"SN- * in Tvv UCSB LIBRARY PICTURE LOGIC PRINTED BY SI'OTTISVVOODE AND CO., NEW-STREET SQUARE LONDON Frontispiece. Destrawney, after carefully perusing the following pages, masters the Man-eater Logic, and scares its foul offspring to flight from the bones of countless unhappy victims upon which they were wont to gloat and feed. PICTUEE LOGIC AN ATTEMPT TO POPULARISE THE SCIENCE OF REASONING BK THE COMBINATION OF HUMOROUS PICTURES WITH EXAMPLES OF Hl'ASONlNG TAKEN FROM DAILY LIFE ALFRED JAMES SWINBURNE, B.A. QUEEN'S COLLEGE, OXFOUD The Lion of Human Understanding in the tangle of Logical Knots assisted bv the Mouse of Illustration WITH ORIGINAL ILLUSTRATIONS FROM DRAWINGS BY THE AUTHOR ENRRAVED ON WOOD BY G. PEARSON FIFTH EDITION LONDON LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO. AND NEW YORK : 15 EAST 16* STREET 1887 All riuht* ret'reed INTEODUCTION. ii was at the beginning of a certain Long Vacation when my father sent for me and delivered himself of the follow- ing remarks : ' My son, your scores at cricket, your racquets, your prowess in the hunting-field and in your college steeple-chases, your numberless invitations and popularity, to you doubtless appear all that can be desired ; to me, Sir, they are nothing nay more they are even positively harmful, seeing that by their fascinating brightness men are blinded to all sense of their true interests and aim viz., to secure their degree as soon as possible with a view to a start in life.' Upon my replying to my father to the effect that every allowance was to be made for him as having left college five-and-twenty years if, as in the pre- sent instance, he manifested lamentable ignorance of the whole state of the University at the present day, and that his milk-and-water reading man would certainly be regarded with loathing and abhorrence by all ' our fellows ' and all the best men at Oxford, and consequently, sinking into ob- scurity, would be ruined for life, and upon my making many other similar assertions, my father, with much warmth, commanded me to be silent, and then asked me if I expected I was to live a life of slothful ease, because I was a rich man's son ; with several other questions which were not meant to be answered ; finally becoming so excited VI INTRODUCTION. as to refer me to his own university career, a subject which he quickly dropped, remembering how often he had told me stories of his undergraduate days before I was sent to col- lege. The result was that I was ordered to select a tutor for two months in the Long Vacation and pass my modera- tions in the following term, or for ever be condemned to the backless slippery heights of office stools. The awful thought of ' wasting my sweetness ' and withering in such a dry and uncongenial soil nerved me for a desperate effort. Of a restless and excitable disposition I was for some time after haunted by dreams of men with pens in their ears, and ledgers with columns of figures to add, so lofty that their bases were on the earth while their summits were lost in the clouds. I never could do mathematics not that 1 was quick at any work even my mother allowed this, for she wrote to my tutor for matriculation to the effect that 'our dear Douglas had manifested symptoms of future greatness, when a child, and still possessed remarkable ability, if it could only be drawn out ; but alas ! there was a want of application, especially in his mathematics.' I therefore determined to take up Logic as a substitute for Mathematics, and wrote to inform my tutor that I should only want help in this subject. He selected a charming spot on the north coast of Devon and we met there. He had one other pupil a very quiet youth and, as it seemed to me, very clever, my fear of whom was heightened con- siderably when I learnt that he had intended to try for a class, but, finding his books in a very imperfect state, was content with passing, though determined not to miss that. The awe with which this piece of information filled me I never succeeded in quite shaking off, though I liked him very much afterwards. He always seemed to me a sort of half-way house between Mr. Practical and myself the idea of any one knowing more than Mr. Practical was an idea INTRODUCTION, Tli that never for a moment entered iny heau Old Prac ' (as we called him afterwards) had such a smooth, comfort- able way of settling any difficulties I proposed so reassur- ing that I verily believe if he had told me that the best way to learn the art of diving and remaining under for a long time was to tie a heavy stone round your neck and get some one to push you in, I should have tried it. His last words the first night were ' Logic to-morrow.' It is needless to say my sleep was much disturbed that night with anticipations and forebodings. What was this new and strange study ? Had I not always heard men speak of its difficulty ? How if the momentous question, ' Was I possessed of a " turn " for Logic ? ' should be an- swered in the negative ; and I fell asleep to dream of mysterious figures, numbers, and symbols on the one hand pitted against the mocking forms of clerks, managers, and office boys on the other. CONTENTS. CHAPTKK PAGE INTRODUCTION ......... v I. WHAT is SCIENCE? 1 II. WHAT is ART? 14 III. LOGIC is A SCIENCE AND AN ART 21 IV. FORM AND MATTER OF THOUGHT 29 V. THE KECONCILIATION, AND AXSO HOW LOGIC is MORE OF A SCIENCE THAN AN ART 38 VI. LOGIC THE SCIENCE OF SCIENCES AND ART OF ARTS . 43 VII. THE BELATION OF LOGIC TO LANGUAGE . . . . 48 VIII. Aii THOUGHT is COMPARISON 53 IX. THE TERM 57 X. CONNOTATION AND DENOTATION 61 XI. PROPOSITIONS 70 XII. DISTRIBUTION OF TERMS IN A PROPOSITION . . .75 XIII HEADS OF PREDICABLF.S . 75 a X CONTENTS. CHAPTER PAGE XIV. DEFINITION 88 XV. DIVISION 96 XVI. INFERENCE 103 XVII. SYLLOGISM 113 XVIII. SYLLOGISM 123 XIX. SYLLOGISM CANON OF FIRST FIGURE REDUCTION . 128 XX. TRAINS OF REASONING SORITES 134 XXI. HYPOTHETICAL SYLLOGISMS 136 XXII. PROBABLE REASONING 142 XXIII. THE FALLACIES 146 APPENDIX A loo APPENDIX B 162 APPENDIX C 163 A LIST OF USEFUL FACTS IN LOGIC 177 LIST OF ILLUSTRATIONS. DKSTRAWNEY OVERCOMES THE SPHINX ' LOGIC* . Frontispiece NONPLUSSED 2 SCIENCE PRESERVED IN JARS > Tofacr 9 SUPERSTITION 11 THE BEGINNING OF SCIENCE 16 THE BEGINNING OF ART 17 ART 17 THE LOGICAL SAUSAGE MACHINE To face 35 TROJA FUIT 4.1 SlNDBAD AND THE SAILOR. . . ..... To face 4i) LOGIC PATS A VISIT 49 LOGIC IN TROUBLE 50 THE LOGICAL HAND 60 DENOTATIVE AND CONNOTATIVE HAND ..... 63 THE GREAT LOGIC BRANCH 73 'A WORD TO THE WISH' 78 THE ESSENCE OF MAN To face 86 xii LIST OF ILLUSTRATIONS. PA OB THE BIPED ANIMAL WHOSE SOLE METAL is MEMORY . . 9o THE FIUHT OF PROPOSITIONS . . . . . . ..110 DEATH OF THE UNIVERSAL . . . . . . . .11" THE SYLLOGISTIC ALP 114 THE FRONT OF A COLLAR 118 MOOD-HUNTING To face 126 PICTURE LOGIC. CHAPTEE 1. WHAT IS SCIENCE? NEXT morning Mr. Practical assumed a grave look and began : ' There is no lack of treatises on Logic, but there is a lack of people who understand them. It is the custom of Passmen to attempt to learn by heart a great deal of matter they do not in the least com- prehend, without attempting to realise the meaning, and so fixing it in the memory. A little understood is better than a volume learnt by heart. I shall not expect you to remember anything you do not under- stand ; nor shall I ever make use of instances other than those of everyday life ; and if my illustrations be too familiar to appear scientific, my excuse will be that I wish to bring home to you what I say, that you may realise and appreciate and so remember its meaning, as a man who has swum two miles, or been ill eight hours on a boat, has no difficulty in remem- bering the force of the expressions " long swim " or B 2 PICTURE LOGIC. " unpleasant cruise." The neat and concise phrases you meet with in your treatises on Logic are decep- tive like the ease of a good skater or runner, they are the results of hard work, and you might as well expect to get that ease at once without practice, as imagine that by learning off those phrases you have mastered Logic. Therefore, pass over all words and Nonplussed. instances that you do not understand as you read your treatises side by side with my attempts at ex- planation.' It would be difficult to express my sensation of relief at these words ; for already I had opened my new ' Elements of Logic,' and, flushed with hope, peeped at Chapter I. ; but, confronted by the very first word, * Psychology,' I felt as staggered and faint WHAT IS SCIENCE? 8 as when, burning to learn the noble art of self- defence, I put on the gloves with the noted Punisher, and he knocked me down the very first blow of the first lesson. * Courage,' I muttered, and pushing on, saw something about * analysing phenomena ' and their ' mutual relations ' and ' the mode of their generation ; ' and after this, I became unconscious, until I was aroused by a shout of breakfast, and found myself sitting staring blankly at my book with ideas of chemists, newspaper accounts of * a strange phenomenon,' aunts and cousins hopelessly com- plicated, and letters in the ' Field ' about the breed- ing of fowls, crowding in wild confusion across my mind. ' Tell me,' resumed my tutor, < what you mean by Logic, Dyver.' * Logic,' replied he, ' is the science and art of reasoning, or the science of the conditions upon which correct thinking depends, and the art of attaining to correct thinking, or the science of the formal laws of thought and other definitions might be given.' Observing my look of despair, Mr. Practical went on : ' Logic seems to be a science and an art, but if I asked you what is a serpent, and you replied "a reptile," this would be no answer if I did not know what " reptile " meant. " This is no answer, thou unfeeling man ! " the beginner might well exclaim, were I to rest content with defining Logic as the science and art of reasoning. If Logic is a science B 2 vell to aid the memory as much as possible by under- standing the derivation and meaning of the names you meet with.' 48 PICTURE LOGIC. CHAPTER VII. THE EELATION OP LOGIC TO LANGUAGE. NEXT day Mr. Practical was compelled to visit the metropolis, and after a brief explanation of the relation of Logic to language he took his departure, expressing a wish that we should both endeavour to illustrate his meaning during his absence. He told us that Logic was really connected with thought, but as it was impossible to get at thought (or at least at other men's thoughts) without the aid of language of some kind or other, Logic was so far connected with thought. The relation of Logic to thought he characterised as primary, while that of Logic to language was secondary. He also showed us how Logic had been held by some to be pri- marily connected with language, and so through errors arising from the inability of language to ex- press exactly what we think, Logic had fallen into disrepute. The remedy for such mistakes was the 'knowledge of more than one language. As an instance of such errors he gave us the notion that the copula implied existence, and promised to explain this farther. Dyver retired to his corner and I to THE KELATION OF LOGIC TO LANGUAGE. 49 mine, and on the following day we produced a couple of rough sketches. This was Dyver's relation of logic to language. Logic pays a Visit. Scene, a man's mouth. Thought peeping from the throat. Language telling Logic (who has come to visit Thought) that his orders are that no. one can see Thought, and that all communications must be made through him (Language). 'So you'd better by 'alf tell me what you want 'owever.' And Logic mutters, * What a coarse medium ! 50 But there is no help for it. and confusions will arise ! ' And this was mine. PICTUEE LOGIC. Alas ! what mistakes Logic in Trouble. A friend of mine, named Jones, who lived in lodgings, used to work with a tutor for Latin prose. Jones was in the habit of leaving his pro- ductions daily at his tutor's, and calling next morning to see the mistakes ; but as Jones was not an early riser his tutor would often step over to his lodgings, and leave the corrected prose with the people of the THE EELATION OF LOGIC TO LANGUAGE. 51 house, pointing out the faults, and begging them to point them out to Jones as soon as he appeared, for he was not yet to be seen. It so happened that the landlady's daughter was very attractive, and by some accident she always chanced to be at hand when Jones's tutor called. Scandal might have arisen from the protracted interviews in the course of which Jones's tutor pointed out to Jones's landlady's daugh- ter the defects in Jones's Latin composition, had it not been well known that the primary object for which the tutor came was not to converse with the damsel, but to instruct the pupil, and being unable to see the pupil, he was compelled to employ the aid of a third person as a medium. His relation to the pupil was, so to speak, primary, his relation to the landlady's daughter secondary. After a time, however, Jones left, but the tutor still continued his visits, and ended by marrying the landlady's daughter. So Logic, led away by the allurements of language, has sometimes neglected thought, the object with which it is primarily concerned, and has thereby become involved in troubles and mistakes, and has fallen into bad repute. Mr. Practical was highly pleased with both our illustrations, and added something to mine which I had not thought of. ' Had your unfortunate tutor,' he said, * moved more in society, and known several of the fair sex, and become more inured to their attractions, he would not, in all probability, have E 2 52 PICTUEE LOGIC. been led into a mesalliance, and in the same way had Logic been conversant with several languages, and become acquainted with their powers of mis- leading and beguiling, instead of only knowing one, Logic would not in all probability have been led into entering upon a relationship with Language which was likely to bring difficulties, error, and evil repute. 53 CHAPTER VIII. ALL THOUGHT IS COMPAEISON. ' WE have seen,' resumed Mr. Practical, that Logic has for its subject-matter thought. What is thought? To give a rough answer to this difficult question, we must say that " all thought is comparison." We have already spoken of thought as consisting of remarks and inferences, for we may consider thought as unexpressed in the mind, or expressed in lan- guage. But these remarks are compounded of two things, something about which we are speaking, and something that we affirm or deny of it. If I say " dogs are animals " I am speaking about " dogs," * and I say something about them " that they are animals." Thought may therefore be divided into three parts The term or concept ; the proposition or judgment ; and the inference or syllogism.' ' Do you mean by thought here the process of thinking or the results attained to ? ' asked Dyver. * I should say the results attained to ; of the faculties we shall speak hereafter, so that if we can show that the term, the proposition, and the infer- ence or syllogism are the results of comparison, we 54 PICTURE LOGIC. shall have proved that all thinking is comparison ; nor need you be alarmed, Destrawney, at any nice distinctions of the sort, for to pass your examination it is not necessary to notice them at all. Remember this : ' 1. The term or concept is anything we can see or imagine. Our minds are stocked with concepts or terms formed in our earliest years. How came they there ? Take an infant, hold a dog up to it, and the infant will recoil with a start of horror ; it has experienced a mere undefined sensation of the presence of something strange, and therefore terrible. .Repeat the operation daily, always taking care to accompany it with the word u bow-wow," and the child, from a comparison of the sensations, forms a concept, and associates these familiar sensations grouped into one idea with the name of " bow-wow," and if, after a time, you merely say " bow-wow," without introducing the dog, the child will manifest joy or terror according as it likes or dislikes the dog, proving that it has formed in its mind the concept or term dog, and can shut its eyes, so to speak, and see a dog though no dog is near. Thus, concepts are the results of the comparison of simple sensa- tions and concepts expressed are terms. We gradually accumulate our concepts and distinguish one from another. As infants we had only a few under which to arrange all the objects that met our view. Papa, moo-cow, gee-gee, and bow-bow formed our stock, ALL THOUGHT IS COMPARISON. 55 then, and under one or other of these heads caine every man and every animal we saw. Nor can we boast much now, for in botany, for instance, many of us have one vague concept, " plant," under which to arrange all the phenomena of that science, and in geology it is generally considered a sufficient reply to the question, " What is this ? " if we say " A kind of rock." * (2.) As the term or concept is a result of the comparison of simple sensations, so the proposition or judgment is a result of the comparison of terms or concepts, and henceforth we shall speak only of terms and propositions, having shown that they are identical with concepts and judgments. With pro- positions thought proper begins. It is true that terms are necessary to form propositions, but they do not by themselves constitute a thought. We cannot have a brace of birds without single birds ; but single birds do not by themselves constitute a brace. Suppose our infant to have formed several terms horse, book, house, sun, large, dry, tall, bright, &c. and never to attempt to couple them together, but simply to repeat them singly, we should at once question its sanity, as being unable to attain to a thought, for, as we have said, man has an innate tendency to group together the like, and this is the origin of thought. We should exclaim impatiently, " Horse, horse, horse ! What about it ? What is the use of going on repeating c5 PICTUEE LOGIC. house, house, house sun, sun, sun ? If you repeat them from your birth to your death you will not have expressed a thought ! " Thought begins when the child, having formed in one part, so to speak, of his mind a term for instance, book, derived from observations in his father's library, &c., and in another part another term, for instance, " nasty," derived from sensations of medicine, chastisement, &c., couples the two together, and exclaims " Books are nasty." Thus propositions are the results of a comparison of terms. * (3.) Lastly, the syllogism is a result of the comparison of two propositions. When the child upon being told to open its spelling book says " nasty," and further, upon being asked why he thinks the book nasty, replies " all books are nasty," he has given utterance to a syllogism which in its full form would read " All books are nasty ; this is a book ; therefore it is nasty." ' We have traced, then, the gradual formation of the term from sensations, the proposition from terms, and the syllogism from propositions ; and shown that they are all results of comparison ; and these are the three parts of thought ; they are also called (as we have seen) the forms of thought. 57 CHAPTER IX. THE TERM. ' As thought,' resumed Mr. Practical, ' is divided into term, proposition, inference, so Logic, or the science of thought, is divided into three parts, under the heads of TERM, PROPOSITION, and INFERENCE ; and you will find this analysis of the subject very useful. I. The term. 1. Definition of term and various kinds of terms. 2. Connotation and denotation of terms. II. The proposition. 1. Definition of proposition and various kinds of propositions. 2. The copula of a proposition. 3. Distribution of terms in a proposition. 4. Heads of predicables, or a list of the relations which the predicate of a proposition can bear to the subject. 6. Definition, or propositions expressing the connotation of ;i term. 6. Division, or propositions expressing the denotation of a term. ILL The inference or syllogism. 1 1 . Definition of inference and various kinds of inference. 2. Moods and figures. 3. Principles, laws, and canons of syllogism. 4. Reduction of syllogisms. 5. Trains of syllogisms. 6. Hypothetical syllogisms. 7. Probable reasoning. 8. The fallacies. 1 The third division, ' inference,' includes inductive inference as well as deductive inference, or the syllogism. But we are only now concerned with that part of inference called ' syllogism.' 58 PICTUEE LOGIC. If you learn this analysis and can give some account of each of the heads, your knowledge will be sufficient for the purpose in view. The analysis is taken from Mr. Fowler's " Deductive Logic," and I refer you to that work or to Mr. Jevons's " Logic " for information upon points that do not seem to require further explanation.' ' I hope,' said I, * you will not leave us too much to our own reading, for somehow or other things seem to me to be put so difficultly in books.' ' I will do my best,' he continued ; ' and first let us discuss the term. It comes from " terminus," or " boundary," because terms are the boundaries of pro- positions ; for a term is defined as anything that may stand as the subject or predicate of a proposition. If a term is to express anything we can see or imagine, it is clear that we must give an exhaustive account of all things if we wish to enumerate terms. Now everything that we can see or think of must be a thing or a quality of thing ; in other words, an individual or an attribute of an individual. Mention a few things, Destrawney.' ' A star, fair, whiteness, chair, Lexicon, beauty,' said I ; ( fun, William, suicide.' 'Every one of these is either an individual or thing, or an attribute or quality ; and you must con- tent yourselves with these expressions, as the question as to " What is the meaning of thing ? " is beyond the sphere of Logic.' THE TERM. 59 Dyver here took occasion to observe that he knew that individual meant something incapable of further division, i.e. a simple whole ; and that attri- butes meant the properties ascribed to such a whole, e.g., tree and greenness, or man and reason, for you couldn't saw the tree or the man asunder without destroying them, and greenness and reason were said to be attributes of tree and man, and ' thing ' and 1 quality ' meant the same as ' individual ' and * attribute.' ' Well, then, a term expresses either an indi- vidual or group of individuals, or an attribute or group of attributes ; and this is as much as to say that terms are an exhaustive enumeration of all that we can see or think of. Take your fingers and thumb, and remember the five terms thus : (See diagram on next page). " If a term expresses an individual it is a singular term, e.g., Socrates (thumb). If it expresses a group of individuals, it may either express the group and not each individual as well; or the group and each individual as well. Thus, the " BLACK WATCH " ex- presses a group of soldiers, but you can't call each soldier a " Black Watch ; " whereas " horse " ex- presses a group of animals, and you can call each of those animals a "horse." The former are called collective terms, e.g., " the Black Watch " (1st finger) ; the latter, common terms, e.g., horse (2nd finger). If a term expresses an attribute or group of attri- 60 PICTURE LOGIC. butes, it is called either abstract (3rd finger) or attributive (4th finger), the abstract term being a substantive, the attributive an adjective.' / % ~* p 3-X X* 1. Socrates. %> ,-^ 2. The Black Watch. r ^.%\ * 3. A horse. 1 /] %O * I m \ 4. Whiteness. J fi H I/// 5. White. N.B. The second finger the largest, and the common term the most important. The Logical Hand. ' Are there not several other kinds of terms ? ' asked Dyver. 4 Yes ; but it is my intention to work through our analysis first, and afterwards to explain briefly any names that may seem to interfere with the sim- plicity of our scheme of Logic.' 61 CHAPTEE X. CONNOTATION AND DENOTATION. * OP the five terms, the common term is that with which we shall have most to do. Let tis endeavour to explain connotation and denotation by taking a common term or class name as an instance. To the question "What is a man?" two answers may be given. Firstly, closing our eyes, we may give the attributes, the possession of which entitles a man to the name of a man saying, " by man is meant the combination of the attributes of life, reason, &c. ; " or secondly, walking to the window, we may point out Smith, Jones, &c. in the street and say, " Those are men." The first answer would give the connotation of man, the second the denotation. Do you follow ? ' ' No!' said I. ' Well, then, look at it thus: Every common term, or class name, is a name given to certain individuals upon their complying with certain conditions, so to speak. You walk in the fields with a friend. Tou speak of trees, men, stones, birds ; and your friend understands you to mean by them four distinct 62 PICTURE LOGIC. things. They all have attributes, and if those attri- butes were all the same, why should you not speak of them all four as " trees ? " ' ' But,' said I, ' their attributes are not the same ; at least, I do not feel my senses affected in the same way when I look at a stone and a tree.' ' Exactly so ! and these very attributes are what we mean by the connotation. With the origin of common terms we have nothing to do. All we know is that certain, class names or common terms exist, and that as fresh individuals present themselves we enroll them under one or other of these names according as they possess certain attributes, e.g., class man, attributes required for admittance rational and animal qualities. Any individual possessing these would be entitled to become a member of the class "man," and so "rational and animal qualities" are the connotation ; and Jones, Brown, Smith, Socrates, &c., are the denotation of the common term " man." Thus the connotation means the attributes in virtue of the possession of which an individual belongs to its class, and the denotation means the individuals which, in virtue of the possession of certain attributes, belong to a class. The connotation answers the question " what ?" and the denotation answers the question "which?" e.g., "What is a steam-ship?" a combination of the attributes of vessel with those of steam ; in other words, " a vessel propelled by steam." "Which are steam-ships?" The Great Eastern, CONNOTATION AND DENOTATION. 63 the Husband's boat, &c. ; or, again : last week when we went gull- shooting, I said, " Perhaps we shall get a puffin ; " and you asked, " What is a puffin ? " and I replied a bird with such and such attributes, with form, colour, flight, &c. (connotation). Soon after several flew over and I said, " Look ! there those are puffins" (denotation). The connotation of a term (under the name of intension] has been well de- fined as the qualities necessarily possessed by objects bearing the name, and the denotation (under the name of extension) as the objects to which the term may be applied. It has also been said that a term con- notes attributes and denotes individuals, and the five terms are thus said to be connotative or denotative. BOTH DENOTATIVE/ M l\ * CONNOTATIVE Denotative and Connotative HanO. 'The singular and collective have only denota- tion; the abstract and attributive only connotation; and the common terms, both. For the singular term is a mere mark arbitrarily imposed upon an indivi- dual, not in virtue of the possession of certain attri- t>4 PICTURE LOGIC. butes, but simply that we may be able to know it from its fellows. When our clergyman christened his boy " Harold " it was not because the boy mani- fested any peculiar attributes or qualities, but simply to distinguish him from his numerous brethren, so that (for instance) when they said " It was Harold who set fire to the barn," he might know which son to chastise. And what the singular term is to an individual, the collective is to a group of individuals a mere mark affixed arbitrarily, for the sake of convenience. ' The abstract and attributive express only attri- butes, and therefore cannot be denotative; though both are capable of being regarded as common terms ; for " redness " and " red " may be regarded as " red things," a class name or common term.' ' I can't quite understand the difference between singular and common terms with regard to connota- tion,' said I. * Take an instance. In my stables I keep a mare known as " Fanny," and a cow known as " Polly." One day I say to my man, " John, we'll change these names ; in future if men ask for their names, tell them the mare is called * Polly,' and the cow ' Fanny.' " Werry good, sir," says John. Next day I add, " John, a further change is necessary ; we will call the mare a cow and the cow a mare, and when men ask what they are, say this (the mare) is a cow and the other a mare." But CONNOTATION AND DENOTATION. 65 John stoutly refuses, and why 9 because the names "mare" and "cow" are common terms awarded to certain animals in virtue of their posses- sion of certain attributes, whereas singular terms are mere marks arbitrarily affixed. Thus common terms are connotative, as implying the possession of certain attributes, and denotative as pointing to certain in- dividuals, while singular terms are only denotative. 'You will see how the connotation of a common term increases as its denotation decreases, and vice versa ; for the more attributes required as a qualifi- cation for admission into a class, the fewer the individuals admitted.' ' Something like an examination which requires wide knowledge, or a club which is very exclusive,' I suggested, ' for the individuals who pass or are admitted are very few.' ' Quite so. Ask for a rose. The connotation is small : " a flower with certain peculiarities ; " the de- notation or individuals answering to that description very numerous. The common rose is plentiful. Then ask for a moss rose. The connotation is now larger. Candidates successful in the previous de- mand are now rejected as lacking the qualities im- plied by the word " moss ; " and so the denotation is smaller, and you may continue the process until you get your connotation so large that there is only one individual, perhaps, that can satisfy all requirements a prize plant and the property of a nobleman. F 66 PICTURE LOGIC. Take one more instance. You advertise in the " Field," " Wanted, a servant ; salary enormous. A. B., High. Street, Oxford." Next morning the whole High, from Carfax to Magdalen, is a seething mass of human beings. The Mayor is furious, and compels you to withdraw your advertise- ment. After a while you insert the advertisement again, only this time you write the word " male " before servant. Once more the High is in an uproar, and the Mayor interferes ; but the numbers are now reduced by about a half, though selection is still hopeless. Angry with your own thoughtless- ness, you determine to cut down still further the number of applicants by adding more qualifications, and eventually your advertisement reads, " Wanted, a male servant, good looking, active, honest, with a perfect knowledge of cooking and riding, who has been in a training stable, and is able to translate Livy and Virgil at sight, and to prepare all his master's lecture- work." People now understand why the salary is large, and upon looking from your window you see two men, or one, or none, to answer the advertisement. Thus the denotation dwindles as the connotation grows.' ' Are not these contrary processes to be seen in the growth of language,' asked Dyver, ' under the names of generalization and specialization ? ' * Yes ; and to remember which is which bear in mind the fact that it is from the denotation CONNOTATION AND DENOTATION. 67 the names are taken. The word " paper " (or papy- rus) originally meant " writing materials made of byblus ; " it gradually came to mean " writing mate- rial made of rags, straw, or anything." The deno- tation has thus grown by the admission of several other kinds of writing material ; and the connota- tion has diminished, for, at first, unless a candidate for the class " paper " (so to speak) could show that it possessed the attribute " made of byblus," it was not admitted ; whereas now the class has been thrown open, and anything that possesses the attri- butes of "writing material" is admitted. On the other hand, "physician" originally meant voint of mfu, THE ESSENCE OF MAN. HEADS OF PKEDICABLES. 87 subject. Man is an animal, is verbal. Man is white or black, real. Of the five heads of predicables, the first three form verbal propositions, the other two real propositions. * With regard to accidents, notice that they are of two kinds, separable and inseparable. " Some men are Europeans," is an inseparable accident. It is not a part of, nor does it follow from, the meaning of man (" rational animal") that he is a European, and so it is an accident ; at the same time it is an abid- ing attribute, so to speak, as compared with such an attribute as " Some men are ill, or eating, &c.," which is called a separable accident. So we talk of men as " inseparables " when they are always found together, though they are not obliged to be together, and man and wife might be called " separables " because to-day they live together and to-morrow they inav be divorced. 5 88 PICTUEE LOGIC. CHAPTER XIV. DEFINITION. ' You have now some idea of the signification of connotation, otherwise called intension, essence, or meaning. The proposition which expresses this connotation is called definition, as the proposition which expresses the denotation or extension is called division. It will be easy to follow now, if the idea of connotation is once grasped. Remember 1. What can't be defined. 2. All definition is incomplete in three ways. 3. All definition is relative. 4. All definition is " per genus et difFerentiam." 5. Rules of definition. ' 1. Singular and collective terms can't be defined. Why ? Definition gives connotation, and these two have none. You give your gardener wasps and ask him for the honey. He says they haven't any. So definition can't give you the connotation of singular and collective terms. Again, simple ideas can't be defined, for all definition is an unfolding, and you can't unfold what is already unfolded. So " thing DEFINITION. 89 or substance," the suinmum genus, can't be defined ; and so sweet, bitter, harsh, &c. " What is love ? " asks your iinsusceptible friend. " Oh, it's very nice, but I can't explain it," you reply. " You must feel it to understand it ; you'll know some day ; it's one of those things that nobody can define. To under- stand what ' sweet ' means, you must taste sugar." * 2. All definition is incomplete because (a) the connotation it gives is only a part of the attributes As we have seen, " man " has an infinite number of attributes, but those implied by " rational animal " are considered enough to represent the class. (6) Even the attributes thus given are not in their simplest form " rational " and " animal " are both capable of analysis (or breaking up into simpler elements). A being of another world may ask you, " What is man ? " and upon your replying " A rational animal," may go on "Yes, but what is * rational,' and what is ' animal ' ? Are not these also open to further explanation ? " and you would have to give a long explanation of both by help of Porphyry's tree. Thus a beggar at your door might receive a crust of bread, and depart grumbling at your charity as doubly incomplete First, because of all your luxuries you only gave him a crust ; and, secondly, because upon inspection even that crust turned out to be mouldy. So definition only gives us a few out of many attributes, and even those few are not in their simplest form, (c) All definition de- 90 PICTURE LOGIC. pends upon the existing state of our knowledge. Fresh discoveries upset old definitions. We talk of plants and animals as two distinct kingdoms, but the jelly fish looks very like a vegetable and certain flowers strongly resemble animals. How if they were discovered to be all one great kingdom instead of two ? All the definitions existing in the two king- doms would be bundled away and vanish as the coaches upon the invention of the rail. '3. All definition is relative. Relative (re-fero) means " has reference to something," and we have seen how the connotation depends upon the point of view you take. The prominent attributes, the " iin- portant-for-the-time-being " attributes are the con- notation, and the prominence depends upon the posi- tion of the spectator. So definition is relative has reference to the point of view, and there are as many definitions of a term as there are points of view from which it can be regarded, e.g., " good country." * 4. All definition is per genus et dijferentiam. If you are asked to define words in examination re- member this. Always make your genus, find your differentia, add the two, and you get genus + differ- entia = species = whole essence, connotation, inten- sion, or meaning : and this is what definition gives, for these four words mean the same. Ask yourself first, "What is it?" and then "What kind of it?"' DEFINITION. 91 ' But is it easy to get the genus and differentia ?' asked Dyver. ' I saw the words botany, monarchy, money, metal, college, in a paper how would you do them ? ' Never having dreamt of attempting to define difficult words like these, I was astonished at the simplicity of the process as then given. ' Nothing easier,' he replied. ' As a last resource you can always call everything " a thing;" e.g., a whip = a thing for driving ; a ship = a thing for going on the sea, and so on ; but you generally know some- thing more about the words, as here. Botany, quid? A science (genus). How different from other sciences? " Concerned with plants " (differentia) ; and hence the " quale quid, " or species, " A science concerned with plants " = whole essence = connotation; ergo this is the definition. So monarchy. Genus ? ' 1 Rule/ said Dyver. < What kind of rule?' ' The rule of one.' 'So money="a medium of exchange." Metal = "a substance hard and bright." College="a society of men formed for the pursuit of knowledge.' " 'May I try " barrister?" ' said I. ' By all means.' 'A barrister is a man, genus (answer to what?), and his differentia is " pleads at law," and so the species," a man who pleads at law." Would this do ? ' 92 PICTURE LOGIC. * Very well indeed.' You see now how definition gives the genus -f differentia (= species.) Description gives you the properties and accidents, e.g., " Man is able-to-do-Euclid," or " Man is a biped." ' ' But if the connotation shifts with the position of the spectator, surely the properties and accidents from one point of view are differentiae from another ? ' said Dyver. * Quite so ; before you begin to draw out your . genus, &c., you must determine your point of view. In the illustration above, the proposition "Man has a certain chest, posture, &c.," is an accident to the student who stands on the other side (so to speak), and to whom the " rational qualities" of man are the prominent ones ; while to the student who regards man as " an animal of certain chest, posture, &c.," the fact that " man is rational " is an accident. Hence the definitions of one science become the descriptions of another, for the definition = genus + differentia, and the description = accidents or pro- perties ; but the differentia becomes an accident or property if you change your science, i.e. your point of view, and so the definition becomes a description. Do you understand ? ' * Not clearly,' said I. 'You are in the train, sitting opposite a prob- able native of the country through which you are passing. You ask, " Is this good country here ? " DEFINITION. 93 He looks at you carefully in order to get some idea of your occupation in life, that he may know the point of view from which you regard things. You look like a farmer. He replies, " Crops is fair." You have a white necktie on. " Ah, sir, there's a deal of drinkin'. " Perhaps you carry a hunting crop. He says, " Not much covert, sir " ; or a mi- croscope with roots in your pockets, he says, " Beautiful flowers about ;" or, lastly, you may be a weary traveller, and he will reply, " Poor accommo- dation, sir." But should your appearance give him no clue, he will reply, " Well, sir, that dippends upon what you mean by country. Yer see, what would make one man call a country good would be quite secondary like to another man. It ain't essential like to the man as looks at country from a 'untin' point of view that there should be purty landscapes, 'owever, &c." In other words, given a class name (e.g., man) with an infinite number of attributes, the promi- nent attributes go to form the differentia, and all the rest of the round (so to speak) sinks into the secondary position of properties and accidents. Definition gives the former; description the latter. Change your point of view or science and your definitions become descriptions. *5. The rules of definition are not difficult to remember. (a) It must be essential (i.e. give the prominent attributes). 94 PICTUKE LOGIC. (&) It must be adequate (i.e. sufficient to dis- tinguish tke term from others). (c) It must not be obscurum per obscurius, i.e. explaining an unintelligible term by terms if anything more unintelligible still; as if to enlighten a rustic you defined the soul " as a species of eutelechy of a potential spiritual existence, my good man," or a flea thus : " A flea, madam, may be defined as an apterous hexa- pod." (d) It must not be "circulus in definiendo." You must not in your definition come round to the term defined, and use it again. You must not say, " Metal is a metallic substance." (e) No metaphors allowed. You must not define memory as " a storehouse of ideas." A metaphor is an image borrowed from one class of things and applied to another. When I speak of a lady '* sailing " through a ball-room, the image is borrowed from ships. Metaphors are apt to mislead. From the lady's " sailing " in a room we might be led to imagine she could float in deep water, and the experiment might drown her ; showing how dangerous meta- phors are. So Logic does not admit them into definitions. Remember these rules DEFINITION. 95 by the examples of their violation. " Man is a biped ;' " Man is an animal ; " " the soul j " " Metal ; ' "Memory," thus: 96 PICTUEE LOGIC. CHAPTER XV. DIVISION. * DIVISION gives the denotation of a term as defini- tion gives the connotation. As there were five heads under which to group all you need know about defi- nition, so there are four heads here. Only under- stand and you will find it easy to remember. 1. Various kinds of division. 2. Technical terms of division. 3. Division and dichotomy distinguished. 4. Rules of division. * 1. When you break a "plate" you divide it into parts, but each part is not a complete plate ; whereas if you divide " plates " into soup plates, salad plates, cheese plates, &c., each member of the divi- sion is called a plate still. So if you divide " man " into " arms, legs, &c." or into " Europeans, Africans, &c." The first kind of division is called partition or physical division ; the second, logical division. One divides wholes into parts, the other classes into classes. There is also metaphysical division or the process of making abstract terms.' 1 What are abstract terms ? ' asked Dy ver. * We have seen that the whole world around us DIVISION. 95 may be regarded as things and their qualities, or individuals and their attributes. As a master of fact we never see things and qualities apart. Every quality we know of is always found in connection with the thing which manifests it. We never see " red " or " white " apart from " red thing," " white thing." But by help of imagination we can picture to ourselves " red " and " white " in the abstract. Now an attribute viewed in connection with its indi- vidual (con-cresco) l is said to be " concrete " ; but viewed apart from its individual it is called "ab- stract " (abs traho), and the process of abstraction is called metaphysical division. So physical division divides wholes into parts, metaphysical separates individuals from attributes, and logical divides classes into classes. ' 2. The technical terms of division are the totuin divisum, the membra dividentia, and the fundamen- turn divisionis. The totum divisum is the whole class to be divided. As in definition you take the species and resolve it into its component genus and differentia ; so in division you take a genus, and by selecting some differentia or point of difference you find all the species that are included in the genus. The genus is then called the totum divisum ; the point of difference, or the ground or source of the 1 Concrescere = ' to grow with.' Abstrahere = ' to draw away.' So to speak, we draw away the green from the trees in bloom when we talk ot ' greenness' the green and the tree grew together. H 98 PICTUEE LOGIC. division, is called fundamentum divisionis ; and the species obtained the membra dividentia. Given the genus, "picture." Divide this. The question is " upon what principle ? What is to be our funda- mentum divisionis ? " Take as F. D. (fundamentum divisionis) " manner of frame," and your M. D. (mem- bra dividentia) become "pictures with gilt frames, pictures with wooden frames, pictures with all other frames ; " or, take as F. D. " material " and your M. D. become " pictures in oil, pictures in water- colour, pictures in all other material." Loosely speaking, definition may be said to break up the species into the genus and differentia of which it is composed, while division, by the addition of dif- ferentia, builds up the species out of its genus and differentia.' ' Please explain this further,' said I. * Given the common term, " guns." Divide this. You must select some point of difference if you want to find the species which form this genus " guns." Take as F. D. "manner of loading," and you get as your species or membra dividentia " breech-loading guns," " muzzle-loading guns ; " or, again, F. D. number of barrels, and M. D. " double barrels " and " single barrels." < T. D., houses ; F. D., " material ; " M. D., houses of brick, houses of stone, houses of all other material. ' T. D., horses ; F. D., " use ; " M. D., hunters, hacks, carriage horses, all other horses. 1 As there are as many definitions, so there are as DIVISION. 99 many divisions as there are points of view, for each fresh point of view will start a fresh F. D. or source of difference from which to form differentise. The ordinary observer divides " animals " into " rational and irrational," the moralist into " animals with a conscience and without," the zoologist into " animals with such and such teeth, breast, or posture," the tailor into " animals to be clothed and not to be clothed," and so on. Each is determined in his choice of an attribute to stand as F. D. by the point of view he takes. ' 3. Dichotomy is a kind of division. Dichotomy (Sifta Tfj.vG>) or the " cutting into two " always divides a genus into two species. It selects an F. D. and divides the class into one part that possesses an attribute implied and another part that does not, e.g., men : F. D. " nation," M. D. " Asiatics and not- Asiatics." It depends upon the law of excluded middle. It is more useful in matters of which we know little. We should not divide the kings of England by dichotomy into Norman and not-Nor- man, and not-Norman into Plantagenet and not- Plantagenet, &c., because we know all the names of the houses. But in dividing mysterious things like the " corns in a horse's foot," if we divided thus CORNS 1 1 ! Corns from Corns from Corns from nature bruises shoeing, H 2 100 PICTUEE LOGIC. a corn might appear which was due to none of these causes, and we should have no class to enroll this new-comer in. Whereas, if we had divided thus, CORNS I From Not from nature nature From Not from bruises bruises From Not from shoeing shoeing, the new comer would be immediately enrolled in the class of " not from shoeing," and our classification would not have been found wanting. ' 4. Learn by heart these rules : (a) Each M.. D. must be a common term. (6) The T. D. must be predicable of each M. D. (c) The M. D.s taken together must equal the T. D. or the division must be exhaustive. (I) There must be only one F. D. ' (&) Distinguishes logical from physical division. You can't say this piece of a plate is a plate, but you can say " soup-plates are plates." ' (c) The membra dividentia taken together must make up the whole genus divided, or the division will not be exhaustive, i.e. will not have exhausted DIVISION. 101 the number of species in the genus. Divide the cartridges in your pouch according to colour the membra dividentia are blue and green cartridges. After shooting away all the blue and green you find several yellow ones, and so your division was not exhaustive luckily, or your shooting must have ended. * (d) There must be only one F. D. or you have a cross division. You may have several F. D.s, but only one at a time. Thus (See pp. 67-69. ' The FIGTIEB lost scalene | triangle.') j j Curvilineal Eectilineal Triangle Quadrilateral Polygon (three-sided) (or four-sided) (or more than four-sided) I I Scalene Equilateral Isosceles (no sides equal) (three sides equal) (two sides equal) ; where subdivisions take place, and there are three different F. D.s in succession (nature of lines, number of sides, equality of sides), but only one at a time. A cross division would be to divide women into sisters of mercy, Americans, spinsters, and loud talkers, for in one division you have the F. D.'s " oc- cupation," " nation," " marriage," and " manner of speech." Eemember this : 102 PICTUEE LOGIC. ' " Your l M. D. is common, TeDious, exhaustive, but never cross," i.e. (1) The M. D. must be common terms. (2) Each. M. D. must be a T. D. (3) The division must be exhaustive (M. D. to- gether = T.D.). (4) No cross division (i.e. one F. D.). 1 ' It has been said that this is equally true -whether M. D. stands for Membra Dividentia, as above, or Membra Dividentes, i.e., Doctors. But Logic is only concerned with the former and less violent rending.' 103 CHAPTEE XVI. INFERENCE. ' WE have now arrived at the third head, Syllogism. Syllogism is a kind of inference. Inference, from in and fero, means "the bringing in of new truth," or the " bringing in" of the same truth in a new form (for some say that in a syllogism we bring in no new truth). Now we may " infer" from particulars to universals, or from universals to particulars. From " John is mortal, James is mortal," &c., we may infer that " All men are mortal ;" or from " No two straight lines can enclose a space," we may infer that these two ramrods cannot enclose a space. The first is called induction, the second deduction. Set- ting aside inductive Logic as beyond our limits, we subdivide deductive inference into immediate and mediate. Immediate where we deduce one proposi- tion directly from another, mediate where we do so not directly, but by the help of a middle term. Hence inference is thus divided : INFERENCE Inductive Deductive I I Immediate Mediate (opposition, conversion, (the syllogism), permutiition) 104 PICTUEE LOGIC. ' To begin with immediate inference, (i) Opposi- tion, where the truth or falsity of one proposition is inferred directly from the truth or falsity of another. The four forms A E I are opposed in various ways, and this you will remember by this figure : Contrary j "f> For the opposition of A and E is called contrary opposition 7 and is called sub-contrary opposition A and I or E and is called subaltern opposition A and OorE and Jis called contradictory opposition,, The only case in which we can always infer the truth or falsity of one proposition from another is contra- dictory opposition, and you need remember nothing more than the names of the rest. To prove an ad- versary's statement false, use contradictory opposi- tion. At first sight contrary opposition seems more powerful. If he says, for instance, " All Englishmen are black-bearded," you are strongly tempted to make a sweeping retort, "No Englishmen are black- JKFEKENCE. 105 bearded ; " but if you do so, as a man who makes too eager a lunge, you expose yourself, for he replies " Jones, Smith, &c., i.e. some Englishmen, are so," and he produces them. In the first instance you should have replied, " Some Englishmen are not black-bearded," and this would have refuted his statement.' ' How can you call it an opposition between / and (" Some men are maniacs" " Some men are not maniacs "), and still more between A and /and i/and (" All men are mortal " " Some men are mortal : " " No men are fishes " " Some men are not fishes ")' ? asked Dyver. * There is an opposition here, but only a very mild one,' he replied. * (ii) The inference called conversion makes the predicate the subject and the subject the predicate, and so gets a new proposition, e.g., " Some men are bold leapers " " Some bold leapers are men." * This change is sometimes dangerous. From " All our loveliest companions are women " it would be a grievous error to infer that " All women are our loveliest companions." Or from " All dogs are ani- mals that bite," that "All animals that bite are dogs," i.e. that there are no other "animals that bite" beside dogs. Here we must change the quantity, and say from " All men are animals " not " All animals are men " (for where would the bears be ?) ; but " Some animals are men." . Where no change of quantity 106 PICTURE LOGIC. takes place it is called " simple conversion ;" where a change takes place it is called " conversioper accidens." A propositions are converted per accidens ; E simply ; I simply ; not at all. There is one case, however, in which A converts simply when the subject and predicate are of the same size, so to speak, or co- extensive. Thus, "All men are rational animals " " All rational animals are men ;" but, as a rule, and unless you know that they are coextensive, convert A per accidens.' * But if you are asked to convert things like, " Talents are often misused, &c.," ' said Dyver. ' It is easy enough, if you will only remember to bring them to one of your four logical forms, A E 10, before you attempt to convert them, and then you know whether they are converted simply or per accidens: e.g., " Fixed stars are self-luminous." This proposition is not recognised by Logic except as an indefinite proposition. You must bring it to one of the recognised forms of Logic (A E I 0}. If you want it converted. Subject. Predicate. All fixed-stars are self-luminous. (A prop, per acciiens.) Some self-luminous are fixed-stars. i.e. Some self-luminous things are fixed stars. " No one is always happy." Logical form : No men are always-happy. (E prop, simply.) No always-happy are men. i.e. No things always happy are men. INFERENCE. 107 " Some of the most valuable books are seldom read." Logical form : Scme-(of)-the-most-valuable-books-are-seldom-read. (I prop, simply.) Some seldom-read are the-most-valuable-books. i.e. Some of the things seldom read are the most valuable books. " Every mistake is not culpable." Logical form : Some mistakes are not culpable. (0, not at all.) For it does not follow that " Some culpable things are not mistakes ; " nevertheless if you wish to con- vert an 0, you can change it to an I by saying, " Some mistakes are not-culpable " and then it converts simply.' * I understand these simple cases, ' said I, ' but how would you treat " He jests at scars who never felt a wound " ? ' ' Be careful about your subjects and predicates. Remember the test questions, " What am I talking of?" "What do I say about it?" What am I talking of here? " He-who-never-felt-a-wound " the subject ; and of him I say that he " jests at scars." It becomes then in logical form ; All who-never-felt-a-wound are people-who-jest-at-scars. An A proposition, which is converted per accidens, thus : Some people- who-j est-at-scars are those-who-never-felt-a- wound ; and this is obvious, for there are others who jest at scars (e.g., hardy men) besides those who never felt a wound. 108 PICTURE LOGIC. * Mistakes often arise from the predicate's position. Always ask yourself the test questions, and put your propositions into logical form before you attempt to convert them. Here is another. " No one is free who doth not command himself " = " No-men-who- do-not-command-themselves are free," an E pro- position converted simply. " Life every man holds dear " = " All life is a thing which every man holds dear," an A proposition per accidens. " Only the brave deserve the fair" = "No not-brave, &c." "Nothing is beautiful except truth" = "No not- truth, &c.," and " Every little makes a mickle " be- comes when converted " One of the things which make a mickle is every little." * (iii) Lastly, permutation (or immediate inference by privative conception) infers one proposition from another by changing the quality alone, e.g., All men are mortal, .'. No men are immortal. No cowards are good soldiers .'. All cowards are bad soldiers Some investments arc made with risk, .'. Some investments are not made without risk. Some investments are not made without risk, .'. Some investments are made with risk. And Mr. Jevons makes this very clear by diagrams, by help of which we might represent it thus : INFERENCE. 109 ' Where it is plain that no part of the included class man can be outside the class mortals : . . No men are immortal. ' No cowards are good soldiers ; they are two sepa- rate classes, and . . All cowards are not good (i.e. bad) soldiers. 1 Here the two classes overlap one another ; and, as some of the investments are things made with risk, it is clear that the part of investments which overlaps is not without the other circle, i.e. is not without risk, and the last case is clear by the same figure. ' N.B. These diagrams also serve to illustrate the two kinds of conversion. The first proves that from 110 PICTUEE LOGIC. " All men are mortals " you get " Some mortals are men ; " the second, that from " No cowards are good soldiers " you get " No good soldiers are cowards ; " and the third, that if " Some investments are things with risk," " Some things with risk are invest- ments ; " and that if " Some investments are not things with risk " you can infer nothing, for it does not follow that " Some things with risk are not in- vestments," for we happen to know that some things with risk are investments.' That night I had one of my Logic dreams. I thought I was walking through a fair. A man was shouting from a platform, ' This way for the real, live, strugglin' propositions ! He very kind of hopo- sition 'twixt them as differ in quantity or quality, or both ! ' I entered and saw all kinds of fights going on between things with small waists, like wasps. The Fight of Propositions. The spectators seemed to take very little interest in the fighting, except when, as every now and then it happened, a small animal engaged a large one and INFERENCE. Ill threw him and mortally wounded him. Then they shouted with delight. For the other combatants made a very poor fight of it. The man told me that what made them fight was that they differed in quantity or quality, or both. Suddenly, I heard shouts of * Contradictory, contradictory ! ' and, hurrying to the spot, saw one of these mortal fights. The smaller animal had ' Particular ' branded on its back, the larger * Universal.' The spectators ap- plauded loudly. Death of the Universal. Quitting this tent, I heard another man crying, * Come and see the operations ! ' I entered a kind of hospital ward. They were operating upon animals similar to those I had seen fighting. They kept cutting off their heads and their bodies, and sticking them on again ; the heads where the bodies were and o * the bodies where the heads were. They don't seem to feel it in the least,' I remarked to a bystander. * Ah ! said he, they be E's and I's ; wait till you see an A done.' Very soon an A did come, and they had a severe struggle to convert him (for they called the operation 'conversion '), and he lost so much blood in the operation, that they all cried, " What a quantity lost! Oh! what a quantity! " Certainly he looked 112 PICTURE LOGIC. much thinner after it, as if he had gone through . an accident (per accidens). Last came an animal that kept struggling so violently that the operator said, ' I hope I don't hurt you? ' and he replied, ' O, not at all ; ' at which the operator turned pale and let him go at once. After that they experimented on one of these animals to show that the addition of a negative to each end of them made no difference to them. They hung one up by his waist, like a pair of scales, and fastened something of equal weight to his head and his body, so that the balance remained as before. 'There,' said the operator, 'that's permutation change of quality alone.' At these words several of his audience looked puzzled; but when he added 'otherwise denominated immediate inference by pri- vative conception ' there was a wild rush to the door, and I was carried along with the panic-stricken crowd, and woke, repeating to myself, ' Opposition, quantity or quality, or both, conversion, subject and predicate, permutation, quality alone, and by this I remember them always.' 113 CHAPTEE XVII. SYLLOGISM. 'MEDIATE deductive inference, or syllogism, is the assertion of a third proposition in virtue of two other propositions. Some say that only inductive inference is entitled to the name of inference. We shall regard the syllogism as an inference for reasons we will afterwards state. Take the instance, " All men are mortal, Socrates is a man, .'. Socrates is mortal.'* 'Here there are three terms. Socrates, man, mortal. The term " man" occurs twice, for it is the middle term through which Socrates and mortal are compared. Hence the name " mediate infe- rence." ' Now there are three things to remember ahout the syllogism. (.4) The principle upon which it depends. (B) The rules which test its validity. (C) The canons of its figures. ' (A) The principle upon which all syllogisms de- pend is that " things which are equal to the same are I 114 PICTURE LOGIC. equal to one another." In the above instance the conclusion is " Socrates is mortal." Our object at starting was to establish a comparison between " Socrates " and " mortal." But it so happened that we could not bring those two terms directly toge- ther, and we employed the help of a third term. You ha.ve a station at the foot of the Alps on the north side, and another at the foot of the Alps on the south side. You can't make a tunnel. How do you effect a junction ? You must ascend to the summit, and from the summit you must descend. So to effect a junction between the terms " Socrates " and "mortal " you must take " man " as a middle term. Thus : The Syllogistic Alp. Here we are asked to establish a comparison between " Socrates " and " mortal." Unable to see SYLLOGISM. 115 through an intervening hill, we climb by ladder to the point man, and then we can see both " Socrates" and " mortal." From the conclusion, remember, we get our names. The predicate of the conclusion is the major term (for the predicate of a proposition is generally a larger class including the subject, as " mortal " is larger than Socrates), and the subject of the conclusion is called the minor term. Hence, major and minor premiss. The proposition which connects the major term and middle term is called the major premiss, and that which joins the minoi and middle terms is called the minor premiss. The former always comes first. Unless the principle that " things which are equal to the same are equal to one another " were true, it would not follow that " Socrates " and " mortal," which are equal to the same (" man "), would be equal to one another. ' (B) The rules of the syllogism. We now know that a syllogism consists of three propositions, con- taining amongst them three terms : minor, major, and middle. Out of the propositions A E I we can frame a large number of such triplets, e.g., " All animals can feel, all cats are animals, therefore all cats can feel," which would be all A propositions, or A A A ; " No angels are human, all women are human, therefore no women are angels," which would be E A E, &c.' * But would they all be true or valid ? ' I asked. t That we shall find out by the application of i 2 116 PICTUEE LOGIC. rules. First of all, Douglas, look carefully at the two syllogisms I have given you, and tell me if you see anything wherein they differ from one another.' ' To be sure/ said I ; ' one is about cats and the other about angels.' 4 True; but that is a difference of matter. What I want is a difference of form, and lest you should be tempted by the flesh of the propositions, so to speak, let us strip them of all but their bare bones ; let us employ ciphers that in Logic we may not be misled by the matter. Always use the same ciphers. A for 1 the major term, B the middle, and C the minor. Thus : A. A. A. All animals can feel \ All cats are animals = ( ! ) " Therefore all cats can ! feel . . j 'All Bis A All C is B /. All C is A (where B = animals, C = cats, A = things that feel.) E. A. E. No angels are human \ All women are human 1 .... Therefore no women f ^ ' are angels . .) No A is B All C is B .'. No C is A (where B = human ,, C = women, A = angels.p Now do vou see any difference between these two cipher syllogisms ? ' * Yes,' said I ; ' the propositions that compose them are different. In the first you have " all," " all," " all," and in the second k < no," " all," " no." ' * Precisely so, and syllogisms differing thus are said to differ in mood. The syllogism A A A differs in mood from E A E, and so moods mean the various aiTangements of propositions in syllogisms. But there is yet another difference.' 1 Do not confuse this A (MAJOR TERM) with Proposition A the first of the four A E I O. SYLLOGISM. 11? Neither of us could detect this until we were told to mark the position of B, or the middle term in the premisses, and then we saw that B was subject in the major premiss (top proposition) of syllogism (i), but predicate of major premiss of syllogism (ii). * Here, then, is another point in which these triplets of propositions, called syllogisms, may differ. And as syllogisms differ in mood according to the arrangement of their propositions, so they differ in figure according to the position of the middle term in those propositions. There can only be four figures. Where the middle term is subject in the major and predicate in the minor premiss, where it is predicate in both, where it is subject in both, and where it is predicate and subject ; e.g., take the mood A A A in all the four figures : A. All B is A A. All C is*B j- Fig. I. A. /. All C is A A. All A is A. AU C is IB (- Fig. II. A. /. AU C is A A. All B is A A. All b is C } Fig. III. A. /. All C is A A. All A JsJB A. All B is C f- Fig. IV. A. /. All C is A We know there can be only four figures ; the ques- tion is, how many moods can we have in those four figures. The four figures may be remembered by the front of a collar. 1 As to moods, it is clear that out of the four forms or propositions A E 1 a large number of different triplets can be made. We 1 See next page. The figures are thus easily remembered ;\||X these lines being taken from the position of the middle term as marked above. For further remarks upon the figures see Appendix A (i.). 118 PICTURE LOGIC. may have A A A in all the four figures, and A A E, A E E, and so on ; these will be all syllogisms, i.e. triplets of propositions comparing two terms through The Front of a Collar. a third ; but whether they will be all valid syllogisms is another question. Supposing we act upon the conclusion we get from a syllogism and fall into error, we should at once turn upon Logic and abuse it. But Logic does not warrant as valid every com- bination of the propositions AEIO in syllogistic triplets.' ' I don't quite understand,' said I. ' Take the mood A A A in the second figure, and tell me whether its conclusion is true : A. all A is B (fig. 2) A. all C is B A. /. all C is A.' * It seems right, as far as I can judge,' said I. * By this syllogism a man might pray for a dissolu- tion of his marriage on the ground that his wife was married to a crocodile ; for " All crocodiles are animals, All men a.re animals, Therefore all men are crocodiles." ' SYLLOGISM. 119 ' In this shape it certainly sounds wrong,' said I. ' Of course ; and there are many other of the pos- sible moods which will be found to be not valid in the same way. A mood not valid in one figure may be valid in another. There are sixty-four possible moods. How many of them can we admit into the four figures as valid syllogisms ? That all the moods are not valid in all the figures is clear from the above instance, where the mood A A A in the second figure is found to produce an unheard-of conclusion. By what test shall we try pretenders to the name of valid syllogisms? The answer is, by applying cer- tain rules to them ; and if they do not violate these rules, they are valid ; and if they do, they are not. These rules are eight. Do not be alarmed ; they are all eight wrapped up in four lines easily learnt. To explain these rules : ' (1) The middle term must be distributed at least once. For unless it be used in its full extent once, it may be used first for one part of itself, and second!)' for another part of itself; e.g. This whole figure represents the class " women ; " parts of this class are " cooks " and " queens." Hence : 120 PICTUEE LOGIC. All queens are women, All female cooks are women, . . all female cooks are queens. Had the middle term " women " been once used in its full extent, this false conclusion could not have been drawn. ' (2) You must only have three terms, otherwise the principle of the syllogism is violated, " things which are equal to the same" &c. An ambiguous middle term is the same as two terms, thus : All chests are boxes, Part of me is a chest, . . part of me is a box, where " chest " means " box " in the major premiss, and " breast " in the minor. ' (3) Two negative premisses prove nothing. For if we wish to compare two things through a third, and neither of these two things is connected with the third, we can draw no conclusion. From " Socrates is not an elephant," and " Pugilists are not ele- phants," I should be in no way helped as to the question whether Socrates was a pugilist or not. ' (4) Two particular premisses prove nothing. For they would be 0, 0, which violates (3), or I, I, which violates (1), or I, 0, which will be found to violate (5).' * (5) If either premiss be negative, the conclusion must be negative. For if, after taking our middle 1 For further explanation see Appendix A (ii.). SYLLOGISM. 121 term as a medium of comparison, we say that one of the two things to be compared is equal to the middle term and the other is not, it follows that the two things to be compared cannot be equal to one another. If we want to compare " Socrates " and " stone " through the medium " animal," we say " Socrates is animal, stone is not animal," and the conclusion must be negative, " . . Socrates is not stone." * (6) If either premiss be particular, the conclusion l must be particular. I will prove this rule afterwards. 1 ' (7) Let no term be distributed in the conclusion, unless it has been already distributed in the premisses. Otherwise we argue from part to whole. Violation of this rule, if it be in the case of the minor term, is called " illicit process of the minor," or, if it be in the case of the major term, " illicit process of the major." ' (8) Let not the conclusion, be negative, unless one 1 of the premisses is negative. For we could not say, " Socrates is not stone " as a conclusion, unless we had a " not " in one of our premisses ; e.g., "' Stone is not animal," " Socrates is animal." * ' Further explanation of these rules I do not think to be necessary, but you can find it in the books of Mr. Jevons or Mr. Fowler. For our purpose it will be enough to remember them by heart, and this you do by learning off these four hexameter lines : 1 For further explanation see Appendix A (ii.). 122 PICTUKE LOGIC. Distribuas medium, nee quartus terminus adsit, ( = Rules 1 and 2.) Utraque nee praemissa negans, nee particularis ; ( = Rules 3 and 4.) Sectetur part em conclusio deteriorem, ( = Rules 5 and 6.) Et non distribuat, nisi cum preemissa, negetve. 1 ( = Rules 7 and 8.) ( = unless when the premiss does so.) * How do you translate the third line ? ' asked Djver. ' " Let the conclusion follow the weaker part." The negative is thought "weaker" than the affirma- tive, and the particular than the universal. Thus this line conveys rules (5) and (6). And before pro- ceeding any further I must beg of you to learn these four lines by heart, in order that you may move amongst the syllogisms, armed, so to speak, with a test, whereby you may prove their validity, and dispel the false ones as evil spirits are dispelled by a charm.' 1 Thus rendered by some young lady friends : 'Distribute the middle, and have only three ; From two part, or neg. premisses proof cannot be; Conclusion with part, or neg. premiss must t>, A.nd be dist. or neg. only if premiss be so.' 123 CHAPTEE XVIII. SYLLOGISM. ' WE are now ready to encounter all moods in all figures ; and, by the help of our " Distribuas medium," &c., to admit the true, and reject the false. Take A A A in all four figures : Fig. i. A. All B.. is A A. All C 'is B A. /.AllCia A [Violates no rule. Call it "bArbArA."] Fig. ii. All A is : B All C is iB /. All C is A [Violates "Distribuas medium" for A props, do not dis- tribute their predicate. Ke- mcmber ASEBINOP. Call this " undistributed middle."] Fig. iii. A. All B is A A. All B is C A. /. All C is A [Violates " Et non distribuat nisi cum praemissa." C is distri- buted in conclusion but not in premiss (ASEBINOP). Call this "illicit process of the minor."] KB. For ASEBINOP refer back to the propositions," pages 75-78. Fig. iv. All A is.B AllBisC .'. All C is A [Illicit process of the minor, as in fig. iii. Kemember ASE- BINOP.] ! Distribution of terms in 124 PICTURE LOGIC. Take E A E in all four figures : Pig. i. Fig. ii. E. No B.is A No A is 3 A. All C is B All C is iB E. /. No C is A /. No C is A [Violates no rule. Call it [Violates no rule. Call it " cElArEnt."] " cEsArE."] Fig. iii. Fig. iv. E. No B is A No A is B A. All iB is C All B"is"c E. .'. No C is A /. No C is A [Illicit process of the minor. [Illicit process of the minor.] From part of C in premiss we argue to whole of C in con- clusion."] Thus, amongst these eight possible moods, we have found three valid ones Barbara, Celarent, and Cesare; and by going through all the possible moods (which you should do for practice), we should find the fol- lowing valid ones : Barbara, Celarent, Darii, Ferioque, prioris : (i.e. in fig. i.) Cesare, Camestres, Festino, Baroko, secunda: (i.e. in fig. ii.) Tertia, Darapti, Disarms, Datisi, Felapton (i.e. in fig. iii.) Bokardo, Ferison, habet: quarto, insuper addit Bramantip, Camenes, Dimaris, Fesapo, Fresison (i.e. in fig. iv.) These hexameter lines should be learnt by heart, as there is much contained in them.' * We have not yet seen what I have much desired to see,' said I * an illicit process of the major.' 1 A. All B is A All herrings are fishes E. No B is C or No herrings are mackerel E. .'. No C is A .*. No mackerel are fishes ; and if ever you have to examine arguments, put them first into ciphers, if possible, in fig. i. ; and then, by SYLLOGISM. 125 the help of " Distribuas," &c. and " ASEBINOP," you will quickly find their weak point. Thus, in the instance above, it is hard to find the flaw in the herring-shape, but in the cipher-shape ASEBINOP finds A undistributed in the major premiss, and dis- tributed in the conclusion ; i.e. an argument from part to whole.' * I have found a mood here,' said Dyver, * which seems right, and yet it isn't among that " Barbara, Celarent " lot ; it is A A I in fig. i.' ' You are quite right it is valid ; it is called " a subaltern mood." There are five of them ; they are really contained in the others. Thus A A I is con- tained in A A A ; for if I can get the conclusion, " all C is A," it contains the conclusion, " some C is A." If from the premisses " all cats are anknals, all animals can feel," I draw the conclusion " all cats can feel," much more can I draw the " weakened conclusion," " some cats can feel." That night I had a strange dream. I thought Mr. Practical told us he had four rooms which he wished to stock with certain specimens. The names of the rooms were ' Fig. i.,' ' Fig. ii.,' ' Fig. iii.,' and ' Fig. iv ' He gave Dyver a kind of hand fire-screen, with ' Distribuas medium,' &c. printed in large letters upon it. He gave me a stout staff, with Truth engraved on the handle, bidding me to knock on the head anything that Dyver could not repel without 126 PICTURE LOGIC. violence. Then, with minute instructions as to the kind of specimens we were to secure (' moods ' was their name), and as to the manner of capturing the right ones and getting rid of the wrong ones (for they were very like one another), and with no small delight on my part at the idea of a liberal use of my staff, and, lastly, accompanied by a keen-scented pointer named ( Asebinop,' we started before daylight, and made for the land of moods. Upon arriving there we saw hundreds of animals of a most wonderful description each looked like three gigantic wasps joined together one above another; and there was a perfect hurricane of ' ergos ' and * therefores,' which they kept hissing with human voices. Suddenly ' Asebinop ' pointed ; Dy ver grew pale, and I clutched my staff. Enveloped in a cloud of darkness, a huge Form loomed before us, and we heard a voice as of an irascible major in hot argument saying over and over again, 'All officers are exposed to temptations, no officers are saints, therefore no saints are exposed to tempta- tions.' A low growl from Asebinop, and the mood (for such it was) caught sight of him for the first time, and shuddered visibly. Meanwhile Dyver was holding up his screen persistently, and shouting out ' Dis-tribu|-as medi|-um, nec|,' &c., with painful stress on the scanning, without any effect, however, upon the monster, until he arrivel at the line ' Et non| distribujat nisi) cum pree),' &c., when the form uttered SYLLOGISM. 127 a cry of pain, and seemed unable to move, being fascinated by the screen. ' Now then, Douglas,' cried Dyver, and with a blow of my club I finished the illicit old wretch. After that we despatched an ' illicit minor J in the same way, and after that an ' undistributed middle.' This last was a horrid sight. It was rolling about in an agony of pain, and gasping out, f I must be right " all lotions are medicine," and "all potions are medicine;" so lotions and potions are the same ; and in swallowing iny lotion to cure this indigestion, T must have been right, but the pain is intense ! ' We heard afterwards that this mood had argued itself into swallowing poison to cure its indigestion. We owed much to ASEBINOP, though sometimes he took no notice of a mood ; but Dyver's distinct reading of the rules was a sure test always. We secured many valid specimens, and brought them home, and Mr. Practical read * Barbara, Celarent/ &c. over them like a roll-call ; and when each mood had answered to its name, he praised us highly for having found them all; and, bidding them retire to their several figures, wished them all ' good night,' and retired. 128 PICTURE LOGIC. CHAPTER XIX. SYLLOGISM CANON OP FIEST FIGUEE EEDUCTION. ' I CAN'T understand how you call a syllogism a uni- versal form of thought, when nobody ever speaks in syllogisms.' said I. * In ordinary writing or speaking,' replied Mr. Practical, * part of the full form is suppressed, and the order changed ; but to examine arguments it is always better to restore them to their full and ori- ginal form. These shortened forms are called " Enthymemes " (from h and 6v/j,6s, because part is suppressed, understood, or kept " in mind," but not expressed). You get three kinds of enthymeme by suppressing either the major premiss, or the minor, or the conclusion. You may say either, " Socrates is a man," .-. " Socrates is mortal," or "All men are mortal, .-. Socrates is mortal," or "All men are mortal, and Socrates is a man." The order of the first two in conversation would be " Socrates is mor- tal, because he is a man," and " Socrates is mortal, because all men are so." As to the last, its order would not be changed, and if you wish to see how quickly men supply the missing conclusion (which is " in the minds," sv Ovpols) go to the most illiterate SYLLOGISM. 129 costermonger and say, " All costermongers are scoundrels, and you are a costermonger," and ob- serve the result. We now pass to ' (C). The canon of the first figure. A giance at all the moods in the first figure shows us that they all agree in having a universal major premiss and an affirmative minor premiss. Hence what is called the canon or law of the first figure, (1) The major premiss must be universal. (2) The minor affirmative. ' There are also " canons " of the other figures. 1 but they are of less importance, and I refer you to other books for them. The use of this first figure canon is that by it we are enabled to be still more sure of the validity of the moods in the remaining figures. By a change that does not interfere willi their validity we can reduce moods of figs, ii., iii., and iv. to fig. i., when we can reassure ourselves as to their validity by applying to them the canon of the first figure. Take CESAEE (i.e. mood E AE in fig. ii.). E. No A is B ~| ^ e wan * to bring this mood in A. All C is IB I fig. ii. to a mood in fig. i., i.e. E. . . No C is A J we wan t to make the middle term come as subject, predicate, instead of predi- cate, predicate (for herein consists the difference of figure). Eemember conversion is our great instru- ment here. If in the major premiss " No A is B " we know by simple conversion that " No B is A," and the reduction is complete, we have * Appendix A (iii.). K 130 PICTUEE LOGIC. 1 E. No B is A A. AllCisB So the mood E A E in the se- cond figure becomes the mood E A E in the first figure, or Ce- sare becomes Celarent. Now apply our canon and we find it obeyed, and we thus have an additional proof of the validity of Cesare. Take FESAPO (i.e. E A in fig. iv.) : 1 E. No A is B 1 ^ e wan t the middle term (B), subject, predicate, in- stead of predicate, sub- ject. We must change both premisses. By simple conversion we make " No B is A," but we must not convert an A pro- position simply, we must employ conversion per acci- dens, and it becomes " Some C is B." We now have A. All B is C O. .'. Some C is not A E. No B is A I. Some C is B 0. . . Some C is not A Here the mood has changed as well as the figure, and FESAPO (or E A of the fourth) becomes FEEIO Apply the canon and you (or EIO of the first). will find it is obeyed. 1 Sometimes you have to change the premisses when you do so remember you change your major and minor terms. Take AEE of fig. ii. (Ca,mestres). A. All A is .B\^'No C is B No B is C E E. No C is 'B ^ \AllAifiiB { s tapiy, T^cT'M Ail ^ B A E. .'. No C is A .'NoCisA /. No A is C... E /. No C is A (by simple conversion.) Apply your canon and you will find it obeyed. 1 See note at the end of the chapter. SYLLOGISM. 131 ' Thus Camestres becomes Celarent. As you must have noticed, the first letter in each of these strange names in figs, ii., iii., iv. means that the mood when reduced becomes a mood which begins with the same letter in fig. i. The vowels of course mean the mood. The letter " s " after the vowel means " sim- ple conversion," and " p " per accidens in the process of reduction. " M " (mutation) means change the premisses, and " k " means " per impossible." All these facts might have been gathered from observa- tion and experiment, but it is a help to memory to learn them thus as well.' ' What does " per impossibile " mean ? asked Dyver.' ' Eeduction, as above exhibited, is called ostensive or simple reduction, but there are two moods, BAEOKO (second figure) and BOKAEDO (third figure), which are beyond the power of simple reduc- tion. The process by which they are proved to furnish us with true conclusions is as follows (and here you had better not attempt ciphers, but remem- ber these instances and that will be quite enough). If the conclusion they give is not true, it must be false. Assume it to be false, and work on the assumption till you are brought face to face with an obvious absurdity, and then retrace your steps saying, " After all our original conclusion was not false, but true." (i.) Take BAEOKO (A 00, fig. ii.). K 2 132 PICTURE LOGIC. A. All bantams are fowls, 0. Some birds are not fowls, O. .*. Some birds are not bantams. If I declared this conclusion to be un- true, an opponent might reply, "Very- well, assume it false, and you will find you get a new conclusion, which contradicts one of your premisses, which, of course, you start by assuming to be true." If " Some birds are not bantams " is false, its contra- dictory, " All birds are bantams " is true. Substitute this new truth for your original minor premiss, and you get All bantams are fowls, All birds are bantams, (from which two premisses it follows that) .-. All birds are fowls. ' But this new conclusion contradicts our old minor premiss " Some birds are not fowls," which we assumed to be true. Therefore we have come to an absurdity, as we must do in any case if we assume our first conclusion, " Some birds are not bantams," to be false. ' Therefore that first conclusion is true. < (ii). So with BOKARDO (0 A 0, fig. iii.). Only here you substitute your new truth for the original major premiss : 0. Some policemen are not fools, A. All policemen are in the Queen's service, 0. .'. Some of those who are in the Queen's ser- vice are not fools. SYLLOGISM. 133 The new truth here will be, " All in the Q. S. are fools." Substitute this for the original major, and we get All in the Q. S. are fools, All policemen are in the Q. S., . . All policemen are fools ; and this new conclusion is antagonistic to our old major premiss, " Some policemen are not fools," a contradiction. Therefore our original conclusion was not false but true. For by the law of excluded middle a thing must be either true or false, and if this conclusion isn't false it must be true.' Note. Putting words for the ciphers above we should reduce thus : E. No colliers can manage balloons, -| or fig. ii. may be A. All good aeronauts can manage balloons, I reduced to fig. i. E. /. No good aeronauts are colliers. J thus : E. No people who can manage balloons are colliers, A. All good aeronauts can manage balloons, R .'. No good aeronauts are colliers. E. No flirts are true women, -> or fig. iv. may be A. All true women are dear to men, > reduced to fig. i. 0. .'. Some of the things dear to men are not flirts. J thus : R No true women are flirts, 1. Some (i.e. one of the) things dear to men are true women, O. .'. Some of the things dear to men are not flirts. 134 PICTUEE LOGIC. CHAPTER XX. TRAINS OP REASONING SOBITES. ' SYLLOGISMS may be " heaped " one above another (po$, a heap) in a train of reasoning, called Sorites. 1 Thus : All A is B, All B is 0, All C is D, All D is E, .-. All A is E. ' This you may resolve into as many syllogisms as there are premisses between the first premiss and the conclusion. Always start with the second pre- miss and the rest is easy All B is C, All C is D, All D is E, All A is B, All A is C, All A is D, .-.All A is C. .-.All A is D. .-.All A is E. * These syllogisms are called pro-syllogisms or epi- syllogisms, according as you regard them as prior or subsequent to one another. There are two rules : (1) Only one premiss (the first) can be particular. (2) Only one premiss (the last) can be negative. 1 Appendix B. TRAINS OF REASONING. 135 ' For if (1) be violated, you will find when you expand your sorites into its full form that you have a particular major in the first figure (contrary to canon), and if (2) be violated you will find in the same way that you have a negative minor in the first figure (contrary to canon). ' [If asked (as possibly you might be) what is the regressive or Goclenian Sorites, remember it is the reverse of the above. Begin with the last premiss and write the train from last to first, and keep the old conclusion, e.g., All D is E, All is D, All B is C, AU A is B, .-. All A is E. * The rules are reversed, too ; only one premiss particular, the last ; only one negative, the first (the same propositions being negative and particular as before, you observe)].' * Would it be enough,' asked I, * if you were asked about the Goclenian Sorites to give a full description of the ordinary Sorites, and then finish up by saying, " Such is Sorites ; and the Goclenian is not this, but the reverse," leaving the examiners to draw upon their imaginations for your meaning.' ' It would be a great deal better than leaving the question out altogether,' he replied with a laugh. 136 PICTUKE LOGIC. CHAPTEE XXI. HYPOTHETICAL SYLLOGISMS. ' As jet our propositions have been only simple or categorical. There are propositions which link together a couple of simple propositions as simple propositions link together a couple of terms. These are called " complex or hypothetical propositions." " Hypothetical " means " with something put under or supposed " (VTTO ridrj^t, = sub-pono = suppose), or " with a condition." Your father says, " I'll give you a horse," that's one thing; but it is quite another thing if he says, " I'll give you a horse IF you pass your examination." The universal dislike of IF's is proverbial, for they make all the difference being the signs of " conditions." Now simple pro- positions may be linked together in two ways : first, where the truth of the consequent depends upon the truth of the antecedent (antecedent and consequent are the names of the two simple propositions when linked together; the first, the antecedent; the second, the consequent) ; and secondly, where the truth of the consequent depends upon the falsity of the antecedent. The first kind are called " conjunc- tive," e.g., " If the weather is rainy my sponge is HYPOTHETICAL SYLLOGISMS. 137 damp" (their sign is "if"). The second kind are called disjunctive, e.g., " Either Logic is deep or I am dull" (their sign is "either or"). Hence we may divide propositions in the following manner : PROPOSITIONS Complex or Simple or categorical hypothetical (of which we have | already spoken). i i Conjunctive Disjunctive. ' Now syllogisms are composed of these hypothe- tical propositions, and so borrow their names. We have conjunctive and disjunctive hypothetical syllo- gisms, i.e. syllogisms composed of such premisses. Cases where both premisses are hypothetical we shall discuss under " dilemma." For the present we shall consider cases where one premiss is hypothetical and one simple. * I. Conjunctive Hypothetical Syllogisms. These ad- mit of two valid conclusions out of the four possible ones you get by amrming and denying the antecedent and consequent. (a) If the weather is rainy, my sponge is damp. The weather is rainy, .. my sponge is damp. Amrming the antecedent for a minor premiss. (6) If the weather is rainy, my sponge is damp. The weather is not rainy. No conclusion. Denying the antecedent for a minor premiss.' 138 PICTUEE LOGIC. * Surely,' said I, ' it follows that " my sponge is not damp." ; ' No,' said he, ' for it may have fallen into the bath. Suppose I say " If the ' Brighteyes ' are going, I shall enjoy the ball;" it does not follow that if they do not go, I shall not enjoy the ball, for I may meet the " Lighttoes." ' ' (c) If the weather is rainy, my sponge is damp. My sponge is damp. No conclusion. Affirming the consequent for a minor premiss. For though it follows that my sponge is damp if the weather is wet, it does not follow that the weather is wet because my sponge is damp. If the wife weeps because the husband is condemned to death, does it follow that the husband is condemned to death because the wife weeps ? ' (d] If the weather is rainy, my sponge is damp. My sponge is not damp. .*. the weather is not rainy. Denying the consequent for the minor premiss. Thus the conjunctive hypothetical syllogism admits of two conclusions where you affirm the ante- cedent called " constructive," and where you deny the consequent called " destructive." II. Disjunctive Hypothetical Syllogisms admit of four conclusions, for you may affirm or deny ante- cedent and consequent. HYPOTHETICAL SYLLOGISMS. 139 e.g., (1) Either Logic is deep, or I am dull. Logic is deep. ..I am not dull. (2) Either Logic is deep, or I am dull. Logic is not deep. .. I am dull. (3) Either Logic is deep, or I am dull. I am dull. .-. Logic is not deep. (4) Either Logic is deep, or I am dull. I am not dull. .*. Logic is deep. * The dilemma is a combination of conjunctive and disjunctive premisses. As it is a difficult matter to understand, I should advise you to remember the three forms of it by their examples, and after your examination go more deeply into the theory of it as expounded in the books on Logic. There are : (i.) The simple 1 constructive / Instance: "Science." (ii.) The complex/ dilemma V Instance: "Politician." iii.) The destructive dilemma. Instance: " Jesting at Scripture." ' (i) The Simple Constructive Dilemma is of this form: If science lightens labour, it should be culti- vated ; and if science invigorates the faculties, it should be cultivated ; But science does one, or the other ; Therefore science should be cultivated. 140 PICTURE LOGIC. ' (ii) The Complex Constructive Dilemma is of this form : If a politician (who finds he is wrong) changes his views, he is inconsistent; and if he does not change them, he is not conscientious ; He must either change them or not change them ; Therefore he must be either inconsistent or not conscientious. ' (iii) The Destructive Dilemma is of this form : If a man were wise, he would not jest at Scrip- ture in fun ; and if he were good, he would not do so in earnest ; He must do it either in fun, or in earnest ; Therefore he must be either not wise or not good. These three (the substance of which is borrowed from Mr. Jevons's book) will be quite enough to show that you understand what dilemma means. A di- lemma may be rebutted thus : 1st Dilemma. " Do not enter into public affairs ; for if you say what is just, men will hate you; and if you say what is unjust, the gods will hate you. You must do one or the other ; therefore you must be hated by gods or by men." 2nd Dilemma. "Do enter into public affairs ; for if you say what is unjust, men will love you ; and if you say what is just, the gods will love you ; therefore you must be loved by gods or men." ' In the " Oxford Spectator " I saw a dilemma,' said I, * which seemed conclusive. How would you HYPOTHETICAL SYLLOGISMS. 141 rebut this : " Examinations are useless ; for if you know the questions already, they teach you nothing ; and if you do not know the questions, they teach you nothing; you must either know them or not know them ; therefore examinations are useless ? " To which Dyver replied, to my astonishment: * Examinations are useful ; for if we do know the questions, they teach us how to express our know- ledge ; and if we do not know the questions, they teach us what our weak points are (and it is not their fault if we do not remedy them) ; we must either know the questions or not know them ; there- fore examinations must he useful.' Mr. Practical expressed his approval, and I began to think that if Mr. Practical taught Dyver much more it would be a case of the young horse running away with the ' coach ' altogether. 142 PICTURE LOGIC. CHA.PTEE XXII. PEOBABLE REASONING. * HITHEETO we have spoken of syllogisms with strictly logical forms of propositions for their premisses, when the conclusions are certain. There are two kinds of reasoning which furnish us with conclusions not strictly certain, but of sufficient weight to in- fluence our actions in life self-infirmative, and self- confirmative inference. By help of such probable reasoning we are enabled to make syllogisms out of propositions with the sign "most'' or "many," instead of " all " or " some ; " and we can take into account the force of such words as " probably," without (as in strict Logic) thrusting them into the subject or predicate. ( (i.) Self-infirmative inference is where each fresh fact weakens the conclusion, so that the more pre- misses you have the less likely is it that the con- clusion will be true. " Never go out of doors in a severe frost," says the anxious mother, " because the Humane Society's men are obliged to drink." * But what has that to do with my " going out ? " you ask. PROBABLE REASONING. 143 * " You know," she replies, " some of those who go out in such times are tempted to skate, and some of those who skate break the ice, and some of those who break the ice are rescued by the Humane Society's men, and some of these men drink to keep themselves warm ; therefore, some of the men who venture out in a severe frost may have to be rescued by possibly intoxicated men." 1 You laugh at this argument, because every fresh premiss weakens the conclusion. So with the words " possibly," " probably," &c. * By this process you can argue that men with money are likely to commit suicide ; thus : Men with money probably invest it ; Men who invest probably speculate ; Men who speculate possibly lose all ; Men who lose all are probably pinched with poverty ; Men who are pinched with poverty probably despair ; Men who despair possibly commit suicide. .-. To this extent men with money are likely to commit suicide. The amount of the probability may be estimated to a fraction; but calculations of this sort seem to belong rather to mathematics than Logic.' . ' What a comfort ! ' I reflected. * (ii.) Self-confirmative inference is where each fresh fact strengthens the conclusion you wish to 144 PICTURE LOGIC. establish. It is called " circumstantial evidence/' or a " chain " or " coil " of evidence. Many verdicts are awarded in the Law Courts solely upon the strength of this evidence, which amounts in some cases almost to certainty. Each fact may be regarded as the minor premiss of a syllogism, with a probable major premiss and a probable conclusion. Given the assertion " That our cook gave the joint to a follower, when she said the dog ate it." It is required to prove this assertion by circumstantial evidence for nobody actually saw her give it. The evidence is as follows : " The dog was a remarkably well-behaved dog." " On the day of the mysterious disappearance the kitchen blinds were kept down." " Certain other articles (such as beer, tea, spirits, &c.), which dogs would not eat or drink, vanished during the same cookship," &c. Each of these facts becomes the premiss of a syllogism ; thus : I. Well-behaved dogs probably are innocent of a theft. This was a well-behaved dog. .-. The dog is probably innocent of the theft. II. The drawing of the blinds probably betokened the presence of a follower. The blinds were drawn. ..A follower was probably present. PEOBABLE REASONING. 145 Tf a follower was present, probably the dog is innocent of the theft. A follower was probably present. Therefore the dog is probably innocent of the theft. III. If tea, spirits, &c. disappeared also, the dog is probably innocent of the theft. Tea, spirits, &c. did disappear. Therefore the dog is probably innocent of the theft. Every syllogism has the same conclusion, you observe ; and every fact thus becomes a link in the chain of evidence. You may find instances for your- selves in the newspapers. This evidence is also called " Self-corroborative," from "robur," strength. * And here 1 may mention an exception to the rule " Ex duobus particularibus nihil sequitur," or "two particular premisses prove nothing" (Eule 4 of the Syllogistic Rules) ; for there is one case in the third figure where two particular premisses do prove Bomethinar; e.g., " Most pins are good ; Most pins are cheap. ..*. Some cheap things are good."' 146 PICTURE LOGIC. OHAPTEE XXIII. THE FALLACIES. * A FALLACY (fallo, to deceive) is an argument which seems to be true, but is really false. The fallacies have been classed under two heads : material (extra dictione) and formal (in dictione), i.e. fallacies arising from mistakes in the matter and the form. For the mistakes in matter Logic is not responsible (see "'Matter and Form of Thought"). But we shall adopt Mr. Fowler's arrangement. (N.B. Learn off this scheme, and read through the explanation that follows). I, Assumption of a false premiss. Achilles and the tortoise. II. Neglect of the laws of deductive inference. Illicit major. 1 ,, minor. Undistributed middle. Petitio principii (begging the question). HL Ignwatio elencki, or irrelevancy. Argumentum ad hominem...(" early rising "). t , populum.,.(" weeping wife"). baculum...(" religious persecution") 1 For several instances ot these see Appendix A (ii\ THE FALLACIES. IV. Ambiguity of language. Ambiguous (analogous, equivocal, &c.) words... (" box, muzzle, &c."). Composition and division... (" 3 and 2 odd and even "). Fallaciae accidentis [2]...(" mad dog's bite "). Paronymous terms... (" drunk once, drunk ever"). Fallacia pluriiim interrogationum...("Have you left off poaching yet ? "). Amphibolia, or amphibology... (" The duke yet lives that Henry shall depose"). Fallacy of accent... (" and they saddled him "). ' (I.) Is a mathematical difficulty, and strictly speaking is out of the sphere of Logic. A tortoise starts so many yards ahead of the fleet Achilles, and, according to mathematical calculations, Achilles never overtakes the tortoise. For when the tortoise has advanced a few yards, Achilles has gained so much that there is only half the distance between them, and presently only a quarter, and then one- eighth, and then one-sixteenth, and so on, the frac- tion becoming smaller and smaller, but never quite vanishing, so Achilles could never (according to this) catch the tortoise quite. The logicians in despair cried, " Solvitur ambulando," or " Walk it and see ; " a better answer would have been, " Logic has nothing to do with the complications and diffi- culties and errors of the matter." (See " Form and Matter of Thought"). 1 Under this head come all fallacies of the matter. * (II.) These have already been explained except the petitio principii. "Begging the question" is proving the conclusion you wish to establish by 1 P. 26 and p. 29. L 2 148 PICTUEE LOGIC. assuming that conclusion to be true before you have proved it to be true. There is the simple form of it. " A man is a man," says a lady. " Why ? prove it," say you. " Because he is a man," she retorts. It may be by a synonym (a like name). " The air is dry." " Why ? " " Because the atmosphere is dry." Under this head comes the " argument in a circle," for you move in circles when you prove your state- ments by making them your premisses as well as your conclusion, e.g., " Fire is hot, because it burns," says your lecturer, and presently, when asked, " But why does fire burn ? " he blandly replies, " Because it's hot, of course." In long speeches such argu- ments pass unnoticed, especially in a language like the English, compounded of Saxon, Norman, and Latin where there are so many different words all meaning the same forming excellent covert for fallacies of this kind to hide themselves in. ' III. Ignoratio elenchi, or irrelevancy, means ignorance of the exact point to be refuted. Your arguments are irrelevant when they miss the point to be assailed, and batter down some unoffending, innocent, unguarded point. Argumentum ad ho- minem misses the theory and assaults the man. Its object is to find a flaw, not in the theory advocated, but in the person advocating. When Mr. Gladstone advocated the theory of Disestablishment of the Irish Church opponents condemned the idea simply be- cause its holder "once thought differently," in other THE FALLACIES. 149 words, galloping by the fortified heights of the theory, they levelled their batteries at the weak flesh from whence it emanated. They made the inconsistency of the person a proof of the inefficiency of the measure. And so when a late riser speaks in glowing terms of early rising and its benefits, people laugh. The point to be assailed may be weak or strong, but the Logician must not swerve from that point.' ' But when a holder is attacked instead of his theory,' said Dyver, ' do we not often find that a man says one thing and does another, and ought \, e not rather to believe what he does than what he says ? ' * True ; but we cannot "practice what we preach." As a Logician you have only to ask, " Is the theory good or bad ? " and all questions of persons should be set aside. The argument " ad populum " appeals to the feelings rather than the judgment of an audience. When a prisoner at the bar brings his weeping wife and children to excite pity he is missing the point, so to speak ; for the point he ought to aim at is to prove his own innocence, the point he does aim at is to win their pity. The argument " ad baculum," declining to face the argument, lays hold upon the voice that pleads it, and by force compels it to hold its peace. It is the refutation of those who are strong of hand, but weak of head, for it crushes theories by brute force. Religious persecution is an instance.' 150 PICTURE LOGIC. ' That reminds me,' said I, ' of the fox and the serpent and the man. There was once a man who found a wounded serpent and put it into his bosom. And as soon as the serpent revived it bit the man's bosom. And the man called it an " ungrateful monster ; " upon which a long argument arose between the two as to whether the man or the ser- pent was the more ungrateful animal on the whole. Appeals were made to various animals (old cows, hunters, &c.) without any abatement of the hot dis- cussion, until the fox was consulted. " If you wish this fierce argument to come to an end," said the fox to the serpent, " be so good as to enter into this bag, and you will be so convinced that you will never utter another syllable." Upon the serpent's ready obedience, the fox tied up the neck of the bag, and handing it to the man said, " Stamp on him," and so the argument was ended.' Mr. Practical was highly pleased at this, and continued. ' IV. All fallacies arising from ambiguous use of language. Equivocal and analogous words are in- stances. Remember this any word may be used in one sense or more than one sense. If it is used in one sense, it is said to be univocally used, as " butter " (there are very few of these). If in more than one sense, there may be a connection between the several senses, or there may not. If there is, it is said to be analogously used, as " muzzle," in its three senses of " part of a gun," " part of a dog," " a gag " (all have THE FALLACIES. 151 something to do with the mouth). If there is not, it is said to be equivocally used, as box in its three senses of a " chest," a " tree," a " blow " (no con- nection between these). Hence ambiguous middles in syllogisms, as " The people here are the church ; the stones built up here are the church ; . . the people here are the stones built up here." * The fallacy of composition is arguing from what is true of things taken separately to what is true of things taken together; e.g., from " two and three are even and odd" to argue "five is odd and even." And division is the converse, from " five is odd " to argue "two and three are both odd." Or from " Jones and his wife were happy when single " to argue " Jones and his wife are happy together ; or from " Jones and his wife are miserable together " to argue that " Jones and his wife were miserable when single." ' The fallacies accidentis are two, (I) the argu- ment " a dicto simpliciter ad dictum secundum quid ; " (2) the argument " a dicto secundum quid ad dictum simpliciter." Which formidable expressions simply mean arguing from what is true as a general rule to what is true under particular circumstance, and from what is true under particular circumstances to what is true as a general rule. * Now as a general rule " it is a bad thing to cut off a man's arm," but under certain circumstances (bite of a mad dog, for instance) it is not bad. Ac- 152 PICTUEE LOGIC. cording to the first of the above fallacies, one would persist in saying, " Do not cut off his arm never mind what has happened do not cut it off, for it's a bad thing for a man to have his arm cut off." According to the second fallacy one would say, " Let us cut off all the arms of all men, for once upon a time I knew a man (who had been bitten by a mad dog) who gained great advantage from losing his arm." ' The fallacy of paronymous terms is exemplified when you say, " Job Turnips is a drunkard," because he has been once or twice drunk ; or " a thief,'* because he has once or twice stolen. ' The fallacia plurium interrogationum is the fal- lacy of risking two questions in one. For instance, take the question of a barrister examining a pri- soner : " Have you left off poaching yet ? " when the unfortunate man criminates himself by saying, " Lor' bles yer, yes, this six months or more." For the barrister asked him two questions in one : " Did you ever poach ? " and " Have you left off yet ? " mean- 'ng only to discover whether the man ever poached at all. ' The fallacy of amphibolia, or amphibology is a purely grammatical one, and is the name given to such doubtful passages as " The duke yet lives that Benry shall depose." Where you do not know whether it is the duke who shall depose Henry, or Eenry the duke. THE FALLACIES. 153 'The fallacy of accent is a mere matter of em- phasis. For instance, if you lay stress upon the pronoun " him " in the following words, " Saddle me the ass. And they saddled him," you convey a wrong impression. Lastly, there are two fallacies not mentioned in the scheme above ; that of " non-causa pro- causa " (as to say, " A comet shone, therefore there will be war "), where you take for a cause that which is not really so ; 1 and the fallacy of the con- sequent (fallacia consequentis or " non-sequitur ") , e.g., " he is an animal ; ergo he is a man." 1 This fallacy is the one referred to by the words, ' Post hoc, sed non propter hoc,' as the man said when he stumbled after partakiug freely of a well-known light wine. APPENDIX A. (i.) WITH regard to the four figures in the Syllogism remember that Fig. I. is most useful for the discovery or proof of pro- perties of a thing. Fig. II. is most useful for the discovery or proof of dis- tinctions between things. Fig. III. is most useful for the discovery or proof of instances or exceptions. Fig. IV. is most useful for the discovery or exclusion of the different species of a genus. (Lambert. ) And this is because : (1) Fig. I. can prove (i.e. have for its conclusion) A, E, I, or O. (2) Fig. II. can prove (i.e. have for its conclusion) E and O only (i.e. negatives only , for as in this figure the middle term is predicate (i.e. predicate in both premisses) unless one of the premisses were negative, the middle term would be undistributed. .*. One of the premisses must be negative. .'. The conclusion must be negative. (3) Fig. III. can prove (i.e. have for its conclusion) I or only (i.e. particulars only). 1 1 By working out the six moods in Fig. III. you will find an illicit minor in each case if you make the conclusion universal. For pr .ctice work them out. Ste Appendix A (iv.). 156 APPENDIX. (4) Fig. IV. proves E, I, 0, and is of little use because its work can be done more easily by Fig. I. N.B. From this it is plain that Fig. III. is the best for the purpose of overthrowing an adversary's conclusion, as it furnishes us with material for the establishment of a con- tradictory opposition (see p. 104). (ii.) There are three rules (4), (6), and (8), which require further explanations : Eule (4). ' Two particular premisses prove nothing.' I and O are the only forms of particular propositions. Two particular premisses must therefore be either I, I ; or O, O ; or I, O ; or O, I. Take these four combinations in all figures : Fig. i. I. Some B is A I. Some C is'fi No conclusion. Fig. ii. Some A is : B Some C is B No conclusion. Fig. iii. Some .B is A Some : B is C Fig. iv. Some A is B Some B is C No conclusion. | No conclusion. For by l ASEBINOP it is plain that the Middle Term (B) is not once distributed in any of these .'. There can be no conclusion. O. Some B, is not A 0. Some C is not'B No conclusion. Some A is not . B Some C is not : B No conclusion. Some ;B is not A Some : B is not C No conclusion. Some A is not B Some B'is cot C No conclusion. In all these there are two negative premisses, which give no conclusion (p. 130). I. Some B is A O. Some C is not"*B No conclusion. Some A is ;B Some C is not ;B No conclusion. Some ;B is A Some ; B is not C No conclusion. Some A is B Some B'' is not C No conclusion. In all these (by Rule (5) p. 130) the conclusion, if there be any, must be negative, and by Rule (6) particular. In all four figures it will be ' .*. Some C is not A. 1 1 For Asebinop, see pp. 78 and 126. It only means that an A prop, dis- tributes its subject, E both subji-ct and predicate, I neither, predicate. APPENDIX. 167 By ASEBINOP we know all four to be cuses of Illicit Major (p. 1245), i.e. the term A is used in its full sense in the conclusion, but only in a partial sense in the premisses and this is arguing from part to whole. 0. Some B is not A 1. Some C is B No conclusion. Some A is not j B Some C is ; B No conclusion. Some : B is not A Some : B is C No conclusion. Some A is not B Some B' is C No conclusion. For here we find that in figs. i. and iii. the Middle Term (B) is undistributed ; and in figs. ii. and iv. there will be an ' Illicit Major ' as above. N.B. ' No conclusion ' means ' No valid conclusion.' Rule (6). ' If either Premiss be particular, the conclusion must be particular.' For, so to speak, universal conclusions are expensive luxuries to their premisses ; premisses of small quantity can- not afford them. To keep up a universal conclusion both premisses must be at their full or universal stage in point of quantity, and any diminution at once tells sensibly upon their conclusion. Two universal premisses can sustain a universal conclusion ; but impoverish one of your premisses, without making a corresponding reduction in your conclusion, and you will find that Illicit Major or Minor has eaten away, like a canker, the truth of your Reasonings. This is best seen by going through all possible combinations of Particular and Universal Premisses (the combination of two particulars is by Rule (4) invalid): These are ,,,,,,. Of these (Q) and () are invalid by Rule (3), p. 120. We have now to show that none of the remaining six moods, or parts of moods, can have a universal conclusion (i.e. A or E) in any of the figures. 158 APPENDIX. Fig.i. A. All Bis A I. Some C is B All A is ;B Some C is ; B Pig. ill. All ;B is A Some 'B is C Fig. iv. All A is /B Some B'IS C Here in figs. ii. and iv. the middle is undistributed (ASEBINOP), and there is no conclusion. In figs. i. and iii. the conclusion cannot be E by .Rule (8) (which will be ex- plained below) ; and it cannot be A, or in both figures you would have Illicit Minor. Fig. i. A. All Bis A O. Some C is not B Fig. ii. All A is jB Some C is not B Fig. iii. All :B is A Some : B is not C Fig. iv. All A is B Some 15 i* not C In all these the conclusion, if universal at all, must be universal neg. (E) by Rule (5). Now supposing E to be the conclusion in each, we have in fig. i. Illicit Minor and Major together (ASEBINOP); in fig. ii. Illicit Minor; in fig. iii. Illicit Major ; and in fig. iv., the middle being undistributed, there can be no conclusion at all. I. Some B is A A. All C is B Some A is B All C is JB Some ;B is A All 'B is C Some A is B All B is C In all of these the conclusion, if universal at all, must be A by Rule (8). In figs. i. and ii. there are no conclusions at all, the middle being undistributed. In figs. iii. and iv. if the conclusion be A, you get illicit minors in both. O. Some B is not A A. All C is B Some A is not ;B All C is B Some :B is not A All te is C Some A is not B All B'is C Here in fig. i. there is no conclusion (undist. mid.). In the rest, the conclusion, if universal at all, must be E (Rule 5), which would involve, in fig. ii. Illicit Major ; in fig. iii. Illicit Minor ; in fig. iv. both together (ASEBINOP). E. No B is A I. Some C is'B No A is .B Some C is : B No ; B is A Some B is C No A is B Some B is C In all these the conclusion, if universal at all, must be E (Rule 5). This would involve an Illicit Minor in all four figures (ASEBINOP). APPENDIX. 159 I. Some B is A E. No C is B Some A is : B No C is : B Some B is A No ^B is C Some A isJB No B is C In all these, the conclusion, if universal at all, must be E (Rule 5). This would involve Illicit Major in all four figures (ASEBINOP). Eule (8). ' Let not the conclusion be negative unless one of the premisses is negative.' The necessity of this is evident from a consideration of the principle upon which all Syllogism depends. For in it two things are compared with one another through the medium of a third thing. The comparison of the 1st thing with the 3rd thing makes one premiss ; the comparison of the 2nd thing with the 3rd thing makes another premiss ; and the comparison of the 1st and 2nd thing which results is the conclusion. Now if this conclusion expresses dissimilitude, i.e. is negative, it is clear that in one or other of the premisses there must have been dissimilitude expressed before, else whence could this dissimilitude have sprung? for the conclu- sion is only a summary of what was contained in the premisses ; in other words, if the conclusion is negative (i.e. expresses dissimilitude between its subject and prsedicate) one of the premisses must have been negative before it. N.B. The following are instances in words as opposed to ciphers. Violations of (Rule 4) : ^ , Kg.i. ' Fishes fly ; fishes do not fly. I. Some fishes fly. This proves the futility of all - = J I. Some things that don't fly aie knowledge.' fishes. No conclusion. ' Lancashire is lovely, old \ ( Fig. U. women are lovely too. So Lan- [ j I- Some of Lancashire is lovely, cashire must be an old woman or | " j I. Some old women are lovely. Logic is untrue ! ' No conclusion. 160 APPENDIX. ' Inspectors are stern, and In- spectors are mild, at the same time and place. So "stern "and "mild" must be the same thing.' ' Some ladies must be addicted I to drink, for they are thirsty, and L thirsty people are often addicted to drink.' Some eagles have no wings ; ' for all birds are not eagles, and there are other winged things besides birds.' ' Silence and speech are the I same things ; for sometimes one is r not seemly, sometimes the other.' j ' Carpenters can't be hand- some, for tall men are often hand- some, and it isn't every carpenter that is tall.' ' Some cabmen are honest, for I all men can't be dishonest, and > . cabmen are men.' Violations of (Eule 6) : ' We must eat cook's children, for we eat cook's productions ; I dumplings are her productions, j and we eat them.' ' How wretched must all men under petticoat government be! For all henpecked men are under petticoat government, and how miserable are some henpecked men ! ' Fig. ill. I. Some inspectors are stern. I. Some inspectors are mild. No conclusion. Fig. iv. I. Some ladies are thirsty. I. Some thirsty people are addicted to drink. No conclusion. I Fig.i. J O. Some birds are not eagles. 1 0. Some winged things are not birds. I No conclusion. / Fig. ii. 0. Some silence is not seemly. ] 0. Some speech is not seemly. No conclusion. IFig. i. I. Some tall men are handsome. 0. Some carpenters are not tall men. No conclusion. I Fig. iii. j 0. Some men are not dishonest. j I. Some men are cabmen. \ No conclusion. i Fig.i. A. All dumplings are to be eaten. I. Some of cook's productions are dumplings. .'. All cook's productions must be eaten. Fig. iii. I. Some henpecked men are miser- able. A. All henpecked men are under petticoat government. .'. All under petticoat government are miserable. N.B. In both of these a particular conclusion would have passed as valid. APPENDIX. 161 fThe Major Premiss must be J universal. (in.) Rules of fag. 11. are s ~ ,. ., -r> . , ] One of the Premisses must be L negative. f The Minor Premiss must be fi". iii. < affirmative. ] The conclusion must be L particular. Fig. iv. can be more clearly arranged as fig. i. (iv.) The moods of fig. iii. are Darapti, Disarms, Datisi, Felapton, Bokardo, Ferison (see p. 124). A. All B is A. A. All B is C. I .. Some C is A. E. No B is A. A. All B is C. O. Some C is not A. I. Some B is A. A. All B is C. I. .'. Some C is A. O. Some B is not C. A. All B is C. O Some C is not A. A. All B is A. I. Some B is C. I. Some C is A. E. No B is A. I. Some B is C. 0. Some C is not A. In all of these a universal conclusion involves an ' illicit minor.' So the 3rd fig. only gives particular conclusions. Putting two of the above into words, we get : P All fishes live in the water. 53 All fishes can swim. j.*. Some of the things that can H swim live in the water. It would not be right to infer that ' all things that can swim live in tlie water,' for even swimming masters do not live there always. 2 Some persons can preach. x , It would be ^ ^ conclu(ie All persons think they can II tfaat a]J thc s that think lfa g. '.Some of thepersons that thmk " can can ^ 55 they can preacli, can preach .) \ 162 APPENDIX B. AN instance of Sorites would be : All fleas are animals. All animals sustain life by assimilating food. All that lives by assimilating food is liable to hunger All that is liable to hunger may be half famished. /. All fleas way be half famished. Here A = Fleas. B = Animals. C = ' Sustaining life by assimilating food.' D = ' Liable to hunger.' E = ' May be half famished.' And the Sorites may be resolved as in the .cipher-form 163 APPENDIX C. TURNING back to p. 103 we find inductive inference put aside. Induction or inductive inference starts from particulars and works towards universals. The process is fully explained under the heading 'What is Science?' (pp. 4 to 13; read carefully) for all science is inductive (p. 184, ' Method '). As deduction has its forms and rules (discovered by Logic), so induction has its forms and rules (discovered by Logic) ; and we have inductive as well as deductive logic. The mind of man is as carefully controlled in its journey (/ut'0ocioc) from the particular facts up to the universal laws, as it is in its journey from the universal law down to the particular facts. (See illustration, p. 45.) Let us consider : 1. Induction what it is. 2. The principles upon which induction ultimately depends, as deduction depends upon its principle, p. 113 (-4.). 1 3. The processes required for induction (observation and experiment). 4. The ' methods ' in Induction corresponding to the syllo- gistic laws in Deduction. 1 This principle of syllogism is founded on the three great laws upon which all deductive reasoning depends (Laws of Thought, p. 160). The principles of inductive inference are not founded upon these three self-evident axioms. Consequently we do not find the same cer- tainty about our conclusions in induction as we have in deduction. For the principles of the syllogism are laws, the violation of which is incon- ceivable, whereas the principles of induction are laws, whereof the violation is not inconceivable. For the principles of induction are generalisations from experience, and not like those of dtduction part of our nature, which we found but did not make. 11 2 1G4 APPENDIX. ( 1) Induction has been called an ' argument from the known to the unknown,' or ' generalisation from experience,' or 'inference from particular facts to universals.' (Pp. 4-13 give the process.) For by induction the old man ascends from the particular objects he lets fall to the universal laws of gravity. Most of the laws which deduction brings down to particular facts have been by induction raised from parti- cular facts beforehand. For induction precedes deduction except in cases where the laws were implanted in us by nature, and even then induction in a sense precedes ; for by it we find those implanted laws (though we do not make them) before we can bring them down to particular facts. Now, induction may be thus subdivided (starting with arguments from the known to the known, and Avorking towards arguments from the known to the unknown) l : Induction Perfect (or Improper.) Imperfect for Proper.) From known to known, 0-.<7- officers Traduction. (Solomon.) Colligation of Facts. (The Floods.) Parity of Reasoning. (Ab uno disce omnes.) Induction per sim- plicem enumera- tionem. (Swans.) Scientific Induction. (Flling Bodies.) army.) In arguing from particular facts to universal laws you may know all the particular facts or you may not. If I say all the officers in the British army weigh more than six stone. after having gone through the Army List, and caused each officer to be weighed, I am not in my calculation stating more 1 The four subdivisions of perfect induction are arranged according as they resemble more or less closely imperfect induction. Parity of reasoning might almost be called imperfect induction ; colligation is nearer than traduction ; traduction and ' from known to known ' are the pure cases of perfect induction. APPENDIX. 165 than I had already stated in my particular premisses. But supposing some of our officers were stationed in parts wheie j.iO means of weighing existed, and I persisted in my conclusion, then I should be slating something more in the conclusion than I had already stated in my particular premisses. Then there would be that ' leap in the dark ' which, according to some, takes away the certainty of induction and makes it im- perfect instead of perfect ; according to others, is the very ' soul ' of induction, and makes it proper, instead of improper, For if you know all your particulars, you gain in the cer- tainty of your conclusion while you lose in its originality (so to speak), for it only tells you what you already knew. Whereas if you do not know all the particulars, but under the impulse of what you do know hazard a conclusion for the rest, you gain in the originality of your conclusion, but you lose in its certainty ; for the particulars you never saw may be un- like those you did see, and this would upset your conclusion. If you read that each of the kings of England was above four years old when he began to reign, your conclusion to the effect that ' all the kings of England were above four years old when they began to reign,' teems with certainty, but lacks interest. But if, after enumerating your racing experiences, you come to the conclusion that ' all gentlemen of the turf are honourable men,' your conclusion, while teeming with origi- nality (and the bigger the leap the more pleasurable the sensation for we have as strong a tendency to jump with the mind as crickets and fleas with the body see pp. 6 and 10), lacks certainty. A merit and a fault, then, attach to each of these two cases ; where you do know all the parti- culars, and where you do not, and so two names have been given to each case, the former being called ' perfect induc- tion ' by those who valued its certainty, but ' improper ' by those who looked for something more in the conclusion than they already had in the premisses ; the latter being called 4 imperfect induction ' by those who looked for certainty, but 166 APPENDIX. proper ' by those who valued the fresh information given by a conclusion which did something more than re-echo the words of its premisses. For rich discoveries in science we are indebted to induction proper (or imperfect), but we must not forget the less brilliant aid of induction proper (or perfect). The ' leap in the dark ' like riding across unknown country, contrasted with trotting along roads has its dangers as well as its charms. Glorious discoveries, like that of the steam- engine, are doubtless the results of such a leap in induction proper, but how many a man has bitterly rued the day when, rejecting the safer argument, he chose the more brilliant one, and from the narrow premisses of his happy experience, ' This married man has peace and that and that, &c.,' leapt in the dark, cried ' all married men have peace,' and took him a wife ! Perfect (or improper] induction also includes traduction, or arguing from particulars to particulars, e.g., Solomon was the wisest man, Solomon was a married man, .*. the wisest man was a married man. Also Colligation of facts, closely resembling the argument from the known to the known as above described, only here our conclusion is a general conception or universal idea rather than a law. Kepler wished to find out the curve described by the planet Mars in its course. He marked all its particular positions, and, when the course was completed, ' read off,' so to speak, an ellipse from his marks. So a man when the floods are out at Oxford, after visiting every side of Oxford is enabled to say ' the floods surround Oxford.' Sup- posing he did not visit every side of Oxford, and still came to the same conclusion, his induction would be ' proper ' instead of ' improper.' Mr. Mill gives the instance of a sailor who views undiscovered land, and after sailing all round concludes that it is an island. Mr. Mill says this is no inference, for it ' brings in ' no new truth (p. 103). At all events it ' brings in ' truth in a new shape, and, as Dr. Whewell observes, the sailor who joins his disconnected observations in one universal APPENDIX. 167 idea, may be as truly said to ' bring in ' something new as the jeweller who strings together the pearls of a necklace ; the pearls were all there before, but the uniting thread is new. Lastly, there is the argument from parity of reasoning, e.g., the propositions of Euclid. We take a single instance of a triangle, and show that any two sides of it are together greater than the third, and from this single instance we lay it down as true of all triangles, that any two of their sides are greater than the third. In walking nobody denies that, ' cseteris paribus,' ' it is a short cut if you can cut off a corner. Now here we argue from the known to the unknown, for no one has seen all triangles, and yet there is such a strong likeness between all triangles, that in a sense we know all if we know one ; Ab uno disce omnes.' Hence there is so much certainty about this inference that it ranks as a perfect induction. Example (p. 180) to be a safe inference, must only deal with cases where a strong resemblance exists between the particular in- stances, as in geometrical figures. We now come to induction proper (or imperfect). This is an argument from the known to the unknown, as well as from the particular to the universal. ' This and that and the other swan all the swans we've seen or heard of (Socrates might have said) ' are white. .*. All swans are white.' ' This and that and the other body, when let fall, fall towards the earth, even though, from the revolutions of the earth, they have to fall upwards. .*. All bodies fly towards the earth.' ' This and that and the other application of fire to powder result in explosion. .*. All do.' And now to distinguish the two kinds of induction proper, notice that two of these conclusions are far more certain than the first. We know that black swans have 1 It would not be shorter if you had a broad river in the -way. ' Caeteris paribus ' means ' all other things being the same.' A good swimmer ewims a mile in shorter time than a bad swimmer, ' all other things being the same,' i.e. if they both have the same conditions of swimming. But ' caeteris ' not ' pari'uus,' or let one tow a boat and the other not, and the bad swimmer may win the prize. 168 APPENDIX. been discovered since the days of Socrates, but we feel con- vinced that bodies will fly towards the earth as long as the earth lasts, and explosions will follow the application of fire to powder as long as tire burns. The explanation of this differ- ence is the secret of scientific induction. For a long time men were content with inductio per simplicem enumerationem, i.e., with saying ' all the swans we know or have heard of are white. .*. All swans are white.' Scientific induction begins with a demand for something more reliable as a guide to our action, and this something is found in the test of what is called cause or causation. Does the swan depend upon his whiteness for being a swan ? Could he be a swan without being white ? Yes ; there are black swans. But could application of fire to powder be an appli- cation of fire to powder without an explosion? No, we should at once say, there is something wrong with the powder; it can't be true powder. To borrow Mr. Fowler's exhausted pump instance. A guinea and a feather in an exhausted air-pump fall in equal times. /. These and all other bodies will, under the same cir- cumstances, do likewise. (2) Now here is an inference grounded on two assump- tions. 1. That everything has a cause (law of causation ). 2. That like causes are followed by like effects 'Jaw of uniformity of nature). We know that in an exhausted air-pump there can be nothing to act upon this guinea and this feather unless it be the action of gravity, or that attraction to the centre of the earth which keeps all our feet upon the spinning globe though our heads may be downwards. We assume that everything has a cause. .*. This fall in equal times must be due to a cause, and the only cause present is the action of gravity. .*. The action of gravity is the cause of the fall. APPENDIX. 169 Again, before inferring that the case will be the same with a shilling, a watch-key, a marble, &c., we must assume that like causes (e.g., the action of gravity here) are followed by like effects (e.g., falls of shilling, watch-key, or marble). Hence, underlying every scientific induction are found these two assumptions or principles as already stated in a note (p. 163). Thus scientific induction, not content with a mere enu- meration of facts, founds upon the principle of causation some more reliable basis of operations. (3) Imagine man in the infancy of the sciences (cf. pp. 9, 10), face to face with a tangled web of hopelessly complicated phenomena; causes and effects mixed myriads together. His innate love of order prompts him to arrange, and group, and classify ; to put things together. He finds that some things always appear side by side, while others appear in succession, like always following like. As a student of scientific induc- tion he will confine his attention to the sequences rather than the co-existences, as likely to produce more certain laws. He Is not unarmed in this battle with nature. His instruments or weapons are observation and experiment. By the former he watches phenomena as they occur ; by the latter he changes their surroundings and sees what happens then. Thus observ- ation is natural ; experiment artificial. The astronomer ob- serves the movements of the stars and makes laws ; the botanist observes the growth of plants and makes laws ; and these laws are certain in proportion as they express the relations between cause and effect. But the plurality of causes (or the fact that the same effect may be produced by several causes, e.g., death by all kinds of things), and the intermixture of effects (or the fact that effects may be produced partly by one thing, partly by another, as water is produced by the mixture of two gases), baffle mere observation, and experiment is called in to ' isolate the phenomena,' as in the air-pump the action of gravity is isolated. By experiment we can produce in our laboratories 1 70 APPENDIX. the lightning in the shape of electrical sparks without the danger or difficulty of watching it in the storm. To find the effect of a given cause, experiment is better than observation ; but to find the cause of a given effect, observation is better than experiment. 1 It is easy to see that the more complicated the phenomena the more difficult it is to distribute and arrange right causes with right effects, and so to produce laws. In astronomy and geometry much has been done, and they are called deductive sciences because all their phenomena have been grouped and classified under a few simple laws. In chemistry (read care- fully pp. 12, 13), it is very hard to isolate the phenomena. In physiology it is still more so. To reduce human action to laws of cause and effect in a social science, 2 is a hopeless task for the same reason. The ancient philosophers not receiving from their fathers the results of previous observation and ex- periment as we do, unaided by all the triumphs of modern invention, were compelled either to give up the attempt of making laws altogether, or else to make theories and force the facts into subjection to them, and call these theories laws. Now hypotheses (see p. 182) are assumptions to explain phe- nomena but only assumptions, and they only become laws by standing the test of verification. Given the phenomena of movements of the sun, winds, and rivers. The ancients said 'a priori' (p. 185), 'things that more are living beings. These move. .'. These are living beings.' They spun out their theories and applied them to the facts, instead of starting with the facts and working upwards. As the spider spins his web, so they their theories out of themselves ; whereas they should have flown from fact to fact like the bee. ' Hypotheses non fingo,' cries a wise man. But hypotheses, like wine, must not be condemned because some people are intoxicated with them. 1 This is important. Think it out and illustrate it by instances from your own experience. 2 Statistics are ' observation systematised* for this purpose. APPENDIX. 171 Alany great discoveries have been preceded by several tenta- tive hypotheses, which would not stand the test of verification. Hypotheses are valuable enough if only subjected to impartial and rigid verification. The following summary of Mr. Fowler's rules should be remembered with regard to observation and experiment : 1. Precision. Exact time at which an event occurs should be noticed, &c. Hence all kinds of instruments watches, thermometers, dials, &c. 2. Waste no time with immaterial circumstances. Set aside everything which you know to have nothing to do with the effect you are trying to find the cause of ; e.g., if you're a doctor and see your patient is worse, don't ask him if he feels better. 3. Vary the circumstances of the phenomenon as much as possible. You do not feel well at Oxford. This is the phenomenon. You say to yourself, ' Probable cause wine.' But before you can be certain, you must take the same wine at several other places; e.g., Brighton, Scarborough, &c. ; and you will often find that the wine is not the cause, but the climate or some other thing. This rule especially applies to ob- servation. 1 4. Isolate the phenomenon. This is a rule for experiment. You bathe in sea-water. Your head aches afterwards. It may be the cold or the salt that is the cause of your pain. Isolate the cold by bathing in fresh water, and you will find out which it is. N.B. The word ' cause ' is loosely used for any of the cir- cumstances which precede a phenomenon. The phenomena (' any things that appear or can be observed by the senses ') which go to form that tangled web above described may be regarded, supposing their orderly arrangement to be completed, 1 Kemember these four by the word VIEW, v vary, i isolate, E exact, w 172 APPENDIX. as rows of soldiers one behind the other, each front rank to the row behind becoming a rear rank to the row in front in other words, each set of phenomena becoming antecedents to the set in front of them and consequents to the set behind. Often many antecedents combine to produce a consequent, and strictly speaking all these antecedents taken together are the cause of the effect. We speak of ' pulling the trigger ' as the cause of the explosion of a gun, but it is only the occasion or last cause. No explosion could have taken place, had it not been for the powder, the cap, the barrel, &c. All these are 'causally connected,' or ' part-causes of the effect.' A cause may be defined as a ' necessary and indispensable antecedent.' The above applies rather to physical or mechanical causes. Efficient causes are those where the movement starts, so to speak ; e.g., the movement of the steam-engine is caused by the revolution of the wheel, which is caused by the working ot the piston-rod, which is caused by the elasticity of the steam, which is caused by the water heated by fire, which is caused by the match applied by man. Now this last agent, man, might or might not have applied the match, but the rest of the causes had no choice about it. They passed on the impetus mechanically. They were physical causes. The man was an efficient cause. A great question the freedom of the will hinges upon this distinction. Whether man is the efficient or physical cause of his actions. If he is only a physical cause, a social science would be possible. (4) The Methods. ' Felix qui potuit rerum cognoscere causas.' Man rules by obeying nature. By finding what effects come from what causes, he can saddle those causes and bridle them (so to speak), and make them his beasts of burden. But he must study them carefully first, or they will crush him to atoms. Inductive logic provides him with these methods of experimental enquiry, as deductive logic gives him the rules of the syllogism. To make these methods clearer we shall give the examples first. APPENDIX. 173 I. The Method of Agreement. You are an inductive logi- cian. The savages of some new island come to you and beseech you to discover the cause of the madness which is raging amongst them. You tell them to bring you instances. They bring a dozen madmen. You find these men have several points in common ; they have all of them always been nervous, delicate, and worn with anxiety ; among other things they have all been bitten by a dog. You cannot isolate your phenomena you cannot separate the nervousness, &c., and the bite. You cannot be sure which is the cause of the mad- ness. You bid them bring you other instances of the same madness, but differing in everything else except that they have this madness. They bring all kinds of instances ; mad horses, mad squirrels, &c. ; and you find that the instances of the madness are so many and so vaiious that they may be said to have only one circumstance in common a bite ; in fact, the only thing you can say of them all is that they have been bitten by a dog. You conclude that the bite is the cause or the effect of the madness. But you know the bite came first, so it must be the cause. This put into formal language becomes : l ' If two or more instances of the phenomenon under investigation have only one circumstance in common, the circumstance in which all the instances agree is the cause or the effect of the given phenomenon.' Here phenomenon = madness ; instances = men, horses, squirrels, &c. ; circumstances in common = bite. The principle of this is that whatever can be cut out with- out affecting the phenomenon is not causally connected with it. II. The Method of Difference. You have two guns of precisely the same value and workmanship. One ' kicks,' 8 and the other does not. Your man tells you that the reason is that one's a badly made gun. But after a careful investigation 1 From Mr. Mill's Logic. * If you use this instance, for ' kick ' road ' recoil ' throughout. 174 APPENDIX. you find that the two guns, the kicker and the non-kicker, are precisely the same except in one thing have every cir- cumstance in common except one viz., that the non-kicker is cleaned daily and the kicker is not cleaned daily. You con- clude that the want o daily cleaning is the cause of the kick- ing of the gun. Put into formal language this becomes : ' If an instance in which the phenomenon under investi- gation occurs, and an instance in which it does not occur, have every circumstance in common save one, that one being pre- sent only in the former, the circumstance in which alone the two instances differ is the effect, or the cause, or an indispensable part of the cause, of that phenomenon.' Here the instance in which the phenomenon under investi- gation occurs is the ' kicking ' gun ; the instance in which it does not occur is the ' non-kicker;' the circumstance in which alone the two instances differ is the matter of cleaning; and the phe- nomenon is ' kicking.' The principle of this is that whatever cannot be cut out without affecting the phenomenon is causally connected with it. III. The Joint Method of Agreement and Difference. An officer who has seen much service finds that on certain days he is subject to twinges of rheumatism. Some of these days are fine, some wet, some cloudy, some clear, some in the sum- mer, some in the winter, some in the town, some in the country; in fact these days of suffering have only one circumstance in common an east wind. On the other hand the days when he feels no twinges are of all kinds also, they also differing in everything except one thing, i.e. having only one circumstance in common the absence of an east wind. The officer con- cludes that the east wind is the cause of the twinges. This put formally becomes : ' If two or more instances in which the phenomenon undi-r investigation occurs have only one circumstance in common, while two or more instances in which the phenomenon does not occur have nothing in common save the absence of that APPENDIX. 175 circumstance, the circumstance in which alone the two seta of instances differ is the effect or the cause or some indispensable part of the cause of that phenomenon.' Here the first set of instances are the wet, fine, cloudy, &c. days, with an east wind. The second set are the various days without an east wind. In the first set rheumatism (the phenomenon) occurs ; in the second it does not. The first set have only one thing in common an east wind ; the second set only one thing in common no east wind, IV. The Method of Concomitant Variations. I rub two sticks together ; the more I rub the hotter they grow, the less I rub the cooler they grow. Therefore the friction is the cause of the heat. 'Whatever phenomenon varies in any way whenever any other phenomenon varies in some particular way is either a cause or an effect of that phenomenon, or is connected with it through some fact of causation.' V. There is also a Method of Residues. ' Subduct from any phenomenon such part as is known by previous inductions to be the effect of certain antecedents, and the residue of the phenomenon is the effect of the remaining antecedents ; ' e.g., A man is taken seriously ill after bathing and oi-ertiring himself and drinking bad wine. Take away that part of his illness which is due to wine and the exhaustion, the residue is caused by the bathing. N.B. (i.) is the method for observation. (n.) is the method for experiment (the best of all the methods). (in.) for cases where you cannot isolate your phenomenon. (iv.) for cases where the causes are pei-manent. We c;m modify heat 1 or the action of gravity, but so long as we are in the world we cannot exclude them. 1 If we could banish the heat altogether, the sticks might be brought to that most useful method of difference. But many causes are perma- 176 APPENDIX. (v.) most fertile in unexpected results. Remember these methods by their instances. ' Even mad creatures recoil from twingey old officers hot as two sticks rubbed together, and seriously ill from various causes.' Or by the hexameter and pentameter : Agreement, difference, first apart, then taken together, Concomitant variations and a fifth Residues. FINIS. Note. The inductive syllogism runs as follows : This, that, and the other body fall to the ground. This, that, and the other body are all bodies. .*. All bodies fall to the ground. This form is true enough, if we know all the instances. (i.e. in perfect induction). In imperfect induction our minor premiss is faulty, and our conclusion therefore not quite certain. Archbishop Whately puts induction into a syllogism in Barbara by making a major premiss of the law of the uni- formity of nature. What | belongs to this, and that, and the other body | be- longs to all. Falling earthwards | belongs to this, that, and the other body.) .'. Falling earthwards belongs to all. Of course this is valid ; the uncertainty of imperfect in- duction is, however, latent in the major premiss, which is only a generalisation from experience. Perfect induction seems to possess the certainty of deduction. nent, and concomitant variations becomes a valuable method. The whole N.B. is important. 177 A LIST OF USEFUL FACTS IN LOGIC. ABSOLUTE terms (opposed to relative terms) mean terms which are ' loosed from ' (absolve) any connection with other tenns (e.g., water) ; whereas relative terms have reference to frefero), or suggest other terms (e.g., father [and son] husband [and wife]). The pairs are called correlatives. You can think oi ' water ' by itself ; but you can't think of ' father ' without also thinking of ' son.' A^AXOGY. 1 An argument whereby from similarity between any two objects in points known we argue to further resemblance in points unknown, e.g., moon and earth are two objects with known points of similarity (clouds, mountains, shape, &c.). The earth is inhabited ; by analogy it follows that the moon is inha- bited also. The value of analogy depends upon the number of points of resemblance known, as compared with the points of dif- ference known, or the points of which nothing is known : e.g. f given two men ; only known point of resemblance is ' both bar- risters.' One we know succeeds ; but it would be a weak argu- ment of an analogy to say .*. ' the other succeeds also.' But given two fast men, with very many points of resemblance. One we know repents in after life. It would be a strong argument of analogy to say, ' .*. the other repents.' A PRIORI. | (gee Method0 A POSTERIORI. J ARGUMENTUM AD JUDICIUM means ' an appeal to the common sense of mankind.' Argumentum ad ignorantiam, f an argument founded on the ignorance of adversaries.' Argumentum ad vere- cundiam, 'an appeal to our respect for some great authority.' Argumentum a concesso, ' a proof derived from a proposition already 1 For 'analogous, equivocal, and uni vocal' words see p. 150-1. N 178 PICTURE LOGIC. conceded.' Argumentum a fortiori,^ ' arguing that you are right in a case which is stronger and better than one in which you were already allowed to be right.' ATTRIBUTE (See Metaphysics). AXIOM. A proposition accepted on its own merits, so to speak, which does not require proving itself, but from which we can prove other proposi tions : e.g., ' The whole is greater than its part ' (See Empiricism). CATEGORIES. A list of ' summa genera ' (or ' highest classes ') given by Aristotle. Everything was said to belong to one or other of these genera, ' substance, quantity, quality, relation, action , passion, place, time, position, habit, or state.' CAUSE means that without which a thing could not exist. Thus, there are four causes ; remember them by a statue. Take away the stuff a statue is made of and there is no more statue ; the material is called the material cause. Take away the shape and you destroy the statue ; the shape or form = the formal cause. Let there be no maker, and the statue can't be made. The maker = the efficient cause. Let there be no aim or object in that maker's work, and the statue is a mass of confusion. The end or aim of the thing is its final cause. Hence there are four things without which a statue ceases to be a statue, and these are the four causes. CONCEPTION (See Faculties). CONCEPTUALIST (See Nominalist). CONTRADICTORY (See Terms). DIALECTIC. The art of discoursing. Also the old name of Logic. Several other meanings. DICTUM DE OMNI ET NULLO. This means to say that what is true of a class is true of each individual in the class. Now to those who hold that classes are merely the sum of individuals composing them, this assertion is a truism. But to those who hold that there is something more in a class than the mere list of its individuals, it becomes an important truth. DILEMMA. Remember the three instances of Dilemma thus : ' Science makes the Politician jest at Scripture (See Chapter on Hypothetical Syllogisms, p. 139). 1 EMPIRICAL (snirttpii, experience). Empirical knowledge is knowledge derived from experience. The knowledge of the old 1 E.g., even dogs can't digest nails, a fortiori dyspeptic invalids can't. A LIST OF USEFUL FACTS IN LOGIC. 179 huntsman, or the old sailor is often empirical. They know what to do in each particular case, not because they have any principles or laws to act upon, but simply because they have an instinctive inclination to act in a certain way under certain circumstances. ' What do you do if a squall strikes the sail the wrong side ? ' you ask your sailor friend. ' Well, Sir,' he replies, ' I don't know what I does I couldn't tell you but when the squall comes I does it quite natural/ He has no principles consciously elaborated from the observation of particular facts, his knowledge is purely ' empi- rical.' A famous dye was lost not long ago by the death of the man who mixed the colours. ' Tell us,' said his employers, ' the principles upon which you mix, that the dye may not perish when you die.' ' Alas,' replied he, ' I know not how I do it. I can mix it myself, but I could not show another person how to mix it. The principles upon which he acted, the ' why ' and the ' where- fore ' and the * how ' he knew not ; his knowledge was purely empirical. EMPIRICISM is the technical name given to the theory that all our principles or laws are derived from experience. All men allow that some are. Such laws as ' the sun rises daily ' are derived from experience or the observation of particular facts. But there are other laws which seem far deeper and more fundamental, such as ' The whole is greater than its part.' We can easily imagine a breach of the law, ' the sun rises daily ; ' but we can't imagine a part greater than its whole. Hence it is supposed that by nature certain laws are implanted in us to be apprehended by our reason and intellect, as particular facts are apprehended by our senses. Of this deep and fundamental character are the laws of thought. Nevertheless it is still true that in the science of thought we start with particulars ; for though the laws of thought already existed, we did not know them ; we found them, though we did not make them ; on our voynge of discovery we stalled with particulars and landed at laws (so to speak), though we did not make the laws any more than Columbus was making America when he started on hia voyage of discovery. Empiricism would maintain that we make all our laws as we make all our laws of nature ; e.g., the laws of tides, sun, wind, &c., whereas others would maintain that laws, whereof the breach is inconceivable, are part of our nature, and found rather than made. 180 PICTUKE LOGIC. EXAMPLE. Analogy takes two instances as its grormdwork. Induction takes more than two or several. Example takes one. By example we take one member of a class to represent the whole class, and argue from the individual to the class ; e.g., l Tyrants are cruel.' Why ? ' Because Pisistratus (a tyrant) was cruel,' i.e. : P. was cruel. P. was a tyrant. . * . all tyrants are cruel. The syntax of grammar abounds with instances. Care must be taken in this dangerous inference that the individual fairly repre- sents the class. EXPEKLMENTTTM CKTicis. 'An experiment which decides be- tween two rival theories, and shews which is to be adopted, as a finger-post shews which of the two roads is to be taken.' Crosses are often erected in Roman Catholic countries at the cross-roads, or places where two or three roads meet. Hence also ' a crucial instance,' one which at once shows you which of two contending theories you are to adopt. FACT. A word used in many senses, strictly means 'what is done or made.' Sometimes it is opposed to universal proposition, and sometimes to what is theoretical. Generally we speak of the facts of a case as the data (or ground, or material given), upon which we are to build up our inferences and theories. Facts would then mean all that is intuitively apprehended by sense or reason. And remember that at both ends of the domain of proof (traversed by the roads or paths called method) are ultimate and simple propositions which are called facts (see Method). FACULTIES OF THINKING. Sensation is the faculty by which we are conscious of the presence of anything, without knowing anything except that our senses are affected (e.g., child with dog, in ' Thought is Comparison '). When we are not only aware of the presence of a phenomenon, but also recognise it, we have at- tained to perception. Conception is the forming of concepts in the mind resulting from sensation and perception ; it employs imagi- A LIST OF USEFUL FACTS IN LOGIC. 181 nation (or the making of pictures or images in the mind). Generalization is a faculty by which we ascend to universals (ideas or propositions), which we apprehend by reason. By in- tuition, we know anything that we know without the aid of proof (see Method). FIGURE OP SPEECH. A fallacy, which comes under amphi- bolia e.g., ' When we run we tread heavily upon what we run on ; sometimes we run on empty stomachs ; . * . sometimes we tread heavily upon empty stomachs.' GENERALIZATION. (1.) Opposed to specialization (see Conno- tation of a Term). (2.) Either the process or the result of our innate tendency to gather and group the like with the like. GENERIC PROPERTY. ' That which belongs to the whole of a genus:' e.g., 'hunger' is a generic property of 'man,' because it belongs to all the other species that go to make up the genus ' animal ' to which the ' species ' man belongs. Whereas ' cooks his food ' is a specific property, for it belongs only to the species ' man.' Both are properties, for both follow from the connotation of man, ' rational animals.' GRAMMAR is the science which is concerned with language primarily, whereas logic is only concerned secondarily with language. The grammatical analysis of the sentence, ' She stoops to conquer,' is into pronouns, verbs, &c., &c., but the logical analysis is into subject copula predicate. For ideas and not words are the important things to logic. Also rhetoric, or the science and art of persuading, differs from logic. For rhetoric persuades, logic convinces. In rhetoric, a fallacy which escaped notice would be no flaw, whereas in logic all fallacies are flaws. Rhetoric appeals to the feelings, logic to the intellect ; and rhe- toric relies upon the warmth of sympathy, while logic only re- cognises the cold, calm intellect. Hence rhetoric is the more popular, but logic the more true. HYPOTHESES (or suppositions, VTTO rid ij jui, sub ponoi) are the con- jectures hazarded by men who seek to establish laws from the observation of particular tacts. If an hypothesis is right it becomes a law. I see several mad dogs at different times. I am anxious to establish a law as to the course of mad dogs. I hazard au 182 PICTURE LOGIC. hypothesis by saying, ' Happy thought ! mad dogs run in circles.' A neighbour acts upon this theory, gets bitten, and dies. I reject this false hypothesis and select others, hoping to find one that accounts for all the particulars. I end with ' The course of mad dogs is a straight line if possible,' and many of my neighbours are saved by attention to this hypothesis, which passes into a law, or valid induction, as soon as it is found to stand the test of appli- cation to particulars. So Kepler rejected about twenty hypothe- ses before he found the true one as to the orbit or course of the planets ; and the true hypothesis became at once a law. INDIVIDUAL. The name given to that which is incapable of logical division, being a single object, as opposed to a class or group of objects. INFERENCE. There are two kinds of immediate inference not yet mentioned, (i.) Inference by added determinants, which is of this form: 'The horse is a beast; .'.the noble horse is a noble beast.' Care must be taken, for from ' The mouse is an animal ' it does not follow that 'A huge mouse is a huge animal.' (ii.) Inference by complex conception of the form : ' The horse is a beast;. '.the stride of the horse is the stride of a beast.' Care must be taken here also, for from 'Misers are men,' it does not follow that ' The most liberal of misers are the most liberal of men.' INTENTION (for Intension see Connotation of Terms). A word is said to be of the first intention when it is the name of a thing ; of the second intention when it is the name of the name of a thing. Thus, man, animal, &c., are names of things, while species, genus, &c., are the names we give to these names of things. "We call 'animal' the 'genus,' 'man' the 'species,' and thus we name again (second intention) what were already the names (first intention) of things. LAWS or THOUGHT. The three great laws upon which all thinking is found ultimately to depend are : I. The law of identity. Whatever is, is. This we assume in every syllogism, for if one premiss changed while we were ex- amining the other no conclusion could be drawn. In the old instance, when I seek to establish a connection between ' Socrates ' and ' mortal,' after asserting ' Socrates is a man,' I may (so to speak) turn my back upon ' Socrates ' in my attempt to find out A LIST OF USEFUL FACTS IN LOGIC. 183 how 'man and mortal ' stand to one another, intending to return to ' Socrates ' as soon as I have found this out If ' Socrates ' changes while my back is turned, what conclusion can I draw ? 3n the contrary, by this law I know that if he is mortal he is, and I need not fear to leave that premiss while I busy myself with the other. II. The law of contradiction. 'A. thing cannot both be and not be.' A man can't be both tall and not tall at the same time. Of course, ' not tall ' means everything that isn't called ' tall,' or you might say ' he is of middle height \(which really means he is not tall). Upon this law, remember, opposition is based. Con- tradictory opposition would be powerless without this law. So also would reduction ' per impossible.' (See Reduction of Figures, p. 133.) III. The laio of excludtd middle, or that which excludes a middle state. ' A thing must either be or not be.' Upon this law depends dichotomy. (See Division.) N.B. Keep distinct ideas of the laws of thought, the principle of the syllogism, the rules of the syllogism, and the canons of the figures. METAPHYSICS. We divided all the universe into two parts. The ego, or person observing (subjective), and the non-ego, or ob- jects observed (objective). We spoke of the attributes of these objects, as though each object was a something underlying its at- tributes, as our own souls and wills underlie our actions. To that underlying something (which we can't see, but imagine to be at the root of those attributes, as our own ' selves ' are at the root of our actions) is given the name of noumenon (yovptvov, the thinking part), or substance as opposed to phenomenon* (the part seen), or attribute. This mysterious something, this substratum, baffles all human powers of search. We think it lies somewhere behind the attributes, so we carefully remove the attributes one after another, and, wonderful to tell, when all the attributes are removed, there is nothing left at all ! e.g., a tree take away all its attributes, ' shape, height, size, hardness,' &c., and you have nothing left. Still (by analogy from ourselves) we speak and think of objects as substance underlying attributes. Now, the science which is conversant with these inscrutable substances is metaphysics, or ontology. NOMINALISTS, REALISTS, CONCEPTTTALISTS. We saw that after a time the infant would start at the name of ' dog ' without the , I show mysel 184 PICTURE LOGIC. presence of a dog. Imagination enables us to picture to ourselves 4 a dog ' which is not this or that dog, but simply a specimen pos- sessing the necessary attributes and no more. Now, with regard to this perfect specimen, this type dog, with all the essential but none of the accidental qualities of ' dog,' the realist holds that it actually exists (though out of our view) as a model or pattern after which all dogs are fashioned, but to the perfection of which type canine frailty cannot attain. The conceptualist says, ' Yes, it exists, but only in our minds, by help of imagination. For seeing many dogs, we gather into one imaginary dog all the essential attributes, and this forms our conception " dog." ' The nominalist says, ' That which we picture to ourselves as " dog " exists neither in the mind nor out of it ; it is merely " this or that dog " some particular dog we have seen, that we have photographed (so to speak) in our souls. Thus the realists believe in the objective existence of general notions (or common terms). The conceptual- ists in their subjective existence, and the nominalists allow them no existence at all.' METHOD (/<' oaoc). All our knowledge comes either from intuition or from proof. There are the universals at the top, so to speak, and the particulars at the bottom ; and the first we appre- hend by reason or intellect, the second by sense. Between these two extremes, which we accept upon intuition, comes a group of facts accepted upon proof or inference. Our ' whys ' and ' be- causes ' are obliged to stop when they reach the upper or lower bounds, beyond which no proof can go. Now in the pursuit of knowledge, as we pass through the domain of proof, we may travel by two grand routes. We may either start with the universal fact and journey southwards, or we may start with the particular fact and journey northwards. And the roads or routes are called fj.iQoSoi (o'floc) or ' ways after something.' The journey downwards is called the deductive, or the d, priori, or the synthetic method, and the upward journey the inductive, or the a posteriori, or the analytical method. The former is also called the method of in- struction, the latter the method of discovery. An instance of the first would be proving that these two slate pencils couldn't enclose a space by starting with the universal proposition, ' two straight lines can't enclose a space.' (For this is one of the ' bounds ' of proof that is accepted on intuition. If any one said* ' Why can't they ? ' you'd A LIST OF USEFUL FACTS IN LOGIC. 185 answer, ' Because they can't, and there's an end of it ; ' for it is one of the upper side ' bounds '). An instance of the second would be to prove that 'all bodies are attracted to the centre of the earth from such propositions as ' this book falls ' (Suppose some one said, ' Prove it falls ' after you've seen it fall, you'd answer Can't you believe your eyes ? ' which means that it is a fact ac- cepted upon intuition or sense one of the lower-side ' bounds ' of proof). [As to Logic, in so far as we start with particulars to find the laws, it's inductive, and in so far as those laws of thought already existed, and we found and did not make them, it's de- ductive.] The truths at the upper end are said to be 'notiora naturae,' or better known in themselves and simpler ; those at the lower end are ' notiora nobis,' better known to us, but more com- plicated. Now as universal truths are simpler, so they are said to be prior to particular truths. Hence a priori and a posteriori, though generally we learn particulars first (as a child calls every man papa). Smith is coming from Leicestershire to hunt with me. A priori Smith is a ' good goer,' for ' all Leicestershire men are good goers.' But Smith prefers the roads when he comes. A posteriori, then, Smith is not a good goer. Synthesis is 'piecing together ' and analysis ' breaking up.' I am anxious to know what this pudding is made of. I may either take simple ele- ments, ' currants,' ' flour,' &c., and ' piece together ' till I arrive at the particular pudding in question, or I may send for Drug, the chemist, and we may analyse the pudding till we get at the simple elements of which it is composed. So with the proposition ' Socrates is mortal,' I may either take simple elementary proposi- tions and piece them together as premisses until I arrive at this conclusion, or I may take the proposition to start with, and eye it narrowly until I find the simple elementary propositions of which it is an instance. In one case I start with the universal, in the other with the particular. Thus a priori and deductive and syn- thetical may be regarded as the same, and posteriori, analytical, and inductive as their opposites. OBJECTIVE (Metaphysics). PRACTICAL UTILITY OF LOGIC. (1) As an abstruse study, it braces the faculties of the mind. The harder the whetstone, the keener the knife ; and when you come to cut wood afterwards it's easy. So it ia with less abstruse questions after Logic. 186 PICTURE LOGIC. (2) It exposes fallacies. These recur. The foxhunter, who has seen many a fox drawn from a covert, is more likely to tell me whether there will be a fox in yonder untried covert than a raw novice, though neither may have seen the covert before. In Logic the covert is a wordy speech, the fox the fallacy, and the old foxhunter the cold logician. When the mob is on the point of ' stones and fire ' with delight at a speech, the logician is mut- tering ' accursed fallacy ! ' (3) It is the study of the highest part of man, and man is the highest thing in the world. Such a study must elevate and ennoble us. PROPOSITION. Indefinite propositions, where the quantity is not specified, as ' girls are shy.' Tautologons, where the predicate simply repeats the subject, and no information is given. Eggs are egg 8 - PSYCHOLOGY. The science of the whole inner nature of man ; i.e. of the whole mind or soul. Its object is to arrange and group these phenomena and find their laws. One of its results is that the mind or soul is broadly divided into three parts. The purely intellectual, the purely animal, and the combination ot the two, or the union of reason and desire. Other sciences then step in, take these three results, and produce further improvements and arrangements. The science of ethics takes ofl the union of reason and desire, as its subject-matter ; and Logic in the same way takes the purely intellectual part. Thus psychology provides Logic with its material, as the art of making oars pro- vides the art of rowing with material to work upon, or the science of Euclid the science of land-measurement. QUANTIFICATION OP PREDICATE. An attempt to quantify the predicate as we do the subject. It is better not to adopt it : (1 ) Because too troublesome. (2) too unusual a form. (3) makes one proposition into two. RATIOCINATION. A grand name for syllogistic inference. REALIST (See Nominalist). RHETORIC (See Grammar). SECUNDI ADJACENTIS. ' Brutus lives ' is said to be a proposi- tion secnndi adjacentis (i.e. with copula lost in Terb). Brutus is brave, is tertii adjacentis with copula distinct. A LIST OF USEFUL FACTS IN LOGIC. 187 SUBSTANCE (Metaphysics). SYLLOGISM. Valuable as an inference, because it brings in truth in a new way, if it does not bring in new truth : moreover it is of the greatest assistance to the memory, as it dispenses with the recollection of innumerable particulars. The principle of syllogism has these corollaries 1 (propositions following from itself, crowning it, so to speak) : (1) Terms whereof both agree with the same middle term agree with one another. (2) Terms wherof one agrees and one does not agree with the same middle term do not agree with one another. (S) Terms whereof neither agrees with the same middle term may or may not agree with one another. TERMS (irregular). Categorematic terms are of the form ' house, horse.' Syncategorematic, ' of, to, from.' ' Grateful,' ' ungrateful ' are positive and negative terms (presence and absence of a quality). ' Dead ' is a privative term (loss of a quality). ' Less and greater ' are opposites (< equal ' intervenes). ' Negatives ' are also called ' contradictories.' TROTSM = a tautologous proposition ; e.g., whatever is, is. This list Mr. Practical gave us as a bricklayer gives a series of dabs of mortar to fill up all crevices. He entreated us to read it over ' the night before the battle,' which I did with the zeal of a Roman Catholic soldier counting his beads, and the result was such as to exceed my wildest hopes. Both Dyver and myself passed with colours flying, Dyver being gently rebuked for giving up in a pass examination papers that would have carried off high honours, and I being complimented on the fact ( that I seemed to understand well what I wrote, and that it was refreshing to read papers that came from the writer's head ; and were not a string of phrases from books learnt off, but never understood.' The triumphant entry at home, the proud honours of a conquering hero, the affable condescension towards a world of inferiors who had never read Logic, or passed a public examina- tion, the earnest desire of the female part of the family that the Dver-wrought brain that had soared to, and faced, and fought, and 1 Corolla a little crown. 18S PICTURE LOGIC. mastered the mighty problems of that dimly awful monster Logic, and passed through the anguish and tribulation and torture of an Oxford examination, should have entire, absolute, and undisturbed rest and enjoyment for months to come: all these things, as likely to work upon the feelings, I leave to rhetoricians to de- scribe; for my part, under the strong influence of my logical teaching, I am disposed to cultivate the cold demeanour of the logician, and to this end I habitually amuse myself by detecting fallacies in the conversation of my father's friends, as they sip their port after dinner, the exposition of which errors does not seem so agreeable to them as it ought, though they are compelled to acquiesce, my father nodding to them, as much as to say, ' Take care, I expect he's right. He passed his examination very well in Logic, you know.' For there is an undefined panic among them at the very idea of Logic as it seems to me, at least : and, failing this, as a last resource I can always call any of their assertions 'A flagrant instance of violation of the principles of constructive, con- junctive, hypothetical syllogisms,' and this produces a dead silence at once. PRINTED BY 6POTTISWOODE AND CO., NBW-STEKKT HyUAHK LONDON 1888. GENERAL LISTS OF WORKS PUBLISHED BT MESSRS. LONGMANS, GKEEN, & CO. LONDON AHD NEW YORK. HISTORY, POLITICS, HISTORICAL MEMOIRS, &C. Abbey's The English Church and its Bishops, 1700-1800. 2 vols. 8vo. 24*. Abbey and Overton's English Chnrch in the Eighteenth Century. Cr. 8vo. It. 6d. Arnold's Lectures on Modern History. 8vo. It. 6d. Bagwell's Ireland under the Tudors. Vols. 1 and 2. 2 vols. 8vo. 32*. Ball's The Reformed Chnrch of Ireland, 1537-1886. 8vo. 7*. fid. Boultbee's History of the Church of England, Pre- Reformation Period. 8vo. 15*. Buckle's History of Civilisation. 3 vols. crown 8vo. 24*. Canning (George) Some Official Correspondence of. 2 vola. 8vo. 28*. Cox's (Sir G. W.) General History of Greece. Crown 8vo. Maps, it. 6d. Creighton's Papacy during the Reformation. 8vo. Vols. 1 & 2, 32*. Vols. 3 & 4, 24*. De Tocqueville's Democracy in America. 1 vols. crown 8vo. 16*. Doyle's English in America : Virginia, Maryland, and the Carolinas, 8vo. 18*. The Puritan Colonies, 2 vols. 8vo. 36*. Epochs of Ancient History. Edited by the Rev. Sir G. W. Cox, Bart, and C. Sankey, M.A. With Maps. Fcp. 8vo. price 2*. 6d. each. Beesly's Gracchi, Marios, and Sulla. Capes's Age of the Antoninea, Early Roman Empire. Cox's Athenian Empire. Greeks and Persians. Cnrteis's Rise of the Macedonian Empire. lime's Rome to ite Capture by tbe Gauls. Merivale's Roman Triumvirates. Sankey 's Spartan aud Thebau Supre- macies. Smith's Rome and Carthage, the Punic Wars. Epochs of Modem History. Edited by C. Colbeck, MA. With Maps. Fcp. 8vo. 2;. 6d. each. Church's Beginning of the Middle Ages. Cox's Crusades. Creighton's Age of Elizabeth. Gairdner's Houses of Lancaster and York. Gardiner's Puritan Revolution, . Thirty Years' War. (Mrs. ) French Revolution, 178SM795. Bale's Pall of the Stuarts. Johnson's Normans in Europe. Epochs of Church History. Edited by the Rev. Mandell Creighton, M.A. Fcp. 8vo. price 2*. M. each. Longman's Frederick the Great and the Seven Years' War. Lucilow's War of American Inde- pendence. M'Carthy's Epoch of Reform, 1830- 1850. Moberly's The Early Tudors. Morris's Age of Queen Anne. The Early Hanoverians. Seebohm's Protestant Revolution. Stubbs's The Early Plantagenets. Warburton's Edward III. Brodrick's A History of the Uni- versity of Oxford. Carr's The Church and the Roman Empire. Hunt's England aad the Papacy. Mnllinger's The University of Cambridge. Overton's The Evangelical Revival in the Eighteenth Century. Perry's The Reformation to England. Other Volumes in preparation. Plnmmer's The Church of the Early Fathers. Stephens' Hildebrand and his Times. Tozer'g The Church and the Eastern Empire. Tucker's The English Chnrch to other Lands. Wakeman's The Church and the Puritans. LONGMANS, GREEN, & CO., London and New York. General Lists of Works. Freeman's Historical Geography of Europe. 2 vols. 8vo. 31*. M. Fronde's English in Ireland in the 18th Century. 3 vols. crown 8vo. 18*. History of England. Popular Edition. 12 vols. crown 8vo. 3*. 6d. each. Gardiner's History of England from the Accession of Jamea I. to the Outbreak of the Civil War. 10 vols. crown 8vo. 60*. History of the Great Civil War, 1642-1649 (3 vols.) Vol. 1, 1642-1644, 8vo. 21*. GrevUte'u Journal of the Reigns of King George IV., King William IV., and Queen Victoria. Cabinet Edition. 8 vols. crown 8vo. 6*. each. Historic Towns. Edited by E. A. Freeman, D.C.L. and the Kev. William Hunt, M.A. With Maps and Plans. Crown 8vo. 3t. Gd. each. London. By W. E. Loftie. Exeter. By E. A. Freeman. Cinque Ports. By Montagu Burrows. Bristol. By the Rev. W. Hunt. Oxford. By the Rev. C. W. Boase. Colchester. By the Rev. E. 0. Cutts. Lecky's History of England in the Eighteenth Century. Vols. 1 & 2, 1700-1760, 8vo. 36*. Vols. 3 & 4, 1760-1784, 8vo. 36*. Vols. 5 & 6, 1784-1793, 36*. History of European Morals. 2 vols. crown 8vo. 16*. Rationalism in Europe. 2 vols. crown 8vo. 16*. Longman's Life and Times of Edward III. 2 vols. 8vo. 28*. Macaulay's Complete Works. Library Edition. 8 vols. 8vo. 5. 6*. Cabinet Edition. 16 vols. crown 8vo. 4. 16*. History of England : Student's Edition. 2 vols. cr. 8vo. 12*. I Cabinet Edition. 8 vols. post 8vo. 48*. People's Edition. 4 vols. cr. 8vo. 16*. | Library Edition. 6 vols. 8vo. 4. Macanlay's Critical and Historical Essays, with Lays of Ancient Rome In One Volume : Authorised Edition. Cr. 8vo. 2*. 6d. I Popular Edition. Cr. 8vo. 2*. 6y Kennedy. Crown 8vo. 10*. Gd. .ffineid, translated into English Verse, by Conington. Crown 8vo. 9*. byW.J.Thornhill. Cr. 8vo. 7*.6 H^B