uni/ef;;Tt' of CALiFOPrjiA s*.rj DiEGO 
 
 3 1822 0271 
 
 9890 
 
 GRI 
 
 soPHicAL Classic
 
 f LlbRAKr 
 
 ^lALIFORNIA |^rt!v-?^ssw-
 
 LIBRARY 
 
 UNIVERSITY OF 
 CALIFORNIA 
 SAN 0IE6O 
 
 ^ 
 
 J 
 
 i
 
 3 
 
 Si
 
 GERMAN PHILOSOPHICAL CLASSICS 
 
 ENGLISH READERS MD STUDENTS. 
 
 EDITED BT 
 
 GEORGE S. MORRIS 
 
 KAI^T^S ETHICS. 
 
 '^ 
 
 I
 
 GRIGGS'S 
 
 PHILOSOPHICAL CLASSICS. 
 
 Under tlio editorial supervision of Prof. G. S. Morris. 
 
 De^mtcd to a Critical Exposition of the Master- 
 pieces of German Thought. 
 
 Kant's Critique of Pure Season. By Prof. G. 
 S. Morris, Ph.D., of the University of Michigan. 
 $1.2.5. 
 
 Schelling's Transcendental Idealism. By 
 
 Prof. .loHN Watson, LL.D., of (^iicuu'i- I'liiversity, 
 Kingston, Canada. S1-~'T- 
 
 Fichte's Science of Knowledge. By Prof. C. 
 C. EvERKTT. U.D , of Harvard I'liiversity. $1.35. 
 
 Hegel's -ffisthetics. By Prof. J. S, Kedney, 
 S.T.D., of tlie Seabury Divinity School. %\:Si. 
 
 Kant's Ethics. By President Noah Porter, D.D., 
 LL.D., of Yale College. $1.25. 
 
 OTHER VOLUMES IN PREPARATION. 
 
 A handy series of the great German thinkers ; of 
 much interest and great convenience to scholars and 
 to the more general reader.— Cmcjwwa^i Com. Gazette. 
 
 This series offers an exceedingly valuable compen- 
 dium of German philosophic thought, valuable in any 
 tongue, and especially so iu the English, in which 
 there is nothing to compare with it.— Gfiicago Times. 
 
 These excellent books, as remarkable for ability as 
 for clearness, will do much to clear the way and make 
 the mastery of the German systems a comparatively 
 easy task.— xVeii' York Examiner.
 
 KANT'S ETHICS. 
 
 A CRITICAL EXPOSITION. 
 
 By NOAH PORTER, 
 
 PRESIDENT OF TALE COLLEGE. 
 
 CHICACiO: 
 C. GRIGGS AND COMPANY. 
 
 1886.
 
 Copyright, 1886. 
 By S. C. GRIGGS AND COMPANY 
 
 I KKIGHT &■■ LEONARD . t
 
 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA. SAN DIEGO 
 
 3 1822 02711 9890 
 
 THIS VOLr:ME IS INSCRIBED 
 
 PRESIDENT MAKK HOPKINS, D.D., LLD., 
 
 IN GRATEFUL RECOGNITION OF HIS EMINENT SERVICES TO 
 
 ETHICAL SCIENCE, 
 
 CHRISTIAN EDUCATION.
 
 PEEFAOE. 
 
 r I IHE essay now given to the public has been 
 -*- promised for several months, but was written 
 for the most part as a vacation exercise during the 
 last summer. Its theme is Kant's Theory of Ethics, 
 as contrasted with his practical teachings, so far as 
 the former is distinctive of his school. For this rea- 
 son it is chiefly concerned with the two treatises in 
 which this theory is explained and defended, viz.: 
 Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, 1785; 
 Kritik der Praktischen Vernunft, 1788. 
 
 As its title imports, this treatise is both expository 
 and critical. In expounding Kant's ethical theory to 
 English readers, the writer has thought it best to 
 state this theory very largely in Kant's own lan- 
 guage, with such comments as might be required 
 to make it intelligible. He has done this for two 
 reasons, that he might be entirely just to Kant him- 
 self, and that he might aid the unpractised student in 
 the somewhat discouraging task of interpreting the 
 German philosopher. For both these reasons he has
 
 Vlii PREFACE. 
 
 often retained Kant's peculiar and frequently highly- 
 technical phraseology in order that, by mere repe- 
 tition, it might become familiar, while yet he has 
 sought to give its meaning in current English, that 
 the student might acquire facility in interpreting the 
 Kantian dialect by its English equivalents. He does 
 not assert that in every case he has been successful in 
 the last-named attempt. The English text, which 
 he has invariably used, is that of the generally ap- 
 proved translation of Professor Abbott, of Trinity 
 College, Dublin.* 
 
 The critical remarks of the author are usually 
 given as a running commentary upon the text with 
 the important exception of §§ 21-33, in which the 
 exposition covers §§ 21-26 and the criticism §§ 27-33. 
 These comments suppose some familiarity with eth- 
 ical theories, and the criticisms and schools to which 
 they have given rise, although the writer has scru- 
 pulously avoided all personal and partisan ref- 
 erences, and endeavored to confine himself to his 
 appropriate functions as the expounder and critic of 
 his author. 
 
 Besides the expository and critical matter thus 
 
 * Kant's Critique of Practical Reason and other works on the 
 Theory of Ethics. Translated by Thomas Kingsmill Abbott. M. A., 
 etc. London ; Longmans, Green & Co., 1879.
 
 PREFACE. IX 
 
 described the reader will find a brief general intro- 
 duction, together with a summary or condensed 
 review of the distinctive positions taken by Kant 
 upon the most important topics as compared with 
 those of other — principally English — writers, and 
 some brief strictures upon Kant by a few German 
 critics. 
 
 The preparation of this essay has cost the writer 
 some Labor, but the labor has brought its own 
 rewai"d. He trusts that the result will be useful as 
 an aid to those students who are interested in the 
 study of ethical theories, and who appreciate the 
 practical significance of such theories at the present 
 
 time. 
 
 N. P. 
 Yale College, Dec. 1, 1885.
 
 CONTENTS. 
 
 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 Plan and reasons for the treatise .... 1 
 Relation of the Kantian Ethics to the Meta- 
 physics 2 
 
 Not necessary to expound the Metaphysics at 
 
 length 3 
 
 Salient features of the same 3 
 
 Kant"s important services to modern thought . 5 
 
 Especially upon Theology and Ethics ... 6 
 
 Their effect upon Faith in the Supernatural . 7 
 Influence upon speculation and literature in 
 
 England and America 8 
 
 Difficulties in criticisingf the same .... 11 
 
 CHAPTER I. 
 
 PRINCIPAL ETHICAL TREATISES. 
 
 Titles of Ethical Treatises 13 
 
 The Critique of Pure Reason 14 
 
 The Prolegomena 15
 
 xii COKTENTS. 
 
 Relation to Ethics l(i 
 
 Critique of Pare Reason — Fundamental ques- 
 tion of 18 
 
 Phenomena vs. Things in themselves ... 19 
 
 Noumena . 20 
 
 Limits of human knowledge 21 
 
 Disappointment 22 
 
 Promised deliverance 22 
 
 Elements of Kant's Constructive Ethics . . 23 
 
 Three important questions proposed by Kant . 25 
 
 Plausibility of his solution ,26 
 
 Obligation to consistency 28 
 
 This solution preliminary and imperfect . . 29 
 
 Principles relative and absolute .31 
 
 Fundamental principles of Ethics readily un- 
 derstood and assented to 38 
 
 In speculative principles, Kant claims only a 
 
 relative authority 34 
 
 Danger of confounding speculative and ethical 
 
 principles 36 
 
 We proceed next to the examination of his 
 
 formal motives .....,.».. 37 
 
 CHAPTER II. 
 
 THE FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSICS 
 OF MORALS. 
 
 The Metaphysics of Morals tentative only . 38 
 
 A Metaphysics of Morals possible o » o . 39
 
 CONTENTS. XIU 
 
 Preliminary sketch of the author's system . . 41 
 
 Division of topics in the Grundlegung . . - 42 
 
 Import of his opening sentence ..... 43 
 
 Kant's interpretation of the " Good-will " . . 45 
 
 (1) An act from inclination, not an act of 
 duty 4-") 
 
 (2) The maxim, not the end, determining 
 moral worth .4(3 
 
 (o) Respect for the law essential to duty . 4(i 
 
 The content or import of the moral law . , 47 
 Kant's scepticism in respect to speculative 
 
 truth 49 
 
 Criticism of Kant's first sentence .... 50 
 
 Diverse meanings of " Good-will " . . . , 51 
 Kant's defective conception of his opponents' 
 
 doctrines 54 
 
 Kant's limited and low conception of hapi)i- 
 
 ness 55 
 
 Gratification of the Reason 5(3 
 
 Kant's defective conception of duty and obliga- 
 tion . 57 
 
 Other oversights of Kant ....... 58 
 
 Kant's second error 60 
 
 Third mistake. Respect for the law a sensibil- 
 ity .... 61 
 
 Conceded to be an " obscure feeling " - . . 61 
 Criterion of an act of duty ... .62 
 
 Second section of Kant's treatise . . 64 
 Kant's first position, that every ideal must be 
 
 actual . o . 64
 
 XIV CONTENTS. 
 
 Whence is the moral ideal derived ? Kant and 
 
 his critics 66 
 
 Kant overlooks the sensibility as an element of 
 
 the ideal 67 
 
 Right action defined in the most general way 
 
 as reasonable action 69 
 
 A perfect will excludes obligation .... 70 
 
 The categorical and hypothetical imperative . 71 
 
 Kant's defective conception of happiness . . 73 
 Kant adopts the criterion of consequences as a 
 
 practical rule 76 
 
 Relation of the moral ideal to the actual, in 
 
 man 79 
 
 A life according to nature 82 
 
 He analyzes human nature before he is aware 83 
 
 Discovers ends of action and personality . . 84 
 But does not formally abandon the categorical 
 
 imperative 87 
 
 And yet he practically shifts his ground . . 88 
 Rationality does not exclude relations to the 
 
 sensibility 90 
 
 Kant's views of the will indefinite .... 92 
 
 The personal Ego overlooked 94 
 
 Transition from the Metaphysics of Morals to 
 
 the Critique of Practical Reason .... 95 
 
 Kant returns to the will and moral freedom . 97 
 
 The man noumenal and man phenomenal . . 100 
 
 Kant's " Freedom " still more exactl}^ defined . 102 
 Kant concedes that the moral law affects the 
 
 sensibilities '= . 104
 
 CONTENTS. XV 
 
 CHAPTER III. 
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. 
 
 Preface and Introduction .... = . 108 
 Practical, not pure and practical .... 109 
 The practical reason supplies an a priori ele- 
 ment 110 
 
 Reply to a criticism Ill 
 
 Twofold function ascribed to the will . . . 113 
 Vacillating and uncertain classification of the 
 
 psychical powers 115 
 
 ^ Kant's indefinite conceptions of the will . .116 
 Knowledge of every sort begins with judgments, 
 
 not concepts r . . 118 
 
 Principles of practical reason defined » . . 119 
 Every motive must address the reason . , . 120 
 
 Empirical principles defined 121 
 
 Material practical principles defined . . . 123 
 Practical principles formal, and not material . 124 
 Two problems proposed ...... = 125 
 
 Autonomy and heteronomy of the will . . . 127 
 
 Ill-desert analyzed 128 
 
 The contrast stated between the pure and the 
 
 practical reason .129 
 
 How can we apply the commands of the prac- 
 tical reason to the world of sense . . . .loo 
 The object and effect of the practical reason » 134 
 The typic of the pure practical reason . . <. 137 
 The motives of the pure practical reason . . 139
 
 XV] CONTENTS. 
 
 Obligation and respect for the law .... 140 
 Acting according to duty, and from a sense of 
 
 duty 142 
 
 Import of a command to love 143 
 
 Apostrophe to Duty 145 
 
 Personality here recognized for the first time . 146 
 Reasons why the practical reason admits a sin- 
 gle systematic form only ...... 148 
 
 Appeal to the universal consciousness . . . 149 
 Difference between physical and psychical 
 
 causes 151 
 
 Relations of man, the nounienon, to time and 
 
 space 154 
 
 Dynamical and mathematical categories . . 154 
 The dialectic of the practical reason . . .156 
 Anticipation of moral satisfaction not moral . 158 
 Self-contentment conceded to be ethically legit- 
 imate 160 
 
 The primacy of the practical above the specula- 
 tive reason 162 
 
 How far have they a common root .... 163 
 
 Argument for immortality 164 
 
 This argument assumes design as objectively 
 
 true 166 
 
 Argument for God's existence 166 
 
 Difference between rational and moral ends . 168 
 
 New argument attempted 170 
 
 Can the practical be independent of the specu- 
 lative reason 172 
 
 DifiFerenee between a hypothesis and a postulate 174
 
 CONTENTS. Xvii 
 
 Kant's argument reduced to — what . . . 175 
 
 Methodology of the practical reason . . . 176 
 
 The starry heavens and the moral law . . . 177 
 
 Practical needs are supreme and isolated . . 179 
 
 <^ Comments on the conclusion 180 
 
 CHAPTER IV. 
 
 A CRITICAL SUMMARY OF KANt's ETHICAL THEORV. 
 
 The practical reason briefly described . . . 184 
 
 Whence its authority 186 
 
 How related to Butler's Principle of Reflection 186 
 
 Kant's objective rule of duty 190 
 
 Good and ill- desert according to Kant and 
 
 Butler . 191 
 
 Kant's doctrine of freedom .....= 193 
 Freedom of the Ego noumenon ..... 195 
 Relation of Kant's Ethics to speculative truth . 198 
 Ethical grounds for Belief in Immortality . » 199 
 Further remai'ks upon the Categorical Impera- 
 tive . , . o 201 
 
 Personality essential to obligation .... 202 
 Sense of authority complex and derived . 204 
 
 The two explanations contrasted . . . . = 205 
 Kant's explanation of the moral law % . ? .201 — 
 Kant's view of conformity to man's moral 
 
 nature 209 
 
 Further criticism of Kant's doctrine of the will 210
 
 XV CONTEN"TS. 
 
 Kant's late and inadequate recognition of pur- 
 pose , . 212 
 
 Kant's failure to do justice to personality . . 214 
 His depreciation of the emotions and the sensi- 
 bility 216 
 
 The intellectual application of Kant's Ethics . 220 
 
 Authority of experience in ethical questions . 221 
 
 Kant's Ethics and the Christian, contrasted . 224 
 
 Relations to Theistic and Christian truth . , 226 
 
 CHAPTER V. 
 
 BRIEF NOTICES FROM A FEW OF KANt's GERMAN 
 CRITICS. 
 
 Introductory o . 232 
 
 Schiller's comments on Kant's Ethics . . . 233 
 
 Schleiermacher and Lotze ...... 239 
 
 Trendelenburg's strictures on Kant . . o . 243
 
 IJSTTRODUCTORY. 
 
 § 1. The title of this treatise describes its pur- 
 pose. It proposes, first to interpret and 
 
 Plan and 
 
 then to criticise the principal features of Reasons for 
 Kant's ethical system. Ft proposes the 
 one in order to effect the other. This method is 
 appropriate to the examination of every philosoph- 
 ical writer and every philosophical system; and so 
 emphatically, that a skilful interpretation is often 
 of itself the most satisfactory criticism, as it is al- 
 ways the most effective preparation for the same. 
 This is preeminently true of every division of the 
 Kantian philosophy, of those even which seem to be 
 the least speculative. It might seem at first thought 
 that the Kantian Ethics, like ethics in general or 
 the principles of any individual ethical system, 
 must be so far independent of any special meta- 
 physical theories as to involve no special difficulty of 
 either interpretation or criticism. This is only true 
 of a few of Kant's leading positions, when inter- 
 preted in their practical spirit and enforced with
 
 2 IXTRODUCTOKY. 
 
 a certain imaginative fervor. On the other hand, it 
 Relation of is most obvious that whatever is espe- 
 tiu- Kantian ^j^jj ^^^ characteristically Kantian in 
 
 Ethics to the ■' •' 
 
 Metaphysics^, ethics is either founded on the Kantian 
 Metaphysics, or else is applied in its service. Not 
 unfrequently Kant's ethical positions seem to be 
 assumed, almost to be devised, either to support or 
 to supplement some cardinal point in his philosophy. 
 Whatever in the Ethics is peculiar in scientific form 
 or principle, in terminology or logical cohei'ence, 
 will be found to be ultimately connected with the 
 Kantian Metaphysics. It follows that the student 
 will find it impossible to understand or to criticise 
 the Ethics of Kant unless he constantly keeps in mind 
 or often refers to the leading principles of his phil- 
 osophy, either as furnishing the foundations on 
 which the Ethics rest or as responsible for the defects 
 which they seek to supplement. Unless we are 
 greatly mistaken, his ethical system is made to fulfil 
 both functions, paradoxical as this may seem, being 
 used at one time as the foundation and at another as 
 the complement of his metaphysics — now as the base 
 which supports the pillars of the springing arch, and 
 then as the keystone which crowns and holds it 
 together. It cannot be denied, we think, that the 
 place which ethics occupy in Kant's theory of knowl-
 
 INTRODUCTORY, 3 
 
 edge is unique and almost paradoxical, and that 
 consequently his system is invested with a special 
 fascination for the careful student of modern specu- 
 lation. 
 
 § 2. The reader will not infer that the author 
 proposes first to interpret Kant's entire Not Necessary 
 speculative system in order that he mav '° ^f,^"""^ 
 
 I J " the Metaphys- 
 
 explain or criticise his Ethics. To do so ics at Length. 
 would be entirely gratuitous, after this work has 
 been done so well by the editor of the present 
 series and by other writers. But he could not avoid 
 the distinct recognition of the relations of the one to 
 the other, so far as this is required, in order to make 
 the Ethics intelligible in both their weakness and 
 strength. He could not but notice that the two are 
 constantly and often inextricably intertwined to- 
 gether. The peculiar and oftentimes the strongly 
 marked terminology of both ethics and philosophy 
 makes it still more necessary to study the one by the 
 light of the other. There is no use in disguising the 
 fact that Kant's terminology is always technical in 
 the extreme, and sometimes absolutely barbarous. 
 Indeed, few writers, ancient or modern. 
 
 Salient 
 
 of such marked ability, who have had so Features of 
 
 , , 1 • i 11 • n the Same. 
 
 reasonable a claim to ask a hearing from 
 
 their generation, have so completely cut themselves
 
 4 INTKODUCTORY. 
 
 off from the generations of philosophers who went 
 before them by the adoption of an artificial and 
 novel diction as Immanuel Kant has done. By 
 this alone he could not but separate himself from 
 the earlier thinking of his own youth and early 
 manhood, as also from the thinking of his own gen- 
 eration, and at the same time load himself with 
 the Herculean task of constructing and forcing 
 upon his readers a peculiar and artificial termi- 
 nology of his own. No writer of modern times, at 
 least no one who has written so voluminously and so 
 ably as Kant, has made so few references or allusions 
 to the great philosophic thinkers of other times and 
 to their opinions. That he had thought earnestly 
 upon the same themes which had occupied their at- 
 tention is abundantly evident; but for some reason 
 or other he seems to have scorned to put himself en 
 rapport with these great thinkers, or to hold with 
 them any intimate relations of either indebtedness 
 or repudiation. Whether it was owing to the depth 
 of the dogmatic slumber in which Wolf had over- 
 whelmed his spirit, or the suddenness and complete- 
 ness of his awakening by Hume, or the delirious 
 intoxication and delight with which his own im- 
 agined discoveries seemed to inspire him, whatever 
 was the cause or the occasion, it is certain that he
 
 INTRODUCTORY, 5 
 
 spake to his generation in a strange philosophical 
 dialect which it has been difficult for many of his in- 
 terpreters to master, and which some have rashly but 
 not unnaturally concluded was scarcely worth the 
 mastering. But notwithstanding the uncouthness 
 of the dialect which Kant employed, he compelled 
 his generation to listen to his words and to attempt 
 to solve the problems which he proposed. Many 
 professed not to understand his meaning, and many 
 complained with reason of the strangeness and 
 harshness of his terminology, but those who listened 
 could not escape the obligation to answer those of 
 his questions which they could not fail to understand. 
 § 3. Another excellent thing he accomplished : 
 He made the men of his time under- Kant's impor- 
 stand that certain of the questions which tan»;^Services 
 
 ■^ to Modern 
 
 he propounded must be answered after Thought. 
 a way to which they had not been accustomed 
 befoi'e.* As the result of his teachings and argu- 
 ments, Speculative Science discovered new necessi- 
 ties, even though she felt herself unable to satisfy 
 them. First of all, Philosophy was forced to confess 
 
 * Daher wird man, wo es sich um die Principien, die eigentliche 
 Anfgabe der Philosophie, handelt, nie vor Kant vorbeigehen diirfen. 
 Mag man in der Lusting des Problems von Kant abweichen miissen, 
 man wird immer von Kant lernen, wie man es zuniichst anfzufassen 
 und anzufassen. A. Trendelenburg, Hist. Beitr. zur Philos., iii, 172.
 
 6 INTRODUCTORY. 
 
 that she could not ignore Theology. Religions un- 
 Pispeciaiiy belief was taught that the shallows in 
 Theoio'^y which it had been content to wade were 
 and Ethics. bordered b}" a deep and boundless sea. 
 As Faith was driven from one of its fancied strong- 
 holds to another, it was seemingly to seek and to 
 find its refuge only in ethical convictions and 
 ethical authorit}'. Whatever impression was made 
 by Kant's speculative system, its ethical tone was 
 felt to be lofty and commanding in its every 
 strain. Wherever the Kantian philosophy was 
 accepted, a noble and high-toned Stoicism took the 
 place of the prevalent sensual and self-indulgent 
 Epicureanism. Self-sacrifice and self-control were 
 honored, and self-indulgence was put to shame. 
 The old and sterner German virtues came to the 
 front, which had been systematically dishonoi'ed by 
 the corrupting sensualism of Voltaire in the youth- 
 ful court of the Great Frederick, and the scarcely 
 less debauching sentimentalism of Rousseau. The 
 new German literature, certainly the better part of 
 it, such as was represented by Schiller and his 
 school, was animated by a genuine, if it was an 
 oversti-ained and romantic, ethical fervor. It is 
 almost universally acknowledged, and cannot be 
 denied, that it was in the Kantian school that the
 
 INTROnrCTORY. 7 
 
 seeds were sown of those better aspirations of patri- 
 otism and self-control, of heroism and of faith, 
 which were first so nobly tested in the war of the 
 liberation and which in our own time triumphed so 
 conspicuously in the resuscitation of Germany and 
 its final consolidation in the New German Empire. 
 
 The influence of the Kantian Ethics upon faith 
 in the supernatural and in the Christian Their Effect 
 verities seemed at first less favorable "''°" 
 
 in the 
 
 than upon faith in human duty and supernatural, 
 patriotic self-sacrifice. This may be largely ascribed 
 to the weakness of theology itself, which required 
 a radical disintegration before it could rise to a 
 newer and better life. Whatever may have been 
 true of the immediate effects of the Critical Phil- 
 osophy, it cannot be denied that so soon as super- 
 natural Christianity rallied from its shallow nat- 
 uralism, as it did in fact at the call of many 
 earnest thinkers, it assumed a loftier ethical tone 
 and proposed to itself a more positive and elevated 
 spiritual ideal than ever before. It was doubtless 
 true that Kant was forced by the logic of his own 
 ethical system to dispense with and openly to dis- 
 honor the supernatural and the personal as of com- 
 paratively little consequence in the Christian his- 
 tory, and as even a corrupting element : but the
 
 8 INTRODUCTORY. 
 
 final eflfect of his teachings, whether by action or 
 reaction, has invested its supernatural facts to those 
 who received them with a profounder spiritual sig- 
 nificance and clothed them with new spiritual power. 
 It may be conceded that for one or two generations 
 the Kantian Ethics have been used as a weapon of 
 effective assault upon historic Christianity in Ger- 
 many, England, and America, while yet it may be 
 asserted with undoubted truth, that his earnest and 
 practical ethical spirit has animated the defenders 
 of historic Christianity with higher and nobler con- 
 ceptions of its spiritual import and enabled them 
 the better to understand and defend it as both the 
 necessity and the strength of modern thought. 
 
 § 4. It will not fail to occur to many of my read- 
 , ^ ers that the Kantian Ethics became a 
 
 Influenceupon 
 
 Speculation significant power in English thought and 
 
 and Literature 
 
 in England feeling long before the Kantian Meta- 
 physics had begun to be appreciated or 
 understood. The eloquent Coleridge is usually cred- 
 ited with having been the earliest effective exponent 
 of both. Some literary critics would find in the 
 awakened interest in the romantic school of Ger- 
 man poetry, the first effect of the Kantian impulse. 
 Even if this were so, Coleridge was foremost even in 
 responding to this awakening power and finding in
 
 IN-TBODUCTORY. 9 
 
 it a more profound and wide-reaching significance. 
 If, however, we limit ourselves to ethics proper 
 we can find no writer who so distinctly and fer- 
 vently insisted as did Coleridge on the need of a 
 better speculative system than that which had been 
 accepted in England, and who also taught that Kant 
 provided for this better system in his distinction be- 
 tween the Reason and the Understanding. The 
 voice of Coleridge was indeed the voice of one cry- 
 ing in the wilderness, bewildering indeed at times, 
 even when inspiring, as is the voice of every 
 prophet, but it was loud and clear in its denuncia- 
 tion of the ethics taught in the English Universities 
 and embodied in Paley's popular text-book. The 
 present readers of Coleridge's criticisms of Paley 
 and his expositions of Kant, find the last seriously 
 defective in scientific exactness, representing Jacobi 
 rather than Kant; but if they have attained to even 
 a slight measure of the historic sense they cannot 
 fail to acknowledge the signal service which he ren- 
 dered in defending the nobler features of the system 
 taught by Jacobi's great master. Carlyle. as a rep- 
 resentative of Kant, was somewhat later than Cole- 
 ridge, and far less philosophical than he in his pre- 
 tensions and his achievements, though perhaps he was 
 equally fervent in his practical aims. It is of little
 
 10 INTRODUCTORY. 
 
 consequence which of the two was the more efficient 
 in introducing the new Ethics to the English public, 
 or how large was the share which James Marsh, 
 George Ripley, and Ralph Waldo Emerson might 
 claim in furthering the same general movement in 
 America. Most intelligent readers know that what 
 after Kant was called the Transcendental Ethics 
 attracted the attention and enlisted the sympathy 
 of a large following in both England and the United 
 States, and made itself felt in their literature and 
 their criticism, in their politics, and their theology. 
 This movement led many to new theories of man's 
 moral nature, to new definitions and principles in 
 speculative ethics, and was followed by the most 
 important consequences in their modes of thinking 
 and feeling in respect to the most vital questions 
 of speculative and practical interest. 
 
 We may say indeed that the Kantian Ethics when 
 conceived in this somewhat indefinite signification 
 has had a far more positive and wide-spread influ- 
 ence in both England and America than the Kantian 
 Metaphysics. The latter has, indeed, of late, through 
 translations and comments, received much attention 
 from speculative thinkers for its own sake and as 
 a preparation for and transition stage to the later 
 schools of German speculation. The former, the
 
 INTRODUCTORY. 11 
 
 Ethics, has not so frequently been fonnaliy ex- 
 pounded or carefully criticised, while yet it has 
 been accepted by very many in a positive but rather 
 indiscriminating w^ay, as being in its distinctive 
 features eminently worthy of confidence and the 
 noblest work of its eminent defender. The Kantian 
 Ethics as a speculative system or as related to the 
 Kantian metaphysics has rarely, if ever, been the 
 subject of careful and thorough criticism by any 
 English writer. For this reason, if for no other, it 
 is at present the more inviting theme for both critic 
 and reader. 
 
 The treatment of this subject is not without its 
 difficulties. Some of these difficulties 
 
 Ditticiilties 
 
 have already been suggested. Others in Criticising 
 
 .,, 1,1 1 1 the Same. 
 
 Will make themselves known as we pro- 
 ceed. Kant is a writer whom it is not always easy 
 to interpret to an English reader, even if his philo- 
 sophical position, his terminology, and his German 
 style presented no peculiar embarrassments. His 
 system, if he can be said to have a system, is by no 
 means so coherent or so closely stated as his uncrit- 
 ical admirers contend, and as some of his commen- 
 tators insist. Let us expect, then, that serious diffi- 
 culties in understanding and criticising him will be 
 manifest as we proceed, and let the expectation
 
 12 IXTRODUCTORY. 
 
 arouse us to resolute effort. Of one thing the earnest 
 student may be confident, and that is that the ques- 
 tions which Kant proposes are invested with an 
 interest and importance which cannot easily be over- 
 estimated. Whether or not these questions are all 
 rightly handled, or whether the solutions for which 
 Kant contends are satisfactory or disappointing — 
 they are all discussed in a manly temper, and with 
 an effort at thoroughness which puts to shame every 
 solicitation of indolence and every incitement of pas- 
 sion or partisanship.
 
 KANT'S ETHICS. 
 
 CHAPTER I. 
 
 PRINCIPAL ETHICAL TREATISES — THEIR 
 GENERAL CHARACTERISTICS. 
 
 § 5. Kant's ethical system may be found in the 
 following treatises, which were published 
 
 Titles of 
 
 in the order and at the times which are Ethical 
 
 . ,. ,111 Treatises. 
 
 indicated below. 
 
 1. Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, 1785, 
 usually translated as The Fundamental Principles 
 of the Metaphysics of Morals. 
 
 2. Kritik der Praktischen Vernunft, 1788, Cri- 
 tique of the Practical Reason. 
 
 3. Die Metaphysik der Sitten, 1797, The Meta- 
 physics of Morals (in two parts, respectively of 
 Rights, and Duties). 
 
 In order to appreciate fully the relations of these 
 treatises to Kant's speculative system, the reader 
 should scrutinize them in connection not only with 
 one another, but with the Critique of Pure Reason, 
 with which he astonished the world in 1781, and 
 
 13
 
 14 kant's ethics. 
 
 also with his Prolegomena to Every Possible Future 
 System of Metaphysics, which was published two 
 years after, i.e., two years before his first treatise 
 upon Ethics. The treatise entitled The Critique of 
 the Faculty of Judgment (Die Kritik der Urtheils- 
 Kraft) also contains some special ethical matter. 
 In all these treatises Kant endeavors to be consistent 
 with himself, aiming in each to be true to the 
 fundamental principles which he had laid down in 
 respect to the sources, the authority, and the im- 
 port of every description of knowledge. In the 
 Critique of Pure Reason, published four years before 
 his first ethical treatise, he says very little of morals, 
 although it is evident from the little that he does 
 say that he had anticipated very distinctly the difii- 
 cult questions which would be forced upon his atten- 
 tion by the logic of his philosophical theory; that he 
 faced them resolutely, and to some extent anticipated 
 the solutions which he subsequently expanded and 
 defended in his formal treatises on Ethics proper. 
 § 6. The Critique of Pure Reason, it hardly 
 need be said to those who have read a 
 
 The Critique 
 
 of Pure few pages, is painfully thought and 
 
 often painfully expressed, apparently to 
 the writer and certainly to the reader. It is charac- 
 teristic of this volume that in it Kant seems to
 
 PRINCIPAL ETHICAL TREATISES. 15 
 
 be a seeker, rather than a finder, of" trutli in liis 
 aims and his processes; that at many points and 
 turns he seems more or less uncertain of his own 
 position, and to take unwearied pains — not always 
 successfully — both in thinking himself clear and in 
 expressing his meaning clearly to others. The 
 probable and even possible inferences which might 
 be derived from his doctrines by his inquirers and 
 antagonists seem to intrude upon his attention at 
 every step, and he is constantly tempted to pause 
 and turn aside from his onward course to explain or 
 overcome these objections and difficulties. 
 
 § 7. In the Pi'olegomena, written two years after- 
 ward, he writes in a different tone — rpj^^ 
 assuming and maintaining a different Prolegomena, 
 attitude. Throughout this work his air is that of 
 a combatant who is sure of his position and con- 
 fident of victory. He writes like the discoverer 
 of an " open sesame" to all future metaphysics of 
 whatever sort, which he has only need to shout 
 and at once every secret metaphysical door will 
 fly open. Instead of inquiring, he propounds; in- 
 .stead of arguing, he explains. The very title of 
 his treatise indicates his position and his feelings, it 
 being a triumphant proclamation of what had been 
 found by himself to be necessary for all future
 
 1(> kaxt's ethics. 
 
 metaphysicians by the experiences and failures of 
 those who have gone before. The style and diction 
 are in full sympathy with this new attitude. The 
 writer is simple, cheerful, and almost defiant in his 
 tone. His opinions are propounded, not inferred. 
 He does not delay to answer objections: he scarcely 
 notices them. He simply lays down the law, as one 
 who is justified in speaking with authority. 
 
 The Prolegomena is confined to speculative meta- 
 Relation to physics, and leaves all ethical questions 
 Ethics. untouched. But the Critique had fur- 
 
 nislied some distinct anticipations of Kant's ethical 
 system. To these he was impelled by the desire to set 
 aside the objections which might be urged against his 
 speculative conclusions so far as these had been 
 reached, viz.: that speculative knowledge, as such, is 
 only trustworthy or valuable so far as it can explain 
 the possibility of experience: urging that if it be 
 true that neither the Soul, nor the Kosmos, nor God 
 can be reached by the pure reason, then it follows 
 that ethics must be the final arbiter which alone 
 can give us solid reality of any sort, especially con- 
 cerning the Soul in its relations to the future life 
 and the Supi'eme. 
 
 The way in which ethics can render this service is 
 explained by Kant at some length in the second
 
 FHIXCIPAL ETHICAL TKEATISES. 17 
 
 chapter of the Transcendentale Methodenlehre, 
 Zweites Hauptstiick, in which he outlines the ethi- 
 cal system whicli lie developed four and seven years 
 afterward in the classical ethical treatises already 
 named {cf.%% 5, 11, 12). 
 
 This preliminary outline deserves a brief notice, 
 if for no other reason, because it serves to explain 
 the original transition or connecting bridge which 
 was designed in the mind of Kant to transfer his 
 readers from his speculative to his ethical theory. 
 It may l)e compared to the rough outline or hast}^ 
 sketch of what afterward became an elaborate 
 drawing, or, more exactly, to the germ of what 
 afterward grew into a fully developed gi-owth. We 
 prefer to explain these relations here, in order that 
 the intimate dependence of the two parts of Kant's 
 system may be made more clear. We do not care to 
 decide which of these theories was first developed, 
 or was first suggested to his own mind. We very 
 well know which was first drawn out in the detail 
 of explanation and defence, lint inasmuch as we 
 find this ethical germ snugly imliedded in this spec- 
 ulative environment, we shall find it convenient first 
 to explain this environment, that we may analyze the 
 germ itself, and follow its subsequent development. 
 
 § 8. It is well known that the question with
 
 18 kant's ethics. 
 
 Critique of which Kant sets off in his Critique of 
 Pure Reason p^^.^ jieASon is this : Are synthetic 
 
 Fundamental •' 
 
 Question of. Jiidf/nteiifs (i pHori possible? Are there 
 such judgments, and how are the}' to be accounted 
 for? The first of these questions is, in Kant's view, 
 answered in the asking. No one will deny that there 
 must be such judgments. Otherwise there could be 
 no science, no mathematics, no logic, no physics, and 
 no psychology.* Every one of these sciences may 
 be traced back to certain comprehensive judgments 
 which are synthetic, i.e., to propositions of which 
 the predicate is not contained in nor implied by 
 the subject, but in which it is affirmed of or super- 
 added to it by a direct and intuitive affirmation. 
 As such an affirmation enlarges one's knowledge, it is 
 called si/iitJietir, in contrast to one which merely an- 
 alyzes or expands the import already affirmed of its 
 subject, and as it does this by a direct assent of the 
 intellect without the intermediation of reasoning, it 
 is called a priori. Examples of such knowledge are: 
 Two right lines cinniot inclose a space. All bodies 
 are extended. Evenj event is caused. Psi/chical phe- 
 
 * The advocates of the doctrine (hat ethics furnislies the foundation 
 for speculative truth of every kind might tiud in tliis argument tlie 
 justification of their position thus: inasmucli as without science man 
 cannot live a human life — llie life worthy of a man, to which his higher 
 aspirations, faith, and convictions c()ini)el liim — it follows that these 
 synthetic speculative judgments must be true.
 
 PRINCIPAL ETHICAL TREATISES. 19 
 
 nomena are experienced hi siicressio)/. The possibili- 
 ty of such propositions is still further explained by 
 ultimate data, which are given by and to the pure 
 reason, in connection with the operations of intui- 
 tion, as these are exemplified in the outer and inner 
 sense and in the higher processes of reasoning. 
 These data are the forms of Sense, which are Space 
 and Time, the Categories of the Understanding, and 
 the three Ideas of the Reason, viz.: the Soul, the 
 Kosraos, and God. Without these a priori relations 
 and the concepts and propositions that depend on 
 them, Kant argues at length there can be no ra- 
 tional knowledge. In every description and degree 
 of knowledge, even in the lowest, more or fewer of 
 these a priori elements are recognized or implied. 
 
 § 9. It is also to be noticed as a capital feature 
 of Kant's system that the materials of 
 
 Phenomena 
 
 knowledge, i.e., its a posteriori elements vs. Things in 
 
 . T he ni Strives 
 
 given by experience, as contradistin- 
 guished from those relations which are given 
 a priori, are assumed to he pheiiomeHa — spiritual 
 or corporeal — but are not things at all, i.e., not 
 things in tJieniselres. When we face the sense- 
 world, we do not discern things or realities, but only 
 phenomena, as sights, feels, and smells, etc. So in 
 the spirit world we are conscious only of sensations,
 
 20 KANT'8 ETH10!5. 
 
 imaginations, and thoughts, but not of oitrsclres as 
 seeinof, hearing, reineiahering, or imagining. Wliat 
 men are accustomed to conceive as realities by emi- 
 nence, i.e., the realities of the material world, and 
 mayhap in the view of some, the realities of spirit — 
 these are only phenomena as contrasted with things 
 in themselves, i.e., solid realities. These phenomena 
 we connect in groups, by sense-forms and thought- 
 categories, calling a group of sense-phenomena a 
 tree, a house, or a horse, uniting them as substance 
 and attribute, as cause and eifect, etc., but never 
 at all reaching things in themselves, Dinge an sick. 
 These remain ever beyond our reach, ever eluding 
 our grasp. The nearest semblance of real oneness 
 which we can come to is some unity of apperception 
 which we can revive or modify after an order or 
 scheme of the imagination derived from time and 
 space relations. 
 
 In contrast with these sense-objects and sense- 
 groups of phenomena we grasp after 
 
 ° Noumena. 
 
 Noumena, i.e., intelligible realities, as 
 possible and actual. We come nearest to these 
 when we seem to be conscious of our own Ego or 
 self, but even then we find that what we seize is 
 but an illusion — an illusion of thought or a 
 figure of speech. However imposing and compli-
 
 PRINCIPAL ETHICAL TREATISES. 21 
 
 cated these may seem to be, they are only plic- 
 )ioiii('Ha, suggesting, it may be, the iioiniiriKt. the 
 tilings which can never be reached. When, however, 
 we rise to the highest forms of knowledge, other a 
 priori elements present themselves and seem to be 
 required to make possible our highest moods of ex- 
 perience, possible or rational. These are the so- 
 called Ideas of the Reason, viz.: the Soul, the orderly 
 Kosmos, and the Self-existent, or the Absolute: God! 
 Without each and all of these a priori elements, we 
 can neither employ nor apply the lessons of expe- 
 rience, we can attain neither speculative knowledge 
 nor practical wisdom. And yet, for all this, we 
 have no scientific authority for believing any of 
 these objects of thought to be real, although we can- 
 not avoid reasoning and acting as if they were so. 
 
 i; 10. This is a brief statement of Kant's specu- 
 lative system and the position into which 
 
 Limits of 
 
 it brings man in respect to his con- Human 
 fidence in the speculative reason. Phe- 
 nomena are known and knowable, and only phe- 
 nomena, phenomena external and internal — never 
 things in themselves. Noumena are neither knowa- 
 ble nor known. Phenomena are connected with one 
 another by I'elations a priori of space and time, also 
 by the relations of thought, making complete the
 
 22 kant\s ethics. 
 
 semblances but never revealing the realities of either 
 things or spirits. Both these again can be con- 
 nected, i.e., regulated by the ideas suggested by the 
 mental and material universe, both being dependent 
 on and united by. the uncreated God. while yet these 
 ideas are vouched for by no absolute and <i priori 
 certainty. 
 
