LIBRARY 
 
 OF THC 
 
 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA. 
 
 Received jan 11 ]H93 - '^9 
 Accessions No. Hqqi'^1. . Class No. 
 
 ^n 
 
 UBlMSr 
 
I 
 
ELEMENTS OF PSYCHOLOGY 
 
 BY 
 
 NOAH K. DAVIS, Ph.D., LL.D. 
 
 Peofessob op Moral Philosophy in the University op Virginia 
 
 E coelo descendit : yvQ9i (reavrSv 
 
 ^•^ OP THB ^« 
 
 SILVER, BURDETT & CO., PUBLISHERS 
 New York BOSTON Chicago 
 
 1892 
 
EDUC. 
 
 PSYCH. 
 
 UBRARY 
 
 GHT 
 
 By silver, BURDETT & CO. 
 
 Copyright, 1892, 
 
 Typography by J. 8. Cdshing & Co., Boston. 
 
 Presswork by Berwick & Smith, Boston. 
 
PREFACE. 
 
 This treatise is intended primarily for those who have 
 not already studied psychology, and now propose to give it 
 thoughtful attention. It is therefore elementary, as its title 
 indicates, and is introductory to the abundant and growing 
 literature of the science. Though no previous acquaintance 
 with the subject is requisite, yet as it can by no means be 
 made light and easy, even an elementary treatise must pre- 
 suppose mental maturity in the reader, and habits of thought- 
 ful study. For him I have tried to prepare a statement of 
 psychological doctrine, broad and true, on which he may 
 build by his own thinking and wider reading. If his occu- 
 pations do not permit this, he will at least have acquired a 
 rounded knowledge of the generally approved principles and 
 chief features of the science. 
 
 A reader already acquainted with the history and litera- 
 ture of psychology will find many familiar things restated. 
 Let him remember that the treatise is for the novice. But 
 he will find some familiar things modified, and some things 
 new. A few may be indicated as follows : The material 
 object immediately perceived ; the argument for immediate 
 perception ; the modified view of intuition ; the argument 
 for duality ; the relation of feeling to cognition ; the char- 
 acter and place assigned to belief ; the separation of feeling 
 
 111 
 
iv PREFACE. 
 
 and desire ; the defence of freedom in willing. On these 
 and other points I earnestly ask for a candid and critical 
 judgment. I care for nothing but truth in the matter, and 
 will heartily join in condemning all else. 
 
 The portion calling for study is given in the main text. 
 It is logically developed, with exact definitions adhered to 
 throughout. Into the many marginal notes are gathered 
 citations of authorities and references to those within easy 
 reach, quotations from general literature, explanatory re- 
 marks, examples, illustrations, — indeed, all sorts of items, 
 some of them mere trifles, the general intent being to en- 
 liven the terse and dry statements thus annotated. 
 
 The style is didactic. Above all things, I have tried to be 
 accurate, concise, and clear, and as simple as possible. It 
 would be much easier to write learnedly and obscurely, and 
 so be judged profound ; but I am willing to take the risk of 
 slight esteem, hoping to be clearly understood. 
 
 The matter of this treatise has been the basis of my 
 teaching for twenty years, with modifications and additions 
 from time to time, so as to include the approved results of 
 the most recent investigations. The interest which my 
 pupils have taken in the subject, and the general favor 
 which has been shown to my treatise on Logic, entitled 
 "The Theory of Thought," encourage the hope that this 
 work also may be found useful. 
 
CONTENTS. 
 
 PHYSIOLOGICAL INTRODUCTION. 
 
 I. The Cephalic Senses. 
 
 PAGE 
 
 § 1. A preliminary physiological view needful 1 
 
 § 2. Logical distribution of the senses 1 
 
 § 3. Of smell — its organ and excitant 2 
 
 § 4. Its relatively sensuous character 3 
 
 § 5. Its percept, odor, a quality or phenomenon of brain 4 
 
 § G. The percept not consciously located 5 
 
 § 7. Of taste — its organ, excitant, sensuousness 5 
 
 § 8. Its percept, savor, a quality or phenomenon of brain 6 
 
 § 9. Analogies of smell and taste 7 
 
 § 10. Of hearing — its organ and excitant 7 
 
 § 11. Its relatively perceptive character 8 
 
 § 12. Its percept, soimd, a quality or phenomenon of brain 8 
 
 § 13. The percept not consciously located 9 
 
 § 14. Binaural audition affords proof that it is intercranial 9 
 
 § 15. Of sight — its organ and excitant 10 
 
 § IG. Its relatively perceptive charactei- 10 
 
 § 17. Its primary percept, color, a cerebral phenomenon 11 
 
 § 18. Binocular vision affords proof 12 
 
 § 19. Its secondary percept, extension. The field of view^ 13 
 
 § 20. Analogies of hearing and sight 14 
 
 § 21. The immediate object in perception 15 
 
 II. The Somatic Senses. 
 
 § 22, Of touch — its organ. The intermediary 17 
 
 § 23. The sensation. Its primary percept, tangibility 18 
 
 § 24. Its secondary percept, extension 19 
 
 § 25. Erroneous views concerning touch 20 
 
 § 26. Of muscular sense — its organ and stimulant 20 
 
 V 
 
vi CONTENTS. 
 
 PAGE 
 
 § 27. The sensation. Its percept, solidity 20 
 
 § 28. Illustrative examples 21 
 
 § 29. The sensus vagus. Temperature. Pure pain 23 
 
 § 30. No knowledge of the outer world given by sense alone 25 
 
 III. The Nervous Organism. 
 
 § 31. The sympathetic system 26 
 
 § 32. The cerebro-spinal system — its distribution 26 
 
 § 33. The cerebral nerves 27 
 
 § 34. The spinal cord and nerves 27 
 
 § 35. The nervous circuit 28 
 
 § 36. Neural reilex action 28 
 
 § 37. Muscular dexterity or habit 29 
 
 § 38. Anatomy of the brain 31 
 
 § 39. "White and gray matter — its distribution 31 
 
 § 40. Cerebral localization 32 
 
 § 41. Unconscious cerebration 33 
 
 § 42. Psychology not dependent on neurology 34 
 
 IV. PhT SIC LOGICAL PSTCHOLOGT. 
 
 § 43. Comprehension of this title 35 
 
 § 44. Historical notices 36 
 
 § 45. P.sycho-physics. Fechner'.s law 37 
 
 § 46. Its critics. Results summarized 39 
 
 § 47. Psychometry — its methods and results 40 
 
 § 48. Limitations of physiological psychology 42 
 
 § 49. Relation of pure to mixed psychology 44 
 
 PART FIRST. — CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 I. Preliminary Definitions. 
 
 §50. Psychology defined. Explication of terms 47 
 
 § 51. The ego and non-ego ^2 
 
 § 52. Subject and object 53 
 
 § 53. Mental powers and activities 55 
 
 II. Generality of Consciousness. 
 
 § 54. Consciousness the suminum genus ^^ 
 
 § 55. Its logical content ^^ 
 
CONTENTS. VU 
 
 III. CoNDlxroNS OF Consciousness. 
 
 FAQB 
 
 § 56. Opposition, a condition of its existence 59 
 
 § 57. Change, a condition of its continuance 60 
 
 § 58. Law of relativity , 60 
 
 § 59. Shock of difference, and of similarity 61 
 
 IV. Limits of Consciousness. 
 
 § 60. It is of the actual, not of the potential 62 
 
 § 6L Of the present, not of the past 62 
 
 § 62. Of the positive, not of the negative 63 
 
 § 63. Are we always conscious ? 63 
 
 § 64. Are we conscious of several things at once ? 64 
 
 § 65. Are there unconscious mental activities ? 65 
 
 V. Facts of Consciousness. 
 
 § 66. Description of the facts of consciousness 68 
 
 § 67. Their essential characters , 69 
 
 § 68, Their enforced acceptance 69 
 
 § 69. Their distinguishing criterion 70 
 
 § 70. Their fundamental importance 71 
 
 VI. Modes of Consciousness. 
 
 § 71. The generic powers. Scheme 72 
 
 § 72. Cognition 73 
 
 § 73. Feeling 74 
 
 § 74. Desire 74 
 
 § 75. Volition 75 
 
 § 76. The specific powers. Scheme 75 
 
 § 77. Unity of mind 75 
 
 § 78. Simultaneity of its activities 76 
 
 PAET SECOND. — IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 I. Cognition. 
 
 § 79. Definition and division of cognition 77 
 
 § 80. Is a comparison and a judgment 78 
 
 § 81. Conditions the other powers 79 
 
 § 82. Attention defined 79 
 
 § 83. Law of Limitation 80 
 
 § 84. Observation and reflection 81 
 
viii CONTENTS. 
 
 PAGE 
 
 § 85. Indefinite or expectant attention 82 
 
 § 86. Involuntary attention. Distraction 82 
 
 § 87. "Voluntary attention. Abstraction 83 
 
 § 88. Is plural attention possible ? 83 
 
 § 89. Tbe sole function of will. Importance of 85 
 
 II. Presentation. 
 
 § 90. Definition and division 87 
 
 § 91. The object given to consciousness 87 
 
 § 92. Representation discriminated 88 
 
 § 93. Presentations, many ; representation, one 89 
 
 § 94. Illustrative examples 89 
 
 III. Perception. 
 
 § 95. Definitions. The percept 91 
 
 § 96. Organs of sense eliminated 91 
 
 § 97. Sensation and perception set apart 92 
 
 § 98. Data of perception strictly stated 93 
 
 § 99. Passivity in perception 94 
 
 IV. External Reality. 
 
 § 100. Doctrine of immediate perception 96 
 
 § 101. Argument in support of 97 
 
 § 102. Replies to adverse view 99 
 
 § 103. Perception of primary qualities of body requisite 100 
 
 § 104. Found in tactile and muscular senses 100 
 
 § 105. Extra-organic body given in voluntary movement 101 
 
 § 106. Outer world given in manipulation 103 
 
 § 107. Order of development unknown 103 
 
 V. Self-Pekceition. 
 
 § 108. Definition. Internal sense 105 
 
 § 109. Distinguished from self-consciousness 105 
 
 § 110. Distinguished from perception 106 
 
 § 111. Subdivision. Introspection. Example 106 
 
 §112. Reflection, Representative. Postponed 107 
 
 VI. Pure Intuition. 
 
 § 113. Intuitions divided. The pure defined 108 
 
 § 114. Examples of pure ideas 109 
 
 § 115. They are abstract 110 
 
COJS'TENTS. IX 
 
 PAGE 
 
 § 116. They are catholic » Ill 
 
 § 117. They are self-evident ; Ill 
 
 § 118. They are certain 112 
 
 § 110. They are necessary. Examples 113 
 
 § 120. They are strictly universal 114 
 
 § 121. Three kinds of general truth 115 
 
 § 122. Catholicity and universality distinguished 110 
 
 § 123. No classification effected 117 
 
 VII. Origin of Pure Truth. 
 
 § 124. Questions stated 118 
 
 § 125, Empiricism. Locke and Mill 118 
 
 § 126. Reply to empiricism. Syllogisms 120 
 
 § 127. Intuitionism. Leibnitz 122 
 
 § 128. Kant. Mansel 123 
 
 § 129. The doctrine restated 125 
 
 § 130. PrefeiTed view. Pure truth objective 126 
 
 § 131. Pure ideas representative 128 
 
 § 132. Objective ground of necessity and universality 129 
 
 § 133. This theory distinct from empiricism 130 
 
 § 134. The discussion metaphysical 131 
 
 VIII. Mind and Matter. 
 
 § 135. Substance intuitive. Monism and Dualism , 132 
 
 § 136. Idealism — its various forms 133 
 
 § 137. Idealists self-contradictory 135 
 
 § 138. Materialism — its creed 136 
 
 § 139. Its doctrine stated 137 
 
 § 140. Its inconceivability an unsound objection 138 
 
 § 141. Three philosophic objections 139 
 
 § 142. Absolute identity — its doctrine 141 
 
 § 143. Concomitant variations do not prove it 142 
 
 § 144. Reduces to other forms of monism 143 
 
 § 145. Dualism — its doctrine and gi'ound 144 
 
 § 146. Proved, as opposed to idealism 145 
 
 § 147. Proved, as opposed to materialism 146 
 
 § 148. Mind and brain correlated 148 
 
 § 149. Mind not related to space 148 
 
 PART THIRD. — MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 I. Representation. 
 
 § 150. Definition. Discriminated from presentation 150 
 
 § 151. Division. Relations of condition 151 
 
§152. 
 
 § 153. 
 
 § 154. 
 
 § 155. 
 
 §156. 
 
 § 157. 
 
 § 158. 
 
 §159. 
 
 §160. 
 
 §161. 
 
 §162. 
 
 § 163. 
 
 §164. 
 
 § 165. 
 
 § 166. 
 
 §167. 
 
 §168. 
 
 § 169. 
 
 §170. 
 
 § 171. 
 
 §172. 
 
 § 173. 
 
 §174. 
 
 §175. 
 
 §176. 
 
 §177. 
 
 §178. 
 
 §170. 
 
 §180. 
 
 §181. 
 
 §182. 
 
 § 183. 
 
 §184. 
 
 §185. 
 
 § 186. 
 
 §187. 
 
 §188. 
 
 § 189. 
 
 CONTENTS. 
 
 PAGE 
 
 The medium, an object perceived 152 
 
 The medium, a mental image or idea 154 
 
 Locality merely represented 155 
 
 Mental images sensuous — from exi^erience 155 
 
 Ideas always representative — in two modes 157 
 
 II. Mediate Perception. 
 
 Distinguished from perception proper 158 
 
 Genesis of a case 150 
 
 Genesis generally stated — four steps 159 
 
 LiabiUty to illusion and error 160 
 
 Eeview of the fourth step in the genesis 161 
 
 Perception of spatial relations 162 
 
 Unity and plurality in space 163 
 
 Solidity and shape of outer things 164 
 
 The direction of objects in space 167 
 
 Direction as judged by hearing 168 
 
 The size and distance of objects 169 
 
 Analysis of this mediate perception 170 
 
 Perspective, ground and aerial 172 
 
 Location of tactile percepts on the body 173 
 
 Location of sense-percepts beyond the body 175 
 
 III. Suggestion. 
 
 Sequence of mental states — of two kinds 177 
 
 Law of similarity — contraries 178 
 
 Law of association or redintegration 179 
 
 Order in association — loss of links 180 
 
 Multiplicity of simultaneous revivals 181 
 
 Indissoluble associations 182 
 
 Wide generality of this law 183 
 
 Law of preference. Four points 184 
 
 The associational school — disapproved 186 
 
 IV. Memory. 
 
 Definition. Theory of repetition 187 
 
 The primary judgment intuitive 187 
 
 The secondary judgment. The attendant belief 188 
 
 Based on suggestion 1 89 
 
 Theory of mental retention. Two objections 189 
 
 Theory of physical retention. Supplementary 190 
 
 Remembrance, involuntary. Subdivided 193 
 
 Recollection, voluntary. Impelled by desire 194 
 
 Cirrunistantial and philosophical. Mnemonics 196 
 
CONTENTS. xi 
 
 V. riWAGINATION. 
 
 PAGE 
 
 § 190. Terms. Definition. The ideal object 198 
 
 § 191. Distinguished from memory 198 
 
 § 192. Limitations of imagination 199 
 
 § 193. Simple imagination — two forms 201 
 
 § 194. Complex imagination, constructive and plastic 202 
 
 § 195. Involuntary imagination or phantasy. Dreams 203 
 
 § 196. Concomitant action of the brain 204 
 
 § 197. Voluntary imagination — subdivisions 207 
 
 § 198. The artistic. Fancy 207 
 
 § 199. Poetic imagination 209 
 
 § 200. The reflective. Philosophic 209 
 
 § 201. Deliberative imagination 211 
 
 § 202. The practical. Ideas of actions 211 
 
 § 203. Ideal standards of actions 213 
 
 VI. Thought. 
 
 § 204. Definition — illustrated. The notion 216 
 
 § 205. Three movements. Abstraction 217 
 
 § 206. Abstract terms 218 
 
 § 207. Generalization 219 
 
 § 208. Conception — particular and general 219 
 
 § 209. Denomination 221 
 
 § 210. Intension and extension of the concept 222 
 
 § 211. Classification 223 
 
 § 212. Review. Judgments — inductions and deductions 224 
 
 § 213. Relation of judgment and conception 225 
 
 § 214. Relation of thought to memory, and to imagination 226 
 
 § 215. Intuitive thinking 227 
 
 § 216. Symbolical thinking 229 
 
 § 217. Test of symbolic thought 2.30 
 
 § 218. Truth — its definition, and its criterion 231 
 
 § 219. Error — limited to thought. What is its source? 234 
 
 § 220. Attributed to imagination 236 
 
 PART FOURTH. — FEELING. 
 
 I. Characteristics. 
 
 •§ 221. Correlation of cognition and feeling 239 
 
 § 222. Their inverse ratio 241 
 
 § 223. Change requisite. Law of accommodation 241 
 
 § 224. Novelty. Familiarity the basis of memory 243 
 
Xll C0^^ TENTS. 
 
 PAGE 
 
 § 225. Desire set apart 244 
 
 § 220. The consciousness of self- existence found in feeling 245 
 
 § 227. Certainty, belief, and doubt 247 
 
 § 228. Pleasure and pain. Aristotle's theory 249 
 
 § 229. Feelings involuntary — their mediate control 252 
 
 § 2.S0. Diffusion of feeling — expression and organic effects 253 
 
 § 231. Logical distribution — scheme 25G 
 
 II. Sensation. 
 
 § 232. Correlation of perception and sensation 258 
 
 § 233. Sensations attending the senstis vagus 258 
 
 § 234. Those of the sensus jixus. Muscular sensations 260 
 
 § 235. Tactile sensations 2G1 
 
 § 236. Odors — their classes 261 
 
 § 237. Tastes — their classes 262 
 
 § 238. Sensations of sound 264 
 
 § 239. Sensations of white light, color, and lustre 265 
 
 III. Emotion. 
 
 § 240. Temperament, mood, disposition 266 
 
 § 241. Characteristics of emotion 268 
 
 § 242. Wonder and its cognates 269 
 
 § 243. Tear — its causes and effects 270 
 
 § 244. Joy and sorrow — their expression 272 
 
 § 245. Affectionate emotions 273 
 
 § 246. Sympathy — its objects. Panic 274 
 
 IV. Sentiment. 
 
 § 247. Correlation of pure intuition and sentiment 277 
 
 § 248. Sensuous sejitiments. Beauty — limitations 277 
 
 § 249. The sublime, the picturesque, and the ludicrous 280 
 
 § 250. Utility — distinct from beauty. 281 
 
 § 251. Pure intellectual sentiments of truth, property, etc 282 
 
 § 252. Those of honor, trust, and pity 284 
 
 § 253. Those of self-esteem, etc. — humiliation, humility 286 
 
 § 254. Pure ethical sentiments of respect, etc. — gratitude 287 
 
 PART FIFTH. — DESIRE. 
 
 I. Its Relations. 
 
 § 255. Definition. Relation to cognition. 289 
 
 § 256. To feeling — pleasure and pain 290 
 
 § 257. To volition — correlative 293 
 
 § 258. Psychical instinct 294 
 
CONTENTS. xiii 
 
 II. Its Kinds. ^^^^^ 
 
 § 250. Logical distribution — list of species 295 
 
 § 260. Appetites — marks of, with examples 206 
 
 § 261. Appetences — illustrative examples in detail 298 
 
 § 262. Affections — benevolent, with examples in detail 300 
 
 § 263. Affections — malevolent, with examples in detail 303 
 
 III. Its Regulation. 
 
 § 264. The conflict among desires 305 
 
 § 265. The two regulative desires — how harmonized 305 
 
 § 266. Their relation to subordinate desires 307 
 
 § 267. The moral impulse conditioned. Conscience 308 
 
 PART SIXTH. — VOLITION. 
 
 I. Its Relations. 
 
 § 268. Definition. Contrasted with cognition 309 
 
 § 269. Its double relation to cognition 310 
 
 § 270. How related to feeling and desire 311 
 
 § 271. Subjective and objective control 311 
 
 II. Its Elements. 
 
 § 272. Two conditions, and three elements 313 
 
 § 273. Choice — its special conditions, and essence 314 
 
 § 274. Intention — its static character 315 
 
 § 275. Effort — the nisus of attention 316 
 
 III. Its Freedom. 
 
 § 276. The two opposed doctrines 318 
 
 § 277. Am I free ? Importance of the question 318 
 
 § 278. An objection to the inquiry retorted 320 
 
 § 279. The presumption, and burden of proof 321 
 
 § 280. The necessitarian argument 321 
 
 § 281. The reply that I am conscious of freedom 322 
 
 § 282. That volition is exempt from causation 324 
 
 § 283. That causality is modified in this case , 325 
 
 § 284. That causation does not apply to mind ^ 327 
 
 § 285. That free agency comports with subjective necessity 329 
 
 § 286. A critical analysis of the argument 332 
 
 -§ 287. A premise corrected in form and denied 333 
 
 § 288. The making the choice distinct from the choice itself 334 
 
 § 289. The choice itself is not a change 335 
 
 § 290. The necessitarian argument invalid 336 
 
 § 291. An indirect demonstration of freedom 337 
 
 § 292. The conditioning antecedents of choice 338 
 
/ 
 
^x^Sov yap TL €y(oye avro tovto <f>r]iJLi eivai (roxfipoavvTjv, 
 TO yiyv(ii(TK€iv kavTov Kal ^u/xt^epo^at rw iv AeA<^o?s avaOevTt 
 TO TOtovTov ypdfJifJia, FN LUG I ^EAYTON. kol yap tovto ovto) 
 fioL BoK€L TO ypap-fia avaKUtrOat, cos hrj Trp6(rpr](Ti.<; ovaa tov 
 6eov Twv elaiovTwv olvtI tov ^atpc. — PlATO, 
 
((UHI7.E.. 
 
 PHYSIOLOGICAL INTRODUCTION. 
 
 -»-oi«<o°- 
 
 CHAPTER I. 
 
 THE CEPHALIC SENSES. 
 
 § 1. -Certain physiological facts, together with inferences 
 from them, form a proper introduction to psychology. As 
 man consists of a body and mind in essential relation, neither 
 can rightly be studied apart from the other. Psychology, 
 the science of mind, involves, therefore, a study of the body 
 as it affects or is affected by mind. Physiology, a science of 
 organized body, considers at large the function of organs; 
 but human physiology, in its direct relation to mind, is con- 
 cerned only with the organs of sense, and the nervous sys- 
 tem in general. These are directly correlated with mental 
 states, and their influence in determining experience is a 
 primary consideration. We begin, then, with a brief exami- 
 nation of the several senses, followed by a sketch of the 
 nervous system, indicating, as we proceed, the results of both 
 observation and experiment. 
 
 § 2. For orderly discussion the following logical arrange- 
 ment is adopted. The senses in general are of two classes, 
 the sensus fixus, that having local organs, and the sensus 
 vagus, the mobile or diffused sense, sometimes called the 
 vital sense.i The sensus fixus is divided into the cephalic 
 and the somatic senses. The former are so named because 
 
 1 Kant, Anthropologic, § 15. 
 
2 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 their several organs are located exclusively in the head. 
 They are smelling, tasting, hearing, and seeing. In smell 
 and taste sensation predominates ; in hearing and sight per- 
 ception predominates ; hence a subdivision of the cephalic 
 senses into the two subjective and the two objective senses. 
 The somatic senses are so named because their organs are 
 distributed over all parts of the body. They are touch and 
 the muscular sense. The former is on the whole the more 
 objective or percipient; the latter, the more subjective or 
 sensuous. The sensus vagus, or vital sense, need not be sub- 
 divided here. It is almost wholly subjective or sensuous. 
 
 The cephalic senses will now be examined in the order 
 of increasing objectivity. 
 
 § 3. The organ of smell lies above the n^^strils in vaulted 
 chambers between the eyes. The mucous membrane lining 
 this cavity is supplied with a great number of delicate olfac- 
 tory fibres which pass up to the overlying brain through sieve- 
 like perforations in the bony cribriform plate that roofs the 
 vaults. Their further connection with the nerve centres is 
 called the first pair of cerebral nerves, or the olfactoiy 
 nerves. But these are not clearly traceable, and the olfac- 
 tory fibres seem rather to be direct processes of the cerebral 
 hemispheres.^ 
 
 Effluvia and certain gases and vapors, soluble in the moist- 
 ure of the mucous lining, excite the enclosed olfactory 
 fibres, and produce a sense-perception of odor.^ 
 
 1 It is very desirable that tlie reader sliould have a knowledge of the anat- 
 omy and physiology of the organs of sense, and of the nervous system 
 generally, far beyond what would be proper, or even possible, to give in the 
 present treatise. Nothing but the barest outline statement being admissible 
 here, he is earnestly reconnnended to inform himself more fully by perusing 
 on these points some good handbook of physiology. To this end T have 
 used satisfactorily with my pupils Huxley's Lesso7is in Elementart/ Pfnjsiol- 
 ogy, published by IMacmillan & Co. 
 
 2 All volatile organic compounds, says Gmelin, are odoriferous. The 
 substances causing pleasant odors are chiefly hydrocarbons, as the ethers. 
 Substances repulsive frequently contain sulphur, as sulphydric acid ; but 
 
THE CEPHALIC SENSES. 3 
 
 § 4. In the ordinary exercise of the sense of smell the 
 agreeable or disagreeable feeling is a marked experience, and 
 greatly predominates over the knowledge it gives of its 
 object. As compared with the other senses, the feeling or 
 sensation in smell is at a maximnm, whereas the accom- 
 panying knowledge or perception is at a minimum. That is 
 to say, smell is the most highly sensuous and most feebly 
 perceptive of the fixed senses. Yet its perceptive power is 
 remarkably acute, and in some cases it surpasses the spec- 
 troscope in detecting the presence of minute particles.^ By 
 attentive exercise its power of discrimination may be greatly 
 improved.^ But by just so much as its perceptive or objec- 
 tive power increases, does its naturally sensuous or sub- 
 jective character decrease, so that it may even cease to be a 
 source of pleasure or pain, all odors becoming subjectively 
 indifferent.^ 
 
 the most offensive have arsenic for their base, as chloride of kakodyle. 
 Odorous matter is such as in general can readily be acted on by oxygen, 
 and unless oxygen passes into the nostrils along with it, no smell is caused. 
 
 1 The perceptive power of this sense to detect the presence of odoriferous 
 particles is marvellous. Sulphydric acid in the atmosphere, in the pro- 
 portion of one to a million, is distinctly perceptible. Valentin has calculated 
 that it can perceive about the three hundred millionths (0.00000003) of a 
 grain of musk. Another chemist estimates that two and a half billionths 
 (0.0000000025) of a grain of camphor is perceptible. So minute a particle is 
 quite imperceptible otherwise; no microscope can bring it within the reach of 
 vision; and even the spectroscope, which can detect the fifteen millionths 
 (0.000015) of a grain, is far surpassed in delicacy by the organ of smell. It 
 furnishes extreme examples of the di^asibility of matter. 
 
 - The blind are guided by it with facility and accuracy. Humboldt says 
 that the Peruvian Indians, in the night, can not only perceive by scent the 
 approach of a stranger while yet far distant, but can say whether he is an 
 Indian, a European, or a negro. The Arabs of the Sahara recognize the 
 smell of fire thirty or more miles away. The Spice Islands of the Indian 
 Archipelago are recognized far out at sea. Nearer home, our tobacco buyers 
 determine differences of value by faint differences of odor quite indistinguish- 
 able by the uneducated. The word sagacious, meaning primarily keen-scented, 
 is often used to denote high intelligence or power of discrimination. 
 
 3 This is true of the blind, who rely on it. To the dog, whose sagacity is 
 proverbial, all odors seem subjectively indifferent. 
 
4 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 § 5. The combined sensation and perception, or sense- 
 perception, of smell is a mental state. The object perceived, 
 the percept, is an odor. By the common judgment of men, 
 odor is a quality of body, an external material cause of the 
 mental state ; it is attributed to body as a quality inherent 
 in its substance. The philosophic correctness of this judg- 
 ment in its general form will be subsequently considered 
 and maintained. Its truth is, for the present, assumed, and 
 we proceed at once to the question: What body has the 
 quality odor ; or what is the material thing that directly 
 excites the sense-perception of smell ? 
 
 It is universally allowed that I have immediate knowl- 
 edge or am conscious of the odor. Now, according to the 
 foregoing assumption, I am therein conscious of the material 
 thing that excites in me this special sense-perception. But 
 the object immediately known in perception must be one 
 which is the proximate cause of the conscious affection ; for 
 a remote cause can be known only by inference, and this is 
 always mediate knowledge.^ 
 
 What, then, is the proximate cause of this affection ? Of 
 what external thing am I conscious ? Certainly not of the 
 rose that I hold in my hand, nor of its effluvium ; for evi- 
 dently these are quite remote causes. Nor am I conscious 
 of the outer organ of smell. Its function undoubtedly is to 
 receive, modify, and transmit the impressions of effluvia. 
 But of this I know nothing consciously. The existence and 
 functions of the outer organ become known to me only as 
 the result of observation and inference. Moreover, its 
 existence is not essential to the percept; for if it be cut 
 away by the surgeon's knife, and an electric shock be passed 
 through the cribriform plate, a sense-perception of odor is 
 experienced. It is evident, then, that the outer organ is 
 only one link in a chain of remote causes, which proceeds 
 
 1 Mediate, not in the logical, but in the psychological sense. That is to 
 say, a remote cause can be known only through a representation, wliich is, 
 psychologically, mediate knowledge. 
 
THE CEPHALIC SENSES. 5 
 
 into the brain. Hence tlie proximate cause of the sense- 
 perception is some interior cerebral movement, some brain 
 cliange, a certain special excitement of the inner sensory, 
 perhaps limited to a detinite part which constitutes the inner 
 organ or centre of smell. 
 
 We reach, then, the unquestionable and very important 
 conclusion that in smell the object external to mind, the 
 object of which I am conscious, is a brain change, and nothing 
 beyond ; that the inner sensory itself, excited in a special 
 manner, is. the proximate cause of the sense-perception, and 
 therefore the brain itself, or probably some part of it, is the 
 percept, the object immediately perceived when I experience 
 the presence of odor. 
 
 § 6. The sense of smell gives the existence of body as hav- 
 ing this one quality, odor. It does not give body as having 
 either extension or place. It does not localize its percept 
 either in the cranium, where it is, or in the nostrils, where it 
 is not. When by aid of other faculties we have ascertained 
 that some remote thing, as a rose, is a cause of the sense- 
 perception, we attribute the odor to it as its inherent quality ; 
 and because of the habitual use of the nostrils as the recog- 
 nized and recognizing instrument, we locate the conscious- 
 ness in them, and seem to experience the odor there. But 
 the foregoing slight analysis shows that both these localiza- 
 tions are acquired and erroneous notions, and identifies the 
 body possessing this quality, this special power of directly 
 affecting me, with the inner sensory, the brain itself. 
 
 The subsequent examination of the other forms of the 
 sensus fixus will show that these conclusions are general. 
 
 § 7. The organ of taste lies in the mucous membrane 
 which covers the tongue, especially its back part, and the 
 hinder part of the palate. The papillce of this membrane 
 receive nervous filaments chiefly from the ninth pair of cere- 
 bral nerves, called the glosso-pharyngeal, but also from a 
 
Q INTRODUCTION. 
 
 branch of the fifth pair, the trigeminal, this branch being 
 called the gustatory nerve. The gustatory nerve mostly 
 supplies the front of the tongue, the glosso-pharyngeal its 
 back part and the adjacent part of the palate.^ These nerves 
 are partly motor, but they are mainly sensor, and it is believed 
 that somewhat different taste sensations arise from each. 
 
 The excitant of taste is sapid matter dissolved in the 
 moisture of the mucous membrane. Insoluble solids are 
 insipid, solubility being a condition of sapidity. But not all 
 soluble matter is sapid.^ 
 
 Taste is highly subjective, the sensation being strongly 
 marked as agreeable, or disagreeable even to disgust, while 
 the percept is proportionately faint.^ Still it is an acute and 
 important means of information, and susceptible of great 
 improvement in delicate discrimination.'* 
 
 § 8. The impression we usually call taste is, however, 
 quite complex, involving not only smell, but touch, muscular 
 sense and temperature, besides stomatic sensations. It is 
 consequently difficult to distinguish and analyze pure taste. 
 But there can be no doubt that its percept, savor, though 
 greatly obscured by this complication, is a simple and ulti- 
 mate enorganic affection. What was said of odor in the 
 preceding section, may be said of savor. It is merely an 
 excited state of an intercranial sensory, and what is immedi- 
 
 1 The latter seems to be more especially the nerve of taste. Animals in 
 •whom it has been severed devour food mixed with the bitterest ingredients. 
 
 2 It should be observed, however, that electricity excites taste. Hence 
 the taste of metals, e.g. of zinc and copper. 
 
 3 To taste means to test, to try. " Taste your legs, Sir ; put them to 
 motion.'" — Ticelfth Night, A. 3, sc. 1. Primarily, to test by touch. Note 
 the extended use of the word in aesthetics, and also the secondary meaning 
 of di.sgust. 
 
 * The tongue can recognize the acidity of a drop of solution consisting of 
 one part of sulphuric acid in 10,000 parts of water, and the bitterness of one 
 of sulphate of quinine in 33,000 of water, quantities too small to be detected 
 by chemical tests. The skilled wiTie-tastcr, it is said, can tell the vineyard 
 of a choice wine, and the year of its vintage. 
 
THE CEPHALIC SENSES. 7 
 
 ately perceived is not something in the mouth, but some- 
 thing in the sensorium. 
 
 § 9. Smell and taste are analogous. The outer organs of 
 both lie in the mucous membrane, and require the solution of 
 their excitants. These seem to be foreign particles acting 
 chemically on the nerve fibres, whereas in hearing and sight 
 the excitement seems due to motion, the vibration of foreio-n 
 particles; hence the two former are sometimes called the 
 chemical senses ; the two latter, the mechanical senses.^ 
 
 Both smell and taste are highly sensuous and feebly per- 
 ceptive ; hence the sensation is much more easily and dis- 
 tinctly remembered than the perception.^ There is great 
 sympathy between these two senses, so that what is agreeable 
 or disagreeable to one is likely to be so to the other, smell 
 thus acting as a preparatory test and safeguard to taste .-^ 
 The similarity of their impressions is such that the words 
 Jlavor and savor often interchange meanings. 
 
 § 10. The organ of hearing is very complex, and the spe- 
 cific function of certain parts is not known. For the present 
 purpose it is sufficient to observe that the vibrations of a 
 sonorous body, as a bell, are communicated to the air, and 
 through this medium to the outer membrane of the tympanum 
 or drum of the ear ; that they thence pass through a chain of 
 small bones, and then through a fluid to certain cells of audi- 
 tory epithelium, where peripheral filaments of the auditory 
 nerve are stimulated ; that this stimulus is propagated along 
 the trunk nerve into the sensorium, there causing an excite- 
 ment or disturbance of the sensory, probably at some aural 
 centre. The consciousness of this final sensorial excitement 
 is the sense-perception of sound. 
 
 1 Wundt classes sight as a chemical sense. 
 
 2 It is because of this subjective character, perhaps, that they have baffled 
 so far all attempts to measure their intensity. 
 
 3 Socrates, in a dialogue with Aristodemus, discourses of this relation as 
 an evidence of design. — See Blackie's Four Phases, p. 78, Am. ed. 
 
8 INTEODUCTION. 
 
 § 11. The sense of hearing is more perceptive or objective 
 than sensuous or subjective. The mere sensuous feeling is 
 ordinarily of low intensity, a single sound or synchronous 
 sounds giving little pleasure or pain. If, however, a sound 
 be very loud, acute, harsh, or discordant, the sensation becomes 
 painful, and the percept loses proportionally its vividness. 
 The enjoyment of music is but slightly sensuous. Sweet or 
 pleasing sounds are perhaps essential, but the enjoyment 
 arises chiefly from the variety and harmonious relations of 
 the sounds. The recognition of this is intellectual, and the 
 pleasant feelings attending it are not properly sensations, but 
 emotions and sentiments. 
 
 On the other hand, the perceptive power of hearing is very 
 comprehensive and discriminating. The number of musical 
 tones that can be distinguished by pitch alone is several hun- 
 dred, and if their intensity and timbre be taken into account, 
 the number is incalculable. Yet to these must be added an 
 innumerable variety of articulate vocal sounds, and to these 
 again an even greater variety of mere noises. 
 
 § 12. The percept of hearing is sound. Hearing is a SY>e- 
 cific sense-perception, a state of mind ; sound is its object, the 
 thing perceived. I am conscious of the sound. Now what 
 is the thing herein immediately known to me ? It is not the 
 bell, nor the aerial vibrations ; these are only remote causes. 
 Indeed, the latter are not requisite, as is proved by a tuning- 
 fork held between the teeth, in which case the vibrations are 
 conveyed by the bones of the face.^ But even vibrations are 
 not essential, nor indeed the apparatus of the peripheral or 
 outer ear ; for if this ear be completely destroyed, and the 
 stump of the auditory trunk nerve irritated with a needle, a 
 sense-perception of sound is produced. The outer ear serves 
 
 1 In case of deafness it may be thus determined whether the cause is a 
 stoppage of the outer passages, or a disorder of tlie inner car. Fish have no 
 ear opening, the vibrations being conveyed from the water to the audittuy 
 nerve througli solid bono. 
 
THE CEPHALIC SENSES. 9 
 
 doubtless to receive, modify, and transmit in all their various 
 characters the sound-producing vibrations ; but of its func- 
 tions, even of its existence, I am utterly unconscious. I am 
 conscious only of a result occurring at the supposed aural 
 centre, the inner ear, which I call a sound. Sound, then, is 
 a phenomenon of brain. The percept is not merely enorganic, 
 but intercranial ; the thing immediately perceived, the proxi- 
 mate cause of the sense-perception, is the inner sensory.^ 
 
 § 13. The percept of hearing is not consciously located at 
 all. It is not perceived to be in the sensorium, where in fact 
 it is, nor in the outer ear, where it is not. That some sounds 
 seem to be in the outer ear is doubtless due to a disturbance 
 of tactile nerves in the vicinity. Commonly we locate a 
 sound, by inference, in its remote cause, as in the bell, or 
 else in its atmosphere. But sound proper is wholly inter- 
 cranial. Outside there are only vibrations, and were there 
 no inner ear to hear, absolute silence would reign throughout 
 the universe. 
 
 § 14. That sound is an intercranial phenomenon is proved 
 by a fact in binaural audition. If two unisonant musical 
 tones be conveyed by acoustic tubes, one to each ear, a 
 smooth musical note is heard ; but if they differ by a quarter 
 tone, a beating note is heard. Now where is this beating? 
 Not in the outside air, which is shut off by the tubes. Not in 
 either tube, for each conveys a smooth tone. It can be only 
 in the brain, and, since the auditory nerves do not decussate, 
 probably at co-ordinated centres where they terminate. This 
 is a physical demonstration by experiment, that sound is not 
 
 1 When we stop our ears with the tips of the fingers a roaring sound is 
 heard, probably due to the circulation of the blood in and about the inner 
 ear. If one will attentively contemplate this subjective sound, as the physi- 
 ologists call it, dismissing all consideration of its cause and its apparent 
 locality in the outer ear, he can more clearly apprehend our doctrine that 
 all sound is subjective, its perception being merely a consciousness of the 
 sensory excited in a peculiar manner. 
 
10 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 something in the sonorous body, or in its atmosphere, nor 
 something in the outer ear, but that it is a cerebral phenom- 
 enon, and that the thing immediately perceived is an excited 
 sensory, probably an aural centre.^ 
 
 § 15. The outer organ of sight, the eyeball, is a camera 
 obscura, having in front a combination of lenses which bring 
 pencils of light to foci on the retina lining the interior. 
 These pencils thus depict on the retina, as on a screen, an 
 ojDtical picture of remote luminous objects. The retina is a 
 complexus of nerve filaments which are ramifications of the 
 optic nerve, and through the optic nerve the impressions on 
 the retina are conveyed in a modified form to a sensorial 
 sight centre, and vision ensues, a sense-perception of colored 
 figure. 
 
 § 16. Sight is the most objective of the senses. Its sensa- 
 tions are ordinarily quite feeble, scarcely marked as pleasant 
 or painful. A very bright light, however, and also a dim 
 light, are painful, because of the overstrained energy they 
 arouse. Certain soft and rich colors, of medium brightness, 
 give a marked sensuous pleasure ; and, in general, light is an 
 agreeable and very effective stimulant.^ But the pleasure 
 we experience in viewing harmonious contrasts of colors and 
 the variations of light and shade is mostly intellectual and 
 
 ^ The experiment was first tried by myself, and the above paragi-aph 
 written, early in the winter of 1876-7. It was at once published to my 
 pupils, and has ever since been used in my teaching. 
 
 In the summer of 1877, Professor S. P. Thompson announced to the Brit- 
 ish Association his own discovery of this phenomenon. (See Beport of Brit. 
 Assoc, Plymouth, 1877, p. 37 ; also Phil. Mag. for October, 1877, p. 274; 
 for November, 1878, p. 38.3 ; and for November, 1881, p. 351.) He pursues 
 the subject by a number of ingenious experiments, and adds many acute 
 observations, dwelling especially on the fact that the sensation of the sound 
 is localized centrally at the back of the head. Viewing the matter as a 
 physicist, he establishes andfliscusses the facts, but nowhere does he draw 
 tlie important psycliological conclusion given above in the text. 
 
 2 <i Truly the light is sweet, and a pleasant thing it is for the eyes to 
 behold the sun."— Eccl. 11 :7. 
 
THE CEPHALIC SENSES. 11 
 
 aesthetic, with very little that is strictly sensuous. The pleasure 
 arising from form without regard to color, as of a statue or 
 a line engraving, is still less sensuous. 
 
 On the other hand, the perceptions of sight are remarkably 
 clear and distinct. The almost infinite variety of shades and 
 hues distinguishable indicates the wide range and acute dis- 
 crimination of vision. It is the most keenly percipient of 
 the senses, and hence, as a source of information, it is by far 
 the most useful sense. 
 
 § 17. The primary percept of sight is color, including 
 under this term not only all hues, but also white and black, 
 and every variety of light and shade. Seeing is a specific 
 sense-perception, a state of mind ; color is its primary object, 
 the thing perceived. I am conscious of the color. 
 
 What, now, is color psychologically considered ; that is, as 
 perceived? It is not a quality inherent in the luminous 
 object ; for a white rose in the beams of the prismatic spec- 
 trum will assume any of its hues, and in the dark all roses 
 are colorless. It is not the light itself; for while many 
 things seem to emit white light, there is no such thing as 
 a white ray, but the impression white is the subjective 
 effect of the combined prismatic colors. Moreover, light 
 is not essential, for with closed eyes I may still perceive 
 phosphenes, due to retinal excitement, displaying many 
 colors.! It is not the retinal picture ; nor the retina itself, 
 of which I am conscious ; for if the eyeballs be removed, 
 and the remains of the optic nerve be irritated, a vision of 
 colors will still be experienced.^ The retina serves to receive, 
 
 1 They may be rendered quite vivid by pressing on the eyeballs. A blow 
 on the head causes one to " see stars." These percepts are evidently not due 
 to ethereal vibrations, but to mechanical disturbance of the retina. An atten- 
 tive contemplation of phosphene ;s, especially if projecting them into space be 
 avoided, will enable one to apj eciate more satisfactorily the fact that the 
 percepts are enorganic. 
 
 2 Moreover, one who has becoi le blind by loss of the eyeballs alone, can 
 still vividly image colored scenes; but "the destruction of the sight centre 
 
 
 \<\ ^ 
 
12 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 modify, and transmit in modified form through the optic nerve 
 the sight-producing vibrations ; but I am unconscious of the 
 part it plays, or even of its existence. I am conscious only 
 of a result, which has been ascertained to occur at a sight 
 centre far within the cerebrum, and I call it a color. 
 
 We thus trace this percept, as the others, into the nervous 
 centres, and find that color, too, is a phenomenon of brain. 
 It is not that we perceive the sight centre to be colored in 
 the manner that we seem to see outward objects colored; but 
 it is that the sight centre is the immediate object, the mate- 
 rial thing, that directly causes the conscious impression of 
 color in the mind, and therefore it is the material object im- 
 mediately known or perceived. 
 
 We commonly attribute color to external objects, and think 
 of it as residing on their surfaces.^ We regard light as some- 
 thing beyond ourselves, filling space. There is, hypotheti- 
 cally, a vibrating ether filling space, which causes the phe- 
 nomenon ; but there is no brightness beyond ourselves out 
 in space, nor any color, blue, yellow, or red, residing on the 
 surface of bodies. Colors are wholly the phenomena of one's 
 brain, caused by the supposed vibrations ; so that, were there 
 no eye to see, the sun would not be bright, the moon and 
 stars would not shine, the sky would have no tints, the land- 
 scape no hues, no shades, and absolute darkness would reign 
 throuGfhout the universe. 
 
 § 18. That color is an intercranial phenomenon finds 
 further proof in a fact of binocular vision. Put two pieces 
 
 not only makes the individual blind presentatively, but blind also representa- 
 tively or ideally, and all cognitions into which visual characters enter in part 
 or whole become mangled and imperfect, or are utterly rooted out of con- 
 sciousness." — I). Fkruier's Functions of the Bmhi, p. 259. 
 
 1 That it does not is confirmed by the remarkable defect, generally con- 
 genital, called color-blindness. It is never entire, but in part it is quite 
 common, about one person in twenty being nive or less color-blind, and the 
 inability to distinguish red being most frequ at. Nevertheless, the subject 
 sees the object, though of a different Ime from ^ /hat we regard as its real color. 
 
 Was not Homer merely color-blind ? The Iliad, like a steel engraving, is 
 colorless. < 
 
THE CEPHALIC SENSES. 1 
 
 Q 
 
 of paper, one yellow, the other blue, in the separate compart- 
 ments of a stereoscope. On lookmg through the lenses, the 
 percept is green. Now, where is this green ? It is not in 
 either eye, for it is physically certain that the picture on one 
 retina is yellow, and on the other blue. The percej^t green 
 cannot be short of the optic chiasm, where the optic nerves 
 partially decussate, and probably it lies much deeper in the 
 cerebrum. This is a physical demonstration by experiment, 
 that in vision of color the object consciously known by this 
 phenomenon is not the retina, and that it is intercranial, an 
 excited cerebral sight centre.^ 
 
 § 19. Beside color, sight is cognizant of extension. On 
 looking at the starry heavens, the luminous points I see are 
 numerous. The points of imjDression being numerous and 
 simultaneous, must be apart in space, and herein is a con- 
 sciousness of extension. 
 
 This extension is not that of the heavens themselves ; for 
 evidently I cannot be conscious of their extension. It is 
 commonly supposed to be that of the retinal picture, the 
 minute chart of the heavens which the pencils of light depict 
 on my retina, mentally projected out, beyond and above me, 
 and thought into a sky. But what I see, and my retinal pic- 
 ture, do not exactly correspond. Moreover, as has already 
 been indicated, the retinal picture is out of consciousness. 
 How, then, shall we interpret this fact of consciousness, the 
 consciousness, in sight, of extension? The true statement 
 seems to be this : The retinal picture determines a complex 
 impression on the inner sight centre, not only of colors, but 
 also of their expanse ; and this combined impression consti- 
 tutes a field of view, consisting of colored figures.^ 
 
 1 The experiment is parallel to that on sound, § 14. It is not new, being 
 found in Brewster's Optics in a different form. The psychological inference, 
 stated above, has not previously, so far as I know, been drawn. 
 
 2 That sight is cognizant of extension in two dimensions, length and 
 breadth (but not depth), is generally conceded. Hamilton argues for it, but 
 unsatisfactorily, 3Ma., Lee. 28. Psychologists of to-day hold it on other but 
 
1-1 IMTKODUVTION. 
 
 Accordingly, we take color, since it is the condition of 
 visible extension, to be the primtuy, and its extension, or 
 figure, to be the secondary, but equally immediate, percept 
 of sight. This consciousness of colored figure is an empiri- 
 cal occasion for the pure idea, or intellectual discernment of 
 space. Also in the changing of visible figure we inmiediately 
 perceive, or are conscious of, motion. 
 
 § 20. The external conditions of hearing and seeing are 
 analogous, being in both cases a vibrating body, sonorous or 
 luminous, and a pulsating medium conveying the movement 
 to the outer organs of sense. The organs, though in appear- 
 ance very dissimilar, are essentially alike in being fitted to 
 receive, modify, and transmit vibrations. Both have nerve 
 ramifications, impressible by vibrations of certain degrees of 
 intensity, and are insensible to others.^ Moreover, both 
 these senses are highly perceptive and feebly sensuous. The 
 
 various gi-ounds. The fact being granted, how shall it be interpreted ? The 
 various hypotheses have been classed by Helmholtz as native and empirical. 
 Of the former, the doctrine of Mtiller is called the hypothesis of subjective 
 identity. "The retina," says he, "feels its own extension and position. 
 Even when not in the least affected by the world without, it feels them as 
 darkness before the eyes." Also there is the hypothesis of projection, main- 
 tahied especially by Volkuiann, which teaches that " the retina is capable of 
 projecting its impressions outward in given lines of direction or of sight." 
 These hypotheses have been variously modified to suit the facts, but are now 
 generally regarded as unsatisfactory. The leading representative of the 
 empirical class is Helmholtz, he holding to the genesis of visual space from 
 experience alone. The peculiar views of Lotze and Wundt on the genesis 
 of the notion of space will be noticed under the head of Touch. 
 
 The interpretation given above in the text may fairly be classed as nativ- 
 ist. A number of facts favor it ; e.g. there is a blind spot on the retina, but 
 no corresponding dark spot in the field of view. 
 
 1 Aerial vibrations fewer than 8 per sec. are inaudible, and at least 16 per 
 sec. are requisite to produce a musical tone. Vibrations of more than 38,000 
 per sec. are inaudible, but painful if intense. Ethereal vibrations fewer than 
 3U!) trillions per sec, the extreme red, do not excite vision ; nor do those of 
 more than 8.31 trillions per sec, the extreme violet or lavender. Thus while 
 the range of the ear is a little more than eleven octaves, that of the eye is- 
 little more than one octave. 
 
THE CEPHALIC SENSES. 15 
 
 sensations are similar in being susceptible of harmony and 
 discord.^ The perceptions are similar in the power which 
 they acquire of giving information respecting remote objects. 
 They have also a remarkable power of analysis, hearing divid- 
 ing time, and sight dividing space, almost infinitesimally. 
 
 § 21. From the foregoing view of the cephalic senses it 
 clearly appears that the immediate percept of each is an 
 excited sensory. The same will on examination be found 
 true of the percepts of the somatic senses. Indeed, the fact 
 is general, true of all those percepts commonly known as the 
 secondary qualities of body, they being in reality affections 
 of the organism, and having no resemblance to any attribute 
 inhering in extra-organic bocUes. This important fact is not 
 new in physiology .^ It has not, however, been fully appre- 
 ciated by psychologists.^ In view of it we are enabled to 
 
 1 The subjective analogy between hearing and seeing is illustrated by the 
 following words of Taylor : " You look around the room as you enter. The 
 whitewash dazzles you. A scarlet geranium in bloom on the \Yindow sill 
 startles you like a trumpet blast amid all this silence of white." 
 
 ■^ Says Mtiller : ' ' External agencies can give rise to no kind, of sensation 
 which cannot also be produced by internal causes exciting changes in the 
 condition of our nerves." — Elem. of. Phys., p. 1059. And, later, Bernstein 
 says : " It is clear that we really have no sensations [perceptions] of objects 
 of the external world themselves, but only of the changes which occur in the 
 sensorium." — Five Senses of Man, Int., p. 5. 
 
 3 Reid held that in looking at the sun we are immediately conscious of it. 
 Hamilton in one place defends this view (Meta., pp. 158-9). In another he 
 says: " Nothing could be more absurd" (p. 357). lie holds that "the ex- 
 ternal object in perception is always in contact with the organ of sense" 
 (p. 375). "Through the eye we perceive nothing but the rays of light in 
 relation to and in contact with the retina " (p. 358). Mansel, his pupil, says : 
 " The presented object is on the surface of the retina " {Meta., p. 75). That 
 is, the retinal picture. But elsewhere (p. 65) he says: "Our own sensitive 
 organism is the only kind of matter that is immediately cognizible by the 
 senses." President Porter says : " The mind does not see the image on the 
 retina" (Hum. Intel!., p. 132). Professor Clifford says: " It is more coi-rect 
 to say that we see with a certain part of our brains, than to say that we 
 see with our eyes." It would be still more rigidly correct to say that we see 
 a certain part of our brains. 
 
16 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 formulate an answer to the general question : What is the 
 material thing which each sense immediately perceives ? See 
 § 5. The answer, which we shall hold to be an established 
 proposition, is : The brain itself is the immediate object in 
 perception. 
 
 This proposition is very important, and therefore its claim 
 of acceptance should be carefully considered. The doctrine 
 of immediate perception, in its usual form, has encountered 
 many objections, which, if our proposition be allowed, are 
 avoided. We shall find hereafter that an escape from ideal- 
 ism, or the doctrine that a non-ego does not exist, can be 
 accomplished only on the ground that extra-organic objects 
 are not immediately perceived. If immediate perception be 
 allowed only to intra-organic objects, we shall be better 
 enabled to establish the distinction between mind and matter, 
 and so, on the other hand, escape the meshes of materialism, 
 or the doctrine that matter only exists. The brain being 
 the matter in opposition to mind, the two being in no sense 
 identical, we can hold the doctrine of two substances, inter- 
 acting, co-ordinated, mutually dependent, and yet entirely 
 distinct. • 
 
 No doubt there is a difficulty in conceiving one's brain as 
 the immediate object perceived. But we must separate our- 
 selves from the usual view, that of looking with the eyes on 
 the thing, and consider merely the subjective impression the 
 thing makes upon us, and observe that it is a knowledge, 
 first, of its existence as something distinct from self, and 
 secondly, as something made known to us by virtue of a 
 single special quality. This wholly subjective view of the 
 brain as an existing, qualified thing, taken by the psycholo- 
 gist, is very different from the wholly objective view of the 
 brain, taken by the anatomist and phj^siologist ; but that it 
 is identically the same thing that presents these different 
 aspects is unquestionable. 
 
THE SOMATIC SENSES. 17 
 
 CHAPTER II. 
 
 THE SOMATIC SENSES. 
 
 § 22. The organ of the sense of touch is the skin. It 
 consists of a superficial layer, the epidermis, and a sub- 
 jacent layer, the dermis, in which capillary nerves terminate. 
 "Where the sense is delicate, as at the finger tips, the dermis 
 rises into many small, close-set, conical papillse, whose apexes 
 come near the outer surface of the epidermis. Eacb of these 
 cones is supplied with a tactile nerve and corpuscle.^ Super- 
 ficially the skin is subdivided into small tracts presenting 
 the appearance of network, and varying in size, being small 
 at the finger-tips and many times larger on the back. Each 
 tract is supplied with the capillaries of a single nerve fibre, 
 and capable of imparting only a single sense-perception.^ 
 
 The epidermis is an intermediary, the impact that stimu- 
 lates the nerve being transmitted through its horny sub- 
 stance to the subjacent ends of the nerve. The thickness or 
 extent of the intermediary seems less important than its 
 capacity for transmitting impulses. The finger nail drawn 
 over a surface affords a most delicate test of its smoothness.^ 
 
 1 At the finger tips about one hundred of these corpuscles may be counted 
 in an area j\ inch square. Elsewhere they are more sparse. 
 
 - E. H. "Weber, who made many experiments determinative of the relation 
 of sense-perception to its excitant, found that two points can be distinguished 
 by the tongue when only J^ inch apart ; by the finger tips when only Jg inch 
 apart ; while they may be one inch apart on the cheek, and even 2\ inches 
 apart on portions of the back, and yet seem single. The areas, having these 
 distances for diameters, Weber calls "circles of sensation." 
 
 3 This was the ancient statuary's test of the smoothness of his marble. 
 Horace uses it figuratively to express perfection : " Ad unguem f actus homo." 
 — Iter Brun., 1. 30. The phrase came from the Greeks : eh 6vvxol. We some- 
 times say, ' perfect to a nail.' 
 
18 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 With a rod in hand, one is able to judge very well of the 
 irresfularities in an unseen surface. In this case the inter- 
 mediary is vastly increased without proportionally diminish- 
 ing the delicacy and accuracy of the perceptive power. Some 
 intermediary is necessary ; for if the epidermis be removed 
 and contact occur with the naked nerve, the sensation is one 
 of pure pain merely, very different from tactile sensation. 
 
 § 23. The skin in certain places where perception is feeble 
 is highly sensitive, as on the cheek ; and where perception 
 is acute, as at the finger tips, the sensation is commonly 
 obtuse. The sensation is a familiar titillation, usually agree- 
 able though unobtrusive in its gentler forms, as the feel of 
 velvet; but it may become disagreeable and painful, as in 
 tickling.^ 
 
 The percept is tangibility, or that quality of body which 
 excites the sense-perception in us by impact or contact. This 
 does not imply area ; e.g. a pin point or knife edge. The 
 finger tips lightly tapped with a card give pure tangibility .^ 
 To this must be added the modified forms, roughness and 
 smoothness. If the card be drawn along the finger tips, we 
 experience one or the other. To produce these forms, motion 
 of the surface touched is essential ; but of the motion, touch 
 does not inform us.^ 
 
 1 It should be observed here that there are other cutaneous sensations, as 
 clamminess, temperature, and others. They belong to the sensus vcKjits, § 20. 
 Also, that even at the finger tips the sensation may become predominant, as 
 in touching a revolving grindstone. 
 
 2 A drop of water falling on the palm, or the breath blown on the fingers, 
 also excite the tactile sense-pcrce])tion. Any motion of the fingers, hand, 
 or arm, in what is called "active touch," or any perceptible pressure, con- 
 fuses the tactile with muscular sense-perception, and with volition. In no 
 treatise I have seen are these properly discriminated. Incomplete analysis 
 causes doctrinal confusion. Hamilton even says : " The organ of touch [the 
 fingers] requires, as a condition of its exercise, the movement of the volun- 
 tary muscles." — Metd., p. ;378. 
 
 3 " I would establish," says Hamilton, "as a fundamental position of the 
 doctrine of immediate perception, the opinion of Democritus [the Atomist, 
 
THE SOMATIC SENSES. 19 
 
 § 24. An impact, say on the finger tips, excites the fibres 
 of the tactile nerves ; these convey the impression to the 
 intercranial sensory, and consciousness ensues. The impres- 
 sion is attended by a vague sense of locality. Hence, analo- 
 gous to sight, the percept of touch is primarily a special 
 sensorial excitement, tangibility, with its modes roughness 
 and smoothness, and secondarily, extension implied in the 
 sense of locality. The extension herein given belongs to my 
 own nervous organism. The locality on the periphery, the 
 exact place touched, is not consciously given, but subse- 
 quently inferred from experience and observation.^ 
 
 in his work ^/cp6s Atd/cocr/ios, 420 b.c, rejected by Aristotle in De Sensu et 
 Sensili, cli. iv.] that all our senses are only modifications of touch; in 
 other words, that the external object of perception is always in contact with 
 the organ of sense." —Meta., p. 375. Herbert Spencer says : " Not only do 
 the conclusions of the physicists support the doctrine which Democritus 
 taught, but the conclusions of the biologists do the Uke. The organs of the 
 special senses are every one of them developed from the dermal system, are 
 modifications of that same tissue in which the tactile sense in general is 
 seated. Nor is this all. It is a remarkable fact that the eye and the ear 
 are, in their types of structure, morphologically identical with the vibrissce, 
 or most perfect organs of touch." — Pj-m. Psyc, § 139, and Prin. Bio., § 295. 
 The reduction, if correct, seems of little consequence. 
 
 1 Here again we hit upon the difficult question of the genesis of the appre- 
 hension of space. See § 19. That touch, as well as sight, is cognizant of 
 extension is generally admitted, but explanations greatly differ. The view 
 proposed in the text, that touch originally gives as a secondary percept a 
 vague sense of locality, is so far nativist. That a more exact knowledge of 
 the locality on the periphery is obtained only as the result of education, 
 belongs rather to the genetic or empirical doctrine. But it must be added 
 that the native cognizance of extension of body by both sight and touch is 
 an empirical occasion for the pure intellectual apprehension of the notion 
 of space. This point will be more fully expounded hereafter. 
 
 Lotze transformed the strictly empirical hypothesis into one more meta- 
 physical and elaborate, called the hypothesis of local signs. Each feeling- 
 point of the body, each "circle of sensation" on the skin, each sensitive 
 point on the retinal expanse, has its local sign. This implies no original 
 localization or cognizance of extension, but simply that each tactile or visual 
 impression presents a peculiar character (^nuance) that serves later to localize 
 it at a certain point of the body. At first these impressions are purely inten- 
 sive, and effect no special determination of any kind. j:,ater the mind, by 
 
20 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 § 25. Besides the percepts just indicated, touch is com- 
 monly held to give us knowledge of many other qualities of 
 matter, and to tell us much about the external world. Also 
 it is described as the instructor of the other senses, and the 
 corrector of their aberrations. This arises from a confusion 
 of touch with the muscular sense and voluntary locomotion. 
 When closely interrogated apart, touch is silent concerning 
 any qualities of body other than those named, and concern- 
 ing even the existence of an extra-organic world. Nor is 
 touch capable of certain lines of education commonly attrib- 
 uted to it, the acute perceptions of the blind being dependent 
 rather on an educated muscular sense. 
 
 § 26. The sensor nerves of the muscles constitute the 
 ortran of the muscular sense. The terminal fibres of a dis- 
 tinct set of sensor nerves, more sparse than those of touch, 
 are distributed to and penetrate the muscles.^ The terminal 
 fibres of the motor nerves also penetrate the muscular tissue. 
 These motor nerves, generally under the influence of the will, 
 cause muscular contraction, and thereby the enclosed sensor 
 nerves are subjected to pressure. The pressure, whether 
 produced thus or by the action of an exterior body, stimu- 
 lates the sensor nerves, causing a neural disturbance which 
 is propagated to the brain, and a sense-perception of physical 
 solidity is the result.^ 
 
 § 27. Tn order to observe the pure muscular sense-percep- 
 
 virtue of laws peculiarly its own, transforms these intensive data into exten- 
 sive quantities, and produces "a reconstruction of space." — Ribot, p. 100. 
 
 "Wundt accepts this hypothesis of local signs, but deems it insuthcient. 
 He rejects the a priori laws of mind in the case, and adds that the different 
 impressions being accompanied by voluntary movement, there attends tlieiu 
 a feeling of innervation, i.e. of the nervous discharge that attends voluntary 
 effort. These two elements, local signs and movement, explain localization. 
 Neither alone would give it, but the two, by a psychological synthesis, form 
 a combination which is, on occasion, the notion of space. 
 
 1 Demonstrated by Sachs in 1874. 
 
 2 Tor historical notices of the muscular sense, see Hamilton in lieid, p. 867. 
 
THE SOMATIC tiENSJES. 21 
 
 tion, some care is requisite that it be not mixed with that of 
 touch, or modified by voluntary effort and movement. The 
 weight of a limb freely hanging gives the simple and pure 
 muscular sense-perception.^ 
 
 The sensation is clearly marked as pleasurable or painful. 
 The pleasure of physical exercise arises mostly from muscular 
 sensations, and also the pleasant feeling in stretching. Fatigue 
 is perhaps an increased degree of the feeling that accompanies 
 all muscular exertion, and when moderate is not unpleasant. 
 In straining and in cramp the violent contraction of the mus- 
 cles causes an extremely painful pressure on the nerves. 
 
 The percept is physical solidity or impenetrability, one of 
 the defining qualities of body. To this must be added its 
 modifications arising from gravity, known as heavy and light, 
 and from cohesion, known as hard and soft. As immecUately 
 perceived, these are affections of the excited sensory, which 
 we learn to attribute to external bodies, meaning that they 
 have power to cause these sensorial states in us. 
 
 In different parts of the general organ, as in case of touch, 
 sensation and perception vary inversely. In many parts the 
 perceptive power is very acute, is a most important means of 
 information, and is susceptible of high education. 
 
 It must be noted that the skin under pressure, as when 
 slightly pinched, gives quite the same sense-perception, and 
 so far coincides with muscular sense. But, let it be observed, 
 this impression is very different from the tactile impression 
 proper, one point of difference being that the latter is acute, 
 the former the massive; the one has intensity, the other 
 quantity. 
 
 § 28. As the muscular sense is sometimes overlooked or 
 not sharply discriminated even in scientific treatises, we will 
 add some illustrations of its special importance. 
 
 1 Neither Hamilton nor Mansel attribute any special percept to the mus- 
 cular sense apart from voluntary locomotion. This seems to be very generally 
 true of both psychologists and physiologists. 
 
22 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 One's knowledge of the posture of his body, as standing, 
 sitting, or reclining, and of the position and motion of his 
 limbs, is dependent on this sense. All balancing of the body, 
 though usually assisted by the eye, is largely due to the mus- 
 cular sense, and this alone proves sufficient in the dark. In 
 the feats of a tight^rope dancer, we see it highly educated. 
 Also in the skilful handling of tools. In general, the vary- 
 ing pressures on the muscular sensor nerves furnish intima- 
 tions that enable us to control our movements intelligently.^ 
 
 The soles of the feet are higlily sensitive to touch, and but 
 feebly perceptive ; while, on the contrary, the muscular 
 sensation caused by their pressure under the Aveight of the 
 body is unobtrusive, and the percej^tive power remarkably 
 acute. The tactile sense-perception is largely eliminated by 
 wearing shoes, and it is by the muscular sense that we take 
 knowledge of the ground we step upon. Its importance in 
 walking is evident. 
 
 Our estimate of the weight of a body held in the hand is 
 muscular and quite delicate.^ The small muscles moving the 
 eyeballs greatly assist us, by their various tensions, to judge 
 of the direction, distance, and size of visible objects. The 
 tongue is not only the organ of taste, and exceedingly sensi- 
 tive to touch and to temperature, but it is also a very delicate 
 muscular organ. By a distinct set of sensor nerves we are 
 enabled to know the posture of the tongue, and to adjust it 
 
 1 ' ' The effort needed for the support of the body is ordinarily kept np by 
 the muscular sense. But if the sensor nerve of the leg be paralyzed, the 
 contraction of its muscles cannot be sustained by the strongest effort of the 
 will unless sight be made to replace the lost feeling. The existence of this 
 partial paralysis may sometimes be recognized by the persistent looking 
 downward of those who suffer from it ; for if whilst walking thej'' were to - 
 withdraw their eyes from their feet, their legs would give way under them." 
 — Dk. Carpenter, Mental Phijmology, § 192. See also § 80. 
 
 2 The estimate is determined by two considerations, — the pressure on the 
 muscles underlying it, and the tension of those of the arm. By the former 
 alone Weber found he could distinguish between 14] and 15 oz. ; but when 
 the weight was lifted, exciting the muscles of the arm, he could then distin- 
 guisli between 19] and 20 oz. 
 
THE SOMATIC SENSES. 23 
 
 at will. Upon this fact largely depends the power of articu- 
 late speech. 
 
 Habitually, by an act of will, we fix certain muscles in a 
 state of tension, and then trust them without further thought 
 or volition, though we are probably conscious, obscurely and 
 continuously, of their tension. Thus the muscles of the fore- 
 arm keep the pen lightly held by the fingers while one is 
 thinking what to write, the eyes remain open, the mouth 
 closed, and the muscles of the back keep the body erect, 
 without attention. A muscle thus fixed, like a soldier at an 
 appointed post, does not relax until the order from head- 
 quarters is withdrawn or a new one given. There is hardly 
 a waking moment when many muscles are not thus at ap- 
 pointed service, and but for their faithfulness when not under 
 the eye of attention we should be incapable of our most ordi- 
 nary occupations. When sleep overcomes us, will resigns, 
 these tensions relax, and the system finds relief and repose. 
 
 § 29. An observation on the sensus vagus^ the vital or 
 organic sense, may be inserted here. It might be subdivided 
 into a number of special senses pertaining to the nutritive 
 and other vital functions, and concerned with health and dis- 
 ease. They are highly, almost wholly, subjective, appearing 
 in visceral sensations, marked as agreeable when normal and 
 healthful, but in case of disorder, strongly marked as dis- 
 agreeable and often painful. In many cases they are diffused 
 through the system, as restlessness, faintness, and the idio- 
 pathic sensations generally. 
 
 A number of organic senses are classed as desires under the 
 name of appetites, as hunger, thirst, drowsiness, etc. This is 
 the case when to the sensation is superadded a want, a long- 
 ing for some physical alterative. These will be considered 
 more specifically in their proper place under the head of 
 Desires. 
 
