which had annihilated all interest in ethics, such a manner of viewing the matter sim- ply indicates a forgetfulness of the fact that this orthodoxy in question had been already for almost a century devoid of vitality, and that in the meantime the philosophy of Wolf and the movement of Pietism had given theology an entirely other direction, and that Pietism especially had in fact almost one- sidedly emphasized he moral phase of Christianity, so that there could hardly have been need of the Kantian moralism as the sole salvation against said doctrinal " fanaticism." 338 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [44. The most important theological presentations of ethics from the Kantian stand-point are : J. W. Schmid (" Spirit of the Ethics of Jesus," 1790; "Theological Ethics," 1793; "Chris- tian Ethics," 1797), who presents the founding of ethics on Kantian principles as the sole mission of Jesus ; J. E. C. Schmidt (1799), in a similar spirit; S. G. Lange ; S. Vogel. Staudlin treated theological ethics (from and after 1798) with constant changing of title and stand-point, until in his " New Treatise on Ethics" (1813, third edition, 1825) he despaired of any su- perior principle at all, and brought together, in a wavering eclecticism of heterogeneous thoughts, a feeble whole. The self-metamorphosing C. F. von Amman repeated at first (1795-'98) simply the ethics of Kant, but soon after (1800) broke entirely away from him, without yet getting rid of his own superficiality. SECTION XLIV. The philosophy of Fichte, resting upon Kant, but, with rigid consequentially, proceeding beyond him, manifested itself predominantly upon the ethical field. Fichte endeavored indeed to complement the formal principle by a material one, but both of them are so absolutely devoid of ethical contents, and the material principle stands even so positively in antag- onism to the contents of a really moral conscious- ness, that an actual ethical development of these principles became impossible; and the occasionally sound and morally-earnest contents of the develop- ment in detail could only be loosely associated with these principles, but not scientifically developed from them. The immaturity of the entire stand-point rendered it also impossible that any important ethical tendency in philosophy or theology should arise therefrom. Fichte labored indeed fruitfully in a time which had lost all solid philosophical foot hold, but he formed no school. 44.] FICHTEAN ETHICS. 839 Fichte's " System of Ethics according to the Principles of the Doctrine of Science " (1798) is the most important attempt to apply tlie ground-thoughts of the " Doctrine of Science " to one particular science. We would do injustice to the Fichtean philosophy were we to consider its unfruitful eccentricities apart from their connection with the immediately-preceding philosophy; his philosophy is a scientifically-justified and necessary advance beyond Kant. As Kant had denied to the pure reason all objective knowledge, and also placed all con- tents of the practical reason exclusively in the subject, and derived the objective validity of the law of reason simply from the subject ; so Fichte simply made the validity of the indi- vidual subject, the ego, all-predominant, conceived all object- ive existence merely negatively as the non-ego, and based cog- nition and volitionating absolutely on the individual ego. The ego and the non-ego reciprocally determine each other, and hence stand in reciprocal relation. The ego posits itself as determined by the non-ego, that is, it cognizes ; and it posits itself, on the other hand, as determining in relation to the non- ego, that is, it wlitionates. The two are only two phases of the same thing, inasmuch as the non-ego in its entire being ex- ists only in so far as it is posited by the ego, so that, strictly speaking, the ego is its own object. The ego should in all its determinations be posited only by itself, should be absolutely independent of all non-ego. Only as volitiouating, as abso- lutely determining the non-ego, is the ego free and independ- ent. The ego as rational, should not permit itself to be deter- mined by any non-ego independent of it, should be absolutely independent, should make all non-ego absolutely dependent on itself, should exercise absolute causality upon the same. In freedom, in volitionating, I am rational ; and in that I deter- mine my freedom as an absolutely self-poised power, that is. affirm my freedom, I am moral ; hence morality is self-determi- nation to freedom. I should act freely in order that I may become free, that is, I should act with the consciousness that I determine myself in absolute independence. Hence the formal principle of morality is : " act according to thy conscience," or " act always according to the best conviction of thy duty ; " and as material principle of ethics, there results this: " make thyself into an independent or free being." "I should be a 23 340 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 44. self-dependent being ; this is my destination ; and the destination of things is, that I use them in furthering my independence." So absolutely void a principle of morality was probably never before proposed. The formal principle expresses nothing other than : act according to a yet unknown material principle. As to what the " conscience " is and contains, we are as yet utterly uninformed ; and the material principle gives only the formal presupposition of morality, but not its contents proper ; I must in fact already be free, in order to be able to act morally ; freedom is not the contents, but the form, of moral action. If this material principle is to be taken in its entire significancy (and according to the philosophical presupposition this is strictly consequential), then the very opposite of all morality would be thereby expressed, namely, the acting absolutely with- out law, the virtualizing of freedom in its simple form without contents, and hence as mere individual caprice amounting to a radical absolutism of the individual subject, whereas all morality consists in fact most essentially in a determining of individual freedom by an unconditionally and objectively valid law, is- a subordinating of the subject to a universally-obligat- ing idea standing above the subject. From Fichte's principle there results, not a system of ethics, but, consequentially, only a theory of license. While it is true that in his examinations of particular moral questions only loosely connected with his system, Fichte shows himself, for the most part, high-minded and earnest, though indeed often strangely unpractical, still there lies, at least in his ground-principle and in his general system, no justification thereof. Th*e cold, heartless, non-los- ing, intellectual character of his- discussions, is moreover not very well adapted to awaken a moral interest. What Fichte. says on moral questions in his later, more rhetorical than scientific, writings-, bears in general the same unfruitful stamp, often widely misunderstanding the reality of life ; we need only call' to mind the new system of education proposed in his much admired " Addresses to the German Na- tion," which was presented with the assumption of world- regenerating significancy, but at which, in fact, no experienced educator can avoid smiling, and also his " Doctrine of the State " which is even more than fantastical. The public often allowed itself to be deceived by the ring of his periods, 45.] FICHTEAN RELIGION. 341 and by the loftily enigmatic character of the expression. And it is doubtful whether the fanaticism of the philosopher him- self, or that entertained for him by others, was the greater; certain it is, however, that very soon there was a vast sobering- down of both. We will here only refer to the fact that Fichte was personally very far from drawing the very natural conse- quences of his dangerous moral principle, but that on the con- trary in his rhetorical " Direction for a Holy Life " (1807), in which he already largely departs from his earlier views, and takes a rather mystico-Pantheistic turn, he expressly presents, as the goal of morality, complete " self-annihilation " not, however, in the Christian sense of moral self-denial, but rather in the sense of the religion of India. The belief in our self- existence must be absolutely destroyed ; by this course the ego that was, sinks away into the pure divine essence ; we should not say : let the love and the will of God become mine, because in fact there are no longer two, but only One, and no longer two wills but simply one. So long as man yet desires to be any thing himself, God comes not to him ; but so soon as he annihilates himself fully, utterly and radically, then God alone remains and is all in all. In annihilating himself man contin- ues in God, and in this self-annihilation consists blessedness. The scientific justification of this (in some respects) not un- ambiguous requirement, is not given. Notwithstanding ,the enthusiasm which Fichte's pretentious philosophy excited, especially among the youth, it was unable to create any long- enduring movements of thought. Feeble attempts to develop it further, or, in fact, to apply it to Christian ethics (Mehmel : "Elements," 1811), fell very soon into deserved oblivion. SECTION XLV. Schelling, after passing from Idealism to Panthe- ism, and from Pantheism to a dualistic Theosophy, endeavored, in this his third development-period, to reconcile the freedom of the individual with the sway of necessity, and indeed of necessary evil, by regard- ing individual man as determining himself for evil in an ante-mundane self-determination as influenced CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [45. by a principle of darkness lying in God himself, but as necessary for the self-revelation of divine love. The presentations of philosophical ethics which based themselves on Schelling, have been unable to attain to any permanent significancy. The imperfectly devel- oped anti-Schellingian philosophy ofJacobi answered, in its ethical phases, more to the Christian view, but it also has given rise to no real ethical system. Schelling, appearing at first as a disciple of Fichte (at a period which was very receptive and thankful for philosophy, even for a youthfully unripe one), and then, in a more highly speculative spirit passing beyond him, and also in constant metamorphoses progressively rising above even himself, never settled, never bringing any thing to perfection, did not de- velop in his earlier period any ethical system, and, at furthest, only gave, on purely Pantheistic foundations, more or less clear suggestions toward an ethical system ; however, in his last pro- ductive period (when, under the stimulation of Jacob Bb'hnie and Francis Baader, he plunged into a current of phantasy- speculation not un-akin to Gnostic dualism), he furnished, in his " Philosophical Inquiries as to the Essence of Human Lib- erty" (1809), a less dialectically developed, indeed, than theo- sophically-portrayed. though certainly deeply suggestive, pres- entation of the presuppositions and bases of a system of phil- osophical ethics. In God there exists, before all reality, his eternal ground, his per se unintelligent nature, out of which in all eternity the divine understanding generates itself as the eternal antithesis to this ground-nature, which understanding stands dominatingly over against this nature, rules creatingly in it, and by its acting upon it creates the finite world. Eveiy creature has consequently a twofold nature in itself : an essen- tially dark principle corresponding to the nature-element in God, and also the principle of light or understanding. In the highest creature, man, there exists the entire power of the dark principle, namely, the unintelligent self-will, and also the entire power of light the deepest abyss and the highest heaven. From the fact of his springing from the ground or nature- element in God, man has in himself a principle relatively inde- 45.] SCHELLINGTAN ETHICS. 