 It hardly need be said that this outcome of 
 Di a D int- Kent's Critique is, so far, the exact 
 ment. opposite of what would be anticipated 
 
 from the purposes and promises with wiiich he 
 began. It would seem from the confidence of 
 his promises at the outset, that he was about to 
 introduce us to a wide range of spiritual knowledge, 
 knowledge which should be equally clear and posi- 
 tive on the spiritual and on the material side. Al- 
 lured by these promises, we yield ourselves submis- 
 sively and confidently to his guidance, following 
 him step by step ; but at each step our footing be- 
 comes less firm, the path itself sinks deeper and 
 deeper, and at the end we hardly know whether it is 
 treacherous marsh or iridescent cloud-land on which 
 we seem now to tread and then to fly. But just as 
 we are overwhelmed in the mire of uncertainty or 
 n . . are entangled most hopelessly in the net- 
 
 Promised ° i » 
 
 Deliverance, work of a priori relations, to which we
 
 PRINCIPAL ETIIICAJ. TREATISES. 23 
 
 cling for deliverance, to tind that they do nothing 
 but hold themselves together, we are hailed by our 
 guide with words of cheer in the Kanon of Pure 
 Reason. Under this title he ventures to assure us 
 that his ethical system will remove all the difficulties 
 in which criticism had involved us, that it will bring 
 light and solidity and certainty both to our knowl- 
 edge and our faith, that it will give back to us 
 material things and spiritual entities, God and 
 Immortality, all of which had seemed to take their 
 flight at his conjuring wand — in other words, that 
 tlie Critique of Practical Reason will by the authority 
 of its simple imperative deliver us from the sjDirit of 
 doubt with which the criticism of the speculative 
 reason had overwhelmed us. 
 
 i; 11. The elements of this would-be construc- 
 tive ethics are briefly as follows: Fii'st Elements of 
 of all. our teacher advises us that it is ^^"*^ ,. 
 
 Constructive 
 
 of comparatively little consequence what Ethics, 
 our speculative views may be, even in respect to 
 the most important subjects. We ought not to 
 be seriously disturbed by speculative criticism of 
 any sort, inasmuch as after all our chief concern is 
 with what we should he and do, not with what we 
 can kiioir. The questions which we need most to 
 settle are practical questions, and concern the free-
 
 24 KA^■TV KTIIICS. 
 
 dom of the will, the immortality of the soul, and the 
 existence of God. inasmuch as these atfect what we 
 can do in the exercise of our freedom. As this free- 
 dom is intelligent, its impulses must be stimulated 
 and directed by enlightened reflection on the motives 
 which impel it to action. Hence, if there be free- 
 dom there must be knowledge of what is profitable 
 and useful and desirable, not of what merely seems 
 to be. but of what (icfiialh/ Is. It also implies the 
 knowledge of what ought to be done — consequently 
 that which if it ought, inai/ be done. Both these 
 descriptions of motives are Jairs or imperatives, either 
 the imperative of interest, saying: If you will gain 
 this or that, do so or so; or the imperative of free- 
 dom, telling us what ought to be done, and therefore 
 implying that it can be done, in the exercise of man's 
 highest prerogative. That is. so far as the direction 
 of conduct is concerned, it is of no consequence 
 whether what seems to be actually is what it ap- 
 pears to be. or whether we can know what it is, or 
 whether anything is, m the sense of reality, pro- 
 vided we are confronted with the imperative. Do this 
 or tJiat. 
 
 With the mutual relations of these two kinds of 
 law we have nothing to do, so long as the law of 
 duty unconditionally presents what ive oax/ld to do.
 
 PRINCIPAL ETHI(A]> TREATISES. '40 
 
 Xor is it of any consequence whether they are or 
 are not reconcilable, or whether they have any com- 
 mon root. The prescription of reason still remains 
 supreme. Do flxft ichir/i is rif/lif. 
 
 ^ 12. In respect to our highest good, however, or 
 the sintiiiuim boHiiin, the question of Ti,ree impor- 
 the mutual relations of what is and ^f " Q^e^^^io"^ 
 
 1 ropof e« by 
 
 ought to be, is most important. The Kam. 
 satisfactory answer to this turns upon the three 
 inquiries: What am I knoir'f Wlmt oii(/lif I to do? 
 ]VJt((t tiiai/ I hope fofi:' 
 
 TJie first of these questions had been partially but 
 unsatisfactorily answered in the terms: I can know 
 only phenomena, not nouinena or things m them- 
 selves. I can also know their relations in some 
 sense, provided it be not what might be called their 
 nature or essence. TJie second, being practical, can- 
 not be answered in terms of intellectual knowledge, 
 inasmuch as intellectual knowledge only gives us an 
 acquaintance with phenomena, but never with reali- 
 ties or things in themselves. The third, however, 
 is both practical and theoretical, and in fact is 
 answered thus: You can know that the something 
 which you hope for will be, because it ought to be. 
 You can know there is a God and a future life, 
 because both must be, in order that virtue may be
 
 26 rant's ethics. 
 
 rewarded and vice may be punished; or, in other 
 words, that what ought to be must be. In other 
 words, tlie problem of knowledge, which, as a prob- 
 lem of the speculative reason, has hitherto been un- 
 solved, and baffled all our attempts to explain it, is 
 settled by the impei-ative demands of the practical 
 reason. The comprehensive principle which is the 
 basis of all practical knowledge, and indirectly of 
 all knowledge whatever, is the principle that the 
 virtuous ought to be happy. They cannot be happy 
 unless there is another life. They cannot be happy 
 unless God exists to reward them and to punish the 
 bad ; or, more comprehensively, unless certain sem- 
 blances or phenomena of things are conformed to 
 things as they are, i.e., to things in themselves. 
 
 § 13. Whatever on second thought we may think 
 Plausibility of ^^ ^^^^^ argument, it cannot be denied 
 His Solution. ^Ij^i- ^^ ^j.^^ yjg^y -^ gggi^^j. plausible, and 
 
 for the reason that it recognizes moral relations 
 a.s 2) I'ctcti call 1/ supreme — and if ethical relations are 
 practically supreme, they are not only themselves 
 speculatively true, but they impart authority and 
 validity to certain relations and things which are 
 purely speculative. When tried by the criterion 
 of the realities of common sense, w^hich holds to 
 the possibility of the knowledge of nouinena, at
 
 PRINCIPAL ETHICAL TREATISES. 37 
 
 least in the world of spirit, which recognizes a 
 community of relations between the intellectual 
 and the ethical universe, common sense asserts 
 that the ethical and the emotional stand high- 
 est of all rational considerations as grounds of 
 truth and evidences of realit3\ But when viewed 
 against the background of the Kantian scepticism, 
 which limits all knowledge to phenomena, and. 
 after denying the capacity of reason to discover the 
 objective truth which it yet asserts must be as- 
 sumed, comes in to help reason out of the ditch into 
 which it had plunged it, by requiring it to abandon 
 its own appropriate functions, the argument is not 
 likely to be so readily welcomed as a helper. The 
 blow which first strikes a man to the earth, if it is a 
 blow of dishonor, is far more likely to be remem- 
 bered and resented than the helping hand which is 
 subsequently moved in condescending pity to lift 
 him up. Unsophisticated and logical common sense 
 suggests the thought that if the mind be as limited 
 in the range and authority of its knowledge as 
 Kant has written a long book to persuade us is true, 
 then we can know only the relations of phenomena, 
 in ever\' form or method of reasoning, the specula- 
 tive and practical alike. Likewise when I reason 
 that T shall live another life because I ought to be
 
 28 rant's hthkjs. 
 
 rewarded or punished, and shall find a God living to 
 deal with me iiccordiiig to my deserts, then I have 
 already assumed tlx' i-cality of two uoiimeiia at 
 least, if not Ihe reality of three; certainly that of the 
 conscious Ego and God the rewarder, and, it would 
 seem, of the Kosmos, as a permanent noumenon, 
 with its changing phenomena of a here and a 
 hereafter. 
 
 i; 14. I)i»nl)l less Kant easily persuaded l)imself, 
 oiiiiKiitioii t.. "^^ ^^^ many of his readers, that he re- 
 CoiiHisteiicy. li^ves himself from this a[)parent in- 
 consistency by his view of the superior character 
 of ethical relations. But he cannot thereby evade 
 the obligation- to be consistent with himself. He 
 tells us, indeed, thnt the practical reason not 
 only affirms certnin relations of conduct, by syn- 
 thetic judgments h priori, but that it also en- 
 forces them in the f(jriiis of command. He asserts, 
 moreover, that these commands involve relations of 
 merit and demerit, and that these i-o([uire a being 
 who is able and willing to enforce them. Hut he 
 forgets altogethei' to recognize the truth that in all 
 these assertions he lias overstepped the limits within 
 which he had entrenclKid hiinsell: Ihat every one of 
 these ethical demands supposes noumcna in the form 
 of personal beings — that only the Ego as an exist-
 
 PKIXCIPAL ETHICAL TREATISES. 20 
 
 ing being, and not at all as a phenomenon, can 
 respond to a command or apprehend merit or a pos- 
 sible iiii mortality, and that all the plausibility that 
 his argument gains when regarded as a proof for the 
 Ego, or a future life, or an existing God. is derived 
 from the dexterity, or, rather, we should say. the 
 unconsciousness, with which at the critical or turn- 
 ing points of his argument Kant adroitly substitutes 
 the noumenal for the phenomenal, and interchanges 
 the relations which are appropriate to each. That 
 moral relations and moral interests may be the most 
 convincing of all in respect to the continued exist- 
 ence of the soul, and that the moral constitution of 
 the soul may be the one transparent medium 
 through wliich we gain and keep our faith in the 
 moral pei'fection and righteous government of God. 
 are both most important truths. These truths lend 
 color and plausibility to Kant's ethical remedy 
 against the scepticism he had created: but they 
 cannot in the least justify or alleviate the sugges- 
 tion of the scepticism with which he had pi-eviously 
 cut the nerve of our confidence in every description 
 of truth, whether rational or ethical, 
 ii 1"). It should be remem])ered that 
 
 This Soliilion 
 
 this exposition and defence which Kant Pi-ciiminaiy 
 has furnished of his ethical theorv is '
 
 30 rant's ethics. 
 
 merely an anticipation of what he subsequently 
 expounded at lengtli in his two principal treatises. 
 As we have already stated, the attitude which he 
 assumed with respect to his ethical system became 
 more positive and assured after the publication of 
 the first Critique. His statements became more and 
 more dogmatic, his defences more assured, and his 
 illustrations more complete. He never, however, 
 parts with his intellectual dignity, or loses aught of 
 the most complete self-respect or reverence for his 
 own pei'sonal uprightness. 
 
 Thus far we have been occupied with these ethical 
 anticipations only, as we find them in the Critique 
 of Pure Reason. It was four years after its publi- 
 cation that he took a more positive attitude, and 
 gave to the world the Fundamental Principles of the 
 Metaphysics of Morals. Die Grundlegung zur Meta- 
 physik der Bitten. ITS-"). In this treatise he proposes 
 to himself the task of positively determining what 
 are the ultimate grounds or fundamental ejements 
 of moral science, as preliminary to the Critique 
 of Practical Reason. So far as the titles of these 
 two works would indicate a ditference in them as 
 objects or products of thought, the first would be 
 an analytic search for the principles of the science 
 of dutv. and the second a critical examination of
 
 PRINCIPAL ETHICAL TREATISES. 31 
 
 those functions of the same reason which originate 
 and sustain these principles or conclusions. The 
 second treatise, which in a sense was a supplement, 
 or completion, of the first, was published in 1788, 
 three years later. 
 
 § 16. In scrutinizing these treatises, we need to 
 be reminded, first, that it is not easy Kanfs 
 under any circumstances to thread our j^""thVaiui 
 way through the mazes of Kant's anal- Absolute, 
 yses and argumentations. Especially is this true 
 of his ethical writings, for the reason that man}^ of 
 the underlying practical truths which give color 
 and dignity to his discussions are so elevated and 
 weighty, and in their applied signification seem 
 so axiomatic and self-evident. Whether or not they 
 are scientifically exact, they are unquestionably in 
 some practical signification clothed with the highest 
 authority. Hence, in reading Kant's ethical writ- 
 ings, we are often exposed to the danger, and this 
 is often serious, of confounding popular with scien- 
 tific propositions, and of attaching a metaphysical 
 import and philosophical authority to distinctions and 
 propositions that are simply practical, and popular. 
 To avoid this danger, the following observations ma}' 
 not be out of place. 
 
 A sharp distinction should be made and held
 
 32 Kant's ethics. 
 
 between those metaphysical principles* which are 
 relatively and those which are absolutely primitive 
 and fundamental, i.e., between those propositions 
 which are axiomatic to one science and a group of 
 sciences, on the one hand, and those which, on the 
 other, are fundamental to all the sciences and to 
 scientific thinking as such. For example, it will not 
 be questioned that a few physical sciences rest upon 
 certain principles which are peculiar to themselves, 
 and yet are common to them all. The relations 
 being common, the concepts and principles are com- 
 mon. When grouped together, they constitute the 
 metaphysics which is common and fundamental 
 alike to all the physical sciences, as mechanics, 
 optics, chemistry, etc. Similarly, each individual 
 science has its own metaphysics, and we speak briefly 
 and confidently of the metaphysics of mathematics, 
 of chemistry, etc. Similarly, we speak of the meta- 
 physics of the organic or vital sciences in common, 
 and of the metaphysics of plant and animal life in 
 special. Similarly, it may be supposed that there 
 may be special and general metaphysics of all spirit- 
 ual beings in common, and of the intellectual, emo- 
 tional, and voluntary activities in particular. 
 
 *Por variety in the signififatioii of Principles see Porter: Iliunan 
 Intellect, § 514.
 
 PKlJSrCIPAL ETHICAL TKEATISES. 33 
 
 § 17. We observe here that the special meta- 
 physical principles which are funda- Fnndamentai 
 
 Principles 
 
 mental to ethics have the very peculiar of Ethics 
 attraction of beino- easilv apprehended ''^"'^^'^^'"'^*"'" 
 
 " .'11 gtood and 
 
 by, and, so to speak, accessible to, all Assented to. 
 men. They commend themselves to the assenting 
 convictions of all. More than all, they appeal to 
 the emotions of mankind, and to the emotions 
 which are the strongest and most tender. They 
 are clothed with the most sacred authority, and 
 evoke the noblest and the most disinterested of 
 the affections. For these reasons it often happens 
 that men who deny all other axioms, because per- 
 haps they cannot understand them for the general 
 or abstract language in which they are phrased, 
 cannot withhold their assent to the axioms of eth- 
 ical truth, and, for the simple reason that these 
 are the only principles with which they are familiar 
 and which they can understand, are ready to ac- 
 cept them as the only truths which are invested 
 with self-evident certainty. Hence, should the de- 
 mand be made upon them in view of the obscurity 
 or the uncertainty of all other fundamental truths, 
 to accept ethical truths as the possible foundations of 
 all the rest, the demand finds a comparatively ready 
 
 response. Every other special mpta[)hysics is to their 
 3
 
 34 • K A NT's ETHICS. 
 
 mind more or less abstract and unfamiliar, whether 
 it be the metaphysics of mathematics, or chem- 
 istry, or physics, etc. The same is true of general 
 metaphysics, i.e., the metaphysics of everything 
 that is knowable, whether subdivided into spirit and 
 matter, or generalized as being, finite and infinite. 
 B);t the special axioms of duty, the truths and laws 
 which are suggested on all occasions and enforced by 
 universal experience, these are so clear, so severe, 
 and so true that no man can question them. What- 
 ever else a man may question, he will never question 
 these "truths which wake to perish never."' It is 
 not surprising that the mind which is shaken by 
 every other scepticism should not only rest upon 
 ethical truths as unshaken, but should also accept 
 these as giving authority to truth of ever}^ kind, and 
 as being themselves the cornerstones of all knowl- 
 edge and the tests of all our other faiths, whether in 
 man, or nature, or God. 
 
 § 18. We should never lose sight of the fact that 
 
 , , . the speculative metaphysics of Kant, as 
 
 In Speculative ^ ^ 
 
 Principles presented in the Critique of Pure Rea- 
 
 Kant Claims 
 
 Oniya Relative SOU, not onlv failed to procure assent to 
 
 ion y. itself as thoroughly trustworthy, but 
 
 formally renounced for itself any other than a partial 
 
 and relative supremacy. While its able expounder
 
 PRIXCIPAL ETHICAL TREATISES. 35 
 
 contended for the necessity of assuming certain fun- 
 damental principles of the speculative reason as the a 
 priori conditions of all knowledge, he as deliberately 
 and scientifically contends that this necessity is 
 simply subjective and carries with it no objective 
 reality. The forms and categories and ideas which 
 enter into the very structure of all scientific knowl- 
 edge, are held by him to be simply necessary to make 
 experience possible and science trustworthy. The 
 a priori or metaphysical elements are necessary, 
 otherwise common experience and reasoned science 
 would be impossible. But as to whether these sub- 
 jective elements have also any objective reality, he 
 teaches us that we can neither affirm nor deny. It 
 is not surprising that under the pressure of this 
 necessity he should have reverted to the sacred rela- 
 tions of dut}' as the sheet anchor of both science 
 and faith, that in this desperate need the practical 
 axioms of prudence and duty should take occasion 
 to assert their superior attractiveness and authority, 
 nor that the appeal should also be made to them 
 as competent to clear up whatever else seemed ob- 
 scure, and to restore the faith in scientific truth 
 I? 
 
 which had been deliberately undermined. In other 
 words, it is not surprising that the axioms of a 
 special science should have been generalized so
 
 36 rant's ethics. 
 
 broadly as to serve as a speculative basis lor the 
 entire truth of the sciences in general, and that the 
 fundamental truths of ethics should be accepted as 
 fundamental, not only to the successful conduct of 
 life, but to every description of knowledge whatever. 
 § 19. The reasons why such a transfer and con- 
 fusion of in'inciples and of thoucrht 
 
 Danger of Con- '■ '■ ^ 
 
 founding would be plausible, have already been 
 
 Speculative 
 
 and Ethical e.xplained. That Kant had sought to 
 ""^'^"'''' prove the objective untrustworthiness 
 of any and every form of purely speculative meta- 
 physics, has been made sufficiently clear. As we 
 have already explained, it is no part of our duty to 
 discuss at any length the question whether these 
 attempts to weaken our confidence in this trust- 
 worthiness were successful. That inquiry must be 
 transferred to the critical examination of his specu- 
 lative system. Nor have we as yet attempted to 
 show that his effort to substitute an ethical for a 
 rational metaphysics was a failure. We have only 
 suggested certain reasons why ethical or practical 
 principles might readily be accepted by many stu- 
 dents and readers as fundamental.for all knowledge, 
 when there was no occasion to resort to them, on 
 the one hand, nor any demonstrated capacity in 
 them to meet the demand, on the other. It was
 
 PRINCIPAL P:THICAL TREATISES. 37 
 
 Kant who attempted to show that they could meet 
 the supiK)sed exicjenev. It is our first „, „ 
 
 1 ' o . \\ Q Proceed 
 
 duty to inquire whether he was sue- ^ext to the 
 
 Examination 
 
 cessful. But all this is preliminary to of His Formal 
 our formal examination of Kant's ethi- ^ 
 cal system as a whole. This examination, we may 
 expect, will develop the weakness and strength of 
 his exposition of his views upon every point. Our 
 critical comments, thus far, have been confined to 
 the brief anticipations of his ethical theory which we 
 find in the Critique of Pure Reason.* 
 
 The detailed exposition of Kant's ethical system is 
 found in the two treatises already referred to. We 
 begin with the first. 
 
 * Transceudentale Methodenlclire, 2tes Hauptstiick.
 
 CHAPTER II. 
 
 THE FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE 
 METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. * 
 
 § 20. This treatise does not profess to be a com- 
 The Metaphys- plete discussion of all the metaphysical 
 
 ics of Morals ... i • i n i i ^ ^ 
 
 Tentative principles which are rundamental to 
 *-*"'y- practical and scientific ethics. It is 
 
 rather a statement of its more important prob- 
 lems, i.e., such as are preliminary to a critical ex- 
 amination of the practical reason or the so-called 
 moral faculty, and to a completed and ration- 
 alized system of duties and precepts as a final 
 result. The treatise also supposes the reader to be 
 acquainted with the author's speculative system as 
 expounded in the Critique of Pure Reason, and the 
 distinctions which that treatise labors to establish. 
 The writer had certainly a right to assume that 
 the doctrines which he had so elaborately ex- 
 pounded in his magnum opus had by this time 
 become familiar to every reader of the later trea- 
 tise, and he does not hesitate to proceed upon this 
 assumption. In this way we explain and excuse the 
 brevity and the abruptness of some portions of this 
 
 * Grnndlegung ziir Metaphysik der .Sitten. 
 38
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 30 
 
 his first ethical essay, and the apparent obscurity of 
 some of its allusions. 
 
 § 21. In the preface Kant directs the attention 
 of the reader to the fact that all knowl- 
 
 A Metaphysics 
 
 edge is either /'or/^(f/i or material — the o^'^^ora.i^ 
 
 Possible. 
 
 formal concerning itself with the uni- 
 versal laws or relations of thought, without re- 
 spect to its objects, while the material respects the 
 varying properties of existing things as either phys- 
 ical, i.e., necessar}'', or spiritual, i.e., free. He also 
 notices that the laws which respect either may re- 
 spect events as they are or as they ought to be; thus 
 giving the distinction between physics and ethics. 
 Then again, we call philosophy empirical so far as it 
 is based on experience, and metaphysical when it 
 rests on a priori principles. Consequently, physics 
 and ethics may be either empirical or pure, so far 
 as they rest upon either. 
 
 These distinctions being established, the writer 
 proposes the question whether it is possible to estab- 
 lish a system of ethics that shall be a purely rational 
 science, and as such " perfectly cleared of every- 
 thing which is only empirical and which belongs to 
 anthi'opology."* To this he replies, that such a 
 
 * We notice here once for all that the doctrine which Kant so 
 often refers to and so often rejects under this title, was the current
 
 40 K ant's ethics. 
 
 [ihilosophy is possible " is evident from the common 
 idea of duty and of the moral law/' For example, 
 the precept, " Thou shalt not lie,"' is not valid for 
 man alone as man. but also for other rational 
 beings, and consequently its basis is not to be sought 
 in man's human nature, nor in his circumstances. 
 " but a priori simply in the conceptions of the pure 
 reason. * * * Though this or any other precept 
 which is founded on mere experience may be in cer- 
 tain respects universal, yet so far as it rests on an 
 empirical basis, even only as to its motive, such a 
 precept, though it may be called a practical rule, 
 can never be called a moral law * * * Moral 
 philosophy when applied to man does not borrow 
 the least thing from the knowledge of man himself 
 {i.e., from anthropology) but gives laws (/ priori to 
 him as a rational being. * * * a metaphysics of 
 moi'als is therefore indispensably necessary, not 
 merely for speculative reasons, * * * but also 
 because morals themselves are liable to all sorts of 
 corruption so long as we are without that clue and 
 
 theory received from the aucient schools, that a life of virtue or 
 moral excellence is "a life according to nature," human nature being 
 understood by this term. It is singular that Kant should have over- 
 looked the possible reply to his oft-repeated strictures; that it was 
 human nature g?/a-rational, that was intended, and that the ideal of 
 aspiration and the norm of judgment was never the emotional or 
 the passionate, or, as Kant would <:all it, the empirical, in man.
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 41 
 
 supreme canon by which to estimate them correctly. 
 For in order that an action should be morally good, 
 it is not enough that it should conform to the moral 
 law, but it should also be done for the ml;e of tlie 
 law.'' 
 
 In order to make it clear that the author's theory 
 of ethical ideas diifers from that which was current 
 in his time, he calls attention to the doctrine of 
 Wolf in his Propa?deutic, who contends for the free- 
 dom of the will as the foundation of moral concepts, 
 but, in the judgment of Kant, overlooks altogether 
 the point that it is with acts of pure will, as such, 
 that moral freedom is especially concerned; in other 
 words, that the subjective element of freedom, as 
 such, is not the preeminently ethical element, but 
 that what is distinctively ethical is the a priori, 
 motive with which the will is confronted by and from 
 the reason. 
 
 § 22. In these terms and statements the author 
 vaguely sketches the theory which he preliminary 
 proposes to explain and defend at length ^^"i,*!',,'!'!."^ ^^"^ 
 in respect to the fundamental concep- ^vstem. 
 tions*of scientific morality, and more than vaguely 
 hints what that theory will inevitably prove to be. 
 The chief points which he has thus far explicitly 
 stated, seem to be the following: That moral relations
 
 42 kant's ethics. 
 
 are discerned b}' the reason, and by the reason only, 
 and consequently have no discernible or necessary 
 relation to the empirical or emotional nature, which 
 neither enters into their essence nor imparts to them 
 authority. It follows, as it would seem, that he 
 holds that neither the nature of man as man nor as 
 a sensitive, rational being furnishes the ground or 
 enters into the definition of ethical conceptions, but 
 that these distinctive elements are simply a priori, 
 i.e., are a peculiar class of relations, which are dis- 
 cerned and enforced by the practical reason inde- 
 pendently and alone. All this is vaguely assumed 
 in the preface, or intimated as certain to be. the 
 result of the subsequent discussion. It is also man- 
 ifest even to the superficial reader that this preface 
 was written after the essay, and cannot be fully 
 appreciated till the essay shall have been read, de- 
 pending as it does for its interpretation and enforce- 
 ment upon the subsequent discussions of which it 
 gives an indefinite outline or an obscure anticipa- 
 tion. It concludes with the programme in which 
 the author proposes, (1) to proceed from 
 
 Division of 
 
 Topics in the the common to the philosophical knowl- 
 
 Grundlegung. , 
 
 edge ot morals, (2) irom popular, 
 i.e.., g'Ma.si - rational, morals to its metaphysics, 
 and (3) from its metaphysics to the Critique of
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MOKALS. 43 
 
 the Pure Practical Reason — the second treatise, 
 for which this is the introduction. This pro- 
 gramme, in a general way, is adhered to by the 
 author with no great rigor of method: as is 
 manifest from the digressions and anticipations 
 which characterize his always somewhat rambling 
 discussion. 
 
 § 23. The hrst section of the treatise 
 
 Import of his 
 
 opens with the memorable and often opening 
 
 , - _ , . Sentence. 
 
 quoted utterance, that JNothing can 
 possibly be conceived in the world, or even out of it, 
 which can be called good without qualification, except 
 a good will." If character is compared with gifts of 
 nature, as intelligence, courage, and gifts of fortune, 
 as riches, health, or contentment, all these are de- 
 fective, " if there is not a good will to correct their 
 |)ossible perversion and to rectify the whole princi- 
 ple of acting, and adapt it to its end." A man 
 who is endowed with every other good can never 
 give pleasure to an impartial rational spectator. 
 unless he possesses a good will. " Thus a good will 
 appears to constitute the indispensable condition of 
 being worthy of happiness. * * * Moreover, a 
 good will is good, not for what it effects, but for 
 what it intends, even when it fails to accomplish its 
 vurposes, * * * as when a man wills the good
 
 44 rant's ethics. 
 
 of anothev and is impotent to promote it, or actuall}' 
 effects just the opposite of what he proposes or 
 wills." 
 
 The author anticipates that this last proposition 
 may seem extravagant, and for this reason he sub- 
 jects it to a careful scrutinj^ He urges that if 
 happiness,* as such, were the chief purpose of na- 
 ture, this end would have been more effectually pro- 
 vided for by a simple instinct impelling directly and 
 invariably to this end, instead of being left to the 
 fallibility of the individual reason and the caprice of 
 the individual will. The actual arrangements of 
 nature, as we find them, would seem to indicate that 
 they all suppose adaptation to the occasions and ser- 
 vice of a good will as a good in itself. This good 
 will as a good in itself must be "'the supreme good 
 and the condition of every other, even of the desire 
 of happiness," though it is not the sole or the com- 
 plete good, inferior and accidental goods being 
 often connected with or separated from this as the 
 supreme. 
 
 § 28. Kant proceeds to reason if we seek to 
 
 * As though happiness, as sucli. or the production of happiness, had 
 ever been supposed to have any niorjl excellence, or anything short of 
 the i>o^(7)i«ri/ production of happiness, and of the hiirhest happiness at 
 that. .\s though all moralists who are worth considering had not em- 
 pliasi/ed the good will, or tlic willing of good, as the supreme excel- 
 lence.
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF ilOKALS. 45 
 
 define this '"good will" — in other words, to define 
 an act of duty — we must first set aside 
 
 Kanfs liitiT- 
 
 all those actions which are inconsistent prutation of 
 
 the Good Will. 
 
 with duty. JNone oi these can proceed 
 from a "good will.'' We shall also exclude all those 
 acts which are consistent with duty, and yet are 
 done from incliiiafion oiihj, and not with a conscious 
 recognition of them as morally good, (i) An Act 
 
 T 1 -i. • J 1 ii from Inclina- 
 
 in every such case, it is assumed by the .. „ ^ 
 
 •' ' -^ tion Not an 
 
 author that the act cannot be an act of -'^ct of Dnty. 
 duty at all. As, for example, a trader is honest 
 from good policy only, or a man preserves his 
 life as duty requires, but not because duty re- 
 quires; or, though to be beneficent where we can 
 be is a duty, yet if a man is beneficent because of 
 the delight which follows to his pathological or emo- 
 tional nature, his acts are not acts of duty, "' For 
 the maxim of conduct here wants the moral import, 
 namely, that such actions be done from diit)/, not 
 from inclination. * * * It is in this manner, un- 
 doubtedly, that we are to understand those passages 
 of Scripture, also, in which we are commanded to 
 love our neighbor, even our enemy. For love,* as an 
 
 * We notice here that Kant doeir not recoirnize the i)ossibiIity that 
 love, or any affection or emotion, shonld be impelled or regiil;ited Ijy the 
 will, but conceives of the will as the controller of the actions only, j.^"., 
 the bodily actions. Consequently, the comprehensive law, '-Thou shall 
 /ove the Lord thy God," becomes to him impossible and nnnieanint.'.
 
 46 KAXT's ETIIIUS. 
 
 afiPection. cannot be commanded, but only beneficence 
 for duty's sake, even though we are not impelled to 
 it by any inclination, nay, are even repelled by a 
 natural and unconquerable aversion. It is prac- 
 tical love, and not pafJiolof/ical, a love which is seated 
 in the will, and not in the propensions of sense; in 
 principles of action, and not of tender sympathy; 
 and it is this love only which can be commanded." 
 
 § 24. The second proposition is, " that an action 
 (2)The Maxim, done from duty derives its moral worth, 
 no^ u> IK. ^^^|. £j.Qj^^ j.|jg purpose which is to be at- 
 Moral Worth, tained by it,"' but from the maxim by 
 which it is determined, and that its moral character, 
 therefore, does not depend on the purpose being 
 realized, but merely on the " principle of the voli- 
 tion " which has produced the action. Such a prin- 
 ciple is formal or a priori, as contrasted with a 
 spontaneous or material spring of action. 
 
 We observe here that by maxim Kant means the 
 action in the mind of the individual, the intended 
 object, when expressed as purposed by the individual, 
 and thus indicating the rule by which he is in fact 
 controlled. 
 
 (3) Respect S 25. The third proposition derived 
 
 .?' ^!-. ,'r from the foregoing is, that "dutv is the 
 
 Essential to o f? ■ 
 
 Duty. necessity of acting from respect for the
 
 THE METAPHYSICS 0f""M0RALS. 47 
 
 law. I may have an inclination for an object as 
 an effect of my action, but I cannot have respect 
 for it, just for this reason, that it is an effect and 
 not an energy of will. * * * Jt is onlij what is con- 
 nected with the will as a principle, but by no means 
 as an effect — what does not subserve my inclination, 
 but overpowers it, or, at least, in case of choice ex- 
 cludes it from its calculation — in other words, it is 
 simply the law of itself, which can be an object of 
 respect, and hence a command. 
 
 •■ But what sort of law can there be, the very 
 thought of which must determine the The Content 
 will, without reference to any effect? °^j™_'*°j'^^^j 
 * * * Every impulse, as such, has Law. 
 been set aside from being a principle. Nothing 
 remains but the universal conformity of action 
 to law in general." In other words, " I am never 
 to act otherwise than so that I could also will 
 that my maxim should become a universal law." 
 What the author intends by this very abstract state- 
 ment he illustrates by an example: I ask, may I ever 
 when in distress make a promise, with the intention 
 not to keep it? We do not ask, Is it never prudent, 
 but is it ever right, thus to do? For myself it may 
 be safe and advantageous, not only in a single in- 
 stance, but in every case. There is a short way to
 
 48 kant's ethics. 
 
 decide the question, " whether a lying promise is 
 ever consistent with duty," and that is to ask 
 whether such a rule of action can ever be made 
 a universal law. Though I can will a lie, I can- 
 not will that lying should be a universal law. 
 Why this should be, Kant does not here attempt 
 to explain. He would even assert that no explan- 
 ation of this unfitness "" to become a law is pos- 
 sible. This remains as an unsolved problem, and 
 yet somehow we know that a law, to be moral, must 
 be such as can enter into universal legislation; also 
 that it must extort or command respect, and that this 
 respect takes precedence over and sets aside what- 
 ever is recommended by inclination. Moreover, the 
 necessity of acting from pure respect to the law 
 constitutes duty, and is the condition of that good 
 will which is a good in itself, and consequently is 
 the only thing which can be styled good without 
 qualification. 
 
 In concluding the first section, the author adverts 
 to the fact that the practical reason reveals its dis- 
 tinctions with a simplicity and an authority which 
 are strikingly contrasted with the maxims and pvin- 
 
 *" Fitness to become a law," it should bo observed, is no adap- 
 tation that is founded in the nature of man, indi\idually or socially; 
 Kant says of it, that it is purely rational, whatever this may be, ami 
 moreover, that it extorts and commands respect.
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 4.9 
 
 ciples taught by the speculative reason. Conse- 
 quently, to accept the first, he urges, is eminently 
 safe and wise, even when they seem to be inconsis- 
 tent with the teachings of the last. And yet we are 
 impelled by a necessity which we cannot resist to 
 attempt to reconcile the two, but always with a 
 tenacious faith in the superior commands of the 
 practical reason. 
 
 § 26. We have already adverted {cf. § 10) to the 
 (/i<c/s«-sceptical mood in respect to the ,, . , 
 
 ^ >■ - Kant s Scep- 
 
 trustworthiness of speculative truth, ticism in 
 
 Respect to 
 
 with its forms and its categories, with speculative 
 its ideas, phenomena, noumena. and all, 
 into which Kant had brought himself and would 
 fain bring his reader, as the outcome of the 
 Critique of Pure Reason. We have also ex- 
 plained the deliverance from these entanglements 
 which he anticipated as possible through the cate- 
 gorical imperative of duty, as implied in and en- 
 forced by the practical reason. The principal 
 elements of this concept of dut}- have been given 
 in this first section, as he conceives them to occur 
 in the experience of unreflecting men. To these 
 experiences, as we have seen, he makes his final 
 appeal. Whether his analysis of these experiences 
 is satisfactory in all these particulars remains to be
 
 50 kaxt's ethics. 
 
 seen, as we seek to subject it to careful criticism 
 before we proceed to an examination of the ampler 
 discussions which follow. We do this at once be- 
 cause this section presents in a brief but popular 
 form many of the distinctive features of Kant's 
 entire theor}', the fallacy of which, when detected 
 and exposed, may aid the reader in detecting similar 
 errors in the subsequent arguments, and especially 
 may sharpen his discernment to distinguish between 
 a popular and a scientific metaphysics of ethics. 
 § 27. Thus far have we been content to explain 
 Kant's argument. We begin our criti- 
 
 Criticism of 
 
 Kant's First cism with Kaut's first sentence, an ut- 
 
 Sentence. , i • i i i i • /> 
 
 terance which has become classic rrom 
 its fervid tone, and which, when rightly inter- 
 preted, expresses an important practical truth. 
 ''Xofhhtg can jwssibli/ be conceired in the icorld, or 
 even out of it, which can he called good ivithout 
 qualification, except a good iriJI.'' To this propo- 
 sition, as an utterance of practical ethical truth in 
 popular language, the adherent of almost every 
 ethical theory would give his ready and fervent 
 assent. But as uttered by Kant, it expresses the 
 metaphysical principle (in technical language) that 
 moral goodness has no relation to any other good- 
 ness; that it is not only superior in quality to
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OP MORALS. 61 
 
 every other, but cannot properly be classed or com- 
 pared with any other. As accepted with equal posi- 
 tiveness and fervor, as it may be and often is, by 
 those who dissent from Kant, it asserts the incom- 
 parable and unquestioned superiority of the moral 
 among the other kinds of good with which it can, 
 and, as it would seem, iinist be compared, in order 
 that its supremacy may be manifest. As applied by 
 Kant, it asserts that there is but one real good, 
 "good without qualification,"' and that is moral 
 good, which cannot be defined in terms of any other, 
 and which certainly cannot be classed with any 
 other, and as it would seem can be compared with 
 no other. As assented to by those who dissent from 
 Kant's philosophy, it would require them to substi- 
 tute the phrase, "the supreme good," for "good 
 without qualification," meaning by " supreme " the 
 "best in quality or kind,'' as distinguished from 
 the most energetic or intense. 
 
 § 28. The "good will'" which either is or brings 
 so great a good, in the view of those who 
 
 Diverse 
 
 dissent from Kant, is an act or state of Meanings of 
 the will, a voluntary choice or love of 
 the highest or supreme natural good, which for 
 this reason is both logically and actually superior to 
 every other, "a good without qualification,"" "a
 
 52 KANT*S ETHICS. 
 
 good beyond compare." The difference between the 
 two positions is explained by the fact that, according 
 to Kant, the good will is determined by no impulse 
 of or motion in, the sensibility, eitlier felt or dis- 
 cerned, but by the simple authority' of the reason, 
 which utters its dictum or command without a 
 reason. Hence the good will which is recognized 
 
 (as "a good without qualification'" is a will deter- 
 mined hy the reason onJij, not merely in spite of 
 certain lower impulses of the sensibility, but inde- 
 pendently of any motives whatever which are ad- 
 dressed to any sensibilities that are higher. Ac- 
 cording to the dissentients from Kant, a good v^^ill 
 is an act or state of will which responds to a mo- 
 tive that addresses the highest or best natural sen- 
 sibility. The choice of such a good, but not the 
 chosen good, is the morally good will. 
 
 It would seem that when Kant's proposition was 
 thus fully and fairly stated, it would at least fail to 
 command unquestioning assent, if it did not in 
 many eases elicit a positive dissent. And yet it is 
 not difficult to understand why it should frequently 
 seem to be axiomatic and self-evident. It strikes 
 the key-note of Kant's ethical system, revealing its 
 apparent strength and its real weakness. It finds 
 its apparent strength in its homage to the higher
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 53 
 
 impulses, which it would fain exalt so high that they 
 should seem to rise above the region of the sensibil- 
 ities proper, and to float in the empyrean of the pure 
 reason. It finds additional plausibility in the em- 
 phasis which it lays upon the will as the centre and 
 source of all human responsibility, when contrasted 
 with the sensibility and intellect, either or both. Its 
 weakness lies in its oversight of the fact that it is 
 only through the sensibilities that the will can act 
 morally at all, by energizing and controlling them — 
 this oversight involving the depreciation and almost 
 the contemptuous disesteem of the feelings as psy- 
 chical experiences, and justifying the inference that 
 the emotional or pathological in man's nature, even 
 when animated and controlled by the will, is not 
 only not moral, but is positively immoral in its 
 functions and its products. 
 