 The sensations of heat and cold, being felt acutely by the 
 skin, have commonly been attril)uted to touch. But the 
 
24 INTE OB UCTION. 
 
 cheeks are more sensitive to temperature tlian the lips,^ and 
 the palms than the linger tips ; so that sensitiveness to tem- 
 perature does not correspond to tactile sensibility. The 
 nerves exciting a sense of temperature constitute probably a 
 system distinct from the tactile nerves. Certain minute areas 
 of the skin, called " temperature spots," and these only, re- 
 spond to thermal stimulus. Pricking them does not give 
 pain, nor tactile sensation, but only a sense of heat or cold. 
 For some of these minute areas, the " cold spots," are sensi- 
 tive to cold only ; others, the " heat spots," to heat only. 
 They are very irregularly distributed, but where the skin is 
 most sensitive to either temperature, the corresponding kind 
 of spot is most numerous. These facts, and the fact that the 
 sense of temperature is more percipient than the vital senses 
 generally, suggest that it might fairly be classed as a sensus 
 fixus? 
 
 All overstrained sensations are painful. But there is a 
 form of physical pain which may be distinguished from all 
 others ; it is the pain attendant on lesion. Since it is unac- 
 companied by any perceptional phase, it may be called pure 
 pain.3 We are wholly occupied with the subjective state, 
 and perception seems reduced to zero. The distinction be- 
 
 1 The cheeks burn with a blush. A laundress usually tests her smoothing- 
 iron by holding it near her cheek. The elbow is very sensitive to tempero/- 
 ture, and the German mother tests the baby's bath with it rather than with 
 her hand. 
 
 2 Weber found that by the finger he could perceive a difference of about 
 1° F., which is less than that marked on common thermometers. We call 
 a body cold when it draws heat from us, and warm when it imparts heat. 
 The human zero is about 98° F. That of cold-blooded animals must be 
 lower. 
 
 3 Weber observes that if we place the edge of a sharp knife gently on the 
 skin, tactile sensation is experienced, and perception attributes to the edge 
 tangibility. But if we press on it and cut the skin, the feeling is one differ- 
 ing not merely in degree, but distinctly in kind. We feci pure pain, a feeling 
 not attributed to tlie knife by any accompanying perceptional power ; for the 
 knife is recognized as the cause quite indirectly, only through the senses- 
 proper. 
 
THE SOMATIC SENSES. 25 
 
 tween pure pain and that attending sense-perceptions is in 
 many cases obscure, especially in the idiopathic sensations of 
 numbness, nervousness, shuddering, and the like ; but in 
 general it may be described as the pain attending lesion, dis- 
 order, disorganization, and death. 
 
 Physiologically and pathologically the senstts vagus is of 
 the highest interest, but its study has added little to the 
 knowledge of mind. 
 
 § 30. If the foregoing views be correct, it is evident that, 
 were we limited to the perceptions of sense, we would be shut 
 up from a knowledge of the outer world, for no one of the 
 senses, nor any combination of them, reveals to us aught be- 
 yond certain states of our own nervous organism. It will be 
 hereafter explained that it is the power of voluntary locomo- 
 tion, combined with sense-perception, that gives knowledge 
 of external body, and introduces us to the outer material 
 universe. 
 
20 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 CHAPTER III. 
 
 THE NERVOUS ORGANISM. 
 
 § 31. Having spoken of the senses specially, we proceed to 
 examine the sentient or nervous organism generally, in order 
 that we may better understand the relation of consciousness 
 to our physical changes. 
 
 Physiologists distinguish two nervous systems, — the sym- 
 pathetic and the cerebro-spinal. The former consists chiefly 
 of a double chain of nervous ganglia lying at the sides and 
 in front of the spinal column, and connected vnth. one 
 another and with the spinal nerves by commissural cords. 
 From these ganglia nerve trunks are given off, which are 
 distributed in filaments for the most part to the vessels 
 of the body. Accordingly, this sympathetic system is re- 
 lated especially to the viscera. It influences the muscles 
 of the vessels generally, those of the heart, of the intestines, 
 and others. The action of these muscles is beyond the reach 
 of volition, and normally not attended by consciousness. 
 Hence we may omit any special consideration of the sympa- 
 thetic system. 
 
 § 32. The cerebro-spinal system consists of the cerebro- 
 spinal axis, and the nerves branching from it. The axis con- 
 sists of the brain and the spinal cord. The nerves are of 
 two sorts. First, the afferent nerves, which convey influences 
 from the periphery toward the centre of ramification, and 
 are mostly sensor nerves exciting the brain, and so causing 
 sense-perceptions. Secondly, the efferent nerves, which 
 convey influences from the centre of la mi neat ion toward the 
 
THE NERVOUS ORGANISM. 27 
 
 periphery, and are mostly motor nerves contracting the 
 muscles.^ 
 
 § 33. There are twelve pairs of cerebral nerves. The 
 first pair, the olfactory nerves, seem to be direct processes 
 of the cerebral hemispheres or upper lobes of the brain. 
 The second pair, the optic nerves, are traceable through 
 the central organs, called t|ie optic thalami, into the cere- 
 bral hemispheres. The rest seem to emanate from the 
 medulla oblongata, the lowest member of the brain. The 
 peripheral terminations of eight of these are distributed, some 
 to the skin of the face, and to the cephalic sense organs, 
 others to the related muscles. Some are afferent sensor 
 nerves ; others are efferent motor nerves. The two remain- 
 ing pairs of cerebral nerves pass into the trunk. 
 
 § 34. The s^^inal cord is a column of soft gray and white 
 neural substance, extending down from the medulla oblon- 
 gata, with which it is continuous, nearly to the second lumbar 
 vertebra, where it tapers off. It is divided longitudinally by 
 deep fissures into two lateral halves connected by a narrow 
 bridge. 
 
 There are thirty-one pairs of spinal nerves. They branch 
 off in two lateral series, one from each half of the cord. Each 
 trunk nerve has two distinct roots connecting it with the 
 cord, one afferent and sensor, the other efferent and motor. 
 After some continuity the trunk nerve subdivides ; one por- 
 tion, the motor, after many further ramifications, is distributed, 
 in minute nervous filaments, to the voluntary muscles ; the 
 other portion, the sensor, after similar subdivisions, is ulti- 
 mately distributed for the most part to the skin. Every 
 voluntary muscle of the trunk and limbs is penetrated 
 throughout its mass by filaments of the motor nerves, and 
 the entire area of the skin has underlying it a complexus 
 
 ^ The distinction between sensor and motor nerves was discovered and 
 demonstrated by Sir Charles Bell in 1821, followed by Magendie. This dis- 
 covery marks the most important epoch in neurological science. 
 
28 lyTRODUCTION. 
 
 of filaments of sensor nerves so complete and close that it 
 can nowhere be punctured by a needle without irritating- 
 them. 
 
 § 35. When the skin, say of the foot, is touched, the ter- 
 minations of sensor nerves immediately beneath are affected. 
 The molecular disturbance thus begun is propagated at a slow 
 rate (about 111 feet a second) along the tactile filaments to 
 the nerve trunk, and along that through its posterior sensor 
 root to the spinal cord ; then along that to the brain and 
 sensory, when consciousness ensues, a sense-perception of 
 contact. This continuous neural connection is requisite to 
 the normal excitement of the sensory, and the excitement of 
 the sensory is essential to sense-perception. 
 
 Now, under the influence of will, another disturbance may 
 begin, which proceeds from the brain down the spinal cord, 
 out through an anterior motor root, into and along the trunk, 
 then through the nerve filaments that jDenetrate the muscles, 
 say of the calf of the leg, which muscles thereupon contract, 
 and the foot is moved. This continuous connection between 
 brain and muscle is essential to voluntary locomotion. 
 
 § 36. The circuit may take place differently. If the sole 
 of the foot be touched with a feather, in an instant the mus- 
 cles of the leg contract, and the foot is jerked away. Con- 
 sciousness occurs, but too late for the action. The thing is 
 done before the will has time to act.^ If the spinal cord 
 have suffered lesion about the middle of the back, so great 
 as to cut off communication between the lower limbs and the 
 brain, the same action occurs, but without consciousness.^ 
 In either case the action is involuntary, instinctive, auto- 
 matic. 
 
 1 This movement is made by a sleeping person. The hand of a babe asleep 
 will close upon a coin as quickly and firmly, in proportion to its strength, as 
 th(! hand of a vigilant miser. 
 
 '■^ This case actually occurred with Dr. Jolm Hunter, who asked his aston- 
 islied patient if he felt the tickling. "No, sir," said he, "but you see my 
 legs do." — CAKrENTKii, Mental J'/tijsiolo(/y, § 08. 
 
TUE NERVOUS ORGANISM. 29 
 
 The interpretation is that a molecular disturbance is prop- 
 agated centripetally from the sole of the foot along afferent 
 nerves to ganglia of the spinal cord, and that it there arouses 
 a comparatively vast amount of molecular activity, which is 
 propagated centrifugally througli efferent fibres to the mus- 
 cles of the leg. This is called neural reflex action, which, in 
 general, may be defined to be the direct conversion, at a 
 ganglionic nerve centre, of afferent into efferent impulses, 
 without the intervention of will, or even of consciousness.^ 
 
 Many muscular activities are due to reflex action. Some 
 are determined by the spinal ganglia, as swallowing, vomit- 
 ing, shuddering; others, by the brain (which comprises 
 ganglionic centres), as winking, and the facial grimace at a 
 bad smell. In a number of cases the involved sensor and 
 motor nerves are partly cerebral and partly spinal, as in 
 breathing, shrinking from a blow, and starting at a sound. 
 All native reflex actions, being involuntary and automatic, 
 are strictly physical instincts .^ 
 
 § 37. A form of activity originally voluntary may by fre- 
 quent repetition become involuntary and purely automatic, 
 
 1 The reflex action of the nervous system was discovered by Dr. Marshall 
 Hall, and announced in Philosophical lyansactions for 1833. It is evidently 
 not a mere rebound, as the phrase (first used by Astruc) suggests, of the 
 afferent impulse into an efferent channel, but rather as if an order were given 
 along the afferent nerve to a ganglionic centre, and executed by it often with 
 a vast expenditure of force. An unexpected whisper from behind, in the ear 
 of a nervous person, is a very slight impulse, which passes along the afferent 
 auditory nerve to the medulla oblongata, and there causes a kind of explosion 
 which affects the majority of the motor nerves of the whole body, manifest 
 in a violent convulsive start, to which is added perhaps a scream, all this 
 enormously disproportioned result being involuntary, instinctive reflex action. 
 
 2 In the winking that moistens or guards the eye, the optic nerves are the 
 afferent, and the facial nerves the efferent, channels. In the grimace at a 
 bad smell, the olfactoiy nerves are the afferent, and the facial nerves again 
 the efferent, channels. All these nerves are cerebral. Other examples are 
 the contraction of the iris under the stimulus of strong light, the contraction 
 of the ciliary muscle in the adjustment of the eye to distinct vision, and the 
 muscular adjustment of the tension of the tympanic membrane of the ear to 
 sounds of various intensity. The flow of saliva excited by a sapid body, and 
 
30 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 the activity being then determined wholly by the reflex 
 action of the nervous system. In the process there is 
 a gradual and more or less complete transfer from mental 
 ao-ency to physical agency. This is muscular education, the 
 acciuisition by repetition of a physical habit or muscular 
 dexterity. Examples are, learning to walk, to dance, to 
 write, to handle tools, to play a musical instrument. Such 
 actions are never performed with ease, grace, and skill, until 
 they have become largely mechanical, and the performer an 
 automaton. An act of volition is usually requisite to start 
 the series of movements, which then continues automatically 
 by mere reflex action. Being obscurely conscious of the 
 series as a whole, without distinguishing its members, we 
 superintend its course, and are ready at any instant to inter- 
 fere by volition, and so check, modify, or suspend the 
 action.^ 
 
 It is evident that in reflex action we have a complete 
 
 the flow of tears excited by a mote in the eye, are remarkable as reflex action 
 on glands instead of muscles. 
 
 In many cases the nerves belong partly to the cerebral and partly to the 
 spinal series. For example, the sucking of an infant. Cold on the face, as 
 from the action of a fan, stimulates respiration. When one's toes are trod 
 upon there is a sudden, instinctive, involuntary outcry and a wry face. 
 Warding off a blow, and all instinctive gesticulation are cases in point. 
 
 It should be observed that the reflex action upon the voluntary muscles 
 can be more or less completely inhibited by the will of the patient. If he 
 anticipates the consequence of- the impression, he can in most cases prevent 
 its occurrence by a resolute resistance. E.g. writhing, jerking, and laughing, 
 the natural effects of tickling, may all be restrained, and (juiet maintained 
 under it. The inhibition in many cases may become habitual, and the mus- 
 cles cease to respond to the excitation. 
 
 1 In walking, the reflex action is sustained by the successive pressures of 
 the feet on the ground, each of these exciting the next movement. Numerous 
 instances are on record of a soldier continuing to march although fallen 
 asleep. 
 
 Houdin practised juggling with balls until he could keep in the air four 
 balls at once. He then accustomed himself, still keeping the balls going, 
 to read without hesitation or distraction. — Autobioffraphy, p. 2(5. I myself 
 have seen a pianist reading a novel placed on the music desk while i)ractising 
 intricate finger exercises. 
 
THE NEEVOUS ORGANISM. 31 
 
 explanation of acquired skill, dexterities, and habits, without 
 recourse to a theory of obliviscence, or to one of latent voli- 
 tions or other unconscious modes of mind. It is an exjolana- 
 tion now universally approved, and transfers the further 
 consideration of these phenomena from psychology to physi- 
 ology. 
 
 § 38. The anatomy of the brain is intricate, and the func- 
 tions of its members are obscure. The lowest part is the 
 medulla oblongata, into which the spinal cord passes insen- 
 sibly. In rear of its upper portion is a laminated spheroidal 
 mass called the cerebellum. Above and in front of these 
 stands the cerebrum, consisting of two symmetrical halves, 
 called the cerebral hemispheres, connected by a voluminous 
 commissure. Each hemisphere presents a central mass and a 
 peripheral envelope, which last is marked superficially by 
 numerous and intricate convolutions.^ 
 
 § 39. The neural matter of the organism in general is of 
 two sorts, — the white and the gray matter. The white matter 
 is fibrous in structure, even where it lies in masses ; the gray 
 matter is cellular. The nerve fibres and trunks consist of 
 white matter. The spinal cord and the medulla consist of 
 both, the white outside, the gray within. The cerebellum 
 and the cerebral hemispheres also consist of both, but with 
 them the gray is outside, and the white within. The central 
 mass, which presents a number of distinct organs, consists of 
 the two kinds of matter variously intermixed. Apparently 
 the function of the white fibrous matter is to transmit impres- 
 sions ; that of the gray cellular matter, to receive, transform, 
 and emit impressions. 
 
 The peripheral or outer organs of sense and of motion are, 
 
 1 "Les difBcultgs que prgsente I'etude de la physiologie cerebrale sont 
 grandes. II n'y a pas seulement divergence d'hypotheses ; les faits eux- 
 memes ne sont point certains, et les contradictions abondent. C'est dire 
 que la base sur laquelle doit s'elever I'edifice fait encore defaut." — M. de 
 Vakigny, in Bevue des Deux Mondes, Oct. 15, 1880. The article reviews 
 especially Dr. David Ferrier's investigations. 
 
 V 
 
32 INTBODUCTION. 
 
 with two exceptions (sight and smell), connected by white 
 fibres with the medulla. This again is similarly connected 
 with the various organs which constitute the central mass of 
 each cerebral hemisphere. The fibres penetrating these organs 
 are probably in communication Avith their gray cellules. From 
 these cellules start out other white fibres, directed towards 
 the cortex of the hemispheres, in such vast numbers that the 
 white matter of each hemisphere presents the appearance of a 
 solid mass. These fibres terminate probably in the gray cel- 
 lules of the cortex. The central organs thus seem interposed, 
 in the course of the cerebral fibres, between their common 
 receptacle, the medulla, and their central terminations in the 
 outer coating of the brain. 
 
 § 40. This anatomical disposition seems to indicate that 
 the central organs of the hemispheres are not, as has been 
 supposed, the place where sensitive impressions terminate 
 and in which motor incitations originate. Rather the pe- 
 ripheral convoluted envelope or cortex of the hemispheres 
 would seem to be the seat of those molecular changes which 
 are attended by consciousness, and transform sensor into 
 motor influence. This is the doctrine which now tends to 
 prevail among physiologists. Recent observations and experi- 
 ments have rendered it at least highly probable that specific 
 superficial tracts of the hemispheres are in their functions 
 essential to specific sense-perceptions, others to voluntary 
 muscular action, and yet others to specific modes of intelli- 
 gence. Dividing the hemispheres into three zones by nearly 
 vertical planes, sense-perception has been attributed to the 
 cortex of the posterior zone, and the sight centres definitely 
 located; motor powers have been attributed to the middle 
 zone, and intellectual powers to the anterior zone.^ 
 
 1 Until quite recent times the central mass was the chief object of study, 
 and the convolutions were neglected. Hippocrates saw in them only a gland ; 
 so also Malpighi and Vli'ussfns. liuysoh, struck with their vascularity, con- 
 sidered them a simple laris saiujuin ; Boerhaave and Ilallcr adopted this 
 
THE NERVOUS ORGANISM. 33 
 
 § 41. There is a reasonable supposition tliat the various 
 centres of the brain operate and interact, in a manner akin to 
 the reflex action already described, at times when the mind's 
 activity is temporarily suspended or engrossed by other impres- 
 sions ; and that the results of this brain work, of which at the 
 time we may be wholly unconscious, become manifest subse- 
 quently in an increased facility of mental exercise in certain 
 directions, in new suggestions, and even in elaborate intel- 
 lectual products. This is the hypothesis of unconscious cer- 
 ebration. It serves to explain a number of phenomena which 
 otherwise are obscure. The invigorating influence of rest and 
 sleep is no doubt due to the restoration of nervous waste, and 
 a readjustment of functional powers. The refreshment found 
 
 conclusion. Vicq d'Azyr was the first to examine their structure ; since 
 tlien Baillarger, Ehrenberg, Purkinje, Meynert, Luys, Betz, and Charcot 
 have made them precisely known. So much for the anatomy. 
 
 As for the physiology, Gall maintained that intelligence is a function of 
 the convolutions ; Desmoulins, that it is in direct proportion to their number 
 and depth ; which, indeed, seems to have been affirmed by Erasistratus, the 
 grandson of Aristotle. In 1861, Broca, taking the notions and facts of Dax 
 and Bouilland, and adding his own views, announced the first-known localiza- 
 tion, that of articulate speech or word-forming ijower, in the third frontal 
 convolution of the left hemisphere. 
 
 In 1870 two German savans, Eritsch and Hitzig, passed a current of 
 electricity across the head behind the ears, and observed that it deter- 
 mined the movement of the eyes. This was an epoch-making discovery. 
 By varying the experiments it was established that in the periphery of the 
 brain there is a part appropriate to the production of movements, i.e. a motor 
 region ; and another where excitation does not pi'ovoke any exterior manifes- 
 tation, i.e. a non-motor region. Moreover, the motor region is stibdivided 
 into a certain number of small tracts, each of which presides over the motion 
 of a particular group of muscles, and of this group only. Such is the point 
 of deijarture of the theory of cerebral localization. 
 
 David Eerrier advanced beyond these conclusions, and it appears to result 
 from his investigations that the convolutions, both in man and in brutes, are 
 divided into three regions, as stated above in the text. See his Functions 
 of the Brain. Of late the matter has been much discussed, and authorities 
 greatly differ. Adhuc sub judice lis est. The literature is abundant. The 
 reader may profitably consult Ladd's Outlines of Physiological rsychology 
 (1891), chs. 8 and 9. Also Am. Journal of Psychology, April, 1891 ; article 
 iii., on Cerebral Localization. 
 
34 IN TE OD UCTION. 
 
 in passing from one mental occupation to another is due to 
 the employment of a different set of organs, giving the others 
 time for renewal. It seems, therefore, no very violent suppo- 
 sition that the brain, apart from all consciousness, may evolve 
 actual products which afterward come into mind, and startle 
 us as strange, unsought, unexpected. 
 
 We have seen that conscious voluntary exercise of the 
 muscles becomes by repetition involuntary and automatic, 
 and is performed under nervous influences with a minimum 
 of consciousness, or perhaps unconsciously. Similarl}', the 
 brain may fairly be supposed to acquire habits, and to operate 
 with facility along certain lines of preferred activity inde- 
 pendently of consciousness. This analogy goes to support 
 the hypothesis of automatic brain action, or unconscious 
 cerebration.! 
 
 § 42. In psychology proper or pure, which is altogether 
 subjective, being concerned only with the facts of conscious- 
 ness, there is no need to determine the functions of the vari- 
 ous brain organs, or to fix upon distinct sensor and motor 
 centres, or to ascertain what work the brain does apart from 
 mind. These interesting and important questions belong 
 rather to physiological psychology. There is no doubt that 
 the cerebral hemispheres are the seat of physical powers essen- 
 tial to the phenomena of consciousness. This general fact of 
 neurology is sulhcient for psychology ; and so, when occasion 
 requires the reference, we shall continue, as heretofore, to 
 designate in an indefinite way, the brain organ, or complexus 
 of organs, whose functional exercise is attended by conscious- 
 ness, as the sensory, and the place within the cranium where 
 this exercise occurs, as the sensorium.^ 
 
 1 See Dr. Carpenter's Mental Phijsiolof/fj, ch. 13, for arguments and 
 striking illustrations. 
 
 " Seiisoriuni is a place, not an organ. "Bene multi barbarum scholastico- 
 runi, qui interduin sunt siniia; GnBCorum, tlicunt AiffOrjrripLov. Ex quo illi 
 fecerunt sensitorium pro sensorio, id est, organum sensationis." — Goclenils, 
 Lexicon Philosophicum, ad verb. Leibnitz emphasizes this. 
 
PHYSIOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGY. 35 
 
 CHAPTER IV. 
 
 PHYSIOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGY. 
 
 § 43. It is evident that the facts considered in the preced- 
 ing chapters are in the main physiological, and that the 
 inferences have been made from this objective standpoint. 
 The neural functions, especially relative to sense-perception, 
 have been briefly treated, and some important general conclu- 
 sions reached respecting the relation of physical to subjective 
 or psychical states. The whole of this introductory part, 
 might, therefore, be included under the title of Physiological 
 Psychology, which has been widely described as " psychology 
 approached from the physiological side or point of view," and 
 more accurately defined as " the science of the phenomena of 
 human consciousness in their relations to the structure and 
 functions of the nervous system." ^ 
 
 But the phrase may be fairly, and indeed is commonly, 
 understood to refer specifically to certain researches with 
 their results which have been prosecuted with great zeal of 
 late years. The investigator, starting with physiological 
 facts, and seeking to discover what elementary psychological 
 facts are connected with them, adds external experiment to 
 internal observation. He begins without and seeks to pene- 
 trate within experimentally. The method consists in varying 
 the external conditions that are necessary to produce the in- 
 ternal phenomena, the former being a doorway to the latter. 
 Moreover, he proposes, as far as practicable, to measure the 
 quantities of the phenomena, and thus elevate psychology, 
 from a science of classification and description, to the rank of 
 
 1 Ladd's Outlines, p. 5. See also his more elaborate Elements of Physio- 
 logical Psychology. 
 
36 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 an exact science in which determined quantities are super- 
 added to observed qualities. ^ Tlie avowed end is to con- 
 struct a new psychology on a new basis, the means being 
 physiological. This is Physiological Psychology in the nar- 
 rower sense. Accordingly, under this title, we now propose 
 to give a brief sketch of the work done and the results 
 attained, together with an estimate of their value.^ 
 
 § 44. Johann Miiller, the famous physiologist of Berlin 
 University, in metaphysics a disciple of Kant, is the founder 
 of this branch of psychology. In his great work on physi- 
 ology^ he pays much attention to psychological questions, 
 and endeavors to assign an objective basis to the subjective 
 forms in intuition. He transformed, for example, the Kan- 
 tian doctrine of space, claiming that the retina has a native 
 feelinsr of its extension. 
 
 Subsequently each kind of sensation became an object of 
 research, the qualitative and intensive differences being care- 
 fidly estimated. E. H. Weber, of Leipsic (1840), first sub- 
 jected consciousness to methods of exact experiment. He 
 published the results of nearly twenty years of the most 
 painstaking observations on the effects of touch and pres- 
 sure, in a Latin monograph, and wrought out the first form 
 of the psycho-physical law, the exact application of which 
 is now reduced to narrow limits chiefly by the labors of 
 Fechner. 
 
 Helmholtz, the physicist of Berlin, having measured the 
 rate of nervous propagation, was followed by Donders, wlio 
 attempted to determine the duration of psychic acts. Sensa- 
 
 1 Certain scientists, pliysicists especially, are disposed to claim that no 
 complement of knowledge can i^roperly rank as a science until it has become 
 quantitative. We cannot assent to this. Science is primarily and essentially 
 qualitative classification. See § 50. 
 
 2 See Ribot's German rsycholomi of To-day, to which I am indebted for 
 many points. A fair sketch of Experimental Psycholor/n, by Professor, now 
 President, G. Stanley Ilall, will be found in Mind for April, 1885. 
 
 3 Ilandliirh der Physioloijir dcs ^fens<•hc)l, 2 vols., 1841-44. 
 
PHYSIOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGY. 37 
 
 tion was siDecially studied, and inferences made to other 
 mental activities. 
 
 Besides the savans already named, Herbart, Duhois-Rey- 
 mond, Volkmann, Lotze, Delbceuf, Exner, Wundt, Zeller, 
 Hall, and many others, have contributed to this branch of 
 psychology, most of them being distinguished in other 
 departments of scientific research. 
 
 Wundt of Leipsic is perhaps the most eminent living rep- 
 resentative of experimental psychology. He alone, says 
 Ribot, has treated it in all its area. He alone has made a 
 complete and systematic study of its problems from this 
 standpoint. The unity of his work arises from his method. 
 It is based on the data of physiology. It deals directly with 
 sensation, which he distinctly considers the basis of all psy- 
 chology, and further with involuntary movement, language, 
 and the natural expression of feelings; indirectly it deals 
 with the will, attention, complex notions of space and time, 
 the general notion, the aesthetic and the religious feeling. 
 When physiology fails, recourse is had to anthropology, 
 ethnography, history, or statistics. To introspection, which 
 cannot be set aside, it adds external observation and experi- 
 ment, seeking where possible to apply quantitative measure- 
 ment. This is physiological psychology in its widest sense. 
 
 § 45. We shall now attempt a brief sketch of the subordi- 
 nate branches psycho-physics and psychometry, in order that 
 the reader may have a more definite conception of the 
 methods and results of physiological psychology. 
 
 Weber inferred inductively, from his experiments on 
 length, weight, sound, etc., a general law. Its formula is : 
 "Sensation grows with equal increments, when the excita- 
 tion grows with relatively equal increments." By relatively 
 equal increments is meant a constant fraction of the succes- 
 sive excitations. 
 
 From this starting point Fechner pursued his studies 
 whose results were published in 1860 under the title Ele- 
 
38 INTEOBUCTION. 
 
 ments of Psycho-physics. He says : " I understand by psycho- 
 physics an exact theory of the relations of soul and body, 
 and in a general way of the physical world with the psychi- 
 cal world." But though he thus proposes to give a general 
 theory, his experimental research bears definitely on a single 
 point — the relation of excitation and sensation. To deter- 
 mine this, he spent years in experiment and calculation. His 
 object is to measure sensation, passing from mere quality to 
 exact quantity. For sensations obviously have both quality 
 and intensity or quantity. Thus red, blue, green, are quali- 
 ties marking kinds of color, but each varies in intensity. So 
 every sensation has a quantitative value. Now what better 
 means for estimating this value of a sensation can be found 
 than the external movement from which the sensation arises? 
 The excitation is not only the most direct, but perhaps the 
 only possible measure of sensation. It is the intensity of the 
 cause used to estimate the intensity of the effect. 
 
 To measure the differences in intensity of a given sensa- 
 tion, Fechner applied his "method of smallest perceptible 
 differences." 1 If an imperceptible difference between two 
 weights be caused to grow, it will at last become just percep- 
 tible. This minimum difference he adopted as a unit of sen- 
 sation. Having obtained it, by numerous experiments, for 
 sensations of pressure, of temperature, and of sound, he con- 
 cluded, in order that each of these sensations shall increase 
 by its smallest perceptible difference, the excitation must 
 increase by one-third of its intensity .^ 
 
 In order to construct a scale of magnitudes, besides the 
 unit of division, the zero point must be ascertained. Evi- 
 dently in these cases the zero is where the incipient sensation 
 arises. The quantum of excitation requisite to produce this 
 
 1 Fechner supplemented this method by two others, " the method of true 
 and false cases," and "the method of nieiiu errors," all leading by different 
 routes to the same end. 
 
 2 He found that light requires an increase of only a hundredth part of its 
 intensity, in order to cause a perceptible difference. 
 
PHYSIOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGY. 39 
 
 beginning of sensation was called by Herbait the value of 
 the threshold of the stimulus or excitation (^Reizschivelle). 
 It was needful, therefore, to determine, if possible, by a series 
 of observations and experiments, the exact threshold value 
 for each kind of sensation. Accordingly, it was determined 
 for pressure on various parts of the body, for temperature, 
 for sound, and for light. 
 
 The zero of each being fixed, and the scale constructed, a 
 comparison of scales revealed a uniformity which Fechner 
 formulated into his now famous Law of Psycho-physics. 
 One expression is : The excitation must grow in geometrical 
 progression in order that the sensation shall grow in arith- 
 metical progression. One more exact is : The sensation 
 varies as the logarithm of the excitation. 
 
 § 46. How shall we estimate the value of this law ? By 
 the fierceness of the contention which has arisen about it? 
 Then surel}^ it is of very great weight. Hering of Prague 
 attacked psycho-physics at all points, denying the conclu- 
 sions of Fechner, especially that the logarithmic law follows 
 from Weber's law, and that it has any wide generality. His 
 is the severest assault that the partisans of the doctrine have 
 had to meet. Delboeuf defends Fechner on some points, but 
 will not allow the mathematical form which his work assumes. 
 In short, he rejects a part of the doctrine, and modifies what 
 he does not reject. To his denial that the smallest perceptible 
 difference is constant, Wundt replies that it is necessarily so ; 
 for "• if the change of either of the two sensations compared 
 were greater or less than the other, it would be therein 
 greater or less than the perceptible minimum, which is con- 
 trary to the hypothesis." But while defending this funda- 
 mental point, Wundt does not accept the entire doctrine, he 
 having original views respecting the measurement of psychic 
 facts. Zeller argues the impossibility of their absolute meas- 
 urement, and Wundt replies that by similar reasoning it 
 mig-ht be maintained that no external natural phenomena are 
 
 ^-5^-^ OF THS ^« 
 
40 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 measurable. The discussion has been wide, profound, and 
 seems interminable. " Fechner, " says Delboeuf, " has against 
 him both his declared adversaries and his more or less faith- 
 ful disciples." To this Fechner replies: "The Tower of 
 Babel was not finished because the workmen could not agree 
 as to the method of constructing it; my psycho-physical 
 monument will remain because the workmen cannot agree as 
 to the method of destroying it." 
 
 "The most that can be said," Professor Ladd concludes, 
 "is this: The law summarizes many facts reasonably well 
 within a certain range of sensations lying near the middle of 
 the scale of quantity, and for certain of the senses." Ribot 
 sums up the results of criticism thus : " First, that under its 
 mathematical form the law of Fechner cannot be accepted. 
 Second, that observation and experiment show that, gener- 
 ally speaking, sensation grows more slowly than excitation. 
 Thirdly, that though it be verified within certain limits 
 for visual and auditory sensations, it is contested for pressure, 
 and does not hold for the other sensations." 
 
 § 47. Experiments have been made to determine the time 
 occupied by certain mental acts, and the results given under 
 the title Psychometr}^ It has always been a common belief 
 that some time, however short, is required to think, to re- 
 member, and even to feel. Measurements of this time were 
 made, especially by Bonders, followed by Exner of Vienna, 
 Wundt, Kries, and many others, from 18(50 to 1880, with fair 
 chronoscopic accuracy. 
 
 In 1850 Helmholtz, incited by the views of Dubois-Rey- 
 mond on the electric properties of nerves (1849), ascertained 
 by experiment the time of the transmission of neural action 
 through a definite nerve length.^ Other scientists renewed 
 
 1 He excited the nerve near the muscle on which it acts, and noted the 
 time between the excitation and the contraction. 'PhtMi rcpeatinj^ the experi- 
 ment at a point more distant from tlie nuiscle, he found tlie time to be 
 greater. Tlie difference of distance iu the difference of time gives the rate. 
 
PHYSIOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGY. 41 
 
 the investigation, and the average of results is given by Her- 
 mann (1874) as 83.9 metres, or about 111 feet a second.^ 
 
 This being settled, suppose a patient to receive a slight 
 electric shock in his finger-tip, and to respond as promptly as 
 possible by a tap with a finger of the other hand. The total 
 interval, called the reaction time, is found to be about 0.15 
 of a second. Now it is evident that this period consists of 
 three parts : first, the time of transmission from the finger- 
 tip to the brain along a sensor nerve ; second, that from the 
 brain along a motor nerve to the muscle moving the other 
 finger, these two together being called the physiological 
 time ; and third, an interval occupied by sense-perception 
 and volition, called the psychological or psychic time. Now 
 subtracting the physiological time from the total or reaction 
 time, 0.15 sec, we have the psj^chic time, equal to about 
 0.08 sec.^ The experiment has been performed a great many 
 times, and modified for the different senses. 
 
 Efforts have been made to analyze the psychic interval into 
 the time of sense-perception and the time of volition. It 
 is concluded that the duration of volition depends chiefly on 
 the more or less direct connection between the sensor and 
 motor centres. When this mechanism, and also the natural 
 quickness and habits of the patient, these last constituting 
 his " personal equation," are favorable, the time for the 
 volition is much diminished. It should be added that the 
 expectation of the patient, and the degree of his attention, 
 as well as the intensity of the stimulus, shorten the reaction 
 time. 
 
 Various methods have been employed to measure the dis- 
 
 1 The rate of this propagation is comparatively slow, being only about yV 
 that of sound waves in the air, which is 1120 ft. per sec. at 60° F. Its nature 
 is unknown. Clearly it is not electric. It may perhaps prove to be electro- 
 lytic, or analogous to electrolysis, whose rate has not, I believe, been deter- 
 mined, though it would seem easy to measure the retardation, if any, of the 
 electric current through an electrolyzed medium. 
 
 - It would be better to call this psycho-physical time, because during this 
 interval the central physical changes in the cerebrum also take place. 
 
42 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 cernment time, i.e. how long it takes to distinguish one of 
 two impressions of sense. In one methpd the patient is 
 Avarned to expect one of two colors named, but is not told 
 which. He is to decide which appears, and to signal the 
 instant the discrimination is effected. The mean time, from 
 many experiments by this method, was found to lie between 
 0.047 and 0.086 of a second. Combining it with the results 
 of other methods, the discernment time is found to vary, 
 when the conditions are of the simpler sort, from 0.1 to 0.03 
 of a second or less. 
 
 Similar investigations on the time required to reproduce 
 ideas by memory conclude in general : first, that the repro- 
 duction takes longer than the original production ; second, 
 the time depends largely on the degree of attention given to 
 the original production, and also to that given to the repro- 
 duction. 
 
 Finally, the time requisite to a logical process, say the 
 subordination of a species under its genus, has also been a 
 matter of experiment. It is found that the time is shortest 
 when the subject is concrete and the predicate a narrow 
 class, e.g. lions are cats ; and longest when the subject is 
 abstract and the predicate a notion of wide generality, e.g. 
 holiness is the sum of perfections. This is what might be 
 expected from the comparative difficulty of the thoughts. 
 The experiments result in an average of about one second.^ 
 
 § 48. Thus in the most elementary manner we have tried to 
 give a glimpse of what has been done and is doing in physi- 
 ological psychology. It is obviously a bare beginning on a 
 new line, and what may come of it no one can say. But 
 the limitations to which it is necessarily subject forbid 
 the notion that it can ever occupy a chief position in the 
 .science of mind. The possibly measurable (^[uantities in the 
 case are only intensity and duration. The measurement of 
 intensity is rendered very doubtful l)y tlie questionable char- 
 
 1 Baldwin's Handbook of Psycholof/y, p. 112. 
 
PHYSIOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGY. 43 
 
 acter of the unit of sensation employed. And how may we 
 hope to find units for the measure of higher feelings ? Meas- 
 urement of duration does not encounter this difficulty. But 
 is not the so-called psychic interval due to the cerebral move- 
 ments on which the mental process is conditioned ? If so, 
 then this is a neural and not a mental measurement. Aside 
 from these points, it is evident that the microscopic character 
 of the work, the variations due to individual differences, and 
 to other unavoidable causes, limit reliable experiment to the 
 simplest cases, and in these prevent results of more than an 
 average and tentative value. 
 
 Moreover, when we take into consideration the impossi- 
 bility of even approaching the higher powers of mind by 
 such experimentation, our esteem for the method greatly 
 diminishes. All the higher processes which constitute the 
 rational, emotional, and volitional life of man are out of 
 its reach. Ribot, an extreme partisan of the " new psy- 
 chology," himself says, " In all that concerns these phe- 
 nomena, experimental research is necessarily useless." Yet 
 these are of pre-eminent interest, and constitute the great 
 ends of psychological science. 
 
 It may therefore fairly be asked, when all the patient, 
 tedious, minute labor demanded by this method in its narrow 
 field is done, and results apparently so insignificant attained, 
 are they worth their cost ? It is impossible to say. Let us 
 remember the lesson, so often taught in the history of 
 scientific investigation, that no one can forecast what may 
 come of a search in the dark, and that any fact well estal> 
 lished is an addition to the sum of knowledge that may 
 prove of inestimable worth. The difficulties, the obstacles 
 which the physiological psychologist encounters, are very 
 great, but perhaps they may be conquered at last, and we 
 should encourage the audacity that attacks them. The field 
 is new, barely broken and unpromising, but we must admire 
 the patient zeal, the earnest hopefulness that labors for 
 fruitful results where but few, if any, are possible. 
 
44 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 § 49. It is important to observe that this mixed psy- 
 chology is, in all of its aspects, subordinate to and dependent 
 on pure psychology. 
 
 Evidently neither physiology alone, nor psychology alone, 
 can ever give knowledge of the other. Pure psychology is 
 strictly a subjective science, a science of introspection ; pure 
 physiology is strictly an objective science, a science of 
 external observation. It is true that mental action being in 
 direct connection and correlation with neural action, neither 
 can be fully understood without regard to the other. For 
 it is within the province of psychology to trace the mental 
 conditions of knowledge and feeling from the inner towards 
 the outer world ; and it is within the province of physiology 
 to trace their physical conditions from without towards the 
 inner circle of experience. But neither can penetrate into 
 the domain of the other.^ The most perfect analysis of the 
 facts of consciousness could never reveal the functions or 
 even the existence of the outer organs of sense, nor the 
 objective existence, in its physiological aspect, of the cortex 
 of the brain or sensory, the inner organ of consciousness. 
 On the other hand, the most profound and exhaustive study 
 of neurology can never explain the facts of consciousness, 
 or even confirm their existence. If all the cells and fibres 
 involved in each intellectual act or emotional state were 
 numbered, measured, weighed, and their changes exactly 
 ascertained, if all the circulating, thermal, chemical, and 
 electrical motions were exactly formulated, the utter unlike- 
 ness between the objective phenomena and tlie correlative 
 subjective phenomena would completely debar the passage 
 from one to the other, and afford not the slightest knowledge 
 
 1 Says Bain: "Mental states and bodily states are utterly contrasted; 
 they cannot be compared, for they have nothing in common except the most 
 general of all attributes — degree, and order in time ; when engaged with 
 one we must be oblivious of all that distinguishes the other. ( )ur feelings 
 and thoughts have no extension, place, form, or outline, no mechanical division 
 of parts ; and we are incapable of attending to anything nuntal until we shut 
 off the view of all that." — Miixf mid Ihidij. \\ V-V^. 
 
PHYSIOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGY. 46 
 
 of the intellectual act or emotional state. ^ Between the 
 objective and the subjective there is a great gulf fixed. 
 Whatever relations are discernible, it is impossible that the 
 one class of facts should ever replace the other, or that either 
 should ever be interpreted in terms of the other. 
 
 In consequence, however, of the essential connection of 
 mind and body, the phenomena of each stand to those of the 
 other in the relation of cause and effect.^ Upon this the 
 mixed or physiological psychology relies, and seeks in its 
 narrow field a more exact expression and measurement of 
 the facts. Nervous process in its single aspect belongs to 
 physiology; nervous process in this double aspect belongs 
 to the mixed psychology. It studies psychical variations 
 indirectly by the aid of physical variations that can be pro- 
 duced directly. It has for its object the facts of conscious- 
 ness that accompany nervous phenomena. 
 
 This combination of two distinct sciences implies a knowl- 
 edge of each. The physiology of the nervous system must 
 be known to some extent before nervous action can be made 
 the basis of higher experimentation. The better it is known, 
 the more hopeful the procedure. Likewise, the combination, 
 instead of excluding the results of the pure psychology, pre- 
 supposes them. One must know what the phenomena of 
 
 1 Professor Tyndall says ; "Let the consciousness of love be associated 
 with a right-handed spiral motion of the molecules of the brain, and the con- 
 sciousness of hate with a left-handed spiral motion ; we should then know 
 when we love that the motion is in one direction, and when we hate that 
 the motion is in the other, but the v^luj would still remain unanswered." 
 Dr. McCosh adds : " Not only so, but without self-consciousness we could 
 never know that there was love, or that there was hate, or that they had any 
 connection with the motions of the brain." 
 
 2 It was a sore problem with the earlier philosophers as to how mind and 
 matter could interact. Descartes solved it by his theory of occasional causes. 
 Leibnitz solved it by his theory of pre-established harmony. Both had 
 recourse to the Deus ex machina of the ancients. For these historic curiosi- 
 ties, see Hamilton, Meta., p. 208 sq., or any History of Philosophy, e.g. 
 Ueberweg's, § 114 and § 117. We accept the interaction as an ultimate, 
 inexplicable fact. 
 
46 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 consciousness are, must analyze and classify them, must know 
 their relations and laws, before any hopeful attempt can be 
 made to produce and measure them. One must know him- 
 self as thoroughly as possible by an internal study of him- 
 self, together with a comparison of this observation with the 
 observation of others and by others, before he can reasonably 
 enter on an investigation of the quantities of the ascertained 
 facts. Professor Ladd very truly says: "The phenomena 
 of consciousness as primary facts can be ascertained in no 
 other way than in and by consciousness itself. AVhatever 
 fault may be found with the so-called introspective method 
 in psychology, on account of its alleged inaccuracy, lack of 
 scientific and progressive quality, etc., from the very nature 
 of the case, no other way of ascertaining what the phenomena 
 of consciousness in themselves are can ever take the place of 
 the direct examination of consciousness. And there is no 
 way of directly examining consciousness but the way of 
 beinof conscious of one's self." 
 
 Let us then enter upon the study of the pure psychology, 
 a very old science, since it has Aristotle for its founder, 
 fully persuaded that during the twenty centuries of its con- 
 tinuous life, matter worthy of preservation has accumulated, 
 and that it can never be superseded so long as there are sub- 
 jective facts to be investigated, so long as consciousness is 
 the ultimate ground of all science. 
 
ELEMENTS OF PSYCHOLOGY. 
 
 -o-o>»<0<>- 
 
 FART FIRST. 
 
 CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 CHAPTER I. 
 
 PRELIMINARY DEFINITIONS. 
 
 § 50. Psychology is the science of the phenomena of mincl.^ 
 The several terms of this definition call for some explication. 
 
 A science is a logical system of truths. Its matter is exhi- 
 bited in a fixed terminology of precise definition, and in a 
 thoroughly systematized classification. It is a complement of 
 knowledge, a knowledge of the princif)les and causes of the 
 things and events within its bounds,' and of their essential 
 relations, excluding accidental matter.^ 
 
 Sciences are speculative and empirical.^ Speculative or 
 
 1 The word psychology is from \pvxvi soul, and X670S, a reasoning or dis- 
 course. Aristotle has a treatise -n-epl i^vxv^, the De Anima, but the term 
 psychology is quite modern, not being found earlier than 1575. Goclenius 
 first adopted it as a literary title in 1504. Coleridge apologizes for using 
 the insolens verbum, but it is now familiar, and the approved title in all 
 European languages of the subject before us. 
 
 2 Science, Lat. scicntia, from scire, to know ; Grk. eTTLffTrjur], for it leads 
 to some stop or boundary of things (iirl (TrdcTiv). This etymology is given 
 by Plato in the Crutyliis, p. 434 a, ed. Steph. But cf. p. 412 a, ^ eiroixivq rots 
 irpd'yfjLaffi.v. 
 
 3 Speculative, Lat. speculari, to spy out or look into, from specere. 
 
48 CONSCIOifSJ^ESS. 
 
 a priori science is a metliod of pure thought, deducing its 
 system from intuitive, necessary principles \iy the synthesis 
 of these principles alone ; as philosophy, logic, mathematics. 
 Empirical or a posteriori science arises from the facts of expe- 
 rience and observation, and through inductive inference devel- 
 ops its system by the analysis and synthesis of these facts ; as 
 psychology, physiology, chemistry .^ Though necessarily in- 
 volving intuitive principles, empirical science is a knowledge 
 of facts as distinguished from j)rinciples,2 and may be delined 
 as a science of facts generalized and inductively formulated 
 in laws from which deductions are made. 
 
 Empirical, Grk. ifnreipia, experience. Empirical or historical kuowledge, 
 the knowledge of experience, is the knowledge that a thing is, yvua-is &tl ea-ri. 
 Speculative or philosophical knowledge, the knowledge of ratiocination, is the 
 knowledge why or how a thing is, ywQais 5i6ti '4<7ti. ""Ori scienticc fiinda' 
 laentum est, 5i6ti, fastigium.''^ — Trexdelenberg, Elem. Log. Arist. See 
 Sir William Hamilton's detailed account of the term empirical in 3Ieta., Lee. 3. 
 
 1 The phrases a priori and a posteriori were used by the schoolmen in a 
 sense derived from Aristotle, the former to denote a reasoning from cause to 
 effect, the latter a reasoning from effect to cause. More commonly now, in 
 logic, they are used to distinguish between the deduction of a special case 
 from first principles, and the induction of a general truth from observed 
 facts. In philosopliy and psychology knowledge a priori, according to Kant, 
 is that which is independent of all experience, and logically prior to it ; 
 knowledge a posteriori is that acquired by observation of facts, and therefore 
 dependent on, and logically jxisterior to, experience. The one is knowledge 
 of pure, the other of empirical, truth. — Critique of Pure Reason, Int., § 1. 
 Cf. Esser, Logik, §§ 4 and 12 ; Fries, Logik, § 124. Also Hamilton, Meta., 
 p. 285, and Logic, p. 385 (Am. eds.), and his note in BeixFs Works, p. 762. 
 Also Thompson, Outline of the Laics of Thottght, §§ 32, 33 ; and Trendelen- 
 burg, Kj-ccrpta, p. 81. 
 
 2 Principles (principia, oi dpxal, beginnings, elements) are those primary 
 truths which underlie all knowledge. They may either be stated as original 
 elements, in which case they are constitutive, or be formulated as original 
 laws, in which case they are regulative. When taken in a more general 
 sense, the word jmnciple denotes that on which some other truth depends. 
 In this use we may distinguish between a primary or first principle and a 
 secondary principle ; though in strictness the one phrase is tautological, the 
 other self-contradictory. Aristotle notices several meanings of apxaii, and 
 says : " What is common to all principles is tliat they are the primary source 
 from which anything exists, is imxlnced, or is known." — Metn , iv. 1, 3. Cf. 
 Descartes, Priucijii((, /'jiisf. An/. 
 
PRELIMINABr DEFINITIONS. 49 
 
 A phenomenon is that which appears, either to the external 
 or to the internal sense. ^ It is anything manifest to mere 
 observation, as distinguished from the elements into which it 
 is resolved, and the forces and laws by which it is explained. 
 The moon and its changes, if observed, are physical phenom- 
 ena, antecedent to any explanation. The facts of experience, 
 or more generally of consciousness, are psychical phenomena. 
 
 Since the phenomena of mind are facts of experience, psy- 
 chology is an empirical science. It becomes a science by infer- 
 ring from these facts obtained by introspection universal 
 propositions which are formulated as laws of mind, and is 
 therefore an inductive, a posteriori science. And since these 
 facts are modes of consciousness, it may very well be defined 
 as the science of the facts of consciousness. It is the natural 
 history of mind, the science of human nature. 
 
 It is true, however, that on analyzing the facts of conscious- 
 ness we shall find certain elements that are not empirical, not 
 given by, but along with, experience. A consideration of 
 these elements will carry us beyond the bounds of empirical 
 science into philosophy. In this, and perhaps other respects, 
 psychology leads so directly into metaphysics that it is not 
 desirable, and indeed hardly possible, to observe strictly the 
 bounds of these sciences. Whenever, then, it seems needful to 
 elucidate the matter in hand, to confirm the doctrine, or to aug- 
 ment our information, we shall freely transgress the limits of 
 empirical psychology, and touch upon metaphysical inquiries.^ 
 
 1 Phenomenon, (paivofxaL, to appear. In the Kantian philosophy, phenome- 
 non is opposed to noumenon or thing in itself (das Ding in sich) ; that is, the 
 real taken absolutely. Phenomena are things in consciousness ; noumena 
 are things out of consciousness. — C. P. i?., p. 178. A phenomenon, then, is 
 the thing as presented to external or internal sense, as it stands related to 
 mind. Perhaps more fundamentally and strictly a phenomenon is merely 
 an observed change in consciousness. Psychology is concerned only with 
 mental phenomena, with what appears in consciousness, or with the changes 
 in modes of consciousness. It has nothing to do with the nature of interior 
 realities apart from consciousness, this being the province of metaphysics. 
 
 2 To empirical psychology is opposed rational psychologj\ The distinction 
 was first made by Wolf in his works entitled Psyclwlogia Empirica, and 
 
50 CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 The mind is commonly thought of as a substance.^ Matter 
 is extended substance. Mind is conscious substance. Mat- 
 ter and mind arc known to us only under two totally distinct 
 series of phenomena or qualities. Matter manifests extension, 
 solidity, divisibility, figure, motion, color, heat, etc. Mind 
 manifests knowing, feeling, desiring, and willing. Now no 
 quality can be conceived as existing apart, by itself, in abso- 
 lute independence, per se. We necessarily think it the quality 
 of some thing, and the thing in which the quality inheres, 
 that which manifests the phenomenon, we call substance.^ 
 
 Psychologia Rationnlis, 1734. The latter is a branch of ontology, seeking 
 to evolve a priori from the conception of spiritual being those principles 
 that govern its manifestations. The method was in high repute until Kant 
 assailed it, so successfully that it is now hardly recognized. Hence the 
 simple title Psychology is usually given to the empirical science. 
 
 1 The word mind is Anglo-Saxon, allied to Lat. mois and Grk. fi^vos, all 
 probably from a common root preserved in the Sanscrit mena, to know. 
 Soul is now synonymous with mind. Originally it signified only the principle 
 of organic life (anima, i^vx^^), which meaning may be traced in the N. T. 
 trichotomy of body, soul, and spirit (crw/xa, ^/vx-ri, Trvevf/.a). — See 1 ThesS. 5: 
 23. Cf. Plato, in the Timmts, 34 d. sq., and 36 e. sq., ed. Steph. ; also Aris- 
 totle, Pol. 1. In the 0. T. soul (Heb. nephesh) generally means life. Spirit is 
 generic, meaning either an immaterial part that is or has been connected 
 with body, or else an immaterial being never so connected. The words soul 
 and spirit have such strong theological associations that they are little used 
 by psychologists. 
 
 It is remarkable that many words synonymous with mind signify, prima- 
 rily, air in motion. E.g. ypvx"^, dvfx6s, irvevtxa, spiritns, each meaning wind or 
 breath (see John 3:8); animns, from dve/xos, wind ; soul, Ger. Seele, from 
 a Gothic root meaning to storm ; ghost, Ger. Gei.'<t, ghastly, and gas are 
 from a root meaning air ; and the Ileb. nephesh, soul, and ruach, spirit, are 
 from a root which means to breathe. Cf. Gen. 2:7: "breathed into his 
 nostrils the breath of life, and man became a living soul." 
 
 2 Substance (sub and sto, stans, that standing under) has in scholastic 
 philosophy two distinguishable meanings : — 
 
 1st. Ens per se snhsistens, ovala. It is conceived as apart from all qualities, 
 as merely existing. Spinoza says: '■'Per suhstnntiiim iiitclligo id quod in 
 se est, et per se concipitur ; hoc est id cujns conceptus nan indiget conceptii, 
 alterius rei a quo formari dchent.'''' — Ethics, Def. 3. 
 
 2d. Id quod suhstnt accidentibus, vivharacTLS, inroKelixtvov, i.e. the substratum 
 in which qualities inhere, and which is their bond of union. Says Locke : 
 "Tlie idea which we have to which we give the name substance is nothing 
 
PEELIMINABY DEFINITIONS. 51 
 
 Matter is the substance in which material or physical qvialities 
 inhere. Mind is the substance in which mental qualities 
 inhere.^ Since there is no common quality, the presence of 
 any one is distinctive. Some qualities, however, are essential, 
 others accidental. Extension, being an ever-present quality 
 of matter, is considered essential, and taken as its defining 
 quality. Consciousness, being characteristic of all mental 
 phenomena, is considered essential, and taken as the defining 
 quality of mind.^ 
 
 Mind, then, is conscious substance, or better, is the con- 
 scious subject. But this logical definition a priori is of little 
 advantage, the notion being so nearly ultimate. It is more 
 satisfactory, since we know mind only in its phenomena, its 
 conscious acts and affections, to explain the meaning of the 
 word and the nature of the thing by stating them summarily, 
 thus : Mind is that which knows and feels, desires and wills. 
 This is sometimes called the definition a posteriori, but is 
 rather a logical division of the mental powers.^ 
 
 but the supposed but unknown support of those qualities we find existing, 
 which we imagine cannot exist sine re siihstante, without something to sup- 
 port them. We call that support substantia.'''' 
 
 "In the former meaning,"- says Hamilton, "substance is considered in 
 contrast to and independent of its attributes; in the latter, as conjoined with 
 these, and affording them the condition of existence." — Meta., p. 105. 
 
 Herbert Spencer defines the substance of mind as " that which undergoes 
 a modification producing a state of mind." He adds: "Consequently, if 
 every state of mind is some modification of this substance of mind, there can 
 be no state of mind in which the unmodified substance of mind is present." 
 Hence unmodified substance of mind is unknowable. — Principles of Psy- 
 chology, § 59. 
 
 1 Whether these be two distinct substances or only one, a common, 
 substance is a question which just now is disregarded. An examination of 
 it will be found in a subsequent chapter on Mind and Matter. 
 
 2 Descartes said : " Thought is the essence of spirit, extension the essence 
 of matter. The one is known by consciousness, the other by perception." 
 This is, at least, badly stated. Bather, this: "Consciousness is to mind 
 what extension is to matter. Both are phenomena, but both are essential 
 qualities ; for we can neither conceive mind without consciousness, nor body 
 without extension." — Hamilton, Meta., p. 109. 
 
 3 Aristotle, in De Anima, ii. 1, gives an a priori definition of the soul, 
 
52 CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 It will be better, however, to exclude all consideration 
 of substance, and use the word mind to stand merely for a 
 complement of activities. Its substantial essence is a meta- 
 physical theme that does not concern us at present, and would 
 hinder rather than promote our strictly psychological inquiries.^ 
 
 § 51. The most thoroughgoing distinction in psychology is 
 the antithesis between the ego and the non-ego, between self 
 and not-self. The ego is identical with- my mind; the non- 
 ego is any and everything else. All the material universe, all 
 human beings, except myself, are non-ego. My body is mine, 
 but is not I myself. It may be mutilated ; I am still entire. 
 Even the innermost organ of my brain is non-ego. The ego 
 is I myself who stand in conscious opposition to the non-ego. 
 I can conceive myself to exist apart from every organ, but I 
 cannot conceive myself to exist apart from consciousness. 
 This or that mode may not be necessary, but in some mode it 
 is necessary that I be conscious in order to be. I, the ego, 
 therefore am essentially a conscious being, and my true char- 
 acter is that of an intelligence served by organs.^ 
 
 ^ux'7) which has been much discussed. It is : " The soul is the first entel- 
 echy of a physical, potentially living and organic body." This is cited by 
 Leibnitz as an illustrious example of obscurity. In ii. 2, Aristotle gives his 
 a posteriori definition of tpvxv: " The soul is the principle by which we live 
 and move, perceive (or feel, aiadavoixai) and understand." 
 
 1 Wundt says there are only two ways of conceiving the soul, either as a 
 substance or as an act. To the first conception belong all theories according 
 to which psychic facts are manifestations of a liypothetical substratum, a 
 substance material or immaterial. According to the latter the psychic is 
 pure actuality, immediately given in the manifestations of the mental life. 
 Hume, Kant, Fichte, and Hegel are representatives of the theory of actuality. 
 Psychology does not, like the physical sciences, attach itself to a metaphysi- 
 cal conception outside the fact of internal perception, or allow itself to be 
 embarrassed by an hypothesis of substance, not needed in the explanation. 
 Thus we have, despite its etymology, " psycliology without a soul." 
 
 ^ Throughout this treatise, the pronouns I, mine, me, are used generically, 
 meaning the ego as it is in every person, single in each, but common in 
 character. They should be taken to mean the reader, rather than the 
 writer. 
 
PEELIMINABY DEFINITION !S. 53 
 
 There is a further distinction between the ego and its con- 
 scious modes. I distinguish myself from my thoughts. They 
 are manifold and various ; I, on the contrary, am one and the 
 same. Their change is sometimes determined by me, some- 
 times by that different from me, and because of this changing 
 I can distinguish myself from my thoughts. But I am a 
 permanent being, an enduring subject, of whose existence 
 these thoughts are only conscious modes or phenomena.^ 
 
 § 52. Another thoroughgoing antithesis, very similar to 
 but not strictly identical with the preceding, is that between 
 subject and object. The subject (the mind, the ego) is that 
 in which the phenomena of consciousness inhere.^ The sub- 
 jective is that which belongs to or proceeds from or directly 
 relates to the subject. The object is that about which the 
 subject is conversant. The objective is that which belongs 
 to or proceeds from or directly relates to an object.^ 
 
 The subject knows ; the object is known. They are essen- 
 tial correlatives ; no subject, no object ; no object, no subject. 
 All consciousness involves a subject and an object, the one 
 determined, the other determining. The subject is conscious 
 only in being affected by an object ; an object is known only 
 as affecting the subject. The whole science of mind is little 
 
 1 ' ' Consciousness comes from the firmly founded relation of the mental 
 modifications, a founding which implies a something relatively in repose, 
 which transcends in force the simple modifications. This thing of relative 
 repose is the ego." — Kirchmann. 
 
 ' ' "Was ist doch tiberhaupt das Ich ? Warum sagen wir immer so leicht : 
 mein Geist, meine Seele, als wenn noch ein andrer Regent hoher iiber diesen 
 Regierenden in uns stjinde." — Tieck. 
 
 2 The word subject is pretty much the same as substance, but psychology 
 has usurped it to itself, so that currently in philosophical writings the con- 
 scious subject and the subject (unqualified) mean the same thing and are 
 equivalents of mind. 
 
 3 This distinction between subject, id in quo, and object, id circa quod, 
 corresponds pretty nearly with Aristotle's distinction between to. vfxiv, things 
 in us, and to, (pijaeL, things in nature. See Hamilton in Reid, note B, § 1, 6, 
 footnote (p. 806), for a discussion of the liistory and nature of the distinction. 
 
54 CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 else tlian an exposition of these opposites in tlieir mutual 
 relations.^ 
 
 When the object is immediate and a present non-ego, that is, 
 something external to the mind and yet within the sphere of 
 consciousness, it is called simply the object, in a specific sense. 
 But while the subject is always the ego, the immediate object 
 is not always a non-ego. Very often a present mental state 
 itself is objectified, or becomes an object of cognition. For 
 example, a mental image, as of the moon, being a mode of the 
 mind itself, is in that respect subjective ; as a thing known, 
 it is objective, an object of knowledge. Although really iden- 
 tical with the ego, the mind distinguishes it as a mode from 
 self. It projects, as it were, this subjective phenomenon from 
 itself, objectifies it, and views it as a non-ego. Hence it is 
 distinguished as a subjective object, or subject-object. 
 
 The mental image, the subject-object, immediately repre- 
 sents some remote object, as the moon itself. It is remote in 
 the sense of being now beyond the sphere of consciousness, 
 or not here and now present and consciously known. This 
 remote object is something either real, as the moon, or at least 
 logically possible, as a centaur. It is called by way of dis- 
 tinction, an objective object, or object-object. 
 
 In cognitive states the subjective is that pertaining to the 
 mind as observant or reflective ; the objective is that pertain- 
 ing to the thing on which the mind's attention is fixed. But 
 by its definition, the objective means not only what belongs to 
 or proceeds from an object, but also what directly relates to it. 
 
 1 Some illustrative examples may be heli)ful. The extended landscape 
 before nie is an object; my enjoyment of it is subjective. 1 liear a sweet- 
 toned bell ; the bell and its tones are objects or objective; the hearing and 
 the sweetness are subjective. To be convinced is subjective ; to convict is 
 objective. Certainty, as a state of mind, is subjective ; as a character of 
 proof, it is objective. Benevolence is subjective ; beneficence is objective. 
 That suicide is a crime is an objective fact ; that Cato tliinks otherwise is a 
 subjective fact. A code of morality that allows a man to fix his own standard 
 of ri^ht and wronj,' is subjective ; but tlie moral law is said to have objective 
 authurity, an authority belonging to itself, apart from the opinions of men. 
 
PRELIMINABY DEFINITIONS. 55 
 
 Hence those modes of mind which are immediately conversant 
 with an object, as perception, are called objective modes. 
 
 § 53. Power is the possibility of change. Possible mental 
 changes, known from experience, are classified as powers of 
 mind. Primarily we have two classes, the active powers or 
 faculties, and the passive powers or capacities. A faculty 
 is a power to change, a capacity is a power to be changed ; 
 the one is a power to impart, the other to receive. This dis- 
 tinction is of some value in marking relations, but it is not 
 essential, any power being active or passive according to the 
 relation in which it is viewed. An uncaused act of will is 
 an exception, being absolutely active. 
 
 Potential or virtual existence is that which at some future 
 time cau be ; actual existence is that which now is. Patti is 
 a singer when silent, not in actu, but in posse, or virtually ; 
 she can sing. Power, faculty, capacity, disposition, habit, are 
 expressions for potential or possible mental modes. Act, 
 operation, energy, exercise, denote actual modes. Affection 
 and passion denote a present suffering.^ 
 
 It is a very simple inference from observing what the mind 
 does, to conclude that it has a power or faculty of doing it. 
 But of the power when not in exercise, as of the substantial 
 mind itself, we are utterly unconscious. We are conscious 
 only of mental action and of reaction in suffering. It would 
 be better, therefore, if our psychological nomenclature were 
 so constructed as to confine our attention to the actual phe- 
 nomena of which we are conscious, and we should endeavor 
 to represent the facts as actual rather than potential. 
 
 1 FacuUas is the same asfacUitas, from facilis, facere, and means ability 
 todo. " Facilitates sunt, aut quihus facilins fit, aut sine qidhus aliquid coiifici 
 non potest.'' — Cicero, Invent., ii. 40. Faculties and capacities are natural 
 powers; disposition is a natural tendency. "Habit, ?|is, is discriminated 
 from disposition, Siddea-is, in this, that the latter is easily movable, the 
 former of longer duration and more difficult to be moved." — Aristotle, 
 Catagorice, viii. Habit is the effect of repetition or custom. "For use 
 almost can change the stamp of nature." —Hamlet. Its law may be stated 
 thus : Our powers acquire strength, facility, and a permanent tendency by 
 repetition of the same exercise. 
 
56 CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 CHAPTER II. 
 
 GENERALITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 § 54. The primary and fundamental truth of psychology, 
 that indeed from which all other truths arise, is the simple 
 judgment, I am conscious. This proposition is incapable of 
 proof, and needs none, for it is evidently true on the slightest 
 self-inspection. It is requisite, however, to know what is 
 meant by the concrete term conscious, and its abstract form 
 consciousness.^ 
 
 The complete generality of consciousness is the most impor- 
 tant point to be noted. Having examined the various mental 
 modes and abstracted their common qualit}^ we call that con- 
 sciousness. Every mental state, then, is a conscious state, or 
 consciousness is the name of a quality characteristic of every 
 mental state. As matter in all of its modes is extended, so 
 mind in all of its modes is conscious.^ 
 
 Actual consciousness is always concrete in some particular 
 
 1 Consciousness, conscientia, joint knowledge, from con, together, and 
 scire, to know. Etymologically the word is the same with conscience ; but 
 while the latter is narrowed in usage to an ethical sense, the former is greatly- 
 widened in meaning, and must not be bound by its etymology. The ancient 
 Greeks had no term for consciousness. The Greek Platonists and Aristote- 
 lians of the Christian era adoi)ted the term crvvai(r6r}ffLs, which properly denotes 
 the self-recognition of sense and feeling, and extended it to mean conscious- 
 ness in general. TertulHan (a.d. 100-220) was the tir.st to use conscientid in 
 its psychological sense, but prior to Descartes it only occasionally occurs. 
 
 - Consciousness is mental life. " It is," says Cousin, "the interior light 
 which illuminates everything that takes place in the soul ; it is the accompani- 
 ment of all our faculties, and is, so to speak, their echo." — /list, of Mod. 
 Phil., t. i, p. 247. It would be more accurate to say that whatever takes place 
 in the soul is self-luminous ; that consciousness does not attend, but per- 
 meates and informs all our faculties, and is, not their echo, but their voice. 
 
GENERALITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 57 
 
 state of mind, as perceiving, or remembering, or thinking, or 
 feeling. Each of these is a mode of consciousness, and there 
 is no unmodified consciousness. Its abstract, comprehensive, 
 generic relation is merely logical. 
 
 Because of its complete generality, consciousness cannot be 
 logically defined. There is no higher genus to which it can 
 be referred. It is the summum genus of the mental series. 
 We must be content, therefore, to have it merely indicated ; 
 e.g. when one is falling asleep, he is losing consciousness, etc. 
 
 § 55. Since we cannot refer consciousness to any higher 
 notion, let us look down its logical series, consider its content, 
 and thus render the notion distinct. The modes of conscious- 
 ness are knowing and feeling, desiring and willing. 
 
 When I am knowing a thing I know that I am knowing it, 
 or more properly, I am conscious of knowing it, or am con- 
 sciously knowing it. But these phrases convey the impres- 
 sion that the knowing a thing, and the consciousness of 
 knowing it, are distinguishable facts, which is not true. Also 
 they waste words ; for knowledge is merely and in itself a mode 
 of consciousness, and in saying simply I know, I say that I am 
 conscious. So also of feeling. Desiring and willing also are 
 severally and essentially conscious activities.^ 
 
 I may, however, accurately say I know that I feel, or that 
 I desire, or will. But when this is strictly correct, the feel- 
 ing, the desiring, or the willing has been objectified, has 
 become a subject-object of cognition. This is not feeling, or 
 desiring, or willing, but knowing. It is self-perception, a 
 mode of cognition. The state is commonly and faii'ly ex- 
 pressed thus : I am conscious of feeling, etc. Hence many 
 have been led to regard consciousness in general as a kind or 
 mode of knowledge, the knowledge of self, as distinguished 
 from the knowledge of an external object. Others, enlarg- 
 
 1 Said the schoolmen: '■'-Non sentimns, nisi sentiamus nos sentire ; non 
 intelliiiiruHs, nisi intplligamus nos intelligere.''^ But Aristotle had said: ovk 
 
58 CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 ing the view, hold consciousness to be the immediate knowl- 
 edo-e of any object. But both these subordinate consciousness 
 to knowledge, define it, and so deny to it the complete gener- 
 ality and supremacy that belongs to its nature.^ 
 
 Does the reality justify and require the more extended 
 meaning of the term consciousness ? Is each of the several 
 activities in itself a conscious activity ? Desires and volitions 
 are not commonly considered as in themselves conscious 
 activities, but that they are so is evident ; for, when cogni- 
 tion and feeling are constant, the intensity of consciousness 
 varies with the intensity of desire, or of volition. 
 
 1 Nearly all writers on psychology offer a definition of consciousness. 
 Stewart says: "It is the immediate knowledge which the mind has of its 
 sensations and thoughts, and, in general, of all its present operations." This 
 makes it a special faculty cognizant of self, which, indeed, was the doctrine 
 of Stewart, and of Reid, Royer-Collard, and Adolphe Gamier. Hamilton on 
 one page renounces any attempt to define it, and on the next says: "It 
 is the recognition by the mind or ego of its acts and affections. " — il/e to. , 
 pp. 132, 133. This is the mere conscia sibi. So Porter, Htim. Intel, §§ 67, 
 75. Elsewhere Hamilton has: "Consciousness and Immediate knowledge 
 are terms mutually convertible ; and if there be an immediate knowledge of 
 things external, there is consequently the consciousness of an outer world." 
 — Discussions, p. 57. This is better. But still better: "Consciousness is 
 the fundamental form, the generic condition of all the modes of mental 
 activity." — Id., p. 54. Cf. Meta., p. 126. Says Mill : " A feeling and a state 
 of consciousness are equivalent expressions. Feeling is a genus, of which 
 sensation, emotion, thought, and volition are subordinate species." — Zof/ic, 
 bk. i, ch. 1, §§ 3, 5. The extent here given to consciousness is just ; but not 
 that given to feeling. They should not be identified. 
 
