IN MEMORJAM 
 
 JESSICA PEIXOTTO 
 1864-1941 
 
THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 
 
 HKW YORK BOSTON CHICAGO DALLAS 
 ATLANTA SAN FRANCISCO 
 
 MACMILLAN & CO., LIMITED 
 
 LONDON ' BOMBAY CALCUTTA 
 MELBOURNE 
 
 THE MACMILLAN CO. OF CANADA, Lm 
 
 TORONTO 
 
THE 
 LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 BY 
 
 O. FRED BOUCKE 
 
 Professor of Economics at Pennsylvania 
 State College 
 
 gotfe 
 
 THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 
 1920 
 
 All rights reserved 
 
I 
 
 COPYRIGHT, 1920, 
 BT THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 
 
 Set up and elcctrotyped. Published April, 1920. 
 
 IN MEMORIAM 
 
PREFACE 
 
 At the present time the general reader will, the author 
 believes, be interested in some of the following questions 
 which socialism has sought to answer in its own peculiar 
 way. First, to what extent can the income of the average 
 man be raised under socialism, as contrasted with the pres- 
 ent individualistic regime? Second, if any marked change 
 in national income is to be expected from socialism, in 
 what direction will it most naturally occur, and what are 
 the limits set to this endeavor? Third, is it true that so- 
 cialism can establish a democracy in the political sense such 
 as individualism has not as yet pretended to have realized? 
 Fourth, is Marxian economics an indispensable basis to 
 the program mapped out by socialists, or is the refutation 
 of such doctrine, as hitherto submitted by professional 
 economists, a relatively unimportant step which in no wise 
 invalidates the general outlook of socialists? Fifth, if 
 socialism is a theory of prosperity, what is the scientific 
 basis for it, and, more particularly, what data has present 
 day science to offer in support of the thesis expressed or 
 implied by socialism, that a rational method for socio- 
 economic reform exists? Sixth, what are the ultimate 
 questions which socialism has attempted to answer, or 
 must feel obliged to discuss hereafter, in order to find a 
 logical groundwork for its demands? 
 
 These and some other outstanding topics have been 
 given consideration in the following pages, and it is hoped 
 that in them will be found a review, from partly new 
 standpoints, of what is most important in socialistic plat- 
 
 M141411 
 
PREFACE 
 
 forms. The fourth and fifth chapters contain founda- 
 tions for all later ones. On them the treatment of the 
 whole subject largely rests. However, it is hoped that the 
 summary which opens the last chapter will furnish a con- 
 venient guide to some of the main points advanced, and in 
 this way make clearer the idea of limits in socialism, within 
 which socialists hand in hand with social scientists may 
 continue their studies, but beyond which progress is less 
 certain and more open to the sort of criticism which up 
 to date has injured the socialist cause. 
 
 State College, Pa. 
 
TABLE OF CONTENTS 
 
 PART I 
 THE LIMITS IN THEORY 
 
 CHAPTER ONE PAGE 
 
 THE PROBLEM 1-10 
 
 CHAPTER TWO 
 KARL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 1143 
 
 CHAPTER THREE 
 THE ECONOMIC INTERPRETATION OF HISTORY . . 44-57 
 
 CHAPTER FOUR 
 
 THE ECONOMIC INTERPRETATION OF HISTORY (CON- 
 TINUED) 58-108 
 
 CHAPTER FIVE 
 JUSTICE 109-125 
 
 PART II 
 THE LIMITS IN PRACTICE 
 
 CHAPTER SIX 
 THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 126-159 
 
 CHAPTER SEVEN 
 THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION . , 160-189 
 
CONTENTS 
 
 CHAPTER EIGHT PAGE 
 
 THE LIMITS IN CONSUMPTION 190-210 
 
 CHAPTER NINE 
 THE LIMITS IN GOVERNMENT 211-237 
 
 CHAPTER TEN 
 A PETITION ... . 238-256 
 
LIST OF TABLES 
 
 TABLE ONE PAGES 
 
 A Comparison of Marxian with Ricardian and 
 Marginal Economics 267 
 
 TABLE Two 
 
 Age Distribution in the Population of Different 
 Countries in 1910 133 
 
 TABLE THREE 
 
 Possible Changes in the Labor Supply of the 
 United States for the Year 1910, According to 
 Socialistic Standards 135-6 
 
 TABLE FOUR 
 
 Industries with Small-Scale Production, United 
 States, 1910 142 
 
 TABLE FIVE 
 
 The Distribution of Incomes in the United States 
 
 in 1910 147 
 
 TABLE Six 
 
 American Manufactures in 1914 Which Were Con- 
 sumed Chiefly by People Earning Over $1200 a 
 Year 151 
 
 TABLE SEVEN 
 
 Number of Gainfully Occupied in the United 
 States in 1910, to be Reduced or Eliminated Under 
 Socialism , , 153-4 
 
THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 CHAPTER I 
 THE PROBLEM 
 
 i. General Statement of the Problem. Social sci- 
 ence has to do with social processes. It studies the 
 facts of social life and seeks to discover whatever prin- 
 ciples of general validity and permanent operation may 
 underlie them. The sociologist and economist notably 
 are interested in this side of the subject. Each studies 
 the phenomena and looks for laws with a possible view 
 to application. The basic sciences for them are biology 
 and psychology. After they have laid down the funda- 
 mentals obtaining in social life the statesman may try to 
 make use of them for his own purposes. Politics is then 
 the science dealing with the application of principles 
 formulated by sociology and economics. 
 
 This is one way of stating the sociological problem 
 in general. A second is the common sense view which 
 simply asks: Are there any social evils? Is there any- 
 thing to correct in the life of individuals or nations? If 
 so, how may it be done? As regards the evils, are they 
 inherent in life or are they eradicable? Are they of per- 
 sonal making or should we look for their explanation in 
 certain objective conditions over which the individual has 
 no control? In so far as evils are removable, shall we 
 rely upon one major remedy relative to which all others 
 are merely auxiliary, or is the cure to be effected by call- 
 ing to aid many forces for betterment, no one of them 
 
 1 
 
2 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 sufficient by itself, but their joint effect being a regenera- 
 tion of society? 
 
 At all times we have these questions to face, because 
 evils always have existed and likely always will exist. If 
 the word evil is rightly understood, its complete elimina- 
 tion will not be expected by any scientist. There is al- 
 ways room for improvement; we shall never adjust our- 
 selves to our surroundings perfectly. 
 
 2. The Socialistic Platform in the United States. 
 Socialism is a doctrine and a movement for reform which 
 has seen some of the deeper aspects of the problem and 
 tried to solve them in a rather unique way, by abolishing 
 capitalism. The core of socialism is the abolition of pri- 
 vate property in production and distribution, and the sub- 
 stitution for it of public ownership. The public in gen- 
 eral, and not particular individuals, are to own the means 
 by which goods are produced and exchanged. This sub- 
 version of one regime, and the introduction of another 
 in which the capitalist is superseded by the state or by 
 the community, is the central theme of socialists. 
 
 Socialism however is more than one single thing. It is 
 not simply a theory, but also a movement for redress of 
 evils. It is preaching and practice in one. It is the 
 enumeration of evils, their explanation, and a prescrip- 
 tion for betterment. Socialism consists of an indict- 
 ment, a theory, and a platform for propaganda and 
 eventual realization. Socialists have a creed which guides 
 their conduct, and in this respect they are much stronger 
 than many other would-be reformers. Scientific socialism 
 is scientific because it properly inquired into the Why of 
 affairs before proposing to get at the How. 
 
 The socialistic attitude may be illustrated from a simile 
 in a charming book written by Edward Bellamy. 1 
 i Bellamy, E., "Looking Backward," p. 10. 
 
THE PROBLEM 3 
 
 Society there is compared to a coach driven by Hunger 
 and dragged on a seemingly interminable highway by a 
 throng of toilers. What a hilly road it is ! What 
 windings and obstacles ahead. What a wearisome jour- 
 ney for the common folk! 
 
 On top of the coach ride a few privileged ones who en- 
 joy themselves to their hearts' content. They admire the 
 beauty of the landscape on each side of the road, and fill 
 their lungs with exhilarating breezes. They do not gaze 
 too fondly upon the embarrassment of the team below, for 
 the spectacle of distress jars on their delicate sensibili- 
 ties. They are willing of course to dress the wounds of 
 those bruised by the ceaseless straining in harness, but 
 they wish to keep the vehicle moving at all costs, and they 
 spur on the laggards with false words of cheer. 
 
 Yet they do not always remain in their seats, nor are 
 all those below condemned to perpetual toil. An exchange 
 of seats does take place from time to time. Some of the 
 throng, perhaps, manage to slough off the shackles which 
 bind them, and succeed in climbing to the top. They 
 then join the crowd of joyriders and are received with 
 more or less coolness. Or some of the privileged ones 
 suddenly come to the end of their life's journey and be- 
 queath their rights to those below waiting anxiously for 
 the favor. 
 
 A seat on top is what everybody wants. And yet no 
 one there is really happy, for all are trembling in ever- 
 lasting fear of a disaster. At every turn of the road, at 
 every blocking of the track, they shake with trepidation 
 lest the coach be upset and a painful ending meet them 
 below. They enjoy their advantages such as an unequal 
 assignment of labors may give, but they face the future 
 pessimistically, because their conscience smites them. 
 
 Socialists have accepted the picture as substantially 
 
4 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 true to life. They have called attention to the inequali- 
 ties in social arrangements and demanded a change for 
 the better. They have insisted upon an upsetting of the 
 coach because they see no other way out of the difficulty. 
 The socialistic theory of progress has been formulated 
 to make this clear. 
 
 Scientific socialism comprises four points of theory 
 that formerly were considered essentials for its success 
 as a political party in action. It was the first of so- 
 ciological doctrines to preach that prosperity must be 
 measured by wealth, that all social relations turn on 
 facts of wealtlPand its production or exchange, that 
 evils are the result of a maladjustment socially grounded, 
 and that a revolution was impending because of a uni- 
 versal law which no man and no act of legislation could 
 defy. This is in large part the significance of socialism. 
 It taught us to connect our moral ratings with the eco- 
 nomic facts of life. It pointed out the paramount im- 
 portance of income for purposes of self realization. It 
 treated the problem of misery objectively, and yet hu- 
 manized it by holding man responsible rather than nature. 
 And finally it exemplified the might of maladjustment by 
 showing how private property under different systems of 
 production could have entirely different results for the 
 masses of the people. From this many things followed, 
 but one of them notably was the value of sociological 
 analysis and the need of enlightenment which should rem- 
 edy evils before a law of evolution did so abruptly. 
 
 Marxian economics and Marx's interpretation of his- 
 tory have been mainly associated with socialism. It has 
 been held that the economics expounded by Marx in his 
 Capital was the making or marring of socialism, and 
 that socialism loses its usefulness, becomes a failure, if 
 certain contentions in the theory of value or in the eco- 
 
THE PROBLEM 5 
 
 nomic interpretation of the past could be proven unten- 
 able. In this spirit mere details have often been magni- 
 fied into decisive issues, or what were salient features have 
 been made the test by which to settle once and for all 
 the questions of social reform. Yet it is significant, and 
 it should be well noted by the critics of early let us say 
 dogmatic socialism, that the arguments of Karl Marx 
 have been in large part abandoned by his successors with- 
 out weakening in the least their ardor, or the chance of 
 their achieving unusual things. This alone should have 
 disillusioned those who thought that the end of the Marx- 
 ian system meant the death-knell of the socialistic move- 
 ment. It manifestly could not mean that. 
 
 Since 1890 the German socialists have said little about 
 surplus value and much about political rights. Oppor- 
 tunism has diluted scientific socialism, but it has given 
 a new lease of life to the main assertion of socialists that 
 great evils exist, that they are widespread and perceived 
 by the masses; and that the socialization of capital will 
 alone relieve mankind of its social diseases. 
 
 The war has further modernized socialistic demands, 
 besides putting practice in the foreground; and in the 
 United States it has widened the vision of reformers, so 
 that to-day American socialism is stronger theoretically 
 and practically than ever. 
 
 The party platform of 1918 2 calls for the federation 
 of all nations with a view to ending wars. It pleads for 
 a uniform monetary system for all the world, for the 
 devising of machinery to adjust credit to international 
 needs, for the reduction of armaments, and for an inter- 
 national minimum wage scale. Those things in particular 
 are to be made the concern of all nations in an endeavor 
 to promote universal goodwill and peace. 
 
 2 Congressional Platform of the (American) Socialist Party, 1918. 
 
6 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 In addition however many other demands are made, 
 some of them familiar and approved by the founders of 
 socialism, and others of recent origin, the result of con- 
 ditions which Marx could not foresee. We have again, 
 for instance, the clarion call for a nationalization of priv- 
 ate capital, without which socialists would lose their most 
 distinctive mission. Public utilities and basic industries 
 including mines, grain elevators, stockyards, and banks 
 are specifically enumerated as preferential subjects for 
 socialization. 
 
 Other items of note are the abolition of child labor, 
 a reduction of the working day commensurate with tech- 
 nical progress, the official recognition of a national mini- 
 mum wage, the extension of the right to strike and to 
 boycott, the appointment of shop committees with rep- 
 resentation of labor, the introduction of free vocational 
 education, gratuitous insurance of all workers, both rural 
 and urban, against accident and sickness, and the guar- 
 antee of employment to all who seek it. 
 
 These are the main economic rights which socialism 
 to-day grants to the working classes, and the acknowl- 
 edgment of which by the state is the goal socialists are 
 aiming at. They come first and overshadow certain po- 
 litical reforms that are also urged, but which, we may 
 be sure, will follow automatically once the economic rights 
 of the citizen are put into operation. 
 
 3. Leading Questions for Socialism. The question 
 is: Are these demands fair? Do they harmonize with 
 socialistic theory ? Or more to the point, are they agree- 
 able to the data of social science which socialism has al- 
 ways made it a point to consult in the framing of political 
 and economic platforms? 
 
 One may, to begin with, put this more concretely by 
 asking what socialism promises in case it is given a free 
 
THE PROBLEM 7 
 
 hand, and how much of its promise is realizable. Grant- 
 ing the socialization of capital, what can socialism do to 
 root out evil and improve our living? According to its 
 own admission the facts of production, exchange and 
 control occupy a preeminent place in any scheme of 
 meliorism. If then the socialist is confident of accom- 
 plishing by his system what heretofore we have not 
 managed to do, on what grounds does he make his 
 promises ? 
 
 As to production, e. g., can socialism produce so much 
 more than individualism? And in what kinds of goods 
 is the gain to come? As to distribution, what is meant 
 by a new principle in the pricing of goods and services? 
 In how far may socialism ensure each man his product, 
 when the competitive regime fails to do so? What are 
 the limits in measurement of values and services? What 
 is to define for us a need, according to which family bud- 
 gets will be made out? 
 
 Or take the problem of consumption and of control. 
 What will socialism mean by consumption that the ortho- 
 dox economist has not meant by it? To what extent can 
 economic income regulate psychic outgo? How far may 
 we hope for race improvement by means of socialistic re- 
 forms ? And in what sense can socialism make democracy 
 real, when up to date it has been a mere sham, or at best 
 a modest approximation to a lofty ideal? Can the people 
 be led to direct themselves politically? Is the prospect 
 of perpetual peace bright enough, so that our time hal- 
 lowed traditions of nationalism may give way to a more 
 generous view of mankind? 
 
 Such are immediate practical questions that the social- 
 istic theory inspires. But, in the second place, it prompts 
 us to meet squarely the far broader problem whether a 
 rationale of meliorism really exists? Is it possible, and 
 
8 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 why and within what limits, to establish principles of re- 
 form which shall satisfy our craving for justice and social 
 welfare at a given moment? Is reform, in other words, 
 a matter of science, or of whim and hazard without pos- 
 sibility of guidance? Do we feel wrongs without having 
 redress elsewhere than in our personal adjustments, or is 
 there a way for governing people so that the welfare of 
 the largest number becomes feasible and normal? 
 
 This larger phase of the socialistic movement forces us 
 to search into the nature of knowledge, into the relation 
 of social aspects which the founders of socialism so bluntly 
 stated and sought to demonstrate to a critical world. It 
 is ultimately a matter of psychology and sociology, if by 
 the latter term we may designate the sum total of investi- 
 gations into social man; However, the psychological 
 data may be divided into the logical and the psychological 
 or biological, and the first then asks : What is our 
 knowledge, how do we reason, and what is the meaning 
 of laws and causation? And the second then treats of 
 the subjective interpretation of the social process. Man 
 of necessity is in the center of things. The social student 
 invariably will go wrong unless he considers all sociological 
 and economic data an expression of living men and 
 women, whose innermost nature is the key to any prob- 
 lem that may present itself. 
 
 An answer to socialism hence involves an inquiry into 
 the process of learning by which stimuli become response 
 and thoughts are converted into actions of enduring 
 value. It is for the critic of, or sympathizer with, social- 
 istic teachings to picture the relation between economic 
 and non-economic conditions as an individual experience. 
 Only in this manner can the Marxian interpretation be 
 rectified in the modern scientific spirit. Only by this 
 route shall we succeed in tracing the real connection be- 
 
THE PROBLEM 9 
 
 tween historical events which to some seem not at all re- 
 lated, and to others are almost identical. If socialists 
 dwelled on the causative force of methods of production, 
 "wereTEey wrong or right? Was the relation stated cor- 
 rectly, or is civilization an organic whole whose parts 
 the historian may not separate on any excuse? 
 
 The wider treatment of the question of meliorism leads 
 to a conception of progress and prosperity not altogether 
 opposed to the notions held by early socialists. It must 
 be part of the would-be reformer's education to define 
 prosperity, since Marxian philosophy is so incisive on 
 that point. It is necessary to appreciate its view of 
 misery as an integral part of an outlook developed not 
 by economics, but by metaphysics. It is inevitable in- 
 deed that a contemplation of socialistic ideals and prom- 
 ises suggests an answer to the query: What is the ulti- 
 mate good, what is justice, and what is the bearing of 
 science on norms of life that under individualism as well 
 as under socialism are reflected in acts of the legislature? 
 
 Socialism, since it is a theory of prosperity, implies all 
 these questions, and more. It compels us to take a long 
 view of things, not a near at hand view individualistically 
 trumped up. Socialism is stern and bold. It boasts a 
 noble intellectual lineage, and will not be put off or 
 downed by flippant banter. Complacency cannot undo 
 the ills that are known to exist, and an appeal to national 
 traditions will deceive none except the thoughtless ones. 
 Socialism is neither a chimera nor a crime, though by a 
 few it has been considered both. 
 
 The need for reform seems universallv conceded. But 
 whether it is or not, the reality of the larger problem 
 no one can deny. It is worth while to know whether 
 social evils have causes that we can specifically unearth 
 and offset by remedial measures. It is important to de- 
 
10 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 cide whether politics is more than a game among fight- 
 ing cocks. It does pique the curiosity of many good 
 folk to see illegalities and absurd criminality flourishing 
 in this age of enlightenment. They involuntarily ask: 
 Is it unavoidable, or may we right things by using our 
 wits? 
 
 The world to-day is in ferment. The war has set 
 people's teeth on edge, and the post-war effects are not 
 calculated to soothe their feelings on sundry matters. 
 The terrible, the unbelievable, the overwhelming fact re- 
 mains that many millions had to die innocently in a 
 stupendous struggle that the achievements of the nine- 
 teenth century should have made impossible. Whatever 
 we may think of the war just concluded, of its causes 
 and instigators, of its political consequences or costs in 
 material and men, the one great question is now before us. 
 We must know whether the social process logically in- 
 volves such disasters,, or whether the safety and welfare 
 of the masses may be procured by rational means at the 
 disposal of government, supposing social science continues 
 its labors. 
 
 Socialism has many times replied to our questions. It 
 has placed the blame on a certain form of economic or- 
 ganization and pledged itself to deliver us from all evil if 
 we please to listen to its sermon. Social scientists can do 
 no better than to think of socialists as students who de- 
 sire to substitute sense for sentiment in reforming man. 
 Whether they have struck the right path, whether social- 
 ism alone will do, whether science can espouse a collectiv- 
 istic program favoring some of the demands voiced by 
 socialists, these^are questions that at the present moment 
 confront us. ifljie ultimate place of science in social re- 
 form cannot be determined just now, hiTt_it.s )->pa.ringr on 
 socialism is self evident. 
 
CHAPTER II 
 KARL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 
 
 i. Marx as an Eclectic Marx's Kapital is consid- 
 ered an offshoot of English classic economics, whose chief 
 exponents are Smith, Ricardo, Senior, and J. S. Mill. 
 The connection between especially Ricardo and Marx is 
 so obvious that it seems hardly necessary to trace out 
 other lines of descent. Yet it is by no means true that 
 the individualistic scheme of economics as it prevailed at 
 the beginning of the nineteenth century was logically es- 
 sential to Kapital. Rather, if one excepts the labor 
 doctrine of value, there is scarcely any point of prime 
 importance in Ricardo's Principles that reappears in 
 the German work. The Bible of socialism uses English 
 < economics mainly to refute or recast it, not to build with 
 it a theory tor lighting capitalism. That was surely 
 quite out of the question. 
 
 One may explain this difference in another way by 
 noting Marx's essentials of character, for plainly he was 
 an iconoclast by inborn temperament who saw everywhere 
 idols and images where others lingered reverently, and 
 whose one mission seemed to be to dethrone the false 
 gods. Marx seldom was satisfied with what he saw about 
 him. He was an idealist in spite of his crass materialistic 
 sv > stem of sociological thoughi. To him it was painful 
 to see people practice quite the opposite of what they 
 preached, to hear them expound theories that nowhere 
 squared with the facts, while attempting to hide their real 
 sentiments under a mask of scholarly impartiality. He 
 
 11 
 
12 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 sought to go beneath the surface of things and see what 
 was really at stake, but in so doing he usually encount- 
 ered truths that rankled because those most obligated to 
 honor them proved their worst enemies. 
 
 Marx was a man of great acumen and incredible capa- 
 city for work. He could read hundreds of books within 
 a short time and digest most of what was significant in 
 them. He would listen to many men but ultimately go 
 his own way. He borrowed without plagiarizing, and he 
 returned with interest the principal which he openly made 
 use of. Whatever passed through the alembic of his 
 mind came out as a product distinctly his own. He took 
 pieces here and there, but never all. Thus from Hegel 
 he took the dialectic, but inverted his order of syllogisms. 
 He rejoiced in Bentham's positivism, but scoffed at his 
 individualistic norm of utilitarianism. Of Proudhon he 
 had, with respect to some of his preachings, a high 
 opinion, but see how he ranted at What Is Property! 
 Feuerbach gave him inspiration and definite ideas as to 
 the meaning of the dialectic process, but for all that he 
 turned away from the Essence of Christianity. The 
 naturalistic philosophy excited his admiration in so far as 
 it combated transcendentalism, but beyond that he had 
 as little use for it as Hume or Blackstone. In all in- 
 stances he listened attentively at first, but before long 
 found flaws that invalidated most of what to others 
 seemed valuable. 
 
 Thus it was that in spite of the remarkable stage of 
 perfection which the economic science had reached in 
 Marx's days, little of it is constructively incorporated 
 in the Critique of 1859. The physiocrats had written 
 their ponderous tomes, Smith and Ricardo had estab- 
 lished firmly the principles of competitive economics, the 
 reaction against Manchestrianism had yielded some 
 
KARL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 13 
 
 notable results both among the French and the English, 
 and in Germany the Historical School was beginning to 
 develop a philosophy of methods. Yet none of it furn- 
 ishes foundations for Karl Marx. Instead he takes a bit 
 here and a bit there. He nibbles and absorbs a detail, 
 or plows diligently over a vast field and then claims no 
 fruits whatsoever. 
 
 The naturalistic view he could not entertain seriously 
 because it meant statics, and he saw in the social process 
 everywhere motion and conflict. The utilitarian norms 
 were repugnant to him because they smacked of senti- 
 mentalism, or of professions of faith that had nothing 
 to do with stern reality. Hi one hobby was the majesty 
 of logic. The logic of events overawed him, if anything 
 ever did. He saw regularity and necessity where others 
 looked for willed plans subjectively valuated. He had no 
 patience with the slogan which would change the world 
 by giving it an emotional gruelling. People, he argued, 
 should not thus be fed and broken in. 
 
 As for the movement fostered by Hildebrandt and 
 Knies, he considered it a children's play because it worked 
 with nationalistic premises, its chief aim being the 
 economic development of Germany. Marx detested such 
 an outlook. The world to him seemed too large to be 
 bounded by race prejudices, and on the other hand he 
 could not approve of a school which catered more to 
 nationalism at any cost than to internationalism on behalf 
 of helpless masses. So, while taking some note of 
 Roscher and his colleagues, he bantered with them 
 lightly, content to pass their notions over with a sar- 
 castic remark at opportune moments, while immersing 
 himself deeply in the radical literature of Thompson, 
 Hodgskin, Bray, and Gray. What these men had penned 
 in their admiration for the French revolutionary spirit 
 
14 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 he thought over carefully, with consequences known to 
 students of socialism. But even their suggestions did 
 not enslave him. He was impressed, it appears, with 
 their collectivistic treatment of a problem which the dis- 
 ciples of Ricardo so despised, but he went decidedly 
 farther, besides bringing in thoughts no mere economist 
 would have tried to master. 
 
 And so, in a most serious sense, also with his use of 
 Ricardian tenets. He read and digested thoroughly what 
 this banker had said, but in the end he disagreed with him 
 on most important points. Much he openly rejected and 
 criticized as utter nonsense. The rest he put to such 
 novel uses that Ricardo would probably not have recog- 
 nized his contributions in " Das Kapital." Living amidst 
 substantially like environments their teachings yet go far 
 apart. What Marx saw in his long stay in London did 
 not give him the convictions voiced so modestly in 
 Ricardo's Principles. There were similarities between the 
 two that might have augured well for a correspondence 
 of views, but there existed differences, no less, that in the 
 end made them strangers. Their premises were not alto- 
 gether the same, and for this reason they emphasized dif- 
 ferent facts in the world about them. 
 
 To follow this thought of likeness and unlikeness a little 
 farther for it is rather interesting Ricardo might 
 very well be called an optimist, complacently active, who 
 thought the world the best possible, considering the laws 
 of nature, and looked after his business on Exchange. 
 Marx was a pessimist who could see nothing good in the 
 world that treated the laboring classes so shabbily. But 
 on the other hand he looked forward to a change brought 
 about by a law of evolution of universal validity, while 
 Ricardo for all his serene temperament was the stout de- 
 fender of a law of diminishing returns which condemned the 
 
KARL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 15 
 
 masses forever to a hand-to-mouth living. This was cer- 
 tainly a gloomy outlook. No wonder men spoke of the 
 " dismal science " of economics. 
 
 Both Ricardo and Marx were Jews converted to 
 Christianity, but neither professed to have understood all 
 of the adopted creed. Both were men of outstanding 
 personality and mind, men who could think in abstract 
 terms and pack a wealth of heterogeneous facts into a few 
 concepts. Because they towered so far above the general 
 run of people they had little confidence in its rantings 
 and judgments. They did not think the average man 
 capable of sustained mental labors. They despised the 
 sentimentalities of the mob, however sympathetic they 
 were toward their hardships which they witnessed with 
 sorrow and tried sincerely to ease. Both were generous 
 and modest, unostentatious and averse to publicity. 
 Both disliked false show, and especially pseudo sentiments 
 which they sometimes detected where no one else could. 
 Marx derided the moralism of the Benthamites, but in his 
 own home he was the most exemplary of husbands and 
 fathers, punctilious to a fault, and as conventional in mat- 
 ters of morality as he was a free lance in theorizing. 
 Like Ricardo he was a formalist, a stickler for niceties in 
 reasoning, but the most convivial of friends. Like 
 Ricardo he was a leader among men, a leader in thought, 
 a prophet who foresaw the future. Like Ricardo he 
 worked indef atigably on behalf of truth ; only while 
 Ricardo supported the government Marx labored to sub- 
 vert it. Marx was only a few years old when Ricardo 
 died. Had they been contemporaries acquainted with each 
 other's work, it would seem that they should have gotten 
 along very well together, even if they parted company as 
 philosophers. 
 
 2. Ricardian Economics. Ricardo in his " Prin- 
 
16 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 ciples of Political Economy " modified at important points 
 the Smithian tradition. He called attention to many in- 
 consistencies in his predecessor's statement, but he agreed 
 with him in one all important respect, namely he accepted 
 the institution of private property as an indispensable 
 part of his economic environment. Adam Smith had not 
 questioned this either. He had thought it sufficiently 
 justified by the facts of human nature which he studied 
 at leisure long before he wrote his Inquiry. In stating 
 his Theory of the Moral Sentiments he had dwelt long on 
 the innate goodness of man. He was greatly impressed 
 with the reality of an altruistic instinct in men, which 
 prompted them to do right even if at times they fell 
 from grace. To Smith the selfish and the social senti- 
 ments were pretty well balanced. There was no fear that 
 society would go to ruin as long as each was left to his 
 own devices as producer and consumer. Discretion, he 
 thought, would win the day. But as against the slight 
 risks of self-assertion he placed the menace of tyrannical 
 government. Only if men are permitted to enjoy the 
 fruit of their labor will they strive to please others and to 
 progress. However unfortunate the disappearance of 
 communism and he hints now and then at the burdens 
 of entail and primogeniture private capitalism had its 
 virtues. It was folly to study wealth relations on any 
 other basis. 
 
 Ricardo was satisfied with this view, and so it was 
 natural that his definitions of value and capital should be 
 the competitive concepts which economists have learned to 
 respect. The determination of price is left to supply and 
 demand, but the value of a good in the long run is the 
 amount of labor involved in its production. Labor costs 
 measure exchange value. This is the rule. The excep- 
 tions are monopoly, as for instance in the ownership of 
 
KARL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 17 
 
 non-reproducible articles artworks, old vintage, etc. 
 and the effect of durable machinery which would vary ac- 
 cording to its nature and use. Capital as well as land are 
 genuine producers. They are agents essential to the cre- 
 ation of values like labor itself. Consequently these fac- 
 tors are entitled to a share in the national output. 
 Whatever the income is, that must be divided among the 
 several agents so that production may continue. From 
 the competitive standpoint, furthermore, productivity is 
 a rate of production per unit of cost in labor and material 
 spent, though the materials embody past labor. It is 
 therefore with values that Ricardo deals mainly, and not 
 with concrete stuffs or with service as such. The aim of 
 the agents is maximum output of values, not of physical 
 things. 
 
 The physical aspect becomes important in only one re- 
 spect, namely when the ratio of food supply to the popu- 
 lation is considered ; but here its importance is so engross- 
 ing that virtually the whole distributive scheme is deter- 
 mined by it. For ever since the Malthusian doctrine 
 found acceptance among economists as a law explaining 
 wars and disease it also furnished the clue to the puzzles 
 of distribution. It was now perfectly evident that people 
 had little to eat chiefly because they would marry and rear 
 children. This alone kept them at starvation's door. 
 The sex impulses being so much more dominant than any 
 other appetite men must work harder each generation to 
 procure a minimum food supply, regardless of what bene- 
 fits might accrue to them from technical improvements in 
 another field. The law of diminishing returns in agricul- 
 ture, after a certain point of maximum yield relative to 
 the effort had been passed, punished the thoughtless 
 masses and proved a veritable goldmine to the proprietors 
 of the one indispensable means of production, to wit land. 
 
18 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 The landlord profited by the stinginess of nature. He 
 pocketed the difference between the return on the worst 
 land under cultivation and the yield of his own superior 
 land. Against the rapacious landlord, therefore, must 
 be pitted the enterpriser and the wage earner: the former 
 because competition tended to reduce his profits to a mini- 
 mum scarcely better than a decent livelihood, and the 
 latter because in spite of all inventions he could not im- 
 prove his daily board. He was bound to live frugally, 
 so the owner of the natural resources might live in splen- 
 dor. The outlook was a discouraging one, but what 
 could be done about it ? It seemed, nothing. Our only 
 hope could be a further diversification of products, and 
 perhaps in the very distant future a restraint of the sex- 
 passions, so that the masses might have somewhat more 
 meat and wheat to consume. But of general affluence 
 there could be no question. 
 
 Ricardo does not differentiate clearly between the shares 
 going to capital and those of enterprise, but he informs 
 us that both will gradually shrink, while labor, being al- 
 ready at its lowest, will hold its own. To try to improve 
 the wage earner's lot would be folly, for laws of nature 
 militate against such a plan. " Wages, like other con- 
 tracts, should be left to the fair and free competition of 
 the market, and should never be controlled by the inter- 
 ference of the legislature." l Such is the verdict handed 
 down from the court of classic economy. 
 
 3- Marxian Economist But to Marx all this was 
 cant, or else nothing but shameful ignorance. He retorts 
 in a manner the classic economists never approved of. 
 Namely he refuses to lay social evils at the door of the 
 individual laborer, and instead holds the capitalist to be 
 the malfeasant. He begins by denying what Ricardo 
 i Ricardo, D., " Principles of Political Economy," ch. 5. 
 
KARL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 19 
 
 took for granted, and ends by asserting what to Ricardo 
 would have been incomprehensible. In other words, he 
 starts with the question: What does private capitalism 
 lead to that socialized capital would not permit? And he 
 suggests the answer by opening his monumental work with 
 a discussion of foe exchange process which makes prices 
 out of utility, and profit out of labor.^ 
 
 There is some evidence to show that Marx was influ- 
 enced by the critics of the Ricardian system who wrote in 
 the first third of the nineteenth century. W. Thompson, 
 for instance, published his " Inquiry into the Principles of 
 the Distribution of Wealth " in 1824. Like others on the 
 continent he had learned from the French Revolution 
 and continued the work carried on by the naturalists who 
 harped on the rights of man. But in England liberalism 
 naturally took jm. ^cpnomic turn. Thompson" thus fol- 
 lowed the mechanistic concepts of the French encyclo- 
 pedists chiefly for the purpose of illustrating the nobility 
 of labor. A common element was to be found in all kinds 
 of occupation, no matter how intellectual it might be in 
 fact or in appearance. He writes : " What is thought 
 but motion produced and felt in the brain ? " 2 and 
 thereby challenges the opinion that different sorts of 
 work are incomparable. To Thompson and to Hodgskin, 
 his colleague, labor is at bottom only one thing. It is 
 expenditure of energy and therefore measurable for pur- 
 poses of distribution. 
 
 It is not unlikely that Marx obtained some of his ideas 
 from this group of writers. But, if so, it is certain that 
 
 2 Thompson, W., " Inquiry into the Principles of the Distribution 
 of Wealth, Preliminary Observations," 1824. See also Bray, J., 
 " Labor's Wrongs and Labor's Remedies, 1839," from which Marx 
 quotes at length in his "Misery of Philosophy," written in 1846. 
 A large part of the Marxian viewpoint is also to be found in Gray, 
 J., " The Social System, 1831." 
 
20 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 he went much farther in his use of the physical notion of 
 labor, for he deliberately lumps all classes of labor and 
 arrives at a unit of " socially necessary labor " by sum- 
 mation and division. He tells us in the first pages of his 
 book that " skilled Jabor counts only as simple labor 
 intensified." 3 That is to say, instead of two measures of 
 a product the skilled laborer turns out three or four in 
 the same time ; but otherwise his contribution is on a par 
 with that of the jack-of -all-trades. He furthermore de- 
 fines for us the term " socially necessary " labor. He 
 urges that it comprises three elements always, viz., strictly 
 human effort, valuable effort, and outlay of energy. 4 All 
 labor, he insists, is of man. Labor is the source of all 
 wealth. Nothing is produced, but the hand or mind of 
 man has exerted energy which roughly is measurable and 
 may be imputed to joint producers. But he granted that 
 unless turned to productive uses an expenditure of phys- 
 ical force (Arbeitskraft) would not yield values. 
 
 Production being thus made possible by labor solely it 
 followed that machinery was not a productive agent, and 
 hence that capitalists had no just claim to the social divi- 
 dend. Capital, Marx argued, was but solidified labor. 
 It was labor in concrete form; labor that had crystal- 
 lized as salts might crystallize from a solution. Capital 
 was mere congealed labor, and hence the owner of capi- 
 tal had no right to its products. 
 
 Marx devoted endless pages to showing that capital 
 was but a by-product of competition and of the contract 
 system of production which the champions of Laissez Faire 
 had popularized by their ingenious treatises. To him 
 capital was nothing if not the fruit of laws whose very ex- 
 
 s Marx, K., " Capital," ,as published by Ch. Kerr & Co., vol. 1, 
 * Ibidem, 'en. T, plfesim. 
 
KARL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 21 
 
 istence should be justified first, but which the facts of 
 production could not justify. " Capital," he exclaimed, 
 " is dead labor that vampire-like fattens on the blood of 
 living labor." Capital was no more than legalized rob- 
 bery. It was a wolf in sheepskin, a license .to steal, an 
 interloper in honest business, a letter patent for mulcting 
 the real producer of his wealth, and a system of pillage 
 whose ramifications threatened to undermine the social 
 order. What Ricar^o had attributed^tothe blind work- 
 ings of a n]^rjness laaL^of rmt^fpg/J^ffl.-rv inrmpffprl ex- 
 clusively with, a faulty economic regime,^ albeit one which 
 could be overthrownand replacecMSy a more logical one, 
 if the masses ~ 
 
 In "^Capital" the anomalous position of private prop- 
 erty is pictured less forcefully than in earlier essays, but 
 it is still emphasized that private property was once in 
 its place, and has lost its rights only because the methods 
 and means of production were changed in principle during 
 the century immediately preceding the Marxian analysis. 
 Between 1750 and 1850, it is pointed out, the self-suffi- 
 ciency of the laborer has given way to a minute division 
 of labor, so that trade is everything and the handicraft of 
 the individual little or nothing. While one man could 
 turn out a finished article, or as long as the joint authors 
 of a product jointly owned the tools they worked with, 
 private ownership was natural and harmless. But it 
 ceased to be innocuous when mechanical power and intri- 
 cate machinery did away with the need of muscle and 
 simple tools. 5 To put the ownership of the means of pro- 
 duction now in the hands of a few men meant to 
 enslave the worker who had nothing to offer but labor- 
 power. 
 
 5 See, e. g., ibidem, vol. I, pp. 88-91, and wellknown passage in 
 "Holy Family." 
 
22 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 Henceforth exploitation began and enriched the non- 
 worker under the protection of contract and law. 
 
 Theoretically Marx had only contempt for the Mal- 
 thusian formula. He could not tolerate its implications 
 for fear of losing the main plank in his economic plat- 
 form. Yet it appears ever and anon that the subsistence 
 wage of the proletariat had no other solid foundation 
 than its preference for a large family, or at least for sex 
 indulgence, to a table freighted with good things to eat. 
 It should, then, be understood that Ricardo after all led 
 Marx into his central position, even though from a desire 
 for consistency this was loudly denied. Marx in fact 
 consents to write : " The wages are regulated on the one 
 hand by a natural law; their minimum is determined by 
 the physical minimum required by the laborer for the 
 conservation of his labor-power and for its reproduc- 
 tion ; " but " historically developed social needs " 6 help 
 to fix this minimum. So far the author of " Capital," to 
 which may be added Engels' stress of the opposite view- 
 point that " the underconsumption of the masses is a nec- 
 essary condition of all forms of society in which robbers 
 and robbed exist, and therefore of the capitalist system." 7 
 The difficulty of harmonizing these two contentions must 
 have been apparent to Marx, but it is never candidly 
 acknowledged. 
 
 But if labor is the sole fount of wealth land is not gen- 
 erically different from capital. This is the point brought 
 out by Marx, as a result of which he again takes issue with 
 Ricardo. For he now grants to land a share for the same 
 reason that he also favors the capitalist. Rent, too, is 
 part of the loot legalized by the private property regime. 
 Rent is plunder precisely in the same sense that profits 
 
 5 Marx, K., ibidem, vol. 3, p. 1000; or vol. 1, pp. 189-190. 
 7 Engels, F., Anti-Diihrmg." 
 
KARL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 23 
 
 were. Capitalist and landlord were two of a kind. 
 Neither was acting honestly. However, unlike Ricardo 
 who pointed his accusing finger at the landlord, Marx was 
 chiefly intent upon exposing the trickery of the capitalist. 
 Industry had grown since Ricardian days. The city 
 worker was everywhere in evidence. It seemed natural to 
 bring the offending industrialist to justice first, and to 
 let the minor culprit go free for a while. In a sense, the 
 socialists had to admit, the landlord was the spoiled dar- 
 ling of mother nature, just as the classic economists had 
 themselves believed. 
 
 But what of the employment of capital and labor in its 
 effects upon profits, particularly upon the rate of profit? 
 Marx got into difficulties, as is well known, because his 
 labor theory of value left no room for the productiveness 
 of machinery. The employer raised his profits as he in- 
 creased the number of laborers engaged. This agreed 
 with Marxian theories and should have prevented the 
 movements of the dividend, that is of profits which the 
 market recorded. Some critics of Marx have maintained 
 that by this test alone the labor notion of price fell down 
 completely, since facts contradicted it constantly. Either 
 price and profits were not solely dependent on labor, or 
 the Marxian analysis failed to take care of one problem 
 in distribution. The harm, however, was not as great as 
 may appear. For if Marx had insisted that, while labor 
 was the sole source of value, it was only one factor com- 
 bining with capital goods for purposes of production, he 
 would have been safe. The varying ratios of capital and 
 labor in a productive act need then not have bothered him 
 so much. The decisive factor would still have been labor, 
 though its alliance with capital was a condition of pro- 
 ductiveness usually, if not always. But for that matter 
 the case was not nearly so much of a test for socialistic 
 
24 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 philosophy as has been affirmed by its most outspoken ene- 
 mies. The Marxian system is not shaken by confessions 
 of error in pricing schemes. Nothing great was at stake. 
 Marx knew that the rate of profits varied with the volume 
 of capital used, 8 and remembering it he could admit it 
 without renouncing his labor theory of value. 
 
 The Marxian viewpoint is in other respects self-con- 
 sistent like the Ricardian which he combats. He believed 
 that a rising share of the national income had to go to 
 land and capital. This followed naturally from the sur- 
 plus notion which pictured the laborer as receiving only 
 what was necessary to reproduce his labor power, while 
 the excess of time he worked yielded products stolen by the 
 owner of capital who thus accumulated huge sums, until 
 finally a catastrophe would overtake him. But of this 
 more in a later chapter. 
 
 It is worth while to point to the distinction between the 
 percentage of the aggregate social income accruing to 
 labor or capital, and the rate of profits or wages. The 
 latter refers to what the average capitalist or wage 
 earner gets, the former would mean the share known as 
 profits or wages distributed among all the capitalists or 
 workers respectively. As others had long pointed out: 
 According to the Malthusian principle the labor con- 
 tingent increases and their total food wages may rise, but 
 the income of each laborer in foodstuffs cannot rise, and 
 may shrink. Similarly in the Marxian position. The 
 average laborer has no prospect of improving his lot, 
 though there will be a growing number of laborers claim- 
 ing an absolutely larger amount in wages. Only, Ricardo 
 
 s " Die Profitrate nimmt ab im Verhaltnis zur steigenden Akkumu- 
 lation des Kapitals, und der ihr entsprechenden steigenden Produk- 
 tivkraft der gesellschaftlichen Arbeit"; in "Capital," vol. 3, p. 384. 
 But see also pp. 193 & 199. 
 
KARL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 25 
 
 thought that owing to technical improvements the laborer 
 would benefit somewhat in the end by gaining on enter- 
 prise, even if he paid tribute to the landlord. Marx could 
 not agree to this concession, and drove his premises to 
 their ultimate conclusion. Marx consequently had to 
 cast about for other means to save the masses. 
 
 That under such circumstances he could not love the 
 competitive spirit goes without saying; however, he pro- 
 fessed to like it because its continuance and unhampered 
 sway would precipitate the proletarian revolt. This was 
 the nature of his tolerance toward Laissez Faire. He 
 would vote for it and for free trade since it tended natur- 
 ally to destroy individualism. It was, therefore, a good 
 thing to espouse. 9 But Ricardo preached Laissez Faire 
 because he argued from promises first laid down by Adam 
 Smith, the acceptance of which inevitably led to con- 
 clusions out of accord with state interference. 
 
 As will be seen from Table One the two philosophies 
 agree in only eight out of the eighteen points specified. 
 The departures on the part of Marx from the classic sys- 
 tem are more marked than his agreements with it, and 
 the practical consequences are poles asunder. 
 
 | 4. Criticism of Marxian Economics. What is to 
 be said in regard to the position which Marx defended so 
 strenuously during his lifetime and which since then has 
 often been restated by his followers? 
 
 In the first place, evidently, the Marxian analysis can 
 no longer satisfy us because the facts go against it. The 
 lot of the average man has been improved instead of going 
 from bad to worse as Marx predicted. He has more to 
 spend and has a greater variety of goods to consume than 
 a few generations ago. The level of living has risen per- 
 
 In a speech delivered on Jan. 1 1849, in Brussels on " Die Lage 
 des Freihandels." 
 
|3^ 8 
 
 sTll-l 
 *%&** 
 
 ^Illbl 
 
 * 8 f*l|8 
 
 " * Z| .2 S j? 
 
 fcC 
 
 ll 
 
 ^ S >^^ s s ^ 
 
 i! 
 
 & ^ S 3 Is 
 
1 1 
 
 1 *(,* 
 
 Mi . 
 
 tji|i" 
 
 ^ O J^ O *S 
 
 || 3 gs 
 
 If * |5 
 
 ~r ll-si 
 Ilin^ 
 
 O 
 
 c 3 
 
 1 1 4S 5 & 
 
 ^saj. 
 
 <- s^^ 
 
 o * ~ * 
 
 H ^ .s a 
 
 - g tf aj .s 
 8 1* us 
 
 bC 03 fac 
 
 -.S" S'S 
 
 'cS S 
 
 = 3 
 
 S 
 
 :i 
 
 G PH 
 
 ^ -ij M O ^_l 
 
 >>r-i n3 n ,-1 
 
 -a-a -sa 
 
 .2 
 
 | 
 
 9 
 
 cu 
 
 PH 
 
 I 
 
 4J t- CU CD 
 
28 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 ceptibly, and the middle class, so far from dying out, has 
 increased numerically. True, the bulk of the popula- 
 tion even in the most progressive countries is still work- 
 ing under contract, the capitalist having usually the upper 
 hand in the bargaining, but this has not prevented labor 
 from obtaining a goodly part of the improvements en- 
 joyed by the wealthy. Cycles of booms and depressions 
 have recurred as before, but exploitation has not grown in 
 proportion, as Marxian economics taught. If all, or 
 even the major portion, of what labor produces above a 
 bare subsistence fund, had gone to capital the misery of 
 the multitude would be infinitely greater than it is. 
 
 In the second place, the theory of surplus value becomes 
 logically untenable when competition between laborers, 
 due to the complete mobility of labor which it assumes, 
 ends. One cannot accept this thesis of ruthless exploita- 
 tion without imagining the individual worker left entirely 
 to his own resources, deserted by his mates and betrayed 
 by a plutocratic government. But this sort of mobility 
 never existed, as even Adam Smith was anxious to admit 
 for all his belief in individualism. Human nature is often 
 stronger than legal provisions for freedom of contract 
 and of residence. People become addicted to habits. 
 They develop a fondness for places and memories. They 
 will not move, though offered a higher wage. Also, they 
 have since the rise of socialism learned to combine. The 
 right of association has not been denied them. The union 
 has done away with the advantage that men of means, and 
 particularly of the means of production, used to have, or 
 reputedly had, in bargaining with labor. A new method 
 of pricing has arisen that is a long way removed from 
 the facts of competition and mobility which the classics 
 pictured. 
 
 In the third place capital is not solidified labor, be- 
 
KARL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 29 
 
 cause matter is not altogether the same as mind. Motion 
 is not notion. True, we do well in tracing mental phe- 
 nomena by their physiological equivalents. The plan of 
 the scientist to ascertain the nature of mental states by 
 forms of behavior objectively measurable is not a con- 
 temptible one. The physical correlatives are ordinarily 
 there to be studied. They enable us to determine the 
 routine of reactions in man, which otherwise might re- 
 main undecipherable. But this does not mean the identi- 
 fication of quantity and quality. Generic differences be- 
 tween mind and matter should be granted to exist unless 
 special purposes forbid. 
 
 So, by the same token, it is an error to call machines 
 mere material put together by a working hand. Work for 
 the economist is not what it is to the physicist. The 
 physicist defines work as the overcoming of resistance 
 through space. He is interested in actions and reactions. 
 He deals with quantities only. The social student, on the 
 contrary, is primarily engrossed in questions of value. 
 Values are the subject matter particularly of economics. 
 And values originate in scarcity, whatever amount of en- 
 ergy is needed to change the forms of matter. 
 
 Goods represent ideas. They are the embodiment of 
 thoughts infinitely rare at one time, and made cheap only 
 in the course of social evolution. All labor, to illustrate 
 our point, may be divided into the repetitive and the in- 
 novating kind. The former may be quantitatively meas- 
 ured. It suggests comparisons. If, for instance, I 
 plow now one acre, and the next time two acres, using 
 the same tools and methods, I have added' to value and 
 may anticipate an increased return. But I have created 
 nothing new. I get more wheat, but it is of the same sort. 
 I used more implements, but of the same sort. Everything 
 was repetition or multiplication. But suppose I breed a 
 
30 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 new variety of wheat, suppose I make certain alterations 
 in the plow-share, suppose I change my principle of fer- 
 tilizing the soil. Here we have an innovation that leads 
 to distinct products: Perhaps it is a new sort of wheat, 
 or wheat in larger amounts for constant effort. 
 
 There is a reliable test for invention or innovation. 
 Namely, if with constant effort, thanks to changes in capi- 
 tal or in the use of it, I procure a bigger return, then I 
 have been an inventor. Or, if I create a new article, 
 something not heretofore on the market, then again I 
 have shown inventiveness. All things now familiar were 
 new once upon a time. There is hardly anything on the 
 market but it was invented once. If an article becomes 
 cheaper or is improved, that change means an innovation 
 in the economic sense. 
 
 Considering these objective tests for an innovation we 
 have an excellent way for distinguishing between things 
 and thoughts. In a printing press we have a combination 
 of thoughts that may or may not have cost effort-in-time. 
 It is not always easy to say when or how an idea origi- 
 nated. In general, to be sure, ideas are the fruit of 
 much intellectual toil. We must have so much school- 
 ing and technical training, whether it's as novelists or as 
 chemists or as mechanics. There is work back of inven- 
 tion. But at the moment a thought comes it may not 
 involve a time-element of labor. Effort-in-time is the 
 sort of effort spent in digging a ditch. We see the mo- 
 tions and may measure them by the hands on the dial of 
 a watch. So with most repetitive acts producing wealth. 
 Yet this is not so applicable to inspirations resulting in 
 new products or in cheapening methods. What shall we 
 say of the inventor of rod and reel, of Arabic numbers, 
 of the alphabet, of the steam engine, or of whatever 
 
KARL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 31 
 
 innovation in science or economics we may have in mind? 
 These are the result of immeasurable labors. 
 
 Ideas are rare, and therefore fetch a high price. It 
 was a good principle for Marx to demand the socializa- 
 tion of ideas, but a bad one to put all sorts of labor into 
 a single class. " Socially necessary labor " is a concept 
 as inadequate as we know the concept of averages to be. 
 Innovations and repetitions should not be put on a level. 
 They are incomparable. Capital goods are not labors 
 piled up in a heap, to be assembled and taken apart at 
 command. The funding of all labor varieties was an 
 awkward scheme for determining price, which after all was 
 not Marx's main task. 
 
 Let us put the matter in another way by asking what 
 would become of the surplus if innovation ever ceased. 
 Marx declares that by making the laborer work for longer 
 hours than are needed to supply him with the essentials 
 of life the capitalist reaps a rich harvest. It is said he 
 takes the extra hours' product and uses it to employ more 
 labor to continue his unfair practices. Thus he waxes 
 rich, and labor is cheated of its belongings. One is 
 tempted to give ear to the argument, were it not for the 
 accumulation of the surplus. If at the beginning this sur- 
 plus is wheat, what do we use it for? The answer can 
 not be that it is to employ more labor to cultivate more 
 land so as to produce more wheat. For, in the first 
 place, this is not the record of economic achievements, and 
 in the second place it does not appeal to our sense of pro- 
 portions. Ere long we should have enormous stocks of 
 wheat; but what for? It is easy to provide for a rainy 
 day, and it is natural to hoard some things. But an 
 endless accumulation of one commodity does not help 
 much. The end of life is variation. The spice of life is 
 
32 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 variety. The march of progress is toward diversification. 
 Ever new things, this is the motto : not an excess of some 
 one staple like wheat. A surplus, originally of foods 
 perhaps, could be valuable only if part of it were used to 
 feed men, not to till the fields to produce wheat, but to 
 produce another kind of food product, or more likely 
 something not to eat, but to wear. And later on each 
 year's surplus of a given class of goods should serve only 
 to dedicate energy to new endeavors. An increase of 
 labor is necessary for the diversification of products. 
 Growth of population is neither an end, nor always an 
 incident, in economic progress. Not multiplication of 
 men and materials, not this primarily, but diversification 
 of products is the chief aim. A larger number of goods 
 produced at less cost ! 
 
 What is the moral? This, that exploitation in itself 
 could not help the captialists if they were not assured of 
 new methods and new products, that is of ideas, of inven- 
 tions which might have been their own, or the laborer's. 
 The surplus view of Marx must either recognize classes of 
 work distinct in a value analysis, or it preaches a silly 
 accumulation of goods that nobody wants because they 
 would soon exceed all possible needs. 
 
 But, in the fourth place, value itself is not measurable 
 by the amount of labor spent in its creation. That fol- 
 lows from what has just been said. But it also is shown 
 by everyday experience, and besides, it was admitted by 
 Marx. Marx indeed had two ways of stating his atti- 
 tude. He could say: Under competitive individualism 
 value is determined by something else than labor cost. 
 True, but I disapprove it. And he could argue: Under 
 socialism prices will vary with costs as defined, that is 
 with socially necessary labor. The latter is the only cor- 
 rect pricing principle. But as we know, Marx did not 
 
KARL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 33 
 
 commit himself in that manner. Instead he pictured 
 prices as labor results quantitatively measurable and com- 
 parable, while insisting also upon a standard of living 
 which according to his surplus theory of value did not 
 exist under capitalism. That under socialism as well as 
 on present terms costs of labor cannot always fix values 
 appears at first moment, but Marx thought the excep- 
 tion to his rule inconsequential. 
 
 5. Marginal Economics. The Marxian economics 
 should be taken seriously and hence criticized where mod- 
 ern science urges it. But it is easy to belittle the Marx- 
 ian concept without remembering its great merits and the 
 influence it has wielded over later minds. More particu- 
 larly one may make sport of some Marxian notions, for- 
 getting that our current economic viewpoint does not 
 rise much above them. The group of economists who 
 stood out in arms against the socialists also attacked the 
 historical movement in general, and of course they had in- 
 creasingly occasion to revise the classic version to Smith, 
 Senior, Ricardo, and of the two Mills. The prevailing 
 economics, though no longer as homogeneous as at the 
 opening of this century, is therefore a reaction against 
 both Ricardianism and against historism. The hope of 
 deducting permanent principles from an exhaustive 
 searching into economic history has been pretty well 
 abandoned. A number of factors contributed to the de- 
 cline of the historical methods, though we may regard 
 J. S. Mill's Logis, which appeared in 1842, as a turning 
 point for economic method; for Mill's own Principles of 
 Economics show no trace of a method distinctive of social 
 science, as presaged in the Logic. If the acute J. S. Mill 
 returned to deduction, what could others expect from his- 
 torism? The Austrian economists combated historism 
 because of their training under philosophers who sep- 
 
34, THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 arated rigidly deduction from induction, and had no con- 
 fidence in Hegelian prophecies. Hence men like Menger 
 and Wieser, Boehm-Bawerk and Sax were ready to re- 
 claim the field of investigation, which the Historical 
 School, like scientific socialism, had declared barren and 
 unfit for use. 
 
 But in fact, the marginal approach was in thorough 
 agreement with the psychological movement of the second 
 and third quarters of the nineteenth century. The trend 
 was distinctly toward introspective analysis supplemented 
 and corrected by exact measurement of reactions to ex- 
 ternally applied stimuli. Psychology rapidly established 
 itself as an objective science, with the result that the 
 facts of human nature were definitely classified and char- 
 acterized. 
 
 This way of redefining values marks also the marginal 
 school of economists who, beginning with Gossen, Walras, 
 and Jevons, revamped the Ricardian notions by shifting 
 the emphasis from work to wants, and from materials to 
 margins of response. Much of the classic structure was 
 left untouched, but the nomenclature changed greatly. 
 
 The marginal viewpoint abandoned the attempt of ex- 
 plaining prices through expenses in time and effort. It 
 went directly to the question of wants, and by compar- 
 ing their different intensities tried to explain prices. It 
 showed that we care relatively the less for a stock of 
 goods the larger it is, and that we constantly seek to 
 equalize our supplies of different kinds of commodities. 
 Hence the marginal procedure led away from costs to 
 sacrifice, and from production of stuffs to creation of 
 values, no matter whether they took palpable form or not. 
 
 Like the Ricardian the marginal view is static. It pic- 
 tures a process at rest in a given moment, much as a pho- 
 tograph reveals certain facial expressions. The advan- 
 
KARL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 35 
 
 tages of a moving picture over a snapshot compare ap- 
 proximately with the superiorities of a dynamic over a 
 static method of dissection. 
 
 Like Ricardo, the Marginists, too, assume competition, 
 private property, and freedom of contract. It is not for 
 them to question the worth of our social order. They 
 take it as it is and proceed to define their terms accord- 
 ingly. Everything hinges on competition and on the mo- 
 bility of labor and capital. Since, furthermore, capital is 
 a right under the law it is entitled to a share of the na- 
 tional product. But here the Marginists became bold in 
 making out of capital goods a bundle of property rights 
 rather than a work of ideas. Rights were continually 
 stressed, and social aspects subordinated to them. Capi- 
 tal, even if not taking concrete shape, they called a 
 factor of production just as truly as manual labor or soil 
 fertility. There existed consequently at least three " fac- 
 tors " of production, though toward the end of the century 
 enterprise was segregated from labor upon due recog- 
 nition of its unique functions under individualism. Thus 
 we get really four agents in production, all of which had a 
 share in the social dividend according to some principle of 
 distribution. 
 
 The notion of cost was materially modified, for as 
 against the classics the Marginists did not begin with 
 labor. They started with desires. They asked: Why is 
 so much labor spent in producing an article, and instead 
 of answering as the older men would have, that the tech- 
 nique of production could not do it in less time, they 
 pointed to the intensity of our want. Man, it now ap- 
 peared, was willing to give so much labor to the creation 
 of a certain commodity because compared with others he 
 wanted it so much that the labor did not seem excessive. 
 The need of food, shelter, and clothing comes first. Noth- 
 
36 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 ing can take precedence over it, and hence any amount of 
 toil necessary to produce them will be expended. But for 
 the remainder of our level of living we are governed by 
 different rates of wants, some being intense enough to fol- 
 low immediately after the essentials, and others being 
 classed as luxuries. The march of progress is the exten- 
 sion of wants and the thinning of the margins at which we 
 choose to buy one article instead of another. When we 
 have decided on this matter, then the amount of effort de- 
 voted to the production of an article will be revealed. 
 Costs are the proof of valuation measured by our willing- 
 ness to sacrifice one good for another. Time and energy, 
 materials and thought, are secondary facts in the explana- 
 tion of price. 
 
 The whole subject of cost versus want was finally 
 worked over and the true relation between the two dis- 
 closed. It could hardly escape the notice of observant 
 students that expenses as treated by the marginal view 
 were valuations of the past, and that therefore in a sense 
 all costs were values. But by the same ruling expenses 
 could be admitted as a certain objective way of measur- 
 ing subjective aspects, and so, in stretching the static 
 outlook to cover decades at a time, costs and wants be- 
 came complementary. " In the long run " they could be 
 pictured as two sides of one and the same thing. The 
 reconciliation seemed opportune, and served to give a new 
 lease of life to the individualistic conception of product 
 and price. 
 
 As shown in our Table, productivity according to the 
 Marginists is a rate of return in goods per outgo of other 
 goods, each good being defined as a scarce transferable 
 utility, and a utility as anything satisfying any want. 
 From this followed the interesting development of the con- 
 cept of diminishing returns which no Ricardian would 
 
KARL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 37 
 
 have understood. It was shown that since production is 
 a competitive concept referring to values, the costs of 
 production could not fall merely in agriculture. For one 
 thing, the yield in concrete things did not mean every- 
 thing because economics reckons in values, in dollars and 
 cents. If the farmer, for instance, sold a smaller crop 
 at a larger aggregate gain than a larger crop in the 
 previous year, then his rate of return had risen. And in 
 the next place it became more and more apparent that in 
 all fields of endeavor there is a right and a wrong way 
 of doing things. The terrifying law of diminishing re- 
 turns thus was converted into the perfectly harmless prin- 
 ciple of a proportionality of factors. It was shown, as 
 everybody indeed knew, that temperance is a virtue, that 
 a sense of proportions will do wonders, that too much 
 of one element in a compound will spoil it. The marginal 
 view made land, labor, capital and enterprise the four 
 factors of production. Let them be mixed in one way, 
 and maximum return results for the business manager ; let 
 him violate the law of proportions and he will obtain less 
 than the maximum. Space and time also entered into the 
 situation, and all in all the purification of Ricardian no- 
 tions left the economist little better off than he had been 
 before. 
 
 But the marginal definition of productivity helped in 
 one respect. Namely the rule of margins in valuation 
 was applied to the services of the agents in production, 
 the rate of pay depending on the marginal product of 
 each agent. On a short-time view the least effectively 
 employed unit of labor or capital set the pace for the 
 remaining units. None could get more than the marginal 
 one, for the same reason that the least valued dose in a 
 stock of homogeneous goods fixed the value of the whole 
 stock. One had only to multiply the number of units 
 
38 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 in a stock by the utility or value of the marginal 
 item to compute the value of the whole stock. Incomes 
 varied on the same principle. On a long-time view how- 
 ever the better worker was a blessing to the inferior, 
 for competition would sooner or later force a distribution 
 of the additional product, the marginal man benefiting 
 with the rest. Each factor received his " product " as 
 per definition. Profits were the only exception, because 
 they tended toward a minimum. Or rather, as some an- 
 nounced, there were no profits under perfect competition, 
 only a wage of management. 
 
 Consequently land and labor benefited most by technical 
 improvements. Interest rates were also subject to the 
 general law, but meant less to the practical-minded 
 student of distribution. Laborers would obtain a grow- 
 ing share of the national dividend because of the effect of 
 invention on productivity. The landlord could not claim 
 it all, as Ricardo had apprehended. The economic process 
 was less cruel than the classics had made it out to be. 
 Hence the Marginists favored frankly the competitive 
 principle and tolerated interference only where it was 
 proven absolutely indispensable. They had shown that 
 each gets what he deserves according to definitions of 
 utility, value, and capital, so no occasion arose for com- 
 plaint. 
 
 A glance at Table One informs us that the marginal 
 and the Ricardian viewpoints are not as far apart as 
 either compared with the socialistic. In spite of im- 
 portant revisions the Ricardian doctrine survived the ad- 
 vent of Marginism. The modern orthodox economic 
 standpoint marks a step in advance, but its logic is the 
 old. The competitive principle colors everything. Ab- 
 stractions rule as before. Ricardo like the Marginists 
 approved of the world as he found it. As the Table 
 
KARL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 39 
 
 shows they agreed in nine out of the eighteen points, while 
 Marx and the Marginists had only five in common. Four 
 of the eighteen points were held in common by Ricardians, 
 Marxians, and Marginists, but of course Marx's defini- 
 tions of value are only provisional. He is opposed to the 
 individualistic norms. He uses them solely to arraign the 
 capitalist. His chief aim is the annihilation of what the 
 other two groups wished to leave undisturbed. 
 
 The question then is not merely one of logic. One will 
 ask : How much more satisfactory was the marginal view 
 than the heresies of socialism? Or, more to the point, 
 what oddities of reasoning appear in it that orthodox 
 economics is not guilty of, too? 
 
 | 6. Criticism of Marginal Economics. The Marxian 
 like the Ricardian view emphasizes labor as the source of 
 values, and it measures them by the amounts of labor 
 spent in the creation of a value. This is one way of mak- 
 ing values objective and is naturally thought of first be- 
 cause time and effort are facts every one is acquainted 
 with. Marx saw no reason for rejecting the labor 
 standard, though he enlarged upon the concept by social- 
 izing labor. He not only proposed to attribute all values 
 in exchang^ to the labor needed for the production of 
 scarce utilities, but he furthermore averaged different 
 rates of production. He made three points : He de- 
 clared labor to be the sole fount of all values ; he reduced 
 all kinds of effort, manual and mental, to a homogeneous 
 stock (what he called labor power) and he standardized 
 costs in labor by establishing an arithmetical average of 
 different amounts of labor applied, in terms of hours of 
 work, by different individuals or groups to the produc- 
 tion of equal values. This latter procedure was 
 peculiarly Marxian. 
 
 Now, the marginal procedure is different in one sense, 
 
40 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 but much like it in another, for while it displaces labor 
 by valuations, it none the less averages different valua- 
 tions just as Marx averaged different productivities 
 measured by effort-in-time. According to the marginal 
 view different want intensities of different individuals with 
 different tastes and different incomes, that is purchasing 
 powers, may be reduced to an average which expresses 
 itself in the bidding of buyers and sellers in a competitive 
 market. It has been pointed out by critics that such is 
 not an admissible device, because logically no such average 
 can be proven to exist. Individuals as averages are a 
 piece of fiction anyway. But it deserves mention here 
 that the marginal economists made this average a central 
 feature in their price determination. 
 
 What is more, the Marxian assumption of a fairly con- 
 stant labor-power per average individual has the ad- 
 vantage of making one cost do for several sales at differ- 
 ent times. But if the Marginists are right, valuations 
 fluctuate constantly so that really an article is sold at a 
 valuation of the present moment which in all probability 
 differs from the valuations embodied in the article at the 
 time it was produced. That is, we must resort to another 
 averaging of variations of want in order to establish 
 some fixed relation between the price of a finished com- 
 modity, which by the way represents as many prices as 
 it has constituent costs, and the productivity-rate of re- 
 turn. To the Marginists this relation is a very definite 
 one. It is one of identity. Prices measure factorial 
 shares. But the averaging is as risky for the pro- 
 ductivity-theory of incomes as it is inadequate for the 
 explanation of commodity prices. 
 
 Marx was not so embarrassed, for in adopting im- 
 plicitly, though not expressedly, the Malthusian formula 
 he simplified distribution as Ricardo had done. There 
 
KARJL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 41 
 
 were only three factors. One was paid a subsistence 
 wage, the other received a supra-marginal product from 
 the soil, and the third took the leavings. Very simple ! 
 
 The marginal standpoint, however, led to other predic- 
 aments, some of them not more amusing than impressive. 
 For instance, according to the concept of consumer's sur- 
 plus a man saved the more the less he saved. In the 
 great majority of cases a purchase was a saving because 
 the article was worth more to the buyer than he was 
 forced under competition to pay for it. He had all kinds 
 of units of utility left after he got his money's worth. 
 Let him, therefore, spend more and enjoy more consumer's 
 surplus. 
 
 On the other hand there was the bugbear of alternative 
 costs which no entrepreneur could escape. He was rarely 
 sure of having invested his funds the best possible way. 
 Every advantage in employment of capital was offset, by 
 the sacrifice of investment elsewhere. The option was a 
 nagging thought that should figure in the ledger when 
 investment was not the most lucrative possible. A farmer 
 too should reckon as costs for fodder the price at which 
 he would have had to buy it hadn't he produced it himself 
 at a lower cost. And the interest charge grew every 
 minute, for everything reconvertible into pure capital, or 
 what once was in the shape of liquid capital, ate up in- 
 terest. All consumption goods, indeed, might have been 
 used as capital. Since they were not, a loss could be 
 claimed. The individualistic outlook permitted such cost 
 accounting. 
 
 It also gave birth to the famous paradox of value which 
 the Austrian economists first expounded, and which has 
 often since served to illustrate the principle of marginal 
 utilities. But note what one might flippantly infer from 
 it : It apparently makes it possible to destroy and create 
 
4 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 capital in the same act. If the spice-importers, for in- 
 stance, feared the effect of large supplies on price they 
 could save themselves by sinking a portion of the cargo 
 of spices. They would sink the ships and raise the prices 
 and probably aggregate profits. Such is the test of 
 monopoly. They used the cargo as part of their working 
 capital, say of their " circulating " capital. They de- 
 stroyed part of this capital by casting spices overboard. 
 But the same act also increased the value of the residual 
 of spices. Capital was therefore created while it was 
 destroyed. 
 
 Or notice the curiosity of the marginal capital defini- 
 tion, by which one and the same article became alternately 
 capital and non-capital, that is a consumption good. 
 The piano in the baker's shop was capital while used to 
 attract customers. It was part of his earning assets 
 then. But if used to entertain the same people after 
 closing hours it became a mere utility. The baker's fam- 
 ily listened to an instrument forming part of his wages of 
 management ; the customers were regaled by the employ- 
 ment of capital. Likewise cocaine sold illicitly at a drug- 
 store was capital, while mother's care of her children was 
 non-productive labor, since it was not offered for sale in 
 the open market. 
 
 Finally, it deserves mention that Marx was at least con- 
 sistent in his position as ethicist. He did better than the 
 marginal group for two reasons. Namely, in the first 
 place he did not incorporate moral topics in his Capital. 
 True, like his followers, he hinted plainly at a moral 
 issue. Nobody could condemn private capital and not 
 plead guilty to a charge of moralism. But Marx kept 
 reform programs out of his text. He did not profess 
 to purge economics of all ethical background and then 
 proceed to discuss at great length many questions of re- 
 
KARL MARX AND THE ECONOMISTS 43 
 
 form and legislation such as frequently characterize 
 modern texts for school use. 
 
 In the second place he grounded his ethics more se- 
 curely than the Marginists who were drilled in the meta- 
 physical style of moralizing. If economics declines to 
 deal with moral matters, pretending that somebody else 
 has preempted that field, it is guilty of a contradiction 
 of terms. It was socialism which first drove home this 
 point, and familiarized the man of the street with the 
 social aspects of religion and ethics. The Marxian 
 economics excels in that it makes ethics part of social 
 science. It reduces all knowledge to experience, that of 
 "the moralist included. Largely to demonstrate this 
 unity of thought and to give reform movements a solid 
 basis the founders of socialism elaborated their concept 
 of history, thus preparing the way for a view of life 
 which must unify all sciences, however distinct their sub- 
 jects. 
 
CHAPTER III 
 
 THE ECONOMIC INTERPRETATION OF 
 HISTORY 
 
 i. Main Roots of the Economic Interpretation of 
 History Back of Marx's " Kapital " is his economic in- 
 terpretation of history. It is hardly possible to under- 
 stand fully what he meant to say in his ponderous econo- 
 mic treatise without looking into his other views of a some- 
 what philosophic nature. In regard to Marx we have 
 here a situation that not infrequently is true of other 
 great minds. We read one of their works and judge them 
 by it, or at least consider it something complete in itself, 
 forgetting that, if more was written, it probably bears 
 on the very book we are studying. For mind is a unit, 
 and eminent thinkers have given perspective to their 
 thought so that what appears at one place is more or 
 less closely connected with everything else. As we grow 
 we frequently change our interests and write on subjects 
 originally not at all in our mind. We are driven from 
 one problem to another, and so ultimately arrive at ideas 
 that will influence us the rest of our life in treating of 
 anything, no matter how far apart the topics. Thus it 
 is difficult to appreciate Aristotle's " Politics " unless one 
 is familiar with his Metaphysics and Ethics. Thus 
 we may read Adam Smith on the " Wealth of Nations," 
 but fail to get its total range without some knowledge 
 of his " Theory of the Moral Sentiments." Thus again 
 one is entitled to judge John Stuart Mill by his " Prin- 
 ciples of Political Economy." That work should stand 
 
 44 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 45 
 
 or fall by its contents. But how much may easily be 
 missed if his " Logic " has not been given a thorough in- 
 spection beforehand! 
 
 And so with Marx and Engels as founders of social- 
 ism. Their criticism of the individualistic economics of 
 their day is one thing. We may understand it and draw 
 our conclusions. But what Marx said in his " Kapital," 
 and how he said it, that is a point to be inquired into by 
 an independent study of his earlier expositions on history 
 and Hegelianism. Huge growths have remote beginnings. 
 Giant trees send out their main roots deep into the soil, 
 and far from the trunk feeders are still to be found 
 whose function is to give life to the very trunk that seems 
 so majestically self-sufficient. Great rivers similarly 
 have their headwaters in perhaps far off, inaccessible 
 regions. In lofty heights the stream is born that later 
 on we find so useful and overpowering in its grandeur. 
 We do not possibly care to explore the upper reaches, 
 but in this distant ancestry that gives rise to so many 
 tributaries we have the explanation of the end result it- 
 self. 
 
 The founders of socialism were no mean men. They 
 were extraordinary men who worked like titans and 
 pierced the surface of things. They went far for their 
 raw material out of which the socialistic creed was slowly 
 built. They consulted many sources and drew inspiration 
 from thinkers that in their time had no interest in matters 
 economic. Thus the intellectual labors of preceding cen- 
 turies bore fruit in the controversial writings of Marx 
 and Engels, and in their propaganda which since has 
 given so much food for thought to an inquiring age. One 
 must read Marx's articles in the Rheinische Zeitung, or 
 his books against Proudhon and the Feuerbach group, to 
 divine some of the thoughts basic to socialism. In his 
 
46 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 " Misery of Philosophy " and " Holy Family " are ele- 
 ments reconstructed later in the " Critique of Political 
 Economy," but utilized also in the " Communist Mani- 
 festo," as well as in the " Kapital." Of Engels the out- 
 put is in a sense not so important because it was for the 
 most part written after the economic interpretation of 
 history had been formulated. Yet there is much of value 
 in the " Anti-Diihring " and in the " Essay on Feuerbach," 
 both of which represent answers to critics of scientific 
 socialism as it flourished in the last quarter of the nine- 
 teenth century. Engels was the philosopher, if Marx was 
 the economist. However, on the one hand, Marx could 
 think philosophically himself, though he had done with it 
 comparatively early in life, and on the other hand Engels 
 never forgot the economic background whose disagreeable 
 features had prompted him to describe the condition of 
 the working classes in England, as they existed in the 
 second quarter of his century. Strictly speaking both 
 were incapable of the sort of thinking which character- 
 izes professional philosophers. We do not find any evi- 
 dence that they could follow Hegel, e. g., through the 
 maze of his reasoning which led from " Logic " to the 
 " Philosophy of History." In perusing the youthful 
 works of Marx one is struck with what he didn't notice 
 in Hegel rather than with what he selected for criticism. 
 However, while he made no pretense of fathoming the full 
 depth of metaphysical problems, he took care to seize 
 upon salient points that could prove useful to his sociolo- 
 gical outlook. Hence the transcendental thought of 
 Hegel's time is part of scientific socialism. Hence the 
 " Critique of Political Economy " really begins with 
 searchings into matters not now recognized as scientific. 
 
 Whether the economic interpretation of history is 
 peculiarly the product of Marx and Engels is perhaps 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 47 
 
 not an important question. Those who have delved some- 
 what into the genesis of that mighty concept will prob- 
 ably concede to the founders of socialism a large measure 
 of originality in this respect. One may make many ex- 
 cursions into the relevant literature of those days with- 
 out meeting any such formula as Marx and Engels made 
 famous in their " Manifesto of 1848." On the whole it 
 seems fair to grant these two men the lion share of the 
 glory, and to distinguish generously between the in- 
 gredients they found at hand and the product they turned 
 out with them. There had been materialism before, as 
 everybody knows, but it had not been given a historical 
 application. There had been economic interpretations of 
 life from the early eighteenth century on, but they had 
 not been cloaked in a metaphysical form. Historio- 
 graphy is of ancient origin, and the notion of change 
 dates from early Greek speculation, but none of it yielded 
 a Marxian recipe. 
 
 Again, the genetic standpoint which socialism has al- 
 ways so ardently defended predominated when Marx 
 was born. The Romantic movement was essentially 
 genetic. One looked back to forget the present, or to 
 understand it. The great names of that age are known 
 as. well for their views on the social process as for their 
 literary creations. But, once more, this does not rob 
 Marx and Engels of their supreme merit as first expound- 
 ers of a materialistic view of history. 
 
 We might say : England is the cradle of materialism 
 as the metaphysician understands the term. From there 
 it went to France and gave rise to a school of thought 
 whose culminating achievement is, in a way, the Mecha- 
 nique Celeste of La Place. The writings of Cabanis and 
 Diderot and Helvetius familiarized people with a ma- 
 terialistic valuation of life. The Baron d'Holbach also 
 
48 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 contributed his mite. But this type of materialism was 
 too mechanical to suit Marx. Like Engels he relied more 
 upon Hobbes and Locke than upon the French. On the 
 other hand, the historical viewpoint had gained ground 
 notably in France. Lamarck and Condorcet were great 
 figures. And again, if from England came Spencer, 
 Darwin, and Wallace, Germany furnished a Herder, 
 Humboldt and Goethe. Thus three countries provided the 
 streams of thought that finally converged in the socialistic 
 movement. The biological aspect is English, the his- 
 torical aspect first gained repute in France, and the so- 
 ciological or economic aspect was most cultivated in Ger- 
 many. Together these nations developed the evolution- 
 ary standpoint. Thanks to such beginnings the social- 
 ists could go ahead. Hegel completed for Marx what 
 Hobbes and Montesquieu had begun. 
 
 The German materialistic view of Biichner and his 
 ilk was of no great moment for Marx. It came some- 
 what too late. Furthermore, Marx wanted concepts of 
 motion, not pronouncements on matter or space. The 
 achievements of chemistry therefore did not greatly im- 
 press him aa, a student in quest of a masterkey which 
 should open the doors to social progress The inclination 
 for a matter of fact view of life existed early in him 
 no less than in Engels, but the impetus that moved him 
 onward till death came from the last of the philosophic 
 critics ! Hegel " made " Marx ! 
 
 2. Influence of Hegel It is of no import here 
 what Hegel preached and how he reacted upon the 
 " Critique of Pure Reason." But we must keep in mind 
 some of the main tenets on which he erected his phe- 
 nomenal reputation as a metaphysician. Hegel was a 
 Platonian absolutist, for one thing. In the second place 
 his analysis of mind and knowledge led him to the evolv- 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 49 
 
 ing of a concept of progress and reality which is unique 
 in philosophic history. Hegel not only believed in a 
 reality transcending our sense experience, but he pictured 
 the processes of cognition as focussed upon a single point 
 which marked the terminal of social evolution. To 
 Hegel there was a design in history. The teleological 
 assumption pervades all his reasoning. And with this he 
 coupled a theory of State that has astonished those who 
 dwell fondly on his Logic. Hegel, then, was a theist 
 with monarchical leanings, an exponent of idealistic 
 values, and a firm believer in the scientific character of 
 introspection, of what he called the science of all sciences, 
 to wit Logic. 
 
 Marx was not enamored with this side of the great 
 teacher at Berlin. But he, like Engels, took readily to 
 the other side in Hegelian teachings which later on gave 
 rise to diverse empirical movements in philosophy. 
 Hegel namely sought to establish the identity of nature 
 and mind in a manner not attempted by Kant. He bore 
 in mind more consistently than his illustrious predeces- 
 sors the maxim that whatever we know is limited by a 
 knoweiv Intelligibility rests on the intelligence, and to 
 look beyond this is a task distinct from the first prin- 
 ciples in logic. The first principles must seek to explain 
 how we know anything and how our experiences may 
 change without losing continuity. This problem drove 
 Hegel to his dialectic by which he connected the object 
 with the subject. He admitted that in reflecting upon 
 our experiences we actually alter their contents, but he 
 also pointed to the connecting link between steps of cog- 
 nition. We do get ahold of the world about us, though 
 our conclusions change as we shift viewpoint and alter 
 premises. A contrasting and compounding of judgments 
 ever takes place. By it we secure new truths, but move 
 
50 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 in pendulum swings that turn truth into falsehood. We 
 go from thesis to antithesis, and hence to synthesis. In 
 an Aufhebung der Momente, as Hegel styles the process, 
 we add to our knowledge while losing part of what we have 
 felt. Thus, logically viewed, learning is given movement 
 and direction. All things become relative. We live in a 
 world of contradictions. What the old logicians said 
 about laws of Identity and Excluded Middle is only under 
 certain reservations acceptable, for a thing may both be 
 and not be. It may be good and bad also. If it is not, it 
 may become. If it is, there exists a raison d'etre, but as 
 against this we have the prospect of decay and a resur- 
 rection of the old in totally different forms. 
 
 This idea that all things are relative to each in the 
 sense that one judgment necessarily grows out of a pre- 
 ceding one a thought Hegel seems to have distilled from 
 studies in Greek metaphysics this idea suited the tem- 
 perament and needs of Marx and Engels. They poked 
 fun at the absolutistic phase of Hegelian beliefs, but they 
 were deeply impressed with the weight of his main con- 
 tention. 
 
 When Hegel wrote that " the State represents God's 
 progress in the world, it rests on the power of will taking 
 embodiment in Reason. The State must not be identified 
 with any particular nation, but with God himself " l - 
 Marx could not give assent. As early as 1843 he sug- 
 gests that " the worst enemy of real humanism (that 
 is of socialism) in Germany is speculative idealism." 2 
 And in the " Holy Family " Feuerbach is lauded because 
 he put Man in the place of " all this f olderol about the in- 
 
 1 Hegel, " Enzyklopaedie," 258; 272. 
 
 2 Marx, K., " Heilige Familie," Preface, printed in Mehring, F. 
 Aus dem Literarischen Nachlass von Karl Marx, Friedrich Engels, 
 und Ferdinand Lassalle, Volume I. 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 51 
 
 finite self-consciousness," 3 which Hegel made the center 
 of his Logic. Idealism was not to the liking of men who 
 were engrossed in economic studies and sought a remedy 
 for existing evils. More particularly Marx was not 
 satisfied with the type of historism he read out of the 
 Enzyklopaedie. He exclaims : " Hegel's historical con- 
 cept is nothing but a speculative expression of the Chris- 
 tian-Teutonic dogma of opposition between spirit and mat- 
 ter, between God and the world." 4 Such a construc- 
 tion was alien, perhaps, to the mind of a converted Jew. 
 
 But all the more glad, then, were the founders of scien- 
 tific socialism when after HegePs death one grow) of 
 disciples turned radical and exploited/the relativisticl side 
 rather than the idealistic. Hegel's* Immense range and 
 generalizing applications admitted naturally of a great 
 variety of interpretations. Those who saw the force of 
 the first and second part of his Logic agreed to ignore 
 the third, thus getting rid of absolutism. The pragmatic 
 penchant in the master was now boldly emphasized and 
 quickly elaborated into a new sort of humanism. We 
 have men who like the brothers Feuerbach, like Bauer 
 and Strauss transferred the logical relativity into a 
 sociological one. Feuerbach especially created a stir with 
 his " Essence of Christianity " in which religion was hu- 
 manized and Christianity expounded in metaphysical 
 fashion. In the end Ludwig Feuerbach turned away 
 from the materialistic position that at first his readers 
 placed him in, but Marx kept what he found good and 
 used it for his historical interpretation. 
 
 Hegel himself had furnished part of the Marxian view, 
 as was frankly admitted. As Engels at a later date put 
 it: "From this (the Hegelian) point of view the history 
 
 a Ibidem, Chapter VI. 
 * Ibidem, Chapter V. 
 
52 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 of mankind no longer appeared as a wild whirl of sense- 
 less deeds of violence, all equally condemnable at the judg- 
 ment seat of mature philosophic reason, as deeds which 
 are best forgotten, but as the process of evolution of man 
 himself. It was now the task of the intellect to follow 
 the gradual march of this process through all its devious 
 ways, and to trace out the inner law running through all 
 its apparently accidental phenomena." 5 And when 
 Feuerbach added to this the humanistic concept by which 
 man was made the center of things, the sole judge and 
 jury of all values in science and philosophy, then his- 
 torism assumed definite meaning. The hedonistic view of 
 Friedrich Feuerbach prevailed over the theism of his elder 
 brother. 6 
 
 Hegel's devotion to an Absolute was ridiculed. His 
 transcendentalism evoked only the scorn of Marx who 
 concluded that the metaphysical procedure turned things 
 upside down, making a phantom out of what was real, 
 and worshipful truth out of what man had known and 
 never could sense. To Hegel, we read in Engels' " So- 
 cialism Utopian and Scientific," " the thoughts within his 
 brain were not the more or less abstract pictures of 
 actual things and processes, but conversely things and 
 their evolution were only the realized picture of the Idea 
 existing somewhere from eternity, before the world was. 
 This way of thinking turned everything upside down and 
 completely reversed the actual connection of things in the 
 world " 7 About the same time this was in 1873 
 Marx wrote in the Preface to the first volume of his Kapi- 
 
 5 Engels, F., "Socialism, Utopian and Scientific," p. 95. A popu- 
 lar version in English dress of the same author's " Anti-Diihring." 
 See especially Friedrich Feuerbach, "Die Religion der Zukunft." 
 7 Engels, F., "Socialism, Utopian and Scientific," p. 86, and in 
 "Anti-Diihring," p. 30. 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 53 
 
 tal : " To Hegel the life process of the human brain, i. e., 
 the process of thinking which, under the name of the Idea 
 he even transformed into an independent subject, is the 
 demiurgos of the real world, and the world is only the 
 external, phenomenal form of the Idea. With me, on the 
 contrary, the ideal is nothing else than the material world 
 reflected by'Tlie Human mind, and translated into forms of 
 thought." 
 
 The dialectic now became a simple affair. It was, as 
 Engels observes in his " Anti-Duhring," " nothing but the 
 science of the universal laws of motion and evolution in 
 nature, human society, and thought." That is to say, 
 Marx and Engels transferred the thought of relativity 
 from the field of psychology, or better still of induction, 
 to the field of historiography. It was clear to them that 
 what Hegel treated only as a mode of individual reason- 
 ing was really a principle of progress by which past and 
 future might be explained. If one judgment gives rise 
 to an opposite the fusion of the two being a new truth, 
 then surely historical epochs could similarly move by ex- 
 tremes. If contradiction was the leading characteristic of 
 cognition, why not overlapping of ideas and conditions the 
 core of history ? If we have partial identity in a continu- 
 ous flux of realities, why should not different historical 
 epochs be linked by institutions only partly in harmony 
 with them ? The predetermination of conclusions by their 
 premises surely had a counterpart in the casual connec- 
 tion between successive environments, their particulars 
 and interlaced aspects. 
 
 3. The Marxian Statement of the Economic Inter- 
 pretation of History. Thus the Logic of Hegel was con- 
 verted by Marx and Engels into a temporal process gov- 
 erning the life of nations. What some have dubbed Eco- 
 nomic Determinism is the outgrowth of Hegelian dialec- 
 
54 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 tics. 8 From the Enzyklopsedie to " Das Kapital," this is 
 a true line of descent ! The Hegelian method, some have 
 argued, was vigorously applied in Marx's analysis of ex- 
 change and surplus value. No doubt one may defend that 
 view. But more direct is the relation between Hegelian 
 metaphysics and the prosaic, empirical concept of his- 
 tory by which the indictment spread before us in Kapital 
 is reduced to a mere detail. 
 
 The economic version of history develops rapidly in 
 Marx's mind after Hegel and the Hegelian Left had chal- 
 lenged his attention. His intimate associations with the 
 radicals in philosophy furthered greatly his intellectual 
 progress. As early as 1843, a propos of a review of 
 Hegel's Rechtsphilosophie, Marx says : " Theories among 
 people are put into realization only so far as its practical 
 needs demand. It isn't enough that ideas urge us to 
 action ; the actualities about us must generate the 
 thoughts themselves before they may become prac- 
 ticable." " We insist," adds Engels at a much later 
 date, " that all hitherto formulated theories on ethics are 
 the outgrowth, at last analysis, of the economic condi- 
 tions ruling during the period in question." Eighteenth 
 century materialism was thus reapplied in a novel man- 
 ner. The static view was displaced by the dynamic. 
 Motion was given to a play of forces once pictured as at 
 rest. Social facts are classified and compared as to their 
 antecedents and stage of evolution relative to a given 
 epoch. The economic interpretation is rounded out, and 
 
 s Compare the Marxian view with Feuerbach, L., in " Essence of 
 Christianity" (translated by N. Evans), p. 23: "Time, and not the 
 Hegelian dialectic, is the medium for uniting opposites in one and 
 the same subject." 
 
 Reprint in Mehring, F. Nachlass, Volume I. 
 
 10 Engels, F., " Anti-Diihring." 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 55 
 
 by the time that Marx left the continent, to spend the 
 remainder of his busy life on English soil, the materialis- 
 tic conception of history is already full-blown. Modifi- 
 cations were later allowed by Engels, 11 doubtless as a sop 
 to party demands, and also by way of defense against 
 accusations hurled at his revered friend, but for all un- 
 biased students the passage in Marx's " Critique of Politi- 
 cal Economy " will rank as the most authoritative and 
 most complete statement of scientific socialism. 
 
 We read in the Critique, 12 published many years before 
 the first volume of Kapital came from the press : " In the 
 social production which men carry on they enter into defi- 
 nite relations that are indispensable and independent of 
 their will. These relations of production correspond to a 
 definite stage of development of their material powers of 
 production. The sum total of these relations of produc- 
 tion constitutes the economic structure of society the 
 real foundation, on which legal and political superstruc- 
 tures arise, and to which correspond definite forms of so- 
 cial consciousness. The mode of production in material 
 life determines the general character of the social, polit- 
 ical, and spiritual processes of life. It is not the con- 
 sciousness of men that determines their existence, but on 
 the contrary their social existence determines their con- 
 sciousness." 
 
 Let us note, before quoting further, that the material 
 basis of life is said to consist of the means and modes of 
 production, and that these give rise to " relations of pro- 
 duction " which in turn furnish the substratum for all 
 non-economic relations. Thus law and religion, art and 
 
 11 Engels, F., " Der StOzialistische Akademiker," 1895 (Zwei 
 Briefe). 
 
 12 Marx, K., "Critique of Political Economy," Preface, 1859. 
 English translation by N. I. Stone, published by Ch. Kerr & Co. 
 
56 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 science receive their impress from the mold into which 
 they are (according to Marx) necessarily cast. 
 
 But Marx goes on to show how economic relations are 
 everchanging, the superstructure therefore becoming like- 
 wise unstable. Different rates of change are virtually re- 
 ferred to. A maladaptation of customs to conditions in 
 the concrete is the result which is generally accompanied 
 by social unrest. The Zeitgeist " must be explained from 
 the contradictions in our collective living, from the exist- 
 ing conflict between the social forces of production and the 
 relations of production." These latter are known to us 
 as " the property relations " because of the stage of eco- 
 nomic development that mankind has now arrived at. 
 When the faultline in these strata of social life becomes 
 too marked an upheaval may naturally be expected. 
 Changes then will come rapidly. In the facts of the pres- 
 ent moment we have the part determiners of a future 
 crisis, a thought put by Marx as follows : " No social or- 
 der ever disappears before all the productive forces, for 
 which there is room in it, have been developed; and hew, 
 higher relations of production never appear before the ma- 
 terial conditions of their existence have matured in the 
 womb of the old society. Therefore mankind always 
 takes up only such problems as it can solve, since, looking 
 at the matter more closely, we will always find that the 
 problem itself arises only when the material conditions 
 necessary to its solution already exist, or at least are in 
 the process of formation." 
 
 By this route then Marx has finally reached the point 
 which relates most closely to his practical aims. He re- 
 minds us of the cosmic principle governing all life, and 
 adds : " The bourgeois relations of production are the 
 last antagonistic form of the social process of production 
 antagonistic not in the sense of individual antagonism, 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 57 
 
 but antagonism arising from conditions surrounding the 
 life of individuals in society. But at the same time the 
 productive forces developing in the work of bourgeois so- 
 ciety create the material conditions for the solution of 
 that antagonism." 
 
 The economic analysis thus becomes simply a monu- 
 mental proof of a theorem regarding historical evolution. 
 Surplus theory and the socialization of capital are con- 
 cepts centering about the Economic Interpretation of His- 
 tory. The misery of the masses, Marx demonstrates, is 
 bound to end because beliefs and laws change with the 
 material, economic environment. The case of the prole- 
 tariat rests with the gods who laid down a mighty prin- 
 ciple of life, but also with man to the extent that he is 
 able to utilize the principle. Things move in a cycle, or 
 perhaps we should say, in a spiral course leading upward. 
 Capitalism is doomed, for it leads to exploitation of labor, 
 to overproduction and unemployment, to vast combina- 
 tions of capital destructive of small enterprise, and hence 
 to rebellion on the part of an outraged populace. 
 
 The Marxian idea of history, for this reason, could not 
 fail to buoy up the spirits of those who, resentful of their 
 employers' tactics, yet saw no way of regenerating them 
 by peaceful methods. 
 
CHAPTER IV 
 
 THE ECONOMIC INTERPRETATION OF 
 HISTORY (Continued) 
 
 | i. Importance of the Economic Interpretation of 
 History. A correct interpretation of history is im- 
 portant because of its bearing on our future conduct. 
 Logically we should be guided by events of the past, for 
 history is only a record of past events which resulted from 
 the interaction of human nature and of environment. If 
 as a result of certain actions a situation developed which, 
 in reviewing it, we dislike we should feel prompted to do 
 differently next time. This is the significance of all in- 
 terpretations of the past, the Marxian not excluded. 
 
 Marx chose three points in his contemplation of history 
 and made these his loadstar for speculations on the fu- 
 ture. They were first, a division of events into the eco- 
 nomic and non-economic, second, the establishment of a 
 causal relation between the two, and third the explanation 
 of misery as a maladjustment of past and present. Grant 
 these features, and the paramount importance of his at- 
 tempt must appear at once. History consists of records 
 of past events, and these were once the present. The 
 historian, then, treats of social processes as well as the 
 sociologist or economist, only he studies them as some- 
 thing old and completed. The historian speaks of com- 
 pleted series of events; the student of contemporary 
 events regards them as processes still under way. 
 
 A critique of the Marxian economic interpretation of 
 history will turn on the points made by Marx himself, but 
 
 58 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 59 
 
 it will also aim to restate, when necessary, those facts of 
 the social process which relate to the Marxian program 
 of reform. If socialism wishes to change the social order 
 it must acquaint dtself with the precise meaning of mal- 
 adjustment, of causal relation, and of the economic inter- 
 pretation of history in general. Only thus can it obtain 
 elements for a theory of prosperity which it seeks to for- 
 mulate; only thus can concepts of justice, democracy, and 
 progress assume definiteness. The limits as well as the 
 possibilities of socialism are given by the analysis of the 
 social process which the Marxian interpretation of history 
 involves. 
 
 Marx speaks of cause and effect. He held the economic 
 data responsible for the character of the superstructure. 
 There was no equivocation on that subject. He is very 
 plain in his statements. But what is cause and correla- 
 tion? If the economic and non-economic facts are re- 
 lated, of what sort is this correlation? And how do we 
 find such interrelations? The Marxian theorem compels 
 us to face these questions. It is a step in our general 
 appreciation of the socialistic platform to ascertain the 
 nature of cause and correlation. Correlation has to do 
 with the grouping of events that fill our life. Cause has 
 to do with classifying the events for future use. The 
 study of cause and effect turns on a selection of elements 
 in a situation with a view to forecasting future correla- 
 tions or to controlling them, if we dare and care. 
 
 2. The Problem of Correlation All our experi- 
 ence is of events happening in groups. We do not sense 
 things as units entirely segregated from other units any 
 more than we see individuals living as hermits, secluded 
 from the rest of the world. Events come in series, in suc- 
 cession or in coexistence. We see lightning and hear 
 thunder. We look out into the street and behold in- 
 
60 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM. 
 
 numerable facts related in various ways : the children play- 
 ing by groups, the traffic in a certain order, the array of 
 houses and the framing of it all in an environment of sky 
 and nature and conditions of the weather, in space and 
 in time. Everything thus appears to us as happening 
 either simultaneously or successively. In the former case, 
 as when I see a tree with its trunk and foliage, its color 
 and size, or the shape of its leaves, the logician speaks 
 of coexistence of facts. In the latter case, when for in- 
 stance the clouds gather before a storm, the streets next 
 begin to be pelted with big drops of rain, and eventually 
 a gust blows amid flashes from the sky, the logician speaks 
 of sequences. The events happen in a certain order in 
 time. 
 
 The problem of correlation, which leads up to the ques- 
 tion of causation, consists of two parts. The first is the 
 facts of remembrance of correlations, and the second is 
 the method of discovering new correlations which are not 
 obvious to the sense. The picture I get of the street is 
 one presented immediately to my eye. The correlations 
 are discovered by being seen. That is all. We learn in 
 this manner to adjust ourselves to the facts present. But 
 without memory the adjustment would be incomplete, since 
 instinctive reactions do not always answer. The differ- 
 ence between animal and man is largely the difference in 
 memory, though of course animals also remember things. 
 
 Our ability to remember is grounded in the facts of 
 metabolism and of a nervous mechanism which have been 
 disclosed chiefly during the nineteenth century. For the 
 psychologist the fundamental facts in consciousness are 
 sensation, selection, and memory. We have the principle 
 of sensing things, of being stimulated and responding, of 
 responding not to all stimuli, but only to some, and of 
 storing impressions so they may color future impressions. 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 61 
 
 This trio of principles forms the foundation on which 
 most facts of consciousness and behavior rest. But for 
 the purposes in hand it is more convenient to take sensa- 
 tion for granted, and to single out for special mention the 
 nature of association, before trying to understand cause 
 and effect. 
 
 We are stimulated from the outside, that is peripherally, 
 o*r from within, that is centrally. Anything calculated 
 to produce physico-chemical changes, no matter how 
 minute, in our body, represents a stimulus. We live in 
 the midst of such excitations, and we respond to them 
 often. One stimulus may produce several distinct reac- 
 tions, or one reaction may be the result of several stimuli. 
 This follows from the interlacing of the carriers of excita- 
 tion. 
 
 - The human body, in one aspect, is a vast network of 
 nerves, and the nervous mechanism is a system of conduc- 
 tion units by which stimuli are converted into more or less 
 complex responses. The unit is the neurone of which bil- 
 lions exist, and over which stimuli are transmitted to 
 reach the proper centers and connections that ensure 
 suitable reaction. The end of life is action ; the purpose 
 of the neurone is the conduction of stimuli for right reac- 
 tion. In a reflex action the stimulus is carried over a 
 simple arc connecting receptor with motor organ. The 
 twitch of a muscle is a case in hand. But the great ma- 
 jority of reactions are established more circuitously, by 
 means of switchings of excitation, of redirection in the 
 spine and in the cortex, so that highly elaborated series of 
 movements, of ideas and feelings become possible. 
 
 And this is particularly made possible by the capacity 
 of the organism to remember. Man remembers experi- 
 ences. His nervous mechanism is said to respond in the 
 sense that it carries stimuli, and carries them the more 
 
62 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 readily the oftener they come, though other principles 
 also decide. Physiologically the explanation is a lessen- 
 ing of resistance to the current that travels over the neu- 
 rones. It is inconsequential whether we imagine the trans- 
 mission as one akin to the burning of a fuse leading to 
 discharge and detonation, or whether the transmission 
 partakes of the nature of an electric current. But it is 
 important to note the effect of repetition upon the nerve 
 cells. The places at which the neurones connect the 
 synapses yield more readily to a second or third than 
 to a first excitation, other things being equal. It is like 
 folding a garment. Gradually a crease is made, and sub- 
 sequent folding is easy; it follows the old crease. Thus 
 paths are made from continual walking in the same line. 
 Thus rivers dig their channel through solid rock. And 
 similarly the excitation of the optical nerve survives the 
 stimulus itself. After-images are somewhat like memory. 
 The effect outlasts the cause. 
 
 We learn by remembering, that is by reducing the re- 
 sistance originally offered to stimuli and to their passages. 
 Either we are naturally predisposed toward the accept- 
 ance of a stimulus, or we acquire the ability to receive and 
 transmit it. " Learning," in the words of a psychologist, 
 " is a process of making easier the passage of an impulse 
 from neurone to neurone." 1 The function of education 
 is to control the stimuli reaching us, at the beginning of 
 life, from the outside, and later from within also. It is 
 to cull out the bad, to strengthen the desirable, and to 
 redirect them so as to effectuate the best possible adjust- 
 ments, that we receive instruction. 
 
 The outward proof of memorizing, of lessening the re- 
 sistance to impulses and their transmission, is the forming 
 
 iPillsbury, W. B., "Essentials of Psychology." Revised Edition, 
 p. 55. 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 63 
 
 of habits. Habituation is one of the most fruitful of all 
 capacities. It is the most common of traits. ': We all be- 
 come addicted to things ; we all learn to react habitually. 
 We learn, in short, to do things without paying attention, 
 without noticeable effort, without being conscious of the 
 act of doing. Thus with walking, eating, dressing, play- 
 ing an instrument, etc., etc. Habituation means a sense 
 of comfort because of the ease with which things are done 
 and reacted to. It is not merely a question of motor re- 
 actions, however ; a response in belief and ideals is equally 
 in point. What we are used to we commonly like and 
 prefer to strange things. The strange is usually distaste- 
 ful to us, unless some features in it, reminding us of 
 features in familiar things, break down our instinctive or 
 acquired aversion. 
 
 The effect of frequent repetition is therefore an atti- 
 tude of expectancy. We are keyed up to anticipate 
 events, and to react suitably. Experience permits us thus 
 to save time and energy. Habituation means looking for- 
 ward to events because they happened in the past. If 
 they suddenly cease to happen, we feel disappointed or 
 queer. Nothing jars like habits broken off at short no- 
 tice, like regularities ending of a sudden. The converse 
 to this jarring of unforeseen interruption upon our nerves, 
 upon our consciousness, is our disposition to believe the 
 familiar things, and to believe that they will occur again. 
 So many successions of day and night, for instance, have 
 occurred in our individual lives, that the non-recurrence 
 is thought impossible. It is only when other experiences 
 directly, or by a process of reasoning soon to be discussed, 
 induce us to consider the possibility of a non-recurrence 
 that we fail to believe in its necessity. Thus with the 
 repeated appearance of a certain number in the throw of 
 the dice. Here contrary experiences tend to weaken our 
 
64 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 attitude of expectation. But in general repetition means 
 anticipation, or as the logician has put it : We infer things 
 by way of enumeration. We number events and then 
 cherish beliefs accordingly. If winter has always, or so 
 many times, brought snow and ice, we expect more ice 
 and snow the next winter. We learn to induce future oc- 
 currences from the past. 
 
 This is the first important circumstance in a study of 
 our inference and correlation. The second is selection 
 and attention. 
 
 Not all things are noticed and remembered. Our en- 
 vironment consists really only of the facts we react upon. 
 We sense things according to definite principles and ig- 
 nore more or less fulty everything else. Or we see things, 
 but do not pay particular attention to them, that is we 
 do not make them the center of things, we do not focus our 
 mental eye upon them to the exclusion of much else. Only 
 for particular purposes do we single out events for pro- 
 longed study. Only because the reaction to stimuli serves 
 to protect and develop our interests do we select our 
 stimuli. Selection is a necessary corollary to spec- 
 ialization of means and ends in species, each specie hav- 
 , ing its own characteristics of needs and habits. 
 