 The opponents of Kant find no difficulty in assent- 
 ing to every one of his utterances as true and im- 
 portant, so long as they read between the lines their 
 own interpretation of the terms and propositions. 
 But while they accept with all their hearts his lead- 
 ing propositions when thus modified, they must pro- 
 test against the dishonor done to the sensibilities as 
 either an immoral or an unethical element of char- 
 acter. They would say emphatically, while it is
 
 54 KAKTS ETHICS. 
 
 true that mere sensibility, except as it is penetrated 
 and directed by the will, has no ethical character 
 whatever, it is equally true — a fact which Kant 
 overlooks, and would almost seem to deny — that an 
 act of mere will, except as it animates and controls 
 the sensibility, is equally unethical. Thej^ accept 
 the doctrine that " a good will is not good because of 
 what it performs or eflfects, nor b}' its aptness for 
 the attainment of some proposed end, but simply by 
 virtue of the volition," and yet reject the inference 
 that it is ''good in itself," if this implies that no 
 good, i.e., no sentient good, is in fact intended, pro- 
 posed as a maxim, felt as a motive, or obeyed as a 
 law, by this masterful good icill. 
 
 § 29. As we follow the argument of Kant, it 
 Kant's Defect- would seem as though he was led to 
 
 ive Conception 1,1 n pi- 1 • 
 
 of His Oppon- ^i^i^P^ct the soundness or his exclusion 
 ents' Doctrine, gf sentient good as an essential ele- 
 ment of the satisfactory definition of a good will, 
 when he urges that, were happiness the end of man's 
 existence it were better and more economical for na- 
 ture to bestow happiness on him without the hazard 
 of freedom, taking on herself the choice not only of 
 the ends of human life, but also of the means for 
 their attainment, and with wise forecast intrusting 
 both to " instinct" — as though anyone had contended
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OV MORALS. 65 
 
 or dreamed that any single element could constitute 
 the " good will." How could he overlook the fact 
 so often emphasized by himself, that the element of 
 freedom must be prominent in the intelligent 
 choice — as we say between higher and lower forms 
 of natural good — in order to impart to it a qual- 
 ity so peculiar that it alone could deserve to be 
 called "good in itself"? Is it not Kant himself who 
 contends that if nature would adapt means to an end, 
 " its true destination must be to produce a will, not 
 merely as a means to something else, but good in 
 itself, for which reason was absolutely necessary"? 
 Here the question cannot but suggest itself, if reason 
 was absolutely necessary to this good will, why might 
 not freedom also be necessary (contrary to his sup- 
 position of instinct), and if freedom and reason, 
 why might not sensibility be also required, with its 
 capacity for and its impulses toward higher and 
 lower natural good, even though it must also be vol- 
 untary and directed by reason in order to obtain an 
 ethical value and to rise to the unmatched excel- 
 lence of " the good will." 
 
 § 30. But from the position that the " good 
 will" is a "good in itself," Kant easily Kant's Limited 
 glides into the conclusion that it must !^"*^ °Z * 
 
 ° Conception of 
 
 control every other good, even " the Happiness.
 
 56 rant's ethics. 
 
 desire of happiness," as though these two could 
 in any sense be coordinate or come into conflict. 
 We notice here, and intreat our readers never to 
 lose sight of the fact, that " happiness " and the 
 •' desire of happiness," are invariably used by Kant 
 in a special and sensuous import, being limited to 
 the animal and other lower affections as contrasted 
 with the rational and higher. It will hardly be cred- 
 ited, and yet it is true, that an analyst and observer 
 ^ ^ . so acute as Kant fails to discern that 
 
 Gratification 
 
 "ftiie "the gratification of the reason'' in- 
 
 Reasoii. 
 
 volves the existence of one at least of 
 the higher classes of sensibilities as springs or 
 motives of action, implying the possibility of a 
 peculiar kind of happiness, and this although imme- 
 diately in this connection he observes that " the rea- 
 son recognizes the establishment of a good will as its 
 highest practical distinction, and in attaining this 
 purpose is capable of a satisfaction of its oivn pecu- 
 liar kind, viz. : that derived from the attainment of 
 an end which again " is determined by the reason 
 only, notwithstanding that this may involve many a 
 disappointment to the ends of inclination." No 
 language, it would seem, could be more explicit in 
 asserting that the reason and '' inclination " have each 
 its appropriate sensibility, dependent on its special
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 57 
 
 conditions, indeed, and its peculiar laws, but both be- 
 ing capacities for emotion and involving enjoyment 
 or suffering of differing kinds and degrees. There 
 can be no escape from this interpretation, unless the 
 satisfaction peculiar to reason is limited to that 
 which follows voluntary action. But in such case it 
 could not be brought into competition with inclina- 
 tion proper, and would have no meaning for Kant's 
 argument. There can be no escape from the conclu- 
 sion that Kant implicitly, if not avowedly, more than 
 once recognizes a natural happiness which reason 
 gives and which competes with inclination, even if 
 he did not explicitly recognize the ethical principle 
 of Aristotle, that one of the conditions of rational 
 satisfaction is the attainment of the end or purpose 
 of one's being, or the acting according to nature, — 
 which last Kant uniformly interprets as involving 
 empirical as opposed to ethical relations. 
 
 § 31. The next topic which is discussed by Kant 
 is the conception of duty. The first j^^^^^, 
 characteristic which he notices is that Defective 
 
 Conception 
 
 duty implies an activity of the will of Duty and 
 
 ■ . 1 • 1 Ti • r Obligation. 
 
 against conscious hindrances. It is a fa- 
 vorite and an oft-repeated doctrine of his that an act 
 of duty must be positively indifferent or disagree- 
 able to the natural sensibilities. He even formally
 
 58 rant's ethics. 
 
 defines " Duty as a compulsion to a purpose or aim 
 unwillingly adopted." Moreover, unless an act is 
 performed from a sense or motive of simple duty, 
 whether the person is or is not impelled by inclina- 
 tion, the act is not morally good. For this reason, 
 those acts to which we are impelled by strong nat- 
 ural sensibility, may fail to be morally good in spite 
 of this fact, and, in a sense, in consequence of it. 
 All of which is true, but not for the reason given 
 or assumed, that the element of sensibility is a 
 vitiating element, but because it is the rolmitanj ele- 
 ment alone which determines the moral quality of 
 the action, not as antagonistic to sensibility of every 
 sort, but as it selects between the lower or higher 
 natural sensibility, i.e., chooses between the higher 
 and lower natural good. It is also worthy of 
 notice that Kant fails altogether to discriminate 
 between internal and external acts of duty, usually 
 limiting duty to the latter, i.e., to the henejicent act 
 as contrasted with the benevolent volition — limiting 
 the sensibility to acts only as thus defined and con- 
 ceived, and appropriating the voluntary and re- 
 sponsible to the internal. 
 
 In still further elucidation of his 
 
 other 
 
 Oversights theory, he observes that right actions 
 must "be done from dutv, not from in-
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 59 
 
 clination," as though it were not equally true and no 
 paradox to say, that if such acts were not done from 
 inclination, i.e.^ were not voluntary or volitionized, 
 they would not be acts of duty at all. 
 
 Under the necessities of his theory, he does not 
 hesitate to affirm that those passages in the Scrip- 
 tures which command us to love our neighbor and 
 even to love our enem}^ do not respect the feelings 
 or volitions of benevolence, but only the duties of 
 beneficence, for the reason that love and forgiveness 
 cannot be the subject of a command, practical and 
 not pathological love alone being a matter of duty. 
 We need use no words to explain how inadequate 
 is this view of the reach and import of the moral 
 law as explained in the Scriptures, which not only 
 insist that love is the fulfilling of the law, but 
 that if love is wanting, though every conceivable 
 act of beneficence should be performed, not a single 
 act of duty is done. The truth which misled the 
 author is the commonplace truth that duty, if it be 
 ethical and genuine, must show itself in acts, else it 
 is hypocritical or hollow, and hence acts, as well as 
 purposes and feelings, are insisted on as the exter- 
 nal and bodily stuff of which duty is made and 
 through which it is manifested. The truth which 
 Kant caricatures is that the will, as distinfjuished
 
 60 kant's ethics. 
 
 from the sensibility, is the only possible subject of 
 the law of duty, and that what the sensibilities are 
 in their impulsive energy and proportionate energy, 
 depends partly on the individual temperament and 
 culture. For this reason, and for this alone, the 
 acts and not the feelings are the measures and prac- 
 tical tests of duty. 
 
 § o2. Kant's second iiroposition concerning duty 
 Kaiifs ^•''' ^''^^ ^^ derives its moral worth, not 
 
 Second Error. fj-Qm the purpose or end which is to be 
 attained b}^ the act, but from the principle of the 
 volition wliich pervades it. If he means that the 
 actual fulfilment or execution of the volition does 
 not decide its moral quality, he asserts an impor- 
 tant truth, but if he means, as his words would 
 imply, that the subjective moral character of the 
 act of duty is not determined by what we object- 
 ively intend or morally prefer, he commits a se- 
 rious speculative and practical error. The contrast 
 which he sets up. between the principle of the will 
 and the expected or chosen end in the act proposed 
 or its result, cannot hold. To call the one formal 
 and a priori and the other material does not avail 
 except to the ear. 
 
 Kant's third proposition respecting duty is thus 
 expressed: "Duty is the necessity of acting from
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MOEALS. 61 
 
 respect to the law." In this definition respect is 
 opposed to inclination, the one being ^^.^^ 
 concerned with the regulation of the en- Mistake. 
 
 Respect for 
 
 ergy of the will, or the activity itself, the Law a 
 and the other with the anticipated 
 effect of an act. That respect on the one hand, and 
 desire or inclination on the other, are properly con- 
 trasted we do not deny, but we deny altogether that 
 respect is not pathological and emotional, albeit that 
 both as sensitive and impulsive it is distinguished 
 from the lower sensibilities. We dissent from 
 Kant's assertion that we cannot have respect for a 
 feeling or an inclination in ourselves and others, 
 although we grant that, to become an object of re- 
 spect, such a feeling must be vivified by the will 
 and the product of self-command; but the response 
 of respect which it exacts is none the less emotional 
 in its nature. 
 
 § 33. It is interesting to notice that at this 
 stage of the development of Kant's 
 
 Conceded to be 
 
 theory, with the first introduction of an " obscure 
 
 Feeliu"'." 
 
 " respect for the law" as an essential ele- 
 ment or condition of duty, he recognizes the objec- 
 tion as possible that this respect for the law must in 
 some sort be an " obscure fed'oKj."' This difficulty 
 he attempts to evade by explaining the nature of the
 
 62 kant's ethics. 
 
 feeling by the object which occasions it, as a concept 
 of the reason, " the law only, and that the law which 
 we impose on ourselves." All which does not tend 
 to take respect out of the category of feeling, but 
 only fixes it more firml}^ within it! Let it be ob- 
 served here that it is with the subjective state of 
 the man that we are concerned, not at all with the 
 object which occasions it. 
 
 Leaving this difficulty unsolved, it being assumed 
 that the law as such commands respect, 
 
 Criterion of 
 
 an Act of our author proceeds to inquire, What 
 kind of a law is that which is clothed 
 with this moral authority? To this question he 
 replies, Only a law which is fitted to be a universal 
 maxim, I.e., " I am never to act otherwise than so 
 that I could will that my maxim should become a 
 universal law." This position he illustrates at length 
 in answer to the question whether it is ever right to 
 make a promise with the intention never to keep it, 
 giving a variety of reasons why any other rule of 
 conduct than the one which in this case he approves 
 would be unfit to be a universal law. These reasons 
 we need not state. It is enough to say of them that 
 they are all considerations of coiiipa/ibiliti/ or incoiit- 
 patiJtHihj irifli liKiiiiiH irell-hciiKj. In this case at 
 least, so far as the reasoning of the author has an}'
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 63 
 
 meaning, the fitness of a course of conduct to be a uni- 
 versal law is argued on grounds of its tendencies, or 
 the consequences, good or ill, to the natural sensibili- 
 ties, if the conduct supposed were occasionally or con- 
 stantly put in practice. The self-asserting and self- 
 asserted majesty of the law, which will bye-and-bye 
 emerge in the autocratic grandeur of the categorical 
 imperative, is here by the author's own showing rep- 
 resented as simply an appeal to that instinctive desire 
 for or sympathy with universal well-being, which is 
 supposed to be dominant in every human breast. In 
 all this it is also assumed that the human reason dis- 
 cerns certain ends which are revealed in this consti- 
 tution of man, individual and social, and which are 
 capable of being recognized by every thinking being, 
 as laws to his own will and to that of his fellow man. 
 It also supposes that with the well-being of the uni- 
 verse and its necessary conditions every man has a dis- 
 interested sympathy, latent or active, and so becomes 
 a lawgiver to himself as he interprets these ends 
 and designs, and recognizes nature and God as impos- 
 ing and confirming them as moral law. This law is 
 eminently reasonable and self-confessed, and there- 
 fore is responded to with emotions of honor and 
 respect, which are none the less sensibilities because
 
 64 kant's ethics. 
 
 attended, when the reflecting judgment comes in.* 
 
 with self-ministered and self-inflicted joys and pains. 
 
 § 34. Thus far we have followed Kant in his 
 
 attempt to effect a transition from the 
 
 Second Sec- 
 tion of Kanfs " common rational knowledge " of mo- 
 rality to the philosophical, within the 
 domain of common intelligence. We proceed next 
 to the second section, in which he treats of the trans- 
 ition from the popular philosophy to the metaphysics 
 of morals, proposing hereafter to interpret and criti- 
 cise him point by point — changing our method to 
 that of a running criticism. 
 
 The first position which Kant takes, and to the 
 Kanf<Fir'<t discussiou of which he devotes several 
 Position, that pages, is that no example of ideal moral 
 
 Every Ideal . 
 
 must Be perfection has ever been actually dis- 
 
 covered in any single individual. He 
 contends that not only has no perfect human being 
 ever been known actually to exist, from whose exam- 
 ple an ideal of moral excellence could be derived 
 and by which it could tested, but it may be ques- 
 tioned whether any (single) example of a single 
 
 *Ho\v he comes to be a lawgiver to himself and incidentally to 
 others, we do not here inquire. It is enough that we know that the 
 fact is unquestioned. We are only concerned here with the po-iition 
 that the respect which is exacted is a sensibility fnuiuled on the knowl- 
 edge of the natural desirableness of that conduct which men call duty 
 in feeling and in act.
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 65 
 
 perfectly morally good action can be found in the 
 history of man. The inference suggested does not 
 hold, even if the supposition be allowed. It is tena- 
 ble only against the theory that the ideal of duty can 
 only be derived from some example of its realization, 
 which is very different from the position, that a moral 
 ideal cannot be constructed or proposed from the actual 
 facts, i.e., the possibilities or constitution of human 
 nature. It does not follow that the ideal of moral 
 goodness is any the less actual as an ideal, or any the 
 less excellent or desirable, because it may have never 
 been realized, provided it be true that its elements 
 are found in man's actual capacities. Its elements 
 as an ideal may have been derived froiy human nat- 
 ure and verified in human experience, even though 
 its realization may have never been observed or es- 
 tablished as a fact. The only truth that we need to 
 enforce is that the ideal of moral goodness is derived 
 from reason and is proposed to and enforced upon 
 the will. This ideal cannot, however, be proposed as 
 an object of choice or action. Men choose objects, 
 not volitions. Though the object of moral choice is 
 related to the act by which it is chosen, the moral 
 act itself is not chosen. Moral excellence does not lie 
 in what is chosen, but in the act or response of choos- 
 ing or the eflfeet of having chosen. But whether act 
 5
 
 66 kant's ethics. 
 
 or effect, in both cases it is subjective, however this 
 actual or anticipated state may be related to its 
 object, or color or affect that object. 
 
 The only question between Kant and his critics 
 . , is, from what source is this moral ideal 
 
 W hence is the 
 
 Moral Ideal derived? This question Kant would 
 
 Derived? 
 
 Kant, and His answer by saying. From the reason only, 
 by an imperative dictum proposed to 
 the will. His critics would say, From a correct in- 
 terpretation of the relations of the voluntary sensi- 
 bilities to one another, as proposed to the will, 
 through the respective objects which excite them. 
 
 Of this tbeor}^ Kant takes a brief notice in pass- 
 ing, to return to it more fully at length, represent- 
 ing it as having been held under the titles of " the 
 special distinction of human nature (including, how- 
 ever, the idea of a rational nature generally) at one 
 time perfection, at another happiness, here moral 
 sense, there fear of God, a little of this, and a little of 
 that, in marvellous mixture, without its occurring 
 to the upholders* of these theories to ask whether the 
 principles of morality are to be sought in the knowl- 
 edge of human nature at all (which we can have 
 
 * It may not be amiss to observe in passing that in none of his eth- 
 ical writings does Kant evince an exact and critical knowledge of the 
 writers whose systems he criticises, as those of Aristotle. Wolf, or 
 Shaftesbury, although he prosecutes an active polemic against each of 
 them in turn.
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 67 
 
 only from experience), oi', if this is not so, if these 
 princii^les are to be found altogether (i priori^ free 
 from everything empirical, in pure rational con- 
 cepts only and nowhere else, not even in the small- 
 est degree," etc. 
 
 Not only does he express his dissatisfaction with 
 these theories, but he shadows forth the outlines of 
 his own as in his view altogether original. He re- 
 peats the injunction that a pure ethics must be con- 
 structed by reason alone, and, " unmixed with any 
 foreign addition of empirical attraction,"' must give 
 us " the pure conception of duty," and that " the 
 conception of the moral law exercises on the human 
 heart by way of reason alone an influence so much 
 more powerful than all other springs which may be 
 derived from experience." This prepares us for 
 what follows. 
 
 Having made so much of reason, Kant very prop- 
 erly begins with a definition of reason and of ra- 
 tional beings in their ethical relations. Rational 
 beings are such as have the power of acting accord- 
 ing to laws as intelligently apprehended. To be 
 able to act thus, man must be endowed j^^^^^ q^.^^. 
 
 with will. It deserves attention that '""^s the Sen- 
 sibility as an 
 Kant's conception of the will includes Element of the 
 
 two elements only, Intelligence and Ac-
 
 68 rant's ethics. 
 
 tion, overlooking any effect on the sensibilities as 
 such, or any rational relations which pertain to the 
 feelings, as a condition of action, or a criterion of 
 character. What action is, i.e., what ethical or re- 
 sponsible action is, he nowhere exactly defines. The 
 term " action " is constantly employed, indeed, but 
 action of what kind? Not bodily action, as it would 
 seem, for in bodily action by itself there is no moral 
 significance and can be no moral responsibility. 
 Not intellectual action only, for here freedom has no 
 place. Is it perhaps emotional action? Certainly it 
 is not any mere passive sensibility. But no other is 
 recognized in the Kantian analysis, the sensibility as 
 such not being conceived as admitting of any volun- 
 tary direction or any rational reasons of higher or 
 lower, and consequently of any ethical relations by 
 being subject to the will.* Certainly the possibility 
 of such a relation is at least ignored. Were this 
 allowed, it would imply some possible relation of 
 reason to the sensibility, and make right and wrong 
 to depend on that blending of the rational and the 
 
 * It should never be forgotten that the will as conceived by Kant 
 was the power to act, i.e., the capacity for impulse or desire. To Icnow, 
 to feel, and to act, — internally as well as with the body — were the three 
 functions of man which he recognized. The power to choose between 
 impulsive sensibilities was not distinctly conceived by him as possible, 
 hence his incapacity to recognize any conflict except a conflict be- 
 tween reason and feeling. Hence his paradoxical statement that the 
 moral law respects the acts only, and not the feelings.
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 69 
 
 emotional, i.e., of the a priori and the empirical, 
 against which Kant constantly protests, as impossi- 
 ble, and under the rejection of which his theory con- 
 stantly labors. 
 
 § 36. After this imperfect analysis of the relation 
 of the reason to the springs or impulses jj. j^^^ Action 
 of action and of the nature of action Defined in the 
 
 Most Genei'al 
 
 itself, we are told, in the most general wayasReason- 
 
 ,,,.,, , . . , . able Action. 
 
 way, that right action is reason put in 
 practice and that action or conduct controlled by 
 reason is practical reason, reason being required not 
 merely to apprehend whatever should be done, but to 
 apprehend it in its principles. In case reason infal- 
 libly and actually determines the conduct, the ac- 
 tions made objectively necessary to the intellect are 
 subjectively necessary to this will. That is, we sup- 
 pose, the convictions of the reason actually control 
 the impulses without conflict or friction, and the 
 reasonable is actually responded to by the active im- 
 pulses, called by Kant the will. But if the will 
 is not thus subjectively determined by these objec- 
 tive conditions without conflict, the determination of 
 such a will is ohligatory. This can occur only when 
 the sensibilities resist the I'eason. In case the sensi- 
 bilities are reluctant, the objective principle becomes 
 a command and the formula is imperative, all impera-
 
 70 kaxt's ethics. 
 
 tives being expressed by the word oiKjld. Every im- 
 perative does indeed say that something w^ould be 
 good, were it done or not done, but it says this to a 
 will which does not actually conforni to the good as 
 thus conceived. The obligatory, moreover, is distin- 
 guished from the pleasant, in that the pleasant 
 influences the will only by means of sensations 
 from merely subjective causes which are valid only 
 for the sensibility of this or that individual, while 
 the obligatory is recognized as a principle of the 
 reason which holds equally for all men. 
 
 § 37. A perfectly good will, Kant proceeds to 
 expound, would invariably be subiect to 
 
 A Perfect Will ^ ' J J 
 
 Excludes all the objective laws of the reason, but 
 could not be conceived as ohliged to act 
 lawfully, because by its subjective constitution it is 
 of itself already determined by the objectively good * 
 without any counteracting impulses. No impera- 
 tives are possible, or have any significance for the 
 desires of a holy will. The conception of obliga- 
 tion is here totally out of place, because such a will 
 
 * It were better to say, and this would reconcile Kant with his dis- 
 senters and critics, that the moral imperative as imperative does not 
 contemplate solel)' the anticipated sentient good, simply as good, but 
 anticipates what the choice would be as morally good. But then, 
 what would be chosen? not the choice, but the object of choice. But 
 is the object chosen morally good, or is it the choice that is morally 
 good ?
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 71 
 
 is already in harmony or unison with the objective 
 law and no conflict or dissent is conceivable. 
 
 § 38. In order to enforce still further his concep- 
 tion of the authority of the moral law, The Cate- 
 Kant introduces and exj^ands the dis- H^potiietjcai 
 tinction between the hypothetical and imperative. 
 the categorical imperative. In the first case, the ac- 
 tion concerned is a good as a means of something 
 else; in the second, it is good in itself. In either case, 
 it is a good which determines the will. It would 
 seem that "the good in itself" and "the good with 
 respect to something else '" are tacitly conceived by 
 the author as holding some sort of a relation to one 
 another, else they would not be conceived as included 
 under the common genus of a good or goods. If 
 this were conceded, must not this generic conception 
 be synonymous with the desirable in the largest or 
 widest sense of the term, and if both objects are desir- 
 able must they not both in some way affect and move 
 the sensibilities? 
 
 The distinction set up between the categorical and 
 the hypothetical imperative is so obvious as scarcely 
 to need comment or explanation. There are im- 
 peratives of skill, which simply require and in a 
 sense command that if a man will accomplish a 
 given purpose, he must gain some capacity by
 
 72 kant's ethics. 
 
 training of the band or of the eye. There is also 
 a common end which may be supposed to be uni- 
 versal with all rational beings, and that end is 
 happiness. For this reason the hypothetical im- 
 perative, whether in its narrow or more extended 
 application, is expressed in the form of an asser- 
 tion, rather than in that of command. Skill in 
 the choice and use of means to this common end, 
 i.e., to man's highest well being, Kant contends, is 
 prudence in a broader or a narrower sense. Dis- 
 tinguished from both of these, sharply and strongly, 
 is the categorical imperative, which proposes certain 
 actions (actions in the broadest sense of the term, as 
 activities of feeling or will and even of disposition 
 and character, and impulses and dispositions involv- 
 ing habits) without any condition in its implied or 
 express reference to any end. This imperative, as 
 Kant insists, concerns not any matter or any in- 
 tended or implied result of an action, but only the 
 form and principle of the action, i.e., the intention 
 or disposition itself, be its tendency or operation 
 what it may. This imperative is the sole imperative 
 which morality recognizes. Hence, in his view, we 
 have three kinds of obligation, involving rules of 
 skill, counsels of prudence, and laws of morality, 
 the first two being conditional, and the last manda-
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. ?3 
 
 tory. The first two labor under the disadvantage 
 that we cannot always satisfactorily determine the 
 conditions of human happiness for ourselves or for 
 others. To a greater or less extent, our conclusions 
 in regard to them are conjectural and at the best 
 are invested with a higher or lower degree of proba- 
 bilit3^ But the mandates of duty are unconditional 
 and imperative. The first say, Do this or that if you 
 would be happy; the last, Do this because the act is 
 reasonable, i.e., is morally right, or, In the name of 
 reason do it, or simply, Do it. 
 
 § 39. This contrast between the two classes of 
 imperatives is expanded by Kant at Kaut's 
 great length in illustrations which we „ ,. , 
 
 ° » Conception of 
 
 need not repeat. His argument is open Happiness, 
 to a single but important critical observation, viz.: 
 That the author in his conceptions of possible and 
 actual happiness confines himself altogether to the 
 external consequences of actions and makes not the 
 least recognition of that subjective good or hap- 
 piness which attends the exercise of a voluntary 
 impulse or feeling. Had he done JT5stice to this dis- 
 tinction he would have found it easy ;.to distinguish 
 between prudence and morality in terms of volition- 
 ized sensibility — pn;dence respecting the external 
 consequences of a volition, and morality the internal
 
 74 K A NT's ETHICS. 
 
 affections. The possibility of any other terms of 
 contrast seems not to have occurred to the author 
 at this stage of his inquiries. He subsequently 
 recognizes this possibility, but in the treatise before 
 us, he finds no alternative possible except between 
 the external reward of the virtuous will, which he 
 limits to the matter of conduct, and the categorical 
 command of the reason, which he terms its form, 
 while the form contemplates rational or logical rela- 
 tions only. 
 
 As Kant proceeds with his argument in support 
 of this contrast, he acknowledges that the difficul- 
 ties thicken about him. He concedes that we can- 
 not appeal to experience as our arbiter, because our 
 convictions are not grounded in experience. But on 
 the other hand, our conviction of the truth of this 
 distinction is confirmed by human experience and is 
 necessary in order that experience may be possible. 
 Unless the categorical imperative were actually en- 
 forced, there could be none of that morality which 
 we find to be both real and influential and neces- 
 sary. But he reasons from the analogies of the 
 speculative reason, that if a priori speculative prin- 
 ciples must be assumed as the ground and explana- 
 tion of speculative science, it is reasonable to sup- 
 pose that ethics should rest in like manner on
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 75 
 
 ultimate a priori principles of its own. He urges 
 that if we find it difficult to conceive the possibility 
 of the one class of axioms, it ought to be no matter 
 of wonder that the fundamental axioms of ethics 
 should occasion equal and similar embarrassment, 
 forgetting that the difticulties of speculative philos- 
 ophy had already driven him, tentatively, at least, 
 into the domain of the practical reason as a city of 
 refuge, and that the axioms of morals had been 
 accepted as truth and invested with a sacred and 
 final authority in both spheres. 
 
 We have already adverted to the views of the 
 relations between ethical and speculative science, 
 which are conspicuously characteristic of Kant, and 
 to the changes in these views which can be traced in 
 his successive treatises. It is a matter of constant 
 surprise that the unsatisfactory workings of his 
 doctrine of tlie d priori ideas and principles of the 
 speculative reason did not awaken the suspicion that 
 the difficulties attendant upon the new set of simi- 
 lar principles which he provided for ethics might 
 indicate some common weakness latent in both. It 
 could give little satisfaction to Kant himself to con- 
 fess that " the difficulty of discerning the possi- 
 bility of the categorical imperative is a very pro- 
 found one," and ." it is an a priori synthetical
 
 76 KANT S ETHICS. 
 
 practical proposition, and as there is so much diffi- 
 culty in discerning the possibility of speculative 
 propositions of this kind, it may be readily supposed 
 that the difficulty will be no less with the practical." 
 § 40. But he proceeds to say, if we cannot ex- 
 Kant Adopts plain the possibility of the categorical 
 
 the Criterion . . i o • ; • 
 
 ofConse- imperative, we can denne its import, 
 
 quencesasa ^^^ j^j^-g ^^^ ^^^^ ^^ ^^ ^^ follows: " Act 
 Practical 
 
 Rule. only on that maxim whereby thou canst, 
 
 at the same time, will that it should become a uni- 
 versal law," or, inasmuch as the laws by which effects 
 are produced characterize nature, he amends it thus: 
 " Act as if the maxims of thy action were to be- 
 come by thy will a law of nature." Here we notice 
 as before, that both in form and by every one of 
 the examples employed in illustration, the tests of 
 right conduct and of the law of duty are found by 
 Kant in the effects of conduct or in the tendencies of 
 conduct to affect human well-being, and that the 
 euphemistic phrases of the fitness of a rule to be- 
 come a universal law can signify nothing less than 
 the tendencies of conduct with respect to individual 
 and social welfare. Thus interpreted, the form of 
 the moral law would respect the intentions or the 
 voluntary purposes or the sensibilities as animated 
 and controlled by the will, or as thus brought into
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 77 
 
 mutual relations — these relations being always the 
 same in matters which come under the categorical 
 imperative, i.e.. which affect the disposition and 
 the character, while the matter of human action, 
 inasmuch as it pertains to the external and varia- 
 ble, the outward and prudential, is capable of found- 
 ing onl}^ probable and proximate and to some extent 
 variable rules of conduct. 
 
 After laying down the principle cited above, Kant 
 proceeds to illustrate it by four examples. The first 
 example is that of a man who is prompted by de- 
 spair to commit suicide : the second, of one who 
 under extreme necessity borrows money, falsely 
 promising to repay it ; the thii'd, of one who 
 wastes in self-indulgent sloth, superior capacities for 
 usefulness to his fellow-men ; the fourth, of a man 
 who indulges selfish indifference to the miseries of 
 mankind. The conduct of each of these persons is 
 universally condemned as morally wrong, and why? 
 Because it is not fitted to be a universal law; but 
 why? Because of its more or less certain effects or 
 tendencies, were it to be accepted and acted on by all 
 men. That Kant should be so utterly unconscious 
 of the logic of his own arguments is sufficiently sur- 
 prising. It is still more strange that he should be 
 totally unaware that in every one of the examples
 
 78 kant's ethics. 
 
 which he cites, he makes use of " tendency to promote 
 the general welfare " under the fair title of " fitness 
 to be a universal law of nature." Similarly, in en- 
 forcing the duty of cultivating one's gifts, he urges 
 that "as a rational being he necessarily wills that his 
 faculties be developed, since they serve him for all 
 sorts of possible purposes and have been given him 
 for this end." The most superficial reader does not 
 need to be told that here is an argument from the 
 adaptations of nature with respect to the end for 
 which man's endowments are given, which, as an ul- 
 timate ground of moi-al obligation, had already been 
 formally repudiated by Kant as beyond man's ca- 
 pacity to decide or even to surmise. 
 
 Still more grossly does he offend against his pro- 
 fessed principles and the entire spirit of his moral 
 teachings, when in the fourth case supposed, he ar- 
 gues that a man cannot justify himself in indiffer- 
 ence to the sorrows and wants of his fellow-men, for 
 the reason that " a will that resolved this would con- 
 tradict itself, inasmuch as many cases might occur 
 in which one would have need of the love and sym- 
 pathy of others and in which by such a law of nat- 
 ure, springing from his own will, he would deprive 
 himself of all hope of the aid he deserves." How 
 strangely do these words sound from Kant ! What
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 79 
 
 a plump descent into selfish utilitarianism is made 
 by the usually high-toned Kant ! One would hard- 
 ly have expected this of him. How singular that so 
 acute a critic as Kant should first explain the ten- 
 dency of sympathy to beget sympathy as a simple 
 consistency of reason with itself, involving no rela- 
 tions of feeling ! How unconsciously also does he 
 descend from this thin air of his transcendental 
 axioms into earthly considerations of self-regarding 
 l)rudence, without being aware of the downward 
 plunge, and least of all that he has substituted the 
 impulse from self-interest oi* man's instinctive desire 
 of happiness, for a harmony of reason with itself, 
 which, if it means anything, can only be the logical 
 law of identity ! 
 
 ^ 41. Thus far our philosopher pei'suades him- 
 self that he has been concerned with the Relation of the 
 categorical intiierative in its ideal nat- "'^" ^ '^^ !° 
 
 ^ ^ the Actual in 
 
 uve, without deciding whether it is Man. 
 
 ever actualized in man. And how does he decide this 
 question? Not, as it would seem, by any inquiry 
 of fact, but by some process or assumption o priori. 
 lest the '■ critical method "' should not be main- 
 tained. Kant does not hesitate to assert that what 
 man is. whether he is, or is not, a rational or moral 
 being, has nothing to do with deciding this question.
 
 80 kant's ethics. 
 
 He contends most persistently that we may not as- 
 sume that the essential constituents of manhood 
 throw any light upon the essential elements of 
 moral responsibility or the nature and grounds of 
 moral obligation or the moral law. He urges that 
 since moral laws ought to hold good for every ra- 
 tional creature, they must all be derived from the 
 general concept of a rational being. " and in doing 
 so. we must not make its principles." i.e., the princi- 
 ples of the moral law, to be " dependent on the par- 
 ticular nature of human reason." What the author 
 understood by this distinction between " the general 
 concept of a rational being"' and "the particular 
 nature of human reason "' is not so clear as it is that 
 he intended to disparage and reject anj'' analysis of 
 the nature of man as the foundation of. or prelim- 
 inary to, the determination of moral conceptions in 
 general. We may presume that what he intends by 
 the phrase, " the particular nature of human rea- 
 son," is that modification of the rational powers 
 which is occasioned by the emotions and their rela- 
 tions to the higher powers. What he would insist 
 on is that moral law is the same for all moral be- 
 ings, and that all moral beings have a common moral 
 nature {i.e., as he interprets this, a common rational 
 nature), to the exclusion of whatever is peculiar to
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 81 
 
 the individual oi* the race, in the way of sensibilities 
 or the relations which they involve. This may be 
 admitted; but when he would leap to the conclusion 
 that the moral relations are rational only, not mere- 
 l}^ in their form but in their matter, so that neither 
 emotion nor will is required to constitute a moral 
 being, he takes a leap in which few will follow him, 
 and in which, as it would seem, on second thought 
 he would scarcely follow himself. It would seem 
 that no one would contend more earnestly than he 
 that the moral law, as rational, must presuppose a 
 will in every being over whom it has authority; and 
 that without a will, whether in man or any other 
 being, reason would neither discover nor enforce 
 moral relations of any kind. But if a moral being 
 must be endowed with a will, in order that it may be 
 moral, why may it not be equally necessary that he 
 should be endowed with sensibility also, and why may 
 not the several sensibilities stand in certain natural, 
 even rational, relations to one another, such as might 
 be the conditions of the moral? Why. not only may 
 ' it not be true, but why must it not be true, that 
 a sensitive nature is the essential condition and me- 
 dium for voluntary, i.e., for moral, action and moral 
 responsibility? Kant reasons well when he reasons 
 
 that certain sensibilities, such as might be supposed 
 G
 
 82 rant's ethics. 
 
 peculiar to human beings, are in no sense essential 
 to moral responsibility, e.g., some of the human ap- 
 petites or tastes, such as are dependent on the body 
 or the special physiological constitution of the hu- 
 man race. But Kant reasons incorrectly when he 
 excludes, as accidents of humanity and as non-es- 
 sential to the discernment and enforcement of the 
 moral law, every species of sensibility whatever as 
 the possible subject of rational discrimination and 
 moral relationship. 
 
 § 42. Doubtless in this critical polemic Kant 
 had in mind the definition given by 
 
 A Life » '' 
 
 According to the ancieiits of moral perfection as a 
 Nature 
 
 life according to nature. He frequently 
 criticises this doctrine and protests against it, as 
 involving a limited or a varying standard and 
 as inconsistent with his doctrine of the uncondi- 
 tioned and positive character of the practical reason. 
 It would seem that he might have noticed the truth 
 to which we have adverted, viz. : that in respect of 
 monal relations, reason supposes sensibility and its 
 relations, as truly as it does the will, and that with- 
 out sensibility there can be no aim or purpose for 
 reason in the practical sense of lawgiving end. 
 Perhaps also — in all probability it was true in fact 
 — what Kant had in mind in his protest against the
 
 THE METAPItTSICS OE MORALS. 83 
 
 psychological study of human nature, was to express 
 his dissent from the doctrines of the moral sense, as a 
 mere accident of human nature, or an arbitrary ele- 
 ment in its constitution, such as would make morality 
 to be a matter of feeling or taste and in opposition 
 to which he would set up the universal reason as 
 the lawgiver of ethical truth and ethical authority; 
 overlooking the fact that in doing this he must 
 reduce reason to the mere relationships of formal 
 logic, without any practical significance of value or 
 worth.* 
 
 § 43. And yet he cannot confine himself to 
 these relationships. Sooner than he is Analyzes Hu- 
 
 ,, . , , J. 1 • man Nature 
 
 aware, or rather without being aware ^,gj.^j^g pj^ j^ 
 of what he does, he finds himself fol- ^^'^f^. 
 lowing the method of a psychological analysis of the 
 nature and processes of reason which he had seemed 
 to set aside, and proposing to himself the ques- 
 tion, Why must all rational beings judge of their 
 actions by maxims imposed on themselves as univer- 
 sal laws ? This question he answers thus: All 
 
 * The fact is worth noticing, that while Butler, on the one kand, 
 insists as positivelj' as does* Kant that the distinctive feature of the 
 moral faculty in man is its authority, he affirms as positively, on the 
 other hand, that the moral relations are discovered by a reflective 
 study of the nature of man. We may say that metaphysically Butler 
 agrees with Kant, while psychologically he dissents from him most 
 widely. {Of. § 94.)
 
 84 . Kant's ethics. 
 
 rational beings mu.st not only approve as rational 
 the means which are adapted to ends, but also 
 the ends which these means subserve. In other 
 words, the subjective grounds of rational actions are 
 desires; their objective grounds are motives. The 
 hypothetical imperative respects the means, the cat- 
 egorical, the ends of our actions. " All objects of 
 the inclinations have only conditional worth," inas- 
 much as we might suppose these inclinations not to 
 exist, in which case their objects would have no 
 Discovers worth. Rational beings are indicated 
 and Person-"'^ ^^ nature as being ends in themselves, 
 aiity. and are consequently called persons 
 
 who can never be regarded as means only, but 
 possess absolute and independent worth. An end 
 in itself becomes invested with the authority of 
 a categorical imperative, the foundation of which 
 is the principle: " A rational nature exists as an end 
 in itself," and from this the imperative follows: 
 " So act as to treat humanity, whether in thine own 
 person or in that of every other, in every case as an 
 end, withal never as a means only," — the postulate, 
 as it would seem, being assumed that every rational 
 being regards his existence as I do my own, and 
 that, in the arrangements of nature and of rea-
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 85 
 
 son, the realization of the ends of each is compatible 
 with the same by othei's. 
 
 The attentive and critical reader will not fail to 
 have noticed that in these last assumptions Kant 
 has abandoned forever the ground which he had 
 taken in respect to the impossibility of deriving the 
 categorical imperative from a critical examination of 
 the constitution of man and the purposes of nature 
 with respect to man as individual and social. In every 
 one of these assumptions, on the other hand, he affirms 
 the possibility that the ends provided in the consti- 
 tution of every rational being should be discerned, 
 as also the compatibility of the well-being or ra- 
 tional welfare of the individual with that of the 
 community. In other words, Kant has returned 
 to the doctrine of the ancients, that the moral 
 law is summed up in the rule to act according to 
 nature, and that man's nature can be discerned 
 and interpreted, if, indeed, its supreme end and 
 adaptations can be understood. 
 
 These postulates being assumed, we need not ex- 
 plain how they are applied in detail in enforcing 
 special classes of duties. The examples selected by 
 Kant for illustration are the same as those previ- 
 ously used, viz.: (1) The duty of rejecting suicide; 
 (2) Of keeping one's promises; (3) Of living an
 
 S6 K A NT's ETHICS. 
 
 elevated personal life; (4) Of living a life devoted 
 to the welfare of others. We need use no argu- 
 ment to show how the assumptions given above 
 explain and enforce the several duties as they arise, 
 and how they cannot be enforced without these, and 
 how they are enforced by Kant himself after this 
 very theory. 
 