 Wundt's view is not unlike that taken in the text. He holds that per- 
 ception, representation, idea, feeling, volition, form a continuity called con- 
 sciousness, of which only tautological definitions can be formulated. Its 
 fundamental characteristic, given in experience, is unity ; its condition, that 
 mental facts be united and co-ordinated according to law. The physiological 
 basis of the unity of consciousness is the continuity of the nervous system, 
 and this excludes the possibility of diverse kinds of consciousness. Con- 
 sidered in its psychological aspect, consciousness is a unification, an activity 
 that essentially unites and combines all mental phenomena as their common 
 characteristic. 
 
CONDITIONS OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 59 
 
 CHAPTER III. 
 
 CONDITIONS OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 § 56. The constitution of mind and brain being given as a 
 primary condition, we may discover still two other conditions 
 of consciousness, the first a condition of its existence, the 
 second of its continuance.^ 
 
 Opj)osition conditions the existence of consciousness. 
 Primarily an opposition between the ego and a non-ego is 
 requisite.^ This non-ego must be not merely different from 
 the ego, but also in direct opposition to it ; it must through 
 some channel of sense enter in upon and forcibly impress the 
 ego, otherwise consciousness can never be. The first awak- 
 ening, the first moment of consciousness is due doubtless to 
 the impression of a non-ego through the tactile or muscular 
 sense. Thereafter throughout life our various senses are 
 almost constantly in exercise. Their objects are continually 
 assailing the ego, and by virtue of such opposition there is 
 consciousness. 
 
 Moreover, opposition between coexisting states of mind 
 excites consciousness. Opposition occurs between sense- 
 perceptions, memories, imaginings, and thoughts, between 
 feelings of pleasure and pain, between conflicting desires, 
 between the alternatives of .choice, between an effort of the 
 will and the resistance it encounters. Thus within each of 
 the departments of mind, as well as by their contrasts with 
 
 1 A condition (conditio sine qua non) is something that must be in order 
 that something else may be. 
 
 2 The contrast between existence and non-existence is insufficient, for I 
 cannot be conscious of the non-existent. The non-ego opposed to self, de- 
 spite the negative form of the word, must be a positively existing thing. 
 
60 CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 each other, the conclition is fulfilled, and all are self-luminous 
 with consciousness. 
 
 § 57. Change conditions the continuance of consciousness. 
 We have spoken of coexisting states ; we are now to speak 
 of successive states. 
 
 It is a constitutional fact that consciousness awakened in 
 any one mode does not long continue. It directly begins to 
 subside, and in most cases subsides rapidly. The tactile 
 impression, for example, must be continually renewed in 
 order to be maintained. And this is true in all departments 
 of mind. An unvarying impression soon ceases to affect 
 us, and consciousness of it soon sinks to zero. But, on the 
 other hand, changes of impression maintain full conscious- 
 ness, and rapid changes excite intense consciousness. For 
 example, the irregularity of motion in a stage-coach, and the 
 clangor of a bell. 
 
 § 58. The condition change is subordinate to opposition, 
 for change is only the introduction of some new opposition, 
 bringing about successive states unlike, and therefore opposed 
 to each other. Hence we may comprise the two under a single 
 formula, the Law of Relativity : Every mode of consciousness 
 subsists by virtue of an opposition. This is a primary law 
 of mind. In respect of experience, it is universal. Every 
 experience is tAvofold. All feeling, all knowing, is double. 
 The doctrine that contraries are congenital, that they are pro- 
 duced together and necessarily coexist, is illustrated by the 
 multitude of correlative terms in every language, as straight 
 and crooked, knowledge and ignorance. Every afifirmation 
 is, therefore, also a negation, and the knowledge of tlie abso- 
 lute is impossible.^ 
 
 1 Omnis affinnalio est negatio. — Si-iJiosA.. On the law, with many ilhis- 
 trations, see Bain, Mind and Body, ch. 4 ; and Senses and Intellect, p. ?21. 
 The absolute is that which has no relation. 
 
CONDITIONS OF CONSCIOUSNESS. HI 
 
 § 59. In the awakening of any mode of consciousness, and 
 in each subsequent modification, we experience a shock of 
 difference. Both the opposition in coexisting states and the 
 change in successive states are attended by this feeling, itself 
 the beginning or the revival of the mode of consciousness. 
 Hence the most elementary, the most fundamental movement 
 of mind implies a discrimination, a comparison, a contrast, and 
 without this neither the most elaborate nor the most refined 
 and transient mood is possible. I could not know even my 
 own existence did not some other existence press in upon me, 
 and in the shock of difference make me conscious that I am. 
 
 By a familiar logical law no two things are absolutely dif- 
 ferent, they must in some respect be similar; nor are there any 
 two things absolutely similar, they must in some respect be 
 different. A consciousness of the difference implies a con- 
 sciousness of the similarity ; for by the law of relativity 
 itself there can be no consciousness of the one except by 
 virtue of an opposed consciousness of the other. They are 
 psychological correlatives.^ All knowledge, then, resolves 
 ultimately into a consciousness of similarity in the midst of 
 contrariety. A definition, for example, is a perfected expres- 
 sion of knowledge, and to define a thing is to state its agree- 
 ment with some things (^emts), and its disagreement with 
 others (^differentia'). 
 
 1 In Nic. Mh., vi, 1, Aristotle adopts the principle of similarity as the 
 basis of all knowledge. 
 
62 CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 CHAPTER IV. 
 
 LIMITS OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 § 60. Consciousness is subject to limitations. First, it is 
 only of the actual, not of the potential (§ 53). I know the 
 alphabet, I can sa}^ it. This is potential knowledge, but not 
 actual, not conscious knowledge, the thing not being just now 
 present in consciousness. I can suffer pain, but just now am 
 conscious of none. Conscious pain must be actual. I am not 
 at all conscious of any of my powers, except when in actual 
 exercise. I may be conscious of a belief in my power to do 
 this or that, but this confidence is not a consciousness of the 
 ability, of the faculty itself. 
 
 § 61. Secondly, consciousness is only of the present. I can- 
 not be conscious of the past, for it has ceased to be, or of the 
 future, for as yet it is not. I cannot be conscious of what 
 does not exist. Nor can I be conscious of what is absent, for 
 virtually it is non-existent. I am conscious only of what is 
 present in time and space, of what is now and here. 
 
 Hence what is consciously known is immediately and not 
 mediately known, for that which is now and here does not 
 need, does not admit, a medium, but is Avithin the sphere of 
 consciousness. Memory, for example, is a conscious act, 
 a mode of consciousness. In it my present mental image of 
 a past event is immediately, consciously known, for it is now 
 and here witliin consciousness ; but the past event itself is not 
 consciously, but mediately, known through the mental image. 
 A belief concerning a past event is often called a conscious- 
 ness of it ; for example, I am conscious of having done wrong. 
 Obviously this is mere belief. I am conscious of the convie- 
 
LIMITS OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 63 
 
 tion, but not of the wrong-doing itself, for it has passed 
 away. 
 
 § 62. A third limitation is that consciousness is only of the 
 positive, not of the negative. Though I cannot be conscious 
 of an absent thing, may I not be conscious of the absence 
 of a thing? We say, I am conscious of silence, i.e. of the 
 absence of sound, a pure negative. But this means only that 
 I am not conscious of sound. A consciousness of ignorance 
 means only an unconsciousness of knowledge. When a thing 
 is absent from consciousness, we speak of its absence as if 
 that were itself a thing. But it is a nothing, a void, a mere 
 negation of the thing, and so there is merely unconsciousness 
 of it. It were absurd to say, I am conscious of unconscious- 
 ness. 
 
 § 63. Certain other conceivable limitations are questioned. 
 First. Are we conscious always? Since consciousness varies 
 in intensity, does it not sometimes sink to zero ? 
 
 Though we often speak of being wholly unconscious, it 
 cannot be proved that there is ever such a state. We can- 
 not observe directly the consciousness of another, much less 
 an unconsciousness. When his external senses are com- 
 pletely torpid, and all communication thereby closed, how 
 can we judge of his inner state ? That we can find no 
 external signs of consciousness does not prove unconscious- 
 ness. 
 
 Nor can one testify to his own unconsciousness. On arous- 
 ing from complete torpor, I can say only that I remember 
 nothing. That there seems no interval of time between 
 before and after is merely no memory. Having no memory 
 of consciousness does not prove unconsciousness. 
 
 The supposition that consciousness, in its varying intensity, 
 may sometimes reach zero, is fairly balanced by the supposi- 
 tion that there may be a minimum for consciousness short 
 of zero. 
 
G4 CONSCIOUSJ\'J£Sti. 
 
 Therefore it cannot be said that there is ever a dreamless 
 sleep. But the fact that the mind is often awake and dream- 
 ing while the senses are asleep is established ; whereas that 
 it sometimes sleeps along with them is unproved. Hence it 
 is admissible to suppose that it is always awake, is always 
 conscious. This justifies the definition of mind as conscious 
 substance, and has been the common opinion of psychologists.^ 
 
 § 64. Second. Are we conscious of more than one thing 
 at a time ? A slight consideration will show that we are 
 usually conscious of many things simultaneously. Cognition, 
 feeling, desire, and volition are distinct conscious activities, 
 and all are constantly in exercise. My cognitive conscious- 
 ness is never exclusively occupied with a single object. 
 Many colors, many sounds, are simultaneously perceived. 
 All the senses may be at once in action, and each on a vari- 
 ety of objects. Memory is never of one thing alone, but of 
 many together, and the same is true of thouglits. Yet I 
 perceive, remember, and think, all in the same instant. 
 
 Along with these cognitions are many sensations and emo- 
 tions. Surprise, mirth, admiration, vexation, belief, are all 
 compatible in consciousness. Even opposites may coexist. 
 I may, while hoping for one thing, despair of another ; while 
 courageously meeting a danger, dread its possible conse- 
 quences. There is often a conflict of emotions, and also of 
 desires, not a duel, but a battle between hosts. 
 
 Whoever will examine any ordinary state of his mind 
 must soon discover that he is conscious, not of one, nor of a 
 few, but of a multitude of things at once. It should be 
 
 1 Plato affirms the continuous energy of intellect. Aristotle is undecided. 
 Cicero says : ^'■Nunqnam animus agitatione et niotu vacuus potest esse." — 
 De Div. ii, 02. So also Auj;ustinc. Descartes made thought the very essence 
 of mind, which therefore always thinks. Locke maintained the contrary. — 
 Essay, bk. ii, ch. 1. Leibnitz opposed Locke's views, showing them incon- 
 clusive, but did not himself affirm. — None. Ess., lib. ii, ch. 1. Kant affirms. 
 — A nthropoUxjip, §§ oO, o(5. Hamilton affirms with some hesitation. — Mcta., 
 Lee. 17. Joui'froy affirms decidedly. — Mchinijes, p. 290 sq. 
 
LIMITS OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 65 
 
 remarked, however, that of this multitude very few are in 
 clear consciousness ; the great majority, though distinguisha- 
 ble, are indistinct, actually but only obscurely present. ^ It 
 is the function of attention to bring an object already present 
 in cognitive consciousness, though obscure and confused with 
 others, out into clear and distinct consciousness. It operates 
 according to the following law of limitation : The extension 
 of our knowledge is in inverse ratio to its intension. That is 
 to say, the more intently we consider an object, the fewer or 
 less clear will be the other objects present in consciousness ; 
 and, on the other hand, the greater the number of objects to 
 which our consciousness is simultaneously extended, the 
 smaller is the intensity with Avhich it is able to consider any 
 one. When consciousness takes hold on and attends to one 
 object in disregard of others, then the intensity of conscious- 
 ness relatively to it is acquired at the expense of the vivid- 
 ness of the other objects, they becoming confused, obscure, 
 and many perhaps passing entirely out of consciousness. 
 Thus the intension limits the extension. 
 
 § 65. Third. Are we conscious of all mental activities ? 
 Are there not certain mental activities of which we are un- 
 conscious ? 
 
 Quite a number of facts in the history of mental experi- 
 ence are hardly explicable upon commonly admitted psycho- 
 logical principles. To explain them, an hypothesis of 
 unconscious activities has been proposed. It supposes that 
 simultaneously with our conscious activities there is a con- 
 tinuous series of activities out of consciousness, either of an 
 intensity too low to excite a consciousness of them, or of a 
 
 1 Says Leibnitz : "We must observe that we think of a great many things 
 at once, but take heed only of those thoughts that are the more prominent." 
 — Nouv. Ess., lib. ii, ch. 1. Cardaillac recognized the importance to psychol- 
 ogy of this doctrine. See his Etudes Element, de Philos., t. ii, ch. 5. The 
 scholastics earnestly discussed the question : " Possetne intellectus noster 
 plura siinul mtelligere.'' The widely comprehensive area of consciousness 
 is now generally admitted. 
 
66 CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 nature that excludes them from consciousness. It supposes 
 that these latent or sub-conscious activities are important fac- 
 tors of conscious life, so that states of which we are conscious 
 often originate in and are determined by activities of which 
 we are unconscious. The hypothesis is not new, but has 
 grown into new favor of late, and been expanded into a 
 philosophy of the unconscious.^ 
 
 But sub-conscious activities can only be inferred to exist 
 as causes of unexplained effects, those causes being otherwise 
 utterly unknown. Now, logical law condemns an hyj)othesis 
 of a cause which is not vera causa (a cause otherwise known 
 to be), especially in the absence of proof that no other 
 hypothesis can account for the facts. The present hypoth- 
 esis fails on both points, and therefore stands condemned. ^ 
 
 Further investigation may perhaps refer the unexplained 
 facts to known causes. This has been the case in several 
 
 1 Leibnitz held the doctrine, but not clearly. Hamilton in one place says : 
 "The rise or awakening of a mental modification is also the rise or awak- 
 ening of consciousness." — Meta., p. 242. Nevertheless, with characteristic 
 inconsistency, he explicates Leibnitz's view, and founds his doctrine of 
 memory upon it. His " demonstration " (Meta., p. 243 sq.) begs the ques- 
 tion by assuming that a cause too feeble to awaken consciousness (e.g. a ray 
 of light) excites an activity, which therefore is out of consciousness. In an- 
 other view it is Fallacia divisionis. Thus: Since the two halves of a mini- 
 mum visibile taken together cause activity, therefore each taken separately 
 Causes activity. In his Examination of Sir William Hamilton'' s Philosophy, 
 ch. 8, Mill severely criticises these views. 
 
 The hypothesis is still in vogue, and has been worked up by Hartmann into 
 a Philosophij of (he Unconscioits. Among many others, AVundt seems to 
 hold it. He says : " A full-grown science tends to unity. And observation 
 conducts to unity in psychology. But the agent of this unity is outside of 
 consciousness, which knows only the results done in the unknown laboratory 
 beneath it. Suddenly a new thought springs into being. We know no 
 whence it comes, for the conditions which have produced it have already 
 disappeared. Ultimate analysis of psychical processes shows that the uncon- 
 scious is the theatre of the most important mental phenomena. The con- 
 scious is always conditioned on the unconscious." — P/i^s. Pstjc, Int., p. 8. 
 If, as is probable, by " the agent of this unity " he means the cortex of the 
 brain, then we waive objection. 
 
 ■^ Sec Mill's Lof/ir, bk. iii, ch. 14, § 4. 
 
LIMITS OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 67 
 
 instances. More especially we observe that our acquired dex- 
 terities and liabits which have been referred to unconscious 
 mental action, are now fully explained phj^sically by reflex 
 action (§§ 36, 37). Moreover, the spontaneous ordering of 
 thoug'lits may fairly be referred to unconscious cerebration 
 (§ 41), which reference to.another hypothetical cause, at least 
 transfers the question to physiology. Again, the phenomena 
 of spontaneous memory may fairly be referred to obscure 
 consciousness (§ 64). When we are startled by some un- 
 sought remembrance, it is sufficiently explained as the result 
 of interaction in obscure consciousness, and so does not 
 require the hypothesis of unconscious activities. 
 
 When we observe that the variations of consciousness and 
 activity are concomitant, intense consciousness attending 
 high activity, and feeble consciousness attending low activity, 
 in dii'cct proportion throughout, we rightly conclude that, if 
 consciousness and activity are to be regarded as distinct facts, 
 then they are related either as cause and effect, or as the 
 effects of a common cause. If the former, then the presump- 
 tion is that the cessation of either is attended by the cessa- 
 tion of the other. If the latter, then the presumption is that 
 a cause too feeble to arouse consciousness is too feeble to 
 arouse activity. It follows that activity and consciousness 
 come into existence together, and cease together, and there 
 are no sub-conscious activities. 
 
 But why regard activity and consciousness as distinct 
 facts? Is it not better to identify them? Let us say that 
 all consciousness is mental activity, and that all mental 
 activity is conscious activity. Thus it is opposed to physical 
 activity, to unconscious material energy. In this vicAV, the 
 phrase " unconscioi,:^s mental activities " is self-contradictory 
 and absurd. 
 
68 CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 CHAPTER V. 
 
 FACTS OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 § 66. The conditions being fulfilled, what, within the 
 limits indicated, is given by consciousness? What are facts 
 of consciousness ? Whatever I immediately know, whatever 
 I feel, or desire, or will respecting myself, or respecting an 
 object present to consciousness, is a fact of consciousness. 
 My own existence in some distinct mode, or in other words, 
 the existence of my present mental state, is a general fact of 
 consciousness. That I see, that I remember, that in thinking 
 I abstract and generalize, that I feel pain, that I desire hap- 
 piness, and make efforts to attain it, these, as present mental 
 modes, are special facts of consciousness. In perception, the 
 existence of the object also is given as a fact; I not only 
 consciously know, but also am conscious of the thing known. 
 In short, whenever I can trul}^ say, I am conscious of this or 
 that, the fact, in so far, is a fact of consciousness. ^ 
 
 The phrase, I am conscious of this or that, is often loosely 
 used of matter not trul}^ within consciousness. Should one 
 say, I am conscious of the warmth of the sunshine, we may 
 grant him conscious of warmth, but that it is of the sunshine 
 is an inference, and is not given or affirmed by consciousness. 
 To reach a sound basis for our speculations, we must analyze 
 the mental content, and abstracting from all derived matter, 
 make clear the fact or facts of conscious] * ss. 
 
 1 " Whenever, in our analysis of the intellectual ])henomena, we arrive at 
 an element which we cannot reduce to a generalization from experience, but 
 ■which lies at the root of all experience, and which we cannot, therefore, re- 
 solve into any higher principle, this we properly call a fact of consciousness." 
 — Hamilton, il/efa., p. 187. 
 
FACTS OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 69 
 
 § 67. A fact of consciousness, since it lies at the beginning 
 of a mental combination, is primary ; being incapable of analy- 
 sis into constituent facts, it is simple ; being in itself not sus- 
 ceptible of explanation, it is ultimate ; and being merely given 
 as an existing distinct fact, it is original and not derived.^ 
 Moreover, since the data of consciousness constitute the 
 ground of proof of all other facts, they themselves are incap- 
 able of proof. But they do not need any. They have the 
 light of truth in themselves. They are self-evident. No 
 appeal can weaken or strengthen them. They are firmly 
 established by their self-evidence, and by that alone. ^ 
 
 § 68. A fact of consciousness is merely given, but it is, as 
 it were, forcibly given. It cannot be refused, its self-evidence 
 cannot be disregarded, it must be accepted. In my conscious- 
 ness that a thing exists, it is implied that I am constrained 
 to accept this existence as real. For example, I hear a loud 
 continuous sound, let us say a locomotive whistle. Of the 
 sound, I am truly conscious. I may question its direction, 
 its cause, and many other things respecting it, but its ex- 
 istence and my sense-perception of it, I cannot doubt for 
 an instant. I cannot contradict this affirmation of conscious- 
 ness. The acceptance of it is enforced upon me ; and this 
 is implied in saying that I am conscious of the sound. 
 
 This constraint attends consciousness only. The existence 
 
 1 Consciousness merely reveals that it is, not how or why it is. For if 
 the how or why were given, then it would be a derived or secondary, and not 
 an original and primary datum. An inference as to its exciting cause or 
 occasion is a rational but not a conscious explanation. 
 
 It is simple as a fact, is the last fact attainable by analysis. We shall 
 hereafter find that every fact of consciousness is capable of resolution into 
 essential elements, empirical and pure. But since these elements can have 
 no separate existence in consciousness except as mere logical abstractions, 
 they are not properly facts of consciousness, and so we refuse them that title. 
 
 2 Each one must discern the facts for himself in the depths of his own 
 consciousness. We can only help him to find them. The process of disclos- 
 ing them may involve proof ; but once disclosed, no proof can be offered in 
 support of them. 
 
70 CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 of a thing not within consciousness is not assertive, but prob- 
 lematical. How can I affirm it to be ? I may believe very 
 strongly that it is, as I believe the sun to be in the sky. I 
 may accumulate logical proof. I may remember that it 
 was within consciousness a moment ago. But now that it 
 is not within consciousness, it may possibly or conceivably 
 have ceased to be. Its existence, not being a fact of con- 
 sciousness, is questionable. 
 
 § 69. The consciousness of reality involves a feeling of 
 certainty. When I am conscious of the existence of a thing 
 I feel certain of it. The certainty is pure, strict, positive, 
 absolute. In the consciousness that I am, for instance, there 
 is, together with the cognition of my existence, a certainty 
 of the fact, a faith in it, that has no limit. Indeed, to pro- 
 fess a doubt of a fact of consciousness is the -highest form of 
 self-contradiction. Should one say, I doubt my own exists 
 ence, we ask him, who doubts ? There can be no delusion or 
 illusion in what is given by consciousness. Its facts stand 
 high above the reach of skepticism.^ 
 
 It is very important to discriminate clearly the facts of 
 consciousness from other facts. Their strict certainty may 
 serve as a criterion. If it be possible in any manner or 
 measure to doubt a fact without self-contradiction, then it 
 falls short of certainty, and is not immediatel}', consciously, 
 given, but is inferred, mediate, and represented. But if even 
 the form of doubt be impossible, then the feeling reaches 
 strict certainty, the fact is a fact of consciousness, is immedi- 
 ately, consciously given, is an intuition, a presentation. 
 
 One limitation is needful. A demonstration, proceeding 
 logically from intuitive principles, carries their certainty 
 
 1 Says Leibnitz : " There may be intelligible reason for error in our medi- 
 ate and external perceptions ; but if our immediate, internal experience could 
 possibly deceive us, there could no longer be for us any truth of fact (rente 
 de fait), nay, nor any truth of reason (rerite de raisuu).'''' — Nonv. Ess., lib. 
 ii, ch. 27, § 13. The untenable notion that possibly my conciousness may in 
 some respect deceive me, is noticed in a subsequent chapter. 
 
FACTS OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 71 
 
 along with it, yet its result is not a fact of consciousness ; 
 for it is not original, but derived. Hence tlie criterion reads 
 thus : A fact of consciousness is certain and original. 
 
 § 70. The facts of consciousness constitute the subject- 
 matter of psychology. Having ascertained them, and 
 accepted them without retrenchment, distortion, or addition, 
 we proceed to generalize and classify them, and to formulate 
 accordingly the ultimate laws of mind. When this is 
 thoroughly done, we have a true science of mind.^ 
 
 But their importance is more manifest when we consider 
 that they alone are given to man to know : any further truth 
 he must win by thinking on and from them. They alone, 
 with what may be strictly demonstrated from them, are 
 certain; all other truth is, in a higher or lower degree, 
 merely probable. They are the ultimate ground, not only of 
 all the sciences, but of all knowledge whatsoever. Their 
 study, then, is of the highest dignity. We are searching the 
 oi'iginal and immovable grounds of all truth, of all faith. 
 Science in its perfection is knowledge of myself, of the world, 
 and of God. This is its beginning, its mean, and its end. 
 The great problem is : Given self, to find God. 
 
 1 Hamilton says : " Psychology is only a developed consciousness ; that is, 
 a scientific evolution of the facts of which consciousness is at once the guar- 
 antee and revelation, a systematic evolution of the contents of consciousness 
 through the instrumentality .of consciousness." — Discussions, p. 91. 
 
 J. S. Mill says : " All theories of the human mind profess to he interpre- 
 tations of consciousness ; the conclusions of all of them are supposed to rest 
 on that ultimate evidence, either immediately or remotely. What conscious- 
 ness directly reveals, together v?ith what can be legitimately inferred from 
 its revelations, composes, by universal admission, all that we know of the 
 mind, or indeed of any other thing. When we know what any philosopher 
 considers to be revealed in consciousness, we have a key to the entire char- 
 acter of his metaphysical system." — Ex. of Hamilton's Philos., oh. 8. 
 
7 2 CONSCIO USNESS. 
 
 CHAPTER VI. 
 
 MODES OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 § 71. Consciousness is the universal and fundamental phe- 
 nomenon of mind, all whose modes are conscious modes. 
 These modes are first divided into those that are modes of 
 consciousness and nothing more, and those that are con- 
 sciousness and something more. This something more is an 
 endeavor, and hence the modes differentiated by it are called 
 conations.^ In modes that are consciousness merely, we are 
 knowing and feeling ; in conation we are consciously wanting 
 and doing. This indicates a subdivision into subjective and 
 objective modes. The objective mode of consciousness is 
 cognition or knowledge ; its subjective mode is feeling or 
 sensibility. The subjective mode of conation is desire ; its 
 objective mode is volition. These generic relations are 
 conveniently exhibited in the following : — 
 
 SCHEME OF THE GENERIC POWERS. 
 
 Consciousness. 
 
 , A . 
 
 (Feeling. Cognition. "» 
 
 )■ Objective. 
 Desire. Volition, j 
 
 Conation. 
 
 Consciousness, in its most general sense, we have called 
 the fundamental phenomenon. Consciousneas in the nar- 
 rower sense and conation may be called the primary powers. 
 
 ^ Conation (conari, ronntu!<) means an efforl, a nisus, a strivinp, an en- 
 deavor, and must be taken hero to include the impulse and the determmation 
 or choice that gives direction to the effort. 
 
MODES OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 73 
 
 Coo-nition and feelin^, desire and volition, we shall call the 
 generic powers ; their subdivisions, the specific powers.^ 
 
 Coo-nition and feeling cannot exist apart, nor, if taken 
 strictly, can desire and volition. Moreover, conations are 
 conditioned on the modes of consciousness, that is, without 
 a present cognition and feeling, a conation cannot be. 
 Hence the subjacent position of conation in the scheme .^ 
 
 § 72. Cognition is consciousness of an object. To cognize 
 is to know. Obviously we cannot know without knowing 
 something, and that something is the object. The specific 
 powers of cognition are determined by specific differences in 
 the objects known. Knowledge is accordingly of two kinds, 
 immediate or intuitive or presentative, and mediate or 
 representative. 
 
 The immediate cognition of a non-ego or object proper, is 
 perception ; the immediate cognition of a subject-object is self- 
 perception. These are specific presentative powers. They 
 are both empirical intuitions. But actual cognition involves 
 also a pure or non-empirical element, not cognized by sense, 
 but by intellect, and tliis immediate knowledge is attributed 
 
 1 The Peripatetic division is into the gnostic and oretic powers, famltates 
 cognoscendi et appetendi, which survives in the speculative and active powers, 
 or the understanding and will. It confuses desire and will, and omits feeling. 
 Kant {Critique of Judgment) made feeling co-ordinate, thus : thought, feeling, 
 striving, Denk, Gefiihl, Bestrebungsverm'ogen, the latter including desire and 
 will. This trichotomy, opposed in Germany but adopted in France, prevails 
 in England and with us under the modified form: intellect, sensibilities 
 (including desire), and will. Hamilton followed Kant, thus: cognition, feel- 
 ing, conation. We have adopted a dichotomous division and subdivision as 
 more strictly logical, and more in accord with the natural relations and 
 mutual dependence of the phenomena. 
 
 2 It may be permitted to note that this distribution is most ancient. 
 " When the woman saw that the tree was good for food [cognition, a percep- 
 tion and a judgmenf], and that it was pleasant to the eyes [feeling, a sensa- 
 tion and a sentiment'], and a tree to be desired to make one wise [desire or 
 velleity, xcith final causeT], she took thereof and did eat [volition, including 
 choice, intention, and effort with fruitiony — Gen. 3 : 6. 
 
74 CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 to a third special presentative faculty called pure intuition or 
 reason. 
 
 A remote object, one beyond the sphere of consciousness, 
 can be known only mediately, that is, through some repre- 
 sentative. The specific powers thus cognizing a remote 
 object, an object-object, are called the representative powers, 
 and their exercise, representation. They are nmnori/, imagi- 
 nation, and thought. 
 
 § 73. Feeling or sensibility, in the most general view, is 
 consciousness of self, of the subject. In every state of con- 
 sciousness there is essentially an objective and a subjective 
 element ; there is both a consciousness of an object as distin- 
 guished from self, a cognition, and a consciousness of self as 
 distinguished from an object, a feeling. These are psycho- 
 logical correlatives, existing only as they coexist ; they con- 
 dition and complement each other; they are the poles of 
 consciousness. • Hence, as cognitions are modes of objective 
 consciousness, so feelings are modes of subjective conscious- 
 ness ; and consciousness is distributed as the cognitive con- 
 sciousness and the sensitive consciousness.^ Relatively to 
 each other, the feelings fall into two classes, states of pleasure 
 and pain. Relatively to the coexistent cognitions, there are 
 three classes, — sensation, correlative to perception, emotion 
 and sentiment, correlative to intellect. 
 
 § 74. Desire is the subjective element in conation, correla- 
 tive to volition, the objective element. These complement 
 and condition each other. As feeling has the modes pleasure 
 and pain, so desire has the similar modes, desire proper and 
 aversion. In general we have a desire for what gives pleas- 
 ure, and an aversion for what gives pain. Desires are also 
 
 1 A fuller justification of this view will be given when we come to treat 
 specifically of the feelings, Part IV. The essential and important distinction 
 between feeling and desire, so commonly disregarded, will also be subse- 
 i|ucntly treated, Tart V. 
 
MODES OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 75 
 
 divided into the physical, as the appetites, which correspond 
 to sensations, and the psychical, as the affections, which cor- 
 respond to sentiments. 
 
 § 75. Volition or will, the objective mode of conation, has 
 for its direct, immediate object an action. There are at least 
 two elements : first, choice, or the preference given to one 
 action over another; and, second, the effo7't to perform that 
 action. The immediate issue of choice is intention ; the 
 immediate issue of effort is attention. The latter determines 
 both mental and muscular action. 
 
 § 76. The foregoing analysis of the mental powers, in their 
 co-ordination and subordination, gives rise to the follow- 
 ing:— 
 
 SCHEME OF THE SPECIFIC POWEKS. 
 
 I. Consciousness. 
 
 1. Objective consciousness, or Cognition. 
 
 A. Presentation, or Intuition. 
 
 (1) Perception. I g^^^^^^ 
 
 (2) Self -perception. J 
 
 (3) Pure Intuition. 
 
 B. Representation. 
 
 (4) Memory. J> Intellect. 
 
 (5) Imagination. 
 
 (6) Thought. 
 
 2. Subjective consciousness, or Feeling. 
 
 (1) Sensation. 
 
 (2) Emotion. 
 
 (3) Sentiment. 
 II. Conation. 
 
 1. Subjective conation, or Desire. 
 
 (1) Physical. 
 
 (2) Psychical. 
 
 2. Objective conation,' or Volition. 
 
 (1) Choice. 
 
 (2) Effort. 
 
 § 77. A mind is a unit. In the various divisions of its 
 powers we are apt to see corresponding parts of mind ; in its 
 
76 CONSCIOUSNESS. 
 
 various acts, various actors ; in its various functions, various 
 organs. But the mind, unlike the body, has no parts, has no 
 organs. It is conscious of differences in its modes of activity, 
 and these it distinguishes by names, and classifies. But the 
 absolute one that knows is the same that feels, is the same 
 that strives. So one and the same particle of matter attracts 
 all others, elects some, emits light and heat, and exerts and 
 is subject to electrical influences. A particle of matter may 
 fairly be defined as an origin of forces. These forces are 
 manifest in their effects, in objective phenomena. Perhaps 
 physical force is one, and the variety in phenomena due to 
 the various conditions under which it acts. It may help our 
 conception of the unity of mind to consider that in like man- 
 ner the conscious subject is merely a source of powers mani- 
 fest in their effects, in subjective phenomena, and that these 
 powers are modifications of one, of consciousness. 
 
 § 78. It is important to observe also that the generic powers 
 of mind are always simultaneously in exercise. Cognition, 
 feeling, desire, and will may be discerned in every actual state 
 of this unit. Each state is a single instantaneous activity capa- 
 ble of only a logical resolution into conceivable components 
 which never in any case exist singly and apart. Successive 
 states exhibit a varying predominance of one element over 
 another, and but for this the analysis would perhaps be imprac- 
 ticable. Moreover, the specific powers likewise act simulta- 
 neously, yet with varying intensity. At one and the same 
 instant the conscious subject may be perceiving, remembering, 
 imagining, thinking, experiencing sensations and emotions, 
 desiring, choosing, striving. This should not tax our credulity 
 more than the familiar fact that a single particle of matter 
 constantly and simultaneously exerts a great variety of widely 
 distinct j^hysical forces. 
 
PART SECOND. 
 IMMEDIATE KNO^A^^LEDGE. 
 
 CHAPTER I. 
 
 COGNITION. 
 
 § 79. A consideration of cognition in its general aspect is 
 prerequisite to the specific treatment of immediate knowl- 
 edge. 
 
 A state of consciousness contemplated on its objective side, 
 that is, as related to an object, is called a cognition.' Cogni- 
 tion is consciousness of an object. This is knowledge. To 
 cognize is to know.^ 
 
 All forms of cognition are merely modes of the objective 
 consciousness. We cannot specifically discriminate percep- 
 tion, or memory, or imagination, or thought, from knowing, 
 for these are only modes of knowing. Every act of intelli- 
 gence is thus a modified consciousness, and the cognitive con- 
 sciousness has no existence whatever except in one or another 
 of these special modes.^ The mode which it shall assume is 
 determined by the object known. If the object be present 
 
 1 "Cognition, Lat. cognitio, a finding out; co- (for con, wliicli for cmn, 
 togetlier) and gnoscere, to know." — Skeat. Cf. yuuxris, from yvQvaL. 
 
 2 For illustration : Goethe found every organic member of a plant to be 
 a modified generic leaf. The fruit, the flower and its parts, the plant as a 
 whole, are each metamorphosed leaves. And, indeed, the leaf proper is 
 only a nearer approximation in form to the generic typical leaf. So each of 
 the intellectual states is a modification of one generic form, which apart 
 from these has only a logical existence. 
 
 77 
 
78 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 now and here, within the sphere of consciousness, and there- 
 fore immediately known, then we have a presentation, an 
 intuition or immediate knowledge. If the object be remote 
 ill time or space, beyond the sphere of consciousness, and 
 therefore known only through some medium, then we have a 
 representation or mediate knowledge. Specifically, a present 
 color, sound, or odor determines the mode to be perception; 
 a representation of some past experience, memory ; and so on. 
 The modes thus determined are presently to be discussed. 
 
 § 80. It has already been pointed out that a state of con- 
 sciousness is produced by a shock of difference, and that a 
 cognition of difference involves discrimination and comparison 
 (§ 59). This becomes quite evident when we consider that 
 all knowledge is a relation between a subject knowing and an 
 object known, as expressed in the general formula : I know it. 
 Now it is impossible for this relation to subsist, unless there 
 be a contrast, and the subject so constituted as to discrimi- 
 nate. For I know only in so far as I know something, and I 
 know that something only in so far as I distinguish it from 
 what it is not. This discrimination implies a comparison, and 
 it follows that comparison occurs in every act of knowledge, 
 even the simplest.^ 
 
 Comparison implies analysis and synthesis. In so far as 
 objects are found dissimilar they are set apart ; this is analy- 
 sis. In so far as they are found similar they are united ; this 
 is synthesis. Hence the issue of comparison is judgment, for 
 judgment is the conscious act wherein one thing is atlirmed 
 or denied of another, a declaration of similarity or difference. 
 Judging is commonly considered a compound or derivative 
 operation, but here it appears that the simplest act of intelli- 
 
 ^ The first experience, the first moment of consciousness, is doubtless a dis- 
 covery of tlie existence of two things, ego and a non-ego, by virtue of their 
 opposition, which implies comparison. And so throughout cognition. Our 
 originally simple and our factitiously complex, our abstract and our general- 
 ized notions, all are acts and results of comparison in its various applications 
 and degrees. 
 
COGNITION. 79 
 
 gence implies a judgment, and that so far from being a pro- 
 cess only subsequent to the acquisition of knowledge, it is 
 the very essence of every cognitive act.^ 
 
 We should, however, distinguish between primary or psy- 
 chological judgments and inferences, the latter being secon- 
 dary and logical. A psychological judgment, such as, I am, 
 is certain and original, and so a fact of consciousness. A 
 logical judgment or inference, such as, I shall be, is uncertain 
 and derived. The one cannot be proved, but is self-evident ; 
 to obtain the other a logical process is requisite, and so it is 
 an inference. Psychological judgments are the condition and 
 ground of all others ; they are the foundation of knowledge. 
 
 § 81. Cognition is a condition of all other mental activities. 
 I cannot feel unless there be some known object to determine 
 in me the kind and degree of feeling. I cannot desire, unless 
 there be some known object toward which my longing tends. 
 I cannot choose, unless there be alternative objects of cogni- 
 tion desired. I cannot make a voluntary effort, unless I form 
 prospectively an image of the action. Hence I am essentially 
 an intelligent being. Since cognition conditions the other 
 generic powers, it is proper to treat of it first. 
 
 § 82. Attention is an intensity of cognition. We have 
 defined cognition to be consciousness of an object. We now 
 define attention to be consciousness concentrated on an ob- 
 ject ; or a concentration of the cognitive consciousness. This 
 intensified, concentrated consciousness is, of course, always 
 in some special mode, in some special faculty of cognition, as 
 perception, memory, thought.^ 
 
 1 In the psychology of Lotze and of Wundt, the act of comparison under 
 the eye of attention, i.e. the discernment of tlie relation between objects, has 
 received the title apperception, a term borrowed from Leibnitz. It has value 
 as emphasizing an act common to all cognitive states, and thus unifying their 
 exercise. 
 
 2 The etymology of the word attention {ad-tendere, to stretch towards) in- 
 dicates intensity, a cognate word. Cf. the words lust, list, listen, listless, 
 
80 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 Some psychologists have treated attention as a special 
 faculty. But attention is coextensive with the cognitive con- 
 sciousness ; for it requires a known object, and any object 
 that can be known may, through its special faculty, become 
 an object of attention. Cognition and attention cannot there- 
 fore be distinguished as differing in kind. The difference is 
 merely one of degree.^ 
 
 But may not consciousness be concentrated in the subject ? 
 Certainly there is an intense self-consciousness. All feelings 
 vary in intensity, as also do desires. Yet, since there is no 
 object, we never speak of them as attentive, but rather as 
 passionate. Attention knows an object, and hence the limi- 
 tation to cognition. 
 
 § 83. Attention operates according to the following Law 
 of Limitation : The extension of cognition at any instant is 
 in inverse ratio to its intension. That is to say, the more 
 intently I consider an object, the fewer or less clear will be 
 the other objects in consciousness ; and, on the other hand, 
 the greater the number of objects to which consciousness is 
 simultaneously extended, the smaller is the intensity with 
 which it is able to consider any one.^ I am usually conscious 
 of many things at once (§ 64). Now when consciousness is 
 concentrated on some one of these, to the disregard of others, 
 
 from the Anglo-Saxon lustan, to incline or lean towards. Their secondary 
 meaning was suggested, possibly, by the natural attitude of the body corre- 
 sponding to the state of mind. 
 
 1 In recent psychology as well as in the earlier, there is a strong disposi- 
 tion to treat attention as a special and dominant faculty. See Eibot, Studies 
 in Attention. But, beside what is said above, this violates a fundamental 
 law of philosophizing, called Occam's Law of Parcimony : " Entia non sunt 
 muItipUcanda praiter necessitatem.'''' A plurality of principles is not to be 
 assumed when the phenomena can be explained by one. " Frustra fit per 
 plura quod fieri potest per pauciora." See Hamilton, Aleta., p. 225, and 
 p. 321 ; also in lieid, note A (p. T-'Sl, at foot); but especially Grote, Aristotle, 
 vol. ii, p. 25, note. Logical absurdity is a violation of the Law of Contradic- 
 tion. Philosophical absurdity is a violation of the Law of Parcimony. 
 
 2 Thus the old adage: ^^ Phirifms intentus, minor est ad singula sensus.''^ 
 See Hamilton, Meta., pp. 1()4, 171. 
 
COGNITION. 81 
 
 then the intensity rehative to it is acquired at the expense 
 of the vividness of the others. They become confused and 
 obscure, and perhaps many pass entirely out of consciousness. 
 Thus the intensity of present knowledge limits its extension. 
 When listening to an eloquent discourse an assembly will 
 remain motionless ; but no sooner is it ended than a move- 
 ment of the whole audience shows that each one has become 
 conscious of some discomfort which he seeks to relieve, and 
 perhaps is startled to find himself suddenly in the presence 
 of hundreds, when but the moment before he was alone with 
 the speaker. Many a soldier wounded during the heat of 
 battle has not discovered it until exhausted by loss of blood ; 
 and many a martyr has suffered at the stake with calm 
 serenity, his attention being so engrossed with beatific visions 
 that the flames had no power of torture. ^ 
 
 § 84. Attention to an external thing is observation ; atten- 
 tion to an internal mental image of a thing is reflection.^ 
 The former relates to objects of sense ; the latter, to subjec- 
 tive objects. Observation is only of a thing present ; whereas 
 reflection considers also something not now present, but 
 represented by the mental image. Observation without 
 reflection hardly does more than amass facts ; reflection with- 
 out observation needs material. As a habit of mind one or 
 
 1 Sir Walter Scott, while painfully ill, dictated almost the whole of Ivan- 
 hoe. When a dialogue of special interest was in progress, he would rise 
 from his couch and walk to and fro with the greatest animation, unconscious 
 of the pangs that a moment before and after extorted from Mm groans of 
 agony. — Lockhart, Life of Scott, ch. 44. 
 
 A skilful portrait-painter will depict the features of his subject clearly and 
 distinctly, but will "sink" the drapery, the background, and other acces- 
 sories, making them comparatively indistinct. This does not represent nature 
 as it is, but as it appears ; it corresponds to our state of consciousness when 
 we intently observe the features of another person. The artist thus leads us 
 to contemplate the features of the portrait, for that is the attitude in which 
 the spectator finds most ease. 
 
 2 Reid, as understood by Stewart, gives us this distinction, but in common 
 usage it is not strictly observed. 
 
82 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 the other generally preponderates, so that men of science 
 may fairly be divided into observers and thinkers ; the former 
 furnisliing matter, the latter forging it into shape. 
 
 § 85. Besides attention to a definite object there is an 
 indefinite or expectant attention, having no particular, dis- 
 tinct object. Consciousness is, as it were, concentrated 
 within itself, and thus intensified awaits a definite object, 
 expected but as yet undetermined, on wliich it shall concen- 
 trate. 
 
 A teacher says to his pupils : Attend to what I am about 
 to say. There is a pause, during which their minds are 
 attentive ; they are listening, their attention is arrested, but 
 its object is as yet undetermined. Anxiety, vague forebod- 
 ing, and anticipation in general, involve this state. Coleridge 
 says : " In attention we may keep the mind passive, we sub- 
 mit it to an impression, we keep it steady in order to receive 
 the stamp." ^ 
 
 § 86. An important distinction is between voluntary and 
 involuntary attention ; the one active, the other passive. 
 
 The latter occurs when some sudden or persistent presen- 
 tation excites consciousness intensely, distracting it from 
 other objects and concentrating it on this one, without the 
 exercise of will. A startling noise, a flash of light, a con- 
 tinuous and acute pain, powerfully attract attention, as also 
 a bright idea, or a striking thought. Likewise a strong desire, 
 as hunger, curiosity, love, excites involuntary attention. A 
 commanding effort of the will may transfer attention promptly 
 to preferred objects, but for an instant at least the distraction 
 is usually irresistible.^ 
 
 1 Aids to Beflection, vol. i, p. 4. This is called by Dr. Carpenter "ex- 
 pectant attention.'" — .l/c?t«. Fhiis., ch. 3. A knock at the door excites it. 
 Also the military command, "Attention company." Also the gavel. 
 
 2 " L'esprit du plus grand homme du monde n'est pas si independent, 
 qu'il ne soit sujet k etre trouble par le moindre tintamarre qui se fait autour 
 de lui. II ne faut pas le bruit d'un canon pour empecher ses pensfies ; il ne 
 
COGNITION. 83 
 
 Involuntary attention and distraction are correlatives, 
 implying each other, the positive and negative aspects of the 
 same state. In such attention the mind is attracted by an 
 object ; this is positive. In distraction, the mind is drawn 
 away from other objects ; this is negative. 
 
 § 87. Voluntary attention occurs when the ego, by an 
 inherent, original, and constitutional power, chooses to con- 
 centrate consciousness, and does actually concentrate it, on a 
 chosen object. This is intentional attention.^ Its correlative 
 is abstraction. These are the same exercises viewed in dif- 
 ferent relations, the positive and negative aspects of the same 
 act. In attention the mind centres on an object ; this is the 
 positive view, the giving of mind to the thing. In abstrac- 
 tion the mind draws away from other objects; this is the 
 negative view, the withholding of mind from those things. 
 What we call absence of mind is abstraction, the mind hav- 
 ing withdrawn from things to which we think it should be 
 attending.^ 
 
 § 88. Can I attend to more than one thing at a time? 
 The question is concerning a fact of consciousness, and can 
 be answered only by an appeal to consciousness. 
 
 faut que le bruit d'une girouette ou d'une poulie. Ne vous etonnez pas s'il 
 ne raisonne pas bien a present ; une mouche bourdonne a ses oreilles ; e'en 
 est assez pour le rendre incapable de bon conseil. Si vous voulez qu'il puisse 
 trouver la verite, chassez cet animal qui tient sa raison en echec, et trouble 
 cette puissante intelligence qui gouverne les villes et les royaumes." — Pascal, 
 Pensees^ I, vi, 12. 
 
 A rustic cannot think amid the bustle of a city ; but J. S. Mill tells us 
 that he thought out the greater part of his System of Logic during his daily 
 walks in the crowded and noisy streets of London, and that, so complete was 
 his abstraction, he suffered no distraction. 
 
 1 As attention is related to cognition, so is intention to volition. Inten- 
 tion is volition concentrated ; it is will determined on an action. Both are 
 objective. Flirting is attention without intention. 
 
 2 It is preoccupation of mind. Inattention, absolute, probably never 
 exists, the mind being always more or less attentive to something. 
 
84 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 Consciousness of an object should be distinguished from 
 attention to an object. I am always conscious of many 
 things at once, and the effect of attention is to bring an 
 object out from obscure into clear consciousness. Now can I 
 select several of the objects, and attend to each separately 
 and at once ? I find on trial that I cannot. I can attend to 
 a group of things, but not to them severally. A group is 
 but one object. I can transfer my attention rapidly from one 
 thing to another, but succession is not simultaneity. I find 
 I can attend to only one thing at one time.^ 
 
 If it were otherwise, then it might become possible for 
 me to pursue two distinct trains of thought simultaneously. 
 Who has ever done this ? ^ I cannot attend even to two per- 
 sons talking to me on different subjects at the same time. I 
 can attend to either one at pleasure without being much dis- 
 turbed by the other; I can, if versatile, rapidly alternate my 
 attention, and thus, perhaps, catch the meaning of both ; but 
 if I try to listen to both strictly at once, I can understand 
 neither. Indeed, if plural attention were possible, why should 
 there be such a thing as distraction? But we are often so 
 distracted by a call for double attention as to be incapable of 
 any.^ 
 
 1 Hamilton per contra^ Meta., Lee. 13, 14. He offers a direct argument 
 which is a bald petition. — See p. 165. He confuses consciousness of many 
 objects, with attention, e.g. : "If mind can attend to, or be conscious of, 
 only a single object at a time, how is comparison possible ? " — p. 175. This 
 is ignoratio eleitchi. President Porter follows Hamilton. — Hum. Intellect., 
 § 180. Yet, with approbation, Hamilton quotes Jouffroy as saying : " It is 
 established by experience that we cannot give our attention to two different 
 objects at the same time." — p. 227. 
 
 2 Gibbon says of the emperor Julian : " He possessed such flexibility of 
 thought, and such firmness of attention, that he could employ his hand to 
 write, his ear to listen, and his voice to dictate, and so pursue at once three 
 several trains of ideas, without hesitation and without error." — Decline and 
 Fall, ch. 22. Hardly historical. 
 
 ** Plural attention is apparently supported by such cases as Napoleon I 
 dictating to a dozen secretaries, and Paul Morphy blindfolded playing eight 
 games of chess at once. But these are explained by alternating attention, 
 
COGNITION. 85 
 
 It is fairly asked : How, then, is comparison (§ 80) possi- 
 ble? The answer is easy. In order to compare, a relation 
 must be discerned between two objects within consciousness. 
 By virtue of this relation the two become one, for "the 
 knowledge of relatives is one." The more intimate the rela- 
 tion, the more complete is the fusion in consciousness; but 
 even a remote relation is sufficient so to unite them that they 
 may become a single object of attention.^ 
 
 § 89. It is the special function of the will to fix and hold 
 attention. The great significance of this fact in human 
 nature becomes apparent when we observe that (the control 
 of muscular energy probably not being an exception) the 
 will has no other power. Voluntary attention to this or that 
 object is the sole but sufficient means of self-control. I have 
 no other, and I need no other, means of repressing, arousing, 
 directing, or combining my faculties, whether of cognition, 
 feeling, or desire. 
 
 The command of one's faculties by the power of attention 
 is more or less perfect in proportion to the natural strength 
 of the will, which varies in individuals, and to the develop- 
 ment of its energy under the Law of Habit, namely: Our 
 powers acquire facility and strength by exercise. This 
 development requires that hindrances be resolutely met and 
 overcome, that distractions be persistently reversed until they 
 
 aided by powerful memory. Great versatility, the ready and rapid transfer 
 of attention, often quite remarkable in women, startles us who are slow to 
 follow by an appearance of plural attention. But how is it that a pianist can 
 play two discordant tunes, one with each hand, while singing a third ? Two 
 at least are produced automatically, without attention (§ 37). 
 
 1 Contrariorum eadem est scientia, said the scholastics. Mere juxtaposi- 
 tion is sufficient for unification, enabling us to group as one the most hetero- 
 geneous objects. The subject and predicate of a proposition are thought 
 together only by virtue of the relation constituting them one proposition. 
 Aristotle pronounces the act of judgment to be single and instantaneous. 
 "In general, we may say, whenever by an act of attention mental data are 
 unified into a related whole, this is an act of apperception." — Baldwin, 
 Psychology, p. 56. See § 80, note. 
 
86 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 cease. To acquire this power of attention should be the 
 primary purpose of all mental discipline ; for by it alone can 
 one cultivate and realize his natural gifts, by it alone can 
 he rigorously train them, by it alone can he direct their exer- 
 cise in the manner best suited to expand and elevate, and by 
 it alone can he restrain them from all that would limit and 
 debase. Moreover, the discovery of truth requires the labor 
 of attention. " It is only the labor of attention," says Male- 
 branche, "that has light for its reward. The attention of 
 the intellect is the natural prayer by which we o]:)tain the 
 enlightenment of reason. Since the fall, the intellect can 
 but feebly pray, the labor of attention fatigues and afflicts it. 
 Indeed, this labor is at first great, and the recompense scanty ; 
 nevertheless, it is necessary; we must invoke reason to be 
 enlightened; there is no other way of obtaining light and 
 intelligence. Faith is a pure grace, but the understanding 
 of truth is a grace that must be merited b}^ labor ; so that 
 without this laborious attention, which is the force of intel- 
 lect, we shall never be enabled to comprehend the grandeur 
 of religion, the sanctity of morals, and the littleness of all 
 that is not God." ^ 
 
 1 Free quotation from Traite de Morale, I, v, 4 ; vi, 1. See Hamilton, 
 Meta., p. 177 sq. for excellent remarks on the value of attention, supported 
 by many striking examples. Cf. Stewart, Elements, ch. i, p. 122 sq., and 
 p. 352. The following, said of Cardinal Richelieu, illustrates several of the 
 foregoing points : — 
 
 "Ce jour-la, il fut remarqu6 par ses serviteurs (c'etaint a pen pres tous 
 ceux qui rapprocbaient) que, depuis son lever jusqu'a la nuit, il ne prit 
 aucune nourriture, et tendit tellement toute I'application de son ame sur les 
 6venements necessaires a conduire, qu'il triompha des douleurs de £ m corps, 
 et sembla les avoir dgtruites a force de les oublier. C'fitait cette puissance 
 d'attention et cette prfisence continuelle de I'esprit qui le haussaient presque 
 jusqu'au g6nie. II I'aurait atteint s'il ne lui eut manqufi I'filgvation native de 
 I'ame et la sensibility g6n6reuse du coeui-." — Vigny, Cinq-Mars, p. 157. 
 
PRESENTATION. 87 
 
 CHAPTER II. 
 
 PRESENTATION. 
 
 § 90. So far of cognition in general. We are now to con- 
 sider immediate knowledge or presentation specially. 
 
 Presentation is a mode of the cognitive consciousness. It 
 is called presentation because its object is present to me 
 here and now ; or because the object is viewed as given or 
 presented to consciousness. The definition of presentation 
 is immediate knowledge ; that is, knowledge wherein no 
 medium lies between the subject knowing and the thing 
 known. Expressed positively, this is direct knowledge. 
 
 Presentative knowledge being immediate or direct is also 
 intuitive ; the subject and object are, as it were, face to 
 face.^ Now intuition is of two kinds, empirical and pure. 
 Empirical intuition is either of an external thing or non-ego 
 known in perception, or of an internal subjective object 
 known in self-perception. Pure intuition is of non-sensu- 
 ous objects intellectually discerned. These special powers 
 are to be discussed in their order. 
 
 § 91. In presentation, consciousness is primarily not actively 
 exerted, but passively affected, does not act, but merely reacts, 
 is merely receptive of the impression which the object makes 
 upon it. A flash of light, or a sudden noise, is a presenta- 
 tive object making an impression on me, and this impression, 
 of which I am passively conscious, is, in the first instant of 
 cognition, a presentation.^ 
 
 1 Intuition, from intueri, to behold, to look directly upon, Ger. Auschauung. 
 The term, says Duns Scotus, was probably sus:gested to the earlier scholas- 
 tics by the Vulgate of 1 Cor. 13 : 12, '■'■facie ad faciem.'''' 
 
 2 So, also, the mental image I now form of an absent object, as the moon, 
 
88 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 A presentation is a psychological judgment (§ 80) afBrm- 
 ing existence, and affording certainty of the actual, of the 
 here and now existent. That is, the object is consciously 
 known as real, or, in other words, its reality is given as a 
 fact of consciousness.^ 
 
 § 92. The logical opposite of presentation is represen- 
 tation. Representative knowledge is mediate knowledge or 
 cognition, since therein the conscious subject knows through 
 a medium some remote object beyond its sphere. In presen- 
 tative or immediate knowledge, there are only two factors, 
 a conscious subject and an object consciously known. In 
 representation, there are three factors, a conscious subject, 
 the medium or object representing, and the remote object 
 represented. So far as the immediate object is considered 
 in itself alone, the cognition is a presentation ; as, I hear a 
 sound. But when this object is considered with reference to 
 some other beyond consciousness, the cognition is a repre- 
 sentation; as, I hear a voice. If I think of Alt. Blanc, there 
 is an image or idea of it formed by my mind of which, as a 
 present object, I am conscious ; this idea, as a medium, repre- 
 sents the real mountain, but of the mountain itself I am not 
 conscious. Again, I am angry, and am subjectively self- 
 conscious of this state. If, now, I contemplate it as a subject- 
 object, this knowledge of it is merely presentative. If, 
 afterward, the anger having ceased, I remember and reflect 
 
 considered in itself alone without regard to the remote object, is a subjective 
 presentation. 
 
 1 A presentation is always numerically single, an individual, undivided, 
 though not necessarily indivisible. E.g. a chain, or one of its links ; a sen- 
 tence, a word, a letter ; each of these is an individual. 
 
 Tresence here and now, in both space and time, is requisite to a presenta- 
 tion of external sense, as the book before me ; but time only to a presenta- 
 tion of internal sense, as my interest in it. But thoughts, as representative, 
 are emancipated from both bonds. So Thomas Aquinas: " While sense can 
 know existence only under the limits of space and time (cognoscU esse sub 
 hie et nunc), the intellect apprehends it absolutely, or with reference to all 
 time," — Sum. Theol., i, 75, 6. 
 
PRE SEN TA TION. 8 9 
 
 upon it, there is then an image of it present to my mind, 
 through which I know the past anger. This image, itself a 
 presentation, represents the past anger, and the total state 
 is representative. The medium or object representing is 
 consciously or immediately known in itself, and therefore, 
 considered irrespectively of what it represents, is itself a 
 presentative object. A representation, then, involves a pres- 
 entation ; it is a presentation, and something more. 
 
 § 93. The many objects usually present within the cog- 
 nitive consciousness, with perhaps a single exception, are 
 merely presentative. In the impression they make, the great 
 majority are cognized more or less obscurely, only a few are 
 clearly known ; but in so far as each is known, it is known 
 in itself, immediately, and without reference to anything 
 else beyond. When attention is fixed on any one, it is 
 thereby drawn, into clear and distinct consciousness, and 
 may become also representative. A state of attention seems 
 requisite to a representation; and, since we can attend to 
 but one object at a time (§ 88), it follows that, amid the 
 many objects present in consciousness, only one can be 
 representative. Also, let it be remarked, if the attention 
 be involuntary, the total state is primarily passive; but if 
 it be voluntary, then, relatively to the object of attention, 
 consciousness is at once active and passive; passive in 
 receiving the impression, active in giving attention to it. 
 
 § 94. Further illustration will perhaps be helpful here. 
 A book is before me, and my hand rests upon it. I am 
 conscious of the sensuous impression which the object makes 
 on me. If no more than this, then there is a presentation 
 only, a mere perception in the strict meaning of that term, 
 an immediate cognition. But if my attention is turned to it, 
 I recognize it as a book, I refer it to a class, and this is a 
 representation, an apperception, a thought. 
 
 Words spoken to an absent-minded man are heard as sounds. 
 
90 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 but are not understood. Also lie stares in the face of his 
 friend without recognizing him. When the latter enforces 
 his attention, the recognition takes place, and the remembered 
 sounds are now perhaps understood. But he knows that the 
 impressions did not just then begin, but his attention to the 
 impressions now interpreted. 
 
 Suppose one born blind to receive sight, and to have as 
 his first visual percept red light. This experience being quite 
 new, he cannot at once refer the object to any class of things 
 already known, he cannot give it a name, he cannot analyze 
 it into parts or qualities, he did not will to produce it, he 
 cannot at will modify it, it is given to him and he is passively 
 receptive ; he must cognize it, but does not recognize it. So 
 far it is a presentation merely. But perhaps when he has 
 reflected a moment he recognizes it as a percept of sense. 
 This reference to a class is a thought, a representation. 
 
 Ordinarily the transition from the presentative to the repre- 
 sentative state is almost instantaneous, quicker than lightning. 
 For when a flash of lightning unexpectedly occurs, I first 
 perceive an object suddenly presented, but before the flash 
 has passed away, or before its impression on ni}^ retina has 
 ceased, I recognize it, now as a visual object, a flash, next 
 as out before me in space, then as a flash of lightning. 
 
 In the first glance at a new landscape, I have only an intu- 
 ition of the scene, a confused knowledge of it as one whole, 
 without a recognition or even a clear distinction of parts. 
 This is mere presentation. But in an instant I recognize 
 trees, buildings, streams, rocks, hills, etc., and apprehend 
 their relations, or apperceive them, in respect of distance, 
 magnitude, etc., and thus come to think out the landscape as 
 a whole. This thought of the whole is far more complete 
 knowledge than the intuition of the whole, which was all 
 that sense gave us at the first momentary glance. Tn this 
 example it is very evident that presentation furnishes the 
 iii;it(Mi;ils with wliicli iiitcllfcl builds. 
 
PERCEPTION. 91 
 
 CHAPTER III. 
 
 PEKCEPTION. 
 
 § 95. Perception is the immediate knowledge of an exter- 
 nal object. Being immediate, it has but two factors, a sub- 
 ject knowing and an object known. Since all modes of 
 cognition are modes of objective consciousness, and since 
 consciousness is always immediate, it follows that perception 
 is consciousness of an external object. Accordingly, the ob- 
 ject, though external, that is, a thing distinct from mind, is 
 nevertheless within the sphere of consciousness. Being an 
 object perceived, it is called a percept. 
 
 § 96. The physical organs of sense are closely associated 
 in our thoughts with the exercise of perception; they are 
 sometimes spoken of as physical media between the subject 
 perceiving and the object perceived ; and some authors have 
 thought it right and sufficient to define perception as knowl- 
 edge by means of the senses. We should, however, remem- 
 ber that our science is only a development of the facts of 
 consciousness, that it originates in and proceeds from these, 
 and that to consider aught else is to abandon its proper held. 
 We are limited, then, to what consciousness gives in an act 
 of perception. 
 
 Now, of the several outer organs of sense, the eye, the ear, 
 etc., consciousness tells us nothing whatever. We are not at 
 all conscious even of their existence, much less of their struc- 
 ture and functions. Observation and inference apprise us 
 that they exist, and also that they are physical conditions of 
 perception (§ 5). The investigation of their structure and 
 
 'UNIVBErf^ 
 
 
 (^^ ^ »»• 
 
92 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 functions belongs to anatomy and physiology, and with them 
 psychology strictly has nothing to do. 
 
 Moreover, we have already found tliat the true percept 
 lies not beyond, but on this side, so to speak, of the outer 
 organ of sense (§ 21); so that the organ cannot, even in the 
 freest view, be considered a medium, but only as an antece- 
 dent condition. 
 
 Therefore we must eliminate these organs entirely from 
 our present considerations. I must retire within and ask : Of 
 what am I conscious when perceiving? And this standpoint 
 must be rigidly maintained if we would enjoy the certainties 
 of consciousness. 
 
 § 97. Within the domain of consciousness we are still 
 liable to confusion, and perception projDcr needs to be sharply 
 discriminated from certain things which lie close to it ; first 
 from its correlative sensation. 
 
 The primary power, consciousness, was sub-divided into 
 cognition and feeling (§ 71). These, though always coex- 
 istent, may be clearly distinguished. A cognition is objec- 
 tive, a feeling is wholly subjective. Now, perception is a 
 special kind of cognition (§ 72), and sensation a special kind 
 of feeling (§ 73). The consideration of the latter must be 
 postponed to Part IV. We have here to do with perception 
 only.i 
 
 But another distinction is needful. The definition dven 
 
 1 "A conscious presentation," says Coleridge, "if it refer exclusively to 
 the subject as a modification of its own state of being, is a sensation ; the 
 same, if it refer to an object, is a perception, which, when hnmediate and 
 individual, is an intuition." — Church and State, p. 301. See also Hamilton, 
 Meta., p. o35, and lieid, note D*. The word sensation is still used by some 
 scientists to denote sensitive apprehension, both in its subjective and in its 
 objective relations, like the Greek atfferiffis. It was limited first by the Carte- 
 sians, and thereafter in the Scottish school, to the subjective phase. We 
 should not expect sensation and perception to be distinguished in common 
 language, for the purposes of common life do not require it; but in psy- 
 chology they should be discriminated as obverse and reverse. Neglect of 
 this has caused, like the shield in the story, many a knightly tilt. 
 
PERCEPTION. 93 
 
 is of perception proper, that is, of immediate perception. 
 There is another quite complex mode of cognition, of which 
 perception proper is only a part, but which is always in com- 
 mon speech called perception simply, though involving much 
 more. Since it is largely a representative state, we shall call 
 it mediate perception.^ 
 
 What, for example, in looking at a house, do I truly and 
 really see ? Certain colored figures ; nothing more. These, 
 and these only, constitute the object presented, the object 
 immediately, intuitively perceived by sight. As a result of 
 experience and observation, they have become also signs to 
 me by or through which I judge a house to be there, and 
 judge also of its details. The house is doubtless real, but is 
 not the real object of direct perception. The vision of col- 
 ored figure only is given by sight (§§ 17, 19). All else that 
 I seem to see and say that I see is inferred, represented, and 
 known in mediate perception. So also of the commonly sup- 
 posed objects of the other senses. We must, therefore, elim- 
 inate from our present considerations all mediate, all repre- 
 sented, matter, and limit them to the immediate, presented 
 percept. 
 
 § 98. What remains in perception when we disregard all 
 that is mere sensation, and all that is mediate ? In the exer- 
 cise of each sense, I perceive immediately, or am conscious 
 of, the positive existence of a phenomenon. I do not perceive 
 substance, but a quality of substance. I do not perceive its 
 cause, but know there must be a cause of the phenomenon. 
 Altogether, I perceive the positively existing and caused qual- 
 
 1 In the comparatively recent psychology of Lotze, of Wundt, and of their 
 strict followers, this is called simply perception, and is classed as one of the 
 apperceptive faculties (§ 88, note). Leibnitz, however, from whom comes 
 the term apperception (§ 80, note), calls the cognitive exercise described 
 above, mediate perception (§ 69, note). The psychologists referred to lose 
 the important distinction between sensation and immediate perception, and 
 commit the error of treating mediate perception as a special or simple 
 faculty. 
 
94 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 ity of something that is not I. If I go one step beyond the 
 presentative state, I know the percept to be an odor, or a 
 sound, or a color, as the case may be. Nothing more than 
 these simple percepts is immediately given. I do not perceive 
 that they are qualities of something outside my own body ; 
 for the senses do not singly or together tell me that a body 
 belongs to me. Nor do they primarily reveal to me the exten- 
 sion or existence in space of anytliing whatever. 
 
 § 99. An important feature common to the several modes 
 of perception is their passivity relatively to their objects. 
 
 In modes of mediate cognition, in remembering, in imag- 
 ining, in thinking, I am consciously active, either sjjonta- 
 neously or voluntarily. With conscious energy, I form and 
 contemplate representative ideas of remote objects. Each 
 image thus presented by consciousness to consciousness is 
 subject to consciousness ; it may be dismissed or modified 
 either in spontaneous action or at will. I myself am the 
 author and master of these mental modes, they being the 
 products, or, rather, the exercises of my own conscious activ- 
 ity determined directly by me. 
 
 In perception, the case is different. When my eyes and 
 ears are open I receive impressions of light and sound with- 
 out the slightest effort on my part. I may place myself in 
 an attitude favorable to the impression, and thus increase its 
 effect. I may pay little or no attention to it. I may remove 
 entirely out of the way, as by shutting my eyes. But while 
 within its reach, I have power to receive, that is, passive 
 power, but no power to reject the impression. Also, I am 
 powerless to change or modify it in kind, but onl}- in degree. 
 Its existence is wholly determined for me, not at all by me. 
 
 For example, while I am absorbed in study, my clock 
 strikes. Is it true that I do not hear it ? No ; for if asked 
 the time a few moments afterwaid, I remember having heard 
 it. If a speaker's voice or topic is disagreeable, I may " turn 
 a deaf ear," or give little heed to it, and so diminish the 
 
PERCEPTION. 95 
 
 effect ; but I cannot at will refuse to hear, and so be uncon- 
 scious of the sound. Let us suppose I am standing alongside 
 a steam engine, studying its mechanism, when suddenly the 
 whistle blows. What can I do? Can I refuse to hear? I 
 stop my ears with my fingers, but that only abates the horror. 
 I can run away, but shall have to run very far. I can commit 
 suicide, as perhaps it disposes me to do. Otherwise I hear. 
 Can I continue my study ? Not at all. The powerful over- 
 mastering sound comes upon me, dominating all my faculties, 
 and they become helpless and useless under its power. The 
 same, mutatis mutandis, is true of each of the six senses. 
 
 Perception, then, relatively to its objects, is an affection, not 
 an action ; a capacity, not a faculty. In it, the mind receives 
 impressions without being able to reject or to modify them ; 
 it does not act, but is acted on ; it does not affect, but is 
 affected. In perception my state is merely receptive ; I am 
 strictly passive. 
 
 There is no such thing as absolute passivity. All things 
 are at once acting and reacting, and the reaction, which is 
 positive, is the passion. It is this positive reaction, this 
 passive resistance, of which I am conscious when receiving 
 a sensuous impression, and I am conscious that it is reaction, 
 a passion, and not an action, that I am the patient, and not 
 the agent. I am therein the subject of experience in the 
 strictest sense, and perception is pre-eminently the power 
 wherein I am subjected to experiences.^ 
 
 1 The verb to eorperiment always implies activity, while to experience is 
 always used with reference to a passive, receptive state. Both words are 
 from the same deponent verb experiri, to try or to be tried. We try an 
 experiment (Ger. Versuch), we undergo an experience (Ger. Erfahrung). 
 See § 60, note. The noun trial is eitlier an action or a passion. Passivity 
 seems to be a special characteristic of experience. Let us note also that a 
 passive state is not a quiescent one. The former is positive, the latter merely 
 negative. 
 
96 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 CHAPTER IV. 
 
 EXTERNAL REALITY. 
 
 § 100. The percept is external to mind, is a non-ego. This 
 seems almost paradoxical. How can mind be conscious of 
 that which is beyond it ? The doctrine is not to be rejected 
 because it is incomprehensible, for the primary data of con- 
 sciousness, being the conditions under which all else is com- 
 prehended, are of course themselves incomprehensible. We 
 can only know that they are, not how they are. To explain 
 how they are would be to refer them to some higher princi- 
 ple ; but there is none. If a clearly correct analysis ascer- 
 tains that mind is conscious of something distinct from itself, 
 there is an end of the matter ; the fact is ultimate, and must 
 be accepted.^ 
 
 It is admitted by all philosophers and skeptics that I am 
 conscious of the percept, for example, of an odor or a sound. 
 This, therefore, may be taken for granted as undisputed and 
 indisputable. It is the common conviction of men that the 
 percept is a non-ego. This, certain philosophers pronounce a 
 delusion, holding the percept to be merely an objectified mode 
 of the ego itself. Of these, some theoreticall}^ deny the exist- 
 ence of a non-ego ; others admit its existence, maintaining, 
 however, that this is not immediately, but mediately known. 
 
 1 "Herein," says Herbert Spencer, "is an all-sufficient warrant for the 
 assertion of objective existence. Mysterious as seems the consciousness of 
 something; wliich is yet out of [i.e. distinct from] consciousness, the inquirer 
 finds that he alleges the reality of this something in virtue of the ultimate 
 law, he is obliged to think it. It is impossible by reasoning either to verify 
 or to falsify this deliverance of consciousness." — Pn'nciph's of Psychology, 
 § 448. 
 
EXTERNAL REALITY. 97 
 
 Our view, on the contrary, is that in perception I am con- 
 scious of a non-ego ; that is to say, I immediately know that 
 the object is a non-ego. This is the doctrine of immediate 
 perception.^ 
 
 § 101. In a previous section (§ 99) it was shown that per- 
 ception relatively to its object is strictly a passive power, 
 contrasting in this respect with the representative faculties. 
 What now is involved in this fact of consciousness, this com- 
 plete and positive passivity of mind in perception? A patient 
 implies an agent, and a consciousness of one correlative im- 
 plies a consciousness of the other. My consciousness of the 
 agent or object lies in my consciousness of its action on me ; 
 and herein I am conscious of its activity. Thus in percep- 
 tion, while consciously passive, I am conscious of an activity. 
 Now, as I cannot be both active and passive myself, in one 
 and the same relation, it is evident that this activity must be 
 the activity of a non-ego ; and, since I am conscious of this 
 activity as a positive fact, I am therein conscious of, or per- 
 ceive, a positive non-ego.^ 
 
 1 It is the chief cliaracteristic of the Scottish school of philosophy, the 
 school of Eeid and Hamilton, in opposition to idealism, and under various 
 forms of statement now widely prevalent in the philosophemes of Europe 
 and of this coiintry. It is held in the present treatise with important though 
 not essential modifications, and supported on original grounds. 
 
 ■^ We are well aware that Mill (Logic, bk. iii, ch. 5, § 4) teaches that the 
 distinction between agent and patient is illusory, being merely verbal. But 
 surely a distinction embedded in the very structure of all languages is founded 
 on something more than mere expression. Surely there is some essential 
 difference between I strike, and I am stricken. It is unquestionably true, as 
 he says, that " in case of a sensation produced in our organs, the laws of our 
 organization, and even those of our minds, are as directly operative in deter- 
 mining the effect produced, as the laws of the outward object." Still it 
 remains that there is a real distinction between these antecedents, and not 
 merely that one is taken arbitrarily as the theatre or "scene in which the 
 effect takes place." The ground of the distinction seems to be in the rela- 
 tion to volition, which is essentially active. The antecedent which is more 
 nearly related to will, or more directly traceable to it, is the agent. Or, that 
 antecedent in which a will is forcibly dominated or unresistingly subject, 
 
98 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 Another view. In my conscious reaction I am conscious 
 the object as a cause or force irresistibly and irreversibly 
 constraining me, oftentimes compelling my attention, and 
 sometimes completely dominating all my faculties. I cannot 
 expel it from my consciousness, within whose sphere it has 
 appeared, exerting a mastery, and determining that peculiar 
 state of consciousness we call perception. That in being thus 
 forced, I am conscious of force, cannot be questioned. Such 
 force in one case we call light, in another sound, in another 
 odor, etc. We usually identify it with some external force, 
 but contemplate it here only as adventitious energy, coming 
 into the sphere of consciousness, and determining its state. ^ 
 
 I am conscious that my own mental energy, and this 
 physical energy, experienced in perception, are entirely inde- 
 pendent of each other in their origin, and wholly different in 
 their operation. 1 have a positive, unmistakable conscious- 
 ness that they are often in actual conflict, the one tending to 
 produce a peculiar mental state, the other striving to counter- 
 act its influence ; though indeed the conflict is one-sided ; 
 for I find no mode of direct resistance, and no present recourse 
 save in flight. 
 
 This opposition and subjection mark consciously and 
 clearly two distinct realities external to each other. Neces- 
 sarily in my consciousness they are apprehended as two 
 realities ; I cannot possibly unite them in one conception. 
 The one is consciously the property and manifestation of me 
 myself. The other is consciously the property and manifes- 
 
 directly or remotely, is the patient. Where no relation to will is discoverable, 
 the distinction becomes uncertain, and hence illusory, but not even then 
 groundless. 
 
 Because of the doubt which Mill's view may excite as to the validity of 
 the argument in the text above, founded on the distinction between action 
 and passion in the antecedents, another form of the argument is presented, 
 founded on the distinction between cause and effect, or antecedent and conse- 
 quent. 
 
 1 "La force proprement dite, c'est ce qui rfigit les actes, sans r6gler les 
 
 VOlontfes." — COMTE. 
 
EXTERNAL BEALITY. 99 
 
 tation of something in direct opposition to me, the manifes- 
 tation to consciousness of a positive non-ego. 
 
 Surely, then, it is a primary fact of consciousness, original 
 and not inferred, certain and beyond the possibility of the 
 least actual doubt, that the immediate object in perception is 
 consciously not I. 
 
 § 102. There are those who hold that consciousness may, 
 and probably does, deceive me in this matter. They dis- 
 tinguish between the fact that consciousness testifies to the 
 existence of a non-ego, and the truth of its testimony. The 
 former, they admit, cannot be doubted; but the latter, they 
 affirm, may reasonably be doubted. 
 
 In reply it is said that if consciousness can possibly deceive 
 me in any one particular, then all trust in it is at an end ; 
 for I have nothing higher by which, as a criterion, to test its 
 deliverances, and so a doubt of any one is equally applicable 
 to all. Hence all philosophy would reduce at once to 
 extreme agnosticism, or the impossibility of any certain 
 knowledge whatever.^ 
 
 1 This is the gist of Hamilton's famous argiiment for immediate percep- 
 tion, which contributed more perhaps than any other one thing to his gi-eat 
 reputation. See it elaborated in Meta., Lee. 15; and in Discussions, article 
 Phil, of Percep.; but most carefiiUy and fully stated in Reid, appendix, 
 note A. 
 
 The argument is open to criticism at several points. E.rj. it hinges in its 
 progi'ess on the statement that because it has never been shown that con- 
 sciousness contradicts itself, therefore the logical presumption is in favor of 
 its truthfulness. Allowed ; but since there can be no more certainty in a con- 
 clusion than is in the premises, his conclusion is merely presumptive, and not 
 demonstrative as he claims it to be. 
 
 Again, the argument is in form a reductio ad ahsurdtim. But the conclu- 
 sion does not contradict an assumed premise, nor is it self-contradictory ; 
 there is no logical absurdity. Nor is there even a philosophical absurdity, i.e. 
 a violation of the Law of Parcimony (§ 82, note). The conclusion, if proved, 
 would violate our most cherished convictions, but should not on that account 
 alone be rejected. 
 
 Moreover, the subsequent paragraph in the text above shows that the 
 argument is Fallacia ficjurce dictionis, a form of fallacy on which Hamilton 
 heaps contempt. See his Logic, § 78. 
 
100 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 A better reply is as follows : The distinction between the 
 fact that testimony is given, and its truth, is inej)t in this 
 case. Testimony implies two parties ; here is but one. To 
 say that literally I myself testify to myself is absurd. Con- 
 sciousness as a witness is only a misleading metaphor. 
 Dismiss the figure of speech, and the distinction vanishes, 
 the testimony of consciousness to a non-ego becomes simply 
 consciousness of a non-ego. 
 
 § 103. Let it be granted, then, that each of the percepts is 
 a quality of a non-ego. Most of them, however, as odor, 
 savor, sound, color, and tangibility, are, in immediate percep- 
 tion, only excited states of the sensory or brain, which is, 
 therefore, the true non-ego of consciousness. They have no 
 existence, as we perceive them, in external bodies. These 
 are only the occult and remote causes of the percepts, which 
 are consequently reckoned as merely secondary qualities of 
 body. The primary, essential, and defining qualities of body 
 are extension and impenetrability.^ These are supposed to 
 exist in the external body itself in the same manner in 
 which they are perceived. Unless they are immediately 
 perceived, we cannot be sa,id to have immediate perception 
 of body as it really exists, a consciousness of matter in its 
 essential features. 
 
 § 104. Perception of extension, which is denied to the 
 other senses, is attributed to sight and touch as a secondary 
 percept (§§ 19, 24). Let us examine touch. Suppose that 
 without seeing it, or other premonition, my open palms are 
 lightly touched simultaneously. Tlie contacts are not to 
 differ in kind or degree. Now it is unquestionable, not only 
 that I am conscious of these contacts, but that I consciously 
 distinguish them numerically as two. But this is impossible 
 unless I am conscious that they are apart from each other. 
 
 1 The primary and secondary qualities of body are discussed, historically 
 and critically, by Hamilton in Iteid, note D. See also Mansel, Meta., p. 97. 
 
EXTERNAL REALITY. 101 
 
 The consciousness that they are apart is consciousness of 
 extension. 
 
 It is needless just now to follow out the details by which I 
 pass from this elementary form of the cognition to a full 
 knowledge of body as occupying space in three dimensions. 
 It is sufficient here that by touch I have an immediate knowl- 
 edge of body in this primary quality, geometrical extension.^ 
 
 Now consider the percept of the muscular sense. The 
 weight of my limbs necessarily exerts various pressures on 
 the nerves that penetrate the muscular tissue. There can be 
 no pressure without its correlative resistance. Of this resist- 
 ance I am passively conscious. But the consciousness of 
 the resistance of body to compression is a consciousness of 
 its physical solidity, or impenetrability. 
 
 Thus in the exercise of touch and the muscular sense, 
 which usually co-operate, is given an immediate and proper 
 knowledge of body in its real and essential characteristics. 
 
 § 105. The body thus made known to me is my own sen- 
 sitive organism. This much is given by sense. If no more 
 
 1 The origin of the notion of space is much discussed by recent psycholo- 
 gists. Is the knowledge of extension and its determinations, length, breadth, 
 thickness or distance, position, form, etc., inborn or derived from experience? 
 Many theories have been proposed, classified by Helmholtz as native and 
 empirical. Empiricists hold that knowledge of extension comes through 
 experience from elements that have no spatial form, either by deduction 
 from them (Herbart), or by a transforming power of association (Bam). 
 Nativists maintain that knowledge of space cannot originate in data of con- 
 sciousness which are merely intensive, and that it is an original datum, 
 native, innate. Nativism is divided into nativism of product (Kant) and 
 nativism of process (Lotze, Wundt). The latter is well expressed thus : 
 ' ' The mind has a native and original capacity of reacting upon certain phys- 
 ical data in such a way that the objects of its activity appear under the 
 form of space." — Baldwin, Psychology, p. 121. See also Ribot, German 
 Psychology of To-day, ch. 4. The doctrine of the present treatise might be 
 classed as nativism of process, differing, however, from the foregoing, and 
 holding that on an empirical occasion, i.e. a sense presentation, the pure 
 intellect has native power to discern space, time, and other non-sensuous 
 realities. Our views are given below, in chs. 6, 7. 
 
102 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 than this, I could never know even of the existence of an 
 outer world of things. But my limbs are framed for loco- 
 motion by voluntary muscular energy. Herein is a new 
 experience, a new immediate cognition. I am conscious of 
 an effort, of a nisus or striving to overcome a resistance.^ In 
 the muscular sense-perceptions that follow it, I am conscious 
 that the resistance yields, that is, I am conscious of inertia 
 overcome. This is a consciousness of motion.^ 
 
 In this experience I am not merely a patient, but also an 
 agent. My nervous organism is herein cognized, not as 
 merely affecting me, but as a means, subject to my will, by 
 which I affect something else. In this positive activity, in 
 this consciousness of being a cause, I immediately cognize 
 the effect on something opposed to and distinct from my 
 organism, on some outer thing resisting the action. Thus, in 
 the exercise of locomotive energ}'-, I become aware of the 
 existence and properties of material tilings outside of my 
 organism.^ 
 
 Hence it appears that the primary knowledge of extra- 
 organic body, or in general, of an outer world, depends, not 
 
 1 Accordiug to "Wundt there are two distinct elements involved in volun- 
 tary movements of the muscles : first, a feeling of effort, and second, a feel- 
 ing of resistance. The feeling of effort arises from the expenditure of nervous 
 energy at the centres, and is called also feeling of innervation. The feeling 
 of resistance, on the other hand, seems to have its seat in the muscle atlected. 
 It is the sense of opposition to muscular movement, and is connected with 
 sensations of pressure. — Theorie der Sinneswahrnehmung, p, 376 sq. See 
 Baldwin, Psychology, p. 89. 
 
 2 "That a thing is movable cannot be known a priori, but only from ex- 
 perience." — Kant, C. P. li., p. 95, note. 
 
 3 "When I am conscious," says Hamilton, "of the exertion of an cnor- 
 ganic volition to move, and am aware that the muscles are obedient to my 
 will, but at the same time aware that my limb is arrested in its motion by 
 some impediment, — in this case I cannot be conscious of myself as the 
 resisted relative without at the same time being conscious, being immediately 
 percipient, of a not-self as the resisting correlative. ... In the conscious- 
 ness of being thus resisted is involved, as a correlative, the consciousness of 
 a resisting something external to my organism." — In Jieid, note D* (pp. 
 866, 882). 
 
EXTERNAL REALITY. 103 
 
 on the relation in which it stands to perception by the senses, 
 but to volition. Voluntary energy is the source of this 
 knowledge ; the muscular sense, only the secondary and pos- 
 sibly the contingent accompaniment.^ 
 
 § 106. When a limb, moved by volition, encounters an 
 exterior obstacle, I could not, probably, by the combination 
 of volition with muscular sense alone, distinguish between 
 the limb and the obstacle. But since such encounter involves 
 contact with the skin, the sense of touch co-operates with 
 these, and enables me to make the distinction. By the triple 
 combination, then, I discriminate between my own frame and 
 foreign bodies. The mechanism of the hand and arm is 
 peculiarly fitted for the exercise of this combination. B}^ 
 manipulation or handling I ascertain the shape and many 
 other qualities of things. By this I learn the shape of my 
 own body, distinguishing between it and foreign bodies 
 by virtue of the double touch which it affords. Manifestly, 
 the experience is quite different when I clasp my hands, and 
 when I grasp the hand of another person. 
 
 It appears, then, in general, that we have an immediate 
 perception, not merely of a material non-ego, but further, of 
 extra-organic body, and that the existence of an outer world 
 of things is a fact of consciousness. 
 
 § 107. The order in which the senses and their percepts 
 
 1 "Supposing all muscular feeling abolished (the power of moving the 
 muscles remaining, however, entire), I hold that the consciousness of the 
 mental motive energy, and of the greater or less degree of such energy re- 
 quisite, in different circumstances, to accomplish our intention, would of itself 
 enable us always to perceive the fact, and in some degree to measure the 
 amount, of any resistance to our voluntary movements ; howbeit, the con- 
 comitance of certain feelings with the different states of muscular tension 
 renders this cognition not only easier, but, in fact, obtrudes it upon our 
 attention." — Hamilton, in Reid, note D (p. 8G4). He does not, however, 
 attribute any special percept to muscular sense (§ 27) apart from that given 
 in voluntary movement. And this is very generally true of the more recent 
 psychologists. 
 
104 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 have been discussed must not be thought of as the natural 
 order of development. Of this nothing lias been said. The 
 elements of the discussion have been obtained by logical 
 analysis, and recombined in logical order. Any attempted 
 synthesis in natural order would be largely conjectural. The 
 processes have mostly occurred at a period too early to be 
 remembered, some of them probably m utero} As we know 
 not how the bones do grow in the womb, so we know not 
 how the mind proceeds in its development. Only the 
 matured consciousness is capable of introspection, and it 
 finds its percepts already bound up with acquisitions into a 
 complexus that is almost inexplicable, and that completely 
 defies the most skilful analyist to tell how it was woven. 
 
 It is, however, worthy of remark that the combination of 
 the tactile sense with the muscular sense under the influence 
 of volition, seems to be an important condition of the deveb 
 opment of the cognitive intelligence. With the other senses 
 only, we would be forever shut up to a knowledge of self in 
 oj)position to a few sensorial phenomena. But the combina- 
 tion named introduces us to the universe. Men are some- 
 times born destitute of smell, taste, hearing, sight, but never, 
 perhaps, of the tactile and muscular senses. Defects of 
 sense, such as actually occur, consist with a limited intelli- 
 gence, but it is inconceivable how intelligence, even of a low 
 brute form, could arise in a being deprived of tactile and - 
 muscular sense, or, indeed, if all the senses were perfect and 
 volitional power over the muscles were wanting. 
 
 1 Miillor (see § 44) very plausibly speculates as follows : " The uterus 
 which compels the child to assume a determined position, and gives rise to 
 sensations in it, is also the means of exciting in the sensorium of the child 
 the consciousness of something thus distinct from itself, and external to it. 
 The child governs the movements of its limbs, and thus perceives that they 
 are instruments subject to the use and government of its internal self ; while 
 the resistance which it meets with around is not subject to its will, and there- 
 fore gives it the idea of an absolute exterior. In this way is gained the idea 
 of an external viovld."" — Physiology, p. 1080, Baly's tr. 
 
SELF-PERCEPTION. 105 
 
 CHAPTER V. 
 
 SELF-PEECEPTION. 
 
 § 108. The specific power of mind next in order after per- 
 ception is self-perception. Self-perception is the immediate 
 cognition of a subjective object. Consciousness is sometimes 
 defined as the immediate knowledge of our mental actions 
 and affections. If this were correct, there would be no dif- 
 ference between consciousness and self-perception. But con- 
 sciousness is much more than this ; it is general, it attends 
 all our mental activities, it is their common characteristic, 
 every mental state is in itself a conscious state ; whereas self- 
 perception is only one special mode or modification of the 
 cognitive consciousness, and might fairly be defined as the 
 consciousness of a subject-object. 
 
 This power is sometimes called the internal sense, and we 
 shall find it convenient to use the term sense thus generi- 
 cally, as including both perception and self-perception, the 
 external and the internal sense, these being our faculties of 
 cognitive experience, or empirical intuition. 
 
 § 109. The distinction between self-perception and self- 
 consciousness is refined, but real and important. It will be 
 remembered that we resolved consciousness into the subjec- 
 tive phase feeling, and the objective phase cognition (§ 71). 
 According to this view the term self-consciousness is appro- 
 priate to the subjective j)hase, but not to the faculty we are 
 considering, since this is distinctly objective. True, its object 
 is always subjective, always a mode of self, but it is a mode 
 of self objectified. 
 
 We may illustrate the distinction thus : I am beholding a 
 
106 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 color, let us say the blue of tlie sky. I consciously perceive 
 the color, or am conscious of perceiving the color, or am con- 
 scious of the color. This is perception. It is objective, for 
 it relates directly to an object. Now the subjective correla- 
 tive of perception is sensation, which is not a mode of cogni- 
 tion, but of feeling, and in and by virtue of the sensation 
 only am I conscious tliat it is I who perceive. This is self- 
 consciousness. I may, however, objectify a mental state. I 
 may contemplate it as though it were apart, a thing distinct . 
 from me, yet known to be a mode of self. To do so is an act 
 of cognition, is a consciousness of an object, though it is, 
 indeed, a subjective object. This is self-perception. 
 
 § 110. Cognition is either presentative or representative. 
 Presentative or intuitive cognition is either empirical or pure. 
 Empirical intuition is distributed as perception and self-per- 
 ception, the one relating to external, the other to internal ex- 
 periences (§ 76). Hence the latter might fairly be defined 
 as the consciousness of a subjective empirical intuition. By 
 perception we have intuitive knowledge of matter ; by self- 
 perception we have intuitive knowledge of mind. The ob- 
 jects of perception are conditioned on and presented in time 
 and space. The objects of self-perception are conditioned on 
 and presented in time and self. Space is peculiar to the one, 
 self to the other. Time is common. 
 
 § 111. The subjective object is really identical with the ego, 
 is a mere modification of mind, but still the mind distinguishes 
 it as an accident, as a mode from self. By an original con- 
 stitutional power, I, the subject of that accident, project, as it 
 were, my own act or state from myself, objectify it. view it as 
 a phenomenon. A difference in the character of the objects 
 thus presented authorizes a distinction of two varieties of self- 
 perception, introspection, and reflection. 
 
 Let us exemplify the first. I am angr}^ and I am conscious 
 of it, or rather it is a conscious state. But perhaps my cogni- 
 
SELF-PER CEPTION. 107 
 
 tive powers are fully occupied by the object that angers me ; 
 then, though there is subjective consciousness of anger, there 
 is no cognitive introspection of it. Now some one asks me : 
 Are you angry ? An introspective glance, a momentary objec- 
 tification of my state while it still exists, an instant of self- 
 perception, and the state is cognized and recognized, and I 
 answer : Yes. So any present mental state not representative, 
 as a perception, a feeling, a desire, a choice, an effort, may be 
 cognized, may become the direct object of introspection. 
 It is by this power of introspection that we are hereafter 
 to study the phenomena of feeling, desire, and volition. 
 
 § 112. The other kind of self-perception is reflection. 
 Reflection has already been distinguished from observation 
 as attention to an internal object (§ 84). It is distinguished 
 from introspection b}^ the specific character of its object. The 
 direct object of reflection is a mental image, such a one as I 
 now form of a centaur, of the moon, of a strain of music, of 
 the odor of violets, of my past anger, or of any object of past 
 experience, external or internal. This image is itself a mere 
 mode of mind, for it cannot be distinguished from the act of 
 cognition. Since it is subjective, \&t at the same time the 
 object of cognition, a mode of self objectified, it is a specific 
 object of self-perception, the immediate object of reflection. 
 
 The image is an object unlike the object of introspection. 
 The latter is not, whereas the former is, representative. The 
 object of introspection is complete in itself, being merely pre- 
 sentative ; whereas the object of reflection, the image is 
 incomplete in itself, being not merely presentative, but also 
 representative of some other, of some remote, object; and 
 this of necessity, for no act of cognition can terminate on 
 itself. 
 
 Since reflection is, therefore, always an element of repre- 
 sentative or mediate knowledge, the further consideration of 
 it is postponed to Part III. 
 
108 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 CHAPTER VI. 
 
 PURE INTUITION. 
 
 § 113. Knowledge must have an ultimate basis. By a 
 thorough analysis of our cognitions we must finally come to 
 primitive truths beyond which we cannot and need not go. 
 These primary cognitions are simple facts of consciousness. 
 As merely given, they are presentative ; as free from any 
 intervention, they are immediate ; as seen face to face, they 
 are intuitive. 
 
 As a molecule or ultimate particle of water, one which 
 cannot be resolved into constituent aqueous particles, is capa- 
 ble nevertheless of resolution into two impalpable gaseous 
 elements of opposite character, so every fact of conscious- 
 ness, though ultimate as a fact, is susceptible of analysis into 
 at. least two constituent and essential elements, the one sen- 
 suous, the other intellectual. That which is contributed to 
 the total presentation or intuition by sense external or inter- 
 nal, by perception or self-perception, is sensuous, and being 
 the element of experience, is called the empirical intuition. 
 The datum of intellect, it being not at all sensuous, is called, 
 negatively, the pure intuition. The union of the two is 
 essential to the total and single cognitive fact, but by logical 
 abstraction either may be contemplated apart from the other. 
 
 Although neither of these intuitive elements can be actu- 
 ally realized in consciousness apart from tlie other, still, in 
 the logical analysis of the mental acts, they are assigned to 
 different faculties. The empirical intuition is exercised by 
 sense strictly taken, either by perception or by self-perception. 
 The pure intuition is exercised by pure intellect or reason. ^ 
 
 1 This name of the faculty, pure reason, or simply reason, recalls the 
 Platonic distinction lutwcen the uituitive reason, voOs, and the discursive 
 
PURE INTUITION. 109 
 
 The objects cognized by pure reason are called pure or a jjriori 
 intuitions, ideas, notions, principles, and pure or necessary 
 truths. Accordingl3% pure intuition may be defined as the 
 immediate cognition b}^ pure reason of a pure idea or neces- 
 sary truth.i 
 
 § 114. Let ns consider some examples of pure intuition. 
 Whatever I am conscious of is always given along with the 
 notion of its existence, i.e. it is, it exists here and now. 
 Every act of consciousness is thus an affirmation of the exist- 
 ence of a thing ; for we are conscious only as we apprehend 
 a thing, and we apprehend it only as we affirm it to exist ; 
 hence existence must be attributed to the thing by the mind.^ 
 Now existence itself is not an object of sense, but of pure 
 intuition. Every object of sense, however, is attended by 
 this idea, and each immediate cognition, therefore, is made 
 up of a presented sensuous experience of a thing, comple- 
 mented by a pure intellectual intuition of its existence. 
 
 When phenomena of mind or of matter, subjective or ob- 
 jective, occur in succession, it is evident that the cognition 
 implies, in the concrete, the cognition of time. Now what is 
 time ? It is not an object of perception ; we can neither see 
 it, nor hear it, nor handle it, nor is it a mode of mind. It is 
 simple, not being capable of resolution, and as a last product 
 
 reason, didvoia, running to and fro. Let us, then, not confuse reason with to 
 reason or reasoning. The one is a faculty, giving immediate insight, the 
 other is a logical process. Kant used the name pure reason, die reine Ver- 
 nunft, followed by Jacobi and the German thinkers generally. As reason is 
 opposed to the logical faculty, so pure is opposed to sensuous. Hamilton 
 calls pure reason ' ' the regulative faculty,' ' but doubts if it be properly a 
 faculty. Other names have been used and abused. 
 
 1 The nomenclature of the subject is remarkably varied and unsettled. 
 See Hamilton's famous note A, in Reid^ § 5, for a historical and critical 
 examination of the multitude of synonyms used ; cf. Meta., p. 514. For the 
 use of a priori and a posteriori by Kant, as distinctive of pure and empirical 
 cognitions, see § 50, note. 
 
 2 Existence, ens, is commonly viewed by philosophers as the prinucm cog- 
 nitiim. 
 
110 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 of analysis it is ultimate. It is indefinable and incomprehen- 
 sible, not being referable to any more general idea. Yet 
 every human mind has knowledge of time, and needs only 
 that the meaning of the word be pointed out in order to 
 make the simple analysis that abstracts the pure idea, and 
 clearly apprehends it apart. 
 
 Again, when I am conscious of body, which is a sensuous 
 experience, there is implied an apprehension of space. Now 
 what is space ? It is not an object of sense. Yet as an idea 
 original, simple, clear, and incomprehensible, it is in posses- 
 sion of every one. 
 
 When I am conscious of a change in phenomena, either 
 subjective or objective, I apprehend there must be some cause 
 of the change. Now in this proposition change is a sensu- 
 ous element, it is a conception which can be derived only 
 from experience. But what of causation? This idea is not 
 sensuous, but pure, not derived from experience, common 
 to all minds, primary, indefinable, presentative, immediate, 
 intuitive. 
 
 In general, then, these pure elements of cognition are not 
 given by, yet always attend, or are evoked by, sensuous 
 experience. I have no proper experience of them, they are 
 not empirical. Separated by abstraction from their empiri- 
 cal accompaniments, they are distinguished as pure intuitions, 
 or pure ideas. 
 
 Other examples are the idea of substance, of unity, of 
 identity, the law of contradiction, the idea of right, and of 
 infinity. 
 
 § 115. The characteristics of these pure ideas and principles 
 are now to be considered. 
 
 They are abstract. The pure or a priori, and the empiri- 
 cal or a posteriori, elements are always originall}^ conjoined, 
 and indeed, without the union of the two, no cognition is 
 possible. Since the pure elements actually occur only in 
 this concrete combination, it requires analysis by abstraction 
 
PUEE INTUITION. Ill 
 
 to effect their logical separation. Qualities of things, such as 
 tall, strong, brave, honest, which cannot actually exist apart 
 from the things, have assigned to them by abstraction a logi- 
 cal independence, as expressed by the abstract terms height, 
 strength, courage, honesty. So the pure elements of cogni- 
 tion, which, though not qualities, yet are actual only in the 
 concrete, have a similar logical independence given them, as 
 expressed by the abstract terms time, place, substance, cau- 
 sation, etc. 
 
 Complete cognition does not require this analytic abstrac- 
 tion. Actually an intuition consists of pure and empirical 
 elements in the concrete. Only by thinkers is the pure ele- 
 ment clearly discerned, and set apart as an abstract idea. The 
 chief difference is that so long as it is in the concrete, the 
 pure element is limited, by the connection in which it stands, 
 to that individual case ; whereas, when taken abstractly, then 
 its strict universality appears. 
 
 § 116. They are catholic ; that is, they exist in every human 
 mind, even the most ignorant, the most immature. Any one 
 bearing of a murder will ask : When ? Where ? Why ? Where- 
 fore? These inquiries imply the pure ideas of time, place, 
 efficient cause, and final cause. Every one regards murder 
 as a crime. This implies the intuitive distinction between 
 right and wrong.^ 
 
 The catholicity of the pure elements of cognition is with- 
 out limit. Manifestly the vulgar mind is regulated by such 
 ideas and principles, and though it does not usually explicate 
 them, still, did they not exist, the simplest knowledge would 
 be impossible. 
 
 § 117. They are self-evident. Many of the pure intuitions 
 may be expressed in propositions instead of single terms, and 
 perhaps some require this form. U.f^. : A whole equals the sum 
 of its parts; Every event is caused ; Benevolence is right, etc. 
 
 1 See Cousin, Le Vrai, U Beau, et le Bien, p. 41. 
 
112 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 In this form they are called principles, axioms, first truths, 
 transcendental truths, constitutive and regulative trutlis, 
 primary laws, etc. These are self-evidently true ; they have 
 in themselves original authority. 
 
 That a thing cannot both be and not be, is a proposition 
 which the human mind can neither deny nor doubt. Yet it 
 has no guarantee, it reposes on nothing beyond itself, it is 
 merely self-evident. That the three angles of a triangle are 
 together equal to two right-angles, is not self-evident, though 
 it may be clearly, positively, and with certainty demonstrated ; 
 for its truth is not seen without proof, without reference to 
 principles. But that two straight lines cannot enclose an 
 area, does not require, and indeed is incapable of proof ; it 
 cannot be deduced or inferred, it has the light of truth in 
 itself and needs not to borrow. Such principles or first truths 
 are the primary ultimate premises of all demonstrated truth.^ 
 
 § 118. They are certain ; that is, their truth being uncon- 
 ditional or absolute, a doubt of it cannot exist. Absolute 
 truthfulness and self-evidence are the negative and positive 
 views of the same thing. Attending it is the feeling of 
 entire and immovable certainty. Says Aristotle : " It is not 
 only necessary that we should be endowed with an antece- 
 dent knowledge of first principles, but also that this knowl- 
 edge should be of paramount certainty. For, whatever com- 
 nuuiicates a quality to other things, must itself possess that 
 quality in a still higher degree, as that on account of which 
 we love all objects that partake of it, cannot but be itself 
 pre-eminently an object of our love. Hence, if we know and 
 
 1 Self-evidence is the first of Bufficr's essential qualities of primary truths. 
 "The first of these characters is tliat they be so clear that when one under- 
 takes to prove them, or to disprove them, he can do it only by propositions 
 which manifestly are neither more clear, nor more certain." — Traite des Pre- 
 mieres Veritps (a.d. 1717). His was perhaps the first comprehensive attempt 
 to found philosophy on primary truths. 
 
 It was a principle with Descartes that " all things which we may clearly 
 and distinctly (chn'ro H distinctc) conceive are true." — 0« Method, pt. iv. 
 
PURE INTUITION. 113 
 
 believe through first principles, we must know and believe 
 these themselves in a superlative degree, for the very reason 
 that we know and believe all secondary truths through 
 them."i 
 
 § 119. A primary fact, a fact of consciousness as a whole, 
 was likewise found to be self-evident and certain (§§ 67, 69). 
 These characteristics, therefore, will not serve to distinguish 
 the pure element from the empirical matter with which it is 
 combined. A criterion is needful to mark the distinction, 
 and it is found in the necessity which specifically character- 
 izes the objects of pure intuition. 
 
 A j)ure idea or truth is necessary ; one involving empirical 
 matter is contingent. That is contingent of which I can at 
 least conceive that it need not be ; that is necessary of which 
 I cannot conceive that it need not be, or, positively, of which 
 I must conceive, not merely that it is, but that it must be. 
 Facts of experience are such as are themselves possible, and 
 whose opposites also are possible ; they are such as are liable 
 to occur, yet may not ; they are incidental and casual and 
 dependent on circumstances or choice ; in a word, they are 
 contingent. But pure truth has no negative alternative in 
 any case ; it is in no manner or measure whatever reversible 
 in thought; I cannot but think it; the opposite is incon- 
 ceivable ; in a word, it is necessary .^ 
 
 For example : In analj^zing any cognition whatever, I find 
 
 1 Anal. Post., i, 2, § 16. 
 
 2 Necessity as opposed to contingency is of two kinds. The certainty that 
 attends a present fact of consciousness (§ 69) comes of the necessity I am 
 under of cognizing it as actually existing. Still this actuality of existence is 
 merely accidental. When it is not present, but is contemplated through a 
 representative idea, this necessity disappears ; there is no necessity that I 
 should think it to be, or that it should be ; it may or may not be, it is wholly 
 contingent. But in case of a datum of pure intuition, I am necessitated to 
 think not merely that it is, but that it necessarily js. When it is not present, 
 but represented through a pure idea, this necessity remains. It is this sort 
 of double necessity that differentiates the object of pure intuition. Hence we 
 call it specifically a pure and necessary idea. 
 
114 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEUaE. 
 
 always this fact of consciousness, self-existence, I am. Now 
 in this duad the element self is contingent. While in fact I 
 do exist, my existence is not at all necessary. I am a mere 
 accident in the universe, my presence therein is not essential, 
 and my annihilation is quite as conceivable as my creation. 
 But the other term of the duad, the idea existence, is not at 
 all contingent, it is necessary. I cannot conceive of a non- 
 existent; whatever I conceive is necessarily conceived as 
 existing. So the primary datum of consciousness, I am, con- 
 sists of two elements, one empirical, one jDure. 
 
 Another example : That body is heavy is a judgment a pos- 
 teriori, a synthesis from experience. Now though my expe- 
 rience of weight in connection with body has been invariable, 
 without ever an exception, yet the judgment is contingent, it 
 may or may not be. I can easily conceive of a body having 
 no weight. Indeed, until recently, a class of imponderables 
 was recognized by physicists. But that bod}^ occupies space 
 is not given by experience, is not an empirical fact or judg- 
 ment, but an analytic judgment a priori, a pure intuition. 
 For while we have experience of body as heavy, we have no 
 experience by any sense that it occupies space, since no sense 
 is percipient of space. Yet this judgment is self-evidently 
 true ; it is not at all contingent, it is necessary. We cannot 
 conceive of body not occupying space ; that it does occupy 
 space must of necessity be true.^ 
 
 § 120. Furthermore, "an empirical judgment never ex- 
 hibits strict and absolute, but only assumed and comparative, 
 
 1 See Kant's celebrated analysis of judgments, C. P. R., Int., § 4. The 
 distinction between necessary and contingent truth can be traced to Aris- 
 totle. Descartes uses necessity as a criterion in many places. E.cf. : " This 
 proposition, I am, I exist, is 7ierp,sfinrn)j true." Again : "T now admit noth- 
 ing that is not necessarily true." — Meditations, ii. Yet again : "Though 
 certain general objects, as bodies, be imaginary, we are nevertheless abso- 
 lutely necessitated to admit the reality of, at least some other objects still 
 more simple and universal than these." — Id., i. It was, however, first ex- 
 plicitly enounced as a criterion by Leibnitz, and used systematically and 
 efficiently by Kant in his Kritik der reinen Vernunft. 
 
PURE lyTUITION. 115 
 
 universality. Therefore, the most we can say is, so far as we 
 have hitherto observed, there is no exception to tliis or that 
 rule. If, on the other hand, a judgment carries with it strict 
 and absolute universality, that is, admits of no possible excep- 
 tions, it is not derived from experience, but is valid abso- 
 lutely a priori. Necessity and strict universality, therefore, 
 are infallible tests for distinguishing pure from empirical 
 knowledge, and are inseparably connected with each other. 
 But as in the use of these criteria, the unlimited universality 
 which we attach to a judgment is often a more convincing 
 proof than its necessity, it may be advisable to use the criteria 
 separately, each being by itself infallible." ^ 
 
 It is manifest that necessity and strict universality are the 
 same thing in different aspects ; for when a truth is necessary, 
 it is eo ipso universal, and that a truth is strictly universal is 
 an unerring index that it is necessary. Hence neither is to 
 be considered as secondary, or as subsidiary to, or as derived 
 from the other. Both are named, because sometimes the one 
 is more easily applied as a test, sometimes the other. 
 
 § 121. In connection with the characteristic of strict uni- 
 versality, it should be particularly observed that general 
 truth is of three distinct kinds : — 
 
 First, a mere logical generality is attained when we think, 
 within the limits of experience, the similar to be the same. 
 Thus : All the members of my class are studious : Every day 
 I find a duty; Each of the States has two senators. This 
 generalization is an artifice or fiction of intellect, a fictitious 
 means of giving order and compactness to knowledge, and 
 thus bringing it within grasp. 
 
 Second, by the hazard of induction, truth is extended 
 beyond the limits of actual experience, and declared general 
 or universal. Thus : Every particle of matter attracts every 
 other particle ; Day always succeeds night ; No one is per- 
 
 1 From Critique of Pure Reason., Int., § 1. 
 
116 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 fectly content. This, however, is only an empirical, inductive, 
 and precarious universality. Exceptions may actually, or at 
 least conceivably, occur. 
 
 Third, pure truth also is said to be general, but this gener- 
 ality is attained neither by generalization, nor by induction. 
 When we have abstracted the pure element, we immediately 
 cognize it as absolutely universal, true always and everywhere. 
 Every rule derived from experience has actual, possible, or at 
 least conceivable exceptions ; a rule given by pure reason has 
 no exception, it is without the conceivable possibility of an 
 exception, past, present, or future, in all the univei'se of things. 
 Such truth transcends the limits of possible experience, and 
 has unlimited, universal validity. Thus : Space is infinite ; 
 An attribute and a being exist only as they coexist ; Contra- 
 dictory attributes cannot coexist ; I ought to be truthful. 
 As has already been said, most persons do not abstract and 
 formulate these primitive a priori cognitions. Nevertheless, 
 their strict universality is practically, though obscurely, appre- 
 hended, which is evident from the unhesitating use of them 
 in each particular case ; and likewise their necessity, as is 
 shown by the confident assertion that such and such a thing 
 must be so, it would be nonsense to speak otherwise. The 
 thinker disengages them, and sets the abstract and universal 
 forms clear in consciousness. This, however, is not to consti- 
 tute, nor to derive, nor to generalize them ; but only to 
 discern them. They leap ready armed from the womb of 
 reason, like Pallas from the head of Zeus. 
 
 § 122. The catholicity just referred to must also be distin- 
 guislied from universality. The one means that the pure 
 intuitions are, potentially at least, in every human mind ; the 
 other, that they are universally true, always and everywhere, 
 even should all mind cease to be. That pure truths are com- 
 mon to all mankind is simply a consequence of their own 
 inherent necessity and universality. 
 
 On the other hand, because a judgment is common, it does 
 
PURE INTUITION. 117 
 
 not follow that tlierefere it is a pure truth. All men once 
 held that the sun revolves around the earth ; and that a body 
 cannot act where it is not. This last, indeed, has much the 
 appearance of an intuitive, axiomatic, necessary truth, but 
 falsely assumes that body acts only by contact.^ That all 
 men judge so and so, is not a guarantee of truth of any sort ; 
 but when a truth is intuitive, this is a sure guarantee that all 
 men think accordingly. 
 
 § 123. Many attempts have been made to classify pure 
 intuitions, but none has been generally approved. It is con- 
 ceded that Kant's system of categories is a failure. These 
 ideas are so subtle, so mutually interwoven, so evasive aud 
 pervasive, that they seem to defy distinct enumeration and 
 articulate arrangement. We can hardly divest them com- 
 pletely of empirical matter, and in cases where thought 
 succeeds in this, language fails to express them in pure 
 nakedness. They appear to be numerous ; but could we fix 
 the naked truths, each by a suitable sign, it might greatly 
 reduce their apparent number, and enable us to classify them. 
 We shall not attempt a classification, nor discuss them in 
 detail. Indeed, not much can be said about them. Their 
 light, says McCosh, is like that of the sun, which darkens as 
 we gaze on it. They behave like Macbeth 's witches. " When 
 I burned in desire to question them further, they made them- 
 selves — air, into which they vanished." 
 
 1 This reminds us that Newton, it is said, was sorely perplexed by the 
 notion of gravity, being unwilling to admit the possibility of action at a 
 distance, which Faraday also rejected as an impossible conception. Should 
 not these eminent physicists have admitted it as a fact revealed by nature, 
 as ultimate and therefore incomprehensible ? 
 
118 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 CHAPTER VII. 
 
 ORIGIN OF PURE TRUTH. 
 
 § 124. A close consideration of the origin of pure ideas 
 and principles reveals many difficulties. Psychologists and 
 metaphysicians entertain various opinions respecting it, and 
 just here engage in such fierce and endless controversies, that 
 the ground we now venture upon is fairly termed campus 
 philosojyhorum. The questions in debate may be stated thus : 
 Does the knowledge of pure truth originate within or with- 
 out ? is it innate or adventitious ? Is the object ideal, or has 
 the pure idea a corresponding reality in nature ? If real, is 
 that reality itself intuitively known, or is it known only 
 through a representative idea ? These are difficult questions. 
 The first alone offers room for wide divergence. The history 
 of opinions, touching the acceptance or rejection of such 
 notions as native, is, in a manner, the history of philosophy ; 
 for as the one alternative or the other is adopted in this 
 question, the character of a system is determined. The cliief 
 parties to this primary form of the controvers}^ are empiricists 
 who deny, and intuitionists who affirm, the innate or sub- 
 jective origin and character of the pure intuitions. 
 
 § 125. Modern empiricism has Locke for its founder. He 
 maintained an old aphorism, traceable to the Stoics, that there 
 is nothing in intellect that was not previously in sense. "/>i 
 intelleetu nihil est, quod non prius fuerit in sensu.^' To sup- 
 port their doctrine, the Stoics had seized upon a passage in 
 Aristotle, in which intellect prior to experience is compared 
 to a tablet on which nothing has been actually written, a 
 
ORIGIN OF PURE TRUTH. 119 
 
 " tabula rasa" ^ This also Locke adopted, and the two have 
 since been the favorite text and formuhx of his followers. 
 
 His doctrine he states as follows : " Whence hath mind all 
 the materials of reason and knowledge? To this I answer 
 in one word, from experience ; in that all our knowledge is 
 founded, and from that ultimately derives itself. Our obser- 
 vation employed either about external sensible objects, or 
 about the internal operations of our minds, perceived and 
 reflected on by ourselves, is that which supplies our under- 
 standing with all the materials of thinking. These are the 
 fountains of knowledge from whence all the ideas we have, 
 or can naturally have, do spring, that is, sensation and 
 reflection." ^ 
 
 Empiricism has found many able advocates, but none 
 stronger than J. S. INIilL His avowal of it is very distinct. 
 " It remains to inquire," says he, " what is the ground of 
 our belief in axioms, what is the evidence on which they 
 rest ? I answer, they are experimental truths, generalizations 
 from observation. The proposition : Two straight lines can- 
 not enclose a space, is an induction from the evidence of our 
 senses." 3 He finds necessity or inconceivability to consist 
 either in invincible association, or in that a logical contra- 
 diction is meaningless. 
 
 1 De Anima, iii, 4, § 14. The context seems inconsistent with the infer- 
 ence that Aristotle favored empiricism. 
 
 2 Essay on the Human Understanding, bk. ii, ch. 1. Condillac and others 
 of the French philosophers rejected reflection as a distinct source of knowl- 
 edge, and their doctrine, to distinguish it from that of Locke, is called sensa- 
 tionalism. What Locke means by reflection is obscure, and has been the 
 subject of much debate. 
 
 3 Logic, bk. ii, ch. 5, § 4. See also his Ex. of Hamilton's Phil., ch. 6. 
 " Two and two may be five in some other world," he says. Herbert Spencer 
 sharply criticises Mill's views in Principles of Psychology, § 426 sq. He 
 maintains the "universal postulate" that "cognitions of which the predi- 
 cates invariably exist along with their subjects express a necessary relation 
 in consciousness, and have the highest possible certainty." To his criticism 
 Mill replies in the eighth edition of his Logic. See addendum to bk. ii, 
 ch. 7, § 4 sq. 
 
120 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 Thus the empirical philosophy denies all a priori cognition 
 of truth, all purely intuitive ideas and princij)les. It denies 
 that the intellect is itself a source of knowledge, and that 
 there is any essential distinction between contingent and 
 necessary truth. It holds that sensuous experience is the 
 origin and sole basis of all knowledge, and that necessity 
 arises only because of an experience that is invariable, and 
 hence invincible in thought. Logically and historically, em- 
 piricism results in materialism ; its more immediate offspring 
 is sensationalism or sensualism.^ 
 
 § 126. A reply to empiricism, denying the sufficiency of 
 experience and insisting that the distinction between con- 
 tingent and necessary truth is essential, is as follows : Expe- 
 rience, even invariable experience,, however large, cannot 
 establish necessit}^ That the sun moves westward is our 
 invariable experience, yet it is not conceived as necessary, 
 but as contingent, for however improbable an exception, one 
 is easily conceivable.^ On the other hand, experience is not 
 requisite to necessity. That two intersecting circles have 
 two and only two points in common, is a truth which does 
 not require any specific experience in order to command 
 assent, and which is conceived not at all as contingent, but 
 as necessary. It must be so in ever}^ case, ahvays and every- 
 where. An exception is absolutely inconceivable, and would 
 be more than a miracle.^ There is, therefore, an essential 
 difference in such conceptions, indicating a different origin. 
 
 Let us argue the distinction more articulately. The 
 proposition. Every change is caused, is, saj^s the empiricist, 
 an induction from experience. But it cannot be so for these 
 reasons : — 
 
 ' Tornied contemptuously by Fichte, "the dirt philosophy." 
 
 2 E.g. the dial of Ahaz. — 2 Kings 20: 11. 
 
 8 This strong expression is used advisedly. Infinite power may cause the 
 sun to retrograde, or may quicken the dead, but cannot make a thing to be 
 and not be, cannot reconcile contradictories. The infinite is limited. 
 
ORIGIN OF PURE TRUTH. 121 
 
 First: An empirical judgment is not necessary. Experi- 
 ence tells us only what actually is, not what must be. The 
 most ample evidence from observation that each change does 
 actually have a cause would never prove that change must 
 have a cause. Induction from experience reveals the estab- 
 lished laws of nature, but can never discover what connec- 
 tions of things are necessary. 
 
 But this judgment is necessary. It is not that changes 
 commonly have a cause, or even that they always in fact do 
 have a cause, but that they must have a cause, and cannot 
 possibly occur without a cause. 
 
 Therefore, this judgment is not empirical. ^ 
 
 Second : An empirical judgment is not strictly universal. 
 It can have only a degree of probability proportioned to our 
 experience, and is always so understood as to leave room for 
 exceptions, if future experience shall discover any. The law 
 of gravitation, that every particle of matter in the universe 
 attracts every other particle, has as full proof from experi- 
 ence and induction as any empirical truth can be supposed to 
 have, yet physicists have supposed the existence of imponder- 
 able bodies. Such universality, then, is not strict, but haz- 
 ardous, precarious, probable perhaps in a very high degree, 
 but liable to exceptions that are at least conceivably pos- 
 sible. 
 
 But this judgment is strictly universal. Neither philoso- 
 phers nor the vulgar have ever considered the principle as 
 one admitting limitation or the possibility of exception. 
 They consider that it must always have been true, must now 
 be true, must always hereafter be true, in every case through- 
 out the universe. 
 
 Therefore, this judgment is not empirical. 
 
 Third: An induction must have sufficient grounds in 
 experience. Unless the principle of causation now before us 
 be itself involved in the proof, it requires a very thorough 
 experience of very many cases to justify an induction of a 
 general truth, and this is the most hazardous form of indue- 
 
122 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 tion. But it is obvious that the principle cannot be used in 
 proof of itself. Hence if it be an induction, it can be so only 
 through much experience of it. 
 
 But this judgment has not sufficient grounds in experience. 
 The causes of by far the greater part of the few changes in 
 nature that fall within our observation are wholly unknown, 
 and therefore our experience does not inform us whether 
 they have causes or not. Indeed, causation is not an object 
 of external sense. The only actual experience we have of it 
 is in the consciousness of an energy in ordering our thoughts 
 and actions. Surely this is insufficient ground for the gen- 
 eral conclusion that every change in the universe that has 
 been or shall be must have a cause. 
 
 Therefore, this judgment is not inductive.^ 
 
 § 127. The opposed intuitional philosophy, in its modern 
 phase, originated with Descartes. " Of ideas," says he, 
 "some appear to me to be innate, others adventitious, and 
 others to be made by myself." ^ Leibnitz expounded and 
 defended it more fully. He controverted Locke's Essay in 
 a work bearing a like title,^ and subsequently * made an addi- 
 tion to the empirical text, thus: "iw intellectu nihil est, quod 
 non prius fuerit in sensu, nisi intellectus ipse "; which clever 
 retort, more clever perhaps than clear, has become famous. 
 
 1 The logic of these statements is unquestionably good, and cannot be 
 refused, but an empiricist would deny the premises. E.g. Mill, in his oppo- 
 sition to metaphysical conceptions, as a disciple of the positivist Comte, 
 denies any experience of efficiency in causation, and reduces cause to " un- 
 conditional invariable antecedent." — Logic, bk. ii, ch. 5, §§ 2, 6. His 
 denial of all intuitive knowledge leads him to maintain that while the princi- 
 ple of causation is the ground of induction, induction is the ground of the 
 principle of causation. Empiricism revolves in this circle, and Mill labors 
 to justify it with all his great acumen. — Id., bk. ii, ch. 4, § 3 ; and ch. 21. 
 Within our limits it is impossible to discuss empiricism adequate^. We can 
 only introduce the reader to the question. 
 
 2 Meditations, iii. 
 
 ^ Nouvcaux E.t.taift .'<ur PEntendcmrnt Ilnmain. 
 * In a letter to Wn vVimi, a.d. 1710. 
 
ORIGIN OF PURE TRUTH. 123 
 
 He means to say that the intellect itself is a source of knowl- 
 edge, in accordance with the much lauded brocard : " Cogni- 
 tio nostra omnis a mente primam originem, a sensibus exordium 
 pri7num, Jiahetr ^ 
 
 This doctrine denies the tabula rasa of Locke. " We have 
 ideas," says Leibnitz, '' that are native to the mind (mentis 
 insitls}, that arise from the profundities of the intellect,^ 
 though they do not come into actual being until sense pre-l 
 sents an occasion for their appearance. The truths of pure 
 mathematics, for instance, have principles the proof of which 
 does not depend on examples, and consequently not on the 
 evidence of sense ; howbeit that without the senses we should 
 never have found occasion to call them into consciousness." 
 So also of logic, and metaphysics, and ethics. In speak- 
 ing of the power by which we know such truths, he says : 
 " It is not a naked faculty, which consists in the mere possi- 
 bility of understanding them ; it is a disposition, an aptitude, 
 a preformation, which determines our mind to elicit them, 
 and which causes that they be elicited." ^ 
 
 § 128. In the system of Kant the pure intuitions are dis- 
 tinguished as " forms of cognition." The form is that which 
 the mind itself contributes as the condition of knowing, and 
 which it imposes on the matter of its knowledge. They are, 
 then, wholly subjective, having nothing objective correspond- 
 
 ' 1 Patricius ; see Hamilton, Meta., pp. 285, 515. 
 
 2 Nouv. Ess., I, i, § 11. In illustration he says : " Let us make use of the 
 simile of a block of marble which has veins, rather than of one wholly uni- 
 form, or of blank tablets ; for if the mind resembled these blank tablets, 
 truths would be in us as the figure of Hercules is in a piece of marble when 
 the marble is altogether indifferent to the reception of this figure, or of any 
 other. But if we suppose that there are veins in the stone which would mark 
 out the figure of Hercules by preference to other figures, the stone would be 
 more determined thereunto, and Hercules would exist there innately, in a 
 certain sort ; although it would require labor to discover the veins, and to 
 clear them by polishing, and the removal of all that prevents their manifes- 
 tation. It is thus that ideas and truths are innate in us, like our inclina- 
 tions, dispositions, natural habitudes or virtualities, and not as actions." 
 
124 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 ing to them. He says : " That which in the phenomenon 
 corresponds to the sensation, I term its matter, but that 
 which effects that the content of the phenomenon can be 
 arranged under certain relations, I call its form. . . . The 
 matter of all phenomena is given to us a posteriori ; the form 
 must lie ready a priori for them in the mind." See § 50, note. 
 '"'■ There are two pure forms of sensuous intuition, as prin- 
 ciples of knowledge a priori, namely, space and time. . . . 
 Space is nothing else than the form of all phenomena of the 
 external sense, that is, the subjective condition of the sensi- 
 bility, under which alone external intuition is possible. . . . 
 Time is not something which subsists of itself, or which 
 inheres in things as an objective determination. Time is 
 nothing else than the form of the internal sense." ^ 
 
 In general, then, in the words of ]\Iansel, '' If there are in 
 every act of consciousness certain invariable elements, which 
 no change of consciousness can ever obliterate or alter, which 
 no effort of thought can get rid of or conceive as absent, and 
 without which consciousness itself cannot be imag-ined as 
 possible, these may be conjectured to owe their existence to 
 the constitution of the subject, which remains one and un- 
 changed in successive acts, while the changeable features 
 which distinguish one mode of consciousness from another 
 are probably due to the different constitutions of the several 
 things of which the subject is successively conscious. The 
 former may therefore be distinguished as constituting the 
 form or subjective ingredient of consciousness, the latter as 
 constituting the matter or objective ingredient." ^ 
 
 This is the extreme of intuitionism. Those who hold with 
 Kant this doctrine of transcendental knowledge in pure ideas 
 must go with him into formal or critical idealism, and thence 
 logically with Fichte into absolute idealism, and further into 
 nihilism.^ 
 
 ^ Critique of Pure Heason, p. 21 sq. ^ Metaphysics, p. 55. 
 
 3 Hamilton, dominated by Kant, accepts the doctrine of innate forms, and 
 then sees only one escape from idealism, which is to admit both an empirical 
 
ORIGIN OF PURE TRUTH. 125 
 
 § 129. The intuitionism now widely prevalent among phil- 
 osophical thinkers is essentially that of Leibnitz and Kant. 
 It may be restated succinctly thus : — 
 
 An empirical intuition is adventitious to the mind, and 
 strictly sensuous. Being a posteriori or logically subsequent 
 to, and in consequence of, the exercise of its powers of obser- 
 vation, it is, therefore, acquired and contingent. The matter 
 is given to consciousness. A pure intuition is native to the 
 mind, and strictly intellectual. Being a priori, or a logical 
 antecedent, a condition and not a result of the exercise of 
 its powers of cognition, it is, therefore, original and neces- 
 sary. The form is given by consciousness. 
 
 That pure truths are native to the mind, or innate, does 
 not mean that they are congenital in the sense of being 
 born with and in us, and in conscious possession of the 
 mind from the moment of birth. It means rather that 
 the power of supplying such truth is provided for in the 
 constitution of the mind, so that, when an occasion is pre- 
 sented by experience, it is then born of the mind, it then 
 "arises from the profundities of the intellect," and com- 
 plements its empirical occasion so as with it to constitute 
 a cognition, somewhat as a lamp furnishes from within oil 
 which rises to meet the inflowing air, and the two combine, 
 giving light. 
 
 Pure ideas and principles are thus the conditions of knowl- 
 edge, having a source and origin wholly subjective. They 
 are formed in and by consciousness, which is constitutionally 
 predisposed to this end. They are elicited or evoked by 
 sense, yet are not the effects of sense, but are self-developed. 
 As the condition of its intelligent exercise, they are logically 
 but not chronologically prior. 
 
 Their criterion, necessity, is also viewed as wholly subjec- 
 
 and a pure knowledge of space and time. He holds, therefore, that they are 
 " both real forms of thought and conditions of things." — Hfeta., p. 647 ; see 
 also pp. 346, 401. This is very curious, and savors more of eclecticism than 
 of parcimony. 
 
126 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 tive in its origin. Necessity is usually defined, negatively, 
 as the impossibility of conceiving the contrary ; positively, 
 as the absolute subjective constraint to think and believe thus 
 and so. Consequently, it is made to appear that pure ideas 
 and principles, instead of being in their own nature irrever- 
 sible and authoritative, owe this character to the peculiar 
 constitution of mind, to the imbecility or the constraint of 
 intellect. They are truths to us merely because our nature 
 is such that we must think and believe them.^ 
 
 § 130. It seems possible to take and maintain a view of the 
 origin of necessary truths more in accord Avith the approved 
 principles of jDsychology, and with the common judgments of 
 men, possible to adopt a course which will carry us clear of 
 both the Scylla of idealism and the Chary bdis of materialism. 
 This view is that mind is constituted with powers to know 
 both itself and things other than itself, the conditions of their 
 being, as well as their relations to each other; and not con- 
 stituted with things or ideas of things implanted to be known, 
 and with a predisposition to know them. Our cognitive con- 
 stitution is such as fits us, not only for the empirical, but also 
 for the pure intuition of objective reality. Consciousness in 
 the presence of some adventitious, empirical matter perceived 
 by sense, external or internal, has, beside and along with 
 
 1 That intuitionism logically and historically results in idealism, or that 
 empiricism leads to materialism, is not an argument against either, but merely 
 a warning to the student of philosophy. We have offered some logical objec- 
 tions to empiricism ; let us here note one against the extreme intuitionism 
 just described. We accuse it of bald self-contradiction. The necessary idea, 
 of space for instance, is, according to Leibnitz, innate, and therefore, accord- 
 ing to Kant, wholly subjective, having no corresponding objective reality. 
 Nevertheless, according to both, I must think it real. Now look this in the 
 face. I must think tliat real, which I prove to be unreal. I must believe 
 that true, which 1 hold to be false. What I cannot possibly doubt, I do 
 actually doubt. Is there any escape from this absurdity ? It would seem 
 to be merely an identical proposition that the reality and truth of what i& 
 necessarily conceived and believed to be real and true cannot be sincerely 
 questioned or doubted. 
 
ORIGIN OF PURE TRUTH. 12T 
 
 sense, an intellectual power to discern in the total fact an 
 essential element, equally adventitious, but not at all sen- 
 suous. This is the power of pure reason. That element of 
 the total which is not the object of sense, is the object of 
 reason ; and both elements are objective and real in the total 
 thing known. Our capacity to know, though limited, is a 
 capacity to know that which really is, though now we know 
 only in part, yet that part truly. '•''Nam neque decipitur ratioy 
 nee decipit unquam.^^ ^ 
 
 For example : A series of events is observed to occur. 
 That they are plural is not known by sense, but by intellect, 
 the plurality not being imposed by me on them, but existing 
 in the total datum, and discerned by pure reason. Let us 
 suppose that the events are a series of thoughts ; the time 
 that is discerned as involved in the conscious succession is 
 not a form imj^osed by me on the fact, but the form or rather 
 condition of the fact itself ; it is not an idea born of me, but 
 an idea given to me by that and of that which actually and 
 really exists in the fact, and is discerned by my power of 
 pure intuition. Again, in reflecting that these events, these 
 changes that occur, are not detached but grow out of each 
 other, one producing another, I discern the necessary relation 
 of cause and effect, a pure intuition of a reality existing in 
 the relations of the things themselves ; not imposed by me 
 on them, but discerned by me as existing in them. Such 
 ideas and principles, then, are not native or innate, do not 
 originate in mind, but are adventitious, originating in the 
 object, and mind has only a native or natural power to know 
 them. 2 
 
 According to this view, pure truth is objectively real. 
 Time, space, causation, and the rest, are entities and facts, as 
 truly so as matter and events. Their real existence does not 
 
 ^ Manlius, ii, 131. 
 
 2 "Ni nos idees, ni nos sentiments, ne sont inngs, mais ils sont naturels, 
 fondes sur la constitution de notre esprit et de notre ame, et sur nos rapports 
 avec tout ce que nous environne." — Tuegot, CEuvres, t. iv, p. 308. 
 
128 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 depend at all on mind either to originate or to apprehend 
 them, and they would continue to be, should all mind cease 
 to be. Nor are they dependent upon things like qualities, 
 which inhere in things, but, on the contrary, things are de- 
 pendent on them. They stand thus prior to things in the 
 relation of condition to conditioned. They must be, in order 
 that things may be ; the former necessary, the latter contin- 
 gent. Thus time is a condition of events, space a condition 
 of body, cause a condition of change, substance a condition of 
 quality, non-contradiction a condition of thought, right a 
 condition of obligation, etc. If a thing be real, its condition 
 must be real.^ 
 
 § 131. Pure truth is primarily and immediately discerned 
 in a presentative fact of consciousness. By abstraction it is 
 contemplated logically apart from the accompanying empiri- 
 cal elements, and afterward this abstract object alone may be 
 recalled to mind. Then and then only is it properly a pure 
 idea. 
 
 An idea, whether pure or empirical, whether abstract or 
 concrete, is always representative. The pure idea of time, 
 for example, represents the objective reality. My idea of 
 Mt. Blanc is an image representative of an objective reality, 
 and by abstraction my idea of the space it occupies, and of 
 the infinite space that surrounds it, is also representative 
 of an objective reality. I cannot, however, form an image of 
 that which is strictly pure, an image being always sensuous. 
 T'he pure representative idea is entertained in like manner as 
 I entertain other abstract cognitions ; it is enabled to repre- 
 
 1 While observing that the pure element is objectively a condition of the 
 existence of a thing, conditio essendi, it should be noted that subjectively the 
 case is reversed, and the empirical element or sensuous experience which 
 occasions the pure intuition is the condition of my discerning it, conditio 
 cofjnoscendi. E.g. sjiace must bo, in order that body may be ; but an expe- 
 rience of body must be, in order that a discernment of space may be. This 
 corresponds to the logical condition or reason. E.tj. if body is, tlien space 
 must be. 
 
ORIGIN OF PURE TRUTH. 129 
 
 dent its object by virtue of some image of which it is the 
 condition or which symbolizes it. Thus our complement of 
 pure ideas and principles, originally adventitious, and ac- 
 quired on the occasion of an exercise of sense, is retained by 
 memory as a complement of abstractions, representative of 
 objective and concrete realities. 
 
 § 132. Furthermore, necessity is recognized as the efficient 
 and sufficient criterion of pure truth, but not at all as its 
 ground, or as explanatory of its nature. Instead of exjjlaining 
 the nature of the idea by subjective necessity, we explain 
 subjective necessity by the nature of the idea. We hold pure 
 truth to be in its own nature essentially irreversible. That 
 it is to us self-evident, adds nothing to its authority, but is 
 merely the recognition of an authority which is inherent.^ 
 That a thing cannot both be and not be, that space is a real 
 objective condition of body, that every change is caused, that 
 love is a duty, are truths self-evident, authoritative, regu- 
 lative, simply because in and of themselves true ; subjectively 
 necessary, because objectively real. Since I consciously and 
 constrainedly know that things exist (§ 68), I am necessitated 
 to conceive the existence of their essential conditions. I know 
 certainly that body is, therefore I know necessarily that space 
 is. So long as things are, their conditions must be. Pure 
 principles are not true because we must believe them, but we 
 must believe them because they are true. Their contraries 
 I cannot conceive even as logically possible, because to do so 
 I must first annihilate in thought the existing order of things 
 with their conditions, and then, out of pure negatives, construct 
 an inverted cosmos, which I freely confess myself unable to do. 
 
 1 Dr. McCosh, like Father Buffier, takes self-evidence to be the primary 
 characteristic of intuitive truth (see § 117, note). He shrinks, he says, from 
 maintaining that a proposition is true because we must believe it, and adds : 
 " I would not ground the evidence on the necessity of the belief, but I would 
 ascribe the irresistible nature of the conviction to the self-evidence. — Intui- 
 . tions of the Mind, p. 32. 
 
130 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 Along with necessity is given universality. When I 
 abstract the conditioning fact, its strict universality immedi- 
 ately appears. For example, when I discern cause as con- 
 ditioning a change, this is to discern it as conditioning 
 chano-e in the abstract, and what is this but to think cause 
 as conditioning change always and everywhere? This is 
 not to generalize it, but merely to recognize a universality 
 that is inherent. Generalization is a subjective fiction ; uni- 
 versality is an objective fact. It is incapable of conceivable 
 limitation, because to assign a limit would be to conceive 
 beyond the limit an inverted order that is confessedly incon- 
 ceivable.^ 
 
 § 133. But does not this recoil from the Leibnitzio-Kantian 
 view of the origin of pure truth carry us back into empiri- 
 cism ? Not so far. Do we give up pure intuition ? Not at 
 all. We hold that in addition to, or rather along with, per- 
 ception and self-perception, there is intuition of truth that is 
 both pure and real. The Lockian empiricism declares sense 
 and reflection alone to be the sources of knowledge. We 
 find a source also in pure reason. The knowledge is adven- 
 titious, but not sensuous. It is not an experience, nor given 
 
 1 The general doctrine here proposed accords with the common sense of 
 mankind, and is not wholly new in philosophy. Cousin says: "Conscious- 
 ness is only a witness, it makes what is appear, it creates nothing. It is not 
 because consciousness says to us that pure reason is constrained to admit 
 such or such a truth, that this truth exists ; it is because it exists that it is 
 impossible for reason not to admit it. The truths that reason attains are 
 absolute truths; reason does not create them, it discovers them. Absolute 
 truths, are, therefore, independent of experience and consciousness, and at 
 the same time they are attested by experience and consciousness. On the 
 one hand, these truths declare themselves in experience ; on the other, no 
 experience explains them." — Trvr, BemitifuJ, and Good, p. 49. 
 
 Sir John Herschel says sturdily : "The reason why we apprehend things 
 as without us is that they are without us. We take it for granted that they 
 exist in space, because they do so exist, and because such existence is a mat- 
 ter of direct perception, which can neither be explained in words nor con- 
 travened in imagination ; because, in short, space is a reality." — Review of 
 Whewell, Essays, p. 202, 
 
ORIGIN OF PURE TRUTH. 131 
 
 by experience, but in or along with experience. Empiricism 
 declares that what we call a pure truth is merely an induc- 
 tion, a generalization from sensuous experience ; we hold 
 that its strict universality cannot possibly be reached by 
 induction, and is not generalization at all. While we deny 
 that a pure idea or principle is a priori, in the sense of 
 native, we affirm that it is a priori in the more accurate 
 sense of a condition, and that the empirical element is a 
 posteriori, not as adventitious, but as conditioned. 
 
 § 134. In the examination of pure ideas and principles, we 
 have passed from psychology into the domain of philosophy, 
 the science of principles. That the laws of thought are 
 laws of things, is a metaphysical thesis. To discover the 
 relation that exists between sensible phenomena and super- 
 sensible entities, to determine the relation between the sub- 
 jective necessities of thought and the objective necessities of 
 things, to ascertain the relation of self-evidence to reality, 
 are problems that have engaged the closest attention of the 
 profoundest thinkers. But no approved and established 
 solution of them having been reached, the controversy still 
 goes on. The hope that it shall end is a hope for a solution, 
 for these questions cannot be dismissed. They represent 
 the deepest needs of human intellect. They lie on the 
 threshold of the science that searches for freedom, immor- 
 tality, and God. For while psychology is merely a system of 
 natural order, and ethics a system of natural jurisprudence, 
 metaphysics, in its full conception, is a system of natural 
 theology. 
 
132 IMMEDIATE EyOW LEDGE. 
 
 CHAPTER VIIL. 
 
 ]\nND AND MATTER. 
 
 § 135. Thus far we have constantly endeavored to look 
 upon mind as merely a complement of powers in exercise, 
 that is, as a series of subjective phenomena, the thought- 
 series let us call it, distinct from the objective or material 
 phenomena, the thing-series. AVe have not allowed our 
 examination of mind to be burdened and embarrassed by any 
 theory as to its ultimate nature, and have made no inferences 
 from the character or relations of the substratum underlying 
 subjective phenomena.^ There are, however, important ques- 
 tions respecting this substratum, questions that press for an 
 answer, and that lead to grave consequences whatever an- 
 swer they receive. We propose, therefore, in this supplemen- 
 tary chapter, to present briefly the principal ^dews which are 
 held by philosophers on the subject. 
 
 There are those who consider the substratum underlying 
 phenomena, inasmuch as it is not an object of sense, to be 
 merely imaginary and hypothetical. More generally, how- 
 ever, it is considered to be real, by empiricists as well as by 
 intuitionists. The latter hold it to be necessary in thought. 
 Substance is certainly not an object of sensuous perception, 
 
 1 There are only two ways, says Wundt, of conceiving the mind, as an 
 act and as a substance. According to the first, tlie psychic is pure actuality, 
 immediately given in the manifestations of the mental life. Hume, Kant, 
 Fichte, Hegel, and Wundt himself, give prominence to this view. To the 
 second conception belong all theories according to which psychic facts are 
 manifestations of a substratum, a substance material or immaterial. Most 
 philosophers discuss this view subordinately. 
 
MIND AND MATTEB. 133 
 
 but is discerned by reason, by the insight of pure intellect.^ 
 In everything which I perceive or can imagine as existing, I 
 distinguish two parts, qualities which are multiple and vari- 
 able, and a being which is one and identically permanent. 
 The former are perceived, the latter is a pure intuition. 
 These two elements of a cognition are so united that I can 
 separate them only logically. I cannot even imagine either 
 one as truly existing apart from the other. There is no 
 quality, property, attribute, mode, or activity which is not 
 of necessity the quality or activity of some being, and this 
 being having the quality or activity is substance. Each of 
 the thought-series, each of the thing-series, must be referred 
 to a basis, to an underlying substratum, to a being of which 
 it is the manifestation, and which gives unity to each series. 
 Mind or the ego is commonly viewed as the permanent basis 
 of the thought-series, and matter as the permanent basis of 
 the thing-series. 
 
 Now the difficult and weighty question arises : Are the 
 two series manifestations of one and the same substance, or 
 of two diverse substances ? Monism is the doctrine of one 
 substance. It has taken three specific forms, idealism, ma- 
 terialism, and absolute identity. Dualism is the doctrine 
 that mind and matter are two distinct substances. Of these 
 now, in their order. 
 
 § 136. Idealism teaches that mind is the only substance. 
 The existence of things in space is either doubtful and 
 undemonstrable, or false and impossible. The first is the 
 problematical idealism of Descartes. It admits the strict 
 
 1 See it mentioned at the close of § 1 14. See especially § 50, and the notes. 
 " Substance is a term for the substratum we are obliged to think as under- 
 lying mode, state, quality, etc." — Hamilton. "It is the abiding which 
 changes only in its affections." — Aristotle. It involves existence, perma- 
 nence, and active power or causality. "Die Substanz in Eaume kennen 
 wir nur durch Krafte." — Kant. " Substance is action." — Leibnitz. Bos- 
 chovich reduces quality to force, and substance to centre of force. 
 
134 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 certainty of only one empirical proposition, to wit : I am ; 
 alleging an inability to prove, on this exclusive basis, by 
 means of immediate experience, the existence of anything 
 besides self and its modes, and so leaving objective reality 
 in doubt and improbable. The second is the dogmatical 
 idealism of Berkeley. It maintains that neither space nor 
 the things of which it is the inseparable condition, are real, 
 but are mere products of imagination. I have sensations and 
 ideas ; these alone exist, all else is unreal ; the existence 
 of an external world being an illusion which philosophy 
 corrects. 
 
 Hume, accepting the principles of the then prevailing 
 philosophemes, by a cogent logic drove idealism into nihil- 
 ism. ^ This brought about a clearing up (^AufMiirung^ in 
 philosoph3^ Kant awoke from his " dogmatic slumber," and 
 founded the critical philosophy. He gives a " refutation of 
 idealism " whicli concludes : " The consciousness of my own 
 existence is at the same time an immediate consciousness of 
 the existence of other things without me." ^ Thus he affirms 
 objective reality, but he denies any possible knowledge of 
 things in themselves, noumena, maintaining that we know 
 only phenomena. Hence his doctrine becomes at last a 
 formal, or critical, or transcendental idealism. 
 
 The Kantian doctrine was apodeictically resolved by Fichte 
 and Jacobi into absolute idealism, in which this form of 
 
 1 "The celebrated David Hume was one of those geographers of human 
 reason who beheve that they have given a sufficient answer to all questions 
 raised by pure reason, by declaring them to lie beyond the horizon of our 
 knowledge, a horizon which, however, Hume was unable to determine. Yet 
 he was perhaps the ablest and most ingenious of all sceptical philosophers, 
 and his writings have, undoubtedly, exerted the most powerful influence 
 in awakening reason to a thorough investigation into its own powers." — 
 C. P. R., pp. 462-4. 
 
 2 Critique of Pure Benson, p. 10() sq. Subsequently, he says that this is 
 "The only possible demonstration of the reality of an external world." See 
 note by Hamilton, Discussions, p. 07, and Meta., p. 648, Am. eds. 
 
MIND AND MATTER. 135 
 
 monism at once culminated and broke down.^ Thereupon 
 Comte mercilessly exposed the fruitlessness of speculation, 
 and contemptuously dismissed metaphysics to make room for 
 the positive philosoph}'.^ Still idealism lingers in Germany, 
 especially in the modified form of which Schopenhauer was 
 the apostle. " The world," says he, " is merely my represent- 
 ation (^Dle Welt ist meine Vorstellung').'''' He reduces all 
 existence to force, and this to will; "reality is only an 
 infinitely varied impulse of will," and "the world is one vast 
 will constantly rushing into life (^der Wille zum Leben). " 
 With this he associated the now popular doctrine of pessi- 
 mism.3 
 
 § 137. Further mention of idealism will be made subse- 
 quently (§ 146). Just here we add only that a self-contra- 
 diction is chargeable, not perhaps on the doctrine itself, but 
 upon its advocates. The most authoritative with candor 
 admit that we of necessity, by the very constitution of our 
 nature, do believe in the existence of external reality.* 
 
 1 See close of § 128. The dogmatism of Fichte finally reached nihilism, 
 which is scepticism of all existence. "The sum total," says he, "is this: 
 There is absolutely nothing permanent either without me or within me, but 
 only an unceasing change. I know absolutely nothing of any existence, not 
 even of my own. I myself know nothing, am nothing. Images (Bilder) 
 there are ; they constitute all that apparently exists ; images that pass and 
 vanish without there being aught to witness their transition. I myself am 
 one of these images ; nay, I am not even thus much, but only a confused 
 image of images. All reality is converted into a marvellous dream without a 
 life to dream of, and without a mind to dream ; into a dream made up only 
 of a dream. Perception is a dream ; thought — the source of all the existence 
 and all the reality which I imagine to myself of my existence, of my power, 
 of my destination — is the dream of that dream." 
 
 2 See Buckle, Hist, of Civ., p. 113 ; and Comte's treatise, translated by 
 Harriet Martineau. 
 
 3 " Qu'est-ce que I'homme ? Son savoir n'est qu'ignorance, sa grandeur 
 que bassesse, sa force qu'infirmite, son plaisir que douleur. J'avais lu cela 
 dans Schopenhauer, qui I'avait lu dans Heraclite." — Mounier. Cf. Pascal, 
 Pensees, pt. i, art. 7. 
 
 * See Berkeley and Hume,. quoted by Hamilton, Meta., p. 201 ; and many 
 others in Reid, note A, § 1. 
 
136 ni MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 They maintain, however, that possibly, or certainly, we are 
 deceived in this by the false testimony of consciousness.^ 
 That is, what they do believe, they do not believe. To say 
 that " what I am constrained to regard as not me, is only a 
 modification of me, wliich I, deluded by my nature, mistake, 
 and must mistake, for something different from me," is 
 obviously self-contradictory .^ 
 
 § 138. Materialism, the second form of monism, teaches 
 that matter is the only substance. It originated in the fifth 
 century, B.C., with the atoraists. The Epicureans adopted 
 it. It was advocated by Lucretius.^ It has had adlierents 
 ever since, though never rising to the dignity of a philoso- 
 pheme. In modern times the sensualism of Hobbes and 
 Locke has given a materialistic tendency to English thought, 
 but excepting Priestly hardly any of note have been out- 
 spoken materialists. In Germany, thorough-going materialism 
 was first avowed by Moleschott in 1852, followed very soon 
 by Vogt and Biichner.* 
 
 1 See § 102. Calderwood says: "The testimony of consciousness cannot 
 be denied without self-contradiction. He who doubts it relies on the testi- 
 mony of consciousness for the affirmation of his doubt." — Moral Phil., 
 Int., § 7. 
 
 2 Hamilton well says : "To doubt whether what we necessarily think in a 
 certain manner, actually exists as we conceive it, is nothing less than an 
 endeavor to think the necessary as not necessary or the impossible, which is 
 contradictory." — Logic, p. 382. See § 129, note. 
 
 " The belief which accompanies consciousness," says Stewart, " as to the 
 present existence of its appropriate phenomena (and this has never been 
 questioned) rests on no foundation more solid than our belief of the existence 
 of external objects. The only account that can be given of this belief is that 
 it forms a necessary part of our constitution, against which metaphysicians 
 may easily argue so as to perplex the judgment, but of which it is impossible 
 for us to divest ourselves for a moment, either in the business of life or in 
 the pursuit of science." — Phil. Essays, in H'oyA-.s, vol. v, p. 57. 
 
 3 In his poem, De Rernm Natura, first century, b.c. 
 
 * The latter is its popular exponent. His work. Matter and Force, which 
 was first published in 185(5, has run through many editions, and lias been 
 translated. Its point of departure, its basic principle, is : "No matter with- 
 out force, and no force without matter." 
 
MIND AND MATTER. 137 
 
 The following may be taken as its creed : " Instinct, 
 passion, thought, are the acts of organized substance. All 
 causes are material causes. In material conditions I find the 
 origin of all religions, all philosophies, all opinions, all vir- 
 tues, all spiritual states and influences, in the same manner 
 that I find the origin of all diseases and of all insanities 
 in material conditions and causes. I am a creature of 
 necessity ; I claim neither merit nor demerit. I feel that 
 I am as completely the result of my nature, and impelled to 
 do what I do, as the needle to point to the north, or the 
 puppet to move according as the string is pulled. I can- 
 not alter my will, or be other than Avhat I am, and cannot 
 deserve either reward or punishment." ^ 
 
 § 139. The most refined and subtile form of the doctrine is 
 as follows : " Mind is merely the consequence of a certain 
 mode of material organization. It is not a distinct substance, 
 but merely a series of phenomena which are as truly phe- 
 nomena of matter as the physical phenomena. Sundry brain 
 centres have the function of producing consciousness, or 
 rather, of manifesting the phenomena of consciousness, while 
 manifesting physical phenomena. In these centres the physi- 
 cal series and the psychical series always appear together, 
 the one objectively, the other subjectively ; that is to say, the 
 matter constituting a centre has two sides or faces, the 
 objective or physical, and the subjective or psychical. These 
 are in no sense commutable, for the psychical series is merely 
 a subjective shadow that attends the objective physical 
 series. 
 
 " A molecule that undergoes a certain chemical change, 
 experiences a sensation. As the one is a mode of motion, 
 so is the other, or rather, they are two distinct manifestations 
 of the same motion. Mental movement of any sort is not at 
 all due to self-determination, but is a movement of the ner- 
 
 1 From a work by H. G. Atkinson and Harriet Martineau. 
 
188 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 vous mechanism as to its subjective face. Perception, mem- 
 ory, and reasoning are only the mental side of changes in the 
 brain, and a change of ideas means that the corresponding 
 physical states have been displaced by others." ^ According 
 to this doctrine, brain itself is I. 
 
 § 140. Mind and matter are made known to us b}' two 
 widely distinct series of phenomena, which we have called 
 the thought-series and the thing-series. The seeming incom- 
 patibility of these to inhere in one substance is not sufficient 
 ground for rejecting the materialistic hypothesis. Though I 
 may be unable to conceive of conscious matter, it may never- 
 theless be actual. The question is not to be settled by my 
 preconceived notions of what may or may not be, but by a 
 philosophical and logical treatment of the facts. If they can 
 be explained on the hj^pothesis of one substance, then, by 
 the law of parcimony, that entities are not to be multiplied 
 without necessity, this hypothesis is preferable to the dual 
 hypothesis.^ 
 
 1 From Professor Bowne's lecture on " Some Difficulties in Modern Mate- 
 rialism." — Christian Philosophy Quarterly for October, 1881. 
 
 We may at once observe that materialism, approaching mind from the 
 outside, and interiireting the facts of psychology in the language of physi- 
 ology, seeks to replace terms of mind by terms of brain. It proposes to 
 identify mental with cerebral functions, and to reduce intellectual action to 
 molecular motion. David Ferrier, an authority in physiology, and a favorite 
 with the materialists, says: "No purely physiological investigation can 
 explain the phenomena of consciousness. We may succeed in determining 
 the exact nature of the molecular changes which occur in the brain-cells 
 when a sensation is experienced, but this will not bring us one whit nearer 
 the exi)lanation of the ultimate nature of that which constitutes a sensation. 
 The one is objective, the other subjective, and neither can be expressed in 
 terms of the other. We cannot say that tliey are identical, but only that tlie 
 two are correlated." — Functions of tin' Brain, § 89. 
 
 2 See § 100 and § 82, note. Pascal says: " Quand on pr6tendrait que 
 nous fussions simplement corporal, cela nous exclurait de la connaissance 
 <les choses, n'y ayant rien de si inconceivable (]ue de dire que la matiere 
 puisse se connaitre soi-memc." — Pcnsi'cs, pt. i, art. 7, § 2(i. 
 
 II;Miiiltnii snvs: " W'c know nothing whatever of niiiul ami iiialtei' con- 
 
MIND AND MATTER. 139 
 
 All ground for the objection disappears when we find that 
 the conception is not, in some aspects, impossible, nor indeed 
 very difficult. That a living molecule which is warm should 
 feel warm, seems not hard to conceive, especially when we 
 consider that the first is objective, a manifestation to an 
 observer, the other subjective, a manifestation to itself. It 
 would seem harder to conceive that this molecule both 
 attracts and repels at once an adjacent molecule, yet no one 
 questions the fact. 
 
 § 141. Further mention of materialism will be made subse- 
 quently (§ 147), but we remark here, in passing, some objec- 
 tions having greater weight than that just considered. The 
 hypothesis assumes the substantial existence of matter, and 
 reduces to it the phenomena of mind. It entirely ignores the 
 prior and hard problem of philosophy which questions the 
 existence of external reality. At the outset it assigns sub- 
 stance to the thing-series, and so makes an unwarranted 
 assumption. 
 
 If we allow that the two series of phenomena are given in 
 equipoise, then the materialist must show whj^ the thing- 
 series should have preponderance. His reasons do not appear. 
 Primarily, in a monist scheme, it would seem as reasonable 
 to claim that the thing-series is an objective phase of mind, 
 as that the thought-series is a subjective phase of matter. 
 But, indeed, it is more reasonable ; for objects are known 
 only by their opposition to a subject, the material phenomena 
 only through the mental. The facts of consciousness being 
 
 sidered as substances ; they are known to us only as a two- fold series of 
 phenomena ; and we can justify, against the law of parcimony, the postulate 
 of two substances only on the ground that the two series are reciprocally so 
 contrary and incompatible that one cannot be reduced to the other, nor both 
 be supposed to inhere in one common substance." — In Beid, note A, § 2. 
 See also Meta., p. 97. President Mark Hopkins in his Lowell Lectures takes 
 the same ground ; and many others. A hundred years ago Dr. Priestly refuted 
 this dualist argument in his work, MatrriaJism. See also Herbert Spencer's 
 sweeping and eloquent rebuke in his Principles of Fsychology, § 268 sq. 
 
140 niMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 known to us immediately and in themselves, and the facts of 
 the external world being known, not in themselves, but 
 mediatel}^ through the facts of consciousness, surely if one 
 series is to exj^lain the other, the thought-series should be 
 applied to explain the thing-series. Hence, in assigning a 
 substratum, it is evident that the thought-series, being first 
 in order of knowledge, has the first claim ; and so, in a 
 monist scheme, the logical presumption is in favor of ideal- 
 ism. The materialistic philosophy must, therefore, first 
 dispose of idealism, then, by the law of parcimony, it can 
 claim the logical presumption against dualism. It makes no 
 pretence, however, to any such process, and consequently 
 lacks logical and philosophical warrant. 
 
 Materialism assumes that all forces are physical forces, 
 that all causes are material causes. This begs the whole 
 question. For if, by the doctrine of the conservation of 
 energy, each physical antecedent is entirely exhausted by 
 its physical consequent, then each physical consequent is 
 fully explained by its physical antecedent. This shuts spirit 
 out of the circle, allows it no link in the chain of cause and 
 effect, and simply denies its separate substantial existence. 
 But what fact of nature or principle of science forbids the 
 supposition that there are psychical as well as physical forces ? 
 In the acknowledged phenomena of the thought-series we 
 have at least as much evidence of the existence and play of 
 force, as in the phenomena of the thing-series. Moreover, it 
 is also a fact of consciousness that certain of the thoug-ht- 
 series are the unconditional antecedents or causes of certain 
 changes of the thing-series, and vice versa. The claim that 
 force is only of one kind is arbitrary. The assumption -is 
 unwarranted.^ 
 
 1 Bain, in a somewliat rhetorical passage, quoted approvingly by Ferrier, 
 says : " It would be incompatible with everything we know of cerebral action 
 to suppose that the physical chain ends abruptly in a physical void occupied 
 by an immaterial substance ; which immaterial substance, after working 
 alone, imparts its results to the other edge of the physical break and deter- 
 
HIND AND MATTER. 141 
 
 Let us add to these philosophic objections, that the logical 
 consequence of materialism is extreme agnosticism. It 
 involves the doctrine of a necessitated will, and reduces man 
 to an irresponsible automaton. 
 
 § 142. The third form of monism is absolute identity. It 
 appears that a unitarian scheme, starting with the subjective 
 fact of self-existence, and accepting that only as original and 
 genetic, can never get beyond self, and develops into ideal- 
 ism ; and on the other hand, starting with the objective fact of 
 material existence, and accepting that only as original and 
 genetic, can never by this path discover self, and develops 
 into materialism. But there are monists who admit the tes- 
 timony of consciousness to the equipoise of the mental and 
 
 mines the active response — two shores of the material with an intervening 
 ocean of the immaterial." — 3Ii.nd and Body, p. 131 ; Functions of the Brain, 
 § 88. But by onr theory mind and brain act concomitantly, § 143. 
 
 Huxley, in his lecture " On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata," 
 says: "Molecular changes in the brain are the causes of all states of con- 
 sciousness. Is there any evidence that these states of consciousness may, con- 
 versely, cause those molecular changes which give rise to muscular motions ? 
 I see no such evidence. If there be none, it follows that our mental condi- 
 tions are simply the symbols in consciousness of the changes which take 
 place automatically in the organism ; and that, to take an extreme illustra- 
 tion, the feeling we call volition is not the cause of a voluntary act, but the 
 symbol of that state of the brain which is the immediate cause of that act." 
 He allows that the thing-series causes the thought-series (though not in the 
 sense of expending energy upon it), but not the reverse. 
 
 Carpenter may be quoted in reply : ' ' There is just the same evidence of 
 correlation between nerve-force and that primary state of mental activity we 
 call a sensation, that there is between light and nerve-force ; each antecedent 
 being followed by its corresponding consequent. The like correlation may 
 be shown to exist between mental states and the form of nerve-force which 
 calls forth motion through the muscular apparatus. That mental antece- 
 dents can thus call forth physical consequents is just as certain as that 
 physical antecedents can call forth mental consequents ; and thus the cor- 
 relation between mind-force and nerve-force is shown to be complete both 
 ways, each being able to excite the other." — Mental Physiology, §§ 11, 12. 
 The evidence of correlation between mental and neural forces is stronger 
 than that of correlation between physical forces ; for the latter is deduced 
 from observation, while the former is within consciousness. 
 
142 UIMEUIATE nyowLKDi.::. 
 
 material phenomena, and do not attempt to reduce mind to 
 matter, or matter to mind. They reject, however, the evi- 
 dence of consciousness to their antithesis in existence, and 
 maintain that mind and matter are only phenomenal modifi- 
 cations of the same common substance. This is the doctrine 
 of absolute identity.^ 
 
 § 143. The advocates of this doctrine rely for proof upon 
 the admitted thorough-going concomitance of mental and 
 material phenomena. There is no mental action, even that 
 commonly reckoned as at furthest remove from physical 
 action, such as a discernment of pure intellect or a gentle 
 monition of conscience, without a corresponding movement 
 of neural matter and a waste of nervous energy; and, on 
 the other hand, there is no normal nerve-stimulus without 
 its corresponding consciousness. This correspondence is also 
 in degree, the increased or diminished intensity of the one 
 being attended by a like change in the other.^ Moreover, 
 mind and brain develop together. Sensation, reflection, 
 moral sensibility, are gradually evolved, growing as the 
 nerves grow, and as the brain takes shape and organs.^ 
 
 1 Spinoza expresses it pantheistically thus: "Matter and spirit have no 
 sepai-ate existence ; there is only one substance in the universe, of wliich 
 extension and thought are the corresponding attributes or phenomena, each 
 correspondent to each." So also Fechner, in Phys. und Phil., p. 258 sq. 
 
 2 " We believe," says Tyndall, "that every thought and every feeling has 
 its definite mechanical correlative, that it is accompanied by a certain break- 
 ing up and remodelling of the atoms of the nervous organism." Bain says: 
 "For every mental shock, every awakening of consciousness, every mental 
 transition, there must be a concomitant nervous shock ; and as the one is 
 more or less intense, so mu.st be the other." — Mind and Body, p. 42. 
 
 This admitted concomitance is in opposition to the excessive spiritualizing 
 tendencies of the Platonic school, and of those theological schools that con- 
 sider the body as a clog, a fetter, a prison-house of mind, and it calls for a 
 modification of both psychological and theological doctrine. Its evidence is 
 to be found in a multitude of observed facts which cannot here be cited. 
 3 "For nature, crescent, does not grow alone 
 In thews and hulk ; but as this temple waxes, 
 The inward service of the niiiul and soul 
 Grows wide withal." — Ilamlct, A. 1, sc. 3. 
 
MIND AND MATTER. 143 
 
 The refined monist infers from tliis concomitant variation 
 identity of substance. But logic teaches that when phenom- 
 ena vary concomitantly, it is proof either that they are related 
 as cause and effect, or as effects of a common cause, and it 
 adds that by this method alone we cannot determine which.^ 
 Accordingly, since the subjective and objective phenomena 
 vary together, there is a bond of causation between them, yet 
 a doubt remains. But our refined monist does not allow the 
 doubt. On this inductive method alone, holding it to be the 
 only one applicable to the case, he affirms the phenomena 
 to be the effects of a common cause.^ He goes further, with- 
 out proof, and affirms that the common cause is the only sub- 
 stance in the case. Had he proved the common cause, the 
 oneness of substance would not follow. The oceanic varies 
 with the atmospheric tide ; are they one in substance with 
 their common cause ? The admitted concomitance of mind 
 and brain is insufficient ground for holding the identity of 
 substance. It would be hard to find in sober science another 
 example of such an unwarranted, illogical inference. 
 
 § 144. When we examine this doctrine historically, we find 
 that it is a position of unstable equilibrium. Those who have 
 endeavored to maintain it from a subjective standpoint, have 
 eventually resolved all existence into mind and ideas, and 
 become pronounced idealists. Those who have tried to main- 
 tain it from an objective standpoint, have gravitated into a 
 refined materialism.^ Indeed, it does not seem of consequence 
 
 1 See Mill, Logic, bk. iii, cli. 8, § 6. 
 
 2 See Bain, Mind and Body, ch. 3. Its title is: "The connexion viewed 
 as correspondence, or concomitant variation." Cf. Spencer, quoted below. 
 
 3 The most illustrious advocates of the doctrine in modern times are Schel- 
 ling, Hegel, and Cousin. They endeavor to maintain it from the subjective 
 standpoint, but eventually resolve all existence into mind and ideas, and 
 are known as idealists. 
 
 Spencer declares that "the truth is not expressed either by spiritualism 
 or by materialism, however modified and however refined" ; and concludes 
 that "it is one and the same ultimate reality which is manifested to us sub- 
 jectively and objectively. For while the nature of that which is manifested 
 
144 IMMEDIATE KXOWLEDGE. 
 
 by what name we call the one substance. If one, it is one 
 that manifests both mental and material phenomena. But it 
 is impossible to maintain their equipoise ; for the unavoidable 
 necessity of explaining one through the other brings about a 
 preponderance that quickly reduces the scheme, either to 
 idealism or to materialism. 
 
 § 145. Dualism teaches that mind and matter, specifically 
 brain, are two co-ordinated but distinct substances, widely 
 differing in kind, indeed, having no quality in common. 
 Matter is the substance in which physical phenomena, those 
 of the thing-series, inhere. Mind is the substance in which 
 physical phenomena, those of the thought-series, inhere. In 
 short, matter is extended substance ; mind is conscious sub- 
 stance (§ 50) .1 
 
 under either form proves to be inscrutable, the order of its manifestations 
 throughout all mental phenomena proves to be the same as the order of its 
 manifestations throughout all material phenomena." — Principles of Psy- 
 chology, §§ 272-3. 
 
 Bain's conclusion is similar. He says : " The arguments for the two 
 substances have, we believe, now entirely lost their validity ; they are no 
 longer compatible with ascertained science and clear thinliing. The one 
 substance with two sets of properties, two sides, the physical and the mental, 
 a double-faced unity, would appear to comply with all the exigencies of the 
 case. We are to deal with this, as in the langnage of the Athanasian creed, 
 not confounding the persons, nor dividing the substance." — Mind and Body, 
 p. 196. 
 
 But again the position has proved unstable, and gravitates in these cases, 
 on the other hand, into materialism. Bain himself calls it " a guarded or 
 qualified materialism, saving the contrast of mind and matter." — Id., p. 140. 
 Spencer, however, denies that he identifies mind with matter, saying, " I do 
 no such thing ; I identify mind with motion, and motion is inconceivable by 
 us as in any sense material." Hut motion is only an accidental property of 
 body, manifest by change of place. That is, mind is a property of matter. 
 
 1 The philosophic doctrine of dualism, or spiritism, originated in the ideal- 
 ism of riato. Gradually becoming more and more refined by constant dis- 
 putation, it culminated in the speculations of the scholastic Tliomas Aquinas, 
 1225-74. He maintained that the human soul is a imit and a spirit, in the 
 strictest sense immaterial, the distinction between mind and matter being 
 thorough-going and inerasible. His views received the dogmatic sanction of 
 the Council of Vienna in 1311, they were adopted and enforced by Calvin, 
 and have since prevailed in theology. 
 
MIND AND MATTER. 145 
 
 Dualism opposes monism primarily on the ground that no 
 hypothesis of unity has explained or can explain the facts, 
 and secondarily, because in every form it leads, logically and 
 historically, to revolting consequences. Holding that an 
 hypothesis of plural entities is necessary to the explanation, 
 it does not violate, but is in accord with the law of parcimony. 
 Inasmuch as the scheme of absolute identity reduces inevi- 
 tably either to idealism or to materialism, we may omit fur- 
 ther notice of it, and confine our attention to these. Some 
 objections to both have been offered already. We now pro- 
 pose to supersede them by citing evidence in favor of dualism. 
 
 § 146. Beginning, as we must, with a datum of conscious- 
 ness, we find that the Cartesian "I am" is but a part of 
 the primum cognitum} the complete fact of consciousness 
 consisting of essential correlatives, the full dualistic formula 
 being: Both I and another exist. The conclusion reached 
 at the close of § 101 is only another statement of the same 
 principle. If it be accepted as established, the earlier forms 
 of idealism, which it contradicts, are refuted.^ 
 
 1 See § 114, note 2. 
 
 2 Reid, as well as Kant, was roused by the scepticism of Hume (§ 136). 
 He also allowed Hume's logic to be irrefragable, and found that philosophy 
 could be saved only by a reformation of its generally admitted principles. 
 This he applied himself to bring about, and on subjecting them to a new and 
 rigorous criticism, enounced the doctrine of the immediate perception of 
 external reality, or the consciousness of the non-ego. 
 
 Hamilton, the best exponent of this cardinal doctrine of the Scottish 
 philosophy, seemingly the only means of escape from idealism, states it thus : 
 "In the act of sensible perception, I am conscious of two things ; of myself 
 as the perceiving subject, and of an external reality, in relation with my 
 sense, as the object perceived. Of the existence of both these things I am 
 convinced ; because I am conscious of knowing each of them, not mediately 
 in something else, as represented, but immediately in itself, as existing. Of 
 their mutual independence I am no less convinced ; because each is appre- 
 hended equally and at once, in the same indivisible energy, the one not pre- 
 ceding or determining, the other not following or determined ; and because 
 each is apprehended out of, and in direct contrast to, the other." — In Beid, 
 note A, § 1. 
 
146 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 But this, the usual statement of the doctrine immediate 
 perception, is insufficient. It does not save us from the hiter 
 forms of idealism with their consequences (§ 136). It must 
 also be established that I immediately perceive body in its 
 essential and objectively existing characters, extension and 
 impenetrability; that it possesses these in the same manner 
 as they are perceived by me ; that thus and so far I know 
 the thing in itself; that thus and so far noumena become 
 phenomena. Such is the conclusion reached at the close of 
 § 104. If it be accepted as established, all forms of idealism 
 are refuted. 
 
 § 147. Materialism, as opposed to dualism, remains to be 
 considered. In §§ 99, 101, it is maintained that in perception, 
 in our consciousness of material phenomena, in the action of 
 the object and passion of the subject, there is an opposition 
 of existence. If I am truly conscious of this opposition of 
 an object, then I, the subject, and that object are two distinct 
 beings, and I immediately perceive or am conscious of the 
 existence of a positive non-ego. This conclusion, reached 
 from the subjective or psychological standpoint, is exj^ressed 
 in the proposition : The immediate object in perception is 
 consciously not I. 
 
 In §§ 5, 21, it is maintained that the material object of 
 consciousness in perception is enorganic ; that it is the excited 
 sensory or brain itself. For the immediate object of percep- 
 tion must be its proximate cause. Tracing the chain of cause 
 and effect inward, we discover that the final physical effect 
 antecedent to consciousness is a certain excited state of the 
 sensory, and we conclude this to be its proximate cause, and 
 iience the object immediately perceived. This conclusion, 
 reached from an objective or physiological standpoint, is 
 expressed in the proposition: Brain itself is the immediate 
 object in perception. 
 
 Now combining the subjective fact with the objective fact, 
 we have : The immediate object in perception is consciously 
 
MIND AND MATTER. 147 
 
 not I ; but brain itself is the immediate object in perception ; 
 hence, brain itself is consciously not I, 
 
 If this conclusion, which necessarily follows from the prem- 
 ises, be true, then materialism is false ; for it concludes that 
 brain, the material substance last in the chain of physical 
 causes, and so standing nearest to consciousness, is a non-ego.^ 
 
 From this, further, it is an immediate inference that I 
 myself am not matter, or, in other words, that subjective 
 phenomena are the phenomena of an immaterial substance. 
 If this be allowed, dualism is established.^ 
 
 1 Might it not be said that some centre or organ of the brain is ego (see 
 close of § 139), while others are non-ego, or that certain molecular centres 
 constitute the ego, while adjacent molecules are the non-ego ? Hardly ; for 
 how there could be that " extreme contrast or antithesis " (Bain), that " dif- 
 ference transcending all other differences" (Spencer), between one mass or 
 molecule of neural matter, and another mass or molecule of neural matter, 
 is out of reason. Yet this seems the only alternative hypothesis. 
 
 The opposed views, materialism and dualism, may be crudely illustrated 
 as follows: "We figure to ourselves "a double-faced unity" as having its 
 sides, subjective and objective, concave to each other, thus : (s. o.) ; but a 
 single- faced duality requires an antithesis or opposition of faces, faces con- 
 vex to each other, thus : s.) (o., and so, necessarily, faces of a duality. 
 
 2 Philosophers quite generally rely upon the unity of mind (see § 77) in 
 consciousness, as Apposed to the plurahty of material things, for proof of 
 dualism. E.g. Lotze says : " The fact of the unity of consciousness compels 
 us, in the explanation of the mtellectual life, to put in the place of visible 
 substance a supersensuous essence as supporter of the phenomena, and to 
 suppose that there is a completely indivisible unity in the subject which 
 exercises the comprehending activity of consciousness." — Mikrokosmus, i, 
 72, et al. 
 
 In this connection let us quote from Ferrier, as follows: "The brain, as 
 an organ of motion and sensation, or presentative consciousness, is a single 
 organ composed of two halves ; the brain as an organ of ideation, or repre- 
 sentative consciousness, is a dual organ, each hemisphere being complete in 
 itself. When one hemisphere is removed or destroyed by disease, motion 
 and sensation are abolished unilaterally, but mental operations are still 
 capable of being carried on in their completeness through the agency of the 
 one hemisphere. The individual who is paralyzed as to sensation and 
 motion, by disease of the opposite side of the brain, is not paralyzed men- 
 tally, for he can still feel and will and think, and intelligently comprehend 
 with the one hemisphere. If these functions are not carried on with the 
 
148 IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 § 148. jNIind and brain, then, are two distinct substances, 
 having no quality and no law in common, yet in our present 
 state they are so connected and correlated that neither is 
 capable of its functions without the other, actual consciousness 
 being known to us only in this concrete relation.^ In sense- 
 perception, or in the presentative consciousness in general, 
 the cerebral or sensorial excitement is the cause of the men- 
 tal excitement ; for in this case I am consciously a patient. 
 In voluntary memory, imagination and thought, or the 
 representative consciousness, the mental is the cause of the 
 sensorial excitement ; for in this case I am consciously 
 the agent. The sensorium, then, is the place where physical 
 force directly causes certain states of consciousness, and 
 where mental energy enters the physical sphere. 
 
 § 149. The mind cannot be assigned to any bodily organ 
 as its seat. The famous expression " seat of the soul " is 
 utterly meaningless to any but a materialist.^ Locality can 
 
 same vigor as before, they at least do not appear to suffer in respect of com- 
 pleteness." — Functions of the Brain, § 88. Brown-Sequard even more fully 
 and emphatically maintains that we are possessed of two distinct brains. See 
 his article in Tlie Forum for Aug. '90. This opinion of eminent physiologists, 
 compared with the generally admitted unity of mind in consciousness (^e.g. the 
 inability to carry on two distinct trains of reasoning on different subjects at 
 once), disfavors their hypothesis of materialism, and favors that of a single, 
 regnant, spiritual entity. 
 
 1 See § 143. It may be asked : Then, at, and after death, what? Psy- 
 chology has no answer to that question. Philosophy, perhaps, has grounds 
 on which to conjecture an after life. Revelation only brings life and immor- 
 tality to light. It is conceivable that disembodied spirit may be enabled to 
 perform its proper functions, but it should be observed that, at the resurrec- 
 tion, " God giveth it a body even as it pleaseth him, and to each seed a body 
 of its own. ... It is sown a natural body, it is raised a spiritual body." — 
 1 Cor. 15:30,44. 
 
 2 Aristotle taught that the soul is " all in the whole and all in every part." 
 — De Anima, i, 6, 31. Probably he means, without reference to body, that 
 the entire soul thinks, feels, and wills (see § 78), a strong expression of its 
 essential unity ; for in the same treatise he excludes place and motion from 
 the exercises of mind. The formula was adopted, however, by the Neo- 
 
MIND AND MATTER. 149 
 
 no more be attributed to mind than extension ; either re- 
 duces mind to matter. Mind in itself bears no rehition 
 whatever to space. To ask where the soul is, or to say that 
 it is here, or there, or that it pervades the brain, or the 
 nervous system, is sheer nonsense. If it have place either 
 it is a mathematical point, or it has shape, divisibility, and 
 size ; length, breadth, and thickness ; in short, is matter. 
 Hamilton says very rightly : " It has not always been no- 
 ticed, even by those who deem themselves the chosen cham- 
 pions of the immateriality of mind, that we materialize mind 
 when we attribute to it the relations of matter. Thus we 
 cannot attribute a local seat to the soul without clothing it 
 with the material properties of extension and place, and 
 those who suppose this seat to be but a point only aggravate 
 the difficulty." 
 
 platonist Plotinus to express the relation of mind to body. See Ueberweg, 
 Hist. Phil., §§ 68, 88. It was so used by Augustine : " in toto tola est.'" — • 
 De Trinitate, vi, 6. This application is approved by Hamilton and others. 
 Meta., pp. 272, 356 ; Mansel, Meta., p. 86. See an allusion to it in Milton, 
 Samson Agonistes, line 90 sq. Thus interpreted, the formula affirms the 
 omnipresence of mind in body, and has been adopted in theology as descrip- 
 tive of the omnipresence of the Deity. 
 
 Others affirm a "dynamical presence " in the entire organism. So Lewes : 
 "The position of the centre of gi-avity is a continually shifting point. The 
 attitude of the personality is similar, a personal centre." — Problems of Life 
 and Mind, 3d series. Anticipated by Chalybaus, in Zeitschr. von Ficlite, 
 XX, 69. 
 
 Others, again, regard mind or the soul as difiused throughout the ner- 
 vous system, pervading it. So Fischer, Metaphysik, Sitz der Scele, § 8 ; and 
 Porter, Hum. IntelL, § 129. This is the old ghost notion belonging properly 
 to the primitive races, by whose crude thinking the notion of a strictly imma- 
 terial spirit was unattainable. See Taylor, Primitive Culture, vol. i, p. 387. 
 
 Descartes held "the seat of the soul" to be the pineal gland. — De Pas- 
 sionihus Anima, art. 31 sq. Cf. Meditationes, ch. 6. Laromiguiere takes a 
 similar view, and compares the soul to a spider at the centre of its web. — 
 LeQons, t. ii, p. 251 sq. Descartes elsewhere says: "I have no need of 
 place." — On 3Iethod. pt. iv. Says Kant: "The soul is an absolute iinit, 
 and as it is no object of outer sense, it is immaterial ; and, though it is 
 present and operates in space, it does not occupy space, and has no special 
 place in body." — Vorlesungen ilber Metaphysi/c, p. 133. 
 
PART THIRD. ■ 
 MEDIATE KNO^ATLEDGE, 
 
 CHAPTER I. 
 
 KEPKESENTATION. 
 
 § 150. Representation is mediate cognition, or more fully 
 it is knowledge of one or more remote objects through a present 
 medium which resembles, or otherwise stands for them. 
 
 In presentation there is but one object or thing known, 
 and this object is intuitive. In representation there are 
 two objects ; the proximate representing medium intuitively 
 known and the remote represented object-object mediately 
 known. The medium is either some external object, or a 
 mental image, a subject-object. In either case this medium 
 or representing object, considered irrespectively of what it 
 represents, is itself an intuitive presentative object. Rep- 
 resentation, then, is a presentation with something super- 
 added, namely, the reference to a remote object. ^ 
 
 In the presentative consciousness, a thing is known in it- 
 self. This knowledge involves the fact of the existence of the 
 
 1 See § 92 sq. Immediate and mediate cognition should not be confused 
 with immediate and mediate inference. The one is psycliological, the other 
 logical. Mediate cognition is through a presented representing medium, 
 mediate inference is through a middle term to a conclusion. Yet the results 
 of logical inference are always entertained representatively, so that whatever 
 is inferred is also mediately cognized. The direct rtference of an object to 
 a class, a logical process, is sometimes called mediate knowledge, since the 
 object then becomes known through or by means of its relation to other 
 objects. Tills, too, should be set clearly apart. 
 150 
 
EJ^PRESENTATION. 151 
 
 object. In the representative consciousness, a thing is known 
 in or through something not itself. This knowledge involves 
 only the possibility of its existence. The presented object 
 is, therefore, always real, the represented object may be real 
 or ideal, but must at least be logically possible, ens rationis, 
 that is, must involve no contradiction. 
 
 In presentation the object is present to me here and now, 
 in representation the object-object is not present but remote. 
 The one is knowlege of what is present in time ; the other, 
 of what is past. An immediate, conscious knowledge of what 
 is past is impossible ; for to know the past immediately, it 
 must be known in itself, and therefore as now existing; but 
 the past is a negation of the now existing. 
 
 Presentative knowledge, being of the really existing here 
 and now, is original and certain ; representative knowledge, 
 being of the past, or the possible, the not here or not now 
 existing, is derived and uncertain. The degree of assurance 
 or belief in a representation may be any but the liighest ; it 
 can never attain the certaintj^ of intuition, of consciousness. 
 
 Finally, in presentation the object is always an individual, 
 either an external thing perceived, or a state of mind self- 
 perceived. In representation the remote object may be either 
 an individual, or a plurality of individuals united in a class, 
 and known by means of a concept or general notion.^ 
 
 § 151. Representative cognition is distributed into three 
 special modes. When the medium represents some object 
 
 1 Our science is indebted to Hamilton for tlie first clear and distinct state- 
 ment of this fundamental and important distinction. See especially in Beid, 
 note B, § 1. In the Leibnitzian and subsequent philosophemes of Germany, 
 the term representation (Vurstellung, which is, rather, presentation) is used 
 with vague generality for any cognitive act considered in relation to the thing 
 known. By Kant it is used to include, as species, intuition, perception, and 
 even sensation, as well as memory and thought. His ambiguities and obscur- 
 ities arise largely from lack of the stated distinction. Hamilton, however, 
 went so far, on the other hand, as to identify representation with imagi- 
 nation, thus excluding even memory. See Meta., Lee. 32. In accord with 
 good authority, we take it to be generic, inclusive of memory and thought. 
 
162 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 previously known, which is thus recognized, the act is called 
 a memory. When the medium is a factitious mental image 
 representing what is logically 2:)ossible but merely ideal, the 
 act is called an imagination. When the medium represents 
 an abstract unity, or a plurality reduced to unity in a general 
 notion or concept, the act is called a thought. 
 
 From what has been said it is evident that representation 
 is conditioned on presentation. We add that each of the 
 specific powers of rei^resentation conditions that following 
 it in the order named; memory conditions imagination, and 
 imagination conditions thought; and all are conditioned on 
 pure reason. But let us recall that no given total mental act 
 or state consists of any one of these alone (§ 78). It is always 
 an intricate complexus, in which these several specific activi- 
 ties may be distinguished as factors, and comprises, moreover, 
 feeling, desire, and volition. 
 
 The distinction between the presentative and the represent- 
 ative faculties is not identical with the familiar distinction 
 between sense and intellect. The intellectual faculties in- 
 clude pure reason, sometimes called pure intellect, vov<;, and 
 this we have classed under presentation.^ 
 
 § 152. As the medium is the characteristic feature of rep- 
 resentative states, let us consider it more particularly. It 
 may be either an object perceived, or a mental image of an 
 object of perception. 
 
 That objects perceived are often representative is an obvious 
 and familiar fact. The portrait of my friend represents him, 
 and serves as a medium by and through which I contemplate 
 his actual appearance. All jiictures are thus representative; 
 so also the drama, and the fine arts generally, indeed whatever 
 is imitative.^ It is not that an imitation is merely suggestive, 
 
 1 See § 7G. Intellect, from inter, among, between, and legere, ledum, 
 to gather, to collect, to read. It apprehends more than is seen ; it reads 
 between the lines. 
 
 - The literal observance by the Saracens of the second commandment gave 
 
REPllESENTATION. 153 
 
 and on the principle of association directs our thoughts. It 
 does this no doubt in the first moment; but instantly it be- 
 comes representative, and tlu'ougli it we contemplate a remote 
 object. Again in studying geometry, we di-aw a figure on 
 the blackboard. The proposition demonstrated by means of 
 the figure is true, not of the thing perceived, but of what it 
 represents, that is, of all conceivable figures of that kind ; for 
 in the demonstration we use only such properties as are com- 
 mon to all. We contemplate in the figure perceived these 
 properties, and through it we think what is true of all mem- 
 bers of the class. This mode of representation may be called 
 the mimetic or exemplar. 
 
 But in order to representative cognition it is not necessary 
 that the medium should resemble the object it represents ; it 
 may be merely symbolic.^ The national flag represents one's 
 country or government, and excites patriotic feeling. A 
 crown represents royalty, a sceptre authority, a throne power, 
 a triangle the Trinity. Algebraic symbols and signs repre- 
 sent certain quantities and their relations. Words, either 
 seen or heard, symbolize things, and through the word we 
 think the thing. So also signals of all kinds. There is a 
 wide difference between portraiture or descriptive art, and the 
 symbolic art which produces, for example, a painting of Jus- 
 tice or a statue of Psyche ; but it is plain that each equally 
 furnishes media for representative cognition. 
 
 rise to a style of decorative art not representative, and called, after them, 
 the arabesque. Like music, it does not mean anything, but is in itself 
 beautiful. 
 
 That is simply negative ; but what is to misrepresent ? Shylock, posed 
 as a tyi^ical, representative Jew, is a misrepresentation. So say the Jews. 
 The portrait is not a likeness. It was drawn by the master when there were 
 no Jews in England. It was the outcome of tradition, .spite, and tyranny. 
 Shakespeare never saw a Jew. In like manner they denounce Isaac of York 
 as a misrepresentation. They claim Sir Moses Montefiore and Baron Hirsck 
 as true representatives of the modern race. 
 
 1 Ophelia's flowers were representative; but Peter Bell's primrose "a 
 yellow primrose was to him, and nothing more." 
 
154 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 § 153. The medium in representation may also be, and 
 usually is, a mental image, an idea. The power which mind 
 has of forming- mental images of its past experiences has often 
 been mentioned. It belongs to the essential constitution of 
 mind, is an element in all intellectual exercise, and a thor- 
 ough knowledge of it is of the highest importance in psy- 
 chology. The power is unique, peculiar, and therefore inde- 
 finable and indescribable, but every one is familiar with it in 
 his own consciousness. 
 
 I see a book lying before me, and apprehend it merely as. 
 an object of perception. Now I shut my eyes. I no longer 
 literally see the book, it is not now depicted on my retina, 
 but I have a mental image of it, I still see it with " my mind's 
 eye." Yesterda}^ I was angry. To-day I muse, I meditate 
 upon my anger. I form an image of it which I contemplate. 
 I have just read a vivid description of the battle of Waterloo. 
 I reflect upon it, and have formed by aid of the description 
 an image of the scene, its exact military movements inter- 
 weaving with its noisy confusion and horror. Our minds are 
 constantly occupied, or rather engaged, with such images 
 or ideas representative of remote objects.-^ 
 
 The mental image has no existence apart from the mental 
 
 1 The word idea, introduced into philosophy by Plato, worthy of all honor 
 because of its own soft beavity, its rich setting, its antiquity and its paternity, 
 has been and is greatly abused, being most frequently mispronounced by the 
 vulgar, and constantly misapplied by the specialist. See its lamentable 
 history detailed by Hamilton, in lieid, note G, p. 025 sq. ; and in Discnssio)is, 
 p. 75, note. Cf. Trench, EnriJish Past and Present, p. 154. Hamilton pro- 
 nounces it unlitted for scientific use. But we cannot spare it, and shall 
 use it legitimately, as strictly synonymous with mental image, and so repre- 
 senting an individual. Let it not be confused with the concept, which also 
 is representative, but is a general notion, i.e. applicable to a plurality of 
 individuals. 
 
 Seneca marks the distinction between i54a and eUos thus : When a sculp- 
 tf)r hews a statue of Venus, she is his idia ; the statue is the eiSos, the idol, or 
 marble image. The I8^a is out of and before the work, the eJSos is in the 
 work. — Epist. 58, §§ 15-18. So Milton : 
 
 " God saw liis works were good, 
 Auswering hie fair ideu." 
 
REPRESENTATION. 155 
 
 act. I image a centaur. What is this centaur? It has no 
 externally real, but only an ideal existence. It is only an 
 image, and as such is an indivisible mode of mind. The 
 cognition and its object are in fact identical. As relative to 
 the mind knowing, it is called a cognition, an act of knowl- 
 edge, an exercise of the imaging power, etc. ; as relative to 
 the externally unreal but conceivable possibility which it 
 represents, it is called a representation, a subject-object, an 
 image, an idea, etc. But the act and the object are the 
 same. 
 
 § 154. We say these images are formed by the mind, are 
 of the mind, etc. To say, as is quite common, that they are 
 in the mind is misleading. We are very apt to think of them 
 as literal images, as little miniatures or models or pictures 
 of the things they represent, very like them on a small scale, 
 and located in the mind or brain, entirely apart from their 
 originals. Images, however, being mental modes, neither 
 shape, nor size, nor place can be attributed to them. The 
 shape, size, and place they seem to have are identical with 
 those of the thing represented. Where is my image of the 
 book on which I shut my eyes ? Out there on the table. 
 Where is my image of Waterloo? In Belgium. Where is 
 my image of the celestial sphere ? In the heavens, and as 
 vast as they. Where is my image of yesterday's anger? 
 Nowhere. It is referred to past time, but not to place, 
 since no mental affection can have locality. It is obvious 
 that figure, size, place, etc., are qualities of the thing imaged 
 and not of the image itself. They are merely represented, 
 as truly so as the color, material, etc., of the originals. We 
 might as well say that the image has actual color, as to say 
 that it has actual place. 
 
 § 155. Mental images are always sensuous, that is, they 
 represent objects of sense, external or internal, given in 
 some former experience. They consist of, or are con- 
 
156 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 structed, so to speak, from materials collected by experience. 
 In this view, we may say that the image re-presents, that 
 is, presents again, what has already been given or presented ; 
 so that what was formerly cognized is now recognized. I 
 cannot image what I never experienced. Even the most 
 bizarre imaginings are combined, like the centaur, out of 
 fragments of experiences. I cannot image a logical absurd- 
 ity. A biangular figure is non-sense.^ 
 
 Moreover, a thing is always represented as the object of the 
 sense originally perceiving it. The sound of a trumpet we 
 represent as assailing the ear; its brazen color, as dazzling 
 the eye ; its surface, as smooth to the touch, etc. These 
 images of various percepts combine, however, in one com- 
 plex image, in a single representation of a thing. It should 
 be noted that though visual images are so constantly present 
 and so vivid that the language of this subject is largely 
 derived from them, yet we form as well images of sounds, of 
 tastes, of odors, of tactile and muscular impressions, of vis- 
 ceral pleasure and pain, and of oljjects of self-perception.- 
 
 § 156. Images are always representative. An absolute 
 image is a contradiction, for the image is essentially relative. 
 It always stands for, or is vicarious of, a remote object, one 
 either real, or at least logically possible. 
 
 Representation by an image, like representation by an 
 object, has two modes ; the image is either an imitation or a 
 symbol. I can represent a horse by an image of one stand- 
 ing before me, an image of myself as an observer being per- 
 haps always a part of the total representation. I can image 
 a triangle representing primarily a real figure, and second- 
 
 i At first glance these statements may seem inconsistent •with the theory 
 of pure ideas already discussed at length, pt. ii, chs. 0, 7. Hut it should he 
 observed that by pure idea is meant an idea of a pure or non-sensuous 
 object, e.g. space. Such an object can be entertained only symbolically, 
 through or by means of some sensuous, representative, mental image or idea. 
 See especially § 1.'>1. 
 
EEPEESENTATION. 157 
 
 arily all possible triangles. In these cases the image is 
 ideally mimetic or exemplar. 
 
 I cannot thus image the Chinese Empire ; it is too com- 
 plex. I cannot image virtue, or any other abstraction not a 
 percept of sense. But I entertain thege cognitions by means 
 of images symbolical of them. The symbol may be merely 
 the name, which I image as heard, or as seen in print, which 
 then represents primarily the real sound or print, and second- 
 arily the thing or things of which it is the name.^ 
 
 1 "The product of the representative power, or the object which the mind 
 creates and apprehends in memory and imagination, has been the occasion 
 of much confusion of thought, and not a Uttle controversy. Scarcely any 
 single topic has been more vexed in ancient or medifeval philosophy, than 
 the nature of ideas or representative images. As the term idea in the Eng- 
 lish language is applied to the widest possible range of objects, so these con- 
 troversies either include or trench upon almost every possible question in 
 metaphysical philosophy, beginning with the images or species, material or 
 quasi-material, that were supposed to be given off from every object perceived 
 [see Ueberweg, Hist, of Phil., § 25], and ending with those eternal ideas 
 which Plato and his followers hold to be the archetypes of all created beings, 
 and which they even hypostatized into actual and almost divine agents. 
 These controversies and questions respect ideas of perception, of memory, of 
 imagination, and of thought — ideas a posteriori, or ideas of experience, and 
 ideas a priori, or ideas that are original and necessary. But to all these the 
 ideas of the memory and imagination have a very close relation, and hence a 
 just determination of their real nature will go very far toward an accurate 
 understanding and a satisfactory solution of the questions and controversies 
 which concern the remainder." — Porter, Hum. Intdl., § 224. 
 
 '^ OF THT^ 
 
 
158 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 CHAPTER II. 
 
 MEDIATE PERCEPTION. 
 
 § 157. Perception taken strictly is immediate. Each sense 
 has its special percept, the inner sensory excited in a special 
 manner. Sight and touch make a conscious reference of 
 their percepts to space, thus furnishing a consciousness of 
 extension. In resistance to voluntary locomotion is given 
 the existence of an outer world. These results of the anal}-- 
 sis of perception are in themselves very meagre, but they 
 constitute the sufficient foundation of knowledofe. From 
 them and their combinations, we make inferences, and com- 
 bine inferences with inferences, and thus attain a detailed 
 knowledge of the material universe. 
 
 This inferred knowledge is in certain cases so clear, exact, 
 and reliable that it seems to be direct conscious perception. 
 We seem to see directly the house out yonder, to hear the 
 bell and the birds, to smell the flowers, to feel the fanning 
 breeze, and the firm ground beneath our feet.^ But each of 
 these is a complex total involving a percept as one element, 
 all other elements being the results of inference. Since the 
 percept is a vivid element, and since the whole is usually 
 esteemed simple, it is commonly spoken of as a thing per- 
 ceived.^ We should discriniinate, however, between the 
 primary percept and the inferred matters associated -with it. 
 These supplementary cognitions are mere images or mental 
 
 1 "This universal and primary opinion of all men is soon destroyed by 
 the slightest philosophy. Thi! table which we see seems to lUniinish as we 
 remove further from it ; but the real table which exists independently of us 
 suffers no alteration ; it is, therefore, nothing but its image which is present- 
 to the mind." — IIijmk, Essays^ vol. ii, p. 154. 
 
 ' See § 97 and its notes. 
 
MEDIATE PERCEPTION. 159 
 
 representations, and may fairly be called represented per- 
 ceptions, or secondary perceptions, or still better, mediat(! 
 perceptions. The process by which they are obtained I,; 
 usually termed the education of sense, and hence they have 
 also been called acquired perceptions, which name is some- 
 times, though inaccurately, understood to imply that the 
 senses acquire power to perceive more than their original 
 percepts. 
 
 § 158. Let us take a simple example, and then attempt a 
 general explanation. An orange, a thing we will suppose 
 new to me, is placed in my hand. I perceive by handling 
 that it has a rough surface, that it is spherical, solid, and 
 heavy. By sight I simultaneously perceive a yellow color, 
 mottled and shaded, having a circular figure. Now I iden- 
 tify the rough sphere with the colored circle ; for as I move 
 it with my hand, the pictorial aspect changes concomitantly 
 with the tactile and muscular impressions, and I infer that 
 they have a common cause. What I see is what I handle ; 
 and I not only attribute the perceived color to it as the 
 cause, but I project the color upon that outer thing. So 
 also, what I smell or taste is the same thing that I handle 
 and see. 
 
 If next day I should see on my table a circular yellow 
 figure, mottled and shaded, I would recognize the figure and 
 color, and attribute to the thing sphericity, solidity, weight, 
 roughness, flavor, etc. Combining what is presented by 
 sight with what is thus represented by images, I would 
 recognize the whole as an orange ; and because the visual 
 percept is the given and most obtrusive element in this com- 
 plex cognition, I would say I see an orange. 
 
 § 159. Now, in general : That the change in my conscious- 
 ness in case of a single percept, is caused by something, 
 this I intuitively know. When two or more percepts of 
 different senses occur, when the impressions are simulta- 
 
160 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 neous and their variations concomitant, I inf erentially attrib- 
 ute these imjDressions to the same thing as their cause, 
 regarding them as qualities of that thing, that is, as powers 
 belonging to it, and capable of producing these effects in 
 me. Thus I assemble upon one thing or substance as one 
 object of cognition the various qualities perceived, and it 
 becomes as completely known as is jDossible by sense. 
 
 Secondly, in case of a similar set of experiences, I infer 
 inductively that the cause is the same or similar, and this 
 constitutes recognition. Soon I go so far as to hazard the 
 general induction that whenever I experience such effects 
 they arise from the same or a similar cause. 
 
 Thirdly, having observed that a certain set of qualities 
 accompanj^ each other, I regard each as characteristic of the 
 thing. Now when any one is ex]3erienced as a percept, I 
 infer the presence in the thing of the rest, and supply them 
 to it by a mental image. 
 
 Finally, these experiences and inferences having been 
 often repeated, the several qualities become associated in the 
 mind with each other, so that upon the presentation of any 
 one of the distinctive percepts, the rest are suggested 
 immediately, that is, without any renewal of the process of 
 inference, and the complementary image or images are at 
 once supplied. 
 
 Such, in general, is the genesis of mediate perceiDtions. 
 They are evidently logical judgments or thoughts, retained 
 in memory by association with percepts. Therefore, it should 
 be particularly observed that mediate perception is not at 
 all a distinct, special faculty of mind, but a combined exercise 
 of several faculties. 
 
 § 160. It should further be observed that our senses, 
 strictly taken, never deceive us. When we consciously per- 
 ceive a color, a sound, an odor, it is impossible even to con- 
 ceive that we have mistaken sometliing else for color, for 
 sound, for odor. A jaundiced man seems to sec all thino-s 
 
MEDIATE PERCEPTION. 161 
 
 tinged with yellow. We may easily convince him that the 
 tilings are not yellow, but it is impossible for him to doubt 
 that he perceives j^ellow. A ringing in the ears we may 
 take for a distant bell. We mistake about the bell, but not 
 about a sense-perception of sound. ^ 
 
 But the mediate process of acquisition described above 
 involves at least one inference from effect to cause. This 
 induction is liable to the fallacy called "plurality of causes." 
 A variety of causes may .produce indistinguishable effects. 
 The sound by which I am affected, and which I judge to be 
 caused by a steam- whistle, may in fact be caused by a trumpet. 
 The doubtful induction is a source of error or delusion in our 
 acquired perceptions, and we pronounce our senses untrust- 
 worthy. It is not, however, the sense that errs, but the 
 judgment. Now in every case of illusion, and indeed when- 
 ever delusion is conceivably possible, the matter is not given, 
 but judged; is not presented, but represented.^ 
 
 § 161. Let us remark and illustrate the final step in the 
 genesis described above (§ 159). When a number of percepts 
 have become closely linked by association, the experience of 
 
 1 See Leibnitz, quoted in § 69, note. Says Kant : " Wahrlieit oder Schein 
 sind nicht im Gegenstande, so feme er angescliaut wird, sondern im Urtheile 
 iiber deuselben, so feme er gedaclit wird. Man kann also zwar richtig sagen 
 dass die Sinne nicht irren, aber niclit daruin, weil sie jederzeit riclitig ur- 
 tiieilen, sondern weil sie gar nicht urtheilen." — Kritik der r. V., p. 238. 
 
 2 Delusion believes something false to be true ; it attributes to a fallacious 
 appearance objective reality. Illusion occurs when one is not actually de- 
 ceived, yet cannot resist an impression known to be false in fact, and a mere 
 subjective affection. Delusions are what Bacon calls idols of the den (idola 
 specus^ § 220). A deep pool of clear water looked at aslant seems shallow, 
 and if I take it to be shallow, this is a delusion. My walking- cane put half- 
 way and aslant in the water seems crooked ; but since I know it to be 
 straight, this is merely an illusion. The pretty story told by Tliny of the 
 contest between Zeuxis and Parrhasius recites cases of delusion. The mirage 
 of the desert is to the ignorant a delusion, to the informed an illusion. 
 Dreams are delusive. Hallucinations are abnormal, and either illusive or 
 delusive ; e.g. a crazy beggar thinks himself a king, and in his rags sees 
 robes. See below, § 195, note. 
 
162 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 any one seems to cany with it the experience of the others. 
 Thus one sense apparently acquires power to perceive quali- 
 ties of objects that are originally given by other senses. For 
 example, an orange looks rough, an apple smooth, gloss 
 being an accepted sign of smoothness.^ Obviously this 
 apparent transfer of percepts is a mediate judgment, a given 
 percept being a sign of the presence of other perceptible 
 qualities, which are accordingly represented. To discrimi- 
 nate in a total complex cognition the elements that are 
 strictly presentative from those that are representative, we 
 make use of the criterion described in § 69. 
 
 § 162. It would be needless to consider the subject further, 
 were it not that there are certain cognitions relative to space 
 and extension in space, and given only in connection with 
 voluntary locomotion, which present peculiarities and diffi- 
 culties requiring special examination. 
 
 1 Strictly, I do not see, but judge them to be rough and smooth, and these 
 qualities are represented as felt by the fingers. See § 155, second paragraph. 
 In such case sight seems to have acquired power to perceive qualities known 
 only to touch. On the other hand, those who have become blind are some- 
 times able to distingui.sh the colors of cloth by touch. Those born blind, 
 however, know nothing about color. Locke tells of one who on handling 
 scarlet cloth said it felt to him like the sound of a trumpet. — Essay, bk. ii, 
 ch. 4, § 11. Beethoven, after he became quite deaf, would play the organ in 
 the dark, and greatly enjoy the music. By touch, or rather by manipulation, 
 he seemed to perceive sound. 
 
 Further illustrations : When I perceive a certain fragrance that suggests a 
 rose, T instantly supply by an image its visual aspect, and perhaps a tactile 
 feeling of its thorns. Without discriminating what is presented and what 
 represented, I say I smell a rose. So we judge of viands by smell. I do not 
 see the table before me, but a colored figure which is to me the sign of a 
 table. The mountain path looks wearisome, a nuiscular percept which I 
 represent in connection with the visual aspect of the path, and judge to 
 belong to it. We connect many objects with the sounds they emit. The 
 quality of a musical note enables us to recognize the instrument, and we 
 supply a visual image of it. We recognize animals by their cries, and a 
 friend by his voice, cough, or footfall. By tapping a barrel, we measure its 
 contents. By their ring we discriminate stone, wood, glass, iron, pottery, 
 and also base from good coin, when in tJiis case no sense except hearing 
 would perceive a difference. 
 
MEDIATE PERCEPTION. 163 
 
 We have found that none of the senses proper give us a 
 knowledge of the existence of extra-organic or outer thino-s, 
 and concluded that this is given only in connection with the 
 tactile and muscular senses by voluntary locomotion or 
 manipulation (§§ 105, 106). It follows that our knowledge 
 of outer things as they really exist in space, as to their num- 
 ber, shape, direction, size, distance, locality, etc., can be 
 given directly only by or in connection with the same 
 energy. 
 
 Since a percept can be represented only in the sense origi- 
 nally giving it, e.g. a color as seen, a sound as heard, etc. 
 (§ 155), so also these cognitions arising in manipulation or 
 voluntary locomotion can be truly represented only as in 
 that act. Nevertheless they seem to be direct perceptions 
 of sense. Sight being keenly perceptive and also cognizant 
 of extension, they are habitually associated with its exercise. 
 We shall therefore examine them more especially, as mediate 
 or acquired perceptions of sight. 
 
 § 163. The real unity or plurality of objects in space is 
 known directly and originally only in manipulation. We 
 commonly suj^pose that we directly see a single object to 
 be one thing. What we consciously see is only a colored 
 figure on the field of view. But things may not be as they 
 appear in this field. A single thing seen by one eye, may 
 be apparently two.i Also the rays from two or more objects 
 may be united so that we shall see but one. If we doubt, 
 we handle. 
 
 In binocular vision a single object is seen as one, although 
 there are two retinal pictures of it. This is not because it 
 is one, but because the double picture is associated with the 
 
 1 If we make two pin-holes in a card less than one-twelfth of an inch 
 apart, and, closing one eye, look through them with the other at a pin, we 
 see two pins. Iceland spar doubles a hair-line ; and the well-known " multi- 
 plying glass " makes many coins of one. 
 
164 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 judgment of one thing, known to be one by handling. ^ On 
 the contrary, the stereoscope presents two objects, but they 
 seem to be one, because the lenses cause the pictures to fall 
 on associated parts of the retinas. Whenever we have doubt 
 of physical integrity or suspect duplicity, we take the mat- 
 ter in hand, and test it by a grasp. Optical illusions in 
 general show that the unity or plurality of things is not pre- 
 sented in vision, but represented in manipulation. ^ 
 
 § 164. The geometrical solidity or shape of outer things 
 is not directly perceived, but only judged of by the eye. 
 
 ' Wheatstone holds that unity in binocular vision is an inference from the 
 mental combination of the two retinal pictures. Some physiologists have 
 explained it by supposing a special provision in the structure of the organ. 
 See MuUer, Phi/sioJogy, pp. 1197, 1205 ; also Carpenter, Physiology, p. 917. 
 Lotze explains it by his theory of local signs. Various views are held by the 
 physiological psychologists. See Ladd, Elements of, p. 420 sq. 
 
 If the forefinger be held vertically a foot from the eyes, and a pencil a foot 
 beyond, then on looking at the linger I see also two pencils, and vice versa. 
 If I squint, all objects depicted on " the yellow spot" {macula lutea, the 
 central and most sensitive portion of the retina) seem double. One whose 
 strabismus has been corrected has double vision. For example, every road 
 forks before him. The illusions continue until gradually he forms new judg- 
 ments and habits of sight. Tliese facts seem favorable to Wheatstone's view, 
 which we have adopted. On squinting, see Helmholtz, Physio. Optik., Fr. 
 tr., p. 882. 
 
 2 Nor is the i;nity of an outer thing discernible by touch alone. A pea 
 touched by the forefinger certainly seems single, just as when seen with one 
 eye. If touched by the fore and middle fingers, it still seems one, as when 
 seen with both eyes, and for the similar reason that simultaneous contact 
 with the adjacent sides of these fingers has long been an accepted sign of 
 a single body. Now let the middle finger be crossed over the forefinger, and 
 the pea placed between their tips ; I distinctly perceive two, as when I siiuint, 
 and for the similar reason that contact with the opposite sides of those fingers 
 usually indicate two things. The impression is aided, no doubt, by the fact 
 that surfaces concave to each other are a usual sign of unity, and surfaces 
 convex to each other (apparently so in this case) are a usual sign of duplex- 
 ity. This childish illusion, which interested and was discussed by Aristotle, 
 shows that unity is not, as commonly supposed, directly perceived by touch. 
 It is inferred, a mediate perception, given originally in voluntary handling, 
 sometimes called active touch. 
 
MEDIATE PERCEPTION. 165 
 
 The field of view may be regarded as a plane at right angles 
 to the optic axis. That the eye perceives the two dimen- 
 sions of figure as projected on this plane is obvious, but we 
 must remember that this figure is determined by the retinal 
 picture, and is not at all the superficial figure of any outer 
 thing (§ 19). A circle seen aslant depicts an ellipse, and it 
 is an ellipse that is actually seen, and not a circle, though 
 we may mediately judge it to be in reality a circle. The 
 real figure of the outer thing is known originally only by 
 manipulation. 1 
 
 The third dimension, since it does not at all exist in the 
 picture, the eye does not find there; and though we may 
 seem to see it, yet is it merely inferred from certain signs, 
 certain pictorial aspects, which we know, by experience in 
 handling under the eye, that solid bodies present.^ Thus a 
 sphere is actually seen as a circle, but the shading of its sur- 
 face is a sign by which from experience we judge, and say 
 we see, a sphere.^ 
 
 In binocular vision we have, besides the shading, yet 
 another means of judging geometrical solidity or shape. 
 In looking at a thick book, for example, lying on my table, 
 there are not only two pictures, one on each retina, but these 
 pictures are different, since the book is seen from different 
 points of view. Knowing from experience that the differ- 
 
 1 Volney observed, in a case of couching for cataract, that the patient^ 
 who was a good geometrician, not only distinguished plane figures as differ- 
 ent, but also correctly named the circle, the triangle, etc. But on being asked 
 how he was enabled to do this, he replied that he tried to think how they 
 would feel if he should pass his fingers over the outline. 
 
 2 " The ' old psychology ' was accustomed to hold that we cannot perceive 
 the third dimension with the eyes. This is undoubtedly erroneous. Depth 
 and distance are immediately perceived by sight." — Ladd, Outlines of Phys- 
 iological Psychology, p. 339. We quote this remarkable assertion merely to 
 show that other opinions are entertained. 
 
 3 The sun and moon, and the planets as seen through a telescope, being 
 destitute of this shading, appear to be flat discs, though we know them to 
 be and think of them as spheres. The shading is often exhibited on a flat 
 surface, as in good frescoes, so skilfully as completely to deceive us. 
 
166 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 ence is produced by a solid bod}-, I seem to see a solid, I 
 seem to see the third dimension. It is, however, merely 
 represented, and the judgment involved is called the stereo- 
 scopic judgment.^ 
 
 The physical solidity of outer bodies is known originally 
 in their resistance to voluntary locomotion. Mere contact is 
 usually an accepted sign of a physical solid. If we doubt, 
 we apply pressure as the test,^ Opacity is also a sign. But 
 to both touch and sight physical solidity is a mediate and 
 acquired perception, and occasionally they betray our trust.^ 
 
 In all cases of suspected error in any of these cognitions 
 originally given in voluntary locomotion, and acquired as 
 mediate perceptions by the other senses, we almost instinc- 
 tively have recourse to their source ; we test them by hand- 
 ling. This is why children and uncultivated people are so 
 strongly disposed to handle whatever they see. They show 
 thereby a lack of culture, it is true, but it is an indispen- 
 sable part of the process of culture. 
 
 1 From (TTepeSs a-KOTreTv, to see a solid. The pretty illusions of the reflecting 
 and refracting stereoscopes of Wheatstone and Brewster, which supply to 
 vision the requisite conditions, are familiar, and prove the mediate character 
 of this cognition. 
 
 Molyneux asked Locke whether a man born blind could on receiving sight 
 distinguish between a cube and a sphere by the eye alone. The question has 
 been much discussed. The answer is that he could distinguish the projected 
 plane figures as different, but could not know in them a cube and a sphere. 
 — Locke, Essay, ii, 9. Nunneley, On the Onjans of Vision, p. 31 (1858), 
 describes a case of couching with careful observations. See also Naville, 
 Bevue Scientifique, p. 943 (1887). The oldest but most famous case of 
 Cheselden is detailed m Philosophical Tra)isactions for 1728, No. 402. See 
 it quoted by Hamilton, Meta., p. 391 sq. ; and, with other cases, by McCosh, 
 Psychology, vol. i, p. 45 sq. All the observed facts in these cases confirm 
 the view we have adopted. 
 
 It is well worth noting that the giving sight to a man born blind, recorded 
 in John 9, was more than a physical miracle. He received not merely a 
 sense, but an educated sense, such as took Cheselden's patient many months 
 to acquire. 
 
 2 See Luke 24 : 39 ; and John 20 : 24-27. 
 
 8 For example, we sometimes mistake a panel mirror for an open door, 
 and attempt to pass through. 
 
MEDIATE PERCEPTION. 167 
 
 § 165. The perception of the direction of objects is a 
 mediate perception. The terms right and left, before and 
 behind, above and below, refer to my own position. They 
 are the names strictly of relations, and mere relations of 
 things are not at all objects of sense." The knowledge is 
 given in the movement of my limbs requisite to reach things, 
 or in the movement of my eyes requisite to see them. Upon 
 this experience rests the judgment of direction.^ 
 
 The tensions of the small muscles that move the eyeball 
 furnish a very delicate indication of direction. They cor- 
 respond with the various positions of the optic axis, so that 
 when this is turned from one object to another they tell of 
 the different directions, the sweep of the eye giving the 
 angular deviation. The estimate of an angle of difference 
 of direction by this movement of the eye reminds us of the 
 sweep of the index arm of a mariner's sextant.^ 
 
 The doctrine that an object is judged to be in the direc- 
 tion which the axial ray of light from it has on entering the 
 eye, is true, excepting that the last direction of the ray is 
 not at all the ground of the judgment; for of the ray, as 
 well as of the eye itself, we are utterly unconscious. The 
 accord between a visual judgment of direction and the last 
 line of light is because the latter most generally lies in the 
 
 1 The attitude of the body being erect, it seems not unlikely that we refer 
 a line of direction to three co-ordinate planes at right angles to each other, 
 one horizontal through the eyes, the others vertical, one of which passes 
 through the ears, and the three having their common point in the middle of 
 the head. If it be true that we naturally figure to ourselves in a vague way 
 this construction, each one thus assuming himself to be a centre of things 
 and an origin of co-ordinates, then the Cartesian system of rectangular co- 
 ordinates was not so much an invention as a discovery. 
 
 2 On the authority of Wundt we have that " one sviffering from paresis of 
 the right external muscle of the eye, so that the nmscle is not able by the 
 utmost effort to effect a lateral movement of more than 20", locates an object, 
 which in reality is only 20° distant from the median plane, at a point so far 
 ovitward as corresponds to the utmost outward movement of the normal eye, 
 and, when asked to touch the object, places his finger far beyond it to the 
 right." — See Baldwin, Psychology, p. 128, note. 
 
168 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 true direction. The ground of judgment, originally certain 
 muscular impressions, is transferred to certain visual im- 
 pressions. These, not the last direction of the light, some- 
 times mislead us. It is thus that refraction, reflection, and 
 aberration cause illusions; for example, the sun appears to 
 have fully risen, when it is in reality still below the 
 horizon.^ 
 
 In explaining visible direction, the complete inversion of 
 the retinal picture has been a great puzzle. But it is easily 
 solved by the consideration that we are unconscious of the 
 retinal picture itself. Being conscious only of the impres- 
 sions which it determines on the inner sight centre, we 
 judge from them of direction according to experience. But 
 on any supposition, the inversion of everything is equiva- 
 lent to the inversion of nothing. Total inversion does not 
 change or modify any spatial relations whatever. ^ 
 
 § 166. The ear learns to estimate direction. There is an 
 axis of hearing, the line passing through the two ears. 
 Experience teaches that the most distinct sounds come in 
 the direction of this line. We judge that the sound having 
 a maximum distinctness in one ear, and a minimum in the 
 other, has its source in the direction of the auricular axis. 
 An angle formed at the ear by this axis with a radius of the 
 aerial waves, and estimated by the degree of distinctness, 
 
 1 Like a coin viewed aslant in a teacup of water. 
 
 2 This last is Miiller's explanation. — Hum. J'hys., p. 910. It is adopted 
 by Carpenter, who objects to Brewster's theory that the Ime of visible 
 direction is immediately given by the path of the axial ray. Le Conte revives 
 Brewster's theory thus: "Each focal impression is referred back to its 
 corresponding radiant, and thus the external image is reconstructed in space 
 in its true position, or is reinverted in the act of projection." — Sight, p. 85. 
 This is merely a geometrical fancy, without a fact to support it. Our knowl- 
 edge of the direction and relative position of objects seen is an aquisition by 
 sight from our experience in handling them. When we dress before a mirror, 
 we perform a series of partial inversions, perplexing at first, but soon as easy 
 as if we were working under direct vision. So also the microscopist and 
 teiescopist adjust themselves to the inversions of their lenses. 
 
MEDIATE PERCEPTION. 169 
 
 also enables one to perceive the direction of the sonorous 
 
 centre. 
 
 But the judgment of direction by the ear is much less 
 accurate and reliable than by the eye, since the ear has no 
 appendages similar to the muscles of the eyeball for counter- 
 checking its estimates ; and also because the aerial Avaves are 
 not so rigidly direct as the ethereal rays. Frequent illusions 
 warn us and impair our confidence. Yet we as truly hear 
 the direction of a sonorous body as we see that of a luminous 
 one. The art of ventriloquism lies chiefly in a skilful 
 mimicry of sounds, so that in spite of reason we misjudge, 
 on grounds of experience and confirmed association, their 
 direction as well as their distance and source. ^ 
 
 § 167. The size of things, and their distance from each 
 other and from me, are given originally only in voluntary 
 locomotive energy. Size or comparative magnitude is meas- 
 ured extension taken as a quality of body. It is given 
 directly in differences of grasp for small bodies, in differ- 
 ences of reach for the larger, and in differences of total 
 movement, as in walking over or about them, for the largest. 
 Distance is the measured extension of the free space between 
 bodies. It is similarly given. What is meant by an object's 
 being four yards from wheje I stand ? This at least, that it 
 would require a certain number of paces to come up to it, a 
 certain amount of voluntary effort, a certain expenditure of 
 muscular energy. The true and ultimate meaning, then, 
 of size and distance, as objects of experience, is tactile and 
 muscular in connection with voluntary locomotion. ^ 
 
 1 One of the most pleasing of illusions is echo. Other senses learn to 
 estimate direction. We are led by smell in the direction of fire. We can 
 perceive muscularly, while walking at night, our direction pretty well, but 
 an inexperienced person is liable to wander. 
 
 2 When I say that yonder log is six yards long and a yard in circumfer- 
 ence, this ultimately means that it would take so many strides to traverse its 
 length, and the full extent of my arms to embrace it. To get an idea of a 
 mile, I must travel it, and a hundred miles is a hundred times that energy. 
 
170 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 Each of the special senses acquires power to discern dis- 
 tance; that is, each of the percepts becomes a ground on 
 which we estimate it. We judge of distance by smell, and 
 even by taste, as when we perceive that we are approaching 
 the sea by the taste of its salty air. The mediate perception 
 of distance by sound is habitual. The sharp clap of thunder 
 is near ; the long, subdued roll is far off. We hear the bay- 
 ing of our hunting-hounds, and perceive that they are half a 
 mile away. By the sound of footsteps on a pavement at 
 night we hear them first approach, and then recede. Hence 
 many illusions. The exciting crescendo of an unseen trum- 
 pet seems to advance; the soothing diminuendo seems to 
 recede, and die away in the distance. Similarly the ven- 
 triloquist, imitating the count of a regiment in line, pro- 
 duces an illusive vista of sounds ; and by playing in many 
 ways, with our accustomed sonorous perspective, he cheats, 
 not our ears, but our judgments, and sets them to contra- 
 dicting each other. 
 
 § 168. The estimate of the size and distance of near 
 objects by the eye involves several elements. The visual 
 angle, or the angle at the eye which the object subtends, 
 measures the apparent size on the field of view.^ Now, 
 
 An infant crawls about its nursery, and handles all it can get hold of, thus 
 investigating size and distance. The natural standards are taken from the 
 human body ; as, the inch, or thumb joint ; the span ; the foot ; the cubit, or 
 forearm ; the yard, or arm's length or a stride ; the fathom, or a man's 
 height, or reach with both arms; the league (Ger. Stxinde), or an hour's 
 walk, etc. This accords with the ultimate muscular meaning of size and 
 distance. So also my tongue tacitly tells me the size of a morsel. 
 
 1 The visual angle should be distinguished from the optic angle. The 
 latter is the angle formed by the optic axes of the eyes, and has its apex in 
 a ijoint of the object seen. It varies inversely with the distance. It has been 
 supposed by Brewster and many others that the knowledge of this angle, 
 given by the tension of the external and internal recti muscles, enables us to 
 judge the distance of near objects. To this is added the tension of the ciliary 
 muscle, altering the convexity of the crystalline lens (Ilelmholtz). But 
 Wheatstone ascertained by exix-riments that "unless other signs accompany 
 
MEDIATE PERCEPTION. 171 
 
 since this apparent size is a projection of real size, it is 
 obvious that there is a certain direct correspondence between 
 them, and that the one furnishes, in part, ground for judging 
 the other. 
 
 But it is also obvious that apparent size depends not 
 merely on real size, but also upon the distance from the 
 observer. Apparent size varies inversely as the square of 
 the distance. But the distance, having no projection, no 
 representative, on the field of view, can be judged only 
 indirectly, and with much uncertainty. ^ 
 
 Apparent size is given. If real size be known, distance 
 may be estimated. If distance be known, real size may be 
 estimated. If neither real size nor distance be known, one 
 of the two must first be estimated in order to judge the 
 other. Which comes usually first? Since distance has no 
 projection or representative on the field of view, evidently 
 there will first be an estimate of size in order to an estimate 
 of distance.^ 
 
 The distance of two objects from each other is estimated 
 ocularly by judging first their real size; then, if they are 
 
 the sensation of convergence of the optic axes, the notion of distance we 
 thence derive is uncertain and obscure." For example, the vision of a single 
 luminous point shining in the dark. See Phil. Trans, for 1852, Bakerian 
 Lecture, by Sir Charles Wheatstone. 
 
 1 Thus the full moon is as large as the sun, though the intense brightness 
 ■of the sun makes the false impression that it occupies more space on the 
 field of view. The moon appears much larger than Jupiter, and still larger 
 than Sirius, and these projected on the face of the sky may be so situated 
 as to appear at equal distances from each other. All this is unreal. A dime 
 held up in the field of view eclipses the moon, and the moon in turn eclipses 
 the sun, all in one apparent place. And so of terrestrial objects. A book in 
 my hand is as large as the window, i.e. it occupies as much of the area of 
 vision. A straw stuck on the window-pane is as high as the pine tree beyond, 
 and as the further mountain. A carriage moving off from me is a striking 
 experience. At first it rapidly, and then more slowly, dwindles. But the 
 carriage itself does not grow smaller ; hence what I see is not the carriage. 
 See § 157, note. 
 
 2 This conclusion thus reached a priori is the same as that reached by 
 Wheatstone a posteriori, or by experiment. 
 
172 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 in a line with the observer, his own estimated distance from 
 each gives, by subtraction, their distance from each other; 
 if not in line with liini, an easy method of natural triangu- 
 lation ascertains the distance, and this, by practice, with 
 remarkable accuracy.^ 
 
 § 169. The estimate of the size and distance of objects 
 more than twenty feet away depends mainlj- upon perspec- 
 tive. Ground perspective, as it is technically called, is 
 determined by the number and arrangement of objects in the 
 field of view. Some of these being known in respect of size 
 or distance, furnish means for judging others. The simplest 
 case is that of a vista, as an avenue of trees, or the houses 
 along a street. All lines parallel to the line of sight seem 
 to meet it in the vanishing-point on the horizon, and the 
 length of all vertical lines, as the height of the trees, 
 houses, columns, etc., apparently diminishes in the ratio of 
 the distance. In case of a landscape, a known object, as a 
 man in the middle ground, enables us to appreciate the size, 
 distance, and relative position of objects in the fore and 
 back grounds.^ 
 
 1 Then scientific trigonometry is not so mucli an invention as a discovery. 
 
 Tliat distance, as discerned by sight, is not at all an original but a second- 
 ary perception, was maintained by Berkeley in his Essay toward a New 
 TJieory of Vision (1709), a prelude to his doctrine of the Perception of a 
 Material World. See § 1.30. The latter has been generally rejected, the 
 former as generally accepted. It is noteworthy that Descartes, in his treatise 
 on Dioptric, anticipated, in every point, the views of Berkeley respecting 
 vision. See especially Discourse, vi. 
 
 For further proof we add tlie pathological fact, that in case of paralysis of 
 of the abductor muscle of the eye, the patient sees objects further from him 
 than they really are. A stonemason afflicted with this disease strikes his 
 hand with the hammer Instead of hitting the stone (Wundt). But little by 
 little lie recovers his judgment of distance, thougli by great effort. ' 
 
 - Optical illusions are so frequent tliat the word apparent is used in oppo- 
 sition to 7-eal (v{. apparition). The full moon and the sun, when near the 
 horizon, appear larger and further tlian when overhead, though, in fact, the 
 angular diameter is then somewhat less. This is because at the horizon 
 intervening objects furnish a perspective. If we cut off this by looking 
 
MEDIATE PERCEPTION. 173 
 
 Aerial perspective or atmosphere is the greater or less dim- 
 ness or distinctness of an object. This, having been found 
 to vary with the distance, furnishes a basis of estimate. 
 Thus we judge the relative distances of mountain peaks ris- 
 ing above and beyond each other, and becoming more and 
 more dim.^ 
 
 The art of landscape-painting depends on the principles 
 of perspective. In early life, before the visual signs of real 
 size and distance have been investigated, and the secondary 
 perception acquired, it is probable that a real landscape is 
 viewed as an erect surface like a picture. An important 
 part of the education of artists consists in learning to view 
 landscapes thus, in order to depict them, which is called by 
 Ruskin "recovering the innocence of the eye." 
 
 § 170. The definite location of the percepts of touch on 
 parts of the skin is an acquired perception. It is evident 
 that we cannot locate these percepts unless we have knowl- 
 edge of the superficial form of the body. If my foot and 
 shoulder be lightly struck, I would surely be conscious that 
 the contacts were two, even if simultaneous, and this doubt- 
 less by virtue of the independence of the nerve connections; 
 but I could not locate the contacts without some knowledge 
 of the localities. Now a knowledge of the superficial extent 
 or shape of my body is acquired by the voluntary locomotion 
 of one part, as the hand, over other parts. Having thus 
 learned it, I entertain a representative image of my figure, 
 
 through a tube, the estimate is instantly reduced. For the same reason the 
 dome of the sky appears flattened, or less than a hemisphere. A landsman's 
 estimate of distance at sea is liable to be very erroneous, his accustomed 
 basis of ground perspective being wanting. 
 
 1 In the clear air of Italy the background of the landscape seems much 
 . nearer than in hazy England. A man seen in a fog appears gigantic ; the 
 aerial effect overcomes and reverses the usual order (§ 168) ; we overestimate 
 his distance first, and then his size. On illusions see Keid, Inquu-ij into the 
 Hummi Mind, ch. 6, § 22 ; also Brewster, Letters to Sir Walter Scott on 
 Natural Magic; also Memoirs of Bohert Houdin, an autobiography. 
 
174 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 and then it becomes possible to Ibcate a contact on the foot, 
 or hand, or trunk, or head. But since this is done through 
 a representative knowledge of my superficial figure, it 
 follows that this localization is representative, mediate, and 
 acquired. 1 
 
 Moreover, if a tactile sensory nerve trunk be tied with a 
 thread, all parts of the skin supplied by it become wholly 
 insensible; but if the trunk be irritated above the thread, 
 pain is felt, which, however, is referred to those parts, 
 although the nervous communication with them is entirely 
 cut off. So when the foot is asleep, the disagreeable sen- 
 sation of numbness, which is distinctly referred to the foot, 
 is because of an injurious pressure of a trunk nerve, per- 
 haps in the thigh, and we greatly mistake the true situs of 
 the disturbance. Such facts show that the definite location 
 of the sense-percept is mediate. The remarkable illusion, 
 known in surgery as "the phantom limb," not only accords 
 with, but strongly confirms this view.^ 
 
 What has been said of the location of tactile sense-percepts 
 is true of cutaneous sensations generally, and also of all 
 
 1 See § 24, note on "local signs." When a babe is hurt by a pin, it 
 screams with pain, but shows no sign of knowing where the hurt is. Some- 
 times the dentist pulls the wrong tooth, because we cannot tell him certainly 
 which one it is that aches. 
 
 2 After an arm has been amputated the patient still locates sense-percep- 
 tions in a representation of it. He will say : My hand is open ; now it is 
 shut. I am touching my little finger with my thumb, etc. An irritation in 
 the stump he feels in the phantom hand. Muller insists that " these illusions 
 are permanent and preserve the same intensity throughout life." — /'/«?/s., 
 p. 043.- Vulpian, Carpenter, Spring, and others, hold the contrary. Also 
 Dr. S. Weir Mitchell, who has made a special study of the phantom limb, 
 says: "The site of the amputation does not seem to exercise any influence 
 upon the consciousness of the existence of the limb, but in time, if not 
 reminded by pain or other subjective symptom, the patient is apt to lose 
 sense of the presence of the part, and this, I think, is most liable to occur 
 as regards the leg." — Lessons of the Nerves, p. 350 ; cf. p. 350. That is, 
 the old judgments of locality are gradually replaced by new ones. 
 
 It was this curious fact that led Descartes to explain localization by asso- 
 ciation. See remarks by Coleridge, Biog. Lit., oh. 5. Also by Ribot, Ger. 
 Psych., pp. 111-2. 
 
MEDIATE PERCEPTION. 175 
 
 internal sensations. The latter, however, owing probably to 
 the comparative sparseness of the nerve connections and to 
 their being less accessible to observation, are localized with 
 more difficulty and less accuracy. Painful disturbances of 
 the liver, the spleen, the kidneys, are hardly distinguish- 
 able, and are often misplaced even by those who know some- 
 thing of their own anatomy. The well-informed physician 
 often applies local remedies to parts remote from those where 
 the pain is distinctly felt. 
 
 § 171. Let us consider another curious and significant 
 fact. If I touch a rough wall with the end of a rod, the 
 roughness is not perceived at the hand grasping the rod, but 
 beyond, at the wall. Moreover, I locate the sensation also 
 at the remote end of the rod, rather than in my body. Tlie 
 end of the rod seems to be sensitive. I feel out there the 
 roughness and hardness. The perception apparently carries 
 the sensation perforce along with it out of my body ; or we 
 might say, my personality seems enlarged and extended to 
 the point of the rod. Upon this principle depends the 
 efficacy of tools. If we felt merely their contact with the 
 hand, and not their hold and movement on the material, 
 they would be unmanageable and useless. So the knife and 
 fork, the knitting and the sewing needle. So the probe of 
 the surgeon ; he feels the bottom of the wound. The stick 
 of the groping blindman seems to him a part of himself. 
 This extension of tactile and muscular sense-perception 
 beyond the periphery is obviously representative and ac- 
 quired.i 
 
 1 This feeling of enlarged personality is quite remarkable. If I hold a rod 
 by the middle, I feel its weight only ; but if by any other part, or if balanced 
 vertically on my finger, I feel its length, and am carried out beyond myself 
 to that extent. If I swing a plumb-line, I feel its length; the plumb has 
 become a part of me, and describes my own circumference. If I balance a 
 bowl on the tip of my finger inside, and some one taps its edge with a stick, 
 I feel the expanse of the bowl. 
 
 This will account perhaps for some fancies in dress. High heels give a. 
 
176 MEDIATE KISOWLEBGE. 
 
 The i)ercepts of our other senses are also located upon 
 what is conceived to be their proximate cause. As Ave 
 assign tangibility to what is perceived to be in contact with 
 the skill, so we locate the red color on the rose, and Ave 
 assign the blue to the sky, even after we have found out 
 there is no such thing as a sky. We locate the blast of a 
 trumpet in its throat, the peal of a church-bell in the 
 steeple, sweetness in the sugar, and perfume in the violet. 
 If, however, I have learned that odor is caused by an ether, 
 I may come to represent it as diffused in the ambient air. 
 The physicist, who is accustomed to represent sound as 
 aerial vibration, will locate the tones of the bell, not in the 
 steeple, but in its atmosphere. In these cases, the sensa- 
 tion, if located at all, is referred to one's own body, generally 
 to the organ of sense in exercise. 
 
 feeling of height from the ground up. A man sets his beaver square on his 
 head, and feels its weight only ; a dandy sets his a little to one side, feels 
 its swing, and is elevated to its centre of gravity. So the waving curls and 
 floating sash of a young miss, and the long train of a duchess, give a wide 
 and enjoyable sweep to their feeling of presence. 
 
 It will also account, in part at least, for our fondness for horseback 
 exercise. A rider is more than a man ;• he is, in one word, a horseman. He 
 feels the stroke of the horse's feet on the ground ; feels it himself to be hard 
 or soft ; feels the animal's strength and speed to be his own. and will say, I 
 have just galloped a mile, when in fact it was the horse only that galloped. 
 Perhaps the myth of the centaur took its rise from this feeling. 
 
 Lotze discusses these feelings at some length. See Mikrokosmus, bk. v, 
 Geisty ch. 2, Die menchliche sinnlichkeit. 
 
SUGGESTION. 177 
 
 CHAPTER III. 
 
 SUGGESTION. 
 
 § 172. Before discussing the specific powers of mediate 
 knowledge, it is needful to consider the sequence of mental 
 states. Perceptions being dependent on the presentation of 
 external objects, the order in which they follow each other 
 is determined from without and not by the mind. Repre- 
 sentations, being wholly subjective, and so independent of 
 external objects, their order of sequence must be either 
 altogether fortuitous, or else determined by some principle 
 of the mind itself. We are conscious of a constantly chang- 
 ing train of mediate cognitions ; one follows another unceas- 
 ingly. Evidently they do not arise at hap-hazard, but are 
 connected by bonds which determine the train. 
 
 Logical sequence occurs when one or more cognitions 
 implicitly contain one other which the process of thinking 
 explicates.^ The sequence is intrinsic in the thoughts 
 themselves. The individual thinker propels the train, but 
 does not determine its order: this is the same in all minds, 
 being independent of experience and habit. 
 
 Suggested sequence occurs when a present mental state 
 induces the repetition of a past similar state with its associa- 
 tions. This bond between the present and the past is estab- 
 lished by the experience, and strengthened by the habits of 
 the individual mind. It determines that a present state 
 shall be followed by a repetition of past states. This, as dis- 
 tinct from the logical order, may be called the psychological, 
 
 1 For example, the notion of a triangle is followed by the notion that an 
 exterior angle is equal to the sum of the two opposite interior angles. The 
 consideration of logical sequence is postponed to the topic Thought. 
 
178 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 or the empirical, order. Its procedure is expressed in three 
 laws, called the Laws of Suggestion. ^ 
 
 § 173. The first is the Law of Similarity, or of Repeti- 
 tion, thus : A present mental mode tends to suggest a past 
 similar mode. The suggesting and the suggested states are 
 similar, but differ in time. For examples : I see a man and 
 recognize him as having been seen before; the grief that 
 now agitates me recalls a former grief. ^ This law expresses 
 a primary condition of complete recognition, of the repro- 
 duction, renewal, revival, or repetition of a previous state, 
 according to subsequent laws.^ 
 
 Present mental states tend to revive also their contraries. 
 The brightness of to-day may remind one of the darkness of 
 last night.* But this occurs only through the law of repe- 
 
 1 Hamilton's treatmeut of this subject, Meta., p. 428 sq., abounds iii good 
 illustrations, but is philosophically defective. See Mill, Ex. of H.'s Phil., 
 ch. 14. But in Reid, note D***, Hamilton gives it a much more thorough 
 and satisfactory analysis. 
 
 2 Other examples : I hear a sound, as of a steam-v^'histle, and recognize it 
 as indistinguishable from what I have often heard before. A sweet taste just 
 now experienced reminds me of a sweet taste experienced some time ago. 
 The present thought of a social duty suggests the entirely similar thought of 
 yesterday. 
 
 Let it be noted that the principle of similarity is not association, for the 
 mental states implied have not been experienced together, which is essential 
 to association. Wit, which always presents somethmg new, has been fairly 
 defined as a quick discovery of remote resemblances. E.g. the French say, 
 a prudent man is like a pin, his head keeps him from going too far. Voltaire 
 said, ideas are like beards, women and boys have.jione. Putting these in 
 form of question and answer, we have the conundrum. So also punning, 
 rhyming, and alliteration depend on similarities, and not at all on association. 
 
 3 For shock of similarity as fundamental, see § 59. 
 
 The terms reproduction, etc. , are apt to mislead. A present state cannot 
 be strictly a revival or renewal of our past. It is similar, but not the same, 
 for it differs in time, without having persisted meantime, which is essential 
 to identity. 
 
 * Other examples : The cold of this winter suggests the heat of last summer ; 
 the frigid, the torrid zone. Seeing the strength and boldness of a lion, I may 
 think of the weakness and timidity of a hind. A mountain reminds me of an 
 abyss. The brevity of life brings to mind eternity. Sidney Smith said that 
 in time of danger presence of mind is good, but absence of body is better. 
 
SUGGESTION. 179 
 
 tition. We have seen that, by the law of relativity (§ 58), 
 every cognition coexists with its opposite or contrary. 
 Hence a state may recall a past contrary, but not directly. 
 Either it recalls its own past similar, and with it the paot 
 contrary, or the present contrary recalls its past similar. ^ 
 
 § 174. The second is the Law of Association, or of 
 Redintegration, thus: Mental modes occurring together or 
 in close succession, adhere, so that the after-recurrence of 
 any of them tends to suggest the others. The suggesting 
 and suggested states are dissimilar, but have previously 
 occurred at the same time.^ For example : A spoken word 
 strikes my ear. The sound is somewhat familiar; that is, 
 the present is similar to some previous mental state, which 
 being thus partially revived, constitutes a partial recogni- 
 tion. So far, this is according to the law of similarity. 
 But the previous state was associated with other dissim- 
 ilar yet simultaneous or successive states, to which it ad- 
 heres. Bj^ virtue of this adhesion they also are recalled, 
 and I now fully recognize a peculiar pronunciation as the 
 habit of a friend whose person I now mentally represent, 
 together with the circumstances of a conversation I had with 
 him yesterday while dining with him at his home. Thus 
 having revived, according to the law of similarity, one point 
 of a past experience, the mind then, according to the law of 
 redintegration, spreads, as it were, through all the attendant 
 
 1 We proceed, as it were, along the sides of a rectangle, rather than directly 
 along its diagonal. Alexander of Aphrodisias held that the suggestion of 
 contraries is equivalent to that of similars, because contraries always have 
 common attributes. — In Top., i, 18. 
 
 For failures in the law of similarity, due to feebleness or to diversity of 
 impression, .see Bain, Senses and Intellect, p. 461 sq.. Am. ed. 
 
 ^ See this law as stated by Kant, Anthropologie, § 30. Juxtaposition is 
 also usually held to cause association, as lips and teeth, Naples and Vesuvius. 
 Hence this is often named the law of contiguity in time and place. But 
 objects in space are known to be contiguous only by being observed simul- 
 taneously or in succession ; and it is this, and not juxtaposition, that is the 
 proximate cause of the adhesion. 
 
180 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 circumstances with whicli the point was associated, and so 
 reintegrates, or makes whole again, the former total state. 
 This second law is obviously conditioned on the first. ^ 
 
 § 175. When the experience causing the adhesion is one 
 of succession, then the total reproduced is a total of succes- 
 sion, and the order is the original order. We can easily say 
 the words of the Lord's Prayer in their order; but it would 
 not be easy to say them backwards. Yet regressive order is 
 not disorder, only it is not the order of association. ^ A 
 natural order in some cases determines the associated order; 
 for examples : an observed cj-cle, as that of the seasons ; an 
 evolution, as the growth of plants ; cause and effect, as hail 
 and damage. But more often the order is arbitrary or acci- 
 dental. 
 
 After a chain of associations has been formed, it not 
 infrequently occurs that intermediate links disappear, those 
 that remain interlinking with each other, and still preserv- 
 ing their original order. Thus the feeling of pleasure 
 
 1 Thus the name Alexander the Great may suggest Alexander the Copper- 
 smith. Campbell's lines, — 
 
 " — we linger to survey 
 The promised joys of life's iiurueasured way," 
 
 very readily suggest those of Pope : — 
 
 " — we tremble to survey 
 The growing labors of the lengthened way." 
 
 The striking similarities enable us to recall the differences. 
 
 The following, from Hobbes, is an oft-repeated and classical illustration : 
 "In a company in which the conversation turned upon the late civil war 
 [1042-49], what could be conceived more import hient than for a person to 
 ask abruptly, what was the value of a Roman denarius ? On a little reflec- 
 tion, however, I was easily able to trace the train of thought which suggested 
 the question ; for the original subject of discourse naturally introduced the 
 history of the king, and of the treachery of those who surrendered his person 
 to his enemies ; this again introduced the treachery of Judas Iscariot, and 
 the sum of money which he received for his reward." — Leviathan, pt. i, ch. 3. 
 
 A number of fine illustrations are given by Stewart, Elements, i, ch. 5. 
 
 2 The notes of a familiar tune suggest each other, and we sing it through. 
 Now try to sing it backwards. 
 
SUGGESTION. 181 
 
 becomes associated in the mind of the miser directly with the 
 mere possession of money, he having lost the connecting link, 
 conveniences procured by money, out of the chain, money, 
 conveniences, pleasure.^ Thus it is that thoughts which 
 originally followed each other in the order of logical 
 sequence, and were linked by reasonings, become associated 
 by these experiences, and afterward suggest each other in 
 the same order, but without a repetition of the reasoning. 
 We have many special examples of this in the mediate per- 
 ceptions (§ 161). 
 
 § 176. When the total revival is a complement of states 
 associated by simultaneity, the likeness to a chain does not 
 hold. In speaking of a train of thoughts thus associated, 
 it should not be understood that one idea or mode brings up 
 another, and this a third, and so on, in a simple chain. We 
 should remember that ordinarily in an}' given state we are 
 conscious not of one, nor merely of a few, but of a great 
 many things at once (§ 64). Now each of these things may 
 have its own peculiar connections with previous states of 
 the same manifold sort. Whichever one, then, operates to 
 suggest its special associations, that brings up, not merely 
 another one, but a new multitude, and some one of this 
 throng brings up still another throng of cognitions, feelings, 
 states, of every kind. The succession, then, is not like that 
 of the links of a chain, but rather like that of the links of 
 an intricate network, each of which has its own independent 
 and numerous connections. Thus in lively conversation, 
 the several topics, suggested often by chance words or phrases, 
 come freely, without logical connection, and the mind is 
 
 ^ Hartley expresses this in liis Law of Transference. — Observations on 
 Man, ch. 4. See also Morell, Hist, of Phil, pt. i, cli. 1, § 3. Thus, proba- 
 bly, Hamilton lost B, his A interlinking directly with C. — Meta., pp. 244 
 and 430 sq. So the events of history come to be immediately associated with 
 its monuments, a long intermediate chain of studies being overlooked. xVmid 
 the ruins of ancient Rome, '■'■quocunque enim ingredimur, in aliquam histo- 
 riam vestigium pon'imus.'''' — Cicero, De Finibus, bk. v, ch. 1. 
 
182 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 crowded with successive swarms of ideas, images, thoughts, 
 and feelings. In reverie, images come and go in great 
 troops, every moment the scene changes, we can scarce tell 
 how, and host follows host unceasingly. ^ 
 
 § 177. vSome states between which there is no necessary, 
 and it may be no natural, connection become nevertheless 
 so firmly adherent by a frequent experience of them together, 
 and perhaps never an experience of them apart, that they 
 cannot be separated. If one exists, the other exists along 
 with it in spite of every effort made to disjoin them. This 
 is called indissoluble association.^ For example, it is hardly 
 in our power to dissociate color and extension. We have 
 constantly seen them combined; we have, perhaps, never ob- 
 served color unless apparently spread, as it were, on a sur- 
 face ; they have been invariably conjoined. Whenever, then, 
 the idea of the one occurs, that of the other comes along with 
 it, and is retained as long as the first remains. Yet there is 
 no necessary connection between them. Color is wholly sub- 
 jective ; extension is objective. The man born eyeless appre- 
 ciates extension without color; and if his inner organ be 
 excited by an electric shock, he experiences color without 
 extension. "There is no more connection," says Stewart, 
 "between color and extension, than there is between pain 
 
 1 " Lulled in the secret chambers of the brain, 
 
 Our thoughts are linked by many a hidden chain ; 
 Awake but one, and lo ! what myriads rise, 
 Each stamps his image as the other flies." 
 
 — KoGEKs, Pleasures of Memory. 
 
 "Zwar ist's mit der Gedankenfabrik 
 AVie mit cinom Webermcisterstiick, 
 Wo ein Trilt tausend Fiiden regt, 
 Die Schifflein heriiber hiniiber schiessen. 
 Die Fiiden ungesehen flicssen, 
 Ein Schlag tausend Verbindungen schlagt." 
 
 — Fmtst, p. 73, Whitney's ed. 
 
 See Cardaillac, J^Audes Element, de Philos., t. ii, oh. 6. 
 2 See James Mill, Analysis, etc., ch. 3. 
 
SUGGESTION. 183 
 
 and solidity." He might have said, not so much, for solid- 
 ity may be a cause of pain, but extension cannot be a cause 
 of color. 
 
 § 178. Clearly the two laws which have been stated are 
 applicable to various modes of cognition. Perceptions be- 
 come associated merely by the experience of them together 
 or in close succession, so that tlie subsequent presentation 
 of one excites a representation of the other (§ 161). Upon 
 this depends the possibility of language. ^ So also memories, 
 imaginings, and thoughts may suggest each other.^ 
 
 The adhesions determined by experience are not, however, 
 limited to cognitions, but take place between any, even the 
 most heterogeneous mental states. Not only may a feeling 
 be associated with a feeling, or a volition with a volition, 
 but a cognition may be united Avith a feeling,^ a volition 
 
 1 The association between a vocal sound and the position of the organ of 
 speech requisite to produce it enables the one to recall and reinstate the 
 other. Hence the power of imitating sounds, or of producing them at will. 
 Again, these sounds are associated with the things which they name, and in 
 written language the visible forms of words are likewise associated with the 
 things. Moreover, the sound and the written word are associated with each 
 other. These connections are almost wholly arbitrary, yet they are the 
 essential basis of human speech. So a child comes to distinguish its right 
 hand from its left (see Jonah 4 : 11), by associating the words with a par- 
 ticular set of muscular sense-perceptions. 
 
 One who has an ear even slightly educated appreciates the rhythm and 
 rhyme of verses in silent reading ; and a musician silently scans writtv n 
 music, enjoying its beauties and critically judging its merits. 
 
 2 No logical connection is requisite. I see a toad, and instantly think of 
 Ithurial's spear. But for the toad, I should not have thought of the spear. 
 See Paradise Lost, bk. iv, 11. 797-882. 
 
 3 A burnt child dreads fire ; or, as a Hebrew proverb has it : Who has 
 been bitten by a snake is afraid of a rope. Says Ossian : "The music of 
 Carryl was, like the memory of joys that are past, pleasant and mournful 
 to the soul." Descartes, in illustrating association, says that when a child 
 he had as a playmate a little girl with a squint, whose early friendship made 
 him ever after regard this defect with favor. See an odd case mentioned by 
 McCosh, Emotions, p. 179. 
 
 The fact of associations or adhesions between mental states other than 
 
18 i MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 with a cognition, an affection with a sensation, and so on; 
 and these then suggest each other. Indeed, an association 
 may be so strong as to reproduce, not merely mental, but 
 also physical states.^ 
 
 § 179. The third law is the Law of Preference, thus: 
 Suggestion takes the direction and is in the ratio of the 
 interest which objects have for the individual mind. The 
 two previous laws do not account for all the phenomena. 
 They explain recurrence by association, but not Avhy one 
 idea or mode takes preference of others. They explain the 
 fact of adhesion, but not why A preferably adheres to C 
 rather than to B. They explain the general tendency, but 
 not the mode of realization. The third law is complemen- 
 tary. 
 
 Associations are established by exjDcrience, but they are 
 modified and directed by the native disposition, tastes, and 
 habits of the individual. Two persons under entirely similar 
 circumstances will recur to very different ideas, and that 
 
 cognitive shows that the phrase "association of ideas," whicli is the usual 
 title given to this whole subject, is much too narrow. It originated with 
 Locke, who, however, used the term idea in a wide sense. The old scholas- 
 tic title, " the excitation of species," is also inadequate, since adhesions occur 
 between heterogeneous states. 
 
 1 Reading a bill of fare may excite hunger. One who has taken quinine 
 lu coffee, for weeks tastes its bitterness in every cup. A remedy for inebriety 
 is to put tartar-emetic in the drink ; thereafter liquor is nauseous. See a 
 curious statement in Rush, Afedical Inquiries, vol. ii, p. 42. Thinking of a 
 precipice excites a thrill, and even may make one dizzy. Imagine a nail 
 drawn across a slate, the flesh creeps. The sight of the surgeon who lias 
 performed a painful operation on me revives my agony, and excites a dislike 
 for his person. See the anecdote in Locke, Essa)/, bk. ii, ch. 23, § 14. News 
 of a battle makes a veteran's old wound burn. So Heine's ballad, Die Grni- 
 adiere : " Wie breunt meine alte Wunde ! " Seeing the assassin who has 
 recently attempted one's life may cause the wound to bleed. Possibly in 
 this originated the old and widely spread notion that a murderer's approach 
 to the corpse of his victim causes the wound to bleed afresh. See Nihelun- 
 genlied, Siebenzehntes Ahenteuer ; Richard III, A. 1, sc. 2; Fair Maid of 
 Perth, ch. 23 ; and Marhle Faun. 
 
SUGGESTION. 185 
 
 perhaps in spite of the natural relations of things. Such a 
 relation subsists between the ideas horse and work, and also 
 between rain and growth, and to a farmer the one will sug- 
 gest the other. But to a jockey the idea of a horse suggests 
 a race, and to a tramp rain suggests mud. The preference 
 is determined by the interest arising from taste and habit. 
 Likewise our interpretation of events is determined largely 
 by preference in associations according to taste and habit. ^ 
 
 The points determining preference are sometimes stated 
 as the secondary laws of association,^ thus: 1. Long con- 
 tinuance or frequent repetition of impression confers prefer- 
 ence. This is by the general law of habit. 2. Natural 
 adliesiveness causes preference. One's disposition, as 
 gloomy or cheerful, his taste, as vulgar or refined, his 
 talents, as for languages or mathematics, will generally 
 
 1 A very fine illustration, too long to quote, will be found in Merchant of 
 Venice, A. 1, sc. 1, speecli of Salarino. 
 
 When Moses and Joshua were coming down from the mount, and heard 
 from far the noise of the people as they shouted, the warrior said with mili- 
 tary brevity : — 
 
 " A noise of war in the camp." 
 
 But the poet said : — 
 
 " Not the voice of them that shout for mastery, 
 Nor the voice of them that cry for being overcome, 
 But the voice of them that sing, do I hear." — Exodus 32 : 18. 
 
 The following classical illustration is taken from Helvetius : "The passions 
 not only concentrate our attention on certain exclusive aspects of the objects 
 which they present, but they likewise often deceive us in showing these same 
 objects where they do not exist. The story is well known of a parson and 
 a gay lady. They had both heard that the moon was peopled, believed it, 
 and telescope in hand, were attempting to discover the inhabitants. If I 
 am not mistaken, says the lady, who looked first, I perceive two shadows ; 
 they bend toward each other, and are doubtless two happy lovers. Lovers, 
 madam, says the divine, who looked next, oh, fie ! The two shadows you 
 saw are the two steeples of a cathedral. This story is the history of mankind. 
 In general we perceive only in things what we are desirous of finding. On 
 earth, as in the moon, various prepossessions make us always recognize 
 either lovers or cathedrals." — De V Esprit, dis. i, ch. 2. 
 
 2 See Brown, Phil, of Hum. Mind, § 37. 
 
186 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 give direction to his associations. ^ 3. Recentness of the im- 
 pression. 4. Concentration of mind in attention. 
 
 § 180. The English school of psychologists hold that the 
 principle of association is the fundamental law of mind. 
 All our psychic states are merely transformed associations. 
 "Not only our intellectual pleasures and pains, but all 
 the phenomena of memory, imagination, volition, reasoning, 
 and every other affection and operation, are only different 
 modes or cases of the association of ideas ; so that nothing 
 is requisite to make any man whatever he is, but a sentient 
 principle with this single property. "^ 
 
 We have endeavored to exhibit the princij^le of associa- 
 tion, not as productiA^e or transforming, but as merely re- 
 productive. It is unquestionably of wide and important 
 consequence in mental processes, especially as underlying 
 the specific faculties of representation. To these we now 
 proceed. 
 
 1 Says Aristotle in De Memoria: "Certain things with certain minds 
 become more intimately associated at the first movement than with other 
 minds, though this be frequently repeated. Hence it is that some objects 
 which we have seen but once are more perfectly remembered by us than 
 others which we have oftentimes beheld." 
 
 2 Priestley, Hnrtleifs Theory, Int. Essay, p. 24. The whole theory of 
 evolution is contained in the last clause. 
 
 The general subject is discussed by Aristotle, De Mem. et Rem., ii, 8 ; by 
 Augustine, Confessions, lib. x, ch. 19 ; by Leibnitz, JVouv. Ess., I, ii, ch. 33 ; 
 by Hobbes, Leviathan, ch. 3 ; and by Coleridge, Biog. Lit., chs. 5-7. The 
 theory culminated with Hartley, Observations on Man, ch. 4. He found in 
 association the fundamental law of mind, which alone accounts for all mental 
 phenomena whatever ; the prolific principle, which evolves from mere expe- 
 rience all our activities of both consciousness and conation. He held that 
 "transference" is the generalization of this process (§175, note). The 
 theory has been variously modified by its chief advocates, .Tames Mill, John 
 S. Mill, Bain, and Spencer, but in its essential features is characteristic of 
 the English school of thinkers. 
 
MEMORY. 187 
 
 CHAPTER IV. 
 
 MEMORY. 
 
 § 181. Memory is the representation of a past experience. 
 This definition implies that the past experience is repre- 
 sented as a past experience. Memory is a recognition, a 
 knowing over again, a consciousness of a certain mental 
 image, involving the conviction that this image now repre- 
 sents ideally what was formerly experienced really. 
 
 It seems to be an nltimate constitutional fact, which, 
 therefore, is not in itself susceptible of explanation, that 
 mind tends to modes consciously similar to previous modes, 
 or tends to a conscious repetition of its modes, and this 
 tendency, in respect of cognitions, gives rise to the phenom- 
 ena of memory. This we shall call the theory of repetition. ^ 
 
 § 182. There is in an act of memory, a primary and a 
 secondary judgment. The primary is a psychological judg- 
 ment, a fact of consciousness. It is that I have heretofore 
 experienced a state similar to the one now present. More 
 than this it does not afiirm. It makes a conscious reference 
 to past time, but is wholly indefinite as to time when. This 
 primary judgment may not attend a renewed cognition. A 
 state that has in fact been experienced before may seem quite 
 novel, may not be recognized. Then it is not memory. 
 
 1 A thing is said to be repeated when there is another thing numerically 
 distinct, but otherwise indistinguishable; i.e. precisely similar. They are 
 either separate in space, as two coins; or in time, as a double rap ; or m 
 both, as the twin Dromios. Mental states are repetitive when they differ in 
 time only. An act of memory repeats but a part. When I represent a 
 former presentation, the two states differ in many respects besides time ; still 
 some common or repeated element produces the shock of similarity. 
 
188 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 But when this judgment does occur, recognition, in so far, 
 is intuitive and unerring. 
 
 That this is a psj^chologieal judgment is evident. The 
 shock and judgment of simihxrity, in case of simultaneous 
 impressions, is allowed by all to be an ultimate, intuitive fact 
 of consciousness. Surely in case of successive impressions, 
 as the strokes of a clock, the judgment of similarity is not 
 less a fact of consciousness, not less an intuition. 
 
 § 183. The secondary judgment of memory affirms the 
 time, place, and circumstances of the past experience, and 
 constitutes complete recognition. The primary judgment 
 is immediate and certain; the secondary is mediate, and 
 liable to error, being subsequent and inferred. Hence all 
 distrust of memory has reference exclusively to this second- 
 ary judgment. For we are very apt to conjoin circum- 
 stances which were really separate in time and place, and so 
 to mistake an act of imagination for one of memory. ^ 
 
 The secondary judgment may be attended by any degree 
 of belief, from the faintest suspicion, up to the highest con- 
 fidence, falling just short of strict certainty. The degree of 
 this belief seems to correspond with the degree of familiarity 
 excited by the incoming circumstances. ^ When this feeling 
 is strong, the judgment is quite pronounced and confident. 
 In case two points belonging to my past experience recur in 
 memory, each is attended by its own degree of familiarity. 
 If, however, they originally occurred together, their recur- 
 
 ^ For example, on meeting a man I recognize him as one I met yesterday. 
 I call him by name, and speak of our previous meeting; but in a moment he 
 convinces me that he is another person whom I have never met before. Did 
 I altogether mistake ? Not every particular. I am still certain that the 
 impression he made was in some respect quite similar to a former impression. 
 My error was solely in the secondary judgment. The trustworthiness of 
 one's memory lies largely in the ability to distinguish between a real and an 
 ideal coneinuitance of circumstances. 
 
 ^ For the feelings of certainty and belief, see § 227. For familiarity as a 
 basis of memory, see § 224. 
 
MEMORY. 189 
 
 rence is attended by a degree of familiarity more than is due 
 to their sum, for to this sum we must add the familiarity 
 arising from their original connection. Then I am highly 
 confident that the two originally occurred together, i Thus 
 our confidence in recollecting a past fact is greatly increased 
 by connecting with it minute and otherwise insignificant 
 circumstances. 
 
 § 184. It is quite evident that memory acts according to 
 the laws of suggestion. Its primary judgment is a specific 
 judgment of similarity, one relative to the past. This cor- 
 responds to the first law of suggestion, the law of similarity. 
 Its secondary judgment is a judgment of totality, bringing 
 in the time, place, and circumstances. This corresponds to 
 the second law, the law of association or redintegration. The 
 laws of suggestion, therefore, as applied to cognitions, are 
 laws of memory. 
 
 § 185. The law of memory is involved in the more general 
 law that mind tends to modes similar to previous modes, or 
 tends to repetition. This theory of repetition is in contrast 
 with what may be called theories of retention. ^ 
 
 One of these holds that a state of mind excited by an 
 
 1 It has often been asked, for instance, why it is that on trying to recall 
 the name of a person while looking at him, I successively reject Smith, Jones, 
 and others, but on trying Brown, I am at once assured that this is his name. 
 Augustine, Confessions, bk. x, ch. 19, gives an explanation differing from 
 that above. 
 
 - In common speech the phenomena of memory are usually expressed 
 metaphorically. The mind is said to retain its knowledge and to revive or 
 reproduce it on occasion. Memory is a storehouse where the accumulations 
 are treasured up, a thesaurus omnium rerum, says Cicero, De Oratore, i, 5. 
 It is a bureau where facts are filed for reference, a reservoir of experiences, 
 Tj IMV-^M awrvpia aiadvcrews, says Plato, PMlebus, 34 Steph. All such figurative 
 expressions are unscientific. They are accommodations to be tolerated only 
 in the poverty of language. See Locke, Essay, bk. ii, ch. 10, § 2. Yet 
 many psychologists undertake to explain how mind does literally retain and 
 reproduce its acquisitions. 
 
190 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 object is actuall}' retained ever afterward in a condition of 
 tension, and on a fit occasion springs forth into conscious- 
 ness. A mental activity can never absolutely cease to be. 
 Its predominance is lost, but the activity itself does not, can 
 not, cease. It continues as an activity of inferior, and it may 
 be of extremely low, tension, until some combination occurs 
 that revives its intensity, when it reappears, again predomi- 
 nant, and the same, having persisted tlu'oughout.^ 
 
 Two objections may be offered in passing. All agree that 
 my consciousness of an event is my knowledge of that event. 
 But according to the theory, my knowledge next day in 
 memory of the event is this same knowledge revived. 
 Hence this knowledge in memory is a consciousness of the 
 event of yesterday; that is, I am conscious of the past, 
 which is absurd. 
 
 A perception and my recollection of it are states differing 
 widely in kind. The one is relative to a present external 
 object, the other is wholly subjective; the one is passive, 
 the other active; the one is attended by sensation, the other 
 not. There is a similarity amid these differences, yet they 
 are such as preclude identity. 
 
 § 186. Other psychologists attribute memory to physical 
 action, and find ground in the brain for the phenomena of 
 retention. "We know what are the conditions of makinsf 
 an acquirement, or of fixing two or more things together in 
 
 1 So Herbart and his followers. See especially Schmidt, Versiich einer 
 Metaphi/ftiJc der innern Natur, p. 231 sq. This view was adopted by Hamil- 
 ton, who defines memory as "the power which the mind possesses of retain- 
 ing hold of the knowledge it has acquired." — ,l/e^(7., Lee. 30. He calls it 
 "the conservative or retentive faculty in which the phenomenon of retention 
 is the central notion." — M, p. 412. He distinguishes it sharply from "the 
 reproductive faculty, or the process by which what is lying dormant in 
 memory is awakened." — Id., p. 427. Bain condemns this as fictitious. — 
 Logic, p. G40. Yet elsewhere he says : " The fundamental property of intel- 
 lect, named retentiveness, supposes that somi'thing lias been ingrained in 
 the mental structure that succeeding impressions have not been able to blot 
 out." — Senses mid Intellect, p. 325. 
 
MEMOBY. 191 
 
 memory. The separate impressions must be made together, 
 or flow in close succession, and they must be held together 
 for a certain length of time, either on one occasion or on 
 repeated occasions. Now to each impression, each sensation 
 or thought, there corresponds physically a group of nerve- 
 currents. When two impressions occur, or closely succeed 
 one another, the nerve-currents find some bridge or place 
 of continuity, better or worse, according to the abundance 
 of nerve-matter available for the transition. In the cells 
 or corpuscles where the currents meet and join, there is, in 
 consequence of the meeting, a strengthened connection or 
 a diminished obstruction, a preference track for that line 
 over other lines where no continuity has been established. 
 This is merely a hypothetical rendering of the facts, yet it is 
 a very probable rendering."^ 
 
 When we consider the concomitance and interdependence, 
 the mutual action and reaction, of mind and brain, and the 
 progressive growth and gradually confirmed organization of 
 the latter, this hj^othesis, though perhaps too specifically 
 stated, seems plausible. That the brain acquires prefer- 
 ences is possible, and if so, it may largely determine in 
 spontaneous memory the succession of images, and in volun- 
 tary memory the greater ease with wliich certain lines of 
 thought are recalled. As in perception, the mind is passive 
 and determined to its special state by the condition of the 
 excited sensory, so it is conceivable that in memory it may 
 be passively determined to certain successive states by ac- 
 quired brain tendencies, by physical preferences, which have 
 become established through habitual exercise.^ 
 
 1 Bain, 3lind and Body, p. 117. We adopt the illustration of Gassendi, 
 who compares mind to a sheet of paper which is capable of receiving very 
 many folds, and which not only repeats those in which it has been often 
 or sharply laid, ^'■vernm etiam possint facili negotio excitari, redire, appa- 
 rare, quatenns una plica arrepta, cceterce, quae in eadem serie quasi sjwnte 
 seqimntur.'''' — Physica, lib. viii, ch. .3, § 3. 
 
 2 This will explain why aged persons often have a vivid memory of early 
 events, and one dim of those recent, as illustrated by the character Elspeth 
 
192 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 This supposed transference of cause from the mental to 
 the physical sphere has an analogous precedent in the ac- 
 quisition of physical dexterities and habits under the law 
 of reflex action (§ 37). We may conceive that as muscular 
 movements, originally voluntarj^, become by habit involun- 
 tary physical instincts, a ganglionic nervous centre acquir- 
 ing the power to determine and co-ordinate them as j)urely 
 reflex actions, so brain may acquire such conformation as to 
 determine automatically a series of states, and their con- 
 comitant states of consciousness. Such transference from 
 the mental to the physical seems to be according to laws of 
 growth and complete development. ^ 
 
 in Scott's Antiqiiary. We may suppose that in old age certain lines of cere- 
 bral communication have become iixed, and the brain indurated by a sort of 
 organic crystallization, with a loss of youthful plasticity and the power of 
 forming new combinations. 
 
 The hypothesis is helpful in accounting for the loss of speciiic memories. 
 Dr. Beattie lost, for some time, from a blow on the head, his knowledge of 
 Greek, whilst his other mental stores were left intact. Ballantyne relates 
 of Scott that when J'he Bride of Lammermoor was submitted to him after 
 an illness, he did not recognize it as his own, though the original tradition 
 was still clearly remembered. 
 
 We often hear of cases of marvellous power of memory, and they make 
 on us the impression that the power is unlimited. But every one is a block- 
 head in something, and memory in the lines of incapacity is a rope of sand. 
 Moreover, much improvement in later life is a substitution, which is not an 
 addition, of mature for immature judgments. We lose at one end as much 
 as is gained at the other. Newton, turned theologian, forgot his own scien- 
 tific discoveries ; and Erasmus forgot his mother-tongue in favor of Latin. 
 These limits to memory are best explained by identifying them with the 
 limited capacity of the brain to receive and retain lines of preferred activity. 
 
 1 Spencer carries this very far. " Memory belongs to that class of psychi- 
 cal states which are in i^rogress of being organized. It continues so long as 
 the oi-ganization of them continues, and disappears when the organization of 
 them is complete." Memory is "incipient instinct," and instinct "a kind 
 of organized memory," it is "Inherited experience." — Prinnplcs of Psy- 
 chology, §§ 102, 202. Birds instinctively building tiicir nests are exercising 
 a fully organized, and so obsolete, inherited memory. They are, then, more 
 completely developed beings than we, who are In an earlier, transition stage. 
 Humanity, then, is running down to the brutal forms. But how did we ever 
 get, from our zoophyte beginning, up to our present unstable height? Does 
 evolution work butli ways at once? 
 
MEMORY. 193 
 
 It appears reasonable, therefore, to accept the hypothesis 
 that, as a result of mental exercise, the concomitant activi- 
 ties of the brain induce lines of preferred or more facile 
 nervous action, having various degrees of permanence, which 
 determine subsequent mental tendencies.^ But this hypoth- 
 esis cannot be held exclusively. It is not sufficient to 
 account for all the facts. It does not explain voluntary 
 recollection, wherein will determines the train of images. 
 It affords no explanation of first spontaneous memories, 
 wherein experiences often recur to us for the first time with 
 a vividness and vigor surpassing old established memo- 
 ries ; nor why recentness of impression is a special occasion 
 of vivid memory. Hence the theory of a mental tendency 
 to repetition is held by us as expressing the original and 
 ultimate ground of memory; and the theory of physical 
 retention is allowed as supplementary. 
 
 § 187. Having defined memory, and discussed the princi- 
 ples and causes to which it is to be referred, we now turn to 
 examine its kinds. A distinction is taken according as 
 memory is exercised spontaneously, called remembrance, or 
 under the direction of will, called recollection. ^ 
 
 In remembrance one image follows another, according to 
 the laws of suggestion and involving a reference to past 
 time, without the intervention of will. The mind is passive, 
 operating spontaneously, and Ave are reminded of things 
 simply and solely as they hapj^en to be similar or associated, 
 without any exercise of choice. It is so in reverie. In 
 
 ^ In that case it is tlie brain, and not the mind, which is retentive of 
 impressions, but not of knowledge, much as the printed page retains its 
 story, or the worn channel its current. Brain is the bank of deposit which, 
 when drawn upon, yields not the same, but similar and equivalent knowledge. 
 The beaten and established paths are preferred by mind in subsequent 
 movements. Or, to speak literally, neural states facilitated by exercise tend 
 to siiperinduce mental states similar to those previously concurring. 
 
 2 The distinction dates from Aristotle, and occurs even in the title of his 
 treatise, De Mem. et Bern., wepl ixvrjfj.i]s Kal dvdfj.vr]cn^. 
 
194 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 dreams, also, we have an illustration of mere remembrances, 
 the absence of a directing will over the train of images being 
 characteristic of dreaming. 
 
 Remembrance or involuntary memory may be subdivided 
 into simple recognition or reminiscence, and complex recog- 
 nition or remembrance proper. We are often reminded of 
 something, with a sense of familiarity, but without any 
 remembrance of the time, place, or circumstances of tlie 
 former experience. This is simple recognition or reminis- 
 cence, the law of repetition alone being effective.^ When, 
 however, the law of redintegration also becomes involun- 
 tarily effective, suggesting the time, place, or other associ- 
 ated circumstances, this fuller reminding may be distin- 
 guished as complex recognition, or remembrance proper, 
 
 § 188. Recollection is voluntary or intentional memory. 
 It is an activity, a deliberate choice being followed by an 
 endeavor to recall something fully to mind. The special 
 function of will is to fix attention, to concentrate conscious- 
 ness on a chosen object (§ 89). The immediate effect is to 
 intensify the consciousness of the chosen object at the 
 expense of others within its sphere, according to the law of 
 limitation (§ 83). A further consequence is that the 
 adhering states are brought into clear consciousness accord- 
 ing to the law of redintegration (§ 174). Thus we re-col- 
 lect the former circumstances. From among these we may 
 then choose one as a new object of attention, and repeating 
 
 1 From such vague impressions Plato drew an argument for the pre-exist- 
 ence of the soul ; and, indeed, it is easy to fancy that they are memories of 
 a previous life, of another \^rld. So Wordsworth, in his famous ode, " Inti- 
 mations of Immortality " : — 
 
 " Our birth is but a sleep and a forgetting ; 
 The soul that rises with lis, our life's star, 
 Hath had elsewhere its setting, 
 And conieth from afar. 
 Not in entire forgetfulness, 
 And not in utter nakedness, 
 But trailing clouds of glory, do we come 
 From God, who is our home." 
 
MEMORY. 195 
 
 the process determine continuously the succession of the 
 intellectual train. 
 
 The subjective correlative of will is desire (§§ 71, 74). An 
 effort to recollect implies a want, it is an endeavor to gratify 
 a desire, e.g. curiosity. But desire is conditioned on cogni- 
 tion. This implies that the thing we seek for intentionally 
 in memory is not wholly out of consciousness, not wholly 
 unknown. We cannot endeavor to recollect something of 
 which we have at present no remembrance whatever. " We 
 still hold of it, as it were, a part, and b}^ this part which we 
 hold we seek that which we do not hold."^ Throughout the 
 process, the effort is stimulated by the want, which at its 
 close is satisfied, and both together cease. ^ 
 
 1 Augustine, Confessions, lib. x, ch. 18. 
 
 2 The process of recollecting may be illustrated thus : Suppose I wish to 
 make a quotation, but have in mind only the first few words, " Take physic, 
 pomp ; — " I repeat this much over and over with close attention, but what 
 follows does not recur. I then turn my attention to some associated circum- 
 stances, and fix on Shakspeare as its author. His name suggests the titles 
 of his plays. I run these over in mind, and the fragment seems best suited 
 to, or most familiar in connection with King Lear. I recall attentively one 
 and another of the characters of the tragedy, and it strikes me as most likely 
 that Lear himself would use such words. I then picture with attention his 
 several situations, and the storm scene apparently connects with the words. 
 I recall the image of the hovel, and the humiliated king stooping to enter it ; 
 then his words come in full to mind ; I can almost hear him saying : — 
 
 " Take physic, pomp; 
 Expose thyself to feel what wretches feel, 
 That thou raayst shake the superflux to them, 
 And shew the heavens more just." — A. 3, bc. 4. 
 
 Says Aristotle : "When we accomplish an act of recollection, we pass 
 through a certain series of precursive movements until we arrive at a move- 
 ment on which the one we are in quest of is habitually consequent. Thus it 
 is that we hunt through the mental train." Perhaps this suggested the com- 
 parison of Longinus : "For as dogs," says he, "having once found the 
 footsteps of their game, follow from trace to trace, deeming it already all 
 but caught, so he who would recover his past cognitions from oblivion must 
 speculate the parts which remain to him of these cognitions, and the circum- 
 stances with which they chance to be connected, to the end that he shall 
 light on something which shall serve him for a starting-point from whence 
 to follow out his recollection of the others." 
 
196 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 § 189. A distinction of some practical importance is that 
 between circumstantial and philosophic memory. Circum- 
 stantial memory is dependent on accidental relations, such as 
 the sensuous or superficial resemblance of things, their anal- 
 ogies, their contrarieties, their vicinity in time or place, or 
 other insignihcant coincidences. A philosophic memory is 
 determined by essential relations, such as cause and effect, 
 means and end, premises and conclusion, associating things 
 by their scientific affinities and logical connection. The first 
 is manifested by childi-en, or by undisciplined minds gener- 
 ally, and seems more natural ; the second is rather a result 
 of intellectual education, and seems more artificial. The 
 one is read}^ and quick, and often surprises us ^yith its 
 extent, variety, and minute accuracy of detail; the other 
 appears sluggish, is complained of as defective, and fails in 
 non-essential particulars. All minds make use of both; but 
 with one class of minds the former, with another class, the 
 latter, kind of memory is lu-edominant and habitual. ^ 
 
 1 In looking up a quotation, one person can tell whereabouts in the book 
 it occurs, whether on the right or left hand page, and whether at top, middle, 
 or bottom ; another person recalls only its logical connection with the subject- 
 matter of the book. A punster and a rhymster are engaged by accidental 
 coincidences in the sound of syllables ; a wit and a poet are occupied with 
 the inner, subtile, and delicate logic implied in the expression. Magliabecchi, 
 librarian to the Grand Duke of Tuscany, was asked to produce a certain rare 
 book. '• It is impossible," said he ; " there is but one in the world, and that 
 is in the Grand Seignior's library at Constantinople, the seventh book, on 
 the fifth shelf, on the right hand as you go in." Montaigne, whose cast of 
 mind was reflective and speculative, more tenacious of principles than of 
 facts, complained of want of memory. "I am forced," says he, "to call 
 my servants by the names of their employments, or by the countries where 
 they were born, for I can hardly remember their proper names ; and if I 
 should live long, I question whether I should remember my own name." 
 
 All the great masters of human nature mark the distinction. Cervantes 
 makes Sancho Panza, the boor, talk very circumstantially ; but Don Quixote, 
 the cultivated man, though crazed and absurd, is made to talk quite i)hilo- 
 sophically. But compare, especially, Hostess Quickley's speech before the 
 Chief Justice, in King Henry IV, pt. ii, Act 2, so. 1, with that of Lady Percy 
 to Northumberland, so. 3. 
 
MEMORY. 197 
 
 Circumstantial memory is often used specifically to 
 strengthen bonds of the same sort, or to supplement philo- 
 sophic memory, and confirm its more uncertain adhesions.^ 
 Mnemonics, the art of memory, memoria technica^ is an 
 expansion of this principle into a system. The possession 
 of such artificial means accounts for many wonderful feats 
 of memory. Ver}^ many systems have been devised, but 
 they are of little value, the adhesions being only temporary.^ 
 
 1 The familiar doggerel, "Thirty days hath September," etc., is useful in 
 its way. The word vihgyor, composed of the initials of the seven prismatic 
 colors, helps us to remember them in their order. A quaint phrase serves a 
 similar end ; as, " Shakspeare died in the two sixteens," i.e. a.d. 1616. The 
 scholastic logic abounded in mnemonic devices, the most famous and useful 
 one being the hexameters beginning " Barbara, Celarent," etc. 
 
 2 It is highly probable that such a system was used by Seneca, who boasts 
 that on one occasion, two hundred unconnected verses having been pro- 
 nounced in his hearing, he repeated them in reverse order. The feat of the 
 law-student of Padua, cited by Muretus, and recited amazedly by Hamilton, 
 Meta., p. 421 sq., was doubtless of this sort, for he proposed to teach a 
 fellow-student the art; hence his '■'■farinus mirificissimum'''' is unworthy of 
 so much sterile astonishment. Simonides, the Greek poet, 5th century n.c., 
 invented a system which is described by Quintilian. When Simonides pro- 
 posed to teach Themistocles his art, Themistocles, whose natural power of 
 memory was such that he knew by name each of the twenty thousand citi- 
 zens of Athens, replied: "I had rather you should teach me the art of 
 forgetting." He had found that memory, like other gifts, is the curse of the 
 gods when they give too much. "Si la souvenir embellit la vie, I'oubli seul 
 la rend possible. Dieu a mesure la peine a nos forces en nous donnant 
 I'oubli." Sophocles pronounced memory the queen of powers, nnd the 
 earlier Greeks affirmed that the nine Muses were the daughters of Zeus and 
 Mnemosyne. 
 
198 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 CHAPTER V. 
 
 IMAGINATION. 
 
 § 190. The representative state, considered generically, 
 is called an image, the act an imaging. Having thus far 
 found these terms sufficient, Ave have reserved the word 
 imagmation, with its conjugates, to imagine, imaginari/, etc., 
 as exclusively applicable to the mode of representation now 
 before us, co-ordinate with memory and thought. 
 
 Imagination is the representation of an ideal object. In 
 this definition it is needful to explain the specific difference, 
 ideal object. There are two spheres of cognition, or two 
 kinds of objects of knowledge, the real and the ideal. The 
 real object is one that truly exists either objectively, being 
 given in perception, or subjectively, given in self-percep- 
 tion ; or it is one that actually has been, and is now repre- 
 sented in memory. The unreal is that which does not, and 
 perhaps never did, exist, a negation of the real, and so 
 furnishing no object of cognition. Now, by the logical law 
 of excluded middle, there can be nothing between the real 
 and unreal ; yet the mind has power to consider a real object 
 as unreal, that is, to disregard the fact, and also power to 
 form images or ideas rei)resenting things that are in fact 
 unreal. Such objects are ideal objects, and the act represent- 
 ing them is imagination. 
 
 § 191. In memory the representation is judged to be of a 
 past experience; in imagination it is not so judged. In 
 other words, the objects of memory are facts of experience ; 
 those of imagination may or ma}' not be facts of experience, 
 the question is not considered, the representation is in disre- 
 ['\Y(\ of experience. 
 
IMAGINATION. 199 
 
 " Memory is an immediate knowledge of a present idea, 
 involving an absolute belief that this idea represents another 
 act of knowledge that has been. Imagination is an immedi- 
 ate knowledge of an actual idea, which, as not subjectively 
 self-contradictor}^, but logically possible, involves the hypo- 
 thetical belief that it objectively may be, that it is really 
 possible." 1 Imagination is productive; memory is merely 
 reproductive. The object represented in memory is real; 
 that represented in imagination may be unreal. Memory 
 is mediate knowledge of tlie actual in the past; imagina- 
 tion is mediate knowledge of the possible in the past, pres- 
 ent, or future. 2 The ideas or images in both cases are real, 
 but they diifer in their origin and in their objects. 
 
 § 1#2. The sphere of the real is finite ; that of the unreal 
 is infinite. Mind trangresses the bounds of the real, and 
 forms for itself ideal objects in the boundless unreal. But 
 there are limits to its excursive power. That imagination 
 is conditioned on memory is one limitation. Although it 
 disregards experience, it cannot transgress the bounds of 
 
 1 Hamilton, Discussions^ p. 58, Am. eel. 
 
 2 Were this power wholly lacking, we should be unable to devise for the 
 future, or to anticipate and provide for even the next coming moment. All 
 hope, all reasonable forecast of events, all inspired prophecy, the history of 
 the future, are wrought out by imagination, and then become memories as 
 time flows by. The young, says Aristotle, live forwards in hope, the old live 
 backwards in memory. — Rhet. , ii, if^ The following lines of Shelley mark 
 the distinction : — 
 
 " You are not here ! the quaint witch Memory sees 
 In vacant chairs your absent images, 
 And points where once you sat, and now should be, 
 But are not. I demand if ever we 
 Shall meet as then we met; and she replies. 
 Veiling in awe her second-sighted eyes : 
 'I know the past alone; but summon home 
 My sister Hope, she speaks of all to come.' 
 But I, an old diviner, who know well 
 Every false verse of that sweet oracle, 
 Turned to the sad enchantress once again, 
 And sought a respite from ray gentle pain. 
 By acting every passage o'er and o'er, 
 Of our communion." 
 
200 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 experience. At the furthest extreme, its images are com- 
 binations of partial experiences given by memory; it is 
 only the combination that is new.^ The limitation is not 
 to objects of sight, nor in general to those of sense. ^ All 
 presentations, external and internal, all sensations, emo- 
 tions, desires, affections, volitions, and thoughts furnish, 
 through memory, materials for imagination. Whatever can 
 be remembered can be idealized. The true linutation is 
 experience reproduced in memory. 
 
 A second limitation : Imagination, being representative of 
 an intuition, is, like intuition, possible only on condition 
 that its immediate object be individual. If we try to form 
 the image of a triangle, it must be of some individual figure. 
 To the individual is opposed the general. I can foi-ni no 
 image of the general. The notion triangle can attain to 
 generality only by surrendering distinct existence in space. 
 Nature and fact do not present the general, but only indi- 
 
 1 " For it is not in the power of the most exalted wit or enlarged under- 
 standing, by any quickness or variety of thought, to invent or frame one 
 new simple idea in the mind. The dominion of man, in this little world of 
 his own understanding, is much the same as it is in the great world of visible 
 things, wherein his power, however managed by art and skill, reaches no 
 further than to compound or divide the materials that are made to his hand, 
 but can do nothing towards the making the least particle of new matter, or 
 destroying one atom of what is already in being." — Locke, Essay, h^i. ii, 
 ch. 2, § 2. Experience is the quarry whence memory draws the materials 
 with which imagination (Ger. Einhildungskraft) builds. 
 
 Hume asks, however, whether one who had seen blue and yellow, but not 
 green, would not be able to form an idea of green by compounding the others 
 in imagination. 
 
 2 We most readily represent visual objects, and thi§ with surpassing clear- 
 ness and accuracy, and so become slaves to the eye, — a despotism from 
 which Tythagoras by his mimeral and Plato by his musical symbols, as the 
 first irpoiraidevTiKdv of the mind, .sought to emancipate their disciples. See 
 Fhoido, GO Ste. Some writers have so far yielded to this sway of the eye as 
 to teach that imagination is. limited to visual ol)jects. So Addison, Pleasures 
 of r may.. Sped. 40; and Reid, Intellect. Powers, Essay, iv, ch. 1. Others 
 teach that it is limited to objects of sense. So Stewart, Elements, pt. i, cli. ;] ; 
 and also Descartes, who says: "Tmagiiiari nihil aliud est quam rei corporese 
 figuram seu imaginem contemplari." — ^Jed., ii. 
 
IMA GIN A TION. 201 
 
 viduals, having each a distinct existence in space or time.i 
 My experience, then, is only of individuals ; and as images 
 are representations of experience, they are limited to indi- 
 viduals. 
 
 The third limitation of imagination is common to all 
 powers of knowledge. Every cognitive experience is con- 
 ditioned on pure ideas and principles, discerned by reason, 
 acting as regulative, or rather as limitative, of cognition 
 (§ 151). These, then, set bounds that imagination cannot 
 transcend. We cannot imagine a body out of space, or an 
 uncaused event, or an absolute beginning or ending, or con- 
 tradictories coexistent, or irresponsible personal actions. 
 Beyond the sphere thus strictly circumscribed, imagination 
 cannot pass. The light dove cleaving in free flight the thin 
 air, whose resistance she feels, might think that her move- 
 ments would be far more free and rapid in air-less space. 
 But her flight fails from lack of support even in the rare 
 regions, long before she reaches the invisible yet absolute 
 limit, beyond which the lightest wing can never soar. So 
 within a vast unmeasured region of pure ideas, the atmos- 
 phere of reality, imagination may play, but not beyond. 
 
 § 193. Within these limits, imagination shows various 
 modes of activity. Certain differences fairly distinguish 
 kinds; others seem to be marks rather of degree. One 
 mode of exercise we will call the simple to distinguish it 
 from the complex or productive imagination. 
 
 Simple imagination consists in the transfer of an object 
 from the real to the ideal sphere. It represents an object 
 that is real without reference to its reality, that is, in disre- 
 gard of the fact; as, If the sun be now in the sky. Here a 
 known reality is idealized: the matter is treated hypotheti- 
 cally. Another simple exercise is to idealize in spite of 
 fact, taking the obverse of reality; as. Were the sun not in 
 
 1 See Mansel, Metaphysics, p. 129. 
 
^02 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 the sky. To realize is the converse of to idealize ; it is to 
 bring matter from the ideal sphere into the real ; as, But the 
 sun is now in the sky. The obsolescence of the subjunc- 
 tive mood, which is the ideal mode of speech, indicates a 
 common neglect of these distinctions. 
 
 § 194. From the individual objects presented to sense, 
 external or internal, and represented in memory, thought 
 abstracts qualities, and forms representative notions by 
 combining them into new qualitative wholes ; this is anal}'- 
 sis and synthesis. From such individual objects, the com- 
 plex or productive imagination severs parts, and forms ideas 
 by recombining them into new quantitative wholes, into new 
 individuals ; this is dissection and construction. The objects 
 thus represented are contingent or unreal, the only actual 
 existence being the factitious images or ideas of the mind, 
 representing what would be possible to intuition, and cor- 
 responding to objects merely hypothetical.^ 
 
 Dissection and composition constitute one special exercise 
 of the productive faculty. It may, however, merely alter 
 proportions, or size, or motion, making transformations as to 
 space or time. The former species is constructive imagi- 
 nation; the latter is plastic imagination. ^ 
 
 1 Thus out of materials funiished by memory are constructed new geo- 
 metrical figures, new mechanical inventions, palaces of pearl, satyrs and 
 mermaids, all fabulous monsters and events, the novelties of prose fiction, 
 the creations of poesy and art. For an excellent example of dissection and 
 composition, see the description of Chimera by Homer, Iliad, vi, 144 sq.; and 
 by Hesiod, Theoffony, v, 322 sq. 
 
 2 Hence the grotesque Caliban, the fantastic Touchstone, and the extrava- 
 gant Parolles. Hence the Brobdignags and Lilliputians, the nut-shell car of 
 Queen Mab (Romeo and Juliet, A. 1, sc. 4), the golden car of Juno {Iliad, 
 v), and the great chariot of the Sun-god Phoebus. Time, space, and motion 
 are its subjects. It expands a geologic cycle to myriads of centuries, com- 
 presses the stellar system to a celestial vault, and inspires Puck's prophetic 
 brag: " I'll put a girdle round about the earth in forty minutes." — Midswn- 
 mer XiyhVs Dream, A. 2, sc. 1. 
 
 Are its productions creations ? Is imagination creative ? Creation is the 
 bringing into existence what did not before exist. Bringing order out of 
 
IMAGINATION. 203 
 
 § 195. Other distinctions may be taken, determining 
 varieties according to the reLative predominance of co-operat- 
 ing activities. The first cLaiming our attention is character- 
 ized negatively by the absence of volitional control. 
 
 Involuntary imagination is spontaneous, without choice. 
 Phantasy is an appropriate name for this variety. The 
 phantoms that fright us in the dark, the spectral voices that 
 we hear, the odd, ludicrous, and absurd ideas that strike us, 
 are among its products. Phantasies have an instinctive 
 origin. Slental instincts are the promptings of blind de- 
 sires ; that is, of such as are not directed by thought. These 
 arouse imagination to a disordered activity, producing the 
 fantastic. Phantasy, therefore, is characterized by the im- 
 pulsion of desire in the absence of intelligent choice. ^ 
 
 Dreams afford familiar examples of phantasms. They 
 have already been noted as involuntary memories (§ 187) ; but 
 perhaps their images are less memories than new combi- 
 nations, " wherein blind phantasy would fain interpret to the 
 mind the painful sensations of distempered sleep." ^ Reverie, 
 castle-building, or day-dreaming is a pleasing play of phan- 
 tasy, not, however, altogether pure, since a fanciful purpose 
 generally gives some voluntary direction to the combina- 
 
 chaos is a creation. Order, laarmony, fitness, new proportions, new combi- 
 nations into new wholes, are creations, and he who produces these is a maker, 
 TToiijTT??, a poet. "Though there were many clever men in England during 
 the latter part of the seventeenth century," says Macaulay, "there were 
 only two great creative minds. One of those minds produced the Pai-adise 
 Lost, the other the Pilgrim's Progress.'" — Esscnj on Southey''s Bunyan. 
 Shakspeare, "I'homme qui a le plus cree apres Dieu," out -doing history, 
 has peopled his realm with immortals. The Black Prince was, but is not ; 
 Prince Hamlet was not, but is, and will be forever. 
 
 1 From (t>a.vTa.^eLv, to cause to appear. Gurney defines a sensory halluci- 
 nation to be "a percept which lacks, but which can only by distinct reflection 
 be recognized as lacking, the objective basis which it suggests." — In Mind, 
 No. 38, p. 163. This scarcely differs from illusion. See § 160, note. We 
 take illusion to be the genus, and hallucination its species, differentiated by 
 being abnormal. 
 
 2 The will resigns control, and these sensations, together with appetites 
 
204 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 tions. The craze of delirium and of monomania are extreme 
 cases.^ 
 
 § 196. Let us consider here, once for all, the relation of 
 imagination to brain action. It has been scientifically ascer- 
 tained that when the inner"* organ of sight is disorganized, 
 it becomes impossible to image scenes ; and we hold it gen- 
 erally true that all mental activities are specially conditioned 
 on concomitant brain action (§ 143). Voluntary efforts of 
 imagination doubtless require for their success a physical 
 response, a corresponding molecular movement of the brain 
 substance, probably that of the inner organ of the sense 
 originally presenting such objects as are now represented.^ 
 
 and other forms of desire, impelling blindly in the general torpor of intelli- 
 gence, arouse imagination to unchecked extravagance. 
 
 " When nature rests, 
 Oft in her absence mimic fancy wakes 
 To imitate her; but, misjoining shapes, 
 Wild worlv produces oft, ;ind most in dreams, 
 III matching words and deeds long past or late." 
 
 — Milton, Paradise Lost, bk. v, 109 sq. 
 
 It is remarkable that the power of self-control seems to have so little 
 reserve force that it is the first of our faculties to break down, not only in 
 sleep, but in grief, in intoxication, in fever, in case of a stunning blow, etc. 
 Other faculties continue active when this has completely succumbed. The 
 torpor of volition during sleep is an important element in explaining the 
 phenomena of dreaming. 
 
 1 In reverie the imagination suffers but little restraint. Images assemble, 
 form, and dissolve, not so much at will as at pleasure. It is the dolce far 
 niente, the luxury of idleness. "La reverie est le dimanche de la pensfie." 
 — Amiel. 
 
 The generic character and difference of delirium and monomania come to 
 light on comparing Otway's line, — 
 
 " Lutes, laurels, seas of milk, and ships of amber," 
 with Lear's pathetic words, — 
 
 " What! have his daughters brought him to this pass? " 
 
 2 " What is the manner of the occuiJation of the brain with a resuscitated 
 feeling of resistance, a smell, a sound ? There is only one answer that seems 
 admissible: The renewed feeling occupies the very same parts, and in the 
 same manner, as the original feeling, and no otluT parts, nor in any other 
 assignable manner." — 15ai.\, iienses and JntcUect, p. ;3;J8. See § 17, note 2. 
 
IMAGINATION. 205 
 
 It is certainlj'' true that imaged activity always tends strongly 
 to go out into real activity. When we image a leap, we are 
 ready and disposed to spring ; when we con over a proposed 
 speech we are apt to break out with it aloud ; a fancied blow 
 causes one to start or dodge ; and on this principle alone can 
 we account for many varieties of involuntary gesticulation 
 and facial expression, which it requires severe discipline to 
 repress.! In all such cases the cause is mental, and brain 
 change the effect. 
 
 The reverse is true in perception. Here the brain is 
 active and the mind recipient. Probably this is the case 
 also in involuntary memory and imagination ; brain changes 
 are the cause, mental images the effect. Certain molecular 
 movements take place in an inner organ of sense confusedly 
 along lines of preference established by habit, and these 
 determine or cause a succession of corresponding mental 
 images in more or less confusion and disorder. Hence a 
 man dreams in character. Physical appetites also, as hunger 
 and thirst, will direct and color a dream. Hence likewise 
 the subjective effects of brain fever, and the extravagant 
 visions of the opium eater.^ All these are cases of neural 
 disturbances determining mental images. Hence it appears 
 that involuntary or spontaneous memory and imagination 
 
 1 Miiller cites the following instances: "The mere idea of a nauseous 
 taste can excite the sensation even to the production of vomiting. The qual- 
 ity of the sensation is the property of the sensitive nerve, which is here 
 excited without any external agent. The mere sight of a person about to 
 pass a sharp instrument over glass or porcelain is sufficient, as Darwin 
 remarks, to excite the well-known sensation in the teeth. The mere think- 
 ing of objects capable, when present, of exciting shuddering, is sufficient to 
 produce that sensation of the surface in persons of irritable habit." — Physi- 
 ology, p. 945. 
 
 2 The doctrine is not new. It occurs in the following : — 
 
 "Lovers and madmen have such seething braiuB, 
 Such shaping fantasies, that apprehend 
 More than cool reason ever comprehends." 
 
 — Midsummer Night's Dream,, A. 5, so. 1. 
 
 Observe also the accurate and happy use of the terms apprehend and com- 
 prehend. 
 
206 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 differ from perception in degree rather than in kind, it being^ 
 no essential difference whether the movement of the sensory 
 be determined by a physical habit, by the stimulus of fever 
 or of opium, or by a normal influence passing from the outer 
 organ along the nerve of sense to the inner sensory. 
 
 Brain excitement in the cases of spontaneous memory and 
 imagination is ordinarily of lower degree than in case of per- 
 ception. Accordingly images are normally much less vivid 
 than percepts.^ It is by this different degree of vividness 
 that we usually distinguish an image from an object proper ; 
 that is, from a sensorial excitement due to an extra-organic 
 cause.2 But when memory or imagination are extraordina- 
 rily aroused by a brain excitement correspondingly great, 
 images may be as vivid as percepts, and then can be dis- 
 tinguished from them only by applying several senses as 
 tests. The madman and the ghost-seer are conscious of 
 
 1 Says Spencer: 'Terceptions are vivid states of consciousness ; memories 
 are faint states of consciousness.' ' 
 
 2 Upon this ground we regard mental images iu dreams, without doubt or 
 question, as external realities. Descartes asks, " How do we know that the 
 thoughts which occur in dreaming are false, rather than those otlier which we 
 experience when awake, since the former are often not less vivid and distinct 
 than the latter ? Attentively considering these cases, I perceive so clearly 
 tliat there exist no certain marks by which the state of waking can ever be 
 distinguished from sleep, that I almost persuade myself that I am now 
 dreaming." — 0« Method, pt. i. See also Meditation 1st, and Principles, 
 pt. i, § 4. 
 
 Is it not conceivable, then, that hereafter we may awaken from life into 
 some higher state of intelligence, and discover that what in life we took to be 
 external realities were merely mental images ? Is it not true that, — 
 
 " We are such stuff 
 As dreams are made on; ami our little life 
 Is rounded with a sleep."— Tempest, A. 4, sc. 1. 
 
 Had we no other means than degree of vividness by which to distingui.sh 
 the ideal from the real, we might be led by the idealist to doubt reality. 
 When asleep and dreaming, we have no other means ; but when awake there 
 do exist very certain marks, overlooked by Descartes, which leave no doubt. 
 The aroused and masterful volition applies the tests of various senses, and so 
 determines the (juestion. See § Kil, last paragraph ; but more especially see 
 the chapter on External Reality, § 100 sq. 
 
IMAGINATION. 207 
 
 objects which are truly external to self, though enorganic, and 
 they mistake only in referring them to extra-organic causes.^ 
 
 § 197. Returning to the varieties of imagination, we are 
 now to consider what is commonly called the voluntary 
 imagination. It is distinguished from phantasy in being 
 governed by a purpose. This purpose is conditioned on and 
 impelled by a desire, it may be a desire to feel, or a desire to 
 know, or a desire to do, and imagination is made to represent 
 accordingly. Hereon, then, we ground a subdivision of its 
 modes. Impelled by intelligent desire and controlled by 
 will, imagination may be exercised with special reference to 
 sentiment, giving the artistic imagination ; or with reference 
 to knowledge, giving the reflective imagination ; or with ref- 
 erence to performance, giving the practical imagination. The 
 order here adopted is continuously progressive toward the real. 
 
 § 198. The artistic imagination, or that characterizing the 
 fine arts, has two sub-varieties, or rather degrees, fancy and 
 
 1 When one's terrors conjure up a ghost, it is truly a visible thing, external 
 to the seer, existing in his visual organ. 
 
 " This is the vei'v coinage of your brain; 
 This bodiless creation ecstasy 
 Is very cunning in.'.' — Queen to Hamlet, A. 3, sc. 4. 
 
 Huxley, remarking the famous case of Mrs. A., detailed by Brewster in 
 his Natural Magic, says, " Mrs. A. undoubtedly sav? what she said she saw." 
 — Physiology, p. 269. That is, as he explains, her retina was affected from 
 within so as to present the image of an object which did not otherwise exist. 
 Says Gurney : "In the most complete or ' external ' form of hallucinations, a 
 refluent current will pass downwards to the external organ, and the percep- 
 tion will be referred to the eye or ear, just as though its object were really 
 acting on those organs from outside." — In Mind, No. 38, p. 191. Proofs 
 are : 1st. Pressure on one side of one eyeball, or squinting, doubles the 
 phantom. 2d. A hemiopic case, where only the upper half of a phantom 
 was seen, the upper half of the retina being anopic. 3d. The surviving of 
 dream-images into waking moments. This last was remarked by Spinoza, 
 and observed by MiiWer. ~ Physiology , p. 945. Wundt suggests that, in case 
 the phantom does not move with the eye, this centrifugal retinal stimulation 
 is disproved. — Phys. Psych., vol. ii, p. 356, 
 
208 MEDIATE KXOWLELXJE. 
 
 the poetic imagination. They have this in common, and are 
 thereby distinguished from other varieties of imagination, 
 that they have direct reference to sentiment, but more espe- 
 cially to the aesthetic feeling, aiming to excite the pleasing 
 sense of beauty, and being governed by the aesthetic judg- 
 ment conformably to the laws of taste. Their difference is 
 one of degree.^ 
 
 Fancy excites only the more delicate sentiments, and these 
 delicately; poetic imagination aspires to awaken emotion and 
 often soars to the sublime. The latter adheres more closely 
 to the truth of nature, and is more severely logical ; the 
 former disregards the truth of nature, creating a new idea, 
 a fairyland of its own, and submits to logic only so far 
 as not to fall into the disorder and misrepresentations of 
 phantasy. Thus fancy is an advance beyond phantasy in 
 the movement from the impossible and absurd, toward the 
 actual and real.^ 
 
 1 The Greeks used <pavTaaia to designate both, but modern usage distin- 
 guishes them. Wordsworth, in the preface to his Lyrical Ballads, marks 
 clearly the difference. See also Trench, Study of Words, ad verb. Previously 
 Addison confused them. — Sjwct. No. 40. Afterward Coleridge went to the 
 opposite extreme, affirming that "fancy and imagination are two distinct 
 and widely different faculties." — Biog. Lit., ch. 4. 
 
 2 Shakspeare strikingly marks this triple gi-adation in the famous and 
 familiar speech of Theseus in Midsummer Night's Dream, A. 5, so. 1. 
 
 Fancy finds play not only in literature, but in all the fine arts. It conde- 
 scends to a lower plane, and appears in conversation, in dress, and in the 
 decorative arts. It revels in associations that are remote, arbitrary, and 
 capricious, and so indulges in whimsical conceits and prettiuess. Cowley's 
 genius was fanciful, Milton's imaginative, Shakspeare was lord of both 
 realms. The Midsummer Xiglit's Dream is a perfect example of the fanci- 
 ful, wlierein imagination moves on a wing as light as Ariel's. Fancy is 
 always more nimble than strong, more gentle than bold, more witty than wise. 
 The goddess of wisdom sprang from the head of Jupiter. A little song in 
 Shakspeare asks : — 
 
 "Tell me where is fancy bred, 
 Or in tl)o heart, or in the head ? 
 How begot, how nourished ? 
 Reply, reply." 
 
 Goethe answers: "Fancy is the ever-movhig, ever-new, Jove's loveliest 
 daughter, child of his heart." 
 
IMA GIN A TION. 209 
 
 § 199. The higher degree of the artistic imagination is 
 called the poetic imagination. The word poetic must be 
 here understood as excluding the merely fanciful, and as 
 including much of prose fiction and of mimetic fine art.^ Gov- 
 erned by laws of taste more exacting, more nearly connected 
 with reason, the poetic imagination is closely observant of 
 nature, heedful of truth, and submissive to logical sequence.^ 
 It is popularly supposed to disregard or even defy logic ; 
 whereas it is strictly logical. Throughout every poem must 
 lun a continuous thread of logical sequence, however con- 
 cealed, to give it cohesion and unity, and in the truly great 
 poems there is a reason assignable, not only for every word, 
 but for the place of every word, just as there is likewise one 
 for every curve in a statue, for every hue in a painting, and 
 for every passing note in a sonata. 
 
 § 200. Next in the approach toward the real, is the reflec- 
 tive imagination. It is so called because it especially relates 
 to thought in the search for knowledge. Herein imagination 
 
 1 Poetry aud music coalesce in song, and it is admissible to say that the 
 symphonies of Beethoven are tone poems, that the Cupid and Psyche of 
 Canova is a marble lyric, and that the Vatican frescoes of Raphael are the 
 «pic of the Church. 
 
 2 Both fancy and the poetic imagination are creative. "Imagination, in 
 the sense of the poet," says Wordsworth, "has no reference to images that 
 iire merely a faithful copy, existing in the mind, of absent external objects, 
 but is a word of higher import, denoting operations of the mind upon these 
 objects, and processes of creation or composition governed by fixed laws." — 
 Preface to Lyrical Ballads. 
 
 The German calls a poet a thinker (Dichter, related to DenJcer), and poet- 
 ical power the power of thought (Dic)itungskraft). Some one has said that 
 high art is deep metaphysics. Whether it be in poetry or music, in painting 
 or sculpture, the triumph of the artist lies, not in presenting us with a tran- 
 script of things that may be seen or heard or handled in the world around us, 
 but in carrying us across the gulf which separates the real from the ideal, 
 and placing us in the presence of the truly beautiful, and surrounding us 
 with an atmosphere more pure than that which the sun enlightens. "For, 
 with the exception of the self-existent Being," says Rousseau, "there is 
 nothing beautiful but that which is not.' ' 
 
210 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 submits to yet closer bonds. Regardless of sentiment, it 
 seeks neither the beautiful nor the sublime, but harnessed by 
 logic, and driven by desire to know, it labors after truth, 
 which when ascertained it strives to represent with clearness 
 and fulness. 
 
 Reflective imagination, like the artistic, has two degrees. 
 The first let us call the philosophic or scientific imagination. 
 This is largely occupied in representing the hypotheses of 
 thought in its tentative excursions. It images conceivable 
 possibilities relative to the question in hand, which thought 
 scrutinizes and adopts or rejects according to the facts ; as 
 Huygens' hypothesis of a vibrating luminiferous ether filling 
 space was adopted in place of Newton's emission hypothesis. 
 Moreover, when thought reaches its conclusion, imagination 
 pictures it in full, filling up the outlines, supplying accordant 
 circumstances, enlarging perhaps beyond the strict limits of 
 ascertained truth.i 
 
 1 The geometrician figures before his mind's eye an original construction 
 to which his theorem applies, and then varies its proportions from limit ta 
 limit, and combines it with others, thus testing its consistency and its appli- 
 cations. D'Alembert says that, of all the great men of antiquity, Archimedes 
 is, in respect of imagination, best entitled to a place beside Homer. The 
 historian reasons on the circumstances of an event, and depicts the results in 
 a detailed description. Macaulay's fine historic imagination renders his style 
 autoptic. The astronomer discovers a new law, and in applying it, perfects 
 by imagination his knowledge of the mechanism of the heavens. The human 
 body, by the power of imagination, becomes transparent to the eye of the 
 anatomist ; the frame of the earth, to the eye of the geologist. 
 
 Unless held under severe clieck, the philosophic is very liable to return 
 into the poetic imagination. The most illustrious example is Plato, whom 
 Panoetius calls the Homer of philosophy. Aristotle pronounces his system 
 of ideas a collection of poetical metaphors. "Abandoning the world of 
 reasoning, because of the narrow limits it sets to the understanding, he ven- 
 tured," says Kant, "upon the wings of ideas beyond it, into the void space 
 of pure intellect." — C. P. /?., Int. § 3. "Nothing is more dangerous to 
 reason," says Hume, "than flights of imagination, and nothing has been the 
 occasion of more mistakes among philosopliers. Men of bright fancies may, 
 in this respect, be compared to those angels whom the Scriptures represent 
 as covering their eyes with their wings." — Treatise of Human Nature, bk. i, 
 pt. iv, § 7. 
 
IMA GIN A TION. 211 
 
 § 201. The second degree of the reflective imagmation 
 corresponds pretty closely with what Aristotle calls "the 
 deliberative imagination." It is still more confined than the 
 first, representing in a concrete image merely and strictly 
 the attributes that constitute a thought, and thus operating 
 to embody the thought while testing its logical possibility. 
 Its importance is inestimable. Its special consideration is 
 postponed to the next topic, Thought, with which it is so 
 intimately related (§ 214). 
 
 § 202. Still nearer to the reality stands the practical imag- 
 ination. The bounds are here greatly narrowed. Phantasy 
 is checked only by the bare necessities of intellect ; fancy is 
 more orderly ; the higher poetic imagination still more closely 
 conforms to nature ; philosophic imagination represents what 
 is moreover regarded as true ; but practical imagination is 
 confined to what may also become actual fact. These wide 
 extremes, the possible idea, and the possible fact are the 
 bounds of imagination. 
 
 In the practical imagination, also, we distinguish two varie- 
 ties. The first forms ideas of actions ; the second, ideal 
 standards of actions. Of these in their order. 
 
 The first variety bears a special relation to volition. It is 
 that mode of voluntary imagination which has for its object 
 voluntary activity tending directly to realization. Every 
 outward activity requires that we should previously construct 
 its image. I cannot pick up a pin, or stick one in my dress, 
 or take a seat in a chair, or reach for a book, without a prior 
 image of myself as doing these acts. So in all things small 
 and great, from the plucking of an apple, to an Alexandrine 
 conquest. This variety of the practical imagination is im- 
 plied in all provision ; it is prerequisite to every desired end, 
 to every step of prudence, to every act of duty.^ 
 
 1 I cannot pen a syllable without first imagining that syllable, and myself 
 as writing it ; then my pen traces on the paper the form which imagination 
 has already imprinted there. The mechanic who invents a machine must 
 
212 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 A sharp limit is set to this exercise of imagination by a 
 certain judgment and belief. Any one may easily imagine 
 himself leaping over a house, but knowing that he cannot, 
 believing it impracticable, this is merely a bizarre fancy, and 
 not the practical imagination. To be the latter, the action 
 imagined must be regarded as possible. I cannot even at- 
 tempt what I judge and believe to be impracticable. An 
 insane man might try to leap over a house, but it is impossi- 
 ble for a sane man to try. No matter how intense may be 
 my wish that it Vv^ere possible for me to do a thing, I must 
 not only imagine the doing it, but also must believe, rightly 
 or not, at least that perhaps I can do it, before I can make 
 the effort. An actual effort, unsustained by this judgment 
 and belief, is a psychological impossibility .^ 
 
 construct it in imagination before he can realize it in wood and iron. If a 
 mountain is to be tunnelled, the engineer must devise the means ; if a river is 
 to be bridged, he has already marked the progress of the work while yet the 
 timber is in the forest and the metal in the mine. The merchant in his 
 counting-room plans distant voyages ; the general in his solitarj^ winter 
 quarters maps out the next summer's campaign. The artist who paints a 
 fresco, or carves a statue, or builds a temple, has devised mentally before he 
 produces manually ; his representative ideas exist before they are embodied 
 in representative things. 
 
 " Such tricks bath strong imagination, 
 That if it would but apprehend some joy, 
 It comprehends some bringer of that joy." 
 
 — Midsummer Night's Dream, A. 5, bc. 1. 
 
 The work presupposes, first, the artistic imagination to compose, then the 
 practical imagination to. devise, and then the manual skill to execute. If 
 any one of the three is defective, the work is marred. In general, the ability 
 to frame practical images of what one would do, to plan one's conduct and 
 action, is the mark of an efficient character ; to do so promptly on euu-rgency 
 is presence of mind. Executive talent is little else than another name for 
 practical imagination. He who has none, or does not exercise what he has, 
 blunders along through life, and is the victim of accidents. He leaves his 
 teaspoon standing .in his cup, sets down a coal-bucket at the head of the 
 stairs, packs his trunk on the assumption that it is to continue right side up 
 throughout his journey, is too late for the train, demands his dinner in less 
 than five niiimtes, and neglects to write proper names, especially his own, 
 with absolute plainness. 
 
 1 The belief that I can do a thing may be a delusion, but while the dclu- 
 
IMAGINATION. 213 
 
 § 203. The second variety of the practical imagination is 
 the forming of ideals. We have spoken of the ideal sphere 
 of cognition in opposition to the real, and of all objects of 
 imagination in general as ideal objects (§ 190). But the noun 
 ideal has acquired a specific sense. It designates an idea 
 proposed by the mind for imitation or attainment, a paradigm 
 or standard or model of perfection in things or actions which 
 invites realization. We frame an ideal of whatever is capa- 
 ble of various degrees of excellence by collecting' in one the 
 best elements of many, thus representing the highest extreme 
 of an idealized perfection. This then affords a standard 
 towards which we strive, and by which we measure the real- 
 ized fact. 
 
 In its psychological character an ideal seems to hover 
 between an idea and a concept. That it is a representation 
 of something which we endeavor to make real, marks it as a 
 product of practical imagination. That it is constituted of 
 
 sion lasts I can try. But if in fact the thing is easy, yet my delusion now is 
 that I can't do it, then it is impossible for me to try. The child at school 
 who says, " I can't," and believes it, says true, no matter how easy the task 
 may be ; and it is sheer cruelty to enforce a simulated effort. The ineffi- 
 ciency of a hopeless disposition is proverbial. We exhort youth to attempt 
 great things. The words are idle, unless he is convinced that to him great 
 things are possible. " Possunt posse quia videnter." — Virgil. The under- 
 estimate of one's powers by just so much retrenches efficiency ; whereas some 
 overestimate, which is likely to be corrected by failure, will bring out their 
 full strength. 
 
 Another psychological fact should be here noted. All the ideal within the 
 described limit strives to cross the opposite limit, and pass into the real. It 
 lies deep in human nature that whatever is vividly conceived, it strongly 
 tends to produce. Imagination reacts to strengthen desire, which urges 
 realization, and we are impelled to accomplish in fact what we image in 
 vision. Looking down a precipice suggests so forcibly the idea of falling, 
 that an effort of self-control is requisite to keep one's self from acting it out. 
 Cherishing merely the thought of a crime will bring forth the crime. Brood- 
 ing on the idea hatches the thing. If virtue be teachable, it is here. Inflame 
 imagination with its charms, and it will become a hfe. Fill the mind with 
 great thoughts, and they will become great deeds. The subjective evolves 
 the objective. The human mind represents a Utopia, and struggles to realize 
 it. The Divine Mind conceived a kosmos ; the universe appeared. 
 
214 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 qualities abstracted from various sources, which collected in 
 one have an application more or less general, assimilates it 
 to a product of thought. Hence we may properly be said 
 to conceive an ideal ; whereas we do not properly conceive, 
 but frame or form an imaefe or idea. 
 
 An artist selects and assembles in one whole the beauties 
 and perfections which are found in different individuals, 
 excluding everything defective or unseemly, so as to form a 
 type or model of the species. His artistic imagination pro- 
 poses some particular composition, but his practical imagina- 
 tion has already conceived something higher, towards which 
 he strives, to which he would make his production conform. 
 This is the hemi ideal., in a sense critical and aesthetic, a tj'pe 
 of the beautiful in hypothetical perfection.^ 
 
 Perhaps every man forms ideals of character and conduct. 
 We set before us standards of personal attainment, physical, 
 
 1 In illustration of the Platonic meaning of TrapdSeiy/jia, or an ideal, Cicero 
 tells us that Zeuxis had five of the most beautiful women of Crotona as 
 models, from whom to make up his picture of a perfect beauty. — Z)e Inven- 
 tione, ii, 1. Thus he hoped to realize his ideal. Elsewhere Cicero observes 
 that there is nothing so fair but that a fairer may be conceived. We can, for 
 example, conceive of statues more perfect than those of riiidias. " Nor did 
 this artist, when he made his statue of Jupiter or of Minerva, contemplate 
 any one individual from whom to take a likeness ; but in the depth of his 
 soul resided a perfect type of beauty, on which he gazed, and which guided 
 his hand and skill — ad iUius siinnUudiiiem artem et manum dirigebat.''^ — 
 De Oratore, ii, 9. "Thus his ideal is the artist's object of passionate con- 
 templation. Assiduously and silently meditated, unceasingly purified by 
 reflection and vivified by sentiment, it warms genius and inspires it with an 
 irresistible need of seeing it realized and living." — Colsin, DuVrai, du Bcmi, 
 et du Bien, 8me le§on. 
 
 It can hardly be doubted that the Platonic theory of ideas originated in 
 the contemplation of these natural products, the ideals of the human mind. 
 For an account of their historical genesis, see Aristotle, 3Ieta., i, 0, 9. To 
 whatever niay receive a common name, there is posited an answering idea ; 
 or, as Aristotle says : " Plato places an idea to every class of being." — Meta., 
 xii, 3. Notwithstanding this generality, the Platonic idea is an individual, 
 eiSos, formed of the essence of individual things. iEsthetically and ethically 
 it is perfect, and to it the corresponding realities, erSwXa, remain perpetually 
 inferior. It is the archetype or pattern, TrapdSeiytxa, to which things conform, 
 
IMA GIN A TION. 215 
 
 intellectual, or moral. The early visions of hope and the 
 romance of reverie build ideals of excellence towards which 
 we longingly struggle, to which we aspire to conform. 
 What a man most admires in character is a sure index, if 
 not of what he is, at least of what he would become. If his 
 ideal be pure and true, then it is his guardian angel, ever 
 leading him to something higher and better. 
 
 The ideal of the artist once conceived, all his works, 
 though increasingly beautiful, are mere idols ; that is, rude 
 images of a superior beauty which they fail to realize. So 
 also, tell me of a noble action, and I will instantly imagine 
 one still more noble. The ideal is ever higher than achieve- 
 ment. It flies before the real like a shadow, never to be 
 overtaken ; it is the unattained and unattainable paradise 
 of our despair. " Continually receding as we approach, it 
 expands at last to the infinite, to God ; for the true, the 
 absolute and the complete is God himself. L'ideal, viola 
 I'echelle mysterieuse qui fait monter Tame du fini a I'infini ! " 
 
 by which they are realized, toward which they ascend. The individual things 
 have necessarily a participation, fi^de^is, in, or are an imitation, fiifi-rjcns, 
 ofioiixjffLs, of the idea. The idea, though existing independently, aiirb KdO' 
 avTo, has also a certain community, KOLvujvLa, with things. It is in some sense 
 present, irapova-ia, in them, but yet complete in itself. See JSophistes, 256 a ; 
 and Parmenides, 132 b. 
 
216 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 CHAPTER VI. 
 
 THOUGHT. 
 
 § 204. Thought is representation by means of a notion. 
 Thus by thinking I form a general notion to which I give the 
 name lily, and this notion is representative of many individ- 
 ual lilies. In another aspect to think is to determine a 
 logical subject. Thus when I see a lily, I consider that its 
 needs are all supplied, that it toils not, neither does it spin, 
 that it is gloriously arrayed, etc. Here the subject, lil}-, is 
 in several respects determined. By these considerations I 
 know it more intimately, by these it is distinguished from a 
 great many other things. All that can be said of the sub- 
 ject is but a continuation of this process ; and each affirma- 
 tion or denial is a thought.^ 
 
 1 Even in scientific treatises the words thought, to thinli, etc., are com- 
 monly used very widely, not to say loosely. In Descartes, for example, cogi- 
 tatio or pensee denotes "all that in us of which we are immediately con- 
 scious. Thus all the operations of the will, of the imagination, and senses, 
 are thoughts." — Kesp. ad Sec. Obj., p. 85, ed. of 16G3. Cf. Hamilton in 
 Reid, p. 222, note. So Wundt. With him thought, Gedanke, is a state of 
 consciousness in general ; but he regards every such state as reducible to a 
 single fact, i.e. to reasoning or inference, Schliessen. This is his fundamen- 
 tal position. See his Physiologische Psychologie, p. 714. Without offering 
 here any opinion respecting this doctrine, we restrict thought by definition, 
 and treat it as a distinct faculty or activity. 
 
 It has a variety of synonyms ; e.g. discursive faculty or discursive reason, 
 as opposed to pure reason (Plato, Kant; see § 113, note), comparative fac- 
 ulty, faculty of relations, elabnrative faculty (Hamilton), faculty of compre- 
 hension, faculty of understanding ( VcrMand, Kant), for one understands a 
 thing when he makes it stand under a class. 
 
 We prefer the word thought, Anglo-Saxon theaht, N. II. Ger. Bedacht, Ge- 
 danke, a mental putting or bringing together of things, from deiileii, to think, 
 related to dkhlen, to compose, and so to dkht, compact, and dick, thick. 
 
THOU GUT. 217 
 
 The word 7iotio7i occurs in the foregomg definition. We 
 use it generically to designate products of thought, and these 
 only, and therefore as ox:)posed to the idea or image. Notions 
 are either marks or concepts. ]\Iarks are the various quali- 
 ties or attributes of an object analyzed by thought. A 
 concept is the result of the act of conception, or the act of 
 grasping together into one the various marks which charac- 
 terize an object.^ 
 
 § 205. It is obviously a primary condition of thought that 
 there should be an object or objects presented or represented 
 by the subsidiary faculties. These must furnish the crude 
 material out of which thought elaborates the concept. In 
 this exercise three elements or operations or movements are 
 logically distinguishable, — abstraction, generalization, and 
 conception. 
 
 Abstraction is simply withdrawing the mind from other 
 objects l)y fixing attention on one. Thus, if I consider a 
 personal action, and observing that it is generous, fix my 
 attention on that, thereby withdrawing my mind from all 
 concomitant attributes, consciousness is abstracted from these 
 by concentrating upon the one, the generosity. Abstraction 
 
 Thus think comes from the same original root as thicl; tlie n (not found in 
 thowjM) being merely casual. In thinking we thicken by uniting many in 
 one. 
 
 1 Both psychology and logic treat of thought ; the former treats of it 
 inter alia; the latter exclusively. Yet these sciences taken strictly do not 
 intersect ; each has its special point of view. Psychologj- views the act and 
 product of thought in their relation to mind. It inquires a posteriori into 
 the phenomena of thought, seeking their explanation and laws. Logic views 
 the product of thought without reference to the producing mind. Starting 
 with axioms, it demonstrates a priori the laws that govern the process, 
 and whose violation nullifies thought. Psychology is the natural history 
 of thought. Logic is the theory of thought. See Mansel, Prolegomena 
 Logica, ch. 9. Herbart says: "Die ganze reine Logic hat es mit Verhiilt- 
 nissen des Gedachten zu thun ; aber iiberall nirgends mit der Thatigkeit des 
 Denkens, nirgends mit der psychologischen Moglichkeit desselben." — Psy- 
 chologie als Wissenschaft, th. ii, § 119. 
 
218 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 then is the act whereby consciousness is withdrawn from 
 other qualities of an object, or from other objects, by concen- 
 trating upon one. 
 
 It has already been pointed out (§ 87) that attention and 
 abstraction are psychological correlatives, the one the positive, 
 the other the negative, aspect of the same act. In the psy- 
 chological and negative view, we are understood to abstract 
 or draw away the mind from certain features of objects pre- 
 sented, absfrahere mentem a differentiis. In the logical and 
 positive view, we are said to abstract certain portions of a 
 total cognition from the remainder, ahstrahere differentias. 
 
 Mental dissection differs from abstraction. Abstraction 
 relates to qualities, dissection to quantities. It separates a 
 whole into its quantitative or mathematical parts, as head, 
 trunk, and limbs. It seems to be a movement of imagination 
 rather than of thought. Quantitative parts, however, may be 
 and often are viewed as qualities, and then are thoughts, as 
 vertebrate and invertebrate. 
 
 § 206. The process of abstraction is analytical, and the 
 result is the separation of a quality or attribute of a thing or 
 of an event from those with which it is really or in fact con- 
 comitant. This product, which truly has no independent 
 existence whatever, is viewed mentally as though it were in 
 itself an independent thing. Hence a simple abstract notion 
 is a mark considered as a thing. 
 
 The name of a quality in the concrete is an adjective noun, 
 and is always grammatically dependent ; as, Solomon the 
 wise. The name of a quality in the abstract is a substantive 
 noun, and may be the subject or the object of a proposition ; as. 
 Wisdom is the principal thing, therefore get wisdom. Such 
 abstract notions are primarily thought of as peculiar, and may 
 or may not be generalized. Particular marks or qualities 
 are individua sir/nata., belonging to this one thing and to no 
 other. Tliey may be taken abstractly, but are not susceptible 
 of generalization. 
 
THOUGHT. 219 
 
 § 207. The second function of thought is generalization. 
 Upon abstracting qualities from two or more objects we may- 
 be struck by the similarity of the qualities. If so, we simplify 
 and unify the cognitions by thinking the similar qualities to 
 be the same. For example, this paper, the wall, chalk, and 
 snow are each of them white. Similar qualities are those that 
 stand in similar relation to our organs and faculties. When 
 the similarity is complete, the effects which they determine 
 in us are indistinguishable. What we cannot distinguish are 
 to us virtually the same, that is, they are subjectively to us 
 precisely as if they were objectively identical. The same, 
 accordingly, we consider them to be, though really in different 
 objects. This act, to think the similar the same, to consider 
 a plurality a unit}^ is the essence of generalization and is a 
 fundamental fiction of thought. The several objects whosa 
 mark has been generalized, we comprehend under a common 
 concrete name ; e.g. white thing. The generality of this 
 name consists solely in that it is applicable indifferently to 
 any one of the objects it comprehends. Hence generalization 
 is the act of comprehending in one notion several objects 
 agreeing in some quality which we abstract from each of 
 them, and which the common name serves to indicate. 
 
 § 208. The third operation of thought is conception. It 
 may occur immediately upon abstraction ; that is, without 
 generalization. When a number of marks have been ab- 
 stracted they may be collected by thought into one notion. 
 This is the act of conceiving or of conception, and the com- 
 plex notion thus obtained is the concept. A concept, then, 
 is a union of marks in one notion; or, we may say, a concept 
 is a bundle of marks.^ 
 
 Every object presented to the mind has an indefinite plu- 
 rality of marks. Observation can make many known to us, 
 
 1 To conceive, from eon-caper e, to grasp together ; Ger. hegreifen, Begriff, 
 allied to Eng. grip, grab, grasp, group. " A collection of attributes, united by 
 a sign, and representing a possible object of intuition." — Mansel. 
 
220 MEDIATE EyOWLEDGE. 
 
 but our knowledge, though constantly increasing in fulness 
 and complexity, can never become complete. Indeed, the 
 limited powers of the mind cannot take in at once all those 
 marks Avhose presence is known. A representation becomes 
 confused when we attempt to grasp or comprehend in one 
 notion more than a very few of them. Giving up the attempt, 
 we form a concept of the thing, embracing comparatively few 
 of its ascertained marks, making selection of such as are dis- 
 tinctive and essential. This is a singular or particular con- 
 cept. It is complex, but not general. To it we may apply 
 Esser's definition : A concept is the representation of a thing 
 through its distinctive marks. ^ 
 
 The particular concept is potentially general,^ and may 
 become actually so by being generalized.^ 
 
 On the other hand, if instead of particular marks I have 
 a number of common marks, that is, marks each of which has 
 already been generalized, these may likewise be conceived 
 together, and constitute at once a complex general notion, 
 general by virtue of the factitious generality of each one 
 of its constituents.* 
 
 1 In this way one forms a notion of historical characters, e.g. of Socrates, 
 of Csesar. In like manner every man forms a notion of himself, often 
 altogether erroneous. 
 
 2 Unless it involve a peculiar mark, as Cfesar, the conqueror of Pompey. 
 But even in such case there is no logical objection to the ancient supposition 
 that the whole history of mankind is constantly repeated from recurring 
 epochs, and so the name and actions of Csesar or Achilles will be found in 
 several individuals at corresponding periods of every cycle. See Virgil, 
 Eclogue, iv, 34 sq. , and Eccl. 1 : 9 ; also Mansel, Proleg. Logica, p. 70, and 
 Mill, Logic, p. 250, Am. eds. 
 
 3 For example : If I consider the several marks of the apple which I hold 
 in my hand, that it is vegetable, seed-bearing, edible, sugary, spherical, etc., 
 and, grasping these marks in one notion, thus form a notion of this apple, 
 then I have a particular concept of it. Afterward I observe that a similar 
 bundle of marks may be formed from other apples ; also from an orange, a 
 peach, a pear, a cherry, etc. Consequently, I consider these several similar 
 concepts to be the same, i.e. I generalize, and call this complex general notion 
 by the common name fruit. 
 
 * For example : I take the following marks, each of which I have separ- 
 
THOUGHT. 221 
 
 The general notion, perfected as to its content, is the ulti- 
 mate product of thought. Hence to think is to conceive, is 
 to form concepts, and a concept is a mental combination, or 
 reduction to unity of the similar qualities or marks of objects 
 of thought. It is true that it involves the representation of 
 a part only of the various marks, attributes, or characters of 
 which the individual object is the sum, and therefore affords 
 only a one-sided and inadequate knowledge of things. This 
 inadequacy is a consequence of the limited jDOwer of mind, 
 which must accept a small part as the whole of a thing, and 
 so resort to a fiction in order to comprehend, even in an im- 
 perfect manner, a plurality of things.^ 
 
 § 209. A process subsidiary to thought is denomination or 
 naming. The uniformities of things embraced in concepts 
 would quickly escape us, if we did not fix and ratify them by 
 sensuous signs.^ " A sign is necessary to give stability to our 
 intellectual progress, to establish each step in advance as 
 a new starting-point for our advance to another beyond. 
 A country may be overrun by an armed host, but it is only 
 conquered by the establishment of fortresses. Words are the 
 fortresses of thought. In tunneling through a sandbank it 
 is impossible to succeed unless every foot, nay, almost every 
 inch, in our progress be secured by an arch of masonry, before 
 we attempt the excavation of another. Now language is to 
 the mind precisely what the arch is to the tunnel. The power 
 of thinking and the power of excavating are not dependent 
 
 ately thought as common to many individual things : self-laminous, spark- 
 ling, celestial, very distant, relatively fixed, etc., and form a concept of star. 
 This complex notion is applicable to a host of things, for of many individuals 
 each has all of these marks. The notion is, therefore, general by virtue of 
 the generality of its several constituents. 
 
 1 See Hamilton, Logic, § 21. 
 
 2 See Mill, Logic, bk. iv, ch. 3. A uniformity is a notion of resemblance ; 
 hence general names or terms, the signs of general notions, have been called 
 termini similitudinis. Every common noun, as man, tree, fruit, star, is a 
 
 .sign and expression of a concept. 
 
222 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 on the word in the one case, nor on the mason-work in the 
 other ; but without these subsidiaries, neither process could 
 be carried on beyond its rudimentary commencement." ^ 
 
 § 210. An important subsidiary fact is that every concept 
 comprehends, on the one hand, a number of attributes or 
 marks, and, on the other, extends to a number of objects or 
 things. Thought reduces many marks to unity, comprising 
 them in one product, and many things to unity, including 
 them under that product, the concept.^ The sum of the 
 marks connoted is the intension of the concept ; the sum of 
 the things denoted is its extension. Hence the concept has 
 a kind of two-fold quantity : first, the number of marks con- 
 stituting its connotation, comprehension, intension, qua7ititas 
 complexus, or depth, jBdOo'^ ; secondly, the number of things 
 constituting its denotation, extension, quantitas ambitus, or 
 breadth, TrXaro?. 
 
 It is evident that if the number of marks in a concept be 
 diminished, it will extend to a greater number of things ; 
 and if the marks be increased, it will extend to fewer things.^ 
 When we think marks in, we think things out, and vice 
 versa. Hence the general law. The greater the intension, 
 the smaller the extension; and the smaller the intension, 
 
 1 Hamilton, Logic, § 23. See also Brown, Fhil. of Hum. Mind, Lee. 47. 
 " Without the use of such signs," says Stewart, "our knowledge must have 
 been confined to individuals, and we should have been perfectlj^ incapable 
 both of classification and of general reasoning." But the thought must 
 be before the word. Advanced thuikers exploring the unknown must be 
 independent. 
 
 " Words are but the under agents in their hands ; 
 When they are grasping willi their greatest strength, 
 They do not breathe among them." 
 
 2 Thus my notion man comprehends the marks rational, sentient, organ- 
 ized, existing ; and contains under it Aristotle, Ca;sar, Kant, Napoleon, and 
 all individual men. 
 
 8 Thus the concept bird connotes the marks feathered, winged, biped, 
 etc., and denotes and is predicable of many individual things ; whereas the 
 concept swan has more marks, as, web-footed, etc., but denotes fewer 
 individual things. 
 
THOUGHT. 223 
 
 the greater the extension. Or, more briefly ; the two quan- 
 tities of the concept are in inverse ratio. 
 
 § 211. We are now prepared to observe that generalization 
 is classification. By thinking a mark as common to several 
 individuals, we thereby constitute a class containing them. 
 Indeed, every common noun is the name of a class of things, 
 and concepts are often and properly called class notions. 
 
 We do not, however, stop at a first generalization. On 
 comparing two or more given class notions we reject their 
 differences to form still another more general concept.^ The 
 operation is repeated until we arrive at an absolute limit in 
 the notion of being or thing, which connotes only one mark, 
 existence, and denotes everything. This process is called 
 par excellence^ generalization, but since it is the forming of 
 genera by uniting species, it is also called generification. 
 
 Reversing the process, we restore the differences and pro- 
 ceed towards the individual, which is the limit, connoting an 
 unlimited plurality of marks, and denoting only one thing.^ 
 This process is called division or determination, and since 
 we are herein forming species by subdividing genera, it is 
 also called specification. 
 
 Thus it is that thought forms classes of things and of 
 events. The systems thereby elaborated are wholly subjec- 
 tive, existing only in the mind of the thinker, and are deter- 
 mined chiefly by the purpose he has in view, and the utility 
 of certain relations for certain ends.^ Thought is constantly 
 
 1 Thus by abstracting from the different while retaining the similar marks 
 in the several general notions, bird, beast, fish, reptile, man, and thinking 
 the similar the same, I form the concept animal. This genus has fewer 
 marks than any one of the species, but it contains under it a greater number 
 of individual things. 
 
 2 Taking the concept animal, for instance, we bring in the mark rational, 
 which throws out all animals except man. Then suppose we bring in the 
 mark born in Virginia. This excludes the bulk of mankind, and we have 
 the concept Virginian. Now bring in pater patrm, and we have Washington. 
 
 3 In civil affairs one would never divide mankind iiito horsemen and foot^ 
 men, but from a military point of view this distributiion is imix)rtant. Cejtain 
 
 ((USI7BRSIT71 
 
224 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 and exclusively occupied with the discovery of the relations 
 of things or of events, and with the arrangement of them in 
 classes. Observed uniformities in things give genera, ob- 
 served uniformities in events are formulated as laws. The 
 perfection of a system of classes is the perfection of knowl- 
 edge. 
 
 § 212. Let us now examine the process and product of 
 thought under a different aspect, and with a somewhat varied 
 terminology. It has already been noted that every act of 
 cognition involves the shock of similarity and difference, 
 that this is essentially comparison, and that the issue of com- 
 parison is a judgment (§§ 59, 80). Hence every movement of 
 the cognitive consciousness, from the primitive affirmation 
 that I am, to the most fully elaborated cognition, is a judg- 
 ment. 
 
 Judgments are of two kinds, intuitions and inferences. 
 The intuitive judgment is original, the other is derived. In 
 the intuitive judgment the matter is given already deter- 
 mined. An inference determines its matter. The one is the 
 psychological, the other the logical judgment. The latter 
 only is a thought. 
 
 The striving of thought has two directions. It strives 
 either to attain universal judgments respecting things and 
 events, or, on the contrary, to bring these under such compre- 
 hensive notions as may have been already attained. Hence 
 inferences, or logical judgments, or simply judgments, are of 
 two kinds, inductions and deductions. 
 
 An induction is a generalization from and beyond experi- 
 
 natural relations give order to tlie classes of objects for purposes of natural 
 •science ; but the only strictly necessary principle of distinction between 
 objects is the numerical diversity of individuals, all other divisions being, in 
 some sense, arbitrary and artificial. The naturalist may class man and the 
 ape together as having hands ; the moralist will place them far asunder as 
 rational and irrational, responsible and irresponsible. But no system can 
 possibly make Socrates the same individ\ial as Plato, or regard an act of 
 yesterday as nununically one with an act of t(.)-day. 
 
THOUGHT. 225 
 
 ence, whereby I bring in (in-duco) unobserved facts, and 
 class them with observed facts. Thus I attain universal 
 judgments based upon experience. But this wide generality 
 is precarious ; exceptions may always conceivably occuro 
 This characteristic uncertainty is spoken of as the hazard of 
 induction (§ 121). 
 
 Having attained universals, thought proceeds to deduce 
 from them judgments either equally or less general. Deduc- 
 tions are of two kinds, immediate and mediate or reasoning. 
 The development of their forms belongs to Logic. 
 
 The a priori sciences, as pure mathematics, proceed from 
 intuitive universals or pure principles, and employ deduction 
 only. The a posteriori or empirical or inductive sciences, as 
 physics, chemistry, etc., proceeding from facts of observation 
 and experiment, attain universals by induction, and then 
 employ deduction, inferring from these universals special or 
 particular cases. 
 
 § 213. It will be well to remark here the relation in which 
 judgment and conception stand to each other. A slight con- 
 sideration shows that they are essentially identical ; related 
 as merely different aspects of the same thing. When an 
 object is presented, I proceed to think it distinctly by analy- 
 sis and synthesis. I abstract. its qualities in succession; this 
 is analysis. I affirm of each that it is a mark of the thing ; 
 this is synthesis, and the affirmation is a judgment. If these 
 marks are collected and reduced to unity by an act of con- 
 ception, I therein affirm or judge that they are congruent, 
 and that this unity characterizes the thing. In generalizing, 
 I affirm a mark or a concept to be common to several objects. 
 Hence, each of the three movements in conceiving is a judg- 
 ment. So also in classification, when I am systematizing my 
 concepts. To think marks in is to affirm, to think them out 
 is to deny. 
 
 Every concept, then, is an implicit judgment. It is the 
 product of a foregone judgment or judgments recorded in a 
 
226 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 word or sign, and it is amplified only by judging, by thinking 
 other attributes into it. On the other hand, every judgment 
 is an explicit concept. It is either the result of analyzing a 
 concept into its original components, an analytic judgment, 
 or the act by which a new attribute is for the first time 
 annexed, a synthetic judgment.^ 
 
 § 214. Having examined the two general aspects of the 
 process of thought, conceiving and judging, it is now needful 
 to consider the relation of thought to other powers. 
 
 It is sufficiently obvious that if the objects thought about 
 are not themselves present to sense, the thinking is conditioned 
 on memory. Thought limited to objects actually present has 
 very little range. Excepting this narrow case, memory fur- 
 nishes the materials for the elaboration of thought, and thus 
 becomes, in general, its condition.^ 
 
 The relation of thought to imagination is less obvious. The 
 concept is representative of the objects of intuition from which 
 it was originally derived, and whose place it occupies in the 
 further processes of thought. " In one respect, indeed, con- 
 ception may be regarded as representative in a stricter sense 
 than imagination. Imagination, though representative, is 
 presentative also, and so far has a close affinity to sense. It 
 is presentative of the image, which is itself an intuitive ob- 
 
 1 For the Kantian distinction of judgments, as analytic and synthetic, see 
 Critique of Pure Reaso7i, Int., § 4. 
 
 Also observe that a mark is potentially a concept, and a concept is poten- 
 tially a mark. A concept is expressed by a substantive noun, a mark by an 
 adjective noun ; and the interchange of these grammatical forms is frequent, 
 e.g. man is a mortal, and man is mortal. The distinction consists in the use 
 made of the notion ; if used denotatively, it is a concept ; if used connota- 
 tively, it is a mark. 
 
 2 On the relation of these several activities it is noteworthy that in the 
 exercise of sensuous intuition, i.e. of perception, there is an affirmation of 
 distinct present existence (§ 98) ; in memory, the affirmation of past exist- 
 ence ; in imagination, of potential existence ; in thought, of relative existence ; 
 that is, on the hypothesis of the present, past, or possible existence of two 
 objects, thought affirms or denies the existence of a relation between them. 
 
THOUGHT. 227 
 
 ject as well as representative of the object of sense. But the 
 concept, so far as its objects are concerned, is purely represen- 
 tative. It presents nothing on which the mind can rest as an 
 adequate object of consciousness, nothing which is not in its 
 nature incomplete and relative, nothing, in short, but the fact 
 of thinking. Pure thought, if by that expression is meant the 
 consciousness of general notions and of nothing else, is an 
 operation which perhaps may be possible to higher intelligence, 
 but which never takes place in the human mind." ^ 
 
 Thought being thus purely representative, relies upon an 
 object, presented either by sense or imagination, which em- 
 bodies its conception. Imagination presents an image, and 
 it is this image on which the mind rests as an adequate object 
 of consciousness, and it is by virtue of this image that it is 
 enabled to elaborate and comprehend the concept. Thus 
 thought is conditioned also on imagination.^ The special 
 exercise of imagination in which it acts as a servitor of 
 thought we have ventured to call the deliberative imagina- 
 tion (§ 201). 
 
 § 215. The concept itself cannot be imaged, for it is general, 
 and an image is always individual.^ How then does imagi- 
 
 1 Mansel, Metaphysics, p. 166. 
 
 2 So Aristotle: "Common notions, voy)tiaTa, are not without images, ovk 
 
 dvev (paPTaa-ndTuv.''^ — Ilepi ^vxv^, iii, 7. Cf. id. iii, 30. So also Milton: — 
 
 " In the Boul 
 Are many lesser faculties that serve 
 Reason as chief; among these Fancy next 
 Her ofBce holds; of all external things, 
 Which the five watchful senses represent, 
 She forms imaginations, airy shapes, 
 Which Reason, joining or disjoining, frames 
 All what we affirm, or what deny, and call 
 Our knowledge or opinion." — Paradise Lost, v, 100 sq. 
 
 3 Psychologists now agree that the general notion cannot be imaged, 
 though Locke maintained the contrary. Essay, bk. iv, ch. 7, § 9. Indeed, the 
 supposition involves a contradiction. E.g. I have the notion triangle, a figure 
 of three sides. It is applicable to several species, among others to the equi- 
 lateral and to the scalene. Now should I propose to image triangle in its 
 generality, it must be at once equilateral and scalene. Here emerges the 
 
228 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 nation enable thought to realize its products, how does it 
 serve to this end? It operates in two waj^s ; either by the 
 intuition of a case, or of a symbol. The exercise of thought 
 under the former mode is called intuitive thinking ; under 
 the latter, symbolical thinking.^ 
 
 In intuitive thinking a concrete case or example of some 
 individual member of a class is imaged by the mind. This 
 individual, by embodying all the marks that constitute the 
 concept, is made to stand for or represent all members of the 
 class. Thus when thinking of triangle, I may image a par- 
 ticular triangle, and thereby hold in mind and together all 
 the marks that make up my general notion of triangle. In 
 doing this I disregard the non-essential marks of the triangle 
 imaged here and now, so that they may at any instant be 
 rejected in favor of those of any other. Or instead of that, 
 I may draw a triangle on paper, and then, by means of this 
 object of sense, without the aid of imagination, entertain and 
 elaborate my notion. So any object of sense may be contem- 
 plated with reference to its generic marks, and as representa- 
 tive of its class.^ 
 
 contradiction that its sides must be all equal and all unequal. Hence such 
 an image is impossible. 
 
 The mind can hnage only those things which, in their elements at least, 
 have been actually experienced in presentative intuition. But the universe 
 of things consists of individuals. There is no general thing existing in the 
 external world. Generality is a fiction of thought (§ 207), and has no exist- 
 ence except as thought. Hence it cannot possibly be presented as an oViject 
 of adventitious experience, and so cannot be nnaged. Our experience is 
 exclusively of individuals, and therefore we can image only individuals. 
 
 An individual is " e?is indivisxan in se, et divisuin ah omni alio; . . . id 
 citpts proprietates alteri simul cnnvenire non possnntV — Porphyry. " What- 
 ever occupies a distinct portion of space is an individual object of external 
 intuition ; and vfhatever occupies a distinct moment of time, without exten- 
 sion in space, is an individual object of internal intuition. . . . The general 
 notion as such is emancipated from all special relation to space or timg. The 
 definition of triangle must not imply where it exists ; nor the definition of 
 anger when it takes place." — Mansel, Meta., pp. 37, 39. 
 
 ' Spf §§ ir,2, 153, and 150. 
 
 ■■' When 1 am looking at a rose, and say that it is a flower, 1 view it as 
 
THOUGHT. 229 
 
 Intuitive thinking or conception, then, is that in which an 
 individual case or example, present to sense or imagination, 
 and embodying the attributes of a general notion, is regarded 
 as representing all members of its class. 
 
 § 216. In symbolical thinking, an arbitrary sign or symbol, 
 either perceived or imaged, is used as expressive of the con- 
 cept. Instead of representative examples, we may have rep- 
 resentative signs, either presented to sense or imaged by the 
 mind. Language furnishes a system of such signs. All words 
 and combinations of words that we read or hear are sensible 
 signs representative of thought. Ntmiina sunt notionum tiotce. 
 When thinking of triangle, instead of an example I may 
 image merely the name of the thing, and thereby entertain 
 the thought. 
 
 By means of symbols we are enabled to grasp thoughts 
 beyond the reach of intuition. The notion civilization, for 
 instance, is too complex to be clearly represented by an exam- 
 ple, but we hold it fast by this word which is its sign. Thus 
 verbal signs supersede intuitive examples, and the process of 
 thinking becomes algebraic.^ 
 
 representing the class. If I smell its perfume, and attend to that quality in 
 the sensation that marks the rose odors and distinguishes them from the 
 jessamine odors, then this sense-perception is a representative example of 
 rose odors. So, if I am listening to some one singing a ballad, I may think 
 of it as generically different from operatic or sacred song. There is no essen- 
 tial difference in the mode of thought, whether by percept or by image, by 
 object or by subject-object. There is a difference in degree of facility, some- 
 times in favor of one, sometimes of the other. Geometrical figures drawn 
 on the blackboard help a beginner; so also the famous "object lessons for 
 children." But the very narrow range of thinking by means of objects of 
 sense-perception is obvious. 
 
 ' Investigation by the geometric method is intuitive thinking ; that by the 
 algebraic method is symbolic thinking. By the former, Newton expounded 
 the celestial system in the Principia; by the latter, Laplace elaborated 
 La Mecaniqtie celeste. 
 
 Why is it that the first step in school education, i.e. learning to read and 
 write, is so great a stride ? Why should it divide society by one of its sharpest 
 hnes? The illiterate think mostly by example; so far as they think sym- 
 
230 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 Sj^mbolical thinking or conception, then, is that in which 
 an arbitrary sign or symbol, present to sense or imaged by the 
 mind, and associated with the attributes of a general notion, 
 is regarded as significant of all members of the class.^ 
 
 § 217. Being able to employ signs of thoughts in various 
 and changing relations without calling to mind the meaning 
 originally assigned to each,^ our thoughts gain in celerity and 
 flexibility, but they lose in distinctness, and are in danger of 
 being false.^ Consequently, it is needful at the end of a pro- 
 cess of thought, and even occasionally at intermediate stages, 
 to submit the result to the test of an example, and thus 
 
 ■bolically, it must be chiefly by imagining the sounds of words, — a rather 
 obscure and difficult means. Perhaps the prime advantage conferred by the 
 humble acquisitions reading and writing is that they furnish a system of 
 visual signs available for symbolic thinking. 
 
 1 The distinction between intuitive and symbolic thinking was taken for 
 the first time in modern philosophy by Leibnitz in his Latin tract on ' ' Knowl- 
 edge, Truth, and Ideas," 1684, a translation of which is appended to Bayne's 
 English edition of the Port Eoyal Logic. According to Hamilton, this dis- 
 tinction superseded in Germany the whole of the bitter and even bloody 
 controversy between Nominalism and Conceptualism which agitated France 
 and England during several centuries. — Logic, § 30, pp. 127, 129. The dis- 
 tinction was elaborated by Wolf, a disciple of Leibnitz, in his Psijchologica 
 Empiricn, §§ o26, .329. I find, however, the same distinction taken sharply 
 and clearly by Aristotle in De Soph., i. 
 
 2 "It is not necessary," says Berkeley, " even in the strictest reasonings, 
 that significant names which stand for ideas [notions] should, every time 
 they are used, excite in the understanding the ideas they are made to stand 
 for. In reading and discoursing, names are for the most part used as lettoi's 
 are in algebra, in which, though a particular quantity be marked by each 
 letter, yet, to proceed rightly, it is not requisite that at every step each letter 
 should suggest to our thoughts that particular quantity it was appointt'd to 
 stand for." — Minute rhiJosnpher, Dialogue vii, § 8. Established and familiar 
 propositions are used, like algebraic formulas, without our looking into tlu'ir 
 meaning ; and words are combined into projiositions without our stopping to 
 weigh the significance of each in its new connections. 
 
 8 I may speak of a trilateral figure, and I can easily image one. I may 
 also speak of a bilateral figure, but when T try to image it, I find that it is 
 non-sense. So is it when one says: There is no rule without exceptions ; for 
 this is itself a rule, and if it have exceptions, there are rules without excep- 
 
THOUGHT. 231 
 
 ascertain the possible coexistence of the attributes in a corre- 
 sponding object of intuition. The existence of a class is 
 possible only if the existence of the individual members is 
 possible ; hence symbolical cognition supposes intuitive cog- 
 nition, actual or possible, as its condition, and derives validity 
 from it. This testing process is a function of the deliberative 
 imagination.^ 
 
 § 218. The special function of thought is search for truth. 
 Truth is the abstract name of a quality, a contingent quality, 
 belonging to judgment. A judgment, or its expression, a 
 proposition, may or may not be true. It is true when the 
 affirmation or denial which it makes is in accord with the fact. 
 The usual definition is : Truth is the agreement of a cognition 
 with its object. That is : Truth is the correspondence between 
 
 tions. Said Voltaire: " Le superflu, c'est le vrai nScessaire." Pope has a 
 satirical " Song by a Person of Quality," beginning: — 
 
 " Gloomy Pluto, king of terrors, 
 Armed in adamantine chains, 
 Lead me to the crystal mirrors, 
 Watering soft Elysian plains." 
 