343 pendent of God, which, answering to this ground, is darkness, but which becomes transfigured by the light, the spirit. But while in God the two principles are indissolubly united, in man they are separable, that is, man has the possibility of good and evil. The dark principle can, as selfishness, separate itself from the light ; self-will can endeavor to be, as a separate will, that which it truly is only in unity with the universal will, can endeavor to be, also in the periphery or as a creature, that which it is only in so far as it remains in the divine center ; this self-severing of self-hood from the light is evil. Evil, as the dissevering of the two principles, is necessary in order to a revelation of God ; for if these principles remained in man as unseparated as they are in God, then there would be no differ- ence between God and man, and God could not manifest his omnipotence and love ; but God must of necessity so reveal himself. For this reason, the self-will of man is influenced by that dark unintelligent principle in God, man is tempted to evil, in order that the will of divine love may find an opposing element, an antithesis, wherein it can realize itself. Hence evil exists in man as a natural tendency, for the reason that the disorder of his powers, as occasioned by the awakening of self- will in the creature, communicates itself to him in his very birth ; and this ground-element in God works also constantly in man, and excites his self-hood and individual will, in or- der that in antithesis to it, the will of divine love may find scope for action. Hence results a general necessity of sin, which, however, by no means does away with the personal guilt of man, for the dark ground in God realizes not evil as such, but only prompts thereto. The actions of actual man result, indeed, with necessity from his essence, but this es- sence man himself has determined by an act of self-determi- nation beyond all time and co-incidently with creation itself. Man is indeed born in time, but he has, himself, determined his life and character before his temporal life, yon side of time, in eternity. Hence our actual act.-'ons are, on the one hand, necessary, and, on the other, within our own respon- sibility. That Judas betrayed Christ, was absolutely neces- sary; neither himself nor another could have changed the matter; and nevertheless it was his own guilt, for he had so determined himself from eternity. As every man now acts, 344: CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 45. so acted he, as the identical person, already at the beginning of creation ; he is not simply now forming his character, but his character is already formed. All men have determined themselves from eternity to egotism and self-seeking, and are born with this dark principle essential in their being. Evil, however, ought not to remain, but to be overcome by the good principle. Schelling promised a fuller development of these ground- thoughts, but did not carry it out. The enthusiasm with which this philosophy of his (which promised the solution of all the enigmas of existence), was received, an enthusiasm which was not dampened, but rather heightened by its orac- ular tone and by the boldness of assertion which often as- sumed in it the place of scientific proof, gave occasion also in the ethical field, to various, though mostly feeble, fruit- less and soon abandoned, attempts at a further carrying-out of his ground-principles, some of them in greater approxi- mation to the Christian consciousness ; (Buchner, 1807; Than- ner, 1811; Klein, 1811; Holler, 1819; Krame, 1810, though deviating considerably from the master, and rather independ- ent). The facility with which other kindred currents of thought admitted of being joined into Schelling's theosophi- cal outbursts, was indeed very tempting to the book-prolific spirit of the age, but it also soon awakened in the sobering- down spirit of the time a degree of distrust ; and the fame obtained by the master in his meteoric flight, showed itself less partial for his zealously-imitating scholars; and when Daub, after welcoming, in their regular order of succession, all the philosophies from Kant to Hegel, advanced in his "Judas Iscariot" (1816), on the principles of Schelling, to a sort of personality of evil, to a philosophical Satanology, which indeed is yet far different from the Christian view, then, at last, the predominantly Rationalistic spirit of the age began to lose confidence in the worth of the more recent philosophy as a whole. F. H. Jucobi of Munich, who, in antithesis to all Pantheism, took his departure from the stand-point of the free personal spirit, has given in his miscellaneous and unsystematic writings * only hints and suggestions toward an ethical sys- * Werke, 1812, 4 vols. 46.] JACOBI HEGEL. 345 tern. He opposed to the Pantheistic philosophy, however, rather, merely the consciousness of its untruth than a sci- entifically-constructed theory. He emphasized very strongly the personal, moral will-freedom of man as opposed to all necessary determination, without, however, creating for it a really scientific basis, appealing here, as also in the case of the idea of the personality of God, to inner spiritual experi- ence to feeling. Morality, he based on a primitive feeling for the good, which is independent of the striving after hap- piness ; the good must be accomplished for its own sake, and not as a means to happiness. In general, Jacobi did not rise beyond the views of Rationalism. The few moralists who followed in his wake, defend indeed the Christian stand-point as against the Pantheistic tendency, but they have no -very great scientific significancy. Among them belongs essentially also the Roman Catholic theologian, Salat (1810 and later). SECTION XLVL The philosophy of Hegel knows nothing of ethics under this name; upon its Pantheistic ground no really personal freedom can find foothold, although it makes all possible endeavors to find scope therefor. The reality of freedom appears essentially only under the form of necessity, as that right which, on the part of the subject, is duty ; ethics appears only as the Doctrine of Right ; its scientific significancy lies in its decided advance beyond the previous subjective stand-point (which appears even yet in Kant) to the objective validity and reality of morality in the family, in society and in the state, as real moral forms of humanity. In the fact, however, that only the State is conceived as the highest realization of objective morality, lies also the one-sidedness of the view, inasmuch as the full reality of moral freedom remains unrecognized. The Hegelian school has not developed philosophical ethics beyond the positions 346 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 46. of the master; its application to theological ethics by Daub and MarTieineke presents the un refreshing picture of a vain attempt at harmoniously reconcil- ing irreconcilable contradictions. The school of Pan- theistic radicalism, which is nominally connected with Hegel but is in reality based rather on Spinoza, has produced no real system of ethics, but only nar- row-minded and absurd essays on particular ethical topics. The ethics of Hegel, as presented in his "Philosophy of Right," (1821; better by Gans, 1833) the field occupied by which constitutes a part of the Philosophy of the Spirit, rests on the Pantheistic current set in motion by Spinoza, and appears, in higher scientific maturity than in Schelling. The rational spirit, as the unity of the objective conscious- ness and of the self-Consciousness, is the true free-become spirit; it cognizes every thing in itself and itself in every thing, is, as reason, the identity of the objective All and the ego. In that the rational spirit recognizes rationality in nature, and hence nature as objective reason, it is theoretical spirit. But reason knows its own contents also as its object, objectivizes the same, posits them outwardly, that is, the spirit is practical spirit volitionates. But in so far as it is determined to this volitionating by no other object foreign to itself, but determines itself simply by virtue of its rational being, it is free spirit. Hence the spirit posits itself out- wardly from within, objectivizes itself in freedom, realizes itself in an objective manner. This its realization is not nature, but is essentially of a spiritual character, is a spiritual world, a kingdom of the spirit which exists not merely in the ego, but has an objective reality the creator of which is the free rational spirit ; the objective-become spirit is the historical world in the widest sense of the word. The freedom of the rational spirit is, however, with Hegel, by no means a real freedom of choice ; such a freedom finds in the Pantheistic world-theory no legitimate place ; it is only the spirit's active relating to itself, its being independent upon any other ex- ternal entity, but it is nevertheless essentially at the same time 46.] HEGELIAN ETHICS. 347 necessity. Thus the free spirit creates a world as the objective reality of freedom, a reality, however, which has a general significancy transcending the individual being, becomes a power over the individual spirit, assumes the form of necessity, whereby the individual subject is determined in his freedom, and which consequently must be recognized by the individual as the higher factor, is a general will over against the individ- ual will, is right, which becomes for the individual, duty. The Philosophy of Right falls into three parts. (1) The free will is primarily immediate, as individual will. The subject of right is the person, which stands to other persons primarily in an excluding relation. The person confers upon itself the reality of its freedom posits a special sphere of its subjective freedom in property. I declare an ob- jective entity as my own, and hence as that upon which another has no right. This is primarily as yet an outward and not necessary action ; it lies not in the essence of the thing itself that I declare it as my property ; hence right in this sphere is the merely formal, abstract right. The freedom of the subject is assured and recognized by the fact that other subjects must concede the validity of my freedom, my property, my right ; freedom receives thus a general signifi- cancy, becomes right. The freedom of individual subjects is regulated by law, is reduced to general harmony. But that the reality of this right rests primarily on the subjective will, and that the general will is the product of the individual will, is as yet an irrational state of things, and abstract right advances now, (2), to morality, wherein the individual will becomes the product and expression of the general will, but on the basis of freedom, through free recognition. In the first sphere the subjective freedom of the individual is bound by the right of the other, and hence trammeled. But in the free recognition of this right, the bondage, the trammeling element, is thrown off; right and law are no longer a merely outward limiting element, but become the personal law of the subject, the contents of his free self- determination. In the mere fulfillment of right the disposi- tion does not come into question ; I may concede to another his right unwillingly, and hence immorally ; so soon, how- ever, as right becomes morality, the disposition, the intention, 348 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 46. becomes the chief thing, and the outward act a merely second- ary matter. A man may be forced to right, but not to mo- rality ; only free, cheerful action is moral. That which in the sphere