 Our selection of possible stimuli is governed by objective 
 and subjective conditions. The intensity of the stimulus 
 is an example of the first kind ; the facts of training, of 
 the second. According to our general schooling and ex- 
 perience, according to purposes at the moment when the 
 stimulus is present, according to immediately preceding 
 sensations, to predispositions inherited, or to pressure 
 brought to bear upon us by our fellowmen, we notice or 
 ignore things, treat them indifferently or make them the 
 special subject of our investigation. We shut out most 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 65 
 
 elements in a given situation from our vision. This is 
 true not only in an optical sense, but likewise of our 
 method of learning. 
 
 From the general law of selection follows our habit of 
 comparing things. Our system becomes attuned to simi- 
 lar stimuli in different ensembles of facts, or to different 
 stimuli in like ensemble of factsAxJLt is essential to the 
 maintenance of life to discriminate and to compare. 
 From infancy on we classify stimuli and develop our re- 
 sponses specifically. Classification may not be conspicu- 
 ously carried on ; no more than motor reactions always de- 
 pend on concentration of effort. But comparison and 
 grouping of data are daily practices without which the en- 
 vironment could not be mastered. We remember to se- 
 lect and compare, and we also select our stimuli in order 
 to learn the right reactions. 
 
 But note that as a result of this eternal process of at- 
 tention a group of events never really embraces all of the 
 factors in the group. In a thunder storm, e. g., I see 
 many things, but not nearly all. I select only as my in- 
 stincts command, or as experiences seem to justify. In- 
 numerable elements in the situation called a thunderstorm 
 remain unobserved by me. I may at a later date see more 
 of them, or I may have reasons for looking for more. Or 
 I may have seen a greater number at an earlier date, but 
 forgotten. All this varies and depends on the principles 
 of selection and remembering already referred to. In this 
 survey the only notable fact is the variable number of 
 facts constituting a complete situation what we call 
 the correlation regularly recurring, such as the aforesaid 
 thunderstorm. We seem to have the complete situation, 
 but do not, as later experiences may prove. For practi- 
 cal ends at a given moment the correlation may be per- 
 
66 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 *C"~ 
 
 feet, but it does not remain so. Our perception, in short, 
 is of selected materials in a structure.^/ We perceive sali- 
 ent features, what to us seems essential according to par- 
 ticular, perhaps practical, ends, but this subjective pic- 
 ture may not correspond to reality, or what at another 
 time seems reality. Percepts are always abstractions. 
 
 But before fully understanding the percept the prin- 
 ciple of association must be invoked. It is through as- 
 sociations that we greatly enrich our power of reactions 
 and facilitate our search for new truths. 
 
 The theory of association may be stated as the belief 
 everywhere held, and by science duly recognized as a fact, 
 that our ideas are governed by the past. Connections of 
 the past govern the reproduction of ideas. To have per- 
 ceived means not only to recognize by force of memory, 
 but also to see anew in the light of experiences not per- 
 haps directly connected with the prototype of the par- 
 ticular new experience. If for instance I have seen the 
 striking of a match to lead to ignition I may remember 
 this, and the motions involved in the act of striking will 
 become the easier the oftener I repeat the performance. 
 This is simply a case of memory. But the effect of asso- 
 ciation is the recall of events not happening at the time of 
 recall. To see a match struck, for instance, and to recall 
 the sound it usually makes, without hearing it at the time, 
 that is memorizing by association. 
 
 The physiological aspect of this important fact lies in 
 the intertwining of nerve paths, and in the existence of 
 association areas in the cortex, whose function is primarily 
 the connecting of different sensations, or of movements 
 with sensations for adjustment to the largest possible 
 number of stimuli. To quote from an authority : " When 
 a group of neurones was active at the time of the original 
 experience, paths of connection were formed, synapses 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 67 
 
 were opened between them, and later, when any element of 
 the complex is aroused in any way, the impulse tends to 
 spread over the partially open synapses to the other ele- 
 ments of the whole." 2 That is to say, we may imagine 
 different nerve paths to have part of their course in com- 
 mon. They converge and part again. Excitations from 
 different sources travel partly over the same path, and at 
 the points of contiguity of the neurones they are connected 
 so that one stimulus may arouse others, and lead to a long 
 series of reactions. The stimuli may be aroused peripher- 
 ally or centrally. Ideas are for the purpose of the psy- 
 chologist as truly sensations as those generated by out- 
 side facts. 
 
 The principles of association are those first suggested 
 by the Greeks, namely of association by resemblance, con- 
 trast, contiguity or continuity. But evidently this is a 
 mere classification, not an explanation of the process. 
 Nor are the four truly distinct, since resemblance and con- 
 trast imply comparisons in space and time, which prob- 
 ably account for all rearousals. And again, as our writer 
 admits, the association is more truly one of neurones than 
 of ideas, the association not following strictly the prin- 
 ciples laid down by the ancients. Thus " not only must 
 we limit the application of the doctrine of associations by 
 the assertion that it is the neurones at the basis of the 
 elements of ideas that are associated rather than the ideas 
 themselves, but we must also recognize that associations 
 give only the possibility of recall, and that selection must 
 be made between the possibilities by more remote fac- 
 tors." 3 We do not associate all things seen together in 
 space or time. Inhibitions come naturally, and are spec- 
 ially cultivated by education. Thus attention becomes 
 
 2Pillsbury, W. B., "Fundamentals of Psychology," p. 223. 
 3 Ibidem, p. 227. 
 
68 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 fruitful, and adjustment rapid and exact. In other 
 words, the selective forces affect association as well as 
 memory itself. 
 
 Yet the fundamental fact is as stated. We are again 
 and again led to recall the past by stimuli in the present 
 somehow related to stimuli in an earlier situation. The 
 principle reminds one of the Lamarckian contention ac- 
 cording to which acquired traits are inherited. The son, 
 it is said, will act somewhat as the environment made the 
 father act, even though the son lives in a different en- 
 vironment. It is again a case of memory and habitua- 
 tion, but this time by indirect stimulation. Recall in this 
 manner enlarges our capacity for learning. " Learning," 
 we are told, " is always the formation of connections be- 
 tween neurones ; retention is always the persistence of the 
 connection, or the partial openness of synapses which per- 
 mits an impression to pass from one to the other of the 
 connected elements : recall is the rearousal of the whole 
 complex by some one of the elements that may be stimu- 
 lated from the outside world, directly or indirectly." 4 
 A part suffices to arouse the whole; that is the main 
 characteristic of association. 
 
 A distinction should, however, be made between recall of 
 events regularly correlated, and a recall of events which 
 only in part recur regularly. If, to return to the illustra- 
 tion of the match, I expect ignition at the striking of a 
 match because it has always resulted in ignition, this is 
 direct association of events invariably coupled. They 
 belong together as integral parts of a series, and have so 
 been classified. But if, on hearing a melody, I am re- 
 minded of childhood scenes, and then perhaps of a long 
 chain of happenings covering many years, relating to 
 places and persons nowhere before me now while I hear 
 
 * Ibidem, p. 225. 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 69 
 
 the melody, then the association is indirect, of things not 
 regularly recurring or correlated. The only binding link 
 is perchance a single quality of tone, or a mistake made in 
 playing the instrument, or a peculiar way of ending the 
 performance, and so on. A few elements are sufficient to 
 reconstruct all the elements, or at least a great many ele- 
 ments, in the older situation. The one thing held in com- 
 mon by the old and tho new series of events is responsible 
 for the recall of all the rest in the old series. Thus ideas 
 skip and travel at an amazing rate. Thus in the twinkle 
 of an eye one may traverse the universe and rehearse a 
 lifetime of struggles. Indirect association is the import- 
 ant principle for the extension of our knowledge, and for 
 the understanding of trifles in our daily conduct. It is 
 the transfer of ideas that counts, more than the recol- 
 lection of events experienced together regularly. Or, to 
 put it differently, the association by resemblance (or con- 
 trast) is far more important than association by con- 
 tiguity and succession. The latter helps to explain ex- 
 pectation and beliefs, but the former is instrumental in 
 multiplying the data for belief. 
 
 Just what elements in the new sensations guide my con- 
 catenation of thoughts, and in what direction it ultimately 
 leads me, depends, as already remarked, to some extent 
 upon the general laws of selection. I am sure to be in- 
 fluenced by previous associations, by moods of the moment, 
 by ideas uppermost in my mind, by facts of temperament 
 and of training. They all determine the scope and nature 
 of my transfer of ideas, they all influence us in our search 
 for new facts. 
 
 The principles of finding a new correlation connect with 
 this circumstance. If the correlation is not one directly 
 submitted to my senses, such as the sequence of work and 
 fatigue, or the coexistence of flame and heat, special ef- 
 
70 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 forts must be made to find it. This is our task from birth 
 to death. We continually look for new groups of events, 
 see them repeat themselves, and add one correlation to the 
 next by virtue of memory and selection. 
 
 One way of ascertaining new correlations is to try out 
 alternatives. If, for instance, I cannot open a door which 
 I have opened often and expect to be able to open by the 
 usual method, I will be puzzled for a while and then look 
 for the cause. That is, since just now we are not in- 
 terested in cause per se I will try to get the complete 
 set of facts connected with the impossibility of opening 
 the door. I may try to lift it by the knob, or press it 
 downward or push it toward me or from me, or shake it, 
 or look for obstructions on either side if I can do so. I 
 go on the supposition that many elements go into the 
 situation which is new to me, and that I may hit upon 
 some elements essential to its not opening, just as I had 
 known some elements to be essential to its opening. I 
 may come upon the factors and remember them. 
 
 Or suppose I have a watch which keeps good time in 
 one place, but loses time in another. If I feel so inclined 
 I may ascertain the pertinent facts at random. Let us 
 assume, at any rate, that I am guided by no prior experi- 
 ence of any kind, an abstraction permissible for the pur- 
 pose. I then might use my developed powers of selection 
 and attention. I begin to compare two different situ- 
 ations and to classify events according to resemblance and 
 difference. I say, here is my habit of wearing the watch, 
 the way it lies in my pocket, the way and time in and at 
 which I wind it up, the facts about the watch itself, my 
 way of walking and using it when consulting the dial. 
 And so on. I may enumerate and put in two columns the 
 facts I hold alike and those peculiar to each situation. It 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 71 
 
 is likely that I find many similarities and some differences. 
 
 The whole procedure so far is that made famous by 
 Mill's canons of induction. I compare and tabulate re- 
 sults. Mill pointed out that where all things except one 
 are held in common by two or more different situations 
 the one differential assumes unusual significance. But let 
 us note simply that at last I have found some differences 
 which I think sufficient to round out the new situation in 
 which the watch does not keep time. I may now take the 
 watch several times from one place to the other and note 
 that each time in place A it runs accurately, and in place 
 B it falls behind. If I repeat this often enough, what will 
 be the effect on my opinion about the watch? I shall 
 simply come to believe that in the future also the watch 
 will fail me in one situation, but respond well in the other. 
 The force of repetition will set in as usual. On the prin- 
 ciple of induction by enumeration I shall develop a belief 
 that past correlations will recur. I shall speak of a law, 
 for the watch, of keeping time and losing time respectively 
 in two different places. Laws are nothing but such regu- 
 lar recurrences of sequences and coexistences, as logicians 
 found out centuries ago. 
 
 Very well. But it is not likely that I shall experiment in 
 that fashion. Scientists particularly do not ascertain 
 new correlations, that elude the five senses, in such a hap- 
 hazard manner. They proceed with some eye to economy. 
 They select the facts to be watched, and shape before- 
 hand their plans. How, then, are thinkers as a rule 
 guided? What is the modus operandi in reasoning? 
 What is the approved and common method of inference? 
 
 It is reasoning ~by analogy. It is by resort to mem- 
 ory and association. Instead of dwelling long on deduc- 
 tion and canons of induction Mill, as modern psychology 
 
72 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 sees it, might have better put analogies in the foreground 
 of his discussion. Inference by analogy is the rule rather 
 than the exception. And not only that, it also marks the 
 nature and limits of most of our knowledge. 
 
 In the case of my watch, then, I shall do as I did when 
 trying to open the door. I shall proceed by hypotheca- 
 tion in accord with the dictates of association and mem- 
 ory. I tried to open the door by lifting or downward 
 pressing at the knob, because I knew that wood swelled, 
 and that this might make the opening difficult. Only 
 after these expedients failed would I normally look for 
 other faults, or for some one on the other side holding the 
 door, or for its being locked contrary to orders. 
 
 As to the watch, I cast about for explanations also. 
 That is, I cast about for groups of events which in their 
 entirety would give the experienced result. I am influ- 
 enced by the principle of association. I look for a factor 
 which other situations share with the new one. Or rather, 
 one or more elements in the new situation remind me of 
 other situations containing many more than the particu- 
 lar factors. I am led to make comparison in a certain 
 direction. Guided by knowledge, we say. Yes, guided 
 by knowledge, or by a fund of associations, which is much 
 the same thing. Instead of finding the differentials there- 
 fore by piecemeal classification and enumeration I resort 
 to a circuitous method. I do in reasoning what the en- 
 terpriser does when he substitutes machinery for manual 
 work. I take indirect routes which at first have cost 
 much effort and time, but by their aid I can now achieve 
 results more expeditiously. 
 
 I am willing to look for differences and resemblances by 
 comparing a former situation with the present, because in 
 the past such partial resemblances have meant resemblance 
 m toto. Association directs me; but it does not affect 
 
INTEPBETATION OF HISTORY 73 
 
 us all equally. Association leads to observation of like- 
 nesses and unlikenesses. A few of them are quickly noted 
 and kept in mind. And now I fall back again on the prin- 
 ciple of enumeration. Since up to date situations have 
 proven alike in all parts when only some of them were for- 
 merly observed to be alike, and since I have witnessed long 
 chains of happenings to recur exactly as I predicted after 
 having found some of the happenings similar to some no- 
 ticed at other times, I infer a like aggregate result for 
 similar future chains of happenings. And furthermore, 
 the fact that part resemblances often mean complete re- 
 semblance, and that a recurrence of a former entire series 
 is the likelier the more nearly its beginning events resemble 
 those of an older correlation, also induces me to compare 
 the nature of the resemblance. 
 
 But my faith is reenforced from still another quarter. 
 Namely, it is a common observation that the distribu- 
 tion of events is either regular or irregular. If regular I 
 attribute it to a law of nature which comprises the regu- 
 larities just discussed correlations which form the bulk 
 of scientific knowledge. Or I attribute it to human inter- 
 ference and design. Man always places himself in the 
 middle of a situation. He feels himself to be the planner 
 and architect of his fortunes. When he acts, the results 
 of regularity are of his making and hence, he avers, ex- 
 plained. But when neither a natural law nor the hand of 
 man can be predicated as part of the regularity of events 
 their distribution is felt to be a chance event. An ir- 
 regularity is expected. We see irregularity where we do 
 not refer one group of facts to another group, just as we 
 ascribe to chance what is really an unknown principle 
 about which perhaps we care nothing. 
 
 Probability then is a forecast based on retrospects. 
 The chance of regularity is the greater the more definite 
 
74 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 our comprehension of laws or of human design back of it. 
 And my belief that a whole series of events will recur 
 when some of them have in the past proven to be part of 
 a particular larger series, is the stronger the greater the 
 number of events common to both situations. The more 
 resemblances pile up, and the oftener they recur, the more 
 convinced I am that the entire series is of the old sort ; 
 and I am willing to predict accordingly. This is the 
 reason for my inferring things by analogy. In this man- 
 ner I am led to discover the new correlation centering 
 about my watch when it loses time. Thuswise the prin- 
 ciples of association, selection, and memory collaborate to 
 help me discover new truths. 
 
 Reasoning by analogy indeed becomes so habitual that 
 often we are unaware of using it. Thus recognition of 
 things may be regarded as much as an act of inference as 
 of mere perception. A physician, for instance, may not 
 diagnose a case by exhaustive, systematic enumeration of 
 symptoms as observed in the study of my watch. As- 
 sociation may be direct and suggest at once the nature of 
 the disease. He sees certain events or characteristics, is 
 reminded of similar ones connecting with a malady called 
 scarlet fever, and at once pronounces the new case to be 
 one of scarlet fever. The tendency to recognize things as 
 alike is always strong, when some one element of similarity 
 exists. And the fact that a disease is in question 
 strengthens the inclination to infer from analogy. But 
 of course, this first recognition may soon be superseded by 
 cautious study. If contradictory evidence presents itself 
 new lines of associations and of reasoning will be opened. 
 
 If I see some objects on a table, looking round and red- 
 dish, of a certain texture and size or shape, I will imme- 
 diately call them apples, and all of them apples, without 
 having compared them carefully with another object 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 75 
 
 known to be an apple, or even without rehearsing my own 
 experiences with like objects. Recognition, that is " the 
 reference of an event or object to some earlier time and 
 place," 5 satisfies the needs of the case. Thus also, if a 
 boy should be run over by a vehicle, or somebody fall down 
 the stairway and appear to be seriously injured. I have 
 seen no details, but infer so quickly by association that 
 the recognition is almost a single act. I believe the entire 
 situation to be such and such because part of it resembles 
 an earlier one of a certain kind. In brief, my perception 
 is a partial summary of events which are rearoused by new 
 events. 
 
 The percept is a compound much as water is one. The 
 joint result of individual actions is no mere summation, 
 but a new product. Perception is more than association 
 if that is to mean a stringing together of sensations, as 
 we might thread pearls. The Herbartian doctrine of ap- 
 perception was a great step in advance precisely because 
 it realized this characteristic Q perception and freed us 
 from the older mechanistic notion./ 
 
 "Percepts," according to'^one psychologist, "are se- 
 lected groups of sensations in which images are incor- 
 porated as an integral part of the whole process." 6 In 
 the words of another competent authority, quoted several 
 times before, " the world that we have in memory or in 
 reason is not the sum of particular experiences; it is al- 
 ways the mass of particular experiences worked over, and 
 crystallized about standards." 7 " What is perceived is 
 not merely a mass of sensations nor is it a single sensation 
 that suggests some other single sensation or group of sen- 
 sations ; rather is it a type, an organized product of many 
 
 s Ibidem, p. 366. 
 
 Titchener, E. B., "Textbook of Psychology," p. 367. 
 
 7 Pillsbury, W. B., " Psychology of Reasoning," p. 76. 
 
76 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 experiences which have finally given rise to a construct 
 consistent with all of our different related experiences." 8 
 The percept, then, is the result of many correlations not 
 having all events in common, but many of them. Percepts 
 are averages, so to say. Roughly speaking they describe 
 situations, but each new situation will have its own pecu- 
 liarities, and each new act of sensing will reckon with the 
 differences. 
 
 I perceive what is important, and I sense what is con- 
 spicuous. A picture is an abstract for that reason. It 
 has meaning because I see only part of the lines and planes 
 in it, and not all, and because I see them in certain rela- 
 tions of space to each other. My perspective is spoiled 
 when I step too close. The picture goes and a tangle of 
 lines and dots is left, but it conveys no idea. It only ir- 
 ritates me. Thus everything perceived is a cluster of ele- 
 ments many of which recur over and over again, in ap- 
 proximately the same juxtaposition of time and space. 
 But the fact that percepts are only approximations is of 
 great importance to our analysis of correlation and cause, 
 for by virtue of it science becomes fallible and plastic, 
 subject to correlation and growth, an estimate rather than 
 a set of laws immutable for all times. 
 
 It is not necessary to preach phenomenalism in order 
 to agree to the relativity of scientific truths. Nor will all 
 assent to William James' dictum that pragmatists are 
 necessarily realists. The core of the epistemological 
 problem is the fact of reasoning, which is based on data 
 of psychology. The Beyond need not detain us, espec- 
 ially since all philosophies of the absolute have broken 
 down by assuming part of what they sought to demon- 
 strate independently. 
 
 sPillsbury, W. B., "Fundamentals of Psychology," pp. 395-96. 
 See also the same writer's " Psychology of Reasoning," pp. 90 & 97. 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 77 
 
 But there is no doubt that inference by analogy ac- 
 counts for most of our beliefs and of our knowledge even 
 such as is verified in an objective sense. The thought of 
 chance distribution and of probability is doubtless a prod- 
 uct of such reasoning. The explanation here offered of 
 the method for discovering new correlations is itself an 
 instance of inference from analogy. And mathematics 
 and history are almost entirely limited to such procedure, 
 the latter admitting it frankly, while the latter was long 
 held to work with instruments infallible and inscrutable. 
 Historians reason by reference to occurrences in their own 
 environment, or by deductions from human nature, that 
 is by analogy. The great bulk of verities that the social 
 student and ethicists of the old type gave to the world 
 were unprovable. They were true in so far as they ac- 
 corded with the principles of thinking just mentioned. 
 Put otherwise: They were and always will be true in so 
 far as modes of thinking among men are the same, due to 
 millions of years of environments shared in common by our 
 ancestors. Evolution has made us in some things alike, 
 and our reasoning process is part of this universal hu- 
 man nature, though our funds of knowledge and of as- 
 sociations, and hence the trend and power of our reason- 
 i/ng vary enormously. Sociological events are scattered in 
 time and place. Besides, they are non-reproducible in 
 their entirety. We express this by admitting that an in- 
 determinate number of factors enter into a given situa- 
 tion, whose control is ordinarily beyond us. In this sense 
 most sociological events cannot be " proven." Yet we 
 can measure by averages and rejoice in the recurrence of 
 averages approximately and for limited period of time 
 or areas or groups of people. Insurance rates thus be- 
 come possible, though rates will change with conditions. 
 Mortality figures thus assume much definiteness. and are 
 
78 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 deemed reliable, though they change in time and place. 
 Averages, for that matter, prevail everywhere, both in 
 natural and social science. 
 
 Is there no proof, then? Or better: What is proof? 
 When is something absolutely true? The question is 
 natural because deduction is supposed to furnish irrefut- 
 able proofs such as should satisfy the most ambitious of 
 metaphysicians. 
 
 We may answer yes or no according to the nature of 
 facts in question, and according to our notion of truth. 
 Proof namely is in the eating of the pudding, which means 
 that all so-called verification (" making true ") is by ap- 
 peal to the senses. But in as much as the senses differ we 
 cannot believe that all things are true in exactly the same 
 way to all people. We can only say that some elements 
 in a situation will be perceived by all in like manner, and 
 that this rough correspondence is equivalent to proof. A 
 proposition is proven when demonstrated to the eye or ear 
 or taste, etc. It is proven true when it " works well," 
 when the application of science, e. g., brings desired re- 
 sults. This does not mean that truth depends on appli- 
 cation, or science on commercialization. No, it means 
 simply that some judgments are true to all in so far as 
 our sensing or perceptions veer about types common to 
 us all. 
 
 But where objective verification is impossible, as in the 
 case with most of the verdicts of social science, there be- 
 lief of experts is tantamount to proof. The general run 
 of people will accept expert advice as truth because they 
 are swayed naturally by superiority or by the socialized 
 agents of control. . And if both verification and expert- 
 ness are lacking, then the opinion of the majority becomes 
 the standard. Mere number wins in many cases. For 
 want of better evidence we go to the multitude. Thus 
 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 79 
 
 public opinion becomes truth, and thus our ideals seem to 
 us indisputable truths. We have arrived at them by much 
 the same methods of reasoning that the scientist uses. 
 The ways of common sense are the ways of science. 
 
 The chief difference between the layman and the scien- 
 tist is therefore not one of methods, but one of instru- 
 ments and results. Science has inestimable advantages 
 in control, measurement, and associations. It may iso- 
 late phenomena, select its facts carefully and place them 
 in surroundings that make observation of details possible 
 and easy. It uses artificial means of reproducing events 
 so as to be able to know exactly what is going on. This 
 power of rehearsing the course of events in a given correla- 
 tion leads to the establishment of new correlations by 
 elimination and introduction of factors chosen for special 
 purposes. A plan of action characterizes the investiga- 
 tions of the professional which the tyro rarely knows of. 
 
 And besides, there are means of measurement vastly su- 
 perior to the ordinary. An indirect method is here the 
 chief advantage. Differences in weight and length, in 
 force and volume that could not be detected by the naked 
 eye become marked as soon as special devices are called 
 into service. The micrometer and the seismograph, the 
 stop-watch and galvanometer, or the vacuum-balance are 
 invaluable aids in minute differentiations that may lead to 
 a new conception of the situation studied. 
 
 The fund of associations grows steadily ; partly be- 
 cause records are filed for future reference so that the 
 memory of science is made more reliable than that of the 
 average individual, and partly because incessant spec- 
 ialized study enlarges the fund of known facts that will 
 serve to stimulate further inference. From the known to 
 the unknown is always the course in learning, but it has 
 special significance for the trained investigator who de- 
 
80 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 liberately sets himself problems remote from everyday ex- 
 periences. A large fund of associations is indispensable in 
 his undertaking. The greater the number of correla- 
 tions, the larger is the choice of resemblances and differ- 
 ences, and consequently the less liable to error the reason- 
 ing from analogy. Verification may or may not be de- 
 finitive, but the subsumption of a new particular under 
 an old generality is facilitated by the increase of facts as 
 such. 
 
 ' People frequently are called illogical when they are only 
 ignorant. They are incapable of reasoning on a certain 
 subject because their fund of associations is too small. 
 They may do better somewhere else. They may also lack 
 the kind of memory type that aids in specialized pursuits 
 of knowledge. It is well known that not all are equally 
 adepts in the same field. We differ, but need not be 
 dunces because we fail in one direction. According to our 
 powers of visualization our associations may promote in- 
 ventiveness or stifle it. Some are the prey of their as- 
 sociations which make them roam aimlessly without focus- 
 ing on a point. Others gain by their memory and culti- 
 vate a habit of thought, of fruitful thinking. This is 
 really possible, though not often practiced. 
 
 Sciences also grow. Sciences shift their boundary lines 
 and the centers of emphasis which from period to period 
 characterize their inquiries. They start out with well de- 
 fined lines for subject matter and scope, but eventually 
 feel less sure about the divisions. Chemistry and physics 
 thus have points in common, where workers meet and find 
 problems overlapping. Biology is no longer considered 
 to be worlds apart from psychology, and the social sci- 
 ences have always been at odds over the precise demar- 
 cation of their borders. 
 
 The correlations grow, and the factors in each correla- 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 81 
 
 tion increase. The tendency is commonly toward further 
 reduction of apparent irreducibles. We are driven from 
 one ultimate to another. We divide more minutely and 
 distinguish things by finer lines. Physics for instance 
 adds the corpuscle to the atom and makes gravity a func- 
 tion of motion. Chemistry no longer reckons with atoms 
 and molecules merely. It recognizes in addition isomer- 
 ism, and wonders about the relation of the elements, the 
 transmutation of matter being an observed fact. New 
 elements in a narrow sense, and new constituents of a cor- 
 relation in a wider sense have crept into the chemist's 
 range of vision. 
 
 What was once held to be the make-up of a good soil 
 now seems like an inadequate analysis. We consider much 
 more than the ratio in which chemical elements are com- 
 bined, and the ratio in which such compounds appear in 
 the soil. We figure on many other things before pro- 
 nouncing on the worth of it. Similarly the biologist has 
 gone from one reduction to another. The cell has 
 ceased to be a homogeneous unit. We now regard it as a 
 highly elaborate mechanism for bodily functions or for 
 reproduction. We have gone from plasm to nucleus, and 
 from nucleus to, say, chromatin, and from that to chro- 
 mosomes, and thence to determinants in the chromosomes 
 which we think are the bearers of heredity. An indeter- 
 minate number of factors is said to be lodged in the chro- 
 mosomes, the combination and placements of which vary, 
 and lead to varying results in the individual. Psychology 
 no longer speaks of " faculties," as if they were entities 
 functioning in separate compartments. Consciousness is 
 too complex a thing for that. The percept is recognized 
 as a joint effect of innumerable sensations present di- 
 rectly or by recall. It is like a mosaic that for all its 
 variegation and numberless bits presents a unified whole, 
 
82 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 an agreeable picture and a plan adaptable to definite ends. 
 
 And so with most sciences. The substitution by the 
 economist of the law of the proportionality of factors for 
 the Ricardian notion of diminishing returns is a further 
 instance of growth in factors and correlations. There 
 is no need for expatiating on a familiar fact. Every- 
 where the sense of simplicity in correlations is lost. We 
 see a greater number of elements, a larger number of 
 variables whose measurement becomes increasingly diffi- 
 cult. The impression of preciseness and absolute regu- 
 larity is lost in proportion as we see and know more. 
 Science is not as cocksure and dogmatic as it used to be. 
 " The progress of science," as one philosopher puts it, 
 " is a proces-s of successive approximations, in which new 
 and more precise, more probable and more extended in- 
 ductions result from partially verified deductions, and 
 from those contradictions that correct the implicit hy- 
 potheses." 9 
 
 That is the true state of affairs. Science approximates 
 and revises. It must periodically face discrepancies and 
 contradictions. Doubt alternates with belief. Doubt is 
 a feeling resulting from a conflict of ideas, of associations. 
 Any one who has tried to solve a problem in the abstract, 
 or to overcome an unexpected practical obstacle, knows 
 what misery accompanies a clash of trains of reasoning, 
 each good in itself, but in discord with others. When 
 such memory associations come to blows, as it were, the 
 mind suffers as a whole. It means misery and sleepless 
 nights, perhaps loss of appetite and incapacity for routine 
 actions. Doubt is the opposite of belief which is the fruit 
 of habituations developed at leisure. 
 
 Science, then, has limitations which bear on all matters 
 of study and are of significance even for the socialist who 
 Enriques, F., " Problems of Science," p. 166. 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 83 
 
 would reform the world. Science is not the simple de- 
 vice for ascertaining irrefutable truths that socialism has 
 often pictured it to be. It is a case of change in venue. 
 Laws are mutable, though of many things we all 
 obtain like impressions. Mill's canons erred in promising 
 science more than it has accomplished. In particular is 
 the Canon of Difference no more infallible than any of 
 the others, for the missing link or cause may be much 
 more than a single agent. Its reduction may be impend- 
 ing. 
 
 What we are sure of, so far as modern psychological 
 evidence is concerned, is the existence of one method of 
 reasoning employed by all sciences. The number of sci- 
 ences may be increased indefinitely according to our con- 
 ception of correlations of events, but they all resort to the 
 same mode of discovery and of generalization. Deduc- 
 tion and induction, for the same reason, are not two dis- 
 tinct methods, but two aspects of one single process of 
 reasoning. In the syllogism the conclusion follows from 
 the premises because we have always known a part of a 
 thing to be smaller than the whole. This axiom decides 
 in the end. But the rules of distribution result from the 
 principles of association that are used in collocating two 
 premises so as to make their bearing upon the conclusion 
 plain. Induction underlies the construction of the syllo- 
 gism, though after the premises are laid down a purely 
 deductive act takes place. But it remains true, as was 
 stated over a century ago, that the syllogism in itself can- 
 not extend knowledge, because it assumes what at the mo- 
 ment is not verified or perhaps cannot be verified. 
 
 3. The Meaning of Causation These things being 
 so the meaning of cause and effect also becomes clear. In 
 the words of J. S. Mill : Cause is " The sum total of con- 
 ditions, positive and negative, taken together; the whole 
 
84 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 of the contingencies of every description, which being 
 realized the consequent invariably follows." 10 And to 
 quote from two later writers : " There is no particular 
 difference between knowledge of causes, and our general 
 knowledge of the combinations, or succession of combina- 
 tions, in which the phenomena of nature are presented to 
 us, or found to occur in experimental inquiry." J1 
 " Things are not either independent, or causative. All 
 classes of phenomena are linked together, and the prob- 
 lem in each case is how close is the degree of association." 12 
 
 That is to say, every factor in a given situation no 
 matter how far we may go in our choice of factors, is 
 either cause or effect according to viewpoint and need. 
 Objectively they function in this respect all in the same 
 way, but our subjective choice leads to the designation of 
 some 'particular facts as causes. All sequences and co- 
 existences consist necessarily of causal relations, no matter 
 how obscure. Even the random arrangement of furniture 
 in a room represents cause and effect if one wishes to 
 speak accurately. Any set of facts is cause and effect, of 
 which some facts become causes in a narrow sense. 
 
 We select particulars on the principle of attention al- 
 ready discussed. Stimuli interest us in different ways. 
 We react not in like ways to things. Our life is a process 
 of adjustmet to physical and economic environment, such 
 that some elements in a situation will seem vital while 
 others are negligible. Causation is a selective act. To 
 ascribe cause to something is to give it a special value for 
 particular purposes. For instance, to say that cold 
 freezes water into ice is a way of calling attention to a 
 
 10 Mill, J. S., "Logic," Book III, Chapter 5, No. 3. Similarly 
 also Venn, J., in his " Empirical Logic," p. 67. 
 
 11 Jevons, W. S., " Principles of Science," Book II, Chapter 1. 
 
 12 Pearson, K., "Grammar of Science," Edit. 1911, Volume 1, p. 
 166. See also p. 177. 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 85 
 
 factor influencing our behavior at the time. Many things 
 go into the situation : The location of water, the atmos- 
 pheric conditions, the qualities of matter in general and 
 of water in particular, such as expansion, weight, trans- 
 lucency, etc., etc. But one group in the ensemble known 
 as cold gets the credit or blame for the entire complex. 
 Except by reference to will and will-to-live our designa- 
 tion of cause and effect must appear quite arbitrary. 
 
 Nietzsche, the German prophet of a revaluation of 
 values, remarks in his " Will to Power " that " the so- 
 called instinct of causality is nothing more than the fear 
 of the unfamiliar, and the attempt at finding something 
 in it which is already known." That is a pithy way of 
 stating one of the principles governing our designation of 
 cause. We see ourselves as agents and call the facts 
 about us frequently the effects of our action, we being the 
 cause. The Ego is a unit. Its expressions are results of 
 a will. We are cause and bring about effects. And just 
 as people from time immemorial have personalized unex- 
 plained facts, making out of them gods in human shape or 
 powers of human capacity magnified many times, so by 
 reasoning from analogy we attribute a causative function 
 to other live or moving factors in a situation. Fear 
 prompts us, and introspection guides us in this step. Ani- 
 mals are pictured as agents, and inanimate things become 
 causes when made conspicuous in some way. 
 
 A second principle in our choice of cause, then, is mo- 
 tion. In the midst of immobile things the moving appear 
 more commonly as cause, if no other principle interferes. 
 The falling of a leaf from a tree, for instance, is said to 
 result from a gust of wind. The wind was felt or heard. 
 The rotting of the stem of the leaf, the extra weight of 
 it due to an excrescence on the underside, the condition of 
 
 is "The Will to Power, Aphorism," No. 551. 
 
86 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 the twig whence it came, the law of gravitation these 
 and more facts were overlooked or taken for granted. 
 The idea of force impelled us to hold the breeze re- 
 sponsible. Again. We say motion causes friction, not 
 friction motion. This seems reasonable; but why? The 
 two form a coexistence. We cannot set the moment at 
 which friction ensues after motion has commenced. The 
 two coincide absolutely. But motion is more apparent 
 than friction, and back of motion is noticed, or under- 
 stood to act, an agent who really is the causative fact 
 we allude to. 
 
 4 Often, however, and in the third place, we distinguish 
 etween things controllable by man and those not so con- 
 trollable. The former are then the causes, and the latter 
 the effects, or the subliminal facts of no consequence. 
 What cannot be changed we do not attack in a plan of 
 action. We divide the world say for purposes of re- 
 form into variables and constants, thinking of the lat- 
 ter as facts unalterable. Thus the law of gravitation is 
 taken for granted. We expect men to protect themselves 
 against it in certain situations. We provide means of 
 support for objects. Buildings and chairs are devices for 
 utilizing or offsetting the general law. We do not blame 
 the law when something falls. We ask people to be more 
 careful and hold on to things, or to build better founda- 
 tions. 
 
 Or suppose a man is found destitute of the means of 
 livelihood. We can assign this to a hundred facts, but 
 probably will not think of the man's stupidity first. Or, 
 if we do, we proceed to emphasize another fact as cause. 
 The pauper himself may complain of unemployment or 
 illness in the family, or of an accident, and what not. 
 Or we find him indolent, inattentive, intemperate, etc. 
 Or we speak of hard times, of bad politics, of unfavorable 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 87 
 
 weather for the sort of work the poor man wanted. The 
 factors we can control or believe we can change become 
 cause ; the rest is ignored. 
 
 In the fourth place special purposes may guide us. 14 
 We speak of prejudices and axes to grind, of malice and 
 ulterior motives, and like things that color our judgment 
 and decide our choice of cause. Or it is the event nearest 
 in time or place that looms up as cause, as when a crowd 
 gathers in a street and I notice a boy looking for a coin. 
 I make him the starting point of my location of cause and 
 effect because I saw him and watched the number of on- 
 lookers grow after his loss. I do not ask why he dropped 
 the coin, whether he was day-dreaming or had a nervous fit, 
 or what led to day-dreaming. And so on. The nearest 
 concrete and active factor becomes the cause. The mur- 
 derer is arraigned and condemned partly for this reason. 
 We either disdain searching into his history or that of 
 the victim, in order to extend the chain of factors, or we 
 take refuge in a postulate of freewill and then pronounce 
 judgment. 
 
 We cannot trace all the intervening links in a lengthy 
 chain of facts constituting a correlation regularly recur- 
 ring. When a cow gives birth to a calf we ascribe the 
 flow of milk to that event. We do not go back to the 
 facts of fertilization that would logically form a more 
 correct starting point for the whole correlation. Or say 
 a war breaks out. Will not the cause be the occasion 
 that historians distinguish from the " underlying " causes ? 
 And are not the remote " causes " certain facts preceding 
 the declaration of war? Is it not plain that only a few 
 
 i* What is known as the pragmatic movement in philosophy has 
 developed this point into a system of thought, of which Schiller, 
 F. C. S., is a typical representative. See this writer's " Formal 
 Logic," pp. 277 & 283. Likewise: Enriques, F., "Problems of 
 Science," p. 142; James W., " Pragmatism." 
 
88 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 out of the whole number of facts in a situation are rather 
 arbitrarily selected as the cause? 
 
 The most obvious and nearest incidents impress us as 
 causes, but in reality the situation is not so simple. 
 Especially in the organic and social sciences the number 
 of relevant factors is legion. We may pounce on par- 
 ticulars, but no proof for such cause and effect will be 
 forthcoming. For not only is reproduction of the situa- 
 tion technically impossible, but what is more, we shall not 
 all classify cause and effect in the same way. It is often 
 a case of weighing trained knowledge against amateur 
 views, with the understanding that in the end either may 
 feel right. Where no direct appeal to the senses whose 
 reactions we all share in common is possible, the rule of 
 public opinion or of reputed authority begins. 
 
 4. Causation and Economic History. If, now, we 
 apply this analysis of correlation and causation to the 
 Marxian statement of the economic interpretation of his- 
 tory, or to the question of the relation between economic 
 and non-economic facts, we shall see that causal connec- 
 tions such as socialism has commonly asserted do not 
 exist. The economic world embodies stimuli that act 
 upon man, but so do many non-economic facts. And man 
 himself is needed in the situation to give contents to both. 
 The economic facts are part of our thinking and feeling. 
 If any one fact is a cause in such an ensemble it should be 
 man whose mind is a unit, and whose facts of conscious- 
 ness are all inextricably interwoven. 
 
 From the psychological standpoint, that is to say, the 
 Marxian superstructure of law and philosophy is merely 
 a set of interests somewhat farther from the primitive 
 man, from the center of attention and striving, than the 
 acts of production and exchange. Man's needs are 
 graded because of the facts of his evolution and physical 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 89 
 
 constitution. Some of our reactions, correspondingly, 
 will suit the immediate needs of survival or social devel- 
 opments ; others may persist even when primary needs 
 catering to survival have changed. 
 
 To illustrate. It should not be difficult to trace a con- 
 nection between prohibition and the value of sobriety in 
 modern production, or between the sanctioning of fe'male 
 modern rights and women's industrial activities, or be- 
 tween our present praise of thrift and the debt of the 
 United States or our fear of propertyless masses. Such 
 " ethical " facts may be thought to rest directly on eco- 
 nomic facts, though the causal chain runs both ways. 
 But, on the other hand, the economics of the ancient 
 Hindoos could only faintly be reconstructed from the 
 Vedas. Our idea of Chinese economic environment can- 
 not be properly derived from a study of their voluminous 
 literary works. The art of all ages shows considerable 
 uniformity of ideas and technique, and but little pe- 
 culiarity indicative of particular modes of living. Simi- 
 larly with scientific speculation, philosophy, and con- 
 cepts of government or morality. The principles of 
 sociation which sociology and economics study rest on 
 facts of human nature, and these are so constant that 
 certain rules of conduct are valid for all times, however 
 variable their form and economic expression. 
 
 To speak of interaction of economic and non-economic 
 facts is chiefly to use a figure of speech, for what is in- 
 teraction? If I see a cat and dog fighting I can follow the 
 movements of each and see each acting upon the other, 
 with results visible perhaps to the eye. That is interac- 
 tion in the real sense of the word. But in social affairs 
 the relation is more nearly one of force according to the 
 physicist's use of the term. The physicist can describe 
 force only as a product of two factors ; or, to be quite ac- 
 
90 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 curate, force to him is simply a ratio, a function of vari- 
 ables. Force refers to couples never reducible to entities. 
 So it is with economic and non-economic aspects. We 
 have never seen them apart. We can only say, as the 
 phychologist sometimes says, that two sets of events move 
 in unison, parallel to each other. Whether interaction in 
 the strict sense of the term takes place he may be loth to 
 decide. He pleads ignorance and goes ahead confident of 
 results from his labors. So with the student of social 
 events. In speaking of their interactions he really has 
 in mind only coexistences which, in any given correlation, 
 appear to him as an organic whole. He cannot reduce it 
 to independent units, though he may picture the parts as 
 functioning like the parts, say, of the human body. The 
 picture helps us to understand, to get meaning out of our 
 words. 
 
 But the relation of economic to so-called non-economic 
 events may be still better elucidated by modern psychol- 
 ogy, whose conclusions are important for all phases of 
 sociological analysis. 
 
 Three fundamental facts need to be remembered in this 
 connection. The first is that all objects, not merely the 
 economic, may act as stimuli. The second is the differ- 
 ences in reactions by different men upon like stimuli, or 
 conversely the fact that different men react upon differ- 
 ent things. 
 
 Our environment may be defined as the things we con- 
 sciously or unconsciously react upon. It is what we re- 
 spond to in a physical or mental way that constitutes part 
 of our life, not everything about us in space. Shake- 
 speare, thus, becomes part of my experience, while people 
 still alive, but many miles away and in no wise brought in 
 touch with me personally or indirectly, are strangers that 
 do not figure in my environment. Again, since our life 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 91 
 
 is a cycle of growth and decay, it is natural that at dif- 
 ferent ages different things should enter into our psychic 
 world. The boy does not see what interests an adult, but 
 he observes much else that grown-ups overlook. Sex and 
 age and profession and congenital proclivities aVe deter- 
 minants of environment psychologically viewed. 
 
 But from this follows the individuality of thought and 
 feeling, and more especially the independence of both from 
 the external world. Thirdly, then, the effect of memory 
 and associations stands in no measurable relation to the 
 objects about us, and furthermore, centrally aroused sen- 
 sations become more and more important with age and 
 historical development of races, so that correlations be- 
 tween economic data and mentality are altogether inde- 
 terminate. One cannot infer from external facts what 
 precise value our thought will take. Inventions, e. g., 
 start commonly with economic facts, but their direction 
 depends on memory associations which in their turn are 
 governed by predisposition, by the laws governing per- 
 ception, immediate purpose, etc., etc. As the psycholo- 
 gist expresses it : " It is seldom that an act or thought is 
 controlled merely by a single stimulus or even by the 
 stimuli that are being received at the moment of action. 
 The laws of facilitation and inhibition of one set of cor- 
 tical activities by others that are going on simultaneously 
 in other paths and in other areas are needed if we are to 
 obtain any accurate picture of cortical action," 15 and 
 that means also of concepts in general. Attitude is a 
 great deal. Whether the picture in the book looks to me 
 like a rabbit or like a duck's bill depends on angle of vision 
 and on subconscious activities within me. The thought of 
 a seismograph on seeing a crisscross of lines may only oc- 
 cur to a person after other facts have suggested earth- 
 is Pillsbury, W. B., "Fundamentals of Psychology," p. 91. 
 
92 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 quakes, as an actual experience has shown. My trend of 
 reasoning and the direction of discovering vary with pre- 
 vious training and general interests. This is the over- 
 whelming evidence of the history of science. Thoughts 
 have their own history, and their economic ef- 
 fects are consequents in point of time rather than 
 coexistences, though the historian expands his con- 
 cept of simultaneity and thus obtains a comparison 
 of economic and non-economic events. " The movement 
 of thought might be regarded as an interaction of pur- 
 poses and environment, each of which in some measure 
 modifies the other. At least no interpretation and no 
 improvement can be considered as a discrete event. It 
 has its meaning in, and its appearance and development 
 is controlled by, wider mental and physical contexts. 
 These serve to determine the nature of the appreciation 
 and to give the desire that leads to the particular im- 
 provements. In this way the progress of thought is one 
 continuous operation. No part can be understood unless 
 it is considered with the whole." 16 
 
 The independence of thought is real. Economic facts 
 do not make or mold the non-economic, nor must a history 
 of religion or of jurisprudence be referred to particular 
 and corresponding economic epochs. Such a cross refer- 
 ence may form a part of an historical study, but cannot 
 be essential except in a few cases. The study of legis- 
 lation regulative of economic relations, including property 
 relations, is an economic subject, though legislation is a 
 political function. Politics is the application of the prin- 
 ciples of sociology and economics toward social better- 
 ment. In this sense jurisprudence and law are best un- 
 derstood in the light of economic data, but this is no in- 
 stance of the economic man making our non-economic his- 
 , W. B., "Psychology of Reasoning," p. 286. 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 93 
 
 tory. It shows the possibility merely of studying eco- 
 nomic relations from two view-points, the individual and 
 the collective. 
 
 5. The Law of Maladjustment The Marxian in- 
 terpretation of history takes due notice of a conflict be- 
 tween individuals and ideas, and makes it the basis for a 
 theory of revolution and progress which is more in accord 
 with scientific thought than his subordination of the in- 
 tellectual and moral force to the economic. He an- 
 nounced the impending doom of capitalism on two grounds, 
 first because systematic exploitation would ultimately 
 consolidate all property into the hands of a few who, 
 while having no competitors to fear, would be faced by 
 a hungry proletariat that would claim what was right- 
 fully theirs, and secondly because economic and non-eco- 
 nomic achievements~and norms tend to overlap at certain 
 times, the maladjustment growing until a break was in- 
 evitable, which would restore an adjustment between the 
 two fields of thought and action. The exact manner in 
 which this periodic maladjustment is brought about does 
 not appear to have been described anywhere, but one must 
 infer that differences arising between new ideas and old 
 traditions were meant. 
 
 In a sociological sense conflicts are ordinarily of two 
 kinds. Men fight each other in the peaceful way that 
 modern economics exemplifies so strikingly, or they are 
 torn by inner conflicts. We either have to contend with 
 others, or with ourselves. The underlying reasons are 
 often the same for both cases, but the feeling created is 
 far from the same. We cannot hate ourselves, though 
 we sometimes think so. On the other hand it is hard to 
 forgive our enemies, though there is much to excuse them. 
 Misery has these aspects. It is objective when disease and 
 poverty stalk among the masses and make their life a 
 
94 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 burden. It is objective in so far as the economic rela- 
 tions between men have been regulated by laws open to 
 inspection. It becomes subjective when we think of one 
 set of men holding ideas scorned by a second set, the two 
 quarreling about their rights and duties. And it again 
 takes a subjective hue when we look into our own self and 
 find doubt and scruples, ideals falsely focussed, practices 
 incompatible with resolutions made and cherished. 
 
 The law of progress enunciated by Marx is a reflex of 
 these several forms of conflict, and it agrees partly with 
 the facts of correlation and causation considered a while 
 ago. Maladjustment does occur pretty regularly. Per- 
 haps it would not be wrong to make it a part of human 
 history as much as reversion is part of evolution. A cut- 
 ting back is no worse, no more irregular, than a cutting 
 ahead. Tne recapitulation theory for that reason has 
 been revised by careful biologists. 
 
 Conflict always accompanies control, and is a result of 
 two sorts of differences between men, namely those that 
 appear when we compare them at an instant of time, and 
 those due to afferent rates of reaction and growth cover- 
 ing a longer j^ej-iod. 
 
 The social process is one of interaction between man 
 and environment. The environment is physical and social, 
 and for reasons already suggested it may at times be ad- 
 vantageous to separate social activities into the economic 
 and non-economic. Physical environments exercise a 
 great influence over men, and they differ from place to 
 place. The* environment is chiefly climate, but climate 
 comprises many factors such as temperature, humidity, 
 solar radiation, length of day and season, wind pressure 
 and direction, variability per month and day, extremes of 
 range during the year, the combination of temperature 
 with humidity and wind pressure, and so on. The effect 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 95 
 
 of such variations upon man, and in particular upon 
 labor capacities, has been carefully studied. That cli- 
 mate has much to do with temperament is well known. 
 That literature and art no less than economic achieve- 
 ments or the nature of scientific endeavors bear testimony 
 to the influence of climate has also been admitted for many 
 decades. But it is a more recent opinion that energy and 
 inventiveness are functions of climate, and that the his- 
 tory of civilizations is largely one of climatological 
 changes now hidden from view, but powerful in their 
 day. 17 
 
 Climate is part of latitude and topography, but the 
 latter has direct bearings, too, on the development of 
 transportation and travel. Facilities for communication 
 vary with the lay of the land, with coastal contour and 
 the characteristics of river and lake systems. Mountain 
 ranges and plateaus, drainage basins and passes, the slop- 
 ing of ranges and their passes, these and other features 
 count in history. They form the outer limits, so to say, 
 beyond which human will dare not move. What the earth 
 provides in minerals and timber, soil fertility and water 
 power, that is a maximum man can seldom ignore. If, 
 therefore, men live in greatly different physical environ- 
 ments their capacities and wants cannot correspond favor- 
 ably. There will arise opposing viewpoints. 
 
 Yet it has been to many thinkers axiomatic that malad- 
 justment is not a product of nature conditions, but in- 
 stead a social excrescence. Man nmlcps hjyn^plf miserable: '._ 
 he is not made so by nature. The trouble ordinarily 
 lies then in economic conditions, relative to which differ- 
 ences in physical environs and in human nature may be 
 discounted. Men are congenitally very different and will 
 
 17 See especially Huntington, F., in his " Civilization and Climate," 
 and his more recent : " World Power and Evolution." 
 
96 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 never sympathize with each other on all points. They are 
 bound to part company somewhere. So also the differ- 
 ences of climate develop their peculiarities. But we must 
 assume these facts and, making them our constants, at- 
 tempt to adapt economic facts and personal relations to 
 them. An offsetting policy would be always opportune. 
 If, however, the economic differences in wealth and up- 
 bringing, in aptitudes and daily occupation, in modes of 
 living and social control, if these facts, too, separate men, 
 their interests may become irreconcilable. 
 
 And to this source of misunderstanding and friction we 
 are bound to add the effect of different rates of change in 
 the several factors, physical, personal, and economic. 
 
 The physical environment changes but slowly : so slowly 
 that, barring earthquakes and floods or such like, it ap- 
 pears to us stagnant. Only the geologist is interested 
 in the imperceptible movements that are part of our 
 earth's record. 
 