 Campbell has a whole chapter on this point, Fhil. of Bhetoric, bk. ii, ch. 7. 
 See Mill's Political Economy, bk. iii, ch. 1, § 4 ; which work, by the way, 
 he introduces with a chapter of " Preliminary Remarks," in which, we may 
 understand, he takes a prospective review of the subject. See also Stewart's 
 Elements, ch. iv, § 4 ; Hume's Treatise of Human Nature, pt. i, § 7 ; and 
 Locke's Essay, bk. ii, ch. 22, § 7 et al. 
 
 1 See Mansel, Meta., p. 169 sq. ; and Proleg. Logica, pp. 36 and 52. He 
 says: "Like a bank-note, a symbol is representative of value without having 
 an intrinsic value of its own ; and, like the bank-note, its real worth depends 
 on the possibility of its being at any time exchanged for coin. But as the 
 note is treated in practice as if it were real money, so commonly we treat 
 symbolical knowledge as if it were itself the complete consciousness to which, 
 if valid, it may at any time be reduced." The test of symbolic thought is 
 thus the image or intuition of an example. We must individualize our con- 
 cepts, look them in the face, envisage them ; Ger. anschauen. This test is, 
 however, merely negative ; it does not determine the truth of the thought, 
 l3ut merely assures us of self-consistency. Still it is evident that intuitive 
 thought is a necessary, though only a negative, test of symbolic thought. 
 
232 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 the representation we make of an object, in thought, and the 
 qualities presented by that object in intuition.^ 
 
 The old question : What is truth ? seems to call for some- 
 thing more than a definition of the word.^ It seeks a univer- 
 sal and secure criterion of truth. Since thought is the highest 
 cognitive activity, the others being subservient, there is no 
 superior authority to which it should submit. Therefore it 
 must itself, by aid, if need be, of the subordinate powers, fur- 
 nish the criterion, the test of the truth of its own products, 
 if any such criterion there be. 
 
 It has just been stated that the test of symbolical thinking 
 is the intuition of an example. But this is merely a negative 
 criterion of the possible existence of an object of sense ; that 
 is, whatever cannot stand this test cannot be. Quite simi- 
 larly Logic presents us with negative criteria of truth in the 
 universal and necessary laws of thought. Whatever violates 
 these laws is false, because thereby thought contradicts itself. 
 But a thought may be perfectly accurate as to logical form, 
 and yet not be in agreement with its object. Consequently 
 
 1 Mansel, Meta., p. 145. riato's definition is: Truth is conformity with 
 tlie ideas. Aristotle's : Truth is the agreement of knowledge with reality, 
 T(? yap elfdi TO. TTpdy/jLa r) /nrj dX-qdris 6 X670S •^ feuSrjs Xiyerai. — Categ., ch. 12. 
 This dictum he particularizes, in Afeta., iv, 7, thus: "Affirming non-existence 
 of the existent, or existence of the non-existent, is error ; but affirming exist- 
 ence of the existent, or non-existence of the non-existent, is truth." His 
 doctrine, more fully stated by Ueberweg, is: "Truth in a logical judgment 
 is the correspondence of the combination of mental representations with a 
 combination of things, or, in case of the negative judgment, the correspond- 
 ence of a separation of representations in the mind with a separation of 
 things. Falsity [error] in judgments is the variation of the ideal combination 
 or separation from the real relation of the things to which the judgments 
 relate." — Hist. P/til., § 47. The scholastic definition is tantamount: " Veri- 
 tas est adequatio intellectus et rei, secundum quod intcllectus dicit esse, quod 
 est, vel non es.se, quod non est." — Aqcinas, Con. Gen., ill), i, oh. 59. On 
 truth and error, see Hamilton, Logic, §§ 90, 91. 
 
 - The Greeks used the question to push pretenders into a corner, forcing 
 them either to commit stupid sophisms, or to confess ignorance. The Romans, 
 in their profound skepticism, asked it in scorn, as a first yet unanswerable 
 question. See John 18: :IS. 
 
THOUGHT. 23S 
 
 the merely logical criterion of truth, namely, the accordance 
 of the cognition with the universal laws of thought, is noth- 
 ing more than a conditio sine qua non^ or negative criterion 
 of truth. Further than this Logic cannot go, and of the 
 error which depends, not upon the form, but on the matter 
 or content of the cognition, it has no test to offer. 
 
 " Of the truth of our cognitions in respect of their matter, 
 no universal [positive] test can be demanded, because such a 
 demand is self -contradictory. For since truth is the agree- 
 ment of a cognition with its object, this object must be ipso 
 facto distinguished from all others. Now a universal crite- 
 rion of truth would be that which is valid for all cognitions, 
 without distinction of their objects. But it is evident that 
 since, in case of such criterion, we make abstraction of all 
 content of a cognition, and since truth relates precisely to 
 this content, it is absurd to ask for a universal and positive 
 mark of the truth of the content." ^ 
 
 How, then, since we can have no universal and positive 
 .criterion of truth, are we to know that we know ? For, " to 
 know that we know what we know, and that we do not 
 know what we do not know, that is true knowledge." Giv- 
 ing up the universal criterion, we observe that all knowledge 
 originates in intuition ; that pure intuitions or principles are 
 necessary truths, we necessarily know them to be necessarily 
 true ; that empirical intuitions are necessary also in the sense 
 that we are constrained to know in them the existence of 
 their objects. So much is certain, out of reach of all ques- 
 tion. Now from these data exclusively we make logical 
 inferences. If the logic be good, the conclusion is equally 
 
 1 Kant, C. P. R., p. 51. In this connection he remarks : "To know what 
 question we may reasonably propose is in itself a strong evidence of sagacity 
 and intelligence. For if the question be in itself absurd and insusceptible of 
 a rational answer, it is attended with the danger — not to mention the shame 
 of him who proposes it — of seducing the unguarded hearer into making 
 absurd answers, and we are then presented with the ridiculous spectacle, 
 described by the ancients, of one milking a he-goat while another holds a 
 sieve." 
 
234 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 ■certain ; as, for example, in pure mathematics. But if the 
 .axioms be not strictly pure, or if the empirical facts be not 
 perfectly ascertained and justly appreciated, or if our infer- 
 ences be not strictly logical, we should doubt. To know 
 that we know, we must review and perfect these. Then we 
 have truth. If from the nature of the matter, purification 
 be impracticable, we should carefully entertain as to the 
 conclusion the full measure of doubt that belongs to the 
 premises, together with all that may have been gathered in 
 the logical process. Then we have only greater or less 
 probability. This, perhaps, is the meaning of Plato, when 
 he speaks of experience, wisdom, and reason as affording 
 conjointly a Kpinjpiov of truth.^ 
 
 § 219. The opposite of truth is error, a false judgment, the 
 disagreement of a cognition with its object.^ All primitive 
 or psychological judgments are true ; it is impossible to err 
 in a fact of consciousness (§ 69). Our senses never deceive 
 us (§ 160). Pure intuitions are certain and necessary (§§ 118, 
 119). Error, then, has no place in the presentative faculties. 
 
 1 Politica, 582 a, Step. Many criteria have been proposed. Descartes 
 affirmed: "All that is very clearly known and perceived is true." — Mccl, iii. 
 But he admits elsewhere the vagueness of this criterion. Wolf gives : " De- 
 terminabilitas prsedicati per notionum subjecti." But this applies only to 
 explicative propositions. Hamilton says: "The criterion of truth is the 
 necessity determined by the laws which govern our faculties of knowledge ; 
 and the consciousness of this necessity is certainty." — Logic, § 90. But 
 this, being a reference to the laws of pure logic, is merely negative, and so 
 too narrow. Thompson says: "Evidence is the sole means of establishing, 
 and therefore the sole standard for testing, the truth of any proposition." 
 This also is too narrow, since it relates only, on the other hand, to empirical 
 truth. Besides, it involves, as he says, "the whole science and rules of 
 evidence." — OrUliim of the Lairs of Thoyf/ht, § 114. 
 
 ^ To escape confusion, let us distinguish veracity and falsehood from truth 
 and error. Veracity or truthfulness is characterized by a belief in the agree- 
 ment of the judgment with the proposition or expression. Falsehood or a 
 lie is a conscious ilisagTeement between the judgment and its expression. 
 Both are subjective ; whereas truth and error, as above described, are 
 objective. 
 
THOUGHT. 235 
 
 Imagination, taken strictly, affirms only the congruity or 
 incongruity of images, and this, being a primitive judgment, 
 does not err. The primary judgment of memory is a fact of 
 consciousness, a primitive judgment, and therefore cannot 
 err ; its secondary judgment is an inference of thought from 
 given impressions, and so is liable to err (§§ 182, 183}. Only 
 logical judgment may be false, may involve error ; it is 
 thought alone that errs. 
 
 Why should thought err? In symbolic thinking we have 
 a test to discover incongruity (§ 217). The principles of 
 Logic furnish a criterion that saves us from self-contradic- 
 tion (§ 218). By these negative tests we may escape absurd- 
 ity, if not error ; we may at least be consistent, which is a 
 great gain. But, moreover, by a thorough investigation of the 
 principles on which a judgment rests, by pursuing them to 
 their original intuitive sources, we may determine positively 
 its truth or falsity, and in such case need not err. If this 
 thorough investigation of principles and process be beyond 
 our powers, still, in many cases, we may be able to go far 
 enough to estimate fairly the degree of probabilit}^ belonging 
 to the matter. If not, then we should suspend judgment, 
 and rest in .contented ignorance, which is wiser than pre- 
 sumptuous knowledge. 
 
 But to be content not to know is commonly too hard for 
 us. Impelled by instinct towards knowledge, we form, often 
 very hasty and crude, but almost always very decided opin- 
 ions about all sorts of matters. And so we blunder, and 
 stumble, and fall. Carelessness, • lack of love for truth, 
 indifference, lack of interest, and consequent thoughtlessness, 
 leave open the by-paths, and we wander. But none of these, 
 nor a neglect of the means in our power, can be called a 
 cause of error, for they are all negative, and there is no such 
 thing as a negative cause. The absence of a thing cannot 
 properly be accounted a cause. All causes are present and 
 positive. 
 
 No doubt our opinions are largely determined by our feel- 
 
236 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 ings and desires. Things appear to be true or false according 
 as they please or displease, according to desire or aversion ; 
 for the will arrests attention npon the agreeable, and refuses 
 to consider the disagreeable. ^ But these several activities 
 are all conditioned on and subsequent to cognitive exercise, 
 and so, however influential, are not the primary causes of 
 "error. 
 
 § 220. The question then recurs : Why should we err, and 
 that so frequently, so fatally ? We now bring the charge 
 against imagination, that it is the chiefest, perhaps the sole 
 direct source and cause of error.^ In the right adjustment 
 and exercise of our faculties imagination is the servant, the 
 handmaid of thought. But too often, proud in her queenly 
 beauty, and haughty in her fascinating power, she becomes, 
 by unnatural inversion, the mistress of thought, a mistress 
 lawless and tyrannical. All the illusions of sense are vain 
 images, and its delusions are false inferences induced by 
 imagination (§160). Again, we often believe that we remem- 
 ber circumstances which never in fact coexisted, and have 
 mistaken an act of imagination for an act of memory (§ 183). 
 In disguise it has deceived and misled us, and caused us to 
 
 1 " Ansi Tesprit marchant d'uue piece avec la voluntg, s'arr&te a regarder 
 la face qu'elle aime, et en jugeant par ce qu'il y voit, il regie insensiblement 
 sa croyance suivant rincliuation de la voluntij." — Pascal, Pensees, pt. i, 
 art. (3, § 13. 
 
 2 The indictment is not new. Says Pascal: " Cette superbe puissance, 
 ennemie de la raison, qui se plait a la controler et a la dominer pour montrer 
 combien elle pcut en toutes choses, a 6tabli dans riionime une seconde nature. 
 . . . Elle ue pent rendre sages les fous, niais elle les rend contents, a Penvi 
 de la raison. . . . Qui dispense la reputation, qm donne le respect et la 
 veneration aux personnes, aux ouvrages, aux grades, sinon I'imagination ? 
 Combien toutes les richesses de la nature sont elles insuffisantes sans son 
 consentement ? L' imagination dispose de tout ; elle fait la beautfi, la justice, 
 et le bonheur, qui est le tout du monde. . . . Cette maitresse d'erreur est 
 d'autant i)lus fourbe (ju'elle ne Test i^as toujours ; car elle serait re^le infailli- 
 ble de la v6rite, si elle I'fitait infaillible du mensonge. Mais, Ctant le plus 
 fausse, elle ne donne acunne marque de sa qualitfi, marquant de mume 
 caractfere le vrai et le faux." — H/id., § 3. 
 
THOUGHT. 237 
 
 » 
 
 judge falsely. Again, when testing symbolic thought, the 
 deliberative imagination often presents an image so clear and 
 distinct, so congruous and consistent, as to impose upon us, 
 and in our unguarded weakness we accept this impression 
 as an evidence of truth. How often, too, does a brilliant 
 illustration carry captive our convictions in spite of sound 
 argument. A frequent, perhaps the most frequent, form of 
 error is an over-hasty generalization, a precipitate induction. ^ 
 No induction is strictly certain, for its basis is empirical. 
 The numerous modifications which each of the physical 
 sciences has undergone furnish historic evidence of the fact. 
 But we often overlook this, and accept a mere induction, 
 perhaps a very weak and even a groundless induction, with 
 the confidence of intuitive truth. This can occur only 
 under the influence of imagination whose vivid representa- 
 tion disperses the shadow of doubt.^ 
 
 In all men there is a natural, a necessary, a devotional 
 love of truth. They fail often to attain it because "it 
 hideth, and the labor of discovery is great, and the recom- 
 pense scanty ; while, at the same time, we are unceasingly 
 solicited, pressed, agitated by the imagination and the pas- 
 sions, whose inspiration and impulse it is always agreeable 
 to obey. Truth is a pure grace, but the understanding of 
 truth is a grace of such character that it must be merited by 
 
 1 The Psalmist corrects himself : "I said in my haste, all men are liars." 
 
 — Ps. 116: 11. He does well ; for the saying included himself, and therefore 
 should not be credited. 
 
 2 Bacon was the first philosopher who attempted a systematic and exhnust- 
 ive enumeration of the kinds of human error, and he ascribes tlieni all to 
 imagination. He made a quaint classification in four genera, under the sig- 
 nificant name of Idols (idola, eldos, an image), in the sense of illusions, 
 ■described as if presented in a magic mirror. He says : " I do find, therefore, 
 in this enchanted glass four idols, or false appearances, of several distinct 
 sorts." The four are, Idola tribus, Idola specus, Idola fori, and Idola theatri. 
 
 — Nov. Organ., lib. i, sum. of pt. ii, aph. 38 sq. See also Hamilton, Logic, 
 Lee. 28 ; and Hallam, Lit. of Mod. Europe, pt. iii, ch. 3, §§ 58, 59. 
 
238 MEDIATE KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 labor.^ But men love not labor, and so imagination usurps^ 
 the throne of thought. Dazzling and complaisant in her 
 ready power, she wins the homage due to the truth she 
 feigns ; while truth, far removed in her severe simplicity, i& 
 prized chiefly through her brilliant substitute. " Truth may 
 perhaps come to the price of a pearl, that sheweth best by 
 day, but it will not rise to the price of a diamond that 
 sheweth best by varied lights. But howsoever these things 
 are thus in men's depraved judgments and affections, yet 
 truth, which only doth judge itself, teacheth that the inquiry 
 of truth, which is the love-making or wooing of it, the knowl- 
 edge of truth, which is the presence of it, and the belief of 
 truth, which is the enjoying of it, is the sovereign good of 
 human nature." 
 
 1 Malebranche, Traite de Morale, pt. i, ch. 5, § 5. " It is a mere sophisma 
 pigrum, and (as Bacon hath said) the arrogance of pusillanimity, which lifts 
 up the idol of a mortal's fancy, and commands us to fall down and worship 
 it as a work of divine wisdom, an ancile or palladium fallen from heaven." 
 — Coleridge, Biog. Lit., ch. 8. For the final quotation see Bacon, Essay, i. 
 On Truth. 
 
PART FOURTH. 
 
 FEELING. 
 
 CHAPTER I. 
 
 CHARACTERISTICS. 
 
 § 221. We are now to consider the second class of the 
 generic powers, the feelings. ^ These are modes of self-con- 
 sciousness, or subjective consciousness, in logical opposition 
 to cognitions, wliich are modes of objective consciousness 
 (§§ 71, 73). Feeling and cognition are psychological correla- 
 tives, existing only in coexistence. The state of conscious- 
 ness that is objectively a cognition is subjectively a feeling. 
 Every cognition implies a feeling, and every feeling implies 
 a cognition. They are logically distinguished as merely 
 different aspects of the same actually indissoluble mental 
 mode, as really inseparable as the convex and concave sides 
 
 1 The word feeling was originally the name of the tactile sensation only, 
 but has been extended in common usage to all states of consciousness marked 
 by pleasure or pain. The cognate term Gefuhl in German has had a like 
 expansion of meaning. The same may be said of the Greek ata-e-rja-is ; and 
 also of the Latin sensus, sensatio, with their derivatives in the modern 
 Romanic languages. 
 
 Brown extended the meaning to an identity with consciousness. — PML 
 of Hum. Mimh Lee. 11. Also J. S. Mill. See him quoted in § 55, note. So 
 also Bain and Spencer, and associationists generally. Says Clifford: "It 
 means thought or emotion or volition or sensation of any kind ; anything that 
 goes on in the mind may be called a feeling." — Seeing find TlnnJdng, p. 88. 
 This violates usage, and confuses modes that are clearly distinguishable. 
 See § 97 and its note. 
 
 239 
 
240 FEELIl^G. 
 
 of a circular arc. Looked at on the subjective side, that is, 
 rehxtively to the subject, the mode is a feeling; looked at 
 on the objective side, that is, relatively to the object, it is a 
 cognition, the obverse and reverse of the same state. As 
 experienced they are the combined, simultaneous, or rather 
 the single consciousness of the ego and non-ego in their 
 essential antithesis. 
 
 That a cognition is objective means that consciousness is 
 therein relative to something distinct from the conscious 
 subject. A feeling is subjective in that consciousness is 
 therein limited to the pleasure or pain experienced by the 
 conscious subject. Specifically, perception is a kind of 
 cognition, and sensation a kind of feeling. Perception is 
 the consciousness by sense of the qualities of an object 
 known as distinct from self. Sensation is the consciousness 
 of the subjective feeling, pleasant or unpleasant, which 
 accompanies that act of knowledge. In the complete state, 
 which we call a sense-perception, perception is the objec- 
 tive element, sensation the subjective element (§ 97). This 
 contrast or opposition of perception and sensation is 'an 
 obtrusive, but still only a special example of the law that 
 universally divides the generic phenomena of knowledge 
 and feeling. They always correlatively coexist.^ 
 
 It is sometimes said that the external object causes the 
 sensation alone, which then causes or occasions the percep- 
 tion, thus making sensation antecedent to perception. On 
 the other hand, in case of intellectual states, it is said that 
 tlie cognition is the cause or occasion of the concomitant 
 feeling. 15 ut in fact neither is the chronological, or the 
 psychological antecedent of the other. There is, for exam- 
 ple, no more ground for holding that sensation precedes 
 perception, than the reverse. Indeed, feeling and cognition 
 
 1 See Hamilton, Meta., p. 335. Matthew Arnold revived a phrase originally- 
 used by Swift in his "Battle of the Books," and made it stand as a mark 
 of culture — "sweetness and light," a union of kindly fooling and briglit 
 intolloct. 
 
CHARACTERISTICS. 241 
 
 in general are equally original and complementary, and can 
 be distinguished only logically. 
 
 § 222. But though always correlatively coexistent, cogni- 
 tion and feeling are not directly proportional. On the con- 
 trary, feeling, when it rises above a certain degree of 
 intensity, obscures cognition, because of the concentration 
 of consciousness in the subjective affection; and, on the 
 other hand, an acute, intense cognition draws consciousness 
 away from the feeling, which thereby sinks to a lower 
 intensity and becomes faint. The rise of one is at the 
 expense of the other. 
 
 Moreover, in some special sense-perceptions, as in sight, 
 the perceptive power is normally very acute, while the sen- 
 sation is so faint as to be hardly discernible; in others, as 
 in smell, the perception is quite obscure, while the sensation 
 is very decided. Hence, the stronger the sensation, the 
 weaker the perception, and vice versa. But the law is gen- 
 eral, thus : Cognition and feeling exist only as they coexist, 
 and are in inverse ratio. ^ 
 
 § 223. While thus observing the relation of cognition 
 and feeling, it will be well to recall that change has already 
 been noted as a condition of consciousness in general (§ 57). 
 More specifically we now remark that change is necessary to 
 continuity of feeling. We soon become unconscious of 
 unremitted impressions. The degree of feeling is propor- 
 tional to the change, and abruptness of transition enhances 
 the effect. 2 For example: When the temperature of the 
 body is uniform at about 98° F., we feel neither warm nor 
 cold ; a variation above or below this grade excites the sense 
 of temperature. It is only after want that we feel the 
 
 1 Says Kant: " Je starker die Sinne, bei eben demselben Grade des auf 
 sie geschelienen iMiiflusses, sich afficirt fiihlen, desto weniger leliren 
 sie. Uingekehrt, wenn sie viel lehreii sollen, miissen sie mas sig afficiren." 
 — Anthropologie, § 20. 
 
 - See Eain, Emotions and Will, p. 78. 
 
242 FEELING. 
 
 blessing of plenty; only after sickness do we enjoy health; 
 only after war do we really feel the bliss of peace. The 
 feelings that attend freedom and restraint, power and 
 impotence depend largely on the transition from one to the 
 other. The effect of novelty, of news of all sorts, is stim- 
 ulating; that bad, or even good news, should be broken 
 gradually is well known. ^ 
 
 There is naturally a tendency to accommodate one's self 
 to any continuous condition, which is called the subordinate 
 
 1 "Sense, properly so called," says Hobbes, "must necessarily have in 
 it a perpetual variety of phantasms, that they may be discerned from one 
 another ; it being almost all one for a man to be always sensible of one and 
 the same thing, and not to be sensible at all of anything." So a variety of 
 viands at table is requisite to the enjoyment of taste ; imiformity disgusts. 
 A person having fetid breath has no sense of it, and yet is sensitive to fugi- 
 tive and delicate odors. In a smooth sailing ship we lose the sense of 
 motion, but not in a stage-coach. The contact of the still air with the skin 
 excites no tactile sensation, but a fitful breeze fanning the cheek keeps tac- 
 tile consciousness awake. The enormous pressure of the atmosphere on 
 our bodies is unfelt, unless a marked variation is caused, as by descending 
 in a diving-bell, or ascending in a balloon. We suffer much from our sudden 
 and extreme changes of weather ; whereas neither the Laps suffer from cold, 
 nor the Boers from heat. The effect of unvarying fortune is exemplified in 
 the insensibility of the rich, and the stolidity of the poor. Those who have 
 experienced opposite circumstances are they who feel. 
 
 Monotony produces tedium, emmi, and some variety is needful for a 
 healthy play of our energies. He who muses much, needs to be amused. 
 But, as Prince Hal says : — 
 
 " If all the year were playing holidays. 
 To sport would be as tedious as to work ; 
 But when they seldom come, they wished for come, 
 And nothing pleaseth but rare accidents." 
 
 — King Henry IV, pt. 1, A. 1, sc. 2. 
 
 " The feeling of tedium or e>ui?n"," says Hamilton, " is like that of being 
 unable to die, and not being allowed to live ; and sometimes becomes so 
 oppressive that it leads to madness and suicide. It is less felt by the uncul- 
 tivated than by the educated. Our easy occupations we call pastimes. All 
 occupation is either labor or play. In both there must be ever a change of 
 object, or both will soon grow tiresome. They must alternate, or we shall 
 never know true enjoyment in life." — .1/^^r, p. 017. A due proportion 
 between uniformity and variety is somelinics given as a definition of objec- 
 tive beauty. More generally, a mean seems to be most pleasing. 
 
CHARACTERISTICS. 243 
 
 law of accommodation. No feeling can long persist in its 
 original intensity. The second day of a holiday is attended 
 with less flush than the first. The millionnaire's accumula- 
 tions strike him Avith feebler and feebler impulses. The 
 delights of knowledge, and even of virtue, are subject to 
 decline. When the lower level of either pleasure or pain 
 has been reached, we become, as it were, accommodated to 
 the situation, and the feeling thenceforth maintains an even 
 tenor. ^ 
 
 The principle of relativity has already been resolved into 
 the shock of difference, with its correlative shock of simi- 
 larity (§ 59). Now be it observed that a shock is not at all 
 a cognition, but strictly a feeling. Hence it appears that 
 the primary movement of consciousness lies rather in feeling 
 than in cognition, the shock being the logical antecedent or 
 condition of the intellectual discrimination. Unless we 
 feel, we cannot know. In the shock determined by the 
 difference between two objects or ideas, we feel; in the 
 discrimination we make between them, we know. The con- 
 sciousness of the shock is feeling; the consciousness of the 
 difference is cognition. ^ 
 
 § 224. Novelty has already been mentioned. It is not 
 itself a feeling, but merely expresses the superior force of 
 all stimulants of feeling on being first applied. It is a fact 
 which contributes to raise the intensity of our energies, and 
 consequently to determine a corresponding degree of pleasure 
 or pain. It is realized chiefly in youth when all feelings 
 are fresh. New scenes, new modes of life, constitute the 
 attractions of travel. Inventions, discoveries, artistic effects, 
 especially in the pages of story, have the charm of novelty, 
 and in fashion it is supreme. Novelty in pain has the same 
 
 1 It is said that at the overthrow of the Bastile the prisoners manifested 
 no joy at tlieir release. Long and unintermitted confinement had accom- 
 plished its perfect work of accommodation to bondage. 
 
 2 "We note the common phrases : a shocking impropriety, a startling event, 
 a striking remark, a surprising likeness. 
 
244 FEELING. 
 
 enhancing effect. The first encounter with a cause of pain 
 involves the worst experience. 
 
 As variety or change is opposed to monotony inducing 
 tedium, so novelty is opposed to familiarity. Novelty is 
 the absence of familiarity, and so is merely negative and not 
 itself a feeling. But familiarity is positive, a feeling quite 
 general and of great moment. It is the feeling correlative 
 to memory, and so to all powers conditioned on memory. 
 In a very important sense it seems to be the basis of all the 
 convictions of memory. It attends repetition, and so is 
 distinguishable from the shock of similarity that attends 
 simultaneous impressions, but must be considered as merely 
 another form of this ultimate experience (§§ 182-3). 
 
 The strength of the feeling of familiarity is proportioned 
 either to the vivacity of a single impression, or to the fre- 
 quency of the subsequent repetitions, the word being more 
 commonly applied to the latter case. It will also be largely 
 determined by the degree of attention given to the ante- 
 cedent impression. All memory, but especially its primary 
 judgment, seems to be based upon and guaranteed b}^ this 
 peculiar and unmistakable feeling of familiarity. AVhen I 
 meet a stranger a second time, when I write my name for 
 the thousandth time, because of the familiarity, I feel sure 
 that these have been known before. Mediate perceptions 
 are not usually thought of as involving memory. When, 
 for example, I judge that two sounds come from different 
 directions (§ 166), is there any appreciable reference to past 
 experience? Only perhaps in the unmistakable feeling of 
 familiarity with the direction of sounds, which implies 
 previous experience. In all cases this feeling is the ground 
 of our confidence in the judgment. 
 
 § 225. The distinction between feeling and desire is to 
 be more fully stated hereafter. It is admissible here to refer 
 to § 74, Avith the remark that the distinction is usually 
 neglected. It seems, however, of great importance, and 
 
CHARACTERISTICS. 245 
 
 quite clear. In desire there is essentially a want, a longing, 
 an impulse towards some object of cognition. In feeling 
 there is no want, no longing, no impulse whatever. "It is 
 altogether different to feel hunger or thirst and to desire its 
 appeasement; and again different is it to desire its appease- 
 ment, and to enjoy the feeling afforded in the act. Feel- 
 ing belongs exclusively to the present, desire only to the 
 future; for it is a longing either to maintain the present 
 state, or to exchange it for another. "^ Thus desire is not 
 feeling, but an activity which feeling sets in motion. We 
 are now undertaking a consideration of the feelings only, 
 excluding the desires. 
 
 § 226. There are several marks or qualities which are 
 characteristic of feeling in general, that is, found in feelings 
 of all classes and in feelings only, and so distinguish them 
 from all other mental activities. One primary and most 
 important is consciousness of self. 
 
 That the consciousness of self, of my own existence, 
 originates and is constant in feeling is an easy deduction. 
 In every cognition there is essentially an opposition between 
 a subject knowing and an object known. The subject, then, 
 is not cognized, else it would be both subject and object at 
 once, and these being contraries cannot coexist. Hence the 
 consciousness of the subject, its self-consciousness, not being 
 found on the cognitive side of the mental state, must be 
 grounded in the correlative feeling. Given a cognition of 
 an object, then in the correlative feeling is given self. Thus 
 the consciousness that I am is essential in the original fact 
 that I feel. 2 
 
 Hence it is that I distinguish myself from the rest of the 
 world so absolutely that this distinction has an entirely 
 different value from the distinction of another thing from a 
 
 1 Hamilton, 3Ieta., p. 572. 
 
 2 For the distinction between self-perception and self-consciousness, see 
 § 109. 
 
246 FEELING. 
 
 third. Each of my states, all that I suffer or do, is marked 
 off immediately by a feeling, which is lacking when I con- 
 sider the doing or suffering of another. In feeling, then, is 
 to be found the motive of the peculiar distinction by which 
 each person sets himself over against the universe, and the 
 consciousness of his own existence as contradistinguished 
 from every other existence.^ 
 
 That the consciousness of the ego or I myself, of my OAvn 
 being, lies primarily and indeed exclusively in feeling, and 
 moreover is an essential element in each and every feeling, 
 is confirmed by the fact that the intensity of the conscious- 
 ness of self varies with the intensity of feeling. When 
 cognitive exercise is intensified, the correlative feeling is, 
 according to the law of inverse ratio, enfeebled, and such 
 states are attended by a comparative forgetfulness of self; 
 but where there is great pain or passion, cognition is enfee- 
 bled, and the consciousness of self predominates. Hence, 
 not in cognition, but in feeling is self given. ^ 
 
 The primary consciousness of a feeling and an after cogni- 
 tion of it should be discriminated. The former is experi- 
 enced, and involves the consciousness that I am, when 
 indeed I do not at all think about it. The most ignorant 
 person, the new-born babe, must be fully conscious of self- 
 
 1 Lotze emphasizes this, and adds: "Diese beiden Leistungen also, sein 
 eigenes Wesen zu kennen, und sich als ein Selbst zu fiihlen, sind mit einan- 
 der nicht nothwendig verkniipft. Als das erste haben wir eben dieses 
 unmittelbare Selbst g e f ii h 1 to betrachten, dessen Vorhandeiisein ebensowohl 
 wie seine Lebhaftigkeit ganz unabhiingig sind von deni Grade der Selbst- 
 e r k e n n t n i s s, die wir gewohnlicli unter dem Namen des Selbst b e w u s s t- 
 seins denken. Vielmehr ist diese letstere nur die im weiteren Verlanf 
 unserer geistigen Entwicklung zu Wegc komniende denkende Interpretation 
 jener urspriinglichen nur in der Form des Gefiihls niogliclien innereu Erfah- 
 rung." — GrumlzYuje der Ps>/choIofjie, Dictate, § 52. 
 
 2 This discovery of the consciousness of self in feeling rather than in 
 cognition would justify a correction of the famous " Cogito, ergo s?/?»" of 
 Descartes. It would read more accurately : I feel, therefore I am. But the 
 illation cannot be allowed ; as an enthymeme it is false to the fact, which 
 fact is more truly expressed in the form : I am, in that I feel. 
 
CHAR A CTERIS TICS. 247 
 
 existence in every sensation. ^ The feeling may be eventu- 
 ally objectified even while it still exists, and analyzed by 
 thought, and thus I come to a knowledge that I am, which 
 is quite different from the simple and original consciousness 
 of it, the mere feeling it. All feel it constantly; some, 
 perhaps many, never think it. 
 
 § 227. Strict certainty, the correlative of immediate cogni- 
 tion, is the feeling attending a consciousness of necessity; 
 that is, in so far as there is necessity on the objective or 
 cognitive side, its psychological correlative, a feeling of 
 certainty, exists on the subjective side. Since all intuitions 
 a.re attended by this feeling, and since they are component 
 elements in every cognition, it follows that the feeling of 
 certainty relative to them intermingles with every state of 
 consciousness. It also attends the results of rigid demon- 
 stration. In character it is strict, absolute, admitting of no 
 degrees and incompatible with any measure of doubt (§ 69).^ 
 
 Belief, the subjective correlative of mediate cognition, is 
 the feeling attending all forms of representative knowledge. 
 Since in every cognitive activity there is always an exercise 
 of the representative faculties, it follows that the feeling of 
 belief relative thereto is also intermingled with every state 
 of consciousness. It has many degrees of intensity, and is 
 compatible with doubt. In its highest form it approximates 
 certainty, but never attains it; like a conic curve constantly 
 approaching yet never reaching its straight asymptote. As 
 inference never becomes intuition, so belief never becomes 
 strict certainty. As there is good reason for distinguishing 
 mediate from immediate knowledge, so it is proper to dis- 
 
 ' Even the brute must be conscious of self-existence, but surely cannot 
 have a notion of it. 
 
 2 It is this feeling vs^hich is referred to by Aristotle when he says that 
 knowledge, in the last analysis, reposes on a blind and necessary belief. So 
 also Hamilton: "A fact of consciousness is one whose existence is given 
 and guaranteed by an original and necessary belief." — Meta., p. 188. 
 
248 FEELING. 
 
 tinguish belief from certainty; though indeed the latter 
 word is often inaccurately used for a liigh degree of belief. 
 
 The logical or formal opposite of belief is disbelief, but as 
 a mental fact they are one, disbelief being belief of the 
 contrary. The psj^chological and real opposite of belief is 
 the feeling of doubt. These two always coexist, but in 
 inverse ratio. With the highest belief, falling just short of 
 certainty, there is some remainder of doubt, of uncertainty. 
 Descending the scale, while belief diminishes, doubt in- 
 creases, but does not reach its maximum in ignorance, but 
 along with a minimum of belief. Doubt cannot exist where 
 there is no trace of belief. Ignorance, a pure negation of 
 both knowledge and feeling in respect of any matter, lies 
 beyond. Certainty and ignorance, then, are not the termini 
 of this psychological scale, but are just beyond its opposite 
 ends. As ignorance, a negation of belief, is never accounted 
 a degree of doubt, so certainty, the negation of doubt, should 
 never be reckoned a degree of belief. As doubt never be- 
 comes blank ignorance, so belief never becomes strict cer- 
 tainty. ^ 
 
 1 In psychological treatises generally the doctrine of certainty, belief, and 
 doubt is either neglected entirely or slighted, or else confused with tliat of 
 knowledge. The confusion arises from the intimate relation of belief and 
 knowledge. Truly they are inseparable, yet cannot be identified. The 
 words to know and to believe are often used interchangeably, either as 
 implying the other, to know being the stronger expression ; but accurate 
 use distinguishes them, e.g. Isa. 43 : 10 ; 1 Tim. 4 : 3. One is thought of as 
 conditioning the other. The famous dictum of Aristotle, 5ei yap iriiyThieiv 
 rbv fj.avddmvTa ('Zo(})ia-T., 2), accords with the humble Crede ut intelligas of 
 Anselm, but contrasts with the hauglity IntcJVnje ut crt'das of Abelard. This 
 last seems to be the true logical relation, as already indicated in § 81. 
 
 The doctrine that certainty, belief, and doubt are merely simple feelings 
 does not derogate from their importance, but rather serves to bring feeling 
 forward to its true position, and show its weighty importance in human 
 nature. The common si)eech of men supports our view, since it always 
 recognizes these mental states to be feelings, as seen in the familiar phrases, 
 I feel quite certain, I feel sure, or assured, I feel a strong conviction, I feel 
 very doubtful, etc. The complex state, reliance, trust, faith, in which belief 
 is a predominant element, is likewise recognized to be feeling in the phrase, 
 
CHARACTERISTICS. 249 
 
 Mediate judgment and belief are the obverse and reverse 
 of the same mental state, but the strength of the belief does 
 not depend on the soundness or accuracy of the judgment, 
 but upon its clearness and distinctness, or its singleness, all 
 alternatives being obscured or eliminated. What is really 
 false may thus be heartily believed. An error is an error 
 only when taken for truth, and the correlative feeling may 
 mount to the highest conviction. So it is that belief attends 
 the false when thought of as true, just as the feeling of 
 moral approbation attends wrong conduct when judged to be 
 right. 1 
 
 § 228. Every feeling is marked by pleasure or pain. It 
 has, therefore, been proposed to make a primary division of 
 feelings into pleasant and painful. But this gives insuffi- 
 cient ground for subdivisions. Indeed, the distinction is 
 not always sharply marked, being of degree rather than of 
 kind. Pleasant feelings often graduate into painful feel- 
 ings, and vice versa., without change of any other quality, or 
 even of name, by a change of intensity only. A pleasing 
 musical tone may gradually become so loud as to be displeas- 
 ing. Pleasant expectation may pass into painful anxiety. 
 It is better, therefore, to take them together, though oppo- 
 sites, as a characteristic of feeling in general. ^ 
 
 I feel confident. The whole matter deserves an expanded treatment beyond 
 what our present limits will permit ; but if we have truly and clearly indicated 
 the right place for these modes of consciousness in the psychological system, 
 and their relations to other modes, this alone is a great gain. For the senti- 
 ment of truth, see § 251. 
 
 1 Opinion primarily means a feeling of conviction of a truth on merely 
 probable evidence. "Every opinion," says Montaigne, "is strong enough 
 to have had its martyrs"; and Luther cries: "0 doxa ! doxa ! quam es 
 communis noxa ! " Emotion by heightening the intensity of its correspond- 
 ing idea, greatly influences belief, and our desires react in like manner to 
 determine opinion. " Quse volunt sapiunt, et nolunt sapere quse vera sunt," 
 said St. Hilary ; and so Demosthenes : BovXerai rovd' ^Karros /cat o'lerai. — 
 Ohjnth., iii. 
 
 2 "Pleasure and pain," says Hamilton, "are the phenomena which con- 
 stitute the essential attribute of feeling under all its modifications." — Meta., 
 
250 FEELING. 
 
 Both pleasure and pain are positive, but either may, 
 Avith reference to the other, be viewed as negative. Abso- 
 lute pleasure or absolute pain never exists. Actually they 
 always coexist in the coexistence of various feelings, and 
 tend to neutralize each other, so that the total state is only 
 relatively pleasant or painful, or perhaps neutral. One 
 form of relative pleasure arises from contrast, in the mere 
 diminution or cessation of pain.^ 
 
 Aristotle's explanation of these phenomena, referring them 
 to their causes, has been very generally accepted. Pleasure 
 is the effect of certain harmonious relations, of certain agree- 
 ments ; pain is the effect of certain unharmonious relations, 
 of certain disagreements. The pleasurable is therefore prop- 
 erly called the agreeable, the painful, the disagreeable. 
 Pleasure is the reflex of spontaneous and unimpeded energy. 
 Pain is the reflex of over-strained or repressed energy. 
 Here the term spontaneous refers to subjective, the term 
 unimpeded to objective perfection. Each power tends spon- 
 taneously, that is, of its proper nature and without effort, 
 to put forth a certain maximum of free energy. If this 
 maximum be reached there is pleasure. If less, the energy 
 is repressed, if more, it is over-strained, and there is pain. 
 The term unimpeded stipulates that, in order to pleasure, 
 the object should not check the spontaneous spring of the 
 
 p. 573. See his distribution. — /r?., p. 602. "Inasmuch as suffering treads 
 always on the lieels of deliglit, and each kind of sweet has its cognate bitter, 
 it would be divorcing the closest relationship to partition the human feelings 
 into pleasures and pains as the primary division of the whole," — Bain, 
 Emotions and Will, p. 77. 
 
 1 Plato, in the Philebxis, taught that pleasure is merely relative, tlie absence 
 of or passing from pain, dei yiyvdfjLevov, ovd^Trore 6p. Kant adopted this view, 
 according to the quotation in Hamilton's Meta., p. 5i)9 sq. But in another 
 place Kant says: "Sie sind einander nicht wie Erwerb und Mangel (+ und 
 0), sondern wie Erwerb und Verlust (+ und — ), d. i. eincs dem andern nicht 
 bios als Gegenthell (cnntrndirtnn'r, sc. logice oppositnm), sondern audi als 
 Widerspiel {contrarie, sc. realitier oppositum) entgegengesetzt." — A7ithro- 
 pologie, § 59. Aristotle hold that both are positive, and his views now 
 generally prevail. — Nirom. Ethics, bk. x. 
 
CHARACTERISTICS. 251 
 
 energy towards, nor stimulate it beyond, its natural maxi- 
 mum. Thus all pleasure arises from the free natural play 
 of our faculties ; all pain, from their repression or their 
 over-strain. More tersely and more widely: The normal 
 gives pleasure; the abnormal, pain.^ 
 
 Pleasure and pain taken together have been regarded as 
 the fundamental and sole determinant of character and con- 
 duct; but we shall find in the sequel that there are other 
 determinants which often oppose and overcome this one. 
 The application of the principle has been further extended 
 to explain the entire nature, not only of man, but of all 
 sentient beings; for the doctrine of the evolution of the 
 varied forms of animal life from primordial forms by nat- 
 ural selection, is grounded on the natural impulse toward 
 pleasure and shrinking from pain.^ 
 
 lA famous dictum of Descartes is: " Tota nostra voluptas posita est 
 tantum in perfectionis alicujus nostrse conscientia." — Ejnst., pt. i, No. 6. 
 Says Kant: "Pleasure is tlie feeling of the furtherance (Beforderung), pain 
 -of the hindrance of life." So Herbart : "Feeling is the immediate percep- 
 tion [?] of hindrance or furtherance among the presentations extant at any 
 moment in consciousness, i.e. the immediate consciousness of the momentary 
 rising or sinking of the mental vital activity." — Cf. Lotze, Psychologie, 
 Dictate, § 47. Says Bain: "States of pleasure are connected with an 
 increase, states of pain with an abatement, of some or all of the vital func- 
 tions." — 3Iind and Body, p. 59. Spencer says : "Pains are the correlatives 
 of actions injurious to the organism, while pleasures are the correlatives of 
 actions conducive to its welfare." — Data of Ethics, § 33. 
 
 For illustration : Extremes of heat and cold, the one stimulating the vital 
 functions to excessive action, the other depressing them, are painful ; whereas 
 a medium temperature is pleasant. Darkness and also silence long continued 
 are depressing and painful ; intense light and sound are exciting and pain- 
 ful ; but the medium exercise of the eye and ear is pleasant. Harmony is 
 especially pleasing ; but discordant colors or sounds, harsh lights or grating 
 noises irritating the nerve conduits, are painful. In hope there is a healthful 
 stimulus ; depression in despair. The pain of tedium, ennui, arises from a 
 repressed natural tendency to action. The more varied the objects presented 
 to thought, the more varied and vivacious our activity, the intenser will be 
 the enjoyment of life. See § 223, note. 
 
 2 See Darwin, Origin of Species, ch. 4 ; but Spencer, passim. 
 
252 FEELING. 
 
 § 229. A negative characteristic of feelings in general is 
 that they are spontaneous, or at least involuntary; that is to 
 say, Ave cannot at will directly originate, or control, or 
 suppress any feeling. The sole function of will is to con- 
 centrate the cognitive consciousness on an object, which is 
 voluntary attention (§ 89). Any influence, therefore, voli- 
 tion may have over other activities is only indirect, only 
 through attention. It can excite or repress feeling only by 
 a command of its causes and conditions, which, however 
 effectual, is mediate control. Therefore the feelino-g, in. 
 themselves considered, are wholly involuntary. When their 
 causes are unknown or obscure, we call them spontaneous. 
 
 The rare and difficult art of self-mastery implies control 
 of feeling. The opposite is passion. This is a subjective 
 state, either of feeling or desire, or of both, so intense that 
 will is overpowered by blind instincts, the intellect being 
 darkened according to the law of inverse ratio, and tlie 
 sufferer from self becomes j)assively enslaved. If will suc- 
 cessfully resists this subjection, it is done by withdrawing 
 from the exciting object, that is, by attending to some other. 
 This persisted in, the passion subsides; but it appears to be 
 flight rather than victory. It is much the same when the 
 exciting object continues present, and one maintains self- 
 control, restrains action, speaks calmly and holds an imi)as- 
 sive countenance, by giving his attention strongly to thoughts 
 of duty, or fit conduct, or consequences of passionate action 
 in the case; then the flight is not so far. But one may 
 conquer self, yet only indirectly. If attention be fixed, if 
 the cognitive consciousness be strongly concentrated on the 
 exciting object itself, then, by the law of inverse ratio, the 
 objective side of the mental state is intensified at the expense 
 of the sul)joctive side. Thus a determined intellectual 
 activity relative to the object restrains and subdues passion- 
 ate feeling. This is victory. A humane surgeon calmly 
 and steadily does his work, and, though pitiless for the time, 
 is not so before and after. The coolness of a general is 
 
CHARACTEEISTICS. 253 
 
 perhaps due to intense attention to the phin and progress of 
 the battle. 
 
 When attention is firmly fixed on an object, the causes of 
 feelings other than those attending it are inoperative. 
 Hence extreme enthusiasm, or powerful emotion of any 
 kind, may make us insensible to physical pain, and even 
 gentle emotions assuage bodily suffering. On the other 
 hand, the effect of fixing attention on the feeling itself as a 
 subject-object, tends to increase its quantity and intensity. 
 A slight discomfort, if heeded, soon becomes intolerable. 
 Dis-ease becomes disease. A cherished sentiment becomes 
 a passion. 
 
 § 230. It is a general characteristic of feeling that it 
 tends to produce certain specific physical effects, both in the 
 orsfans of movement and in the viscera. Smiles and tears 
 are examples. Every pleasure and every pain, every mode 
 of feeling, has a definite wave of effects which speads more 
 or less widely through the nervous system, affecting organic 
 functions, or manifest in expressive movements. 
 
 This diffusion of feeliiig, as it is called, must be distin- 
 guished from reflex action. Tlie latter may or may not be 
 attended by consciousness ; the former is always attended by 
 consciousness. Reflex actions have a very limited range, 
 each being strictly confined to its single effect; whereas in 
 feelincr there is an influence diffused over the members more 
 widely, a general wave of effects. But the chief distinction 
 is that in reflex action mind is not at all concerned, unless 
 it may be as affected ; but in diffused feeling mind is pri- 
 marily the cause of the physical changes. 
 
 Reflex action has been designated as purely physical 
 instinct (§ 36). The diffusion of feeling, being partly 
 mental and partly physical, may be termed psja^ho-physical 
 instinct. Hereafter, under desire, we shall find a third 
 class of instincts, those purely mental, the psychical instincts 
 (§ 258). All instincts are involuntary and spontaneous. 
 
254 FEELING. 
 
 Generally, if the action be anticipated, it may be inhibited ; 
 if it have already begun, it may be suppressed by volition. 
 In the psycho-phj^sical instincts, however, this is true only 
 of movements dej^ending on the voluntary muscles. Organic 
 effects, such as blushing, are mostly beyond our power. The 
 suppression of displa}^ may become habitual, yet the feelings 
 themselves will still occur, though not unmodified by the 
 refusal to allow them their natural vent.^ 
 
 Feeling being the subjective side of cognition, it follows 
 that when a cognition ceases, the feeling should cease. But 
 in fact feeling often seems to persist, and to subside only 
 gradually, as in joy and sorrow. This seeming persistence 
 is because we commonly confound the feeling itself with its 
 physical effects. The latter may persist, but the former 
 ceases to be Avhen the correlative cognition ceases to be, its 
 physical effects becoming in turn the causes of sensations 
 more or less continuous. 
 
 The effects of feeling in physiognomic expression are 
 largely through the facial nerve. Different fibres of its 
 motor branches determine different movements of the face in 
 response to specific feelings. The lifted or frowning brow, 
 as in supercilious pride, or in anger, pain, doubt, or embar- 
 rassment, is very expressive, and easily read. The connnon 
 elevation of the lip and nose gives expression to disdain or 
 disgust. There are nine muscles moving the mouth, making 
 it the most expressive feature, far more so than the eye. 
 
 1 "Most of our emotions," says Darwin, "are so closely connected with 
 their expression, that they hardly exist if the body remains passive. Louis 
 XVI, when surrounded by a hostile mob, said : ' Am I afraid ? Feel my 
 pulse.' So a man may intensely hate another ; but until his bodily frame 
 is affected, he cannot be said to be enraged." — Expression, p. 239. This 
 recalls that Aristotle, in De Anhna, says: "Very often a thing takes place 
 which has to be described by different men in different ways. Supposing a 
 man is angry, lie would be so described by the poet or the historian. Thus 
 the poet would say, this man is in a boiling rage, Jie is exceedingly angry, 
 and is likely to do certain things. But the naturalist would say, there is a, 
 boiling up of the blood about his heart." 
 
CHARACTERISTICS. 255- 
 
 This power of expression is seen in smiles, pouting, the 
 curled lip of scorn, the depressed corners in sadness, the 
 open mouth of wonder, and many others. The tones of 
 the voice correspond. ^ Next to the facial, the respiratory 
 nerves are most susceptible, as in sighing, breathless sur- 
 prise, and panting eagerness. The convulsive movements 
 of the diaphragm in laughter and sobbing are noticeable 
 displays, the latter due to partial and transient paralysis. 
 During the sway of certain passions, as anxiety, fear, terror, 
 all the muscles of the body become relaxed, the motor powers 
 of the brain and spinal cord being depressed.^ 
 
 The organic effects of feeling are those produced on the 
 glands, lungs, heart, stomach, kidneys, and viscera gener- 
 ally, and on the skin. Effusion from the lacrymal gland is 
 an accompaniment of grief, but there are also tears of merri- 
 ment, of joy and of anger. Cheerfulness promotes diges- 
 tion, while all depressing feelings tend to arrest the healthy 
 action of the stomach, liver, bowels, and kidneys. In fear, 
 the mouth is parched by a suppression of saliva, and a cold 
 sweat breaks out on the skin. The disturbed action of the 
 heart under emotion is a remarkable instance of the influence 
 of feeling on the movements of an organ supplied by nerves 
 of the sympathetic system. This influence is so great that 
 
 1 The language or articulate expression of feeling consists in the few 
 interjections that belong to speech, as Oh ! Ah ! Alas ! To these add words 
 and phrases used interjectionally, as Bravo ! Hurrah ! Dear me ! Alas for 
 the rarity of human charity ! This is a very limited means of expression, 
 far more so than facial change and gesticulation, and it utterly fails unless 
 the tone corresponds. Music, however, song without words, is so exclu- 
 sively and widely expressive of emotion that it might fairly be named the 
 language of feeling. On_"Le Language des Emotions," see Revue des Deux 
 Mondes for March 1st, 1887. 
 
 2 Expression is a relief. A groan is a solace. A sigh, a flood of tears, 
 discharges a surplus of nervous excitement, thus preventing the reaction 
 which suppression would ensure, and the consequent exaltation of feeling. 
 A secret is a burden until told. A shout, a burst of applause is followed by- 
 renewed calm. 
 
256 FEELING. 
 
 the heart is popuhirly spoken of as the special seat of feeling, 
 as the brain is of intelligence. ^ 
 
 § 231. In conclusion we will now state the logical distri- 
 bution of feelings, determined by specific characteristics. 
 
 It will be observed that desires are excluded from this 
 classification, being reserved for subsequent and distinct 
 treatment. Yet some anticipation in the discussion will 
 perhaps be unavoidable, because of the intimate relation of 
 feelings and desires. They commingle and coexist, act and 
 react upon each other, though, in general, feeling excites 
 desire, and hence stands naturall}^ and logically prior. Both 
 are wholly subjective, and in them lie one's character and 
 disposition, just as his talents and abilities lie in the objec- 
 tive powers of cognition and volition. In consequence of 
 this intimacy, feelings and desires have a number of names in 
 common, and a term properly belonging to one is often in 
 usage transferred to the other. Passion, for examj)le, is 
 recognized in either, or in both. Most t]-eatises do not 
 distinguish between them, and hence mucli confusion and 
 variety of doctrine in the literature of the subject (§ 225). ^ 
 
 1 See Miiller, Physiology, pp. 932-4 ; and Sir Charles Bell's Anatomy of 
 Expression (1844). 
 
 ■■^ Kant divides feelings (Gefiihle) into sensual and intellectual. Tlie 
 sensual are those of sense or physical pleasures, and those of imagmatioi: 
 or pleasures of taste. Tlie intellectual ai'e those connected witli the concepts 
 of the understanding, and those connected with the ideas of pure reason. — 
 Anthropologic, bk. 2. He treats of desires (Beghrungsvennogen) apart from 
 feelings in bk. 3. Brown divides feelings into immediate, prospective and 
 retrospective, confusing desires with them. — Phil. <>f Ihtm. Mind, J^ec. i'^2. 
 Hamilton divides feelings first into pleasures and pains. — Lee. 44 (see § 22S). 
 Afterward he divides them into sensations and sentiments, which latter he 
 subdivides into the contemplative and the practical. Under the practical 
 sentiments he introduces desires. — Lee. 45. Bain does not distinguish feel- 
 ing and desire. — Emotions and Will, see p. 11. The two are confused also 
 by McCosh. — The Feelings. Waitz, following suggestions of Herbart, divides 
 into feeling proper (1, formal, 2, fiualitative) and complex emotional states, 
 which latter are made to include desires. 
 
CHARACTERISTICS. 257 
 
 By keeping clear of the desires many difficulties are 
 avoided, but many remain. A rigid classification is perliaps 
 impossible. It would seem that, if our view of feelings as 
 the subjective side of cognitions be true, the task should be 
 easy, and consist merely in transferring the divisions and 
 subdivisions of cognition to feeling, and marking the correl- 
 atives. This is the case so far as perception proper and 
 sensation are concerned. But beyond these we find it 
 impracticable. For illustration, many feelings accounted 
 simple in themselves have very complex correlative cogni- 
 tions. Shame at wrong conduct, for example, implies 
 introspection, and perhaps memory, with thought, and this 
 under a law of duty discerned by pure reason. It is evident 
 that it cannot be classed as correlative to any one of these 
 exclusively. Hence, after sensaiion, some other ground of 
 classification must be sought. As sufficient for the purpose 
 of orderly discussion, we have adopted the following : — 
 
 SCHEME OF THE FEELINGS. 
 
 I. Consciousness. 
 
 1. Objective consciousness, or Cognition. 
 
 2. Subjective consciousness, or Feeling. 
 
 (1) Sensation. 
 
 a. Sensus vagus. 
 h. Sensus fixus. 
 
 (2) Emotion. 
 
 (3) Sentiment. 
 
 a. Sensuous. 
 h. Pure. 
 
 («) Intellectual. 
 
 (h) Ethical. 
 
 The ground of the several subdivisions will be given in 
 the progress of the discussion. Cf. § 76. 
 
258 FEELING. 
 
 CHAPTER II. 
 
 SENSATION. 
 
 § 232. Sensations bear a specific relation to the organism. 
 Tliej, together with the attendant perceptions, are the effects 
 of external physical causes. The immediate perception is of 
 the proximate cause as an immediate object ; the sensation is 
 the subjective side of the same mental state. Sensations are 
 sometimes described as physical feelings, and sentiments as 
 mental feelings. Sensations have a physical basis, but are 
 none the less strictly mental states, as truly so as sentiments. 
 Perhaps it is sufficient to say simply that sensations are the 
 feelings that attend the exercise of sense, and that senti- 
 ments attend the exercise of intellect. 
 
 The distinction between sensation and perception was 
 noted in § 97, and their inverse ratio has been repeatedly 
 mentioned. It remains to say that the diffusion of feeling 
 (§ 230) should be distinguished from sensation. In sensa- 
 tion the feeling is an effect, in diffusion it is a cause. 
 True, diffusion causes a cpiaai sensation, as when one [)ain- 
 fuUy shudders at the thought of crime, when horror chills, 
 when a blush burns. But these diffusive effects of feelincr 
 in general should be distinguished from the primary sensa- 
 tions attending the senses proper. 
 
 § 233. The sensus var/us, as in })ure pain or in the sense 
 of temperature, is highly subje(>tive (§ 29). The fact, how- 
 ever, tliat we locate many of these sensations is evidence of 
 percipient power. Under this head are included a variety 
 of sensations, ministering for the most part to tlie oigaiiic 
 functions, and to the conservation of the body. Nearly all 
 
SENSATION. 259 
 
 parts of the frame have their several feelings of comfort and 
 pleasure, of discomfort and pain ; but in some of the deeply 
 seated organs no strong sensation occurs, unless in the form 
 of pain indicating a disordered condition. Several distinct 
 groups of these feelings are discernible, of which the follow- 
 ing are examples : — ■ 
 
 The nerves and nerve centres determine a class of sensa- 
 tions according to the organic condition of their own tissue. 
 Pain arising from wounds, diseases, headache, toothache, 
 and neuralgia, should probably be classed as pure pain. 
 But nervous exhaustion produces a distinct sensibility, 
 while repose, refreshment, and stimulants engender an oppo- 
 site condition. Under the general term nervousness is 
 included quite a variety of sensations, usually arising from 
 a waste of nervous energy and substance. This pain is not 
 acute but massive, having quantity rather than intensity. 
 It is widespread and oppressive, and is expressed by col- 
 lapsed features, restlessness, and fretting, and, when extreme, 
 drives to madness and suicide. The feeling arising from a 
 healthy and fresh condition of the nervous tissue is of an 
 opposite character and a pleasurable consciousness. The 
 nervous substance is, of course, necessary to all forms of 
 sensibility, but we are here noting the effect of its own 
 state, and not the effect propagated from some other tissue. 
 
 The sensations attending respiration include the enjoy- 
 ment of pure air, and the various shades of ojjpression from 
 foul air, lack of breath, and suffocation. The influence of 
 pure air is stimulating and spreads over the system, elevat- 
 ing other functions by improving the quality of the blood. 
 But in the lungs themselves is felt a pleasurable sensibility, 
 not acute, but refreshing. No feelincr arises from the luno-s 
 in ordinary steady action, but either acceleration or retarda- 
 tion at once gives rise to the characteristic sensations. The 
 feelings of insufficient or impure air are manifested in faint- 
 ness, weariness, exhaustion, and suffocation. No voluntary 
 effort can long maintain suspended respiration. 
 
260 FEELING. 
 
 Digestion affords all the conditions of a sense, and like 
 the sense of temperature niiglit fairly be assigned to the 
 sensus jixus. There is an external object, the food; a dis- 
 tinct organ, the alimentary canal ; and a set of sensations, 
 distinct and specific, arising from contact. Excluding taste, 
 the sensation arising from a healthful meal is massive, I'ich, 
 and luxurious. Its magnitude appears in its ability to sub- 
 merge many irritations, and for the time to rule conscious- 
 ness. The feelings attending unsatisfied hunger and thirst 
 become states of prevading, massive, deep, and intolerable 
 wretchedness. They are more intense than nervous depres- 
 sion, and accordingly we take more precautions against 
 them. They incite furious passions which we call wolfish. 
 The feeling of nausea is distinctly stomachic, exciting reflex 
 muscular convulsions that result in vomiting. An experi- 
 ence of sea-sickness enables one to estimate the depth of 
 misery reached by this sensation. Deranged digestion pro- 
 duces a depression of spirits difficult to resist. One pos- 
 sessed by the demon Dyspepsia is not himself, is hardly 
 accountable, and lives in gloom and wretchedness.^ 
 
 § 234. The sensations of the sensus jixus are now to be 
 examined. Those of the two somatic senses (§ 22 sq. ) are 
 similar to those of the sensus vagus. The muscular sensation 
 is the massive sense of pressure, which within limits, as in 
 squeezing the hand, or in the hug of affection, is pleasur- 
 able ; but in higher degrees it becomes oppressive and pain- 
 ful, as in cramp and spasm. According to Brown-Sdquard, 
 the pain is in proportion to the resistance offered to the 
 muscular contraction. 
 
 Fatigue is a muscular sensation. Over-fatigue is painful, 
 
 1 While the writer is responsible for the general treatment of the feelings, 
 he must acknowledge his great indebtedness to the excellent works of Mr. 
 Bain for very many of the details in this and other chapters. They have 
 been used freely, even as to phraseology, without minute indications, in the 
 hope that this general acknowledgment would be deemed sufficient. 
 
SENSATION. 261 
 
 is sometimes used as a punishment, and is a part of the 
 miseiy attending toil. Many causes of suffering are called 
 burdens. Within limits, fatigue is pleasurable, as from 
 walking, running, dancing, swimming. The lassitude that 
 follows such pleasurable muscular exertion is agreeable. 
 To this must be added the luxury of slumber, for the massive 
 sensation we experience when falling asleep has its seat 
 mostly in the muscular tissue. 
 
 § 235. The tactile sensation excited by soft clothing, a 
 glove, or a cushion, is agreeable, not acute, but massive, and 
 resembling the sensation of gentle warmth. Pleasurable 
 contact keeps a new-born animal by its mother's side. A 
 gentle slapping or stroking of the hand, as in caress, is 
 agreeable.! But when, instead of soft touch extending over 
 considerable area, we have intense action over small area, as 
 by the stroke of a whip, an acute and painful sensation 
 results, so intense as to make the whip the most effective 
 instrument of torture. 
 
 Tickling is a peculiar sensation, and may become an 
 intolerable agony, exciting convulsive laughter, sneezing, 
 jerking the limbs, and extraordinary efforts at deliverance. 
 Clamminess, arising from the adhesion of some foreign sub- 
 stance to the skin, is an uneasy, disagreeable feeling. The 
 skin is also liable to feelings not due to contact, and hence 
 called subjective sensations; such as the creeping feeling, 
 as if produced by a crawling insect, and numbness, or the 
 tingling of a limb asleep. 
 
 § 236. Of the cephalic senses the sense of smell is the 
 most subjective (§ 4). The varieties of odor are endless, 
 and their classification difficult. The following will per- 
 haps be sufficient for our present purposes : — 
 
 1 " The sensation specially due to contact in a kiss, or other gentle caress, 
 disappears in the greater strength of the accompanying sentiment, and the 
 consequent diffusive thrill." — Bain. 
 
262 FEELING. 
 
 First, the fragrant odors, or those that appeal to the ol- 
 factory sensibilities, and represent the pure and jjroper 
 sensations of smell. The odors of the violet, rose, jessa- 
 mine, orange, lemon, lavender, and rosemary are examples. 
 We call them sweet odors. ^ The opposite is stench. It is 
 intense rather than massive, and we are discomposed rather 
 than depressed by it. Asafoetida, sewer smells, and the 
 cadaverous odor are examples. 
 
 Secondly, fresh odors are those that owe their character to 
 the sympathy of the lungs. Eau de Cologne, the resinous 
 perfume of the pine forest, the balmy odors of the field and 
 garden, are examples. The opposite is the suffocating odor, 
 as of a red-hot stove, or the effluvia of a crowd. 
 
 Thirdly, the appetizing odors, producing a sympathetic 
 effect on the stomach, as the savory smell of roasting meat. 
 The opposite is the nauseous odor, as of rotten eggs. 
 
 Fourthlj-, the pungent odors are such as seem to excite, 
 with the olfactory, the tactile nerves. Ammonia or smelling 
 salts, nicotine or snuff, pepper and mustard are pungent. 
 Snuff-takers who have lost the power of smelling the sweet 
 odors, are still susceptible of the nicotine pungency. 
 
 § 237. Taste is less subjective and more percipient than 
 smell (§ 7). For this reason perhaps it is that tastes are 
 more distinctly remembered, and hence their repetition more 
 eagerly sought.^ A viand or a wine tasted to-da}- may be 
 
 1 "Sweetness is a name for a variety of pleasm-es. Derived orii^inally 
 from taste, it is extended to smells, to sounds and to several of the hisiher 
 emotions, such as the tender affections and the beautiful in nature and in 
 art. These feelings are so far of a kindred nature, as to suggest and support 
 each other. They all agree in being forms of pure passive pleasure, and in 
 this they resemble repose, wanntli and liealthy digestion.'" — Bain, Sciixes 
 and Intellext, p. 150. For the present classification, see /(/., p. \o'-\ sq. It is 
 gi'ounded on the effects produced on our organs. Linnieus made seven 
 classes. See Longet, p. 151. 
 
 - Yet, as Longet observes, in dreaming of a banquet we see, but neither 
 siurll iinr taste the viands. , For the following classes, see Senses and Intellect, 
 p. 144 Ai\. It is taken in part from Gmelin's Chemistry, 
 
SENSATION. 263 
 
 confidently pronounced the same as one tasted long ago. 
 The sensuous pleasures of taste are great and strongly- 
 marked, but they should be distinguished from the sensa- 
 tions of the alimentary canal, relish and nausea. A health- 
 ful state of the digestive organs and hunger are the requisite 
 conditions of a strong relish. When hunger is satisfied, 
 there still remains the enjoyment of sweets, as at dessert, 
 due to their independent effect on the gustatory nerves. 
 After sea-sickness, when there is no relish for food, the taste 
 of sweet or bitter is still acute. 
 
 Tastes may be more clearly classified than odors. First, 
 the sweet taste, of which sugar furnishes the type, due 
 generally to the actual presence of sugar, the faint sweetness 
 of the alums being an exception. The true opposite is 
 bitter, as in quinine and aloes. As sweetness is the pleas- 
 ure proper to taste, so bitterness is the pain, and these 
 words are used to describe, metaphorically, many kinds of 
 pleasure and pain. 
 
 Secondly, acid taste, which when moderate is an agreeable 
 pungent stimulus, as in vinegar, lemonade, and acid fruits 
 generally. When powerful, the sensation is sharp and 
 penetrating, producing the pain of a burn, rather than of 
 rejjulsive taste. The opposite is the alkaline taste, as in 
 soda, and is rarely agreeable. 
 
 Thirdly, the saline taste, as of common salt, due princi- 
 pally and therefore similar to that of the base. The repul- 
 sive taste of Epsom salts, as also the styptic taste of ink, 
 seems to be compounded of saline and bitter. 
 
 Fourthly, the fiery taste, as of mustard, pepper, camphor, 
 volatile oils, and alcoholic liquors. This, however, seems 
 not truly gustatory, but an effect upon the sense of tem[)er- 
 ature. Peppermint produces a marked sensation of cold. 
 Acrid substances and astringents, as alum, affect the tactile 
 rather than the gustatory nerves, but the effect is usually 
 spoken of as an acrid or an astringent taste. 
 
2G4 FEELING. 
 
 § 238. The sensations attending the exercise of the two 
 objective or percipient cephalic senses are, unless extreme, 
 comparatively slight. We refer to the pleasures or pains 
 that are wholly in sense, to the exclusion of those intellec- 
 tual delights, and their contraries, of which hearing and 
 sight are the most copious and constant channels. Music is 
 the natural lanonuao-e of sentiment. The discernment of 
 beauty by the eye is its prerogative. But sentiment in 
 general and that of beauty in particular are intellectual cor- 
 relatives, and not sensations. We are here considering 
 sensations only. A disorder of one of these senses, or its 
 excessive action, may produce great misery, j^et their highest 
 pleasures lift us but little above indifference. Still their 
 pleasures do not cloy so quickly as those of smell and taste, 
 and hence we obtain from them a larger amount of sensuous 
 enjoyment than if they also were limited by speedy satiety. 
 
 Hearing is more sensuous than seeing (§ 11). Sounds 
 differing in degree cause distinguishable sensations. Those 
 having volume or quantity, as distant thunder, produce a 
 massive sensation. Loud or intense sounds, as loud speak- 
 ing, produce an acute sensation. Increased intensity gives 
 pain, as a scream. A difference of pitch gives rise to a 
 difference of sensation, grave sounds being generally volu- 
 minous, acute sounds intense. A sound may be both volu- 
 minous and intense, as a steam-whistle. The crescendo and 
 diminuendo have a special sensuous effect, the former stimu- 
 lating, the latter depressing, as in the moaning of wind, the 
 swell of a trumpet, the cadences of an orator. 
 
 Sounds differing in kind may be distinguished as articu- 
 late, imisical, and noisy. In the first, the hissing of the s, 
 the burring of the r, and the hum of the m, produce differ- 
 ent sensations. In musical tones, the different quality or 
 timbre produces distinguishable sensations, as the same note 
 from a flute, a violin, a trumpet, and a voice. The pleasure 
 of several smooth tones in concord is peculiar, and the 
 highest known to the ear. