THE RATIONAL GOOD : A STUDY IN THE LOGIC OF PRACTICE BY THE SAME AUTHOR THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE Demy 8vo. 7s. 6d. net. " No modern writer has so clearly worked out the main theoretical relations of the State to the individual citizen and to other social forces and institutions. The reasoning is close and cogent. Prof. Hobhouse is an admirable guide." Manchester Guardian. "The reasoning throughout is lucid and vigorous, and the style as non-technical as the subject will admit." Spectator. Ex Libria C. K. OGDEN THE RATIONAL GOOD: A STUDY IN THE LOGIC OF PRACTICE By L. T. HOBHOUSE, D.LiT., LL.D., MARTIN WHITE PROFESSOR OF SOCIOLOGY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF LONDON LONDON: GEORGE ALLEN & UNWIN LTD. RUSKIN HOUSE, 40 MUSEUM STREET, W.C. i First published in 1921 (All rights reserved) SANTA BAKBAKA Hfc CONTENTS PAQK INTRODUCTION ......... 9 CHAPTER I THE SPRINGS OF ACTION ....... 19 (i) Impulse, as opposed to reason, seems to dominate human action. (2) This view has been fortified by psychological analysis which sees in the alleged " reasons " for action an expression for underlying impulses. (3) But, if intellect without impulse is void, impulse without intellect is blind, (4) and the intellectual element is not purely derivative but has intellectual sources. (5) On the other hand, it is a fallacy to oppose the Practical Reason to the body of impulse as a whole. (6) In fact intelligence begins by defining the ends of impulse, (7) while, as it develops, impulse is transformed. The question is, what part intelligence (and in particular Reason) plays in the transformation. CHAPTER II IMPULSE AND CONTROL ....... 36 (1) " Bare " impulse involves but is not identical with feeling. (2) The function of feeling is to guide impulse in adaptation to the conditions of life. (3) Impulse informed by anticipation of an end is desire. The term has then a wider meaning than that of " bare " impulse. (4) The impulse to an inclusive End involving many related desires is a volition, (5) and the impulse to an end dominating all life is the Will. (6) The Will is the mass of impulse as an organized system (7) resting on feeling in a generic sense of the term. (8) The principle of Control then lies not outside, but within the system of impulse-feeling, and it is here if anywhere that practical rationality must be found. 5 6 THE RATIONAL GOOD CHAPTER III PAOK THE RATIONAL ......... 56 (1) The rational judgment is that which is consistent, grounded and objective, the first two characters being the test of the third. (2) The search for grounds leads up to immediate judgments both particular and general. Particular immediate judgments, however, are not indubitably true, but are corroborated by interconnexion. (3) Immediate general judgments likewise require interconnexion. (4) Interconnectedness is in fact the rational basis of belief. (5) The grounds on which intercon- nexion rests are universal relations. (6) The principles of interconnexion rest on the consilience of all consistent acts of inference. (7) The rational in cognition is then the effort to attain truth by the persistent interconnexion of judgments through universal relations. CHAPTER IV THE GOOD ......... 65 (i) Is there any reason in the choice of ultimate ends, i.e. is there a Rational Good ? (2) Generically the Good appears as a harmony (mutual support) of feeling and effort, (3) or of feeling and passive experience including, e.g., observation of the behaviour of another. Generically pleasure is feeling in har- mony and pain in disharmony. (4) The fact asserted by the judgment " This is Good " is thus a relation between an experi- ence and a feeling. Either element may be called good as pertaining to the whole. CHAPTER V THE RATIONAL GOOD ....... 78 (i) The Rational Good must be a consistent scheme of purposes interconnected by universal relations in which subjective disturbance is eliminated. (2) This involves a dual harmony of feeling with feeling and of feeling with experience. (3) There may be internal consistency from a more partial point of view but rationality involves universalism, i.e. a system compre- hending the whole world of all minds in a single scheme. (4) The authority of this scheme rests on the fact that the judg- ments composing it form a reasonable system, and assert a CONTENTS 7 PAGE reality which is not dependent on the opinion of the individual. Its psychological force is the organization of impulse-feeling which reason effects. (5) The foundation of the reality which it asserts is the interconnectedness of all minds. (6) The elements of impulse-feeling evolve under the conditions of existence and are of the instinctive type. (7) The impulse towards harmony is rational though it has not attained finality but continually corrects itself. CHAPTER VI THE REALIZED GOOD ........ 96 (i) Harmony involves the modification of impulses so far as incompatible. (2) This depends on the development of per- sonality, (3) and of the social principle. (4) Development is a progressive harmony (5) which in its matured form may be described as happiness in the fulfilment of life as a whole. (6) This definition is not incompatible with the principle that the individual mind requires an object beyond itself. CHAPTER VII APPLICATIONS . . . . . . . . .120 (1) The recognized moral order contains irrational elements. (2) How are rational principles to be brought into relation with it ? (3) Different interests must be preserved except so far as they conflict. (4) Where there is conflict the test is consistency carried through life as a whole. (5) In developing a rational order three rules of method are of use, (6) viz. (a) the system must " work," (7) (&) must impose no restraint not necessary for its working, (8) (c) must be impartial. (9) Bearing of the principle on abstract rights and collective wholes. CHAPTER VIII IMPLICATIONS 137 (1) Relation of the Principle of Harmony to Utilitarianism (2) and to Idealism. (3) Self-sacrifice cannot be resolved into self-realization. (4) Disparity of values, apparently opposed to the principle, is found to corroborate it. (5) The sanction of the principle is internal harmony. (6) It accords with a spiritual interpretation of the world-process. (7) The anti- ethical view of development is false. PREFACE THE following chapters were originally written in 1908-9, in amplification of a sketch of ethical theory contained in my Morals in Evolution, which had been published three years earlier. I was not, however, satisfied with the result, and put the manuscript aside for several years. It has now been almost entirely re-written. My obliga- tions to various writers on Psychology and Ethics will be manifest, but the general theory which most nearly corresponds to the central doctrine of the work is one which I heard expounded in a paper read in New York in 1911 by a distinguished lecturer on Ethics, and have never met with again in print. Mr. J. A. Hobson kindly read the work in its original form, and made many valuable criticisms. Mr. A. W. Ferris has performed the same service to the revised work, and several alterations and additions are due to his sugges- tions. I have also to thank him for revising the proofs. L. T. H. WIMBLEDON, October, 1920. INTRODUCTION WHAT is right, we have often been told, is the easiest thing in the world to know and the most difficult thing to do. Unfortunately truth will not compress itself into epigram, and a facile antithesis is usually misleading. To deal plainly with himself is perhaps enough for a man in ninety-nine cases, but the hundredth, if he still deals plainly, will present a real difficulty. Moreover the ninety-nine cases are, or appear to be, so easy because the man lives and moves and acts in a society with denned standards, established relations, express or implied under- standings under which he has himself grown up and to which his sense of right and wrong has adapted itself. He knows in the ordinary case what is expected of him, and he expects nothing else of himself. If these standards are assumed, private conduct becomes a matter of their application, and it is true that this is, in any ordinary case, simple enough. But suppose the social standards themselves to be called in question. By what standard shall they be judged ? Here is a question which is so far from simple that the plain man recoils from it. Why question the wisdom of our ancestors, the system which has worked not perfectly perhaps, but still has worked and has made us what we are ? Let us do our duty in that state of life to which it shall please God to call us, and be thankful that we are members of a stable community with stations provided for all respectable people to fill. Unfortunately we cannot dispose of the question in this manner. Our standards criticize them- selves. We have spoken of defined and recognized rules io THE RATIONAL GOOD which are not difficult to apply. But if we look closely into the network of current ideas of conduct we shall find not one standard but several. There are codes of law and custom, good manners and good taste, partly supplementing, partly correcting one another. In par- ticular, behind the code of ordinary respectable society are principles higher and more austere, intolerant of much which the working standard allows. In large measure these principles are embodied in the teaching of the Churches and in that sense belong to the officially recognized tradition. The shifts and devices by which they are accommodated to the working standard form the familiar theme of the satirist, and do not concern us for the moment. Our point is merely that while it may be quite easy for a man to apply the everyday standard to his particular case, and equally easy as an intellectual exercise to apply an ideal standard, he may find in the result that what is permitted by one code is repudiated, if he takes it seriously, by the other, and his real difficulty is to answer the question : under which Lord ? Now the same question at bottom confronts society as a whole. It lives on a certain tradition. It has its network of institutions, customs, and understandings. But it also contains germs and possibilities of a different life. The time is past when men in the mass simply took the established order for granted. They react upon it freely and seek avowedly to mould it to their own ideals. But again, there are more ideals than one, and between them what is to decide ? The established order sits serene while the ideals wrangle over the succession. Indeed, to some of them it may apply the wit of Charles II : " They will never kill me, James, to make you king." It must be admitted that ideals may attract the fanatics, the ill-balanced, and the mischief-makers. Violence is met by violence, and the question of right and wrong becomes an issue between numbers and organization, perhaps in the last resort between the bomb and the machine gun. Morality itself is as old as mankind, but the moral ideal seems to be by comparison a recent growth. The INTRODUCTION n question has often been asked whether any tribe, however primitive, has subsisted without some form of religion, and the answer depends on what we mean by religion. But if the question be whether any tribe has existed without morality, the reply can be made more definite. Investigation has shown that the simplest and most primitive peoples known have their definite codes of custom according to which every one knows what he is to expect and what is expected of him. The code is ordinarily observed, and it suffices to cover as much as is essential in the simple relations of primitive life, to give a certain protection to person and property, and a certain regularity to sex-regulations. Generally, it has behind it a certain body of belief, sometimes of religious, more often of magical, colour. But its real strength is the force of custom itself and the underlying fear of anything that would profoundly change or destroy the social order. In this sense, then, investigation shows morality to be universal, and general considerations point to the same conclusion. For we may well ask how any number of human beings could live permanently together unless they understood one another, and how they could understand one another unless they knew what to expect and what would be expected of them under given con- ditions, and unless, on the whole, they had confidence that the expectations would be realized. These things can only be if men have defined obligations to which ordinarily they are loyal. As society enlarges and developes, morality is elaborated and, on the whole, refined. The code has to deal with wider and more complex relations, and primitive custom breaks up into the law which has its definite organs of enforcement and morality in the narrower sense, which covers the finer and more personal issues. There is, as we all know, a rich variety of detail in the legal and moral codes of various times and places, yet in fundamental principle there is more agreement in the actual working codes of society than we of the " higher " civilizations like to acknowledge. For the working code, we may say 12 THE RATIONAL GOOD generally, is of the nature of a compromise between self and society. It takes the ordinary man just as he is with all his confused and often conflicting impulses, good and bad, social and selfish, and it puts him under certain restraints. He must not move his neighbour's landmark, but on the whole he may do what he will within his own. Life is a kind of game, in which each is expected to play for his own hand, only he must play according to rule. But some few centuries before our era there emerged a very different conception of life and duty. According to this conception life is not a game to be played by man against man, or family against family, or community against community. Life rests on a secret, profound, yet exceedingly simple once revealed, which dissipates all its difficulties, puts an end to strife and sorrow, shows us the way of light, emancipa- tion, and peace. The secret is to put off self-hood, and merge ourselves in the life of others, of all living things, perhaps of the universe, to ask for nothing, to be ready to give everything. " Full of hindrances is household life, a path defiled by passion, free as the air is the life of him who has renounced all worldly things." * Such a man is in charity not only with all mankind, but with all created things. " And he lets his mind pervade one quarter of the world with thoughts of love, and so the second, and so the third, and so the fourth. And thus the whole wide world, above, below, around, and everywhere, does he continue to pervade with heart of Love, far reaching, grown great, and beyond measure. Just, Vasettha, as a mighty trumpeter makes himself heard and that without difficulty in all the four directions, even so of all things that have shape and life, there is not one that he passes by or leaves aside, but regards them all with mind set free, and deep, full love." * How far this Buddhist conception is original and what elements it may have derived from earlier Brahmanic 1 Buddhist Suttas, Sacred Books of the East, vol. xi. p. 187. 3 Ibid., p. 201. INTRODUCTION 13 teaching we need not here enquire. We may remark only on the striking analogies in the doctrine of Lao Tse : " To joy in conquest is to joy in the loss of human life." " Who- soever humbleth himself shall be exalted, and whosoever exalteth himself shall be abased." " I would return good for good, I would also return good for evil. I would likewise meet suspicion with confidence." x We may think also of the doctrine of equal universal benevo- lence upheld by the philosopher Mih against the protests of the classical moralists as evidence that wherever or whenever these conceptions originated they took root in China as well as in India. Spreading West they inspired various ethical and religious disciplines, and received one of their noblest expressions in the Christianity of the Gospels. 