r. L LIBRARY Owivlk'hy of california SAN DITOO ^ J ■1 3""i822""01147 9193 M ■>.!■ Central University Library University of California, San Diego Note: This item is subject to recall after two weeks. Date Due NOV ^ 2 m? HAY 2 9 1994 0139(1/91) UCSDLib. A STUDY IN REALISM CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS C. F. CLAY, Manager LONDON : FETTER LANE, E.G. 4 NEW YORK : THE MACMILLAN CO. BOMBAY CALCUTTA ■ MACMILLAN AND CO., Ltd. MADRAS TORONTO. : THE MACMILLAN CO. OF CANADA, Ltd. TOKYO: MARUZEN-KABUSHIKI-KAISHA ALL RIGHTS RESERVED A STUDY IN REALISM BY JOHN LAIRD, M.A., PROFESSOR OF LOGIC AND METAPHYSICS IN THE QUEEn's UNIVERSITY OF BELFAST CAMBRIDGE AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS 1920 To thee, O man, the sua his truth hath given, The moon hath whisper'd in love her silvery dreams ; Night hath unlockt the starry heaven, The sea the trust of his streams : And the rapture of woodland spring Is stay'd in its flying; And Death cannot sting Its beauty undying. Robert Bridges. TO THE MEMORY OF MY BROTHER HUGH BLACKHALL LAIRD SEOOND-LIEUTENANT, YORKSHIRE REGIMENT WHO FELL IN ACTION AT TRONES WOOD DURING THE BATTLE OF THE SOMME 8th JULY, 1916 PREFACE WHEN I set out to write this book, I meant to give the reader a methodical, brief survey of some of the chief problems in philosophical realism (as I understood it), and to spend most of my labour on certain points in the theory which I found especially perplexing. I thought, indeed, that many of the cardinal features of realism had been investigated so minutely within recent years ^ that I could afford to omit some of them from my discussion and to be very brief in my treat- ment of certain of the others. Per contra, I considered that realists had commonly paid too little attention to certain varieties of knowledge in which, at the first look, other theories seemed better suited to the facts. The creative imagination of the artist, for example, the constructions of science, and even the meanings of perception, might seem to belong to a wholly different order from the simpler ways of apprehending which the realists dissect (I except Mr Alexander, whose Space, Time, and Deity had not appeared when I wrote) and I wished to examine whether contrasts of this striking kind were securely established in fact. In other words, I wished to search those other theories on the very ground they had chosen for them- selves, feeling convinced that realism was strong enough to occupy it, and knowing, as a thing of course, that if realism were to fail in this enterprise, it could only be a provisional, departmental theory, and not (as it claims to be and as I believed) a final, catholic one. 1 The theory of relation is an instance. viii PREFACE I never expected, I hoj)e, to do more than an underling's work in so slight an essay upon so large a theme, but, even so, I wish that my confidence had not oozed so persistently as I wrote, and that I could have felt less like a child in chase of a rainbow. And now that the printer has put an end to my struggles with logic and my nibblings of the pen, I am better able to appreciate the yawning chasm between antici- pation and achievement. I am doubtful, now, whether I should not have included much that I passed over of set purpose ; and I sigh for the equipment which would have enabled me to deal more adequately with many of the problems that have sought me out. On the other hand, I think I may claim that I have faced any of the difficulties I was able to understand, openly enough and squarely; and that I have honestly endeavoured to keep objections in the foreground instead of attempting to gloss them over. Be that as it may, I make no apologv for the spirit of this adventure; and I should not wish to do so, even if such an apology could ever condone the offence. There can be no health in philosophy, I am sure, without continual discussion ; and I still believe most firmly that realism is a truly philo- sophical theory of knowledge, by which I mean that the realists' point of view, literally interpreted and resolutely argued, may be sustained, consistently and without special pleading, throughout the whole wide territory of the theory of know- ledge. No part of this book has been published before; but I have contributed (copiously, I am afraid) to the philosophical journals during the past year or two, and these pages show traces of portions of this published matter and of certain com- ments upon it. To be more precise, two articles in Mind are connected with the subjects of the third and of the eighth PREFACE ix chapters in this book; an article in the British Journal of Psychology dealt in advance with some of the problems of the second chapter; the concluding pages of the sixth chapter are tinged with the remembrance of an article I wrote for The Mo7iist; and the general argument of the book has a certain affinity with the contentions I put forward in a paper pub- lished in the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. In writing the eighth chapter I had to deal, in part, with the subject-matter of a former book; and I hope I have learned from my critics. I am most grateful to my father for the pains he has taken in reading the book in proof, and for advising me of many of my mistakes. And, like so many others, I have the pleasant privilege of thanking the Syndics of the Cambridge University Press for the honour they have done me in publishing the book, and of expressing my gratitude to all who may be con- cerned for the skilful care which has been given to the printing of it. So much in the book is due to what I learned at Cam- bridge that I may be pardoned, I hope, for finding a peculiar delight in this privilege. J. L. Juhj V2, 1920 CONTENTS CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION Realism ...... A short retrospect: Arnauld and Raid Assumptions ..... PAGE 1 2 8 CHAPTER II. THE THINGS WE PERCEIVE Perception, judgments of pei'ception, and sensation Direct perception ........ The theorj' of sensory atomism ...... Dr \\'ard's theory ........ Sign-facts and continuants ....... Perception and the discovery of an independent world The perception of 'matter' ...... CHAPTER III. THINGS REMEMBERED AND THINGS EXPECTED The 'specious present' ...... Immediate knowledge of the past and of the future Analysis of memory : reproduction and recollection The place of memory-images ..... CHAPTER IV. THE STUFF OF FANCY Fancy and imagination .... Images ....... Dream and waking ..... The elements of fancy : and their meaning . Constructive imaging : and psycho-analysis Theory of fancy ...... CHAPTER V. THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF Perception and judgment . Propositions about the world The space and time of common belief Causal interpretation . Error. ..... 15 17 18 25 27 30 30 45 49 51 55 60 61 65 67 75 81 83 86 93 95 103 CONTENTS CHAPTER VI. PRINCIPLES General facts : ami first principles The order of tlieir discovery Tlie being of categories and of universals Univeraulia in re . . . . Induction and pure logic The law of parsimony .... CHAPTER VII. The value of things . . . . Whether beauty is only delight . Whether morals are matter of feeling Value and existence . . . . VALUES CHAPTER VIII. THE MIND The realistic theory of knowledge The place of psychology Consciousness Consciousness and behaviour The nature of consciousness Introspection and its difficulties The spiritual substance Objections .... Realism and the self . CHAPTER IX. THE LARGER OUTLOOK The sufficiency of realism ..... Realism and the theory of probability Realism in hypotheses ..... Tlie methods of biology ..... Realism in the human sciences : and, first, economics Historical knowledge and the philosophy of history Finding and making in knowledge Imagination and the world of art Representative knowledge ..... Religion and mysticism ..... EPILOGUE The vision of Thales INDEX . PAGE 105 107 108 115 119 123 125 126 135 144 149 150 1.52 155 160 162 172 173 179 180 182 183 186 189 193 201 204 209 211 218 223 CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION Comme done il est clair que je pense, il est clair aussi que je pense a quelque chose, c'est-a-dire, que je connais, et que j'aper^ois quelque chose. Car la pensee est essentiellement cela. Et aiiisi, ne pouvant y avoir de pensee ou de connaissance sans objet conuu, je ue puis non plus me demander a moi-meme la raisou pourquoi je pense a quelque chose, que pourquoi je pense. Arnauld, Des vrayes et desfausses Idees. Ihere is no best way of beginning a book, but journeys have to start somehow, and intending travellers expect to be ap- prised of certain matters before they set out. If you would go with us, gentle reader, you have the right to ask what we intend to discuss, and what our chief assumptions are. You will not ask more than this from an introductory chapter; for you are discerning and experienced, dear sir or madam, and we would not address you if you were not. But you cannot ask less, and we cannot do less than comply. No philosopher wants to talk about words more than he can help doing in the ordinary way of business, and the retort that philosophy is a wordy business at the best is far too cheap to be worth a glance. There would be some excuse, it is true, and perhaps some little interest, in discussing the various senses in which critics and philosophers have used the word realism. It is a hard-used drudge of a word in art and philosophy (it would turn if a word could), and that is not surprising, for reality is a difficult thing to get away from. Those who try to turn their backs upon it set their faces towards another reality, and those who desert the actual for the ideal soon bestir themselves to prove that this ideal is the only genuine fact. Realists by profession, therefore, are very apt to assume a virtue to which others are equally entitled, and the end of this thing is confusion. If everyone is a realist 2 INTRODUCTION lch. after his own fashion, and if the fashions differ, how can the word realism always mean the same thing? Plainly it has not always meant the same thing in the mouths of philosophers. In mediaeval times, as we all know, realists disputed with conceptualists and nominalists concerning the logical preeminence and the dynamic potency of Universal Forms. There is so little affinity, however, between the mediaeval and the modern usage of the term realism that even the ghost of this ambiguity has ceased to haunt the word. On the other hand the modern usage is amazingly and un- comfortably protean. If the shade of Reid could visit these regions to-day it would greet Mr Prichard of Oxford, but it would be startled by Mr Alexander, bewildered by Mr Russell and distressed by Mr Holt. Indeed one is tempted to think that any realism defined to the quick becomes nothing but the definer's private philosophy, and that the term itself cannot signify more than an attitude and a tendency. Realism in modern philosophy is born in controversy, and its foe is idealism in some form. History repeats itself in this matter, and there is a very clear similarity between Arnauld's reply to Malebranche, Reid's reply to Berkeley and Hume, and Mr Moore's criticisms of Mr Bradley. On the other hand, the three idealisms thus attacked were, after all, very different philosophies, and the Greek rule that a thing is best known by contrast with its opposite has a very precarious value when the ' opposite ' does not remain the same. The choir of heaven and furniture of earth, as Berkeley saw them, look like a cockle-boat on the ocean of the Absolute, and Reid's cudgels use a ruder science than Mr Moore's rapier. If anyone were to write a history of realism (and there is room for this enterprise) he would have to take Arnauld very seriously. The ' great doctor,' ' le plus savant mortel qui j amais ait ecrit ' as Boileau's stately epitaph puts it, had too little leisure in his tempestuous career to become a great philosopher. Still, he was eighty-two when he died, and he never understood how anyone could need repose ' when he had all eternity to rest in' ; so he found time to take the lion's share in the Port Royal Logk^ to write the best set of objections to the Medita- i] INTRODUCTION 3 tio7is of Descartes and to correspond doughtily and lengthily with Leibniz. His greatest achievement in philosophy, how- ever, was his criticism of Malebranche in a book which he described (perhaps sincerely) as a 'bagatelle,' and entitled Des vraies et desfaiisses Idees. Even those who, like Sainte Beuve^, maintain that Arnauld was no philosopher because they detest his terre-a-terre methods and love the beauty and polish of Malebranche, have to admit that the rigour, strength, and sureness of Arnauld's logic made him an easy victor. His relentless pursuit of Malebranche's doctrine of representative knowledge is still the classic exposure of that theory and would have killed it if philosophers had learned to avoid the mistakes of their ancestors. What is more, Amauld laid the foundations of a comprehensive theory of knowledge, all the more interesting on account of its Cartesian assumptions, and on account of the formal precision of its statement. We must hurry on, however, and avoid history except when we need it. But we shall be the better of a little history, and we may approach our subject by a short consideration of Reid's philosophy. Reid''s earliest and most interesting book was his Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of' Common Sense. It was a treatise on the problem of perception, and Reid claimed that all previous philosophers had espoused a most vicious fallacy. They all supposed that we perceive, not things them- selves, but their representatives; and Reid tried to show that the rerum simidacra tenuia of Lucretius, the species of the Greeks and the schoolmen, and the 'ideal theory"* of Descartes and Locke, Malebranche, Berkeley and Hume were only variants of this radical misconception. According to Reid, every one of these philosophers believed that perception is a kind of contact between mind and thing, so that anything directly perceived must touch the mind in space, and be present with it at the same moment of time. If so, it is clear that what we call the external world cannot be directly perceived. The ^ Cf. his Port Royal, vol. v. p. 449, "Allons! on peut faire d'Arnauld un grand logicien, on en peut faire un cart^sien disciple, et le premier entre les disciples; on n'en fera jamais un philosophe." 1—2 4 INTRODUCTION [ch. sun affects our bodies (and perhaps our minds) when rays from it reach us, but the sun itself does not wander into the optic nerve, and there cannot be any instantaneous compresence between the mind and the sun since the rays take time to travel. It follows that the plain man is mistaken when he supposes that he can see the stars and the hills, or feel the support of good shoe leather ; and the ancients, Reid argued, failed to notice their total disagreement with common sense simply because they con-ected one bad hypothesis with a worse one. They supposed that the circular yellow patch which we see when we look at the sun is the copy or representative of that orb. But the moderns, and especially Berkeley, easily proved that this correcting hypothesis was utterly baseless, and then they were left without any world at all. These reflections of Reid's go to the heart of the question, and they might well have proved more disturbing to common sense than Reid supposed. The plain man believes, it is true, that he perceives the sun and the earth, but he also believes that the cause of his perceiving is the fact that the sun and the earth affect his eye and his hand. If he believes further, as in fact nine men do out of ten, that all causal action is by contact, he has a very pretty problem on his hands, quite hard enough to gravel most philosophers. The problem was certainly too hard for many members of the Scottish school which Reid founded. So many Scottish clergymen knew that Hume was wrong, so many Englishmen of Dr Johnson''s type found Berkeley''s immaterialism absurd, and so very few of them were able to support their convictions by argument that any attempt at a reasoned defence of common sense fell on very quick ears. There is no other explanation for the immediate success of Oswald's ponderous invective or of Beattie's shallow elegance in his Essay on Truth. On the other hand, Reid himself was neither a furious zealot nor a plain man in enormous blinkers, and Priestley showed little penetration when he arraigned the whole ' triumvirate ' com- posed of the Glasgow professor, the author of The Minstrel^ and the minister of Methven. One can sympathise, indeed, with Priestley's annoyance at ' this sudden torrent of nonsense i] INTRODUCTION 5 and abuse that is pouring down upon us from the north' threatening to overturn the sciences and to lead to a state of affairs in which ' the whole business of thinking will be in a manner over, and we shall have nothing to do but to see and believe^,' for most of the partisans of the new philosophy understood it no better than Burns did when he wrote : Philosophers have fought and wrangled And mickle Greek and Latin mangled. Till, wi' their logic jargon tired And in the depth of science mired. To common sense they now appeal, That wives and wabsters see and feel and that interpretation is unfair, even to Beattie. Indeed, a grand jury of women and weavers would have been too sophis- ticated for some of the arguments given in the name of common sense; and some of Reid's appeals to the constitution of human nature are liable, in principle, to the same condemnation. In their essence, however, Reid's investigations were of a wholly different order from this crude acceptance of everyday beliefs, and there is really no excuse for identifying his philosophy, or any realism, with a blind belief in the existence of matter. The theme of his Inquiry was restricted, it is true, but the Inquiry itself, as Hume said in a letter to Reid, was ' deeply philosophical-,'' and Reid's survey of the mind and the world in his Intellectual Powers was both penetrating and compre- hensive despite its limitations and its occasional inconsistencies on points of detail. It is unlikely, indeed, that Reid's influence would have endured so long had there been no salt of philosophy in it. The Inquiry was published in 1764, and as late as 1857 Cousin distinctly stated that any radical departure from Reid's philosophy in Aberdeen, Glasgow or Edinburgh would be a European calamity*. The great influence of Reid's ideas in France during the first half of the nineteenth century began 1 An Examination of Dr Reid's Inquiry, etc. p. 200 and p. 202. 2 Hill Burton's Life and Correspondence of David Hume, vol. ii. pp. 153 — 154. 3 In the preface to the third edition of his Philosophic ICcossaise. Cousin omitted St Andrews from the list because Ferrier was there ! 6 INTRODUCTION [ch. with the chance which led M. Royer-Collard to purchase a copy of the Inquiry at a book -stall near the Seine in 1811, and was stimulated both by Hamilton's ostensible discipleship of Reid, and by the desire of the French people to avoid 'quelque importation de la mauvaise metaphysique de rAllemaffne deaeneree^"' This Franco-Scottish alliance, how- ever, could not have been built wholly upon sand and prejudice, and since Cousin's Philosophie Ecossaise is still the best com- mentary on the movement, there is good reason for considering what Cousin said of it. Cousin claimed that Reid's discoveries in metaphysics were of the same fundamental importance as Adam Smith's in political economy^, and he found the essence of Reid's discovery and method in a passage at the end of the Inquiry. In this passage Reid contrasted the 'way of reflection' with the 'way of analogy.' All previous philosophers, he maintained, chose the ' way of analogy.' They tried to interpret the mind in the light of inappropriate analogies ultimately derived from the contact of bodies in space, and so they went to their destruction. The ' way of reflection,' Reid continued, avoids this initial fallacy. Its beginnings are set in ' reflection,' and that, in its turn, is just accurate attention to the mind itself. When our mental processes are carefully discriminated without prepossessions, and particularly without the prejudice that results from supposing that explanations of the mind must conform to causal and spatial canons which in fact are wholly inapplicable, the chief problems of knowledge solve themselves 1 Cousin's phrase, ibid. There is a curious irony in reading these state- ments nowadays, and the reader may be interested in the similar attitude of Scottish theologians in those times. "For those who are not inclined to study German philosophy" Dr Chalmers said a few years earlier "I do not recommend that they should suspend for it their ordinary readings. Their very ignorance of the German idealism, the very confinement of their mental philosophy to the doctrine and metaphysics of the Scottish school, are guarantees in themselves against the deleterious influence of these out- landish speculations" (Fraser, Biographia Philosophica, p. 74). Chalmers, for his part, preferred ' plain Scottish boluses ' ; he was convinced that ' the unintelligible does not always imply the solid or even the profound ' ; and of much more to the same effect. He preferred Kale to Sauerkraut. 2 Philosophie Ecossaise, Avertissement, p. ii. i] INTRODUCTION 7 in the sense that accurate observations followed by careful reasoning give an answer that can neither be impugned nor rejected. "When the operations of the mind are exerted, we are conscious of them, and it is in our power to attend to them, and to reflect upon them, until they become familiar objects of thought. This is the only way in which we can form just and accurate notions of those operations^"" In itself, this account of the spirit of Reid's enterprise, does not differ importantly from the programme of Locke's Essay -^ and Reid's hint, later on in the same chapter, that this method of direct deduction from the phenomena without analogy or hypothesis had been attended by great success in the domain of physics is thoroughly characteristic of the eighteenth century. The glamour of Newton's achievements led all the philosophers of that age to have great hopes of experimental inquiries into human nature. "When Reid was a student in Aberdeen he learnt as much as that from his master Turnbull^, and the subtitle of Hume's Treatise declares it in so many words*. There is nothing peculiarly distinctive, therefore, in Reid's conception of his task. His merit lies in the tenacity with which he clung to the phenomena he found, and in his refusal to be fobbed off with anything else. What, then, are these phenomena.? It would seem from the above quotation that Reid took them to be the operations of the mind, or, rather, those mental operations which are specifically concerned with the business of knowing. If so, he deserved great credit for his thorough and searching survey of these complex and varied operations in his Intellectual Powers, and for his courage in insisting, to the point of tedium, on the fundamental doctrine that these operations should be studied for themselves alone and should not be supposed to have the characteristics of other things unless and until they ^ Inquiry, Hamilton's edition, p. 201. 2 George TurnbuU (1698—1748) Wcas a regent of Marischal College, Aber- deen, from 1721 till 1727. Eeid's name was on his roll in 1726. Turnbull wrote many books, and his Anticnt Paintings is one of the unfortunate tomes ■which the porter found too heavy in Hogarth's picture. » "A Treatise of Human Nature: Being an Attempt to introduce the experimental Method of Reasoning into Moral Subjects." 8 INTRODUCTION [ch. have been proved to have them. On the other hand, the bays which he rightly earned on this account would make Ijut half a diadem. The operations of the mind that is bent on knowing are only a part of the relevant phenomena. While there is remembering, supposing and believing of the one part, there are the things remembered, supposed or believed of the other part. Anyone, that is to say, who sets himself to reflect upon the operations of the mind in knowledge, has also to reflect upon the objects before the mind, and anyone who distrusts specious analogies concerning the process of knowing should also distrust elusive and figurative descriptions of the objects which in fact are known. He must examine and consider most scrupulously what it is that we apprehend in any given instance, instead of arguing that we must apprehend this or the other kind of thing because our theories of the universe, untested by observation, have it so. Reid's detailed investigations (and the concluding chapter of the LTquiry, for that matter) show that he had grasped this double aspect of his problem very firmly indeed, even if some of his definitions incautiously omit it. If this be allowed, Reid's work as a whole is a sane and resolute application of the funda- mental principle of any realism. For realism is a theory of knowledge whose essence is to supply a complete phenomeno- logy of knowing and of things known, or, in other words, to make an accurate and thorough survey both of the processes of knowing and of the objects directly known through these processes. The trouble is, of course, that so many philosophies make precisely the same claim. Did not Hegel write his Plieno- menology, and do not James or Bergson or Avenarius give us a philosophy of pure experience, each in his several way ? All these philosophers, it would seem, want the same thing and they attain something very different. There must therefore be something peculiar and distinctive in realism to explain its difference from these other philosophies. This distinctive thing, I suppose, is an affair of assumptions, and, perhaps, of hopes and expectations. The main assumption of realism is that things can be known as they really are. The I] INTRODUCTION 9 secondary, but scarcely less important assumption, is that anything is precisely what it appears to be when sufficient precautions have been taken to avoid confusion between the actual genuine appearance and spurious though very plausible glosses upon it. It follows, of course, that these genuine appearances cannot contradict one another; for things cannot contradict one another. It also follows that true knowledge of this or the other thing need not logically imply the knowledge of all its conditions. To say that things can be known means, of course, that they can be known by us. We, however, are finite beings, and so we cannot hope to know more than a very small part of the infinitude of existence. Peo' contra^ we have no right to deny the usual, and, in all probability, the very just belief that everything in the universe has strictly infinite ramifications, so that, if we were sagacious enough, we might pass from cats to clover and from clover to the stars. Similarly we have no right to deny the orthodox assumption of psychology that any piece of thinking is a subtle web whose pattern, perhaps, was woven long before the days of our eolithic ancestors, and whose yarn, even now, is three parts spun in a blind loom of miles of branching nerves. Thus if we know anything as it really is we must be able to know it despite the fact that we do not know much that pertains to it in the way of conditions and connections. These assumptions distinguish realism very sharply from the Anglo-Hegelian idealism which was lately dominant and still is fashionable in these islands. Even the Oxford idealists, however, might find a meaning for them which they would consider tolerably innocuous and moderately true ; and the pragmatists or M. Bergson might contrive to accept them totidem verbis. Some further explanation is needed, therefore. The statement that things can be known as they really are is simple in appearance only. We need not stay, it is true, to consider what is meant by a 'thing,*' for 'things' in this general statement must clearly be understood in the most general sense possible. Any entity whatsoever that can be apprehended by the mind is a ' thing ' in this sense, so that rainbows, dream castles, a yearning for Nirvana, and the null-class are included 10 INTRODUCTION [ch. in the statement as well as the ships and the rifles which take part in the executive order of the physical world. On the other hand, two points at least require special discussion. To say that things may be known does not tell us what their reality is. That is a problem for investigation, not something that can be defined in advance, and, of course, there is no implication that knowledge can be satisfied in all its enterprises. There may be many things which we cannot begin to apprehend. A being like Voltaire's Micromegas, for example, with his thousand senses, would be acquainted with more than nine hundred and ninety kinds of sensible qualities from which we are cut off. Again, there are many things of which we know only that they are, not xohat they are. The meaning of the statement, then, is only that there is nothing in the relation between the mind and things which, of itself, makes anything inaccessible to knowledge. To put it other- wise, the reason for ignorance never lies in the ineptitude of knowledge. It is due, when it occurs, simply to the empirical iact that the mind either does not apprehend these things, or, for some reason of fact, is not in a position to apprehend them. A blind man should blame his eyes and not his mind when he cannot see the sunset. What, then, is this knowledge for which so much is claimed.'' According to M. Bergson, true knowledge is intuition \ and that, in its turn, is a process of union and becoming. The man who grasps anything by intuition worms his way into the very being of that thing until it is incorporated into him and he into it. We know a thing by becoming it, and it is known by becoming us. Others, again, maintain that knowledge of a thing is the possession of an image or representative of it, so that we know anything when we possess certain pictures or tokens, and not otherwise. The pragmatists, for their part, are shy of such theories because they do not take knowledge very seriously. They consider it a temporary adjustment between ourselves and our environment, a useful compromise which enables us to get along ; and from that point of view ^ See his Introduction to Metaphysics, passim. i] INTRODUCTION 11 it is only idle fancy to believe that anything could be finally and utterly what we take it to be. Realists, however, deny all these theories, though they ad- mit a subsidiary and consequential truth to some of them. The first they deny altogether. Knowledge, they think, is never a kind of identity, and they are apt to choose very common- place illustrations to support their contention. We do not become Niagara by looking at it ; we do not become the past by remembering the Great War ; we do not become a set of figures by contemplating the multiplication table ; and so on. On the contrary, if we became these things we could not know them at all. According to realists, the process of knowledge always implies that the mind is confronted with an object, and always implies that we are never under any conceivable circum- stances identical with that object. Even when we apprehend our own experiences, the process of apprehension cannot be identical with the experience which is apprehended. Realists therefore deny the reality of intuition in M. Bergson''s sense but they need not be quite so intransigeant in respect of the other theories. They need not deny that much of our knowledge is merely representative. What they deny is, firstly, that knowledge means representation, and secondly that representative knowledge could occur without a direct, non -representative basis. If knowledge meant representation, statues of dead men would know the dead men, and the still pools would know the clouds and the trees which they reflect. Indirect or representative knowledge, again, implies direct acquaintance at some point. The collector who finds an ancient coin, for example, has only an indirect acquaintance with the potentate whose image is stamped upon it, but he is directly acquainted with the coin, and he could not know that the impression stamped upon it really is an image unless he were able to compare some portraits with some originals from direct acquaintance with both. And realists are in earnest concern- ing truth and knowledge while pragmatists are not. They need not deny, indeed, that knowledge is useful precisely in proportion as it affords guidance here and now, or that a lucky guess or a vague approximation may often work as well 12 INTRODUCTION [ch. as, or even better than, well-grounded knowledge. What they are bound to deny is that the mere fact of being guided by ideas,expectations,preiudicesandthelikeis">- believe in this physical world of common sense, and our judg- ment (as Hume said) ' peoples it-."' We can perceive, remem- ber and judge the same things, but our judgment apprehends 1 The Grammar of Assent, 3rd ed. p. 90. 2 Treatise, bk i. pt in. sect. ix. : " 'Tis this latter principle which peoples the world, and brings us acquainted with such existences, as by their removal in time and place, lie beyond the reach of the senses and memory." 6—2 i 84 THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF [ch. these things at its own level, and interprets the rudimentary meanings of direct memory and perception in a much more explicit fashion. And we have seen already that perception and judgments of perception are not the same. To choose Meinong"'s example, there is a difference between the red cross which is perceived and the belief that the cross is red^ True, the only possible evidence for the belief that the cross is red is the perception of the red cross, and this evidence, we are sure, is amply sufficient. None the less, a thing, in so far as it is perceived, is not a proposition, and propositions, in strictness, are what we believe. There is the same kind of dis- tinction between perceived meanings and the set of propositions which interpret these meanings in terms of judgment. It may seem very absurd, prima facie ^ to pay any attention to this believed thing which common sense calls a world, because science and philosophy pride themselves upon being better interpreters of fact than the plain man. What the world is in detail, what space and time are, what the consti- tution of matter is, must be inferred from the detail of what we perceive or remember, and require the most intimate partnership between rigorous deduction and unbiassed obser- vation, between parsimony of principles and genius for experi- ment. On the other hand, the data of science and philosophy include judgments of perception as well as perception itself, so that even the most philosophical improver of common sense cannot avoid the problem altogether, and the reflective inter- pretations of common sense, however hasty and crude and dogmatic they may be, must have gold in them as well as dross. At the worst they are a muddy deposit which may be clarified by those who make a business of clarifying, and, at the best, common sense may be right in its main conclusions although impatient of detail, confused in its expressions, and halting in its proofs. We believe (I think justly) that there is a physical world. This world contains the things we perceive and remember and expect, and it also contains a vast apparatus of things which connect these. This connective tissue permeates and encom- 1 Veber Annahmen, Kap. 6, 1st ed. p. 110 and passim. v] THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF 85 passes these perceived things, and it is beheved to exist just as certainly as they and much in the same manner. If a letter reaches me from America I can obtain some evidence about its journey from my own perception and from that of other people. The letter was perceived by the writer and by some postmen and sorters. Someone saw it when it was dropped into a bag, and someone saw the bag put on board a ship. The pilot who steered the ship out of the harbour used his ejes; the captain or the mates perceived the ship and the sea during the whole voyage ; and so on. Still there was far more in the ship than the ship's company perceived at any moment, and more in the ocean than the watchers saw from the bridge. The ship, and the ocean, and the world itself are believed things inferred from these partial and intermittent soundings of perception and memory, even granting that these soundings have always a meaning beyond themselves. The world is a continuing thing, spread out and enduring; and its features, except tentatively and in shreds and patches, are not perceived but judged and inferred. The things which appear to perception also appear to belief, and philosophers should scrutinise these beliefs in the same spirit as they scrutinise per- ception. We perceive sign-facts, and we believe — what .'' When Hume said that judgment 'peoples the world"* he assumed without any question that belief attaches itself to the impressions of the senses and of memory^ We are tied down to these beliefs and constrained by them just as if our ideas were things (to borrow a phrase from Tolstoi). Hume did not suppose, however, that this sense of constraint, this firm- ness and steadiness of conception, was confined to perception and memory. He knew that it also belonged to anything 1 Treatise, bk i. pt in. sect. ix. : "Of these impressions or ideas of the memory we form a kind of system, comprehending whatever we remember to have been present, either to our internal perception or senses; and every par- ticular of that system, join'd to the present impressions, we are pleased to call a reality. But the mind stops not here. For finding that with this system of perceptions there is another connected by custom, or, if you will, by the rela- tion of cause and effect... it forms (these ideas) into a new system, which it likewise dignifies with the title of realities. The first of these systems is the object of the memory and senses; the second of the judgment." 86 THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF [ch. which we take to be causally connected with perceived or re- membered things. Indeed, Hume meant by 'judgment' pre- cisely this extension of perception and memory by causal interpretation, and he was concerned to show that all causal interpretations are extensions of the memory and senses. It is plain that he was right in this. Causal interpretation, to be sure, supplements observation and interpolates numberless unobserved links, but the world of common belief rests on per- ception in the end. If we can observe or remember that 'the stick began to beat the dog ' we may be able to infer the chain of events which led to the old woman's difficulty at the stile and the rest of it, but without this observation or recollection the whole chain of inference would dangle without a support, and our ideas about the world would be as impotent as Baron Munchausen's method of descending from the moon, when he slid halfway down the rope and then made use of the upper portion that had become useless. Assuming, then, that the physical world is a realm of existence in which fragments are perceived or remembered and the rest ' peopled ' by things which are required to satisfy our causal interpretations of these fragments, we have to ask how far, in broad outline, this world may be said to be discovered. To speak more accurately, the physical world is that system of things which, if it exists, is the foundation of the truth of a certain set of beliefs, i.e. the beliefs based directly on perception and memory and the beliefs derived from these by causal in- terpretation. To believe in the existence of this world is to believe in the truth of these propositions, and plainly the most important question to ask is what these propositions are. Nearly anyone would admit that these propositions, if they are true, are about the world or parts of it, and that the world guarantees and controls them. That admission, however, does not tell us what these propositions are, how they are about the world or how the world controls or guarantees them ; and so we must ask these questions for ourselves. Let us ask, then, in the first place, what these propositions are. What precisely is before the mind when anyone believes proposi- tions like ' The cross is red ' or ' lialage has torn her pinafore ' ? v] THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF 87 Adapting a term of Meinong's^, we may say that proposi- tions are asserted 'objectives.'' An example will show what is meant. When we perceive a red cross we are justified in be- lieving that the cross is red. ' That-the-cross-is-red ** (or ' the- redness-of-the-cross,*' if the reader prefers) is the objective of the judgment. The proposition ' The cross is red ' asserts this objective, but anyone who questioned this judgment or began to consider ' Well ! what about this redness of the cross .''' would merely contemplate the objective without also asserting it for true. The indicative mood expresses assertion, while the optative or subjunctive moods do not ; and yet precisely the same objective — this 'redness-of-the-cross' — is before the mind in all these moods. Propositions, therefore, are asserted objectives; and these objectives in their turn are manifestly complex. The next step, therefore, is to find the elements of the objectives. An objective is the kind of fact which we express by a verbal noun, and a verb usually expresses a relationship between at least two things. That is clearly true in the case of Lalage and her pinafore, so perhaps we may turn to the more fundamental example of the red cross. The objective in this case contains a relation between the cross and redness, i.e. a relation between a logical subject or individual and a universal quality belong- ing to it. And that raises difficulties. It is clear that the red cross is an existing thing and that redness is not. ' Redness ' does not do any work. It does not even keep its place through inertia, for it has no place and no inertia. It is only a universal. So much is clear, but the very obviousness of this analysis is beset with difficulties. The objective, we have said, is complex and contains a universal related to its logical subject. But what is this subject .'' If it is the red cross, the subject, so to speak, is red already, and there is therefore no need for, and no value in, the universal. If, on the other hand, the logical subject is the cross unqualified by redness, the trouble is still greater, if that be possible. For the cross is red, and it is never unqualified in fact. The supposed subject would, therefore, be a nonentity. Again, the red cross ^ Ueher Annahmen , passim. 88 THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF [ch. is perceived. It is just one thing, and to analyse it into two things is the merest makeshift. Perhaps we may circumvent these difficulties by considering another aspect of the affair. We perceive the red cross and we believe that the cross is red. Our belief, we say, is about the red cross, and the perception of the cross is the evidence for the belief. What, then, is the relation of the belief to the percept, and in what sense is it about the thing perceived ? As we have seen, we perceive physical things, and we do not, strictly speaking, perceive mere percepts any more than we expect expectations or promise promises or intend intentions. Perception, it is true, like any other mode of apprehension, im- plies certain limitations in our acquaintance with the thing, but although we apprehend things in this limited fashion we never attribute these limitations to the things themselves. Thus although the red cross is perceived, it is not a mere per- cept, but a thing. The percept, on the contrary, is only a sign-fact, in part literally identical with the thing, in part significant of certain further aspects of the thing's thinghood. Now this same thing that we perceive is also the subject about which we judge, and the universal 'redness' is about its subject simply in the sense that the thing is characterised by this universal quality just as it is characterised by many other universal qualities. We refer to things in judgment, not to objectives, precisely as we perceive things and not percepts ; and an objective of this kind means a thing in so far as it is restricted in the special mode of judgment, while a percept is the same thing in so far as it is restricted in the special mode of perception. Judgment always selects some one of the many universal characteristics which things have. Perception does not select in this fashion although it selects in another fashion. None of the restrictions implied in either judgment or percep- tion is attributed to the thing itself, and, at the same time there is no need for supposing that things themselves are not literally all that they are perceived to be and all that they are judged to be, though they are not limited to the features or pro- perties which perception or judgment is capable of selecting. Let us consider some of the objections to this position. v] THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF 89 Those who beheve that we perceive percepts (or sense data) usually regard this percept as an ultimate of ultimates, so much pure fact wholly self-enclosed and incorrigibly real. This view, I have tried to show, is mistaken, but it would vitally affect our theories of the world if it were true. As we have seen so very often, it is plain that a thing endures al- though it is perceived intermittently, while it is equally plain that a percept cannot endure, simply because it is confined to intermittent apprehension. Moreover, it is plain that a per- cept cannot be identical with an objective since the objective is judged and not perceived, since the percept is particular while the objective contains a universal, and since the percept has not the kind of complexity which the objective has. For these and similar reasons writers of this school give a totally different analysis of the facts from the one we have chosen. A judgment of perception, they say, is the apprehension of an objective which corresponds to a percept. The objective, as a whole, is about the percept, and the percept is never a con- stituent of it. As it seems to me, anyone who holds this theory is forced to relinquish the most certain thing in this puzzling matter. What seems to me most certain is that I discover the character of the thing I perceive in all true judgments of perception. * This book which I see is red.' If I really mean what I say when I make this assertion, my belief must refer to the book itself, and I must also perceive that very book. The theory before us ignores the book altogether, and cheats us with ob- jectives and sense data instead; and this omission seems to me a sufficient refutation of it. A second objection runs somewhat as follows. When we assert that the cross is red, the 'is' in our assertion is unintel- ligible unless it asserts identity; and that is inconsistent with our analysis. For 'redness' is not a part of the book, like one of its pages, still less identical with the book; and the book is a thing and not a collection of universals like redness, heaviness, and the like. This argument raises many problems concerning the status of universals and some of these must be postponed until the 90 THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF [ch. next chapter. Its main purport, however, can be examined independently of these investigations. Redness, I take it, is a characteristic of many red things — of sunsets and uniforms and sealing wax and new-born infants, for example. When we say that any of these things is red, we mean that it is red and we do not mean that it is identical with redness. The 'is' of predication is not the 'is' of identity. What is it, then ? Why, the 'is' of predication. According to a third objection 'redness' is only a concept, and consequently only a mental gloss upon things, not a dis- coverable property of them. We perceive reds, not redness, and redness itself is only a product of mental comparison. It is the result of mental experiments which n)ay be utterly capricious, for, if we choose, we may compare anything we like from carburetters to chalcedony, and from the mad hatter's tea-party to the debates on Olympus. There is no need for profound thinking to answer this ob- jection. Certainly we have to conduct intellectual experiments in order to find out what 'redness' is, and we have complete liberty concerning the things that we choose to compare, but these experiments, like any others, are a means of discovery, and the results of the experiments are made for us and not by us. The air in ancient Corinth contained its twenty per cent, (or thereabouts) of oxygen before Priestley discovered 'dephlogisticated air\' or Van Helmont distinguished ga,^ from bias. Similarly, redness is discovered to be a common property of blood and of sunsets whenever we choose to make this experiment in comparing. A fourth objection still remains. Judgment, we are told, confounds the unity of things by dividing their substance. It gives us a series of items in an inventory, like a grocer's list. In fact vermilion is red and heavy and so forth, but it is all these in one. In our judgments we take these items separately, like the rosy cheek and coral lips and snowy brow of a Jacobean poem. The dead hand of analytic separation is 1 Stephen Hales had priority in this discovery, but his researches were not followed up. v] THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF 91 heavy on all judgment, and this paralysing analysis, like a speck of rust, corrodes all the linen. Now it is true that judgment selects items, but the selection, unless it is wholly misconceived, does not impair a thing's integrity. To say that vermilion is scarlet and heavy does not mean that it is two things, a scarlet thing and a heavy one, somehow connected together. It is just one thing all the time, scarlet and heavy and much besides; and the analysis of these properties never divides the substance. The point is fundamental, for judgment is incomparably the most important means of apprehending things, and if things are not really and ultimately what they are judged to be, then farewell to serious thinking. The implications of perception and memory are worth very little unless they are followed out into a chain of judgments, and the chain itself is worthless unless each several link in it can be proved. He who trusts himself to logic must trust altogether. He cannot seriously, like the instrumentalists or Mr Bradley, step into the stream with one foot and keep the other on the bank ; for the bank is not firm enough and the stream too masterful. According to Mr Bradley, logic is forced to assume what metaphysics is forced to reject. That is marching with the Pretender and investing in the Funds. All thinking must assume what logic assumes, and realism, at bottom, is just the assertion of this principle. Indeed, we might define realism as the theory of knowledge which literally accepts all the logical assumptions which Mr Bradley sees to be involved in logic. The most im- portant of these assumptions are the following. Logic, Mr Bradley says, is forced to assume that the processes of distinguishing, comparing and constructing do not modify their data \ that attention, retaining and holding together be- fore the mind do not alter the content apprehended", and that the Identity of Indiscernibles is true in the sense that 'so long as an ideal content is identical no change of context can destroy its unity'."" It would not be easy to give a better definition of our thesis. 1 Principles of Logic, p. 506. "^ Ibid. p. 502. =* Ibid. p. 264. 92 THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF [ch. Perhaps we should linger to notice a consequence of our position before proceeding to a further description of the world of common belief. Just as the judgment that vermilion is red and heavy seems, on its first aspect, to disintegrate the one perceived thing into a list of separate items, so a chain of judgments may seem to separate the world itself into so many separate rigidities. It is important to notice that this conse- quence does not follow. It is logically possible, to be sure, that the world is a loose, disjointed, strung-along affair, but this logical possibility is certainly not a logical certainty, and even if Caird and his followers were right in maintaining that the world is a ' seamless unity,' the chain of logical inferences would not therefore be impugned. It does not follow that linen is rent into whiteness and glossiness merely because we are able to judge truly that it is both white and glossy. It is white, glossy linen, and the predicates of these two judgments characterise one and the same piece of linen without doing violence to its unity. Each is partial but neither falsifies. Similarly any chain of true beliefs which characterises different portions and features of the world is partial but does not falsify. The world need not be a mere collection just because it can be parcelled into sorts, and it need not be strung along in a chain simply because true beliefs are linked together chain- wise. The world would have room for this chain of beliefs even if it were a seamless unity, and neither the links nor the chain need be false just because the world itself is more intimately knit than any chain of items. Summing up, then, we may say that the world of daily life is a believed thing rather than a perceived or remembered one, although some of the things in it are perceived or remembered. It is a set of connected things having the characters recognised in judgment; and this explains the sense in which the pro- positions in which we believe are about things and the sense in which things control our beliefs. We have also seen that the world contains the structure and implications of logic, precisely because it is thinkable. Its empirical properties, however, are not merely logical. The logical connection of subject and predicate, for example, does v] THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF 93 not explain the yellowness of ochre or the blueness of the sky, and the logical relation of difference does not account for the empirical fact that Warsaw is not Paris or that geese are not swans. This empirical connectedness and difference, therefore, which is not a merely logical thing, ought to be considered. We know that ochre is yellow because we perceive yellow ochre. Perception, therefore, is our warrant for believing in this empirical proposition, and perception similarly entitles us to believe in many other empirical propositions which assert a connection between things. When we believe that the pea is under the thimble, or that the report comes after the flash, or that Lalage has torn her pinafore, our beliefs are either in- ferences from perception or directly based upon it, and if they are inferences, these inferences, in their turn, depend upon the direct perception of empirical things empirically related. We ' may be wrong about the pea and the thimble, but at some point we perceived these two things in a certain spatial re- <:^ lation. We may have to remember the flash when we hear the report, but some intervals of time may be apprehended in a single span of perception. We may have misjudged Lalage, but we have often perceived children and puppies tearing things to pieces. We interpret the world spatially, then, and we have to distinguish between the space of direct perception and the space of belief. As we have seen, the things we perceive are obviously extended, or, at any rate, things which are seen or touched are extended, and also toothache and bruises when we feel them. Perceived things, moreover, are suffused with a perceived meaning, and this, in its turn, indicates a wider spatial context. The order of space in Avhich we believe is an interpretation of the sign-facts perceived or remembered. It is based on the properties and the meaning of these sign -facts. Common sense, it is true, does not think out these interpreta- tions to their full conclusion, and consequently it is puzzled by much that philosophers and physicists say about space. It is offended by I'latland, and amazed by Einstein, but the truth is that the common-sense belief in a single spatial world in , three dimensions is too little developed to be able to discuss ' 94 THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF [ch. such points. It is not in a position to argue whether space is absolute or relative, whether ' the space of the real world is a space of six-dimensions', whether the older physics or the Quantum theory is in the rights and so forth. The world is in one space for common sense because there is a general spatial ■ order at least within the stellar universe, and it has three di- mensions because one man can go east and another north and another go up in the air. These meanings are found in per-., ception, and common sense carries this perceptual meaning very much further than perception can. If its orbit is too narrow for science it is wide enough for most ordinary purposes. The perceived meaning of extended things, then, cries out for and receives the interpretation of judgment, and the beliefs so arising commit us to the belief in a general spatial '" order. We are constrained to interpret things in terms of spatial continuity. The margin of perception, to mention no other circumstance, forces us to conclude that any perceived thing is of a piece with its surroundings, and that these sur- roundings do not come into being when we attend to them closely, although they are perceived but dimly on the margin and beyond the margin are not perceived at all. The spaces [ we perceive are filled spaces, that is to say, there is continuity ] within them ; and when our attention passes from one thing to another the interval is also filled space. We interpret these ^'^ indications of perception when we believe that the world as a whole is spatially continuous in the same sense as any per- ceptible portion of it, and our spatial explorations in the way of perceiving are subject to this interpretation. Similar arguments hold of time. The world of common belief is a world of continuants which are either simultaneous or successive in the general order of time. The perception of transience, with its order of earlier and later, is the basis and the empirical warrant for this belief, and the common order of time is the correlation of all perceived simultaneities and suc- cessions. Common sense, it is true, has not reflected very ^ Eussell's Mysticism and Logic, p. 138. 2 Cf. J. W. Nicholson's paper in Prohlenns of Science and Philosophy, Aristo- telian Society, Supplementary Vol. ii, 1919. y] THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF 95 deeply upon time, or upon its continuity and its common order. It does not cross-examine the Man with the Scythe very sharply, and therefore it is not prepared to say whether the structure of time may not be corpuscular^ whether the measurement of time does not always move in a circle, whether the time of the stellar universe may not be only a sort of local time, whether time and space are not indivisibly united in the fact of motion, and so on. It does assume, however, that every perceptible event is either simultaneous or successive as compared with every other perceptible event, that the inter- mittence of perception does not annul the temporal continuity of any continuant, and that any continuant has just one history. These assumptions, taken together, sufficiently define the beliefs of common sense, and the last of them sums up the position. If we want to know whether Kaspar Hauser was really a wild man of the woods we have to trace his biography, and if that can be done the problem is solved, just because he had only one biography. A ship has only one history, and therefore we should be likely to discover what argosy was wrecked at Tobermory if we could trace the history of every other ship in the Armada. Our belief in the world, then, is an interpretation of the things and events we have perceived or remember. It is reflection following out and giving full weight to perceived meanings. The world, it is true, is richer than our judgments, because we perceive so little and reflect so ill ; and it is far richer in qualities than its logical structure and the order of space and time imply of themselves. For these are only the skeleton of a body which has flesh and blood and is clothed besides. Common sense, however, uses at least one other general principle of interpretation, since it interprets things causally, and we must therefore examine this principle. Under causal interpretation I mean to include causal correla- tions like the growth of stamens and pistils in a poppy, causal laws like the law of gravitation, and causes and effects like the stroke of the bat that sends the ball to the boundary. As all the world knows, Hume made the difficulties of ^ Eussell's Mysticism and Logic, p. 129. 96 THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF [ch. causal interpretation so very clear that no philosopher coming- after him has any excuse for neglecting theni\ The principal counts in Hume's indictment are that causation is never per- ceived, and that it cannot be inferred from the perceived phenomena without an immense fallacy. Although we say that bread nourishes, we never observe any mysterious tie between the bread and the formation of tissue. We can only observe a uniform sequence between the swallowing and digesting of the bread and the subsequent formation of tissue. This uniform sequence maybe uncontradicted in our experience. Bread always nourishes if we assume that when it does not nourish it is either not bread or rejected by the stomach. But if the causal action of the bread cannot be observed in any single instance, it plainly cannot be observed in a series of instances, and the problem, therefore, is how the number of instances (granting that there are no known exceptions) can guarantee the causal interpretation when no single instance does so. According to Hume, this inference from repetition of in- stances to their necessary connection is quite unjustifiable. The repetition neither discovers nor produces anything new in the phenomena, and yet we infer that bread must always nourish and tire always consume, because we have repeated experience that they have done so in the past. This inference can scarcely pretend to be valid. If we say that bread will nourish in the future because it mtist nourish, we have begged the question; and if we say that fire will continue to consume in the future because it has always consumed in the past, our inference manifestly outruns the evidence. Those philosophers who had wit enough to see the force of Hume's difficulties have usually attempted to answer him in one or other of two ways. The first answer is that causality is an a priori law somehow involved in the possibility of things. Hume answered this contention when he pointed out that there is no contradiction in denying causal laws. There is no logical contradiction in supposing that bread may cease to nourish without any reason whatever; and that seems final, 1 Treatise, bk i. pt iii., and Enquiry concerning the Human Under- standing, sect. vii. v] THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF 97 even granting that Kant gainsaid it. According to Kant there is some sort of intrinsic connection between causation and the hypothetical judgment in the logical category of rela- tion i. This contention, however, is only a tour deforce inspired by Kant's belief that every 'principle of the understanding' must have a twin brother in the logical table of judgments. The other attempted answer to Hume maintains that we can directly perceive certain causal connections in our own persons. We feel that we can enforce, and also that we can be compelled against our wills. This reply, however, does not wring Hume's withers. These feelings of compulsion and spontaneous enforcement are highly capricious and irregular, and they cannot justify any inference to that necessity for uniform behaviour which Hume took to be the meaning of causality. Hume might well have thought this argument sufficient in itself, but he supplied many other arguments in case any one should want them, like the nine and twenty excellent reasons which the Mayor of Coventry gave for refusing to ring the bells in honour of Queen Elizabeth after he had stated ^Imprimis we have no bells' by way of preface. These arguments are set forth in his Enquiry, §§ 52 and 53, where he asks whether we know the secret union between mind and body, whether we know why the will controls the fingers and does not control the liver, whether we can really discern the connection between volition and the nerves, muscles and tendons of the body, whether we know the precise manner in which the soul creates images in the fancy, whether we can tell bow the mind commands itself at some times and fails to do so at other times, or how men have greater self-control in health than they have in sickness. Only experience, Hume argues, can tell us what we can do and what we cannot do, and this experience is never the perception of necessity. That is surely clear, and we might add (if it were permissible to labour the point further than Hume himself) that even if, per impossibile, we had this direct acquaintance with necessary connection in our own persons, we should have very little reason ^ Critique of Pure Reason, Analytic of Conceptions, Sections ii. and in. L. 7 98 THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF [ch. for extending it by analogy to the inanimate world. Do we seriously suppose that we are acquainted with the dynamics of impact just because we can belabour a punching-ball? Because we sympathise with Tantalus, have we any right to maintain that the tides are due to the moon's unavailing thirst for the sea? Hume did not deny, of course, that we believe in causes. He was too indolent, he said, not to believe that fire burns, although he had proved that this belief had no rational grounds^ He peopled his world by judgment (including causal interpretation) like other folk. The problem is there- fore whether this peopling of the world has any grounds which Hume overlooked ; and this question is clearly of the first im- portance. Causal interpretation, indeed, is nine parts of the world of common belief We read a letter and infer that it came over the seas, we see the sun and infer that rays from it must reach us through some medium. The postal system and the solar system are believed things based on the causal in- terpretation of a few vestiges of perceived fact. Causation, in a word, is our clue to the continuous filling of space and time. Hume"'s analysis was defective because he overlooked the perceived meaning of perceived things. He admitted that we perceive succession directly, as well as figure, colour and sound; but he maintained that all perceived things are loose and separate, and that we always perceive bare conj unction without any hint of connection. Both these assumptions are false in fact. We perceive things within a context, and all perceived things have a meaning when they are apprehended. Wliat is more, this meaning is not mere conjunction (or bare to- getherness in space and disconnected succession in time). The context which signified in perception is not a mere skeleton of conjunction, because we never perceive empty space and empty time; and the meaning directly perceived in the filling of space and time has the seeds of causality in it. 1 Treatise, bk i. pt rv. sect, vii.: "My natural propensity reduces me to this indolent belief in the general maxims of the world." " If we believe that fire warms, or water refreshes, 'tis only because it costs us too much pains to think otherwise." v] THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF 99 Causal interpretation implies the irrelevance of mere space and mere time. Time and space, to be sure, are not irrelevant in one sense. A plant takes time to grow, and needs room to grow in, but the causal interpretation of its growth depends upon the assumption that the rate of its growth and the stature which it attains depend upon the kind of thing which it is, the degree in which it can keep itself alive and utilise surrounding things, and so forth. Things are in space and in time, and therefore their actions and reactions are spatial and temporal too; but empty space and time are subordinate in all causal determinations because the determining factor in the behaviour of things is taken to be the properties of the things themselves. Neither position by itself, nor succession by itself, nor these twain together can explain the causal connectedness of anything; and Hume's argument shows very clearly why it must be so. His argument also shows that causal connected- ness means nothing without perception and experience. In point of fact, however, perception does contain a causal meaning, and so does the experience of voluntary movement. This perceived causal meaning, to be sure, is only a perceived meaning, unverbalised and very easy to interpret falsely when we reflect upon it, but it contains a presumption which is the nucleus of a principle. To state it broadly, this presumption is that anything which occupies a place thereby keeps other things out and makes a difference to other surrounding things, and that any continuant changes or remains identical because of the kind of thing it is and because it is set in a certain environment. In particular cases we can perceive things play- ing their part, making a difference to other things or clinging temporarily to their individual being ; and this fact of percep- tion is the ultimate basis of causal interpretation. This broad presumption, it is true, does not of itself justify the transition to unvarying causal laws. From the principle that everything makes some kind of difference to other things, or that every happening has some kind of explanation in its surroundings, it is (juite impossible to infer that all causation is regular and uniform. Simplv because a thing plays its part, it does not follow that the same thing always plays the same 7—2 100 THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF [ch. part in the same surroundings, still less that the same kind of thing always plays the same part. We never perceive necessary connection, although in some cases, after long experience, we come to expect some res'ults with very great confidence indeed. On the other hand, if we grant the presumption (even with- out the certainty) that everything which exists plays a part in the world, it is reasonable for us, and even necessary, to consider what part it plays; and if the result of this enquiry is to show, on the whole, that the same kind of thing always seems to play a uniform and regular part, there is no coercive reason for rejecting this specific interpretation of the causal principle. When we are scientifically minded we assume that all physical events are regularly determined in this way, and probably that psychological events are causally determined too. Indeed we argue, not only that every physical event is a member of some uniform causal series, but that it is highly probable that we can discover by our methods of elimination ivhat causal series it belongs to; and we explain apparent ex- ceptions by supposing that there always is a cause for them even although we have not had the luck to discover it. Common sense, however (unless it is content to echo the trumpets of science), is not nearly so positive in its experi- mental determinism. It is quite ready to admit that some things are as capricious and irregular in their behaviour as a woman's wit. Indeed, common sense often supposes that the human will is a citadel of irregularity, though never that it is disconnected with other things or that it is not even an irregular cause. Still, unless changes are regular there is no use in expecting, and common sense has its expectations ful- filled often enough to continue expecting with a good heart. The belief in these detailed expectations is just the world of common sense, and therefore it is very important to consider whether these expectations can or cannot be justified. Necessary connection is not a perceived meaning, and neither are the causal laws of science. Galileo had to drop the weights from the tower at Pisa in order to prove that the light one and the heavy one took the same time to fall. The tested v] THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF 101 uniformities of science do not lie on the surface and do not leap to the eyes like colour or shape. Per contra^ some of the acquired meanings of adult perception are of the same type as scientific generalisation, and even the prelogical generality which M. Levy-Bruhl attributes to savages is very often an instance of the same kind^ The savage belief that foreigners bring pestilence or bad luck is an obvious application of the Method of Difference, though it may be very hard upon some of the visitors. Savages believe that fire burns and that water quenches it for the same logical reasons that constrain civilised thinkers to believe that prices must rise when goods are scarce or that dominants and recessives will mix according to the proportions of MendeFs formulae. These common- sensical expectations, it is true, are less carefully sifted than the scientific ones, for common sense does not show any in- temperate zeal in searching for negative instances. But the principle is the same, although the applications of it may be hastier than they ought to be. Our contention is that perception always has a general precausal meaning, that it often has a specific precausal meaning, and that this precausal meaning is of the same type, logically speaking, as any causal generalisation in science. Hume was wrong, therefore, in his analysis of the observed facts; and he may also have been wrong in his inference that causal laws are only irrational habits of expecting. I suggest that he was wrong in maintaining that repeated experience discovers nothing new in the phenomena. We all know that familiar things are not the same to our perception as they were when we perceived them first, and this truism also holds of causal meanings. Adam may not have known what fire would do, but his children have a very shrewd idea. Fire has acquired a meaning for them, and it has acquired a specific causal meaning. Why therefore should we deny that the repetition has discovered something new ? It does not discover ^ Les Fonctions nientales dans les Socu'U's infirieures, passim. M. L^vy- Bruhl believes that this prelogical mind of the savage is different in kind from the reasoning mind of civilised people, but his grounds for drawing this distinction are extremely flimsy. 102 THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF [ch. a 'mysterious tie,' to be sure. Causes are not magic filaments, and anyone who looks for such filaments may expect to be disappointed. He need not expect to find more than causal connection since there is nothing more to find. Indeed, in the last analysis, we seem to have the same kind of evidence for believing in the causal properties of things as for believing in any of their attributes. If we perceive that this water is limpid, may we not also perceive that this water cleanses.? And if we cannot perceive that fire always burns, we have surely no right to say that all fire is ruddy just because some particular flame is. This meaning also has to be acquired. The ultimate difference in the case is that properties belong to things while causal connection is a relation between them. Related things are perceived, however, and their rela- tions are causal as well as spatial and temporal. If perception is evidence that a flame is ruddy it is also evidence that fire burns. Such, then, is the world we believe in. It has a logical structure, and a general order of space and time. There is always some connection in it, and frequently there is regular connection. That is all we discover at the plane of common experience, and there is no need to discredit this discovery so far as it goes, although there is utter need and unlimited opportunity for going further in the way of reflection and experiment. Some philosophers argue, it is true, that our ideas must really be more penetrating than common sense ones if the common sense point of view is itself possible. We could not have any idea of causality, they say, even a halting idea and irresolute, unless the law of universal causation were true to its marrow. That seems an overstatement. We could not have the idea of regular causes, I suppose, unless there were some approximately regular connections in past experience, but if vermilion is usually heavy and politicians usually de- ceitful that in itself would be a sufficient psychological basis for supposing necessary heaviness or necessary deceit: and if this approximate regularity were all the regularity that exists, our ideas, in all probability, would be very much what they v] THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF 103 Perhaps I should append some remarks on error. Those who maintain that we judge objectives and not facts, usually say that there is no room for error except upon this assumption^; and they point out, very justly, that error is the familiar spirit of true belief. Truth is not a mint with an image and super- scription that falsity lacks. It has not even a cachet which only the learned can descry. On the contrary, false propositions are believed as well as true ones; and they are the same, to our inspection, as the true ones. Most of us believe that James IV perished at Flodden, but many believed in the legend that he died of old age in a monastery, just as many believed in similar legends concerning the death of Barbarossa, or Gordon, or Kitchener. If judgment characterises the real James IV^, how can it characterise him falsely.'^ Yet there are certainly false objectives, and propositions, in themselves, do not guarantee their own truth or falsity. We have to suppose, therefore (according to this argument), that objectives are judged and not fact itself. If fact itself were judged there would be false facts; and that is nonsense. On the other hand there are false objectives, and it is reasonable to hold that true objectives correspond to fact while false ones do not. The trouble about explanations of error is always in the beginning. Once it is admitted that true judgments are in- distinguishable from false ones, there is just as much difficulty in explaining why false objectives should appear to correspond to reality as in explaining how reality can appear falsely. Either we know this correspondence directly in some cases or we do not. If we never know it, truth is mere supposal. If we know it, we must know both terras of the correspondence. We must compare the fact with the objective, and this com- parison is itself a judgment. If facts cannot be judged, therefore, the relation between facts and objectives cannot be judged; and, in that case, what becomes of the theory? It is impossible to explain error. We must simply accept this eternal possibility and try to be as careful and consistent ^ Cf. Kussell, 'On the Nature of Truth and Falsehood,' in his Philosophical Essays, 104 THE WORLD OF COMMON BELIEF [cii. v as we can. Apprehension always has the seed of misappre- hension in it, and judging the chance of misjudging. 'Ex- planations' of eiTor only stave it off for a little. We may, if we choose, try to explain the mistake about James IV by saying that all the elements in this false judgment may be true in some other judgment. James IV did not die in a monastery, but Charles V did. It is true, then, that there are monasteries, that some monarchs have died in them, and that James was a monarch. But James did not die another man's death, and his death in a monastery is not less of a sham because Charles really died in one. Our only comfort is that the eternal risk of error is not an everlasting presumption in its favour. CHAPTER VI PRINCIPLES Let somebody now demonstrate this Triangle described in the Matter to have its three angles equal to two right ones; Why yes, saith the Soul, this is true, and not only in this particular Triangle but in all plane Triangles that can possibly be described in the Mutter. And thus, you see, the Soul sings out the whole Song upon the first hint, as knowing it very well before. Henry More, An Antidote against Atheism. Philosophers may be divided into two classes, the class for whom facts are just facts and the class for whom facts are only suggestions. Those who belonged to the first class used to be called empiricists, and the second class, in its extreme form, includes Hugo of St Victor, for whom physical things were literally nothing but symbols of the Christian revelation, and Professor Macran, who says that "the first step in philosophy, though by no means the whole of philosophy, is idealism or the denial of the fact\" Now realists, I suppose, are as em- pirical as they dare, but however empirical one may be, it stands to demonstration that the most empirical thinking is logically bound to accept general truths as well as particular truths of fact. The proof is simple and Mr Russell has put it so simply that the best thing I can do is just to quote him: Of course it is clear that we have general propositions Wq have such propositions as 'All men are mortal' and 'Some men are Greeks.' But you have not only such propositions; you have also such ./rtc^* You cannot ever arrive at a general fact by inference from particular facts, however numerous. The old plan of complete induction, wliich used to occur in books, which was always supposed to be quite safe and easy as opposed to ordinary induction, that plan of complete induction, unless it is accompanied by at least one general proposition, will not yield you the result tliat you want. Suppose for example that you wish to prove in that way that ' All men are mortal,' you are supposed to proceed by complete induction, and say 'A is a man that is mortal,' 'B is a man 1 Hegel's Doctrine of Formal Logic, Introduction, p. 13. 106 PRINCIPLES [CH. that is mortal,' ' C is a man that is mortal,' and so on until you finish. You will not be able in that way, to arrive at the proposition 'AH men are mortal' unless you know when you have finished. That is to say that, in order to arrive by this road at the general proposition 'All men are mortal,' you must already have the general proposition 'All men are among those I have enumerated.' You can never arrive at a general proposition by inference from particular propositions alone. You will always have to have at least one general proposition in your premises^. AVe must accept principles, therefore, even in an empirical inventory of fact; and there is nothing unusual in this pro- cedure; for the world of common belief, as we have seen, is just an interpretation of perceived or remembered fact in the light of certain principles. Common sense, however, uses general principles without reflecting very deeply upon them. It is a world of axiomata media, not of 'Ap-^ai; and therefore, as a Hegelian would say, the reach of common sense is greater than its grasp. The destiny and the ineluctable privilege of philosophy, on the other hand, is to pursue these principles so far as thinking can, to reach categories (or first principles), and to be an untiring critic of these categories. I shall not attempt, of course, to deploy the categories in full array. No one but a fool or a demi-god would try to do so in a few pages. The time has passed since courtiers wanted thumb-nail sketches of ultimate metaphysics, since sovereigns requested the quintessence of truth before breakfast, or since Mme de Stael asked Fichte for a complete revelation of the Ich and the Anstoss in five minutes. Instead of treating metaphysics in this princely style, I shall be content if I can answer a few questions about principles, and especially if I can sketch in outline what kind of being a principle or a category has. To say that a principle holds of certain facts is to say that these facts are instances of the principle; and an instance is something which can be logically derived from its principle. Such principles, plainly, may themselves be instances of more fundamental principles or they may not. If they are, they are axiomata media in Bacon's language. They are dependent 1 The 3Ionist, vol. xxix. No. 2, pp. 198-199. vi] PRINCIPLES 107 principles, intermediate in a possible hierarchy. If they are not, they are logically primitive; that is to say, they are ^Kpyai^ or first principles, or categories. There is always considerable difficulty in knowing for certain whether a principle which seems to be primitive may not really be derivative. On the other hand, it is usually comparatively easy to have an inkling, at least, of the whereabouts of a first principle. Indeed, we know this whenever we find that we always need to make a certain kind of assumption in order to avoid a fallacy, however ingeniously we may twist and turn our arguments: for then it is certain that there really is some dogged and elusive principle which is always present although it is sometimes hidden and often disguised. The notion of value, for example, is logically primitive in any system of ethics. If you say that one thing is better than another be- cause it is more highly developed, you must first assume that development is necessarily improvement, i.e. that there is always greater value in a thing in proportion to the degree of its development. If, like St Thomas, you believe that a thing is good in the measure in which it is 'natural,' you require St Thomas's premiss: Qiiod omne agens agit proj)ter bonum^. If you argue that the good is what ought to be desired, you need a premiss to the effect that everything that is better than some other thing ought therefore to be desired before it, and conversely. Value or goodness in a word must always be included in the ultimate premises of ethics. Granting, then, that there are principles and first principles, we may proceed to consider certain questionsabout them, and we may begin by considering how they are discovered in experience. One of the favourite arguments of historical empiricism is that experience begins without principles and that nothing can be apprehended intellectually unless it has previously been sensed. Now it is true that the reflective recognition of principles comes late in psychological development, if, indeed, it ever 1 Summa Philosophica, liber iii. caput iii. St Thomas tries to derive this proposition from in. ii., Qitod omne agens agit propter finem, on the ground that ihe finis of anything is conveniens ei. But then he quietly begs the point at issue by saying 'Quod autem conveniens est alicui est illi bonum' (iii. ibid.). 108 PRINCIPLES [cH. comes; but principle and instance are correlative terms, and the use of principles comes very early indeed. We begin, in fact, with inarticulate principles and come to find out what they are, and, in the same sense, we begin with inarticulate instances and come to find out what they are. Prelogical generality has a double aspect affecting principle and instance alike, and it is not difficult to see that prelogical generality comes very early indeed. The child who calls all men 'daddy' classifies all men together, and at the same time does not fully appreciate the difference between his father and all other men. The savage who tries to express all his thoughts with a vocabulary of some four hundred words, generalises when he speaks, but the reason is that he ignores important differences in things or, at least, cannot express them. Those who speak indifferently of trees when they mean to refer to beeches, oaks and poplars, may never have noticed the differences carefully, and in that case they are not more reflective than botanists but less so, because they have not examined the facts. MilFs village matron who supposed that the medicine which had cured Lucy of whooping-cough must also cure Mary's chilblains', generalised; but she generalised very badly, because she had not examined the instances closely enough. The process of psychological development is the passage from prelogical generality to the logic of principles, and not from an explicit knowledge of particular facts to certain mysterious 'high priori "■ categories. Principles are discovered pari passu with their instances. When this is granted we are plunged at once into a far more perplexing and important set of problems. What are these general facts.'' What kind of being have principles or categories ? It seems to be evident that general facts do not exist; for whatever exists is particular, and principles are universal. When I learn on the authority of Euclid, for example, that 'Of all rectangles which have the same perimeter, the square has the greatest area,' my information may indeed apply to this rectangle and to this square, but the general fact itself 1 System of Logic, bk ii. chap. iii. § 3. vi] PRINCIPLES 109 concerns the rectangle and the square. It is applicable to par- ticular existing things but it does not concern them directly, because the existence of instances in reriim natura is no part of the proof or of the being of the principle. Universals are the stuff of general facts and universals do not exist. Red things exist, but not redness. In view of these reasons we are commonly told that universals do not exist but merely subsist ; that particular things like tables or churches or trades unions exist ; and that both have being. Being, therefore, is a general term which describes both existence and subsistence, and it describes the common relation which existing things and subsisting ones have to the mind. Being is always determinately so-and-so and confronts the mind in this determinate character ; it always constrains the mind ; it is always objective in the sense that this or that is true of it without appeal. In respect of knowledge, therefore, the status of existing things is very much the same as the status of things which merely subsist; indeed the only im- portant difference is that the former may be perceived or felt and that the latter cannot. There is the same kind of constraint and the same kind of confronting when I judge that sugar is sweet and when I judge that a'" x a" = «'"+". The general proposition and the existential one are discovered by the mind in the same sense, both propositions are true independently of our thinking, both are equally binding, equally indisputable, and equally incorrigible. This contention seems very just, but it plainly gives rise to a great many problems. Even if a dualism between existence and subsistence is the last word in this important matter, it is clear at least that the relation between these two divisions of being needs to be considered very closely indeed ; for some general facts hold of all existent fact. To take the most obvious point, existing things would not be thinkable at all unless logical principles at least were applicable to them. Existing things are what they are and are not other things, and the laws of identity and contradiction are the most general of all general facts. Let us consider, therefore, whether it is possible to avoid this dualism. 110 PRINCIPLES [CH. In the first place, an attempt may be made to dispense with universals altogether. The appearance of universality, of course, is beyond question, and we have already seen that there are general facts. None the less, attempts are frequently made to show that universals have no independent status, and that they are only parts of the world of existence. Most of the materialisms which delight tough-minded gentry are committed to this view, and most of the evolutionisms which attract ' advanced thinkers.'' This problem therefore may even have some general interest despite the austerity of its subject. Those who try to reduce universals to a variety of existent fact have to choose one or other of three roads. They may hold either that universals are only attenuated existents, or that thev are functions of certain privileged existents, or that they are a kind of organisation of existence. Let us con- sider these views in turn. The first view is the most usual. Universals, we are told, are mere abstractions and they are nothing else. In this character they are treated with contempt, or pity, or sorrow, according to the critic's mood. Your full-blooded critic is always scornful. He prefers a man to his wraith, lusty things to anaemic ones, Tom Jones to poor Tom's a-cold. Other critics are more merciful. These poor abstractions, they tell us, are as true as abstractions can be, and they are often very useful indeed; for although we always want a full draught of reality we have often to put up with the small beer of abstraction for our stomachs' sake. These full draughts of reality take too long to digest. There may be some comfort, therefore, in finding that universals are not abstractions at all, since the Abstraction Theory is utterly unable to account for them. According to this theory, we are supposed to pare away the distinctive peculiarities of things, and so to be left with their common elements. This elimination, however, to use Hegel's metaphor, is only peeling the coats off an onion ; and such a process can never generate a universal from a particular. The effect of it is only to get less onion and in the end no onion at all. Elimination takes something away, and leaves the rest. There is nothing else for it to do. And even if elimination in this VI] PRINCIPLES 111 sense sometimes seems to be possible, and sometimes seems to leave a common residue, it is abundantly evident that many universals have not the faintest semblance of being such a residue. It might be possible to arrive at redness by this pro- cess after eliminating the distinctive shades of red, but it would be interesting to know what colour is when the redness of the reds and the greenness of the greens have been abstracted from it. The residue might be a neutral grey, but neither redness nor greenness is a kind of grey. Again, the mutilated figure of a triangle which is neither right-angled, acute-angled or obtuse-angled, is plainly not triangular, and one would fain know what man is in the abstract when he is neither dusky nor fair, neither short nor tall, neither male nor female nor hermaphrodite, or how abstract man, thus denuded, could also contain all the males and females and hermaphrodites that ever were or will be. This theory begins by stripping a man of all that he possesses and then requires him to support the race. There is no road this way, therefore, and so we must try the next. Universality, according to this second theory, is a function of certain particulars, i.e. of words and images and other signs. These words and images are particular in them- selves. A word is just a noise and as particular as the boom of ordnance or the whistling of reeds. Its universality lies in its function, and this function is twofold. The particular things which have this function are labour-saving substitutes, and they lead the mind to the same terminus as the particulars for which they are substitutes. It saves me a great deal of trouble to know that a dog's dentition is so-and-so, for then I do not need to examine Tray's mouth or Fido's every time. And if I do not bring my eggs to market, the substitute signs in a letter about them may still find a purchaser. Now it is clear that words and other signs certainly have this function, since they may be used as substitutes for things ; and they save a great deal of trouble. On the other hand, it is equally clear that these signs save trouble precisely because they signify universals and because these universals therefore apply to their particular instances. Why is the sound 'red- ness' a substitute for the detailed examination of red things.'* 112 PRINCIPLES [CH. The sound, surely, is only the symbol for the quality and there- fore not identical with it; and if we need not examine red things when we are sure of their redness the reason is simply that we know in advance that 'redness' must hold of all red things. If Stevenson's style resembles Sterne's, and if Gibbon's style does not resemble Kipling's, there really is resemblance or difference in these cases, and consequently the universals 'resemblance' and 'difference' apply directly. These state- ments use words, but they also express general facts because the words themselves have a general meaning. It is possible, to be sure, to attend to the signs only, and to practise the manipulation of symbols for its own sake. We do this when we work out examples in school arithmetic or in the differential calculus, for then we concentrate our attention upon certain counters and manipulate them according to the rules. Even in that case, however, the counters have a meaning if we choose to consider it, and when words are used to express general facts this meaning, usually, is clearly before the mind. It is simply absurd to say that words are identical with general facts. Some words express particular facts, and other words express general facts, and the difference, in both cases, can be seen in the facts themselves. We may pass, then, to the third view according to which general facts are only the way in which existence organises itself. This contention may take very different forms, but its primary significance is clearly in terms of the mind, and this primary significance is far more important than any other. For it is clear that we organise our experience, and that, in a certain sense, we organise our world. Some enthusiastic realists, it is true, tell us that the laws of gasoline engines were just the same in the days of the ancient Athenians as they are no\v\ These laws, however, were certainly not con- tained in the organised experience of the ancient Athenians, and, in a way, had nothing whatever to do with the ancient world. 1 Montague, Studies in the History of Ideas, p. 236. Quoted by J. E. Kantor, ♦ Instrumental Transformism and the Unrealities of Realism,' Journ. of Philosophy , etc., vol. xvi. No. 17, pp. 452-453. vi] PRINCIPLES 113 Indeed, if things were our thoughts about them, and if any man's world were just the group of ideas which he has come to learn and recognise, we might say very truly that what our logic (or our causal interpretation) does for us is simply to put our worlds into order. Principles undoubtedly regulate our thoughts, and, through our thoughts, our actions. A logical mind is one which organises its experiences in a logical way; a scientific mind arranges its observations in a quantitative, causal way; and so on. These statements, however, are surely incomplete, just because the problem is taken too narrowly when it is restricted to the mind's arrangement of its ideas. It is true that I organise my ideas when I think, but it is not true that this organisation is the whole of the matter. When, for example, I organise my ideas about the physical world, my endeavour is to discover the characteristics of the physical world itself. I have to arrange my ideas consecutively in order to appreciate the logic in the facts, but this arrangement is not itself the discovery to which it is a means. Logical think- ing, indeed, is a habit of following the logical structure of things. This structure controls and determines the habit, and the habit, once formed, has a certain momentum in it. But that is a different matter. Even the most uncompromising idealist (and his pragmatic brother) would admit the justice of this criticism, if nothing could be taken into account except the individual mind, on the one hand, and the world itself on the other. This theory would entrap me within myself for ever if my logic were only my private habit of organising; and no one wants to be a solipsist. By general admission, therefore, the theory nmst be stated more broadly. According to the Absolutists, the Ex- perience which is organised is not really anyone's private experience, for private experience, as we call it, is only a part (and, in some ways, a spurious part) of Absolute Experience; and Cosmic Experience includes all private worlds as well as all finite selves. There is no opposition, therefore, between my ideas and the world ; and even my private habits, as I call them, have a new significance when I realise what they truly are. These private habits are tiny wavelets in the current of the 114 PRINCIPLES [cu. universe, and this current itself is the sweep of principles which, like the Ideas of Plato, are always supposed to be dynamic and productive, although they act, of course, in the majestic timeless fashion of Absolute Reality itself. The pragmatists, to be sure, cannot go all the way with the absolutists, but they have gone to school with them, and most of them, by substituting the life-process, or the Zeitgeist, or the intelligence of a great people, for the Absolute contrive to retain some of the momentum of the Platonic Ideas and yet to dress the world in workmen's overalls, or to credit it with the overwhelming vitality of a gendering bull. Both sets of theories, however, presuppose that truth is a kind of con- struction and that thinking somehow produces the world. When this assumption is granted, principles may very well be the self-organisation of thinking and nothing else whatever; but the falsity of the assumption is apparent of itself, and that is a bad augury for the conclusion of the argument. This theory, indeed, is in conflict with itself. It maintains that all principles and all thinking is just a kind of constructiveness, and yet professes to describe the facts of Experience (with a capital E). This description, however, is also a piece of thinking, and so, on the theory, would have to be a fresh piece of constructiveness and nothing more. That is nonsense. If the Absolute or the Zeitgeist or creative life organises experience, this experience surely is organised and, if so, the recognition of the orderly result is surely different from the production of it. Even an organising principle has its own character, and this character cannot be another organising principle. It, at least, is simply found, and there is no room for this naked discovery in terms of the constructive theory itself. The description of an orderly mental product, in a word, is logically in pari materia with any other piece of description, and so implies that general facts hold of particular ones in the same sense as they hold on any other theory. Nothing is gained by stating the problem in terms of mental organisation, and so we may leave the theory of dynamic impulses on one side. The important logical problem remains precisely where it was. The being of principles is guaranteed by the logic of any vi] PRINCIPLES 115 theory that has faced the facts; and our original problem concerning the kind of being which principles have is still with us. As we have seen, there seems to be a dualism between the mode of being which general facts have and the being of particular facts. For general facts merely subsist, and par- ticular facts (unless they are the universal instances of universal principles) also exist. On the other hand, a dualism of these modes of existence is a difficult theory to sustain, since all particular existences logically require some general principles to hold of them. Perhaps we may find some light in our perplexity if we consider the famous pact between universals and particulars according to which universals are in re and neither ante rem nor post rem^. Part of this contention is so manifestly true that it has only to be stated to be accepted. Particular things are determi- nately so-and-so; that is to say, they have universal characters; that is to say, universals are in them. Again, red things are not redness. The universal is onlym its instances, if it is in them at all. It is not identical with them, and it is not identical with any part of them, since any portion of a particular thing is just as particular as the particular thing itself. All particular things, therefore, logically require universals; and we should avoid any taint of dualism if we could also show that all uni- versals logically require particular instances which actually exist. This supposed requirement seems certainly to be fulfilled in the case of some universals. What kind of being could redness have if nothing were red, or what could sweetness be if there were no toothsome things .f* What would baldness, or sententiousness, or sleepiness be if they were not found in the world.'' Any adjective, indeed, has a universal corresponding to it, and some adjectives seem to be utterly and intrinsically 1 In the mediaeval controversy concerning the existence and potency of universals, the extreme realists like Bernard of Chartres or William of Cham- peaux held the ante rem theory, and nominalists like Eoscellinus held the post rem theory in a most uncompromising form. Universalia in re is the mediating position. See Mercier, Criteriologie ginirale (5th edition), pp. Z2Qsqq. 116 PRINCIPLES [CH. empirical. Universals of that kind, therefore, are surely in their particulars, and have no other conceivable mode of being. Indeed, there seems to be only one limitation to this account of the status of universals like redness or sententiousness. Logic is satisfied if there are some existing instances of these universals; it cannot deduce all the particular instances which happen to exist. Kiilpe says, for example, that there are about 150 discriminate colours ^ I do not know whether that is the right number, but I can be quite certain that the right number, whatever it may be, cannot be deduced from the universal 'colour.' Granting then that 'colour' logically requires to have some varieties in the world, it does not logically require to have any determinate number of varieties. The universal ' man ' may logically require mankind, but this circumstance does not relieve the census officials. This limitation is important, but there is a still more im- portant point to notice. Even if the universal 'sententiousness'* seems to be logically derived from existence, many universals do not. It seems perfectly clear, for example, that two and two would be equal to four if no couples existed in the world. Pure mathematics, to continue the argument, is logically in- dependent of its application to existence, and so is the pure logic on which pure mathematics is based. For logical prin- ciples are a pylori, and they apply to any thinkable being whether such a being could exist or not. Logic applies to all possible worlds as well as to the actual one, and if there are thinkable beings which could not exist in any possible world logic applies to these beings too. It is true, of course, that a pj-iori principles, like those of logic and number, do in fact apply to existence. All existing things have a logical structure. Eggs, again, can be counted. Therefore they have a number. Therefore they have all the characteristics and implications of numerable things. If pure geometry, as some maintain, can be completely arithmetised, its application to existence needs no argument. If not, its application to existence is not imperilled, for if the geometrical 1 Outlines of Psychology, p. 127. vi] PRINCIPLES 117 relation of betweenness, for example, is not a mere logical relation, it is extra-logical simply in so far as it is tinged with a meaning observed in empirical existence ; and this may per- haps be inferred from the fact that the betweenness of right and left is logically identical with the betweenness of before and after, although these, most manifestly, are not the same. These facts, therefore, do not affect the argument. It is possible to maintain, it is true, that the general facts of num- ber logically require some application to existence, although this application to existence is taken for granted throughout any demonstration in pure mathematics, and therefore does not enter into the demonstration itself. If this contention were sound it would meet the argument that two and two would plainly make four even if no couples and no quartettes existed; but it is impossible to see what grounds can be adduced in its favour; and it is clearly absurd to argue that pure logic or pure mathematics logically require existence just because they apply to existence. We must conclude, therefore, that some general facts are logically independent of existence although existence itself cannot be independent of general facts. In other words the ultimate difference between existence and subsistence re- mains. It must remain, I think; and yet there is an excuse, at least, for dallying with a very old conjecture. If subsistence cannot be shown to be only a species of existence, may not existence be only a species of subsistence? This contention has a long history behind it. Plato's account of the participation of the world of generation and corruption in the hierarchy of Forms is an illustration of it. It is assumed in Anselm's form of the Ontological Argument. It is seen in the Cartesian and Leib- nizian theory that sensations are only confused reasoning, and music, for example, a piece of unconscious arithmetic. Kant, it is true, by insisting on the ineradicable difference between sensation and understanding, led philosophy on to another track, and razed the Ontological Argument to the ground. But Kant himself strove to find a common font for these two jets, and HegePs Absolute Idealism claimed to have overcome 118 PRINCIPLES [CH. the dualism. In our own days Mr Holfs 'neutral monism^' has very obvious affinities to the older view. Existence, to be sure, seems to differ toto coelo from mere logical subsistence. A hundred dollars are very different from the mere idea of the same. Living men are not merely the logical properties of vitality. We shed no tears over death in the abstract, unless we are worthless sentimentalists. Only existing things can do any work, and no other things can, properly speaking, be idle. And yet it is possible to argue the question. In the first place there is a well-known argument of Hume\s, "To reflect on anything simply," he says, "and to reflect on it as existent are nothing different from each otherl"" And that, in a sense, is true. Existence, so to speak, happens to the things we contemplate. When we think of an angel and j udge that an angel exists, the angel has the same characteristics in both cases. The only difference is that we judge that it exists in the second case and not in the first. This difference, how- ever, is all-important. Indeed, it is so important that it refutes Hume's argument. Anyone can think of an angel stirring the waters, but not everyone is constrained to believe that a real angel really stirred them. The only way of constraining us to this belief would be to produce evidence that some trustworthy person had actually perceived the angel. In other words a special sort of evidence is required of all propositions which assert existence in rerum natura. Anyone can think of Gaunilo's perfect island^ but no one would believe that the perfect island existed unless some one had seen it; and if any mariner brought the news of it, we should think ourselves bound to test his story by sending an expedition to the spot. In the second place, it might be argued that existence is just ^ In The Concept of Consciousness. 2 Treatise, bk i. pt n. sect. vi. 2 Gaunilo, a monk contemporary with Anselm, disputed the Ontological Argument of Anselm's Monologium in his Liber pro insipiente. In terms of Anselm's reply, the ' insipiens' was unconvinced ' quia non magis consequitur hoc, quod dico, quo mains cogitari non possit, ex eo quia est in intellectu, esse et in re, quam perditam insulam certissime existere ex eo quia cum describitur verbis, audiens eam non ambigit in intellectu suo esse.' Liber apologeticus contra Gaunilonem. VI] PRINCIPLES 119 the kind of subsistence which spatial and temporal things have. Existence is the asserted being of spatial and temporal things, as opposed to their contemplated being. When we make judg- ments about things which are also perceptible, our assertions claim to be time of existence. Otherwise, they should not. This argument seems to be an ignoratio eletichi, because it is clearly no answer at all to the contention that existence is a different order of being from mere subsistence. The fact that perception (or introspection) is the only possible evidence for existence is common ground, and therefore does not tell in favour of this argument. Moreover, there is no contradiction in believing in the possibility of non-spatial and non-temporal existence, although we do not encounter such things in ordinary life. Orthodox theology, it is true, maintains that God is non-spatial and non-temporal, but these orthodox tenets may very well rest on a mistake. It is a mistake, for instance, to suppose that God's existence must be fleeting and perishable just because it is temporal; for God is not mocked if he endures while infinite time endureth. Again, it is a mistake to argue that changelessness is more noble than change, or that God, being changeless, is out of time. For change in itself is not a defect, and the unchanging is just as temporal as the changing. The everlasting hills are not less temporal than a poppy's petals. They only endure longer. And I cannot see that there is anything derogatory in spatial existence whether or not it is totum in toto ac totum in qualibet parte. But enough of this digression. We have no certain evidence for the existence of anything which is neither spatial nor temporal; and we have no right to deny the possibility of such existence. AVe conclude, therefore, that there are general facts as well as particular ones; that these general facts may apply to existence, but that their validity is logically independent of existence; and that the subsistence of general facts cannot be reduced to any characteristics of existence, nor conversely. If this dualism seems lamentable, there is no way of avoiding it. And there are compensations. The existent world, it is true, is a very wide parish, but even the immensities and the eternities are parochial in comparison with the discoveries of 120 PRINCIPLES [CH. the logical intellect. The freedom of thought is not a mean thing, and the wings of the logical intellect are clipped if logic is hampered by persistent appeals to sensory fact. Logic and pure mathematics are more certain than inferences based on sense, and they are not less worthy of being followed to a con- clusion. There is a genuine basis in reality for the distinction between what used to be called the verites Hernelles and the veritea dejait, between the Forms and Becoming, between the relations of ideas and the relations of matter of fact. The new discoveries concerning infinity, or the analysis of arithmetic and its logical basis which Mr Russell, stimulated by the researches of Cantor, Peano and Frege', has forced upon philosophy's attention, are not retrograde steps, although they come nearer to Leibniz or Plato than to Heg-el. On the con- trary they bring, as Mr Russell claims, 'a sense of power and a hope of progress ^^ It is highly important, too, that the status of general facts should be recognised to be what it is. Classical idealism in the grand marmer of Hegel sought to correct empiricism by giving the understanding its due as well as the senses, and then found a home for both of them in the higher synthesis of Absolute Spirit. Now it is true that the first step in philo- sophy is frankly to see that the senses cannot be the basis of all knowledge, but it is a serious mistake to conclude that what is not sensory must be the work of the mind. That is only another fetter due to this arbitrary restriction of thought to mere existence. Principles, it was argued, must be mental because existence itself is either sensory or mental, and because principles, plainly, are not sensory. We must strike off this fetter too. General facts, as we have seen, are just as objective as the facts of existence although they do not exist. They confront the mind and reveal themselves to it. They are in- dependent of our thinking and they are literally discoverable 1 Mr Eussell, who always makes a point of explaining his indebtedness to other authors, explains that he himself amved independently at Fi'ege's definition of number. See e.g. his Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, p. 11. 2 The External World, p. 30. vi] PRINCIPLES 121 as they are in themselves. For that reason they do not need a higher immediacy. They are not aimless migrations of wandering adjectives but ascertainable facts and relationships. And we should accept them as we find them. That is one side of the story. The other side shows that there is insight as well as prudence in rendering unto Caesar the things that are Caesar"'s. The general truths which depend upon sensory observation are only probable conjectures al- though they require a prioi'i principles. Scientific induction is not strict demonstration; and the point is fundamental. Even granting that causal interpretations have a basis in perception, it is plain that our inferences to particular causal laws are neither certain nor demonstrable. In an inductive proof we argue that any A must be a B because all observed A's have been B"'s. As it stands, this inference is a fallacy. The most we can infer is that such a connection is likely. And induction by means of the hypothetical method is also fallacious on the face of it. We are never in a position to prove that any given hypothesis is the only possible one, and therefore we commit the formal fallacy of affirming the con- sequent in all such inductions. Obviously, therefore, we must conclude that inductive con- clusions are matters of probability at the best. Probability, however, is a branch of logic. It is the logic of relevant but inconclusive evidence, and its axioms and assumptions are a priori. It follows therefore that induction requires a priori principles, and it is plainly not completely a priori since the evidence for it is also, in part, the observation of certain particular instances. But there is a further difference still, since, as Mr Broad has shown recently^, there is no known principle of mere probability which justifies our belief in scientific inductions. For a full proof of this conclusion I must refer the reader to Mr Broad's article, but I can sketch some of the main points here. If I infer that the atomic weight of nickel is 58*68 the quantity of nickel that has been weighed is wholly insignificant in comparison with the quantity of nickel in the universe, 1 Mind, N.S. vol. xxvn, No. 108, pp. dS% sqq. 122 PRINCIPLES [en. Now the probability in this case is measured by the fraction ^ where m is the number of observed cases and n the number of cases in the universe. This probability, therefore, is too slight to be worth believing. It is true that the proba- bility of the next case of nickel having the atomic weight 58'68 is ~ , but this formula will not help us very much. In the first place we always infer the general law, and not merely the probability of the next case; and in the second place the formula for the next case is far too feeble for the inference we want to make. If an inexperienced student with a poor balance found the weight to be 61 "23 four times running, then the odds would be five to one that the weight in the next case would also be 61*23. Such a principle, therefore, is not sufficient for our purposes. No one would put his trust in induction unless he supposed that he had obtained enough relevant evidence to justify assertions about the atomic weight of nickel. Induction, in a word, is worthless without certain special assumptions about nature itself. We always suppose, in fact, that the weight of nickel is constant when no one is weighing it, and that fair samples of the element can be obtained so that the experimental results in a few instances are evidence for any instance. We assume, in other words, that there are parallel cases, and that we can recognise the species of things if we take the trouble to examine them carefully. Without these assumptions induction would not yield any likelihood worth considering, and with them it is only probable; for we all admit that the increase in the number of instances makes the evidence better, and our admission would be meaningless if the conclusion stood to demonstration. This difference in the character of inductive evidence as compared with pure logic, is interesting in many regards, and it is particularly important in view of certain metaphvsical theories. The ideal of all rationalism is to show that every feature of the realm of being can be shown to be a consequence of a few comparatively simple principles, and we may conclude vi] PRINCIPLES 123 this chapter by considering, very briefly, whether this ideal is well founded. As we have seen, the a priori laws of logic, number and the like, cannot be the principle of the empirical connectedness of existence, although they hold of all existence. We have to observe nature in order to discover her laws, and we have to argue from these observations inductively and at our peril. On the other hand, it is at least possible that nature behaves in conformity with a comparatively small number of relatively simple principles, and that these may be discovered. We saw in an earlier chapter that the continuity and connectedness of nature is given to the mind in perception in a fragmentary but not in a negligible fashion. The inductive assumptions that there are parallel cases and that fair sampling is possible are extensions of this perceived meaning — too sweeping, indeed, to be indisputable consequences from it, but, on the whole, legitimate and even moderate. Is it not possible, then, to include the interpretation of perceived meanings together with the foundations of inductive inference concerning nature in some general Law of Analogy or Principle of Sufficient Reason .P Even if this principle is not wholly certain, it is supported by very many facts and contradicted by none. And it is, perhaps, the metaphysical ground of that law of parsi- mony to which, as many consider, all sound thinking conforms. The Law of Parsimony — the Friistrajit per plura quodjieri potest per pauciora of Occam''s razor — is manifestly just and highly important. In logic it means that 'analysis is to be carried as far as possible^'; in physical science it means that 'as hypothesis increases necessity diminishes^'' Again it is a principle of elegance. The fewer the assumptions the neater the proof. It is an appeal for economy, too, and sumptuary edicts have excellent intentions, although luxury is a hard thing to define and an impossible thing to curb. On the other hand the limitations of a finite intellect compel us to be sparing in our assumptions if we hope to understand anything of im- portance; the power of the intellect is simply its grasp of a 1 P. E. B. Jourdain, The Monist, vol. xxix. No. 3, p. 451. 2 Whitehead, The Organisation of Thought, p. 176. 124 PRINCIPLES [ch. vi multitude of details in a single principle, and no intellect can grasp very many principles in this thorough fashion. Those who count knowledge precious may therefore be expected to believe that nature responds to a principle of this kind. Natura Jiorret superjluum. The structure of reality is simple and so our thinking should be simple too. This final step seems more seductive than solid. True, we cannot understand things unless we can bring them under a comparatively simple principle, and we are bound to believe that there are principles, and that explanations can be given in terms of them. It does not follow, however, that the principles which are most important for our understanding of things are also most important in the order of nature, still less that nature as a whole is peculiarly adapted to our limitations. If maxim can be met with maxim, we might follow Kant by opposing Entium varietates no?i temere sunt minuendae to Occam"'s razor*. The complexity of the universe is always with us and we have no right to set bounds to it. We may hazard the guess that logic cannot be less fundamental in the world than in those selected portions of reality which we are capable of apprehending; and we should not go further than that. ^ In the Appendix to the Transcendental Dialectic. CHAPTER VII VALUES The world that earth-born man, By evil undismay'd, Out of the breath of God Hath for his heaven made. Where all his dreams soe'er Of holy things and fair In splendour are upgrown, VVTiich through the toilsome years Martyrs and faithful seers And poets with holy tears Of hope have sown. Robert Bridges. The value of things, I think, does not raise any special prob- lems in the theory of knowledge. Value is a quality which things may have or may not have, and it can be recognised by the mind like any other quality. On the other hand, the problems of value are important and distinctive enough to repay separate discussion. According to many philosophers, value and existence are somehow one, and this principle, if it were true, would plainly have most important metaphysical consequences. Again, even apart from the perplexities of that majestic theme, there are many humbler difficulties in the conception of value, and some of these difficulties, if they were insurmountable, would have very important results ; for they would show either that there is no such thing as value, or else that values cannot be known. And if knowledge is impotent concerning all questions of worth there might perhaps be neither use nor worth in considering it. The orthodox tradition in philosophy classifies values into truth, beauty and goodness, and then sets about to establish a legislative and executive union of logic, aesthetics and ethics. This procedure, I think, is mistaken. It omits certain im- portant values from the list (happiness, for example), and it includes truth which is not, properly speaking, a value at all. 126 VALUES [CH. True knowledge is a value, and perhaps the highest of all values, but truth itself means only that the facts are so, and it is hard to see how that can fortify anyone's soul. There may be value and importance in krwwing that Popocatepetl is higher than Shooter's Hill, but this true proposition itself is only a state of affairs. It is otherwise with beauty and goodness, for these are valuable in themselves, whether or not anyone appreciates the fact. The justice of Aristides was independent of the suffrages of the Athenians, and if the man was just he was therefore worthy. In the same way, beauty need not wait upon the fashion. A romantic revival may be needed to reveal the stateli- ness of gothic cathedrals or the serene splendour of Alpine summits, but this beauty, and the worth of it, belonged to the Alps and the sanctuaries all the time. These statements, I am well aware, require a defence, and I hope to give one (with certain reservations concerning beauty). The most formidable lion in my path is the common and most pertinacious attempt to prove the subjectivity of all values. Aesthetics gives the strongest case for this argument, but the subjectivists also attempt to annex the whole province of morals. We must therefore consider these topics in their order. Mr Saintsbury, defending Castelvetro's doctrine that delight is the sole end of poetry, writes as follows: — "That Burns administers, and has a right to administer, one delight to one class of mind, Shelley another to another: that Beranger is not to be denied the wine of poetry because his vintage is not the vintage of Hugo : that Longfellow, and Cowper, and George Herbert are not to be sneered at because their delight is the delight of cheering but not of intoxication : that Keble is not intrinsically the less a poet because he is not Beddoes, or Charles Wesley because he is not Charles Baudelaire — or vice versa in all the cases — these are propositions which not every critic — which perhaps not very many critics — will admit even in the abstract, and which in practice almost every critic falsifies and renounces at some time or other\" 1 History of Criticism, vol. ii. p. 87. vii] VALUES 127 The reason for this inconsistency among the doctors is not far to seek. Common sense and the King's English renounce subjectivism, and so the critics are bound to contradict them- selves verbally unless they are intolerably prolix, and are cer- tain to contradict themselves really whenever they relapse into common ways of thinking through the weakness of their critical flesh. And there may be another reason. Perhaps the critics cannot keep faithfully to their own standards, because these standards are false, and because the truth of the opposite catches them unawares whenever they try to state their posi- tion fully. Be that as it may, there is a strong personal obstacle, at all events, in the way of complete subjectivism among the critics. If they were consistent subjectivists, none of them could be right and none of them could be wrong. This consequence would be fatal to their pretensions ; and perhaps their pretensions, in this instance, are better than their creed. Delight, I take it, is simply a feeling, and feelings are neither right nor wrong. It is illogical, therefore, to dispute about tastes, if tastes are only feelings; and those critics who follow the subjectivist theory have only the right to say that they like Baudelaire or Mrs Aphra Behn with some special and peculiar relish ; and either that they are not alone in their taste or that they are proud to be alone. The critics, to be sure, may explain the way in which this or that offends them, and point out what they like best, just as Meredith complained of smug Victorianism in the Idylls of the King, or as Francis Jeffrey drove about Edinburgh declaring there had been 'nothing as good as Nell since Cordelia^' Delight in detail, however, does not differ in principle from delight in the whole, and there is as much logic in Stevenson's blunt dislike of M. Anatole France as in Meredith's contrast between the * gentleman Boccaccio' and the 'Sir Pandarus public' which liked 'the Euphuist's tongue, the Exquisite's leg, the Curate's moral sentiments, the British matron and her daughter's purity of tone' in The Holy Grail-. It is all one to delight in 1 On the authority of Forster's Life of Dickens, vol. i. p. 226. 2 The Letters of George Meredith, vol. i. pp. 197-198. 128 VALUES [cH. a jewel five words long and to delight in a quarto from frontis- piece to colophon. The only difference is that the latter delight needs more space. Anthologies may give delight like the flowers in a crystal vase, but the flowers are as sweet in the garden, and they are better in the field. Excellence should not be rent into patches. The author has to struggle for the mot rat/onnant, but his travail should be the reader's ease. Very few of the great critics, I fancy, hold that delight is mere liking without any qualitative differences in it. Mr Saintsbury plainly does not; and, indeed, he adds an aggrieved and petulant footnote to the statement quoted above. " It is perhaps well," he says, " to meet a possible though surely not probable objection. 'Do you deny ranks in poetry.''' Cer- tainly not, but only the propriety of excluding ranks which do not seem, to the censor, of the highest^" Mr Saintsbury's view is that there are different kinds of delight, and different ranks in it, and our problem is whether his theory is sufficient, and what is the logic of it. Meanwhile we must certainly admit that there are, in fact, different kinds of delight. From the aesthetic point of view pushpin is not as good as poetry when the quantity of pleasure is equal ; and Yvetot is not as good as Constantinople. The delight in one of Vermeeren's paintings is not the delight in Bach, and the gourmefs delight in plovers' eggs is not comparable to our delight in a Delia Robbia. Each of the arts, indeed, has its appropriate delight, and each division within each art. The delight in Theocritus differs from the delight in Lucretius, and the delight in Donne is other than the delight in Heine. Indeed, there is no good reason for stopping at this point. There are many strings in Erato's lyre, and each has its appropriate charm. Melpomene has many masks, and each mask has its own delight. The greatest poets give the greatest range of delights, and critics excel when they respond to them all. These facts, however, do not prove that beauty is only a feeling of delight ; and that is the subjectivist's case. Let us ask, therefore, whether he can support his position by argument. 1 History of Criticism, vol. ii. p. 87 n. vii] VALUES 129 It is commonly argued that beauty is plainly a thing of the mind and therefore subjective. The reply to this argu- ment is that the fact is doubtful and the inference false. There is beauty, I take it, in sky and cloud and sea, in lilies and in sunsets, in the glow of bracken in autumn and in the enticing greenness of a leafy spring. Nature, indeed, is infinitely beautiful, and she seems to wear her beauty as she wears colour or sound. Why then should her beauty belong to us rather than to her ? And why should the beauty of art need a different explanation ? A melody can be heard, and temples, paintings, and statues can surely be seen. If every- thing we perceive is mental, then beauty, of course, is mental too. But where is the necessity otherwise ? Literary art, it is true, may seem of a different order, but this appearance may be a deceit after all. The cadence of words is just a kind of music, and the magnificence of numbers can be heard. It is idle to argue that this cadence and this magnificence are the vestures of thoughts and that thoughts are mental ; for thoughts, to be sure, are mental, but literature does not pre- sent us with thoughts. It presents us with things that we think about. Anyone, I think, who takes the trouble to con- sider what precisely is before his mind when he reads a page of Tom Sawyer or of Blake's Songs of Experience finds the problem very puzzling. Images are blended with words, and these in their turn with present questionings. But whatever the pattern of the fact may be, fact of some kind is certainly before the mind. The printed page is a turnstile which clicks us into things. We are confronted with fact when we read, and this fact is not our thoughts about it. It is difficult to see, therefore, why so many philosophers and critics hesitate to ascribe beauty to things in the same sense as they ascribe colour or shape, but even the most deter- mined realists incline towards compromise at this point and admit that the status of the ' tertiary qualities "' is somewhat dubious. Probably they are swayed by several considerations, but we may consider two at this stage of our argument. The first is the intimate connection between beauty and delight, and the second is the extent to which personal meanings L. 9 130 VALUES [CH. and personal associations are involved in the appreciation of beauty. The first consideration is not convincing. Feeling is always blended with our thinking. A man has his feelings even when he thinks of the multiplication table, but that does not prove that the multiplication table is part of his mind. Certainly, it is far easier to distinguish the feeling from the multiplication table than to distinguish the delight in poetry from the beauty of it. That is no proof of identity, however; and in certain palpable instances the judgment of beauty seems to differ very notably from any feeling of pleasure. Indifferent art is not always unpalatable. There are many who prefer Mr Standfast to Colonel Jack, although they know perfectly well that Colonel Jack is far the better. If pleasure were the sole criterion, this discrimination would be out of the question, and it is difficult to see how the discrimination can be due to a qualitatively different feeling of delight in the two cases; for both Defoe's story and Mr Buchan's are just vigorous pieces of narrative. Indeed, the fact seems to be, quite plainly, that we judge Defoe's work to be the better, but that we may find more interest in Mr Standfast for the time being. The second circumstance is equally unconvincing. True, the beauty of literature, for example, is permeated with associa- tions. Without these, wit and simile, irony and allusion would- be utterly wasted, and these things are the attic salt of good prose and of good verse. Pathos and anti-climax, again, or the sermo pedester in place of superbia canji'momm, construct ionis elatio and excellentia vocabulorum, offend us precisely because of the discord which their inevitable associates bring. In the same way, the expressiveness of chiselled stone or shining canvas is im- personal only in the sense that it is catholic. The eye of the beholder must bring experience with it in order to appreciate the charm and the meaning of these things. It is impossible, however, to extract a convincing argument from this circum- stance. All our perception has an acquired meaning, and even the allusiveness of literature is not on a different plane from the meaning of perception or judgment. It is subtler, more recon- dite, more palpably acquired, but the essence of it is the same. vii] VALUES 131 It would be most illogical to argue that nothing can be objective if it is acquired and not primitive, but even this argument is not open to the subjectivists. For by what right do they deny that a sense of beauty really is primitive ? The noble savage, it is true, is so often a stupid fiction that it is useless to speculate about him, and the zeal of missionaries to discover whether there are savages without a code of morals or a belief in unterrestrial potentates, has left us very sparse data for guessing how far the untutored races appreciate the beauties of nature. On the other hand, art is nearly as old as man. It is a very long time since the first cave was rudely adorned, since barbaric taste thrilled with the joy of glittering things, since song and dance appealed to men, and since sagas were told over crepuscular embers. We may safely conjecture, then, that the sun-god was seen in his beauty as soon as he was seen at all, and that Neanderthal man had something of the artist in him when he rejoiced in the spring. Men have fancied that molluscs sing praises to God. It is easier to fancy that they respond to beauty. Peter Bell is not the only type of peasant, and yellow primroses are only yellow to many who are not peasants. Have we not heard, indeed, of a great philosopher who likened the stars to a rash ? Let us pass, then, to the most familiar argument on this topic. Beauty, we are told, must be subjective because it varies from man to man. Fire burns here and in Persia, but the standards of good taste vary with time and climate and training. There is a pleasant tale of certain anthropologists who visited the Malay Archipelago, and took records of the native music. They found a sort of rhythm in the head- drummer's measures, but no music ; and they rejoiced when an understudy took his place, for then they heard something like music. The natives thought otherwise, however, and were as disappointed as a music-hall audience when a popular comedian falls sick. Who can arbitrate, then, between the taste of the anthropologists and the taste of the natives ? And the same thing holds universally. The precious ones who cannot admire Raphael differ from the great public, but which of them is right ? And if anyone prefers I^andseer to Cezanne why must 132 VALUES [CH. he be wrong ? There are different fashions in these affairs, and what else is there ? These contrasts, I think, are more striking than just. There are great differences, to be sure, between the age of Solomon and the age of Queen Anne in all matters of sensibility, and between Constantine''s taste and the demon-trappings of some patron of ju-ju. Such contrasts, however, need not be about the same things. Perception depends so much upon what we have learned to look for, that it is not surprising if primitive taste differs from civilised. A savage does not perceive the same thing as a modern European, and if the pair could pass an eye round, like the Graiae, each might perceive the same beauty. Again, the contrast is not so absolute as it seems. The Indian''s beads and wampum have a certain beauty; and we can understand his delight and even share it if we choose. Beauty need not be denied just because it does not seem the best, and if the golden splendour of Solomon''s temple with its palm-trees and cherubim and open flowers was too ostentatious, and the brazen pillars of his house with their chapiters of brass and their two hundred pomegranates were too sumptuous for modern taste, the temple and the palace were magnificent all the same, and would have seemed so to anyone. Indeed, it is very easy to exaggerate this clash in the standards of beauty. The return to old standards is as patent a fact as the alternation of new ones. Greek beauty has been the perpetual privilege of all beholders, though sometimes a Winckelmann was needed to point it out. Great art has a catholic and an abiding appeal. This argument, to be sure, is easily overstated, but there is enough of truth in it to show that the clash of standards is not the whole truth. This clash of standards, moreover, only proves that judgments of beauty are often wrong, and that it is difficult to be certain when any of them is right. True, the difference between maintaining that there is beauty al- though no one can ever know when he has found it, and that there is no such thing as beauty, is so slender that it is not worth quarrelling over; but the difference is crucial if (as seems to be the fact) taste is not wholly wayward, if its development vii] VALUES 133 is intelligible, if its early stages are not superseded utterly, and if the great epochs of beauty in art can almost always be ap- preciated by later ages, although each age must be doubtful of its own art until time has taken its measure. Beauty, in fact, is something that is judged, not something that is merely felt. None of the arguments of the subjectivists is able to impugn this fact, and our judgments of beauty are either right or wrong simply because judgment itself must be either true or false. Indeed, the doctrine of ranks in beauty already admits this conclusion by implication. The comparative must have the same logic as the positive, \\Tiat- ever is placed in a higher rank must be placed there because it really is better ; and if it is better it must either be good or bad in itself. At the same time it is possible to argue that nothing is beautiful save our delight itself, and that we call things beautiful just because they cause beautiful delights. Our judgments of beauty, on this view, would refer to our feelings, and not to things. Our delights really are valuable, some delights are really better than others ; and that is the sum of the matter. We must consider this theory, therefore, for something more than completeness' sake. Is it true in fact that there is no beauty in comeliness or majesty save only the feeling of delight.'' It is plain, of course, that we do not usually say this even if we mean it, for we say that Fiesole, or Leonardo's Last Supper or Beethoven's Ninth Symphuny is beautiful without further ado. Language, how- ever, has a short way of dealing with intricate matters, and its crude methods should not, perhaps, affect our conclusions. The problem is not about what we say but about what, on reflection, we really mean. The most extreme contention on the opposite side would be that the Ninth Symphony would be beautiful if no one had ever heard it, and that the frozen seas would still glisten with loveliness after all life has departed from the earth. This view, I think, is not nonsense, and it is, of course, extremely simple, but most philosophers recoil from it for better reasons than mere repugnance. This contention, they think, plainly 134 VALUES [cH. goes beyond the evidence ; for beauty, in our experience, is never appreciated without delight, and therefore it is illegiti- mate to argue that beauty would still be beauty in the absence of any possible delight. The fact of inseparability, to be sure, would not prove very much in itself, for many things are inseparable which are plainly distinct, but when the companionship, as in this instance, is peculiarly close and peculiarly relevant the inseparability may mean a gi'eat deal. The fact is not simply that we find charm wherever we find beauty, just as we find scales wherever we find fish. It is easy enough to distinguish between the fish and their scales, but the union between beauty and delight seems to be as close as the union between a man's enjoyment and the fruition of his wishes. On the other hand the delight in beauty is a very complex thing, and it is far richer than mere feeling. If the sense of beauty must be suffused with delight, this delight, in its turn, presupposes a very subtle harmony of the mind as a whole. The delight needs vision and insight and under- standing. It is not merely superadded to these, but it blends with them; and they in turn blend with it. Words like 'charm' or 'delight,' to be brief, signify, not mere feeling, but an intricate sentiment of the soul in which feeling, how- ever predominant, does not extinguish all else. If our minds are charged with feeling whenever we appreciate beautiful things, our feelings are also enlightened by our knowledge of the significance of these things. Beautiful things, therefore, are much more than occasions of beautiful feelings, and if beauty is not a predicate of non-mental things simplic'iter, it cannot hold of anything less than the whole complex ' thing-that-is- felt-with-delight.' A perceiving and comprehending delight is no mere feeling. We may conclude, then, that delight enters into the recognition of all beauty, but that beauty is not merely de- light, even if we have no right to maintain that things can be beautiful apart from a mind. They might be, but we cannot tell. On the other hand, things may certainly be beautiful when they bring delight, and the beauty (and there- vii] VALUES 135 fore the value) of these delightful things is a predicate of them just as certainly as their lustre is a predicate of my lady's diamonds. The subjectivists can unmask the same batteries against moral standards as against aesthetic ones. Shaftesbury, for example, spoke of a taste or relish for virtue^ although he recoiled from any determined logical pursuit of his own theory. Most people who do not make a business of reflecting on these matters are content to believe that conscience is only a feeling, and that wicked imaginings ought to be destroyed simply because they are felt to be defiling. For conscience is an oracle, and oracles love the twilight. Again, the variations of ethical standards are as striking as the variations in the fashions of beauty. Those puberty rites that seem so foul to us are the first obligation in Central Australia. We have no moral copybooks for the ethics of a strike, and war convulses the duties of the moral world as thoroughly as any cataclysm convulses the face of nature. Indeed, nothing is easier than the dialectic of naturalism which sets about to prove that any commandment in morals is a mere convention like the rule of the road, and that the abiding thing in conduct is just life and its instincts. 'Thou shalt not steaP — but what is robbery ? If a man's ancestors have been allowed to keep a piece of land, why should the community pay tribute for it.^* And what is wrong in promiscuity of ownership except custom, con- venience and strong prejudice ? What are the rights and wrongs of polygamy, and where is the pretence of inter- national morality when there is no international police ? The whole thing is an affair of sentiment and convenience (is it not ?), and moral standards, like all religions in Gibbon's epi- gram, are equally true in the eyes of the populace, equally useful in the eyes of the magistrate, and equally false in the eyes of the philosopher. Hunger and lust, ambition and comradeship, love of ease and joy of battle are the only enduring forces in a human polity. Even if these arguments were sound, however, they would not prove their conclusion unless they could explain the fact 1 'An Inquiry concerning Virtue, or Merit,' Characterititickn, vol. ii. 136 VALUES [CH. of moral obligation ; and they cannot do that. Moral obli- gation is neither habit nor fear, neither custom nor obedience, neither fashion nor deference, and it is not the obscure feeling of these. For what do we mean when we say that we ought to do certain things, and ought not to do certain other things ? Clearly we do not mean that we are forced to do the one and forced not to do the other. Our zeal for righteousness may perhaps constrain us but nothing else need ; and righteous- ness itself includes obligation. Neither the enactments of our rulers with their sanctions in the police court, nor the com- mands of God with the carnal and spiritual penalties which the lawyerly minds of priests have devised, are moral obliga- tion itself. And obligation is neither custom nor habit. There are customary obligations, it is true; and just men, I suppose, have formed the habit of walking uprightly; but there are obligations to non-conformity too, and these are felt and acted on. The Hobbists among our moralists, therefore, have reached a most desperate pass. They have to maintain, by hook or by crook, that obligation is really the constraint of fear although it does not seem so to us. Obligation, they say, is an obscure sort of fear, which we take for an ultimate principle, and it would vanish if we knew our own emotions thoroughly. A theory which leads to such a morass as this should be avoided at all costs, and yet Hobbes's attempt to base obligation on fear\ was better argued and more plausible in itself than most of the modern attempts to base it on tribal ritual or a nation's habits. What, then, is obligation ? It is tempting to suppose that obligation is an ultimate of ultimates, an autonomous imperative of which it is enough to say that he who cannot discern it of itself need not borrow a lantern elsewhere. Moral obligations, in a word, like ^ Leviathan, pt ii. chap. xvn. : "The Lawes of Nature. ..of themselves, without the terrour of some Power, to cause them to be observed, are contrary to our naturall Passions.... And Covenants, without the Sword, are but Words, and of no strength to secure a man at all. Therefore, notwithstanding the Lawes of Nature... if there be no Power erected... every man will, and may law- fully rely on his own strength and art, for caution against all other men." vii] VALUES 137 Luther's Ich kann nicht anders, or the modem Englishman's and the ancient Persian's ^ pride in keeping his word, plainly are imperatives which take precedence over all else. On the other hand, there are reasons for any imperative, gi'anting that moral obligation is rightfully lord over the will. The good does not wait upon the ought, and the ought is en- lightened by the good. For the will always seeks an end, and it is contrary to all sound reasoning to suppose that the imperative justifies the end. On the contrary, the end justifies the imperative. The reason for obligation, then, lies in the value of the end. It is always legitimate to ask why anyone ought to do this or that, and always sufficient to answer (if we can) that he ought to do it because it is the best thing to do. The analysis of obligation, therefore, shows, on the one hand, that obligation cannot be resolved into a mere feeling or sentiment, and, on the other hand, that there are reasons for obligation based upon judgments of value. Morality stands or falls, therefore, with the validity of judgments of value; and if these are not true, the grounds of right action cease to hold. We have already considered most of these indict- ments in principle, but the subject is so important that it is better to consider them again from the point of view of moral theory. Those who resolve a judgment of beauty into a species of appreciative feeling commonly maintain that moral judg- ments are also a kind of appreciative feeling. Virtue pleases us in a certain Avay, and vice displeases us in its appropriate emotional fashion. Inequality or injustice offends us some- times and arouses our resentment. At other times it pleases us, for our sympathies may be with the princes, or the pluto- crats, or the other superiors which God or our own indolence have set above us. This analysis, however, palpably fails to describe what we mean by injustice or any other moral evil. We know very well that A has no moral right to prefer him- self to B unless A's value is really greater than B's, and we know that the justice or injustice of princes is not an affair 1 Cf. Herodotus, History, i, 138. 138 . VALUES [CH. of sympathy or resentment. Indeed, those who take this line of argument speedily give the case away by the modifications which they are compelled to make. Sympathy, they admit, is not moral in itself. What is moral is sympathy with a 'flavour of generality ^^ Resentment is not moral ; it has to be the resentment of Adam Smith's ' impartial spectator' ; it has to be watered with sympathy and enlightened knowledge. These are desperate expedients, for they are intended to explain why moral judgments claim to be binding on all and to hold irre- spective of persons, although sympathy and resentment make no such claims. What these theories really do is to give an analysis of moral feelings which is as nearly accurate as may be, granting the false assumptions that there are no moral judgments and that moral judgments have no connection with moral feelings. These moral sentiments certainly exist and we should be grateful to Hutcheson, Hume and Westermarck for their psychological analyses of them ; but they are not the whole of moral theory. Conscience is not merely the abhorrence of foul deeds, although foul deeds are abhorrent ; and the head con- demns Heliogabalus or Alexander Borgia, granting that the heart loathes them too. These sentiments, indeed, like any other sentiments, are allied to judgments, and, what is more, are allied to judgments of value as well as to judgments of fact. Righteous anger, for example, is enlightened by, and derived from, the discovery of unrighteousness. Sentiments are never blind, and reason is neither quite cold nor quite aloof, although all the subjectivists in morals from Hume- to Mr Bertrand Russell' have supposed so. These writers 1 Westermarck, The Origin and Development of the Moral Ideas, vol. i. pp. 104 sqq. ■■* Treatise, bk n. pt ni. sect. iii. : " Eeason alone can never be a motive to any action of the will," "Eeason is and ought only to be the slave of the passions, and can never pretend to any other office than to serve and obey them "; and the whole section. •* Principles of Social Reconstruction, p. 12: "Only passion can control passion, and only a contrary impulse or desire can check impulse. Eeason, as it is preached by traditional moralists, is too negative, too little livmg, to make a good life. ...All human activity springs from two sources: impulse and desire." vii] VALUES 139 maintain that morality must be an affair of feeling or impulse just because moral ideas stir our emotions and lead to action. They admit, to be sure, that the head plays some part in action however cold it may be, for knowledge of the means to an end clearly guides our actions, and blind feelings are as useless in practical affairs as they are in a boxing-bout; but they arbitrarily assume, none the less, that knowledge of the values of the ends of action is impotent and aloof. Why ? The only possible proof of this contention would be a demon- stration that there is no such knowledge ; and this proof has never been given. We may pass, then, to other arguments. If beauty is sometimes supposed to be subjective because of its close con- nection with personality, one would suppose that this argument holds a fortiori of morals. For persons are the bearers of morality, and so far as we know, the only bearers of it. God and the angels are moral beings if, and only if, they are persons ; and theologians, recognising the difference between God's per- sonality and ours, feel bound to hold that God is good per alium modum eminentiorem^. Again, if animals have rights (as most of us believe in a way) they must also have duties, but moral obligations among the animals are so primitive and so rudimentary that they are rightly excluded from serious consideration in ethical theories. Persons, then (together with their character, actions, and capacities), are the final subjects of moral obligation, and, as all Kantians know, the subjects of this law are also the law- givers. These lawgivers, indeed, must not only be conscious but must have foresight, choice of alternatives, some know- ledge of means, some knowledge of values and some recogni- tion of the independent worth of other subjects in the king- dom of ends. These requisites are very stringent and they exclude most of the animals and all of the plants, to say nothing of ions and engines. Those, indeed, who maintain 1 Smnma Contra Gent. , lib. i. caput xxx. : " Quia enim omnem perfectionem creaturae est in Deo invenire, sed per alium modum eminentiorem quaecum- que nomina absolute perfectionem absque defectu designant, de Deo predi- cantur et aliis rebus: sicut est bonitas, sapientia," etc. 140 VALUES [CH. that there arc no morals without Sittlichkeit deny morality to anyone who is not a member of a relatively organised human community, but they go beyond their record. A man's duties in the concrete, to be sure, are so intimately connected with the rights and aspirations of his fellows that there is no sphere of private existence which the community does not touch ; and even the most austere anchorite is no exception to this truth. But the community is not a moral being. It is a community of moral beings, and a man owes duties to himself irrespective of the rest of society. Robinson Crusoe did not have to wait for man Friday's coming in order to have duties, and a man's morals are not entirely submerged in his social station. There is nothing subjective in this view, despite Hegel. The thesis of the Phenomenology^ and its successors is that gifts and capacities are not valuable in themselves because they may be either good or bad, that their value lies in the rational organisation of them, that the state is just this rational organisation, and so that the bearer of value cannot be anything less than the state. It is an odd thing, perhaps, that a theory which persistently contrasts the unity of the cosmos with the imperfections of the sciences should be so ready to find Reason writ large in politics. Reason must be strong indeed to shine through the nmddle and the meannesses, the intrigues, rancour and pretence of political history ; and the philosophers of Hegel's school shut their eyes so often to the facts of history, and so often descry Utopias by faith alone, that their thesis has to be accepted blindly before it can be followed wittingly. But enough of that. Gifts and capacities have a value just because they are either good or bad. These values imply a world of claims and counter claims, and the claims are worth meeting just because they are genuine. Although the conflict of values may be pernicious, the settle- ment of them is worthless unless there are values to settle. Values, in a word, are not subjective. They really pertain to individual characters and capacities and do not merely seem to do so. A man's capacities belong to him : his needs require his neighbours ; and this objectivity is so thoroughgoing that 1 Professor Baillie's translation, vol. i. pp. Z&'dsqq. and especially p. 373. vii] VALUES 141 it constrains some and dismays others, that it wrecks lives as well as makes them. Even if truth were unknown and impo- tent, it might still be objective; but the values of morals and of conscience are known and felt. The strongest arguments for the subjectivity of moral judgments are varieties of the plea that moral judgments are so much expediency and opportunism, capricious, wavering and temporary. It is held that some moral rules are plainly arbitrary, and therefore that all may be : that some moral rules are things of fashion or social status and therefore that all may be : that moral rules are nothing unless they are uni- versally binding, whereas it is admitted that every command- ment has its exceptions. The first argument need not detain us long. There is nothing sacrosanct about many rules of conduct; but even if every particular rule were arbitrary, it would not follow that it is arbitrary to have any rules at all. Even the rule of the road is not arbitrary in this sense, for the road would be worthless if there were no rules. The laws of property, again, as we find them in any given community, may not have a very secure basis in ethics. A family may own estates because the ancestors of its second cousin's great-uncle helped a weak sovereign to despoil an arrogant bishop. Even if all the legal titles to property were worthless, however, no society could continue without rules for its security in possessing the goods required for food, production, and comfort. Moralists, indeed, usually try to prove too much. If they were content to prove that there must be some rules of property or some rules for the relations of the sexes, it would be impossible to gainsay them. Instead of that they often argue as if there were no alternative between chaos and primogeniture, or between Christian wedlock and promiscuous sexual intercourse. It should not be necessary to point the moral. Rules of property and rules of wedlock are justified, pro tcmto, if they work. These affairs must be regulated to prevent utter disorder. And we know from experience that disorder is barbarous, wretched and vile, even if a starving renniant of redeeming virtues fllourishes sporadically in it. 142 VALUES [CH. The second argument can .summon innumerable examples, but it is enough to refer to a few modern instances. Why should uprightness be less of a virtue in the press than on the bench, why should it be pardonable to cheat the revenue or to steal from a hotel, why should blacklegs be judged so variously, and why should a fallen woman be treated so differently from a male libertine ? Some flimsy reasons may be given in these cases, it is true, just as reasons may be given to prove that duelling was once a duty and is now a crime, that debts of honour should be met before tradesmen's bills, or that lynching is not really the thing that it is. But these reasons are mere excuses. Nothing is more precious than honour ; and nothing, it would seem, more wayward. Evidence of this kind, however, is far too slender to justify the sweeping conclusion that there is neither reason nor truth in morals. It would be a strange thing, indeed, if moral rules were less capricious than they are ; for duty is just as complicated as life. If we could be reasonably certain that a few moral rules are generally binding, that is the most that could be expected even of a society that reflected seriously on its duty. And there never was such a society. Intuition takes the place of reflection with nine men out of ten, and the moral reflec- tions which abound in our novels, our pulpit and our press, are only scattered suggestions summoned by a few notable perplexities. When a man's standards of honour depend as much as they do upon hearsay evidence and the expectations of his friends, when conditions change so much that circum- stances perpetually alter cases, when the ends of action vary so nicely with the conditions of living, it would be strange indeed if anyone could be sure of more than a very few moral rules. But can we be certain of any ? Are any moral rules uni- versally binding ? One wonders what is meant by this question. It is true, perhaps, that any code of rules like the ten com- mandments conflict here and there, and that there is always the chance of a hundredth case which contradicts one of the rules flatly. I admit I cannot think of a case in which wanton cruelty or sexual perversion is a plain duty ; but perhaps vii] VALUES 143 there are such eases. Again it may be true that very general rules like Sidgwick's Axiom of Benevolence, or Kant's in- junction to treat humanity always as an end, or the 'golden rule' of our childhood, are either too abstract to apply deter- minately to any particular case or else are faulty in some respects. The principle that my neighbour's welfare ought to count as well as mine never tells me by itself how to treat my neighbour; I may have to treat engine-drivers as mere means for my purposes : and the golden rule is false unless I do unto others as they ought to do unto me, and even then would fail signally if there were relevant differences between us. But to grant all this leaves the main question untouched. Every rule of conduct must be justified by the values it subserves. When persons and circumstances differ as much as they do, therefore, it is not at all remarkable that a course of action that would be the best for most people under most circumstances should not be the best for all people under all circumstances. The rule ought to differ in its applications if there are relevant differences between its instances ; and what is generally right may sometimes lead to disaster. The logical thing to do is to rejoice that so many rules hold in nearly all cases, for this enables us to follow the rule with as little risk as may be, and generally to dispense with the pains of hard thinking. What is more, it puts the onus prohandi on any one who holds that the rule does not apply in such and such a case. But if the rule can ever be proved to be inapplicable (as when the rule against suicide is absurd if the fortress must fall and the women in it have something worse than death to expect at the hands of their conquerors) then the rule ought not to be followed in these cases for precisely the type of reason which determines that it ought to be followed in other cases. Suicide is a wanton destruction of values and therefore wrong ; but if life must certainly be worse than death, then suicide is a duty. This circumstance, therefore, so far from proving moral judgments invalid, may prove precisely the contrary. That treachery is generally unjustified and promises generally binding is as firm a rule as anyone ought to wish for ; and 144 VALUES [cu. there is no laxity in maintaining that reasons can be shown for exceptions in war or in civil commotion. It would be an accident if any rule were always binding so that we could always 'damn the consequences'' and never needed to consider the case on its merits. This accident may sometimes happen, and one would be interested to meet a case of justifiable in- gratitude, or praiseworthy lust, or admirable malice. The argument, however, does not stand or fall because of the certainty of rules without any possible exceptions, and it is better to leave it so. Summing up this long discussion, we may say that human actions, human character and human dispositions have value or worth. They are good or bad in a moral sense, and value or its opposite belongs to them in the same sense as redness belongs to a cherry. For similar reasons, the values of beauty or its opposite belong to certain things in certain connections just as objectively as any other qualities. And the reasons which seek to prove the contrary are not well founded. This result may seem to be very disappointing, for value is the crux of most of the larger issues concerning the relation of the human spirit to the world, and if philosophical enquiry shows only that some things are valuable, some opposed to value, and others indifferent, what grounds have we for hope in our destiny or for reverence in the order of existence .'* Religion seeks a metaphysical basis for the conservation of values ; and beauty or happiness or true knowledge or moral worth indicate, though they are not identical with, a certain harmony between man and his environment. If the physical order as a whole is indifferent to values, bringing tornados as well as zephyrs, and earthquakes as well as sunshine, values seem to be but fortunate accidents with little promise of stability and no secure basis in the constitution of things. Our argument, to be sure, has not attempted to prove that the values which we can discern empirically are the only values there are, but it has given no hint of the kind of premiss which is sought by those who wish to establish a larger union between values and existence. A survey of the empirical facts seems to show conclusively that value and existence are not vii] VALUES 145 the same, since many things are neither good nor bad ; and it finds no excuse for denying or mitigating the facts of suffering or ugHness or sin. Again, it is impossible to prove from empirical data by themselves that the universe has a bias to- wards the good, that the human spirit is all but certain to have ample opportunities in the world, or that there is always a balance of good over evil. If these things are true, the reason, it would seem, must be extrinsic to the character of existence and of value as we find them. The world, perhaps, is the work of a Creator whose aim is the good of his creatures or his own glory; and the stubbornness of our environment may really be our school and our opportunity. This extrinsic connection, however, is not enough for most idealists, and idealism appeals to many of us precisely because of its faith in the reality of ideals. It takes its stand upon the superior might of ideals in comparison with fact. The ideal, we are told, is reality itself, and what we call fact is only the tarnished surface of the ideal deceiving the foolish and rewarding the wise. The universe is transfigured good because it is trans- figured mind ; and without some premiss of this kind we are yet in our sins. According to Dr Bosanquet^ and those who think with him, the thesis of the idealists depends on the unassailable premises that there is no individuality short of complete existence, and that the harmonious organisation of existence is just what we mean by value. Anyone, we are told, who has fully realised that existence is one and individual, therefore knows that all is well with the world ; and he may even entertain a certain chastened optimism concerning human life. Our private in- terests, it is true, and our temporal and contingent aspirations must expect a short shrift and a perfunctory hearing. Finite personality is not a serious matter for this transfigured good. Length of days, the reverence for human beings in a kingdom of ends, the love of one man for another and the joy of the lark in its freedom are only the fruits of finitude, and so are without true being. If Absolutism gives us hope, therefore, it gives little hope for those personal ties and temporal goods 1 The Principle of Individuality and Value. L. 10 146 VALUES [en. which most men hold so dear. It is enough for us if values exist, and absurd to ask who has them. Indeed it is kinder to pluck the eye of finitude out than to let finitude pervert a philosophy. Even the removal of suffering, the unmasking of hypocrisy, the suppression of infamy, crime and pollution, are in a way, less urgent duties according to this philosophy than according to most others, for if all is well with the world then the poisonous stench of iniquity and the unspeakable horrors of lust and plague and war are not ultimately evil, and so are either too superficial for genuine philosophy or else are necessary elements in the dramatic fitness of things. ' Pity would be no more if we did not make somebody poor, and mercy no more would be if all were as happy as we.' On the other hand, this optimism which is only another name for the necessary perfection of the universe, has an impersonal and timeless splendour of its own. For the sum of being is enough for any man, and our finitude is a sorry thing to yearn after when we participate in the whole. The temper of realism is the reverse of this. Realists need not deny, it is true, that the universe as a whole is a sublime unity sempiternally perfect, but realism does not imply this conclusion, and it does imply the full reality of good and evil as we find them. For the realists, Borgia was a villain and Francis a saint. What is more, Borgia's wickedness was Borgia's affair, and not the work of the universe. The qualities of the whole need not be the qualities of the parts; and many of the parts may be very bad indeed even if the whole is good. Realists, therefore, may logically accept the facts which they find without referring to the whole which they do not know ; and when they fight against real abuses, they are not compelled to enquire into the perfection of reality as a whole. It is difficult, no doubt, to avoid prejudice in these matters. Very few philosophies stand in the way of anything a man has a mind to do, and there is nothing to prevent an absolutist or a mystic or any other metaphysical idealist from becoming a crusader against sin and suffering and crime. Even if wicked- ness is an illusion, that in itself is not a command to refrain from meddling with it. Its half-being may disturb the half- vii] VALUES 147 being which we call life, and there is nothing illogical in setting our own half-being against it. Indeed, it is possible that philosophers could devise a theory according to which time, although an illusion, is less of an illusion in its illusory early stages than in its later ones, and thence infer that the universe has summoned us to be instruments of progress, and has enabled us to guess at the nature of the progress from the character of the impulse to improve. This inference from idealistic premises is not more illogical than quietism or in- difference, but it is not less illogical; and there can be little doubt that any theory which impugns the reality of time or sin or suffering lessens the importance of removing evil. If nothing but the whole matters ' in the end,' any finite enter- prise and any human crusade is thereby belittled. It can only ameliorate finite conditions; and there is a great difference between theories which maintain that finite abuses and finite remedies are real, and those which maintain the contrary. " But you go too fast,'' I think I hear. Even if the penalty of believing that ' the ideal only is actual ' were a certain carelessness concerning the apparent rottenness of apparent institutions, a certain acquiescence in the established order of things, and a certain tardiness and conservatism in the appli- cation of remedies, does not idealism contain a stimulus to progress which realism must wholly lack ? Struggle is pathetic without the conviction of victory, and how is this conviction possible without the knowledge that the universe itself is on the side of righteousness ? Idealism encourages hope just because it gives a reason for this conviction, and the realistic temper has no such prop to sustain it. When the actual is taken to be finally true, nature is taken to be in- different to values, and man, waging a precarious and unequal struggle on the crust of the earth, has no prospect before him save the temporary alleviation of a few evils. He cannot cope with the greatest of all evils, for that is just the purposeless- ness of human existence itself, and the littleness of mere humanity. Is it really so ? To begin a struggle without hope is indeed a pitiful thing, but is it pitiful for man to struggle even if 10—2 148 VALUES [CH. vii he cannot count on the succour of the universe ? If human life can be made worth living, is not that worth striving for ? If wrong can be worsted, is not that worth doing ? Is duty nothing because it is only a man's duty, and suffering nothing because it is only human suffering ? On the contrary, if these things are trivial, human existence itself must be trivial. If it is, why should the universe trouble to help us ? It might surely find something better to do. And if human existence is not trivial, where is the worthlessness of the struggle ? Throw a man on his own resources and he may do something worth while. Make a pensioner of him and he will repay your alms with feeble dependence. CHAPTER VIII THE MIND These postulata being admitted, it will follow in due course of reason- ing that those beings, which the world calls improperly suits of clothes, are in reality the most refined species of animals ; or, to proceed higher, that they are rational creatures or men. For, is it not manifest that they live, and move and talk, and perform all other offices of human life? are not beauty, and wit, and mien, and breeding their inseparable proper- ties? in short, we see nothing but them, hear nothing but them. Swift, A Tale of a Tub. It is time to pass from the objects of knowledge to the process of knowing and to the mind itself. When things confront the mind, the mind has to accept them, and realists should be able to explain what they take this knowledge to be Realists are committed to a doctrine of logical pluralism. They maintain that there is nothing in the nature of knowledge to prevent any given judgment from being wholly and finally true, irrespective of the conditions of existence and of the truth of other judgments, however closely the judgment may be connected with these in fact. And realists accept a kindred theory of perception, for they hold that physical things may be revealed to the perceiving mind as they really and truly are in their own proper character. Many things, that is to say, can be known bi/ us. The knowledge and observation which realists set out to defend is human knowledge and human observation, not the celestial apprehending of some impersonal cosmic intelligence. Realists, it is true, should not deny knowledge of some sort to the ape and the python on the one hand, or to the angels in heaven on the other, but their principal concern is man's mind as they find it. Our knowledge is a temporal affair happening in common- place life-histories, passing rapidly from one thing to another, overcome by a drowsy nod, a whiff of ether or a gust of 150 THE MIND [ch. passion. At the same time it is acquired continuously, it is fostered by education and experience, and it is not quite un- systematic or quite capricious. Realists, therefore, have to defend the reality of a mind which grows and then grows old, which learns and forgets, which struggles, and studies, and takes its ease. Thus far they are committed by their theory of knowledge; but they are not committed further; and so they may differ from one another very sharply indeed, in their views of the mind in detail. Any psychology, indeed, which does not implicitly or of set purpose deny that Smith or Jones may know this or that finally and without qualification is consistent with realism. On the other hand, realism would be only a torso without some philosophy of the mind, and so I intend to pass to this question without further preamble. To be brief, my thesis is that we must look to psychology if we wish to know what the mind is, and that there are no sound metaphysical principles which prove that psychological results must be merely pro- visional. No psychologist or philosopher pretends, of course, that he has obtained complete insight into the mind and its workings, but no sane enquirer makes this pretence in any of the sciences. It is enough in any science if we can know part of the truth and if we are justified in believing that the methods and principles which have already obtained this partial success are also the remedy for our present ignorance. If this thesis were not denied so frequently, and sometimes so bitterly, there would be excellent reasons for supposing it an innocuous truism, cautious to a fault. In reality, however, there is no such thing as caution in these matters. For it is meaningless to defend psychology without explaining lohat psychology is defended ; and psychologists are so radically and so acrimoniously divided upon the meaning, the scope and the methods of their science that any one who explains his position in detail has to face the certainty of disagreeing with most of them. Psychology, we may suppose, seeks to obtain a certain body of knowledge, and such knowledge is about the mind. This inevitable supposition, however, is dangerous enough to ruffle viii] THE MIND 151 the waters of itself. For what is the mind, and how can we know what it is? If psychologists were agreed in their general opinions on these matters, they might cheerfully leave the answer to the detailed results of psychological investigation. In fact, however, they are not at all agreed upon these funda- mental questions, either before they begin their enquiries or after they have finished them; and so it is idle to expect that psychological problems will solve themselves by patient psychologising. Too many false starts are possible, and there is not even a consensus of opinion among the experts to guide us in determining which of these starts are the false ones. It has always been recognised that human beings are mind- bodies, or (if the reader prefers) body-minds, and again that the empirical study of the mind trenches upon the metaphysics of the soul. At the present time, however, the trend of speculation has profoundly altered the perspective of psy- chology. It is not merely that souls have gone out of fashion. Psychologists, rightly or wrongly, seldom took souls very seriously. What has gone out of fashion is traditional psy- chology itself. The doctrine of evolution has conquered biology so thoroughly that biologists can afford to be critical of it. Psychologists, on the other hand, write as if they were thrilled with the novelty of the notion, and as if they were bound to accept it with the faith of a little child. Armed with this confidence they seize the flail of evolution, demolish the cob- webs of theology, stifle philosophy in the filmy ruins and then, with the lust for destruction hot within them, turn and belabour consciousness itself. The mind of a man may seem very wonderful but, look you, it has the pedigree of the ape. And a man's ancestry is the stuff of him. The continuity of the germ-plasm has seen to that. Therefore man is the ape's brother under his skin, just as Judy O'Grady is sister to the colonel's lady. Our simian ancestors, it is true, have unfor- tunately perished (I think we developed too fast for the truth of these theories) and so we should look to the gorilla and the chimpanzee, or better still, simplify our theorv by declaring that the most prominent characteristics in the higher animals are also most fundamental in mankind. The higher 152 THE MIND [ch. animals are dominated by instinct. Therefore man is also a bundle of instincts. And when this stage of the argument is reached it seems a pity to stop. Animal intelligence is a risky thing to think about, for animals are not introspective and do not connnunicate with us. Let us therefore renounce introspection, and then we shall know where we are in psy- chology. Instincts, again, are conscious processes and conse- quently elude the biologist and his methods. Let us therefore deny the existence of consciousness and study behaviour instead. When we track behaviour behind the reflexes down to the simplest conceivable response, we shall then, at long last, turn our backs upon superstition and discover what the mind really is. Thus all will be ad maiorem naturae gloriam. Those of us who believe that Newton did a little thinking before he wrote his Principia, and that his protoplasmic ancestry was incapable of anything of the sort, are not likely to be impressed by these rhapsodies. If we were pressed for an argument, we might reply that continuity of development, interpreted in this preposterous sense, cuts both ways. If Newton cannot be more than his pedigree, his pedigree must be at least as good as Newton. That being so, it is not at all unscientific to take the mind of man as we find it. The question is. What do we find ? In our own persons, at all events, we find consciousness ; and if our theories deny consciousness to other people, so much the worse for our theories. What then is this conscious- ness? The only possible answer to this question, it is plain, is just a description of fact. Colour is proved to exist when it is pointed out, and not otherwise. And so with consciousness. We are aware of our own consciousness, and we can usually detect the signs of consciousness in others. When a man, as we say, regains consciousness after chloroform, he feels, perceives and attends where he could not do so before. The evidence in these cases, it is true, is sometimes deceptive. The ' ether cry ^ has been heard in cats whose cerebral hemispheres have been removed, and these pitifully mutilated creatures have been known to show an anger-mimesis though never the viii] THE MIND 153 pleasure-mimesis of purring ^ This occasional uncertainty, however, proves nothing. It is impossible to prove that no Englishman enjoys roast beef just because we cannot always be certain whether our guests like their dinner or not. It seems clear, however, that something more than bare feeling is needed if consciousness can be said to exist in the usual sense. Etymology, indeed, is a perilous guide, and so it may be irrelevant to point out that the word's history implies a certain togetherness of experiencing in co?isciousness. On the other hand, consciousness, in ordinary usage, implies a certain organisation of experiencing and at least a hint of memory. The total absence of memory from moment to moment in cases o^ petit mal inclines us to deny consciousness altogether; and the twilight sleep under scopolamine is doubtfully con- scious precisely because the patient's retentiveness is so re- markably fugitive. On the other hand, it is easy to exaggerate the minimum of togetherness which consciousness involves. The unity of consciousness, it is true, has been a favourite theme with philosophers. Kanfs account of the unity of apperception, for example, is a pre-requisite of the possibility of scientific experience. At a humbler level, again, it is fair to point out that there cannot be disappointment unless the disappointed person is also the person whose hopes have been frustrated, and that there cannot be inference unless one and the same mind is aware of the premises and draws the conclusion. Unity of this kind, however, is far closer than the minimum required for consciousness to exist. A dog's consciousness, or a child's, and sometimes a man's, is much more loosely united than this. True, there is some togetherness of experiencing in any consciousness, and a mens rnomentanea is not a mind at all; but there need not be very much togetherness. There is still less justification for the view that conscious- ness implies self-consciousness, or that this togetherness of experiencing must not only exist, but must also be known to exist, ere consciousness occurs. The primary function of 1 Sherrington, The Integrative Action of the Nervous System, pp. 254-255. 154 THE MIND [ch. consciousness is to refer beyond itself, and for the most part consciousness fulfils this function without any nrriere pensee towards the self. No one, therefore, has a right to deny con- sciousness to an animal or to an infant simply because they are probably not self-conscious except in a most rudimentary fashion. Deliberate self-cognition, again, requires a special effort which is seldom made; and very little can be inferred from the circumstance that a man who attends to other things can attend to himself if he chooses, and that he is, for the most part, inattentively self-conscious. Many philosophers, it is true, are at pains to point out that consciousness tends to disappear altogether when intense interest fills the sails or utter concentration takes the helm. Self-forgetfulness, they say, is the law of crisis, of spiritual awakening, of deeds of valour in mettlesome emergencies, of love and joy and supreme skill. The wrestler is his tottering opponent, the hunter is the trigger of his Winchester. T^Tiis argument, however, is beside the point; for what is absent in these cases is not consciousness but self-cognition. Archimedes was not unconscious when the soldier killed him, but he was so intent on geometry and so inattentive to himself that he was as defenceless as a penguin. Absent-mindedness of this notable kind is only the mind's absence from practical con- cerns. It is not the absence of consciousness; and there is nothing miraculous in the fact that the mind, in moments of crisis, is often too busy to attend to itself. Another argument is sometimes added to this one. Ac- cording to it, we know from experience that attention (and even consciousness) tend to cease when the need for them has gone. The tyro at the pianoforte has to attend to each movement and to each note. The finished pianist attends to the score, and his fingers, as it were, act of themselves. This argument certainly shows that consciousness, regarded as the guide to action, is not always indispensable. We breathe too well to need consciousness, and consciousness is often a hindrance when we have it. Consciousness comes on the scene when our breathing is disturbed; and even then it is more of a nuisance than a help, like an old maid weeping when someone is hurt. viii] THE MIND 155 But although this argument may disprove the usefulness of consciousness in certain contingencies, it has no further bearing on the issue, and it has very little bearing even on the con- nection between consciousness and self-consciousness. The tyro need not be self-conscious though he may be. He learns the better if he is not ; and if he is self-conscious when he is skilful enough to dispense with consciousness, his self-consciousness need not do any harm although it may sometimes disturb the routine of action in its perverse attempt to probe into the action''s machinery. Although these arguments are designed to belittle con- sciousness, they admit, at any rate, that we know what consciousness is; and anyone who denies this is beyond the pale of argument. On the other hand, it is plausible to urge that our knowledge of consciousness carries us but a little way. Our experiences, we are told, are a motley crew of contingent, evanescent, superficial events. Consciousness is only the iri- descent surface of bodily life, and the best way of studying the mind is to leave consciousness alone. In the last analysis, indeed, consciousness is only a kind of response which a living body makes when it has reached a certain level of integration, and the real business of psychology is to study the nervous system. The general outline of the argument which is deduced from these considerations is now so familiar that it can be indicated very briefly. The study of the human organism shows, in the first place, that it is a selective instrument. The eye is attuned to light, the ear to sound. In the second place, this selection from the environment is only the beginning of a process, not the consummation of it. Stimuli are selected, and every stimulus issues in movement. The schematic outline of this process is expressed by the conception of a simple reflex. Such a reflex is the conduction of a stimulus through a chain of neurons, passing through the central system and issuing in movement. What we find in experience, however, is an inte- gration of compound reflexes. We are the creatures of reflex patterns, and the root conception of the whole enquiry is the alliance of certain reflexes, the inhibition of others, and, most important of all, the regulation of alternating reflexes in time. 156 THE MIND [ch. Reflexes reinforce one another when a succession of weak stimuh in the same region, or a number of stimuli from different organs, debouch simultaneously on a final common path and lead to a single strong thrust. This implies, of course, that there is inhibition of antagonistic reflexes. If all the reflexes were stimulated together we should have the strenuous impo- tence of tetanus or strychnine poisoning. Most reflex patterns, however, are alternating. Food is first chewed, then swallowed. Walking is the alternating contraction of the flexor and the extensor muscles. And so on. Coordination in time, therefore, is the fundamental requirement for the integration of reflexes, and this, we may suppose, is the distinctive office of the central nervous system ^ This theory explains much more than consciousness. The movements of developed animals are integrated through the nerves and the central nervous system, and this ample kingdom includes unconscious reflexes like breathing, and subconscious- ness at all its levels, as well as our intermittent consciousness. It would be highly illogical, however, to infer on this account that consciousness is an otiose affair. Even if the same kind of work, broadly speaking, could be done without consciousness as with it, it would be very unlikely, in terms of the argument, that the special work of consciousness could be done quite so well, or quite in the same way, if consciousness were absent. Reflexes may be integrated through the spine or the bulb, but the hemispheres, we are bound to suppose, are better than the spine or the bulb for certain kinds of response; and if con- sciousness, as the argument indicates, is the highest level of this integrating process, we must conclude that it is better for cer- tain necessary purposes than any infra-conscious integration. The argument, indeed, is usually developed along these lines. Sometimes, it is true, the consciousness accompanying a reflex seems merely to register an occurrence in our bodies. The sneeze goes off, and we feel it going off, and that is all. Even in this case, however, consciousness is not really inert, for we can delay the sneeze if we try; and in the general case consciousness does not seem to be merely a spectator of an 1 The outlines of this account follow Sherrington, op. cit. viii] THE MIND 157 organic disturbance. It seems to play its part in the process, and the evidence suggests that it really does so. When we distinguish between conscious and unconscious response, the chief differences seem to be the presence of pain and pleasure, of the one part, and an extension of the range of response, of the other part. The biological utility of pain and pleasure has been noticed so frequently that it is needless to dwell upon it here. Pain is the signal of utter need, sometimes mischievous, but salutary on the whole. And the extension of the range of response which we find in conscious reactions is even more striking. The skeletal muscles (which are the voluntary ones) are specially connected with the senses which have the longest range, and all the evidence shows that consciousness is a pre- venient thing, anticipating movement, and permitting more delicate adjustments When the peril is near, it is true, there is no time for consciousness. The eye, unless it is a baby's eye, closes quicker than the branch that meets it, and we marvel at our cleverness (if we are wise) apres coup. But when there is time we need all the wits we have. The cat stalks the mouse and crouches before it springs. If this statement of the case confined itself to the primary biological function of consciousness, there would be no occasion to dispute it. The dispute begins with the magisterial an- nouncement that the primary biological function of con- sciousness is all that consciousness is; and this announcement is a mere non sequihir. To say that consciousness helps the nervous system and that, in certain selected cases, it does the same kind of work as the nervous system might do without it, is not even the beginning of a proof that consciousness is only a species of nervous process. It is highly important, for example, to show that there is a certain continuity between lifeless and living things, but such arguments can never prove that life itself is not an emergent, radically novel in comparison with its antecedents, although requiring these and using them for its own ends. Similarly there is nothing against believing, and a great deal in favour of believing, that consciousness is an emergent, and not simply a modification of antecedent ^ Cf, Sherrington, op. cit. especially Lecture IX. 158 THE MIND [ch. nervous processes. If so, a certain continuity of function with the nervous systeni and a certain solidarity with it is not to the point, for that may be admitted without touching the argument; and it would even be permissible to argue that consciousness, beginning as humble menial, gradually became the governor and even the tyrant of man's life. The thing has been known to happen. The statement of this possibility, it is true, is not a proof of its truth, and there are plenty of modish arguments which try to show that the encroachments of consciousness are either negligible or non-existent. Man, we are told, is a bundle of instincts and the consciousness of instinct is buried in the nervous system. Instincts are more subconscious than con- scious; and it does not matter in principle which they are. The discussion of this theory in detail would need a long argument. Here it must suffice to say that if an instinct be defined in the usual way as a racial habit, relatively little educable, and serviceable, on the whole, after very little ex- perience on the part of individuals, then man is the least instinctive of animals. Human beings acquire most of their habits, and it is foolish to argue that 'direct action,' or the habit of drawing cheques, or the movements of armies, are strictly comparable to a moorhen's instinct for diving, or to the weary journey of Fabre's caterpillars^ when the thread they had spun had been made a closed circle instead of a trail to lead them homewards. Of course it is easy to exaggerate the fixity of instinctive routine, on the one hand, and the reflec- tiveness and initiative of human behaviour, on the other; but human behaviour, whether in society or in the cloister, is reflective, adaptive and opportunist to an extent which no other species of animals can match. Those who deplore the herd-like irrationalism of the masses cannot have listened to working men discussing their own proper business, and they ignore the extraordinary adaptiveness of modern society. Ten years ago, no one would have predicted that the British working man would show a business-like respect for ration- 1 For a short account see the Essay in Fabre's The Wonders of Instinct, EngUsh translation. viiij THE MIND 159 cards, but when ration-cards were needed the very children in the streets clung to them with the tenacity of limpets. When Florence Nightingale tried to induce the soldiers in the Crimea to save some of their pay, Lord Panmure said bluntly that the British soldier was not a remitting animal. The British soldier became a remitting animal as soon as he saw the need for it. These considerations cannot be discounted by exploiting biological arguments. Certainly it takes a very cool philo- sopher not to see the necessity that a man must live, but arguments concerning the biological utility of consciousness, however important they are, cannot be conclusive of themselves. Civilised man must be cunning enough to avoid motor cars and runaway horses, and in that respect he is on a par with the animals; but he lives the better if he has his children vaccinated and his house disinfected, if he pays policemen to protect him, and sees to it that those who bring him his food in ships are commanded by expert navigators. There is more biological utility in the discovery of salvarsan or chloroform, in the sextant, and in the town's water-supply, than in all the instincts of fear and flight and protective mimicry put together. Granting that life must be preserved and fostered, intelligence at the helm is woi'th a whole cargo of instinct. If these per- versely narrow biological theories were right, the lion and the tiger would rule the world, and man, bereft of fire and ships, of clothes and gunpowder, would cling forlornly to some tree- top, cursing the loss of his tail, and gibbering morosely at the di'yness of the nuts within his reach. The moral of these arguments is that any psychology worth the name must take knowledge very seriously indeed. Man, to be sure, is a psycho-physical being sprung from lowly origins, and there should be no dispute concerning the im- portance of his muscular apparatus or of his nervous system. On the other hand, we must frankly recognise his intelligence as we find it, either in the subtle theorising of Laplace or in the humbler workings of a skilled artisan's mind. Even if a theory of consciousness could be devised which accounted for perception and instinct with reasonable completeness, this theory would be only the beginning of psychology and not the end of it. 160 THE MIND [ch. Every theory of the type we are now considering tries to explain what consciousness is by describing what it does; and so it is important to point out that even a complete account of the functions and of the effects of consciousness would be a very poor substitute for a description of consciousness itself. Even if our consciousness always did the same kind of work as the nervous system it would not therefore be the nervous system ; and even if it were the eye wherewith the universe beholds itself there would still be a question concerning the kind of eye which the cosmos selected for this purpose. Both the naturalistic and the idealistic theories of consciousness, however, fail to notice this important point, and their failure is worth examining. The naturalists, as we have seen, start from the nervous system and maintain that consciousness is just the central part of a delicate neural adjustment comprehensively organised. What is more, they hold that consciousness makes precisely the same selection as the body does. Its material, they say, is just what the sense organs select, and consciousness, so far from being distinctive and peculiar, is simply a certain selection from things and a certain arrangement of them. Consciousness has no peculiar stuff in it, and the same things may be either conscious or not. Bells are associated with books and candles. That is one of their relationships. They also agitate the sur- rounding atmosphere when they are struck by a clapper. That is another relationship which they commonly have, and the truth is that out of the infinite variety of relationships which bells have, one set or pattern is called physical and another is called psychical. The same bell appears in both the patterns. To say that there is consciousness is to say that a thing is selected and organised in a certain way ; and that is the whole mystery. A more ancient and more magnificent theory of the same type states that the function of the mind is to be a microcosm of the universe. The mind is a chameleon of the cosmos perpetu- ally mirroring the totality of things in its subtle, tiny trans- lucence. It is needless to cite authorities in support of this conception since it is, on the whole, the orthodox opinion of the viii] THE MIND 161 classical tradition in philosophy, but I cannot resist the temptation of quoting from an author who is but little read since I do not see how the point could be better put. In his Synthetica^ the late Professor Laurie explained that he took the universe to be a whole of things "which find their truth in the last term of a continuoifs and unbroken system ; that is to say, as presented to conscious subject which makes its appearance in the evolution of the world-organism, for the mere purpose (so to speak) of gathering up the universal record into itself as that record is therein written; man himself being the concluding chapter of that record — the individual into whom the whole is poured^" " Colour,"" hesaid again, "demands me for its own purposes. Colour and I are fellow creatures in the same related system, helping each other's full reality out-." And once more: "If I might indulge in rhetoric I would even say : The natural world of flowers and stars might be regarded as waiting patiently for the emergence in the system of a con- scious entity that they might fully realise themselves. The said consciousness, however, adds nothing to what they truly are, save the awareness in feeling of what they ti'idy are. And you might even imagine a dim thrill of joy in the star- world when a conscious subject first beheld them in their reality, and again when Copernicus and Newton revealed their ordered motions. The stars then sing together. Any other view is, to my mind, crude dualism ^^ The objection to these theories is that they deal only with a part of the problem. Granting that consciousness is the means which the universe has chosen for self-revelation (it is common to choose one's biographers oddly), we have still to consider precisely what this chosen means is, since the universe, for aught we know to the contrary, might have selected very different means. It is very important, to be sure, to try to see consciousness in its true perspective, and therefore to show its relations to its bodily conditions on the one hand, and to the putative needs of the universe on the other. But that is an account of the setting of consciousness, not of its character,^ 1 Synthctica, vol. i. p. 79. '^ Ibid. p. 92. ^ j^jV/. p, ng. L. 11 162 THE MIND [ch. and the only way of discovering this character is just to observe consciousness itself. Such observation is introspection, and common sense is fully convinced of the feasibility and reliability of that process. The plain man knows from his own experience what pleasure or sorrow or excitement feels like. Indeed, he knows these ex- periences infinitely better than he knows his brain or the needs of the universe. He has only a hearsay knowledge of grey matter or the Fissures of Sylvius, and he does not dare to guess at the needs of the universe; but he knows directly in his own person what joy or pity or desire is. Introspection, to be sure, is not infallible. There is no pontifical magister'mm about it, and it is easy, I daresay, to set it too many riddles, and to base ex cathedra encyclicals upon it which have no better warrant than inclination or theory. These admissions however do not affect the issue as the plain man understands it. The character of his consciousness, he thinks, is not hid from him; for he can observe it introspectively. This point is disputed, however, and, clearly, one of the most pertinent objections to it is the theory that consciousness is not really a distinctive, peculiar thing. Those who main- tain this view challenge the plain man's interpretation of introspection, and hold that the facts which his introspection reveals can be studied better in another May. We have already seen the main outlines of this theory, and now we may consider it more narrowly. Up to a point it is eminently successful, since it criticises most effectively the natural, reverend and most mistaken doctrine which asserts that consciousness consists of an inner world of mental images and sensations mirroring the outer world of things. Berkeley, it is true, exploded this fallacy long ago; but superstitions linger, and the inverted Berkeleianism of the American 'new realists' is at least a most interesting experiment in exorcism. As we have seen in earlier chapters, the principal objects of our consciousness are things perceived, remembered, or imaged, together with principles and universals; and the analysis of the American new realists is fully in accord with our con- clusions concerning most of these objects. The things we viii] THE MIND 163 perceive may also be remembered, expected or imaged, and we have seen reasons for believing that precisely the same things may be studied in the science of physics. Different men, it is true, make different selections from perceived reality, and the same men make different selections from things according as they perceive, remember, or image them. It does not follow, however, that perceived things or imaged ones belong to an inner mental world. We may grant, then, that if consciousness were a name for the 'inner"* world, and if the 'inner' world consisted of sense-data, images and the like, then, in all probability, this 'inner' world would be only a selection from the stuff which, otherwise selected, is the 'outer' or physical world. This theory, it is true, might have greater difficulties in explaining the status of universals and of general facts, but it would be sufficient for the others. Sense data are not timeless or colour- less or unextended; they do not have a peculiar non-physical temporality or spaciousness or colour; and if introspection were the observation of sense data and images, it might, indeed, perform a useful office but it would not differ in kind from the observation of physical things. Its results, therefore, might be attained more simply and more fruitfully in some other way. It is a great thing to have avoided this confusion between 'inner' and 'outer,' and yet it is not enough, for these perceived and imaged things which confront our consciousness are not themselves consciousness at all. When I see a blue sky on a winter's day and notice sadly how different the trees are from their budding greenness in spring, the blue is not conscious of the green, or the green of the blue, and the principle of differ- ence is not conscious of either. It is I who am conscious, I who apprehend the green and the blue and the difference. My consciousness is not a character of the things I observe or think or imagine, and it is very doubtful whether it is ever written on the faces of the things I know. My consciousness is my awareness or apprehension of these things, together with the feelings and strivings which accompany my apprehension. Nothing, surely, can be plainer than this, and yet stress must be laid upon it because it is neglected in so many theories of knowledge. 11—2 164 THE MIND [ch. We may say with Dr Strong that these theories of the American realists neglect the fact of givenness^ When a thing is given to the mind it does not therefore acquire a new and peculiar mode of being; but things may exist without being given, and it is useless to argue about the given without ad- mitting the ultimate fact of givenness. Or, again, we may say that it is one thing for an object to exist and quite another thing for that object to appear. When a thing appears, it need not appear otherwise than it is; but it cannot appear unless there is awareness of it, and it can exist without that. When it appears, moreover, it must appear to something, and this something must be or contain awareness or consciousness. The theory of the American new realists, in a word, deals onlv with the objects of consciousness, and so it is not a theoiy of con- sciousness at all. Here is the fatal gap in the theory, and the point, perhaps, may become clearer when it is approached in another way. Dr Ward's Psychological Principles is rightly regarded as the chief systematic work on psychology which any living English- man has produced. We may therefore consider his analysis of the mind^. According to Dr Ward, psychology is the study of individual experience^, and experience itself is the commerce between subject and object*. In the next place, he distinguishes the 'objective"" from the 'subjective' aspect of experience'. The objective aspect of experience, he maintains, consists of sense data, images, and the like — in a word, it consists of presenta- tions^. The subjective side consists of feeling and attention '^. Dr Ward interprets 'feeling' very narrowly, for he restricts it to pleasure and pain^, and he uses 'attention' very broadly, for he means by it any sort of perceiving, inferring, desiring or striving, and even what we should usually call inattention. 1 The Origin of Consciousness, chap. i. pp. 31 sqq. - The reader will see that I differ from Dr Ward on a great many points. My object is to elicit certain conclusions from his analysis of psychology, and neither to accept nor to criticise his view au pied de la lettre. 3 Psychological Principles, p. 28. * Ibid, chap i. especially § 3. 5 Ibid. pp. n sqq., SO sqq. 6 j^^^^^ pp^ 46 sqq. 7 Ibid. e.g. General Analysis, pp. 55 sqq. ^ Ibid. p. 45. viii] THE MIND 165 According to him there is attention whenever we are active enough to receive impressions \ It is clear that the analysis of the American new realists deals Avith what Dr Ward calls the objective aspect of ex- perience, and omits the subjective aspect altogether. Anyone, indeed, who maintains that there is no distinctive stuff of consciousness has to argue that the subjective side of ex- perience is really part of the objective side. Let us see then, what these philosophers say. They begin with the argument that feeling is a sensation and therefore in pari materia with other sensations ; and they can claim distinguished authority in support of this contention. Indeed, we should all agree with Stumpf- in believing that bodily pain and bodily pleasures, like the comfort of a warm fire or the smoothness of underwear, are sensations; and perhaps we should follow him in his further contention that the pleasures and pains of the special senses are very often sen- sations. Toothache and nausea, for example, are organic sensations, and the ache of the one and the diffused disagree- ableness of the other seem to belong to the tortured organism. The pleasures of sight, again, are blended with the smoothness of ocular adjustment and that is an affair of kinaesthetic sensation. There is a bodily resonance, indeed, in all emotion, and the most refined delight has its own thrill of organic harmony. On the other hand, our delight in the neatness of an argument or in the point of a jest is not merely the smile, or the laugh, or any other bodily accompaniment. The bodily movements, indeed, may be repressed (perhaps by a rather painful effort), and the delight still be felt. Such delights, therefore (and the pains of remorse or failure), are certainly not sensations, even if organic sensations accompany them; and therefore the theory falls. Indeed, there is no difficulty in distinguishing mental pains and pleasures from the pleasures and pains of sensation. The latter are organic sensations which are localised within the 1 Psychological Principles, p. 49 and p. 60. 2 Zeitschrift fur Psychologic, xliv. 1906, 1 sqq. Cf. Titchener, The Psy- chology of Feeling and Attention, Lecture III. 166 THE MIND [ch. body. The former are not. They have no habitation in muscle or eye or ear, because they are not bodily at all. Passing, then, from feeling to attention, we may ask whether attention belongs to the objective aspect of experience. The effect of attending to anything, it is generally agreed, is to increase the clearness of that thing and also to secure a certain dominance for it. Attention lays hold on a thing, brings its outlines into relief and tends to keep irrelevant things from appearing. There are differences, therefore, on the side of the object according as it is attentively or inattentively regarded, and the problem is whether these differences on the side of the object can be all that attention means. This discussion may seem very strange, but the strangeness, after all, may be due to our own misconceptions. It seems absurd to ask whether things themselves are clear or obscure, because we always suppose that clearness or obscurity depends upon us. We are fully convinced that things themselves can- not differ in point of clearness, and therefore infer that these differences in clearness are manifestations of our activities. Still, this interpretation, spontaneous and inevitable as it seems, may be mistaken. To parody a famous saying of Hume"'s, " Wlien we exclude consciousness, we really do exclude it." Is it not possible that this enhanced clearness, steadiness and dominance in the objects of attention is all that attention is, and that the attentive consciousness which we take to be the cause of these characteristics is only a myth.'* In point of fact we should have no business to infer that these differences in clearness and the rest were due to attention unless we were acquainted with attention itself. If the attentive process can be observed it is possible to apply the usual logical methods and to infer that clearness results from attention because it increases as attention increases and is absent when attention is absent. Without this acquaintance the hvpo- thetical cause of the increase in clearness might be anything under the sun. The plain man's certainty, then, is due to the fact that he is directly acquainted with attention itself, and not merely with its effects. But since this point is disputed I prefer to approach it gradually. viii] THE MIND 167 As we have seen, Dr Ward takes 'attention'' to include per- ceiving, inferring, desiring and striving. This is not a common use of the term, and it is not a very good one. But that may pass. The point which I wish to put before the reader is the difference between these varieties of 'attention.' No one denies, I suppose, that perceiving is a different process from inferring, and that both perceiving and inferring differ from desiring. To infer an ecHpse is very different from seeing one. It is one thing to see the Kaiser hanged and another thing to desire his execution. My question is: How do we know these differences? We are as certain of them as of anything in the world, and there must be some explanation. What is it, then.-^ Plainly, the certainty cannot be due to any difference in the objects. There is generally a difference in the objects, it is true, when there is a difference in the mental experience. We do not perceive what we desire. The fox saw the grapes, but he desired to eat them ; and eating is not seeing. No one, again, is dazzled by an inferred corona. On the other hand, some of these differences are independent of any differences in the objects. If one man tells me that Yorick is dead and another questions the statement, both of them refer to the death of poor Yorick, but one of them believes it and the other doubts. It is clear, I think, that the difference between believing and merely supposing, or again between desiring and inferring, can be readily discerned by inspection; but if the reader jibs he may be invited to consider what happens when we doubt and when we believe precisely and numerically the same thing. It is quite certain, therefore, that some of the differences in what Dr Ward calls the 'subjective aspect of experience'' do not belong to the 'objective aspect,' and surely there is no need to prove that doubting, supposing, believing, and the like, are conscious processes and that their differences are diffei'ences in consciousness. Any theory, therefore, which identifies con- sciousness with the objects of consciousness has failed in most elementary fashion. These objects of consciousness are not consciousness at all, except in the special case of introspection. Consciousness is the awareness of them, the striving for them, 168 THE MIND [ch. the joy in them, not the things striven for, apprehended or enjoyed. This finding changes the course of the debate. Conscious- ness, it appears, is different from the objects of consciousness, and we are directly acquainted with it. The problem is there- fore, how we are acquainted with it, and what we learn from this acquaintance. The simplest answer to the first of these questions is Locke's. The mind can notice its own operations. This simple answer, I think, is the right one, and I propose to defend it; but it is contradicted so flatly by so many eminent philosophers that its defence, unfortunately, is rather a lengthy business. For some maintain that we do not observe in this way, and others that we do not need to do so, and others that we could not if we would. The first objection, I think, is contrary to fact and based on misconception. We can and do observe our own conscious- ness, and anyone who doubts this statement may perhaps see the truth of it when he considers the alternatives. We have seen already that our knowledge of our consciousness cannot be an affair of inference. If it were, there would not be any radical difference in experience between our knowledge of our own anger and our knowledge of the Apostle Paul's. In fact, however, we are directly acquainted with our own anger and not with the Apostle's, and our acquaintance with our own consciousness must depend upon observation unless it is a different species of awareness from any other. For knowledge is either observation or inference. As might be expected, therefore, we have to meet the argument that our acquaintance with our own minds is altogether sui generis. This conclusion, we are told, is inevi- table, since observer and observed are one in the case of introspection. We have to observe a saucepan in order to be aware of it, but we do not need to observe our anxiety in order to apprehend it. Anxiety is a mode of consciousness, and we are conscious of anxiety whenever we are anxious. There is no difference between the consciousness and our awareness of it, since consciousness is itself awareness. viii] THE MIND 169 This argument is thoroughly fallacious. In the first place, anxiety and the awareness of anxiety are not the same; for awareness is a kind of knowing and anxiety is an emotion. At the best, therefore, this argument would hold only of the awareness of awareness, and not of the awareness of emotion or striving. In the second place, it is abundantly clear that attention to our own minds is only an occasional process which need not be very efficient. Some psychologists even affirm that attention to ourselves always disturbs the current of our con- sciousness, and TurgeniefF went further, for he said: "When my sufferings are unendurable I follow Schopenhauer's advice. I analyse my sensations, and my agony departs for a period." Be that as it may, it is plain that attention to our consciousness is not the same thing as being conscious. When we are con- scious we are usually aware of our consciousness at least dimly, but we need not always be ; and we have to attend very hard if we wish to discern the features of our consciousness accurately. What is more, we often make mistakes in this enterprise. This obvious reflection, however, is often forgotten. M. Berg- son forgets it in his theory of intuition^ and all the mystics forget it when they argue that knowing and being are one in the case of the self. Now it is true that the self can behold itself, but this self-observation is never the identity of observ- ing and being. If it were, how could there be any occasion for attending to ourselves ? We cannot help heing ourselves; and if our conscious being were identical with this knowing, we should always have a complete answer to all psycho- logical questions through the mere fact of existing. The mystics and the intuitionists, indeed, can give no reason for the pains and labour which they think intuition requires. They tell us that anyone who would learn of them must make an unusually resolute effort to sink into himself: but if being conscious and knowing one's consciousness are one and the same, where is the need for this effort .'' We always are what we are without anv effort whatever, and we do not have to struiiiile in order to become ourselves. 1 Introduction to Metaphysics, passim. 170 THE MIND [ch. Granting, then, that consciousness and the awareness of consciousness are not the same, it remains to consider whether this awareness of consciousness is a kind of observation. If it is, it has to dispense with eyes and ears, but that is no ob- jection. Indeed, to cut a long story short, the difficulties that have to be met are really a priori difficulties. Berkeley has told us that there can be no awareness of activity^, and the Kantians, following their master's lead% assert that there can be no awareness of awareness. Berkeley's argument rests on confusion. We can certainly observe conscious processes as they occur, and this is the deter- mining circumstance here. Activity, to be sure, is not observed if it is taken to mean the hidden spring of change, the mystery that makes motion move, but activity in that sense is a will o' the wisp like the 'force' of unreflective dynamics. On the other hand we can certainly observe our consciousness playing its part in bodily adjustments and in subsequent conscious- ness; and the experiences of striving, willing, and the like, may well be called active since they are peculiarly bustling and purposeful. Such consciousness, then, 'has hands and feet,' in the classic phrase, and we can see it at work^ We are left, therefore, with the celebrated dogma that there can be no awareness of awareness. The principal argu- ments in favour of this contention seem to be thi'ee, and we may consider each in turn. It is argued, imprimis, that such awareness is never a fact of experience; deinde, that whatever we know is an object, so that if consciousness is made an object it is therefore transformed utterly ; adhuc, that knowledge always refers beyond itself, and consequently that it cannot refer to itself. " I have to confess," Mr Russell says, "that the theory which analyses a presentation into act and object no longer satisfies me. The act or subject is schematically convenient, but not empirically discoverable It seems to me imperative, therefore, to construct a theory of presentation or belief which makes ^ Principles, §27. ^ Metaphysische Anfangagriinde der Naturicigsenschaft. ^ Cf. James, Essays in Radical Empiricism, pp. 155 sqq. viii] THE MIND 171 no use of the subject or of an 'acf as a constituent of a presentation ^^ It must be admitted that it is difficult to observe acts of knowledge. Our thinking processes, it is plain, are thoughts of something, attention to something. It is unlikely, therefore, that they could be isolated and set up for inspection by them- selves ; and certainly they are not isolable in this way. None the less, these acts of attention and belief can be discovered empii'ically for the reasons already given. When we consider doubting, believing and supposing, for example, we can observe very clearly that these attitudes may refer to the same object and yet differ intrinsically. This difference is plainly a differ- ence in the character of the mental processes themselves; and we cannot observe these differences in the acts without ob- serving these very acts. Tlie trouble is that when we look for knowledge we often expect to find something more than the process of apprehension, and therefore may be inclined to dispute the existence of knowing just because we find nothing except knowing. And that is not a reasonable objection". The objection that the observation of consciousness trans- forms it into an object may be dismissed very briefly. The primary function of knowledge, it is true, is to know something that is not itself, but this does not prove that knowledge itself, or any other form of consciousness, cannot be known. As I have said in another place, " To be directly acquainted with anything, and to be directly acquainted with that thing ' as an object,' express precisely and numerically the same fact. The subject 'as known' or 'as an object' is just the subject itself. If we are acquainted with it, then we are acquainted with it, and no qualification of this statement is permissible 1 ' Problems of Science and Philosophy ' {Aristotelian Society, Supple- mentary vol. n. 1919), pp. 25, 26. 2 I assume that Mr Kussell means that the knowing subject is not empiri- cally discoverable. It is nonsense to say that the feeling and striving subject is not. And perhaps I may add that the analysis of act and object has suffered some harm by Mr Moore's description of ' acts ' as ' diaphanous ' (' The Kefu- tation of Idealism,' Mind, N.S., vol. xii. (1903)). The diaphaneity of an act of knowledge, as I understand the description, only means that the charac- teristics of the act do not appear in the object, and not that the act has no observable characteristics when attention is paid to it. 172 THE MIND [ch. unless the acquaintance is mistaken, or the word ' object,' for purposes of technical convenience, is defined in some restricted sense. Nothing can be transformed in any sense whatever simply owing to the fact that it is known. To suppose the contrary is scepticism ^"'"' The third argument is equally inconclusive. The process of knowledge, it is true, refers beyond itself, and therefore an act of knowledge can never be aware of itself. This fact, however, does not justify the inference that acts of knowledge cannot be observed. Such acts cannot observe themselves, but why should not another act observe them ? Introspection is a de- liberate inspection of awareness, and the empirical evidence strongly suggests that it is always a different act from the act of which it is aware. Our minds, however, are rich enough to contain a multitude of awai'enesses almost at the same moment. For thought is quick. In a word, observer and observed are one in introspection, because the act of introspection and the experience which it observes form part of one and the same mind, but this circumstance does not imply the absurdity of an act of attention attending to itself. We conclude, then, that consciousness can be directly ob- served, and this result is of the utmost importance for psy- chology. Psychology is the study of the mind, and the phenomenal mind is just the living continuity of desiring, choosing, perceiving, and similar experiencings. It is these processes in their union, and it is nothing else. What is more, there is no good reason in metaphysics for maintaining that this phenomenal self differs from the real self. It would be other- wise if our acquaintance with it could be discredited ; but that, we have seen, is not the fact. It would be otherwise, again, if any phenomenal thing had to have a noiimenal basis which always eludes observation, but this metempirical nucleus of thinghood is only a sort of transcendental blessing upon a union which God has already decreed without the laying on of philo- sophical hands. Substance is always a descriptive term indi- cating a unity which exists de facto. It does not make the connectedness of properties; it only describes their connected- 1 Article, 'Introspection,' Mind, N.S., No. 112, pp. 396, 397. viii] THE MIND 173 ness. It is not even an accessory after the fact. Minds are substances simply because desiring, willing, and knowing do not float about loosely. They always unite in a personality, and this united fact is the spiritual substance just as the cohesion of certain molecules is the whole substance of a pie-dish. The self, to be sure, is not the same sort of thing as a pie-dish. But that is another story. What objections are there to this conclusion ? It may be said, in the first place, that the self, after all, may only be the body. The plausibility of this argument disappears, however, when the argument is sufficiently precise to be worth considering. As we have seen, it is easy enough to show that con sciousness continues the work of the nervous system and even that it does the same kind of work in certain cases. These suggestions, however, are not proofs of identity. Does the brain discriminate, judge or infer, does it choose or resolve, does it feel and enjoy ? To ask these questions is surely to answer them. We know what these processes are because we can observe them, and we know that we could not observe them if we turned our lenses upon the brain after some delicate operation of trepanning. What is more, we know that this consciousness which we observe is different in kind from any- thing that could be observed in the brain. The only reasonable conclusion, therefore, is that consciousness is not cerebral move- ment. If the brain is the coloured, irritable, convoluted pulp that physiologists study, then this quivering indented thing is not the mind ; and to say that it may also be conscious is only a quibble. For anything one can prove to the contrary, some pebble on the side of Ararat may have spent the days and nights of the Flood in working out differential equations, but then it was not the sort of pebble which Dr Johnson kicked or physicists consider. If the brain means what physiologists mean by it, it is not a mind. If not, you may ascribe to it any properties you choose, but it is mockery to call it only a brain. It may be said, in the second place, that the work of the mind is far too arduous and too intricate for mere conscious- ness to perform. At the most obvious empirical level, con- sciousness is nothing without memory or retentiveness, and 174 THE MIND [ch. consciousness itself, fleeting and evanescent, is not even a permanent condition of its own retentiveness. Here, surely, is a singular argument. If consciousness is really continuous and retentive it cannot also be less retentive than it is ; and if it is fleeting it must be at least as retentive in its fleetingness as we find it to be. Nothing ever accounts for itself, and the only sense in saying that a thing accounts for part of itself is to show the interconnectedness of its parts. It is useless, therefore, to suppose that the self, or anything else, could account for memory otherwise than by having the function of memory deeply implanted in it. And it is plain that memory belongs to the self in this sense. Systematic de- scription is the only possible explanation of such matters. A systematic description of the self, it is true, is incomplete in many particulars. For the self is a continuant, and we only observe fragments of it in introspection. In this respect the self is like any other empirical thing. Our conscious lives are infinitely richer than the casual records of introspection; and introspection, perhaps, is not very thorough, even when it is careful. The conscious self, therefore, is very largely an in- ferred thing, but it is not merely inferred, since its principal features and the outlines of its connectedness can be observed introspectively. True, the fragments of consciousness which we observe in this fashion do not do the whole work of conscious- ness. But then they are only parts of a conscious mind. There is no difference in principle when mind is taken at its highest level. Kant's proof of the unity of apperception showed, once and for all, how subtle knowledge is ; but even if the most commonplace judgment implied all the principles of logic and most of the categories, that in itself would not show that empirical consciousness is incapable of the work of know- ing ; and Kanfs other arguments on this question make quite unnecessary assumptions. As his most recent commentator points out, Kant's theory implied the consequence (which Kant himself was very loth to accept) that " the activities generative of consciousness have to be recognised as themselves falling outside it. Not even in its penumbra, through some vague form of apprehension, can they be detected. Only the viii] THE MIND 175 finished products of such activities, not the activities them- selves, can be presented to consciousness ; and only by general reasoning inferential of agencies that lie outside the conscious field can we hope to determine them^" Kant held, therefore, that the work of thinking was performed by an unknowable and indispensable faculty which he called productive imagina- tion, and his argument has appealed to many philosophers. It rests on the assumption, however, that consciousness re- quires 'generating activities' outside itself, and there seems to be no good reason for denying that consciousness does its own generating. Conscious knowledge is just knowledge at work — a piece of being, strenuously alive. It may be objected in the third place that the real and the phenomenal self cannot be identical because personal identity belongs to the real self and because it is not found in our consciousness. There is no identity between our childish esca- pades and our present dignified and important pursuits; and even when childhood is left out of account, there is little identity between Lord Braxfield on the bench and Lord Braxfield in his cups, or between John Newton the pirate and John Newton the hymn-writer. Indeed, it is needless to consider these striking instances, or the still more extreme cases of William Sharp and his feminine personality "Fiona Macleod," or of multiple per- sonality in the Hanna case or the Beauchamp family. The same kind of abrupt variation, we are told, occurs in every life al- though we are too little reflective to rate it at its proper worth. There are two questions to consider here, a question of logic and a question of fact. The logical question concerns the meaning of identity. If nothing is identical unless it persists unchanged then, plainly, there is no such thing as personal identity, and there is no identity of body or brain. Neither mind nor body persists unchanged, and it is foolish to speak of their identity in this sense. If there is any pitiful remnant of unchanging consciousness in us, this dubious residuum is certainly not ourselves, just as our bodies are not those scraps of tissue, if there are any, which have never been renewed. ^ Mr Norman Smith's Commentary on Kant's Critique of Pure Eeason, pp. 263, 264. 176 THE MIND [ch. Personal identity, therefore, is either a mere fiction or else it does not mean unchanging existence. If it is a fiction, it shares the illusion with any other existing thing. If not, identity must be sought, not in unchangeableness of material, but in continuity of character and function. And this brings us to the question of fact. Our bodies remain the same, not because they are composed of the same material, but because they retain the same type of organisation in similar material ; and identity in this sense also holds of personal consciousness. Any self has a certain typical organisation. The emotions are organised into sentiments; inherited habits unite with acquired ones to make a formed will and a formed character; and knowledge is organised too. Our knowledge is complex in its simplest manifestations. It is charged with meaning and servile to a host of principles. It has to look before and after in order to look at all. That is personal identity in general. In particular, each self is born different, and acquires its own individual organi- sation. What is acquired may lessen the original differences or it may accentuate them. The army or the public school may standardise men, and a bohemian existence may foster the same sort of imitative eccentricity. On the other hand, each member of the same family or school or nation sets about living in his own. way, and each makes something different of his capacities and opportunities. These personal differences per- sist despite the most radical changes of outlook or opportunity. When a timid sinner is converted, he usually becomes a timid saint; and even when he is made strong out of weakness, his strength has quite a different fibre from the strength of those who were strong before. A man's feelings, again, are not a child's. The man outgrows his childhood, as he outgrows sailor suits and a taste for Henty, but we can see the marks of his childish selfishness in his manhood's considerateness, and we can feel his boyish shyness quivering through his sophis- ticated aplomb. If the man himself is too blind to trace this continuity, his mother is not. ' Personal identity, then, is not a superstition. It is a reality ; and the most serious difficulty in it is not the variations of personality, but the recurrent annihilation of conscious viiij THE MIND 177 personality in sleep, and its occasional annihilation in a trance or in an accident. That, of course, is the standing argument in favour of materialism. It takes courage to defend conscious identity when it evaporates with a breath of narcotile, and when a brickbat sends it spinning. On the other hand, it takes foolhardiness to deny it. Peter wakes up the self-same Peter every morning. He rises earlier than usual if he has to catch a train, he starts at a burglar's stealthy tread, and he is the same old Peter in his dreams. Perhaps, then, it is unlikely that Peter's consciousness vanishes utterly during sleep, but there is certainly very little empirical evidence of it during profound slumber, and none at all when Peter is under chloroform. Peter's identity, therefore, may have gaps in it, for sometimes there seems to be no Peter at all. And why not ? Peter is Peter when he exists. When he does not exist, there is naturally no Peter. Conscious personality, therefore, is not unbroken existence, but it is distinctively individual in a way that is matched by nothing else that we know. Some have supposed, even, that there is an ultimate metaphysical principle to the effect that no part of a self can also be part of any other self; and the facts of experience, with a few dubious exceptions, would cei*tainly support this metaphysical principle. Castor and Pollux may have similar thoughts when they think of the same thing, but Castor's thoughts do not pass into Pollux. All this is commonplace, to be sure. I mention it — apolo- getically — because it is true. We are told that this is precisely the principle which all good Platonists are most concerned to deny^ It ossifies the self into a repellent unit, it is perversely ' linear ' where it should also be 'lateral,' it exaggerates the unity of finite self- hood and substitutes a supposititious entity for a description of fact, it loses sight of the truism that the state is more individual than any of its members, and it ignores the funda- mental canon of all true philosophy that nothing can be ^ W. K. Inge, ' Platonism and Human Immortality,' Aristotelian Society Proceeding}!, 1918-1919, p. 286, referring to Bosanquet (Proceediiu/K, 1917- 1918, pp. i8'2sqq.)., and to his criticism of the present writer. L. 12 178 THE MIND [ch. individual short of the whole. These are high matters and I must forbear to debate them at length. But I shall hazard a few reflections. If the cosmos be indeed a unity whose all-encompassing extent is welded in an indivisible harmony, its members may still have an individual office and themselves be worlds within a world. A monistic metaphysic, on this interpretation of monism, has room for Leibniz as well as for Spinoza, and neither 'good Platonists' nor good Hegelians should take sides on the question. No one claims, however, that mortal man can discern either the cosmos or its members in their fulness of harmonious being; and it should not be at all astonishing if some parts of the whole exhibit a greater degree of unity than other parts or than the whole itself. If conscious selves are the best examples of individuality that we know, neither monists nor pluralists should be surprised. The statement that anyone who believes in the reality of finite selfhood therefore considers the self a bare or repellent unit is a piece of scandalous sophistry. Nothing is repellent, or isolated, or shrunken, or dreary, simply because it is itself. A man does not lose his individuality by cooperating with others, or by sympathising with them, and those who worship 'organic unities' have no reason to draw this consequence from their beloved metaphor. Heart and brains and liver do not transfer their characters from one to another. On the contrary, a differentiated organism details its functions to specific organs. There is nothing in our theory to prevent the most strenuous belief in the impossibility of ' self-realisation ' apart from social influences, although, equally, there is nothing to compel this inference unless the facts prove it of themselves. It is the same with 'linear' and 'lateral' identity \ The ' lateral ' side of the self apparently consists of everything which personality touches, the lives of others, the fruits of the earth, and anything which a man's interests concern. If our view is correct, this ' lateral ' aspect of personality is no part of the person, but we certainly do not deny that we really have these interests and possessions and influence, or that our lives 1 Bosanquet, op. cit. p. 498. viii] THE MIND 179 may be spent in their service. A general does not cease to control his soldiers just because he and they are different beings, and those who know Pan and old Silvanus and the nymphs of the field do not therefore become part of the soil. We know enough of the self to be able to scan its main features, and to be justified in believing that the hidden mind is of a piece with the mind that is known. Indeed, we know what we are, sufficiently well to be much more confident of the reality of our conscious personality, as a finite discoverable thing, than of the reality of the transfigured selfhood which so many philosophies proclaim. We are not adjectives of the cosmos any more than a dog's tail is an adjective of a dog, and the characteristics which belong to us need not belong to the universe. And, as we have seen, we are not adjectives of the state, even if that institution, by some light-fingered subreption, is first of all identified with the community and thereafter with the Athenian 7roXtpiap, Opg.TTd rtj ififieXris Kal xa/'^«c<''a depawaivU avoaKQipai X^yerai. ws ra fikv fv ovpavw irpodvfj.oiTO eldivai, ra 5' ^ixirpoadev avrou Kal irapa 7r65aj \avdavoi avrbv. Taiirhv 5k dp/cet cTKCofifia iirl irdvTas 6(toi iv s(2. Clay, E. R. : on the specious present, 45 ?!. Clay, Henry: his definition of econ- omics, 191. Clearness : and attention, 166. Coleridge : on fancy and imagination, 60; an the images in Kubla Khan, 64 sq.; on ' esemplastic ' imagina- tion, '204. 'Complication': 24 8^., 40. Conrad: on imagination, 60«(;.; his word-painting, 210. Consciousness: and unconsciousness, 152 sq.; togetherness of, 153; and self -consciousness, 153 sq . , 169 sqq . ; its utility, 154 sqq. ; and nervous in- tegration, 155 sqq.; its functions, 157 sqq.; and psychology, 159; its nature, 160 ; and introspection, 162 ; and its objects, 162sqq.; and the brain, 173 ; its capacities, 173 sq. ; its 'generative activities,' 174 sg. ; its temporary annihilation, 176 s<7. 224 INDEX Construction: in memory, 51 sg . , 56*7. ; in the fancy, 74:sqq.; in logic, 91; of organising principles, 112 igqq. ; in probability and hypotheses, 182 .tqq.; and the theory of know- ledge, 201 sqq.; artistic, 205 sqq. Continuants: explained, 27 sqq.; and sign-facts, 36; relation to perception and judgment, 42; of common be- lief, 94 s(/.; in self-hood, 174. Continuity: a descriptive term, 26; spatio-temporal-causal, 94sqq.; of development, 152; of nerves and mind, 157 sq. ; and the identity of things, 176; and the intellect, 187. Continuum: thepresentational, 25x^7. Correspondence: in truth and error, 103. (See also • representation ' .) Cousin, V. : his Philosophie Ecossaise, 5.s(/. Croce : on history, 200. Dane,Clemence: on imagination, 205. Dating: of memories, 5i sq., 71 sq. Descartes: 3, 117. Development: of perception, 16, 25 sqq., 40 sq. ; and acquired mean- ing, 31; and evolution, 151 sq.; in history, 19S sqq. Dickens: Jeffrey on, 127; hismethods, 206*5-. Discovery: knowledge as, 14: in per- ception, 30877. ■> in memory, 51 S77.; in fancy, 69 S77. ; in belief 86 S77. ; of constructions, 81, 184, 202; and organisation, 113. Dreams: as presented fact, 61; and waking, 65, 68; and psycho- analysis, 75 sqq.; illusion in, 82. Economic theory of history : 198. Economics: type of knowledge in, 189 S77. Einstein: 93. Emergent: 157 S7. Empiricism: historical, 107 87. Error: 103 S7.; in perception, 41 .S7. Existence: and subsistence, 50, 109 sqq.; organisation of , 112 S77.; of mathematical facts, 116 S77. ; in- cluded in subsistence? 117 .S77.; non-spatial, non-temporal, 119; and value, 125, 144 S77. Expectation : primary and secondary, 49 «77. ; compared with memory, 53; scepticism concerning, 58; justification of, 100. Experience: 'pure,' 8S7. ; organisation of, 112 S77. Fabre: on beetles, 51; on pine-cater- pillars, 158. Fancy: and memory, 57, 69 .S77. ; and imagination, 6OS77., 192, 204 877.; general theory of (see images). Feeling: and judgment, 130, 133*77. ! moral, 137*77. ! nature of, 164 .S77. ; in economics, 192 «7.; in history, 200; in mysticism, 213 S77. Flaubert : his art, 201, 204, 207, 209. Flux : on economics and psychology, 191. Freeman : on the Norman Conquest, 195. Frege: on arithmetic, 120, 120?i. Freud : on association, 75. Galton: on images, 62. Gaunilo : on the ontological argument, 118, 118 7i. General facts : 105 S77. (and see prin- ciples). Geography: and history ; 197 «7. Givenness: in perception, 3I.S77.; overlooked by the 'new realists,' 164; in knowledge, 202*7. Grote, J.: on perception, 15. Green: on Synthesis and Eelating, 32. Hales, Stephen: and oxygen, 90 7i.; quoted, 188. Half-recollection: in association, 73. Hamilton, Sir W. : on the past, 49. Hegel : his Phenomenolgy, 8, 140, 214 ; on abstraction, 110; on reason and sense, 117, 120; his monism, 178; on the philosophy of history, 197*77. History : and knowledge, 181, 200 S7. ; and economics, 189, 193 ; and nar- rative, 193*77.; pictorial method in, 196 ; the philosophy of, 197 S77. Hume : criticised by Eeid, 2 S77. ; and by Beattie, 63; on images never sensed, 69; on 'judgment,' 83, 85*7.; on cause, 95*77.; ^^ exis- tence, 118 ; on morals, 138; parodied, 166. Hutcheson : on moral sentiment, 138. Huyghens : his scientific imagination, 183. Hypothesis : and realism, 182 S77. Idealism: and realism, 2, 13*7., 204*77.; Anglo-Hegelian, 9; inter- pretation of images, 61, 64, 73*7. ; on universals, 112 S77. ; on reason and sense, 117*77. > '^^ individuality and value, 145*77-; on mind as INDEX 225 Idealism (cont.) microcosm, 160 sq. ; on personality, 177»(/.; and monism, 179; scope of, 180 s