 We agree altogether with Kant, that our faith in 
 each of the several postulates which have been 
 stated in respect to the constituents and the har- 
 mony of a universe of rational and voluntary per- 
 sons, is an original and necessary belief. But we 
 disagree altogether with him v/hen he seems now 
 and then to argue that our faith in these categories 
 rests upon the authority of the practical reason 
 as it commands this faith as a duty, except in the 
 vague and popular acceptation, that every man 
 acknowledges the intellectual supremacy of his ra- 
 tional convictions. The speculative and the practi- 
 cal reason cannot both be the ultimate foundations 
 of our philosophical and ethical convictions, respect- 
 ively, notwithstanding that Kant seems to inter- 
 change his allegiance to each, without being con- 
 scious of the incompatibilit}^ of making each in 
 its turn the cornerstone of his philosphical creed. 
 
 In the present case he argues from the position,
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORA^ g9 
 
 that the principle that every human, and, ii--.nd 
 every rational, being is an end in and for itself, is not 
 borrowed from experience, but is an original and 
 rational axiom. We agree with him in this, and also 
 in the doctrine that this principle is essential alike 
 to rational philosophy and sound ethics. We disa- 
 gree with him in the occasional assertion, and in the 
 general tendency of his argument, that this belief 
 has its foundation, not in the speculative, but in the 
 practical reason. From this rational postulate which 
 we hold in common, it follows, that the ethical will 
 or command of duty, which every man accepts and 
 imposes on himself, is a universally legislative law, 
 every moral agent being at once the giver and sub- 
 ject of the law as he imposes and accepts it for him- 
 self and also imposes it on and exacts it from every 
 other rational being. 
 
 We may not conclude, as we have already inti- 
 mated, that Kant, in using this Ian- ^^^ ^^^^ ^^^ 
 guage and availing himself of these re- Formally 
 
 " " ° _ Abandon the 
 
 lations, has formally abandoned his dis- categorical 
 tinctive position, that the law of duty 
 is a simple and categorical command, which never 
 appeals to the speculative reason, and takes no ac- 
 count of the feelings or the relations which they 
 involve, but is derived from the authority of the
 
 88 K A NT's ETHICS. 
 
 practical reason alone. On the contrary, he returns 
 to it anew, and enforces it by additional arguments 
 under a new appellation of the aiUonomij of the will, 
 or the direct or sovereign authority of duty as a 
 rational law, as contrasted with its heteronomy, or 
 subjection to some other impulse besides itself. And 
 yet here he insists as before tlmt duty does not rest 
 on the feelings or inclinations, but on the relations 
 of rational beings to the end of their being and 
 actions. 
 
 § 44. In arguing from rational ends to person- 
 And yet He ality, our author treads upon ground 
 siilfts'^HiJ which is new to him. though not new 
 Ground. ^q Aristotle or other philosophers wlio 
 
 had recognized the ends of human nature as a 
 fruitful and fundamental conception in ethical phil- 
 osophy. But while he acknowledges the reality of 
 ^finality, he does not, however, discuss its nature or 
 its authority; he simply assumes its trustworthiness 
 and its fruitfulness, without even recognizing the fact 
 tliat in his speculative system it had previously met 
 with a most inhospitable reception at his hands; his 
 aim being apparently to reconcile it with the views 
 which he had already expounded. He first reasserts 
 that the will is conceived as a faculty of determining 
 itself to action in accordance with the conception of
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 89 
 
 certain laws. And such a faculty can only be found 
 in rational beings. Then, for the first time in the 
 treatise he says, " Now what serves the will as the 
 objective ground of its self-determination is the end, 
 and if this is assigned by reason alone it must hold 
 for all rational beings." Here again we have either 
 the studied or the unconscious assertion that if ends 
 are rational and discerned by the reason they exclude 
 all elements of feeling, and, it would seem, all appeals 
 to the will. As if to secure this main position by 
 every possible consideration, he makes a distinction 
 between a spring or subjective ground of desire and a 
 motive as an objective ground of volition, in order to 
 enforce the distinction between subjective and ob- 
 jective ends, and again between practical precepts 
 or motives as being formal, when abstracted from 
 all subjective ends, and material when they assume 
 and addi-ess such ends. He insists that all ends 
 which are derived from the effects of actions are 
 relative and occasion the hypothetical imperative, 
 while all motives that have absolute worth suppose 
 no springs of action or desire, but are simply ra- 
 tional and formal, and enforced by the categorical 
 imperative. That there are such motives, he argues 
 from the distinction between things which have '' a 
 relative value as means," and rational beings which
 
 ()0 KANT^S ETHICS. 
 
 are "called persons" "because their very nature 
 points them out as ends in themselves " having abso- 
 T?.f oif l^^te worth. We assent to this distinc- 
 
 does not fjon, and recQcrnize its supreme import- 
 
 Exclude Eeia- ^ '■ 
 
 tionstothe ance in ethics, but we raise these ques- 
 tions: Whether a person who is an end 
 to himself, for that reason finds no interest in the 
 several ends, even the highest, which inspire his ac- 
 tions; — whether the fact that he assumes these ends 
 to be final and supreme in the kingdom of ends, and 
 is interested in them as such, is inconsistent with the 
 fact, or rather explains the fact, that they are em- 
 phatically and supremely rational; — whether, on the 
 contrary, the fact that they are rational does not 
 arise from the fact that they are distinctively and 
 emphatically moving of or motiving to the respon- 
 sive sensibility ; whether, in short, a rational na- 
 ture, in the sense of an insensitive nature, can be 
 an end to itself; and finally, whether the persistent 
 attempts of Kant to interpret the rational as exclud- 
 ing the emotional are not invariably mere flights of 
 language in the excitement of which the analyst 
 leaves his logic behind. 
 
 We argue the question still further, whether the 
 phrase. " a kingdom of ends," which is rightly con- 
 ceived as a community of rational beings acting in
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MOKALS. 91 
 
 hai'mony with and subordination to one another, 
 according to claims of duty and on grounds of 
 duty — whether such a kingdom could be assumed 
 unless the value and the worth of its constituent 
 elements were capable of being translated into terms 
 of feeling,/.^., unless they interested the human sen- 
 sibilities. 
 
 The further questions also suggest themselves, 
 What is the relation of the will as autonomous, or 
 self-law-giving, to the practical reason and its cat- 
 egorical imperative y Are the will and practical rea- 
 son regarded by Kant as faculties of the soul, and if 
 so, what are the appropriate functions of each? 
 What are the relations of the motives which each is 
 said to present as objective, when contrasted with 
 the springs of action which are confessedly subjec- 
 tive? Can there be a moving object, whether sensi- 
 tive or rational, which does not also arouse or inter- 
 est the feelings, and if so, is not the contrast between 
 the higher and lower motives to be found solely in 
 the natural quality of the emotions and desires which 
 they excite, as also in the results which they accom- 
 plish, and consequently in their relative value, in- 
 volving their natural and moral worth? 
 
 § 45. What are Kant's views of the will in 
 these applications it is not easy to determine. We
 
 93 kant's ethics. 
 
 ask, again and again, Does he mean by 
 
 Kant's Views 
 
 of the Will the will an endowment or faculty of 
 
 Indelinite. •■ t i. -^i .1 
 
 human nature coordinate with the rea- 
 son or the intellect, and possibly — why not? — with 
 the sensibility, or does he absorb the reason into the 
 will by making the person to be the reasonable will, 
 and leave the sensibility unconsidered at all, regard- 
 ing it as a pariah in the spiritual organism of forces 
 and ends? The latter seems to be the view which 
 he would take. That he usually connects and almost 
 blends the reason with the will is evident from the 
 terminology and logic of his argument. As we have 
 already noticed, the will, whose autonomy and hete- 
 ronoray he discusses, is another name for the moral 
 person as self-regulating in the one instance, i.e., as 
 finding the moral law in his own internal constitu- 
 tion, whatever that may be; or, in the other, as deriv- 
 ing both law and impulse from any source motives 
 which may address some inferior sensibility. The 
 use of this peculiar phraseology adds nothing to his 
 argument, and it need detain us no longer than to 
 direct the attention to the singular indefiniteness of 
 meaning which Kant attaches to the term " will," and 
 by which he mystifies his reader without adding either 
 to the clearness or the force of his own theoiy. 
 
 It is not exactly true or just to say that Kant
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MOKALS. 03 
 
 finds no reason foi' using the phrase, "the hete- 
 ronomy of the will," inasmuch as under this gen- 
 eral title he subjects to a brief review the several 
 theories of morals in which he finds this doctrine 
 to be exemplified. All these theories in his view 
 are either empirical or rational, the first being 
 founded on simple feeling, either physical or 
 moral, or the principle of happiness; and the last on 
 the principle of perfection, either as a rational 
 conception of a possible ideal, or as exemplified 
 in or enforced by the will of God. Under the 
 first is classed the theory of ultimate happiness 
 and the theory of the moral sense; under the sec- 
 ond, the theories of perfection as a rational con- 
 ception and as divinely commanded. Of the ulti- 
 mate grounds of obligation which he thinks are 
 found in each of these pairs of theories, the author 
 rejects the doctrine of ultimate happiness as being 
 selfish and arbitrary, for the reasons already given. 
 The theory of a moral sense he rejects as depend- 
 ent on an arbitrary constitution, though he lands 
 it as unselfish, while the theory of the divine com- 
 mand he condemns as being arbitrary and change- 
 able. 
 
 Here the author ends his argument, having proved 
 to his own satisfaction that the universally receivil
 
 94 kant's ethics. 
 
 doctrines of practical morality imply the categorical 
 imperative and the autonomy of the trill. These two 
 metaphysical foundations of morals he accepts as 
 established by this analysis. 
 
 § 46. We have already in passing noticed the ob- 
 jections which might be urged to the use 
 E^o Over- o^ these and kindred phrases, in place of 
 looked. ^jjg personal Ego, which in our view 
 
 can alone be accepted as the moral lawgiver over 
 the individual will, or can enforce the moral law of 
 the consenting universe. The scepticism and denials 
 of Kant's speculative theory in respect to iioumena, 
 both material and psychical, had unfortunately cut 
 him off from the possibility of recognizing the per- 
 sonal Ego as anything more than a logical fiction, 
 and the attempt to find a substitute for it in the 
 categorical imperative of the practical reason can 
 only be regarded as a logical makeshift such as might 
 give plausibilit}^ to the platitudes of a sentimental 
 morality or the Protean forms of some imaginative 
 metaphysical hy|)olhesis. 
 
 The unsatisfactory character of the new elements 
 in Kant's system, which we have noticed, is made 
 especially manifest in his attempts to solve the four 
 practical questions which he had previously pro- 
 posed. Kant's second attempt to answer these
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 95 
 
 questions in the terms of his enlarged theory de- 
 cisively proves that what he calls rationality and the 
 doctrine of ends involve sensibility, and that the 
 highest ends always imply the demands of tlie 
 noblest feelings — in short, that worth and value are 
 terms which can have no import, unless the emo- 
 tions are appealed to. 
 
 In the tliifd or last section, Kant attempts to 
 effect a transition from the Metaphys- Transition 
 
 ics of Morals to the Critique of Practical fi^o'" the Meta- 
 physics of 
 Reason. That is, he attempts to show Morals to the 
 
 , , . , • , 1 J 1 • 1 , Critique of 
 
 how the conceptions which he thinks he Practical 
 has discovered to be essential to moral ^''^^°"- 
 science as such, may be justified by a critical exami- 
 nation of the Practical Reason. By the practical rea- 
 son he must understand the human intelligence as 
 concerned with ethical conceptions, or the reason so 
 far as it deals with human action. It will be re- 
 membered that Kant has hitherto persistently 
 refused to find in the constitution of human nature 
 the ultimate explanation for ethical phenomena or 
 ethical ideas, for the reason that this process would 
 seem to found scientific truth, which in its nature is 
 permanent and universal, upon what might be con- 
 sidered as the arbitrary and mutable constitution of 
 man. As contrasted with this source of knowledge
 
 96 K A NT's ETHICS. 
 
 and its results, Kant proposes the critical method, 
 which should test the pure rational faculty by means 
 of its products in human knowledge, and infer the 
 nature and authority of human reason from these 
 products. Kant's problem would be as follows: 
 Given a certain kind of knowledge as trustworthy 
 and universally accepted, to examine its elements or 
 products and find in them a method for interpreting 
 these truths and the warrant for accepting them. 
 Now, we find in science of every kind, and, indeed, 
 in all human experience, certain postulates and as- 
 sumptions which command intellectual confidence 
 and give law to human action. In these conceptions 
 and principles we find the vouchers for our inter- 
 pi'etation of the merit and authority of hximan 
 reason, both speculative and practical; the specula- 
 tive i-eason giving us the norms and principles of 
 speculative science, and the practical the faiths 
 which command and control our conduct. If now 
 our critical analysis of the metaphysical conceptions 
 of ethics is correct, we shall learn what are the 
 axioms and what is the nature of the practical 
 reason. There are not two Reasons in man, he 
 graciously informs us, however. Though we speak 
 of the Speculative and the Practical, the two are one 
 and the same, and the principles of the one must be
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 97 
 
 assumed to be consistent, if they are not identical, 
 with those of the other. Hence our question is 
 legitimate, " How can we effect a transition from 
 the metaphysical conceptions of morals as we find 
 them in human experience, to a critical and scien- 
 tific knowledge of the intellect ? " It should not be 
 forgotten here that Kant had already subjected the 
 scientific reason to a critical examination in his 
 first famous Critique, and had also written his con- 
 fident, if not defiant. Prolegomena to All Future Met- 
 aphysics. It ought not to surprise us that he should 
 imagine that these inquiries had already determined 
 the reach and trustworthiness of the same reason 
 when applied to ethical distinctions, and that he 
 should use their results to solve the difficulties and 
 answer the inquiries which he might encounter in 
 his analysis of ethical or practical phenomena. 
 We shall find that his explanations are not wanting 
 in ingenuity, even if they fail to produce conviction. 
 § 47. Kant begins with the concept of the Will 
 and its freedom as the ground of its Kant Returns 
 autonomy. He finds that the will is a ."^j^^*j J, 
 causality peculiar to rational beings in Freedom, 
 being free from, or independent of, an}^ agency 
 foreign to itself. This definition of freedom is nega- 
 tive, however, and yet it involves the consequence
 
 98 kant's ethics. 
 
 til at the will is a law to itself, finding "the reasons 
 for its action in its own nature. An absolutely 
 good will, moreover, is that whose maxim or act- 
 ually accepted rule or principle of action may 
 always be regarded as a universal law for all ra- 
 tional beings, every one of whom is also assumed to 
 be free. 
 
 But every such being, so far as- he is rational, 
 must also take an interest in duty, in order to re- 
 spond to its claims. As a sensitive being, he should 
 also have an intei'est in the actions which duty com- 
 mands, but the two interests are of a different sort. 
 The one of these interests, however, does not exclude 
 the other, the obligatory * not being incompatible 
 with the desirable. 
 
 The next point which is made by Kant is, that 
 while we are not directly conscious of freedom as a 
 psychological fact, and cannot in tJiis way prove it to 
 be an endowment of ourselves or others, or of human 
 nature, there are reasons why we must yet assume 
 it to be a universal endowment of ourselves and our 
 
 * Here the critical inquirer would doubtless iuterpoee with the 
 question, whether the response of the will to the imperative of the 
 reason, or to the original motive which is the ground of the moral 
 command, may not and must not be a response of feeling. This last, 
 we have already seen, Kant positively and pertinaciously denies, 
 saying, If reason recognizes or enforces any motion of sensibility, it 
 can no longer be reason, and if it appeals to desire, it will no longer 
 be an imperative.
 
 THE METAfHYSICS OF MOKALS. 99 
 
 fellows. It is not interested feeling alone which 
 urges me to action, but there is an obligation to 
 take an interest, an ought which every rational 
 being must acknowledge. This holds for every 
 rational being so far as reason influences or controls 
 his acts. For all those beings wlio, like men, are 
 also endowed with sensibility, and in whom there is 
 not a ready res^jonse to reason, hut a reluctant sensi- 
 hiJitij, this objective rational necessity becomes an 
 ought, implying a can, while the subjective necessity 
 {e.g.. of the sensibility) differs from the objective. 
 These Kant bids us take as ultimate facts, though 
 we cannot explain them. 
 
 It is true that Kant here concedes that we can 
 and do take an interest in our own personal attain- 
 ments, i.e.. " We can be interested in being worthy of 
 happiness without the motive of participating in 
 the happiness." And yet, this experience, and the 
 prospect of it, is only an attestation of that human 
 weakness under which we are not, and cannot 
 be, independent of all consideration of happiness, 
 Kant is also aware that here is a circle from which 
 it is not easy to escape. It is the old difficulty of 
 conceiving that the action which is worthy of hap- 
 piness should not of itself be regarded as desirable, 
 and thus become an object of desire at the same time
 
 100 kakt's ethics. 
 
 that it is clothed with oblij^'ation. So, also, he 
 admits that in the order of" ends and adaptation 
 we may conceive ourselves subject to moral law, 
 because we are convinced that we are free. 
 
 § 48. Prom this dilemma we may perhaps deliver 
 The Man ourselves by asking whether it does not 
 
 * °"'"''"" arise from our looking at the same sub- 
 
 aiid Man * 
 
 Phenomenal, ject from dift'erent points of view — i.e., as 
 we consider ourselves as phenomenal so far as ob- 
 jects affect us, i.e., move our sensibilities, but as 
 tln'jifjs in themselves, so far as we respond to the 
 moral law — and whether the same object-matter 
 may not at one time address the feelings and at 
 another the reason. He avers that " We can 
 never know objects speculatively as they are in 
 themselves, but only as they affect us"; while 
 yet "Man must necessarily suppose something 
 else as their basis, namely, his Ego. whatever its 
 characteristics in itself may be. * * * In respect 
 to perceptions and the receptivity of sensations, 
 he may reckon himself as belonging to the world 
 of sense; but in respect to his pure activity, and 
 that which reaches consciousness immediately and 
 not through the affections of the senses, he must 
 reckon himself as belonging to the intellectual 
 world, of which, however, he has no further knowl-
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 101 
 
 edge" than that it is a fact. "Now man finds in 
 himself a faculty by which he distinguishes himself 
 from everything else, even from himself as affected 
 by objects, and that is reason." It follows that a 
 rational being regards himself and all his actions 
 from two points of view: "First, so far as he belongs 
 to the world of sense and finds himself subject to 
 the laws of nature (this being heteronoiiij/) ; secondly, 
 as belonging to the intelligible world, under laws 
 which, being independent of nature, have their 
 foundations, not in experience, but in the autonomy 
 of the reason only." So far as we conceive ourselves 
 free, we transfer ourselves into the world of under- 
 standing, and recognize the autonomy of the will; 
 whereas, so far as we consider ourselves as under 
 obligation, we regard ourselves as belonging to the 
 world of sense, but also to the world of understand- 
 ing, the sensibility resisting and the reason command- 
 ing. Now, it is evident if there were two worlds, of 
 sense and understanding respectively, they could 
 have no common relations and no bond of connection 
 whatever. "Since, however, the world of under- 
 standing contains the foundation of the world of 
 sense, and consequently of its laws also, and accord- 
 ingly gives laws to the will," the reason, here called 
 the understanding, assumes the right to command
 
 103 Kant's ethics. 
 
 the sense-impulses by tlie catecrorical imperative. 
 Hei'e we encounter the reason, viz. : the practical 
 I'eason, with its synthetic imperative a priori. It 
 should be remembered, however, that obligation pre- 
 supposes the reluctant impulses of sense, and so in 
 every case there must be conflict between the two, 
 since obligation can only be felt when the autonomous 
 will encounters the resisting sensibility. It is not to 
 be forgotten, however, that the reason not only asserts 
 its natural authority as reason over sense, but that, 
 as this authority is responded to as a fitness to be a 
 universal law, it awakens the feeling of respect, it 
 being always remembered, however, that the rela- 
 tion of fitness to control precedes and occasions, but 
 never follows, the feeling of worth or desirableness. 
 § 49. It should also be observed that the freedom 
 of the will, according to Kant, is not psy- 
 Freedom chologically conceivcd as the capacity to 
 
 still More 
 
 Exactly choose between two or more objects which 
 
 address the sensibilities, but signifies 
 only that freedom from the impulses of the feelings, 
 which necessarily belongs to any act ivhich responds 
 to the commands of reason. The will itself is the 
 capacity to respond to these commands, independ- 
 ently of, i.e.., with freedom from, the impulses of sense. 
 The evidence for the reality of freedom is found
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 103 
 
 not in the testimony of consciousness, but solely in 
 the fact that it is implied by the commands of reason, 
 and is accepted by the mind as an a priori truth. 
 
 The order of thought by which this freedom is 
 assented to, and the subject-matter of which it is 
 affirmed, may be thus stated. The practical reason 
 proposes to the will a maxim that is fit to be a 
 universal law. The man addressed, so far as he 
 is reason, assents, therein exercising his practical 
 capacity to know things as they are, and hence the 
 law is invested with final and supreme authority. 
 So far as the sensibility is concerned, it apprehends 
 and assents to objects as they aifect the feelings, 
 the objects varying with the varying sensibility 
 which they address. Hence the man oscillates be- 
 tween the proper self, the self of the reason, and the 
 self of the sensibilities, the noumenal and the phe- 
 nomenal. The reason, however, has no proper 
 knowledge of entities in a positive form, such knowl- 
 edge being limited to the senses, the reason presup- 
 posing another order of existence, which is super- 
 sensible, and by this very circumstance is exempt 
 from the law of cause and effect. 
 
 It would seem from this statement that reason 
 gives the knowledge of things in themselves so far 
 as that they exist, but gives us no knowledge of what
 
 104 kant's ethics. 
 
 the}' are, because this would imply a knowledge of 
 the laws under which they act as phenomena, iu 
 obedience to the relations of cause and effect. This 
 apparent contradiction was recognized by Kant, but 
 he attempts to set it aside by the consideration that 
 behind the appearance or the phenomena of the 
 sensibility, as obeying the law of natural causation, 
 there must lie at their root (though hidden) the 
 things in themselves, which we cannot expect will 
 be governed by the same laws. 
 
 § 50. While thus Kant cannot and does not pro- 
 Kant fess to explain the freedom of the will 
 that the ^^Y farther than by showing that it is 
 Moral Law ^^^^ impossible, he urges that we cannot 
 
 Affects the i o 
 
 Sensibilities, explain another fact equally undeniable, 
 i.e., the fact that the moral law affects the sensibil- 
 ities of men. That man takes some interest in this 
 law he does not deny, although he i-ejects the doc- 
 trine, in whatever form it may be held, that this 
 interest is the foundation of the moral judgments, 
 or their authority. He insists, however, that the 
 reason has the power to infuse a pleasure into the 
 soul at the fulfilment of duty, i.e., directly to affect 
 the sensibility painfully or pleasantly. How this 
 can be he does not explain. Indeed, he asserts that 
 such a fact must be inexplicable {i.e., the fact that
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MOKALS. 105 
 
 a thought can awaken pleasure or pain). The exist- 
 ence of such a causal power is itself incapable of any 
 solution. The only suggestion which he can give is 
 that the sensibility, with the phenomenal in general 
 and all its relations, is necessarily subordinated to 
 the thing in-itself and its possible relations. And 
 yet of the thing-in-itself with its interior and e.x- 
 terior relations, we confessedly know nothing beyond 
 the phenomenal effects in which it is manifested 
 under the laws of cause and effect. It were most 
 presumptuous, however, he suggests, for us to assert 
 that it has no other laws than these. The authority 
 of the moral law, the suitableness of its maxims to 
 be universal, the reasonableness of " a kingdom of 
 ends," all require the reality of moral freedom as 
 their subjective counterpart. 
 
 He urges that these ultimate facts in the actual or 
 possible constitution of things must all be assumed. 
 They cannot be explained, but they are themselves 
 necessary in order to explain the phenomena of 
 human experience. It cannot be reasonably urged 
 against them, that they are unconditioned or inde- 
 pendent, for wherever we go we must encounter 
 certain ultimate facts or truths, whether these are 
 found in the will of the Creator, the constitution of 
 things, or the behests of reason. Similarly, Kant
 
 106 Kant's ethics. 
 
 would say that he refers us to the practical reason 
 as the ultimate and the unconditioned moral element 
 in the careful critique of which he expects to find 
 the solution of all the problems of ethics, as by the 
 examination of the pure I'eason he had essayed to 
 explain the ultimate asseverations of speculative 
 truth. 
 
 Here he leaves us, at the end of his attempt to 
 bring into distinct apprehension and bold relief the 
 principal metaphysical concepts which are at the 
 foundation of ethical science. These concepts, thus 
 developed by the analytic method, he proposes sub- 
 sequently to explain by a critical examination of the 
 pi'actical reason, which should render a service to 
 ethics similar to that which he had hoped to derive 
 from the Critique of Pure Reason in the interest of 
 speculative science. 
 
 The conclusion which he reaches, and in which he 
 rests for the time, is the following: Though we 
 cannot explain or reconcile the ultimate concepts 
 or assumptions of the practical reason and the sci- 
 ence of ethics, we can explain their incomprehensibil- 
 ity. This incomprehensibility is similar to that 
 which had been reached in the Critique of Pure 
 Reason, as characteristic of the principles of specula- 
 tive science. It arises from the axiomatic or dosrmatic
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS. 107 
 
 character of certain irreconcilable or unadjustable 
 a priori elements, all of which must necessarily be 
 assumed in order to explain the possibility of human 
 experience — the experience in the one case being 
 the experience of knowledge, in the other the expe- 
 rience of duty. 
 
 Whether the Critique of Practical Reason, when 
 prosecuted, will fulfil the anticipations of its author, 
 whether it will be equally successful with this pre- 
 liminary essay on the Metaphysics of Morals, or 
 more so, remains to be seen. We must look forward 
 with interest to its solution of the problem which it 
 has imposed upon itself, viz.: to find in the postu- 
 lates of the practical reason not merely the synthetic 
 principles a priori which shall serve as a foundation 
 for ethical science, but which shall also, through 
 ethics, peiform the additional service which the 
 Critique of Pure Reason has shown to be so neces- 
 sary, and yet so impossible, for speculative philoso- 
 phy.
 
 CHAPTER III. 
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON.* 
 
 § 51. The reader of the preface to this treatise 
 Preface and should not fail to keep in mind the fact 
 Introduction, ^j^^^ -^ ^^^^ published seven years after the 
 Critique of the Pure Reason, and three years after 
 the Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics oif 
 Morals. Its author might very reasonably suppose 
 that his readers were familiar with both these trea- 
 tises, and the place of each in the development of 
 his philosophical system. The remarks made in 
 both preface and introduction are obviously designed 
 to recall distinctly, and to reimpress forcibly the 
 conclusions which he supposed himself to have 
 reached, involving, as the attempt necessarily did, a 
 short review of his entire system, and a series of 
 short and sharp statements of its distinctive prin- 
 ciples. No one who reads these two papers atten- 
 tively can doubt what his leading positions were in 
 respect to the most important questions which he 
 had proposed to consider and answer. 
 
 * Die Kritilc der Pralitisclien Vernunft. 
 108
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PKACTICAL REASON. 109 
 
 He begins by explaining why he entitles the pres- 
 ent treatise the Critique of the Practical 
 
 Practical, not 
 
 Reason, and not the Critique of the Pure Pure anA 
 Practical Reason, and gives the follow- 
 ing: That if there is or can be a reason that is truly 
 practical, it must necessarily be pure, that, is a 
 priori in its positions, inasmuch as it must begin 
 with an ultimate, actual fact, the fact of freedom, 
 and this in its very nature is involved in an uncon- 
 ditioned and an unconditional imperative. Now, 
 the Critique of the Pure Reason, the author proceeds 
 to urge, has shown by its analysis of all higher 
 human knowledge that it must involve an a priori 
 element, called the unconditioned. And yet of this 
 t( priori element, the speculative reason does not 
 and cannot affirm objective reality. 
 
 Qncere, here and always: Why does it not? Does 
 it not in fact? Why does not the analysis which 
 shows the unconditioned to be subjectively necessary 
 in order to the completion and trustworthiness of 
 human knowledge, and particularly of human sci- 
 ence — why does not this very analysis involve and 
 justify the belief that this, being unconditioned, is 
 also an objective fact? 
 
 P)ut it being assumed that this essential a priori 
 element must be furnished, we find that it is sup-
 
 110 kaxt's ethics. 
 
 plied by the practical reason, viz. : the element of free- 
 , „ . , dom, which, speculatively or in its scien- 
 
 The Practical '■ •' 
 
 Reason titic or philosophical relations, is the un- 
 
 Siipplies an 
 
 a jmori conditioned, since it is ideally involved in 
 
 the categorical imperative of duty. But 
 freedom (if not ideally, at least practically) implies 
 Cxod and immortality, if it is to be accepted as a fact. 
 Hence we have the basis of all a priori knowledge in 
 that unconditioned fact of freedom which is implied 
 in the moral law, inasmuch as the elements of trust- 
 worthy speculative knowledge rest on faith in duty, 
 this being given as objectively true, with the subjec- 
 tive freedom which it implies. That which was a 
 problem becomes an actual fact — amplifying itself 
 as the Soul, God, and Immortality. In this way, 
 through the medium and by the authority of the 
 practical reason, we establish the authority of these 
 speculative ideas of the pure reason. 
 
 Moreover, we explain by means of our critical an- 
 alysis of the speculative reason, why the practical 
 reason should be able to supply to the speculative an 
 element which it confesses to be wanting to itself. 
 The Critique of the Pure Reason has shown that two 
 kinds of knowledge are supposable, viz. : the knowl- 
 edge of phenomena, i.e., of things as conditioned by 
 sense-forms, the categories, and in a certain sense
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. Ill 
 
 by ideas — i.e., the knowledge of things as they ap- 
 pear — and the knowledge of noumena, i.e., of things 
 as they really are. This last confessedly cannot be 
 gained by the speculative reason, but if it can be 
 assured by the practical reason, this last consequently 
 deserves to be accepted as pure so far as it is practi- 
 cal, and because it is practical. 
 
 To the analysis of the practical reason as thus 
 outlined, the author adds that his previous treatises 
 are preliminary, both the speculative and the practi- 
 cal — the speculative as justifying the critical method 
 and its postulates, and the ethical as defining or 
 vouching for its subject-matter. Under the first are 
 included the famous Critic^ue and the Prolegomena, 
 and under the last the Metaphysics of Morals. 
 
 § 52. He notices, next in order, a criticism of this 
 last work which he deems worthy of his Reply to a 
 attention, viz.: that he did not begin his Criticism, 
 discussion with a definition of good, and also that he 
 did not define the faculty of desire. The objections 
 of the critic seem to us well taken, and to spring 
 into the face of the writer at almost every turn of 
 the subsequent discussion. We shall have frequent 
 occasion to refer to both as we proceed, and there- 
 fore say here only in passing, that the attempt of 
 Kant to meet these objections seems to increase
 
 li-2 rant's ethics. 
 
 rather than relieve the difficulty. The objections 
 seem to strike the ke^^-note of the error which 
 pervades his entire theory of the relations of 
 the sensibility to the will, and of both to the 
 intellect (or moral reason, as it is often called) 
 in its ultimate ethical concepts and judgments. 
 To this error we have had occasion previously to 
 advert, viz. : the error that because the experiences 
 of feeling and of voluntary affection are in their 
 very nature personal and empirical, they cannot 
 hold any relations to the will or to one another, 
 inasmuch as the voluntary are rational and per- 
 manent, and involve authority and obligation. The 
 grossness of this error is manifest in the absurd- 
 ity of Kant's attempt in the note, to define desire 
 and pleasure by merely intellectual concepts and 
 rational relations. We notice this error at the out- 
 set, and forewai-n the reader that it will be repeated 
 in form or in fact scores of times in the treatise. 
 For the present he must content himself as well as 
 he may with the following: "'The faculty of desire 
 is the being's faculty of becoming by means of its 
 ideas the cause of the actual existence of the objects 
 of these ideas." Our objection to this would be that 
 it does not conform to the facts of conscious experi- 
 ence. Tt seems but little better than trifling to say
 
 THE CKITIQUE OF PKACTICAJ, UEASOX. 113 
 
 that in desire the soul by means of its ideas becomes 
 the cause of the objects of these ideas. One does not 
 need to be told by Kant that this definition, with 
 others. '" is composed only of terms belonging to 
 the understanding, i.e.. of categories which contain 
 nothing empirical.'" So much for the preface. The 
 remaining topics, though instructive and interesting, 
 do not relate to Kant's Ethics, directly or indirectly, 
 and are beside our purpose. 
 
 § 53. In the brief introduction which follows, 
 two points deserve special attention in 
 the two-fold function which the author Function 
 asserts for the will. According to the Ascribed to 
 
 " the Will. 
 
 first, "the will is a faculty either to pro- 
 duce objects corresponding to ideas," or, according to 
 the second, " to determine ourselves to the effecting 
 of such objects (whether the physical power is sufli- 
 cient or not)." This twofold definition is not unfa- 
 miliar in our English nomenclature, Sis first, the capa- 
 city to accomplish physical effects of any kind, either 
 muscular or corporeal in ourselves or others, in the 
 world of matter with which our bodies are con- 
 nected, or even in the world of spirit, so far as other 
 spirits are subject to any agency of our own ; and 
 second, the capacity to pi'oduce effects which are
 
 114 K ant's ethics. 
 
 purely spiritual and in the domain of feeling, by a 
 direct energy of volition. 
 
 According to Kant, the agent in either case is not 
 the will, but reason — reason being conceived of as 
 the agent which acts on the will, and in one of the 
 two ways, either under "empirical conditions," as 
 when motives of sense or desire solicit or take 
 possession of the will, or when the motive or com- 
 mand of duty appears as the categorical imperative, 
 in some empirical form indeed, or, we should say, in 
 some concrete example, but still as exemplifying 
 some relation of duty. But this command of reason 
 supposes freedom, or the capacity of unconditioned 
 action. What this freedom is, as a psychological 
 endowment or act, Kant does not attempt to explain. 
 He does not even afifirm it of the will as a power to 
 choose, and scarcely recognizes the will as a faculty 
 of the soul at all. He discu.sses freedom, not as per- 
 taining to an activity of the spirit, but simply as 
 involving a special metaphysical relation of ideas, 
 giving the unconditioned in objective thought. 
 
 The recognition of this double aspect or effect of 
 the will's supposed response to reason, either in 
 internal, i.e., ethical, results, or in those which are 
 bodily and mechanical, is most important, and it is 
 surprising that more of it is not made by Kant.
 
 'ISE CRITKiUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. 115 
 
 The oversight is but one of many examples of his 
 neglect of the psychological aspects of his themes in 
 favor of the metaphysical. We note a still more 
 serious defect in his failure to see that reason may 
 be as truly a moving and constraining force with 
 the freely acting v^^ill, when it addresses the feelings 
 and urges the claims of the sensibilities, as when it 
 confronts the will with what Kant calls ideas, or the 
 commands of the reason. As we have already in- 
 timated, the assumption is utterly unwarrantable on 
 which Kant's entire theory rests, that the feelings, 
 as related to one another and to the highest and best 
 achievements of man, are empirical as contrasted with 
 the truly ra.tional. Moral freedom, or what Kant 
 calls the unconditioned, is just as compatible with 
 those rational concepts of the natural or pathological 
 feelings which the moral will can make supreme, as 
 with those concepts which are derived from intel- 
 lectual objects or their relations. 
 
 § 54. The indefinite and vacillating conceptions 
 of Kant in respect to this topic can only Vacillating 
 be explained by the fact that in his classification 
 times, and even since, the will has been °5 ^^^ 
 
 Psychical 
 
 conceived and defined in so indefinite Powers. 
 and vacillating a fashion. The powers of the soul 
 have often been held to be only two, viz.: to Know
 
 116 KANT^S ETHICS. 
 
 and to Feel, while under feeling has been included 
 every state that has to do with action, whether 
 internal or external. When an improvement has 
 been made upon this classitication, and a threefold 
 division introduced, founded on " to Know, to Feel, 
 and to Act," as three separate functions, great inde- 
 terminateness has still been attached to the meanings 
 of both feeling and action. It has not been decided 
 whether desire belonged partly or wholly to action, 
 or whether it partly pertained to feeling and partly 
 to will. Those who denied freedom, or did not 
 emphasize freedom, have made desire equivalent to 
 action or impulse. Even since the three designa- 
 tions, to Know, to Feel, and to Choose, were intro- 
 duced, to Know and to Will have been recognized 
 as the two leading powers, and at times have pre- 
 occupied for analysts the entire psychical arena. 
 
 § 55. It is also worthy of notice, as essential to a 
 correct interpretation of Kant's reason Kant's 
 ing, that Kant's use of the word " will "' ^"definite 
 
 Conceptions 
 
 is conspicuously indefinite and variable, "f 'hewni. 
 Now he seems to make it the capacity for ethical 
 choice, whether as a special form of psychological 
 activity which is purely spiritual, or whether it 
 passes over into a corporeal effect. Then again, 
 which is still more surprising, he repre.sents the
 
 THE CRITIQL'E OF PRACTICAL REASON. 117 
 
 will as the giver or enforcer of the moral law, 
 as when he speaks of it as the autonomous, as 
 contrasted with the heteronomous will, making it 
 synonymous with the practical reason — now the 
 giver of and then the respondent to the law of one 
 or both. In this brief introduction a distinction is 
 made between '"the empirically conditioned reason,' 
 on the one hand, "claiming exclusively to furnish the 
 ground of determination of the will," and the "pure 
 reason," on the other. This can only be understood 
 by apprehending the diiferent senses in which the 
 term "reason" is used, prominent among which is 
 the sense in which it is used as the lawgiver to the 
 moral, i.e.. the free will, which again is distin- 
 guished from the sensibility with its strong impulses, 
 passionately and passively yielding to the excite- 
 ments of sense. 
 
 In the conclusion of his brief introduction, the 
 author adds an important remark, the full import 
 of which might easily escape the attention of the 
 reader. He says: "The order in the subdivision of 
 the analytic will be the reverse of that in the 
 Critique of the Pure Speculative Reason. For in 
 the present case we shall commence with the prin- 
 ciples and proceed to the concepts, and only then, if 
 possible, to the senses; whereas, in the case of the
 
 118 Kant's ethicj,. 
 
 speculative reason," i.e., as analyzed in his famous 
 Critique, "" we began with the senses, and had to end 
 with the iH'inciples." 
 
 § 56. This remark of Kant suggests the inquirj" 
 whether knowledge of every kind, begin- 
 
 Knowledge ° j ' o 
 
 of Every Sort ning with the sense-perceptions and end- 
 Begins with 
 Judgments. iug with the intuitions of the reason, is 
 
 not Concepts. ,• ■ \ ^ c t. • iii -j- 
 
 not invariabh' lirst given to the mind in 
 the form of propositions or principles, which are 
 subsequently analyzed into percepts, concepts, or 
 ideas; and whether the sceptical distrust with which 
 Kant invested all the processes of the speculative 
 faculty, and which he seeks to overcome by such 
 manifold and unnatural ways of resort to the prac- 
 tical reason, would not have been rendered un- 
 necessary by the distinct recognition, on his part, of 
 the truth which he limits to the practical reason, 
 viz.: that knowledge of every kind is originally given 
 in the form of judgments, involving the concepts, 
 which are expressed in propositions by manifold 
 relations. These relations, when subsequently ana- 
 lyzed and generalized b}^ the critical judgment, are 
 revealed as the a priori bonds by which concepts are 
 united, and these, again, are mentally isolated and 
 analyzed as forms of sense, categories of the under- 
 standing, and ideas of the reason, which are also
 
 THE ClilTIQUE OP PRACTICAL KEASON. 119 
 
 assumed psychologically as the subjective conditions, 
 and metaphysically as the objective forms of all 
 human know^ledge. Such a correction of Kant's 
 theory would justify our confidence in the specu- 
 lative reason, and might have saved Kant the neces- 
 sity of resorting to the practical reason as a make- 
 weight or a make-shift for his imperfectly or rnis- 
 conceived pure reason. 
 
 § 57. Following Kant still further, we find that 
 the first chapter of the Critique treats of principles of 
 the principles of pure practical reason, J^'^^^'^^ 
 and begins with a definition of practical Defined, 
 principles, as " propositions which contain a general 
 determination of the will, having under it (itself) 
 several practical rules." The phrase allgemeine 
 Besthnnmiig des Willens is sufficiently abstract and 
 indefinite. It certainly does not mean a moving force 
 or agency which actually effects a right or wrong con- 
 dition of will, and we conclude that it must signify 
 any accepted maxim or rule which characterizes or 
 defines the will as morally good or evil, /.p., in a gen- 
 eral way, admitting, of course, sundry subordinate 
 particulars, or varieties of individual character. Or 
 more exactly, it is any universal rule which by be- 
 ing adopted expresses the moral character of the will. 
 