3 Vary as it may in detail and in the cosmological ideas associated with it, the doctrine of the selfless life is one, and easily recognizable in all its expressions. Its promul- gation constitutes the one really great epoch in moral evolution, and is comparable in its effect to the Copernican revolution in astronomy and the remodelling of scientific method achieved in the period from Galileo to Newton. No one who has ever entered at all into the spirit of the teaching can see life again in quite the same light. It is one of the revelations, like falling in love, or like parenthood, each of which also puts life on a different plane. Yet, with all its potency, the alleged simplicity of the doctrine was a delusion. It has not been found possible for men in the mass to live by it, and its recep- tion as an orthodoxy has always been a disaster to the creed. I would not deny that, now and again, we catch a glimpse of it in our working life, and one or two of us may have known a woman or even, rarer exception, a man whose nature seems by some divine gift moulded throughout on the lines of the selfless religion. But to attract numbers, and keep them, the teachers and the 1 The Path of Virtue, Tr. by Old, chaps, xxii, xxxi, and xlix. 1 And let us add, for the sake of justice, in the Pauline account of charity. i 4 THE RATIONAL GOOD Churches have striven in vain by asceticisms and brother- hoods, disciplines and charities. They could enforce the rules, but not breathe the spirit into the mass. 1 Here is the main root of that divided allegiance of which we have spoken. For all Christian communities the laws of God and of man fall asunder and the patchwork compromises are so often threadbare that we are driven to wonder whether the franker Paganism did not gain in honesty what it lost in idealism. But the real trouble lies deeper even than the difficulty of forcing too lofty a creed on imperfect mankind. The doctrine itself is only one-half of the truth, and, if the Western world has some hold of the complementary half, the means of fitting them together are still to seek. For the Eastern doctrine in itself tends to quietism and resignation, and the truth that the West has discovered a truth originating perhaps with the Greeks, but revived with new meaning in modern times points in the most opposite direction. For collec- tive mankind resignation is not a duty, but a coward's plea. Its duty is not to do the will of the gods, but to refashion the world to its own will, whereto, so far as concerns material things, it is slowly finding out the * The conversion of the Empire was a pyrrhic victory for Christianity. How was communism to be reconciled with pro- perty, " take no thought for the morrow " with industry and thrift, non-resistance with the law courts and, above all, with war, the prohibition of oaths with judicial procedure, and so forth ? On some points the Church put up a fight, e.g. at one period it actually secured the suspension of the death penalty, and on the whole it had its way (whether for good or ill) in the law of marriage and divorce. But in the main the official churches adopted a question- able form of compromise, maintaining their principles in the letter while admitting ingenious devices for nullifying their application, and thus introducing an element of sophistry into the public ethics of the modern world which we do not find in antiquity. On the other hand there have seldom been wanting small, unorthodox bodies which have stood for the Christian ethics in their purity, and the influence of these bodies has been great and sometimes decisive. The whole subject has been discussed by Lecky, History of European Morals, chap, iv, and in the present writer's Morals in Evolution (3rd edition, p, 519), INTRODUCTION 15 way. Of the individual, it is true, the utmost sacrifice may be demanded, but for a cause, not as an end in itself, not to destroy individuality. On the contrary the demand is pervading and universal, for rights, scope, the means of expression, the conditions of happiness, whether for the individual, the class, the sex, the nation, or the race. For every human seed the fullness of its flower and fruit. This is a creed not of resignation, but of assertion. The danger is that becoming self-assertion, it may turn to anarchy, and that is why, if we could but find the way, it must be welded upon the old lore of the East. In the meantime men find themselves in a new world of vast possibilities and increasing power. They are fired with new hopes, and impatient of old restraints. Often they are tempted to trust to passion rather than reason, and sometimes to rely more on force than on justice. In the welter of new elements it is not wonderful that it should be so. The world was not made in six days, nor will it be remade in six generations, and mean- while ideals will, if we may so put it, contend with as much violence and as little scruple as persons. But is there not, after all, a more excellent way ? Is there not a method of bringing reason to bear on matters practical and social as on matters physical and mathe- matical ? In the world of thought there is a reality to which preconceived opinion and rebellious emotion alike must bow. When experiment and calculation have spoken controversy is put to silence. Is there no corre- sponding reality, no analogous method in the world of practice, and of human values ? There is, it may be said, this essential difference. The Reality of Science recks nothing of human wishes and emotions. But the values of human life are the objects of our wishes, and form the very tissue of our emotions. They neither subsist nor go forward like a planet in its orbit without regard to the human will, but are made and unmade by that will. They are what we would have them to be, whereas the reality which science studies is what it is, no. matter what we would jiaye it to be. Rational proof^ 16 THE RATIONAL GOOD then, is inapplicable to human ends. Feelings and desires are not susceptible of truth and falsity, and there is nothing to be proved or disproved about them. Such is the first and most obvious retort to the claim of Reason to govern the world of practice. But a little consideration suggests some points at which the contrast between theory and practice is overstated. Is the world of Values to go to the central point so cor^ shut off from the world of truth and reality as tf assumes ? No one would deny that given a cert the means employed to bring it about may be will " really " succeed or " really " fail. No deny that in this respect our judgments abo 1 m may be true or false. But what of our ends when we have gained them ? Do we not find that some are " really " satisfying, and others " really " vain and illusory, and if so, must we not admit that there is a reality and an unreality in the world of our desire, and a truth and falsity in our judgments as to what is good ? Lastly, if A pursues an end which is very satisfactory to him, but a crushing blow to B, is that end good as A thinks, or bad as B considers ? Is there no court of appeal, nothing to determine what is just and fair between the parties ? A strong and persistent impulse if we are to appeal only to impulses urges us to " see fair " in such a case, and that means to find something which is " really " right no matter what A and B may severa* think. It looks, then, as though right and wrong rr stand to the will much as true and false stand to judgment. It would seem that they, too, claim a k of validity which is regardless of any individual aberrat If that is so we shall not be surprised if we find sometL , analogous to the reason which determines what is tr in the processes which establish what is right. Whether these things are so is the question to be ask* in this volume. We are concerned with the function Reason in practical life. We shall enquire whetl there is a Rational, and therefore a demonstrable, standard of values to which the actions of man and the institutions INTRODUCTION 17 of society may be referred for judgment. If we find such a standard, which we may call the Rational Good, we shall have to ask in what sort of life inward and outward is it realized, what authority and power does it possess to dominate the actual conduct of men, and what light 4oes it throw on the relation between human aspirations and the cosmjc processes among which the life of the >?^r ( i^ numbered. These are all questions of the first ,^es of Ethics and Religion. To apply such principles ^-^ofial structure, which is the great need of our P equires a systematic study of " axiomata media " Concrete enquiry into the actual working of insti- .jWhich cannot be attempted on this occasion. 1 ne co A mexion of wide generalities with particular facts involves the establishment of many intervening links. These facts must be left to the student of society and the student of character. But it will be found in the sequel that our principles involve, as all substantial propositions must, the general rules and directions for their application. RU 9: o , THE RATIONAL GOOD CHAPTER I THE SPRINGS OF ACTION i. IN the world of turbid feeling and conflicting impulses wherein active life moves and has its being, Reason is a strange, an unbidden and often an unwelcome guest. A philosophic theory may explain, but seldom guides the actions of men. An ideal must usually be translated, perhaps mistranslated, into a symbol ; it must be per- sonified, perhaps mispersonified, in a leader, before it will command the devotion of the multitude. Once woven into habitual modes of feeling, once caught into the web of daily effort and strife, once entangled in all the associations of victory and defeat, satisfied ambition or glow of resentment, it may gain a power to conjure from the memories it evokes. It will seldom kindle and sustain by its inherent force and value. The effective rules of conduct are rather those which formulate what men feel than those which tell them what they ought to feel. Indeed, it was the master of thinkers who said that bare thinking sets nothing moving. In some directions no doubt the growth of applied science has extended the sphere of reason in human affairs. Yet in the world of mind, which might seem to be her own domain, reason in these days seems sadly out of fashion. Psychology, which begins to reduce the play of mental activity to a science, has not fostered the con- ception of conduct as a reasoned art. On the contrary, 19 20 THE RATIONAL GOOD its tendency is to emphasize the primacy of feeling, the sway of instinct, the prevalence of the irrational in the mass movements of mankind. What is still more remark- able, philosophy itself, once the appointed guardian and advocate of reason, shares in the irrationalist tendency. We shall end by denning man as the irrational animal, and the modern philosopher as his prophet. 2. So far as psychology is concerned the emphasis on the irrational is easy to understand. When men first reflect upon their behaviour they naturally start with things of which they are fully conscious. If I am asked why I do this or that, my answer is given in terms of an End. If I cannot state the end clearly I seem to myself rather foolish, and to my neighbour, perhaps, insincere. So axiomatic does it seem that to use the Greek phrase everything is done for the sake of the apparent good that is to come from it. But to Psychology this mode of explanation will often seem very superficial. Going behind the ordinary consciousness, psychology is very largely concerned in distinguishing the forces operating in the twilight of semi-consciousness, if not in the dark of the unconscious, upon which our purposes depend, and, since new discoveries are very like new toys, it is not surprising if some psychologists, in their delight with the forces that they have laid bare, make of these the whole of mind, and, while elevating impulse and emotion to the highest place, regard reason and will as superficial conceptions. On this way of thinking the reasons that we give for action are merely ex post facto formulae for the impulses and emotions that really prompt the act. The impulses are not based upon the reasons but the reasons on the impulses. A man may think that he loves a woman because she is beautiful, but in reality she is beautiful to him because he loves her. He says, and even believes, that he resents another's claim because it is wrong. In reality he finds it wrong because he resents it. He does this or abstains from that in conscious obedience to the will of God. In reality the effective will of God is the expression of impulses, within THE SPRINGS OF ACTION 21 himself, as modified by social traditions reposing in the last resort on cognate impulses in the minds of other men. From this last case it appears that not only does a man's personal account of his personal nature rest on his personal impulses, but social theories, traditional beliefs, ancestral customs, and new departures spring, not from the reasons given for them, but from impulses, permanent or transitory, of mankind. Thus, a com- pletely new mode of explaining social institutions arises. When it was first discovered that many " primitive " peoples buried food and implements, perhaps horse and wife into the bargain, with a dead chieftain, the interpre- tation was, very naturally, that they believed the dead man to enjoy a continued existence very similar to his life on earth, and they buried with him all that he would most need in the future state. What had to be explained on this view was the genesis of the belief. That being given, the funeral practices would follow. But the psychological methods that we are considering tend to reverse the order. They suggest that certain emotions about the dead, a strange blend of fear, regret, and affec- tion, prompted the offerings, and the theory came in afterwards as an explanation. In the Banks Islands they place a piece of banana trunk on the bosom of a dead mother. This is to deceive her ghost, which would otherwise carry off the living child. Could even the Banks Islander be so childish as to cheat himself with this reasoning if he were really moved by reasoning alone ? The truth is that a powerful sentiment urges him to give the dead woman that which she most cherishes. A still more powerful sentiment bids him save the baby. Between the two he devises a compromise of make-believe, all in logical terms, but full of inconsistencies. The mother remains alive enough to desire her baby, but not intelligent enough to distinguish between the baby and a piece of wood. The compromise could deceive no one, however savage, if he had not made up his mind to be deceived. Now the cruder self-deceptions may be only possible at the lower stages, but, fundamentally, the 22 THE RATIONAL GOOD same relation between impulse, emotion, desire on the one side, and explicit purposes, ideals and principles upon the other, holds for all stages of development. The wicked do not at bottom fear hell, but live in a hell of fear. We do not punish criminals because punishment is just, but because we hate or fear them, and out of our hatreds and fears we weave a system of ideas in which, as though on impersonal and impartial principles, suffering is attached to wrong-doing. Our ethical and social principles are in the same case. The French philosophers announce the rights of man, as so many abstract principles founded on reason and applicable at all times and places to all mankind. In reality they formulated the resent- ment of the French bourgeoisie against aristocratic privilege and monarchical misrule. To the English Utilitarian democracy which he formulated as a logical deduction from principles of ethics and psychology meant, in fact, the supremacy of his own middle class, and Liberty meant the plenitude of opportunity for its commercial ambitions. So we might go on with the religious, ethical, or social principles that the world has known. The whole may be summed up in this way. At bottom man is moved, not by ideas or principles, but by impulses and emotions, or to put them into a compound term since they are so closely allied by impulse-feeling. But he is influenced not only directly but in many subtle ways by the impulse-feeling of others, and he has to give and receive an account of what he does and what they do. Hence he formulates his impulses into ends, and explains them by reasons which are mutually intelligible. This explanation has a use of its own. It serves intercommunication and mutual under- standing. But in the order of causation it arises ex post facto. The real cause, whether of the personal act or the social custom, or the ethical principle, lies in impulse- feeling. To treat the alleged reason as the true ground is the fallacy of intellectualism. In fact it would seem, on this view, that man is not precisely the irrational animal as suggested above. Still THE SPRINGS OF ACTION 23 less is he the rational animal of his own philosophy. We might describe him rather as the would-be rational animal. Among his other impulses he owns this curiosity among desires the desire to explain himself to himself and others. Acting under this impulse he forms theories of " life and action," and, taking these theories seriously, he becomes an intellectualist. In reality reason, intellect, perhaps consciousness itself, are only " epiphenomena." They are the fly upon the wheel which in reality revolves on the hub of emotion, or rather of still deeper, perhaps purely physical, forces, which for some unintelligible reason have felt emotion as their concomitant a useless concomitant, functionless, an effect, but not a cause, a fly upon the wheel. 3. With the ultimate questions of causation involved I cannot deal here. I must assume in general terms that the life of mind has a true meaning and function, that it is not merely an effect of bodily movements or their projection, as it were, upon another plane, but takes part in them, and through them makes itself effective in the world. 