r 
 
 V 
 
 UNivs- 5:ty of 
 
 CALIFOR-NIA 
 SAN DIE«0
 
 ■It 

 
 ^. 
 
 History of Philosophy 
 
 BY 
 
 ALFRED WEBER 
 
 PROFESSOR IN THE L'NIVEKSITY OF STRASBUKQ 
 
 ^utf)orijeti ^Translation 
 
 FRANK THILLY, A.M., Ph.D. 
 
 PBOFE8SOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF MISSOURI 
 
 FROM THE FIFTH FRENCH EDITION 
 
 V^^gvy 
 
 NEW YORK 
 
 
 CHARLES SCRIBNKR'S SONS 
 
 
 1901 
 
 
 [All riyhts retei-ved] 
 
 
 
 100 
 
 
 ^3 6
 
 LI B lyAR Y 
 
 S C R I P P S ly'^S t\ T U T I O N 
 OF OC2ANOGRA,PHY 
 UNlVER^Si;»V OF CALIFORNIA 
 ft.LA. CALIFOJ^IA 
 
 Copyricjhf, 1,996, 
 By Chaklks Scribnkk's Sons. 
 
 John Wilson and Son. Cambkidoe, U.S.A.
 
 TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE 
 
 There is, in my opinion, no book so admirably fitted for 
 acquainting the student with the development of thought 
 as the able work of Professor Weber of the University of 
 Strasburo-. The author combines in his person the best 
 elements of French and German scholarship. His knowl- 
 edge of the subject is thorough and extensive, his judgment 
 sound, his manner of expression simple, clear, and precise. 
 His expositions remind one vividly of Kuno Fischer's fas- 
 cinating presentation of philosophical teachings. They 
 reproduce the essential thoughts of the great masters in 
 language which is singularly free from obscurities and un- 
 defined technical terms. The different systems are not 
 mechanically joined together like so many dominos ; the 
 history of philosophy is not conceived as an aggregate of 
 isolated, disconnected theories, but as an evolution, as a 
 more or less logical development, as a process from the 
 simple to the complex. It is not a comedy of errors, a 
 Sisyphus labor, a series of mighty efforts and corresponding 
 failures, but a gradual advance towards truth. There are 
 differences and contradictions, it is true, and many devia- 
 tions from the ideal straight line which the historian, 
 overlooking the entire course of development, may draw 
 between the beginning and the end. Pliih)sophy often 
 follows false paths and loses itself in l»Iind alle3^s. Yet 
 this does not mean that it is a wild-goose chase.
 
 iv PREFACE 
 
 We have long wanted a text-book of tlie liistoiy of phi- 
 losopliy that covers the whole field, and presents the subject 
 in a manner suited to the needs of the beginner. Zeller's 
 admirable compendium of Greek philosophy and Falcken- 
 berg's History of Modem Philosophy deal with special 
 periods. Windelband's voluminous History of Philosophy^ 
 with its arbitrary divisions and unfortunate method of cut- 
 ting up a system into parts and discussing these separately, 
 under entirely different heads, hopelessly confuses the stu- 
 dent. Besides, its account of philosophy since the days of 
 Kant — a period in which our age is especially interested — 
 is wholly inadequate. Professor Weber's work is the most 
 serviceable manual thus far published. It begins as simply 
 as the history of philosophy itself, and gradually introduces 
 the reader to the complex problems of modern thought, to 
 wliich it devotes more than one-half of its entire space. 
 The portions dealing with Kant and his successors are 
 particularly admirable. The clear and comprehensive ex- 
 position of the Hegelian philosophy will greatly assist the 
 student in his endeavors to understand that much abused 
 system. And the modern theory of evolution, wliich has 
 revolutionized the thought of our century, and which is 
 barely mentioned by Falckenberg and Windelband, surely 
 deserves the attention and criticism it here receives. 
 
 This translation is made from the fifth French edition 
 (1892), and includes a number of changes and additions 
 which the author kindly communicated to me in manu- 
 script. I have taken pains to render the original into clear 
 and simple English, and to increase the usefulness of the 
 book wherever it seemed possible and proper to do so, al- 
 ways keeping in mind the demands of the readers for whom 
 the work is intended. All material inserted by me is
 
 PREFACE V 
 
 placed in square brackets. I have increased the bibliog- 
 raphy (1) by adding the titles of standard American, Eng- 
 lish, German, Frencli, and Italian works ; (2) by mentioning 
 translations of foreign books referred to in the text and 
 notes ; (3) by giving the names of important philosoph- 
 ical journals published in tliis country and abroad ; (4) by 
 placing at the end of the volume a list of the best modern 
 works on logic, epistemology, psychology, anthropology, 
 ethics, aesthetics, the philosophy of history, the philosophy 
 of religion, jurisprudence, politics, etc. I have also pre- 
 pared an index. 
 
 FRANK THILLT, 
 
 University of Missouri, 
 May, 1896.
 
 CONTENTS 
 
 INTRODUCTION 
 
 Paob 
 
 § 1. Philosophy, Metaphysics, and Science 1 
 
 § 2. Division • ^ 
 
 § 3. Sources 
 
 I. GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 THE AGE OF METAPHYSICS PROPER, OR PHILOSOPHY 
 OF NATURE 
 
 (b. c. COO-400) 
 
 § 4. The Origin of Greek Philosophy 17 
 
 § 5. The School of Miletus. Thales, Anaximander, 
 
 axaximenes 21 
 
 § 6. The Problem of Becoming 24 
 
 A. The Negation of Becoming 
 
 § 7. Eleatic Philosophy. Xexophanes, Parmenides, 
 
 Melissus, Zexo, Gokgias 24 
 
 B. The Apotheosis of Becoming 
 
 § 8. ITeraclitu8 33
 
 Viii CONTENTS 
 
 C. The Explanation of Becoming 
 
 Page 
 
 § 9. The Pythagorean Speculation ^7 
 
 § 10. Empedocles 44 
 
 § 11. Anaxagoras */ 48 
 
 § 12. Diogenes of Apollonia, Archelaus, Leucippus, De- 
 
 mocritus 53 
 
 THE AGE OF CRITICISM, OR PHILOSOPHY OF MIND 
 
 § 13. Protagoras o9 
 
 § 14. Socrates ... 63 
 
 § 15. Aristippus and Hedonism. — Antisthenes and Cyni- 
 cism. — Euclides and the School of Megara . 71 
 
 A. The Negation of Matter. — The Apotheosis of Thought 
 
 § 16. Plato 75 
 
 (1) The Idea 81 
 
 (2) Nature 91 
 
 (3) The Highest Good 98 
 
 § 17. Aristotle 1*^4 
 
 (1) First Philosophy 108 
 
 (2) Second Philosophy, or the Philosophy of 
 
 Nature 118 
 
 B. The Apotheosis of Matter. — The Negation of the 
 Thought- Substance 
 
 § 18. Epicurus 134 
 
 C. The Apotheosis of Will 
 
 § 19. Stoicism 140 
 
 §20. The Sceptical Reaction. — Pyrrhonism .... 148 
 
 § 21. Academic Scepticism 150
 
 CONTENTS IX 
 
 Page 
 
 § 22. Sensationalistic Scepticism 152 
 
 § 23. The Scientific Movement 159 
 
 § 24. Eclecticism 162 
 
 § 25. Plotinus and Xeo-Platoxism 167 
 
 § 26. The Last Neo-Platonic Polvtheists. — Porphyry, 
 
 Jaaiblichus, Proclus 179 
 
 II. PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 THE REIGN OF PLATONIC-CHRISTIAN THEOLOGY 
 
 § 27. Christian Platonism 18y 
 
 § 28. St. Augustine 188 
 
 § 29. The Death Struggles of the Roman World. — 
 Barbarism. — The First Symptoms of a New 
 
 Philosophy 198 
 
 § 30. Scholasticism 201 
 
 § 31. ScoTus Erigena 204 
 
 § 32. St. Anselmus 210 
 
 § 33. Realism and Xominalism 219 
 
 § 34. Abelard 222 
 
 § 35. Hugo of St. Victor 227 
 
 § 36. The Progress of Free Thought 230 
 
 THE REIGN OF PERIPATETIC SCHOLASTICISM 
 
 A. Semi-Reallsttc Penpateticism 
 
 § 37. Growing Influence of the Philosophy of Aristotle 235 
 
 § 38. The Tekipatetics of the Thiktkenth Century . 239 
 
 § .39. St. Thomas of \iiv\s 241 
 
 S 40. Duns SctjTus 246
 
 X. CONTENTS 
 
 B. Nominalistic Peripateticism 
 
 Txas 
 
 § 41. The Reappearaxce of Nominalism. — Dukand, Oc- 
 cam, BURIDAN, D'AlLLY 252 
 
 §42. The Downfall of Scholasticism. — The Revival 
 OF THE Interest in Nature and Experimental 
 Science. — Roger Bacon. — Mysticism .... 256 
 
 § 43. The Revival of Letters 261 
 
 §44. Neo-Platonism. — Theosophy. — Magic 265 
 
 § 45. Aristotle versus Aristotle, or the Liberal Peri- 
 patetics. — Stoics. — Epicureans. — Sceptics . 267 
 
 § 46. The Religious Reform 274 
 
 § 47. Scholasticism and Theosophy in the Protestant 
 
 Countries. — Jacob Bohme 277 
 
 § 48. The Scientific Movement 281 
 
 III. MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 THE AGE OF INDEPENDENT METAPHYSICS 
 
 (From Bruno to Locke and Kant) 
 
 § 49. Giordano Bruno 286 
 
 § 50. ToMMASO Campanella 291 
 
 § 51. Francis Bacon 295 
 
 § 52. Thomas Hobbes ,300 
 
 § 53. Descartes 305 
 
 § 54. The Cartesian School 317 
 
 § 55. Spinoza 323 
 
 I. Definitions 325 
 
 II. Deductions 326 
 
 (1) Theory of Substance 326 
 
 (2) Theory of Attributes 329 
 
 (3) Theory of Modes 334 
 
 S 56. Leibniz 343
 
 CONTEXTS XI 
 
 THE AGE OF CRITICISM 
 
 Page 
 
 § 57. John- Locke • 370 
 
 § 58. Berkeley 391 
 
 § 59. CONDILLAC 399 
 
 § 60. The Progress of Materialism 404 
 
 § 61. David Hume 417 
 
 § 62. Immaxuel Kant 434 
 
 I. Critique of Pure Reason 437 
 
 II. Critique of Practical Reason 462 
 
 III. Critique of Judgment 468 
 
 § 63. Kant and German Idealism 473 
 
 § 64. Fichte .481 
 
 §65. SCIIELLING 487 
 
 § 66. Hegel 496 
 
 I. Logic, or Genealogy of Pure Concepts . 501 
 
 II. Philosophy of Nature 510 
 
 III. Philosophy of Mind 513 
 
 § 67. Herbart 535 
 
 § 68. Schopenhauer 544 
 
 § 69. Darwin and Contemporary INIonism 560 
 
 § 70. Positivism and Xeo-Criticism 573 
 
 § 71. Conclusion 587 
 
 Bibliography 605 
 
 LvDEx 613
 
 HISTORY (3F PHILOSOPHY 
 
 INTRODUCTION 
 
 § 1. Philosophy, Metaphysics, and Science 
 
 Philosophy is the search for a comprehensive view of 
 nature, an attempt at a universal explanation of things. It 
 is both the summaiy of the sciences and their completion ; 
 both general science and a specialty distinguished from 
 science proper ; and, like its elder sisters, religion and poe- 
 try, forms a separate branch among tlie manifestations of 
 the human mind. 
 
 The different sciences have special groups of facts for 
 their subject-matter, and seek to discover the causes of these 
 phenomena, or to formulate the laws according to which 
 they are produced. In philosophy, on the other hand, the 
 human mind endeavors to rise beyond such groups and 
 their particular laws, and to explain the world as a whole, 
 or the universal fact or phenomenon^ by the cause of the 
 causes, or the fii-st cause. In other words, it attempts to 
 answer the question, Why does this world exist, and how 
 does it happen to be what it is ? ^ 
 
 ' As a searcli for the first cause, pliilosophy is defined, more par- 
 ticularly, as melaphysics, ontology, or apeculcitive philosophy. The phil- 
 osophy which abandons this search, and contents itself with being 
 scientific synthesis, is called po.tilive philosophy or positivivn. Posi- 
 tivism may simply be groiinderl upon the historical fact that systems 
 constantly contradict each other, in which case it rests on a purely 
 empirical basis, or it may be based upon the rational analysis of the 
 human understanding. In the former case, it is scepticism, in the 
 latter, criticism. Opposed to scepticism we have dofjmatism, that is, 
 the naive or deliberate belief iu the ability of the liiinian mind to 
 
 1
 
 2 INTRODUCTION 
 
 But though philosophy has its own subject-matter and 
 a separate sphere of its own, it is none the less connected 
 with positive science by the closest of ties ; and science 
 cannot break these bonds without danger to itself. It is 
 from the positive sciences, and particularly from psychol- 
 ogy and allied branches, that philosophy derives its methods 
 and the matter for its systems. The sciences, without phil- 
 osophy, are an aggregate without unity, a body without a 
 soul; philosophy, without the sciences, is a soul without 
 a body, differing in nothing from poetry and its dreams. 
 Science is the indispensable foundation and the matter, as 
 
 reach an objective knowledge of things and their first cause. Ration- 
 alism claims to arrive at this knowledge by a priori reasoning ; em- 
 piricism assumes no other method than observation and induction, or 
 a posteriori reasoning. Pui'e, or a priori, speculation is the method pre- 
 ferred by idealism, which regards thought as the original fact, prior 
 and superior to all reality. Empiricism, on the contrary, is based 
 iipon the view that thought, far from being the first cause, is derived 
 from a pre-existing reality ; that is, upon realism in the modern sense 
 of the word. (See also § 33.) When the action of the first cause is 
 considered unconscious and involuntary, as distinguished from teleo- 
 logical (or making for an end), realism becomes materialism and mech- 
 anism. Idealism in tm-n becomes spiritualism when it personifies the 
 first cause, and regards it, not merely as an idea that realizes itself, 
 but also as a heing that hovers above things (supranaturalism, transcen- 
 dentalism') and governs them according to its free-will (theism), or by 
 means of unchangeable laws (deism) ; this is the dualism of mind and 
 matter, of creator and nature, as opposed to pantheism, naturalism, or 
 monism. Pantheism, naturalism, or monism identifies the idea of cause 
 with the concept of substance, and considers the first cause as the 
 innermost substance of things (immanency of God), and the totality 
 of its modes or phenomena, the universe, as a living unity (monism), 
 as one and the same collective being governed according to the laws 
 which follow from its own nature (natm'alism) . Monism is either 
 absolute or plural, according as it considers the cosmic substance as an 
 absolute unity, or as a collection of irreducible unities ; it is atomism 
 or dynamism, according as these imities are regarded as infinitely small 
 extensions (atoms), or as absolutely unextended centres of force (dyna- 
 mides or monads).
 
 PHILOSOPHY, METAPHYSICS, AND SCIENCE 3 
 
 it were, of pliilosopliy ; it is, to use an Aristotelian pkrase, 
 potential philosophy. Philosophy, in turn, is science in 
 actu, the most exalted function of the scholar, the supreme 
 satisfaction of the scientific spirit and its natural tendency 
 to comprehend everything into a unity. 
 
 Philosophy and science are intimately related, not only 
 in essence and in interests, but also as to their origin and 
 destiny. Animated by the same all-powerful instinct to 
 discern the causes of tilings — rerum cognoscere causas — 
 and to comprehend them into the unity of a first cause, the 
 human mind no sooner reaches certain elementary truths 
 in physics, mathematics, and morals, than it hastens to 
 synthesize them, to form them into universal theories, 
 into ontological and cosmological systems, i. e. to philosO' 
 pliize, to make metaphysics. It makes up for its ignorance 
 of realit}^ either by means of the imagination, or by that 
 wonderful instinct of childhood and of genius which divinea 
 the truth without searching for it. This accounts for the 
 aprioristic, idealistic, and fantastic character of the philoso- 
 phy of the ancients, as well as for its incomparable grandeur. 
 In proportion as our stock of positive knowledge is in- 
 creased, as scientific labor is divided and consequently de- 
 veloped, philosophy becomes more and more differentiated 
 from poetry; its methods are recognized, its theories gain in 
 depth what the sciences acquire in scope. Every scientific 
 movement gives rise to a philosophical movement ; every 
 new philosophy is a stimulus to science. Though this bond 
 of union seems to have Ijeen ruptured during the Middle 
 Ages, the breach is but an apparent one. Whatever hostil- 
 ity or indifference is manifested towards science, comes from 
 the official pliilos()])hy of the School ; it is never found among 
 the independent philosophers, l)e they Christians, Jews, or 
 Arabians. Tliere may be as much opposition between sci-. 
 ence and a certain pliilosopliy in the nineteenth century as 
 there was in the times of Roger Bacon and Lord Verulam.
 
 4 INTRODUCTION 
 
 True science and true philosopliy have always been in perfect 
 accord, and though there may be a sembhmce of rivalry, 
 their relations are to-day as harmonious as tliey can be.^ 
 
 § 2. Division 
 
 To the Ionian Greeks belongs the honor of having crea- 
 ted 2 European pliilosophy ; to the Neo-Latins and the Ger- 
 mans, that of having given to it its modern development. 
 
 Hence there are, in the history to be outlined by us, two 
 great and wholly distinct epochs, which are connected by 
 the Middle Ages (period of transition). 
 
 1 [On the nature and import of pliilosophy, and its relation to 
 other sciences, consult Ladd, Introduction to Philosojihy, New York, 
 1891 ; Volkelt, Vortriige zur Einfiihrung in die Philosophie der Gegen- 
 wart, Munich, 1892; Paulsen, Einleitung in die Philosophie, 3d ed., 
 Berlin, 1895 ; English translation by Frank Thilly, New York, 1895. 
 -Tr.] 
 
 2 By this word we do not mean to imply the absolute originality of 
 Hellenic philosophy. The influence exercised upon its development 
 by the Orient cannot be doubted. There is no trace of philosophy, 
 properly so called, among the Greeks before they come in contact 
 with Egypt, that is, before the reign of Psammetichus, who admits 
 them into the country. Moreover, the fathers of Greek philosophy are 
 all lonians ; from Asia Minor philosophy was imported, first into 
 Italy, and at a comparatively recent period into Athens, that is, into 
 Greece proper. But what is most important, we find in Ionian phil- 
 osophy, and that too at its very outset, conceptions the boldness of 
 which is in marked contrast with the comparative timidity of Attic 
 philosophy, — conceptions which pre-suppose a long line of intellectual 
 development. The influence of Egj^tian and Chaldean science, which 
 is, moreover, attested by Herodotus, may be compared to that exer- 
 cised by the Arabian schools upon the development of Clu-istian 
 thought in the Middle Ages. It has been exaggerated by Roth {Ge- 
 schichte unserer abendldndischen Philosophie, vol. I., 1846, 1862 ; vol. II., 
 1858) and unjustly denied by Zeller (Die Philosophie der Griechen, 5th 
 ed. 1892, vol. I.; English translation by Sarah AUeyne). Concerning 
 the relation of Pythagoreanism and Platonism to Indian and Iranian 
 speculation, and the part played by Babylon as the centre of intellec 
 tual exchange between the Orient and the Occident, see § 9.
 
 DIVISION 5 
 
 I. In the development of Greek philosophy, we have two 
 separate periods, — a period of spontaneous creation, and 
 one of sceptical reflection and re^^roduction. 
 
 1. The problem which dominates the former is the 
 problem of the origin of things : the problem of lecoming. 
 Among the lonians, tliis pliilosophy assumes the form of 
 materialistic pantheism; among the Italian philosophers, 
 who are influenced by the Doric spirit, it is essentially 
 spiritualistic pantheism. The systems produced by these 
 two schools contain in germ all the doctrines of the future, 
 especially the monistic and atomistic hj^^otheses, the two 
 poles of modern scientific speculation. — From Thales to 
 Protagoras, or from 600 to 440 b. c. 
 
 2. The age of critical reflection is inaugurated by the 
 irdvT(ov fxerpov avdpco7ro<; of the Sophists. This period 
 evolves the important truth, foreshadowed by Zeno, Par- 
 menides, and Anaxagoras, that the human understanding 
 is a coefficient in the production of the phenomenon. To 
 the problems of nature are added the problems of the soul ; 
 to the cosmological questions, logical and critical questions ; 
 to the speculations on the essence of things, investigations 
 concerning the criterion of truth and the end of life. 
 Greek philosophy reaches its highest development in Plato, 
 as far as depth is concerned ; in Aristotle and in the sci- 
 ence of Alexandria, as regards analysis and the extent of 
 its inquiries. 
 
 II. Scientific progress, and consequently speculation, 
 was arrested by the invasion of the Northern races. The 
 philosophical spirit was extinguished for want of something 
 to nourish it. Ten centuries of uninterrupted labor were 
 followed by ten centuries of sleep, — a sleep that was deep 
 at first, and then broken by bright dreams of the past (Plato 
 and Aristotle) and forecasts of the future. Altliougli 
 the logic of liist^jry is less transparent during the middle 
 ages tlian before and after this period of transition, wo
 
 6 INTRODUCTION 
 
 notice two epoclis that run parallel with those of Attic 
 philosoph}- : one, Platonic, realistic, turned towards the 
 past (from St. Augustine to St. Anselm), the other, Peri- 
 patetic, nominalistic, big with the future. 
 
 III. Modern philosophy dates from the scientific and 
 literary revival in the fifteenth century. Its history, like 
 that of Greek speculation, presents, — 
 
 1. A period of expansion and ontological synthesis 
 (Bruno, Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz), and, 
 
 2. A period of critical reflection and analysis (essays 
 concerning the human understanding : Locke, Hume, Kant, 
 and liis successors). 
 
 § 3. Sources 
 
 The principal sources for the history of jDliilosophy are : 
 
 For pre-Socratic speculation : Plato and Aristotle. ^ 
 
 For Socrates: Xenophon^ and Plato, particularly the 
 
 Apologj/, the CrtYo, and the Fhcedo. 
 
 For Plato : the Republic^ the Timceus^ the Syviposium, the 
 
 Fhcedrtcs, the Thecetetiis, the Gorgias, the Protagoras.^ 
 For Aristotle : the Meta])hysics, the Logic, the Ethics, the 
 
 Physics, the Psychology, the Politics ; the commentators of 
 
 Aristotle, especially Simplicius.* 
 
 * Especially the first book of the Metaphysics (see § 17, first note), 
 which is a historical summary of philosophy from Thales to Aristotle. 
 The fragments of the pre-Socratic authors have been collected by 
 Mullach, Fragmenta phil. grcec. ante Socratem, 3 vols., Paris, 1860 
 [also by Ritter and Preller (mentioned on page 8). English trans- 
 lations in Burnet's Early Oreek Philosophy (page 8), and of Heraclitus, 
 in Patrick's Heraclitus on Nature. For translations of classical writers, 
 consult Bohn's Classical Library. — Tr.]. 
 
 2 Memorabilia Socratis recens. J. G. Schneider, Oxf., 1813. 
 « [See § 16, note 2. — Tr.] 
 
 * Comment, in Arist. physicorum libros, ed. by Hermann Diels, Berlin, 
 1882 ; Comment, in libros de anima, ed. by M. Hayduck, Berlin, 1882.
 
 SOURCES 7 
 
 For the post-Aristotelian schools and Greek philosophy 
 in general : Lucretius,^ Cicero,^ Seneca,^ Plutarch,* Sextus 
 Empiricus,^ Diogenes Laertius,^ Clement of Alexancb.ia,7 
 Origeu,^ Hippolytus,^ Eusebius,!^ Plotiniis," Porphyry,ii 
 
 1 Lucretii Cari de rerum natura libb. C. Lachmaun rec. et illustr., 
 Berlin, 1850 ff. [edited also by Bernays, Munro, and others]. 
 
 2 The De divinatione et defato, the De natura deorum, the De offi- 
 ciis, the Dejinihus, the Tusculance disputationes, and the Academica; 
 Opera omnia, ed. I-^e Clerc, Bouillet, Lemau-e, 17 vols., Paris, 1827-32 ; 
 Opera philosophica, ed. Goerenz, 3 vols., Leipsic, 1809-1813 ; Ciceronis 
 historia pldlosophics antiquce, ex omnibus illius scriptis collegit F. 
 Gedike, Berlin, 1782, 1801, 1814. 
 
 3 Opera qu£e extant c. not. et comment, varior., 3 vols., Amsterdam, 
 1672. 
 
 * De physicis philosophorum decretis libb., ed. Beck, Leipsic, 1777; 
 Scripta mornlia, 6 vols., Leipsic, 1820 ; Opera omnia graece et latine ed. 
 Reiske, 12 vols., Leipsic, 1774-82. 
 
 s Sexti Empirici opera (Uvpfxoveicop vTrorvnuaeoiv libb. IIL ; Ad ver- 
 sus mathematicos libb. XL) graic. et lat. ed. Fabricius, Leipsic, 1718 
 and 1842 ; ed. Emm. Bekker, Berlin, 1842. 
 
 8 Diogenis Laertii de vitis, dogmatibus et apopTithegmatibus darorum. 
 philosophorum libb. X. grsece et latine ed. Hiibner, 2 vols., Leipsic, 
 1828, 1831 ; D. L. 1. X. ex Italicis codicibus nunc primum excussis 
 recensuit C. Gabr. Cobet, Paris, 1850. Diogenes Laertius flourished 
 about 230 of oiir era. 
 
 ' dementis Alexandrini opera, Leipsic, 1830-34 (Adyo? TrporpfnTiKos 
 TT/joy 'EXXj^ms- ; IlatSaycoyos ; Srpco/xaTf Is) . 
 
 8 De principds gr. ed. c. interpret, lat. Rufini, et annot. instruxit ed. 
 R. Redepeuuing, Leipsic, 183G ; Contra Celsum libb. ed. Spencer, Cam- 
 bridge, 1671 ; Origenis opera omnia quje graece vel latine tantum ex- 
 stant et ejus nomine circumferuntur, ed. C. et C. V. Delarue, denuo 
 recens. emend, castig. C. H. E. Lommatzsch, 25 vols., Berlin, 1831-48. 
 
 * S. Ilippolyti refutalionis omnium hceresium libror. X. quae super- 
 Bunt graice et latine ed. Duncker et Schneidewin, Gbtt. 1856-59. 
 The firbt book, known by the title ({)iXo(To(f)oCixfva, was for a long 
 time attributed to Origen ; l)Ooka TV.-X., whioli were discovered in 
 Greece in 1842, were first pu]>]i9hed by Emm. Miller, Oxford, 1851, 
 under the title Origenis philosophumena, etc. 
 
 1* Eu.seliii Paniph. Pncparatio evangelica, ed. Ileiiiichen, Leipsic, 
 1812. 
 
 u See § 25.
 
 8 INTRODUCTION 
 
 Proclus,! Eunapms,^ Stobseus,^ Photius,* Suidas,^ and mod- 
 ern historical Works.^ 
 
 1 See § 25. 
 
 2 Euiiapii Sard. VitCB philosophorum et sophistarum, ed. Boissonade, 
 Paris, 18i9. 
 
 8 Stobfei Eclogarwn physicarum et ethicarwn libb. graece et latine ed. 
 Heeren, 2 vols., Gdtt. 1791, 1801 (out of print) ; id. ed. Meineke, 
 2 vols., Leipsic, 1860, 1864; Stobsei Florilegium, ed. Th. Gaisford, 
 4 vols., Oxford, 1822 ; Leipsic, 1823 ; Meineke, 4 vols., Leipsic, 1855-57. 
 
 * MyriobihUon, ed. Hdschel, Augsburg, 1801. The patriarch Pho- 
 tius flourished in the 9th century. 
 
 ^ Lexicon of Suidas, ed. Gaisford, London, 1834 ; Bernhardi, 2 vols., 
 Halle, 1834. Suidas flourished about 1000. 
 
 6 Especially : [jNIuUach, Fragmenia jihilosophorum Grcecorum, 3 vols., 
 1860-1881; Diels, Doxographi Grceci, Berlin, 1879] ; Ritter and PreUer, 
 Historia philosophice Graeco-Romance ex fontium locis contexta [7th ed., 
 Schultess and Wellmann, Gotha, 1888] ; Ritter, Geschichte der Philo- 
 sophie alter Zeil, Berlin, 1829 ; Brandis, Handhuch der Geschichte der 
 griechisch-rbmischen Philosophie, 3 vols., Berlin, 1835-1860 ; same author, 
 Geschichte der Entwickelungen der gr. Philosophie, etc., 2 vols., 1862-64 ; 
 Roth, Geschichte unserer abend land ischen Philosophie, 2 vols., Mannheim- 
 1848-58 ; Laforet, Histoire de la philosophie ancienne, 2 vols., Brussels, 
 1867 ; Ed. Zeller, Die Philosophie der Griechen in ihrer geschichtlichen 
 Entwickelung [(five editions since 1844), 5th ed. begun in 1892, 3 pts. 
 in 5 vols., Leipsic (Engl, transl. of all but part dealing with Ai'istotle 
 and elder Peripatetics, by S. F. AUeyne and O. J. Reichel, London and 
 New York, 1876-1883. Same author's smaller work, Grundriss der 
 Geschichte der griechischen Philosophie, 4th ed., Leipsic, 1893 ; Engl, 
 transl. by S. F. AUeyne and Evelyn Abbot, Xew York, 1890. — Tr.]. 
 Tlie following may also be consulted with profit : Grote, Histoi-ij oj 
 Greece, 6th ed., 10 vols., London, 1888 ; the same author, Plato and 
 the other Companions of Socrates, 5th ed., London, 1888 ; [same author, 
 Aristotle, 2 vols., 2d ed., 1879; Schwegler, Geschichte der griechischen 
 Philosophie, 3d ed. Tiibingen, 1886 ; Ferrier, Lectures on Greek Philoso- 
 phy, 2 vols., Edinburgh and London, 1866 ; London, 1888 ; Teichmiiller, 
 Studien zur Geschichte der Begriffe, Berlin, 1874 ; Neue Studien, Gotha, 
 1876-79; Byk, Die vorsokratische Philosophie, Leipsic, 1875-77; Burnet, 
 Early Greek Philosophy, London and Edinburgh, 1892 ; INIayor, A Sketch 
 oJ Ancient Philosophy from Tholes to Cicero, Cambridge, 1881 If. ; Benn, 
 The Greek Philosophers, 2 vols., London, 1883 ; Windelband, Geschichte 
 der griechischen Philosophie, 2d ed., Munich, 1894 ; Marshall, A Short
 
 SOURCES 9 
 
 For the Patristic period : the polemical writiugH of the 
 Fathers, 1 especially the X0709 TrpoTpeirrLKo^ 7rpo<i "EXXt;- 
 va<i, the Pedagogue, and the arpoiixara of St. Clement of 
 Alexandria, the Principles and the Anti-Celsus of Origen, 
 the Apologcticus of Tertullian, the Tnstitutiones divincc of 
 Lactantius, the City of God and the Confessions of ^t. 
 Augustine. 
 
 For the Scholastic period : the De divisione naturce of 
 Scotus Erigena, the Monologium, the Proslogium, and the 
 Cur Deus homo of St. Anselmus, the Theology, the Pthics, 
 and the Dialectics of Abelard, the Sentences of Peter the Lom- 
 bard, the Commentary of Averroes, the Sum of St. Thomas, 
 the Qiuvstiones of Duns Scotus and Occam, the Dims onajus 
 of Roger Bacon, the writings of Raymundus Lullus, the 
 historical works of Ritter, Cousin, and Haur(^au.2 
 
 Hislori/ of Greek Philosophy, London, 1891 ; Chaignet, Histoire de la 
 psijchologie des Grecs, 5 vols., Paris, 1887-92; Ziegler, Die Ethik der 
 Griechen und Romer, Bonn, 1881 ; Schmidt, Die Ethik der alten Grie- 
 chen, 2 vols., Berlin, 1881 ; Kdstlin, Die Ethik des klassischen Alter- 
 //jwms, Leipsic, 1887; Luthardt, Die antike Ethik, 1887; W'dlter, Die 
 Geschichte der Aesthetik im AUerthum, Leipsic, 1893; Rohde, Psyche, 
 SeelenkuU und Unsterhlichkeitsglauhe der Griechen, 2 vols., Freiburg, 
 1890-9-1; Bergk, Griechische Litteratiiryeschichte, 2 vols., Berlin, 1872, 
 1883; K. O. Miiller, Die Geschichte der gi-iechischen Litteratur, 2 vols., 
 Stuttgart, 1882-84 ; Mahafify, History of Classical Greek Literature, 
 3 vols., 2d ed. London, 1892 ; Teuffel, Geschichte der romischen Littera- 
 tur, 5th ed., Leipsic, 1890; Bender, Grwuh-iss der romischen Litteratur- 
 geschichle, 2d ed., Leipsic, 1889 (Engl, transl. from first ed. by Crowell 
 & Richardson, Boston, 1884) ; Preller, Griechische Mythologie, 2 vols., 
 Berlin, 187.5; Lehrs, Pojmldre Aufsdtze aus deni AUerthum, 2d ed., 
 Leipsic, 1875; Laurie, Historical Survey of Pre-Christian Education, 
 Londoji, 1895 (first published as a series of articles in the " School 
 Review," May, 1893-April, 1895). For further references, see L'eber- 
 weg-IIeinze, § 7, pp. 27-33. Consult also the general histories of 
 philosopliy iiHMitionod on pages 13 IT. — Tit.]. 
 
 1 Colleclfd by J. P. Mignc, Paris, 1810 ff. 
 
 2 [For primitive Christianity, i)atristic and scholastic philosophy 
 consult, besides the general histories of philosophy mentioned on pages
 
 10 INTKODUCTION 
 
 For the philosophy of the Renaissance : the De docta tgno' 
 rantia of Nicholas of Cusa, the De suUilitate and the De 
 rerum varietate of Cardanus, the De immortalitate animce 
 of Pomponatius, the Animadversiones in dialecticam Ari~ 
 stotelis of Ramus, the Essais of Montaigne, the TriumpJius 
 philosophice, the De rerum ceternitate^ and the De mundo of 
 Taurellus, the Aurora of J. Boehme.^ 
 
 13 if. : Drummond, Philo Judceus, or the Jewish-Alexandrian Philosophy 
 in its Development and Completion, 2 vols., London, 1888 ; Deutinger, 
 Geist der christlicheii Ueherlieferung, Regensbm-g, 1850-51 ; Ritsclil, 
 Die Entstehung der altkatholischen Kirche, 2d ed., Bonn, 1857 ; de Pres- 
 sense, Histoire des trois premiers siecles de Ve'glise, Paris, 1858 ft". ; 
 Baur, Das Christenthum der drei ersten Jahrhunderte, 2d ed., Tubingen, 
 1860 ; J. Alzog, Grundriss der Patrologie, 3d ed., Freiburg, 1876 ; 
 Pfleiderer, Das Urchristenthum, Berlin, 1887; Stockl, Geschichte der 
 Philosophie der patrisllschen Zeit, Wiirzburg, 1859 ; Huber, Die Philoso- 
 phie der Kirchenrdter, ^lunicli, 1859; Xeander, Christliche Dogmenge- 
 schichte, ed. by J. Jacobi, Berlin, 1857 ; Harnack, Lehrbuch der 
 Dogmengeschichte, 3 vols., 2d ed., Freiburg, 1888-90 ; Donaldson, A 
 Critical History of Christian Literature and Doctrine, 3 vols., London, 
 1885-66 ; same author, The Apostolic Fathers, London, 1874 ; Ritter, 
 Die christliche Philosophic, 2 vols., Gottingen, 1858-59 ; Rousselot, 
 Etudes sur la philosophic dans le moyen-dge, Paris, 1840-42; Ilaureau, 
 De la philosophie seolastiqufi, 2 vols., Paris, 1850; same author, Histoire 
 de la philosophie scolastique, 2d series, Paris, 1872-80 : Stockl, Geschichte 
 der Philosophie des Mittelalters, 3 vols., Mayence, 1864-66; Baeumker, 
 Beitrdge zur Geschichte der Philosophie des Mittelalters, Miinster, 1891 
 ft.; Renter, Die Geschichte der religiosen AufkUirung im Mittelalter, 
 
 2 vols., Berlin, 1875-77; W. Kaulich, Geschichte der scholastischen Phil- 
 osophic, Prague, 1863; Werner, Die Scholastik des spiiteren Mittelalters, 
 
 3 vols., Vienna, 1881 if. ; Gass, Geschichte der christlichen Ethik, Berlin, 
 1881 ; Ziegler, Geschichte der christlichen Ethik, Strasbiu'g, 1886 ; 2d 
 ed., 1892; Luthardt, Geschichte der christlichen Ethik, 1888; Lecky, 
 A History of European Morals from Augustus to Cliarlemagne, 2 xoh., 
 London, 1869; 3d ed., 1877 ; Denifle, Die Uniccrsitliten des Mittelalters, 
 Berlin, 1885 ; Laurie, The Rise and Early Constitution of Universities, 
 New York, 1888. For further references, see Ueberweg-Heinze, vol. 
 IL, §§ 1, 3, 4ff.; §§ 19 ff. — Tr.] 
 
 * [For the Renaissance, see the general and modern histories of 
 philosophy (pp. 12-16), and the following : Carrifere, Die philoso
 
 SOURCES 11 
 
 For modern times : Bruno's Del infinito universo and De 
 mo/iade, Campanella's Atheismus triumphatus, Pliilosophia 
 sensibus demonstrata^ and De geiitilismo^ Francis Bacon's No- 
 vum organum, Hobbes's De cive and De corpore^ Descartes's 
 Discourse on Method and Princij^les., Malebranche's Recherche 
 de la verite, Spinoza's Dtltics, Locke's -Essay concerning Hu- 
 man Understanding, Leibniz's New Essays and Monadology, 
 Berkeley's Principles of Human Knowledge, Condillac's 
 Treatise on Sensations, Holbach's System of Nature, the 
 Essays of Hume and Reid, Kant's Critiques, Fichte's Science 
 of Knowledge, Schelling's System of Transcendental Idealism, 
 Hegel's Logic and Encyclopedia of Philosophical Sciences, tlie 
 Metaphysics and the Psychology of Herbart, Schopenhauer's 
 World as Will and Idea, Comte's Course on Positive Phil- 
 osophy, J. S. Mill's Logic, Herbert Spencer's First Prin- 
 ciples, Albert Lange's History of Materialism, Ed. von 
 Hartmann's Philosophy of the Unconscious, etc. ; likewise 
 the cliief works of modern scientific literature of general 
 and therefore philosophical interest, like the Celestial 
 Bevolutions by Copernicus, the Mathematical Principles of 
 Natural Philosophy by Newton, the Spirit of the Laws by 
 Montesquieu, the Analytical Mechanics by Lagrange, the 
 Natural History of the Heavens by Kant, the Celestial 
 Mechanics and Exposition of the System of the World by 
 Laplace, Darwin's book on the Origin of Species, etc. ; 
 
 phische Weltanschauunf/ der Refonnntlonszcit, 1817. 2(1 ed., Leipsic, 
 1887; Voigt, Die Wictlerhdehung des clnxsischen Altcrthums, 1859; 3d 
 ed., edited l)y Lehnerdt, 2 vols., Berlin, 189:3; Biirckhardt, Die Cultur 
 der Renaissance, 2 vols, 1860, 4th ed. l>y L. Geiger, Leipsic, 1886 
 (Engl, transl. l)y S. G. C. Middleman, London, 1878 and 1890); 
 Geiger, Rennv<snnce und Ilumnnismus in Italien und Deulschlnnd, Berlin, 
 1882; .Symonds, The Renaissance in Itahj, 7 vols., London, 1875- 
 1886 ; Pesfhel, Geschichte des Zeilalters der Entdeckungen, 2d ed., 
 Leipsic, 1879. For further references, Ueberweg-Heinze, vol. III., 
 §§ 2-0. - Tu.]
 
 12 INTRODUCTION 
 
 finally, the historical works of Ritter,i Erdmann,^ Barchou 
 de Penhoen,3 Michelet* (of Berlin), Willm,^ Clialyb£eus,« 
 Bartholmess,^ Kuno Fischer,^ Zeller,^ Windelband,io etc.^^ 
 
 ^ GescMchte der neueren Philosophie (vols. IX.-XII. of his Ge- 
 schichte der Philosophie^, 1850-53. 
 
 2 Versuch einer toissenschaftlichen Darslellung der neueren Philosophie, 
 6 vols., Riga and Leipsic, 1834-1853. 
 
 ^ Histoire de la philosophie allemande depuis Leibniz jusqu^ a nos jours 
 Paris, 183G. 
 
 * Geschichte der letzten Systeme der Philosophie in Deutschland von 
 Kant bis Hegel, 2 vols., Berlin 1837-38. 
 
 * Histoire de la philosophie allemande \puis Kant jusqu'a Hegel, 4 
 vols., Paris, 1846-49. 
 
 * Historische Entwickelung der spekulaliven Philosophie in Deutschland 
 von Kant bis Hegel, Dresden, 1837, 5tli ed., 1860 ; Engl, translation, 
 1854. 
 
 ' Histoire des doctrines religieuses de la philosophie moderne, 2 vols., 
 Paris, 1855 ; Histoire philosophique de PAcade'miede Prusse, 2 vols., Paris, 
 1851. 
 
 8 Geschichte der neueren Philosophie, 8 vols., Mannheim and Heidel- 
 berg, 1854 ff.; [2d ed., 1865 ff. ; 3d ed., vol. I., 1 and 2, 1878, 1880; 
 vol. IL, 1889; vols. III. and IV., 1882; 2d ed., vol. V., 1885, vol. 
 VI. 1895 ; vol. VIT. (Hegel) not yet published ; vol. VIII. (Schopen- 
 hauer), 1898. Engl, translation of vol. I., 1, by J. P. Gordy, New 
 York, 1887; of vol. III., book 2, by J. P. Mahaffy, London, 1866; of 
 vol. v., chaps, i.-v., by W. S. Hough, London, 1888. Baco und seim 
 Nachfolger, 2d ed., Leipsic, 1875, Engl, translation by Oxenford, Lon- 
 don, 1857. — Tr.]. 
 
 ^ Geschichte der deutschen Philosophie seit Leibniz, Munich, 1872 ; 
 2d ed., 1875. 
 
 ^^ Geschichte der neuern Philosophie, vol. I., 1878, vol. II. 1880. 
 
 " [Lechler, Geschichte des englischen Deismus, Stuttgart and Tubin- 
 gen, 1841 ; Biedermann, Die deutsche Philosophie von Kant bis auf 
 unsre Zeit,2 vols., Leipsic, 1843; Damiron, Essai sur P histoire de la 
 philosophie au 17""^ siecle, Paris, 1846; Fortlage, Genetische Geschichte 
 der Philosophic seit Kant, Leipsic, 1852; Ch. de Remusat, Histoire de la 
 philosophie en Angleterre, etc., 2 vols., Paris, 1875; Harms, Die Philo- 
 sophie seit Kant, Berlin, 1876 ; Leslie Stephen, History of English 
 Thought in the Eighteenth Century, London, 1876 ; Eucken, Geschichte 
 und Kritik der Grundbegriffe der Gegenwart, Leipsic, 1878 ; 2d ed,,
 
 SOURCES 13 
 
 For European philosophy in general : (Stanley ^), 
 Brucker,^ Tiedemann,^ Buhle,* Deg^rando,^ Tennemann,^ 
 
 1893 (Engl, transl.by Stuart Phelps, 1880) ; Seth, From Kant to Hegel, 
 London, 1882 ; Eucken, Beitriige zur Geschichte der neueren Philosophie, 
 1886 ; Monrad, Denkrichtungen der neueren Zeit, Bonn, 1879 ; HofEding, 
 Einleitung in die englische Philosophie unserer Zeit (German transl. by 
 Kurella), Leipsic, 1889 ; Bowen, Modern Philosophy, 6th ed.. New 
 York, 1891 ; Roberty, La philosophie du siecle, Paris, 1891 ; Royce, The 
 Spirit of Modern Philosophy, New York, 1892; Biu"t, A Histortj oj 
 Modern Philosophy, 2 vols., Chicago, 1892 ; Falckenberg, Die Geschichte 
 der neueren Philosophie, 2d ed., 1892 (Engl, transl. by A. C. Ai'mstrong, 
 Jr., New York, 1893); Iloffding, Den Nyere Filosojie Hiatorie, Kopenhar 
 gen, vol. I., 1891 ; vol. II. will be issued in 1895 ; German translation 
 of both volumes, by Bendixen, in the press (O. Reisland, Leipsic) ; 
 W. Whewell, History of the Inductive Sciences, London, 1837, 3d ed., 
 1863; J. Schaller, Geschichte der Naturphilosopihie seit Bacon, 2 vols., 
 Leipsic, 1841-44 ; J. Baumann, Die Lehren von Rauin, Zeit und Mathe- 
 matik in der neueren Philosophie, 2 vols., Berlin, 1868-69 ; Konig, 
 Die Entwickelung des Causalprohlems von Cartesius bis Kant, Leipsic, 
 1888 ; same author. Die Entwickelung des Causalprohlems in der Phi- 
 losophie seit Kant, 2 pts., Leipsic, 1889-90 ; Lasswitz, Geschichte der 
 Atomistik vom Mittelalter his Newton, 2 vols., Ilambiu'g and Leipsic, 
 1890; Grimm, Zur Geschichte des Erkenntnissproblems von Bacon bis 
 Hume, 1890 ; Vorlander, Ge.^chichte der philosophischen Moral, Rechts-, 
 
 ^ [History of Philosophy, London, 105.5 ; in Latin, 2 vols., Leipsic, 
 1712. Also, Pierre Bayle, Dictionnaire historiqtie et critique, 2 folio 
 vols., 1695-97 ; 4th ed., revised and enlai-ged by Des Maizeaux, 4 folio 
 vols., Amsterdam and Leyden, 1740 ; Boureau-Deslandes, Histoire 
 critique de la philosophie, 3 vols., Paris, 1730-36 if. — Tk.] 
 
 2 Historia critica philosophire inde a mimdi incunahilis, 6 vols., Leip- 
 sic, 1742-07. 
 
 8 Geist der spekuluticen Philosojjhie, 6 vols., Marburg, 1791-97. 
 
 • Lehrbuch der Geschichte der Philosophie, S vols., Gottingen, 1796- 
 1804. 
 
 • Histoire comparde des systhnes de la philosophie, 3 vols., Paris,1803; 
 2ded., 4 vols., 1822-23. 
 
 • Geschichte der PhUosophie, 11 vols., L(!ipsic, 1798-1819'; Grundriss 
 der Geschichte der Philosophie, Leipsic, 1812 ; [l-ngl- transl. 1833 and 
 1.852 (liolm'a Library)].
 
 14 INTRODUCTION 
 
 Ritter,^ Hegel,^ Schwegler,^ Renouvier,^ Nourrisson,' 
 Cousin,* Janet," Prantl,^ Lange,^ Erdmann,^*^ Ueberweg," 
 
 und Staatslehre der Engliinder und Franzosen, Marburg, 1855 ; Mack- 
 intosh, On the Progress of Ethical Philosophy during the \lth and l^th 
 Centuries, Edinlmrgli, 1872; Jodl, Geschichte der Ethik in der neueren 
 Philosophie, 2 vols., Stuttgart, 1882-89; Bluntschli, Geschichte des all' 
 gemeinen Staatsrechts und der Politik seit dem 16. Jahrhundert, Municli, 
 1864 ; O. Pfleiderer, Religionsphilusophic auf geschichtlicher Grundlage, 
 2 vols., 3d ed., Berlin, 1S93 (vol. I. : Geschichte der Religionsphilosophie 
 von Spinoza bis zur Gegenivart) ; Engl, transl. by A. Stewai't and A. 
 Menzies, London, 1886-1888 ; Punjer, Geschichte der christlichen Re- 
 
 1 Geschichte der Philosophie, 12 vols., Hamburg, 1829-53. 
 
 * Vorlesungen iiber die Geschichte der Philosophie, published by 
 Michelet, Berlin, 1833 (vols. XIII.-XV. of the Complete Works); 
 [Engl, transl. by E. S. Haldane in 3 vols., London, 1892-1896. 
 -Tr.] 
 
 ' Geschichte der Philosophie iin Umriss, Stuttgart, 1848 ; 15th ed. 
 1891 ; [Engl, translations by Seelye, Xew York, 1856 if., and J. XL 
 Stirling, 7th ed., Edinburgh, 1879]. 
 
 ^ Manuel de philosophie ancienne, 2 vols., Paris, 1844 ; Manuel de 
 philosophie moderne, Paris, 1842. 
 
 5 Tableau des progres de la pense'e humaine depuis Thales j'usqua 
 Leibniz, Paris, 18.58, 1860. 
 
 ® Cours dliistoire de la philosophie, Paris, 1829 [Engl, transl. by 
 
 0. W. Wight, 2 vols., New York, 1889. — Tr.] ; Histoire gene'rale de 
 la philosophie depuis les temps les plus anciens jusqxi' au dix-neuvieme siecle, 
 1 vol., Paris, 1863; 12th ed. published by Barthelemy Saint-Hilaire, 
 Paris, 1884. 
 
 ' Histoire de la philosophie morale et politique dans Vantiquite et dans 
 les temps modernes, Paris, 1858. 
 
 ^ Geschichte der Logik im Abendlande, 4 vols., Leipsic, 1855 ff. 
 
 ' Geschichte des Material is7nus, 3d ed., Iserlohn, 1876-77; [Engl, 
 transl. m 3 vols, by E. C. Thomas, London, 1878-81. — Tr.]. 
 
 ^^ Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie, 2 vols., 3d ed., Berlin, 
 1878; [4th ed. prepared by B. Erdmann, 1895; Engl, transl. 3 vols., 
 ed. by W. S. Hough, London, 1890. — Tr.]. 
 
 " Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie, 3 vols., 7th ed., published 
 and enlarged by Heinze, Berlin, 1888 ; [8th ed. vol. L, 1894, voL IIL, 
 
 1, 1896; Engl, transl. by G. S. Morris, New York, 1872-74, — Tr.J.
 
 SOtRCES 15 
 
 Scholten,! Dulu-ing,2 Lewes,^ Lefevi-e,* Alaux,^ Franck,« 
 FoiiiU^e,7 Fabre,^ Kirchner.^ 
 
 ligiompldlosopUe seit der Reformation, 2 vols., Braunschweig, 1880-83; 
 Engl, transl. by W. Hastie, vol. I., Edinburgh and London, 1887; 
 Dessoir, Geschichte der neueren deutschen Psychologie, vol. I., Berlin, 
 1895; Buckle, History of Civilization in England, London, 1857-60; 
 Draper, History of the Intellectual Development of Europe, New York, 
 1863; Lecky, History of the Rise and Influence of the Spirit of Rational- 
 ism in Europe, London, 1885, 5th ed., 1872 ; Dean, The History of Civ- 
 ilization, New York and London, 1869 ; Hettner, Litteraturgeschichte 
 des 18. Jahrhunderts, 3 parts, Braunschweig, 1862-70; Paulsen, Ge- 
 schichte desgelehrten Unterrichts (from middle ages to the present time), 
 Leipsic, 1885 ; Engl, transl. by E. D. Perry, New York and London, 
 1895. For further references, see Falckenberg (trans.), pp. 15-17 ; also 
 Ueberweg-Heinze, vol. III., § 1 ff. ; and Windelband's History of 
 Philosophy. — Tr.] 
 
 1 History of Religion and Philosophy, 3d ed. much enlarged, 1868 
 (Dutch) ; French transl. from 2d ed. by Reville, Paris and Strasburg, 
 1861 ; German translation from 3d ed. by Redepenning, Elberfeld, 
 1868. 
 
 2 Kritische Geschichte der Philosophie, 4th ed., Leipsic, 1894. 
 
 8 A Biographical History of Philosophy from its Origin in Greece down 
 to the Present Day, 3d ed., London, 1863. 
 
 * La philosophie, Paris, 1879. 
 
 ' Histoire de la philosophie, Paris, 1882. 
 
 8 Dictionnaire des sciences philosopldques, 2d ed., Paris, 1875. 
 ■^ Histoire de la philosophie, Paris, 1875,4th ed., 1883; Extraits des 
 grands philosophes, Paris, 1877. 
 
 8 Histoire de la philosophie, Paris, 1877. 
 
 • Katechismus der Geschichte der Philosophie, Leipsic, 1878 ; 2d ed., 
 1884. [To these may be added : Trendelenburg, Historische Beilrdge zur 
 Philosophie, -ivoh., Berlin, 1816-67; Zeller, Vortrage und Ahhandlungcn, 
 3 series, 1865-84; Ilartenstein, Historisch-philosophische Ahhandlungen, 
 Leipsic, 1870; Sigwart, Kleine Schriflen, 2 vols., 1881 ; 2d ed., 1889; 
 Eucken, Lebensanschnuungen der grossen Denier, Leipsic, 1890; Bau- 
 mann, Geschichte der Philosophie, 1890; "NVindelband, Geschichte der 
 Philosophie, Freiburg', 1892 (Engl, transl. by ,7, IL Tufts, London and 
 New York, 1893) ; Bcrginann, Geschichte der Philosophie, 2 vols., Berlin, 
 1892-9t; Deussen, Allgemeine Geschichte der Philosophic, in six parts, 
 vol. L, part 1, Leipsic, 1891; Willmann, Geschichte des Idealhmus,
 
 16 INTRODUCTION 
 
 3 vols., vol. I., Braunschweig, 1894. For further references, see Ueber- 
 weg-Heinze, vol. I., § 4, Falckenberg, and Windelband. Histories of 
 special philosophical sciences : Prantl (mentioned above) ; Harms, 
 Die Philosophie in ihrer Geschichte, vol. I., PsychoJogie, vol. XL, Logik, 
 Berlin, 1877, 1881 ; Siebeck, Geschichte der Psijchologie, Gotha, 1380- 
 84; ; Sidgwick, History of Ethics, London and New York, 3d ed., 1892 ; 
 Paidsen, System der Ethik, 2 vols., 3d ed., Berlin, 1894 (vol. I., pp. 
 31-191, contains a history of ethics) ; Paul Janet, Histoire de la 
 science politique dans ses rapports avec la morale, 3d ed., Paris ; same 
 author's History of Ethics, mentioned above ; Bosanquet, The History 
 of ^Esthetics, London and New York, 1892 ; Flint, History of the 
 Philosophy of History, New York, 1894. For further references, see 
 Ueberweg-Heinze, vol. I., § 4, pp. 8-15 ; Windelband (transL), pp. 20, 
 21 : and Falckenberg, pp. 15-17, 628-629. The following are the 
 most important philosophical journals : The Philosophical Review, vol. 
 4, 1895; Mind, New Series, vol.4; The Monist, vol. 5; The Ainer- 
 icon Journal of Psychology, vol. 6 ; The Psychological Review, vol. 
 2 ; International Journal of Ethics, vol. 5 ; Zeitschrift fur Philosophie 
 und philosophische Kritik, New Series, vol. 106 ; Vierteljahresschrift 
 fiir wissenschaftliche Philosophie, vol. 18 ; Philosophisches Jahrhuch, 
 vol. 8 ; Zeitschrift fur Philosopjhie und Pedagogik, vol. 2 ; Jahrhuch 
 fur Philosophie und spekidative Theologie, vol. 9 ; Zeitschrift fiir exacte 
 Philosophie, vol. 21 ; Archiv fir Geschichte der Philosophie, vol. 8 ; Archiv 
 fur systematische Philosophie (Npw Series of the Philosophische Monats- 
 hefte), vol. 1; Philosophischt: Studien, vol. 11; Zeitschrift fir Psy- 
 chologic und Physiologic der Sinnesorgane, vol. 8 ; Zeitschrift fiir Volker- 
 psychologie und Sprachwissenschaft, vol. 25 ; Revue philosnphique, vol 20 ; 
 Revue de metaphysiqne et de morcde, vol. 3 ; L'annee philosophique, vol. 5, 
 1894 ; Vannee psychologique, vol. 1 ; Rivista Italiana di Filosofia, vol. 9. 
 The following American and English philosophical series are of value 
 to the student of philosophy: Griggs's Philosophical C/asszcs -(German 
 philosophers), G. S. Morris, editor, Chicago; Philosophical Classics for 
 English Readers, W. Knight, editor, Philadelphia and Edinburgh ; 
 Series of Modern Philosophers, E. H. Sneath, editor, New York; Ethical 
 Series, E. H. Sneath, editor, Boston ; The Library of Philosophy, J. H. 
 Muirhead, editor, London and New York ; The English and Foreign 
 Philosophical Library, London ; Ethical Library, J. H. Muirhead, editor, 
 London and New York ; Bohn Library, London. The most extensive 
 Grerman collection of philosophical works is the Philosophische Bibli- 
 othek, J. H. von Kirchmann, editor, Heidelberg. Felix Alcan, Paris, 
 publishes the Bibliotheque de Philosophie. — Tit.]
 
 I 
 
 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 FIRST PERIOD 
 
 iLGE OF IklETAPHYSICS PROPER OR PHILOSOPHY 
 OF NATURE 
 
 (600-400) 
 
 § 4. Origin of Greek Philosophy ^ 
 
 lyLE ptiilosophy of the Hellenes emancipates itself from 
 their religion in the form of theology and gnomic mo- 
 rality.2 Aryan naturalism, modified by the national genius 
 
 ^ [Cf. chapters on mythology, etc., in Grote's History of Greece 
 (cited page 8) ; Preller's Mythologie (cited page 9) ; Lehrs, Populdre 
 Aufsatze (cited page 9) ; and histories of Greek philosophy. — Tr.] 
 
 2 That is to say, philosophy is of comparatively recent origin, while 
 religion, which precedes it historically, is as old as nations and hu- 
 manity itself. Philosophy, being a late product of human develoj> 
 ment, plays but a subordinate and intermittent part in history. 
 Religion, on the other hand, guides its destinies. It is the primordial 
 and permanent expression of what lies at tlie very root of our nature, 
 that is, the will, and consists essentially in the rvill to be, until the evolu- 
 tion of consciousness enables it to foresee its highest and absolute 
 end, the good. To will-to-live means to resist annihilation, conse- 
 quently, to dread everything that is supposed to have the power of 
 destroying and of preserving life. Now, the horror of death and of 
 the forces which produce it, the passionate desire for life and what- 
 fver is able to preserve it, is precisely what constitutes the essence of 
 (iiaififia, the characteristic trait of the religious phenomenon. This 
 is 80 true that we find the ])elief \\\ immortality and the worship of 
 tlie dead ax beings that continue to live in spite of all, intimately con- 
 nected with all religions. Such a belief simply represents the desire 
 of tlio will-to-live to continue even after death and beyond the grave. 
 
 3 
 
 609-^
 
 18 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 and the physical conditions under which it developed, 
 forms its starting-point. This naturalism had passed the 
 period of infancy long before the appearance of philoso- 
 phy. The luminous Ether (Diaus-Zeus), the Sun and 
 its fire (Apollo), the Storm-cloud and its thunderbolts 
 (Pallas- Athene), were originally taken for the gods them- 
 selves. Just as the child transforms its surroundings 
 into an enchanted world, and regards its doll and wooden 
 horse as living beings, so the humanity-child makes na- 
 ture after its own image. For the contemporaries of 
 Homer and Hesiod, such objects are merely the sensible 
 manifestations of the invisible divinity concealed behind 
 them, a being that is similar to the human soul, but superior 
 to it in power, and, like it, invested with immortality. The 
 gods form a kind of idealized, transcendent humanity, 
 whose vices as well as virtues are magnified. The world 
 is their work, their empire, the theatre of their wishes. 
 
 The Old Testament, which might be cited against us, and which is cer- 
 tainly far from being explicit on the subject of individual immortality, 
 is so much the more outspoken on the question of the immortality of 
 Israel. Nay, the immortality of Israel is its fundamental dogma. It 
 has been well said, men would have no religion at all if there were no 
 death ; and the essence of the religious phenomenon was excellently 
 characterized by the preacher who once remarked : " I never have such 
 well-disposed hearers as on Good Friday, and what makes them so 
 religious is the memento mori." Hence we may define religion as fol- 
 lows : Subjectively, it is the fear with which the givers of life and 
 death, be they real or imaginary, inspire us ; objectively, it is the sum 
 of ideas, doctrines, and institutions resulting from this feeling. 
 Religious theory, or theology, and religious practice, or worship, the orig- 
 inal form of morality, are constitutive, but derived and secondary 
 elements, the products of an essentially emotional, instinctive, and 
 {esthetical phenomenon called religion. By reflecting upon itself 
 religion becomes theology ; theology, in its turn, reflects upon itself, 
 and becomes religious criticism, philosophy (Xenophanes). [Concern- 
 ing the origin and evolution of religion, see Paulsen's Introduction to 
 Philosophy, pp. 266 ff.]
 
 ORIGIN OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY 19 
 
 defeats, and triumphs. Man, whom they envy rather than 
 love, exists for their pleasure. They are the highest 
 personifications of the will-to-live, and are jealous of their 
 unquestioned superiority, hence they deny him perfect 
 happiness. The most assiduous worship, the richest sacri- 
 fices, the most perfect fidelity, cannot move them when our 
 prosperity displeases them. Hence the melancholy which 
 breathes in the gnomic poetry of a Solon or a Theognis, 
 who prefer death to life, and esteem them happy who have 
 never been born or who die young.^ 
 
 In the measure in which the moral conscience is devel- 
 oped and re lined, religious ideas are transformed and spirit- 
 ualized. The gods of Homer, who reflect the exuberant, 
 versatile, and quarrelsome youth of the Hellenic nation, are 
 succeeded by tlie just and wise gods, the creations of its 
 riper manhood (Pindar, ^Eschylus, Sophocles). This qual- 
 itative transformation of the religious ideas is accompanied 
 by a quantitative transformation. Polytheism aims at 
 greater simplicity. The good, which the will perceives as 
 its highest end, is synonymous with harmony, and harmony 
 means unity in diversity. Religious and moral progress is, 
 in consequence, a progress in the unitary and monotheistic 
 direction. 
 
 The moral consciousness, which among the Greeks is 
 identical witli the sense of the beautiful, finds a powerful 
 ally in reason and its natural tendency to unity. Guided 
 by the monistic instinct, theology asks itself tlie question, 
 Who is the oldest of tlie gods, and in what order do they 
 spring from their common Father ? and receives an answer 
 in the theogonies of Hesiod, Pherecydes of Syros,^ and 
 Orpheus.^ Here, for the first time, the philosophical spirit 
 
 ' Cf. ZclliT, vol. I., Introduction. 
 
 ^ F^herecydis frafjmpnta coll. et illustr. Fr. G. Sturz, 2il ed., Leipsic, 
 1834. 
 
 ' See concerning Orjilu'us llif scholarly work of Lobcck, Aglaopha' 
 mux sive de theologice mysticat Grcccorum causis, 2 vols., 1829.
 
 20 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 finds satisfaction; tliese fantastic conceptions are anticipa- 
 tions of the rational explanation of nature. 
 
 To conscience and reason a third factor, experience, is 
 added. Tliis, too, assists in the transformation of religious 
 ideas by demonstrating, with increasing evidence, the im- 
 possibility of explaining all phenomena, without exception, 
 by capricious wills. The facts of mathematics, because 
 of their universality and necessity, especially defy theo- 
 logical interpretation ; how indeed can we assume the fact 
 that twice two is four or that the three angles of a triangle 
 are equal to two right angles, to be the result of caprice 
 and not of absolute necessity ? In the same way the obser- 
 vation of astronomical and physical facts, and their constant 
 regularity and periodicity, gives rise to the idea of a Will 
 that is superior to the whims of the gods {ava<^Kif]^ aSpdareia, 
 fiolpa^ rvxv)-> of ^^ immutable Justice (Sikj], elixap/xevr]), of 
 a divine Law (delo^ v6/Mo<i), of a supreme Intelligence {d€io<; 
 X0709, 6eio<; vov^). The pioneers of philosophy, men like 
 Thales, Xenophanes, and Pythagoras, who were the first 
 to protest against theological antliropomorphism, were like- 
 wise mathematicians, naturalists, and astronomers, if we 
 may so designate men who had an elementary knowledge 
 of the course of the stars, the properties of numbers, and 
 the nature of bodies. 
 
 Philosophy dates her origin from the day when these 
 physicians, as Aristotle terms them in distinction from 
 their predecessors, the theologians, relegated the traditional 
 gods to the domain of fable, and explained nature by prin- 
 ciples and causes (apxal koX ahia). Emerging as she did 
 from the conflict between reason and religious authority, 
 which sought revenge by systematically accusing her of 
 atheism and treason, philosophy did not at once cast off 
 the mythological garb. She loved to express herself in the 
 rhythmical language of the poets; and even- her concep- 
 tions retained the marks of the religious faith from which
 
 THE SCHOOL OF MILETUS 21 
 
 she sprang. The gods are not abolished ; they are restored 
 to their true nature, and regarded as elements (aTocxda). 
 Following the example of theology, pliilosophy begins to 
 ask herself the question, What is the primitive element, 
 the one that precedes the others in dignity and in time, 
 and from which, consequently, the others have been gen- 
 erated ? The theogonies become cosmogonies, and the only 
 important question concerning which the first thinkers 
 differ is the question as to what constitutes the primor- 
 dial natural force, the principle (apxi])- 
 
 § 5. The School of Miletus. Thales, Anaximander, 
 Auaximenes ^ 
 
 1. Thales,^ the head of what may be called the school 
 of Miletus, and the father of all the Ionian schools, lived 
 about 600 B. c. According to him, water is the first prin- 
 ciple, the universal substratum, of which the other bodies 
 are merely modifications ; water envelops the earth on all 
 sides ; the earth floats upon this infinite ocean, and con- 
 stantly derives from it the nourishment it needs. 
 
 This doctrine is the old Aryan myth of the heavenly 
 Okeanos translated into scientific language : the water of 
 the storm-cloud fructifies the earth and is the father of 
 all living things.^ It is all we know positively of the 
 philosophy of Thales. He is, moreover, represented to us 
 by antiquity as the first geometrician, the first astronomer, 
 and the first physicist among the Greeks. He is said to 
 
 1 [For the pre-Socratics, see the collections of Fragments, Teich- 
 miiller's Studien and Neue Studien, Byk, Burnet, etc., cited above. 
 Translations of the Fragments found in Burnet. See also Ritter, 
 Geschichle der ionischen Philosophir, Berlin, 1821. — Krische, For- 
 tchuitfjen auf dem Gehiet der alien I'hilo^op/iie, (icittiiigen, 1840. — Tu.] 
 
 3 Chief source, Mel., I., 3; [Hitter and Treller, 7th ed., pp. 6-11. — 
 Tb.]. 
 
 » Plato, Cratylus, 402 B.
 
 22 GREEK PHn.OSOPHY 
 
 have predicted the eclipse of the 28th of May, 585, and to 
 have been acquainted with the phenomenon of magnetism, 
 as well "as with the attractive property of polished amber 
 {rjXeKTpov). 
 
 2. According to Anaxiimander,! ^ fellow-countryman 
 and disciple of Thales, the author of a work O71 Nature, the 
 first principle is not water, but the infinite atmosphere (to 
 aTveipov), from which it comes in order to fructify the earth. 
 This infinite, indistinct matter is the mother of the heavens 
 and the worlds which they encompass (joiv ovpavwv koI tojv 
 iv avrol<i Koa/jicov). Everything that exists owes its being 
 to the first principle, and arises from it by separation ; it is 
 therefore just that everything render to it, at the hour 
 appointed by Fate, the life which Fate has given it, in order 
 that this life may circulate and pass to new beings. The 
 opposites, warm and cold, dry and moist, which do not 
 exist in the aireipov, the primitive chaos where everything 
 is neutralized, are gradually parted off, and form nature, 
 with its contraries, its opposite qualities, and separate ele- 
 ments. The first opposition is that between the warm and 
 dry, on the one hand, and the cold and moist, on the other ; 
 the former occurring in the earth, the latter in the heavens 
 which surround it. The earth is a cylindrical body, and 
 floats freely in the infinite ether, being held in equilibrium 
 because of its equal distance from all the other heavenly 
 bodies (§ia t?)^ o/xoiap TrdvTwv aTroaraaiv). There are an 
 infinite number of worlds (Oeot), which are alternately 
 termed and destroyed. The fu-st animals were produced 
 
 1 Sources: Aristotle, Met., XII., 2; Phjs., III., 4; Simplicius, In 
 Phys., f. 6, 32 ; Plutarch, in Eusebius, Prcep. evang., I., 8; Hippolytus, 
 Refut. hceres., I., 6; Cicero, De nat. deor., I., 10; Schleiermacher, Ueber 
 Anaximandros, Complete Works, 3d series, vol. II., pp. 171-296; Ritter 
 and Preller, pp. 12-19; [Mullach, Fragmenta, I., p. 240; Burnet, pp. 
 47 ff. — Tr] ; C. Mallet, Histoire de la philosophie ionienne, Paris, 1842 ; 
 [Teichmuller, Studien and Neue Studien. — Tr.].
 
 THE SCHOOL OF MILETUS 23 
 
 in the water, and from tliem the more advanced species 
 gradually arose. Man sprang from the fish. Individuals 
 and species constantly change, but the substance whence 
 they are derived, the uTreipov, is indestructible {d(f)dapTov, 
 addvarov, dvQ}\e6pov), because it is uncreated {dyevvi]Tov). 
 It envelops everything, produces everything, governs ev- 
 eiything (Trepie'vet diravra Kal irdvra Kv^epva), It is the 
 supreme divinity {jo delov), possessing a perpetual vitality 
 of its own. 
 
 3. Anaxe^ienes 1 of Miletus, the disciple of Anaximan- 
 der and third representative of the Ionian philosophy, calls 
 the generative principle of things air or breath {d^p, nrvevp.a, 
 -^vx^])' His pliilosophy, which is a more exact formulation 
 of Anaximander's doctrine, may be summarized in the fol- 
 lowing words : infinite matter, a perpetual motion of con- 
 densation and rarefaction that is something like a plastic 
 principle, necessity directing the motion (St'/c?;, avdy/crj). 
 Matter, motion, motive force, directing necessity : we find 
 among the lonians all the elements of the explanations 
 of nature attempted afterwards. But their systems are 
 like rudimentary organisms. The perfection of a living 
 being depends upon the greater or less differentiation of its 
 organs; the more its constitutive parts differ from each 
 other and become specialized, the higher it rises in the 
 scale of beings. Now, the Ionian philosophy is, when com- 
 pared with that of Aristotle, perfectly uniform. Thales 
 regards water, Anaximenes air, as substratum, motive force, 
 and fate, or the law of motion.2 Progress in science, as 
 well as in nature, is made possible by the division of labor, 
 by differentiation of the constitutive elements of being, by 
 the multiplication and opposition of systems. 
 
 1 Plutarch, in Eusebius, Prnsp. evaruj., I., 8; Cicero, De nat. dear., 
 I., 10 ; Schleicrmacher, Ucber Dioijenes von Apollnnia {he. cit.) ; Ritler 
 and Preller, pp. 20-23 ; [Burnet, pp. 79 II. — Tk.]. 
 
 a Aristotle, Met., T., 10, 2.
 
 24 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 § 6. The Problem of Becoming 
 
 1. The first question that arouses controversy is the 
 problem of becoming. Being persists, beings constantly 
 change ; they are born and they pass away. How can being 
 both persist and not persist ? Reflection upon this problem, 
 the metaphysical problem par excellence^ since it lies at the 
 root of all the sciences and dominates all questions, gives 
 rise to three systems, the types of all European philoso- 
 phies, — the Eleatic system ; the system of Heraclitus ; the 
 atomistic system, wliich was proclaimed in the idealistic 
 sense by the Pythagoreans, in the materialistic sense by 
 Leucippus and Democritus, and with a dualistic turn by 
 Anaxagoras. The first two are radical; each suppresses 
 one of the terms of the antinomy ; the third is a doctrine 
 of conciliation. According to the Eleatic hypothesis, being 
 is everything, change is but phenomenal ; according to 
 Heraclitus, change is everything, and being, or permanence, 
 is but an illusion ; according to the monadists and atomists, 
 both permanence and change exist : permanence in the he- 
 ings,^ perpetual change in their relations. The Eleatics 
 deny becoming ; Heraclitus makes a god of it ; the atomists 
 explain it. 
 
 A. Negation of BECO]\nNG 
 
 § 7. Eleatic Philosophy. Xenophanes, Parmenides, 
 Melissus, Zeno, Gorgias ^ 
 
 At the time when Anaximander flourished in Miletus, 
 another Ionian, Xenophanes of Colophon, immigrated into 
 
 1 Considered by the Pythagoreans as ideal unities or numbers ; by 
 the atomists as real or material unities. 
 
 * [Karsten, Philosophorum grcecorum veterum operum reliquice, 2 vols., 
 Amsterdam, 1835 f£. ; Bergk, Commentatio de Arist. lihello de Xeno 
 phane, etc., Marburg, 1843. — Tr.]
 
 ELEATIC PHILOSOPHY 25 
 
 Magna Grsecia, travelled through the cities as a philosopher 
 and rhapsodist, and finally settled in Elea in Lucania, 
 where he gained adlierents. His theological innovations 
 were developed and systematized by Parmenides of Elea 
 and Melissns of Samos, who raised them to the dignity of 
 a metaphysic. Zeno of Elea, the disciple of Parmenides, 
 undertook to defend them by means of dialectics, tliereby 
 becoming the precursor of the Sophists. 
 
 1. Xexophanes 1 is a decided opponent of the national 
 mythology, towards which he assumes a similar attitude 
 to that of the Hebrew prophets who raised their powerful 
 voices against polytheism and its empty conceptions. His 
 written and spoken words proclaim him as the real creator 
 of philosophical monotheism, which he identifies with pan- 
 theism. With an eloquence that is full of irony, his satires, 
 some frao-ments of which are extant, combat the error of 
 those who infinitely multiply the divine Being, who attrib- 
 ute to liim a human form (anthropomorphism) and human 
 passions (anthropopathism). There is one God, he says, 
 one only God, comparable to the gods of Homer or to mor- 
 tals neither in form nor in thought. This God is all eye, 
 all ear, all thought. Being immutable and immovable, he 
 lias no need of going about, now hither, now thither, in 
 order to carry out his wishes, but without toil he governs 
 
 1 Aristotle (?), De Xenophane, Zenone, el Gorgia ; Clement of Alex., 
 2Tpa>fiaTa, V., p. GOl C ; ibid., p. 711 15 ; Bulile, Commentatio de oriu et 
 profjressu panlheisjni inde a Xenophane, etc., Golt., 1790; V. Cousin, 
 Xenophane, fondateur de Vecole d'Ele'e (in the Nouveaux frarpnents phi- 
 losophiquex), Paris, 182S; Kern, Qurestiones Xenophanece, Naumburg, 
 1846; MuUach, Frarjmenta, I., pp. 101 ff. ; Ritter and Preller, pp. 75- 
 84; [Burnet, pp. 115 if.]; J. Freiidenthal, Ueber die Theologie des 
 Xenophanrx, P>roslau, 1880. Freudouthal bases his view partly on 
 the words iv roU 0(ol(n (Mullacli, p. 101), and makes Xenophanos 
 a polytlieist. This is a strange misconception of the spirit for the 
 letter, and would be like reckoning Spinoza among the theists, becausa 
 he call.s nature God, and God a thinking thing.
 
 26 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 all things by his thought alone. Mortals, of course, accept 
 the authority of Homer and Hesiod, and think that the gods 
 are born as they are, and like them have feeling, voice, 
 and body ; and they ascribe to the gods all things that are 
 a shame and disgrace among men, — theft, adultery, and 
 falsehood. They do as the oxen or lions would do if they 
 could paint: they would certainly represent their gods 
 in the form of lions or oxen. In place of these imaginary 
 beings, let us adore the one infinite Being, who bears us in 
 his bosom, and in whom there is neither generation nor 
 corruption, neither change nor origin.^ 
 
 2. Parmenides 2 completes the teachings of his master, 
 and makes them the starting-point for a strictly monistic 
 
 1 MuUach, pp. 101-102 : 
 
 Eis 6fos €V T€ 6(01(71 KM dvOpanoicn fxeyidTOS, 
 0VT€ 8e'/xas 6vr]Toi(HV ofioi'ios ovre v6r]fia. 
 
 OvXos opa, ouXos Se wet, ovXos 8f t uKOvei. 
 
 *AXX* aTrdvevde novoio vSov (j)p(v\ navra Kpabaivet. 
 
 Atfi S' fV TCIVTM T( p.€V(LV KLVOVflfVOV Ov8fV, 
 
 ovbe fierepxfo'dal p.iv ennrpeTTfi aWore aWr/. 
 
 ciXXa fipoTo\ boKiovai deoiis yevmadat 
 T^v iT(f>fTepr]v T aiadrjaiv e'x^"' 4'^''^^ '''^ Befiai re. 
 
 ndvTa Bfols dvedrjKav Onrfpos ff HcrioSo? rf 
 ocrtra Trap' dvdpdnroicnv 6vfi8ea Koi "^oyos eariv, 
 Itai TrXeicr' ecfiSey^avro 6fa>v d6fni(TTia tpya, 
 KXfTTTfiu, noL^ev€Lv Tf KOI dWrjXovi anareveiv. 
 
 AXX' etVot ;(etpdy y* (tx°^ /3ofS rje Xfocrff, 
 T] ypd\j/ai ;^fipe(Tcrt Koi i'pya TfXf'iu dnep livhpfi, 
 Xirrroi p.iv 6' Iitttoktu ^oes Se re ^ovaiv o/j-oias 
 
 Kai K€ 6(u>v ideas typacpop 
 
 * Sextus Empiricus, Adv. malh., VII., Ill ; Simplicius, Inphys., f. 7, 
 0, 19, 25, 31, 38 ; Proclus, Comment, in Plat. Timceum, p. 105 ; Clem, 
 of Alex., Strom., V., pp. 552 D, 614 A ; MuUach, Fragm. phil. gr., 
 I., pp. 109 ff.; Ritter and PreUer, pp. 85 ff.; [Burnet, pp. 218 ff.].
 
 ELEATIC PHILOSOPHY 27 
 
 system. Since there is no change in God, and since God 
 is everything, that which we call change (aWoiovadaL) is 
 but an appearance, an illusion (86^a), and there is in 
 reality neither origin nor decay. The eternal being alone 
 exists : tliis thesis forms the subject of a philosophical 
 poem, the fragments of which are the most ancient monu- 
 ment in our possession of metaphysical speculation proper 
 among the Greeks. In the ih-st part, dedicated to Trutli, 
 he demonstrates by means of specious arguments that our 
 notions of change, plurality, and limitation contradict 
 reason. In the second part, which deals with the merely 
 illusory, he attempts to give an explanation of nature from 
 the standpoint of illusion. 
 
 Starting out with the idea of being, he proves that that 
 which is cannot have become what it is, nor can it cease 
 to be, nor become something else ; for if being has begun to 
 exist, it has come either from being or non-being. Now, 
 in the former case, it is its own product, it has created 
 itself, which is equivalent to saying that it has not origi- 
 nated, — that it is eternal. The latter case supposes that 
 something can come from nothing, which is absurd. For 
 the same reasons, that which exists can neither change nor 
 perish, for in death it would pass either into being or into 
 non-being. If being is changed into being, then it does 
 not change ; and to assume that it becomes nothing is as 
 impossible as to make it come from nothing. Consequently 
 being is eternal. It is, moreover, immovable ; for it could 
 move only in space ; now space is or is not ; if space is, it 
 is identical with l)eing, and to say of being that it is moved 
 in space is to say that being is moved in being, which 
 means that it is at rest. If space is nothing, there cannot 
 be any movement either, for movement is possible only in 
 space. Hence, movement cannot be conceived in any way, 
 and is but an appearance. Being is a continuous (a-vvex^) 
 and indivisible whole. There is no void anywhere. There
 
 28 GKEEK PHELOSOPHY 
 
 is no break between being and being ; consequently these 
 are no atoms. Let us suppose, for the sake of argument, 
 that there existed a void, a break between the assumed 
 parts of the universe. If this interval is something real, 
 it is what being is, it continues being, instead of interrupt- 
 ing it ; it unites the bodies instead of dividing them into 
 parts. If the void does not exist, then it can no longer 
 divide them. There is then no interval between being 
 and being, and all beings constitute but one single being. 
 Being (the universe) is absolute and self-sufficient ; it has 
 neither desires nor wants nor feelings of any kind. If it 
 were relative, it could depend only on that which is or on 
 that which is not. If being depends on being, it depends 
 upon itself or is independent ; if it depends on that which 
 does not exist, it is still independent ; which excludes from 
 it all desire, all need, all feeling. When one is everything, 
 one has no desires. Finally, being is one; for a second 
 being or a third being would be but a continuation of it, 
 that is, itself. Hence, to sum up : Being can only be 
 conceived as eternal, immutable, immovable, continuous, 
 indivisible, infuiite, unique. There is for the thinker but 
 one single being, the All-One, in whom all individual dif- 
 ferences are merged. The being that thinks and the being 
 that is thought are the same thing (tcovtov 8' eVrl voelv re 
 Kul ovv€K€v icrrt vojjfxa).^ 
 
 In the second part of his poem, Parmenides deals with 
 opinion (86^a)^ which depends on the senses and is con- 
 cerned with what is merely illusory. The universe, which 
 reason conceives as an indivisible unity, is divided by the 
 senses into two realms or rival elements : night or cold ; 
 and light, fire, or heat. The universe, which to reason is 
 without beginning or end, has its a]3parent origin, its genesis ; 
 and this genesis is the successive victory of the principle of 
 
 1 Simplicius I?i Phys., f. 19 A, 31 B.
 
 ELEATIC PHILOSOPHY 29 
 
 light over the principle of darkness. Night is the mother, 
 the luminous principle is the father, of all forms {etSi]). 
 The world shows the traces of the two elements to which 
 it owes its origin even in its smallest parts. The warm 
 and the cold, the clear and the obscure, are universally 
 combined in constant proportions. The universe is com- 
 posed of a series of concentric spheres, in which the light 
 and warm spheres alternate with the dark and cold spheres. 
 The outermost sphere, which encloses all the rest (to 
 7re/3ie%oy), is solid, cold, and dark ; beneath it lies the fiery 
 sphere of the fixed stars ("OXu^ttTro? eaxaro^). The central 
 sphere is also solid and cold, but it is surrounded by a 
 sphere of light and life. This fiery sphere which encircles 
 the solid core of the earth is the source of movement 
 (that is, of illusion i), the hearth of universal life (eana rov 
 iravTo^), the seat of the Divinity (Aaifxcov), the Queen of 
 the world (/cu/SepyjyT?/?), Justice (Ai'/c?;), Necessity (AvdyKr]), 
 the Mother of Love (A(}>poBiTi]). 
 
 These doctrines, which partially reproduce Ionian and 
 Pythagorean speculations, are not offered as the truth, but 
 as hypotheses intended to orient us in the world of illu- 
 sion. They have not for Parmenides the importance which 
 they have for the louians. Inasmuch as he does not grant 
 the existence of motion, but rejects as illusory that which 
 constitutes the essence of nature, he accepts no other science 
 than metaphysics, no other metaphysics than that of a priori 
 reasoning. On account of the opposition which he creates 
 between the real and the intelligible, he is the chief fore- 
 runner of Platonic idealism, witliout, however, being a spir- 
 itualist in tlie modern sense. Spiritualism distinguishes 
 between corporeal substance and soul-substance; Eleatic 
 metaphysics makes no such distinction. Tlic being which 
 it allinns is neither l)ody nor soul, neither matter nor 
 spirit; it is being, nulliiug but l)cing; and everything else 
 
 1 Cf. tlif! Miija of the Iliiuloos, the luuther of illusions.
 
 30 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 is merely an accident, an appearance, an illusion. Nay, if 
 we interpret the word matter in the subtle, metaphysical 
 sense of suhstance or universal suhstratiwi, we may reckon 
 Parmenides among the materialists, like his modern imi- 
 tator Spinoza. But it would be a mistake to call liim a 
 materialist in the sense in which the term is applied to 
 Democritus and the modern materialists ; for materialism, 
 properly so-called, exists only in opposition to spiritualism, 
 wliich is later than Parmenides. The monism of Par- 
 menides and Heraclitus is like the block of marble which 
 may be formed into a basin or a Jupiter, or like the mother- 
 cell from which, according to circumstances, a Socrates 
 or an Erostratus may come ; it is capable of being differ- 
 entiated and developed into materialistic or spiritualistic 
 monism. 
 
 3. Plato deduces idealism from it, while Melissus of 
 Samos^ (440) interprets it in an altogether materialistic 
 sense. This philosopher, who was also a brave general and 
 a clever politician, opposes the Ionian cosmogonies with 
 the Eleatic doctrine of the eternity of the world. If 
 becoming is impossible, it is henceforth useless and absurd 
 to inquire into the manner in which the universe originated. 
 Being (to 6v) is infinite in time, and — which is contrary 
 to the view of Parmenides, who conceived it as a sphere — 
 infinite in spfice {coairep icrrl alei^ ovrco koI to fx.€jado<; anreipov 
 aid xpv €lvaL). This latter trait, which leaves no doubt as 
 to the materialism of Melissus, gives his system a wholly 
 modern stamp, and distinguishes it from most of the an- 
 cient systems, particularly from that of Aristotle. For the 
 Greek, who judges of things artistically, regards the infi- 
 nite as the imperfect, as without limitation ; and the uni- 
 verse, which is the acme of perfection, is surely the perfect 
 
 1 The author of a book, iripi tov ovtos (in the Ionian dialect), quoted 
 in different passages by Simplicins, Ln Pkys., f . 22, and paxsim ; [Ritter 
 and Preller pp. 106-111 ; MuUach, I., pp. 261 ff. ; Burnet, 338 ff. — Tr.].
 
 ELEATIC PHILOSOPHY 31 
 
 sphere, one half of which is revealed to us by the sense of 
 sight, and of which the earth is the centre. 
 
 4. Zeko,^ a pupil and follower of Parmenides, is the 
 controversialist of the school, the inventor of the process 
 of demonstration called reductio ad ahsu?rhim, the father of 
 dialectics and sophistry. The One alone is conceivable; 
 extension, magnitude, motion, and space, cannot be con- 
 ceived. If there is such a thing as a (limited) magnitude, 
 it must be infinitely great and infinitely small : infinitely 
 great, because, being infinitely divisible, it is composed of 
 an infinite number of parts ; infinitely small, because unex- 
 tended parts, even though multiplied by infinity, cannot 
 produce extension or magnitude. 
 
 Movement cannot be conceived ; for the line which sep- 
 arates its starting-point from its point of rest is composed 
 of points, and, since the point has no extension, of an infi- 
 nite number of points. Hence every distance, even the 
 smallest, is infinite, and the stopping-point can never be 
 reached. However near you may imagine the swift 
 Achilles to be to the slow tortoise, he will never be able 
 to overtake it, since, in order to do so, he would first have 
 to pass over one half of tlie distance', however small, which 
 separates him from the tortoise, and, in order to pass over 
 this half, he would first have to pass over the half of the 
 half, and so on to infinity. The infinite divisibility of the 
 line is for liim an insurmountable oljstacle. You have an 
 idea that the arrow flies through space. But in order to 
 reach its destination, it must pass over a series of points in 
 space ; lience it must successively occupy these diiferent 
 points. Now, to occupy a point of space, at a given mo- 
 ment, means to be at rest : therefore tlie arrow is at rest 
 and its movement is but illusory. 
 
 » Aristotle, Pk;/s., VI., 2, 9 ; Siinplicius, In IVn/s., f. 30, 1.30, 255; 
 MuUach, I., pp. 266 IT.; Ritter and Preller, pp. 100 £f.; [Burnet, pp. 
 828 ff.].
 
 32 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Fiu-thermore, if movement takes place, it can take place 
 only in space. Now, if space is a reality, it exists some- 
 where, that is, in a space, which in turn exists in another 
 space, and so on ek direipov. Motion is, therefore, impos- 
 sible from every point of view, and we cannot suppose it 
 to be real, unless we are willing to affirm an absurdity. 
 Being alone exists, and this being is immutable matter.^ 
 
 5. GoRGiAS 2 of Leontinum, the rhetorician, a pupil of 
 Zeno, who was sent by his country as an ambassador to 
 Athens in 427, deduces the ultimate consequences from the 
 Eleatic principle and ends in nihilism. He is not, like 
 Zeno, content with denying motion and space ; as his 
 treatise, irepl rou fir] 6vT0<i rj irepl (f)vae(i)'?, shoAVS, he negates 
 being itself. Nothing exists, he says ; for if a being existed, 
 it would have to be eternal, as was proved by Parmenides. 
 Now, an eternal being is infinite. But an infinite being 
 cannot exist in space or in time without being limited by 
 them. Hence it is nowhere, and that which is nowhere 
 does not exist. And even if, assuming the impossible, 
 something did exist, we could not know it ; and even if we 
 could, this knowledge could not in any wise be communi- 
 cated to others. 
 
 Gorgias is the enfant terrible of the Eleatic school, whose 
 extravagances turn the tide in favor of the Heraclitean 
 principle : Being is nothing, hecoming is everything. The 
 heing of Parmenides and Zeno, wdiich is eternal and im- 
 mutable, but devoid of all positive attributes, is, in fact, a 
 mere abstraction. It resembles the garment of the king, 
 the fine texture of which everybody pretended to admire, 
 until, at last, a little child exclaimed, in the simplicity of 
 its heart : " Why, the king is naked ! " 
 
 » Aristotle, Met, III., 4, 41. 
 
 " Aristotle, De Xenophane, Zenone, et Gorgla ; Sextus Empir., Adv. 
 math., VII., 65, 77 ; Ritter and Preller, 187 ff.
 
 HERACLITUS 33 
 
 B. Apotheosis of Beco^shxg 
 § 8. Heraclitus 
 
 Heraclitus,^ who, on account of his love of paradox, was 
 called the Obscure, flourished at Ephesus, near the end of 
 the sixth centuiy. He has left a deeper impress on Greek 
 thought than any of the physicists of the fii"st period, and 
 more than one modern hypothesis is either foreshadowed 
 or expressly formulated in the valuable fragments of his 
 book On Nature (^irepl <^vae(o<;). 
 
 Like the physicists of Miletus, Heraclitus considers all 
 bodies as transformations of one and the same element. 
 But this element is not, as with Anaximenes, the atmos- 
 pheric air; it is a liner, more subtle substance, which he 
 sometimes calls foe (ttO/o), sometimes warm breath (■v/^i'X?;), 
 and which resembles either what physics formerly called 
 caloric^ or the oxygen of modern chemistry. This original 
 matter extends from the boundaries of the earth to tlie 
 limits of the world. Everything that exists is derived 
 from it, and strives to return to it ; every being is trans- 
 formed fire ; and, conversely, every being may be, and, as 
 a matter of fact, is, eventually changed into fire.^ Atmos- 
 
 » Chief sources: Plato, Crahjlns, p. 402 A; Pint. Is. el Osh:, 45, 
 48; Clem, of Alex., Strom., V. pp. 599,003; Diog, L., IX.; Sext. 
 Emp., Ado. virith., VII., 126, 127, 133; Stolwus; Sclileiermacher, 
 Herakleitoa der Dunkle von Epheaos, {Complete Works, Part IH., vol. 2, 
 Berlin, 1838) ; Jac. Bernays, Heraclilea, Bonn, 1848 ; Die HeraklitixcJien 
 Br'ipfe, Berlin, 1809; [Las.salle, Die Philonophie Herakleitos dex Dunkeln 
 von Ephesox, 2 vols., Berlin, 1858; Teiclimiiller, Studien and Neue Stu- 
 dien, quoted above; E. Pfleidorcr, Die Philosophie dcs Heraklit von 
 Ephexux, Berlin, 1880; G. T. W. Patrick, Hentelitttx on Nature, Balti- 
 more, 1889. — Ti:.]; Mullacli, I., pp. 310 ff. ; Ilerarliti Ephesii reliquio', 
 collected by Bywater, Oxford, 1877; Bitter and Preller, 24 ff. ; [Bur- 
 net, pp. 13.3 ff.]. 
 
 ' The phy.sicH of Ileraclitu.s reminds one of the mechanical theory 
 of heat taut,dit by modern physics, ■which, like the sage of Ephesus, 
 oonBiderfl all organic life as a transformation of solar heat.
 
 34 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 plieric air and water are fire in process of extinction or in 
 process of renewal ; earth and solids are extinguislied fire, 
 and will be rekindled afresh at the hour fixed by Fate. Ac- 
 cording to an immutable law, the fire of the heavenly regions 
 is successively transformed into vapor, water, and earth, only 
 to return again, in the opposite direction, to its principle ; 
 then it thickens again, re-ascends into the heavens, and so 
 on ad infinitum. The universe is, therefore, fire in the 
 process of transformation (vri/po? Tpoirai), an ever-living 
 fire, which is periodically kindled and extinguished. It is 
 neither the work of a god nor of a man. It has had no be- 
 ginning, and it will never end. There is an end of the 
 world in the sense that all things ultimately return to fire ; 
 but the world eternally re-arises from its ashes. Universal 
 life is an endless alternation of creation and destruction, — 
 a game which Jupiter plays with himself. Rest, stand-still, 
 in a word, being, is an illusion of the senses. It is not 
 possible to descend twice into the same stream ; i nay, it is 
 not even possible to descend into it once ; we are and we 
 are not in it ; we make up our minds to plunge into the 
 waves, and, behold ! they are already far away from us. In 
 the eternal whirl, the nothing constantly changes into be- 
 ing, and being is incessantly swallowed up in nothingness. 
 Since non-being produces being, and vice versa ; being and 
 non-being, life and death, origin and decay, are the same. 
 If they were not, they could not be transformed into each 
 other. 
 
 The perpetual fiow of things is not, as the expression 
 might lead one to think, an easy process, like the gliding 
 of a brook over a bed of polished stones. Becoming is a 
 struggle between contrary forces, between opposing cur- 
 rents, one of which comes from above and strives to trans- 
 form the celestial fii'e into solid matter ; while the other 
 
 1 Plato, Cratylus, p. 402 A : iravra X<«>pfi f«' ovhkv fxevei k. t. X.
 
 HERACLITUS 35 
 
 re-ascends into the heavens, and strives to change earth 
 into fire. It is this continuous battle between two con- 
 trar}" currents that produces all vegetable, animal, and 
 intellectual life on the sui'face of the earth. Everything 
 arises from the strife of opposites.^ Organic life is pro- 
 duced by the male and the female ; musical harmony, by 
 sharp and flat notes ; it is sickness that makes us appre- 
 ciate health ; ^dthout exertion, there can be no sweet 
 repose ; without danger, no courage ; without evil to over- 
 come, no \drtue. Just as fire lives the death of air, air, 
 the death of fu-e, water, the death of air, earth, the death 
 of water; so, too, the animal lives the death of the vege- 
 table, man, the death of the animal, the gods, the death 
 of man, virtue, the death of vice, and vice, the death of 
 virtue. Hence, good is a destroyed evil, evil, a vanished 
 good ; and since evil does not exist without the good, nor 
 the good without the evil, evil is a relative good, and good 
 i relative evil. Like being and non-being, good and evil 
 disappear in the universal harmon3^ 
 
 The emphasis which Heraclitus la3S on the perpetual 
 flux and the absolute instability of things, on the vanity of 
 all in<lividual existence, the impossilnlity of good without 
 evil, of pleasure without pain, of life witliout death, makes 
 liim the typical pessimist of antiquity, as opposed to the 
 optimist, Democritus.2 His negation of being likewise 
 implies scepticism.^ Inasmuch as truth is the same to-day, 
 to-morrow, and forever, there can be no certain and final 
 knowledge if everything perceived by the senses constantly 
 changes. Tlie senses, however, are not our only means of 
 
 1 Ililipolytiis, Ref. hfcr. IX., 9: rroXf/xor (Darwin would translate it 
 struf/f/le for life) -ni'ivrtjiv nuTrp tan kiu jUacriXfVi. 
 
 2 See § 12. 
 
 « The school of lleraclilu.s, and particularly Cratylua, the best 
 known of hia diaciples and one of the teachers of Plato, taught 
 scepticism.
 
 36 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 knowledge; in addition to them we have reason (voG?, 
 \6yo<i). The senses show us what passes away, and knowl- 
 edge that is based on sensation alone is deceptive • reason 
 reveals to us what is staljle : the divine law (6^eto? v6fxo<;), 
 the only fixed point in the eternal flow of things. But 
 the most enlightened human reason is still as far removed 
 from divine reason as the ape is removed from human per- 
 fection.i gy distinguishing between the sensible phenome- 
 non and the noumenon, as Heraclitus did, Ionian philosophy 
 emerges from the state of innocence, as it were ; it begins 
 to suspect its methods, to distrust itself, to ask itself 
 whether the ontological problem can really be solved at 
 all ; in a word, it foreshadows the critical question. 
 
 Anthropology cuts loose from general speculation and 
 begins to form a prominent part in the system of Hera- 
 clitus. The soul is an emanation of the celestial fire, 
 and can live only by remaining in contact with this source 
 of life. It is constantly renewed by means of respiration 
 and sensation. Generation is the transformation of the 
 liquid seed into dry breath. Hence the latent fire of the 
 earth passes through the liquid state and returns to its 
 original condition in the human soul. The driest breath 
 constitutes the wisest soul, but woe to the drunkard who 
 prematurely causes Ins soul to pass back into the liquid 
 state ! In death the breath of life or the soul gradually 
 returns to earth. An individual's energy will depend upon 
 his more or less constant communion with the celestial fire, 
 the supremely intelligent and wise soul of the world. 
 
 Here we have the first feeble beginnings of physiological 
 psychology, and they are naively materialistic. The phil- 
 osophy of this period speaks of mind as popular chemistry 
 speaks of spirits and essences ; but though materialistic, 
 it is so little aware of the fact that it does not even 
 possess a technical term for matter. We are not con- 
 1 See the Greater Hippias, p. 289 A.
 
 THE PYTHAGOREAN SPECULATION 37 
 
 scious of ourselves except in opposition to what we are 
 not. Hylozoism does not become materialism until it is 
 opposed by the spiritualism of the Pythagoreans.^ 
 
 To sum up : All things proceed from a dry and warm 
 principle and eventually return to it ; everytliing is in a 
 state of perpetual change, and there is nothing immutable 
 in the eternal process but the Law wliich governs it and 
 wliich neither gods nor men can mochfy. 
 
 C. Explanation of Beco^ming 
 8 9. The Pythagorean Speculation 
 
 Do the metaphysical doctrines of Pythagoreanism ^ go 
 back, in part at least, to Pythagoras himself? Are they 
 the teacliings of the members of the Pythagorean order, of 
 men like Philolaus, who was exiled from Italy in the first 
 half of the fifth century, and Archytas, who flourished at 
 Tarentum during the second half of that centuiy ? The 
 mystery in which the order was enshrouded from the 
 very beginning makes it altogether impossible to answer 
 this question. Aristotle himself seems to be in doubt in 
 the matter ; he never speaks of the teachings of Pythagoras, 
 
 ^ Ilippasus of Crotoua (or ^Mptapontuin) fuses Ileracliteaii and 
 Pythagorean conceptions. See Kitter and Preller, p. -14. 
 
 ■■' Stobaeus, Eclog., I.; Plato, Timceua; Aristotle, Met., I., 5 passim, 
 Decalo, II., 13; Diog. L., VIII.; Porjiliyry, Life of Pjjthar/ams; Juni- 
 bliclius, Life of Pijthagoras ; RluUach (P;/tha(/oreinn carmen aureitm, 
 p. 193; Ocelli Lucani de tiniversa nalura libellus, 388; 1 1 ieroclis co?n- 
 menlarius in carmen aurenm, 410; Pi/lhnf/oreorwn aliorumque philosopho- 
 rum frarpnenla, 18;") ff. [vol. II., pp. 9 if.]) ; Hitter and Preller, pp . 10 
 ir. ; [Hitter, (Jesrhic/ile der pi/lhrir/oreischen P/tilosophie, Ilaniburi;', 182(5]; 
 A. Laugel, Pi/l/iof/ore, sa iloclrine et son histoire il'a/ires hi critique alle- 
 mantle ( Revue (les Deur-Momles, 1804); C. Scliaarscliniidt, Die anf/ehliche 
 Schriftstellerei r/es Philolnnx, etc., Bonn, 1864; Chaignet, Ptjtliaqore et la 
 philosophic piflhnfforicienne, Paris, 1873. [See also Grote's History o 
 Greece, vol. II.]
 
 38 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 but only of the Pythagoreans. However that may be, 
 one thing is certain : the first impetus towards arithmetical 
 speculation known under the name of Pythagorean phil- 
 osophy was given by the great mathematician of Samos, 
 and even though direct and positive proofs are wanting, 
 nothing can liinder us from proclaiming him as the origi- 
 nator of the doctrines set forth in this section. 
 
 Pythagoras, like Thales, of Ionian origin, was born at 
 Samos during the first half of the sixth century. He was 
 at first the pupil of the theologian Pherecydes and perhaps 
 also of Anaximander, the physicist. According to a tradi- 
 tion which, it must be confessed, has nothing to warrant it 
 among the ancients, he visited Phoenicia, Egypt, and Baby- 
 lon, where he was initiated into the Eastern theological 
 speculations, and introduced to the study of geometry, 
 which had already attained a liigh degree of perfection on 
 its native soil. Returning to Greece aljout 520, he realized 
 his ideals of religious, social, and philosopliical reform at 
 Crotona in ^lagna Grsecia, l)y founding a kind of brother- 
 hood, the members of which entertained the same opinions 
 concerning morality, politics, and religion.^ 
 
 1 "When we compare the doctrines, aims, and organization of this 
 brotherhood, as portrayed by the Xeo-Platonic historians (especially 
 Jamblichus), with Buddhistic monachisra, we are almost tempted 
 (with Alexander Polyhistor and Clement of Alexandria) to regard 
 Pythagoras as the pupil of the Brahmans, nay, to identify him with 
 Buddha himself. Indeed, not only do the names (J1v6mv, Uvdayopas 
 = an inspired one, a soothsayer, and Buddha = enlightened) bear such 
 close resemblance to each other that even the most fastidious philol- 
 ogist can find no objection in translating Uvdayopeios by " preacher of 
 Buddhism," but the P\i;hagoreau and Buddhistic teachings are very 
 much alike. Dualism, pessimism, metempsychosis, celibacy, a common 
 life according to rigorous rules, frequent self- examinations, medita- 
 tions, devotions, prohibitions against bloody sacrifices and animal 
 nourishment, kindliness towards all men, ti'uthfulness, fidelity, justice, 
 — all these elements are common to both. The fact that most ancient 
 authors and above all Aristotle himself have comparatively little to say
 
 THE PYTHAGOREAN SPECULATION 39 
 
 Nothing certain is known of the end of the philosopher. 
 His work prospered. The Pythagoreans were the posses- 
 sors of all the sciences known in their time, — geometrj^, 
 astronomy, music, and medicine,^ — and consequently ac- 
 quired an overpowering influence among the Doric people, 
 who were less advanced than the lonians. They pre- 
 ponderated at Crotona, at Tarentum, and in the Sicilian 
 republics, until the middle of the fifth century, when the 
 victorious democracy partly expelled them. The exiles 
 repaired to Thebes or to Athens. Here their influence 
 counteracted that of the Sophists, and brought about the 
 spiritualistic reaction of Socrates and Plato against the 
 materialism and scepticism which had, in the same epoch, 
 been imported from Sicily, Tlu-ace, and Ionia. 
 
 Ionian metaphysics springs from physics ; Pythago- 
 rean metaphysics is grafted on mathematics, and is conse- 
 quently totally different from the former at the very outset. 
 What interests the philosophers of Miletus is matter and its 
 
 concerning the person and life of Pythagoras, would tend to confirm 
 the hypothesis of the identity of Pythagoreanisni and Buddhism. 
 However, the existence of Pythagoras, the mathematician, five centu- 
 ries before the Christian era, is placed beyond doultt by the testimony 
 of Heraclitiis, Herodotus, etc. Furthermore, Buddhism in the form 
 of Manicha;ism (that is to say, monachism) did not begin to spread 
 westward before the third century of our era. We may perhaps ex- 
 plain everything satisfactorily by distinguishing between the Pytha- 
 goroanism of the Neo-Platonic historians and primitive and genuine 
 Pythaforeanism. Tlie biographers of Pythagoras were without exact 
 and sufficient data regarding the life and work of the sage of Samos, 
 and somewhat unscrupulous, besides, in the choice of then- sources. 
 They likewise allowed themselves to be misled by certain analogies ; 
 the essential features of their imaginary portrait are derived from 
 Persian dualism and Hindoo pessimism. 
 
 1 These sciences, which constituted tlie subjfct-matter of Pythago- 
 rean instruction, were called fiadnfinra, — the term from wliich tlic word 
 mathematics is derived. The original meaning of the word omliracoo 
 the totality of human knowledge,
 
 40 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 perpetual movement; what impresses Pythagoras and the 
 Pythagoreans is the immaterial in matter, the order which 
 prevails in the world, the unity, proportion, and harmony 
 in its contrasts, the mathematical relations underlying all 
 thino-s. In geometry, in astronomy, and in music, every- 
 thing is ultimately reduced to number. Hence number is 
 the principle and innermost essence of the world; and 
 things are sensible numbers. Every being represents a 
 number, and the final goal of science is to find for each 
 beino- the number for which it stands. The infinite series 
 of numbers, and consequently of things, is derived from 
 unity. As number is the essence of things, unity is the 
 essence of number. Pythagoreanism distinguishes two 
 Ivinds of unities : (1) the Unity from which the series of 
 numbers (Ijeings) is derived, and which therefore contains 
 and comprehends them all; the absolute and unopposed 
 unity, the Monad of monads (?} /xom?), the God of gods ; 
 and (2) the One, the first in the series of derived numbers, 
 which is opposed to the numbers tioo, tJvree, and every plu- 
 rality (yr\i]9o<i^, and consequently limited by the two, the 
 three, and the plurality; it is a relative unity, a created 
 monad (^to eV). The opposition between the 07ie and the 
 majii/ is the source of all the rest. All the contrasts of 
 nature, the dry and the moist, the Avarm and the cold, the 
 clear and the obscure, the male and the female, the good 
 and the evil, the finite {Treirepaa- [xevov) and the infinite 
 (diretpov), are but varieties of the ev and the ttXt/^o?, or 
 of the odd (jrepmov) and the even {apnov). Plurality 
 as such is without consistency and may be divided into 
 unities; the even number is reducible to the odd unit. 
 The absolute unity is neither even nor odd ; or rather, it is 
 as yet both even and odd, singular and plural, God and 
 the world. It is to Pythagoreanism what the aireipov is in 
 the system of Anaximander: the neuter being that is 
 superior and anterior to sexual contrasts, the absolute
 
 THE PYTHAGOREAN SPECULATION 41 
 
 indifference which precedes and creates the dualism of 
 forces and elements. But the Pythagoreans guard against 
 calling it aireipov^ since the aireipov is, according to them, 
 opposed to the irepaivov^ as passivity to activity, or matter 
 to the workman, or form, or plastic principle. Inasmuch as 
 everything is, according to them, reduced to number, nu- 
 merical relations, and ultimately to Idea, the matter and 
 motion of the lonians are, in their opinion, merely negative, 
 the absence of ideal unity. Concerning the question of 
 movement and origin, the conclusions of the Pythagoreans 
 do not differ from the Eleatic doctrines. Movement and 
 origin seem to be incompatible with their idealism. Al- 
 though they have their own cosmogony, like the other 
 schools of the period, they do not assume that the universe 
 had a beginning in time, and consequently that there was 
 a time wlien the universe did not exist. The world has 
 existed e| a/ww? kuI ek aiMva, and the cosmogony simply 
 aims to explain the order, law, or series, according to which 
 things eternally emanate from their principle. 
 
 Pythagorean physics therefore accommodates itself to 
 human sensualism, just like the physics of Parmenides. It 
 makes what is in itself immutable, variable. It places itself 
 on the sensualistic standpoint held by the novices among its 
 followers (aKovaixarLKoi), and represents the eternal unity 
 as a sphere {r) rod 7ravTo<; a(^alpa), as a compact sphere, in 
 which ihe parts are not distinguished (irXrjpe^;, avvex^<i\ 
 and which floats in the infinite (aireipov). The ideal opposi- 
 tion l)etween the even and the odd, the one and tlie many, 
 becomes the real o])position of the full and the void. At 
 the origin of things, the full was without the voi<l, oi', at 
 least, the void was external to it. The foimation of the 
 cosmos Ijegins by the vend l)reaking in upon the full. 
 This process is like a perpetual breath which iinilates the 
 world (tti/o/;, irvevpa). The; void penetrates the a<^alpa 
 and establishes itself in it, thereljy breaking it up into au
 
 42 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 infinite number of infinitesimal particles, reduced images of 
 the (T(f>aLpa (the ciro/xa of the atomists). Since, from the 
 geometrical point of view, quality is reduced to quantity 
 and form, these particles differ only in quantity and in 
 figure. They form either cubes or pyramids (tetrahedrons) 
 or octahedrons or icosahedrons or dodecahedrons. The 
 unity reacts against this endless separation, and the parti- 
 cles are joined together again according to their geometric 
 affinities and form elementary bodies: earth, fire, air,- water, 
 and etlier. Fire is the element par excellence^ being formed 
 of tetrahedric particles. It is the symbol of the divine 
 principle in nature and is concentrated into a central sun, 
 the hearth of the universe and the abode of the Supreme 
 God {karla rov iravTO'i), around which revolve (1) tlie Oura- 
 nos, embracing the coufiter-earth (avrix^av) and the earth ; 
 (2) the Cosmos proper, consisting of the moon, the sun (?) 
 and the planets ; (3) the Olympus with the fixed stars. 
 Pythagoras substitutes for the earth a central fire (which 
 is invisible because the earth keeps facing it with the part 
 that is opposite to the one we inhabit), and makes the earth 
 revolve around this centre. But tliis does not mean, of 
 course, that he advanced the heliocentric theory ; he merely 
 foreshadowed the system which his school formulated 
 during the following centuries without succeeding in hav- 
 ing it accepted by the majority of scientists. The distances 
 separating the spheres are proportional to the numbers 
 which express the relations that exist between tones and 
 the respective lengths of vibrating strings ; and the result 
 of their revolutions around the axis of the world is a divine 
 harmony which the musical genius alone can perceive. 
 This harmony is the soul of the universe. The different 
 beings form an ascending scale according to the degree of 
 perfection with which they reflect the universal harmony. 
 The motion of the elementary being, the physical point, 
 produces the line ; the line moves and produces the plane ;
 
 THE PYTHAGOREAN SPECULATION 43 
 
 the plane produces the body, from which sensation, percep- 
 tion, and intelligence gradually arise (emanation). 
 
 The individual is mortal in so far as he springs from the 
 temporary union of corporeal elements, according to a ratio 
 that varies witliin certain limits. When these limits are 
 passed, proportion becomes disproportion, an unequal strug- 
 gle, disease, decay, and death. But the ideal contents of 
 the broken vase are secure against destruction. The soul 
 is a fixed number in the eternal scale of things, a portion 
 of the world-soul, a spark of the celestial fire, a thought of 
 God. In this respect it is immortal; at death it enters 
 upon a state that is superior or inferior to our present life 
 or like it, according as the soul has lived for God, for the 
 world, or for itself (metempsychosis and palingenesis). 
 
 Although the Pythagoreans, like Parmenides and Hera- 
 clitus, accentuate one of the constitutive elements of reality 
 and eventually negate concrete existence in order to exalt 
 the Idea, they none the less introduce into Greek thought 
 one of the most important factors in the solution of the 
 Eleatic-Heraclitean problem: What is becoming or the 
 process of perpetual change affirmed by the philosopher 
 of Ephesus, and how can it be reconciled with the con- 
 ception of the permanence and immutability of matter, 
 which is advanced, no less authoritatively, by the school of 
 Elea? We mean their theory of monads : the infinitosimal 
 particles or physical points of which matter is made up. 
 The subsequent systems all attempt to reconcile Elea and 
 Ei)hesus by means of the physico-arithmetical theory of 
 elementary units. Thought discovers in the atomistic 
 hypothesis the middle term that unites Parmenides, who 
 denies the great empirical fact of generation and change, 
 and Heraclitus^ who sacrifices being and its permanence to 
 becoming, — tliereby combining the two rival systems into 
 a liigher synthesis, — and lays the foundation for every 
 rational explanation of the process of becoming. Hence-
 
 44 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 forth philosophy no longer regards matter as a continuous 
 mass, the essential properties of which are incessantly 
 transformed. It breaks them up into parts that are in 
 themselves immutable, but which continually change their 
 relative positions. As a consequence, there can be both 
 perpetual change in the aspects of matter (bodies) and per- 
 manence in the essence and properties of matter. All 
 change is reduced to change of j)lace : mechanism. 
 
 Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and Democritus, who hold this 
 theory, differ from each other as Heraclitus, Pythagoras, 
 and Anaximander differ among themselves ; that is to say, 
 the first makes motion, the second, the Idea (i^ou?), the 
 third, matter, the keystone of his system. 
 
 § 10. Empedocles 
 
 Empedocles,! of Agrigentum, in Sicily (450), who in 
 consequence of his knowledge of medicine, the cures which 
 he effected, and the mystery with which he loved to sur- 
 round himself, was regarded as a magician and a god, is the 
 author of a grand philosophical poem, the fragments of 
 which seem to place him in an intermediate position 
 between the Eleatics and the lonians. 
 
 He sides with the Eleatics in his denial of becoming, as 
 Heraclitus understands it ; and approaches the lonians in 
 assuming the reality of motion. Matter is immutable in 
 its essence, but bodies are in a state of constant change ; 
 their constituent elements are combined and separated in 
 different proportions. We cannot conceive how fire as 
 such can become air, air, water, and so on ; Init it is con- 
 
 1 Sext. Emp., Adv. math., VTL, 123; Simplicius, In PJn/s., f. 24, 
 f. 76; Plutarch, De plac. pJnl; Aristotle (Met., Phys., and Psychology), 
 etc.; Fragments of Empedocles, collected by A. Peyron (Leipsic, 1810), 
 S. Karsten (Relii/mce pUl vet. gr., vol. IT., Amst., 1838), Th. fBergk 
 (Leipsic, 1843), II. Stein (Bonn, 1852), Mullach (I., pp. 1 ff.), Rittei 
 and PreUer (pp. 125 ff.) ; [Burnet, pp. 218 ff.].
 
 EMPEDOCLES 45 
 
 ceivable that the thousand different combinations of these 
 elements should produce an infinite variety of bodies. 
 Hence we must abandon the notion of elementary unity ; 
 we must cease deriving air from ether, water from air, 
 earth from water, and consider these four elements as 
 equally original. 
 
 Hsi\e the fo^ir elements {arofxela) movement of their own, 
 or have they received it from a distinct principle, from a 
 Irigher force? It is hard to separate the thought of the 
 philosopher from his poetical phraseology, encumbered as it 
 is by images and contradictions. We may, it seems, con- 
 clude from his poem that he no longer assumes hylozoism, 
 the eternity of motion, and the original vitality of matter in 
 the same sense as the Ionian physicists. He appears to 
 explain movement by an immaterial principle, or rather, by 
 two distinct immaterial principles, one of which unites the 
 elements, while the other separates them: Love {(f)iXia, 
 ^fXoT?;?, aTopyrj) or the principle of union, and Discord 
 (veiKO'i, epL<;, e;^^o?), the principle of separation.^ These two 
 motive causes, which the imagination of the poet interprets 
 as opposing divinities, alternately rule the elements. Love 
 first unites them and forms them into a single spherical 
 body {(r(f)alpo<;). Discord ensues and divides them ; as a 
 result, the earth, the ocean, the atmosphere, the heavenly 
 ether, and the stars arise. This period of })rimitive crea- 
 tion, which is tlie A\'ork of Discord, is followed by an epoch 
 of struggle between Discord and Love, during which 
 plants, animals, and men originate. Discord lias, in sepa- 
 rating the elements, prepared for each class of beings the 
 habitation adapted to them, l)ut it coidd not form tlie organ- 
 isms themselves, which are a mixture of the four elcmoits 
 and consecpiently tlie work of the unifying i)rinciple, the 
 product of Love reacting against tli(; exclusive sway of vVn- 
 
 ^ Nowaflays we should us<j the terms attraction and niitilsion. The 
 cosmogony of KmiMidocles contains the germ of Kant's.
 
 46 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 tipatliy. Although the two principles are now at war with 
 each other, Love will ultimately gain the victory, and the 
 four spheres of the world, which are at present separated, 
 will, on the last day, be combined into a new chaos. This 
 alternation between periods of separation and periods of 
 union is a fatal necessity, and will go on forever. 
 
 Like Anaximander and Heraclitus before him, Empe- 
 docles explains the origin of beings by the process of 
 evolution, but he explains it in his own way. Their 
 organs, he believes, first arose as shapeless and discon- 
 nected rudiments, then disappeared and reappeared, sepa- 
 rated and reunited, until, at last, they were adapted to 
 each other and joined together for good. The first forma- 
 tion of these beings was the result of chance ; but their 
 preservation, proficiency, and development were due to the 
 fitness which they ultimately attained.^ Our philosopher 
 also regards individual existence as a doubtful good. He 
 is, therefore, the precursor of Schopenhauer as well as of 
 Darwin. With Heraclitus and Hippasus, he identifies the 
 soul with the fiery principle. Discord detached it from 
 the a^atpo';, in which it originally existed, mixed with 
 all the other beings. Like the rest, it will eventually 
 return thither. Life is the expiation of the soul's desire 
 for a separate existence. Passing through the stages of 
 plant, animal, and man, it rises by degrees, and, by absti- 
 nences, fasts, and continent living, finally again becomes 
 worthy of returning to God. The propagation of the hu- 
 man species is an evil, since it perj^etuates the actual state 
 of things and retards their return to the original unity .^ 
 
 1 MuUach, pp. 315, 316. 
 
 2 The same views are held by Anaximander, who regards death as 
 an expiation; by Plato, who despises the world of sense, and eagerly 
 desires the return to the realm of pure ideas ; by Plotinus of Lyco- 
 polis, who is ashamed of his body and the manner in which he entered 
 into the world. The religious conceptions of the fall, of original sin 
 and expiation are familiar to Aryan Europe as well as to Asia.
 
 EMPEDOCLES 47 
 
 Man is the image of the a(f)alpo<i. The four radical elements 
 are represented in him : the earthly element, by the solid 
 parts of the body ; water, by its liquid parts ; air, by the 
 vital breath ; fire, by the spirit. He is likewise affected by 
 Love and Hate. His intellectual superioritj^ follows from 
 the fact that all the cosmical elements are concentrated in 
 him. He perceives everything, because he is everything ; 
 he perceives solids because he is earth ; liquids, because he 
 is water ; and so on. We have here a theory, or let us rather 
 say, the beginnings of a theory of sensation that might be 
 called homceojjathic as distinguished from the allopatliism 
 of Anaxagoras. The latter derives sensation from the 
 coming-together of contraries; according to Empedocles, 
 sensation results from the contact of similars. The blood, 
 in which the four elements are most closely mingled, is the 
 seat of sensation and of the soul. This is proved by the 
 fact that when we withdraw all the blood from the body 
 we deprive it of sensation, consciousness, life, — in a word, 
 of soul. The health of a man depends on the composition 
 of his blood. "We are health}" and good wlien our blood is 
 normally composed (/xeo-?; Kpaai^). The blood is sacred, 
 and ought not to serve as noui-ishment. In these doctrines, 
 which remind us of Egypt, Moses, Buddha, and Zoroaster, 
 we see the dawn, as it were, of modern pliysiology. 
 
 In his theology, Empedocles conceals his naturalism 
 under the traditional forms of mythology. He deifies — 
 in name onlj, not actually, like popular belief — the 
 four elements, which he calls Zeus, Hera, Orcus, and 
 Nestis, and the two motive principles. Love and Discord. 
 But we find in Empedocles, alongside of liis tlieological 
 atomism and naturalized polytheism, Eleatic monism and 
 the tendency to reduce elements and j)rinciples to a liiglier 
 unity, which is tlie only true God. Love is the principle 
 of principles ; the four elements are merely its agents, and 
 Discord itself its indispensable accomplice : it is the inef-
 
 48 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 fable, invisible, incorporeal God, flashing through the whole 
 world with rapid thoughts.^ 
 
 The leading thought in the teaching of Empedocles, 
 freed from its theological shell, meets us again in the sys- 
 tem of the Ionian Anaxagoras. Anaxagoras is the founder 
 of corpuscular physics, and, by his hypothesis of the order- 
 ing vov<i, anticipates the teleology of Plato and Aristotle. 
 
 § 11. Anaxagoras 
 
 Anaxagoeas 2 was born at Clazomense in Ionia, of an 
 illustrious family. He seems to have emigrated to Athens 
 about 460, and to have been, for thirty years, the central 
 figure in this new intellectual centre of Greece. His 
 friendship for Pericles, Euripides, and Protagoras, and his 
 profound contempt for the official religion made it neces- 
 sary for him to retire to Lampsacus towaids tlie close of 
 his life. Here he died about 429 B. c. Like the majority 
 of the great physicists of antiquity, he left a book irepl 
 ^vaeoj'iy a few fragments of which are still extant. 
 
 Anaxagoras opposes Heraclitus in two essential points : 
 
 1. He opposes his dynamism with a mechanical cos- 
 mogony. 
 
 2. He substitutes dualism for hylozoistic monism, as- 
 suming the existence of an unintelligent, inert substance 
 and of an intelligent principle, the cause of motion. 
 
 1 MuUach, p. 12, V. 395: — 
 
 ^pijv ifpfj Koi d6tiT(f)aTOs enXfTo fiovvov 
 (ppovTicn. Kt'iafxov airavra KaraLcrcrovaa 6of)cn,v. 
 
 2 Aristotle, Met., I., 3 ; passim ; Simplicius, In Phijs., f. 33, 34, 35, 
 38; Diog. Laertius ; Fm^men^s collected by Schaiibach (Leipsic, 1827), 
 Schorn (Bonn, 1829), MuUach (I., pp. 243 ff.), Ritter and Preller (pp. 
 112 ff.) ; [Burnet (pp. 282 ff.) ; Breier, Die Philosophie des Anaxagoras, 
 Berlin, 1840] ; Zevort, Dissertation sur la vie el la doctrine d' Anaxagore, 
 Paris, 1848.
 
 ANAXAGORAS 49 
 
 1. The Materials of the Cosmogony. — Mattel 
 cannot be reduced to a single element, to a homogeneous 
 substance, like water, aii-, or fii*e, that may be transformed 
 into other substances. It is inconceivable how a substance 
 can become another substance. Hence there are several 
 primitive elements, and not only four, as Empedocles 
 teaches ; nay, there is an iniinite number of them. These 
 germs of things (jjirepixara) are infinite in number and 
 infinitely small (^(^pii'-j^aTa airetpa koI irXriOo^ koI a-fJUKpo- 
 r}]ra), uncreated, indestructible, and absolutely unchange- 
 able in essence. The quantity of these fii'st principles is 
 always the same; nothing can be destroyed or added 
 (jravra laa aei . . . ael Travra ovSev iXdcrao) ecrrlv ovSe 
 TrXetoj) ; they change neither in quality nor in quantity. 
 Nothing comes into being or passes away. Our usual 
 notions of birth (coming-into-being) and death (passing- 
 away) are absolutely VvTong. Nothing is produced ex 
 nihilo, and nothing is lost ; things are formed by the com- 
 bination of pre-existing germs, and disappear by the disin- 
 tegration of these germs, which still continue to exist. 
 Hence it would be better to call coming into being, mixture, 
 and j^assing away or death, separation} There is no other 
 change except change of place and grouping, external meta- 
 morphosis, movement; the notion of change of essence or 
 ti-ansubstantiation is a contradiction. 
 
 2. Efficient and Fiscal Causes of the Cos- 
 mogony. — Anaxagoras no longer regards the motion 
 which produces and destroys things as an original and 
 eternal reality, inherent in the very nature of the ele- 
 ments. The latter are inert and incapable of moving by 
 themselves. Hence they cannot account for the move- 
 
 * Simplicins, In Phya., 3 1 : To 5f yli'taffat koi dnoWvirdni ovk 6p6uyi 
 vofii^ovniv ol "EXXfjz/ff ■ ov^iv ya/) )(f)rifin ovi^e ytverai ov^e unoWvrai, aXX' 
 anb (i')VT<t)V ^(prjiiuTOiiv (TvfXixioytTdl re kui SinAcpiVfrai. Km oiTcof 3i/ opdSit 
 KoXoitv TO T( yivtaOai avpiiia-ytadai, koi to dnoXXvaOai SiaKpiutadai, 
 
 4
 
 50 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 ment in the woi-ld and the order which rules it. In order 
 to explain the cosmos, we must assume, in addition to the 
 material, inert, and unintelligent elements, an element 
 that possesses a force and intelligence of its own {vov<;). 
 This element of elements is absolutely simple and homo- 
 geneous ; it is not mixed with the other elements, but is 
 absolutely distinct from them. The latter are wholly 
 passive ; the vov'i, however, is endowed with spontaneous 
 activity; it is perfectly free {avTOKparr}^)^ and the source 
 of all movement and life in the world. The inferior ele- 
 ments have no consciousness of their own ; the mind 
 knows all things past, present, and future ; it has ariunged 
 and organized everything with design and according to 
 its teleological htness ; it is the eternal governor of the 
 universe, more powerful than all the other elements put 
 together. 
 
 3. Cosmogony. — In the beginning, the inert and 
 unintelligent elements were all jumbled together {ojjlov 
 irdvTo). In this original chaos (/jLiyfia), everything was 
 in everything : gold, silver, air, ether, all things which are 
 now separated, formed an indeterminate and inert mass. 
 The intelligent substance alone lived a distinct life of its 
 own. Then it entered the chaos and disentangled it, mak- 
 ing the cosmos out of it (elra vov'i iXOcov iravra 8l€k6- 
 a/xTjae). The germs, being set in motion by the Nous, were 
 separated and mingled together again according to their 
 inner affinities. From the point where movement is im- 
 parted to the chaos, the whirling motion (Slvo<;) gradually 
 extends over a wider and wider space to all parts of the 
 world ; it continues, as is proved by the rotation of the 
 heavens, and will continue without interruption until 
 the fity/jia is completely separated. Our earth is a cylin- 
 drical body and is composed of the heaviest germs, which 
 were carried towards the centre of the world by the orig- 
 inal motion. The lighter corpuscles, which form water,
 
 ANAXAGORAS 51 
 
 were deposited upon this solid mass ; higher up, the atmo- 
 sphere is formed by the germs of air ; at last, in the 
 heavenly regions, the most subtle elements, the tier}- 
 ether, are mixed together again. A second separation of 
 elements takes place, and the original motion parts off from 
 the earth the different solid, mineral, and other bodies 
 which compose it; from the water it parts off the differ- 
 ent liquids, and so on, until our central world receives 
 the shape which it now has. The stars are solid masses, 
 which were torn from the earth by the rotatory motion 
 originally possessed by it in common with the rest of the 
 universe, and which were ignited by coming in contact 
 witli tlie celestial ether. The sun is a fiery mass, fMv8po<; 
 hidirvpo^. The moon has mountains and valleys in it, and 
 borrows its light from the sun. 
 
 The views Avliich we have just expounded forecast the 
 cosmogonic theories of Buffon, Kant, and Laplace. Anaxa- 
 goras also anticipates comparative physiology by advancijig 
 the principle of the continuity of beings, by pointing out 
 the unity of purpose in the diverse vegetable and animal 
 types. In spite of all that has been said, however, he is so 
 far from being a spiritualist in the Cartesian sense of the 
 term, that he conceives animals, and even plants, as sharing 
 in tlie vov<;. If man is more intelligent than animals, it 
 is, lie believes, because liis mind employs more developed 
 organs. All living things, without exception, are endowed 
 with mind. 
 
 How do living beings partake of mind ? Does the intel- 
 ligent principle of Anaxagoras exist outside of these 
 bemgs, or is it but the sum of all the intelligences, all 
 the purposes, and all tlie motive forces, whence move- 
 ment in general results ? On the one hand, it is certain 
 that, inasmucli as the vov<i knows all things past, present, 
 and future, and knows them before the organization of 
 matter, it in no wise resembles either the Substance of
 
 52 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Spinoza or the active Idea of Hegel; for the Substance 
 of Spinoza and the Idea of Hegel know things only through 
 tlie mediation of the human brain ; that is to say, by means 
 of previously-organized matter. Anaxagoras is so decided 
 in his assumption that the vov^i is free and conscious of its 
 action, tliat he regards the word Fate (elfiapfjiev't]) as devoid 
 of meaning. Besides, the very term which he uses to 
 designate the motive principle signifies reason, purpose. 
 He seems to make a transcendent being of it, one that 
 exists independently of other beings, and acts upon them 
 in a purety mechanical way. He even seems to consider 
 these beings, not as intelligent in the true sense of the 
 word, but as automata which appear to be intelligent with- 
 out really being so. On the other hand, he speaks of the 
 presence of the vou<i in living creatures as though he were a 
 pantheist. The long and short of it is, the thinkers of this 
 remote age never broached the questions of transcendency 
 and immanency, personality and impersonality, conscious 
 intelligence and unconscious intelligence. Heraclitus found 
 nothing objectionable in assuming a primitive substance and 
 a perpetual state of change. Similarly, we may suppose, 
 Anaxagoras maintained both the transcendency and the 
 immanency of the vou<i, without even susjDccting that he 
 was contradictincr himself. 
 
 The same may be said in answer to the question whether 
 the voik of Anaxagoras is simply less material than 
 other substances, or whether it is an absolutely immaterial 
 entity. It is undoubtedly true, on the one hand, that the 
 attributes of the vov<i are altogether like those of the spirit 
 of spiritualism, and that the vov'? seems to have nothing in 
 common with matter except existence. Yet, on the other 
 hand, there seems to be but a difference of degree between 
 the vou<; and material substances : the wO?, in fact, is the 
 finest, the most mobile thing of all {XeirroTaTov Travrcov 
 ■^(^priixdrwv) ; it is identical with the ar)p -xjrvxi] of Anax-
 
 DIOGENES OF APOLLONIA, ARCHELAUS, ETC. 53 
 
 imenes.^ Hence, it is merely the highest kind of matter 
 and, consequently, not absolutely opposed to it as in spirit- 
 ualism proper. The dualistic conception is, as yet, only 
 vaguely defined in the system of Anaxagoras, who finds it 
 hard to cut loose from the materialism of the physicists. 
 Tliis is evident from the fact that Archelaus, his disciple, 
 considers the vov<i as the finest kind of matter. Moreover, 
 Anaxagoras himself fails to apply the notion of finality 
 and his principle that the prime mover is an intelligent 
 being. Aristotle justly censures him for using mind as a 
 deus ex macliina to account for the movement of matter, 
 and then wholly abandoning it for physical and mechanical 
 causes as soon as it has served his purpose in explaining 
 the origin of the first movement.^ 
 
 Nevertheless, Anaxagoras went far enough in spiritual 
 ism to cause a reaction in Ionian physics, which became 
 decidedly materialistic in consequence of this opposition. 
 
 8 12. Diogenes of Apollonia, Archelaus, Leucippus, 
 Democritus 
 
 1. Diogenes of Apollonia^ rejects both the pluralism 
 of elements and the dualism of unintelligent matter and 
 immaterial intelligence. He is a disciple of Aiiaximenes, 
 and assumes only one original element, air, which is the 
 source of all life in nature, and tlie essence of all bodies. 
 Mind, -wliicli Anaxagoras seems to regard as a separate 
 
 * 'I'lms Aristotle finds fiiuK \\\\\\ Anaxagoras for ideiitifyinsj^ i/oCs 
 witli -^vxT}- thoii(,Oi prctciidin^- to distinguish between ihoin {Do 
 animn, T., 2). 
 
 2 Aristotle, Met., T., 4, 7. C"f., Plato, Pl,fr,1o. 07 R. 
 
 » Simplicius, In Pfn/s., ^'2, .3.3; Diog. L., TX. ; [Fmrfmrnts, coll. hy 
 Schorn, Tionn, 1829]; Mnllach, T., pp. 252 ff. ; fHittn- and Picllcr. ].p. 
 172 ff. : Hurnot, pp. 'VW f . ; .'^oliloicrniafln'r, Udter Dini/rnes vnn Apol- 
 Innin (Works, i>art TIL, vol. 2, R.-rlin, 1S.'5S) ; Panzerbieter, De Ding 
 A. vita et scriptis, Mciningcn, 1823. — Tk.].
 
 54 GEEEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 principle, is wholly dependent on air. This is proved by 
 the fact that the spirit leaves the body as soon as the 
 breath is taken away. Hence we cannot say that air is the 
 product of mind or thought ; nay, the reverse is true, mind 
 is the product of air. Without air there can be no life, no 
 consciousness, no intelligence ; hence air, that is, matter, 
 is the only principle. Intelligence is not a distinct sub- 
 stance, but an attribute of air. It is obvious, says Dio- 
 genes, that the principle we assume is both great and 
 mighty and eternal and undying and of great knowledge 
 (jxeya Kol ia')(ypov kol athiov re ical aOdvarov koX ttoWo, 
 eiSo9). It is the opinion of this physicist, whose views 
 are closely akin to those of Melissus and the Eleatics, that 
 dualism is the negation of the fundamental principle of 
 science (e^ ez'o? aTravra). I believe, he goes on to say, that 
 all things are differentiations of the same thing, and are 
 the same thing ; and this seems obvious to me. How, 
 indeed, could the so-called elements, earth, water, air, etc., 
 mix with one another, if they were not fundamentally the 
 same ? How could they help or harm each other ? How 
 could the earth produce plants, and plants animals ? Let 
 us therefore confess, with the ancient physicists, that all 
 things arise from the same substance, and are destined to 
 return to the same thing.^ 
 
 2. Aechelaus.^ — Archelaus of Athens, or, according 
 to others, of Miletus, is a disciple of Anaxagoras. He ad- 
 heres to his teacher's atomism, but protests against the 
 dualistic interpretation of his system. The vov'i is a sepa- 
 rate thing like water, gold, and iron. It differs from these 
 substances as these substances differ among themselves. 
 Gold is not iron, but iron and gold are both matter. So, 
 too, mind, though neither gold nor iron, is, nevertheless, 
 
 i MuUach, p. 254. [Ritter and Preller, p. 173.] 
 2 Diog. L., II. ; SimpL, In Arist. Phjs., fol. 6 ; [Ritter and Preller, 
 pp. 178 ; Mullach, I,, pp. 257 ff . ; Burnet, pp. 367 ff.].
 
 THE ATOMISTS 55 
 
 material ; it is the finest, the most subtle, the most intan- 
 gible substance, without, however, being a simple tiling. 
 A simple substance is a substance that is composed of 
 nothing, and consequently does not exist. Matter and 
 substance are, therefore, synonymous terms. 
 
 3. The ATo:\nsTS. — That is also, on the whole, the 
 teaching of Leucippus and his cUsciple, Democritus of 
 Abdera, in Thrace, the most learned of the Ionian physi- 
 cists and the head of the ancient and modern materialistic ^ 
 school (420 B.C.). His numerous writings have been lost, 
 but important fragments remain. Besides, direct sources 
 being wanting, we may refer to the exposition of atomistic 
 principles in the poem of Lucretius.^ 
 
 The somewhat vague doctrines of Anaximenes, Dio- 
 genes, and Anaxagoras, on the nature and organization 
 of matter, are clearly formulated by Democritus.^ With 
 Anaximenes and Diogenes, he affirms the homogeneity 
 of all bodies; but, with Anaxagoras, he conceives this 
 indeterminate matter as divided into an infinite num- 
 ber of infinitely small molecules, which come together and 
 separate. In that way bodies are formed and destroyed. 
 These molecules are infinite in number and indivisible 
 
 1 We say muterialistic, and not atomhtic. For atomism is as old as 
 Anaxagoras and his theory of the ^pr^fiaTa "meipa kqi n'KTJdos Km afiiKpo- 
 TT]Ta, in fact if not in name. 
 
 2 [De natiira rerum, ed. by Lachmann (1850), Bernays (1852), 
 Munro, with Eng. tr. (1886). See Masson, The Atomic Theory of 
 Lucretius, London, 1884. — Tr.] 
 
 « Aristotle, Met., I., 4; De coelo, III., 2; De mwna, I., 2; Sext. 
 Emp., Adv. math., VII., 135; Diog. L., IX.; Lucretius, De rerum 
 natura; Clem, of Alex., Stromaleix; Mullach, I., pp. 330 ff . ; Ritter 
 and Preller, ])p. 154 ff. ; [Liard, De Democrito philofopho, Paris, 1873; 
 Brii.'ger, Die Urhm-egnng der Atome, Ilalle, 1884; Natorp, Forschungen 
 zur Geschichte des Erlcenntnis.sprohletnx im Alterlhum, Berlin, 1884; 
 Liepmann, Die Mechanik der Leucipp-Dcmolritschen Atome, Leipsic, 
 1885; Hart, Zur Seelen- und Erkcnntnisdehre des Demnkrit, Mu\hauseu. 
 1880; Xatorp, Die Ethika des Demokrilos, Marburg, 1803. — Th.].
 
 56 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 (aTOfxa), without, however, being mathematical points, for 
 an unextendecl thing would be nothing. They are identi- 
 cal in chemical quality (to yevo'i eV), but differ in size 
 (lu,€ye6o<;) and form (ax^f^a,)- They are endowed with pe]> 
 petual motion, which they do not receive from a tran^ 
 scendent principle, but which belongs to their essence. 
 The force which moves them acts according to necessity 
 (Ka6' elfxapfievr] vtt avdjKi]'i), and not, as Anaxagoras 
 seems to think, according to design (vov-i) and purpose 
 (reXo^;). Democritus rejects all teleology, but denies chance 
 also, though he sometimes employs the word ruxv in the 
 sense of necessity {avd<yfC7]). According to him, the word 
 " chance " merely expresses man's ignorance of the real 
 causes of phenomena. Nothing in nature happens without 
 cause ; all things have their reason and necessity.^ 
 
 The Eleatics denied the void and consequently motion. 
 To assume movement is equivalent to affirming the void 
 (rb Kevov). If there were no void, the atoms could not 
 even be distinguished from one another; that is to say, 
 they could not exist. Hence the void is the incUspensable 
 condition of their existence. It is also the condition of 
 movement, and therefore as important in the formation of 
 things as the full {to irXrjpe'i). The void is, as it were, a 
 second principle, which is added to the ^natter of material- 
 ism, and gives the system of Democritus the dualistic 
 turn which the most consistent monistic philosophies have 
 not been able wholly to avoid. The void of Democritus 
 meets us under the name of uTreipov in Pythagoras ; it is 
 the fir) 6v of Plato, Aristotle, and Plotinus, the negativity 
 of Campanella and of Hegel. Democritus regards it as the 
 condition of motion and of matter ; the idealists regard it 
 as the condition of the dialectical movement of thought. 
 The perpetual motion {atho^ Kivr}ai<;) produces a whirl' 
 
 1 Stobfeus, Ed. pJnjs., p. 160; Mullach, p. 365: Ov8ev xpw^ f^^'''T 
 yiverai, a\\a navra f k "koyov Km vn dmyKi]s.
 
 THE ATOMISTS 57 
 
 ing movement (Stw?) among the atoms, in consequence of 
 which they are combined according to their external affin- 
 ities, — that is, according to size and form ; for since they 
 are all chemically the same, they neither attract nor repel 
 each other. The heaviest atoms naturally move down- 
 wards in infinite space, while the lightest form the atmos- 
 phere. Some atoms have uneven, rough, sharp, or hooked 
 surfaces. These catch hold of each other and form acid or 
 bitter substances ; while atoms with smooth surfaces form 
 substances which impress the senses agreeably. The soul 
 consists of the finest, smoothest, and therefore most nimble 
 atoms. When such atoms exist in isolation, or are mixed 
 together in small quantities, the soul-atoms are insensible ; 
 when they are joined together in large masses, they acquire 
 the faculty of sensation. They are scattered over the en- 
 tire body, but gathered together more numerously in the 
 sense-organs, where sensation is produced : in the brain, the 
 seat of thought ; in the heart, the seat of the affections ; and 
 in the liver, the seat of desire. Sensation and perception 
 are explained as follows : Effluences {airoppoiai) go forth 
 from all bodies and enter our organs of sense, where they 
 excite sensation, and the brain, where they produce ideas 
 or images of things {elhaXa). 
 
 Sensation is the only source of knowledge, and there is 
 nothing in thought that has not passed tlu'ough the channel 
 of the senses. Our ideas represent our impressions, that 
 is, the relations existing between ourselves and the external 
 world; they are not direct reproductions of the objects 
 themselves, the inner essence of which is concealed from 
 us. We ctre self-conscious as long as the soul-atoms remain 
 intact in the body ; sleep ensues, and with it loss of con- 
 sciousness, when a certain number of atoms escape ; when 
 nearly all of tliem escape, and ])ut a few remain, Ave fall 
 into a state of seeming deatli ; aii<l, fniiilly, when all the 
 psychical atoms are separated from the Ijody at once, we
 
 58 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 die. Deatli cannot destroy these atoms, because the atom 
 is indivisible and therefore indestructible ; it destroys their 
 temporary union in a body, and, consequently, the individ- 
 uality formed by such a union. Since feeling does not 
 belong to isolated atoms, but is jjroduced only by a combin- 
 ation of atoms in the brain and in other organs, death puts 
 an end to feeling and destroys the personality. 
 
 The gods are more powerful beings than man, but their 
 immortality is not absolute. Since they are composed of 
 atoms, like mortals, they eventually succumb to the com- 
 mon fate of all, though they live longer than human beings. 
 In the eternal universe, no one has any absolute privileges. 
 Since the gods are more powerful and wiser than ourselves, 
 we should venerate them. We may assume that they come 
 into relation with us, — in cbeams for example ; but we 
 should free ourselves from all superstitious fears concern- 
 ing them, and not forget that above these beings, however 
 powerful they may be, there is one still more powerful than 
 they, — Necessity, the supreme, impersonal, and impartial 
 law which governs the heavens and the earth. To this law, 
 which nature imposes upon all beings alike, we must submit 
 with joyous hearts. Our happiness depends upon it.^ 
 
 Atomistic materialism culminates in scepticism in Pro- 
 tagoras of Abdera, the philosophy of Heraclitus in Cratylus, 
 and the Eleatic doctrine in Gorgias. This period forms a 
 fruitful crisis in the history of Greek philosophy. Though 
 temporarily discouraged by the examination of her resources 
 for knowing the truth, philosophy emerged from the dark- 
 ness, strengthened and exalted, conscious of her powers, 
 and enriched by a series of studies that had, until then, 
 never been pursued; I mean the intellectual and moral 
 sciences. 
 
 1 See Bur chard, Fragment e der Moral des Aider iten Demokritus, 
 Minden, 1834. For the points of contact between Democritus and 
 modern positivism, see Aristotle, Phys., VIII:, 1, 27.
 
 SECOND PERIOD 
 AGE OF CRITICISM OR PHILOSOPHY OF :^^KD 
 
 § 13. Protagoras 
 
 Peotagoras,^ a fellow-countiyman and friend of Denio- 
 critiis, acquired fame through the eloquent lectures which 
 he delivered in Sicily and at Athens. He was no longer a 
 (f>LX6cT0(f)0'i, but a o-o^to-T779, that is, a teacher of piiilosophy 
 who received pay for his lessons. His example was fol- 
 lowed by a number of talented men, who undertook to 
 acquaint the educated public with the conceptions of the 
 pliilosophers, which had hitherto been restricted to the 
 narrow confines of the schools. The laxness of their moral 
 principles and their unbelief in polytheism caused these 
 clever popularizers of knowledge to be stigmatized as 
 Sophists. Their work, however, ranks in importance with 
 that of the Humanists and Encyclopedists. Pampered as he 
 was by the cultured, wealthy, and sceptical youths of the 
 age, but detested by the common people, who remained pas- 
 
 1 The Thecetetus of Plato ; Diog. L., IX. ; Sext. Emp., Hiipohjp., I., 
 217; Adv. math., VII.; [Mullach, vol. II., Iviii., pp. 130 ff.] ; R'itter 
 and Preller, pp. 183 ff. ; Vitringa, De Profogorce vita et philosnphla, 
 Groeniiigen, 18.52; [Xatorp, For.schiingcn zitr Geschichte des Erlennl- 
 nissprohlems (see above, page 55) ; Harpf, Die Ethik des Protaijoras, 
 Heidelberg, 1884. For the Sophists in general, see Grote, Hislory oj 
 Greece, vol. VIIT. ; Hegel ; Hermann, Geschichte und System der plato- 
 nischen Philosnphie, pp. 179 ff., 290 ff.; J. Geel, Hisloria critica sophisla- 
 rum, etc., Utrecht, 1823; Valat, Essai historique sur les sophistes grecs 
 (Investiqaleur, Paris, 1859) ; Schanz, Bp.itrdge zur vorsok-ratischen Philo- 
 xophie, I.; Die Sophislen, fliittingen, 1807; Blass, Die allische Beredsavi- 
 kfiilvon Gorf/ias bis zu Lysias, Leipsic, 1808; II. Sidgwick, The Sophists 
 {Journal of Philology, IV., 1872, pp. 288-300; V., 1873, pp. 00-80); 
 Siebeck Untersuchungcn znr Philosophic der Griechen (I. : Uebev So 
 krates' Verhaltniss zur Sophistik), 2d ed., Freilnirg, 1888. — Tu.].
 
 60 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 sionately attached to the religion of their forefathers, Pro- 
 tagoras, like his contemporaries Anaxagoras and Socrates, 
 fell a victim to the fanaticism of the masses and the 
 hypocrisy of the great. He was banished, and his writings 
 burned in the market-place (411). We may assign as tlie 
 immediate cause of his condemnation, the doubts Avhich he 
 expressed concerning the existence of the gods in his book 
 irepl deoiv. 
 
 The scepticism of Protagoras represents the conclusion 
 of a syllogism of wliich the Trdvra pel of Heraclitus forms 
 the major, and the sensualism of Democritus, the minor 
 premise. The sensible world is a perpetual metamori^hosis ; 
 the senses show only the things that pass away ; they do 
 not reveal the immutable, necessary, and universal. Hence, 
 if we would know the truth, we must derive it from a 
 better source than our deceptive senses ; we must appeal 
 to reflection, to reason. But, according to Democritus, 
 reflection is simply the continuation of sensation, from 
 which it does not essentially differ. Consequently, if sen- 
 sation is changeable, uncertain, and illusory, and is at the 
 same time the only source of knowledge, it necessarily 
 follows that all knowledge is uncertain. No one knows 
 anything but his own sensations. Things that are not given 
 to us in sensation do not exist for us. Whatever we feel 
 exists for 7(s. Since the atoms of Democritus are not 
 perceived by the senses, they are merely hypotheses without 
 any real value, and the importance whicli the philosopher 
 attaches to them is inconsistent with his doctrine. The 
 same may be said of the germs of Anaxagoras, the elements 
 of Empedocles, the principles of the school of Miletus; 
 they are all purely hypothetical theories, and cannot be 
 demonstrated. There is no truth for man except in what 
 he perceives, feels, and experiences. And as sensations 
 differ for different individuals, a thing seeming green to 
 one and blue to another, large to one and small to another,
 
 PROTAGORAS 61 
 
 it follows that there are as many truths as"" individuals ; 
 that the individual is tlie measure of the true and the false 
 OjrdvTcov YprjfiaTcov fxerpov dvOpcoiro^, tcov jxev ovroiv co? ecrn, 
 TMV S' ovK ovTcov w? ovK ecTTLv'^) \ that thcrc are no univer- 
 sally valid truths or principles, or, at least, that we have 
 no certain criterion (/cpn^pLov) by which to recognize the 
 absolute truth of a metaphysical or moral proposition. The 
 individual is the measure of the true and the good. An 
 act that benefits one man harms another ; it is good for the 
 former, bad for the latter. Practical truth, like theoretical 
 truth, is a relative thing, a matter of taste, temperament, 
 and education. ]Metaphysical controversies are therefore 
 utterly vain. It is not possible for us to prove anything 
 but the particular fact of sensation ; still more impossible 
 is it to know the causes or ultimate contlitions of reality, 
 which escape all sense-perception. 
 
 Let man, therefore, occupy himself with the only really 
 accessible object, with himself! Let him abandon his sterile 
 speculations concerning ultimate causes, and concentrate 
 his attention upon what is, after all, the only problem of 
 importance, — the question concerning the conditions of 
 happiness. Happiness consists in governing one's self and 
 others ; to govern one's self means to be virtuous ; hence 
 philosophy is the art of being virtuous. In order to gov- 
 ern others — in a society that is captivated by the beauties 
 of language and always ready to sacrifice the matter to the 
 form — it behooves one to be eloquent, that is, to think 
 correctly and to speak correctly. Hence, philosophy is 
 the art of thinking correctly and of speaking correctly. It 
 consists of the following three branches: practical ethics, 
 dialectics, and rhetoric. 
 
 These doctrines, in which tlie subject and the object are 
 for the first time opposed to each other, exaggerate a 
 
 1 I Hog. L., IX., 51.
 
 62 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 highly important truth : the truth that realit}^ is not some- 
 thing external to the thinking and feeling subject ; that the 
 feeling and thinking subject is a coeflicient in the produc- 
 tion of the phenomenon ; in a word, that thought — whether 
 it be transformed sensation or something else — is one of 
 the principles of things, one of those primary conditions of 
 reality for which philosophy has been seeking, a principle 
 which it divined in the Xo'70? of Heraclitus, the eV of 
 Pythagoreanism, and the vov<i of Anaxagoras. Thought 
 7iot only strives to reduce things to a unity, it is the unify- 
 ing principle itself (to eV), that which unities and measures 
 reality. It is, indeed, Trdvrcov '^^^pijfxdrcov /xerpov, and in so far 
 as it is not conscious of itself except in man, Protagoras 
 and the Sophists were perfectly right in saying : iravrav 
 'X^prjijArcov fxerpov dvOpwiro^. This maxim is no less epoch- 
 making in the liistory of ancient philosophy than the 'yvG>6i 
 aeavTov of Socrates. It demolishes the past in order to 
 make room for new and sounder theories based upon the 
 consciousness of self, and inaugurates tlie age of criticism. 
 
 The criticism of Protagoras and the Sophists yields 
 many fruitful results. 
 
 It destroys the mental foundations of polytheism and 
 prepares the way for the religion of Socrates, Plato, and 
 the Stoics. In the second place, it destroj's the naive 
 dogmatism of fantastic speculation ; and its dialectical 
 extravagances and sophistries compel thought to give an 
 account of itself, its mechanism, its methods, and its 
 laws. For several centuries, philosophy had used its 
 reasoning powers without accounting for the nature and 
 the forms of the syllogism; it had made its inferences 
 and deductions without investigating the inductive and 
 deductive methods. In this respect it resembled the mil- 
 lions of creatures who see and hear without having the 
 slightest notion of the mechanism of sight and hearing. 
 Sophisticism, even though it abuses the laws of thought,
 
 SOCKATES 63 
 
 nay, let us say, precisely because it abuses them, makes the 
 niind conscious of its laws and causes it to analyze them, 
 and so becomes the forerunner of the science of logic, the 
 development of which constitutes the glory of Aristotle. 
 Simultaneously with the science of thought, it creates the 
 science of its inseparable outer shell, language, — grammar, 
 syntax, or philology in the broadest sense of the terra. By 
 laying so much stress on form, and showing such care in 
 the use of wortls, the Sopliists rendered the Greek language 
 more flexible, and fashioned it into the wonderful instru- 
 ment of thought wliicli we admire in the dialogues of Plato. 
 
 The error of Protagoras and the subjectivistic Sophists 
 consists in their interpreting dvdpcoTro^ to mean, not man 
 in general but the indi\ddual, not the human understand- 
 ing but the understanding of each particular inchvidual, 
 and in assuming, in consequence, as many measures of the 
 true and the false as there are individuals. Protagoras, 
 like the majority of the Greek philosophers, exaggerates 
 (1) the physiological and mental differences existing be- 
 t^veen individuals ; (2) the illusions of sensation. He 
 ignores the fact which science has since demonstrated, 
 that the investigator may correct the data of the senses 
 by means of each other, and his ignorance of this fact 
 leads him to deny the existence of an objective criterion 
 of truth. He fails to see that the human reason is 
 essentially the same in all incUviduals. ^len hinder him 
 from seeing man. 
 
 It is this cardinal error in his philosophy which is recti- 
 fied by Socrates. 
 
 § 14. Socrates 
 
 Socrates of Athens ^ (409-399), once a sculptor like liis 
 father, was attracted to philosophy by the teachings of the 
 
 1 .Sources : Xenophon's Mpmnrnhilla and Spitposium ; Plato, Apol- 
 og>/. Phuln, PJuetlrus, Metio, Thentetus, etc., Aristotle, Met., T., and
 
 64 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Sophists, and, like them, devoted his life to the instruction 
 and education of the youth. The brilliancy and spiritual- 
 ity of his conversation, which was Attic to a fault, the 
 grandeur of his ideas, the boldness of his political para- 
 doxes, everything about the man, except his outward form, 
 was calculated to charm and attract. The martyrdom 
 which he suffered only helped to raise the admiration of 
 his many disciples to the highest pitch. Though ar_ adver- 
 sary of the Sophists, whose venality he condemned, he 
 resembled them so much that he was mistaken for a 
 Sophist. Like them, he expressed a contempt for meta- 
 physics, natural science, which, he said, culminates in 
 atheism, and mathematics, which, to his mind, consists of 
 nothing but barren speculations. Like them and like the 
 true Athenian that he was, he placed the study of the moral 
 man and of the duties of the citizen in the veiy centre of 
 education ; like them, finally, he rated the formal culture 
 of the mind much more highly than material instruction, 
 without calculating the effect of intellectual freedom on 
 the religion and the constitution of the State. Hence, he 
 was, not without some show of reason, identified with the 
 Sophists, and the hatred of the conservative democracy 
 in its turn destroyed him. Aristophanes opened the battle 
 against the reformer. He ridiculed him in the Clouds and 
 
 passim ; Cicero, Acad., I., 4, 15, and passim ; Ritter and Preller, 192 ff. ; 
 Freret, Observations sur les causes de la condamnation de Socrate (an 
 essay I'ead in the year 1736, printed in the M^moires de I'Acad^mie 
 des inscriptions, vol. 47 B, pp. 209 if.) ; [Grote, History of Greece, vol. 
 Vm., chap. 68; Kdchly, Sokrates und sein Volk {A kademische Vortrage 
 und Reden, I.), Zurich, 1859 ; Alberti, Sokrates, ein Versuch iiber ihn 
 nach den Quellen, Gottingen, 1869] ; Chaignet, Vie de Socrate, Paris, 
 1868 ; [Antonio Labriola, La dottrina di Socrate, Naples, 1871 ; Sie- 
 beck, Ueher Sokrates' Verhdltniss zur Sophistik {Untersuchungen zur 
 Philosophie der Griechen, 1873; 2d ed., Freiburg i. B., 1888)]; Fouillee, 
 La philosophie de Socrate, 2 vols., Paris, 1874. [Wildauer, Sokrate^ 
 Lehre vom Willen, Innsbruck, 1877. — Tr.]
 
 SOCRATES 65 
 
 at the same time aroused suspicion against his religious 
 and political vie"\vs. After the fall of the Thirty Tyrants, 
 Socrates was accused " of not believing in the gods of the 
 State, of proclaiming other gods, and of corrupting the 
 youth," and condemned to chink the hemlock (399). 
 
 Although Socrates left no writings, we have a better 
 knowledge of liim than of his predecessors. For this we are 
 indebted to two of his enthusiastic pupils, Xenophon and 
 Plato. Their accounts do not, by any means, agree with 
 one another in all respects. The Socrates of the Memor- 
 abilia is ' a moral philosopher and an apostle of natural 
 religion rather than a metaphysician ; the Socrates of the 
 Dialogues of Plato is a keen and profound thinker, the rival 
 of Heraclitus, Parmenides, and Anaxagoras. The simplest 
 explanation of the diiference is as follows : Xenophon pre- 
 sents the teacliings of the master according to his under- 
 standing of them ; while Plato, whose philosophical horizon 
 is broader than that of Socrates, exaggerates the metaphy- 
 sical import of his doctrine and uses Socrates as a mask 
 for his own ideas. Happily we liave, besides the very 
 detailed but sometimes uncertain data of the two disciples, 
 the opinion of Aristotle to guide us, and he cannot, to say 
 the least, be accused of partiality.^ 
 
 The scepticism of Protagoras and the Sopliists forms 
 the starting-point of the philosophy of Socrates. All he 
 knows is that he knows nothing ; he is, furthermore, con- 
 vinced tliat certainty is impossible in the case of physical 
 science. However, though he is a sceptic in cosmology, 
 his scepticism does not extend to the field of morals. He 
 believes — and tliis conviction of liis forms a new and pos- 
 itive element in tlie pliilosopliy of his times — lie believes 
 that there is something in the universe tliat can be known, 
 
 » Met., I., 6 ; XIII., 4. Top. I., 2. Eth. Nic, passim. [Cf. Klctt, 
 SoLrdlfis Tifich lien Xenophontischen MfiiiordhUlcii, Canstatt 18n;i. — 
 Joel, Der echtt und der Xenophonlische SoLrates, Berlin, 189:}. — Tu.]. 
 
 5
 
 66 GEEEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 and known absolutely ; this, as the words inscribed on the 
 temple of Delphi : Know thyself^ indicate, is man. We 
 can never know exactly what is the nature of the world, 
 its origin, and its end, but we can know what we ourselves 
 ought to be, what is the meaning and aim of life, the high- 
 est good of the soul ; and tliis knowledge alone is real and 
 useful, because it is the only possible knowledge. Outside 
 of ethics there can be no serious philosophy. 
 
 By making man the real object of science, Socrates evi- 
 dently did not intend to create a scientific anthropology, 
 or even to give us a psj^chology in the strict sense of the 
 word. Man means for him the soul as the seat of" moral 
 ideas. He accepts no other science than ethics, of which 
 Aristotle calls him the founder ; but ethics is, in his opin- 
 ion, a real, certain, and positive science resting on universal 
 principles. Seemingly, indeed, Socrates does not get beyond 
 the standpoint of Protagoras and his principle that man is 
 the measure of all things. But the moral system of the 
 great Sophist was not scientific, because it failed to recog- 
 nize universal principles. By man as the measure of all 
 things, Protagoras means the individual, and not human 
 nature in general ; he means the particular, accidental, 
 changreable individual, and not the immutable and neces- 
 sary moral element which is common to all. He did not 
 believe in tlie existence of such a fundamental human 
 nature. Moral ideas do not, in his opinion, possess objec- 
 tive and absolute value; goodness, justice, and truth 
 depend upon individual taste, which is the sole and final 
 judge. There are, therefore, as many systems of ethics as 
 individuals, which amounts to saying that there is none. 
 The Sophists were deceived by the diversity of opinions, 
 judgments, and feelings which they discovered among men. 
 This diversity is but apparent and on the surface. The 
 moral ideas lie concealed and slumbering, as it were, be- 
 neath individual prejudices. We have only to remove this
 
 SOCRATES 67 
 
 superficial layer by means of education, in order to dis- 
 cover in all the same ideas and the same aspirations towards 
 goodness, beauty, justice, and truth. 
 
 Socrates' merit, therefore, consists in having attempted, 
 at least in morals, to separate the general from the particu- 
 lar ; in having advanced from the individual to the univer- 
 sal ; in having again chscovered, beneath the infinite variety 
 of men^ the one unchangeable man. Beneath the confused 
 mass of opinions held by a demoralized century, he finds 
 the true and immutable opinion, the conscience of the 
 human race, the law of niinds.^ Hence Socrates not only 
 rendered a service to ethics, he benefited metaphysics as 
 well. In the midst of intellectual anarchy, he teaches 
 thought how to infer and define, and helps to put an end 
 to the confusion of ideas by giving words their exact 
 meaning.^ Thus, as long as there is no exact definition of 
 the notion of God, a man has as much right to espouse 
 atheism as theism : theism, if by God is meant the one 
 indivisible Providence that governs the world ; atlieism, 
 if we mean those antlu'opomor^jhic beings with whom the 
 Greek imagination peopled the Olympus. The main thing, 
 therefore, is to come to some agreement as to the terms ; 
 and to this end we must define them exactly, — an art in 
 which Socrates excelled. He was, says Xenophon,^ untir- 
 ing in his efforts to examine and define goodness and wick- 
 edness, justice and injustice, wisdom and folly, courage 
 and cowardice, the State and the citizen. He did not offer 
 his definitions to his liearers ready-made. He differed from 
 the sensualist Protagoras in his conviction that moral 
 ideas are fundamental to humanity, that eveiy human mind 
 is hi(j ivitli truth, that education creates notliiug tliat is not 
 already tliere, but merely awakens and develops the latent 
 
 1 The Koivoi \6yoi of Ilcjiaclitiis. 
 
 2 AristoU.', Mri., I., (3; XIII., 4, 8-0, Z'>; Top., I., 12. 
 « Mem., I., 1, 10.
 
 68 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 germs of knowledge. He contented himself with being a 
 spiritual midivife^ and his chief delight lay in teaching his 
 hearers how to discover the true definitions for themselves. 
 A better teacher never lived. He practised his art, which 
 he loved to compare with that of his mother,^ in the jDublic 
 places, on the walks, and in the work-shops ; wherever he 
 found an intelligent face before him. He was in the habit of 
 plying those whom chance made liis pupils with questions, 
 — questions that were often trifling in their natui'e. He 
 began by chiming in with their views. Then, by means of 
 the most skilful questioning, he gradually forced them to 
 confess that they knew little or nothing, and, finally, 
 brought them to see the truth. The dialogues of Plato 
 give us an insight into the famous dialectical method, which 
 enabled Socrates to confound the learned pretensions of his 
 interlocutors, and which has been called the Socratic irony. 
 Though Socrates sought to enlighten men, to teach 
 them how to flunk correctly and to know the truth, his 
 object was not to make them learned, but to make them 
 happy and useful citizens.^ Ever since the days of Socra- 
 tes, philosoph}" has regarded it as her prerogative to take 
 the place of religion, morality, and positive faith, in the 
 absence of a universally recognized official religion. This 
 accounts for the peculiar character of the Socratic and 
 post^Socratic schools, which are as much religious brother- 
 hoods as learned schools. For Socrates, Avho is, to a cer- 
 tain extent, a national tliinker, a full-fledged Athenian, 
 and for whom actual life has greater charms than abstract 
 theory, vrisdom or knowledge is not the goal ; it is the 
 means, the indispensable means, of right living, as essential 
 to the private individual as to the citizen and statesman. 
 The intimate relation which exists between knowledge and 
 
 1 Plato, Thecetelus, 149 A, 151. Mem. IV., 7, 1. 
 
 2 Mevi., I., 1, 11 ; Aristotle, Met., I., 6; XIII., 4; De part, anim., 
 I., 1, 642 ; Cicero, TuscuL, V., 4.
 
 SOCRATES 69 
 
 will constitutes the fundamental principle and, in a meas- 
 ure, the very soul of his philosophy. The essential thought 
 is that the more a man thinks and knows, the better will 
 he act; that our moral value is directly proportional to our 
 lights. From tliis principle the other cliaracteristic propo- 
 sitions of his philosophy necessarily follow, namely : that 
 virtue is teachable ; that it is o)ic^ which means that we 
 cannot be virtuous in one thing without being so in all 
 things, or vicious in one without being so in all ; finally, 
 that no one is voluntarily bad; that evil is the fruit of 
 ignorance.^ 
 
 The ethical system of Socrates is a mean between the 
 idealism of Pythagoras and the realism that is inseparable 
 from the sensationalistic and materialistic trend of the Ionian 
 schools. It aims at the ideal, but it loves to express this 
 ideal in sensible forms, to reflect moral beauty in physical 
 beauty. Socrates is far from being an ascetic : he strives 
 to subdue nature, to make it the instrument of intelli- 
 gence, to rule over it as an absolute master ; but he never 
 di'eams of suppressing it.^ He is a Grecian and an Athen- 
 ian above everything else, and so sensitive to external 
 charms and phj-sical beauty that he feels himself obliged 
 to wage constant yx-AY with the allurements of matter. 
 
 He agrees with liis predecessors on religious matters in 
 that he repudiates mythology and its fables, without, how- 
 ever, being a free-thinker in the modern sense. His spirit- 
 ualistic faith is not even devoid of superstition. He 
 believes in the supernatural, in superior beings who watch 
 over nations and insjiire individuals (Sai/xovia). But he 
 strongly emphasizes the universality of Providence, and 
 thereby attacks the particularism of the Athenians, thus 
 paving tlie way for the notion of tlie universal brotherhood 
 of man, tauglit l)y Stoicism and Cllnistiaiiity.^ 
 
 ' Afcm., III. t); IV., 0; Arist., Kth. Nic, III., 1 ; Vi., 13. 
 * T'lato, Si/mposium, lid, 214, 220. 
 » Afem., I., 1, 18; IV., Vi, Vi.
 
 70 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 In short, the founder of Attic philosophy is very much 
 inferior, as a theorist, to his modern antitype, Emanuel 
 Kant. Owing to his heroic death, his importance, though 
 great, was overrated at the expense of that of liis pre- 
 decessors, who were philosophers of the highest order. But 
 he is, nevertheless, one of those reformers whose sojourn 
 on earth has been productive of lasting and fruitful re- 
 sults. His great work consists in having given to con- 
 science the honored place wliich it deserves, in having 
 reinstated the absolute, immutable, and universal. At a 
 time when men publicly declared that good and evil are 
 relative, and that the rule for judging an act is not the 
 " changing " law of conscience, but its success, he had the 
 courage to proclaim the authority of a conscience that 
 merely varies in ajDpearance, and the superiority of the 
 moral law over individual caprice. Now, to maintain the 
 absoluteness of morality meant the reform of philosophy 
 as well as that of morals. For, in spite of what indepen- 
 dent moralists may sa}^, human thought cannot, without 
 contradiction, affirm the absolute in practice and jQi deny 
 it in theory. 
 
 Of the many disciples of the new school, some, like 
 Aristippus and Antisthenes, develop the ethical teachings 
 of Socrates in opijosition to the metaphysical speculations 
 of the old schools ; others, like Euclides and Plato, unite 
 the Socratic conception of the liighest good and the Eleatic 
 notion of the absolute, the end of the moralists and the j^rs^ 
 cause of the metaphysicians, and therebj^ re-establish the 
 union between the philosophy of morals and the philosophy 
 of nature, wliich had been dissolved by scepticism.
 
 AKItjTIPPUS, x^NTISTIIENES, EUCLIDES 71 
 
 § 15. Aristippus and Hedonism. — Antisthenes and Cynicism. 
 Euclides and the School of Megara 
 
 1. Aeistippus of Cyrene ^ was a sensualistic Sophist 
 before joining the Socratics, and adhered to the theoretical 
 teachings of that school. With Protagoras, he maintains 
 that all onr knowledge is subjective, and that we cannot 
 know what things are in themselves. He sharply dis- 
 tinguishes between the object of knowledge and Kant's 
 thing-in-itself^ that is, the external and absolutely unknown 
 cause of our sensations (to eixiTOLrjTiKov tov 7rddov<i^? His 
 ethics, too, is more in accord with the principles of Pro- 
 tagoras than those of Socrates. Pleasure {rjhovri) is, ac- 
 corchng to him, the ultimate aim of life. Hence the name 
 hedonism is applied to his doctrine, which must not, how- 
 ever, be interpreted as a coarse sensualism. Pie is a follower 
 of Socrates and his moral principles on this important 
 point, and demands, above all, moderation in indulgence, 
 rational self-command in presence of the allurements of 
 sense, and intelligent control of the vulgar instincts of our 
 nature. AVe must, he said, remain masters of ourselves 
 under all circumstances, so that we may say : ep^co ovk 
 exofiai, or, as the Latin poet translates the maxim of 
 Aristippus : — 
 
 — Mihi res non me rebus suhjnngere Conor. ^ 
 
 ]\Iental pleasures, friendship, paternal and filial love, art 
 and literature, take precedence, in the scale of enjoyments, 
 over fleeting sensuous feelings ; and the wise man should 
 particularly seek, not the pleasures of the moment, but 
 
 1 Diog. L., IT.; Sext. Enip., .-If/r. math., VII., 191-192; [Kilter 
 and Treller, pp. 207 ff.-, MuUacli, II., 397 If.; Wendt, De philosophia 
 Cyrenaica, Gottingen, 1841. — Tk.] ; II. v. Stein, De philosophia 
 Cyreuaica, Gottingen, 1855; [Watson, Hedonistic Theories from 
 Arislijipus to Spencer, New York, 1895]. 
 
 2 Sext. Eini)., Adv. math., A'll., 191. 
 • Horace, Epistles, I., 1, 17.
 
 72 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 lasting joys, a permanent state of moral content (%a/3a, 
 €v8aL/jL,ovia). Moreover, Aristippus and his adherents agree 
 witli tlie Sopliists that all action has for its motive the 
 desire to be happy, and for its end the pleasure which the 
 act procures. They likewise agree with Protagoras in 
 religion. The hedonists were outspoken freethinkers, and 
 helped to demolish the remnants of the polytheistic faith 
 among the educated classes. In a work entitled The Gods, 
 Theodoras of Cyrene, called the Atheist,^ openly espoused 
 atheism; another hedonist, Euhemerus,^ held, in a sensa- 
 tional treatise {lepa avajpacf)^] ^), that the gods were heroes, 
 kings, and distinguished men who had been deified after 
 their death. This theory proved very acceptable to a great 
 number of Romans, and even Christians, who rejoiced at 
 having paganism furnish them with such powerful weapons 
 against itself. However narrow this view may seem, it 
 has the merit of being one of the first attempts at a 
 science which it has been left to our age to study and 
 develop : I mean the philosophy of religion. 
 
 Hedonism passes tlu-ough a process of evolution which 
 may, at first sight, seem surprising, but which is no more 
 than natural ; it changes into pessimism in the philosophy 
 of Hegesias,* called TretaLddvaro'i (" persuader to die "). 
 This evolution was the logical outcome of the hedonistic 
 principle. The aim of life is, according to the Cyrenaic 
 school, pleasure; the sensation of the moment (rjSovr] iu 
 Kivrjaei), according to some, permanent pleasure or happi- 
 ness (xapct, evSaifxovLo), according to others. Now experi- 
 ence proves that life affords more pain than pleasure, and 
 
 1 About 310 B. c. ; a contemporary and protege of Demetrius of 
 Phalerus and of Ptolemy I. [Fragments of the Cyi-enaics in Mullach, 
 II., pp. 397 ff. ; Ritter and Preller, 207 ff . — Tr.] 
 
 2 About 310 B. c. 
 
 ' Fragments preserved by Diodorus and Eusebius. 
 * A contemporary of Ptolemy I.
 
 AEISTIPPUS, ANTISTHENES, EUCLIDES 73 
 
 that unalloyed happiness is a ciream. Hence the end of 
 life is not and cannot be realized. Life, therefore, has no 
 value. As a consequence, death is preferable to life ; for 
 death at least procures for us tlie only happiness possible 
 to human beings, a negative happiness consisting in the 
 absolute suppression of pain.i Tliis is the way in which 
 Hegesias reasons, and all must reason who regard pleasure, 
 jo}', or happiness as the only end of life (reXo?). Life has 
 real value only for such as recognize a higher aim, namely, 
 moral goodness, the performance of duty, virtue for virtue's 
 sake ; in other words, life has value only for him who con- 
 siders it as a means and not as an end in itself, that is, in 
 short, for the idealist. For him, virtue is the highest good. 
 Now virtue can be realized only by living beings. Hence 
 life itself, being the means and indispensable condition of 
 virtue or of the liighest good, is a relative good, and not 
 the summum homim. Hence moral idealism necessarily ex- 
 cludes pessimism. 
 
 The hedonistic school, which again becomes optimistic in 
 Anniceris of Cyrene,^ is continued by the school of Epi- 
 curus,^ who supplements the ethics of Aristippus with the 
 physics of Democritus. 
 
 2. Antisthenes.'^ — The idealistic teachings of Socrates 
 are reproduced and exaggerated l)y Antisthenes of Athens, 
 the founder of the Cynic school. The school was named 
 after the gymnasium of Kynosarges^ where Antisthenes 
 delivered his lectures. Its motto is: Virtue for virtue's 
 sake ; Virtue is the final and only goal of all our actions ; 
 
 1 Cicero, Tusc, I., 34 : A malis mors ahducit. 
 
 2 Aliout 300 II. c. See Diog. L., II., 03 ff. 
 « § 10. 
 
 * Diog. L., VI.; [for A. and lii.s scliool, see also, Mullach, II., 
 pp. 201 ff. ; Hitter and Preller, pp. 216 ff. ; Dueniinler, Antistheriica, 
 IlaUe, 1882. —Tk.]
 
 74 GKEEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Virtue is the highest good. The Cynics, his successors, go 
 so far in their enthusiasm as to prochiim the doctrine that 
 pleasure is an evil ; that man cannot be virtuous unless he 
 renounces all material and even intellectual pleasures ; they 
 even reject mental culture and philosophy itself as evils. 
 Despising, as they did, the pleasures of social life, they 
 came to violate the simplest rules of politeness, and, in 
 principle at least, rebelled against the laws themselves. 
 For a life of refinement and civilization these " Rousseaus of 
 antiquity " substitute the state of nature ; cosmopolitanism 
 takes the place of patriotism. The principle of individual 
 autonomy, which had been proclaimed by the Sophists and 
 by Socrates, passes from theory into practice. Not all the 
 Cynics, however, are radicals. We must make allowances 
 in the well-known history of Diogenes of Sinope,^ the dis- 
 ciple of Antisthenes, for popular malice, which naturally 
 goes to extremes, and is apt to culminate in caricature. 
 The moral idealism of Antisthenes, which was disfigured by 
 the exaggerations of some of the Cynic philosophers, reap- 
 peared in a new and purer form in the doctrines of Zeno 
 and the Stoics. 
 
 3. EucLrDES,2 the founder of the school of Megara, 
 made the first attempt to give the ethical system of the 
 master a metaphysical support, wliich he finds in the phil- 
 osophy of the Eleatics. He accepts the teaching of Par- 
 menides that being is one, and the Socratic notion concern- 
 ing the reality of the vov<i and of moral principles. From 
 these premises he boldly draws the conclusion, wliich was 
 again advanced by Fichte in modern times, that mind or 
 goodness is being, the only absolutely-existing being. All 
 
 1 [Goettling, Diogenes der Kyniker oder die Philosophie des grieschi- 
 schen Proletariats (Geschichtl Abhandlgn., vol. I.), Halle, 1851. — Tr.] 
 
 2 Diog. L., IT. [Ptitter and Preller, pp. 223 ff. ; Mallet, Histoire de 
 Ve'cole de Megare, etc., Paris, 1845. — Tr.]
 
 PLATO 75 
 
 we know of Euclides is summed up in this sentence. But 
 this alone assures liim a distinguished place among the Attic 
 pliilosophers ; his system forms the connecting link between 
 Socrates and Plato. The school of Megara, which Stilpo ^ 
 made famous, and that of Elis, which was founded by 
 Phtedo,2 the favorite pupil of Socrates, devoted themselves 
 to the development of eristic dialectics, hut soon found 
 themselves eclipsed by the schools of Plato, Aristotle, 
 Epicurus, and Zeno. 
 
 During the first period, philosophical interest was cen- 
 tered upon nature and the problem of becoming. vSpec- 
 ulative Socraticism inaugurates tlie era of the philosophy 
 of mind, which predominates in the second period, and 
 in turn becomes (A) idealism, (B) materialism and eudae- 
 monism, and (C) concrete spiritualism, according as it re- 
 gards as the essence and highest aim of our being, thought 
 (Plato and Aristotle), sensation (Epicurus), or voluntary 
 action (Stoicism). 
 
 A. Negation of Matter. Apotheosis of Thought 
 
 § 16. Plato 
 
 Plato of Athens was born of a noble family, about 427. 
 He received his first instruction from Cratylus, the disciple 
 of Heraclitus, then became a pupil of Socrates, and later of 
 Euclides of Megara, who introduced him to the study of 
 Parmenides. The mathematical speculations of the Pytha- 
 goreans also exerted a decided influence upon the develop- 
 ment of his thought. From 385 to the close of his life 
 (347), he taught philosophy in the Academy, a place which 
 was presented to him by generous friends and for centuries 
 remained in possession of the Platonic school. 
 
 1 Diog. L., TT. ; Seneca, Ep. IX. 
 « Diog. L., loc. cit.
 
 76 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 It is not a matter of indifference, says a great writer,^ by 
 which door we enter life. Socrates, the child of a family 
 of artisans and himself an artisan during liis younger days, 
 took pleasure in mingling with the crowd whose follies he 
 despised, and endeavored to instruct, elevate, and ennoble 
 them. Plato, the descendant of Codrus and of Solon, was 
 by birth predestined to become the author of the aristocratic 
 Republic^ the idealistic philosopher, for whom form is every- 
 thing and matter a contamination, an obstacle, and a 
 check ; the poet-prophet who will have nothing to do 
 with vulgar reality, and whose home is in the realms of the 
 eternal, the absolute, and the ideal ; the favorite teacher of 
 the Fathers of the Church, the theosophists, and the mys- 
 tics. Socrates exercises a somewhat prosy cautiousness in 
 his thought. He is not willing to take any risks, he avoids 
 hypothesis and the unknown. The philosophy of Plato is 
 conspicuous for its bold imprudence, its love of adventure 
 and mystery. His speculation is not like the Philistine 
 whose life is spent in the market-place or in the workshop, 
 and whose world is measured by the narrow boundaries of 
 his native town ; it is the lord of the manor, who retires to 
 his mansion, after having seen the world, and turns his 
 gaze towards the distant horizon ; disdaining the noise of 
 the cross-roads, he mingles only in the best society, where 
 is heard the most elegant, the noblest, and the loftiest 
 language that has ever been spoken in the home of the 
 Muses. 
 
 Plato is the oldest Greek pliilosopher whose wi'itings 
 have been preserved, and the only one of whom we possess 
 the complete works.^ Of the treatises attributed to him by 
 
 1 Goethe. 
 
 ' The principal modern editions of Plato's Complete Works : The 
 Bipontine edition, Zweibriicken, 1781-87 ; Tauchnitz, Leipsic, 1813 ff. ; 
 Bekker, Berlin, 1816-23, London, 1826 ; F. Ast, Leipsic, 1819-32 ; 
 Stallbaum, Leipsic, 1821 ff. ; Baiter, Orelli, and Winckelmann, Zurich,
 
 PLATO 77 
 
 tradition some are surely spurious ; others, like the Par- 
 7nenides, the SopJiist, the Crati/lus, and the Philehiis, are 
 of doubtful origin. Criticism has also, but without just 
 grounds, questioned the authorship of the Apology and the 
 Crito. The writings whose genuineness is beyond doubt 
 are nine in number, namely: (1) The Phcednis, which 
 opposes the selfish rhetoric of the Sopliists with the true 
 eloquence of the philosopher, whose chief object is the 
 knowledge of the invisible world; (2) the Protagoras, or 
 the Socratic doctrine of virtue ; (3) the Spnposiuin, or con- 
 cerning the different manifestations of the eras, from sensual 
 love to the philosopliical love of beauty, truth, and good- 
 ness, as tills was personified in Socrates ; (4) the Grorc/ias, 
 the true sage as opposed to the Sophist ; (5) the Republic, 
 or concerning the State which realizes the idea of justice ; 
 (6) the Timceus, or concerning the nature and origin of the 
 
 1839-i2; Ch. Schneider (Greek and Latin), Paris, 1846-56 ff . ; K. F- 
 Hermann, Leipsic, 1851-53 ; [Schanz, Leipsic, 1875 ff. Ritter and 
 Preller, pp. 233 ff.]. 
 
 {The Dialofjues of Plato. Translated into English, with Analyses and 
 Introductions, by B. Jowett, 4 vols., Oxford, 1871 ; 3d ed. revised and 
 corrected, 5 vols., New York and London, 1892 ; Platans Werke, Ger- 
 man transl. by Sclileiennacher, 3d ed., Berlin, 1855-62 ; also by II. 
 Miiller, 8 vols., Leipsic, 1850-66. — Ti?.] ; Plato's T-For^-s, French transl. 
 by V. Cousin, 8 vols., Paris, 1825-40. 
 
 For Plato and his writings, consult: [Ast, Platans Lehen und 
 Schriflen, Leipsic, 1816 ; K. F. Ilerinanu, Geschichle und System der 
 platonischen Philosophie, Heidelberg, 18:59]; Grote, Plato and the other 
 Companions of Socrates, 3 vols., London, 1865 [new ed. 1885], also the 
 same author's History of Greece : Schaarschmidt, Die Saiiimlung der 
 platonischen Schriflen, Bonn, 1800 ; Fouilloe, La philosophie de Platan. 
 Exposition, histoire, et crilirpie de In thi'orie des idc'es, 2d od., Paris, 1SS8-S9 ; 
 [Chaignot, La vie et Ics ccrits de Platan, Paris, 1871 ; Benard, Platan. 
 Sa philosojthie, pre'ce'de'e d'un aperfu de sa vie et de ses e'crits, Paris, 1892; 
 Huit, La vie et Voeuvre de Plalon, 2 vols., Paris, 1893 ; Pater, Plato and 
 Platonism, Xew York and London, 1893 ; Van Oordt, Plato and his 
 Times, Oxford and the Hague, 1895; B. Bosanquel, A Companion to 
 Plato s Republic, New York, 189.5J.
 
 78 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 world ; (7) the Thecetetus, or concerning knowledge and 
 Ideas ; (8) the Phcedo, or concerning the innnortality of the 
 soul ; (9) the Laius^ a work which seems to be a partial 
 retraction of the Republic. These treatises are dialogues.^ 
 Socrates is the cliief spokesman in the majority of them, 
 and his speeches reflect the author's thought most faith- 
 fully. His use of the dialogue-form enables Plato to 
 present us with his own philosophy as well as with the his- 
 tory of its origin, or the manner in which it arose among 
 the Socratics. It is true, the dialogue-form may perhaps 
 be objected to on the ground that it hinders us from ob- 
 taining a comprehensive view of the author's philosophy ; 
 indeed, the statement has been made that it is so diilicult 
 to systematize Plato's teachings because of his use of the 
 dialogue. The reverse seems to be the case ; in our opin- 
 ion Plato employs this form precisely because he has no 
 finished system like Plotinus, Spinoza, and Hegel. The 
 dialogue might be regarded as an unsuitable method of 
 exposition in case it concealed the philosopher's thoughts. 
 But it hides nothing ; form and content are here the same, 
 and the dialogues of Plato present his philosophy in its 
 psychological development.^ 
 
 A real difficulty, however, arises from the frequent use 
 of myths and allegories. Plato employs them, either in 
 order to assist his readers in understanding abstract truths, 
 or in order to mislead the fanatical democracy as to 
 
 1 Regarding the difficult question as to the cln-ouological order of 
 the dialogues of Plato, consult the Introductions of Schleiermacher, the 
 German translator of Plato, and the investigations of Socher, Ast, 
 K. F. Hermann, Bonitz, Zeller, Susemihl, Suckow, Munck, Ueberweg, 
 [Schaarschmidt, Teichmiiller, and Siebeck ; also, Horn, Platonstudien, 
 Vienna, 1893. — Tr.]. 
 
 2 Concerning the genesis of Platonism, see Karl Joel, Zur Erhennt- 
 niss der geistigen Entwickelung und der schriffstHlerischen Motive Plato's, 
 Berlin, 1887 (reviewed by M. Reinach in the Revue critique, Aug. 22, 
 1887).
 
 PLATO 79 
 
 Ids religious convictions,^ or, finally, in order to hide the 
 contradictions of his thought and to escape philosophical 
 criticism by seeking refuge in the licence of the poet. 
 Most of the Platonic myths are mere allegories, which, 
 as the author himself cautions us, must be taken for what 
 they are worth. Some of them, however, seem to express 
 the philosopher's real views. Hence the difficulty which 
 we experience in the Timceus and the Phccdo, of distinguish- 
 ing clearly between the pedagogical element and the teach- 
 ino- itself, between the accidental and the essential, between 
 the poetical symbol and the real meaning. Though Plato 
 himself gives us an allegorical exposition of the drama of 
 creation in his Timceus, does it therefore follow that the 
 idea of creation is absolutely foreign to his mind ? When 
 he speaks of a creator and follows popular fancy in pictur- 
 ino- him as a human workman, does that mean that theism 
 is not the essential element of his thought ? The Fhcedo, 
 too, is full of mythological allegories, but who would have 
 the boldness to declare, with Hegel, that Plato assumed 
 pre-existence and immortality only for the world-soul and 
 the divine vov<; ? We must, in choosing between the idea 
 and the form, — a delicate and rather difficult task, — avoid 
 two contrary conceptions, both of which our historical sense 
 would compel us to reject. In the first place, we must not 
 be deceived by Plato's symbolism ; we must not lay too 
 much stress on what is but a literary form, and mistake 
 mere figures of speech for the hidden meaning of things. 
 But we must also abandon the notion that Plato was too 
 great a man to be influenced in liis reason by the imagi- 
 nation. We have no right to make liim a Christian or a 
 mo(k'rn philosopher. It is un(h)ubt(Mlly true that Catholic 
 mysticism borrows extensively from Platonic theology, and 
 it is equally certain that Plato's dialectics contain the rudi- 
 
 » Timceus, 28 C, 29 C-D.
 
 80 GREEK THILOSOPHY 
 
 ments of the Hegelian system. But twenty centuries of 
 development lie between the sowing of the seed and the 
 full fruition, and we cannot identify the beginning and the 
 end without anachronism. It is not enough to point out 
 that the future is contained in the past ; we must also in- 
 dicate in what form it is found there, and show that this is 
 not the final stage of evolution. 
 
 Plato is the product of Heraclitian, Socratic, and Italian 
 philosophy. With the school of Heraclitus he believes that 
 the visible universe is in a state of perpetual change, that 
 the senses are deceptive and cannot yield us truth, that the 
 immutable does not exist in the world of sense, but in the 
 world of ideas. From Socrates he learned that though we 
 cannot know the ultimate principles of the universe, we can 
 at least know ourselves, and that we can attain to a knowl- 
 edge of the highest good through an infallible inner sense. 
 But Socrates remained a sceptic as far as metaphysics 
 vas concerned. The Italic philosophy induced Plato to 
 take a decisive step. In the Pythagorean and Eleatic 
 systems he finds the inner sense (of Socrates) proclaimed, 
 not only as the moral conscience and practical reason, 
 but as theoretical reason, capable of revealing to us the 
 absolute, eternal, and necessary essence of things. In 
 mathematics and its self-evident axioms he discovers the 
 most powerful weapon against the Trdvra pel, in the 
 sense in which Cratylus and the Sophists applied the 
 principle. Geometry made a particularly deep impres- 
 sion upon him : the geometrical method served as a model 
 for his metaphysics. Indeed, he even borrowed his philo- 
 sophical vocabulary from tliis science. Geometry is based 
 on a 2^rio7-i intuitions ; lines, triangles, circles, and spheres, 
 are ideal figures or intelligible realities ; their properties 
 remain the same forever, and survive all the changes of 
 the material world which reflects them. It is a rational 
 science and has nothing to do with sense-perception, of
 
 PLATO 81 
 
 which its trutlis are absolutely independent. Hence Plato's 
 pliilosophy is, like mathematics^ the only self-evident and 
 necessary science, a science of a priori intuition and rea- 
 soning. Because of their resemblance to the principles of 
 geometry, these a priori intuitions, upon which the sys- 
 tem is grounded, are called Ideas (etS?;, ISeai), or unchano-e- 
 able forms, or the eternal types of fleeting thino-s, or nou- 
 mena (voov/xeva), the objects of true science {eTnan^ixri) as 
 distinguished from phenomena, the objects of sense-percep- 
 tion (atadrjaa) and opinion {86^a). The philosophy of Plato 
 is the science of Ideas. It is called dialectics after its new 
 method. To this science of first principles, which is the 
 fundamental and only science worthy of the name, is added 
 the iheori/ of nature {cj^vaiKi]). The latter, however, is of 
 secondary importance, and does not deserve the name of 
 science. Ethics, or the science of the liighest good, is the 
 last branch of dialectics and the crown of philosoph3\ 
 
 Hence we have to consider with Plato : (1) The Idea as 
 such ; (2) the Idea acting upon matter as a plastic principle, 
 or nature ; and (3) the Idea as the final goal of nature, or 
 the highest good. 
 
 1. The IdeaI 
 
 "Wlien we compare the mother who gives up her life for 
 her child, the warrior aaIio dies in defence of his country, 
 and the philosopher wlio sacrifices himself for his convic- 
 tions, we notice a similarity in their actions ; they have 
 the same common trait, and reproduce one and the same 
 type, — the Idea of t])e good. Wlien we compare a mas- 
 terpiece of areliitecture or of scidpture with a tragedy of 
 Sophocles and a beautiful human form, we discover in 
 
 ' For Plato's dialectics and idoolopy, see especially the Thetxtetus 
 (lol ff.), the Sophut (218 ff.), the Philehus (15, 54, 58 if), Parmenides 
 (130 ff.), and the Rfjmhlic (especially books VI. and VII.). 
 
 6
 
 82 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 these apparently different objects a common trait, — beauty, 
 or the Idea of the beautifuL When we compare the indi- 
 *viduals of a species, say the human race, we find in them 
 a number of qualities common to all, an identical type ; 
 these common characteristics, or the type whicli is repro- 
 duced in all, constitute man-in-himself {avTodv6p(07ro<i), or 
 the Idea of man. Finally, when we compare all the beings 
 perceived by our senses, we notice that all have this in 
 common : they exist or do not exist, they move or are at 
 rest, they are identical or they differ from each other. 
 Now, tliis heing, shared ])y all, this non-being, or movement, 
 or rest, or identity, or difference, is what Plato calls the 
 Idea of being, the Idea of movement, etc. Hence he un- 
 derstands by the term Ideas {eiSi], IBeat) : (1) what modern 
 philosophy calls laws of thouglit, morality, or taste (ISeaL) ; 
 (2) what Aristotle calls categories, or the general forms by 
 means of which we conceive things, and which are em- 
 braced under the preceding class {yevr]) ; (3) what natural 
 science calls types, species, or, as Plato would say. Ideas 
 (etBi] proper). In short, he means by Ideas all possible 
 generalizations ; there are as many of them as there are 
 common names. Every common name designates an Idea, 
 as every proper name designates an individual. The 
 senses reveal particulars, or natural objects ; abstraction 
 and generalization {eTrayco'yy]) give us Ideas. 
 
 The great mission of Socrates was to form general ideas. 
 But, like the sensationalistic school, which he opposed in 
 other respects, Socrates simply regarded these ideas as 
 thoughts or concepts of the mind {ivvorjixara). At this point 
 Plato shows his originality. According to sensualism, our 
 sense-perceptions alone represent real beings existing out- 
 side of us. According to Plato, general notions or concepts 
 also represent realities, and these realities, these objects of 
 our notions, which sensualism denies, he calls leleas. Ideas 
 are to our notions what natural objects are to our sense-
 
 PLATO 83 
 
 perceptions : they are their objective causes. The objects 
 which the deceptive and vulgar organs of sense present to 
 us ^ve regard as real objects ; while the Ideas which we 
 acquire through reason, the messenger of the gods, are 
 looked upon by us as fleeting shadows that come and go 
 with self-consciousness ! If we consider sensible objects 
 as real, how much greater reason have we to assume the 
 reality of the objects of the intellect ! The general Ideas, 
 expressed by our concepts. Good, Being, Identity, Man, 
 etc., are therefore realities. Hence the name realism was 
 inaptly applied to mediasval Platonism, which is diametri- 
 cally opposed to modern realism. Platonic realism is 
 thorough-going idealism, the theory which conceives Ideas 
 as real beings. 
 
 What ! Shall we say. Ideas are real beings ; the Idea of 
 being, more real than being ; the Idea of the sun as real 
 and even more real than the sun which shines upon us 
 from the heavens ; the Idea of man as real, and even much 
 more real than Socrates, Antisthencs, and Euclides ! Com- 
 mon-sense rebels against such paradoxes. Socrates I see, 
 but I do not see the man-type ; I see beautiful men, beau- 
 tiful statues, and beautiful paintings ; I do not see the 
 beautiful as such. I see moving bodies; I do not see 
 motion as such, or the Idea of movement; I see livinpf 
 beings, but being or life in itself I cannot see anywhere. 
 All these generalizations exist only in my mind, and have 
 nothing real corresponding to them. Plato answers such 
 objections by saying that when the sensualist sees beauti- 
 ful o])jects and just acts, and fails to perceive beauty as 
 such, or justice as such, it is because he has tlie sense for 
 the former, wIiIIl- liis sense for Ideas or liis reason is at 
 fault. If this were suiricicntl}- developed, it would no 
 longer see tlie real reality {rh optco'; ov) in material exist- 
 ence, but in till; Ideas; it Wdiild lodk f(ir reality, not in 
 the world of sense, l)Ut in the intelligible world. We
 
 84 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 consider general Ideas as the mental copies of sensible 
 beings, whose reality we assume. The reverse is true; 
 the Ideas are the models or the originals, and the natural 
 beings or the incUviduals are the copies. The Ideas are 
 both our thoughts (Koyot) and the eternal objects (to, ovra) 
 of these thoughts ; they are the thoughts of God, which no 
 human intelligence can wholly reproduce, but which are 
 none the less real, absolutely real. 
 
 Let us take the Idea of the beautiful, or beauty absolute 
 (avrb TO KaXov). For the sensationalist, the beautiful, like the 
 good and the just, is a quality which Ave abstract in thought 
 (abstrahere') from the sensible objects, and which does not 
 exist apart from these objects. For Plato, the beautiful is 
 a reality^ ; it is not only real, but much more real than all 
 the beautiful things put together. Whatever endures is 
 more lasting and therefore more iral than that which 
 passes away. Now, every beautiful object, be it a man or 
 a statue, an act or an individual, is doomed to destruction 
 and oblivion ; Icauty in itself is imperishable. Hence it 
 must be more real than all the things the sensationalist calls 
 beautiful. So, too, the type of man is more real than the 
 particular man, because it remains unchanged, while the 
 individual passes away ; the Idea of the tree or flower is 
 more real than a 'particidar tree or a 'particular floM^er, 
 because it endures. The Idea is what it expresses ; it is 
 this ahsolutely and without qualification ; all we can say of 
 the sensible object is that it has sometliing of what the 
 Idea is, tliat it 2jarta'kes of it (yLieTe;^ei), while the Idea is 
 undivided being. 
 
 Let us again inquire into tlie beautiful, which is Plato's 
 favorite Idea,^ and which he loves to identify with the 
 good. Its manifestations in the sensible world are only 
 relatively beautiful, that is, as compared Avith ugly objects ; 
 
 1 Symposium, 211ff.
 
 PLATO 85 
 
 they are not beautiful wlien we compare them with more 
 beautiful things. They are fair to-day, foul to-morrow; 
 fair at one place, or in one relation, or in one point of view, 
 or to one person ; foul under different circumstances and 
 in the judgment of other persons. Hence ever;y'thing in the 
 world of phenomenal beauty is relative, fleeting, and uncer- 
 tain. Ideal beauty {avro to koKov) is ever-lasting; without 
 beginning and without end ; without diminution and v/ith- 
 out decay; invariable, innnutable, and absolute {ixovoeihh 
 ael 6v) ; it is beautiful in all its relations and from all 
 points of view ; it is beautiful at all times and in all places 
 and for all persons; it is pure and clear and unalloyed, 
 and therefore transcends the powers of the imagination 
 {el\iKpLve<i, d/xtKTov^ KaOapov). It is neither a mere notion 
 nor purely individual knowledge {ou8e rU Xo'709 ovSe rh 
 i7riaT)]fJLr]'), but an eternal reality. 
 
 Wliat is true of the beautiful is true of the great and the 
 small, and of all Ideas in general. Simmias is tall as com- 
 pared with Socrates, but small by the side of Phaedo. The 
 Idea of the great is great in all points of view ; it is abso- 
 lutely great. Hence to sum up: (1) The Ideas are real 
 beings; (2) the Ideas are more real than the o])jects of 
 sense ; (-3) the Ideas are the onli/ true realities ; the ob- 
 jects of sense possess a merely borrowed existence, a 
 reality which they receive from the Ideas. Tlie Ideas 
 are the eternal patterns (TrapaSeiyfiaTa) after which the 
 things of sense are made ; the latter are the images 
 (eiScoXa), the imitations, the im[)erfect copies (ofioiMixara, 
 fj,L/xT]a€L<; ^). The entire sensible world is nothing but a 
 symbol, an allegory, or a figure of speech. The mean- 
 ing, the Idea expressed by the thing, alone concerns the 
 philosopher. His interest in the sensi])le world is like 
 our interest in tlie iK)rtrait of a friend of whose living 
 presence we arc drpiiviMl, 
 
 * Puniicnides, \'-i2; Tiiiucus, ^H.
 
 86 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The world of sense is the copy of the workl of Ideas ; 
 and conversely, the world of Ideas resembles its image ; it 
 forms a hierarchy. In our visible world there is a grada- 
 tion of beings from the most imperfect creature to the 
 perfect, sensible being, or the universe. The same holds 
 true of the intelligible realm or the pattern of the world ; 
 the Ideas are joined together by means of other Ideas of a 
 higher order ; the latter, in turn, are embraced under others 
 still more exalted, and so on ; the Ideas constantly inci'ease 
 in generality and force, until we reach the top, the last, the 
 highest, the most powerful Idea or the Good, which com- 
 j)rehends, contains, or summarizes the entire system, just 
 as the visible universe, its copy, comprehends, contains, or 
 summarizes all creatures. The relation existing between 
 the Ideas and the highest Idea is analogous to that exist- 
 ing betv/een objects of sense and Ideas. The objects, as 
 we have said, fartahe, of the Ideas which they express ; ^ 
 they exist, not in themselves, but as reflections of their 
 Ideas ; they have no reality other than that which they 
 receive from these Ideas ; they are, in short, to these Ideas 
 what accidents are to substances. Similarly, the Ideas of 
 a lower order exist by themselves and as substances, only 
 as compared to their visible copies. As compared to the 
 highest Ideas, they cease to be substances ; they become 
 modes of the only really ahsohite Idea, the Idea of the 
 Good ; in the presence of tliis sun of the intelligible 
 world, their individuality passes away as the stars vanish 
 at the coming of the orb of day. 
 
 Hence the Ideas are both individual or self-existent 
 atoms and members of a higher unity. Plato liimself 
 emphasizes the principle of the unity and connection 
 of Ideas at the expense of their indiAdduality ; his dis- 
 ciples, on the other hand, seem to lay more stress on the 
 
 1 Phcedo, 100.
 
 PLATO 87 
 
 atomic and hypostatic character of the Ideas than on their 
 unit}'.! The clear and transparent Ideas of the master are, 
 to use a figure of speech, precipitated by the scliool, and 
 the Lyceum consequently censures the Academy for adding 
 to the material world another wholly useless material 
 world. The Ideas of Plato form a unity or an organism ; 
 they live a common life ; and it is utterly impossible to 
 separate them from each other and to make chstinct beings 
 of them.2 Indeed, they are independent of all time and 
 space, that is, of the principle of separation and individuali- 
 zation. It is true, Plato speaks of the heavens as their 
 abode, whither we must rise in order to contemplate them 
 in their thvine purity .^ But tliis heaven is not a part of 
 the physical universe. The home of the Ideas is not the 
 same as that of the things {aladrird^ tottos:) ; it is sui gen- 
 eris, a place suitable to tlie nature of the Ideas, an ideal, 
 intelligible jDlace {voi]To<i totto^) ; the home of the Ideas is 
 mind (z^oO?), that is, the Idea as such. The Idea has no 
 place outside of itself ; it does not, like the atoms of Demo- 
 critus, exist by virtue of empty space, but by itself {avro 
 Kad^ avTo). A prouder challenge could not be hurled at 
 materialism : Space which you conceive as a condition of 
 reality is quite the reverse ; it is the cause of non-being 
 and impotence. The Idea is real because it is one and 
 unextended, and because unity is force, power, or reality. 
 Now, that which is concentrated in the Idea as in a mathe- 
 matical point, is distributed in space and time, scat- 
 tered over a thousand places and a thousand different 
 moments, and conseciuently enfeebled, impoverished, and 
 
 1 This substantialization of the Ideas is already noticeable in the 
 Sophist, and has been regarded by some as an argnment against tlie 
 genuineness of the dialogue. (See Schaarschniidt, in the work cited 
 above.) 
 
 2 Mpho, 81. 
 
 « Phvedrus, 2i7. •
 
 88 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 relatively destroyed (m 6v). Compared with the Idea, 
 which you regard as a poor reflection of the real world, 
 your supposed real world is itself but an Idea in the 
 vulgar sense which you attach to the word, that is, a 
 shadow, a nothing. The world is the relative; the Idea, 
 the absolute (/ca^' avro 6v). 
 
 If the Idea is the absolute, what is God, to whom Plato 
 often refers, and, as it seems, refers in different senses, 
 sometimes using the plural, sometimes the singular ? In 
 the Timccus,^ the Creator (6 Bi]ixLovpy6^) is spoken of as the 
 eternal God (cSv ael Oeo'i, 6 6e6<i) ; his immediate creatures 
 (the stars and the celestial spirits) are called 6eoi\ Oeol 6eo)v, 
 ovpdvLov deo)v yevo<i ; while the sensible universe is a god in 
 process of becoming {iaofjievo^ 6e6<;). Evidently, the god who 
 is to be and the created divinities are accommodations to 
 official polytheism, and the Creator is the only true God. 
 But even this highest God does not seem to be absolute ; in 
 creating the universe he contemplates the eternal (to athiov)^ 
 wliieh serves as his model. Now, the Idea or the Good is 
 the eternal. Hence the Creator is dependent on the Idea as 
 the copyist depends on the pattern which he follows. In 
 order that the Creator may be the Supreme Being or the 
 absolute, the model must be the Idea in itself or the Good 
 personified. The assumption of an intermediate principle 
 is apparently a necessary consequence of Plato's dualism 
 between Idea and matter, while the conception of the 
 Demiurge as a workman following a pattern forms a part 
 of the mythical element in the narrative ; the Creator and 
 the pattern of creation are merged in the creative Idea, of 
 which the Demiurge is the poetical personification. God 
 and the Idea are so closely identified in Plato that it seems 
 at times as though God depended on the Idea, at others, as 
 though the Idea sprang from God as the eternal source of 
 
 * Timceus, 28, 34, 41, passiin.
 
 PLATO 89 
 
 all things. Since God is sometimes represented as below 
 and sometimes as above the Idea, nothing is left to us but 
 to take the middle ground and to say that the God of Plato 
 is neither inferior nor superior to the Idea, but that he 
 coincides with it, or that he is the Idea itself, considered 
 as an active, plastic, and creative principle. That the 
 Platonic school identified God with the absolute Idea may 
 be readily inferred from the attributes which are ascribed 
 to the Good and to the Suj)reme Being. A brief compari- 
 son will suffice to convince us of this fact. The absolute 
 Idea (the Good, the One) is the lord of the spiritual world, 
 as the sun is the lord of the visible world.^ It even exceeds 
 being and essence in dignity and power.^ It is the uni- 
 versal author of all things beautiful and right, parent of 
 light and of the lord of light in this visible world, and the 
 immediate source of reason and truth in the intellectual. 
 On the other hand, the God of gotls is represented to us as 
 the eternal cause of the good in the world ; as the supreme 
 wisdom, by the side of wliich all human philosophy is im- 
 perfect ; as the supreme justice, law-giver, and liighest law, 
 who rules the beginning, the end, and the middle of tilings ; 
 as the pure reason which has nothing to do with matter or 
 witli evil.-'^ Hence, tliere cannot be the least doubt that the 
 God of Plato is the aljsolute Idea of the good. Does that 
 mean that because his god is an Idea he is not a reality ? 
 On the contrary; because he is an Idea, and nothing hut 
 an Idea^ he is the liighest reality ; for, from Plato's point 
 of view, the Idea only is real. 
 
 Now the Idea docs not exist in space proper, but in the 
 
 1 Republic, YI, 508 D. 
 
 * OvK oiaias ovroi tov ayadov aX\ fVt fntKdva Trjs ovcrias npccr^da 
 Koi bvvdiid vnfpixovToi- 
 
 ' Re/jufjiic, VI, 500 ff. ; VII, 517: TlavTibu avrfj (fj tov dya6ov 18(a) 
 6f)6(ou T( Koi KoXSiv aiTia . . . ovrrUi ai8ioi rfj? t uyndov (i)viTfCLii (ilrui . . . tp 
 T( rtjiuTd rfiCjs . . . TfKoiaa, iv t( i/o/jro) . . . dXrjdfun', khi vuvv napa<rx(>fi(vr].
 
 90 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 intelligence which is its natural and, in a certain sense, its 
 native abode. It cannot, therefore, come to us from with- 
 out,^ and it is a mistake to derive it from sensation. The 
 absolute Idea, and with it all the other Ideas, are original 
 endowments of the mind ; they form its very essence. But 
 they are at first latent in the mind, and Ave are not con- 
 scious of them. The senses show us their external copies, 
 and, to a certain extent, remind us of the originals existing 
 in us {avdfxvT]aL<;). Sensation pi'ovoJces Ideas ; it does not 
 produce them. Its function consists in recalling to our 
 minds the a priori Ideas which we possess without susjDect- 
 ing it. Moreover, the senses are deceptive ; and instead of 
 revealing the truth, they keep it from us. Reasoning 
 {v6r](n<i) is the only road to truth ; and this springs from 
 love {ep(o<i). The love of truth is but a particular form of 
 universal love. The homesick soul, living in exile in the 
 world of sense, fervently longs to be united with the ab- 
 solute, to come face to face with the principle of light and 
 truth. Tliis pure and holy desire seeks for satisfaction 
 in earthly emotions, in friendship and aesthetic pleasure. ^ 
 But the human embodiments of the Idea, or the material 
 incorj)orations of the Idea in art, do not satisfy it. It has 
 need of the pure Idea, and this it strives to contemplate 
 directly or immediately by means of pure thought. The 
 enthusiasm of the lover and the artist is but a feeble begin- 
 ning of the enthusiasm felt by the pliilosopher in the pres- 
 ence of unveiled truth, ideal beauty, and absolute goodness. 
 
 ^ Strictly speaking, it is not even correct to say: it cannot come to 
 MS, etc. ; we should say : the knowledge of the Idea, the notio/i {\6yos:) 
 cannot come to us, etc. ; for the Idea exists independently of the notions 
 of our mind ; it is ovbe t\s \6yos ov8e ema-rfjfir] (p. 85) ; it neither 
 comes nor goes ; all that comes to the mind, or becomes, or is formed, 
 or is developed, is simply our concepts (ewo^/xara), which, like the 
 sensible things, are but shadowy copies of the eternal Ideas. — (Alle- 
 gory of the Cave, Rep. VII.) 
 
 ^ PhcBdrus, 242 ft.
 
 PLATO 91 
 
 Moreover, the philosopher need not boast of having attained 
 this ideal goal, for absolute truth is in God alone.^ God, 
 who has absolute truth because he is absolute truth, and 
 the uncultured man, who does not even suspect its exist- 
 ence, do not search for truth ; the love of truth [<^L\oao(^Ca) 
 is peculiar to the man who is filled with light from on 
 high. 
 
 In spite of its mjstical character, Plato's method is 
 rationalistic in the strict sense of the term. There is no 
 contracUction between the terms mystical and rationalistic. 
 Rationalism and mysticism are extremes that meet. In 
 fact, idealistic rationalism, and the deductive method pecu- 
 liar to it, invariably presuppose as their starting-point the 
 immecUate and a priori perception of an absolute principle, 
 a perception wliich we call mystical, precisely because it is 
 immediate and unanalyzable. Platonic idealism, like its 
 offshoots, the systems of Plotinus, Spinoza, and SchelUng, 
 begins with a mystical act and culminates in a religion.^ 
 
 2. Natuee 
 
 The transition from Idea to being, from metaphysics to 
 physics, is not easy for Plato. If the Idea is self-sufficient, 
 and if the intelligible world is a system of perfect beings^ 
 what is the use of a sensible reality, that must of necessity 
 be imperfect, alongside of the Idea ? What is the use of a 
 material world that is inevitably doomed to evil ? What is 
 the use of copies by the side of the original, of copies that 
 cannot reproduce it in its divine purity ? The real world 
 is evidently as great a source of trouble to Plato as it 
 was to Parmenides. It cannot be explained by the Idea 
 
 * Phcedrus, 278 : To fxtv aofpuv . . . ifxoiyt y^tya dvai boKfl tcai 6t<ji 
 1X09(0 ■npinfi.v. 
 
 * See Ilartmann, Philosophy of the Unconscious (translated hy E. G 
 Thomas), the chapter entitled : On tlic Uuconscioua in Mysticism.
 
 92 GREEK PHILOSOrHY 
 
 alone, but presupposes a second princii^le, ^A'hich is no less 
 real than mind: matter. Hence, when you assume the 
 reality of the sensible world, you abandon the absolute 
 monism of the Idea ; you confess that the Idea constitutes 
 only a part of reality, and make concessions to sensualism 
 and materialism. And yet the sensible world exists ; it is 
 an undeniable and stubborn fact that has to be explained. 
 Though full of imperfections, it is, after all, a sublime work 
 of art, whose infinite harmonies inspire the idealist as well 
 as the materialist with feelings of delight. The mind of 
 man cannot wholly unravel the mysteries of the universe. 
 Nevertheless, he should investigate it to the best of his 
 ability, and untiringly search for a satisfactory solution of 
 the problem. Plato finds the key to the answer in the con- 
 ception of divine goodness ; this enables his thought to 
 pass from the ideal to the real.^ The Idea is the absolute 
 good ; God is sujDreme goodness. Now the good or good- 
 ness cannot but create the good. God is life, and life 
 must create life. Hence God must create ; the Idea must 
 reproduce itself. 
 
 Inasmuch as the Idea is the only reality, there is notliing 
 outside of it but non-being {firj 6v). But, in so far as it is 
 the highest reality, it is also the highest activity, the heing 
 that communicates itself to non-being. Hence, the Idea 
 becomes a creator, a cause, a will, or a plastic principle 
 in reference to non-being ; so that non-being in turn be- 
 comes like being [tocovto tl olov ro 6V), and takes part in 
 the absolute existence of the Idea (Koivcovia, fiede^i-i). 
 The non-being thus becomes the first matter out of which 
 the Idea forms, after its own image, the most perfect, 
 divine, and finished visible world possible : it becomes mat- 
 ter (vXr]), as Plato's successors would say. According to 
 Plato and idealism, matter is notliing corporeal; it is 
 something that may become so, through the plastic action 
 1 Timceus, 29 E.
 
 PLATO 93 
 
 of tlie Idea. The body is a determinate, limited, qualified, 
 and qualifiable thing; matter, considered as such and 
 apart from the forms which the Idea impresses upon it, is 
 the unlimited itself {to aireipov) ; it is devoid of all positive 
 attributes, and cannot therefore be designated by any posi- 
 tive term, since every term cletermines ; it is the indefinable 
 (aopLarov), the formless (afiop(f}ov), the imperceptible [aopa- 
 Tov). But though in itself indeterminate, formless, and 
 imperceptible, it may, through the plastic action of the 
 Idea, receive all possible forms and determinations {irav- 
 Se%e9) ; it may become the mother of all sensible things 
 Qiv (p yiyverai ro jLyvofxevov, ra vdvra Sexofi^vr]), the uni- 
 versal recipient {8e^a/j.ev7]). It is identical with space and 
 the place filled by bodies (j(a>pa^ totto'^'^'). It is not the 
 product of the Idea, the creature of God, for : (1) Being 
 cannot produce non-being, and matter is non-being (/x?) 6V); 
 (2) creation is action ; now, all action presupposes an oljject 
 to be acted upon, or an object which suffers action (ttci- 
 (Txov) ; hence the divine activity presupposes matter, and 
 does not create it. iMatter is the condition of the creative 
 activity of the Idea (avvaiTLov)^ and therefore co-eternal 
 with God. The eternity of matter does not detract from 
 the supreme majesty of the Idea {^aatXeia) ; the Idea con- 
 tinues to remain the highest being, while the eternal exists 
 ence of matter is equivalent to eternal non-being. 
 
 But though eternal matter docs not limit llie Idea, which 
 as such is absolute, it does, none {he less, limit its operation 
 in the universe. INIatter is both the conditic^n sine qua non 
 of the action of the Idea and its eternal obstruction. It 
 is both the indispensable auxiliary and the irreconcilable 
 foe of tlie creative Idea. True, it is passive, but its pas- 
 
 ^ Ai'istotlf, Ph>/x., IV. 2: Aio Ktu YIXutcov tt/u vXt]u koi Trjv ^^aypav 
 aiiTO (Lr](Tiv (ivai (P tu Tifitiico • . • Ofian mv ti'itto:' kcu rrjv ^ojjxiv to avro 
 anffpfivaro. Cf. C. Ha;uinker, Das Problrm tier Mulifrie in <lcr (jriechl 
 schen rhilu.iophie, Miiiister, 1890.
 
 94 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 sivity does not consist in absolute non-interference. Its 
 cooperation is resistance. It is formless and unlimited, 
 and therefore opposes and resists the form, limitation, 
 and finish which the eternal artist desires to give it ; 
 this resistance manifests itself as inertia, weight, dispro- 
 portion, ugliness, or stupitUty. It is non-being or the 
 perpetual negation of being, and consequently opposes and 
 resists everything positive, stable, and immutable, and for- 
 ever destroys the works of God. It is the primary cause 
 of the imperfection of things, of physical and moral evil, 
 as well as of their instability, their constant change, and of 
 all that is uncertain, perishable, and mortal in them. 
 
 From the union of the ideal or paternal principle with 
 the material or maternal principle springs the cosmos, the 
 only son and image of the invisible Divinity (uto? /lovoyevj]^, 
 etKoiiv Tov Oeov), the god that is to be (ia-o/jievo^ ^eo'?), the 
 visible god {aladrjTO's 6e6^), Avhose relative perfection re- 
 minds us of the Father of the Universe {7ron]T7]'i koX irarrip 
 TOV iravTo^)^ the living animal (^«oi^), that reproduces, as 
 faithfully as it can, the eternal ideal animal {^wov alhiov). 
 This cosmos has (1) a body (a-co/xa) governed by necessity 
 (avdyKi]) ; (2) a rational content, a purpose, or a meaning 
 (yoO?, ^a)ov evvovv), a final goal for which it was made, an 
 end to realize (reXo^;) ; and finally (3) a soul {■^vXHi ^"^^^ 
 €/x'^v')(^ov)y the mysterious link which unites the contrary 
 principles in the cosmos, and whose function it is to sub- 
 ordinate the material world to the Idea, or to subject brutal 
 necessity to reason, to adapt it to the final purpose of the 
 Creator. The body of the universe has the sliape of a 
 sphere, which is the most beautiful form imaginable, 
 and makes the world the most faithful image of its in- 
 telligil)le archetype. It revolves upon its own axis and 
 thus constantly returns to itself; hence it executes the 
 most perfect movement, a movement which of all possible 
 movements is most appropriate to the eternal repose of the
 
 PLATO 95 
 
 Idea and best symbolizes its immutability. It is perfect 
 (reXeov) and not liable to old age (ayijpcov) and disease 
 (avoaov) ; for it comprehends all the forces of nature, and 
 nothing outside of it can hiu't or destroy it. The universe 
 cannot be eternal like the creative Idea ; hence God makes 
 it eternal, so far as this is possible ; that is, he creates end- 
 less time. The vov<; or mind of the universe, that is, the 
 purpose revealed in its organization, or, in short, its final 
 cause, is the most perfect possible reproduction (or as we 
 should say nowadays, realization) of the Idea of the Good. 
 Finally, the soul of the world consists of Number, which 
 subjects chaotic matter to the laws of harmony and propor- 
 tion (avaXoyLo)} 
 
 Atomistic materialism rejects final causes, and therefore 
 opposes the' view that the world has a meaning, or that 
 it realizes an idea. Platonic idealism takes the vov<i of 
 Anaxagoras seriously, and explains the creation of the 
 world wholly from the teleological point of view. It 
 acknowledges the existence of physical causes, but it sub- 
 ordinates them to final causes ; the former are tlie means 
 or involuntary instruments of the latter. Thus, the ele- 
 ments, in regard to which Plato follows Empedocles, are 
 explained teleologically : fire, as a means of vision, earth, 
 as a means of tactile perception. Two other elements are 
 needed as intermediaries between these two extremes, that 
 is, four in all, because the number four represents corporeal- 
 ity. We have seen how Plato (who, like all true Pytha- 
 goreans, is a geometrician above ever^-thing else) identifies 
 matter and extension ; he is therefore forced, with the 
 Eleatics, to reject the void, which, according to Democritus, 
 exists alongside of matter. Since matter is identical with 
 space, and since space is universally the same, the substances 
 composing it are not heterogeneous, as Anaxagoras claimed ; 
 the spaces, considered apart from their content, differ only 
 » Tim(eus, 28 H, 31 C, 31 A, 39 D, 41 A, 92 B.
 
 96 GKEEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 in their outward form, or in figure. In this case Plato, 
 who usually follows Pythagoras, involuntarily agrees with 
 Leucippus and Democritus. Matter is divided into homo- 
 geneous corpuscles of different shapes. Only, these figures 
 are not accidental like the forms of the atoms ; they are 
 absolutely geometrical, that is, ideal, final, and providen- 
 tial. The solid element is composed of cubes ; water, 
 of icosahedrons ; air, of octahedrons ; and ether, of 
 pyramids. 
 
 After fashioning the first matter with a view to its ulti- 
 mate structure, the divine architect created the stars, first 
 the fixed stars, then the planets, and then the earth ; all 
 these beings are created gods and therefore mortal in 
 themselves ; they were, however, endowed with immortal- 
 ity through the goodness of the Creator. At his command, 
 these divinities, particularly the earth, the most venerable 
 of all, produced organized beings, and, chief among these, 
 man, the paragon of creation, for whom everything on earth 
 was made. Plants were formed 171 order to nourish him, ani- 
 mals, in order to serve as a habitation for fallen human souls. 
 Woman herself is a degeneration of man, the first-born 
 son of Earth. Man is the epitome of the macrocosm ; his 
 soul is endowed with reason and then incorporated in a 
 body. Everything in this body is arranged according to a 
 fixed plan and for a rational end. The head is the seat of 
 reason and therefore round ; because this form is the most 
 perfect of all and alone worthy of what is perfect. It is 
 placed at the top of the body in order to direct the entire 
 organism. The body has legs for locomotion, and arms 
 with which to take hold of things. The breast is the seat 
 of the noble passions ; it is placed beneath the head in order 
 that these passions may be under the rule of reason, but 
 separated from the head by the neck, so as not to be identi- 
 fied with it. Finally, the coarser appetites reside in tlie 
 abdomen and are separated from the noble passions by the
 
 PLATO 97 
 
 diaphragm. In order to i subject them to the rule of reason 
 and the noljler passions, nature phiced in this region the 
 liver, a smooth, bright organ, wliich resembles a mirror and 
 is intended to reflect the images of thoughts. It is com- 
 posed of bitter and sweet substances ; by means of the 
 former it restrains the disordered cravings, and discharges 
 the latter when our desires conform to reason ; at certain 
 times it also acquires the power of divination. Finally, 
 there is also a moral reason for the great length of the in- 
 testine which is coiled around itself ; this hinders the food 
 from passing tlirough the body too quickly, and conse- 
 quently keeps the soul from having a constant and immod- 
 erate desire for food, a desire which would stifle in it the 
 love of wisdom and the voice of conscience. In short, the 
 human body is, according to Platonism, a house of correc- 
 tion and education, constructed and organized Avith a view 
 to the moral perfection of the soul. 
 
 The human soul, like the soul of the world from which 
 it emanates, contains immortal elements and mortal ele- 
 ments ; or rather, it combines them ; it is the union of the 
 two, or the proportion according to which these two kinds 
 of elements (Idea and matter) are united in the individual. 
 Intelligence or reason {to Xoyta-riKov /^epo?) is the immortal 
 part ; sensuality {to iin6v[xr}TLK6v\ the mortal part, because 
 it essentially depends on corporeal life ; will, energy, or 
 courage (to ^u/zoetSe'?), is the union of the two, and consti- 
 tutes the soul proper and its individuality. Tlie iniinor- 
 tality of the intelligent soul follows: (l)from its simplicity, 
 whicli renders all decomposition impossible ; (2) from the 
 
 1 All these data are taken from tlio Timmus. We have reproduced 
 them here and italicized these in order to's and for the purpos^e nf's, 
 simply to give the reader a classical saiii]>le of tlu! theory of final 
 causes in its apitlication to nature. Thoujrh the theory contains a 
 spark of truth, it has for centuries impeded the progress of the phy- 
 sical sciences, by substituting the dreams of fancy for the observation 
 of facts. * 
 
 I
 
 98 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 goodness of the Creator ; (3) from the fact that it is the 
 very principle of hfe, and a transition from being into non- 
 being is impossible. The immortality of the intelligent 
 soul is also proved by the philosopher's desire to be freed 
 from the body and its fetters, and to come into direct com- 
 munion with the intelligible world ; by the fact that life 
 invariably and universally produces death, and death, a 
 new life ; by the pre-existence of the soul, which is demon- 
 strated by the doctrine of avdfjLvr]at,<; (if the soul has existed 
 before the body, why should it not exist after its decom- 
 position?); by the relation existing between the soul and 
 the Ideas (it conceives the intelligible, and must therefore 
 be homogeneous with it and akin to it, that is, immortal, 
 like its object) ; and finally, by the fact that it controls the 
 body, which would be inconceivable if, as some Pythago- 
 reans claim, it were but the resultant of the bodily func- 
 tions. Immortality, however, is the prerogative of reason. 
 The eTndvfirjTLKov cannot lay claim to it, and the will 
 itself, in so far as it is bound to the organism, has no part 
 in it.i 
 
 In so far as the problem of the soul borders upon physics, 
 it cannot be solved with absolute certainty. There is no 
 science of passing things. The only certain science is the 
 science of Ideas ; for Ideas alone are eternal and necessary. 
 In the domain of physics we must content ourselves with 
 probabilities ; science (eTnarrnxr}^ being impossible here, we 
 are reduced to faith (Trio-Tt?).^ 
 
 3. The Highest Good 
 
 Man is the end of nature, and the Idea the end of man. 
 As a consistent idealist, Plato, like Antisthenes and the 
 Cynics, finds the highest good, not in pleasure, but in 
 man's most perfect likeness to God. Now, since God is 
 
 1 Phcedo, 61-107. ' ^ Timceus, 51, 52.
 
 PLATO 09 
 
 the Good or absolute Justice, we can resemble him only in 
 justice (SiKaLoavurj). It is impossible, says Socrates-Plato,^ 
 that evils should pass away (for there must always remain 
 something which is antagonistic to good). Having no place 
 among the gods in heaven (ef ^eoi?), of necessity they 
 hover around the mortal nature and tliis earthly sphere 
 (rovSe rov tgttov TrepnroXel i^ avd'yK7]^). Wherefore we 
 ought to fly away from earth to heaven as quickly as we 
 can (^XPV ^pOevSe eKelae (f)evy6Lv on rd^iaTa), and to fly away 
 is to become like God, as far as this is possible {(f>vy7] Se 
 6fioLQ}at<; TO) dew Kara to Swarov). Now God is never in 
 any way unrighteous ; he is perfect righteousness ; and he 
 of us who is the most righteous is most like him.^ Justice 
 is the fundamental virtue, the mother of the virtues belong- 
 ing to each of the thrSe souls. For the intelligence it con- 
 sists in the correctness of thought {ao(f)ia, (f)iXoao(f){a) ; for 
 the will, in courage (avSpia) ; for the sensibilit}', in temper- 
 ance {(Tco^poavvrf) . Wisdom is the justice of the mind; 
 courage, the justice of the heart; temperance, the justice 
 of tlie senses. Piety (ocnoTri^) is justice in our relation 
 with the Deity ; it is synonymous with justice in general. 
 
 i\Ian must be educated in order to attain justice and 
 thi'ough it to become like God. He can never realize this 
 virtue in isolation. Justice, or tlie final goal of things, is 
 realized only in the collective man or in the State (-TroXt?). 
 Plato's ideal State, like the individual, embraces three parts 
 or separate classes: (1) the philosophers, who constitute the 
 legislative and executive power, the intelligence and the 
 head of the State, or tlie ruling class; (2) the warriors, 
 who are the heart of the State, or the militant class ; 
 (8) tlie merchants, artisans, agriculturists, and slaves, or 
 the servant class, who correspond to the sensual soul, 
 which is restricted to the lower ])arts of the human 
 body. Wisdom Ijclongs to the ruling chuss ; courage to 
 » Theatetus, 170. « Republic, X., G13.
 
 100 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the niilitaiy class ; obedience to the two higher classes, 
 who think and fight for them, belongs to the laboring, 
 commercial, and serving classes. In order that the col- 
 lective man or the State may form a real unity or an 
 individual on the large scale, particular interests must be 
 merged in the general interest, the family must be absorbed 
 in the State, the individual must cease to be a proprietor. 
 Henceforth the children belong to the State only, which 
 forms one large family .^ The State is the father of the 
 children ; the State also educates them. Up to the age of 
 three, the education of the child consists solely in caring 
 for the body. From three to six, its moral education is 
 anticipated by the narration of myths. From seven to ten, 
 gymnastics. From eleven to thirteen, reading and writing. 
 From fourteen to sixteen, poetry and* music. From sixteen 
 to eighteen, mathematics. From eighteen to twenty, mili- 
 tary exercises. When the twentieth year is reached, the 
 State makes its first selection among the young people, 
 choosing such as are fitted for the military career, and 
 such as are qualified for the government. The latter make 
 a thorough study of the different sciences until they are 
 thirty years old. At the age of thirty, a second selection is 
 made. The least distinguished enter upon the secondary 
 positions of the administration ; the others continue the 
 study of dialectics for a number of years, and crown their 
 education with ethics. After they have been introduced 
 to the knowledge of the highest Good, they are capable of 
 assuming the most exalted duties of the State. The latter 
 is essentially a pedagogical institution, whose mission is to 
 realize Goodness Eind Justice on our earth, and will not, 
 therefore, tolerate art itself, except in so far as art is a 
 
 ^ This arrangement might seem strange to us, did we not remem- 
 ber that the Greek State simply consisted of the city. Furthermore, 
 the communistic teachings of the Republic are not repeated in the 
 Laivs.
 
 PLATO 101 
 
 means of education, and is employed in the service of the 
 Good.i 
 
 These deductions, wliieh are idealistic in the extreme, 
 bring us back to the ontology of Plato. Reality, it must be 
 remembered, does not, according to him, belong to sense- 
 objects (or phenomena), but to the Ideas or types which 
 these ol)jects reproduce and which are perceived (conceived) 
 by reason (the noumena). The phenomenon is real, only 
 in so far as it partakes of the ideal type of which it is a 
 copy. Now, the highest Idea, which is to the world of in- 
 visible realities what the sun is to the phenomenal uni- 
 verse, is the Good or absolute Goodness, the fu'st and final 
 cause of all being, and consequently superior and anterior 
 to being itself, which it creates by natural radiation. 
 
 Tills ontology may be defined as the monism of the good. 
 It is, undoubtedly, the sublimest and purest product of 
 pliilosophical genius. Others may have advanced beyond 
 it ; no one has ever excelled it. Kant himself, who denies 
 real existence to the phenomenon, making it conditional on 
 sensibility and the intellect, and then proclaims practical 
 reason as the judge of theory, and goodness as the judge 
 of truth, is in reality but a reproduction of Plato minus the 
 poetical element. Modern science is nominalistic ; never- 
 theless it regards realism as relatively true. The real ob- 
 ject of science is the general, tlie universal, or the ty[)ical 
 law of the particular facts. Thus, when the anthropolo- 
 gist occupies himself with Peter and Paul, his ol)ject is 
 to know what man is ; and the physicist's interest in 
 the apple that falls from the tree, or in tlie snow-flake 
 that floats in the air, or in the sinking avalanche, is occa- 
 sioned by the fact that tliese particular phenomena serve 
 t() exemplify his theory of weight. The modern scientist, 
 
 1 Hence tlie theatre is not permitteil in Plato's cominonwealth ; 
 for it set* before us a world in which good and evil are necessarily 
 intermingled. — (/^/>u/y., III., .OfH-lOj.)
 
 102 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 like Plato, regards the phenomenon as changing, the law 
 as stable and therefore moi-e real than the particulars (jo 
 6vT(o<i 6v). The mistake does not lie in exalting the uni- 
 versal over the particular ; it consists in separating the 
 former from the latter metaphysically, and in making a 
 transcendent entity of the genus or type ; it does not 
 consist in exalting vov<; over at'o-^T/cri?, but in making 
 two separate and even incompatible principles of vov<; and 
 atadrjaL'i. In themselves, the type and the individual 
 which realizes it, the law and the phenomenon wdiich is 
 its ap[)lication, are but one and the same reality considered 
 from different points of view ; observation and reasoning 
 are merely two stages of one and the same method. A 
 physic, a physiology, or an anatomy that is the creation of 
 pure reason is inconceivable. The universal must be de- 
 rived from the particular, because it cannot be found any- 
 where else. Plato's failure to escape the illusion that the 
 Idea is something separate, real, and transcendent, is in part 
 due to the imperfect state of the philosophical terminology 
 of his time. If, in place of elSo? (aspect, form, type), he had 
 used the word w'/^o?, or law, the term with which modern 
 science has become so familiar, he would not easily have 
 fallen into the error of the separatisfic conception. But it 
 is not merely the terminology that misleads him ; it is the 
 poet in Plato that impels the philosopher to realize the 
 Idea. Aristotle, in a spirit of controversy, and a few sin- 
 cere but unintelligent disciiDles of Plato, exaggerated the 
 realism of the master, but the realism is there none the 
 less,^ and its consequences are only too aj)parent. The 
 Idea is real in itself, and does not need to be realized. 
 Then the cosmic process loses its raison d'etre ; it no longer 
 consists in the realization of an Idea ; it is the fall of a god. 
 Creation would be the overflowing of the Idea, as it were, 
 and the generation of being, that is, according to Plato, 
 1 See especially Repub., VI, 509.
 
 PLATO 103 
 
 of spii-itual being, thought, or intelligence ; for the being 
 wliich comes from the Idea must "■ resemble " it as the 
 son resembles his mother. Beinc/, in the real and absolute 
 sense of the term, and being-mind (thought) are one and 
 the same thing, from tliis point of view. Tliis explanation 
 of the v.'orld, which, to tell the truth, is but a figure of 
 speech, would perhaps suffice, if the world were actually a 
 society of pure spirits, the abode of goodness, justice, and 
 perfection. But it is a mixture of being and non-being, of 
 spirituality and corporeality, of good and evil. Whence 
 comes this second constitutive element of the phenomenon, 
 this non-being f From the Idea ? Impossible. The Idea 
 can create nothing but being, intelligence, and goodness. 
 Hence, a second principle that is co-eternal with the Idea 
 has participated in the creation of the world ; the monism 
 of the good becomes a dualism of Idea and matter. By 
 coming in contact with the latter, the Idea, or rather in- 
 telligence, its offspring, is polluted, diminished, and im- 
 poverished. Hence, intelligence must consider matter as 
 its natural enemy, as the chief cause of its diminution, as 
 the seat and the principle of evil ; the mind will, of course, 
 desire to be freed, as soon as possible, from the body which 
 holds it in bondage, and from the visible world, which is a 
 prison, a place of correction. The Uto})ian system of poli- 
 tics, wliich sacrifices nature to an al)stract principle, asceti- 
 cism, monachism, the horror of matter which we find among 
 the Neo-Platonists, the Gnostics, and even Catliolics, all 
 these elements are the logical consequences of a conception 
 that makes the Idea a reality. 
 
 Speusippus, the successor of Plato in the Academy (347- 
 339), seems to see the need of combining the One (the Idea) 
 and the many (matter) by means of a concrete princi})le 
 that contains them l;otli. He lays great weight on tlie 
 P}'thag(uean notion of emanation, devck)})ment, and scries, 
 wliich forms the very essence of 2seo-I*lalonism, luid teaches,
 
 104 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 in opposition to Plato, that perfection is to be found, not in 
 the original and abstract unity, but in the developed, differ- 
 entiated, and organized unity. ^ But his reverence for the 
 name of Plato, and the position which he held as the 
 scliolarch of the school hindered him from subjecting the 
 master's view to an impartial criticism.^ The same is 
 true of Xenocrates, Polemo, Grantor, and Crates, who 
 were succeeded by the sceptic Arcesilaus.^ It was left 
 to Aristotle, the most distinguished among the pupils 
 of Plato and the founder of a new school, to criticise 
 and reform Academic idealism from the standpoint of 
 concrete spiritualism. 
 
 § 17. Aristotle 
 
 APvISTOTLE,* was born at Stagira, not far from Mount 
 Athos, in 385. His father, Nicomachus, the physician 
 
 * Aristotle, Met., XII, 7 : To KaWiaTov Km to apiarov fir] iv ap^rj fivat. 
 
 Cf. § 65. 
 
 2 Cicero, Acad, post., I, 9, 3i. 
 
 3 See § 21. [For the Platonic school, see Diog. L., IV, ch. 1-5; 
 Mullach, vol. Ill, pp. 51 ff.; Ritter and Preller, pp. 283 ff. For 
 further references, see Ueberweg-Heinze, I, § 44. — Tr.]. 
 
 * Aristotle's Complete Works ; the Berlin edition in 5 vols. : vols. 
 I. and II., the Greek text (rec. Imm. Bekker, 1831) ; vol. III., a Latin 
 translation (1831) ; vol. IV., the principal commentaries (coll. by 
 Chr. Aug. Brandis, 1836) ; vol. V., fragments and commentaries (coll. 
 by V. Rose), Index Aristotelicus ed. H. Bonitz, 1870 ; the Didot edition, 
 5 vols., Paris, 1848-70; Tauchnitz edition, 1831-32, 1843; [Aristotle's 
 Psychology, in Greek and English, with introduction and notes, E. 
 Wallace, Cambridge, 1882 ; Nicomachean Ethics, transl., with an anal- 
 ysis and critical notes, by J. E. C. Welldon, Xew York and London, 
 1892 ; transl. also by Williams, Hid., 1876, Chase, ibid., 1877, Hatch, 
 ibid., 1879, Peters, ibid., 1881, Gillies (Sir John Lubbock's Hundred 
 Books), ibid., 1892; Politics, transl. by Welldon, Cambridge, 1888, 
 Jowett, 2 vols., Oxford, 1885-88, Ellis, with an introduction by H. 
 !MorIey (Sir John Lubbock's Hundred Books), London, 1802 ; On the 
 Constitution of Athens, transl. and annotated by F. G. Kenyon, Lon-
 
 ARISTOTLE 105 
 
 of King Amyntas of ]MacedoD, came from a family of 
 physicians. The blood of experimentalists and positive 
 scientists flowed in his veins. In the year 367, he 
 entered upon liis course of study (as we should say now- 
 adays) at Athens, where he became lii'st a pupil and then 
 the successful rival of the veteran Plato. From 343 to 
 340, he was the teacher of Alexander, the son of Pliilip. 
 The friendship betw^een him and Alexander proved advan- 
 tageous to Aristotle, for it enabled liim to accumulate vast 
 collections, and contributed largely toward making him the 
 father of natural science. In 334 he began to teach his 
 pliilosophy in the walks of the Lyceum at Athens ; hence 
 the name applied to his school, and the epithet given to liis 
 disciples, — Peripatetics. After the deatli of Alexander, he 
 was accused of Macedonianism and atheism, and compelled 
 to retire to Chalcliis, in the island of Euboea, where he 
 died in 322. 
 
 don, 1891 ; Poetics, transl. by Wharton, Cambridge, 1883 ; Rhetoric, 
 transl. by Welldon, London and Xew York, 1886 ; translations of 
 the above and of the Metapliy^oi, Organon, and History of Animals in 
 the Bohn Lil)rary; editions of the Politics, -with introduction by 
 Kewman, 2 vols., Oxford, 1887, of tlie Ethics, by A. Grant, 2 vols., 
 4th ed., London, 1884, and Bywater, Oxford, 1894; German transla- 
 tions of Ai-istotle in Metzler's collection, Hoffmann's Uebersetzungs- 
 hibliulhek, Engelmann's collection, and in Kirchmann's Philosophical 
 Library. — Tu.]. The Metaphysics has been translated into French 
 by Pierron and Zdvort, 2 vols., Paris, 1840; the Politics, Logic, Ethics, 
 Poetics, and Meteorology, by Barthelemy Saint-IIilaire, Paris, 1837-62. 
 [For the philosophy of Aristotle, see Biese, Die Philosophic cles Aris- 
 toteles,2 vols., Berlin, 18:35-42 ; A. Posmini-Serbati, 'Arislotele esposto 
 ed esaminato, Turin, 1858; Bonitz, Aristolelische Studien, I.-V., Vienna 
 1«(;2-6G; I-K3\ves, Aristotle,. Loudon, 1864; Grote, Aristotle, ed. by A. 
 Bain and G. C. Robertson, 2 vols, (incomplete), London, 1872, 3d ed., 
 1884; E. Wallace, Outlines of the Philosophy of Aristotle, Oxford, 1875, 
 3d ed., 188:5; A. Grant, Aristotle (in Ancient Classics for English 
 Rf'(idirs), Edinburgii and London, 1878; David.son, Aristotle and An- 
 cient Ednrational Ideals, New York, 1892; Kappes, Aristolclcs-Lcxikon, 
 Paderborn, 1894. — Tit.]
 
 106 GREEK PHlLOSOrHY 
 
 The writings attributed to Aristotle deal with almost all 
 the sciences known to antiquity, that is, according to the 
 philosopher's own classification,^ with the theoretical sci- 
 ences, which have truth for their oliject (mathematics, 
 physics, and theology, or the fii-st philosophy), with the 
 practical sciences, which treat of the useful (ethics, politics, 
 etc.), and with the j^oetical sciences, whose object is the 
 beautiful. The Categories, the Be interjyretatione, the two 
 Analytics, the Topics, etc., which have been collected under 
 the name Organon, make Aristotle the real founder of logic. 
 True, he was not the first to conceive all the principles 
 of logic ; the discussions of the Eleatics, the Sophists, and 
 the Socratics, have shown us how reason gradually be- 
 came conscious of. the processes winch it originally em- 
 ployed instinctively ; thus the elementary axioms, such 
 as the principle of contradiction, the principle of sufficient 
 reason, the imncipium e.rclusi tertii, the dictum de oiiini et 
 nullo, and without doubt also the more special rules of the 
 syllogism came to be formulated. But it required the 
 genius of an Aristotle to co-ordinate these elements, to 
 complete them, and to formulate them into the system of 
 deductive logic, wliich constitutes his chief claim to fame.^ 
 The physical and natural sciences are ably set forth in the 
 Physics, the De coslo, the De generatione et corruptione, the 
 Meteorology, the De anima, the Parva naturalia, the His- 
 tory of Animals, the treatises On the Parts of Animals, 
 On the Progression of Animals, On the Generation of 
 Animals, etc. The problems of philosophy proper are 
 discussed in a number of writings on first principles, 
 which a hiacncevaari^'i collected into a single work com- 
 
 ^ Metaphysics, VI., 1, 9. 
 
 ^ For Aristotle's logic, see Trendelenburg, Elementa logices Aristote- 
 lece, Berlin, 183G ; 8th ed., 1878. lEiiduterungen, 3d ed., Berlin, 1876 ; 
 Prantl, Geschlchte de?- Logik, vol. I. ; Eucken, Die Methode der aristote- 
 lischen Forschung, Berlin, 1872. — Tu.]
 
 ARISTOTLE 107 
 
 prising fourteen books, and placed after the writings on 
 2)Jii/sics (^fxera ra ^vaLKo) : hence the name metaphysics^ 
 wliich has since been applied to pliilosophy proper, a term 
 with which Aristotle liimself was not acquainted. Ethics 
 and politics are treated in the Nicomacheaii Elhics,, in the 
 Magna moralia, in the Eudemean Ethics, in the eight books 
 of the Politics. Rhetoric and poetry are discussed in the 
 books known by those titles. Taken altogether, the 
 works of Aristotle constitute a veritable encyclopedia 
 of the knowledge possessed by the fourth century before 
 Chi'ist.i 
 
 Philosophy is defined by Aristotle as the science of uni- 
 versals (^ kuOoXou iina-T'qiJLr]). Every real science is, or at 
 least aims to be, a view of the whole, a general theoiy ; 
 hence the special sciences are partial i^hilosoiyhics {c^lKo- 
 ao(f>iai), as well as general theories concerning one or more 
 groups of given facts, theories which are summarized and 
 systematized by general philosophy. Conversely, philo- 
 sophy proper or the fii'st science {Trpcorr] cf)L\ocro(j)ia) is a 
 separate science ; it is co-ordinated with other sciences 
 (second philosophy), and has a distinct subject-matter of 
 its own: being as such, the absolute or God. But it is 
 at the same time the universal science embracing all the 
 specialties, because its object, God, embraces and contains 
 the principles of all the sciences and the first causes of 
 
 ^ For the lost works, see E. Heitz, Die verlorenen Schriften des Ari- 
 stoteles, Leipsic, 18G5, and Fragmenta ArUtotelis, collegit ]En\. Ileitz, 
 Paris, 1809. One, whose loss was much to be deplored, the treatise 
 On the Constitution of Athens, lias recently been found (January, 1891) 
 on a papyrus in the British Museum. Some of the extant works are 
 mutilated and form a confused mixture of genuine texts and sjiurious 
 commentaries. Some, like the Caterjories, the De tnterprelntione, the 
 treatise De Melisso, Xenophane et Gorgia, the Eudemean Ethics, etc., 
 are doubtful. Others, at bust, like the De motu auimnlium, the (f)v(rio- 
 yvufjUKtl. the (J'Jconoinics, tlie Rhetoric to Alexander, etc., are certainly 
 bpurious.
 
 108 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 everything that exists (?; tmv Trpoircov apx^v kuI uItlcov 
 decoprjTiKr])} 
 
 There was no doubt in Aristotle's mind as to the pos- 
 sibility of science, which had been denied by the Sophists 
 and the Sceptics. Man is the only being who partakes of 
 the active intellect, that is, of God himself, and tln-ough 
 him of the knowledge of the absolute ; man alone is en- 
 dowed with speech. By means of language, we designate 
 {KaTTjyopov/xev) things as we conceive them ; by reason, 
 we conceive them as they are. The general ways of 
 designating things, or the parts of discourse (the categories 
 of language and of grammar), correspond to the different 
 forms according to Avhich we conceive them, or to the cate- 
 gories of the understanding (substance, quantity, quality, 
 relation, place, time, position, mode of being, activity, pas- 
 sivity), and these categories of the understanding in their 
 turn signify the modes of being of the things themselves 
 (icaT'q'yoptai. rov 6vto<;) ; that is, the things are in reality 
 either substances or quantities or relations, etc., and are 
 not merely conceived as such.^ 
 
 1. First Philosophy ^ 
 
 The mathematical and physical sciences treat of the 
 ■ quantity, quality, and relations of things ; the first philo- 
 
 1 Met. I., 2, 14. Cf. L, 8 ; L, 10. 
 
 2 Met. v., 7 ; VI., 4. 
 
 3 For the Metaphysics, consult [Schwegler, Die Metaphi/sik des Ari- 
 stoleles (text, translation, and commentary), 4 vols., Leipsic, 1847-49] ; 
 II. Bonitz, In Arisiotelis Metuphysica, 2 vols., Berlin, 1848-49; C. L. 
 Michelet, Examen critique de Vouvrage d'Aristote intitule' Metaphysiqiie, 
 Paris, 1836 ; Vacherot, Theorie des premiers principes suivant Aristute, 
 Paris, 1837 ; Felix Ravaisson, Essai sur la metaphysique d^Arislote, Paris, 
 1837 ; Jacques, Aristoie considere' comme hislorien de la philosophie, Paris, 
 1837; Jules Simon, Etudes sur la thcodicee de Platon et d'Aristote, Pa- 
 ris, 1840 ; [Glaser, Die MetapJiysik des Aristoteles, Berlin, 1841 ; Bar- 
 thelemy Saint-Hilaire, De la metaphysique, etc., Paris, 1879 ; Bullinger, 
 Aristoteles' Metaphysik, Munich, 1892, — Tk.].
 
 ARISTOTLE 109 
 
 soph}- lias as its object the queen of tlie categories, the 
 category of substance {ovaCa), to which all the rest are re- 
 lated and on which they are based. It inquires into the 
 nature of being as such, regardless of all relations of time, 
 place, etc. {to ti rjv elvai), that is, absolute and necessary 
 being, the eternal essence of things as opposed to the rela- 
 tive, contingent, and accidental.^ 
 
 Hence Plato is light in regarding it as the science o^^ 
 real being (ro 6vt(o<; qv), as distinguished from that which 
 appears to he, and is in reality but a passing relation. He 
 errs in conceiving the Ideas as real beings existing apart 
 from the individuals which express them (IBeai ')(Q3pi(jTaL). 
 In vain do we search in Plato's writings for the proof 
 that Ideas subsist apart from tilings. Moreover, it is 
 hard to see what this theory accomplishes. It does not 
 solve the metaphysical problem, but merely complicates it 
 by adding to the real world a world of useless homonyms. 
 The separate Ideas do not, in fact, contribute either towards 
 the production, or the preservation, or the science of things 
 (et? yvcoaiv). We are at a loss to know what is the rela- 
 tion lietween things and Ideas (rpoiro^ /cad^ ov rdXXa ck 
 Twv eihoiv eariv). The assertion that the Ideas are pat- 
 terns and that the things participate in them is to speak 
 vain words, and to utter poetic metaphors {ro he Xe'yeiv 
 TrapaSeiyfiara elvai kuI fi€T€)(^€iv avroiv raWa KevoXoyeiv 
 iarl Kal fxeTa^opa'i Xeyeiv 7roL7]TiKd'i). Besides, if tlie gen- 
 eral Idea is the substance of the particulars or the essence 
 of the things, how can it exist apart from that of whicli it 
 is the substance and the essence (x^pt? t7]v ovaiav Kal ov 77 
 ovaia)? The general cannot exist outside of and along- 
 side of the particular {to kuOoXov p-ij eari tl irapa tcl Kad^ 
 eKucTTa). Hence the Ideas or spccilic types, cf)nsi(leied as 
 siicli and aijart fi'om the tilings, are not real beings or sul)- 
 btances {ovaiai), if we understand l)y ovaia that wliich exists 
 1 Mei.\\.,\; XL, 4, 7.
 
 110 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 by itself. 1 Aristotle does not, however, deny the objective 
 existence of species. For him as well as for Plato, the 
 general Idea is the essence of the i:)articular, and may 
 be called ovaia^ in so far as this word signifies essence. 
 What he denies is that Ideas exist apart from things 
 {')(a)p(,<i). The Idea is inherent or immanent in the thing ; 
 it is its form^ and cannot be separated from it except by 
 abstraction. It is the essence of the particular and with 
 it constitutes an indivisible whole. For the ev Trapa ra 
 iroWd we must substitute the ev Kara tcov ttoWmv or 
 iv Tol'i TToXXot?.^ 
 
 On the other hand, the materialistic theory is equally 
 untenable. JNlatter has no reality apart from the form 
 (eZSo?, /jLop^T], that is, not only the shape, length, breadth, 
 and height of the thing, but all of its properties). Mattel" 
 without the Idea is as much of an abstraction as the Idea 
 apart from the particular object which realizes it. Nor does 
 movement exist by itself ; it presupposes a substratum. 
 Hence, neither the Idea nor matter nor movement has real 
 or substantial existence ; reality consists of all these taken 
 as a whole (a-vvoXov), or of the particular (ro'Se tl). Reality 
 is a concrete thing {iilktov) ; it contains constitutive ele- 
 ments, which thought distinguishes, but which do not exist 
 apart from each other. The most important (KvpLoiTepov) of 
 these elements is the Idea or the form, whicli Aristotle con- 
 ceives as identical with essence or soul. Matter is merely 
 its support, but it is an indispensable support. 
 
 The next question is, What are the generative causes of 
 real being ? All tilings which are produced either by nature 
 or art have a material cause (vXrj, vTroKei/xevov), a formal 
 cause (to elSo?, ro tl ian, to tL r]V elvai), an efficient or 
 moving cause (ap^V '^V'^ jeveaecoi;, ap-)(r} tt]^ KLVi^aeco';, to odev 
 rj Kivrjcn^i to odev r/ ap')(r) t>}9 KLVqaew'i, to aiTLOV Tr]<i fxeTU' 
 
 1 Met, I., 9, 15, 16; V., 8, U; XIL, 10, 22; XIV., 3, 12, 4, 9. 
 
 2 Met, III., 4, 1 ; Analyt. post., I., 11.
 
 ARISTOTLE 111 
 
 yi9oX^9, TO KLvovv^ TO KLvqTLKov), and a final cause {to ov eveKa, 
 TO TeXa, Tctjadov).^ Tims, to take an example from art. A 
 bed or a statue presupposes (1) matter : the wood or the 
 marble or the brass of which the thing is made ; (2) an 
 Idea (a plan or a pattern) according to which it is made ; 
 the idea of the statue exists in the mind of the sculptor, 
 the idea of the bed, in the mind of the joiner ; (3) arms, 
 hands, and tools, as motive forces and efficient causes j 
 (4) a purpose or motive that sets these forces in action, 
 and effects the transition from capacity or potentiality 
 (SvvajjLi^) to actuality (ivepyeLa). The same is true of 
 nature and particulaily of organic nature. A living 
 organism, as, for example, a man, is the product of the 
 following four causes : (1) the substance wliich forms the 
 starting-point and substratum of the embryonic develop- 
 ment ; (2) the Idea or specific tj'pe according to which the 
 embryo is developed, the form which it tends to assume ; 
 (3) the act of generation ; (4) the (unconscious) j^urpose of 
 this act, namely, the production of a new man. There are, 
 then, for every fact and for the universal fact itself (the 
 world), four kinds of causes : matter. Idea, force, and the 
 final purpose. Through the cooperation of these four prin- 
 ciples, the real being, be it an object of art or a living 
 being, is produced. These principles, moreover, do not 
 subsist as substances ; the}^ always inhere in a particular 
 thing : every natural product is preceded by an individual 
 of tlie same species, from which it is generated. Similarly, 
 every phenomenon in art and ethics presupposes an actual 
 cause. Each man is educated Ijy another educated man ; 
 the efficient cause is always a concrete being, and that 
 wliich exists potentially becomes actual, only through the 
 instrumentality of some actual thing. 
 
 Though philo8oi>hieal reflection distinguishes four gener- 
 ative principles of tilings, three of thorn, the Idea, the 
 
 » Met. I, :i. Cf. Vil., 7. IT.
 
 112 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 motive cause, and the final cause, are very often identified, 
 and constitute but a single principle (e/a^erai 8e to, rpia ek 
 TO ev TToXXaKt^). Thus, in art, the Idea of Hermes in the 
 imagination of the sculptor, moves his nerves and muscles, 
 and at the same time constitutes the end which he aims 
 to realize by means of matter. Take an illustration from 
 nature. A man is to be produced. 3Ian is the Idea which 
 is realized by generation ; a man realizes it, and he realizes 
 it in order to reproduce man (^rb fiev yap tl ian koI to ov 
 eveKa ev ecrri, to 8' o6ev t) KivriaL^ tm etSei tuvto tovtol<; ^). 
 In both cases the Idea is the formal cause, the motive 
 c^use, and the final cause. 
 
 There are then, ultimately, only two principles of things, 
 — the Idea or for7n which causes them and at which they 
 aim, and the matter of which they are made: elSo? and 
 vXi]. The former is essential and the cause proper; the 
 latter is of secondary importance and a mere condition 
 (avvaiTLov). Since these two principles are the necessary 
 antecedents of all becoming, they cannot have been pro- 
 duced themseWes ; for in that case they would have had to 
 exist even 'prior to being, which is impossible. They neces- 
 sarily precede all generation, since generation is possible 
 only through them.^ Both Aristotle and Plato regard mat- 
 ter and form as eternal ; only, the Stagirite does not con- 
 ceive the eternity of matter to mean absolute dualism. If 
 matter and Idea are diametrically opposed to each other, as 
 they seem to be in Plato, how can they ever be united, how 
 can they co-operate and produce all things ? Tilings that 
 are diametrically opposed cannot be united {airaOi) fyap tcl 
 kvavTia {nr aA,Xr;X&)V •'^). 
 
 Plato's yu.77 ov^ that is to say, non-being or absolute priva- 
 tion {aT€priaL<i)^ and real matter are two entirely different 
 things. Matter is accidental non-being (kuto, (TV/ji^e/3i]K6<;), 
 whereas privation is non-being as such. The conception of 
 
 1 Phys., II., 7. 2 Id., I., 10, 8. 8 3Iet., XII., 10, 7.
 
 ARISTOTLE 113 
 
 matter is one tliat is closely akin to the notion of sub- 
 stance ; in certain respects matter is substance itself, while 
 privation is nothing of the kind.^ It is not the firj 6v or 
 non-being, but the ^jli] tto) 6v or potential being (SwdfieL 6V), 
 the possibility or capacity of being, the germ and the be- 
 ginning of becoming. Concrete being, or the particular, 
 represents the development of this germ, the realization of 
 tliis possibility, the potential actualized (ivepyeia). Matter 
 is the germ of the form, the potential form ; the form, in turn, 
 or rather the union of form and matter, which constitutes 
 the particular thing, is matter in actuality. ^ Thus, in the 
 teclmical field, wood, the matter of which the table is made, 
 is a potential table ; the finished table is the same wood in 
 energy. Brass is a potential statue ; the statue is the 
 actualization of the brass. In nature, the egg is a bird in 
 capacity ; the bird is its ivepyeta. Matter is the beginning 
 of all things ; the Idea (shape or form) is the goal for 
 which it strives ; matter is the rudimentary or imperfect 
 state ; the form is the perfection or completion (ivreXey^eia). 
 If v\r] were synonymous with arepj]aL<;^ matter could not 
 become anything, it could not be united with a form or 
 assume those definite outlines which define the real being ; 
 for from nothing nothing can come. Instead of struggling 
 against the form, it strives after it, it desires it (opeyerai % 
 as the female desires the male.* Matter and Idea or form 
 are, therefore, correlative notions ; instead of excluding 
 each other, they presuppose and supplement each other ; 
 motion or evolution (Kivrja-i';, jxera^oXr] ) is the term which 
 mediates between them ; motion is the transition or trans- 
 
 1 Php., X., 10, 4. 
 
 2 3/e/.,VIII., 6, 19. 
 
 » It is identical with Leibniz's conception of effort (§ 56), and 
 Scliopenliaucr's u-ilt or will to be (^ Gl). Aristotle iiiniself uses the 
 expression ^ovXtadm, in sjjeaking of nature (I'olit., I., L', 'J, 14j. 
 
 * Phyx., I., 10, 7. 
 
 8
 
 114 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 formation of the former into the latter. Hence the impor- 
 tance ascribed by Aristotle to the idea of movement ; ^ it 
 enables him, in a certain measure, to escape the dualism of 
 Plato, which the latter himself had attempted to avoid by 
 means of the conception of number or ylrv^i]. His entire 
 system is founded on the trinity of Svvafxa, Kivr)aL<i, and 
 ivepjeta.^ If matter is to form what capacity is to energy, 
 the germ to the finished organism, then the 02:)position 
 between the two principles is far from absolute, and all 
 things are both potentiality and actuality, matter and form. 
 Brass is form or energy in relation to the raw mineral, 
 matter or potentiality in relation to the statue. The tree 
 of which a bed is made is form, shape, or actuality in rela- 
 tion to the seed from which it grew, formless matter in 
 relation to the bed. The youth is form (ivepyeia iarl) in 
 relation to the infant, formless matter in relation to the 
 grown man. 
 
 The rule that every being is both form and substratum, 
 idea and matter, soul and body, admits of but a single ex- 
 ception : the Supreme Being is pure form and without mat- 
 ter. According to Aristotle, matter invariably forms the 
 starting-point for a process of develojjment ; it is the ante- 
 cedent of a higher perfection. Now the Supreme Being is 
 absolute perfection ; hence he contains no matter for a more 
 exalted being; in short, he is immaterial. Aristotle here 
 seems to contradict the nominalistic theory, on which his 
 polemic against the separate Ideas of Plato is based, and, 
 above all, refutes his own statement that everything is 
 material {airavra v\r] eari^). But this difficulty jjartly 
 
 1 Id., III., 1 if. 
 
 2 Met., XII., 5, 6 ; 10, 21. Cf. XII., 2, 10 : Tp'ia 8r) rh mna Km rpe'is 
 ai dpxai, k. t. X. The difference in the names (aTeprjon, vXt], popcprj) 
 i.s not fundamental ; for Aristotle has in mind, on the one hand, the 
 three phases of being (elvai), on the other, the three constitutive prin- 
 ciples of existence (ov). 
 
 8 Met., XII., 3, 8.
 
 ARISTOTLE 115 
 
 disappears wlien we take into consideration his definition 
 of the word matter. He means by it matter that has not 
 yet been formed, the provisional as opposed to the final ; it 
 denotes imperfection, capacity, undeveloped germ. If this 
 is what is meant by matter, then, evidently, every being- in 
 the universal scale of beings is idea or perfection, as coiu- 
 pared -to the lower stages, and matter or imperfection, as 
 compared to higher beings ; and the Supreme Being — but 
 the Supreme Being only — is pure idea, pure form, or pure 
 actuality. Aristotle also declares that the last matter (mat- 
 ter in the final stage of development) and the form are the 
 same (?; iax<iTr] vXrj koL rj /jLop(f)ij ravTo ^). Hence we may 
 conclude that he would not, perhaps, have objected to call- 
 ing the Supreme Being icrxart] vXtj or the final stage of 
 the universal evolution, though he would have denied that 
 this higher phase of existence is in part material. But 
 he does not accept the pantheistic conception of an abso- 
 lute that develops, and is matter before being form, poten- 
 tiality he/ore being energy .^ If the Supreme Being had first 
 existed in germ and as potentiality, then it would have 
 been necessary for an actual being to exist antecedent 
 to God in order to energize tliis germ and to make God 
 actual ; for not only does all seed come from a pre-existent 
 actual being, but no capacity ever becomes actual wdthout 
 the cooperation of an actual being. Not capacity but 
 energy, not the potential but the actual, not the imper- 
 fect but the perfect, is the first principle anterior and 
 superior to everything else.-'' T1iis favorite conception of 
 Aristotle really agrees with the Kleatic doctrine : ex nihilo 
 nihil ; its logical conseq\ience is the negation of the chaos 
 as the original form of existence, if we may apply tlie term 
 "form" to the formless as sucli, or to the complete absence 
 
 J hi., Vlir., G, If). Cf. Vir., 10, -27 ; XIL, 3, 8; 10, 8. 
 "- hi, XI r., 7, l!)-2(). Cf. Plnj^ , II., 0, G. 
 » Ibid.
 
 116 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 of all order. Since form or absolute energy and matter 
 are both eternal, it follows that matter has never been 
 without form, and that there never was a state of chaos.^ 
 
 The eternal actual Being is both the motive or generat- 
 ing cause, the form, and the final goal of things. 
 
 It is the first mover and itself immovable {irpcoTov klvovv 
 ov KiVQv^evov). The existence of this first mover is the 
 necessary consequence of the principle of causality. Every 
 movement implies, in addition to the thing moved, a moving 
 principle, which, again, receives its motion from a higher 
 motive force. Now, since there can be no infinite series of 
 causes, we are obliged to stop at a first mover. To deny 
 this and at the same time to assume the reality of motion, 
 to assume with Leucij^pus, Democritu's, and others, an in- 
 finite series of effects and causes without a first cause, is 
 to violate one of the most fundamental laws of thought. 
 Moreover, the first cause acts forever, and the ensuing 
 motion is likewise eternal. The universe has neither a 
 beginning nor an end in time, although it has its limits 
 in space. 
 
 Here a difficulty {airopia) arises : How can that which 
 is immovable and remains so, move ? How can the mo- 
 tive cause act without setting itself in motion ? It must 
 be assumed that God acts as the beautiful and the desirable 
 act. Thus, a master-piece of art or nature moves and 
 attracts us, and yet remains completely at rest itself. 
 Similarly, the ideal which I strive to realize, or the goal 
 at which I aim, sets me in motion without moving itself. 
 So, too, matter is moved by the eternal Idea {to ri rjv elvai 
 TO TrpcoTov) without the slightest movement on the part of 
 the absolute being. It has a desire for God (opeyeTai), but 
 God is the first cause of this desire.^ 
 
 Inasmuch as the Supreme Being is immaterial, it can 
 have no impressions, nor sensations, nor appetites, nor a will 
 1 Met. XII., 6, 15. 2 j,j^^ XII., 7, 3.
 
 ARISTOTLE 117 
 
 in the sense of desire, nor feelings in the sense of passions ; 
 all these tilings depend on matter, the passive or female 
 principle, the recipient of the form. God is j^ure intelli- 
 gence. The human understanding {vov<i iradrjTLKO'i) passes 
 from a potential state through the stages of sensation, per- 
 ception, and comparison. The divine vov<i has an imme- 
 diate intuitive knowledge of the intelligiljle essence of 
 things. Our discursive thought pursues an ol)ject whicli 
 is different from it and which cannot be attained cxcej)t by 
 gradual stages, wlule the absolute thought is identical with 
 its object. Since nothing is higher than God, and since the 
 thought of God has the highest possible object, God is the 
 object of his own thought (voT]aeQ}<i voija-a). God's life is 
 free from all pain and imperfection, and therefore beyond 
 desire and regret (aTraOi]^) ; it is supremely happy ; hu- 
 man life with its emotions is but a feeble image of it. 
 God enjoys what Ijut few favored mortals enjoy, and then 
 only for a limited period of time ; his life consists in the 
 pure contemplation of the intelligible truth, in Oecopia 
 [Siwycoyy] S' icrrlv oia rj apiart] fiLKpbv "^pouov rj/xlp i). 
 
 As the iinal cause of the universe and the highest good 
 (to ayadov koI to apiarov)^ God is both in the things or 
 tlieir immanent essence {rd^L<i) and ahuve the things, apart 
 from the world, or transcendent (/ce^ajptcr/xeVoi^ tl koX avrb 
 Kad' avTo). Discii)line exists both in an army and outside 
 of it in the mind of the general. Similarly, God is both 
 the law and the law-giver, the order and the orderer of 
 tliinos .2 Everything is organized, ordered, and harmonized 
 ])y liim and witli a view to iiim ; and since he is one (mat- 
 ter alone is iiiiiiiifold ■'), tlicre can be but one single, eternal 
 universe. Conversely, the unity which prevails in the 
 world proves tlie unity of God. Ovk a^yaOhv iroXvKotpaviiy 
 
 €i9 KOipaVO<i tCTTO).^ 
 
 » Afet., XII, 7, 11. 2 /,/., XIT., 10, 1, 2. ' Id., YIU., G, 21. 
 * Id., XII., 10, 2:3 ((iuotatiou I'rom lloincr).
 
 118 GREEK THILOSOPHY 
 
 On this principle of principles depend the heavens and 
 nature.^ 
 
 2. Second Philosophy, or the Philosophy of Nature 
 
 According to Aristotle, the sky is the perfect sphere of 
 which the earth is supposed to be the centre ; nature is 
 everything within this sphere that is subject to motion or 
 to rest ; or, more abstractly, it is motion itself, in no far as 
 the latter emanates from the first mover and is continued 
 by the secondary causes. Physics is a tlieory of motion.^ 
 It inquires into the immovable principle (the divine), the 
 imperishable moving power (the heaven), and the perish- 
 able world or sublunary nature.^ There are as many kinds 
 of movement as there are categories of being.* The prin- 
 ciDal ones are : (1) movement that affects the substance, or 
 origin and decay {jepeaL^; koI cf)dopd) ; (2) movement that 
 affects the quality, or change of quality, alteration {Klvr^aa 
 KUT ctWoicoaLv, fieralSoXr]) ; (3) movement that affects the 
 quantity, or addition and subtraction {kivi^o-l^ kut av^i^cnv 
 Kol (^Oiaiv) ; (4) local movement, or change of place ((f)opd, 
 Kivi]aL<i Kara top tottov ^). The first (origin and decay), how- 
 ever, is not, strictly speaking, a movement, while, of the 
 other three, change of place is regarded l\y all the physi- 
 cists, and especially by Anaxagoras, as the most important, 
 the most universal, and the most original form of motion.^ 
 Motion, change, energy, or cntelechy^ is the realization of 
 the potential as such.' But it is not a substance (ovcria), 
 and does not exist apart from the things which it affects 
 (jrapa ra TrpdyfjLara). 
 
 1 Met., XII., 7, 11 : 'Ek Touwrrj^ I'lpa apxn^ rjpTrjTai 6 ovpavh'S K.a\ rj 
 
 2 Phis., ni., 1, 1. » Id; II., 7. * Id., III., 1, 2. 
 6 Id., III., 1, 7. « Id., VIIT., 10. 
 
 ' Id., III., 1, 7: *H Tov dvvafjifi ovTos eWeXe^j^rta.
 
 ARISTOTLE 119 
 
 Space (%w/3a, r67ro<i) is more like a substance. It is, 
 however, ueitlier the material of wliich bodies are made, 
 as Plato erroneously supposes in the Timmus.} nor their 
 form, nor the interval which separates them {8idaTi]fj,a), 
 but the limit between the surrounding and the surrounded 
 body,2 between the contents and the container. Tliis sin- 
 gular definition is intended by Aristotle as a disavowal of 
 the conception that there is such a tiling as empty space 
 separating boches fi'om each other (the k€v6v of Democritus), 
 a view which he regarded as erroneous. Movement, ac- 
 cording to him, does not imply the existence of the void ; 
 it is invariably a change of place of cUfferent bodies. The 
 condensation of a body presupposes the rarefaction of the 
 surrounding body, and vice versa. Consequently, there is 
 no void either in the bodies or outside of them.^ Since 
 space cannot be conceived without movement, the im- 
 moval)le (the divine) is not in space. Moreover, inasmuch 
 as space is the boundary between the container and the 
 contained, and since the universal is not contained in any- 
 tliing, but contains everything, the universe or the All 
 cannot occupy a particular place. Hence the universe, 
 or the whole of things, does not, strictly speaking, move. 
 Its parts alone suffer a change of place. Taken as a 
 whole, however, it can only revolve upon itself. Indeed, 
 certain portions f)f the heavens move, not upwards and 
 downwards, l)ut in a circle, and only the denser or lighter 
 substances are carried downwards and upwards.^ 
 
 Like space, time exists only as the condilion of motion ; 
 it is the measure or number of motion. It is potentially 
 infmite like motion (whatever Plato may say of it), and 
 this distinguishes it from s])a(^e which is limited. It is 
 nonsense to speak of an actually intinite space. Inhnit) 
 
 1 I>l,;,s., I \'., 1 . 
 
 - f/f., IN'., <) : To ntixii nw TitjntxnvTi)^ tToJuaToa. 
 
 ' lU., IV., 8. * M, IV., 7, 5.
 
 120 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 is merely potential and never actual ; for the actual has 
 form ; it is determined or finite ; the potential is not finite, 
 but infinite. Conversely, infinity has potential existence 
 only in the infinite multiplication of numbers and the in- 
 finite divisibility of magnitudes. Now, time is the measure 
 of motion and consequently a numljer, and number pre- 
 supposes a person who can count. Hence it follows that 
 time presupposes a soul and cannot exist except for a 
 numbering soul.^ 
 
 We distinguished between several kinds of movement, 
 the most important of which is called change of place. 
 The latter, again, has different forms. The fii'st and the 
 most perfect of these is movement in a circle, which is 
 the only motion that can be endless, simple, and uniform. 
 Rectilinear motion cannot be constant, and is therefore 
 less perfect than the other. It cannot be continued ad 
 infinitum, because Aristotle's universe is limited ; hence, 
 in order to continue, it must return upon itself or become 
 oscillatory ; and there is bound to be a stop, however mini- 
 mal it may be, at the point where the movement begins 
 again to go in the oj^posite direction. 
 
 Circular movement and rectilinear movement upward 
 and downward are the two great forms of Kivricn^ in the 
 physical world. The former, which is the most ]3erfect, 
 because it is simple and continuous, belongs to the highest 
 heavens (tt/ocoto? oupavo^), the solid vault which supports 
 the fixed stars ; ^ the latter, wliich is less perfect because 
 
 1 PJnjs., IV., 20, 4. 
 
 2 The modern theory of heavenly bodies moving in space, a view 
 which prevailed among the lonians and the Pythagoreans, seems to 
 be wholly foreign to Aristotle. When he speaks of the heaven and 
 its motion, he does not mean, by metonymy, the motion of the stars 
 enclosed in this space ; his idea is that the heaven itself, that is, the 
 entire series of concentric spheres, which consist of the same sub- 
 stance as their stars, moves. lie also likens the motion of the stars to 
 the movement of a person seated in a chariot ; the person is immov- 
 able and yet advances as the chariot advances.
 
 ARISTOTLE 121 
 
 it is not absolutely continuous, moves the lower or central 
 parts of the universe. The eternal revolution of the outer- 
 most heavens around the axis of the world is immediately 
 caused by the immovable first mover, who moves the other 
 parts of the world only indirectly and by means of the 
 7r/3WTo<f ovpavof;. Hence, the sphere of the fixed stars is 
 in the rrpoorov klvovv Kivov/jLevov, the first moved mover, and 
 communicates its motion to the lower or planetary spheres 
 (Sevrepo^ oupav6<;). These solid but transparent spheres, of 
 which there are about fifty, revolve around a common cen- 
 tre, the centre of the earth, wliich is also the centre of the 
 world. But their movement is no longer a simple move- 
 ment ; they rotate from left to right, like the outermost 
 heaven, but they also move from right to left. This com- 
 plicated movement can only be explained on the assump- 
 tion that each sphere has, in addition to the fu'st moved 
 mover, a particular, relatively-independent mover. Finally, 
 the central sphere, that is, the earth and its iidiabitants, its 
 ocean, and its two atmospheres, is placed under the direct 
 guidance of the XDlanets and under the indirect influence of 
 the fixed stars. It does not revolve around its own axis, 
 but executes complex movements, the fundamental form 
 of which is upward and downward movement. 
 
 Tliins'S that move downwards from the universal circum- 
 ference to the universal centre are called heavy; things 
 that move ujjwards from the earth towards the sky are 
 called liglit. Tlie opposition between heavy and light is 
 the same as that between cold and warm ; for experience 
 shows tliat cold air falls and warm air rises. On this 
 douljle opposition depends the differentiation of elements. 
 Heavy and cold matter forms the earthy or solid element; 
 lifdit and warm matter produces fire. Water and air, that 
 is, moisture and diyness, form two intermediate elements, 
 whose purpose is to reconcile tlie contrary extremes. 
 Altliough Aristotle thus assumes the four aroixda of
 
 122 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Empedocles, he maintains with Heraclitus and Democritus 
 that these elements are homogeneous, and that they rep- 
 resent successive transformations of one and the same 
 matter. In fact, experience sliows liim tliat solids pass 
 into liquids, liquids into gases, gases into fu-e, and vice 
 ve7'sa, that fire and gases are liquefied, and liquids solidi- 
 fied. Hence, he identifies the chemical notion of element 
 with the physical notion of state. 
 
 The chfference existing between the elements of sub- 
 lunary matter depends essentially on the nature of the 
 movement peculiar to the earth, and does not extend 
 beyond our world. It is not found in the celestial spheres, 
 which consist of pure ether. Tliis ether is not a fifth ele- 
 ment Qrreinnov aroLxeiov^, as has been erroneously believed, 
 but the original and neutral substance which Anaximander 
 called the direLpov, and which is the substratum common to 
 the four elements of the terrestrial sphere. There can be 
 no dense liquid, gaseous, or fiery elements in the heavens, 
 because there is no contrast between heavy and liglit, cold 
 and warm, in that region ; and this contrast does not exist 
 in the heavenly spheres, because rectilinear and vertical 
 motion is unknown there. 
 
 Removed as they are from the contrasts of our perishable 
 world, and coming into direct communion with the first 
 mover, who dwells in the outermost heaven,^ the bright 
 inhabitants of the sides enjoy happiness unalloyed, and are 
 endowed with immortality. They of all beings most re- 
 semble the unmoved first mover. Their movements are 
 not arbitrary ; what seems to be an imperfection is in reality 
 a divine prerogative. Even the free man is much more 
 determined in his actions than the slave and the animal ; 
 for he obeys the established laws of tlie State, while they 
 contribute but little to public affairs, and habitually act by 
 chance.2 The more reason a being possesses, the more reg- 
 1 Phys., Vm., 14, 24. 2 Met., XII., 10, 4.
 
 ARISTOTLE 123 
 
 ular are its acts, and the less arbitrary is its behavior. 
 Moreover, the more immovable the secondary gods are, the 
 more they resemble liim in whom there is neither move- 
 ment nor change of any kind. As immovable beings, any 
 numljer of them can exist in one and the same sphere. The 
 planets, which are inferior in dignity to the fixed stars, are 
 likewise immortal and nncreated beings endowed with life 
 and activity.^ The movers of the planets impart to their 
 respective spheres movements that are opposed to the 
 divine and perfect movement of the TrpoJro'i ovpavos^ thereby 
 declaring their independence of the Deity and their hostility 
 towards the universal order. We have here the beginning 
 of evil, but so small a beginning that the life of Mercury, 
 Venus, Mars, Jupiter, Saturn, the Sun and the IMoon,^ 
 is, as compared with the life of the earth, a divine, perfect, 
 and happy existence. 
 
 The operation of the four elements, and the perpetual 
 change of bodies resulting from it (the iravra pel of Hera- 
 clitus), are confined to the terrestrial and sublunary sphere. 
 Tills is the sphere of becoming, l)irth, and death, and — in 
 so far as ^vai<i signifies production, generation, or becom- 
 ing — the stage of nature proper as distinguished from the 
 sky, which is the abode of the strpernatural., tliat is, of the 
 unchangeable and everlasting.^ 'Jlie opposition between 
 earth and heaven, evddoe and e'/cet, the Here and tlie Beyond, 
 the natural and the supernatural, has not, it is true, the 
 same meaning and import in Aristotle as in Catholicism ; 
 still it is certain that this dualism adds to liis cosmology a 
 tinge of Platonic mysticism that contrasts with his onto- 
 logical principles. It was this (bialistic conception of an 
 eaitli placed in the centre of the world and a God placed 
 at the periphery, as far from the earth as possible, that 
 
 1 De ccelo, 2U2. 
 
 * !)(>tli Kuri ami moon an; considered as ])lanel9. 
 
 » Met., XI., G, 12.
 
 124 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 caused the Church to adopt the Aristotelian system, and 
 led to its being forced upon the minds of men as revealed 
 truth, even after the great majority of scientists had taken 
 sides with Copernicus. 
 
 Aristotle's meteorology is more independent than liis 
 astronomical theories, which are based on the preconcep- 
 tions of his age. The terrestrial atmosphere comprises two 
 regions (tottol), one of which is moist and cold, and sur- 
 rounds the earth and the ocean ; while the other is formed 
 of an element that is lighter and warmer than air, called 
 TTvp by Heraclitus, and extends to the vault of the 
 heavens. 1 In the liighest atmosphere are situated the 
 comets and the milky-way (!). The lower atmosphere pro- 
 duces winds, storms, rainbows, and other meteors, which 
 are explained, in the same way as earthquakes and tides, 
 by the reciprocal action between the upper and lower 
 atmospheric strata and the waters of the earth. Aristotle's 
 theory, or at least his explanation of aerial and ocean cur- 
 rents, contains, as we see, a shadow of the truth. But it 
 is in the sjjhere of natural science proper that his genius 
 bursts forth in all its grandeur. 
 
 The organic world is the real domain of fmal causes. 
 Here, more than anywhere else, nature reveals herself as 
 an artist of infinite capacity, universally choosing the sim- 
 plest and the best means of arriving at her goal. What 
 distinguishes nature from art (rex^v) is this : The goal at 
 which the artist aims exists in his thought as a clearly-con- 
 ceived idea, while in nature it exists as an instinct. There 
 is an end to be realized in the case of the bird which cre- 
 ates itself as well as in tlie case of tlie bed that is made by 
 the joiner. In order to become a reality, the end bed 
 needs the hands of the joiner ; the end hird realizes itself ; 
 in both instances, however, final causes play an important 
 part. But, what of the objection that nature sometimes 
 1 Meteorology, 1, 3.
 
 ARISTOTLE 125 
 
 produces monsters ? Well, mistakes may be made in her 
 domain as well as in the domain of art. A grammarian 
 may, in spite of his knowledge, make a mistake in spelling ; 
 a physician, though skilful, may administer the wrong- 
 medicine. So, too, errors can creep into tlie operations of 
 nature, and monstrosities are merely deviations from a goal 
 that is aimed at without success.^ Nature desires the best 
 without always being able to achieve it.^ Her mistakes 
 must be charged to matter, not to the active idea.^ Fur- 
 thermore, it would be absurd to deny natural teleology sim- 
 ply because we do not see in natm-e a deliberating motive 
 principle. Art does not deliberate either ; in the majority 
 of cases there is no need of reflection. Art moves from 
 without, nature from within. If the art of naval construc- 
 tion were in the wood, it would resemble natiu'e in its 
 action.^ Hence nature acts teleologically as well as art.^ 
 The end or iDurpose is the verij i^riiiciple that makes her 
 ad^ and 'pre-exists in principle in the organisms p)roduced 
 hi/ herJ 
 
 Organisms differ from inorganic bodies in that they are 
 impelled by an inner principle (j^v^v}, which employs a 
 number of organs (opjava) in order to realize its purposes. 
 The vegetable kingdom is not an end in itself ; the animal 
 which lives on the i)lant is its end. Hence the soul of the 
 plant simply performs the functions of assimilation and 
 reproduction (^t6 OpemiKov). The soul of tlie animal has, 
 in addition, the faculty of feeling {to ala-OrjriKov), to wliich 
 is added, in liigher animals, the capacity to retain sense- 
 impressions (fiv-qfij]). The sensations of sight, hearing, smell, 
 taste, and touch, meet in a connnon sense (kolvt) atadrjai'i), 
 
 1 Phys , If., 8, 9. » Pullllrs, I., 2, 14, 19. « Phijs., IT., 8, 8. 
 
 * 'I'liis is what inoderii metaphysics calls the immanent teleology of 
 uature. 
 
 • Phys.,U.,8, 1.', Ifj. j,i^ u., y, 4 
 ' Mel., IX., S; De ]»irt. aiiiiii , II., 1.
 
 126 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 which synthesizes them and constitutes a rudimentary form 
 of inner apperception. The soul of the animal is suscep- 
 tible of pleasure and pain ; hence it strives for what makes 
 an agreeable impression upon it, and shuns the contrary (to 
 opeKTLKov^ the active faculty or will). Hence the spon- 
 taneous movement of the animal {(fiopd, to KivTjrtKov Kara 
 Tov TOTTov). In addition to all these endowments of animal 
 life, the human soul possesses the faculty of knowledge or 
 reason (to StavorjTLKov). Owing to this, man is the master- 
 piece of nature, the most perfect organic being (ex^i- o 
 avOpunro'i ttjv (fivaiv a7roTtTeXeo-/x€VT]v ^). He is the linal 
 goal (TeXa) at which nature aims throughout the advan- 
 cing forms of the animal kingdom. Her failure to attain 
 this goal immediately is due to the resistance of matter; 
 but, untiring in her eiforts, she makes many attempts which 
 come nearer and nearer to the final purpose for which she 
 strives, until the end is finally realized. So, too, the young 
 artist tries a thousand times before completely realizing his 
 conception. 
 
 The organic world therefore forms an ascending scale. 
 The organisms and their corresponding souls are per- 
 fected in the measure in which the ultimate piu'pose 
 of the zoological development, the human species, pene- 
 trates and overcomes inorganic matter.^ Corres]3onding 
 to the elementary plant-soul we have an organism in 
 which up and down are distinguishal)le, but in which 
 there is no difference between front and back, right and 
 left ; the plant has its mouth below (the root) and its 
 genital apparatus above (the flower) ; it has no back or 
 chest. A body corresponds to the animal soul, in which 
 is found the double ojoposition between up and down, 
 right and left. In man, at last, the up and down coin- 
 cides with the absolute up and down. 
 
 ^ Historia animalium, IX., I. 
 
 * The fuudameutal conception of comparative anatomy.
 
 ARISTOTLE 127 
 
 The animal kingdom is divided into two classes, one 
 of wliicli embraces sanguineous animals, viz., mammalians, 
 bii'ds, tislies, amphibia ; wliile the other consists of insects, 
 crustaceans, testaceans, and mollusks.^ Warmth is in 
 separable from life, and the relative perfection of an 
 animal directl}^ depends upon the amount of lieat in it. 
 Aristotle believes in spontaneous generation on a grand 
 scale, although he denies it in the case of higher ani- 
 mals. Owing to his ignorance of the facts established 
 by modern geology in reference to the changes which the 
 earth has undergone, he seems to assume the eternity of 
 life and of species a parte ante as well as a parte post. 
 
 The relation existing between the organized body and 
 the soul, its vital principle, is the same as that existing be- 
 tween matter and form, potentiality and actuality, capacity 
 (8vuafMi<;) and function (ivTeXe^eia). Because of this inti- 
 mate correlation, the organized body exists and lives only 
 for the sake of the soul, which is its final cause or the pur- 
 pose for which it exists (to ov eveKa to aMfxa) ; but the soul, 
 too, is a reality only in so far as it animates something, in 
 so far as it is the soul of a body, the energy of an organ- 
 ism, the function of an instrument {evTeXe-xjeia tov crcofxaTo^). 
 Without the body the soul may, indeed, exist potentially 
 (Bwdfiei), but not actually or in reality (ivep'yeia). It is, 
 according to Aristotle, as impossible to feel, to desire, and 
 to will, without the necessary corporeal organs, as it is to 
 walk without feet or to make a statue out of nothing 
 (^ahi^eiv avev ttoSwi', opav ciuev 6(f)da\fj.o)V, avSpi,a<; dvev 
 XaXKOv^). The soul is to the body what cutting is to the 
 axe ; the function of cutting w(juld be the soul of the axe 
 if the latter were a living being. Now, just as cutting is 
 impossible without an axe, so too the constitutive functions 
 of the soul are inseparable from the body. 
 
 ^ I>e partiliiis anundlium, T., •?. 
 
 * Di; (jeueratione iniimiillmu, II., '-i. Cf. Mr/., ^'II., 11, 11.
 
 128 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 From the relation ol:)taining between the organism and 
 its vital principle, it necessarily follows, in the second 
 place, that metempsychosis, or the doctrine according to 
 which any soul may inhabit any body, is impossible. Since 
 the soul is the function of the body, or rather, the sum of 
 its functions or the resultant of its forces, it is evident that 
 its manifestations or acts (that is, in the last analysis, the 
 soul itself, since it is essentially action and energy) are 
 determined by the nature and special organization of the 
 body which it animates. We cannot produce the tones of 
 the flute by means of an anvil, nor the sound of an anvil 
 by a flute. It is equally impossible to have a human soul 
 in the body of a horse, and vice versa. 
 
 The body is potentiality or capacity, and the soul its 
 energy or function. The latter, again, is potentiality or 
 capacity, or rather a sum of capacities {Svvd/j.eL<;) ; it con- 
 sists of the capacities of feeling, perceiving, and willing, 
 of which sensation, perception, and volition are the actions 
 or energies. Hence the soul is the entelechy or primary 
 function of an organized bod//, and its manifestations or 
 effects are the secondary functions or energies of this 
 body.i 
 
 In so far as the soul is sensation, imagination, memory, 
 and will, it suffers the fate of all earthly things ; it is perish- 
 able {^dapro^ 2). The intellect itself has a mortal part in 
 addition to its immortal and divine element. The mortal 
 part comprises the sum of our ideas in so far as these are 
 determined by bodily impressions, that is, whatever the 
 intellect receives, suffers, and does not create or bring 
 forth. The entire passive side of the intelligence (i^oO? 
 iraOrjriKo^) shares the fate of the body, without which it 
 cannot be conceived. Only the active intellect (voC? ttoit]- 
 
 1 De anima, II., 1 : Ei 8/; ri koivov €n\ Trda-rjs '^vxrjs Set 'Keyeiv, e'lrj av 
 ivTiKi^eia 17 Trparr] aafiaros (pvaiKoii opyaviKov. 
 
 ^ De anhna, III., 5 : 'O Se ivadrynKos vovs (pdapTos-
 
 ARISTOTLE 129 
 
 Tt/cd?), tlie pure reason, which conceives the universal and 
 the divine, enjoys the privilege of immortality ; for it alone 
 cannot be explained as a function of the body ; nay it is 
 essentially different {-fvxr'i'i ^evo^ hepov) and separable 
 (Xcopio-Tov) from this, while tlie other faculties cannot be 
 separated from it (ra Xolttci p,6pLa rr}? t/tui^t}? oiiic eari 
 ^(opiard ^). The active intellect is not a capacity, but an 
 actual being {ovaia ivepyeia u>v) ; it is not a product of 
 nature, a result of the development of the soul, like sen- 
 sibility, imagination, and memory ; it is not a product, an 
 effect, or a creature at all, but an absolute principle (Oelov), 
 that existed before the soul as w^ell before the body, and 
 was united with it mechanically {dvpadev). This separate 
 intellect (%cy/3to-To?) is absolutely immaterial (aiiLyr]<i), im- 
 passive {anraOrj^), imperishable, and eternal {adavaro'i koI 
 atSco^) ; without it the passive and perishable intellect can- 
 not think (dvev tovtov ovSev voel ^). 
 
 This seeming immortality,^ with which Aristotle endows 
 the soul, again disappears when we remember that not only 
 does the active intellect not constitute the thinking indivi- 
 dual, but that it does not even form a part of him, — that it 
 comes from without (OvpaOev), and is not bound to the 7ne 
 by any organic tie. It is hard to tell what Aristotle really 
 means by this active intellect, and the majority of his many 
 commentators have exhausted their wits in trying to explain 
 it. Tlie logic of the S3'stem demands that we identify it 
 with God himself ; for its definition agrees, in every re- 
 spect, with tliat of tlie absolute vov<;.^ Moreover, Aristotle 
 cannot assume a plurality of sei)arate intelligences without 
 contradicting a pi'liicipli' <>f his nictaphysics : vjhatever is 
 plural is material:' 'i'lic vov'i ttolijtiko^ is declared to be 
 
 * De anliiia, 11., 0. 
 
 2 /J., III., .'). Cf. De (jener. el cvrnij,!.. 11, :{. 
 » Mrf., XII.. ■■'>, li>. ^ Jhul. 
 
 • Id., XIII., (i, 'Jl. 
 
 »
 
 130 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 absolutely immaterial {airaOri^, ctfiiyri^). Hence it can only 
 exist in the singular : it is unique, and resembles tlie im- 
 manent reason, the world-soul, or the universal spirit (\0709 
 rov Traz^To?) of Stoic pantheism, of which the particular souls 
 are temporary personifications. The transcendency of the 
 God of Aristotle Avould not exclude such an interpreta- 
 tion, for the Metaphysics affirms both the transcendency of 
 the Deity and his immanency in the universe as the phy- 
 sical and moral order of the world ; but what excludes it 
 is the very emphatic assertion that the active intellect is 
 substantial {ovTO<i 6 vov^ x^pLaTo<i kol airadr]^ koX a/xLyr]^, ry 
 oua-ia wv ivepyeia ^). Logically, tliis intellect can be nothing 
 but the Supreme Being himself. When Aristotle allows 
 himself to call the vov<i atSLo<; a part of the soul and its im- 
 mortal part at that, we shall say that his logic is at fault. 
 One tiling, however, is certain : by affirming that the eter- 
 nal intelligence alone is immortal, he positively denies 
 individual immortality. On this point of the Peripatetic 
 teaching there cannot be the slightest dispute. 
 
 The active intellect (TrotT^ri/co?) is by no means identical 
 with the human intellect, and its immortality is of little or no 
 use. Indeed, according to Aristotle's theory of knowledge, 
 which is closely akin to the teachings of Democritus and 
 sensationalism, the human understanding is not the creator 
 or the father (TroLrjr^-i), but only the recipient or the mother 
 of ideas. It is, by nature, devoid of all content, and re- 
 sembles an empty tablet or a wliite page (jpafxfiaretov u> firjOev 
 virapx^i- ivreXexe^ajeypafi/Jievov^). Peripatetic sensualism 
 does not, however, exclude the excipe intellectum of Leibniz, 
 but assumes that ideas pre-exist in the mind, if not actually, 
 potentially at least (Swdfiei) ; in other words, it maintains 
 that the mind originally possesses, not ready-made ideas, 
 but the faculty of forming them.s The ex nihilo nihil is 
 
 1 De anima, III., 5. ^ Id., III., 4. 
 
 f See the discussions of this subject by Locke and Leibniz (§§ 56 
 and 57).
 
 ARISTOTLE 131 
 
 one of Aristotle's fundamental doctrines. Although he 
 holds that the infant mind is an empty tablet, that expe- 
 rience is the source of our knowledge, that intelligence 
 is developed and realized by sensation, he does not teach 
 either an anti-philosophical dualism or a vulgar mechan- 
 ism. On the contrary, dualism affirms one of the principles 
 of knowledge to the exclusion of the other ; it isolates 
 thought and keeps it from having intercourse with nature, 
 on the plea that any increase produced through the senses 
 would be a pollution. Plato teaches such a dualism. As 
 far as Aristotle is concerned, the charge of dualism may 
 -with justice Ije brought against his theology, on the one 
 hand, and his theory of the active intellect, on the other. 
 
 The presence of the vov<; makes the human soul an inter- 
 mediate being between the animal and God. In seiisibilit}^ 
 perception, and niemor}", it resembles the animal ; in reason 
 it is like God. This dual aspect constitutes its originality 
 as a moral being. There can be no morality without the 
 coexistence of animal and intellectual principles. The ani- 
 mal is not a moral being, because it is devoid of intellect. 
 Nor can there be any question of morality in the case of God, 
 who is pure thought. Hence morality is the distinguish- 
 ing characteristic of human nature, and if the end of every 
 being is the complete and j^erfect realization of its nature, 
 the end of human life consists neither in the one-sided 
 development of the animal functions nor in changing man 
 into God (\\hich would be foolish and impossible), but in 
 the complete and harmonious expansion of our dual essence. 
 For man the highest good consists in the happiness (evSai- 
 liovia) resulting from the harmonious cooperation of the in- 
 tellect and the animal elements. Such a state of equilibrium 
 constitutes virtue. Tlie liarmoii}' between the active and 
 passive intellect is called intellectual virtue {aperr} Btavorj- 
 TLKrj) ; this manifests itself as wisdom in theoiy, and as 
 prudence or common-sense {(^p6vr]cn<;^ ev^ovXia) in practice.
 
 132 GHEEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The harmony between the intellect and the will is called 
 ethical virtne {aperrj 7]6iki])^ that is, courage, temperance, 
 liberality, magnificence, magnanimity, gentleness, sincer- 
 ity, and sociableness. Virtue is not the extreme opposite 
 of vice (as Plato holds) ; it is the mean (ro jxeaov) between 
 two extremes {aKpa). Courage, for example, is a virtue, 
 and as such the mean between timidity and foolhardiness ; 
 liberality is the mean between avarice and prodigality. ^ 
 
 Inasmuch as man is (f)V(r€t ^cpov ttoXltiicov^ individuals 
 cannot make and change the State at will ; on the con- 
 trary, the State forms the individuals. The family, prop- 
 erty, and slavery are natural institutions. It is no truer 
 that the same form of government is as suitable to all 
 nations and circumstances than that the same garment fits 
 everybody. The monarchy is the best form of government 
 when the power is in the hands of a good prince ; for in 
 this case it is an image of the government of the universe : 
 a perfect monarchy under a perfect monarch. But this 
 form is the m.ost odious of all when it becomes tyranny. 
 The safety of the State consists in a just apportionment 
 of powers, and depends essentially on tlie strength of 
 the middle classes.^ 
 
 Aristotle's ethics and politics, like his metaphysics, are 
 decidedly antagonistic to the Utopian ideals of Plato. He 
 is a realist and a positivist, a common-sense thinker, so to 
 speak, and takes into special account the facts of experi- 
 ence ; he is exceedingly careful not to set up an ideal goal 
 which humanity can never reach. His entire philosophy is 
 a doctrine of the golden mean, and as far removed from a 
 coarse sensationalism as from an idealism that is out of 
 harmony with real life. In his love of science for science's 
 sake, the suppleness and versatility of his genius, his predi- 
 lection for measure, proportion, and the harmony of the 
 
 ^ NicomacTiean Elides, II., 5 ff . ^ Politics, IV., 9.
 
 ARISTOTLE 133 
 
 ideal and the real, Aristotle represents the climax of Greek 
 thouo-ht. But he also marks its decline, and inaugurates 
 a new epoch in the general evolution of humanity. He 
 resembles a Semite or a Roman in the unremitting good 
 sense wliich he displays, and in his sober positivism. His 
 style is not, like that of his master, the work of the Muses. 
 But liis pliilosophy is even more realistic in matter than 
 in form. His fundamental metaphysical teacliing, which 
 makes matter a necessary element of fhiite existence ; the 
 epistemological doctrine that the mind is an empty tablet ; 
 his monotheism, wliich is much more outspoken and absol- 
 ute than Plato's ; his morality of the golden mean ; Ids 
 monarchical tendencies, — everj-thing about his system is a 
 forecast of the new world, the elements of which were pre- 
 pared at Bella, Rome, Alexantbia, and Jerusalem. 
 
 AmoncT the most distinj^uished scholarchs who succeeded 
 him in the Lyceum are to be mentioned Theophrastus,^ 
 Dicsearchus,^ Aristoxenus,'^ and, above all, Strato of Lamp- 
 sacus,* the teacher of Ptolemy Philadelphus. Aristoxenus 
 denies the immortality of the intellect, and Strato the exist- 
 ence of God ; which proves, either that the master's doctrine 
 of immortality and the first mover was merely an accom- 
 modation, or that his ancient followers were even less 
 united than his mediaeval disciples. What distinguishes 
 the pupils from the master, and what characterizes post- 
 Aristotelian philosophy as a whole, is the gradual division 
 of scientific labor A\'hich takes place after Aristotle. The 
 work of Aristotle the scientist was continued in Sicily, 
 
 ^ Cicero ar/ Attic, II., 16; Acad, post., I., 9; De fini!)us,\., 5, 12; 
 Tuscul. v., 9 ; Siini)licius, Iti P/n/s., f. 225. [See also for Theopliras- 
 tus and other disciples of Aristotle, Hitter and Preller, pp. 3(il ff. ; 
 Mullach, vol. II., pp. 29:} ff. ; Writings edited by Schneider, 1818 ft'. ; 
 Fragments, hy Wiinmer, 1851, 1862. — Tu.] 
 
 2 Cic, Tuscul. I., 10. 3 Jhltl. 
 
 * Cic. de nat. deor., 1, 13; De Jin., V., 5; Diutj. L., V., 58; Siiiv 
 pliciu.-*, loc. cil.
 
 134 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Eg3rpt, and the islands of the Mediterranean ; while Athens, 
 and in Athens the Lyceum itself, merely retained a philoso- 
 phy of reasoning, dialectics, and eristics, which cared less 
 and less for the physical cosmos^ and devoted its entire 
 attention to the soul. 
 
 What is the essence, the aim, the destiny of the human 
 soul, the favorite toj)ic of Attic pliilosophy ? Plato regards 
 thought as the essence and end of the soul, and Aristotle's 
 theology is at bottom simply an apotheosis of roO?. Epi- 
 curus, however, like Democritus, negates the thought- 
 substance and teaches a philosophy of pleasure. Between 
 these two extremes we have the concrete Spiritualism of 
 the Stoics. 
 
 B. Apotheosis of Matter. Negation of the 
 Thought-Substaxce 
 
 § 18. Epicurus 
 
 Epicurus ^ was born about 340, at Gargettos, of Athenian 
 parents. Reflection on liis mother's superstitious practices 
 and the study of Democritus made him sceptical, and 
 convinced him that our fear of the gods and the hereafter 
 is the principal obstacle to the happiness of man ; and it is 
 the business of philosophy to make us happy by freeing us, 
 tlii'ough observation and reasoning, from the belief in the 
 
 ^ Sources : Diog. L., X. ; Cic, Defin., I. ; Lucretius, De rerum natura : 
 Sext. Emp., Adv. math., XI. ; Gassendi, De vita, moribus, et doctrina 
 Eplcuri, 1647, and Syntagma pldlosopMce Epic, 1655 ; The Studies on 
 Epicurus and Lucretius by J. Rondel (Paris, 1679), Batteux (1758), 
 etc. ; Ritter and Preller, pp. 373 if. ; Guyau, La morale d' Epicure et 
 ses rapports avec les doctrines contemporaincs, Paris, 1878; [Trezza, Epi- 
 curo e V Epicureismo, Florence, 1877, 2d ed. INIilan, 1885; P. v. Gizycki, 
 Ueher das Leben und die MoralphilosopMe des Epikurs, Halle, 1879; 
 W. Wallace, Epicureanism, London, 1880 ; Usener, Epicurea, Leipsic, 
 1887. See also Grote's Aristotle, and Susemihl, mentioned p. 140. — ■ 
 Tk.1.
 
 EPICURUS 135 
 
 supernatural. In the society wliicli he founded at Athens 
 about 306, his personal influence seems to have been very 
 great, and the maxims which he dictated to his cUsciples 
 [KvpLai So^ai) formed the permanent basis of the Epicurean 
 teacliing long after his death (270). But neither polythe- 
 ism nor Clu'istianity had any interest in preserving his 
 numerous writings,^ nearly all of which have been lost, and 
 this Socrate double cVun Voltaire has been more bitterly 
 attacked than any other founder of a school. 
 
 Unlike Aristotle, who loves science for science's sake, 
 and considers the tirst philosophy as the best and most 
 divine science^ "although others may be more useful," ^ 
 Epicurus makes science the servant of life, and is inter- 
 ested in theory only in so far as it is related to practice. 
 The aim of philosophy,^ which he cUvides into the canonic 
 (logic), physics, and etliics, is, according to him, to make 
 human life tranquil and peaceful {arapa^ia), and this aim 
 he finds realized in the system of Democritus, w4th whom 
 he agrees in almost every respect. 
 
 Matter is not non-heinr/, as Plato holds, but the positive 
 and onl}^ principle of things, the universal substratum, of 
 which soul, mind, and thought are mere accidents (avfiTrroi}- 
 fiara rj (rv/x^e/SrjKora). Outside of it, there is nothing but 
 the void, the condition of movement. Matter is composed 
 of innumerable, uncreated, and indestructible atoms in per- 
 petual motion. According to Democritus, these coipuscles 
 naturally and necessarily mo^■e downward. But inasmuch 
 
 1 About three hundred, according to Diogenes Laeriius. With tlie 
 exception of the Letters, etc., preserved by this historian, we know 
 nothing of the lost writings except what we can learn from the quota- 
 tions found in various Greek authors, the valuable re'sMme' presented 
 by Lucretius in his Dc rerurn nntura, and the fragments of the work 
 TTfpi (})va«os, etc., discovered at Ilerculaneum. 
 
 2 Met., I., 2, 19-2.5. 
 
 * Epicurus defines it as follows : 'Epfpyf la Xoyots kqi SiaXoyianon tuv 
 iviaifxova ^lov irfpinotovaa (Sext. Emp., A'lv. iiialh., XI., I'llt).
 
 136 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 as they are joined together and form bodies, it must be 
 assumed, according to Epicurus, that they deviated from 
 the perpendicuhir line. Such a deviation couhl only have 
 been the result of chance. Epicurus is not, therefore, an 
 absolute determinist, for he assumes chance, that is, the 
 possibility of an effect without a cause. This view allows 
 him to recognize in etliics the freedom of indifference, or 
 causes without effects.^ 
 
 But though, by an inconsistency that does more credit to 
 his imagination than to his logic, he differs from Democritus 
 on the subject of causality, he agrees with him regarding 
 the eternity of the universe. The absolute creation and 
 absolute destruction of the world are out of the question. 
 Creation in the proper sense of the term is impossible. In 
 order to convince ourselves that the world is not the work 
 of the gods, we have simply to consider the nature of 
 its alleged creators, on the one hand, and its imperfections, 
 on the other. Why should such perfect and supremely 
 happy beings, who are self-sufficient and have no need 
 of anything, burden themselves with creating the world? 
 Why should they undertake the difficult task of governing 
 the universe ? Let us, however, suppose for a moment that 
 the Avorld is their product. If they have created it, they 
 have created it either eternally or in time ; in the former 
 case, the world is eternal ; in the latter, we have two pos- 
 si])ilities: Either creation is a condition of divine happi- 
 ness, and then the gods were not supremely happy for an 
 entire eternity, inasmuch as they did not create the world 
 until after the lapse of an eternity of inaction ; or, it is 
 not, and in that case, they have acted contrary to their 
 innermost essence. Moreover, what could have been their 
 purpose in making it? Did they desire a habitation? 
 That would be equivalent to saying that they had no dwell- 
 ing-place for a whole eternity, or at least, none worthy of 
 1 Lucretius, De rerum nutura, II., 216 ff. ; Diog. L., X., 133-134:.
 
 EPICURUS 137 
 
 tliem. Did they create it for the sake of man ? If they 
 made it for the few sages whom this workl contains, their 
 work was not worth the ti'ouble ; if they did it in order to 
 create wicked men, then they are cruel beings. Hence it 
 is absokitely impossible to hold that creation is the work 
 of the gods. 
 
 Let us examine the matter from the standpoint of the 
 world. How can we assume that a world full of evils is 
 the creation of the gods ? What have we ? Barren deserts, 
 arid mountains, deadly marshes, uninhabitable arctic zones, 
 regions scorched by the southern sun, briars and thorns, 
 tempests, hail-storms and hurricanes, ferocious beasts, dis- 
 eases, premature deatlis ; do they not all abundantly prove 
 that the Deity has no hand in the governance of things ? 
 Empty space, atoms, and weight, in short, mechanical 
 causes, suffice to explain the world; and it is not neces- 
 sary for metaphysics to have recourse to the theory of 
 final causes. It is possible, nay, it is certain that gods 
 exist : all the nations of the earth agree to that. But 
 these supremely happy beings who are free from passion, 
 favoritism, and all human weaknesses,^ enjoy absolute 
 repose. In their far-off home they are unmoved by the 
 miseries of humanity; nor can they exert any influence 
 on the life of man. There can be no magic, divination, 
 or miracles, nor any kind of intercourse between them 
 and us. 
 
 "SVe should cease to fear the punishments of Tartaras. 
 Tlie soul Ls material, and shares the fate of the body. 
 What proves it to be matter — exceedingly iine matter, of 
 course — is the influence exercised upon it by tlie body in 
 fainting, aria'stliesia, and delirium, in cases of injury and 
 disease, and above all, the fact tliat the advance and 
 the decline of the soul correspond to analogous bodily 
 
 ^ Diof^. ly., X. '[■')'■) : To fiuKupiov Km ii<^6aj)Tov . . . oSr opyais ovrt 
 ^dpicn (Tvvi)(fTaL. tv daOfvei yup nuv tu Tmnvruv.
 
 138 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 conditions. The intellectual faculties are weak in the 
 period of childhood ; they grow strong in youth, and 
 gradually decay in old age. Sickness causes a serious 
 reaction upon the soul ; without the body the soul has no 
 power to manifest itself. Nay, more than that ; the dying 
 man does not feel his soul gradually withdrawing from 
 one organ to another, and then finally making its escape 
 with its powers unimpaired ; he experiences a gradual 
 diminution of his mental faculties. If the soul retained 
 full consciousness at death, and if, as certain Platonists 
 maintain, death were the transition of the soul to a 
 higher life, then, instead of fearing death, man would re- 
 joice at it, which is not the case. Moreover, our fear of 
 death is not caused by our dread of non-existence ; what 
 makes us regard it with such terror is the fact tliat we 
 involuntarily combine with the idea of nothingness an idea 
 .)f life, that is, the notion of feeling this nothingness ; we 
 •magine that the dead man is conscious of his gradual 
 destruction, that he feels himself burning, or devoured by 
 the worms, that the soul continues to exist and to feel. If 
 only we could succeed in wholly separating the idea of life 
 from its opposite, and bravely relinquish all thought of im- 
 mortality, death would lose its terrors. We should say to 
 ourselves : Death is not an evil ; neither for him who is 
 dead, for he has no feeling; nor for the living, for him 
 death does not yet exist. As long as we are alive, death 
 does not exist for us, and when death appears we no longer 
 exist. Hence we can never come in contact with death ; 
 we never feel its icy touch, which we dread so much. 
 
 Consequently, we should not be hindered by foolish fears 
 from attaining the goal of our existence, happiness. Pleas- 
 ure is the highest good ; not the pleasure accompanying a 
 passing sensation (rjBovrj iv /civijaei), but pleasure as a per- 
 manent state (rjSovrj KaraaTTi^aTLK-q)^ — that state of deep 
 peace and perfect contentment in which we feel secure
 
 EPICURUS 139 
 
 against the storms of life. The pleasures of the mind 
 are preferable to voluptuousness, for they endure ; while 
 sensations vanish away like the moment which procures 
 them for us. We should avoid excess in everything, lest 
 it engender its opposite, the permanent pain resulting from 
 exhaustion. On the other hand, we must consider such 
 painful feelings as, for example, painful operations, as good, 
 because they procure health and pleasure. Virtue is the 
 tact which impels the wise man to do whatever contributes 
 to liis welfare, and makes liim avoid the contrary. Virtue 
 is not the highest good, but the true and only means of 
 realizino- it.^ 
 
 Owino- to its simplicity, its anti-mystical character, and 
 its easy application, the Epicui^ean system became a for- 
 midable rival of Platonism, Peripateticism, and Stoicism. 
 Italy received it with especial favor, and reckoned among 
 its disciples, the poet Lucretius, who wrote the De rernm 
 natura, T. Cassius, L. Torquatus, T. Pomponius Atticus, 
 Cgesar, Horace, and Pliny the Younger. During the reign 
 of the Caesars, Stoicism was represented by the republican 
 opposition, wliile Epicureanism gathered around its standard 
 the partisans of the new order of things, who were fortu- 
 nate in being able to realize the ideals of the master under 
 the auspices of a great and peaceful power. Protected as 
 it was by the Emperors,^ the school destroyed what re- 
 mained of the crumljling edifice of polytheism, and at the 
 same time attacked the new religion and the supernatural 
 Christian. 
 
 1 Dioy. L., X., 1 10 : OIk ecrriv ijflf'cof (rjv avev rov (/);ir)i't/xa)y koX AtaXcof 
 
 2 A Latin aiul Greek inscription recently discovered in the excava- 
 tions of the Archa-olo^ical Society at Athens and dating from the 
 time of Hadrian, wholly confirms what we already know as to the 
 special protection accorded to the school of Epicurus by the Em- 
 Ijerors. Owing to this, it exerted the preponderating influence during 
 the first centuries of our era, and aroused great jealousy among the
 
 140 GREEK nilLOSOPHY 
 
 C. Apotheosis of Will 
 § 10. Stoicism 1 
 
 The founder of the Stoic school, Zeisto^ of Citiiim in 
 Cyprus, was the son of a family of merchants of Phoenician 
 origin. Upon losing his fortune through shipwreck, he 
 decided to indulge his taste for study. He was alternately 
 the disciple of Crates, the Cynic, of Stilpo, the Megarian, 
 and of the Academicians, Xenocrates and Pole mo. There- 
 upon he taught philosophy in the Iroa toikiXtj at Athens. 
 Convinced of the rightness of suicide, he put an end to 
 his life about 2G0, leaving a great reputation and a large 
 number of disciples behind. The school was continued by 
 Cleantlies,^ a native of the Troad, the supposed author of 
 the so-called hymn of Cleanthes,* and after the voluntary 
 
 Platonic, Peripatetic, and Stoic schools. The inscription also gives 
 us some information, at least indirectly, concerning matters hitherto 
 little known, as for example, the organization of the school during the 
 imperial period, its mode of appointing scholarchs, etc. 
 
 1 [Flitter and Preller, pp. .392 ff. ; Tiedemann, System der stoischen 
 Philosophie, 3 vols. Leipsic, 1776; TtELxaisson, Essai sur le stoicisme, 
 Paris, 18.56 ; Leferriere, Me'moire concernanl Vinfluence du stoicisme sur 
 la doctrine des j'ltrisconsidies romains, Paris, 1860 ; Hirzel, Untersuchun- 
 gen zu Ciceros Philonophie, 3 vols., Leipsic, 1877-83 (Part II., pp. 1-.566, 
 for Stoics) ; Weygoldt, Die Philosophie der Stoa, Leipsic, 1883 ; Oge- 
 reau, Essai sur le systhne philosophique des Sloiciens, Paris, 188.5 ; Bon- 
 hdfer, Epiktet und die Stoa, Stuttgart, 1890 ; and Die Ethilc des 
 Stoikers Epiktet, Stuttgart, 1894 ; Schmekel, Die Philosophie der mil- 
 tleren Stoa, Berlin, 1892; Zahn, Der Stoiker Epiktet, 2d ed., Leipsic, 
 1895; Stein, Die Psycholorjie der Stoa, 2 vols., Berlin, 1886-88; 
 F. Susemihl, Geschichte der Litteratur in der Alexandrinerzeit, 2 vols., 
 Leipsic, 1891-92. — Tr.] 
 
 2 Diog. L., VII. [Pearson, Fragments of Zeno and Cleunthes, Cam 
 bridge, 1889]. 
 
 3 Diog. L.,VIL, 168 ff. 
 
 * Hymn to Jupiter (Stobaeus, Eel., I., p. 30),
 
 STOICISM 141 
 
 death of the latter, by Chiysippus of Tarsus ^ (according 
 to others, of Soli) in Cilicia (280-210), in whose numerous 
 polemical -syriliiigs against the Academy, the teachings of 
 the school received their final form.^ 
 
 In order to form a correct conception of Stoicism we 
 must remember (1) that it is not merely a philosophy and 
 a system of ethics, but a religion raised upon the ruins of 
 popular polytheism ; (2) that its founder and its most ar- 
 dent disciples trace their origin either to Semitic Asia or 
 to Roman Italy; (3) that it is not the work of a single 
 individual, but a collection of doctrines from different 
 sources wliich meet in one and the same channel like the 
 tributaries of a river. Hence its conservatism in religion 
 and its dogmatism in metaphysics. Hence also its prac- 
 tical turn, and, finall}', the complex and wholly eclectic 
 nature of its teachings. 
 
 Like Epicurus, Zeno and the Stoics pursue science for 
 tlie sake of life ; truth, in so far as it is good and useful 
 (to i7nTt]8€iOP, TO (pcpeXifxov) ; the search for the Jlrst cause 
 of being, in order to discover the Jinal goal of life {ro 
 Te\o<;). AVisdom, i. e., theoretical and practical virtue, is 
 the goal. Theoretical virtue consists in tliinlving correctly 
 (aperr] XojiKrj) and in having correct notions of the nature 
 of tilings {aperr] ^vaLKrj) ; but practical virtue, which con- 
 sists in right living and in acting according to reason, is 
 the highest type of virtue, the goal aimed at by theoretical 
 virtue, which is but a means. Whatever does not tend to 
 make us better, and has no influence on our impulses and 
 actions, is indifferent or bad. Logic, metaph3'Sics, and the 
 sciences have no raison d'etre except in so far as they are of 
 practical value. They introduce us to the study of ethics, 
 and this gives them their importance in the teachings of 
 the school. 
 
 1 Diog. L., VIT., 179 ff; Cicero, passim. 
 
 a Cicero, DeJIn., IV., 10, 50; Diog. L., VII., 1 ; Ogeroau, op. cil.
 
 142 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Conformably with its voluntaristic and anti-dualistic ten- 
 dencies, Stoicism rejects Plato's separate Idea, even more 
 emphatically tlian Aristotle. Ideas or iiniversals have no 
 objective existence ; they exist neither outside of things, 
 as Plato teaches, nor in things, as Aristotle holds ; they 
 are mere abstractions of thought {evvorj^iara), to which 
 nothing corresponds in reality. Moreover, tlie soul has 
 no innate ideas ; it is an empty tablet, and all its concepts 
 come to it from without {Ovpadev). The sensible impres- 
 sion (TU7ra)cri<?) is, according to Cleanthes, like an impression 
 made upon a material object, like the mark of a seal upon 
 wax. Cln-ysippus defines it as a modification of the soul 
 (eTepoicoai'i). Sensation (atadijai^) is the common source 
 of all our ideas {(^avraaCai). The latter are divided into 
 four categories, according as they express : substantiality 
 (vTroKeLfieva), quality (Troid), mode of being (ttco? exovra), 
 or relation (Trpo? ri ttw? exovra). An idea is true when it 
 is an exact reproduction of its object. The criterion of the 
 truth of an idea is its clearness, its self-evidence {c^avraaCat 
 KaTakriTrTiKal). There are, accorchngto Zeno, four degrees 
 of knowledge : presentation, {^avTaaia), assent (a-uyKard- 
 0€(n<i), comprehension {KaTdXr]-yln'i), and understanding 
 {eTncrr-qixri). In order to illustrate the highest degree of 
 knowledge, which the philosopher alone attains, Zeno, 
 it is said, used to place his left hand upon his clenched 
 right. Following the example of Aristotle, the Stoics 
 regarded grammar and rhetoric as integral parts of logic. 
 They are worthy successors of the great logician in this 
 field ; indeed, the majority of our technical terms in gram- 
 mar and syntax are of Stoic origin. ^ 
 
 1 For the Stoic logic, see Diog. L., VII., 41 ff. ; Cic, Acad, pr., II., 
 47, and post, I., 11; Sextus Emp., Adv. math., VIII.; Stobaeus, Ed. 
 I.; Simplicius, In Cafeg., f. 16b; [Prantl, Geschichte der Logik : 
 Heinze, Ziir Erkenntniitslehre der Stoiker, Leipsic, 1880 ; Stein, Die 
 Erkenntnisstheorie der Stoiker, vol. II. of work mentioned above. — 
 Tk.].
 
 STOICISM 143 
 
 The Stoic metaphysic is, like their theory of knowledge, 
 even more realistic than the system of Aristotle. It is 
 concrete spiritualism pure and simple. Mind and body 
 are two aspects of one and the same reality. In the real 
 being, mind is the active element {ro ttoiovv) ; matter, the 
 passive element (ro Trdaxov). There is no such thing as 
 pure spirit. Whatever Aristotle may think of liim, God 
 has a body, and the world constitutes this body. The uni- 
 verse is a living being {^q)ov), of which God is the soul 
 (yjrvxr] rov Koafxov), the governing intelligence (pov<i, \6'yo<; 
 Tov 7ravT6<i), the sovereign law (elfiapfievr], avdjKi]), the 
 motive principle, the animating warmth {irvev^ia irvpoeihe';^ 
 irvp TeyviKOV^ irvp voepov, irvev/jia StrjKov Bi* uXov tov Kocrfiou). 
 
 The Stoic theology is a kind of compromise between pan- 
 theism and theism. God is identical with the universe, 
 but this universe is a real being, a living God who has 
 a knowledge of things (fou?), who governs our destinies 
 (-rrpovoia), who loves us {(f)L\dv0 p(0'Tro<;), and desires our 
 good (Ki]Se/xoviK6'?, (0(fie\L/jb0';, ev7rou]TiKO'i dv6pai7roc<;), with- 
 out, liowever, participating in human passions. The Stoics 
 ascribe providential love to the Infinite Being ; hence their 
 teaching cUffers essentially from that of the Peripatetics 
 and Epicureans {ovk addvarov jjlovov Kai fiaKdpiov, akXd koI 
 (fjiXdvOpcoirov). Their pantheism, which does not exclude the 
 notion of Providence, is essentially religious. They have 
 a pious respect for the religious forms of paganism ; they 
 grant the existence of gods who are inferior to Jupiter, 
 and who are revealed either in the stars or in tlie forces 
 of nature ; but they declare these gods to be mortal, and 
 ascribe immortality to tlic Supreme Being alone. ^ 
 
 1 The Stoics of the different periods differ widely as to religion. 
 The ancient Stoics are unenlightened enough to combat the heliocen- 
 tric system in the name of religion, while the Roman Stoics are much 
 more lilx^ral, hut not less accommodating. They look u])on myths as 
 allegories, the hidden meaning of which must be unravelled. Jui)iter 
 is the soul, but the intelligent soul, of the world.
 
 144 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The Stoic system of physics is like that of Heraclitus ; it 
 adopts the view that heat is the principle of life, the theory 
 of the periodical conflagration and renewal of the world, 
 and shows what an important part the struggle for ex- 
 istence plays in nature. Inasmuch as the world is the body 
 of the Deity, it is necessarily a perfect organism {rtXeiov 
 aMfia}, and immaculately beautiful. Conversely, the per- 
 fection of the universe proves that it envelopes an infinite 
 Intelligence,! which is not, it is true, a transcendent prin- 
 ciple, like the God of Aristotle, who moves only the Empy- 
 rean, but an omnipresent being like the human soul, which 
 is present in all parts of the body. The evil in the world 
 cannot shake the Stoic's faith in God ; for just as a false 
 note may contribute to the general harmony, and as, in a 
 picture, the shadows tend to relieve the light and the 
 colors, so, too, the evil contributes to the realization of the 
 good. In the struggle with injustice, cowardice, and in- 
 temperance, justice, courage, and moderation shine with a 
 brighter light. Instead of shaking the faith of the Stoic in 
 Providence, evil confirms it, for evil adds to the universal 
 harmony. The details alone are imperfect ; the whole of 
 things is supremely perfect. 
 
 Man is to the God-universe what the spark is to the 
 flame, the drop to the ocean. Our body is a fragment 
 of universal matter ; our soul, a warm breath emanating 
 from the soul of the world {irvevfia evOep/xov). Since, from 
 the Stoic point of view, reality is synonymous with cor- 
 poreality, the soul too is matter. If it were not so, the 
 reciprocal action between it and the body would be incon- 
 ceivable. The incorporeal cannot act upon a body. The 
 decomposition of the body does not necessarily involve 
 the destruction of the soul ; and even if there be no here- 
 after for all men, the soul of the sage at least, which is 
 more vigorous than that of common mortals, survives death. 
 1 The physico-theological argument.
 
 STOICISM 145 
 
 But though it may exist beyond the grave, say for cen- 
 tui'ies, even the pliilosopher's soul is not innnortal in 
 the absolute sense ; for on the last day it will, like every- 
 tliing else in the world, disappear in the universal con- 
 flaoration {eKTrvpwcn^). Absolute immortality belongs to 
 God alone. The fate which awaits the soul is not, how- 
 ever, a destruction of its substance ; it will return to the 
 infinite ocean whence it came.^ 
 
 The Stoics had no fixed dogmas concerning theoretical 
 questions like the above ; one might believe in innnortality 
 or not, without ceasing to be a disciple of the Stoa.^ What 
 constituted the Stoic and united all the members of the 
 school was the moral idealism which had been taught long 
 before the times of Zeno by men like Socrates, Plato, and 
 Antisthenes ; and their motto was virtue for virtue's sake. 
 The highest good, according to Stoicism, is to practise vir- 
 tue for its own sake, to do your duty because it is your 
 duty; everything else, health, fortune, honors, pleasures, 
 are indifferent {aSLd(j>opa), and even bad, when they are the 
 sole object of your strivings. Virtue alone makes us happy, 
 provided we seek it in a disinterested manner. It does not 
 consist merely in the outward performance of the good (to 
 Ka6i]Kov), but in an habitual disj)Osition of the soul (e^t?, 
 KUTopdcofxa). It is one ; you cannot be Adrtuous in one re- 
 spect and vicious in another. It is the common source of 
 what we call the virtues^ i. e., wisdom ((f)pov7](T:^), courage 
 (avSpia), temperance {a-ax^poavvri)^ and justice (ZLKaioavvjf). 
 To possess one of these cardinal virtues is to possess them 
 
 1 For the Stoic metapliysics and physics, see Diog. L., YII. ; 
 Stobaeus, Ed. I.; Cic, De nat. deor. ; De fato : Seneca, Epislle (id, 
 etc.; Plutarch, De Stoic. Rep., 41 ff. [Cf. also vol. I. of L. Stein's 
 work, cited, p. 140; Sieheck, (Intersurhunf/en, cited p. .59; M. Iloinze, 
 Die Lehre lom Logos, etc., Oldenburg, 187*2. — Tu.] 
 
 * Thus the sr-hool of Rhodes, a branch of tlie Athouian school, 
 rejected the doctrine of final conflagration. 
 
 10
 
 146 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 all in principle ; not to have one of them means to have 
 none. A man is good in all things {crirovBalo';) or bad in 
 all (4)avXo<i). There is no mean between virtue and vice 
 {d/j,dpTr]fji,a). Theoretically, there are but two classes of 
 men, the good and the bad, although in reality there seem 
 to be shades, transitions, and compromises between good 
 and evil. Happy is the sage, who, versed in the secrets of 
 nature, knows himself and others ; whom this knowledge 
 frees from the guardianship of men, the times, social preju- 
 dices, and the laws themselves, in so far as they are the 
 products of human caprice and not of reason {6pdo<; X0709, 
 Kotvo<i X070?). He alone is truly free ; he has overcome 
 the world as well as his own passions. Nothing can affect 
 him nor make him falter ; neither the happenings of the 
 world nor the storms in liis own heart. Let come what 
 come may, he is resigned; for everything is decreed by 
 Nature and Fate ; and Nature and Fate are synonymous 
 with Reason, Providence, and good Will.i Hence, the 
 supreme rule which he observes in all things : sequi na- 
 turam, to follow nature, that is, the law which nature 
 enjoins upon conscience, and which is identical with the 
 law that governs the world {uKoXovdcci ry cfivcrei, Kara 
 (^vaiv ^rjv, Kara \6yov ^rjv, XoycKoyi ^tjv). 
 
 It would be an easy task to point out the contradictions 
 in the theories which we have just outlined, to contrast 
 the moral idealism of the Stoics with the thorough-going 
 realism of their ontology. But, as was ^aid, we have in 
 Stoicism not the system of a single individual but a col- 
 
 1 For Stoic ethics, see Diog. L., VII. ; Stobaeus, Eclog. ethic. IT.: 
 Cicero, Defn. ; TuscuL, etc. The writings of the later Stoics, Seneca, 
 Epictetus-Arrianus, Marcus Aurelius, etc. [Ravaisson, De la morale 
 deti Sloiciens, Paris. 1850 ; Fortlage, Ueher die Gluckselif/leilslehre der 
 Stoiker (in Seeks philosophische Vortrdge, Jena, 1867); W. T. Jackson, 
 Seneca and Kant, 1881 ; Apejt, Beitrdge zur Geschichte der griechischen 
 PhilosopUe, Leipsic, 1891. — Tr.]
 
 STOICISM 147 
 
 lection of doctrines advanced by one and the same sect, 
 a religion for the educated chisses, who desired to bring 
 then- " new faith " into harmony with the old, a kind of 
 union between virtue and the polytheistic Church, embra- 
 cing the most diverse elements, but inspired with the same 
 ideals. Pantetius of Rhodes ^ and Posidonius of Apamea,^ 
 the teacher of Cicero and Pompey, introduced the teach- 
 ings of Stoicism into the Roman world. Owingf to the 
 close affinity existing between these teachings and the 
 Latin and Semitic spirit, the Stoics were not long in gain- 
 ing adherents. Those especiall}^, who, on the decline of 
 the Republic, battled unsuccessfully against the growing 
 despotism of the Caesars, men like Cicero, Cato, and 
 Brutus, found in tliis philosophy a deep source of encour- 
 agement and consolation. To Stoicism we owe Cicero's 
 Dc finihus honorum et malorum, Seneca's ^ Moral Letters^ the 
 noble teachings of Epictetus wliich Flavins Arrianus pre- 
 served in his Bncheiridion, and the twelve books Ad se 
 ipsurii of the Emperor Marcus Aurelius, one of the most 
 admirable products of ancient ethics. Nevertheless, its 
 influence cannot be compared with that of Christianity.* 
 
 1 Died in the year 112 b. c. See Suidas ; Cicero, De Jinibus ; De 
 officii^ ; De divinatione : De legihus ; Seneca, Epistle 116 ; Diog. L., YII. 
 
 - Suidas and Diogenes Laertins. 
 
 3 The theory has long ago been abandoned that Seneca and the 
 Apostle St. Paul As-ere on terms of f^-iendship with each other. The 
 Vjest the extreme advocates of the view that a relationship exists be- 
 tween Stoicism and Paulinism can do, is to appeal to the fact that 
 Chrysippus, the chief founder of Stoicism, and the Apostle St. Paul 
 (who was, however, educated at Jerusalem), were born in the same 
 province and perhaps in the same town. 
 
 * We have pointed out the distiiigiiisliiug oliaraotcristics of Stoi- 
 cism and Christianity in another work {De rcconomie du salut. Jjltude 
 sur les rapports du dotjine el de la morale, Strasburg, 18G3). See also, 
 Dourif, Du stcicisme et du christlanisme consideWs dans leurs rapports, 
 leurs differences, et V influence respective qu'Us o'U exercee sur les 7i>(rurs, 
 I'arJH, 1K(;;{. [Hryaut, 77.<? Mutwd Influence of Christianity and the 
 Stoic School, I>oriil()ii, IHOO ; Capes, Stoicism, Loudon, 18.S0.]
 
 148 GREEK PIIILOSOrHY 
 
 It was confined to the world of letters and hardly pene- 
 trated the masses. Stoicism has nothing to make it pop- 
 ular ; it pursues the paths of science and of meditation ; it, 
 too, shuns " the vulgar crowd " and is identified, in practice, 
 with Epicureanism.^ 
 
 § 20. Sceptical Reaction. Pyrrhonism ^ 
 
 Aristotle was both a zealous theorist and an earnest 
 dogmatist. Although Zeno and Epicurus cared very little 
 for abstract science, they recognized its importance for life. 
 According to the Stoics, who differ from the Cynics in this 
 respect, science teaches us to recognize Providence in 
 nature and in history, to respect its authority, and to follow 
 
 1 [For Cicero (edition of TForts-, p. 7), see Krische, Forschumjen ; 
 Ilerbart, Ueher die PJdlosophie des Cicero ( Works, vol. XII., pp. 167- 
 18-2) ; Hirzel, Untersuchungen zu Cicero's pMlosopJtischen Schriften, 
 3 Parts, Lriipsic, 1877-83; Schmekel, Die Philosoplne der mitileren 
 Stoa, pp. 18-184 ; H. Duraud de Laiir, Moucement de la pensee philosn- 
 pliique depuis Ciceron Juxqu'a Tacite, V ersailles, 187-4 ; for Seneca 
 (edition of Works, p. 7) see : F. Clir. Baar, Se7ieca und Paulus, in Drei 
 Abliandlungen zur GescUchte der alien Philosoplne, ed. by Zeller, 1875 ; 
 W. Ribbeck, L. A. Seneca der Philosoph, etc., Hanover, 1887; Light- 
 foot, St. Paul's Epistle to the Phi/ippians, 4th ed., London, 1878. For 
 Epictetus : ed. of the £^iaTpif:iai and 'Eyxetpi8iov by Schweighauser, 
 Leipsic, 1799-1800 ; Engl, transl. by T. W. Higginson, Boston, 1865 ; 
 Bonhofer, op. cit. For Marcus Aurelius : ed. of his Ta els iavrov by 
 Stich, Leipsic, 1882; Eng. tr. by G. Long; Zeller, Marcus Aurelius 
 Antoninus, in Vortrdge und Ahhandlungen, pp. 82-107 ; E. Renan, 
 M. Aurelius et la Jin du monde antique, Paris, 1882; Watson, The Life 
 ofM. Aurelius, London, 1884. — Tr.] 
 
 2 Diog. L., X., IX.; Sextus Emp., Hypol. Pijrrh., L; Ritter and 
 Preller, pp. 367ff. ; [N. Maccoll, The Greek Sceptics, London and Cam- 
 bridge, 1869; L. Haas, De philosophorum scepticorwn successionihus, 
 etc., Wiirzbnrg, 1875; "Waddington, Pyrrho et Pyrrhonisme, Paris, 
 1877; Hirzel, Untersuchungen zu Ciceros philos. Schriften (op. cit.); 
 Natorp, Forschungen {op. cit.y\ ; V. Brochard, Les sceptiques Grecs, 
 work crowned by the Academy of Moral and Political Sciences, Paris, 
 1887; [Sepp, Pyrrhonische Sludien, Freising, 1893].
 
 SCEPTICAL REACTION. TYRRHONISM 149 
 
 its inspirations ; according to the Epicureans, it frees us from 
 superstition and tlie spiritualistic prejudices wliich destroy 
 our happiness. Both schools agree that there is a criterion 
 of truth. Peripatetic dogmatism is opposed by the scepti- 
 cal reaction which had been inaugurated by Democritus 
 and Protagoras. Pykeho of Elis,^ a contemporary of Aris- 
 totle and a friend of Alexander the Great, represents this 
 movement. He, too, like the Socratics and Epicurus and 
 Zeno, his younger contemporaries, desires arapa^la ; but 
 he does not believe that metaphysics can obtain it for us. 
 There are, as a matter of fact, no two schools of philosophy 
 that agree upon the essential problems. Hence, instead of 
 procuring peace, the source of ti'ue happiness, speculation 
 brings us trouble and uncertainty, and involves us in end- 
 less contradictions. It is useless, because it causes disputes 
 without end; impossible, because we can, in every case, 
 prove both the affirmative and the negative side QavriXoyia, 
 avTi6ecn<i rcov Xojcov). The essence of things is incompre- 
 hensiljle {aKaToXr^irro'^). Pyrrho's sage refrains from mak- 
 ing dogmatic statements on either side; he suspends his 
 judgment as much as possible (iire'x^eiv, eTro;^^;), and be- 
 wares against taking part in heated discussions. lie 
 avoids al)solute negation as well as categorical affirmation, 
 and therefore differs from the dogmatists, who al'firm 
 knowledge, and the Sophists, who demonstrate its impos- 
 sibility. 
 
 The physician Temon,^ an admirer and friend of P3a-rho 
 of Elis, puljlished, among other sceptical writings, a satir- 
 ical poem (Ot StXXot), in which he emj)hasizes the contra- 
 dictions of the metaphysicians from Thales to the Acad- 
 emician Arcesilaus. Eusebius lias preserved the fragments 
 of this work in liis Prccparatiu evaiKjclica. His doctrine 
 
 ^ I'.orii aliuut ;J<I."). 
 
 2 Miill.'icli, Timonis Pliliasii frngmctilti, 1., ]i]). s:' ft',; AVaclisiiiulh, 
 De Tiinone Plilias'w ccEtv risque s'dloijniiihis G'nicis, Leipsic, IbOU.
 
 150 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 maybe summarized in three paragraphs: (1) The dogmatic 
 philosophers cannot prove their starting-point, which there- 
 fore is merely hypothetical'; (2) it is impossible to have an 
 objective knowledge of things : we know how they affect 
 us, we shall never know what they are apart from our 
 intelligence and our senses; (3) hence, in order to be 
 happy, we must abandon barren speculations, and unre- 
 servedly obey the law of nature. 
 
 Pyrrhonism reminded the philosophers, in a pointed way, 
 that the problem of certitude is a fundamental one. In 
 consequence of the rivalry existing between the Academy 
 and the younger dogmatic Stoic school, the sceptics soon 
 found themselves established in the chair of Plato. The 
 first appearance of the critical problem inaugurated the age 
 of reason in Greece, its reappearance after the death of 
 Aristotle marks the period of decline in Hellenic philos- 
 ophy. 
 
 § 21. Academic Scepticism 
 
 The scepticism of the Academy is simply an exaggera- 
 tion of the underlying principle of this school, and, in a 
 measure, a return to the original sources. Scepticism, as 
 we know, formed the starting-point of Socrates and Plato. 
 The names of Arcesilaus and Carneades, the founders of 
 the Middle and the New Academy, are connected with this 
 movement. Aecesilaus of Pitane,^ the successor of the 
 scholarch Crates, returns to the Socratic method. He does 
 not set up a system of his own, but contiiies his efforts 
 to developing the minds of his hearers ; he teaches them 
 how to think for themselves, to investigate, to separate 
 truth from error. His only dogma is : to assume nothing 
 unconditionally. He was at first a critical philosopher, 
 
 1 In Aeolia, 318-244:; Sources : Diog. L., IV.; Sextus Enip., Hyp. 
 Pyrrh. , I. ; Adv. math., VII. ; Hitter and PreUer, pp. 4il ff. [See also, 
 Hii-zel and Sclimekel, opera citato.']
 
 ACADEMIC SCEPTICISM 151 
 
 but the dogmatic opposition of Zeno cbove liim into the 
 arms of extreme scepticism. Zeno makes clear ideas Qcfyav- 
 raaiai KaraXijirriKai} the criterion of truth. Arcesihius, 
 however, calls attention to the many illusions in which the 
 senses mvolve us. Socrates had said : One thing alone I 
 know, and that is that I know notliing. Arcesihius exag- 
 gerates his scepticism and declares : I do not even know 
 that with certainty. He does not, however, deduce the 
 final consequences of his principle. Certainty cannot be 
 reached in metaphysics, but it is possible in the domain 
 of ethics, in which he agrees with the Stoics. But his 
 successors are logically compelled to extend their scep- 
 ticism to ethics. 
 
 The most consistent among them is CAEisrEADES,^ who 
 differs in nothing from the Sopliists of the fifth century. He 
 is an opponent of the Stoics in ethics and religion as well 
 as in ontology and criticism. With wonderful dialectical 
 skill he brings out the contradictions involved in the Stoic 
 theology. The God of the Porch is the soul of the world ; 
 like the soul, he possesses feeling. Now a sensation is a 
 modification (erepouwo-t?). Hence the Stoic God may be 
 modified. But whatever is changeable may be changed for 
 the worse ; it can perish and die. Hence the God of the 
 Stoics is not eternal, their sensational God is not God. 
 Moreover, as a sensible being the God of the Stoa is 
 corporeal, which suffices to make him mutable. If God 
 exists, Carneades goes on to state, he is either a finite or 
 an infinite being. If he is finite, he forms a 2'><^'rt of the 
 whole of things, he is a part of the All and not the 
 complete, total, and perfect being. If he is infinite, lie 
 is immutable, immovable, and without modification or 
 
 1 215-i:}0. Sources: Diog. L., IV.; Soxtus Emp , ^</f. math., 
 VII. ; Ritter and Prellcr, pp. Hi ff. ; Victor Ikochaid, op. cil. ; 
 Coii.stant Martlia, Le philosnj>liti Cnriicddf {linue den Deux Muiults, 
 rol. XXIX.). [See also Iliizel and Schinckel.]
 
 152 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 sensation; which means that he is not a living and real 
 beine'. Hence, God cannot be conceived either as a finite 
 or an infinite being. If he exists, he is either incorporeal 
 or corporeal. If he has no body, he is insensible ; if he 
 has a body, he is not eternal. God is virtuous or with- 
 out virtue ; and what is a virtuous God but a God who 
 recognizes the good as a law that is superior to his will, 
 i. e., a god who is not the Supreme Being? And, on the 
 other hand, would not a god without virtue be inferior to 
 man ? The notion of God is therefore a contradictory one, 
 however you may conceive it. 
 
 Carneades handles the conceptions of right, duty, and 
 responsibility in the same way. Upon being sent to Rome 
 on a political mission, he delivered two sensational speeches, 
 one in favor of justice on the first day, another against it, 
 the next. There is no absolute certitude in morals any 
 more than in metaphysics. In the absence of evidence, we 
 must content ourselves Avith probabilit}^ {to indavov) in 
 theory as well as in practice. 
 
 Neo-Academic scepticism was superseded among the 
 scholarchs who succeeded Carneades by a somewhat in- 
 genious form of critical eclecticism, and then by a syn- 
 cretism that indiscriminately combined the doctrines of 
 Plato, Aristotle, Zeno, Epicurus, and Arcesilaus. 
 
 § 22. Sensationalistic Scepticism. 
 Idealistic scepticism, Avhich traces its origin to the Ele- 
 atics, was opposed by sensationalistic scepticism. This form 
 of scepticism, which had been taught by Protagoras, Aris- 
 tippus, and Timon, was continued by a number of thinkers 
 who were for the most part physicians. The invariable 
 result of their investigations is that we have no criterion 
 of truth, no knowledge of things-in-themselves. Arcesi- 
 laus and Carneades base their arguments upon dialectics 
 and the inevitable con tradictions involved in it ; wliile em-
 
 SENSATIONALISTIC SCEPTICISM 153 
 
 piristic scepticism, the type of modern positivism, appeals 
 also to a series of physiological and experimental facts. In 
 liis eight books on Pi/rrhonism, valnable fragments of 
 which have been preserved by Sextus,^ one of these donbt- 
 ers, ^ExESiDE:Mrs of Cnossns,^ develops the reasons which 
 intinenced Pp-rho and induced the author liimself to call 
 in question the possibility of certain knowledge. These 
 reasons (rpoiroL i) tottol eiroxris:) are as follows : — 
 
 (1) The differences in the organization of sensible be 
 ino's, and the resulting different and sometimes contradic- 
 tory impressions produced by the same objects. All things 
 seem yellow to a man suffering from the jaundice. Simi- 
 larlv, the same object may be seen in different colors and 
 in different proportions by each particular animal. 
 
 (2) The differences in the organization of human 
 beings. If all things were perceived by us in the same 
 way, we should all have the same impressions, the same 
 ideas, the same emotions, the same desires ; which is not 
 the case. 
 
 (3) The differences in the different senses of the same 
 individual. The same object may produce contrary im- 
 pressions upon two different senses. A picture may 
 impress the eye agreeably, the touch disagreeably ; a bird 
 may please the sense of sight and have an unpleasant 
 effect upon the hearing. Besides, every sensible object 
 appears to us as a combination of diverse elements: an 
 apple, for example, is smooth, fragrant, sweet, yellow or 
 red. Now, there are two possibilities. The fruit in ques- 
 tion may be a simple object, which as such has ncitlier 
 
 1 Sext. Emp., IIjip. P'/rrh., I., Diog. L., TX. ; Kitter and Preller, 
 pp. 481 ff. ; V. Broclianl, op. nl. 
 
 2 Born in Cnossu.s in Crete. iEne.sidenm.s (Ati>r]ai8r]fjL0i) prol)al)ly 
 lived in AU'xamlria at tlic Ix'ginnins of the Cliristian era. [See 
 Sai.sset, Le Srrpticisme. JEudsideme , Pascul, Kant, 2d ed., Paris, 18G7 ; 
 >'atorp, oji. cit. — 'l"n.].
 
 154 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 smootnness nor sweetness nor color, but occasions an 
 impression sui generis in eacli particular sense depend- 
 ing upon the particular nature of the sense-oi'gan. But it 
 is also possible that the apple is quite the reverse of 
 simple ; it may be still more complex than it appears to 
 us ; possibly it contains an infinite number of other very 
 essential elements, of which we have no knowledge what- 
 ever, because the corresponding senses may be lacking. 
 
 (4) The circumstances in wliich the sensible subject is 
 placed produce infinite differences in his impressions. 
 During our waking states things appear otherwise than in 
 sleep ; in youth they affect us otherwise than in old age, 
 in health, otherwise than in sickness, in the normal state 
 of the brain, otherwise than in drunkenness. 
 
 (5) The uncertainty of knowledge resulting from the 
 position, distance, and general topical relations of objects. 
 A vessel seen at a distance seems stationary ; a light burn- 
 ing in broad daylight is invisible ; an elephant looks enor- 
 mous near at hand, small at a certain distance ; the neck 
 of a pigeon changes its color according to the observer's 
 point of vision. Phenomena are, therefore, always deter- 
 mined by the relative position of the object and its distance ; 
 and since the objects which we observe are necessarily in a 
 certain position and at a certain distance, we may, indeed 
 say what they are in such and such positions and at such 
 and such distances, but not what they are independently of 
 these relations. Experience never gives us anything but 
 I'elative knowledge. 
 
 (6) No sensation is pure ; foreign elements coming 
 either from the external world or from ourselves are mixed 
 with each. Sounds, for example, are different, according 
 as the air is dense or rare. Spices emit a stronger odor in 
 a room and when it is warm than in the open air and in 
 the cold. Bodies are lighter in water than in air. We must 
 also take into account what our own bodies and minds add
 
 SENSATIONALISTIC SCEPTICISM 155 
 
 to the sensation. We must note the influence exercised on 
 sensation by the eye, its tissues and its humors : an object 
 that is green to my neighbor seems blue to me. Finally, 
 we must take into consideration the influence of our un- 
 derstantling, tlie changes it may produce in the data fur- 
 nished by the senses in order to convert them into ideas 
 and notions. 
 
 (7) Qualities differ according to quantities. The horn 
 of a goat (the whole) is black; the detached fragments 
 (the parts) are whitish. Wine taken in* small quantities 
 has a strengthening effect ; taken in large doses it weakens. 
 Certain poisons are fatal when taken alone ; in mixture 
 with other substances, they cure. 
 
 (8) We perceive only phenomena and relations ; we 
 never perceive the things themselves. We know what they 
 are in relation to other things and ourselves ; we are 
 absolutely ignorant of what they are in relation to them- 
 selves. 
 
 (9) A final and one of the strongest reasons for doubt 
 is the influence of liabit, education, and social and religious 
 environment. We are accustomed to seeing the sun and are 
 therefore indifferent to it ; comets, hoAvever, are exceptional 
 phenomena and consequently produce the most vivid im- 
 pressions in us. We esteem wliat is rare ; we desjjise the 
 connnon things, although the latter may have more real 
 value than the former. For tlie Jew educated in the wor- 
 sliip of Jehovali, Jupiter is l)ut an idol ; for the Greek, who 
 has been taught to worsliip Jui)iter, Jehovah is the false 
 God. Had the Jew been lH)ni a Greek, and the Greek de- 
 scended from the race of A]>raham, the reverse would 
 be true. The Jew abstains from l)k)ody sacrifices, be- 
 cause his religion commands it; the (Jreck has no scruples 
 wliatever against ilic piactice, lu'causc his priests find 
 notliing olijectionablc therein. DKfcreiit couiitrics, differ- 
 ent cusUjuis I It seems as though we shall never be able
 
 156 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 to say what God is in himself and independently of human 
 notions, or to know right and wrong as such and apart from 
 our conceptions. 
 
 The same philosopher subjects the notion of causality to 
 a critique ^ the essential features of which are reproduced 
 by David Hume. The causal relation is, according to 
 YEnesideraus, inconceivable for the corporeal as well as 
 for the incorporeal world. Nor can it exist between 
 bodies and minds. The efficient cause of a body cannot 
 be a body; in fact, we cannot conceive how two can be 
 derived from the unit, three from two, and so on. For 
 the same reason, the eflicient cause cannot be an imma- 
 terial entity. Besides, an immaterial being can neither 
 touch matter nor be touched by it, neither act upon it 
 nor be acted upon by it. The material cannot produce 
 the immaterial, and vice versa, since the effect is neces- 
 sarily of the same nature as the cause ; a horse never 
 produces a man, and vice versa. Now, with regard to 
 objects wliich we call causes, it must be said that only 
 bodies and immaterial beings exist. Hence, there are 
 no causes in the proper sense of the term. 
 
 "We reach the same conclusion in reference to motion 
 and rest. Rest cannot produce motion, nor motion, rest. 
 Similarly, rest cannot produce rest, nor motion, motion. 
 
 The cause is either simultaneous with, or antecedent to, 
 or consequent upon, its effect. In the first case, the effect 
 may be the cause, and the cause the effect ; in the second, 
 there is no effect as long as the cause acts, and there is no 
 longer an acting cause as soon as the effect is produced. 
 The tliird case is an absurd hypothesis. 
 
 What we call a cause must act by itself or through the 
 mediation of something else. On the first hypothesis the 
 cause would have to act always and in all cases, which is 
 
 1 Sextus Emiiii'icus, Adv. malli., IX., 220 ff.
 
 SENSATION ALISTIC SCEPTICISM 157 
 
 disproved by experience ; on tlie second, the intermediate 
 cause may be the cause as well as the so-called cause. 
 
 The supposed cause possesses a single property or it pos 
 sesses several. In the former case, the supposed cause must 
 always act in the same manner under all circumstances ; 
 wliich is not true. The sun, for examjjle, sometimes burns, 
 sometimes warms without burning, and sometimes illumi- 
 nates the object without burning or warming it ; it hardens 
 clay, tans the skin, and reddens fruits. Hence the sun has 
 diverse properties. But, on the other hand, we cannot 
 conceive how it can have them, because, if it had them, it 
 would at once burn, and melt, and harden everything. 
 
 The objection that the effect produced by it depends on 
 the nature of the object exposed to its rays makes for scep- 
 ticism. It is equivalent to a confession that the hardened 
 clay and the melted wax are as much causes as the sun ; 
 hence, tliat the real cause is the contact between the solar 
 rays and the object acted upon. But the contact is exactly 
 wliat we cannot conceive. For it is either indirect or im- 
 mediate. If indirect, there is no real contact ; if direct, 
 there is no contact either, but the two objects are united, 
 fused, identified. 
 
 Passive action is as incomprehensible as efficient action 
 To be passive or to suffer means to be diminished, to be 
 deprived of being in a certain measure. In so far as I am 
 passive, I am non-existent. Plence, to be passive means 
 to be and not to be at the same time ; which is contrar 
 dictory. Furthermore, the idea of becoming involves an 
 evident contradiction ; it is absurd to say that clay 
 Iccomes hard or wax lecomcs soft, for it is assuming that 
 clay is hard and soft, or wax soft and hard, at the same 
 moment; it amounts to saying that what is not, is, and 
 what is, is not. Jlence, no iK'Coming. Hence, also, no 
 causality. Tlie im])ossibility of causality mt-ans that Ikj- 
 coming is impossiljlc.
 
 158 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Agrippa, another sceptic, about a century later than 
 ^nesidemus, also emi^hasizes the relative and sul)jective 
 character of our conceptions, the discord among philo- 
 sophers, their predilection for theories, their reasonings 
 in a circle,^ and the fact that the syllogism cannot give 
 us certain knowledge, inasmuch as every major premise 
 is the conclusion of a preceding syllogism, and so on ad 
 infinitum (j'cgressus in infinituni). 
 
 The last and boldest of the Greek sceptics is Sextus 
 Ejmpiricus, a physician of vast learning, who lived at 
 Alexandria about the year 300 A. d., and of whom we 
 have two valuable works : the Fyrrlionic Hyi^otyposes and 
 the treatise Against the Mathematicians. He turns his at- 
 tention to science, which, in consequence of its self-evident 
 principles, offers a final refuge to dogmatism and meta- 
 })hysics, and maintains the uncertainty, not only of gram- 
 mar, rhetoric, music, astronomy, and the philosophical 
 sciences proper, but also of arithmetic and geometry, in 
 which he discovers the fundamental contradiction that the 
 line is both extended and composed of inextended points. 
 Hence no science is certain ; everything is vague, doubt- 
 ful, and contradictory, both in theory and in method ; in 
 mathematics as well as in physics, in logic as well as in 
 ethics. True scepticism, like Pyrrho's, does not even grant 
 unconditionally that all sciences are uncertain. The cate- 
 gorical assertion that metaphysics in the Peripatetic sense, 
 i. e., knowledge of things-in-themselves, is impossible, 
 stamps one as a dogmatist and metaphysician. This is, 
 according to the Pyrrhonians, the error in the scepticism 
 of the New Academy, which is but a negative dogmatism. 
 The true sceptic refrains from making any absolute judg- 
 ment whatsoever. His perfect neutrality (eVox^') enables 
 
 1 The Stoics, for exami)le. proved the existence of God by the 
 perfection of the world, and the perfection of the world by the 
 existence of God.
 
 THE SCIENTIFIC MOVEMENT 159 
 
 him to realize, if not a state of absolute apathy, at least 
 that repose and moral equilibrium QfierpoTrddeca^ in which 
 true happiness consists. The sceptic, like the Stoic and 
 Epiciu'ean, pursues a practical end above ever3'thing- else, 
 but the way to reach it is to abstain from ontology. His 
 system consists in not having a system ; and should the 
 fancy seize him to advance a dogma, it would be to doubt 
 his own scepticism. 
 
 But by doubting its own conclusions, radical scepticism 
 abdicated in favor of Academic probabilism. 
 
 § 23. The Scientific Movement * 
 
 While pliilosophy was degenerating into barren scepti- 
 cism, the sciences, wliich had one by one cut loose from the 
 parent science, cro^ta, made wonderful strides in the Greek 
 islands of the Mediterranean and in Egypt. jNIathematics 
 flourished in Eg}^3t at a time when Greece was still steeped 
 in barbarism. Experimental science, it is true, advanced 
 but very slowly. It was, like pliilosophy, paralyzed by the 
 insane delusion that the senses are deceptive and that rea- 
 son is incapable of rectifying them. Besides, the natural 
 impatience of the Greeks inclined them to reasoning and 
 a i^riori speculation rather than to the detailed and pains- 
 taking labor involved in observation and experience. But 
 the sciences in which reasoning plays the chief part, mathe- 
 matics and mathematical physics, the exact sciences, in a 
 word, made rapid strides. Tliey alone escaped the destroy- 
 ing touch of universal scepticism. In si)ite of the attacks 
 of empiricism, there could be no reasonable doubt of the 
 
 1 ^fontucla, Ilbtoire des sciences viatJu'mntiques, especially the first 
 two vohirnf^s, Paris, 17")8; Delaiiil»r<!, Ilktoire tie I'astrouomie, 7 vols., 
 Paris, 1817-2;]; Draper-, History of the Intellecttial Developiinnt in Eu- 
 rope, N<i\v York, 18'i3 ; Cliaslcs, Aperfu hisforiijue sur I'ariyine et le 
 de'veloppemrnt ties nu'thmlis en f/i'omi'irie, 2(1 t-d., raris, 1875; [Cantor, 
 Geschichle der Muthfrndtit, T., Leipsic, 188()].
 
 160 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 truth tliat twice two are four, and that the three angles of 
 a triangle are equal to two right angles. 
 
 In Sicily, where Pythagorean traditions had been per- 
 petuated, Hicetas and Archimedes of Syracuse taught a 
 system of astronomy (as early as the third century B. c.) 
 tliat closely resembled the Copernican system. Archi- 
 medes gave to physics the method of determining specific 
 weights, invented the sun-glass and the endless screw, 
 and created the science of mechanics by his theory of the 
 lever. At the same time, a fellow-countryman of Pytha- 
 goras, Aristarchus of Samos, proposed that the distance 
 between the earth and the sun be measured by the dicho- 
 tomy of the moon, and, what is more important, — for 
 this method has proved to be impracticable, — attempted 
 to substitute for the geocentric system of Aristotle the 
 hypothesis that the earth revolves around the sun. This 
 theory was accepted and developed by Seleucus of Seleucia 
 in Babylonia, but stamped as impious by the Stoics, and 
 rejected by Ptolemy himself, the most celebrated if not the 
 greatest among the astronomers of Alexandria. It did not 
 succeed in supplanting the old conception until the dawn 
 of modern times, when it was advanced by Copernicus, 
 Kepler, and Galileo. 
 
 On the opposite shore of the Mediterranean arose the city 
 of Alexandria wliich was founded in the second half of 
 the fourth century by the conqueror who gave it his name. 
 Under the Ptolemies this became the educational as well 
 as commercial centre of the world. Here rather than at the 
 schools of Athens are to be found the legitimate spiritual 
 descendants of Plato and Aristotle. Athens had banished 
 the king of science, and its star went down forever. The 
 spirit of the Stagirite descended upon his pupil, and from 
 Alexander to Ptolemy and his successors. The Museum 
 which they founded in the new capital of Egypt was a 
 wonderful institution. Nothing in ancient or modern
 
 THE SCIENTIFIC MOVEMENT 161 
 
 times can be compared to tliis attempt to organize science. 
 Here scholars from every nation were entertained at public 
 expense ; thousands of students flocked hither from all 
 the surrounding countries. Here the naturalists found a 
 botanical garden, a vast zoological collection, and an ana- 
 tomical building ; the astronomers, an observatory ; the 
 litterateurs, grammarians, and pliilologists, a splendid li- 
 brary, which contained, during the fu'st centuries of our 
 era, 700,000 volumes. Here Euclid wrote (about 290) his 
 Elements of Geometry, his treatises on Harmomj, Optics, 
 and Catoptrics ; here Eratosthenes, the royal librarian under 
 Ptolemy Pliiladelphus, pui-sued his remarkable astronomi- 
 cal, geographical, and historical labors ; here ApoUonius of 
 Perga published his treatises on Conic Sections ; here Arys- 
 tillus and Timocharus made the observations wliich led to 
 the discovery of the precession of the equinoxes by the 
 astronomer Hipparchus ; here Ptolemy wrote the Almagest 
 (^fxeydXi] avvra^a^, which remained the authoritative sys- 
 tem of astronomy until the time of Copernicus, and his 
 Geography, which was used in the schools of Europe for 
 fourteen centuries. Ever since this epoch, the conceptions 
 of the sphericity of the earth, its poles, its axis, the equator, 
 the arctic and antarctic circles, tlic equinoctial j)oints, tlie 
 solstices, the inequality of climate on the earth's siu'face, 
 have been current notions among scientists. The mechan- 
 ism of the lunar phases was perfectly understood, and 
 careful though not wholly successful calculations were 
 made of intersidereal distances. 
 
 On the other hand, literature and art flourished under 
 the careful protection of the Court. Literature and its 
 history, philology and criticism, became sciences. Tlie 
 Hebrew Bibh.- and other books nf Oriental origin were 
 tiaiislated into Cireek. Buddhists and Jews, Greeks and 
 Egyptians, mingled together, bringing witli llicin tlie most 
 diverse fonuM of religion. These conditions led to tlio 
 
 11
 
 162 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 development of comparative theology, on the one hand, 
 and to the fusion of beliefs or a kind of religious eclec- 
 ticism, on the other, and paved the way for Catholic unity. 
 
 § 24. Eclecticism ^ 
 
 The scientific movement of Alexandria was suddenly 
 checked in the second century by the centi-alizing power 
 of Rome. From that time on, the Greek genius showed 
 unmistakable signs of decay. Literature and art declined 
 rapidly. Pliilosophy was suffering from the incurable dis- 
 ease of scepticism. Torn from its native soil, it went to 
 seed. The physical sciences remained stationary after the 
 days of Galen, the physician, and the astronomer Ptolemy. 
 The religion of the fathers became an object of scandal 
 and derision ; wliile ethics, which ought to have taken the 
 place of religion, wavered between the trivialities of Epi- 
 cureanism and the Utopias of the Stoa; the nearer it 
 seemed to approach its ideal, ataraxia, the more the latter 
 seemed to elude its grasp. In this state of senile pros- 
 tration, Greek thought looked back with longing to the 
 days of its creative force ; it cultivated a taste for history 
 and archeology, in a word, for the past. Sceptical even of 
 scepticism and yet unable to produce anything original, it 
 became eclectic and lived on its memories. The ancient 
 schools, each of which but recently possessed a separate 
 principle, a distinguishing characteristic, and an indivi- 
 duality of its own, the Academy, the Lyceum, and the 
 Stoa, after a struggle of three centuries, gradually became 
 reconciled with each other and were eventually fused into 
 a colorless syncretism. 
 
 It was, however, not impotence alone that led to such 
 a fusion of elements. As long as Judaism retained its 
 
 ^ Soin-ces : Suidas, the Treatises of Philo the Jew, Plutarch, and 
 Apuleius ; Eusebius, Prcej). evangelica, XI., XV., etc.
 
 ECLECTICISM 163 
 
 national and exclusive form, it proved ineffective. But 
 when Philo of Alexandria ^ attempted to reconcile the 
 teacliings of Moses and Plato, and Jesus and liis apostle, 
 Paul of Tarsus, divested Judaism of its national garb, 
 there was no further obstacle to its progress in the Grseco- 
 Roman world. Public opinion had long ago inclined 
 towards monotheism. Peripateticism and lloman Stoicism 
 boldly advanced it, but their teachings reached the edu- 
 cated classes alone. Christianity was a religion in the 
 true sense of the term. Eminently popular, it showed 
 a preference for the uncultured, the poor, and the lowly, 
 for all sucli as desired the coming of a better world (/Sacn- 
 Xeta Tou 6eov). Hence it became a formidable adversary, 
 before whom it was necessary to close the ranks and firmly 
 reunite the disjecta membra of ancient pliilosoi^hy. 
 
 Pythagoras and Plato were invoked against Biblical reve- 
 lation ; the God of Xenophanes, Socrates, and Aristotle, 
 against the God of the Jews and the Christians. The Stoic 
 example was followed, and the attempt made to reconcile 
 traditional polytheism with monotheism by means of the 
 
 ^ A Jewish theologian, a contemporary of Jesus. Many of his 
 writings are still extant; the majority of them are commentaries on 
 the Old Testament. In order to reconcile Scripture with the philo- 
 sophy of his century he had recourse to allegory, like the Stoics. His 
 theory of the Xoyof (the Word, as the revelation of God, tlie Son of 
 God, the second God) has passed into Christianity (The Gospel ac- 
 cording to St. John, chap. I.). Philonis Judcei opera omnia, ed. llieliter, 
 4 vols., Leipsic, 1828-30; [P. AVendland, Neuentdeckte Fraijmente 
 Philos, Berlin, 1891; (Jfrbrer, Philon und die alexandrinische Theo- 
 sophie, Stuttgart, 1831, 2d ed., 1835; Diiline, Gescliichtliche Darstellung 
 der jUdisch-alexandriuischen Religionxphilosophie, Ilalle, 1831 ; AVolff, 
 Die pJiilonische Philomphie, 2d ed., Gothenl)urg, 1858 ; lldvillo, Le 
 logos d'apres Philon d'AlexandrJe, (Jencva, 1877; M. Ilcinze, Die Lehre 
 vom Logos, etc., Oldenhmg, 1872: James 1h-\unmon(\, Philo-Judfeus, 
 etc., London, 1888; Schurer, Geschichle dcs Jiidischen Volks imZeitulter 
 Jesu Christi, 2d ed. ; Kng. trans. History of the Jewish People, etc., 5 
 vols., Xew York, 1891. — Tit.].
 
 164 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 pantheistic conception of a supreme and unique principle, 
 embod3dng itself in a number of secondary divinities. 
 This conception passed into monotheism and found expres- 
 sion in the eons of the Clnistian Gnostics, the sephiroth of 
 the Jewish cahalists, and the hypostases of Catholic the- 
 ology. In conformity with the Greek spirit and in oppo- 
 sition to Christian tendencies, the times continued to 
 identify the beautiful and the good, the ugly and the bad, 
 metaphysical evil and moral evil. Good was ascribed to 
 spirit, the formal or ideal principle, evil to matter strug- 
 gling against the dominion of the Idea. Some conceived 
 God as a neutral principle, superior both to mind and mat- 
 ter, and yet the cause of both ; others identified liim with 
 the spiritual or ideal principle, meaning thereby not the 
 unity of contraries but the antithesis of matter. Hence- 
 forth matter is not his product or creation, but a rival prin- 
 ciple co-eternal with him and equal in power. Here we 
 have a more or less pronounced dualism, whicli exercises 
 an influence on its adversaries and is reflected in the 
 gnostic heresies. If God alone, it is held, is without sin, 
 it is because he alone is -without matter ; and if matter is 
 the soui'ce of evil, then every corporeal being is sinful. 
 Hence follow the necessity of sin and the obligation on 
 part of the sage to mortify the body by ascetic practices 
 and abstinences. The Christian belief in the resurrection 
 of the flesh is opposed by the Platonic dogma of the im- 
 mortality of the soul apart from the bod}^ ; creation ex 
 niJiilo, by the conception of the pre-existence of souls and 
 the eternity of matter. 
 
 Nevertheless, the greatest concessions were made to the 
 enemy. Provided he consented to place Orpheus, Pytha- 
 goras, and Plato in the same category with Moses, Isaiah, 
 and St. Paul, and recognized the thinkers of ancient Greece 
 as the organs of the eternal X0709, lie was oifered the hand 
 of friendship. All religions were held to be akin to each
 
 ECLECTICISM 165 
 
 other, and conceived as products of a primitive revelation 
 moditied in various ways by differences in nationality. 
 The most liberal thinkers, men like Moderatus, Nicoma- 
 chus, and Numenius, loved to call Moses the Jewish 
 Plato, and Plato the Attic Moses (Mojua-?}? cittikc^oov). 
 But with the exception of a few Cluistian doctors, most 
 of the adversaries rejected the compromise offered by 
 eclecticism. Although disposed to recognize the scat- 
 tered truths in Plato, they called in question Plato's 
 originality and alleged that he had di'awn them from 
 the Bible. 
 
 Greek pliilosophy found itself obliged to change its old 
 methods of controversy in dealing with the arguments of 
 Chi'istianity. With the exception of a few Fathers of the 
 Church, who were as tolerant as they were learned, the 
 Christians, following the example of Judaism, recognized 
 no other pliilosophy than Biblical exegesis, no other cri- 
 terion of the truth of a doctrme than its agreement with 
 revelation, as set forth in Scri^^ture. Hence it was neces- 
 sar}^ to apj^eal to the texts or to lower one's colors to Chris- 
 tianity ; arguments drawn from pure reason and discussions 
 not based on the texts were no longer accepted. Hence also 
 tlie unusual ardor with wliich the philosophers of tlie peiiod 
 studied the texts of their predecessors, particularly those of 
 Plato and Aristotle. Indeed, their enthusiasm degenerated 
 into a veritable fetichism of the letter, Avhich proved to be 
 no less extreme than the letterworship of their adversaries.^ 
 The writings of the great Attic pliilosophers became a kind 
 of Bible, a kind of supernatural revelation, in contents as 
 well as in form. They were regarded as inimitable master- 
 pieces and so greatly admired that every phrase and eveiy 
 word was considered insj)irod. 'J'lie pliilologists, gram- 
 
 1 Tlie genuine ■writings of the ancient jdiilosuiiliers ditl not suffice, 
 hence the Orphicx, tlie Books nf Hermes, tha Clialilean Oracles, etc , were 
 manufactured. This is the golden age of apocryphal literature.
 
 166 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 marians, and critics vied with each other in their efforts 
 to analyze, purify, establish, and explain the texts. They 
 loved to imitate not only the mode of thought but the style 
 of Plato ; indeed these form-loving Greeks valued the lat- 
 ter almost as highly as the contents. Alcinous and Atticus 
 wrote commentaries on Plato ; Alexander of Aphrodisias 
 — to mention only the most distinguished among the com- 
 mentators — devoted his learning and ingenuity to the 
 interpretation of Aristotle. 
 
 Among some, literalism gave rise to the strangest super- 
 stitions. Plutarch ^ of Chseronea and Apuleius,^ mistaldng 
 the form for the contents, the allegorical meaning for the 
 real meaning, looked upon Plato as an apostle of the most 
 vulgar polytheism. But, on the other hand, Ammonius 
 Saccas, the founder (though otherwise little kno\vn) of the 
 Neo-Platonic school of Alexandria,^ Longinus, the sup- 
 posed author of the treatise On the Sicblime^ Erennius, the 
 successor of Ammonius, and above all Plotinus of Lyco- 
 polis, penetrated more deeply into the spirit of the illus- 
 trious Athenian and gave liis conceptions the systematic 
 and definitive form which they had hitherto lacked. In 
 Neo-Platonism and particularly in the pliilosophy of Ploti- 
 nus, the Greek mind seems to make a final serious attempt 
 to formulate the result of ten centuries of reflection and to 
 express its final convictions concerning God, the world, 
 and the human soul. 
 
 1 [See p. 7, note ; Ritter and Preller, pp. 507 ft. ; transl. of Morals, 
 ed. by Goodwin, 5 vols., Boston, 1870; R. Volkmann, Leben, Schriflen 
 unci Philosophie des Plutarch, 2 pts., Berlin, 1872.] — Tr. 
 
 2 [ Works, ed. by Goldbacher, Vienna, 1876. See Prantl, Geschichte 
 der Locjik, I., pp. 578-591. — Tr.] 
 
 3 [Ritter and Preller, -pV- ^^'^ ^- '■> flatter, Sur Vecole d'AIexandrie, 
 Paris, 1820, 2d ed., 1840-48]; Jules Simon, Histoire de I'ecole d'AIex- 
 andrie, 2 vols., 1844-1845 ; Vacherot, Histoire critique de Vecole d'AIex- 
 andrie, 3 vols. Paris, 1846-51.
 
 FLOTINUS AND NEO-PLATONISM 167 
 
 § 25. Plotinus and Neo-Platonism 
 
 Plotinus 1 of Lycopolis in Egypt, a clisciple of Ammo- 
 nius Saccas of Alexandria, came to Rome about 244, and 
 taught pliilosophy for twenty-five years. The school which 
 he foiuided in that city included men from every country 
 and every station in life : physicians, rhetoricians, poets, 
 senators, nay, even an emperor and an empress, Gallienus 
 and Salonina. It became the centre of what remained of 
 Pagan pliilosoj^hy, science, and literature. Countless com- 
 mentaries were written on the Attic pliilosophers ; they 
 were even worshipped as Jesus, the apostles, and the 
 martyrs were worshipped by the Christian community, 
 which had in the meanwhile become large and influential. 
 Plotinus, who wrote nothing until he was fifty years old, 
 left fifty -four treatises at the time of his death (270). 
 These liis disciple Porphyry published in six Enneads or 
 series of nine writings each. 
 
 The fundamental conception of tliis important work is 
 emanatistic pantheism. It looks U2:ton the world as an 
 overflow^ as a diffusion of the divine life, and upon its 
 re-ahsorption in God as the final goal of existence. The 
 stages in the overflow are : spirituality, animality, and cor- 
 poreality ; of re-absor2:)tion : sensible perception, reasoning, 
 mystical intuition. Let us consider, with the author, 
 (1) tlie principle, and (2) the three stages in the hierarchy 
 of beings. 
 
 1 [Complete odition of the Works of Plotinus with the Latin trans- 
 lation of IVIarsilius Ficinus, pul)]ishecl l)y Wyltenbach, ]\Ioser, and 
 Creuzer, 3 quarto vols., Oxford, 1835 ; by Creuzer and Moser, Paris, 
 1855 ; by A. Kirchhoff, Leipsic, 185G. Ritter and Preller, pp. 517 ff. 
 Engl, transl. of parts by Th. Taylor, London, 1787, 1794, 1817; 
 French transl. and eoninicntary by Pouillct, 3 vols., Paris, lS.")(i-0(). 
 SeeC. IL Kircliner, I>ie P/il/osophie drs P/olin, Halle, 1851 ; A. Kiclilcr, 
 Npuplatojibrhr. S/udirn, 5 pis., Malle, lS(il— 07; Ilarnaok, Article in 
 E»ri/rlo/>e<H(i Britannica, on Nio-Platonlxm; Walter, Geschtchte der Acs- 
 Uielilc in Allr.rlhum, pp. 730-780,] — Tu.
 
 168 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 I. God. — Every being is composed of matter and form, 
 God (the One, the Form) and matter (uX?;) are the consti- 
 tutive principles, and, as it were, the two j^oles of the uni- 
 verse. God is the Svva/xi'i wliich produces everything, the 
 active power; matter, the 8vm/xi<; which suffers everything, 
 becomes everything, and is infinitely modified ; it is the 
 opposite of the absolute ivepyeia. However, though mat- 
 ter takes on form, it does not, according to Plotinus, 
 constitute an absolute antithesis; there is, in the last 
 analysis, but one supreme principle : Form, Unity, or 
 God. 
 
 Divine unity is not a numerical unity. The unity of 
 number presupposes the two, the three, and so on, while 
 the divine unity is equal to infinity and contains every- 
 thing. It is not divisible like the numerical unity with its 
 endless fractions ; it transcends our conception ; it is the 
 miracle of miracles. It produces all things and is pro- 
 duced by none ; it is the source of all beauty, without being 
 beautiful itself, the source of all form, without having 
 any form itself, the source of all thought and intelligence, 
 without being a thinking and intelligent being itself, the 
 principle, the measure, and tlie end of all things (Travrav 
 ixerpov Kol Trepa?), without itself being a thing in the proper 
 sense of the term. It is pure thought, the source of every 
 concrete thought, the pure light wliich makes us see all 
 things, and which consequently we do not, ordinaril}-, dis- 
 tinguish from the things themselves ; it is the principle 
 of goodness, the highest good, without being goocU like a 
 creature participating in goodness. It has neither good- 
 ness nor beauty nor intelligence, but is goodness, beauty, 
 and thought itself. To attribute inner perception to God 
 and to make an individual being of him, means to diminish 
 liim. Self-consciousness has value for us ; it would have 
 none for God. What is obscure seeks for light by means 
 of vision ; but has light itself any need of sight ? Not that
 
 PLOTINUS AND NEO-PLATONISM. 169 
 
 the Supreme Being is unconscious or blind like a stone 
 or plant ; he transcends the unconscious as well as the 
 conscious ; the opposition between the conscious and un- 
 conscious does not exist for God. Nor has he a will in 
 the human sense of the term ; he does not strive for any 
 good ; he does not desire anything but liimself, because 
 there is nothing desirable outside of liim ; he is peace, rest, 
 and supreme content. He is neither free, as souls are, nor 
 determined, like bodies ; he is suj)erior to free-will, which 
 wavers between opposing notions, and to corporeal beings, 
 which are impelled by a foreign power. Inasmuch as every 
 quality assigned to him limits him, we must refrain from 
 giving him attributes ; he is both everytlung and nothing 
 imaginable. To attribute or to give to him any tiling what- 
 ever, means to deprive liim of it. 
 
 Hence Plotinus is obliged to confess that the attributes 
 which he himself had ascribed to God (the One, the Good, 
 pure Thought, pure Actuality) are inadequate. All we can 
 say of God is that he transcends everything that can be con- 
 ceived and said. Strictly speaking, we cannot even affu-m 
 that he exists^ for he transcends existence itself. He is the 
 highest abstraction, and we cannot reach him except by 
 means of an absolute and radical abstraction. We cannot 
 even conceive Ideas without abstracting from the sensible 
 data ; noAV, since God is as far su})erior to Ideas as these 
 are to sensible things, we must, iji order to reach God, ab- 
 stract from all Ideas. After thought has arrived at this 
 heig]it, it must push away tlie ladder which helped it rise, 
 and abandon itself to meditation ; it becomes contenq)lation 
 or adoration. To attcnipi to define God cither in thought 
 or in language means to lose liiin. 
 
 Plato's God is superior to being,' l)ut not to the Idea; 
 he is the king of Ideas and the Idea as sucli ; he is acces- 
 sible to reason. Tlic God of N(!o-I*lalonisiii is superior 
 
 ' itrpuh., VI., '){)[).
 
 170 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 even to the Idea,^ and therefore eludes thonght (eireKeLva 
 vo7](Teco<i} . Consequently, there is an undeniable difference 
 between the two systems. We have no right, however, 
 to exaggerate this difference and to bring Plotinus the 
 mystic in opposition with Plato the rationalist. The hu- 
 man mind can, according to Plotinus, be united with the 
 absolute, only after it has performed diligent intellectual 
 labor and has previously passed tln-ough all the interven- 
 ing stages between vulgar opinion {86^a) and philosophical 
 knowledge Qyvoi(n<i). Although he holds that thought 
 cannot penetrate into the sanctuary, he considers it as an 
 indispensable means of carrying us to the threshold of the 
 temple ; and though he discharges liis guide upon arriving 
 at the goal, it is not because he disdains him. On the 
 other hand, as we have seen, Plato's philosophy contains 
 all the elements of what has been called Alexandrian 
 mysticism : intellectual love, enthusiasm, the sage's delight 
 in the world of ideas .^ 
 
 The universe emanates from the absolute as light eman- 
 ates from the sun ; as heat, from fire ; the conclusion, from 
 the axiom. God is goochiess, the Father who desires that 
 all things should exist.^ But there is a vague or conscious 
 desire in all things that emanate from him to return to him 
 (eTncTrpo^rf). Everything is attracted to him and desires 
 to approach him. Individuality is not the final form of 
 existence ; it is merely the passage from God, the principle 
 of things, to God, their ideal goal ; from God, the infinite 
 hvvajJLi'i^ to God, the absolute ivepjeia. If the world is a 
 
 ^ Plotinus, it must be added, is not ahvays consistent. Like his 
 modern imitator, Schelling, he regards God, sometimes as the unity 
 which is superior to all contrasts and therefore to the contrast be- 
 tween matter and mind, sometimes as spirit in opposition to body. 
 The latter conception dominates his moral system. Asceticism and 
 the nirvana are the natural consequences of the view. 
 
 2 Enneads, I., 8, 2 ; III., 9, 3 ; V., 3-5. 
 
 8 Tiynmis, 29 E.
 
 PLOTmUS AKD KEO-PLATONISINI. 171 
 
 system of harmony, it is because all things converge toward 
 the same absolute. The return of being to its divine source 
 is made possible through thought, contemplation, intuition 
 (Oecopla)^ which alone gives the soul the supreme satisfac- 
 tion which it demands. To perceive, to see, to contem- 
 plate, is the goal of all action, of all striving, of all 
 movement. Each man seeks for the absolute in his own 
 manner. There are meditative natures and practical na-" 
 tures ; but the former are, according to Plotinus, superior 
 to the latter. Both aspire to the same goal. The former, 
 however, seek to reach it by the most direct way, i. e., by 
 thought ; the latter, by endless meanderings ; for action is 
 an aberration of thought and denotes a relative weakness 
 of the understanding (aadeveLa ^ew/Jia?). Contemplation is 
 not only the final goal of life, but life itself (e/c decopia^ koI 
 Oecopia icTTi^. Animals, plants, nay, everything in exist- 
 ence are endowed Avith perception. Since all life is ulti- 
 mately reduced to thought, and since God is the creator 
 of all things, we may say with Aristotle (qualifying the 
 statement as above), that God is pure thought, having no 
 other object than himself, the principle of intelligence, or 
 the power of intuition which makes us see all things with- 
 out seeing itself. 
 
 II. The Three Stages of Being. 1. Intelligence. — 
 Intelligence is the first divine emanation and therefore the 
 greatest thing in the world ; the succeeding emanations 
 are more and more imperfect. Creation is a fall, a pro- 
 gressive degeneration of the divine. In the intelligence, 
 tlie absolute unity of God splits up into intelligence proper 
 (voO?) and the intelligible world (/cocryu.09 yo7;To<?), subject 
 and object (to use the modern expressions). However, the 
 intelligence is, as compared to bodies, almost an absolute 
 unity ; at any rate, the intelligible world and the reason 
 contemplating it are not, as yet, separated either in time or 
 in space ; tlie voik and tlie Kdafio<; vo-qro'^ are in each other.
 
 172 GKEEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The Ideas are immanent in the intellect which conceives 
 them ; the intellect is inseparable from the Ideas. 
 
 The passage of the divine unity into this first duality, 
 the how of the emanation, is as much of a mystery as God 
 himself. Whatever rational explanation might be given, it 
 Avould still be insufficient. If the dyad, it has been said, 
 comes from the monad, then the latter contains the former 
 " in germ. But that would make the monad a dyad and not 
 a monad in the absolute sense. Others identify the One 
 and the All. But if God is only the sum of existing 
 things, then he is a mere word used to designate the result 
 of an addition, and not the supremely real principle from 
 which the things are derived. God is anterior to the All 
 (irpo irdvTcov'), in dignity if not in time. Still, we may 
 call Inm ttuv, in so far as he is the essence of everything 
 in existence. An attempt has been made to explain ema- 
 nation by calling it a partition of the original unity. But 
 the divine unity, which is not a numerical unity, is indivi- 
 sible. It has been compared with the gleaming of a bright 
 body (7re/)tXa/x-v/ri?), with the radiation of the sun, with a 
 cup that eternally overflows, because its contents are in- 
 finite and cannot be held in it. However beautiful these 
 figures may be, they are taken from the material world and 
 cannot explain the immaterial. Hence, emanation is in 
 reality a miracle (daviJ^a), like God himself. 
 
 There are two kinds of Ideas ^ : (1) genera (yepr]), or 
 general forms of all existing things, viz., being (6V), iden- 
 tity (rauTOT?;?), difference (erepoTiT;), rest (o-tcio-k:), motion 
 (^Kivrja-i^'), and (2) specific types of individual beings {eiSr])} 
 We may conceive all genera as modifications of the only 
 being, and all specific t}^es as comprehended in a single 
 being: the universal Tj-pe, or the Idea of the universe 
 (/coo-^09 vot]r6<i}. Everything that exists in the visible 
 world has its corresponding Idea or prototype in the in- 
 1 Enneads, XL, 1-3. ^ i^,, yi., o, 8.
 
 PLOTIXUS AND NEO-PLATONISM 173 
 
 telligible world. Not only the Idea of man, but Ideas of 
 Socrates, Plato, and so on, exist ; that is to say, there are 
 as many Ideas as individuals. Each one of us realizes a 
 distinct Idea. Hence the Idea is not the species resolving 
 itself into a number of passing individuals ; it is the in- 
 chvidual considered as eternal. From the fact that there 
 are as many Ideas as individuals, it does not follow that 
 the number of Ideas is unlimited. Though the number of 
 existing individuals is infuiite for our imagination, it is not 
 actually infinite ; if it were so, the universe would not be 
 a perfect being, i. e., perfect in the Greek sense (^wov irav- 
 reX&i'). So, too, a fixed and unchangeable number of Ideas 
 or types of individuals exist in the intelligence, the creation 
 of God. 
 
 2. The Soul. — The intelligence, too, is creative, like 
 the absolute whence it emanates, but its productive power 
 is less. Its emanation or radiation is the soul Q^vxv^->^ 
 which is like the yoO? but inferior to it. The fact is, 
 reason finds its Ideas in itself ; they are its immanent 
 possession and sul^stance, while the soul must search for 
 them or ascend to them liy reflection (Sidvoia)., and there- 
 fore reaches, not the Ideas themselves, but tlieir more or 
 less adequate images, the simple notions (\070t). The soul 
 is not, like the intellect, endowed with immediate and 
 complete intuition ; it is restricted to discursive thought, 
 or analysis. 
 
 It is subordinate to the intellect, and therefore strives 
 towards it as reason itself strives towards, God. Its mis- 
 sion is to become wliat the intellect is a priori ; that is, 
 intelligent {voepd). Just as there is but one absolute, one 
 reason, and one intelligible woild, sf) there is, at the bottoni 
 of all individual souls, but one single soul manifesting 
 itself in infinitely different forms: the soul of 1 lie world 
 {'^^XV '^^^ Koafiov). Ivike tlie vov'i, mIucIi contemplates 
 * Eiincwla, \y.
 
 174 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the absolute and also produces tlie ■yjrvxv-, tlie soul has 
 two functions, one of which is to contemplate and look 
 inward, where it finds the Ideas and the absolute, while 
 the other is expansive and creative. Its emanation, wliich 
 is less perfect than itself, is the body.-' 
 
 3. The Bod//. — Though the body is far removed from the 
 source of all things (God is the One, the body, the greatest 
 plurality), it bears the stamp of the absolute. The intel- 
 lect has its Ideas ; the soul, its ^notions ; the body, its 
 forms. Through these the body still belongs to the higher 
 spheres of being : they are to the body what perceptions 
 are to the soul, what Ideas are to reason : a reflection of 
 the absolute, a trace of the divine. The form of bodies 
 represents what reality tliey have ; their matter, what 
 they lack of reality ; their form is their being ; their mat- 
 ter their non-being. Corporeal nature {(f>vai'i) fluctuates 
 between being and non-being ; it is eternal becoming, and 
 everything in it is in perpetual change. 
 
 After the world of bodies comes pure matter, or non 
 being, an obscure and bottomless abyss {aireipov)^ as it 
 were, into which the ideal world projects its rays. Mat- 
 ter is not body, for every body is composed of matter and 
 form ; it is but the substratum, the principle of its inertia ; 
 it has neither form, nor dimension, nor color, nor anything 
 that characterizes the body; all these qualities proceed 
 from the formal principle, the absolute ; it has no other 
 attribute than privation (o-Tep?;crt<?). Since all force and 
 life has its source in the intellect and in God, matter is 
 impotence, boundless indigence, the negation of unity, the 
 cause of the infinite multitude of bodies, incoherence, dif- 
 fusion, the absolute absence of form, i. e., ugliness itself ; 
 the absence of the good, i. e., evil itself. ^ From the stand- 
 point of Plotinus as well as of Hellenism in general, unity, 
 form, intelligence, beaiity, and goodness are synonymous 
 1 Enneads, III. 2 7^,^ n.
 
 PLOTINUS AND NEO-PLATONISM 175 
 
 terms, as are also, on the other liand, pluralit}-, matter, 
 ugliness, and evil- 
 It must not be understood that he considers matter and 
 evil as non-existent. To assume that he denies the exist- 
 ence of matter and of evil would be equivalent to making 
 liim say that poverty is the absence of wealth and there- 
 fore nothing, that it does not exist, and, consequently, that 
 charity is useless. Matter is so great a reality that its in- 
 fluence is exercised, not only upon the corporeal sphere, 
 but also upon the soul and upon reason itself. We have 
 seen that the body still, though vaguely, resembles the 
 mind, because of the form which it assumes and wliich is 
 nothing but an embodied Idea. Conversely, we shall say, 
 however superior the mind may be to corporeal nature, it 
 is not ahsolutely immaterial. Matter exists in the mind, 
 though in another form than in nature ; i. e., as the notion of 
 matter (v\t] voi^rrj), intelligibly, in the conceptual state, not 
 corporeally. But more than that ; not only is matter in the 
 mind in so far as the mind conceives it ; it is mingled with 
 every one of its thoughts, indissolubly connected with all 
 its conceptions. Without matter, the mind would not be 
 distinct from the absolute. In fact, God alone is unity 
 in the absolute sense ; the intellect is not unity in the 
 same sense ; in it unity expands into a plurality of Ideas, 
 which are cUstinct from one another, although they are 
 perceived by one and the same intellectual intuition. It 
 is true, the Ideas in our mind are not separated corporeally; 
 but it is also certain that the mind contains them as plurali- 
 ties. Now, matter is the very principle of plurality. Hence 
 it lies at the very basis of the intellect, wliicli, without it, 
 would be SAvallowed uj) in the absolute unity of (iod. 
 
 In order to understand this paradox, whicli is essentially 
 Platonic, it must be remembered that the matter of Plato, 
 Aristotle, and Plotinus, is not the matter of the material- 
 ists, l)nt wliat Scliclling and Schopcidiaucr would call
 
 176 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 will^ or the will-to-be ; it is not body, but the transcendent 
 substratwn, the principle of corporeality, that which makes 
 the body a body, but is itself an incorporeal thing like the 
 mind. It even transcends the intelligence ; it rises above 
 it like an impenetrable mystery that defies the reason even 
 of the gods. Moreover, Plotinus does not place matter 
 among the genera ; he places it beyond the world of Ideas 
 in the supra-intelligible realm which reason cannot reach, 
 although we may recognize the Idea of matter in the ideas 
 of otlicrncss and movement. If we call what can be the 
 object of intelligence, what the intelligence can define, 
 comprehend, or embrace under an exact formula, " intelli- 
 gible," then matter is evidently not intelligible ; for it is 
 the opposite of form; it resists all limitation and conse- 
 quently all comprehension. To comprehend matter is to 
 see darkness ; to see darkness is to see nothing ; hence, to 
 comprehend matter is to comprehend nothing. 
 
 Is matter a second absolute ? One is sometimes tempted 
 to regard Plotinus as a decided dualist ; his system of 
 ethics, especially, lays itself open to the charge of dual- 
 ism. But the metaphysician cannot assume two absolutes. 
 Plotinus, therefore, recalling the statement of Aristotle 
 that the first matter and the first form are identical,^ con- 
 ceives the supra-intelligent matter, or, in other terms, the 
 first cause of bodies, as identical with God. Matter, ^^'hich 
 Platonism loves to call the infinite, is, in the last analysis, 
 nothing but infinite potentiality, unlimited productivity, 
 the creative power of God. The highest ivepyeia is also 
 the highest Bvva/jii<;. How is that possible ? The question 
 is the same as the one raised above : How can plurality 
 emanate from divine unity ? How can we explain emana- 
 tion, creation ? That is a mystery. 
 
 III. Ethics. — The soul, which is intermediate between 
 the intellect and the body, contains elements of both, and 
 1 Metaphysics, VTTT., 6, 19.
 
 PLOTINUS AND NEO-PLATONIS.M 177 
 
 is an epitome of the universe. It is, as it were, the meet- 
 ing place of all cosmical powers. Logical necessity reigns 
 in the intellectual sphere ; physical necessity, in the world 
 of bodies. The soul is the seat of the free will. It is sub- 
 ject to the allurements of the body and those of the intel- 
 lect. It may therefore turn towards reason and live 
 a purely intellectual life, but it may also turn towards 
 matter, fall, and become embodied in a low and earthly 
 body.^ Hence, there are three kinds of souls : (1) souls 
 which live for reason and for God, or divine souls ; (2) souls 
 which waver between mind and body, heaven and earth : 
 demons, or geniuses which are partly good and partly bad ; 
 (3) souls which dwell in matter and inhabit base bodies. 
 The heavenly souls, like tlie soul of the world itself, are 
 supremely happy. Their happiness consists in their ap- 
 athy^ in their obedience to divine reason, and in the con- 
 tem})lation of the absolute. Their bodies consist wholly 
 of light, and have nothing material in them, using this 
 term in the sense of terrestrial? Eternally perfect and 
 always the same, they have neither memor}^ nor prevision, 
 neither hope nor regret ; for only such beings have mem- 
 ory and hope as change their conditions, be it for better 
 or for worse. They are not even, like the human soul, 
 conscious of themselves ; they are absorbed in the con- 
 templation of Ideas and of the absolute. It is this un- 
 consciousness, this exclusive apperception of divine things, 
 wliich constitutes their supreme liappiness. 
 
 Human souls were not always enclosed in base bodies ; 
 they were at first heavenly souls, conscious of God alone 
 and not of themselves; but they separated their lives from 
 the universal life, in order to become selfish individuals 
 and to assume vulgar bodies, which isolate tliem from each 
 other. The assumption of an earthly body is a fall for 
 
 1 Enneails, IL, 3, 0; TIL, T), 6; TV., :5, 8. 
 
 2 Cf. St. Taul, First Letter to the Corinthians, XV., 40. 
 
 12
 
 178 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 which the miseries of our present existence are the just 
 punishment.! It was a free act, in so far as no power out- 
 side of us forced us to do it ; a necessary act, in so far as 
 our own nature determined it. Every man is the author 
 of his fate, and, conversely, his fate depends upon his in- 
 dividual character. True, we choose only the fate wliich 
 we can choose, but we choose this simply because we do 
 not desire anything else. 
 
 Moreover (and here we note a difference between Neo- 
 Platonism and modern pessimism in favor of the former), 
 incarnation is but a relative misfortune and even a bless- 
 ing, provided the soul descends into matter merely in order 
 to transform it, and ascends heavenwards as soon as pos- 
 sible. Nay, the soul profits by its contact with the body, 
 for it thereby not only learns to recognize evil but also 
 to exercise its hidden powers, to produce works wliich it 
 would otherwise not have been able to accomplish. Fur- 
 thermore, though closely connected with the body, it re- 
 mains separate from it. This is proved by the fact that, 
 instead of assisting our aspirations towards the ideal ^^^orld 
 the body opposes them, and that the philosopher welcomes 
 death.2 The human soul is like the Olympus whose sum- 
 mit is steeped in azure while its sides are beaten by the 
 storm ; it is not confounded with the body, but escapes its 
 bondage by means of the intelligence, its better part. 
 
 The ethical system of Plotinus reminds us of Plato and 
 Stoicism. The end of human life is the purification of the 
 soul and its gradual assimilation with the di^'inity. Three 
 roads lead to God:^ music (art), love, and philosophy; 
 three paths, or rather a single one with three stages. The 
 artist seeks for the Idea in its sensil)le manifestations ; the 
 lover seeks for it in the human soul ; the philosopher, 
 
 1 Cf. p. 46, note 2. 
 
 2 Cf. St. Paul, Epistle to tie Philippians, I, 23. 
 ' Enneatis, T., B.
 
 PORPHYRY, JAMBLICHUS, PROCLUS 179 
 
 finally, seeks for it in the sphere in wliich it dwells without 
 alloy, — in the intelligihle world and in God. The man who 
 has tasted the delights of meditation and contemplation 
 foregoes both art and love. The traveller who has beheld 
 and admii-ed a royal palace forgets the beauty of the apart- 
 ments when he perceives the sovereign. For the philoso- 
 pher, beauty in art, nay, living beauty itself, is but a pale 
 reflection of absolute beaut}^ He despises the body and its 
 pleasures in order to concentrate all his thoughts upon the 
 only thing that endures forever. The joys of the philoso- 
 pher are unspeakable. These joj'S make liim forget, not 
 only the earth, but Ids own individuality ; he is lost in the 
 pure intuition of the absolute. His rapture is a union 
 (eWo-t?) of the human soul Avith the cUvine intellect, an 
 ecstasy, a flight of the soul to its heavenly home.^ As 
 long as he lives in the body, the pliilosopher enjoys this 
 vision of God only for certain short moments, — Plotinus 
 had four such transports, — but what is the exception in 
 this life will be the rule and the normal state of the soul 
 in the life to come. Death, it is true, is not a direct pas- 
 sage to a state of perfection. The soul which is purified 
 by philosophy here below, continues to be purified beyond 
 the grave until it is divested of individuality itself, the 
 last vestige of its eartlily bondage .^ 
 
 § 2G. The Last Neo-Platonic Polytheists. Porphyry, 
 Jamblichus, Proclus 
 
 1. Ph)tiiius Avas succeeded in the Neo-Platonic school at 
 Rr)me by his friend Malchus or PnRPiTYrvY,^ a native Plire- 
 nician, who publislied the Erinrnds. Porphyry is still more 
 convinced than liis master of the identity of the doctrines 
 of the Academy and the T,yceum. Although much inferior 
 to Plotinus, on whom his teachings essentially dejx'nd, he, 
 
 » Enneads, V., 5, 10. « Id., IV., 3, 32. » Died at Roiuo, 301.
 
 180 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 nevertheless, exercised an influence on the progress of phi- 
 losophy during the following centuries, because of the clear- 
 ness with which he set forth the problem of universals in 
 liis Introduction to the Oater/uries of Aristotle.^ Indeed, the 
 question whether genera and species are realities apart 
 from the thouglit wliich conceives them, forms the chief 
 topic of interest during the Middle Ages. 
 
 Neo-Platonism changes in character towards the end of 
 the fourth century without essentially modifying its prin- 
 ciples. Plotinus and Porphyry, who antedate the reign 
 of Constantine and the ultimate triumph of Christianity, 
 are outspoken opponents of superstition, like all the great 
 tliinkers since the days of Xenophanes. But among their 
 successors the search for truth is gradually subordinated to 
 the interests of religion and apologetics. After ten cent- 
 uries of opposition against traditional religion, philosophy 
 became alarmed at its work of destruction ; it came to the 
 conclusion that its stubborn opposition had simply advanced 
 the cause of a religion that w^as foreign to the Greek spirit 
 and hostile to classic culture, and that its official repre- 
 sentatives would be a thousand times more intolerant than 
 the Greek and Roman priesthood. Thus it happened that 
 philosophy, the sworn enemy of the popular faith, became 
 the palladium of the persecuted gods ; she became ancilla 
 Panthei, prior to becoming ancilla Ecdesice. To promote 
 
 1 PorplHjriide quinque vocihm, sice in categorias Aristotelis inirodiictio 
 (eiVaywy^), Paris, 15i3 ; Latin translation, Venice, 1546, 1506. We also 
 have of Porphyry a Life of Protagoras, a Life of Plotinus, and an 
 Epistle to Aneho (fragments collected by Gale, Oxford, 1678), etc. Sev- 
 eral of his treatises, the most important perhaps, are lost. Sources : 
 Suidas ; Eunapius, Vita Soph. ; Augustine, De civitate Dei, X. ; the 
 De Mysteriis Mgyptinrum, ascribed to Jamblichus ; [Ritter and Preller, 
 pp. 541 ff.] ; N. Bouillet, Porphi/re, son role dans Ve'cole ne'oplatonicienne, 
 etc. Paris, 1864; Adrien ']s&v\\\e, Julien V Apostat et la philosopTiie du 
 polytheisme, Paris and Neuchatel, 1877. See, besides, the works quoted 
 on p. 166.
 
 PORPHYRY, JAIVIBLICHUS, PROCLUS 181 
 
 polytheism, to promote it at all hazards : such Avas the 
 desperate task undertaken by lier. Henceforth she re- 
 gards everything in paganism as good ; she not only 
 excuses and tolerates the strangest superstitions, the ex- 
 orcism of spirits, the practices of sorcery, magic, and the- 
 urgy, but even commends them and practises them with 
 feverish zeal. The Greek mind literally lapses into its 
 second cliildhood. 
 
 The death-struggle is, however, broken by lucid mo- 
 ments. Among the few sui'viving defenders of the dying 
 polytheistic faith we must mention two men who, though 
 compromising with paganism and pompously assuming the 
 title of hierophants, bring the history of ancient philosophy 
 to a brilliant close. I mean Jamblichus of Chalcis in 
 Coelesyria (died about 380), tlie most distinguished cham- 
 pion of what we call Syrian Neo-Platonism (in order to 
 distinguish this ultra-mystical movement from the philos- 
 ophy of Plotinus, which is still profoundly Greek), and 
 Proclns of Byzantium (412-485), wdio taught at Athens 
 and occupied a position between the school of Rome and 
 Jamblichus, of whom he was an enthusiastic admirer. 
 
 2. Jamblichus ^ draws liis inspiration from the specula- 
 tions of non-Christian literature, from Pythagoras, Plato, 
 the religious tratUtions of the Orient and Egypt, and 
 especially from his sacred triple ternary. His mathemati- 
 cal genius and Inilliant imagination enable him to under- 
 take a philosophical reconstruction of the pagan Pantheon. 
 Tlic gods emanate from tlic dcjjths of the unspeakable 
 unity in ternary series, and form a triple halo, as it were, 
 
 1 De vita Ptjlhagorce ; Protrepticce oraliones ad philo.tnphiam ; De 
 tnysteriis A^r/pliorum (Creek and Latin ed. liy Tli. (iale, Oxford, 
 1078; by (i. ParUu'V, Bfiilin, IB."). Oilier soiux-os : Proclus, In 
 Timcpum; Suidas; [Kilter and Preller, pp. nili if.]; IlelxMistrcit, Dc 
 Jamhilchi, jifiilosoplii Si/ri, doctrina, etc., Lei)),sic, ITUl. [Knj;l. tr. of 
 Life of Pifthngorus, by Taylor, London, 1818 ; E<jyplian Mysteries, 
 Chiswick,'l82i.j
 
 X82 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 around the Monad of monads. He opposes the Christian 
 conception of the God-man and exaggerates the theological 
 spiritualism of Plotinus hy declaring the absolute to be 
 non-covwiunicaUe (a/xedeKTO'i). The Supreme God is not 
 only divested of all intelligence, but of all qualities what- 
 soever. Hence the real beings do not participate in the 
 absolute unity but in the secondary unities (evaSa) eman- 
 atino- from it. These beings are also transcendent (virep- 
 ovaiai), but plural. This hierarchy of derived gods is 
 divided into three stages : intellectual gods {voepoi)^ supra- 
 mundane gods [vTrepKoafiiOL), and the immanent gods of 
 the world (^ejKoafiLot'). We come into communication 
 only with thesfe gods (the Ideas of Plato, the Numbers of 
 Pythagoras, the substantial Forms of Aristotle) ; they are 
 our Providence. The absolute has no share in the gover- 
 nance of things. 
 
 3. Pkoclus ^ derives the priestly characteristics of liis 
 philosophy from Jamblichus, and his systematic and schol- 
 astic tendencies from Plotinus. He bases his system on 
 the triple triad of Jamblichus, and deduces from the abso- 
 lute and non-communicable (a/^iedeKTos) unity: first, being 
 (oV), i. e., the infinite {airetpov), the end or form (Trcpa?), and 
 their unity, the finite (/juktop, ireirepaaixevov) : secondly, 
 life (^ft)?;), i. e., potentiality (Svvafjn^'), existence (yTrap^t?), 
 and their unity, intelligible life (^ft)^ vojjt/]) ; thirdly, intel- 
 ligence (yoO?), i. e., static thought (^fxeveiv'), thought in 
 motion or perception (irpoLevaC), and their unity, reflective 
 
 1 Works of Proclus : In theologiam P/a/o?; i>,libri VI. ; Instiiutw theo- 
 logica ; In Platonis Timmum, etc. Prodi opera omnia, ed. V. Cousin, 
 Paris, 1819-27, 2d ed. in 6 vols., 1864 ; [Ritter and PreUer, pp. 5.56 ff.]. 
 See on Proclus : Marinus, Vita Prodi; Suidas ; Berger, Produs, expo- 
 sition de sa doctrine, Paris, 1810 ; J. Simon, Du Commentaire de Produs 
 sur le Time'e de Platon, Paris, 1839; C. 11. Kirchner, De Prodi neo- 
 platonid metaphijsica, Berlin, 1846. See also concerning Jamblicluis 
 and Proclus the histories of the Alexandrian school mentioned on 
 page 166.
 
 PORPHYRY, JAMBLICHUS, PROCLUS 183 
 
 thought (^eTTLarpocf)^'). Each of these three triads^ reveals 
 to those initiated into pliilosophy (^/xva-nKW^ one of the 
 aspects of the first and supra-intelligible cause : fii'st, his 
 unspeakable unity ; secondly, his inexhaustible fertility 
 (vTrepoxyf) ; thirdly, his infinite perfection. These are the 
 emanations of the absolute. The absolute in itself is 
 superior to being and even to thought, as the principle is 
 superior to its consequence and the cause to its eifect, and 
 therefore forever unknowable. Whatever is supernatural 
 in its essence can be reached only by supernatural means ; 
 theurgy 2 alone can reveal it to the initiated. Knowledge 
 is confined to the intelligible sphere and needs the realities 
 of religion in order to attain to the supra-intelligible. 
 
 Tills is, in language freed from senile pedantry, the last 
 word of Neo-Platonic metaphysics, " the last will and testa- 
 ment " of antique thought. From the ontological point of 
 view and compared with primitive Platonism, Neo-Pla- 
 tonism would be an advance in the monistic direction, if it 
 had been content to subordinate the Idea to a higher prin- 
 ciple containing both being and thought.^ But its oppo- 
 sition to Clu-istianity, the fundamental dogma ^ of which 
 assumes the communicalility of the divine, impelled it 
 wantonly to exaggerate the transcendency of this supreme 
 principle ; which was precisely the chief defect of Platon- 
 ism. And how much inferior it is to Platonism fiom the 
 ethical and religious point of view ! Proclus looks upon 
 the practice of magic as the essence of religion ; for Plato 
 religion means the 2^f^(:icticc of justice. There is as great a 
 difference between these two conceptions as between ma- 
 ture, enlightened, and vigorous manhood and decrepit and 
 superstitious old age. 
 
 1 Cf. the triple triad in the system of Hegel. 
 
 ^ Qfovpyia, (pyov roii 6fov, manifestation of the divine power. 
 
 • Tlif! irill of concrete spiritualism. 
 
 ■• 'J'lie docrnia of the incarnation.
 
 184 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 In 529 the last refuge of polytheistic Neo-Platonism, the 
 school at Athens where Proclus had taught/ was closed by 
 order of the Emperor Justinian. The- public manifested 
 such indifference towards these ruins of the past, that the 
 edict was scarcely noticed. Christianity had taken pos- 
 session of the empire two centuries ago ; the concrete and 
 thrilling questions of religion, wliich is a product of the 
 will, and the troubles caused by the invasions of the bar- 
 barians, superseded the serene and peaceful Oawpia. 
 
 ^ The last scholarchs are : Marinus of Flavia Neapolis in Pales- 
 tine, the successor of Proclus, Isidore of Alexandria^ and Zeno- 
 dotus and Damascius of Damas (Quiestiones de primis principiis, ed. 
 Kopp, Francf., 1826). The school was closed while the latter was 
 at its head. With the school of Athens is connected the name of the 
 Cilician Simplicius, the excellent commentator of Epictetus and Aris- 
 totle (Categories, De anima, De calo, and Physics), who was a fellow, 
 student and af terwai-ds a pupil and companion in exile of Damasciu>>-
 
 n 
 
 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 FIRST PERIOD 
 
 REIGX OF PLATONIC^CHRISTIAN^ THEOLOGY 
 § 27. Christian Platonism^ 
 
 The breath of expiring Hellenism passed into Chris- 
 tianity. The doctrines of Plato and his latest interpreters 
 continued to influence the ablest thinkers among the fol- 
 lowers of the Gospel, and the philosophy of the Church 
 during the entire ]\Iiddle Ages merely re-echoes the teach- 
 ings of the great Athenian philosopliers. 
 
 In the cosmopolitan city of Alexandria, where the Greek 
 mind came in contact with the Semitic genius, there was 
 
 1 For Patristic speculation, consult the general histories of philo- 
 sophy, the Church histories, and the works mentioned on page 10 ; 
 [Collection of the works of the Fathers, Patrum Aposlnllcorwn Opera, 
 ed. by O. de Gerhardt, A. Ilarnack, and Th. Zahn, Leipsic, 1875 ff.; 
 Eng. trans.. Library of Xicene and Post-Xicene Fathers, ed. Schaff 
 and Wace; Moller, Lehrbuch der Kirchengeschichte (vol. I., Die alte 
 Kirche, Freiburg, i. B., 1889) ; A. Ilarnack, Geschichte der altchrist- 
 lichen Litterafur bis Emebim, Part L, Leipsic, 1893. — Tr.] For the 
 systems classified under heretical Gnosticism, see [Neandcr, Gene- 
 tuicke Enlicickelung der vornehmlen gnoslischen Si/stterne, Berlin, 1818; 
 Engl. tr. by Ton-ey, Boston, 180.5] ; J. Matter, Hisfoire criti/jue du 
 (jnoMicisme, .3 vols., Paris, 182-3; 2d ed., 1843; F. Chr. Baur, Die chrlst- 
 liche Gnosh, Tubingen, 1835; [Lipsius Der Gnoaliciamua, etc., Leipsic, 
 1800 : W. Moller, Geschichte der Kosmnlof/ie in der (jricchischen Kirche 
 bii auf Orirjeries, Halle, ISOO, pp. 189-473; H. L. Mansel, The Gnostic 
 Heresies, etc., London, 1H75. — Tr.]
 
 186 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 formed, at the beginning of the third century, a kind of 
 Chi'istian Neo-Platonic schooL The Latin Fathers, Ter- 
 tullian,^ Arnobius, and Lactantius,^ rejected philosophy as 
 a heathen product, contact with wliich must be avoided. 
 The Greek and Egyptian Fathers, however, never ceased 
 to cultivate it. Indeed, the attacks cUrected against the 
 Gospel by philosophy itself compelled them to study it. 
 Owing to the successful pressure thus exerted, the Christ- 
 ian faith was reduced to dogma {Soj/jlo) ; it was formu- 
 lated and systematized. The authors of the dogmas had to 
 'philosophize in spite of themselves and in self-defence, so to 
 speak. Some of them went so far as to regard the teach- 
 ings of the heathen sages as divine rcAelalions similar to 
 the Gospel. Plato was the only philosopher A^•ho received 
 serious consideration. The school of Alexancbia tauglit 
 an essentially religious })hilosophy, differing in this respect 
 from the other schools, wliich were, for tlie most part, scep- 
 tical. One could not but recognize certain similarities 
 between Plato and Christianity; but how was this rela- 
 tionship, which sometimes amounted to identity, to be 
 explained ? Some — and they were in the majority — 
 believed that Plato had cbawn from the writings of 
 the Old Testament. The enlightened minority concluded 
 that the philosophers worthy of the name must have 
 been inspired by tlie same divine reason (Xo'709) wliich 
 revealed itself in Jesus of Nazareth. Still others had re- 
 course to both hj^potheses. Justin the INIartyr, the author 
 of an Apology of Christianity, assumes that the Xoyo^ is 
 
 ^ TertulL, De prcescript. hcer., c. 7; Apol., c. 47; Adv. Marcion.,Y ., 
 19. The Credo quia absurdum of Tertullian is to be taken literally. 
 If reason has become deceptive in consequence of the Fall, it is evi- 
 dent that a doctrine contradicting it (an absurd doctrine) has more 
 chances of being true than one conforming to it. Nothing is more 
 logical than the challenge which this distinguished theologian hurls at 
 reason. 
 
 * Lact., Div. instit; III., 1.
 
 CHEISTIAN PLATONISM 187 
 
 universal in its operation, and claims eternal happiness for 
 Socrates, Heraclitus, and, in general, for those among the 
 heathen, Avho, though not knowing Jesus, lived according 
 to Keason.^ Athenagoras, the author of the treatise On 
 the Resurrection of the Dead, Tatian the Apologist, St. 
 Clement of Alexandria, and his chsciple Origen, all express 
 Neo-Platonic conceptions in their A^ritings. The apostles, 
 says Origen,^ have set forth the fundamental doctrines of 
 the faith in a manner capable of being understood by the 
 ignorant and the learned alike, leaving it to such among 
 their successors as were endowed with the Spirit to ths- 
 cover the reasons for their assertions. Origen consequently 
 makes a chstinction between the popular and the scientific 
 manner of expressing the Christian faith, between the form 
 it assumes in the writings of the apostles and the form in 
 which it must be conceived by the Christian pliilosopher : 
 a distinction which forms the basis of Scholastic rational- 
 ism. Finally, Athanasius, Basil the Great, Gregory of 
 N3'ssa, Gregory of Nazianzus, and among the Latin Fathers 
 (most of whom were hostile to philosoph}-), Augustine, 
 were directly or indirectly influenced by Academic and 
 Alexandrian teachings. 
 
 It would be impossible to enter upon a detailed study 
 of the Patristic doctrines without encroaching upon the 
 domain of pure theology ; hence it will be enough for our 
 special purpose to explain the philosophy of Augustine, 
 whose writings form the connecting link between Greek 
 thought and Scholastic speculation. 
 
 ^ Apolor/J/, TI., p. 83 : Ti)v Xpia-Tuv irjiUiTi'iTOKov tov dtov (ivai (8i8dx0rilJ-(v, 
 Koi 7vp'jffxr]Vv<T<ni(V \6yov oura ov t,uv ytVoy duOpunrtou fifT((T)(f ' kui ol fiera 
 Xoyov jiiuxravTfi ■x^piaTinvo'i fieri-, Kav tidfoi (wofiia-drjaav, olou fv"E\\q(ri [lev 
 SooK/juTT^f Koi H/ju((X«trof k(u aK\oi iroXXoi. 
 
 2 De princ'qnis, rreface. J. Dtiiiis, De la philosuphie d'Orighie, I'aiis, 
 1884.
 
 188 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 § 28. St. Augustine 
 
 After a youth of dissipation, the rhetorician Aurelius 
 AuGUSTiNUS of Thagaste, Africa, (354-430), embraced the 
 religion of his mother. He united in his soul a deep love 
 of Christ and an ardent zeal for philosophy, although, 
 after becoming Bishop of Hippo, he gradually favored an 
 absolute submission to the religious authority rei^resented 
 by him. His writings, the most important of which are 
 the Confessions and the City of G-od,^ have left a deep 
 impress upon the doctrines and the entire literature of 
 the Roman Church. 
 
 For him as for Plato, science means a purer, clearer, 
 more exalted life, the life of the thinker.^ Reason is 
 capable of comprehending God (cajjahilis) -, for God has 
 given it to us in order that we may know all tilings and 
 consequently God.^ To philosophize is to see truth directly 
 and without the intervention of the eyes of the body. Rea- 
 son is the eye of the soul. Wisdom is the highest truth 
 after which we should strive. Now, what is wisdom but 
 God ? To have wisdom means to have God. True philo- 
 sophy is therefore identical with true religion : * both have 
 the same strivings for the eternal. Why should God de- 
 spise Reason, his first-born Son, — Reason, wliich is God 
 
 1 Other writings of St. Augustine : De libera arhitrio ; De vera reli- 
 gione; De immortalitate animce ; De prcedestinatione et gratia ; Retractiones ; 
 "etc. Worlcs of St. Augustine, Paris, 1835, ft. ; [vols. XXXIT.-XLVIL 
 of Migne's collection; tr. ed. by Dods, 15 vols., Edinburgh, 1871-77, 
 also in Scliaff's library, Nicene and Post-Xicene Fathers, vols. L-VIII., 
 Buffalo, 1886-88. See Bindemann, Der lieilige Augustinus, .3 vols., 
 Berlin, etc., 1844-69; A. Dorner, Augustinus, etc., Berlin, 1873; Bohr- 
 inger, Geschichte der Kirche Chri>^ti (vol. XL), 2d ed., Zurich, 1861; 
 Xeander, Allgemeiiie Geschichte der Religion, etc. (II., 1, 2), 8d ed., 
 Gotha, 1850; Eng. tr. by J. Torrey. — Tr.]; Ferraz, La psijchologie 
 de Saint Angus! in, Paris, 1863. 
 
 2 De libera arbitrio, I., 7. « Id., II., 3, 6. * De vera religione, 5.
 
 ST. AUGUSTINE 189 
 
 himself ! He gave it to us in order to make us more per- 
 fect than other beings. Nay, fuith, which some oppose 
 to reason, is possible only to a being endowed with reason. 
 Chronologically, faith precedes intelligence : in order to 
 understand a tiling we must first believe it, — credo ut 
 iiitdligam. However, though faith is a condition of 
 knowledge, it is nevertheless a provisional state, infe- 
 rior to knowledge, and ultimately resolves itself into it. 
 The theocUcy of St. Augustine is essentially Platonic, 
 and at times even aj)proaches the boldest conceptions of 
 the school of Alexandiia. God is the being beyond whom, 
 outside of whom, and without whom, nothing exists ; he is 
 the being below whom, in and through whom, everything 
 exists that has reality ; he is the beginning, the middle, 
 and the end of all things.^ Goodness, justice, and wis- 
 dom are not accidental attributes of God, but his innermost 
 essence. The same is true of his metaphysical attributes. 
 Omnipotence, omnipresence, and eternity are not mere acci- 
 dents of the Divine Being, but his divine essence. God is 
 substantially omnipresent, without, however, being every- 
 thing ; everything is in him, though he is not the All. He 
 is good and yet without quality ; he is great, without being 
 a quantity; he is the creator of intelligence and yet supe- 
 rior to it ; he is present everj^where, without being bound to 
 any place ; he exists and yet is nowhere ; he lives eternally 
 and yet is not in time ; he is the principle of all change 
 and yet immutable. In speculating about God, reason is 
 necessarily involved in a series of antinomies ; it states 
 what he is not, without arriving at any definite conclu- 
 sion as to liis nature; it conceives him, — in this sense it 
 is capable of him (capahilis'), — but it cannot comprehend 
 him in tlie fullness of liis perfection. Tlie imj)ortant point 
 is to distinguish carefully between God and tlic woild. St. 
 Augustine, whose conceptions closely bordei' \\\Hm panthe- 
 
 1 SnUlnrj., T., 3-1.
 
 190 nilLOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 ism, us the preceding shows, escapes it by his doctrine of 
 creation ex nihilo.^ If the universe has emanated from 
 God, then it is itself of divine essence and identical with 
 God. Hence, it is not an emanation but was created by an 
 act of divine freedom. God is not the soul of the world ; 
 the world is not the body of God, as the Stoics held. The 
 immanency of God in the world would be contrary to the 
 divine majesty .^ 
 
 Some falsely interpret the doctrine of the Trinity in the 
 tritheistic or polytheistic sense. Here lies another danger. 
 The tlu-ee hypostases, although distinct, constitute but one 
 and the same God, just as reason, will, and the emotions 
 form but one and the same human being.^ St. Augustine's 
 criticisms on Arianism are very profound. What do you 
 mean, he demands of the Arians, by assuming that the Son 
 created the world at the command of the Father ? Do you 
 not thereby assert that God the Father did not create the 
 world, but simply ordered a demiurge to create it ? What 
 is the Son if not the word of God, and what is a command 
 if not an act of speech ? Hence, God commanded the Son 
 through the Son to create the world. What a strange and 
 absurd conclusion ! Arianism errs in that it desires to pie- 
 ture the Trinity to itself ; it imagines two beings placed 
 very near to each other; each one, however, occupying 
 his particular place ; and one of them commands, while the 
 other obeys. Arianism should have seen that the com- 
 mand by means of which God created the world out of 
 nothing simply means the creative Word itself. God is 
 a spirit, and we should not and cannot form an image 
 of the immaterial.* 
 
 Inasmuch as God created the world b}' an act of free- 
 dom, we must assume that the world had a beginning ; for 
 
 ^ De libero arbitrio, L, 2. ^ j)g ciritate Dei, IV., 12. 
 
 ^ De trinitate, IX., 3 ; X., 11. * Contra serm. avian.
 
 ST. AUGUSTINE 1^1 
 
 eternal creation, the conception of Origen and the Neo- 
 Platonists, is sj-nonyinous with emanation. Philoso^jhers 
 raise the objection that creation in time would imply an 
 eternity of inaction on part of the Creator ; but they 
 are wrong. Their error consists in considering the eter- 
 nit}' which i^rcccdcd creation as an infinitely-long dura- 
 tion. Duration is time. Now, outside of creation there 
 is neither space, nor time, nor, consequently, duration,^ 
 Time or duration is the measure of motion ; where there 
 is no movement there is no duration. Since there is no 
 movement in eternity and in God, there is no duration in 
 him, and time, as Plato aptly remarks, begins only with 
 movement, that is, with the existence of finite things. 
 Hence, it is incorrect to say that the God of the Clu-is- 
 tians cUd not create things until after an infinite series of 
 intinitely-long periods of absolute inaction. Moreover, St. 
 Augustine recognizes the difficulty of conceiving God 
 without the universe. On this point, as well as on many 
 others, Augustine the philosopher conflicts witli Augustine 
 the Christian. This constant discord between his faith and 
 his reason leads to numerous inconsistencies and contradic- 
 tions. God, for example, created the world by an act of 
 his free-will, and yet creation is not the result of caprice 
 but of an eternal and immutable decree.^ It is immaterial 
 whether the immutal)le will of God compels liim to create 
 the world at a fixed period of time or whether it eternally 
 compels him to do it; in either case we have absolute de- 
 termination. St. Augustine i-oalizes this, and eventually 
 uiireservedl}^ declares that divine freedom is the princi])le 
 and supreme norm of things. Since llie di\ine will is the 
 idtimate prineiple. tliau wliieh there is nothing higher, it 
 is useless and absurd to inquire into the final cause of 
 
 » Confes^x., XI , U ft. ; De civ. Del, XL, 4-G. 
 2 De'cio. Del, Xlb, 17.
 
 192 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 creation.^ God called other beings than himself into ex- 
 istence, because he willed to do so. Human reason has no 
 right to go fartlier than that. All it may do is to ask itself 
 the question : Why did God make things so different from 
 each other and so unequal ? St. Augustine answers, with 
 Plato, that the diversity of the parts is the condition of the 
 unity of the whole. 
 
 The existence of the soul is proved by thought, con- 
 sciousness, and memory. You are in doubt about your 
 existence, are you? But to doubt means to think, does 
 it not? and to think is to exist, is it not?^ It is more 
 difficult to say what the soul is. According to some, it is 
 lire or fine air or the fifth element, possessing the property 
 of thought, understanding, and memory ; others identify it 
 with the brain or the blood, and make thought an effect of 
 the organization of the body. But these are mere hypo- 
 theses, disproved by the simple fact that we are not con- 
 scious of any of these substances constituting the soul. If 
 we were made of fire or of air or of any other material, we 
 should know it by an immediate perception which would 
 be inseparable from our self-consciousness. The soul is a 
 substance differing from all known matter as well as from 
 matter in general ; for it contains notions of the point, 
 the line, length, breadth, and other conceptions, all of 
 which are absolutely incorporeal.^ 
 
 Granting this, what shall we say of the origin of the 
 soul? There are thinkers, even among the Christians, 
 who conceive it as emanating from God. That, however, 
 does it too much honor. It is a creature of God, and has 
 had a beginning, like every other creature.'' However, 
 
 1 Qucesf. (liv., quccst., 28. The same views are held by the pantheist 
 Spinoza, the atheist Schopenhauer ( Welt ah Wille, II., Epiphilosophie), 
 and Claude Bernard (quoted by the Revue chredenne, March, 1869, 
 p. 1.38). 
 
 2 This is the cogito ergo sum of Descartes. 
 
 • De quantitate animce, 13. * Epistle 157.
 
 ST. AUGUSTINE 193 
 
 even among those who on principle assume that the soul 
 is a creature, opinions differ as to the mode of its creation. 
 Some hold that God directly created only the soul of Adam 
 and that the souls of other men are produced per traducem. 
 This theory (which undoubtedly favors St. Augustine's 
 doctrine concerning the transmission of Adam's sin to his 
 descendants) is materialistic, for it considers the soul as 
 capable of being communicated and divided. Others main- 
 tain that souls were created, but existed before bodies ; 
 they were not introduced into them until after the Fall ; 
 the object of their captivity being the expiation of the 
 errors of a previous life. This doctrine^, wliich Plato 
 holds, is disproved by the fact that we have not the slight- 
 est recollection of any such state of pre-existence. Plato 
 finds that even illiterate persons will, upon proper ques- 
 tioning, assert great mathematical trutlis, and concludes 
 therefrom that such persons existed prior to the present, 
 and that the ideas aroused in theii' minds by our inquiries 
 are but reminiscences. But his hypothesis loses its force 
 when we remember that such ideas may be developed by 
 the Socratic method in all minds endowed with common 
 sense. If they are reminiscences, it would have to be 
 assumed that all men were geometricians and mathema- 
 ticians in their pre-existent state ; which, judging from 
 the small number of transcendental mathematicians among 
 the human race, seems very improbable. Plato's argument 
 in favor of pre-existence would perhaps have more weight in 
 case great mathematical truths could ])e extracted only from 
 a few minds. Finally, there is a third conception, accord- 
 ing to which souls are created as soon as bodies are created. 
 This theory is more in line with spiritualistic principles, 
 although it is not so good a su2)port for the dogma of 
 original sin as the others. 
 
 Tlie immoitality of the soul necessarily follows from its 
 rational nature. Reason brings the soul into immediate 
 
 13
 
 194 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 communion with eternal truth ; indeed, the soul and truth 
 constitute but one and the same substance, as it were. The 
 death of the soul would mean its utter se^Daration from 
 truth; but what finite being would be powerful enough 
 to produce such a violent rupture ? and why should God, 
 who is truth personified, produce it? Are not thought, 
 meditation, and the contemplation of divine things inde- 
 pendent of the senses, independent of the body and of 
 matter? Hence, Avhen the body turns into dust, why 
 sliould that which is independent of it perish with it?i 
 In rejecting the notion of pre-existence, St. Augustine 
 also abandons the theory of innate ideas, or rather, he modi- 
 fies it. He assumes, with Plato, that when God formed 
 the human soul, he endowed it with eternal ideas, the 
 principles and nouns of reason and will. Thus interpreted, 
 St. Augustine accepts the doctrine of innate ideas. He 
 denies, however, that these ideas are reminiscences or sur- 
 vivals of a pre-existent state, and he does so on the ground 
 that if such a theory were true, we would not be creatures, 
 but gods. He rejects the doctrine of pre-existence because 
 it implies an existence that has no beginning. He also be- 
 comes more and more suspicious of the theory of innate 
 ideas, because the theory might lead one to conclude that 
 ideas existed originally in the human soul and were not 
 implanted a posteriori by a being outside of the soul. St. 
 Augustine's chief aim is to elevate God by debasing man ; 
 to represent the latter as a wholly passive being who owes 
 nothing to himself and everything to God. In the words 
 of the Apostle : " What hast thou that thou didst not re- 
 ceive ? Now, if thou didst receive it, why dost thou glory 
 as if thou hadst not received it ? " ^ Man as such is the 
 personification of impotence and nothingness. Whatever 
 he possesses, he has received from others. 
 
 ^ De immortalitate animce, I., 4, 6. 
 ^ St. Paul, 1 Corinthians, TV. 7.
 
 ST. AUGUSTINE 195 
 
 The human soul is passive, receptive, contemplative, and 
 nothing more. It receives its knowledge of sensible tilings 
 through the senses ; it receives its moial and religious no- 
 tions through the instrumentality of the Spirit. It owes 
 its conception of the external world to the terrestrial 
 light surrounthng its body, and its knowledge of celestial 
 things to the heavenly light which forms its spiritual en- 
 vii-onment. However, this interior light, which is nothing 
 but God liimself, is not outside of us ; if it were, God would 
 be an extended and material being ; it is in us without 
 being identical with us. In it and tlirough it we perceive 
 the eternal forms of tilings, or as Plato calls them, the Ideas, 
 the immutable essences of passing realities. God himself 
 is the form of all tilings, that is, the eternal law of their 
 origin, development, and existence. He is the Idea of the 
 ideas, and, consequently, the true reality, for reality dwells 
 not in the visible but in the invisible ; it is not found in 
 matter but in the Idea.^ 
 
 St. Augustine's idealism, which comes from Plato and 
 anticipates Malebranche's vision in God and Schelling's 
 intellectual intuition, was, like his philosophy in general, 
 subjected to the influence of the theological system cham- 
 pioned by him during the latter part of his life. The 
 inner light, ^^'llich reveals to the thinker God and the eter- 
 nal types of things, seems to him to grow dimmer and dim- 
 mer, the more convinced he becomes of the fall and radical 
 corruption of human nature. Reason, which, before the 
 Fall, was the organ of God and the infallible revealer of 
 celestial things, is obscured by sin ; the inner light changes 
 into darkness. Had it remained pure, God would not liave 
 had to incarnate himself in Jesus Clirist in order to reveal 
 himself to humanity. Reason would have wliolly sufficed 
 to reclaim th(; lost liuman race. But tlie woid was made 
 
 ' De civ. Dei, XIII., lit; Dc lib. urhitrio, II., ;}, (J; De immort. 
 anim., G.
 
 196 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 flesh, and, the inner light being obscured, the Father of 
 lio-ht appealed to our senses in order to transmit through 
 them what reason was no longer able to give us. In this 
 way, .Vugustine the theologian transforms the idealism of 
 Augustine the philosopher into sensualism. 
 
 The moral ideas of St. Augustine suffer the same changes. 
 His conceptions rise far beyond the general level of patris- 
 tic ethics, when Plato inspires liis thought. In Iris polemic 
 against moral philosophy, Lactantius had declared in true 
 Epicurean fashion : Non est, ut aiunt, })roiAcr seiinam virtus 
 expetenda, sed propter vitam bcatam, quce virtutem necessario 
 sequitur,^ and TertuUian had written the words : Bonum 
 atque optimum est quod Dens prcecepit. Audaciarn existimo 
 de bono divini prcecepti disputare. Neque enim quia honum 
 est, idcirco auscultare dehemus, sed quia Deus prcecepit.'^ St. 
 Augustine's reply to Lactantius is, that virtue and not 
 happiness constitutes the highest goal of free activity, 
 or the sovereign good. He opposes to eudsemonism ethi- 
 cal idealism. Against the indeterminism of TertuUian 
 he raises the objection that the moral law does not depend 
 on any one, but that it is itself the absolute.^ The divine 
 will does not make goodness, beauty, and truth ; absolute 
 goodness, absolute beauty, and absolute truth constitute the 
 will of God, Is the moral law good because God is the 
 highest lawgiver ? No. We regard him who has given us 
 the moral law as the highest lawgiver, because it is good. 
 A thing is not bad because God forbids it ; God forbids it 
 because it is bad. St. Jerome and St. Chrysostom con- 
 doned and even authorized official falsehood. Permit false- 
 hood, and you permit sin ! answers the Bishop of Hippo.* 
 
 St. Augustine is perfectly aware of the insoluble diffi- 
 culties which the problem of human freedom considered in 
 its relations to divine prescience, and the question of the 
 
 1 Imt. Dir., III., 12. 2 ])g pcenitenda, IV. 
 
 ^ De lib. arbitr., I., 3. "* Contra mendacium, c. 15.
 
 ST. AUGUSTINE 197 
 
 origin of evil present. If God foresees our actions, these 
 lose their fortuitous character and become necessary. Then 
 how are we to explain free-will, responsibility, and sin? 
 If God is the source of all things, must we not also assume 
 that evil proceeds from liis will ? And even if evil were 
 only privation, the absence of good, would not this lack 
 of virtue be caused by the refusal of the divine will to en- 
 lighten the soul and to turn it in the direction of the 
 good ? 
 
 The jjbilosophical reasons inclining St. Augustine tow- 
 ards determinism are supplemented by religious reasons.^ 
 He feels that he is a sinner and incapable of being saved 
 through his own efforts. The natural man is the slave of 
 evil, and divine grace alone can make him free. Now, 
 divine grace cannot be brought about by man ; it is entirely 
 dependent on God's freedom. God saves man because he 
 desires it, but he does not save all men. He chooses 
 among them, and destines a certain number for salvation. 
 This election is an eternal act on his part, antecedent to 
 the creation of man. That is, some men are p7'edestined 
 for salvation, others are not. St. Augustine ignores the 
 question of predestination for damnation, as far as he can, 
 but it is logically im})ossible for him to escape this neces- 
 sary consequence of his j)remise. 
 
 However suj^erior his teaching may be to that of Pela- 
 gius his adversary, it is plain tliat, as soon as his thought 
 enters upon the path of theological fatalism, it gradually 
 sinks to the level of the ethics of Lactantius and Tertul- 
 lian. The determinism in whicli his metaphysical specu- 
 lations culminate is absolute, embracing man and God in 
 its scope ; while the determinism postulated by his religious 
 consciousness applies only to man and Icum-s God abso- 
 lutely undetermined. For Angusline the tliinkor, abso- 
 
 1 De civ. Dei, XX. ; Oc r/ratia Dei el lib. arb., G ; De pnrdesliiiatione 
 saiiclortim, 18; De j/rail. il rjralia, 2.
 
 198 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 lute goodness constitutes the essence of the divine will ; 
 for Augustine the champion of predestination, good and 
 evil are dependent on God's will. The God of the Pla- 
 tonic tliinker manifests himself to the world in Jesus 
 Christ by virtue of an inner necessity ; according to the 
 doctor of the Church, the incarnation is but one of the 
 thousand means which God might have employed to realize 
 his aims. The philosopher admires and respects the ancient 
 virtues ; the theologian sees in them nothing but vices in 
 disguise, splcndida vitiaJ- 
 
 St. Augustine excellently exemplifies the intellectual 
 and moral crisis that forms the boundary between the 
 classical epoch and the Middle Ages. 
 
 § 29. The Death Struggles of the Roman World. — Bar- 
 barism. — The First Symptoms of a New Philosophy 
 
 When St. Augustine expired, the Western Empire lay 
 at the point of death. From every side the Northern 
 hordes broke through the frontiers. Gaul and Spain were 
 in their hands, and Italy menaced. With the collapse of 
 the State, the entire Gra^co-Roman civilization sank into 
 ruins. The Church alone of all the old institutions had 
 a chance of weathering the storm. She opened the gates of 
 a better world to the naive believers of the North as well 
 as to the Uase Grseco-Latin sceptics, and closed them upon 
 the unworthy. This power of the keys she received directly 
 from God, and it gave her a powerful hold on both Romans 
 and barbarians. Moreover, the Church not only repre- 
 sented the ancient ideals, which the future had to develop 
 or transform ; she also proclaimed the essentially new and 
 fruitful principle of the equality of nations and individuals 
 before God, the doctrine of the unity and solidarity of the 
 human race; in a word, the idea of humanity. And 
 
 ^ De clvitafe Dei, XIX., 25.
 
 FIRST SYMPTOMS OF A NEW PHILOSOPHY 199 
 
 SO it happened that, when the catastrophe arrived, the 
 Church remained stable and inherited tlie empire. As the 
 heir of chissical culture and the depositary of the instru- 
 ments of salvation, she henceforth bestows the gifts of 
 education upon the barbarians, and the bread of Heaven 
 upon all. She establishes new nations ; and under her 
 fostering care the Neo-Latin and Germanic civilization 
 shows the first signs of life. 
 
 However, centuries passed before the death struggles of 
 antiquity ended, and a new world was born. The lit- 
 erary traditions of Greece and Rome were kept alive in 
 parts of Italy and the Eastern Empire. While the last 
 thinkers of paganism were consuming their strength in 
 weak efforts to revive the religion of the past, a Christian, 
 hiding his identity beneath the pseudonym of Dionysius 
 the Areopagite,^ advanced beyond the timid speculations of 
 the Greek Fathers, and christianized the Neo-Platonic 
 system, thereby sowing the seed in Clxiistian thought which 
 sprang up in jNIaximus the Confessor,^ Scotus Erigena, 
 Hugo and Richard of St. Victor, Eckhart, Bohme, and 
 Bruno. ]Marcianus Capella (about 450) wrote an encyclo- 
 pecha of the sciences.^ John Philoponus,* a contemporary 
 of the Xeo-Platonist Simplicius, published commentaries 
 on the works of Aristotle and defended the teachings of 
 Christianity. At about the same period, the Roman Boe- 
 thius ^ translated Plato and Aristotle, and wrote his deliohtr 
 
 O 
 
 1 Dionysii Areopagitse Opera, Greek and liatiii, [Bale, 1539] ; Paris, 
 1615, 1C14: (2 folio vols.) ; raise in Migne's collection]; Engelhardt, 
 De ortfjine scriptorum Areopayilicorum, Erlangen, 1823; [J. Colet, Ttoo 
 Treatises on the Hierarchies of Dionysius, with Transl., Introduction 
 and Notes, by J. II. Lupton, London, 1869. — Tr.]. 
 
 2 580-662. Opera, ed. Conibefisius, 2 vols.,- Paris, 1675. 
 
 * Satyricon, ed. Kopp, Francf., 1836; [Kyssenhardt, Leijisic, 1866]. 
 
 * Ili.s coninientaries on the Aualylics, the Physics, and Psychology, 
 etc., were repeatedly printed during the sixteenth century. 
 
 * A statesman who \v;is executed in the reign of Theodoric, 525. 
 Opera, [Venice, 1491]; Bale, 1546, 1.570, folio; [also in Migne's coUeo
 
 200 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 ful treatise Be consolatione philosophioe, which breathes the 
 spirit of Epictetiis and Marcus Aurelius ; Cassiodorus,i 
 another Italian (died 575), published the treatise De arti- 
 bus ac discijplinis lihcralium litterariC7n, which with the 
 Encyclopedia of Marcianus Capella, the commentaries of 
 Boethius, and the Isagoge of Porphyry, formed the basis 
 of mediaeval instruction.^ Let us also mention Isidore of 
 Seville and his twenty books of Etymologies ; St. John of 
 Damas, a celebrated theologian and scholar ; and Photius, 
 the Patriarch of Constantino|)le, the author of the Bibliotheca 
 or Myriohilion, a kind of philosophical anthology. 
 
 It is evident, literature gradually retires within the 
 confines of the Church. In the West, especially, all intel- 
 lectual activity centred in it. But the smouldering spark 
 of learned culture was with difficulty kept alive in the 
 hearts of a clergy for the most part recruited from the 
 barbarians. The times were steeped in ignorance. The 
 Latin language, wliich the Church continued to use, 
 formed the only bond of union between the classical world 
 and the new generation. At a time when brutal passions 
 raged, when the secular clergy themselves were addicted 
 to a vulgar realism and showed an absolute indifference to 
 spiritual things, the convents became the refuge of thought 
 and study. Here, the mind, elsewhere distracted by ex- 
 ternal things, found ample opportunity and leisure moments 
 to contemplate itself and its real treasures. Unable as yet 
 to produce original works of their own, the monks spent 
 
 tion]. Gervaise, Htsfoire de Boece, se'nateur romain, Paris, 1715; 
 [Prantl, Geschichte der Logik, I , pp. 679-722]. 
 
 1 Opera omnia, [Paris. 1579]; Rouen, 1679; Venice, 1726. St. 
 Marthe, Vie de Cassiodore, Paris, 1095. 
 
 2 According to this scheme of instruction, there are seven liberal 
 arts, three of which, grammar, rhetoric, and dialectics, form the 
 trivium; while the other four, m^^sic, arithmetic, geometry, and 
 astronomy constitute the quadrivium. There is a threefold and a four- 
 fold path leading to the highest science, theology.
 
 SCHOLASTICISM 201 
 
 their time in copying manuscripts, and to their zealous 
 activity we owe our knowledge of quite a number of 
 ancient masterpieces. 
 
 But they did more ; they founded schools and instructed 
 the youth (scliolce, scholastici^ doctriaa scholastica). The 
 monastic schools rivalled the cathedi-al schools. Great 
 Britain possessed model monasteries, which produced such 
 men as the Venerable Bede,^ Alcuin,^ a pupil of the school 
 of York, who became the counsellor and friend of Charle- 
 magne, and helped to found the Palatine Academy and a 
 great number of cathedral and monastic schools ; finally 
 and above all, Scotus Erigena, the first and, on the whole, 
 most profound philosopher of tlie Cluistian Middle Ages, 
 the founder of Scholasticism. 
 
 The fatherland of Scotus, Occam, and the two Bacons, 
 has every reason to boast of being the Ionia of modern 
 philosophy. 
 
 § 30. Scholasticism ^ 
 
 As the sole legatee of the Roman Empire, the Church 
 is the predominant power of the jMiddle Ages. Out- 
 side of the Church there can be no salvation and no 
 science. The dogmas formulated by her represent the 
 truth. Hence, the problem no longer is to search for it. 
 The Church has no place for philosophy, if we mean by 
 philosophy the pursuit of truth. From the mediaeval point 
 
 i673-73o; Opera, Paris, 1521 f . ; Tmle, 1563; Cologne, 1612. 
 [A. Giles, The Complete Works of Venerable Beila (Latin), 12 vols., 
 London, 1843-44.] 
 
 2 726-801; Opera, Pari.s, 1617; Patisb., ]77:5. 2 fol. vols. 
 
 8 [Con.sult the works of Ritter, Kou.sselot, Ilaiueau, Stbckl, etc., 
 mentioned on page 10; also the general histories of philosophy referred 
 to on pages 13-16. —Th.] Cousin, Frnc/ments philnsnphii/ues, P/iilo- 
 sophie Kcolastique ; Itilrndnclion to Knno Fischer's Hlslor;/ of Modern 
 Philosophy; [S. Talamo, L'ArisloteliKtno nella storia ildia Jilosojia, 3d 
 ed., Siena, 1882; French trunsl., Paris, 1876. — Tr.]
 
 202 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 of view, to philosophize means to exphxin the dogma, to 
 deduce its consequences, and to demonstrate its truth. 
 Hence, philosophy is identical with positive theology; 
 when it fails to be that, it becomes lieretical. Christian 
 thought hemmed in by the law of the Church resembles a 
 river confined between two steep banks ; the narrower the 
 bed, the deeper the stream. Being unable to escape from 
 the dogma encompassing it, it endeavors to penetrate it, 
 and eventually undermines it. 
 
 Thus the philosophy of the Christian School, Scholasti- 
 cism, arises and gradually gains a foothold. Scotus Eri- 
 gena is its founder; St. Anselmus, Abelai'd, St. Thomas, 
 and Duns Scotus, are its most distinguished representa- 
 tives. Scholasticism is modern science in embryo ; ^ the 
 philosophy of the Euro})ean nations developing within the 
 mother Church in the form of theology. It is not, like 
 the speculation of the Church E'athers, a child of classical 
 antiquity, from which the fall of the Roman world sep- 
 arates it. It springs from the healthy soil of the Ger- 
 manic and Neo-Latin world, and is the product of other 
 races and a new civilization.^ France, England, Spain, 
 Germany : Western Europe, in a word, is its home. It has 
 its period of youth, maturity, and decline. Scholastic 
 philosophy is at first influenced by Platonism through the 
 mediation of St. Augustine ; from the thirteenth century 
 on, it gradually suffers the influence of Aristotle's philo- 
 sophy. Hence, we notice two great periods in the history 
 of Scholasticism : the Platonic period and the Peripatetic 
 period. The latter divides into two su]>periods, of which 
 the first interprets Aristotle in the realistic sense, while 
 the second conceives him as a nominalist. From the four- 
 teenth century on. Scholasticism is engaged in the struggle 
 
 ^ Hegel, Vorlesungen iiber die Geschichte der Philosophie, vol. III., 
 p. 118 ; [vol. XV., of Complete Works}. 
 2 Id., p. 139.
 
 SCHOLASTICISM 203 
 
 between the realists and nominalists^ and towards the 
 midtlle of the fifteenth century, it succumbs to the secu- 
 lar and liberal reaction inaugurated by the Renaissance- 
 After that it ceases to be a great intellectual power, and 
 seeks refuge, body and soul, within the pale of the Church, 
 of which it is, to this day, the official philosophy.^ 
 
 What is its ruling thought, its fundamental doctrine ? 
 The " last of the Scholastics," though passing over the Mid- 
 dle Ages with " seven-leagued boots," ^ formulates it most 
 aptly in the following words : " Philosophy and theology 
 have the same contents, the same aim, and the same inter- 
 ests. ... In explaining religion, pliilosophy simply explains 
 itself, and in explaining itself it explains religion." ^ In- 
 deed, this principle lies at the root of all its systems. The 
 distinguishing characteristic of the period upon wliich we 
 are now entering is, that it reconciles elements previously 
 and subsequently in conflict with each other. An alliance 
 is formed between pliilosophy and theology, faith and 
 reason, "grace" and "nature." The Latin Fathers, as 
 well as the free-thinkers by whom modern philosophy was 
 founded, considered these two spheres as antagonistic. 
 The Fathei-s took sides with "grace"; the philosophers, 
 with " nature " ; while in the judgment of the Schoolmen, 
 at least those of the first period, there can be no contradic- 
 tion between the revealed dogma and natural reason. But 
 inasmuch as doctrines seemed to contradict each other on 
 many points, the problem became to reconcile them, to 
 demonstrate the truth of the dogma, and to prove that 
 
 ^ The most distinguished among its post-Renaissance representa- 
 tives is Francis Suarez of Granada (1518-1G17), a follower of Thomas 
 of Aquin and author of the Dispulnliones melaphysicce (Paris, 1619), 
 etc. 
 
 2 Hegel, Vorlesungen iiber die Geschichle der Pkilosophie, vol. III., 
 p. 00. [Engl, translation by Haldane, vol. III., p. 1.] 
 
 8 Vorlesungen iifjcr die Philosophie der Religion, vol. I., p. 5 ; [vol 
 XI., Complete Woiks.'j
 
 204 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 ecclesiastical Christianity is a rational religion. To ren- 
 der the dogma acceptable to reason, says an eminent 
 follower of the pliilosopher just quoted,^ that is the pro- 
 gram of Scholasticism. The dogma affirms: Deus homo; 
 Scholasticism asks : Cur Deus liorno ? In order to answer 
 this question, theology forms an alliance with pliilosophy ; 
 faith, with science. This alliance constitutes the very 
 essence of Scholasticism. The latter is a compromise 
 between philosophy and faith. Indeed, Scholasticism 
 declines as soon as the nominalistic doctors, on the one 
 hand, and the humanists, on the other, recognize the 
 necessity of separating the two domains. 
 
 § 31. Scotus Erigena 
 
 The fu'st great Schoolman, John Scotus Erigena, a 
 native of Ireland, was invited to take charge of the Pala- 
 tine Academy by Charles the Bald, about the middle of the 
 ninth century. His treatise, De divina prcedestinatione, 
 which he wrote against the heresy of Gottschalk, and his 
 Latin translation of Dionysius the Areopagite, which he 
 failed to submit to the Pope for approval, alienated from 
 him the sympathies of the Church. He continued to enjoy, 
 however, the protection of the Emperor. The date of his 
 death is as uncertain as the date of his birth. 
 
 Scotus resembles Origen in breadth of mind, and is 
 much superior to his times. He suffered the same fate : 
 the disfavor of the Church, which failed to canonize him. 
 His learning, however, rises far beyond the scientific 
 level of the Carlovingian epoch. Besides Latin, he knew 
 Greek and perhaps also Arabic. In addition to his knowl- 
 edge of the Greek Fathers and Neo-Platonism, he possessed 
 wonderful powers of speculation and boldness of judgment. 
 He stands out like a high volcano on a perfectly level 
 
 1 K. Fischer, op. cit., vol. I., 1, ch. IV.
 
 SCOTUS ERIGENA 205 
 
 plane. His philosophy, as set forth in the De divisione 
 naturce} is not, indeed, an innovation on the Neo-Platonic 
 doctrines. Like the Pseudo-Dionysius, the Areopagite, it 
 reproduces the system of emanation of the Alexandrine 
 school in Christian form. But it was almost a miracle for 
 any one living in the ninth century and on this side of the 
 Pyrenees to understand Plotinus and Proclus. 
 
 The object of philosophy is, according to Scotus, identi- 
 cal with that of religion.^ Philosophy is the science of the 
 faith, the understanding of the dogma. Speculation and 
 reliarion have the same divine content and differ in form 
 only. Religion worships and adores, while philosophy 
 studies, discusses, and with the aid of reason explains 
 the object which religion adores : God or uncreated and 
 creative Nature. 
 
 In its broadest sense, the word nature comprises all 
 beings, both uncreated and created tilings. Nature thus 
 interpreted embraces four categories of existence : (1) that 
 which is uncreated and creates ; (2) that which is created 
 and creates ; (3) that which is created and does not create ; 
 (4) that, which is uncreated and does not create. Exist- 
 ence is possible only in these four forms. 
 
 This classilication may, however, be simplified. 'J^he 
 first class is, in fact, the same as the fourth, for both of 
 them contain that wliich is uncreated, and consequently 
 correspond to the only being existing in the absolute sense 
 of the word, to God. Tlie first class embraces God in so 
 far as he is the creative principle, the beginning or the 
 
 1 Edited l)y Thomas Gale, Oxford, 1G81 ; Schliiter, Minister, 1838; 
 H. J. Floss, Paris, 1858 [in vol. 122 of Migiie's collection, which con- 
 tains also the treatise De ilirina prfrdextinatione and the translation 
 of Dionysius] ; St. Rene Taillandicr, Scnl Eriffhie el la philosophie 
 scolasdque, Strasburg, 184;5 ; [Iliiber, Jolainnes Scotus Erigena, etc., 
 Munich, 1801]. 
 
 * De divinn proedestinatione. I'rodiuinin {\n (WWn-ri ISIauguin, /1mc<. 
 qui nono saec. de pi fed. et yral. scripscrunt <tj)era, Paris, 18."iO).
 
 206 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 source of things ; the fourth also contains God, but only in 
 so far as he is the end, the consummation, and the highest 
 perfection of things. We also hnd, upon comparing the 
 second and the third classes, that they form a single class 
 containing all created things, or the universe, in so far as 
 this is tUstinct from God. The Idea-types, which are real- 
 ized in individuals, are productive created beings (the 
 second class). ^ Individuals are created and non-productive 
 things ; for types or species, not intlividuals, possess the 
 power of reproduction. Hence, we have left two classes in 
 place of the four original ones : God and the universe. 
 
 But these two categories or modes of existence are also 
 identical.^ In fact, the world is in God, and God is in it 
 as its essence, its soul, its life. Whatever living force, 
 light, and intelligence the world contains, is God, who is 
 immanent in the cosmos ; and the latter exists only in so 
 far as it participates in the divine being. God is the sum- 
 total of being without division, limit, or measure j the world 
 is divided and limited being. _ God is unexplicated being ; 
 the world is explicated, revealed, manifested (^Beot^dvaa) 
 being ; God and the universe are one and the same being, 
 two different modes or forms of the only infinite being ; or 
 rather, the world alone is a mode of being, a modification, 
 aiid limitation of being, while God is being without mode 
 of being or any determination.^ 
 
 Scotus derives the word ^eo? either from Oewpw^ video, or 
 from ^e&), curro.^ According to the former etymology, it 
 means absolute vision or intelligence ; according to the 
 latter, eternal movement. But both meanings are merely 
 figurative. For, since God is the being by the side of 
 
 ^ De dlvisione natures, II., 2. 
 
 2 Id., IIL, 22. 
 
 ' De divisione naturce. III., 10 : God is everything, and everything 
 is God; III., 17-18: Hence we should not consider God and the 
 creature as a duality, but as one and the same being ; of. 22-23. 
 
 * Id., L, 14.
 
 SCOTUS ERIGENA 207 
 
 whom or in whom there is no other being, we cannot, 
 strictly speaking, say that God sees or comprehends any- 
 thing. And as far as divine movement is concerned, we 
 may say that it in no wise resembles the locomotion pecu- 
 liar to creatm-es ; it proceeds from God, in God, towards 
 God ; that is, it is synonymous with absolute rest. Since 
 God is superior to all differences and all contrasts, he can- 
 not be designated by any term implying an opposite. We 
 call him good, but incorrectly, since the difference between 
 good and evil does not exist in him {v7r€pdjado<i plus quam 
 bonus est ^). We call him God, but we have just seen that 
 the expression is inadequate. We call him Truth; but 
 truth is opposed to error, and there is no such antithesis in 
 the Infinite Being. We call him the Eternal One, Life, 
 Light ; but since the difference between eternity and time, 
 life and death, light and its opposite, does not exist in God, 
 these terms are inexact. No term, not even the term heing^ 
 will do him justice, for being is o^Dposed to non-being. 
 Hence God is indefinable as well as incomprehensible. He 
 is higher than goodness, higher than truth, liigher than 
 eternity ; he is more than life, more than light, more than 
 God (y7rep6eo<;), more than being itself (yirepovaio^^ super- 
 essentialis). None of the categories of Aristotle can com- 
 prehend him, and inasmuch as to comprehend means to 
 bring an object under a class, God himself cannot be 
 comprehended. He is the absolute nothing, the eternal 
 Mystery.^ 
 
 Tlie innermost essence of tlie human soul is as mysterious 
 and impenetrable as God, since tliis essence is God himself.^ 
 All that we know of it is tliat it is movement and life, and 
 that this movement, this life, lias three degrees : sensation, 
 intelligence, and reason: the Imman image of the divine 
 Trinity. The body was created with the soul ; but it has 
 
 * Dh divisione nnlurcn, I., 14. 
 
 2 Id., L,1(J; in.,!'.). 8 Id., I., 78.
 
 208 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 fallen from its ideal beauty in consequence of sin. This 
 beauty, wliich is latent in tlie actual organism, will not 
 manifest itself in its purity except in the life to come. 
 Man is an epitome of all terrestrial and celestial creatures. 
 He is the world in miniature, and as such the lord of cre- 
 ation. He differs from the angels only in sin, and raises 
 himself to the level of divine being by penitence. Sin 
 belongs to the corporeal nature of man ; it is the necessary 
 effect of the preponderance of the senses over the intel- 
 lectual life in process of development. 
 
 The fall of man is not only the consequence, but also 
 the cause of his corporeal existence. The imperfections 
 and the diseases of his actual body, his dull materiality, 
 the antagonism between the flesh and the spirit, the differ- 
 ence of the sexes, all these things in themselves constitute 
 sin, fall, separation from God, the dismemberment of the 
 universal unity.i On the other hand, since there is no real 
 being outside of God, what we call separation from God, 
 fall or sin, is but a negative reality, a defect or privation. 
 Evil has no substantial existence. A thing has real exist- 
 ence only in so far as it is good, and its excellence is the 
 measure of its reality. Perfection and reality are synonyms. 
 Hence absolute imperfection is synonymous with absolute 
 non-reality; which implies the impossibility of the exist- 
 ence of a personal Devil, that is, an absolutely wicked 
 being. Evil is the absence of good, life, and being. De- 
 prive a being of everything good in it, and you annihi- 
 late it.2 
 
 Creation is an eternal and continuous act, an act without 
 beginning or end. God precedes the world in dignity, not 
 in time.3 God is absolutely eternal ; the world is relatively 
 so. It emanates from God as the light emanates from the 
 aun, or heat from fire. In the case of God, to think is to 
 
 1 Cf. §§ 10, 16, 25, 68. 
 
 2 De divisinne natura, TTT., 1, 4. ^ Id., III., 8.
 
 SCOTUS ERIGENA 209 
 
 create (videt operando etvidendo opcratitr'^)^ and his creative 
 activity is, like his thought, without beginning. Every 
 creature is virtually eternal ; our entire being is rooted in 
 eternity ; we have all pre-existed from eternity in the in- 
 finite series of causes which have produced us. God alone 
 is eternal actu ; he alone never existed as a simple germ. 
 The notliingness from which the world is derived, accord- 
 ing to Scripture, is not equal to ; it is the ineffable and 
 incomprehensible beauty of the divine nature, the supra- 
 essential and supernatural essence of God, inaccessible to 
 thoucjht and unknown even to the ano-els.^ 
 
 The genera, species, and individuals are evolved in suc- 
 cession from the Infinite Being. Creation consists in this 
 eternal analysis of the general. Being is the highest gen- 
 erality. From being, wliich is common to all creatures, 
 life, wliich belongs ordj to organized beings, is separated 
 as a special principle. Reason springs from life and em- 
 braces a still narrower class of beings (men and angels) ; 
 finally, from reason are derived wisdom and science, which 
 belong to the smallest number. Creation is a harmonious 
 sum of concentric circles ; we have constant crossings be- 
 tween the di%'ine essence, wliich overflows, expands, and 
 unfolds, and the world or the periphery, which strives to 
 return to God and to be merged in him.-^ The aim of 
 human science is to know exactly how things spring 
 from the first causes, and how they are divided and sub- 
 divided into species and genera. Science in this sense is 
 called dialectics,'* and may be divided into physics and 
 ethics. True dialectics is not, like that of the Sophists, the 
 product of human imagination or capricious reason ; the 
 autlior of all sciences and all arts has grounded it on the 
 very nature of things. Tlirough knoAvledge and wisdom, its 
 culmination, tlie human soul rises above nature and be- 
 
 1 De divisione naturce, III., 17 ff. 2 7,/^ uf., ij). 
 
 8 Id., I., 10. ■• Id., I., 2!», KJ; V-,4. 
 
 14
 
 210 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 comes identified with God. This return to God is effected, 
 for nature in general, in man ; for man, in Christ and the 
 Christian ; for the Christian, in his supernatural and essen- 
 tial union with God through the spirit of wisdom and sci- 
 ence. Just as everything comes from God, everything is 
 destined to return to God. Scotus teaches predestination, 
 i. e., universal predestination for salvation. All fallen an- 
 gels, all fallen men, all beings, in a word, will return to God. 
 The punishments of hell are purely spiritual. There is no 
 other recompense for virtue than the vision or immediate 
 knowledge of God, no other pain for sin than remorse. 
 Punishments have nothing arbitrary in them; they are 
 the natural consequences of the acts condemned by the 
 divine law.^ 
 
 § 32. St. Anselm 
 
 Scotus Erigena went out like a meteor on a dark night. 
 While the Arabian schools ^ were continuing the jjhilo- 
 
 ^ De div. prcedestinatione, 2-4:. 
 
 2 Tlie most celebrated schools in the Orient were : Bagdad, Bas- 
 sora, Bokhara, Konf a ; in Spain : Cordova, Granada, Toledo, Sevilla, 
 Murcia, Valencia, Almeria, etc. The Arabians are apt pupils of the 
 Greeks, Persians, and Hindoos in science. Their philosophy is the 
 continuation of Peripateticisni and Neo-Platonisra. It is more learned 
 than original, and consists mainly of exegesis, particularly of the 
 exegesis of Aristotle's system, the strict monotheism of which recom- 
 mended it to the disciples of Islam. The leaders of Arabian thought 
 are, in Asia : Alkendi of Bassora, a contemporary of Scotus Erigena ; 
 Alfarabi of Bagdad (same century), among other things the author of 
 an Encyclopedia, which the Christian Schoolmen valued very highly; 
 Avicenna (Ibn-Sina died at Ispahan, 1036), celebrated in Em-ope as 
 a physician and learned interpreter of Aristotle ; Algazel of Bagdad 
 (died 1111), a sceptical philosopher and orthodox Mussulman; in 
 Spain: Avempace (Ibn-Badja) of Saragossa, died 1138, Ibn- Top- 
 hail of Cadiz (1100-1185), Averroes (Ibn-Pvoschd) of Cordova, the 
 "commentator of commentators" (1126-1198), all of them learned 
 physicians, mathematicians, philosophers, and fruitful writers. After 
 the days of Averroes, Arabian philosophy rapidly declined, never to
 
 ST. ANSELM 211 
 
 sophical and scientific traditions of Greece and the Orient 
 with credit to themselves, the alliance between reason and 
 faith had only a few isolated representatives in Cluistian 
 Europe during the tenth and eleventh centuries, viz. : Ger- 
 bert 1 (Sylvester II.), who is indebted for his knowledge to 
 the Arabians ; Berengar of Tours ; ^ Lanfranc ; ^ and Hil- 
 debert of Lavardin, Bishop of Tours, the author of a treatise 
 on morals.* The great questions which occupied the mind 
 of Scotus no lono-er interested them. These subtle reasoners 
 spent their time in discussing the most trivial subjects and 
 the most childish problems : Can a prostitute again become 
 a virgin through the divine omnipotence ? Does the mouse 
 that eats the consecrated host eat the body of the Lord? 
 Christian pliilosophy is still in its infancy, and therefore 
 delights in such childish sports. But these sports are sig- 
 niticant preludes to the combats which the future has in 
 store. 
 
 The first really speculative thinker after Scotus is St. 
 Anselm,^ the disciple of Lanfranc. He was born at Aosta 
 
 rise again, but it left its impress on Jewish thought (Avicehron or 
 Ibn-Gebirol, eleventh century, the author of the Fountain of Life ; Closes 
 ]\Iaiinonides, 1135-1204, the still more noted author of the Guide to the 
 Mii^guided, etc.), and through the latter on Christian thought. See 
 [Schnicilders, Docuwiew^a pJdlnsophire Arabum, Bonn, 1886]; same au- 
 thor, Essai sur les ecoles philosophiqiieit chez les Arahea, Paris, 1842; 
 [Ilammer-Purgstall, Geschichte der arabischen Litteralur, vols. I.-YII., 
 Vienna, 1850-56]; Munck, Melanges de philosophic juire ef arabe, I'aris, 
 18.50; Kenan, Averroeset PAverroisme, 8d ed., Paris, 1860; [F. Dieterici, 
 Die Philosnphie der Araber im 10. Jahrhundert. 8 pts., Loipsic, 1865-76; 
 M. Eisler, Vorlesnngen iiber die Judische J'hilosopliie des Afiftelalters, 3 
 vols., Vienna, 1870-84 ; i\I. Joel, Beilrdge zur Geschichte der Pliilosophie, 
 2 vols., Breslau, 1876. — Tr.]. 
 
 1 Died 1003. 
 
 2 Died 1088. De sacra ccena adversus iMnfr., Berlin, 1844. 
 » Died, 1089. Opera, ed. Ciiles, Oxford, 1854. 
 
 * 1>1(m1 1134. Opera, '\. Beaugendre. 
 
 ' Opera, Xurciiilicrg, etc, 1401 ff. ; also in vol. 155 of Migne's col-
 
 212 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 (1033), entered the monastery of Bee in Normandy (1060), 
 succeeded Lanfranc as Abbot (1078), and as Archbishop 
 of Canterbury (1093). lie died in 1109. He left a great 
 number of writings, tlie most important of which are : the 
 Dialogus de (jravimatico, the Monolorjium de dlvinitatis essen- 
 tia sive Uxemplum de ratione fidei,i\\Q Proslogium sive Fides 
 qucerens intellectum, the Be veritate, the Be fide trinitatis, 
 and the C^ir Bens liomo ? 
 
 The second Augustine, as St. Ansehn has been called, 
 starts out from the same principle as the first ; he holds 
 that faith precedes all reflection and all discussion con- 
 cerning religious things. The unbelievers, he says,^ strive 
 to understand because they do not believe; we, on the 
 contrary, strive to understand because we believe. They 
 and we have the same object in view ; but inasmuch as they 
 do not believe, they cannot arrive at their goal, which is to 
 understand the dogma. The unbeliever will never under- 
 stand. In religion faith plays the part played by experi- 
 ence in the understanding of the things of this world. The 
 blind man cannot see the light, and therefore does not 
 understand it; the deaf-mute, who has never perceived 
 sound, cannot have a clear idea of sound. Similarly, not 
 to believe means not to perceive, and not to perceive means 
 not to understand. Hence, we do not reflect in order that 
 we may believe ; on the contrary, we believe in order that 
 we may arrive at knowledge. A Christian ought never to 
 doubt the beliefs and teachings of the Holy Catholic 
 Church. All he can do is to strive, as humbly as possible, 
 to understand her teachings by believing them, to love 
 them, and resolutely to observe them in his daily life. 
 
 lection, Paris, 1852-54 ; [Hasse, Ansehn von Canterhimj, 2 pts., Leipsic, 
 1843-52] ; Charles de Remusat, Ayiaelme de Cantorhery, tahJeau de la vie 
 monastique, etc., Paris, 1854 ; 2cl ed., 1868 ; [Shedd, History of Christian 
 Doctrine, vol. II., New York, 1864]. 
 ^ Cur Deus homo ? I., 2.
 
 ST. AXSELM 213 
 
 Should he succeed in understanding the Clmstian doc- 
 trine, let him render thanks to God, the source of all intel- 
 ligence ! In case lie fails, that is no reason why he should 
 obstinately attack the dogma, but a reason why he should 
 bow his head in worship. Faith ought not merely to be 
 the starting-point, — the Christian's aim is not to depart 
 from faith but to remain in it, — but also the fixed rule 
 and goal of thought, the beginning, the middle, and the 
 end of all philosophy. i 
 
 The above almost literal quotations might give one the 
 impression that St. Anselm belongs exclusively to the 
 Ihstory of theology. Such is not the case, however. This 
 fervent Catholic is more independent, more of an investi- 
 gator and philosopher than he himself imagines. He is a 
 typical scholastic doctor and a fine exponent of the alliance 
 between reason and faith which forms the characteristic 
 trait of mediieval philosophy. He assumes, a priori, that 
 revelation and reason are in perfect accord. These two 
 manifestations of one and the same Supreme Intelligence 
 cannot possibly contradict each other. Hence, his point of 
 view is chametrically opposed to the credo quia ahsurdum. 
 Moreover, he too had been besieged by doubt. Indeed, 
 the extreme ardor which impels him to search ever}- where 
 for arguments favorable to tlie dogma, is a confession on 
 his part that the dogma needs support, that it is debatable, 
 that it lacks self-evidence, the criterion of truth. Even as 
 a monk, it was liis cliief concern to find a simple and con- 
 clusive argument in support of the existence of God and of 
 all the doctrines of the Church concerning the Supreme 
 Being. Mere affmnation did not satisfy him ; he demanded 
 proofs. This thought was continually before his mind ; it 
 c;iused him to forget his meals, and pursued him even 
 (hiring the solemn moments of worsliii^. He comes to the 
 conclusion tliat it is a temptation of Satan, and seeks dellv 
 
 ^ De fide Irinilatis ; cf. Monoloijium, Pifliice.
 
 214 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 erance from it. But in vain. After a night spent in medi- 
 tation, he at last discovers what he has been seeking for 
 years : the incontrovertible argument in favor of the Chris- 
 tian dogma, and he regards himself as fortunate in having 
 found, not only the proof of the existence of God, but his 
 peace of soul. His demonstrations are like the premises of 
 modern rationalism. 
 
 Everything that exists, he says,i has its cause, and this 
 cause may be one or many. If it is one, then we have 
 what we are looking for : God, the unitary being to whom 
 all other beings owe their origin. If it is manifold, there 
 are tlii-ee possibilities : (1) The manifold may depend on 
 unity as its cause; or (2) Each thing composing the 
 manifold may be self-caused ; or (3) Each thing may owe 
 its existence to all the other things. The fii'st case is 
 identical with the hypothesis that everytliing proceeds 
 from a single cause ; for to depend on several causes, all 
 of which depend on a single cause, means to depend on 
 this single cause. In the second case, we must assume 
 that there is a power, force, or faculty of self-existence 
 common to all the particular causes assumed by the 
 hypothesis ; a power in which all participate and are com- 
 prised. But that would give us what we had in the first 
 case, an absolute unitary cause. The third supposition, 
 which makes each of the " first causes " depend on all the 
 rest, is absurd ; for we cannot hold that a thing has for its 
 cause and condition of existence a thing of vfhich it is 
 itself the cause and condition. Hence we are compelled 
 to believe in a being which is the cause of every existing 
 thing, without being caused by anything itself, and which 
 for that very reason is infinitely more perfect than anything 
 else : it is the most real {ens rcalissiinum), most powerful, 
 and best being. Since it does not depend on any being or 
 on any condition of existence other than itself, it is a se 
 1 Monologium, c. 3.
 
 ST. ANSELM 215 
 
 and x>^r se ; it exists, not because something else exists, but 
 it exists because it exists j tliat is, it exists necessarily, it 
 is necessary being.^ 
 
 It would be an easy matter to deduce pantheism from 
 the arguments of the Ilonologium. Anselm, it is true, 
 protests against such an interpretation of his theology. 
 With St. Augustine he assumes that the world is created 
 ex nihilo. But though accepting this teaching, he modi- 
 fies it. Before the creation, he says, things did not exist 
 hi/ themselves, independently of God; hence we say they 
 were derived from non-being. But they existed eternally 
 for God and in God, as ideas ; they existed before their cre- 
 ation, in the sense that the Creator foresaw them and pre- 
 destined them for existence.^ 
 
 The existence of God, the unitary and absolute cause of 
 the world, being proved, the question is to determine his 
 nature and attributes. God's perfections are like human 
 perfections; with this difference, however, that they are 
 essential to him, which is not the case with us. Man has 
 received a share of certain perfections, but there is no 
 necessary correlation between him and these perfections ; 
 it wouhl have been possible for him not to receive them ; 
 he could have existed without them. God, on the con- 
 trary, does not get his perfections from without ; he has 
 not received them, and we cannot say that he has them ; 
 he is and must be everything that these perfections imply ; 
 his attributes are identical with his essence. Justice, an 
 attribute of God, and God. are not two separate things. 
 We cannot say of God that he has justice or goodness ; 
 we cannot even say that lie is just ; for to be just is to 
 participate in justice after the manner of creatures. God is 
 jutsice as sucli, goodness as such, wisdom as such, happiness 
 as such, truth as such, being as such. Moreover, all of 
 God's attril)utes constitute ])ut a single attribute, by virtue 
 * Moiiolnnuim, c. 3. ^'/'j c. 9.
 
 216 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 of the unity of his essence (unum est quidquid essentialiter 
 de summa substantia dicitur^). 
 
 All this is pure Platonism. But, not content with spirit- 
 ualizing theism, Anselni really discredits it when, like a 
 new Carneades, he enumerates the difficulties which he finds 
 in the conception. God is a simple being and at the same 
 time eternal, that is, diffused over infinite points of time \ 
 he is omnipresent, that is, distributed over all points of 
 space. Shall we say tliat God is omnipresent and eternal ? 
 This proposition contradicts the notion of the simplicity of 
 the divine essence. Shall we say that he is nowhere in 
 space and nowhere in time ? But that would be equiva- 
 lent to denying his existence. Let us therefore reconcile 
 these two extremes and say that God is omnipresent and 
 eternal, without being limited b}" space or time. The fol- 
 lowing is an equall}' serious difficulty : In God there is no 
 change and consequently nothing accidental. Now, there 
 is no substance without accidents. Hence God is not a 
 substance; he transcends all substance. Anselm is 
 alarmed at these dangerous consequences of his logic, and 
 he therefore prudently adds that, though the term " sub- 
 stance " may be incorrect, it is, nevertheless, the best we 
 can apply to God — si quid digne did potest — and that to 
 avoid or condemn it might perhaps jeopardize our faith in 
 the reality of the Divine Being. 
 
 The most formidable theological antinomy is the doc- 
 trine of the trinity of persons in the unity of the divine 
 essence.^ The Word is the object of eternal thought ; it 
 is God in so far as he is thought, conceived, or compre- 
 hended by himself. The Holy Spirit is the love of God 
 for the Word, and of the Word for God, the love which 
 God bears himself. But is this explanation satisfactory ? 
 And does it not sacrifice the dogma which it professes to 
 explain to the conception of unity? St. Anselm sees in 
 1 Monologium, c. 17. 2 /j.^ c. 38 ff.
 
 ST. ANSELM 217 
 
 tlie Trinity and the notion of God insurmountable difficul- 
 ties and contradictions, vrhich the human mind cannot 
 reconcile. In his discouragement he is obliged to confess, 
 with Scotus Erigena, St. Augustine, and the Neo-Platon- 
 ists, that no human ^^■ord can adequately express the 
 essence of the All-High. Even the Avords "-Avisdom" 
 (^sapientia^ and "■being" (essentia^ are but imperfect ex- 
 pressions of what he imagines to be the essence of God. 
 All theological phrases are analogies, figures of speech, and 
 mere approximations.^ 
 
 The Proslogium sive Fides quoerens intellectum has the 
 same aim as the Monologium : to prove the existence of 
 God. Our author draws the elements of his argument 
 from St. Augustine and Platonism. He sets out from the 
 idea of a perfect being, from which he infers the existence 
 of such a being. We have in ourselves, he saj-s, the idea 
 of an absolutely perfect being. Now, perfection implies 
 existence. Hence God exists. This argument, which has 
 been termed the ontolofjical ((rt/wiucnt, found an opponent 
 worthy of Anselm in Gaunilo, a monk of Marmoutiers 
 in Touraine.2 Gaunilo emphasizes the difference between 
 thought and being, and points out the fact that we may con- 
 ceive and imagine a being, and yet that being may not exist. 
 We have as much right to conclude from our idea of an 
 enchanted island in the middle of the ocean tliat such an 
 island actually exists. The criticism is just. Indeed, the 
 ontological argument would be conclusiA^e, only in case 
 the idea of God and the existence of God in the luiman 
 mind were identical. If our idea of God is God himself, 
 it is evident that this idea is tlie immediate and incon- 
 trovertible proof of the existence of God. liut wliat the 
 
 ' Monuloffium, c. 05. 
 
 "^ (jauiiilo's refutation of tho ontological proof is fouiid in iho 
 works of Anselm under the title: Liber pro insipleitte adcemus S 
 J^nxfiJini in Proslo'jii) ruliuvitiuliuncm.
 
 218 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 theologian aims to prove is not the existence of the God- 
 Idea of Plato and Hegel, but the existence of the personal 
 God. However that may be, we hardly know what to 
 admire most, — St. Anselm's broad and deep conception, 
 or the sagacity of liis opponent who, in the seclusion of his 
 cell, anticipates the Transcendental Dialectic of Kant. 
 
 The rationalistic tendency which we have just noticed in 
 the Monologium and the Proslogium meets us again in the 
 Cur Deus homo ? Why did God become man ? The first 
 word of the title sufficiently indicates the philosophical 
 trend of the treatise. The object is to search for the 
 causes of the incarnation. The incarnation, according to 
 St. Anselm, necessarily follows from the necessity of 
 redemption. Sin is an offence against the majesty of God. 
 In spite of his goodness, God cannot pardon sin without 
 compounding with honor and justice. On the other hand, 
 he cannot revenge liimseK on man for his offended honor ; 
 for sin is an offence of infuiite degree, and therefoie 
 demands infinite satisfaction ; wliicli means that he must 
 either destroy humanity or inflict upon it the eternal pun- 
 ishments of hell. Now, in either case, the goal of creation, 
 the happiness of his creatures, would be missed and the 
 honor of the Creator compromised. There is but one way 
 for God to escape this dilemma without affecting his 
 honor, and that is to arrange for some kind of satisfaction. 
 He must have infinite satisfaction, because the offence is 
 immeasurable. Now, in so far as man is a finite being 
 and incapable of satisfying divine justice in an infinite 
 measure, the infinite being himself must take the matter in 
 charge ; he must have recourse to substitution. Hence, the 
 necessity of the incarnation. God becomes man in Christ; 
 Christ suffers and dies in our stead ; thus he acquires an 
 infinite merit and the right to an equivalent recompense. 
 But since the world belongs to the Creator, and nothing 
 can be added to its treasures, the recompense wliicli by
 
 REALISM AND NOMINALISM 219 
 
 right belongs to Christ falls to the lot of the human 
 race in which he is incorporated : humanity is pardoned, 
 forgiven, and saved. 
 
 Theological criticism has repudiated Anselm's theory, 
 which bears the stamp of the spirit of chivalry and of 
 feudal customs. But, notwithstanding the attacks of a 
 superficial rationalism, there is an abiding element of truth 
 in it: over and above each personal and variable will there 
 is an absolute, immutable, and incorruptible will, called 
 justice, honor, and duty, in conformity with the customs 
 of the times. 
 
 We have now to speak of the part the great Schoolman 
 j^layed in the discussion that arose after his promotion to 
 the Archbishopric of Canterbury: I mean the controversy 
 between the realists and the nominalists, or let me rather 
 say, between the idealists and the materialists, — for this 
 " monkish quarrel " was in reality a conflict between meta- 
 physical principles.^ 
 
 § 33. Realism and Nominalism ^ 
 
 The Catholic or universal Church does not merely aim 
 to be an aggregation of particular Christian communities 
 and of the believers composing them ; she regards herself 
 as a superior j)Ower, as a reality distinct from and inde. 
 pendent of the individuals belonging to the fold. If the 
 Idea, tliat is, the general or universal (to kuOoXov), were 
 
 ^ AVe should say realists instead of " materialists," were it not for 
 the fact that the former term was, during the Middle Ages, applied to 
 the opposite side. We mean the party which unduly emphasizes the 
 real or material principle, and whicli in the history of mediicval phil- 
 osophy represents Tonianism and r(Mii)ateticisiu, as distinguished from 
 Academic idealism. 
 
 ^ [C. S. Barach, Zur Geschlckte des Nomlnnlismus vor Jioscelliu, 
 Vienna, 1800,- J. If. Lowe, Der Kanij/f zwlschen dcm Ileulismus und 
 Noviinalismus iin Millelaller, sein Ursjirung und sriii I'tr/auf, rragne. 
 Ib7(i. — Tu.j
 
 220 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 not a realiti/, "the Church" woukl be a mere collective 
 term, and the particular churches, or rather the individuals 
 composing them, would be the only realities. Hence, the 
 Church must be realistic,^ and declare with the Academy ; 
 Universalia sunt realia. Catholicism is synonymous with 
 realism. Common-sense, on the other hand, tends to 
 reo-ard universals as mere notions of the mind, as signs 
 desio-nating a collection of individuals, as abstractions hav- 
 ing no objective reality. According to it, individuals alone 
 are real, and its motto is : Universalia simt iiomina ; it is 
 nominalistic, individualistic. 
 
 The latter view was advanced and developed about 1090 
 by RoscELLiNUS, a canon of Compiegne. According to him, 
 universals are mere names, vocis Jiatus, and only particular 
 thino-s have real existence. Though this thesis seemed 
 quite harmless, it was, nevertheless, full of heresies. If 
 the individual alone is real, the Church is but a flatus vocis, 
 and the individuals composing it are the only realities. 
 If the individual alone is real, Catholicism is no more than 
 a collection of individual convictions, and there is noth- 
 ing real, solid, and positive, but the personal faith of the 
 Christian. If the individual alone is real, original sin is a 
 mere phrase, and individual and personal sin alone is reah 
 If the individual alone is real, there is nothing real in God 
 except the three persons, — the Father, the Son, and the 
 Holy Ghost ; and the common essence which, according to 
 the Church, unites them into one God, is a mere nomen, a 
 flatus vocis. Roscellinus, who is especially emphatic on 
 
 1 Let me remind the reader that in the Middle Ages the term 
 realiiit meant idealist, that is, the direct opposite of what it means 
 now. The same is true of the words objective and subjective. What 
 we call objective, Scholastic philosophy calls subjective (viz., that which 
 exists as a subject, substance, or reality independent of my thought) ; 
 while what we call subjective is called objective (viz., that which exists 
 merely as an object of thought and not as a real subject). This ter- 
 minology, the couvei-se of ours, is still found in Descartes and Spinoza.
 
 REALISM AND NOMINALISM 221 
 
 the latter point, is not content with defending his tritheis- 
 tic heresy ; he takes tlie offensive and accuses his adver- 
 saries of heresy. To hold that the Eternal Father himself 
 became man in Christ in order to suffer and die on Cal- 
 vary, is a heresy condemned by the Church as Patripas- 
 sianism. Now, if the Father, the Son, and the Holy 
 Ghost have the same essence, and if this essence is an 
 objective reality, it follows that the essence of the Father 
 or the Father himself became man in Cluist : a statement 
 which is explicitly contradicted by Scriptui-e and the 
 Church herself. 
 
 Roscellinus had pointed out a difficidty in the dogma, — • 
 an offence for which the Church never forgave him. The 
 Council of Soissons condemned his heresy and forced liim 
 to retract (1092). Nominalism thus anathematized held its 
 peace for more than two centuries, and did not reappear 
 until about 1320, in the doctrine of Occam. 
 
 The most ardent champions of realism in the controversy 
 aroused by the canon of Compiegne were St. Anselm and 
 William of Champeaux, a professor at Paris and after- 
 wards Bishop of Chalons.^ St. Anselm combated not 
 only the dogmatic heresy but also the philosophical heresy, 
 namely, the negation of Platonic idealism, the antithesis of 
 speculative philosophy. " Reason," he says,^ "is so confused 
 with corporeal ideas in tlieir souls (he is speaking of the 
 nominalists), that they find it impossible to get rid of them 
 and to separate from such material ideas that which ought 
 to be considered in itself and independently of all corporeal 
 intermixture. . . . They cannot understand that man is 
 something more than an individuaiy 
 
 William of Champeaux deduces the extreme conse- 
 
 ' Died 1121. [Michaud, GuiUaume de Champeaux et les ecoles de 
 Paris au Xfl^e siecle, Paris, 1SG8. — Tr.] 
 
 2 De fide trin., c. 2. We were, tlierefore, juslificd in translaliiig 
 nominalism by tlie word viateriulism. j). 21!*.
 
 222 niiLOSorHY of the middle ages 
 
 quences of realism. According to him, nothing is real but 
 the universal ; individuals are mere Jiatus vocis. From 
 the anthropological point of view, for example, there is in 
 reality, accorcUng to Champeaux, but one man, the univer- 
 sal man, the man-type, the genus man. All individuals 
 are fundamentally the same, and differ only in the acci- 
 dental modifications of their common essence. Champeaux 
 is but a step removed from pure pantheism, and yet he 
 is the defender of orthodoxy, the passionate adversary of 
 the heresy of Roscellinus ! What a strange confusion of 
 ideas and interests ! What an intellectual chaos, out of 
 which the Catholic theology of our day is with difficulty 
 beginning to bring order! 
 
 Between extreme nominalism, which says : Universale 
 'post rem, and extreme realism, which has for its motto : 
 Universale ante rem, there was room for a doctrine of 
 mediation, which may be summarized as follows : Univer- 
 sale neque ante rem nee post rem, sed In Re. Tliis we get 
 in the concept iialism of Abelard. 
 
 § 34. Abelard 
 PiEERE Abelaed, or Abailard,! ^^^^ i^q^.j-^ [^i Palais, 
 near Nantes, 1079, and studied at Paris under William of 
 Cliampeaux, the most skilful controversialist of the period. 
 Quarrelling with his teacher, who Avas jealous of his pupil's 
 brilliant talents, Abelard, though only twenty-two years 
 of age, opens a school at Melun, then at Corbeil. His 
 reconciliation with Champeaux brings him back to Paris, 
 where he meets with unparalleled success as a teacher. 
 Fallino- a victim to the vindictiveness of the canon Fulbert, 
 
 1 Abaelardi Opera, ed. Cousin, 1849-59 ; V. Cousin's Introduction to 
 Ouvrages inedits d'Ahelard, Paris, 1836 ; Cousin, Fragments de phi- 
 losophie xcolasiigiie, Taris, 1840 ; Charles de Rcmusat, Abelard, 2 vols., 
 Paris, 1845; [Ilausrath, Peter Abelard, Leipsic, 1892].
 
 ABELARD 223 
 
 whose niece he had seduced, he retires to the Abbey of St. 
 Denis, while Heloise takes the veil at Argenteuil. In his 
 retirement he writes the treatise Dc trinitate, a work wliicli 
 brings down upon his head the wrath of the Church. The 
 Council of Soissons condemns him to deliver his book to the 
 flames (1122). At Nogent-sur-Seine he founds an Oratory, 
 which he dedicates to the Tiinity, and particularly to the 
 Paraclete. Tliis he afterwards surrenders to Heloise, in 
 order to enter upon his duties as Abbot of St. Gildas de 
 Ruys. Denounced as a heretic by St. Bernard of Clair- 
 vaux, he is again condemned, this time to imprisonment 
 (1140) ; but he finds an unexpected refuge in the Abbey 
 of Clugny, and a noble protector in Peter the Venerable, 
 through whose efforts St. Bernard is finally moved to for- 
 giveness. These troubles undermine his health, and cause 
 his death in 1142. In addition to his Be trinitate, we have 
 to mention his Letters, his Introductio ad theologiam, and his 
 Thcologia Christiana, his Ethics (Nosce te ipsuni), the Dia- 
 logue between a Philosopher, a Christian, and a Jew, pub- 
 lished by Reinwald (Berlin, 1831), and the treatise Sic 
 et noii^ published by V. Cousin in the Ouvrages inedits 
 d'Ahelard (Paris, 1836). 
 
 Abelard is too speculative a thinker to accept the notions 
 of Roscellinus, and too positivistic to subscribe to the 
 theory of William of Champeaux. According to him, the 
 universal exists in the individual ; outside of the individual 
 it exists only in the form of a concept. Moreover, though 
 it exists in the individual as a reality, it exists there not 
 as an essence but as an individual. If it existed in it 
 essentially, or, in other terms, if it exhausted the essence 
 of the individual, what would l)e the difference between 
 Peter and I'aul ? Altliough Abelard's theory is not iden- 
 tical with nominalism, it comes very near it. It is to the 
 ultra-idealistic doctrine of Champeaux what the concrete 
 idealism of Aristotle is to tlie abstract idealism of IMato.
 
 224 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 Abelard, who was not acquainted with Aristotle's Meta- 
 physics, divines its contents from the few hints he gets 
 from the Organon. That alone would assure him a high 
 place among the doctors of the Middle Ages. 
 
 Abelard is, moreover, the most independent, the most 
 courageous, and the most relentless among the Schoolmen. 
 Thouo-h respectful towards the Church, he is not afraid of 
 incurring its displeasure, when occasion demands it. He 
 agrees with the author of the Cit7' Deus homo ? that revealed 
 truth and rational truth are identical, but he does not, like 
 Anselmus, accept St. Augustine's credo lU intelligam. It 
 is surprising with what frankness his Iiitroductlo condemns 
 the presumptuous crediditij of those ivho indiscriminately 
 and hastily accept any doctrine whatsoever hefore considering 
 its merits and whether it is worthy of belief. He is an en- 
 thusiastic admirer of Greek philosophy, which, however, as 
 he himself confesses, he knows only from the works of St. 
 Augustine. 1 He finds all the essential doctrines of Cliris- 
 tianity, its conception of God, the Trinity, and the incar- 
 nation, in the great thinkers of antiquity, and the distance 
 between Paganism and the Gospel does not seem so great 
 to him as that between the Old and the New Testaments. 
 It .is especially from the ethical point of view, he believes, 
 that Greek philosophy has the advantage over the teach- 
 ings of the sacred books of Israel. Hence, why should we 
 deny the pagan thinkers eternal happiness because they did 
 not know Christ ? What is the Gospel but a reform of the 
 natural moral law, legis naturalis reformatio ? Shall we 
 people hell with men whose lives and teachings are truly 
 evangelical and apostolic in their perfection, and differ in 
 nothing or very little from the Christian religion ? ^ 
 
 ^ TJieoIogia ch-istiana. Book IT. : Qiice ex philn^opJiia coUeqi fe^^fimonia, 
 non ex eorum scriptk, quce nunquam fortasse vidi, imo ex libris B. Aiigustini 
 colleg'u 
 
 * Theologia Christiana, 11.
 
 ABELARD 225 
 
 How does Abelard manage to find such doctrines as the 
 Trinity in Greek pliilosophy? The three persons are re- 
 duced to three attributes {proprietates own essentia^') of 
 the Divine Being : power, wisdom, and goodness. Taken 
 separately, he says,i these three properties : power, knowl- 
 edge, and will, are nothing ; but united they constitute the 
 highest perfection (tuta iKrfcdio honi). The Trinity is the 
 Being who can do what he wills, and who wills what he 
 knows to be the best. From the theological stand-point, 
 this is monarchism, a heresy opposed to the tritheism of 
 Roscellinus. Metaphysically, it is concrete spiritualism, 
 which denies that force and thought are separate entities, 
 and holds that they are united in the vnll. 
 
 In times of religious fervor, morality is identified with 
 piety, ethics with theology, while enlightened and sceptical 
 periods tend to separate them. The first appearance of a 
 system of ethics independent of dogmatics is therefore an 
 important symptom. Such a work is Hildebert of Lavar- 
 din's popular treatise on ethics, Moralis philosopJna,^ an 
 imitation of Cicero and of Seneca ; such is, above all, the 
 much profounder and more scientific treatise of Abelard : 
 Nosce te ipsum. 
 
 Not that Abelard dreams of separating ethics from onto- 
 logy, as our independent moralists do. But the 6v on which 
 he bases the moral law is not the divine free-will of the 
 Latin Fathers. Since God is the best and most perfect 
 Being, all his acts are necessary. For, if it be right that a 
 thing he done, it is wrong not to do it ; and whoever fails 
 to do what reason demands is no less at fault than he who 
 does what it prohibits. And just as God's conduct is de- 
 termined by reason, we, his creatures, are, in tui-ii, deter- 
 mined by the divine will. Inasmuch as God is llie ilbsolute 
 cause, tlio Being in whom we live, move, and liave our 
 being, and wlio is lli(;refore tlie source of onr jjowci- and 
 
 ' T/,r„/of/i<i r/iris/iaiKj. 2 s.-e § :V2. 
 
 li
 
 226 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 will, it follows that God is, in a certain sense, also tlie 
 author of whatever acts we may perform, and that he does 
 what he makes us do {quod nos facer e facif)} 
 
 The tendency to evil is not sin, but the condition of vir- 
 tue, for virtue is a struggle, and all struggle presupposes 
 opposition. Nor is the act as such the 7natter of the sin ; 
 the act as such is indifferent. The sin lies in the form of 
 the act, that is, in the will which chctates it. Neither the 
 tendency to evil nor the act in itself is sin, but the inten- 
 tion, though arrested, of satisfying an evil desire or indulg- 
 ing a passion. It follows that the man who has consented 
 to an evil action and is hindered in its accomplishment by 
 some circumstance or other, is as culpable as though he had 
 performed it. The intention deserves punishment as much 
 as the act, and he who consents to do evil has already done 
 evil. The Supreme Judge does not judge appearances and 
 the outside, but the spirit. By distinguishing between the 
 desire and the intention to surrender one's self to it, be- 
 tween the natural craving and the will to follow it, Abelard 
 repudiates that exaggerated form of pessimism which re- 
 gards the life of man as one perpetual sin ; by characteriz- 
 ing the external act as indifferent, he attacks the growing 
 formalism of Catholic morality. As was pointed out, the 
 conceptualistic theory shows the first signs of the influ- 
 ence exerted by Aristotle on the Middle Ages. The ethics 
 of Abelard reminds us of Aristotle and his ethics of the 
 golden mean .2 
 
 The influence of Abelard was considerable. We observe 
 it in Bernard of Chartres called Si/lvestris,^ in William of 
 Conches,'^ the learned professor of Paris, who, in his Fhilo- 
 
 1 Cf. the Ethics of Geulincx (§ 54). 
 
 2 [Cf/Th. Ziegler, AbcehmVs Elliica, Freiburg, 1884. — Tr.] 
 
 3 Megacosmus et Microcosmus [ed. by C. S. Barach, ISTfi] ; frag- 
 ments published by Cousin. 
 
 * Magna de naiuris philosophia: Dragmaticon pMlosopJiue, etc.; Philo- 
 
 sophia minor.
 
 HTGO OF ST. VICTOR 227 
 
 Sophia minor^^ protests against ecclesiastical intolerance, 
 in Gilbert tie la Porrde, Bishop of Poitiers,^ in John of 
 Salisbmy, Bishop of Chartres,^ and even in his adversary 
 Hugo of St. Victor. Gilbert is branded as an atheist by 
 St. Bernard because he distinguishes between God and the 
 Deit}', between the person and the essence of the Supreme 
 Being. ^' The divine Spirit," says John of Salisbury in his 
 Polycraticus,'^ " the creator and giver of life, replenishes not 
 only the human soul but every creature in the universe. 
 . . . For outside of God there is no substantial creature, 
 and things exist only in so far as they share in the divine 
 essence. By his omnipresence God envelopes his creatures, 
 penetrates them and fills them full of himself. . . . All 
 things, even the most insignificant, reveal God, but each 
 reveals him in its own Avay. Just as the sunlight is tlif- 
 ferent in the sapphire, the hyacinth, and the topaz, so, too, 
 God reveals himself in an infinite variety of forms in dif- 
 ferent orders of creation." 
 
 The same freedom of form and the same monistic ten- 
 dency as regards the matter, joined with the deepest and 
 purest religious feeling, we find in Hugo of St. Victor, 
 the fii-st great mystic of the Middle Ages. 
 
 § 35. Hugo of St. Victor 
 
 We observe a most striking diiTerence between Hugo of 
 Blankenburg,° a raonk of St. Victor at Paris, (1096-1140), 
 
 ^ Philosophia minor, I., 23. 
 
 2 Died 1154. Conun. in Buelh. de trin. ; De sex principiis. 
 
 « Died IISO. Opera, ed. Giles, 5 vols., 0.\ford, 1S18; [also in 
 Migne's collection, vol. 199; C. Schaarschniidt, ./(>/K/;///e.s' Saresberien- 
 m, etc., Leipsic, 1862. — Th.]. 
 
 * Polycralicm, I., 1, 5; III., 1 ; VIF., 17. 
 
 6 Opera, Venice, 1.5H8 ; Rouen, KJlS; [Migne, vols. IT.')-]??; Lieb- 
 ner, Hugo von St. Viktor, Leipsic, iS.-jr,; Pieger, Gcschichte der 
 deutxchen Myslih im Mittelaller, etc., Munich, 1875. — Tic]
 
 228 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 and his illustrious contemporary. Abelard is a French- 
 man : he has a perfect mania for clearness, precision, and 
 form ; his faith is a matter of knowledge ; logic is his 
 "god." Hugo is of German origin. His tastes as well 
 as his duties exclutle him from the brilliant scenes in 
 which the genius of Abelard unfolds itself. In the soli- 
 tude of his cell, he devotes himself to study, meditation, 
 and contemplation. He is no less independent than Abe- 
 lard, but with him it is all a matter of feeling rather than of 
 reflection. He is a skilful dialectician, but opposed to the 
 formalistic rationalism of the School. Although his liber- 
 alism differs very much from that of Abelard, he arrives at 
 similar results. Rationalism and mysticism both tend 
 towards monism. Hence mysticism exercises a no less 
 harmful influence upon the dogma than rational criticism, 
 during the Middle Ages ; hence, also, mysticism and pan- 
 theism are synonymous in France. 
 
 Hugo's views, especially as set forth in his work, De 
 sacramentis christiance fidei, are surprisingly bold. An 
 absolute orthodoxy does not seem to him to be essential to 
 salvation, or even possible. We ma}^ according to him, be 
 thoroughly convinced of the truth of the dogmas without 
 agreeing on their interpretation ; unity of faith by no 
 means implies identity of opinions concerning the faith.i 
 It is impossible to have uniform notions of God, because 
 God transcends all human conception. This is a charac- 
 teristic trait of mysticism, and essentially distinguishes it 
 from the rationalism of Abelard and Anselm. Although 
 assuming with the latter that the Trinity is simply supreme 
 power (the Father), supreme intelligence (the Son or the 
 Revealer), and supreme goodness (the Holy Ghost), Hugo 
 teaches that the infinite Being is absolutely incompre- 
 hensible. 
 
 God is not only supra-intelligible ; nay, we cannot even 
 
 "^ De sacramentis, I., p. x., c. 6.
 
 HUGO OF ST. VICTOR 229 
 
 conceive him by analogy. What, indeed, is analogous to 
 God ? The earth ? The heaven ? The spirit ? The soul ? 
 None of all these is God. You say: I know that these 
 tilings are not God; but they bear some resemblance to 
 him, and may therefore serve to define him. You might as 
 well show me a body in order to give me an idea of mind. 
 Your example would surely be inappropriate, and yet the 
 distance from mind to body is less than that between God 
 and mind. The most opposite creatures differ less among 
 themselves than the Creator differs from the creature. 
 Hence it is impossible to understand God, who exists only 
 for faith. ^ For Abelard, the pure dialectician, an incom- 
 prehensible God is an impossible God; for Hugo, tlie intui- 
 tionist and mystic metaphysician, he is the liighest reality. 
 Hugo was the first, after St. Augustine, to pay serious 
 attention to psychology. He is an earnest champion of 
 animism in this field. Body and soul are, in his opinion, 
 separate substances, without being absolutely opposed to 
 each other ; for there is a double bond of union between 
 them : the imagination, which is, so to speak, the corporeal 
 element of the soul, and sensibility, which is, as it were, 
 the spiritual element of the body. The soul possesses 
 three fundamental foj'ces: natural force, vital force, and 
 animal force. The natural force has its seat in the liver, 
 where it prepares the blood and the humors whieli are dis- 
 tributed through the veins over the entire body. It is 
 alternately appetitive, retentive, expulsive, and distributive, 
 and is common to all animals. The vital force, which 
 resides in the heart, manifests itself in the function of 
 respiration. It purifies the blood by means of inhaled air, 
 and causes it to circulate through the arteries. It also pro- 
 duces vital heat.2 The animal or psychic force, which is 
 
 ^ De sacramenlis, I., p. x., c. 2. 
 
 '^ Hugo has a vague idea of the ciiTuliilinn lA' liu' lilood ;iinl llin 
 difference between venous and artciiid l)lood. He also seems to regard 
 the liver as the cliief organ for tlie preparation of tlie vital Ihiid.
 
 230 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 situaled in the brain, produces sensation, movement, and 
 thought. Each of these manifestations of the soul employs 
 a different region of the brain. Sensation is connected 
 with the anterior portion, movement with the posterior 
 portion, and thought with the middle portion of this organ. 
 We have not two different souls: a sensitive soul, the 
 principle of corporeal life, and an intelligent soul, the prin- 
 ciple of thought. The soul Qanirna') and the spirit {ani- 
 mus sive s-piritus) are one and the same principle. The 
 spirit is this principle considered in itself and indepen- 
 dently of the body : the soul is this same principle in so far 
 as it animates the body.^ 
 
 There is a genuineness about these lines of the De anima 
 that contrasts with the fruitless quibblings of dualistic 
 spiritualism ; and when in the Zihri didascalici Hugo of 
 St. Victor traces the successive stages of psychical life 
 from the plant to man, he seems to anticipate evolution 
 and comparative psychology. 
 
 § 36. The Progress of Free Thought 
 
 The disciple of Hugo, the Scotchman Richard,^ Prior 
 of St. Victor, outlines a system of religious philosophy in 
 his De trinitate that breathes the same spirit of free inves- 
 tigation as the writings of his master. This may be seen 
 from the following characteristic lines : " I have often 
 read," he says, " that there is but one God, that this God 
 is one as to substance, three as to persons ; that the divine 
 
 1 De anima, II., 4 : Uiius idemqiie spiritus ad seipsum dicitur spnr- 
 itus, et ad corpus anima. Spiritus est in quantum est ratione pra:dita sub- 
 stantia; anima in quantum est vita corporis. . . . Non duce animcB, 
 sensualis et rationalis, sed una eademque anima et in semet ipsa vivit per 
 intellectum et corpus sensijicat per sensum. 
 
 2 Died 1174. Opera, Venice, 1506; Paris, 1518; [Migne, vol. 194; 
 J. G. V. Engelhardt, Richard von St. Victor und Johannes Rmjshroek, 
 Erlangen, 1838. — Tr.].
 
 THE PROGKESS OF EKEE THOUGHT 231 
 
 persons are distinguished from each other by a characteris- 
 tic propert}' ; that these three persons are not three gods, 
 but one only God. We frequently hear and read such 
 statements, but I do not remember ever having read how 
 they are proved. There is an abundance of authorities 
 on these questions, but an extreme dearth of arguments, 
 proofs, and reasons. Hence, the problem is to find a 
 firm, immovable, and certain basis on which to erect the 
 system." ^ 
 
 Richard finds such a basis for the dogma of the Trinity 
 in the idea of divine love, which necessarily creates an ob- 
 ject for itself. But tins proof he does not regard as sufii- 
 cient. AVhile liis De triuitate is conceived in the spirit 
 of Abelard, Ins Be cuntemplatiom openly espouses Hugo's 
 views. Richard abandons the attempt to reach God by 
 the reasoning powers, and substitutes feeling for reflection. 
 He distinguishes six stages in the mystical ascension of 
 the sold towards God. In the higher stages the soul is 
 expanded, raised above itself, delivered from itself {dilatatio, 
 sublevatio. alienatio, excessus). HoAvever, whether you call 
 him a mystic or a rationalist, Richard teaches a kind of 
 Neo-Platonic emanation and the identity of nature and 
 of grace. 
 
 Alaxus of Lisle,'-^ though an orthodox cliurchman, 
 tries to construct a sj'stem of dogmatics by means of a 
 strictly matlicmatical metliod, and concludes that every- 
 thing is in God and God in ever3-thing. 
 
 Robert of Melun ^ distinguishes — a serious symptom ! 
 — hetween event as f^ui secundum rcrum ncituram contingunt^ 
 et evenius qui contingunt secundum Dei potentiam quce supra 
 
 1 r., cii. o-o. 
 
 2 Alaims ab insulis, proffssor at Paris, flierl 1203. Opera, ed. by 
 
 Visch, Antwerp, 105:5; fvol. 120, Alit^iic]. 
 
 8 Dif'd 1173. Suiiuiiu tlieolofjki (llaiir(jau, in tlic wmk filed, 1., 
 pp. '.V-\2 fT.).
 
 232 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 reru'in naturam est. He is, however, truly devoted to the 
 Church and its doctrines, defending it against the heresies 
 which begin to threaten it. There are people, he says, 
 who deny the miraculous conception of Christ on the 
 jrround that such a phenomenon would be contrary to the 
 natural course of events. But is not God, the author 
 of nature, above nature, and has he not the power to 
 chano-e the regular course of nature? How are these 
 doubters going to explain the origin of Adam and Eve? 
 Just as the protoplasts could originate without an earthly 
 mother, Jesus was able to come into the world without 
 a human father. 
 
 In addition to these attempts at Christian pliilosophy 
 we have the HigJit Books of Sentences by the Englishman, 
 Robert Pulleyn,^ and the Four Books of Sentences by 
 Peter of Novaro, or the Lombard {Magister sententiarum).^ 
 Peter the Lombard's work, the success of which soon 
 eclipsed PuUeyn's, forms a complete sj'stem of dogmatics. 
 It considers a whole host of questions which betray the bar- 
 renness of Scholastic discussions, but wliich also show what 
 progress has been made by thought in its opposition to the 
 guardiansliip of the Church : How can we reconcile divine 
 prescience with free creation? (If God foresaw that he 
 would create, then he had to create, and creation is not an 
 act of freedom. If God did not foresee it, Avhat becomes 
 of his omniscience ?; Where was God before creation ? (He 
 could not have been in heaven, for heaven too was created.) 
 Could God have made things better than he has made 
 them? Where were the angels before the creation of 
 heaven ? Can angels sin ? Have they a body ? In what 
 form do God and the angels appear to men ? How do de- 
 
 1 Died about 1154. 
 
 2 Died 1164, Bishop of Paris. Lihri quatiior senientiaruvi (Venice, 
 1477 ; Bale, 1516, etc. Migne, vol. 192) ; [F. Protois, Pierre Lombard, 
 etc., Paris, 1881. — Tr.].
 
 THE PROGRESS OF FREE THOUGHT 233 
 
 mons enter into men ? What was Adam's form before his 
 appearance on earth ? Why was Eve taken from a side and 
 not from some other part of Adam's body ? Why was she 
 created while Adam was asleep ? Would man be immortal 
 if he had never sinned ? And in that ease how would men 
 have multiplied ? Would children have come into the world 
 as full-grown men ? Why did the Son become man ? Could 
 not the Father and the Holy Ghost have become man? 
 Could God have become incarnate in Avoman as easily as 
 in man? These hoivs and why's, multiplied without end, 
 betray the naive curiosity and the charming indiscretion 
 peculiar to the child, but they are at the same time unmis- 
 takable symptoms of the coming maturity and freedom of 
 thought. 
 
 The Sentences intensified the pious mystics' dislike for 
 the subtleties of dialectics. Graduall}^ abandoning sys- 
 tematic theology, mysticism turns its attention to prac- 
 tical Christianity, to preaching and the composition of 
 devotional books ; and while the Master of the Sentences 
 professes to serve the Church with no less zeal than Robert 
 of Melun, Walter of St. Victor, who died about 1180, de- 
 nounces the Lombard, his pupil Pierre of Poitiers, Gilbert 
 of I^orrde, and Abelard, as the four lahjrinths of France in 
 whicli we must take care not to lose ourselves.^ But tliis 
 opposition merely helped to develop heresy. A distinction 
 is made not onl}- between the effects of the divine will and 
 the effects of nature, but between philosophical truth and 
 religious truth. Tlie view begins to prevail that a thing 
 may be true in philosophy without being true in religion, 
 and vice versa. A vague suspicion arises that the Church 
 is fallible, and tliat a l)reach between faith and science, 
 theology and philosopliy, is not impossible. 
 
 A number of critical thinkers, influenced by Arabian 
 pantheism, were bold enougli to defend tlic ])]iil(is()])hy of 
 
 * ])u Boulay, Ilisloria u)iicersitatis I'arisiensis, vol. 1., p. Wl..
 
 234 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 immanency. They regarded the three persons of the Trin- 
 ity either as three successive manifestations of the Divine 
 Being, or as three different stages in the development of 
 the human conception of God. The Father is the ,God 
 of the Ohl Testament, God dwelling in heaven ; the Son is 
 the God of the New Testament, God bridging tlie chasm 
 and coming nearer to man ; the Holy Ghost is the God of 
 the future, the true God conceived as the universal and 
 omnipresent Being. God is everything and produces 
 everything in all things. He is, therefore, not only pres- 
 ent in the consecrated host, but also in the daily bread. 
 His spirit manifested itself in the great men of Greece as 
 well as in the Prophets, Apostles, and Fathers. Tliere is 
 no other heaven than a good conscience, no other hell than 
 remorse ; and the worsliip of saints is idolatry. 
 
 These doctrines, which were ably taught by Simon of 
 Tournay, Amalric of Bena, and David of Dinant,^ spread 
 rapidly among the clergy and the laity. About tlie year 
 1200 they formed a formidable though secret opposition to 
 the supreme authority of tradition. The Church, seriously 
 threatened in its unity, averted the danger by burning a 
 great number of heretics at the stake and anathematizing 
 the phj^sics of Aristotle, from which David of Dinant was 
 accused of having drawn his heresies (1209). 
 
 ^ For the pantheistic heresy of Amalric and David, see Ch. 
 Schmidt, Histoire et doctrine de la secte des Cathares, 2 vols., Paris, 
 1849.
 
 SECOND PERIOD 
 THE REIGN OF PERIPATETIC SCHOLASTICISM » 
 
 A. Semi-Realistic Peripateticism 
 8 37. Growing Influence of the Philosophy of Aristotle 
 
 We have pointed out the relation existing between Pla- 
 tonic realism and the Catholic system. In Catholicism as in 
 Platonism, in the Chnrch as in Plato's State, the universal 
 is superior to the particular ; the whole precedes, rules, and 
 absorbs the parts ; the Idea is the true reality, the power 
 superior to all individual existences. The philosophy of 
 a period reflects the spirit peculiar to that period. The 
 heroic age of Catholicism, the age of faith which produced 
 the Crusades and built the Gothic cathedrals, could not 
 but have an essentially idealistic, Platonic, and Augus- 
 tinian philosophy. Scotus Erigena and St. Anselm were 
 the great representatives of this epoch. But even in the 
 writinsfs of these men, and still more so in those of their 
 successors, we discover, beneath the seeming harmony of 
 their jjhilosophy and theology, contrasts, disparities, and 
 contradictions. E^rigena culminates in monism ; William 
 of Champeaux, in the philosophy of identity ; Abelard, in 
 determinism ; Alanus, Gilbert, and Amalric of Bena, in 
 pantheism. The Schoolmen of the period, if we may be- 
 lieve them, are convinced that reason and tlie dogma agree ; 
 and their philosophy merely aims to prove the agreement 
 an<l to justify the faith. But it is certain that from 1200 
 on this conviction was gradually sliaken. As soon as Scho- 
 
 ^ A. .Tonrdaiii, Reclie.rches critiques sur I'df/e el I'orli/ltir de;; Irddur 
 lions Iftiiues iV Arislote, Paris, 1819; L'd ed., 1813.
 
 236 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 lasticism discriminated between philosophical truth and re- 
 ligious truth, it divided into the disparate elements which 
 it professed to unite, and sealed its doom. Scholasticism 
 had not reached the climax of its development before it 
 began to show symptoms of decay. It needed a power- 
 ful stimulus to keep it alive ; new life and vigor had to 
 be infused into it from without ; this it received from 
 Aristotle. 
 
 At the beginning of the thirteenth century, Christian 
 Europe knew nothing of Aristotle's writings except a part 
 of the Organon in the Latin translation ascribed to Boethius. 
 From this time on, things rapidly change. About 1250, 
 Robert, Bishop of Lincoln, translates the Nicomackean EtJiics 
 into Latin. The Dominicans Albert of BoUstiidt and St. 
 Thomas of Aquin write valuable commentaries on the 
 Stagirite, and in every way encourage the translation of his 
 works. But it is particularly^ to the Arabians ^ that the 
 Christian Middle Ages owe their knowledge of his treatises 
 on physics and ontology. During the eleventh and twelfth 
 centuries, Avicenna in Persia and Averroes in Spain pub- 
 lish commentaries on them, and either by oral teaching 
 or by their written works intensify the interest for Peri- 
 patetic philosophy. Two royal friends of letters, Roger II. 
 of Sicily and the Emperor Frederick II., surround them- 
 selves with Arabian scholars, under whose direction Latin 
 translations of Aristotle and his commentators are made. 
 These translations are presented to the universities of 
 Bologna, Paris, and Oxford. In this way thousands of 
 students become acquainted with the doctrines of the great 
 Greek. Prior to this time, only Aristotle the logician had 
 been studied, and that, too, rather superficiall}-. Hence- 
 forth, Aristotle the moralist, the physicist, and the meta- 
 physician, becomes an object of study. 
 
 The Aristotelian system was an innovation, and conse- 
 
 1 See p. 210, note 2.
 
 GROWING INFLUENCE OF PHILOSOPHY OP ARISTOTLE 237 
 
 quently the conser^-ative Church had to combat it. For was 
 not its author both a heathen and a favorite of the disciples of 
 the false prophet, and, therefore, the incarnation of all anti- 
 Christian tendencies ? Was he not, in a certain measure, 
 the soiu'ce of the heresies of David of Dinant and his con- 
 sorts ? The Church condenuied Aristotle's treatises on 
 physics in 1209, and his Metaphysics in 1215. But she 
 soon saw the error of her ways. From 1250 on, she 
 allowed public lectures on Aristotle to be delivered at 
 Paris ; and fifty years later the Stagirite became her offi- 
 cial pliilosopher, whom one could not contradict without 
 being accused of heresy ; he is the precursor Christi in 
 rehus naturalihus, sicitt Joannes Baptista in rebus gratuitis. 
 This reaction was no more than natural. True, Aristotle 
 was a pagan philosopher, and consequently an opponent of 
 the faith; but if, in spite of that, his doctrine should be 
 found to agree with the Gospel, it would add all the more 
 to the glory of Christ. Aristotle taught the existence of a 
 God apart from the universe, and that alone ought to have 
 won him the sympathies of the Church threatened by the 
 pantheistic heresy, which appealed to Plato for aid. 
 
 More than that ; Aristotle offered the Churcli a system 
 wliich she had the greatest interest in appropriating, with 
 certain limitations. The times had already become familiar 
 with the conception of nature. They spoke of nature and 
 its course as opposed to God and the effects of liis will. 
 Christian thought could not help returning to this funda- 
 mental conception of science, in the course of its develop- 
 ment, wliile the Church could no more oppose it than she 
 could hinder the formation of the European States. Slie 
 could not destroy these States, and tlierefore made them 
 subject to herself; she was unal)le to extirpate the con- 
 ception of nature, and tlierefore drew it into lier service. 
 Now, the metaphysics of Aristotle was adniiral)ly fitted for 
 such a [)ur[)OS('. For, does not Aristotle regard nature as a
 
 238 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 hierarchical system of which God — and consequently the 
 Church — is both the basis and the summit ? With the 
 admirable tact which seldom failed her, Catholicism recog- 
 nized Aristotle in order to make capital out of him. 
 
 But the chief advantaofe resultinof from an alliance with 
 Peripatetic philosophy was the following: As soon as 
 Aristotle's system received recognition as the only authen- 
 tic expression of human reason, its authority naturally tran- 
 scended that of free thought. Hence Peripateticism gave 
 tlie Church a still better means of regulating Scholastic phi- 
 losophy than she already possessed. During the Platonic 
 period thought enjoyed a relative independence ; its ob- 
 ject was to prove the agreement between the dogma and 
 natural reason ; and, as we have seen, it was quite rational- 
 istic in the performance of this task. Henceforth the ques- 
 tion no longer is to prove the agreement between the 
 dogma and natural reason, but its agreement with the 
 letter of Aristotle's writings. The proof of this agree- 
 ment makes Aristotle the highest authority and his system 
 the official criterion of a philosopher's orthodoxy. Aristotle 
 still stands for reason, but reason now is disciplined and re- 
 duced to a fixed code. Left to itself, reason is a change- 
 able authority, and its agreement with faith not necessarily 
 a settled fact. What to St. Anselm seemed agreement, 
 Abelard, Gilbert, Amalric, and David regarded as contra- 
 dictory. The mind is mobile, revolutionary ; the letter is 
 eminently conservative. By adopting the philosophy of 
 Aristotle, the Church made use of the most illustrious 
 thinker in order to enslave thought. 
 
 The advantages arising from this alliance with Peripa- 
 tetic philosophy were, it is true, accompanied by disadvan- 
 tages that became serious dangers in the sequel. In the 
 first place, the truth of the dogma was proved by its agree- 
 ment with Aristotle ; this raised the authority of Aristotle 
 and philosophy above the authority of the Church. Then
 
 PERIPATETICS OF THE THlRtEENTH CENTURY 239 
 
 the influence of the Stagirite necessarily introduced into 
 Sehohisticism a new element, not very favorahle to the 
 spiritual omnipotence of the Chui-ch : the taste for science 
 and the spirit of analysis. 
 
 § 38. The Peripatetics of the Thirteenth Century 
 
 The Church was converted to Peripateticism by a num- 
 ber of eminent thinkers who were less original than St. 
 Anselm and Abelard, but, owing to the more abundant 
 material at their disposal, more learned than their prede- 
 cessors. At their head stands the Englishman Alex- 
 A^'DER OF Hales,! professor of theology at Paris, whose 
 commentaries on the Sentences of Peter the Lombard and 
 the De anima of Aristotle won for him the title doctor 
 irrefragahilis. 
 
 William of Auvergne, Bishop of Paris,^ whose learn- 
 ing equalled that of Alexander, wrote a series of treatises 
 inspired by Aristotle, and a voluminous work, De universo, 
 a kind of metaphysics, the wonderful erudition of which 
 proves that the author was thorouglily acquainted with the 
 Arabian commentaries on the Stagirite. His Peripatetic 
 leanings, however, did not hinder him from denying the 
 eternity of the world, nor from believing in creation, Prov- 
 idence, and the immortality of the soul. 
 
 The Dominican Vincext of Beauvais,^ the teacher of 
 the sons of St. Louis, gathers the treasures of learning and 
 of Peripatetic speculation in his Speculum quadruplex : na- 
 turale, doctrinale, morale, et liistoriale. He cites almost all 
 the writings of Aristotle, and already speaks triumphantly 
 of tlie nova loyica as opposed to the logica fetus. He is an 
 
 ' Dif'il Vl\'>. Summa unirerscE thcolofi'ict, Venice, L")70. 
 
 2 I)if;d 1210. Opera, ed. Blaise Leferon, (Jrleans, 1071; [N. Valois, 
 Guillawne d'Auuergne, Paris, l.S8()]. 
 
 * Died 1204. Speculum fii.ctriitdle, Straslmri^, 1173; S/x-culntn tjun- 
 thupler, clr., 1021.
 
 240 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 open adherent of the Lyceum on the subject of universals, 
 which still forms the chief topic of discussion among the 
 Schoolmen, and declares with Abelard : Universale in re. 
 Universals are real, even more real than particulars, with- 
 out, however, existing independently of particulars. As in 
 the system of Abelard, universals and particulars are no 
 longer abstractly and mechanically juxtaposed in the meta- 
 physics of Vincent, but are joined together by the principle 
 of individuation {incorporatio). A new terminology is used 
 by this Schoolman to express Aristotelian conceptions. 
 The Ti ean of Aristotle, for example, becomes the quidditas. 
 The philosophical vocabulary is developed and enriched at 
 the expense of Ciceronian Latin, which the Renaissance 
 afterwards undertakes to rescue from the neglect of the 
 School. 
 
 Though a realist, in so far as he regards the universal as 
 a reality, Vincent makes an important advance towards 
 nominalism by distinguishing between universale meta- 
 phi/sicum and universale logicnm, i. e., between the specific 
 type which really exists in the individuals composing the 
 species and the general notion which corresponds to this 
 type, and is but an abstraction of thought. This distinc- 
 tion is a nominalistic deviation from realism, for the pure 
 realism of Champeaux and Anselm absolutely iden- 
 tifies the specific type and the general idea. It is, how- 
 ever, far from being pure nominalism, for nominalism is 
 the absolute negation of the universale metaphysictnn as an 
 objective reality. 
 
 Another Dominican, who has already been mentioned,^ 
 Albert of Bollstadt,^ wrote commentaries on most of 
 Aristotle's works, and labored with untiring zeal for the 
 
 1 § 37. 
 
 2 Albertus Magnus, died at Cologne in 1280. Opera, ed. by P. 
 Jammy, Lyons, 1651 (21 folio vols.). [J. Sighart, Albertus Magnus, 
 etc., Regensburg, 1857; Eng. tr. by Dixon, 1876.]
 
 ST. THOMAS OF AQUIN 241 
 
 propagation of the Peripatetic philosophy. He manifests 
 a remarkable taste for natural science, in which respect 
 he anticipates Roger Bacon, Raymundus Lullus, and the 
 scientilic Renaissance. We see how danp-erous the Peri- 
 patetic alliance proved to the Church ! 
 
 The Franciscan John of Fidaiiza, known as St. Bona- 
 VENTUKA,^ is less learned and less interested in nature, but 
 more speculative than Albert. He admires both Aristotle 
 and Plato, rational philosophy and contemplative mysti- 
 cism, piet}' and knowledge, thus uniting in liis person two 
 elements which were growing farther and farther apart. 
 The Church recognized his services by canonizing him, and 
 the School bestowed upon him the title of doctor seraphicus. 
 
 Filially, two illustrious rivals complete the Peripatetic 
 galaxy of the tliirteenth century and finish the work of 
 conciliation between the Church and the Lyceum : the 
 Dominican St. Thomas of Aquin and the Franciscan Duns 
 Scotus. 
 
 § 39. St. Thomas of Aquin 
 
 THo:yrAS of Aquin 2 (Aquino), the son of a noble family 
 in the kingdom of Naples, preferring the peaceful pleas- 
 
 ^ Died 127-4. Author of a Commentary on the Sentences of the Lom- 
 bard, of an Itinerarium mentis in Dewn, conceived in the spirit of the 
 mystics of St. Victor, etc. Edition of Strasburg, 1482, Rome, 1588, ff., 
 etc.; [K. Werner, Die Psychologic imd Erkenntnisshhre dcs Bouav&ntura, 
 Vienna, 1876.] 
 
 2 Opera omnia, Rome, 1570 (18 foHo vols.); Venice, 1504; Ant- 
 werp, 1612; Paris, 1660; Venice, 1787; Parma (25 vols.), 1852-71; 
 [Thomas Aquinads opera omnia jussn impensaque Leonis XITl., P. M. 
 edila, vols. I. & II., Rome (Freiburg i. H.), 1882, 84]; Ch. Joiudain, 
 La philosophic de Saint Thomas d' A qtiin, Pari.s, 1858; Cacheux, De la 
 philosophic dc Saint lltouias, Pari.s, 1858; [Karl 'NAVrner, Der hcUiqe 
 Thomas von Aquino, 3 vols., Regen.slnirg, 1858 IT. ; Z. Gonzales, Estudios 
 sobre la filosofia dc S. Tmnds, 3 vols., Manila, 1864 (Cu-nnan translation 
 by C. J. \olte, Regen.sburg, 1885). — Tu.] He was called doctor 
 aufjellcus. 
 
 16
 
 242 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 ures of study to the adventurous life of a feudal lord, 
 entered the order of St. Dominic, in spite of the formal pro- 
 tests of his father. On the eye of his departure from Italy 
 to Paris, he was kidnapped by his brothers and imprisoned 
 in the paternal castle, from wliich he managed to escape 
 two years later. Taking up his abode at Cologne, he be- 
 came an enthusiastic disciple of Albert the Great and a 
 profound student of Aristotle. Henceforth all his efforts 
 were directed towards acquainting tiie Christian Occident 
 with the Aristotelian philosophy as set forth in the Greek 
 text, particularly with the Physics and Metaphysics^ of 
 which only Latin translations made from Arabian trans- 
 lations were known. He afterwards returned to the 
 Peninsula, where he died in 1274, scarcely fifty years 
 of age. 
 
 Philosophy is indebted to him for a series of treatises 
 bearing on the metaphysics of Aristotle (Opuscula de materia; 
 natura, de ente et essentia, de jprincipiis naturce, de jjrincijno 
 individuationis, de universalihus, etc.). His Summa theologies, 
 which gradually eclipsed the Sentences of Peter the Lom- 
 bard, forms the basis of the dogmatic teachings of the 
 Chiu'ch, 
 
 The philosophy of St. Thomas has no other aim than the 
 faithful reproduction of the principles of the Lyceum. We 
 are therefore interested, not so much in the contents, as in 
 the Neo-Latin form in which the ideas of the Stagirite are 
 expressed. Our modern philosophical vocabulary is in part 
 derived from the system of St. Thomas. 
 
 Philosophy proper or the 'first philosophy has for its ob- 
 ject being as such (ens in quantum ens = to ovfj 6v). There 
 are two kinds of beings {entia) : objective, real, essential 
 beings (esse in re), and beings that are mere abstractions of 
 thought or negations, such, for example, as poverty, blind- 
 ness, and imperfection in general. Poverty, blindness, 
 and privation exist ; they are entia (ovtu), but not essen-
 
 ST. THOMAS OF AQUIN 243 
 
 tice {ovaiat)} Essences, substances, or beings properly 
 so called {essentia^ substanticc) are, in turn, divided into 
 simple or pui'e essences, and essences composed of form 
 and matter. There is but one simple essence or pure form : 
 God. All the rest are composed of matter and form. 
 
 Matter and form are both beings (entia) ; they differ 
 from each other in that form is in actic, while matter 
 is as yet merely in j^otentia. In a general sense, matter 
 is everything tliat can be, everything that exists in pos- 
 sibility. According as the possible thing is a substance or 
 an accident, metaphysics distinguishes between materia ex 
 qua oliquid fit (potential, substantial being, — example: the 
 human seed is materia ex qua homo fit, a potential man) 
 and materia in qua aliquid fit (potential accident, — exam- 
 ple : man is materia, in qua gignitur intdlectus). Materia 
 ex qua does not exist in itself; materia in qua exists as a 
 relatively-independent subject {suhjectum). The form is 
 what gives being to a thing.^ According as this thing is a 
 substance or an accident, we have to deal with a substan- 
 tial form or an accidental form. The union of matter {esse 
 in potentia) and form {esse in actii) is generatio Q^iveadai)^ 
 whicli is, in turn, substantial generation or accidental gen- 
 eration. All forms, God excepted, are united with matter 
 and individualized by it, constituting genera, species, and 
 individuals.^ 
 
 Only the form of forms remains immatci'ial and is sub- 
 ject neither to generation noi- decay. The more imperfect 
 a form is, the more it tends to increase tlie number of in- 
 dividuals realizing it ; the more perfect a form is, the less 
 it multiplies its individuals. The form of forms is no 
 longer a species composed of separate individuals, but a 
 single being within whicli all differences of person are 
 constantly merged in tlie unity of essence. Since God 
 
 ^ Opuxcxilum (If. entc. el fssfnlin. 
 
 ^ Opusc. <lc jiiin'i/iiis iKilttrre. 8 j,] ^ q 3_
 
 244 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 alone is pure form [actus 'pu-'us)^ without matter and con- 
 sequently without imperfection (matter being that Avhicli 
 does not yet exist, or the lack of being), God alone is the 
 perfect arid complete knowledge of thingSo^ He possesses 
 absolute truth because he is absolute truth. Truth is the 
 agreement of thought with its object. In man, there is 
 more or less agreement between thoughts and objects ; 
 they are, however, never identical. God's ideas not only 
 exactly reproduce the things, they are the things them- 
 selves. Things first exist, and then man thinks them : in 
 God, thought precedes the things, which exist only because 
 and as he thinks them. Hence there is no difference in 
 him between thought and being; and, since this identity 
 of knowledge and its object constitutes truth, God is truth 
 itself. From the fact that he is the truth it follows that 
 he exists ; for it is not possible to deny the existence of 
 truth ; the very persons who deny it assume a reason for 
 doing so, and thus maintain its existence.^ 
 
 The demonstration of the existence of God is the first 
 and principal task of philosophy. Pliilosophy could not, 
 however, perform this task, or even have a conception of 
 God, had not the Creator first revealed himself to man in 
 Jesus Christ. In order that the human mind might direct 
 its efforts towards its real goal, it was necessary for God 
 to point it out, that is, to reveal himself to humanity at 
 the very beginning. No philosophy is legitimate that does 
 not take revelation for its starting-point and return to it as 
 its final goal : it is true only when it is ancilla e.cclesim, and, 
 in so far as Aristotle is the precursor of Christ in the scien- 
 tific sphere, ancilla Aristotelis. The Church of God is the 
 goal towards which all things tend here below. 
 
 Nature is a hierarchy in which each stage is the form of 
 the lower stage and the matter of the higher stage. The 
 
 1 Summa theologice, I., question 4. 
 
 2 I<1., question 2, article 1.
 
 ST. THOMAS OF AQUIN 245 
 
 hierarchy of bodies is completed in the natural life of mail, 
 and this life, in turn, becomes the foundation, and, in a 
 certain measure, the material for a higher life, the spiritual 
 life, wliich is developed in the shadow of the Clmreh and 
 nourished by its Word and its sacraments, as the natural 
 life is nourished by the bread of the earth. The realm of 
 nature is therefore to the realm of grace, the natural man 
 to the Christian, philosophy to tlreology, matter to the sacra- 
 ment, the State to the Church, and the Emperor to the 
 Pope, what the means are to the end, the plan to the exe- 
 cution, the potcntia to the actus. 
 
 The imiverse, which consists of the two realms of nature 
 and of grace, is the best possible world. For God in his 
 inthiite wisdom conceived the best of worlds ; he could not 
 have created a less perfect world without detracting from 
 his wisdom. To say that God conceived perfection and 
 realized an imperfect world would presuppose an opposi- 
 tion between knowledge and will, between the ideal prin- 
 ciple and the real principle of things, ^hich contradicts 
 thought as well as faith. Hence the divine will is not a 
 will of inchfference, and the freedom of God, far from being 
 S}Tionymous with caprice and chance, is identical with 
 necessity. 
 
 In spite of seeming contradictions, tlie same is true of 
 the human will. Just as the intellect has a ])iineij)le (lea- 
 son) which it cannot discard without ceasing to l)e itself, 
 the will has a principle from Avhich it cannot deviate with- 
 out ceasing to be free : the good. The will necessarily 
 tends to the good ; but sensuality tends to evil and thus 
 paralyzes the efforts of the will. Hence sin arises, which 
 has its source, not in the freedom of indifference or of 
 choice, but in sensuality,^ Tliere is moral predestina- 
 tion, but not arl)itrary yn-edcstination, for the divine will 
 itself is suborflinated to reason. Dclcnniuism extended 
 1 Suimna theolut/iie, <iuestion b'2; Contra (jcul'dts, III.
 
 246 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 to God loses the offensive character which it had in the 
 theology of St. Augustine. 
 
 The system of St. Thomas marks both the climax of the 
 development of Catholic metaphysics and the beginning of 
 its fall. Before the days of St. Thomas, Scholastic philos- 
 ophy had shown symptoms of decline ; in him it shines 
 with a light before Avhich the most illustrious names pale. 
 His devotion to the Church and its interests, his philosophi- 
 cal talents, which he employs in the service of Catholicism, 
 and his faith in the perfect harmony between the dogma 
 and philosophical truth as set forth in Aristotle, make him 
 the most typical doctor of the Church after St. Augustine 
 and St. Anselni. But his faith, ardent though it be, 
 does not possess the strength of an unshakable convic- 
 tion ; it is rather a willed faith, an energetic will con- 
 stantly struggling against the thousand difficulties Avhich 
 reflection throws in its way. From St. Thomas downwards, 
 reason and Catholic faith, official theology and philosopliy, 
 are differentiated and become more or less clearly con- 
 scious of their respective principles and interests. Meta- 
 physics continued, for a long time, to be subject to 
 theology; but though dependent, it henceforth had a 
 separate existence, a sphere of activity of its own. 
 
 Pliilosophy proper receives its official sanction, as it 
 were, by the organization of the four Parisian faculties, an 
 event wdiich occurred during the lifetime of St. Thomas. 
 This period marks the decline of Scholasticism. The 
 theologians themselves, with John Duns Scotus at their 
 head, do all they can do to hasten it. 
 
 § 40. Duns Scotus 
 
 JoHX Duns Scotus of Dunston (Northumberland), a 
 monk of the order of St. Francis, professor of philosophy 
 and theology at Oxford and Paris, was the most industri-
 
 DUNS SCOTUS 247 
 
 ous among the Schoolmen. Although he tiled at the age 
 of thirty-four (1308), his writings fill a dozen volumes.^ 
 
 We have just seen how philosophy was officially recog- 
 nized as a science distinct from theology. During the 
 times of Duns Scotus, i. e., about the end of the tliirteenth 
 century, philosophy formed an independent science by the 
 side of theology, and even dared to oppose the latter. The 
 philosophers, said Duns Scotus, differ from the theologians 
 as to whether man has any need of acquiring, by super- 
 natural means, knowledge wliich his reason cannot attain 
 by natural means. This statement not only shows the 
 existence of a philosophy that is independent of theology, 
 but the disagreement which has existed between philoso- 
 phers and theologians ever since. 
 
 Duns Scotus, like a genuine Schoolman, occupies a 
 position between the two camps. With the theologians 
 he recognizes the need of revelation ; but he agrees with 
 the philosophers that St. Augustine is wrong in assuming 
 that man can know absolutely nothing of God without 
 supernatural revelation. With the theologians he de- 
 clares that the Bible and the teachings of the Church are 
 the supreme norms of pliilosophic thought ; but he is, on 
 the other hand, a philosopher and a rationalist to the ex- 
 tent of believing in the authority of the Bible and of 
 ecclesiastical tradition, only because the doctrines of the 
 Bible and the Church conform to reason. Hence reason is, 
 in his eyes, the liighest authority, and the sacred texts have 
 for him but a derived, conditional, and relative authority. 
 With this as his guiding principle, he does what no School- 
 man had done before him : he attempts to prove the credi- 
 bility of Holy Writ, and, in choosing his arguments, he evi- 
 dently gives the preference to the internal ])roofs.2 
 
 1 Opera omnia, Lyons, 1639. For the system of Duns Scotus, see 
 Rittcr, Vol. Vlir.; [Werner, Stiickr. 
 ' D. S f/i Mdfjifitnim spnfi'nlltiruin.
 
 248 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 The more familiar we become with Schohistic literature, 
 the less apt are we to exaggerate the progress of free 
 thought from the thirteenth to the nineteenth centuries. 
 The historians who endeavor to trace all modern negations 
 to the Reformation ignore, or affect to ignore, the fact that 
 in the ninth century the Catholic Scotus Erigena denied 
 eternal punislmient ; that in the twelfth, the Catholic Abe- 
 lard declared the teachings of the Greek philosophers to be 
 superior to those of the Old Testament ; that in the thir- 
 teenth, a great number of Catholics refused to believe in 
 the miraculous conception and in the resurrection of Christ ; 
 til at in the same century, or two hundred years before the 
 Reformation, and at a time when the power of the Holy 
 See was at its height, St. Thomas and Duns Scotus found 
 themselves obliged to prove, with all the arts of logic, the 
 need of revelation and the credibility of the Divine Word ; 
 finally, that these submissive, devoted, and orthodox doc- 
 tors of the Church combined with their Clnistian convic- 
 tions a freedom of thought, the like of which is but rarely 
 met with in the Protestant theology of the seventeenth 
 century. 
 
 The Thomistic system borders on pantheism, while the 
 philosophy of Duns Scotus is decidedlyPelagian ; the illus- 
 trious Dominican sacrifices the freedom of the individual 
 to the great glory of God ; while the Franciscan doctor 
 believes that he is rendering God a no less signal service 
 by exalting the individual and free-will at the expense of 
 grace. 
 
 Duns Scotus serves the order to wliich he belongs as 
 faithfully as his God and the Church. The great mediaeval 
 orders are the forerunners of the theological parties of 
 Protestantism. They are, at present, merged in the indi- 
 visible unity of the Roman orthodoxy ; during the period 
 of which we are speaking, they Avere real parties, opposed 
 to each other, not only on practical questions, but on points
 
 DUNS SCOTUS 249 
 
 of doctrine Avliich do not, even now, strike us as secondary. 
 The rivalry between these two orders often infused new 
 life into Scholasticism. The contest between Duns Scotus 
 and the Scotists against Thomism really represents a strug- 
 gle for Church supremacy between two powerful orders. 
 The glory reflected upon the Franciscan order by St. 
 Bonaventura was dimmed by the fame of the Dominicans, 
 Albert the Great and Thomas of Aquin. Jealous of the 
 good name of his order, Duns Scotus endeavors to expose 
 and refute what he calls the errors of Thomism. Thomas 
 remaining true to the dogmatic and didactic tenets of his 
 order, is the apostle of faith and grace. Duns Scotus, 
 whose heart is also hlled with the spirit of liis order, — a 
 spirit of living and practical piety, — becomes the apostle 
 of action, meritorious works, and human freedom. With 
 an acumen that is wholly in keeping with his title, doctor 
 subtilis^ he undertakes the criticism of St. Thomas. 
 
 Thomistic determinism, assuming as it does the superi- 
 ority of the intellect over the will, has the true ring of 
 Catholic philosophy. By benchng the will beneath the yoke 
 of an absolute principle, it humiliates the self-love of the 
 individual, desti'oys his confidence in his own powers, and 
 makes him conscious of his insignificance. But when the 
 foundations of the system are laid bare they are found to 
 be very weak. Thus, on the one hand, it makes God liim- 
 self a relative being, whose will is the slave of his intelli- 
 gence. On the other hand, it does more than humiliate 
 the individual: it discourages him and cbives him to 
 despair or moral indifference. Should the Church adopt 
 this system, it would without fail soon cease to be the 
 sanctuary of virtue and the mother of saints. Hence the 
 jyrimacy of the intelligence must be opposed by tliat of 
 the will,^ and for determinism we nuist sul)stitute tlie true 
 
 1 Tilt! voluntarism Q^ Duns Scotus is to tli<; intclltcliKilIsm of 'I'lioiniis 
 what the Kant of the Criti'jue of /'radical Rcaaon is to Uic Kant of the
 
 250 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 philosophy and the real thought of Aristotle: the doctrine 
 of divine and human liberty. 
 
 If we would not confuse t\o true God with the Fate or 
 the natura naturans of the Neo-Platonists, we cannot hold, 
 with the Thoniists, that the world is the necessary product 
 of his essence, his intelligence or his will. God created the 
 world by an act of freedom. It would have been possible 
 for liim not to create it. His will was not inclined that 
 way by any higher principle, for it is itself the highest 
 principle of divine acts. The existence of the world, far 
 from being necessary, is the free effect of the free will of 
 God.i Abelard is therefore wrong in assuming that God 
 could create only what he created, and that what he cre- 
 ated he created necessarily ; and Thomas is in error when 
 he teaches that the world is necessarily the best possible 
 world. God does not create all that he can create; he 
 creates only what he desires to call into existence. 
 
 The first cause of things, the divine will, is consequently 
 also the supreme law of created spirits. Goodness, jus- 
 tice, and the moral law are absolute, only in so far as they 
 are willed by God ; if they were absolute independently of 
 the divine will, God's power would be limite ! by a law not 
 depending on him, and he would no longer be the highest 
 freedom or, consequently, the Supreme Being. In reality, 
 the good is therefore the good, only because it is God's 
 pleasure that it should be so.^ God could, by virtue of his 
 supreme libert}^, supersede the moral law which now gov- 
 erns us by a new law, as he superseded the Mosaic law by 
 that of the Gospel ; above all, he could — and who knows 
 but what he really does in many cases ? — exempt us from 
 doing good without our ceasing, on that account, to be 
 
 Critique of Pure Reason, and what the panthelism of Schopenhauer is 
 to the panlogism of Hegel. 
 
 1 In ilf . sentent., I., distinction, 39, question, 1. 
 
 2 Id., distinction 44.
 
 DTOvS SCOTUS 251 
 
 good. In the creation as in the government of the world, 
 God knows no other hiw, no other rule, no other principle, 
 than his own freedom. And it is because he is free to 
 exempt us, in case he so desii-es, from carrying out any 
 particular law of the moral code that the Church in tui-n 
 has the right to grant dispensations. If God is not abso- 
 lutely free in tins matter, as he is in all things ; if he is, 
 as Thomas of Aquin claims, a being absolutely determined 
 in his will by his supreme wisdom, what becomes of the 
 right of indulgences ? Like God, man is free ; the Fall did 
 not deprive him of free-will ; he has formal freedom, i. e., 
 he may will or not will ; and he has laatcrial freedom, i. e., 
 he can will A. or will B. (freedom of choice or indifference). 
 
 These doctrines, though diametrically opposed to St. 
 Augustine's, could not be disagreeable to the Church, the 
 Pelagian tendencies of which they reflected and encour- 
 aged. But they concealed a danger, and the Church, which 
 failed to canonize Duns Scotus, seems to have appreciated 
 it. By Iris emphatic affirmation of individual liberty, the 
 subtle doctor proclaimed a new principle, an anti-authori- 
 tative power, which grew from century to century, and 
 finally led to the emancipation of the religious conscience 
 and the downfall of ecclesiastical tradition as the su- 
 preme autliority in matters of faith and conscience. So, 
 too, on the subject of universals, Duns Scotus approaches 
 nominalism and empiricism, though striving to remain true 
 to the realistic and rationalistic system upheld by the 
 Church. All his sympathies are, at bottom, for the indi- 
 vidual ; for the will is his principle ; and though reason is 
 common to all, the will is what characterizes the individual. 
 The question of individuation is his favorite problem. His 
 contemporaiy, Heniy Goethals,^ following the exami)le of 
 William of Chainpeaux, regarded the principle of individu- 
 
 1 l-217-l-'!'o. Quodlihela theologica,V[\\\\\b\>^\ Sunima lliml., Vnrh, 
 1520; I'cirara, I'ilG.
 
 252 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 ation as a mere negation ; while St. Thomas based it on 
 matter (the non-being). Duns Scotus, however, declares 
 it to be a positive jDrinciple, and gives it the name of 
 lioecceitas. The individual is, according to him, the sum of 
 two equally positive and real principles : the quidditas (the 
 universal, or the type common to the individuals of one and 
 the same species) and the Jtcecceitas, the principle of the 
 individuality or of the difference of individuals. The quid- 
 ditas has no reality apart from the hceeceitas, nor the hccc- 
 ceitas apart from the quidditas. Reality is found in the 
 union of the two principles, of the ideal and the real, that 
 is, in the individual. 
 
 By his doctrines of individual liberty and Jicecceitas Duns 
 Scotus paves the way for the nominalism of his disciple 
 Occam. His doctrine of accidental creation hastens the 
 rupture between science and the authoritative rationalism 
 of the Church, and the advent of modern empiricism ; for 
 if the law^ of nature and the moral law itself are contin- 
 gent, all science and morality itself depend on experience 
 as their only basis. To place the will in the first rank in 
 metaphysics and reason in the second, means to subordinate 
 reasoning to the methods of observation and experience. 
 Duns Scotus not only hastens the breach between science 
 and dogma ; but, the breach seems to be already made 
 when, in his Qumstioncs subtilissimw., he rejects innate 
 ideas, and declares the proof of the immortality of the soul 
 and of the existence of God to be impossible from the 
 standpoint of science. 
 
 B. NoRirtsTALisTic Pekipateticism 
 
 § 41. Reappearance of Nominalism. Durand, Occam, 
 Buridan, D'Ailly 
 
 The distance from the conceptualism of Vincent of Beau- 
 vais, Thomas of Aquin, and Duns Scotus to nominalism is
 
 KEAPPEARANCE OF NOMINALISM 253 
 
 not o-reat. Indeed, the semi-realism of Duns Scotus re- 
 sembles the doctrine of Roscellinus more closely than that 
 of Champeaux. William Duua^^d of Saint-Pourcain,i 
 fii-st a disciple of St. Thomas, then influenced by the doc- 
 trines of 'Scotus, comes still nearer to nominalism in 
 formulating the following thesis : To exist means to he an 
 individital. Finally, the Franciscan Willia.m of Occam,^ 
 the precursor and fellow-countryman of John Locke, openly 
 antagonizes realism as an absurd system. According to 
 the realists, he says, the universal exists in several things 
 at once ; now the same thing cannot exist simultaneously 
 in several different things; hence the universal is not a 
 thing, a reality {res), but a mere sign that serves to desig- 
 nate several similar tilings, a word {mmeii) ; and there is 
 nothing real except the individual.-^ 
 
 Scepticism is the necessary consequence of nominalism, 
 which has already been outlined in § 33. Science has 
 for its object the general, the universal, the necessary. 
 The science of man, let us say in the spirit of Plato, does 
 not deal with Peter for the sake of Peter, or with Paul for 
 the sake of Paul; it studies Peter and Paul in order to 
 know what man is. It is the universal man, the species 
 man, wliom it seeks in the individual. The same is true 
 of all sciences. Now, if the universal is a mere word 
 liaving no objective reality, and if the individual alone is 
 real, then there can be no anthropology, nor any science. 
 
 1 IJorn in Auvergne, died 13-32, Bishop of Meaux. Comment, in 
 mag. senlent., Paris, 1508; Lyons, 1568. 
 
 2 Died 1343. Quodlibela septem, Strasburg, 11!)1 ; Summa toliu!! 
 lugices, Paris, U88 ; Oxford, 1G75; Qiiccsliones in lihrnx plu/sicoruin, 
 Strasburg, 1491 ; QucBstiones et decimmex in quatuor lib. sent., Lyons, 
 1405; Centilogium iheoL, Lyons, 14y(i ; Ex/mxilio aurea super totam 
 artem veterem, Bologna, 1400. [Cf. W. A. Sclirr-ilior, Die pnHtischen uud 
 rdigiosen Doclrinen unter Ludwig drm Bnier, Laiidshut, 1858 ; Pranll, 
 Geschichte der Logik, Vol. III., pp. 327-120. — Tr.J 
 
 3 decani, fn I. I. .tentenlinruin, dist. 2, qnfstion 8.
 
 254 PHILOSOPHY 01^ THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 We can know and tell what both Peter and Paul are ; we can 
 study each particular plant and animal ; but the universal 
 man, plant, and animal can never become objects of science, 
 because they nowhere exist. Hence, nominalism is scep- 
 tical of science ; its motto agrees with that of Protagoras : 
 IVie individual is the measure of all things. 
 
 The liighest science, theology, does not escape William's 
 sceptical criticisms. He accepts the teacliing of his master, 
 and declares that it is impossible to demonstrate the exist- 
 ence and unity of God.^ The ontological and cosmologi- 
 cal arguments are equally weak, in his judgment, and the 
 necessity for the existence of a first cause seems to him to 
 be a purely hypothetical necessity. Indeed, reason may 
 invariably oppose the no less probable theory of the infinite 
 causal series. Hence, there can be no rational or scientific 
 theology ; and if the science pursued by such thinkers as 
 Origen, Augustine, Anselmus, and Thomas is impossible, 
 then Scholasticism itself becomes a mere heap of barren 
 hypotheses. Science belongs to God, faith to man. 
 
 Let the doctors of the Church recognize the futility of 
 their speculations, and become interpreters of practical 
 truth and propagators of the faith ! Let the Church 
 a})andon this empty, terrestrial science ! Let her cast off 
 all the worldly elements with which she has been tainted 
 by her contact with the world ; let her reforin and return 
 to the simplicity, purity, and holiness of the Apostolic 
 times ! Though Occam sided with the King in the quarrel 
 between Philip the Fair and the Holy See ; and though 
 he fled from France and offered his services to Louis of 
 Bavaria,^ who was also at loggerheads with the Vicar of 
 Christ, he was neither hostile nor indifferent to the Church. 
 
 1 Occam. In I. I. sentent., dist. 3, quest. 4; Centilnglum theologicum 
 f. I. 
 
 2 He is said to have addressed the following remark to Louis : Tu 
 me defendas gladio, ego le defcndam calamo.
 
 REAPPEARANCE OF NOMINALISM 255 
 
 On the contraiy, like all true followers of St. Francis, he 
 felt a deep love for liis spiritual mother. And because he 
 loved her, he desired to see her great and hoi}- and removed 
 from the harmful influences of the world ; he could not 
 approve of the Pope's interference with the temporal 
 affairs of the European States. It was his devotion to the 
 Church that forced him to make common cause with the 
 enemies of the Hol}^ Father. 
 
 Xominalism not only weakens the alliance between faith 
 and science ; it also attempts to sever the bond which had 
 for centuries united the Church with the world. Its reap- 
 pearance not only marks the decline of Scholasticism ; sim- 
 ultaneously with it, we notice the fii'st symptoms of the 
 decadence of the Papal power, to wliicli the European mon- 
 archs henceforth offer a successful resistance. The nomin- 
 alism of Occam, though sincere in its desire to promote the 
 welfare of the Church, nevertheless resembles all philos- 
 ophy ; it mirrors the ruling purpose of the age, i. e., the 
 necessit}' on part of the secular powers, the states, the 
 nations, the languages, intellectual culture, the arts, the 
 sciences, and philosophy, to shake off the yoke of Christian 
 Rome. From the reappearance of nominalism we date the 
 first beginnings of national life and modern languages, and 
 tlie opposition to the political, religious, and literary cen- 
 tralization, to which the heir of Caesarean traditions had 
 subjected Europe. Xominalisra therefore conceals beneath 
 its seeming devotion to the Church and its pious contempt 
 for science, a mass of tendencies hostile to Catliolicism. 
 And the Church gives it the same reception wliich she had 
 given Aristotle a century before : she condemns it. But 
 the heresy had taken deep root this time ; it satisfied the 
 political, intellectual, and religious strivings of tlie epoch 
 tcjo well to be suppressed. 
 
 The doctrines of Duiand and Occam gave the signal for 
 the struggle l)etween the i-ealists and nominalists. Tlie con-
 
 256 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 flict raged during the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries ; 
 it transformed the universities into veritable iiekis of battle 
 — the expression is not a metaphor— and continued down 
 to the Renaissance and Reformation. Realism had dis- 
 tinguished followers during the fourteenth century, e. g., 
 Walter Burleigh, who defended it in the name of science 
 and philosophy ; Thomas op Bradwardine,^ Archbishop 
 of Canterbury, who upheld it in the name of the faith, and 
 accused Occam of Pelagianism ; Thomas of Strasburg,^ 
 and Marsilius of Inghek,^ the first rector of the Univer- 
 sity of Heidelberg, who tried to reconcile the opposing doc- 
 trines. But even in its conceptualistic form, it attracted 
 only the most speculative minds ; the clear and well-defined 
 conceptions of nominalism appealed more and more to what 
 is called common-sense. In spite of the obstinate resistance 
 of the realistic party and of the government which this 
 party had succeeded in interesting in its behalf, the teach- 
 ings of Occam eventually made their wa}^ into the Sorbonne, 
 where they were ably reproduced by John Buridan,^ and 
 more or less modified in the dogmatic sense, by Pierre 
 D'AiLLY,^ the eagle of France. 
 
 Nominalism represented the reformatory tendencies of 
 the times, and could not but triumph. 
 
 § 42. Downfall of Scholasticism. Revival of the Interest 
 in Nature and Experimental Science. Roger Bacon. 
 Mysticism 
 
 In vain did the nominalist Pierre d'Ailly struggle 
 against the conclusions of Occam, and attempt to defend 
 
 1 Died 1349. 2 Djed 1357. s Died 1396. 
 
 * Died about 1360. He wi'ote Summa dialect , Paris, 1487; Comp. 
 log., Venice, 1480 ; and a series of commentaries on Aristotle, pub- 
 lished in Paris and Oxford. 
 
 ^ Died 1425. Qucefttinnex super quatunr I. sent., Strasburg, 1490; 
 Tractatus et sermones, 1490.
 
 DOWNFALL OF SCHOLASTICISM 257 
 
 Scholasticism against the claims of scepticism. The alliance 
 between the essential elements of Scholasticism had been 
 seriously weakened. It is true, Occam, Durand, Buiidan, 
 and Gabriel Biel,^ are sceptics only in metaphysics; still by 
 holding that we can know nothing of God, Providence, the 
 Fall, Kedemption, liesurrection, and Judgment, and that 
 we must be content with helieving all these doctrines, they 
 make them uncertain and problematical, and involuntarily 
 advance the cause of heterodoxy. They themselves give 
 up science for faith ; others, who are less devoted to the 
 Church, gradually abandon faith and become freethinkers. 
 Thus in 1347, Johx of Mercuria, a member of the Cis- 
 tercian order, was condemned for having taught : (1) that 
 everything that happens in the world, the evil as well as 
 the good, is eif ected by the divine will ; (2) that sin is a 
 good rather than an evil ; (3) that he who succumbs to an 
 irresistible temptation does not sin. Thus also in IS-IS, a 
 bachelor of theology, Nicolas of Autkicueia, had the 
 boldness to present the following theses to the Sorbonne : 
 (1) We shall easily and quickly reach certain knowledge, if 
 we abandon Aristotle and his commentaries, and devote 
 ourselves to the study of nature itself. (2) It is true, we 
 conceive God as the most real being, but we cannot know 
 whether such a being exists or not. (3) The universe is 
 infinite and eternal ; for a passage from non-being to being 
 is inconceivable. — Such expressions of free tliought were 
 as yet uncommon, but for that very reason all the more 
 remarkable. 
 
 Speculative philoso})liy and its anti-scholastic strivings 
 received a powerful ally in tlie experimental sciences, 
 whicli were revived Ijy the study of Aristotle's works on 
 physics and l)y the influence of the Aral)ian scliools of 
 Spain; to these we owe our S3st('iii of iiuincials, tlie 
 elementaiy principh'S of algcl)ra and clicniistry, an<l our 
 
 1 I'rofessor at 'I'iiliiiigcii, dii'd lliJ.j. 
 17
 
 258 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 knowledge of the astronomical traditions of tlie Orient. 
 The instruction offered in Christian schools was purely 
 dialectical and formal ; it trained the mind for discussion, 
 but left it an utter blank. As early as the thirteenth 
 century, the Franciscan monk Roger Bacon,i a professor 
 at Oxford, recognized tlie serious imperfections in the 
 system, and conceived the plan of reforming it by the 
 introduction of the sciences. His three works, Oims 
 majus,^ Opus mimis, and Ojyus tertiiwi,^ the fruit of twenty 
 years' investigation, to which he devoted his entire for- 
 tune, constitute the most remarkable scientific monument of 
 the Middle Ages. Not only does he call attention to the 
 barrenness of the scholastic logomachies, the necessity of 
 observing nature and of studying the languages, but he 
 recognizes, even more clearly than his namesake of the 
 sixteenth century, the capital importance of mathematical 
 deduction as an auxiliary to the experimental method. 
 Nay, more than that ; he enriches science, and especially 
 optics, with new and fruitful theories. But his scientific 
 reforms were premature in the year 1267, which marks the 
 appearance of his Ojpus majns. His plan was submitted to 
 the court of Rome, but owing to the intrigues of the 
 obscurantist party, it fell flat, and procured for Roger 
 twelve years of confinement. The seed sown by this most 
 clear-sighted thinker of the Middle Ages upon the barren 
 soil of Scholasticism did not spring up until three cen- 
 turies later. 
 
 Albei't the Great (§ 38), though not attaining to Bacon's 
 eminence, shows a marked preference for the study of 
 
 1 Doctor mirabllis, 1214-1294. 
 
 2 Ed. Jebb, London, 1773, folio. 
 
 ' In Rogeri Bacon Opera qucedam hactenus inedila, ed. J. J. Brewer, 
 London, 1859 ; Charles, Roger Bacon, sa vie, ses ouvrages, ses doctrines, 
 d'apres des textes inedits, Bordeaux, 1861 ; [K. Werner, Psychologic, 
 Erkenntniss- und Wissenscha/lslehre des Roger Baco, Vienna, 1879. — 
 Tk.].
 
 DOWNFALL OF SCHOLASTICISM 259 
 
 nature, which he himself, like his age, confused with magic. 
 During the same epoch, Don Raymoxd Lin.LUS ^ of Palma, 
 a curious mixture of theologian and naturalist, missionary 
 and troubadour, endeavored to popularize the science of the 
 Arabians by means of a universal method, which he called 
 ars magna. His teacliings, which were recorded in numer- 
 ous writings, gained for him, during the succeeding cen- 
 turies, enthusiastic followers, whose chief concern was to 
 chscover the philosopher's stone and to make gold. As- 
 sisted by such trifles, the human mind gradually returned 
 to the observation of reality, and came to regard nature as 
 an object of study no less important than Aristotle. About 
 1400, the physician Ray^iond of Sabltnde,^ a professor 
 at Toulouse, had the boldness to prefer to books made by 
 human hands the hook of nature, ivkich hchig the uvrk of 
 God is intelligible to all. 
 
 The official philosophy, with its barren formalism, its 
 ignorance of reality, and its hopeless indolence, had 
 arrayed against it thought chafing under the yoke of the 
 ecclesiastical Aristotle and yearning for progress and free- 
 dom, and natural science, which foreshadowed its future 
 grandeur in the rudimentary form of magic. Finally, it 
 also gave offence to religious feeling and mystical piety 
 because of its inability to supply the soul with substan- 
 tial nourishment and to inspire the Christian life witli 
 an ardent love for goodness. Mysticism bad for cen- 
 turies been the ally of Scholastic speculation ; in Scotus 
 Erigena, the sages of St. Victor, and St. Bonavcntura, it 
 tempered the cold reasonings of tlic School with its glow- 
 ing warmth, aiid (IcscciKlcd upon their barren logic like 
 
 ^ 1234-1315. Raipmti>f/l Lull! Ojiera,^trnn]nirg,'ir)0H; Opera omnia, 
 ed. Sulzingcr, Maycucc, ]7"J1 It'. 
 
 ^ Died 1130. Raunundi lihcr natnrd' sire crcalitrarum Qhcohxjia natu- 
 ralls), Strasbiirg, 1490; Paris, 1509; Siilzl):icli, 1852; Kleiber, De 
 Raimundi vita el srriptix, Berlin, 1850.
 
 260 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 a refreshing dew. It widened the narrow circle of an in- 
 tolerant orthodoxy by emphasizing the fides qua creditur 
 instead of the fides quae creditur, by laying greater stress 
 upon faith itself as a subjective phenomenon and the ani- 
 mating principle of the soul, than upon the object of faith. 
 But the more deeply Scholasticism became absorbed in 
 formal disputes and childish discussions, the more distaste- 
 ful and antagonistic it became to the religious spirit which 
 longed for a life in God and was stifled by the categories 
 of Aristotle. 
 
 Some mystics, like St. Bernard ^ and Walter of St. 
 Victor, inveigh against logic because they consider it 
 dangerous to the dogmas of the Church. Others, who are 
 less scrupulous in tliis respect, but equally anxious to 
 possess God, are carried away by the ardor of their 
 religious sentiments to the extreme conclusions of pan- 
 theistic speculation. According to them, dialectics is a 
 lal)yrinth in which the soul, instead of reaching God, is 
 farther and farther removed from him, and finally loses him 
 altogether. Feeling, they believe, brings us directly into 
 communion with God ; with one bound we overcome the 
 obstacles of discursive thought and are carried to the centre 
 of things and the source of being, where self-consciousness 
 is merged in the consciousness of God. According to some, 
 feeling alone will transport the soul by enchantment to the 
 summit of existence and the source of life. So Eckhart,^ 
 the Dominican provincial of Cologne and a t}^3ical panthe- 
 istic mystic. Others, though seeking to be united with 
 God, do not expect to reach their goal except after long and 
 wearisome trials ; hence, to the love of God they add the 
 love of goodness and moral struggle as indispensable con- 
 
 1 1091-1158. 
 
 2 Died about 1300. [Bach, Meister Eckhart, etc, Vienna, 1864; 
 Lasson, Meister Eckhart, der Mystiker, Berlin, 1868] ; Ch. Jundt, Essai 
 sur le mysdcisme speculat'if de maltre Eckhart, Strasburg, 1871.
 
 THE REVIVAL OF LETTERS 261 
 
 ditions of tlie Christian nirvana to which they aspire. To 
 tliis chiss belong John Taflep.,^ a Dominican preacher of 
 Cologne and Strasburg, J0H2; AVessel,"'^ and Thomas a 
 Ke:mpis,2 the supposed author of the Imitation of Christ ; 
 all of these are indebted for the new element in their 
 teachings to the wholly Pelagian influence of nominalism. 
 Tills influence is still more pronounced in the Frenchman 
 John Gersox,* the chancellor, and Nicolas of Clemanges,^ 
 the rector, of the University of Paris, whose mysticism is 
 nothing but moral asceticism, and differs essentially from 
 its German namesake. But beneath these different forms 
 lurks one and the same anti-scholastic tendency, one and 
 the same spirit of reform. 
 
 § 43. The Revival of Letters 
 
 Corresponding to each of the elements of progress just 
 mentioned, we notice a group of highly important historical 
 facts, which give a decided impetus to these tendencies. 
 Free thought eagerly seizes upon the literary master- 
 pieces of antiquity, wliich are made known by Greek 
 emigrants, and which the timely invention of printing helps 
 to render accessible to all. The scientific spirit of the age 
 and its naturalistic bent, admirably assisted by the inven- 
 tion of the compass and the telescope, triumphs in the 
 discovery of America and of the Solar System. The con- 
 templation of these new and infinite worlds arouses feel- 
 ings of enthusiasm and confidence which become more and 
 more dangerous to Scholasticism and tlic authoritative 
 
 ^ Died LSOL [Editions of Tauler's sermons, Leipsic, 1498 ; Bile, 
 1521 f. ; Cologne, 1543. Modern edition, Frankfurt a. M., 1820 and 
 18G4. — Tr.] 
 
 2 Died 1489. 8 Died 1 171. 
 
 * Died 1420. [Opera, Cologne, 1483 ff.] See C. Scliniidt, Essai sw 
 Jean Gerson, Strasburg, 1830. 
 
 6 Died 1440.
 
 262 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 system of the Church. At the same time, the religious 
 spirit receives encouragement from the great reform move- 
 ment of the sixteenth century, inaugurated by the literary 
 awakening in the fifteenth. 
 
 Under the auspices of the Byzantine government, which 
 survived the ruin of the ancient world, the Hellenic pen- 
 insula preserved, in antiquated and pedantic form, the 
 literary and philosophical traditions of antiquity, its taste 
 for classical learning, and its love for the great philosophers, 
 Plato and Aristotle. Here the writings of these thinkers 
 were studied in tlie original at a time when Greek was not 
 only a dead language but absolutely unknown in the Occi- 
 dent. A kind of worship grew up around them, and the 
 more impossible it seemed to surpass them, the greater admir- 
 ation they inspired. As long as such stars and their 
 satellites shone in the heavens of Byzantium and Athens, 
 the taste for learned studies and free speculation could not 
 disappear from Grecian soil, and even the theological 
 pedantry of the Emperors could not destroy it. In the 
 main, therefore, the Orient exerted a wholesome and lib- 
 eralizing influence on the Occident. 
 
 In a certain sense, this influence goes back to the period 
 of the Crusades. By an " irony of fate," not unfrequent 
 in history, the Catholic Church failed to reap the expected 
 fruits of these expeditions. The Orient had been invaded 
 in the name of the Roman faith, and the Crusaders brought 
 back nothing but heresies. The futile efforts made by the 
 "Western Church, during the first half of the fifteenth 
 century, to bring about a reconciliation with the Eastern 
 Church resulted similarly. The influence of the Greek 
 Orient was beneficial to the Occident, but injurious to the 
 hierarchical tendencies of Catholicism. Some centuries 
 before, the Calabrians, Barlaam and Leontius Pilatus, and, 
 after them, Dante, Petrarch, and Boccaccio had cultivated 
 a taste for Greek literature in Italy ; but the Orient did
 
 THE REVIVAL OF LETTERS 263 
 
 not exercise a direct and lasting influence upon Europe 
 until after 1438, when the B3'zantine Church sent her 
 scholars to Florence. The object of their mission was the 
 reconciliation of the two churches ; but they became the 
 missionaries of classical ci^"ilizalion from the Orient to the 
 Empire of the Popes. 
 
 Greek scholars flocked to Italy in still greater numbers, 
 causing a veritable migration from the Orient, when 
 Bj-zantium and the last remains of the Eastern Empire fell 
 into the hands of the Turks (1-153). This event raised 
 Italy to the position which she had occupied in literature, 
 art, and pliilosophy two thousand years before ; she again 
 became Magna Graccia. In the year 1410, the Greek 
 scholar, Geoegius Gej^hstus Pletho,^ an ambassador to 
 the Council of Florence, whom the munificence of Cosmo dei 
 MecUci had succeeded in detaining in Italy, founded a Plu- 
 tonic Academy in Florence. His fellow-countryman Bes- 
 SARION 2 succeeded him in the government of the school 
 and in the work of propaganda. He defended the Acad 
 emy against his compatriots Gennadius, Theodorus Gaza, 
 and Georgius of Trebizond, followers of the Lyceum, and 
 gained a large number of Italian adherents for Plato, not- 
 withstanding the opposition of the Peripatetics and their 
 orthodox supporters. 
 
 The fellow-countrymen of Dante were completely fasci- 
 nated with the Greek language. It was studied with the 
 passionate ardor peculiar to the Italian people. Philosophy 
 became the all-important science. The Venetian Hiiioro- 
 LAUS BARBAiti's, I^AUMEXTILTS Valla of Rome, and Ax- 
 
 ^ Ilfpi ojf ^ \pi(TT0Ti\r)<; TTpns nXdrcowi ^ui(\)(p(T<n, Paris, 1540 ; Nd/xcoi' 
 (Tvyytmrprf (frafj;iiients collccttMl l)y C Alcxaiidri' and translated into 
 Frencli l>y A. PcUissitT, I'aris, 1858). [See F. Sc-liultze, Gcschichte iler 
 Philosophie der Renaissance, vol. I., Geo. Gem. Pkthon, -Fma, 1871. — 
 Tk.] 
 
 2 Adversus calumniatures Platonis, Rome, IKiO; [Opera onniia, cd. 
 MigiK", I'aris, 18fK5\
 
 264 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 GELIJS PoLiTiANUS were zealous disciples of the exiles of 
 Byzantium. The love of ancient literature and the dislike 
 for the language of the School extended even to the leaders 
 of the Church. The Cardinal Nicolas of Cusa (Kuss i), 
 who possessed the qualities of a Bruno and a Descartes, had 
 the courage openly to criticise the errors of Scholasticism, 
 and recommended the philosophy of Plato, which he iden- 
 tified with the Pythagorean theory of numbers, as in every 
 way preferable to the reigning system. The wave of classi- 
 cism even reached the throne of St. Peter; and it is a 
 Avell-known fact that Leo X. and liis secretary Bembo 
 greatly preferred Cicero to the Vulgate. The religion of 
 Virgil and Homer superseded the religion of Christ in the 
 hearts of the high dignitaries of the Church and the secu- 
 lar scholars, poets, and artists; the joyful Olympus was 
 exchanged for the severe Golgotha ; Jehovah, Jesus, and 
 Mary became Jupiter, Apollo, and Venus ; the saints of 
 the Church were identified with the gods of Greece and 
 Rome, — in a word, the times returned to paganism. 
 
 Marsilius Ficinus,2 a pupil of the Florentine Acad- 
 emy, continues the struggle begun by Bessarion in behalf of 
 
 1 Diocese of Treves. " Cusanus, whose real name was Ivi-ebs, died 
 in 146i. His Works appeared in three folio volumes, Paris, 1514 
 [German transl. of his most important writings, by F. A. Scharpff, 
 Freiburg, 1862]. The best known of his treatises, De docta ignorantia, 
 is foimd in the first volume. The second, which contains his treatises 
 on astronomy and mathematics, makes him the forerunner of Coper- 
 nicus and of the reform of the calendar. He anticipates Bruno by 
 his do"ctrine of the absolute unity-God, and Schelling and Hegel by his 
 conception of the coincidence of contradictories. See Richard Falcken- 
 berg, Grundzlige der PJiilosophie des Nicolas von Cusanus, Breslau, 1880. 
 
 2' A Florentine, 1433-lt99. Florence and the century of the liter- 
 ary renaissance also produced the great politician and Italian patriot, 
 Nicolo Maoehiavelli (1469-1527), the author of 11 imncipe, etc. [works 
 translated by C. E. Detmold, Boston, 1883], whose system is based on 
 the principle that the end justifies the means (separation of politics from 
 morals).
 
 NEO-PLATONISM 265 
 
 Plato. For him, Platonism is the quintessence of human 
 wisdom, the key to Christianity, and the only efficient 
 means of rejuvenating and spiritualizing the Catholic doc- 
 trine. As the editor, translator, and commentator of Plato 
 and the Alexandrians, Marsilius Ficinus is one of the 
 fathers of modern classical philology as well as of the phil- 
 osophical Renaissance. An equally distinguished person is 
 the Count Jolui Pico of Mirandola (1463-1494). Pico 
 recommends Hebrew in addition to the study of the Greek 
 language and literature ; believing, as he does, that the Jew- 
 ish Cabala ^ is as important a som-ce of wisdom as Plato 
 and the New Testament. He bequeaths his love of phi- 
 lology and his Cabalistic prejudices to his nephew, John 
 Francis Pico of Mirandola, a less talented but more pious 
 man than his uncle, and to the German Reuchlin, who, 
 upon returning to the Empire, becomes the founder of 
 classical and Hebrew philology in his countr}^ and by com- 
 bating Hochstraten and the obscurantists paves the way 
 for the spiritual deliverance of his native land. 
 
 § 44. Neo-Platonism. Theosophy. Magic 
 
 The mixture of new ideas and old superstitions gives 
 rise to a number of curious theories, partially modelled 
 after Neo-Platonic doctrines, which represent the stages, 
 as it were, by which the philosophical and scientific mind 
 gains its independence. Tliey may be classed under the 
 title theoso'phy. Tlieosophy sliares theology's belief in the 
 supernatural and philosophy's faitli in nature. It forms an 
 intermediate stage, a kind of transition, between theology 
 and ])ure philosophy. It does not attain to tlie dignity of 
 modern experimental science; for it rests upon an inner 
 revelation, which is superior to sensible experience and 
 
 1 Coiiceniiii^ IIk' Cabala, see Munck, %.s7me de la Kabbalc, Viiv\s, 
 1812; M(!lan<jcx de philosophle jnive ct arahe, Paris, 1859.
 
 266 riiiLOSOPHY of the middle ages 
 
 reasoning. It does not study nature for nature's sake, but 
 in order to discover the traces of the mysterious Being 
 which nature hides as well as reveals. Now, in order to 
 discover it, theosophy needs a key of Sesame, a no less 
 mysterious instrument than the object of its studies. It 
 therefore enters upon a search for secret doctrines, and 
 greedily seizes and utilizes whatever is offered in this line. 
 Hence the enthusiasm M^hich the teachings of the Jewish 
 Cabala and of Neo-Platonism arouse in Pico of Mirandola, 
 who compares them with those of the Bible, and in Reuch- 
 lin, who exalts them in liis Dc vcrho mirifico ^ and his Be 
 arte cahalistica? 
 
 Theosophy is not content with fathoming the great mys- 
 tery ; it does not regard it as enough to know nature ; it 
 desires what Francis Bacon afterwards desired: to rule 
 over it, to master it, to control it. And just as it claims to 
 reach a knowledge of things by means of secret doctrines, 
 it boasts of being able to control them by secret arts, by 
 formulas and mysterious practices. That is to say, it neces- 
 sarily becomes magic or theurgy.-^ Magic is based upon 
 the Neo-Platonic principle that the world is a hierarchy of 
 divine forces, a system of agencies forming an ascending 
 and descending scale, in which the higher agencies com- 
 mand and the lower ones obey. Hence, in order to govern 
 nature and to change it according to his wishes, the theos- 
 ophist must be united with the higher forces on which the 
 sublunary sphere depends; and since, according to Aris- 
 totle and Ptolemy, the heavenly powers or the sidereal 
 agencies are uch higher forces, astrology plays an impor- 
 tant part in the lucubrations of the theosophist. 
 
 This union of Platonism, or rather Pythagoreanism, 
 with theurgy and magic is best exemplified in Reuchlin's 
 disciple, Agrippa of Nettesheim,^ the author of a treatise, 
 
 1 Bale, 1494. 2 Hagenau, 1517. 3 Cf. §§ 25 and 26. 
 
 * Born at Cologne, 1487 ; died at Grenoble, 1535.
 
 ARISTOTLE VERSUS ARISTOTLE 267 
 
 J)c vanitate scientiarum, directed against scholastic dogma- 
 tism ; in Jerome Cardaxits,^ a noted physician and mathe- 
 matician, whose teachings, a singular mixture of astro- 
 logical superstitions and liberal ideas, are stamped as 
 anti-Christian by the orthodoxy of the period; in the 
 learned Swiss physician Theophrastus of Hohenheim, called 
 Paracelsus,^ who shares the belief of Pico, Reuchlin, 
 and Agrippa in the inner light " that is much superior to 
 bestial reason," and their love for the Cabala, whose doc- 
 trines his system identifies with those of Christianity. 
 From the Adam cadmon, who is none other tlian Christ, 
 spring, according to Paracelsus, the soul of the world and 
 the many spirits governed by it, the Sylvans, Undines, 
 Gnomes, and Salamanders , and whoever, through absolute 
 obedience to the divine will, is united with the Adam 
 cadmon and with the heavenly intelligences, is the best 
 physician, and possesses the universal panacea, — the phi- 
 losopher's stone. With a great deal of superstition and a 
 little charlatanism, the precursors of the scientific reforma- 
 tion combine a keen love of nature and a profound aversion 
 to Scholasticism, which their opposition largely assists in 
 overthrowing. 
 
 § 45. Aristotle versus Aristotle, or the Liberal Peripatetics. 
 Stoics. Epicureans. Sceptics 
 
 While Pletho and Bessarion were preaching Plato, Gen- 
 nadius, Georgiusof Trebizond, ainrrheodorus Ciaza, ardent 
 
 1 Of ravia, 1 501-1 .IT'i. Oppra omnia. Lyons, IfiO:]. Cardaiius is 
 reTnemberocI in the history of inathi'iiiaties by liis rule for the sohiliou 
 of equations of the tliird degree (Ars magna sive de regulis nlgehraicix, 
 published 1543, tlie date of the appearance of Copernicus's Celestial 
 Revoluliom). [Cf. Rixner and Sil)f'r, Beilriifje zur Geschichte der Phys- 
 iologie, 7 i.ts., Sulzbadi, 1819-20; 2d cd. 1829 ] 
 
 2 119:5-1511. (9/>em, IJuIe, L-,8!» ; Strasburj^, lOKI ff. [Cf. Sijrwart, 
 Kieine Schriftcn, I., pp. 25 ff. ; Eiicken, Beilriige, etc., pj). 32 if.]
 
 268 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 Peripatetics and adversaries of the Academy of Florence, 
 introduced the learned Italian public to the study of the 
 texts of Aristotle. The better they became acquainted 
 with the words of the great philosopher, the more they 
 recognized the notable differences between the real Aris- 
 totle and the Aristotle of Scholasticism ; and while Plato, 
 Plotinus, and Proclus attracted the more imaginative 
 minds, the positive thinkers, who were no less hostile to 
 traditional philosophy than the Academicians of Florence, 
 appealed from Aristotle misinterpreted to the authentic 
 Aristotle of the Greek texts. As a result, the Stagirite 
 met with a fate similar to that experienced by Hegel 
 about 1835. The system which had been regarded as the 
 strongest support of the Church was found to cUsagree 
 with her on several essential points. A liberal Peripatetic 
 school, chiefly composed of laymen, was formed in oj^posi- 
 tion to official Peripateticism. Although maintaining a 
 prudent reserve towards the Church, these liberal Peripa- 
 tetics assisted in undermining her authoritative system 
 by laying bare, one after another, the heresies of the philo- 
 sopher whom she shielded with blind tenderness. To con- 
 vict an author of heresy whom the Church had declared 
 infallible, was to make the Church fallible ; was to attack 
 her supreme authority in the field of thought ; was to 
 respond to the emancipation of conscience, taking place 
 beyond the mountains, with the emancipation of the 
 intellect. 
 
 In his treatise On the ImmortaUtij of the Soul,^ the 
 leader of the new school,^ Petrus Pompoxatius (Pom- 
 ponazzi^), boldly raises the question whether immortality 
 
 ^ Tractatus ile immortalitate animae, 1516; numerous editions. 
 
 2 Called the school of Padaa, in honor of the city in which Pom- 
 ponatius taught. 
 
 3 Born at Mantua, 1462; died, 1525; professor at Padua. See on 
 Pomponatius : [F. Fiorentino, Pietro Pomponazzi, Florence, 1868] ;
 
 ARISTOTLE VERSUS ARISTOTLE 269 
 
 is a corollary of Aristotle's principles, and, with Alexander 
 of Aphrodisias,^ answers it in the negative. He thereby, 
 on the one hand, ignores the authority of St. Thomas, 
 who had declared that the philosophy of the Stagirite was 
 favorable to this fundamental dogma of religion ; and, on 
 the other, denies the doctrine itself; for both Pomponatius 
 as well as the Church regarded the philosophy of Aristotle, 
 not as a system among other systems, but as the true phi- 
 losophy. Pomponatius, who had to make his peace with 
 Leo X. in order to escape the anathemas of the Church, 
 declares that he personall}' believes in immortality, because 
 he accepts the authority of the Church in matters of 
 religion ; but it is evident from the manner in which he 
 refutes the objections raised against the opposite view that 
 he does not believe in it. 
 
 Say what you will, he writes, it cannot be held that all 
 men achieve intellectual perfection ; while moral perfec- 
 tion does not consist in an ideal that cannot be realized 
 on earth, but in the conscientious performance of the 
 duties imposed upon each individual by his special task. 
 The conscientious and upright magistrate attains the per- 
 fection in his sphere of which he is capable and for which 
 he is destined; the industrious farmer, the merchant, the 
 honest and active artisan, realize, each according to his 
 means, the relative perfection of which nature has fur- 
 nislied them the elements. Absolute perfection belongs to 
 the absolute Being alone. 
 
 The argument which infers tlie immortality of the soul 
 
 Ad. Franck, Mnralistes et pMlosophes, 2tl ed., Paris, 1874 ; [L. Ferri, 
 La psicologia di P. Pomponazze, Rome, 1877]. 
 
 ^ See on the Alexaiidrists and the Averroists, Marsilius Ficinus, 
 Preface to the Translation of Plolhius, Some interjirctcil Aristotle, as 
 did Averrocs, in the pantheistic sense; others as;re('d with Alexander 
 of Aphroilisias, and interiirctcd him in the deistic sense. All rejected 
 individual immortality and miracles.
 
 270 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 from the necessity of an eternal reward of virtue, and an 
 eternal punisliment of crime, is based upon a false, or at 
 least inij^erfect and vulgar, conception of virtue and vice, 
 reward and punishment. Virtue which is exercised merely 
 for the sake of a reward other than itself, is not virtue. 
 This is proved by the fact that everybody regards an act 
 performed in a wholly disinterested manner, and without 
 the hope of some material advantage, as more meritorious 
 than an act performed for an advantage or to satisfy an 
 interest. We must distinguish between the essential re- 
 ward and the accidental remuneration of virtue. The 
 essential recompense, which is inherent in virtue and 
 consequently never lacking, is virtue itself and the insep- 
 arable joy connected with it; and the same may be said 
 of vice, which carries its own punishment with it, even 
 though it is not followed l)y external and accidental pains. 
 It is an incontrovertible fact that men practise righteous- 
 ness for the sake of the reward be3'ond the grave, and that 
 they abstain from crime on account of their fear of hell ; 
 but this 23roves that their moral ideas are still rudimentary, 
 and that they have need of rattles and bugbears where the 
 philosopher acts solely from principle. 
 
 But if the soul is not immortal, all religions are in error, 
 and the whole world is deceived ! Well, does not Plato 
 say that all men are in many respects deluded by the same 
 prejudice ? And does he not therefore hold of little worth 
 arguments based on the conse^isus gentium ? Finally, as 
 regards apparitions of the dead, resurrections, and ghosts : 
 such proofs in favor of a hereafter do not prove anything 
 but the marvellous power of the imagination influenced by 
 faith. If, as Aristotle explicitly teaches, the soul is the 
 function of the body, it is evident that there can be no 
 soul without a body. And what, then, becomes of sorcery 
 and the exorcism of s^jirits ? What becomes of the super- 
 natural ?
 
 ARISTOTLE VERSUS ARISTOTLE 271 
 
 In his treatise On Magic,^ Pomponatius openly avows 
 his disbelief in miracles as the suspension of the natural 
 order of things ; and thoug-h lie admits the miracles of 
 Jesus and Moses in order to mislead the Inquisition, lie 
 explains them naturall}-, that is, he denies them indirectly. 
 And he rejects them, on the authority of the man whom 
 the Church considered as the staunchest supporter of the 
 supernaturalistic Christian, — on the authority of Aristotle. 
 
 Finally, in his treatise On Fate? he dwells, with apj^arent 
 satisfaction, on the contradictions involved in the doctrines 
 of divine prescience and providence, predestination and 
 moral freedom. If God ordains everything in advance, 
 and foresees everything, then we are not free ; if man is 
 free, then God does not foresee his acts, and his knowledge 
 is dependent on his creatures. Aristotle himself, — Pom- 
 ponatius does not dare to say so openly, so great is the 
 authority of the pliilosopher of the Church, — Aristotle 
 contradicts himself on this important question, the solution 
 of which seems to transcend the ca[)acity of human reason. 
 However that may be, determinism has all the logic on its 
 side, and Pomponatius is in sympathy with it. In that case 
 God is the source of evil ! Scholastic nominalism interposes. 
 Our philosopher is forced to admit this; but he consoles 
 himself with the thought that if there were not so much evil 
 in the world, there ivouhl not he so much good in it. 
 
 PoRTA,^ ScALiGER,* Cremonini,^ Zabarella,^ Continue 
 the liberal Peripateticism of Pomponatius during the six- 
 teenth centuiy, and advocate his theory of the soul. They 
 
 ^ De naturalium effecluum adinirandorum causis sire dr. incanlalioni- 
 bus liber, Bale, 1550. 
 
 2 De fato, lihero arhilrio, prcedeslinnlione, proridnilia Dei, Uhri K., 
 Bolof^na, 1520; Ralo, 1525 11". 
 
 8 J )!(•(], 1555. De rerum nalurnlihux prinripiis, FJoiviice, 1551. 
 
 * 11>>1-155S. Exerc. adv. C<trdaiiu»i. 
 
 » 1552-lG:n. Pr(.f('s.s<ir .it Frirara and Pailua. 
 
 • 15:}:5-15S9. Professor at I'a.liia. O/// m, Lry.lni. 15.S7.
 
 272 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 also practise his prudent reserve, as the following motto 
 recomniended by Crenionini shows : Intus ut lihet, forts ut 
 moris est. The Church, however, kept a close watch upon 
 them, and suspected them of atlieism. A product of this 
 school, LuciLio Vanini,^ a restless and extremely vain soul, 
 was burnt by the Inquisition, in spite, or perhaps because 
 of, his declaration " that he would state his opinions con- 
 cerning the immortality of the soul only in case he were 
 old, rich, and a German." These Peripatetics of the left no 
 longer swear by the words of the master like the orthodox 
 Peripatetics. They venerate Aristotle as the highest type 
 of the philosophical mind; but their Peripateticism does 
 not consist in a servile obedience to the letter of his 
 writings, from which they frequently deviate. 
 
 Some, impressed by the similarity between the real 
 teachings of Aristotle and the Platonic and Alexandrine 
 doctrines, approximate the Florentine Academy, though 
 still following the standard of the Lyceum ; while the Pla- 
 tonists, on the other hand, whom a careful study of 
 Aristotle had initiated into the secrets of his metaphysics, 
 consent to a compromise between Platonism and Peripa- 
 teticism. On the Platonic side we have John Pico of 
 Mirandola, whose work on the agreement between Plato 
 and Aristotle remained unfinished ; on the Neo-Peripatetic 
 side, we have Andreas CyESALPiNUS,^ a learned naturalist, 
 who anticipated Harvey's discovery, and created an artificial 
 
 ^ His real name was Pompeio Lucilio Vanini. In his works he 
 calls himself Julius Caesar Vaninus. He was born at Tauresano, near 
 Naples, in 1584, and burnt alive at Toulouse on the 9th of February, 
 1619, after having had his tongue cut off. He left two works : Amphi- 
 theatrum ceternce providenikc, Lyons, 1615, and De cDlmlrandis naturce 
 arcanis, Paris, 1616 (best known by the title Dialogues on Nature, 
 transl. into French by Cousin). 
 
 2 1519-1603. Physician of Clement VIII. Qucestiones peripaletl- 
 cce, Venice, 1571; Dasmonum investigaiio perip., Venice, 1593; compare 
 p. 284.
 
 ARISTOTLE VERSUS ARISTOTLE 273 
 
 system of botany. The universe, according to Gsesalpinus, 
 is a living- unity, a perfect organism. The " first mover " 
 is the innermost substance of the world, — the substance of 
 which the particular tilings are the modes or determina- 
 tions. He is both absolute thought and absolute being. 
 Thouo'h a mode of the divine substance, the human soul is 
 none the less immortal, since its essence, thought, is inde- 
 pendent of the bod}-. 
 
 Still others, like Bernardino Telesto^ of Cosenza 
 (1508-1588), the founder of the Academia Telesiana or 
 Cosentina of Naples, and Francesco Patrizzi^ (1527- 
 1597), who were trained in the humanities as well as in the 
 secret science of Paracelsus and Cardanus, approximate the 
 naturalistic systems of the Ionian school in their cosmologi- 
 cal conceptions. In connection with Telesio, we must 
 mention the illustrious names of Giordano Bruno (§ 49) 
 and Francis Bacon (§ 51), both of whom knew his writings 
 and were influenced b}^ them. 
 
 While the speculative genius of Southern Italy was 
 revealing to the world the real Aristotle, Plato, Parmeni- 
 des, and Empeclocles, the French and Flemish thinkers on 
 the other side of the mountains, took a deeper interest in 
 moral philosophy and positive science than in metaphysical 
 speculation. Pyrrhonism was revived in the Essays^ of 
 Michel de Montaigne (1533-1592) and in the writings 
 
 1 De rerum nalurn juxtn propria principia, lihri IX., Naples, 158G ; 
 [F. Fiorentino, Bernardino Telesio, 2 vols., Florence, 1872-74; L. 
 Ferri, La flosofia della not. e dottrlne di B. Telesio, Turin, 1873; cf. 
 also Rixner and Siher, mentioned p. 267. — Tr.]. 
 
 2 Discussiones peripateticce, Venice, 1571 ff. ; Bale, 1581; Nova de 
 unirersis philosophia, Ferrara, 1491. 
 
 > First edition, Bordeaux, 1580; nioderji edition, with notes of all 
 the commentators, by IM. J. V. Leclerc, and a new study of Montaigne 
 by rr<?vo.st-Paradol, Paris, 1805; [Engl, transl. by .Tolin Florio, with 
 introduction by George Saintsbury, London, 1892; l»y C. Cotton, with 
 life and notes by W. C. Ilazlitt, 3 vols., 2d cd., Louden, 1892. — Tu.] 
 
 18
 
 274 PHiLOSoriiY of the middle ages 
 
 of Pierre CharronI (1541-1603), Sanchez 2 (died at 
 Toulouse, 1632), Lamothe-Levayeu 3 (1586-1672); Sto- 
 icism, by Justus Lipsius* (1547-1606); Epicureanism, 
 by the learned physicist Gassendi,° the opponent of Car- 
 tesian intellectualism, (1596-1655). Although these free- 
 thinkers, with the exception of Gassendi, whose teachings 
 were again taken up by the eighteenth century, do not 
 contribute directly to the reform of philosophy, they at 
 least exert an indirect influence by discrediting the still 
 powerful metaphysics of the School, by exposing the use- 
 lessness of its formuhe and the barrenness of its disputes. 
 Humanists and naturalists, dogmatists and sceptics, Ital- 
 ians and Frenchmen, are united in the common desire 
 for emancipation, reform, and progress. Nature is their 
 watchword ; here, as in Greece, the theological age is 
 followed by the era of the physicists. 
 
 § 46. The Religious Reform ^ 
 
 Ideas enlighten humanity on its onward march, but the 
 will or the instinctive passions impel it onward.^ The 
 
 ^ De la sar/esse, Bordeaux, 1601. 
 
 2 Tractatus de multum nobili et prima universali scientia, quod nihil 
 scitur, Lyons, 1581 ; Tractatus philosophici, Rotterdam, 164S* ; [cf. L. 
 Gerkrath, Francois Sanchez, Vienna, I860]. 
 
 3 Cinq dialogues fails a limitation des anciens, Mons, 1673 ; Works, 
 Paris, 1653. 
 
 * Manuductio ad stoicam philosophiam, etc., Antwerp, 1604. 
 
 ^ De vita, moribus et doctrina Epicuri, Leyden, 1647; Animadversio- 
 nes in Diog. L. de vita et phil. Epic, ibid., 1649; Syntagma phil. Epic, 
 The Hague, 1655; Opera, Leyden, 1658; Florence, 1727; [cf. Lange, 
 History of Materialism, I., 3, chap. 3.] 
 
 ^ [K. Ilagen, Deutschlands Utterarische und religiose Verhliltnisse im 
 Reformationszeiialter, 3 vols., Frankfurt, 1868; M. Carriere, Die Welt- 
 anschauung der Reformationszeit ; W. Dilthey, Auffassting und Analyse 
 des Menschen im 15. u. 16. Jahrhundert, Archiv f Geschichte der Philos., 
 IV. and v.; same author, Das naturliche System der Geisteswissen- 
 schaften im 17. Jahrhundert, ibid., IV. — Tr.] 
 
 ' §4.
 
 THE RELIGIOUS REFORM 275 
 
 Humanists demolished, piece by piece, the system which 
 had been so carefully constructed by the doctors of the 
 Church ; but their excessive prudence or their indifference 
 hindered them from attacking the Church herself, towards 
 whom they affected an attitude of respectful submission. 
 Pomponatius, Sealiger, Erasmus, and ^Montaigne were more 
 liberal than the leaders of the Reformation ; but their lib- 
 eralism is exactly what rendered them indifferent to religion 
 and unfitted them for the grand work of the emancipation 
 of conscience. The Church was so tolerant of pagan an- 
 tiquity, so fond of classical studies I The Popes them- 
 selves were so cultured, so liberal, and so worldly! Yet, 
 the spiritual onuiipotence of Rome formed one of the chief 
 obstacles in the way of philosophical reform, and it took a 
 more powerfid force to shake the colossus than the love of 
 lettei"s or the taste for free thought. Such a force was 
 the religious conscience of Luther and the Reformers. In 
 the name of the inner power tliat controlled them and im- 
 pelled them onward, they attacked, not the philosophical 
 system patronized by the Cluirch, but the Church herself 
 and the principle of her supreme authorit}-. 
 
 As we have seen, the media3val Church is both church 
 and school, the depositary of the means of salvation and 
 the dispenser of profane instruction. As long as the 
 people continued in a state of barbarism, the power which 
 she exercised in this double capacity was beneficent, legiti- 
 mate, and necessary. But after the pupil becomes of age, 
 the l)est of guardians acts as a Ifindrance from which he 
 seeks deliverance. The Renaissance had actually destroyed 
 tlie claim, which the Church advanced, of being the sole 
 and privileged school, but it acknowledged tlie Churcli as 
 tlie liigliest religious and moral autliority. The Reforma- 
 tion liiiishes the work of lh<' lil'tcciith century by emanci- 
 pating the conscience. The sale of indulgences formed 
 the iminetUate occasion for the outbreak. This shameful
 
 276 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 traffic had been legalized by the Catholic system. Since 
 tlie Church is God's representative on earth, whatever 
 she commands agrees with God's own will. Hence if she 
 demands money from the faithful and couples with the 
 contribution the promise of the pardon of sins, the faithful 
 can do nothing but submit to her authority. The proce- 
 dure may perhaps shock the moral sense a little. But 
 what are our individual feelings against the revelation 
 which the Church receives from God? Are God's ways 
 our ways, and is not the divine folly wiser than the wis- 
 dom of men? Was not the revealed truth an offence to 
 the children of the age from the very beginning? . . . 
 Luther's conscience rebelled against such sophistry. By 
 protesting against these scandalous indulgences he revolted 
 against the dogma sanctioning them, and against the spir- 
 itual power which recommended them. For the author- 
 ity of so evil-minded a church he substitutes the supreme 
 authority of Scripture ; against the Catholic principle of 
 meritorious works he opposes the doctrine of justification 
 by faith. 
 
 The principle proclaimed by Luther, and soon after by 
 Zwingli, Calvin, and Farel, quickly penetrated and power- 
 fully influenced all spheres of human action. As soon 
 as it was acknowledg-ed as a truth that salvation comes 
 through faith alone and not by works, the dispensations con- 
 ferred by the Church lost their value. If grace is every- 
 thing and merit nothing, then, it must be confessed, God 
 cannot be thankful to us for renouncing family, society, 
 and the joys and duties of life. Even Luther, who is by 
 no means a lover of philosophy, but who has a very lively 
 . appreciation of nature, really advances the humanitarian 
 and modern cause by repudiating, in principle at least, the 
 dualism of the spiritual and the temporal, of priests and 
 laymen, of heaven and earth. Melancthon, who is both a 
 disciple of the Renaissance and a champion of the Refor-
 
 SCHOLASTICISM AND THEOSOPHY 277 
 
 mation, plainly recognizes the community of interests 
 existing between tlie literary and the religious revival. 
 Tlie two currents ultimately meet in Ulrich Zwingli, ^ who 
 was both an earnest Christian and a profound thinker, 
 and whose theology is an energetic protest against the 
 antithesis of a crodless nature and a God antagonistic to 
 nature. 
 
 8 47. Scholasticism and Theosophy in the Protestant Coun- 
 tries. Jacob Bohme 
 
 Zwingli's progressive tendencies, however, made little 
 headway, during the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, 
 against the doctrinary zeal of the theologians of the North. 
 The authority of the Church and of the Pope was super- 
 seded, among the Protestants, by the symbolism of the 
 Reformation. It was impossible to pass immechately from 
 the rule of authority to absolute freedom. The religious con- 
 science, which had been violently agitated by a sudden re- 
 volution, needed a capable guide in place of the one just lost. 
 Theology, again, could not, in its struggle with Catholicism, 
 do without an external, visible, and standard authority in 
 matters of science and religion. Hence the Reformation 
 produced no immediate change in philosophy. In spite of 
 the efforts of Nicolas Taurellus,^ of Mompelgard (1547- 
 1606) and Pierre de la Ramee or Ramus,'^ (1515-1572), 
 
 1 Works, ed. Schuler and Schulthess, 8 vols., Zurich, 1S2S-42 ; [E. 
 Zeller, Das theolofjische Sijstem Zirincjlis, Tubingen, 1853 ; Dilthey, 
 A. f. G.d. Ph. VI.\ 
 
 2 Philosophice Iruimphus, Bale, 1573; Alpes rccsfe (ai^ainst CcTsalpi- 
 nus), Frankfort, 1507; Sijnnpsis Arist. Metnphy^., Hanover, 1500; De 
 mundo, Aml)erg, 1003 ; Uranolnr/ia, ih., 1603; De rerum ceternitdle, 
 Marburg, 1004. See F. X. Schmidt aus Schwarzenberg, Nicolas 
 Taurelliis, der ersfe deutsche Philosoph, 2d ed., Erlangen, 1864. 
 
 ' Scholarum phijs. libri VflL, Paris, 1505; ScJidI. mctnpJn/s. libri 
 XIV., Paris, 1560. See the monographs of Ch. Waddington (Paris, 
 1848) and Cli. Demaze (Paris, 18G1).
 
 278 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 who bitterly opposed tlie routine methods and the system 
 of Aristotle, as then understood, the Universities continued 
 to teach traditional Peripateticism in the form adapted by 
 Melancthon ^ to the needs of the Protestant dogma. 
 
 The anti-scholastic opposition of Reuchlin, Agrippa, and 
 Paracelsus was continued by the Saxon pastor Valentine 
 WEirxEL,2 (1533-1503), the two Van Helmonts,^ the Eng- 
 lishman Robert Fludd,* (died 1637), who, like a true 
 Protestant, bases his cosmology on Genesis, the learned 
 Comenius,^ (died 1671), whose trinity of matter, light, and 
 spirit calls to mind the three stages of being in Plotinus 
 and the three Peripatetic principles of matter, movement, 
 and action; finally, by Jacob Bohme the theosophist of 
 Gorlitz (1575-1624). 
 
 Bohme ^ was born of poor parents and apprenticed to a 
 shoemaker at an early age. He received absolutely no 
 instruction, and knew only the Bible and the writings of 
 Weigel. But these sufficed to develop the latent capaci- 
 
 1 EiJiicce cloctnnre elementa, 1538. [See Dilfchey, A.f. G. d. Ph. F/.] 
 
 ^ Fvccdi aeavTov, nnxce te ipsum, 1G18, etc. [See the works of J. Opel 
 (Leipsic, 1861), and A. Israel (Zschopau, 1889).] 
 
 3 J. Bapt. Helmont (died 1644). Opera, Amsterdam, 1648; [Germ. 
 ed. 1683]. F. Merc. Helmont (died 1699). Seder olam s. ordo sceculo- 
 rum, hoc est historlca enarratio doctrince philosophicce per unum in quo sunt 
 omnia, 1693. [See Rixner and Siber]. 
 
 * Hixtoria macro- et microcosmi metaphi/sica, pliysica et technica, Op- 
 penlieim, I6I7 ; Pkilos. Mosaica, Giida, 1638. 
 
 ® Synopsis pJu/sices ad lumen divinum refnrmatce, Lei]3sic, 1638. [Cf. 
 J. Kvacsala, Ueber J. A. Comenius Philosophie, Leipsic, 1886.] 
 
 6 [Coll. Works, ed. by Schiebler, 2d ed., 1 861 ff. ; English transl. by 
 William Law, 2 vols. 4°, 1864 ; French transl. of several writings, by 
 L. C. St. Martin, Paris, 1800. Cf. v. Baader, Vorlesunf/en iiber Bohme^s 
 Theologumena (Works, vol. TIL, pp. 357-436; also vol. XIIT.) ; II. A. 
 Fechner, Jacob Bohme, sein Leben und seine ScJiriflen, Gorlitz, 1853 ; 
 A. Peip, Jacob Bohme der deutsche Philosoph, Leipsic, 1860 ; also Car- 
 riere (cited before) and Windelbaud, Geschichte der neueren Philoso- 
 phie, vol. I., § 19 .— Tr.]
 
 SCHOLASTICISM AND THEOSOPHY 279 
 
 ties of this cliild of the people. He divines that the visible 
 things conceal a great mgsteri/, and he experiences a deep 
 desire to unravel it. An earnest Cliiistian, he studies the 
 Scriptures, entreating God to enlighten him with liis Spirit, 
 and to reveal to him what no mortal man can discover 
 tlu'ough his own efforts ; and his prayers are answered. In 
 three successive revelations, God shows him the inner centre 
 of mysterious nature and helps liim to penetrate the inner- 
 most heart of creatures at a single rapid glance. Yielding 
 to the urgent wishes of some of his friends, he decides 
 to record his vision in a treatise called Auo'ora, which pro- 
 cures liim the title, the Go-man philosopher. This book, 
 like liis other works, ^ is written in German, the only 
 language with wliich Bohme was familiar, and for that 
 reason, if for no other, belongs to the modern world. It 
 contains heresies of which the author has not the slightest 
 notion, but which are vigorously condemned by the 
 ecclesiastical authorities of Giirlitz and cause him to be 
 placed under strict surveillance for the rest of his days. 
 
 Indeed, from the Preface on, the sincerest orthodoxy is 
 mingled with the most advanced conceptions of ancient 
 and modern speculation. If you desire to be a philosopher 
 and to fathom the nature of God and the nature of things, 
 first pray to God for the Holy Ghost, who is in God and in 
 nature. Aided by the Holy Spirit, you can penetrate even 
 into the hody of God, who is nature^ and into the essence of 
 the holy Trinity : for the Divine Spirit dwells in the whole 
 of nature as the human spirit dwells in the body of man. 
 
 Enlightened by this Spirit, what does Bdlime find at the 
 
 * Von (Jen drei Principifn rles goltUchen Wexe.na ; Vom dreifachen Lehen 
 (les Mnnschen ; Von der Menschicerdung Jesii Christi ; Vom irdischen und 
 hhnmUsrhf'.n Myxlerinm: Von wahrer Busse : Van der Wieflerc/ehurt ; Von 
 der Gnadenwahl , ]\fi/stn-iiim wnginim, cto. (all in Cormaii). Editions 
 of Amstorduiii (1075, ins2, 17:^0) aiul Lcijisic (1S:',1 ff., 7 vols.). 
 
 ■^ Aurnni, cliap. ii. 12; X. 50, und j)assi7n.
 
 280 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 very source of tilings ? A constant duality, which he calls 
 o-entleness and sternness, sweetness and bitterness, good 
 and evil. Everything that lives contains these contraries. 
 Indifferent things, — things, that is, neither sweet nor bitter, 
 neither warm nor cold, neitlier good nor bad, — are dead. 
 Bohme sees this conflict, this struggle between two opposing 
 principles, which become reconciled in death, in all beings, 
 without exception, — in terrestrial beings, in angels, and in 
 God,i who constitutes the essence of all beings.'^ God with- 
 out the Son is a ivill that desires nothing because it is 
 everything and has everything, — a will without a motive, a 
 love without an object, a powerless power, an unsubstantial 
 shadow, a blind essence witliout intelligence and without 
 life, a centre without a circumference, a light without bright- 
 ness, a sun without rays, a night without stars, a chaos with- 
 out light, color, or form : a bottondess abyss, eternal death, 
 nothingness. God the Father and the Son is the living God, 
 the absolute or concrete spirit, the perfect being. The Son 
 is the self-centred infinity, the heart of the Father; the torch 
 that illuminates the boundlessness of the Divine Being, as 
 the sun sheds its light into the immeasurable space ; the 
 eternal circle which God describes around himself ; the hody 
 of God, having the stars as its organs, and their orbits as its 
 eternally-throbbing arteries ; the totality of the forms con- 
 tained in heaven and earth; the mysterious nature that 
 lives, and feels, and suffers, and dies, and is again revived 
 in us. But the opposition which constitutes the essence of 
 God and of all beings is not the primordial being : it comes 
 from Unity ; the Son comes from the Father and is a sec- 
 
 1 Id., chap. ii. 40. 
 
 2 Aurora, Pref., 97; 105: Gott, in dcm Alles ist und der seJber AUes 
 ist; chap. i. 6 : Golt ist der Quellbrunn oder das Herz der Natur : iii. 12 : 
 Er ist von Nichts hergekommen, sondern ist selber AUes in Eioigkeit ; 
 iii. 14 : Der Vater ist Alles und alle Kraft besteht in ihm ; vii. 20 : Seine 
 Krnft ist Alles und allenthalben : vii. 25: Des Voters Kraft ist AUes in 
 und liber alien Hhnmeln ; and passiin.
 
 THE SCIENTIFIC MOVEMENT 281 
 
 ondaiy being. First nature, then mind ; first will without 
 an object or self-eonsciousness (^der uiigrundlichc Wille)^ 
 then conscious W\\\ {der fassliche Wille^). 
 
 Although we may without difficulty extract the charac- 
 teristic conceptions of concrete spiritualism from these 
 metaphors, they assume a purely theological form in 
 Bohme. This pioneer of German philosophy is a seer, a 
 prophet who does not seem to understand himself, so im- 
 bued is he with the traditional view of things. Thought 
 has simply changed masters in the Protestant world ; it is 
 what it was before, a servant, ancilla theologicc. It owes 
 its final deliverance to the discoveries of Columbus, 
 Magellan, Copernicus, Kepler, and Galileo, who refute the 
 accepted notions concerning the earth, the sun, and the 
 heavens, and thereby destroy the prejudice which makes 
 the Scripture what it neither is nor claims to be : an 
 infallible text-book of physical science. 
 
 8 48. The Scientific Movement 2 
 
 From the middle of the fifteenth century on. Western 
 Europe experienced a series of surprises. Led by the Greek 
 scholars who settled in Italy, she entered directly into the 
 promised land, which the Arabians of Spain had in part 
 revealed to her : I mean, antiquity with its literature, phi- 
 losophy, and art. The historical horizon of our fathers, 
 which originally bounded tlie Catholic era, grows larger 
 and extends far beyond the beginnings of Christianity. 
 The Catholic Church, outside of which nothing but dark- 
 ness and T^arbarism seemed to prevail, Avas now regarded 
 
 1 M)ixterlnm mngnum, chap. vi. ; Von ikr Gnadenwahl, chap. i. ; Au- 
 rora, chaps, viii.-xi. 
 
 2 See the works of Montucla, Dclambre, Chaslos, Draper, etc., 
 quoted on p. 159; IIumboMt, Cosmos, vols. T. and IT.; K. Fischer, 
 Introduction to the History of Modern Philosophy, vol. T., 1 ; [Peschel, 
 Geschickte des Zeilallers der Enidicknngen. — Tit.].
 
 282 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 simply as the daughter and heir of an older, richer, more 
 diversified civilization, of a civilization more in accord 
 with the genius of the Western races. The Romance 
 and Germanic nations of Europe feel closely akin to these 
 Greeks and Romans whom the Church excluded from her 
 pale, but who were, in so many respects, superior to the 
 Christians of the fifteenth century in all the spheres of 
 human activity. The Catholic prejudice, according to 
 which there can be neither salvation nor real civilization 
 nor religion nor morality beyond the confines of the 
 Church, gradually disappears. Men cease to be ex- 
 clusive Catholics and become m^n, humanists, and phil- 
 anthropists in the broadest sense of the term. Not merely 
 a few stray glimpses of the past, but the whole history of 
 Aryan Europe with its countless political, literary, philo- 
 logical, arclueological, and geographical problems are un- 
 rolled before the astonished gaze of our ancestors. 
 Henceforth the historical sciences, which received but 
 little attention during antiquity, and were almost unknown 
 to the Middle Ages, constituted an important branch of 
 study, and finally occupied the centre of interest. 
 
 Scarcely had man discovered humanity when he was 
 made acquainted with the real form of his earthly habita- 
 tion, of which he had hitherto seen but one of the fa^'ades. 
 The Catholic universe consisted of the world known to 
 the Romans, i. e., of the Mediterranean valley and the 
 Southwestern part of Asia, with Northern Europe added. 
 But now Columbus discovers the New World. Vasco De 
 Gama sails around the Cape of Good Hope and finds the 
 sea-route to India ; above all, Magellan succeeds in making 
 the tour of the earth. These discoveries verify an hypo- 
 thesis with which the ancients had long been familiar, — 
 the hypothesis that our earth is a globe, isolated and sus- 
 pended in space. Wliat could be more natural than to 
 infer that the stars too float in space without being attached
 
 THE SCIENTIFIC MOVEMENT 283 
 
 to anything, and that the s^jheres of Aristotle are mere 
 illusions ? 
 
 The earth is now conceived as a globe, but everybody 
 still regards it as the immovable centre around which the 
 heavenly spheres revolve. Tycho Biiahe directs the first 
 attack against the traditional and popular cosmography by 
 placing the sun in the centre of the planetary system ; but 
 he still believes that this solar system revolves around the 
 earth. Copernicus ^ takes the decisive step by placing 
 the earth among the planets and the sun in the centre of 
 the system. Tins theory, which had already been advanced 
 by several of the ancients,^ and which Copernicus presents 
 merely as an liypothesis, is confirmed by the splendid labors 
 of Keplei;,^ who discovers the form of the planetary orbits 
 and the laws of their motion ; and of Galileo,* who teaches 
 that the earth has a double motion, and, with a telescope 
 of his own construction, discovers the satellites of Jupiter 
 and the law of their revolution. 
 
 The heliocentric theory arouses great alarm in both 
 Churches. Kepler is persecuted; Galileo is forced to 
 retract. The stubborn conservatives maintain that the 
 accex)tance of the Copernican system would destroy the 
 very foundations of Christianity. If the sun is the centre 
 of the planetary orbits, if the earth moves, then, so they 
 hold, Joshua did not perform his miracle, then the Bible 
 is in error, and the Church fallible. If the earth is a 
 planet, then it moves in heaven, and is no longer the anti- 
 thesis of heaven; then heaven and earth are no longer 
 
 1 De orhium coelestlum revolutionibus lihri VI., Nuremberg, 1543. 
 
 2 8 22. 
 
 ^ Aslronomia nova, Prague, 1009, etc.; Complete Works, ed. by 
 Friscli, Frankfurt, 185S if. [Cf. Sigwart, Klelne Srhriflen, I. \)p 182- 
 220; Kucken, Britriige znr Geschichle der neuern I'liiJoso/ihii'.'] 
 
 * Complete Works, o<l. Alberti, Florence, 184:i fl'. |C'f. Natorp, 
 Galilei ah Pfiilosopk, Philos. Momilshrfic, 1882, pp. 193 ff.]
 
 284 PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE AGES 
 
 opposed, as tradition assumed, but form one indivisible uni- 
 verse. Moreover, to affirm, in defiance of Aristotle, that 
 the world is infinite, is to deny the existence of a heaven 
 apart from the universe, of a supernatural order of things, 
 of a God on high. That is the way the Church reasoned ; 
 she identified faith with doctrines of faith, God with our 
 ideas of God, and stamped the adherents of Cojjernicus as 
 atheists. 
 
 But in spite of the efforts of the Church, the new the- 
 ories spread, tlie discoveries and inventions multiplied. 
 First came the invention of printing, then the compass, 
 and then the telescope. Before Newton completed the 
 new cosmology by his theory of universal attraction, and 
 transformed what, until then, had been a mere Ixypothesis 
 into an axiom, the sciences had shaken off the yoke of 
 Scholasticism, and slowly but surely advanced. Leonardo 
 DA Vlnci and his fellow-countryman Fracastor continue 
 the labors of Arcliimedes and the scholars of Alexandria in 
 physics, optics, and mechanics. The Frenchman Viete 
 extends the limits of algebra and applies it to geometry ; 
 and the Englishman Neper (Lord John Napier) invents 
 the logarithms. In biology, the Belgian Vesale, by his 
 De corporis humarii fahrica (1553), lays the foundation of 
 the science of human anatomy ; and the Englishman Har- 
 vey, in a work published 1628,^ proves the theory of the 
 circulation of the blood, i:)reviously advanced by the Span- 
 iard Michel Servet,^ and the Italians Realdo Colombo ^ 
 and Andi'eas Csesalpinus.'* 
 
 Of all the modern discoveries, the Copernican theory 
 
 ^ De motu cordis et sanguinis, Frankfurt, 1(328, 
 
 2 Pulmonary circulation is taught in a passage of the Christianismi 
 restitutio, begun as early as 1546. 
 
 8 1494-1559 ; Vesale's successor at Padua (1544), and the author 
 of De re anatomica (1558). 
 
 * 111 his Qucestiones mediccc, 1598.
 
 THE SCIENTIFIC MOVEMENT 285 
 
 proved to be the most influential. The appearance of the 
 Celestial Revolutions is the most important event, the great- 
 est epochs in the intellectual history of Europe. It marks 
 the beginning of the modern world. By revealing to us 
 the infinite^ wliich antiquity conceived as a mere negation, 
 it did not, indeed, shake our faith in things invisible, — 
 nay, it revived and strengthened the same, — but it seri- 
 ously moditied our ideas concerning their relation to the 
 world. For transcendentalism, the ruling notion of the 
 Middle Ages, it definitively substituted the modern j^rin- 
 ciple of divine immanency} 
 
 This conception had as its necessary consequence the 
 philosopliical reform, which was inaugurated by the free- 
 tliinkers of the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries and 
 continued, about the year IGOO, by a number of bold 
 innovators (Bruno in Italy, Bacon in England, Descartes 
 in France). 
 
 ^ Hegel (p. c), who recognizes in immanency the ruling thought of 
 the modern world, though dating it from the Lutheran Reformation, 
 characterizes the transition from the Middle Ages to our own epoch 
 as follows : " It seemed to mankind as though God had just created 
 sun, moon, stars, plants, and animals ; as if the laws of nature had 
 just been established. Now, for the first time, they became interested 
 in all these things, recognizing their own reason in the universal rea- 
 son. "War was declared, in the name of the natural laws, against the 
 great superstition of the period, and against the prevailing notions 
 regarding the formidable and remote powers, which, as was thought, 
 could not be overcome except by magic. h\ the battle which ensued, 
 Catholics and Protestants fought side by side."
 
 Ill 
 
 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 FIRST PERIOD 
 
 THE AGE OF INDEPENDENT METAPHYSICS 
 (FROM BRUNO TO LOCKE AND KANT) 
 
 § 49. Giordano Bruno 
 
 Giordano Bruno ^ was born at Nola, near Naples, in 
 1548. While still a young man, he entered the Doniini- 
 
 1 [For references, see especially pp. 12-15. — Tr.] 
 
 2 The Italian writings edited by A. Wagner, 2 vols., Leipsic, 1829 ; 
 [new edition by P. de Lagarde, 2 vols., Gbttingen, 1888-89] ; Latin 
 writings ed. by A. F. Gfrorer, Stuttgart, 1834, incomplete; [also by 
 Fiorentino and others, 4 vols., Naples, 1880, 188G; Florence, 1889; 
 W. Lntoslawski, Jordani Bruni Nolani 0pp. iiiedita manu propina scrlpta, 
 Archiv f. Geschichte der Philos., II., .S26-.371, 394-417 ; F. Tocco, Le 
 opere inedite di G. B., Naples, 1891. — Tr.]. See Christian Barthol- 
 mess, Jordano Bruno, 2 vols., Paris, 1848-47 ; [R. Mariano, G. B., la 
 vita et ruomo, Rome, 1881]; H. Brunnhofer, G. B.'s Weltanschauung 
 und Verharigniss, Leipsic, 1882 ; [J. Frith, Life of G. B., the Nolati, 
 revised by M. Carriere, London, 1887 ; Sigwart, Kleine Schriften, I., 
 pp. 49 ff. — Tr.]. M. Felice Tocco has published : Le opere latine di 
 G. B. esposte e confrontate con le italiane, Florence, 1889, and Le opere 
 inedite di G. B. M. Tocco distinguishes three phases in the philo- 
 sophical development of Bruno : a Neo-Platonic, an Eleatic and Ilera- 
 clitean, and a Democritean phase. With the head of the materialistic 
 school, Bruno advances the notion of an infinite number of worlds 
 and the theory of atoms, which, from his animistic point of view, 
 become monads. Bartholmess lays especial stress on the first of these 
 phases ; Brunnhofer, on the second ; but neither interpretation ex- 
 hausts Bruno's thought.
 
 GIORDANO BRUNO 287 
 
 can order, but the influence exercised upon liim by the 
 writings of Nicohis Cusanus, Raymond Lullus, Telesio, 
 and his profound love of nature, soon tmiied him against 
 the monastic life and Catholicism. He visited Geneva, 
 where he met with bitter cUsappointments, Paris, London, 
 and Germany, journeying from Wittenberg to Piague, from 
 Helmstaedt to Frankfort. But Protestantism proved no 
 more satisfactory to him than the religion of his fathers. 
 Upon liis return to Italy he was arrested at Venice by order 
 of the Inquisition, imprisoned for two years, and then burnt 
 at the stake in Rome (IGOO). His adventurous life did not 
 hinder him from writing numerous treatises, the most 
 remarkable of which are the following : Delia causa, prin- 
 cipio ed uno ^ (Venice, 1584) ; Del infinito universo e del 
 mondi^ {id., 1584); De tripUei miiiimo et mens ur a (Fiwnli- 
 f ort, 1591) ; De moiiade, numero et figura {id., 1591) ; De 
 immenso et 4miumerahilibics s. de universo et mundis ^ {id. 
 1591). 
 
 Bruno was the first metaphysician of the sixteenth cen- 
 tury who um-eservedly accepted the heliocentric system. 
 Aristotle's spheres and divisions of the world he regarded 
 as purely imaginary. Space, he held, has no such limits, 
 no insurmountable barriers separating our world from an 
 extra-mundane region reserved for pure spirits, angels, 
 and the supreme Being. Heaven is the infinite universe.* 
 The fixed stars are so many suns, surrounded by planets, 
 which, in turn, are accompanied by satellites. The earth 
 is a mere planet, and does not occupy a central and 
 privileged place in the heavens. The same may be said 
 of our sun, for the universe is a system of solar systems. 
 
 1 [rifrnian transl. by A. Lasson in Kircliinann's PhUnanphinrhe Bib- 
 liothfiL; 2(\ ed. 1889. — Tu.] 
 
 2 (■florman transl. })y L. Kuhlciibock, Berlin, 1S93. — Tr.] 
 8 r/^/.. 1800. — Tr.] 
 
 * D'^ bniiif'ii.to ft !rt)i7imeriihl/iljiis, ]^. 1.50.
 
 288 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 If the universe is infinite, we must necessarily reason 
 as follows : There cannot be two infinities ; now the exists 
 ence of the world cannot be denied ; hence God and the 
 universe are but one and the same being. In order to 
 escape the charge of atheism, Bruno distinguishes between 
 the universe and the world: God, the infinite Being, or 
 the Universe, is the principle or the eternal cause of the 
 world : natura naturans ; the world is the totality of his 
 effects or phenomena : natura naturata. It would, he 
 tliinks, be atheism to identify God with the world, for the 
 world is merely the sum of individual beings, and a sum is 
 not a being, but a mere plu'ase. But to identify God with 
 the universe is not to deny him ; on the contrary, it is to 
 magnify liim; it is to extend the idea of the supreme 
 Being far beyond the limits assigned to him by those who 
 conceive him as a being hy the side of other beings, i. e., as a 
 finite being. Hence Bruno loved to call himself Fhilotheos,'^ 
 in order to distinguish clearly between his conception and 
 atheism. This proved to be a useless precaution, and did 
 not succeed in misleading his judges. 
 
 As a matter of fact, the God of Bruno is neither the 
 creator nor even the first mover, but the soul of the world ; 
 he is not the transcendent and temporary cause, but, as 
 Spinoza would say, the immanent cause, i. e., the inner and 
 permanent cause of things ; he is both the material and 
 formal principle which produces, organizes, and governs 
 them from within outwardly : in a word, their eternal sub- 
 stance. The beings which Bruno distinguishes by tlie 
 words " universe " and " world," natura naturans and 
 natura naturata, really constitute but one and the same 
 thing, considered sometimes from the realistic standpoint 
 (in the mediaeval sense), sometimes from the nominalistic 
 standpoint.2 The universe, which contains and produces 
 
 ^ Philotheus Jordanux Brxmus Nolanus de compendiom architectura et 
 compkmento artis Lullii, Paris, 1582. 
 2 Delia causa, 72 ff.
 
 GIORDANO BEUNO 289 
 
 all things, has neither beginning nor end ; the world (that 
 is, the beings which it contains and produces) has a begin- 
 nino- and an end. The conception of nature and of neces- 
 sary production takes the place of the notion of a creator 
 and free creation. Freedom and necessity are synonymous ; 
 beino-, power, and will constitute in God but one and the 
 same indivisible act.^ 
 
 The creation of the world does not in any way modify 
 the God-universe, the eternally-identical, immutable, in- 
 commensurable, and incomparable Being. By unfolcUng 
 himself, the infinite Being produces a countless number 
 of genera, species, and individuals, and an infinite variety 
 of cosmical laws and relations (which constitute the life of 
 the universe and the phenomenal world), without himself 
 becoming a genus, species, individual, or substance, or 
 £ubjecting himself to any law, or entering into any rela- 
 tions. He is an absolute and intUvisible unity, having 
 nothing in common with numerical unity; he is in all 
 things, and all things are in liim. In him every existing 
 tiling lives, moves, and has its being. He is present in 
 the blade of grass, in the grain of sand, in the atom that 
 floats in the sunbeam, as well as in the boundless All, — 
 that is, he is omnipresent, because he is indivisible. The 
 substantial and natural omnipresence of the infinite Being 
 both explains and destroys the dogma of his supernatural 
 presence in the consecrated host, which the ex-Dominican 
 regards as the corner-stone of Christianity. Because of 
 this real all-presence of the infinite One, eveiything in 
 nature is alive ; nothing can be destroyed ; death itself is 
 but a transformation of life. The merit of the Stoics con- 
 sists in their having recognized the world as a living 
 being; that of the Pythagoreans, in having recognized the 
 mathematical necessity and immutability of the laws gov 
 eming eternal creation.^ 
 
 * De immenso el inuvrnfrahilibux, I., 11. ' Id., A HI-, 10 
 
 I»
 
 290 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Bruno sometimes calls the Infinite, the Universe, or God, 
 matter. Matter is not the (j^t) 6v of Greek idealism and 
 the Schoolmen. It is inextended, i. e., immaterial in its 
 essence, and does not receive its being from a positive 
 principle outside of itself (the form) ; it is, on the contrary, 
 the real source of all forms ; it contains them all in germ, 
 and produces them in succession. What was fir-st a seed 
 becomes a stalk, then an ear of corn, then bread, then 
 chyle, then blood, then animal semen, then an embryo, 
 then a man, then a corpse, and then returns to earth or 
 stone or some other material, only to pass tlu'ough the 
 same stages again. Thus we have here something that is 
 changed into all tilings, and yet remains substantially the 
 same., Hence, matter alone seems to be stable and eternal, 
 and deserves to be called a principle. Being absolute, it 
 includes all forms and all dimensions, and evolves out of 
 itself the infinite variety of forms in which it appears. 
 When we say a thing dies, w^e mean that a new thing has 
 been produced ; the dissolution of a combination means the 
 formation of a new one. 
 
 The human soul is the highest evolution of cosmical life. 
 It springs from the substance of all things through the 
 action of the same force that produces an ear from a grain 
 of wheat. All beings whatsoever are both body and soul : 
 all are living monads, reproducing, in a particular form, 
 the Monad of monads, or the God-universe. Corporeality 
 is the effect of an outward movement or the expansive 
 force of the monad; in thought the movement of the 
 monad returns upon itself. Tliis double movement of 
 expansion and concentration constitutes the life of the 
 monad. The latter lasts as long as the backward and for- 
 ward motion producing it, and dies as soon as this ceases ; 
 but it disappears only to arise again, in a new form, soon 
 after. The evolution of the living being may be described 
 as the expansion of a vital centre ; life, as the duration of
 
 TOMJVLA.SO CAMPANELLA 291 
 
 the sphere ; death, as the contraction of the sphere and its 
 return to the vital centre whence it sprang.^ 
 
 All these conceptions, especially the evolutionism of 
 Bruno, we shall meet again in the systems of Leibniz, 
 Bonnet, Diderot, and Hegel, which his philosophy contains 
 in germ and in the undifferentiated state, as it were. As 
 the synthesis of monism and atomism, idealism and ma- 
 terialism, speculation and observation, it is the common 
 soui'ce of modern ontological doctrines. 
 
 § 50. Tommaso Campanella 
 
 Another Southern Italian and Dominican, ToiviiviAso 
 Cajvipanella,2 anticipated the English and German essays 
 concerning human miderstanding, i. e., modern criticism. 
 Tliis doughty champion of philosophical reform and Italian 
 liberty was born near Stilo in Calabria, 1568, and died at 
 Paris, 1639, after spending twenty-seven years in a Nea- 
 politan dungeon on the charge of having consjjired against 
 the Spanish rule. 
 
 Campanella is a disciple of the Greek sceptics. This 
 school taught him that metaphysics is built on sand unless 
 it rests on a theory of knowledge. His philosophy conse- 
 quently first discusses the formal question.^ 
 
 Our knowledge springs from two sources : sensible ex- 
 perience and reasoning ; it is empirical or speculative. 
 
 ^ De iriplici minimo, pp. 10-17. 
 
 ^ Ope)-e di Tommaso Campanella ed. by A. d'Aiicoiia, Turin, ISol 
 {Campnnellce Philosophia sen.iibus demonstrata, Napli's, 15!iO; Philos. 
 rationnlis e( realis paries V., Paris, 1G38; Uniceisalis philosopJiue sire 
 metaphysicarum rerum juxta propria dogmata })atirs Iff., id., l(i;58; 
 Atheismus triumphalus. Koine, 1^31 ; De gentilismo nan retincndo, Paris, 
 1830, etc.) ; [Cf. Baldaciiini, Vita e JHosofn di T. C, Naples, 1840-43; 
 Sigwart, Kleine Schri/ten, I., pp. 125 ff. — Tn.] 
 
 ' For Cainpanella's theory of knowledge, see especially the Inti-o- 
 duclion to his Universal f^hilosoplnj or Metapliysics.
 
 292 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Is the knowledge acquired by sensation certain? Most 
 of the ancients are of the opinion that tlie testimony of the 
 senses must be ignored, and the sceptics sum up their 
 doubts in the following argument : The object perceived 
 by the senses is nothing bvit a modification of the subject, 
 and the facts which, the senses tell us, are taking place 
 outside of us, are in reality merely taking place in us. 
 The senses are my senses ; they are a part of myself ; sen- 
 sation is a fact produced in me, a fact which I explain by 
 an external cause ; whereas the thinking subject might be 
 its determining but unconscious cause as easily as any 
 object. In that event, how can we reach a certain knowl- 
 edofe of the existence and nature of external thing's? If 
 the object which I perceive is merely my sensation, how can 
 I prove that it exists outside of me ? By the inner sense, 
 Campanella answers. Sense-perception must derive the 
 character of certitude, which it does not possess in itself, 
 from reason ; reason transforms it into knowledge. Though 
 the metaphysician may doubt the veracity of the senses, he 
 cannot suspect the inner sense. Now, the latter reveals 
 to me my existence immediately, and in such a way as to 
 exclude even the shadow of a doubt ; it reveals me to 
 myself as a being that exists, and acts, and knows, and 
 wills ; as a being, furthermore, that is far from doing and 
 knowing everything. In other words, the inner sense 
 reveals to me both my existence and its limitations. Hence 
 I necessarily conclude that there is a being that limits me, 
 an objective world different from myself, or a non-ego ; and 
 thus I demonstrate by the a posteriori method a truth that 
 is instinctive, or a priori, or prior to all reflection: the 
 existence of the non-ego is the cause of the sensible per- 
 ception in me.i 
 
 Does this argument refute scepticism ? To tell the 
 truth, it only half refutes it, and our jihilosopher has no 
 
 ^ Unwersalis pliilos. sive metaphys., Part I., 1, c. 3.
 
 TOMMASO CAMPANELLA 293 
 
 thought of claiming the victory. Indeed, it does not neces- 
 sarily follow that because the senses are veridical in show- 
 ing us objects, they show us the latter as they are. The 
 agreement which, dogmatism assumes, exists between our 
 mode of conceiving things and their mode of being, is, 
 accorcUng to Campanella, a consequence of the analogy of 
 beings, and tliis, in turn, is the consequence of an indemon- 
 strable truth : their unitary origin. Besides, he will not 
 grant that the human mind has an absolute knowledge of 
 things. Our knowledge may be correct without ever being- 
 complete. Compared with God's knowledge, our knowledge 
 is insignificant and as nothing. We should know things 
 as they are, if knowledge were a pure act (if to perceive 
 were to create). In order to know the things in them- 
 selves, or absolutely, we sliould have to be the absolute 
 as such, i. e., the Creator himself. But though absolute 
 knowledge is an ideal which man cannot realize, — an evi- 
 dent proof that this world is not his real home, — the 
 thinker ought to engage in metaphysical research. 
 
 Considering its subject-matter, universal philosophy or 
 metaphysics is the science of the principles or fii'st condi- 
 tions of existence {principia, proprincipia, prwialitates 
 essendi). Considering its sources, means, and methods, it 
 is the science of reason, and more certain and authoritative 
 than experimental science. 
 
 To exist means to proceed from a principle and to re- 
 turn to it.^ What is the j)rinciple, or rather, what are 
 these principles? for an abstract unity is barren. In other 
 words: Wliat is essential to a being's existence? An- 
 swer: (1) That this being Z>e a 5/c to exist. (2) That tlici-e 
 be in natuic an Idea of wliicli this being is tlic realization 
 (for without knowledge nature would never })roduce any- 
 thing). (•') 'ilial llicn; be a tcndcncij^^ or desire for realiz- 
 
 * Univ. phil. sire me.tnphys., P. T., 2, c. 1. 
 
 2 By thus categorically affiniiiiig the will as tho principium essendi,
 
 294 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 ingit. Power (]>osse, potcstas^ pote7itia essendi), knowledge 
 (cognoscere, sapicntia)^ and will {telle, amor essendi), — such 
 are the principles of relative being. The sum of these 
 principles, or rather, the su^jreme unity ^^4iich contains 
 them, is God. God is absolute power, absolute knowl- 
 edge, and absolute will or love. The created beings, too, 
 have power, perception, and will, corresponding to their 
 propinquity to the source of things. The universe is a 
 hierarchy comprising the mental, angelic, or metaphysical 
 world (angels, dominations, world-soul, immortal souls), 
 the eternal or mathematical world, and the temporal or 
 corporeal world. All these worlds, even the corporeal 
 world itself, participate in the absolute, and reproduce its 
 three essential elements : power, knowledge, and will. So 
 true is this that even inert nature is not dead ; nay, feel- 
 ing, intelligence, and will exist, in different degrees, in all 
 beings, not even excepting inorganic matter.^ 
 
 Ever}^ being proceeds from the absolute Being, and 
 strives to return thither as to its principle. In this sense 
 all finite beings whatsoever love God, all are religious, all 
 strive to live the infinite life of the Creator, all have a 
 horror of non-being, and in so far as all bear within them- 
 selves non-being as well as being, all love God more than 
 themselves. Religion is a universal phenomenon and has 
 its source in the dependence of all things on the absolute 
 Being. Religious science or theology is so much higher 
 than philosophy, as God is greater than man.'^ 
 
 In spite of these concessions to Catholicism, in spite of 
 his Atlieisvius iriumphatus, and his cbeam of a universal 
 monarchy for the Holy Father, Campanella's attempted 
 
 Campanella differs both from the materialists and the pure idealists. 
 No one before Leibniz more clearly conceived the fundamental cou- 
 ception of concrete spiritualism. 
 
 1 Univ. phil, P. I., 2, c. 5 f£. 
 
 2 Id.. lU., 16, 1-7.
 
 TRAXCIS BACON 295 
 
 reforms were suspected by the Church, and miscarried. 
 Philosophy could not hope to make any advance in Italy ; 
 henceforth she takes up her abode in countries enlightened 
 or emancipated by the religious reformation : in England 
 and on both banks of the Rhine.^ 
 
 § 51. Francis Bacon 
 
 In England the philosophical reform receives the impress 
 of the Anglo-Saxon character, and takes quite a different 
 turn from the Italian movement. The sober and positive 
 Eupflish mind distrusts the traditions of Scholasticism as 
 well as the hasty deductions of independent metaphysics. 
 It prefers the slow and gradual ascent along the path of 
 experience to Italian speculation, which quickly reaches 
 the summit, and then, unable to maintain itself, becomes 
 discouraged and falls back into scepticism. It is impressed 
 with the fact that the School and its methods had no share 
 in the recent progress of the sciences ; that these intellec- 
 tual conquests were made outside of the School, nay, in 
 spite of it. The sciences owe their success neither to 
 Aristotle nor to any other traditional authority, but to the 
 direct contemplation of nature and the immediate influence 
 of common-sense and reality. True, the bold investiga- 
 tors of science reasoned no less skilfully than the logi- 
 cians of the School, l»ut their reasonings were based on the 
 
 1 The most di.-itiiiguislied among the Italian philosophers of the 
 seventeenth and eighteenth centuries is Giovanni Battista Yico, who 
 died in 1741. He is noted foi' his Scienza nunva (Naples, 17'25), one 
 of the first attempts a^ a pjiilosophy of history. The attempt lias 
 Ijecn made by able modern thinkers like (Jalhipi, Rosmini, Giol)erti, 
 Mamiani, Ferrari, etc. (>j 71), to restore to Italy the pliilosopliical 
 prestige enjoyed by that country during the period of the Renaissance 
 (see Rajihael Mariano, La philosophie contemporaine en Italie, Paris, 
 1808). [On Vico see l^rofessor Flint's book in Blackwood's Phil. 
 Classics. — Ti!.]
 
 296 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 observation of facts. Conversely, when they started from 
 an a jri'iori conception, or hypothesis, they verified it by 
 experience, as Columbus did, and refused to recognize its 
 truth until it had received this indispensable sanction. 
 Thus we have, on the one hand, an utterly powerless and 
 barren official philosophy ; on the other, a surprising ad- 
 vance in the positive sciences. The conclusion which 
 forced itself upon English common-sense was the necessity 
 of abandoning a priori speculation and the abused syllo- 
 gism in favor of observation and induction. 
 
 This conviction, wdiich had been expressed by Roger 
 Bacon as early as the tliirteenth century, is proclaimed in 
 the writings of his namesake FiiAXCis Bacox, Baron of 
 Verulam, Lord Chancellor of England (1561-162G): De 
 dicjnitate et augmentis scientiarum ;'^ Novum organum scien- 
 tiarum^ etc.^ 
 
 ^ Appeared in English, 1605. 
 
 2 First published nnder the title Cogitata et visa in 1612. 
 
 3 Complete Works, [ed. William Rawley, Amsterdam, 1663] ; ed. 
 Montague, London, 1825-34; H. G. Bohn-, London, 1846; ed. Ellis, 
 Spedding, and Heath, London, 1857-50, completed by J. Spedding; 
 The Letters and Life of Francis Bacon, including all his occasional 
 works, newly collected, revised, and set out in chronological order, tciih a 
 commentary biographical and historical, London, 1862-72; [also a briefer 
 Account of the Life and Times of Francis Bacon, by J. Spedding, 
 2 vols., London, 1879] ; Bacon's works, tr. into French by Lasalle, 
 15 vols., 8vo, Paris, 1800-1803; and by Riaux (CEuvres philosophiques 
 de F. Bacon, in the Charpentier collection, 2 vols., 12mo, 1812). See 
 Ch. de Remusat, Bacoji, sa vie, son temps, sa philosophic et son influence 
 jiisqu'a 710S jours, 2d ed., Paris, 1858 ; Kuno Fischer, Fra7icis Bacon 
 und seine Nachfolger. Entivickelungsgeschichte der Erfahrungsphiloso- 
 phie, Leipsic, 1856 ; 2d ed., completely revised, 1875 ; [Engl, trans, by 
 J. Oxenford, London, 1857]; Chaignet et Sedail, De I'infnence des 
 travaux de Bacon et de Descartes sur la marche de Vesprit humain, Bor- 
 deaux, 1865 ; [Th. Fowler, Bacon (English Philosophers^ Series), Lon- 
 don, 1881 ; J. Xichol, Bacon (Blackwood's Philosophical Classics), 
 2 vols., Edinburgh, 1888-89 ; Heussler, Francis Baco und seine 
 geschichtliche Stellung, Breslau, 1889. Concerning Bacon's predeces-
 
 FRANCIS BACON 297 
 
 The problem is, to begin the Avhole labor of the mind 
 again, to raise science upon an absolutely new basis {instau- 
 ratio magna). If we would ascertain the hidden nature 
 of things, we must not look for it in books, in the authori- 
 ties of the School, in preconceived notions and a priori 
 speculations. Above all, we must give up imitating the 
 ancients, whose influence has retarded the progress of 
 knowledge. With the exception of Democritus and a 
 few positivists, the Greek philosophers observed but little 
 and superficially. Scholasticism followed in the footsteps 
 of antiquit3% It seems as though the Schoolmen had lost 
 their sense of the real. Our knowledge is full of preju- 
 dices. We have our wliims, our preferences, our idols 
 {idola t rib us, fori, spccus, theatri), and we project them 
 into nature. Because the circle is a regular line and 
 affords us pleasure, we infer that the planetary orbits are 
 perfect circles. We do not observe at all, or we observe 
 but poorl3% We infer that because persons have escaped 
 a great misfortune five times, some sujjcrnatural agencies 
 have been at work ; and we fail to take account of the 
 equally numerous cases when they did not escape. One 
 may truly say Avith the j^hilosoplier who was shown, in 
 a temple, the votive tablets suspended by such as had 
 escaped the peril of shipwreck : " But where are tlie por- 
 traits of those who have perished in sj)ite of tlieir vows ? " 
 We assume final causes, and apply them to science, thereby 
 carrying into nature wliat exists only in our imagination. 
 Ijistead of understanding things, we dispute al)out words, 
 which each man interprets to suit himself. We continu- 
 ally confuse the objects of science with those of religion, — 
 a procedure wliich results in a superstitious i)hilosophy 
 and a lieretical theology. " Natural j)hilosophy is not yet 
 
 sor.s, Digliy and Temple, see J, FrcndentJial, Beilrdffe zur Gexchichte 
 derengl. Pkilos., A./, d. G. d. Ph., IV., pp. 450-477, 678-G03, V., 
 pp. 1-11. — Tn.].
 
 298 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 to be found unadulterated, but is impure and corrupted, — 
 by logic in the school of Aristotle ; by natural theology in 
 that of Plato ; by mathematics in the second school of 
 Plato (that of Proclus and others), which ought rather 
 to terminate natiu-al pliilosophy than to generate or 
 create it." 
 
 Philosophy's only hope in this chaos of opinions and 
 a 'priori systems is to break entirely with Greek and 
 scholastic traditions, and to accept the inductive method. 
 What traditional philosophy calls induction proceeds by 
 simple enumeration, leads to uncertain conclusions, and is 
 exposed to danger from one contradictory instance, decid- 
 ing generally from too small a number of facts. Genuine 
 induction, the method of modern science, does not hurry 
 on rapidly from a few isolated and uncertain phenomena 
 to the most general axioms, but patiently and carefully 
 studies the facts, and ascends to the laws continually and 
 gradually. In forming our general law " we must examine 
 and try whether it be only fitted and calculated for the 
 particular instances from which it is deduced or whether 
 it be more extensive and general. If the latter, we must 
 observe whether it confirm its own extent and generality 
 by giving surety, as it were, in pointing out new particu- 
 lars, so that we may neither stop at actual discoveries, nor 
 with careless grasp catch at shadows and abstract forms." ^ 
 
 It is an exaggeration of Bacon's merit to regard him as 
 tlie creator of tlie experimental method and of modern 
 science.'^ On the contrar}^. Bacon was the product of the 
 
 1 Novum organum, B. I., §§ 1, 2, 3, 14, 15, ]9, 20, 31, 38-68, 71, 77, 
 79, 82, 89, 9(3, 100 ff. [Translations taken from Devey's ed. of 
 Bacon's works in Bohn's Library. — Tr.] 
 
 2 His scientific merit has given rise to an interesting controversy. 
 See Ad. Lasson, Ueher Bacon's ivissenscliaftUclie Principien, Berlin, 
 IBGO; Justus v. Liebig, Ueher F. Bacon von Verulam und die Methode 
 der Naturforschunfj, Munich, 1863 ; tr. into French by Tchihatchef, 
 Paris, 1866. Cf. the replies of Alb. Desjardins, De jure apud Fr.
 
 FRANCIS BACON 299 
 
 scientific revival of the sixteenth century, and his mani 
 festo is but the conclusion, or as we might say the moral, 
 which English common-sense cbaws from the scientific 
 movement. But though lie cannot be said to have origi- 
 nated the experimental method, we must at least concede 
 to liim the honor of having raised it from the low condi- 
 tion to wliich scholastic prejudice had consigned it, and of 
 having insured it a legal existence, so to say, by tlie most 
 eloquent plea ever made in its favor. It is no small matter 
 to speak out what many think and no one dares to confess 
 even to himself. 
 
 Nay, more. Though experimental science and its methods 
 originated long before the time of the great chancellor. 
 Bacon is none the less the founder of experimental pJiilos- 
 ophii, the father of modern positivistic philosophy, in so 
 far as he was the fu'st to affirm, in clear and eloquent 
 words, that true philosophy and science have common in- 
 terests, and that a separate metaphysics is futile. An out- 
 spoken adversary of the metaphysical spirit, he expressly 
 begs his readers " not to suppose that we are amljitious of 
 founding any philosophical sect, like the ancient Greeks or 
 some moderns ; for neither is this our intention, nor do ive 
 think that peculiar distract opinions on nature and the prin- 
 ciples of things are of much importance to men's fortunes.'''' ^ 
 Hence he not only opposes Aristotle, but " every abstract 
 opinion on nature," i. e., all metaphysics not based on 
 science. 
 
 He distinguishes, moreover, between primary philosopliii 
 and metaphysics. I'rimary pliilosophy treats of the notions 
 and general propositions common to the special sciences, 
 viz. (accoi-ding to Bacon's strange division, "that is derived 
 
 Baconem, Paris, 1802; of Si.i,^\vart, Ein P/illo^opJi und fin Nalurfori'rher 
 uher Bacon {PreussiscJie .TahrhUcher, vol. XIL, August, 1H03 ; vol. XIU., 
 January, 1801). 
 
 1 Novum orrjanum, I., 110.
 
 300 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 from the three different faculties of the soul," memory, 
 imagination, and reason) • histury^ which includes civil Ids- 
 tory and natural history ; poesy ; and philoso2)hy, which 
 he divides into natural theology, natural philosophy, and 
 human philosophy. Metaphysics is the speculative part of 
 natural philosophy ; it deals with forms (in the scholastic 
 sense) and final causes, whereas the practical part of natural 
 philosophy, or physics propei', deals only with efficient 
 causes and substances. But Bacon does not value meta- 
 physics very highly, and it sounds like irony when, after 
 having called final causes barren virgins, he assigns them 
 to this science. As regards natural theology, its sole aim 
 is " the confutation of atheism." Dogmas are objects of 
 faith, and not of knowledge.^ 
 
 Tlris method of distinguishing between science and 
 theology, philosophy and faith, reason and revelation, is 
 diametrically oj^posed to the ways of the School. The old 
 realistic Scholasticism identified philosophy with theology. 
 Bacon, like the nominalists, cannot keep them far enough 
 apart. He justifies himself for being a naturalist in science 
 and a supernaturalist in theology on the ground of this 
 absolute distinction, and a number of English thinkers 
 follow his example. But the distance is not great between 
 the exclusion of the invisible from the domain of science 
 and its complete denial. Thomas Hobbes, a friend of 
 Bacon, teaches a form of materialism which his political 
 conservatism scarcely succeeds in disguising. 
 
 § 52. Thomas Hobbes 
 
 Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679), the son of a clergyman, 
 born at Malmesbury, in Wiltshire, was the tutor of Lord 
 Cavendish, and, owing to the latter's influence, a loyal 
 friend of the Stuarts. Returning to his country after an 
 absence of thirteen years in France, he devoted himself 
 
 1 De dignitate et augm. sc, III.
 
 THOMAS HOBBES SOI 
 
 exclusively to literary labors.^ Hobbes's fame as a political 
 writer and moralist has somewhat obscured his merit as an 
 ontologist and psychologist. And unjustly so ; for he is the 
 forerunner of materialism, criticism, and modern positivism. 
 Philosophy is defined by Hobbes as the reasoned knowl- 
 edge of effects from causes, and causes from effects.^ To 
 philosopliize means to think correctly; now, to tliink is 
 " to compound and resolve conceptions," i. e., to add or 
 subtract, to compute, or to reckon ; hence, to tliink correctly 
 means to combine what ought to be combined, and to sep- 
 arate what ought to be separated. Hence it follows that 
 philosophy can have no other object than composahle and 
 decompoHible things, or bodies.^ Pui-e spirits, angels, 
 
 * Elementa philosophica de cice, 1642 and 1647; Human Nature^ or 
 the Fundamental Elements of Policy, London, 1650; Leviathan sire de 
 materia, furma et pot estate civitatis ecclesiasticce el civilis, 1651 ; 1670 (in 
 Latin) ; De corpore, 1655 ; De homine, 1658. [First Latin edition of 
 his collected works (published by himseH), Amsterdam, 1668 ; first 
 English edition of his moral and political works, London, 1750J ; 
 CEuvres philosophiques el politiques de Th. Hobhes, etc., transl. into 
 French by one of his friends, 2 vols., 8vo, Neuchatel, 1787 ; His com- 
 plete works (English and Latin), collected and edited by J. Moles- 
 worth, 16 vols., 8vo, London, 1839-45 ; [77/e Elements of Lan\ Natural 
 and Political, ed., with preface and critical notes, by F. Tunnies. To 
 which are subjoined selected extracts from unprinted MSS. of Th. H., 
 London, 1888 ; Behemoth, or the Long Parliament, ed. for the first time 
 from the original MSS. by F. Tonnies, London, 1889; Siebzehn Bricfe 
 des Th. Hobbes, etc., ed. and explained by F. Tonnies, A. f G. d. Ph., 
 III., pp. 58-78, 192-232; Hobbes's Leviathan in Morleifs Universal 
 Library, London. On Hobbes see : F. Tonnies's four articles in Vier- 
 teljahresschrift f. wiss. Ph., 1879-1881 ; same author, Leibniz und H., 
 Philos. Monatshefte, 1887, pp. 557-57."} ; and Th. //., Deutsche Rund- 
 schau, 1889, 7 ; G. C. Robertson, Hobbes {Philosophical Classics), Edin- 
 burgh and London, 1886; G. Lyon, La philosophic de Hobbes, Paris, 
 1893. — Tk.]. 
 
 ' De corjiore, p. 2. 
 
 • Id., p. 6 : Subjectum philosophice sive materia circa quam versatur 
 est corpus.
 
 30^ MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 ghosts, and God, cannot be thought. They are objects of 
 faith, and belong to theoh^gy, — not objects of science 
 falling within the scope of philosophy. Corresponding to 
 the division of bodies into natural and artificial, moral and 
 social bodies, we have : iihilosophia naturalis (logic, on- 
 tology, mathematics, physics) and philoso^phia civilis 
 (morals and politics). Physics and moral philosophy are 
 both empirical sciences, having boches as tlieir objects, 
 and outer and inner sense as their respective organs. 
 Outside of the science of observation, there is no real 
 knowledge.^ 
 
 From these premises follows a wholly materialistic theory 
 of perception. Inner perception, the primary condition 
 and basis of intellectual life, is merely our feeling of brain 
 action. To think, therefore, is to feel. Knowledge con- 
 sists in the addition of sensations. Sensation, again, is but 
 a modification, a movement taking place in the sensible 
 body. IMemory, the indispensable auxiliary of tliought, is 
 simply the duration of sensation : to remember is to feel 
 what one has felt. Sensations cannot be explained, in the 
 manner suggested by some of the ancients, as effluences 
 emanating from bodies, and similar to them. These si7n2i- 
 lacra reruon, or, in the terminology of the Schoolmen, 
 sensihle and intelligible species, are, according to Hobbes, as 
 bad as the occult qualities and other hypotheses of the 
 Middle Ages. Instead, we must say : The simple motion 
 which the objects produce in surrounding matter is com- 
 municated to the brain by the mediation of the nerves. 
 
 Hobbes here states a truth already known to Democri- 
 tus, Protagoras, and Aristippus : the highly important truth 
 of the wholly subjective character of perception. What 
 we perceive — light, for example — is never an external 
 object, but a motion, a modification taking place in the 
 
 ^ De corpore.
 
 THOMAS HOBBES 303 
 
 cerebral substance.^ AVe need no further proof of this 
 than the fact that light is perceived when the eye receives 
 a more or less powerful blow ; the sensation is merely the 
 effect of the excitement produced in the optic nerve. And 
 what holds for light in general may be said of . each par- 
 ticular color, which is but a modification of light. The 
 senses therefore deceive us in so far as they make us be- 
 lieve that sound, light, and colors exist outside of us. The 
 objectivity of the phenomenon is an illusion. The qualities 
 of tilings are accidents of our o^^'n being, and there is noth- 
 ing objective except the motion of bodies, which arouses 
 these accidents in us. Hobbes reasons as Berkeley after- 
 wards reasoned ; but the latter carries out liis argument to 
 the very end; proceeding from sensuaKstic premises, he 
 finally denies the existence of bodies, and culminates in 
 subjective idealism. Hobbes only goes half way : the reality 
 of matter is, in his opinion, an unimpeachable dogma.^ 
 
 Soul or spirit he defines sometimes as brain action, some- 
 times as nervous substance. By spirit, he says, I under- 
 stand a physical body refined enough to escape the obser- 
 vation of the senses. An incorporeal spirit does not exist.^ 
 The Bible itself make no mention of such a being. Ani- 
 mals and man differ in degree only ; both being corporeal 
 beings. We possess no real advantage over brutes except 
 speech. We are no more endowed with free-will than the 
 lower beings. Like them, we are governed by irresistible 
 appetites. Reason without passion, moral principles with- 
 out a material attraction, exert no influence on the human 
 will ; it is impelled by the expectations of the imagination, 
 the passions, and tlie emotions: love, hatred, fear, and 
 hope. "A voluntary action is that wliicli proceedetli from 
 
 1 ITnman Nature, p. : The image or colour is hut an apparition unto 
 us of the motion, atjilalion, or alteration which the ohjert works in the 
 brain or spirits, or some internal substance of the head. 
 
 2 r<I., \>i>. 9 f. » Id., i'\>. 71 f.
 
 304 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the will;" but the volition itself is not voluntary; it is 
 not our deed ; we are not the masters of it. Every act has 
 its sufticient reason. According to the indeterminists, a 
 free or voluntary act is one which, though there be a suf- 
 ficient reason for its performance, is not necessary. The 
 absui-dity of this definition is obvious. If an occurrence or 
 an act does not happen, it is because there is no sufficient 
 reason for its happening. Sufficient reason is synonymous 
 with necessity. Man, like all creatures, is subject to the 
 law of necessity, to fate, or, if we choose, to the will of 
 God. Good and evil are relative ideas. The former is 
 identical with the agreeable ; the latter, with the disagree- 
 able. Interest is the supreme judge in morals as in every- 
 thing else. Absolute good, absolute evil, absolute justice, 
 absolute morality, are so many cliimeras, gratuitous inven- 
 tions of the theological mind and metaphysics.^ 
 
 Hobbes's system of politics is consistent with these onto- 
 logical premises. Liberty he considers as impossible in 
 politics as in metaphysics and ethics. In the State as well 
 as in nature might makes right. The natural state of 
 man consists in the helium omnium contra omnes. The 
 State is the indispensable means of putting an end to this 
 conflict. It protects the life and property of individuals at 
 the cost of a passive and absolute obedience on their part. 
 What it commands is good ; what it proliibits is bad. Its 
 will is the supreme law.^ 
 
 We shall not dwell on this absolutistic theory, the logi- 
 cal consequence of materialism. Let us note in what two 
 important respects Thomas Hobbes differs from Bacon. 
 First, Hobbes teaches a system of metaphj^sics, — the 
 materialistic metaphysics ; secondly, his definition of phi- 
 losophy places a higher value on the syllogism than the 
 author of the Novum organum sets upon it. The latter 
 
 1 Treat, of Liberty and Necessity, London, 1656. 
 
 2 De cive, 6, 19 ; 12, 8 ; Leviathan, c. 17.
 
 DESCARTES 305 
 
 had, in proclaiming induction as the universal method, 
 overlooked (1) the part deduction plays in mathematics, 
 and (2) the part played by the mathematical element and 
 a priori speculation in the discoveries of the fifteenth 
 century. Hence Hobbes occupies a position between pui's 
 empiricism and Cartesian rationalism. 
 
 § 53. Descartes 
 
 RejSTE des Caetes,^ born 1596 at La Haye in Touraine, 
 and educated by the Jesuits of La Fleche, spent the greater 
 part of liis life abroad. In German}^ he fought as a lieu- 
 tenant in the Imperial army ; in Holland he pubHshed liis 
 
 1 JVorks [Latin ed., Amsterdam, 1650 ff ; French, Paris, 1701] ; 
 French ed. by Victor Cousin, 11 vols., Paris, 1824-26; Philosophical 
 Works of Descartes, by Garnier, 4 vols., Paris, 1835, and by Jules 
 Simon in the Biblioiheque Charpentier, 1 vol. 12mo, 1842 ; Moral and 
 Philosophical Works of Descartes, by Amadee Prevost, Paris, 1855 ; 
 Unpublished Works of Descartes, by Toucher de Careil, I860; \_Un- 
 published Letters, by E. de Bude, Paris, 1808 ; by P. Tannery, A. f. G. 
 Ph., vols. lY. and v.; F^ngl. transl. of The Method, Meditations, and 
 Selections from the Principles, by J. Veitch, 10th ed., Edinburgh and 
 London, 1890; of the Meditations, by Lowndes, London, 1878 ; of 
 Extracts from hi^ V/ritings, by H. A. P. Torrey (Series of Modern Phi- 
 losophers), Xew York, 1892. — Tr.]. A. Baillet, La vie de Mr. des 
 Cartes, Paris, 1691 ; Francisque Bouillier, Ilistoire de la philosophie 
 carte'sienne, Paris, 1854, 3d ed., 1868 [a hLstory of Cartesianism]; 
 [C. Schaarschmidt, Descartes und Spinoza, Bonn, 1850] ; J. Millet, 
 Histoir de Descartrs avnnt 1637 suivie de Vanalyse du Discours de la 
 methode et des Essais de philosophie, Paris, 1867; Bertrand de Saint- 
 Germain, Descartes considere comme phi/siolnrjiste et comme medecin, 
 Paris, 1870 ; |"J. P. IVIahaffy, Descartes (Blackwood's Philosophical 
 C/a.Wc.s-), Edinburgh and Philadelphia, 1881. See also: M. Ileiiize, 
 Die Sitlenlehre des Descartes, Leipsic, 1872; Grimm, Descartes^ Lehre 
 von den angehorenen Ideen, Jena,, 1873; G. Glogau, Darlegung it. Kritik 
 des Grundgedankens der Cartesian. Metaphysik, Zlschr. f Ph., vol. 73, 
 1878; A. Koch, Die Psychologic Dtscartes\ Munich, 1881; Natorp, 
 Descartes' Erkenntnissthmrie, Marburg, 1882; K. Twardowski, Idee 
 und Peripptinn hei Descartes, Viciiiia. 1892. — 'I'lt.]. 
 
 20
 
 306 MODERN PHILOSOi'IIY 
 
 Philosophical Essays^ comprising the Biscours de la methode 
 (1637), the Mcd'dationes de prima 'idiUusujihia (164:1), the 
 Frincipia philosophiae (1644). His adiuirer Queen Clu'istina 
 invited him to Sweden, where he died 1650, the same year 
 in wliich liis TraitS des passions de I'dine appeared at Amster- 
 dam. Besides the above, we must mention the foUowino' 
 characteristic works : Le monde ou traite de la htmiere, and 
 the Traite de rhomnie ou de la formation du foetus, wliich 
 were published after the death of the author. 
 
 In order to understand Descartes the philosopher, we 
 nnist remember that he wr,s an emulator of Gassendi, 
 Galileo, Pascal, and Newton, the successor of Viete, and 
 one of the founders of analytical geometry. Descartes 
 was a mathematician above everything else ; a geometrician 
 with a taste for metaphysics rather than a philosopher with 
 a leaning for geometry and algebra. Indeed, liis philoso- 
 phy simply aims to be a generalization of mathematics ; it 
 is his ambition to apply the geometric method to universal 
 science, to make it the method of metaphysics. The Dis- 
 course on Method does not leave us in doubt on this point : 
 "Above all," he says, "I was delighted with the mathe- 
 matics on account of the certainty and evidence of their 
 demonstrations, but / had not as yet found ont their true 
 iise, and although I supposed that they were of service only 
 in the mechanic arts, I was surprised that upon founda- 
 tions so solid and stable no loftier structure had been 
 raised."! And again: "Those long chains of reasoning, 
 quite simple and easy, which geometers are wont to em2)loy 
 in the accomplishment of their most difficult demonstra- 
 tions, led me to think that everything lohich might fall under 
 the cognizance of the human mind might he connected together 
 in the same manner^ and that, provided only one should 
 take care not to receive anything as true wliich was not so, 
 and if one were always careful to preserve the order neces- 
 
 ^ Discours de la inelhode (Torrey's translation), Part I., § 10.
 
 DESCARTES 807 
 
 saiy for deducing one truth from another, there "would be 
 none so remote at which he might not at last arrive, nor 
 so concealed which he might not discover." ^ 
 
 These passages and many others make it quite plain that 
 the Cartesian method consists in mathematical deduction 
 generalized. How, then, did Descartes come to be called 
 the inventor of inner observation or the psychological 
 method ? Descartes needed first jjrinciples from which to 
 proceed in his deductions, and self-observation furnished 
 him with such principles, from wliicli he deduced all the 
 rest more (jcovietrico. Hence, those who regard Descartes 
 as the author of the psychological method are right, in so 
 far as observation is one of the phases and the preparatory 
 stage, as it were, in the Cartesian method ; l)ut they err in 
 so far as they regard it as more than an introduction, or 
 kind of provisional scaffolding for deductive reasoning, 
 which undoubtedly constitutes the soul of the Cartesianism 
 of Descartes. Let us add that Descartes not only uses 
 inner observation ; he is a learned anatomist and physiolo- 
 gist (so far as that was possible in the seventeenth cen- 
 tury), and as such appreciates the great value of experience. 
 He loves to study the great hook of the world ; 2 and for any 
 one to oppose him to Bacon on this point is sheer ignor- 
 ance. The most recent historians of Cartesianism justly 
 insist that it is impossible to separate Descartes the pliil- 
 osopher from Descartes tlie scientist; and French positi- 
 vism, too, is right in reckoning among its ancestors a man 
 Avho tried to make philosophy an exact science. Descartes's 
 failing, a failing A\hich lie shares Avith very many metaphy- 
 Bicians, and wliich is the result of his scholastic training, 
 consists in liis impatient desire to conclude and sj'stema- 
 tize ; which hinders liim from distinguishing sufficiently 
 between the method of scientific investigation and the 
 method of exposition. 
 
 * Discows fie In melhoih: (Torrey's (ruiislaticjii), Tart 11., § 11. 
 2 Id., Part I., § 15.
 
 308 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The application of the geometrical method to metaphy- 
 sics for the purpose of making it an exact science : that 
 is the leading thought in Cartesianisra. The geometer 
 starts out from a small number of axioms and definitions, 
 and, by means of deduction, reaches wonderful results. 
 Descartes follows this method. He needs, first, axioms 
 and definitions ; the first part of our exposition will show 
 us how inner observation, aided by reasoning, supplies 
 them. From these definitions he then deduces a series of 
 consequences, wliicli will form the subject of the second 
 part. 
 
 1. Observing that all he knows or thinks he knows he 
 has received througli the senses and from tradition, and 
 that the senses often deceive us, Descartes resolves to 
 doubt everytlung : to traditional science he opposes a radi- 
 cal doubt. But he does not doubt merely for the sake of 
 doubting. Ilis scepticism, though radical, is provisional, 
 and has for its object the creation of certain and self- 
 acquired knowledge. He differs both from the j^hilosophers 
 of the Church and the sceptics properly so-called. The 
 Schoolmen had said : Credo ut intclUgam ; he however says : 
 Duhito ut intelligam. Pyrrho, Sextus, and Montaigne had 
 doubted before him, but they did not succeed in mastering 
 their doubts ; they were tired of seeking for the truth, and 
 so made doubt an end in itself, a definitive and hopeless 
 system. For Descartes doubt is but a means which he 
 hastens to abandon as soon as he has discovered a certain, 
 primary truth. This, rather than his scepticism, the fact, 
 namely, that he adds to his negation a positive and emi- 
 nently fruitful principle, makes him the father of modern 
 rationalistic philosophy. 
 
 What is this principle, and how does Descartes discover 
 it? His very doubts reveal it to him. I doubt, says he: 
 that is absolutely certain. Now, to doubt is to think. 
 Hence it is certain that I think. To think is to exist.
 
 DESCARTES 309 
 
 Hence it is certain that I exist. Cogito^ ergo sum} Though 
 Descartes derives the substance of his argument from St. 
 Augustine, he formuhites it differently ; he presents it in 
 such an attractive and precise form as to impress the mind 
 and to gain its immediate approval. To the classical for- 
 mula, cogito ergo sum, Cartesian philosophy owes a large 
 share of its success. Descartes's motto is not, however, an 
 inference, and he does not wish us to regard it as such. 
 As an inference it would be a i^etitio lyrincvpii ; for the con- 
 clusion is really identical with the major premise. It is 
 a simple analytical judgment, a self-evident proposition. 
 
 Here then we have a certain basis, on which to con- 
 struct a system of no less certainty than its fundamental 
 principle ; for it is evident that all the propositions follow- 
 ing necessarily from an axiom must be as true as the axiom 
 itself. 
 
 Thus far, then, I merely know that I exist. I can- 
 not advance and extend the circle of my knowledge without 
 exercising the greatest care ; I must remember constantly 
 tlLCit self-evidence, and that alone, is needed to make me cer- 
 tain of anything. It is evident that I think and that I 
 exist, but it is not e^ddent that the object of my thought 
 exists outside of me, for the nature which deceives me by 
 making me believe in the rising and the setting of the sun, 
 may also delude me by making me assume the reality of 
 sensible tilings. My ideas may be merely the product of 
 my own imagination. Heat, cold, and even disease, may be 
 hallucinations. We sliould have to abandon all attempts 
 to prove the contrary, we should forever remain confined 
 within the narrow circle of certitude described by the sum 
 quia cogito, and doubt every^thing else, did we not find 
 among our ideas one whose foreign origin is self-evident- 
 the idea of God or of the infinite and perfect Being.^ 
 
 1 Discours ilc la nit'thnde, IV. Cf. the se<;oii(l MalUation. 
 * Meditulions, III., V.
 
 310 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Tliis idea cannot be the product of my thought, for my 
 thought is finite, limited, and imperfect, and it is self- 
 evident that a finite cause cannot produce an infinite effect. 
 Shall we say that the idea of the infinite is purely nega- 
 tive ? On the contrary, it is the most positive idea of all, 
 the one which precedes all the others, and without which the 
 idea of the finite Avould not be possible. Shall we raise 
 the objection that the human ego, though achudly imper- 
 fect, may be fotentially infinite, because it strives for per- 
 fection, and can therefore produce the idea of God ? But 
 the idea of God is not the idea of a potentially-perfect 
 being, it is the idea of the actually-infinite being. We do 
 not attribute to God an acquired perfection. Our knowl- 
 edge increases and grows more perfect little by little, 
 perhaps indefinitely; but nothing can be added to God, 
 the eternally-absolute and perfect being. Hence, if the 
 idea of God cannot come from us, it must necessarily 
 come from God, and God necessarily exists. 
 
 Moreover, the existence of God follows from the very 
 idea of the perfect being, for existence is an essential 
 element of perfection ; without it, God would be the most 
 imperfect of beings. This argument, advanced by St. 
 Anselmus, apparently makes the existence of God depend 
 on our idea of the perfect being. Such, however, is not 
 Descartes's meaning. We should not say, God exists 
 because my mind conceives him ; but, My reason con- 
 ceives God, because God exists. The true foundation of 
 our faith in God is not our own conception of him, — that 
 would be a suljjective and weak basis, — but God himself, 
 who reveals himself to us in the innate idea of infinity. 
 The objection that the existence of a mountain or a valley, 
 for example, does not follow from the intimate and neces- 
 sary correlation existing between the idea of a mountain 
 and the idea of a valley, is a sophism. From the fact 
 that I cannot conceive a mountain without a valley, nor
 
 DESCARTES 311 
 
 a valley without a mountain, it does not follow that a 
 mountain or a valley exists, but that the two ideas are in- 
 separable from each other. Similarly, from the fact that I 
 cannot conceive God except as existent, it follows that the 
 idea of God implies the existence of the perfect Being.i 
 
 1 know, then, (1) that I exist ; and, (2) that God exists. 
 The certainty of God's existence is a matter of the greatest 
 importance ; on it depends all truth, all certitude, all posi- 
 tive knowledge. Without it I could not advance beyond 
 the cogito^ ergo sum ; I should know myself and never know 
 the not-me. It enables me to destroy the barrier erected 
 by doubt between thought and external things. It teaches 
 me (3) that the corporeal ivorld exists. God, and God 
 alone, vouchsafes the reality of my ideas ; the idea of 
 God which he has implanted in me is the perpetual refu- 
 tation of scepticism. In short, as long as I leave out of 
 account the idea of God, I may suppose that the sensible 
 world is an illusion caused by some evil demon, or by the 
 nature of my own mind. But the existence of God as the 
 author of all things being pj'oved, it becomes evident that 
 my instinctive belief in the existence of the world is well 
 founded; for I receive it from a perfect being, that is, 
 from a being incapable of deceiving me. Henceforth, 
 doubt is impossible, and wliatever trace of scepticism I 
 may hav'e retained is superseded l)y an unshakable conii- 
 dence in reason.^ 
 
 ^ Iji reality, the ontological ai'guinent is no iiioi'C of an inference 
 than the cogito, ergo sum. It is an axiom, a trutli wliich the soul per- 
 ceives immediately and prior to all reflection. 
 
 2 Meditutinn, V., 8: " Uiit after I have recognized the existence of 
 a God, and because I liave at the same time recognized the fact 
 that all things depend upon him, and that he is no deceiver, and in 
 consequence of that I have judged that all tliat I conceive clearly 
 and distinctly cannot fail to be true ... no opjiosing reason can be 
 brought against me which should make nie ever call it in question ; 
 and thus I have a true and certain knowledge of it. And this same
 
 312 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The three realities whose existence has been joroved, — 
 God, the ego, and the corporeal world, — ■ may be defined as 
 follows : God is the infinite substance, on which everything 
 depends and whicli itself depends on nothing ; the soul is 
 a substance that thinks ; ^ the body is an extended sub- 
 stance. By " substance " we can understand nothing else 
 than a thing which so exists that it needs no other thing 
 in order to exist.^ 
 
 2. Observation and reasoning form the basis of the Car- 
 tesian system. A priori deduction completes the struc- 
 ture. 
 
 And here we find, at the very outset, a syllogism which 
 contains the elements of the Spinozistic system. If sub- 
 stance is a tiling which needs no other thing in order to 
 exist, it follows that God alone is a substance in the real 
 sense of the term.^ Now, by substance we can conceive 
 nothing else than a thing which so exists as to need nothing 
 except itself in order to exist. There may be some ob- 
 scurity in the plu-ase : ••' to need nothing except itself ; " for, 
 strictly speaking, God alone is such a heing^ and no created 
 
 knowledge extends also to all the other things which 1 recollect 
 having formerly demonstrated, as the truths of geometry and others 
 like them ; for what is there which can be objected to oblige me to 
 call them in question ? Will it be that my nature is such that I am 
 very liable to be mistaken? But I know already that I cannot 
 deceive myself in judgments the reasons for which I clearly perceive. 
 Will it be that I have formerly regarded many things as true and 
 certain which afterwards I have discovered to be false ? . . . Will it 
 be that perhaps I am asleep ? . . . But even if I am asleep, all that 
 presents itseK to my mind with evidence is absolutely true. And thus 
 I recognize very clearly that the certainty and the truth of all knowl- 
 edge depend on the knowledge alone of the true God : so that before 
 I knew him I could not perfectly know anything else. And now that 
 I know him, I have the means of acquiring a perfect knowledge of an 
 infinitude of things, not only of those which are in him, but also of 
 those which belong to corporeal nature. . . ." 
 
 1 Principles, I., 9-12. « Id., I., 51. 3 Jd.
 
 DESCARTES 313 
 
 thing can exist a single moment without being sustained 
 and preserved by his power. Accordingly, the School is 
 rio-ht in saying that the term " substance " does not apply 
 to God and the creatures uiiivocalUj} Hence, creatures 
 are not substances in the proper sense. Some are sub- 
 stances as compared with others ; they are not substances 
 as compared with God, for they depend on liim. 
 
 Descartes, therefore, understands by relative and finite 
 sitbstance a thing which needs nothing but God in order to 
 exist ; by mode, that which cannot exist or be conceived 
 without sometliing else which is its substance ; by attribute, 
 the essential quality of the substance, from which we can- 
 not abstract without at the same time destroying the 
 substance itself. 
 
 Minds and bodies are (relative) substances. Thouglit 
 constitutes the attribute, i. e., the essence of mind ; ^ exten- 
 sion, the attribute, i. e., the essence of body. 
 
 From the fact that extension constitutes the essence of 
 body, it follows : (1) That there can be no extension in 
 the universe without body, i.e., no empty space; nor 
 bodies without extension, i. e., atoms ; (2) That the cor- 
 poreal world is illimitable, since extension cannot be 
 conceived as having limits (here Descartes contradicts 
 Aristotle and agrees with Bruno) ; (3) That body has, 
 strictly speaking, no centre, that its form is naturally 
 eccentric and its motion centrifugal; for the centre is a 
 mathematical point, and the mathematical point, inex- 
 tended. 
 
 The properties of extension are divisibility, figurability, 
 and mobility. But divisibility is merely a movement of 
 
 * Principles, I., 51. 
 
 ' Id., I., 9 : By the word thought I understand everything that so 
 takes place in us that we of ourselves ijnmediatoly perceive it ; hence, 
 not only to undrTstaud, to will, to imagine, but even to feel, are the 
 same as to think.
 
 314 MODERN THILOSOrilY 
 
 separation and of union. Hence, the properties of exten 
 sion, and consequently of matter, consist in motion. 
 
 There is no other motion than motion in extension, local 
 motion or change of place. 
 
 Furthermore, motion cannot originate in the bodies them- 
 selves : they cannot be said to viove titemselves, to set them- 
 selves in motion and to persist in it of themselves ; for 
 bocUes are extended, extended only, even in their smallest 
 parts, and absolutely devoid of the inner principle, the 
 centre of action and impulsion which we call soul or ego. 
 They are entirely passive ; they do not 7]iove themselves at 
 all, but are moved by external causes. We cannot even say 
 that they are heavy, if we understand by weight a tendency 
 of the body to fall towards the centre of the earth, i. e., a 
 kind of spontaneous activity in matter. The material 
 world knows no other law than the law of necessity. The 
 particles of matter, to which the Creator originally imparted 
 rectilinear motion, are distributed in vortices {tourhillons), 
 forming stars, then planets, which are extinguished stars, 
 and filially other heavenly bodies. The science of the 
 world is a problem of mechanics. The material world 
 is a machine, an indefinite — not infinite — chain of move- 
 ments, the origin of which is in God.^ 
 
 However, we must not mix theology with our interpre- 
 tation of nature ; and physics should entirely abandon the 
 search for final causes, which has hitherto impeded the 
 progress of this science.^ 
 
 Minds are diametrically opposed to bodies : i. e., they are 
 essentially active and free ; and just as there is nothing 
 inextended in body, mind contains nothing that is not 
 thought, inextended, and immaterial. Body is everything 
 that mind is not ; mind is the absolute negation of every- 
 thing that body is. The two substances entirely exclude 
 each other, they are entirely opposed to each other : body 
 ' Principles, II., III. 2 /,/., j., 28.
 
 DESCARTES 315 
 
 is absolutely soulless ; the soul, absolutely immaterial (dual- 
 ism of substances, dualistic spiritualism). ^ 
 
 Like soul and body, the science of soul and the science 
 of body have nothing in common. Physics should confine 
 itself wholly to mechanical interpretation, while the soul 
 shoidd be explained only in terms of itself. 
 
 Although sensation seems to be an action of the body 
 upon the soul, voluntary motion, an action of the soul upon 
 the body, tliis is not actually the case ; for there can be no 
 reciprocal action between substances whose attributes ex- 
 clude each other. Man is a composite being, a combina- 
 tion of soul and body. The soul derives its sensible ideas 
 from its own nature on occasion of the corresponding ex- 
 citations ; the body, on the other hand, is an automaton, 
 whose movements are occasioned by the volitions of the 
 soul. The body and the soul lead separate lives ; the body is 
 subject to necessity, the soul endowed with free-will ; being 
 independent of the body, it survives its destruction. The 
 two parts composing the human being are so exclusive as 
 to make a real union between sold and hodij ahsohdely impos- 
 sible. " Tliose who never pliilosophize," Descartes ^ writes to 
 Princess Elizabeth, " and employ their senses only, do not 
 douljt that the soul moves the body, and that the body acts 
 upon tlie soul. But they regard them both as one and the 
 same thing, i. e., they conceive them to be united ; for to 
 
 1 Medilntion, VT. Here we notice a striking difference between 
 Descartes and Leibniz, between dualistic spiritualism and concrete 
 spiritualism. Descartes goes so far as to deny force {tendance) to 
 body, while Leibniz attributes to it (i. e., to the monads constituting 
 it) not only force, but also perception : it contains the idea whicli it 
 desires to realize, without, however, being conscious of it. The char- 
 acteristic trait of mind as compared with bfxly is not perception but 
 apperception, not the tendency itself, but the consciousness of the goal 
 aimed at. 
 
 '^ A Madame Pjizrdieth, Princexse Palatine (Lf'tlcr XIX., Vol. TIL, 
 ed. GarnjiT).
 
 316 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 conceive things as united is to conceive them as one and the 
 same thlruj^ And when she objects that the reciprocal 
 action between soul and body is a self-evident fact, and 
 that it is easier to attribute extension to the soul than to 
 contradict this evidence, Descartes replies : " I pray your 
 higlmess kindly to attribute matter and extension to the 
 soul, or, in other words, to conceive it as united to the 
 body ; and after you have so conceived it and have tested 
 the notion in your own case, it will not be difficult to see 
 that the matter attributed to thought is not thought itself, 
 and that the extension of this matter is quite different from 
 the extension of thought : the former is bound to a certain 
 place from which it wholly excludes the extension of the 
 body, which is not the case with the latter, and your high- 
 ness will find no trouble in understanding the distinction 
 between body and soul in spite of the fact that your high- 
 ness has conceived them as united." 
 
 The theory, however, does not hinder Descartes from 
 speaking of the reciprocal action between soul and body, 
 as though this action were real and direct. His anthropol- 
 ogy, particularly as formulated in the Traite des passions,^ 
 everywhere assumes what his metaphysics denies. In con- 
 tradiction to the very explicit statements which have just 
 been quoted, Descartes holds that the soul is united to all 
 parts of the body; that it exercises its functions more 
 especially in the pineal gland ; that the soul and the body 
 act upon each other through the medium of this gland and 
 the animal spirits. However, he never goes so far as to 
 identify the " two substances." The Traite de Vhomnie ct 
 dc la formation du fcetus ^ points out the distinction which 
 he draws between them : the body walks, eats, and breathes ; 
 the soul enjoys, suffers, desires, hungers and thirsts, loves, 
 hopes, fears ; perceives the ideas of sound, light, smell, 
 
 ^ Amsterdam, 1650. 
 
 2 Paris, 166-1 (published by Clerselier). In Latin, Amst., 1677, 
 cum noils Lud. de la Forge.
 
 THE CARTESIAN SCHOOL 317 
 
 taste, and resistance ; wakes, dreams, and faints. But all 
 these phenomena are consequences — consequences and 
 not effects — of movements caused in the pores of the 
 brain, the seat of the soul, by the entrance and the exit of 
 the animal spirits. Witliout the hochj, and particularly 
 without the Irain, all these phenomena, as well as the memorij 
 in tvhich theij are retained, ivould disappear, and nothing 
 would be left to the soul except the conception of pure 
 ideas of substance, thought, space, and infinity, — ideas 
 which are wholly independent of sensation. Moreover, 
 the ideas which need the cooperation of the senses, and 
 consequently of the brain, are entirely different from the 
 objects which we suppose them to represent. The idea is 
 immaterial ; the object, material ; the idea is therefore the 
 opposite of the object, even though it be its faithful image. 
 Our ideas of material qualities no more resemble the ob- 
 jects than pain reseml^les the needle causing it,i or the 
 tickling resembles the feather which occasions it. 
 
 We see, the founder of French philosophy, though a 
 rationalist and spiritualist in principle, really approximates 
 empiricism and materialism. His animal-machine antici- 
 pates the Man a Machine of La Mettrie. Though dog- 
 matic in his belief that extension is a reality, he is the 
 precursor of Locke, Hume, and Kant, in that he makes 
 a clear and absolute distinction between our ideas of 
 material qualities and their external causes. 
 
 S 54. The Cartesian School "^ 
 
 The philosophy of Descartes clearly and accurately ex- 
 pressed the ideals of its age: the downfall of traditional 
 
 1 Traile'flu monde ou de la lumiere, chap. 1, Paris, 1664 (published 
 by Clerselier). 
 
 2 F. Bouillier, Ilisloire de In philosnphie carte'sleune ; Dainiron, 
 Hvitoire de la philosnphle du dix-xt>plleme siecle ; E. Sai.sset, Prdcursenrs 
 et disriplfs de Df-sraiirs, Paris, 1862 ; [G. Monclianij), Histoirr du Car- 
 Itsianisme en Belf/iipie, UriLsst-ls, 18S7].
 
 318 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 authorities in matters of knowledge, and the autonomy of 
 reason. It met with immense success. Though accused 
 of neologism and atheism by the Jesuits of France and 
 the severe Calvinists of Holland, though attacked in the 
 name of empiricism by Thomas Hobbes and Pieriie 
 Gassendt, and in the name of scepticism by IIuet, Bishop 
 of Avranches,^ and Piemre Bayle,^ it gathered around 
 its standard men like Clerseliei;,^ de la Foik^e,* 
 Sylvain Ri^.Gis,^ Clauberg,*^ Arnauld,'' Nicole,^ Male- 
 
 BRANCHE, GeULINCX, BALTHAZAR BeKKER, and SPINOZA. 
 
 Even the leaders of militant Catholicism, Bossuet and 
 Fenelon, felt its irresistiljle influence.^ 
 
 1 1G30-1721. Censura philo.'iophice carlesiancB, Vnv\s,lQQ9, etc. The 
 sceptical freethinker Huet differs from Bayle, and resembles Pascal 
 in that he teaches theological scepticism, i. e., a form of scepticism 
 which serves as a stepping-stone for religious faith. 
 
 2 lGi7-170G. Author of the celebrated Dictionnalre histnrique et 
 critique (Rotterdam, 1697 ff.), and j)recarsor of the religious criticists 
 of tlie eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. [SeeL. Feuerbach, Pierre 
 Bayle, etc., Leipsic, 1844.] 
 
 3 Died 168G. Publisher of Opera pm^lhuma De^carli^. 
 
 * Tractatus de mente humana, ejus facultatibus et fuiictionibus, Am- 
 sterdam, 1G69. 
 
 6 1632-1707. Conrs entier de la pJiilosophie, 3 vols., Paris, 1G90; 
 Amst. 1691. 
 
 ® 162.5-1665. Initiatio pliUnsnphi s. did)!tatio cartesiana, 1655 ; Loc/ica 
 vetus, et nova: ontosophia ; de cnc/rritione Dei et nostri, Duisburg, 165G; 
 Opera phdonophica, Amst., 1G91. [See H. Miiller, /. Clauherg und 
 seine Stellung im Cartesianismus, Jena, 1891.] 
 
 T Died 1694. Works, Lausanne, 4.5 vols., 4to, 1775-1783 ; [philo- 
 sophical works published by J. Simon and C. Jourdain, Paris, 1893. 
 See F. R. Vicajee, Antoine Arnaidd, Bombay, 1881]. 
 
 8 Died 1695. Philosophical works published by Jourdain, 1845. 
 [For the Port-Royalists Arnauld and Nicole see : PL Reuchlin, 
 Geschiclitc von Port-Royal, Hamburg and Gotha, 1839-44 , St. Beuve, 
 Port-Royal, 3d ed., Paris, 1867]. 
 
 ^ The former, in his Traite de la connaisance de Dieu et de soi-meme ; 
 the latter, in his Traite de Vexistence et des atlributs de Dieu, and his 
 Lettres sur la viclaplnjsique.
 
 THE CARTESIAN SCHOOL 319 
 
 Two great problems dominate the speculations of the 
 new school. What is the relation between soul and 
 body, mind and matter? That is the ontological ques- 
 tion, with which the question regarding the origin of 
 ideas and the certainty of knowledge, or the critical 
 problem, is closely allied. What is the relation between 
 the soul and God, — between human liberty, on the one 
 hand, and di\-ine onmipotence, on the other ? That is 
 the moral question, which is closely connected with the 
 preceding. 
 
 In order to solve the former, reasoning and experience 
 must be reconciled. If we consult the facts only, sensa- 
 tion is evidently the body's action upon the soul, the action 
 of matter on mind. And evidently, voluntary movement 
 is the action of the mind on the body. We are acted upon 
 by matter, and react upon it. Hence a relation, a very 
 intimate relation, obtains between the two substances. But 
 when they compare the results of observation with the 
 dualistic metaphysics of the master, the Cartesians become 
 involved in insoluble difliculties, and are confronted by 
 mysteries on every side. The mind is a thinking sub- 
 stance and without extension ; the body, an extended and 
 unconscious substance. The mind is nothing but thought ; 
 matter, nothing but extension. Now, though we may con- 
 ceive that an extended substance receives an impulse from 
 another extended substance, and then communicates this to 
 a third substance, likewise extended, the aforesaid extended 
 substance cannot possibly be moved by something abso- 
 lutely inextended; nor, conversely, can an absolutely inex- 
 tended thing transmit any movement whatever to sucli an 
 extended substance. We can coiun'ive of mutual action 
 l)et\veen similar substances, but not l)etwecn oi)j)ositr sul)- 
 stances. Hence we cannot assume that a real iiiihient'e 
 {injluxtis physicus) is exercised l)y the ]nn\\ iqioii the soul, 
 or vice versa.
 
 820 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 According to Arnold Geulincx ^ of Antwerp and Nicho- 
 las Malebranche,^ a member of the Oratory of Jesus, tlie 
 most illustrious representatives of the Cartesian school, 
 the " apparent " action between soul and body can be 
 explained only by the supernatural concourse of God. 
 God intervenes on occasio7i of every volition, in order to 
 excite in our bodies the movement which the soul cannot 
 communicate to it of itself, and on occasion of each cor- 
 poreal excitation, in order to produce the corresponding 
 perception in the soul. Our volitions are the occasional 
 causes, God the efficient cause of our movements; the 
 sense-objects are the occasional causes, God the efficient 
 cause of our perceptions. 
 
 1 1625-1669. Arnoldi Geulincx, Logica fandamenlis suis, a quihus 
 hactenus collapsa fuerat, reslituta, Leyden. 1662 ; Metaphysica vera et ad 
 mentem peripateticam, Amsterdam, 1691; Tvoodi aeavrov slve Ethica, 2d 
 ed., with notes, Leyden, 1675 ff. ; Plti/sica vera, 1688 ; etc. [^Philos- 
 ophical Works of Geulincx, ed. by J. P. N". Land, 3 vols , The Hague, 
 1891-93. On Geulincx see: E. Pfleiderer, Arnold Geulincx, etc., 
 Tiibingen, 1882 ; same author, Leibniz wid Geulincx, ib., 1884; V. van 
 der Haeghen, Geidincx, jStiide sur sa vie, sa philosophie et ses ouvraxjes, 
 Ghent, 1886; J. P. N. Land, A. G. u. seine Philosophie, The Hague, 
 1895. — Tr.] 
 
 2 1638-1715. De la recherche de la ve'rite', on I'on traite de la nature, 
 de Vesprit de Vhomme et de Vusage qu'il'doit faire pour e'viter I'erreur dans 
 les sciences, Paris, 1675; 1712; [new ed., with an introduction by 
 F. Bouillier, Paris, 1880 ; Engl. tr. by Taylor, London, 1700, 1720] ; 
 Conversations meiaphysiques et chretiennes, 1077; Traite de la nature et 
 de la grace, Amsterdam, 1680, [Engl.tr., London, 1695]; Traite de 
 morale, Rotterdam, 1684; [new ed. by H. Joly, Paris, 1882]; Medita- 
 tions metaphysiques et chretiennes, 1684 ; Entretiens sur la metaphysiqrie et 
 sur la religion, 1688 ; Traite de I'amour de Dieu, 1697 ; etc. (Euvres, 
 Paris, 1712; (Euvres, hy Genoude, 2 vols., Paris, 1837; (Euvres de 
 Malebranche, published by Jules Simon, 4 vols., Paris, 1871. Blam- 
 pignon, £tude sur Malebranche, d\ipres des documents manuscrits, Paris, 
 1862 ; Leon OUe-Laprune, La philosophie de Malebranche, 2 vols., 
 Paris, 1870-72 ; [Mario Novaro, Die Philosophie des Nicholas Male- 
 branche, Berlin, 1893; Francois Pillon, L'e'volution de Videalisme en dix- 
 huitieme siecle : Malebranche et ses critiques (L^Anne'e philosophique, 
 IV., 1894) ; Spinozisme et Malebranchisme (Id. Y., 18.Q.')- — T'r.].
 
 THE CARTESIAN SCHOOL 321 
 
 Occasionalism concealed the boldest negations beneath 
 its seeming naiveness. For, in the first place, if there is 
 no direct influence between mind and body; if God, that 
 is, infinite wisdom and goodness, is the necessary and only 
 mediator between matter and soul, we must conclude, with 
 the Dutch Cartesian Balthasar Bekker,^ that sorcery, 
 magic, or spiritism, in every shape or form, is a detestable 
 and ridiculous superstition. 
 
 Nay, more. If God is the efficient author of all my per. 
 ceptions and movements, I am nothing but a nominal, ap- 
 parent, and fictitious subject, and God is the real subject of 
 my actions and thoughts : it is he who acts in me ; it is he 
 who thinks in me. The former consequence of occasional- 
 ism (God acts in me) was cbawn by Geulincx, the latter 
 (God thinks in me), by Malebranche. According to Geu- 
 lincx, we are not, strictly speaking, minds, but modes of 
 mind. Take away the mode, and God alone remains.^ 
 According to Malebranche, God is the abode of spirits, as 
 space is the abode of bodies. He is to the soul what light 
 is to the eye. Just as tliis organ dwells in the light, so the 
 mind is in God, thinks in God, sees in God.^ We do not 
 perceive the material things themselves, but the idea-types 
 of the tilings, their ideal substance as it exists in God. In- 
 deed, how could the eye of the mind see matei'ial things ? 
 To see an object means to assimilate it, to make it our own, 
 does it not? And how can substances whicli exclude each 
 other by their very essence, how can niiiid and matter, ])en- 
 etrate each other ? TTow can the sj^iritual eye assimilate 
 
 ^ 1634-1698. Dft philoi^n/ihin cnrt. (iilmniiitin ran/Iitla et sincera, 
 Wosel, 1608; De hetover'le iveerp.l'l {The V/orld Beicilched), 4 vols., Leu- 
 warden, 1690; Ainsterdain, 1001 (a work occasioned hy the appear- 
 ance of tlie comet in 1680). 
 
 * Meln/jfnjsicn, j). 56 : Suinus hjilur modi titcniis, si uufcras jiiodum, 
 remanet Deus. ('f. ]>. 1 10. 
 
 ' T)e hi rpi'hrrrhe de la ri'rili', TTI., 2, 6. 
 
 •>\
 
 322 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 what is foreign to its nature ? Mind can see nothing except 
 mind. 
 
 Cartesianism, though at first theistic, ultimately changed 
 into a kind of pantheism in the systems of Geulincx and 
 Malebranche, which naturally led to absolute determinism 
 in ethics ; for it made God the universal agent, so to speak. 
 This element particularly impressed the Dutch Calvinists 
 and the Catholics who accepted Jansen's and St. Augus- 
 tine's teachings on predestination and prevenient grace 
 (Arnauld, Nicole, Lancelot, etc.). These thinkers com- 
 bined extreme rationalism with the mysticism of Pascal.^ 
 
 1 1623-1662. CEuvres completes, 1779; published by Bossut, 1819. 
 Pense'es, fragments et lettres de Blaise Pascal, published by Faugere, 2 
 vols., 1814 ; Pensees publ. dans leurs textes authent. avec une introduction, 
 des notes et des remarques, by M. E. Havet, 2d ed., 2 vols., Paris, 1866; 
 [Engl, transl. of Pascal's Thoufjhts by C. Kegan Paul, London, 1885; 
 of Provincial Letters, 1889]. V. Cousin, j^ludes sur Pascal, 5th ed., 
 Paris, 1857 ; Vinet, ^Etudes sur Blaise Pascal, Paris, 1818 ; 3d ed., 1876 ; 
 Tissot, Pascal, reflexions sur les Pense'es, Dijon and Paris, 1869 ; [Drey- 
 dorff's monographs, 1870, 1875 ; E. Droz, ^tude sur le scepiicisme de 
 Pascal, etc., Paris, 1886. — Tr.] As a physicist and mathematician, 
 and especially as a writer, the author of the Pense'es and Lettres pm- 
 vinciales ranks with Descartes. As a philosoj)her he was at first equally 
 attracted by Cartesian dogmatism, which appealed to his " geometric 
 mind," and the new Pyrrhonism of Montaigne. Then, owing to the 
 influence of Port-Royal and the occiu-rence of an event which produced 
 in him an entire change of heart, he became an enthusiastic adherent 
 of Aiigustinian Christianity. Ilis Pensees form the raw material, so 
 to si^eak, of what he intended to be an apology of his new faith. Rea- 
 son revealed itself to him in all its weakness, and made him a sceptic ; 
 natm-e appeared to him in all her ugliness, and made him pessimistic. 
 It was the " heart " — we should say, the conscience — that revealed to 
 him the real God, the living and personal God of the Gospel. For 
 philosophy he henceforth had nothing but contempt. — Among the 
 modern writers who have made a study of Pascal, Yinet possesses the 
 merit of having presented him in his true light, i. e., as the forerunner 
 of Schopenhauer and Schleiermacher. Cousin saw in Pascal nothing 
 but the sceptical and maniacal element. Tliough not ignoring the 
 pathological element in his mysticism, we, for our part, discover three
 
 SPINOZA 323 
 
 But the system had only to be cli vested of its theological 
 shell to become Spinozistic natui-alism. 
 
 § DO. Spinoza 
 
 Baruch (Benedict) Spinoza,^ Spinosa, or Despinoza, was 
 born at Amsterdam, in 1632, of Portuguese Jewish parents, 
 
 truths iu his philosophy : first, reason and experience, without con- 
 science, cannot yield us real truth ; secondly, experience without con- 
 science necessarily leads to pessimism ; and finally, the will — for that 
 is what Pascal means by the words heart (cceur) and feeling (senllment) 
 — takes precedence of reason, and subjects it to its laws. 
 
 ' Benedicts de Spinoza opera quce supersunt omnia, iterum edenda 
 curavit, prcefationes, vilam auctoris, nee nan notitias, quce ad historiain 
 scripluruin pertinent, addidit, H. E. G. Paulus, Jena, 1802-03. More 
 recent editions by A. Gfrtirer, Stuttgart, 1830 ; Riedel, R. des Cartes et 
 B. de Spinoza prcecipua opera philosophica, Leipsic, 1843 ; C. H. Bruder, 
 3 vols., Leipsic, 1843-40 ; completed hy J. van Vlooteu, Ad. B. de Sp. 
 opera quce supersunt omnia, supplementum contin. tractatum de Deo et 
 homine, etc., Amsterdam, 1862 ; [best edition by Van Vlooten and 
 Land, B. de Sj). opera quotquot reperta sunt, 2 vols.. The Hague, 1882- 
 83]. Spinoza's complete works translated into French by Saisset, 
 Paris, 1842; 18G1 ; 3 vols., 1872; [into German by B. Auerbach, 2d 
 ed., 2 vols., Stuttgart, 1872; phil. works trans, into German by Kirch- 
 mann and Schaarschmidt (in the Philos. B'thliothek, 2 vols.). The Chief 
 Works of B. de Sp., transl. into English by R. H. M. Elwes, 2 vols., 
 London, 1883-84 ff. ; Ethics, transl. by White, London, 1883 ; 2d ed., 
 1894; Selections, tv. by Fullerton, Xew York, 1892; new ed., 1895; 
 transl. of Trnctntus de intellectus emendatione, by White, Xew York, 
 1895. — Tr.] Biographies of Spinoza by Coler (in Dutch, 1705, in 
 French, 1706) and Lucas (La vie et Vesprit de Mr. Benoit de Spinosa, 
 1719); Arniand Saintes, JJisloire de la vie et des ouvrafjes de Spinosa, 
 Paris, 1842; J. van Vlooten, Baruch d'Espinoza, zyn leven en schriflcn, 
 Amsterdam, 1802; [2d ed., Schiedam, 1871]. [T. Camerer, Die Lehre 
 Spinozas, Stuttgart, 1877; F. Pollock, Spinoza, His Life and Philosoph;/, 
 London, 1880; J. IMartineau, A Study of Spinoza, London, 1882; also 
 in Tapes of Ethical Theory, Oxford, 18SG; J. Caird, Spinoza, Edin- 
 burgh, 18S8; R. Worms, ia morale de Spinosa, Paris, 1892; L. Brun- 
 schvigg, Spinoza, Paris, 1891. See also K. Fisdicr's excellent volume 
 on Spinoza, History of Philosophy, ]., 2. For full ri'ft'riMices see LVber- 
 weg-Hr-iiize and .\. van d'-r Linth', />. Sjiinoza Bibliografie,Griive\\h!ige, 
 1871. — Tu.]
 
 324 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 who were, it seems, in good circumstances. In accordance 
 with, the wishes of his father he studied theology, ^«5ut soon 
 showed a decided preference for free philosophical specula- 
 tion. After being excommunicated by the synagogue, which 
 made unsuccessful attempts to bring him back to the faitli 
 of his fatliers, he repaired to Rhynsburg, then to Voorburg, 
 and finally to The Hague, where he died, a poor and per- 
 secuted man, in 1677. His love of independence led 
 him to decline the Heidelberg professorship of philosophy 
 offered him by Karl Ludwig, the Elector Palatine. He 
 wrote his principal works at The Hague between the 
 years 1660 and 1677. In 1663 he published the treatise 
 entitled: Benati Descartes 'principiorum philosopJiice Pars 
 I. et II. more geometrico demonstrato}, and in 1670, the 
 anonymous work : Tradatus thcologico-poUticus, in which 
 he discusses and gives rationalistic solutions of such prob- 
 lems as inspiration, prophecy, miracles, and free inves- 
 tigation. His chief work, Eihica more geometrico demon- 
 strata, and several other less important treatises, were 
 issued after his death under the care of his friend 
 Ludwig Meyer.i His Tradatus de Deo, homine, cjusque 
 felicitate was unknown to the philosophical public until 
 1852.2 
 
 Spinozism, as set forth in the Dthics, is the logical con- 
 sequence of the Cartesian definition of substance,^ and the 
 consistent application of the method of the French philoso- 
 
 1 [Ludwig Stein has shown (Neue Atifschlusae uher den litterarischen 
 NacJilass und die Heramgabe der Opera posilmma Sp.'s, Arch. f. G. d. 
 Ph., T, 18SS) that the Opera posthuma were published by the physician 
 G. H. SchuUer and not by Meyer. Meyer most likely wrote the pref- 
 ace. — Tr.] 
 
 2 Published by Ed. Bohmer, Halle, 1852 ; [by Van Ylooten, Am- 
 sterdam, 1862 ; by Schaarschmidt, id., 1869. German translation ; by 
 Schaarschmidt (vol. 18, Phil. Bihliothek), 1869; by Sigwart, 2d ed., 
 Tubingen, 1881. — Tu.]. 
 
 * PrincipJes, I., .51.
 
 SPINOZA 325 
 
 pher.^ Our author is not content with developing his 
 doctrines by pure deductive reasoning, but also presents 
 them )iwre yeometrico. From a certain number of deluiitions 
 he deduces a system whose parts are logically connected 
 with each other. This method of exposition is not an 
 arbitrary form or a provisional fiamework : it is of a piece 
 with the system, and, one might say, constitutes its perma- 
 nent skeleton. When Spinoza treats of the world, of man 
 and his passions, as Euclid in his Elements treats of lines, 
 planes, and angles, it is because, in principle and in fact, 
 he sets as great a value upon these objects of philosophy as 
 the geometer upon his.'-^ Just as the conclusions of geom- 
 etry inevitably follow from their axioms, so the moral and 
 physical facts which the philosopher considers follow with 
 absolute necessity from the nature of things, expressed by 
 their definitions ; and he no more inquires into their final 
 causes than the geometer asks to what end the tliree angles 
 of a given triangle are equal to two right angles. It is not 
 his method that leads him to mathematical determinism ; 
 on the contrary, he employs it because, from the very out- 
 set, he views the world from the geometrical, i. e., deter- 
 ministic standpoint. He agrees with Descartes, Plato, 
 and Pythagoras that philosophy is the generalization of 
 mathematics. 
 
 I. Defestitions 
 
 The fundamental notions of Spinoza's system are sub- 
 stance, attribute, and mode. " By substance,''^ he says, " I 
 
 ^ We do not at all wish to be understood as denying the influence 
 which the Jewish theology of the Middle Ages exercised on Spinoza's 
 intellectual development. This influence is apparent, and it would be 
 ridiculous to call it in (|iies1i()ii. It was owing to it that Spinoza found 
 what he did find in Descartes; he was already a pantheist when lie 
 took up the study of the French piiilosopher. SI ill, we nuist main- 
 tain tliat his leading thought, and particularly his method, aii; llio 
 logical outcome of Die Cartesian system. 
 
 ^ Trachihm politiciis, c. 1, § 4; J-Jl/u'rs, III., Preface.
 
 326 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 understand that which exists in itself, and is conceived by 
 itself, i. e., that which does not need the conception of any 
 other tiling in order to be conceived."^ "By attrihutc I 
 understand that wliich the intellect perceives as constitut- 
 ing the essence of the substance." ^ " By ?nocle I under- 
 stand the modifications of the substance, i. e., that which 
 exists in and is conceived by something other than itself." ^ 
 
 II. Deductions 
 
 1. Theory of Substance 
 
 From the definition of substance it follows: (1) that 
 substance is its own cause ; ^ otherwise it would be pro- 
 duced by sometlnng other than itself, in which case it 
 would not be a substance ; (2) that it is infinite ^ (if it were 
 finite, it would be limited by other substances, and conse- 
 quently depend on them); (3) that it is the only sub- 
 stance ; ^ for if there were two substances, they would limit 
 each other and cease to be independent, i. e., they would 
 cease to be substances. Hence there can be only one sub- 
 stance, which depends on nothing, and on which everything 
 depends.'' At this point Spinoza deviates from the Car- 
 tesian philosophy; but he deviates from it because the 
 system itself invites him to do so. Descartes himself had 
 
 ^ Ethics, I., Def. 3: Per suhMantiam hitelllgo id quod in se est et per 
 se concipitur : hoc est id, cujus conceptus non indiget conceptu alterius rei, 
 a quo formari deheat. 
 
 2 Eth., I., Def. 4 : Per attrihutum intelligo id quod intellectus de sub- 
 stantia percipit, tanquam ejusdem essentiam constituens. 
 
 ' Elh., I., Def. 5 : Per modum intelligo substantice affectiones sive id 
 quod in alio est, per quod concipntur. 
 
 4 Eth., I., Prop. 7. 5 7f/.^ i^ Pi-op. 8. « Id., I., Props. 11 f. 
 
 ' Monotheism here becomes monism. According to monotheism, 
 God is the only God but not the only being ; according to monism or 
 pantheism, he is the only being and the only substance ; he is the only 
 existing being {Eth., I., Prop, li ; Letter XLI.).
 
 SPINOZA 327 
 
 intimated by his definition of substance that in reality 
 God alone is substance, and that the word substance when 
 applied to creatures has not the same meaning as when 
 applied to the infinite Being.i But instead of removing 
 the ambiguity, he continued to call finite things substances ; 
 and in order to distinguish them from God, created sub- 
 stances, as though liis definition could make a created, 
 relative, and finite substance anything but a substance that 
 is not a substance. Hence we must refrain from applying 
 the term "substance" to tilings which do not exist by 
 themselves ; the term must be reserved for the being- 
 which exists in itself and is conceived by itself, i. e., for 
 God. God alone is substance, and substance is God. 
 
 Substance being the only being, and not dependent on 
 anything, is absolutely free in the sense that it is deter- 
 mined solely by itself. Its liberty is synonymous with 
 necessity, but not with constraint? To act necessarily 
 means to determine one's self; to act under constraint 
 means to be determined, in spite of one's self, by an exter- 
 nal cause. That God should act, and act as he does, is as 
 necessary as it is that the circle should have equal radii. 
 Because a circle is a circle, its radii are equal ; because 
 substance is substance, it has modes , but it is free because 
 its own nature and no extraneous cause compels it to 
 modify itself. Absolute freedom excludes both constraint 
 and caprice.^ 
 
 Substance is eternal and necessary; or, in the language 
 of the Sc])<)ol, its essence implies existence. It cannot l)e 
 an individual or a ])erson, like tlie God of religions; for, in 
 that case, it would be a determined being, and all deter- 
 mination is relative negation.* It is the common source of 
 all personal existences, without being limited by any of 
 them. It lias neither intellect nor will : ^ for botli presup- 
 
 1 Principles, I., 51. 2 pjj,^ y^ p,.o],. 17 
 
 « Id, r. rir.p. 17, Sdioliurn. * .Set- also p. 3:51, 1. 8. 
 
 * Eth., I., rr(ii>. 32 and CoroUariL-s.
 
 328 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 pose personality. Not being intelligent, it does not act 
 with an end in view ; it is the efficient cause of things. 
 " I confess," says Spinoza, " that the view wliich subjects 
 all tilings to the indifferent will of God, and makes them 
 all depend on his caprice (Descartes, the Jesuits, and the 
 Scotists), comes nearer the truth than the view of those 
 who maintain that God acts in all things ^v'ith a view to 
 the good (sub ratione boni). For these latter persons — 
 Plato, for example — seem to set up some tiling outside of 
 God, which does not depend on God, but to which God, in 
 acting, looks as a model, or at which he aims as a goal. 
 This surely is only another way of subjecting God to fate, 
 and is a most absurd view of God, whom we have shown 
 to be the first and only free cause of the essence and the 
 existence of all things." ^ 
 
 Though Spinoza calls God the cause of the universe, he 
 takes the word " cause " in a very different sense from its 
 usual meaning. His idea of cause is identical with his 
 notion of substance ; his conception of effect, with that of 
 accident, mode, modification. God, accorcUng to him, is 
 the cause of the universe as the apple is the cause of its 
 red color, as milk is the cause of whiteness, sweetness, and 
 liquidness, and not as the father is the cause of the child's 
 existence, or even as the sun is the cause of heat. The 
 father is the external and transient cause of his son, who 
 has a separate existence of his own. So, too, heat, though 
 connected with the sun, has an existence apart from the 
 star producing it : it exists alongside of and outside of the 
 sun. The case is not the same mth God as related to 
 the world ; he is not its transcendent and transient cause, 
 but the imriument cause ; ^ i. e., if we understand Spinoza 
 correctly, God is not the cause of the world in the proper 
 and usual sense of the term, a cause acting from without 
 and creating it once for all, but the permanent substratum 
 1 Eth., T., Prop. 33, Scholium, 2. * Id., I., Prop. 18.
 
 SPINOZA 329 
 
 of things, the innermost substance of the universe.^ God 
 is neither the temporal creator of the workl, as dualism 
 and Chi-istiauity conceive liim, nor even its father^ as 
 Cabalistic and Gnostic speculation assumes ; he is the uni- 
 verse itself, considered sub specie ^ternitatis, the eter- 
 nal universe. The words God and universe designate one 
 and the same tiling : Nature, which is both the source of 
 all beings {natura naturans sive Deus) and the totality of 
 these beings considered as its effects {natura naturata). 
 
 In short, Spinoza is neither an acosmist nor an atheist, 
 but a cosmotheist or pantheist in the strict sense of the 
 word ; that is to say, his cosmos is God himself, and liis 
 God the cosmical substance. 
 
 2. Tlieonj of Attributes 
 
 Substance consists of infinite attributes, each of which 
 expresses in its way the essence of God.^ The human in- 
 tellect knows two of these : extension and thought. The 
 cosmic substance is an extended and thinking tiring ; ^ it 
 forms both the substance of all bodies, or matter, and the 
 substance of all minds. ^Matter and mind are not two oj)- 
 posite substances, as in Cartesianism ; they are two different 
 ways of conceiving one and the same substance, two differ- 
 ent names for one and the same thing. Each of the attri- 
 butes of the substance is relativcl// infinite. Tlie sul)stance 
 is absolufeli/ infinite in the sense that there is nothing be- 
 yond it : the attribute is only relatively infinite, that is, 
 after its kind.* Extension is infinite as sucli, and thought 
 is infinite as such ; l)ut neitlier extension nor thought is ab- 
 solutely infinite, for alongside of extension there is thought, 
 
 ^ Hence, the Spinozistic conception of iiniii.nu'ncy implies ho\h 
 permanency and, if we may use the term, iulerinrilij ; tliat is to say, 
 the immanent God is both the inner and the permanent cause of the 
 universo. 
 
 2 Eth., [., T).-f. 0. 8 A/., II., Props. 1 and 2. 
 
 * III., I., iJef. 6, Explanation.
 
 330 MODEKN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 and alongside of thought there is extension, not counting 
 such attributes of substance as are unknown to us. Sub- 
 stance as such is the sum of all existing things ; extension, 
 though infinite as extension, does not contain all existences 
 in itself, since there are, in addition to it, infinite tliought 
 and tlie minds constituted by it ; nor does thought embrace 
 the totality of beings, since there are, besides, extension 
 and boches. 
 
 It seems difhcult, at first sight, to reconcile the theory of 
 substance with the theory of attributes. According to the 
 former, substance is ens absolute ijideterminatum ; according 
 to the lattei', it has attributes and even an infinity of attri- 
 butes. Hence, Spinoza's God seems to be both an unquali- 
 fied being and an infinitely-qualified being. It has been 
 suggested that Spinoza, like the Neo-Platonic philosophers 
 and the Jewish tlieologians who do not apply attriljutes to 
 God, may haA^e meant by attributes, not qualities inherent 
 in God, the supra-rational, incomprehensible, and indefina- 
 ble being, but the different wa^'s according to which the 
 understanding conceives God, i. e., purely subjective and 
 human ways of thinking and speaking. An attribute would 
 then mean : what the human understanding att7'ibutes, as- 
 cribes, and, as it were, adds to God, and not what is really 
 and objectively (or as Spinoza would say, formally) in God ; 
 and substance would be conceived as an extended and 
 thinking thing, without really being so. Spinoza's defini- 
 tion of attribute {id quod intelleetus dc substantia perciint 
 taxqua:m cjusdem essentia m constituens) is more favorable to 
 this interpretation than one would suppose. In our opinion 
 it signifies : that which the intellect perceives of substance 
 as constituting the essence of it ; but it might also mean : 
 that which the intellect perceives of substance as tliough it 
 constituted its essence.^ However, if the second interpre- 
 
 1 [The difference between tlie two interpretations may be more 
 clearly stated as follows : Some construe tlie participle constituens as
 
 spmozA 331 
 
 tation were the correct one, Spinoza could not have said 
 that the substance is an extended and thinking thing, nor, 
 above all, that we have an adequate idea of it. Besides, it 
 is wholly unnecessary to translate the passage in the sub- 
 jectivistic and " non-attributistic " sense, simply in order to 
 reconcile the seemingly contradictory theses of Spinoza. In 
 fact, the contradiction is purely imaginary and arises from 
 a misconception. The celebrated determinatio negatio est ^ 
 does not signif}^ : determination is negation, but : limitation 
 is negation. By calling God ens ahsolute indetcrmiiiatum, 
 Spinoza does not mean to say that God is an absolutely in- 
 determinate being, or iion-being, or negative being, but, on 
 the contrary, that he has absolutely unlimited attributes, or 
 absolutely infinite perfections, — that he is a positive, con- 
 crete, most real being, the being who unites in himself all 
 possible attributes and possesses them without limitation. 
 
 Spinoza evidently intended to forestall the objections of 
 the non-attributists 2 by ascribing to God infinita attributa, 
 which seems to mean both infinite attributes and an infinite/ 
 of attributes. God is therefore no longer conceived as 
 having separate attributes, which would make liim a 2mr' 
 ticular being ; he is the being who combines in himself all 
 possible attributes, or the totality of being Now each 
 divine attribute constitutes a world : extension, the mate- 
 agreeing -with (juod, wliile others refer it to intellcctus. According to 
 the Litter (formalislic) view, which is accepted by Hegel and Ed. Erd- 
 niann, the attri])utes are mere modes of human thinking, they are 
 merely in infellectu, not extra intellectum, not realities in God. Accord- 
 ing to the former (realistic) explanation given by K. Fischer and 
 others, the attributes are not merely modes or forms of thought, but 
 expressions of (Jod's nature. They are not merely in the human mind 
 but in God. God is equal to all his attributes. See Kuno Fischer's 
 discussion of the point in his Geschichle der neuern Philosophie, I., 2, 
 Book nr., chap. III., ;}._Th.] 
 
 1 Letter L. 
 
 ' "Who maintain that to give attributes to God means to limit hiin.
 
 332 MODEKN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 rial world ; thought, the spiritual world. Hence, we must 
 conclude from the infinite number of divine attributes that 
 there exists an infinite number of worlds besides the two 
 worlds known to us, — worlds which are neither material 
 nor spiritual, and have no relation to space or time, but 
 depend on other conditions of existence absolutely inacces- 
 sible to the human understanding.^ This conception opens 
 an immense field to the imagination, without being abso- 
 lutely contrary to reason. However, it must be added, 
 strictly speaking : injinita attrihuta are boundless attributes 
 rather than innumerable attributes. Had Spinoza been 
 decided on the question as to whether the absolute has 
 attributes other than extension and thought, he would evi- 
 dently not have employed an ambiguous expression. In 
 fact, his substance has extension and thought only, but it 
 has them in infinite degree. 
 
 Let us point out another difficulty. Spinoza holds that 
 God has neither intelligence nor will ; yet he attributes 
 thought to him, and speaks of the infinite intelligence of 
 God. These two assertions seem to contradict each other 
 flatly. But we must remember that according to Jewish 
 and Catholic theology (and Descartes himself), God has 
 not discursive understanding, which needs reasoning and 
 analysis in order to arrive at its ends ; they attribute to him 
 intuitive understanding, the t'oO? TroirjrLKO'i of Aristotle. We 
 must remember, above all, tliat Spinoza's God is not the 
 " author of nature," but nature itself. Now there is indeed 
 reason in nature, but it is unconscious. Tlie spider weaves 
 its web without the sliglitest notion of geometry ; the ani- 
 mal organism develops without having the faintest concep- 
 tion of physiology and anatomy. Natui'e thinks Avithout 
 thinking that it thinks ; its thought is unconscious, an 
 instinct, a wonderful foresight which is superior to intelli- 
 gence, but not intelligence proper. By distinguishing be 
 
 1 Letters LXVI. and LXVH.
 
 SPINOZA 333 
 
 ^ween cogitatio and inteUecins,'^ Spinoza foreshadows the 
 Leibnizian distinction between perception and apperceptio7i, 
 or conscious perception. 
 
 As compared with Cartesianism, Spinozistic metaphysics 
 has the merit of having realized that thought and extension 
 do not necessarily presuppose two opposite substances. Its 
 fruitfid notion of their consubstantiality anticipates the 
 concrete spiritualism of Leibniz. The assertion that one 
 and the same substance may be both the subject of thought 
 and the subject of extension is, as Leibniz aptly says, neither 
 materialism nor idealism in the narrow sense of these terms ; 
 it combines the truths contained in these extreme theories 
 into a higher synthesis. It is not materialism ; for Spinoza 
 does not hold that thought is an effect of movement, or to 
 use his own terminology, a " mode of extension." Each 
 attribute, being infinite and absolute after its hind, can be 
 explained by itself alone. Hence, thought cannot be ex- 
 plained by matter and movement (by this thesis he wards 
 off materialism) ; nor can extension and movement, i. e., 
 matter, be the product of thought (by this thesis he wards 
 off the idealism of Malebranche). But though thought and 
 extension exclude each other in so far as they are attributes, 
 they belong to the same substance ; conceived thus, mind 
 and matter are the same thing (eadem res)? These " attri- 
 butes of substance " are not dependent on each other ; mat- 
 ter is not superior and anterior to mind, nor does thought 
 in any way excel extension ; one has as much worth as the 
 other, since each is, in the last analysis, the substance itself. 
 This identity of sul)stance, unrecognized by Descartes, ex- 
 plains tlie agreement l)etween the movements of the body 
 and the "movements" of tlie soul in man and in animals. 
 Since one and tlie same svdjstance and, wliat is still more 
 important, one and the same being manifests itself in the 
 physical ordei- ;ind in the intellectual order, this snl)stance, 
 
 1 Elh., I., Prop. :'.l. 2 /'/., If-, l'i"i>. 7, Scholium.
 
 334 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 this being, manifests itself in both spheres according to the 
 same hiws, and the two realms are parallel : ordo idearum 
 idem est ac ordo rerum.^ 
 
 3. Theory of Modes 
 
 The modifications of extension are motion and rest ; the 
 modifications of thought are intellect and will. Movement, 
 intellect, and will, i. e., the entire relative world (iiatura 
 7iaturata) are modes or modifications of substance, or, what 
 amounts to the same, of its attributes. These modes are 
 infinite, like the attributes which they modify. Movement, 
 intellect, and will, the physical universe and the intellectual 
 universe, have neither beginning nor end. Each one of the 
 infinite modes constitutes an infinite series of finite modes. 
 Movement, i. e., infinitely-modified extension, produces the 
 infinitude of finite modes which we call bodies ; intellect 
 and will, becoming infinitely diversified, produce particular 
 and finite minds, intellects, and wills. Bodies and minds 
 (ideas) are neither relative substances, which would be a 
 contradiction m adjecto, nor infinite modes, but changing 
 modes or modifications of the cosmical substance, or, what 
 amounts to the same, of its attributes.^ 
 
 By distinguishing between infinite modes and finite 
 modes, Spinoza means to say that motion is eternal, while 
 the corporeal forms which it constitutes originate and decay, 
 — that intellects and wills have existed for eternities, but 
 that each particular intellect has a limited duration. Bodies 
 or limited extensions are to infinite extension, particular in- 
 tellects to the infinite intellect, and the particular wills to 
 the eternal will, what our thoughts are to our soul. Just as 
 these exist only for the soul, of which they are temporary 
 modifications, so too this soul, like the bod}-, exists only for 
 the substance, of which it is a momentary modification. 
 Compared with God, souls and bodies are no more sub- 
 
 1 Eth., II., Prop. 7. 2 i^i/e,. LXXI.
 
 SPINOZA S35 
 
 stances than our ideas are beings apart from ourselves. In 
 strictly philosophical language, there is only one substan- 
 tive; everj'thing else is but an adjective. The substance 
 is the absolute, eternal, and necessary cause of itself ; the 
 mode is contingent, passing, relative, and merely possible. 
 The substance is necessary, i. e., it exists because it exists ; 
 the mode is contingent and merely possible, i. e., it exists 
 because something else exists, and it may be conceived as 
 not existing. 
 
 In view of this opposition between immutable substance 
 and modes, we may ask ourselves the question : How much 
 reality do modes possess in Spinoza's system ? A mode is 
 inconceivable without a subject or a substance that is modi- 
 fied. Now, the substance is unchangeable, it cannot be 
 modified ; hence the mode is nothing ; movement, change, 
 the cosmic process, particular beings, individuals, bodies, 
 souls, the natura naturata, in a word, have no real exist- 
 ence. Still this conclusion, which Parmenides and Zeno 
 drew, is not Spinoza's. On the contrary, he declares with 
 Heraclitus that motion is co-eternal with substance ; he 
 makes an infinite mode of it. Unmindful of the principle 
 of contradiction, but supported ])y experience, he affirms 
 botli the immutability and the perpetual change of being. 
 In this conflict between reasoning and the evidence of facts, 
 wliich is as old as metaphysics, he deserves credit for not 
 sacrificing thought to reality, or experience to reason. But 
 he tries to smooth over the difficulty ; he does not perceive, 
 or does not wish to perceive, the antinoni}^, leaving it to 
 modern speculation to point it out and to resolve it. 
 
 The human soul, like all intellectual modes, is a modifi- 
 cation of infinite tliought, the hiiinaii body a modification 
 of infinite extension. Since the intelU'ctual or ideal oi-dcr 
 and tlio real or corporeal order are parallel, every soul cor- 
 responds to a ])ody, and every body corrcsjjonds io an idea. 
 Tlie mind is Ihercfon; tlie conscious image of (lie l)o(ly i^idea
 
 336 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 corporis).^ Not that the mind is the body becoming con- 
 scious of itself ; the body cannot be the conscious subject, 
 for thought cannot come from extension, nor extension from 
 thought. Spinoza, like Descartes, regards body as merely 
 extended, and soul as merely thought. But the body is the 
 ohjed of thought or of soul, and there can be no thought, 
 apperception, or soul, without a body. The mind does not 
 know itself, it is not idea mentis except in so far as it is 
 idea corporis or rather idea affectionivm corporis?' 
 
 Sensation is a bodily phenomenon ; it is a prerogative of 
 animal and human bodies, and results from the superior 
 organization of these bodies. PercejDtion, on the other 
 hand, is a mental fact : simultaneously as the body is 
 affected by an excitation the mind creates an image or idea 
 of this excitation. The simultaneity of these two states is 
 explained, as we have said, by the identity of the mental 
 and bodily substance. The mind is always what the body 
 is, and a well-formed soul necessarily corresponds to a Avell- 
 organized brain.^ By the same law (the identity of the 
 ideal and the real orders), intellectual development runs 
 parallel with physical development. Bodily sensations are 
 at first confused and uncertain ; to these confused mochfi- 
 cations of the imperfect organism correspond confused and 
 inadequate ideas of the imagination^ the source of prejudice, 
 illusion, and error : this makes us believe in general ideas 
 existing independently of individuals, in fuial causes pre- 
 siding over the creation of things, in incorporeal spirits, in 
 a divinity with human form and human passions, in free- 
 will and other idols.^ 
 
 1 Etl., IL, Prop. 13. 
 
 ~ Id., Prop. 23 : Mem seipsam nan cognoscit nisi quatenus corporix 
 ajfectiomim ideas percipit. The reader will observe that Spinoza does not 
 say : corporis affectiones, but rather : corporis affectionum ideas per- 
 cipit ; so greatly is his psychology still influenced by Cartesian dualism. 
 
 3 Eth., III., Prop. 2, Scholium. 
 
 * Eth., II., Prop. 36 ; Piop. 40, Scholium ; Prop. 48 ; HI., Prop. 2, 
 Scholium.
 
 SPINOZA 337 
 
 It is characteristic of reason to conceive adequate and 
 perfect ideas, that is to sa}-, such as embrace both the ob- 
 ject and its causes. The criterion of truth is truth itself 
 and the evidence peculiar to it. He who has a true idea, 
 at the same time knows that he has a true idea, and cannot 
 doubt it.i To the objection that fanaticism too is convinced 
 of its truth and excludes uncertainty and doubt, Spinoza 
 answers that the absence of doubt is not, as yet, positive 
 certainty. Truth is true in itself ; it does not depend on 
 any argument for its truth ; if it did, it would be subject to 
 that ; it is its own standard. Even as light reveals both 
 itself and darkness, so is truth the criterion both of itself 
 and of error.2 
 
 The imagination represents things as they are in relation 
 to us ; i-eason conceives them from the standpoint of the 
 whole in which they are produced, and in their relation to 
 the universe. The imagination makes man the centre of 
 the world, and what is human the measure of all things : 
 reason rises beyond the self ; it contemplates the universal 
 and eternal, and refers all things to God. All ideas are true 
 in so far as they are referred to God,^ that is, whose objects 
 are conceived as modes of the infinite Being. It is also 
 characteristic of reason that it rejects the notion of con- 
 tingency, and conceives the concatenation of things as 
 necessary. The idea of contingency, like so many other 
 inadequate ideas, is a product of the imagination, and is 
 entertained by such as are ignorant of the real causes and 
 tlie necessary connection of facts. Necessity is the first 
 postulate of reason, the watchword of true science.* The 
 imagination loses itself in the details of phenomena ; reason 
 grasps their unity ; unity and consubstantialit}-, — that is 
 the second postulate of reason. Finally, it rejects, as pro- 
 
 i a;///., n., Trop. 4:]. '•^ /'/.. n., Srli,,lium. 
 
 8 Id., II., I'n^p. :tJ. •» A/., I., rn.p. L"^. 
 
 22
 
 338 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 ducts of the imagination, final causes and universals con- 
 sidered as realities. 
 
 The only universal that really exists and is at the same 
 time the highest object of reason, is God, or the infinite and 
 necessary substance of which everything else is but an acci- 
 dent. According to Spinoza, reason can form an adequate 
 idea of him, but not the imagination. ^ 
 
 The will or active faculty is not essentially different 
 from the understanding.^ It is nothing but a tendency of 
 reason to retain ideas agreeable to it, and to reject such as 
 are distasteful. A volition is an idea that affirms or negates 
 itself. 
 
 Will and intellect being identical in their essence, it fol- 
 lows that the development of the one runs parallel with 
 that of the other. Corresponding to the imagination, 
 which represents things according to our impressions, we 
 have, in the practical sphere, passion, or the instinctive 
 movement which impels us towards an object or makes us 
 shrink from it. When what the imagination shows us, is 
 of such a nature as to give our physical and moral life a 
 greater intensity ; or, in other words, when a thing is agree- 
 able and we strive for it, this wholly elementary form of 
 willing is called desire, love, joy, or pleasure. In the oppo- 
 site case, it is called aversion, hatred, fear, or grief. 
 
 To the higher understanding corresponds, in the prac- 
 tical sphere, the will proper, that is, the will enlight- 
 ened by reason, and determined, not by what is agreeable, 
 but by what is true. Not until it reaches this stage 
 can the will, which is quite passive in the state of 
 instinct, be called an active faculty. We act, in the 
 philosophical sense, when anything happens either within 
 us or outside of us, of which we are the adequate cause 
 
 1 Eth., II., Prop. 47 and Scholium. 
 
 ^ Id., II., Prop. 49, Corollary : Voluntas et intellectus unum el idem 
 sunt.
 
 SPINOZA 339 
 
 (adcequata), that is, when anything follows from our nature 
 within us or outside of us, which can be clearly and dis- 
 tinctly understood through our nature alone. On the 
 other hand, we are passive when something happens within 
 us or follows from our nature, of which we are but the 
 partial cause. ^ To be passive or to be acted upon does not, 
 therefore, mean not to act at all, but to be limited in one's 
 activity. We are passive in so far as we are a part of the 
 universe, or modes of the divine being. God or the uni- 
 verse, by the very fact that he is unlimited, cannot be 
 passive. He is pu.re action, absolute activity. 
 
 However active man may seem in his passions, he is 
 really passive in the proper and primar}^ sense of the term : 
 i. e., limited, impotent, or the slave of things. He can be 
 made free and become active onl}^ through the understand- 
 ing. To understand the universe is to be delivered from 
 it. To understand everything is to be absolutely free. 
 Passion ceases to be a passion as soon as we form a clear 
 idea of it.^ Hence, freedom is found in thought and in 
 thought alone. Thought, too, is relatively passive in so 
 far as it is limited by the imagination, but it can free 
 itself from this yoke by sustained application and persistent 
 effort. Since freedom is found only in tliought, our knowl- 
 edge of things is the measure of our morality. That is 
 morally good which is conducive to the understanding ; 
 that is bad which landers and diminishes it.^ 
 
 Virtue is the power of the understanding ; or, still better, 
 it is man's nature in so far as this has the power of pro- 
 ducing certain effects which can be exj)lained by the laws 
 of that nature alone.* To be virtuous is to be strong, or 
 to act; to be vicious is to be weak, or passive. From this 
 point of view, not only hatred, anger, and envy, but also 
 
 1 Eih., III., IXf. 2. 2 /,/., iii^ Prop. 59; V., Prop. 3. 
 
 « Elh , IV., Props. 20 iind 27. Cf. § 14. 
 * Id., IV., Def. 8.
 
 340 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 fear, hope, and even pity and repentance, must be reckoned 
 among the vices. Hope is accompanied by a feeling of 
 fear, pity and sympathy, by a feeling of pain, that is to 
 say, by a diminution of our being, by a weakening of our 
 energy. Repentance is doubly bad ; for he who regrets is 
 weak and is conscious of his weakness. The man who 
 orders liis life according to the dictates of reason will 
 therefore labor with all his might to rise above pity and 
 vain regrets. He will help his neighbor as well as im- 
 prove himself, but he will do it in the name of reason. 
 Thus will he be truly active, truly brave, and truly virtu- 
 ous (in the original sense of the Latin word). He will be 
 brave, for he will not let himself be conquered either by 
 human miseries or his own mistakes, and he will not let 
 himself be vanquished, because he knows that all things 
 follow from the necessity of God's natui'c. 
 
 For the pliilosopher, who is convinced of the necessity 
 of human actions, nothing merits hatred, derision, con- 
 tempt, or pity.i From his absolute standpoint of reason, 
 even the crimes of a Nero are neither good nor bad, but 
 simply necessary acts. Determinism makes the philoso- 
 pher optimistic, and raises him, by gradual stages of per- 
 fection, to that disinterested love of nature which gives 
 everything its value in the whole of things, to that amor 
 intellectuals Dei, or pliilosophical love of nature, which is 
 the summit of virtue. This sentiment differs essentially 
 from the love of God of positive religions. The latter has 
 for its object a fictitious being, and corresponds to the ele- 
 mentary stage of understanding called opinion or imagina- 
 tion. Since the God of the imagination is an individual, a 
 person like ourselves, and like every living and real per- 
 son, possesses feelings of love, anger, and jealousy, our 
 love for him is a particularistic feeling, a mixture of love 
 and fear, of happiness and restless jealousy ; and the hai> 
 
 ^ Tractalu:^ poUticus, T., 4.
 
 SPINOZA 341 
 
 piness whicli it procures for us is still far removed from 
 the perfect blessedness to wliicli we aspii^e. 
 
 The philosophical love of God, on the other hand, is an 
 absolutely disinterested feeling ; its object is not an indi- 
 vidual who acts arbitrarily and from whom we expect 
 favors, but a being superior to love and to hate. This God 
 does not love like men ; for to love is to feel pleasure, and 
 to feel pleasure is to pass from less to greater perfection ; 
 now the infinitely perfect being cannot be augmented.^ 
 Hatred likewise is foreign to him, since to hate is to be 
 passive, and to be passive is to be diminished in one's 
 being, which cannot be the case with God. Conversely, 
 the hatred which some men entertain towards God, and 
 their complaints against him, are possible only from the 
 standpoint of the imagination, which conceives God as a 
 person acting arbitrarily. We hate persons only ; we can- 
 not therefore really hate God, conceived as the necessary 
 order of things, as the eternal and involuntary cause of 
 eveiything that exists. The philosopher cannot help lov- 
 ing God ; at least, he cannot but feel perfectly contented, 
 peaceful, and resigned in contemplating him. This com- 
 plete acquiescence of the thinker in the supreme law, this 
 reconciliation of the soul with the necessities of life, this 
 entire devotion to the nature of things, — is what Spinoza, 
 by accommodation, without doubt, calls the intellectual 
 love of God,2 the source of eternal happiness. 
 
 In this peculiar feeling, the difference between God and 
 the soul, or substance and mode, is obliterated ; the loved 
 object becomes the loving subject, and conversely. The 
 intellectual love of man towards God is identical with the 
 love of God towards himself.^ Owing to this " trans- 
 formation of natures," the human soul, which is perishable 
 in so far as its functions are connected with the life of the 
 
 1 Elh., v., Prop. 17. - Id., V., Prop. iiL', Corollary. 
 
 8 Id., \., Prop. ;iG.
 
 342 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 body,^ is immortal in its divine i^art, the intellect. By the 
 immortality of the soul we mean, not so much the infinite 
 duration of the person ^ as the consciousness that its sub- 
 stance is eternal. The certainty that the substance of our 
 personality is imperishable, because it is God, banishes 
 from the soul of the philosopher all fear of death, and fills 
 him with an unmixed joy. 
 
 Let us sum up. Substance is that which exists by itself 
 and by itself alone. Hence neither bodies nor minds can 
 be called substances ; for both exist by virtue of the divine 
 activity. God alone exists by himself and by himself alone : 
 hence there is but one absolutely infinite substance. This 
 substance or God has two relatively infinite attributes : 
 extension and thought. Extension is modified, and forms 
 bodies ; thought is infinitely diversified, and forms minds. 
 Such is the metaphysics of Spinoza. Necessity and joyful 
 resignation : these two words sum up his ethical teachings. 
 
 We have shown in what respect Spinozism advances be- 
 yond the Cartesian philosophj^ By making mind and mat- 
 ter, soul and body, manifestations of a common principle, it 
 destroys the dualism of a physical universe, absolutely di- 
 vested of all ideal content, and an exclusively intellectual 
 order of things, a world of abstract, incorporeal entities, 
 which are as different from the real cosmos as the latter is 
 supposed to be from the realm of pure thought. The uni- 
 verse is one. True, it contains two elements that are eter- 
 nally distinct and cannot be explained in terms of each other: 
 matter and thought ; but these two elements, although dis- 
 tinct, are inseparable because they are not substances, but 
 attributes of one and the same substance. Every movement, 
 or, in other words, every modification of infinite extension, 
 has an idea, i. e., a modification of infinite thought, corre- 
 sponding to it ; and vice versa : every idea has as its necessary 
 accompaniment a corresponding fact in the physiological 
 1 Eth., v., Prop. 21. 2 id^^ v., Prop. 34, SchoHum.
 
 LEIBNIZ 343 
 
 order. Thought is not without matter, nor matter without 
 thought. Spinozism points out the intimate correhition be- 
 tween the two elements of being, but guards against iden- 
 tifying them, as materialism and idealism do, from opposite 
 points of view. 
 
 But this gain is counterbalanced by a difficulty which, 
 seems to make for Cartesian dualism. Spinoza holds that 
 one and the same thing (substance) is both extended and 
 tliinking, that is, inextended ; hence, he flagrantly violates 
 the law of contradiction. True, he anticipates this objec- 
 tion by declaring, in opposition to Descartes, that corporeal 
 substance is no more divisible, in so far as it is substance, 
 than spiritual substance ; ^ and so prepares the way for the 
 Leibnizian solution. But, on the other hand, he goes right 
 on calling corporeal substance extended (res extensa)? Now, 
 indivisible extension is a contradiction in terms. 
 
 It was left to Leibniz to prove that there is nothing con- 
 tradictory in the assumption that one and the same thing 
 can be hoih the principle of thought and the principle of 
 corporeal existence. He proclaimed the truth which is now 
 accepted as a fundamental principle in physics, that the 
 essence of matter does not consist in extension, but in for^e, 
 and thereby turned the scales in favor of concrete spiritual- 
 ism. It is a contradiction to hold that the same thing is 
 both extended and inextended ; it is not a contradiction to 
 say that the same thing is force and thought, perception 
 and tendency. 
 
 § 56. Leibniz 
 
 The life of Gottfried Wjlhelm Leibniz, like his doc- 
 trine, forms the counterpart of Spinoza's. The illustrious 
 Jew of Amsterdam was poor, neglected, and persecuted even 
 
 ^ Elh., I., Prop. 13, Corollary: Ex hix .leqiiilur inillnm suhstnntia)ii ct 
 consequcnter nullam suhxtdutidin corpoream, quatcnus subxtanlia est, esse 
 divisihilem. 
 
 ^ Tfl.,\l, Prop. 2.
 
 344 MODEKN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 to his dying day, wliile Leibniz knew only the bright side 
 of life. Most liberally endowed with all the gifts of nature 
 and of fortune, and as eager for titles and honors as for 
 knowledge and truth, he had a brilliant career as a jurist, 
 diplomat, and universal savant. His remarkable success is 
 reflected in the motto of his theodicy : Everything is for the 
 lest in the best of possible worlds. He was born at Leipsic in 
 1646, and died on the 14th of November, 1716, as Librarian 
 and Court Counsellor of the Duke of Hanover, Privy Coun- 
 sellor, Imperial Baron, etc., etc. 
 
 His principal pliilosopliical writings are: Meditationes de 
 cognitione, veritate et ideis (3684); Zcttres sur la question si 
 I'essenee du corps consiste dans Vetendue (in the Journal des 
 savants, 16Q1) ; Nouveaux essais sur Ventendement humain 
 (in reply to Locke's Essay) ; Essais de Theodicce sur la honte 
 de Dieu, la lihertS de lliomine et Vorigine du mal (1710), dedi- 
 cated to Queen Sophia Charlotte of Prussia ; Za monado- 
 logie (1714) ; Principes de la nature et de la grdce.fondes en 
 Q^aison (1714) ; fuially, his Correspondence?- 
 
 ^ His writings, most of which are brief, have been collected and 
 edited by Raspe (Amsterdam and Leipsic, 1765) ; Louis Dutens (Ge- 
 neva, 1768) ; J. E. Erdmann, Berlin, 1840 ; Foucher de Careil ((Euvres 
 de Leihniz, published for the first time after the original manuscripts, 
 Paris, 1859 ff.) ; Paul Janet (2 vols., Paris, 1866, with the correspond- 
 ence of Leibniz and Arnauld); [C. J. Gerhardt, Philosophical writings 
 of Leibniz, 7 vols., Berlin, 1875-90. German writings ed. by G. E. 
 Guhrauer, Berlin, 1838-40. Engl, translation of important philosophi- 
 cal writings by G. M. Duncan, New Haven, 1890 ; of the New Essaya, 
 by A. G. Langley, London and New York, 1893]. [G. E. Guhrauer, 
 G. W. Freih. v. Leihniz, 2 vols., Breslau, 1842, 1846; Engl, by Mackie, 
 Boston, 1845 ; Ludwig Feuerbach, Darstellumj, Entwickelung und Kritik 
 der leibnizschen Philosophie, Ansbach, 1837 ; 2d ed., 1844]; Nourrisson, 
 LapMosophie de Leibniz, Paris, 1860 ; [J. T. ISIerz, Leihniz(m Blackwood's 
 Philosophical Classics), London, 1884 ; J. Dewey, Leibniz's New Essays 
 concerning the Human Understanding (Griggs's Philosophical Classics), 
 Chicago, 1888; E. Dillmann, Eine neue Darstelhmg der leibnizschen 
 Monadenlehre, Leipsic, 1891.] For the Leibnizian doctrme of matter
 
 LEIBNIZ 345 
 
 Leibniz opposes to the dualism of extended or unconsci- 
 ous substance and inextended or conscious substance his 
 theory of monads or inextended and 7nore or leas conscious 
 substances. It seems that he derived the expression and the 
 conception from Bruno's De monade and Dc triplici minimo ^ 
 (1591). 
 
 Both the physical and mental realms contain a series 
 of plienomena which do not depend exclusively either on 
 thouo-ht or on extension. If the mind is conscious thousfht 
 and nothing but that, how shall Ave explain the countless 
 mimite perceptions (^p)^^^c(^pt^ons p)ctites') ^ whicli baffle all ana 
 lysis, those vague and confused feelings which cannot be 
 classified, in short, everything in the soul of which we are 
 not conscious ? ^ The soul has states during which its per- 
 ceptions are not distinct, as in a profound, dreamless sleep, 
 or in a swoon. During these states the soul either does not 
 exist at all, or it exists in a manner analogous to the body, 
 that is, without consciousness of self. Hence there is in 
 the soul something other than conscious thought : it con- 
 tains an unconscious element, which forms a connecting 
 link between the soul and the physical world.^ 
 
 and monads see Hartenstein, Commentatio de materkti apud Leibnizium 
 nutione, Leipsic, 1846 ; for his theodicy, J. Bonifas, Etude sur la The'o- 
 dice'e de Ledmiz, Paris, 1863 ; for his doctrine of pre-established har- 
 mony, Hugo Sommer, De doctrina quam de harm, praest. L. proposuit, 
 Gottingen, 186-1; etc., etc. [Cf. also: Foucher de Careil, Leibniz, 
 Descartes et Spinoza, Paris, 1863 ; E. Pfleiderer, Leibniz und Geulincx, 
 Tubingen, 1881; L. Stein, Leibniz und Spinoza, YtGi-Ww, 18!X); G. Har- 
 tenstein, Locke's Lehre von der merischlichen Erkenntniss in Vergleichnnfj 
 mil Leibniz's Krilik dnselben, Leipsic, 1.S61; Frank 1'hilly, Leibnizens 
 Slreit gegen Locke in Ansehung der angeborenen Ideen, Heidelberg, 1891 ; 
 and especially K. Fischer's History of Philosophg. — Tu.] 
 
 * [According to L. Stein (Leibniz und Spinoza), from F. Mercurius 
 van Ilelmont. — Tu.] 
 
 2 Nouveaux Essais, Preface. * lifonaddhigic, §11. 
 
 * Nouveaux Essais, Book IT., cli. IX. and XIX.; Principes dehi na- 
 ture et de la grdce, § 4.
 
 346 MODERN THILOSOPHY 
 
 Moreover, what are attraction, repulsion, heat, and light, 
 if matter is inert extension, and nothing but that ? Cartesi- 
 anism can neither deny nor explain these facts. Consist- 
 ency demands that it boldly deny, on the one hand, the 
 existence of order and life in the corporeal world, on the 
 other, the presence in the soul of all ideas, sensations, and 
 volitions which temporarily sink below the threshold of 
 consciousness and attention, and reappear at the slightest 
 inner or outer solicitation. It must unhesitatingly affirm 
 that there is nothing inextended in the material world, and 
 nothing unconscious in the spiritual world. But that would 
 be to fly in the face of facts, and to assert an absurdity. No ; 
 extension, as the Cartesians conceive it, cannot of itself ex- 
 plain sensible phenomena. It is synonymous with passivity, 
 inertia, and death, while everything in nature is action, 
 movement, and life. Hence, unless we propose to explain 
 life by death, and being by non-being, we must of necessity 
 suppose that the essence of body consists of something dif- 
 ferent from extension. 
 
 And, indeed, does not the state of extension, which con- 
 stitutes the nature of body, presuppose an effort or force 
 that extends itself, a power both of resistance and expan- 
 sion? Matter is essentially resistance, and resistance 
 means activity. Behind the (extended) state there is the 
 act which constantly produces it, renews it (extension). A 
 large body moves with more difficulty than a small body ; 
 this is because the larger body has greater power of resist- 
 ance. What seems to be inertia, or a lack of power, is in 
 reality more intense action, a more considerable effort. 
 Hence, the essence of corporeality is not extension, but the 
 force of extension, or active force. ^ Cartesian physics deals 
 with inert masses and lifeless bodies only, and is therefore 
 identical with mechanics and geometry ; but nature can be 
 
 1 Lettre sur la question de savoir si Vessence du corps consists dans 
 Vetendue (ed. Erdmann, p. 113),
 
 LEIBNIZ . 347 
 
 explained only by a metaphysical notion that is higher than 
 a purely mathematical and mechanical notion; and even 
 the principles of mechanics, that is, the first laws of mo- 
 tion, have a higher origin than that of pure mathematics.^ 
 Tliis higher notion is the idea of Force. It is this power 
 of resistance that constitutes the essence of matter. As to 
 extension, it is nothing hut an abstraction ; it presupposes 
 something that is extended., expanded., and continued. Ex- 
 tension is the diffusion of this " something." Milk, for 
 example, is an extension or diffusion of whiteness; the 
 diamond, an extension or diffusion of hardness ; body in 
 general, the extension of materiality. Hence, it is plain 
 that there is something in the body anterior to extension ^ 
 (the force of extension). True metaphysics does not recog- 
 nize the useless and inactive masses of which the Car- 
 tesians speak. There is action everywhere. No hodij 
 without movement, no substance loithout effort.^ 
 
 Only the effects of force are perceptible ; in itself it is 
 an insensible and immaterial thing. Now force constitutes 
 tlie essence of matter; hence matter is in reality imma- 
 terial in its essence. This paradox, Avhich is also found in 
 Leiljniz, Bruno, and PlotiniLS, in principle overcomes the 
 dualism of the physical and mental worlds. Though force 
 forms the essence of that which is extended, it is itself 
 inextended; it is therefore indivisible and simple; it is 
 original ; for composite tilings alone are derived and have 
 become what they are ; finally, it is indestructible, for a 
 simple substance cannot be decomposed. A miracle alone 
 could destroy it. 
 
 Tims far Leibniz speaks of force as Spinoza speaks of 
 
 ^ Leitre sur la rjueslimi tie savoir si V essence dn corps consiste dans 
 Vetendue (ed. Enliiiami, p. IK?). 
 
 2 Exurncn des principes de Mnlehranche (Knlmaiiii, p. 002). 
 
 ' Eclaircissement du nouueau syst^me de la communication des suh- 
 stances, p. i;J2.
 
 348 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 substance, and there seems to be merely a verbal difference 
 between him and his predecessor. But here their paths 
 diverge. Spinoza's " substance " is infinite and unique ; 
 Leibniz's " force " is neither one nor the other. If there 
 were but one single substance in the world, this one 
 substance would also be the only force ; it alone would be 
 able to act by itself, and everything else would be inert, 
 powerless, passive, or rather, would not exist at all. Now, 
 the reverse is actually true. We find that minds act by 
 themselves, with the consciousness of their individual 
 responsibility ; we likewise find that every body resists all 
 other bodies, and consequently constitutes a separate force. 
 Shall we say, in favor of Spinozism, that the indwelling 
 forces of things are so many parts of the one force? But 
 that cannot be, since force is essentially indivisible. By 
 denying the infinite diversity of individual forces, the 
 abstract monism of Spinoza reverses the very nature of things^ 
 and becomes a pernicious doctrine} Where there is action 
 there is active force ; now there is action in all things ; 
 each constitutes a separate centre of activity ; hence there 
 are as many simple, indivisible, and original forces as there 
 are things. 
 
 These original forces or monads may be compared to 
 physical points or to mathematical points ; but they differ 
 from the former in that they have no extension, and from 
 the latter, in that they are objective realities. Leibniz 
 calls them metaphysical points or points of substance ^ (they 
 are both exact, like mathematical points, and real, like 
 physical points*), formal p)oints, formal atoms, substantial 
 forms (in scholastic language), to indicate that each con- 
 stitutes an individual, independent of all the other monads, 
 acting of itself and depending only on itself in form, 
 character, and entire mode of life. 
 
 1 De ipsa natura, sive de vi ins'ita actionibusque creaturarum, § 8 
 Cf. Lettre 11. d, M. Bourguel. 
 
 2 Nouveau systeme de la nature, § 11.
 
 LEIBNIZ 349 
 
 Whatever happens in the monad comes from it alone ; 
 no external cause can produce modiiications in it. Since 
 it is endowed with spontaneous activity, and receives no 
 influence from without, it differs from all other monads, 
 and differs from them forever. It cannot be identified with 
 anytliing ; it eternally remains what it is {priiicipiuiii clis- 
 tinctionis). It has no ivindotvs hj ivhich anything can enter 
 or pass out.^ Since each monad differs from and excludes 
 all the rest, it is " like a' separate world, self-sufficient, 
 independent of every other creature, embracing the infinite, 
 expressing the universe." ^ It follows that two individual 
 things cannot be perfectly alike in the world. 
 
 But here a serious objection arises. If each monad con- 
 stitutes a separate world, independent of all other beings ; 
 if none has " windows " by which anything can enter or 
 dej)art; if there is not the slightest reciprocal action be- 
 tween individuals, — what becomes of the universe and its 
 unity ? Spinoza sacrificed the reality of individuals to the 
 principle of unity ; does not Leibniz go to the other ex- 
 treme? Are there not, according to his assumption, as 
 many universes as there are atoms? This difficulty, which 
 necessarily confronts all atomistic theories, Leibniz circum- 
 vents rather than solves. lie has broken up, shattered, 
 and pulverized the monolithic universe of Spinoza : how will 
 he l)e able to cement these infinitesimal fragments together 
 again, to reconstruct the ev kuI vdv? 
 
 He finds the synthetic principle in the analogy of monads 
 and in the notion of pre-estahlished harmony. Though each 
 monad differs from all the rest, there is an analogy and a 
 family resemblance, so to speak, between them. They 
 resemble each other in that all are endowed with ^jcrcc^> 
 
 ^ Afonft'Iolog'te, § 7. 
 
 2 Nouveau syslhne de la nature, § KJ. [I have in many instances 
 used Duncan's translations, making sucli changes as 1 dccnied proper. 
 _Tk.]
 
 350 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 tion and desire or a2y2^etition, — Schopenhauer would say, 
 will. Those on the lower stages in the scale of things, as 
 well as the highest and most perfect monads, are forces, 
 entelechies, and souls} Souls alone exist, and that which 
 we call extension or body is nothing but a confused per- 
 cej)tion, a phenomenon, a sensible manifestation of effort, 
 that is to say, of the immaterial. Thus the dualism of 
 soulless matter and denaturized mind is forever overcome. 
 " Whatever there is of good in the hypotheses of Epicurus 
 and of Plato, of the greatest materialists and the greatest 
 idealists, is here combined." ^ Matter signifies a relation, a 
 negative relation ; it does not express a mode of the 
 monad's positive being, as the negative expression impetie- 
 trable very well indicates; thought ([)erception) and tend- 
 ency (appetition) are positive attributes, permanent modes 
 of being, not only of the higher monads but of all without 
 exception. Leibniz emphatically maintains that perception 
 is universal,^ and answers the objection that beings inferior 
 to man do not tJiinJc, by the statement that "there are 
 infinite degrees of perception, and perception is not neces- 
 sarily sensation." * The more the Cartesians persisted in 
 denying all analogy between human thought and the mental 
 phenomena in animals, the more he inclined towards this 
 paradoxical conception. The perceptions of lower beings 
 ai-e infinitely minute, confused, and unconscious ; those of 
 man are clear and conscious : that is the entire difference 
 between soul and mind, perception and appercejytioti. 
 
 The perceptions of the monad do not, it is true, extend 
 beyond itself. Having no "windows by which anything 
 can enter or depart," it can only perceive itself. We our- 
 
 1 Blonadolof/ie, §§ 19, 66, 82. 
 
 2 Re'plique aux reflexions de Bayle, p. 186. 
 
 ^ Ad Des Bosses Epist. 111. : Necesse est omnes enielechias sive 
 monades perceptione prcediias esse. 
 * Lettre a M. des Maizeaux.
 
 LEIBNIZ 351 
 
 selves, the higher monads, do not perceive anything except 
 our own being, and that alone we know immediately. The 
 real world is wholly inaccessible to us, and the so-called 
 world is merely the involuntary projection of what takes 
 place within ourselves. If, notwithstanding, we know 
 what takes place outside of us, if we have an (indirect) per- 
 ception of the external world, it is because we are, like all 
 monads, representatives of the universe, and because, con- 
 sequently, that which takes place in us is the reproduction 
 in miniature of that which takes place on the large scale in 
 the macrocosm. Since the monad directly perceives itself 
 alone and its own contents, it follows that the more ade- 
 quate an image it is itself, the more complete will its per- 
 ception of the universe be. The better a monad represents 
 the universe, the better it represents itself. If the Imman 
 soul lias a clear and distinct idea of the world, it is because 
 it is a more exact and more faithful image {idea) of the 
 universe than the soul of the animal and the soul of the 
 plant.i 
 
 All monads represent and perceive, or, in a word, rei)ro- 
 duce the universe, but they reproduce it in different degrees, 
 and each in its own way. In other terms, there is a grada- 
 tion in the perfection of the monads. In the hierarchy thus 
 formed, the most perfect monads rule, the less perfect ones 
 o])ey. Accordingly, we must distinguish between physical 
 individuals, such as nature offers, and the metaphysical in- 
 dividuals or monads composing them. A plant or an animal 
 is not a monad and individual in the metaphysical sense, 
 but a comljination of monads, of which one rules and the 
 otliers obey. The central monad is \\hat is called tlie soul 
 of tlie plant, animal, or man; the subordinate monads 
 grouped around it form what we call body. " Each living 
 
 1 Replique aux reflexions de Bayle, ]>. IS I ; Munadologle, §§ 50-02 ; 
 Principes de la ualure el de Id fjruce, § -i.
 
 352 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 being," as Leibniz expressly states,^ " has a ruling entel- 
 echy, which is the soul in the animal, hut the memoers of 
 this living body are full of other living beings, — plants, 
 animals, — each of which has also its entelechy or govern- 
 ing soul." " Each monad," he also says,^ " is a mirror of 
 the universe, from its point of view, and accompanied by a 
 multitude of other monads composing its organic body, of 
 which it is the ruling monad." ^ 
 
 However, by virtue of the autonomy of the monads, this 
 dominating influence of the central monad is purely ideal ; 
 the latter does not really act upon the governed monads.* 
 The obedience of the governed monads is, in turn, quite 
 spontaneous. They do not subordinate themselves to the 
 ruling monad because this forces them to do so, but because 
 their own nature compels them to do it.^ In the formation of 
 organisms, the lower monads group themselves around the 
 more perfect monads, wliich, in turn, spontaneously group 
 themselves around the central monad. This process might 
 be compared to the construction of a temple in which the 
 columns spontaneously put themselves in the desired place, 
 with the capital pointing upwards and the pedestal at the 
 bottom. An inorganic body, a rock, or a liquid mass is 
 likewise an aggregation of monads, but witliout a ruling 
 monad. Such bodies are not inanimate ; for each of the 
 monads composing them is both soul and body ; but they 
 seem inanimate because their constitutive monads, being 
 of like nature, do not obey a governing monad, but hold 
 themselves in equilibrium, so to speak. 
 
 After these preliminaries, we expect Leibniz to solve the 
 
 1 Monadologle, § 70. ^ Lettre a M. Dangicourf, p. 746. 
 
 8 Extrait d'une lettre a M. Dangicoiirt, p. 746 ; Monadologie, § 70. 
 
 * Monadologie, § 51. 
 
 5 Ad Des Bosses Epist. XXX. : Substantia agit quantum potest, nisi 
 impediatur: impeditur autem etiam substantia simplex, sed naturaliter non 
 riisi intus a se ipsa.
 
 LEIBNIZ 353 
 
 problem of the reciprocal action of soul and body in the 
 simplest and easiest manner. Thought and extension are 
 not substances which repel and exclude each other, but dif- 
 ferent attributes of one and the same substance. Hence, 
 notliing seems more natural than to assume a direct con- 
 nection between intellectual phenomena and the facts of 
 the physiological world. That is not the case, however, 
 and the metaphysics of Leibniz finds itself as powerless as 
 Cartesianisn before this important problem. The connec- 
 tion just mentioned would be perfectly apparent if the 
 human individual were a single monad, having as its im- 
 material essence the soul, and as its sensible manifestation, 
 the body. If by body we meant the material element in- 
 herine- in the central monad (for it must be remembered 
 that each monad, and consequently also the central monad 
 or the liighest soul, is both soul and body), notliing would 
 be more proper than to speak of a mutual action between 
 soul and body. But, as we have just shown, the physical 
 individual is not an isolated monad, but a central monad 
 surrounded by other monads, and it is the latter, or tliis 
 group of subordinate souls, which, strictly speaking, con- 
 stitute the body of the individual. Now, the monads have 
 no windows ; witliin one and the same monad, the ruling 
 monad, for example, there may and must be a causal rela- 
 tion between its successive states; such a relation, how- 
 ever, is impossible between two different monads. 
 
 Hence a real and direct action of the dominant monad 
 upon the subordinate monad, or of soul upon body, is as 
 impossible in Leibniz's system as in that of Descartes. 
 Tills action is merely apparent. In sensation the soul 
 seems to suffer the influence of the body, and the parts of 
 tlie T)ody, in turn, move as thougli their movements were 
 determined by tlie volitions of the soul. As a matter of 
 fact, neither one imr 1h(; (.thor is affected by something ex- 
 ternal to it. No soul state, no volition, for example, can 
 
 S8
 
 354 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 " penetrate " the monads constituting the body ; hence the 
 soul does not act directly upon the body ; our arms are not 
 moved by an act of will. Nothing in the body can " pene- 
 trate " the dominant monad : hence, no impressions enter 
 the soul through the senses, but all our ideas are innate. 
 Body and soul seem to act on each other ; the former moves 
 when the latter wills it, the latter perceives and conceives 
 when the former receives a physical impression, and this is 
 due to a i^re-estahlished harmony, owing to which the monads 
 constituting the body and the ruling monad necessarily 
 agree, just as two perfectly regulated clocks always show 
 the same time.^ 
 
 The theory of pre-established harmony differs from the 
 occasionalistic system in an important point. The latter 
 assumes a special divine intervention every time the soul 
 and the physical organism are to agree. God regulates the 
 soul by the body or the body by the volitions of the soul, as 
 a watchmaker constantly regulates one clock by the other. 
 According to Leibniz, the harmony between the movements 
 of the body and the states of the soul is the effect of the 
 Creator's perfect work, as the perpetual agreement between 
 two well-constructed watches results from the skill of the 
 mechanic who has constructed them. Those who assume 
 that the Creator constantly intervenes in his work, regard 
 God as an unskilful watchmaker, who cannot make a per- 
 fect machine, but must continually repair what he has 
 made. Not only does God not intervene at every moment, 
 but he never intervenes. " Mr. Newton and his followers," 
 says Leibniz,^ '' have a curious opinion of God and his work. 
 According to them, God must wind up his watch from time 
 to time ; otherwise it would cease to move. He had not 
 sufficient insight to make it run forever. Nay, God's 
 
 1 Second eclaircissemenf du systeme de la communication des substances, 
 pp. 133-134. 
 
 * Lettre a Clarke, p. 746.
 
 LEIBNIZ 
 
 365 
 
 machine is so imperfect, according to them, that he is 
 obliged to clean it, from time to time, by an extraordinary 
 concourse, and even to repair it as a watchmaker repairs 
 his work ; the oftener he is obliged to mend it and to set it 
 right, the poorer a mechanic he is." ..." According to 
 my system, bodies act as if there were no souls, and souls 
 act as if there were no bocUes, and both act as if each influ- 
 enced the other." ^ 
 
 Perhaps,^ from the theological point of view, Leibniz's 
 theory of pre-established harmony is preferable to the hy- 
 pothesis of the assistance or perpetual concourse of God, 
 but it does not satisfy the curiositij of the philosopher any 
 more than does the Cartesian theory. To say that body and 
 soul agree in their respective states by virtue of a pre-estab- 
 lished harmony is to say that a thing is because it is. Leib- 
 niz conceals his ignorance behind a science that rises above 
 all the theories of the past. When we consider how ex- 
 travagantly Leibniz's friends and Leibniz himself eulogized 
 his system, we hardly know what to wonder at most, the 
 delusion of our philosopher or the simplicity of his ad- 
 mirers. 
 
 We have found, with Leibniz, that monads reflect the 
 universe in different degrees ; that some monads reflect it 
 better than others. This pre-supposes the existence of a 
 lowest monad, which reproduces the universe in the most 
 elementary manner possible, and a highest monad, which 
 expresses it in a perfect manner : a positive and a superla- 
 tive. Between these two extremes we have an iniinite 
 
 ^ Monadologie, § 81. 
 
 2 We say perhaps ; for tlie o1)j<'cti()n may l>e urged against Leibniz 
 that tlie pfTpetual miracle of the Cartesians is not a miracle in the 
 sense that the natural course of things is violently interrupted, and 
 that it is not a miracle' precisely because it is perpetual. From this 
 point of view, pre-esta])lished harmony, a miracle i-frfurnicd once for 
 all, at the beginning of things, is a concept i.ni plilldsopiiically inferior 
 to the Cartesian hypothesis.
 
 356 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 chain of intermediate monads. Each intermediate monad 
 forms a different point, and, consequently, a different j^oint 
 of view, on the line connecting the extremes ; each, as such, 
 differs from all the rest. But the monads are infuiite in 
 number. Hence we have on tlie ideal line between the 
 lowest and the highest monad, i. e., on a line that is limited 
 on all sides and is not infinite, an infinity of different points 
 of view. Fiom this it follows that the distances separating 
 these points of view are infinitely small, that the difference 
 between two adjacent monads is imperceptible (discrimen 
 indiscernible). 
 
 The 'principle of continuity'^ removes the gaps which 
 are supposed to exist between the mineral and vegeta- 
 ble kingdoms, and the vegetable and animal kingdoms.^ 
 There are no gaps, no absolute oppositions in nature ; rest 
 is an infinitely minute movement ; darkness, infinitely 
 little light; the parabola, an ellipse one of whose foci is 
 infinitely distant ; perception in the plant, an infinitely con- 
 fused thought.^ This conception bridges the chasm which 
 the Cartesians made between brutes and man. Brutes are 
 merely imperfect men, plants imperfect animals. Leibniz 
 does not, however, regard man as a product of evolution. 
 Far from it. Each monad remains eternally what it is, and 
 the soul of the plant cannot therefore be transformed into 
 an animal soul, nor an animal soul into a human soul. But 
 his doctrine of the pre-existence of monads, and his teach- 
 ing that they develop indefinitely, logically culminate in 
 the theory of transformation. " I recognize," he writes * 
 to Des Maizeaux,^ " that not onl}^ the souls of brutes, but 
 all monads or simple substances from which the composite 
 phenomena are derived are as old as the world ; " and a 
 
 1 Tht'odicee, § 348. 2 i^ff^e IV. a M. Bourguet. 
 
 ' Noureaux exaah. Preface. * Erdmann's edition, p. 676. 
 
 ^ The biographer of Bayle and editor of his Dictionnaire historique 
 et critique.
 
 LEIBNIZ 357 
 
 few lines above he says : '' I believe that the souls of men 
 have pre-existed, not as reasonable souls hut as merely sensi- 
 tive souls, wliich did not reach the superior stage of reason 
 until the man whom the soul was to animate was conceived." 
 The view that man pre-existed in the animal could not be 
 stated with greater clearness. It even seems as though 
 Leibniz's " souls " pre-exist in the inorganic world, like so 
 many germs. In its state of pre-existence, he saj^s, in sub- 
 stance, the monad which is to become a soul is ahsolutely 
 7iaked,^ or without a bod}- ; that is to say, it is not sur- 
 rounded by that group of subordinate monads which will 
 form its organs, and, consequently, exists in a kind of un- 
 conscious state. Hence, the monads destined to become 
 either animal or human souls wholly resemble inanimate 
 bodies, from the beginning of the world until they are in- 
 corporated. 
 
 The passage of the monads into Ixxlies (incarnation) can- 
 not be conceived as a metempsychosis or a metasomatosis, 
 if we mean by these two terms the introduction of the soul 
 into a body formed without its assistance. Nor can future 
 life be considered in such a light. By virtue of the law of 
 pi'e-establislied harmony, the development of the soul runs 
 parallel with that of the body, and althougli there is no real 
 and immediate communion Ijctween the central monad and 
 the subordinate monads constituting its body, there is an 
 ideal correlation between the latter and the soul. With the 
 reservation made above,^ it is correct to call the soul the 
 architect of the body. A soul cannot give itself any body 
 whatsoever, nor can any Ijody serve as its organ.^ Each 
 soul has its body. But though there is no metempsychosis, 
 i. e., no passage of souls into bodies already foiincd, there 
 
 ' Manndologiey § 24. 
 2 p. :}r,2. 
 
 • This expression can only he nsfd in a figurative sense by Lcil>niz 
 for there is no actiuil relation between body and soul.
 
 358 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 is metainorphosis, and perpetual metamorpliosis.i The soul 
 changes its body only gradually and by degrees. 2 Owing 
 to the principle of continuity, nature never makes leaps, 
 but there are insensible transitions everywhere and in 
 everything. 
 
 Future life cannot be incorporeal. Human souls and 
 all other souls are never without bodies ; God alone, being 
 pure action, is wholly without body. Since the central 
 monad is " primitive " like all monads, it cannot be created 
 ex nihilo upon its entrance into actual life, nor annihilated 
 at its departure. " What Ave call generation is development 
 or increase ; what we call death is envelopment and dim- 
 inution. Strictly speaking, there is neither generation nor 
 death, and it may be said, that not only is the soul inde- 
 structible, but also the animal itself, although its machine 
 is often partially" destroyed." ^ As regards rational souls, 
 it may be assumed that they will pass " to a grander scene 
 of action " at the close of their present life. Moreover, their 
 immortality is not the result of a i3articular divine favor or 
 a privilege of human nature, but a metaphysical necessity, 
 a universal phenomenon embracing all the realms of nature. 
 Just as each monad is as old as the world, so, too, each one 
 " is as durable, as stable, and as absolute as the universe of 
 creatures itself."^ The plant and the grub are no less 
 eternal than man, the angels, and the archangels.^ Death 
 is but a turning-point in the eternal life, a stage in the 
 never-ending development of the monad. 
 
 1 Principes de la nature et de la grace, § 6. 
 
 2 Monadologie, § 72. « Id., §§ 73, 77. 
 
 * Nouveau aystbne de la nature, § 16. 
 
 * Ad Wagnerian, p. 467: Qui hrutis animas,aliisque mater ice partibus 
 omnem perceptionem et organismum negant, illi divinain majestatem non 
 satis agnoscunt, iniroducentes aliqidd indignum Deo et incultum, nempe 
 vacuum metaphysicum . . . Qui vero animas veras perceptionemque dant 
 hrutis, et tamen animas eorum naturaliter perire posse statuunt, etiam de- 
 monstrationem nobis tollunt, per quam ostenditur mentes Jiostras naturaliter 
 perire non posse.
 
 LEIBNIZ 359 
 
 In the system of Leibniz we again find Spinoza's ex- 
 tended and thinking substance ; but here it appears as the 
 force of extension and perception, and is multiplied infin- 
 itely. We likewise meet liis notion of mode and his de- 
 terminism, but this is softened by the doctrine of the 
 substantiality of individuals. In spite of its absolute 
 identity, the monad develops continually. Our author 
 takes it " for granted that every being, and consequently 
 the created monad also, is subject to change, and even that 
 this change is continual in each."^ The soul, like the 
 body, is in a state of change, tendency, and appetition. 
 This perpetual change is called life. Each of these states 
 composing it is the logical consequence of the preceding 
 state and the source of the following state. "As every 
 present state of a simple substance is naturally a conse- 
 quence of its preceding state, so its present is big with the 
 future." 2 
 
 Hence, freedom of indifference is out of the question in 
 the human soul. In the system of Leibniz, each substance 
 or monad is free in the same sense as Spinoza's unitary sub- 
 stance ; i. e., it is not determined by any power outside of 
 itself. But though not determined from without, it is not 
 on that account independent of its own nature, free in 
 reference to itself. The determinism of Leibniz is to that 
 of Spinoza what the determinism of St. Thomas is to the 
 predestination of St. Augustine. It allows each spirit to be 
 " as it were, a little divinity in its own department," and 
 so softens the element in fatalism whiih is objectiona1)le to 
 the moral sense, without, however, ceasing to apply the 
 law of causality and the principle of sufficient reason to 
 botli the physical and moral realms. "• 1 am very far 
 removed," lie says, '"• from accepting the views of Hrad- 
 wardine, Wiclif, Hobbes, and Spinoza, but we must always 
 bear witness to tlie truth,"-' and lliis trutli is autcMiomous 
 
 1 MoHudologie, § 10. ^ /,/.^ § -jl'. « T/icudicce, !I.
 
 360 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 determinism : nothing determines the acts of the soul ex- 
 cept the soul itself and its preceding acts. 
 
 If each monad is, " as it were, a little divinity in its own 
 department," if each is a little absolute, what is the highest 
 Divinity, the real absolute? If we were to judge from 
 what we now know of the theory of monads, we should 
 reply : Leibniz substitutes for the monotheism of Descartes 
 and the pantheism of Spinoza a kind of polytheism, for the 
 monarchical conception of the universe, a kind of cosmical 
 republic governed by the law of harmony. But, though that 
 may be his secret thought, it is not his exoteric doctrine. 
 The harmony which governs the universe is a harmony 
 pre-established hij God : it is not itself the absolute. The 
 monads, which " are the true atoms of nature and the ele- 
 ments of things," 1 are none the less created.^ They are 
 indestructible, but a miracle can destroy them.^ That is 
 to say, they are neither absolutely primitive and eternal, 
 nor, in a word, the absolute ; but they depend on a divin- 
 ity, " the primitive unity or the original simple substance, 
 of which all monads, created or derived, are the pro- 
 ducts, and are born, so to speak, from moment to moment, 
 by continual fulgurations of the Divinity." * Hence, we 
 have created monads on the one hand, and an uncreated 
 monad, the Monad of monads, on the other ; the former are 
 finite and relative ; the latter is infinite and absolute. 
 
 This Monad of monads is not, like Bruno's, the universe 
 itself considered as infinite ; it is a real God, that is, a God 
 distinct from the universe. Leibniz proves his existence 
 by the principle of sufficient reason. " This sufficient 
 reason for the existence of the universe cannot be found in 
 the succession of contingent things, that is, of bodies and 
 their representations in souls ; because matter being indif- 
 ferent in itself to motion and to rest, and to this or that 
 
 1 Monad ologie, § 3. '^ Id., § 47. 
 
 3 Id., § 6. * Id., § 47.
 
 LEIBXIZ 361 
 
 motion, we cannot find the reason of motion in it, and still 
 less of a particular motion. And although tlie present 
 motion which is in matter comes from the preceding mo- 
 tion, and this, in turn, from one preceding it, we do not 
 advance one step though we go ever so far ; for the same 
 question always remains. Thus, it is necessary that the 
 sufficient reason, which has no further need of another 
 reason, be outside of this series of contingent tilings, and 
 be found in a substance which is their cause, or which is a 
 necessary being, having the reason of its existence in itself, 
 otherwise we should still have no sufficient reason at which 
 to stop. And this ultimate reason of things is called God. 
 This simj)le primitive substance must contain in itself 
 eminently the perfections contained in the derivative sub- 
 stances wliich are its effects ; hence it will have perfect 
 power, knowledge, and will, that is, it will have omnipo- 
 tence, omniscience, and supreme goodness." ^ Although 
 Leibniz protests against anthropomorphism, he speaks of 
 God as having " chosen the best possible j^lan in creating the 
 universe, . . . and, above all, the laws of movement best 
 adjusted and most conformable to abstract or metaphysical 
 reasons." . . . Such, for example, by virtue of which " the 
 same quantity of total and absolute force is always pre- 
 served in it," and that other law by virtue of which 
 " action and reaction are always equal." ^ 
 
 The difiiculty confronting the Leibnizian theology is the 
 same as that which meets Descartes. The latter had to 
 confess that the word ''substance " when apj)lied to God has 
 not the same meaning as when applied to the creature, and, 
 consequently, that the creature is not a substance in the 
 true sense : a statement wliicli occasioned the system of 
 Spinoza. Leil^niz's theology, too, seems to be cauglit on 
 the horns of a dilemma : Either God is a monad, and in that 
 
 ' Principes de la nature ef <le In rjr/lce, §§ 8, 9. 
 2 Id., §§ 10, 11. Cf. Thtodicee, III., § 315.
 
 362 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 case finite beings are not monads in the strict sense of the 
 term (which overthrows the monadology) ; or, created be- 
 ings are monads, and then we cannot call God a monad 
 unless we identify him with his creatures. But the pliant 
 and cautious genius of a Leibniz turns to account even his 
 defeats. Though the idea of God is confused and contra- 
 dictory for our intelligence, it is not so in itself. The fact 
 that we are confronted with insoluble difficulties in contem- 
 plating the absolute, simply proves that the human soul is 
 not the Monad of monads, — that it occupies a distinguished 
 but not the highest place in the scale of substances. Hence, 
 it must follow from the very nature of things that we can 
 have only a confused notion of the Supreme Being. Just 
 as the plant has a confused perception of the animal, and 
 the animal a confused perception of man, so, too, man has 
 only an indistinct perception and a faint inkling of higher 
 beings and the Supreme Being. In order to have an ade- 
 quate notion of God, one would have to be God, and the 
 fact that we have no such notion finds its natural explana- 
 tion in the transcendency of the Supreme Being. God is 
 supernatural or transcendent in relation to man, as man is 
 a supernatural being with respect to animals, the animal a 
 supernatural being with respect to plants, and so on. If 
 we mean by reason the human understanding, God is also 
 supra-rational in so far as he surpasses human nature (or is 
 supernatural) ; that is, he transcends human intelligence as 
 much as his perfection surpasses ours. 
 
 We see with what skill the philosopher of universal 
 conciliation acquits himself of his task as a mediator be- 
 tween science and Christianity. Unlike the English phi- 
 losophers, his contemporaries, who in true nominalistic 
 fashion endeavor to separate religion and philosophy, he 
 begins the work of St. Anselm and St. Thomas all over 
 again on a different plan. His highest ambition is to form 
 an alliance between philosophy and faith, and, if possible,
 
 LEIBNIZ 363 
 
 between Lutlieranism and Catholicism. He adopts the 
 motto of the Schoohnen : Absolute agreement between the 
 dogmas of the Church and human reason. ^ He antagonizes 
 those who distinguish between pliilosopliical truth and re- 
 ligious truth, — a distinction which saved the freethinkers 
 of the Renaissance from anathema, — and he finds fault 
 wdth Descartes for having cleverly evaded the discussion of 
 the mysteries of faith, as though one could hold a philos- 
 ophy that is irreconcilable with religion, or as though a 
 reliirion could be true that contradicts truths otherwise 
 proved.^ 
 
 Behind liis seeming orthodoxy, however, we may easily 
 detect the traces of his rationalism. When he proclaims 
 theism he does so in the name of philosophy ; when he 
 affirms the supernatural he does it in the name of reason, 
 and, to a certain extent, by means of rationalism. He is so 
 far removed from assuming the absolute transcendency of 
 the divine being, as to hold that what transcends human 
 reason cannot contradict reason. Like the ancient School- 
 men before him, he continues to remind us that whatever is 
 above reason is not therefore against reason, that whatever 
 is decidedly contradictory to reason cannot be true in reli- 
 gion. By virtue of the law of universal analogy, there must 
 be an analogy, an agreement, a harmony, between divine 
 reason and human reason ; and a radical opposition between 
 the Creator and tlie creature is not conceivable. Owing to 
 this agreement, man naturally possesses faith in God and in 
 the immortality of tlie soul, these two central doctrines of 
 all religion ; and revelation simply helps to bring out the 
 
 1 Xotliiiig better characterizes the essentially scholastic tendency 
 of Leibniz than the followinff title of one of his last compositions : The 
 Principles of Nature and of Grace, Founded on Reason (1711), and this 
 other title ; Discourse on the Conformity of Faith with Reason (Intro- 
 duction to the Theodicy). 
 
 2 De vero methodo philosophioi et Iheologiie, p. 111.
 
 364 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 truths whicli have been implanted in the human mind by 
 the Creator. Christianity is evidently reduced to the narrow 
 proportions of deism in the system of Leibniz, and revela- 
 tion becomes a mere sanction of the principles of natural 
 religion. 
 
 But, how could a thinker who held that souls have " no 
 windows through which any tiling can enter or pass out " 
 do otherwise than favor theological rationalism ; how could 
 he seriously declare that the soul is enlightened by a super- 
 natural revelation ? How could the man who laughed 
 at Newton and the Cartesians for assuming that God in- 
 terferes with the world, really assume a special interven- 
 tion of God in history? If we believe in revelation, we 
 must also assume that God has given or can give to the 
 soul the means of communicating with the external world, 
 or windows, to use Leibniz's expression. Now, if God can 
 give windows to the intelligent monad, then it is not con- 
 trary to its nature to have them, — then it can have them. 
 Tliis means that it can cease to be an absolutely spontane- 
 ous force or an absolute ruler in its domain ; it means, in a 
 word, that it ceases to be a monad. Leibniz must choose 
 between two alternatives : he must either accept the theory 
 of monads and pre-established harmony, which, according 
 to his explicit declaration, ^ excludes all special divine in- 
 tervention, or abandon his system in favor of the faith of 
 the Church. 
 
 The author of the Theodicy^ like St. Thomas, subordinates 
 the will of God to the divine reason and its eternal laws. 
 This is a characteristic trait of Leibnizian rationalism, and 
 contrary to the doctrines of Descartes and his teachers, the 
 Scotists and the Jesuits, according to whom not only meta- 
 phj^sical and moral truths, but even mathematical axioms, 
 depend on the divine will. " It must not be imagined," he 
 says,^ " as is sometimes done, that the eternal truths which 
 
 ^ Principes de la nature et de la grdce, § 13. ^ Monadologie, § 46
 
 LEIBNIZ 365 
 
 are dependent on God are arbitrary and depend on liis will, 
 as Descartes and afterward M. Poiret ^ seem to have be- 
 lieved. . . . Nothing could be more unreasonable. . . . For 
 if the establishment of justice (for example) happened arbi- 
 trarily and without reason, if God hit upon it haphazard, 
 as we draw lots, then his goodness and wisdom are not 
 revealed in it, and it does not bind him. And if he es- 
 tablished or made what we call justice and goodness by a 
 purely arbitrary decree and without reason, he, can unmake 
 thciii and chanye their nature, so that we have no reason to 
 suppose that he will observe them always. ... It is no 
 more contrary to reason and piety to say (with Spinoza) 
 that God acts Avithout knowledge, than to claim that his 
 knowledge does not find the eternal rides of goodness and of 
 justiee among its objects ; or finally, that he has a will which 
 has no regard for these rules." ^ 
 
 Hence, the God of Leibniz is not like an Oriental mon- 
 arch ; he is a sovereign bound by laws which he cannot un- 
 make, a kind of constitutional king and chief executive of 
 the universe, rather than the all-powerful autocrat of Ter- 
 tullian and Duns Scotus. He resembles the God of Mon- 
 tesquieu, who " has his laws," rather than the God of the 
 indeterministic theologians. The supreme power is not 
 the will of God taken hy itself, but his will governed by the 
 eternal laws of his intelligence, laws which determine his 
 conduct without constraining him, since they constitute the 
 very essence of his nature. Instead of the nature of God, 
 Spinoza simply said nature. According to Leibniz, the 
 Supreme Being is nature manifesting itself through the 
 
 1 A pastor at Ilamlmrg, a native of Metz (1040-1710). Against 
 the theory of innnte ideas of his sometime teacher Descartes, and 
 Locke's theory of acquired ideas, he sets up liis mystical tlicory of in- 
 fused ideas, that is, ideas communicated by an inspiration from on high 
 {CEconomie divine, 7 vols., Amsterdam, 1687 ; etc.). 
 
 2 Thtodice'e, II., 170-177.
 
 ^QQ MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 medium of a personal will ; according to Spinoza, he is na- 
 ture acting without such a medium ; or, if we choose, an 
 unconscious will. Hence, both thinkers are determinists, 
 however violently Leibniz may protest against the teachings 
 of the Jew of Amsterdam. 
 
 In creating things, God was determined by his infinite 
 reason, and necessarily created the best possible world. 
 Evil exists only in the details, and serves to enhance the 
 glory of the good : the whole is supremely perfect. The 
 Tlieodicy deals with the question of physical, metaphysical, 
 and moral evil, and aims to refute those who regard the ex- 
 istence of evil as an argument against Providence. It is a 
 popular rather than a scientific book. It is surprising with 
 what familiarity the author speaks of God, just as though 
 God had initiated him into the innermost secrets of his 
 nature. How can Leibniz, who has such certain knowledge 
 that God is not the free author of the natural and moral 
 law s, that his will depends on his intelligence, that he neces- 
 sarily created the best possible world, maintain that God is 
 supra-rational ? What a strange procedure ! First he rele- 
 gates the Being of Beings to the domain of mystery, like so 
 many theologians, and then he defines him, describes him, 
 and makes out a complete inventory of his attributes, as 
 though he were describing a plant or a mineral. For this 
 reason as well as on account of his attitude towards empir- 
 icism, Leibniz, whose monadology is so great, so original, 
 and so modern, still belongs to the tribe of the Schoolmen. 
 
 But the time had now come for subjecting ontology to 
 the critical sif ting-process. The controversy between Leib- 
 niz and the Englishman Locke concerning the origin of 
 ideas formed the prelude to an important epoch in the his- 
 tory of modern philosophy. 
 
 In view of his principle " that the monad has no w^in- 
 dows," Leibniz cannot grant that our knowledge has any 
 other source than the soul itself. Nothing can enter it;
 
 LEIBNIZ 367 
 
 hence, strictly speaking, tlie direct observation of external 
 facts or experience is impossible. Experience through the 
 mecUum of the senses is an illusion ; it is, in realit}', noth- 
 ing but confused thought. He repeatedly declares that the 
 soul, and the soul alone, is both the subject and the ob- 
 ject of sensation. We never perceive and experience any- 
 thing but ourselves. Everything in the mind is spontane- 
 ous production, thought, oi- speculation. Whether we shall 
 regard our thought as the result of an impression from with- 
 out, or as the product of the mind itself, will depend on 
 its degree of clearness or confusion. Thought, however, 
 though autonomous, is not arbitrary and free from law. It 
 obeys the sovereign laws of contradiction and sufficient 
 reason. But it does not depend on anything external to 
 the thinking monad, around which the principium dis- 
 tinctionis rises like an impassable wall. Leibniz also 
 declares, in answer to Locke's denial of innate ideas, ^ 
 that nothing is inborn in the understanding except the 
 understanding itself, and, consequently, the germ of all 
 our ideas.'-^ 
 
 The difference between Leibniz and Locke seems very 
 slight : Locke by no means denies the innate power of the 
 mind to form ideas, while Leibniz grants that ideas do not 
 pre-exist in the mind aetualhj ; they exist in it virtually, as 
 the veins in a block of marble might mark the outlines of a 
 statue to be made from it. Now, then, either the ex})ression, 
 virtual or potential existence of ideas in the mind, has no 
 meaning, or it is s^-nonymous with power (potent in, rii'tus'), 
 or mental faculty of forming ideas, a faculty wliich Locke 
 is perfectly willing to admit. lUit this seemingly insig- 
 nilieant controversy really represented (he opposition l)c- 
 
 * Essay concernrng Human Understanding, cli. I. 
 
 2 Nouveaux essais, I'rcfaco : Nous sommes inncs d nous memes pour 
 ainsi dire ; id., II., 1 : Nihil est in intellectu quod nonfuerit in sensu, ex- 
 cipe : nisi ipse intellectus.
 
 368 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 tween the Middle Ages and modern philosophy, between the 
 speculative method, which passes from conceptions to facts, 
 and the positive method, which passes from facts to concep- 
 tions. Locke does not merely combat the idealistic princi- 
 ple ; what he especially antagonizes is the idealistic prejudice 
 that a 2Jriori reasoning relieves the philosopher of the duty 
 of directly observing facts. By declaring himself against 
 the author of the Essay concerning Human Understanding^ 
 Leibniz, who was otherwise more profound and more specu- 
 lative than his opponent, sided with the School, that is, with 
 the past against the future. 
 
 All that was necessary was to present his doctrines 
 in scholastic form. This the mathematician Christian 
 Wolff 1 proceeded to do. The Leibnizian system con- 
 tained a precious gem : the conception of active force, 
 which had superseded the dualism of thought and exten- 
 sion, and this treasure was lost in the labored attempts of 
 the professor of Halle to remodel the system. This clear 
 and systematic but narrow-minded thinker revived the ex- 
 tended and thinking substances of Cartesianism, without 
 even suspecting that he was thereby destroying the cen- 
 tral and really fruitful notion of the Monadology. Thus 
 altered and divided into rational ontology, psychology, 
 cosmology, and theology, the Leibniz-Wolffian metaphys- 
 
 1 1679-1754:. Professor at the University of Halle, from which the 
 influence of the Pietists succeeded in removing him. He was recalled 
 by Frederick II. Latin works : Oratio de Sinariim philosophia, Halle, 
 1726; Philosophia radonnlis sive logica methodo scientijica pertracta, 
 Frankfort and Leipsic, 1728 ; Philosophia prima s. ontologia, id., 1730 , 
 Cosmologia generalis, id., 1731; Psychologia empirica, id., 1732; Psy- 
 chologia rationalis, id., 1734; Theologia naturalis, 1730-37 ; Jus natures, 
 1740; Philosophia moralis sice ethica, Halle, 1750; Philosophia civilis 
 sive politica, id., 1746; Jus gentium, 1750; and a large number of 
 treatises in the German language. [See, on AVolff and his school, 
 Zeller, Die deutsche Philosophie seit Leibniz, 2d ed., Munich, 1875, 
 pp. 172 ff.]
 
 LEIBNIZ 369 
 
 ics dominated the German schools until the advent of 
 Kantianism.^ 
 
 1 The principal disciples of the Leibniz- Wolffian school are : Ludo- 
 vici (A usfukrlicher Entwurf einer vollsldmlifjen Hislorie der wolffischen 
 Pliilosophie, 3 vols., Leipsic, 1736-38) ; Billinger (1(393-1750), author 
 of numerous and lucid commentaries on the philosophy of Leibniz 
 and Woltf ; Thumniing {Inst'Uutiones ph'dosophke Wolffiance, etc.) ; Baum- 
 garten (1714-1762), who, in his jEsthetica (2 vols,, 1750-58), adds 
 the theory of the beautiful in art, or cesthetics, to the philosophical 
 sciences, etc. Kant himself was a disciple of Wolff before he became 
 his adversary, and the numerous representatives of the German Auf- 
 Uarung, which preceded the appearance of the Critiques, were related 
 to Wolff (Reimarus, Moses Mendelssohn, Lessing, Nicolai, etc.). [See 
 R. Sommer, GrundzUge einer Geschichte der deutschen Psycliolorjie und 
 JEsthelik, etc., Wiirzburg, 1892, and Dessoir's work, supra, p. 15.] 
 
 M
 
 SECOND PERIOD 
 
 AGE or CRITICISM 
 
 § 57. Jolin Locke 
 
 The author of the work criticised by Leibniz, John 
 Locke/ was born at Wrington in Somersetsliire. A fel- 
 low-countryman of Occam and tlie two Bacons, he shows 
 the anti-mystical and positivistic tendencies common to 
 English philosophy. The study of medicine revealed to 
 him the barrenness of scholastic learning. What, in his 
 opinion, perpetuated the traditions of a jjriori speculation 
 and the ignorance of reality, was the Platonic doctrine of 
 innate metaphysical, moral, and religious truths, teachings 
 which Ralph Cud worth ^ and Descartes himself had 
 
 1 1G32-1704. Complete works, London, 17U ff. ; 9 vols., id., 1853 ; 
 philosophical works, ed. by St. John, 2 vols., London, 1854. Next 
 to his Essay concerning Human Understanding, his most important 
 work is Thoughts on Education, London, 1693; in French, Amster- 
 dam, 1705. [Lord King, Life of Locke, London, 1829 ; H. R. Fox 
 Bourne, The Life of John Locke, 2 vols., London, 1876] ; V. Cousin, 
 La philosophie de Locke, 6th ed., Paris, 1863; [A. de Fries, Die Sid?- 
 stanzenlehre John Locke's, etc., Bremen, 1879; Th. Fowler, Locke {Eng' 
 lish Men of Letters), London, 1880;- A. C. Fraser, Locke {Blackwood's 
 Philosophical Classics), Edinburgh, 1890; M. M. Curtis, An Outline of 
 Locke's Ethical Philosophy, Leipsic, 1890 ; G. v. Hertling, John Locke 
 und die Schide von Cambridge, Freiburg i. B., 1892; Marion, /. Locke, 
 Paris, 1893. See also T. H. Green's Introduction to Hume and the 
 works pertaining to both Locke and Leibniz, mentioned under 
 " Leibniz." — Tr.] 
 
 2 1617-1688. In his chief work, The True Intellectual System of 
 the Universe (London, 1678), he combats the materialistic conclusions
 
 JOHN LOCKE 371 
 
 undertaken to defend. The fact is, if truth is native to 
 the mind, it is useless to search for it outside by observation 
 and experimentation. Then we may, by means of a iniori 
 speculation, meditation, and reasoning, evolve it from our 
 own inner consciousness, as the spider spins its web out of 
 itself. This hypothesis Descartes consistently carries out 
 when he " closes his eyes and stops his ears," and abstracts 
 from everytliing acquired by the senses ; but he ceases to 
 be consistent when he assiduously devotes himself to the 
 study of anatomy and physiology. Indeed, the favorite 
 method of the metaphysics of the monasteries and univer- 
 sities was to close one's eyes, to stop one's ears, and to 
 ignore the real world. This method prevailed as long as 
 the conviction existed that our ideas have their source 
 within us. Hence, it was necessary, in order to make the 
 philosophers " open their eyes to the real world," to prove 
 to them that all our ideas come to us from without, through 
 the medium of sensation : it was necessary to demonstrate 
 that our ideas are not innate but acquired. 
 
 This Locke undertook to do in his Essay concerning 
 Human Understanding ^ (London, 1690), A\hich, witli im- 
 portant additions by the author, \^'as translated into French 
 by Coste (1700). This great work marks the beginning of 
 a series of investigations Avhich were completed by Kant's 
 Critique. Locke's aim is : (1) to discover what is the origin 
 of our ideas ; (2) to show what is the certainty, the evi- 
 dence, and the extent of our knowledge ; (3) to compel 
 
 of Thomas Ilobbes witli tlie system of Christianized Platoiiism, whicli 
 also influenced men like Maleliranche, I.ei])niz, I'onnet, and Herder. 
 [See C. E. Lowrey, The Philosnp/ii/ of Ralph Cudworlh, New York, 
 1S85.] 
 
 * [Edited, collated, and annotated by A. C. Eraser, 2 vols., New 
 York, 1894 ; J. E. Russel, The Philono})h>/ of Lode in Extracts from 
 the ICs.sat/, etc. {Series of Modern Philosophers), New York, 1891. 
 -Th.]
 
 372 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 philosophy to abandon what surpasses human comprehen- 
 sion lij clearly marking the limits of its capacity} 
 
 We have no innate knowledge : such is his revolutionary 
 doctrine against idealism. 
 
 As it is evident that new-born children, idiots, and even 
 the o-reat part of illiterate men, have not the least appre- 
 hension of the axioms alleged to be innate, the advocates 
 of innate ideas are obliged to assume that the mind can 
 have ideas without being conscious of them.^ But to say, 
 a notion is imprinted on the mind, and at the same time to 
 maintain that the mind is ignorant of it, is to make this 
 impression nothing. If these words, to he in the under- 
 standing, have any positive meaning, they signify to he per- 
 ceived and to he understood hy the understanding : hence, if 
 any one asserts that a thing is in the understanding, and 
 that it is not understood l)y the understanding, and that it 
 is in the mind without being perceived by the mind, it 
 amounts to saying that a thing is and is not in the under- 
 standing. 
 
 The knowledge of soine ideas, it is true, is very early 
 in the mind. But if we will observe, we shall find that 
 these kinds of truths are made up of acquired and not of 
 innate truths.^ It is by degrees that we acquire ideas, 
 that we learn the terms which are employed to express 
 them, and that we come to understand their true connec- 
 tion.'* The universal consent of mankind to certain truths 
 does not prove that these are innate ; for nobody knows 
 these truths till he hears them from others. For, if they 
 
 1 Essay, Book I., ch. I., Introduction. 
 
 2 Thus Leibniz speaks of unconscious perception, and Leibniz is 
 right, notwithstanding the English philosopher's objections. His 
 only mistake consists in his failure to recognize that the unconscious 
 perceptions need some external solicitation in order to become con- 
 scious, which, however, his preconceptions will not allow him to 
 assume. 
 
 3 Book I., ch. IL, 5, 15. * Id., 15.
 
 JOHN LOCKE 873 
 
 were innate, " wliat need they be ]3roposed to gain assent ? " 
 An innate and unknown truth is a contradiction in terms. 
 
 The principles of morals are no more innate than the 
 rest, unless we so call the desire for liappiness and the aver- 
 sion to misery, which are, indeed, innate tendencies, but 
 which are not the expressions of some truth engraven on 
 the understanding.^ In this field universal consent cannot 
 be invoked in any case ; for moral ideas vary from nation 
 to nation, from religion to religion. The keeping of con- 
 tracts, for example, is without dispute one of the most un- 
 deniable duties in morality. But, if you ask a Christian, 
 who believes in rewards and punishments after this life, 
 why a man should keep his word, he will give this as a 
 reason : Because God, who has the power of eternal life and 
 death, requires it of us. But if a Hobbist be asked why, 
 he will answer. Because the public requires it, and the 
 Leviathan Avill punish you if you do not. Finally, a pagan 
 philosopher Avould have answered that the violation of a 
 promise was dishonest, unworthy of the excellence of man, 
 and contrary to his vocation, which is perfect virtue. 
 
 The fact is urged against Locke that conscience re- 
 proaches us for the breach of the rules of morality. But 
 conscience is nothing else but our own ojnnion of our otvii 
 actions,^ and if cons(;ience were a proof of the existence of 
 innate principles, these principles could be contrary to each 
 other, since some persons do, for conscience's sake, wliat 
 others avoid for the same reason. Do not the savages prac- 
 tise enormities without the sliglitest remorse ? Tlie break- 
 ing of a moral rule is undoubtedly no argument that it is 
 unknown. But it is impossible to conceive that a Avholc 
 nation of men sliould all pul)licly reject what every one of 
 them certainly and infallibly knew to be a moral law. No 
 practical rule which is auywliere transgressed bi/ general 
 consent can be regardiMl as innate. I'o ln'M that tlie prac- 
 1 c. 111,3. ■' Id.,^.
 
 374 MODERN THILOSOrHY 
 
 tical principles are innate is to declare all moral education 
 impossible. 
 
 That does not mean that there are only positive laws. 
 There is a great deal of difference between an innate law 
 and a law of nature, between a truth originally imprinted 
 on our minds and a truth which we are ignorant of, but 
 may attain to the knowledge of by the use and due applica- 
 tion of our natural faculties. Furthermore, consider the 
 origin of a host of doctrines which pass as indubitable 
 axioms : though derived from no other source than the su- 
 perstition of a nurse or the authority of an old woman, they 
 often grow up, by length of time and consent of neighbors, 
 to the dignity of principles in religion and morality. The 
 mind of the child receives the impressions Avhich we desire 
 to give it, like white paper on which you write any charac- 
 ters you choose. When children so instructed reach the 
 age of reason and come to reflect on themselves, they can- 
 not find anything more ancient in their minds than those 
 opinions, and therefore imagine that those p-opositions of 
 xoliose knowledge they can find in themselves no original, arc 
 the impress of God and natitrc, and not things taught them 
 hg any one else} 
 
 Moreover, how can a truth, that is, a proposition, be in- 
 nate, if the ideas which make up that truth are not ? In 
 order that a proposition be innate, certain ideas must be 
 innate ; but, excepting perhaps some faint ideas of hunger, 
 warmth, and pains, which they may have felt in the mother's 
 womb, there is not the least appearance that new-born 
 children have any settled ideas. Even the idea of God is 
 not innate; for besides the individuals wdio are called 
 atheists and who are really atheists, there are whole nations 
 who have no notion of God nor any term to express it. 
 Moreover, this notion varies infinitely from coarse anthro- 
 pomorphism to the deism of the philosophers. And even if 
 
 1 c. III., 23.
 
 JOHN LOCKE 375 
 
 it were universal and everywhere the same, it would not, 
 on that account, be more innate than the idea of fire ; for 
 there is no one who has any idea of God who has not also 
 the idea of fire.^ 
 
 The soul is originally an emjyty tallet. Experience is the 
 source of all our ideas, the foundation of all our knowledge, 
 that is, the observations which we make about external sen- 
 sible objects or about the internal operations of our minds. 
 Sensation is the source of our knowledge of external objects, 
 reflection, of our knowledge of internal facts. There is not 
 in the mind a single idea that is not derived from one or 
 both of these principles. The first ideas of the child come 
 from sensation, and it is only at a more advanced age that 
 he seriously reflects on what takes place within him. The 
 study of languages may be cited in support of this thesis. 
 In fact, all the words which we employ depend on sensible 
 ideas, and those wliich are made use of to stand for actions 
 and notions quite removed from sense have their rise from 
 thence, and from obvious sensible ideas are transferred to 
 more abstruse significations. Thus, for example, to imagine, 
 apprehend, comprehend, adhere, conceive, instil, disgust, 
 disturbance, tranquillity, etc., are all words taken from the 
 operations of sensible things and applied to certain modes 
 of thinking. Spirit, in its primary signification, is breath ; 
 angel, a messenger. If \ve could trace all these words to 
 their sources, we should certainly find in all languages the 
 names which stand for things that fall not under our senses 
 to have had their first rise from sonsil)le ideas.^ Follow a 
 child from its birth and observe the alterations that time 
 makes, and you shall find, as the mind by the senses comes 
 more and more to ])e furnislied with ideas, it comes to be 
 more and more awake, and tliink-s more, the more it has 
 matter to think on. 
 
 Locke answers the question. When do we l)egin to think? 
 
 1 c. III.. 'J. MJ. ill ('liap. I., 5.
 
 376 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 as follows : As soon as sensation furnishes us with the ma- 
 terials. We do not think before we have sensations. Nihil 
 est in intellectu quod non antea fuerit in sensu. According 
 to the idealist, thought is the essence of the soul, and it is 
 not possible for the soul not to think ; it thinks antecedent 
 to and independently of sensation ; it always thinks even 
 though it is not conscious of it. But experience, which 
 alone can settle the question, by no means proves it, and it 
 is not any more necessar^j for the soul always to think than it 
 is for the body ahvays to move?- The absolute continuity of 
 thought is one of those hypotheses which have no fact of 
 experience to bear them out. A man cannot think without 
 perceiving that he thinks. With as much reason might we 
 claim that a man is always hungry, but that he does not 
 always feel it.^ . Thought depends entirely on sensation. 
 In its sublimest ideas and in its highest speculations it does 
 not stir beyond those ideas which sense or reflection has 
 offered for its contemplation. In this part the understand- 
 ing is purely passive. The objects of our senses obtrude 
 their particular ideas upon our minds whether we will or 
 not. These simple ideas, when offered to the mind, the 
 understanding can no more refuse to have, nor alter, nor 
 blot them out, than a mirror can refuse, alter, or obliterate 
 the images of the objects placed before it.^ 
 
 There are two kinds of ideas, some simple and some 
 complex. These simple ideas, the materials of all our 
 knowledge, are suggested to the mind only by those two 
 ways above mentioned, viz., sensation and reflection. The 
 mind, though passive in the formation of simple ideas, is 
 active in the formation of complex ideas. It receives the 
 former, it males the latter. When it has once received 
 the simple ideas it has the power to repeat, compare, and 
 unite them, even to an almost infinite variety, and so can 
 make new complex ideas. But it is not in the power of 
 1 B. II., chap. I., 10. 2 1,1^ 19. 3 la., 25.
 
 JOHN LOCKE 377 
 
 the most fruitful mind to form a single new simple idea, 
 not taken in by the wa}^ of sensation and reflection. The 
 dominion of man, in tliis little ^yorld of his own under- 
 standing, is the same as it is in the great world of visible 
 things, wherein his power, however managed by art and 
 skill, reaches no farther than to compound and divide the 
 materials that are made to his hand ; hut can do nothing 
 towards the making the least particle of new matter^ or 
 destroying one atom of what is already in heing.^ 
 
 The simple ideas come into our minds by one sense only, 
 or by more senses than one, or from reflection only, or, 
 finally, by all the ways of sensation and reflection.^ 
 
 Among the ideas which come to us only through one 
 sense (colors, sounds, tastes, smells, etc.), there is none 
 which we receive more constantly than the idea of solidity 
 or impenetrabilit3^ We receive this idea fi-om touch. This, 
 of all simple ideas, is the idea most intimately connected 
 with and essential to bod}-. Solidity is neither space — 
 with wliich the Cartesians erroneously identify it — nor 
 hardness. It differs from space as resistance differs from 
 non-resistance. A body is solid in so far as it fills the space 
 which it occupies to the absolute exclusion of every other 
 body ; it is hard, in so far as it does not easily change its 
 figure. It is not properly a definition of solidity that 
 Locke pretends to give us. If we ask him to give us a 
 clearer explanation of solidity, he sends us to our senses to 
 inform us. The simple ideas we have are sucli as experi- 
 ence teaches us ; but if, l)e3'ond that, we endeavor to make 
 them clearer in the mind, we sliall succeed no Ix'tter. 
 
 The ideas which come to tlie mind by more lliaii one 
 sense (sight and toucli) are those of space or extension, 
 figure, rest, and motion. By reflection we get tlie ideas of 
 perception or the power of tliinking, and the ideas of vol- 
 ition or tlic ]K)\ver to act. Finally, the ideas of ])leasure, 
 » J5. II., dial.. II., -J. •■' y</., cluip. III., 1.
 
 378 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 pain, power, existence, and unity come to us by sensation 
 and reflection. 
 
 Some of the external causes of our sensations are real 
 and positive, others are only privations in the objects 
 from whence our senses derive those ideas, like those, for 
 example, which produce the ideas of cold, darkness, and 
 rest. When the understanding perceives these ideas, it con- 
 siders them as distinct and as positive as the others, with- 
 out taking notice of the causes that produce them, which 
 is an inquiry not belonging to the idea, as it is in the 
 understanding, but to the nature of the things existing 
 without us. Now these are two very different things, and 
 caref idly to be distinguished ; we must not think that our 
 ideas are exactly the images and resemblances of something 
 inherent in the object which produces them ; for most of 
 the ideas of sensation which are in our minds are no more 
 the likeness of something existing loitlwut us, than the names 
 that stand for them are the likeness of our ideas, although 
 these names are apt to excite ideas in us as soon as we 
 hear them.^ 
 
 Different things should have different names ; hence, 
 whatsoever the mind perceives in itself, every perception 
 that is in the mind when it thinks, Locke calls idea, and 
 the power or faculty to produce any idea in oiu- mind he 
 calls the quality of the subject (we should say: of the 
 object). 
 
 That being established, Locke, like Hobbes, distinguishes 
 two kinds of qualities.''^ Some, such as solidity, extension, 
 
 1 B. II., chap. VIII., 1 ff. Here we have the fundamental princi- 
 ple of criticism which, as we have seen, was advanced by Aristippus, 
 Pyi-rho, J]^nesidemus, Hobbes, and Descartes. The eighth chapter of 
 the second book of the Essay, of which the above is a summary, and 
 especially § 7 of this chapter, is the classical expression of the 
 philosophy to which Kant gives its real name. 
 
 2 /(/., 9.
 
 JOHN LOCKE 379 
 
 figure, and mobility, are inseparable from the body, in what 
 state soever it be : such as it constantly keeps in all the 
 alterations it suffers. These are the original or 'primary 
 or real qualities of body.^ Others, like colors, sounds, 
 tastes, etc., do not belong to the boches themselves, and are 
 nothing but the power which they have to produce various 
 sensations in us by their primary qualities, that is, by the 
 bulk, figure, texture, and motion of their insensible parts. 
 Locke calls them secondary qualities : qualities, in order to 
 comply with the common way of speaking, wliich con- 
 siders white, red, and sweet as something inherent in the 
 bodies ; secondary, in order to distinguisli them from those 
 which are real qualities. 
 
 Whatever reality we may by mistake attribute to them, 
 colors, smells, sounds, and tastes are nothing but sensa- 
 tions produced in ils by the primary or real qualities of 
 bodies, — sensations which in no way resemble the qualities 
 which exist in the objects. What is sweet, blue, or warm 
 in idea is nothing but a certain bulk, figure, and motion 
 of the insensible parts in the bodies themselves which we 
 call so. Take away the sensation which Ave have of these 
 qualities ; let not the eyes see light or colors, nor the ears 
 hear sounds ; let the palate not taste, nor the nose smell ; 
 and all colors, tastes, odors, and sounds will vanisli and 
 cease to exist. In the opposite hypothesis, the result will 
 be the same. Suppose man were endowed witli senses suf- 
 ficiently fine to discern the small particles of bodies and tlie 
 real constitution on which their sensible qualities depend, 
 and they will produce in him quite different ideas. The 
 effects of the microscope prove it; blood, for ex:nn])le, 
 seems quite red to us, but l)y means of this instrument, 
 which discovei's tf) us its sm;illest particles, we see nothing 
 but a very small nnniher of red globules; and we do not 
 know how these led globules would appear if we could 
 1 15. II., cl.ai). VIII., t).
 
 380 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 find glasses with a magnifjdng power that is a thousand or 
 ten thousand times greater. 
 
 The formation of ideas presupposes the following facul- 
 ties in the understanding : (1) perception, which is the first 
 step and degree towards knowledge, and the inlet of all 
 the materials of it; (2) retention, which keeps the ideas 
 brought into the mind, for some time actually in view (con- 
 templation), and revives again those which after imprinting 
 have disappeared from it (memory) ; (3) discernment, or the 
 faculty of clearly distinguishing between the different ideas ; 
 (4) comparison, which forms that large tribe of ideas com- 
 prehended under relations ; (5) comjjosition, whereby the 
 mind joins together several simple ideas which it has re- 
 ceived from sensation and reflection, and cpmbines them into 
 complex ones ; finally (6) abstraction.'^ If every particular 
 idea that we take in should have a distinct name, the num- 
 ber of words would be endless. To prevent this, the mind 
 makes the particular ideas received from particular objects, 
 general ; it separates them (ahstrahere) from all the circum- 
 stances which make these ideas represent particular and 
 actually existent beings, as time, place, and other concomi- 
 tant ideas. This operation of the mind is called abstrac- 
 tion. It is the prerogative of the human mind, whereas 
 the preceding faculties are common to man and brutes. 
 
 The mind is passive in perception proper, but becomer 
 more and more active in the following steps ; comparison, 
 the composition of complex ideas, and abstraction, are the 
 three great acts of the mind. But, however active the 
 mind may be in the formation of complex ideas, these are 
 in the last analysis but modes or modifications of the 
 materials which it passively receives from sensation and 
 reflection. 
 
 Thus the ideas of place, figure, distance, and immensity 
 are modifications or modes of the simple idea of space, which 
 1 B. IL, chaps. IX., ff.
 
 JOHN LOCKE 381 
 
 is acquired by sight and toucli ; the ideas of periods, hours, 
 days, years, time, eternity, are modifications of the idea of 
 duration or succession, which we acquire by observing the 
 constant train of ideas which succeed one another in our 
 minds ; the idea of finite and infinite, modifications of the 
 idea of quantity.^ 
 
 If it be olijected that the ideas of infinit}^ eternity, and 
 immensity cannot have the same source as the others, since 
 the objects whicli surround us have no affinity nor any pro- 
 portion with an infinite extension or duration, Locke an- 
 swers tliat these ideas are merely negative, that we do not 
 actually have in the mind any positive idea of an infinite 
 space or an endless duration ^ (Aristotle). All our positive 
 ideas are always limited. The negative idea of an infinite 
 space and duration comes from the power which the mind 
 has of extending its ideas of space and duration by an end- 
 less number of new additions. 
 
 We get the idea of active and passive power (recep- 
 tivity) when we observe, on the one hand, the continual 
 alteration in things, and, on the other, the constant change 
 of our ideas, which is sometimes caused by the impression 
 of outward objects on our senses, and sometimes by the 
 determination of our own will. 
 
 When we reflect on the power which the mind has to 
 command the presence or the absence of any particular 
 idea, or to prefer the motion of any i)art of tlie l)0(ly to its 
 rest, and vice versa, we acquire the idea of \\ ill. 1(7// is not 
 opposed to necessity/, but to restraint. Liberty is not an 
 attribute of the will. Will is a power or al)ility, and free- 
 dom another power or ability; so that to ask a man 
 whether his will l)e free is to ask wliether one power has 
 another power, one ability anotlier ability .^ To speak of a 
 free will is like speaking of swift sleep or scpiare virtue. 
 
 1 ii. U,, cliaps. XII. ly. 2 /(/.^ (,i,;ip. XVII., 13. 
 
 8 Jd., cluq.. XXI.
 
 882 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 "VVe are not free to will. We are not free to will or not to 
 will a thing wliich is in our power, when once we give our 
 attention to it. The will is determined by the mind,^ and 
 the mind is determined by the desire for happiness. On 
 this point Locke, Leibniz, and Spinoza are in perfect 
 accord, and unanimously opposed to Cartesian indeter- 
 minism. 
 
 The notions which we have just analyzed are combina- 
 tions of simple ideas of the same kind {simple modes). 
 Others, like obligation, friendship, falsehood, and hypocrisy, 
 are composed of simple ideas of different kinds {mixed 
 modes). Thus, the mixed mode which the word lie stands 
 for is made of these simple ideas : (1) articulate sounds ; 
 (2) certain ideas in the mind of the speaker; (3) words 
 which are the signs of those ideas ; (4) those signs put 
 together by affirmation or negation, otherwise than as the 
 ideas they stand for are in the mind of the speaker. 
 
 We get the idea of these mixed modes as follows: (1) 
 By experience and observation of things themselves. Thus, 
 by seeing two men wrestle or fence we get the idea of 
 wrestling or fencing. (2) By invention, or voluntary put- 
 ting together of several simple ideas in our own minds : so 
 he that first invented printing or etching had an idea of it 
 in his mind before it ever existed. (3) By explaining the 
 names of actions we never saw, or notions we cannot see. 
 The several fashions, customs, and manners of a nation 
 give rise to several combinations of ideas which are 
 familiar and necessary to that nation, but which another 
 people have never had any occasion to make. Special 
 names come to be annexed to such special combinations of 
 a people, to avoid long periphrases in things of daily con- 
 versation {ostracism among the Greeks, ]3roscription among 
 the Romans), and so there are in every language particular 
 terms which cannot be literally translated into any other. 
 1 B. 11., chap. XXT., 29.
 
 JOHN LOCKE 383 
 
 So niiicli for the complex ideas that express modes. 
 
 The complex ideas of substances (man, horse, tree) are 
 formed as follows : The mind observes that a certain num- 
 ber of simple ideas, conveyed in by the different senses, con- 
 stantly go together, and accustoms itself to regard such a 
 complication of ideas as one object, and designates it by one 
 name. Hence, a substance is nothing but a combination of 
 a certain number of simple ideas, considered as united in 
 one thing. Thus the substance called sun is nothing but 
 the aggregate of the ideas of light, heat, roundness, and con- 
 stant, regular motion. By substance, the philosophy of the 
 School, and afterwards Descartes, imagined an unknown 
 object, which they assumed to be the support (sahstratum) 
 of such qualities as are capable of producing simple 
 ideas in us, which qualities are commonly called accidents. 
 But this substance considered as amjthing else but the com- 
 bination of these qualities, as something hidden behind 
 them, is a mere phantom of the imagination. We have no 
 distinct idea of such a substratum without qualities. If 
 an}- one should be asked wherein color or weight inheres, 
 " he would liave nothing to say, but the solid extended parts ; 
 and if lie were demanded what is it that solidity and exten- 
 sion adhere in, he wouhl not be in a much better case than 
 the Indian before mentioned, who, saying that the world 
 was supported by a great elepliant, was asked what the ele- 
 phant rested on ; to which liis answer was, — a great tor- 
 toise ; but being again pressed i^ know what gave support 
 to the broad-backed tortoise, replied, — something, he knew 
 not what." ^ Our knowledge does not extend beyond the 
 assumed accidents, that is, beyond our simple ideas, and 
 whenever meta[)hy8ics attempts to proceed beyond them it 
 is confronted with insurmountable diiliculties. 
 
 The third chiss of comjih-x ideas express relation. The 
 most comprehensive relation wherein all things are con- 
 1 15. II., .hai.. XXIII., 2.
 
 884 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 cerned is the relation of cause and effect. We get tlie idea 
 of this by noticing, by means of the senses, the constant 
 vicissitude of tilings, and by observing that they owe their 
 existence to the action of some other being. Locke does 
 not analyze the idea of cause as thoroughly as his successor 
 Hume. We shall see that the latter regards it as no less 
 illusory than the idea of substance, or substratum. 
 
 In passing from the study of ideas to the problem of 
 knowledge and certitude, Locke enters upon a philological 
 discussion, which we have partly reproduced above, and 
 which stamps him as one of the founders of the philosophy 
 of language. 
 
 All things that exist are particulars. The far greatest 
 part of words (with the exception of proper names) are 
 general terms ; which has not been the effect of neglect or 
 chance, but of reason and necessity. In what do the species 
 and genera consist, and how do they come to be formed ? 
 Our ideas are at first particular. The ideas which the chil- 
 dren have of their nurse and their mother represent only 
 those individuals. The names which they first gave to 
 them are confined to these individuals and designate only 
 them. Afterwards, when time and a larger acquaintance 
 with the world have made them observe that there are a 
 great many other things that resemble their father and 
 mother and those persons they have been used to, they 
 frame an idea, which they find those many particulars do 
 partake in ; and to that they give, with others, the name 
 ma7i. And thus they come to have a general name, and a 
 general idea ; wherein they make nothing new, but only 
 leave out of the complex idea they had of Peter and James, 
 Mary and Jane, that which is peculiar to each, and retain 
 only what is connnon to all. In the same way they acquire 
 all general ideas. This process of abstraction and general- 
 ization is a necessity ; for it would be impossible for each 
 tiling to have a particular name. It is beyond the power
 
 JOHN LOCKE 385 
 
 of human capacity to frame and retain distinct ideas of all 
 the particular things we meet with, — of every tree, of every 
 plant, of every beast, that affected the senses. Still less 
 possible would it be to retain their names. But even if it 
 could be done, it would not be of any great use for the im- 
 provement of knowledge ; for although our knowledge is 
 founded on particular observations, it enlarges itself by 
 general views, which can only be formed by reducing the 
 things to certain species under general names. 
 
 General notions {universalia) are nothing but abstract and 
 partial ideas of more comjilex ones, taken from particular 
 existences. They are simple products of our minds. Gen- 
 eral and universal belong not to the real existence of things ; 
 hut are the inventions and creatures of the understanding} 
 It is true that nature, in the production of things, makes 
 several of them alike ; there is nothing more obvious, espe- 
 cially in the races of animals, and all things propagated by 
 seed. But the reduction of these things to siJccies is the 
 workmanship of the understanding. Owing to its lack of 
 a thorough knowledge of nature, the Platonic doctrine, 
 which regarded universals as the ingenerable and incorrupt- 
 ible essences of things, disregarded tliis fact of experience 
 that all things that exist, besides their author, are liable to 
 change ; thus, that which was grass to-day is to-morrow the 
 flesh of a sheep, and within a few days after becomes part 
 of a man. In the organic world, as elsewhere, the genera, 
 species, essences, and substantial forms, dreamt of by the 
 metaphysicians, far from being things regularly and con- 
 stantly made by nature and having a real existence in 
 things themselves (Aristotle) or apart from them (Plato), 
 "appear, upon a more wary survey, to be nothing else but an 
 artifice of the understanding, for the easier signifying such 
 collections of ideas as it should often have occasion to com- 
 municate by one general term." Notice, moreover, how 
 
 1 B. III., cliap. III., 11. 
 2J
 
 386 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 doubtful is the significatiou of the word " species," and how 
 difficult it is to define organic beings. ^ So uncertain are 
 the boundaries of animal species that none of the definitions 
 of the word " man " which we yet have, nor descriptions of 
 that sort of animal, are so perfect and exact as to satisfy a 
 considerate inquisitive person.^ We may find that learned 
 men multiply species too much, but we may also hold the 
 opposite. Why, for example, are not a shock and a liound 
 as distinct species as a spaniel and an elephant ? Any one 
 who carefully observes the individuals ranked under one 
 and the same general name can hardly douljt that many of 
 them are as different, one from another, as several of those 
 which are ranked under different specific names.^ 
 
 We may remark, in passing, that the modein theory of 
 the transmutation of species is nothing but an application 
 of Locke's teaching that sj)ecies have no objective reality. 
 Let us also note the important fact that this extreme nom- 
 inalism closely approximates extreme realism. Scholastic 
 nominalism denies the reality of species, and absolutely 
 affirms the reality of individuals to the exclusion of every- 
 thing else. In this sense Leibniz is a nominalist. English 
 nominalism, from which the theory of transformation takes 
 its rise, denies not only the existence of species, but also the 
 stability of the individuals themselves. All things, says 
 Locke, besides their author, are liable to change. Now this 
 is exactly what Spinoza teaches. lie is not content with 
 repudiating universals for the sake of the one universal 
 Being, but considers the individuals themselves as passing 
 modes of what he calls substance, what the materialists 
 call matter, and Locke and the positivists call the great 
 unknown. 
 
 Hence, species, genera, and universals are mere words 
 {flatus vocis). The traditional error of the metaphysicians 
 
 1 B. III., chap, v., 9. 2 Id., chap. VI., 27. 
 
 ■ Id., chap. VI., 38 ; chap. X., 20.
 
 JOHN LOCKE 887 
 
 consists m taking words for things} The disciples of the 
 Peripatetic philosophy are persuaded that the ten categories 
 of Aristotle, substantial forms., vegetative souls, ahhorrcncc of 
 a vacuum.) are something real. The Platonists have their 
 soul of the world, and the Epicureans their endeavor to- 
 wards motion in their atoms. All this is gibberish, which, 
 in the weakness of the human understanding, serves to pal- 
 liate our ignorance and cover our errors.^ We must be 
 content ; there are limits to our knowledge that cannot be 
 crossed. 
 
 Well, then, what is knowledge ? 
 
 It is nothing but the perception of the connection and 
 agreement, or disagreement and repugnanc}', of any of our 
 ideas. From this definition it follows that our knowledge 
 does not reach further than our ideas ; nay, it is even much 
 narrower than these, because the connection between most 
 of our simple ideas is unknown. Hence we may affirm that, 
 altliough our knowledge may be carried much further than 
 it has liitherto been, it will never reach to all we might de- 
 sire to know concerning those ideas we have, nor be able 
 to resolve all the questions that might arise concerning any 
 of them. Tims, we have the ideas of matter and tliinking, 
 but possibly shall never be able to know whether any mere ma- 
 terial thing thinks or no ; it being impossible for us to discover 
 ivhether Omnipotency has not given to some systems of matter 
 fitly disposed., a power to perceive and think.^ We are per- 
 fectly conscious of the existence of our soul, without know- 
 ino- exactly wliat it is; and he who will take the trouble to 
 consider freely the difficulties contained in both the spirit- 
 ualistic and the materialistic hypotheses, will scarce find his 
 reason able to determine him fixedly for or (t gainst the souVs 
 materiality. Just as wc an; absolutely ignorant whether 
 there is any opposition oi- coiimMtioii between extension and 
 thouglit, matter and perception, so too it is impossible for 
 
 1 B. HI., chap. X., 11. 2 Id. • H. IV., chap. III., 0.
 
 38S MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 lis to know anything of the union or incompatibility be- 
 tween the secondary qualities of an object (between its 
 color, taste, and smell), on the one hand, and between any 
 secondary quality and those primary qualities on which it 
 depends, on the other. 
 
 Thouo-h our knowledsre does not reach further than our 
 ideas and the perception of their agreement or disagree- 
 ment, and though ive have no knowledge of what the things 
 they represent arc in themselves, it does not follow that all 
 our knowledge is illusory and chimerical. 
 
 We have an intuitive and immediate knowledge of our 
 own existence, even if we are ignorant of the metaphysical 
 essence of the soul. We have a demonstrative knowledge 
 of God, although our understanding cannot comprehend 
 the immensity of his attributes. Finally, we know the 
 other things by sensation. It is true, we do not know 
 them immediately, and consequently our knowledge is real 
 only so far as there is a conformity between our ideas and 
 the reality of things. ^ But we are not absolutely without 
 a criterion for knowing whether our ideas agree with tho 
 things themselves. It is certain that our simple ideas cor- 
 respond to external realities ; for since the mind can by no 
 means make them to itself without the intervention of the 
 senses (as witness men born blind), it follows that they are 
 not fictions of the imagination, but the natural and regular 
 productions of things without us, really operating upon us. 
 The reality of external things is further proved by the fact 
 that there is a very great difference between an idea that 
 comes from an actual sensation and one that is revived in 
 memory, and that the pleasure or pain which follows upon 
 an actual sensation does not accompany the return of 
 these ideas when the external objects are absent. Finally, 
 our senses bear witness to the truth of each other's report 
 concerning the existence of sensible things without us. 
 1 B. IV., chap. IV.. a
 
 JOHN LOCKE 389 
 
 He that sees a foe may, if he doubt whether it be anything 
 more than a bare fancy, feel it too, and be convinced by 
 putting his liand in it, which certainl}- could never be put 
 into such exquisite pain by a bare idea or phantom.^ 
 
 Let us sum up. There are no innate ideas ; no innate 
 truths, maxims, or principles ; no other sources of knowl- 
 edge but sensation for external tilings, and reflection for 
 what takes place witliin us. Consequently, it is impos- 
 sible to know anything outside of what experience, be it 
 external or internal, furnishes us. Pliilosophy must aban- 
 don the transcendent problems of substance, essence, and 
 the inner constitution of things, as well as all methods 
 except observation, induction, and experience. The soul 
 exists, but we cannot know whether its essence is material 
 or immaterial. The freedom of indifference is denied. 
 God exists, but we know nothing of his nature. Outside 
 of us exist solidity, extension, figure, and motion, as 
 primary qualities, or such as inhere in the bodies them- 
 selves. The substance of bodies is identical with the sum 
 of these qualities. These qualities are distinguished from 
 secondary qualities (colors, sounds, tastes, smells, etc.), 
 which are merely sensations of the soul produced by the 
 primary qualities of bodies, and do not exist as such in the 
 objects themselves. Finally, the reality of species is abso- 
 lutely denied. 
 
 These doctrines are the culmination of tlu- noiuiualistic 
 movement which was inaugurated l)y Roscclliuus and re- 
 newed by Occam; they likewise form the beginning of 
 modern scientific philosophy. As the preceding jjara- 
 graphs show, the teachings of Descartes and Bacon greatly 
 resemble each other in many res})eets, particularly in the 
 matter of final causes. A no less noteworthy fact, one that 
 may serve as an argument against the scepticisTu which ])ases 
 itself solely on the constant disagrccniciit aiiKHig philoso- 
 » H. IV.,cli:ip. XI., 7.
 
 890 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 phers, is tlie harmony existing between Locke and Spinoza, 
 that is to say, between empiricism and rationalism. Locke 
 agrees with his contemjjorary at Amsterdam not onl}^ in his 
 repudiation of species, but in his denial of the liberty of 
 indifference, and in his view that ethics is as susceptible of 
 demonstration as mathematics. 
 
 The name of the most illustrious scientist of the seven- 
 teenth centiu-y is connected with Locke's empiricism sup- 
 plemented by mathematical speculation. I mean Isa^vg 
 Newton (16-42-1727), the founder of celestial mechanics, 
 whose 3Iathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy ^ is, 
 next to the Celestial Revolutions of Copernicus, the grandest 
 monument of modern science. His calculus of fluxions, 
 wliich anticipated, or at least was discovered independently 
 of, Leibniz's integral and differential calculus, his analysis 
 of light, and, above all, his theory of universal gravitation, 
 according to which bodies are attracted to each other in 
 direct proportion to their masses and in inverse ratio to the 
 squares of their cUstances, have exercised an incalculable 
 influence upon what he calls natural philosophy. 
 
 Locke's philosoph}', with its principles of observation and 
 analysis, also formed the nucleus of a distinguished school 
 of English moralists. We might mention the names of: 
 Shaftesbuky,2 Clarke,^ Hutcheson,* Ferguson,^ 
 
 ^ Natnralis pMIosophice principia niafhcmatica, London, 1687. 
 
 2 1671-1713. [Characteristics of Me7i, Manners, Opinions, and Times, 
 1711 ; ed. by W. Hatch, 3 vols., London, 1869. See Steplien, Essays on 
 Freethinking and Plainspeaking ; G. v. Gizycki, Die Philosophie Shnfles- 
 bury's, Leipsic and Heidelberg, 1876; Th. Fowler, Shaflesbury and 
 HulcJieson, London. 1882; Ernest Albee, The Relation of Shaftesbury 
 and Hulcheson to Utilitarianism (Phil. Rev., Y., 1). — Tr.] 
 
 8 1675-1729. Works, 4 folio vols., London, 1738-1742. 
 
 * 1694-1747. [Inquiry into the Original of our Ideas of Beauty and 
 Virtue, London, 172.5 ff. ; Philosnphice moralis institutio, Glasgow, 1745 ; A 
 System of Moral Philosophy, id.. 1755. See Fowder and Albee. — Tr.] 
 
 6 1724-1816. \ Institution of Moral Philosophy, London, 1769 ; tr 
 into German by Garve, Leipsic, 1772. — Tr.]
 
 BERKELEY 391 
 
 Ad^oi S:mith,^ and many others.^ The freethinkers,^ who 
 flourished in Great Britain and on the Continent at the end 
 of tliis period, and the philosophers proper whom we have 
 still to consider, are likewise descendants of Locke. Eng- 
 lish philosophy is, to this day, almost as empirical and pos- 
 itivistic as in the times of Bacon and Locke. We may 
 even claim, in general, that England, though rith in think- 
 ers of the highest order, has never had but a single school 
 of philosoph}-, or, rather, that it has never had any, for its 
 philosophy is a perpetual protest against Scholasticism. 
 
 § 58. Berkeley 
 
 After what has been said of the agreement existing be- 
 tween Locke and Spinoza, it will hardly surprise us to see 
 a disciple of the English pliilosopher offering the hand of 
 friendship to Leibniz and Malebranche, the champions of 
 intellectualism and innate ideas across the sea. Although 
 
 ^ 1723-1790. [Theory of Moral Sentiments, London, 1759. Cf. 
 Farrer, Adam Smith (^English Philosophers Series), London, 1880. — Tu.] 
 Works, 5 vols., Edinburgh, 1812. 
 
 2 [Cumberland, De leyihus naturce, London, 1072; Kiigl.tr. by Jean 
 Maxwell, i(].. 1727. Cf. Ernest All)ee, The; Ethical System of Richard 
 Cumberland {Phil. Review, 1895). Joseph Butler, Sermons u])on Hu)nan 
 Nature, London, 1726. Cf. W. Collins, Butler (Phil. Classics), Edin- 
 burgh and London, 1889. Home, Essays on the Principles of Morality 
 and Natural Religion, 1751. Paley, Principles (f Moral and Political 
 Philosophy, London, 1785. J. Bi'uiliaux. Princij)lis (f Morals and Let/is- 
 lation, 1789. See Gizycki, Die Ethik Hume's, IJivslau, 1878; ISIaekiii- 
 tosh, On the Progress of Ethical PhUosophy chiijly during the XVII. and 
 XVIII. Centuries, Gil. hy \\ . Whewell, -llh ed., Edinburgh, 1872. — Th.] 
 
 ' [John Toland, Chri^titiuity not Mysterious. London, 1096. \. Col- 
 lins, A Discourse of Freelhinking, London. 171.3. I\r. Tiiidal, Christian- 
 ity as Old as the Creation, J^ondoii, 17-)0. 'I'hoiiiiis Chubb, A Discourse 
 concerning Reason with Regard to Rdiginn. Lomli^ii, 17.%. 'I\ Morgan, 
 The Moral Philosopher, London, 17-)7 IT. I.onl Uoliii^^broke, Works 
 ed. by D. Mollet, 5 voIh., 1753-51. (T. on lli.' ihisis. V. Lechler, Ge- 
 schichte des euglhichen Deismus, Stuttgart, iSll ; limit, History of Re- 
 ligious Thought in England, I..(>ndon, 1871-73; and i^esiie Stejihen'u 
 work citcfl \i. 12, iiotr 11. — Tit. J
 
 392 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Locke and liis opponents differ on several essential points, 
 they reach practically the same conclusions concerning tlie 
 world of sense. Malebranche and Leibniz spiritualize mat- 
 ter; they explain it as a confused idea, and ultimately 
 assume a principle endowed with desire and perception, 
 that is, mind. Locke's criticism, on the otlier hand, does 
 not wholly reject the material world ; one half of it is re- 
 tained. Extension, form, and motion exist outside of us ; 
 but neither colors, nor sounds, nor tastes, nor smells exist 
 independently of our sensations. Moreover, Locke attacks 
 the traditional notion of substance, or substratum, and de- 
 fines real substance as a combination of qualities. Indeed, 
 he goes so far as to say that the idea of corporeal substance 
 or matter is as remote from our concejotions and apprehen- 
 sions as that of spiritual substance or spirit ! ^ Hence, all 
 that was needed to arrive at the negation of matter or abso- 
 lute spiritualism was to efface the distinction which he had 
 cbawn between primary and secondary qualities, and to call 
 all sensible qualities, without exception, secondary. 
 
 This is done by GeoPvGE Berkeley, who thus enters 
 upon a course against which Locke had advised in vain. 
 Berkeley was born in Ireland, 1685, of English ancestors, 
 became Bishop of Cloyne, 1734, and died at Oxford, 
 1753. The following are his most important works : Essay 
 toioards a New Theory of Vision,'^ Treatise on the Principles 
 of Human Knowledge,^ Three Dialogues between Hylas and 
 Philonous,'^ Alciphron, or the Minute Philosopher .^ 
 
 1 Essay concerning Human Understanding, II., ch. XXIII., 5. 
 
 2 Dublin, 170.9. This remarkable treatise clearly anticipates the 
 modern principles of the physiology of sensation. 
 
 3 Dublin, 1710. [Krauth's ed., 187L] 
 
 4 London, 1713. [Calcutta, 1893.] French, Amsterdam, 1750; 
 German, Rostock, 1756. 
 
 6 London, 1732 ; French, The Hague, 1734 ; German, Lenigo, 1737. 
 The works of G. Berkeley, London, 1781, 1820, 1843, 1871. This last 
 edition, published in 4 vols., by A. Campbell Fraser, is the most com-
 
 BERKELEY 393 
 
 Locke recognizes, with Descartes and Hobbes, that color 
 is nothing apart from the sensation of the person seeing it, 
 that sound exists only for the hearing, that taste and smell 
 are mere sensations, and do not inhere in the things them- 
 selves. But in addition to such secondary qualities, which 
 do not inhere in the objects but in the perceiving subject, 
 he assumes primary qualities existing without the mind and 
 belonging to an unthinking substance : extension, figure, 
 and motion. And that is "\^■here he is wrong. Just as color, 
 smell, and taste exist only for the person perceiving them, 
 so extension, form, and motion exist only in a mind that 
 perceives them. Take away the perceiving subject, and you 
 take away the sensible world. Existence consists in per- 
 ceiving or being perceived. That which is not perceived 
 and does not perceive does not exist. The ohjects do not 
 exist apart from the subjects perceiving them. According 
 to the common view, these objects — houses, mountains, and 
 rivers — have an existence, natural or real, distinct from 
 their being perceived by the understanding, and our ideas 
 of them are copies or resemblances of all these things witli- 
 out us. Now, says Berkeley,^ either tliose exteinal objects 
 or originals of our ideas are perceivable, or tliey are not 
 perceivable. If they are, then they are ideas (for an idea 
 = something perceived). In that case, there is no dilTei- 
 ence between objects assumed to be without us and our 
 ideas of them ; and " we liave gained our point." '' If you 
 say they are not, I appeal to any one whether it be sense to 
 assert a color is like something which is invisibh' ; liard 
 or soft, like something which is intangible ; and so of the 
 
 I^lete. ISeleclions J'rom Berkeley, with introduclioii and notes, l»y A. 
 Campbell Fraser, ith ed. (revised), 1891. Cf. T. C. Simon, Uniccrsal 
 hnmaterialism, London, 18fj'2; Controversy between Ueberweg and 
 Simon, in Fichte's Z.f. Ph., vol. 55, 1860; vol. 57, 1870; vol. 59, 1871 ; 
 A. C. Fraser, Berkeley (Philosophical Cltissic.t), IMinburgli and Lon- 
 don, 1881. — Tk.] 
 
 1 Principles of Ifuwuu Knoirledije, § 8.
 
 394 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 rest." Hence, there is no real difference between things 
 and our ideas of them. The words seMsiUe thing and idea 
 are synonymous. 
 
 Our ideas, or the things which we perceive, are visibly 
 inactive. It is impossible for an idea to do anything, or to 
 be the cause of anything. Hence, spirit or thinking sub- 
 stance alone can be the cause of ideas (sensible things). A 
 spirit is one sim})le, undivided, active being, — as it per- 
 ceives ideas, it is called the understanding^ and as it produces 
 or otherwise operates about them, it is called will. Now 
 all ideas (perceived things) being essentially passive, and 
 spirit eminently active, it follows that we cannot, strictly 
 speaking, have an idea of spirit, will, or soul ; at any rate, 
 we cannot form as clear an idea of it as of a triangle, for 
 example. Inasmuch as the idea is absolutely passive and 
 spirit the very essence of activity, the idea of spirit is a 
 contradiction in terms, and no more like spirit than night 
 is like the day.^ 
 
 In so far as mind perceives ideas it produces things ; and 
 these are not two distinct operations : to perceive signifies 
 to produce, and the ideas arc the tilings themselves. Never- 
 theless, the objects which I perceive have not a like de- 
 pendence on my will. Nay, very many of them do not 
 depend on it at all. " Wlien in Ijroad daylight I open my 
 eyes, it is not in my power to choose whether I shall see or 
 no, or to determine what particular objects shall present 
 themselves to my view." There is therefore — thus Berke- 
 ley proves the existence of God — some other will that 
 
 1 Berkeley repeatedly points out the impossibility of forming an 
 adequate idea of spiritual things, such as spirit, soul, or will, and he 
 explains this by the radical difference existing between spirit, the 
 essentially active thing, and idea, the essentially passive thing {Prin- 
 ciples of Human Knowledge, §§ 27, 89, 135). He likewise insists on the 
 necessity of clearly distinguishing between spirit and idea, thus con- 
 tradicting Spinoza, who regards them as synonyms {id., § 139).
 
 BEKKELEY 395 
 
 produces tliem, a more powerful spirit that imprints them 
 upon us. "' Now the set rules or established methods 
 wherein the ]Mind we depend on excites in us the ideas of 
 sense, are called the laws of nature ; and these we learn by- 
 experience. . . . The ideas imprinted on the senses by the 
 Author of natuie are commonly called real things ; and those 
 excited in the imagination being less regular, vivid, and 
 constant, are more properly termed ideas or images of things. 
 The ideas of sense are allowed to have more in them, that 
 is, to be more strong, orderly, and coherent, than the creat- 
 ures of the mind ; but this is no argument that they exist 
 without the mind."* 
 
 To the objection that this makes the sensil)le world, with 
 its sun, stars, mountains, and livers, a chimera or an illu- 
 sion, Berkeley answers that he does not in the least doubt 
 the existence of things. He is even Avilling to accept the 
 term corporeal substance if we mean by it a combination of 
 sensible qualities, such as extension, solidity, weight, and 
 the like. But he utterly repudiates the scholastic notion 
 which conceives matter as a substratum, or support of acci- 
 dents or qualities without the mind perceiving them, as a 
 stupid, thoughtless somcv:hat, which can neither perceive nor 
 be perceived, existing alongside of, and independent of, llie 
 thinking substance.^ The objection that, according to his 
 principles, we eat and drink ideas, and are clothed with 
 ideas, is not more serious tlian tlie preceding one. It over- 
 looks the fact that he em])loys tlie word idea, not in its 
 usual signification, Ijut in the sense of perceived thing. But 
 it is certain that our victuals and our ai)parel are things 
 which we perceive immediatel}^ by our senses, that is, ideas. 
 Finally, it is held that, according to his teaching, the sun, 
 moon, and trees exist f)idy w])en tliey are perceived, and 
 are anniliilated when we no longer perceive tlitiii. They 
 woulil iiiidoul)1i-dl V (•(■ase to exist if theic were no one to 
 
 1 J'rinrijiiis tif lluindn Knowlulijf, § 75.
 
 396 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 perceive them ; for existence consists in being perceived or 
 in perceiving. But if our mind cannot perceive tliem, an- 
 other spirit can perceive them or continue their existence, 
 so to spealv ; for tliough Berkeley denies the objective exist- 
 ence of bodies, he assumes a plurality of spiritual beings. 
 
 It is true, mankind and even philosophers steadfastly 
 assume the existence of matter. The explanation is simple. 
 They are conscious that they are iLot the authors of their 
 own sensations, and evidently know that they are imprinted 
 from without. They have recourse to the liypothesis of 
 matter as the external origin of their ideas, instead of de- 
 riving them directly from the Creative Spirit which alone 
 can produce them, (1) because they are not aware of the 
 contradiction involved " in supposing things like unto our 
 ideas existing without; (2) because the Supreme Spirit, 
 Avhich excites those ideas in our minds, is not marked out 
 and limited to our view by any particular finite collection 
 of sensible ideas, as human agents are by their size, complex- 
 ion, limbs, and motions ; and (3) because his operations are 
 regular and uniform. Whenever the course of nature is 
 interrupted by a miracle, men are ready to own the presence 
 of a superior agent. But when we see things go on in the 
 ordinary course they do not excite in us any reflection." 
 
 The negation of matter as a substance without the mind 
 silences a number of difficult and obscure questions : Can 
 a corporeal substance think ? Is matter infinitely divisible ? 
 How does it operate on spirit ? These and the like inquir- 
 ies are entirely banished from philosophy. The division of 
 sciences is simplified, and human knowledge reduced to two 
 great classes : knowledge of ideas and knowledge of spirits.^ 
 Moreover, this philosophy is alone capable of overcoming 
 scepticism. If we assume, with the ancient schools, that a 
 
 1 Principles of Human Knoivledge, § 86. Berkeley afterwards (§ 89; 
 adds a third group of knowledge : that of relations existing either be- 
 tween things or ideas (physical sciences and mathematical sciences).
 
 BERKELEY 397 
 
 substance exists without the mind, and that our ideas are 
 images of it, then scepticism is inevitable. On that hypoth- 
 esis, we see only the appearances, and not the real qualities 
 of things. What may be the extension, figure, or motion 
 of anything really and absolutely, or in itself, it is impos- 
 sible for us to know ; we know only the relations which 
 things bear to our senses. All we see, hear, and feel is but 
 a phantom. All these doubts are inevitable as soon as we 
 distinguish between ideas and things.^ 
 
 The absolute spiritualism of Berkeley is a unitary, homo- 
 geneous system, unquestionably superior to the hybrid phi- 
 losophies of Descartes and Wolff. Nay, it is, in my opinion, 
 the only metaphysic that may be successfully opposed to 
 materialism, for it alone takes into consideration the partial 
 truth of its objections.2 It overcomes the dualism of sub- 
 stances, and thus satisfies the most fundamental demand of 
 the philosophical spirit, — the demand for unity. In this 
 respect it has all the advantages of radical materialism 
 without being hampered by its difficulties. It greatly re- 
 sembles the system of Leibniz, but excels it in clearness, 
 consistency, boldness, and decision. Leibniz's opinions on 
 matter, space, and time are iiiidecided, conciliatory, and 
 even obscure. Berkeley shows no sign of hesitation. An 
 earnest and profoundly lionest tliinker, he tolls us, in a 
 straightforward manner, that the existence of matter is an 
 illusion; that time is nothing, abstracted from the succes- 
 sion of ideas in our minds ; ^ that space cannot exist willi- 
 out the mind;* tliat minds alone exist; and tli;tt these 
 
 1 Kant's conclusions fully confirni these profound remarl^s of 
 Berkeley (PrincipU-s, §§ 8') fF.). It was because the Cr!li(jufi of Pure 
 Reason asserted the dogma comhated hy the Irish idiilosojiher (the 
 ;//in(7-?n-j<,<i?{/' considered as existing indiqiendently of the phenomenon) 
 that it became involved in sci'pticism. 
 
 * Cf. our conclurtionH in § 71. 
 
 ' Pnnciplex, §98. ■* /'A. § 118.
 
 898 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 perceive ideas either by themselves or through the action 
 of the all-powerful Spirit on which they depend.^ 
 
 But besides these advantages, his philosophy also posses- 
 ses disadvantages. We need not repeat the petty objection 
 of his supposed adversaries, who make him say that we eat 
 and drink ideas and are clothed with ideas. We may, how- 
 ever, ask. What, on his theory, becomes of the vegetable 
 and animal kingdoms, which the more realistic Leibniz re- 
 gards as having objective existence ? If it be true that 
 unperceiving and unperceived things do not exist, what 
 becomes of the soul in deep sleep ? If the picture opposite 
 to my bed exists only because I see it, what minds perceive 
 it after I have gone to sleep, and thus hinder it from ceas- 
 ing to exist ? How shall we picture to ourselves a plurality 
 of human individuals, if space exists in the mind only ? 
 How does Berkeley know that there are other minds than 
 his own ? How, moreover, does the creative Spirit produce 
 sensible ideas in us ? All these points and many others re- 
 main unexplained ; for his deus ex machina explains nothing, 
 and his theory of intervention is of no more avail than oc- 
 casionalism and pre-established harmony. He is both a 
 thorough-going theologian and a philosopher ; his interests 
 are both scientific and religious, and he attacks materialism 2 
 not only as a theoretical error but as the source of the most 
 serious heresies.^ 
 
 1 Principles, § 155. 
 
 2 By materialism Berkeley understands not only the negation of 
 spiritual substance, but the view that there existi5, independently of the 
 mind, a substance, or substratum, of sensible qualities, which it per- 
 ceives. To assume the reality of matter is enough to stamp one as a 
 materialist in the Berkeleyan sense. 
 
 8 §§ 133 ff. — A system wholly similar to that cf Berkeley was taught 
 by his contemporary and colleague, the churchman Arthur Collier 
 (1680-1732), a disciple of Malebrauche and author oi Claris universalis, 
 or a Neio Inquiry after Truth, Being a Demonstration of the Non-existence 
 or Impossibility of an External World, London, 1713. [See G. Lyon, Un 
 idealiste Anglais au XVIII'. siecle {Revue phil. vol. 10, 1880). — Tr.]
 
 CONDILLAC 399 
 
 § 59. Condillac 
 
 The philosophy of Locke was introduced into France by 
 Voltaire.^ Here it found an original follower in the abbot 
 Etienne Bonnot de Condillac,^ the founder of absolute 
 sensationalism. 
 
 Locke distinguishes two sources of ideas : sensation and 
 reflection, wliile Condillac, in liis Traitc des sensations rec- 
 ognizes but one, making reflection a product of sensibilit3\ 
 His proof is ingenious. He imagines a statue, which is 
 organized and alive, like ourselves, but hindered b}' its 
 marble exterior from having sensations. Its intellectual and 
 moral life advances as the various parts of this covering are 
 removed. 
 
 Let us first remove the marble covering its olfactorj'- 
 organs. Now the statue has only the sense of smell, and 
 cannot, as yet, perceive anything but odors. It cannot 
 acquire any idea of extension, form, sound, or color. A 
 
 ^ 1094-1778. Lettres sur les Anglais, 1728; £lemenls de la pJiiloso- 
 pJiie de Newton, mift a la porlee de tout le monde, Amsterdam, 1738 ; La 
 metaplnjsique de Nevlon ou parallele des sentiments de Neivto7i et de Leib- 
 niz, Amsterdam, 1740 ; Candide ou sur roptimisme, 1757 ; Le philosnphe 
 ignorant, 1767. Simultaneously with these writings of Voltaire, the 
 Entretiens sur la pluralite des mondes of Fontenelle (1657-1757), and 
 the works of Maupertuis (1098-1759) made known to the French the 
 labors of Copernicus and Newton, which were continued by Lagrange 
 and Laplace (page 11). [On eighteenth century philosoi^hy in France 
 see Damiron, ^r^moires pour servir a Vhisloire de la philosophic au X VIIL 
 siecle, 3 vols., Paris, 1858-64 ; and IJarlholmess (p. 1'2). On Voltaire 
 see the works of Bersot, Strau.ss, John Morley, Desnoiresterres, and 
 Mayr. — Tr.] 
 
 2 Born at Grenoble, 1715; tutor of the Prince of Parma; abbot of 
 Mureaux ; died 1780. Besides the Traile des sensations (1754), he jiro- 
 duced the followiug works : Essai sur I'origine des counaissances huintnnes 
 (1710); Traite' des systemes (171'.)) ; Traitc des animnux,\l'ib\ Logiipie 
 (posthuniou.s, 1781) ; Laugue des auimaux (imst humous). Comi)lete 
 works, Pari.s, 1798; 1803, 32 vols, in 12mo. F. ilethord, Condillac ou 
 I'empirisme et le rationalisme, Paris, 1804.
 
 400 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 rose is placed before it. From the impression produced by 
 it, a sensation of smell arises. Henceforth it is, from our 
 point of view, a statue that smells a rose ; in reality, how- 
 ever, it is nothing but the odor of this flower. The statue 
 does not and cannot, as yet, possess the slightest notion of 
 an object ; it does not know itself as the subject of sensa- 
 tion; its consciousness, its "me," is nothing but the scent 
 of the rose, or rather, \vhat ive call the scent of the rose. 
 
 Since this impression and the resulting sensation is the 
 only thing with which our statue is occupied, that single 
 sensation becomes attention. 
 
 We take away the rose. Our statue retains a trace, or 
 an echo, as it were, of the odor perceived. This trace or 
 echo is ■memory. 
 
 We place a violet, a jasmine, and some asafoetida before 
 the statue. Its first sensation, the odor of the rose, was 
 neither agreeable nor disagreeable, there being nothing to 
 compare it with. But now other impressions and other 
 sensations arise. These it compares with its memory 
 images. It finds some agreeable, others disagreeable. 
 Henceforth the statue desires the former, and rejects the 
 latter. Towards these it entertains feelings of aversion, 
 hatred, and fear, towards those, feelings of sympathy, affec- 
 tion, and hope. That is to say, from the sensations experi- 
 enced by it, and their comparison, arise the passions, desires, 
 and volitions. I will signifies / desire. The will is not a 
 new faculty added to sensibility ; it is a transformation ol 
 sensation ; sensation becomes desire and impulse after 
 having been attention, memory, comparison, pleasure, and 
 pain. 
 
 From comparison, that is, from the multiplication of 
 sensations, arise, on the other hand, judgment, reflection, 
 reasoning, abstraction, in a word, the understanding. Our 
 statue perceives disagreeable odors, and at the same time 
 recalls other odors which gave it pleasure ; these past sen-
 
 CONDILLAC 401 
 
 sations reappear in opposition to the present sensation, not 
 as immediate sensations, but as copies or images of these 
 sensations, tliat is, as ideas. It directs tlie attention to two 
 different ideas and compares them. When tliere is double 
 attention, there is comparison ; for to be attentive to two 
 ideas, and to compare them, is the same thing. Now, the 
 statue cannot compare two ideas without perceiving, some 
 difference or resemblance between them : to perceive such 
 relations is to judge. The acts of comparison and judgment 
 are therefore merely attention ; it is thus that sensation be- 
 comes successively attention, comparison, and judgment. 
 
 Some odors, that is, some of the states experienced by the 
 statue, yielded pleasure, others yielded pain. Hence it will 
 retain in memory the ideas of pleasure and pain common to 
 several states or sensations. Pleasure is a quality common 
 to the rose-sensation, the violet-sensation, and the jasmine- 
 sensation ; pain is a c{uality common to the odor of asa- 
 foetida, decaying matter, etc. These common cliaracteristics 
 are distinguished, separated, ahsfr acted, from the particular 
 sensations with wliich they are associated, and thus arise 
 the abstract notions of pleasure, pain, number, duration, etc. 
 These are general idea.<!, being common to several states or 
 modes of being of the statue. We do not need a special 
 faculty to explain them. Abstraction itself, tlie highest 
 function of the understanding, is a modification of sensa- 
 tion, which, consequently, embraces all the faculties of the 
 soul. The mner perception^ or tlie me., is merely the sum of 
 the .sensations we novj have, and those which tvr hare had. 
 
 Condillac endows his statue with a single sense, — tlie 
 sense of smell, — nml then evolves all mental faculties out 
 of sensation.^ Any one of the live senses would have 
 served his pui])f)se equally ANidl. 
 
 ^ Condillac'fl ol)j<'ct in clioosiiig tlio least important of Uio five souses 
 is plain. If the sense of smell sufficos to make a <ciiii)ili(i' soul, tln'ii, 
 a y*or//V<r/, the coiiiliination of all five rciisl-s, or tin' IdIiI sctisihility, 
 will HuHicfj;. '^^
 
 402 MODEEN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 If now, we join to smell : taste, hearing, and sight, by 
 taking away one marble covering after another, then tastes, 
 sounds, and colors will be added to the odors perceived by 
 the statue, and its intellectual life will become so much 
 richer, more manifold, and complex. 
 
 There is, however, an essential idea which neither smell, 
 nor taste, nor hearing, nor even sight, can yield, and that is 
 the idea of an ohject, the idea of an external world. Colors, 
 sounds, odors, and tastes are mere sensations or states, not, 
 as yet, referred to external objects. Before external causes 
 can be substituted for its sensations, the statue must be en- 
 dowed with the most important of all senses : the sense of 
 touch. Touch alone can reveal to us the objective world, 
 by giving us the ideas of extension, form, solidity, and body. 
 Even sight cannot suggest them. Persons born blind can- 
 not, upon receiving their siglit, distinguish l)etween a ball 
 and a block, a cube and a sphere, until they t(mch these 
 objects.^ On\j after having touched things do we refer the 
 impressions received by our other senses, such as colors, 
 sounds, tastes, and smells, to objects existing outside of us. 
 Hence, touch is the highest sense, and the guide of the 
 other senses ; it is touch which teaches the eye to distribute 
 colors in nature. 
 
 Conclusion and summary : All our ideas, without excep- 
 tion, are derived from the senses, and especially from touch. 
 Though Condillac is a sensationalist, and a sensationalist 
 in the strict sense of the term, he 1^ not, on that account, a 
 materialist.2 He differs from Locke, who grants that mat- 
 
 1 Allusion to Cheselden's celebrated operation. 
 
 2 Sensationalism is usually, but erroneously, confused with materi- 
 alism. Sensationalism is a theory concerning the origin of our ideas, 
 an explanation of the phenomenon of mind {eine Erkenntnisstheorie, as 
 the Germans would say), while materialism is an ontology, a system of 
 metaphysics. Sensationalism and materialism are undoubtedly closely 
 related, for materialism is necessarily sensational. But the reverse is 
 not true.
 
 CUNDILLAC 403 
 
 ter can think, and agrees ^vith the Cartesians that com- 
 ptHinds cannot think, and eonseqnently that the subject of 
 sensation cannot be corporeal in its nature. The move- 
 ments of the body are, according- to him, merely occasional 
 causes of mental phenomena. ISIoreover, it is not certain 
 tliat the body is an extended substance, as Descartes claims. 
 But even if there were no real extension, that would not he a 
 suijicient reason for denijing the existence of bodies. Hence 
 the negation of extension as such does not, according to 
 Condillac, involve the acceptance of the innnaterialism of 
 Berkeley. He agrees with Leibniz that bodies might really 
 exist and yet not be extended in themselves, that their es- 
 sence might consist of something other than extension, and 
 that this might be merely a subjective phenomenon, or a 
 mode of perceiving them. At all events, there is something 
 other than ourselves ; that cannot be doubted. But what 
 may be the nature of this " other thing," the statue does not 
 know, nor do we know. That is, Condillac, the consistent 
 disciple of Locke, is a sceptic in metaphysics, but his scep- 
 ticism does not, as we have just seen, call in question the 
 existence of matter, nor, consequently, materialism, using 
 the term in the Berkeleyan sense. If to assume the reality 
 of matter is to be a materialist, then, of course, he is a ma- 
 terialist. But in tliat case, Descartes is also a materialist. 
 jMoreover, he too, like Descartes, curries favor with the 
 Church, which, in his capacity as a priest, he dare not 
 openly antagonize. True, the human soul is merely the 
 recipient of sense-impressions, and devoid of all faculties of 
 kiiowh'dgc except sensation; it is nothing Init a prolonged 
 and infinitely modified sensation. But that does not mean, 
 lie intimates, tliat it has aiwai/s l)een restricted to sensation 
 as tlie source of trnth : its ])resent nature dates from the 
 I-'aih Perhaps it was en<l<)wed with a higher faculty hcfore 
 the Fall. All we can say is that this is no longer the case. 
 It is hard to take th('S(! restrictions of the ahhe of iMu- 
 reaux seriously.
 
 404 MODERN PHILOSOPHY' 
 
 § 60. Progress of Materialism i 
 
 The empirical school's contempt for metaphysics refers 
 only to the clualistic metaphysics, and not to the system of 
 Ilobbes, Gassendi, and Democritus. Philosophy gradually 
 abandoned dualism. It might have adopted the im materi- 
 alism of Berkeley and Collier ; but this hypothesis, though 
 satisfying the monistic instinct, had against it the evidence 
 of facts and the native realism of the French and English 
 minds. Hence, philosophy continued, in spite of Berkeley, 
 to concede 'primary qualities to bodies. True, tastes, smells, 
 colors, sounds, and temperature are nothing but sensations 
 of the subject which perceives them, and do not exist, as 
 such, in the things themselves and outside of us. But ex- 
 tension, impenetrability, figure, motion, etc., are primary 
 qualities, i. e., inherent in a reality external to and inde- 
 pendent of our perception, and of these qualities bodies, or 
 matter, are composed. Hence, the latter has objective real- 
 ity, and does not owe its existence to our sensation, i. e., to 
 the mind, as Berkeley claimed. 
 
 The belief in the objective and absolute existence of 
 bodies persisted. Hobbcs's assertion that all suhstances are 
 bodies, and the hypothesis of Locke, according to which 
 matter can think, seemed less presumptuous when Leibniz, 
 repudiating the Cartesian teaching, substituted for extended 
 matter, matter endowed with force,^ a kind of intermediate 
 reality, or connecting link between brutal matter and pure 
 spirit. This conception made it possible for one to assume 
 a real and physical action of body on mind, without fear of 
 materializing spirit. Experience, moreover, on whose ter- 
 ritory the new philosophy had firmly established itself for 
 all time to come, advanced the cause of materialism by its 
 
 ^ See Damiron, Me'moires pour servir a Vhistoire de la philosoph'e au 
 dix-huitihne siecle, §§ 8 ff. 
 •^ Cf. pp. 310 f.
 
 PROGRESS OF MATERIALISM 405 
 
 emphatic declaration that body acts on mind, and that the 
 mental world depends on the physical world. 
 
 John Toland (1670-1721), a fellow-countryman of 
 Berkeley, whose genius, character, and fate remind one of 
 Bruno and Vanini, becomes the champion of materialism in 
 his Letters to Serena^ and his Pantheisticon (1710). Matter 
 is not, according to him, the " extended substance " of Des- 
 cartes, an inert, lifeless mass that receives its motion from 
 a transcendent deity ; it is an active substance, that is, force. 
 Extension, impenetrability, and action are three distinct 
 notions, but not three different things; they are simply 
 three different modes of conceiving one and the same mat- 
 ter.2 Matter is originally and necessarily active, and hence 
 does not receive its motion from Avithout; motion is its 
 essential and inseparable property, — as essential and in- 
 separable as extension and impenetrability. Since matter 
 as such is force, motion, and life, we do not need either a 
 soul of the world, in order to explain universal life, or au 
 individual soul as the source of i)sychical life and the A'ital 
 principle of the organic body. The liylozoistic and vital- 
 istic hypothesis is based on the erroneous conception that 
 matter is inert, that it is merely tlie theatre and the means, 
 and never the source, of action. The abandonment of this 
 false view will result in the collapse of the dualistic theory. 
 Body ceases to be a substance that cannot think, and soul or 
 mind is simply one of its functions. Furthermore, thought 
 does not belong to substance in general, as Spinoza assumes ; ^ 
 matter, though active, is unconscious in itself, and becomes 
 
 ^ Letters to Serena (Serena is Queen Sophia Cli.irlotto of Prussia, 
 the friend of Leibniz, at whose court Toland lived from 1701-17012), 
 followed by a Refutation of Spinoza, and a treatise on movement as the 
 essential jtroiK^rty of matter (London, 1701). [('!'. (!. Herthold, J(;///i 
 Toland und dcr Monismus ilrr (Jcgenwdrt, I Icidcllirri,', lS7(i ] 
 
 2 Let tern to Serena, pp. 230 ft". 
 
 • Deus est res coyilans (^Elli., II., I'rop. 2).
 
 406 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 conscious only in the brain (a view already held by Demo- 
 critus). There can be no thought without a brain ; thotujlit 
 is the function of this organ, as taste is a function of thfi 
 tongue.^ ' 
 
 Less bold in form but the same in substance are the con- 
 clusions of the Observations on Man^ the work of the phy- 
 sician and naturalist David Hartley (1704-1757). There 
 can be no thought without a brain. The brain is not the 
 thinking subject; the soul is the thinking subject. But 
 though the soul is entirely distinct from the body, it cannot 
 be regarded as essentially different from corporeal substance. 
 The action of the brain on thought is estal:)lished by the 
 facts, and proves conclusively that matter and mind differ 
 in degree and not in essence, for there can be no reciprocal 
 action between two essentially different substances. The 
 so-called material world represents an ascending scale of 
 substances, or rather forces ; these become more and more 
 refined and spiritualized, as we pass from mineral masses to 
 light. The distance from the stone to the luminous agent 
 is so great that one is tempted to oppose the latter to the 
 former as spiritual substances are opposed to material 
 substances. And yet no serious thinker would dream of 
 removing optical phenomena from the domain of physics. 
 The infinitely subtile, refined, and intangible substance 
 called light is none the less matter. Why, then, should we 
 not assume that the above-mentioned series continues be- 
 yond ether, and finally ends in thought or soul ? This 
 mental agent is so far removed from light, in fineness and 
 mobility, as the latter is from the stone and wood, without 
 on that account ceasing to he matter. 
 
 1 Paniheisticon, p. 15. 
 
 2 Observations on Man, his Frame, his Duty, and his Expectations, 
 London, 1749 ; 6th ed., 1834. [Cf. G. S. Bower, Hartley and James 
 Mill {Engl. PhUosophers), London, 1881; B. Schoenlank, Hartley und 
 Priestley, die Begriinder des Assoc iationisinus in England, Halle, 1882. 
 — Tk.i
 
 PROGRESS OF MATERIALISM 407 
 
 The white medullary substance of the brain and the spinal 
 marrow constitute the seat of sensation and the source of 
 voluntary motion. Every moditication of this substance is 
 accompanied by a corresponding modification in our soul- 
 life. The modifications of the cerebral and nervous sul> 
 stance, corresponding to those of the soul, are vibrations or 
 " tremblings " produced by external excitations and trans- 
 mitted tlu'ough the sensory nerves to the central portion of 
 the brain. The nervous substance, which may be perceived 
 by our senses and experimented on, most probably contains 
 an infinitely subtile and mobile fluid, which might be iden- 
 tified with electricity ^ and ether. The vibrations of tliis 
 fluid or ether cause sensations. When these vibrations are 
 reproduced a certain number of times, they leave traces ; 
 these traces are our ideas. Our soul-life depends entirely 
 on the association of these ideas, which, in turn, depends 
 on the association of sensations, i. e., vibrations of ether or 
 nervous fluid. True, these vibrations are not, as yet, sen- 
 sations ; they affect the body, and sensations affect the soul ; 
 they belong to the domain of physiology, and sensations 
 belong to the domain of psychology. But the fact tliat the 
 latter are effects of the former conclusively proves that cor- 
 poreal substance is analogous, if not identical, with think- 
 ing substance. 
 
 Joseph Ppjestley (1733-1804), tlieologian, philosopher, 
 and naturalist, to whom we are indebted for tlie discovery 
 of oxygen,^ considers, in his Disquisitions relating to Matter 
 and Spirit,^ tlie proofs of liis predecessors, ancient as well 
 
 * As lia.s Ijeen done, in our ooutury, }>y the Berlin scientist, E. tlu 
 Bois-Kcyniond. 
 
 ' Thus nain<'<l l)y Lavoisirr, wlio iccoL^ni/.cil it as one of the essen- 
 tial ehnnents of atmospheric air. 
 
 ' London, 1777. \'l'hi: Dnrlrinr of P/iilos()/)li!r(it Nrci'ssili/. London, 
 1777; Free DiscunKioua of the iJavlrincs af M<iiiri<ilism, Londnn, 177^ 
 -Tic]
 
 408 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 as modern, in favor of the materiality of the soul, and adds 
 some arguments of his own : 
 
 1. If the soul is an inextended substance, it does not 
 really exist in space ; for to be in space is to occupy a por- 
 tion of it, be it never so small. Hence the soul is not in 
 the body : such is the absurd conclusion which Cartesian 
 spiritualism compels us to draw. 
 
 2. Principia non sunt multiplicanda prcctcr necessitatem. 
 Now, there is no need of assuming for thought a new and 
 essentially different principle from the principles by which 
 science explains the phenomena of light, electricity, etc., 
 which show striking similarities with psychical phenomena. 
 
 3. The development of the soul runs parallel with that 
 of the body, on which it wholly depends. 
 
 4. There is not a single idea of which the mind is pos- 
 sessed but what may be proved to have come to it from the 
 bodily senses, or to have been consequent upon the percep- 
 tions of sense. 
 
 5. Our ideas of external objects, — the idea of a tree, for 
 example, — consist of parts, like their objects. How is it 
 possible that such ideas should exist in an indivisible and 
 absolutely simple soul ? 
 
 6. The soul ripens and declines. How can an absolutely 
 simple being without parts be increased, modified, or dimin- 
 ished ? 
 
 7. If man has an immaterial soul, every animal, which 
 feels, perceives, remembers, combines, and judges, must 
 have one also. 
 
 8. What is the use of the body, and why is the soul as- 
 sociated with it, if it can feel, tliink, and act independently 
 of it? 
 
 9. Spiritualism claims that an extended being cannot 
 think. But is it not still more inconceivable that an inex- 
 tended entity — a simple mathematical point — should 
 contain an infinite number of ideas, feelings, and volitions,
 
 PROGRESS OF MATERLVLISM 409 
 
 as the human soul does? The soul is a reality no less 
 manifold than the universe Avliich it reflects. 
 
 10. The will is determined by motives, reasons, and argu- 
 ments. Hence, spiritualism objects, if the soul is material, 
 matter is moved by motives, reasons, and arguments. 
 But the matter which materialism invests with tlie faculty 
 of thinking is not the gross and inert mass wliich it is at 
 first supposed to be ; it is the ether, that mysterious agent 
 which we know only by its manifestations, but which we 
 assume to be the basis of intellectual phenomena as well as 
 of extension, impenetrability, and movement. Besides, it 
 may be said, in answer to the spiritualists, that if the theory 
 of " matter influenced by motives " is objectionable to them, 
 their "simple substance influenced by an extended su1>- 
 stance " (in sensation and perception) is no less ol)jection- 
 able to the materialistic thinker. 
 
 11. If the soul, says spiritualism, is composed of parts, 
 atoms (or, as we should say nowadays, of living cells of 
 gray cortical substance), how can it be felt as a unity? 
 How does it become conscious of the me ? ^ This feeling, 
 this perception of the unity which is called tlie ego^ is con- 
 ceivable only in a real individual, in a unity, monad, or 
 atom, and not in a sum of monads, atoms, or individuals, 
 not in the whole nervous system. For a sum or whole is 
 merely an idea, a mental being; its parts alone have real 
 existence (nominalism). Hence these (the monads, atoms, 
 or individuals making up the nervous system) can feel 
 themselves, each for itself and separately, as unities or I's ; 
 but the nervous system, the whole, cannol, for the whole is 
 not an indivicbial, an ol)jfctive and existing icality. This, 
 as Priestley himself confesses,^ is the strongest, and. in fact, 
 
 1 In a word : How can the one arise from the many V 
 
 2 [I cannot find anyUiinf; in the Disf/uisllions to provi' tliis stalc- 
 nient. What Priestley does say is this: "This argnment has hecn 
 nnieh liaekncyt'<l, and much cnnfidcMl in hy mctai>hysicians ; t>ut, for 
 jny pari, 1 cannot iMiccivc, the least ftirce in it." (p. 118.) — Th.J
 
 410 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the only serious argument that spiritualism can oppose.^ 
 How can the one arise from the many? He declares that 
 he cannot explain the difficult}', but that, if it really is a 
 difficulty, it exists for spiritualism as well. Psychological 
 consciousness is nothing but plurality reduced to unity, or 
 unity derived from plurality, or, in a word, the synthesis 
 of the one and the many, i. e., an inexplicable mystery. 
 Spiritualism is as unable to tell how a multitude of ideas, 
 feelings, and volitions can constitute tlie unit}^ of self, as 
 materialism is powerless to explain how a multitude of 
 atoms can form a unity. Hence, spiritualism has no ad- 
 vantage over its adversary in this respect. 
 
 12. It is objected that the soul wars against the body, 
 that it is possessed of a self-moving power, while the body 
 needs a foreign mechanical impulse, that the body alone be- 
 comes weary and never the soul ; finally, that, if the human 
 soul is material, God liimself ceases to be a pure spirit. 
 Priestley replies that there are also conflicts between the 
 different tendencies of the soul, and yet that spiritualism 
 does not dream of referring each of these tendencies to a 
 principle or a chfferent suljstance ; that the body is not in- 
 ert, as was believed before the days of Leibniz, and that no 
 substance is without force ; that thought fags and exhausts 
 the brain, which is refreshed in sleep ; finally, that we cannot 
 extend our reasonings concerning finite beings to the infin- 
 ite, but that the " materiality " of God is more consistent 
 with the dogma of omnipresence than the opposite view. 
 
 Priestley appeals to the Bible, and believes that his sys- 
 tem can be reconciled with Christianit}^ and even with 
 Calvinism. 2 French materialism, however, does not share 
 
 ^ Albert Lange shares this view. In his History of Malerialmn, he 
 holds that the above argument hits the weak spot in materialism. 
 
 2 There is, indeed, a connecting link between Priestley's system 
 and the reformed dogma : we mean their common opposition to inde- 
 terminism. Indeterministic and Pelagian Catholicism offers material- 
 ism no such support.
 
 PROGRESS OF MATERIALISM 411 
 
 these illusions. In tlie Testament de Jean Mcslicr,^ which 
 Voltaire made public, we find the bold utterances of To- 
 land repeated. The same may be said of the writings 
 of the physician, Julien Offroy de la Metteie ^ (1709- 
 1751), who was one of the first outspoken materialists in 
 France. Curiously^ enough, tliis leader of the opponents 
 of spiritualism is a disciple, not of Toland, but of the man 
 whom French spiritualism recognizes as its head : Des- 
 cartes. We must remember that Descartes was not only 
 the author of the Meditations and the dualistic hypothesis, 
 but that he wrote the Treatise 07i the Passions of the Soid, 
 and founded the modern mechanical theor}-. Descartes not 
 only proved the existence of God and the spirituality of 
 the soul,^ but also showed '^ how all the limhs can he moved 
 hy the objects of the senses and hy the spirits without the 
 AID OF THE SOUL;"^ that it resides in the pineal gland; 
 that memory presupposes cerebral impressions ; that animals 
 are machines ; that the intellectual phenomena which we 
 discover in them can and must be mechanically explained. 
 The advance from the animal-machine of Descartes to the 
 homme-viachine is slight; and La ]Meltrie makes it. If 
 the animal can feel, perceive, remember, compare, and 
 judge, without the aid of an innnaterial soul, simply by 
 means of its nervous and cerebral organization, there is no 
 reason why we should concede a soul to man, Avhose sensi- 
 bility, will, and understanding are merel}' more highly 
 
 1 A curt of Etrepigny in Champagne, died 173."). 'J'cslami'iil de 
 J. Meslier, pul)lisli(.'d in 3 vols., with a preface and a biographical 
 introduction, by K. Charles, Amsterdam, 18G5. 
 
 2 Ilistolre naturelle de Vthne, The Hague (Paris), 1745; VHomme- 
 macli'ine, Leyden, 171 S; L'llomme-plnnle, Paris, 1718. "Works of I>a 
 Mettrie, London (ik-rlin), 1751. [Cf. Lange, lUstorij of Materid/isni.'] 
 
 3 Tliese "errors" are, in La Mettrie's opinion, notiiing Imt "a 
 trick to make the theologians swallow the poison of mechanism. 
 The anh'xd-jnarhine is Descartes's grandest discovery." 
 
 * Passions de I'dine, I., Art. 10.
 
 412 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 developed animal functions. Man is not an exception ; he 
 does not form a separate and privileged caste in universal 
 nature. The laws of nature are the same for all. There 
 can he no difference in this respect hetween men, hrutes, 
 plants, and animals. Man is a machine, hut a more com- 
 plicated machine than the animal : " he is to the ape or the 
 most intelligent animals, what Huyghens's planetary pen- 
 dulum is to a watch made by Julien Leroy." 
 
 This developed animal did not fall from the clouds, nor 
 did it arise, ready-made, from the bowels of the earth. It 
 is not the work of a supernatural creator, the realization of 
 an idea : it owes its origin to a natural evolution which 
 gradually evolves more and more perfect forms from the 
 elementary organisms. Tlie human species is no more a 
 separate creation than the other animal and vegetable spe- 
 cies ; its present form has been evolved from lower animal 
 forms, slowly and by progressive stages. The evolutionistic 
 and transformistic conception, familiar to ancient philoso- 
 phy,i reappears, in various forms, but wholly conscious of 
 its aims, in the Pensees sicr rinterprStation de la nature of 
 Denis Diderot,^ in the work, De la nature, of Robinet,^ 
 in the Palingenesie philosophiqiie of Charles de Bonnet,* 
 
 1 We found it in Anaximander, Empedocles, xVnaxagoras, and 
 Democritus. 
 
 2 Born at Paris, 1713; died 1784. The founder of the Encydo- 
 pedie (Dictionnaire rahonne des arts, des sciences el des metiers. Par 
 nne socie'te' de gens de letlres, 7nis en ordre el public par M. Diderot, Paris, 
 1751-1703). His most important philosophical writings are: Pensees 
 sur V interpretation de la nature, Paris, 1754 ; Reoe de D'Alemberl ; Let Ire 
 sur les aveurjles ; iSlements de physiologic. M. Assezat has edited the 
 Complete Works of Diderot from the original editions. He includes 
 what has been published at different periods, and the unpublished 
 manuscripts preserved in the Hermitage library (Paris, 1875). [On 
 Diderot see the works of K. Rosenkranz (1866) and John Morley 
 (1878, 1886).] 
 
 3 1723- 1789. De la nature, 4 vols. 8vo, Amsterdam, 1763-68. 
 
 * A Genevan, 1720-1793. La palingenesie philosophique ou idees sui 
 Vetat passe et sur I'e'tat futur des etres vivants, Geneva, 1769.
 
 PROGRESS OF MATERL\LISM 413 
 
 precursors of Lamarck and Darwin. According to Diderot, 
 the entire universe is an endless fermentation, a ceaseless 
 interchange of substances, a perpetual circulation of life. 
 Nothing lasts, everything changes, — species as luell as 
 individuals. Animals have not always been what they are 
 now. In the animal and vegetable kingdoms, individuals 
 arise, grow, decline, and die. Can we not say the same 
 for entire species ? Now, there is an afifinity, and pei'haps 
 identity, between kingdoms, just as between species. Thus, 
 who can ever exactly determine the boundaries between 
 plants and animals? Plants and animals are defined in 
 the same way. We speak of three kingdoms, but why 
 should not one emanate from the other, and why should 
 not the animal and vegetable kingdoms emanate from uni- 
 versal heterogeneous matter ? The evolution is wholly me- 
 chanical. Nature, with its five or six essential properties, 
 such as potential and active force, length, breadth, depth, 
 impenetrability, and sensihility, tvhich exists potcatially in 
 the inert molecule, and matter, sufiices to explain tlie world. 
 We should not search for designs (intentions') where there 
 are only accidental facts. The spiritualists say : Look at 
 man, that living proof of final causes ! What do they mean ? 
 The real man or the ideal man ? Surely not the real man, 
 for there is not a perfectly constituted, perfectly sound man 
 on the entire surface of the earth. The human species 
 consists of an aggregation of more or less deformed and 
 unhealthy individuals. Now, why should that make us 
 sound the praises of the alleged creator? Praises, indeed! 
 We have nothing but apologies to offer for him. And 
 there is not a single animal, a single plant, a single mineral, 
 of which we cannot say what has just l)een said of man. 
 Of what use are the phalanges in the cloven foot of the 
 hog? Of what use are the mamma' in males? 'I'lie act- 
 ual world is as a day-fly to the millions of wA (>r possil)le 
 worlds of the past and future; it is what the insect of
 
 414 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Hypaiiis is to man, wlio sees it live and die in the passing 
 of a day. The day of a woild lasts a little longer, that 
 is all. 
 
 These conceptions of the world and man are shared by 
 Helv^tkjs,^ who, like Thomas Hobbes and Mandeville,^ 
 considers egoism and self-interest as the true and sole mo- 
 tive of our acts; by the mathematician D'Alembert,^ 
 whose pliilosophy reveals a delicate tinge of scepticism, 
 which distinguishes it fa^■orably from its environment, and 
 brings it nearer to criticism; by the political economists 
 TuRGOT "* and Condorcet,-^ who construct a. positive phi- 
 losophy of history, based on the necessity of human actions 
 and the laAV of continued progress; by the Baron d'HoL- 
 BACH,6 whose Si/steme de la nature, published at London, 
 1770, under the pseudonym of Mirabaud, is a comijlete the- 
 ory of ontological and psychological materialism. Matter 
 and motion : these two words sum up everything. INIatter 
 and motion are eternal. The universe is neither governed 
 l)y a God nor by chance, but by immutable and necessary 
 laws. These laws do not depend on a personal power capa- 
 ble of modifying them ; nor do they form a brutal necessity, 
 a Fate hovering above things, a yoke imposed upon them 
 
 1 Claude Adrien, 1715-1771. De Ve.^pnt, Paris, 1758 (anonymous) ; 
 De Vhonime, de ses facidles et de son education, London (Amsterdam), 
 1772 (anonymous) ; Les procjres de la raison dans la recherche de la 
 vcritd, London, 1775. Complete works, Amsterdam, 1776 ; Zwei- 
 briicken, 1784; Paris, 1794; 1796 (this last edition in 10 vols., 12°). 
 
 2 Bernard de iVfandeville, 1670-1738. The Fable of the Bees, or 
 Private Vices made Public Benefits, London, 1714, 1719. 
 
 3 1717-1783. Author of the masterly Discours preliminaire of the 
 Encyclopedia, which he helped to found. iMclanr/es de Ulterature, d'kis- 
 toire et de philosophic, 5 vols., Paris, 1752. 
 
 * Discours siir les progres de Vesprit hnmain. etc. [Complete works 
 by Dupont de Xemours, 4 vols., Paris, 1808-1811.] 
 
 ^ Esquisse d'un tableau historique des progres de Vesprit humain (post- 
 humous work). 1794. 
 
 « 1723-1789.
 
 PROGRESS OF MATERIALISM 415 
 
 from without : they are merely the iiroijcrties of things, the 
 expression of their innermost nature. The universe is 
 neither an al)Solute monarchy () /(( Duns Scotus, nor a con- 
 stitutional monarchy it la Leibniz, but a republic. Theism 
 is the sworn enemy of science. Pantheism is merely a 
 shamefaced theism, or atheism in disguise. The mechani- 
 cal theor}^ sufficiently explains all things. There is no 
 finality in nature. Eyes were not made/o?- seeing, nor feet 
 for walking, but seeing and walking are the effects of a 
 certain arrangement of atoms, which, if different, would 
 produce different phenomena. There is no soul apart from 
 nervous substance. Thought is a function of the brain. 
 iNIatter alone is immortal ; individuals are not. The free- 
 will of the indeterminists is a denial of the universal order. 
 There are not two separate realms and two series of laws, 
 — physical laws and moral laws, — but one undivided and 
 indivisible universe, subject, in all its parts and at all peri- 
 ods, to the same necessity. 
 
 Finally, on the eve of the Revolution, the phj'sician Ca- 
 BANIS (1757-1808), in his Considerations generates su7' I'etude 
 de Vhomme et sur Ics rapports de son organisation piliysiqnc 
 avec ses facultes intellectuellcs et morales,^ formulated the 
 pi-inciples of psychological materialism with such frankness 
 and vigor as have never been excelled. Body and mind are 
 not only most intimately connected ; they are one and the 
 same thing. The soul is body endoAved with feeling. The 
 body or matter tliiuks, feels, and wills. Pliysiology iuid 
 psyc^hology are one and the s;im(^ science. Man is simply a 
 bundle of nerves. Thought is IIk; function of the brain, as 
 digestion is the function of the stomach, and (he secretion 
 of bile tlie function of the liver. 'Ihe imjjrcssions reaching 
 the brain cause it to act, just as tlie food introduced into 
 the stomach sets that organ in motion. It is the business 
 
 1 III Hm- Me'moires (le riiistllul, years I\'. and \1. (ITiiOainl 1798): 
 rti-riiit^-.l, I'aiis, 180 J.
 
 416 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 of the brain to produce an image of each particular impres- 
 sion, to arrange these images, and to compare them with 
 each other for the sake of forming judgments and ideas, as 
 it is the function of the stomach to react upon food in order 
 to dio-est it. Intellectual and moral phenomena are, like all 
 others, necessary consequences of the properties of matter 
 and the laws which govern beings.^ 
 
 On this latter point, philosophers, be they conservative or 
 radical, dogmatic or sceptical, jurists and litterateurs, natu- 
 ralists and pliysicians, agree. By subjecting the Deity him- 
 self to laws, Montesquieu simply denies God as an absolute 
 personal power. His God is the nature of things, in which 
 are orounded the necessary relations which we call laws.^ 
 Voltaire is a deist, but he assumes, with Locke, that mat- 
 ter can think. 3 J.J. Rousseau is a spiritualist in his way, 
 but 7iature, ivhich ive have ahandoned and to which we must 
 return, is his God also.* The pioneers of German litera- 
 ture, Lessing, Herder, and Goethe, combine with the highest 
 idealism the same naturalistic and monistic, if not material- 
 istic, tendency. What united these different thinkers was 
 their outspoken or secret opposition to Cartesian dualism, 
 which set up a separate order of things, called free spirit- 
 ual substances, not subject to the laws of nature, a kind of 
 caste or privileged aristocracy. Equality before the law 
 
 1 Closely related to the system of Cabanis is the intellectual or 
 cerebral physiology (known by the name oi phrenology) of Gall, Spurz- 
 heim and Broussais. 
 
 2 De r esprit des lots. I., ch. I. : Les loix, dans la signification la plus 
 etendue, sont les rapports necessaires qui derirent de la nature des choses ; 
 et, dans ce sens, tons les etres ont leurs lois : la divinite a ses his, etc. 
 
 8 See page 399, note 1. 
 
 * 1712-1778. Discours siir Forigine et les fondements de Vine'galite 
 parmi les Jwmmes, Paris, 1753 ; Le contrat social, 1762 ; ^mile ou de 
 V education, 11 ^>2. [ffiwrre.?, Paris, 1764 ; 1818-20; 1868. L. Moreau, 
 J. J. Rousseau et le siecle phUosophique, Paris, 1870; John Morley, 
 Rousseau, 2 vols., London, 1873.— Tr.]
 
 DAVID HUME 417 
 
 of nature, and (in view of the failure of sense-perception 
 and speculation to establish the freedom of indifference) 
 determinism for all^ without excepting even the Supreme 
 Being : these were the watchwords of the philosophers un- 
 til they became the watchwords of the Revolution in 1789. 
 
 § 61. David Hume ^ 
 
 "There are no bodies," the idealists dogmaticallj^ de- 
 clared; "there is no spiritual substance," was the equally 
 dogmatic assertion of the materialists. The Scotchman, 
 David Hume (1711-1776), an acute thinker and classi- 
 
 1 [Treatise on Human Nature, 3 vols., London, 1739-174:0; ed. by 
 Selby-Bigge, Clarendon Press, 1888. Hnme afterwards worked over 
 the three books of the Treatise, and published them under the follow- 
 ing titles: An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, 1748; A 
 Dissertation on the Passions; and An Enquiry concerning the Princinles 
 of Morals, 1751. The first and last of these works, reprinted from 
 the posthumous edition of 1777, have been edited, with introduction, 
 etc.," by J. A. Selby-Bigge, Oxford, 1894. Essays, Moral, Political, 
 and Literary, 1741. The Natural History of Religion, 1755. All of the 
 above-mentioned works, except the Treatise, were published under the 
 title. Essays and Treatises on Several Subjects, London, 1770. The 
 best edition of this collection (with introduction and notes), by T. H. 
 Green and T. H. Grose, 2 vols., London, 1875, new ed., 1889. The 
 Dialogues concerning Natural Religion appeared after Hume's death. 
 These, together with the Treatise, are published, witli introduction and 
 notes, by T. H. Green and T. H. Grose. 2 vols., London, 1874, new 
 ed., 1889. The Autobiography was published by Adam Smith, London, 
 1777. The essays on Suicide and the Ininwrtalify tf the Soul appeared 
 1783. Selections from the Treatise (H. L), by IL A. Aiken, in Series 
 of Modern Philosophers, New York, 1893; from Hume's ethical writ- 
 ings, by J. H. Hyslop, in tlie Ethical Series, Boston, 1893. Works on 
 Hume: F. Jodl, Leben und Philostq/hie Darid fhnne's, Halle, 1872; K. 
 PHeiderer, Empirismus und Skepsis in D. II.'s Phil., Berlin, 1871; 
 Mciiiong, Hume-Siudieu, 2 vols., Vienna, 1877, 18S2; G. v. Gizycki, Die 
 Ethik D. II.'s, Hreshiu, 1878; T. Huxley, Hume, London, 1879 ; \\ . 
 Knight, Hume (Philosophical Cla.i.tics), London, 1880; Introduction to 
 od. of Hume's works by T. H. Green. — Tr ] 
 
 •27
 
 418 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 cal historian of England,^ opposes to eacli of these schools 
 the doubts of Protagoras and Locke : Can the human mind 
 solve the ontological problem ? Is metaphysics, considered 
 as the science of the immanent essence and primary causes 
 of things, possible? In his Essays^ which are inimitable 
 masterpieces of acumen and clearness, modern philosophy 
 enters upon the path marked out by English empiricism. 
 The human mind begins to reflect upon its resources with 
 a view to ascertaining the pre-conditions of knowledge, the 
 origin of metaphysical ideas, and the limits of its capacity. 
 Philosophy becomes decidedly critical and positivistic. 
 
 For the old metaphysics, i. e., the alleged science of the 
 essence of things, " that abstruse philosophy and metaphysi- 
 cal jargon^ which, being mixed up with popular superstition, 
 renders it in a manner impenetrable to careless reasoners, and 
 gives it the air of science and loisdom,'''^ we must, according 
 to Hume, substitute criticism. In other words, we must 
 inquire seriously into the nature of human understanding, 
 and show, from an exact analysis of its powers and capa- 
 city, that it is by no means fitted for such remote and 
 abstruse subjects as traditional metaphysics busies itself 
 with. We must submit to this fatigue, in order to live at 
 ease ever after; a7id must cultivate true metapihysics with 
 some care, in order to destroy the false and adulterate. 
 
 Though criticism is more modest in its pretensions than 
 ontology, it is no inconsiderable part of science to know 
 
 1 History of England from the Invasion of Julius Ccesar, etc., 6 vols., 
 London, 1754-1763. Hume's historical work made a greater impres- 
 sion on his age than his philosophical works. He himself was espe- 
 cially proud of his achievements as a historian (see Letters of David 
 Hume to WiUiam Sfrahan. Now first edited by G. Birkbeck Hill, 
 Oxford, 1888). Oiu- age, however, has reversed this opinion. Hume, 
 the spiritual father of Kant, now takes precedence over Hume, the 
 rival of Robertson and Gibbon. 
 
 2 An Enquiry concerning Human UnderMinding, sect. I. [Green's 
 edition of Hume].
 
 DAVID HUME 4l9 
 
 the different operations of the mind, to separate them from 
 each other, to chiss them under theii' proper Iicads, and to 
 correct all that seeming disorder in which they lie involved, 
 when made the object of reflection and inquiry. This 
 science has the immense advantage over metaphysics* of 
 being* certain. Nor can there remain any suspicion that 
 this science is luicertain and chimerical; unless we slioidd 
 entertain such a scepticisiii as is entirely suhversioe of all 
 speculation^ and even action} To throw up all at once all 
 pretensions of this kind may justly he deemed more rash, pre- 
 cipitate, and dogmatical than even the boldest and most ajflr- 
 riiative philosophy? We esteem it worthy of the labor of 
 a philosopher to give us a true system of the planets, and 
 adjust the position and order of those remote botlies. IIow 
 nuich more highly should we value tliose who, with so 
 much success, delineate the parts of the mind, in which we 
 are so intimately concerned ! We have succeeded in deter- 
 mining tlie laws by wliich the revolutions of tlie planets 
 are governed. And there is no reason to despair of equal 
 success in our inquiries concerning the mental powers and 
 economy. All we have to do is to enter upon the enter- 
 prise with thorough care and attention.^ 
 
 Hume loves to call himself a sceptic, and lie is a sceptic 
 as regards dogmatic metaphysics. But from the above 
 explicit statements and man}- otlier like assertions, it 
 would seem that his philosophy is notliing but criticism. 
 It is not his purpose to renounce })hiloso}»hy or even meta- 
 physics, but to give it a different direction and a (htferent 
 object, to turn it from fruitless speculation, antl to estab- 
 lish it on the firm and certain foundation of experience* 
 Had Hume been an aljsolute sceptic lie could never have 
 produced an Iminanucl Kant. Now, whatever difference 
 
 * An Enquirij coiicerniiKj Iluinan Uitderstdndinq, srct. I., jt. 10. 
 2 Id., p. IL'. 8 Id. 
 
 * Id., sect. XII., i.iuL III., p. 13;}.
 
 420 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 there may be between the results of these two thinkers, 
 one thing is certain : The spirit of their theoretical philos- 
 ophy, the fundamental conception of their investigations, 
 and the goal at which they aim, are perfectly identical. 
 Theirs is the critical spirit, and positive knowledge the 
 goal at which they aim. To claim for Kant the sole honor 
 of having founded criticism is an error which a closer study 
 of British philosophy tends to refute. 
 
 The following is the substance of Hume's inquiries con- 
 cerning human understanding : — 
 
 All our perceptions may be divided into two classes : 
 ideas or thoughts and impressions. Ideas are the less lively 
 perceptions, of which we are conscious when we reflect on 
 our sensations. By the term " impression " Hume means 
 all our more lively perceptions, when we hear, or see, or 
 feel, or love, or hate, or desire, or will.-' Nothing, at hrst 
 view, he says, seems more unbounded than thought ; but 
 a nearer examination shows that it is really confined within 
 veiy narrow limits, and that it amounts to no more than 
 the faculty of compounding, transposing, augmenting, or 
 diminishing the materials afforded us by the senses and 
 experience. All the materials 0/ our thinking are derived 
 either from our outward or inward sentiment; the mixture 
 and composition of these belongs alone to the mind and will? 
 Or, in other terms, all our ideas or more feehle perceptions 
 are copies of our impressions or more lively ones. Even the 
 idea of God arises from reflecting on the operations of our 
 own mind, and augmenting, without limit, those qualities 
 of oroodness and wisdom which we observe in ourselves. 
 
 o 
 
 1 An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, sect. TI., p. 14. 
 
 2 Id., p. 14. We have here, word for word, the teaching of Kant, 
 who, however, adds that this mixtm-e and composition depends on 
 a priori forms, inherent in the mind. Hmne also assumes that it 
 depends on principles; but, absolute sensationalist that he is, derives 
 the principles themselves from sensation, experience, and habit.
 
 DAVID HUME 421 
 
 We may prosecute this inquiry to what length we please ; 
 we shall always find that every idea which we examine is 
 copied from a similar impression. A blind man can form 
 no notion of colors ; a deaf man of sounds.^ Moreover, all 
 ideas, compared to sensations, are naturally faint and 
 obscure.^ 
 
 After having proved that all our ideas are derived from 
 sensation, Hume shows that they succeed each other in a 
 certain order, and that there is a certain connection be- 
 tween them. This order and this connection presuppose 
 certain principles of connection, according to which our 
 thoughts succeed each other. They are: Resemblance, con- 
 tiijiiity in time or ijlacc, and causality. The question here 
 presents itself : Are these principles, especially causality, 
 the most important of all notions, a priori^ innate, anterior 
 to all impressions, as idealism claims, or are they ideas 
 in the sense which sensationalism attaches to the term, 
 i. e., faint sensations, copies of similar impressions ? Kant 
 answers the first question in the affirmative ; Hume, the 
 latter. He devotes all the efforts of his criticism to the 
 notion of causality, force, power, or necessary connection, 
 and the explanation of its origin. This idea, like all 
 others, arises from sensation. Experience teaclies us that 
 one billiard-ball communicates motion to another ujjou 
 impulse, and that the latter moves in a certain direction. 
 We have no a priori knowledge either of the movement or 
 of the direction of the movement. Between what we call 
 the cause and what we call the effect there is no necessary 
 connection that could ever be discovered a priori. The 
 effect is totally different from the cause, and consequt'ntly 
 can never be discovered in it. The mind can never pos- 
 sibly find the effect in the supposed cause, by the most 
 accurate scrutiny and examination ; and whi-rcver exj)eri- 
 
 ^ An KTifjuirij concerniu<j Ilujii'tn Understititillng, s^'vi. II.. \k I.ji 
 2 Id., p. 10.
 
 422 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 ence shows us that a particular effect succeeds a particular 
 cause, there are always many other effects which, to reason, 
 must seem fully as consistent and natural.^ In vain, there- 
 fore, should we pretend to determine any single event, or 
 infer any cause or effect, without the assistance of obser- 
 vation and experience. In a word, the idea of cause is no 
 exception to the rule according to which all our ideas arise 
 from sensation. 
 
 It remains to be seen how it is derived, what is the 
 impression from wliich it comes? 
 
 Let us first observe — and here the sensationalistic ex- 
 planation strikes a difficulty which Hume fully appreciated 
 
 let us observe that what we call power, force, energy, or 
 
 necessary connection can never be perceived. One object 
 follows another in an uninterrupted succession ; that is all 
 we see ; but the power or force which actuates the whole 
 machine is entirely concealed from us. We know that, in 
 fact, heat is a constant attendant of flame ; but what is the 
 connection between them we cannot conjecture or even 
 imagine. Since external objects give us no such idea, let 
 us see whether this idea be derived from reflection on the 
 operations of our own minds. It may be said that we are 
 every moment conscious of internal power ; while we feel 
 that, by the simple command of our will, we can move the 
 oro-ans of our body, or direct the faculties of our mind. 
 But the influence of volition over the organs of the body is 
 a fact which, like all other natural events, can be known 
 only by experience. The motion of our body follows upon 
 the command of our will. Of this we are every moment 
 conscious. But the means by which this is effected; of 
 this we are so far from being conscious that it must for- 
 ever escape our most diligent inquiry .^ A man suddenly 
 struck with a palsy in the leg or arm, or who had newly 
 
 1 An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, sect. IV., p. 27. 
 
 2 Id., sect. YLI., pp. 51 f.
 
 DAVID HUME 423 
 
 lost those members, frequently endeavors, at first, to move 
 them, and employ them m their usual offices. Here he is 
 as much conscious of power to command such limbs as a 
 man in perfect health. But consciousness never deceives. 
 Consequently, neither in the one case nor in the other, are 
 we ever conscious of any power. We learn the influence 
 of our will from experience alone. And experience onl}^ 
 teaches us how one event constantly follows another, with- 
 out instructing us in the secret connection whicli binds 
 them together and renders them inseparable. 
 
 The idea Avhich we are examining is not derived from 
 any consciousness within ourselves. Nor do we get it 
 through the senses. Then how does it originate ? As we 
 can have no idea of an3^hing which never appeared to our 
 outward sense or inward sentiment, the necessary conclu- 
 sion seems to be that we have no idea of power or connec- 
 tion at all, and that these words are absolutely without 
 meaning, when employed either in philoso^jhical reason- 
 ings or common life. 
 
 l>ut there still remains one method of avoiding this con- 
 clusion ; it is to explain the idea of cause by custom or liabit. 
 We are accustomed to seeing certain events in constant 
 conjunction. When any natural object or event is presented, 
 it is impossible for us, by any sagacity or pcnetiation, to 
 discover or even conjectui-e, without experience, what event 
 will result from it, or to carry our foresight Ijcyond that 
 object which is immediately present to tlie memory and 
 senses. But wlien one particular s])ecies of event lias al- 
 ways, in all instances, been conjoined with another, we 
 make no longer any scruple of foretelling one upon llie 
 appearance of the otlier.' We o])serve, for example, tluit 
 there is a constant connection between h(!at and flame, be- 
 tween solidity and weight, and we are accustomed to infer 
 the existence of onf frriin tlx; existence o'i tlic other. We 
 
 ' An J'Jriqniri/ rrnicf iniiii/ //iminu b'nt/rrstnutlini/, si-ci. \'II., p. (t2-
 
 424 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 then call the one object, cause, the other, effect. We sup- 
 pose that there is some connection between them, some 
 power in the one by which it infallibly produces the other, 
 and operates with the greatest certainty and strongest 
 necessit^^. 
 
 Hence the idea of cause does not arise from any single 
 impression, from the perception of a particular object ; it 
 springs from our habit of seeing several impressions and 
 several objects follow each other in regular order. This 
 connection, therefore, which we feel in the mind, this cus- 
 tomary transition of the imagination from one object to its 
 usual attendant, is the sentiment or impression from which 
 we form the idea of power or necessary connection. 
 
 To recapitulate : Every idea is copied from some preced- 
 ing impression or sentiment ; and where we cannot find 
 any impression, we may be certain that there is no idea. 
 In all single instances of the operation of bodies or minds, 
 there is nothing that produces any impression, nor conse- 
 quently can suggest, any idea of power or necessary con- 
 nection. But when many uniform instances appear, and 
 the same object is always followed by the same event, we 
 then begin to entertain the notion of cause and connection. 
 We then feel a new sentiment or impression, to wit, a cus- 
 tomary connection in the thought or imagination between 
 one object and its usual attendant ; and this sentiment is 
 the original of that idea which we seek for. 
 
 Hume, whose criticism aims to overthrow the principle of 
 causality on the ground that it is neitlier an a jjriori pos- 
 session, nor derived from any particular experience, is nev- 
 ertheless a thorough-going determinist in morals and in 
 history. Indeed, he is, with Hobbes and Spinoza, one of 
 the founders of positive historical science, which is based on 
 the principle of necessary human action. " It is universally 
 acknowledged," he says,^ "that there is a great uniformity 
 
 1 An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, sect. VIII., p. 68.
 
 DAVID HUME 425 
 
 among the actions of men, in all nations and ages, and that 
 human nature remains still the same, in its principles and 
 operations. The same motives always produce the same 
 actions; the same events follow from the same causes. 
 Ambition, avarice, self-love, vanity, friendship, generosity, 
 public spirit ; these passions, mixed in various degrees, and 
 distributed through society, have been, from the beginning 
 of the world, and still are, the source of all the actions and 
 enterprises which have ever been observed among mankind. 
 Would you know the sentiments, inclinations, and course 
 of life of the Greeks and Romans ? Study well the temper 
 and actions of the French and English ; you cannot be much 
 mistaken in transferring to the former most of the obser- 
 vations which you have made with regard to the latter. 
 Mankind are so much the same, in all times and places, 
 that liistory informs us of nothing new or strange in this 
 particular. Its eliief use is only to discover the constant and 
 universal principles of human yidturer 
 
 " Were there no uniformity in human actions, and were 
 every experiment which we could form of this kind irregu- 
 lar and anomalous, it were impossible to collect any general 
 observations concerning mankind. . . . The vulgar, who 
 take things according to their first appearance, attribute 
 the uncertainty of events to such an uncertainty in the 
 causes as makes the latter often fail of their usual opera- 
 tion, though they meet with no impediment in theh- o])era- 
 tion. But philosophers, observing that almost in every part 
 of nature, there is contained a vast variety of springs and 
 principles, which arc hid l)y tlieir minuteness or remoteness, 
 find that it is at least possible tlie contrariety of events 
 may not proceed from any eontingency in the cause, but 
 from the secret operation of contrary causes. This possibility 
 is converted into certaintij by farther observation, when they 
 remark that, upon an exact scrutiny, a contrariety of effects 
 always betrays a contrariety of causes, and proceeds from
 
 426 MODERN PHILOSOniY 
 
 their mutual opposition. A peasant can give no better 
 reason for the stopping of any clock or watch than to say 
 that it does not commonl}^ go right, but an artist easily 
 perceives that the same force in the spring or jjendulum 
 has always the same influence on the wheels, but fails of its 
 usual effect, perhaps by reason of a grain of dust, which 
 puts a stop to the whole movement. From the observation 
 of several parallel instances, philosoj^hers form a maxim 
 that the connection between all causen and effects is equally/ 
 necessary^ and that its seeming uncertainty in some instances 
 proceeds from the secret opposition of contrary causes.^' The 
 human will is governed by laws which are no less steady 
 than those wliich govern the winds, rain, and clouds (Spi- 
 noza) ; the conjunction between motives and voluntary 
 actions is as regular and uniform as that between the cause 
 and effect in any part of nature.^ 
 
 This truth has been universally acknowledged among 
 mankind ; it is the source of all the inferences which we 
 form concerning human actions, the basis of all our infer- 
 ences concerning the future. Physical necessity and moral 
 necessity are two different names^ but their nature is the 
 same. Natural evidence and moral evidence are derived 
 from the same principle. In spite of the reluctance which 
 men have to acknowledge the doctrine of necessity in 
 words, they all tacitly profess it. " Necessity, according 
 to the sense in which it is here taken, has never yet been 
 rejected, nor can ever, I think, be rejected by any philoso- 
 pher. . . . By liberty, then, we can only mean a power of 
 acting or not acting, according to the determinations of the 
 will (Locke). ... It is universally allowed that nothing 
 exists without a cause of its existence, and that chance, 
 when strictly examined, is a mere negative word, but it is 
 pretended that some causes are necessary, some not neces- 
 sary. Here then is the advantage of definitions. Let any 
 
 1 An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, sect. VIII., pp. 71 f.
 
 DAVID HUME 427 
 
 one define a cause, without comprehending, as a part of the 
 definition, a necessary connection with its effect. Whoever 
 attempts to do that will be obliged either to employ unin- 
 telligible terms, or such as are S3-nonymous to the term 
 wliich he endeavors to define, and if the definition above 
 mentioned be admitted, liberty when opposed to necessity, 
 not to constraint, is the same thing witli chance, which is 
 universally allowed to have no existence." 
 
 Experience refutes the dualism of will and physical 
 agencies ; it also destroj^s the dualism of reason and in- 
 stinct. Animals, as well as men, learn many things from 
 experience, and infer that the same events will always fol- 
 low the same causes. By this principle they become 
 acquainted with the more obvious properties of external 
 objects, and gradually, from their birth, treasure up a 
 knowledge of the nature of fii^e, water, earth, stones, heights, 
 depths, etc., and of the effects which result from their 
 operation. The ignorance and inexperience of the young 
 are here plainly distinguishable from the cunning and 
 sagacity of the old, who have learned, from long observa- 
 tion, to avoid what hurt them, and to pursue what gave 
 ease or pleasure. A horse that has been accustomed 
 to the field becomes acquainted with the proper height 
 which he can leap, and will never attempt A\hat ex- 
 ceeds liis force and ability. An old greyhound will trust 
 the more fatiguing part of the chase to the younger, and 
 will place himself so as to meet the hare in her doubles ; 
 nor are the conjectures which he forms on this occasion 
 founded in any tiling hut hia observation and experience. An- 
 imals, therefore, are not giiid('(l in llicsc infciciitcs Ity 
 reasoning, neither are children, neither are the generality 
 of mankind, in their oidinary actions and eonchisions ; 
 neither are \\\v, jiliilosopliei's lliemselves. Animals nn- 
 doubt(,'dly owe a large part of their k#iowledge to wliat we 
 call instinet. But the crjierii/icnial rcnsonlmj itself ^ iclu'ch
 
 428 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 we possess in coinmon with beasts, is nothing hut a species of 
 instinct or mechanical power that acts in us unknown to 
 ourselves} 
 
 The universal propensity to form an idea of God, if not 
 an original instinct, is at least " a general attendant of 
 human nature." ^ Tliis proposition contains the gist of 
 Hume's theology. He is an outspoken opponent of all 
 positive religions, and fuids it hard to regard them as 
 " anything but sick men's di'eams," or " the playsome 
 whimsies of monkeys in human shape." ^ The doctrine of 
 immortality is " a riddle, an enigma, an inexplicable mys- 
 tery." He opposes the following arguments to miracles : 
 There is not to be found in all history any miracle attested 
 by a sufficient number of men, of such unquestioned good 
 sense, education, and learning, as to secui'e us against all 
 delusion in themselves ; of such undoubted integrity, as to 
 place them beyond all suspicion of any design to deceive 
 others ; of such credit and reputation in the eyes of man- 
 kind, as to have a great deal to lose in case of their being 
 detected in any falsehood ; and at the same time attesting 
 facts performed in such a public manner, and in so cele- 
 brated a part of the world, as to render the detection 
 unavoidable. The passion of surprise and wonder gives a 
 sensible tendency towards the belief of those events from 
 which it is derived. Supernatural relations abound among 
 ignorant and barbarous nations; or if a civilized people 
 has ever given admission to any of them, that people will 
 be found to have received them from ignorant and bar- 
 barous ancestors, who transmitted them with that invio- 
 lable sanction and authority which always attend received 
 opinions. It is a general maxim that no testimony is suf- 
 ficient to establish a miracle, unless the testimony l:)e of 
 
 ^ A71 Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, sect. IX., pp. 85 if 
 - The Naturcd History of Religion, sect. XV., p. 362. 
 3 Id., p. 362.
 
 DAVID HUME 429 
 
 such a kind that its falsehood -\voidd be more miraculous 
 than the fact which it endeavors to establish.^ 
 
 Although Hume's conclusions in theology, as well as in 
 ethics and psychology, wholly agree, on the one hand, with 
 the doctrines of the rationalist Spinoza, and on the other, 
 with those of the French materialists, the Scotch philoso- 
 pher nevertheless maintains to the end liis scepticism, as he 
 loves to call it, or criticism, or positivism, as we designate 
 it nowadays, in order to distinguish it from the scepticism 
 of the ancients. True scepticism, as he conceives it, does 
 not consist in perpetually doubting all things, but in lim- 
 iting " our enquiries to such subjects as are best adapted 
 to the narrow capacity of human understand ing.^ . . . 
 This narrow limitation, indeed, of our enquiries, is, in 
 ever}^ respect, so reasonable, that it suffices to make the 
 slightest examination into the natural powers of the human 
 mmd, and to compare them Avith their objects, in order to 
 recommend it to us." ^ 
 
 The most salient feature of this scepticism, as compared 
 either with metaphysical dogmatism, or the naive object- 
 ivism of cominon-seiue, is that it distinguishes between 
 things as they are and things as they appear to us. With- 
 out any reasoning, says Hume,* we always suppose an 
 external universe, which depends not on our perception, 
 but would exist, though Ave and every sensible creature 
 were absent or anniliilated. This very table, Avhich Ave 
 see Avhite, and Avliicli Ave feel liard, is believed to exist, 
 independent of our perception, and to be something exter- 
 nal to our mind, wliieh perceives it. Our presence bestows 
 not being on it; our absence does not anniliilali- it. It 
 preserves its existence uniform and entire, independent of 
 the situation of intelligent beings, Avho perceive or con- 
 template it. But this universal and primary opinion of 
 
 ^ Exsay concerning Human UndcrsUiudiiKj, soct. X.. ]>. !M. 
 
 2 Id., XII, p. 133. « Id. * /,/., p. 121.
 
 430 MODERN rHlLOSOPHY 
 
 all men is soon destroyed by the slightest philosophy. 
 And no man who reflects ever doubted that the exist- 
 ences which we consider, when we say, this house and that 
 tree^ are nothing but perce])tions in the mind, and fleeting 
 copies or representations of other existences which remain 
 uniform and independent. Even the iirimary qualities 
 of extension and solidity are perceptions of the mind. 
 — (Berkeley.) 
 
 Are these perceptions produced by external objects re- 
 sembling them? Here experience, which alone can 
 answer this question of fact, is and must be entirely silent. 
 Do external objects at least exist? Experience is equally 
 silent on this point. However, to doubt the existence of 
 bodies is an excessive scepticism, which action and employ- 
 ment, and the common occupations of life, subvert. This 
 excessive scepticism, or Pyrrhonism, true scepticism rejects 
 as barren.^ Every time it attempts to reappear, nature 
 puts it to flight. Nevertheless, the existence of bodies, 
 being a matter of fact, is incapable of demonstration. The 
 only objects of real knowledge and demonstration are quan^ 
 tit}^ and number. Experience decides concerning all mat- 
 ters of fact and existence, and experience never goes 
 beyond probability .^ — (Carneades.) 
 
 Hume's teachings were violently opposed, in the name of 
 common-sense and morality, by Thomas Reid,^ the founder 
 of the so-called Scottish school, and by his disciples, 
 
 ' Essay concerning Hximan Understanding, p. 130. 
 
 2 111 excluding physics from the sphere of pure knowledge, the 
 idealist Plato advances the same opinion. 
 
 3 1710-1796. Professor at Glasgow. Inquiry into the Human Mind 
 on the Principles of Common-sense, London, 1764 ff. [Selections from 
 the Inquiry by E. Sneath in Series of Modern Philosophers, Xew York, 
 1892. Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, 1785; Essays on the 
 Active Poioers of Man, 1788. Complete works, ed. by W. Hamilton, 
 Edinburgh, 1827 ff. On the Scotch School see James McCosh, The 
 Scottish Philosophy, London, 1875 ; Xew York, 1890. — Tr.].
 
 DAVID HUME 431 
 
 Oswald,! Beattie,^ and Dugald Stewart.^ All of these 
 men were psychologists of merit, but, with the exception of 
 Reid, mediocre metaphysicians.^ In order to refute Hume 
 it was necessary to put oneself in his position, — the critical 
 position, — to use liis own weapons, to renew tlie inquiry 
 into the human understanding, and, if possible, to make it 
 more thorough and complete. Kant, the most illustrious 
 continuer and the most acute critic of the Scotch philosopher, 
 saw that very clearly. ''Common-sense," he says, "is a 
 precious gift of God. But we nuist prove it by its acts, by 
 deliberate and rational thought and speech, and not appeal 
 to it as to an oracle, vv^henever reasons fail us. It is one of 
 the subtle devices of our times to appeal to common-sense 
 when our knowledge gives out, and the shallowest fool con- 
 fidently measures his strength with the profoundest think- 
 er's. . . . And what is this appeal to common-sense but a 
 bid for the applause of the rabble, which cannot but bring 
 the blush to the cheek of the philosopher? I cannot help 
 
 1 Appeal to Common Sense in Belialf of Religion. Edinlnirgh, 17GG. 
 
 " 173.5-1803. Professor at Edinburgh. EssaiJ on the Nature and 
 Tmmutahiliiy of Truth in Opposition to Sophis'ry and Scepticism, Edin- 
 burgh, 1770 : Th<^orij of Lan(jua(je, London, 1778 ; Elements of the Science 
 of Morals, 1790-1793. 
 
 8 1753-1828. Elements of the I'hilusnplni of the Human Mind. ?, vols., 
 London, 1792-1827; Outlines of Moral Philosoph;/. 1793 [ed. witli critical 
 notes by J. McCosli, London, lSf>3. Collected works, ed. by W. Ham- 
 ilton, 10 vols., Edinburgh, 18.54-1858. Thomas Brown (1778-1820), 
 a pupil of Stewart, approximates Hume (Tnqnirij into the Relation of 
 Cause and Effect, Edinb., 1803 IT.) — Tn.]. 
 
 * In the i)liilosophy of William Hamilton (1788-185')), the Scottish 
 school, following the example of the Academy, culminates in scepti- 
 cLsm, which it had vindertalcen to combat in David Hume. Sir W. Ham- 
 ilton was noted for his Discussions on Philosophy and Literature, London 
 and Edinburgh, 1852; 3d ed., 1800; Lectures on ^fetaphysics, 2d ed., 
 1800. and on L.otfic, 2d ed., 1800. See J. Stuart Mill, Examination of 
 Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy, Lomlon, 1805; 5th ed., 1878; 
 [Veitch, Ilautilton {Philosopliical Classics)}.
 
 4S2 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 thinking that Hume had as much good sense as Beattie." 
 Reason can be corrected by reason alone.^ 
 
 It is true, Hume's philosophy was not unassailable. 
 There were breaks in his criticism ; difficulties were eluded 
 rather than solved. If experience is the sole source of knowl- 
 edge, whence arises the exceptional character of absolute 
 certainty which Hume himself concedes to mathematics ? If 
 there is nothing in the intellect which was not previously 
 in the senses, how shall we explain the ideas of cause, 
 necessary connection, and necessity? As was seen, the 
 Scotch criticist explains the idea of necessary connection 
 by the principle of habit. After the constant conjunction 
 of two objects, we are determined by custom alone to expect 
 the one from the appearance of the other. But this explan- 
 ation does not suffice. The idea of necessity cannot come 
 from experience alone, for the widest experience supplies 
 us only with a limited number of cases ; it never tells us 
 what haj^pens in all cases, and consequently does not yield 
 necessaiy truth. Besides, it is not true that the notion of 
 causality is that of necessary contiguity in time.^ Causality 
 signifies connection, and therefore contains an element not 
 
 ^ Prolegomena zu einer jeden lAinftigen Metaphysik, Preface, vol. III. 
 (Rosenkranz), p. 8. 
 
 2 What succession, as Thomas Reid aptly remarks, is older and 
 more regularly observed than that of day and night ? Now, it never 
 occurs to any one to consider night as an effect of day, and day as the 
 cause of night. JMoreover, there is this peculiarity about the truths of 
 experience that the certainty we get from them is susceptible of in- 
 crease and diminution. After a second successful test, the physician 
 is more convinced of the virtue of his medicine than after the first, 
 and so on, until a long line of authentic cases changes into certainty 
 what was at first a mere presumption and surmise. The case is quite 
 different with a truth like the following : Nothing happens without a 
 cause. The child, whose experience has just begun, believes in it with 
 the same instinctive force as the adult and the old man, and experi- 
 ences multiplied by the myriads can neither increase nor diminish its 
 certainty.
 
 DAVID HUME 433 
 
 included iu the notion of contiguit}-. Now, Hume expressly 
 states that one event follows another^ hut that we can never 
 observe any tie between them. They seem conjoined^ but never 
 connected.^ Hence, if experience never shoivs us a cause, 
 but onl}' a succession of events (for that is what Hume 
 means by the ill-cho§en term conjunction, wliich is synony- 
 mous with connection), must we not either negate the idea 
 of causation, or infer a diif erent origin for it ? 
 
 At this point Hume's criticism is corrected and com- 
 pleted by that of Kant.^ 
 
 ^ An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, sec. VII., p. 62. 
 
 - [Before the advent of Kant's criticism, German philosophy was 
 dominated by the Leibnizo- Wolffian school (see pp. 368 f.), which cul- 
 minated in a form of eclecticism similar to the English common-sense 
 philosophy. J. H. Lambert (1728-1777), one of Kant's correspondents, 
 attempts to reconcile Wolff and Locke, German metaphysics and Eng- 
 lish empiricism (Kosmologische Briefe, Augsburg, 1761) ; N. Tetens 
 (1736-1805), who influenced Kant, aims to reconcile the rationalistic 
 and sensationalistic psychology ( Versuch iiber die menschlicke Natur, 
 1776); M. Knutzen (died 1751), Kant's teacher, endeavors to reconcile 
 Wolffian metaphysics, Newton's natural philosophy, and orthodox 
 theology. Other representatives of this eclectic movement are the so- 
 called popular philosophers, whose chief aim is to popularize philosophy : 
 Moses Mendelssohn (1729-1786; complete works, 7 vols., Leipsic, 
 1813-44) ; C. Garve (1712-1798), the translator of Ferguson's and A. 
 Smith's writings ; J. J. Engel (1741-1802 ; Der Philosoph f/ir die Welt, 
 1775-77); T. Abbt (1738-1766; Vom Tode furs Vaterland, Berlin, 
 1761); Ernst Platner (1741-1818; Philosophische Aphorismen, 1776); 
 F. Nicolai (1733-1811). To the Aufkldrung also belong the deist 
 II. S. Reiinarus (1694-1765; Ahhandlnngen run den vornehmsten W(dir- 
 heiten der nalUrlichen Religion, Hamburg, 1754, 6th ed., 1794; aud the 
 poet G. E. Leasing (1729-1781). — Tii.]
 
 434 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 § 62. Kanti 
 
 Immanuel Kant,2 jjQj.j^ in KonigsLerg, Prussia, 1724, 
 
 was the son of plain people. His paternal grandparents 
 
 emigrated to Germany from the fatherland of Hume. 
 
 After pursuing his studies at the University of his native 
 
 1 [For the period beginning with Kant see, besides the general and 
 modern histories of philosophy, the works of Chalybseus, Biedermann, 
 Miclielet, Willni, Fortlage, Harms, Zeller, Seth, Eoyce, etc., mentioned 
 on pp. 12-15 ; also O. Liebmann, Kant und die Epigonen, Stuttgart, 
 1865. — Tr.] 
 
 2 Kant's complete works, published by: G. Hartenstein, 10 vols., 
 Leipsic, 1838-39 ; new edition, 8 vols., Leipsic, 1867-69 ; Rosenkranz 
 and Schubert, 12 vols., Leipsic, 1838-42 ; [with notes in Kirchmann's 
 Philosoplmche Bibliothek, Heidelberg, 1880 ff. The three Critiques and 
 several other works, ed. by K. Kehrbach, in Reclam's Universal-Bib- 
 liolhek, Leipsic. A new edition is being prepared by the Berlin 
 Academy of Sciences. B. P>dmann has published Reflexionen Kanfs 
 ztir tritischen Philoxophie in 2 vols., Leipsic, 1882-84 ; R. Reicke, Lo.^e 
 Blatter aus KanCs NacJdass, Kbnigsberg, 1889, 1895]. Charles Villers, 
 Philosophie de Kant, Metz, 1801 ; Amant Saintes, Histoire de la vie et 
 de la philosophie de Kant, Paris, 1844 ; V. Cousin, Lemons sur Kant, 
 Paris, 1842, 4th ed., 1864 [Engl. tr. by A. Henderson, London, 1870] ; 
 £mile Saisset, Le scepticisme, iSnefidhne, Pascal, Kant, Paris, 1865; 
 D. Nolen, La critifjue de Kant et la melaphysique de Leibniz, Paris, 1875; 
 M. Desdouits, La philosophie de Kant d'aprh les trois critiques, Paris, 
 1876 ; [F. Paulsen, Versuch einer Entwickelungsgeschichte der kantischen 
 Erkenntnisstheorie, Leipsic, 1875 ; A. Riehl, Der philosophische Kriticis- 
 mus, etc., vol. I., Leipsic, 1876 ; E. Caird, The Philosophy of Kant, 
 London, 1876 ; same author, The Critical Philosophy of Kant, 2 vols., 
 London and New York, 1889; C. Cantoni, E. Kant, 3 vols., Milan, 
 1879-1883 ; Adamson, The Philosophy of Kant, Edinbixrgh, 1879 ; W. 
 Wallace, Kant {Philosophical Classics), London, 1882; K. Fischer's 
 Kant in his History of Philosophy (see p. 12) ; F. Paulsen, Was Kant 
 uns sein kann {V. f. w. Ph., pp. 1-96, 1881) ; Journal of Speculative 
 Philosophy, ed. by W. T. Harris, July and October numbers, 1881; 
 J. G. Schurman, Kant's Critical Problem (Phil. Rev., XL, 2, 1893) ; 
 E. Adickes, Kant-Studien, Kiel and Leipsic, 1895 ; same author. Bibli- 
 ography of Writings by Kant and on Kant, in the Philosophical Revieiv, 
 beginning with vol. II., 3 ff. See also Schopenhauer's Kritik der 
 Kantischen Philosophie, and T. H. Green's Lectures on the Philo.^ophy 
 of Kant. —Tr.]
 
 KANT 435 
 
 city (1740-1746), Kant became a private tutor, tlien a 
 Piivatdocent in the University of Konigsberg (1755), 
 where he taught logic, ethics, metaphysics, mathematics, 
 cosmography, and geography. He was made full Professor 
 in 1770, and continued his lectures until 1797. In 1804 
 he died, rich in honors and in years. Kant never left his 
 native province, and never married. He enjoyed good 
 health, was absolutely regular in his daily habits, free from 
 the cares of family-life, and, for three-quarters of a cen- 
 tury, devoted to science and intellectual pleasures. Thus 
 he realized, in a certain measure, the ideal of the philoso- 
 phers of Athens and Rome ; but his cheerful temperament 
 and sociable disposition softened the harshness in the char- 
 acter of the Stoic sage. When we remember, besides, that 
 he was a reformer in philosophy, it will hardl}- surprise us 
 to hear that history likens him to Socrates. 
 
 His philosophical writings may be divided into two sep- 
 arate classes. Those of his dogmatic period ^ betray the 
 disciple of Leibniz and Wolff ; though anticipating, espe- 
 cially liis Trdiime eines Geistcrseliers (17()G), the teach- 
 ings of his maturer years. Those of his second period 
 (1770-1804), during which the influence of Hume led 
 him to break with dogmatism, present a new philosophy. 
 Chief among them are : De vnindi sensibilis atque intclligi- 
 hllis forma et j^rincijiiis'^ (1770); Kritik dcr reinen Ver~ 
 nunft (1781 ; 2d edition, revised, 1787) : ^ liis master-work, 
 
 * To the first period l)elon;;.s his Allf/emeine Naturgeschkhte unci 
 Theorie ties Himmeh, one of the masterpieces of general physics. [For 
 the development of Kant's critical philosophy consult, especially, the 
 works of Paulsen, Riehl, and Caird, mentioned in the preoedinc; note, 
 as well as Hartmann's KanCs I'lrkeiinliuan-lheone, etc., Leipsic, 18!)l. 
 -Tk.] 
 
 2 [Translated into Knglish, with an introduction and discussion, by 
 W. .1. Kckoff, New York, 1894. — Tn.] 
 
 2 [Separate editions of the Kriti/,; \>y Ki'luliadi (l)nsed u]i(iii ilu' 
 first edition). P.. Krdrnann, and K. Adickcs (l>ot li Imsril upon llir sec- 
 ond). Kngl. traiislalions (of 2d ed.) by Aleiklcjolin (lioliti's Library),
 
 436 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 wliich forms the basis of the following: Prolegomena zu 
 einerjeden kuiiftigen Metapkysik'^ (1783); Grundleyung zur 
 Metaphysik der Sitten"^ (1785); Metaphysische Anfangs- 
 griinde der Naturwissenschaft^ (1786) ; Kritik der prakti- 
 schen Vernunft^ (1788); Kritik der l/rtheilskraft^ (1190); 
 Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft^ 
 (1793). 
 
 Our age, as Kant often says, is the age of criticism ; and 
 by that word he understands the philosophy which, before 
 affirming, weighs, and, before assuming to know, inquires 
 into the conditions of knowledge. Not only is the philoso- 
 phy of Kant criticism in this general sense ; it is also 
 criticism in the special sense of being a theory of ideas ; it 
 is critical, as distinguished from the extreme theories of 
 Leibniz and Locke, in that it discriminates {KpiveLV, dis- 
 cernere}, in the formation of ideas, between the product of 
 sensation and the product of the spontaneous activity of 
 
 London, 1854; (of 1st ed., with supplements of 2d), by Max Miiller, 
 London, 1881 ; Paraphrase by Maliaffy and Bernard, London and 
 New York, 1889 ; Selections (from Critique of Pure Reason, Critique oj 
 Judgment, and ethical writings) by J. Watson {Modern Philosophers), 
 2d ed., New York, 1888. See also Stirling's partial translation of the 
 Critique in the work cited, p. 437, note 1. — Tr.] 
 
 1 [Engl. tr. by Mahaffy and Bernard, London and New York, 
 1889; by Bax {Bohn's Library). — Tr.] 
 
 2 {^Foundation of the Metaphysics of Ethics; Engl. tr. by T. K. 
 Abbott, 4th ed., London, 1889. — Tr.] 
 
 3 [Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science ; Engl. tr. by Bax 
 (Bohn's Library). — Tr.] 
 
 4 [Critique of Practical Reason; Engl. tr. by T. K. Abbott in same 
 volume as above. — Ti?.] 
 
 6 [Critique of Judfjment ; Engl. tr. by J. H. Bernard, London and 
 New York, 1892. — Tr.] 
 
 * [Relir/ion tvithin the Bounds of Pure Reason; first part tr. by T. K. 
 Abbott in the same volume with the ethical writings, .mpra. Trans- 
 lations of the Philosophy of Law and Principles of Politics, including 
 essay on Perpetual Peace, by W. Hastie, Edinburgh, 1887, 1891. 
 -^Tr.]
 
 KANT 437 
 
 pure reason. It acknowledges with sensationalism that the 
 matter of our ideas is furnished by the senses ; A\ith idealism 
 it claims that their /o;v?i is the work of reason, — that reason, 
 by its own laws, transforms into ideas the given manifold of 
 sensation. Criticism neither aims to be sensationalistic nor 
 intellectualistic in the extreme sense of these terms, but 
 transcendental ; i. e., going beyond {transcend ens) the sen- 
 sationalistic and idealistic doctrines, it succeeds in reaching 
 a higher standpoint, which enables it to appreciate the rela- 
 tive truth and falsehood in the theories of dogmatism. It 
 is a method rather than a system, an introduction to philos- 
 ophy rather than a finished system. Its motto is the 'yvoidt 
 aeavTov of Socrates, which it interprets to mean : Before 
 constructing any system whatever, reason must inquire into 
 its resources for constructing it. 
 
 In its examination of reason, criticism carefully separates 
 the chfferent elements of this faculty, and, true to the critical 
 spirit whence it springs, distinguishes between the theo- 
 retical order, the practical order, and the a^sthetical order. 
 Reason resembles a queen, who, under three different 
 names, governs three separate states, each having its own 
 laws, customs, and tendencies. In the tlieoretical spliere, 
 it manifests itself as the faculty of knowing, or the sense 
 of truth ; in the practical sphere, as the active faculty, or 
 the sense of goodness ; in the ffisthetical sphere, as the 
 sense of beauty and teleological fitness. The Kantian [)hi- 
 losophy gives each of these three spheres its due, exam- 
 ining one after another, without prejudice or dogmatic 
 prepossessions. 
 
 I. Critique of Pure Reason 1 
 
 And, first of all, it asks : What is knowlfdgc? 
 
 An idea taken by itself (man, earth, lieat) is not knowl- 
 
 ' [H. Vaihiiij((jr, Cmmncnlnr zu Knnfs Kritik tier rrimii Vinmnft, 
 vol. J., Stuttgart, lb«l ; vul. 11, //;., ISlfL'; II. Colxrw, KauCs Tkeorieder
 
 438 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 edge ; in order to become knowledge, the ideas of man, 
 earth, and heat must be combined with otlier ideas ; there 
 must be a subject and a predicate, i. e., a judgment. Ex- 
 amples : Man is a responsible being ; the earth is a planet ; 
 heat expands bodies. Hence, all knowledge is formulated 
 into propositions ; all knowledge is judgment, but not every 
 judgment is knowledge. 
 
 There are analytic judgments and synthetic judgments.^ 
 The former merely analyze {avaXveiv) an idea, without ad- 
 ding anything new to it. Example : Bodies are extended. 
 The predicate extended adds nothing to tlie subject that 
 is not already contained in it. This judgment tells me 
 notliing new ; it does not increase my knowledge. When, 
 on the other hand, I say : The earth is a planet, I make a 
 synthetic judgment, i. e., I join {avvTiOrjixL) to the idea of 
 the earth a new predicate, the idea of a planet, which can- 
 not be said to be inseparable from the idea of the earth ; 
 nay, it has taken man thousands of years to connect it with 
 the latter. Hence, synthetic judgments enrich, extend, and 
 increase my knowledge, and alone constitute knowledge ; 
 Avhich is not the case with analytic judgments. 
 
 But here Kant makes an important reservation. Not 
 every synthetic judgment is necessarily scientific knowl- 
 edo-e. In order to constitute real scientific knowledge, 
 with which alone we are here concerned, a judgment must 
 be true in all cases ; the union which it establishes between 
 subject and predicate should not be accidental, but neces- 
 
 Erfahrung, Berlin, 1871, 2d ed., 1885 ; J. Volkelt, Kanfs Erl-enntnhstheo- 
 rie. etc., Leipsic, 1879 ; E. Pfleiderer, KantUcher Ki-iticismus und englische 
 Philosophie, Tubingen, 1881 ; J. K. Sthling, Text-hook to Kant, Edin- 
 burgh and London, 1881 ; Watson, Kant and his English Critics, Lon- 
 don, 1881 ; G. S. Morris, Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (Griggs's 
 Philosophical Classics), Chicago, 1882 ; K. Lasswitz, Die Lehre Kant's 
 von der Idealildt des Raumes und der Zeit, Berlin, 1883. — Tr.]. 
 
 1 Kriiik der reinen Vernunft (Ilosenkrauz), p. 21 ; Prolegomena, 
 p. 16.
 
 KANT 439 
 
 saiy. " It is warm," is undoubtedly a synthetic judgment, 
 but it is accidental and contingent, for it may be cold to- 
 morrow ; hence it is not a scientilic proposition. Wlien- 
 ever, however, you say : Heat expands, you state a fact 
 which will be as true to-morrow and a thousand years from 
 now as it is to-day ; you state a necessary proposition and 
 a concept properly so-called. 
 
 But what right have I to affirm that this proposition is 
 necessar}^, universal, true in every instance ? Does expe- 
 rience reveal to me all cases, and are there no possible 
 cases, beyond our observation, in which heat does not ex- 
 pand the boches which it usually expands ? Hume is right 
 on this point. Since experience always furnishes oidy a 
 limited number of cases, it cannot yield necessity and 
 universality. Hence, a judgment a posteriori, i. e., one 
 based solely on experience, cannot constitute scientific 
 knowledge. In order to be necessary, or scientilic, a judg- 
 ment must rest on a rational basis ; it must be rooted in 
 reason as well as in observation ; it must be a judgment 
 a priori. Now, mathematics, physics, and metaphysics 
 consist of synthetic judgments a priori.^ Hence, to sum 
 up : Knowledge may be defined as synthetic judgment 
 a priori. This is Kant's answer to his preliminary ques- 
 tion : What is knowledge ? 
 
 How can we form synthetic judgments a priori? In 
 other terms : Under what conditions is knowledge possible ? 
 This is the fundamental problem which Kantian criticism 
 undertakes to solve.- 
 
 It is possible, Kant answers, providcfl the senses fnrnish 
 the materials for a jndgment, and reason the cement 
 needed to unite tlieni. Take the proposition already cited: 
 Heat expands bodies. This proposition contains two dis- 
 
 1 Prolegomena, \>\i. 22 &. — Before Kant's tnuc, mathematical pro 
 poKitioiiH were regarded as analytic. 
 ' Proleyomeiia, pp. L'S IT.
 
 440 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 tinct elements: (1) the elements furnished by sensation: 
 heat, expansion, bodies ; (2) an element not given by sen- 
 sation, bnt derived solely from the intellect: the causal 
 relation wliich the sentence in question establishes between 
 heat and the expansion of bodies. What is true of our 
 example is true of every scientific judgment. Every scien- 
 tific judgment necessarily contains sensible elements and 
 pure or rational elements. In denying the former, idealism 
 ignores the fact that persons born blind have no idea of 
 color, and, consequently, no notion of light ; in denying 
 the rational, innate, a priori element, sensationalism forgets 
 that the most refined senses of the idiot are incapable of 
 sup'frestingr a scientific notion to him. The critical philos- 
 ophy occupies a place between these two extreme theories, 
 and recognizes both the role of sensibility and that of pure 
 reason in the formation of our judgments. 
 
 But we must make a more penetrating analysis of the 
 faculty of Ivnowledge. As we have just seen, it is divided 
 into two sub-faculties, one of which furnishes the materials 
 of our knowledge, while the other fashions them, or makes 
 concepts of them. Hence, our examination of reason, in 
 the broad sense of faculty of knowledge, will take up: 
 (1) the sensibility (intuitive reason) and (2) the under- 
 standing proper.^ 
 
 1. Critique of Sensibility^ or Transcendental ^stJietic 
 
 We now know in a general way that knowledge is the 
 common product of sensibility and the understanding. 
 But what are the conditions of sense-perception, or, to use 
 Kant's language, intuition {Anschauung) ? 
 
 Sensibility, we said, furnishes the understanding with 
 the materials of its knowledge. But the materials them- 
 selves, of wliich the garment is to be made, already have 
 
 1 Krilik, p. 28.
 
 KANT 441 
 
 a certain shape; they are no h3nger absolutely raw ma- 
 terials : the latter have been subjected to the preliminary 
 processes of spinning and weaving. Or, in other words, 
 our sensibility is not purely passive ; it does not turn 
 over to the understanding the materials which the latter 
 needs, without adding something of its own ; it impresses 
 its stamp, its own forms, upon things ; or, as one might sa}', 
 it marks the perceived object just as the outline of our hands 
 is traced upon a handful of snow. It is in particular 
 what the faculty of knowledge is in general : both receptive 
 and active ; it receives a mysterious substance from without, 
 and makes an intuition of it. Hence, there are, in every 
 intuition, two elements : a pure or a priori element and an 
 a j^osteriori element, form and matter, something that reason 
 produces spontaneously and something, I know not what, 
 derived elsewhere. 
 
 What is this form ? What are the a j^riori elements 
 which our sensibility does not receive, but draws from its 
 own nature and adds to each of its intuitions, just as the 
 digestive apparatus adds its juices to the swallowed food, 
 in order to transform it into chyle ? These a priori intui- 
 tions, which sensationalism denies, and whose existence the 
 Critique of Pure Reason proves, are space^ the form of the 
 outer sense, and time^ the form of tlie inner sense. Space 
 and time are original intuitions of reason, prior to all expe- 
 rience : this is the innnortal discovery of Kant, and one of 
 the fundamental teachings of the critical philosophy.^ 
 
 The following proofs may be offered in support of tlie 
 view that space and time come from reason and not from 
 experience: (1) Although tlie infant has no accurate notion 
 of distance, it tends to withdraw from disagreeable objects 
 and to ap[)roach sucli as give it pleasure. Hence it knows 
 a priori that such objects are in front of it, by the side of 
 it, beyond it, etc. Prior to all other intuitions, it has the 
 » Krilik; pp. ;n-51.
 
 442 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 idea of before^ beside, beyond, i. e., the idea of space, of which 
 these are but particuhir applications. The same is true of 
 time. Prior to all perception, the child has a feeling of 
 before and after, without which its perceptions would be a 
 confused, disordered, disconnected mass. That is, prior or 
 a priori to every other intuition, it has the idea of time. 
 
 (2) Another proof that space and time are a priori intui- 
 tions: Thought may abstract from everything that fills 
 space and time ; in no case can it abstract from space and 
 time themselves. This proves that these intuitions, instead 
 of coming from without, are, so to say, of a piece with 
 reason ; that they are, in the inaccurate language of dog- 
 matic philosophy, innate, that they are, in the last analysis, 
 identical with reason. 
 
 (3) But the decisive proof of the a-priority of the ideas of 
 space and time is furnished by mathematics. Arithmetic 
 is the science of duration, the successive moments of which 
 constitute number. Geometry is the science of space. Now 
 arithmetical and geometrical truths possess the character of 
 absolute necessity. No one would seriously maintain : My 
 previous experience teaches me that three times three are 
 nine, or that the three angles of a triangle are equal to two 
 right angles, etc., for everybody knows that such truths are 
 independent of experience. Experience, being restricted 
 to a limited number of cases, cannot give a truth the abso- 
 lute and unquestionable character possessed by the axioms 
 of mathematics ; these truths do not spring from experience 
 but from reason: hence the sovereign authority which 
 characterizes them, and the impossibility of doubting them 
 for a single instant. But such truths are concerned with 
 space and time. Hence, space and time are intuitions a 
 priori. 
 
 Shall we call them general ideas formed by comparison 
 and abstraction? But an idea thus formed necessarily 
 contains fewer characteristics than the particular idea ; the
 
 KANT 443 
 
 idea of man is infinitely less comprehensive and poorer 
 than the particular idea of Socrates, Plato, or Aristotle. 
 Now, who would be bold enough to assert that universal 
 space contains less than a particular space, or, infinite time, 
 less than a fixed period of time ? The ideas of space and 
 time are, therefore, not the results of an intellectual opera- 
 tion, of the comparison of different sj^aces, from which the 
 general idea of space is derived; or of a comparison of 
 moments of duration, whence arises the general idea of 
 time. They arc not results, but principles, conditions a 
 priori and sine quiLus non of perception. The common 
 man imagines that he perceives space and time, that space 
 and time are, just like their contents, objects of perception. 
 But as a matter of fact, it is as impossible for them to be 
 perceived as it is for the eye to see itself (its image in the 
 mirror is not the eye itself). We see all things in space, 
 but we cannot see space itself, nor perceive duration inde- 
 pendently of its content. All perception presupposes the 
 ideas of space and time ; and unless we liad these ideas 
 a priori^ unless reason created tliem prior to all its intu- 
 itions, unless they pre-existed as original and inalienable 
 forms, sense-perception could never take [)lace. 
 
 We now know tlie con(htions under wliicli sense-percep- 
 tion operates. It depends on the a p)riori ideas of space 
 and time, which are, as it were, the prehensile organs of 
 sensibility. These ideas are not images corresponding to 
 external objects. There is no object called space, nor an 
 object called time. Time and space are not objects of per- 
 ception, but modes of jHrceiving objects, instinctive habits, 
 inhering in the thinking subject. 
 
 The tranHcendental idealiti/ of S|)aee and time : such is 
 the ijnpoitant conclusion reached by tlie critical examina- 
 tion of sensibility, the mene thekel of dogmatism. Let us 
 see what tliis conclusion iinj)bes. If neither space nor 
 time exists independently of reas-^ijii and its intuitive activ-
 
 444 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 ity, then things, considered in themselves and independently 
 of the reason which thinks them, have no existence in time 
 or space. Hence, if sensibility, in consequence of an in- 
 stinctive and inevitable habit, shows us things in time and 
 space, it does not show them as they are in themselves, 
 but as they appear to it through its spectacles, one of 
 whose glasses is called time ; the other, space. As they 
 appear to it ! which means that sensibility gives us appear- 
 ances, or (f)atv6fjb6va, and that it is incapable of giving 
 us the thing-in-itself, the vovjxevov. And since the under- 
 standing obtains the materials which it needs exclusively 
 from the senses, since there is no other channel through 
 which the materials can come, it is evident that it always 
 and necessarily operates upon phenomena, and that the 
 mystery concealed beneath the phenomenon forever bafdes 
 it, as it forever baffles the senses. 
 
 2. Critique of the Understanding^ or Transcendental Logic'^ 
 
 Kant distinguishes, in the general faculty of knowledge, 
 between sensibility, which produces intuitions or sensible 
 ideas, and the understanding, which elaborates them. 
 In the understanding he again distinguishes between the 
 faculty of judgment, i. e., tlie faculty of connecting the 
 intuitions with each other according to certain a priori 
 laws {Verstand), and the faculty of arranging our judg- 
 ments under a series of universal Ideas ( Vernunft, reason, 
 in the narrowest sense of the word). The inquiry con- 
 cerning the understanding is therefore subdivided into the 
 critique of the faculty of judgment (Verstand) and the 
 critique of reason proper ( Vernunft'), or, to use Kant's own 
 language, into the Transcendental Analytic and the Tran- 
 icendental Dialectic. 
 
 1 Kritik, pp. 55 fi.
 
 KANT 445 
 
 A. Transcendental. Analytic 
 
 Just as the intuitive faculty perceives all things in time 
 and space, reason moulds its judgments according to cer- 
 tain forms or general concepts, which, in philosophy, have 
 been called categories, ever since the days of Aristotle. 
 Kant agrees with Hume that the highest category, the idea of 
 cause, conceived as the necessary relation between two phe- 
 nomena, is not derived from experience. Hume, however, 
 regards it as the result of our habit of seeing certain facts 
 constantly conjoined together, and consequently considers 
 it as a prejudice useful to science, but without metaphysi- 
 cal value. Kant, on the other hand, defends its validity ; 
 and from the impossibility of deriving it from experience, 
 infers that it is innate. The idea of cause and all other 
 categories are, accorcUng to him, a priori functions of the 
 understanding, means of knoivledge and not objects of knowl- 
 edge, just as time and Space are, according to the same 
 philosopher, modes of seeing (iyituendi) and not objects of 
 intuition. 
 
 Not content with proving, against empiricism, that the 
 categories are innate, Kant attempts to make out an in- 
 ventory of them, and to deduce them from a principle. 
 He gives us a complete list; indeed, far too complete a 
 list. His love of symmetry impels him to add a category 
 of limitation (which Schopenhauer ingeniously calls a false 
 window), and a category of being and non-being {Dasein 
 und Nichtsein), which he erroneously distinguishes from 
 the concepts of reality and negation. As far as the logi- 
 cal deduction of a priori ideas is concerned, we must confess 
 that it is merely a plum desiderium ; no one before Hegel 
 has really made a serious attempt to solve this problem. 
 
 The tlieory of judgment which Kant linds in traditional 
 logic, serves as his guide in the discovery and classifica- 
 tion of the categories. Indeerl, ho says, tlic judgment is
 
 446 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the liigliest function of the understanding. Now the cate- 
 gories are the forms according to which wo judge. Hence 
 there are as many categories as there are kinds of judg- 
 ments. Logic enumerates twelve of them: (1) the uni- 
 versal judgment (All men are mortal) ; (2) the particular 
 judgment (Some men are pliilosophers) ; (o) the singular 
 judgment (Peter is a mathematician) ; (4) the affirmative 
 judgment (Man is mortal); (5) the negative judgment 
 (The soul is not mortal) ; (6) the limiting judgment (The 
 soul is immortal); (7) the categorical judgment (God is 
 just) ; (8) the hypothetical judgment (If God is just, he will 
 punish the wicked) ; (9) the disjunctive judgment (Either 
 the Greeks or the Romans are the leading nation of anti- 
 quity) ; (10) the problematical judgment (The planets are, 
 perhaps, inliabited) ; (11) the assertory judgment (The earth 
 is round) ; (12) the apodictic judgment (God must be just). 
 The first three express totality, plurality, and unit}', i. e., 
 in a word, the idea of quantitij ; the fourth, fifth, and sixth 
 express reality, negation, and limitation, or, the idea of 
 quality ; the seventh, eighth, and ninth express substan- 
 tiality and inherence, causality and dependence, and reci- 
 procity, or, in short, relation ; fmally, the tenth, eleventh, 
 and twelfth express possibility and impossibility, being 
 and non-being, necessity and contingency, i. e., the idea of 
 modality. 
 
 There are, therefore, twelve categories, arranged in 
 threes, under four groups or fundamental categories : quan- 
 tity, quality, relation, and modality. One of these, relation., 
 governs and embraces all the rest. It is the highest cate- 
 gory, since every judgment, whatever it may be, expresses 
 a relation.^ 
 
 From these four cardinal categories four rules or prin- 
 ciples necessarily follow, which are, therefore, also a priori : ^ 
 
 (1) From tlie standpoint of quantity, every phenomenon, 
 1 Kritik, p. 79. 2 la.^ pp. 131 ff.
 
 KANT 447 
 
 i. e., eveiything presented by the intuitive faculty as exist- 
 ing in space and in time, is a quantity, i. e., a fixed extent 
 and a fixed dui'ation. Tliis principle excludes the hyjjoth- 
 esis of atoms. 
 
 (2) From the standpoint of quality, every phenomenon 
 has a certain content, a certain degree of intensity. This 
 principle excludes the hypothesis of the void. 
 
 (3) From the standpoint of relation, all phenomena are 
 united by the tie of causality ; which excludes the hypoth- 
 esis of chafice ; there is, moreover, a reciprocal action 
 between the effects and their causes ; which excludes the 
 idea of fatiim. 
 
 (4) From the standpoint of modality, ever}' phenomenon 
 is possible that conforms to the laws of space and time, 
 and every phenomenon is necessary., the al)sence of which 
 would imply the suspension of these laws; which excludes 
 miracles. 
 
 The first and second of these principles constitute the law^ 
 of continuity ; the third and fourth, the law of causality. 
 
 These categories and the principles which follow from 
 them form the inire., innate, a priori element, and, as it 
 were, the patrimon}' of the understanding (^Vcrstand). 
 Tlie latter does not receive them ; it draws them from its 
 ov.'ii inner nature ; it docs not find them in the phenomenal 
 world ; it imposes them upon it.^ These conclusions of the 
 transcendental logic are of the liigliest importance. But, 
 before we develop them, we must, in a few words, cxi)lain 
 what Kant means by the schematism of pure reason."^ 
 
 The analysis of the faculty of knowledge has outlined 
 the boundaries between sensibility and the intellect (sen- 
 sibility receives the impressions, co-ordinates tliciu, aii-I 
 makes intuitions of them ; tlie intellect synthesizes the in- 
 tuitions, i. e., judges and reasons). We discriminated, in 
 sensibilit}-, between n posteriori intuitions and llie a priori
 
 448 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 intuitions of space and time ; in tlie understanding we 
 discovered a number of a priori concepts, which are so 
 many compartments, as it were, in which reason stores 
 and elaborates the products of experience. But though 
 containino- many elements, tlie faculty of knowledge is, 
 nevertheless, a unity. This essential unity of reason in 
 the diversity of its operations is the ego, the feeling or 
 apperception of which accompanies all intellectual phe- 
 nomena, and constitutes their common bond, so to speak. 
 Kant is not satisfied with a mere analysis ; not only does 
 he take apart the knowledge-machine, as we might say, 
 he also attempts to explain how it works, and to show 
 how the parts lit into each other. He, therefore, imagines 
 the categories of limitation, reciprocity or concurrence, and 
 reality, as connecting links between affirmation and nega- 
 tion, substantiality and causality, possibility and necessity : 
 fictions Avhich gave rise to the triads of Fichte and Hegel 
 (thesis, antithesis, and synthesis). It is owing to the same 
 demand for synthesis that he raises the question : How can 
 reason act upon the data of sensibility ; by what means, by 
 what arm, as it were, does it lay hold of sensible intuitions 
 and make notions of them? 
 
 This operation is, in his opinion, effected by means of 
 the idea of time, the natural intermediary between intuitions 
 and concepts. Though time, like space, belongs to the 
 domain of sensible things, it is less material than space, 
 and partakes more of the entirely abstract nature of the 
 categories. Owing to its resemblance to the categories, 
 the idea of time serves as an image or symbol to express 
 the a priori notions in terms of sense, and becomes a kind 
 of interpreter between the intuitive faculty and the under- 
 standing, which, without it, cannot assist in the formation 
 of the judgment. 
 
 Considered as a series of moments, or as number, time 
 expresses the idea of quantity : The image of universality
 
 KANT 449 
 
 is the totality of moments of time ; the particular is ex- 
 pressed by a certain number of moments ; the singular, by 
 one moment. The content of time symbolizes the idea of 
 quality (reality is expressed by a time filled with events ; 
 negation, by a time in which nothing happens). Time like- 
 wise symbolizes the idea of relation : Permanence in time 
 represents the idea of substance ; succession of moments, 
 the idea of cause and effect ; simultaneity, the idea of reci- 
 procity and concurrence. Finally, time is the image of the 
 categories of modality : That which corresponds to the con- 
 ditions of time is possible ; that which exists at a definite 
 time is real or actual ; that which is eternal is necessary. 
 Hence, the idea of time serves as a scheme for the a priori 
 concepts of the understanding ; it is a framework, so to 
 speak, of the ideal constructions, for which the senses fur- 
 nish the stones, and reason the mortar. Reason uses the 
 idea of time as an interpreter between itself and sensibility ; 
 and this operation is called, in the pedantic language of 
 criticism, the schematism of pure reason. 
 
 The conclusion of the critique of the intellect merely 
 corroborates the sceptical and subjectivistic results of the 
 Transcendental j^sthetic. 
 
 The critique of the intuitive faculty has demonstrated 
 that we see things through colored glasses (space and time), 
 i. e., otherwise than tliey are in themselves. The examina- 
 tion of the understanding shows that Ave communicate with 
 them through an entire system of glasses. Sensibility per- 
 ceives them, but in doing this, it impresses its forms upon 
 them, i. e., it transforms them. We do not perceive them 
 as they are, but as they appear to us, tliat is, as we make 
 them. When we perceive them, they have already been 
 stamp(;(l ; indeed, they are perceived by the very forms in- 
 hering in sensil)ility (si)afo and time)- They are no longer 
 things; tlicv arc notliing ])iit pheuomma. Ilcnce lli.' plic- 
 nomenon may Ijc defined as tlic thing tiaiisforiiicd l»y tiio 
 
 >'9
 
 450 MODERN THILOSOPHY 
 
 iiiould of the intuitive faculty. What constitutes it is, on 
 the one hand, the thing which impresses the senses, but 
 above everytliing else, the sensibility itself, or reason in the 
 broad sense of the term : it is ourselves ; it is the /, the 
 perceiving and thinking subject, that makes the j^he^iomenon. 
 The phenomenon is the product of reason ; it does not exist 
 outside of us, but in us ; it does not exist beyond the limits 
 of intuitive reason.^ 
 
 Now, while the Esthetic brings us to the threshold of sub- 
 jective idealism, the Transcendental Logic carries us right 
 into it, in spite of Kant's protests against our confounding 
 him with Berkeley. Not only, he tells us, does reason, as 
 an intuition, constitute, produce, or create the phenomenon, 
 but reason, in the form of the understanding, also de- 
 termines the reciprocal relations of sensible phenomena. 
 Reason makes them a priori quantities, qualities, causes, 
 and effects, and thus impresses upon them the seal of its 
 legislative power ; it is tln^ough reason that the tilings 
 become quantities, qualities, effects, and causes, which the}'' 
 are not in themselves. Hence we may say without exag- 
 geration that it is reason ivhich prescribes its laws to the seti- 
 sible universe ; it is reason which makes the cosmos. 
 
 Such are Kant's own words,^ and we emphasize these 
 memorable theses because they form the immediate basis of 
 the systems of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. And yet the 
 latter are called the apostates of criticism, whom Kant 
 himself repudiates ! Nevertheless, the man who said that 
 reason, — and human reason, nota bene, — prescribes its 
 laws to the universe, is the father of Hegelian panlogism. 
 But, we must add, he is so, in spite of himself ; the bent of his 
 philosophy is essentially different from that of his successors. 
 Instead of deifjdng the human understanding, he claims 
 to limit it, — to force the overflowing river into its natural 
 
 1 Kritik, p. 389 ; Prolegomena, pp. 44, 51. 
 ^ Prolegomena, p. 85.
 
 KANT 451 
 
 channel, the phenomenal world, and to exclude forever the 
 sphere of the absolute. When Kant says that reason creates 
 the universe, or at least assists in its creation, he means the 
 phenomenal universe, the totality of phenomena, and he 
 very candidly admits that there may be, beyond the phe- 
 nomenal world, a world of noumena or realities which 
 cannot be perceived, which are inaccessible and conse- 
 quently superior to reason.^ Kant is far from being a pan- 
 logist in the Hegelian sense of the term ; nay, the very 
 object of the entire second part of his critique of the under- 
 standing, the Transcendental Dialectic, is to demonstrate 
 the incompetence of theoretical reason beyond the domain 
 of experience, and the futility of metaphysics considered as 
 the science of the absolute. 
 
 B. Transcendental Dialectic ^ 
 
 From the faculty of judgment ( VerstancT) Kant dis- 
 tinguishes that of embracing the totality of our judgments 
 under certain general points of view, which he calls Ideas. 
 This faculty, the highest of all in the intellectual sphere, 
 is reason in the narrow sense of the term, the voik of the 
 ancients. The concepts of " reason," or Ideas,^ are : the 
 thing-iii-itself^ or the absolute^ the universe, the soul, and 
 God. Their function is similar to that of the a priori 
 intuitions (space and time), and that of the categories. 
 Just as the former arrange the impressions of sense, and 
 the latter, the intuitions, so the Ideas arrange tlie infinite 
 mass of judgments and reduce them to a system. Hence 
 "reason," which fasliions them, is the higlicst synthetic 
 faculty, the systematic and scientilic faculty. Thus, from 
 
 ^ The absolute rationalism of his successors, on the other hand, 
 does not admit any kiml of transcendency. 
 
 « Krilik, pp. 238 ff. 
 
 • The term is deriveil from Platonism, liut Uh' Mi as of Kant aro 
 not, like those of Plato, realities existing ai)arL from oiir tliought.
 
 452 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the co-operation of sensibility, judgment, and " reason " 
 arise the sciences. For example : The outer sense, by 
 means of its a priori intuitions of space and time, furnishes 
 us with a series of phenomena ; tlie understanding, witli tlie 
 help of its categories, makes concepts, judgments, and 
 scientitic propositions of tliem ; finally, " reason " embraces 
 these disjecta membra under the Idea of the cosmos, and 
 makes a science of tliem. So, too, the inner sense furnishes 
 us with a series of facts ; the understanding makes con- 
 cepts of them ; and " reason " combines these concepts into 
 the Idea of the soul, and produces the science of psychology. 
 By viewing the totality of phenomena from the standpoint 
 of the absolute or of God, reason creates tlieoloiju. 
 
 Tlie "Ideas" and "reason," as a separate facidty of 
 the understanding, seem to be superfluities in the Kantian 
 system. The Idea of the cosmos is nothing but the cate- 
 gory of totality ; the Idea of the soul and the Idea of God 
 are the categories of substance and cause, applied to inner 
 facts (soul) and to tlie sum-total of phenomena (God). 
 " Reason," consequently, is not a faculty distinct from the 
 understanding ; it is merely its complete develo})ment. 
 But we shall not insist on this critical detail. Let us 
 rather hasten to discuss the most important topic of the 
 Dialectic : the doctrine of the a-priority of the Ideas.^ 
 
 Just as space and time are not perceived objects, but 
 modes of perceiving objects; just as the categories of quan- 
 tity, quality, and relation are means^ not objects, of knowl- 
 edge, so, too, the universe, the soul, and God are a priori 
 syntheses of reason and not l^eings existing independently 
 of the thinking subject. At least, it is impossible for rea- 
 son to demonstrate their objective existence. Reason, as 
 Kant insists, really knows nothing but phenomena, and 
 receives the matter of all its operations from sensibility 
 alone. Now the universe, as absolute totality, the soul, and 
 1 Kritik, pp. 252 ff.
 
 KANT 453 
 
 God are not phenomena ; the Ideas — in this, sa3'S Kant, 
 they differ from the categories — do not receive any con- 
 tent from sensibility ; they are supreme norms, reguLative 
 points of view, no more, no less. Old metaphysics erred in 
 regarding them as anything else. 
 
 Dogmatism deludes itself when it claims to know the 
 absolute. It resembles the cliild that sees the sky touching 
 the horizon, and imagines that it can reach the sky by mov- 
 ing towards the seeming line of intersection. The sky is 
 the thing-in-itself, the absolute, which hy a kind of optical 
 illusion, seems to us to be an object that can be studied 
 and experienced ; the horizon, which recedes as the child 
 advances, is experience, which seems to attain the absolute, 
 and which, in reality, cannot approach it ; the child itself 
 is the dogmatic metaph^'sician. Let us say, to be just, that 
 the illusion is common to all intellects, just as the illusion 
 that the heaven bounds the earth is shared by all. But 
 there is this difference between the dogmatic philosopher 
 and the critical philosopher. The former, like the child, 
 is the dupe of his illusion, while the latter explains it and 
 takes it for what it is worth. Kant might have summed 
 up his entire critique as follows : Kno\\ledge is relative ; 
 a known absolute signifies a relative absolute ; which is 
 contradictory. 
 
 What is true of traditional ontology is true of psychology, 
 cosmology, and theology. 
 
 Rational psychology, as Descartes, Leibniz, and A\'(>lff 
 conceived it, rests on a paralogism.^ '• I tliiiik," says Des- 
 cartes, " therefore T am " — and mentally adds : a substance. 
 Now, tliat is just what he has no riglit to do. 7 tJil7iky 
 means: I am tin- loL^ical sul)jectof my tlmiiLjlit. Uutliave I 
 the riglit to infer fiom this that I am a suh'Stancc in the 
 sense whicli Cartesian metaphysics attai-hcs to tlic term? 
 A logical subject is one tiling, a metaphysical subject m 
 ' Krid/c, [(p. '21o IT.
 
 454 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 (luite another. When I express the judgment : The earth 
 is a planet, the logical subject of this proposition is the ego 
 that formulates it; while the earth is the real subject. 
 The celebrated thesis of Descartes is a paralogism, because 
 it confuses the /, the logical subject, with the /, the real 
 subject. Metaphysically, I do not know the ego, and I 
 shall never know it, except as the logical subject, as an Idea^ 
 inseparable from my judgments, as the premise and neces- 
 sary concomitant of all my intellectual operations. I shall 
 never know more. As soon as I make a substance of it, I 
 make it the object of a judgment, which is, according to 
 Kant, as absurd as though I pretended to see space and 
 time. Space and time are a priori ideas which serve as a 
 framework for sensible ideas, without being objects of the 
 senses themselves. So, too, the cogito is an a priori judg- 
 ment, preceding all other judgments as a conditio sine qua 
 non, without, however, in any way anticipating the nature 
 of the ego. I cannot judge metaphysically concerning the 
 ego, because it is I who am judging : one cannot be both 
 judge and litigant, as they say in law ; or subject of the dis- 
 course and the real subject, as they say in logic. 
 
 If it is not possible to prove that the ego exists as a sub- 
 stance, the doctrines of the simplicity, immateriality, and 
 immortality of the human soul cannot stand. 
 
 From the existence of simple ideas it does not necessarily 
 follow that the soul is a simple substance, for there are 
 also collective ideas. To conclude from the simplicity of 
 ideas the simplicity of the "spiritual substance" would 
 be equivalent to inferring the simplicity of the cosmical 
 substance from the simplicity of weight, or the unity of 
 motive force from the simplicity of what mechanics calls 
 the resultant. 
 
 Suppose, however, the soul were a simple substance ; 
 simplicity is not immortality. We must remember that, 
 from Kant's point of view, bodies are i^henomena, i. e., facts
 
 KANT 455 
 
 produced by sensibilit}^, the sensible subject or the ego, 
 with the co-operation of an absolutely unknown cause. The 
 phenomenon — we must always return to this fundamental 
 thesis of criticism — the phenomenon is nothing external to 
 the sensible subject ; heat, light, and color, althougli called 
 forth by an external, wholly mysterious, solicitation, are 
 products of sensibility, inner facts, — in short, ideas. 
 
 Kant, it is true, seeks to draw a line of demarcation be- 
 tween the phenomenon and the intuition or idea, between 
 what happens at the boundary of the ego and the non-ego, 
 and what is entirely subjective ; but with indifferent success. 
 The phenomenon takes place in us and is consequently 
 identical with the idea. Hence, in so far as they are phe- 
 nomena, bodies are ideas. Why, then, should not the bodies, 
 on the one hand, and the intuitions properly so-called, the 
 categories, and the judgments, on the other, have a common 
 substance ? Why should not that which we call matter be 
 an immaterial thing, and what we call mind or soul, be a 
 material thing ? ^ 
 
 Immortality, therefore, likewise ceases to be a self-evident 
 doctrine. According to the supporters of this dogma, the 
 soul is not only an indestructible substance, but preserves, 
 in death, the consciousness of self. Now, we discover, in 
 inner perception, infinite degrees of intensity, and may 
 conceive a descenchng scale tliat cuhuinates in complete 
 destruction. 
 
 By showing us tlie possibility of what dogmatism had 
 ])r(!viously aflinncil in Sjiino/.a, vi/., tlic identity of spirit- 
 
 1 A'riVfVr, first edition, J). l.'8S : So kmnle dur/i wold (hixjenigc Klirns, 
 welches (Ip.u dusxpren Ersrlieiiiurif/m zum Gruu/ltj lie;//, tiuis unscrn Sinn so 
 afficirl, ilass er die Vorxlellniuien von lionin, ^[(llf^t•i^\ firslall, etc., JickommL, 
 dieses Elintx . . . kihinle dock auch zufjlcirh dns Subject der Grdanken 
 sein. . . . Dcinnoch ist selhst durch die einf/erdnmte Einfnchheit der Nntur 
 die mensrhlirhe Seele von der Matprie, innun vian sic (wie mnn soil) hlos 
 als Erscheinunfj bclrarlitet in Ansehung des Substrali dcrselben gar nichl 
 hinreichend unterschieden-
 
 456 MODERN rillLOSOPHY 
 
 ual substance and material substance, criticism does away 
 witli the hypotheses of injluxus, divine assistance, and pre- 
 established harmony. These theories lose their raison d'etre 
 as soon as it is proved that the '' substances " of Descartes 
 and the " monads " of Leibniz are nothing but phenomena, 
 derived, perhaps^ from a common source. The problem is no 
 longer to explain the reciprocal action of soul and body, but 
 to ascertain how the same reason, the same ego, can produce 
 phenomena as diametrically opposed as material facts and 
 intellectual facts, extension and thought. In this new 
 form, the question retains all its importance and mj^sterious 
 fascination for Kant. He touched upon it, as we saw, in 
 connection with the idea of time and its function as an 
 intermediary between tlie intuitions and the categories, but 
 he could not penetrate more deeply into the subject without 
 contradicting his premises. To attempt to solve it meant 
 to state what sensibility is in itself, what the understanding 
 is in itself; it meant to make the tliing-in-itself an object of 
 metaphysical knowledge. 
 
 After overthrowing rational psychology, Kant undertakes 
 to demolish rational cosmology in the Wolffian sense.^ In- 
 stead of confining itself to the domain of experience, this 
 alleged science makes an Idea, the cosmos, the object of its 
 speculations. When it considers this Idea from the stand- 
 point of quantity, quality, relation, and modality, it neces- 
 sarily becomes involved in antinomies. Antinomies are 
 theories which contradict each other, each one, at the same 
 time, being as capable of demonstration as the other. 
 
 ANTINOMY OF QUANTITY 
 
 We can demonstrate, with the same show of reason, that 
 the universe is a limited quantity, and that it is unlimited 
 in space and time, i. e., infinite and eternal. 
 
 1 Kritik; pp. 325 ff.
 
 KANT 457 
 
 (1) The miiverse is Ibnited in time and in sjyace. Let 
 us assume, for the sake of argument, that it is uot. The 
 universe, as a whole, is composed of parts which exist sim- 
 ultaneously. Now, I cannot conceive it as a whole except 
 by a mental addition, a successive synthesis of its parts. 
 But, by hypothesis, these parts are infinite in number. 
 Hence their successive addition requires an infinite time. 
 Consequent!}', the idea of the universe, the result of this 
 addition, presupposes that an infinite time has elapsed to 
 form it. But elapsed time is not infinite time. To reach 
 a sum, the number of parts to be added must be limited : 
 we cannot add an infinite number of parts. Now, the idea 
 of the universe is a synthesis, the result of an addition. 
 Hence, the universe has a limited extent (Aristotle). Let 
 us likewise assume that it has no limit in time, that it has 
 no beginning. On this hypothesis, an infinite number of 
 moments have elapsed up to a given time. But an infinite 
 lapse (i. e., finitude) of time is a contradiction in terms. 
 The universe, therefore, is limited in space and in time 
 (Plato). 
 
 (2) The universe is unlimited in space and in time. 
 Otherwise, there would be, beyond its limits, an infinite 
 space (for the idea of space does not admit of liinit-^); 
 hence there would be space by the side of things, and we 
 might speak of a relation between the universe and the 
 inliidte space surrounding it, i. e., of a relation between 
 objects and something whicli is not an object; for we now 
 know that space is not an ol)jc'Ct. But a ivlation l)etween 
 an object and something tliat is not an object is impos- 
 sible; a relation may obtain between tilings in space; there 
 can be none })et\veen things and the space in wliicli tlicv 
 exist. Hence the universe is unlimited. — If it liad had a 
 beginning, it would have been precedcil hy lime without 
 content, i. e., by nothing, for time without content is equal 
 to nothing. Now ex nihilo niliil. Hence tlie univei"se is 
 eternal (Parmcnidcs, Aristotle).
 
 458 MODERN PHILOSOrHY 
 
 ANTINOMY OF QUALITY 
 
 Considered from the standpoint of quality (i. e., of its 
 inner nature), is cosmical matter composed of atoms or 
 elements which are, in turn, composite ? Both the thesis 
 and the antithesis may be proved with equally cogent 
 reasons. 
 
 Thesis : Matter is composed of simple elements, or atoms. 
 Let us assume that the opposite theory is true, and that 
 matter is composed of parts, in turn composed of parts 
 divisible into parts, and so on to infinity. If, in this 
 hypothesis, we abstract from the idea of composition and 
 decomposition, nothing whatever is left ; now, out of noth- 
 ing nothing can be composed. Every composite thing pre- 
 supposes simple constitutive elements. Hence, matter is 
 composed of intUvisible elementaiy substances, monads, or 
 atoms. 
 
 The antithesis, according to which matter is infinitely 
 divisible, is equally easy of proof. In so far as the as- 
 sumed atoms are material, they are extended. Now, that 
 which is extended is divisible. Inextended particles are 
 no longer matter. Hence, there are no simple material 
 elements. 
 
 ANTIKOIMY OF RELATION 
 
 Does the universe, considered as an order of things, em- 
 brace free causes, or is it governed, without exception, by 
 necessity? Metaphysicians have demonstrated both the 
 thesis and the antithesis. 
 
 The thesis, which affirms that there are free causes, is 
 proved as follows : Let us suppose that all things are con- 
 nected with each other by a necessary nexus. If, on this 
 hypothesis, we desire to pass from an effect to its first 
 cause, it will be found that this first cause does not exist, 
 or at least that the cause which seems to be the first is not 
 really the fii'st, but merely a link in the infinite chain of
 
 KANT 459 
 
 events. Now, according to the principle of sufiicient 
 reason, in order that an event be produced, all the causes 
 necessary to its production must exist, and all the con- 
 ditions which it presupposes must be satisfied. If one of 
 these conditions is absent, the event cannot be produced. 
 But, on the hypothesis of an inlinite chain, there is no first 
 cause or concUtion of a given event. If this cause is lack- 
 ing, the occurrence cannot take place. Now, it does take 
 place ; hence, there is a first cause, that is, a cause that is 
 not again the necessarily predetermined effect of a previ- 
 ous cause, or, finally, a free cause. Hence, there are in 
 the world, besides necessary occurrences, free occurrences 
 and free causes. 
 
 According to the antithesis, everything is necessary con- 
 nection, and liberty is merely an illusion. Let us assume 
 a free cause. This cause necessarily exists prior to its 
 effects, and, moreover, it pre-exists in a different state from 
 tliat which it assumes when the effect is produced ; first, it 
 exists as a virgin, then, when tlie effect is produced, as a 
 mother, so to speak. Thus we have, in the cause in ques- 
 tion, two successive states without a causal tie, which is 
 contrary to the principle recognized by the criticpie, that 
 every phenomenon is an effect. Hence, liberty in the in- 
 deterministic sense is impossible. 
 
 ANTnsro^SIY OF ISIODALITY 
 
 According to the thesis, there exists either in the icorld or 
 beyond il, a necessary bein//, an absolute citiisc of thr viii- 
 verse. The demonstration is similar to the jirool' of tin- 
 existence of frec! causes. Tlie world is a series of effects. 
 Each effect, to l)e produced, presupposes a determined 
 series of causes or eoiidilioiis, and, eouse(|ueutly, a lirst 
 cause or coiidilioii, an existence that is no longer contin- 
 ge-nt but necessary.
 
 460 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 According to the antithesis, there is no necessary heing^ 
 either in the universe as an integral part of the cosmos, or 
 beyond it, as the cause of the 'world. 
 
 Now, if there is, in the world and as part of it, some- 
 thing necessary, this can only be conceived in two ways : 
 (1) it exists at the beginning of the world ; or (2) it coin- 
 cides with the whole series of phenomena constituting it. 
 Now, every beginning is a moment of time. Hence, an 
 absolute beginning would be a moment of time without a 
 preceding moment ; which is inconceivable, for the idea of 
 time admits of no limits. Hence, there is no necessary 
 being at the origin of things. But it is also incorrect to say 
 with Spinoza and the pantheists, that the whole of things 
 and the totality of the moments of time, i. e., the universe, 
 is necessary and absolute being. For, however immeasur- 
 able it may be, a totality of relative and contingent beings 
 will no more constitute an absolute and necessary being 
 than a hundred thousand idiots will constitute one in- 
 telligent man. Hence, there is nothing necessary m the 
 world. 
 
 Nor is there anything necessary beyond the universe. 
 For if the necessary being exists outside of the world, it 
 exists outside of time and space. Now it is, by hypothe- 
 sis, the principle, the source, the beginning of things. As 
 their beginning, it constitutes a moment of time. But it 
 is outside of time. That is to say, the necessary being 
 cannot be conceived either in the form of immanency or in 
 that of transcendency. 
 
 The fourth antinomy is not so much concerned with cos- 
 mology as with rational theology, the futility of which it 
 shows in advance. Nevertheless, Kant devotes eighty- 
 eight pages to the critique of the theodicy and the proofs 
 of the existence of God.^ 
 
 1 Kritik, pp. 456 if.
 
 KANT 461 
 
 The ontological proof (Anselm, Descartes) concludes 
 from the idea of God the objective existence of a supreme 
 being, and has no more value than the following reason- 
 ing of a poor man : I have the idea of a hundred thalers, 
 hence these huncbed thalers exist — in my purse. This 
 is the same objection which Gaunilo of Marmoutiers had 
 urged against St. Anselm. 
 
 The cosmological argument (a contingentia mundi) falsely 
 assumes that there can be no infinite series of causes and 
 effects without a first cause. ^ By connecting the series of 
 contingent things with a first and necessary cause, it ima- 
 nnes that it closes the series, while, in realitv, there still 
 remains, between this alleged first cause and the following 
 t-ause, the yawning chasm which separates the necessary 
 from the contingent, and the absolute from the relative. 
 But even granting the cogency of the proof, it would not 
 follow that the necessaiy being, whose existence it claims 
 to establish, is the personal being which theology calls God. 
 
 The teleological or physico-theological proof infers from 
 the finality revealed in nature the existence of an intel- 
 ligent creator. This argument has the advantage that it 
 makes a deep impression on the mind, and the preacher 
 is free to use it in preference to all other reasonings. But 
 from the scientific point of view it has no value ; for (1) it 
 passes from sensible data to something tliat does not fall 
 within tlie scope of the senses; (2) it professes to estab- 
 lish the existence of a God who is the creator of matter; 
 (•S) with what right, moreover, does it compare the universe 
 to a clock or a house ? Is the worhl necessarily a tvork 
 presupposing a workman ? Why, instead of being a macliine 
 begun at a given time, could it not l)e an eternal reality? 
 (4) Besides, what is finality? Is it inlierent in tlie things 
 themselves ? or is not rather our own caprice which confers 
 
 * Sfic tlif f(»urfli aiitiiioiny.
 
 462 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 upon them their teleological character, according as they 
 please us or displease us (Spinoza) ? 
 
 The moral proof, which is based on the purposiveness in 
 the moral order, on the existence of the moral law, on the 
 phenomenon of moral conscience and the feeling of responsi- 
 bility, is peremptory from the standpoint of practical rea- 
 son, but from the standpoint of pure theory it shares the 
 weakness of the teleological proof, of whicli it is, at bottom, 
 merely a variation.^ 
 
 In short, the critique of the faculty of knowledge does 
 not culminate in atheism, but neither does it lead to theism ; 
 it does not lead to materialism, nor does it infer the spirit- 
 uality of the soul and freedom ; that is co say, its last word 
 is the iiroxv in matters of metaphysics. Enclosed within 
 the magic circle of our intuitions, our concepts, our a priuri 
 Ideas, we perceive, we judge, we know, but we know 
 phenomena merely, i. e., relations existing between an 
 object absolutely unknown in itself and a thinking subject, 
 which Ave know only by its phenomena, and whose essence 
 is shrouded in eternal mystery. What we call the world 
 is not the world in itself ; it is the world remodelled and 
 transformed by sensibility and thought ; it is the result of 
 the combined functions of our intellectual faculties and a 
 something, we know not what, which arouses them ; it is the 
 relation of two unknowns, the hypothesis of an hypothesis, 
 the " dream of a dream." 
 
 II. Critique of Practical Reason 2 
 
 Although the Critique of Pure Reason reduces us to a 
 scepticism which is all the more absolute because it is rea- 
 
 1 The critique of monotheism, polytheism, and pantheism, is the 
 same as that of theism. Theism erroneously subsumes an Idea of 
 reason under a category, being ; the error of monotheism, polytheism^ 
 and pantheism consists in applying to the same Idea the categories 
 of quantity : unity, plurality, and totality. 
 
 2 [H. Cohen, Kant's Begriindwig dcr Ethik, Berlin, 1877; E. Zeller,
 
 KANT 463 
 
 soned, proved, scientifically established, and legitimized, 
 it would be a grave mistake to consider the sage of Koeu- 
 igsberg as a sceptic in the traditional sense, and to impute 
 to liim a weakness for the materialism of his age. Scepti- 
 cism is the upshot of the Critique of Pure Reason ; it is 
 not, however, the ultimatum of Kantianism. To assert the 
 contrary is completel}^ to misunderstand the spirit of the 
 philosophy of Kant and the linal purpose of his critique. 
 This is by no means hostile to the moral faith and its tran- 
 scendent object, but wholly in its favor. It is, undoubtedly, 
 not Kant's intention to " humiliate " reason, as Tertullian 
 and Pascal had desired to do, but to assign to it its proper 
 place among all our faculties, its true role in the compli- 
 cated play of our spiritual life. Now, this place is, accoi-d- 
 ing to Kant, a subordinate one ; this function is regulntive 
 and modifying, not constitutive and creative. The Will, 
 and not reason, forms the basis of our faculties and of 
 things : that is the leading thought of Kantian philosoph3^ 
 While reason becomes entangled in inevitable antinomies 
 and involves us in doubts, the will is the ally of faith, the 
 source, and, therefore, the natural guardian of our moral 
 and religious beliefs. Observe that Kant in no wise denies 
 the existence of the thing-in-itself, of the soul, and of God, 
 but only the possibility of proving the I'eality of these Ideas, 
 by means of reasoning. True, he combats s])iritualistic 
 dogmatism, but the same blow that brings it down over- 
 throws materialism ; and though he attacks theism, he like- 
 wise demolishes the dogmatic pretensions of the atheists. 
 Wliat he combats to the utmost and pitilessly destroys is 
 the dogmatism of theoretical reason, under whatever form 
 
 Ueber dus Kanlisclie ^for(l/p|■lncip, Berlin, ISSO ; J. G. Scluinuaii, 
 Kantian Elhics and the Ethics of Erolulion, London, 1881 ; N. rortcr, 
 Kant's Ethics, Cliicago, IHHf! ; V. VV. Fiirstor, Der Eiilirirlrlunf/sf/diuj <lcr 
 Kantischcn Ethik, etc., Berlin, \Hi\ ; Tiinjer, Die Relif/ionslehre Kant's, 
 Jena, 1>^71 — Ti:.].
 
 464 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 it may present itself, whether as theism or atheism, spirit- 
 ualism or materialism ; is its assumption of authority in the 
 system of our faculties ; is the prejudice which attributes 
 metaphysical capacity to the understanding, isolated from 
 the ivill and depending on its oivn resources. By way of 
 retaliation — and here he reveals the dex:)th of his philo- 
 sophic faith — he concedes a certain metaphysical capacity 
 to practical reason^ i. e., to ivill. 
 
 Like the understantUng, the will has its own character, 
 its original forms, its particular legislation, a legislation 
 which Kant calls " practical reason." In tliis new domain, 
 the problems raised by the Critique of Pure Reason change 
 in aspect ; doubts are dissipated, and uncertainties give way 
 to practical certainty. The moral law differs essentially 
 from physical law, as conceived by theoretical reason. 
 Physical law is irresistible and inexorable ; the moral 
 law does not compel, but bind ; hence it implies freedom. 
 Though freedom cannot be proved theoretically, it is not in 
 the least doubtful to the will : it is a j^ostulate of practical 
 reason, an immediate fact of the moral consciousness. ^ 
 
 Here arises one of the great difficulties with which 
 philosophy is confronted : How can we reconcile the pos- 
 tulate of practical reason with the axiom of pure reason 
 that every occurrence in the phenomenal order is a neces- 
 sary effect, that the phenomenal world is governed by an 
 absolute determinism? Kant, whose belief in free-will is 
 no less ardent than his love of truth, cannot admit an abso- 
 lute incompatibilit}^ between natural necessity and moral 
 libert}^ The conflict of reason and conscience, regarding 
 freedom, can only be a seeming one ; it must be possible to 
 resolve the antinomy without violating the rights of the 
 intelliofence or those of the will. 
 
 The solution would, undoubtedly, be impossible, if the 
 
 ^ Zitr Griindlegung der Melaphysik der Sitten, p. 80 ; Kritik der 
 praklischen Vernunft, p. 274.
 
 KANT 465 
 
 Critique of Pure Reason absolutely denied liberty, but the 
 fact is, it excludes freedom from the phenomenal sphere 
 only, and not from the intelligible and transcendent world, 
 which exists behind the phenomenon, though it is unknow- 
 able. Theoretical reason declares : Freedom, though im- 
 possible in the phenomenal world, is possible in the absolute 
 order ; it is conceived as a noumenon ; it is intelligible ; 
 and practical reason adds : it is certain. Hence, there is no 
 real contradiction between the faculty of knowledge and of 
 will. Our acts are determined, in so far as they occur in 
 time and in space, indetermined and free, in so far as the 
 source whence the}^ spring, our intelligible character, is in- 
 dependent of these two forms of sensibility.^ 
 
 This would not be a solution if time and space were 
 objective realities, as dogmatic philosophy conceives them. 
 From that point of vieiv, Spinoza is right in denying free- 
 dom. However, as soon as we agree with criticism, that 
 space and, above all, time are modes of seeing things, and 
 do not affect the things themselves, determinism is reduced 
 to a mere theory or general conception of things, a theory 
 or conception which reason cannot repudiate without 
 abdicating, but which by no means expresses their real 
 essence. 
 
 The Kantian solution of the problem of freedom at first 
 sight provokes a very serious objection. If the soul, as in- 
 telligible character, does not exist in time, if it is not a 
 phenomenon, we can no longer subsume it under the cate- 
 gory of causality, since the categoi-ies api)ly only to phe- 
 nomena and not to " noumena." Hence it ceases to be a 
 cause and a free cause. Nor can we apply to it the cate- 
 gory of unity. Hence it ceases to be an individual apart 
 from other individuals : it is identified with the universal, 
 the eternal, and the infinite. Fichte, therefore, consistently 
 deduces his do(;triiie of tlir iibsoliilc ego from Kantian 
 
 * Krilik till- pruktiachcn Verntnift, \>\>. L'L'.') iT. 
 80
 
 4G6 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 j)remises. Our philosopher, however, does not seem to 
 have the slightest suspicion that this is the logical conclu- 
 sion of his theory. Nay, he postulates, always in the name 
 of practical reason, individual immortality ^ as a necessary 
 condition of the solution of the moral problem, and the 
 existence of a God ^ apart from the intelligible ego, as the 
 highest guarantee of the moral order and the ultimate 
 triumph of the good. It is true, Kant's theology is merely 
 an appendix to his ethics, and is not to be taken very 
 seriously. It is no longer, as in tlie Middle Ages, the 
 queen of the sciences, but the humble servant of inde- 
 pendent ethics. Tliis personal God, afterwards postulated 
 by the Critique of Practical Reason, forcibly reminds us of 
 the celebrated epigram of a contemporary of our philoso- 
 pher : " If there were no God, we should have to invent 
 one." 
 
 The real God of Kant is Freedom in the service of the 
 ideal, or the good Will (der giite JVllle).^ 
 
 His conviction in this matter is most clearly expressed by 
 the doctrine of the primacy of practical reason^^ i. e., of the 
 will.^ Theoretical reason and practical reason, though not 
 directly contradicting each other, are slightly at variance as 
 to the most important questions of ethics and religion, the 
 former tending to conceive liberty, God, and the absolute as 
 ideals having no demonstralile objective existence, the 
 latter affirming the reality of the autonomous soul, responsi- 
 bility, immortality, and the Supreme Being. The conse- 
 quences of this dualism would be disastrous if theoretical 
 reason and practical reason were of equal rank; and they 
 
 ^ Kr'itih der praliischen Vernunff, p. 261. ^ 7^/,^ p_ og4_ 
 
 3 Grundlegunrj zur Melapliysik der Sitten, p. 11 : Es ist uhernll y^icJits 
 in der Welt, ja uberhaupt auch auxser derselben zu denken moglich, loas 
 ohne EinscTirdnkung filr gut konnte gehalten icerden, als allein ein Gutkr 
 
 WiLLE. 
 
 ^ Kritik der prakti^chen Vernunft, p. 258. ^ Id., pp. 105 ff.
 
 KANT 467 
 
 would be still more disastrous, were the latter subordinated 
 to the former. But tlie authority of practical reason is 
 superior to that of theoretical reason, and in real life the 
 former predominates. Hence we should, in any case, act as 
 if it were proved that we are free, that the soid is immortal, 
 that there is a supreme judge and rewarder. 
 
 In certain respects, the dualism of understanding and 
 will is a happy circumstance. If the realities of religion, 
 God, freedom, and the immortality of the soul, were self- 
 evident truths, or capable of theoretical proof, we should 
 do the good for the sake of future reward, our will would 
 cease to be autonomous, our acts would no longer be strictly 
 moral ; for every other motive except the categorical impera- 
 tive of conscience and the respect \\hich i' inspires, be it 
 friendship) or even the love of God, renders the will het- 
 ero7iomous, and deprives its acts of their ethical character. 
 Moreover, religion is true only when completely identical 
 with morality. Religion within the bounds of reason con- 
 sists in morality, nothing more nor less. The essence of 
 Christianity is eternal morality ; the goal of the church is 
 the triumph of riglit in humanity. When the chui'ch aims 
 at a different goal, it loses its raison d'etre} 
 
 ^ Din Rdigion innerhnlh iler Grenzen (krhlosxen Vernnnfl, pp. 130 ff.; 
 205 ff. — The inrlepemlevt mornlitij of the socialist P. J. Proudhon (1809- 
 1805) is grounded on these principles. It is based on the following 
 proposition : " Morality must cease o lean on theolotry for support, it 
 must free itself from all so-called revealed dogmas, and base itself 
 solely on conscience and the innate principle of justice, without re- 
 quiring the support of the l)elief in God and the immortality of the 
 soul." This doctrine of Proudhon has been reproduced and popular- 
 ized by a weekly journal, tlie " Morale imlcpendante," edited by Massol, 
 Morin, and Coignet (1805 11.;.
 
 468 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 III. Critique of Judgment* 
 
 "While the Critique of Practical Reason, with its categori- 
 cal imperative, its primacy of the conscience, and its absolute 
 independence of morality, satisfies Kant's moral feeling 
 and liis great love of liberty, which had been shaken by the 
 conclusions of the Critique of Pure Reason., the philosophical 
 instinct reasserts itself in his aesthetics and teleology, 
 wliich form the subject-matter of his Critique of Judgment. 
 We have seen how, in the Critique of Pure Reason., he 
 universally combines synthesis with analysis, how he solders 
 together the heterogeneous paits of the cognitive appa- 
 ratus : between the functions of sensibility and those of 
 reason he discovers the intermediate function of the idea 
 of time, which is half intuition, half category ; between 
 a 2J^"iort concepts which are diametrically opposed, he 
 inserts intermediary categories. The same synthetic im- 
 pulse leads him, in his Critique of Judgriient, to bridge 
 over the chasm wliich separates theoretical reason and the 
 conscience.^ 
 
 The sesthetical and teleological sense is an intermediate 
 faculty, a connecting link between the understanding and 
 the will. Truth is the object of tlie understanding, nature 
 and natural necessity its subject-matter. The will strives 
 for the good ; it deals with freedom. The ajsthetical and 
 teleological sense (or judgment in the narrow sense of the 
 term) is concerned with what lies between the true and 
 the good, between nature and liberty : we mean the beauti- 
 ful and the purposive. Kant calls it judgment because of 
 the analogy between its manifestations and what is called 
 judgment in logic ; like the judgment, the sense of the 
 
 1 [A. Stadler, Kant's Teleologie, etc., Berlin, 1874; Yi.Co\\&i\, Kant" s 
 Begriinduny der Aesthetik. Berlin, 1889 ; J. Goldfriedrich, Kant's Aes- 
 thetik, Leipsic, 1895 ; J. H. Tufts, The Sources and Development ofKant^s 
 Teleology, Chicago, 1892. — Tr.]. 
 
 2 Kritik der Urtheilskraft, p. 14.
 
 KANT 469 
 
 beautiful and the teleological establishes a relation between 
 two things which as such have nothing in common : between 
 what ought to be and what is, between freedom and natural 
 necessity. 
 
 1. Esthetics. — The sesthetical sense differs both from 
 the understantUng and the will. It is neither theoretical 
 nor practical in character ; it is a phenomenon sui generis. 
 But it has this in common with reason and will, that it 
 rests on an essentially subjective basis. Just as reason 
 constitutes the true, and will the good, so the testhetical 
 sense makes the beautiful. Beauty does not inhere in ob- 
 jects ; it does not exist apart from the ajsthetical sense ; it is 
 the product of this sense, as time and space are the products 
 of the theoretical sense. That is beautiful which pleases 
 (quality), wliich pleases all (quantity), which pleases with- 
 out interest and without a concept (relation), and pleases 
 necessarily (modality).^ 
 
 What characterizes the beautiful and distinguishes it 
 from the sublime, is the feeling of peace, tranquillity, or 
 harmony which it arouses in us, in consequence of the per- 
 fect agreement between the understanding and the imagi- 
 nation. The sul)lime, on the other hand, disturbs ns. agitates 
 us, transports us. Beauty dwells in tlie form ; the sublime, 
 in the disproportion between the form and the content. 
 The beautiful calms and pacifies us ; the sublime brings 
 disorder into our faculties; it produces discord between 
 the reason, which conceives the infinite, and the imagina- 
 tion, which has its fixed limits. The emotion caused in us 
 l)y the starry heavens, the storm, and the raging sea springs 
 from the conflict aroused by these different phenomena 
 between our reason, which can measure the forces of nature 
 and tlic hoavenly distances without l)cing overwhelmed by 
 the enormous figures, and our imagination, which cannot 
 
 * Krilik tier Urtheilskraft, y\k I'j IT.
 
 470 MODERN PHILOSOrHY 
 
 follow reason into the depths of infinity. Man has a feeling 
 of grandeur, because he himself is grand through reason. 
 The animal remains passive in the presence of the grand 
 spectacles of nature, because its intelligence does not rise 
 beyond the level of its imagination. Hence we aptly say, 
 the sublime elevates the soul (^das Urhahene ist erheheml^. 
 In the feeling of the sublime, man reveals himself as a being 
 infinite in reason, finite in imagination. Both infinite and 
 fuiite : how is that possible ? Kant cannot fathom this 
 mystery without surpassing the limits which he has pre- 
 scribed to knowledge.^ 
 
 2. Teleoloiju? — There are two kinds of purposiveness. 
 The one arouses in us, immediately and without the aid of 
 any concept, a feeling of pleasure, satisfaction, and inner 
 harmony : this is subjective finality, which constitutes the 
 beautiful. The other also arouses pleasure, but mediately, 
 in consequence of an experience or an intermediate process 
 of reasoning: tins is objective finality, which constitutes 
 the suitable {das Zwecknu'ismje). Thus, a flower may be 
 both the object of an a3sthetical judgment in the artist, and 
 of a teleological judgment in the naturalist, \A\o has tested 
 its value as a remedy. Only, the judgment which stamps 
 it as beautiful is immediate and spontaneous, while that of 
 the naturalist depends on previous experience. 
 
 The Critique of Pure Eeaso7i regards every phenomenon 
 as a necessary effect, and therefore excludes purposiveness 
 from the phenomenal world. Physics merely enumerates 
 an infinite series of causes and effects. Teleology intro- 
 duces between the cause and the effect, considered as the 
 end or goal, the means, the instrumental cause. Theoreti- 
 cally, teleology is valueless. However, we cannot avoid it 
 so long as we apply our teleological sense to the study of 
 nature. Unless we abandon one of our faculties, which is 
 
 1 Kritik der Urthellskraft, pp. 97 ff. ; 399 ff. 
 « Id., pp. 239 ff.
 
 KANT 471 
 
 as real and inevitable as reason. and will, we cannot help 
 recognizing purposiveness in the structure of the eye, the 
 ear, and the organism in general. Though mechanism 
 fully explains the inorganic world, the teleological vicAV 
 forces itself upon us when we come to consider anatomy, 
 physiology, and biology. 
 
 The antinomy of mechanism, aflirmed by the theoretical 
 reason, and teleology, claimed bj* the teleological sense, is 
 no more insoluble than that of necessity and freedom.^ 
 Teleology is notliing but a theory concerning phenomena. 
 It no more expresses the essence of things than mechanism. 
 This essence is as unknowable for the Critique of Judgment 
 as for the Critique of Pure Beason. Things-in-themselves 
 are not in time ; they have no succession, no duration. 
 According to mechanism, the cause and its effect, accord- 
 ing to teleology, the free cause, the means, and the goal at 
 which it aims, follow each other, i. e., they are separated 
 in time. But time is merely an a priori form of intuition, 
 a mode of conceiving things ; as such and apart from my 
 thought or my theorj^ the cause and the effect of the 
 mechanist, the creative agent, the means, and the goal of 
 the telef)logist, are in each other, inscparaljle, simultaneous. 
 Imagine an understandino; which is not lx)und to the 
 a priori forms of space and time like ours, a free and ab- 
 solute intellectual intuition: such an understanding would 
 perceive the cause, the means, and the end at one glance ; 
 it would identify the end and the principle; the end would 
 not follow tlie efficient cause, but would be innnanent in it 
 and identical witli it. Immanent teleologij, which iden- 
 tifies the ends of nature with the acting causes, is the 
 natural solution of the antinomy of niocliaiiisip. and i)ni- 
 posiveness. 
 
 We see that the sMbjectivity of lime and space is the most 
 
 ' Kiitik iter Urtlttilshafl, 1'1>. '-^^2 IT.
 
 472 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 original and, on the whole, the most fruitful of Kant's 
 teachings. There is no question so subtle, no problem so 
 obscure, as not to be illuminated by it. Space and time are 
 the eyes of the mind, the organs which reveal to it its 
 inexhaustible content. These organs are at the same time 
 the boundaries of its knowledge. But in spite of this 
 insurmountable barrier, it feels free, immortal, and divine ; 
 and it declares its independence in the field of action. It 
 is the mind which prescribes its laws to the phenomenal 
 world ; it is the mind from which the moral law proceeds ; 
 it is the mind and its judgment which make the beautiful 
 beautiful. In short, the three Critiques culminate in ab- 
 solute spiritualism. Kant compared his work to that of 
 Copernicus : just as the author of the Celestial Revolutions 
 puts the sun in the place of the earth in our planetary 
 system, so the author of the Critiq^ue places the mind in 
 the centre of the phenomenal world and makes the latter 
 dependent upon it. Kant's philosophy is, undoubtedly, 
 the most remarkable and most fruitful product of modern 
 thought. With a single exception, perhaps,^ the greatest 
 systems wdiich our century has produced are continuations 
 of Kantianism. Even those — and their number has grown 
 during the last thirty years — who have again taken up the 
 Anglo-French philosophy of the eighteenth century, revere 
 the illustrious name of Immanuel Kant. 
 
 ^ We mean the system of Comte, which is closely related to the 
 French philosophy of the eighteenth century. Comte himself says, 
 in a letter to Gustave d'Eichthal, dated December 10th, 1824 : " I have 
 always considered Kant not only as a very powerful thinker, hut also 
 as the metaphysician who most closely approximates the positive 
 philosophy."
 
 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM 473 
 
 § 63. Kant and German Idealism i 
 
 The dogmatic Leibniz-Wolffiaii scliool,- the sceptic G. E. 
 ScHULZE,^ the eclectic Herdee,"^ Jacobi ^ and Hamann,^ 
 the exponents of religious faith, accept the challenge 
 Avliich Kant had hurled at all traditions. Some "inde- 
 pendents" (Salomon Malmon," Bakdili,^ etc.) take ex- 
 ception to his teachings or protest against them, although 
 they, too, feel his influence. But the Kantian philosophy 
 was eagerly welcomed, though not wholly understood, by 
 numerous disciples, some of tliem (B outer wek,^ Krug,^'' 
 
 ^ [See p. 434, note 1 ; also vol. V. of K. Fischer's Ilislori/ and Zeller's 
 German Philosophy. — Tu.] 
 
 2 Eberhard (1738-1809), professor at Halle, was its chief represen- 
 tative. 
 
 3 1761-1833. Author of ^'Enesidemus, 1792. [If tlie categories can- 
 not be applied to things-in-theniselves, how can we know whether 
 these exist or do not exist? " We can have no absolutely certain and 
 universally valid knowledge, in philosophy, either of the existence or 
 non-existence of things-in-themselvcs and their properties, or of the 
 limits of human knowledge." Kant's critique logically culminates in 
 scepticism. — Tr.] 
 
 * 17-44-1803. The theologian Herder, one of the stars of German 
 literature, teaches a kind of Christianized Spinozism, in which he antici- 
 pates the philosophy of Schelling and Schleiermacher. To the Critique 
 of Kant he opposes his Metakridk, etc., Leipsic, 1799. He also wrote: 
 Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichle der Menschheit, Riga, 1784-1791. 
 
 5 1743-1819. Complete works, 6 vols., Leipsic, 1812-25. [See 
 Harms, Ueher die Lehre von F. H. Jncohi, Berlin. 187G; L. Ldvy-Bruhl, 
 La philosophie de Jacobi, Paris, 1894. — Tu.] 
 
 6 1730-1788. Works published by Roth, Berlin, 1821-43 ; [also by 
 (Jildemeister, 6 vols., Gotha, 1858-73]. 
 
 ^ 1754-1800. ilaimou rejects tlie Kantian notion of Ih.' ihing-in- 
 itself, and approaches Fichte. [Cf. Witlo, S. Maivum, Berlin, 1870.] 
 ' 1761-1S08. Bardili's rational realistn anticipates Hegel's logic. 
 
 • 1706-1828, Professor at Gottingen, known especially by liis Acs- 
 thetik, Leipsic, 1806. 
 
 " 1770-1842. Kant's successor at Kiinigsberg, 1805, then (1809), 
 professor at Leipsic. IJntwu/f eincs ncucn Oryanurt der Philosojdiic,
 
 i74 MODERN riiiLOSoriiv 
 
 FiiiES,^ etc.) being original thinkers. Its chief apostles 
 were: Schillek,^ the national poet of Germany, IIein- 
 HOLD,^ and FiCHTE. The University of Jena became the 
 brilliant centre of the new movement, the crucible, as it 
 were, in which the new views were soon transformed. 
 
 The original and genuine criticism occupied a position 
 between the sensationalism of Locke, Hume, and Condillac, 
 and the intellectualism of Leibniz. Sensationalism had 
 declared : All ideas and consequently all truths, to what- 
 
 Meissen, 1801 ; Fundamentalphilosophie, 2nd ed., 1819 ; Das System der 
 theoretischen Philosophie, 3 vols., 2d ed., Konigsberg, 1819-23; System 
 der practischen Philosophie, 3 vols., id., 1817-19; Handbuch der Philo- 
 sophie, 2 vols., Leipsic, 1820-21 ; Das allgemeine Handbuch der philoso- 
 phischen Wissenschaften, 2d ed., 5 vols., Leipsic, 1832-38. — Krug, who 
 holds that an original a priori sj^ithesis, not further to be explained, 
 takes place within us between beiiig and knowledge, calls his system : 
 transcendental synthetism, 
 
 ^ 1773-1843. Professor at Heidelberg and Jena. Fries refers 
 criticism to the domain of psychology, and bases it on inner observa- 
 tion. His philosophy is a connecting link between Kantianism and 
 the Scotch school. We mention the following writings : System der 
 Philosophie als evidenter Wissenschaft, Leipsic, 1804; Wissen, Glaube 
 und Ahndung, Jena, 1805, 3d ed., 1837; [his best known work : Neue 
 Kritikder Vernunft, 3 vols., Heidelberg, 1807, 2d ed., 1828-31]; and 
 many highly prized text-books. He had numerous disciples; among 
 them : the philosopher Aj)elt, the naturalist Sclileiden, and the tlieo- 
 logian De Wette. 
 
 2 (17.59-1805). Briefe uher rcsthetische Erziehung, 1793-95; \_Ueber 
 Anmuth und Wurde, 1793; Ueber naive und sentimentale Dichtung, 1795- 
 90, Engl. tr. in Bohn's Library. See Kuno Fischer, Schiller als Philo- 
 soph, Frankfort, 1858 ; 2d completely revised ed. (Schillerschriften, III, 
 IV), Heidelberg, 1891-92. — Tr.]. 
 
 3 1758-1823. Versuch einer neuen Theorie des menschlichen Vorstel- 
 lungsvermogens, Jena, 1789 ; ^Das Fundament des philosophischen Wissens, 
 1791]. Reinhold's so-called elementary theory derives the a priori and 
 a posteri<n-i elements of knowledge from a common principle : the 
 faculty of representation ( Vorstellungsvermogen). It anticipates the 
 subjective idealism of Fichte, which calls this common principle the 
 ego.
 
 KA2sT AND GERMAN IDEALISM 475 
 
 ever order they may belong, are derived from tlie senses 
 (and reflection) ; reason does not create them, it receives 
 them. Intellectualism, on the other hand, had asserted: 
 All our ideas and consequently all truths whatsoever are 
 the product of reason. So-called outer perception is merely 
 an elementary speculation ; the thinking subject is wholly 
 active, and even in cases where it imagines that it receives, 
 it creates. Criticism agrees with sensationalism in holding 
 that our ideas, without exception, are given by sensation ; 
 but, it adds, their matter or material alone is given, their 
 form is the product of reason : in tliis respect intellectualism 
 has the right on its side. In other words, it distinguishes, 
 in every idea, a material element, which is furnished a 
 posteriori by the senses, and a formal element, furnished a 
 priori by thought. Every science, therefore, or philosophy, 
 consists of two parts : a pure^ rational, or speculative part, 
 and an empirical part. Hence, criticism recognizes the 
 partial truth of two systems and two methods ; and conse- 
 quently repudiates the pretentious claim of either side to 
 possess absolute truth and to employ the only possible 
 method. It is both idealistic and realistic, and yet, strictly 
 speaking, neither one nor the othei-. 
 
 But this state of equilibrium did not last long. Ueiidiold 
 soon disturbed it with his elementar// theory,^ and Kant lived 
 to see the triumph of absolute intellectualism, whieli, l)y 
 way of reaction, led to the restoration of pure sensational- 
 ism. He protested, as loudly as he could, against this con- 
 dition of things; yet it must be acknowledged that his 
 Critique of Pure Reason, as well as his other two Critiques, 
 contained the germs of the idealistic theories of the nine- 
 teenth century. Under the influence of the Spinozistic 
 system wliicli Lcssing and Herder bad recently intixKhu-ed 
 into f Jermany, tliese germs soon sj)rouled. 
 
 Kant had intiinateil that the iiiysteiit)us unknown eou- 
 
 1 Sec page 171, note ;5.
 
 476 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 cealed beliind the phenomena of sense might possibly be 
 identical with the unknown in ourselves. This simple 
 thought, wliich, however, he failed to carry out, contained 
 the philosophy of Fichte. 
 
 But even if he had never advanced the hypothesis of the 
 identity of the ego and the non-ego, his criticism would still 
 bear a very pronounced idealistic stamp. Although it es- 
 tablishes an independent order of things apart from reason, 
 a transcendent object, which impresses our senses and fur- 
 nishes the material for our ideas, it assigns to pure reason 
 the highest role imaginable. Reason, the thinking subject, 
 creates space and lime ; reason, with the materials supplied 
 by the senses, makes, constructs, or constitutes the phenom- 
 enon. The phenomenon is its work, if not its creation. 
 Reason applies to phenomena the categories of relation and 
 connects them by the tie of causality ; through the legisla- 
 tive power of reason, phenomena become effects and causes ; 
 and if we mean by nature, not the totality of the things 
 themselves, but only the sum of sensible and inner phenom- 
 ena considered in their regular connections, then reason 
 makes or 2Jroduces nature^ for reason prescribes to nature its 
 laws.^ From reason, finally, are derived the Ideas of the 
 world, God, and the absolute. 
 
 If reason makes time and space, if reason determines and 
 regulates the phenomenon, if reason constitutes nature and 
 the universal order, what becomes of that which, according 
 to empiricism, is given to reason ? The raw material of the 
 phenomenon, or, what amounts to the same, of intuition 
 and thought, the unknown quantity which occasions the 
 difference between sound, light, smell, taste, temperature, 
 pleasure, and pain, " something, I-know-not-what," which 
 brings it about that a person born blind, though he may be 
 an excellent mathematician and perfectly able to understand 
 the laws of optics, cannot form a correct notion of light, — 
 1 Proleyomena, pp. 84-85.
 
 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM 477 
 
 that is all that is given to us, everything else being our own 
 creation. Given by whom ? Given by what ? By some- 
 thing, I-know-not^what, which is called tlie thing-in-itself, a 
 transcendent object, which, consequently, cannot be known, 
 a mysterious agent, wliich calls forth sensations, and co- 
 operates in the formation of ideas, but in regard to which 
 I have no right to allirm or to deny anything. 
 
 But how, then, can you affirm that it is an agent, that it 
 provokes sensations ? ^ The transcendent object of intuition 
 (the thing-in-itself) is neither in space nor in time. Space 
 and time contain phenomena only, i. e., that which appears ; 
 and the thing-in-itself does not appear. We cannot apply 
 to it any of the forms of the understanding ; we cannot 
 conceive it, as Kant explicitly states,^ either as magnitude, 
 reality, or substance. Hence we cannot conceive it as the 
 caiise of our impressions, although Kant flatly contradicts 
 himself and regards it as such.^ But if the thing-in-itself 
 cannot be conceived either as a quantity, or as a cause, or 
 as a reality, it cannot be considered as anything; it is 
 nothing, or rather it exists only in the thinking subject ; 
 like space, time, and the categories, it is identical with the 
 subject which conceives it.* The matter of our ideas, 
 the transcendent substratum of the plienomcna of sense, is 
 the same as the substratum of the inner plu'nouu'ua, the soul, 
 or ego, or reason giving to itself not only the funa but also 
 the matter of its ideas. Reason not merely assists in the 
 production of the plienomenon, it is the creator — the sole 
 creator — of llic ])licn(tni(ii:il world. Hence it is, in the 
 
 1 This contradiction was especially pointed out Ity .1. Sigisnmnd 
 Beck (1701-1840), wlio did not, liowevor, succeed in eliminating il 
 from Kantianism. [Hi'ck (Einzif/ vtwfllcher Sl(in(f/»niht oux u-elc/ievi 
 (lie krilische Philo.tophte heurtheill wenlin ?/ims.s, Itiga, ITilO) rejects the 
 thing in-itself, and interprets the Cnti<iue in the idealistic sense. — Tu.] 
 
 2 Krilik der reinen Vernunft, p. 231. 
 » Id. 
 
 * Hence the \muu-, philosuithij nf identity.
 
 47S MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 last analysis, an inconsistency of the Kantian philosophy to 
 concede the existence of a thing-in-itself outside of and lij 
 the side of reason, so to speak. The true consequence of the 
 Critique of Pure Reason is the monism of the ego, or abso- 
 lute idealism. 
 
 But though the Critique of Pure Reason takes us to the 
 threshold of panlogism, with its system and method, does 
 not the result of the Critique of Practical Reason^ the dual- 
 ism of the " two reasons," absolutely hinder us from cross- 
 ing it? The speculative Kantians, with Fichte at their 
 head, do not regard this teaching as an obstacle to their 
 interpretation of criticism, but consider it as an additional 
 argument in its favor. 
 
 To begin with, by subordinating the theoretical reason to 
 the practical reason, and al'lirming the prinuu-y of the moral 
 consciousness, Kant not only proclaims the dualism of the 
 ''' two reasons," but also the monism of the practical reason, 
 of which theoretical reason and the teleological judgment 
 are mere modes or dependencies. He could not have 
 affirmed this primacy, had he discovered absolute contra- 
 dictions or insoluble antinomies between practical reason 
 and theoretical reason. But such is not the case. There 
 is a connecting link between theoretical reason and practical 
 reason, and this connecting link is the tliing-in-itself the 
 noumenon, the intelligible order, supposed by theoretical 
 reason, postulated and openly affirmed by the conscience. 
 
 The " two reasons " would contradict each other, if one 
 denied what the other affirms : the invisible, the ideal, 
 the absolute. In realit}^ the theoretical reason does not 
 reject the absolute ; it simply recognizes its inability to 
 know it and to demonstrate its existence. The same may 
 be said of freedom, which is synonymous with the absolute. 
 What the Critique of Pure Reason does deny is liberty in 
 the phenomenal world. It recognizes in iiatiire nothing 
 but the law of causality, mechanism, the determinism of
 
 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM 479 
 
 facts, but it conceives liberty as a prerogative of tlie thing- 
 iii-itsclf, wbile niaiataiiiing the impossibility of a theoretical 
 demonstration. The thinq-in-itself via// be considered as 
 free. Now, practical reason categorically alhrms the liberty 
 of the acting subject, the freedom of the ego. Hence, the 
 Critique of Pmdical Reason^ instead of contradicting the 
 idealistic conclusions, confirms them : the ego itself is 
 the thing-in-itself (the free tiling) ; the object which seems 
 to determine us from without, is merely the subject acting 
 within ourselves ; object and subject, being and thought, 
 nature and mind, are identical. If the / were determined 
 by an object-z?i-/ts'f7/, the " two reasons " would absolutely 
 contradict each other ; the ego would henceforth be a slave 
 in theory and in practice, and moral freedom woidd be an 
 inexplicable illusion. But the Ihing-in-itsclf, the thing 
 which determines us ''from without" being in reality the 
 soVi\-in-itself the self-determining subject ; the ego, though 
 determined, is free and autonomous, since it determines 
 itself in the form of an external object. 
 
 Instead of making against idealistic monism, Kant's 
 ethics culminates in it. True, it postulates the immortality 
 of the soul and tlie existence of a personal God apart fi-om 
 the eoro. But tliis doul)le affirmation is a mere accident in 
 the system : essential to it is the allirmatioii of the absolute 
 freedom of the ego, the doctrine of the practical al)solute of 
 the ego. Xow, the ego which Kant holds to be absolutely 
 free is not the empirical ego, the plicnomciial self, the self 
 which exists in time, but the noumenal ego, i. e., tlie ego 
 raised al)0ve space and time. To speak of the immortality 
 of an ego that does not exist in time, for whidi, tlierefore, 
 there is no before or after, is an inconsistency similar to the 
 doctrine tliat the tliing-in-itsclf is distinct from tlie personal 
 subject, an inconsistency wliicli has no organic connection 
 with the essence of the Hystem. The same holds foi- the 
 theistic teacliing. Ood is undouljtcdly (li-<(iiict from tlie
 
 480 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 empirical and plienomenal ego, but he cannot be anything 
 but the absolute ego or the intelligible ego ; otherwise there 
 would be two absolutes. 
 
 The Critique of Judgment opened up a still wider field 
 than the other two Critiques to the most illustrious dis- 
 ciples of Kant. They discovered in it not only a certain 
 general tendency towards pantheism, foreign to the other 
 writings of the master, but also theories which could not 
 fail to culminate in pantheism. We mean his theory of the 
 sublime, liis immaiient telcoloffj/, and especially his hypothesis 
 of an intellect capable of an immethate and comprehensive 
 intuition of things. The first makes a God-man of man ; 
 the second substitutes for the notion of creation that of 
 evolution; the third makes a serious, though indirect, con- 
 cession to dogmatic rationalism. True, Kant does not 
 concede intellectual intuition to the human intellect, but he 
 does not deny it to the intellect in general, and Schelling 
 had only to generalize the Kantian hypothesis to convert the 
 intellectual intuition into a philosophical method. 
 
 Such is the relation between Kantianism and the systems 
 of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. Though these three phi- 
 losophies, or rather, these three phases of one and the same 
 teaching, all proceed from criticism, they really make against 
 it in so far as they occupy themselves particularly with 
 what Kant had declared " forbidden fruit," i. e., the abso- 
 lute. Their common aim is to re-establish the old meta- 
 physics, but to re-establish it upon the basis of criticism. 
 In almost the same way the monarchies which emerged 
 from the ruins of the Revolution restored the past upon the 
 basis of the principles of 1789. Kant and Fichte, in his 
 first phase, are the philosophers of the Revolution ; Schel- 
 ling and Hegel are the philosophers of the Restoration.
 
 FICHTE 481 
 
 § 04. Yichte^ 
 
 English sensationalism and ihc philosophy of relativity 
 were founded by a student of medicine and a layman. 
 German idealism and the philosophy of the absolute come 
 from theology. Johaxn Gottlieb Fichte (1765-1814), 
 its founder, like Schelling and Hegel, first studied for the 
 ministry. His Versuch eiiicr Kritik aller Offenbarung (1792) 
 won for him a professorship in Jena (1793). In 1794 he 
 published his chief work: GriLiidlage der gcsammtcn Wisseii- 
 SGliaftslelire^ which was afterwards revised and republished 
 under different titles ; and in 1796 his Grundlage dcs JSfatur- 
 rechts. Accused of atheism, he resigned his chair (1799), 
 and for ten years he and his young family suffered the trials 
 attendant upon a more or less nomadic life. He died as a 
 professor of the University of Berlin, founded in 1809. 
 Besides the works which established liis fame, we mention 
 the following: Die Bestimmung des Menschen^ (1800); 
 Ueber das Wesen des G-elehrten und seine Erscheinungen im 
 Gebiete der Freiheit^ (1805); Die Amveisungen zum scligeii 
 Leben oder auch die Religioiislehre * (1806) ; Reden an die 
 
 1 [Posthumous works, edited by J. H. Fichte, 3 vols., Boun, 1834; 
 complete works, ed. by J. II. Fichte, 8 vols., 1845-4G. Fichte's Popular 
 Works, tr. by W. Smith, 4th ed., Londou, 1889. A. F. Kroeger, The 
 Science of Kuoidedge (translations of the GrimiUage der (jesammlen 
 Wissenscha/lslelire : (^rundrisa des Eif/entfiiimllchcn der Wissenschafls- 
 lehre ; etc. etc.), London, 1SS9; The Science of liii/hls (tr. of Natur- 
 rechl), id., 1889. See also the Journal of Speculative Philosophy. On 
 Fichte see: J. II. Lowe, Die Philosophie Fichte's, Stuttgart, 1802; 
 Adamson, Fichte (Blackwood's Philosophical C/n.w/c.s), London, 1881 ; 
 C. C. Everett, Fichte's Science of Knoirledr/e (Crifff/s's Philosophical 
 Classic.i), Chicago, lS8i; F. Ziiniiwr, /. G. Fichte's Rili(/ionsphilo.<tophie, 
 Berlin, 1878; and especially tlie fifth volume of K. Fischer's Historit 
 of Philosophy. — Tk.]. 
 
 2 \_The Vocation of Man, translated l>y Smith, supra. — Tit.] 
 
 • \_The Nature of the Scholar, tr. by Smith, .ittpra. — Th.] 
 
 * [Tr. by Smith (o.c.) under the title. The Doctrine of Religion. Til.]
 
 482 - MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 deiUsche Nation (1808) ; etc. The German uprising against 
 Napoleon was largely due to his influence. 
 
 Though his thought, like tliat of so many contemporary 
 Germans of the Republic and the Empire, showed two dis- 
 tinct phases : one, rationalistic, humanitarian, and in sym^ 
 pathy with the Revolution, the other, mystical, pantheistic, 
 and patriotic; the central notion of his system remained 
 the same. This concei^tion, or, let us rather say, this truth, 
 the most exalted and at the same time the most paradoxical 
 ever formulated by pliilosophy, is the inonism of the moral 
 
 vAll.^ 
 
 Fichte is to Kant what Euclid-Plato is to Socrates, and 
 to Spinoza what Euclid-Plato is to Parmenides. With Kant 
 he affirms the moral ideal, and with Spinoza, the unity of the 
 " two worlds." Hence his pliilosophy is a synthesis, unique 
 in its kind for modern times, of what seemed forever 
 irreconcilable : monism and liberty. Identity of the ethical 
 principle and the metaphysical principle : that is the funda- 
 mental dogma of his system. The real reality is, according 
 to Fichte, the Good, active Reason, pure Will, the moral 
 Ego. What the common mind regards as real is nothing 
 but a phenomenon, a manifestation, a faithful or imperfect 
 translation, a portrait or a caricature. The ultimate and 
 highest principle from which we come and towards which 
 we strive is not leing but dutij ; it is an ideal which is not, 
 but which ought to be. Being as such has no value, and 
 does not, strictly speaking, exist. The stability or immo- 
 bility of what we call substance, substratum, or matter, is a 
 mere appearance (Heraclitus and Plato). It is all move- 
 ment, tendency, and will. The universe is the manifesta- 
 
 1 Although we recognize the truth of the central thought of FicMe's 
 philosophy, we cannot accept his theory of the absolute ego, which 
 Schelling refuted, nor, particularly, his method of a priori construc- 
 tion, which rests on a confusion of the will and the understanding, 
 common to most of the thinkers prior to Schopenhauer.
 
 rlCHTE 483 
 
 tioii of pure Will, the S3aiibol of the moral Idea, which is 
 the real thing-i)i-itself, the real absolute.^ To philosophize 
 is to convince one's self that being is nothing.^ that clutg is 
 everything ; it is to recognize the inanity of the phenomenal 
 world apart from its intelligible essence ; it is to regard the 
 objective world, not as the effect of causes foreign to our 
 practical reason, but as the product of the ego, as the objec- 
 tified ego. There is no science except the science of the ego 
 or consciousness. Knowledge is neither in whole (Hume, 
 Condillac) nor in part (Kant) the product of sensation ; it 
 is the exclusive work, the creation., of the ego. There is 
 no philosophy but idealism, no method but the a i^riori 
 method. Philosophy does not discover ready-made truths, 
 or establish facts that already exist. To philosophize, or to 
 know, is to produce such facts, to create such truths.^ 
 
 Speculative thought does not begin with a fact, with 
 something received or suffered by the ego, but with a spon- 
 taneous act of its creative energy {nicht Thatsache, sondern 
 Th a th a ndlung ^). Its theses result from a regular succession 
 of intellectual acts, which follow the law of opposition and 
 reconciliation, foreshadowed by Kant in his threefold divi- 
 sion of the categories (affirmation, negation, and limitation). 
 The original act of the understanding, and every intellect- 
 ual act in general, is threefold : (1) The ego posits itself ; 
 this is the act by which the ego takes possession of itself, 
 or rather, the act l)y which it creates itself (for to take pos- 
 session would presuppose an ego existing prior to the ego, 
 or a given fact) ; (2) A non-ego is opposed to the ego, or the 
 ego is negated; (3) The ego and tlie non-ego reciprocally 
 limit each other. 
 
 As tlie essential elements of one and the same concrete 
 reality, these three original acts (thesis of th(» ego, antilJirsis 
 of the non-ego, and sgntliesis of the ego and non-ego) form 
 but a single act. By affirming itself as a sul)jcct, the ego 
 
 1 Complete Works, II., p. 0.07. ^ /,/.^ \-.^ j,,, ;],sl ff. 
 
 8 hi.. l.,Ul if.
 
 484 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 distinguishes itself from an oliject which is not the ego ; in 
 producing itself, it at the same time produces its opposite, 
 its limitation : the objective world. The latter is not, as 
 "common sense" and empiricism claim, an obstacle which 
 the ego encounters ; it is a limitation which it gives to itself. 
 The sensible world has the appearance of something exist- 
 ing outside of the perceiving and thinking subject. It is 
 an illusion which Kant himself could not wholly destroy. 
 The limitation of the ego, the objective world, exists, but 
 it owes its existence to the activity of the subject. SuiJipress 
 the Ego, and yon suppress the world. Creation is reason 
 limiting itself ; it is the will or pure thought, limiting, de- 
 termining, or making a person of itself.^ 
 
 However, Fichte is obliged to confess, the ego limits 
 itself by an inner necessity, which it cannot escape through 
 thought alone : for it cannot think without thinking an 
 object ; it cannot perceive without affirming the existence 
 of something which is not itself. Fichte recognizes with 
 Kant, that the thing-in-itself cannot actually be reduced 
 to thought, but he nevertheless maintains, in principle, that 
 the thing-in-itsclf is merely the thinking principle itself. 
 The dualism of the thinking sul^ject and the thouglit object 
 is an inevitable illusion of theoretical reason, from which, 
 considering the infirmity of thought, action can and must 
 free us. Hence, practical activity is the real triumj^h of 
 reason, the affirmation of its omnipotence. True, in reality, 
 the will is no more successful than the understandina: in 
 completely conquering the resistance of matter; in the 
 phenomenal world, in which thought holds us captive, we 
 cannot entirely escape the determinism of facts, or fatalism. 
 The absolute autonomy of reason is an ideal which the ego 
 pursues, but never attains. But this very conflict between 
 the empirical and ideal reality proves that we are destined 
 
 1 Complete Works, T., pp. 83 fp. ; V., 210.
 
 FICHTE 485 
 
 for an immortal lot : it is the source of our progress, the 
 moving principle in history.^ 
 
 Fichte thus confirms the " primacy of practical reason," 
 proclaimed by Kant. Moreover, he endeavors to insert this 
 essential doctrine, which had been mechanically added to 
 the Kantian system, into the very body of his [)hilosophy. 
 
 Freedom is the highest principle, the essence of things.^ 
 It is even superior to truth, considered from the purely 
 theoretical standpoint, or rather, it is the highest Truth. 
 For that very reason it is not an abstraction, but the supreme 
 reality. But this reality, the source of all other realities, pre- 
 cisely because it is freedom, cannot be an empirical datum, 
 an immediate, brutal, and fatal fact. If freedom were given, 
 or made, or produced, as the facts of the physical order are 
 produced, it would not be freedom. True freedom is the 
 freedom which creates itself, or realizes itself. Self-realiza- 
 tion means self-development in a series of stages, or entrance 
 into the conditions of duration and time. Now time, like 
 space, is an a priori intuition of theoretical reason, a form 
 of the understanding; time is the intuitive faculty itself, 
 or the understanding exercising its elementary and original 
 function. And since it is, as we have just seen, the neces- 
 sary instrument of freedom, we conclude that the under- 
 standing, the theoretical reason, the faculty which divides 
 the ego into subject and object, is the auxiliary of practical 
 reason, the organ of the will, the servant of freedom. 
 
 Again : Freedom realizes itself in time ; time is its 
 means, its indispensable auxiliary. But time is the intui- 
 tive faculty itself, the theoretical reason pci-ceiving things 
 successively/. Theoretical reason, or the understanding, is 
 therefore the means, the organ, which practical rt'ason em- 
 ploys to realize itself. Instead of being, as Kant seemed 
 to conceive it, a power foreign and therefore iiostile to 
 
 ' Die f,'riiiiill(t>ip. (les Nalunechtu {^Complete ir</;7.>', III.), 
 a Works, I., 489.
 
 486 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 practical reason, theoretical reason thus naturally and neces- 
 sarily becomes subject to the will ; it humbly enters the 
 service of the moral ideal. The dualism of the "two 
 reasons " disappears ; the understandhuj smiidy becomes a 
 phase in the development of Freedom ; ' knowledge is a 
 means, a secondary thing ; action is the principle and final 
 goal of being. The non-ego is, in the language of Aristotle, 
 the matter which the form needs in order to realize itself 
 as supreme energy ; it is the limit which the ego sets itself 
 in order to overcome it, and thus to realize its essence, 
 freedom. Self-assertion or self-realization means struggle ; 
 struggle presupposes an obstacle ; this obstacle is the phe- 
 nomenal world, tlie world of sense and its temptations.^ 
 
 Liberty, we said, realizes itself in time and by means of 
 thought, i. e., by distinguishing between a subject which 
 perceives and thinks, and an object which is perceived and 
 thought. But this object, which the magician Reason shows 
 to the ego, the external world, the non-ego, is in turn com- 
 posed of a multitude of egos, of personalities apart from 
 mine. Hence, freedom does not realize itself in the separate 
 individual (the empirical ego), but in human society. In 
 order to become a reality, the ideal ego divides itself into a 
 plurality of historical subjects, and realizes itself in the 
 moral relations established between them, and these rela- 
 tions are the source of natural, penal, and political rights. 
 
 Considered apart from the individuals which realize it, 
 the absolute or ideal ego is a mere abstraction.^ The real 
 God is a living God, or the God-man. " I abhor all reli- 
 gious conceptions," says Fichte, " which personify God, and 
 regard them as unworthy of a reasonable being." And 
 why? Because a personal being, or a subject, does not 
 
 1 Read tuill, and you have, word for word, the teaching of Schopen- 
 hauer minus his pessimism. 
 
 2 Works, Y., 210. 
 
 8 Kritlk aller Offenharung, {Works, V,).
 
 SCHELLIXG 487 
 
 exist without an object that limits it. True, this limitation 
 is the work of the subject itself ; but Avhether limited by 
 itself or by something else, the subject is a limited being, 
 and God cannot be conceived as such. God is the moral 
 order of the world, the freedom which gradually realizes 
 itself in it : he is notliing but that. 
 
 Fichte's opposition to the idea of a personal God is the 
 criticism of Ms own system, or, at least, of the subjectivistic 
 form which it assumed under the influence of Kant, and of 
 Avhich it gradually divested itself under the influence of 
 Spinoza. By denying the personality of God, he condemns 
 both the notion of an absolute ego, as the creator of the 
 non-ego, and the method of a irriori construction. 
 
 Schelling, Fichte's most brilliant chsciple, turns his atten- 
 tion to this contradiction. 
 
 § 65. Schelling 1 
 
 Friedi-ieh Wilhelm Joseph Schelling, born 1775, at 
 Leonberg, in Wiirtemberg, received the master's degree 
 from the University of Tlibingen, when seventeen years 
 old, and continued his studies at Leipsic. In 1798 he was 
 made professor of philosophy at Jena, where he became 
 ac(iuainted with Fichte and renewed liis friendship with 
 his fellow-countryman Hegel. In 1803 we find him at the 
 University of Wiirzburg; then he becomes the General 
 Secretary of tlie Munich Academy of Plastic Arts (1800- 
 
 1 Complete \Yorks in two series, ed. l)y his son, It vols., Stiitt,i;:irt 
 and Augsburg, 185Gff. [Engl, translations in the Journal of Specula- 
 tice Philosophy. "[ French translations : 5e/ec/ /«ns, hy C. Benard ; Sijf- 
 tern of Transcendental hlralism, by Griml)lot ; Bruno, by IIussou. [Cf. 
 Kosenkranz, ScheWnrj, Dantzic, 181:]]; Mignet, Notice hislorifjue sur la 
 vie et les traraux de Srhrllinf/, Paris, IS.'jH; [J. Watson, Schelling's Trans- 
 cendental Idealism {arififtss Philosophical Classics), C'liicagn, ISS-J. See 
 also Will m, o. c, vol. III.; Kuno Kisclur. o. c, vol. V!.; and H. 
 Ilayni, Die romanlixche Srhule, 187U. — Tk.].
 
 488 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 1820). After serving as a professor in the Universities of 
 Erlangen, Municli, and Berlin, he died (1854) in the seventy- 
 ninth year of his age. A precocious and fruitful ^ writer, 
 but an inconsistent thinker, Schelling passed from Fichte 
 to Spinoza, from Spinoza to Neo-Platonism, from Neo-Pla- 
 tonism to J. Bohme, with whom his friend and colleague 
 Franz Baader ^ had made him acquainted. The following 
 works ^ belong to his Spinozistic and Neo-Platonic phase, 
 which he calls his " negative philosophy " : Idccn zu ciner 
 Fhilosophie der Natur^ (1797} ; Vo7i der Weltsede (1798); 
 System des transcendentalen Idealismiis^ (1800); Brwno, 
 Oder ubcr das naturliche und gottliche Princip der Binge 
 (1802) ; Vorlesungen uber die Metliode des akademischen Stu- 
 diums (1803) ; Philosophie und Religion (1804). To his 
 " positive " period, which is characterized by the influence 
 of Bohme and a more or less pronounced tendency to ortho- 
 doxy, belong : JJntersuchungen ilher das Wesen der mensch- 
 lichen Freiheit (1809); Ueher die Gottheiten von' Samothrake 
 (1816) ; Vorlesungen ilher die Philoso2')Me der Mythologie 
 und Offenharvng, published by his son. 
 
 1. The non-ego, Fichte had said, is the unconscious pro- 
 duct of the ego, or, what amounts to the same thing, the 
 product of the unconscious ego. But, Schelling objects, 
 the unconscious ego is not really the ego ; what is uncon- 
 scious is not yet ego or subject, but both subject and object, 
 or rather, neither one nor the other. Since the ego does 
 not exist without the non-ego, we cannot say that it pro- 
 duces the non-ego, without adding, conversely : the non-ego 
 produces the ego. There is no object without a subject, — 
 as Berkeley had previously declared, — and in this sense 
 Fichte truly says that the subject makes the object ; but 
 
 1 At least during his earlier stage. ^ See § 71. 
 
 8 "We mention only the most important. 
 
 * In this work he cuts loose from Fichte. 
 
 5 The most consistent and systematic of his writings.
 
 SCHELLING 489 
 
 neither can there be a subject without an object. Hence 
 the existence of the objective Avorkl is as much the condi- 
 tion siiic qua noii of the existence of the ego, as conversely. 
 Fichte, who implicitly recognized this in his profession of 
 pantheistic faith, regards the distinction between the empi- 
 rical ego and the absolute ego as fundamental to liis thought. 
 But what right has he to speak of an absolute ego, when it 
 is certain that the ego, or the subject, is never absolute, but 
 limited, as it necessarily is, by an object? Hence we nuist 
 abandon the attempt to make an absolute of the ego. 
 
 Is the non-ego absolute ? Not at all, for it does not exist 
 unconditionally ; it is nothing without the thinking subject- 
 Hence we must either deny the absolute or seek it hei/ond 
 the ego and the non-ego^ or beyond all opposition. If tlie 
 absolute exists, — and how can it be otherwise I — it can 
 merely be the synthesis of all contraries, it can only be out- 
 side of and beyond all conditions of existence,^ since it is 
 itself the highest and fu-st condition, the source and end 
 of all subjective as well as of all objective existence. 
 
 Consequent!}', we can neither say that the ego produces 
 the non-ego (su])jective idealism), nor that the non-ego pro- 
 duces the ego (sensationalism) ; the ego and the 7ion-€go, 
 thought and being, are both derived from a higher principle 
 which is neither one nor the other, although it is the cause of 
 both : a neutral principle, the indifference and identity of 
 contraries.2 This brings us to SjDinoza's i)oint of view ; 
 though different terms are used, we find ourselves face to 
 face with the infinite sid)stance and tlie parallelism of tilings 
 emanating from it: tliouglit (the ego) and extension (tlie 
 non-ego). 
 
 Philosophy is the science of the absolute in its double 
 manifestation : nature and mind. It is philosophy of nature 
 and transcendental pliilosophy. or pliilosojiliy of mind. \\\ 
 adding the science of nature to the science of mind. Schcl 
 
 1 Cf. §§ 2o aiul :{1. 2 ]Vor/:s, first series, V(j1. X., pp. U-J-[),i.
 
 490 MODEEN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 ling fills the great gap in Fichte's system. His method 
 does not essentially differ from that of liis predecessor. 
 Schelling, it is true, recognizes that the universe is not, 
 strictly speaking, the creation of the ego, and, consequent- 
 ly, has an existence relatively distinct from the thinking- 
 subject. To think is not to produce, but to reproduce,. 
 Nature is, according to him, what it is not for Fichte : a 
 datum or a fact. He cannot, therefore, escape the necessity 
 of partially recognizing experience and observation; he 
 even goes so far as to call them the source of knowledge. 
 
 But, the reader will please observe, though Schelling 
 denies that the ego makes the non-ego, he denies, with 
 equal emphasis, that the non-ego makes the ego, that sense- 
 perception constitutes thought (Locke, Hume, Condillac). 
 Thought, knowledge, science, cannot be derived from the 
 non-ego and outer or inner perception; they have their 
 source and principle in that which also constitutes the source 
 and principle of the non-ego, in the absolute. Experience 
 is but the starting-point of speculation, the point of cle- 
 fcirture in the literal sense of the term: a 2^riuri specula- 
 tion continues to be the philosopliical method. Speculation 
 operates with the facts of experience, but these facts cannot 
 contradict a priori thought ; they must, therefore, conform 
 to its laws, because the world of facts (the real order) and 
 the world of thoughts (the ideal order) have a common 
 source, the aljsolute, and cannot contradict each other. 
 Nature is existinrj reason, mind is thinking reason. Thought 
 must accustom itself to separating the notion of reason from 
 the idea of mind; it must conceive an impersonal reason, 
 and no longer regard this formula as a contradiction in 
 terms. We must conceive the substance of Spinoza as 
 impersonal reason embracing the ego and the non-ego ; we 
 must look upon things as the images of thought, and 
 thought as the twin brother of things. There is a thorough- 
 going parallelism between nature and thought, and they
 
 SCHELLING 491 
 
 have a common origin: the one develops according to the 
 same law as the othcr.^ 
 
 Thought, as Fichte, inspired by Kant, had said, is inva- 
 riably thesis, antithesis, and synthesis. Natui-e, the image 
 of thought, is (1) matter or gravity (thesis : brutal allirma- 
 tion of matter) ; (2) form or light (antithesis : negation of 
 matter, principle of organization and individuation, ideal 
 principle) ; (3) organized matter (synthesis of matter and 
 form). The three stages of material evolution are not sep- 
 arated in nature ; no more so than the tlu-ee original acts of 
 thought. The whole of nature is organized even in its 
 smallest details (Leibniz), and the so-called inorganic world, 
 the earth itself, and the heavenly bodies, are living organ- 
 isms. If natui-e were not alive, it could not produce life. 
 The so-called inorganic kingdom is the vegetable kingdom in 
 germ ; the animal kingdom is the vegetable kingdom raised 
 to a liigher power. The human brain is the climax of uni- 
 versal organization, the last stage of organic evolution.^ 
 J»lagnetism, electricity, irritability, and sensibility are mani- 
 festations of the same force, in different degrees (correlation 
 and equivalence of forces). Nothing is dead, nothing is 
 stationary^ in nature; every^thing is hfe, movement, becoming, 
 perpetual oscillation between two extremes, productivity^ 
 and product, polarity (electricity, magnetism, and intellectr 
 ual life), expansion and contraction, action and reaction, 
 struggle between two contrary and (at tlie same time) 
 correlative principles,* the synthesis of wliicli is the soul of 
 
 the world.^ 
 
 The pliilosophy of mind or transeeiKlciilal iiliilosopby '^ 
 has for its subject-matter tlie evolution of psychical life, the 
 genesis of the ego, and aims to demonstrate the parallelism 
 of tlie physical and moral oiders. 
 
 1 Workx, TV., pp. 105 ff. * r.ionlaiio Bruno. 
 
 • The Wille of .Scliop(;iili:ui«r. * 'I'li" ■nn\f(xo<: of Ilcnicliliis 
 
 « I'hito uii.l the Sloici. • Wurks, III., pp. 327 IT.
 
 492 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The stages in the evolution of mind are : sensation, outer 
 and inner perception (by means of the a priori intuitions 
 and the categories), and rational abstraction. Sensation, 
 perception, and abstraction constitute the theoretical ego, 
 the different degrees of the understanding. Through abso- 
 lute abstraction, i. e., the absolute distinction which the in- 
 telligence draws between itself and what it produces, tlie 
 understanding becomes will : the theoretical ego becomes 
 the practical ego. Like magnetism and the principle of 
 sensibility, intelligence and will are different degrees of the 
 same tiring.^ They are merged in the notion of i^ruductivity^ 
 or creative activity. The intellect is creative without 
 knowing it ; its productivity is unconscious and necessary ; 
 will is conscious of itself ; it produces with the conscious- 
 ness of being the source of what it produces : hence the 
 feeling of freedom accompanying its manifestations. 
 
 Just as life in nature is the result of two contrary forces, 
 so the life of the mind springs from the reciprocal action 
 of the intellect, which posits the non-ego, and of the will, 
 which overcomes it. These are not new forces ; they are 
 the same forces which, after having been gravity and light, 
 magnetism and electricity, irritability and sensibility, mani- 
 fest themselves, in the sphere of mind, as intelligence and 
 will. Their antagonism constitutes the life of the race : 
 history. 
 
 History unfolds itself in three ages which run parallel 
 with the three stages of organic evolution, corresponding 
 to the three kingdoms. The primitive age is characterized 
 by the predominance of the fatalistic element (thesis : 
 matter, gravity, intelligence without will) ; the second, 
 which was inaugurated by the Roman people and still con- 
 tinues, is the reaction of the active and voluntary element 
 against the ancient /«^?6»i ; the third, finally, which belongs 
 to the future, will be the synthesis of these two principles. 
 1 Spinoza and Fichte.
 
 SCHELLING 493 
 
 Mind and nature will gradually be blended into a liarnio- 
 nious and living unity. The idea will become more and 
 more real ; reality will become more and more ideal. In 
 other words : the absolute, which is the identity of the ideal 
 and the real, will manifest and realize itself more and more. 
 
 However, as history is developed in time, and as time 
 has no limits, history necessarily consists in infinite progress, 
 and the realized absolute remains an ideal which cannot 
 be definitively and completely realized. Hence if the ego 
 were merely theoretical and practical, it could never realize 
 the absolute ; for, reflection as well as action is necessarily 
 subject to the law of the dualism of subject and object, of 
 the ideal and the real. Thought, it is true, can and nuist 
 rise beyond reflection and its dualism ; tlirough the intellect- 
 ual intuition ^ we deny tlie dualism of the ideal and the real, 
 we afhrm that the ego and the non-ego s})iing from a higher 
 unity in which all antitheses are blended; we rise, in a 
 measure, beyond personal thought and ourselves ; we iden 
 tify ourselves with impersonal reason, which becomes 
 objectified in the world and is personified in the ego. In a 
 word, we partially return into the absolute whence we came. 
 
 But even this intuition cannot completely free itself from 
 the law of opposition ; consequently it is still a polarity, 
 forming, on the one hand, a perceiving subject, on the 
 other, an object perceived from without. The ego is on 
 one side, (lod on the other; the dualism continues; tin- 
 absolute is not a reality possessed or assimilated by the 
 mind. The mind does not attain or I'calize the al)soliit(', 
 either as intelligenci! or action, but as tlie feeling of tlie 
 beautiful in nature and in art.'- Ait, religion, iind revela- 
 tion are one and tlie same thing, suju'rior even to jihilosophy. 
 Philosophy co'/ir-cms God; art /.s (!od. Kiiowledgi' is the 
 ideal presence, art the real presence of the Deity.^ 
 
 1 riat<i, I'loliiius, Si. Augu.stiiK-, iiii<I tli.' Mystics. 
 
 a Kant. ° Nco-riatoiiisin.
 
 494 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 2. Sclielling's "positive" philosophy, inauguratecl in 
 1809 by the dissertation on human freedom, accentuates 
 the mystical element contained in the foregoing sentences. 
 Under the inlluence of Bohme, the philosopher becomes a 
 theosophist ; the pantheist, a monotheist. He insists on 
 the reality of the divine idea, on the personality of God, on 
 the cardinal importance of the Trinity. However, when 
 we peer beneath the strange forms enveloping his romanti- 
 cism, we find that there is less change in the essence of his 
 thought tlian one would suppose ; this essence is monism, 
 a form of monism, however, which, under the influence of 
 Bbhme, is clearly defined as voluntarism} The absolute, 
 the absolute indifference or identity, of " negative " philo- 
 sophy exists, but it now receives the name applied to it by 
 the Saxon theosophist : primitive will {ungruncllicher Wille). 
 The foundation or first principle of the divine being, and of 
 all being, is not thought or reason, but will striving for 
 being and individual and personal existence, or the desire- 
 to-he. Before being (ex-istere'), every being, God included, 
 desires to be. This desire or unconscious will precedes all 
 intelligence and all conscious will. For God, the evolution 
 by which he realizes himself, personifies himself, or makes 
 himself God, is eternal, and the stages thi'ough which this 
 evolution passes (the persons or hypostases of the Trinity) 
 are merged into each other; but they are cUstinguished 
 
 1 The voluntaristic conception is, it is true, abeady found in the 
 Abhcmdlungen zur Erlduterung dea Idealismiis der WissenscTiaftslehre, 
 published by Schelling in the PJdlosopJiisches Journal (1796 and 1797), 
 as well as in numerous passages in Fichte, whose philosophy is entirely 
 impregnated with it. But he clearly and consciously affirms the prin- 
 ciple in his treatise on liberty : Es giebt in der leizten und hochsten In- 
 stanz gar kein anderes Sein als WoUe7i. Wollen ist Ursein, und avf dieses 
 allein passen alle Pradikate desselhen : Grundlosigkcit, Eicigkeit, Unah- 
 Tidngigkeit von der Zeit, Selhsthejnhung. Die ganze Philosophie streht nur 
 dahin, diesen hochsten Ausdruck zu finden. ( Works, first series, vol. VII 
 p. 350.)
 
 SCHELLING 405 
 
 from each other in the human consciousness, appearing 
 successively and forming- stages in the rehgious develop- 
 ment of humanity. The evil in the M-orld has its source, 
 not in God considered as a person, but in what precedes his 
 personality, in that wliich, in God, is not God himself, i. e., 
 in the desidcrium essemli wlrich we have just recognized as 
 the first cause of all things, and which Schelling does not 
 hesitate to call the divine egoism. In God, this principle 
 is eternally merged in his love; in man, it becomes an 
 independent principle and the source of moral evil. But 
 however great the latter may be, it serves the purposes of 
 the absolute, no less than the good. 
 
 We shall not here consider the jJiilosoph^ of mytholoiji/ 
 and revelation, which we have set forth in another work,^ 
 and which interests the historian of religion rather than the 
 historian of philosophy. Our main purpose was to outline 
 the contents of the principal treatises written by Schelling 
 from 1795 to 1800, and to elucidate : (1) his masterly 
 critique of Ficliie' a cfjoism {Iclikhre) ; (2) his conception of 
 the absolute as will, the common ground of the object and 
 subject (Kant), of the ego and non-ego (Fichte), of thought 
 and extension (Spinoza); (3) his pliilosophy of nature, 
 which, though abandoned by positive science, produced 
 such naturalists as Burdach, Oken, Carus, Oei-sted, Steffens, 
 G. H. Schubert, and, by carrying speculation into a lield 
 from which ideological investigations had banislicd it, pre- 
 pared the way for the fusion of metaphysics and science, 
 which we are now endeavoring to bring about; (4) his 
 philosophy of liistory, a liappy prelude to Hegel's philoso- 
 phy of mind. 
 
 The philosophy of Schelling, the influence of whit-h 
 was partially counteracted and obscured l)y tlie Ilcgeliau 
 
 » Exumen crilujw: dc la j>hilosoj)hie relijleuse de Schelliug, Strasluirg. 
 ISUU.
 
 49(3 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 school,! i-eally consists of two very distinct systems, which 
 are connected by a common principle : ^ according to the 
 hrst, which forms its starting-point, thought precedes being 
 (idealism) ; according to the second, (potential) being is 
 the antecedent of thought (realism). Under the influence 
 of the former, he speaks of intellectual intuition and con- 
 ceives his TranscencUntalphilosopUe, while the latter exalts 
 experience and the philosophy of nature. The one leads to 
 Heo-el and the a priori construction of the universe and of 
 history, the other, to Schopenhauer and contemporaneous 
 empiricism. 
 
 § 66. Hegel 3 
 
 Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel was born at Stuttgart, 
 1770, and died as a professor in the University of Berlin, 
 
 1 Nevertheless, this influence was considerable. Even omitting 
 the disciples properly so-called, we can detect it in most of the thinkers 
 mentioned in § 71. Observe that the most celebrated among contem- 
 poraneous German philosophers, Eduard von Hartmann, is as much a 
 disciple of Schelling as of Schopenhauer, and that the most original of 
 our French metaphysicians, Charles Secretan, is an avowed adherent 
 of the " positive philosophy." 
 
 2 We noticed the same dualism in Plotinus. 
 
 3 Complete works, 19 vols, and supplement, containing Hegel's 
 biography by K. Rosenla-anz, Berlin, 1832-44. The most important 
 works of Hegel have been translated into French by A. Vera, professor 
 at Naples, who has also written an Introduction a la philosophie de Hegel, 
 2d ed., Paris, 1864. Consult also: [K. Rosenkranz, Krltische Erldu- 
 terungen des hegelschen System!^, Konigsberg, 1840; H. JJlricl Princip 
 und Methode der hegelschen Philosophie, Berlin, 1843 ; E. Haym, Hegel 
 und seine Zeit, Berlin, 1857] ; P. Janet, Etudes snr la dialectique dans 
 Platan et dans Hegel, Paris, 1860; [Foucher de Careil, Hegel et Schopen- 
 hauer, Paris, 1862] ; E. Scherer, Hegel et Vhe'ge'lianisme (in his Melanges 
 d'histoire religieuse, 2d ed., Paris, 186.5) ; J. H. Stirling, The Secret oj 
 Hegel. The Hegelian System in Origin, Principle, Form, and Matter, 2 
 vols., London, 1865; [K. Kbstlin, Hegel, Tubingen, 1870; E. Cau-d, 
 Hegel {Blackwood's Phil. Classics'), l^onAon, 1883; J. S. Kedney, HegeVs 
 Esthetics (Griggs's Series), Chicago, 1885 ; G. S. Morris, Hegel's Phi-
 
 HEGEL 497 
 
 1831. Like his friend Sclielling, he attended the theological 
 seminary at Tubingen. Jena, where he renewed and then 
 dissolved the friendship with his fellow-countryman, who 
 was live years his junior, Xuremberg, where he liad charge 
 of the Gymnasium, Heidelberg, and the Prussian capital, 
 mark the different stages in his academic career. We 
 mention the following works : (1) Phiinomenologie des 
 Geistes ^ (1807) ; (2) Wissenschaft clcr Loijih^ in three vol- 
 umes (1812-181G) ; (3) Enctjdopedie der philosopldschen 
 Wisscnschaftcn ^ (1817) ; (1) Crrundiinien der Philosophie 
 des Rechts * (1821) ; also, Vorlesungen uber die Philosophie 
 der Geschichie,^ Vorlesungen iiber die ^sthetik,^ Vorlesungen 
 iiber die Philosophie der Religion^"' Vorlesungen iiber die 
 Geschichte der Philosophie,^ published after liis death. 
 
 losophy of the Slate and of History {id.), 1887; W. T. Harris, Hegel' » 
 Logic {id.), 1890; A. Seth, Hegelianism and Personality, 2d ed., Edin- 
 bui-gh and Loudon, 1893 ; AV. Wallace, Prolegomena to the Study oj 
 HegeVs Philosophy and especially of his Logic, 2d ed., Clarendon Press, 
 1894. See also the works on Post-Kantiau pliilosopliy. p. 431, note 1. 
 
 1 [Translation of chs. 1, 2, and 3 in Journal of Speculative Philo- 
 sophy, vol. II. — Tr.] 
 
 2 [Vol. 11., tr. by W. T. Harris. See also Stirling, cited p. 490, 
 note 3.] 
 
 8 [W. Wallace, The Logic of Hrgrl. Translated fnnn the Encyclo- 
 ] edia of the Philosophical Sciences, 2d ed., Oxford, ls!)2 ; same trans- 
 lator. Philosophy of Mind, id., 1S94. — Tr.] 
 
 * [Selections from this work translated hy J. ^f. Sterrett, under the 
 title. The Ethics of Hegel (in the Ethical Series), Hostun, 1893. — Tr.] 
 
 6 [Philosophy of History, tr. by J. Sibree, Bolni's Library, 18G0. — 
 Tk.] 
 
 8 [Introduction to the Philosophy of Art. tr. by B. Bosanqnet, Lon- 
 don, 1«80 ; Phil, of Art, abridged tr. l>y W. Ilastie ; tr. of second part 
 by W. Bryant in Journal of Speculative Philosophy, \.-\ll., XI.-XIII. 
 -Tr.] 
 
 7 [Part. tr. in Journal of Spec. J'hil., vols. XV.-XXI. — '1 R.] 
 
 8 [History of Philosophy, tr. by K. S. Ilaldane, 3 vols, London, 
 lH92 fT. ; parts Ir. in Journal of Spec. Phil., vols. IV , V., XIII., XX, 
 -Tb.J
 
 498 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 According to Fichte, the thlng-in-itself (the iibsolute) is 
 the ego itself, which produces tlie phenomenal world by an 
 unconscious and involuntary creation, and then overcomes 
 it by a free and conscious effort. According to Sclielling, 
 the absolute is neither the ego nor the non-ego, but their 
 common root, in which the opposition between a thinking 
 subject and a thought object cUsappears in a perfect indif- 
 ference ; it is the neutral principle, anterior and superior to 
 all contrasts, the identity of contraries. Fichte's absolute 
 is one of the terms of the opposition, that of Sclielling is 
 the transcendent, mysterious, impenetrable source of the 
 same. Fichte's conception errs in reducing the absolute 
 to what is but one of its aspects : the absolute of Fichte 
 is the ego limited by a theoretically inexplicable non-ego ; 
 it is a prisoner, it is not really the absolute. Schelling's 
 absolute is a transcendent entity, which does not explain 
 anything, since we do not know either how or why to 
 deduce from it the oppositions constituting the real world. 
 The absolute indifference, far from being the highest and 
 most concrete reality, is, at bottom, nothing but an ab- 
 straction. 
 
 According to Hegel, the common source of the ego and 
 of nature does not transcend reality ; it is immanent in it. 
 Mind and nature are not aspects of the absolute, or a kind 
 of screen, behind which an indifferent and lifeless God lies 
 concealed, but its successive modes. The absolute is not 
 immova])le, l)ut active ; it is not the j)rinciple of nature and 
 of mind, but is itself successively nature and mind. This 
 succession, this process, this perpetual generation of things, 
 is the absolute itself. In Schelling, things proceed from the 
 absolute, which, for that very reason, remains outside of 
 them. In Hegel, the absolute is the process itself ; it does 
 not produce movement and life, it is movement and life. 
 It does not exceed the things, but is wholly in them ; nor 
 does it, in any wa}^, exceed the intellectual capacity of man.
 
 HEGEL 499 
 
 If we mean by God the being transcending human reason^ 
 then Hegel is the most atheistic of philosophers, since no 
 one is more emphatic in affirming the immanency and 
 perfect knowableness of the absolute. Spinoza himself, 
 the pliilosopher of immane^icy^ does not seem to go so far; 
 for, although he concedes that the intellect has an adequate 
 idea of God, he assumes that the Substance has infinite 
 attributes. 
 
 While modifying the Schellingian idea of the absolute, 
 Hegel at the same time subjects the extravagant imagina- 
 tion of his friend to a merciless intellectual discipline. In 
 order to arrive at a knowledge of the principle and logical 
 connection of things, we must, of course, think, but we 
 must think logically and methodically. Only on that con- 
 chtion will the result tally with that of infinite thought in 
 nature and history. The absolute, let us say, is movement, 
 process, evolution. This movement has its law and its goal. 
 Its law and its goal are not imposed upon the absolute from 
 without ; they are immanent in it, they are the absolute it- 
 self. Now the law which governs both human thought 
 and unconscious nature is reason ; the end at wliich things 
 aim is, likewise, reason, but self-conscious reason. Hence 
 the terms absolute and reason are synonymous. The abso- 
 lute is reason, wliich becomes personified in man, after pass- 
 ing tlu-ough the successive stages of inorganic and living 
 nature. 
 
 But reason is not, as Kant conceives it, the luiman under- 
 standing, a faculty of the soul, a coml)ination of principles, 
 forms, or rules according to which we think things. It is 
 the law according to which being is produced, constituted, 
 or unfolded ; or rather, it is botli a subjective faculty and 
 an oljjective reality : it is in me as the essence and norm of 
 my thouglit, and it is in the things as the essence and law of 
 their evolution. It foUows that its categoiics liave a nuich 
 greater siguiHcancc! than Kanlianism supposiMl, They aro
 
 nOO MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 not only modes of tJiiuJdni/ thing's; tliey are the modes of 
 being of the things themselves. They are not empty frames, 
 which receive their contents from without ; they are sub- 
 stantial forms, as the Middle Ages used to say ; they give 
 themselves their own content ; they are creative acts of 
 divine and human reason. They are both the forms which 
 mould my thought and the stages of eternal creation. ^ 
 
 Hence it is of essential importance to metaphysics that 
 we make a more thorough study of the categories, their 
 nature and, above all, their connection. Kant had already 
 observed that the categories are not separate from and in- 
 different to each other, ranged alongside of each other in 
 our intelligence like drawers in a piece of furniture, but 
 intimately connected with each other. They are, in short, 
 nothing but transformations of one and the same funda- 
 mental category, the idea of being. Hence it will not suf- 
 fice to discuss them at random ; we must consider them in 
 their connection, surprise them, as it were, in the very 
 act of their mutual production. Kant saw the impor- 
 tance of such an a priori deduction of the categories, and 
 attempted it, but his deduction is, in reality, a merely em- 
 pirical enumeration (incomplete at that) of pure concepts. 
 We must return to Kant's notion, but we must substitute 
 for his table of categories a real deduction, a true genealo- 
 gical table. 
 
 This is the most exalted and withal the most arduous 
 task of metaphysics. In order to succeed in it, we must 
 eradicate our prejudices, all our sensible ideas, and trust to 
 reason alone ; we must let it unfold its own contents, and 
 do nothing ourselves but follow it in its development 
 (nach-denJcen'), or record its oracles, as it were, at the very 
 time of their production. To leave thought to itself, to 
 abandon it to its spontaneous self-activity {Selbstbewegung 
 
 1 Logic, vol. I., Introduction; Enci/clopedie der philosophischen Wis- 
 senschoften, Introduction.
 
 HEGEL 501 
 
 des Beyriffs) : that is the true pliilosophical method, the 
 immanent or dialectical method. 
 
 The science which does all this is logic, i. e., in the sense 
 of Hegel, the genealogy of pure concepts. But since, in the 
 panlogistic hypothesis, the X6yo<i, the object of logic, is both 
 the principle ^^^hich thinks the things in us, and the objec- 
 tive cause which produces them, or the tldng-in-itself ; the 
 genealogy of its concepts is at the same time the genealogy 
 of the things, the explanation of the universe, or meta- 
 physics. Hegel's speculative logic is both what the school 
 calls logic (Dcnklehre) and what it calls metaphysics or 
 ontology (^Sclnslehre'). It is called spccidative, in order to 
 distinguish it from the former and to include the latter. It 
 is metaphysical, for it speaks of mechanical, chemical, and 
 organic processes, and likewise embraces ethics, since it 
 treats of the good. In this it is consistent with its panlo- 
 gistic premises : if reason not only conceives^ but produces 
 being, if it is the creator of things, if it is everything; the 
 science of reason (Xo^yiK-rj) must be the universal science, 
 which includes all the particular sciences. 
 
 It is an inconsistency ^ in Hegel, as we have shown else- 
 where,^ to have his Logic followed by a Philosojjhy of Nature 
 and a Philosophy of Mind. Logic treats of reason in ah- 
 stracfo, the philosophy of nature and of mind reveals it to 
 us as it realizes itself in the universe and in history. 
 
 I. Logic, or Genealogy of Pure Concepts 
 
 1. Quality, Quantity, Measure^ 
 
 The common root of the categories or pure concepts is 
 the notion of helny, the emptiest and at the same time the 
 
 * The philosophy of nature and the philosophy of mind are already 
 implicitly contained, the former in the first and .second, the laller in 
 the third, part of the logic. 
 
 2 Introiluclion hintorifjnc a la philosophie h^gdliennc, Paris and Stras- 
 bur^,', ls(;(;, p. k;. 
 
 • Loyic, vol. I. ; Encyclopedia, §§ 81 if.
 
 502 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 most comprehensive, the most abstract and the most real, 
 the most elementary and the most exalted notion. It is the 
 identical substance, and the material of all our notions, the 
 fundamental theme which runs through them all. Indeed, 
 quality is a mode of heing, quantity, a mode of leinij, pro- 
 portion, phenomenon, action, modes of hcing. All our 
 concepts express modes of being, and hence are merely 
 transformations of the idea of being. 
 
 But how shall we explain these transformations ? How 
 does leing, which is everything, become an/jthiiig else ? In 
 virtue of what principle or inner force is it modihed ? The 
 contradiction which it contains is this principle or force. 
 Being is the most universal notion, and for that very rea- 
 son, also the poorest and emptiest. To be white, to be 
 black, to be extended, to be good, is to be something : being 
 without any determination is non-being. Hence, being 
 pure and simjjle is equal to non-being. It is both itself 
 ana its opposite. If it were only itself, it would remain 
 immovable and barren ; if it were only nothing, it would 
 be equal to zero, and, in this case, perfectly powerless and 
 fruitless. Because it is loth it hecomes something, a differ- 
 ent thing, everything. The contradiction contained in be- 
 ing is resolved in the notion of hecoming^ or development. 
 Becoming is both being and non-being (that which will be). 
 The two contraries which engender it, being and nothing, 
 are contained and reconciled in it. A ncAV contradiction re- 
 sults, which is resolved by a new synthesis, and so on, until 
 we reach the absolute idea. 
 
 This, then, is the moving principle in the Hegelian logic : 
 a contradiction is reconciled in a unity, reappears in a new 
 form, only to disappear and reappear again, until it is re- 
 solved in the final unity. By repudiating the irrinciplc of 
 contradiction of Aristotle and Leibniz, according to which a 
 thino- cannot both be and not be, it takes sides with the 
 Sophists, without, however, falling into their scepticism.
 
 HEGEL 603 
 
 The contradiction does not, according to Hegel, exist in 
 thouglit alone, but also in the things themselves ; existence 
 itself is contradictory. When, with the realistic and dual- 
 istic systems, we separate thought from its object and con- 
 cede to each an independent existence, the antinomies of 
 thought necessarily become a source of discouragement and 
 scepticism. However, when we regard nature as the self- 
 development of thought, and thought as nature becoming 
 conscious of itself, when we recognize that the world, being 
 thought objectified, contains nothing but thought ; the con- 
 tradiction in which the philosopher is involved ceases to 
 be an obstacle to the understanding of things, and appears 
 to him as their very essence reflecting itself in the antino- 
 mies of his thought. 
 
 Now that we know the moving principle and the unchan- 
 ging form of the Hegelian dialectics, we need not follow out 
 the unvarying and monotonous mechanism of its deductions. 
 It will be sufficient to emphasize the most salient points of 
 his metaphysics as set forth in the Logic. 
 
 The contradiction found in the idea of being is resolved 
 in the notion of becoming. Being becomes, i. e., determines 
 itself, limits itself, defines itself. But determinate or finite 
 being continues ad infimtum ; the finite is infinite ; nothing 
 compels thought to assign limits to it. Here we have a new 
 contradiction, which is resolved in the notion of individ- 
 2iaUtg (l)eing-for-self, Filrsichsein). The individual is the 
 unity of the finite and the infinite. To consider these two 
 terms as excluding each other is to forget tliat the infinite, 
 excluded by tlie iinite, would be limited by the finite, or 
 A\'(nild l)e finite itself. If the infinite begins where the finite 
 ends, and if the finite begins where the infinite ends, so that 
 the infinite is beyond the finite, or the finite on this ddc of 
 the infinite, it would not really be the infinite. The infinite 
 is the essence of the finite, and tlic finite is the manifestation 
 of th(i infinite, the infinite existing. Infinity deterniineits
 
 504 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 itself, limits itself, sets boundaries to itself ; in a word, it 
 becomes tlie finite by the very fact that it gives itself exist- 
 ence. Existence is possible only under certain conditions, 
 in certain modes, or within certain limits. Existence is 
 self-limitation. Existence is finite being.^ Finite being, 
 the individual, the atom, is infinity existing in a certain 
 manner, limited infinity : quality becomes quantity. 
 
 Quantity is extensive quantity (^lumler^ or intensive 
 quantity {degree). Number, which is quantity broken up, 
 so to speak, and degree, which is concentrated quantity, 
 are reconciled in the notion of measure and iiro])ortion. 
 
 Measure is being becoming essence ( Wescn'). 
 
 2. Essence and Appearance. Suhstantialitij and Causality. 
 Reciprocity ^ 
 
 Essence is being, unfolded or expanded so that its aspects 
 reflect each other. Hence the categories which follow 
 come in pairs : essence and appearance, force and expres- 
 sion, matter and form, substance and accident, cause and 
 effect, ground and consequence, action and reaction. This 
 reflection-into-itself {Befieonon in ihm selbst), or if we prefer, 
 this reflex, is the 'phenomenon. Essence and phenomenon 
 (appearance) are inseparable ; indeed, the phenomenon is 
 the very essence of essence ; or, in other terms, it is as 
 essential to essence to appear ((paiveaOac), to life to manifest 
 itself, to the principle to produce its consequences, as it is 
 essential to the phenomenon to imply an essence. Phe- 
 nomenon without essence is mere show, or mere appearance. 
 
 The essential is opposed by the accidental or contingent, 
 which in turn becomes essential in the sense that the idea 
 of the essential needs it in order to be produced. No cate- 
 gory, we see, is independent of its neighbors. Although 
 excluding each other, the categories need and mutually 
 engender each other. 
 
 1 Cf. § 50. '^ Logic, vol. II. ; Encycl, §§ 112 £f.
 
 HEGEL 505 
 
 Essence expresses itself in a series of phenomena, and 
 constitutes the thing or ohjeat, which is a totality of charac- 
 teristics connected by one and the same essence. Consid- 
 ered in their relation to the object, these characteristics or 
 phenomena are called ■properties. Just as there is no essence 
 without a phenomenon, there is no thing apart from its 
 properties. A thing is what its properties are ; nothing else. 
 Se[)arate the thing from its essential properties, and noth- 
 ing is left ; its qualities are the thing itself. 
 
 As the generative principle of the phenomenon, the 
 essence is the force or agent of which the phenomenon is 
 the act or expression. Since a force is nothing but a total- 
 ity of phenomena considered in their identity, and its ex- 
 pression merely the acting force itself, in so far as it exerts 
 itself, it is a mere tautology to explain an act by an agent 
 {ciir opium facit dormire ? — q^uia., etc.). As the matter, so 
 its form ; as the agent, so the act ; as the character, so its 
 manifestations ; as the tree, so its fruits. 
 
 The dualism : essence and phenomenon, ground and con- 
 sequence, force and expression, agent and act, matter and 
 form, is resolved in the notion of activity.^ the synthesis and 
 summary of the preceding notions. This logical category 
 corresponds to what is called nature in metaphysics-^ In 
 short, nature is action, production, creation. All the treas- 
 ures lying in her fruitful lap, she manifests, produces, and 
 then takes back, only to reproduce and take back again, 
 and reproduce eternally. 
 
 Activity is synonymous with reulitij ( WirUichl-eit). 
 Nothing is active except what is real, and nothing is real 
 except what is active.^ Absolute rest does not exist.^ 
 
 1 It must not be forgotten that Ilegel identifies logic and meta- 
 physics. 
 
 ' Since " reason alone is real," Ilegel concludes that what is real is 
 rational (p. 52 1). 
 
 ' ndtna x.oip('i «"* oibiv fUpd (§ 8).
 
 506 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Reality, compared with mere possibility^ becomes necessity. 
 What is real is necessarily active. Activity, reality, and 
 necessity are synonymous. A being exists in so far as it 
 acts, and acts in so far as it exists. 
 
 Essence or reality, considered as a necessary principle of 
 activity, becomes substance. Substance is not a substratum 
 in the proper sense of the word, but the sum of its modes. 
 Hence we must abandon : in theology, the idea of a God 
 existing outside of the universe ; in psychology, the idea of 
 a soul existing independently of the phenomena constituting 
 the ego ; in physics, the assumption of a kind of mysterious 
 substratum of phenomena, of an unqualified and unqualifi- 
 able something, I-know-not-what, without extension, with- 
 out color, without form, and yet supposed to be something 
 real. A substance so constituted as to escape scientific ob- 
 servation would be a pure chimera. It was owing to an 
 illusion peculiar to dualism that the poet could say : "• No 
 mere created mind e'er penetrates the heart of nature." ^ 
 Nature has no heart or inner part; the outside of matter is 
 matter itself ; it belongs to its essence to unfold itself, to 
 have no inner life {das Wesen der Natur ist die Aeiisscr- 
 lichkeit). 
 
 Substance is the totality of its modes. But it is not, on 
 that account, as Spinozism conceives it, a purely mechanical 
 aggregate, a mere sum ; it is a living totality, united with 
 its modes by an organic tie : it is the cause of its modes, and 
 its modes are the effects of the substance. These notions 
 are not indifferent to each other ; they are correlative pairs. 
 The cause is inseparable from its effect; the effect indis- 
 solubly connected with its efficient cause. The latter is 
 immanent in the former, as the soul in the body. Modes 
 are unfolded, revealed, expressed substance ; the effect is 
 
 1 [Ins Innere der Natur dringt kein erschaffner Geist : 
 Zu giiisklich, wenn sie noch die aussre Schale weist. 
 
 Haller, Die menscMichen Tuycnden. — Tr.]
 
 HEGEL 607 
 
 the cause effected, explicated, manifested. There is noth- 
 ing in the effect which is not also in the cause ; nor is there 
 anything in the cause that does not effect, assert, or realize 
 itself. The idea of the effect cannot be separated from the 
 idea of the cause ; nay, every effect is, in turn, a cause, and 
 every cause, the effect of a preceding cause. In any series 
 of causes and effects. A, B, C, D . . ., the effect B is noth- 
 ing but the cause A asserting itself as a cause, and becom- 
 ing in B the cause of C, in C the cause of D, and so on. 
 
 The causal series is not, as formal logic maintains, an 
 indefinite series, a progrcssus in infinitum^ in which each 
 effect produces a new effect without reacting upon the 
 cause that produced it. The truth is, the effect B is not 
 only the cause of C, but also the cause of A. In short, A 
 would not be a cause unless it effected B ; hence it is owing 
 to B, or hecausc of B, that A is a cause ; hence B is not only 
 the effect, but also the cause of the cause A. By. a neces- 
 sary reaction, every effect is the cause of its cause, and 
 every cause the effect of its effect. Rain, for example, is a 
 cause of moisture, and moisture, in tiu'n, a cause of rain,* 
 or again : The character of a people depends on their form 
 of government, but the form of their government also 
 depends on the character of the people. Hence, since the 
 effect is not fatally jire-determined by its cause, but reacts 
 on it, the causal series in nature is not a straight line pro- 
 longed to infinity, but a curved line wliich returns to its 
 starting-point, i. e., a circle. The notion of a rectilinear 
 series is a vague and indefinite conception ; the idea of the 
 circle is exact and clearly defined, a finished whole (also- 
 lutuni). 
 
 This reaction of tlie effect upon tlie caUvSe (reciprocal 
 action^ Wechsehvirkxviuj) eidiances tlie im]:)ortance of the 
 effect, and gives it the cliaracter of freedom, which it lacks 
 ill the system of Spinoza. Accor(Uiig to tliis ])liih)Sopher, 
 the effect necessarily dupentls upon the pre-existing cause j
 
 508 MODEKN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 in reality, however, it is an effect only in a certain measure^ 
 and is but relatively determined. There is neither in the 
 beginning, nor in the middle, nor in the end of the causal 
 series, a cause distinct from all the rest, and absolute with 
 reference to the others. The absolute is not to be found 
 in any particular part of the causal chain ; it resides in the 
 sum-total of the particular and relative causes. The latter 
 are not so many slaves following the triumphal chariot of 
 a first cause which excludes all other causality, and with 
 regard to which the relative causes are as nothing ; but 
 each cause takes part in the absolute. Each is relatively 
 absolute, none is absolutely absolute. No one has an 
 exclusive claim to omnipotence ; the sum of individual 
 energies, or, to express it still more clearly, everything 
 that exists tlu-ough causal power, constitutes all existing 
 'power. 
 
 In reciprocal action, the two spheres into which being 
 is divided when it becomes essence and phenomenon, are 
 reunited and thus become logical totality. 
 
 3. The Notion^ or Subjective, Objective, and Absolute 
 Totality ^ 
 
 Outside of totality, none of the ideas thus far evolved 
 has reality. A quality, a quantity, a force, or a cause, is 
 nothing apart from the whole in which it is produced. 
 Nothing in nature exists in isolation ; nor can anything in 
 the domain of thought lay claim to autonomy. This be- 
 longs only to the categories taken in their totality. Lib- 
 erty is found in the whole alone. Hence in logical totality 
 or the notion (Begriff),^ being and essence return into 
 themselves. 
 
 1 Logic, vol. III. ; EncycL, §§ 160 ff. 
 
 ■•^ Hegel regards Begriff as synonymous with Inhegriff, whole, 
 totality.
 
 HEGEL 609 
 
 The idea of totality is divided into subjective totality (the 
 notion proper) and objective totality. 
 
 The essential elements of the idea of life : essence, phe- 
 nomenon, and reciprocal action, reappear in the concept of 
 subjective totality or notion, as tinkcrsalit//, i^articularity, 
 and individualiti/. In the judgment^ which is thought or the 
 subject in action, universality and individuality, generality 
 and particularity, have the appearance of being distinct 
 and separate, while in reality the judgment is merely the 
 affirmation of their identity. When I say that man is 
 mortal, or that Paul is mortal, I affirm that the character- 
 istic common to all created beings, mortality, belongs to 
 the particular being (man), and that the individual Paul, 
 in turn, as a mortal being, is identical with the univer- 
 sality of creatures. In so far as the judgment affirms the 
 identity of the universal and the individual, of the general 
 and the particular, it is contradictory. The solution of the 
 contradiction is found in reasoning, or the syllogmn. The 
 universal or general notion is unfolded in the major prem- 
 ise, the individual notion in the conclusion ; and the 
 minor premise, which is the connecting link lietween the 
 major premise and the conclusion, expresses their identity. 
 
 The subjective notion is a form without matter, a con- 
 tainer without a content. It exists, in principle, as a goal 
 ov final cause^ but does not exist in realit}'. Hence its ten- 
 dency to objectify itself ; it is the eternal source of life in 
 nature and of progress in history. The objectified notion 
 is the universe, the objective ivhole, or objects. Tlie general, 
 the particular, and the individual are successively objec- 
 tified in mechanism (simple external juxtaposition of 
 ol)jects), in chemism (mutual })en3trati(m of objects), and 
 in organism (totality-iniity). 
 
 IIowcvL']-. a notion wliicli is no loii<_;ci' a notion, tliouL;lit 
 which has bcconu- Ixxly, is again contiadictoiv . .Inst as 
 thought is not made to remain empty, but to be filled with
 
 510 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 an ol)jective content; so, too, the world, or the whole of 
 things, is not made to remain a stranger to consciousness, 
 but to be thought or understood. The subjective notion 
 is a container with a content ; the universe which is uncon- 
 scious of itself is a content without a container. The lat- 
 ter contradiction is abolished by the interpenetration of 
 the two spheres in the absolute Idea, which, from the 
 theoretical standpoint, is called Truth, and from the prac- 
 tical standpoint, the Good : tliis is the highest category 
 and the last term in the development of being. 
 
 To sum up : Being is becoming, development. The con- 
 tradiction inherent in being is the principle or impul- 
 sive force of development. Being, self-expansion (self- 
 unfolding), and self-concentration (the understanding 
 of self), constitute the unchanging stages in the process. 
 Quality, quantity, measure ; essence and phenomenon, sub- 
 stantiality and causality, reciprocal action ; subjectivity, 
 objectivity, al^solute : these are the serial stages of being. 
 
 Knowing this principle, this process, and these stages, 
 we know a p^^iori the order followed in the creations of 
 nature (expanded reason) and of mind (concentrated and 
 comprehended reason). 
 
 II. Philosophy of Nature 
 1. The Inorganic World 
 
 Creative thought, like the reproductive thought of man, 
 begins with the most abstract, the most vague, and the 
 most intangible : with space and matter. After passing 
 through a long line of development it culminates in the 
 most concrete, the most perfect, the most accomplished: 
 the human organism. 
 
 ^ Encyclopedia, §§ 245 ff. — We shall consider, in tlie following 
 resume ot the Philosophy of Nature, the changes (which were not very 
 important) to which it was siihjected by the school.
 
 HEGEL 511 
 
 Like beinr/, the first notion in logic, space exists and 
 tloes not exist ; matter is something and nothing. This 
 contradiction is the very principle of physical evolution, 
 the spring which sets it in motion; it is reconciled in 
 movement^ which divides matter into separate unities 
 (Filrsichsein) and forms the heavenly system of them 
 The formation of heavenly bodies is, as it were, the fu'st 
 step taken by nature on the path of individuation. The 
 individualizing tendency, which runs through nature like 
 a mighty desire, manifests itself as attraction. Universal 
 gravitation is the ideal unity whence all things spring and 
 whither they tend, affirming itself in the midst of their 
 separation. It is the individuality, the soul, the cement of 
 the world ; it makes an organism, a living unity (tmiversum) 
 of the world. 
 
 Primitive and formless matter, the common source of the 
 heavenly bodies, corresponds to what logic calls indetermi- 
 nate being. The distribution of this matter, its organiza- 
 tion into a sidereal world, corresponds to the categories of 
 quantity. Gravitation, at last, realizes the idea of pro- 
 portion. 
 
 The astronomical cosmos is an elementary society which 
 anticipates human society. But tlie laws which govern it 
 are, as 3-et, merel}- mechanical laws ; the relations wliich 
 the stars sustain to each otlier are summed up in tlie law of 
 attraction. Hence the science wliich considers this primary 
 phase of being, asd'onomy, deals witli the (hmensioiis of 
 tlie stars, tlicir distances, their external relations, ratlier 
 tlim with their essential (|ualities, their composition, and 
 tlieir pliysiolog}^ 
 
 2. CJiemism 
 
 A second cvolutidii leads to llie (|ualilal i\'e different ia lion 
 of iiiattei-. 'I""li(' oiigiiial state of iiidifrereiice is followed 
 jjy a vaiiety of agencicjs (liglit, electricity, heat), l)y the
 
 512 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 reciprocal action of elements, by the inner process of oppo- 
 sition and reconciliation, separation and combination, polar- 
 ity and union, wliich form the subject-matter of physics and 
 chemistry. 
 
 Sidereal motion affects only the surface of bodies ; chem- 
 ism is an inner transformation, a change not only of place, 
 but of essence, a prelude to that ultimate transformation of 
 " substance " into " subject," of matter into mind, of being 
 into consciousness, of necessity into freedom, which is the 
 thial opoal of creation. 
 
 Nothing in the original flow of things resembles individ- 
 uality ; nothing is stal^le, fixed, or concentrated. But 
 nature soon returns into itself. Just as in logic pure 
 thought returns into itself and forms a circle or totality 
 {Begriff)^ so in nature, the realization of logic, the chemicul 
 process returns into itself at a certain point and forms those 
 centralized wholes which we call organisms, living beings. 
 
 3. The Organic World 
 
 The appearance of life is wholly spontaneous, and needs 
 no deus ex machina to explain it. It is the effect of the 
 same higher and immanent power which, as attraction and 
 affinity, separated the stellar groups and the elements of 
 chemism. Surely, mechanism alone cannot produce it; 
 and if matter were nothing but matter, the course of its 
 transformations would forever be in the straight line and 
 centrifugal. But beneath the physical process the evolu- 
 tion of the Idea takes place, which is the final goal of 
 things, only because it is also their creative principle. 
 
 The earth itself is a kind of organism, a crude outline 
 of the masterpiece which nature tends to realize. In this 
 sense, Schelling and his school have a right to speak of the 
 sold of the celestial bodies, of the life of the earth. This 
 life has its vicissitudes, its revolutions, and its historj-, the
 
 HEGEL 513 
 
 subject-matter of geology, and though it gradually dimin- 
 ishes, it does so merely to become the inexhaustible soui'ce 
 of new, truly organic and individual life. 
 
 From the ashes of the terrestrial organism arises the veg- 
 etable kingdom. But the plant itself is, as yet, merely an 
 imperfect organism, a kind of association or federation, the 
 members of wliich are more or less autonomous individuals. 
 Individuality proper is realized only in the animal king- 
 dom. The animal is, decidedly, an indivisible whole, whose 
 parts are really jncmbers, i. e., servants of the central unity. 
 It asserts its individuality by constant assimilation, respir- 
 ation, and locomotion. It is endowed with sensibility, nay, 
 even with inner heat and voice in its most perfect represen- 
 tatives. However, there are insensible transitions here. 
 As the inorganic kingdom is connected with the vegetable 
 kingdom by astral individualities and cr3'stallizations ; so the 
 vegetable kingdom passes into the animal kingdom in the 
 zoophj-te. Animals are developed by degrees. The same 
 idea, the same fundamental plan, more and more perfectly 
 executed, runs through crustaceans, mollusks, insects, fishes, 
 reptiles, and mammals. Finally, in the human organism, 
 the most perfect animal form, the creative idea is reflected 
 in all its fulness. Here it stops. In the material realm it 
 produces nothing more perfect. We say, in llie material 
 realm, for instead of being exhausted in the creation of 
 man, the creative idea saves its most precious treasures 
 until it reaches the sphere of mind, i. e., lumianity. 
 
 III. Philosophy of Mind 
 
 1, The Suhjcctive Mind, or the Individual 
 
 Man is essentially mind, i. e., consciousness and freedom. 
 But on emerging from the hands of nature he is so only in 
 principle. Tlie mind, like nature, is subject to tlie law of 
 development. Consciousness and freedom do not exist at 
 
 33
 
 514 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the dawn of individual or generic life; they are the pro- 
 ducts of the evolution called history. 
 
 The individual in the state of nature is governed by 
 blind instinct, by brutal passions, and by that egoism 
 Avhich characterizes animal life. But as reason develops, 
 he recognizes others as his equals ; he becomes persuaded 
 that reason, freedom, spirituality — these terms are synon- 
 ymous — are not his exclusive property, but the common 
 possession of all ; he lienceforth ceases to claim them as his 
 exclusive privilege. The freedom of his fellow-creatures 
 becomes the law, the bridle, the limit, of his own freedom. 
 By giving way to this power, which is higher than the indi- 
 vidual, the subjective mind yields to — 
 
 2. The Oljective Mind, or SocieUj ^ 
 
 The blind forces manifested in the state of nature, e. g., 
 the instinct for the propagation of species and the instinct 
 for revenge, continue, but change their form. Henceforth 
 they become marriage and legal punishment: regulated, 
 disciplined instincts, ennobled by the law. 
 
 The objective mind first manifests itself in the form of 
 right, which is freedom conceded and guaranteed to all. 
 The individual who is recognized as free is a person. The 
 personality realizes and asserts itself through property. 
 Each legal person has, by virtue of his free activity, the 
 right to possess, and, consequently, also the right to trans- 
 fer his property. This transference takes place in the form 
 of a contract. The contract is the State in embryo. 
 
 ' Right appears in the fulness of its power, only when 
 individual caprice opposes the general or legal will (the 
 objective mind). 
 
 The conflict between the individual will and the legal 
 will gives rise to wrong (i. e., the un-right, Unrecht, the 
 
 1 Encyclopedia, §§ 482 ff.
 
 HEGEL 515 
 
 negation of right). But though denied b}^ the individual, 
 right remains right, the will of all. Temporaril}- defeated, 
 it triumphs in the form of penalty. Injustice, wrong- 
 doing, and crime thus merely serve to bring out the 
 power of justice, and to prove that reason and right are 
 superior to individual caprice. Punishment inflicted by 
 hxw is not a chastisement or correction, but a just retribu- 
 tion ; it is not a means, but an end. Right rights itself, 
 justice justifies itself, and the penitent is the involuntary 
 instrument of its gloi-ification. Capital punishment is no 
 more than just, and should be maintained. But is it not 
 absurd to attempt to correct an evil-doer by killing him ? 
 This objection, which is too common in our times, rests, as 
 Hegel holds, upon a false notion of legal punishment, the 
 object of which is not the reform of the individual but the 
 solemn affirmation of the violated principle.^ 
 
 There is truth in the objection that the juridical view is 
 one-sided and extreme. The jurist considers only the law 
 and its fulfilment, without regard to the inner motive of 
 the legal act. Nov/ the individual may, in all respects, 
 conform to the prescriptions of the law, he may be per- 
 fectly honorable in his outer life, and yet the general will 
 may not be his will and the true motive of his acts. 
 Hence, in spite of the semblance of conformity, we find a 
 hidden but quite real antagonism between the sul)jective 
 mind and the objective mind. 
 
 This antagonism must disappear, tliis impersonal will, 
 which is called right, justice, must become the personal 
 will of the individual, the inner law of his acts ; legality 
 must become morality; or, rather, to use a Hegelian 
 phrase, the objective mind must become a subject. 
 
 iMorality is the legality of the lieart, the law whicli is 
 identified with tlie will of the individual. In tlic moral 
 
 1 It was a3 a consistent Ilejjjciliaii tli;it the l;ili' M. Vdra, in his 
 capacity a.s a depute, (l(;f(.'n<l.-<l c:ii>it:il ininislinnint.
 
 516 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 sphere the code becomes moral law, conscience, the idea of 
 the good. Morality inquires not only into the act as such, 
 but into the spirit wliich dictates it. The legal sphere 
 regulates the material interests of life, without reaching 
 the conscience ; it fashions the will according to a certain 
 type ; material interest is its highest goal. Morality aims 
 liigher : it subordinates the useful to the good. 
 
 Morality is realized in a number of institutions, which 
 aim to unite the individual wills in the common service of 
 the idea. 
 
 The fundamental moral institution, the basis of all the 
 rest, is marriage, the family. On this institution rest 
 civil society and the Btate. Since the State cannot exist 
 without the family, it follows that marriage is a sacred 
 duty and should be primarily and chiefly based on the con- 
 sciousness of duty, or reason. It is a moral act, only in 
 case it is contracted with a view to society and the State. 
 Otherwise it is almost equivalent to concubinage. From 
 this stand])oint also we must consider the question of 
 divorce. Divorce would be justifiable, only in case matri- 
 mony were merely a matter of sentiment. Rational mo- 
 rality condemns it in principle, and cannot tolerate it in 
 practice except in exceptional cases provided for by the 
 law. The holiness of marriage and the honor of corpora- 
 tions constitute the indispensable basis of society and the 
 State, and the source of a people's prosperity ; prostitution 
 and individual egoism are an infallible cause of decadence. 
 
 Civil society, grounded on the family, is not yet the 
 State. Its aim is the protection of individual interests. 
 Hence the particularism which prevails in smaller coun- 
 tries where civil society and the State are identical, and 
 which disappears with the formation of great united 
 States. The State differs from civil society in that it no 
 longer solely pursues the good of the individuals, but aims 
 at the realization of the idea, for wliich it does not hesitate
 
 HEGEL 617 
 
 to sacrifice private interests. The egoism and particu- 
 larism wliicli prevail in the community are here counter- 
 balanced and corrected. The State is the kingdom of 
 the idea, of the universal, of the objective mind, the goal, 
 of wliich the family and civil society are merely the 
 means. 
 
 The republic is not, according to Hegel, the most perfect 
 form of government. Ultimately resting upon the confu- 
 sion of civil society and the State, it exaggerates the im- 
 portance and the role of the individual. The republics of 
 antiquity were superseded by dictatorsliips, because they 
 sacrificed the idea to the individual, the family, and the 
 caste. In the Greek Tyranny and Ri)man Ciesarism sover- 
 eis-n reason itself condemns the radical vice of the repub- 
 lican, democratic, and aristocratic forms of government. 
 
 The monarchy is the normal political form. In the free 
 and sovereign action of a unipersonal ruler the national 
 idea finds its adequate expression. The State is nothing 
 but an abstraction unless personified in a monarch, — the 
 depositary of its power, its political traditions, and the idea 
 which it is called upon to realize. The prince is the State 
 made man, impersonal reason become conscious reason, the 
 general will become personal will. That is, according to 
 our philosopher, the true meaning of the motto of Louis 
 XIV. : I'^tat ccst moi. 
 
 Though Hegel condemns political liberalism, he favors 
 national liberalism and llie principle of nationality. From 
 the Utilitarian standpoint of civil society, there may be, at 
 best, a union or confederation of hetorogcueous elements. 
 Switzerland is an example of such a federation. But State 
 means nationality, and nationality means nnity of language, 
 religion, customs, and ideas. The State; wliich incorporates 
 a people absolutely different from its own, and, against 
 their will, fastens upon tliem an odious yoke, commits a 
 crime against nature. In such a case, and onl\' then, is
 
 518 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 opposition, or even rebellion, legitiniiite. A political com- 
 munity is impossible without a communion of ideas. 
 
 Here, liowever, a distinction must be made. Annexation 
 is not a crime that justifies rebellion unless the annexed 
 nation represents an idea which is as great, fruitful, and 
 viable as the idea represented by the conquering people. 
 There are nationalities which represent no idea and have 
 lost their raison d'etre. Such nations are to be condemned. 
 The Bretons in France and the Basques in France and Spain 
 belong to this class. 
 
 In spite of appearances to the contrary, the most vigor- 
 ous people, the State representing the most viable idea, 
 always succeeds in gaining the mastery. History is merely 
 an incessant struggle between States of the past and those 
 of the future. The idea of the State is gradually realized 
 by means of such defeats and victories. The historical 
 States are the temporary forms in which it appears, and 
 which it discards when time has worn them out, only to 
 assume new forms. Since the absolute is not restricted to 
 a particular existence, but is always found in the whole, we 
 cannot say that the ideal State is anywhere. The ideal 
 State is everywhere and nowhere : everywhere, because it 
 tends to realize itself in historical States ; nowhere, for as 
 an ideal, it is a problem to be solved by the future. His- 
 tory is the progressive solution of the political problem. 
 Every nation adds its stone to the building of the ideal 
 State, but each people also has its original sin, which brings 
 it into opposition with the idea, and sooner or later com- 
 passes its ruin. Each State represents the ideal from a 
 certain side ; none realizes it in its fulness ; none, therefore, 
 is immortal. Like the logical notions, which are absorbed 
 by a more powerful rival, and by virtue of the same law, 
 the nations, one after another, succumb to each other, and 
 transmit to their successors, in a more developed and en- 
 larged form, the political idea of which they have been the
 
 HEGEL 519 
 
 depositaries, the civilization of which they have been the 
 guardians. 
 
 This passing of ' the civilization of one people to another 
 constitutes the dialectics of history : an expression which is 
 not taken figuratively by Hegel. Logic or dialectics is the 
 evolution of reason in inchvidual thought ; the dialectics of 
 history is the development of the same reason on the world's 
 stage. One and the same principle is unfolded in different 
 environments, but according to an identical law. In pure 
 logic, abstract ideas succeeded each other on the stage 
 of thought and then disappeared, only to be followed by 
 more comprehensive and concrete ideas. In the logic of 
 nature, objectified ideas, material organisms, succeeded each 
 other and formed an ascending scale, thereby realizing, 
 with increasing perfection, the ideal type of physical crea- 
 tions. In the logic of history, ideas, again, become incar- 
 nated in nature, and invisibly weave the web of human 
 destinies. Whether these ideas unfold themselves beneath 
 the spiritual gaze of the philosopher, or whether they suc- 
 ceed each other in the form of bodies, or become incorpo- 
 rated in historical nations, tlrey are always the same, and 
 their order of succession is invariable. Reason is the 
 innermost substance of history, which is a logic in action. 
 In the eyes of the superficial historian, empires rise, flour- 
 ish, and decline, peoples struggle, and armies destroy each 
 other. But Ijchind th(;se nations and their armies are the 
 principles they represent ; beliind the rampaits and the 
 batteries ideas antagonize each otliei'. 
 
 War, like the death penalty, has chinigcd in asj)ecl. AVith 
 the adv'ance of militiuy ait and civilization its ciiU'lties 
 are lessened. But in a tcnipcnMl and inodilicd lorni, it 
 will continue as (tm^ of the imhspensahle means of political 
 progress. It is tlic lioast of oiii' times that we see it in 
 its true light, and no longer ]-egard it as the j)assing satis- 
 faction of the caprice of a sovereign, l)ut as an inevitable
 
 520 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 crisis in the development of the idea. True, legitimate, 
 necessary war is the war for ideas, war in the service of 
 reason, as the nineteenth century has learned to wage it. 
 Not that antiquity and the Middle Ages did not battle for 
 ideas ; but they were not yet conscious of the moral essence 
 of war. The ideas formerly collided with each other, like 
 blind forces ; the modern world is conscious of the cause 
 for which it is shedding its blood. Formerly the conflict 
 was one between passions ; now it is a battle for principle. 
 
 The victorious State is truer, nearer to the ideal State, 
 better, in a word, than the vanquished State. The very fact 
 that it has triumi)hed proves this : its triumph is the con- 
 demnation of the principle represented by the vanquished j 
 it is the judgment of God. Thus interpreted, history 
 resembles a series of divine reprisals directed against 
 everything that is finite, one-sided, and incomplete ; it is 
 an eternal dies irae, which nothing earthly can escape. 
 
 There is, in every epoch, a people in whom mind is more 
 completely incarnated than in the rest, and who march in 
 the front rank of universal civilization. That is, the God 
 of history has successively " chosen " the Egyptians, the 
 Assyrians, the Greeks, the Romans, and the French. The 
 national minds are grouped around the infinite Mind of 
 which history is the temple, and, one after another, become 
 its privileged organs. So the archangels surround the tlirone 
 of the Eternal. 
 
 The three phases of every evolution : being, expansion, 
 and concentration, recur in the three great epochs of history. 
 
 In the Oriental monarchies, the State personified in the 
 sovereign dominates the individual to the extent of anni- 
 hilating him. What does the Ocean care for the waves 
 playing on its surface ? 
 
 In the States of Greece, Asiatic sluggishness is followed 
 by political life and its fruitful conflicts ; the absolute mon- 
 archy is superseded by the republic. Here individuals are
 
 HEGEL 521 
 
 no longer mere modes with wliieli the substance of the State 
 has nothing to do, but integral parts of a whole, which exists 
 only through them ; as such they have a feeling of their 
 importance, and appreciate that the State needs their co- 
 operation. The classical republics last as long as the indi- 
 vidual elements and the State remain in equilibrium. They 
 are imperilled as soon as the demagogue's regime substitutes 
 for the national interest the selfish interests of individual 
 ambition. The Cesarean reaction forces the rebellious in- 
 dividual into obedience ; the habitable world is conquered ; 
 the most diverse nations are tlirown into one and the same 
 mould and reduced to an inert and powerless mass. 
 
 The equilibrium between the State and the individual is 
 restored in the Cluistian and parliamentary monarchy, as 
 the best example of which Hegel regards the English con- 
 stitution.^ 
 
 3. The Absolute Mind 2 
 
 However perfect the moral edifice called the State may 
 be, it is not the highest goal whither the evolution of the 
 Idea tends ; and political life, though full of passion and 
 intelligence, is not the climax of spiritual activity. Free- 
 dom is the essence of mind ; independence is its life. 
 Now, in spite of the contrary assertions of political liberal- 
 ism, even the most perfect State cannot realize this. 
 Whether it be a repu])lic, a constitutional or an absolute 
 monarchy, aii aristocracy or a democracy, it does not cease 
 to be a State, an external, armed, armored power, a kind of 
 prison in which what is essentially infinite is deprived of 
 its vital element. Mind cannot unconditionaUij subject itself 
 to anythin;! but mind. Not iinding in ])olilical life the 
 
 1 We ought to afM tliat wliat iiiflueiicfd II('t,'('rs jutlujiiioiit was not 
 the parliamentarism, Imt thi; conservatism of the Enj^lish constitution. 
 2 Enctjrlopedia, §§ O;'):] ff. See also Hegel's lectures on ^Esthetics, 
 the Philoso/ilit/ of Reli(/ion, and the Illstory nf P/iilosophy.
 
 522 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 supreme satisfaction which it seeks, it rises beyond it into 
 tlie free reahus of art^ religion, and science. 
 
 Does that mean that the mind, in order to realize ite 
 destiny, shall destroy the ladder by which it rose ; shall it 
 overturn the State, society, and the family ? Far from it. 
 Indeed, the creations of art, the religious institutions, the 
 works of science, are possible only under the auspices of a 
 strong State and under the protection of a firmly established 
 government. The artist, the Christian, and the philosopher 
 can no more do witliout society and the State than the 
 vegetable and animal can exist without the mineral king- 
 dom. So, too, the Idea, whether it operates in the form of 
 nature or of mind, never destroys its creations ; it develoj^s 
 and perfects them, and even though their preservation may 
 seem useless to us, it keeps the first-fruits of its labors in- 
 tact. Nature, in which everything appears to be in a state 
 of endless destruction and revolution, is eminently preser- 
 vative : the mineral kingdom contiimes to exist alongside 
 of the vegetable kingdom ; the vegetable kingdom, along- 
 side of the animal kingdom ; and in the animal kingdom 
 the most elementary and most unfinished types exist along- 
 side of the most perfect types : nature preserves them and 
 uses them as a kind of pedestal for her masterpiece. More- 
 over, the higher creations are possible only because those 
 which precede them endure. The mineral kingdom gives 
 life to the vegetable kingdom; the animal lives on the 
 vegetable or on the animal inferior to it; finally, plants 
 and animals nourish man, who cannot live without them. 
 The same is true of the creations of the mind : from the 
 depths of the soul arises the demand for liberty ; from the 
 fact that liberty is claimed by all, grow right, property, 
 and the penal law ; upon the solid foundation of right the 
 moral institutions, the family, society, and the State, are 
 established. All these developments are closely connected 
 vrith each other, and each exists only through the instru-
 
 HEGEL 523 
 
 mentality of the others. Take away one of the foundation- 
 stones, and the entire universal edifice crumbles to pieces. 
 The higher stories of tliis structure presuppose the perfect 
 stability of the lower ones. 
 
 Man was, first of all, an individual (subjective mind) 
 shut up in his native egoism ; then, emerging from him- 
 self and recognizing himself in other men, he formed a 
 community, society, and State (objective mind); finally, 
 returning into himself, he finds at the bottom of his being 
 the ideal of art or the beautiful, the religious ideal or God, 
 the philosophical ideal or truth, and in the realization of 
 this tlu-eefold ideal, the supreme independence to which 
 he aspires : he becomes ahsolute mind. 
 
 In art, the mind enjoys by anticipation the victory over 
 the external world which science reserves for it. The 
 thought of the artist and his object, the human soul and 
 the infinite, become identified ; heaven descends into the 
 soul, and the soul is carried heavenward. Genius is the 
 breath of God, afflatus divinus. 
 
 Religion reacts against the pantheism anticipated by art, 
 and shows us in God the transcendent Being, whom the 
 genius of man cannot reach. By proclaiming the dualism 
 of the infinite and the finite, religion is, in appearance, a 
 relapse, a kind of return of the mind to the external yoke ; 
 in reality, however, it is a necessary crisis of the mind, 
 wliich develops its forces and l>rings it nearer to God, in 
 struggling beneath the yoke. That it is an evolution may 
 be seen from the fact that Christianity itself, its most per- 
 fect form, proclaims the unity of tlie linite and the iniinite 
 in Jesus Christ, and thus anticipates the highest develoi)- 
 ment of the mind : pinlosophi/. 
 
 Pliilosophy realizes wliat art and tlic Cliristiaii dogma 
 foreshadow. Art and religious faith spring from fccHiig 
 and imagination; science is the triumph of pure reason, 
 the apotheosis of mind. By understanding tlie world, tlio
 
 524 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 mind frees itself from it. Nature and its forces, the State 
 and its institutions, wliieli but lately seemed like a pitiless 
 Fate, change in appearance so soon as the mind recognizes 
 in nature the works of reason, i. e., its own works, and 
 regards social and political institutions as the reflection of 
 the moral authority dwelling in itself. If nature, law, 
 right. State, represent different forms of mind (objective 
 mind), all these barriers fall away ; if everything that is 
 real is found to be rational, reason has no other law except 
 itself. On this summit of universal life, the ego and the 
 world are forever united. 
 
 In conclusion, we shall summarize Hegel's philosophy 
 of art, religion, and philosophy, especially the first, which 
 has not been surpassed. 
 
 1, Art is the anticipated triumph of mind over matter; 
 it is the idea penetrating matter and transforming it after 
 its image. But the matter which the idea employs to incor- 
 porate itself is a more or less docile or rebellious servant ; 
 hence the different forms of art, the fine arts. 
 
 In architecture^ the elementary stage of art, idea and 
 form are quite distinct ; the idea cannot as yet wholly con- 
 quer the matter which it employs, and the matter remains 
 rebellious. Architecture is merely a symbolic art, in which 
 the form suggests the idea without directly expressing it. 
 The pyramid, the pagoda, the Greek temple, the Christian 
 cathedral, are admirable symbols, but the distance between 
 these edifices and the idea which they symbolize is as great 
 " as that between heaven and earth." Moreover, the ma- 
 terials of architecture are the most material in the physical 
 world. This art is to sculpture, painting, and music, what 
 minerals are to vegetables and animals. Resembling the 
 astronomical universe in its gigantic proportions and over- 
 whelming majesty, it expresses solemnity, austerity, mute 
 grandeur, the unalterable repose of force, the immovable 
 statu quo of the infinite ; but it is incapable of expressing
 
 HEGEL 525 
 
 the thousand shades of life, the infinitely varied beauties 
 of reality. 
 
 The dualism of form and idea, which characterizes archi- 
 tecture, tends to disappear in sculpture. The art of the 
 sculptor has this in common ^yith architecture : like its 
 elder sister, it employs gross matter, marble, brass ; but it 
 is much more capable of transforming and spiritualizing 
 them. In the purely symbolical work of the architect, 
 there are details and accessories which in no wise assist in 
 expressing the idea ; in the statue, nothing is indifferent, 
 everything is in the service of the idea of which it is the 
 direct expression, the immediate revelation. But the statue 
 is incapable of representing the soul itself as revealed in 
 the eye. This advance is made in painting. 
 
 The matter employed by painting is somewhat less ma- 
 terial than that of sculpture and architecture ; it is no 
 longer the three-dimensional Ijod}-, but the plane surface. 
 Depth is reduced to a mere appearance, produced b}^ per- 
 spective, spiritualized. However, painting can express 
 only a moment of life, a moment which it is obliged to 
 stereotype and consequently to materialize; the idea is still 
 bound to matter and extension. Owing to this common 
 cliaracteristic, architecture, sculpture, and painting, together 
 form objective art. Hence, they are inseparable ; they are 
 combined in a thousand different ways. Tliese first three 
 external, visible, material forms of art are superseded by 
 subjective^ invisible, immaterial art, or music. 
 
 ]\rnsic is a spiritualistic art, the art which can, with 
 tlirilling truth, reproduce the innermost essence of the 
 human soul, the infinite shades of feeling. The direct 
 opposite of architecture, sculpture, and painting, it, too, is 
 an incomplete art. Tliere can be notliing extreme in \)vy- 
 feet art; it is tlie synthesis of all contraries, the harmoni- 
 ous union of the world of nnisic and the woild of objective 
 art. This ail of arts is poetri/.
 
 526 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Poetry is art endowed with speech, the art which can 
 say everything, express everything, and create everything 
 anew, the universal art. Sculpture, like architecture, 
 employs matter in its grossest form, but it spiritualizes 
 marble ; it gives life and intelligence to this block of which 
 architecture can merely make a more or less eloquent 
 symbol. So, too, poetry and music both employ sound, 
 but in music this is vague and indefinite like the feeling 
 which expresses it. In the service of the poet it becomes 
 articulate and definite sound, a word, language. Music 
 makes a symbol of sound, — a piece of music, like an 
 edifice, is susceptible of the most diverse interpretations, 
 — poetry wholly subordinates it to the idea. Architec- 
 ture contents itself with suggesting the Divinity who 
 reigns beyond the stars ; sculpture brings him down upon 
 the earth. Music localizes the infinite in feeling ; poetry 
 assigns to it the boundless realm which of right belongs to 
 it : nature and history. It is all-powerful and inexhaust- 
 ible, like the God who inspires the poet. 
 
 Sculpture and poetry, on the one hand, architecture and 
 music, on the other, are to art what pantheism and theism 
 are to religious thought. Architecture and music show 
 the traces of the theistic idea ; sculpture and poetry, which 
 make the ideal descend into the real, are pantheistic arts. 
 Hence it comes that architecture and music are the faith- 
 ful followers of religion; while sculpture, painting, and 
 poetry, wliich are also enrolled in the service of religious 
 faith, do not serve it so submissively. Sculpture is pagan ; 
 and it was owing to its pantheism that images of God were 
 condemned by Mosaism and rigorous Protestantism. Po- 
 etry, on the other hand, celebrated its great triumphs outside 
 of the domain of religion. Shakespeare, Molifere, Goethe, 
 and Byron are no more Christians than Sophocles, Pindar, 
 and Euripides. Modern religious poetry seems to be 
 afflicted with barrenness. It is because great poetry is so
 
 HEGEL 527 
 
 intimate a union of divine and human elements that the 
 dogma of divine transcendency is actually cancelled by it. 
 
 The epitome and quintessence of all the arts, poetry 
 constructs, sculptfli'es, designs, paints, sings; it is archi- 
 tecture, sculpture, painting, and music, and these diverse 
 forms which it can successively assume are again found in 
 what we call its genres (^GaUungsunterschiede'). 
 
 Corresponding to objective art, represented by architec- 
 ture, sculpture, and painting, we have ejnc poetry, wliich 
 is to poetry what tlie pyramid is to art. The epic rep- 
 resents the childhood of poetry. It is garrulous, ornate, 
 full of the marvellous, like the imagination of the child, 
 indetinitely long, like the first years of life. 
 
 Zgj^c poetry corresponds to music. The epic, like the 
 objective arts, loves to paint nature and its wonders, his- 
 tory and its glories ; lyric poetry falls back upon the invis- 
 ible world, no less vast than the other, called the luunan 
 soul. It is, therefore, an extreme and incomplete class. 
 
 The perfect genre, which reconciles the two worlds, the 
 poetry of poetry, is dramatic poetry. The drama, which 
 flourishes only among the most civilized peoples, repro- 
 duces history, nature, and the human soul with its pas- 
 sions, emotions, and conflicts. 
 
 Art has not only its different forms, it has also, like 
 each of its forms, its historical development in three 
 epochs. 
 
 Oriental art is essentially symbolical. It delights in alle- 
 gory and paraljles. Unlike the Greek masterpieces, which 
 are self-explanatory, its products must be interpreted, and 
 may be interpreted differently. It is still powerless to 
 overcome matter, and the feeling of this weakness reveals 
 itself in all its works. Despising form, finish, and detail, 
 it is fond of caricature, exaggerations, and the colossal, 
 and, in all its creations, l)ctrays its predilection for the 
 inlinile ami iiiconun('nsural)le.
 
 528 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 In Greek art, symbolism is superseded by direct expres- 
 sion; the whole idea descends into the form. But even 
 the sublime and almost superhuman perfection of this art is 
 extreme and imperfect. The idea so completely penetrates 
 the matter as to be, ultimately, indistinguishable from it; 
 it is sacrificed to outward form and physical beauty. 
 
 This defect, which is no less signal than the formless 
 spiritualism of Asiatic art, is corrected in Christian art. 
 Christianity recalls art from the visible world, in which it 
 had lost itself, to the ideal sphere, its true home. Under 
 the influence of the Gospel, the idea of the beautiful is 
 spiritualized, the adoration of physical beauty makes way 
 for the worship of moral beauty, purity, and holiness ; the 
 worship of the Virgin follows the cultus of Venus. Chris- 
 tian or romantic art does not exclude physical beauty, but 
 subordinates it to transcendent beauty. 
 
 Now, the material form is inadequate to the moral ideal. 
 The most finished masterpieces cannot satisfy the Christian 
 artist. The Virgin of whom he dreams, the eternal dwell- 
 ing-places which his spiritual eye perceives, the heavenly 
 music whose harmonies his soul enjoys, the divine life 
 which he desires to portray, his ideal,, in a word, is still 
 more beautiful; so beautiful, indeed, that neither burin, 
 nor brush, nor bow, nor pen, nor anything material can 
 express it. Hence Christian art, despairing of its powers, 
 finally relapses into that contempt for form and that exces- 
 sive spiritualism which is both the characteristic feature 
 and the failing of romanticism. 
 
 2. Though man may, in his inspired moments, regard 
 himself as identical with the God who inspires him, he very 
 soon discovers his insignificance when it comes to giving 
 his ideal a material form. Thus religion springs from art. 
 Primitive art is essentially religious ; natural religion, es- 
 sentially artistic. Idolatry is the connecting link between 
 religion and art.
 
 HEGEL 529 
 
 Religion becomes conscious of itself, and emancipates 
 itself from art by abolishing idols. This advance is made 
 in ]\Iosaism. The Bible condemns idolatry because it recog- 
 nizes man's inability to express the infinite by means of 
 matter; it forbids stone images because the idea has no 
 adequate form except itself. But though it prohibits us 
 hom picturi'mj the invisible, it does not hinder us from pic- 
 turing it to ourselves ; it forbids the outward image, but it 
 does not forbid the imagination itself and the ideas with 
 which it peoples the mind. Far from it. The fact is, 
 religion is essentially representation {Vbrstelhong). Art 
 represents the infinite ; religion represents it to itself as a 
 personal and extra-mundane being. Anthropomorphism 
 is its characteristic feature. In religious thought, the 
 finite and the infinite, earth and heaven, which are united 
 in the feeling of the beautiful, are again disjoined. Man 
 is down below, God is up above, so high and so far that he 
 needs the ministry of angels in order to communicate with 
 the world. Religion is dualistic, but there is nothing final 
 in its dualism. It separates heaven and earth, only to 
 unite them ; it separates God and humanity, only to recon- 
 cile them. 
 
 The essential elements of the religious idea : infinite 
 God, mortal man, and their relation, successively prevail 
 in the history of religion. 
 
 In the religions of the Orient the idea of infinity pre- 
 dominates. Their salient feature is pantheism ; an ultra- 
 religious pantheism, however, which is synonymous with 
 acosmism and may 1)0 summed up in these words : God is 
 everything, man is nothing. Brahmanism is the most com- 
 plete expression of Asiatic pantheism. Mosaic monotheism, 
 though otherwise diifering from Indian religions, shows 
 the same cliaracteristics. The God of the Orient beai-s the 
 same relation to man as the princes of the Orient ])ear to 
 their subjcfts. He is tlie Creatoi-, and men are his crca- 
 
 34
 
 530 MODERN PHlLOSOrHY 
 
 tures ; hence he can dispose of them, he can make them 
 live and die, exalt them and debase them, just as he pleases. 
 Man is to God what the earthen vase, is to the potter ; no 
 more, no less. Human liberty and spontaneity are out of 
 the question. Not only the act, but also the will comes 
 from God ; he enlightens and hardens the hearts ; he pre- 
 destines everything, be it for good or for evil.* Since om- 
 nipotence belongs to God, there is nothing left for man but 
 total impotence and mournful resignation. The inhnite 
 as such cannot tolerate an independent existence by its 
 side ; Siva, Moloch, and Saturn devour their own children, 
 and where this does not happen, the latter, knowing that 
 their existence is displeasing to God, destroy themselves, 
 or suffer a slow martyrdom, or absolutely relinquish their 
 personality. 
 
 Greece is as fond of tinitude and form, nature and the 
 things of the earth, as Asia is religious. Its religion is as 
 serene as its skies, as racUant and transparent as the atmos- 
 phere surrounding it ; the clouds which elsewhere hide God 
 from the eye of man, vanish at the first effort of the mind ; 
 the divine and the human are blended and united ; religion 
 is identified with art, and art with the worship of humanity. 
 The riddle of the Sphinx is the riddle of Hellenic polythe- 
 ism. Man is the solution of the riddle. The God whom 
 the Greek adores under the form of Zeus, Apollo, Athene, 
 Apln-odite, is man and his power, intelligence, and beauty. 
 His divinities are relative beings. Nay, this mythological 
 heaven, radiant with eternal youth, is in reality subject to 
 Fate, the mysterious power which rules over gods and 
 mortals alike. This Destiny, the supreme power of which 
 the poets eagerly strive to exalt, is like a conscience which 
 antiquity cannot silence ; it is the infinite of the Oriental 
 religions, which, like a Shakespearean ghost, haunts the 
 sensuous environment of the polj^theistic cultus. 
 
 The Orient professes the religion of the infinite and
 
 HEGEL 531 
 
 abstract ; Greece worships at the shrine of the finite. 
 These two extremes of religion are reconciled in Christian- 
 it}', in which the spii'it of the Orient and the Gi'eek genius 
 are united. For the Hindoo, God is everything, man noth- 
 ing ; for the Greek, God is nothing or very little, man, 
 everything ; for the Christian, the important thing is 
 neither God considered in the abstract, the Father, nor 
 man in the abstract, but the concrete unity of the divine 
 and the human as realized in Jesus Christ. The God 
 whom Jesus reveals to us is the same as the God who 
 reveals him ; he is neither an infinite being like the God of 
 Oriental religions, nor a finite one, like the pagan divinities, 
 but a Being who is both God and man, the God-]\Ian. The 
 distance between the Christian heaven and the earth, be- 
 tween the God of the Gospel and humanity, is not insuper- 
 able ; nay, tlii^ God comes down from his throne, enters the 
 sphere of finity, lives our life, suffers and dies like us, then 
 rises from the dead and enters into his glory. Christianity 
 is to the preceding religions what poetry is to the fine arts ; 
 it embraces them and at the same time purifies and com- 
 pletes tliem. It is the synthesis of all religions, the absolute 
 religion. 
 
 3. Tlie Christian dogma is truth in the form of repre- 
 sentation (^Vorstellung'). The three stages in the evolution 
 of immanent reason, idea, nature, and mind, ])ecome three 
 persons. Tlu; union of the infinite and finite in human 
 consciousness, i, e., a process embracing the whole of uni- 
 versal liistory, is regarded as an evoit that luippened once 
 for all times in Palestine, eighteen lumdred years ago. In 
 tin's fidin the <l(>gma is an inadiMiuate expression of tlu; 
 truth wliich it contains. Moreover, it is imposed as an 
 ext(.'rnal authority, whereas the miiul, whicli is free in 
 essence, can only be realized as free. In order to reaeli llie 
 climax of its evolution, it has simply to divest the religious 
 doctiine of its irprcseiitative form, ami lo give it tlie rational
 
 532 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 form. This advance is made by philosophy. The Gospel 
 and true philosophy have the same content. But the con- 
 tainer is not the same ; with the Cluistian it is the imarj- 
 ination, with the pliilosopher, reason. Philosophical truth 
 is religious truth in the form of a concept ; it is compre- 
 hended truth. The absolute idea becomes absolute mind, 
 absolute self-consciousness. 
 
 The history of philosophy, like all history, is a regu- 
 lar development, reproducing the entire series of catego- 
 ries : Eleatism is the philosophy of being; Heraclitus is 
 the philosopher of becoming; Democritus and atomism 
 correspond to the idea of individuality (Filrsichsein), and so 
 on.i It attains to its fullest expansion in absolute idealism, 
 i. e., in the system which we have just outlined. 
 
 What truth is there in tliis final claim ? How much of 
 it is illusory ? 
 
 Hegelianism is, without doubt, the most comprehensive 
 and complete synthesis ever attempted by the human 
 mind, — a veritable encyclopaedia, animated by a central 
 idea, and supported by a method that has implicit confi- 
 dence in itself. Hence, if philosophy is what our opening 
 paragraph defined it to be, we must give Hegel the credit 
 of having come nearer to the ideal of science than any of 
 his predecessors. Furthermore, no one, after Kant, gave 
 to modern thought so powerful an impetus, — no one more 
 completely dominated and fascinated it. Jurisprudence, 
 politics, ethics, theology, and sesthetics, — all have suffered 
 his influence. Nor is that all. By demonstrating that be- 
 ing is becoming, logical development, history, that history is 
 not only a science among others, but the science of sciences, 
 he ably seconded, if he did not create, the historical move- 
 ment of the nineteenth century, and impressed upon it the 
 stamp of impartial objectivity wliich characterizes it, and 
 
 1 History of Philosophy, I. 43.
 
 HEGEL 533 
 
 which was foreign to the eighteenth centiiiy. David 
 Stkauss and his Lcben Jesu, Bauk, the celebrated liistorian 
 of primitive Cliiistianity and the founder of the historical 
 school of Tiibingen, Michelet, Rosenkranz, Erdjiann, 
 Peantl, Zeller, Kuxo Fischer, the brilliant interpreters 
 of ancient and modern thought, come from Hegel.^ The 
 conception that philosopliies and religions are different 
 stages of one and the same development; the hypothesis 
 that an unconscious reason creates and transforms lan- 
 guages; the ideas of, and even the expressions, genesis^ 
 evolution^ 2>rocess, the logic of history, and many others, 
 which have become common-places in the political, relig- 
 ious, and scientific press, are products of the Hegelian 
 movement. 
 
 1 For the literature, see § 3. — Outside of Germany and the Xorth- 
 ern countries, where it was taught by Mourad and Lyng at Christi- 
 ania, and by Borelius at Lund (Sweden), the Hegelian philosophy was 
 especially popular in Italy, where Vera, professor at Naples, acted as 
 its chief interpreter. In France it influenced the sociological theories 
 of Proudhon and Pierre Leroux,the first phase {maniere) of V. Cousin 
 (§ 71), and, above all, the idealism of Vacherot {La me'lapJnjsique et la 
 science, Paris, 1852 ; 2d ed., 1802 ; La science el la conscience, Paris, 1872, 
 etc.). Vacherot, who in some respects resembles the eclectics (§ 71), 
 wholly differs from them in that he absolutely denies the personality 
 of God. According to Vacherot, God is the ideal to which things 
 aspire, and exists only in so far as he is thought, while the world 
 is the real infinity. "Eliminate man," he adds, "and God no longer 
 exists ; no humanity, no thought, no ideal, no God, since God exists 
 only for the thinking being." La mc'laphysique el la science, 2d ed., 
 vol. m.. Conclusion. [Representatives of the Hegelian movement 
 in England: J. II. Stirling (see p. 490, note .3), T. II. Green {Works, 
 3 vols., London and New York, 1885-88; Prolegomena to Ethics, 
 1883), F. II. Bradley (Ethical Studies, 1870; Principles of Logic, 
 1883; Appearance ami liealitij, 1891), J. t'aird (Introduction to the 
 Philosophy of Religion, 1880), E. Caird (see p. 131, n.2), li. nosun.piet 
 (Logic, 2 vols., 1888), W. Wallace (see p. 197, n. 3), etc. ; in America, 
 W. T. Harris, Editor of the Journal of Speculative Philosophy, fouiKh-d 
 1807. — Tk.]
 
 534 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 What discredited Hegelianism and pliilosopliy itself -~ 
 for there was a time when the two terms were emph^yed 
 synonymously — was the material errors which necessarily 
 followed from its exclusively a-prioristic method ; was the 
 authoritative tone which it assumed towards the leaders of 
 modern science, Copernicus, Newton, and Lavoisier; was 
 its presumptuous attempt to withdraw the hypotheses of 
 metaphysics from the supreme jurisdiction of facts. If 
 the philosophical mind (die spekidative Vernunft) per- 
 ceives truth by an immediate and instinctive intuition, 
 whereas experience discovers it step by step only, then its 
 oracles, precisely because they are immediate, i. e., unproved, 
 and wholly unaccounted for, need the counter-signature of 
 experience in order to have the force of laws in the scien- 
 tific sphere. The immediate and spontaneous, as Hegel 
 himself declares, is never definitive, but the starting-point 
 of an evolution. Hence, a priori speculation, as he con- 
 ceives and pursues it, cannot be the final form of science, 
 but should, at the very least, be verified by experience, 
 and, in case of need, be corrected by criticism. Moreover, 
 the defects of the Hegelian method and the errors of fact 
 following from it are due to the rationalistic prejudice 
 of which the system is the classical expression. According 
 to Hegel, the absolute is idea, thought, reason, and nolhing 
 hut that; whence he concludes that the idea, or, as tlie 
 School says, the form^ is also the content, the matter^ of 
 things. When he assumes that the ideal tvorld of science 
 can be deduced from reason alone, it is because, according 
 to him, the real ivorld, the world of leings, is derived from 
 reason and reason alone. Now the absolute, or at least — 
 since the absolute is unknowable as such — the primary 
 phenomenon (das UriJlidnomoi) is not thought, intelli- 
 gence, reason, but will.^ Thought is a mode of the cre- 
 
 1 See §§ 68 and 71.
 
 HERBART 535 
 
 ative activity of things ; it is not their iirinciple} It 
 follows that the Iinowlcd(jc of tilings does not come from 
 pure thought, but from thought supported and governed 
 by experience. 
 
 § 67. Herbart^ 
 
 Kant, the master, protested against the absolute idealism 
 of his " false disciples," and opposed to it his ideo-realism, 
 which distinguishes between the form and the matter of 
 our knowledge, considering the form alone as given a 
 priori^ and the content, the matter, as solely and necessarily 
 furnished by the outer and inner sense. Reason produces 
 a priori the categories of quality, quantity, causality, and 
 measure, which are indispensable to the knowledge of na- 
 ture ; but it cannot produce a priori the ideas of iron, light, 
 pleasure, and pain, w^hich experience alone supplies. Ex- 
 perience has its a priori conditions, which pure sensation- 
 alism erroneously denies ; but experience alone gives us 
 complete and concrete ideas properly so-called, while the 
 categories, which reason produces a priori^ are not, strictly 
 speaking, ideas, but mere frames for our ideas : which is an 
 entirely different thing. Schelling himself concedes that, 
 in the last analysis, everything comes from experience, al- 
 though experience presupposes a priori conditions without 
 
 1 According to tlie Christian dogma itself, which Hogcl pi'ofesses 
 to translate into philosophical language, the \6yos is created and is not 
 the " Father." 
 
 ^ [Briefer philosophical writings, etc., ]>uljlished l)y (i. Ifarton- 
 stein, :i vols., Leipsie, 1812; complete works, eil. l>y G- Ilartenstein, 
 12 vols., Leipsie, 1850 ft". ; complete works, ed. by K. Ktdirbach, Lan- 
 gensalza, 18S2 ff. ; pedagogical works, ed. l)y O. AVillmann, 2 vols., 
 2d ed., Leipsie, 1877. Cf. G. Ilartenstein, Die Probleme und Grnnd- 
 lehren der (dlrjeineinen MelapJnjslL; Li'ipsic, 18:)(j; .1. Kaftan, Solleii 
 und Sein (a critique of Ilcrhart), Leipsie, 1872; .1. Capesius, Die 
 Metaph'jsik Ilerbart's, Leipsie, 1878; Th. Uihot, Fai psr/rholoffie nlle- 
 mande cuntemporaine, I'aris, 1879; Kngl. tr. by IJaldwin, 1880. — Tii.J
 
 536 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 which it would be impossible. That is, in truth, the real 
 teaching of Kant. 
 
 A number of thinkers, and particularly Johann Fried- 
 rich Herbart (1776-1841), professor at Konigsberg and 
 Gbttingen, followed the master. They occupied a position 
 between Hegel, whose star sank in 1830, and Locke, whose 
 empiricism, which had been temporarily checked by the 
 idealism of the Restoratioii, only to reappear, more power- 
 ful than ever, as positivism, after the setting of the Hegel- 
 ian sun. The most important philosophical writings of 
 Herbart are : Allgemeine Metaphysik ^ and Fsychologie als 
 Wissenschaft, neu gegrlindet auf Erfahruny, Metaphysihy 
 und Matliematik?' What especially characterizes them is 
 their systematic opposition to the principles, method, and 
 conclusions of Hegel. Things are not merely our tlioughts, 
 as idealism holds ; they exist really and independently of the 
 reason which thinks them (realism in the modern sense). 
 Hence, the problem of philosophy is not to construct the 
 universe, but to accept it as it exists, and to explain its 
 mechanism, so far as that can be done. Observation and 
 experience form the indispensable foundation of specula- 
 tion. A philosophy not based on the positive data of science 
 is hollow. It has merely the import of a poem, and we 
 cannot concede to it any scientific value. Herbart restores 
 to philosophy the boundaries which Kantian criticism had 
 declared impassable. 
 
 Philosophy is defined as the elaboration of the concepts 
 which underlie the different sciences.^ Such general 
 ideas * are not free from contradictions, and should there- 
 fore be revised. This work is the real business of the 
 metaphysician. 
 
 ^ Complete Works (Hartenstein), vols. III. and IV. 
 2 Works, vols. V. and VI. Cf. AVillm, op. cit., vol. IV. [His Lehr- 
 buck der Psychologie has been translated by M. K. Smith, 1891.] 
 
 * Lehrbuch zur Einleitung in die Philosophie. vol. I., ch. 2. 
 
 * For example, the ideas of cause, space, and the ego.
 
 HERBART 637 
 
 The contradictions which philosophy is asked to resolve 
 have been ascertained by the Eleatics, the Sceptics, and 
 Hegel. But Zeno of Elea, instead of resolving them, con- 
 sidered them insoluble, and hence inferred that nothing real 
 corresponds to them. The Sceptics saw in this a reason for 
 repudiating metaphysics. Hegel, at last, does not deny 
 that our ideas are contradictory, but by a tour de force un- 
 heard of in the liistory of philosophy, accepts the contradic- 
 tion without reserve, and declares that it forms the very 
 essence of thought and being. That is, he pretends to dis- 
 pense with the principle of contradiction. But we cannot, 
 with impunity, violate the law which has governed human 
 thought from the very beginning, and we shall have to 
 reckon with it as long as reason is reason. The Hegelian 
 paradox is not a solution. Scepticism has its raison d'etre ; 
 it is even necessary, in a certain measure ; it forms the 
 starting-point, in the history of thought, of the great philoso- 
 phies (Socrates, Descartes, Kant). But to remain sceptical 
 is to give proof of the incompetence of speculation. Doubt 
 m its most absolute form, scepticism extended even to the 
 existence of things, is refuted by one of the most simple 
 reflections. Though it may be doubted that things exist, 
 it is beyond douht that they a2)pear to exist. This appear- 
 ance (phenomenon) is absolutely certain, and the most obsti- 
 nate sceptic cannot doubt it. The phenomenon exists. 
 If nothing existed, nothing could appear to exist. But, 
 though we assume what is evident, namely, the existence 
 of things, it is not so certain that tliC}' are what we think 
 they are, that they exist as they are thouglit (yEncsidenuis, 
 Sextus), that they are iii time and space, connected by the 
 tie of causality (Hume, Kant). This doubt, founded, as it 
 is, on the contradictions and obscurities which even the 
 most superficial reflection can discover in our ideas, is 
 perfectly legitimate, provided it provokes philosophical 
 thought
 
 538 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The business of philosophy, as we have said, consists 
 essentially in revising and correcting our general ideas, in 
 freeing them from the contradictions which they contain.^ 
 The ideas of extension, duration, matter^ movement, inher- 
 ence^ causality, and egoity, particularly, require elabora- 
 tion. The idea of extension, duration, matter, is the idea 
 of multiple unity (hence the supposed antinomies of rational 
 cosmology). To change, to become, and to move means to 
 be and not to be. By the notion of inherence we assign 
 manifold properties to the same substance ; i. e., we affirm 
 that one thing is several things (colored, odorous, sapid, 
 liquid), that unity is not one. The notion of cause, like- 
 wise, is contradictory from every point of view. We both 
 affirm that the thing modified by an external cause is the 
 same as before, and that it is not the same. When we speak 
 of the self-determination of the subject (Leibniz), we be- 
 come involved in the no less flagrant contradiction that a 
 being is both active and passive, i. e., that it is not one but 
 two. Finally, the notion of the ego with its diverse facul- 
 ties is as contradictory as the idea of inherence, of which it 
 is an application. In all these notions there is a confusion 
 of being and non-being, the one and the many, affirmation 
 and negation, i. e., of two things which exclude each other, 
 and which thought should clearly separate, Hegel to the 
 contrary notwithstanding. 
 
 From the confusion of two contraries arises the idea of 
 limited and relative being. This conception Herbart un- 
 conditionally rejects. Being, according to him, admits of 
 neither negation nor limitation. It is absolute position, 
 Avholly excluding diversity of properties, divisibility, limi- 
 tation, and negation. It cannot be conceived either as 
 quantity or continuous magnitude, or as being in space 
 and time (Kant). It is what Plato and Parmenides called 
 the One, what Spinoza named Substance ; but it differs 
 1 Einleitung in die Philosophie, pp. 194-202; Metaphysik, p. 8.
 
 HEEBART 539 
 
 from the Eleatic principle in that it exists independently 
 of thought, and from Spinoza's Substance in that it is 
 not one. There, are according to Herbart, a plurality 
 of reed beings or realities (Beale)^ and, since each reality is 
 absolute position, a plurality of absolute beings; which 
 seems contradictory, but is not so because extended beings 
 alone limit each other, and the realities are supposed to be 
 inextended. Tlie realities of Herbart, therefore, closely 
 resemble Leibniz's monads ; but they differ from them in 
 an essential respect : the " monads " are complex unities 
 endowed witli many properties, having their inner states, 
 their moditications, and their immanent development ; the 
 realities of Herbart are absolutely simple ; they have only 
 one single property ; they suffer no internal change, they 
 are immutable. 
 
 Real being (das Eecde), then, is not what the senses show 
 us ; for the objects perceived by the senses have many 
 properties. What follows ? Why, the sensible object 
 (iron, silver, oxygen) contains as many realities as it has 
 distinct properties. 
 
 Thus the difhculty involved in the notion of inherence 
 is resolved. This idea is contradictory only when applied 
 to the real being (Kant's thing-iii-itself) ; it is not so when 
 applied to the plienomonal being, or the thing presented 
 by the senses. The latter is always an intcyndion of real 
 beings in greater or smaller numbers, never a unitary real 
 being. 
 
 The ideas of causality and cliange are explained in the 
 same way. The relation of causality cannot obtain either 
 between two real beings (external causality), or between 
 a real being and its supposed cliaracteristics (immanent 
 causality) ; for each real being exists ahsolutcly (by itself), 
 while immanent causality (for example, iron considered 
 as the cause nf lis properties) divides the one into many, 
 i. e., contradicts the notion of real being. Hence, causality
 
 540 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 cannot signify anything but reality and, at the utmost, self- 
 preservation (^Selhsterhaltung^ .^ 
 
 Change cannot be assumed except under certain reser- 
 vations. Change as affecting the real beings is out of the 
 question in metaphysics. Not the substances, but only 
 their mutual relations, are incessantly modified. Geometry 
 shows that a thing can change relatively to another thing 
 without changing itself : the tangent of a circle ABC 
 becomes the radius of another circle D E F. The same is 
 true of music : the same note is true or false, according to 
 its relation to other notes. In pharmacy we observe the 
 same fact : one and the same plant is both a poison and a 
 remedy. 
 
 But though the substances themselves do not change, 
 their mutual relations change. The real beings, though 
 absolute, are related to each other. In order to understand 
 this, we must imagine them to exist in a space which is 
 not phenomenal space, but wliich Herbart calls intelligible 
 space. In this space two monads can occupy different 
 points, and then there is no relation between them ; but 
 they can also, by means of a movement of whose laws we 
 are ignorant, occupy the same point. Nothing can hinder 
 us from assuming this, since we are not here dealing with 
 material atoms. Two or more substances which occupy 
 the same point interpenetrate (as though penetration did 
 not presuppose extension). Substances which thus inter- 
 penetrate may be of the same quality ; they may differ in 
 quality, or, finally, they may be opposite in quality (differ- 
 ence between Herbart and the Greek atomists). If they 
 are identical in quality, their interpenetration produces no 
 
 1 Here Herbart contradicts himself; for self-preservation is a re- 
 flective act, which divides the monad in two, — namely, into a subject 
 which preserves, and an object which is preserved. Now, does Her- 
 bart believe that he can in no case contradict himself, because that 
 would be a reflective act, a division in the monad, an impossibility?
 
 HERBART 541 
 
 change in their respective modes of being ; but if the sub- 
 stance B, which comes to occupy the place of the sub- 
 stance A, is of a different or opposite quality, there will be 
 a conflict between the two monads, since two contraries 
 cannot coexist in one and the same point. Each will tend 
 to preserve itself; it will resist its rival, and affirm its 
 indestructible individuality. 
 
 Thus we may explain phenomena in general, and the 
 phenomenon of thought in particular. The ego ceases 
 to be a contradictory idea when we give up regarding it 
 as a unity composed of different faculties, — a multiple 
 unity, i. e., a miity which is not a unity. The ego has not 
 many functions, but one single function: it tends to pre- 
 serve itself in its indestructible originality. That is its 
 only function, but it varies under the influence of the 
 surroimdings ; its only faculty manifests itself in a number 
 of apparently different faculties, according as the soul is 
 solicited by similar, different, or contrary monads. From 
 such a conflict thought arises. Thought is the act by 
 which the subject affirms itself, preserves itself, in opposi- 
 tion to the object which solicits it. It is infinitely modi- 
 fied, according to the nature of the object. Hence, the 
 infinite variety of om- perceptions. The psychological con- 
 sciousness is the sum of relations which the real being 
 called ego sustains to other real beings. 
 
 Hence, inner perception is not essential to the soul ; it 
 is a mere phenomenon, produced by the coming together of 
 the ego and other realities, — a resultant of the combined 
 actions of the subject and the ol)ject, a relation. If the 
 soul were isolated from all other beings, it would not 
 tliink, feel, or will. Feeling is a thought arrested by other 
 more energ(;tic thoughts ; but this, in turn, may overcome 
 the latter, and become thought wlu-n tlie ego is solicited 
 by other o])jects. Similarly, will is notliing l»ut tliought 
 (Spinoza) ; moral freedom is the permanent domination o/
 
 542 MODEEN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 reflected thouglit over feeling, i. e., a matter of equilib- 
 rium. Psychical life is a mechanism, the laws of which 
 are the same as those of statics and dynamics. Psychology, 
 properly understood, is a true mechanism, an application 
 of arithmetic, an exact science.' 
 
 The scientific bent of Herbart's philosophy, and particu- 
 larly his application of mathematics to the science of the 
 soul, — a bold and original attemj^t, — could not but make 
 him the centre of a large school.^ Hegel's attitude towards 
 
 1 Works, VII., pp. 129 if. 
 
 2 Outside of the lierbartian school proper (Drobisch, Hartenstein, 
 Lazarus, Steiuthal, Striimpell, Thilo, Waitz, Ziinmerniaun, etc.), the 
 exact philosophy especially influenced the psychology of Friedrich 
 Eduard Beneke (1798-1854, extraordinary professor at Berlin) and the 
 metaphysics of Hermann Lotze (1817-1881, professor at Gcittingen and 
 latterly at Berlin), author of MedizinhchePsycholociie, 18."')2, 1896 ; Micro- 
 co.wnis, 3 vols., 18.56-64; [Engl. tr. by Hamilton and Jones, Edin. and 
 N.Y., 1884]; Logik, 1874 ; [Engl. tr. by B. Bosanquet, Oxford, 1884]; 
 Metaphysik; [Engl. tr. by B. Bosanquet, 2 vols., Oxford, 1884. Lotze's 
 Outlines, by G. T. Ladd, Boston, 1885 ff. On Lotze see E. v. Hartmann, 
 Lotze's Philosophie, Berlin, 1888 ; O. Caspari, H. Lotze, etc., 2d ed., Bres- 
 lau, 1894 ; H. Jones, The PhUosophy of Lotze, New York, 1895. — Tr.]. 
 Beneke, whose originality is shown in his theory of the four fundamental 
 processes of soul-life, rejects the psychological atomism of the master 
 as well as his application of mathematics to the science of the mind. 
 Lotze, on the other hand, emphatically protests against being called a 
 Herbartian, and advances, particularly in his later publications, a sys- 
 tem of concrete spiritualism which is dominated by the moral idea 
 (Kant) and the monistic conception (Spinoza). He is the author of 
 the theory of local signs in psychology. In short, psychology and peda- 
 gogy are most indebted to the philosophy of Herbart. Consult, con- 
 cerning the influence of this philosophy on psychology, Ribot, La psy- 
 chologic allemande contemporaine, Paris, 1879, especially chapter II. : 
 Uecole de Herbart et la psychologic ethnographiqne. [Other disciples of 
 Herbart are : F. Exner, G. A. Lindner (Lehrbuch der empmschen Psy- 
 chologic, 6th ed., Vienna, 1886, Engl, tr. by C. De Garmo, Boston, 
 1889) ; J. Nahlowsky {Das Gcfuhlsleben, 2d ed., Leipsic, 1884) ; 
 W. Volkmann (Lehrbuch der Psychologic, 4th ed., Cothen, 1894). 
 Organs of the school : Zeilschrifl fur exacte Philosophie, founded 1861,
 
 HERBART 543 
 
 the pioneers of modem science prejudiced serious thinkers 
 against idealism and drove them into the camp of exact 
 metaphysics. They entered this school for want of a better ; 
 for the philosophy of Herbart, which undertook to free 
 thought from all contradictions, AA-as itself full of the most 
 glaring contrasts. AVhile Herbart's ontology declares real 
 being to be simple and inextended, his psychology is based 
 on the opposite h\i^othesis. His theodicy, which is per- 
 fectly conservative, and his teleology, which is wholly spir- 
 itualistic, seriously clash with his paradoxical theory of the 
 multiple absolute, wliich logically culminates in polytheism, 
 and his mechanism, which is closel}' akin to the material- 
 istic theories. Moreover, his metaphysics contains the 
 strangest contradictions. Reed being excludes the plurality 
 of properties, change, and movement, i. e., in brief, life, 
 and, ultimately, reality. Real reality., life, activity, is ex- 
 cluded from the sphere of beings, and Herbart's Rcahn., 
 instead of being realities, are lifeless abstractions, scholastic 
 entities, and nothing more. Furthermore, his monadology 
 shares all the disadvantages of the Leibnizian theory, which 
 serves as his model. Like the " pulverized universe " with 
 which he presents us, his pliilosoph}' possesses neither the 
 unity nor the homogeneity which we have a right to demand 
 from a doctrine claiming to be a metapliysic. It is, in every 
 respect, the antipode of Hegelian philosophy, and, provoked 
 by the logicism of its powerful rival, affects to ignore the 
 monistic tendency. 
 
 The latter reasserts itself in Schopeuhaiu-r, whose })lii- 
 losophy, a happy mean between speculation and positive 
 knowledge, exercises a preponderating iiinuciuc on uKxU'ru 
 (ierman thought. 
 
 now ('(litt'd by O. Fliifjel ; Zrilfchrifl fdr ]'SlJ,rrpxi/rhi)lofjIc itnit Sprnch 
 wissenschaft, founded IS.jO, edited by l^azurus and Steinthal. — -I'rO
 
 544 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 § 68. Schopenhauer! 
 
 Arthue Schopenhauer, the son of a banker in 
 Danzic, and Johanna Schopenhauer, an authoress formerly 
 well-known in Germany, was born 1788, He studied at 
 Cxottingen (1809-1811) and Berlin (1811-1813), taught phi- 
 losophy at the latter institution as a Privatdocent from 1820 
 to 1831, then abandoned the university career, and spent 
 the remainder of his life at Frankfort on the Main, where 
 he died in 1860. The writings which established his repu- 
 tation are : (1) his inaugural dissertation, Ueber die vier- 
 fache Wurzel des Satzes vom zureichenden Grunde ; ^ (2) Die 
 Wdt als With und Vorstellung ; ^ (3) Ucher den Willen in 
 dcr Natur ; ^ (4) Die leiden GruiulproUeme der EtliiliJ' He 
 heard the lectures of Schulze ^ at Gcittingen and of Fichte 
 
 1 [Complete Works, ed. by J. Frauenstiidt, 6 vols., Leipsic, 1873-74 ; 
 2d ed., 1877 ; ed. by E. Grisebach, Leipsic, 1890 ff. ; ed. by R. Sleiner, 
 13 vols., Leipsic, 1894. Cf. J. Frauenstiidt, Briefe uber die Sch-'sche 
 Philosophies Leipsic, 1854 ; R. Seydel, Schopenhauer's System, Leipsic, 
 1857 ; Foucher de Careil, Hec/el et Schopenhauer, Paris, 1862 ; R. Haym, 
 A. Schopenhauer, Berlin, 1864; Th. Ribot, La philosophie de Schopen- 
 hauer, Paris, 1874 ; H. Zimmern, Schopenhauer, His Life and Philosophy, 
 London, 1876 ; W. Gwinner, Sch.'s Leben, Leipsic, 1878 ; W. Wallace, 
 Schopenhauer (^Great Writers Series), London, 1890 ; J. Sully, Pessimistn, 
 2d ed., London, 1891 ; K. Fischer, Arthur Schopenhauer, Heidelberg, 
 1893. — Tr.] 
 
 2 1813 ; 2d ed., 1847 ; 3d ed., 1864. [Transl. (Fourfold Boot of the 
 Principle of Sufficient Reason) by K. Hillebrand in Bohn's Library, 2d 
 ed., 1891 (the same volume contains the tr. of On the Will in Nature). 
 — Tr.] 
 
 8 Leipsic, 1819 ; 2d ed. in 2 vols., 1844 ; 3d ed., 1859. IThe World 
 as Will and as Idea, tr. by R. B. Haldane and J. Kemp, 3 vols., Lon- 
 don and Boston, 1884-86.] 
 
 4 Frankfort, 1836 ; 2d ed., 18.54 ; 3d ed., 1867. [On the Will in Na- 
 ture, Bohn's Library, see above.] 
 
 6 \_The Tivo Fundamental Problems of Ethics.'] Frankfort, 1841; 
 2d ed., 1860. [Schopenhauer's Essays, selected and translated by Bax, 
 Bohn's Library. See also T. B. Saunders's translations. — Tk.] 
 
 6 See § 63,
 
 SCHOPENHAUER 545 
 
 in Berlin, and devoted himself, particularly, to the study of 
 Kant, Plato, and Buddhism, so far as tills was known in 
 Europe. To Kant, Fichte, and Schelling he owes his car- 
 dinal doctrine, which conceives the will as the absolute, to 
 Plato, his theory of Ideas or stages of the voluntary phe- 
 nomenon, to Buddhism his pessimistic bent and his doctrine 
 of the negation of the will. 
 
 His chief work, Die Welt ah Wille unci Vorstellung^ opens 
 with a glowing tribute to criticism. In asserting, with 
 Kant, that the world is my idea {die Welt ist vieine Vorstel- 
 lung), he does not deny the reality of the world j he distin- 
 guishes between the world as it is in itself, apart from my 
 senses and my intelligence, and the world as I see and 
 conceive it, i. e., the phenomenal world. The phenomenal 
 world is my perception, my idea, the product of my intel- 
 lectual organization. Indeed, if I were differently organ- 
 ized, the world would be different, or, at least, would seem 
 different ; it would consist (for me) of different phenomena. 
 As a reality, it exists independently of me, but as an object 
 of sensibility and the understanding, or, in a word, as a 
 phenomenon, it depends on the s^ihject which perceives it : 
 it is a wholly relative thing, created by the ego and the a 
 priori conditions of thought.^ 
 
 On the other hand, consciousness emphatically declares 
 that behind this phenomenal world, the product of our 
 organization, there is a higher reality, which does not de- 
 pend on us, an absolute, a thing-in-4tsclf. ICant acknowl- 
 edges the existence of the thing-in-itself ; but wliathe gives 
 with one hand he takes back with tlie other. He denies to 
 the understanding the right to apply to this thing any of 
 its categories, maintains that reason is incapal)le of knowing 
 it, and, consequently, regards the plicnomenal world, i. e., 
 in the last analysis, the thinking subject, as alone know- 
 al)lc; for the itlicndinriioii ism// thought, nothing but ?/i^ 
 
 1 Die W<U 'ii-< Wille und Vorstelluiuj, vol. I., pj). H il. 
 35
 
 546 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 tliouo-lit. It is true, the subject canuot get beyond itself, 
 identify itself with what it is not, assimilate things as they 
 are in themselves. But it is equally true that the belief in 
 the existence of the world irresistibly forces itself upon us ; 
 it is, consequently, true that the perception which we have 
 of ourselves gives us, at the very least, an image of what 
 the things outside of us are. It would, undoubtedly, be 
 impossible for me to know anything of the essence of ohjects 
 if I were merely a subject. But I am both the subject and 
 the object of my thought, as I am the object of the thought 
 of others. I am conscious of being an object among other 
 objects. Thus the chasm made by criticism between the 
 thinking subject and the things themselves is partly 
 bridged. I have the right to convert the proposition : I (the 
 subject) am an object, and to say ; most probably — Schop- 
 enhauer, the pupil of Schulze the sceptic, does not lay claim 
 to absolute knowledge ^ — the object (all objects, the entire 
 objective world) is what I am ; its essence is analogous to 
 mine. 
 
 This ancdofjy of all beings, which dogmatism afifirmed in 
 Leibniz, we must assume even from the standpoint of criti- 
 cism. We have the right, even as Kantians, to judge things 
 according to what we find in ourselves. Only, we must 
 make sure of what in us is truly essential, original, and 
 fundamental. According to Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, 
 Hegel, and all the rationalists, this essential thing is thought., 
 intellect. Hence, inasmuch as all existing things are anal- 
 ogous, Leibniz concludes that all beings perceive and think 
 in a certain degree ; but experience does not confirm this 
 hypothesis. Hegel, likewise, regards thought as the uni- 
 versal typical phenomenon. According to Schopenhauer, 
 the essential and fundamental thing in us is the Will, 
 whereas thought is but a derived or secondary phenomenon, 
 an accident of will. Now, we have every reason to believe, 
 
 1 Die Welt ah Wille unci Vovslellung, vol. IL, chap. L., pp. 736 ff.
 
 SCHOPENHAUER 547 
 
 and experience strikingly j)roves, that what is essential and 
 fundamental to us is also the essence, the ultimate principle 
 of the nature of all other beings. We are essentially will, 
 and the entire universe, considered in its essence, is a will 
 that ohjectifies itself, gives itself a body or a real existence. 
 
 In the first place, my body is the product of will; it 
 is my will become phenomenon, my desire-to-be made vis- 
 ible.^ And the objects which I perceive through it are 
 like my body: all are phenomena, manifestations, pro- 
 ducts of a will analogous to mine. The will, the principle 
 of everything that exists, is sometimes pure, i. e., not con- 
 nected with an intellect. In this case it is identical with 
 irritability, the m3'sterious force which governs the circula- 
 tion of the blood, the digestion, and the secretions. Some- 
 times it is connected with the intellectual phenomenon ; it 
 is conscious, and in this case it is what we commonly call 
 will and free-wilL Will, in this special sense, is irritability 
 acting knowingly, and according to motives, as, for example, 
 when I raise my arm. Sometimes, again, our acts are both 
 the result of irritability and motived will ; the pupil is con- 
 tracted Avhen it is excited by too much light ; this is the 
 effect of irritability, a rejlex act ; but it is also voluntarily 
 contracted when we will to observe a very small object. 
 The power of conscious will is immense. We may cite the 
 cases of negroes who committed suicide by arresting their 
 respiration. But, whether it be conscious or unconscious, 
 irritability or free activity, and however diverse and in- 
 numerable its manifestations may be, will as sueli is one. 
 
 AVhether it is conscious or not, the will acts in us witliout 
 interruption. The ])u(\\ and tlie intellect -grow tired and 
 need rest; the will alone is indefatigable; it acts even 
 during sleep and causes dreams. It acts in tlie Ijody not 
 only during its formation, ])ut exists prior to the body. 
 
 1 Die Well nls WUle uml VurslellHng, vol. I., § IS, 1 IS ff. ; H., cliiip. 
 XX.,-J77ff.
 
 548 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The will forms and organizes it according to its needs ; the 
 will, in the embryo, transforms a part of the cerebral sub- 
 stance into a retina in order to receive optical phenomena. 
 The mucous membrane of the thoracic canal is transformed 
 into lungs, because the body wills to assimilate the oxygen 
 of the atmosphere. The capillary system produces genital 
 organs, because the individual in process of formation wills 
 to propagate the species. 
 
 Consider the organization of animals, and you will always 
 find that it conforms to their mode of life. It seems, in- 
 deed, at fust sight, as though their mode of life, their habits, 
 dejjended on their organization ; in the order of time the 
 organization precedes the mode of life. It seems that the 
 bird flies because it has wings, that the ox butts because it 
 has horns. But intelligent observation shows the contrary. 
 We observe that many animals manifest the will to use 
 organs which they do not yet possess. The goat and the 
 ox butt before they have horns ; the wild-boar attacks with 
 that part of his snout where tusks are going to be ; he does 
 not, as might be done, fight with his teeth. Hence, the 
 will is tlie principle of organization, the centre of creative 
 evolution. Wild beasts that desire to tear their prey to 
 pieces, to live on plunder and on blood, have teeth and huge 
 claws, strong muscles, piercing eyes (eagles, condors) ; such, 
 on the other hand, as, by instinct, do not desire to fight, 
 but to seek safety in flight, develop, instead of organs of 
 defence, a fine sense of hearing, slender and agile legs 
 (stags, roe-bucks, gazelles). The bird of the moor, which 
 desires to feed on reptiles, has particularly well-developed 
 legs, neck, and beak (stork, pelican) ; owls desire to see in 
 the dark, and so have enormous j^upils, soft, silken down, 
 in order not to awaken the animal desired for prey. The 
 porcupine, the hedgehog, and the tortoise cover themselves 
 with a shell, because they do not desire to flee. The cuttle- 
 fish conceals itself in a brownish liquid ; the ai, in order to
 
 SCHOPENHAUER 649 
 
 hide from its enemies, assumes the appearance of a tree- 
 trunk covered with. moss. As a rule, especially in the 
 desert, the animal assumes the color wliich least distin- 
 guishes it froju the surroundings in which it lives, because 
 it desires to escape the pursuit of the hunter. In all these 
 cases, the will, or, more correctly, the will-to-be, the will-to- 
 exist, is the principal agent.^ 
 
 Where none of these means suffices, the will provides 
 itself with a still more efficient safeguard, the most efficient 
 of all, intelli(jence^ which, in man, supersedes all the others. 
 The intellect is all the more powerful a weapon because it 
 can conceal the will under false appearances, while, in the 
 case of animals, the intent is alwaj'S manifest and alwaj-s of 
 a definite character. 
 
 The will plays the same part, although this is not so ap- 
 parent, in the vegetable kingdom. Here, too, e\'ery thing 
 is strivi/ig, desire, unconscious a/ppetitlon. The tree-top, de- 
 siring light, invariably tends to assume a vertical position 
 unless it finds it elsewhere. The root, which desires moist- 
 ure, often seeks for it in the most roundaljout manner. The 
 seed planted in the ground will invariably push its stem 
 upwards, its roots downwards, in whatever position it may 
 be placed. The toadstool performs real feats of strength, 
 wonderful acts of will, breaking through walls, splitting 
 stones, in order to reach the light. Potatoes growing in a 
 cellar infallibly turn their sprouts to tlie light. Climbing 
 plants seek supports and make visil>le efforts to reach and 
 catch hold of them. Hence, here, as in tlie animal king- 
 dom, everything is reduced to will, to that elementary will 
 wliieh we call iiritability. There is no essential difference 
 between irrital)ility and the faculty of In-iiig (k'tcniiiiicd by 
 motives; for the motive regularly produces an iniliition 
 whicli sets the will in motion. Tlic [tlant turns to the sun 
 
 ^ See the critiim*' of tliis tlu'ory in § 'i!*- 
 
 2 Die W>:lt ah WlHt nml Vursldhuuj, vol. I., § 27, Y\k 17!) ff.
 
 550 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 by irritation ; the animal likewise ; only, the animal is en- 
 dowed with intelligence, and knows what effect the sun 
 produces on the body. 
 
 Considering its manifestations, it is hardest to recognize 
 the will in the two extremes of creation, i. e., on the one 
 hand, in man, on the other, in the mineral kingdom. Every 
 animal, every vegetable, has its fixed character ; indeed, we 
 can tell in advance what to expect of it. When we are 
 dealing with a dog, or a cat, or a fox, we know at once that 
 the doo- will be faithful, the cat treacherous, and the fox 
 cunnino-. We can predict with certainty that a cactus ivill 
 desire dry surroundings, and a myosotis moist soil. We 
 know at what time a particular plant will bud, when it will 
 bloom, and bear fruit. But in man and in the minerals, at 
 the summit and at the base of creation, the character is 
 full of mysteries. We cannot discover it by direct observa- 
 tion, and we can know it only after prolonged experience. 
 This is a difficult procedure, especially in the case of man, 
 who can conceal his character, and disguise the particular 
 tendency of his will. Nevertheless, we find in man clearly 
 marked tendencies, inclinations, and propensities, while the 
 mineral kingdom has its constant tendencies also. The 
 magnetic needle invariably points to the north. Bodies 
 always fall in a vertical line, and we call this the law of 
 weio-ht or gravitation. Liquid matter obeys the same law 
 in following the descending x)lane. Certain substances in- 
 variably expand under the influence of heat, and contract 
 under the influence of cold ; certain ones form crystals when 
 acted upon by other substances with which they come in 
 contact. Particularly in chemistry do we observe striking 
 examples of such constant wills, sympathies, and antipa- 
 thies.i Moreover, this truth that the will lies at the basis 
 
 1 The objection is made that this is equivalent to anthropomorphiz- 
 ing nature ; but if nature produced man, did it not create him in its 
 own image ?
 
 SCHOPENHAUER 651 
 
 of all things is instinctively proclaimed in a nnniber of 
 characteristic expressions. Thus we say: the tire will not 
 burn ; the water wants to get out ; le fer est avide d' ox y gene. 
 These are not mere figures of speech, but must be taken 
 literally.i 
 
 Hence, that which the Eleatics call the tV koI irav ; Spi- 
 noza, substance ; Schelling, the absolute ; Schopenhauer 
 calls will. But he denies, with pantheism, that this prin- 
 ciple is a person. He regards will as the unconscious force 
 which produces specific beings, individuals living in space 
 and in time. It is that which, not being, strives to be, be- 
 comes life, objectifies itself in individual existence ; it is, in 
 a word, the will-to-be. In itself, will is neither subject to 
 the laws of space and time, nor capable of being known. 
 But its manifestations occur in time and in space, which 
 together form the i^rinciinum individuationis. At least, the 
 intellect conceives its manifestations as alongside of and 
 following each other. 
 
 The phenomena of universal will succeed each other in 
 time according to uniform laws, and according to the im- 
 mutable t;ypes which Plato calls Ideas. These ideas or con- 
 stant forms in which the will objectifies itself in the same 
 species, form an ascending scale, from the most elementary 
 being to man. They are independent of time and of space, 
 eternal and immutable, like the will itself, while individuals 
 hccome and never are. Tlie inferior Ideas, or elementary 
 stages of the manifestation of will are: weight, impenetra- 
 bility, solidity, fluidity, elasticity, electricity, magnetism, 
 chemism. The higher stages appi-ai- in tlie organic world, 
 and the series is completed in man. liiasniuch as the dif- 
 ferent stages of tlie voluntary phenomenon contend with 
 each other for the matter, space, and time wliich they need, 
 the struf/rjlc fur existence arises wliidi characterizes nature. 
 Each organism represents (Ik- idea of wliicli it is tlie copy, 
 
 » Ueher d'u Willni in der Xalur, :J(1 lmI.. \>\k ilC iT. (LiiHj'iisllL).
 
 552 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 minus the amount of force expended to overcome the in- 
 ferior ideas which oppose it. The more the organism suc- 
 ceeds in overcoming the natural forces constituting the 
 lower stages of life, the more perfect an expression is it of 
 the idea which it represents, and the nearer it comes to 
 what, in the species, is called beauty. ^ 
 
 The will is a perpetual desire to be, the never-ending 
 source of the phenomenal world. As long as there is a 
 will, there will be a universe. Individuals come and go, 
 but the will, the desire which produces them, is eternal, 
 like the specific t3rpes according to which it produces them. 
 Birth and death do not apply to the will, but only to its 
 manifestations. Our innermost essence, the will, never 
 dies. The religion of the Hindoos, Greeks, and Romans 
 evidently aims to give expression to this truth in the joyful 
 themes, feasts, and dances depicted on its sarcophagi. 
 
 Death is not a subject for grief. On the contrary ; it is, 
 like birth, the consequence of the universal order. But 
 though the fact that we have in ourselves a part of the uni- 
 versal will, a principle that cannot die, is consoling, because 
 it guarantees us a certain measure of immortality, it is a 
 source of sorrow to those who desire to free themselves from 
 the pains of existence by committing suicide. Since death 
 merely destroys the phenomenon, that is, the body and never 
 the soul, or the universal will, suicide can deliver me from 
 my phenomenal existence only and not from myself. 
 
 The will is the endless source of all life, and hence also 
 the origin of all evil. The world which it produces, instead 
 of being the " best possible world," is the worst of all. In 
 spite of what the poets may say, animals are constantly 
 preying upon each other, and we have simply to balance 
 the sufferings of the victims against the pleasures of the 
 victors, to be convinced that the amount of pain exceeds 
 the pleasure. History, in turn, is merely an interminable 
 1 Welt ah Wille unci Vorstellung, I., §§ 30 ff., pp. 199 ff.
 
 SCHOPENHAUER 553 
 
 series of murders, robberies, intrigues, and lies, and if j^ou 
 know one page of it, you know them all. The alleged hu- 
 man vu-tues, the love of labor, perseverance, temperance, 
 frugalit)-, are nothing but refined egoism, splendida vitia. 
 There is no virtue worthy of the name except j^ity or sym- 
 pathy, the principle of Buddhistic morality, and, Spinoza to 
 the contrary, the basis of all true morality.^ All other vir- 
 tues are grounded on the will-to-live-and-to-enjoy. And 
 what is the use of this mighty effort, this merciless, never- 
 ending struggle? Life is its goal, and life is necessary, 
 irremediable suffering. The more life is perfected, i. e., 
 advanced in the scale of intelligence, the unhappier it be- 
 comes. Man who is capable of conceiving ideas suffers 
 infinitely more than the ignorant brute. Laugliter and tears 
 are peculiarly human phenomena. 
 
 Since being is synonymous with suffering, positive hap- 
 piness is an eternal Utopia. Only negative \\'ell-being, 
 consisting in the cessation of suffering, is possible, and tliis 
 can be realized only when the will, enlightened as to the 
 inanity of life and its pleasures by the intelligence, turns 
 against itself, negates itself, renounces being, life, and en- 
 joyment. This doctrine of salvation by the nerjation of the 
 vnll is the common essence of the Gosj)el and of Buddhism.^ 
 Both Christianity and Buddha hold that man enters the 
 Avorld as a sinner ; he is the product of two blind passions ; 
 for marriage, in tlie oi)inion of St. Paul, is merely a conces- 
 sion to those whose will is not strong enough to coniiucr 
 itself. The propagation of the species is an evil, — the 
 feeling of shame proves it, — and it would be better uot to 
 be born than to deseeud into iliis woiM df liisi aiul pain : 
 such is, according to Seliopenliauei', the meaning of the 
 dogma of original sin and of the miraeulous conception of 
 the Savior. 'J'o recognize through the agency of the intel- 
 lect that everything in our willing is vanity, is what Chiis- 
 
 * Uehtr (Jus Fundament dcr Mural, § 18. 
 
 2 Die We.U ah W'dle und Vomteltunf/, L, 310 IT. (§§ 53 iT.).
 
 554 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 lect that everything in onr willing is vanity, is what Chris- 
 tianity calls the effect of grace, whence spring the love of 
 justice, charity towards neighbors, renunciation of self and 
 our desires, finally, the absolute negation of will (regenera- 
 tion, conversion, sanctification). Jesus is the type of man 
 who understands his vocation. He sacrifices his body, 
 which is the alSrmation of his will ; he stifles the wiU-to-he 
 in himself in order that the Holy Ghost, i. e., the spirit of 
 renunciation and charity, may take its place in the world. 
 Furthermore, it must be acknowledged that Catholicism, 
 with its predilection for celibacy, its vows, its fasts, its alms, 
 and other means of fettering the will, has remained more 
 faithful to the spirit of the Gospel than Protestantism. 
 Christianity is true in such of its teiichings as are derived 
 from the Aryan Orient, especially in its doctrine of the self- 
 sacrifice of the will and universal charity ; but the Jewish 
 elements ^ which it contains are erroneous, particularly its 
 dogma of a personal God, as the creator of the world. 
 
 To snm up, Schopenhauer concludes,^ my philosophy 
 does not presume to explain the ultimate causes of the 
 world; nay, it confines itself to the facts of inner and 
 outer experience, which are accessible to everybody, and 
 points out the true and intimate connection existing be- 
 tween these facts, without, however, concerning itself with 
 that Avhich may transcend them. It refrains from drawing 
 any conclusions concerning what lies beyond experience ; 
 it merely explains the data of sensibility and self-consci- 
 ousness, and strives to understand only the immanent 
 
 1 Schopenhauer's antipathy to the Jews and Judaism is only 
 equalled by his hatred of Hegel and " the professors of philosophy." 
 His attitude is consistent with his Buddhistic principle of " renuncia- 
 tion," which constitutes the essence of morality. Israel seems to be 
 more determined than any other race ??o/ io renounce existence ; it is, 
 therefore, in the eyes of our philosopher, the most "immoral' of 
 peoples. 
 
 2 Vie Welt als Wille und Vorstelluntj, II., chap. L.
 
 SCHOPENHAUER 665 
 
 essence of the world. It is, in this respect, purely Kantian. 
 Consequently, it leaves many questions unanswered, par- 
 ticularly the question. Why are the facts of experience 
 just what the}' are and not different ? All such questions, 
 liowever, are transcendent, i. e., they cannot be explained 
 by the forms and functions of our intellect. The intellect 
 bears the same relation to them as our sensibility bears to 
 such qualities of bodies as we have not the sense-organs to 
 perceive. The mind is fatally dependent on the law of 
 causality, and understands only what is subject to tliis law. 
 The dogmatic metaphysicians and transcendentalists who 
 keep on asking ivhy and whence^ forget that why means hy 
 ivhat cause, that there are no causes and effects outside of 
 time-succession, and that, therefore, the v:]iy has no mean- 
 ing in the sphere to which the forms of time and space can- 
 not be applied, i. e., in the sphere of the transcendent, 
 where there is no befoi-e or after. Everywhere the intel- 
 lect strikes against insoluble problems, as against the walls 
 of a prison-house. The essence of things not only transcends 
 our knowledge, but, most probably, knowledge in general ; 
 it is both unintelligible and unintelligent, ^ and intelli- 
 gence is but a form, an addition, an accident. With the 
 Eleatics, Scotus Erigena, Bruno, Spinoza, and Schelling, 
 I accept the %v koI ttuv, the doctrine of the unitary essence 
 of all beings ; only I am careful not to add : irdp ^eo'f, and 
 so I differ essentially from the pantlieists. Tiie de6<; of tlie 
 pantheists is an ./;, an uukiiown (luantity by means of 
 which tliey aim to explain tiie known ; my " w ill," on 
 the other liand, is a fact of ex[)eiicncc ; I proceed, as all 
 true science must proceed, from llic known to the nn- 
 known. My method is empirical, analytic, inductive; that 
 of the pantheistic metai)liysicians, synthetie and deductive. 
 Pantheism is synonymous with optimism ; in my .system, 
 
 1 'I'lii-ri- is no (lilTcn-iicu here bfitwemi Sclic)|Mii|i;iui'r .iml niiitc- 
 riulbm.
 
 556 MODERN THILOSOPHY 
 
 however, the evil in the world is frankly conceded and its 
 significance fully recognized. In this respect, my system 
 differs from most ancient and modern philosophies, espe- 
 cially from Spinoza, Leibniz, and Hegel. It is to Spinoza 
 what the New Testament is to the Old. 
 
 Schopenhauer, therefore, offers us an empirical meta- 
 physics^ and Ijecause he stands on the ground of experience 
 he is the first to call that which " constitutes the basis of 
 being and its substance " ^ by its right name : Will. That 
 is what constitutes his originality, his merit, the secret of 
 his success in contemporary Germany, which has been sur- 
 feited with a-priorism. His philosophy reunited elements 
 which but recently seemed forever irreconcilable : experi- 
 ence and speculation, realism and idealism, positivism and 
 metaphysics. It is speculative, for it rises to the univer- 
 sal, and it is empirical, because it arrives at it by induc- 
 tion. It is an ontology, for it has for its object the essence, 
 and, if we may venture to say so, the secret, of things, and 
 it is positive, since it rests on the solid basis of facts. It 
 is realistic because of the extreme concessions it makes to 
 materialism : it is idealistic and critical in that it denies 
 the absolute reality of the phenomenal world, and makes it 
 depend entirely on our intellectual organization. It gives 
 promise of the future reconciliation of metaphysics and 
 science, and hence its disciples are willing to condone its 
 theory of ideas, borrowed from Plato and contrary to the 
 essentially nominalistic natural-science of the times ; its 
 extreme pessimism, which, though unquestionably superior 
 to the self-satisfied optimism of Leibniz, rests on an imper- 
 fect knowledge of human nature, and evidently exaggerates 
 the import of our personal experiences ; and finally, the 
 extreme bitterness of its diatribes against Fichte, Schelling, 
 
 1 Ch. Secrdtan {Revue philosophique, VII., 3). True, the term is 
 found in his predecessors, especially in Fichte and Schelling, but 
 Schopenhauer gives it its final sanction as a technical term.
 
 SCHOPENHAUER 557 
 
 and Hegel, from whom, in spite of its protests, it derives 
 the monistic idea, and whose chief wrong really consisted 
 in having been professors of philosoph3\ 
 
 The most original among Schopenhauer's disciples, 
 Eduard vox Hartmaxx,! has made the attempt, in his 
 Fhilosophi/ of the Unconscious, to reconcile Schopenhauer 
 and Hegel, by adding to the will a second principle, which 
 serves as its guide : idea {die Vorstelhtng'). The will, he 
 reasons, reaches its ends as though it were intelligent. In 
 the form of soul, it communicates to the human body such 
 movements as it desires, as though perfectly conscious of 
 the means necessary to realize its purpose. In animals 
 it acts instinctively, like the most consummate intelli- 
 
 ^ Born at Berlin, 1812. Besides the Philosophie des Unleivussten 
 (1869 ; numerous editions) ; [Engl. tr. by E. C. Coupland, London, 
 188G], Hartinann has published : Kritische Griuulleyuny des transcen- 
 dentnlen Realismus (1875) ; Phanomenologie des sitdichen Bewusslseins 
 (1879) ; Das religiose Bewusstsein der Menschheit, etc. (1881) ; etc. 
 [Cf. J. Volkelt, Das Unhewusste und der Pessimismus , Berlin, 1873 ; 
 H. Yaihinger, Hartmnnn, Diihring und Lnnge, Fserlohn, 1870; R. Kober, 
 Das philosopJiische Sijstejii E. v. II. 's, Breslau, 1881; J. Sully, Pessi- 
 mism, ch. v. — Tr.] Other prominent disciplfs: J. Frauenstiidt 
 (181:5-1878), (Briefe iiber die Sch.'sche Philosophic, Leipsic, ISSi; 
 Neue Briefe, etc., Leipsic, 1876, etc. Frauenstiidt is not a servile imi- 
 tator ; he criticises and corrects the master in several important 
 respects. Not only does he distinguisli between the higher or Iniman 
 will and the inferior will of the animal, thereby opposing Schopen- 
 hauer, who identifies them, but also substitutes for liis pessimism a 
 system which aims to reconcile pessimism and optimism) ; Bahnsen 
 (Beilrdge ziir Characternhgie, Leipsic, 1867; etc.); I\Iainliinder (P/a- 
 losophie der Erlosung, Berlin, 1870, 2d ed., 1870) ; Deussen {Elemente 
 der Melaphysik, Aix-larChapolle, 1877); [2d ed., Berlin, 1890; Engl, 
 tr. by C. M. Duff, Xew York, 1894; Uichard Wagner, 181:5-188:5, (he 
 great composer (Coljected writings, 9 vols., 2d ed., 1887-8S) ; Fricd- 
 ricli Xietzschc, l>orn 18 H, {Uuzeilgf-mdsse Belrarhtuugen, Leipsic, 187:5- 
 1876; Meitschliches, Allzurneu.tchlichrs, 2 vols., 2d ed., 1880; Aho 
 sprnch Znrathustra, Cliemnilz, 188:5-1881; Jenscits vnn f!ut und Hose, 
 Leipsic, 1880 ; Znr Genealogie der Moral, 1887. Work.s ed. I.y A. Tille; 
 translations by T. ('(jiumoii, 1890). — Tit.]
 
 558 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 gence. As the curative or catagniatic power in nature, it 
 heals wounds and fractures, like the most skilful physician. 
 Hence it is iiitcllir/ent, but unconscious ; it knows without 
 knowing that it knows. 
 
 Tliis distinction between intelligence and inner apper- 
 ception is not new ; we find it in Leibniz and in Schelling. 
 But Hartmann was the first to formulate it with perfect 
 clearness, and to support it by a great mass of facts. It 
 would, however, be a mistake to regard the doctrine that 
 ideas guide the will as creating an essential difference 
 between the disciple and the master ; for Schopenhauer, 
 too, has his Platonic ideas, which serve as stages in the 
 evolution of the will. Besides, Hartmann's idea cannot 
 hinder the absolute from ivilling, i.e., from realizing itself 
 in a world in which the evil necessarily and infinitely 
 exceeds the good, and to which, though it be the best 
 possible world, nothingness would be preferable. All that 
 it can do is to guide the cosmical evolution, and to influ- 
 ence the absolute, by producing a more profound feeling 
 of the universal misery and a more complete knowledge 
 of the secret of things (in a word, by developing con- 
 sciousness), not to will to be : which would mean the 
 end of the world. Here, then, the difference between dis- 
 ciple and master is more apparent than real. According to 
 Hartmann as well as according to Schopenhauer, the exist- 
 ence of the world is an evil, since it is synonymous with 
 pain, sorrow, and anguish, — feelings which recur, in dif- 
 ferent degrees, in myriads of sensible creatures. But, in 
 Schopenhauer's opinion, the evil is irreparable : the world 
 and, consequently, the pains are eternal, and only the indi- 
 viduals that die are relatively redeemed. According to 
 Hartmann, on the other hand, who rests on the principle 
 that no development is withoid beginning or end, and as- 
 sumes a creation and an end of the world, the evil is 
 reparable : redemption is universal, and even the abso-
 
 SCHOPENHAUER 559 
 
 lute is ultimately redeemed.^ Onlvi ^liis redemption is 
 not fiiialy for we have no assurance that the latent state 
 to which the will returns is final, that it will not be 
 re-aroused, that there will not be a new world, that is, a 
 new hell. Chance has produced the present uni\-erse ; the 
 same chance may, in the future, produce an indetinite num- 
 ber of worlds, that is, hells. And here we are back in the 
 doctrine of Schopenhauer. 
 
 Voluntarism and idealism cannot really be reconciled, 
 unless we reform the very notion of loill, on which the 
 pessimistic system is grounded. Master and disciple both 
 err, not in regarding the will as the essence of things, — 
 that is what it is, — but in making it radically and irreme- 
 diably immoral by assigning as its goal life as such, exist- 
 ence at any cost. Now, existence does not give the will 
 the supreme satisfaction which it craves, unless it be 
 devoted to a higher end. Hence, life is not the absolute 
 end of the creative will, and this is not the will-to-live 
 {der Wille zum Lchoi), Ijut the will which strives for the 
 good, by using life as a means, or, should occasion demand, 
 by sacrificing life (der Wille zwni Guten mittcls dcs Lcbcns). 
 The good, for pessimism, consists in unmalciwj what the 
 will has made, and, finally, — for the very fact of willing 
 is folly,2 — in not willing at all; according to us, it con- 
 sists in perfecting the will, in organizing it, in fashioning 
 it by means of morality. 
 
 ^ Hartmann calls this his evobitinnislic optimisin in ojtposilion to 
 Schopenhauer's absolute pessimism; i. e., he makes the historical 
 evolution culminate at least iu the negative happiness of notliingness, 
 while Schopenhauer recognizes in reality neither history, nor evolution, 
 nor progress of any sort. 
 
 '^ In n-ality God himself committed the "folly" of willing to exist, 
 and, in this sense, his folly is " wiser tiuin the wisdom of men " (St. 
 Va^uX): felix culpa (Augustine).
 
 560 MODEKN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 § 69. Darwin and Contemporary Monism^ 
 
 At this point of its evolution, German philosophy approx- 
 imates the teachings of Hobbes and La Mettrie. Schopen- 
 hauer's system is bound to spiritualism by a very slender 
 thread. Schopenhauer censures phrenology for assuming a 
 connection between the will and a definite portion of the 
 brain : the will is the producer and not the product of 
 organization, a primary principle, preceding the physical 
 organization, and, consequently, independent of the func- 
 tions of the brain. But though he refuses to let material- 
 ism have the will, he abandons to it the intellect, which, he 
 declares, results from brain-action. He holds, moreover, 
 with Kant, that the phenomenal world, and, consequently, 
 the brain itself, which forms a part of it, does not exist inde- 
 
 1 Besides the two principal works of Charles Darwin, Orir/in of 
 Species, and Descent of Man, see especially, David Strauss, Der alte 
 undneue Glauhe, 1872 [seep. 562] ; E. Haeckel, Natiaiiche Schojfimgs- 
 geschichte, Berlin, 1868 ff. ; [Engl, tr., Natural History of Creation, 1875] ; 
 Oscar Schmidt, Descendenzlekre und Darwinismus, Leipsic, 187o ; [Engl. 
 tr., The Doctrine of Descent and Darwinism {International Scientific 
 Series)']; L. Noire. Der monistische Gedanke, Leipsic, 1875; Aphoris- 
 men zur nionistischen Philosophie, 1877. [See also : T. Huxley, Man's 
 Place in Nature, London, 1863; same author, Lectures on the Origin of 
 Species, New York, 18.92 ; H. Spencer, Principles of Biology, London, 
 1863-67; E. Haeckel, Antliropogenie, Leipsic, 1874 ft'.; English tr.. 
 New York, 1895 ; E. v. Hartmann, Wahrheit und Irrthum im Darwin- 
 ismus, Berlin, 1875 {Truth and Error in Darwinism, tr. in Journal of 
 Speculative Philosophy, vols. XI.-XIIL) ; A. Weismann, Studien zur 
 Descendenztheorie, 2 pts., Leipsic, 1875-76; H. W. Conn, Evolution of 
 To-Day, New York, 1886 ; A. R. Wallace, Darwinism, London, 1889 ; 
 G. Romanes, Darwin and after Darwin: I., The Darwinian Theory, 
 London, 1892 ; II., Post-Darwinian Questions (edited by Lloyd INIor- 
 gan), 1895 ; O. Hamann, Entwickelungslehre und Darwinismus, Jena, 
 1892 ; R. Schmid, Die Darwinsclie Theorie und ihre Stellung zur 
 Philosophie, Religion, und Moral, Stuttgart, 1870 ; J. G. Schurman, The 
 Ethical Import of Darwinism, New York, 1887 ; T. Huxley, Evolution 
 and Ethics, London, 1893; A. Sclileicher, Die darwinsche Theorie und 
 die SprachoissenschaftfWeimiu; 1865; 3d ed., 1873. — Tu.]
 
 DARWIN AND CONTEMPOEARY MONISM 561 
 
 pendently of the intellect. The brain and the intellect mutu- 
 ally condition each other ; neither exists without the other. 
 The will alone does not, in any way, depend upon organ- 
 ized matter. However, this will, which strives exclusively 
 for existence, differs, neither in principle nor in fact, from 
 the " force " of the materialists. The Rcalci of Horbart, on 
 the other hand, are so much like '• atoms " as to be mistaken 
 for them. The monads of Leibniz perceive of themselves ; 
 Herbart's " perception " remits from the interpenetration of 
 his Hcalcn, and is not native to them : by themselves they 
 are as unintelligent as atomism's centres of force. Accord- 
 ing to Herbart as well as according to materialism, intelli- 
 gence is a product, not a principle. Similarly, that which 
 Hegel calls the creative idea is not conscious intelligence ; 
 it is a principle that becomes conscious intelligence when it 
 is provided with a cerebrum. Where, then, is the essential 
 difference between an unconscious principle and what mate- 
 rialism calls force-matter? Besides, Hegel, like Schopen- 
 hauer, Spinoza, and Bruno, agrees with materialism in 
 rejecting the dogma of the creation and government of the 
 world by a supra-cosmic Avill, the immortality of the soul, 
 and free-will, i. e., the essential doctrines of spiritualism. 
 The Hegelian concei)tion of things and the materialistic 
 philosophy are fundamentally tin? same, howi'ver opposite 
 they may be in form: both substitute naturalism and mon- 
 ism for theism and dualism. Hegelians, abandon and)igu- 
 ous terms ! Call things by their right names ! Do not 
 designate the sul)stance which exists prior to intelligence 
 idea., but matter ! What distinguishes us from tiie materi- 
 alists is, ultimately, the method we employ. Now, ours is 
 manifestly false, theire is evidently the true one ; hence, 
 let us unite with them ! So sj)oke the lil)eral Hegelians, 
 particularly Ludwk; Feueruacii,^ renowmul for his works 
 
 ' Son of tin; jurist, Aiiseliii FcihtIimcIi ; ls()l-1872 ; coiiipli-ti- works, 
 10 vols., Iy<'ii)sic, 1811! fT. [Cf. K. (iiiiii, A. Ft-ttcrhnrh,'! vols , Lcipsic, 
 1871.] ;iG
 
 562 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 on Das Wcsen des Christenthums'^ and Das JFescn der Be- 
 ligion,^ who was afterwards joined by David Strauss.^ 
 
 Thus materialism,* reinforced by the descendants of 
 Heo-elianism and popularized by such talented writers as 
 Jacob Moleschott,^ Ludwig Buchneii,*^ Carl Vogt,^ 
 and Ernst Haeckel,^ became in German}^ what it had 
 been in France since the eighteenth century : an intellectual 
 power of the highest order, firmly resting upon the basis of 
 facts and having in its favor the double advantage of per- 
 fect clearness and comprehensive, thorough knowledge. 
 
 1 [The Essence of Christianity'}, Leipsic, ISil. " Antliropology is 
 the secret of tJieology. God is man worshipping himseM. The Trinity 
 is the human family deified.'' 
 
 2 Leipsic, 1815. 
 
 8 1808-1874:. Author of Das Leben Jesu, Tubingen, 1835-3G ; [TAe 
 Life of Christ, tr. by George Eliot, London, 1846 ff.] ; Der alte und der 
 neue Glaube, 1872 ff. ; [Engl. tr. by M. Blind, London, 1873. Collected 
 works, ed. by E. Zeller, 12 vols., Bonn, 187G-78. Cf. A. Hausrath, 
 David Friedrich Sti-auss und die Theologie seiner Zeit, 2 voLs., Heidel- 
 berg, 1876-1878. — Tr.] 
 
 * [See P. Janet, Le materialisme contemporain, 6th ed., Paris, 1893; 
 Engl. tr. by G. Masson, London, 1866. — Tr.] 
 
 6 [1822-1893.] Der Kreislauf des Lebens, Mainz, 18.52 ; 4th ed., 1 862 ; 
 Die Einheit des Lebens, Giessen, 1864:. 
 
 6 [Born 1824.] Kraft und Stoff, Frankfort, 1855 ; 16tli ed., 1888; 
 [Engl, tr., Force and Matter, by Collingwood, 4th ed., London, 1884]; 
 Natur und Geist, 1857 ff. ; Seeks Vorlesnngen iiber die Darwinsche Theorie, 
 Leipsic, 1868 ff. ; [Die Stellung des Menschen, etc., Leipsic, 1869 f . ; 
 Engl, tr., Man in the Past, Present, and Future, by W. F. Dallas, Lon- 
 don, 1872.] 
 
 7 [1817-1895.] Phusiohrfsche Briefe, Stuttgart, 1845-47; Kohler- 
 glaube und Wissenschaft, Giessen, 1854 ; Vorlesnngen iiher den Menschen, 
 Giessen, 1863. 
 
 8 [Born 1834.] Generelle MorphoJngie der Organismen, Berlin, 1806 
 ff.; Naturliche Schopfungsgeschichte, Berlin, 1868, 8th ed., 1889 ; [Engl, 
 tr.. Natural History of Creation, New York, 1892; Anthropogenie, Leip- 
 sic, 1874 ff. ; Engl. tr.. The Evolution of Man, Xew York, 1895; Ge- 
 sammelte populare Vortrdge, 1878 ff, ; Engl, tr., Popular I^ectures, 1888. 
 -Tr]
 
 DARWIN AND CONTEMPORARY MONISM 563 
 
 Its alliance with political and religious radicalism gained 
 for it tlie sympathies of the public, and it receives support 
 from a number of recent discoveries and scientific theories. 
 It appeals to the transformistic theory of Lamauck^ and 
 Charles Darwin ^ against the miracle of creation ; to 
 the anatomical study of anthropoid apes, against the view 
 that there is an insurpassable gulf between animals and 
 man, matter and mind ; ^ to tlie advance of chemical 
 synthesis, against the phantom of the vital jjrinciple ; ^ to 
 the theory of the equivalence and transformation of forces ^ 
 and electrological discoveries,^ against the hypothesis of a 
 
 1 [1744-1829.] Philosophie zooloyique, Paris, 1809 ; [new ed. by C. 
 Martins, Paris, 187o]. 
 
 2 [18U9-18S2.] On tlie Origin of Species hij 7neanx of Natural Selec- 
 tion, London, 1859 if. ; \_The Descent of Man, id., 1871; T/ie Expression 
 of the Emotions in Man and Animals, id., 1872 ; etc. See Francis Dar- 
 Avin, Life and Letters of Charles Darwin, London, 1887. Bililiography in 
 J. W. Spengel, Die Darwinsche Theorie, 2d ed., Berlin, 1872. Cf. § G9, 
 notel. — Tr.]. 
 
 ^ Huxley, Man's I'lace in Natxire, London, 18G3; Vogt, Vorlesungen 
 iiber den Menschen, seine Stellung in der Schopfiing itnd in der Geschichte 
 der Erde, French translation by Moulinie, 18G5. 
 
 * R. Virchow [born 1821] Der alte und neue Vitalismus (Archir fiir 
 pathologische Anatomic und Physiologic, TX., 1-2). 
 
 5 Sir Humphry Davy [1778-1829]. Faraday [1791-1867]. J. R. 
 Mayer [181 1-1878, Piemerkungcn iiher die Krafte der nnhchhlen Natur, 
 1842. His troatisf'S were collected under the title, Pic Mrchanik der 
 Wdrme, 2d ed., Stuttgart, 1874. Cf. E. Diihring, R. Mn;/er, der Galilei 
 des 19. Jahrhunderts, Chemnitz, 1880. — Tr.]. H. Hehnholtz [1821- 
 IHQo'], Ueher die Erhaltung der Kraft, Berlin, 1847; Ueher die Wech- 
 selwirkung der Naturkrafte, Kbnig.slu^rg, 1854; both in Vortrdge und 
 Reden, 3d ed., Braunschweig, 1884; Engl, tr.. Popular Lectures, New 
 York, 1881]. (l. A. Hirii, Esr/uisse de la theorie inecanii/ue de la rhaleur, 
 1804. John Tyiidall [1820-1893], Heat considered as a Mode of Mo 
 tion, London, 1803; Mailer and Force, id., ISCG. Combes [1811 -1872], 
 Exposition de la theorie mecanique de la chalcur. Dupny, Transforma- 
 tion des forces. W. f! rove [born 1811], On the Correlation of Phi/sic(d 
 Forces, London, 1810; 0th ed., 1871. 
 
 " E. Dii IJois-Rcyuifdid [born 181s], Untcrsuchungt n uher thierische 
 Elektriciiat, 2 vols., Berlin, 184.S-84.
 
 564 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 separate force for the explanation of thought ; to the geo- 
 loo-ical theory of gradual evolutions and imperceptible 
 changes,! against the theory of cataclysms,^ behind which, 
 according to materialism, lurks the belief in the arbitrary 
 intervention of a supernatural power ; finally, to the many 
 conclusive facts which prove, beyond the shadow of a doubt, 
 that a relation exists between the brain and thought, against 
 the spiritualistic distinction between soul and body. 
 
 Of all these innovations, the Darwinian theory is the 
 one which materialism appropriated most readily, and to 
 which it is most indebted. This theory answers the follow- 
 ing cardinal question, which had remained unsolved until 
 the days of Darwin : How can the purposiveness which is 
 revealed in the structure and arrangement of our organs 
 be produced without the intervention of an intelligent 
 creative cause, and through the purely mechanical action 
 of unconscious forces? or, rather: How can we explain 
 finality [purposiveness, teleology] without final causes?^ 
 Darwinism provides materialism with a satisfactoiy answer 
 to the main objection of theistic spiritualism, and thereby 
 becomes its indispensable ally. So close is this alliance 
 that Darwinism and materialism are regarded as synony- 
 mous terms. 
 
 Ever since the eighteenth century two systems have 
 been opposing each other.* AccorcUng to the one, which 
 rests on the supposed immutability of species, every animal 
 and vegetable species has been created independently of 
 all its congeners (the creationism of Linnaeus and Cuvier) ; 
 according to the other, whose principles were formulated 
 
 1 C. Lyell [1707-1875], Principles of Genhgy, London, 1830; 11th 
 ed., 1872.' 
 
 ^ Georges Cnvier [1769-1882], Di:^conr.f stir les revolutions de la 
 surface du globe (Tntroduction to BecliercTies sur les ossements fossiles). 
 
 * Haeckel, Natural History of Creation, Eng. tr., pp. 390 ff. 
 
 4 See § 60.
 
 DARWIN AND CONTEMPORARY MONISM 565 
 
 by Diderot and Robinet, species are merely varieties, more 
 pronounced and more stable than the forms which we com- 
 monly call varieties, and descend from each other by gen- 
 eration (transforniism, or evolutionism). The theory of 
 transformation opposes to the dogma of the immutability 
 of species the fact of their variability. The parent form 
 and its offspring alwaj's resemble each other; they are 
 never identical. That is to say, there are differences 
 betAveen them. Moreover, — and that is important, — these 
 differences may be transmitted by heredity. But how and 
 by what causes are these endless variations and progres- 
 sive metamorphoses produced ? How and by wliat causes 
 could the tiger and the gazelle, the mouse and the elephant, 
 spring from one and the same source ? According to La- 
 marck and Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire, this is explained by the 
 influence of the environment upon the organism, and by 
 the gradual adaptation of the organism to its conditions of 
 existence. This explanation, which sufficed for a certain 
 number of cases, but left a still larger number unexplained, 
 was completed by Charles Darwin (1809-1882), the most 
 celebrated naturalist of our century, in liis monumental 
 work : On the Origin of Species hij Means of Natural Selec- 
 tion} The transformation of organized beings and tlie 
 diversity of their specific types is, according to Darwin, 
 brouglit about by the natural competition between them, 
 Ijy the struggle for life. This struggle for existence results 
 in a selection wholly similar to the artificial selection by 
 means of which the horticultui'ist and breeder obtain 
 their varieties. What, for instance, does the breeder of 
 pigeons do ? ^ Tie observes tliat one of liis pigeons has 
 one more tail-feather than tlie (jthei's. He finds a female 
 possessing the same ])eculiarity, and tliis j):iir produce off- 
 spring liaving two, three, or four \\\u\\\ tail-feathers than 
 
 » Sie p. .003, note L». 
 
 '•* Orii/iii of Species, Otli t'(l., p]). II IT.
 
 566 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the original stock : the fantail. By a similar process he 
 obtains the pouter, the Jacobin, the tumbler, the carrier, 
 and other varieties. The same principles are followed by 
 horticulturists and breeders of horses, dogs, and cattle : 
 by selecting their pairs and seeds according to certain 
 qualities, these artists succeed in infinitely modifying the 
 types. They realize their purpose by methodical selection 
 and with a distinct object in view ; nature obtains the 
 same results (modification of types) unintentionally, by 
 means of the competition or struggle for existence. As 
 a result of this struggle, a selection, or kind of choice, is 
 made among beings ; some, i. e., the strongest, or the most 
 clever, or such as, for some reason or other, are best fitted 
 to survive, are reproduced \_survival of the fittest^ ; others 
 perish. The latter are the outcasts, the former the elect of 
 nature, the select of the competition, which is not only the 
 principle of all social progress, but also the first cause of 
 all development in nature. Let us imagine, says Strauss, 
 commenting on Darwin,^ a herd of cattle, at a time 
 when these animals had no horns. The herd is attacked 
 by wild beasts. It is evident that in the ensuing struggle 
 for existence, those which have the strongest heads will 
 stand a better chance of surviving than the others, and it is 
 also evident that if tliere be in the attacked herd an indi- 
 vidual possessing rudimentary horns, it will have more 
 chances of survival than the rest of the herd. Great num- 
 bers of the latter will perish ; the favored animal, however, 
 will escape ; it will produce offspring and (what is im- 
 portant in this connection) transmit to its descendants the 
 peculiarity which saved its life and enabled it to be repro- 
 duced: its rudimentary weapons of defence. Its descend- 
 ants will possess the same peculiar characteristic in greater 
 or less degree. The better equipped they are in this re- 
 gard, the greater will be their chances of conquering in the 
 
 ^ Der alte und neue Glaube, 2d ed., pp. 190 fE.
 
 DARWIN AND CONTEMPORARY MONISM 567 
 
 renewed struggle for existence, and of transmitting their 
 organs of protection to the succeeding generations. And 
 thus the organ, wliich, in the fu'st animal possessino- it, 
 was nothing but a freak of nature, and which, without the 
 struggle for existence, would have disappeared with its 
 owner, without leaving a trace in the bovine species, goes 
 on developing and perfecting itself from generation to gen- 
 eration. What was at lii-st a purely individual character- 
 istic becomes a generic characteristic, in consec^uence of 
 the never-ending struggle for existence and the accumu- 
 lated effects of the constantly renewed process of selection. 
 
 In the foregoing example, the selection is determined by 
 a positive advantage, a surplus, but there are cases in which 
 a defect may have the same effect, in which an imperfection 
 may be an advantage and a cause of selection. Let us sup- 
 pose, with Haeckel,! that a swarm of winged insects on an 
 oceanic island are overtaken by a storm, blown to sea, and 
 destroyed. Let us also suppose that one of these insects is 
 wingless; it will not be able to follow the swarm in their 
 flight, and to this verv defect it will owe its safet}'. It -\^•ill 
 survive its winged congeners and transmit its defect to 
 some of its offspring, wliich will, consequently, jjossess 
 the same advantage (that of being "selected") ; and so on, 
 until, from selection to selection, the comijlcte absence 
 of winofs comes to constitute the characteristic f>f the 
 species.2 In this case, undoubtedly, the process of uatural 
 selection is really a retrogi-ession, for liere we have to doid 
 with a deformity, with a gradual weakening; but evolution 
 in nature is retrogressive as well as progressive. 
 
 Selection by means of the struggle for life sulliciently 
 explains cveiy teleologieal characteristic in organisms. It 
 even explains the formation of tlie sense-organs, the eye and 
 
 ' Anlunil Ilialory of Credllon, pp. '-VJ.! ff. 
 
 * [.Si'(? Darwin's explanation <if tlio win^flrss coiulition of tin' M:i- 
 deira beetle, Oritjin of Species, cli, V., pp. 1(U ff. — Tit.]
 
 568 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the ear, these wonderful works of art, which have always 
 been appealed to as the most conclusive evidences of final- 
 istic and creationistic doctrines. The first eye produced in 
 the evolution of the animal kingdom was, like the first horn 
 of the bovine genus, a mere rudimentary organ, differing as 
 much from the eyes of higher species now existing as the 
 fin of the fish differs from the arm of man. But in so far 
 as it refracted light and aroused a luminous sensation, how- 
 ever weak, it gave the individual endowed with it an im- 
 mense advantage in the struggle for existence, and made 
 him the " elect of nature." His blind congeners necessarily 
 disappeared, leaving it to him to preserve the species and 
 to transmit this visual organ, in a more pronounced form 
 perhaps, to the descendants. The same causes continued to 
 act, and to accumulate their effects, from generation to 
 generation, until, after thousands of centuries of progressive 
 evolution, the eye at last attained to its present perfection, 
 surpassing the most consummate products of art and the 
 wisest combinations of intelligence ; and it attained to it, not 
 through intelligent intervention, but by natural selection.^ 
 It was, as we have said, owing to this mechanical expla- 
 nation of finality — an explanation which, in Darwin, does 
 not exclude the idea of creation — that contemporary mate- 
 rialism at once enthusiastically adopted the theory of nat- 
 ural selection. What we attribute to "the wisdom of 
 Providence," or to " the kindness of Mother Nature," ap- 
 peared, in the Darwinian hypothesis, as the product of the 
 natural competition of beings and the selection resulting 
 therefrom. Animals that can live in warm climates with- 
 out any covering are protected by warm fur in Northern 
 regions ; most of those inhabiting the desert resemble their 
 surroundings in color, and are thereby concealed from their 
 enemies ; finally, the existence of every living being is, in 
 a certain measure, " assured." But there is no charitable 
 1 Origin of Species, chap^. VL, pp. 139 ff.
 
 DARWIN AND CONTEMPORARY MONISM 569 
 
 design nor supernatural and providential arrangement in 
 all this. The animals of the North do not have fur in order 
 to protect them from the cold ; they do not suffer from the 
 cold, because they have fur. And they have fur, because their 
 progenitors, whom chance clothed with a thicker skin, were, 
 on that account, better fitted to carry on the struggle for 
 existence than their less favored congeners ; and were able, 
 in consequence of this natural selection, to reproduce them- 
 selves and to transmit their peculiarities to their offspring, 
 whereas the others perished, and their type disappeared. 
 The same may be said of the animals of the desert, and of 
 all animals and plants enjoying some advantage apparently 
 due to fuial causes.-^ 
 
 The principle of selection applies not only to anatomy 
 and physiology, but also to animal psychology. The in- 
 stincts of spiders, ants, bees, beavers, and birds, which, 
 even according to Hartmann's belief, can only be explained 
 by means of a deus-ex machina (the unconscious), are, in 
 Darwin's opinion, nothing but inherited habits, which have 
 become a second nature through the effects of the struggle 
 for life and natural selection. That which is innate in the 
 present generation was not so in the original ancestors, and 
 the wonderful art manifested in the instincts of certain ani- 
 mals is merely the result of an evolution lasting countless 
 ages, and of a gradual perfection, beginning with the very 
 earliest origin of these species. Our intellectual habits 
 originated in the same way. The ideas which spiritualism 
 considers as innate, and which, according to Kant, belong 
 to the veiy constitution of the intelligence, are, undoubt- 
 edly, a part of our present mental organization, but they 
 weie not native to our first progenitors. Tlie latter acquired 
 tliem by experience; they were traiisiiiittcd to us, as intel- 
 lectual habits or dispositions, by heredity aided by selection, 
 and thus eventually became innate. 
 
 * Haeckel, Natural Ilistory of Creation, Locluro XL
 
 570 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 An inevitable corollary of the principle of transforma- 
 tion and selection is the simian origin of man. Darwin 
 advances it in liis second main work : The Descent of Man 
 (1871). Man is the descendant of a variety of apes, more 
 favored than the rest. The false pride which hinders us 
 from accepting this view arises from the fact that the ape 
 has a comical demeanor which gives him the appearance 
 of a cretin^ an idiot, a caricature of a man. We should 
 not feel so, if it were held that we descended from the 
 lion or the rose-bush. Strange to say, we do not even 
 experience this feeling when we read the Biblical story, 
 according to which our species sprang from a clod of earth : 
 a still more humiliating origin, considering the enormous 
 distance between a clod of earth and an organized being, 
 and an organized being as advanced as the ape. The objec- 
 tion is made that a Csesar, a Kant, a Goethe, could not have 
 descended from an animal, — that there is an insuperable 
 distance between them and the ape. But this objection 
 falls to the ground when we take into account, on the one 
 hand, the intermediate links between the anthropoid ape 
 and Caesar (Papuans, New Zealanders, Caffirs, etc.), and, 
 on the other, the immense period of time wdiich nature, 
 i. e., the struggle for existence and selection, needed to 
 effect the evolution from the man-ape to Caesar and Goethe. 
 It is true, the six thousand years, which, according to the 
 Bible, is the age of the world, would not have sufficed. 
 But the palseontological discoveries of our century (lacus- 
 trine deposits, flint tools, cave-dwellers, the kjokken-mod- 
 dings on the Danish coasts, etc.) unquestionably prove that 
 the human race is much older, and that even Egyptian 
 civilization, which is prodigiously ancient, is relatively 
 modern} Infinitely short steps and infinitely long periods : 
 these, says Strauss,^ are the two keys which open the gates 
 hitherto accessible to miracle only. Well ! Does not 
 1 Strauss, Der alte und neue Glaube, p. 202. ' Id.
 
 DARWIN AND CONTEMPORARY ^[ONIS^I 671 
 
 Chi'istianity teach that God became man ? Then why can- 
 not an animal become man ? The non-Christian religions do 
 not believe it to be impossible, as the doctrine of the trans- 
 migration of souls, taught by ancient Egypt, Brahmanism, 
 and Buddhism, shows. In truth, there is no gulf between 
 man and the animal. We cannot deny the latter sensi- 
 bility, memory, and intelligence. The facts which })rove 
 it would fill volumes. The moral sense is not foreign to 
 animals ; it may, as Strauss adds,^ be aroused in the dog by 
 the whip , but can we not say the same for many men ? 
 The animal has feelings of motherly love, attachment, and 
 devotion. It differs from us in degree only ; its " soul " 
 is to oiu-s what the bud is to the flower and the fruit. 
 
 We shall not dwell upon these results of contemporary 
 materialistic thought, which add nothing essentially new 
 to the teachings of the eighteenth century. What charac- 
 terizes modern materialism is not its mechanical explana- 
 tion of the world, nor its absolute negation of linal causes, 
 
 — in this respect as v.^ell as in all the others, materialistic 
 principles have not changed since the times of Democritus, 
 
 — but solely the fact that, thanks to Darwin, it found, as 
 its adherents claim, a ready answer to the constantly reit- 
 erated and never refuted objection of the teleologists : 
 Every work adapted to an end presup[)oses a workman, an 
 intelligence, a design, and shall not the most admiral)le 
 product of all, the most perfect camera obscura, the human 
 eye, presuppose one? 
 
 In other respects, contemporary materialism agrees not 
 only witli the materialism of the eighteenth century and 
 Greek materialism, but also with the essential doctrines of 
 German idealism and Spinozistic pantheism : the Universe 
 or tlie All-One substituted for God, tlie consubstantiality 
 of l)eings, absolute determinism. In order to emphasize 
 tliis agreement, the German materialism of our days calls 
 itself vwnisin. 
 
 1 Dtr (il(€ und neue Glaube, p. 207.
 
 572 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The difference existing between materialistic monism 
 and the idealistic monism of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, 
 may be expressed as follows : The former emphatically 
 denies all finality ; whereas the latter, inspired by Kant's 
 Critique of Judgment^ recognizes in nature, if not the 
 designs of a transcendent Creator, at least an immanent 
 finality. The Idea of Hegel is the highest end of nature 
 realizing itself by means of an evolution that is both phys- 
 ical and logical : phj^sical, in so far as it is unconscious ; 
 logical, in so far as it excludes chance. Hence, it is really 
 identical with what Schelling and, above all, Schopenhauer, 
 call by its true name : Will. 
 
 Now, we may ask ourselves the question : Does not the 
 Darwinian principle, which materialism invokes with such 
 absolute confidence, corroborate, rather than overturn, the 
 hypothesis of immanent teleology ? Is it really true that 
 the struggle for existence is a first cause and exclusively 
 mechanical ? Does not the struggle for life, in turn, pre- 
 suppose Schopenhauer's ivill-to-live, will or effort., without 
 which, according to the profound remark of Leibniz, there 
 can he no substance ? ^ Does it not, therefore, presuppose 
 an anterior, superior, and immaterial cause ? What can the 
 formula : struggle for existence, mean, except : struggle 
 in order to exist? Now, that carries us right into tele- 
 ology. Besides, we cannot deny that the entire Darwin- 
 ian terminology is derived from the teleological theory : 
 the terms, selection., clioice, evidently introduce an intellect- 
 ual element into nature. ^ These are mere images, it is 
 
 1 Haeckel himself says : In the last analysis, the impulses which 
 determine (hedingen, condition) the stiaiggle and its diverse forms, are 
 merely those of self-preservation (Selbstei-haltung). See his Natural 
 History of Creation, pp. 282 ff. Here we no longer have materialism, 
 but pure voluntarism. 
 
 ^ [See Darwin's answer to such objections. Origin of Species, 6th 
 ed., chap. IV., pp. 58 ff. — Tr.]
 
 POSITIVISM AND NEO-CRITICISM 573 
 
 said, or figures of speech. Very well. But does not the 
 very impossibility of avoiding them prove the impossibility 
 of explaining nature by pure mechanism ? 
 
 § 70. Positivism and Neo-Criticism 
 
 Not all materialists, it must be added, are equally posi- 
 tive and dogmatic. Contrary to the opinion of one Lowen- 
 tbal,^ who accuses even the author of Force and Matter of 
 moderantism, there are, in Germany, France, and England, 
 a considerable number of thinkers, moralists and physicists, 
 historians and physiologists, who sympathize with materi- 
 alism more than with an}' other phikisophy, but remain, 
 either through conviction or policy, within the limits as- 
 signed to speculation by the criticism of Locke, Hume, 
 and Kant. In France, tliis party, wliich is decidedly 
 hostile to metaphj'sics and determined to replace it by 
 science^ has, for the last thirty j^ears, been gathering around 
 the standard of Comte. It is known as the positivistic 
 school. 
 
 AuGUSTE Comte was born at ]\Iontpellier in 1789. He 
 entered the Ecole jiolytechiiquc^ then became a tutor and 
 examiner in this school, which, under the Restoration, con- 
 tinued the traditions of the eighteenth century. His Cours 
 cle jjhilosojjJiie positive^ lAaced him among the oiigiual tliink- 
 
 1 Dr. VA. Lciwoiithiil, Si/stetn utul Gcschic/ile des Xiitunilisiitu.^, \A'\\y- 
 sic, 18(51; .Jill ed., 1808. 
 
 2 G vols., Paris, 18:59-12; 2il ed., with a Pre/are by Littre, Paris, 
 1864; [English version freely translated and condensed by Harriet 
 Martineau, London, 185.3. Lat<^r writintjs: Si/slhne dr politique posi- 
 tive, 4 vols., Paris, 1851-51 (Engl, tr., 187.5-77) ; Calcchisnie positirisle, 
 18.53 (Engl. tr. by Congreve, 18.58, 2d ed., 1883). See Littre, Comir el 
 la pJtilosopltie positiriste, Paris, 1803; 2d ed., 1801; J. S. Mill. Cnnte 
 and J'osilivi.sm, ^Million, ISCh) ; 3ded., 18S2; 15. I'linjer, Ikr l'i>siliiis- 
 muK, etc. {Jahrhildier f. Protestantische Theolngie), 1878; E. Caird, T/ie 
 Siiriiil Phil'tSDphi/ and Hilif/loit of ('oiiitr, (Iliisgow, 1885; II. (Inibfr,
 
 574 MODERN rHiLOSOPHY 
 
 ers of our age. Emil Littr^ ^ in France, and John Stuart 
 Mill ^ in England, were the most distinguished of his fol- 
 lowers. He died at Paris in 1857. 
 
 Positivism is not a mere negation, — otherwise it could 
 not have formed a school, — it is a system whose central 
 teaching, the theory of the history of thought, is the realistic 
 counterpart, so to speak, of HegeFs philosophy of mind. 
 
 According to Comte, the human mind successively passes 
 through three stages of thinking or philosophizing : the 
 theological stage, wliich is elementary and represents the 
 period of childhood, the metaphysical stage, and the positive 
 stage. 
 
 From the theological or anthropomorphic point of view, 
 cosmical phenomena are governed, not by immutal^le laws, 
 but by wills like ours. This primitive form of thought has 
 
 Comte und tier Positivistnus, 1890; same author, De'r Posllivismus vom 
 Tode Comte^s, etc., 1S91 ; J. Watson, Comte, Mill, and Spencer, New 
 York, 1895. — Tr.]. 
 
 ^ 1801-1881. Analyse raisonne'e du cowx de philosophie positive de 
 M. A. Comte, Paris, 1845: Application de la philosophie positive au 
 gouvernement des societes, 1849 ; Conservation, revolution et positivisme, 
 1852; Paroles de philosophie positive, 1859; Auguste Comte et la philo- 
 sophie positive, 1863 ; Fragments de philosophie positive et de sociolngie 
 contemporaine, 1876. Littre is also the founder of the Revue positive 
 (1867-83). His Dictionnaire de la langue franqaise constitutes his chief 
 claim to glory. 
 
 2 John Stuart Mill and Littre, however, wholly disavow Auguste 
 Comte's socialistic Utopias, which proceed from Saint-Simon. To 
 these positivists, properly so-called, we must add, as distinguished rep- 
 resentatives of the positivistic movement, two gifted mathematicians : 
 Sophie Germain [1776-1831], who anticipates the system of Comte in 
 her Considerations generates sur Vetat des sciences et des lettres aiix diffd- 
 rentes e'pof/nes de lew culture [posthumous work, published by L'Herbette, 
 Paris, 1833], and M. Cournot, author of an Essai sur les fondements de 
 nos connaissances et sur les caracteres de la critique philosophique (1851), 
 and of a Traile de Venchalnement des ide'es fondamentales dans les sciences 
 et dans I'histoire (1861), the conclusions of which are obviously the same 
 as Comte's.
 
 POSITIVISM AND NEO-CRITICISM 575 
 
 three stages. First, the objects themselves are regarded 
 as animated, living, intelligent (fetichism). On the next 
 stage, invisible beings are imagined, each of them gov- 
 erning a certain gronp of objects or events (polytheism). 
 In a higher form, at last, all these particular divinities 
 are merged into the conception of one God, who created 
 the world and now governs it either directly or through 
 the medium of supernatural agents of the second order 
 (monotheism). 
 
 Metapliiisical thought no longer explains phenomena by 
 conscious wills, but by abstractions considered as real 
 beings. Nature is no longer governed 1)y an anthrf)p()mor- 
 phous God, but by a force, a power, a principle. We repu- 
 diate the divinities with which the ancients peopled nature, 
 only to replace them by souls, mysterious essences. We 
 pretend to explain facts by the tendencies of nature, which we 
 regard as a kind of intelligent rather than impersonal being. 
 We invest it with a tendency towards perfection, a /lorror of 
 a vacuum, a curative virtue (vis viedicatrix), occult qualities. 
 The metaphysical view errs in that it takes abstractions for 
 realities. 
 
 The dominion of metaphysics, more or less influenced by 
 the theological spirit, lasted until tlie end of the Middle 
 Ages, when the controversy between the nominalists and 
 the realists, the first struggle of modern tliought to rid itself 
 of verbal abstractions, inaugurated the positive epoch (I)''S- 
 cartes, Bacon, Hobbes, Galileo, Gassendi, Newton). I'iVer 
 since the advent of this period, the positive explanation of 
 facts is gradually superseding the theological and metaphys- 
 ical explanations, in proportion as the advance of scientilic 
 research brings to liglit an increasing number of invarial)ie 
 laws. 
 
 Like pliilos()])liy in general, eueli science in particular 
 passes tlirougli tiieso thnn; consecutive stages: the theo 
 logical state, the metaphysical state, and the positive stato.
 
 576 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Now, the various brandies of human knowledge have devel- 
 oped with unequal rapidity, and cannot simultaneously pass 
 from one phase to the other. The order of succession in 
 which they enter upon the metaphysical stage and the posi- 
 tive stage is indicated by the logical order in which they 
 follow each other. Thus, the search for the order in wliich 
 the special sciences pass from one phase of thought to the 
 other leads Comte to construct his remarkable classification 
 of the sciences. 
 
 In surveying the different sciences he observes that they 
 are naturally arranged in an order of increasing complexity 
 and diminishing generality: so that each one depends on the 
 truths of all the sciences ivhich precede it, plus stick truths as 
 properly helong to it. 
 
 The science of number {arithmetic and algehra) deals 
 with the most simple, and, at the same time, most general 
 phenomena ; the truths which it formulates hold for all 
 things, and dej)end only upon themselves. We can study 
 it independently of all other sciences ; hence it is the fun- 
 damental science, and, in a certain sense, the first philoso- 
 phy. Then comes geometry, Avhich presupposes the laws of 
 number, and can be studied without previous knowledge of 
 any other science except arithmetic. Then comes rational 
 mechanics, which depends on the science of number and 
 geometry, to which it adds the laws of equilibrium and 
 movement. The truths of algebra and geometry would be 
 true even if those of mechanics were not ; arithmetic, alge- 
 bra, and geometry, therefore, do not depend on mechanics, 
 whereas the latter essentially dej)ends on the science of 
 number and extension. The science of number (arithmetic 
 and algebra), geometry, and rational mechanics together 
 constitute the science of mathematics, the universal science 
 and sole basis of all natural philosoph3\i 
 
 ^ Cours de philosophie positive, vol. I. Cf . Pythagoras, Plato, Des- 
 cartes.
 
 POSITIVISM AND NEO-CRITICISM 577 
 
 Astronomy is directly connected with mathematics. Its 
 truths rest on arithmetical, geometrical, and mechanical 
 truths, upon which it exercises no influence, but to wliieh 
 it adds a groui) of new facts : the laws of gravitation.^ 
 
 Astronomy is followed by j^^i'l/sics, which depends not 
 only on the mathematical sciences, but also on astronomy, 
 for terrestrial phenomena are influenced by the motion of 
 the earth and of celestial bodies. It embraces barologt/, or 
 the science of weight, a transition-state between astronomy 
 and physics ; thermologi/, or the science of heat ; acoustics, 
 optics, and electrology, a connecting-link between physics 
 and the science which immediately follows it in the scale 
 of our knowledge : chemistrt/. 
 
 Chemistry adds its own truths to the laws of pli3-sics, 
 especially to those of thermology and electrology, on which 
 it essentially depends.^ 
 
 Biology (ph^-siology) adds to the laws of the preceding 
 sciences a group of special laws. 
 
 Finally, at the top of the scale, we have social physics or 
 sociology^ which, in turn, depends on all the precethng 
 sciences, and adds new data to them. In fact, the laws of 
 organic and animal life, as well as tliose of inorganic 
 nature, influence human society, either by directly acting 
 upon life, or by determining the physical conditions under 
 which society is developed. 
 
 With the sciences which Comte calls uhstrnct are con- 
 nected the respective concrete sciences : with pliysics and 
 chemistry, abstract sciences, mineralog}^ a concrete sci- 
 ence ; with physiology, an abstract science, zoology and 
 botany, concrete sciences. The latter are concerned with 
 existing beings and ol^jcets ; the former, with the general 
 laws of occnrrencL'. The concrete scieiic-i's necessarily 
 advance more slowly than the abstract sciences, since they 
 
 ' Cours lie jihiloxojihie positive, vol. 1 1. 
 "- l<l., vol. III. a /,/.^ vuLs. IV.-V. 
 
 37
 
 578 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 depend on these. Hence they have not yet passed beyond 
 the descriptive stage. 
 
 The abstract sciences (mathematics, astronomy, physics, 
 chemistry, biology, sociology) pass from tlie theological 
 phase to the metaphysical and positive phase, in the order 
 of their simplicity. The more complex a science is, the 
 more obstacles it throws in the way of the human mind in 
 general as well as of the individual in particular. Thus, 
 mathematics, the simplest of the sciences, has, for thousands 
 of years, been almost positive. Forsooth, it never was the- 
 ological in the sense that any man of common-sense ever 
 prayed to God to make three times three ten, or the sum of 
 the angles of a triangle exceed t^vo right-angles. It was 
 understood, from the very beginning, that in these matters 
 there can be no intervention of freedom whatsoever. 
 
 We cannot say the same for astronomy. It had its theo- 
 logical period, during which the stars were conceived 
 either as divinities, or as moved by many divine wills 
 (polytheism), or by one divine will (monotheism). To this 
 phase belongs the miracle of Joshua. It had its metaphysi- 
 cal epoch, during which the regular motion of the heavenly 
 bodies was explained by their tendency towards perfection. 
 Aristotle is almost a theologian in astronomy ; even Coper- 
 nicus and Kepler are still metaphysicians, and this science 
 does not attain to its positive phase until the days of 
 Newton. In our age positive astronomy has become a part 
 of the popular consciousness. True, we still pray to God 
 for rain and good weather, but we no longer ask him to 
 arrest the apparent motion of the sun, or to change the 
 celestial orbits. We are still theologians in meteorology, 
 because, in this field, the uniformity of phenomena is less 
 marked, and because their apparent irregularity, joined 
 with our ignorance of their true laws, favors the super- 
 stitious belief that they are governed by a free will. 
 Astronomy, however, has abandoned this view.
 
 POSITIVISM AND NEO-CRITICISM 57^ 
 
 Physics and chemistiy were theologico-metaphysical sci- 
 ences longer than the science of celestial bocUes. They 
 abound in occult qualities, horrors, sympathies, and other 
 abstractions assumed to be realities. Chemistry was alchemy 
 down to the eighteenth century, and did not become a pos- 
 itive science until the days of Lavoisier. It took phj-si- 
 ology still longer to reach the threshold of positivism. Un- 
 til recently (tliink of Slahl's animism, of vitalism, Schelling 
 and Oken) it was right in the midst of metaphysics, and 
 positive biology does not go back farther than to Bichat. 
 Finally, sociology (moral and political science) has not yet 
 sui-mounted the barriers which separate metaphysics from 
 positivism. Many of its thinkers have not even passed the 
 theological stage (De ]\Iaistre, De Bonald, the theological 
 school).^ It is true, attempts at political positivism were 
 made by Ilobljes and Spinoza, who treated of man " as 
 though he were dealing with lines, surfaces, and bodies ; " 
 but their efforts met A\'ith no response. The eigliteenth 
 century and the Revolution prepared the Avay for positive 
 social science, without, however, establishing it. Positivism 
 claims the honor of having founded it. 
 
 Political and social ideas succeed each other accordincr 
 to a fixed law. As soon as this law is known, history 
 will cease to be a chaos, and become a science like jjhysics 
 and astronomy. Historical facts follow each other mid are 
 connected with the same necessity as Ijiological i)lifiioiiK'iia. 
 Formerly, one miglit have ])elieved that ciiiiu's and olTciices 
 vary considerably from year to yeai-, that chance and I'ree- 
 will are more ])reval('nt in tliis field than anywhere else. 
 But the statistics })ul)lis]ied by our govi-ninients prove 
 
 ■ TIk:; llirologicul sdiool, chiefly reprosented by Di- Hoiialil (17.")1- 
 1810) and Joseph do Maistn" (1753-181^1), opjioscs to individiial ri'u- 
 Bon the " universal n-itson," to human philosojdiy " (Ii\ in." )>hil(isopliy " 
 asset forth in tin* rcvcali-d (lo;,Mna, to tlic thcorifsof |iulitic;i! and leli 
 gious liheralisin the theocratic syst^-ni now callrd iiltra-nioutanisni.
 
 580 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the contrary. We must therefore insist upon the essential 
 notion that historical events, i. e., social phenomena, are, 
 like everything else, subject to fixed laws, and that super- 
 natural interventions play no part in the development of 
 societies. 
 
 When social ethics will have been raised to the rank of 
 positive science, that is, of science, — for positive science 
 alone is true science, — the totality of sciences, i. e., 
 philosophy, will be positive. Positive philosophy is no 
 longer a separate science, it is the synthesis, the systematic 
 co-ordination of human knowledge. Emanating from the 
 sciences, it does not differ from them in method : it em- 
 ploys the method of experience, supplemented by induc- 
 tion and deduction. Positive pliilosophy, moreover, is 
 philosophy in the true sense of the word, since it has for 
 its object the lohole of phenomena, the uiiiverse. It is the 
 business of positivism to study this totality, to unify the 
 entire field of human knowledge, to make the sciences phi- 
 losophical and philosophy scientific, to give the former the 
 unity they need, and the latter the prestige which it lost in 
 consequence of its recent indiscretions. 
 
 The reign of metaphysics is nearing its end. The reason 
 why the serious thinkers of the day are abandoning it is 
 plain : it never was a real science ; all it did, in ancient as 
 well as in modern times, was to turn out hypotheses after 
 hypotheses, having no stability whatsoever. The systems 
 which it brought forth antagonize each other in their very 
 principles. The history of the sciences represents a con- 
 tinuous advance : what is once acquired is retained for- 
 ever. In metaphj-sics, on the other hand, everything is in 
 a state of perpetual agitation and endless revolution. Meta- 
 physics has, undoubtedl}^, had its historical mission, and 
 has creditably discharged its task. It has demolished the 
 religions, and prepared the field for positive science. In 
 Greece, it overthrew the polytheistic faith and substi-
 
 POSITIVISM AND NEO-CRITICISM 681 
 
 tuted monotheism for it ; in the Clnistian worhl, it pro- 
 duced tlie heresies which, little by little, weakened and 
 disorganized the Catholic system. But this essentially 
 negative and critical task is now fultilled, and the futility 
 of its efforts of two thousand years, when compared with 
 the rapid and continuous advance of the sciences, clearly 
 proves that it is merely a transitory form in the history of 
 the human mind.^ 
 
 The preceding summary emhraces the philosophy of 
 Comte and Littrt^, excepting the political and sociological 
 doctrines of the Comtian system. A mixture of positivism, 
 mathematics, and humanitarian idealism, it exaggerates the 
 views represented in the eighteenth century by the Ency- 
 clopedia, and especially by the D'Alemberts, the Turgots, 
 and the Condorcets. Although the positivism of John 
 Stuart Mill ^ and Herbekt Spencer,^ which proceeds 
 
 1 Cours de la phUosophie positive, vol. VI., pp. Oto if. Little, Ana- 
 lyse raisonnee, pp. 55 ft'. 
 
 2 J, Stuart Mill (1800-1873) is the author of a Si/stein of Lor/ic, 
 Ratiocinative and Inductice, London, 1813 ft".: a capital work, which 
 aims to do for induction what Aristotle had already done for deductive 
 rea.soning, i. e., to reduce the inductive process (inference) to exact rules 
 and a scientific criterion. He also wrote : Examinallon of Sir William 
 Hamilton's Philosophy, 1805 [5th ed. 1878]; Comte and Posilirism, 1805; 
 \_Utilitarianism, 1S0:5; new ed., 1871; Nature, 1874 (posthumous); 
 Autobiography, 1873. Cf. Jevons's criticism, reprinted in Pure Logic, 
 London, 1890; A. Bain, John Stuart Mill, a Criticism, London, 1SS2; 
 H. Lauret, PhUosophie de St. Mill, Paris, 1886; C. Douglas,/. S. Mill; 
 a Study of his Philosophy, Edinl>urgh and London, 1805. See also 
 "Watson and the works montioned in next note. — Tij.] 
 
 8 Ilerhert Spencer (1>orn 1820) developed liis system, whose leadiup 
 conception is evolution (see § 00), in his [Social Statics, London, 1851, 
 2d ed., 1871; Principles of Psychology, 1855; 2(1 ed., 1872; 5tli ed., 
 1890; First Principles, 1862; 7tli ed., 1889; Principles of Biology, 1803- 
 1807; 4th ed., 1888; Principles of Sociology, vol. L, 1870; 3d ed., 1885; 
 vol. II., 1879-1885; Principles tf Ethics (\y,\rt I., The Data of Ethics, 
 1879; 0th ed., 1802; l)art II., The Inductions of Ethics, 1802; part III., 
 The Ethics <f Individual Life, 18:)2; part IV., Justice, ISOI). His
 
 582 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 from Hume, Locke, and Bacon, recognizes the merits of 
 Auguste Comte, it is not so bold as the latter's. More- 
 over, it does not indulge in the socialistic dreams of the 
 French philosopher. Its ontology strikes a liappy mean 
 between a trivial spiritualism and a vulgar materialism. 
 Besides, it remains, more strictly than the positivists 
 of France, within the limits assigned to S|)eculation by 
 the criticism of Hume and Kant, and carefully avoids 
 all philosophy of the absolute as contradictory of posi- 
 tivistic principles, not taking sides, ahsohUcUj, either 
 with materialism or with spiritualism, which, as meta- 
 physical systems, both transcend the boundaries of the 
 knowable. 
 
 For tliis moderate, practical, and truly English form of 
 positivism, there is nothing absolute even in determinism. 
 
 work on Education, published 1863, has passed through twenty-three 
 editions. Authorized Epitome of the Synthetic Philosophy, by F. H. 
 Collins, 1889. — Tr.] The " first " principles to which he reduces 
 everything, matter, motion, and force, are but " symbols of the un- 
 known reality," " a power of which the nature remains forever incon- 
 ceivable." The materialists call it matter, the spiritualists, mind: but 
 " their controversy is a mere war of words, in which the disputants 
 
 are equally absurd each thinking he understands that which it is 
 
 impossible for any man to understand." {First Principles, American 
 edition, Summary and Conclusion, p. 557.) [On Spencer, see : B. P. 
 Bowne, The Philosophy of H. Spencer, New York, 1874, also Wat- 
 son, and Green {Works, vol. I.). — Tr.] English positivism, which, 
 besides the thinkers just mentioned, is represented by Alexander 
 Bain {The Senses and the Intellect, 1856; 4th ed., 1894; The Emotions 
 and the Will, 1859; 3d ed., 1875 ; Menial and Moral Science, 1868; 3d 
 ed., 1872]; S. Bailey [The Theory of Reasnnincj, 1851 ; The Philosophy 
 of the Human Mind, 1855]; G. H. Lewes [Com/e's Philosophy, 1847,- 
 Problems of Life and Mind, 3d ed., 1874] ; Buckle [History of Cimli 
 zation in England, 1857-1860]. See H. Taine, Le positivisme anglais, 
 e'tude sur J. S. Mill, Paris, 1864, and Th. Ribot, La psychologie anglaise 
 contemporaine, 2d ed., 1875 [Engl, translation. New York, 1801]. [John 
 Fiske, Outlines of Cosmic Philosophy, New York, 1874 ff., is an Ameri- 
 can disciple of Herbert Spencer.]
 
 POSITIVISM AND NEO-CRITICISM 583 
 
 Determinism is, in its eyes, a hypothesis with which the 
 sciences cannot dispense, and which daily leads to new 
 advances, but a hypothesis none the less. Experience 
 shows us that facts succeed each other in regular order, 
 hut since it deals only with a small piece of the world and 
 with a short period of time, we cannot tell whether the 
 order in question is ahsolutehj uniform, and whether the 
 succession of the antecedent, which we call the cause, 
 and of the consequent, which we call the effect, is necessary 
 in the metaphysical sense. It is even conceivable that 
 there should be, in certain stellar regions, an entire absence 
 of laws of succession, and that absolute indeterminism 
 should prevail there. We may, according to the same 
 thinker, without proving untrue to the principles of posi- 
 tivism, assume an intelligent and free Creator. We can 
 never reach the absolute ; the relative alone belongs to us. 
 We consequently proceed as thour/h the law established by 
 observation and induction were immutable, as though the 
 order of facts were constant, as though the determinism of 
 phenomena were universal and absolute. That is to say, 
 we invariably proceed like the positive and experimental 
 sciences, whicli have no need to trouble themselves about 
 the absolute and lirst causes ; we merely wisli to sul^stitute 
 positive science for metaphysics, preferring to a science that 
 caZZs t7se// absolute, and that is in reality hollow and l)ar- 
 ren, a science that knows that it is relative, but gradually 
 brings nature under the sway of man and his industry, a 
 science that is useful and the source of all progress. 
 
 In Germany Neo-Kantianism or Neo-Criticism ^ corre- 
 
 1 Positivism also has its representatives in rioruiany. W<' may 
 consider as such : Knjjen DUhring, liorn l.s;{:5 (A- tempore, s/xitio, 
 causalitate, etc., Berlin, 1805; Krithche Gtschichle <ler P/iilosnpliit', [th 
 e<l., Leipsic, 1801; Curnus <kr Philosophie, ISTO; Loyik uud Wisscn- 
 schaftslehre, 1878; etc.); .1. II. von Kirchniami, 1802-1881, aiillior of 
 £1 HVstein wliidi he calls reaUsni, an<l which he sets fortli in a nunilicr
 
 584 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 spends to French and English positivism, which is inspired 
 by Hume and Condillac. Kant, who never ceased to have 
 disciples abroad,^ was neglected in liis own country and 
 almost thrown aside. Since 1860 the cry " Back to 
 Kant " 2 has become the watchword of a new school, the 
 principal leader of which is Albeht Lange,^ the eminent 
 author of the History of Materialism^ Lange is willing 
 to ao-ree with materialism as long as it does not presume 
 to be a system of metaphysics, but contents itself with 
 being a scientific method. Materialism, in other words, is 
 well-founded when it means mechanism, absolute negation 
 
 of writings (" thought and being have the same content, but differ in 
 form ") [Die Philosophie des Wissens, Berlin, 1864] ; Ernst Laas, 1836- 
 1885 {Idealismus und Positivlsmus, 3 parts, Berlin, 1879-84) ; etc. 
 Positivism or German realism differs from Neo-Criticism in that it 
 assumes the objective reality of space, time, matter, and does not, 
 like many Neo-Kantians, incline to Schopenhauer's pessimism. Diih- 
 ring, particularly, "the philosopher of reality " (Wirklichkeitsphilosoph), 
 is both dogmatic (in opposition to Albert Lange, Liebmann, etc.) and 
 optimistic (in opposition to Ed. von Hartmann). 
 
 1 The most deserving of these disciples is Charles Renouvier, 
 author of JSIanuels de pJiihsophie ancienne et moderne (p. 14, note 4) ; 
 Essals de critique ge'ne'rcde, 4 vols., Paris, 18.54-64 ; Science de la morale, 
 2 vols., Saint-Cloud, 1869, etc ; and, from 1872-1889, editor of the 
 Critique philosophique, politique, scierttijique, lilteraire, a worthy rival of 
 the Revue philoxophique of Th. Ptibot. Unlike German Neo-Criticism, 
 which ascribes only a secondary importance to the ethics of the mas 
 ter, Renouvier regards it as the key-stone of the Kantian system. 
 [The Anne'e philosophique, founded in 1890 by Francois Pillon, and 
 edited with the cooperation of the veteran Renouvier, is the able 
 successor of the Critique. — Tr.] 
 
 2 [Otto Liebmann concludes each chapter of his work, Kant und 
 die Epigonen, Stuttgart, 1865, with the refrain : Also 7)iuss auf Kant 
 zuriicl-gegangen werden (hence we must go back to Kant). — Tr.] 
 
 3 1828-1875. Professor at Marburg. 
 
 * [Iserlohn, 1866 ; 4th (popular) ed. (without index and notes), 
 Iserlohn, 1882; 5th ed., ed. by H. Cohen, Leipsic, 1896 ; Engl, transl. 
 by E. C. Thomas, 3 vols., London, 1878-81 ; Logische Studien, 1877. 
 -Tr.]
 
 POSITIVISM AXD NEO-CRITICISM 585 
 
 of final causes. But, he aikls, materialism becomes an 
 illusion and an error as soon as it professes to be a solution 
 of the ontological problem, an explanation of the ultimate 
 essence of things. What is matter ? An idea and nothing 
 more, a representation of the mind ( VorstellungsUld)^ 
 Avhich, we imagine, corresponds to an objective reality, an 
 ens ill se. But between this idea and this reality, there is 
 a gulf which nothing, absolutely nothing, can bridge over. 
 Nay, more than that. In so far as we know matter only 
 as an idea (_ which is in us), idealism, and not materialism, 
 is true. Furthermore, idealism has its undeniable raison 
 d'etre in the fact that it is inchspensable to human life and 
 happiness. The ideal and metaphysics retain all their 
 lights ; but, like religion and art, they have their rights 
 ly the side of science, not in science. Science — as Kant 
 has demonstrated unquestionably and for all times to come 
 — cannot reach the thing-in-itself, the absolute. Let phi- 
 losophy, therefore, frankly and definitively abandon meta- 
 physics, and confine itself to the sphere of the knowable, 
 that is, facts. Onl}' upon this condition will it become what 
 it ceased to be in the hands of Kant's successors : science. 
 
 Neo-Criticism, we see, forms but a part of Kantianism. 
 It is the Kantianism of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kantr 
 ianism minus the categorical imperative and the postulates 
 of practical reason, i. e., scepticism in metaphysics, or, as 
 we should say in France, Positivism. 
 
 Around the standard of Positivism, freed from tlie par- 
 ticular ideas of Comte, and Neo-Criticism are gathered most 
 of the scientific and literary celebrities of our time : men 
 like Claude Bernard,^ E. Du Bois-Keymond,^ H. Helm- 
 
 J 1813-1878. 
 
 * [Born 1818.] Uehcr die Grenzen des Nnlurerkennens (On the 
 Limits of iJifi Knowledge of Nature), Berlin, 1872; 7tli ed., 1801; [Die 
 sit'hfin Wellrdth.iel {The Seven World-riddles), Berlin, 1880; liolli in his 
 Reden uud Au/sdtze, 188"J.] Ills iiHjttcj is: hjnoramus et iynondiimus.
 
 586 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 HOLTZ,^ VIRCHO^Y,2 W. WuNDT,^ H. Taine,* E. Renan,^ 
 
 ScH^REB.^ Their pliilosopliy, wliicli we may call the ^3osi- 
 tivisme dcs savants,"^ is realistic in so far as it is based solely 
 on reality, on facts, on observation and experience ; ideal- 
 istic, in so far as it recognizes that the reality accessible to 
 
 1 See p. 563, note 5. 2 See p. 563, note 4. 
 
 8 [Born 1832. Vorlesungen Uher die Menschen und T/uerseele, Leip- 
 sic, 1863 ; 2d ed., 1892 ; Engl. tr. by J. E. Creighton and E. B. Titch- 
 ener {Human and Animal Psychology), New York, 1895] ; Grundzuge der 
 phy^iologischen Psychologie, 2 vols., 1873-74; [4th ed., 1893]; Logik, 2 
 vols., Stuttgart, 1880-83; [2d ed., 1893]; Essays, 1885; Elhlk, Stutt- 
 gart, 1886 ; [2d ed., 1892]; System der FkUosophie, 1889. In this last 
 work, one of the most important to appear in recent years, Wilhelra 
 Wundt shows himself in a new and unexpected light. He concedes to 
 metaphysics its raison d'etre and the rank which belongs to it in the 
 hierarchy of sciences, provided it be empirical and positive. His system 
 is not, however, one of those innovations which claim to be raised upon 
 the ruins of the past, but a vast scientific synthesis and a happy at- 
 tempt at a reconciliation of the rival doctrines of modern speculation. 
 The whole work is conceived in that elevated, moderate, conciliatory, 
 and impersonal spirit that characterizes the true philosopher. The 
 psychologist of Leipsic is also, let us add, a decided adherent of volun- 
 tarism. (See § 71.) \_Grundriss der Psychologie, Leipsic, 1896.] 
 
 * [1828-1893.] De V intelligence, 2 vols., 1870 ; 2ded., 1882 ; [Engl, 
 tr by Haye, 1871.] 
 
 6 [1823-1892.] La reforme intellectuelle et morale, 2d ed., Paris, 
 1872; PhilosopMe de I'art, 2d ed., 1872; Dialogues et fragments philoso- 
 pJiiques, 1876 ; [Engl tr., 1883; Vie de Jesus, 1863; Engl. tr. by Wil- 
 bour.] 
 
 6 1815-1889. See, especially, the Introduction to Melanges d'histoire 
 religieuse, 2d ed., Paris, 186.5. 
 
 ^ Its organs are : the Revue philosophique of Th. Ribot (the distin- 
 guished psychologist and author of La psychologie anglaise conlempo- 
 raine, 1875, La psychologie allemande contemporaine, 1879, Uheredite 
 psychologique, 2d ed., 1882; [translations of these and other works of 
 Eibot published by the Open Court Publishing Co., Chicago] ; the 
 Zeitschrift fur icissenschaftliche PhilosopMe of Avenarius ; the Rivista di 
 filosofa scientifica; Mind, a Quarterly Review of PsT/chology and Philoso^ 
 phy ; [the Monist of Paul Carus, Fundamental Problems, 2ded., Chicago, 
 1893 ; The Soul of Man, etc.] ; etc.
 
 CONCLUSION 587 
 
 human consciousness is, in the last analysis, merely phe- 
 nomenal, that the facts are, after all, only our ideas, con- 
 sidered as signs or symbols of a reality unknowable in 
 itself. 
 
 § 71. Conclusion 
 
 Although positivistic monism is the dominant feature 
 of the pliilosophy of the nineteenth century, spiritualism 
 ha-s been struggling valiantly, since the days of Reid, to 
 hold its own. Kant, who pitilessly destroyed it in his 
 Critique of Pure licason, calls it back to life in his moral 
 postulates, and, ultimately, renders it a signal service. F. 
 H. Jacobi,^ whom Ave found among the opponents of the 
 Critique, defends spiritualism against the pantheism of 
 Spinoza, Schelling, and Hegel, by appealing to the inner 
 sense. The theologian and philosopher Schleiermacher,^ 
 although an enthusiastic Spinozist, indirectly advances the 
 spiritualistic cause by his appeal to religious feeling (das 
 fromme Gefilhl) and the "awakening" which it tends to 
 produce.^ Christian F. Krause,* a thinker of great merit, 
 
 1 See § 63. 
 
 * 17f!8-lS:M. A disciple of Spinoza (thonsli an original disciple, 
 like Herder), Scheierniach -^r attempts, especially in liis ethics, to 
 reconcile the monism of the master with the principle of individual 
 spontaneity, by substituting for the abstract idea of unity the concrete 
 principle of harmony. His theory of knowledge, as set forth in the 
 first part of his Dlalekllk, is likewise a happy attempt to reconcile the 
 nihil in inlelledu of the pure sensationalists and the nihil in senxu of 
 Fichte and Ilegel. [Complete works, Herlin, 1835-04. lietlcn iiher 
 die Religion, etc., 1709 ; Kng. tv. by J. Oman, London, 18!>3 ; Afonnloffcn, 
 IbOO; Grundriss der philosophischen Ethik; ed. by A. Twesten, 18U.] 
 
 ' The essence of religion is, according to him, the feeling of de- 
 pendence on the infinit<i. 
 
 * 1781-183-J. Grundlage des A^a/un-fcA/.s -Tena, 1803 ; Entwiirf dcs 
 Systems der Philosophic, Jena, 1801; System drr Sitlrnlehre, Leijisic, 
 1810; [2ded., 1HS7]; etc. Krause's stylf, wliich is often unintelligi- 
 ble, greatly retarded the success of his philitsophy. 'I'Ih- following were 
 his adherents : tlie (jlerman Ahrens (died in Leipsic, 187 1), author of
 
 588 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 but unappreciated in his own country, substitutes for pan- 
 theism loancntheism^ or the doctrine of the immanency of 
 things in God, considered as a transcendent personality and 
 yet united in substance with the creature. Christian H. 
 Weisse,! Immaxuel Hermann Fichte,^ a son of the 
 celebrated philosopher, Hermann Ulrici, J. U. WniTH, 
 MoRiTZ Carriere,^ H. M. Chalybaeus,* opposed to this 
 doctrine the system of speculative theism. A. Trendelen- 
 burg,^ inspired by the teleology of Aristotle, teaches a sys- 
 tem of metaphysics, whose leading thought is the idea of 
 movement, the common essence of thought and being. 
 Schelling, in his later stage, Christoffer Jacob Bos- 
 TROM 6 of Upsala, Herjuann Lotze," Gustav Fechxer,^ 
 
 Corns de pJiilosophie, Paris, 1836-38; Cows de droit naturel ou philoso- 
 phle du droit, Paris, 1838; Cows de philosophie de Phistoire, Brussels, 
 184:0 ; the Belgian Tiberghien, author of Essai theorique et pratique sur 
 la generation des connaissances humaines, Paris and Leipsic, 1844; 
 Esquisse de pJiilosophie morale, Brussels, 1854 ; Logique, Paris, 1865 ; the 
 Frenchman Boueliitte, author of tlie article on Krause in the Diction- 
 naire des sciences pJiilosophiques ; the Spaniard J. S. del Rio, who trans- 
 lated several of his works ; etc. Krause has to this day many dis- 
 ciples in Spain. 
 
 1 1801-1866. Die Idee der Gottheit, Dresden, 1833 ; Grundzuge der 
 Metaphysik, Hamburg, 1835 ; etc. 
 
 2 1797-1879. Spekulative Theologie, Heidelberg, 1846-47 ; System 
 der Ethik, Leipsic, 1850-53 ; etc. 
 
 * These three, together with Weisse and the younger Fichte, found- 
 ed the Zeitschrift fiir Philosophie wid philosophische Kritik. They are 
 writers of note. 
 
 * [1792-1862.] System der speculativen Ethik, 2 vols., Leipsic, 1850; 
 etc. 
 
 ' 1802-1872. Professor at Berlin, and author of Logische Unter- 
 suchungen, 2 vols., 3d ed., Berlin, 1870 ; etc. 
 
 ^ On Bostrom and Scandinavian philosophy see the sketch of K. R. 
 Geijer in Ueberweg's History of Philosophy, 7th ed., § 49, pp. 536 ff. 
 
 '' See p. 542, note 2. 
 
 8 1801-1887. The founder of psycho-physics, or the science of the 
 mathematical relations of physics and psychology; author of Ueher
 
 CONCLUSION 589 
 
 Charles Secretan,^ Erxest Naville,^ and, within 
 Catholic circles, Franz Baader,-^ Lamennais,*^ BAUTiUN,^ 
 
 das hochste Gut, Leipsic, 1816; Nanjia oder uber das Seelenleben der 
 PJlanze, lSi8; Zendavesta, 1851; Elemente der Psychophysik, 18G0 ; 
 Die drei Motive und Grilnde des Glaubens, 1863 ; Die Tagesansicht ije- 
 geniiber der Naclitansicht, 1879 ; \_Da$ Buddein com Leben nach dem Tode, 
 1836 ; 3d ed., 1887. Friedrich Paulsen, born 1846, teaches a system 
 of metaphysics similar to Fechner's in his Einhituny in die Philoi^opkie, 
 Berlin, 1891 ; 4th ed., 1895 ; Engl. tr. by Frank Thilly, Xew York, 
 1895]. 
 
 1 Philosophie de la libert,', 2d ed., 1872 ; Recherche de la methode ; 
 Pre'cis de philosophie, etc. The Philosophy of Liberty is the boldest at- 
 tempt at a speculative construction of the dogma of moral freedom 
 which has been made since the days of Schelling. 
 
 2 Publisher of the posthumous works of Maine de Biran, and author 
 of : La vie e'ternelle, Geneva, 1861 ; Le probleine du mat, 1868; Le devoir, 
 1868, etc. 
 
 * 1765-1841. Professor in ]\Iunich ; a disciple of Bbhme, to whose 
 theosophy he introduced his friend and colleague Schelling. Ilis 
 complete works have been published by his zealous adherent, Franz 
 Hoffmann, in 16 vols., Leipsic, 1851-60. 
 
 * 1782-185 L Esquisse d''une philosophie, 4 vols., Paris, 1841—46. lu 
 this masterpiece of speculative theology, the abbe de Lamennais, in- 
 spired by the Xeo-Platonic and Schellingian theory of emanation, con- 
 ceives creation as the unfolding, in space and time, of the divine unity 
 and its infinite content. It is, on the part of the absolute being, an 
 eternal act of immolation and sacrifice, by which God, who is force or 
 power, form or intelligence, and life or love, gives his very substance 
 to his creatures, according to a progression in which the complexity 
 and unity go on increasing, from the nebular ether to the intelligent 
 and free being. And just as the divine life is a perpetual sacrifice, 
 each creature dies in order to transmit its life to other creatures. Each 
 is nourished by all, and all are nourished Ijy God. Ileraclitus (§ 8) 
 had said before him : " Mortals live the life of the gods, and the gods 
 the life of mortals." 
 
 8 1796-1807. Professor and canon at Strasburg, and, since 1819, 
 Vicar-General of the diocese of Paris. His system is contained in: 
 La philosophic dn rhrislianisrne, 2 vols., Strasburg, 1833; La philosophie 
 morale, 2 V(j1s , Paris, 1852 ; and L'esprit huiii'iin I't si's fnriilli's, 2 vols., 
 Paris, 1859. Unlike Lamennais, the alibe IJautain, who was at first 
 liberal, unreservedly submits to the dogma of the Church.
 
 590 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Gkatry,^ Rosmini,2 Gioberti,^ Froschammer,* and many 
 others, attempt to reconcile the spiritualistic faith and the 
 monistic instinct of reason by means of syntheses greatly 
 resembling the panentheism of Krause. 
 
 In the chairs of the University of France, where Condil- 
 lac reigned suj^reme until the Imperial period,^ Cartesian 
 spiritualism again came into vogue about the year 1815, 
 and found brilliant interpreters in Royer-Collard,^ 
 Maine de Biran,'^ Victor Cousin,^ Theodore Joue- 
 
 1 1805-1872. Professor at the Sorbonne. Logique, Paris, 1856 ; 
 La morale et la loi de I'hhtoire, 1868, etc. 
 
 2 1797-1855. Nuovo saggio sulV origine delle idee, Rome, 1830 [tr. 
 into English, 1883-84], and Turin, 1855; Principle della scienza morale, 
 Milan, 1831-37; Rome, 1868; Teosojia, vols. I. to V. of Rosmini's 
 posthumous works, Tm'in, 1859-7-1. 
 
 3 1801-1852. Inlroduzione alio studio della Jilosojia, Brussels, 1840 ; 
 Filosofia della revelazione, Turin, 1856 ; Protologia, Turin, 1857 ; etc. 
 On Rosmini and Gioberti see Ad. Franck, La philosophie italienne, 
 Journal des Savants, 1871 and 1872. 
 
 * [Born 1821.] Die Phantasie als Grundprincip des Weltprocesses, 
 Munich, 1877. 
 
 ^ The chief representatives of his philosophy during this epoch 
 are : Cabanis (§ 60) ; Voluey (1757-1820), CEucres completes, 2d ed., 
 Paris, 1836 ; Destutt de Tracy (1754-1836), iSle'ments d'ide'ologie, Paris, 
 1801-15, Commentaire sur l' Esprit des lois de Montesquieu, Paris, 1819 ; 
 Laromiguiere, Lemons de philosophie ou essai sur les facultes de I'dme, 
 Paris, 1815-18. The latter anticipates the spiritualistic reaction, by 
 introducing into traditional psychology the principle of attention and 
 spontaneity, thereby agreeing with Maine de Biran. 
 
 6 1763-1845. 
 
 ' CEuvres, published by V. Cousin, 4 vols., 1840, and completed by 
 Naville and Debrit, 3 vols., 1859. He is, unquestionably, the most 
 profound among the leaders of the French-Scotch school. He is a 
 representative of voluntarism and concrete spii'itualism, and opposed 
 
 8 1792-1867. Councillor of State, Member of the Royal Council 
 of Public Instruction, Professor at the Sorbonne, Member of the In- 
 stitute, Director of the Normal School, Peer of France, and in addi-
 
 CONCLUSION 591 
 
 FROY.^ The spiritualistic school, which draws its inspira- 
 tion from Descartes, Leihniz, and, especiall}-, from Reid, 
 bases philosophy on psychology, and psychology on inner 
 observation. Besides having enriched the history of phi- 
 
 to the rationalistic and dualistic pliilosopliy of V. Cousin. As adher- 
 ents of M. de Biran we mention Felix Ravaisson (Essai sur la Meta- 
 physique d'Aristote, 2 vols., Paris, 1837 and 1846; Rapport sur la phi- 
 losophie fran(:aise au dix-neuvieme siecle, Paris, 18G8 and 18S.")) and his 
 disciples, Jules Lachelier {Du fondement de Vinduclion, coiirs ine'dits de 
 psycliulogie, logiqiie, morale, Iheodice'e, pro/esses d VEcole normale supe- 
 j-ieure) and Emile Boutroux (Z)e la conlingence des lois de la nature, 
 Paris, 1874). Ravaisson, Lachelier, and Boutroux oppose to the 
 " denii-spiritualisui of the eclectic school " the " true spiritualism, 
 that which regards even matter as immaterial, and explains nature 
 itself by mind " (Ravaisson's Rapport, etc., p. 142). 
 
 1 1790-1842. Melanges, 1833; 1842; Cours de droit naturel, 1835; 
 etc. Jouffroy, one of the most attractive representatives of the 
 school, was especially influenced by Reid, whose works he translated. 
 Among his disciples and successors, we must mention, in the first 
 rank, the present leader of French spiritualism, Paul Janet {Le mate- 
 rialisme contemporain en Allemagne, 1864; [Kngl. tr., German Materi- 
 alism, etc., by G. Masson, London, 1866]; La arise philosophiijue, 1865; 
 Le cerveau el la pensde, 1807; Elements de morale, 1869; [Engl. tr. 
 by Corson, 1884]; Histoire de la science politique dans ses rapports avec 
 la morale, 3d ed., 1887; [La morale, 1874; Engl. tr. by Mary Cliap- 
 man, London, 1883]; Les causes finales, 2d ed., 1882 ; [Engl. tr. by 
 Affleck, London, 1883] ; etc. [On tliis entire school see A. Franck, 
 Moralistes et philosophes, 1872; 2d od., 1871.] 
 
 tion to all this " mode'rateur tmit-pmssant de Venseignement philosopfiique" 
 in the University, under the reign of Louis-Philippe. Cours de I'/iis- 
 loire de la philosophie modeme, first series (1815-20); second series 
 (1828-30); Fragments pliilosojdiiques, 1820; 5th ed., 1806 (5 vols.); 
 etc. — V, Cousin, wlio was a zealous adliercnt of (Jerniau pliilosopliy 
 during his earlier p<-riod, did not really teach a tliorougli-goiiig spirit- 
 ualism until he reached his official stage. See on Cousin a li'Mglliy 
 article in the second edition of tlu^ Dictionuaire des scirnres jdii- 
 losophiques, and on his relation to (lenuan philosophy and especially 
 to Hegel, a series of articles by Janet in the /if cue des Drnx-Mondes.
 
 f 
 
 592 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 losophy with a great number of magnificent works,^ it has 
 the merit of liaving explained, in the acute analyses of Maine 
 de Biran, the important role played by the will, a fact which 
 the sensationalistic school fails to recognize. But while 
 German spiritualism makes the serious mistake of assign- 
 ing to the imagination too exalted a place in its specula- 
 tions, and even shows a willingness to compromise with 
 American spiritism, eclecticism, — the name given to 
 French spiritualism by V. Cousin, — errs in sacrificing too 
 much to rhetoric, and in not sufficiently taking into account 
 the two factors which philosophy cannot neglect with im- 
 punity : positive science and its monistic principle.^ 
 
 Some of its contemporaneous representatives, particu- 
 larly the ablest among them, frankly acknowledge the 
 justice of these criticisms. The pronounced advance of 
 positivistic and materialistic philosophy is due to its close 
 alliance with the physical and natural sciences. In order 
 to combat it we must recognize the elements of truth it 
 contains ; we must assimilate it, absorb it, as Hegel would 
 say, in order to overcome it. Now, positivism is unques- 
 tionably in the right when it declares the age of " romance- 
 metaphysics," a-priorism, and fancy to be at an end. By 
 subjecting philosophy to the methods of science, positivism 
 deprives it of a prerogative which has no raison d'etre in the 
 present state of human development. Only on condition 
 
 ^ To the names already mentioned we may add those of Francisque 
 Bouillier, Haure'au, Matter, Willm, Remusat, Damiron, Saisset, Bar- 
 tholmess, Jules Simon, Nourrisson, Bartlielemy-Saint-Hilaire, Ad. 
 Franck, Ch. Waddington, Caro, Alaux, Ferraz, etc. For Vacherot, 
 whose idealism differs essentially from the eclectic doctrines, see p. 
 533, note 1. 
 
 2 Eclecticism was opposed from different and even opposite points 
 of view, by Bordas-Demoulin {Leitre sur V eclecticisme et le doctrinarisme, 
 Paris, 1834), Pierre Leroux {Refutation de V eclecticisme, 1839), Taine 
 {Les pMlosophes class ifjues fr/mcais du XIX. siecle, 1857; 3d ed., 1868), 
 Secretan (La philosophie de V. Cousin, 1868), etc.
 
 CONCLUSION 593 
 
 that it proceed scientifically can pliilosopliy, temporarily 
 separated from the sciences, regain its former high rank 
 among the branches of human knowledge. 
 
 In our opinion, positivism errs in that it makes science 
 purely utilitarian, or discrowns it, so to speak, by denying 
 to the human mind all knowledge of objects and the essence 
 of things, all metaphysical capacity. It is true, philosophy 
 must identify itself with science in its methods and final 
 goal. But take note that every science, worthy of the 
 name, is the search for a system of laws, principles, or 
 causes, i. e., a search for the universal, sometliing supe- 
 rior to the phenomenon, a suprasensible reality, in a word, 
 a /xera<f)V(nK6v. Hence, every serious science is a partial 
 metaphysic, and philosophy is really a general metaphysic, 
 a metaphysic of the universe. It is furthermore true that 
 knowledge is relative, and that the thiny-in-itself (the 
 term introduced by criticism) is never known ; but this re- 
 lation is evidently determined hy the nature of the thing 
 hiown as well as by our intellectual organization. And 
 finally, experience, joined with speculation, is, without 
 doubt, the indispensable basis of all positive knowledge. 
 But experience, the reasoned study of facts, outer and inner 
 observation, gives us, if not an absolutely clear view, at 
 least a glimpse, of the essence of things ; that is, it arrives 
 gradually, and not at once, at metapliysical conclusions which 
 justify or refute the intuitions of speculative philosophy. 
 
 Ignoring this threefold truth, itositivism is absolutely 
 sceptical of all hvpotheses concerning the first and final 
 causes of the world. It confuses two entirely dilTerent 
 things: dualism, a passing form of Iniiiiaii tliouglit. and 
 metaphysics, its permanent and legitimate go;d. It tails to 
 see that its protest against metai)hysics at the same time 
 attacks tlie very sciences wliich it pretends to substitute for 
 metsipliysics. If this protest were just, then ].liysics, cliem- 
 istry, the natural iuid moral seiences, wouM all have to give 
 
 38
 
 594 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 up formulating universal theories ; for every scientific 
 tlieory is a relatively a priori hypothesis, so long as new 
 facts may be adduced to contradict it, and as this possibility 
 always exists, the most firmly established scientific theory 
 cannot lay claim to the dignity of an axiom. After a the- 
 ory has been confirmed by a great mass of facts, it acquires 
 a certain stability and a relative certitude which is prac- 
 tically equivalent to absolute certitude. Positivism over- 
 looks the fact that the same holds true of philosophy ; it 
 forgets that, though absolute certainty concerning the first 
 causes of the universe is impossible, we can at least attain 
 to a degree of relative certainty, or probability, which is, 
 practically, equal to absolute certainty. 
 
 One phase of the history of metaphysics, the a-prioristic, 
 intuitive, poetic period, is gone, — gone never to return, 
 but metaphysics itself still remains, and its interests, as we 
 have just seen, coincide with those of science. 
 
 To the argument of positivism that metaphj^sics is in a 
 state of endless change, we oppose the entire history just 
 outlined by us. If anything has changed and continually 
 changes, it is the hypotheses of physics, chemistry, and 
 phj^siology ; and if anything has remained in agreement 
 with itself, for more than two thousand years, it is meta- 
 physics. The great h}^otheses of the unity, continuity, 
 and immortality of being, existed prior to Plato and Aris- 
 totle, and constitute tlie immutable substance, as it were, 
 of ancient and modern speculation. 
 
 To the argument drawn from the perpetual disagreement 
 of philosophers, we answer that the historian of metaphysics 
 is most impressed with the open or tacit agreement ex- 
 isting- between rival movements and schools. We have 
 discovered such agreement between Plato and Democritus, 
 Descartes and Bacon, Leibniz and Schopenhauer, Herbart 
 and Hesrel. We have seen how the idealist Plato assumes 
 the eternity of the fjit} ov, and the materialist Democritus
 
 CONCLUSION 695 
 
 proclaims the principle that everytliin<jj in nature has its 
 reason for existing ; we have observed that the intellec- 
 tualist Descartes agrees with the head of the empirical 
 school in protesting against the application of teleology to 
 physics ; we have shown that the atomist Herbart assumes 
 a tii-st cause, and that Hegel, his antipode, considers the 
 atom as a necessary form of being ; that Leibniz, the opti- 
 mist, and Schopenhauer, the pessimist, both teach that 
 "effort" is the essence of things. 
 
 This agreement would be even more complete, were it 
 not for the subjective elements wliich play an essential part 
 in tlie formation of systems. Take away from each that 
 wliich is the result of the circumstances under which it 
 was produced, the self-love of the philosoplier, his desire to 
 be original, all the particular, accidental, and fortuitous 
 elements due to his nationality and individual character; 
 take away, above all, the numberless misconceptions occa- 
 sioned by the imperfections of philosophical language, — 
 and you will find, at the l^ottom of all these theories, one 
 and the same fundamental theme, one and the same phi- 
 losophy, one and the same system, to the construction of 
 which each pliilosopher adds his share. Even wliere the 
 dLsagreement between the thiidvcrs is real, it is not abso- 
 lute. Among the ancients as well as among the moderns, 
 the following are the essential (piestions at stake: Has tlie 
 universe one or many causes, a conscious or an unconscious 
 cause? What is the origin of oui- knowledge, and the true 
 phih>sopliical mctliod? Is metaphysics jiossible? On these 
 important, ontological, metliodological, and critical (pics- 
 tions, philosophers are divided into monists and pliiialists, 
 spiritualists and materialists, idealists or rationalists and 
 sensationalists or empiricists, dogmatists and sceptics. How- 
 ever, none of these systems lias ever l)een so raijiial as not 
 to take into account, in a certain measure, the contrary 
 teaching.
 
 1^ 
 
 596 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 To begin with ; lias there ever been a monistic or plu- 
 ralistic system in the absolute sense of the word ? We can 
 deny it without fear of being contradicted by history. The 
 most characteristic monistic systems are, in antiquity: 
 Eleatism and Neo-Platonism ; in modern times : Spinozism 
 and the philosophies of Fichte and Hegel. Well, we have 
 seen how Parmenides was obliged to concede, at the very 
 least, an apparent plurality of individual beings ; we have 
 seen how Empedocles divided his " Great Being," on the 
 one hand, into two co-eternal rival principles: love and 
 hate ; on the other, into four irreducible elements ; we have 
 seen that Platonism recognizes, by the side of the Idea, a 
 fir] 6v co-eternal with the plastic principle ; we have seen 
 that Spinoza discovers in his "one and indivisible sub- 
 stance " two " attributes," i. e., two things that cannot be 
 reduced into terms of each other : extension and thought. 
 Finally, the most radical among modern monists, Fichte and 
 Hegel, begin by proclaiming, — the former, the identity of 
 the ego and the non-ego ; the latter, the absoluteness of 
 reason, and subsequently confess, reluctantly, no doubt, 
 (1) that the non-ego remains for reason an insurmountable 
 obstacle; (2) that there is, in nature, alongside of the 
 rational element, an illogical, contingent element, which 
 presupposes a principle different from reason. Hence, even 
 the most decided monists advance a relative dualism. 
 
 Conversely, we have ascertained that the most charac- 
 teristic pluralistic systems acknowledge the relative truth 
 of monism. Democritus affirms the qualitative identity of 
 atoms, and his pluralism is merely a plural monism. Leib- 
 niz connects his " windowless " monads by means of " pre- 
 established harmony," which, in his system, represents the 
 monistic principle, and his philosophy too is, vdtimately, 
 nothing but a plural monism, since all of his monads have 
 the same essence : perception and striving. By insisting 
 on the unity of substance in the universe, on the unity
 
 CONCLUSION 597 
 
 of forces, on the unity of la^^•s, does not contemporaneous 
 atomism clearly betray its monistic or unitary preposses- 
 sions? Hence, the most rigorous x)luralists advance a 
 relative monism. 
 
 Between materialism, which recognizes no invisible real- 
 ities except atoms and inlinite space, and spiritualism, 
 wliich adds to the universe a transcendent order of things, 
 we have : Ionian hylozoism, which regards the cosmic sub- 
 stiince itself as intelligence, wisdom, reason, and harmony ; 
 Peripateticism, which affii'ms both the transcendency and 
 the immanency of the absolute ; Stoicism and its divine 
 world-soul ; and modern Pantheism, which distinguishes 
 between thought and apperception, and conceives God 
 either as will (panthelism), or as impersonal reason (panlo- 
 gism), which manifests itself in the world and becomes 
 conscious of itself in the human personality. And take 
 note of this fact ! With a few rare exceptions, the leaders 
 of European })hilo8ophy are not to be found among the 
 pure materialists, or in the camp of the spiritualists ; we 
 must look for them between the two camps. 
 
 We have seen, in the controversy concerning the origin 
 of ideas, that Leibniz, the defender of the theory of innate- 
 ness, and Locke, the champion of sensationalism, are much 
 more closely related than they tliemselves suspect ; neither 
 assuming anything to be innate but the faculty of formiiuj 
 ideas ; we have seen liow Kant sides with both of them, 
 by showing that the matter of all our perceptions is fur- 
 nished l)y the senses, and that the form of «//, witliout 
 exception, is tlie product of the sensible subject, the effect 
 of tlie particular constitution of llie mind: a syntliesia 
 whicli physiology and psychology ten<l more and more to 
 conlirm.^ 
 
 When we consider the question of nittliod, wliich is in- 
 timately connected with the preceding, we lind the same 
 ' See especially Ileliiilioltz, Phijsiolo(jische Optik, p. loO.
 
 598 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 tacit (and most frequently unconscious) agreement between 
 the rival views. Aristotle, Descartes, and Leibniz are sci- 
 entists of the highest order ; Bacon, Locke, and Hume are 
 eminent reasoners. No intellectualist, not even excepting 
 Fichte liiMiself, has ever seriously denied that an empirical 
 datum is, actually, the starting-point of a 2Jriori specula- 
 tion ; no empiricist has ever, actually^ repudiated deductive 
 reasoning. 
 
 And it is important to note, in conclusion, that, since 
 the overtlu'ow of Hegelianism, competent thinkers are 
 becoming more and more agreed as to method. This ques- 
 tion will no longer interest the future. Philosophy is 
 subject to the common law. Henceforth its methods are 
 those of science : speculative observation, deduction based 
 on facts, and induction. The distinction wliich Hegel 
 draws between the philosophical and the non-philosophical 
 sciences, is no longer recognized in our times. Every sci- 
 ence is necessarily philosopliical, every philosophy, worthy 
 of the name, necessarily scientific. We fully understand at 
 present, that, as Bacon excellently expresses it, the im- 
 portant thing is not so much to know the abstract opinions 
 of men, as the nature of things. Under the influence of 
 this view, the mania for original systems will gradually 
 disappear. Progress in philosophy consists less in the pro- 
 duction of new hypotheses than in the empirical demonstra- 
 tion of the true hypotheses wliich European metaphysics 
 has bequeathed to us, and in the refutation, likewise em- 
 pirical, of its errors. The personalities of the pliilosophers, 
 their great and little ^ambitions, their individual hkes and 
 dislikes, all of which played an ail-too important part in the 
 history of pliilosophy, especially during the first half of the 
 nineteenth century, will gradually lose in influence, and 
 theories will ultimately depend on the facts and on the 
 facts alone. Henceforth philosophy will be what Bacon, 
 Descartes, Locke, and Kant desired it to be : a science, —
 
 CONCLUSION 599 
 
 the highest science. Comtian positivism has the merit of 
 having contribnted liberally to these results. 
 
 Though more violent and radical in appearance, the op- 
 position between the dogmatists and sceptics is by no means 
 an absolute one. All the systems of Greece reveal a more 
 or less pronounced tinge of scepticism, Avliile Hellenic 
 scepticism culminates in a form of probabilism ^^•llieh 
 amounts to relative dogmatism. In modern times we see 
 how the type of metaphysical dogmatism, the system of 
 Leibniz, ends with a question-mark : Since the monad has 
 no " windows/' how can it know that which is not itself ? 
 And on the other hand, the fearless destroyer of traditional 
 metaphysics, Immanuel Kant, had no sooner completed his 
 work of destruction than he wrote his Prolegomena to evert/ 
 Future Metaphysics^ his Mctajjhysics of Nature^ and his Meta- 
 phi/sics of Morals. Positivism itself, though asserting that 
 metaphysics is a chimera, is tlie intimate all}' of material- 
 ism, i. e., a system of metaphysics, and thus involuntarily 
 furnishes the proof ad homiucm of the legitimacy, nay of 
 the inevitable necessity, of an ontology, the final goal and 
 highest reward of the labors of the scientist. 
 
 Does that mean that materialism is the culmination of 
 European philosophy and human knowledge ? It is true, 
 this system is supported b\- facts when it claims that an 
 intimate relation exists between inner perception and the 
 regular functions of the brain ; it lias for it the autliority 
 of reason when it proclaims the essential unity of things 
 and the principle of universal causality, tliat is, in a word, 
 monism ; but it is like idealism, its opposite. It has tlie 
 appearance of a universal synthesis, but explains only one- 
 half of tliat which it pretends to explain. We have seen 
 wliat insurmountabli! obstacles confront all idealistic think- 
 ers in llicir attempts to ])ass iVniii tlic ideal to tlie iral. 
 Plat<» succeeded in the acc(»nij»lishnient of this task, only 
 by sacrificing absolute idealism, and inleipolating the liy-
 
 600 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 pothesis of a non-leing, co-eternal with the idea. Hegel 
 solved the problem, only by declaring that the idea includes 
 being, which amounts to abandoning idealism properly 
 so-called: for the idea wliich involves reality, thought 
 which implies force, is more than an idea, more than thought, 
 and the name idea^ given to the principle of things thus 
 conceived, is inadequate to the tiling expressed. Material- 
 ism is confronted with the opposite difficulty : How can 
 we derive the one from the many, the indivisible ego from 
 the aggregation of atoms called the brain? Hence, those 
 among its adherents who are true philosophers love to 
 call themselves, as we have observed, not materialists, but 
 monists. They see that to 'produce intelligence means to 
 contain it, potentially at least ; that the being from which 
 the idea is derived is not the three-dimensional body, matter 
 in the real sense of the term, but the higher unitg ivhence 
 proceed both matter and thought. 
 
 Now tills synthesis of Idea and Force, whither idealism 
 and speculative materialism are tending, is not a mere pos- 
 tulate of reason, a metaphysical hypothesis, — flatus vocis, 
 — but a, fact, nay, the most immediate fact of every one's 
 experience : we mean the Will. Modern science has re- 
 duced matter to force, and Leibniz very aptly said: No 
 substance without effort. Now, to make effort means to 
 will. If effort constitutes the essence of matter, the will 
 must be the basis, the substance, and tlie generative cause 
 of matter. On the other hand, effort is also the source of 
 perception, for there can be no perception without atten- 
 tion, and no attention without effort. Perception proceeds 
 from will, and not vice versa.'^ Hence, the loill is, in the 
 last ancdysis, the higher unity of Force and Idea, the common 
 denominator, and the only one to winch physics and morals 
 
 1 W. Wundt, Physiologische Psychologic : Kein Bewusstsein ohne 
 WUlenstMtigkeit. Cf. Theodor Lipps, Grundthatsachen des Seeletilebens, 
 p. 601 : Das Streben bildet den eigentlichen Kern des Seelenlebens.
 
 CONCLUSION 601 
 
 can he reduced: it is being in its fulness. Everything else 
 is merely a phenomenon. Compared to the cjfort wliich 
 produces them, realizes them, eoiLstitutes them, matter and 
 thought are nothing but accidents : both exist only through 
 the act Avhich produces them. The will is at the basis of 
 eveiy tiling (Ravaisson ^) ; it is not only the essence of the 
 human soul (Duns Scotus, Maine de Biran, Bartholmfess), 
 the primary phenomenon of psychical life (AVundt), but the 
 universal phenomenon (Schopenhauer), the basis and the 
 substance of being (Secrdtan 2), the only absolute principle 
 (Schelling ^). On this princij)le, as Aristotle says, depend 
 the heavens and all nature. 
 
 ]Materialism cannot explain the ego. Bi-substantialistic 
 spiritualism, which regards thought as the essence of mind, 
 and opposes it to extension, the supposed essence of matter, 
 is incapable of explaining nature ; " extended substance " 
 and " thinking substance " are realized abstractions. Con- 
 crete spiritualism alone, which considers ivill as the ground 
 of all things and the common substance of the •' two worlds," 
 is a truly universal metaphysic, combining, to use the words 
 of Leibniz,^ " whatever there is of good in the hypotheses of 
 Epicurus and of Plato, of the greatest materialists and the 
 greatest idealists." Hence in tliis respect as well as in 
 many othei-s, we observe a signilicant agreement between the 
 present leaders of speculative and positive metaphysics; 
 and this agreement — consensus dissentientium — is, unques- 
 tionably, the most characteristic phenomenon in the pliilo- 
 sophic movement of our times. 
 
 Moreovei-, contemporaneous voluntarism diffei-s essen- 
 tially from tlie system of Schopenhauer.'^ According to 
 
 1 li'ij'porl sur In phitosophte frau^aise au dix-tieuvihne sihcle. 
 
 2 limine pf,Uomphl,/ue, VII., 3, p- '^Oi. * Sec p. 187 ff. 
 
 * litjtlii/iin anx rejli'j-ioiui de Baijle. 
 
 * For lh<^ (lifTficnw betwceii pessimistic voliiiitiirism and mr/tor. 
 iflic voluntarism, him; my tieatihcs: Wille zum Libtn udtr W'iilt zum
 
 602 MODERN PHILOSOPHY 
 
 this philosopher, the will strives for being and nothing but 
 being. Now nature, or to speak in the language of the 
 new metaphysics, the will, strives after being, undoubt- 
 edly, but it does so in order to realize, tlu'ough this relative 
 end, an absolute end : the good. If it had no other end 
 than being, it would find complete and supreme satisfac- 
 tion in life, even without morality. Now experience 
 superabundantly proves that the man who lives simply for 
 the sake of living becomes surfeited, and that he alone is 
 not surfeited with life who lives for something higher than 
 life. Besides, a will that is supposed to strive, necessarily 
 and fatally, for being and nothing but being, could not 
 turn against itself, as happens in suicide, and as Schopen- 
 hauer himself ui-ges it to do in liis doctrine of the nega- 
 tion of the will, although otherwise condemning the 
 avToxeipia. Finally, if the ground of things were the will- 
 to-live at any cost, we should be utterly unable to under- 
 stand the voluntary death of a Leonidas or a Socrates, and 
 of all such in whom there is sometliing mightier than the 
 will-to-live. We may, it is true, refuse to believe in the 
 disinterestedness of these sacrifices, in the good desired 
 and done for its own sake, — in a word, in duty. But we 
 may with equal right, and with no less reason, deny the 
 reality of the world, and treat existence itself as an illu- 
 sion. We must confess, there is no other proof for the 
 existence of a world apart from ourselves than the impera- 
 tive of the senses, the self-evidence with which reality 
 forces itself upon our sensibility. Now, in fact, duty is 
 no less evident than the imperative of the senses. The 
 illusions of sense, which philosophy detected at the very 
 beginning of its history, do not hinder the world from 
 being a reality, quite different, it is true, from that which 
 the senses show us, but still a reality ; and in so far the 
 
 Guien f Ein Vorirag uber Eduard von Hartmann'' s Philosopliie, Stras- 
 burg, 1882 ; Ueher die Rolle des Willens in der Relic/ion, 1888.
 
 CONCLUSION 603 
 
 senses are veridical. Similarly, however variable and fal- 
 lible conscience may be in the matter of its prescriptions, 
 their very form compels us to recognize a moral order as 
 the essence and soul of the universe. Whatever part 
 anthropomorphism may play in the vocabulary of Kantian 
 ethics, we must agree that this form is imperative, that 
 there is something even behind our will-to-live, that there 
 is above our individual Mill a higher and more excellent 
 will, wliich strives after the ideal {Wdlc zurii Outcn). This, 
 and not the Wille zum Leben of Schopenhauer, is the true 
 essence and the first cause of being, suhstantia sire I)cus. 
 
 Thus freed from the wholly accidental and passing alli- 
 ance formed with pessimism in Schopenhauer's system, the 
 monism of the will is the synthesis towards Avliieh the 
 tlu-ee factors which, as we have seen, co-operate in the de- 
 velopment of European philosophy (§ 4) are tending. These 
 factors are : reason, which postulates the essential unity of 
 things (Parmenides, Plotinus, Spinoza), experience, which 
 reveals the universality of struggle, effort, will (Heraclitus, 
 Leibniz, Schelling), and conscience, wliich affirms the moral 
 ideal, the ultimate end of the creative effort and universal 
 becoming (Plato, Kant, Fichte). 
 
 Nature is an evolution, of wliiili infinite Perfection is 
 both tlie motive force and the highest goal (Aristotle, Des- 
 cartes, Hegel).
 
 I> 
 
 BIBLIOGRAPHY 
 
 [Modern works on Logic and Epistemology : M. Drobisch, Neue 
 Darstelhuig der Logik, Leipsic, 183G, 5tli ed., 1887; J. S. Mill, 
 Logic, London, 184o, 9th ed., 187.3 ; K. Fischer, Logik und Meta- 
 p/igsik oder Wisscnschaftslehre, Heidelberg, 1852, "id ed., 18Go ; 
 J. Venn, Logic of Chance, Loudon, 1866, 3d ed., 1887; same 
 author, Empirical Logic, 1889 ; C. Sigwart, Logik, 2 vols., Frei- 
 burg i. B., 1873-78, 2d ed., 1889-93; Engl, transl. from 2d ed. 
 hy Helen Dendy, 2 vols., London ond New York, 1895; F. 
 Ueberweg, System der Logik, 5th ed., Bonn, 1882, Engl, 
 transl. ; W. S. Jevons, The Princijjles of Science, London, 
 1874, 2d ed., 1877 ; same author, Shidies in Deductive 
 Logic, 1880, 2d ed., 1884; also Elementary Lessons in Logic, 
 1870, and Pure Lj<)gic, 1890; H. Lotze, Logik, Leipsic, 1871, 
 2d ed., 1881 ; Engl, transl. ed. by B. Bosanqnet, 2 vols., 
 2d ed., London, 1888 ; A. Lange, Logische Studien, Iserlohn, 
 1877; W. Schuppe, Eikenntnissthroretische Logik, Bonn, 1878; 
 E. Duhring, Logik und Wissensrhaftslrhre, Leipsic, 1S78; J. Berg- 
 mann, Heine Logik, Berlin, 1871); W. Wundt, Logik: vol. L, 
 Erkenntnisslehrc, Stuttgart, 1880, 2d ed., 1893 ; vol. U., Mvlhodcn- 
 lehre, ih., 1883, 2d ed., 189-1; F. H. Bradley, The Principles of 
 I^gic, London, 1883; A. Bain, Logic, Deductive and Liductive, 
 New York, 1883; J. N. Keynes, Fornud Logic, London. 1884, 3d 
 ed., 1894; >L Veitch, Institutes of Logic, Edinburgh and London, 
 1885; B. BosaiHpK't, Logic, Oxford, 1888; \\. Enhnaim, f.ogik, 
 Halle, 1892; W. Minto, Logic. Inductire and J)eductive. New 
 York, 1893; A. Sidgwick, 'Tlte J'mnss nf ArguinrnI, London. 
 1893; T. Fowler, Deductive and Inductive Logic, London, l.S'.)5; 
 J. G. Hibben, Inductive Logic, New Y(»rk, 1890. — E. L. FIscIht, 
 Die CrundfriK/en drr Erkmnluisstheorie, Main/, 1HS7 ; Theorie 
 der Gesichtswaliruthniiiiig. 1«'.II ; A. Dorntr, Das nirnscJilic/ie
 
 606 BIBLIOGRAPHY 
 
 Erkennen, Berlin. 1887; C, Stumpf, Psychologie und Erkenntmss- 
 theorie, Munich, 1891 ; H. Sclnviirz, Das Wahrnehmungsprohlem, 
 Leipsic, 1892. — K. Prantl, Geschichte der Logik im Abendlande, 
 4 vols., Leipsic, 1855-70; F. Harms, Geschichte der Logik, Ber- 
 lin, 1881 ; L. Liard, Les logiciens anglais contemporains, Paris, 
 1878; E. Konig, Die Entwickelung des Causalproblems, 2 vols., 
 Leipsic, 1888, 1890 ; E. Grimm, Zur Geschichte des Erkemitniss- 
 problems, Leipsic, 1890. 
 
 Psychology, etc. : H. Lotze, Medicimsche Psychologie, oder Phy- 
 siologie der Seele, Leipsic, 1852, 1896; H. Spencer, Principles of 
 Psychology, London, 1855 ; A. Bain, Senses and Intellect, London, 
 1855,4th ed.. New York, 1894; Emotions and Will, London, 
 1859, 3d ed., 1875 ; M. Lazarus, Das Lehen der Seele, Berlin, 
 1856-57, 3d ed., 3 vols., 1884; G. T. Fechner, Elemente der 
 Psychophysik, Leipsic, 1860 ; W. Wundt, Vorlesungen ilber 
 Menschen- und Thierseele, 1863 (see p. 586); Grundzuge der phy- 
 siologischen Psychologie, 2 vols., Leipsic, 1873-74, 4th ed., 1893 ; 
 H. Maudsley, The Physiology and Pathology of Mind, London, 
 1867 ; W. Carpenter, Principles of Mental Physiology, 4th ed., 
 1876; A. Horwicz, Psychologische Analysen auf physiologischer 
 Grundlage, 3 vols., Magdeburg, 1872-78; F. Brentano, Ps^/cAo- 
 logie vom empirischen Standpunkte, vol. I., Leipsic, 1874; W. F. 
 Volkmann, Lehrbuch der Psychologie, 2 vols., Cothen, 1875, 4th 
 ed., 1894 ; H. Steinthal, Einleitung in die Psychologie und Sprach- 
 wissenschaft, 2d ed., Berlin, 1881 ; J. Sully, Illusions (lit. Science 
 Se7'ies), 1881 ; C. Stumpf, Tonpsychologie, vol. I., Leipsic, 1883; 
 vol. II., 1890; Ur sprung der Raumvorstellung, 1873; Th. Lipps, 
 Griindthatsachen des Seelenlebens, Bonn, 1883; H. Hoffding, Ps^- 
 chologie in Umrissen, tr. into German from the Danish, by Kurella, 
 Leipsic, 1887, 2d ed. , 1893 ; Engl, transl. from German, by M. 
 Lowndes, London and New York, 1891 ; C. Lange, Ucber Gemuths- 
 bewegungen, Leipsic, 1887; G. T. Ladd, Elements of Physiological 
 Psychology, New York, 1887; Psychology, Descriptive and Ex- 
 flanatory, id., 1894 ; H. Munsterberg, Die Willenshandlung, 
 Freiburg, 1888 ; Beitrdge zur experimentellen Psychologie, 1889 ff. ; 
 G. Sergi, La pis^jchologie physiologique, from the Italian, Paris, 
 1888 ; W. James, The Principles of Psychology, 2 vols., New
 
 BIBLIOGRAPHY 607 
 
 York, 1890 ; Th. Ziehen, Leitfaden der physiologischen Psychologie, 
 1891, 2d ed., 1893; Engl, transl., 1892, 2d ed., 1895; J. M. 
 Baldwin, Handbook of PsijcJiohgy, 2 vols.. New York, 1891; J. 
 Sully, The Human Mind, 2 vols., ISTew York, 1892 ; A. Leh- 
 man, Das menschliche GefUhlslehen, Leipsic, 1892 : O. Kulpe, 
 Grundriss der Psychologie, Leipsic, 1893; Engl, transl. by E. B. 
 Titchener, Xew York, 1895; A. Fouillee, La psychologie des 
 idees-forces, Paris, 1893. Experimental Psychology, by Cattell, 
 Sanford, and Titchener. — Kussmaul, Untersuchungen iiher das See- 
 lenlehen des neugehorenen Menschen, Leipsic and Heidelberg, 1859 ; 
 W. Preyer, Die Seele des Kindes, 4th ed., Leipsic, 1895 (tr. in In- 
 ternational Education Series) ; Mental Development in the Child, 
 tr., lb., 1893 ; B. Perez, Les trois premieres annees de Venfant, 
 Paris, 1882, 4th ed., 1888; Engl, transl. 1894; Denfant de trois 
 a sept ans, 1886, 2(1 ed., 1888 ; D education morale d^s le berceau, 
 1888; F. Tracy, Psychology of Childhood, Boston, 1893, 2d ed., 
 1894 ; J. M. Baldwin, Menial Development in the Child and 
 the Race, New York, 1895 ; J. Sully, Studies of Childhood, 
 New York, 1896. — C. Darwin, The Descent of Man, London, 
 1871 ; Expression of the Emotions, 1872 ; G. H. Schneider, 
 Der thierische U7//e, Leipsic, 1880 ; Der menschliche II7//p, Berlin, 
 1882 ; G. Romanes, Mental Evolution in Animals, London, 1883 ; 
 Mentcd Evolution in Man, 1889; Gallon, Inquiries into Human 
 Faculty, London, 1883; Natural Inheritance, 1889; J. Lubbock, 
 Ants, Bees, and Wasps, London, 1883 ; The Senses and Instincts 
 of Animals, 1888 ; L. Morgan, Animal Life and Intelligence, 
 London, 1891 ; Introduction to the Study of Comparative Psychol- 
 ogy, 1895; Espinas, Animal Societies. — IL Spencer, 7Vie Prin- 
 ciples of Sociology, London, 1854; Tii. Waitz, Anthropologic der 
 Natiirvolker, Leipsic, 1859 If., 2d ed., by G. Gerland, 1877 ff. ; J. 
 LubI)Ock, Prehistoric Times, Lon(\ou, 1865,5th od., 1889; Ori- 
 gin of Civilization, 1870 ; E. B. Tyler, Primitive Culture, Lon- 
 don, 1871 ; Anthropology, 1881 ; (). Peschel, ]'olkerkunde,, 
 Leipsic, 1874, 5th ed., by A. Kiivl,l,„fT, 1881 ; J. Ranke, 
 Drr Afp)isch, 2 vols., 2d (•<!., Leipsic, IHDl. — (iriosinger. Die 
 Palhulngir und Thrrapie der psychlschrn hrttukhvitcn. Stuttgart, 
 1845. Itli ed., 1870; K'niiTl-Ebiiig. L,hrt,urh ,lrr J'syrhinfrir, fnh 
 ed., Stuttgart. 18'.I3 ; Meyiiert. /'syrhialric, N'ieiiiia, IHM'.); Lewis,
 
 608 BIBLIOGEAPHY 
 
 Text-hooh of Mental Diseases ; 8tavv, Faim'Uar Forms of Nervom 
 Disease, 2d ed., 1891 ; P. Janet, L'etat mental des hysteriques, 2 
 vols., Paris, 1892-93 ; Ziehen, Psychiatrie ; also Th. Ribot, Dis- 
 eases of the Will, Diseases of Memory^ Diseases of Personality, 
 mentioned before ; A. Biuet, Les alterations de la personnalite, 
 Paris, 1893. For hypnotism, see works of Charcot, Binet, Fere, 
 Bernheim, Krafft-Ebing, P^orel, Dessoir, Wuudt, Schmidkunz, 
 Moll, Gurney, Lic'geois, etc. — Histories of Psychology : F. A. 
 Cams, Leipsic, 1808; F. Harms, 2d ed., Beriin, 1879; H. Sie- 
 beck, Gotha, 1880-84; M. Dessoir, GeschicMe der neueren 
 deutschen Psychologic, vol. I., Berlin, 1895; Th. Ribot's works 
 on German and English psychology of to-day (see p. 586, note 7) 
 Ethics: J. S. Mill, Utilitarianism (cited p. 581, note 2) ; E. 
 Duhring, Der Werth des Lebens, 5th ed., Leipsic, 1894; E. Zeller, 
 Vortrcige imd Ahhandlungen, 3 series, Leipsic, 1865, 1877, 1884; 
 Bain, Mental and Moral Science (p. 581, note 3) ; P. Janet 
 (p. 591, note 1) ; A. Barratt, Physical Ethics, London, 1869; 
 B. Carneri, Sittlichkeit und Darwinismus, Vienna, 1871, 2d ed., 
 Leipsic, 1877 ; H. Calderwood, Handhooh of Morality, London, 
 1872; H. Sidgwick, Methods of Ethics, London, 1874, 4th ed., 
 1890 ; F. H. Bradley, Ethical Studies, London, 1876 ; R. v. Jher- 
 ing, Der Zweck im Recht, Leipsic, 1877-83, 2d ed., 1884-86; 
 M. Carriere, Die sittliche Weltordnung, Leipsic, 1 877 ; E. v. 
 Hartmann (p. 557) ; H. Spencer (p. 581); J. Baumann, Hand- 
 bach der Moral, Leipsic, 1879 ; B. Carneri, Grundlegung der 
 Ethik, Vienna, 1881 ; Entwickelung und Gliickseligkeit, Stnttgart, 
 1886 ; Guyau, Esquisse d'une morale sans obligation ni sanction, 
 2d ed., Paris, 1881 : W. Schnppe, Grundziige der Ethik und 
 Eechtsphilosophie, Breslau, 1882 ; W. H. Rolph, Biologische 
 Probleme, Leipsic, 1882; L. Stephen, 77ie Science of Ethics, Lon- 
 don, 1882; J. H. Witte, Die Freiheit des Willens, Bonn, 1882,- 
 T. H. Green, Prolegomena to Ethics, London, 1883, 2d ed., 1887 •, 
 G. V. Gizycki, Grundziige der Moral, Leipsic, 1883, 2d ed., 1889 ; 
 Engl. tr. by S. Coit ; T. Fowler, Progressive Morcdity, London, 
 1884, 2d ed., 1895 ; Fowler and Wilson, Principles of Morality, 
 1886-1887, 2d ed., 1894; A. Dorner, System derckristlichen Sitfen- 
 lehre, Berlin, 1885 ; H. Steinthal, Allgemeine Ethik, Berlin, 1885 ;
 
 BIBLIOGRAPHY G09 
 
 P. Rt'e, Die Enfstehimg des Gewissens, Berlin, 1S85 ; S. S. Laurie, 
 Ethicn, London, I880 ; N. Porter, EJenwiiti, of Moral Science, 
 New York, I880 ; J. Martineau, Tijpes oj Ethical Theory^ 2 vols., 
 London, 1885, 3d ed., 1891; C. Sigwart, Vorfragen der Ethik, 
 Freiburg, 188G; W. "Wundt (p. 08G) ; F. Tonnies, Gemeinschaft 
 und Gesellschaft, Leipsic, 1887 ; H. liolVding, Ethik, German 
 trausl. by F. Bendixen, Leipsic, 1887; F. Nietzsche, Zur Gene- 
 alogie der Morcd, Berlin, 1887, 2d ed., 1887 ; J. G. Schuriuan, 
 The Ethical Import of Darwinism, New York, 1887 ; G. Rlimelin, 
 Reden und Aiifsdtze, Freiburg, 1888 ; Martensen, Die christliche 
 Ethik, 2 vols., Leipsic, 1872-78; Engl, trausl. in 3 vols., 
 1873-83 ; A. Doriug, Philosophische Gilterhhre, Berlin, 1888 ; 
 S. Alexander, Moral Order and J'rogress, London, 1889 ; 
 F. Paulsen, iSystem der Ethik, Berlin, 1889, 4tb ed., 1895; 
 H. Miinsterberg, Der Ursprung der Sittlichkeit, Freiburg, 
 i. B., 1889; F. Breutano, Vom Ursprung sittUcher Erkennt- 
 niss, Leipsic, 1889 ; Tb. Ziegler, SittUches Sein mid sittliches 
 Werden, Strasburg, 1890 ; J. S. Mackenzie, Introduction to 
 Social Philosnphjf, London, 1890; A 3Iamial of Ethics, New 
 York, 2d ed., 1895; J. Dewey, Outlines of a Critical Theory 
 of Ethics, New York, 1891 ; II. Gallwitz, Das Problem der Ethik 
 in der Gegenwart, Leipsic, 1891 ; G. Runzc, Ethik, vol. I., Prak- 
 tische Ethik, Berlin, 1891 ; G. Simmel, Einleitung in die Moral- 
 wissenschaft, 2 vols., Berlin, 1892-93 ; B. P. Bowne, The Prin- 
 ciples of Ethics, New York, 1892; N. Smytli, Christian Ethics, 
 New York, 1892; C. M. Williams, A Review of the Systems of 
 Ethics founded on Evolution, New York and London, 1893; 
 Til. Elsenliaus, Wesen und Entstehung des Gewissens, Leipsic, 
 1894; D. G. Ritchie, iVrt/Mra^ Rights, New York and London, 
 1895; J. Sctli, yl Study of Ethical Prinrijtles, Edinbiiri:li and 
 London, 2d ed., 1890. — v. Oettingoii, Moral-Sfatisfik, Itli ed., 
 Berlin, 1887; Morselli. Suicide (Int. Sc. Series). — \Y. H Lecky, 
 A History of European Morals, 2 vols., London, 1859, 3d ed., 
 1877, an<l L. Schmidt, Die Ethik der alten Grie h^n, lierlin, 
 1882, are liistories of customs. — On the histttry of ethi«'s see the 
 works of Zicgh-r, Kostlin, Liithardt (cited in noto C, p. 8), G.-iss, 
 Zifgler, Luthardt (p. 9, nol«! 2) ; Vorliiinlcr. Ma kintosh, .lodl 
 (p. 12, note 11), Sidgwick (p. 15. nott; 9^ .lamt (p. I I, iwlc 7;
 
 010 BIBLIOGRAPHY 
 
 p. 15, note 9), and W. Wliewell, History of Moral Science, 
 Edinburffh, 18G3 ; A. Guyau, La morale anylaise cmitemporaine, 
 Paris, 1879. 
 
 Aesthetics : F. Th. Vischer, Aesthetih, 3 vols., Leipsic, 1846-57 ; 
 H. Taine, Philosophie de Vart, Paris, 18G5 ; Engl, trans, by Du- 
 rand, 2d ed., 1873; H. Siebeck, Das Wesen der aesthetischen 
 Anschauung, Berlin, 1875; H. Lotze, Grundzilge der Aesihetik, 
 Leipsic, 1884; Engl. tr. by G. T. Ladd, Boston, 1884; Guyau, 
 Les proUemes de Vestlietique contemporaine, Paris, 1884; E. v. 
 Hartmann, I. Die deiitsche Aesthetik seit Kant, Leipsic, 1886; 
 II. Die Philosophie des Schonen, 1887 ; H. Stein, Die Entstehiing 
 derneueren Aesthetik, Stuttgart, 1886; H. Cohen, Kant' s Begriin- 
 dung der Aesthetik, Berlin, 1889; Monrad, Aesthetik, Christiania, 
 1889 ; K. Kostlin, Prolegomena zur Aesthetik, Tubingen, 1889 ; 
 Th. lA^^^, Aestlietische Faktoren der Raumanschauung, 1891 ; also 
 Psychologic der Komik, Philos. Monatshefte, 1888-89; W. Knight, 
 The Philosophy of the Beautifid, 2 vols., London, 1891-93 ; K. 
 Groos, Einleitung in die Aesthetik, Heidelberg, 1892; L. Arrcat, 
 Psychologie du peintre, Paris, 1892; B. Bosanquet, The History of 
 Aesthetics, London and New York, 1892 ; W. R. Marshall, Pleas- 
 ure, Pain, and Aesthetics, London and New York, 1894; Hirth, 
 Die Physiologic der Kimst. 
 
 Philosophy of Religion: Scholten (p. 15), O. Pfleiderer (p. 12, 
 note 11; vol. 11. , Genetische spekulative Religionsphilosophie) \ 
 
 A. Reville, Prolegomenes de Vhistoire des religions, Paris, 1880, 
 4th ed., 1886; English transl. Prolegomena to the History of Re- 
 ligion, 1884, 1885 ; H. Lotze, Religionsphilosophie, Leipsic, 1881 ; 
 Engl. tr. by G. T. Ladd, Boston, 1884 ; J. Kaftan, Das Wesen 
 de^christlichen Religion, Basel, 1881, 2d ed., 1888; C. P. Tiele, 
 Outlines of the History of Religion, London, 1884, 2d ed., 1888; 
 
 B. Plinjer, Grimdriss der Religionsphilosophie, Braunschweig, 
 1886 (see also p. 12, note 11); W. Bender, Das Wesen der Re- 
 ligion, etc., Bonn, 1886; Chantepie de la Saussaye, Lehrbuch der 
 ReUgionsgeschichte, 2 vols., Freiburg i. B., 1887-89 ; Engl. tr. by 
 B. Ferguson, London, 1891 ; L. W. Rauwenhoff, Religionsphi^ 
 losophie, German transl. by J. R. Hanne, Braunschweig, 1889; 
 K. Kostlin, Der Ursprung der Religion, 1890; J. G. Schurman,
 
 BIBLIOGRAPHY 611 
 
 Belief in God, New York, 1890 ; Agnosticism and Religion, 1896 ; 
 E. Caird, The Evolution of Religion, 2 vols., London and New- 
 York, 1893 ; and Max Muller's Lectures on the Origin and Growth 
 of Religion. 
 
 Philosophy of History : C. Hermann, Die Fhilosophie der 
 Geschichte, Leipsic, 1870; Bernheim, Geschichtsforschiing und 
 Geschichtsphilosophie, 1880 ; W. Dilthey, Einleitung in die Geistes- 
 wissenschaften, Leipsic, 1883 ; A. Dippe, Das Gesckichtsstudiian 
 init seinen Zielen und Fragen, 1891 ; G. Simmel, Die Prohleme der 
 Geschichtsphilosophie, Berlin, 1892; Droysen, Grundriss der His- 
 torik, Engl, tr., I'he Principles of History, by E. B. Andrews, 
 Boston, 1893 ; Flint (p. 15, note 9). 
 
 Jurisprudence, Politics, Institutions, etc. : Austin, Lectures on 
 Jurisprudence ; Bluntschli, Die Lehre vom modernen Staat, 3 vols. ; 
 Engl, tr., Theory of the State; Buckle (p. 12, note 11) ; Burgess, 
 Political Science ; Coulanges, La cite cmtique ; Denis, Theories 
 et idees morales dans Vantiquite ; Donisthorpe, Individualism, a 
 System of Politics ; Hearn, Aryan Household; Holland, Juris- 
 prudence ; Laveleye, De la propriete et de ses formes primitives ; 
 Lieber, Manual of Political Ethics; Lioy, Delia flosofa del 
 diritto (translated) ; Maine, Early History of Institutions ; Ancient 
 Laic and Customs ; Miller, Philosophy of Law ; Mohl, Encyclo- 
 pedie der Staatswissenschaften ; Pollock, Essays in Jurisprudence 
 and Ethics ; History of the Science of Politics ; Puchta, Outlines 
 of Jurisprudence ; Schiiffle, Bau und Leben des sozialen Kijrpers ; 
 Sidgwick, Elements of Politics ; Spencer, The Man versus the 
 State ; A Plea for Liberty ; Tarde, Transformations du droit ; 
 Taylor, The Individual and the State ; Westermarck, The Histoi-y 
 of Human Marriage. — Tr.]
 
 INDEX 
 
 [The asterisk indicates the important places in which authors or subjects 
 are treated; n. stands for note.] 
 
 Abbot, E., 8 n. 6. 
 Abbott, T. 436 n. 2, 4, 6. 
 
 Abbt, 433* n. 2. 
 
 Abelard, 9, 202, 222* ff., 228, 235. 
 
 Academic scepticism, 150 ff. 
 
 Academy, 75. 
 
 Adamson, 481 n. 1, 434 u. 2. 
 
 Adickes, 434 n. 2, 435 n. 3. 
 
 Aenesidemus, 153* ff, 378 u. 1, 537; 
 his critique of causality, 156 f. 
 
 Aeschylus, 19. 
 
 Aesthetics, bibliography of, 610; He- 
 gel's, 524 ff. ; Kant's, 468 ff. 
 
 Affleck, 591 n. I. 
 
 Agrippa of Nettesheim, 266*. 
 
 Agrippa tlie .Sceptic, 158. 
 
 Ahrens, 587* n. 4. 
 
 Alanus ab insulis, 231* 235. 
 
 Alaux, 15. 
 
 All)ee, 390 n. 2, 391 n. 2. 
 
 Albert the Great, 236, 240* f., 250 f. 
 
 Alberti, 63 n. 1, 283 n. 3. 
 
 Alciuous, 160. 
 
 Akuin, 201*. 
 
 Alexander of Aphrodisias, 166* 269. 
 
 Alexander the Great, 105. 
 
 Alexander of Hales, 239*. 
 
 Alexander, S., 609. 
 
 Alexandre, 263 n. 1. 
 
 Alexandria, 160 ff. 
 
 Alfaral)!, 216 n. 2. 
 
 Algazel, 216 n. 2. 
 
 Alkfiidi, 216 n. 2. 
 
 Alley tie, 4 n. 2. 
 
 Alzog, 9 n. 2. 
 
 Amalrir. 234 f. 
 
 Ammonins S,icr-;in, 166*. 
 
 Analytic judgments, 438 ff. 
 
 'Avd/J-vna-ts, Plato's 98. 
 
 Anaxagoras, 5, 48* ff., 60, 95, 118, 412 
 n. 1. 
 
 Anaximander, 22* f., 45 n. 2, 412 u. 1. 
 
 Anaximenes, 23. 
 
 Ancona, 291 n. 2. 
 
 Andrews, 611. 
 
 Augelus Politianus, 263 f. 
 
 Animal psychology, bibliography of, 
 607. 
 
 Auue'e philosophique, 584 u. 1. 
 
 Anniceris, 73*. 
 
 Anselm, 6, 9, 202, 210* ff., 221, 235, 
 362, 461 ; his conception of cause, 
 214 f . ; his ontological argument, 217 ; 
 his proof for the existence of God, 
 214. 
 
 .Anthropology, bibliography of, 607. 
 
 Antinomies, Kant's, 456 ff. 
 
 Antisthenes, 70, 73* f., 98. 
 
 Apelt, 146 n. I, 474 n. 1. 
 
 ApoUonius of Perga, 161. 
 
 Apuleius, 166. 
 
 Arabians, 2.33, 236. 
 
 Arabian schools, 210 n. 3. 
 
 Arcesilans, 104, 150 f. 
 
 Archelans, 54 f. 
 
 Archimedes, 160. 
 
 Ariaiiism. 190. 
 
 Aristarcbus, 160, 
 
 Aristippus, 70, 71* f., 152, 378 n. 1. 
 
 Arist<»j)hanos, 64. 
 
 Aristotle, 5, 6, 20, 73, 82, 102, 104* ff., 
 234. 385, 588, 604 ; his astronomy, 
 120 f. ; and Catholicism. 123 f. ; ami 
 the Pburch, 237 ; his concept of im- 
 iiiirtalitN', 128 ff., of mnttor, 112 ff.. 
 of motion, space, and time, 118 ff..
 
 6U 
 
 INDEX 
 
 of philosophy, 107 f., of soul, 125 ff. ; 
 his critique of materialism, 110, of 
 Plato's idealism, lO'J f. ; his ethics, 
 131 ff. ; his gods, 122 f . ; his meta- 
 physics, 108 ff . ; his meteorology, 1 24 ; 
 his philosophy of nature, 118 ff. ; his 
 politics, 132 f. ; his sensatioualism, 
 130 f. ; his teleology, 124 ff. ; his 
 theology, 114 f . ; and scholasticism, 
 222 ff., 235 ff. 
 
 Aristoxeuus, 133. 
 
 Armstroug, 12 n. 11. 
 
 Arnauld, 318* 322. 
 
 Aruobius, 186. 
 
 Arre'at, 610. 
 
 Arriauus, 146 n. 1, 147. 
 
 Arystillus, 161. 
 
 Asse'zat, 412 n. 2. 
 
 Ast, 76 u. 1, n. 2. 
 
 Athauasius, 187. 
 
 Atheuagoras, 187. 
 
 Atomism, 1 u. 1 ; and teleology, 95. 
 
 Atomists, Greek, 55 ff. 
 
 Atticus, 139, 166. 
 
 Auerbach, 323 n. 1. 
 
 Augustine, 6, 9, 187, 188* ff., 215, 224, 
 322, 493 n. 1 ; his determinism, 196 
 ff. ; his doctrine of creation, 190 ff. ; 
 his ethics, 196 ff. ; his p.?ychology, 
 192 ff. ; his theology, 189 ff. 
 
 Augustinianism, 322. 
 
 Avempace, 210 n. 2. 
 
 Avenarius, 586 n. 7. 
 
 Averroes, 9, 210 n. 2. 
 
 Avicebron, 210 n. 2. 
 
 Avicenna, 210 n. 2. 
 
 Baader, 278 n. 6, 488, 589*. 
 
 Bach, 260, n. 2. 
 
 Bacon, F., 3, 11, 273, 295* ff., 304, 389, 
 
 594. 
 Bacon, B., 3, 9, 258*. 
 Bahnsen, 557* n. 1. 
 Baumker, 9 n. 2, 93 n. 1. 
 Bailey, 581* n. 3. 
 Baillet, 305 n. 1 . 
 Bain, 104 n. 4, 581 n. 2, 581* n. 3, 605, 
 
 606, 608. 
 Baiter, 76 n. 2. 
 
 Baldachini, 291 n. 2. 
 
 Baldwin, 535 n. 2, 607. 
 
 Barach, 219 n. 2, 226 n. 3. 
 
 Barbarus, Ilermolaus, 263*. 
 
 Barchou de Peuhoen, 12. 
 
 Bardili, 473*. 
 
 Barlaam, 262. 
 
 Barratt, 608. 
 
 Bartholmess, 12, 286 n. 2, 399 n. 1, GOi 
 
 Basil the Great, 187. 
 
 Batteux, 133 n. 1. 
 
 Baumann, 12 n. 11, 15 n. 9. 
 
 Baumgarten, 369* n. 1. 
 
 Baur, 9 u. 2, 148 n. 1, 185 n. 1, 5.33*. 
 
 Bautain, 589*. 
 
 Bax, 436 n. 1, n. 3, 544 n. 5. 
 
 Bayle, 13 u. 1, 318*. 
 
 Beattie, 431*. 
 
 Beaugendre, 211 n. 3. 
 
 Beck, 7 n. 4. 
 
 Beck, J. S., 577 n. 1. 
 
 Beda Venerabilis 201*. 
 
 Bekker, 7 n. 5, 76 n. 2, 104 u. 4. 
 
 Bekker, B., 318, 321*. 
 
 Bembo, 264. 
 
 Beuard, 76 u. 2, 487 n. 1. 
 
 Bender, 8 u. 6, 610. 
 
 Bendixen, 12 n. 11, 609. 
 
 Beneke, 542* n. 2. 
 
 Benn, 8 n. 6. 
 
 Bentham, 391* n. 2. 
 
 Berengar, 211*. 
 
 Berger, 182 n. 1. 
 
 Bergk, 8 n. 6, 24 n. 2, 44 n. 1. 
 
 Bergmann, 15 n. 9, 605, 
 
 Berkeley, 11, 303, 391* ff., 403, 430. 
 
 Bernard, C. 192 n. 1, 435 n. 3, 436 n 5 
 
 585*. 
 Bernays, 7 n. 1, 33 n. 1, 55 n. 2. 
 Bernhard, St., 260*. 
 Bernhard of Chartres, 226*. 
 Bernhard of Clairvaux, 223. 
 Bernhardi, 8 n. 8. 
 Bernheim, 608. 
 Bernheim, 611. 
 Bertholdt, G., 405 n. 1. 
 Bessarion, 263*, 267. 
 Biedermann, 12 n. 11. 
 Biel, 257.
 
 INDEX 
 
 615 
 
 Biese, 104 n. 4. 
 
 Bilfinger, 369* n. 1. 
 
 Biudeiuaun, 188 n. 1. 
 
 Biuet, 608. 
 
 Blampigiion, 320 n. 2. 
 
 Blass, 59 n. 1. 
 
 Bliud, M., 562 n. 3. 
 
 Bluutschli, 12 u. 11, 611. 
 
 Boccaccio, 262. 
 
 Boetliius, 199* f. 
 
 Buhine, J., 10, 199, 278* ff., 488, 589 
 
 u. 3. 
 Buhmer, 324 n. 2. 
 Bois.>oiiade, 8 u. 2. 
 Boliugbroke, 39* n. 3. 
 Bouaventura. 241*. 
 Bouhufer, 140 u. 1. 
 Bouifas, 344 u. 1. 
 Bouitz, 78 u. 1, 104 n. 4, 108 n. 3. 
 Bonnet, 291, 370 n. 2, 412 f.* 
 Bordas-Demoulin, 592 n. 2. 
 Borelius, 533* n. 1. 
 Bosanquet, 15 n. 9, 497 n. 6, 533* n. 1, 
 
 542 u. 2, 605, 610. 
 Bossuet, 322 n. 1. 
 Bostroni, 588*. 
 Bouchitte, 587* n. 4. 
 Bouillet, 7 u. 2, 157 n. 1. 180 n. 1. 
 Bouillier, .305 n. 1, -320 u. 2. 
 Boureau-Deislandes, 13 n. 1. 
 Bourne, Fox, 370 u. 1. 
 Bouterwek, 473*. 
 Boutroux, 590* n. 7. 
 Bowen, 12 n. 11. 
 Bower, G. S., 406 n. 2. 
 Bowne, 581 n. 3, 609. 
 Bradley, F. 11., 533* n. 1. 605, 608. 
 Bradwardine, 359. 
 Bralimanism, 571. 
 
 Brand is, 8 n 6, 104 n. 4. 
 
 Breier, 48 n. 2. 
 
 Brentano, F., 606, 609. 
 
 Brewer. 258 n. 3. 
 
 Briefer. 55 n. 3. 
 
 Brocliard. 148 n. 2. 
 
 Brown, Th'.ma.s, 431* n. 3. 
 
 Brucker, 13. 
 
 Bruder. 323 n. 1. 
 
 Brunuliofer, 286 n. 2. 
 
 Bruno, 6, 11, 199, 273, 264 n. 1, 286* S., 
 
 313, 345,347, 491 n. 2. 
 Brunschvigg, 323 u. 1. 
 Brutus, 147. 
 Bryant, 497 n. 6. 
 Biichner, 562*. 
 
 Buckle, 12 n. 11, 581* n. 3, Gil. 
 Buddlii.sm, 545, 571. 
 Buddhism and Pythagoreanismj 3.G n. 1. 
 Bude, 305 n. 1. 
 Buffon, 51. 
 Buhle, 13, 25 u. 1. 
 Bulliuger, 108 u. 3. 
 Burchard, 58 n. 1. 
 Burckhardt, 16 n. 1. 
 Burdach, 495. 
 Burgess, 611. 
 Buridau, 256*. 
 Burleigh, "Walter, 256* 
 Burnet, 6 n. 1, 8 n. 6. 
 Burt, 12 u. 11. 
 Busot, 399 n. 1. 
 Butler, 391* n. 2. 
 Byk, 8 u. 6. 
 Bywater, 33 n. 1. 
 
 Cabalists, 164, 265 ff. 
 
 Cabanis, 415* f., 590 n. 5. 
 
 Caclicnx, 241 n. 2. 
 
 Cae.salpinus, 272* 284. 
 
 Caesar, 139. [o73n. 2, 611. 
 
 Caird, E., 434 n. 2, 496 n. 3, 533* u. 1, 
 
 Caird, J., 323 n. 1, 53.3* n. 1. 
 
 Calderwood, 608. 
 
 Calvin, 276. 
 
 Canierer, 323 n. 1. 
 
 Canipanella, 11, .56. 291* ff. 
 
 Cantoui, 4.34 n. 2. 
 
 Cantor, 159 n. 1. 
 
 Capes, 147 u. 4. 
 
 Capesius, .535 n. 2. 
 
 Cardauus, 10. 267*. 
 
 Carneados, 151* f., 430. 
 
 Carneri, 008. 
 
 Carpf-nter, 606. 
 
 Carrii-re. 10 n. 1, 274 n. 6, 588*, 608. 
 
 Cartesian .sdiool, 318* ff. 
 
 Cams, C. G., 495. 
 
 CaruK, F. A., 608.
 
 616 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Cams, P., 586* n. 7. 
 Caspari, 542 u. 2. 
 Cassiodorus, 200*. 
 Cassias, 139. 
 
 Categories, Kant's, 445 ff. 
 Catholicism and Aristotle, 124 f. 
 Cato, 147. 
 
 Causality, Hegel's doctrine of, 506 ff . ; 
 
 Hume's doctrine of, 421 ff. ; Kant's 
 
 doctrine of, 445 ff . ; Sceptics' doctrine 
 
 of, 156 f. 
 
 Chaiguet, 8 n. 6, 37 n. 2, 63 n. 1, 76 
 
 u. 2, 296 n.3. 
 Clialybaeus, 12, 588*. 
 Chapman, M. 591 n. 1. 
 Charcot, 608. 
 
 Charles, 258 n.3, 411 u. 1. 
 Charron, 274*. 
 Chase, 104 n. 4. 
 Chasles, 159 n. 1. 
 Cheselden, 402 n. 1. 
 Child psychology, bibliography of, 607. 
 Cliristianity, 69 ; and Greek philosophy, 
 
 165; and Stoicism, 147. 
 Christian Platonism, 185* ff. 
 
 Chrysippus, 141*, 147 n. 3. 
 
 Chrysostom, 196. 
 
 Chubb, 391* n. 3. 
 
 Cicero, 7, 147, 148 n. 1, 225. 
 
 Clarke, 390*. 
 
 Clauberg, 318*. 
 
 Cleanthes, 140. 
 
 Clement of Alexandria, 7, 9, 187. 
 
 Clerselier, 316 n. 2, 317 n. 1, 318*. 
 
 Cobet, 7 n. 6. 
 
 Cohen, 437 n. 1, 462 n. 2, 468 n. 1, 584, 
 610. 
 
 Coignet,467 n. 1. 
 
 Coit, 608. 
 
 Coler, 323 n. 1. 
 
 Colet, 199 n. 1. 
 
 Collier, 398 n. 3. 
 
 Collingwood, 562 n. 6. 
 
 Collins, A., 391* n. 3. 
 
 Collins, W., 391 n. 2. 
 
 Colombo, Realdo, 284. 
 
 Columbus, 282, 296. 
 
 Combefisius, 199 n 2. 
 
 Combes, 563* n. 5. 
 
 Comenius, 278*. 
 Common, 557 n. 1. 
 Common-sense philosophy, 430* ff. 
 Comte, 11, 472 n. 1, 573* ff.; his classi- 
 fication of sciences, 576 ff. ; his con- 
 ception of theology, ruetaphysics, and 
 science, 574 ff. 
 Conceptualism, 222 ff. 
 Condillac, ll,399*ff., 590. 
 Condorcet, 414*. 
 Congreve, 573 n. 2. 
 Conn, 560 n. 1. 
 Copernicus, 11, 160, 264 n. 1, 283* 390, 
 
 399 n. 1. 
 Corson, 591 n. 1. 
 Cosmological argument, Kant's critique 
 
 of, 461. 
 Cosmology, Kant's critique of, 456 ff. 
 
 Cotton, 273 n. 3. 
 
 Coulanges, 611. 
 
 Couplaud, 557 n. 1. 
 
 Cournot, 574 n. 2. 
 
 Cousin, 14, 25 n. 1, 76 n. 2, 182 n. I. 
 201 n. 3, 222 n. 1, 223, 226 n. 3. 
 305 n. 1, 322 n. 1, 370 n. 1, 434 n. 2, 
 533 n. 1, 590* 590 n. 7. 
 
 Crantor, 104. 
 
 Crates, 104, 140, 150. 
 
 Cratylus, 75. 
 
 Creighton, 586 n. 3. 
 
 Creuzer, 167 n. 1. 
 
 Criticism, 1 n. 1, 370 ff., 434* ff. 
 
 Critique philosophique, 584 n. 1. 
 
 Crowell, 8 u. 6. 
 
 Crusades, 262. 
 
 Cudworth, 370*. 
 
 Cumberland, 391 n. 2. 
 
 Curtis, 370 n. 1. 
 
 Cuvier, 564* n. 2. 
 
 Cynics, 73* f., 98. 
 
 Cyrenaics, 71* f. 
 
 Daiixe, 163 n. 1. 
 
 D'Ailly, 256*. 
 
 D'Alembert, 414*. 
 
 Dallas, 562 u. 6. 
 
 Damascius, 184 n. 1. 
 
 Damiron, 12 n. 11, 317 n. 2, 399 n. 1 
 
 Dante, 262.
 
 INDEX 
 
 617 
 
 Darwin, C, 11, 46, 404 u. 1, 560 u. 1, 
 
 5G3* ff., 607. 
 Darwiu, F., 563 u. 2. 
 Darwinism, 560* ff. 
 David of Diuaiit, 234. 
 Davidson, 104 u. 4. 
 Davy, 563* n. 5. 
 Dean, 12 n. 11. 
 De Bonald, 579. 
 Debrit, 590 n. 7. 
 De Garnio, 542 n. 2. 
 Dege'rando, 13. 
 Deism, 1 u. 1. 
 Deists, 391. 
 Delaiubre, 159 n. 1. 
 Delame, 7 n. 8. 
 Del Rio, 587* n. 4. 
 De ^laistre, 579. 
 Demaze, 277 n. 3. 
 Deinocritus, 53* ff., 66, 95 f., 134, 297, 
 
 406, 412 u. 1, 594 ff. 
 Dendy, 605. 
 Denifle, 9 n. 2. 
 Denis, 187 n. 2, 611. 
 Descartes, 6, 192 n. 2, 220 n. I, 305* ff., 
 
 370 f., 378 n. 1, 453, 456, .')37, 591, 
 
 594; and French materialism, 411 ; 
 
 and Spinoza, 326 f. ; his physics, 
 
 313 f. ; his scepticism, 308 f.; his 
 
 theory of interaction, 316 f. 
 Dcsdouits, 434 n. 2. 
 De.sjardins, 298 n. 2. 
 Des Maizeaux, 13 n. 1. 
 Desnoiresterres, 399 n. 1. 
 Dessoir, 12 n. 11, 608. 
 Destutt de Tracy, 590* n. 5. 
 Detmold, 264 n. 2. 
 Deussen, 15 n. 9, 557* n. 1 
 Deutiiiger, 9 u. 2. 
 Devey, 298 n. 1. 
 Dcwcy, 344 n. 1, 609. 
 De Witte, 474 n. 1. 
 Dicaearchus, 133. 
 Di.hTot, 291, 412* ff., 505. 
 Dicl.S G n. 4, 8 n. C. 
 DietfTi(i,2I0 n. 2. 
 Diirl.y, 296 n. 3. 
 Dill man, 344 ii. I. 
 Dilthey, L'74 n G, 611. 
 
 Diogenes of ApoUonia, 53* f. 
 
 Diogenes of Laerte, 7. 
 
 Diogenes of Sinope, 74*. 
 
 Diouysius, 199*. 
 
 Dippe, 611. 
 
 Dixon, 240 u. 2. 
 
 Dods, 188 n. 1. 
 
 Dogmatism, 1 n. 1. 
 
 Donaldson, 9 n. 2. 
 
 Douisthorpe, 611. 
 
 Doriiig, 609. 
 
 Dorner, 188 n. 1, 005, 608. 
 
 Douglas, 581 n. 2. 
 
 Dourif, 147 n. 4. 
 
 Draper, 12 u. 11, 159 n. 1. 
 
 DreydorU, 322 n. 1. 
 
 Drobiscl), 542* n. 2, 605. 
 
 Droysen, 611. 
 
 Droz, 322 n. 1. 
 
 Drummond, 9 u. 2, 163 n. 1. 
 
 Dualism, 1 u. 1 ; Descartes's, 305 ff. 
 
 Du Bois-Keymond, 407 u. 1, 563 n. 5, 
 
 585*. 
 Du Boulay, 233 n, 1. 
 Duff, 557 "n. 1. 
 Diihring, 15, 563 n. 5, 583* n. 1, 605, 
 
 608. 
 Dummler, 73 n. 4. 
 Duncan, 344 n. 1. 
 Duncker, 7 n. 9. 
 Duns Scotus, 9, 202, 246* ff. ; his doc 
 
 trine of freedom, 248. 
 Dupuy, 563* n. 5. 
 Durand, 610. 
 
 Durand de Laur, 148 n. 1. 
 Dutens, 344 n. 1. 
 Dynamism, 1 n. 1. 
 
 Enr.iMiAUi), 473 n. 2. 
 Kckhart, 199, 260*. 
 Kckhoff, 435 n. 2. 
 Eclecticism, Greek, 162 ff. 
 Ei.slcr, 210 n. 2. 
 Eleatic philosojihy, 24* fl. 
 Eleatics, 74, 80, 95, .537. 
 Eliot, George, 502 n. 3. 
 Ellis, 104 n. 4, 290 n. 3. 
 KIscnhans, G09. 
 Elwes. 323 n. 1.
 
 618 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Emanation, 190 ff. 
 
 Empedocles, 44* ff., GO, 95, 41i u. 1. 
 
 Empiricism, 1 u. 1. 
 
 Eugel, 433* n. 2. 
 
 Eugelhardt, 199 u. 1, 230 n. 2. 
 
 Epictetus, 146 n. 1, 148 n. 1, 147, 
 
 Epicurus, 73, 75, 134* ff. ; his etliics, 
 138 f. ; his metaphysics, 135 f . ; his 
 conception of philosophy, 135 ; his 
 conception of soul and immortality, 
 137 f. ; his tlieology, 136 f. 
 
 Epistemology, bibliography of, G05 f. 
 
 Eratosthenes, 161. 
 
 Erdmann, B., 434 u. 2, 435 u. 3. 
 
 Erdmann, J., 14, 344 n. 1, .533*. 
 
 Erenuius, 166*. 
 
 Erigena, Scotus, 9, 199, 201, 204* ff., 
 235. 
 
 Espiuas, 607. 
 
 Essence and Appearance, Hegel's doc- 
 trine of, 504 ff. 
 
 Ethics, bibliograpliy of, 608. 
 
 Eucken, 12 n. 11, 15 u. 9, 106 n. 2. 
 
 Euclid, 161. 
 
 Euclides, 70, 74* f., 75. 
 
 Eudffimonism, 75. 
 
 Euhemerus, 72*. 
 
 Eunapius, 8. 
 
 Eusebius, 7. 
 
 Everett, 481 n. 1. 
 
 Evolution, 560 ff. 
 
 Evolution of Man, 570 f. 
 
 Exner, 542 n. 2. 
 
 Experimental psychology, bibliography 
 of, 607. 
 
 Eyssenhardt, 199 n. 3. 
 
 Fabre, 15. 
 Fabricius, 7 n. 5. 
 Falckenberg, 12 n. 11, 264 n. 1 
 Faraday, 563* n. 5. 
 Farel, 276. 
 Farrer, 391 n. 1. 
 Fathers, 185* ff. 
 Faugere, 322 n. 1. 
 Fechner, G., 588* 606. 
 Fechner, H. A., 278 n. 6. 
 Fere', 608. 
 Ferguson, A., 390*. 
 
 Ferguson, B., 610. 
 
 Ferrari, 295 u. 1. 
 
 Ferraz, 188 n. 1. 
 
 Ferri, 268 u. 3, 273 n. 1 . 
 
 Ferrier, 8 n. 6. 
 
 Feuerbach, L., 318 n. 2, 344 n. 1, 561*. 
 
 Fichte, J. G., 11, 74, 474, 481* ff., 495, 
 
 544, 596 ; his relation to Hegel, 498 f. ; 
 
 to Schelling, 488 f. 
 Fichte, J. H., 4S1 n. 1, 588*. 
 Ficinus, Marsilius, 1G7 n. 1, 264* f., 
 
 269 n. 1. 
 Fioreutino, 268 n. 3, 273 n. 1, 286 n. 2. 
 Fischer, E. L., 605. 
 Fischer, K., 12, 201 u. 3, 296 n. 3, 474 
 
 n. 2, 533* 544 u. 1, 605. 
 Fiske, 581* n. 3. 
 Flint, 15 n. 9, 295 n. 1, 611. 
 Florio, 273 n. 3. 
 Floss, 205 11. 1. 
 Fludd, 278*. 
 Flugel, 542 n. 2. 
 Fontenelle, 399* n. 1. 
 Forel, 608. 
 Forster, 462 u. 2. 
 Fortlage, 12 n. 11, 146 n. 1. 
 Foucher de Careil, 305 u. 1, 344 n. 1, 
 
 496 u. 3, 544 u. 1. 
 Fouille'e, 15, 63 n. 1, 76 n. 2, 607. 
 Fowler, 296 n. 3, 370 n. 1, 390 n. 2, 605 
 
 608. 
 Fracastor, 284*. 
 Franck, 15, 268 n. 3, 590 n. 3. 
 Fraser, 370 u. 1, 371 n. 1, 392 n. 5. 
 Frau&nstadt, 544 n. 1, 557* n. 1. 
 Frederick II., 3G8 u. 1. 
 Freethinkers, 390*. 
 Freret, 63 u. 1. 
 
 Freudeuthal, 25 n. 1, 296 n. 3. 
 Fries, A. de, 370 n. 1. 
 Fries, J. F., 474*. 
 Frisch, 283 n. 3. 
 Frith, 286 n. 2. 
 Froschammer, 590*. 
 Fulbert, 222. 
 FuUerton, 323 n. 1. 
 
 Gaisford, 8 n. 3, n. 5. 
 
 Gale, 180 u. 7, 181 n. 1, 205 n. I.
 
 INDEX 
 
 619 
 
 Galileo, 160, 283*, 306. 
 Gallupi, 296 n. 1. 
 Gallwitz, 609. 
 Galton, 609. 
 Garnier, 305 n. 1. 
 Garve, 390 u. 5, 433 n. 2. 
 Gass, 9 u. 2, 609. 
 Gassemli, 274* 306, 318. 
 Gaunilo, 217, 461. 
 Gedike, 7 u. 2. 
 Geel, 59 u. 1. 
 Geiger, 10 n. 1, 588 u. 6. 
 Gennadius, 263, 267. 
 Geuoude, 320 n. 2. 
 Georgius of Trebizoiid, 263, 267. 
 Gerhert, 211. 
 Gerhardt, C. J., 344 u. 1. 
 Gerhardt, 0. 185 u. 1. 
 Gerkrath, 274 u. 2. 
 Gerlaud, 607. 
 Germain, Sophie, 574 u. 2. 
 Gersou, 261*. 
 Gervaise, 199 n. 5. 
 Geulincx, 318* 320 f. 
 Gfrorer, 163 u. 1, 286 u. 2, 323 n. I. 
 Gilbert de la Porree, 227* 235. 
 Gildeineister, 473 u. 6. 
 Giles, 201 n. 1, 227 u. 3. 
 Gioberti, 295 u. 1, 590*. 
 Gizycki, G., 390 n. 2, 391 n. 2, 608. 
 Gizycki P., 134 u. 1. 
 Glaser, lOS n. 3. 
 Glogau, 305 n. 1. 
 Gnostics, 164. 
 Goerenz, 7 n. 2. 
 Goethals, 251. 
 Goethe, 76 n. 1. 
 G(ittling, 74 11. 1. 
 Goldt>achf-r, 166 u. 2. 
 GoMfriedrich, 468 n. I. 
 Gon7,ale.s, 241 n. 2. 
 (joodwiii, 166 n. 1. 
 Gordy, 12 n. 8. 
 GorgiiLS, 32. 
 Grant, 104 n. 4. 
 Gnitry, 590*. 
 
 Greccf, 370 n. 1, .533* n. 1, 608. 
 fircek chiircli, 262 ff. : CmU, 17 ff . ; 
 philoMophy, biiiliograjdiy of, fi ff. and 
 
 note.s ; pliilosophy, jieriods and origin 
 of, 4 n. 5. 17 ff. ; religion, 17 ff. 
 
 Green, 434 n. 2, 533 n. 1. 
 
 Gregory of Xazianz, 187. 
 
 Gregory of Nyssa, 187. 
 
 Griesingor, 607. 
 
 Grimblot, 487 n. 1. 
 
 Grimm, 12 n. 11, 305 u. 1, 600. 
 
 Grisebach, 544 n. 1. 
 
 Groo.s, 610. 
 
 Grote, 8 u. 6, 17 u. 1, 37 n. 2, 63 n. 1, 
 76 n. 2, 104 u. 4, 133 a. 1, 
 
 Grove, 563 u. 5. 
 
 Gruber, 573 n. 2. 
 
 Griin, 561 n. 1. 
 
 Guliraucr, 344 n. 1. 
 
 Guruey, 608. 
 
 Giiyau, 133 u. 1, 608, 610. 
 
 Gwinner, 544 n. 1. 
 
 Haas, 148 u. 2. 
 
 Ilaeckcl, 560 n. 1, 562* 564 n. 3, 567. 
 
 llaeghen, 320 u. 1. 
 
 Hagen, 274 u. 6. 
 
 Ilaldane, 497 u. 8, 544 u. 3. 
 
 llaller, .506 n. 1. 
 
 llamann, J. G., 473*. 
 
 Hamaiin, O., 560 n. 1. 
 
 Hamilton, \V., 430 n. 3, 431* n. 3, 4. 
 
 Hammer-Purg.stall, 210 n. 2. 
 
 Hanne, 610. 
 
 Harms, 12 n. 1 1 , 15 n. 9, 473 n. 5, 606,608. 
 
 Harnack, 9 ii. 2, 167 n. 1, 185, u. 1. 
 
 Ilarjjf, 59 n. 1. 
 
 Harris, 434 n. 2, 496 n. 3, 497 u. 2, 533* 
 
 n. 1. 
 Hart, 55 n. 3. 
 Harten.stein, 15 n. 9, 344 n. 1, 434 n. 2, 
 
 .535 n. 2, 5-J2* n. 2. 
 Hartley, 406* f. 
 Harttnann, II, 91 n. 2,496 n. l,542u.2, 
 
 557* ff., 560 n. 1, 608, 610. 
 Harvey, 272, 284*. 
 Hasse, 211 n. 4. 
 
 Hastio. 12 n. 11. 4.16 n. fi, 407 o. 6. 
 Hatch, 104 M 4. 390 ii. 2. 
 Haun'au, 9 n. 2. 
 Haiisratli, 222 n. 1, 562 n 3. 
 Havet, 322 n. I
 
 620 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Hayduck, 6 n. 4. 
 
 Have, 586 n. 4. 
 
 llaym, 487 n. 1, 496 n. 3, 544 n. 1. 
 
 Ilazlitt, 273 u. 3. 
 
 1 1 earn, 611. 
 
 Heath, 296 n. 3. 
 
 Hebenstreit, 181 n. 1- 
 
 Hedoiiism, Greek, 71*ff., 134 ff. 
 
 Heeren, 8 u. 3. 
 
 Hegel, 11, 14, 52, 56, 79, 183 u. 1, 202 
 n. 1, 203 11. 3, 249 n. 1, 264 u. 1, 285 
 n. 1, 291, 496* ff., 537 f ., 594 ff . ; his 
 ethics, 514 ff. ; aud Fichte, Kaut, aud 
 Schelliug, 498 ff.; his logic, 500 ff.; 
 his philosophy of art, 521 ff. ; his 
 philosophy of mind, 513 ff. ; his phi- 
 losophy of nature, 510 ff. ; his philoso- 
 phy of philosophy, 531 f.; his philo- 
 sophy of religion, 528 ff. ; his politics, 
 533 ff. 
 
 Hegelian school, 533 ff. 
 
 Hegesias, 72* f. 
 
 Heinichen, 7 n. 10. 
 
 Heinze, 142 u. 1, 145 n. 1, 163 u. 1, 305 
 n. 1. 
 
 Heitz, 107 n. 1. 
 
 Heliocentric theory, 283, 287. 
 
 Helinholtz, 563* n. 5, 585* f., 597 u. 1. 
 
 Hehnont, 278, 345 n. 1. 
 
 Helvetius, 414*. 
 
 Henderson, 434 n. 2. 
 
 Heraclitus, 6 n. 1, 33* ff., 60, 75, 80, 
 123, 335, 491 n. 4, 589 n. 4. 
 
 Herbart, 11, 148 n. 1, 535* ff., 594 ff. 
 
 Herbartians, 370* n. 2. 
 
 Herder, 370 n. 2, 473* 475. 
 
 Hermann, C, 611. 
 
 Hermann, K. F., 59 n. 1, 76 n. 2, 78 n. 1. 
 
 Hertling, 370 n. 1. 
 
 Hesiod,' 18 f. 
 
 Heussler, 296 n. 3. 
 
 Hibbeu, 605. 
 
 Hicetas, 160. 
 
 Higginson, 148 n. 1. 
 
 Hilfiebert of Lavardin, 211* 225. 
 
 Hillcbrand, 544 n. 2. 
 
 Hipparclius, 161. 
 
 Plippasiis, 37 n. 1, 46. 
 
 Hippolytus, 7. 
 
 Hirn, 563* n. 5. 
 
 Hirth, 610. 
 
 Hirzel, 140 n. 1, 148 n. 1, 148 n. 2. 
 
 History, bibliography of philosophy of, 
 
 611. 
 Hobbes, 11, 300* ff., 318, 359, 370 n. 2, 
 
 378, 378 n. 1, 414. 
 Hoffding, 12 n. 11, 606, 609. 
 Hoffmann, F., 589 n. 3. 
 Holbach, 11, 414*. 
 Holland, 611. 
 Home, 391* u. 2. 
 Homer, 18 f., 117 n. 4, 
 Horace, 71 n. 2, 139. 
 Horn, 78 n. 1. 
 Horwicz, 606. 
 Hoschel, 8 n. 4. 
 Hough, 12 n. 8. 
 Iluber, 9 u. 2, 205 n. 1. 
 Hiibuer, 7 u. 6. 
 Huet, 318*. 
 
 Hugo of St. Victor, 199, 227 *ff. 
 Huit, 76 n. 2. 
 Humboldt, A., 281 n. 2. 
 Hume, 6, 11, 156, 317, 417* ff., 435,445, 
 
 537. 
 Hussou, 487 u. 1. 
 Hutcheson, 390*. 
 Hnxley, 560 u. 1, 563 n. 3. 
 Hylozoism, 597. 
 Hypnotism, bibliography of, 608. 
 
 Ib\-Topiiail, 216 n. 2. 
 
 Idea, Plato's, 81 ff. 
 
 Idealism, 1 n. 1 ; Augustine's, 125 f.; 
 Berkeley's, 393 ff. ; Greek, 75 ff . ; Kant 
 and, 473 ; realism and, in Middle 
 Ages, 220 n. 1. 
 
 Ideas, Kant's doctrine of, 451 ff. 
 
 Immanency, 1 n. 1, 233 f. 
 
 Immortality, Plato's idea of, 97 f. 
 
 Induction, Bacon's, 298 ff . 
 
 Intellectual intuition, 493. 
 
 Intellectualism, 249 n. 1. 
 
 Intelligible character, 465. 
 
 lonians, 21 ff. 
 
 Isidore of Alexandria, 184 n. 1. 
 
 Isidore of Sevilla, 200*. 
 
 Israel, A., 278 n. 2.
 
 INDEX 
 
 621 
 
 JaCKSOX, 146 11. 1. 
 
 Jacques, 108 ii. ,5. 
 
 Jacohi, 9 ii. 2, 473* 587. 
 
 Janiblichus, 181* f. 
 
 James, G06. 
 
 Janimv, 240 ii. 2. 
 
 Jauet, Paul, 14, 15 n. 9, 344 u. 1, 496 
 
 n. 3, 562 u. 4, 590 n. 8, 591* n. 1, 608, 
 
 609. 
 Jauet, Pierre, 608. 
 Jaiisen, 322. 
 Jebb, 258 ii. 2. 
 Jerome, 196. 
 Jevous, 581 n. 2, 605. 
 Jewish-Greek philosopliy, 163 ff. 
 Jheriug, 608. 
 JotU, 12 n. 2, 609. 
 Joel, K., 65 n. 1, 78 u. 2. 
 Joel, M., 210 n. 2. 
 Johu of Damas, 200*. 
 Jolin of Mercuria, 257*. 
 John of Salisl)iiry, 227*. 
 John Pliilopouus, 199*. 
 Joly, 320 u. 2. 
 Jones, 542 n. 2. 
 Jouffroy, 590*. 
 
 Jourdain, A., 235 u. 1. 318 n. 8. 
 Jourdaiu, C, 241 ii. 2, 318 u. 7. 
 Jowett, 104 u. 4. 
 Jowett's Plato, 76 n. 2. 
 Junilt, 260 n 2. 
 
 Jurisprudence, hihi.iography of, 611. 
 Justin the Martyr, 186. 
 Justinian, 184. 
 
 Kai TAN, 55 n. 2, 610. 
 
 Kappes, 104 n. 4. 
 
 Kant, 6, 17,45n. 1,51, 71, 101,249n. 1 
 317, 369 n. 1, 378 n. 1, 397 n. 1, 431 
 434* ff., 495, 537 ff., 542 n. 2, 587 
 597 ; hi.s aesthetics, 468 ff. ; his anti 
 nomies, 456 ff. ; his critique of cosmo 
 lojjical arfrument, 461, of cosmolof^y 
 456 ff., of judgment, 468 ff., of phy- 
 sico th(ologi<al argument, 461 f., of 
 practii'al rea.son, 462 ff., of psychi'l- 
 ogv, 453 ff., of pure reason, 4'I7 ff., 
 of seiiHihility, 440 ff., of understand- 
 ing, 444 ff. ; his doctrine of idciis, 4 14, 
 
 451 ff., of space and time, 440 ff. 
 of will and freedom, 463 ff. ; his 
 ethics, 461 ff. ; and German idealism, 
 473 ff. ; and Hegel, 499 f. ; his prim- 
 acy of practical reason, 466 f. ; his 
 schematism, 477 ff . ; and his succes- 
 sors, 450 f. ; liis teleology, 468 ff. 
 
 Karsten, 24 u. 2, 44 n. 1. 
 
 Kaulich, 9 n. 2. 
 
 Kedney, 496 u. 3. 
 
 Kehrhacii, 434 n. 2, 535 u. 2. 
 
 Kemp, 544 n. 3. 
 
 Kenyou, 104 n. 4. 
 
 Kepler, 160, 283* 
 
 Kern, 25 n. 1. 
 
 Keynes, 605. 
 
 King, Lord, 370 n. 1. 
 
 Kirchhoff, A., 167 n 1, 607. 
 
 Kirchmann, 15 n. 9, 32.'{ n. 1, 434 n. 2. 
 583* n. 1. 
 
 Kircliuer, C. II., 167 u. 1, 182 n. 1. 
 
 Kirchuer, F., 15. 
 
 Kleiher, 259 n. 2. 
 
 Klett, 65 n. 1. 
 
 Knight, 15 n. 9, 610. 
 
 Knutzeu, 433* n. 2. 
 
 K61)er, 557 n. 1. 
 
 Koch, 305 n. 1. 
 
 Kochly, 63 n. 1. 
 
 Konig, 12 n. 11, 606. 
 
 Ivistlin, 8 n. 6, 496 u. 3, 609, 610, 
 
 Koi)|), 184 n. 1, 199 n. 3. 
 
 Krafft-Khing, 607, 603. 
 
 Krause, 587 *f. 
 
 Krauth, 392 u. 3. 
 
 Krische, 21 n. 1, 148 n. 1. 
 
 Kroeger, 481 n. 1. 
 
 Krug, 473*. 
 
 Kiihlenheck, 287 n. 2, n. 3. 
 
 Kiilpe, 607. 
 
 Kurella, 12 n. II, 606. 
 
 Knssinaul, 607. 
 
 Kvacsala, 278 n. 5. 
 
 La AS, 583* n. 1. 
 Lahriula. 63 n. 1 
 Lachelier, 590* n 7. 
 Laciiniann, 7 n 1, 55 n 3. 
 Lactantins, 9, \x(\, I'.Hi.
 
 622 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Ladd, 4, 542 n. 2, 606, 610. 
 
 Laforet, 8 n. 6. 
 
 L.tgarde, 286 n. 2. 
 
 Lagrange, 11, 399 u. 1. 
 
 Limarck, 563*, 565. 
 
 Lambert, 433* u. 2. 
 
 Lameiinais, 589*. 
 
 LaMettrie, 411* f., 317. 
 
 Lamothe-Levayer, 274*. 
 
 Lancelot, 322. 
 
 Land, 320 u. 1, 323 n. I. 
 
 Lanfranc, 211*. 
 
 Lange, C, 606. 
 
 Lange, F. A., 11, 14, 410 ii. 7, 584* f., 
 605. 
 
 Laugley, 344 n. 1. 
 
 Laplace, II, 51, 399 n. 1. 
 
 Laromigiiiere, 590 n. 5. 
 
 Lasalle, 33 u. 1, 296 n. 3. 
 
 Lassou, 260 n. 2, 2S7 n. 1, 298 u. 2. 
 
 Lasswitz, 12 n. 11, 437 u. 1. 
 
 Laugel, 37 u. 2. 
 
 Laureutius Valla, 263*. 
 
 Laiiret, 581 n. 2. 
 
 Laurie, 8 n. 6, 9 u. 2, 608. 
 
 Laveleye, 611. 
 
 Lavoisier, 407 n. 2. 
 
 Law, 278 u. 6. 
 
 Lazarus, 542* n. 2, 606. 
 
 Leehler, 12 n. 11, 391 n. 3. 
 
 Lecky, 9 n. 2, 12 u. 1, 609. 
 
 Le Cierc, 7 n. 2, 273 n. 3. 
 
 Leferon, 239 n. 2. 
 
 Leferriere, 140 n. 1. 
 
 Letevre, 15. 
 
 Lehmann, 607. 
 
 Lehnerdt, 10 n. 1. 
 
 Lehrs, 8 n. 6, 17 n. 1. 
 
 Leibniz, 6, 11, 113 n. 3, 130 n. .3, 291, 
 293 n. 2, 343* £f., 370 n. 2, 372 n. 2, 
 382, 386, 390, 404, 435, 456, 538, 591, 
 594 ff. ; and Cartesianism, 353 ff. ; and 
 the Cartesians, 346 ff. ; his determin- 
 ism, 359 f., 364 ff. ; his doctrine of 
 force, 346 ff. ; his doctrine of immor- 
 tality, 353 f . ; his doctrine of pre-estab- 
 lished harmony, 349 ff. ; his notion of 
 reciprocal action, 3.)3 ff. ; his rational- 
 ism, 363 f. ; and Ficlite, 366 ff. ; and 
 
 Spinoza, 359 ff. ; his theodicy, 360 ff. ; 
 his theory of knowledge, 366 f . ; his 
 theory of monads, 348 ff. ; his theory 
 of unconscious perceptions, 345 f. ; 
 WoltHau philosophy and, 433* n. 2. 
 
 Lemaire, 7 u. 1. 
 
 Leo X., 264. 
 
 Leontinus Pilatus, 262. 
 
 Lerou.x, 533 n. 1, 592 u. 2. 
 
 Lessing, 369 u. 1, 433* u. 2, 475. 
 
 Leucippus, 55*. 
 
 Le'vy-Bruhl, 473 u. 5. 
 
 Lewes, 15, 104 u. 4, 581* a. 3. 
 
 Lewis, 607. 
 
 L'Herbette, 574 u. 2. 
 
 Liard, 55 u. 3, 606. 
 
 Lieber, 611. 
 
 Liebig, 298 u. 2. 
 
 Liebnaann, 434 n. 1, 584 n. 2. 
 
 Liebner, 227 u. 5. 
 
 Liegeois, 608. 
 
 Liepmanu, 55 u. 3. 
 
 Lightfoot, 148 n. 1. 
 
 Linde, van der, 323 n. 1. 
 
 Lindner, 542 n. 2. 
 
 Linnaeus, 564. 
 
 Lioy, 611. 
 
 Lipps, 600 n. 1, 606, 610. 
 
 Lipsius, 185 n. 1, 274* 
 
 Littre, 573 n. 2, 574*. 
 
 Lobeck, 19 n. 3. 
 
 Locke, 6, 11, 130 n. 3, 253, 317, 366, 
 370* ff., 391 f. ; his faculties of uu. 
 derstanding, 380; his idea of the cer- 
 titude of knowledge, 387 ff. ; his de- 
 nial of innate ideas, 372 ff. ; and 
 Leibniz, 366 ff. ; his simple and mixed 
 modes, 382 ff. ; his nominalism, 385 ff. ; 
 his free will, 381 f. ; his philosophy 
 of language, 384 f. ; his primary and 
 secondary qualities, 378 ff. ; his doc- 
 trine of substance, 383 f. ; his simple 
 and complex ideas, 376 ff. ; his theory 
 of space, 385 ff. 
 
 Logic, bibliography of, 605 f. 
 
 Lommatzsch, 7 n. 8. 
 
 Long, 148 u. 1. 
 
 Longinus, 166*. 
 
 Lotze, 542* n. 2, 588* 605, 606, 610.
 
 <?• 
 
 INDEX 
 
 623 
 
 Lowe, 217 n. 2, 481 n. l. 
 
 Lijwenthal, 573. 
 
 Lowndes, 305 n. 1. 
 
 Lowndes, M., 606. 
 
 Lowrey, 370 u. 2. 
 
 Lubbock, 607. 
 
 Lucas, 323 u. 1. 
 
 Lucretius. 7, 55* 134 n. 1, 139. 
 
 Ludovici, 369* u. 1. 
 
 Lullus, Kayiuuudus, 9, 259* 2S7. 
 
 Luptou, 199 n. 1. 
 
 Lutliardt, 8 u. 6, 9 n. 2, 609. 
 
 Luther, 276. 
 
 Lutoslawski, 286 n. 2. 
 
 Lyell, 564* n. 1. 
 
 Lyng, 5.33* u. 1. 
 
 Lyon, 301 u. 1, 398 n. 3. 
 
 Macchiavklli, 264* n. 2. 
 
 Mackenzie, 609. 
 
 Mackie, 344 n. 1. 
 
 Mackintosh, 12 n. 11, 391 u. 2, 609 
 
 Mucull, 148 n. 2. 
 
 Magellan, 282. 
 
 Magic, 265 ff. 
 
 Maguin, 205 n. 2. 
 
 Mahaff}', 8 n. 6, 12 n. 8, 305 n. 1, 435 
 
 n. 3, 436 n. 1. 
 Maiinon, 473*. 
 Maimonides, 210 n. 2. 
 Maine, 611. 
 
 Maine de Biran. 589 n. 2, 590*. 601. 
 Mainlriniler, 557* n. 1. 
 Malebranrhe, 11, 195, ."ilS* 320* f., 
 
 .333, 370 n. 2, 391 f., 398 n. 3. 
 Mall'-t, 22 n. 1, 74 n. 2. 
 Maniiani, 295 n. 1. 
 Mandevillc, 414*. 
 Mansel. 185 n. 1. 
 Marcianus Capella, 199*. 
 Manns Aurelius, 146 n. 1, 147, 148 n. 1. 
 Mariano, 286 n. 2, 295 n. 1. 
 Marinns. 182 n. 1, 184 n. 1. 
 Marion, 370 n. 1. 
 Marsh.'ill, II. R., 610. 
 .Mar'diall, .!., 8 n. 6. • 
 Mar-ilins Ficinns, see Ficinun. 
 MarHiliuM of Inghen, 256*. 
 
 Martensen, 609. 
 
 Martha, 151 u. 1. 
 
 Martineau, H., 573 u. 2. 
 
 Martiueau, J., 323 u. 1, 609. 
 
 Martins, 563 n. 1. 
 
 Massol, 467 u. 1. 
 
 Masson, 55 u. 2, 562 u. 4. 
 
 Materialism, 1 note 1 ; cighteentli cen 
 tury, 404ff. ; German, 560 ff. ; Greek, 
 55 "ff., 75 ; of Ilobbcs, 301 f. ; and 
 sensationalism, 402 n. 2. 
 
 Matter, 185 n. 1, 166 n. 3. 
 
 Matter, I'lato's conception of, 92 ff. 
 
 Maudsley, 606. 
 
 Manpertnis, 399* n. 1. 
 
 Maximus the Confessor, 199* 
 
 Maxwell, J., 391 u.2. 
 
 Mayer, 563* u. 5. 
 
 Mayor, 8 n. 6. 
 
 Mayr, 399 u. 1. 
 
 McCosh, 430 n. 3, 431 n. 3. 
 
 Mechanism, 1 n. 1. 
 
 MediiBval philosuj)hy, 5, 185* ff. ; bibli- 
 ography of, 9 ff. and notes. 
 
 Megarians, 74* f. 
 
 Meiklojohn, 435 n.3. 
 
 Meineke. 8 n. 3. 
 
 Melancthon, 278. 
 
 Melissns, 30* f. 
 
 Mendelssohn, 369 n. 1, 433* n. 2. 
 
 Menzies, 12 n. 11. 
 
 Merz, 344 n. 1 . 
 
 Me.slier, 411. 
 
 Meyer, 324 n. 1. 
 
 Meynert, 607. 
 
 Michaud. 221 n. 1. 
 
 Michclet, 12, 108 n. 3, 5.3.3*. 
 
 -Middleman, 10 n. 1. 
 
 Migne, 9 n. 1, 188 n. 1. 
 
 .Vlignet, 487 n. 1. 
 
 Mill, J. S., 11, 431 n. 4, 573 n. 2, 574, 
 5S1* ff., 605, 008. 
 
 Miller, 611. 
 
 Miller, K., 7 n. 9. 
 
 .Millet, 305 n. 1. 
 
 Minil, 5S6 n. 7. 
 
 Minto, 605. 
 
 Miral)aiid, 414. 
 
 Miidcr;itns, 165.
 
 624 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Modern philosophy, 286 if. ; hibliogra- 
 
 phy of, 1 1 ff . aud uotes. 
 MOller, 185 u. 1. 
 Mohl, 611. 
 Moleschott, 562* 
 Moleswortli, 301 u. I. 
 Moll, 608. 
 Mollet, 391. 
 Mouad, 348 ff. 
 Mouchamp, 317 n. 2. 
 Monism, 1 u. 1, 560 ff., 596 ff. ; Plato's, 
 
 101. 
 Monist, 586 n. 7. 
 Monrad, 12 u. 11, 533* n. 1, 610. 
 Moutaigiie, 273* f., 296 u. 3, 308, 322 
 
 n. 1. 
 Montesquieu, 11. 
 Moutucia, 159 u. 1. 
 Morgan, L., 560 n. 1, 607. 
 Morgan, T., 391* n. 3. 
 Moriu, 467 n. 1. 
 
 Morley, 104 n. 4, 399 n. 1,412 n. 2. 
 Morris, 15 n. 9, 437 n. 1, 496 n. 3. 
 Morselli, 609. 
 Moser, 167 n. 1. 
 Moulinie', 563 n. 3. 
 Mijller, H., 76 n. 2, 318 n. 6. 
 Miiller, K. O., 8 n. 6. 
 Miiller, M., 435 u. 3, 611. 
 Miinsterberg, 606, 609. 
 Muirhead, 15 n. 9. 
 Mullach, 6 n. 1, 8 u. 6. 
 Munck, 78 n. 1, 210 n. 2, 265 n. 1. 
 Munro, 7 n. 1, 55 n. 2. 
 Mysticism, 259 ff., 493 n. 1 ; medieval, 
 
 227 ff. ; Plato's, 91. 
 
 Nahlowskt, 542* n. 2. 
 
 Napier, 284*. 
 
 Natorp, 55 n. 3, 59 n. 1, 148 n. 2, 283 
 
 n. 3, 305 n. 1. 
 Natural selection, 565 ff. 
 Naturalism, 1 n. 1. 
 Nature, Plato's doctrine of, 91 ff. 
 Naville, 180 n. 1, 589*, 590 n. 7. 
 Neander, 9 n. 2, 185 n. 1, 188 n. 1. 
 Nemours, 414 n. 4. 
 Neo-Criticism, 573 ff. 
 Neo-Kantians, 583 ff. 
 
 Neo-Platouism, 167 * ff., 210 n. 2, 265 ff.. 
 
 493, 596. 
 Newman, 104 n. 4. 
 Newton, 11, 306, 390*, 399 n. 1. 
 Nichol, 296 n. 3. 
 Nicholai, 369 n. 1, 433* n. 2. 
 Nicholas of Autricuria, 257*. 
 Nicholas of Clemanges, 261*. 
 Nicholas of Cusa, 10, 264*, 287. 
 Nicole, 318* 322. 
 Nicomachus, 165. 
 Nietzsche, 557* n. 1, 609. 
 Noire', 560 n. 1. 
 Nolen, 434 n. 2. 
 Nolte, 241 n. 2. 
 Nominalism, 240, 252 ff. ; and the 
 
 Church, 255; and Realism, 219 ff. 
 Nominalists and Realists, 203. 
 Notion, Hegel's doctrine of, 508 ff. 
 Nourrisson, 14, 344 n. 1. 
 Novaro, 320 n. 2. 
 Numenius, 165. 
 
 Objective and Subjective in Middle 
 
 Ages, 220 n.l. 
 Occam, 252, 389. 
 Oersted, 495. 
 Oettingen, 609. 
 Ogereau, 140 n. 1. 
 Oken, 495. 
 
 Olle-Laprune, 320n. 2. 
 Oman, 587 n. 2. 
 Ontological Argument, Auselmus's, 
 
 217; Descartes's, 310 f. ; Kant's cri 
 
 tique of, 461. 
 Ontology, 1 u. 1. 
 Oordt, Van, 76 n. 2- 
 Opel, 278 n. 2. 
 Orelli, 76n. 2. 
 Origan, 7, 9, 187* 191. 
 Orpheus, 1, 9. 
 Oswald, 431*. 
 Oxenford, 296 n. 3 
 
 Palet, 391* n. 2. 
 Panietius, 147. 
 Panentlieism, 588. 
 Panlogism, 249 n. 1. 
 Pantheism, 1 n. 1, 233 f., 597.
 
 ct 
 
 INDEX 
 
 625 
 
 Panthelism, 249 a. 1. 
 
 Panzerbieter, 5.3 n. 3. 
 
 Paracelsus, 267*. 
 
 Parmenides, 5, 26* ff., 74 f ., 335, 538, 596. 
 
 Parthey, 181 u. 1. 
 
 Pascal, 306, 322*, 463. 
 
 Pater, 76 n. 2. 
 
 Patrick, 33u. 1. 
 
 Patristic, 185ff. 
 
 Patrizzi, 273*. 
 
 Paul, Kegan,322n. 1. 
 
 Paulsen, 4, 1 2 u. 11 , 1 5 u. 9, ! 7 n. 2, 434 
 
 n. 2, 588* n. 8, 609. 
 Paulus, 323 n. I. 
 Pearson, 140 n. 2. 
 Peip. 278 n. 6. 
 Pelagianisiii, 248 f. 
 Pelagians, 197. 
 Pellissier, 263 n. 1. 
 Perez, 607. 
 
 Peripateticism, 210 n. 2, 235 £f., 597. 
 Peripatetics, 105, 267 ff. 
 Perry, 12 n. 11. 
 Pesciiel, 10 M. 1, 281 n. 2, 607. 
 Peter the Lombard, 9, 232* f., 239. 
 Peter the Venerable, 223. 
 Peters, 104 n. 4. 
 Petrarch, 262. 
 Peyron, 44 n. 1. 
 Pfleiderer, E., 33 n. 1, 320 n. 1, 344 u. 1, 
 
 437 n. 1. 
 Pfleiderer, 0., 9 n. 2, 12 n. U, 610. 
 Phado, 75. 
 Phelps, 12 n. 11. 
 
 Phenomenon, Kant's definition of, 449 f. 
 Pherecydes, 19,38. 
 Philo, 163* f. 
 Philolau.-^, 37. 
 
 Philosophical .Journal.'?, 15 n. 9. 
 Photius, 8, 200*. 
 Physico-tlieological argument, Kaut'8 
 
 critique of, 461 f. 
 Pico, 265*, 272. 
 Pierron, 104 n 4. 
 Pillr.n, 320 n. 2, 584* n. }. 
 Pindar, 19. 
 Platner, 4.33* n. 2. 
 Plato, 5 f., 46 n. 2, 50, 65, 70, 75 * ff.. 105, 
 
 109, 112,134,150 l>r5 (1,385, t.lOu. 2, 
 
 451 n.3,491 ;;.5, 493 n. 1,538,594 ff. ; 
 his ethics. 9S ff. ; antl geometry, 80 f. ; 
 his uiytlis, 79 ; his piiilosopiiy of 
 nature, 91 ff. ; his doctriue of pro- 
 e.xisteuce, 98 ; his rationalism, 89 ff. ; 
 his psyciiology, 97 f. ; iiis realism, 82 
 ff., 101 ff. ; his teleology, 95 ff . ; hie 
 theulogv, 88 f. ; his theory of state, 
 99 ff. " 
 
 Platonic .\cademy in Florence, 263 f. 
 
 Platoiiisin. Christian, 185 ff.; and medi- 
 a.'val I'eripateticism, 235 ff. ; and Scho- 
 histicisiii, 219 ff. 
 
 Pletiio, 203* 267. 
 
 Plinv, 139. 
 
 Plotiiius, 7, 46 u. 2,56, 91, 167* ff., 347, 
 493 u. 1, 496 n. 2 ; ids ethics, 176 ff. ; 
 his tlieology, 168 ff. ; liis theory of 
 emanation, 171 ff. ; his tlieory of intel- 
 lect, soul, and body, 171 ff. 
 
 Pluralism, 596 ff. 
 
 Plutarch, 7, 166*. 
 
 Polemo, 104, 140. 
 
 Politics, bibliography of, 611. 
 
 Pollock, 323 n. 1, 611. 
 
 Pompey, 147. 
 
 Pomponatius, 10, 268* ff. 
 
 Porphyry, 7, 37 u. 2, 167, 179 * f., 200. 
 
 Porta,' 271*. 
 
 Porter, 462 n. 2, 609. 
 
 Port-Royalists, 318 n. 8, 322 n. 1. 
 
 Posidonius, 147. 
 
 Positivism, 1 n. 1, 573* ff. ; critique of, 
 592 ff. 
 
 Prantl, 14, 15 u. 9, 106 n. 2, 146 u. 1, 106 
 n. 2, 199 n. 5, 53.3*, 606. 
 
 Pre-existence, Plato's doctrine of, 9rt. 
 
 Preger, 227 n. 5. 
 
 Preller. 6 n. 1. 8 n. 6, 17 n. I. 
 
 Pre8sens(5, 9 n. 2. 
 
 Pre'vost, 305 n. 3. 
 
 Pn-vost-I'aradol, 273 n. 3. 
 
 Preyer, 607. 
 
 Prie.stley, 407* ff. 
 
 Primary (|u:i!itic.H, 404, 4.30; and second 
 ary <|ii.iliti(M, 37s f.. 392. 
 
 Probaliilisin, (iriM-k, J 59. 
 
 Prochw, 8, 182» f.. 1H4 n. I. 
 
 Pruta-oKW. 5, 59* ff , CO, 71, 158
 
 Y 
 
 626 
 
 INDEX 
 
 ff. ; 
 
 610. 
 
 and 
 120 
 
 I'rotois, 232 n. 2. 
 rroudhon, 467 n. 1, 533 ii 1. 
 Psychiatry, bibliograpliy of, 607 f. 
 Psychology, bibliography of, 006 
 
 Kant's critique of, 453 ff. 
 Ptolemy, 160 f. 
 Puchta^ll. 
 
 Punjer, 12 n. 11, 462 n. 2,573 n. 2, 
 Pyrrho, 149* 308, 378 n. 1. 
 Pyrrhonism, 148 ff. 
 Pytliagoras, 20, 38* ff., 56, 69 ; 
 
 "Biuldha, 38 n. 1. 
 Pythagoreans, 37* ff., 75, 80, 95 f., 
 n. 2, 160. 
 
 QuADRiviUM, 200 n. 2. 
 
 Ramus, 10, 277 * f. 
 
 Kanke, 607. 
 
 Ectspe, 344 n. 1. 
 
 nationalism, 1 n. 1. 
 
 Raiiweuhoff, 610. 
 
 Ravaisson, 108 n. 3, 140 n. I, 146 n. 1, 
 590* n. 7, 601. 
 
 Pawley, W., 296 n. 3. 
 
 Raymond of Sabunde, 259*. 
 
 Ravmundus Lullus, 9, 259 *, 287. 
 
 Realism, 1 n. 1, 240; Plato's, 82 ff . ; 
 Platonic, 101 ff. ; and idealism in 
 Middle Ages, 220 n. 1 ; and nominal- 
 ism, 219* ff. ; and nominalists, 203. 
 
 Reciprocal action, Hegel's doctrine of, 
 507 f. 
 
 Redepenning, 7 n. 8, 15 n. 1. 
 
 Re'e, 608. 
 
 Reformation, 274 ff. 
 
 Regius, Sylvain, 318. 
 
 Reichel, 8 n. 6. 
 
 Reicke, 7 n. 4, 434 n. 2. 
 
 Reid, 11, 430* f., 587, 591; and cau- 
 sality, 432 n. 2. 
 
 Reimarus, 369 n. 1, 433* n. 2. 
 Reinach, 78 n. 2. 
 Reinhold, 474,*475. 
 Rein-ivald, 233. 
 
 Religion, bibliography of philosophy 
 of, 610 f.; origin of, 17 n. 2. 
 
 Remusat, 12 n. 11, 211 n. 4, 222 n. 7, 
 
 296 n. 3. 
 Kcuaissance, 261 ff. ; bibliograpliy of, 
 
 10 n. 1. 
 Henan, 148 n. 1, 210 n. 2, 586. 
 Kenouvier, 14, 584* n. 1. 
 Re'thore, 399 n. 2. 
 Retrogression in evolution, 567. 
 Keuchlin, 265* 318 n. 8. 
 Renter, 9 n. 2. 
 
 Keville, 15 n. 1, 163 n. 1, 610. 
 Hevue positive, 574 n. 1 ; philosophique, 
 
 586 n. 7. 
 Riaux, 296 u. 3. 
 Kibbeck, 148 u. 1. 
 Kibot, 535 n. 2, 542 u. 2, 544 n. 1, 581 
 
 n. 3, 584, 5S6* u. 7, 608. 
 Richard of St. Victor, 230 * f. 
 Richardson, 8 n. 6. 
 Kichter, 163 u. 1, 167 n. 1. 
 Uiehl, 434 n. 2. 
 Ritchie, 609. 
 Ritschl, 9 u. 2. 
 Ritter, 6 n. 1, 8 u. 6, 9 n. 2, 12, 14, 21 
 
 n. 1, 37 n. 2 ; and Preller, 8 n. 8. 
 Rivista di filosofia, 586 n. 7. 
 Rixner, 267 n. 1. 
 Robert of Lincoln, 236. 
 Robert of Melun, 231* f. 
 Robert Pulleyn, 232 *. 
 Robertsc»i, 104 n. 4, 301 n. 1. 
 Roberty, 12 n. 11. 
 Robinet, 412*, 565. 
 Roth, 4, 8 n. 6, 473 n. 6. 
 Rohde, 8 n. 6. 
 Rolph, 608. 
 Roman Stoicism, 147. 
 Romanes, 560 n. 1, 607. 
 Rondel, 134 n. 1. 
 Roscellinus, 220 * ff., 389. 
 Rose, 104 n. 4. 
 Rosenkranz, 412 n. 2, 434 n. 2, 487 n. 1, 
 
 496 n. 3, 533 *. 
 Rosmini-Serbate, 104 n. 4, 295 n I, 
 
 590*. 
 Roussellot, 9 n. 2. 
 Rovce, 12 n. 11, 497 n. 1. 
 Royer-Collard, 590 *. 
 Rumelin, 609.
 
 <> 
 
 INDEX 
 
 627 
 
 Ruuze, 609. 
 Russel, 371 u. 2. 
 Ruysbroek, 230 u. 2. 
 
 Sainte-Bkive, 318 n. 8. 
 
 Saiut-Germaiu, 305 u. 1. 
 
 Saint-Hilaire, B., 104 u. 4, 108 n. 3. 
 
 Saint-IIilaire, G., 565. 
 
 8t. Johu, 370 n. 1. 
 
 St. Martha, 200 u. 1. 
 
 St. Martin, 278 u. 6. 
 
 St. Paul, 147, 177 n. 2, 178 n. 2, 194. 
 
 St. Reue Taillaudier, 205 ii. 1. 
 
 Saiut-Simon, 574 u. 2. 
 
 Saiutes, 323 n. 1, 434 n. 2. 
 
 Saiutsbury, 273 n. 3. 
 
 Saisset, 153 u. 2, 317 n. 2, 323 n. 1, 434 
 u. 2. 
 
 Salzinf!;er, 259 n. 1. 
 
 Sauchez, 274*. 
 
 Sauuders, 544 u. 5. 
 
 Saussaye, Chautepie de la, 610. 
 
 Scaliger, 271 *. 
 
 Scepticism, 1 n. 1, 253 ; Greek, 148* ff. 
 
 Sce{)tics, 537. 
 
 Schaarschinidt, 37 n. 2, 76 n. 2, 78 u. 1, 
 227 n. 3, 305 n. 1, 323 n. 1, 324 u. 2. 
 
 Schaffle, 611. 
 
 Schaff, 185 n. 1. 
 
 Schaller, 12 n. 11. 
 
 Schanz, 59 n. 1, 76 n. 2. 
 
 Seharj)ff. 264 n. 1. 
 
 Schauliacii, 48 n. 2. 
 
 Schelliiig, 11, 91, 170 n. 1, 195, 264 n. 1, 
 482 n. 1, 487* ff., 601 ; aud Fichte, 
 488 ff. ; and Hegel, 498 f. ; liis nega- 
 tive philosophy, 488 ff.; his positive 
 philosopliy, 494 f. 
 
 Scherer, 496 n. 3, 586*. 
 
 Schiehler, 278 n. 6. 
 
 Scliiller, 474*. 
 
 Schleicher, 500 n. 1. 
 
 Schleiden, 474 n. 1. 
 
 Schloierniaclur, 22 n. 1, 23 n. 1, 33 n. 1, 
 53 n. 3, 70 n. 2, 78 n. 1 , 322 ii. 1 , 587 *. 
 
 Schluter, 205 n. 1. 
 
 Schinckel, 140 n. I, 148 n. 1. 
 
 Kchinid, R., 500 n. 1. 
 Scliiiiidt, C, 234 n. I, 261 n. 4. 
 
 Schmidt, F. X., 277 n. 2. 
 
 Schmidt, L., 8 n. 0, 609. 
 
 Schmidt, O., 5G0 u. 1. 
 
 Schnuihlers, 210 u. 2. 
 
 Schneider, Ch., 76 n. 2. 
 
 Schneider, G. H., 607. 
 
 Schneider, J. G., 6 u. 2, 133 n. 1. 
 
 Schneidewiu, 7 n. 9. 
 
 Schoenhmk, 406 n. 2. 
 
 Schohisticisni, 201 * ff., 297. 
 
 Scholten, 15, 610. 
 
 Schoohnen, 201 ff. 
 
 Schools, 201. 
 
 Scliopeniiauer, 11,46, 113 n. 3, 192 u. i, 
 
 249, n. 1, 322 n. 1, 445, 491 u. 3, 544* 
 
 ff., 594 ff., 601 ; his pessimism, 552 ff. ; 
 
 liis relation to other systems, 545 ff. ; 
 
 his school, 556 ff. 
 Schorn, 48 n. 2, 53 n. 3. 
 Schreiber, 253 n. 2. 
 Scliubert, F. W., 434 n. 2. 
 Schubert, G. H., 495. 
 Schulcr, 277 n. 1. 
 Schuller, 324 n. 1. 
 Schultess, 8 n. 6. 
 SchuUliess, 277 a. I. 
 Schultze, 263 n. 1. 
 Schulze, 473*, 544. 
 Schuppe, 605, 608. 
 Schurer, 163 n. 1. 
 Schurman, 434 n. 2, 462 n. 2, 5G0 n. 1, 
 
 609,610. 
 Schwarz, 606. 
 
 Schwcgler, 8 n. 6, 14, 108 u. 3. 
 Schweighiiusur, 148 u. 1. 
 Science, Greek, 159 ff. ; modern, 281 ff. 
 Scotcii i)liilosopliy, 430* ff. 
 Scotus Duns, .see Duns. 
 Scotus Krigena, sre Krigena. 
 Secn'tan, 496 u. 1, 556 n. 1, 589*. 592 
 
 n. 2,001. 
 Sedail, 296 n. 3. 
 Seleucus, 100. 
 
 Seneca, 7, 140 n. 1, 147, 148 n. 1, 225. 
 Sensationalism, and materialism, 402 
 
 n. 2 ; and scei)ticiiim, 152 ff. 
 Sc])p, 14H n. 2. 
 Sergi, 006. 
 1 Servet, 284.
 
 628 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Seth, A., 12 n. 11, 496 n. 8. 
 
 Seth, J., 609. 
 
 Sextus Empiricus, 7, 153, 158* f., 308. 
 
 Seydel, 544 u. 1. 
 
 Shaftesbury, 390*. 
 
 Shedd, 211 u. 4. 
 
 Sibree, 497 n. 5. 
 
 Sidgwick, A., 605. 
 
 Sidgwick, H., 15 n. 9, 59 n 1, 608, 609, 
 
 611. 
 Siebeck, 15 n. 9, 59 n. 1, 63 n. i, 78 u. 1, 
 
 608, 610. 
 Sieber, 267 n. 1. 
 Sighart, 240 n. 2. 
 Sigwart, Chr., 15 n. 9, 267 n. 2, 298 n. 2, 
 
 324 n. 2, 605, 609. 
 Simmel, 609, 611. 
 Simon, J., 108 n. 3, 166 u. 3, 182 n. 1, 
 
 305 n. 1, 318 n. 7, 320 n. 2. 
 Simon, T, C.,392u. 5. 
 Simon of Tournay, 234. 
 Simplicius, 184. 
 Smith, A., 391* 
 Smith, M., 536 n. 2. 
 Smith, W., 481 n. 1. 
 Smyth, 609. 
 
 Sneath, 15 n. 9, 4.30n. 3. 
 Socher, 78 n. 1. 
 Socrates, 6, 6.3* ff., 71, 75, 80, 82, 150, 
 
 537. 
 Socratic schools, 71*ff. 
 Solon, 19. 
 
 Sommer, H., 344 n. 1. 
 Sommer, R., 369 n. 1. 
 Sophists, 59* ff., 80. 
 Sophocles, 19. 
 
 Space, Kant's doctrine of, 440 ff. 
 Spedding, 296 n. 3. 
 Spencer, 7 n. 8. 
 Spencer, H. 11, 560 n. 1, 581* ff., 606, 
 
 607, 608, 611. 
 Spengel, 563n. 2. 
 Speusippus, 103* f. 
 
 Spinoza, 6, 52,91, 192 n. 1, 220 n. 1,32.3* 
 ff., 347 f., 359, 382, .391 f., 394 n. 1, 
 455, 462,465,492 n. 1, 495,499, .538 f., 
 542 n. 2. ; his definitions, 325 f. ; and 
 Descartes, 326 f. ; his determinism, 
 335 f. ; and Leibniz. 359 ff . ; and ma- 
 
 terialism, 333 ; his method, 324 f. ; 
 
 his pantheism, 326 ff. ; his theology, 
 
 326 ff. ; his theory of attributes, 
 
 329 ff. ; his theory of modes, 334 ff . ; 
 
 his theory of passions, 338 ff. ; hia 
 
 theory of substance, 326 ff. 
 Spiritualism, 1 n. 1, 587 ff., 590 ff. ; 
 
 Berkeley's, 393 ff.; Greek, 75 ff. 
 Stadler, 468 u. 1. 
 Stallbaum, 76 u. 2. 
 Stanley, 13. 
 Starr, 608. 
 Steffens, 495. 
 
 Stein, H., 44 n. 1, 71 n. 1, 610. 
 Stein, L., 140 n. 1, 142 u. 1, 324 n. 1, 
 
 344 n. 1, 345 n. 1. 
 Steiner, 544 n. 1. 
 Steinthal, 542* n. 2, 606, 608. 
 Stephen, L., 12 n. 11, 390 n. 2, 608. 
 Sterrett, 497 n. 4. 
 Stewart, A., 12 n. 11. 
 Stewart, D., 431* 
 Stich, 148 n. 1. 
 Stilpo, 75, 140. 
 Stirling, 437 n. 1, 496 n. 3, 533* 
 
 n. 1. 
 Stobaeus, 8. 
 Stockl, 9 n. 2. 
 Stoicism, 69, 74, 75, 140* ff., 597 ; and 
 
 Christianity, 147. 
 Stoics, 491 a. 5. 
 Strato, 133. 
 Strauss, 399 n. 1, 533* 560 n. 1, 562* 
 
 566 ff. 
 Strumpell, 542* n. 2. 
 Strufrgle for existence, 565 ff. 
 Stumpf, 606. 
 Sturz, 19 n 2. 
 Suarez, 203* n. 1. 
 Subjective and objective in Middle 
 
 Ages, 220 n. 1. 
 Suckow, 78 n. 1. 
 Suidas, 8. 
 
 Sully, 544 n. 1, 557 n. 1, 606, 607. 
 Supranaturalism, 1 n. 1. 
 Survival of fitte.st, 566 ff. 
 Susemihl, 78 n. 1, 140 n. 1. 
 Symonds, 10 n. 1. 
 Synthetic judgments, 438 ff.
 
 (y 
 
 INDEX 
 
 629 
 
 Taise, 581 u. 3, 586*. 592 n. 2, 610. 
 
 Talaiiio, 201 n. 3. 
 
 Tauueiy, 305 n. J. 
 
 Tarde, 611. 
 
 Tatian, 187. 
 
 Tauk-r, 261*. 
 
 Taurellus, 10, 277* f. 
 
 Tavlor, 167 n. 1, 181 u. 1. 
 
 Taylor, T. W., 611. 
 
 Tciiihatchef, 298 n. 2. 
 
 Teichmiiller, 8 n. 6, 21 n. 1, 33 n. 1, 78 
 n. 1. 
 
 Teleology, 1 n. 1, 564, 566 ff. ; of Kaut, 
 468 S.] of Plato, 95 £C. ; and Atom- 
 ism, 95. 
 
 Telesio, 273* 287. 
 
 Temple, 296 n. 3. 
 
 Teuuemaun, 13. 
 
 TertuUian, 186, 196,463. 
 
 Teteiis, 433* n. 2. 
 
 Teuffel, 8 n. 6. 
 
 Thales, 5, 20, 21* f. 
 
 Theism, 1 d. 1. 
 
 Theodoras, 72*. 
 
 Theodorus of Gaza, 263, 267. 
 
 Theognis, 19. 
 
 Theophrastus, 133. 
 
 Theo.sophy, 265 £f., 277 ff. 
 
 Thilly, 4 n. 1,344 n. 1. 
 
 Thilo, 542* n. 2. 
 
 Theologv, Plato's, 88 f. ; Kant's Critique 
 of. 
 
 Things in themselves, 71, 444, 447, ff. ; 
 Beck's rejection of, 477 n. 1 ; Fichte 
 and, 484; Kant's, 451 ff. ; Schopen- 
 hauer and, 545 ; Schulze's critique of, 
 473 n. 3. 
 
 Thoma-s 236, 584 n. 4. 
 
 Thomas of Aquin, 9, 202, 241* ff. ; 
 his determinism, 245 f. 
 
 Thomas of IJradwardine, 256*. 
 
 Thomas a Kempis, 261*. 
 
 Thomas of Straslturg, 256*. 
 
 Thiimming, 369* n. 1. 
 
 Tiherghien, 587* n. 4. 
 
 Tiedemann, 13, 140 u. 1. 
 
 Tifdf, 610. 
 
 Tille, .557 n. 1, 
 
 Time, Kant's <Ioctrino of, 440 ff. 
 
 Timocharus, 161. 
 
 Timon, 149* f., 152. 
 
 Tiudall, 391* n. 3. 
 
 Tissot, 322 n. 1. 
 
 Titcheuer, 586 n. 3, 607 
 
 Tocco, 286 n. 2. 
 
 Toland, 391* u. 3 ; his materialism, 
 
 405* f. 
 Tonnies, 301 u. 1, 609. 
 Torquatus, L., 139. 
 Torrey, H., 305 u. 1. 
 Torrey, J., 185 n. 1, 188 n. 1. 
 Tracy, 607. 
 
 Transcendentalism, 1 n. 1. 
 Trendelenburg, 15 n. 9, 106 n. 2, 588*. 
 Trezza, 133 n. 1. 
 Trivium, 200 n. 2. 
 Tufts, 15 n. 9, 468 n. 1. 
 Turgot, 414*. 
 Twardowski, 305 n. 1. 
 Twesteu, 587 n. 2. 
 Tycho Brahe, 283* 
 Tyler, 607. 
 Tyndall, 563* n. 5. 
 
 Ueberweg, 14, 78 n. 1, 392 n. 5, 605. 
 
 Ulrici, 496 n. 3, 588*. 
 
 Unconscious, Leibniz's doctrine of the, 
 
 345 f. 
 Universals, 219 f. 
 Usener, 133 n. 1. 
 
 Vacherot, 166 n. 3, .5.33* n. 1. 
 
 Vaihinger, 437 u. 1, 557 n. 1. 
 
 Valat, 59 n. 1. 
 
 Valois, 239 n. 2. 
 
 Vanini, 272*. 
 
 \'asco de Gama, 282. 
 
 \'eitch, 305 n. 1, 4:51 n. 4, 605. 
 
 Venn, 605. 
 
 Vera, 496 n. 3, 515 n. 1, 533* n. 1. 
 
 Vesale, 284*. 
 
 Vicajcc, 318 n. 7. 
 
 Vico, 295* n. 1. 
 
 Victorines, 227 ff. 
 
 Victo, 284* 300. 
 
 Villers, 434 n. 2. 
 
 Vincent of Hoauvais, 239* f. 
 
 Vinci, Leonanio di, 284*.
 
 630 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Vinet, 322 n. 1. 
 Virchow, 563 n. 4, 586* 
 
 Viseli, 231 n. 2. 
 
 Vischer, 610. 
 
 Vitringa, 59 u. 1. 
 
 Vlooteu, Vau, 324 u. 2, 323 n. 1. 
 
 Vogt, 562, 563 u. 3. 
 
 Voigt, 10 n. 1. 
 
 Volkelt, 4, 437 n. 1, 557 n. 1. 
 
 Volkinauu, R., 166 u. 1, 542- n. 2. 
 
 Volkniaiiu, W., 606. 
 
 Voluey, 590* n. 5. 
 
 Voltaire, 399*. 
 
 Vohmtarism, 249 u. 1, 601 ft. 
 
 Vorliluder, 12 n. 11, 609. 
 
 Wace, 185 n. 1. 
 
 Wachsmiith, 149 u. 2. 
 
 AVaddiugton, 148 n. 2, 277 n. 3. 
 
 Wagner, A., 286 n. 2. 
 
 Wagner, R., 557* n. 1. 
 
 Waitz, 542* n. 2, 607. 
 
 Wallace, A. R., 560 n. I. 
 
 Wallace, E., 104 n. 4. 
 
 Wallace, W., 133 n. 1, 496 u. 3, 497 u. 3, 
 
 533* n. 1, 544 n. 1. 
 Walter, 8 n. 6, 167 n. 1. 
 Walter of St. Victor, 233, 260. 
 Watson, 148 n. 1, 435 n. 3, 437 n. 1, 
 
 487 n. 1, 533* n. 1, 573 n. 2. 
 Weber, 147 n. 4, 495 n. 1, 501 n. 2, 
 
 601 n. 5. 
 Weigel, 278*. 
 Weismann, 560 n. 1. 
 Weisse, 588*. 
 Welldon, 104 n. 4. 
 Wendland, 163 n. 1. 
 Weudt, 71 n. 1. 
 
 Werner, 9 n. 2, 241 u. 1, 241 n. 3 
 258 n. 3. 
 
 Wessel, 261*. 
 
 Westermarck, 61 1 . 
 
 Weygoldt, 140 n. 1. 
 
 Wharton, 104 n. 4. 
 
 Whewell, 12 n. 11, 391 n. 2, 609. 
 
 White, 323 n. 1. 
 
 Wiclif, 359. 
 
 Wilbour, 586 n. 5, 
 
 Wildauer, 63 n. 1. 
 
 Will, 600 ff . 
 
 William of Auvergne, 239*. 
 
 William of C'hampeaux, 221* ff., 235. 
 
 William (.,f Conches, 226* f. 
 
 William Durand, 253*. 
 
 William of Occam, 253* f. 
 
 Williams, 104 n. 4, 609. 
 
 Willm, 12. 
 
 Willmaun, 15 n. 9, 535 n. 2. 
 
 Wilson, 608. 
 
 Wimmer, 133 n. 1. 
 
 Winckelmanu, 76 n. 2. 
 
 Windelband, 8 u. 6, 10. 
 
 Wirth, 588*. 
 
 Witte, 608, 473 n. 7. 
 
 Wolff, 163 n. 1, 368* f., 435. 
 
 World-Soul, riato's, 94 f. 
 
 Worms, 323 n. 1. 
 
 Wundt, 586* 600 u. 1., 601, 605, 600, 
 
 608, 609. 
 Wyttenbach, 167 n. 1. 
 
 Xenocrates, 104, 140. 
 Xeuophanes, 20, 24* ff. 
 Xeuophon, 6, 65, 67. 
 
 Zabarella, 271*. 
 
 Zahn, 140 n. 1, 185 n. 1. 
 
 Zeitschrift fiir exacte Philosophic, 
 542 n. 2. 
 
 Zeitschrift fiir Philosophic, 542 n. 2, 
 588 n. 3. 
 
 Zeitschrift fiir wissenschaftliche Phi- 
 losophic, 588 u. 7. 
 
 Zeitschrift fiir Volkcrkunde, 542 n. 2. 
 
 Zcller, 4, 8 n. 6, 12, 15 n. 9, 19 n. 1, 
 78 n. 1, 148 n. 1, 277 n. 1, 368 n. 1, 
 462 n. 2, 533* 565 n. 3, 608. 
 
 Zeno the Eleatic, 31* f., 335. 
 
 Zeno the Stoic, 5, 74, 140* ff., 151. 
 
 Zenodotus, 184 n. 1. 
 
 Ze'vort, 48 n. 2, 104 n. 4. 
 
 Ziegler, 8 n. 6, 9 n. 2, 226 n. 2, 609. 
 
 Ziehen, 607, 608. 
 
 Zimmer, 481 n. 1. 
 
 Zimmerman, 542* n. 2. 
 
 Zimmern, 544 n. 1. 
 
 Zwingli, 276 f.
 
 if
 
 vf
 
 UC SOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY 
 
 mil 1 1 II! M 
 
 AA 000 807 053 4 
 
 CENTRAL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY 
 ^n-ersity Of California. sJC 
 
 DATE DUE