 But since men are so differently constituted some will 
 keep abreast of their times, and many will not. The in- 
 ventive man who helps to reconstruct our economic 
 mechanism is, along some lines, likely to adjust himself 
 to each moment, but to the average man the trend of 
 economic affairs is only a means to greater creature com- 
 forts, and beyond that a source of annoyances, his habits 
 being jolted by new demands arising from he wonders 
 where. However, even the innovator, the man chiefly in- 
 strumental in translating ideas into a concrete world of 
 goods, will retain many habits as of old, even when they 
 are affected by his own scientific contributions. Man is 
 a unit. Yes. But his mental associations need not 
 therefore all move on one level. A master mind in science 
 or merchandising is often a mediocre in his appraisal of 
 non-professional facts. He has for the first score of 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 97 
 
 years been under guidance that impregnated him with 
 ideas not all adaptable to the new conditions which he 
 himself assists in creating. For one thing some memory 
 associations antedate our creative life, and that has pro- 
 found significance for the facts of maladjustment. And 
 for another thing, even during the creative period of life 
 men remain conservative in many respects. Ideas move 
 in groups. Many groups will not be directly involved in 
 the process of thought filling our professional life. Oth- 
 ers will be gradually revised, and some ideals as well as 
 habits will not budge a bit. Thus each man, the most 
 richly gifted not excluded, may be pictured as keeping 
 only here and there pace with his outer world. Ideas 
 radiate changes in many directions, but within us the 
 change moves more nearly in certain specialized fields. 
 The realignment of stimuli from the outside, though 
 forced by our innovations, calls for a wider range of adap- 
 tation in response and habits of thinking than we are 
 capable of. The result is a testing within, which may 
 eventually spell skepticism and revolt, misery objective no 
 less than subjective. It is again a matter of difference 
 in degree as between different social groups. None are 
 altogether exempt from the ordeal. 
 
 But furthermore, the lines of cleavage socially are ac- 
 centuated by the power of custom. Custom is habit 
 viewed socially. Habit dies with the individual : custom 
 does not. Custom is opinion preserved and transmitted 
 from generation to generation, the modifications being; 
 hardly noticeable, though marked at last. If all men were 
 equally endowed with intelligence and energy custom would 
 be less important and conviction more. But as things are, 
 the norms of a minority are sure to impress the majority, 
 and Personality survives person. 
 
 Habits are standardized. Ideals are habits of thought 
 
98 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 on certain matters. Ideals are norms governing our con- 
 duct, or tending to do so on the average. These norms 
 become frequently traditions handed from father to son, 
 from one age to another. They have been called sanctions 
 because only by popular sanction can these practices in 
 thought and action exercise such control over our lives. 
 Many of these norms are institutionalized in church and 
 school, family and government, or in business etiquette. 
 They envelop us from the very beginning and do not 
 leave us until death. They gather momentum which tri- 
 umphs over reason. That is to say, just as our strictly 
 personal views and habits are more or less mobile, some 
 making for changes in our environment and some failing 
 to move in unison with them, so social heredity may make 
 a fetich of norms after they have ceased to correspond 
 closely with the world about us. Or, to state the situa- 
 tion differently: Some of our views and habits change 
 more slowly than others, not only by nature, but because 
 of the daily impress of authority from without. The 
 power of parental control should be distinguished from 
 the control of law or government, and the joint effect of 
 all must be compared with the associational process con- 
 stituting our mental life, which for some is so productive 
 of tangible economic results, while to others it means 
 little either in creativeness or in feelings of conflict. 
 
 If then we speak of being out of harmony with our 
 environment we mean these three things, first that our 
 mental development has progressed unevenly in different 
 directions ; secondly that some of us have grown while 
 others have stagnated, content to accept matters as they 
 are, regardless of the demands of the more progressive; 
 and third, that our fellowmen are to us an objective real 
 influence in different degrees. 
 
 As to this social environment. In one sense the 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 99 
 
 phrase " social environment " is inapt, for society is a 
 unit, and from the collectivist standpoint of the sociolo- 
 gist a social environment can only mean society con- 
 fronted with nature. But that is not the sense in which 
 the phrase is commonly used. So it must express an indi- 
 vidual standpoint. The individual calls all his fellowmen 
 his environment. But is this a correct attitude? In so 
 far as all individuals are substantially alike, one cannot 
 make or mar the other. Nature conditions set real limits 
 to human striving, but my average compatriot cannot. 
 Or, at any rate, if he is my environment so am I his. 
 Hence the term has a dual aspect which may easily be for- 
 gotten. 
 
 Nevertheless does it refer to something very definite in 
 another sense. For since men are not all equal, since 
 some exercise lasting influence over others it follows that 
 much of the average man's environment is the superior 
 man of talent or genius. To those supermen the social 
 environment is, in its living members, a minor factor, al- 
 beit not a negligible one. But to their mediocre contem- 
 poraries they themselves are major factors, a social en- 
 vironment in a much more serious sense. The great men 
 originate and propagate ideas. They prescribe rules of 
 conduct, even if the observance thereof rests mainly with 
 the imitators. The supermen alter conditions and often 
 defy the sanctions. They induce the less gifted to ques- 
 tion the traditional, perhaps to make sport of long hal- 
 lowed customs. Thus the course of maladjustment be- 
 tween social groups is hastened, and finally a movement 
 becomes visible whose aim is confessedly the assault upon 
 social heritage. Something like this effect is produced by 
 migrations. If many millions move from one physical and 
 economic environment into a very different, they are likely 
 to receive a shock, because their habits and ideals cannot 
 
100 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 migrate in the same way. They are firmly lodged and 
 offer a wall of resistance to whatever demands a new 
 outer world makes. The result is disconcerting, and for 
 some individuals may spell disaster. The Scotchman's 
 thrift may look like niggardliness when he migrates from 
 his inhospitable heath to the fertile plains of America. 
 The European who is taught to flatter and fawn if he 
 would succeed, finds his habits unprofitable in a land where 
 mobility of rank and power is no less understood than the 
 mobility of labor and capital. 
 
 Maladjustment, however, results from innate predispo- 
 sitions as well as from a conflict of ideas representing dif- 
 ferent interests acquired during the individual's life. 
 People are congenitally conservative and radical with re- 
 gard to different norms of living, or some are predomi- 
 nantly conservative while others tend strongly toward 
 radicalism. The conservative clings to existing institu- 
 tions and customs, and is naturally suspicious of all in- 
 novations whose practical value is not immediately ap- 
 parent. The radical is disposed to doubt the goodness of 
 practices generally approved, but is greatly impressed 
 with the need of reform along intellectual or moral lines. 
 The one type seems to build up only harmonious associa- 
 tions of thought, that lead to further developments of a 
 line of reasoning, but are incapable of reconstruction into 
 new valuations ; the other type, on the contrary, means in 
 professional pursuits a novel selection of data and theo- 
 ries, with the result that new vistas of thought are opened 
 up, sometimes perhaps to cause a revolution in science and 
 economic activities. 
 
 The radicals are apt to get the worst of it in the early 
 parts of a transition period; the conservatives seem out 
 of place in the latter stages when people have become 
 sufficiently acclimated in a new environment of thought to 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY* 101 
 
 see the shortcomings of the pas"t: ' "Tite >illacTj<uste<J 'in, 
 either case are punished for their minority views when the 
 dominant group of the ruling class objects to them. Im- 
 prisonment and fines are ordinary methods of chastise- 
 ment. Or more frequently still we express our disap- 
 proval by dubbing the maladjusted ones iconoclasts and 
 rebels, cranks and fogeys, freaks and maniacs. The in- 
 novator in science and art will be put down as a phantast 
 or a charlatan until he has found an audience whose sym- 
 pathy gives " tone " to his creations. In politics the most 
 defiant of traditions are known as radicals or progressives, 
 or, as nowadays, they become bolshevists whose teachings 
 infuriate the standpatter. But not infrequently such dar- 
 ing spirits have immortalized themselves. They have died 
 on the scaffold only to be praised in song and oratory 
 thereafter. As patriots and fathers of their country 
 some of them have gained undying fame, when during 
 their lifetime they were but an object for derision and 
 slander. In all fields of achievement this- turn-about in 
 valuations has repeatedly come, and it will come again. 
 The daring business man who at the outset seemed a 
 crackbrained plunger makes good eventually as pioneer 
 and founder of a firm. The visionaries and the heretics 
 who become respectively prophets and saints, the rebel 
 whose treason inspires later generations, they are all 
 examples of maladjustment brought about by large social 
 movements. 
 
 6. The Theory of Prosperity. However, though 
 overlappings of ideals new and old occur continually, this 
 does not do away in the slightest degree with the reality 
 of an objective standard for measuring welfare. The 
 economic interpretation, on the contrary, includes such a 
 test, and the Marxian view implies it even though the idea 
 was not anywhere elaborated. Human history, from this 
 
102 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 standpoint, has meant for the most part progress and 
 social betterment. In spite of recurring periods of mal- 
 adjustment the trend has been steadily toward the attain- 
 ment of a higher plane of prosperity. The world is 
 truly becoming better, and social science, having estab- 
 lished its norm, may consciously promote the wellbeing of 
 men. It would be fatal for us to assent to John Stuart 
 Mill's dictum that " questions of ultimate ends are not 
 amenable to direct proof. Whatever can be proved to be 
 good must be so by being shown to be a means to some- 
 thing admitted to be good without proof." 18 If he were 
 correct in believing that " the sole evidence it is possible 
 to produce that anything is desirable is that people do ac- 
 tually desire it " 19 if this were so, then social science in 
 a very serious sense had lost its mission. 
 
 The failure of utilitarianism as once understood is 
 clearly presaged in this essay of a mighty thinker. How- 
 ever, on the one hand, we are convinced these days that 
 Mill himself need not have rejected the economic tests be- 
 cause he started with pleasure and pain, and on the other 
 hand it is not necessary to abjure all personal tests be- 
 cause of a social approach to the problem. 
 
 The objective tests of prosperity may be given first 
 consideration even if we feel bound to believe in an Abso- 
 lute such as happiness, pleasure, salvation of the soul, god- 
 liness, etc. It is essentially a question of coupling a 
 measurable sort of welfare with the immeasurable. The 
 concepts of a supreme good which the Asiatics and Greeks 
 first formulated, and whose history is virtually the history 
 of all speculative thought, do not lend themselves to meas- 
 urement. We cannot tell when a man is happy ; we can- 
 not measure different amounts of pleasure and pain, 
 
 is Mill, J. S., " Utilitarianism," Chapter 1. 
 i Ibidem, Chapter 4. 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 103 
 
 though the hedonists once hoped to find principles for 
 measurements. It is impossible to gauge the goodness of 
 a man if his innermost creed as to world and infinity is to 
 serve as a criterion. The salvation of the soul may be 
 the greatest of human achievements and the sine qua non 
 of peace here on earth, but its roots and course of devel- 
 opment escapes our vigilance, no matter how we watch it. 
 Old norms then have failed in the sense that we have not 
 been able to prove their existence in individual cases, nor 
 found any means of measuring them and comparing them. 
 It is not an unreasonable conjecture to make, seeing what 
 we know of the evolution of men, that the cavedweller was 
 as happy or as good, in the conventional ethical sense, as 
 the modern man. But if we compare their respective 
 achievements and social organization, or if we should be 
 able to test their respective efficiency and modes of living, 
 the gains of civilization would stand out boldly enough. 
 The poorest may be happy and virtuous, if the two words 
 are defined suitably, but so may the wealthy and pro- 
 ficient, the healthy and intelligent. 
 
 An idiot is guiltless ? Probably. But we do not there- 
 fore put him on a par with the gifted. The sick are good 
 and willing? No doubt, but their pains and foibles em- 
 barrass them nonetheless. The paupers have merry mo- 
 ments and cultivate their soul? Certainly, but their 
 distress is real for all that, calling for redress on the part 
 of a legislator or friend who would add health, wealth, 
 and efficiency to all the possible kinds of goodness the 
 human mind has dreamed of. The need of an empirical 
 &nd economic standard of prosperity is therefore our need 
 _for a goal, in the attainment of which society at large 
 "shall rest satisfiedTand strong. The need is for the pos- 
 session of goods that make possible learning and leisure, 
 variety of experience and a full mete of self-realization. 
 
104 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 The functions of an economic concept of prosperity 
 may be illustrated from the relation of art to life. Art 
 is an ideal as well as a fact taking sens-ible forms. 
 Art has always been lauded as one of the highest manifes- 
 tations of reason and genius. The world has produced 
 much art, and certain nations have excelled in wonderful 
 creations of music or painting, architecture, literature, 
 and sculpture. But the criteria of art are elusive. What 
 is real art and what is banality or shallow imitation few 
 will decide. Opinions are nowhere more subjective than 
 in the realm of art where canons change continually. 
 
 Art also has no value at a supreme moment, in a 
 struggle of nations, in the contest between social groups 
 fighting for power and happiness as they understand 
 them. The nations most productive of art have had their 
 ascendancy and their decline. A people totally devoid of 
 art may easily score a victory over a foe than whom none 
 has achieved finer things judged aesthetically. The vulgar 
 view of art, then, is at odds with man's intense desire for 
 life and supremacy. Art goes for nought when a battle 
 opens. 
 
 The ethical norms, too, may appear inferior to none, 
 but if they do not issue in appropriate social expression 
 they leave no impress. Whether a group or a nation shall 
 live depends on its equipment in peace and war, on its 
 treasure of goods, their volume and nature, their distribu- 
 tion and use. He who is healthy has an advantage over 
 the ailing. He who has wealth is better off than the poor, 
 if otherwise their lots are equal. He who can do things 
 is superior to the helpless and ignorant. 
 
 But the economic norm of prosperity is social. Only 
 for large groups of people living together can efficiency, 
 health, and wealth be tested. Individual training is not 
 the only factor of importance in the productiveness of a 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 105 
 
 nation, as history has shown from earliest days on. As 
 soon as individual self-sufficiency came to an end, as a 
 result oFT;he economies of division of labor, proficiency 
 took on a social meaning. Thereafter the usefulness of a 
 man was shown best when he produced jointly with others. 
 
 And so with health and wealth. They count most when 
 related to communities as a whole, to nations and races. 
 Wars are won by nations whose social organization per- 
 mits them, in various ways, to promote the norms of pros- 
 perity more generally than their opponents are capable of. 
 
 Virtue is, at a crucial moment, good citizenship. It 
 points to the right place for the individual among his 
 fellowmen whose wellbeing is ordinarily his own. Such 
 virtues are consequently measurable by particular forms 
 of conduct. We can tell whether a man has sinned against 
 the rules of health and efficiency when we have no means 
 of finding out whether he believes all that's in a cate- 
 chism. 
 
 Wealth in tangible goods is as essential to progress as 
 it is fit for measurement and comparison. The inherent 
 ingenuity of man accounts for the first steps toward civ- 
 ilization, but once wealth was acquired it became a further 
 guarantee of progress. For surplus means leisure and 
 JT|nj_pfi.3iTig specialization of workers, ^and this in turn en- 
 hances social productiveness. Education is impossible 
 without leisure. The modern forms of research could not 
 continue if our regular surplus of goods were suddenly to 
 disappear. Much work would then stop. Production it- 
 self, however, necessitates also technical cooperation, a 
 corollary of which is a sense of interdependence and a 
 social conscience, that is a feeling of worth in our fellow- 
 men, our rivals or friends. Wealth brings cumulatively 
 the means of communication which perpetuate knowledge 
 and help disseminate it among the masses. And since the 
 
106 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 power of our association of ideas varies largely with their 
 range and character, early training and selection become 
 important. Thus methods of production stand in some 
 ratio to existing wealth. We learn to " find " ourselves, 
 to trace correlation expressive of health and illness. Our 
 hygienic and sanitary measures are prophylactic as well as 
 corrective. The general round of wealth, leisure, knowl- 
 edge, proficiency, health, vigor, and production repeats 
 itself endlessly. There is no other way of attaining pros- 
 perity than the economic, though we may translate this 
 into visions of personal value, into precepts of conduct 
 sanctioning what the biological and psychological facts 
 have already urged. The sociologist, thus, will utilize 
 their data for purposes of understanding social inter- 
 course in general, but the economist has to add the rides 
 of production and exchange by which wealth, health, and 
 efficiency are procured most abundantly. 
 
 7. Summary on the Economic Interpretation of 
 History. To conclude. The economic interpretation of 
 history comprises several noteworthy points. Fir^fef- the 
 tracing of a causal relation between economic and non- 
 economTc events is an idle undertaking because all life is 
 a unit and all economics the product of a mental unit: 
 manhimself. The concept of causation is evidence merely 
 6~F~our penchant for selection and concentration. All 
 events are interrelated, but it is as correct to write a his- 
 tory of religion without resort to economics as to record 
 economic developments without injecting a dissertation 
 on religion. The precise bearing of one on the other is a 
 rather personal matter. 
 
 In the second-place, the sufficiency of a purely empiri- 
 cal viewpoint cannot be doubted. We can never do with- 
 out premises in one respect, but all the attempts of the 
 
INTEPRETATION OF HISTORY 107 
 
 metaphysician have presumed upon our credulity by tak- 
 ing for granted much of what was to be explained and 
 proven. Socialism has done better, therefore, by con- 
 fining its investigations to a world realistically conceived 
 and familiar to all. The materialistic viewpoint has 
 proven useful, for it has helped us to think of society as 
 governed by fundamental instincts instead of its being the 
 pet of Providence. 
 
 In the thirdj^lace, maladjustment is a regular part of 
 life springing from the'veTy^foundations of human nature 
 w and~its~relation to a changeable environment.. We shall 
 perhaps never eliminate it completely. For this reason 
 alone, if for no other, the Marxian aim at a millennium 
 must lead to disillusionment. Misery, tho best understood 
 as a social excrescence, is yet something for which science 
 has so far found no single antidote. We cannot expect a 
 cure by one step, nor a curing of evils by one means ap- 
 plied to all times. 
 
 In the fourth place^ the facts of biological and social 
 sciences lead us to the adoption of a utilitarian stand- 
 point, but utility is then not defined as pleasure or ab- 
 sence of pain. The norms of welfare are not individual 
 whose aggregate sums make prosperity for the nation at 
 large. Our norms, rather, must be objective even for the 
 individual. Not his feeling's, but facts of health, wealth, 
 
 ^Hi^*-~ c-i / . ^ 
 
 and efficiency decide the question. In part individually, 
 in part socially measdi'able, Llity Tell us what degree of 
 wellbeing a people has reached, and how it compares with 
 other social units. Correspondingly virtue is not creed, 
 but conduct. The test of virtue is not suffering, as the 
 Flagellants and like-minded folk preached, but service, as 
 taught by the Christ. 
 
 The economic interpretation of history comprises this 
 
108 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 view of goodness and righteousness. It embraces the 
 whole field of conduct associated formally with ethics, and 
 logically compels socialism to redefine justice. Pros- 
 perity is the result of just relations between men, but that 
 they are just is shown by the objective realities studied 
 chiefly by economists. 
 
CHAPTER V 
 JUSTICE 
 
 i. The Principle of Differentiation. The founders 
 of socialism said little about justice, but a great deal 
 about the evils of an unequal distribution of wealth. 
 They were interested in the principles of sociation and of 
 economics, not in abstract questions of right and wrong. 
 Their works abound in passages criticizing theoretical 
 positions of an opponent, while to the sentimental plead- 
 ings of the Utopians they turned a deaf ear. Since then 
 the attitude of socialists has remained about the same. 
 They have insisted on an objective treatment of socio- 
 logical subjects. They have sought to lay bare the foun- 
 dations of the social structure rather than launch reforms 
 from a sense of morality or fair dealing. Scientific so- 
 cialism has endeavored to understand the laws of nature 
 rather than individualistic concepts of justice and good- 
 ness. 
 
 Yet the definition of justice is a corollary to the eco- 
 nomic interpretation of history proclaimed by Marx and 
 Engels, and the idea of a better world in which equity 
 v should rule for the protection of all is really prominent 
 in the teachings of socialism. What is popularly sep- 
 arated from matters of fact as a distinct question of 
 ethics has been by socialists incorporated with social sci- 
 ence. Ethics and economics have been fused into one 
 single topic. There is no way of answering the questions 
 first put by Marx without reaching also some definite con- 
 
 109 
 
110 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 elusions on the ends of government and the nature of 
 justice. 
 
 But the definition is implied rather than stated in so 
 many words. And again, the modern view of history or 
 of social processes and of prosperity does away with the 
 old-time notion of a distinct science of ethics detachable 
 from social sciences, such as sociology and economics are. 
 Justice cannot be defined in general terms. To try it is 
 even less profitable than defining fundamentals in other 
 sciences. As soon as we seek to embrace all in a single 
 sentence we lose the meaningfulness of words. They be- 
 come nondescript and unsatisfactory to all but a few of 
 the initiated. And to them the broadest definitions are 
 useful only because supported by a wealth of particulars 
 held in the background of consciousness. 
 
 What is justice? The definition would resemble the 
 vagueness of definitions on matter and force, life and 
 space, electricity and motion, mind and value and time. 
 We define such words, but make mental reservations. Our 
 ideas change, and we have to redefine. Science changes its 
 point of view and stresses new facts. The life of a thinker 
 is a quest for definitions. He would give contents to the 
 vehicles of expression that the man on the street uses so 
 lightly. It is the mark of a thinking man that he knows 
 what his words mean, and differentiates nicely between 
 their exact meanings. But the largest concepts cannot 
 be defined so as to have lasting value for science. Jus- 
 tice may be defined a half a dozen ways without giving us 
 an idea of its relation to everyday experience. Justice 
 should be referred to particulars. 
 
 There is another approach to the problem of justice 
 which agrees well with the scientific viewpoint of social- 
 ism. We may go over all the cases of justice or injustice 
 that we can remember, and we shall then notice that the 
 
JUSTICE 111 
 
 question always turns on a comparison of inequalities. 
 
 Life is nothing if not inequalities as to things, and be- 
 tween men. No two things are exactly alike. This is a 
 trite saying. Differences are the rule, and resemblances 
 are only of a degree. In physical environment, in the 
 characters of men, and in the institutions of society the 
 fact of inequality attracts our attention. 
 
 The world's resources for instance are very unequally 
 divided between nations, some having an abundance of 
 mineral and good soil, and others practically nothing of 
 either. The Eskimo might compare his fate with the 
 Frenchman's or American's, and bewail his fate. Or the 
 Patagonian might gaze with envy upon the riches be- 
 stowed by nature upon his northern neighbors in the Ar- 
 gentine. Races in prehistoric times settled in different 
 parts of the globe, or migrated several times since then. 
 They cannot be said to have chosen their abode with an 
 eye to resources excepting fertility of soil, for the kinds 
 of wealth which are now prized most highly were then un- 
 known as an instrument for progress. It is chance that 
 gave to some great resources, while others were allotted a 
 meager store of bare necessities. 
 
 So with the differences among humans. Sex itself is a 
 differentiation of far reaching import. We might com- 
 pare the characteristic activities, the burdens and privi- 
 leges, of male and female and find much that seems unjust 
 in a sense. At times we have been so told. Or there are 
 race traits to compare ; the superiorities of a white man 
 over the Hottentot and the mode of living which, in part 
 resulting from these differences, drives the two groups far 
 apart. History is colored deeply by racial characteris- 
 tics. It is folly to overlook them in a larger survey. 
 
 And what of the inborn differences traced to heredity or 
 to variation ? What of the strong in body and mind, and 
 
THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 the frail? What of the subnormal and the super-normal, 
 the types of personality that are to be met everywhere in 
 life? The variety is bewildering and is said to lend charm 
 to life. Probably so. But the fact of such differences 
 remains and cannot be attributed to any particular, meas- 
 urable action of those possessing the advantages or the 
 handicaps. We simply accept the differences. We know 
 that some are born lucky and others unlucky. We know 
 that some will struggle throughout life without achieving 
 anything unusual, while others will succeed virtually with- 
 out effort. We know that the pretty girl is surrounded 
 by admirers and looks forward to all sorts of blessings, 
 when her less comely sister is left to walk alone. We know 
 that some will work creatively and reap rewards, while the 
 less gifted but perhaps more industrious will live in pen- 
 ury, forgotten and cheerless. 
 
 History is itself a record of differences sometimes ap- 
 palling to behold. What cruelties and hardships have be- 
 fallen millions of innocent people ! We read of catas- 
 trophes wiping out the lives of thousands. We hear of 
 cripples and the demented, or of miserable wretches 
 stricken with loathsome diseases. We read that an ex- 
 plosion has killed so many miners in a second. We think 
 of the wars that have killed and maimed hundreds of 
 millions for no reason except that life seems to be a battle 
 in which some fight and suffer more than others. We 
 turn the pages of a History of the World and are im- 
 pressed with nothing so much as with the inequalities of 
 men and their fates. And many have endured horrible 
 pains. Indeed, one might add that the path of human 
 progress is strewn with the wrecks of men and women who 
 suffered without guilt. Some were put to horrible tor- 
 tures or consigned to the flames. Some were immured 
 
JUSTICE 113 
 
 alive or flayed to death. Some died on the rack, and 
 others were butchered as a sacrifice to false gods. Many 
 perished from famine, and others again fell a prey to wild 
 beasts. If differences as such are to count in the problem 
 of justice, why should we not muse over the mysteries of 
 Fate that let some live amidst the comforts of the twentieth 
 century while the great majority lived a coarse struggling 
 life in the earlier stages of human development? As the 
 believer in justice sees it, these differences form a dis- 
 enchanting chapter in the history of the world. 
 
 And yet this is not all. For we have still two other 
 types of disparity to remember, to wit, the socio-economic 
 stratification, and the suffering of the innocent for the 
 guilty. 
 
 As to the former, the evidence is about us abundantly. 
 It forms the chief theme of reformers, and is a cardinal 
 point in the program of socialism. The world's goods, 
 they say, are too unevenly divided. Some are born rich 
 and others never save a penny. Some toil but remain 
 poor, while others bask in affluence without turning a 
 finger. As goods are distributed, so are the pleasures 
 and privileges that money can buy or that it procures in- 
 directly. It is for some to walk in the best of society 
 however understood and to shape the destiny of mil- 
 lions, while the multitude follows and sees little of what 
 their age represents. Some will shoulder burdens to re- 
 lieve others who tread lightly and carefree. In a war, 
 for instance, one group goes to the front, perhaps never 
 to return, or worse yet, to return crippled and helpless. 
 But another group stays at home because its services are 
 needed there, or for some less pressing reason. The stay- 
 at-homes may be getting their deserts, but note that they 
 live in comforts and grow rich while their compatriots go 
 
114* THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 into a living death. And often the brave are slain, and 
 the pretenders thrive. How common indeed that heroes 
 are buried by hypocrites ! 
 
 The innocent also get the worst of it when the offender 
 goes scot free. We see defenseless nations insulted and 
 abused by unscrupulous neighbors, by the Goliaths who 
 are itching for a fight. We see a neutral nation pay for 
 the follies of the combatants. We see a whole nation suf- 
 fer for the wrongs of its government which after all is 
 not truly representative. Or perhaps the children pay 
 for the sins of their fathers, or we must make good the 
 losses incurred by careless friends. 
 
 All this and more is common knowledge. The inequali- 
 ties have always existed and must be expected to recur on 
 general principles of induction. We cannot eradicate all 
 of them. There are some beyond our control, as well as 
 others that we may consider the expressions of will on 
 the part of men. 
 
 We shall have to discriminate but we shall also feel 
 compelled to admit that life without inequalities is un- 
 thinkable. The task of the reformer is not the uni- 
 formization, but the coordination of specialized forms of 
 living so that the largest number of people may live in 
 relative peace and contentment. Not a leveling for its 
 own sake, but leveling with a view to progress, this is the 
 task before us. To level rights and duties for classes of 
 people rather than for all people, this must be our aim. 
 Differentiations are the prime characteristic of life, and 
 the price of evolution. We cannot abolish them. But 
 we can divide society into groups with specialized func- 
 tions, and then assign to each its burdens and privileges. 
 Equality for all in a given class, such leveling is feasible. 
 Equal rights for all members in a certain occupational 
 class, or of an age group, or per sex, or relative to civic 
 
JUSTICE 115 
 
 status, and so on. This is the sort of uniformity com- 
 patible with economic advancement and urged by our ob- 
 jective norms of prosperity. All self-imposed or socially 
 induced forms of pain should be eliminated. 
 
 2. The Nature of Justice Such a view of equaliz- 
 ation suggests also several negative answers to the prob- 
 lems of justice. It is clear, for instance, that the promise 
 of heavenly rewards cannot hush the protests of the un- 
 lucky, for according to this promise the fortunate here on 
 earth will fare equally well in the hereafter. Where, then, 
 is the logic of inequality during this life? 
 
 Again, justice cannot be called rightly an institution 
 of nature, as was held by the ancients and by philosophers 
 since. This idea that nature is peace and happiness, and 
 society a decline and fall from virtue, is pure superstition, 
 however revered it may be by some who are more influ- 
 enced by religious promptings than by facts. There is 
 nothing to show that the jungle life is more pleasant than 
 ours. On the contrary, we have proof of its being every- 
 where a harsh struggle, and most so among the brutes. 
 Nature has not set the table for men. What they want 
 they must for the most part earn. Life is a battle, not 
 a frolic and minstrel show. The naturalistic view of 
 origins of injustice is as fanciful as its conclusions on the 
 founts of constitutional government. 
 
 In thethird place, we may also be sure that norms of 
 equity cannot be based on mere intuitions. No more 
 than men by nature are altruistic are they capable of 
 distinguishing between right and wrong. The history of 
 morals, which has been studied by many men with great 
 diligence, shows the relativity of ethical norms and the 
 immense variety of conceptions on right and wrong. At 
 different times different codes of conduct have arisen. 
 Any one who observes has profited in this respect from his 
 
116 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 travels. We see much dissension among people on identi- 
 cal points. Customs vary, and laws reflect the economic 
 setting of officially sanctioned demands for justice. Laws 
 cannot be understood to make justice, for what is held 
 just at one time may become unsatisfactory long before 
 the lawmaker adapts himself to the change. This phase 
 of maladjustment has been discussed in an earlier chap- 
 ter. Laws do not create justice, but they give evidence 
 of norms accepted by people as right or fair. Law is a 
 derivative whose original is science or the mores or the 
 standard set by exceptional men. 
 
 Justice, then, is this one positive thing, whatever else 
 may be said about it: Justice refers to human institu- 
 tions and to facts of life unknown to barbarism. Justice 
 is an ideal presupposing a reasoning man, a willing being, 
 a responsible being. Justice is for thinking men on an 
 advanced level of living. Only when somehow we be- 
 lieve ourselves as individuals capable of willed action, only 
 when we possess the ability to foresee certain events or 
 to master a set of relations, only then are we fit to de- 
 velop a notion of justice and to govern ourselves accord- 
 ingly. Justice is a general policy comprising actions 
 suited to reason and responsibility. The things we can 
 control become subjects for reform. The facts utterly 
 beyond our guidance we leave out of the equation. Jus- 
 tice always is a social norm that deals with the relations 
 between thinking and striving members of a large whole. 
 That is just which subserves the end of the largest possible 
 number, after the end has been defined according to the 
 dictates of social science. Justice is an ideal of social 
 relations and of aims varying with times. 
 
 " Right," the author of * 4 Folkways " informs us, " can 
 never be natural, or God-given, or absolute in any sense. 
 The morality of a group at a time is the sum of the 
 
JUSTICE 117 
 
 folkways by which right conduct is defined. Therefore 
 morals can never be intuitive. They are historical, insti- 
 tutional, and empirical." * The just act is one which is 
 conducive to the welfare of the largest possible number, 
 welfare having previously been rated by the economic tests 
 compared to which all other norms are subjective and in- 
 capable of measurement. " The problem of morality is 
 the formation, out of the body of original instinctive im- 
 pulses which compose the natural self, of a voluntary self 
 in which socialized desires and affections are dominant, 
 and in which the last and controlling principle of delib- 
 eration is the love of the objects which will make this 
 transformation possible." 
 
 We repeat, justice has connotations of reason and re- 
 sponsibility socially utilized. Irrational people cannot 
 be expected to deal squarely with their fellowmen. Or, 
 since this test of reason itself is the power of coordinating 
 efforts, we had better admit that justice is reason, and 
 that the objective tests of social welfare furnish the best 
 proof for the existence of either. When society pro- 
 gresses and th,e need of the average man is reflected in the 
 strength of the larger unit, then justice prevails. It is 
 justice in the long run, in large categories, in vital affairs 
 that matters. Sacrifices of self and of detail is insepar- 
 able from justice properly conceived. " Justice may be 
 defined as such an adjustment of the conflicting interests 
 of the citizens as will interfere least with, and contribute 
 most to, the strength of the nation." 2 The might of the 
 many, measured in terms of health, wealth and efficiency, 
 is the sole available proof of the general prevalence of 
 justice. And in a struggle between different social groups 
 or between nations it will appear soon enough as to where 
 
 iSumner, W. G., "Folkways," p. 29. 
 
 2 Carver, Th. N., " Essays in Social Justice," p. 9. 
 
118 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 justice has asserted itself most completely. There are 
 degrees of justice from the social standpoint, whatever 
 our opinion about justice in a particular. We may con- 
 sider a man either right or wrong, a verdict either just or 
 unjust, disdaining to bicker about shades and shares. 
 But since justice is for individual cases and since life 
 comprises so many duties and rights it is inevitable that, 
 while in some respects we are just to each other, in others 
 we are not. The ideals of politics and economics center 
 about such weighing of pros and cons, our choice finding 
 expression in social structure and economic or military 
 power. 
 
 Grant the will-to-live, and you must grant the worth of 
 social strength. Grant reason in man and you will want 
 to hold him responsible for his action. Grant norms of 
 conduct however evolved or formulated, and you will con- 
 sult them before long when passing judgment on par- 
 ticulars. Will is assumed as a means of eliminating the 
 unfit. The freedom of the will is a tactical device by 
 which we can compare the good with the bad and endeavor 
 an adjustment of conflicting wishes. 3 Will is basic to 
 justice, just as the law of averages is back of our notion of 
 the ought. But will, the psychologist knows, is the sub- 
 jective aspect of a condition as suitable for examination 
 as the facts of motion. To say that one ought to do a 
 certain thing merely means that as a rule such acts will 
 prove beneficial according to definition, or that out of a 
 hundred men, put in a given situation, a certain per- 
 centage would act as the particular one " ought to." 
 What the majority does conformable to the needs of so- 
 ciety, to needs that sometimes are objectively verifiable 
 
 3 Mill, J. S., in his "Logic" (Book Six, Chapter 2, No. 2) gives 
 a definition of determinism which seems still the most lucid and 
 comprehensive of many offered by logicians. 
 
JUSTICE 119 
 
 and measurable but at other times are accepted by rea- 
 soning from analogy without careful testing, that becomes 
 moral. The injunction to act, the assertion that a 
 certain thing ought to be or ought to be done, rests 
 on a belief that in most cases justice will thereby 
 triumph. 
 
 The much mooted topic of motives versus results loses 
 its vexatious character when treated as a matter of aver- 
 ages. If, e. g., I am instrumental in a child being run 
 over through my attempting to save it from that very 
 fate, the result is taken to be an exception to the rule. 
 Extenuating circumstances will be pleaded because I acted 
 in good faith, i. e., with the intention of saving the child 
 from impending danger. It will be argued that in most 
 cases such a policy on my part brings good results, and 
 that consequently my failure in a particular instance is 
 a contingency to be reckoned with. The principle is 
 deemed more vital than any one application of it, be it 
 successful or not. Thus the law may condemn me, but 
 my sin is pardonable in the eyes of most witnesses. Leni- 
 ent treatment will be urged. 
 
 Motives, therefore, assume a moral aspect only in the 
 sense that they are forecasts of events which in them- 
 selves are either social or anti-social. If the former, 
 motives are excusable though leading to undesirable re- 
 sults in one instance; if the latter, motives are repre- 
 hensible though leading accidentally to good results. Mo- 
 tives in this respect are like efforts spent in doing a piece 
 of work. I may work hard and get results not com- 
 mensurate with my efforts and unsatisfactory by ob- 
 jective tests. My reward will agree with the net result, 
 not with the labor expended. But in the long run, it is 
 true, a man is the more likely to accomplish great things, 
 the harder he tries, the more tireless his striving. Hence 
 
120 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 it is not unfair or illogical to rate men somewhat by their 
 tenacity and diligence. 
 
 3. Justice and Competition If we apply this 
 maxim of average results and of reasoning by analogy, 
 for an individual act, to the relation between religion and 
 economics, or of might to right, we shall be able to solve 
 what otherwise may appear an unsolvable proposition. 
 
 It has often been argued that Christianity, for instance, 
 is irreconcilable with economics or with common practice, 
 and similarly that socialism is incompatible with religion. 
 However, the antinomy is not one given by two contrast- 
 ing viewpoints, but rather it results from one-sided in- 
 terpretations and abstractions. 
 
 The Christian creed is of course a mixture of many 
 tenets not all of which belong to the Gospel as 
 originally preached so far as historical investigation has 
 been able to ascertain. We have the eschatology and the 
 golden rule, the one chiefly, though not entirely, developed 
 after the death of the founder of Christianity, and the 
 other antedating even the advent of the Christ. 
 
 The preachings on a .monotheistic world order, on an 
 absolute God, his fatherhood, and the endowment of man 
 by God with faculties of reason and with infallible intu- 
 itions of right and wrong, these teachings which are 
 grouped about the doctrine of an immortal soul and re- 
 demption by proxy may be conveniently detached from 
 the moral code. The Sermon on the Mount has a value 
 independent of the theological superstructure. The idea 
 of a forgiving father and of a final court of appeal above 
 human jurisdiction anchors deep in the human breast. 
 It will be true in all ages that the leveling of rights as 
 preached in the brotherhood of men has salutary social 
 effects. It is an axiom, also, among scientists that their 
 own conclusions are subject to error and to occasional 
 
JUSTICE 
 
 correction, and that all inquiries of the mind have limits 
 beyond which men may still hope and aspire to unknown 
 things. 
 
 But on the other hand, the moral precepts of all great 
 religious teachers have been one-sided. They have looked 
 to only one out of several relations existing with regard 
 to any problem. Thus the precepts of Christianity are 
 bold abstractions from concrete instances. They are the 
 fruit of reasoning by analogy. For instance, it is good 
 to treat others as we would treat our own self, but, to 
 begin with, human nature is not altogether of that in- 
 clination, and in the second place a rigid regard for this 
 ruling would lead not infrequently to self-effacement. Bi- 
 ologists are not sure that evolution could have operated 
 exclusively on that principle. 
 
 The way out of the apparent conflict between religion 
 and reality is not a campaign for changing human nature, 
 but a return to other facts in the situation, and to a re- 
 construction of our religious beliefs. There is a social 
 basis for religion. In the measure that our abstractions 
 are reconverted to the concrete conditions whence they 
 sprang shall we succeed in uniting theory and practice 
 without destroying the social fabric. Economics, for in- 
 stance, will be able to adopt a collectivistic viewpoint 
 without ceasing to be scientific if it abandons some of its 
 problems which an earlier age, before natural and social 
 sciences had far progressed, had set, and if it subordinates 
 ethics to social science instead of borrowing from meta- 
 physicians. The stand taken by classic economics to- 
 ward questions of morality, which once were associated 
 with metaphysics, is responsible for the seeming heartless- 
 ness which some critics detected in professional economists. 
 It made John Ruskin say : " I neither impugn nor doubt 
 the conclusion of the science [he refers to economics], if 
 
THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 its terms are accepted. I am simply uninterested in them, 
 as I should be in those of a science of gymnastics which 
 assumed that men had no skeletons." It elicited from 
 Carlyle the characteristic exclamation : " All this Mam- 
 mon Gospel of Supply and Demand, Competition, Laissez 
 Faire, and the Devil take the hindmost, begins to be one of 
 the shabbiest Gospels ever preached, or altogether the 
 shabbiest." 5 
 
 The " economic man " was somewhat of an abstraction, 
 but even more so is the definition of justice and of the ul- 
 timate good whose study the economists wished to leave 
 to another line of thinking. 
 
 Competition need not be what the " dismal science " 
 made it. It need not incite the admirer of the Christian 
 creed to the thought that " competitive industry and 
 commerce are based on selfishness as the dominant instinct 
 and duty, just as Christianity is based on love." 6 If 
 the fault were as grave as pictured, if " our whole socio- 
 economic structure rests theoretically upon the appeal to 
 the selfish ," 7 then socialism would logically be the only 
 alternative to individualism. 
 
 It may be so anyhow, though for different reasons. 
 But recent interpretations of fair competition have sug- 
 gested a way out, and the conception of the Ought as an 
 estimate of average results desirable to society as a whole, 
 does a similar service. 
 
 Competition has by the courts been considered fair 
 when, first, the inequalities between competing parties are 
 
 * Ruskin, J., in his " Unto This Last." 
 
 s Carlyle, Th., "Essays, Past and Present: The Working Aristoc- 
 racy." 
 
 e Rauschenbusch, W., " Christianity and the Social Crisis," p. 310. 
 See also the same author's " Christianizing the Social Order." 
 
 7 Murdoch, J. G., " Economics as a Basis of Living Ethics," p. 
 47. 
 
JUSTICE 
 
 natural, as for instance the innate differences of ability 
 and temperament, or when secondly, the differences arise 
 accidentally, as at the outbreak of the war, which gave 
 some dealers a great advantage over those not stocked up 
 with European products ; or in the third place, when the 
 differences are not sufficiently great to make the result of 
 the struggle between rivals a foregone conclusion, or 
 when, in the fourth place, the price and quality alone de- 
 cide in the sale of goods ; or when, finally, goods are mar- 
 keted by rivals at a price which generally speaking yields 
 a profit permitting of a continuance of business. 
 
 To define competition as " fair " under such circum- 
 stances is to admit the impossibility of equalizing all facts. 
 It does not dictate an abandonment of the principle of 
 striving among producers and consumers, but it hints at 
 limitations that in the long run safeguard both competi- 
 tor and the public. 
 
 Some sort of inequality and hence of injustice, as popu- 
 larly understood, is bound to linger among us. Right 
 cannot be right to all contending parties. Might always 
 exists, if by that term we mean the superiority in some 
 respects of force over mere good will, or of law over com- 
 mon sense. 
 
 4. Might versus Right. But if we inspect the mat- 
 ter of might versus right more closely we shall find that 
 might means nothing except by reference to something 
 else. Might may mean either muscular strength or me- 
 chanical power, or such brain powers as are exercised in- 
 dividually or by dint of social organization. If the force 
 is physical the individual ordinarily is the active agent, 
 as when pugilists settle a question of superiority. Na- 
 tions also fight, though armies nowadays represent much 
 more than skill or muscle strength. In all such cases 
 might may consist of physical force only, and it deserves 
 
THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 mention that ultimately all other values will stand or fall 
 according to the issue of a physical combat. 
 
 But manifestly such struggles have nothing to do with 
 social values unless we first posit the latter as occasion for 
 the former. Might strictly speaking is right only when 
 a predominating opinion cannot be upheld by physical 
 force. In that case our disappointment is voiced in the 
 remark that might has triumphed over right. When ex- 
 pert opinion is defied, or the will of the majority is dis- 
 obeyed (particularly on the confession of the offender 
 himself) then his exercise of physical power is reproved. 
 
 Might is right, therefore, when the majority sanctions 
 the force used to uphold its views, whether science sup- 
 ports public opinion or not ; or when in the absence of any 
 social values physical force alone governs ; or when, in the 
 third place, approved norms of conduct prevail indepen- 
 dent of physical coercion. In the long run the will of the 
 majority, however inspired, carries the day. Right, con- 
 sequently, must triumph as a general rule even though for 
 groups of people and for limited periods of time condi- 
 tions may be at variance with public opinion. 
 
 The law of approximations and of averages thus 
 equates the two sides of right and might for the same 
 reason that it brings into logical relation the fields of re- 
 ligion and of social science, or of economics and of ethics. 
 There is no impassable gulf between socialism even as 
 taught by Marx and the religious beliefs. It is not 
 necessary to oust competition from the field of economic 
 endeavor. But on the other hand it is doubtful whether a 
 categorical exclusion of the collectivistic standpoint from 
 economic science will further the interests of economics 
 itself. Justice must be socially conceived and measured. 
 Socialism has first called attention to the need of such a 
 
JUSTICE 125 
 
 gauging of right and wrong. The future development of 
 social science seems bound to fuse ethics and economics 
 into one single problem, so that people will more nearly 
 than at the present be in accord with scientific conclusions. 
 
CHAPTER VI 
 THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 
 
 i. National Income and Consumption of Goods. 
 
 TJigjiath-to progress is through plenty. There is no way 
 in which the condition of the average man can be bettered 
 except we raise his income first. Whatever the limita- 
 tions of mere wealth may be, if we have no wealth, if man- 
 kind lives uncertainly from hand to mouth, everything else 
 will also be lacking that is typical of a civilized state. All 
 history so far has forced us to take this attitude. Hu- 
 man development from beginning to end has been a piling 
 up of economic goods the consumption of which has been 
 accompanied regularly by advances in art and science, 
 in speculation and moral judgments. 
 
 It is then no trifle if socialism declares to have found 
 a short cut to wealth. If it is true that national in- 
 come may be greatly increased by abolishing private prop- 
 erty we should favor the revolution even though it entail 
 much personal effort and sacrifice. If, as an eminent 
 socialist leader avers, " the transformation of the capi- 
 talist system of production into the socialist system 
 must inevitably result in a rapid increase of the quantity 
 of wealth produced " * an important question is happily 
 settled. The raising of the general level of living is the 
 concern of all statesmen and reformers. ^Nothing is so 
 palpably desirable as a doubling of wages, if by it we mean 
 
 a doubling of the average person's purchasing power./ 
 
 I. ,*/ 
 
 1 Kautsky, K., " Class Struggle," a running commentary on the 
 Erfurt Program of the German Sozial-demokratische Partei, trans- 
 lated by Bohn, W. E., p. 145. 
 
 126 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 127 
 
 Socialism hopes to accomplish this miracle in two ways, 
 namely first by augmenting the national aggregate of 
 goods, and secondly by changing the ratio in which neces- 
 sities and luxuries are now commonly turned out. The 
 first is no doubt the more important step in the long run, 
 but the second could be attempted at shorter notice. 
 And it deserves mention again that this change is to con- 
 cern, not the monetary values in which we now measure 
 wealth, but the latter itself, that is the amount by weight 
 or volume of the goods that enter into the market. Let 
 the tons or quarts or cubic feet of consumables be doubled 
 or tripled, that is the proposition before us. 
 
 We may introduce the nature of this problem by making 
 a distinction between consumables and non-consumables 
 which also figure in the national dividend. 
 
 People have often referred to the income, in dollars 
 and cents, of the American nation, with the idea of show- 
 ing how the average man would fare if the principle of 
 equality were applied. It has been pointed out that, on 
 such a basis, the laborer would have perhaps twice as 
 much as he enjoys to-day. If the total national income 
 in 1918, for instance, amounted to $75,000,000,000 and 
 we assume a population of one hundred million, then the 
 per capita income averaged $750. For a family of five 
 that would mean $3,750, a sum certainly not earned by 
 most families, though enormously below what the richest 
 can boast of. 
 
 Such a view, however, is from the very outset mislead- 
 ing because a nation's total annual output of goods is not 
 so to be divided. There are three kinds of funds to be 
 taken into consideration, only one of which becomes avail- 
 able for personal use. ^PfeeJIcstJs the fund needed to re- 
 place capital goods worn out in the process of production, 
 or otherwise subject to deterioration. The second is our 
 
128 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 savings fund which normally swells our national wealth 
 and makes industrial growth as well as a rising level of 
 living, that is a rising fund of consumables, possible. 
 Ajid the third onljk. namely the consumables just alluded 
 to, constitute the real income which people have in mind 
 when wishing for greater riches. A loaf of bread is part 
 of my consumables. The service rendered by actors 
 whose art I see displayed on the moving picture screen 
 is another such item of income for personal use. Many 
 properties held by governments, though used collectively, 
 serve the same purpose. 
 
 But the replacing of capital used in the production of 
 consumables does not gratify me in the same sense, nor 
 is the surplus devoted to the enlargement of capital a 
 genuine part of my income. They are merely means to 
 an end which, at last analysis, is national development. 
 The relative size of the shares varies with the economic 
 resources of the country, with its stage of economic de- 
 velopment, growth of population, habits of living, etc. 
 A land richly endowed with resources can evidently main- 
 tain a high level of living and yet set aside a large sur- 
 plus. A country poor in resources may save a relatively 
 large portion of the total income by consuming little. 
 Frugal habits may lead either to a rapidly growing popu- 
 lation, or to the accumulation of an investment fund 
 which may be placed either abroad or at home. If re- 
 sources are lacking it is not likely that the surplus will 
 be large, nor that it finds employment at home. In gen- 
 eral the surplus is the larger the greater the total na- 
 tional income, and the replacement fund will grow of 
 course more or less proportionate to the growth of in- 
 vestments. In " young " countries where resources are 
 plentiful and labor scarce the level of living will be high 
 if reckoned by foodstuffs, but low by other standards. 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 129 
 
 Capital will be imported, that is machinery and ideas will 
 be bought at a high interest rate. The interest will be 
 paid in rawstuffs and rights to natural resources, or the 
 payment will be postponed until suitable consumption 
 goods can be added to the export of raw materials. In 
 such countries the investment fund will grow more rapidly 
 than the flow of consumers' goods, while advanced stages 
 of economic development usually mean a relatively large 
 fundof consumption goods. Legislation, however, may 
 regulate the ratios somewhat so as to promote the in- 
 terests of the largest number. It is possible to neglect 
 the cultivation of the soil in an endeavor to multiply in- 
 dustrial goods or personal services. In the United States 
 the recent trend has been toward a rapid industrializa- 
 tion of capital. The farmer received probably less than 
 his share. The consumer consequently could not keep 
 as good a table as formerly, though he gained in other 
 directions. It is for the government or the individual 
 to decide which is th^moye preferable/ cheap food or a 
 variety of industrial goods ancTbT services. 
 
 Socialism will no doubt decide in favor of foods before 
 investing heavily in the industries. The aim of socialists 
 is to raisethe income of the poor. If then to return 
 to our little problem we must deduct some fifteen bil- 
 lion dollars a year for replacing worn out capital and 
 expanding business we get instead of $750 per capita 
 only $600 annually in consumables. To raise this, so 
 that the masses will have what ten per cent, now get, 
 means not only to increase the national aggregate, but . 
 jajsojbochange tne ratios of investment, replacements, and 
 consumption Tunds irT" some measure. This socialism 
 hopes to do. It will try to better conditions by substitut- 
 ing necessities for luxuries as well as by adding to the 
 total. 
 
130 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 2. What Determines National Income Now pro- 
 duction depends on three factors, namely, on natural re- 
 sources, labor-supply, and efficiency. It is by whatever 
 changes will occur in these factors that socialism will bring 
 about the betterment of income. If it can add to our re- 
 sources, if it can increase the stock of labor-power either 
 by adding to the number of workers or by lengthening the 
 work-day, and if in the third place it can make men more 
 proficient, whether as individuals or as cogs in a great in- 
 dustrial machine, then its promises of a higher level of 
 living may be fulfilled. If not, the promises can mean 
 nothing. 
 
 The answer to our question is not, however, easily 
 given, for the data at hand are extremely limited and not 
 always reliable. It is only with reference to the labor 
 supply that our information is approximately correct. 
 Possible gains or losses in social efficiency cannot be de- 
 duced directly from statistics on education or health or 
 socialistic programs, and the effect of socialism on natural 
 resources can be stated only negatively. 
 
 It is certain that socialism cannot produce natural re- 
 sources. It can only look for them and then use them. 
 But since socialists have not claimed a greater ability in 
 locating resources than our experts possess now the chief 
 question is that of using them. 
 
 The producer distinguishes between physically existent 
 resources and those he can exploit at prevailing prices. 
 He will not work a mine if the vein is too thin or the ore 
 of low yield. He will keep his property but wait for 
 rising prices. When demand has increased and prices 
 rise faster than expenses he is likely to reach for his 
 reserve stocks. He will work less rich tracts of land or 
 deposits of coal and ore if he has to, provided his own 
 profits are not diminished materially. This principle of 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 131 
 
 diminishing returns governs all production and is re- 
 spected by socialists. 
 