 The remark appended, that some motive to such a
 
 120 kakt's ethics. 
 
 state or activity of the will must always be assumed 
 to be possible, is unquestionably correct. 
 
 § 58. The added remark that such a motive must 
 address the reason onlv, as contradistin- 
 
 Every Motive 
 
 must Address guished from the feelings, i.e., must be 
 
 the Reason.' . , i -.i ,1 ,1 
 
 rational as contrasted with the patho- 
 logical, implies that a motive furnished by reason 
 must exclude the feelings as such, or any relations 
 to them. We have already observed that such an 
 assumption or assertion would be emphatically re- 
 jected by many of Kant's critics. No one, however, 
 would deny for this reason that certain practical 
 principles are universal, inasmuch as all would con- 
 tend that it is always reasonable that the lower 
 natural feelings should give way to the higher, as 
 also the injurious to the beneficent. All men would 
 also assert that physical laws differ from moral laws, 
 and that moral laws are in their nature imperative, 
 though on a different theory from Kant's. All will 
 agree with him that the moral law is both internal 
 and external, that is, determines or commands both 
 the internal state of the will and the bodily or 
 external actions which the will controls. Certain 
 moral laws are also categorically imperative so far 
 as they suppose certain conditions to be common to 
 all men, and concern themselves with those internal
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF I'RACTICAL REASON. 121 
 
 states of the will which are within the reach of all 
 men. So far as it may be supposed that the condi- 
 tions which respect the outward conduct are varia- 
 ble, the moral law proper concerns itself universally 
 with the internal states of the will, and with them 
 only. So far as these purposes or feelings require a 
 single course of action, so far is the rule of action 
 uniform and fixed. In all these general positions the 
 practical theory of Kant may be accepted by those 
 who reject altogether his doctrine of a blind cate- 
 gorical imperative which assumes dictatorially to 
 guide and control the moral reason. 
 
 In Theorem I. we find the following: "All practical 
 principles which presuppose an object of 
 
 ^ ^ lit- J Empirical 
 
 the faculty of desire as the ground of the Principles 
 determination of the will are empirical, 
 and can furnish no practical laws." Two reasons 
 are given for this position : F/'i'st, The desire precedes 
 the rule, and is founded on a pleasure actually expe- 
 rienced. Now, it is impossible to know befoi'ehand 
 what any pleasure will be, and consequently we must 
 try a pleasure before we prescribe a law for or against 
 it. To this we reply: The law of duty prescribes an 
 affection as voluntary, in comparison with some 
 other one or more affections also voluntary, i.e, an 
 affection of some class, in competition with one of
 
 122 KANT*S ETHICS. 
 
 another as a class. On any theory, it supposes we 
 know the natural excellence or desirableness of such 
 aifections. It supposes this even on the theory of 
 the categorical imperative, which commands the act, 
 as distinguished from a feeling, i.e., makes it mor- 
 ally binding because by some sort of experience it 
 knows it to be naturally good, i.e., fit to he a uni- 
 versal ride. The first experience in the order of 
 time is that an action, say, of love or pity or self- 
 sacrifice, is naturally good. The knowledge of this 
 natural excellence is derived from some source be- 
 fore it is enforced by a moral command. Kant says,. 
 indeed: "It is impossible to know a- priori of any 
 idea whether it will be connected with pleasure or 
 pain, or be indifferent.''" That is true, and for this 
 very reason we must wait till we know whether it 
 is connected with pleasure or pain, either by em- 
 pirical experience or by testimony, before we can 
 decide whether it comes under the law. If this is 
 so, why then must or may we not know the rela- 
 tions of actions emjjirically before we know them 
 morally, or, as Kant would say, before we know 
 them formally? 
 
 He adds in the second place, that pleasure and 
 pain cannot hold in the same degree for all rational 
 beings, and hence cannot be the foundation of a law.
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. 123 
 
 We answer: If they do not hold in the same degree, 
 that is, are not equally intense or strong, they can be 
 the same to all men in their relative natural value 
 so far as quality is concerned, i.e., natural quality. 
 Otherwise the beings concerned with them do not 
 belong to the same species, and consequently cannot in 
 any sense accept the same moral law on grounds of 
 reason. In Kant's terminology, unless the relations 
 of the empirical endowments of men are the same, 
 their moral relations could not be formally the 
 same, inasmuch as the formal cannot be known in 
 psychological experience, except as it is exemplified 
 in the empirical, i.e., cannot be proposed as a rule or 
 standard, except it presents an ideal which has rela- 
 tions to the actual nature of the being on whom 
 and by whom it is self-imposed. 
 
 § 59. Theorem II. is that " all material practical 
 principles, as such, are of one and the Material 
 same kind, and come under the general "'' !*^^ 
 
 ' ° Principles 
 
 principle of self-love or private happi- Defined, 
 ness." 
 
 In support of this position he contends that there 
 is no distinction possible between the desires, as 
 higher and lower; that the reason, as an impulse or 
 a motive, neither appeals to nor satisfies any desires 
 whatever, and, moreover, that pure reason " must
 
 134 kant's ethics. 
 
 be able to determine the will by the mere form of 
 the practical rule, without supposing any feeling." 
 But he adds: ''Then only when reason itself deter- 
 mines the will (not as the servant of the inclina- 
 tion), is it really a higher desire, to which that 
 which is pathologically determined is subordinate, 
 and is really and even specifically distinct from the 
 latter, so that even the slightest admixture of the 
 motives of the latter impairs its strength and supe- 
 riority"; and still more positively: "Reason, with 
 its practical law, determines the will immediately, 
 not by means of an intervening feeling of pleasure 
 and pain, not even of pleasure in the law itself; and 
 it is only because it can, as pure reason, be practical 
 that it is possible for it to be legislative." 
 
 These assertions need no comment except to refer 
 the reader to the concession made by Kant in the 
 passage cited above, that reason acts through a 
 higher desire whenever it in fact determines the 
 will. 
 
 § 60. In Theorem III. he repeats the position that 
 
 Practical every one of the maxims cited is a practical 
 
 nncip es universal law in form only, as contrasted 
 
 tormal, and •' ' 
 
 not Material. ^Jth matter. Form is also frankly and 
 forcibly defined to be fitness for universal legisla- 
 tion. This fitness is illustrated by examples of the
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. 135 
 
 workings of the four previously supposed rules of con- 
 duct in respect to human welfare. If these instan- 
 ces mean anything they justify the interpretation 
 that Kant's formula of universal legislation is always 
 to will such a purpose or voluntaiy desire as would 
 produce acts which promote the highest well-being 
 of man. {Cf. § 40.) 
 
 § 61. Two problems are then proposed. The first 
 is, to find the nature of the will that can Two Problems 
 be determined b}^ such a law, and the Proposed, 
 answer is only such a will as is free from natural 
 causality, i.e., the will as such; in simple English, 
 the will as a purpose or voluntary desire when con- 
 trasted with the manifestation or execution of its 
 volition in words or bodily acts. The second prob- 
 lem is, "given such a will, to find a law competent 
 to determine it necessarily," which is solved by the 
 discovery of a supposed unconditioned practical law. 
 To this is appended the remark, which not unfre- 
 quently occurs in the discussion, that the possibility 
 of freedom would never have been dreamed of and 
 its reality never accepted as a fact, had not the 
 moral law enforced obligations which implied its 
 possibility and reality. Physical science does not 
 know it, nor does the experience of common life. It 
 is ethical experience only which implies and affirms
 
 126 kant's ethics. 
 
 it. In Kant's own language, man "judges, there- 
 fore, that he can do a certain thing because he is 
 conscious that he ought, and he recognizes that he is 
 free, a fact which but for the moral law he would 
 never have known." This is true with a qualifica- 
 tion. We may concede that man would in fact know 
 no freedom except through his moral experiences, 
 but instead of holding with Kant that man knows 
 he is free because he knows he ought, we contend 
 that he believes that he ought because he knows he is 
 free. Kant's position is still more explicitly assert- 
 ed in the remark that follows, to which is added a 
 corollary, which asserts that the moral law extends to 
 all moral beings, with this important exception, that 
 for the Infinite Being an act becomes holiness which 
 in created beings would be obedience, inasmuch as 
 that obedience of which the con-elate is obligation, 
 is possible only when there is struggling disinclina- 
 tion. In all finite beings, therefore, in whom virtue 
 always involves a conflict and who always reluctate 
 in opposing desire, its triumphs are progressive but 
 never complete. This is the logical and the accepted 
 outcome of Kant's theoiy of obligation, and needs 
 no further comment here. {Cf. § 37.) 
 
 4; 62. Theorem TV. treats of the Autonomj^ and 
 Heteronomy of the will, with the same results as in
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. 127 
 
 the first treatise. {Cf. § 45.) Special stress is laid 
 upon the now familiar principle that the 
 
 ^ Autonomy and 
 
 authority of the moral law lies not in its Heteronomy 
 
 of the Will. 
 
 matter, but m its form, and that the latter 
 consists in its fitness to be universal. As previously, 
 so here, the examples find all their interest and force 
 as illustrations of the adaptation of right purposes 
 and conduct to promote the welfare of man. Apart 
 from such tendency or fitness, as implied in every 
 example cited by Kant, that is, as he would insist, 
 apart from the inatfer, and regarded as a merely 
 formal element, the condition of universal fitness can 
 only require logical consistency, and can signify or 
 imply nothing more. 
 
 In the remarks which follow, Kant recognizes the 
 fact that happiness may be the object of every hu- 
 man being, and that all men find a rational sym- 
 pathy in the happiness of others, and both these 
 must be assumed in order to make the law of duty 
 practical or efficient, while he insists that inasmuch 
 as these elements are material and not formal they 
 can neither originate nor enforce the law of duty. 
 That this extreme position is necessary to his view of 
 the authority of the law, as the categorical impera- 
 tive, is sufficiently clear. 
 
 in Remark 2, he seeks to reinforce his previous
 
 128 rant's ethics. 
 
 arguments by the consideration that while men know 
 what duty is with unquestioning convictions, they find 
 it difficult to decide the questions which relate to hap- 
 piness, overlooking entirely the point that questions 
 of duty are clear only so far as the purpose or inter- 
 nal volition or state is concerned, while questions of 
 happiness (and, we might add, of duty, so far as they 
 depend on questions of happiness) turn on contin- 
 gent and doubtful matter, viz. : on changing circum- 
 stances. It is sufficient to say that no ethical system, 
 whatever its professions, can usually go a whit far- 
 ther than the purposes or intentions in laying down 
 axiomatic principles or rules of duty. Directions 
 for the conduct generally admit of qualifications and 
 exceptions. 
 
 § 63. Ill-desert is next noticed, which is the ra- 
 iii-desert tional prerogative of moral volition when 
 Analyzed. j^ transgresses the moral law, right- 
 eously to suffer evil. This property is treated as 
 original, and, as we should infer by the logic of Kant, 
 it must be directly enforced by the categorical imper- 
 ative. {Cf. §94 on Bishop Butler.) By what reason- 
 ing or through what relation it is proved that the 
 purpose (or rather the man) which is not conformed 
 to the law which is fit to be universal, deserves to 
 suffer evil, is not explained. It is only assei-ted that
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. 129 
 
 were this not true, the conception of justice would 
 be impossible. 
 
 The theory of a moral sense is next referred to. 
 This Kant seems to have known imperfectly, as it 
 was held by Hutcheson and Shaftesbury. It is, of 
 course, summarily set aside because it uses feeling 
 where reason alone is appropriate. The theory of 
 perfection which was taught by Wolff before and in 
 Kant's day is also noticed, but it is dismissed as em- 
 pirical, even when held in the form of man's highest 
 dignity as suitable to the end of human existence, 
 and for the reason that it supposes an empirical 
 knowledge of human nature, and therefore must 
 rest on a material, as contrasted with a formal, prin- 
 ciple of legislation. 
 
 § 64. After this analysis, the author proceeds to 
 gather up and in a sense to restate the The Contrast 
 results which it seems to justify in the ^je't^veen the 
 contrast which it discovers between the ^^^""^ '"'^ 
 
 the Practical 
 
 pure and practical reason. Reason. 
 
 The speculative reason gives us no principles a 
 priori, but only time and space as a priori forms, 
 necessary to the sense-perceptions. Besides these it 
 gives no knowledge of noumena or things in them- 
 selves, but only of objects of possible experience as 
 connected by a priori cateyorics. It established, how-
 
 130 kaxt's ethics. 
 
 ever, the necessity of thinking certain HOioneini, and 
 thus provided negatively for freedom, /.e., for the be- 
 lief of something more than sense experience as such, 
 but without any positive knowledge concerning it. 
 It pointed to facts and relations beyond the world of 
 sense, to freedom, not merely in a negative, but also 
 in a positive sense, as supposed and implied in the 
 moral law. This introduced into sensible nature a 
 nature that is super-sensible, or, as we may say, con- 
 nects an autonomy of pure practical reason with the 
 heteronomy of nature, the one controlling and in- 
 fluencing the other without interfering with the 
 laws of either — the moral also proposing the control 
 of the rational or sensible by its own laws, so as to 
 produce the siimmum homim. 
 
 For the truth of this analysis Kant appeals to ex- 
 perience. The moral imperative, he asserts, obliges 
 everyone to speak the truth, to preserve his own 
 life, etc. These acts are not, however, taught by 
 nature as inductions or lessons of experience, but by 
 sundry higher laws as ideals which can only be ac- 
 tualized in experience. Here also, he says, we notice 
 the difference between the laws of a system to which 
 the will is subject and of a system which is subject 
 to a will. In the one case the objects are the causes 
 of the ideas that determine the wall, in the other the
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON". 131 
 
 will is the cause of the objects. Hence the two 
 problems; the first, how the pure reason can cog- 
 nize objects a priori, the second, how it can deter- 
 mine objects a priori The first has been determined 
 by the answer — only so far as to show how sense-ex- 
 perience is possible by a priori intuitions, and with- 
 out the knowledge of things in themselves. The last 
 does not explain how experiences of desire are pos- 
 sible, for these have also been provided for — but only 
 how reason can determine the maxims of the will. It 
 does not point to an a priori intuition, as in the case 
 of the speculative reason; it relates to the states of 
 the will only, separately from their manifestations 
 in sense-activity, inasmuch as any realization of an 
 act or state by the sensibility would carry us into 
 the field of the speculative reason. 
 
 In answering these several questions, the critical 
 philosophy begins with certain practical laws or 
 rules of duty as real. Instead of the receptive forms 
 of intuition (the a priori element in sense-perception) 
 it assumes the concept of freedom, inasmuch as prac- 
 tical laws of any kind are only possible on the sup- 
 position of freedom. We do not explain how free- 
 dom is possible, but finding the law of duty as a 
 fact, we know that it implies freedom as a fact. 
 The one is an essential element, and in that sense a
 
 133 Kant's ethics. 
 
 condition of the other. This finishes the exposition 
 of the fundamental principle of the practical reason. 
 
 ItH deduction, that is, the justification of its va- 
 lidity, is not so easy as is that of the principles of 
 the speculative reason. These last are confirmed by 
 an appeal to experience. But in morals we cannot 
 refer to actual experience, but only to the ideal, i.e., 
 to what ought to be. To another fact, however, we can 
 refer. The fact of freedom, which even the specu- 
 lative reason was obliged to assume as possible in 
 the form of the unconditioned, is now enforced as 
 the condition of that law of duty, which is imposed 
 by the practical reason. In this way, what was a 
 negative but necessary speculative conception gains 
 objective reality for ethics, and the reason, from a 
 transcendent position or use, passes to one that is 
 immanent — i.e., which is applicable to the feelings 
 and the actions as phenomena. 
 
 In the world of sense every cause is a conditional 
 cause, and yet in every series an unconditioned ele- 
 ment is supposable. We saw that while in the 
 sphere of phenomena freedom is inconceivable and is 
 excluded from positive knowledge, it may still be pos- 
 sible in the woi'ld of uoumena. But what was thus 
 conceived as simply possible is now recognized and 
 enforced by the practical reason as a condition of the
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. 133 
 
 law of duty, and is therefore accepted as true. A 
 causa HOHineKon, i.e., a free cause, is not directly 
 known, and cannot even be conceived by the specula- 
 tive reason, and yet it can be believed and assumed 
 as implied in the imperative of the practical reason. 
 § 65. The preceding suggests the question again, 
 How can we reconcile the extension, be- pj^^, p,,,^ y^^ 
 yond its appropriate limits, of the knowl- Apply the 
 
 Commands of 
 
 edge thus gained by the practical reason, the Practical 
 
 Reason to the 
 
 i.e., from nouraena to the objects and world of 
 
 Sense? 
 
 phenomena of the sensible world? 
 
 In reply to this question, as formally stated, the 
 author refers to Hume's celebrated argument, that 
 the law of causation involves no objective necessity, 
 and is the mere product of association, so far as this 
 can be applied to make experience possible. He 
 concedes that so far as phenomena are concerned, 
 this may hold good, while yet it does not extend to 
 noumena or the intelligible world. He contends 
 that the conclusions which we have reached in re- 
 spect to the reality of freedom, as implied by the 
 necessities of the practical reason, simply establish 
 the fact, and consequently its possibility, but do not 
 provide for the determination of any one of its 
 laws, such laws being possible only in the sphere of 
 phenomena. And yet we can know freedom so far as
 
 134 rant's ethics. 
 
 it intrudes into a.nd inodifie.s plienoniena, although 
 we cannot subject it to laws, for to do so would be 
 to make it cease to be freedom. But we gain this 
 much: if we find no incompatibility between the two 
 spheres, we can accept the one as consistent with the 
 other. We even do more: we hold that both are 
 necessary — the one to make experience possible, i.e, 
 possible to speculative reason in the realm of con- 
 crete and sensible phenomena, and the other to 
 make noumena, though unconditioned, to be not 
 only intelligible, but necessary to our reason, i.e., to 
 our practical reason, so far as it imposes on us the 
 law of duty, thereby involving freedom. 
 
 § 66. Chapter II. is entitled. The Concept of an 
 The Object Object of Practical Reason; or, as it 
 the^Pr^cHcaf "^^^^^^ '^^ interrogatively expressed. With 
 Reason. what kind of objects does the practical 
 
 reason concern itself, and what kind of products can 
 it bring to pass by its appropriate activity? 
 
 The answer to this question is brief, viz.: The 
 object or effect produced is in no sense physical: it 
 is simply moral, i.e.^ morally good or evil; or, as 
 Kant would say, simply good or evil, inasmuch as 
 he acknowledges no relation between sentient good 
 and evil, on the one hand, and the moral on the 
 other. In our English terminology we should say it
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASOJiT. 135 
 
 was simply psychical, a state of the will existing for 
 and provided by the will alone; equally good or 
 bad, whether passing over to any outward act oi- no. 
 Kant urges that these two kinds of good must be 
 derived from different sources — the first from the 
 sensibilities, and the second from the commands of 
 the moral reason, as their originator — and that each 
 is independent of the other. If the contrary were 
 true, i.e.. if moral good and evil were that which 
 produces pleasure and pain, he iirges that experience 
 would be necessary to tell us which is good or evil, 
 because it is only by experience that we can learn 
 the cause of either. The maxim of the schoolmen. 
 Nihil apj)t'fii)iiis iiii^i si(h rafio)ie boiii, is often cited 
 to sustain this view. But Kant contends that this 
 adage is misleading by reason of the ambiguity of 
 the word bonum, which may mean either sentient or 
 rational, i.e., moral, good. If both senses are in- 
 cluded, then the term is ambiguous; if only the first, 
 then it is false. Well and ill refer to the pleasant 
 or unpleasant, as determined by the sensibility; but 
 good or ei'il pertains to the will as determined by the 
 reason. It is true that man is a rational being, and 
 as such must use his reason to judge between means 
 and ends, and in this sense to judge between sentient 
 good and evil; but he also uses this power in the
 
 136 kaxt's ethics. 
 
 higher function of judging of that which is good 
 and evil of itself, I.e., morally right or wrong. In 
 the decision of this question, we observe we are 
 compelled to select between two alternatives. We 
 must either, on the one hand, accord to the reason 
 itself the capacity to originate a rational principle, 
 which it applies as a law. which law directly deter- 
 mines the will, as by its choice or rejection it becomes 
 morally good or evil. But if we take this position, 
 we must adopt an apparent paradox, viz.: that the 
 concept of moral good and evil is not determined 
 before the moral law, but is determined after it and 
 by means of it. The other alternative is for us to 
 accept the necessity of defining good and evil in 
 terms of sensibility, and so, as Kant reasons, make 
 both the products of experience. 
 
 Moral distinctions, however, he next proceeds to 
 say, pertain only to the states of the will itself, as dis- 
 tinguished from their effects in any forms of external 
 action. But the external actions being phenomena 
 of sense, moral experience must come under at least 
 one of the categories, i.e., of causality as exemplified 
 in the will or voluntary action. So far as they are 
 manifested in the forms of external action, they 
 must also appear in or take form from all the cate- 
 gories. The relations of these moralized categories
 
 TUK CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL KKA80N. 13T 
 
 to one another are explained at some length, but as 
 this point seems not to be material to the essential 
 features of Kant's theory, we pass it over. 
 
 § 67. What Kant calls the Typk of the pure 
 practical reason presents some important The Typic 
 and interesting features. The objects of" ^ *j*j ^"*^ 
 the will are either good or evil according Reason, 
 as the practical reason determines the choice of them 
 by the will to be either morally right or wrong. In 
 other words, says Kant, the will is pronounced by 
 the practical reason right or wrong according as it 
 chooses this or that object, the objects chosen them- 
 selves thereby becoming right or wrong. Inasmuch, 
 however, as these moral states, or free acts, go over 
 into the sphere of the sensible world which obeys 
 physical laws, the question is at once suggested. How 
 such external actions can be morally right or wrong. 
 As a sensible event, such an action can be conceived 
 as explained by the schematism of the imagination, 
 though it is the product of freedom, but it is not 
 easy to see how a material or sensible event can take 
 on or be penetrated by moral quality, obe^ung as it 
 must the physical conditions of existence. This diffi- 
 culty of Kant's own suggestion it would seem to be 
 difficult for him to answer, but he attemjjts it by 
 asserting that " the understanding for the purposes
 
 138 kaxt's ethics. 
 
 of judgment can provide not a scheme of the sensi- 
 bility, but a law" such "as can be exhibited in 
 concreto in objects of the senses." " The rule of the 
 judgment according to laws of practical reason is 
 this: Ask yourself whether, if the action you pro- 
 pose were to take place by a law of the system of 
 nature of which you were yourself a part, you could 
 regard it as possible by your own will." He then 
 refers to the four cases of obvious immorality 
 (which he had cited more than once), contending that 
 the acts supposed would be wrong, not simply be- 
 cause of the etiects or consequences which would fol- 
 low were the immoral acts in question accepted as 
 laws of nature, but that such laws would in a sense 
 be types of the moral principles required in their 
 several cases. He reasons, whatever his reasoning- 
 may signify, that we must hold the moral law to be 
 the type of a natural law, so as to guard it against 
 that empiricism which judges of conduct by conse- 
 quences, and yet, on the other hand, we must defend 
 ourselves against the mysticism which holds our 
 judgments aloof from and above all consideration of 
 the tendencies and eflFects of conduct. Truly a wise 
 precaution on his part, but how the desirhrota can 
 be provided by his theory it is not so easy to dis- 
 cover.
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. 139 
 
 § 68. Chapter III., of the motives of pure practi- 
 cal reason, is one of the most instructive The Motives 
 in the treatise, giving, as it does, a series ° ^. ^^^ 
 
 ' o =' Practical 
 
 of very lucid statements of the practical Reason, 
 working of Kant's theory and anticipating many of 
 the objections and difficulties which he could not but 
 foresee would be urged against it. The first sen- 
 tence is at once forcible and comprehensive: "What 
 is essential in the moral worth of actions is that the 
 moral law should directly determine the will." It 
 must do this '" directly." with no intervention of 
 feeling, inasmuch as this would make the act not to 
 be done for the sake of the law, and thus eviscerate 
 it of its morality. If we understand by motive the 
 subjective ground of an act whose objective ground 
 is not reason, then the Divine Will cannot be influ- 
 enced by motives, and if the motive of the human 
 being is the moral law alone, " the objective princi- 
 ple of determination must always and alone be also 
 the subjectively sufficient determining principle.*" 
 We cannot show how a law can directly determine 
 the will, for tliat were to explain the mystery of free 
 will. But we need to clear its action from every in- 
 fluence upon the feelings, which can only hinder or 
 divide it. 
 
 § 69. We observe, then, that the moral law acts
 
 140 kant's ethics. 
 
 on the will not only without the cooperation of the 
 sensibilities, but often, if not always, in 
 
 Obligation 
 
 and Respect resistance to them. When this last hap- 
 
 for the Law. . /. i ■ i • i • 
 
 pens, it checks the leelmg which it over- 
 comes, producing as a consequence indirectly and 
 negatively another feeling, which is painful and is 
 the only feeling, the nature and actuality of which 
 ma}^ be understood a priori, viz. : the feeling of obli- 
 gation. All the inclinations as such tend to happi- 
 ness and are classed as ministering to selfishness or 
 to self-conceit. Selfishness is checked by the reason, 
 which prescribes rational welfare, self-conceit is 
 summarily set aside and rejected. The capacity of 
 reason thus to humble selfish vanity is also known 
 a priori and awakens respect for the law, a feeling 
 which, he tells us, is not empirical, but is known 
 a priori, being a feeling which is directly produced 
 by an intellectual cause. The strong tendency to 
 make a subjective into an objective determining 
 principle is checked and humiliated by the moral 
 law, for which respect is at once awakened as supe- 
 rior to any pathological experience or affection. 
 Thus, by means of this negative operation of repres- 
 sion, there is awakened a positive emotion in opposi- 
 tion to self-love. Doubtless, Kant gladly availed him- 
 self of the opportunity to interpose at this point the
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. 141 
 
 following remark: " No special kind of feeling need 
 be assumed for this under the name of a practical or 
 moral feeling as antecedent to the moral law and 
 serving as its foundation." This negative effect is 
 pathological. So far as the individual as a sensitive 
 being is concerned, it is also humiliating, and so far 
 as the law is concerned, it is respect, which may be 
 indirectly called moral feeling. The effect produced, 
 liowever, is not pathological, but practical, and the 
 respect for the law is not a motive to morality, but 
 is morality itself subjectively considered as a mo- 
 tive. This respect and all which it involves cannot 
 hold good of the Supreme Being or any being who 
 like Him is incapable of sensibility. As for respect, 
 it need not be said it applies to persons only and not 
 to things, i.e., to persons as exemplifying the moral 
 law. Respect for the law may become an interest 
 in so far as it impels us by desire to live a life gov- 
 erned by itself as an objective motive, and also in 
 the technical sense a maxim, but in these effects it 
 can be applied only to imperfect and sentient beings. 
 And yet the interest awakened is in some se)ise 
 moral, just as the feelings are called moral by 
 courtesy. An action determined by the law against 
 inclination is duty, and duty includes practical ob- 
 ligation, i.e.. a deterniiuMtion against reluctant feel-
 
 142 kajs't's ethics. 
 
 ing. The feeling of elevation at being animated by 
 such a motive involves self-approbation. In this way 
 Kant very rapidly dispones of some of the most im- 
 portant and characteristic ethical emotions. 
 
 § 70. The difference between acting according to 
 duty and from a sense of duty, Kant 
 
 Acting '' 
 
 According to continues, is obvious from the principles 
 
 Duty and 
 
 from a Sense laid dowu, and is itself most important. 
 " ^' The first, i.e., legality, is possible if the 
 
 inclinations determine the will; the second, only 
 when the moral law is the objective motive. For a 
 perfect being the moral law is a law of holiness; 
 for a being morally imperfect, it is a law of duty. 
 " It is a very beautiful thing to do good to men 
 from love to them and from sympathetic good will, 
 or to be just from love of order; but this is not the 
 true moral maxim of conduct which is suitable to 
 our condition among rational beings, as iHe)i, when 
 we pretend with fanciful pride to set oui'selves above 
 the thought of duty, like volunteers; and, as if we 
 were independent of the command, to want to do of 
 our own good pleasure what we think we need no 
 command to do. * * * Duty and obligation are 
 the only names that we must give to our relations 
 to the moral law." 
 
 § 71. The njoral law commands love to God and
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL KEASOX. 143 
 
 our neighbor, but it commands neither as an affec- 
 tion. " To love God means in this sense 
 
 Import of a 
 
 to like to do His commandments; to love Coinmand 
 one's neighbor, to like to practice all 
 duties to him." But this is not a command to have 
 the disposition in question, but to " endeavor after 
 it. * * * That law of all law^s," viz.: the law of 
 love, exhibits the moral disposition in its perfection 
 as a moral ideal of holiness, when it shall have out- 
 grown the relation of duty and obligation. 
 
 After enlarging upon this theme, Kant adds that 
 these remarks are not so much designed to oppose 
 religious fanaticism as that moral fanaticism which 
 imagines that human virtue ought not to be mili- 
 tant, but to be already perfect in holiness. 
 
 "Now, if we search we shall find for all actions 
 that are worthy of praise a law of duty which com- 
 mands, and does not leave us to choose what may be 
 agreeable to our inclinations. This is the only way 
 of representing things that can give a moral train- 
 ing to the soul, because it alone is capable of solid 
 and accurately defined principles. 
 
 " If fanaticism in its most general sense is a 
 deliberate overstepping of the limits of human rea- 
 son, then moral fanaticism is such an overstepping 
 of the bounds that practical pure reason sets to
 
 144 kant's ethics. 
 
 mankind, in that it forbids us to place the subjective 
 determining principle of correct actions, that is, 
 their moral motive, in anything but the law itself, 
 or to place the disposition which is thereby brought 
 into the maxims in anything but respect for this 
 law; and hence commands us to take, as the supreme 
 vital principle of all morality in men, the thought 
 of duty, which strikes down all arrogance, as well as 
 vain self-love. 
 
 "If this is so, it is not only writers of romance or 
 sentimental educators (although thej'^ may be zeal- 
 ous opponents of sentimentalism), but sometimes 
 even philosophers; nay, even the severest of all, the 
 Stoics, that have brought in moral fanaticism, in- 
 stead of a sober but wise moral discipline, although 
 the fanaticism of the latter was more heroic, that of 
 the former, of an insipid, effeminate character; and 
 we may, without hypocrisy, say of the moral teach- 
 ing of the Gospel, that it first, by the purity of its 
 moral principle, and at the same time by its suit- 
 ability to the limitations of finite beings, brought 
 all the good conduct of men under the discipline of 
 a duty plainly set before their eyes, which does not 
 permit them to indulge in dreams of imaginary 
 moral perfections; and that it also set the bounds of 
 humility (that is, self-knowledge) to self-conceit as
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. 145 
 
 well as to self-love, both of which are ready to mis- 
 take their limits. 
 
 "Duty! Thou sublime and mighty name, that 
 dost embrace nothing charming or insin- Apostrophe 
 uating, but requirest submission, and ^oDuty. 
 yet seekest not to move the will b}' threatening 
 aught that would arouse natural aversion or terror, 
 but merely boldest forth a law which of itself finds 
 entrance into the mind, and yet gains reluctant 
 reverence (though not always obedience), a law 
 before which all inclinations are dumb, even though 
 they secretly counter- work it! What origin is there 
 worthy of thee, and where is to be found the root of 
 thy noble descent, which proudly rejects all kindred 
 with the inclinations; a root to be derived from 
 which is the indispensable condition of the only 
 worth which men can give themselves? 
 
 " It can be nothing less than a power which ele- 
 vates man above himself which can enable a man 
 to appreciate the obligation and elevation of such a 
 life. * * * This power is nothing but personal if ij, 
 tliat is, freedom and independence of the mechanism 
 of nature, yet, regarded as a faculty of a being who is 
 subject to special laws, namely, pure practical laws 
 given by its own reason, so that the person, as be- 
 longing to the sensible world, is subject to his 
 10
 
 146 rant's ethics. 
 
 own personality as belonging to the intelligible 
 world." 
 
 § 72. It is worthy of notice that prrsonalittj is 
 here recognized for the first time in 
 
 Personality ^, ,, ,, • , , ,• mi j 
 
 Ht-reRecog- Kant s ethical treatises, ihe pregnant 
 nizedforthe i^^pQ^t of this vecuIiuiH of human nature 
 
 First Time. '■ ^ 
 
 and prime essential of responsibility, 
 seems to have occurred to him late in his researches, 
 especially in its relations to freedom and duty, and 
 to have scarcely unfolded its enormous significance 
 in respect to those ideas and emotions which are dis- 
 tinctively ethical. This late recognition is still 
 more significant, in view of the fact that in all the 
 assumptions and conclusions of the Critique of Pure 
 Reason the Ego is regarded as a very evanescent 
 though potent noumenon, which might possibly be 
 recognized as a " logical" experience capable of ren- 
 dering a questionable though important service in 
 cases of need. No sooner is it once fairly introduced 
 than it expands itself into an abundant and definite 
 import of means and ends, involving some of the most 
 important social relations and pointing toward the 
 most important ethical experiences. Under the ex- 
 citement of this new and thrilling discovery, Kant 
 seems to forget all questionable metaphysics and to
 
 THE CRITIQUE OP PRACTICAL REASON. 147 
 
 break out into other eloquent and elevating pas- 
 sages such as we cannot forbear to cite. 
 
 "On this origin are founded many expressions 
 which designate the worth of objects according to 
 moral ideas. The moral law is hohj (inviolable). 
 Man is indeed unholy enough, but he must regard 
 humanity in his own person as holy. In all creation 
 everything over which one has any power can only be 
 used merely as means; man alone, and with him 
 every rational creature, is an end in himself. By 
 virtue of the autonomy of his freedom he is the sub- 
 ject of the moral law, which is holy. Just for this 
 reason every will, even every person's own indi- 
 vidual will, in relation to itself, is restricted to the 
 condition of agreement with the autonomy of the 
 rational being; that is to say, that it is not to be 
 subject to any purpose which cannot accord with a 
 law which might arise from the will of the imssive 
 subject himself; the latter is, therefore, never to be 
 employed merely as means, but as itself also, concur- 
 rently, an end. We justly attribute this condition 
 even to the Divine Will, with regard to the rational 
 beings in the world, which are His creatures, since 
 it rests on their personality, by which alone they are 
 ends in themselves. 
 
 " This respect-inspiring idea of personality, which
 
 148 Kaxt's ethics. 
 
 sets before our eyes the sublimity of our nature (in 
 its higher aspect), while at the same time it shows 
 us the want of accord of our conduct with it, and 
 thereby strikes down self-conceit, is even natural to 
 the commonest reason, and easily observed. Has not 
 every even moderatelj' honorable man sometimes 
 found that where by an otherwise inoffensive lie he 
 might either have withdrawn himself from an un- 
 pleasant business, or even have procured some ad- 
 vantages for a loved and well-deserving friend, he 
 has avoided it solely lest he should despise himself 
 secretly in his own eyes?" 
 
 § 72. In the Analysis of Pure Practical Reason, 
 
 the writer raises the inquiry why it must 
 
 the Practical have this and no other systematic form, 
 
 a sinX^ '^''"''' ^^^^" compared with the speculative sys- 
 
 Systematic tem, which is founded on a similar faculty 
 
 Form Only. 
 
 of knowledge. Both kinds of reason are 
 alike in that both are pure, or a priori. They differ 
 in that in the theoretic we begin with the intuitions, 
 i.e., with the sensibility, and. proceeding to concepts, 
 end with principles. The practical reason begins 
 with doing, instead of with knowing, i.e., with a will 
 which is a causality, and therefore assumes practical 
 principles a priori, and out of these it constructs its
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. 149 
 
 concepts, i.e., beginning with principles, it ends with 
 concepts.* 
 
 § 73. In further support of the contrast which 
 Kant observes between the Sciences of Appeal to the 
 
 Truth and of Duty, he appeals to the ^'niver.ai 
 ^ '^'- Conscious- 
 
 universal consciousness of man, to decide "^ss 
 
 whether it does not recognize the moral law as alto- 
 gether a priori, and whether its authority is not 
 characterized by a peculiar kind of sentiment which 
 always follows, but never precedes, the regulation 
 of the practical reason. He is careful to remind 
 us, however, that we do not, for this reason, re- 
 nounce all claim to happiness on the simple author- 
 ity of duty, nor do we altogether take no account of 
 happiness. On the other hand, he urges that it is 
 our duty to provide for our happiness for other 
 
 * We notice here that the dissentients from Kant would say, that 
 theoretic and practical knowledge are alike In beginning with proposi- 
 tions and ending with concepts, although some of these principles, in 
 both, are a priori and others a posteriori. They would also contend 
 that the materials of the two differ in that, in the one case, they are 
 facts of sense and facts or phenomena of spirit as controlled by fixed 
 laws, while in the other they are activities of spirit as controlled by the 
 will. These dissimilar phenomena, moreover, indicate laws and pur- 
 poses which justify scientific indications, on the one hand, of physical 
 or permanent laws in the realms of both matter and spirit, and which 
 also suppose moral laws, on the other, so far as freedom and knowl- 
 edge make these possible. As against Kant, we contend that the differ- 
 ence between the operations of pure and practical reason lies in the 
 difference in material in the two cases, and not, as Kant contends, in 
 a difference in the method or logic appropriate to each.
 
 150 KANT^S ETHICS. 
 
 reasons than those of conscience, but it is never our 
 duty to be happy as such, or to obey any law of 
 duty in view of its known relation to our well- 
 being. 
 
 He also adds: The possibility of this ethical 
 knowledge cannot be demonstrated a priori. All 
 that we can do is to show that it cannot be shown to 
 be inconsistent with empirical knowledge. He em- 
 phasizes the fact that there are those who explain 
 freedom on empirical principles, and treat freedom 
 as a psychological fact, attested by an inspection of 
 the soul and its phenomena, and not as a transcen- 
 dental predicate of an agent operating in the world 
 of sense; but he objects that they thereby deprive the 
 soul of all knowledge of a supersensible, i.e., of a 
 noumenal world. 
 
 From all these difficulties Kant would deliver us, 
 as we have seen, by the, to him, familiar distinction 
 between things in themselves and phenomena in 
 time, although he contends at the same time that that 
 which is transcendently free can also produce sensi- 
 ble effects in the world of sense, under the relations 
 of time, and after laws of physical causation. 
 
 § 74. Others, he urges, would relieve us from this 
 difficulty by distinguishing the causes that are con- 
 cerned, calling the one mechanical and the other
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASOK. 151 
 
 spiritual or psychical. Mechanism, he replies, does 
 not designate the nature of the material _ ^ 
 
 ° Difference 
 
 which operates, but the laws of its work- between 
 
 Physical and 
 
 ing. An automaton is an automaton, p><ychicai 
 whether it is material or spiritual in its 
 structure. Moreover, we should remember that, so 
 far as consciousness decides, it attests that so far as 
 the relations of time and the senses are concerned, 
 we are under the law of necessity; but so far as we 
 are conscious of ourselves as noumena., or things, itt 
 themselves, we are certain that we are free. He 
 adds, what a man is in himself is his character — 
 that permanent something to which he imputes his 
 several acts — and with this distinction all the phe- 
 nomena of common life are in complete harmonj^ 
 
 "It may, therefore, be admitted that if it were 
 possible to have so profound an insight into a man's 
 mental character, as shown by internal as well as 
 external actions, as to know all its motives, even the 
 smallest, and likewise all the external occasions that 
 can influence them, we could calculate a man's con- 
 duct for the future with as complete certainty as a 
 lunar or solar eclipse; and nevertheless, we may 
 maintain that the man is free. In fact, if we were 
 capable of a further glance, namely, an intellectual 
 intuition of the same subject (which, indeed, is not
 
 152 rant's ethics. 
 
 granted to us, and instead of it we have only the 
 rational concept) then we should perceive that this 
 whole chain of appearances in regard to all that 
 concerns the moral law depends on the spontaneity 
 of the subject as a thing in itself, of the determina- 
 tion of which no physical explanation can be given. 
 In default of this intuition, the moral law assures 
 us of this distinction between the relation of our ac- 
 tions, as appearances to our sensitive nature, and the 
 relation of this sensitive nature to the supersensible 
 substratum in us. In this view, which is natural to 
 our reason, though inexplicable, we can also justify 
 some judgments which we passed with all conscien- 
 tiousness, and which yet, at first sight, seem quite 
 opposed to all equity. There are cases in which 
 men, even with the same education which has been 
 profitable to others, yet show such early depravity, 
 and so continue to progress in it to years of man- 
 hood, that they are thought to be born villains, and 
 their character altogether incapable of improvement; 
 and nevertheless they are judged for what they do 
 or leave undone, they are reproached for their faults 
 as guilty, nay, they themselves (the children) regard 
 these reproaches as well founded, exactly as if, in 
 spite of the hopeless natural quality of mind 
 ascribed to them, they remained just as responsible
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. 153 
 
 as any other man. This could not happen if we did 
 not suppose that whatever springs from a man's 
 choice (as every action intentionally performed un- 
 doubtedly does) has as its foundation a free caus- 
 ality, which from early youth expresses its char- 
 acter in its manifestations, i.e., outward actions. 
 These, on account of the uniformity of conduct, 
 exhibit a natural connection, which, however, does 
 not make the vicious quality of the will necessary; 
 but, on the contrary, is the consequence of the evil 
 principles, voluntarily adopted and unchangeable, 
 which only make it so much the more culpable and 
 deserving of punishment." 
 