1 But if that is assumed, the question of the true relation between the unconscious and the con- scious, the emotional and the rational, impulse and idea, still remains, and the question will run all through our enquiry. Clearly, it is fruitless to speak of a Logic of Practice if there can be no practical significance in logic. What may be remarked as a preliminary is that, of the examples chosen above, the reader will probably have found some much more convincing than others. Thus, to take the very first, love is proverbial for its blindness, and for its power of endowing the loved object with all lovable qualities. This is perhaps the strongest case for the theory that the emotion creates its own excuse. But even Love may, tragically, have its eyes opened. It could not be maintained that faults never appear till 1 For a thoroughgoing defence of this view see Dr. McDougall's Body and Mind. In excuse for my omission here I may be allowed to refer to my Mind in Evolution, chap, ii, and Development and Purpose, Part II, chap. iv. 24 THE RATIONAL GOOD love is dead. It must be allowed that it is the blemish that sometimes gives it its mortal wound. Take next, resentment. If our anger seeks justification, is it not equally true that to be required to state our case has its effect upon our anger ? When we lay it before another in plain language are we not forced to make some dis- tinction between our personal sources of irritation and the offence which will be recognized as such by an impartial man, and would it be questioned that the judgment of our neighbour has its effect, if not on the emotion itself, at any rate upon its practical expression ? Grant, for the sake of argument, that legal punishments originate from emotions of blinded indignation and fear. The fact remains that, as they stand, they constitute a penal code formulated in abstract terms, defining impersonally the crimes for which they are due, the procedure by which guilt is to be ascertained, and so forth. There is a long interval between the penalty so inflicted and the direct emotional expression of resentment by an injured man, and that interval is occupied by processes of deliberation, discussion, comparison, by considerations of public interest, by reflective notions of justice, responsibility and desert. It may be said that, if we take away the primitive emotion, all this legal mechanism would be as powerless as the cold gun without the powder. Maybe, but without law and morals the emotion would be as ill-directed as the powder without the gun. There are two elements in human action, and they are necessary to one another. Whether idea or impulse comes first may be difficult in a specific case to determine, but, whichever comes first, both in the end are equally essential to the developed purpose. It may well be that some sentiment about the dead first prompted funeral gifts. But they could never have assumed their elaborate 1 Whether it be fear or love. It looks as though the burning, burial or destruction of the dead man's belongings were prompted, at the lowest stage, by a kind of dread expressed, in the first degree of reflection, in the magical conception of a death infection. The kindlier feeling is perhaps later. THE SPRINGS OF ACTION 25 development including sometimes the sacrifices of slaves, and even of the widow, at the grave but from the positive and articulate belief in survival. Nor would this belief have arisen out of the sentiment alone if it had not been favoured by the intellectual situation. The belief in continuity is founded on a very simple logic, and, for the simpler peoples, obtained some corroboration from dreams and an easy explanation from the animistic conception of soul and body. In fact, when this conception is shattered, the practices are changed and reduced to a shadow of themselves. Often we can clearly see that it is the belief which causes practices that probe the very depths of human emotional capacity. Take the case of human sacrifice. Are we to attribute this to a direct delight in cruelty, or even negatively to a special callousness in savage peoples ? There is not the smallest reason to regard agriculturists as inherently more callous than other men. On the contrary, the manners of a settled agricultural people are in general milder, if anything, than those of the herdsman and the hunter. But the overwhelming majority of cases of human sacrifice are found among agricultural peoples of the second and third stages, and the reason is simply the widespread belief, of magical origin, in the influence of a human victim upon the crops. We cannot suppose that our ancestors, in the period of religious persecutions, suddenly acquired an increment of natural cruelty which they lost again when the persecutions ceased. These appalling cruelties began when heresy arose, under the influence of the belief that heresy put all men who might be influenced by it in jeopardy of eternal suffering. When this belief began to be weakened heretics were no longer burnt. Un- doubtedly the psychologist will trace many unavowed emotional elements in the work of the inquisitor. In particular he will realize that it is the inquisitor's own fear which points his zeal. In exterminating the doubter he hopes vaguely to extinguish the doubt. Nevertheless the belief is in the governing fact. The fanatic would not experience these particular fears in this marked degree 26 THE RATIONAL GOOD if his imagination had not painted an unjust God in the image of a Philip II. Still less would he have been able to persuade the balanced, moderate man to join with him in burning noble men and women of pure lives had not one and all been in intellectual agreement on their theory of the universe. 4. To this the reply may be that, however influential the conception of God, of the future life, of the universe and man's place in it may be, the conception itself rests on human emotions, and expresses the character of a race, an age, an epoch in civilization. Civilized people do not tolerate a Moloch. The story of Isaac embodies the memory of the abolition of human sacrifice under the influence of a dawning humanity. Plato, with all his respect for the traditional religion, has to urge a purgation of the Homeric Olympus. Christian doctrine rightly placed Charity above Faith, and, if men in general had been in their heart as in their profession Christians, they would never have acquiesced in a conception of Deity which necessitated persecution. Indeed, as manners grew milder they revolted against it. Thus, if it is con- ceded that theory influences practice, it will only be on the understanding that theory is itself determined by character. But this objection only allows a part of the truth. When God has become the ideal of goodness a position only reached at an advanced stage of religious development it would certainly seem that the character attributed to God must reflect the essential elements of perfection as conceived by man. But to frame a consistent ideal of perfection is itself as much an intellectual as a moral effort, and to reconcile perfect goodness of will with the possession of disposing power over the universe is emphatically a problem for the intelligence, and one which it could not, in fact, solve. The God of Christianity was encumbered from the first with remnants of the Old Testament tradition which to this day are quoted as an excuse for vicarious punishment and it was difficult to get rid of these inconsistencies without shaking the authority of tradition. What was more serious was THE SPRINGS OF ACTION 27 that to meet purely intellectual needs God was the creator of all things and the disposer of the eternal destinies of men. Hence all the problems of the origin of evil, of free will, desert, grace, and predestination, problems of intellectual origin that could neither be solved nor even discussed without raising acute moral questions. To take an illustration from quite another part of our field, how great has been the influence of biological investigation on modern social theory. The conception of natural selection and the struggle for existence has been used at one time to justify competition and obstruct the growing sense of collective responsibility, at another to justify war and conquest, and silence the claims of personal liberty and international right. Clear thinking is every whit as necessary as right feeling to the discussion of the moral issues raised by such theories. It is perfectly true that they owe their ready acceptance to a favourable emotional prepossession. It is quite easy to understand why some of the modern Eugenic arguments are popular among the classes that are fortunately circumstanced and can barely obtain a hearing from the " bottom dog." But though the desires and emotions of men account for the popularity or unpopularity of social theories they do not account for the theories themselves. These arise out of the intellectual situation, just as the prevalent attitude towards them arises out of the emotional situa- tion, and, like all theories, they have in the end to run the racket of logical and evidential tests. It would, I admit, be too much to say that a popular theory may be killed instantaneously by disproof. It dies hard, or rather undergoes a process of evanescence, fading away first from the discourse of educated and intelligent men, becoming a mark of ignorance, of simplicity, and so by stages dissolving into oblivion while quicker minds are busied in finding a substitute. Theories, then, exert a real directive influence, and theories have their main root in the intellectual world in the state of knowledge, the level of intellectual clarity, the mode in which men conceive the problems of life 28 THE RATIONAL GOOD and society. The critic of intellectualism can see the point quite clearly when the deficiencies of theory are in question. He will show how the abstraction of natural rights or of popular sovereignty justified some of the worst mistakes and excesses of the French Revolution, how ideas of Liberty and Equality overshadowed the structure of the American Constitution, how weaknesses in Bentham or in Cobden vitiated much of the work of English Liberalism. Admitting that theories may be influential for evil he does not recognize that they can be influential for good. Yet his whole criticism is an unwitting testimony to the importance of well-reasoned ideals. If defects in the theories of Rousseau or Bentham are seriously chargeable with certain bad results in practice, it follows that, if these mistakes had been corrected in good time by a better way, those ill results would have been avoided. On the whole question of the real influence of social theories and I would associate religious ideals with them for this purpose we ought, I would contend, to keep an open mind and look to careful historical and comparative investigation rather than to theories of human motive alone to give us the answer. The historic fortunes of ideals, what has actually determined their growth, what real influence they have exerted upon events, how far they have been merely an intellectualized version of some process that was going on, and would have gone on to the end, without them, how far they have really been effective in altering the face of society these are questions on which, within certain limits, general psychology leaves us with an open mind. It indicates several highly interesting possibilities, and it is the fascinating, though exceeding difficult, task of sociology to determine in each case which possibility ha.s been realized. Was the Stoic philosophy, for example, a real force in the remodelling of Roman jurisprudence, or did it merely furnish a convenient formula for changes necessitated by an expanding civilization, and the needs of a cosmopolitan empire ? If the mere needs were the primary causes of change, would they have been so clearly THE SPRINGS OF ACTION 29 felt, or the lines of solution so readily discoverable without the aid of the larger principles which the philosophy furnished ? How far, again, in the fourth and fifth cen- turies was Christianity the conqueror or the conquered ? Was the world Christianized at bottom, or the Church paganized ? How far, in modern times, were the theories to which we have alluded above merely a reflection of popular movements in the minds of bookish men ? How far was there an interaction between theory and event, and would a more adequate theory have had practical effect in giving increased coherence to the impulses of men ? These are questions to which, I think, the concrete answer must be supplied in each case by the social historian trained in psychological analysis. As we proceed we shall see, in general, something of what theory can and of what it cannot do, and for our present purpose these generalities will have to suffice. 5. One thing we can, in fact, see emerging from the considerations already reviewed. Much of the prejudice against reason is due to a misconception for which its friends are as much responsible as its enemies. By both alike reason is often taken as a thing apart. On the side of knowledge it is divorced from experience, on the side of conduct from feeling. In both cases the divorce is fatal to a true understanding. In regard to conduct the " practical Reason " is not a faculty which sits aloft, issuing impotent orders to a refractory multitude of impulses and emotions. It is not a faculty concerned with a system of abstract truths deducible, like so many mathematical formulae, from first principles that have nothing to do with human feeling. It is rather a general expression for something which careful analysis reveals in permanent operation within the emotional field. The stupidest human being outside an idiot asylum is not guided by pure impulse alone. With greater or less clearness he realizes what he is about, he has an idea of his immediate end, he can follow the concatenation of ends and means, and he can weigh the advantages and disadvantages of one end against another. Irrational as 30 THE RATIONAL GOOD the average life may seem when tested by comparison with some all-embracing, self-consistent principle of conduct, it is orderly when compared with the chaos of spluttering impulses which would remain if the element of reason were once for all abstracted. If a man has no dominating purpose or creed that effectively directs his life as a whole, he has as a rule threads and filaments of purpose running through and connecting branches of his conduct. He has probably his trade or profession, his family life and affections, his hobbies, his house and possessions ; each of these gives a certain order and consecutiveness to his conduct, and renders it so far purposive, continuous, and rational. The total result, it is true, may be a patchwork rather than a pattern, and the colours may not always match. One hand may undo the work of the other, and the contrasts of character presented by the same being in different relations may be a legitimate theme of satire ; but it is fair to judge in the end not only by failures, but by successes, not only by things done ill, but by ill-doings avoided. There are elements of order, of restraint, of consecutive purpose in the ordinary life, and the starting point of ratiocination is the conception that these elements are the partial and imperfect incarnations of a purpose which is comprehen- sive, self -consistent, and complete. The threads which string together portions of human conduct are what a thinker, who was no rationalist, called organic filaments. They are shreds from the tissue of a higher organism, which it is the problem of reason to apprehend in its wholeness. 