of right is wrong, becomes in the moral sphere moral guilt. The intention of the moral action directs itself pri- marily upon the rational subject himself, wills his welfare ; but, as rationality has a general significancy, this intention looks also to the general welfare, to the realizing of the rational will and hence of rationality in general, that is, to the good. To realize the good, is for the individual subject, duty, is no longer a merely outward law, but an inner, freely appropriated one. The good as the unity of the no- tion of the rational will and of the particular will of the individual subject, is the end, the goal of the universe. But in the accomplishing of this duty of realizing the good, the subject finds himself involved in a multitude of contradictions and conflicts; the outer objective world is, as related to the subject, a something different from and in- dependent of him; hence it is doubtful and fortuitous whether or not it is in harmony with the subjectively moral ends, whether or not the subject finds his well-being in it. The abstract right was a merely outward and formal one ; morality is a merely inward subjective something, has harmony only as a postulate, as an "ought;" the good is, as yet, only the abstract idea of the good ; hence there is need of a third, higher stage wherein the subjective and the objective phases are united, where the postulate of the harmonizing of the two spheres is realized, where the ought is also reality, where the good is no longer an abstract gen- eral something over against which the subject stands as yet as an isolated individual, but where the good has attained to reality, where freedom has become nature, and law has be- come custom. This brings us, (3), to the sphere of customari- nesit the completion of the objective spirit. In customariness the spirit enters into its true reality ; the person finds the good outside of himself, as a reality to which he subordinates himself, as a moral world. Thus Hegel, deviating from the ordinary usage of language, distinguishes morality [moralitat] from customariness [sittlichkeit], conceiving the former as the merely subjective and individual morality, and the latter 46.] HEGELIAN ETHICS. 349 as civic or social morality. In the sphere of morality man is considered as an individual who determines himself accord- ing to abstract moral laws ; in that of customariness he is considered as an essential member of a moral community, of a moral whole, so that he now fulfills not abstract laws, but the requirements of the concrete-become spirit of a moral, social reality. Hence the end of customariness is primarily and immediately, not the individual, but the moral whole. The moral organisms constituted by reason as become object- ive, present themselves in the three development-stages of the family, of civil society (in which the individual subjects are bound together only by legal relations), and of the state, in which appears the full reality of morality. The state is the moral substance as conscious of itself, the objectively- realized moral and rational spirit, the union of the principle of the family and of civil society, the outer full realization of freedom, inasmuch as here the moral reality rests no longer (as in the case of the family) upon a nature-ground, and no longer (as in the case of civil society) upon merely outward legal relations, but upon the common conscious- ness wherein the individuals are conscious of themselves as organic members of the whole. Hence the state is the per se rational existence, the highest manifestation of moral reason in general. Hegel conceives the state in higher significancy than antecedent philosophers, namely, not as a mere means for the end of the individual citizens, but as end per se, to which the individual must sacrifice his particular and finite ends. This is a decided advance, especially in contrast to the utterly perverse and entirely anti- Christian state-doc- trine of the eighteenth century, when it was regarded as perfectly self-evident that the state has no other task than to serve the interests of individuals, whether the interests of the individual citizens of a state, or the interests of a class in society, or those of a prince, but not to fulfill a moral idea. But the state is also here the ultimate and high- est form of all morality, as, indeed, Hegel recognizes no higher existence yon-side the finite reality of the natural All, but not an absolutely self-existent, infinite, personal spirit. The purely moral reality of the church, which in its purely spir- itual interests is far above the necessary outward limitations 350 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [46. of the state, far above classes of society and national bound- aries, and has a super-mundane eternal goal, and which, as resting absolutely upon freedom, does not exert coercive power, finds no room for itself in Hegel's system. All morality, without exception, appertains to the state, and all reality of the church must be merged into it, a doctrine which of course was especially favorable to the absolutism of politics then in vogue. All that was usually ascribed to the church in its significancy for the moral, falls here to the state, while religion is regarded only as tlie basis, but not as the essential reality, of the moral spirit. "The state should be reverenced as an earthly-divine element ; the state is divine will as present and developing itself into the real form and organism of a world." Hence with Hegel, as also with the Greeks, morality is merged in the state, and has no significancy beyond it. " What man has to do, what the du- ties are which he has to fulfill, is, in a moral community, easy to determine : nothing else is to be done by him than that which is prescribed, expressed, and made known, in his rela- tions. " That this moral community may also be morally a very perverted one, and that consequently man may be morally obligated to resist it, and that even the most perfect actual state, does not embrace the whole field of the moral commu- nity-life, of all this the Hegelian system takes no account. In the carrying-out of the classification of the moral subject- matter, the " Philosophy of Right " varies largely in many places from the presentation given in the "Encyclopedia" and in the "Phenomenology of the Spirit." The transition from morality to customariness seems artificial and very ar- bitrary. The freedom of choice here largely brought into requisition is entirely without justification in the system, and even contradictory thereto. The classification itself is also not rigorously kept apart, nor indeed can it be ; the sphere of right falls largely into that of civil society, in so far as there is any real attempt at carrying it out ; and the protec- tion of right, which according to Hegel falls into the sphere of civil society, is utterly impossible without the state. Furthermore, it is worthy of note that Hegel, in perfect con- sistency with the principle naturally following from his sys- tem, namely, that "all that is real is also rational," regards 46.] DISCIPLES OF HEGEL. 351 war, not as an evil, but as a phenomenon necessarily con- nected with the highest moral community-life or the state, and, hence, as entirely rational, and which simply expresses in act the frailty and finiteness inherent in all finite being, and which has in the moral sphere the same inner necessity and normalcy, as death in the nature-sphere; war is death exalted into the moral sphere.* The Hegelian school, dividing itself soon after the master's death into a right wing, which progressively drew nearer to the Christian consciousness, and into a left wing, which sank lower and lower in the direction of radicalism and destruc- tiveness, has not produced any very important results in the ethical field. (Michelet gave a " System of Philosophical Ethics," 1828; Von Henning presented the "Principles of Ethics," historically, 1824); Vatke ("Human Freedom in its Relation to Sin and to Grace," 1841) develops, in opposition to Julius Muller's "Presentation of the Christian Doctrine of Sin," the Hegelian view in a very ingenious manner, with- out, however, succeeding in reconciling the unf reedom essen- tially inherent in the Pantheistic System with the general consciousness of moral freedom of choice ; evil, though re- garded as ultimately to be overcome, is yet held to be an absolutely necessary incident of the good. Daub and Mar- Tieineke undertook, in their ethical works, t the vain and thankless task of giving to the Pantheistic ground-thoughts of Hegel such a turn, and of clothing them in such forms of expression, as to make them appear as a higher scientific ex- pression of the Christian doctrines. But the rapidly disen- chanted age soon saw clearly enough the impossibility of this undertaking. Daub's Ethics, as edited from his lectures in an easy and often conversational style, though proposing to present Biblical ethics, is yet unwilling to derive the moral law from the Scriptures, but seeks for it only in reason, re- garding it as inherent therein, and forces the Biblical teach- ings, frequently with violence, into conformity to the already adopted system; the lofty self-complacency of the philoso- phizing theologian looks often contemptuously down upon * Phanomenol., p. 358 ; Phil, des Rechtt, pp. 417, 427, sqq. t Daub : Prolegomena sur Moral, 1839 ; System d. theol. Moral., 1840 ; Marheiueke: System d. theol. Moral., 1847. 352 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 46. the churchly consciousness, and oftener still, artfully explains away its significancy. Marheineke divides ethics into the doctrine of the law as the objective phase, into the doctrine of virtue as the subjective phase (virtue being taken as the harmonizing of the will with the law) and into the doctrine of duty. Despite a very pretentious style, the positive con- tents, consisting in many places merely in a loose series of single, and not always ingenious, and sometimes even insipid, observations, are really quite barren, and often involved in violent self-contradiction. The left wing of the Hegelian school, which strayed still further from the master in the direction of a vulgar Panthe- ism based on Spinoza, and which does not rise in the ethical field even to the honest consequentiality and earnestness of Spinoza, but, for the most part, sinks back into the most vulgar freethinking of French materialism, has shown itself utterly unfruitful in ethical works ; it has made itself felt, on the field of ethics, less by scientific productions than by im- pudent assertion. David Strauss is unwilling to admit the fatalistic necessity of all the individual phenomena of life, so consequentially affirmed by Spinoza ; but he gives scope, with- out hesitation, to chance and to arbitrary discretion, and affirms (of course without any justification in his system) even the freedom of the human will. What the world had not as yet known, Strauss presumes to assert, and takes the liberty of blankly contradicting the principle of Spinoza, that the hu- man will is a causa non lihera, sed coacta. In his view, Pan- theism alone guarantees the free self-dependence of man. If God is immanent in the world, and hence also in man ; if, as in the Christian world-theory, the finite stands over against the absolute Agent as a distinctly different object, then is this finite (the world) only in a condition of absolute passivity ; but in Pantheism the absolute actuosity lies in the collec- tivity of finite agencies, as their own activity. While in monotheism it holds good, that as truly as God is almighty so truly are men unfree, in Pantheism it holds good that as certainly as God is self-active so truly are men also so, in whom He is so.* What the drift of this special-pleading inference is, appears at once from the following observations : * Glaubenslehre, ii, 364. 46.] STRAUSS FEUERBACH. 353 "This holds good, of course, only of our conception of the divine essence; whether it holds good also in the recip- rocal relation of finite things, where Spinoza denies it, is another question, and one which does not concern us in this place." He makes, however, in this connection, in order to maintain against Spinoza the freedom of the will, also the following very curious observation : "Spinoza declares indi- vidual man as unfree, for the reason that only that determined- ness of his essence and activity remains to him which all other tilings leave to him; but in this connection he overlooked the fact that also, conversely, only that much remains to all other things which the individual leaves to them ; this is of course not freedom of choice, but it is also not coercion." The honest Spinoza would doubtless have shaken his head in as- tonishment at this naive objection. Strauss, naturally enough, recognizes also, as the highest moral reality, the state as sepa- rated from the church and as entirely swallowing it up within itself ; in the place of the worshiping of God must be substi- tuted art, and especially the theater; for genuine morality, that is, for the life in the state, religion is not only super- fluous but hurtful ; for whoever thinks he has, outside of his duties as a citizen of the state, still other duties as a citizen of heaven, will, as a servant of two masters, necessarily neglect the first class of duties.* In this expression of opin- ion he gives to governments a very significant hint, as to how dangerous for the state is an ecclesiastically pious dis- position in the people, and how great is the duty of an en- lightened government to guard against it. Lewis Feuerbach, who finds in religion only a morbid delusion, namely, in that man regards his own being as a divine object, declares re- ligion, and especially the Christian religion, as the destruction of morality, inasmuch as it makes the validity of the moral law dependent on religious faith. Nature is every thing, and exclusively so ; to follow the voice of nature is the highest principle of morality. This voice, however, teaches us love to our fellow-men, whereas religion teaches only hatred against those who believe differently from us, and directs the love and activity of man, not toward other men, but to- ward a non-existing being God ; only the religiouless man * Glaubenslehre, ii, 615 sqq. 354 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 46. can have universal love to man, which is per se always practi- cal atheism, namely, a denial of God in heart, in sentiment, and in act. For a scientific justification of these wonderful assertions we seek in vain; morbid bombast supplies its place. That this theory of morality must lead to the vul- garest enjoyment- seeking, is perfectly natural ; and Feuerbach himself explains himself as to the nature of this morality of human love, very clearly, thus: "When I am hungry then nothing is more important to me than the enjoyment of food, after the meal, nothing more than rest, and after rest, nothing more than exercise; after exercise, nothing more than conversation with friends ; after the completion of the work of the day, I court the Brother of Death as the most beneficent of beings ; thus every moment of the life Of man has something, but nota bene! something human in it."* Thus the philosophy of " modern science " has returned, in rapid circuit, back to the morality of French materialism, to the practical morality of Philip of Orleans under Louis XV. The more advanced and almost insane productions of the still more "radical" circle, especially of the circle of "emanci- pated" ones, which formed itself around Bruno and Edgar Bauer, and by whom even Feuerbach was soon stigmatized (Max Stirner) as belonging among "theologians," "believing hypocrites " and " slavish natures," belong not in the sphere of a history of science, but, at best, only in that of the his- tory of the morals of the nineteenth century. We will mention additionally, in passing, only the material- istic world-theory, which, though not directly springing from the Pantheistic philosophy, yet coincides with it in its ulti- mate results, and which has its origin more in the empirical study of nature than in philosophy, and which in its moral riews has sunk back to the French materialism of the Systeme de la Nature (Moleschott, Vogt, Biichner, etc.). If spirit is sim- ply a phenomenon of brain-force, and if man is nothing more than a highly organized animal, then the moral catechism is very easy and short. Vogt declares it as presumption in man to pretend to be any thing essentially different from the brute ; man belonged originally to the ape race, and has only gradu- * Werkt, i, 355. 47.] VOGT MOLESCHOTT. 355 ally developed himself somewhat more highly. Man is guided and impelled, just as the brute, by his own nature, that is, by the laws of his material existence, and with inner irresist- ible necessity; every so-called act of the will is strictly a necessary product of the material conditions of the brain and of the outer sensuous impressions, as determined by nutrition and by the peculiarity of the brain-substance. Hence also there can be no manner of moral responsibility; all so-called sins and crimes are only "consequences of a defective nutri- tion and of an imperfect organization of the brain." The distinguishing between morally good and evil actions is merely a self-deception; "to comprehend every thing in- volves also the justifying of every thing, " says Moleschott. Hence, the moral amelioration of man takes place solely through suitable and strengthening nutrition. " The more fully we are conscious that by the proper proportioning of carbonic acid, ammonia, and the salts, etc., we are contrib- uting to the highest development of mankind, so much the more are also our efforts and work ennobled." Upon eating and drinking, these writers naturally enough lay very great emphasis ; it appears to them as a sacred rite, and Moleschott is not ashamed even to compare it with the holy eucharist. It was also reserved for this writer to stigmatize the Christian world-theory and Christian custom as detrimental to the public good, and for this, among other reasons, that thereby the national wealth suffers a considerable loss from the prac- tice of burying corpses in special graveyards, whereas the bodies of the dead should rather be used for manuring the fields. Those who look always for the truth simply in a "progress" beyond that which has hitherto been known and practiced, can perhaps inform us what the next further progress beyond this world-theory will lead to. SECTION XL VII. The philosophical ethics of the two last decades, based in general on Hegel or on Herbart, shows a manifestly growing approximation to the Christian world-theory ; but because of the rather unphilosophi- 24 356 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 47. cally-inclined spirit of the age, it has exerted less in- fluence upon society at large than the immediately preceding philosophy. The most recent times have suddenly shown, after an ex- cessive and almost morbid intensity of enthusiasm for philoso- phy, an all the greater lack of earnest interest therein. The excessive expectations were soon followed by discouraging disappointments; and while at the beginning of the century the most crude products of philosophy, if they were only presented with assurance, were sure of an enthusiastic wel- come, the, in general, far more mature and more scientific and profound works of recent times have met with but cold indifference ; and though the philosophers of the present day have some reasons to complain of the thanklessness of the educated world, and that only ambitious rhetoric is now able to win applause, nevertheless this state of things is clearly explainable as a reaction from the wild intoxication of the past. Nearly contemporaneously with Hegel wrote Herbart of Konigsberg. Taking up his position outside of the histor- ical development-course of philosophy, and, in keen skepti- cism, discarding the unity of the principle of reality, he had in his elegantly written " Practical Philosophy " (1808) thrown open a new path. In his view the previous treatment of ethics, as the doctrine of goods, of virtues and of duties, makes the will of a twofold character a norming or com- manding one, and a derived or obeying one, and hence makes of the will its own regulator ; but this is impossible and absurd. On the contrary, a will-less judgment as to willing precedes all actual willing; this judgment cannot command, but only approve or disapprove; but it never acts upon the will as strictly isolated!, but always as a member of a relation. Hence all willing presu'pposes moral taste, which has pleasure in the morally-beautif uf ; thus the moral is conceived essen- tially esthetically. The esthetical judgment as to the will leads it to action, but not necessarily ; the will should be obe- dient, but it can be disobedient ; taste is immutable, the will is flexible ; thus manifests itself the idea of inner freedom. Together with this idea Herbart assumes still others, ideas 47.] HERBART CHALYBAUS. 357 which are connected, but reduced to no real unity, with this idea, and which precede all exertion of will, namely, the ideas of perfection, of benevolence, of right, and of fitness ; by virtue of these five ideas the moral taste passes upon an act of the will, directly and involuntarily, a judgment of ap- proval or disapproval. The full realization of the moral is society^as expressing itself in different stages. This work of Herbart, though little regarded in its day, contains in its details many profound and ingenious thoughts ; the violently original character of the whole is very stimulating, but not satisfying; the unity* of the theory as a whole is defective. Hartenstein wrote in the spirit of Herbart, his "Fundamental Notions of the Ethical Sciences," 1844, a work full of thought, and presenting^ a much more candid view of the realities of life than the writers of the Hegelian school, and not unfrequently assailing Schleiermacher and Hegel with keenness and success. As primitive ethical ideas, he assumes those of inner freedom, of benevolence, of right and of fitness. Similarly also Allihn: "Fundamental Doctrines of General Ethics," 1861. (Beneke: "Elements of Ethics," 1837, en- tirely empirical, and only partially basd on Herbart. Ehenich: "Moral Philosophy," 1830, based on evangelically- modified Kantian views.) The "Speculative Ethics" (1841) of Wirth sprang from the Hegelian school, but deviates therefrom in many respects ; the Pantheistic fundamental view is not entirely overcome ; (ethics is "the science of the absolute spirit as will realiz- ing its absolute self-consciousness into its likewise infinite reality ; " in details it offers many good thoughts, though also many mere empty phrases, especially where it treats of relig- ious" morality; to close the development of ethics with an amateur-theater as one of the most important moral agencies, is surely a very odd fancy). ChalyMm of Kiel: "System of Speculative Ethics," 1850, doubtless the most important treatise on philosophical ethics in modern times. Chalybaus, in his work, breaks entirely away from the Pantheistic view of Hegel, and treats ethics on the basis of the idea of per- sonal freedom, and does not, as Hegel, regard the ideal and the real as in perfect harmony, but on the contrary recog- nizes evil as merely possible in virtue of freedom, and hence 358 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [47. its reality as only fortuitous and guiltily-incurred, but not as necessary. A candid, sound view of reality is combined with an ingenious development of thought in clear vigorous lan- guage ; and notwithstanding a few cases of the lowering of Christian doctrines, this philosophical ethics expresses the Christian consciousness, in many cases, more faithfully than does Rothe's "Theological Ethics." Also J. H. FWte (son of the philosopher) places himself in his " System of Ethics," 1850, upon a decidedly theistical stand-point, and strongly emphasizes the idea of personality, whiph in Hegel falls into so dubious a back-ground. (The essence of the moral ap- pears as love, which, as an "unselfing of the personal ego," is carried out somewhat one-sidedly so far as to throw the valid- ity of self and of right quite too much into the back-ground.) K. P. Fischer (of Erlangen): "Elements of a System of Speculative Ethics," 1851, briefer than the preceding works, freighted with thought, likewise an essential advance of re- cent philosophy toward a deeper comprehension of the Chris- tian consciousness. (Martensen : " Outlines of a System of Moral Philosophy," 1845. Schliephake: " The Bases of the Moral Life," 1855, inspired by Krause, empirical toward the close, but keen and judicious). In this place belongs also, in part, the ingenious and deeply Christian work of StaJil : " The Philosophy of Right "* based in the beginning rather on Schelling, but afterward more independent ; the idea of the human personality as a copy of the personality of God is, in contrast to all naturalistic philosophy, raised to the full sig- nificancy and to the foundation of all morality and of all right. (The preposterously original Schopenhauer goes back to In- dian conceptions, and finds morality only in an annihilating of the individuality. The will to live is the root of all evil ; the denying of this will is virtue. The will must turn away from existence, must turn to will-lessness ; for existence is ab- solutely null, and the will a delusion, from which we must become free. Vulgar suicide is indeed not right, for it is a phenomenon of a strongly-affirming will ; on the contrary, a voluntary starving of one's self to death is a real moral sacri- *1830, 3'ed., 1851. 48.] THEOLOGICAL ETHICS. 359 ficing of the will to live. "The two Fundamental Problems of Ethics," 1841; "The World as Will and Conception," 1819, '44, '60.) SECTION XLVIH. The, Theological ethics of the nineteenth century, in so far as it came not into a relation of complete dependence upon some particular philosopher of the day, remained either upon a purely Biblical ground, making no use or only a very moderate use of philo- sophical thoughts, or assumed a rather eclectico-phil- osophical character. Rationalism proved surprisingly unfruitful. Ethics was treated in a predominantly original manner by Schleiermacher, in a widely differing and irreconcilable double-form of philosophical and of theological ethics, in the former case entirely irre- spective of the God-consciousness, and in the latter, from the inner nature of the pious Christian con- sciousness, with great richness and ingenuity of thought, but also without a rigidly scientific form, and, in a violently-revolutionary originality, in many cases beclouding the Biblical view with foreign thoughts. Rothe shaped his "Theological Ethics" into a system of theosophic speculation, resting upon the philosophy of Hegel and Schleiermacher, but carried out in an unclear originality, covering almost the entire field of Christian doctrine, constituting a work in which a pious mind, and exotic thoughts deeply endangering the Christian consciousness, go hand in hand. Although the scientific treatment of the subject-matter of ethics in the earlier and (in the main) Biblical moralists of the nineteenth century, may be regarded as relatively feeble, 360 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [48. yet they have this not to be despised significancy, that in an age almost entirely estranged from Biblical Christianity they kept alive the consciousness of this estrangement, and faith- fully held fast to the indestructible bases of Christian Ethics. ReinharcTs "System of Christian Ethics" (1780-1815) has indeed neither any special depth of thought nor a rigidly scientific form, and contains many insipid and useless discus- sions, and furnishes no just comprehension of the inner essence of the moral idea ; but yet it gives indication of a thorough examination of the Scriptures, and of an unpreju- diced observation of real life, furnishing often in detail good and morally earnest discussions, and avoiding all eccen- tricity. His classification of the whole is poorly adapted to give a clear steadily-progressive development of the subject- matter. In his third edition Reinhard declares himself very decidedly against Kant. Flatt of Tubingen in his "Lect- ures on Christian Ethics" (published by Steudel in 1823) gives only carefully-compiled, purely Biblical material, with- out impressing upon it a scientific form. F. H. C. ScJiicarz of Heidelberg in his "Evangelically-Christian Ethics," 1821, presents ethics in two different forms, in the first vol- ume in a scientific, in the second in an edificatory form, but which is designed to serve at the same time in elucidation of the first, presenting for the most part a simple evangelical view, brief, clear, but without deeper foundation. De Wette has furnished a threefold treatment of ethics, which more than the above-mentioned works is imbued with philosophical thoughts (from the stand-point of the Kantian Fries). His "Christian Ethics" (1819) one half of which is occupied by the history of ethics (which is introduced be- tween the general and the special part), is more ingenious than profound, and does not appreciate the full significancy of the evangelical consciousness. His "Lectures on Chris- tian Ethics," 1824, are intended for a wider circle of readers. (His Compendium of Christian Ethics, 1833, is only a brief outline.) With the exception of this rather Rationalistic than evangelical treatment of ethics, Rationalism has, con- trary to what might have been expected, produced but very little in the ethical field. The next most noticeable work is Amman's (comp. 43) later "Hand-book of Christian 48.] SCHLEIERMACHER. 361 Ethics." (1823, '38), scientifically very unimportant, and con- taining, besides many examples and anecdotes, mostly only commonplace thoughts and mere objective observations, without in any degree going into the depth of the subject. Biiumgarten-Crusius in his "Compendium," * breaks already, in many respects, with Rationalism ; his work is ill-digested, but in many respects instructive. KaJiler, in his "Christian Ethics" (1833; a "Scientific Abridgment," 1835) hesitat- ingly endeavors to rise beyond the Rationalistic stand-point, and gives much that is peculiar, and also much that is super- fluous. Philosophical and theological ethics were treated very profoundly and very peculiarly, but in a manner violently revolutionary and different from all precedent treatment of the subject, by Schleiermacher; indeed in no other science does the inner and unmediated scientific dualism of this writer appear so prominently as here. His critical acumen, his restlessly changing and almost fitfully metamorphosing productiveness, showed itself here under the most brilliant forms ; but there is for that reason all the greater need of a cautious guarding against being deceived by the arts of his dialectic genius. Introduced into the field of philosophy by the study of the Greeks, and especially of Plato, enthusi- astic for Spinoza, and building mostly upon him, but also powerfully incited by Fichte and Schelling, and uniting in himself the collective, anti-historical and anti-Christian cul- ture of his day, Schleiermacher was not able to harmonize his Pantheistic and unhistorical metaphysics with his heart- Christianity, which latter, though sometimes drooping and wounded, yet grew constantly more and more vital with the advance of his years ; he left these two forces standing side- by-side in his soul, and honestly entertained and expressed religious convictions with which his philosophical opinions stood in irreconcilable antagonism ; and it would be a great mistake to undertake to interpret the ones by the others. Schleiermacher did not rise above this inner dualism, a state which not every mind would be able to endure. In his first period, he manifested in the field of ethics a keen critical power, but also as yet great unclearness as to the * Lehrbuch, 1826. 362 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 48. positive essence of Christian morality; and he did not keep free from some of the serious errors of the uncurbed spirit of the age. The moral laxity of the " geniuses " then reign- ing supreme in the world of letters, threw its dusky shadows also over this mighty spirit. His justificatory "Letters" 011 Schlegel's immoral "Lucinde, " 1800, were of a nature to be used, and unfortunately not without ground, by Gutzkow in countenancing the " rehabilitation of the flesh" which was then taught by this writer, and in casting reproach upon the sacredness of wedlock.* In his "Discourses on Religion," 1799, which breathe a Spinozistic spirit under the drapery of poetic rhetoric, Schleiermacher declares also evil as belonging to, and co-ordinate in, the beauty of the universe. Morality rests upon religion. In his "Monologues," 1800, which em- phasize the ethical phase, there is manifested a bold, high- aiming self- feeling, the full, overflowing self-consciousness of the youthful genius. Self-examination appears here as the basis and fountain of all wisdom, not indeed in the sense, that man is to compare himself in his reality with an idea or a divinely-revealed law, in order to arrive at humility and at a consciousness of his need of redemption, but on the contrary it is an immersing of self in one's own immediate genial reality as the fountain of all truth and strength, a full, self-satisfying enjoyment of self, a pride-inspired self- mirroring of a nobly-aspiring spirit, f Though this unhumble spirit of self-enjoying was not peculiar to him, but was rather the spirit then dominant among the excessively self- conscious "geniuses" of the day, still there hiy therein the germ of an ethico-scientific peculiarity of Schleiermacher, as against the Kantian school. In the latter, individual man is a mere moral exemplar shaped after a general pattern, merely a single fulfiller of an impersonal moral law, the essence of which consists precisely in not recognizing the peculiarity of the person, but in throwing it off, and in giv- ing validity only to the general. Schleiermacher maintains, on the contrary, that every man is to represent humanity in a * Comp. Vorlander's : ScMeierm.'s Sittenlehre, p. 69 ; C. H. Weisse in Tholuck's Litter. Am., 1835, 408 sqq. ; Twesten, in his preface to Schleiermacher's Grundriss, p. 76 sqq. t Compare the dissenting judgment of Twesten, idem, p. 83 sqq. 48.] H SCHLEIERMACHER. 363 peculiar manner, and that, accordingly, it is the very opposite of correct to propose to one's self simply the question, " whether this my maxim is adapted to be exalted into a law for all men." Even as the artist does not produce an object of beauty by representing simply abstract, mathematic- ally-correct forms, but by expressing that which is individu- ally-peculiar, so is also the moral man to be an artist, an artist whose task it is to develop himself into a personally peculiar art-work, and not merely into a monotonous expres- sion of the species. He is not to strip off, but, on the con- trary, artistically to develop, his personal peculiarity, he is not to cast himself down before duty as a thought different from his individual personality, but rather on the contrary "constantly to become more fully what he is ; this is his sole desire." Thus Schleiermacher, in opposing the Kantian one- sidedness, involves himself in the opposite one ; both posi- tions are equally true and equally untrue, and the Christian view stands in the middle-ground between them. If the Kantian view answers rather to the Old Testament law-system, then that of Schleiermacher would answer rather to the Chris- tian idea of the freedom of the children of God (at least, in case it were applied to spiritually-regenerated children of God, which, however, is not the case), so that consequent- ly the presentiment of the higher truth turns into untruth, into a perilous holding-fast to self, ariQ this all the more so for the reason that it is absolutely and independently based upon mere self, for "from within came the high revelation, produced by no teachings of virtue and by no system of the The "Elements of a Criticism of Preceding Ethics," 1803, able but in a heavy and often unclear style, and hence more celebrated than known, relate only to philosophical ethics, and discard, in keen but sometimes unjust criticism, all previ- ous methods of treating this science, and present (as opposed to the more usual method of treating of ethics as the doctrine of virtues or duties) the doctrine of goods as the basis of the science, and, hence, ethics as an analysis of the highest good; the good is the objective realization of the moral. The criti- cism of the work is applied not so much to the contents as to the scientific form, and seeks to show that the contents can be 364 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. " [ 48. true only when the form is perfect ; there is no other criterion of truth in ethics than the scientific form. Plato and Spinoza are esteemed most highly. In explaining away the almost unbounded self-feeling of the author, large account must be made for the spirit of the times; less care is given to the demonstration of his own view than to the many-sided assail- ing of the views of others. The "Sketch of a System of Ethics" (published in 1835 by Schweizer, from Schleiermacher's posthumous papers, in an imperfect digest of different sketches ; in a briefer and more general form in 1841 as "Outlines of Philosophical Ethics" with an introductory preface by Twesten) * rests upon the philosophy of Spinoza and the earlier views of Schelling, but contains speculations in many respects peculiar, and not always sufficiently developed. In this philosophical ethics Schleier- macher leaves entirely out of consideration the Christian consciousness, and indeed the religious consciousness in general, knows nothing of a personal God as moral Law- giver, nor of an immortal personal Spirit independent of nature; this religious basis is left so entirely in the back- ground that Schleiermacher (as late as in 1825) answered the question : whence, then, arose in the moral law the idea of a " should," which seems to refer to a commanding will ? by saying, that in the Jewish legislation the divine will had been conceived as of a*magisterial character demanding obe- dience ; and that this form had also been adopted in Christian instruction, and " thus arose the custom of associating with moral knowledge also the ' should,' and this custom was re- tained even after men had begun to reduce moral knowledge to a general form, wherein there was no longer any reference to an outwardly-revealed divine will, but human reason itself was regarded as the legislating factor." f The two manifes- tation-forms of God in Spinoza, namely, thought and exten- sion, and the primitive antithesis of Schelling, reappear here as the antithesis of the universe in reason and nature, in. the ideal and the real. The highest antithesis in the world is the an- tithesis of material (known) and of spiritual (knowing) exist- ence. The existence in which the former element predominates *Comp. Vorlander : Schleierm? ' Sittenlehre, 1851, keen and clear but not evangelical. t Werlce, iii, 2, 403. 48.] " SCHLEIERMACHER. 365 is nature; the existence in which the knowing element predomi- nates is reason, the two appearing in man as body and soul. Hence reason is essentially knowing, and. in so far as it is self- active, willing. Speculative reason is ethics, which has, then, physics over against itself, the two embracing the whole field of science, so that ethics appears essentially as the collective philosophy of the spirit, an entirely unjustifiable deviation from all previous nomenclature.* Ethics presents the col- lective operation Of active human reason upon nature. Hence the aim of moral effort is, the perfect interpenetration of rea- son and nature, a permeation of nature by reason, and indeed of all nature in so far as standing in connection with human nature. This interpenetration is the highest good,t the sum total of all single goods ; it is embodied in the thought of the Golden Age, where man dominated absolutely over nature, and in the thought of everlasting peace, of the perfection of knowledge, and in the thought of a kingdom of heaven, and in a free communion of the highest self-consciousness by means of spiritual self-representation. In the individual the attain- ment of the moral goal appears as personal perfection, as a perfect unity of nature with intelligence, and hence as a per- fect blessedness. But the unity of reason and nature is to" be conceived in a threefold manner : (1) In reference to the end- point of the moral striving, namely, the real unity of reason and nature, as the highest good ; herein is embraced the mul- tiplicity of particular manifestations of said unity, and hence of good ; this is ethics as the doctrine of goods or as the doc- trine of the highest good; (2) in reference to the beginning- point of the moral striving, namely, the efficiency of reason in human nature, and hence said unity conceived as power, that is, as virtue, the doctrine of virtue ; \ (3) in reference to the relation between the beginning-point and the end-point, and hence in the movement of the power toward the goal, and consequently a modus operandi of reason in realizing the high- est good; this is the doctrine of duties.^ Hence a threefold * See his discussion of the difference between natural and moral law : Werke, iu, 2, 397. t Ueber das hocJiste Gut, 1827, '30 ; Werlce, iii, 2, 446. J Comp. Abh. ub. d. Behundlung des Tugendbegriffs, 1819 ; idem 850. Comp. Abh. ub. d. Behandlung des Pftlchtbegrifes, 1824; idem 379. 366 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [48. manner of presenting ethics is possible and necessary ; each embraces really the whole field of the moral, but as considered from a different point of view, each, however, refers to the others. In giving all the goods, one must give at the same time all the virtues and duties, and the converse. However, the doctrine of goods is the most self-based and independent, because it embraces the ultimate goal. ''Every definite ex- istence is good in so far as it is a world for itself, a copy of absolute being, and hence in the disappearing of the antithe- ses";* a good is "every harmony of particular phases of rea- son and nature," that wherein "the interpenetration of rea- son and of nature is independently brought about, in so far as this unity of reason and nature bears itself like the whole in an organic manner. t The doctrine of goods alone is fully de- veloped, while the doctrine of virtue and of duties is treated but very briefly and meagerly. In the doctrines of goods Schleiermacher distinguishes -a twofold moral activity : (1) In so far as reason exerts itself upon nature as external to it, it is organizing, in that it makes nature an organ of reason ; (2) in so far as the interpretation of reason and nature is already posited, the activity of reason is of a symbolizing character, in that it makes itself recogniz- able in its work. These two activities manifest themselves in turn in two different manners. In as far, namely, as reason is the same in all men, in so far also these two activities are alike in all ; but in as far as individual men are originally and in their very idea different from each other, in so far also is the activity of an individual character, shaping itself in a peculiar manner in each individual. This notion of a legitimate per- sonal peculiarity, Schleiermacher emphasizes very strongly, without, however, really grounding it philosophically. Virtue expresses itself either as enlivening or as militant: as enliven- ing, it expresses the harmonious union of reason and nature ; as militant, it overcomes the resistance of nature ; under anoth- er phase it is either cognoscitive or representative; thus we arrive at four cardinal virtues : the enlivening virtue as cognoscitive or representative is wisdom or soundness of judgment; as repre- sentative it is love ; the militant virtue as cognoscitive is pru- * System, p. 54. t Ibid. , p. 7 2. 48.] SCHLEIERMACHER. 367 dence; as representative it is persistence. (In his academical Dissertation on the notion of virtue, Schleiermacher varies in form somewhat from his System of Ethics.) The very unequal currying out of the subject in detail presents, together with great acumen, also much unsound and fruitless sophistry ; the brilliant thoughts shoot forth in every direction in sharp-cut crystal-gleams before the dazzled eye of the beholder, but often only to dissolve themselves suddenly again into a state of form- less fluidity. The interrupted, incomplete, un-uniform presenta- tion, as given in the hastily-edited edition, render the reading of this work very difficult, and the ethical results appear by no means so rich as, from the pretensions of the system, one might be led to expect ; and it is often impossible to resist the impression that the work abounds in unprofitable sophistry. The academ- ical Essays that belong here, though ably developed, present after all but mere fragments of the whole. A wholly different picture is furnished by the Theological Ethics, which was edited by Jonas in 1843, from Schleier- macher's posthumous papers, and from notes written by his hearers, under the title: "Christian Ethics according to the Principles of the Evangelical Church." * The idea of the moral is developed from the Christianly-determined self-conscious- ness ; hence ethics is the analysis and presentation of the Chris- tian self-consciousness, in so far as the same tends to pass over into act. The moral subject is not considered as a mere iso- lated individual, but predominantly as being a member of the Church, and as influenced by the spirit of the Church. The state of the human self-consciousness as in communion with God through Christ, is salvation and blessedness. This salvation, however, is primarily merely an incomplete but progressive one, seeing that we are always still in need of redemption ; hence our life is a constant alternation of pleasure and unpleasure, and therein lies an "impulse" to activities in view of arriving at true blessedness. In unpleasure lies the impulse to a man- ner of action whereby the momentarily-disturbed normal state is to be restored, that is, a restorative or purifying manner of action ; in pleasure lies the impulse to a manner of action which subordinates a lower life-power (as willingly yielding itself to a higher one) directly and without any resistance to the higher * Die christliche Sitte, etc. 368 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [48. one, thus educating the lower power, and, hence, deepening and extending the harmony of the two, the deepening and ex- tending manner of acting. Both manners of acting aim at effecting something, at bringing about a change, and, hence, constitute unitedly the operative form of action, whereby man is to pass from one condition into another. The purifying form of action relates primarily to Christian communion, and appears as Church-discipline and as Church-reform (reformatory action) ; and then again, in relation to civil society, as domestic discipline, as the administration of civil justice, as State- reformation, and as purifying action in the relation of one state to another. The extending form of action, which is essen- tially the educating of the, as yet lower,, but willing life through the higher, takes place primarily in the sphere of the Church, aims to widen and intensify the efficaciousness of the Holy Spirit as dwelling in the Church, and of Christian sentiment. This presupposes the propagation of the human race, the pro- duction of human personalities. Hence the extending form of activity in the Church is primarily the communion of the sexes, and then the inner extending and heightening of the life of the Church. Then also the extending form of action relates to the state, and looks to the training of all human talents, and to the transforming of nature for the spirit, in both cases as one common act of all the individuals belonging to the human race, and hence a maturing of all the citizens through spiritual and material commerce ; (in this connection it is treated of property, of trade, of money, etc.). This is the first part of ethics, that which embraces the operative form of action. Now, between the moments of pleasure and unpleasure there occur moments of satisfaction (and which are consequently distinguished from those of pleasure), that is, of relative bless- edness, the fundamental feeling proper of the Christian, and which is at the same time also an impulse to acting. This acting, however, aims not at effecting a change, but only at revealing itself outwardly, at making known its condition of happiness to others, and hence is not an operative but a repre- sentative acting. The operative form of acting is only the way for attaining to the perfect dominion of the spirit over the flesh, that is, to the feeling of blessedness ; and the active 48.] SCHLEIERMACHER. 369 expression of this feeling and of this dominion is the repre- sentative form of action, which manifests this inner self-con- sciousness by means of communion with others, and hence from motives of love. The essence of love is the inner neces- sity of the constant intercommunion of self-consciousness as separated by personality, rests upon communion, and devel- ops it to a higher degree. Although the representative form of action takes its rise from the communion of the subject with God, yet this communion is mediated by the Holy Spirit that dwells in the Christian society. Hence the representative fonn of action relates primarily to the evangelically-religious com- munion, is divine worship, or the sum total of all actions whereby we present ourselves as organs of God by means of the Holy Spirit ; it embraces, in the wider sense, also the vir- tues of chastity, patience, endurance, humility, in so far as in them is manifested the dominion of the flesh over the spirit. Then again, this form of action relates to general human communion, which is the outer sphere of this action, as divine worship is the inner, in other words, the sphere of social life, the representative form of action in the intercourse of men, as not immediately connected with Christian communion, not, however, as an operative form of action, but predominantly merely as beholding and enjoying. In this connection, Schleier- macher considers, first, the social life proper, and particu- larly social intercourse in eating and drinking under circum- stances of luxury and decoration, and, then, art, and lastly play. However much we may admire the creative genius whereby Schleiermacher endeavored to establish and carry out his highly peculiar classification of ethics, still in reality we can- not but declare it as unadapted and unsuccessful ; and, in spite of the great and almost idolizing admiration shown by the public for the skillful thought- artist, this piece of art has not succeeded in calling forth any imitation. At the very r tirst glance one recognizes the utter unnaturalness of making Chris- tian ethics begin with Church-discipline and Church-reforma- tion, and close with the subject of play ; while, in the second part, is presented the widening form of action in Church-com- munion, and, in the third, the ecclesiastical worship of God, as also the unnaturalness of placing sexual communion along- 370 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 48. side of Church-communion as simply its presupposition, and of treating it only subsequently to the discussion of Church- discipline and domestic discipline, and of treating of four Christian virtues, in isolation from all the others, under the head of divine worship, and among them that of chastity, which of course falls under the head of sexual communion, whereas in fact all and every other of the Christian virtues might with just as good right be treated under the rubric of divine worship. The chief subdivisions of Christian acting as purifying, extending and representative acting, cannot by any means be sharply separated from each other ; on the contrary, in each one of them also the other is necessarily involved ; the extending or distributive acting is not possible otherwise than by a representing. At all events the purifying activity could not be the first, for the obtaining and confirming of life-com- munion with God must, as moral activities, precede the purify- ing of the already-obtained communion. The feelings of pleasure and displeasure are, as pure states of experience, not by any means per se the bases of the Christianly-moral activ- ity ; both feelings may per se be just as readily immoral as moral ; and the first moral striving must be directed to the end that the pleasure and displeasure themselves be moral, whereas they are here presupposed unconditionally as " impulses " to the moral ; but this system of ethics is not written for saints (who might indeed be regarded as determining themselves by the simple feeling of pleasure or unpleasure per se), since it sets out with a purifying form of action, relating to the subject himself. It is true, Schleiermacher brings this pleasure and displeasure into relation to communion with God; but the apostle distinguishes, also in the saints, a pleasure and a dis- pleasure in this God-communion (Rom. vii, 22 sqq.) ; hence if there exists also in the Christian, before his final perfection, as yet an unpious pleasure and an impious displeasure, it follows that the moral striving must in fact direct itself primarily upon this pleasure and unpleasure. Furthermore, the entirely unu- sual separating of the pious pleasure-feeling and of the blessed- ness-feeling (so fully that two chief-divisions of ethics are based thereupon), is neither justifiable nor practical. The objective goal of the moral activity, that is, the doctrine of moral good, is rather presupposed than developed. Knowledge or Chris- 48.] ROTHE. 871 tian \visdom is thrown quite disproportionately in the back- ground, behind the subjects of feeling, of disposition, and of acting. In general we find, notwithstanding the great dialec- tic art employed, especially in the analysis of ideas, still quite frequently an indefiniteness and unfruitfulness of the moral ideas in their practical significancy, an excessive prominence of the subjective peculiarity and a corresponding unprominence of a simple Biblical spirit. The ecclesiastical element with which, from unecclesiastical quarters, Schleiermacher has been reproached, is in fact reduced in him to its merest minimum. " With the exception of the free activity of the Holy Ghost nothing is to be regarded as absolutely fixed by the Holy Scriptures, but every thing as accepted only provisionally, and to be regarded as remaining subject to a constant revision." All symbolical settlings of doctrine are Romanizing, and must be made revocable.* We cannot see, however, why precisely the activity of the Holy Ghost is to be regarded as an abso- lutely-established point, and not also subject to a constant re- vision, why it is not " revocable " ; and just as little can we see why this activity, if it is valid at all, should not lead to a real knowledge of the truth, and hence to a definitively-estab- lished knowledge. Richard Rotht, standing in part upon Schleiermacher's stand-point, but also making use of Hegelian and Schel- lingian philosophy in combination with his own somewhat peculiar and daring form of speculation, furnishes, in his "Theological Ethics" (1845-'49, thoroughly revised, 1867) a system of theosophy embracing also a large portion of dog- matics and even some extra-theological topics, which, how- ever much we may admire its erudition and earnest thought- labor, yet, in view of its wonderful commingling of Christian faith, extra-Christian philosophy and extra-philosophical fantasy, we cannot avoid regarding as a failure. Rothe manifests, in contrast to a large number of more recent speculative theologians, an estimable sense for scientific honesty ; and where he deviates from the ecclesiastical and Biblical view (and this occurs in very essential and funda- mental things) there he does not disguise the antithesis in fine-sounding words ; not every one, however, could succeed * CJirittl. Sittc., etc., eil., p. 184. 25 372 CHKISTIAN ETHICS. [48. so naively as Rothe in harmonizing with a pious faith in other respects, such questionable contradictions to the general Christian consciousness as are found, e. g., in his doctrines of the omniscience of God (which he limits to the past, the present, and the necessary), and in his doctrine of the church (which he treats in the spirit of entire anti-ecclesiasticism). His merely-apparently profound and frequently very un- bridled speculations do not constitute a steadily progressive ana regularly-developed line of thought, but are in many respects mere plays of thought and fantasy ; and it is only after passing through these portions of the work (which, though treated with a certain amateur-fondness, are yet really very unfruitful of ethical results, and are presented in a not unfrequently sadly misused language), that we enter, in the third part, upon a frequently excellent, beautifully-presented, and really ethical current of thought, though not without also occasionally meeting with surprising eccentricities. Rothe's view of ethics as a science we have already men- tioned ( 3, 4). The moral task of man is, by virtue of his free self-determination, to appropriate material nature to his own personality; hence the idea of the moral is: "the real unity of the personality and of material nature, a unity as im- pressed upon nature by the personality itself in virtue of its nature-determining functions, or, the unity of the personality and of material nature as the appropriatedness of the latter to the former." Morality is an independent something along- side of piety, and rests by no means upon piety, is entirely co-ordinate to and independent of it. Ethics falls into three divisions: it considers (1) the moral as being a product, that is, the pure and full manifestation of the moral in the un- folded totality of its special moments and of their organiza- tion into unity, that is, the moral world in its completeness the doctrine of goods. The good is the normal real unity of the personality and of material nature, the appropriatedness of the latter to the former. Here Rothe considers, first, the highest good as an abstract ideal, irrespective of sin ; (in this connection are treated also of six forms of moral communion, of which the highest and most comprehensive is the State, which is ultimately destined to embrace all moral life, and to absorb the communion of piety, namely, the church, into 48.] ROTHE. 873 itself ; the church has only a transitional significancy, but the state a higher, permanent one). Hereupon follows a com- plete treatment of eschatology. The other, next-following, phase is the highest good in its concrete reality ; here it is treated, first, of sin, as something inhering in human nature, and hence necessary and originally co-posited in the divine world-plan ; and, then, of redemption, where a complete doc- trine of redemption is presented. (2) The causality or power bringing forth this product, that is, virtue, and hence the doc- trine of virtue, is treated of in the second part, and, in con- nection therewith, also the corresponding un-virtues. (3) As this power is a self-determining one, hence there is need of a determined formula of the moral product, namely, a moral law, by the observing of which, on the part of the producing moral power, the real production of the moral world is con- ditioned, namely, the doctrine of duties, which in turn falls into the doctrine of self-duties and the doctrine of social duties. In the two first and rather speculative parts of the work, Rothe treats of many things which one would not look for in a work on ethics, e. g. , of pure matter, of space and time, of extension and motion, of atomic attraction and re- pulsion, of gravity, of fluidity, of crystallization, of vegeta- tion, of comets, and the like; these digressions into the sphere of natural philosophy belong among the oddities of the work. The excessively artificial schemata are repeated in constant and very strange application, the quadropartite division being throughout observed, even though the ob- serving of it requires the invention of entirely new definitions and new words ; and not unf requently are found entirely' use- less and profitless splittings of ideas. The chief fault of this work, however, seems to us to lie in the fact, that it unhesi- tatingly lays at the foundation of Christian Ethics, theories which are utterly foreign to the Christian world-theory, such as that of the philosophical ethics of Schleiermacher, which, however, Schleiermacher himself declared to be inapplicable to Christian ethics. Rothe's notion of the moral is endurable only in a philosophical system such as Schleiermacher's ; and, even there appearing only as an oddity, is not only per se en- tirely unsound, but also utterly in contradiction to the entire evangelico-ethical consciousness. This consciousness has as 374 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [48. its moral goal something utterly other than the appropriating of material nature to the personal nature ; the kingdom of God has with this nature primarily and essentially nothing to do. The other more recent writers on ethics keep themselves more independent of recent philosophy. The work of Har- less: " Christian Ethics " (since 1842 in five almost similar editions ; the sixth edition, 1864, greatly enlarged), is a brief, able and purely- Biblical treatise, practical, purely- evangelical and well written; but the scientific form is faulty ; the ideas are not sharply distinguished nor always held fast to; the clearness is more frequently appearance than reality ; the development of thought is neither vigor- ous nor uninterrupted; the classification (salvation-good, salvation-possession, salvation-preservation) is not capable of being kept distinct ; the second and third parts overlap each other, for there is no possession without preservation ; and what appears here as preservation is in fact possession ; the general introduction is insufficient, and Harless himself says of his book, that it contains "no trace of a system." * The work of Sartoriw. "The Doctrine of holy Love, or Elements of Evangelico-Ecclesiastical Moral Theology," (third edition, 1851-'56), is intended for the general public, and is not a sci- entific treatise, nor yet a book of edification ; but it goes be- yond the limits of mere ethics, and embraces love in the wid- est sense ; hence it treats also of the love of God to himself, and of its realization in the Trinity, and to man, also of creation and redemption, thus combining much dogmatical matter with ethics. The spirit of the work is purely evan- gelical, of ardent' faith enlivened and enlivening. The dis- cussion, however, remains mostly in the sphere of the general; the individual moral phenomena are neither com- pletely nor closely examined. (W. Bohmer: "Theological Ethics," 1846~'53). C. F. Schmid's "Christian Ethics," edited by Heller, 1861, is of a truly Biblical spirit, earnest, judicious, and giving evidence of Christian life-experience ; the scientific classification and form are not happy are not derived from the subject-matter, but outwardly thrown upon it; many weighty points are omitted, and the manner of treatment is unequal. Palmer's "Ethics of Christianity," * Varr. t. 6 Au. XV. 49.] ROMISH ETHICS. 876 1864, is an outline destined for wider, cultivated circles; the view taken is sound and evangelical, morally earnest and judicious, and the style pleasing, light, and untechnical. T. Culmanri's " Christian Ethics, " first part, 1864, is based upon Baader's theosophy, and is in sharp antithesis to all rationalistic superficiality, although, notwithstanding its many ingenious and even profound thoughts, it strays away into many, and even anti- Scriptural, assumptions and dreamy brain-fancies. SECTION XLIX. The ethics of the Roman Catholic Church since the dissolution of the Order of the Jesuits has been becoming, even in the circles which stood in connec- tion with this Order, considerably more cautious ; in other respects it has been treated (when not casuis- tical) principally on the basis of Thomas Aquinas. The influence of recent philosophy has made itself in many respects apparent ; in part, there has been also a noticeable approximation to the evangelical consciousness, without, however, rising beyond a hesi- tating half-way position. The ground-character of the Romish church as distinguished from the evan- gelical, namely, its tendency to conceive the moral predominantly under the form of law, whereas the latter conceives it more as virtue, remains the same even up to the present. During the last two centuries the ethics of the Roman Catholic church has made decided advances toward the bet- ter. The growing indignation against the perversion of the same by the Jesuits rendered even the Jesuits themselves more cautious, although also the works of the earlier Jesuits have been very largely in use up to most recent times. Alphonzo de Ligorio's Theologia maralis, since 1757, (an en- largement of the work of Busenbaum), is yet to-day one of the most highly prized hand-books of ethics ; (on it are 376 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [49. based the works of Waibel: "Moral Theology," 1841-'47, and of Scavini : " Theologia Moralis," ninth edition, 1863.) The Jesuit Stattler of Ingolstadt (Ethica Christiana communis, 1791) taught, however, pretty boldly the old principles of the Order ; whereas, on the other hand, the opposition thereto was growing more emphatic, and has resulted in bringing about a purer moral view. The moralists who based themselves on the Scholastics, especially on Thomas Aquinas, have been very numerous; (Besombes, from and after 1709; Amort, 1789, '58, who wrote also a system of "Casuistry," 1733, '62; Tournely, 1726 and subsequently; Concina, 1745; Patuzzi, 1770 ; and others) ; of the large number of ethical works, however, only a few have any thing original ; the majority simply compile from their predecessors. Under the influence of Kant, wrote Isenbiehl (1795), Muttschelle (1801, Schenkl (1803), and others; Riegler's "Christian Ethics," 1825, rests in part on Schenkl, and is much used, though scientifically unimportant. Braun, in his "System of Christian Catholic Ethics," (1834), and Vogelsang in his "Compendium" (1834), applied the philosophy of Hermes to ethics. Sailer's ' ' Hand- Book of Christian Ethics," (1818, '34) is of a very mild and generally evangelical spirit ; and the approximation to a purer evangelical view, though often somewhat infected with Rationalism, shows itself also in other more recent moralists. Hirscher's "Christian Ethics" (1835, fifth edition, 1851) is doubtless scientifically the most important, and its general view is largely based on essentially evangelical principles ; distinctively Romish views are in many cases very much modified and, advocate-like, .idealized and brought nearer to evangelical views ; this, however, is not accomplished with- out some sophistry. Also Stapf ("Christian Ethics," 1841 ; Theologia Moralis, fourth edition 1836) endeavors to shape the older ethics more Biblically; Jocham's "Moral Theol- ogy," 1852, is simple and clear; Martin, 1850-'51 ; Werner, 1850. These improvements of Romish ethics do not succeed, how- ever, in changing its ground-character as in contrast to evangel- ical ethics ; the notion of the meritoriousness of human works as co-working toward salvation is not yet overcome, virtue is not mere thanks, but it establishes claims ; the moral life is not 49.] ROMISH ETHICS. 377 the spontaneously-cmt-streaming radiance of the faith-inspired loving soul, but it is a something yet distinct from faith and rela- tively independent, a laborious working upon salvation as only associatedly conditioned by faith, but not yet really obtained. The divine will has not as yet become an inner property of the believing soul in spiritual regeneration, but simply still hovers before it as a something other from and objective to it ; hence the largely predominant character of legality in Romish ethics, even where, on the basis of Thomas Aquinas, the form of the doctrine of virtue is chosen. And here is manifestly the reason why the Romish form of theology has produced a far richer ethical literature than the Evangelical, seeing that in the Romish Church not merely the scientific but also the prac- tical need for moral instructions and rules, is much greater than in the sphere of the Evangelican consciousness, which lat- ter is no longer " under the law," and has consequently in ethics less a practical than a purely scientific interest. To the Cath- olic the Gospel is essentially also a newZaw, simply a further- development of the Old Testament law ; and it is the task of ethics to digest this new legislation and shape it more or less into a statutory form ; only to a Romish moralist is it possible to take up into a treatise on ethics a civil criminal code, as Stapf has done, in detailed thoroughness, with the Austrian. The Christian never succeeds, here, in bearing in himself the Divine will otherwise than in a law learned by study ; the law and the moral subject still continue exterior to each other, and the former is objective to the latter; to act according to the authority of an outward law appears as a special merit ; the law interpenetrates not the human soul, and the soul not the law ; there remains between the two an impassable gulf; hence the law and the person content themselves, at last, with the outward; obeying outweighs loving; and loving is never a merit, as obeying, however, may be. Because of the placing of faith simply along-side of works, there lacks to the moral the unitary center-point in the heart, and hence the good appears predominantly as a plurality of virtues, and the moral life pre- dominantly as a countless sum of single cases ; hence in Romish ethics the predominance of the casuistical treatment, which is not yet thrown aside even in the most recent treatises; the thought of ethics awakes at once in the Catholip's mind the UCSB LIBRARY 378 CHRISTIAN ETHICS. [ 43. notion of a Summa casuum ; also, in this respect, \ve see a manifestation of the predominant character of externality. The notion of a Gocl-sonship manifesting itself in a new free life never comes to full appreciation in Romish ethics ; the no- tion of a son of the Church is, in it, much more familiar; and here at once the ecclesiastical State, with its legal character, steps into the fore-ground of the moral life. END OP HISTORY OP ETHICS.