 Here, however, another difficulty is interposed, 
 unless it is escaped by the theory of the author that 
 time and space are not realities, but are only forms 
 of sense. If they were realities and man were created 
 with a sense-organization conformed to them as such, 
 then all his acts in time and space would be the neces- 
 sary effects of his nature as adapted to this environ- 
 ment, even if we should accord to him as a nou- 
 menon moral freedom, inasmuch as in such a case 
 his acts would be the necessary products of his cir- 
 cumstances. 
 
 § 75. From this difficulty we can deliver our- 
 selves by supposing that man is created as a noume-
 
 154 KANT*S ETHtCS. 
 
 non. and with no real relations to time and space, 
 „ , ,. , if indeed neither time nor space has any 
 
 Relations of '■ •' 
 
 Man the reality, both being simply forms of sense. 
 
 Noiimenon 
 
 It) Time and Hence his responsibility can not extend 
 pace. ^^ j^._^ ^^^^ ^^ related to either. This 
 
 solution of a serious diflficulty. Kant urges, not 
 only relieves us from the direct presence of a per- 
 plexing dilemma, but indirectly confirms our faith in 
 the original assumption, which was made in the 
 Critique of Speculative Reason, that space and time 
 are only forms of sense, but are not realities or 
 things in themselves. This relief is confirmed by a 
 direct appeal to the practical reason and the testi- 
 mony which it gives, that man is only responsible for 
 what he is in himself, by his free and spiritual activ- 
 ity, and so far is independent of his Creator. 
 
 Another incidental argument in support of the 
 Dynamical view that freedom is not inconsistent 
 audMathe- ^^-^j^ ^j^^ doctrine of the categories is 
 
 matical ° 
 
 Categories. this: That while the mathematical cate- 
 gories are simply analytic, asserting nothing in the 
 predicate which is not contained in the subject, the 
 dynamical are synthetic and in their very nature 
 introduce new matter. This allows us to suppose 
 the unconditioned to come in and interact with or to 
 act upon the conditioned, and produce new effects,
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PKACTICAL REASON. 155 
 
 and to connect together two kinds of causality, the 
 tixed and the free. This indirect confirmation of his 
 doctrine of the categories is welcomed by Kant with 
 the following interesting comment: 
 
 " Let me be permitted on this occasion to make 
 one more remark, namely, that every step that we 
 make with pure reason, even in the practical sphere 
 where no attention is paid to subtile speculation, 
 nevertheless accords with all the material points of 
 the Critique of the Theoretical Reason as closely and 
 directly as if each step had been thought out with 
 deliberate purpose to establish this confirmation. 
 Such a thorough agreement, wholly unsought for, 
 and quite obvious (as anyone can convince himself, 
 if he will only carry moral inquiries up to their 
 principles), between the most important propositions 
 of practical reason and the often seemingly too sub- 
 tile and needless remarks found in the Critique of 
 the Speculative Reason occasions surprise and aston- 
 ishment, and confirms the maxim already recognized 
 and praised by others: namely, that in every scien- 
 tific inquiry we should pursue our way steadily with 
 all possible exactness and frankness without caring 
 for any objections that may be raised from outside 
 its sphere, but as far as we can, should carr3' out our 
 inquiry truthfully and completely by itself. Fre-
 
 156 kant's ethics. 
 
 quent observation has convinced me that when such 
 researches are concluded, that which in one part of 
 them appeared to me very questionable, considered 
 in relation to other extraneous doctrines, when I left 
 this doubtfulness out of sight for a time, and only 
 attended to the business in hand until it was com- 
 pleted, at last was unexpectedly found to agree per- 
 fectly with what had been discovered separately 
 without the least regard to those doctrines, and 
 without any partiality or prejudice for them. Au- 
 thors would save themselves many errors and much 
 labor lost (because spent on a delusion) if they could 
 only resolve to go to work with more frankness." 
 § 76. From the Analytic of Pure Practical Rea- 
 son, Kant proceeds to its Dialectic, that 
 
 The Dialectic ^ 
 
 of thePracti- is, to the explanation and removal of the 
 illusions which necessarily pertain to our 
 inquiries. These illusions, according to Kant, are 
 incidental to their anal3'ses, as to those of the specu- 
 lative reason, and for a similar reason, viz.: that 
 neither the practical nor the speculative can pene- 
 trate to the knowledge of things in themselves, and 
 yet both are prone to mistake the knowledge of the 
 sum of the conditions of phenomena for the properly 
 unconditioned. The only relief we can find is b}^ the 
 discovery of the grounds of each, and the fact that we
 
 THE CKITIQL'E OF PRACTICAL REASON. 157 
 
 mistake the one for the other. Under this misleading 
 tendency in ethics men have substituted the gratifi- 
 cation of the inclinations, under the title of the sum- 
 niiim boiniin, for that which is good in itself as given 
 b}^ the practical reason. We have already seen that 
 the moral law is the sole determining principle of 
 the will, as law, not as good, simply from its form or 
 fitness to serve as a universal principle. The siwi,- 
 Duon hoinnii may be, in fact, involved in it, but the 
 moral law is to be obeyed as law, and not to be 
 sought as good. Otherwise we introduce heter- 
 onomy into the will. 80 if the SKniniidii hoiuon in- 
 cluded the moral law as conditional to itself, then 
 the good, and not the law, would give it force over 
 the will. How then shall Ave rightly conceive and 
 define the two in their mutual relations? This is 
 attempted in Chapter II, in which Kant first re- 
 marks that sumtnum may mean supreme, i.e., ulti- 
 mate, or complete, i.e., entire. The first is depen- 
 dent on no other ; the second is wanting in nothing. 
 Virtue has been already shown to be Avorthy of hap- 
 piness, and in this sense it is not happiness, nor does 
 it involve happiness, but only desert of the same, 
 virtue being the condition of happiness, but still 
 happiness as dependent on virtue. The one is not 
 identical with the other through an analvtical con-
 
 158 kant's ethics. 
 
 nection, neither as the Epicureans nor as the Stoics 
 connected the two, but virtue must first exist, by the 
 free activity of . the will, in order that happiness 
 should either be discerned or enjoyed, and this by an 
 a priori necessity. This involves an antinomy of 
 the practical reason, viz.: (1) either the desire of 
 happiness must be the motive to the maxims of vir- 
 tue, or (2) the maxims of virtue must be the causes 
 of happiness. The first is impossible, Kant would 
 contend, as has been abundantly shown ; the second 
 also, because happiness in this world depends on 
 other knowledge than ethical, and the observance of 
 other laws. The antinomy seems at first insoluble. 
 It is solved, however, by a resort to the always con- 
 venient distinction between things in themselves 
 and phenomena. The first proposition given above, 
 that the desire of happiness produces virtue, is abso- 
 lutel}^ false ; the second is not false absolutely, but 
 only so far as the moral holds relations to the sensi- 
 ble world, that is conditionally; it may. therefore, 
 be true, so far as this sensible world is viewed as 
 controlled by a superior will. 
 
 § 77. But here, again, the author warns his read- 
 Anticipation ers against confounding the influences 
 s f °t-^t which proceed from the anticipated 
 Not Moral. pleasure that follows virtue Avith the
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PKACTICAL KEASON. 159 
 
 legitimate iiiiiuence which the moral law exerts 
 directly on the will. 
 
 "Now the consciousness of a determination of the 
 faculty of desire is always the source of a satisfac- 
 tion in the resulting action ; but this pleasure, this 
 satisfaction in oneself, is not the determining prin- 
 ciple of the action; on the contrary, the determina- 
 tion of the will directly by reason is the source of 
 the feeling of pleasure, and this remains a pure 
 practical, but not a sensible, determination of the 
 faculty of desire. Now, as this determination has 
 exactly the same effect within, in impelling to activ- 
 it}^ that a feeling of the pleasure to be expected 
 from the desired action would have had, we easily 
 look on what we ourselves do as something which 
 we merely passively feel, and take the moral spring 
 for a sensible impulse, just as it happens in the so- 
 called illusion of the senses (in this case in the inner 
 sense). 
 
 "Respect, not pleasure or enjoyment of happiness, 
 is something for which it is not possible that reason 
 should have any a)itecedent feeling as its foundation 
 (for this would always be sensible and pathological); 
 and consciousness of immediate obligation of the 
 will by the law is b}' no means analogous to the 
 feeling of pleasure, although in relation to ik^
 
 160 rant's ethics. 
 
 faculty of desire it produces the same effect, but 
 from different sources. It is only by this mode of 
 conception, however, that we can attain what we 
 are seeking, namely, that actions be done not merely 
 in accordance with duty (as a result of pleasant 
 feelings), but from duty, which must be the true 
 end of all moral cultivation." 
 
 § 78. Will it be believed that immediately on 
 writing these words our critical phi- 
 
 Self -con tent- ° ' 
 
 ment Con- losopher recovers his thoughts and asks: 
 
 ceded to 
 
 be Ethically " Have we not, however, a word which 
 
 Legitimate. j j. • j. i • 
 
 does not express enjoyment, as happiness 
 does, but indicates a satisfaction in ones existence, 
 an analogue of the happiness which must necessarily 
 accompany the consciousness of virtue? Yes! this 
 word is seIf-contentine)it, which in its proper signifi- 
 cation always designates only a negative satisfaction 
 in one's existence, in which one is conscious of need- 
 ing nothing. Freedom, and the consciousness of it, 
 as a faculty of following the moral law with un- 
 yielding resolution, is independent of inclinations, 
 at least as motives determining (though not affect- 
 ing) our desire; and so far as I am conscious of this 
 freedom in following my moral maxims, it is the 
 only source of an unaltered contentment which is 
 necessarily connected with it, and rests on no special
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. 161 
 
 feeling. This may be called intellectual content- 
 ment. The sensible contentment (improperly so 
 called) which rests on the satisfaction of the inclina- 
 tions, however delicate they may be imagined to be, 
 can never be adequate to the conception of it. For 
 the inclinations change; they grow with the indul- 
 gence shown them, and always leave behind a still 
 greater void than we had thought to fill. Hence 
 they are always burdensome to a rational being, and 
 although he cannot lay them aside, they wrest from 
 him the wish to be rid of them. Even an inclination 
 to what is right {e.g., to beneficence), though it may 
 much facilitate the efficacy of the moral maxims, 
 cannot produce any. For in these all must be 
 directed to the conception of the law as a determined 
 principle, if the action is to contain morality, and 
 not merely legality. 
 
 " Freedom itself becomes in this way (namely, 
 indirectly) capable of an enjoyment which cannot 
 be called happiness, because it does not depend on 
 the positive concurrence of a feeling, nor is it, strictly 
 speaking, hliss. since it does not include complete 
 independence on inclinations and wants; but it re- 
 sembles bliss in so far as the determination of one"s 
 will, at least, can hold itself free from their influ- 
 ence; and thus, at least in its origin, this enjoyment 
 11
 
 162 kant's ethics, 
 
 is analogous to the self-sufl&ciency which we can 
 ascribe only to the Supi-eme Being." 
 
 § 79. Chapter III. opens a topic of marvellous in- 
 The Primacy terest, viz.: the primacy of pure practical 
 Practical reason in its union with the speculative 
 
 above tiie reason. The brief remarks which the au- 
 
 Speculative 
 
 Reason. thor offers are admirable for their practi- 
 
 cal good sense, however unsatisfactory some of them 
 may seem for the want of scientific exactness. We 
 accept with thanks what he says in the following, when 
 it is popularly or practically interpreted: "But if 
 pure reason of itself can be practical, and is actually 
 so, as the consciousness of the moral law proves, then 
 still it is only one and the same reason which, whether 
 in a theoretical or a practical point of view, judges 
 according to a priori principles; and then it is clear 
 that although it is in the first point of view incom- 
 petent to establish certain propositions positively, 
 which, however, do not contradict it, then as soon as 
 these propositions are inseparably attached to the 
 practical interest of pure reason, it must accept 
 them, though it be as something offered to it from a 
 foreign source, something that has not grown on its 
 own ground, but yet is sufficiently authenticated; 
 and it must try to compare and connect them with 
 everything that it has in its power as speculative
 
 THE CRITIQUE OP PRACTICAL REASON. 163 
 
 reason. It must remember, however, that these are 
 not additions to its insight, but yet are extensions of 
 its employment in anothei", namely a practical 
 aspect; and this is not in the least opposed to its 
 interest, which consists in the restriction of wild 
 speculation. 
 
 " Thus, when pure speculative and pure practical 
 reason are combined in one cognition, the latter has 
 the primacy, provided, namely, that this combination 
 is not contingent and arbitrary, but founded a priori 
 on reason itself, and therefore necessary." 
 
 § 80. The practical wisdom and the catholic lib- 
 erality of these views are obvious to any 
 
 How Far 
 
 candid mind. The only question which Have the Two 
 they might suggest would be in what ^^^°'J'°'°° 
 respects the practical reason differs from 
 the speculative, and wherein they spring from a 
 common root of a priori truths. If they are so 
 nearly akin as to be in substance the same, how can 
 it be that the categorical principles of the two are 
 held by Kant to differ so widely, and by what au- 
 thority does the practical reason supplement the 
 speculative in so many important particulars? As 
 Kant appeals to the authority of the practical rea- 
 son as supreme in the chapters which follow, we are 
 tempted to ask whether the speculative does not in
 
 164 K ant's ethics. 
 
 fact play as important a role as the practical in sup- 
 port of the vital truths which he proceeds, in the 
 next chapter, to present in order as " Postulates of 
 the Pure Practical Reason." 
 
 § 81. IV. The first of these is the immortality 
 Argument for of ^^^^ soul. Kaut's argument that this 
 Immortality, j^ demanded by the " practical reason " is 
 as follows. A will controlled by the moral law will 
 of necessity require the realization of the sunimum 
 bonum. But in such a will there must be the com- 
 plete accordance of the feelings {dispositions, Gesinn- 
 ungeii) with the moral law. This must be practicable, 
 or it would not be required. But such a perfection 
 is holiness, of which no rational being in the condi- 
 tions of sense-existence is capable. It can be found 
 only in his pi'ogress ad Injinitum toward this ideal. 
 But this progress involves actual immortality, or an 
 endless duration of the existence and personality of 
 the rational being who is the subject of the law of 
 duty; the sit 1)1 nuoH bonum required by the moral law 
 being attainable only on condition of the soul's actual 
 experience of an endlessly continued, i.e., an immor- 
 tal existence, or rather a long-continued existence 
 which has no raison d'etre after moral perfection has 
 been attained and the service of duty has been 
 exchanged for the raptures of holy love.
 
 thp: ckitique of practical reason. I(i5 
 
 This argument needs only a brief comment. It 
 assumes that whatever is demanded by the moral 
 law will in every case be realized, i.e., that all moral 
 ideals must sooner or later be fulfilled in fact or 
 tendency. The assumption is set aside by the plain 
 fact of experience that these ideals in many cases 
 are not made good. The underlying principle can- 
 not be accepted as a postulate which admits of no 
 exception, and if the postulate fails, the conclusion 
 derived from it must fail also. 
 
 What gives plausibility to the argument is the 
 appeal to purpose or final cause, which may be sup- 
 posed to underlie this verbal argument of Kant. 
 Thus interpreted, the argument would be as follows: 
 Perfect holiness, in some moral beings, at least, 
 must be the final issue of the system of moral 
 influences by which men are disciplined. Such holi- 
 ness, it may be conceded, requires for its consum- 
 mation a long-continued, i.e., a practically endless 
 existence. Therefore, in this sense, and by this 
 logic, the conscience, or moral reason, demands and 
 insures an immortal existence to some moral beings, 
 and perhaps to all. 
 
 § 82. Admitting that this argument, stated in 
 this form, is valid, it should be observed that it rests 
 solely on the relation of purpose or final cause.
 
 166 kaxt's ethics. 
 
 which is a category of the pure reason, if of either ; 
 and derives all its logical or rational force 
 
 This Argil- ° 
 
 ment Assumes from a relation which Kant's practical 
 
 Design as 
 
 Objectively rsason does not recognize, viz.: the re- 
 lation of adaptation. The subject-matter 
 of the argument is ethical, indeed, but the logic 
 is altogether speculative. The necessity of ap- 
 pealing to the practical reason for a logic which the 
 speculative reason fails to present, is so far from 
 being made good that, on the other hand, the val- 
 idity of speculative logic with its rational categories 
 is made more conspicuous by the very argument 
 which is introduced in its place from the sol-disant 
 practical reason alone. Moreover, the grand con- 
 summation which both these ponderous Critiques 
 were constructed to achieve, viz. : that the categories 
 of the speculative reason are failures except so far as 
 the}' are enforced by the practical reason, is brought 
 to nothing by the very argument for immortality, 
 with which this latter would triumphantly reinfoi'ce 
 our philosophy and our faith. 
 
 § 83. Kant's argument for the existence of God 
 from the practical reason is closely allied 
 
 Argument 
 
 for God's to his argument for man's immortality. 
 The moral reason commands man to real- 
 ize the first element of the summurn boinon, i.e.,
 
 THE CRITIQUE OP PRACTICAL REASON. 167 
 
 moral perfection, or, as Kant terms it, holiness, in 
 the sense of a cheerful and loving acquiescence in 
 the law of duty. But such holiness is only possible 
 on the supposition of the continued, i.e., the im- 
 mortal, existence of the human sou). It follows that 
 if man is a moral, he must be an immortal being. 
 But the same moral law, in its demand of the reali- 
 zation of the summum bonum as a duty, also requires 
 that the moral being, so far as he is sentient, should 
 be made happy, not on the ground that the con- 
 ception of holiness includes in its contents any rela- 
 tion whatever to sentient enjoyment, but on the 
 ground that moral goodness in its very essence or 
 nature involves desert of sentient good, i.e., worthi- 
 ness to be happy. This, according to Kant, is the 
 second or completing half of the conception which is 
 enforced by its demand. 
 
 This being assumed, he proceeds to reason thus: 
 The moral law% in demanding this of the moral will 
 — this desert of happiness — assumes the possibility 
 that this desideratum should be realized. But this 
 implies that a being exists who is both able and dis- 
 posed to reward the good; i.e., it implies the exist- 
 ence of God. " It was seen to be a duty for us to 
 promote the summum bonum, consequently it is not 
 merely allowable, but it is a necessity connected
 
 168 kant's ethics. 
 
 with duty as a requisite that we should presuppose 
 the possibility of this f^innmum honum, and as this is 
 possible only on condition of the existence of God, it 
 inseparably connects the supposition of this with 
 duty, that is, it is morally necessary to assume the 
 existence of God."' That we should presuppose this 
 possibility. Kant reasons, follows from the obligation 
 to promote the sum mum honum in its double form of 
 moral and natural good, but the realization of this 
 possibility seems also to require that we suppose 
 a supreme intelligence. As a principle of ex- 
 planation for the speculative reason, this may be 
 called a hypothesis, but when viewed in the light 
 of the moral significance of the imperative of the 
 moral law, it may be called faith. 
 
 § 84. In this argument, if it can be called an 
 
 Difference argument, Kant overlooks the obvious 
 
 etween distinction between the proposition that 
 
 Rational and ^ ^ 
 
 Moral Ends, the universe is controlled and, so to 
 speak, administered by an intelligent being for 
 rational ends, and the truth that he administers it 
 for moral ends, and is, therefore, a moral being, as 
 is I'equired by our faith in duty, and our rational 
 inferences from this faith. We cannot forget that, 
 in the Critique of the Pure Reason he had criticised 
 the principal speculative arguments for the existence
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. 169 
 
 of God, and had found in them all, the common 
 weakness that, in his view, pertains to all the specu- 
 lative relations of the unconditioned, whether viewed 
 in idea or in fact. In the Critique of the Practical 
 Reason he had proposed to supply this defect, and to 
 furnish the materials and to explain the processes 
 which through our moral faith should establish God 
 to our speculative reason, and thus supplement all 
 the defects and JactDue which the latter was so quick 
 to discover, but so impotent to supplement or to 
 overcome. How does he succeed in these promises, 
 long deferred and stoutly maintained? We are 
 compelled to say that the import of the promise 
 seems almost to have been forgotten, in the seeming 
 effort to fulfil it. All that Kant even attempts to 
 prove is, that the moral law, in imposing or assert- 
 ing the truth that moral goodness deserves to be 
 rewarded, requires for this end a moral being who 
 is able and willing to effect its behests. As if there 
 were no difference between what ought to be and 
 what actually is, and as though the moral law, as 
 ideal and mandatory, were not conspicuous in en- 
 forcing this distinction. Meanwhile, the point is 
 certainly overlooked, that the apparent force of the 
 argument is derived from the assumption that there 
 is a rational and almighty Intelligence behind the
 
 170 KANTS ETHICS. 
 
 sensible universe, in respect to whom, provided we 
 
 are assured that He exists, it may be argued that He 
 
 is moral, and will enforce the behests of the moral 
 
 law. But we have been waiting all this while under 
 
 the questioning, not to say the sceptical, suggestions 
 
 of the first Critique, to know whether we may trust 
 
 our speculative reason confidently enough to know 
 
 whether God actually exists. Meanwhile, we have 
 
 been told that the practical reason would remove 
 
 and settle all these questionings. It is somewhat 
 
 tantalizing, after all this delay, to be informed that 
 
 all that it can do for us is to make it clear that if 
 
 there is a God, "He is a rewarder of those who 
 
 diligently seek Him"; but that all we can know of 
 
 God, in fact, is included in certain moral necessities 
 
 of man, and whatsoever these may imply. 
 
 § 85. Our philosopher is not content with leaving 
 
 this topic here. He seems to be fully 
 New ^ ; 
 
 Argument aware that he has not entirely cleared it 
 up to the satisfaction of his readers, and 
 perhaps not completely to his own. After a few 
 remarks in respect to the teachings of the ancient 
 religions, and particularly the Christian, he seeks to 
 make his views more clear in respect to the postu- 
 lates of pure practical reason in general, viz.: im- 
 mortality, freedom, and God. The first, as has
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PIIACTICAL REASOX. 171 
 
 already been explained, is derived from the duty 
 enjoined completely to fulfil the moral law, or to 
 attain that holiness which can only be achieved by a 
 continued and practically endless future existence. 
 The second, freedom, is implied in that practical in- 
 dependence of all motives of sense which is involved 
 in obeying a rational law. The third, the existence 
 of God, is implied in the realization of the summam 
 honum by the sole agency which is conceivable as 
 adequate to its achievement — that of the Supreme. 
 These ethical postulates of the practical reason lead 
 to inferences which the speculative reason necessarily 
 proposes to itself, but cannot solve. Should it 
 attempt to do either, it must fall into paralogisms, 
 and therefore it must content itself with knowing of 
 each that there is a something ethically related to 
 the moral nature, or law and destiny of man, of 
 which it knows that its moral needs require so much 
 and nothing more. 
 
 " Is our knowledge, however, actually extended in 
 this way by pure practical reason, and is that itniiid- 
 nent in practical reason, which for the speculative 
 was only transcendent? Certainly, but only m a 
 practical point of view. For we do not thereby take 
 knowledge of the nature of our souls, nor of the 
 intelligible world, nor of the Supreme Being, with
 
 172 rant's ethics. 
 
 respect to what they are in themselves; but we have 
 merely combined the conceptions of them in the 
 practical concept of the sitDDHHin honum as the object 
 of our will, and this altogether a priori., but only 
 by means of the moral law, and merely in I'eference 
 to it, in respect of the object which it commands. 
 But how freedom is possible, and how we are to 
 conceive this kind of causality theoretically and 
 positively, is not thereby discovered; but only that 
 such a causality is postulated by the moral law and 
 in its behoof. It is the same with the remaining 
 ideas, the possibility of which no human intelligence 
 will ever fathom, but the truth of which, on the 
 other hand, no sophistry will ever wrest from the 
 conviction even of the commonest man." 
 
 § 86. This attempt at explanation suggests to 
 Can the ^^^^ critic himself'the following pertinent 
 
 Practical be inquirv (VII): '" How is it possible to 
 
 Independent 
 
 oftheSpecu- couceive an extension of pure reason in 
 
 lative Reason? ,• i • l f • ^ 
 
 a practical point oi view, unless its 
 speculative knowledge is also at the same time en- 
 larged? '" This question he answei*s as follows: The 
 warrant for practically extending a pure cognition 
 must be furnished by some purpose or end enforced 
 on the will by the categorical imperative. " Thus, 
 by the practical law, which commands the existence
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. 173 
 
 of the highest good possible in a world, the possi- 
 bilit}^ of those objects of pure speculative reason is 
 postulated and the objective reality which the latter 
 could not assure them." That is, the theoretical 
 knowledge is enlarged, but only so far as the practi- 
 cal necessities require. But this extension gives no 
 warrant for making any theoretical use of the same. 
 Nothing i? gained except that these concepts exist 
 and have their possible objects. These three ideas 
 are in themselves not cognitions of fact, but they are 
 concepts in which there is nothing impossible. 
 Being necessary conditions of objects that are mor- 
 ally imperative, they become real without our know- 
 ing how they are intellectually or rationally related 
 to our conception of them. In a word, we know that 
 they are, but do not know what they are in any real 
 sense so that we can define them completely or 
 derive from them any other than certain limited 
 practical inferences. To the speculative reason they 
 are transcendent and I'egulative only. When the 
 categories are to be applied to these ideas, it is not 
 possible to find any existing objects for them by in- 
 tuition, but only for the concepts which are involved 
 in the siiniinuin hoiiiint which the practical reason 
 requires. It will be observed that the limitations 
 enforced upon the speculative reason are not limita-
 
 174 K A NT's ETHICS. 
 
 tions in the number of the relations or properties 
 affirmed, but in the kind of those which can possibly 
 be asserted of them. Were the first true, the defect 
 of ethical concepts would be a defect of degree only; 
 whereas the defect is owing to the nature of the 
 subject-matter, which refuses to be classed with the 
 relations or methods that belong to any objects which 
 are subjected to the forms or intuitions of space or 
 time. 
 
 § 87. The requirement or ground of belief in 
 ^,.^ each of these cases is peculiar (VIII), 
 
 Diflfereiice ' ^ ' 
 
 between a "A want or requirement of pure reason 
 
 Hypothesis 
 
 and a in its Speculative use leads only to a 
 
 hypothesis, that of pure practical reason 
 to a postulate.'''' In the one case I suppose or find a 
 set of facts which I explain to my reason. In the 
 other, I find a duty, the possibility of which requires 
 certain conditions, as God, freedom, and immortality. 
 The duty is independent of these conditions, but the 
 disposition to perforin it presupposes that its perfect 
 realization is possible, as a fact, with all that this 
 realization implies. 
 
 It would seem at first that this doctrine implies 
 that a rational faith is in so far a matter of com- 
 mand. Let it be observed, then, that the first ele- 
 ment, duty as duty, is the subject of a command, but
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON. 175 
 
 only while the second, the possibility of the realiza- 
 tion of the happiness which duty merits, is a ques- 
 tion in respect to which a doubt is possible. The 
 mind which is rightly disposed will accept but one 
 conclusion. This faith " may at times waver in the 
 well disposed, but can never be reduced to unbelief." 
 § 88. If this is the conclusion which Kant reaches, 
 it would seem to lower our faith in these 
 
 Kant's Argu- 
 
 three supreme conditions of the suminnm ment Reduced 
 honum to a simple hypothesis which is 
 highly probable because it is enforced by our noblest 
 aspirations. As against this objection, Kant care- 
 fully defines the limitations of our cognitive faculties, 
 both speculative and practical, which are taught in his 
 speculative and practical treatises. This exposition 
 is given in the concluding Chapter IX. under the 
 title, " Of the Wise Adaptation of Man's Cognitive 
 Faculties to his Practical Destination," and consists 
 of the following suggestions: Were our capacities 
 for speculative and practical knowledge less limited 
 than they are, could we completely understand the 
 nature of things by our speculative and practical 
 reason, including God and all his relations to nat- 
 ure and to man; we should live and act in the con- 
 stant and living presence of these astounding and 
 comprehended truths. It may be supposed that in
 
 176 rant's ethics. 
 
 such a case we should necessarily and constantly 
 conform our characters and conduct to these over- 
 whelming realities. But such a conformity would be 
 mechanical, necessary, perhaps interested and selfish, 
 and at the best it would fail of that nol^le and disin- 
 terested virtue which the present limitations of our 
 knowledge render possible and even necessary. We 
 conclude, then, that for the purposes of moral disci- 
 pline and culture these limitations are wisely adapted 
 to man's true well-being, and in this wise adaptation 
 we find an additional evidence that our theory is 
 true. 
 
 § 89. The second and concluding part of this 
 Critique is entitled "The Methodology of 
 
 Methodology 
 
 ofthePrac- Pure Practical Reason," and is a brief 
 treatise on the best practical methods by 
 which the practical reason may be instructed and 
 trained. In it the author reiterates in a practical 
 form the doctrines of his treatise, that morality 
 must be disinterested and self-centred, authoritative 
 and unselfish, and that whether it can be success- 
 fully imparted will depend largely on the method by 
 which it is inculcated and exemplified by teachers 
 and writers, by parents and guai-dians. In this dis- 
 cussion he presses very hard upon sentimental and 
 selfish moralists because, in his opinion, they use flat-
 
 THE CRITK^UE OF PKACTICAL REASON. 177 
 
 tery and employ mercenary appliances, and fail to 
 set forth duty in its majestic and self-asserting 
 authority, and to invest it with its simple dignity and 
 grace. 
 
 The discussion ends with the following celebrated 
 and oft-quoted meditation: 
 
 "Two things fill the mind with ever new and 
 increasing admiration and awe, the oft- The starry 
 ener and the more steadily we reflect on ^J*!f"'' 
 
 •' and the 
 
 them : the starry heavens above and the Moral Law. 
 moral law within.* I have not to search for them 
 and conjecture them as though they were veiled in 
 darkness, or were in the transcendent region beyond 
 my horizon. I see them before me, and connect 
 them directly with the consciousness of my exist- 
 ence. The former begins from the place I occupy in 
 the external world of sense, and enlarges my con- 
 nection therein to an unbounded extent with worlds 
 
 * It is possible that Wordsworth's Ode to Duty may have been 
 inspired by these thoughts, particularly the following: 
 "Stern Lawgiver! yet thou dost wear 
 
 The Godhead's most benignant grace; 
 
 Nor know we anything so fair 
 
 As is the smile upon thy face. 
 
 Flowers laugh before thee on their beds, 
 
 And fragrance in thy footing treads; 
 
 Thou dost preserve the stars from wrong: 
 
 And the most ancient heavens through thee are fresh and strong." 
 Or, which is still more probable, both may have been unconsciously 
 suggested by Psalm xix, vss. 1, 7, 8. 
 
 13
 
 178 kant's ethics. 
 
 upon worlds and systems of systems, and. moreover, 
 into limitless times of their periodic motion, its be- 
 ginning and continuance. The second begins from 
 my invisible self, my personality, and exhibits me in 
 a world which has true infinit}', but which is trace- 
 able only by the understanding, and with which I 
 discei'n that I am not in a merely contingent, but in 
 a universal and necessary connection, as T am also 
 thereby with all those visible worlds. The former 
 view of a countless multitude of worlds anni- 
 hilates, as it were, my importance as an animal 
 creature, which, after it has been for a short time 
 provided with vital power, one knows not how, must 
 again give back the matter of which it was formed 
 to the planet it inhabits (a mei-e speck in the uni- 
 verse). The second, on the contrary, infinitely ele- 
 vates my worth as an intelligence by my personality, 
 in which the moral law reveals to me a life inde- 
 pendent on animality, and even on the whole sensi- 
 ble world, at least so far as may be inferred from 
 the destination assigned to my existence by this law, 
 a destination not restricted to conditions and limits 
 of this life, but reaching into the infinite. 
 
 " But though admiration and respect may excite to 
 inquiry, they cannot supply the want of it. What, 
 then, is to be done in order to enter on this in a
 
 THE CRITIQUE OP I>RACTlCAL KEASOK. 179 
 
 useful manner, and one adapted to tlie loftiness of 
 the subject? Examples may serve in this as a warn- 
 ing, and also for imitation. The contemplation of 
 the world began from the noblest spectacle that the 
 luiman senses present to us, and that our under- 
 standing can bear to follow in their vast reach, and 
 it ended in — astrology. Morality began with the 
 noblest attribute of human nature, the development 
 and cultivation of which give a prospect of infinite 
 utility, and ended in — fanaticism or superstition." 
 
 § 90. The answer which we should give to this 
 pregnant inquiry of Kant is the exact practical 
 opposite of the conclusion which he de- g^prem^g^and 
 rives from the critique to which he has if'olated. 
 subjected the practical reason. We should say that 
 ethical phenomena and laws are as truly the subjects 
 of scientific investigation as those which are physical. 
 Misdirected agencies and imaginative theories in both 
 lead to mischief of every species. It is only as we 
 understand the nature of the subject-matter of both 
 that we can adopt a true method for either. With 
 this interpretation we should heartily adopt his 
 parting words: "In one word, science (critically 
 undertaken and methodically directed) is the nar- 
 row gate that leads to the true doctrine of prac- 
 tical wisdom, if we understand by this not merely
 
 180 KANT^S ETHICS. 
 
 what one ought to do, but what ought to serve 
 teachers as a guide to construct well and clearly 
 the road to wisdom which everyone should travel, 
 and to secure others from going astray. Philoso- 
 phy must always continue to be the guardian of this 
 science, and although the public does not take any 
 interest in its subtle investigations, it must in the 
 resulting doctrines which such an examination first 
 puts in a clear light." 
 
 § 91. This rhapsodical conclusion of this elaborate 
 Critique reminds the reader of the title 
 
 Comments 
 
 on the of the last chapter of Dr. Johnson's 
 
 Rasselas, viz. : " The Conclusion in Which 
 Nothing is Concluded." The imaginative meditation 
 of the eloquent writer upon the starry heavens and 
 the law of duty is both impressive and elevating; but 
 the vague replies to our most serious questionings 
 with which it puts us off, and its indefinite resolu- 
 tion of our philosophic doubts, only serve to aggra- 
 vate the keenness of our disappointment. The first 
 of these treatises which we have reviewed, the 
 Grrundlegung, had professed only to prepare our 
 way for moi'e exact analyses and more scientific 
 inquiries. It left us with the equivocal consolation 
 of being at least made fully acquainted with the 
 reasons why the ultimate concepts and axioms of
 
 THE CRITK^LK OF PRACTICAL REASON. 181 
 
 ethical science must in some sense be ultimate and 
 incomprehensible. But notwithstanding this dis- 
 couraging intimation, we were encouraged to hope 
 that the Critique of the Practical Reason might not 
 only clear up the incomprehensibilities into which 
 the earlier ethical treatise had plunged us, but that it 
 might redeem the hope or promise which had cheered 
 us on our thorny path, viz.: that the analysis of the 
 practical reason, in dissipating its own difficulties, 
 would restore our confidence in the decisions of the 
 speculative reason. But, alas I at the end of our toil 
 we are informed that the axioms of ethical faith are 
 rooted only in our own ineradicable conviction of 
 their i^ractical importance, and that they scarcely 
 seem capable of either scientific formulation or phil- 
 osophic adjustment; while the practical reason 
 itself is so far from going farther than this, or 
 from rendering its proifered and promised aid to the 
 speculative, that it can best satisfy its own needs 
 and that of its elder sister by looking up to the 
 heavens in an attitude of wondering worship, and 
 down into the heart of man in reverent faith. We 
 confess ourselves surprised at this conclusion, after 
 the long trial to our patience from the scholastic 
 terminology, the acute criticism, and the sharp in- 
 sight with which these treatises superabound, all of
 
 182 kant\s p:THicft. 
 
 which had prepared us to hope that all these prepa- 
 rations would have given us something more than 
 this effusion of the imagination, truthful and eloquent 
 though it be. 
 
 The conclusion also suggests a thought which, in 
 our opinion, is of no inconsiderable importance as an 
 explanation of the charm with which Kant's original 
 researches continue to be invested, and of their 
 power to excite and hold the minds of men long 
 after the original questions, as Kant proposed them, 
 had taken new forms, and been expressed in new 
 terminology. Kant's extraordinary power to attract 
 and hold his readers seems to lie in that rare combina- 
 tion of metaphysical acuteness with imaginative verve 
 and inspiration, by which he is distinguished. Not 
 unfrequently he seems to lose himself and to bewilder 
 his readers in the entangled maze of his over-refined 
 analyses and his barbarous terminology. On other 
 occasions he sinks in helpless discouragement under 
 the weight of those transcendental ideas which his 
 philosophy is forced to recognize, but is incapable of 
 defining and defending by his own chosen termi- 
 nology. In these extremities, however urgent, his 
 imagination never fails to find language in which to 
 give expression to those faiths which he has the 
 magnanimity to confess are "the light of all our see-
 
 THE CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON". 183 
 
 ing," while his glowing rhetoric lights up the thorn- 
 iest maze of abstract reasoning with a radiance which 
 extorts the wonder of the admiring reader, even when 
 the argument, thus illuminated, fails to commend it- 
 self to his cooler judgment. For this reason, among 
 many others, it seems to us that the watchword. '''Back 
 to Kant,'' will long be repeated and responded to 
 even by those students of philosophy who find no 
 occasion to accept Kant as their master.
 
 CHAPTER IV. 
 
 A CRITICAL SUMMARY OF KANT'S ETHICAL 
 THEORY. 
 
 § 92. AVe begin with Kant's doctrine of the 
 The Practical pfcictical veasoH. The introduction of 
 eabon ^j^j^ appellation by Kant excited wonder 
 
 Described. and Called forth criticism from many 
 quarters. How can there be two sorts of reason, 
 was asked by his critics, and with what propriety 
 can reason be designated as practical at all? In 
 answer to these queries, Kant denied that be held to 
 two kinds of reason, but sought to justify the double 
 application of the term by explaining that it was 
 occasioned by the difterence in the subject-matter* 
 with which reason has to do, and the consequent 
 difference in the relations or attributes which it is 
 supposed to discern. While the speculative reason is 
 concerned with the attributes of fact or truth, the 
 
 *It is pertinent here to ask, however, whether, according to Kant's 
 own analj'sis, oliligation, or the nucleus of the same, must not first be 
 experienced or felt, before It is discerned, i.e., whether some form of 
 sensibility and its relations, rather than the intellect, does not fur- 
 nish the objective material oi moral distinctions, contrarilj' to his 
 entire thcorv. 
 
 184
 
 SUMMARY OF KANT*S ETHICAL THEORY. 185 
 
 practical is limited to attributes of action and of 
 duty; the one affirming what is true and should be 
 assented to, the other what should be done or effected ; 
 the first implying knowledge , and the second obi iff a- 
 tioii. It may be questioned, however, whether the 
 language which he used, and the illustrations and 
 arguments which he employed were not all fitted to 
 leave the impression that the diff"erence was in no wise 
 limited to the objective matter of intellectual assent; 
 but was also extended to the subjective character of 
 the processes by which ethical truth is responded 
 to or obeyed. At all events, it is certain that Kant 
 intended that, as in the phenomena of speculative 
 reason the intellect alone is concerned only with 
 relations of fact or truth, so the practical reason im- 
 plies only relations to the will, and enforces relations 
 of duty. It would follow that the will, being the 
 necessary correlate of the intellect, acting as the 
 practical reason, both logically and actually, might 
 also occasionally be used by Kant interchangeably 
 Avith it — the practical reason discerning and enforc- 
 ing obligation for and upon the will, and the will 
 subjectively responding to this relation in its free- 
 dom under a sense of mere authority. 
 
 § 93. It is also a fundamental truth with Kant, 
 and oft repeated by him, that the authority of its
 
 186 kant\s ethics. 
 
 commands is not derived from the goodness of that 
 Whence Its which is Commanded; but that an act 
 Authority. ^^ morally good because it is commanded 
 by the reason. No action is commanded because it is 
 good, or as being good; but it is good because and 
 in so far as it is enforced by the practical reason, 
 it being first simply commanded and accepted as 
 morally right, and thereby becoming morally good. 
 It is not enforced as morally right, because it is 
 desirable, or excellent, or good; but is good because 
 it is enforced as right by the reason. The sense of 
 obligation, moreover, it should be noticed, in all 
 cases supposes a reluctant, even though it be an 
 obedient will. A being who responds to the judg- 
 ments of the practical reason without a conflict, — 
 showing that his emotional and active nature is 
 already in harmony with the moral law, — has no 
 sense of obligation, however complete his holiness, 
 and the decisions or judgments of the practical 
 reason do not assume for him the power or force of 
 law. Such a man is a holy, but not a virtuous man. 
 § 94. The practical reason of Kant seems at first 
 How Related thought to be identical with the " supe- 
 to Butler s ^.•^^, p^.^j^g^-^jg Qf reflection or conscience " 
 
 Principle or '^ •■ 
 
 Reflection. of Bishop Butler, whose functions are 
 thus defined; it "distinguishes between the internal
 
 SUMMARY OF KANT's ETHICAL THEORY. 187 
 
 principles of his heart''; it "passes judgment upon 
 himself" and other men; it "'pronounces determin- 
 edly some actions to be in themselves just, right, and 
 good," etc., "without being advised with"; it ''un- 
 questionably exerts itself, and approves or condemns 
 him the doer." Butler recognizes in these features 
 " a prerogative or natural supremacy of this moral 
 faculty," or, as he once calls it, "the moral reason," 
 and contends that "we may have a clear conception 
 of the superior nature of our inward principles to one 
 another," and gathers the result of his analysis into 
 the pregnant conclusion that "this is a constituent 
 part of the idea — that is, of the faculty itself — and 
 to preside and govern from the very economy and 
 constitution of man, belongs to it. Had it strength 
 as it has right, had it power as it has manifest 
 authority, it would absolutely govern the world." 
 These and other assertions of Butler seem to be 
 almost literal translations of the language of Kant 
 in respect to the practical reason and the categorical 
 imperative. It is worthy of notice, however, that 
 Butler finds in these doctrines only illustrations and 
 confirmations of the truth held by the best Greek 
 schools, that the nature or constitution of man is the 
 norm or standard by which moral distinctions are 
 tested and enforced, and that the rule " to follow
 
 188 rant's ethics. 
 
 nature," or "to live according to nature," was in his 
 view broad enough to provide for every special 
 ethical direction. While Butler appears to agree 
 with Kant in holding the categorical imperative, he 
 differs from him in finding the enforcement of its 
 authority in the constitution of man as its powers 
 and ends are interpreted by himself. That is to say, 
 as against Kant, he founded the authority of con- 
 science on the matter of its commands, as contrasted 
 with their mere /orw. This difference, expressed in 
 other language, would be as follows: While Kant 
 begins with a simple dictum of authority, Butler 
 explains and enforces this authorit}^ as an interpre- 
 tation of the ends of reason, as manifested in the 
 constitution of the soul and the universe of God, 
 and enforced by their ultimate authority. Instead 
 of a categorical imperative, Butler furnishes an 
 imperative that is hypothetical, enforcing its dicta 
 with the implied condition. If you would act accord- 
 ing to the nature of things, or the ends for which 
 you exist, you will do or avoid so and so. It is 
 true, he assumes the nature of man to be so and 
 so. Eveiy occasion of doubt will bring up the ques- 
 tion. Is this nature such as you assume it to 
 be? By what methods or tests we are to discover 
 and determine this nature, with its subordinate
 
 SUMMARY OF KANT'S ETHICAL THEORY. 189 
 
 or supi*erne ends, Butler does not explain. Indeed, 
 he attempts no analysis or explanation, or ver\' 
 scantily, of what he means by conformity to nature, 
 being content with a few positive and disconnected 
 utterances, which he does not attempt to reconcile 
 or adjust with one another, either by psychological 
 introspection or metaphysical analysis. 
 
 The very elaborate preface to his sermons is in- 
 structive and suggestive in respect to all the points 
 to which we have referred, and particularly the gen- 
 eral truth that he relies on the analysis of man's 
 nature for the determination of the purposes for 
 which it exists, and the normal uses to which it should 
 be applied. It is particularly worthy of notice that 
 the authority of this "superior principle of reflec- 
 tion " is partially explained by its being other than a 
 " propension " or impulse. It is true that Butler, like 
 Kant, in words attaches to a simple thought-object 
 a lawgiving power over an impulse, and there leaves 
 the analysis of obligation; but he does not, like 
 Kant, exalt a metaphor into a theory, and hyposta- 
 size an abstraction into a fancied personality, called 
 the categorical imperative. In this he may have 
 been Kant's inferior as a poet, but he was his superior 
 as a philosopher. 
 
 § 95. The next question is. What rule of duty is
 
 190 kant's ethics. 
 
 imposed by the moral reason? It is one thing to 
 determine that there is a moral law so 
 
 Kant's Ob- 
 jective Rule far as this is implied in the reality of the 
 
 of Duty. , • 1 
 
 practical reason, and another to determine 
 what this law requires, or what is its import. This 
 question Kant proposes, and labors earnestly to an- 
 swer. He is also clearly aware that it is a question 
 which moralists of all the schools have labored ear- 
 nestly to answer, some saying, Do that which will 
 make j^ou perfect or happy, or that which will ac- 
 cord with human nature, or that which will please 
 God. Indeed, it is with the answers to this question 
 that all theories of morals are chiefly concerned. 
 The answer which Kant gives is simply: That conduct 
 is right which when accepted as a maxim, i.e., an ac- 
 cepted or working rule, is fit to be universal. In other 
 words, universality or universal fitness {for wJiat is 
 not said) is the one criterion which should test every 
 moral law. The application of this criterion, as we 
 have seen, is illustrated by several supposed cases. 
 But all of these supposed cases are not only varied 
 examples of adaptation to an end, but of an adapta- 
 tion to an end which is presumed to be naturally 
 good, involving as the or as a fundamental relation, 
 that of adaptation to natural well-being as an end 
 or law. If it were urged that Kant's criterion, as
 
 SUMMARY OF KAXT's ETHICAL THEORY. 191 
 
 he insists, involved nothing which is worthy to be 
 called matter, then the j^i-inciple would be merely 
 formal, as he contends it ought to be — and this, the 
 identical proposition that like every fundamental or 
 original axiomatic criterion it should be universally 
 applicable. This, as we have seen", would be a very 
 safe but a very useless proposition, which would 
 impart no information and be exposed to no denial. 
 
 § 96. The next element of moral quality which 
 requires attention is qood or ill-desert. 
 
 '■ ^ Good and 
 
 The practical reason, according to Kant, m-desert ac- 
 cording to 
 not merely commands to duty, but it Kant and 
 
 teaches or declares that the obedient 
 will is deserving of good as a reward. While 
 the authority of its command can in no sense 
 be possibly derived from the natural good which 
 lies beneath or follows after the virtuous act that 
 is required, yet if this command is obeyed, the 
 conclusion follows with equal positiveness. that the 
 obedient act and the obedient man deserve only 
 good. In this way do we gain our completed con- 
 ception of the sumniuiH bonuin as including, _yi!">',s^, the 
 good will, which is itself the supreme and ultimate 
 good which is to be followed for its own sake and 
 obeyed for its autocratic authority, and next, the 
 reward which it merits, which completes the circle
 
 193 kant's ethics. 
 
 of possible blessings as involving every kind of good 
 that is conceivable, i.e., the snmmtim honum. No 
 reason is given for this connection of natural with 
 moral good as its reward. Its propriety with its 
 consequent authority, according to Kant, is to be 
 accepted as an ultimate fact. 
 
 In this doctrine Kant also reminds us of Butler, 
 when he says, " Our sense or discernment of actions 
 as morally good or evil, implies in it a sense or dis- 
 cernment of them as of good or ill-desert" (Diss. II.); 
 " Upon considering them or viewing together our 
 notion of vice and of misery, there results a 
 third, that of ill-desert." These judgments, like the 
 others, according to Butler, are not, as was taught 
 by Kant, original and inexplicable, but " Our per- 
 ception of vice and ill-desert arises from and is the 
 result of a comparison of actions ivith the nature 
 and capacities of the agent.'''' By what process or on 
 what grounds he would connect the two. or what is 
 involved subjectively or objectively in the act of 
 comparison is not explained by Butler. Nor is this 
 necessary for our purposes. It is enough that we 
 notice that he grounds the connection of the two 
 upon the consideration of the end for which the 
 moral being exists, and to which his powers are 
 adapted; in other words, that the relation of good
 
 SUMMARY OF KAXT's ETHICAL THEORY. 103 
 
 01- ill-desert is derived from the relation of fitness or 
 suitableness to the end or intention or idea of nat- 
 ure, and is not, as is held by Kant, an original or 
 axiomatic truth of the practical or moral reason. In 
 other words, so far as good or ill-desert is con- 
 cerned, Butler derives the concept of moral from 
 that of natural good, which Kant so positively repu- 
 diates, both in form and in fact. 
 
 § 97. The will, as related to the practical reason, 
 according to Kant, is the capacity in man 
 
 Kant's 
 
 to determine himself to action by the ap- Doctrine of 
 prehension of the laws which the reason 
 imposes. So far as this will is not determined by 
 any of the natui'al impulses of the sensibility, but 
 obeys the behests of the practical reason, it is called 
 free, i.e., free from sense or material motives. Yet 
 in being free from these laws it accepts and obeys 
 the moral law. 
 
 Natural law, however, it should be remembered, 
 pertains only to phenomena, and not to things in 
 themselves. It is apprehended of and enforced upon 
 phenomena as they occur under the form of time, in 
 order to make experience possible. On the other 
 hand, the power to accept and. so to speak, to en- 
 force moral law, pertains to things in themselves, 
 or noiimeiKi, of which causative power is affirmed, 
 13
 
 194 kant's ethics. 
 
 but not relations of time. Through the practical 
 i-eason we reach reality, the Ding an sich, the Ego, 
 or the soul, the nature and reality of which we 
 have previously striven in vain to discover. This 
 reality, however, is not given directly to conscious 
 experience or intuition, but it is given hnpliedly 
 so far, and so far only, as reality is involved in the 
 moral law. We do not assert freedom as a posi- 
 tive endowment of which we are immediately con- 
 scious, but we discern freedom as logically involved 
 in the conscious fact of obligation. We do not say, 
 I can, therefore I ouf/Jit, to choose so and so. i.e., to 
 exercise or assert^ my freedom, but / otifflit, fJtereforc 
 I can. 
 
 We are reminded here of the familiar lines of 
 Emerson, which were doubtless inspired by some of 
 the memorable and spirit-stirring utterances of 
 Kant: 
 
 "So nigh is grandeur to oiu" dust, 
 So near is God to luaii. 
 When duty whispers low, 'Thou must,' 
 The youth replies, 'I can.'" 
 
 The meaning of the poet, at first thought, seems to 
 be obvious, but on a second reading the question 
 might still arise, whether he did not after all have a 
 glimmering reference to the Kantian interpretation,
 
 SUMMARY OF KANT's ETHICAL THEORY. 195 
 
 and find in its paradox a poetic mystery. Some 
 would say the more paradoxical the statement the 
 more profound the truth. But on second thought 
 most readers will hnd in its stirring appeal the ut- 
 terance of the most solid of truths, that of a sense of 
 inward power aroused by the trumpet call of duty. 
 
 It should be observed that the will is also called 
 by Kant the practical reason, because the truth 
 which it assumes and enforces is the moral law, in- 
 volving the idea of duty, which this will acknowl- 
 edges by its subjective assent to its authority, even 
 when it disobeys its commands. This moral law 
 with its objective authority, moreover, is distin- 
 guished from a mere maxim of the will, which 
 may be defined as an}^ special rule which is in fact 
 
 accepted by the individual man for himself, and 
 which may be more or less completely conformed 
 to this comprehensive rule or law. {Cf. §57.) 
 
 § 98. Fi'eedom as the ground of responsibility is 
 onlv apnlicable to the noumenon or thing- 
 
 ^ Freedom 
 
 in-itself, it being excluded from phenom- in the Ego 
 en a by the fact that these only obey the 
 law of causation. And yet Kant inconsistently con- 
 tends that causation can connect the noumenon with 
 phenomena for the reason that being one of the 
 categories, it may be applied to phenomena as such;
 
 196 Kant's ethtos. 
 
 overlooking, as it would seem, that it is only between 
 phenomenon and phenomenon that any of the cate- 
 gories apply. In this way he finds no incompatibility 
 between necessary law and supersensible freedom. 
 By the same rule he distinguishes between a perma- 
 nent or timeless character and a permanent moral 
 state, regarded as the product of will. He goes so 
 far as to affirm that, given a man's character, every 
 act of his could be"predicted as the certain and neces- 
 sary effect of his permanent moral character or 
 state ; while yet for this character man himself is 
 responsible, because as a noumenon he is its origina- 
 tor.* The freedom for which Kant contends in any 
 such application is obviously a conception entirely 
 diffei-ent from that which he had defined as responsive 
 to the imperative of reason, and therefore the negative 
 of an impulse of sense, and in that sense free; it 
 being a positive function which is recognized as the 
 ground of personal responsibility, and finds its war- 
 rant in that direct consciousness which Kant usually 
 treats with supercilious disdain. 
 
 The InteUiyibJe eliaracfer of the noumenon Ego. 
 as thus explained, is also used by Kant as the basis 
 and explanation of that characteristic disposition to 
 
 * Of. Kant's Lehre von rter Freiheit, etc., von Dr. Carl Gerhard. 
 Heidelberg: Georg Weiss. 1885.
 
 SUMMARY OF KAXT's ETHICAL THEORY. 197 
 
 moral evil which lie recognizes as one of the conspic- 
 uous facts of human nature, and which forms the 
 subject of a special essay entitled, " Religion Inner- 
 halb der Grenzen der Reinen Vernunft." In this 
 essay he finds in his ethical theory a naturalistic or 
 physiological explanation of the theological doctrine 
 of man's natural sinfulness or depravity, finding in 
 the reluctance of the sensibility toward the good 
 the ground for the sense of obligation, as elsewhere 
 explained.* [Cf. §§ 25, 31, 38, 61, 69.) 
 
 * Dr. Kurd Lasswitz (Die Lehre Kaiits von der Idealitat des Raumes 
 und der Zeit, etc. Berlin: 1883, §§51-54) distinguishes tiie / or 
 Ego as first the determining agent of all its products or states, and 
 second as the determined product of its own activities. To the first 
 Ego neither the categories nor the time and space-forms have any 
 application. The second is two- fold, consisting of the self-conscions 
 Ego as known in its several states and objects — its Individual thoughts, 
 feelings, desires and resolves — and the objects given by sense-percep- 
 tion. Both the last are objects of experience, i.e., whether events or 
 beings, the experiences of consciousness or sense-perception, and both 
 obey the law of necessity. All that pertains to the Ego as a state or phe- 
 nomenon, i.e., as a tliought," or feeling, or conclusion, obeys the law of 
 causation as truly as do tliose agents which we call physical or material, 
 including as it does the entire realm,of determined psychical experience. 
 Behind and beneath this is the self-determined Ego,which by an activity 
 of its own originates the individual moral self that appears in con- 
 sciousness as a determined force, and gives character to all that con- 
 sciousness takes note of. The ingenious author insists that Kant in 
 this way intended to provide for two noumena in the Ego — the real, 
 active, self-determining Ego of moral freedom, and the second, which 
 is the complex, or content, of those objects and relations which con- 
 stitute experience and are given in consciousness. Of the first only 
 can freedom be affirmed; over the last the law of necessity prevails. 
 
 The distinction is apparently valid, and has been recognized by 
 others. Cf. Alfred Holder: Darstellung der Kantischen Erkenntniss- 
 theorie. Tiibingen, 1874, i)p. 6()-64. Cf.'S. Porter: The Human In- 
 tellect, §§ 86, 96.
 
 198 K A NT's ETHICS. 
 
 § 100. We notice next the relations of Kant's 
 
 Relation of ethics to his Speculative philosophy. As 
 
 an b t 109 ^g have seen, in the soul's knowledge of 
 
 to Specula- ' => 
 
 tive Truth. i^s own freedom is involved the discern- 
 ment of noumena or things in themselves, as con- 
 trasted with phenomena or events as they appear. 
 Through the knowledge of itself as free it breaks the 
 shell of appearances, which follow one after another, 
 and, so to speak, depend on one another after the 
 laws of nature; and knows itself, the Ego, as a thing- 
 in-itself It, moreover, knows itself as a cause pro- 
 ducing phenomenal effects of its own, yet without 
 disturbing the chain or connection of those causes 
 and effects which follow one another according to 
 natural laws. Its knowledge of the Ego does not, 
 however, involve an insight into its constitution or 
 endowment as a thing in itself, but only as capable 
 of free origination, and this so far only as the moral 
 law implies this power, its exercise, and its products. 
 AVith the capacity to respond to this law, personality 
 is implied, and a possible community of persons and 
 aims or ends of activity which are harmonious with 
 one another. Such a community or kingdom of 
 aims or ends was implied indeed in the statement or 
 definition previously given by Kant of the matter of 
 the moral law as a law which is fit to be universal.
 
 SUMMARY OF KaKT^S tTHlCAL THEORY. 199 
 
 But fitness implies adaptation to an end, and tlie 
 capacity for harmony between the ends of each in- 
 dividual, as also a harmony with and subordination 
 to the highest end of each and all. 
 
 It appears from all this that the practical reason 
 in the Kantian system alone gives us reality or 
 things in themselves, so far as to justify some knowl- 
 edge of the soul as a noumenon. The moral law 
 which enforces duty by its command asserts the 
 reality of the Ego as a fact, the nature of which and 
 the law of which it knows only by those phenomena 
 or conscious experiences in which the soul makes 
 itself manifest as an ethical force. 
 
 § 101. It also establishes the soul's immortality, 
 by the behests of the practical reason. Ethical 
 
 mi I • 1 • J.- • J. 1 Grounds for 
 
 ine categorical imperative is not only a ggij^j jj, 
 command that the soul should obey the immortality 
 moral law, wherein are implied its freedom and its 
 actual existence, but it insists that the obedient soul 
 shall be made happy simply because it so requires, 
 and therefore assumes that the soul deserves to 
 become so. So long as it feels obligation it is 
 under the dominion of sensibility, and consequently 
 there must ensue a constant strife between the 
 higher law of duty and the lower or emotional im- 
 pulses of sense and passion. So long as this struggle
 
 200 kaxt's ethics. 
 
 eontinues, it will fail to attain that happiness which 
 the practical reason — the supreme arbiter — pro- 
 nounces that it deserves. But if it deserves this it 
 surely will attain it, because the practical reason 
 commands it. But if it shall attain a complete 
 harmony between resisting impulse and imperative 
 law, it must continue to exist and consequently for 
 all practical purposes it must be immortal and inde- 
 structible, i.e., superior to any of those natural laws 
 which control or effect those changes in phenomena 
 which occur in time. 
 
 If the practical reason requires or commands that 
 the soul should continue to exist, it by the same rule 
 demands that God should exist, in order that its own 
 behests concerning the rewards which goodness de- 
 serves should in fact be accomplished through Him. 
 Thus, by an ethical necessity, the reality of certain 
 nomnena or things in themselves and their more im- 
 portant relations are established, so far, at least, as 
 the practical concerns of man require. At the same 
 time the contrast is indicated and justified between 
 man's absolute ignorance of things in themselves, on 
 the one hand, with the exceptions provided for, and 
 the progressive yet limited knowledge which he 
 attains of their relations and phenomena under nat- 
 ural laws, on the other.
 
 SUMMARY OF KANT's ETHICAL THEORY. 201 
 
 § 102. To the brief summary which we have 
 given of the leading principles of Kant's Further Re- 
 ethical system, we subjoin the follovvinof ^' "" , " "'"'" 
 critical remarks and queries. The first imperative, 
 which we select is the categorical impcrafirr which is 
 enforced and assented to by the practical reason, 
 as an essential attribute, property, or element of the 
 moral law. This is held by Kant to be original and 
 simple and comparable in this respect to any one of 
 those mathematical relations or concepts which we rec- 
 ognize as original. It is also capable of eliciting emo- 
 tions, or one, at least, viz. : that of esteem or respect. 
 The discerned relation of authority is on the one 
 side, and the felt emotion of obligation is on the 
 other. To the recognition of either of these ele- 
 ments as original, whether the objective or the sub- 
 jective, we object that they are unique, and there- 
 fore require an extraordinary claim upon our confi- 
 dence. This claim they are so far from justifying, 
 through their use in explaining " human experi- 
 ence,'' that they contradict the analogies of this ex- 
 perience, while the phenomena for which they are 
 required can be satisfactorily explained by being 
 resolved into other elements. We cannot conceive 
 of a mere fhongJit or Judf/menf of moral import, 
 whether in the general or the individual form, like
 
 202 KANt\s ETHK-'li, 
 
 "Thou shalt love thy neighbor," or, "Thou shall 
 relieve the hunger of A or B," that is capable of ue- 
 ing self-enforced and thus invested with moral au- 
 thority. The conception of authority seems w^holly 
 disparate with or unrelated to any mere thought or 
 judgment, or any hypostasized rational or intellectual 
 entity. 
 
 55 108. We accept the axiom as self-evident that 
 " obligation supposes an obliger,'' as an 
 
 Personality 
 
 Essential to analytic or axiomatic proposition, because 
 the word and the thought suppose a 
 person commanding and a i)erson responding, with 
 the correlate emotion of constraint. It would seem 
 to follow that the relation and the feeling it evokes 
 can belong only to one person as set over against 
 another, and under any conditions that might evoke 
 reverence or fear by command or direction. For 
 this reason it is held by a recent writer, Dr. James 
 Martineau,* that these cannot exist or hold except of 
 man as in contact with his fellow-man or as subject to 
 Grod's command. But man is not only a political and 
 a religious animal, he maintains an economy of organ- 
 ization and rule within himself. By his capacity for 
 self-consciousness or reflection he can give law to 
 himself as truly as, and far more completely than, he 
 
 *On the Relation between Ethics and Religion. London: 1883. 
 Cf. Types of Ethical Theory. London: 1885.
 
 SUMMARY OF KAXT's ETHICAL THEOJiY. 203 
 
 can give law to others. He can obey or disobey 
 himself, and reward or punish himself with his own 
 complacence or displacency, and therefore can hold 
 or bind himself to the feelings and acts which he ac- 
 knowledges to be right or wrong. It is only as we 
 remember that man is endowed with consciousness; 
 and that consciousness can be thus intensified into 
 reflection; and that man as self-conscious is thereby 
 capable of proposing and imposing ideal ends and 
 laws for himself as voluntary, as truly as for others; 
 and that he can respond to these ideals and laws by 
 his freely choosing will, and can also reflect upon his 
 choices and decide upon their conformit}' or noncon- 
 formity to the law self-imposed, and can reward or 
 punish himself by his own approval or condemnation 
 — it is only as we remember all these facts and relations 
 that we can ex[)Iain obligation and authority in their 
 highest significance, with the correlative emotions of 
 reverence and constraint. These emphatically moral 
 relations are emphatically personal relationships. 
 They are incapable of existing where personality is 
 wanting, and are capable of existing in their highest 
 and most perfect form only where personal relations 
 are most energetic and intense. These facts and re- 
 lations of human experience are not denied by Kant. 
 They are most distinctly recognized by him so soon
 
 204 kaxt's ethics. 
 
 as they come prominently into bis field of view. At 
 a late period of his inquiries he defines a person 
 as one who is an end to and within himself, and 
 founds on this definition his doctrine of human 
 rights, when he faces the doctrine of rights; but 
 be overlooks personality altogether in his formal 
 exposition of moral obligation and authority, and the 
 categorical imperative. In the exposition of bis 
 ethical theory and the practical reason he loses sight 
 of the significance of personality, with its individual 
 will, its reflecting reason, and its interpreting power, 
 and only comes back to it after having asked leave of 
 the practical reason to justify bis belief in the re- 
 ality of this noumenon within his breast. {Cf. § 72.) 
 § 103. If now it can be made good that the rela- 
 Sense of tion of authority itself, with its attendant 
 
 Complex and emotion, can be derived from and re- 
 Denved. solved iuto and explained by other known 
 
 endowments of man's nature, it follows that, neither 
 as intellectually apprehended nor as emotionally re- 
 sponded to, can it be accepted as an original relation or 
 ultimate experience. We mean, of course, when we 
 use language witrh any claim or effort for scientific 
 exactness. We know that as a poetic metaphor or 
 an imaginative expression, such a representation mav 
 be both significant and satisfying; but for this very
 
 SUMMARY OF KANT'S ETHICAL THEORY. 205 
 
 reason it may be the more misleading when there 
 is any danger of its being mistaken for analytic 
 or exact terminology. If by the practical reason 
 we are undei-stood to mean the reflective reason 
 when it confronts voluntary activities, there can be 
 no objection to such an application of the term. But 
 if the categorical imperative is made to describe a 
 constraining force over the feelings or will, which is 
 supposed to be emitted or to proceed from an intel- 
 lectual judgment or proposition, instead of the activ- 
 ity of a living personality, then we cannot but call 
 it a metaphor and treat it as such. 
 
 § 104. We prefer our own solution to the Kant- 
 ian, — if the latter deserves to be called 
 
 The Two 
 
 an explanation, and not a mere figure of Explanations 
 
 , , •, /. i 1 Contracted. 
 
 speech. — because it reiers us to known 
 human endowments which cannot be denied, and 
 recognizes their familiar activit}^ and their universal 
 prevalence, and because it fully explains a problem 
 which the Kantian theory does not attempt to solve, 
 but declares to be inexplicable, and which it then 
 proceeds to envelop in a cloud of imposing imagery, 
 and to speed on the winged woi'ds of a soaring 
 poetic diction. Our solution holds fast to the author- 
 ity of the moral reason and the moral law, as recog- 
 nized bv both Kant and Butler, So far as Butler
 
 306 rant's ethics. 
 
 recognizes simple authority as the distinctive attri- 
 bute of the moral reason or the moral nature in the 
 way of personification, without any explanation of 
 the natural endowments which make it possible, so 
 far is he fairly open to criticism. So far as he 
 resolves the possession and use of this authority into 
 the nature of man as a reflective and voluntaiy 
 being, so far does he make his theory rational. 
 
 Another unique feature which remains to be noticed 
 in Kant's conception of obligation, is that he conditions 
 it entirely on the supposed resistance, reaction, or re- 
 luctance of the passions and emotions of the sentient 
 soul. So long as a struggle arises between the reluc- 
 tant passions and the imperative reason — not, be it 
 observed, between the lower and higher emotions, 
 for such a distinction is not admitted by Kant, but 
 between feeling and authority — then, and only then, 
 obligation will be felt. When the passions are all 
 at rest in perfected harmony, then a state of holiness 
 ensues, as contrasted with a condition of reluctant 
 but obedient virtue, and then obligation ceases to be 
 felt or known. " The perfected spirits of the just," 
 according to Kant, have no sense or experience of 
 obligation. A paradoxical statement, like this, can 
 only be accounted for by the necessities of a one- 
 sided theory.
 
 SUMMARY OF KANT'S ETHICAL THEORY. 207 
 
 § 105. The next point to be considered is Kant's 
 conception and attempted definition of Kant's 
 the moral law. The practical reason, f^P ""^''"" 
 
 '■ ' of the 
 
 according to Kant, confronts the will Moral Law. 
 with the categorical imperative. It authoritatively 
 commands the will, but to do or to be what? If it 
 meets the will which, whatever it may be, is cer- 
 tainly a power to do or become something, what does 
 it propose that it be or do? Whether it be in the gen- 
 eral command, Thou shalt love thy neighbor, or in the 
 concrete. Thou shalt will or give him food, there must 
 be a definite kind of feeling or doing proposed or com- 
 manded. What is this command? This question has 
 often been asked, and each answer represents a sepa- 
 rate theory in ethics. To this question, as we have 
 seen, Kant gives no answer except the mere formal 
 rule. See that your law be universal, or fit to be univer- 
 sal — that is, that it admit no exception — when it comes 
 to be applied. What Kant means by this criterion 
 he illustrates by the four oft-repeated suppositions 
 of temptation to personal degradation, to suicide, to 
 an idle and self-indulgent life, and to falsehood. We 
 have seen that in every one of these cases this unfit- 
 ness to be universal is exemplified b}'^ the tendency 
 of the conduct to hinder or mar human well-being. 
 This, Kant would say, is a mere accident of the
 
 308 kant's ethics. 
 
 mattei-, with which we have nothing to do. It is onl}'- 
 with the actual necessity that the law should be uni- 
 versal that he is concerned, not at all with the fact that 
 the act should always conduce to human well-being. 
 If this be so, then it is the fact that the rule admits 
 no exception; that is, it is its formal universality 
 alone which gives it its binding force. But mere 
 universality, as such, when separated from univer- 
 sal results of blessing, would invest the law with no 
 moral authority. Rather would it be the farther 
 removed from such dignity, the more manifest it be- 
 came that, in its tendency to natural evil, it was con- 
 sistent with itself. Does not Milton truly tell us: 
 
 " * * * devil with devil damn'd 
 Finn concord holds; men only disagree." 
 
 The actual universality of a law, or the universal 
 approval of the same, can only be interpreted as 
 the evidence of its manifest tendency to promote 
 the well-being of those whom it concerns. It is 
 strange, indeed, that an eye usually so acute as was 
 Kant's should fail to penetrate so thin a disguise. 
 
 The examples selected by Kant, as explained by 
 himself, show that so far as the content of the moral 
 law is concerned, in each of the instances supposed, 
 it has solely to do with its bearing on human well- 
 being. Kant does not seem to be aware of this fact;
 
 SUMMARY OF KANT'S ETHICAL THEORY. 209 
 
 for not only are these the only examples which he 
 quotes, but they are repeated by him again and 
 again, in oi'der to make clear what he thinks of the 
 content of the moral law, and the reasons for its 
 being of universal obligation. Considerations of this 
 sort constitute and exhaust his entire repertory of 
 reasons. 
 
 § 106. Tills is very remarkable when considered 
 in connection with his constantly repeat- Kant's view 
 ed assertion that the nature of man can °^ 1^13"^'°'^'"' ^ 
 never, as the ancients taught us, explain Moral Nature. 
 the content of the moral law, this being transient 
 matter, the product of arbitrary conditions, and 
 therefore inferior to tJie eternal forms of things, 
 which are supposed to be incapable of change and 
 dissolution. Kindred to this was the assertion, which 
 we shall have occasion to consider, that feeling, as 
 such, and anything which excites feeling, is transient 
 and unstable matter, and therefore incapable of 
 being the element or ground of any rule of duty. 
 The untenableness and the inconsistenc}' of Kant's 
 strictures upon the derivation of the moral law from 
 the constitution of human nature, and upon the defini- 
 tion by the Aristotelian and Stoic schools of virtue 
 as a life according to nature, and their rule of duty 
 
 as derived from the nature of things in general, 
 14
 
 210 kant's ethics. 
 
 together with the dishonor which he puts upon feel- 
 ing as an uncertain and unstable element in the 
 construction of any ethical system, are eminently 
 chai'acteristic of his theory, and are continually pre- 
 senting themselves in one form or another, as 
 stones of stumbling to the ingenuous mind. 
 
 § 107. Kant's doctrine of the will and of free- 
 Further Criti- dora is obscure and unsatisfactory. It is 
 
 cism of Kant's ■, ^ p • i_ • i- xi 
 
 Doctrine of Clear only SO tar as it is negative, t ree- 
 the Will. (Jqj^-^ j^ g^ condition opposed to that of be- 
 
 ing bound by natural laws, viz.: those laws which 
 govern phenomena and which are assumed a priori 
 to be necessary in order to make experience possible. 
 In contrast with the dominion of these laws, it is 
 asserted that the will is free; or rather it is con- 
 cluded that it must be free for the reason that man 
 ought to obey the moral law. The fact or truth of 
 freedom is not known by conscious intuition. Indeed 
 no positive activity is asserted of choice or selection 
 of one of two conflicting objects or between conflict- 
 ing natural impulses. The belief in freedom, what- 
 ever it may be, is in no sense direct and immediate. 
 It is uniformly held as an inference from another 
 fact or truth. The proposition which expresses our 
 faith is, We ought, therefore we can. The truth 
 that tve ought comes first and the truth that ire can
 
 StTMMAilY OF KANt's ETHICAL THEORY. 211 
 
 comes last, as implied and enforced by the categori- 
 cal imperative of the practical reason. We know 
 that we can in knowing that we ought. But why or 
 how. we are not informed. It is pointedly denied, 
 however, that we are conscious that we are naturally 
 or morally free. 
 
 That there neither is nor can be any incompati- 
 bility between freedom and necessity is urged by 
 Kant, and reasoned by him on the ground that 
 necessity pertains to phenomena, while freedom can 
 belong only to noumena. We interpret phenomena 
 by causal relations under natural laws, in order to 
 make experience possible, that is, in order to explain 
 the past and adapt ourselves to the future. We in- 
 terpret freedom of noumena as being something more 
 and possibly exempt from natural laws, even though 
 we conceive of them as causal in their activity within 
 the world of phenomena. But while we know this 
 truth because the exigencies of the moral law force it 
 upon our assent, this is all that we know. We are 
 constrained by the reality of freedom, and accept it 
 as trustworthy simply because it is essential to the 
 assent which we cannot deny to the authority of the 
 categorical imperative. 
 
 The critic of Kant does not find it very difficult to 
 urge that Kant's axiom, wp oiu/Iit, tJtPrefore we can,
 
 213 Kant's ethics. 
 
 is an analytic or identical proposition, asserting that 
 as the ground of our conviction of the fact of obliga- 
 tion, there is involved the discernment of the fact of 
 freedom. The circumstance that Kant is never con- 
 sciously responsible for any psychological, as distin- 
 guished from a metaphysical, analysis, does not 
 make it any the less difficult to suppose that he may 
 mistake the one for the other. But of this more in 
 another place. 
 
 § 108. That Kant does scant justice to the range 
 
 „ ,, r . and import of those truths w^hich self- 
 Kant's Late ^ 
 
 andinade- consciousness attests is still more strik- 
 
 quate Recog- 
 nition of ingly manifest from his scant recognition 
 urpose. ^^ ^^^^ ^^_ design as an element of person- 
 ality and a condition of moral obligation. Freedom 
 implies a choice of a supreme end when recognized 
 as fitted and designed to control free action, per- 
 sonal emotion, and individual activity. This im- 
 plies that a rational universe supposes a harmony to 
 be possible between the best acts of its constituent 
 members, and the best acts and results of all acting 
 together. In the enumeration of the categories of 
 the pure or the practical reason we find no distinct 
 recognition of this fundamental relation as such, 
 and consequently no provision for the use of the 
 same in the analysis or explanation of scientific or
 
 SUMMAKY OF KANT's ETHICAL THEORY, 213 
 
 ethical truth. Consequently it is not surprising that 
 we find this relation nowhere recognized by Kant as 
 furnishing the explanation of the authority of the 
 moral law over the personal will. 
 
 We contend that the end for which one or more 
 forces or agencies exist, especially if it coiitrols the 
 combined or conspiring activity of many others, is 
 rightly conceived as exercising authority over all 
 these forces, and acting as a lawgiver and law-en- 
 forcer for them all. If we find any form of natural 
 good appearing to control unconscious existence or 
 instinctive action, it is regarded as invested with 
 authority and imposing the necessity of obedience. 
 If it is consciously recognized as fit to control the ac- 
 tions and results of one who obeys and disobeys its 
 behests, it is conceived as his ruler, which will not be 
 trifled with, as exercising a mastery which is none 
 the less an object of reverence even if the power 
 which it evokes is blind. If a man offends against 
 his own nature, i.e., his own living self, as represented 
 by the purpose which is the law for his being as to its 
 best possible achievements, he acknowledges its right 
 to command when he feels its power to condemn and 
 punish. If he attains any just idea of the excel- 
 lence of the good (the natural good) which he might 
 have achieved, and the badness of the loss which he
 
 214 Kant's ethics. 
 
 has incurred, he invests such a purpose with author- 
 ity over his will as supreme, having a sacredness 
 which can be compared with no other. But in 
 order that these experiences may be possible these 
 psychological and metaphysical elements must be 
 recognized and applied. Kant fails in both, and 
 consequently fails in the explanation of attaining a 
 good or satisfactory theory of the most important of 
 ethical experiences, that of moral obligation. As if 
 to atone for his failure, he substitutes for it a fig- 
 ment of the poetic imagination, which he invests 
 with the borrowed drapery of factitious disinterest- 
 edness, doing violence at the same time to the most 
 sacred and inextinguishable of human aspirations, 
 the realization of its highest natural capacities of de- 
 sire and impulse, and displacing the rights of the 
 supreme reason by the pretended claims of a blind 
 impei'ative which owns no allegiance to the nature 
 of man, but authoritatively issues its unreasoned de- 
 mands, in response to which it requires an unemo- 
 tional and an unreasoning will. 
 
 § 109. It is not to be wondered at, that in the 
 logical and natural consequence of this 
 
 ° Kant's Failure 
 
 double defect — subjectively in respect to to do Justice 
 
 freedom, and objectively in respect to 
 
 purpose — Kant should fail to recognize the ethical
 
 SUMMARY OP Kant's ethical theory. 215 
 
 significance of personality. In psychology he knows 
 no other Ego than a noumenon capable of the sole 
 function of reverently responding to an irrational 
 moral law, the authority of which it blindly respects 
 and freely though reluctantly follows, while in sci- 
 ence it is known by its reflex in a synthetic apper- 
 ception of the unity which it imparts to the objects of 
 knowledge. The self-conscious Ego, as a choosing 
 and loving being which knows its powers and possi- 
 bilities by its self-conscious judgment, and proposes 
 aims to itself which it imposes as laws ; which, as 
 will, chooses or refuses the good which is made possi- 
 ble by its capacities ; and which by these, as stand- 
 ards, measures and judges its acts and attainments — 
 of all this he knows nothing as the foundation of his 
 ethical conceptions or emotions, but, instead thei-eof, 
 gives us the dry scaffolding of a merely logical 
 hypostasis which he illumines with the weird light 
 of fantastic illustrations. 
 
 When he approaches the sphere of concrete real- 
 ities and touches the realm of the actual, it is not 
 surprising that he recognizes the importance and 
 significance of personality; especially when he treats 
 of the doctrine of human rights in his Metaphysik 
 der Sitten. 
 
 § 110. Kant's dogmatic depreciation of the
 
 ^16 Kant's ethics. 
 
 emotions in his ethical theory is open to the most 
 „. ^ . decided criticism. From the beffinningr 
 
 His Deprecia- ° ° 
 
 tion of the to the end of his expositions he excludes 
 
 Emotions 
 
 and the any recognition of the sensibilities in 
 
 ' ' ^' faculty or manifestation, for the compre- 
 hensive reason that they are necessarily changeable 
 with the individual, and consequently are incapable 
 of any fixed relationships which involve permanent 
 and universal worth. In this general position, which 
 is constantly assumed or asserted, Kant overlooks 
 two considerations; the first that the sensibilities as 
 such are no matter of ethical valuation or authority, 
 but only the sensibilities as energized and regulated 
 by the will. It is not the positive strength of any 
 or all of the passions, as a natural or a hereditary 
 endowment, nor the relative intensity or energy of 
 any one when thus estimated, which is praise- or 
 blame-worthy, but it is the positive strength of one 
 or the relative energy of many as the expression of 
 the individual will, that constitutes character, and 
 is the object of ethical approval or condemnation. 
 While it is true, as Kant contends, that sensibility 
 or emotion, as such, is involuntary, accidental, 
 and arbitrary, and subject to all manner of caprices, 
 it is equally true that the emotions as volition- 
 ized are susceptible of constant relations with an
 
 StJMMAKY OF KANT^S ^:THICAL THEORY. 217 
 
 ever-varying material, and that under an endless 
 variety of energy and activity there may be con- 
 stancy of proportion under the controlling energy 
 of the central will. Man's natural sensibilities of 
 every sort, his responsive loves and hatreds, his 
 sympathies and antipathies, seem as changeable and 
 capricious as the lawless wind; but whenever and so 
 far as they meet in conflict and measure their claims 
 by the highest possibilities of human nature, so far 
 do they admit a standard, a law, a sentence and its 
 execution; in other words, so far do they provide for 
 moral relations, making them both possible and 
 necessary. Tlie second consideration overlooked by 
 Kant is, that the will without sensibility is incapable 
 of stimulating or directing activity, lacking, as it 
 does, any material to regulate, and the motives which 
 might give life to the moral purposes, and warmth 
 and energy to the inner life. Kant's will, without 
 feeling, is simply a capacity for responding to duty 
 and inspiring to outward action by demand of the 
 reason, without involving the emotions. The re- 
 sponses of such impulses must consequently be 
 colorless and cold. Should the affections glow with 
 saintly or seraphic ardor, with self-sacrificing benev- 
 olence or heroic self-control, so far as the devotee of 
 duty finds in his conscious delight in the exercise of
 
 218 KANT^S ETHICS. 
 
 any, even the highest sensibilities, an aniniating 
 impulse or a ground of satisfaction, as contradistin- 
 guished from the simple imperative of the moral 
 law, so far, according to Kant, would the morality 
 of his motives be weakened and dishonored, and the 
 purity of his affections be soiled and smirched. 
 Moreover, he teaches that a command to love, or to 
 exercise or indulge any emotion, is absurd in the 
 eye of reason, which could issue in no moral result 
 were it obeyed. The categorical imperative, he tells 
 us, requires acts, not feelings, for with feelings it 
 disdains to concern itself. It would seem when love 
 becomes most pure, according to Kant's own theory, 
 that it is no longer an activity of reluctant duty, 
 but an inspii'ation of aspiring holiness, but at that 
 instant it ceases to have any properly moral quality, 
 because it is swallowed up in an afflatus of emo- 
 tional sympathy. So far, too, as its subjective as- 
 pects are concerned, the form of virtue which Kant 
 would sanction and cultivate is manifestly apathetic 
 and unsympathizing. It is stoical rather than hu- 
 mane, self-relying rather than benevolent; if it is 
 self-governed and just, it is cold and hard. From 
 what we learn of Kant's personal character and his 
 domestic education, we are confirmed in the conclu- 
 sion which would be suggested by his speculative
 
 SUMMARY OF KANT's ETHICAL THEORY. 219 
 
 system, that bis own morale was chiefly concerned 
 with acts rather than with feelings, at the same time 
 that it was severe in its principles and uncompro- 
 mising in its requirements. His speculative and 
 practical views, as it would seem, were also largely 
 affected by his antagonism to the fanatical emotion- 
 alism of Rousseau, who was in his eyes the repre- 
 sentative of speculative and practical sentimentalism, 
 and very naturally found little favor with the ex- 
 pounder of the categorical imperative and the practi- 
 cal reason; It is beyond dispute or question that Kant 
 was the expounder and representative of an entirely 
 different practical theory, and it seems equally ob- 
 vious that the reaction which he represented was 
 equally extreme in the opposite direction from Rous- 
 seau. Nature, however, will have her revenges, and 
 so we observe that Kant does not always succeed in 
 overlooking or eliminating the element of feeling. 
 He is too honest and logical to the truth of human 
 experience entirely to overlook the AcJitiiiig, or es- 
 teem for the law, which he confesses is conspicuous 
 in human experience, although he strives to square 
 it with his theory by denying that it is properly an 
 emotion at all. The elevating and self-satisfied 
 peace of a good man he was too true to nature to 
 deny or overlook, and yet the dominant spirit of his
 
 220 kant's ethics. 
 
 system was sharply and strongly antagonistic to 
 feeling or emotion of any kind, either as a specula- 
 tive or practical element. 
 
 § 111. We notice the intellect nal services to which 
 Theinteiiec- the Kantian Ethics have been applied. 
 tuaiAppii- ^Yg jj^^g alreadv adverted to the impor- 
 
 cation of .,1 
 
 Kanfs Ethics, tance which Kant ckimed for his practi- 
 cal as a supplement to the speculative reason. We 
 have also stated the course of thought by which he 
 made it to command the soul on its allegiance to 
 duty to accept such truths as the existence and im- 
 mortality of the soul and the being of God. Such 
 positive and extraordinar}' claims for experiences 
 so commanding are imposing by reason of the con- 
 fidence with which they are urged and the impor- 
 tance of the truths which they are supposed to make 
 axiomatic. That the demands of duty extend to the 
 nse which we make of the intellect in its search for 
 truth is most obvious, and that the fidelity with 
 which we respond to these claims often determines 
 the results cannot be denied. But it does not follow 
 that the occasion for the interposition of the so-called 
 practical reason is precisely what Kant represents it 
 to be, or that the method by which it supplies the 
 needs of the speculative reason is that which his 
 theory of its nature supposes.
 
 SUMMARY OF KANT'S ETHICAL THEORY. 221 
 
 § 112. First of all there is, we conceive, a subtle 
 but fascinating haziness in the concep- Authority 
 tions of Kant and many other schools in °^ pj^^c'if"*^*^ 
 respect to the evidence, authority, and Questions. 
 trustworthiness of experience, especially in our ethi- 
 cal activities. That is a simple haziness of thought, 
 if it be not sometimes a mystic dogmatism, which con- 
 ceives of experimental and ethical knowledge as in 
 its nature more positive and satisfying simply because 
 it is unlike the ordinary processes of the intellect 
 when applied to other than matters of faith and 
 duty. When it is said in common life that experience 
 will test ethical truth as nothing else besides, or 
 when it is declared that the honest conscience de- 
 cides many a sophistical doctrine to be incredible, 
 however plausible and unanswerable it may seem to 
 be; when it is said by Kant that it is in order that 
 experience may be possible that we are forced to ac- 
 cept and assert as a priori the forms of sense, the cate- 
 gories of the understanding, and the ideas of the rea- 
 son, we assume that the knowledge given and tested 
 by experience must be trustworthy, not directly be- 
 cause of its practical importance, but rather because 
 men will not trust the interests of their daily and 
 personal life to any other than to such satisfying evi- 
 dence as is sun-clear and sun-bright. It certainly
 
 222 kant's ethics. 
 
 cannot be good logic or good sense to reason simply 
 that because men must live, or gain any other good, 
 therefore the knowledge which they must accept in 
 order to live must always be reliable, and that for 
 this reason the relations of time and space and the 
 other a priori conditions of experience must in some 
 sense be trustworthy. And yet it may be both good 
 logic and good sense to reason that our confidence in 
 any knowledge which is actually tx'usted in ex- 
 perience must be as clear and as self-evident as the 
 light. On the other hand, it may be true that to the 
 practical appeal, II faut vivre, the reply is sometimes 
 pertinent, Je nen vols pas la necessite. 
 
 Similarly, it sounds very satisfactory to say that the 
 practical reason of the conscience requires that we 
 believe in freedom, immortality, and God, because 
 the moral law commands us so to believe, and to rest 
 on the acceptance of this ignava ratio, that we must 
 discern facts or relations to be true, because other- 
 wise faith, and duty, and hope, would be impossible. 
 But this is the logic of Kant, and it is by buttresses of 
 this sort, if his meaning is rightly interpreted, that 
 he would support what he thinks to be the tottering 
 pillars of faith and conscience. That when opposed 
 to the analysis of speculation, Kant's ethical fervor 
 has often been efl:ective, when re-cast and re-inter-
 
 SUMMAEY OF KANT's ETHICAL THEORY. 223 
 
 preted by the unreflecting good sense of many 
 readers, we do not deny. That he has often been a 
 most effective assertor of the speculative and practi- 
 cal authority of moral truth and religious verity, 
 we do not deny, but that this renders any the more 
 trustworthy his uncalled-for concessions of the limit- 
 ations of the speculative reason, and his equally un- 
 authorized extension of the functions of the practical 
 reason, we do not believe to be true. Notwithstand- 
 ing the fervor of his assertions of the authority of 
 ethical and his occasionally eloquent expositions of 
 spiritual truth, it may be seriously questioned 
 whether the honeycombed scepticism of his specu- 
 lative theory has not occasioned unmeasurably 
 greater mischief than his magniloquent and occa- 
 sionally really eloquent utterances for freedom and 
 immortality and God have been able to prevent or 
 to cure. 
 
 There cannot be the least objection to the trial of 
 every system of philosophical truth by ethical tests, 
 provided these tests are legitimately applied, but to 
 assume that there are two kinds of evidence which 
 have no common foundation and which require a dif- 
 ferent or an irreconcilable logic, the so-called logic of 
 the intellect and the logic of the conscience, is to 
 accept a fundamental logic which will be found to be
 
 224 rant's ethics. 
 
 irreconcilable with either science or faith. In the 
 reasonings which we have emploj^ed in this treatise, 
 from the practical features and tendencies of Kant's 
 own system, to its speculative weakness or truth, we 
 constantly assume that what is speculatively true 
 will commend itself as such to the unsophisticated 
 common sense and permanent convictions of man- 
 kind, especially when these are tested by the trying 
 exigencies of practical life, because we believe that 
 all ethical and spiritual convictions stand on definite 
 and discernible speculative foundations. 
 
 This truth may suggest the last topic of criticism, 
 which is none other than the relations of Kant's 
 ethical and speculative system to the Christian ethics 
 and to theistic and Christian truth. 
 
 § 113. The Christian ethics are characteristically 
 Kant's Ethics Severe, uncompromising, and authorita- 
 andthe ^-^^^ ^^ ^j^^ ^^^ hand, while they are 
 
 Contrasted. singularly sympathetic and tolerant, 
 charitable and humane, on the other. The Kantian 
 ethics are certainly no more elevated in their practi- 
 cal ideals than are the Christian; assuredly the}^ are 
 no more positive in asserting the authority of the 
 moral law. We may perhaps concede that the two 
 systems in spirit and requirements are equally rigor- 
 ous and uncompromising. But in respect to the
 
 SUMMARY OF KANT's ETHICAL THEORY. 225 
 
 gentler and the more sympathetic affections, they 
 scarcely belong to the same family. Emotion in all 
 its forms is the very soul of the Christian system. 
 Feeling is the consummate flower of Christian virtue 
 in all its varied hues of tenderness and sympathy. 
 In the theory of Kant sensibility has no place, except 
 a place of weakness and inferiority. It never is 
 recognized as capable of being strengthened and 
 hai'dened by the will, while in the Christian system, 
 if emotion be wanting, whether in its severer or its 
 gentler forms, its absence is considered a sign of 
 special defect. The tolerance and forgiveness of 
 Christian virtue is scarcely provided for by Kant's 
 speculative theory or his practical rules. Marcus 
 Aurelius is immeasurably more Christian in the char- 
 acteristically Christian emotions than is the unsympa- 
 thizing Kant, who is always stern, though sometimes 
 sublime in his rigid severity. So far as he relaxes at 
 all from the rigor of his ethical tone, he is either 
 evaporated into an imaginative sentimentalism which 
 rises above the range of human sympathies, or is crys- 
 tallized into a rigid stoicism which prides itself on 
 its formal perfection. For any practical application 
 to the affairs of common life, his teachings and spirit 
 are singulai'ly unfitted, and for this reason his ethics 
 have been known and practised chiefly among the 
 15
 
 236 kant's ethics. 
 
 ranks of the artificially cultivated, while the Chris- 
 tian moralities have been most distinctl}^ recognized 
 and most effectually honored and most consistently 
 practised in the homes and societies of practical men, 
 who have been schooled to the ethics of common 
 sense, by the trials and conflicts of ordinary life. 
 
 § 114. The relations of the Kantian ethics to the- 
 Reiatioiisto istic and Christian truth should not be 
 The^stic and overlooked. In the ethics of Kant, God 
 
 Christian ' 
 
 Truth. is a scientific necessity, whose presence in 
 
 the moral universe is required, that He may bestow 
 upon the virtuous the reward which they deserve for 
 their obedience to the moral law. Inasmuch as the 
 practical reason not only commands obedience, but 
 pronounces that the obedient will deserves to be made 
 sensitively happy, some agent or agency is required 
 to execute its behests, and therefore God is demanded 
 and accepted by the faith of men. Inasmuch, how- 
 ever, as the good which He bestows is sentient good, 
 and this in the Kantian system is inferior to moral 
 good, the relative place which the Supreme holds in 
 His own universe is by necessity a secondary and 
 inferior one. He is artificially and awkwardly at- 
 tached to the practical reason, as a marshal or 
 sheriff', in order to enforce the moral law, and cannot 
 but suffer in the respect of those who believe in
 
 SUMMARY OF KANT's ETHICAL THEORY. 227 
 
 Him, by reason of this single function, for which alone 
 He is made necessary to their faith. His entire 
 administration must consequently be weakened in 
 its acts and its functions by the circumstance that it 
 addresses the hopes and fears of men. in place of 
 their conscience and moral will, inasmuch as the 
 Kantian estimate of the emotional nature places it 
 out of all relation to the conscience, and degrades 
 the motives which it addresses to man's sensibility to 
 a confessedly inferior authority. Hence the natural 
 theism of Kant, which at first aspect seems to be 
 exalted to the highest supi'emacy over man, even to 
 the judgment seat of the conscience, and conse- 
 quently to stand on the firmest foundations, is prac- 
 tically and fatally weakened by this practical antag- 
 onism between duty and sensibility. The same 
 weakness makes itself more manifest when the 
 Kantian ethics encounters the Christian system in 
 its supernatural Personage, with His miraculous 
 doings and His authoritative commands, with His 
 personal affections, His promised rewai'ds, and His 
 threatened displeasure. While Kant affects no se- 
 crecy, and is chargeable with no affectation in the 
 homage which he renders to Christ as the embodied 
 ideal of moral perfection, as both the example and 
 the inspirer of the ethical life of Christendom, he at
 
 328 kant's ethics. 
 
 the same time treats His claims as the pei'sonal 
 ruler of the world's life as did Herod of old, in- 
 vesting the rightful Lord of the moral universe with 
 a robe of mockery, and putting into his hands an 
 idle sceptre. The Christian history he is compelled by 
 the stress of his ethical system to hold to be impos- 
 sible, or needless, or unscientific. While as a sym- 
 bol the Christian history is worthy of all respect, yet 
 as a supernatural fact it is impossible, needless, or 
 mercenary. As a revelation it is simply impossible, 
 because the ideas and truths which it professes to 
 impart cannot be communicated unless the elements 
 are already in the possession of those to whom it 
 claims to make them known. If these elements are 
 already present, they cannot be enforced by super- 
 natural authority, inasmuch as their natural and in- 
 dependent energy cannot be increased by any extra- 
 neous additions. The axiomatically ethical and spir- 
 itual truth which is slumbering in every man's con- 
 science must be left to be developed, sooner or later, 
 by natural agencies, under the operation of existing 
 laws. This revelation is also useless. If adequate 
 agencies exist, the faith in the moral economy which 
 pervades the universe forces us to believe that no 
 supernatural interposition will be furnished when 
 natural appliances suffice. It is also demoralizing
 
 SUMMARY OF KAXT's ETHICAL THP:OKY. 229 
 
 when contrasted with higher and purer intluences. All 
 conceivable supernatural influences, in the Kantian 
 judgment, address the personal sensibility and appeal 
 to the pathological emotions. Interesting as these 
 may be, and practically effective in the actual affaii's 
 of men, when ethically judged they must be relegated 
 to a lower plane than those which the practical reason 
 presents when it addresses man's autonomous will. 
 Indeed, properly speaking, these influences have no 
 ethical value, but are simply auxiliary to impressions 
 that have no place within the moral in men. If not 
 always anti-ethical, they are at least unethical. The 
 personal character of the Great Exemplar, though it 
 incarnated the ideal of human excellence, and so far 
 is transcendentally elevating, gains nothing in purely 
 ethical force by being real, but rather loses, inas- 
 much as it blends with the purely ethical the per- 
 sonal, which appeals to the affections rather than to 
 the conscience, and moves upon the self-centred im- 
 pulses rather than the simple sense of duty. What- 
 ever may be urged in support of tiie supernatural 
 power of the supernatural Christ can in no sense be 
 recognized among the highest influences, but must 
 be conceded to human weakness, and to the tem- 
 porary predominance of inferior impulses. 
 
 Kant does indeed find a great ethical truth in the
 
 230 kant's ethics. 
 
 perversion of human nature, and in the predom- 
 inance and persistence of those lower impulses which 
 inwardly struggle against the law of duty, and make 
 the sense of obligation so potent and so fearful. 
 But he holds this tenet rather as a myth which illus- 
 trates what he conceives to be a subjective ethical 
 truth, than as having any other significance, while 
 the sacred history of redemption from this moral 
 depravity is to him only a mythic parable, made up 
 of the sensuous drapery of those great moral verities 
 which give it its interest and its power. 
 
 No fact is more notorious, and none more sig- 
 nificant, than that the Kantian Ethics have been a 
 significant and oftentimes a destructive element, 
 whether confessed or unconscious, in the many philo- 
 sophical and historical arguments which have been 
 urged against supernatural Christianity. It may be 
 added that the theory of ethics which does not need 
 a personal Deity to enforce the law of duty, because 
 the law of duty is self-sufficing, or which rejects Him 
 because, forsooth. His efficient authority must address 
 man's sensibility to the personal favor or displeasure 
 of his moral ruler, cannot but labor under a heavy 
 burden of disadvantage when it aspires to a faith in 
 a personal Father in Heaven, or the supernatural 
 Christ, by whom God is manifested to man through
 
 SUMMARY OF KAXT^S ETHICAL THEORY. 231 
 
 human aftections and human sympathies, in order to 
 lift him to that moral perfection which reveals itself 
 as the ideal of every human soul that finds in the 
 end of its being the law of duty, and in its adjusted 
 and purified sensibilities the realization of that 
 blessedness which is the true spiritual life.
 
 CHAPTER V. 
 
 BRIEF NOTICES FROM EMINENT GERMAN 
 CRITICS. 
 
 § 116. It does not fall within tbe plan of this 
 essay to trace the fortunes of Kant's eth- introductory, 
 ical theory in Germany, or to exhibit the criticisms 
 which it has received from the several schools in 
 philosophy which in that country have succeeded one 
 another so rapidly during the present century. 
 Each one of these schools has given more or less 
 attention to ethics, but no one of them has given 
 such prominence to ethical relations as has Kant. 
 Certainly no one has sought as he did to make ethical 
 truth the foundation of speculative philosophy. On 
 the other hand, each one of these eminent leaders of 
 philosophical opinion made ethics subservient to his 
 special philosophy, making the pi-actical to sit at the 
 feet of the speculative reason. While ethics has 
 been held in unfeigned honor in all the modern 
 schools, she has never ventured to speak with such 
 positive authority through the categorical impera- 
 tive, or to stand as sponsor for every species of phi- 
 
 232
 
 BRIEF NOTICES FROM GKUMAX CRITICS. '-iSS 
 
 losophical truth as she has done in the school of 
 Kant. It was not without an occasional earnest 
 pi'otest to the contrary that this was done in Kant's 
 own time. We give the impassioned language of 
 Schiller as an example of the response which Kant's 
 extreme onesidedness called forth from one of his 
 earnest admirers, and also as explaining the mis- 
 chievous practical reaction which was occasioned by 
 Kant's dogmatic extremes: 
 
 § 117. " In Kant's moral philosophy the idea of 
 duty is represented with a harshness 
 
 Schiller's 
 
 which frightened away all the gentler comments on 
 
 p Tx* J • 1 J- -1 i. i. Kant's Ethics. 
 
 graces ot hie, and might easily tempt 
 a weak understanding to seek for moral perfection 
 in the way of a gloomy and monkish asceticism. 
 However earnestly the great philosopher may have 
 sought to guard himself against such a misrepre- 
 sentation, which to his free and noble spirit must 
 have been most offensive, he has yet given occasion 
 for it by the forcible and striking contrast between 
 the antagonistic principles, which he represents as 
 contending for the mastery of the human will. In 
 respect to the truth of his theory there can be no 
 question among thinking men after the arguments 
 which he has urged, and I scarcely know how one 
 would not sooner give up his manhood than adopt
 
 334 K A NT's ETHICS. 
 
 any other conclusion than his. And yet, purely as 
 he proceeded to his task as an inquiry for the truth, 
 and satisfactorily as he conducted his argument 
 upon objective grounds, he still appears to me to 
 have been influenced by certain subjective reasons, 
 which, as I think, are easily explained by the cir- 
 cumstances of his times. 
 
 "The morality of his times as he found it, in both 
 theory and practice, must have outraged him, on the 
 one hand, by the gross sensualism of its practices, 
 and by the unworthy readiness of its philosophers to 
 sanction this corruption by their lax theories. On 
 the other hand, a scarcely less objectionable principle 
 of perfectibility aroused his opposition, which, in order 
 to realize an abstract idea of universal perfection, 
 was by no means sci'upulous in the selection of the 
 means. For these reasons he directed the most 
 cogent of his arguments toward the points where 
 the danger was most imminent and the reform was 
 most needed, and made it at once a solemn obligation 
 to attack sensuality, as well when with brazen front 
 it outraged all moral feeling as when it assumed 
 that imposing garb of high moral aims in which a 
 certain enthusiastic party spirit knew how to array 
 it. For it should be remembered that he had not 
 ignorance to instruct, but perverseness to reprove
 
 BRIEF NOTICES FROM GERMAN CRITICS. 235 
 
 and reclaim. The cure demanded rebuke, not flat- 
 tery or persuasion, and the more striking was the con- 
 trast which the truth presented to current maxims, 
 the more could he hope to arouse his age to reflec- 
 tion. He became the Draco of his time, because his 
 time was not worthy of a Solon, or capable of 
 receiving him. From the sanctuary of pure reason 
 he brought forth the moral law at once so little 
 known and yet so well known, held it up in its 
 austere sanctity before a degraded generation, and 
 cared not to ask whether it had eyes which could not 
 endure the brightness of its purity. 
 
 "But in what had the children of the household 
 offended so grievously that Kant cared only for the 
 servants? Because impure inclinations had usurped 
 the name of virtue, must the most disinterested 
 affections in the noblest hearts be brought under 
 suspicion? Because the moral weakling would in- 
 terpret the law of reason with a laxness which 
 makes it a plaything at his convenience, ought it for 
 this reason to be invested with a rigidity so extreme 
 as would only change the vigorous expression of 
 moral freedom into a more honorable form of bond- 
 age? Has not the truly moral man a freer choice 
 between self-esteem and self-contempt than the slave 
 of sense has between pleasure and pain? Is there in
 
 236 rant's ethics. 
 
 the one case any less constraint for the pure will 
 than in the other for the will that is corrupt? 
 Must humanity itself be indicted and degraded by 
 the imperative form of the moral law, and must 
 the noblest assertion of its greatness become the 
 most abject confession of its weakness? Should not 
 this form of command have precluded the impression 
 that the obligation which man imposes on himself as 
 a rational being, and which for this very reason 
 alone is binding on himself, is reconcilable with his 
 feeling of freedom, and for this reason should it not 
 have avoided the appearance of a foreign and posi- 
 tive command, an appearance which by the radical 
 inclination to act against the same, that is charged 
 upon man, could with difficulty be set aside ? * * * 
 
 " Human nature is, in fact, a more closel}'^ com- 
 pacted whole than it is permitted to philosophei's 
 to allow it to appear, who seem to be unable to 
 accomplish anything except by the process of dissec- 
 tion. Never again can the reason reject, as un- 
 worthy of itself, those affections which the heart 
 confesses with joy, and which every man cannot but 
 exalt in his own esteem, even when he is himself 
 morally degraded. Were the emotional nature uni- 
 formly the depressed and never the cooperative 
 agency, how could it bring the lire of its own emo-
 
 BKIEF NOTICES FEOM GERMAN" CRITICS. 337 
 
 tions even to that triumph which is celebrated over 
 itself ■? How could it be so active a participant in 
 the conscious experience of the pure spirit if it were 
 not so intimately interwoven with the same that 
 even the analytical understanding cannot, without 
 violence, sunder the two? The will, moreover, has 
 a more immediate connection with the capacity for 
 emotion than with that for knowledge, and it were 
 often most unfortunate if in every case it must first 
 adjust itself to the pure reason." — Veber Anmuth 
 und Wfirde* 
 
 We have given these extracts from Schiller because 
 they furnish a vivid and a truthful representation of 
 the impression which Kant's theory made upon an ar- 
 
 *0f this criticism of Schiller, Julius Miiller pertinently remarks: 
 " It will in any event remain as an example of a memorable error of a 
 noble mind that Kant could maintain that true virtue has nothing to 
 do with sympathizing benevolence toward man, or with the interest of 
 the feelings in man's welfare, and can only manifest itself in its 
 purity when it is attended by no pleasure in the object of our will. 
 And yet these consequences cannot be avoided if the essence of 
 morality is derived only from esteem for the moral law, and for the 
 reason that this law bears the formal characteristic of universal valid- 
 ity. Schiller's treatise, Ueber Anmuth und Wiirde, so far as it protests 
 against this rigor which petrifies the moral life, gives expression to the 
 aspirations of Christian truth; but in so far as it will not give up the 
 general principles of the Kantian moral law it is incapable of holding 
 fast to those truths, or of escaping a conflict with itself. An example 
 of this is furnished in its singular complaint against Kanfs morality, 
 that by the imperative form of the moral law (for the very reason 
 that it is a law asserting authority over freedom) humanity itself is 
 held to be degraded."— /Jie Christ liche Lehre von der SOnde, Ersfes 
 Buck, Erste Abfheilung, Zweifes Kajntel. _
 
 338 rant's ethics. 
 
 dent admirer, who was yet an independent critic. 
 While Schiller did not attempt to refute Kant's meta- 
 physical analyses, he was convinced there was some 
 error in his practical conclusions, and indeed in the 
 actual working of his entire ethical theory. The re- 
 volt of his feelings against this theory was shared by 
 a very large proportion of the brilliant writers who 
 followed one another so rapidly, among whom Goethe 
 was as conspicuous for his philosophical insight as 
 for his wondrous imagination. That Kant should 
 have failed to convince this brilliant galaxy of ima- 
 ginative writers, who, while they were overpowered 
 by the acuteness and strength of his logic, and 
 dared not venture to meet him in the arena of 
 metaphysics, were yet confident that his analyses 
 must be either defective or false, goes very far to 
 prove that his ethics, though practically his strong- 
 est point, was in some particulars seriously defec- 
 tive, and especially for its stoical contempt of the 
 sensibilities. That Kant was animated by the 
 noblest purposes in his ethical teachings was freely 
 confessed by those who, like Schiller, were at once 
 his critics and admirers. That the extremest of his 
 one-sided paradoxes may admit of a qualified inter- 
 pretation whicli exalts them into important practical 
 truths may be acknowledged without hesitation by
 
 BRIEF NOTICES FKOM GERMAN CRITICS. 239 
 
 those who reject them the more positively because 
 they see in them an incongruous alternation of im- 
 aginative flights into the empyrean of inspiring 
 truth and of patient mining along the dark and wind- 
 ing passages of bewildering metaphysics. 
 
 § 117. The fact has already been adverted to, 
 that, with one or two important excep- schieiennacii- 
 tions, the theory of ethics has attracted ^^ ^^i Lotze. 
 much less attention since the days of Kant, as a part 
 of speculative philosophy, and least of all has it 
 been recognized, as it was by Kant, as furnishing to 
 speculative truth its sole and solid foundation. While 
 each of the great systems, as of J. G. Fichte, Schel- 
 ling, Herbart, and Hegel, has found as ample a place 
 for ethics in terms of reason or thought, as did 
 Kant, no one of these writers like him has made it 
 the cornerstone of our confidence in speculative 
 truth, or invested its dicta with supreme author- 
 ity. To Schleiermacher belongs the distinction of 
 producing an original system, which was derived 
 from or adjusted to the characteristic philosophy or 
 dialectic which was peculiar to himself. This dia- 
 lectic we have no space to describe, nor would it be 
 easy to do so. We speak of his ethics only as 
 dissenting from the ethics of Kant, in that it does 
 not limit its sphere to the imperative of duty as
 
 240 rant's ethics. 
 
 such, but divides it into three distinct departments, 
 the doctrine of duties, or obligatory acts; of virtues, 
 or of ethical dispositions ; and of habits, or confirmed 
 character. That this classification must rest on a 
 broader psychological and philosophical basis than 
 Kant's practical reason, with its categorical impera- 
 tive and its autonomous will, is too obvious to 
 req.uire any illustration. Both Schleiermacher and 
 Herbart notoriously differ from Kant in their recog- 
 nition of the sensibilities as a prime factor in the 
 ethical experiences and judgments of man. 
 
 Hermann Lotze is another example of a writer 
 of competent knowledge, profound insight, and im- 
 partial judgment, from whose Microcosmus, B. V., 
 Chap, v., § 3, we give the following, observing that 
 in this connection he also notices one or two con- 
 spicuous features of the later ethical systems: 
 
 " * * * There is no doubt something to praise in 
 the austerity with which pi'actical philosophy has 
 sought to free moral precepts from an indirect 
 reference to the personal interest of the agent; but 
 this austerity was wrong in seeking to undo the 
 plain and indissoluble connection between the notion 
 of pleasure — despised, and in most of its applica- 
 tions despicable — and the notion of worth in gen- 
 eral. When Kant believed that he had found a
 
 BRIEF NOTICES FROM GERMAN CRITICS. 241 
 
 universal formula for moral action, in opposition to 
 the aims of self-interest, he was candid enough to 
 admit that he had not discovered in it the precise 
 ground of its binding authority over us. And why, 
 in fact, do we consider it as a matter of course that 
 the maxims of our action must fit into a general sys- 
 tem of law? And which are the maxims which do 
 not thus fit in? Plainly those which, if generally 
 followed, would produce general disorder and the 
 frustration of all effort. But what is this acknowl- 
 edgment of the importance of order, and of the possi- 
 bility of carrying out our intention, if it is not either 
 
 (1) a grand and comprehensive utilitarian principle 
 taking the place of special and narrower ones, or 
 
 (2) the confession that maxims different from those 
 demanded would lead to general misery, and are, 
 therefore, to be rejected? Other systems, while 
 eschewing all pleasure, assure us that the moral law 
 is the one important thing; that the relation of a 
 finite being to the absolute, like that of any point of 
 the periphery to its centre, is a relation of subordin- 
 ation; that human will runs parallel to the develop- 
 ment of the infinite idea, and works for it. But 
 how if the absolute should not desire such a relation? 
 If the submission of the periphery caused only vex- 
 ation to the centre, could it be still maintained that 
 
 16
 
 242 kant's ethics. 
 
 this relation was, notwithstanding, to be maintained 
 as unconditionally worthy in itself? 
 
 " This question should remind us that the sacred- 
 ness of the command depends upon the will of the 
 Supreme Being, upon His capacity of receiving 
 pleasure or pain from our obedience or disobedience, 
 and upon that relation of ourselves to Him, in virtue 
 of which we find our own blessedness in His pleasure. 
 If we eliminate from our conception of the Supreme 
 Being every trace of feeling, and transform our 
 conception into that of inflexible physical force, a 
 power which, though intelligent, is devoid of feeling, 
 we see at once that the subordination above referred 
 to is altogether without worth. * * * 
 
 " What is the meaning of saying that there may 
 be certain relations between diiferent wills, which 
 merit unconditional approbation? Is such a relation 
 to be found anywhere in the world? Are there any- 
 where wills which, apart from all feeling, actually 
 exist, and can enter into relation with one another? 
 And if it were so — if the world consisted of beings 
 that were m.erely intellectual and volitional, and of 
 which none, whether finite or infinite, could anyhow 
 or at any time be capable of feeling pain or pleasure, 
 in such a case what could be the significance of 
 those ideals of action which then would have no one
 
 BftlEP NOTICES FROM GERMAN CRITICS. 243 
 
 Ity whom they could be approved? As a matter of 
 fact, would it be an absolute moral requirement that 
 one existing condition, which caused neither pain nor 
 pleasure to anyone, should be replaced by another 
 condition which would likewise produce no increase 
 of well-being to anyone in the world? Must we 
 believe that the universe is so taken up with cere- 
 mony that it is concerned with nothing but the real- 
 ization of formal conditions? The too stern morality 
 to which we have referred may easily conceal from 
 itself these final results, the transformation of all 
 moral action into, as it were, a mere mechanical 
 putting together; for certainly no one is likely to 
 set up individual moral laws in which there does 
 not lurk some hidden reference to the pleasure 
 which is so much despised; in other departments of 
 life these extreme consequences do occasionally 
 appear." 
 
 § 118. One of the most significant criticisms of 
 Kant's theory from a philosopher of a Trendeien- 
 modern German school has been fur- (^"/ig^jj^es 
 nished by the late eminent Adolf Tren- »" Kant. 
 delenburg, of Berlin. It may be found in bis His- 
 torische Beitrtige zur Philosophic, Dritter Band, Bei*- 
 lin, 1867. The title of the essay is, Der Widerstreit 
 zwischen Kant und Aristoteles in der Ethik.
 
 244 Kant's ethics. 
 
 The first point which the author makes is, that 
 while Kant urges acute objections against those 
 philosophers who would derive the principles of 
 ethics from an anal3'sis of human nature, he alto- 
 gether omits the peculiar form in which this analy- 
 sis is applied by Aristotle. Whereas Aristotle has 
 recognized the inner purpose or end which controls 
 and explains the constitution of man and the activi- 
 ties to which it is destined as its highest and best 
 use, Kant only conceives of this as some external 
 result or achievement, activity, or skill, to which it 
 may be trained. Trendelenburg notices in passing 
 that in order to discover this supreme aim or pur- 
 pose of man's being or constitution, Aristotle would 
 have us resort to psychology, which Kant would 
 reject as involving the study of matter as distin- 
 guished from form, the accidental rather than the 
 essential, and therefore as unscientific. 
 
 Next, Kant insists that all material practical 
 principles must carry us over to the doctrine of 
 self-love or separate, i.e., individual, happiness. This 
 general assertion is met by Trendelenburg with the 
 general denial, that to found our principle in the mat- 
 ter or constitution of man does not necessarily involve 
 the founding it in separate happiness or the so-called 
 principle of self-love. It is the necessary relation
 
 BRIEF NOTICES FROM GEK.MAX CRITICS. 245 
 
 of a morally good or right action to the realization 
 of the end of our being which enables us to exalt 
 this ideal into a principle which becomes controlling 
 and supreme. That its relations to the highest 
 happiness may be the medium by which we discern 
 the activity for which we are destined he concedes, 
 but that happiness is properl}' the end, he denies, but 
 would say the action indicated by the relative hap- 
 piness which it gives is such an end and becomes a 
 law. In brief, he dissents from Kant in his inter- 
 pretation of Aristotle, as to his estimate of the 
 psychological study of man's nature as the ground 
 of an ethical system, as to his judgment of the rela- 
 tion of the formal to the real, and as to his recogni- 
 tion of purpose and design as essential to the inter- 
 pretation of the nature of man, and of man's highest 
 or true happiness as the indication of the highest 
 and best activity, and as, consequently, the revealer 
 and enforcer of the moral law. 
 
 These principles are more distinctly and fully 
 developed in the second part of the essay, from 
 which we give the following: 
 
 Fii'st of all, the author notices that, inasmuch as 
 pleasure {die Lust), being the spring of the indi- 
 vidual life, tends to selfishness, while the good, the 
 bond of the common life, seeks the general well-
 
 ;i46 kant's ethics. 
 
 being, subordinating to it the individual interest, 
 the mutual relation of the two necessarily becomes 
 of the utmost ethical importance. 
 
 After sundry historical and critical notices, he 
 adds that pleasure, ever varied and changeable, can- 
 not for this reason be a guide in action and in life. 
 Neither the highest scale of mere enjoyment, as 
 such, nor any separate good, can serve as a guide or 
 impulse to the general good. Consequently the good 
 will must renounce all separate or selfish good as its 
 end or rule. But it does not follow from this that 
 the good will has no pleasure. Rather, over against 
 selfish good is set its esteem for the law, as that which 
 opposes selfish good, its pleasure being intellectual 
 in its occasion. Moreover, this esteem for the law 
 being general, and not individual in its occasion, is 
 not a transient feeling, but permanent in its expe- 
 rience, a disposition which cannot be content with 
 single actions, but is a permanent state of the will. 
 
 It also involves a superior object of love; for the 
 disposition and will are not cold abstractions, but 
 living activities, which are fixed on commanding 
 objects of good. In such a condition of the soul, 
 impulse and end, a good will and good actions, cor- 
 respond; pure pleasure in the good becomes the 
 constant characteristic of the good disposition.
 
 BRIEF NOTICES FROM GERMAN CRITICS. 247 
 The crood man delicrhts in the law of God after the 
 
 n o 
 
 inward man. In the good disposition character con- 
 sists; and if character is energetic, it will have 
 pleasure in its principle. 
 
 It follows from this analysis that pleasure is at 
 once repelled and embraced; repelled as a ground, 
 and yet retained as a characteristic of virtue. We 
 cannot reconcile the difficulty by making, the good 
 man selfish in his virtiious joys. We rather resort 
 to the organic conception of nature and man, after 
 which one result or aim serves an end or aim still 
 higher than itself, and so on, the highest of all 
 giving law to all which is below. In the highest of 
 all we find the categorical shall, which at last is 
 found to proceed from a will, i.e., if one follows on 
 from the conditioned to the unconditioned, and at 
 last encounters a person. Here we meet the highest 
 for man in the universe of thought and will — the 
 man asserting I ought, the man responding I icill. 
 
 When we come back to the relations of pleasure 
 or happiness to these experiences, and ask for the 
 place which it holds, we find that it is a generic 
 term, and covers or includes a great variety of very 
 iinlike experiences, so unlike as to accept or endure 
 with difficulty any common appellation, yet all hav- 
 ing in common, a tendency to some special activity,
 
 248 kant's ethics. 
 
 which tends in some way to the development or 
 upholding of man. In the two forms of pleasure 
 and pain are indicated the furtherance or hindrance 
 of the individual life. So far as pleasure and pain 
 look beyond, to their respective ends, these expe- 
 riences are secondary and the accomplishment of the 
 end is primary. In animals they are limited to the 
 individual well-being. But in ethics and with man 
 we go farther; we widen our conceptions so as to 
 include the common life. Personality and the state 
 are recognized, also the higher pleasures of art and 
 science and the divine in man. 
 
 The moral training of the will consists in learning 
 to find pleasure and pain in those activities and 
 objects which are befitting. Let no man think that 
 such a discipline can be achieved by the exclusion of 
 pleasure. The springs of action are wanting to the 
 will if the man does not embark in it his inmost 
 life, and does not find his pleasures from moral 
 living; not that he should be active for the sake of 
 pleasure, but should embark his inmost self, without 
 ceasing, in the good. 
 
 " These extracts from writers who are no longer 
 living will be sufficient for our purpose. The num- 
 ber of able critics in Germany who continue to
 
 BKIEF KOTICES FUOM GERMAN CRITICS. 'HO 
 
 discuss Kant's ethical theory seems likely to increase 
 rather than to be diminished. The fascination 
 which brings each new generation to his feet to 
 listen to his teachings — either to accept or reject 
 them — seems of late to be intensified rather than to 
 be weakened. In one way or other, Kant seems likely 
 to continue to stimulate and to instruct the ablest 
 thinkers of the present day. The author of this 
 critical examination of his ethical system yields to 
 no one in his estimate of Kant's superior genius and 
 his quickening power. At the same time he is 
 profoundly of the opinion that the critical philoso- 
 phy, in order to exert its best influence, needs to 
 be thoroughly interpreted, and critically discerned.
 
 i .. . i 
 
 f
 
 
 /■^ciCJiF^ 
 
 .-kjiiC' **A^^ 
 
 ^=gk^\; ''
 
 UC SOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY 
 
 A A 001 415 168 2 
 
 JfTj/MAC,