6. The view thus suggested of the place of thought in general, and of rational thought in particular, in ordinary workaday life, is filled in and justified when we turn to comparative Psychology. The further we go into questions of origin and development the less we shall be disposed to admit the abstract and absolute separatioh of the worlds of thought and feeling. On the contrary, the evidence goes to show that intelligence takes its rise within the sphere of impulse, and has for THE SPRINGS OF ACTION 31 its first function to define the direction of impulse, and shape it to a foreseen End. Impulse, informed by a definite idea of an End, becomes Purpose, and Purpose is at least the beginning of rationality in action. The relation between reason and impulse is fundamental to our enquiry, and as a preliminary to it let us remark here that the evolutionary view of purpose is essential to a just understanding of the controversy between the intellectualist and his opponent. For it traces impulse to deep-seated > conditions of life, and finds for it far- reaching functions in which the interest of the moment is only a fleeting phase. But it may be only this interest that is formulated into a clear purpose. The significance of the act to the agent may then be only a very small part of its significance as understood by the psychologist who traces it to causes of which the agent is unaware and knows that it performs a function which the agent does not grasp. At this point the psychologist is tempted to maintain that the act is irrational unless the reasons which he sees for it are also those which the agent sees. But this is an arbitrary requirement. The truer inference is that the sphere of intelligence we will not here say " reason " in action varies in extent as the bearing and significance of the act is more or less clearly and fully understood. It is fallacious to attribute to every agent a full understanding of all the logical implications of all that he does. It is equally fallacious to maintain that he understands nothing on the ground that he does not understand everything. To take a simple instance. A mother nurses her querulous baby to sleep. The plain man regards her action as purposive and intelligent. She loves the child, cannot bear to see it fret, knows how to quiet it, and does so. The ease of the child is her direct purpose, and so she herself would say. The psychologist descends upon the plain man, and the mother alike with the intellectualist fallacy. For him her action is instinctive and emotional. It is the impulsive outcome of the maternal feeling nourished through ages of selection as a means of securing 32 THE RATIONAL GOOD maternal care for the helpless young. It is rooted in a hereditary mechanism. The embraces and caresses by which it is effected are the instinctive, almost reflex, responses fixed by the inherited machine, and its signifi- cance is seen in the importance of maternal care to the life of the species. Of all this the mother, as mother, recks nothing. She is thinking only of the child and its immediate comfort. She is acting, then, not from reason, but from impulse. But this account is really the intel- lectualist fallacy itself, turned inside out. The mother is not concerned with all the causes that have made her what she is, nor with all the effects which will flow from her actions. But those causes have made her an intelli- gent being with a certain area of purpose, within which she consciously adopts whatever means she finds best suited within that area. If it is an intellectualist fallacy to say that she acts from a conscious sense of the func- tions of motherhood, it is another form of the same fallacy since it assumes that what is rational in action must be deduced from abstract principles, independent of impulse-feeling to maintain that, unless she does so, she is acting by pure impulse. The simple truth in that case lies with the " plain man." The mother acts intelli- gently for the purpose that she has in view, not on the theory which psychologists may frame about the origin or signification of such purposes. We may apply a similar analysis to the rise of social institutions. History will often show that institutions which play some important part in natural life, and look as if they had been designed for that part, never were designed at all. They grew into their mature shape " from precedent to precedent," each change being prompted, not by any general principle, but by the requirements of some particular situation. If that is so, there is, at each stage, no consciousness of the remote and comprehensive end towards which, as we see on looking back, the society is actually tending, and to impute consciousness of the end without direct evidence would be an intellectualist fallacy. But there is conscious- THE SPRINGS OF ACTION 33 ness at each stage of the immediate concrete or practical end, and to deny this would be the reverse form of the same fallacy. If it is often true that men have built better than they knew, the just analysis of the case is that, though they were not guided by a conception of the fabric as a whole, they were well aware of what they were doing as they added each brick. 7. It is not too much to say that the conception of purpose as valid and genuine in spite of limitation is vital to the analysis of reason, and to the whole interpre- tation of mental and social development. The lower forms of action generally serve functions which the spectator can recognize as useful to the organism or the stock, but are not determined by any idea of that utility. We cough not because we are aware that it is desirable to expel a foreign body from the windpipe, but because a crumb touches off a machinery which effects a violent expiration. Again, a dog eats, not that it may sustain life, but because it is hungry. But here, even at this low stage, the underlying impulses which do in fact tend to sustain life begin to force themselves up into conscious- ness. When the dog begs for a biscuit, or the cat runs after the person who is carrying a saucer, it is at least a tenable (if disputed) view that it anticipates this particular meal, is guided by its anticipation, and adopts accordingly the behaviour which on such occasions it has found to yield the required result. Thus, hunger, a feeling based on bodily structure and subservient to vital needs of the race, stimulates in consciousness the anticipation of a certain definite end. That end does not include all the implications which the biologist sees in it. It is very limited and narrow, but within its limits it directs action. Conscious purpose emerges from needs lying below the threshold, but it is none the less purpose, and conscious. Were it otherwise there would be no conscious purpose unless or until we could stand entirely apart from our hereditary nature. But, it may be said, it is not awareness of the end that is in question, but control of the impulse. The 34 THE RATIONAL GOOD irrationalist will admit that, with varying degrees of clearness and comprehension, we know what we are about, but he regards this knowledge as a mere " epiphenomenon." The driving force is still impulse, and our knowledge of its direction neither adds to its energy nor subtracts from it. But if knowledge adds nothing to impulse it does materially affect its execution. Between an impulse acting blindly and the same impulse executing itself on an intelligent plan there will be a world of difference in the actual effect upon behaviour. If this is too obvious to be questioned the reply will be that intelligence may dictate the means to an end, but not the end itself. In assigning a purpose we give a reason for the use of this or that means, but what is the reason of the purpose itself ? Is there any but its foundation in feeling or impulse, which (it will be said) is no reason, but a blunt psychological fact ? To deal with this objection we must decide what reason in matters of conduct means, and that is our main question. But we must remark at once that as life proceeds and intelligence expands there is a transformation not merely of the means by which impulses achieve their satisfaction, but, to all appearance, of impulses themselves. Particular impulses are fitted into a larger scheme, and what is more, are modified or even suppressed in order to fit the scheme. Take the case of maternal love again. The animal mother has the impulse to feed and tend the young, and protect it from an apparent danger, and it is at least a tenable view that in so doing she can on occasion act with some intelligence. It is a tenable view that the hen-bird that goes to find a worm and brings it in to the peeping nestling is not merely prompted from moment to moment by a series of impulses, but by the purpose of filling the yellow beak. However this may be in the case of the bird, it is quite easy to understand that there is a stage of intelligence at which the purpose of feeding the young when hungry, may be formed without any clear conception of the good of the young as a being who is to live and grow, and whose permanent welfare THE SPRINGS OF ACTION 35 should govern every temporary service. Now the human mother certainly can and does form this wider conception. For her the temporary service becomes either a means or a constituent element in this wider end, and the wider end governs the narrower. Her impulse to gratify the child may be over-ruled by the advice of the doctor ; her desire to soothe it may, if it is ill-tempered, be post- poned to considerations of discipline. Her passing impulses are transformed into an abiding love ; her temporary and occasional services, each with its own immediate purpose, become elements in a more permanent, more comprehensive, purpose. Her action as a whole is still based on feeling, and the feeling, if you will, is of instinctive character, but it also involves a wider con- sciousness, a more reflective consideration of the nature and bearing of her actions, an increased capacity of inhibiting immediate impulse, and guiding the behaviour of the moment by ideas of permanent value. Finally, if a woman, capable of all the wealth of maternal feeling, knows herself to be the victim of some fell hereditary disease, and on that ground renounces the hope of motherhood altogether, a deliberate consideration of good and evil results overcomes in her the whole prompting of instinct, and if her renunciation is still based on feeling it is a form of feeling which reflection alone makes possible. To all this the retort will doubtless be that we are labouring the obvious and omitting the essential. No one questions (it will be said) that impulses may be con- trolled, but they are controlled not by reason, but by other impulses that happen to conflict with them. In the last analysis all that " reflection," or anything that we can call reasoning, does is to trace out consequences which show the bearing of one impulse on another. It thus multiplies points of contact, and therefore of possible conflict. But the conflict once joined, the victory is to the strong. The most forceful impulse prevails, and the force of an impulse is something which we may feel, but which we do not alter by reasoning about it. To test this account we must enquire further into the meaning of "im- pulse," the function of feeling, and the nature of control. CHAPTER II IMPULSE AND CONTROL i. THE term impulse has a wider and a narrower signification. In its narrower sense it is opposed to purpose. An impulsive action, e.g. a blow or a threat- ening gesture made in sudden anger, has a definite direction or tendency, e.g. the injury or intimidation of the antagonist. But it does not involve thought. It does not wait for the formation of an idea of its own outcome. On the contrary, the impulsive man acts first and thinks afterwards. But though in impulsive action we do not think we seem always to feel, e.g. in our illustration we feel the hot emotion of anger, and the feeling among other things distinguishes impulsive action from the mechanical reflex. Moreover the element of feeling persists all along the line, and its changes of tone affect the impulse. Thus, if the blow gets home it is probable that the emotion cools down and no further impulse is formed. On the other hand, if the emotion remains the impulse continues. The correlation is so close that we might be tempted to identify them, but we soon discover discrepancies. Thus extreme emotion tends to paralyse impulse, while swift and effective impulse seems (to put it paradoxically) to satisfy emotion before it is fully excited. Furthermore, if the impulse does not satisfy the feeling it may be suspended or reversed. When the timid creature who cannot escape pursuit turns to bay, the flight impulse is discarded as an unfaithful servant, and fear itself elects to fight. Feeling and impulse, though doubtless rooted in the same fundamental suscep- 36 IMPULSE AND CONTROL 37 tibilities and requirements, are distinct branches on the stem, and do not operate on the same lines or on identical conditions. We can best understand their relations by considering the conditions of their development. 2. According to the general evolutionary theory, the structure of an organism grows up under the conditions of the struggle for existence. That is to say, organs useful not only to the individual, but to the stock in that struggle tend to be preserved, and therefore to develop, while organs that are useless or injurious tend to atrophy and disappear. What is true of physical organs will also be true of psychological functions, in as far as psychological functions determine the behaviour of any organism. Whatever in an organism tends to govern its action in relation to its environment must have its effect upon the fortunes of the organism and upon the question whether it will survive and perpetuate its stock. Thus in all the lower ranges of life survival value to the stock is the governing condition upon which the perpetuation of a mode of action depends, and this applies to the psychological just as much as to the physical basis of such action. Some hereditary modes of action seem to be purely mechanical, like the knee-jerk or the narrowing of the pupil in bright light. Others are impulsive in character, devoid of foresight, but informed with feeling and a certain awareness of the objects which excite them. Such are the reactions of anger or fear. Whether such hereditary impulses should as a class be called instincts, or whether the term should be reserved for certain sub- classes need not be discussed here. Nor need we go into the difficult questions of the psychology of instinct. We must, however, note that some hereditary impulses are very definite and difficult to modify. They work with great precision as long as conditions are favourable, but have little power of adapting themselves to changes or peculiarities of the environment. Such is the character of many of the most remarkable instincts of insects. 1 1 Innumerable illustrations may be found in the writings of Fabre and of Mr. and Mrs. Peckham (The Habits and Instincts 38 THE RATIONAL GOOD Others, on the contrary, are plastic and variable. They seem to require something to complete or define them, and they certainly admit of modification. We have now to ask how this modification arises. Far down in the animal world we find indubitable evidence of individual experience entering in as a factor. We find original impulses checked or encouraged, as the case may be, by experience of the results in which they issue, and on the analogy of our own consciousness an analogy which for our purpose we need not criticize with any detail we interpret this experience as consisting in a pleasurable or painful feeling pleasurable in the case in which the impulse is encouraged, painful in the case where it is inhibited. 1 The nature of the change may be best under- of Solitary Wasps), Here is one. The egg of Chalicodoma is laid in a sealed cell. When the grub hatches out it eats its way through the cell wall into the outer world. Fabre set it a problem by lining the cell wall with paper, but the grub ate through paper and wall. He then varied the problem by leaving an interval between the paper and the wall. This was too much for the larva. It ate through the paper and then stopped. It was wound up to eat once but not twice. It would, however, be a mistake to infer that all the instincts of the Hymenoptera are of this mechanical character. On many occasions they show remarkable powers of varying their behaviour to suit special circumstances. The really baffling thing about them is the intermixture of the apparently mechanical with the apparently intelligent. Yet, after all, if they could observe human behaviour they might be almost equally bewildered by the intermingling of crass inertia with originality and initiative. 1 It is usual to speak of feelings of pleasure or pain. But it should be understood that pleasure is a character or tone common to many feelings which in other respects are quite distinct. Thus, there is a pleasure in feeling warm and also in the emotions of a great success. The feelings are very different, but agree in the tone of pleasure. If we call them feelings of pleasure that is merely a linguistic variant for pleasurable feeling. It may be doubted whether there is any feeling which could be accurately described as a feeling of pleasure and nothing else, unless it be some dream- like ecstasy in which all definiteness of content has vanished. Pain on the other hand is used ambiguously, meaning sometimes the feeling tone opposed to pleasure, sometimes certain substantive states, aches, smarts, pricks, etc. Some psychologists on this IMPULSE AND CONTROL 39 stood from a well-known example. A newly-hatched chick will peck indiscriminately, and with an approxima- tion to accuracy, at all manner of small objects strewn about on the ground. This pecking impulse is then apparently inherited as part of the mechanism with which the chick comes ready prepared to face the world. But at this stage the chick will peck with equal avidity at nutritious and innutritious objects. It will peck at grains of corn, for example ; it will also peck at small pieces of orange-peel. But there is a difference in the results. When it pecks at the corn it swallows with avidity ; when it pecks at the orange-peel it gives signs which we inter- pret as signs of displeasure, wiping the bill, for example, and rejecting the morsel ; and after a few experiences ground object to the use of the term pain as the reverse of pleasure. They lay stress on the point that the concrete pains are not always wholly displeasurable, e.g. as counter-irritants or a relief from boredom. Personally I confess to being satisfied with an extremely moderate indulgence in this particular kind of satisfaction. In general the pleasurableness or the reverse of a feeling depends not only on its character but on its degree. Sweetness is pleasant, and more and more pleasant to a point, beyond which it cloys and rapidly becomes disgusting. There is an optimum point at which the pleasure is at its highest. Th s is clearly true of sensory pleasures, and it is on the whole true of emotions, though here the optimum point is much nearer to the maximum of which our feeling is capable. On the whole, however, I think the paradox holds that our moderate joys are more pleasurable than our extreme joys. How far does pain follow a similar curve ? A smart at its lowest stage is little more than a titillation and may even be momentarily agreeable, but it passes so rapidly into the opposite character that we think of smarts, as such, as pains. The slight ache of healthy fatigue is not unpleasant, but aches cannot set in in earnest without being pains. Much the same may be said of melancholy, grief, anger, fear. All these have a pleasurable or at least a bitter-sweet phase, while their further developments are painful in the extreme. It is pretty certain that both sensory and emotional pain, like pleasure, have a maximum (which defeats the ingenuity of torturers), and I incline to think that there is a point in the intensity of the feeling from which the painful character undergoes a decline. Whe.her emotional or sensorial pain seems to involve some reaction of consciousness on feeling, some dis- tinctness therefore between the feeling and the residual self. Now 40 THE RATIONAL GOOD a single one is sometimes enough it learns to leave the orange-psel severely alone. So the chick undergoes a certain education, the broad effect of which is that its diffused and undefined impulse to peck is modified in a way which is very important for the future of the chick itself. It is defined so that there remains only an impulse to peck at certain things, while others are spontaneously neglected. This experience we put down on grounds which, as I say, we here assume to be sufficient, as con- sisting essentially in feelings pleasurable or painful. We assume, that is, that the chick finds the grain of corn pleasant, and the orange-peel bitter and disagreeable. Now, if we make this assumption, a consequence of importance follows with regard to the nature of feeling. We understand this consequence best if we ask first what is the value biologically of this new power of the chicken to learn from experience. The value lies in this, that it enlarges the possible sphere of action. Organisms, which are incapable of learning from experience, may come into the world ready equipped with a structural machinery which guides them with great precision within a certain range. Outside that range they are at a loss how to act, and, in point of fact, they perish for this reason in large numbers, and the stock only maintains itself in virtue of a very high birth-rate. But where learning from experience becomes possible the instinct itself may be more elastic. It may afford a basis for action in a larger variety of circumstances, and if it does not guide there seems to be a stage at which this distinctness is lost and the feeling is for the time all reality " all things were transformed into the agony I wore." At this stage the feeling is more like an outer object and paradoxically is less felt, or more literally is of diminishing painfulness. The next stage is of course the confusion, deadening and final loss of consciousness and therefore of feeling itself. On this view popular usage calls pains feelings which, over nearly the whole range of their intensity, have painful character. I see no reason on account of this usage to expel pain from its use in psychology as the opposite of pleasure, it being understood that in psychological nomenclature both terms signify not feelings, but tones of feeling. IMPULSE AND CONTROL 41 the creature so precisely from the first, it enables it to be guided by its own experience of what is useful or harmful, and so to govern its behaviour as its conditions require in an extended sphere of action. But this salutary result depends on one condition. Experience of pleasure and pain can only aid in preserving the individual or the stock if the pleasurable feelings are excited by actions that are upon the whole beneficial, and painful feelings by actions which are on the whole injurious. The conclusion, then, to which our evolutionary account forces us is that, just as impulse must on the whole be beneficial, so feeling must on the whole run in channels tending to survival. Two remarks must be subjoined here to avoid misunder- standing. Pleasure, as we know in our own case, is not always healthy, either from the point of view of the individual or society. There may be bad pleasures, and there may be pleasures which we deem good, but which have no discernible bearing on survival e.g. the pleasures of art. The reason of this is that survival- value is not the cause of variations, but their limiting condition. It secures that the organs, their functions, and, generally, all that goes to determine the behaviour of the organism should be on the balance suited to the maintenance of the stock ; but it does not render it by any means impossible that organs or modes of behaviour should arise which are indifferent or even harmful to survival, provided always that in the normal case the stock- preserving organs and functions predominate ; and it will easily be seen that the more highly developed the organism, that is to say, the greater its power of mastering the conditions of its life, the greater will be its scope for indulgence in the impulses and feelings of this kind. Hence it is that man of all evolving beings the one which has greatest control over the conditions of his life is capable on the one hand of interests extending far beyond any questions of survival, on the other of impulses violating on the largest scale the conditions of a healthy life. We must not therefore exaggerate the rough and general correspondence between impulse and 42 THE RATIONAL GOOD pleasure on the one hand, and survival- value on the other ; nor, to come to the second point, must we unduly limit the conception of survival-value. That which governs the formation of primitive strata of impulse and feeling is their survival-value, not merely to the individual but to the stock. If the impulse which serves the individual survives, it is rather because through the individual it perpetuates the stock than because it serves the needs of the individual as such. Hence the evolutionary view is opposed to an egoistic account of the primitive basis of impulse and pleasure. The logical consequence to be drawn from biological principles properly understood, is that from the first both impulse and feeling are directed to acts in which others are concerned primarily, the mate and the young, but also in animals that live together, the flock or the herd, or, in such cases as those of the social insects, the animal community. Impulse and feeling alike, then, may to this extent be from their origin altruistic or social in character. We are led, then, to conceive of feeling as a mode of consciousness, the biological function of which is to govern impulse. We may regard it as the response of the hereditary structure, a structure which we are thus forced to conceive as having a psychical side, i.e. as some- thing manifesting itself in consciousness, as well as a physical side, i.e. as something manifesting itself in movements. What we feel will thus be determined in the first place by the structure the psycho-physical structure, as we may call it, to express its double nature just as the impulse is determined by the structure, and the feeling operates, if painful, by checking the impulse, if pleasurable, by encouraging it. 3. But impulse, though governed and re-adjusted by the feeling attendant on its results, does not yet of necessity imply a conscious purpose. The chick's impulse to peck at yolk may be encouraged by its past experience. But this is not a sufficient ground for imputing to it what we know as a remembrance of that experience, or the anticipation of another experience of like character. In IMPULSE AND CONTROL 43 ourselves, however, we are aware of such memories and anticipations, and it is here that what we can fairly call purpose emerges. In the chick's case all that we know is that experience leaves a certain effect, leaves a trace which we know to exist because we see the result in a change of behaviour, though we may know little of its nature. 1 In our case, as stated, we do know something of its nature. We know that on the ground of past experience an idea is formed of a future experience, of an experience that will be gained by a certain act, and this idea regulates the act, reinforcing or checking the impulse to perform it. When an impulse is qualified by such an idea and directed towards an end so antici- pated, it becomes purposive in the true sense of the term and in its first incarnation we may call it a desire. Desire, then, so understood, will be rooted in impulse on the one side and in feeling on the other. 3 The two sources tend 1 We speak of it sometimes as a habit, sometimes as a disposition. Of the precise physical change of tissue involved in the formation of such states we know nothing by direct observation, and the psy- chological state involved in a " disposition " is exceedingly difficult to formulate except in terms of the action or state of consciousness in which in response to the appropriate situation it issues. It is natural to say that the end towards which Desire is directed is the pleasure in the experience. But this does not conform with psychological analysis. What we desire is the experience itself, and our desire has a feeling-tone of its own corre- spondent (not necessarily identical) with the feeling-tone of the desired experience. In fact our power of representing to our- selves a past or future feeling as distinctive from the experience to which it belongs is small and perhaps nil. We can (a) judge intellectually that such a feeling did or will occur, (b) experience now a feeling about the past or future experience. Neither of these is the same thing as the formation of a representative image of a feeling as adequate as our representative image of, say, a figure. Hence it is that our most poignant memories are attached to details sometimes quite trivial details in the scene in which the emotional crisis was cast. Oh, moment one and infinite, The water slips o'er stock and stone ; The West is tender, hardly bright : How grey at once is the evening grown One star its chrysolite. 44 THE RATIONAL GOOD to correspondence, partly because both alike are governed by the conditions of existence, and partly because the experience of feeling is always at work correcting the operation of impulse. At the same time, since desire is thus doubly rooted, we can never be sure that it will coincide with the pleasurable experience which is only one root of the two. They tend to coincidence, but do not necessarily reach it. Often we still feel impelled inexorably to an act from which we know that only disappointment will result. The control of experience is not strong enough to overcome original impulse, and we are forced to desire what will only give us pain. Still, as far as it goes, experience gives unity of direction to impulse, and adjusts it better to the permanent conditions of life as attested by the satisfaction felt in its accom- plishment. It will be observed that the definition of Desire as Impulse directed towards an anticipated end conflicts formally with the narrower usage, which expressly bars anticipation from Impulse. It is here that the double sense of the term impulse appears. For in Desire, and in every action directed towards an end there is precisely the same impulse-feeling that we find in impulsive action proper. The difference is merely that in experiencing the impulse the mind knows what it is about, is conscious of its direction, and foresees or looks towards its final issue. For the purposes of this discussion we shall use the term impulse of this propelling element common to all forms of action, and when we wish to speak of this element as denuded of any anticipation of the end we shall call it " bare " impulse. 1 The picture revives the emotion, not an image of the emotion. The point is well brought out by Dr. Wohlgemuth, though it is possible that his generalization is too sweeping (Pleasure- Unpleasure, p. 218, etc.). For our immediate purpose the result is that the driving force in desire is the tone of present feeling attached to an idea. 1 The technical generic term for Impulse, Desire, and Will is Conation. But there does not seem to be an accepted distinctive term for the element which is common to them all. IMPULSE AND CONTROL 45 4. Desire in its stricter sense seems to be directed to this or that particular object or event, whether it be one's dinner, or success in a competition, or a political triumph, or the possession of a piece of old china. These particulars, however, are not isolated and casual, but are found for the most part to range themselves about certain centres of durable interest. Thus a parent desires a number of different things for his child according as the circum- stances and needs of his child vary from day to day, or year to year. But all the desires alike emanate from the same centre of emotional interest, and, moreover, are controlled by it, so that, e.g., a desire to gratify the child here and now is held back by consideration of some more permanent effect. The system of emotions that cluster round an object, such as another person, is now called a sentiment, and the effect of sentiment on action is that all the impulses and desires relating to the object have a certain common tendency, e.g. the good of the child. In this case the good of the child is an object of volition, and volition is thus not so much a specific impulse as a permeating tendency among a body of impulses and desires, or, if we turn it round and judge it by its aim, it is the direction of effort towards some comprehensive end, to which a mass of impulses and desires are subordinated as being that which makes their real meaning and value explicit. Thus volition introduces unity of direction into desire, just as desire introduced unity into the lower impulses. 5. Now in a normal life there are, of course, many objects which are such centres of durable interest, and there would seem accordingly to be many volitions, and a fair possibility of discord between them. But our personality is one, and it is driven to find some means of correlating them. In normal circumstances normal people can always decide, whether between volitions, desires, or impulses. This power of decision is what we ordinarily call the Will, and it seems to postulate a certain unity of our conative nature, and correlatively some supreme unifying principle, rule, or end of action, setting 46 THE RATIONAL GOOD out the real meaning of our life as a whole, just as any partial volition sets out the real value of the desires and impulses bearing upon its object. In reality, however, this unity l is achieved with a measure of success, which varies very materially with the idiosyncracies of the individual and with the social tradition which supplies the main outer guidance of his life. Where there is a genuine religion, some supreme object or governing con- ception of life so rich and many-sided that smaller things find their appropriate place under its shadow, the solution seems near. Where there is a definite and firmly-held morality there is at least the means of deciding on particular issues. Even a resolute egoism or the obstinate pursuit of a limited object gives some unity to life, though a gaunt and starved unity. If all such governing principles fail we have a being like Plato's " Democratic Man," who decides one thing one moment, and something contrary the next moment, and though such a being has Will, in that he does make decisions, he cannot be said to have Will in the sense of any continuous and consistent direction. It will be seen that the function of the Will is to bring unity into our volitions, as the function of volition was to unify desires. 2 The relation of will to 1 I.e. the unity of consistent action and coherent plan. The basal unity of the self is the continuous identity of that which experiences all the impulses, feelings, etc., whether these lead it to harmonious or distracted and mutually incompatible lines of action. * This terminology is open to criticism on two grounds, (a) It may be said that Volition is merely Latin for " willing," and that I am therefore contrasting willing with will. I might reply that this is pretty much what I mean to do. Our practical attitude towards one of the permanent objects of our interest is, I think, a department of our will, but it is not the whole will. Thus even in e.g. our devotion to a child we must not be like ces peres de families qui sont capables de tout. Thus the contrast is, so to put it, between a will and the will, and since we cannot conveniently use the term " a will " in this sense I substitute " a volition." (6) It may be said that we desire success in many of these permanent objects. The felt contrast between Desire and Will is that, in Desire the end is attractive, and in will it may be either attractive or constrained. This is because Will is concerned with a Whole IMPULSE AND CONTROL 47 general conceptions has seldom escaped attention. It has been well understood that in the cool deliberation which distinguishes voluntary action we bring impulse and desire to the bar of general rules and permanent interests. Before being led by impulse we weigh the result and put a value on the anticipated fruition, and we value it not merely by measuring the particular satis- faction which it promises against the frustration of some other impulse which it may involve, but rather by reference to some standard of admitted value and of general applica- tion. We consider its bearings on our permanent interests, or on the interests of some other person, we ask whether it conforms to law, morals, or religion, we weigh it by standards and principles that we apply to others as well as to ourselves. That is to say, the characteristic of the deliberate voluntary action which distinguishes human from animal action lies in the formation oi general principles of action which tend to correlate our behaviour from moment to moment with the purposes which belong to our life as a whole and to the lives of others with whom we are associated. We are able to do what, apparently, the animal cannot do to conceive ourselves as a persistent identity, abiding through the changing experiences of life, and correspondingly conceive of others as identities of the same kind, that is in a word as personalities. We are able at the same time to appreciate as general truths the rules of action which have grown up in such a community of persons to determine the character of their common life. It is accordingly in proportion to the development of such relatively comprehensive ends of which only some fraction is for the moment in question and the interests of the whole overwhelm the attractiveness of the fraction if there happens to be a collision. Desire and Will may therefore coincide or be opposed. There is no objection to the use of the term Desire in relation to the widest objects, but they are not objects of Desire merely but of Will as well, because they are still pursued in the specific forms or particular direction in which they do not momentarily appear attractive. This holds not only of governing principles of all life but of any enduring objects. Such an object is therefore an object of volition. 48 THE RATIONAL GOOD and principles of action that human conduct comes to form a relatively regulated order, and social life an organized whole. 7. On the other hand the relation of Will to general principles has given rise to great difficulties by suggesting a chasm between Will and impulse-feeling. Will itself must have impulsive quality (in the general sense of the term), or how could it govern us ? But what impulse is or can be inspired by general and abstract principles without reference to the concrete objects in which they are realized ? The reply is that the real meaning of a principle lies in the correlation of a mass of concrete objects which it effects, and so similarly the -strength or impelling force of the Will lies in the correlation of the corresponding impulses. Just as the principle expresses their meaning in general terms, so the Will expresses their common, combined, or organized force. The material, so to say, of Will is just the mass of impulse- feeling, but this mass, instead of acting as a collection of independent forces driving us hither and thither, is organized in a clearer conception of results, and more comprehensive views of life. Out of the original conational tissue which gave rise to feeling and impulse and desire, there develops, if the metaphor be allowed, a new and more precise organ of conduct. Of the original mass of impulses those elements which conflict are in part worn away, in part re-moulded so as to fit in with one another. Others are strengthened and confirmed by practice and by mutual alliance. All have assumed more concrete shape as they come into relation with experience. The total result, so far as the organization of conduct extends, is a synthesis of conational elements moving as a body under the guidance of some definite conception. To picture very imperfectly the nature of this development, let us first imagine the whole conative force of the soul dispersed in impulses and desires capable of acting each only in its own direction, under its appropriate stimulus of sense-perception or of anticipated fruition. Let us then imagine in contrast a gathering of all this energy IMPULSE AND CONTROL 49 of feeling, of emotion, of conation, into an organized whole, moving in a determinate direction, and capable of bringing its whole force to bear at any point. This is the essential contrast between sheer impulse and fully developed will. We can conceive that such an organized psychic movement will present itself rather as the calm and ordered flow of a deep tide of vital energy than as the fireworks of emotion or the half-sensual flow of impulses. Though all these are at bottom one, as manifes- tations of feeling or conative energy, they differ in form and many important consequences flow from their differ- ence. Those err who attribute to bare impulse, emotion or will severally, that which is due to the energy within us which takes all these forms. Will is not emotion, though it is of the force which, dammed back from its outlet in ordered activity, forms the emotional flood. It is not bare impulse, but embodies the active energy of impulse within it. It is a gathering of much, ideally of the whole, conational energy of our nature canalized into a deep and steady stream flowing within determinate limits in ordered activity to foreseen ends It is then in the construction of broad ends, in which the otherwise scattered elements of our nature have their several functions, that the conational synthesis which we express by the term " will " takes its rise, and that our nature as a whole tends to acquire the permanent bent and definiteness of direction which distinguish the life of will from that of impulse and emotion. But the wholeness and unity of our nature remain ideals which are realized in very varying degree. We will, because, in the main, the forces of our nature set in a given direc- tion, but we do not will whole-heartedly because the synthesis is incomplete. The primary impulses remain, and the vision of the wider ends is not clear enough, or not realized with adequate intensity of feeling. And it is because, in the conflict between desire and will, we are urged by massed forces of impulse guided by con- ceptions which, perhaps, we can only in part make articu- late, that we have that sense of constraint which is so 50 THE RATIONAL GOOD conspicuous in the case of felt moral obligation, where there is a definite tension between the rebellious desire and the orderly community which we express as " will." In this tension there is the force of a clearly realized appealing end on the one hand, and the more massive, perhaps less intensely and definitely conscious, main current of our nature upon the other. It diminishes accordingly as the will acquires full control, though it can never vanish for the best of men as long as the tragic complexities of life set duty in opposition to ties of affection. A morality which should be as spontaneous as instinct implies not only a perfect will, but a perfect order of life. 1 Will, then, is the synthesis of impulsive or conative elements in man that responds to comprehensive ends and unifying principles, just as desire is the impulsive element that responds to narrower and more immediate ends. Though bare impulse is left far behind, the impul- sive energies, pruned, refined, consolidated, remain the driving force to the end. Just as action always rests on impulse in this broad sense, so impulse turns on feeling in a similarly broad sense. The term feeling so used is to include the emotion that governs the simplest impulse. It is to include the interest, the excitement, the emotional tone which the idea of the end carries in the period of 1 Our argument tends to the close correlating of the will with the self or the personality and to conceive its ends as those of the self as a whole. This does not imply that the will is peculiarly moved by the idea of the self, or by sentiments and emotions of self-exaltation or self-abasement. Such reflective inward-turned emotions do of course play their part. But to identify the will with the unity of the self in its conational aspect is not to make the self the object of the will. The object of the will, the principles that guide it, are those which interest the self and these are not (for the normal being) the self again. The self is not its own exclusive object, but many things God, humanity, country, morality, another person or persons objects such as these govern- ing large tracts of life are true objects of, or principles guiding, Will. Though some of them may not affect life as a whole they impart a far larger measure of unity than would be achieved by mere impulse or emotion. IMPULSE AND CONTROL 51 anticipation or effort. It is to include the gratification or disappointment which attend upon realization. It is to range from the simple impulses of sense to the most refined and complex interests of ethics, art, or religion. Throughout we may regard an end as the terminal point of a line of action upon which, as the resultant of a thousand tensions and pressures of physical heredity, of present experience, of social interactions, feeling moves. So we may conceive it as feeling crystallized into something definite and conceptual. In all cases a genuine end is something about which we feel, and there is no principle of action derivable from thought or ratiocination abstracted from feeling. On the other hand, feeling is modifiable, and the purposes in which it expresses itself still more modifiable. Experience largely remodels impulse, or suggests new means to the same ends. Divergent ends impinge on one another, social relations not only define the possi- bilities of effective action for the individual, but inter- penetrate and profoundly modify the whole sphere of his feeling itself. Religious and scientific beliefs give the tone to the mass of men's hopes and fears. Hence a double possibility of thorough modification. In a changed intellectual or social situation the same fundamental feelings may give rise to a very different body of purpose, while such changes, and even its own internal growth and interactions, may have far-reaching reactions upon feeling itself. In the sense understood, then, action rests on impulse-feeling, and it is useless to look for anything, call it Practical Reason, Will, or what we may, that stands outside the body of impulse-feeling and controls it. But impulse-feeling is completely trans- formed by a development, which taken as a whole tends to combine its centrifugal elements into an organized body, directed to comprehensive ends which are formu- lated in large and articulate conceptions of the significance of conduct. It is within this development, if anywhere, that we must look for the practical Reason. Our first step in the search must clearly be to form as precise a 52 THE RATIONAL GOOD conception as possible of what is meant by the Rational, and the next to apply our definition in the sphere of conduct. NOTE Since this chapter was written Dr. Wohlgemuth's able mono- graph Pleasure-Unpleasure, has appeared, advocating views of Feeling which, in some points, conflict with those taken above. While I am not here concerned with psychological analysis and do not think that the divergencies in question would sensibly affect ethical theory, I feel obliged to explain why I leave my statement standing, with a modification which I will proceed to state. The main points are two : (i) As to nomenclature, Dr. Wohlgemuth treats it as settled that pain is not the true contrast to pleasure, but is a positive sensation which may be pleasant or unpleasant feeling-tone. As to this, I am inclined to reply : It is agreed that we must distinguish between the feeling-tone of an experience and the whole experience to which the feeling-tone belongs. The traditional psychological nomenclature, as I understand, used the terms Pleasure and Pain for this purpose, viz. as names of two great (if not exhaustive) classes of feeling-tone. But popular language also uses Pain for the whole experience in certain cases, e.g. aches and burns, and not in others, e.g. foul smells. Hence there is a possible confusion which it is certainly desirable to avoid. But does not very nearly the same confusion arise about pleasure ? Here it is that I would modify a sentence (p. 38, footnote). It is true, pleasures do not form so definite a class as pains in popular speech. Yet a good deal of ethical controversy has turned on the relation of pleasure and happiness, and on the whole " pleasure," in ordinary speech, suggests, if not a defined class, at any rate a range of experiences centering on the more elementary rather than the higher side of our nature. Yet to me it seems that the deepest tranquil happiness (as of assured love or firm religious faith) has a strong feeling-tone and that this feeling-tone, with all its vast difference of significance, has a point in common with that of a sensory satisfaction. Be that as it may, there is a clear distinction between pleasure as a feeling-tone and pleasure as the whole experience to which the feeling-tone belongs, and when pleasure is so used the same considerations arise as in the case of pain. For " pleasures " cloy, i.e. assume unpleasant feeling- one just as pains sometimes stimulate, excite, titillate, i.e. assume more or less pleasurable feeling-tone. Hence, if the argument is pressed we must abandon pleasure along with pain and find some quite conventional terms, or perhaps symbols such as P and fl for the opposed feeling-tones in distinction from the experiences IMPULSE AND CONTROL 53 which normally carry such tones. To banish pain and retain pleasure seems illogical. The question of terms, however, runs, as such questions gener- ally do, into one of substance. Dr. Wohlgemuth maintains (esp. pp. 211, 235) that " there are only two qualities of feeling-elements, viz. Pleasure and Unpleasure. Any differences except intensity, duration, and extensity are apparent only and are found to belong to sensations or other cognitive or (to) conative processes." (I imagine that under " extensity " Dr. Wohlgemuth intends to include localization.) It follows that the only feeling-element common to a burning pain and a sickening fear is their unpleasure. All the rest is sensory (or otherwise cognitive) or conational. I find it, from my own introspection or retrospection, exceedingly difficult to accept this. The two states appear to me to agree in something much fuller and richer than the very attenuated abstraction of unpleasantness. This something I should call feeling, and while in each case the feeling has the generic character of unpleasure, I should say that it also exhibited profound specific differences. If you ask me to name these differences, I admit that I find it extremely difficult to do so (apart from localization) except by reference either to the stimulus (including the general situation) or some elements of conation. But I accept the view that the feeling is neither the cognition of the stimulating object nor the conation. I suppose it to be that which stands between and connects them, and I take the difficulty of describing it apart from them as evidence of the intimacy of the union. To a point Dr. Wohlgemuth would agree in this. His rule on the subject is : " The feeling-elements are not attributes or functions of sen- sations or other cognitive processes, but a separate class of conscious processes. Although generally closely dependent upon the cognitive and conative processes to which they belong, they often show a certain degree of independence and detachment." Now I do not think that any one would deny that analysis is capable of distinguishing the element of feeling-tone from the other elements in consciousness along with it. The question is, first, whether the feeling can exist independently of other elements, second, whether what can so exist is pure pleasure or unpleasure denuded of other qualitative content. As to the first point Dr. Wohlgemuth adduces evidence (e.g. that the pleasure may precede the sensation). Here he has only one case (p. 184, referring to exp. Y. 24, see p. 108). What " Y " exactly says is : " First, feeling-tone of pressure sensation (seemed to be pressure down- wards) which was not unpleasant. As pressure increased it became more unpleasant. As the feeling-tone became markedly un- pleasant sensation of pain arose. The unpleasant feeling- tone preceded the pain sensation. I can analyse the unpleasant feeling- tone from the pressure sensation, but not from the pain-sensation.'