 On the other hand they urge that much land and other 
 riches are withheld that should be used now. They argue 
 that to increase these stores is part of their program, and 
 that they will enlarge our resources in the sense that they 
 will not wait for profits as the capitalist undoubtedly 
 does. Let us grant the proposition and add temporarily 
 ten per cent, to our productive power by this route. Yet 
 it deserves noting that the gain will be only temporary. 
 For competitive principles will make an end of specula- 
 tive reservations sooner or later. In Europe the idea of 
 ^ waste through disuse could hardly come in question. In 
 thlPTJmtect states, indeed 'throughout the world, the 
 tendency is steadily toward exploitation of what is in 
 sight. Either, therefore, the gain has been of brief dura- 
 tion or we face the still less pleasant fact that we may 
 hasten development unnecessarily. 
 
 Socialism deals with long stretches of time. It is not 
 interested merely in the immediate future. It will not 
 care, therefore, to raise our level of living by working 
 resources at maximum speed, if as a result of this policy 
 the stock is exhausted the sooner. Yet this has happened 
 before, and may happen again. The world's mineral 
 stocks, notably, are only theoretically inexhaustible. 
 They appear endless when they are not. It is not ad- 
 visable to use them up prodigally when we know that they 
 are unreplaceable. Substitutes cannot always be found. 
 The depletion of our natural stores is a piece of folly 
 that no one will encourage, socialists least of all. To 
 have a nation grow rapidly is a questionable advantage, 
 since the law of decreasing returns obtains everywhere. 
 It is possible to develop power and prestige at the expense 
 of posterity. To skim from the top has been a tempta- 
 
132 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 tion for many settlers of virgin lands with riches beck- 
 oning on all sides, but ere long the exploiting nation pays 
 the penalty. Socialism, precisely because it sees far 
 ahead, will discountenance ruthless exploitation and will 
 husband our resource?. 
 
 A gain in natural resources is therefore not well pos- 
 sible. If income is to be raised 4t-.will be by. changes jn 
 labor supply and its efficiency. 
 
 | 3. Effects of Age Distribution on Production. But 
 before passing to a consideration of such changes in the 
 amount of labor-power which socialism may bring about, 
 let us see what important features of population social- 
 ism cannot directly, nor perhaps indirectly, affect. It 
 will teach us to appreciate the uncontrollable factor in 
 population, while otherwise we might exaggerate the 
 powers of socialism. 
 
 Different populations show very different distributions 
 of age, and this is important because not all ages are 
 equally productive. Rather, we may divide life into sev- 
 eral periods according to their economic productiveness. 
 The first ten years, e. g., represent a clear loss, for at this 
 time the child consumes without producing anything. In 
 the second period, say from the tenth to the twentieth 
 year, it begins to produce, but less than it consumes. 
 There are of course exceptions, and besides it is difficult 
 to rate productivity as soon as we refer to values-in-ex- 
 change. But roughly a balance between income and out- 
 go, between what is produced and what is consumed, may 
 be struck. Let us then call the third period from twenty 
 to sixty or seventy years the most valuable for the nation. 
 In these years the average man produces more than he 
 consumes, and certainly much more than the biologically 
 necessary things. He raises his income by raising his 
 productiveness. It is the time of rearing children and 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 
 
 laying aside savings for a rainy day. Production some- 
 where between thirty and sixty years of age is at top- 
 notch. After the sixtieth or seventieth year we note a 
 
 TABLE Two 
 
 AGE DISTRIBUTION IK THE POPULATION OF DIFFERENT COUNTRIES IN 
 
 1910 
 
 (Distribution in Percentages of the Total Population) 
 Countries 
 
 
 
 
 Ger- 
 
 Austra- United 
 
 Age Periods 
 
 U.S.A. 
 
 France 
 
 many 
 
 Austria 
 
 lia 
 
 Kingdom 
 
 1-10 Years 
 
 . . .22.2% 
 
 17.2% 
 
 23.1% 
 
 26.3% 
 
 41.1% 
 
 20.7% 
 
 10-20 Years 
 
 ...19.8% 
 
 16.6% 
 
 20.3% 
 
 20 % 
 
 
 19 % 
 
 20-30 Years 
 
 .7. 18.7% 
 
 15.9% 
 
 16.3% 
 
 15.4% 
 
 32 % 
 
 8.9% 
 
 30-40 Years 
 
 .,,,14.6% 
 
 14.8% 
 
 15.2% 
 
 12.6% 
 
 
 16.1% 
 
 40-50 Years 
 
 ...10.6% 
 
 13.6% 
 
 10.2% 
 
 10.5% 
 
 18.8% 
 
 13.3% 
 
 50-60 Years 
 
 ... 7.2% 
 
 10.5% 
 
 7.7% 
 
 7.7% 
 
 
 9.7% 
 
 Over Sixty 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 Years 
 
 69% 
 
 12.4% 
 
 7.2% 
 
 7.5% 
 
 7.7% 
 
 6.4% 
 
 
 
 Total Population "'// 
 
 in Millions 
 
 ...92 
 
 39.2 
 
 65 
 
 28.5 
 
 4.45 
 
 45.4 
 
 Note: Age-Periods for the United Kingdom are the following: 
 One to Ten Years; Ten to Twenty Years; Twenty to Twenty-Five 
 Years; Twenty-Five to Thirty-Five Years; Thirty-Five to Forty- 
 Five Years; Forty-Five to Fifty- Five Years; Fifty-Five to Sixty- 
 Five Years; Over Sixty-Five Years. 
 
 Reference: Statistical Yearbooks of United States, France, Ger- 
 many, Austria, Australia, United Kingdom. 
 
 decline. The curve of productiveness falls visibly. Man 
 once more becomes a deficit producer and eventually de- 
 pends entirely upon others for his living. But consump- 
 tion of course drops off also. 
 
 Now Table Two is designed to show some striking dif- 
 ferences between such powers as the United States and 
 Germany, and smaller nations like France or Austria 
 on the other hand. The size of the population is not 
 however the point in question. Rather, it is the effect 
 
134 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 of net birth-rates and of migration. It will be noted that 
 the first two nations mentioned boast a large percentage 
 of young ages, while their proportion of advanced ages 
 is relatively small. In the United States immigration was 
 always a dominant factor. In Germany the natural in- 
 crease counts most up to 1900, and after that decreas- 
 ingly so, while immigration increases. The period of 
 twenty to forty years is well represented in both countries. 
 Labor is cheap relative to resources, and there's enough 
 to make rapid internal development possible. /Powers 
 grow great and rich when the demographic pyramid 
 bulges at the bottom and is contracted at the top, for then 
 the surplus producers or, from a given time standpoint, 
 the prospective surplus producers provide an ample in- 
 vestment funcT) The condition of France and Austria 
 is serious. France suffered most through a decline of the 
 birth-rate; Austria through emigration. Her best men 
 left in the prime of manhood. No nation can easily off- 
 set such a drain. 
 
 There is no need of developing further this point. The 
 differences of age distribution are sufficiently wellknown, 
 but they are recalled here as significant by comparison 
 with such changes in the labor-supply as socialism may 
 at will bring about. The factors not so controllable in- 
 fluence the supply at least as much, and possibly more. 
 
 | 4. Possible Increase of the Labor Supply. The 
 possibilities of socialistic readjustment are tabulated in 
 Table Three. The estimate is of course only a rough one, 
 for statistics are not always on a strictly comparative 
 basis. There is plenty of room for error. Classifica- 
 tions do not correspond exactly, and the statistical serv- 
 ice is not for all countries equally reliable and complete. 
 But so far as the numerical changes in the labor supply 
 are concerned the appended table is suggestive. It shows 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 
 
 135 
 
 TABLE THREE 
 
 Possible Changes in the Labor Supply of the United 
 
 States for the Year 1910, according to Socialistic 
 
 Standards 
 
 (References: Thirteenth Census of the United States, Census 
 Bureau, Volumes on Population and on Occupations.) 
 
 A. NUMBER OF GAINFULLY OCCUPIED AND NON-OCCUPIED IN 1910 
 (Millions omitted) 
 
 Total population 92 
 
 Gainfully occupied 38.2 
 
 Not gainfully occupied 53.8 
 
 Of these were: 
 
 Married women 16.1 
 
 Children under 20 years 31.2 
 
 Females over 65 years 2.1 
 
 Males over 70 years 1.1 
 
 Youths attending school 
 over 20 years of age 0.6^ 
 
 Widows under 65 years 1.6 
 
 Inmates of benevolent in- 
 stitutions 0.6 
 
 Inmates of prisons 0.1 
 
 Idle rich, etc 0.4 
 
 after deduction 
 occupied. 
 
 of gainfully 
 
 B. CHANGES IN LABOR SUPPLY CONFORMING TO SOCIALISTIC 
 STANDARDS 
 
 (Millions omitted) 
 
 Losses 
 
 1. Abolition of work for 
 children under 20. 
 (Count their efficiency 
 at one-half) 3.7 
 
 2. Pensions for all over 60. 
 (Count four-fifths of all 
 males, and one-half of 
 females over 60 as gain- 
 fully occupied in 1910) . 4.1 
 
 Gains 
 
 1. Industrial employment 
 of married women un- 
 der 60 years of age. 
 (Count their present ef- 
 ficiency as two-thirds 
 that developed under 
 socialism) 4.8 
 
 2. Employment of all be- 
 tween 20 and 60 years 
 of age not gainfully oc- 
 cupied in 1910 (except- 
 ing disabled, etc.) 2.1 
 
136 
 
 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 Losses 
 
 Gross loss 7.8 
 
 In per cent, of gainfully 
 
 occupied 20.4% 
 
 3. Loss through reduction 
 of work hours per 
 week 20 % 
 
 Total gross loss in per- 
 centages 40.4% 
 
 Gains 
 
 3. Reduction of involun- 
 tary unemployment, ex- 
 cept through illness .... 0.6 
 
 Gross gain 7.5 
 
 In per cent, of gainfully 
 
 occupied 19.6% 
 
 4. Gain through educa- 
 tional extension, etc., 
 say 25 % 
 
 Total gross gain 44.6% 
 
 Deducting gross loss. .40.4% 
 
 Net gain 
 
 Allow for errors, giving so- 
 cialism the benefit of 
 the doubt . ..10 
 
 Final net gain possible 14.2% 
 
 that more than a ten or fifteen per cent, gain, even when 
 we speculate on the effects of education, should not be ex- 
 pected by socialists. The losses incident to the introduc- 
 tion of socialistic ideals almost counterbalance the gains. 
 
 If we figure the possible gains and losses for the United 
 States on the basis of occupation statistics for 1910 the 
 account would run about as follows. 
 
 The population of the United States in 1910 was 
 ninety-two million. Of these slightly over thirty-eight 
 million were gainfully occupied. That is, they supported 
 themselves entirely or mainly by their own earnings, the 
 remainder of the population depending upon them for a 
 living. The majority thus was not gainfully occupied 
 officially, though many of them doubtless helped to pro- 
 duce values sold in the open market. In addition, we 
 note, there were nearly eighteen million married women 
 exclusively of those gainfully occupied, plus the following 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 137 
 
 non-producers who earned neither money nor otherwise 
 contributed directly to the nation's fund of utilities. 
 Namely, we have first all children under twenty years of 
 age, of whom there were thirty million ; secondly the aged 
 who account for three million, third, young men and 
 women attending educational institutions, fourth, widows 
 not gainfully occupied but less than sixty-five years of 
 age, and finally such other groups as criminals, cripples, 
 and the idle rich. The classification will point out which 
 of these several classes are available for industrial em- 
 ployment, and which are not. 
 
 Socialism hopes to gain most by industrializing the 
 work of women. ^The abolition of the home is understood. 
 by_most socialists in this sense. It is not that they wish 
 to break up"fne personal relation between the married and 
 their offspring, but that they advocate the consolidation 
 of homes into larger units of social life, or if not that, the 
 "conversion of individual work into team work so that un- 
 necessary duplication and waste may be minimized. It is 
 difficult to decide just what socialists propose to do, as 
 current events in Russia show. But it seems best to grant 
 socialists a gain of one-third by their new methods of 
 utilizingjemale labor. The question of home ties and 
 legal relations may then be ignored entirely. It will be 
 noted however that the gain refers only to women not now 
 industrially employed, and then only to those under sixty 
 years of age*_ - 
 
 This second restriction of age follows from the social- 
 istic norm of leisure. An organic law of the Russian- 
 Socialist Federal Soviet Republic, e. g., has classified men 
 nypr sivfy .nrl wrnnpn nvpr fifty years of ape as unable 
 
 jo work., [Jo these age groups it grants a pension, and 
 
 expects no work except it be voluntarily done which it 
 doubtless often is. It seems not unreasonable to figure 
 
138 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 on a loss, therefore, in our calculation of all over sixty 
 who are now gainfully occupied or working as wives and 
 mothers. If we count them as normally efficient this 
 means a loss of over four million workers. 
 
 But to return to the sources of gain. There is in the 
 second place, the employment under socialism of all be- 
 tween twenty and sixty years of age on our supposi- 
 tion that pensions begin with the sixtieth year. No 
 professional loafers will be tolerated. Wealth will be 
 no excuse for idleness, and aversion to work no passport 
 for tramps. A great many widows under sixty years 
 of age that now live on their income will go to work, too ; 
 and perhaps some of those now attending school will not 
 do so after socialism has improved the lower school system. 
 The total gain thus will amount to over two million, as 
 indicated in the Table. 
 
 But this~is" not all. In the third place unemployment 
 may be materially reduced. In 1910 about one-half mil- 
 lion men and women were out of work throughout the 
 year. In some years the loss is still greater, in others 
 much smaller. It is a debatable point indeed whether 
 socialism will improve the productive organization enough 
 to eliminate all this waste. Not many will agree that 
 it can be done. But in order to make the argument as 
 strong as possible we may for the moment grant the ad- 
 justment of supply to demand in goods and labor that 
 socialists demand. An improvement is certainly desir- 
 able, and, what is more to the point, seems practicable. 
 
 This leaves us, in the fourth plaej L _a__gain_diie_to edu- 
 cation. In allowing for this change we are passing from 
 purely quantitative to qualitative aspects of the labor- 
 supply. It is not certain that any kind of estimate is 
 worth while, since efficiency depends on so much else be- 
 sides technical training. But as a rule an advancement of 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 
 
 learning must be held to have perceptible effects. The 
 gain should be real, and in excess of what prevailing con- 
 ditions will lead to. Hence a 25% addition to the gains 
 already registered is proposed in the Table. 
 
 If now we turn to the loss we have first the effect of 
 protection for old age, which was referred to above, and 
 secondly the shrinkage of labor-power due to a prohibi- 
 tion of child labor. One of the most fundamental assets 
 of the socialistic doctrine is its educational program. 
 Knowledge is to be popularized and made free. The 
 average man will have a chance to learn and think as he 
 has not had heretofore. Technical instruction and a lib- 
 eral education in the arts and social inquiries will develop 
 the mind, .while recreation and hygiene will develop the 
 body. ( Without education leisure means little, and with- 
 out leisure education is impossible. The abolition of child 
 labor has thus several motivesr~Ji looks to the intel- 
 lectual uplift of the masses, and it aims at health and 
 vigor. The dissemination of knowledge is only to be ac- 
 companied by a greater regard for physical welfare. 
 
 Just at what age industrial employment is to begin we 
 cannot tell. It has been urged that all youths should 
 have a college education, in which case the period of 
 leisure would have to be extended to the twenty-second 
 year. Others have been content to stop at fifteen. But 
 in as much as the present common school education is 
 found so woefully wanting by all parties, even though it 
 includes eight years of training^jt seems proper to credit 
 the socialistic scheme with an extension of schooling at 
 least up to the twentieth yearT) The less it approaches 
 this goal the weaker its argument, and the smaller of 
 course the gain in productiveness which we have already 
 put on the right side of the ledger. 
 
 If then we combine these two reductions in labor sup- 
 
140 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 ply we have a total of seven million eight hundred thou- 
 sand, against which must be set a gain of seven million 
 five hundred thousand. This leaves a net preliminary loss 
 of three hundred thousand workers. However, the gain 
 in efficiency, which was rated at 25%, more than counter- 
 balances it. A loss of three hundred thousand workers 
 equals not quite one per cent, of the total number of gain- 
 fully occupied who, it will be remembered, made up about 
 thirty-eight million out of a total population of ninety- 
 two million. Deduct this loss of 0.8% from a gain of 
 25% and you obtain an apparent net gain of 24.2%. 
 
 But the gain is apparent only. For in the third place 
 socialism loses by curtailing the number of work-hours 
 per day, week, and year. In 1918 the standard day had 
 about eight hours. Yet many millions worked ten hours 
 a day or over. In 1910 the eight hour schedule was still 
 the exception rather than the rule. Under socialism it 
 may be the rule at first, but the avowed intention of all 
 socialists is the reduction of labor-hours proportionate to 
 technical advance. The more machinery displaces the 
 hand, and the greater the output of goods per hour or 
 month, the shorter the work day. This is the slogan 
 with which socialists fight. It is logical in a way, and 
 should serve to benefit the carefree masses./ But the loss 
 counts and means a shrinkage of goods, that is, not an 
 absolute shrinkage, but one relative to maximum possi- 
 bilities, or to what is now being done. -If we take an 
 average weekly schedule of fifty hours, and clip off one- 
 fifth, we lose in commodities what we gain in freedom. 
 Socialism is willing apparently to reckon with six or seven 
 hours of work a day, and so our deduction of 20% is 
 Ifair. 
 
 We conclude then that nominally the gain in labor- 
 power is less than 5%. However, as remarked, there is 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 141 
 
 no need of sticking too closely to our figures, since there 
 is so much chance for error. Let us, therefore, return 
 to our first announced gain of ten to fifteen per cent., 
 which would be a maximum compatible with the ideals of 
 socialism. More than that it cannot look forward to 
 without becoming untrue to its own professions. 
 
 | 5. Possible Economy in Technical Organization. 
 There remain thus for brief consideration two other sets 
 of facts, namely, first the continuance of disagreeable 
 types of labor, and secondly certain savings due to or- 
 ganization such as socialism hopes to perfect. 
 
 Irksome and dirty work will always have to be done, 
 for as fast as machines in one place relieve men of it, 
 needs in another place reintroduce it. It is likely that 
 in the future occupational diseases and accidents will al- 
 most entirely disappear. Science increasingly finds means 
 for protecting the laborer against the poisons amidst 
 which he plies his trade. Safety devices will be multi- 
 plied and employees properly taught the use of machines. 
 Ignorance, carelessness, and fatigue have been found to 
 be the most common sources of fatal accidents. Social- 
 ism is no doubt right if it claims that the perils of work 
 can be largely eliminated by right precautionary 
 measures. But this is not doing away with crude labor 
 as such. 
 
 Disagreeable labor will always have to be done because 
 man's wants are never completely satisfied. There's 
 always something to attend to, to invent and to produce. 
 As fast as men are displaced by one machine they find 
 employment in some other quarter. Crude labor means 
 energy, and a certain amount of human muscular energy 
 is an indispensable part of the productive organization. 
 The ratio between rough work and the more refined, be- 
 tween manual labor and machino-facture, technical 
 
THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 progress cannot materially change. In the Census 
 figures for 1910 crude labor is just about as prominent 
 numerically as twenty or thirty years earlier. There is 
 no perceptible decline of unskilled occupations or of hard 
 work in the building trades, in engineering, mining and 
 farming. Machines liberate labor for less essential uses, 
 but they do not end cheerless toil. If socialism then 
 
 TABLE FOUR 
 Industries With Small-Scale Production (U. ., 1910) 
 
 Per cent, of Wage-Earners 
 in Establishments Employing 
 
 Industries No Wage-Earners, or 
 
 Less than Twenty (20) 
 
 Bakery products 75% 
 
 Butter, cheese, and milk 80% 
 
 Canning and preserving 31% 
 
 Carriage and wagons 40% 
 
 Cooperage 31% 
 
 Flour mill products 82% 
 
 Unspecified food preparations 40% 
 
 Fur goods 57% 
 
 Manufactured ice 65% 
 
 Leather goods 32% 
 
 Marble works 34% 
 
 Mattresses and beds 43% 
 
 Mineral and soda waters 99% 
 
 Cottonseed oil 34% 
 
 Patent medicines 62% 
 
 Printing 58% 
 
 Tobacco manufactures 52% 
 
 Carved wood 45% 
 
 Reference: Thirteenth Census, 1910, V. 8, Manufactures, P. 186, 
 U. S. Bureau of Census. 
 
 wishes to relieve the masses in this respect, it will have to 
 alternate types of work for given individuals, or else take 
 the sting out of the most dreaded kinds of labor by pay- 
 ing extra wages. 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 143 
 
 This would of course mean some impairment of social 
 efficiency, but it might be worth while nonetheless. Be- 
 sides, there is some room for economy in another field, 
 namely in the organization of capital and labor forces. 
 Socialists commonly dwell on this possibility and point to 
 the immense loss now incurred by the public due to over- 
 production, to unnecessary duplication of plant, small- 
 scale output, and extravagance in the use of machinery 
 as well as of consumption goods. 
 
 The first kind of waste is of course attributed to the 
 lack of correlation between demand and supply, and is 
 therefore a distributive problem which connects closely 
 with the problem of income, of which more hereafter. 
 
 Waste through useless duplication of effort and wealth 
 results naturally from the individualistic principle and 
 cannot be altogether avoided until the entire nation is 
 treated as one market for one single producer, the gov- 
 ernment acting on behalf of the people. At the present 
 an enterpriser is chiefly influenced by personal consid- 
 erations. He will be willing to invest funds if they 
 promise returns, even though the waste for the consuming 
 public is perfectly apparent. Railroads, telephones, 
 street car lines, ships and pikes, factories and office 
 buildings have been needlessly duplicated in this manner. 
 I The waste occasionally has raised a storm of protest, but 
 1 usually the charge upon the consumer has been borne with 
 V^equanimity, as a sort of toll levied by Dame Liberty^; 
 
 Socialism proposes to substitute a collectivistic prin- 
 ciple for the competitive, and thus to end the drain on 
 national resources that selfish duplication entails. It 
 hopes to effect a noticeable saving by a better disposition 
 of labor forces, and it seems reasonable to grant it all 
 the credit that such a change may give the consumer. 
 The policy of consolidation, however, not merely leads 
 
144 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 to a reduction of waste, it also is believed by some to lower 
 costs on the principle that rates of return rise with in- 
 crease of the scale of production. 
 
 In the United States in 1910 there were still a good 
 many industries in which the number of .employees per 
 plant was less than twenty. Indeed, in many of them it 
 was less than ten. Table Four shows typical instances of 
 such small scale production. Three quarters of the 
 bakeries, it will be seen, employed less than twenty work- 
 ers. In the soda water production the percentage is 
 highest, and creameries come next. Goods in these in- 
 dustries may be said to be produced on a small scale, but 
 whether this means waste is another question. It is 
 probable that the manufacturer has adjusted himself to 
 the competitive conditions surrounding him and either 
 cannot extend his business greatly, or else is tending in 
 that direction without our noticing it at once. A bakery, 
 for instance, is no longer a one-man affair. Machines 
 have largely displaced manual labor. Some concerns sup- 
 ply many thousands of customers each day. The man 
 who once had only one or two apprentices now employs 
 ten or fifteen, installing machinery which gives him the 
 largest return in profits. He has enlarged his scale of 
 production, but it seems small compared to the methods 
 used in iron and steel, or in mining. 
 
 The general answer is, however, the old one. Namely, 
 fine work will always be in demand. There are crafts 
 that call for high personal skill, individuality, and ex- 
 treme care in workmanship. For such products large- 
 scale production is out of the question. Their existence 
 is simply evidence of wealth and high prices paid for 
 special quality. Socialism will make an end, possibly, 
 of some of these industries, but this gain of labor-power 
 for uses elsewhere is a detail. 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 145 
 
 On the other hand, if scrapping of machinery and of 
 labor which now is carried on extravagantly can be 
 stopped by collectivistic norms of valuation, a notable 
 saving will be effected. It has been freely admitted by 
 magnates of business that the competitive struggle in- 
 volves a large waste through rapid obsolescence of capital 
 goods. A slight improvement may lead to the abandon- 
 ment of an old process and of the tools going with it. 
 The fear of a competitor who may himself introduce im- 
 provements at any cost to win the market is a factor de- 
 ciding the issue. It is not the cheapening of production 
 that counts, but the difference in sales resulting from any 
 degree of cheapening. If the machine means only a five 
 per cent, saving in " socially necessary labor," to use 
 Marx's expression, the old machine will not be scrapped 
 on socialistic principles. But if between competitors a 
 five per cent, cost reduction means the difference of hold- 
 ing or losing a market the new machine will be installed 
 regardless of what society loses by the substitution. 
 Capitalism not only tolerates but encourages fads and 
 fashions, the discarding of the old, and the frequent re- 
 newal of both production and consumption goods. It is 
 not for most people a question of wearing out apparel, 
 but of being in style. The adventitious values of fashion 
 and elegance which human nature makes possible and 
 social organization has assiduously cultivated for ulterior 
 motives, these values move us to spend our money when 
 we know we shouldn't. Utility is no longer primary, but 
 secondary. We wear clothes not to be warm and com- 
 fortable, but to look well or at any rate look up to date. 
 Waste is not illogically taken to be circumstantial evi- 
 dence of wealth. We may fool our good friends and 
 really have less than they are led to believe, but the im- 
 pression we make repays us for our reckless outlays. 
 
146 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 Socialism may put a curb to this sort of display and 
 waste. Of course, it would be hard to decide whether, 
 for one thing, it can be done, and for another thing, 
 whether the saving would mount up sufficiently, but it is 
 well to grant socialism a gain of labor-power on this 
 score. 
 
 6. Possible Recomposition of the National Income. 
 Savings of this kind however bring us to the second 
 means of a general character for raising the incomes of 
 the masses. The first, we noted, was an increase of labor, 
 natural resources, or of efficiency tested per individual or 
 socially. By these methods we have found an increase of 
 ten or fifteen per cent, in wages to be made possible. But 
 since this is not enough a change in the composition of the 
 national output of goods will have to accompany a change 
 in volume. If we can get rid of all useless types of labor 
 which do not cater to the average wage earner, and con- 
 vert this energy into more generally useful services, then 
 the gain will be real, even though a few rich people are 
 hard hit. 
 
 The extent of this change in the ratio of necessities and 
 luxuries may be gauged in several ways. We may con- 
 sult first, the distribution of income, secondly the statistics 
 on manufactures in which many of the luxuries appear, 
 and thirdly the occupation statistics in which may be 
 found most of the services figuring in large incomes. 
 
 Table Five will serve to indicate the main facts of 
 distribution for 1910. It will be noticed that it is quite 
 unequal, the great majority having less than $1000 a 
 year, while a few boast an income of several millions. 
 Forty per cent of all the families in the United States 
 had less than $700 annually, seven-tenths had not over 
 $1000, and only about ten per cent, had in excess of 
 $1500. Yet the national income at that time was about 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 
 
 147 
 
 $32,000,000,000, of which probably some twenty-five 
 billion represented consumable goods for personal use. 
 The remainder consisted of capital goods. If then we 
 divide this smaller sum of $25,000,000,000 by a popula- 
 
 TABLE FIVE 
 
 The Distribution of Incomes in the United States 
 in 1910 
 
 (Estimates of Dr. W. I. King, in his " Wealth and Income of the 
 People of the United States," pages 224-228.) 
 
 Cumulative Number of Cumulative Amount 
 Family Income Income-receiving Units, of Income, in 
 
 of not over in Thousands Millions of Dollars 
 
 $700 
 $1,000 
 $1,200 
 $1,500 
 
 $4,000 
 
 $5,200 
 
 $10,000 
 
 $100,000 
 
 $1,000,000 
 
 Family Income 
 
 of not over 
 
 $700 
 
 $1,000 
 
 $1,500 
 
 $2,400 
 
 10,878 5,807 
 
 19,402 12,969 
 
 22,830 16,703 
 
 25,243 19,867 
 
 27,016 33,158 
 
 27,496 24,660 
 
 27,644 25,326 
 
 27,818 26,514 
 
 37,941.6 29,521 
 
 27,945 30,038 
 
 Grand Total 27,945.2 30,529 
 
 THE DISTRIBUTION IN PERCENTAGES 
 
 Cumulative Percentage 
 Cumulative Percentage of Total Income 
 of Families Having Received by Given 
 Given Income Class of Families 
 
 19.02$, 
 42.48% 
 
 90.31% 
 96.18% 
 
 74.71% 
 
 tion of ninety-two million we obtain a per capita income 
 of approximately $270. Multiply this by five, and the 
 average family would have an income of $1350. This 
 might, according to socialistic standards, be called the 
 
148 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 normal income at that date. The standard of living is 
 not fixed rigidly any more by socialists than by econo- 
 mists. It varies with time and place, and above all it 
 varies with the productiveness of the nation. There is an 
 objective standard set by the requirements of physical 
 and mental vigor, and a subjective one kept in mind by 
 the individual. Socialism may consider that income nor- 
 mal which at any time embraces the largest class of con- 
 sumers. In that case $1000 annually would be more 
 nearly the goal to steer for than $1350. But it is cer- 
 tain that socialists aim at a marked improvement of the 
 general mode of living. Their ambitions are well known. 
 The quantitative aspect of this desire for betterment will 
 doubtless involve a thorough revision of family budgets. 
 A reapportioning of goods and services will take place, 
 so that all families have the luxuries now (1910) enjoyed 
 by those with $1500 a year or more. 
 
 Four-fifths of the American people in 1910 had not 
 over $1200 income. Luxuries for them were but a small 
 part of their budget. It is indeed doubtful whether at 
 the purchasing power of money for 1910 a family with 
 a hundred dollars a month could have spent more than 
 five per cent, on luxuries. But the other fifth of the 
 population had so much the more. The great bulk of its 
 expenses consisted, according to our definition of a 
 standard of living at that time, of luxuries. Thus, i 
 we make due allowance for what the rich spend in the 
 purchase of necessities, we have about one-fifth of the 
 national income represented by luxuries. It is this fifth 
 which socialism will turn over to the poor. Or rather 
 it is the labor and capital required for producing these 
 luxuries that socialism will turn into other channels. 
 The output of necessities and comforts will increase, and 
 that of extreme luxuries will end. 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 149 
 
 The statistics on manufactures throw further light on 
 the matter. They do not, to be sure, contain all of the 
 luxuries consumed by the wealthy. A variety of things 
 for the use of which the rich are noted is not enumerated 
 by the census taker. There are magnificent mansions, for 
 instance, and golf links and racing stables and Pekingese 
 dogs, and rare viands and art works and pleasure yachts 
 and private Pullmans, and display-fountains and liveried 
 servants and curios and opera seats, fancy dress balls and 
 silver plate, and tiaras and mausoleums, none of which 
 will be found in the official records. Yet they figure in 
 the budgets of the plutocrats. 
 
 Again, it is impossible to tell from the official classifica- 
 tion whether an article is really a luxury or not. The 
 output of woolen mills, for instance, may be luxury or 
 necessity according to quality of the fabric. The choice 
 of tailor and of trimmings will further guide us in defining 
 the finished suit. It may either prove to be a high-class 
 luxury or if the material was made up in the sweatshop, 
 we may be able to buy the suit at such a low figure that 
 we refuse to class it among the luxuries. Shape and 
 style, finish and quality of ingredient, time and place of 
 purchase, these and other items decide whether the com- 
 modity is a necessity or not. 
 
 But even if the limitations of a statistical compilation 
 are glaring, the appended Table Six will have some use- 
 fulness. Whether we agree on all the articles or not, 
 the omitted items will probably somewhere near balance 
 those listed wrongly. Within ten or fifteen per cent, the 
 list of manufactured luxuries will agree with facts. With 
 this understanding it is instructive to note that 10 A% 
 of the aggregate of manufactures consisted of luxuries, 
 the production of which required !!.% of the total 
 labor-force, entrepreneurs and superintendents, etc., in- 
 
150 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 eluded. These figures apply to' the year 1914 when the 
 total national income was about thirty-five billion dollars. 
 In terms of that total, therefore, the luxuries amounted 
 to 7%, while the producing forces made up about 2.5% 
 of all gainfully occupied in that year. 
 
 Most of this material and energy can no doubt be 
 turned to better uses. Socialism has a large field to cul- 
 tivate, and great are the possibilities for reform by way 
 of a recomposition of our national budget. 
 
 It is possible, e. g., to build cottages with the product 
 of brickyards and quarries that now help to build palaces 
 and accessory edifices on the estates of the multi-million- 
 aire. It might even be possible to furnish every family 
 a decent apartment to live in, or a house and lot such as 
 the middle classes now point to with pride ! In 1910 there 
 were over twenty million families in the United States, of 
 which nearly eleven million rented their homes. It is dif- 
 ficult to get at the number of houses occupied by one 
 family or a single tenant because the Census Bureau 
 classed every sort of sleeping quarters as a dwelling, 
 while conversely every dwelling place figured as one fam- 
 ily. 2 Thus a single occupant of a tent or way-car or 
 boathouse was rated as a family, but so were all the 
 inmates of a hotel. They too were counted as one family. 
 Owing to such irresponsible procedure in classification 
 there is no direct way for finding out how many families 
 had an individual home of their own. However, it is 
 significant that only nine million out of twenty million 
 families owned the place they lived in. Judging from 
 that circumstance we can hardly count on more than one 
 dwelling house for every two families in the country. And 
 
 2 "Thirteenth Census of U. S.," Census Bureau, Volume 1, p. 
 1285. 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 
 
 151 
 
 TABLE Six 
 
 American Manufactures in 1914 Which Were Consumed 
 
 Chiefly by People Earning Over $1200 a Year 
 
 (Reference: U. S. Census Bureau, Manufactures in 1914.) 
 (Thousands omitted) 
 
 Number of Value of 
 Industry Persons Engaged Product 
 
 in Industry $ 
 
 Artificial flowers 9,300 19,000 
 
 Artists' materials 1,000 3,000 
 
 Automobile and parts 146,000 633,000 
 
 Fancy boxes 50,600 75,000 
 
 Carpets not rag carpets 33,000 69,000 
 
 Chocolate 5,000 36,000 
 
 Clocks and watches 35,000 34,000 
 
 Fancy articles, not elsewhere specified.... 13,300 25,000 
 
 Fireworks 1,500 2,300 
 
 Fur goods 15,200 46,400 
 
 Leather gloves 12,300 21,600 
 
 Haircloth and hairwork 2,300 5,700 
 
 Jewelry 46,000 119,000 
 
 Millinery and lace 54,000 114,000 
 
 Mineral waters 25,000 58,000 
 
 Motorcycles 7,700 22,000 
 
 Musical instruments 55,000 120,000 
 
 Fountain pens 5,200 7,500 
 
 Photographic apparatus 11,300 39,000 
 
 Rubber goods, not elsewhere specified 62,000 224,000 
 
 Silk goods 116,000 254,000 
 
 Silverware 18,400 38,200 
 
 Sporting goods 6,300 13,000 
 
 Stationery, n<ot elsewhere specified 9,000 32,000 
 
 Stationery and art goods 2,400 4,000 
 
 Toys and games 9,000 14,000 
 
 Upholstering materials 5,000 16,000 
 
 Washing machines 3,000 7,600 
 
 Carved woods 13,400 19,000 
 
 Woolen goods 170,000 395,000 
 
 Total here listed 930,000 2,516,000 
 
 Absolute total 8,265,000 24,200,000 
 
 Percentage of listed workers and values.. 11.2% 10.4% 
 
152 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 of these many live in crowded quarters, a few rooms to the 
 family with small regard for sanitation. 
 
 Considering all things it seems therefore best not to ex- 
 pect too much at once from a regrouping of concrete 
 commodities entering into the average family budget. 
 But there is more chance for doing away with useless types 
 of labor such as now cater mainly to the wealthy. The 
 producers of intangible goods, that is of personal serv- 
 ices, are alljoo numerous from the standpoint of the small 
 earner. Much energy might be liberated by shifting these 
 producers to new fields, by rearranging the ratios of dif- 
 ferent kinds of personal service now rendered. On social- 
 ist principles this change should certainly be strongly 
 urged. 
 
 Table Seven gives the main facts relating to this ques- 
 tion. It will be seen that in 1910 nearly two-fifths of the 
 people gainfully occupied were not producing concrete 
 goods, the majority figuring under the professions or as 
 traders, domestic servants. Out of a total of 38,000,000 
 the professional group teachers, lawyers, etc. ac- 
 counts for nearly 5%, the domestic and personal services 
 for more than 12%, and the personnel employed in trans- 
 portation and trade for another 20%. These are the 
 workers that did not produce food or clothing, but con- 
 sumed both in rendering a different sort of value. Some 
 of them of course were indispensable to the methods of 
 production and to the scale of production which made 
 food and clothing so plentiful. It would be folly to con- 
 sider the employment of all of them as unnecessary to the 
 production of tangible goods. Socialism does not assert 
 this, nor will any one expect socialism to abolish such 
 services altogether. 
 
 The chief task is a reduction of this number, so that 
 the army of farmers and manufacturers is increased. In 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 
 
 153 
 
 TABLE SEVEN 
 
 Number of Gainfully Occupied in the United States m 
 1910, to be Reduced or Eliminated Under Socialism 
 
 (Reference: United States Census on Occupations for 1910.) 
 A. THE GAINFULLY OCCUPIED IN SPECIFIED SERVICES 
 (Thousands omitted) 
 
 Engaged in Transportation 2,637 
 
 Trade 3,615 
 
 Public services 459 
 
 Professional services. 1,664 
 Domestic and per- 
 sonal services 3,772 
 
 Clerical occupations. 1,737 
 
 Note: This represents 
 labor not engaged di- 
 rectly in the Production 
 of concrete goods. 
 
 Total 13,884 
 
 B. ESTIMATED SAVINGS IN CERTAIN OCCUPATIONS 
 (Thousands omitted) 
 
 In Transportation 
 
 Carriage drivers 35 
 
 Chauffeurs 
 
 Garage keepers 
 
 Hostlers, etc , 
 
 46 
 
 5 
 
 63 
 
 Livery stables 35 
 
 Teamsters, etc 16 
 
 Railroad employees 1,247 
 
 Express, telegraph, etc 314 
 
 Others 322 
 
 Total 
 Estimate saving at 
 
 2,083 
 694 
 
 In Trade 
 
 Bankers ................. 56 
 
 Brokers of all kinds ...... 49 
 
 Store clerks, salespersons, 
 
 etc .................. 1,368 
 
 Commercial travelers ..... 164 
 
 Window-dressers, etc ..... 5 
 
 Deliverymen ............. 230 
 
 Floor walkers, etc ........ 21 
 
 Samplers, etc ............ 13 
 
 Insurance agents 98 
 
 Porters, etc 102 
 
 Newsboys 30 
 
 Employment office owners, 
 
 elevators, etc 22 
 
 Real estate agents 126 
 
 Retailers 1,195 
 
 Wholesalers 51 
 
 Canvassers, etc 105 
 
 Book-keepers, etc 487 
 
 Other clerks 720 
 
 Total 4,842 
 
 Estimate saving at % 
 
 In Public Services 
 Marshals, sheriffs, etc. . . . 
 
 Policemen 
 
 Soldiers, sailors 
 
 24 
 64 
 
 77 
 
 Total 163 
 
 Estimate saving at ^ 55 
 
154 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 In Professional Services 
 
 Lawyers, etc 115 Janitors and sextons 113 
 
 Notaries' 7 Hotelkeepers, etc 65 
 
 Keepers of charitable insti- Housekeepers (lodging, 
 
 tutions, etc 23 etc.) 189 
 
 Laborers, unspecified 53 
 
 Total 145 Personal servants 1,572 
 
 Estimate saving at % 100 Waiters, etc 188 
 
 Total 2,631 
 
 In Personal and Domestic Estimate saving at % 2,000 
 
 Services Total saving 6,075 
 
 Barbers, etc 195 All gainfully occupied in 
 
 Bartenders and barkeepers 231 1910 38,200 
 
 Elevator boys, etc 25 Per cent, of saving 15.9% 
 
 1910 about three-fifths of the population furnished all 
 the commodities. Whatever the entire population needed, 
 that was produced by 6%% of it. No more eloquent testi- 
 mony to the wealth of the United States and to the 
 efficiency of its people could be given. It is the result 
 of the same conditions that made it possible for twelve 
 million farmers and farm-laborers to feed the remaining 
 eighty-five million, besides having something left for ex- 
 portation. A rich country will naturally add many per- 
 sonal services to its fund of concrete consumables. The 
 trend toward non-necessities is thus illustrated, and no 
 one would wish a return to the costlier system of the 
 " simple life." 
 
 Yet it is plain that a notable portion of this intangible 
 wealth benefits only a very few, and that much of it is 
 either quite useless, or outright injurious and demoraliz- 
 ing for the general run of people. It is not well that so 
 much energy is wasted in the rendering of trivial serv- 
 ices. Hundreds of thousands of domestic servants are not 
 needed, especially among those who employ them in large 
 numbers. Neither will socialism have much use for the 
 millions that now are engaged in commerce or in some of 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 155 
 
 the professions. We find in the list, for instance, com- 
 mercial travelers and book agents, floor walkers and 
 private secretaries, clerks and typists, teamsters and 
 messenger boys, advertising agents and curb brokers, 
 printers and journalists, janitors and watchmen, body 
 guards and doorkeepers, manicures and maids-in-waiting, 
 charity workers and chauffeurs for private families. A 
 certain percentage of these will and should be retained, 
 but many of them socialism will place in other positions. 
 If, as suggested in the Table, we select certain occupa- 
 tions and then decide upon a curtailment according to 
 the nature of the services now rendered, we shall find that 
 somewhere about one-half of the total number of gainfully 
 occupied not producing concrete goods may be cut off. 
 About 16% of all gainfully occupied in 1910 would thus 
 go into new lines of work. 
 
 It should be noted in passing that our three tests of 
 luxury consumption and therefore of the possibility for 
 a rise of the average man's income correspond roughly. 
 In each case we find a difference of about one-fifth. The 
 redistribution of this fifth marks the extent to which 
 socialism is tolerably sure of helping the masses who in 
 1910 earned less than $1000 or $1200 per year. 
 
 7. Other Limits in Production. Whether all of the 
 poor would hail the readjustment with delight, however, 
 is a question, for the change will involve some losses as 
 well as a great gain. It is ever so. The well-to-do, of 
 course, will suffer most, since the recomposition of the 
 national budget also means a redistribution of incomes. 
 To them the elimination of luxuries in goods and services 
 will bring the greatest sacrifices. But it will also have a 
 drawback for the masses of the people who have long been 
 used to the glamor of city life as competitive principles 
 engendered it. There are some features about the present 
 
156 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 method of retailing goods that those who bother not 
 about maximum welfare will prefer to the socialistic 
 scheme. And one cannot altogether blame them. 
 
 The possession of concrete goods is not everything even 
 to those of limited means. There is some satisfaction in 
 seeing what one cannot own, and there are many who pre- 
 fer the courtesies of a competitive business to the preci- 
 sion of a public service controlled by the state. Thus 
 some will feel that little is gained by having an extra 
 pair of shoes or twice the allowance in furniture, if the 
 goods must be bought from a government-owned ware- 
 house where the clerk cares nothing about the customer, 
 but on the contrary is conscious of rights which place him 
 at an advantage. Shopping is now made a pleasure by 
 those who wish to attract patrons and expand business 
 regardless of social welfare, or perhaps in full harmony 
 with it. The down-town districts of a large city are 
 a commentary on the spirit of modern enterprises. 
 Everything is subordinated to the maxim for profits. 
 The customer is always right as long as he pays the 
 price. Many people enjoy this situation and would 
 rather have the window displays of a fashionable depart- 
 ment store than cheaper ribbon or better housing condi- 
 tions.-. And so with the services of newsboy and shoeblack 
 and hotel-porter and all the rest of servitors catering to 
 the rich chiefly, but to the poor also in some measure. 
 
 And lastly, it is likely that the law of diminishing re- 
 turns will set limits to the output of comforts regardless 
 of what socialism decrees or the people may desire. The 
 staples of life are most subject to decrease in accordance 
 with the principle first enunciated by the Ricardians. 
 We cannot add to our agricultural stores at random as 
 we may increase the output of minerals. These latter 
 returns need not fall off for long times to come, but in so 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 157 
 
 far as farm-products furnish the basis for manufacturing, 
 or supply the population with foods, the national labor- 
 power is always at its mercy. Thus in European coun- 
 tries the peak of productivity has long been reached. In 
 the United States, whatever increases in acre-yield may 
 come, will be expensive. The farmer is sure to sell at a 
 rising price. The gain will be smaller than the cost in 
 labor and capital. The yield per acre may rise, but ex- 
 penses will rise even more. dThe more luxuries of one kind 
 the socialist demands, the more of another kind he will 
 have to forego, or else do without a corresponding amount 
 of necessaries.^ 
 
 The nineteenth century established many records that 
 will not be repeated for a long while. Thanks to them 
 the white race has multiplied its income in goods, learn- 
 ing to cherish precisely such ideals of future development 
 as socialism stands for. But it is not likely that the next 
 few hundred years will witness a similar growth in till- 
 able acreage, in timber supply, and in the output of 
 minerals. Science and organization have done their ut- 
 most. They have made the nineteenth century the 
 wonder of all ages. Yet the level of living has for the 
 masses not risen as much as socialists expect to raise it 
 hereafter, nor has the flow of luxuries sufficed to satisfy 
 the masses. In Europe foreign trade proved a valuable 
 means for the diversification of living. The output of 
 factory and mine was exchanged for raw materials bought 
 abroad, and the teeming millions were fed with stocks 
 grown in the Americas or in the plains of Siberia and 
 Australia. Even the East Indies and the dark continent 
 furnished a quota. 
 
 This, then, is the secret of a high level of living among 
 the minority of Europeans. By exporting large values 
 in tiny packages they managed to obtain the basic ma- 
 
158 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 terials or rare luxuries. In the future, however, this will 
 not be so easy. The more densely populated the erstwhile 
 frontier lands, that were the granaries of Europe, the less 
 certain their exports of foods, and more self sufficient the 
 European nations must become. The regulation of the 
 birthrate is one means of frustrating the designs of a 
 sinister law of nature, but this is not a peculiarly social- 
 istic means. Nor do wars solve the problem. The war 
 just closed e. g., has slain many millions, but it has also 
 exterminated the ablest instead of the worst, and that re- 
 acts disadvantageously upon both agriculture and in- 
 dustry. The only alternative to a reduced food allow- 
 ance, consequently, is an increased acre yield at the cost 
 of comforts and luxuries. In the long run nobody can 
 escape this situation. 
 
 People in the United States do not entertain such fears 
 of a reduction in food. Yet there are indications that for 
 them, too, future gains will mean a more than propor- 
 tionate expense of human and mechanical energy. True, 
 if the United Kingdom can produce thirty-five bushels 
 of wheat per acre, so can we. But this is nothing to gloat 
 over. On the contrary we should regret the step. 
 Furthermore, it will particularly interfere with socialistic 
 plans, since the workers set free by the elimination of use- 
 less services will increasingly be drawn to the farm in- 
 stead of producing manufactures. 
 
 Within a few generations such a turn for the worse is 
 certain unless, as remarked before, birth-control is popu- 
 larized as one may expect it will be. But in any case it 
 deserves notice that in the distant future the over-popu- 
 lated countries will not be able to fall back upon machino- 
 factures for a supply of necessities. The world is becom- 
 ing rapidly settled. Frontier regions still exist, but may 
 not have foodstuffs to export in such amounts as the 
 
THE LIMITS IN PRODUCTION 159 
 
 nineteenth century Europe needed. When that date ar- 
 rives socialism will have only one refuge for the poorly 
 endowed countries. Namely, it will have to fund the 
 world's supplies so as to maintain a high level of living 
 among the least favored nations. The increase of luxuries 
 may then continue, but it will not reach the proportions 
 some hope for, and the funding process which is after all 
 the logical goal of economic socialism will encroach 
 further upon the luxury rations of the inhabitants in the 
 richest lands. Thus will production have found its limits. 
 
CHAPTER VH 
 THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION 
 
 i. The Spending Power of the Rich Production 
 determines distribution. A nation cannot distribute 
 more among its members than it has at its disposal per 
 annum in goods and services. To the extent, therefore, 
 that socialism fails in augmenting the social dividend it 
 must also fail in raising the level of living of the average 
 man. This is on the understanding that the total na- 
 tional income is divided evenly between all the citizens. 
 But of course, this equality never existed and is not con- 
 templated by socialism. 
 
 There is consequently much room for a change of in- 
 dividual or family incomes without altering materially the 
 productiveness of the nation. In 1910 two-fifths of the 
 earning population received less than one-fifth of the na- 
 tional income, and one-fifth of the people claimed over 
 one-half of the aggregate. To-day the distribution can- 
 not be greatly different, though as a result of the war 
 just brought to a conclusion some groups of labor have 
 raised their purchasing power slightly, while some of the 
 formerly well-to-do have lost heavily. Wars always 
 mean a redistribution of incomes. 
 
 But the general fact is the same for all nations. We 
 shall perhaps always have the poor with us if no radical 
 change in economic organization takes place. The poor 
 always have been in the majority so far, and because of 
 this disparity existing everywhere the task of socialism 
 is clearly defined. It may try, and it solemnly promises, 
 to redistribute goods so that all have the necessities, and 
 
 160 
 
THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION 161 
 
 none sj)end greatly in excess of what the average man is 
 allowed. 
 
 It should, however, be understood that the present un- 
 equal distribution is no worse than it has been in the past, 
 that the largest incomes do not measure spending power, 
 and that without state aid a slow diffusion of national 
 wealth among all the inhabitants does take place. Social- 
 istic literature has been somewhat misleading on these 
 points. 
 
 The poor are to-day no worse off than they were in 
 olden times. On the contrary, there is plenty of evidence; 
 to show that unmitigated pauperism is on the wane, j 
 Among the ancients wealth was unevenly distributed be- 
 cause land was the chief natural resource, and this be- 
 longed to a few. When the level of living comprised not 
 much more than food and clothing even for the rich, then 
 the chief privilege of the wealthy was leisure and power 
 over the body. Slavery with all its attendant rights of 
 the owner furnished a sense of power such as nowadays un- 
 doubtedly comes with the control of large industrial 
 plants or public undertakings. All through the Middle 
 Ages this division of privileges and duties was continued. 
 The Church did not discourage it, though it preached now 
 and then of the brotherhood of man. The line of divi- 
 sion between lord and vassal, between freeman and serf, 
 between noble and burgher was distinctly drawn and ob- 
 served in social intercourse. The minority of nobles and 
 clergy owned the land or held it in fee simple from the 
 Crown or Holy See respectively, while the bulk of the 
 population owned no more than the food they ate and the 
 clothes on their back. It was not till the end of the four- 
 teenth century that private ownership among the unnoble 
 became important. Fortunes then were amassed with 
 which eventually the middle class made itself master of 
 
162 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 political affairs. But the concentration of wealth was 
 continued as before, except that new forms of wealth ap- 
 peared, and that hereditary rights to office were over- 
 shadowed by inheritance of wealth. When this change 
 came capitalism had won the day for the plebeian ma- 
 jority, even though income itself still fell into the hands of 
 a small group of enterprisers. 
 
 Until quite recent times wealth was less powerful and 
 conspicuous also in the sense that it could not buy what 
 the rich now display so lavishly. The basis of national 
 subsistence was agriculture. Manufactures made up the 
 smallest part of the social dividend, so that income was 
 spent mainly in the building of castles, and in viands and 
 costly raiments. The materials were expensive enough, 
 but the total effect of such extravagances was not as 
 obvious as it is to-day. Palaces were for protection 
 rather than for comfort, or if meant for comfort the 
 limitations, at any rate, of the value of money were much 
 more apparent than to-day. Science had not yet made 
 the discoveries that furnished the immense variety of com- 
 forts now so highly prized. The rich had more candles 
 to burn, but the light was about the same. They had 
 wood in the winter, but so had most of the tenants on 
 the estate. Rich food and gorgeous though ill fitting ap- 
 parel, security against the enemy in early ages such as 
 the poor could not get, an abundance of silver and gold 
 plate, and perhaps precious jewels from the Orient 
 such were the means by which the millionaires formerly 
 made themselves envied. The forms of display were not 
 as ostentatious as to-day, and the people were not as close 
 to them. The chase and the feud were pastimes the multi- 
 tude did not care for anyway. A difference in learning 
 either did not exist or did not challenge attention be- 
 cause of the limits of science. And besides, the multitude 
 
THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION 163 
 
 until a few generations ago did not aspire to a status 
 such as now is deemed the proof of well-being and democ- 
 racy. 
 
 Again, however, it would be a mistake to assume that 
 the excessively wealthy can spend all they have. The 
 notion that a million dollar income is actually spent for 
 comforts and luxuries, or might be so spent, is erroneous. 
 It has already been shown in a previous chapter that the 
 statistical data disprove such a contention. They show 
 plainly that not over one-fifth of our national product 
 consists of the non-necessities, and that more than one- 
 half of this takes the shape of goods consumed almost en- 
 tirely by incomes ranging between $1000 and $2500 for 
 1910, in the United States. Attention has been called 
 also to the fact that a large portion of every nation's in- 
 come represents capital goods used for producing con- 
 crete or inconcrete consumption goods. Hence this part 
 of the total is not available for consumption. But it is 
 owned mainly by the rich. The small earners save rarely 
 more than one-fifth or tenth of their income. They can- 
 not or will not do so. But the corporation making a 
 25% net profit, the man with a hundred thousand dollar 
 income, these are the centers of financial power. From 
 them the replacement and investment fund flows. They 
 maintain the status quo of industry or expand business 
 so as to raise the next year's social dividend. Out of the 
 millionaire's income thus all but a minor fraction remains 
 normally in productive condition. \ If all incomes over 
 five thousand a year were to be spent in the purchase of 
 luxuries, as has occasionally been suggested, our economic 
 system would collapse./ There would be no labor and 
 capital to provide the necessities ; nor could the plan for 
 the rich men work out well. Such spending would prove 
 to be impossible. 
 
164* THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 Large incomes then do not mean the scale of living 
 that many associate with them. Nor should it be forgot- 
 ten that nearly all wealth eventually redounds to the ad- 
 vantage of the masses. There is no discovery made by 
 science, no invention patented by the manufacturer, no 
 improvement introduced in the realm of exchange, but it 
 sooner or later benefits the average man. It is not pos- 
 sible to secrete ideas forever, vjj, is impossible to with- 
 hold permanently from the people the advantages first en- 
 joyed by the wealthy^;; Most luxuries some day become 
 necessities. Novelties in the course of time become an- 
 tiquities and curiosities of science, commonplaces. A 
 watch to-day is bought for a few dollars, though the work 
 of many great men was necessary to produce it. A Gali- 
 leo had to formulate laws of motion before we could meas- 
 ure time accurately. The dial contains figures that some- 
 body many thousands of years ago invented. The pro- 
 cesses for refining the ore used in the case cover many 
 achievements scientific and mechanic. The purchaser of 
 the watch does not pay for all he buys at the time. He, 
 on the contrary, expects to get the benefit of ideas and 
 efforts made by others, a few of them living, but most of 
 them long dead. Social heredity is the main source of 
 unearned increments. We profit by accepting the knowl- 
 edge of our forebears. We all, in the long run, get the 
 benefit of individual endeavor if it is extraordinary and of 
 lasting value. The rich cannot corner the market of 
 luxuries except for a short while. 
 
 Their own fortunes indeed crumble. From shirtsleeve 
 to shirtsleeve is but three generations, according to an 
 old adage. That does not seem to be true, and it cer- 
 tainly need not apply to the circulation of wealth. But it 
 is true that many huge fortunes are dissipated soon after 
 the founder has gone. In a hundred ways the hoard melts 
 
THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION 165 
 
 to nothing. Periodically some rich men become paupers, 
 and some of the poor accumulate wealth. 
 
 Yet in general there is a permanent concentration of 
 income. The disparity is lasting. The well-to-do con- 
 tinue to be so, and the wage earner of a thousand dollars 
 or two per year continues to stay at that figure. From 
 father to son we have wealth and poverty transmitted. 
 This is the fact that socialism is conscious of and wishes 
 to change. It wishes to hasten the natural diffusion of 
 incomes which the laws of consumption bring about. It 
 insists upon helping the laws of sociation here as at other 
 points in the field of economic relations. 
 
 2. Causes and Consequences of Concentration of 
 Incomes. Socialism has answered the question, why such 
 gross inequalities of income exist, in the spirit of certain 
 British writers whom Marx respected highly. The ques- 
 tion of one and the reply of another will help to make 
 clear the socialistic attitude, which from the days of Marx 
 on has remained the same in this matter. 
 | W. Thompson wrote in 1824 : " How comes it that a 
 nation abounding more than any other [he refers to Eng- 
 land, of course] in the crude materials of wealth in ma- 
 chinery, dwellings and food, in intelligent and industrious 
 producers, with all the apparent means of happiness, with 
 all the outward semblance of happiness exhibited by a 
 small and rich portion of the community, should pine still 
 in privation? How comes it that the fruits of the labor 
 of the industrious, after years of incessant and successful 
 exertion, are mysteriously and without any imputation 
 of fault tojthem, without any convulsion of nature swept 
 away?" 1 \ 
 
 Conditions to-day are not as gloomy as those depicted 
 
 i Thompson, W., "Inquiry into the Principles of Distribution," 
 Introduction. 
 
166 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 by this critic of the individualistic system, but with some 
 modification the challenge might be repeated to-day. And 
 the answer would still have to be what a contemporary of 
 Thompson, namely Hodgskin, thought it was. He de- 
 clared that " the distress our people suffer and the pov- 
 erty we all complain of, is not caused by nature, but by 
 some social institutions which either will not allow the 
 laborer to exert his productive power, or which rob him 
 of its fruits." 2 
 
 Hodgskin demurred to the charge of the Ricardians that 
 nature was at fault, that the law of diminishing returns 
 explained everything, or that sexual passion gave civ- 
 ilization no chance. The socialists from Marx on have 
 supported this criticism of the English radicals and 
 pointed with an accusing finger to capitalism. The more 
 modern view will not accept the whole of the socialistic 
 indictment, but it is indisputably true that a change 
 should and can be made. 
 
 The unequal distribution so far has been the result of 
 innate differences between men, and of other differences 
 less constant, more controllable. The superiorities of 
 some will necessarily bring them victory in any battle. 
 Physical strength and valor win in a hand-to-hand en- 
 counter. Great mental powers bring riches to men. But 
 in addition we have had legal monopolies, the might of 
 socio-economic organization gathered into a few hands, 
 the ownership, by a small group, of natural resources 
 which furnish the staples of consumption, and the right 
 of inheritance, by which the wealthy could perpetuate 
 their holdings not only in consumables but also in the 
 rawstuffs. When the non-productive materials such as 
 mineral and timber and soil fertility and water-power are 
 deeded away to a few, whether by purchase or free gift 
 2 Hodgskin, Th., "Popular Political Economy," 1827; pp. 267-68. 
 
THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION 167 
 
 does not matter, then unusual chances for gain are 
 opened. Organization is the fruit of brain and property 
 rights. It is virtually invincible, barring state action. 
 We can defeat brain by itself, and there is always a 
 method for controlling mere wealth. But let the two com- 
 bine, and the partnership becomes nigh invincible. 
 
 The socialist has his eye on this combination, and de- 
 sires to separate brain from monopoly in the extremely 
 scarce resources of the world. He favors a redistribu- 
 tion of incomes to help the less gifted by nature, and in 
 this he has the approval of science no less than of moral 
 sentiments. 
 
 A theory of prosperity such as social science to-day 
 recommends is incompatible with extremes in distribution. 
 As long as income is a condition to leisure and education, 
 as long as an economic leveling is a prerequisite to a feel- 
 ing of fellowship in matters civic, moral, religious and in- 
 tellectual, so long the juxtaposition of plutocrat and pro- 
 letariat is full of menace. We can develop dormant pow- 
 ers of reasoning and of production or of enjoyment in 
 man. This modern psychology and biology prove. We 
 can produce more than we need to sustain the body. This 
 history has shown. We can produce most by joint enter- 
 prise and capitalistic methods, meaning thereby round- 
 about methods and the use of machinery, no matter who 
 owns it. Since then, according to the verdict of natural 
 science health depends on food supplies and protection 
 against bacterial diseases, and since an economic surplus 
 is necessary to the specialization which makes modern 
 science and discovery possible, it follows that wealth well 
 distributed is most conducive to progress. The same 
 economic interpretation of history which socialism first 
 formulated as a sweeping law of evolution provides also 
 part of our argument for urging equalization of fortunes. 
 
168 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 Approximate leveling must be part of our plan for de- 
 mocratization of all rights and efforts. 
 
 However, we may look at the situation from another 
 angle. We may emphasize the undoubted fact that distri- 
 bution reacts upon production in two ways, viz., by af- 
 fecting our choice of goods, and by influencing the volume 
 of goods turned out, and that for these two reasons a 
 marked concentration of income is reprehensible. This 
 viewpoint has commonly been taken by socialists, and it 
 agrees with the analysis of price advanced by profes- 
 sional economists. People disagree chiefly as to the place 
 of competition in national productiveness.^ 
 
 That an extreme concentration of wealth must influence 
 the enterpriser in his choice of goods to be produced 
 should be self-evident. But if not, it follows logically 
 from the very facts of utility and pricing which most 
 economists content themselves to describe. 
 
 The rich will encourage the production of luxuries when 
 millions lack the necessities. They will do this because 
 of the principle of unlimited wants and of diminishing 
 utility. They will do this because, in equalizing our 
 margins of enjoyment of goods, we are able to offer differ- 
 ent amounts of money for goods, once income is unevenly 
 divided among the consumers. The prices are then for 
 all the same, but the sacrifices are not. This is the cir- 
 cumstance that socialism most deplores. 
 
 Our wants are illimitable. Thanks to our imagination 
 and power of inference we are able to wish for much 
 more than we possess. We are never satisfied ; which is on 
 the whole a good thing. But since there seems always 
 room for things besides those we already own and enjoy, 
 we make unequal efforts or sacrifices to obtain additional 
 goods when our possessions are unequal. 
 
 And we shall ask for different things, not merely for 
 
THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION 169 
 
 larger amounts of any one article. \ We tire of one ar- 
 ticle as we increase our supply of it. We cease to value 
 an over abundance of good things. Too much dinner 
 sates our appetites. One or two musical instruments sat- 
 isfy our longing for music. After we have bought so much 
 of clothing or books or furniture we want no more of it, 
 or we want very different types of each, so that we have 
 virtually something different. 
 
 We therefore always spend our money deliberately in ; 
 that we weigh the desirability of one commodity relative 
 to another. We have options to buy things, but cannot 
 ordinarily buy everything. We must decide what we 
 want, how much of each class of goods, and in what order. 
 If, for instance, a community has a supply of water it will 
 allot it for different uses according to the total supply 
 on hand. We may be sure that our thirst will first be 
 quenched from the supply. We shall put drinking water 
 before everything else. Then, if something is left, we 
 shall perhaps use it for washing purposes and for the 
 laundry. If still more remains we may decide to sprinkle 
 the streets with it, so as to lay the dust. Or possibly 
 our garden back of the house needs it, so we shall use it 
 there. And only if all these needs are looked after shall 
 we think of swimming pools, of public fountains and like 
 details. 
 
 In some such order all our articles of consumption are 
 used. An astonishing uniformity of tastes will manifest 
 itself in the arrangement of broad classes of goods, how- 
 ever infinite the variations in detail. We all know what 
 are the essentials of life on a physical plane. We all at 
 first prefer clothing and shelter to bric-a-brac or sightsee- 
 ing tours abroad. We cannot indulge in trivial comforts 
 antil a minimum for bodily sustenance is provided. Then, 
 beyond that point, and in the finer grading of preferences. 
 
170 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 the individuality of the purchaser appears. The farmer 
 does not value things like the urbanite. A clergyman has 
 a scale of choices different from that of a hard manual 
 worker or a scientist perchance. Our temperaments de- 
 termine our choices. Some would have more food and 
 others more books. Some will like to spend a great deal 
 for pastimes, while others are eager to own a home first 
 or to acquire a college education. Tastes differ in the 
 particulars. 
 
 But let it be noted that the unequal division of wealth 
 greatly accentuates the natural differences in taste. For 
 now one man has much more to compare with his pros- 
 pective purchase than the other. The rich man has a 
 long line of wants already satisfied, consequently thinks 
 little of his potential possessions, that is of his money. 
 He will be willing to give much for trifles which the poor 
 man dare not think of buying, since more important needs 
 would then remain unfilled. The wealthy person thus is 
 apt to demand goods which no one else wants, and which 
 are not really a part of a sound standard of living. He 
 will divert labor and material from employment that would 
 raise the level of living of small earners to others which 
 cannot raise it. 
 
 The overly rich are systematically catered to by all 
 kinds of people anxious to earn a fat living irrespective of 
 social welfare. As the saying is: Money talks and will 
 command anything and, one might add, will command 
 to be obeyed. The rich man pays no more for the ne- 
 cessities than the poor because, being a rare exception, he 
 cannot greatly influence popular demand, that is the ma- 
 jority of valuations and of costs in terms of sacrifice. He 
 will pay ten cents for a pound of sugar, though he could 
 give a hundred times that sum. Physicians, to be sure, 
 have introduced a scale of fees proportionate to earnings 
 
THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION 171 
 
 real or alleged. This is at times held to be an act of jus- 
 tice. And it is, if we single out the services of the phy- 
 sician from all others as being more vital, and hence the 
 most valuable to the poor who on a competitive basis might 
 have to do without them. The scale of prices is there- 
 fore logical. But plainly, if all producers and sellers 
 were to scale their prices according to the purchasing 
 power of the customer, the end result would be simply the 
 maintenance of present distribution. The adjusting of 
 prices, including wages, to ability to pay would prevent a 
 further concentration of wealth, particularly if it were 
 made exactly and consistently for all services. But it 
 could not abolish the present inequalities which socialism 
 condemns. 
 
 The effect of a marked concentration of wealth on pro- 
 ductiveness has been variously estimated. Some have held 
 that it is an essential to maximum effort, while many oth- 
 ers are convinced that the national income is thereby re- 
 duced. 
 
 Sidgwick, the noted English ethicist and economist, be- 
 lieved the former. He feared for the British level of liv- 
 ing if the masses were to get their rights as the socialists 
 saw them. He wrote : " Any great equalization of wealth 
 would probably dimmish the accumulation of capital on 
 which the progress of industry depends ; and would de- 
 teriorate the administration of the capital accumulated." 
 He was afraid, for one thing, of the people spending their 
 additional earnings due to a redistribution of wealth. He 
 no doubt thought that improvidence would get the better 
 of common people and induce them to keep servants or 
 make gluttons of themselves. The capital-fund, as de- 
 fined by competitive economics, would thus shrink, and 
 gradually the flow of concrete goods would end. 
 
 3 Sidgwick, H., " Elements of Politics," p. 153. 
 
172 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 Whether this is a good view to take of the habits of the 
 average man is hard to say. We have no direct evidence 
 to prove that socialism will decidedly increase the product- 
 ive powers of the nation. But on the other hand we 
 know of sumptuary laws and of education which have 
 taught men moderation without hurting their feelings. 
 In the end there will not be a great deal of waste because 
 the ratio of capital to consumption goods is, with the ex- 
 ception of a good possibility for extending personal serv- 
 ices almost indefinitely, fairly constant. It is really im- 
 possible to provide luxuries for those with large incomes 
 unless they themselves or others save, that is see to the 
 production of a suitable amount of capital which is to 
 turn out the luxuries. Only a few may at any given time 
 draw heavily upon their total nominal income in dollars 
 and cents, the majority must be content with investments, 
 so the future flow of consumables may grow. 
 
 As against this fact, however, we must acknowledge 
 that personal services may easily expand unduly, for 
 which reason partly an extreme concentration of wealth is 
 undesirable. As has been shown elsewhere, socialism will 
 increase our labor-power chiefly by making use of this 
 principle. The hosts of men and women now employed 
 in the rendering of trifling services will be turned into 
 socially necessary workers, providing services more in 
 keeping with the needs of the great majority, and rentiers 
 will have to work also. 
 
 As socialists have often remarked, there are at present 
 too many idlers feasting at a table set by others. Heirs 
 and prospective heirs, the children of wealthy folk, grown 
 up men and women, and not least of all married women 
 in affluent circumstances, these are the parasites who de- 
 pend upon others for their fat living. \It is not the money 
 earner himself who spends vast sums, out his family or 
 
THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION 173 
 
 relatives. \ Big producers at all times have been compara- 
 tively sm^ll consumers. Those who give most take the 
 least, and gladly continue to give their services, or at any 
 rate to follow their gainful pursuits. But comumption 
 by proxy becomes a pleasant, because respectable, kind of 
 a debauch. Habitual idleness thus perpetuates itself from 
 one generation to the next. 
 
 Let us admit then that the socialist possibly has exag- 
 gerated the effects of the leisure class on national out- 
 put. But if so he seems to have the better of it when de- 
 fending his principle of collectivistic enterprise against 
 the plea for competition which the friends of the present 
 regime usually bring up first. 
 
 It has been argued that to decrease profits will mean a 
 lowering of our level of living, because the .average busi- 
 nessman will not do his best unless he can keep all he can 
 get. The champions of ruthless individualism have again 
 and again reverted to this position. It has seemed to 
 them axiomatic that the present regime is efficient because 
 the ablest are prodded on by rewards which socialism 
 would withhold from them. If this be so, then of course 
 competition should have no fetters, since the reduction of 
 our income hampers progress, as socialists admit. 
 
 3. Private Property and Efficiency. But what is 
 competition, and what has the past taught us in this re- 
 spect? It is evident that much depends on the definition 
 of our term, to say nothing of the bearing of experience 
 on our topic. 
 
 Now, in the first place, one may retort with the irrefut- 
 able fact that the majority of the producers lack that 
 supposedly necessary incentive already, The "g 
 jority of workers for a wage cannot increase income as 
 they increase their output. Their day's work is roughly 
 fixed, and their day's income is in most cases fixed exactly. 
 
174 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 Piecework has been tried out, and many produce under 
 that system to-day. But it has not always raised produc- 
 tivity, nor has the advantage of a larger output invari- 
 ably offset the disadvantages in other lines. The indirect 
 effects of speeding, whether urged by profit-sharing or by 
 piece wages, have set both labor and legislators against it. 
 
 But, for that matter, it would be difficult to prove that 
 men have produced poorly because they received a con- 
 tractual income. Wages have not prevented us from rais- 
 ing our level of living more in the nineteenth century than 
 before. Many hundreds of thousands have for years 
 worked for salaries and done their best. Corporations 
 have submitted to a restriction of earnings in percentages 
 of their investment and not ceased therefore to serve the 
 public. We have minimum prices and maximum wages, 
 franchise taxes for net profits above a normal interest rate, 
 and fees absolutely independent of demand or of values 
 delivered. If a physician can pursue his practice without 
 charging all the traffic will bear, why should not a busi- 
 ness firm selling rawstuffs or finished goods? It would 
 seem that either we have to divide the population into two 
 groups, namely the greedy and the generous, or else re- 
 define our concept of competition. If, and to the extent 
 that, it is true that some will exert themselves only for 
 the pelf to be gained, while others find their reward in 
 something besides pelf, incomes should be uncontrolled in 
 one case, and curbed in another. But this is not the 
 most obvious way of meeting our dilemma. 
 
 Rather it should be plain that competition involves 
 much more than a lust for maximum earnings. Hodgskin, 
 whom we have quoted several times before, wrote : " I can 
 understand how a right to appropriate the produce of 
 other men, under the name of interest or profit, may be a 
 stimulus to cupidity, but I cannot understand how lessen- 
 
THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION 175 
 
 ing the reward of the laborer, to add to the wealth of the 
 idle, can increase industry or accelerate the progress of 
 society in wealth." This is one kind of rebuttal the 
 socialist might use. But the more scientific one is a cor- 
 rect analysis of the competitive spirit. 
 
 Competition is not simply a struggle for riches, as 
 economics frequently has made it out to be ; nor is it a 
 trial of the pyx by which the pure is separated from the 
 impure. 
 
 The fittest in society is not the fittest among animals. 
 This is the first now universally recognized fact which the 
 individualist has to remember. Evolution is not progress, 
 for man has developed powers of speech and of reasoning, 
 of memory and of associations, which permitted him to 
 master nature rather than live by exploiting his fellowmen. 
 When man began to unfold his learning faculties and to 
 wrest from nature her innermost secrets he was in a fair 
 way to substitute surplus for deficit, and to displace in- 
 ternecine strife by intellectual research. 
 
 Or we may put the matter thus. 
 
 Competition originally had to do with sex and self 
 preservation in a struggle for sheer existence, but later on 
 other factors became more important. Altruism had al- 
 ways been a natural concomitant of sexual reproduction 
 and of parental responsibilities. From it the first un- 
 selfish instincts must have gathered strength. But gradu- 
 ally the enlargement of the individual's environs developed 
 group consciousness in addition to blood ties. The selfish 
 instincts of pugnacity and acquisitiveness which relate 
 closely to the reproductive functions were tempered by 
 feelings for others. A solidarity of interests arose and 
 was cultivated by the requisites of production. Division 
 of labor and technical cooperation could mean nothing 
 * Hodgskin, op. cit., p. 254. 
 
176 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 else, however stimulating in some respects it was for the 
 most individualistically inclined. \ As the material level 
 rose the so-called moral did, too.'' Passion came to be 
 blended with compassion, self-assertion with a suscepti- 
 bility to the approval of outsiders, and the vying for 
 booty with the penchant for achievement. The whole 
 course of civilization is a conversion of the physical self 
 into a social self, and of products into personality. 
 
 The cave-man is still with us, but not in large numbers. 
 He is likely to be a movie hero, or a felon in prison. The 
 pirate of old has turned profiteer perhaps, but most of the 
 profiteers are producers nonetheless. The marauders of 
 the economic world no longer pillage and destroy merely ; 
 they also build or replace in part what they have undone. 
 The chieftain who led his hordes into the bloody fray has 
 given way to the business magnate who excels in the man- 
 aging of labor forces. Not all highwaymen have died 
 out to leave us unmolested, but the surviving must be 
 clever to elude the law, or they must give a quid pro quo 
 of some kind. 
 
 In other words competition, if it ever was merely a 
 struggle for loot, has long ceased to be such. In modern 
 times it has increasingly meant a desire to create as well 
 as a bent for acquisition. The hardest fighters do not^yv, 
 want the enjoyment of their possessions. They do not 
 feast at banquets or spend their day in carousals. The 
 most competitively spirited compete for power which 
 wealth brings, for the prestige that it means, but also for t 
 the joy of the game. 
 
 We love to compare our deeds. Competition is this 
 vying for superiority regardless of emoluments. It is not 
 merely the seeking after rare things money can buy. 
 Some scarcities not in the money market are equally en- 
 trancing, and most of them stand for social order. 
 
THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION 177 
 
 People do their utmost because energy needs a vent. Or 
 they plod along from habit, doing day by day their duty, 
 perhaps unthinkingly. Habit and enerfiy T pride in 
 achievements and the instinct for approval, these are the, 
 elements in competition that count more in the aggregate 
 than the lust for profits. 
 
 Men wish to identify themselves with a piece of work. 
 They crave leadership or distinction measurable by indi- 
 vidual creations. Socialism, therefore, should put a 
 premium of praise and a badge of distinction on the ex- 
 ceptional deed. This all statesmanship will respect, and 
 within a limited sphere always has applied. If under 
 socialism the exceptional producers are permitted to do 
 their own work, to follow up their conceptions and en- 
 deavors, to bring to public notice what they have done, 
 then the curtailment of profits will do no great harm. It 
 will not restrain the most meritorious, though some may 
 desist at the outset. Socialists should make sure of con- 
 necting men with their work wherever possible and in 
 such a way that the two may be identified. It is this 
 which the finest of men will wish. Incentive to produce by 
 mastering the subject, and by demonstrating the results to 
 an admiring or at least to a sympathetic public such 
 is the most fundamental significance of competition. Men 
 of preeminence always will lead. JThe fiffht to lead and 
 to do substantially as we please in creating values will 
 remain for all times to come. We cannot abolish it by a 
 fiat of law. But the right to earn as much as, and by 
 any method, we please is bound to be circumscribed the 
 more, the more advanced scientific thought. 
 
 It might be objected that taxation can take the place of 
 socialization, so our present regime may be left intact. 
 This thought has often been broached, and of course con- 
 tains much truth. But it should also be remembered that 
 
178 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 the final result of greatly increased taxation cannot but 
 be a curb to individual enterprise. 
 
 Taxes are never the most desirable means for rectify- 
 ing distributive errors, for to take taxes is to admit that 
 somebody owns, and this implied or explicit admission of 
 earnings on the part of the tax payer is an injustice to 
 the bulk of the wage earners. In the second place, tax- 
 ation is a roundabout way of leveling incomes, much as 
 Prohibition once labored indirectly because it agitated 
 against consumption long before it argued against the 
 production of liquors. Indirect methods of that sort 
 mean leakage and lost motion. They mean uncertainties 
 and protests that are falsely grounded. 
 
 But, in the third place, it is difficult to see what the 
 central or local governments would do with the receipts if 
 they were to take from the rich by taxes what socialism 
 wishes to give the masses of the people more directly. A 
 revenue four or five times as large as now needed for 
 routine administration would call for investments in an 
 unusual way. In the United States, for instance, the 
 total public revenue, federal and local, was for the year 
 1912 equal to about six per cent, of the social dividend. 
 For every dollar of national income the authorities col- 
 lected six cents in taxes. If the socialistic principles of 
 leveling were to be realized by taxation the revenue would 
 approximate twenty per cent, or more of the total national 
 income. This would possibly look like a nice gain for both 
 government and the poor man who was taxed little or noth- 
 ing. But what would be done with the receipts? They 
 would either have to be redistributed directly among the 
 most needv, or they would mean a vast extension of gov- 
 ernment functions with the result that enterprise would 
 increasingly become a public business. Taxation conso- 
 
THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION 179 
 
 nant with the distributive norms of socialism would thus 
 lead to government ownership anyway. 
 
 | 4. Pricing under Socialism. Socialism, however, 
 would mean more than the socialization of capital. It 
 would not merely prevent the rich from becoming richer, 
 but in addition it plans a revaluation of goods and serv- 
 ices, so that none can earn the hugejsums which now are 
 said to represent their " product." Under socialism there 
 will be no inheritance of _ capital, and .only limited inheri- 
 tance o^^onsumer^goods. This source of rentals then 
 being taken away, and the work of all being valued at a 
 newT^cale, incomes would not "vary "a great deal, though 
 some differences would continue to exist. But at any rate 
 the incomes^ would all be earned. Rent, interest, and 
 profits would have no place in the new regime. All pro- 
 ducers would be wage-earners.. All workers, no matter 
 what their profession or trade, would receive wages by 
 stipulation with the government. \The aleatory gains of 
 the entrepreneur would end, and contractual earnings 
 would alone prevail. 
 
 It would of course be possible t_Q ration out the goods 
 which each worker or head of a family is entitled to. 
 Instead of paying him in token money with which to pur- 
 chase his needs he could be paid in amounts of commodi- 
 ties constituting the value of his labors. In this way the 
 government, or the locally managed public industries, 
 would know exactly what to produce of each kind of good, 
 and the possibilities of foolish spending were removed. 
 To apportion income in this manner has some advantages 
 particularly when we are dealing with irresponsible par- 
 ties. But it also offers great administrative difficulties, 
 and besides, it has not been seriously proposed by social- 
 ists. It is intended, if one may judge by the dominant 
 
180 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 tone of writings on this neglected subject, to retain the 
 use of money in so far as it serves simply as a medium of 
 exchange. Money will be chiefly a claim to values with- 
 out having itself intrinsic value. Paper money will pre- 
 dominate. It will, like poker chips in a game of cards, 
 represent titles to real values, but will have none itself. 
 And trade thus will mean only a moving of goods. Com- 
 merce will at bottom mean regional distribution involving 
 the transportation of commodities. The public central 
 warehouses will supply the stores at which the consumer 
 cashes in his token money. The exchange of goods for 
 services rendered will thus be simplified, and much dupli- 
 cation of effort stop. 
 
 But at what rates will goods exchange? Price is a 
 ratio of exchange. If a bushel of wheat sells to-day for 
 two dollars which buy five pounds of meat, the price of a 
 bushel of wheat is five pounds of meat. Value is price 
 when values are exchanged. Price is the amount of one 
 article given for a unit amount of another, that unit be- 
 ing most commonly known as money. The dollar, e. g., 
 is the unit in terms of which the American people meas- 
 ure Ujeir exchange ratios. 
 
 Their) are jour possibilities of pricing^ one of which 
 socialism will adopt. We may fix the price of commo- 
 dities, but not the wages paid for services. We may fix 
 the wage, but not the price of commodities. We may fix 
 both prices for commodities and wages. And finally we 
 may fix neither prices nor incomes, that is wages. 
 
 At last analysis of course all prices are incomes, and 
 vice versa. If I buy a pair of shoes I have to pay a 
 price, and if a clerk sells them to me he also charges his 
 employer a price for his work. The employer calls the 
 TV age of the clerk a price which forms part of his busi- 
 ness expenses ; but the clerk speaks of wages as income. 
 
THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION 181 
 
 To him it is coming in, though for the owner of the store 
 it is going out. Income and outgo constitute couples 
 that in practice cannot be separated into individual acts. 
 But according to viewpoint one and the same value is 
 either price or income. A price contains the incomes of 
 all those involved in the creation of the article back of the 
 price. In a pair of shoes, for instance, are incorporated 
 many incomes, which in minute amounts went to all those 
 who helped make the shoe, from farm hand tending the 
 steer that furnished the hide to the clerk in the store sell- 
 ing the finished article. 
 
 At present the great bulk of prices, i. e., of prices for 
 commodities and of incomes for services, are determined 
 competitively. We have an open market, and let the 
 forces of supply and demand decide what a commodity 
 shall sell for. This is the theory on which the science of 
 economics proceeded to correlate product ^nd income, and 
 in large measure this is actual fact. VHowever, purely 
 competitive pricing has 'ceased in many fiems of production 
 and exchange. Monopoly has supplanted competition, 
 and public regulation has put limits to both competitive 
 and monopoly-pricing. We might therefore acknowledge 
 frankly that to-day public control of prices^js gaining, 
 
 though competition still holds part of the field. Freight 
 rates and the price of coal or bread are publicly fixed. 
 Urban traction companies may not earn more than a cer- 
 tain per cent, on their investment, and employees of the 
 government of course have as such a publicly set annual 
 income. If necessary their salaries will be adjusted to 
 labor conditions in private business, but roughly speaking 
 the government fixes a wage without regard to competi- 
 tion from outside. Against this rule, however, must be 
 placed the unionization of labor, the upshot of which is 
 the determination of all wages by agreement with the em- 
 
182 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 ployer. Hence a growing part of wage-earners reduces 
 the force of individual competition and puts in place of it 
 what socialism virtually aims at, namely payment in ac- 
 cord with public opinion. A socialistic wage-law will, 
 like any act of legislature, meet the sanction of the ma- 
 jority, but public opinion will be guided from the head- 
 quarters of business. 
 
 Incomes under socialism will be fixed per work hour or 
 per year, but the prices of commodities will vary with de- 
 mand just as they do to-day. This seems to be the plan 
 advocated by most defenders of the new order. Consumers 
 will be allowed to bid for goods as they do now, but in the 
 first place there will be minima and maxima, and in the 
 second place the effect upon production will not be the 
 present one, because incomes will be put more nearly on a 
 par with each other. 
 
 From the standpoint of adjustment of supply to de- 
 mand, however, the free pricing of goods will under social- 
 ism have nothing ahead of the now prevailing system. 
 Nor does there seem any way out of the difficulty unless 
 a rationing of goods takes the place of purchase with 
 money paid by the government for services. If, namely, 
 the government sets prices too high the people may not 
 buy, or buy but little, so that great stocks are left at the 
 end of the year which cannot be used up. But if prices 
 are set too low, the demand will exceed supplies on hand, 
 and, unless maxima prices are decreed, a ruthless bidding 
 will set in. Even though incomes are equally or fairly 
 evenly assigned, many then will still go without the goods 
 they should have as part of a right standard of living. 
 Tastes differ enormously. The ideal of public welfare can 
 only be guarded by specifying all those articles which are 
 part of a normal level of living, and the use of which in 
 stated maximum and minimum amounts is publicly recom- 
 
THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION 183 
 
 mended or ordered. But in either case supply and de- 
 mand will not agree closely. And if no price fixation is 
 planned the discrepancy will be even greater. There will 
 always be too much of some commodities and not enough 
 of others. It will not be possible to ascertain beforehand 
 what people want. The averages of demand will be dis- 
 covered slowly, and perhaps change as fast as they have 
 been tabulated for use in production. At present a deli- 
 cate mechanism of exchange > wholesale and retail, attends 
 to the equilibration which is never perfect, but moves not 
 too far from the median line of adjustment. We have 
 trade journals and government crop reports, international 
 news service and statistical surveys privately conducted. 
 We have brokers and bourses looking after the fluctuations 
 of supply and demand. There is buying and selling in 
 the harvest field, and of harvested crops for delivery many 
 months ahead. And most important of all, we have the 
 pressure of rising prices and the license of falling prices, 
 by which device demand is suited to supplies and price is 
 suited to willingness to pay, the poorest dropping out of 
 the market first. 
 
 It is not likely that socialistic organization will do 
 much better in this respect, than the one now in effect. 
 It will be far more just to the average consumer, but it 
 will not avoid altogether the waste attending the distribu- 
 tion of goods over large areas, among many millions of 
 people. Nor will it be easy to obtain rawstuffs at short 
 notice from abroad, in case demand moves that way, or to 
 find labor in the home market to increase the supply of 
 particular articles. The more socialism seeks to inter- 
 nationalize levels of living, the more it will have to reckon 
 with waste, and with sacrifices for those nations which are 
 most prosperous and technically best administered. 
 
 5. Costs under Socialism. In so far, however, as 
 
184 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 demand is not to fix the price of commodities another prin- 
 ciple will doubtless be invoked, and socialists have often 
 spoken of costs in this connection. It has by some been 
 hinted that goods will be sold at cost, and by others that 
 costs will measure roughly the price of goods. But how 
 far may this rule really be enforced? 
 
 As to sales at cost, the phrase is misleading if it is to 
 convey the thought of prices below the present, because no 
 profits will be made. The sale at cost would be no gain, 
 because socialistic costs would comprise more or less than 
 competitive costs, according as we look at them. 
 
 In general cost is a ratio. Budgets are ratios of in- 
 come and outgo, and cost and return are the two aspects 
 of this mutual relation. If, for instance, I lose one bushel 
 of seedwheat in producing five bushels of harvested wheat 
 I may say that the cost of the five bushels is the one 
 bushel put .into the ground. Cost is outgo measured in 
 terms of income, and the rate of return (or the profit) 
 is income compared with outgo. 
 
 Cost may be expressed either in goods, by weight and 
 volume, or in money. The example of wheat just given is 
 one of cost measurement by weight and tale. But in- 
 stead of referring the five bushels of wheat harvested to 
 one bushel of seed I might also have reckoned the return 
 by the time it took to produce them. I might have said : 
 I produced five bushels in four months. Next year I shall 
 try to produce them in three months, and I shall then 
 have increased my rate of return or decreased my costs. 
 The time element evidently is sometimes important for 
 cost accounting, and it figures prominently in national 
 budgets. But we might, in the third place, measure rates 
 of return or costs by income per capita of the popula- 
 tion. If the output of wheat per capita is ten bushels in 
 one year, and twelve the next, we may call this gain the 
 
THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION 185 
 
 equivalent of cost reduction. We may feel that it reduces 
 our cost of living. We may measure our purchasing 
 power in that way, and feel downcast or elated according 
 to productiveness per average inhabitant. 
 
 But if we pass over to the competitive norm, the rate 
 of return in concrete goods becomes less significant than 
 the income of dollars and cents per outgo of the same. 
 The farmer, thus, may not care whether he grows more 
 wheat per acre, or even more wheat per outlay in goods 
 and services. He may simply ask: What will I get in 
 money for money spent? If I grow less wheat, but sell it 
 at a higher price I shall have raised my profits. My 
 costs will be relatively lower. My income having grown 
 while my expenses remained constant, my expenses have 
 practically shrunk. 
 
 The correct analysis of cost thus leads us to the con- 
 clusion which Marx himself could not escape, but on the 
 contrary placed candidly before his readers. To wit, 
 socialism cannot decrease costs unless it raises efficiency. 
 It will not really confer a benefit upon the consumer, 
 though nominally it sells commodities at cost. The list 
 of costs will have changed. The names may not be the 
 old. But the ratio of income to outgo for the nation as 
 a whole is no better except invention and organization 
 reduce the outgo of effort and material relative to returns 
 in material. 
 
 There will be probably no insurance of capital such as 
 we know to-day. There will be no profits going to a small 
 group of entrepreneurs. But there will be the outgo of 
 raw-materials, of wages in the shape of goods, most of it 
 being paid to the producers of concrete commodities or 
 of personal services, but some of it to officials looking 
 after the non-economic duties such as maintenance of army, 
 of the department of justice, etc. There will furthermore 
 
186 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 be reserves for unforeseen losses, for replacement of capi- 
 tal goods, for expansion of business when and where nec- 
 essary, and for charity and pensions. The cripples in 
 body or mind will be taken care of, and the aged will re- 
 ceive regular remittances which will be paid out of prices 
 and products figuring in socialistic costs. 
 
 But the costs, though determinable in general, will not 
 be measurable for a particular article. The use of ma- 
 chinery precludes such a possibility, and besides, there is 
 the joint product, the by-product, for which costs cannot 
 be computed except very indirectly. The imputation of 
 values to services and to commodities will be as arbitrary 
 under socialism as it ever was. The number of hours it 
 took to create a certain article or its value will in most 
 cases not be ascertainable, since many men have worked 
 together and simultaneously to produce it, to say nothing 
 of overhead expenses and the costs in work hours, of 
 machinery and management and of particular inventions 
 basic to the productive act. 
 
 Prices, in fine, will be fixed somewhat arbitrarily to 
 agree with the ideals of living. The socialistic standard 
 of living will keep some articles cheap so all may buy them, 
 and raise the price of high grade luxuries, supposing they 
 are produced at all. 
 
 6. The Socialistic Principle of Distribution. To 
 assure the average man a decent livelihood prices for serv- 
 ices too will be put nearly on one plane. The revaluation 
 will not only cheapen necessities, but it will give the 
 humblest laborer a return in wages sufficient for all ap- 
 proved wants. Socialism will measure productivity by 
 work hours. The worker, with certain exceptions, will 
 be paid according to the time he puts in at the work 
 bench. It will be assumed that the rate of work, that is 
 of actual achievement, is for men in like occupations uni- 
 
THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION 187 
 
 form, even though some differences may in practice ap- 
 pear. No other method for valuating services can exist 
 under socialism. Ten hours of work will be worth twice 
 as much as five hours. 
 
 Exceptions will do justice to striking differences in the 
 nature of work done. Inventors and novelists, for in- 
 stance, will be rewarded in a lump sum, or on the install- 
 ment plan, for creations of unusual and abiding merit. 
 Managers will receive more than underlings. Those 
 highly trained in science or skilled in handicrafts will have 
 more to spend than crude labor. But the latter will at 
 least have enough for a living standardized by the ob- 
 jective tests of individual and social welfare. It will, in 
 general, be argued as Adam Smith did a hundred and fifty 
 years ago, that " by nature a philosopher is not in genius 
 and disposition half so different from a street porter, as a 
 mastiff is from a greyhound ." 5 This viewpoint will 
 guide the socialist. He will emphasize resemblance in men 
 more than their differences. He will seek to democratize 
 effort and rights. He will differentiate with care, but 
 tolerate no extremes of income. Unlike services, but ap- 
 proximately like pay for all ! The brainiest will give, and 
 the numskulls will take. Those who now by mere cunning 
 and astuteness garner riches will obtain less. What they 
 lack in creativeness will reduce their income as much as 
 now the possession of shrewdness raises it above the aver- 
 age. 
 
 Distribution according to need will, if necessary, take 
 the place of distribution according to number of hours at 
 work. The least gifted will get more than their product 
 even as measured by socialism. The standard of living 
 will be raised for the masses. It will include many items 
 
 5 "Wealth of Nations," Book I, Chapter 2. See also Thompson, 
 W., "Inquiry into the Principles of Distribution," p. 4. 
 
188 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 not now figuring in a wage-earner's budget, and it will allot 
 some of the essentials in a somewhat better proportion 
 than seems now practicable. 
 
 A Minimum Wage Board recently estimated the wage 
 necessary for self-supporting women in the printing in- 
 dustry at sixteen dollars a week. This in the summer of 
 1919 ! It wished to be just, and itemized the expenses for 
 each class of wants. It did the best it could to allow for 
 all essentials, and the showing is not bad at first glance. 
 But when one notices that for charity and organization 
 (union-fee?) each it allowed per year five dollars, for the 
 services of physician or dentist or oculist twenty-five, and 
 about thirty dollars for recreation, amusement, and self- 
 improvement, one wonders how much solace the adjust- 
 ment really brought to the workers. Sixteen dollars a 
 week is not enough by any norm of living scientifically 
 sanctioned. It may be the best possible under prevailing 
 conditions, but it cannot satisfy our sense of fairness, or 
 the demands of those who compare individual earnings 
 with the aggregate social dividend. 
 
 Actual needs are not, furthermore, the same for all 
 people. If distribution is to meet needs rather than pro- 
 ductivity however measured the differences in men 
 and their occupations will have to be duly considered. It 
 will be one of the trying questions of socialism to find out 
 what is best for different people. When the variety of 
 goods is as great as in modern times the individuality of 
 taste has plenty of room for exhibition. There will be 
 differences according to temperament or sex, according to 
 age and condition of body and mind, according to climate 
 and season, and according to types of occupation. It 
 is not simply a matter of preferences such as may prop- 
 erly be ignored, but rather of habits the indulgence in 
 which may play a vital part in the productiveness of the 
 
THE LIMITS IN DISTRIBUTION 189 
 
 worker. It is a matter first of educating tastes correctly 
 by positive and negative means of control, and secondly 
 of adjusting the price of goods so that variety of taste 
 may be met to the satisfaction of the largest number. 
 For this reason price fixation will have but limited use- 
 fulness. It will be the duty of socialists to permit the 
 individual as much freedom in his purchase as seems to 
 agree with his personal welfare or with social efficiency, 
 but just where the two conflict it will not always be easy 
 to determine. 
 
CHAPTER VIII 
 THE LIMITS IN CONSUMPTION 
 
 i. The Nature of Consumption The subject of 
 consumption occupies a peculiar place in the history of 
 economic thought. It has from early times on been re- 
 garded as an integral part of the science of economics, 
 and yet its treatment has varied greatly. Some have 
 viewed consumption as a value aspect, some have ap- 
 pended it to treatises with the thought of showing the 
 bearing of extravagance on public revenues. Some have 
 given it scant courtesy in a discussion of wages, and oth- 
 ers have made it the key to distributive facts in general. 
 
 It does not matter what consumption means to the or- 
 thodox economist. The socialist is professedly governed 
 by the ethical interpretation which Ruskin summed up 
 sententiously if obscurely, in the phrase : " There is no 
 wealth but life." What life, we ask? 
 
 Socialism has helped men to find the objective tests of 
 social prosperity. It also has promoted a fitting regard 
 for the non-economic expressions of economic principles, 
 it some limits of consumption remain that socialists 
 often overlook, or deem extraneous to their subject mat- 
 Consumption should not be defined primarily as a loss of 
 values incurred m ttie production Ol 6theT Vklues, Of as 1 
 destruction of values or of physical things, though the 
 destruction of food for instance has deep significance for 
 the farmer who must replace it annually. A great many 
 commodities are not used up in the act of consumption, 
 
 190 
 
THE LIMITS IN CONSUMPTION 191 
 
 books and paintings and musical compositions and radium 
 and water power being examples. On the other hand, 
 wealth will deteriorate and crumble whether we use it or 
 not, and values competitively calculated may shrink and 
 expand, for instance the price of stocks, independent of 
 even the influence of weathering. 
 
 The real meaning of consumption from a social stand- 
 point is use for reaction physical and psychic. Whatever 
 we react upon is part of our environment. Whatever we 
 respond to has been in a sense an item for our consump- 
 tion. To consume by responding to stimuli, this is the 
 gravamen of life. Social science can do no more than 
 study the relation of stimuli from without and from within 
 in so far as they proceed from, or influence, our wealth re- 
 lations. Consumption is the act of absorbing and assimi- 
 lating things economic, food being converted into blood, 
 communication into knowledge applied, experiments into 
 habits becoming second nature. Consumption is the pro- 
 cess socially directed by which product is converted into 
 personality. 
 
 2. Consumption and Human Nature But the ef- 
 fetfts of consumption on human nature are not measurable 
 in the degree that socialists have now and then believed. 
 The economic interpretation of history may emphasize 
 the relation between economic income and psychic outgo, 
 but it should not induce us to expect the impossible. 
 Evolution is a process almost too slow for human com- 
 prehension. We might indicate its course by a line a foot 
 long and then add a wee speck to mark the historical 
 epoch of which man is, through records more or less re- 
 liable, a witness. The momentum of that long line of 
 tendencies is so great that no one century of reform can 
 overcome it. We must not count on the mutability of 
 human nature, because eons of time have gradually made 
 
192 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 it what it is. The economic interpretation of the past is 
 right when, judging by present experiences, it traces an 
 interrelation between environment and man, between food 
 conditions and physique or mental development; but it 
 errs if it ascribes to our historical economics an influence 
 over the shaping of human traits. These traits are much 
 older than history. They cannot be re-made by environ- 
 mental control, but only be used in such ways as will suit 
 the needs of the moment. 
 
 Socialism will not change human nature, though it turn 
 upside down the present order of things. The La- 
 marckian thought of the transmission of acquired charac- 
 ters has not so far met with a cordial reception, though 
 it has been put to many tests and made some friends 
 among authorities. For one thing, socialism is little af- 
 fected by the acceptance or rejection of Lamarckianism ; 
 for another the doctrine is, in its original and most con- 
 sequential form, discarded by modern biology. 
 
 Socialists like social scientists in general can afford to 
 ignore the Lamarckian idea because it revolves about pe- 
 riods of time in which contemporary science is not directly 
 interested. If acquired traits were immediately hered- 
 itary in a determinable way the socialist would have to 
 create his economic environment for each generation anew, 
 so as to offset what traits might have been transmitted 
 from parent to offspring. Either he does this, or he must 
 stabilize his environment so completely that all inherited 
 traits originated in an environment would suit all future 
 environments. But since life is continuous change 
 through interaction, and since all man-made environment 
 changes from decade to decade, the adjustment for each 
 generation would have to be made independent of the prior 
 one. New characters, new economic conditions, this would 
 be the recipe. 
 
THE LIMITS IN CONSUMPTION 196 
 
 But it appears at once that such a rapid acquisition of 
 traits would, first, make man much less stable than we 
 know him to be, and secondly, would give the reformer no 
 advantage, since good traits might speedily degenerate 
 into undesirable ones through a lack of proper environ- 
 ment control during one single generation. The breeder 
 of animals and plants would be similarly embarrassed if 
 Lamarckianism were so construed, and eugenics, of course, 
 could never hope to evolve a right mankind, because many 
 uncontrollable environmental influences would botch his 
 selections and cultures. 
 
 So it can only be a question as to what the environ- 
 ment accomplishes in the long run, say in the course of 
 millions of years. This view of Lamarckianism seems 
 the only logical one and has been given wide recognition 
 by experts. 
 
 3. The Biological View of Environment A bi- 
 ologist of note has defined an acquired character as a 
 " structural change in the body of a multicellular organ- 
 ism, involving a deviation from the normal and induced 
 during the individual lifetime by a change in environment 
 or in function, and such that it transcends the limits of 
 organic elasticity and therefore persists after the factors 
 inducing it have ceased to operate." In other words, 
 the proof of transmission by organic descent of an ac- 
 quired trait is the fact that it continues to function after 
 the factors responsible for its emergence have disappeared. 
 If the son acts as the father did, because of traits aroused 
 by the father's environment which, however, does not act 
 on the son, then the particular trait is inherited and the 
 acquired one has become organic. The precise problem 
 of biology is: Does such a transmission commonly take 
 place? Is the effect of environment upon offspring 
 i Thompson, J. A., "Heredity," p. 173. 
 
194 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 specific or general, direct through the germ-cell or indi- 
 rect via the body-cell, cumulative or non-cumulative in 
 the sense that the inherited trait is not intensified without 
 further environmental influences? 
 
 Now, the facts of cytology advise us against the ac- 
 ceptance of Lamarckianism. The view " that the germ- 
 plasm responds directly to the experiences of the body 
 has no substantial evidence in its support." And the 
 writer of these words adds : " I know of course that the 
 whole Lamarckian school rests its argument on the as- 
 sumption that the germ-plasm responds to all profound 
 changes in the soma ; but despite the very large literature 
 that has grown up dealing with this matter proof is still 
 lacking. And there is abundant evidence to the con- 
 trary." 2 
 
 Experiments speak in favor of, rather than against, 
 Weismann's doctrine of non-inheritance. The impossi- 
 bility of knowing, especially as regards human beings, 
 whether a trait is really congenital, and whether certain 
 environmental data are essential in the development of an 
 inherited trait acquired by the parent, militates indirectly 
 against Lamarckianism. But the facts first gathered by 
 Mendel, the Austrian amateur biologist, in his experi- 
 ments with the edible pea have enlarged our understanding 
 of the functions of bi-sexual reproduction so that to- 
 day, after years of investigation, agreement seems to have 
 been reached on the points most significant for social sci- 
 ence. 
 
 The seat of heredity has been traced to minute, ultra- 
 microscopic entities imbedded in the chromosomes which 
 in turn are part of the nucleus of every germ cell. It is 
 held that such unit factors must exist because without 
 them the results of hybridization remain inexplicable, 
 2 Morgan, Th. H., " Heredity and Sex," p. 17. 
 
THE LIMITS IN CONSUMPTION 195 
 
 while with them nearly the whole mystery of heredity, sex 
 determination not excepted, appears solved. Three pos- 
 tulates, according to an eminent authority, lie back of 
 the doctrine of unit-factors which determine plant and 
 animal traits, including those of the specie homo sapiens. 
 Namely the assumption that the factors are constants, that 
 two factors for each trait are lodged in the cell, and that 
 these factors segregate, or remain segregated in the ma- 
 turing germ-cell. Grant this, as the facts of the case urge 
 us to, and the riddle of inheritance offers no insurmount- 
 able difficulties. As Professor Morgan puts it : " The 
 validity of the unit-factor conception rests upon the fact 
 that whenever (as often happens) all other conditions, 
 external and internal that modify characters, remain con- 
 stant, then clear-cut ratios are obtained which can be ex- 
 plained only as due to segregation, in definite ways, of 
 particular hereditary factors that perpetuate themselves 
 unchanged from generation to generation." 3 
 
 The " factor " in the chromosome therefore is the fash- 
 ioner of human traits and in a sense, of history. Human 
 traits are built out of them, and each factor affects others 
 while it in turn may be affected from several sides. " A 
 single factor may have several effects, and a single char- 
 acter may depend on many factors ." 4 But " the real 
 unit in heredity is the factor, while the character is the 
 product of a number of genetic factors and of environ- 
 mental conditions." 5 Which is to say, what practically 
 all geneticists admit, that the influence of the environ- 
 ment is real, though indeterminate and indirect. To 
 quote once more from Professor Morgan : " There is a 
 small amount of evidence, very incomplete and insufficient 
 
 s Morgan, Th. H., " The Mechanism of Mendelian Heredity," p. 47. 
 * Ibidem, p. 210. 
 s Ibidem. 
 
196 THE LIMITS OF , SOCIALISM 
 
 at present, to show that changes in the environment reach 
 through the soma and modify the germinal material." 6 
 The extreme view, therefore, that " by the shuffle and deal 
 of the hereditary factors in the formation of two of these 
 cells in fertilization our hereditary natures were forever 
 sealed " 7 should give way to more moderate notions of 
 a primary influence working hand in hand with a sec- 
 ondary from outside. 
 
 The fundamental fact is the interaction of the de- 
 terminers in the chromosomes. Each factor will bear on 
 the other. " An overstatement to the effect that each fac- 
 tor may affect the entire body is less likely to do harm 
 than to state that each factor affects only a particular 
 character." 8 But in addition we have the circuitous 
 route of outside forces in reaching the germ-cell. Human 
 nature is affected from the outside, by post-natal experi- 
 ences, so that the offspring will manifest the result; but 
 the effects are general. No ratio between experience and 
 variation in particular traits can be established. " The 
 effect is general rather than specific, and the result as 
 seen in the offspring has no discoverable correlation with 
 any particular part or structure of the parental soma." 9 
 
 Furthermore, the number of possible combinations by 
 these factors is so immense that, if their shuffling and 
 permutations fashion the characters recognized by man, 
 it is well possible to obtain countless shades and varia- 
 tions, even supposing the environment had no force what- 
 soever. The chief result of bisexual reproduction is a 
 
 Morgan, Th. H., " Heredity and Sex," p. 18. 
 
 7Conklin, E. G., "Heredity and Environment," p. 463. (I. Edit.) 
 
 s Morgan. Th. H., " Critique of the Theory of Evolution," p. 72. 
 
 Guyer, M. F., " Being Wellborn," p. 135. Similarly Thorndike, 
 E. L., "Educational Psychology," Volume III, p. 310. But for a 
 leading authority against the Weismannian view see Cope, E. D., 
 "Primary Factors of Organic Evolution," especially pp. 392-443. 
 
THE LIMITS IN CONSUMPTION 197 
 
 much greater diversification of traits than a sexual life 
 permitted. But it also brings about the ratios first ob- 
 served by Mendel, and other ratios which, though orig- 
 inally interpreted as exceptions to the rule, soon were 
 explained as results of combinations unsuspected by 
 Mendel. In the long run, on the principle of chance vari- 
 ations, regularity in appearance of traits was inevitable. 
 Dependent upon the number of factors, and upon their 
 bundling in the formation of unit-characters, parents 
 would bequeath traits to their offspring in fixed propor- 
 tion. Per thousand or million of inhabitants such and 
 such traits would recur with astonishing regularity. In- 
 deed, the logical bearing of the laws of probability and 
 error upon genetics has been acknowledged with en- 
 thusiasm in support of eugenic programs. In the words 
 of one geneticist : " Nothing is clearer than that the 
 inevitable consequences of bisexual reproduction and of 
 the manner of growth by the halving of the cell-con- 
 tents is to insure that character-combinations, effected in 
 this manner, are brought together in definite mathematical 
 proportions not far from those expressed in the expan- 
 sion of the binomial. This is the real foundation of 
 Mendel's law for characters that do not blend, and it also 
 expresses the relative proportions of characters that do 
 blend." 10 
 
 The latter is the most important point for socialism. 
 It does not matter whether a human trait is deemed a 
 unit in the cytological sense or not. All traits recur on 
 the principle of average and frequency of errors as 
 mathematicians understand the terms. " The differences 
 in hereditary endowment of strength or intelligence, 
 of stature or longevity, of fertility or social disposition, 
 have a certain regularity of distribution, so far as we can 
 
 10 Davenport, E., " Principles of Breeding," p. 546. 
 
198 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 measure them at all. They conform to what is called the 
 Normal Law of Frequency ." n In this sense, there- 
 fore, human nature is constant. Our experiences in 
 everyday life are confirmed. Historians hear their own 
 verdict repeated, and reformers know what not to expect 
 from reforms. 
 
 It is not likely that the abolition of private property 
 will affect posterity through the living generation, ex- 
 cept by way of social heredity. Organic heredity will 
 play no part in the change. Genius will be more plenti- 
 ful perhaps, and certainly types of subnormality ought 
 to become rarer, but we can no more measure a crop of 
 genius by economic income than we can improve the 
 human race unerringly by the application of genetics to 
 society. 
 
 In the case of genius we have still to acknowledge that 
 the occupation of parents and grandparents seems to 
 have exercised no measurable influence upon the direction 
 genius took, and that the characteristics of one eco- 
 nomic period have never given us a clue as to the sorts 
 of genius born in the next epoch. We only know that 
 superior civilizations have excelled in the production of 
 genius, and that these titans of intellect themselves ad- 
 vanced the thought of their age. We do not know 
 whether genius is a mutation in the biological sense, 
 or whether it should be classed as a normal fluctuation, 
 non-hereditary and insignificant for evolutionary pur- 
 poses. 
 
 Fluctuations have been defined as continuous variations 
 " which are graded, the extremes being connected by a 
 complete series of intermediate conditions." 12 A Muta- 
 tion according to one authority, is " a discontinuous 
 
 11 Thompson, J. A., "Heredity" (2nd Edit.), p. 523. 
 
 12 Castle, W. E., " Genetics and Eugenics," p. 56. 
 
THE LIMITS IN CONSUMPTION 199 
 
 germinal change arising from a physical or chemical alter- 
 ation in the structure of the organism, or of one or both 
 of the germ-cells which produce a new individual, or from 
 such a change arising in certain cells elsewhere in the life- 
 cycle of the organism, this change being capable of com- 
 plete inheritance at least in some of the offspring, 
 although reversion may occur in others." 13 What is 
 known of genius might be classed with either definition, 
 but it does not matter much because mental traits are not 
 known to be subject to Mendelian laws of heredity. The 
 cultivation of genius, that is of types of men most in- 
 fluential in the development of races, cannot as yet be 
 considered a subject for science. 
 
 The scope and usefulness of eugenics is, in fact, seri- 
 ously limited by several gaps in our knowledge of the or- 
 ganism. We do not know exactly what constitutes a 
 human unit character, though it is agreed that a single 
 mental trait is compounded of probably many factors in 
 the germ-cell. 14 It is of first importance to ascertain the 
 correlation of good characters, or of the good with the 
 bad, so the latter may be culled out if possible; but the 
 data for such procedure are altogether lacking. It is 
 admitted that human beings, unlike lower forms of life, 
 continue to grow mentally long after physical growth has 
 stopped. In many cases mentality develops most rapidly 
 after the mating age has normally passed, say from the 
 thirtieth year on. It would therefore be a mistake to 
 judge the fitness or excellence of a mating couple purely 
 by its qualifications at the date of marriage. And again, 
 the means of detecting inherent faults and of regulating 
 marriage are exceedingly uncertain. It will always be 
 
 is Gates, R. R., " Tne Mutation Factor in Evolution." 
 i* See e.g., Thorndike, E. L., "Educational Psychology," Volume 
 III, p. 268. 
 
200 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 difficult to accomplish in the breeding of humans what the 
 animal breeder has already achieved. 
 
 And finally there will be much disputing as to what 
 the desired type of manhood or womanhood is. What 
 kind of man is wanted? This is the paramount question 
 which the combined training of natural and social 
 scientists may not enable us to answer. There exist no 
 records by which we may be guided. Each group of ex- 
 perts will describe the ideal man, and in many points the 
 agreement of groups will be ample. 15j But on others no 
 unanimity will be reached. History and sociology only 
 teach the predominance of several types of men, and the 
 apparent necessity of a large number of types for the at- 
 tainment of unusual things. Civilization needs many 
 kinds of people. Specialization should not be coun- 
 selled merely as a precept in education, but if it were 
 possible the eugenist should seek to produce strains highly 
 specialized, so our learning period may be shortened or 
 natural aptitude bring greater results. 
 
 A change of the proportion in which different types of 
 men now are born must plainly have a momentous effect 
 upon future history. But the eugenist seems as help- 
 less in this matter as the socialist. Both must acknowl- 
 edge their limitations. Genetics has not yet furnished 
 us a clue to the elimination of all the unfit, and socialism 
 cannot hope to root out all evils in social life by rooting 
 out private capital. Socialists, however, have the ad- 
 vantage in that the direct and indirect influence of the en- 
 vironment upon the living organism is known and often 
 measurable. Socialists will always have a large field for 
 
 is For leading classifications of People according to dominant 
 traits see, for instance, Ratzenhofer, G., " Soziologische Erkenntnis"; 
 Patten, S. N., "Development of English Thought"; and Giddings, 
 F. H., " Inductive Sociology." 
 
THE LIMITS IN CONSUMPTION 201 
 
 action regardless of what eugenics may claim for itself. 
 The more fickle human nature, the more important a 
 right economic environment for each living generation. 
 The more constant human nature, the more pressing mani- 
 festly our duty to adapt man to his environment and to 
 redirect his inclinations as the facts of social science ad- 
 vise. The economist, like the socialist, cannot lose by 
 any answer finally given to the Lamarckian query, but 
 in the light of current investigations the necessity of 
 sound economy and of wise government seems more obvious 
 than ever before. The variables lie outside of man viewed 
 socially, for while variation is fully as significant as 
 heredity, the law of probability applied to the workings 
 of the hereditary mechanism assures us of a fairly con- 
 stant distribution of departures from type. Some traits 
 are shared by all men. The instincts may be classed 
 among them, though their degree of strength varies. 
 About the more universal we group the less universal 
 human traits. Special deviations occur, but not fre- 
 quently. The more marked a deviation the rarer it is. 
 Thus the core of human nature seems to remain the same. 
 Doubtless it only seems to, for everything changes, the 
 fundamental traits of man not excluded. But the change 
 is so gradual that we do not notice it. It is as with the 
 sun which is said to move toward a far out point in the 
 cosmos. We picture it in motion, and yet make it a con- 
 stant because of the revolution and rotation of the earth, 
 which is so much more in evidence. We ignore the move- 
 ment of the central body and heed only those of our own 
 planet. Human nature may be called a constant for 
 much the same reason. 
 
 4. Income and Efficiency What we can do with 
 men by raising their income is a problem each generation 
 
202 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 must solve anew, 16 but the uncontrollable recurrence of 
 types manifestly sets bounds to our reforms. We should 
 not expect to double efficiency because we double library 
 facilities, and we should not guarantee people happiness 
 because we have added to their creature comforts. The 
 powers of response to economic stimuli such as goods em- 
 body cannot be arbitrarily developed, though something 
 may be done with them. The circumstance thfct all ex- 
 periences are interrelations should convince us of the 
 fatuity of adjustments in one quarter only. It takes 
 more than one element in education to arouse our dor- 
 mant faculties, and it takes many combinations of per- 
 sonal traits and objective facts to make man contented. 
 Perhaps we shall succeed in mastering some of them, but 
 not all. 
 
 In so far as the end of consumption is the development 
 of innate powers for actI6rT7"a sufficient economic income 
 is of course a prerequisite. But since only that is part 
 of our world which we react to. consciously or uncon- 
 sciously, much income is sure to be wasted. It will bring 
 no psychic returns. It may ufldeT special direction b'e 
 used to stimulate reactions and intensify them, but in it- 
 self it may remain inert. Either the initiative is inborn, 
 or it must come from outside through the facts of socia- 
 tion in general and of education in particular. 
 
 Nothing is more familiar than the sight of people who 
 command wealth, but stand helpless not knowing what to 
 do with it. People are surrounded with art treasures, 
 but derive no benefit from them. Opportunity beckons 
 them on all sides, but they will not be inspired. Exten- 
 
 iThe effect of social environment on genius and achievement is 
 stressed notably by Ward, L. F., in his "Pure Sociology," and in 
 his later "Applied Sociology," where Chapter 9 deals with an 
 eminent French study on this subject. 
 
THE LIMITS IN CONSUMPTION 203 
 
 sive travels yield no lasting productive impressions. 
 They see but do not understand. They listen, but do not 
 heed. They associate with the best, but fail to assimilate 
 the best. Suggestions come to them from all sides, but 
 nothing valuable is constructed out of them. 
 
 Many scientists worked without funds or apparatus and 
 laboratory, yet they opened up new and large fields of 
 investigatfon the results of which we call modern civiliza- 
 tion. It is not the number of facts mastered by Aristotle 
 that put him in a class by himself, for many a youth to- 
 day has more of them at his fingers' ends than the in- 
 ventor of the syllogism had ever heard of. Rather it was | 
 what he put into the few facts he knew, the meaning he 
 gave them by properly correlating them, and the rules of 
 conduct he deduced from them in his search for a richer 
 life. A Newton could invent calculus to solve self-imposed 
 problems of physics and astronomy. A Galileo or 
 Lavoisier or Faraday or Helmholz could found a new 
 science without the aid of expensive instruments. 
 
 We shall always have with us the thinkers and the 
 tinkers, those who blaze a trail and lead us to new realms 
 of wonder, and those who patch up matters for a while, 
 but are useful in no finer sense. We shall probably al- 
 ways have men of renown and the mediocre who shine by 
 reflected light. Education will help the slow-witted but 
 it cannot lift them far above their level. Curricula do not 
 make scholars, nor can tutors make wise men out of fools. 
 
 The progress of science and of educational facilities 
 during the last hundred years testifies eloquently to the 
 worth of great men. In some measure, too, it has bene- 
 fited the man of average ability, though he has not been 
 given the chance that he should have. It is not then a 
 point of questioning the importance of education. On the 
 contrary, leaders in the future will wish to vulgarize it 
 
204 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 more than ever, and do it in a thoroughly democratic 
 manner. Even if much time is wasted in culling the 
 talented from the incompetent, even if the best pupils 
 should suffer from the partialities shown to the dunces, it 
 is better that we raise the general level of intelligence an 
 inch than that of a chosen few a foot. 
 
 But on the other hand it must be admitted that school- 
 ing has limited functions. The recent multiplication of 
 institutions of learning, of art works and museums, of 
 public libraries and of free lectures for the delectation of 
 curious folk has not brought the results that might have 
 been offhand expected. The response often has been half- 
 hearted and insincere. The fruits have not repaid for the 
 labors of cultivation. The instructor has not found his 
 audience react in a scientific spirit. Education has even 
 spoiled some for lines of work they were naturally fitted 
 for, while many who went without a long drilling in techni- 
 cal subjects have nonetheless emerged out of the struggle 
 for life with a creditable showing, both in earning money 
 and in contributing toward the world's welfare. At all 
 times, it may be said, education has played a less vital 
 part in the development of exceptional personalities than 
 the friends of erudition have liked to confess. 
 
 Printing has practically done away with illiteracy, but 
 not with paucity of ideas. Books nowadays are cheap, 
 but thinking is still rare. People have garnered rich 
 stores of fact, but failed to build with them. They have 
 remembered, but not applied knowledge intelligently. In- 
 telligence comes slowly. Intelligence is the power of con- 
 quering unforeseen obstacles in theory or practice. In- 
 telligence is the chief weapon of modern times for defense 
 and offense in production. The number of those who have 
 learned to imitate or to understand what was taught at 
 school grows steadily, but the ability to formulate new 
 
THE LIMITS IN CONSUMPTION 205 
 
 problems calling for new solutions is always rare. 
 
 Yet, because education is so important and leisure a 
 prerequisite to it, socialists rightly insist upon an exten- 
 sion of both. The question thus arises: How shall the 
 additional amount of spare time be used? For rest and 
 entertainment, yes. But also for development of the 
 self and of a social sense. Increasingly the last genera- 
 tion of workers has had spare time for all of these pur- 
 poses, but past experience does not permit one to hope 
 that the granting in itself of leisure will suffice. The 
 cheapening of consumption goods has sometimes cheap- 
 ened also our appreciations of art and science. And 
 similarly additional leisure may be abused unless socialism 
 provides the right sort of guidance. One is impressed 
 with the limitations of possession, that is of income, when 
 one watches the way in which people utilize it. To listen 
 to popular music played on the automatic piano, for in- 
 stance, or to the graphophone is to lose faith in the power 
 of riches. Taste has been little improved, but shallow- 
 ness is daily encouraged. The magazines still pander to 
 frivolous inclinations and thoughtless readers. The 
 " best seller " is proverbially an inferior piece of litera- 
 ture, and no doubt will remain so. The masses do not fre- 
 quent our museums, though they have plenty of time for 
 trivialities. The stage does not appeal unless music is 
 reduced to oddities of rhythm and the play made a farce 
 or a melodrama. Everywhere we see tricks of trade 
 prosper, but true art perish. 
 
 Up to the present this may have been an inevitable 
 result of our educational system, or of the stigma put 
 upon serious endeavor in pastimes. But if socialism is 
 to elevate social welfare to its noblest heights and give 
 maximum health and intellectual vigor to all, it will have 
 to revise the leisure schedule also. Much teaching in this 
 
206 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 direction will be needed; much patience and sacrifice on 
 the part of the most highly gifted. Formal schooling will 
 help, but a public supervision of amusements, a fostering 
 of a community spirit for mutual enjoyment and aid will 
 do even more. The socializing functions of play and art 
 have not yet been fully recognized. The charm of en- 
 joying goods in common has not been sufficiently revealed 
 to us because the private property concept has made 
 us suspicious where we should have been open-minded. 
 Leisure may invigorate body and mind, or it may cloy our 
 senses and kill ambition. The habits of the wealthy 
 should be a warning in this respect. They, too, have 
 made less use of their opportunities than seems right. 
 Even among them time drags and ennui is a malady. For 
 lack of natural capacities income and leisure have re- 
 mained sterile. It has brought no fruit because the inner 
 means of response were not developed. 
 
 5. Income and Happiness. What is true of the 
 limits of consumption in developing efficiency and a proper 
 use of consumables is also true of the relation between 
 pleasure and riches. Socialism will not add greatly to 
 happiness, though by objective tests our level of living 
 will be higher. But as remarked before, the objective 
 tests may disagree with the subjective. It is time that 
 people dissociate pleasure from prosperity and judge 
 each by its own indications. 
 
 Pleasure as the opposite of pain has of course been 
 eulogized ever since men have breathed and pondered on 
 final values. The cynics of old thought nothing worth 
 while. They belonged to an age in which the old faith 
 was crumbling and the new knowledge was not able to fill 
 an emotional void. When belief in the gods goes and 
 doubt permeates all fields of inquiry a resort to cynicism 
 is natural. Energy must have an outlet somewhere. But 
 
THE LIMITS IN CONSUMPTION 207 
 
 it might seem strange that even in modern days 
 philosophers have returned to the calculus of pleasure and 
 pain, were it not that they kept in mind the need of uni- 
 versalizing pleasure, instead of centering it in the in- 
 dividual, and that they reasoned from premises no longer 
 accepted by science. They hoped to make all states of 
 feeling quantitatively measurable so that avoidance of 
 pain became the equivalent of pleasure. They sought to 
 please the largest possible number, and aimed at better- 
 ment for that reason, seeing that the masses then had 
 many duties and few privileges. 
 
 Hedonism, however, has gone the way of other dogmas. 
 It rendered the eighteenth century a service, since it pre- 
 pared the way for Enlightenment and the French Revolu- 
 tion, but it no longer meets our requirements because we 
 know that not all feelings can be classified and compared 
 like so many yards of ribbon. The weakness of every 
 subjective norm is its elusiveness. We cannot tell when 
 people are happy. Or if we do dare to, we may be as- 
 sured quite to the contrary. States of feeling cannot 
 satisfy the student of welfare unless they have an ob- 
 jective correlate, the ratio of the two being more or less 
 definite. But such is not the case. 
 
 There are pains akin to pleasure, and states of happi- 
 ness that bring an undercurrent of chagrin. Just as sick 
 men have been known to work creatively and enjoy life 
 though stricken with agonizing diseases, so trying ex- 
 ternal conditions have at times been forgotten over the 
 pleasures of work or of buoyant energy. Brief pleasures 
 have brought lasting misery to some, and painful moments 
 have been deliberately courted because they promised en- 
 joyment thereafter. The miser rejoices in the misery of 
 his greed, and the prodigal bemoans his fate while squand- 
 ering all. 
 
208 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 Pleasures cannot be measured by income alone, and if 
 they could be it would not mean anything for science, for 
 socialism, of for social welfare. Happiness is not always 
 the same as pleasure, if by the latter we mean sensa- 
 tions externally stimulated. But for the most part those 
 who are pleased are happy. It is difficult to tell one from 
 the other, unless we arbitrarily consider one a selfish in- 
 dulgence, and the second an emotion socially sanctioned. 
 But such distinctions are of little import. 
 
 The main fact is our inability to create happy states 
 of being at will. We can promote happiness only by pop- 
 ularizing health, wealth, and efficiency. In the long run 
 health means enjoyment. On an average the well-fed and 
 properly clothed suffer less pain than the paupers who 
 have nothing. As a general rule the most intelligent and 
 efficient have sources of happiness not possessed by the 
 helpless. 
 
 Yet, whether education and intelligence offer compen- 
 sations in the way of happiness for the pleasures common 
 among the ignorant is doubtful. Perhaps it would not 
 be too much to say that happiness is essentially an attri- 
 bute of youth. When we are young and strong, when 
 energy is at a maximum and the power of resisting hard- 
 ships great, then we enjoy life. Happiness is for those 
 in the early stages of life when the blood flows swift in 
 our veins and the metabolic process quickly replaces waste 
 tissue and poisons. Youth means ignorance and in- 
 nocence, and both are sources of contentment. Happi- 
 ness should not be felt, to be real. When we begin to rea- 
 son about it we probably have lost it. In this sense 
 happiness is youth remembered by old age. 
 
 In later life however many sources of happiness arise 
 that childhood is a stranger to. The compensations for 
 toil and duress, for doubt and worries, come in the shape 
 
THE LIMITS IN CONSUMPTION 209 
 
 of creative work or of success in conquering a self-im- 
 posed difficulty. Self-measured success is the acme of 
 happiness. We learn to master ourselves and to help 
 others. There is leadership and a happy home, or friend- 
 ship and convivialities intellectual or otherwise. There is 
 relaxation and a venting of energy at games. We have 
 the applause of the multitude, and affection for and from 
 others. All these are types of contentment constituting 
 in the aggregate a happy state of life. If the Jefferson- 
 ian phrase ever meant anything it must have meant such 
 things, although the thought of rating public welfare by 
 such personal rights and reactions spoiled much of the 
 effect which this creed had upon a later generation. 
 
 But if happiness may come so independent of income it 
 clearly may vanish also without regard to income. There 
 are occasions for unhappiness that no one system of pro- 
 duction or consumption will remove. Most of our 
 troubles, indeed, come from within. At any rate we may 
 call the environment, in this connection, a constant and 
 declare our feelings variable according to our inborn pre- 
 dispositions. We are annoyed by trifles in personal re- 
 lations. We chafe at restraints and slights that even the 
 equalization of wealth and ability cannot rid us of. 
 Human traits are such as to make a certain amount of 
 friction unavoidable. We are bound to struggle and 
 suffer in a measure. Comparisons will always be odious, 
 and failure to accomplish what we set out to do will irri- 
 tate us to the quick. Envy and suspicion, peevishness and 
 false pride embitter the life of many. There is no cure 
 except through gradual adjustment with the aid of edu- 
 cation ; or perhaps still more so, through breeding accord- 
 ing to temperament. Eugenics might in this regard ac- 
 complish what economics and socialism must give up as a 
 hopeless task. 
 
210 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 Socialism, in fine, can help the masses greatly by 
 economic control since leisure, education, health and 
 efficiency go inseparably together. But it would be folly 
 to expect a millennium of happiness for people simply 
 because we have bettered the objective facts of living. 
 The aim of the reformer cannot be happiness; it must be 
 achievement and welfare socially measured. But that is 
 far from ensuring the average man greater bliss con- 
 sciously felt. 
 
CHAPTER IX 
 THE LIMITS IN GOVERNMENT 
 
 i. The Relation of Empiricism to Political Democ- 
 racy. The Communist Manifesto of 1848 concluded with 
 the memorable words : " Workingmen of all the world, 
 unite." It was the final and most stirring appeal of the 
 founders of socialism to the masses whose slavery they 
 hoped to end by a revolution. The nation was not 
 recognized by Marx as the indispensable unit of social 
 life. The fact of the brotherhood of men everywhere was 
 to displace it and make nationalism unnecessary. 
 
 Yet it was significant that the fiery words of Engels 
 and Marx were addressed to the international proletariat 
 for a battle against capitalism. The call was not for 
 peace; it was for war on the exploiters who must be 
 subjugated first before the brotherhood of men could be- 
 come real. Socialism, thus, introduced the idea of cos- 
 mopolitanism with a reminder of class struggle, and it ex- 
 pected to establish democracy only by throwing out of 
 the saddle the proud managers of big business. This 
 was a gain and a loss both. It marked an advance over 
 old ideals because the test of democracy was sought in 
 something more important than the right to cast a 
 ballot, and it seemed a step backward because a supposed 
 iron law of wages was to be abrogated by iron force. 
 So the adherents of socialism long interpreted the Mani- 
 festo, and with this thought of a revolution quickening 
 the pace of evolution they went to work. 
 
 Socialism is a clarion call to action for liberating the 
 
 211 
 
THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 masses. The proof of true socialism is the fraternizing 
 of all men regardless of race or color or nationality, and 
 the extension of the principle of equal rights to all 
 spheres of social activity. Socialism is nothing if not 
 economic democracy internationalized. 
 
 What can be said for democracy and internationalism? 
 
 The thought of democracy doubtless is as old as 
 history, though the word was not coined till the Greeks 
 learned to reflect on the problems of city government. 
 Aristotle then made his distinctions of types of govern- 
 ment and gave reasons for preferring a moderate form of 
 democracy in which the people had a nominal share, but 
 which was really in the hands of a selected few, to 
 monarchy. Democracy as the rule of the people was thus 
 early construed to mean a government by the few for the 
 many. 
 
 It was important, however, that the Greeks were the 
 first to trace the origin of society, for in this way they 
 hit upon the ideal of a state of nature in which all men 
 had been free and equal. The sovereign, they averred, 
 was in those primordial days either the father of the 
 family, or the strongest, most assertive and capable at a 
 crisis. Sovereignty therefore came to signify absolute 
 power, and this has been its main attribute ever since. 
 He is sovereign who has no superior, who exercises his 
 power as he pleases, and who rules by his own initiative, 
 whatever assent expressed or tacit may come from the 
 governed. 
 
 The ingenious notion of a compact whereby the free- 
 men living in a state of nature, protected solely by their 
 personal strength and cunning, relinquished their liberties 
 for the sake of ending interminable feuds, added ma- 
 terially to the reputation of Greek philosophy, besides ex- 
 ercising a lasting influence over the development of modern 
 
THE LIMITS IN GOVERNMENT 213 
 
 politics. From the seventeenth to the latter part of the 
 eighteenth century nothing seemed so self evident as that 
 people, having been originally endowed by their creator 
 with certain inalienable rights, could have given them up 
 only on terms suitable to themselves, self -protection and 
 the promotion of the social welfare being plainly among 
 the aims of government. It followed from this amplifica- 
 tion of an ancient doctrine that the overthrow of the 
 divine right theory of kings was a duty rather than an 
 act of sedition. 
 
 The development of natural science strengthened this 
 view of the situation. The founders of physics, 
 astronomy, and biology were men who had little patience 
 with the metaphysical viewpoint. Their concern was the 
 investigation of facts and the establishment of laws by 
 the experimental methods. Where induction was out of 
 the question, the time-honored syllogism did its work, but 
 it was understood that no matter how philosophy might 
 proceed it would start with certain assumptions that 
 begged the ultimate questions professedly answered. In 
 this spirit the empiricists before long became materialists 
 who considered the world a huge mechanism, and some- 
 what in harmony with this realistic attitude they also 
 treated problems in social life. They favored the utili- 
 tarian notion that government is for the governed. They 
 found in the theory of a compact between people and 
 sovereign nothing very objectionable. They were with- 
 out exception opposed to crass monarchism and took for 
 granted the limitations that gradually were placed upon 
 the Crown. 
 
 The idealists in philosophy, on the contrary, stood with 
 the exception of the gentle Spinoza for state-rights, that 
 is to say for the supremacy of the body politic whose head 
 wielded unrestricted powers. Descartes, Leibniz, Wolff, 
 
214 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 Kant and Hegel all belonged to this class of thinkers 
 whose tracts on government reflected the absolutistic 
 spirit, not only of their political masters, but also of their 
 own metaphysical doctrines. The difference in this re- 
 spect between the idealists and empiricists has not been 
 widely noticed or frankly admitted, but the materials for a 
 testing can be easily collected. Broadly speaking one may 
 draw the line of demarcation as suggested: The one 
 group unfailingly championed constitutionalism in prac- 
 tice no less than in theory, the other, namely the meta- 
 physicians, leaned toward political absolutism, even if 
 ostensibly with some reservations in the other direction. 
 But needless to say, the advocates of popular sovereignty 
 had the better of it. Rousseau's notion of the general will 
 of the people won out. 
 
 It carried the day first because it fell in logically with 
 the general trend of scientific investigations, and secondly 
 because of the change in economic conditions that is some- 
 times described by the phrase The Industrial Revolution. 
 This event inevitably favored the laboring classes in that 
 its success presupposed certain individual economic rights, 
 whose counterpart was the principle of universal suffrage 
 and of legislation in accord with public opinion. Autoc- 
 racy could not hold itself in the face of such changes, 
 though as against this it must be confessed that democ- 
 racy soon received a setback also. 
 
 For it lay in the nature of the new economic situation 
 that the propertied classes held sway over the masses. 
 To be sure, the qualifications for voting or holding a seat 
 in the legislature were soon removed or, as in the United 
 States, never obtained legal recognition. But the en- 
 franchisement was at bottom more nominal than real, 
 since there was as yet no possibility for the poor people 
 to hold office or to swing a vote against the concerted 
 
THE LIMITS IN GOVERNMENT 215 
 
 action of the rich industrials and the landed aristocracy. 
 Those who held the purse controlled the government more 
 than ever. The vaunted signs of popular sovereignty 
 proved to be pleasant deceptions that could not compen- 
 sate the masses for their impotence in the legislative halls. 
 As the decades have rolled by observers have become more 
 and more convinced that something else is needed than 
 the universal ballot to ensure a rule of the people by the 
 people, supposing that such a motto is really recommend- 
 able. 
 
 As one American writer has recently put it : " Uni- 
 versal suffrage has not given us a democratic industrial 
 system. The enfranchised many have failed to translate 
 their democratic ideals into economic fact." * If it is 
 true, as W. Godwin believed in his own day, that " de- 
 mocracy is a system of government according to which 
 every member of society is considered as a man, and noth- 
 ing more," 2 then we are not anywhere near our goal, the 
 use of the representative principle of government notwith- 
 standing. 
 
 But of course the real question is: How far should 
 government be turned over to the populace, to a plebiscite 
 on public problems, and what is the verdict of social 
 science as to the scope of popular rule? 
 
 The pamphleteers of the period of Enlightenment, it is 
 evident, had no appreciation of the real nature of the sub- 
 ject they discussed so glibly now to vindicate absolutism, 
 now to forfend the rights of the citizen. To them man 
 was a finished product of reason chiefly, and society a 
 state designed calculatingly by its members at an early 
 
 1 Hamilton, W. H., "The Price System and Social Policy," in 
 Journal of Political Economy for Jan., 1918. 
 
 2 Godwin, W., " Inquiry Concerning Political Justice," Book Five, 
 Chapter 14, where Aristotle's famous definition of democracy is cited 
 with approval. 
 
216 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 stage of human development. The historical sense had 
 not yet been cultivated. The perspective was that of the 
 artist who studies a completed picture, rather than that 
 of a traveler who beholds everchanging scenes and new 
 possibilities for investigation. To the absolutists, if gov- 
 ernment was divinely ordained, harmony between monarch 
 and subject must in the long run prevail. As for the con- 
 stitutionalist, especially if he accepted the theory of a 
 social contract, a clash of interests could be quickly set- 
 tled by a resort to arms, but he supposed after all that 
 the contract had been so lucidly drawn up, in full view 
 of the inborn and inalienable rights of man, that an 
 estrangement between the two parties was not to be ex- 
 pected. 
 
 But the modern view of the situation cannot be quite 
 so simple. 
 
 Manifestly government and people cannot associate so 
 fraternally on a level as the publicists pictured it. 
 Rather, the two will unavoidably, in a certain sense, be- 
 come strangers for the same reason that boards of di- 
 rectors over a large corporation move in a world differ- 
 ent from that of the employees. It is not a question of 
 class privileges or of social stratification, but of special- 
 ization in work and interests. 
 
 A government becomes a piece of social machinery 
 apart from the general run of people because of the type 
 of men composing it and because of its duties which eo 
 ipso imply unique viewpoints. A government, if it func- 
 tions long enough undisturbedly, will accumulate secrets 
 of trade just as truly as a business concern, and in addi- 
 tion it is bound, in the very nature of its work, to guard 
 important secrets of international relations. Within 
 limits all governments are self-perpetuating bodies, for no 
 change of party or power of ballot can prevent the rise 
 
THE LIMITS IN GOVERNMENT 
 
 of an elite which, on account of its capacities and experi- 
 ence, tends to keep close to the throne, distributing offices 
 among its members. Government cannot be anything else 
 than a business, if by that term we designate a routine 
 of work and a center of interests relative to which all 
 others appear secondary. The governors must act fre- 
 quently as though their interests were undeniably the con- 
 cern of all the governed, even when a difference of opinion 
 might arise at a testing. This is the fundamental fact in 
 the handling of international matters, and on this score 
 the monarchists of old condemned popular sovereignty. 
 
 But furthermore, Government ere long means for any 
 nation a set of rules solemnly recorded and carefully pre- 
 served. It becomes a code of conduct revered by the 
 people, who are taught to regard nothing more sacred 
 than the laws of the land, even though they challenge 
 science and common sense. Government to many people 
 becomes an institution and a habit, a court of wisdom and 
 a seat of coercive power from which there is no appeal. 
 The average man gives his assent by obeying. That is his 
 way of proving his rights of citizenship unless a special 
 occasion arises. 
 
 2. The Premises of Democracy. But in a deeper 
 sense the millions can only be indirect agents of govern- 
 ment, not the immediate supervisors of it, as once was 
 believed. 
 
 Democracy is an ideal of government essential to the 
 progress of man, but based on assumptions for the most 
 part in conflict with known facts. The value of democ- 
 racy is therefore not its literal interpretation, but its psy- 
 chological effect upon people who would do more than they 
 can, who need encouragement the more marked their limit- 
 ation, and who should have the abstraction of justice on 
 their side no matter how difficult its realization in details. 
 
218 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 The premises of democracy are, first, that all people 
 know what is needed for public welfare, second, that all 
 people express their will at the voting booth, and third, 
 that all those elected to office will do the bidding of the 
 people. If we grant these three points we are safe in de- 
 manding an unreserved literal exercising of popular 
 sovereignty, but the less faith we have in the postulates 
 the more we shall be inclined to favor a democracy for the 
 people by some, but not by all, of the people. If the 
 great majority were qualified to pass judgment on politi- 
 cal problems, and if, having formed a judicious opinion, 
 they proceeded to express that and nothing else with the 
 understanding that their nominees would carry out to the 
 fullest of their abilities the opinion and wishes recorded in 
 the ballot, then the more truly representative a govern- 
 ment would be, the finer the results for all parties con- 
 cerned. The theory of democracy allows itself consid- 
 erable license in the premises for the sale of a noble wish ! 
 
 The obstacles to such unhampered democracy are how- 
 ever many; and they are of a kind calculated to instill 
 much respect. 
 
 For as to the first premise we can admittedly not rely 
 on intuitions. What is sound policy for a nation can- 
 not be inferred from scruples of conscience, nor is it to 
 be read from the heavens above. Social phenomena are 
 of all correlations the most complex. We have not yet 
 progressed far in mastering them. We may never feel 
 toward them as the physicist feels about his facts of 
 matter and force or motion. It requires long training 
 and deep attention to seeming trifles to form an opinion 
 of worth on matters sociological. Many facts must be 
 balanced and compared; far more facts than the natural 
 scientist ordinarily reckons with. Hence the uncertainty 
 
THE LIMITS IN GOVERNMENT 
 
 of some rules in social inquiries, and hence the need of 
 prolonged study for the would be citizen. 
 
 But the schooling of the masses has been hitherto un- 
 fair to them. It has been faulty for several reasons, one 
 being a one-sided emphasis on subjects remote from our 
 present environment, and a second the exclusion of the 
 great majority from the higher curricula. Education 
 uptodate could never have been adequate to all ideals or 
 needs, for our limits in production unavoidably debarred 
 millions from its blessings. As was shown earlier, if we 
 wish to extend to all children what we now grant ten 
 per cent, of them we shall have to work much harder and 
 greatly improve our methods of work in factory and home. 
 To-day only ten out of each hundred enter high school, 
 and less than two per cent, matriculate for college work. 
 The remainder, the overwhelming majority, is sent to the 
 workbench at the age of fourteen or fifteen, equipped with 
 a scant reading and writing knowledge, but not taught to 
 think closely, to connect cause and effect, to survey a 
 wide gamut of facts, to pierce the shell of things in order 
 to reach a sympathetic understanding of what at first 
 sight may seem gross injustice or a trite detail. We have 
 given the masses the ability to read, but not to compre- 
 hend things. We have trained them in the crafts, but not 
 in the sciences nor in the supreme art of living. Their 
 abilities, such as they are, have not been unfolded accord- 
 ing to the best prescriptions of the pedagogue. Accurate 
 information is always scarce, but the exclusion of many 
 millions of willing students from the higher branches of 
 learning has made doubly precarious the hold of democ- 
 racy. 
 
 It is acknowledged by one scholar that a true public 
 opinion " can be formed where the bulk of the people 
 
220 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 are in a position to determine of their own knowledge or 
 by weighing evidence a substantial part of the facts re- 
 quired for a rational decision," but he adds that " knowl- 
 edge of facts becomes increasingly difficult." 3 A grow- 
 ing complexity of life and widening of economic interests 
 has accentuated the difficulties of old, while our educa- 
 tional system has failed to take due account of them in 
 preparing people for true democracy. 
 
 Socialists may of course promise to remedy this defect 
 so that everybody will be able to know what is going on, 
 anxious as well as able to participate actively in politics. 
 One is involuntarily captivated by the prospect of a social 
 order in which all of us get a chance to master the es- 
 sentials in natural or social science. However, it would be 
 a grievous mistake to bank extravagantly on the possibili- 
 ties of formal schooling. We may extend educational 
 facilities to a marked degree without obtaining propor- 
 tionate returns in intelligence. It is not true that a fixed 
 ratio of the one to the other exists. Rather, we all know 
 of types of human beings, some of them bound to succeed 
 in life while others fall by the wayside. Human nature 
 comes in types more or less fixed and regularly recur- 
 rent, as the biologist knows. We have the strong and the 
 frail, the clever and the stupid, the imitators and the in- 
 novators, the crafty and the naive, the energetic and the 
 indolent, the courageous and the craven, the stubborn and 
 the docile, and so forth. These classes of people get dif- 
 ferent results out of the same instructional course. It 
 is not to be supposed that all will benefit by guidance re- 
 ceived in the study of social problems, or that, having 
 been informed as to the relevant facts, they will all draw 
 the conclusions most important for the exercise of the 
 rights of citizenship. We may count on many ignora- 
 3 Lowell, A. L., " Public Opinion and Popular Government," p. 46. 
 
THE LIMITS IN GOVERNMENT 
 
 muses even when science is more conscientiously dissemin- 
 ated. People do not entirely select their data from a 
 social standpoint. Though cognizant of certain facts 
 they will ignore them for the sake of emphasizing their 
 own needs. This is the obstacle mainly interfering with an 
 impartial application of knowledge to practical politics. 
 The masses succumb to emotions when reason alone should 
 govern. The type that acts on analysis is in the minority 
 distinctly, and this type will do the directing whether 
 education has enlightened the populace or not. 
 
 The second premise, therefore, loses force also, for just 
 because of the predominance of the strong, calculating, 
 far-seeing minority the great majority seldom remains 
 true to its convictions. Or rather, it receives its ideas 
 from a small group whose word and suggestion superin- 
 tends the casting of the vote. Social control reigns 
 everywhere. The average man does not spend his time 
 thinking out any particular problem in production or 
 government, but he expects somebody else to give him 
 a problem ready made, much of the solution being already 
 outlined. Under those conditions he will work cheerfuUy 
 and deliver a product, but not otherwise. 
 
 Imitation and suggestion thus become staple devices 
 for learning and for exerting influence. The masses 
 absorb the opinions of leaders as a sponge absorbs water. 
 They fall a prey to suggestibility and follow out com- 
 mands adroitly administered. From the press or from 
 the pulpit, from the employer and from friends, from the 
 political machine and relatives the most of us get our 
 ideas as to what is right and what we should vote for. 
 The press especially wields an enormous influence over 
 people's minds. It molds opinion more than it passively 
 reflects it, for the brain of the editorial staff is superior 
 to that of the majority, and where the staff is under the 
 
THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 control of industrialists or public officials it at any rate 
 still spreads views not primarily developed by the gen- 
 eral run of subscribers. 
 
 Ward bosses similarly may move us to vote regardless 
 of our personal desires. We listen to them and feel 
 prompted to credit them with superior wisdom. Or we 
 make of political creed a family affair, the son follow- 
 ing his father's party, actuated partly by a sense of 
 loyalty or the propriety of things, and partly by the 
 force of habit. Thus we do not ask why certain men 
 are nominated in the convention, or why their names ap- 
 pear on the ballot. We do not go into the history of the 
 candidates, except that the party leaders will consider 
 it somewhat in their proposal for nomination. The 
 wishes of the employer may mean more to us than our pri- 
 vate views, for there are avenues that lead to distant goals, 
 and blind alleys that lead us nowhere. Nobody likes to 
 risk much without a chance of gain. Whether it be 
 bribery or promises of advancement, whether it be a mere 
 whim or the innuendos of relatives, whether it be from 
 indifference or because of pressure brought to bear upon 
 men illicitly, men have voted regardless of what they 
 believed, and they will do so again. Few act on decisions 
 painstakingly grounded. Not all are in a position to 
 vote precisely as they please, even if the law protects them. 
 The ballot reflects public opinion, of course, but it 
 originates with a small minority whose powers of percep- 
 tion and of control are plainly in view. 
 
 Democracy, thus, is the will of the majority radiating 
 from select groups who, by courting the consent of the 
 masses, succeed in legalizing what once did not need the 
 sanction of law. Political theory, in other words, is far 
 ahead of practice. " No government," wrote Mill in his 
 magnificent essay on Liberty, " by a democracy or a 
 
THE LIMITS IN GOVERNMENT 
 
 numerical aristocracy, either in its political acts or in the 
 opinions, qualities, and tone of mind which it fosters, aver 
 did or could rise above mediocrity except in so far as the 
 sovereign Many have let themselves be guided, which 
 in their best times they always have done, by the counsels 
 and influence of a more highly gifted and instructed One 
 or Few. The initiative of all wise or noble things comes 
 and must come from individuals ; generally at first from 
 some one individual. The honor and glory of the average 
 man is that he is capable of following that initiative ." 4 
 And in the words of a contemporary writer : " We are 
 governed by minorities just as industries are controlled 
 by them. The problem is not to escape control, but to 
 transform society so that wisdom dominates." 5 
 
 As to the third premise. The people look naturally 
 to leadership, even though at times they are disappointed. 
 They take for granted that their wishes will in the main 
 be honored by the legislator. Yet the pledges for such 
 obedience on the part of men in office are few and in- 
 definite. Party platforms promise much, but are notable 
 for lack of clarity in expression, of precision in the 
 enumeration of particulars. The particulars cannot 
 often be given, for most needs arise after men have been 
 installed in office. The barest outline of policies is 
 offered, but one cannot judge from that as to the final 
 interpretation to be put upon them. Either the measures 
 to be acted on cannot be discussed beforehand to any ex- 
 tent, or the thoughts are couched in phrases susceptible 
 of several constructions. Once the governors begin their 
 work the means of checking them up prove strikingly in- 
 effective. There is no way of judging except to obey im- 
 pulses of the moment. A hostile press may open our eyes, 
 
 * Mill, J. S., " On Liberty," Chapter 3. 
 
 s Patten, S. N., " The Reconstruction of Economic Theory," p. 75. 
 
THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 or an honest opponent may point out errors and de- 
 linquencies, but beyond that the axiom of responsible 
 ministry is purely nominal. Responsibility is to public 
 opinion, not to wishes registered at the poll. It is to de- 
 mands agitated among the reigning economic classes, not 
 to principles formulated by science. The latter so far 
 has enjoyed but a passive share in the administration of 
 public affairs. 
 
 Whichever way we look at the situation we cannot get 
 away from the limitations inherent in popular control. 
 Democracy always will turn out to be a set of rules by 
 which the minority is permitted, willy nilly, to govern 
 the majority. A few outline the policies, that the multi- 
 tudes may put the stamp .of their approval upon them 
 and thus, by rights of suffrage and representation, become 
 parties to a transaction which few of them really com- 
 prehend. The value of political democracy, therefore, is 
 not the equalization of powers of judgment, for that lies 
 far in the future, but the submission of the mighty, always 
 in theory, and in practice now and then, to the will of 
 the weak. For the same reasons that a part of our social 
 surplus of goods produced by exceptional talents should 
 go to the normal or deficit producers, the civic rights 
 and duties should be substantially equalized, so each may 
 feel worthy of a place in the social order. To humble the 
 mighty may at times be necessary. The vote and the 
 election campaigns preceding the voting help to fortify 
 the masses against too deep a sense of their own in- 
 feriority. What an excess of self-assertion leads to we 
 are told often enough, but immoderate subjection of the 
 Self to class standards is equally reprehensible. 
 
 The casting of a vote is symbolic of the power of 
 numbers which the average voter represents. To know 
 that certain offices are legally open to us even when we 
 
THE LIMITS IN GOVERNMENT 
 
 do not aspire to them is consoling, and a spur to our 
 spirit of enterprise. Democracy politically draped is 
 valuable for these reasons. It puts a premium on social 
 cohesion, on united action by all regardless of differen- 
 tiations. It harmonizes with our knowledge of human 
 nature. For the lowly are not impotent unless we deny 
 them assistance. The slow-witted need not be a burden 
 until we belittle their ambitions. All of us feel obliga- 
 tions until we are declared irresponsible. The bane of 
 aristocracy is its tendency to declare inert what is quick 
 with life, and to curb development among the mediocre. 
 In a democracy like the socialistic all will have a right to 
 do the unexpected, provided it helps the public at large. 
 It will be for the governors to encourage every effort to- 
 ward self betterment and to use the data of science so that 
 self and society become one. 
 
 3. Obstacles to Internationalism For a long time 
 to come, however, governments will have to combine 
 science with strategy, for nationalism implies two 
 policies very different in principle. As trustees of the 
 people a government should act honestly, with the re- 
 gard that one member in a partnership has for the 
 other. But as soon as we scent a conflict of interests be- 
 tween nations we must admit the value of statecraft in a 
 competitive sense. 
 
 The scientist should be first of all creative and truth- 
 ful. Nothing counts but the facts. Service is the key- 
 note of labor, and candor a supreme virtue among col- 
 laborators. The government is such an agent of truth 
 and service when it deals with its own constituency. But 
 in its dealings with a hostile outside world it must show 
 discretion regardless of rights of duties. It must add 
 the cunning of the fox to the strength of the lion. It 
 must seek to achieve by circumlocution or by a ruse what 
 
226 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 it could not gain by frankness or amicable advances. 
 Governments are necessarily suspicious of each other as 
 long as they claim sovereignty amidst radically different 
 conditions for prosperity. A nation therefore needs two 
 sorts of men and several criteria of conduct ; one to govern 
 it at home and the other to guard it against lurking foes. 
 The partnership of truth and falsehood can scarcely be 
 dissolved as long as nationalism prevails and different 
 sovereignties compete for supremacy. 
 
 As for the rights of its own citizens a government 
 should subordinate them to the welfare of the great ma- 
 jority. The functions of government, in this respect, 
 will vary with time and place. No one principle can be 
 laid down by which the people are to ensure to themselves 
 utmost personal liberty or a maximum of social striking 
 power. 
 
 It is true, as H. Spencer emphasized, that social jus- 
 tice consists in that " every man has freedom to do all 
 that he wills, provided he infringes not the equal free- 
 dom of any other man," 6 but just when the infringement 
 takes place we do not know, except at a given time and 
 place. Similarly, when J. S. Mill observes that " the 
 only part of the conduct of any one for which he is amen- 
 able to society is that which concerns others " 7 we will 
 agree offhand. But how shall we determine what actions 
 are of social import, and which concern solely the indi- 
 vidual? The proper sphere of government is not found 
 as easily as was thought by the Manchestrians. We have 
 abandoned the theorem that government is an evil and 
 self-expression naturally a virtue. We have individually 
 perhaps held control to be a sad duty, a necessary evil, 
 
 Spencer, H., " Ethics," Part Four, Justice, Chapter 6, No. 27. 
 T Mill, J. S., " On Liberty," Introductory. 
 
THE LIMITS IN GOVERNMENT 
 
 but at the same time we have found out that liberty is 
 not so much a reservation of rights to say and do things 
 as one of duties by the observance of which the largest 
 possible number of people in a given area can master the 
 complexity of civilization. 
 
 The history of American ideals of democracy is an in- 
 structive example of this relativity of freedom. Pater- 
 nalism was once decried as something un-American, as 
 smacking of monarchy. But increasingly as the western 
 frontier has disappeared, as city life has encroached on 
 the country side, as density of population has increased 
 and our economic organization has expanded and become 
 more intricate, increasingly in about the same measure we 
 have added to our functions of federal and local govern- 
 ment, until to-day warnings to do and not to do certain 
 things greet us on all sides. Laws have been passed on 
 behalf of the citizen which two generations ago would 
 have seemed as ridiculous as indeed they would have been 
 inappropriate. What twenty million agriculturally en- 
 gaged Americans considered good government is one thing, 
 and what a seething mass of urbanites without land, hud- 
 dled together like sheep in a pen, deem adequate govern- 
 ment is quite another thing. It would not be an exaggera- 
 tion to say that functions of government grow in propor- 
 tion to density of population and to per capita production 
 of goods. 
 
 Democracy certainly must anticipate dark days when 
 social relations become too interlaced; for it may mean 
 that social stratification is sanctioned and the an- 
 tagonism of economic groups openly recognized. It is 
 when this stage of structural development has been reached 
 that international relations, too, assume a sinister aspect. 
 The functions of government will then proclaim a new 
 
228 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 norm of individualism, one that would outrage the in- 
 dividualistic sense of the primitive man, say of the col- 
 onist in Jacksonian days. 
 
 The prerogatives of sovereignty, however, are most 
 fully invoked in international relations. It is here that 
 the individual is nothing and the state everything. The 
 government acts on behalf of all its citizens against the 
 presumption of outsiders. It speaks as though the citi- 
 zens were temporarily a means to an end, the end being 
 the promotion of interests as understood by the gover- 
 nors. Minority rule is then most in evidence. Leader- 
 ship and might carry the day. The weal and woe of un- 
 told millions rests in the hands of a very few men steering 
 the ship of state. The principle of competition holds 
 sway, and nations match their rights as they ordinarily 
 match their goods in a search for markets. 
 
 The nation is not presumably as old as the race or tribal 
 unit. It depends upon our definitions of both. But 
 there is ample evidence to show that blood ties have never 
 limited the expansion of groups. Whatever race charac- 
 teristics may be, peoples of different physical make-up 
 of different languages and literatures, have been united 
 under one common rule and fought shoulder to shoulder 
 against their own kinsmen as well as against aliens. The 
 nation has always proven to be a union of individuals 
 welded by exceptional leadership. Leaders of men have 
 fought each other, and external circumstances have 
 prompted people to side with one or the other. Groups 
 have been made strong by a minority which, taking upon 
 itself the onus of battle and vigilance, wa's given the con- 
 trol of internal affairs no less than of warfare. 
 
 A nation is the product of force. Leadership has made 
 it. Sovereignty is the absolute right of leaders to safe- 
 guard their nation against the attacks of rival nations. 
 
THE LIMITS IN GOVERNMENT 229 
 
 Such were the original attributes of the sovereign, along- 
 side of which the rights of jurisdiction and of taxation 
 developed early. A nation may not be economically self- 
 sufficient. It rarely has been. But it always represents 
 an organization of fighters who will place their own wel- 
 fare above that of any outsider. This is a rule the ex- 
 ceptions to which are few and far between. 
 
 The .more advanced our methods of production the 
 larger a nation may grow, for plainly it requires either 
 physical force or solidarity of interests to govern mil- 
 lions from a single center. The Ancients, and notably the 
 Romans, succeeded in building vast empires covering mil- 
 lions of square miles because their organization of fighters 
 had no equal. On the other hand, nations may become 
 strong numerically if they are able to find enough food on 
 a small area, or to purchase it with finished products. 
 This was commonly the case since the discovery of new 
 continents, with immense natural resources awaiting ex- 
 ploitation, has furnished European nations a welcome out- 
 let for manufactures. Race ideals have always been an 
 impediment to aggressive nations, but not an invincible 
 one. Differences in language and intellectual traditions, 
 in religion and in physical traits such as color and stature 
 have tended to keep people apart. Yet these natural 
 barriers have not always prevented a conqueror from 
 gathering under his scepter a mighty host of subjects. 
 
 What must determine the size of nations is chiefly tech- 
 nical means of communication, travel, and transportation, 
 methods of production, the disposition of natural re- 
 sources, and principles of government. As long as topo- 
 graphical conditions vary greatly, as long as mountains 
 and water could separate people by making travel impos- 
 sible, as long as sparsity of resources kept people poor 
 and widely scattered, so long the agglomeration of many 
 
230 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 millions under a single flag was out of the question. And 
 for precisely these reasons nationality will be a dominant 
 factor for centuries to come. 
 
 There will never be enough time and wealth to permit mi- 
 gration at regular intervals for the exchange of interests, 
 thoughts, and manners. Physiographic differences are 
 bound to differentiate peoples in different continents, or 
 even within one continent. The historical background of 
 the ancient world is so much a part of its modern inhabi- 
 tants that they can never hope to rid themselves entirely 
 of its fatal effects for purposes of internationalism. 
 There is no promise of an amalgamation of races or of na- 
 tionalized groups. The socialists admit this, and others 
 assume it is a matter of course. 
 
 If socialism then speaks of cosmopolitanism it cannot be 
 with the desire to abrogate nationalism, but only to the 
 end that a better understanding between the several sov- 
 ereign units may be attained. Socialism is eager to fund 
 sentiments, as it has professed great faith in the funding 
 of goods. The most ardent of socialists would abridge 
 sovereign rights so as to make individual nations amen- 
 able to an international tribunal representing the whole 
 world. The underlying thought is the liberation of the 
 masses from the yoke of capitalism, but the incidental 
 feature is the abolition of wars. Socialism pins its faith 
 in the goodness of human nature as found in the average 
 man. It places the responsibility for class struggle and 
 international strife with the magnates of business, con- 
 fident that a reorganization of the industrial system would 
 disarm them and free mankind from a horrible incubus. 
 Socialism wishes to limit sovereignty, but not the duties 
 of government. In this respect its aims are diametrically 
 opposed to those of Laissez Faire and of competitive capi- 
 talism, which stress the need of nationalism as over and 
 
THE LIMITS IN GOVERNMENT 
 
 against the rights of the individual within each nation. 
 The issue is clearly defined. 
 
 But in order to agree to the limits of socialistic govern- 
 ment we must first distinguish between superficial and 
 basic causes of war. Lack of communication cannot ex- 
 plain them, for in the very century that the means of 
 communication and travel were most perfected, intelligence 
 being flashed across continents and oceans with lightning 
 speed, wars have been as common as ever, besides being 
 conducted on a much larger scale. Nor is the type of 
 government apparently a decisive factor, considering that 
 democracies have fought as lustily as autocracies. The 
 overthrow of absolutism did not spare France or England 
 any wars. Neither have the South American republics or 
 the United States escaped them entirely, though thanks 
 to their youth, perhaps, and to their remoteness from the 
 centers of trade they suffered less than the Europeans. 
 
 And in the third place it would be folly to attribute 
 wars to economic pressure if that is to mean lack of food 
 or of the necessaries of life as the masses know them. 
 Wars have been as plentiful in the days of cavedwellers 
 as to-day. Density of population has not multiplied 
 them, nor has the modern abundance of necessities made 
 them impossible. Regardless of an abundance of supplies 
 nations have entered upon costly wars ; regardless of 
 needs, measurable by individual standards, governments 
 have declared themselves constrained to levy armies either 
 in self defense, or on behalf of third parties. 
 
 Hence the meaning of the indisputable fact that wars 
 must be traced to economic pressure is somewhat different 
 from the one commonly accepted. It has to do not only 
 with the " economic man " that economics has so often al- 
 luded to, but likewise with types of men and their role in 
 social growth. 
 
THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 The economic man is a product of evolution. The uni- 
 versal surplus of seed coupled with the scarcity of foods 
 brought about a struggle in which pugnacity and ac- 
 quisitiveness became invaluable assets. Those who would 
 or could not fight to acquire a subsistence were inevi- 
 tably killed off. The instinct of self-preservation could 
 express itself in no other way than in willingness and abil- 
 ity to fight for the biologically essential things. The sex 
 struggle was an accompaniment of the contest for self- 
 preservation, the two being inseparably connected. 
 
 The course of history points to the effect of economic 
 conditions upon the development of social norms, but the 
 innate faculties of man were in turn the means for en- 
 larging the economic environment. Thus the selfish in- 
 stincts eventually aided in the arousal of a group con- 
 sciousness almost as strong as parental love and sex 
 passion. The original need of food ceased to preoccupy 
 men. They specialized more and more for the accumula- 
 tion of non-necessities which their imagination made de- 
 sirable, and the possession of which meant power. That 
 is to say, since strength like everything else is relative, 
 the means to survival were not simply an abundance of 
 food, but all those instruments by which an enemy could 
 be subjugated in a battle. Not the mere muscular 
 strength, but ax and arrow, sword and scimitar became 
 important, and again not weapons but means of defense, 
 like walls and citadels, moats and armor, decided the issue. 
 And later on subtler devices warded off the foe. The 
 power of body was dwarfed by the force of explosives. 
 Armor plate, instead of shielding the knights, was used to 
 clad ships and fortresses. Industry supplied the govern- 
 ment with weapons vastly superior to anything the primi- 
 tive man had known, but the victory still went to those 
 who relatively excelled in men and arms. Iron and coal 
 
THE LIMITS IN GOVERNMENT 
 
 and chemistry and Kartells came to count as much in an 
 international struggle as personal strength and nimbleness 
 for prehistoric tribes. 
 
 The economic man cultivated his powers of reasoning, 
 but he could not divest himself of reflex actions and in- 
 stincts bred in countless ages of ferocious combat with 
 animals and fellowmen. The test for superiority changed, 
 but the instincts remained the same. Instead of foods the 
 desideratum became a surplus of capital goods with which 
 to produce enjoyable consumption goods in times of peace, 
 and weapons of defense in times of war. In his eagerness 
 to acquire creative comforts our ingenious man also ad- 
 vanced the methods of warfare. His prosperity which 
 once turned on the sufficiency of food and clothing now 
 varied with his possession of a large stock of raw ma- 
 terials and finished articles. 
 
 The social group expanded, but leadership became more 
 precarious. Individual might had to be buttressed more 
 and more by the approval of rival companions. Prestige 
 hinged on wealth because everybody valued wealth for its 
 own sake, besides desiring it as token of providential 
 favor or of unusual ability, of privilege and power. 
 Wealth meant leisure in peace, and victory in war. The 
 control of riches in land or in capital enabled man to 
 command respect and obedience where the weight of per- 
 sonality alone might not have sufficed. The economic 
 man, in this sense, is an imperishable product of evolution 
 and progress, a fact all science and sentiment must take 
 into account. While wealth has its uses in war it will be 
 doubly valuable also in days of peace. 
 
 But the accumulation of wealth rests largely with ex- 
 ceptional men. The inventors and managers of capital, 
 the organizers of men for productive purposes, and the 
 proprietors of natural resources these form the nu- 
 
THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 cleus from which social growth must be deduced, just as 
 premises give rise to a conclusion. The correlations of 
 social phenomena are many, and what is cause or effect 
 may never be completely determinable. Yet it is certain 
 that without the right sort of natural resources and right 
 leadership for production or public control nothing great 
 can be achieved. The place of one nation among others 
 varies with the use of resources in material and men made 
 by the small minority now dominating business. When 
 a nation boasts many great leaders it is likely to grow 
 rapidly, to increase its population by selling manufac- 
 tures for foodstuffs, to raise its level of living, to widen 
 its horizon of thought and politics, and to search the 
 world for greater riches. 
 
 If physical barriers do not forbid, an aggressive atti- 
 tude toward outsiders is thus sure to find approval. The 
 leaders want power and empire, the masses demand com- 
 forts and glory, i. e., such glory as the fear of rivals or 
 the consciousness of past triumphs may bring. War, in 
 brief, is a means of equilibrating differentials of power be- 
 tween nations who rank as sovereign units, but whose 
 real might is lodged in the hands of a few who by virtue 
 of office or of inborn superiorities decide the fate of the 
 multitudes. It is hardly an error to call the leaders the 
 creators and destroyers of life, in that their sagacity and 
 energy alone provides the means to an increase of popula- 
 tion. But their struggle for shining supremacy also en- 
 gulfs the masses periodically in bloody wars, wars that 
 decimate the population and redistribute sovereign powers 
 so that another period of growth for somebody may fol- 
 low. 
 
 Differentials of national power will always exist because 
 inventions change the value of natural resources. What 
 at one time means little, may be highly prized and coveted 
 
THE LIMITS IN GOVERNMENT 235 
 
 at another. In ancient days soil fertility was a prime 
 asset. To-day coal and iron stand out prominently. 
 During the later middle ages commerce with the far east 
 helped nations to a lordly position. A century hence 
 maritime facilities may be less significant than circum- 
 stances favoring aerial navigation. Just now oil and 
 copper are items of maximum valuation, but there is no 
 gainsaying that countries now obscure and despised for 
 their backwardness may rise to eminence because of dis- 
 coveries yet to be made by now leading civilizations. The 
 notion of a balance of power dates from days when two 
 or three nations were the arbiters of Europe, but it is 
 doubtful whether it will ever mean anything else than the 
 division of power among a few, whose policy is law for all 
 others. 
 
 No nation is as yet ready to renounce its sovereign 
 rights. All nations have reserved for themselves the right 
 of autonomy in internal affairs, even if elsewhere they had 
 nothing to say. The spirit of nationalism is rampant 
 these days. It has been fed and feted by the latest war, 
 instead of being restrained by it. Even now nations are 
 preparing for rehabilitation commercially, for the ex- 
 pansion of business at the other's expense, for the delimi- 
 tation of spheres of influence. Investments and colonies, 
 mandates and protectorates, alliances and tariff conven- 
 tions figure prominently in the daily press. Sovereignty 
 is still regarded as absolute and inviolable. What kings 
 once claimed is now fitly ascribed to the people, but if 
 nationalism is to continue on competitive lines natural 
 differences will not only be accentuated, but the motto of 
 particularism will estrange nations so that arbitration of 
 clashing claims becomes difficult. 
 
 Human nature gives us no ground for expecting per- 
 petual peace by the introduction of the plebiscite or of 
 
236 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 female suffrage. Women at all times have supported men 
 in a combat. The sex relation is so entirely mutual that 
 it is folly to expect from women what men cannot do. 
 The passions of the multitude are easily aroused to ungov- 
 ernable fury. Nothing appeals like an argumentum ad 
 hominem. If the leading classes give moral support to a 
 martial government it is sure to find a vent. Patriotism 
 covers a multitude of sins. Nationalism is a growth that 
 thrives on secrecy and on centralization of powers. What 
 is a domestic question and what a justiciable case, what an 
 attribute of sovereignty and what a question for adjudica- 
 tion? What are the obligations of a protectorate and 
 what the limits of armament internationally permitted? 
 These are problems not to be solved with science or law, 
 but with combats or concessions. 
 
 Socialism has a hard road to travel in many respects, 
 but it is particularly embarrassed in its attempts at in- 
 ternationalism and enduring we won't say perpetual 
 peace. The safest preventives at its disposal are educa- 
 tion and publicity, decentralization of economic powers, 
 and a leveling of incomes. If by equalization of oppor- 
 tunities and economic rights we can teach the average man 
 to think ; if in the wake of enlightenment morality will 
 gradually subordinate feelings of race and nationality to 
 the concept of humanity ; if in giving the masses an active 
 share in government we can banish camarillas of Machia- 
 vellianism, bringing into the light of day the precise facts 
 at issue then we may hope to chain grim Mars and 
 smooth the path for Peace. But socialism has not yet de- 
 clared itself willing or able to redistribute the world's 
 goods irrespective of national boundaries; nor are the 
 means near at hand that make such an equalization of re- 
 sources and policies possible. Tried in only one or two 
 
THE LIMITS IN GOVERNMENT 237 
 
 countries socialism might meet the fate of bi-metallism 
 which could not hold itself in the midst of gold standards. 
 To conclude. The weaker system of production, if 
 international trade is to follow competitive principles, is 
 assuredly the socialistic. Costs can be lowered if we have 
 no conscience. Markets may be conquered at the sacri- 
 fice of millions at home, provided the law does not inter- 
 fere. Socialism will value personality above product. It 
 may raise the social dividend without cheapening particu- 
 lar types of goods fit for exportation. It might be com- 
 pelled to buy imports at prices costly to the consumer. 
 In rich countries socialism will tend to lower levels of liv- 
 ing if it wishes to aid poorer countries. The gain will 
 come some day, if all cooperate on one principle, but for 
 the present the outlook for internationalism is disquieting. 
 The limits of government point to nationalism in spite of 
 its perils, in spite of grievous experiences in the past. 
 
CHAPTER X 
 A PETITION 
 
 i. Foundations in Social Science Restated. What 
 has so far been said should now enable us to summarize as 
 follows : 
 
 Social reform manifestly must be based on social sci- 
 % ence. The physician in this respect sets a good example 
 to the socialist and to other prophets of a better world. 
 He does not suggest cures until he has analyzed his case. 
 Diagnosis and prognosis go together. What is more, a 
 careful record of the course of the malady is kept, and 
 only in the light of past experiences, which are compared 
 with the individual case, is treatment offered. The phy- 
 sician relies upon the facts of physiology and allied sci- 
 ences for his power of aiding the sick. 
 
 The would-be healer of social ills can do no better than 
 look to the foundations of social processes before going to 
 work. The data of biology and psychology, of sociology 
 and of economics furnish the light by which eventually a 
 prescription may be filled for the curing of social patients. 
 The diagnosis may not be perfect. The symptoms may 
 mislead us. The issue of the disease may be most un- 
 expected. But in spite of the limitations to which all 
 science is subject, and which the reformer must bear in 
 mind, his plans have a chance of success only in so far as 
 they square with actualities. Whether we are dealing 
 with a political platform, or with a petition of rights for 
 the people, each must be based on facts, and accept the 
 
 restraints which facts impose. 
 
 238 
 
A PETITION 239 
 
 For purposes of reform as well as for research in gen- 
 eral the empirical standpoint alone can satisfy. There is 
 no gain in postulating sources of truth which lie beyond 
 the ken of our senses. To predicate innate ideas about 
 anything is useless, for the predication itself is not innate, 
 and if it were it could not change the nature of our know- 
 ing. The distinction between things and things-in-them- 
 selves is entirely gratuitous. It is useless except to call 
 our attention to the sources of our knowledge and to the 
 methods we employ in reasoning. 
 
 There is no way of learning except by our power of 
 sensing things, by our ability to respond selectively to, 
 and to remember, the stimuli acting from without and 
 from within. Our senses furnish the basis for knowledge. 
 The data of our consciousness and its reactions measure 
 the scope of our learning. We receive stimulations and 
 respond in certain ways. We remember and construct 
 associations which according to purpose and setting ter- 
 minate in action, or perhaps do not. 
 
 The outside world is one of regularities because of our 
 ability to perceive, select, and remember. Associations 
 alone make possible the connections by which we bring or- 
 der into chaos. It is through inference by enumeration 
 and by comparison of resemblances and differences that 
 we obtain classes of things and laws of nature. The laws 
 that science speaks of are sequences and coexistences re- 
 curring with different degrees of regularity. We can 
 control them in a measure. We can modify some of the 
 laws, but only by changing ourselves. Everything for 
 that matter is subject to change. Nothing is absolutely 
 rigid or definitive. The groups of events which we bind 
 together and experience as correlatives or laws change in 
 scope and contents. As students we add to, and subtract 
 from, such facts involved in a given situation according 
 
240 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 to time and circumstance. From time to time all our 
 knowledge must be restated. Its values have undergone a 
 change without our at first being conscious of it. Thus 
 sciences grow, and in this sense all sciences are inter- 
 related, the boundary lines shifting and becoming clear 
 and blurred by turns. 
 
 But our knowledge is also relative in this respect that 
 not all people judge facts alike. They have many char- 
 acteristics in common, but in different degrees. Our 
 anatomy, for instance, is substantially the same for all. 
 In instincts tending to survival we are much alike. Our 
 sense perceptions in general correspond so that we all see 
 or hear the objects or noises about us. But increasingly, 
 as we move away from the most fundamental traits of 
 human nature, we notice differences in men, in their inter- 
 ests and methods of valuation. / The number and the sig- 
 nificance of factors in a given situation appear differently 
 to different people. The events may be called variables 
 whose functioning is the subject of science. The fact of 
 interrelation is observed by all, and will be agreed to from 
 the start, but its nature or functioning challenges the 
 acumen of the ablest, indeed cannot often be established 
 indisputably. 
 
 The variables of events, or experiences that fill our life 
 and become the special concern of scientists, are all either 
 causes or effects according to viewpoint and needs of the 
 moment. It is not that the two are generically distinct, 
 but that some factors in a situation are considered as 
 constants, relative to which all others are treated as vari- 
 ables. We understand things by cross reference. We 
 explain the obscure by comparing it with the clear, or 
 what seems clear. We select our subjects for observation, 
 and by focussing our attention upon particulars get the 
 truth which at the time is sought. Purposes and circum- 
 
A PETITION 
 
 stances govern all our searches for law in nature and for 
 rule in personal conduct or social policy. 
 
 It follows then that sciences are not only intercon- 
 nected, but also that for all sciences there is but one 
 method. The man on the street who is not specially 
 trained will yet, in the main, use the modes of reasoning 
 employed by the professional student. The two stand in 
 this respect on a level because both are products of one 
 course of evolution. Just as man is a unit and therefore 
 all social phenomena interrelated, so scientific and un- 
 scientific methods of thinking have much in common. 
 The chief difference between the untutored man and the 
 scientist is the latter's enlarged fund of associations which 
 permits him to extend greatly his comparisons and test 
 thoroughly his inferences by enumeration and analogy. 
 He practices a more careful selection of data, makes ex- 
 acter measurements thanks to the use of instruments not 
 possessed by the layman, and hence, as final result, boasts 
 a wider scope of investigation and of generalization. The 
 scientist stands on a higher plane because he excels in 
 association and measurement. The scientist does not al- 
 low himself to be hindered by irrelevant premises. He 
 assumes only the will to live. That given, his world of 
 experience and truth is mechanistically pictured or at any 
 rate understood. 
 
 Science is necessarily mechanistic. But this does not 
 prevent it from accepting that viewpoint as correct which 
 makes man appear self-directing and responsible accord- 
 ing to socially instituted standards. The notion of free- 
 will is no impediment to the scientist. He may grant it, 
 and then pursue his studies as though it did not exist. 
 Freewill is a way of looking at the outside world from 
 within. It is an egotistic norm of valuation. It enables 
 us to refer events to ourselves, or one part of a situation 
 
THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 to another. In social sciences notably the assumption of 
 a freewill is a prospective way of viewing plans of action, 
 i. e., coming events. There is no objection to considering 
 each man the maker of his own fortune, as though 
 he were lord over his Self and the fashioner of his des- 
 tinies. But statistics show that events, though sup- 
 posedly willed, happen with considerable regularity, and 
 that what a man really does is far different from the 
 things he believes he could do if necessary. A belief in 
 illimitable will is usually a picturing of possibilities with 
 the aid of the imagination. Associations outstrip action ! 
 
 Similarly science does not conflict with ethics or re- 
 ligion. The latter two may be deemed independent fields 
 for investigation if it's found profitable, but the evidence 
 of natural and social sciences favors the subordination of 
 moral norms to the general scheme of consciousness and 
 sociation. What we think right, and what we wish of an 
 unknown future, these are facts that are an integral part 
 of our whole being. There is no method for understand- 
 ing the Ought and the Soul except by analyzing self and 
 society as the scientist is wont to. 
 
 If we apply some of these fundamentals to social sci- 
 ence we shall find at once the limits of all social movements 
 and of all reform schemes. No one can work without the 
 right basis for physical reactions. No one can excogitate 
 a world entirely apart from his surroundings. No one 
 will propose betterments, except he is bound by the tra- 
 ditions back of him and by the shortcomings of science as 
 they exist at his time. All social events are conceived as 
 knit together. The relations are intimate or remote, but 
 they may be proven to exist if we trace events far enough. 
 Yet for the same reason all truths are relative to time, 
 place, and circumstance, or to put it more accurately, to 
 place, period, and people. It is the environment in gen- 
 
A PETITION 243 
 
 eral and particular, it is the epoch of social development 
 or of national growth, it is the group experiencing the 
 events, be it large or small it is in the midst of these 
 facts that all social principles find their bounds. There 
 are too many variables to permit an exhaustive interpre- 
 tation. There are many events functioning as variables, 
 because human nature is so much more complex than either 
 animal or plant, or than any of the relations of the in- 
 organic world. 
 
 On the other hand, the main facts of human nature are 
 definitely ascertainable and virtually immutable. The 
 changes in man come so slowly that we can scarcely per- 
 ceive them. To ourselves we are the constant by refer- 
 ence to which the events about us appear as variables 
 which, more or less completely, we may control. Human 
 nature is practically a constant, though per individual 
 the force of variation is as great as that of heredity is 
 self evident. 
 
 Precisely because of this substantial definiteness of our 
 make-up the data of psychology and of biology furnish 
 us a clue to standards of prosperity. A theory of pros- 
 perity depends on the knowledge of those two sciences. 
 The principles of sociology and of economics are the last 
 auxiliaries toward a science of social welfare which poli- 
 tics should apply. But the social sciences cannot go 
 ahead until the more fundamental inquiries have attained 
 a certain mastery of facts. Psychology, because it 
 studies the individual, serves to clarify our notions of 
 reasoning, and because it is basic to social studies, it may 
 serve also to help formulate our norms of right and wrong. 
 Right and wrong are criteria of social origin whose indi- 
 vidual aspects are treated by psychology. 
 
 Without the combined action of natural and social sci- 
 ence, then, we cannot hope to arrive at clear ideas of 
 
244 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 prosperity or of reform. Socialism was among the first 
 movements for betterment to recognize this cardinal fact. 
 Hence, if for no other reason, it deserves a conspicuous 
 place in the history of human thought. But, indeed, 
 socialism has a mission for other reasons still. It is not 
 only the logical continuation of doctrines first enunciated 
 by Comte the Positivist and Mill the Utilitarian, but in 
 addition it broached for the first time in unmistakable 
 tones the relation of economics to non-economics, or, as 
 we might say, of wealth to weal. 
 
 2. Errors in Socialism. Socialists committed mis- 
 takes in action, and they espoused for a long time (in 
 part still espouse) teachings not tenable in the light of 
 current science. Socialism, for instance, was wrong in 
 promising to eliminate all maladjustment and give to men 
 a millennium. It was wrong in declaring conditions of 
 production and of exchange to be causative of all other 
 facts of sociation, as though one was the maker of the 
 other. It will not help us, as we have seen, to trace a chain 
 of events in one direction only. The relation of events 
 would be warped. It is not a question of economic man 
 building all the rest in man, but one of lines of thought and 
 action radiating from one center. Man is a single whole, 
 and all life's experiences must be interlaced as a result of it. 
 Without this conception life becomes a mystery, or else a 
 mere catalogue of facts as meaningless as the variegation 
 of a kaleidoscope. 
 
 Socialism furthermore erred in attributing all values to 
 one factor, and particularly in comparing effort-in-time 
 with the market values of a competitive regime. Prices 
 are not measured by labor except in a very general way, 
 and what is more important : Prices cannot in this way 
 be identified with incomes. Socialism, by the same token, 
 failed in trying to correlate prices of goods with personal 
 
A PETITION 245 
 
 incomes, or even with factorial incomes. We can some- 
 times impute values to each one of many elements con- 
 tributing toward a single product. The physicist does 
 it, and other sciences may do the same. But in the realm 
 of exchange the imputation is indirect and can lead to no 
 nice measurements. To declare labor an essential in pro- 
 duction is one thing, and to measure wants by work is 
 another thing. The socialist aimed at the wrong thing, 
 to begin with, when he proposed to explain incomes by 
 prices, and he failed again because, having set his target, 
 he did not aim well. 
 
 The founders of socialism similarly erred in expecting 
 everything good from the abolition of capitalism, for pri- 
 vate ownership of the means of production and of ex- 
 change does not explain all evils. They were proven false 
 prophets also by future events, for misery, while it has 
 perhaps not abated a great deal, has certainly not in- 
 creased to the degree that was apprehended. The Marx- 
 ian theory of misery contains an element of truth, but it 
 can be found only in Marx's " Economic Interpretation of 
 History," and there it is marred by the fond belief that 
 nationalization of capital would remove all evils. 
 
 Lastly, socialists laid themselves open to charges when 
 they promised the world a much higher level of living than 
 is now assured to the bulk of the people. They expect 
 a gain in productiveness, thanks to the abolition of private 
 capitalism, which cannot be logically deduced from the 
 facts of population and environment, nor agrees with 
 socialistic ideals of self development. The limits in race 
 improvement are also much in evidence, whether we appeal 
 to our own powers of observation or to the verdict of sci- 
 ence. Everywhere we find bounds prescribed that social- 
 ism has often overlooked, or promised to set at nought by 
 the application of one general principle, to wit the aboli- 
 
246 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 tion of private property. But such optimism is never 
 fruitful. It can only prompt some people to misunder- 
 stand the nature of democracy and to look forward to 
 change such as science knows nothing of. Democracy is 
 more than a distributive norm, and less than a complete 
 equalization of governors and the governed. The same 
 differences among men that prevent us from fixing a ratio 
 between property and personality, or between economic 
 income and psychic outgo, also point to limits in govern- 
 ment, no matter how liberally we scatter rights of voting 
 and of office holding. 
 
 3. Merits in the Viewpoint of Socialism Social- 
 ism, then, may be criticized from many standpoints, since 
 its premises and conclusions partly belong to a period 
 which science has left far behind. But as against these 
 blanks we must note, too, the winning numbers in the 
 game. The founders of socialism have conferred great 
 benefits upon us, because they were exceptional men who 
 saw far and gathered wisdom from many founts. It 
 would be strange if they had not discovered new truths 
 in all their quest for betterment, or failed to enhance the 
 value of old truths. Men like Marx and Engels or Las- 
 salle will always prove a boon to society, for any deter- 
 mined defense of scientific endeavor leads to moral as well 
 as to intellectual regeneration. 
 
 Socialism was right in adopting an empirical position, 
 in emancipating itself from all hankerings for a transcen- 
 dental universe. Socialists were among the first to preach 
 relativism and to apply the principle of instability to 
 human history. The evolution of our thoughts and ac- 
 tions was shown to be a law pervading our whole social de- 
 velopment. The dual aspect of eternal truth was revealed 
 sharply. Thus dogmatism was dealt a severe blow, the 
 
A PETITION 247 
 
 absolutism of Hegel becoming a brief on behalf of the 
 masses. 
 
 Socialism is right in correlating science and reform: 
 It was the earliest of the great movements for reform on 
 a purely scientific basis. True, to divorce science from 
 sentiment is not always possible, nor will all agree to its 
 being a lofty ideal. It is much the same thing when art 
 and morality are coupled. Some object, and others ap- 
 plaud. But it is important for the reformer that he curb 
 his desires in accordance with scientifically established 
 limits, and this the socialists sought first to do. They 
 hoped for betterment through the workings of a cosmic 
 law. They argued for sweeping changes and at times 
 took refuge in rebellion and hyperboles of speech. But 
 on the other hand they did not demand redress merely 
 because their conscience drove them, or because somebody 
 urged them to protect the weak. ^The chief principle from 
 the outset was the connecting of revolution with evolu- 
 tion. J) 
 
 This likewise enabled the founders of socialism to in- 
 corporate ethics with economics. The socialistic theory 
 of prosperity harmonizes with modern science in that it 
 insists upon verification. The proof of conduct is held 
 superior to protestations of creed. Whenever this is 
 done, whenever service is placed above suffering the road 
 is opened for progress. By objective tests the good and 
 the bad should be defined. This socialism has aimed to do 
 from the start. Ethics was recognized as part of social 
 science. The empirical, or if you will, the pragmatic 
 viewpoint was thus given a specific meaning that all could 
 understand and criticize as they pleased. 
 
 The socialization of religion is a by-product of this 
 mode of reasoning. Socialists have always championed 
 
248 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 the Golden Rule as the quintessence of holy communion. 
 They have stood by those who brought religion to earth 
 and gave it a social mission. That ideals are of the earth 
 and yet may rise above the earthy, this is the stand taken 
 by the positivists, and this attitude socialism has con- 
 sistently supported. 
 
 But socialism was also right in stressing the social roots 
 of evil. The older thought that man fell from grace or 
 that nature was to blame if people lived in pain and pov- 
 erty was calculated to encourage pessimism. It drove 
 men to despair and granted an easy sinecure to privileged 
 classes. Compared to this soothing sirup the socialistic 
 medicine had real merit and promised a cure. It agreed 
 with the gospel of prosperity which science now is inter- 
 ested in, and called attention to the predominance of the 
 instincts over our habits of reasoning. That man was 
 first an animal and next a being of reason was always ad- 
 mitted by socialists. The economic interpretation means 
 partly this. But it also hints at the possibilities for self 
 development. Reason enthroned is as true a symbol for 
 socialism as the tiger stalking for prey. The balancing 
 of primordial selfishness with socialized altruism, this is 
 the task of the future, and to this task socialists have 
 ever bent their energy. 
 
 Socialism is not averse to recognizing the beast in man. 
 The veneer of civilization fools least of all the socialist. 
 But for all that he has declined to subscribe to the teach- 
 ings of competitive economics. The founders of socialism 
 were pioneers in social science and advanced critics of the 
 classical system which made a fetich of individualism. 
 They did well in exposing the logical consequences of 
 Ricardianism, and they made some contributions to the 
 critique of marginal economics which until recently held 
 almost undisputed sway. A stress on collectivism may 
 
A PETITION 249 
 
 lead to extravagant, pyppctatjons^ An exclusive reliance 
 on state ownership will disappoint its sincerest friends. 
 But that evils exist and reforms are needed no one will 
 deny. Yet it was socialism which first systematized the 
 business of meliorism and opened our eyes to the signifi- 
 cance of private property. To take nothing for granted 
 is a sound maxim in science. Socialists learned it early. 
 They did not take private property, e. g., for granted. 
 We can do no better than follow in their footsteps and 
 search into the grounds of an institution which exercises 
 such an incalculable influence over our weal and woe. 
 
 4. Existing Evils in Our Economic System. Re- 
 form undoubtedly is needed. Evils exist in plenty, and 
 not all of them are necessary even at this stage of social 
 development. We may agree to the old saw that nothing 
 is perfect and yet apply ourselves with zest to the task of 
 bettering socio-economic conditions. 
 
 The evils are known to all and need no lengthy discus- 
 sion. We have among us the diseased and the cripples, 
 the subnormal in mind and the totally disabled. We have 
 criminals of many types and vice that goes unpunished by 
 law. There is cruel hunger that cannot be stilled, and 
 y pauperism no philanthropist can root out. Some over- 
 ^work or suffer from the effectsToT "exxfessive^specialization. 
 Others again are treated unfairly in a personal way and 
 resent the insults thrust at them. We know of many 
 who are kept unfit for civic duties, who cannot be made 
 desirable members of a democratically governed country. 
 Class struggle is real, and discontent widespread. 
 
 All these evils have existed for centuries and in part 
 cannot be removed. It is not possible for instance to en- 
 sure everybody good health by safeguarding him when at 
 work, or by scientific sanitary engineering. Gluttony and 
 bad habits are as common a source of illness as accidents 
 
250 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 or bad housing conditions. The congenitally disfigured 
 and disabled we shall perhaps have always with us, for the 
 problems of genetics have not yet suggested ways and 
 means for controlling natural variations. The blind and 
 the deaf and dumb are a burden that society must shoulder 
 with resignation. The demented or the moron, that aris- 
 tocrat of the feeble-minded, may be helped by trained 
 guardians, but they will for long times to come form a 
 certain percentage of our population. And so with the 
 rest of the shortcomings. Not all crime is traceable to 
 social surroundings. There is some evidence to show that 
 born criminals exist, and that vicious habits may be in- 
 herited as well as acquired in unobtrusive ways. 
 
 Among the rich, too, there is much profligacy and bar- 
 renness, both of the physical and the intellectual kind. 
 Money rules not uncommonly at the expense of mentality 
 and manhood. The reign of money is plutocracy, whose 
 undesirable features have been sufficiently explained. 
 Even in a political democracy the money-king has some 
 power. And power breeds arrogance, and arrogance 
 leads to friction and class consciousness. Idleness is the 
 fruit of wealth as well as of inherited lethargy. Too 
 many nowadays prosper in languor, supinely enjoying ill- 
 gotten gains. Complacency and egoism flourish among 
 the rich who control a large portion of the national in- 
 come. Extreme concentration of income is as obnoxious 
 from the standpoint of comradeship and solidarity of in- 
 terests as it may seem unjust to the defenders of a high 
 material level of living. It is in the competitive regime 
 as heretofore prevailing that unearned increments enrich 
 the one, while hard laborers are rewarded insufficiently. 
 The unearned portion crops out at all sorts of places. 
 We see it in the appreciations of natural resources, of real 
 estate, in the winnings of the profiteer and stock broker, 
 
A PETITION 351 
 
 in the scoop made by the keeper of roulette tables, in 
 rentals squeezed out of the toiler's weekly pittance, in 
 usury rates levied by the small capitalist, in the collection 
 of royalties and patent rights, in gifts and briberies re- 
 ceived by young and old, with or without their under- 
 standing of the evils involved. 
 
 A further result of past competitive practices has been 
 an absurd valuation of goods and a disproportionate out- 
 put of luxuries, considering the needs of the great ma- 
 jority. The lawyer, for instance, who helps his client in 
 the criminal circumvention of the statutes enacted in de- 
 fense of the consumer is repaid richly for his effort. A 
 princely retainer-fee perhaps is his share of the bargain. 
 He has, for his purposes, made good use of his position. 
 Pandects and precedents at court have to him been not 
 merely a mine of information, but also of gold which 
 many others, covetous of success, will envy him. The 
 farmer on the contrary, who with his toil produces the es- 
 sentials wherewith to feed his nation, is fortunate if he 
 makes a living. Indeed, not infrequently he had less than 
 a standard wage. Again, trivial personal services ren- 
 dered to the wealthy bring a magnificent largess, while the 
 most deserving must get along in beggarly fashion. The 
 businessman knows how to cater to the rich and glean from 
 their table many a crumb. The lowly are naturally in- 
 clined to make the most of an anomalous situation. They 
 cannot change the economic order, so the best thing is 
 servile adaptation, a regard for the wishes of those that 
 have, so they themselves may pocket some gains. For 
 ridiculous services exorbitant prices, and with the price a 
 shower of tips even more generous ! 
 
 Gross inequality in the distribution of incomes has thus 
 
 led to pompous displays on the one hand, and to sad 
 
 \ wants on the other. The contrasts of rich and poor 
 
252 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 evoke dismay and wonder. V It is what the masses do not 
 get rather than what the opulent display that impresses 
 one. One sees what progress so far has not accom- 
 plished. Crowded and filthy tenements not only repel 
 those of cleanly habits, they also are an indictment for 
 those who by their extravagances turn labor into wrong 
 channels. The regalia of West End cannot make us for- 
 get the ragamuffins of East End. The fascinations of 
 Fifth Avenue relieve in no wise the squalor a few blocks 
 away. Slums are an evil, whether we live in them our- 
 selves or not. 
 
 The time for a thorough study of social processes is 
 now. Now is the time to think and act on matters socio- 
 logical. These are the days when reform must interest 
 alert men and women. The European upheaval is an in- 
 stance both of evils fatally ignored and of experiments 
 in social regeneration. Circumstances alter cases. A 
 readjustment to conditions precipitated by the war is im- 
 pending. Whether all of the changes now advocated will 
 meet the test of time no one can tell, but that betterments 
 are under way should be manifest to all. The Old World 
 is rapidly becoming a new world. 
 
 The United States, too, is in a favorable position for a 
 retesting of social norms. It represents the largest block 
 of natural resources ever placed under one flag. No other 
 belt on this globe of ours equals it in richness or in the 
 efficiency of its population. We have minerals and water- 
 power, timber lands and vast plains yielding bountiful 
 harvests. We have untold wealth aiding us in production, 
 a high level of living that may still be raised higher by 
 right methods, and a stock of people whose full capacities 
 have not yet been put to a trial. With so much to act 
 on, with such assets to manage for the best of all, the 
 cause of social science should not be deserted. A disin- 
 
A PETITION 253 
 
 terested but wholehearted application of knowledge can 
 nowhere bring richer rewards. 
 
 The socialist addresses himself in this spirit to all 
 classes of people. Not merely to the professional stu- 
 dent or to statesmen, but to all workers, and in particu- 
 lar to the average wage earner who has most at stake in 
 this movement for a redress of wrongs. Without definite 
 knowledge nothing can be achieved. Without the goodwill 
 of the majority no public action can be taken. Without 
 enthusiasm no sustained effort is likely. But if in the 
 future the average man applies himself diligently to prob- 
 lems of social welfare extraordinary achievements are in 
 store for us. 
 
 5. A Petition. A petition for redress of existing 
 evils rests on this assumption. It takes for granted that 
 the data of social science are duly consulted, and that 
 only a joint effort of all can net lasting benefits. This 
 is the characteristic of a theory of prosperity weaned 
 from the conceits of bygone centuries. 
 
 The socialist, and with him the student of social pro- 
 cesses, pleads for equalization of rights and duties every- 
 where so far as the norms of maximum welfare permit. 
 We must equalize that is make less uneven the dis- 
 tribution of income by virtual, if not actual, abolition of 
 the right of inheritance, by taxation, and by increasing 
 the public ownership of industrial plants and of natural 
 resources. Inheritance, as J. S. Mill acknowledged in his 
 " Principles of Political Economy," is no logical adjunct 
 of private property. Its praiseworthy features are few, 
 but its demerits stand out boldly. 
 
 Taxes also may be revised so as to conform to a collectiv- 
 istic rather than to an individualistic standard. In the 
 past the faculty theory of taxation took for granted 
 what socialism denied. Tax rates were meant to rectify 
 
254 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 errors of ruthless competition, but the roots of the evil 
 were not thereby disturbed. To tax the financially able 
 means to define ability to earn as well as ability to pay 
 taxes. This is the consideration which should govern us 
 from now on. In this way distributive justice may be 
 more nearly achieved than at present. But greatly in- 
 creased taxes necessitate extension of government func- 
 tions. Both local and central agencies will find more to 
 do, and try to solve problems increasingly by appropri- 
 ating the visible means of production. Equalization of 
 income thus means eventually a restriction of private 
 property as well as a revelation of services. Sumptuary 
 laws may also help in equalizing incomes, but the greatest 
 power for good at all times is education. Socialists 
 therefore insist upon the universalization of enlighten- 
 ment, and our friends of reform, whether socialistic or 
 otherwise, will support this view. Education is the 
 means of social advancement. More education, and edu- 
 cation for more people. Both are needed. Education 
 should be made compulsory and free. It should be open 
 to all regardless of wealth or parentage or aims in life or 
 physical prowess, and it should be in the hands of experts 
 whose services are inferior to none. It is necessary that 
 vocational guidance play a part in the placement of men. 
 It is absolutely essential that technical training be sup- 
 plemented by instruction in the arts and sciences, natural 
 or social, and there is hardly any doubt but that education 
 up to the twenty-first year should form our minimum of 
 demands, if democracy is to be more than a name. 
 
 With this right and duty to learn should be coupled the 
 right and duty to work, after schooling and practicum 
 has duly prepared men for their career. Production at 
 most points is a profession as truly as if it were based on 
 
A PETITION 255 
 
 the Liberal Arts. To work well is a duty none can shirk, 
 but the chance to work well must form part of the con- 
 tract. All should be obliged to toil. Idleness is never a 
 gain, but may often turn out to be a vice. Idleness is 
 consumption without production. Leisure is consumption 
 with a view to increased production. Leisure is more than 
 that, but so much at least it means which the life of a 
 wastrel does not mean. There is no excuse for loitering 
 and lolling about in these days of opportunity. The 
 masses should not be expected to work at a treadmill so 
 a few may lead a parasitic existence. Parasites are not 
 necessary in a well-ordered community. But on the other 
 hand, those who have done their share should be allowed 
 ,VK to rest in old age. Leisure for rest, for recreation, and 
 for regeneration of productive powers. Leisure for 
 amusement and sport. Leisure for the young, and re- 
 cuperation for the aged when their strength is on the 
 wane! N 
 
 These and some other rights to be claimed on behalf of 
 the common folk make up the platform of democracy. 
 Socialists have long adopted it, and friends of progress 
 in all walks of life will call it their own. Democracy 
 should profit by social science, not ignore it in the fatuous 
 belief that because its values are not measurable by phys- 
 ical standards they do not exist. The values of life and 
 of sociation are patent enough to those taking the trouble 
 to study them. They form part of the equipment without 
 which men in charge of public affairs are sure to fail. 
 Socialists have understood them in large measure, but 
 must now agree to further amendments of their original 
 creed, if they wish to enlist the sympathies of thinking 
 people. Revision is wholesome according to their own 
 teachings. Revision is a step in the onward march of 
 
256 THE LIMITS OF SOCIALISM 
 
 civilization. Science itself is nothing if not continual 
 growth and redefinition of terms, whose finest fruit is the 
 advancement of humanism. 
 
 It is therefore no disgrace for socialism to have fallen 
 short of its mark, but it would be sad if the lessons it 
 first taught so brilliantly were to be forgotten by re- 
 formers to come. 
 
INDEX 
 
 Achievement versus happiness, 
 210 
 
 Age, distribution in different 
 countries, 132-34 
 
 Alternative costs, 41 
 
 Art, versus the social good, 104 
 
 Association, a factor in reason- 
 ing, 66 ff. 
 
 Averages, as price determinants, 
 20; 40 
 
 Capital, according to Marx, 21, 23 
 capital goods as ideas, 29-31 
 paradox of wealth, 42-2 
 compared with consumables, 
 
 12S-29 
 Causality a question in history, 
 
 59, 89 ff 
 
 based on correlation, 60 ff 
 Causation an act of imputation, 
 
 84-88 
 Christianity and competition, 
 
 120-21 
 
 Climate, effect on social life, 95 
 Communist manifesto, 211 
 Compact, originating govern- 
 ment, 212-13 
 Competition and Christianity, 
 
 120 
 
 fair competition, 122 
 and efficiency, 173-77 
 Conditions, and social institu- 
 tions or ideas, 91-2 
 Conflict, a part of social process, 
 
 94 
 
 Consumption, denned, 191 
 a part of environment, 192 
 and happiness, 206 ff 
 Correlation a basis in reasoning, 
 
 60ff 
 Cosmopolitanism and socialism, 
 
 230 
 
 Cost, Marxian notion, 20-1 
 marginal idea, 35-6 
 
 257 
 
 Cost, socialistic costs, 184-86 
 
 Democracy, upheld by empiri- 
 cists, 214 
 premises of, 218 
 and government functions, 227 
 and war, 234 
 
 and economic reform, 254 ff 
 Dialectics, Hegelian, 49-51 
 Differentiation, 111 
 
 a principle in progress, 114 
 Diminishing returns in the fu- 
 ture, 156-58 
 Distribution, Ricardian view, 17- 
 
 18 
 
 Marxian view, 20, 22-24 
 marginal view, 37-8 
 to-day of incomes in U. S., 
 
 146-48 
 
 and invention, 164 
 causes of unequal incomes, 166 
 unequal and productiveness, 
 
 171 
 
 and taxation, 178 
 under socialism, 186 ff 
 
 Economic interpretation of his- 
 tory, 53-56 
 restated, 106-07 
 Education, limits of, 203-04 
 
 and democracy, 219 
 Efficiency due to competition, 
 
 173-77 
 
 versus income, 202-04 
 Employment, possible savings in, 
 
 138 
 
 changes under socialism, 152 
 Engels, and the socialist theory, 
 
 49-55 
 
 Environment, denned, 90; 99 
 effect on human nature, 192; 
 
 195 
 
 Ethics, and economic interpreta- 
 tion of history, 102-06 
 
258 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Eugenics, 199-200 
 
 Evils now existing, 249 ff 
 
 Factors, in germ-cell, 195 
 
 and variation, 197 
 Feuerbach, L., and Marx, 51 
 
 Government, as professional 
 
 group, 216-17 
 by minority, 222 ff 
 
 Habituation and memory, 62-64 
 Happiness and salvation, 102-03 
 Hedonism, defects of, 207 
 Hegel, influence on Marx, 46. 
 
 49 ff 
 
 Heredity, and germ-cell, 194 ff 
 Historical school of economics, 
 
 33-4, 
 Human nature, is constant, 197- 
 
 98 
 
 types of, 220 
 and peace, 235-36 
 
 Idealism in political philosophv, 
 
 213-14 
 
 Ideas versus conditions, 91-92 
 Income, national, 127-29 
 sources of, 130 
 
 how to be raised under social- 
 ism, 134 
 present distribution in the U. 
 
 S., 146-48 
 
 not all available for consump- 
 tion, 163 
 
 why so unequal, 166 
 determines pricing, 170 
 is a price, 180 
 as part of enviroment, 192 
 and efficiency, 202 
 and happiness, 206 ff. 
 Induction, principles of, 68 ff. 
 why making agreements possi- 
 ble, 77 
 Intelligence, versus knowledge, 
 
 -^04* 
 
 Internationalism, 226 ff. 
 Invention, 30-31 
 
 Justice, presupposes reason, 116- 
 
 17 
 
 aims at social strength, 118 
 and competition, 120 ff. 
 and government, 226 
 under socialism, 255 
 
 Labor power, gain under social- 
 ism, 140 
 
 use of, in U. S. to-day, 152-55 
 Labor theory of value, 20 
 
 criticized, 28-9 
 Lamarckianism, 192-93 
 
 bearing on economics, 201 
 
 attitude of biologists to-day, 
 
 Leisure, how to use it, 205 
 its role in progress, 255 
 
 Luxuries, in the U. S., 149 
 as personal services, 152-54 
 
 Maladjustment, 93 
 
 how brought about, 96-100 
 Malthusianism, 22 
 Marginism (see also Table 1), 
 
 3-40 
 
 attitude toward Historical eco- 
 nomics, 34 
 premises, 35 
 
 notion of cost and price, 35-6 
 on distribution, 37-8 
 criticism of, 39 ff. 
 Marx (see also Table 1), his in- 
 dependence of thought, 12-3 
 and Ricardo, 14-5 
 and W. Thompson, 19 
 his labor-theory, 20-1; 23 
 on private property, 21-2 
 as Malthusianist, 22 
 notion of profit-rate, 24 
 stand on free-trade, 25 
 criticism of Marx, 28-33 
 roots of his philosophy, 45; 54 
 Materialism, and Marx, 47-49 
 Mill, J. S., his Logic, 33 
 Morgan, Th. H., on Lamarck, 
 
 194 ff. 
 
 Motives versus deeds, 119 
 Mutation, versus fluctuations, 
 198-99 
 
 Justice, and inequalities, 111-14 Nation, a unit of force, 208 
 
INDEX 
 
 259 
 
 Nationalism as unit of social life, 
 235 
 
 (Percepts, physiological basis, 
 
 61-4 
 
 defined, 75 
 Platform, of socialism in the U. 
 
 S. to-day, 5-6 
 
 Political philosophy and empiri- 
 cism, 213-14 
 
 Price, Marxian notion, 20-1 
 marginal notion, 35-6 
 governed by income, 170 
 under socialism, 179 ff. 
 Private property, 
 
 Marx's justification of, 21 
 and efficiency, 173-77 
 Probability and enumeration, 
 
 73-4 
 Productivity, marginal view, 
 
 36-7 
 
 Proof, 78 
 
 Proportionality of factors, 37 
 Prosperity, theory of questions 
 
 raised by it, 8-9 
 stated fully, 102 ff. 
 Production, socialist promise of 
 
 increase, 126-27; 131 
 probable actual increase, 134 ff. 
 how affected by distribution, 
 171=72 
 
 Recall, and inference, 68 ff. 
 
 Recomposition of national in- 
 come, 146 ff. 
 
 Religion, social basis of, 121 
 
 Ricardo (see also Table 1), main 
 points of doctrine, 17 
 
 Right versus might, 123-24 
 
 Savings, contrasted with inven- 
 tion, 31-2 
 under socialism, 143-55 
 
 Science (see also Correlation and 
 
 Causation) 
 growth of, 80-82 
 Smith, A., notion of individual- 
 ism, 16 
 
 on equality of men, 187 
 Socialism, platform in U. S. to- 
 day, 5-6 
 
 questions raised by, 7-8 
 plan for raising social income, 
 
 131; 134 ff. 
 
 and leisure, 139; 205 
 and changes in employment of 
 
 labor forces, 150 ff. 
 and competition, 175-77 
 and cost of production, 184-85 
 and improvement of human na- 
 ture, 194 ff. 
 and eugenics, 199 ff. 
 and cosmopolitanism, 230 
 its merits and defects, 244-49 
 principle of distribution, 186- 
 
 87 
 
 Sovereignty, 212; 228 
 Suffering, a problem in justice, 
 
 Taxation, and distributive justice, 
 
 177 
 limits of under individualism, 
 
 178 
 
 Utility, marginal view, 36 
 Valuation, wrong to-day, 251 
 
 how to correct it, 254 
 Variation, biological view, 195 ff. 
 
 and sex, 197 
 
 and mutation, 199 
 
 War, causes of, 231-34 
 
 Waste, avoidance under socialism, 
 
 143-55 
 
 Wealth, and progress, 104-06 
 and war, 233 
 
 PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA 
 
UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY 
 
 BERKELEY 
 
 Co desjt from it nidi bouowed. 
 This book is DUE on the Last date stamped below. 
 
 'D LD 
 
 .'- 
 OCT 
 
 -r" 
 
 'D LD 
 
 1 
 
 OCT 1 4 '6 
 
 RE 
 
 LD 
 
 a 
 
B 66308 
 
 M141411 
 
 THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY