UC-NRLF I $B MS 5D5 Digitized by tine Internet Archive in 2007 with funding from IVIicrosoft Corporation http://www.archive.org/details/essaysonplatonicOOmagurich ESSAYS ON THE PLATONIC ETHICS. CAMBRIDGE: Printed by William Metcalfe, Green Street. ESSAYS ON THE PLATONIC ETHICS.- BY THOMAS MAGUIRE, LL.D., EX S.T.C.D., PROFESSOR OF LATIN, QUEEN's COLLEGE, GALWAV. £1/ ovpavM KTvos irapaoiiyfia avuKturai. RIVINGTONS ^onboit^ ^xlox'ii, anb (S^ambribge W. M^GEE, DUBLIN 1870 B3f2 y re kuI U^rjg, which are the objects of the other two Faculties, we may render dXrjdivrjg dolrjQ EToipog, which has for its object, true glory, i.e. the pleasures of the Timocratic man, Rep. 8. 550, b, as opposed to the respect paid to mere wealth, /cat yap 6 irXouaios viro ttoXXwv rtjuarai. jRep. 582, c. With regard to the exhaustiveness of Plato's tripartition, excepted to by Mr. Grote, 3. 177, note 7, and in a less degree, by Dr. Thompson, 166, we must recollect that Plato is pro- fessedly writing on Ethics, and not Psychology. He, therefore, deals with Psychology, only so far as it supplies Principles and Springs of Action, just as Economy appeals to the same science for its complex mental facts, without requiring any further analysis. For example, it does not enquire whether the Desire of wealth is connate or acquired. Surely an Ethical writer would be warranted in referring the wooing and murder of Desdemona to the same passion, love, although a Psycho- logist would not. For the former considers any given feeling only so far as modifies Conduct for good or ill. But, further, BvfiOQ is in its Ethical function repressive, and not *'protreptic," being evoked whenever the dictates of Reason are disobeyed by the unruly eViOv/im. In the absence of anger, that is, when the Reason is hearkened to, the softer feelings come into play. So the watch-dog, of a good breed, when not angry, is gentle, Rep. 2. 375, e — 6, a; and the judge, save in cases of absolute necessity, tempers severity with the reflexion, that every wrong- doer is the proper object of compassion, as he wrongs himself more than anybody else. Zegg. 731, b — d. dvfxoeidij — yap Toy dyadov. cf. Gorg. 469, a. b. tvp6yr](ng, there is no such contradiction, as Mr. Grote alleges, between the ThecBtetus and the Republic. The question of the The(2tetus is What is Science, iTnaTtjfjLT}, that is. Knowledge considered from the objective side; while the Republic deals with Prudence, p6vri dvdpwTTUf (oairep Kal raAAa, taTiv ore Kal olg (^eXtlov reOvdvai rj tl^v, cuQ de ^eXTLOV TeQvdvai, davfxaaTOU 'iaojQ aoL ) Toiavra vo^i^eiv k. e. cannot be taken thus ; for this would be expressed by oTroaa, roiavT ovTUf "xpri vop'^ctv — and though the order might be H 2 lOO APPENDIX D. changed, the participle would be indispensable. But, even if we conceded such an interpretation, what would become of Trpwroj/ fiey Trrj Trspl fierpov ? It is obvious that, in such a case, irtpL has no meaning nor construction. But, above all, such an expression as, "to have adopted (or received) the eternal nature," is at variance with the whole method of Plato. For if the Good is to be sought for in these, it must be because they are emanations or productions of it ; whereas, according to this view, the Good is superadded to them, and that through their seeking it. But no one conversant with the language will understand yprjcrOai in the sense of 7rapEt\rj(j)evai, or still less of eiXrixivai. And then, again, why have we the perfect ? In speaking of a fact which has no reference to any particular time, the proper tense would have been iXeadai. Those who feel these objections will not need to have them confirmed by a consideration of the unsuitableness of the sense thus extorted from them ; and yet the sense is in itself very objectionable, because it would amount to this — that Plato, having sought by a laborious argument for that which had most affinity with the Good, at last found it — in the Idea of the Good." Now, ovra would spoil the sense, as it would imply that, already being so and so, they had taken on the eternal Nature ; as in the same dialogue, we have TrpoaayopEveig avr dvofioi ovO* irsp^ ovo^aTL, Phil. 13, a.; that is, you call things which are already dissimilar by a distinct name ; whereas the meaning is, that they are so and so, because they have taken. With regard to irpuJTov fjLEv TTT) TTEpl fiETpov, why caunot 7r£joi havc the same construction and meaning as in the next clause and in Symp. 203, c, and Epist. ii. 312, e., Pol. 258, d., 297, c. and else- where passim^ viz. : to denote the id circa quod of anything. The full construction is izpCiTov KTrJixd iarL Tvepl fierpov kcu to fxerpiov Koi Kaipiov, the words being ranged in their logical order. The most valuable acquisition deals with ^erpoy, Measure, Limit, and the Limited, and (therefore, because Limited) the suitable for some end or other. That is, suitableness comes from prior adaptation, and adaptation comes from the adapting principle fiETpoVf TTEpag. With regard to the order of the words, irapd* oTToaa Toiavra occur in this order, Phileb. 54, b., 19, c, 42, d., and the full construction is Trdvd, oiroaa itrn roiavTa, d k. r. \., as in Polit. TTEpl rd IvfifioXaia irdyd\ OTroaa keItui vo'/j(/ia, TrapaXaf^ovtra, APPENDIX D. 1 01 305, b. ; and see on the omission of the copula, Prof. Campbell's note on Polit. 281, c. p. 92. As to the position of yj^r\ with the infinitive, any one who cares to investigate the matter, will see that Plato places x9r\ both before and after the infinitive, apparently guided merely by sound. The word ■^pr\aQai expresses exactly, choice determined hy proper grounds^ in which case the thing chosen is logically prior to the chooser. Besides, jprJffdaL need not, and must not, be taken in the sense of either TrapEikrjcpevaL or el\r)xevai. If we recollect Plato's use of Ojoc'yt <70at, F/iced. 65, c. ; 75, a.; J^ep. syz, a.; I^pist. ii. 312, E.; and Aristotle's objection to Plato's applying icpUadai and opelig to the Numbers, Ethic. Eud. i. 8, we shall see, not only no difficulty, but perfect propriety in the use of the word to express the complete distinctness and harmony of the elements of the Idea. We have a phrase of a similar kind in the Philehus itself, faJc dyadd jiev ovk ovra, iviore ^i Koi evia Bcj^d/zeva rrjv t 434 d e, 435 e, 441 a c, 442 d e, 443 b c, 445 a c, Rep. V. 449 a d, 462 b c, 472 b d. Rep. vi. 484 b, Rep. vii. 541 b. Rep. viii. 543 d, 545 a b c, 548 d, 550 c d, 553 e, 554 b, 555 a b, APPENDIX F. 105 558 c, 559 d e, 561 e, 564 a, 566 d, Rep. ix. 571 a, 574 e, 576 c, 577 c, 578 a, 579 c, 580 c d, 588 b, 592 a, Rep, x. 605 b, 612 c. The Laws deals with the province of Legislation opOoVr/ro'c re jcat a/uaprmc Trcpi vo'/xwv, ^nc Tore eort ^vo-et I, 627 d; and the Politicus sets before us the Master of Statecraft, who combines the comprehensiveness of a Code with the power of scrupu- lously adjusting it to the specialities of Cases, 294 a b, 295 b — 296 a. One would imagine that a disciple of the Positive School would bear in mind the distinctness of the provinces of Ethics and Legislation, yet Mr. G. H. Lewes, in his anxiety to point out the inconsistencies of Plato, confounds Law and Morality in the following passage : ** Even the Socratic view of Virtue being identical with Knowledge, consequently of Vice being Ignorance, and therefore involuntary — even this idea he learned in his old age to repudiate, as we see in the Laws (v. p. 385), where he calls incontinence no less than ignorance (^ cC dfia- 6iav 7) ^i' aKpareiav) the cause of Vice. In the same sense (iv. p. 138), after speaking of anger and pleasure as causes of error, he says, " There is a third cause of our faults, and that is ignorance {rpirov Qyvoiav tQv dfiapTrifidTtJv airUiy). So that here he places Ignorance only as a third Cause ; and by so doing, destroys the whole Socratic argument respecting the identity of Virtue and knowledge." — History of Philosophy, i. 214- — 3, 3rd edition. Whatever destruction there is, does not come of Plato. I do not know to what edition Mr. Lewes refers, but the passage in the fifth book occurs in 734 b. Steph. The second I am unable to find, except in the ninth, 863 b c. Now, in the ninth book, Plato expressly raises the question, How is Legal Responsibility compatible with his doctrine that Vice — Injustice — dlLda — is involuntary ? Legg. 9, 860 b. — 861 e. Plato resolves the difficulty by pointing out, that though Vice — dlida — is involuntary, yet that p\d(3r} — damnum — damage in the legal sense, may be caused either purposely or not. Now, as was shown before. Justice — individual Virtue — tliKaioavvr) — is the ascendancy in action of the higher principles, and Injustice — d^ida — of the lower. But the Legislator is mainly concerned with dfictpTtinara, i.e. Delicts, and with the motives which lead to them — in Roman language their Causce — namely, Passion or Anger — Qv^xo^ ; Pleasure or Sensuality — »/^ov/f ; and 106 APPENDIX F. Ignorance, either mere absence of Knowledge, or positive Delusion, ayvoia, 863 b c. Hence, Plato quite consistently tells us that, an act may be just, but at the same time damnific, and that another may be unjust, but beneficent, 863 e, 864 a. T7?V yap Tov dvjjLov — TT^v TOLavTr}y (3XdPr]v. In modern words, the question. Is A liable to an action in tort ? has nothing to do with the question. Is A in a state of Grace ? In the first passage quoted by Mr. Lewes, Plato is talking of the causes which make a man fall short of ffwcppoavvr], tov (7(i)([)pove~ty ivhriQ a>V, 5, 734 b, and he puts down as causes, djxaQia and a'lCjOaVtia, i.e. a want of ^poprjmg and of dpdpeia. But in tracing the historical growth of states, in Legg. 3, 4, he tells us that he is talking of every day ffwippoavvi], 710 a, and not of abxppoavvt] in its high sense ; and he also insists that a Law should not be merely a command or prohibition, but should have a prooemium or preamble containing the reasons which induce the Legislator to make the Law, 4, 721 — 723 b. The Legislator should also give his subjects a catalogue of divine and human things in their order of desirability. The student of Bentham will remember two similar suggestions. Now amongst these desirable objects are the various kinds of moral life suited to the individual ; and one of these is the temperate, aiocpp^v, in the popular sense ; and the two causes which impede aw(ppoavv7] are uKpareia and dfiadia, that is, in the popular sense, for he had shown in the Protagoras, that dfxaOia was the essence of all Vice. Here then the Legislator is obviously dealing with the motives of Delict and its opposite. In brief. Ethical Wrong — Vice — is involuntary dKovaiovy and is the result of ignorance dfxadia : but Legal Wrong — Delict — dfidp- rr?jua, is the result of dfxaQia, as well as of other causes, and is both aKovaiov and EKovaiov. Besides, the Laws, all through, is conceived in a popular spirit : Plato's assistants are from Sparta and Crete, intellectually the least cultivated of Greek states. Plato, on a remarkable occasion, claims to manage the discussion all his own way, 10, 892 d e, and the Cretan thinks Homer a clever fellow, though he has not read much of him, 3, 860 c. The treatise, too, opens with the statement that the author of Laws is Gfoe, 624 ; and Qeoq and deioQ are always in Plato opposed to rf'x*"^* science, Ion. 542 a b, Mem. 99 c, io end. On the whole, we may pronounce the Laws APPENDIX F. 107 to be an adaptation of Platonism to popular intelligence and sympathies, although even here, Plato maintains that the peculiarities of the Republic are theoretically better than the compromises of the Laws, 5, 739 b. e. The different arrangements of the several polities in the Republic^ the Politicus, and the Laws, which are set forth by Professor Lewis Campbell in his introduction to the Politicus, pp. XLi. — XLV., can be easily accounted for by differences in the Principium Divisionis in each Treatise. Thus, the third Laws deals with the historical growth of Polity, 3, 676 a. The Republic deals with the various Polities in the order of their deviation from the ideal State, Rep. 543 e — 544 a ; that which deviates least, being least bad. There is only one Ideal or perfect state, either Monarchy or Polyarchy, which governs the Whole for the good of the Whole. All others are devia- tions, and govern only for the good of a part. These deviations are infinite in number. Rep, 445 e; cf. Polit. 291 a b; but in this infinity of deviation, we find the four well marked types, Timocracy, Oligarchy, Democracy, and Tyranny. From the point of view of the Republic, Oligarchy takes precedence of Democracy, because Oligarchy governs on principle — the good of the Oligarchy ; whereas Democracy has no principle at all, ^^/- 8, 557 d c, and as the state is, so is the democrat, 561 c d. Everything by starts, and nothing long, and so the Democracy is a very pleasant and genial place to live in, a.^ ov deffTTEffla Kal jj^cla rj TOiavrrj Staywyj? iv rw TrapavTiKa ; 558 a. Now the standard in the Politicus is imffTrJiJiri — science — on the part of the Sovereign, be it one or many, and the deviations are judged of by their pleasantness as constitutions to live under, rig ovv Zri tSv ovk opduiv TroXireiuiv tovtojv rjfcicrTa ■^aXEirrj (TV^fjv, Tracwi/ ^aXcTro/v ovatov, Koi rig f^apvTciTr}. Pol. 302 b. In this way, Democracy is more genial, and therefore preferable to Oligarchy, which, judging from small towns in general, must have been excessively unpleasant. As to the Minos, the following points of resemblance be- tween it and acknowledged dialogues must be admitted, what- ever views be held as to its authorship. Mr. Grote and Mr. Lewes have done good service to criticism in general, by their protest against the German test of authenticity, the Platonisches Gefiihl, which proves any thing. 08 APPENDIX F. 1. AiKaioavPT] makes men dkaioi 314 c, it is also of para- mount excellence, td. d. 2. 1] dXr]d7ig do^a deals with existence, 315 a. 3. Real existence is changeless, 316 b. 4. Laws are for the good of subjects, 318 a b. 5. Crete and Lacedasmon are praised as usual, 318 c d. 6. The good man resembles God, 319 a. 7. Zeus is a o-o^to-T-TJc, and has re'xv?/, 319 c. 8. Law is based on Morality, 320 a. 9. Law, in its effects, is compared to Gymnastic, 321 c d. 10. The definition of Law — Eoyfia TroXeivg — the will of the State, is accepted with qualifiea-tion in both Minos, 314 d e, and Laws, i, 644 d. APPENDIX G. TRUE AND FALSE PLEASURE AND PAIN. Few of Plato's modes of expression have been more vehe- mently assailed than his application of the predicates true and false to Pleasure and Pain. It has been condemned by Mr. Grote, Professor Bain, and Mr. Poste. Whether the terms are appropriate or not is a question of taste ; but the question for the metaphysician is whether the explanation given by Plato is sound or not. Reserving the question of propriety of language, Plato's explanation of the offensive terms is clear, and, I believe, justifiable ; and it is somewhat odd that he carefully provides against the very objection, which is urged against him. As follows : an empirical judgment, Zolsx^ is true or false according as it is verified or falsified by further experience. Thus I see what I imagine to be a man under a tree : I approach nearer and find it to be a wooden figure. My judgment, ?d^a, is accordingly false. Phil, 38, c d. Falsity, accordingly, exists only in the reference to future experience. But the subjective impression, whether ultimately verified or falsified by further experience, is never in itself false, ovkovv to do^d^op, av re opduiQ ay re firj 6pdu)Q do^darjy to ye ^o^d^eiv ovtcjq ovdeiror ciTroXXufftv, 37 a b. In the same way, the pleasure, as actually experienced, cannot be false, but may attract that predicate, when ex- amined by the light of further experience, ovkovv koi to i^dofievov, av re opduie dv re firj rjhriTaif to ye 6vT