* 54 THE RATIONAL GOOD This passage (which by the way tells strongly against the quali- tative distinction between Pain and Unpleasure) does not show that unpleasant feeling-tone arises without any sensation, but only without that definite sensation called by the writer Pain. It arose in the first instance with the pressure and, in its higher degree (as my terminology would put it) became so distinctly painful as to be recognized as such. As to pleasure outlasting sensation, every one knows that the effects of stimuli persist for a little while. The question is in what form does the feeling persist ? Dr. Wohlgemuth has three in- stances. The first of these (W. 32, p. 26) concludes : " There were also organic sensations which seemed to be an integral part of, or helped to constitute, a mood of repose which was distinctly pleasant. Pleasure lasted for some time after removal of stimulus." This speaks for itself. The second case from the same subject is an olfactory experiment in which, without further detail bearing on the point, the subject states, " Pleasure persisted for some time after removal." In fact, scents hang in the nostrils. In the third case, also olfactory, the subject says, " After the stimulus had been removed I had an idea of the act of smelling, and the idea had none of the olfactory quality of the original experience, but it retained the feeling-tone that had accompanied the sensation." That is, the feeling-tone is explicitly attached to the idea. It results that the cases cited do not prove the thesis that feelings arise or persist independently of either cognitive or conative elements. Secondly, as to what the feelings are. Several statements agree that they are distinguishable elements in consciousness, but dis- tinguishable with difficulty. Here is a typical statement (X. 101, quoted p. 211). " As to the quality of the feeling-tones of the sensations, I cannot compare definitely enough to perceive any qualitative difference in them. The difficulty is to distinguish the feeling- tones from the quality of the sensations on the one hand, and the quality of the motor reactions excited on the other hand. Allowing for these differences there seemed to be nothing left except differences of duration and intensity." This will obviously be the result if we put all the qualitative differences into the cognitive or conative elements one or both. But if we do so all that is left for feeling is something so abstract that the subjects have difficulty in distinguishing it. They will agree that it is pleasurable or unpleasurable, because these are admittedly general (if not universal) qualities of feeling. But we are asked to think of this element distinguished so vaguely and with such difficulty as all that we mean by feeling and as capable of an independent existence. It is the combination of these pro- positions which appears to me so difficult. If you will allow me IMPULSE AND CONTROL 55 to include within the scope of feeling elements that you insist on calling cognitive or conative I have no great difficulty in regarding feeling as independent, i.e. as requiring no further co-present element in consciousness to complete it. But if you insist on excluding all these you fall back on what seems to me an abstrac- tion. The most I can admit (as in the text) is that in extreme cases the cognitive elements, that is all that is distinguishable, get merged into one ecstasy of delight or suffering, but I point out that this is the last stage before the entire loss of consciousness, and very significantly, it has been recognized as a stage in which extremes very nearly meet and pleasure and pain themselves are on the verge of becoming undistinguishable. Perhaps I should also add that, at the opposite extreme where feeling is minimal, analysis will find its pleasant or unpleasant character the easiest point to lay hold of. These extreme cases to my mind rather strengthen the position that definite pleasures are attributes of feelings of definite quality other than pure pleasureableness. The further proof, as I think, is that the intensity of feeling does not vary uniformly with its pleasantness or unpleasantness. For example, anger may be very intense but is not proportionately painful unless thwarted. All states of emotional tension are capable at a touch of turning to extremes of pleasant or unpleasant feeling, but while they are themselves very strongly felt the characters of pleasure or unpleasure are not always clearly marked in them. The conclusions which, as at present advised, I should draw are that definite feeling is attached to cognitive or conative elements or both ; that, however, its variations of intensity do not neces- sarily depend on their variations (in clearness, etc.) and it may persist with little or no change through considerable variations of the other element ; that in consequence (though I have criticized his evidence) Dr. Wohlgemuth is right in his conclusion that feeling possesses a partial independence ; that in fact feeling may so encroach on the other elements as in the extreme case to occupy the whole of consciousness ; that at this limit, it would seem, even the knowledge of the feeling certainly any power of naming or classifying it must disappear. On the other hand, the feeling which possesses this measure of independence includes elements which Dr. Wohlgemuth calls sensory or conative ; it exhibits numberless specific variations, and pleasure and unpleasure are merely two of its attributes. Pleasure and unpleasure never exist by themselves but only as characters of some feeling possessed of other characters, though in very low and perhaps in extremely high grades of feeling they are the most easily recognizable characters. I. WE have to ask, then, first what is meant by the Rational, by a rational procedure and a rational order ? If the question is difficult, it is perhaps easier to see what is meant by the Irrational. In the first place, then, inconsistency is admittedly irrational. It is irrational in the field of thought to admit two judgments which contradict each other, in the field of action to pursue two purposes which destroy one another, or to accept and approve a principle of action condemning a purpose which at the same time we pursue. Conversely the rational, whatever else it may be, must at least be self- consistent. Next, though perhaps less obviously, the arbitrary judgment is irrational. This will be more readily admitted if for " arbitrary " we substitute " groundless." It is irrational to form a judgment without a ground, and whatever else we may say about " grounds " it is clear from the very fact that a ground is required, and may not always be found that the ground contains something which is not within the judgment that follows from it. If, then, we would avoid a ground- less judgment we must be able to connect our judgment with something that goes beyond it, and this work of interconnexion is the main positive function of reason. Thirdly, it is held irrational to base a judgment on emotion or desire, or, indeed, on any " subjective " attitude, any impulse that proceeds merely from ourselves. But this condemnation must be subject to two qualifications. In the first place the judgment may be about the emotions, or may be simply an expression of the emotions, e.g. " This 56 THE RATIONAL 57 is revolting," " that is enchanting." For judgments of this class the emotion itself is the only appropriate ground. Secondly, every judgment of mine as it issues from me must in a manner be held to emanate from my subjec- tivity, to be an expression of my thought working in accordance with the methods and processes of my mental constitution. It seems, then, that we cannot mean to condemn the subjective altogether. What we must mean is to condemn it in so far as it diverts us from the objective, and this means something that is, whether you or I happen to think so, or say so, or not. The rational, then, is that which deals with the objective order. But the objective is not unfortunately so plainly hall-marked that we distinguish it immediately and infallibly from the subjective, and if we ask how we effect the distinction the answer is, by the two former require- ments of rationality. We correct error by the exposure of inconsistency. We arrive at such exposure by the interconnexion of one judgment with another. We support judgments by reference to their grounds, and then believe that we have obtained objectivity or, more briefly, truth. Truth, then, is generally the object of reason or the purpose of the rational procedure, and interconnexion subject to mutual consistency its method. 2. But now with regard to interconnexion some serious difficulties arise. First, we have said that we believe the grounded judgment to be true. But this implies that the ground is adequate, and we may well ask what is the test of adequacy. The ground itself, in fact, seems to require a ground, and this threatens to lead to an infinite regress. There must, it should seem, be some primary grounds requiring no further justification, but if so the judgments affirming them would be isolated judgments, and so far, apparently, irrational. And must we not, apart from them, admit other isolated judgments ? I heard a clap. I can bring no evidence in support of my assertion, it may be, and yet the fact is that 1 heard it. That is of itself evidence. It is an ultimate fact, and there is no more to be said. Even if others heard it too, 58 THE RATIONAL GOOD and I bring their evidence in corroboration, is not the ultimate basis a distinct and ungrounded judgment, just " I heard it " from each witness ? There seem, then, to be isolated judgments, e^x , at each end of the scale the most general grounds, and the final particular fact. With regard to the particular, however, a little reflec- tion will show that the judgment which we accept as true is not so isolated as it appears, and that in fact we finally accept it only as grounded, and well grounded, on a general principle. If the question is, did a clap occur, my evidence that I heard it is good in so far, and only in so far, as I am a credible witness, and as my subjective hearing is good proof of an objective sound. In so far as I accept in general the testimony of my senses I assert what they report, so that my particular assertion has a ground in the sense that it is connected with the general body of my sensory judgments, and is, in fact, to be taken as valid in proportion as this body of judgments is to be regarded as generally accurate, and as it the judgment in question is a normal part of them, and is not disturbed by anything exceptional. All evidence as to " particulars " is in fact subject to tests and open to corroboration on such lines as these. Thus the sensory judgment, direct and ultimate as it is, is in its wa}^ a grounded judgment. Yet this statement in turn gives rise to a difficulty. For the ground is in this case another judgment or body of judgments of the same kind. In proof of the existence of a sensible object we may appeal from sound to sight, and from sight to touch, and from one man's sight or touch to another's, but we are always appealing from one sensory judgment to another, and if we appeal to the general credibility of sensory judgments on what would this rest, except on the credibility of numbers of particular sensory judgments ? If, therefore, the intrinsic value of a sensory judgment is nil, and our confidence in it based only on its grounds, these grounds turn out to be equally of zero value, and, the sum of zeros being zero, we get no nearer to any ground of real confidence. It results that we must not deny all value THE RATIONAL 59 to a direct sensory judgment ; if we are going to trust the system formed by such judgments we must allow each such judgment provisional value, such that when confirmed by interconnexion with other judgments of similar provisional value it becomes for us a confirmed or established judgment. This principle may be put generally. A judgment which we form under some stimulus, but not merely on the ground of some other judgment, may be called an immediate judgment. Such judgment has in reason a provisional value, and when interconnected with other immediate judgments so that if they are true it is true it becomes a rationally established judgment. 3. At what point would the process be complete so that we could take the established judgment as estab- lished once for all, beyond possibility of further question or need of further proof ? Clearly it would be complete if we could connect it with some judgments of undoubted truth, which must, of course, in the end be immediate judgments. Now immediate sensory judgments, we have seen, require grounding, for no matter how clearly and forcibly their objects seem to impress themselves upon us we find by comparison that our reports of such objects are not always self -consistent, and though we may admit that there is a core of truth in every immediate sensory judgment, the questions that arise are those of distin- guishing the hard core from the interpretations that gather about it, and this it is clear the immediate judgment does not always effect, since we know cases in which it is erroneous. Are there, then, immediate judgments at the other end of the scale, ultimate generalities of un- doubted truth on which all other judgments may be grounded, and so established once and for all ? Now there certainly appear to be judgments of a general character which are as immediate as the judgments of sense. That is to say, that, contemplating certain ideal objects, we become directly aware in them of relations or characters attaching to them. Propound to the mind the idea of a plane rectilineal figure of three sides 60 THE RATIONAL GOOD and explain the nature of an angle, and the mind will readily grasp that the three-sided figure must have three angles. This is correctly called intuition. In it a character of an object is discerned by a process of mental inspection, and the truth asserted may be called self-evident. But rational criticism will no more let these intuitive judgments alone than it would let sensory judgments alone. On the contrary, it will maintain that the self-evident judg- ment, so long as it is unconnected with others, has only provisional value, and it will accordingly go on to ask, as it did of the sensory judgment, what general credibility is to be attached to intuition. Is every immediate judg- ment that is formed by every mind to be taken as true, and so certainly true as to require no proof ? The answer to this question must be in the negative. It is easy to produce the illusion of immediate obviousness, e.g. a non-mathematical person questioned as to the shortest way from A to B, which is due east of it, will reply as a matter of course that the route must be due east all the way, and will resist as sheer nonsense the statement that a route moving to the north (or south) is in general shorter. But with the aid of a globe, or even a common ball, it is easy to convince even the least mathematical of his error in a couple of minutes. Of course the fallacy rests on a confusion of different things a straight line and a line drawn on the surface of a sphere. But at what point do we become certain that there are no similar elements of confusion in any truth which we affirm as a matter of intuitive apprehension ? Many people would say that to them the existence of a God is a truth of this kind. Others would deny that they have any such intuition. Mathematical axioms that have passed current for centuries have been called in question, and it has been shown possible to construct consistent systems of thought on a basis which involves their negation. Self-evidence is in fact the impression which a propounded object makes upon a mind which thereupon delivers itself of a judgment as to that object, interpreting it after some fashion. This deliverance is a function not of one variable, THE RATIONAL 61 the object, but of two, the object and the mind, with all its peculiarities of structure and make-up, its instincts, innate methods, and history by which these methods have been modified. This make-up may be such that the deliverance is a judgment asserting the object to be what it is, have the characters which it has, stand in the relations in which it does stand, or it may be such as to diverge in some degree or at some point from such corre- spondence. The test can only lie in consistency with other judgments. Here, as elsewhere, interconnexion is required. 4. If this view is correct it results that the basis of certainty and truth is in the end interconnexion. Any isolated judgment, though it may of course be quite true and may be felt to be quite certain, is regarded as pro- visional and subject to criticism and corroboration by other judgments. At the same time each immediate judgment which impresses itself on us as true contributes its measure of support to the system in which it enters, and the strength of the system is in the mutual support or consilience of its component judgments, so that in this case the ground (by way of exception to our first statement about grounds) is really internal. True, the entire system may also be connected with other systems, but if we could arrive at a system containing all thought and all experience, it could have no ground and no proof in anything outside itself, but only in its internal character as a complete system of interconnected parts. Thus the principle that ground or proof lies outside the judgment grounded and proved applies to the relation of part to part or to whole, but the ground or proof of a whole lies equally and in the case of the final ideal whole entirely in the very connectedness of parts, each claiming immediate acceptance, which constitute it. In this sense the ideal of knowledge is self -evidence, not the self- evidence of an isolated truth on which the rest depend, but that of the consilience of a system of partial truths completing each other. 5. Judgments asserting facts are connected by the relations of the facts which they assert. Hence the 62 THE RATIONAL GOOD demand of reason for the ground of any judgment is at the next remove a demand for the ground of the fact. The ground of a fact is such that if the ground exists we believe that the fact, known as its consequent, exists. This in other words amounts to the proposition that in any case where the ground exists the consequent exists. That is to say, the relation of ground and consequent is universal. The search for grounds is thus a search for universal relations underlying or connecting the mass of facts with which thought is confronted. The activity of reason consists in the discovery of universal grounds and their application when ascertained in fresh cases. So far as we reason about a thing we treat it as having a ground which connects it with other things, and as this connection can be constantly extended by repetition of the process we arrive at the ideal of reason as an order of reality built up of a system of universals interconnecting all its parts. 6. We rejected above the view that knowledge could be made to depend on certain universal first principles requiring no ground or interconnexion with other truths, because self-evident. But what, it may be asked, of the principles of interconnexion themselves ? We inter- connect one judgment with another by certain methods which, when we come to analyse them, will be found to involve some principle. How do we know the truth of this principle ? It would appear that we cannot prove it because proof would involve interconnection with something else, and the interconnection would itself imply the principle to be proven. The reply is that the validity of the principle rests on its being a correct analysis of the processes which we go through in reasoning so far as they are consistent with one another. In point of fact we do not always reason correctly, and the nature of our mistakes and their grounds are brought out when we analyse the method and formulate its principle. But if the principle is correctly stated it lays down a consistent method of inference, and every inference that we draw upon this method implies the principle. Thus, through THE RATIONAL 63 the medium of the principle all our acts of inference necessitate or support one another, and each and all require the truth of the principle, so that rational method itself forms a whole of interconnected parts. 7. The conception of reason which thus emerges is not one of a faculty possessed, prior to and apart from experience, of certain clear and indubitable universal axioms with which it confronts a tangled experience proving and explaining so much as can be brought under these axioms and leaving the rest unrationalized. It is the conception rather of a principle operative within experience the work of which is always partial and incom- plete, always extending itself while at the same time pruning and sharpening its own methods. Neither proof nor explanation consist in the reference of the experienced order to something outside it, but in the exhibition of its internal coherence, i.e. the system of universal connexions in accordance with which its parts do not merely tolerate one another in mutual consistency, but require and maintain one another. The provisional and partial truths are established not merely by deduction from some special truth taken as known, 1 but, ultimately, by the simple fact that they form a whole of consilient truths. The isolated and partial fact again is not so much explained by subsumption under some self-evident law as by its part in the comprehensive system of universals which is reality. Finally, as every part -judgment has its proof in the body with which it is connected, so the proof of the body of judgments as a whole is in their standing together as a connected system, and if any part of reality become intelligible by relation to the remainder a whole field of reality becomes intelligible as constituting such a system. Of any part, however great and however articulate internally, we can, and indeed must always go on to ask about its connections with further reality. But if we envisage reality as a whole we can ask no such 1 This of course may be the proximate step, but the truth used as a principle will find its ultimate justification in the manner denoted. 64 THE RATIONAL GOOD question, and here intelligibility must mean simply the internal completeness of interconnexions running through all its elements. Reason then generically is the principle of interconnexion persistently applied. Since the whole of Reality does not fall within our experience, the work of interconnexion is never complete. Hence reason does not necessarily claim finality for its interpretations. What is rationally established is that which is incorporated in a system of consilient judgments. If the reflective judgment, " This is certain," can without contradiction be inserted into any such system, then the system is rationally held certain. But in general there is at least a possibility that further experience may throw fresh light upon established interpretations, and yet this does not prevent them from being the most reasonable interpretation f within our reach. Hence the rational as such is not ! an established system, but a process governed by a principle, the process by which understardirg deepens, \ error is repeatedly eliminated, and truth constantly enlarged. As operating in the sphere of assertion (including knowledge, suggestion, and belief), reason is the use of this principle as the discovery of the objective order, the result of this discovery being truth. As applied in spheres other than that of assertion we have yet to examine what it means. The principle of interconnexion carried through yields a whole in which the parts sustain and necessitate one another, or briefly an organized whole. Thus reason is an organic principle in thought, and so far as incomplete but progressive may be termed an organic impulse. So far as reality is finally intelligible to reason it must similarly be interpre- table as an organic whole, so that we may speak of reason as the ultimate organic principle alike in thought and in reality. Finally, the fact that reason, even as incomplete impulse, is the endeavour towards the whole which inter- connects the parts is the basis of its sovereignty over every partial impulse or isolated belief, whatever degree of immediate subjective certitude such belief may claim. CHAPTER IV THE GOOD i. WE have now to apply the definition of the rational to the world of practice. The first step in this application is simple. It is easy to see that when we give a reason for some act we first connect it with its end or aim, and that, if we want a reason for this end in turn, we must connect it either with some further end, or with some broad principle of action. It is an easy inference that if there is a rational order of action our purposes must form an interconnected system. But from this point difficulties begin. Any system of action that we can propound, however consistent internally, will be discovered to collide with impulses, desires, interests of ourselves or of other people, and the question of the basis and authority of our system will at once arise. An end or principle of action once assumed, the part of reason is intelligible enough. It deduces consequences, connects means and ends, shows that such an action follows from the principle while such another is inconsistent with it. So far it seems to be just the reason of cognition applied to matters of fact, with the difference only that the facts in question are human actions and their consequences. But what is to happen if two ends, two principles, or, in general terms, two (or more) things that we consider good occur to us, and they happen to be incompatible with one another ? We are forced to choose between them. Can reason have anything to do with the choice of ends or the preference of one sort of good over another ? Has it anything to do with ultimate choice, or is it confined 5 * 66 THE RATIONAL GOOD to the cognitive apprehension of consistency or incon- sistency between the several things that we may choose ? Are there ends, or is there some end which must commend itself to a rational being as good, and as so good that everything incompatible with it is bad ? Or is the preference of one thing over another a matter, in the last resort, of a choice with which reason has nothing to do ? Is there, in short, a Rational Good, and if so, how is it to be denned ? 2. We must first be clear as to what we mean by " good." Our words and our thoughts do not always coincide, but sincerely to think that a thing is good is to adopt towards it a certain attitude of mind which affects our actions and affects also our judgments of the actions of others. In so far as we think a thing good for ourselves here and now as opposed to merely doing lip-service to its goodness we are disposed to act in such a way as to secure or preserve it. Our disposition may be overborne by some strong contrary impulse. But if an end is genuinely conceived as good, it means that we have at least some feeling for it. This feeling has several consequences. It tends, though not always with success, to direct our own action towards the end in question ; to make us approve and support those who act in a similar way ; to render us sympathetically interested in anything that promotes it and adversely affected by anything of a contrary tendency. These and similar feelings and dispositions relative to any given end make up the practical attitude which the term " good " expresses. Observe, however, that while the judgment " this is good " expresses a disposition, it also asserts a fact. It asserts something to be the object of a favour- able disposition, and if the judgment is true this relation is real. The practical attitude or disposition is not, indeed, the assertion, but it is a part of that which is asserted. There is thus a double action of the mind involved in the judgment of value, a practical attitude and an assertion of fact, and the practical attitude may be said to express itself in the assertion. THE GOOD 67 But it will be objected, I may recognize as good in some sense much that does not appeal to me. In particular I may recognize that something would be very good indeed for another person, but if I am absorbed in my own interests the knowledge leaves me cold. My attitude to this " good " is an " intellectual," not a practical attitude. Be it so. It still remains that, in recognizing that A B holds this or that to be good for him, I recognize that there is something about which he, and those who are interested in him, are feeling, to which he and they adopt a practical attitude. Similarly, in admitting something to be " good " in a conventional sense which does not in fact appeal to my feelings, I recognize it as part of that which the general fabric of custom and social opinion maintains. Thus the individual may recognize a good that does not directly appeal to him, and this possibility constitutes an essential part of the whole moral problem, yet it will remain true to say that, by the term " good " he signifies something which, in the connexion in which it is applicable, moves feeling, and through feeling disposes to action. 1 If this analysis is correct a judgment of the form " this is good " is an assertion, but something more than an assertion. Unless qualified by some saving clause that makes it " good for some one else, but not for me," " good from your point of view, but not from mine," it is the expression of a practical attitude or disposition. It is an acceptance of something propounded to the mind, an acceptance which may be expressed in the most general terms by saying that something fits in or harmonizes with a mental disposition. This harmony 1 It is natural to say that we pursue an object because we deem it good, but as our whole account of the relation of impulse and intelligence will have shown, it is at least as true to say that we deem it good because we have the impulse to pursue it. More accurately, the idea of good is the definition o an impulse, or at least of a practical attitude. What part ideas themselves play in shaping our practical attitude is a question which runs through all our discussion. In general the relation is reciprocal. At lowest in the very act of defining we modify. 68 THE RATIONAL GOOD has, generically, two aspects. It turns on feeling, and it is effective in action. The two points are readily observable in the simpler cases. Consider any simple direct impulse, as the impulse of a little child to grasp and handle a bright object. The impulse effects itself in a series of efforts which may or may not culminate in the momentary seizure of the thing. Neglecting the latter case, and considering only that in which effort is so far successful as to achieve contact, we still find two strongly marked differences of result. If the bright object is, say, a candle flame, the effort is abruptly broken off and, so to say, reversed. There is a rapid withdrawal of the hand accompanied by a cry, which we interpret on the analogy of our more mature experience as an expression of pain. Whether the pain is to be regarded strictly as the cause of the withdrawal, as in ordinary language we always assume, raises a well-worn meta- physical controversy which we shall here endeavour to avoid the question whether and in what sense a feeling as a state of consciousness can be the cause of a physical change. It will suffice for our purpose to regard the process of sharp withdrawal, crying, and other convulsive motor contractions on the one hand, and the feeling of disappointment and pain on the other, as a whole of many elements wherein the element of feeling appears, at any rate on and after a certain stage of development, to be an integral and essential factor. The whole phenomenon observed or interpreted by us on the one side in terms of feeling, on the other in terms of certain movements of limbs, appears to form a con- nected totality, and we emphasize the principal differences of aspect in this totality by calling it a psycho-physical process. In the psycho-physical process, then, of a baby trying to grasp a candle flame we suppose two essential characters. On the one hand there is effort broken off, frustrated in the moment of achievement. There is, that is to say, disharmony between the effort and its end. On the other hand there is pain felt in the moment of disharmony, and essential thereto. Pain THE GOOD 69 characterizes the feeling involved in disharmony, and the mental attitude concerned in the process of checking and cancelling effort. The inverse case is now readily intelligible. If the object grasped is neither too hot, nor too sharp, nor too rough, the first contact is only the beginning of fruition. The little fingers explore the surface, and they close on it and convey it to the mouth, where, unless the process is broken off by the arbitrary intervention of a higher power, a new experience begins, which will differ again, according as the object turns out to be a sugar plum or a marble. The effort in the case now under consideration is not checked in the moment of attainment. The ball is explored all over, thrown about, and again pursued. The sugar plum is tasted, sucked, and swallowed. The series of actions which the effort sets a-going proceeds to a definite end, 1 and is encouraged so to proceed in the successive stages of attainment. There is a harmony between the effort and its result, and the feeling involved in the harmony is one of pleasant tone, culminating in satisfaction. By harmony is meant, in the last analysis, a form of mutual support. Generally speaking, it is that relation of parts in a whole in virtue of which they maintain and (if they admit of development) further one another. 3 Thus in the case of pleasurable emotion, 1 Or, in the alternative, it is continued as long as the interest is maintained. As this gives way to fatigue the object ceases to stimulate effort and the effort ceases to yield pleasure. The end in such a case, though not precisely definite, has its conditions, either (i) in the nature of the thing which ceases to be interesting when examined on all sides, when we have, as common phrase testifies, " exhausted " it ; or (2) in subjective fatigue, any given faculty of our own being capable of working at its best but for a limited time. In either event the pleasurable activity main- tains itself till certa n natural limits are reached at which it gradually or rapidly ceases to be pleasurable, and even becomes unpleasant. * The mutual relation is essential to the meaning of harmony as used here. It is to be carefully distinguished from the mere subordination of parts to a whole (see below, chap, vi, p. 100 ff). One of its simplest and most perfect examples is seen in those 70 THE RATIONAL GOOD incipient fruition furthers the effort until its achievement is complete, while the maintenance of the effort is, in turn, the condition of full fruition. 3. But neither pleasure or pain on the one hand, nor this internal harmony on the other, have an antecedent effort as their invariable and necessary condition. If the candle touched the child's hand accidentally, the withdrawal would be none the less rapid and the pain none the less sharp. If the sugar plum was put into the mouth by maternal fingers it would be sucked with no less avidity. It takes a philosophic mind to overlook facts so simple as these. Feeling does not merely super- vene upon effort, but may initiate effort, and while pleasure in an experience prompts us to maintain it and carry it through to some culminating satisfaction, pain urges us to be rid of it. In the most passive states, such as enjoyment of warmth or contemplation of a beautiful efforts of art in which the beauty of parts lends beauty to the whole and at the same time derives an enhanced beauty therefrom. In " A voice so thrilling ne'er was heard In springtime from the cuckoo-bird Breaking the silence of the seas Among the furthest Hebrides," each line, at any rate each of the three last lines, is beautiful by itself, but much more beautiful when read with the rest, and the same thing may be said of the four lines together in relation to the whole poem. In Helen's lament over Hector the lines " a\Xa tru TOV y' iirftvffi Trapai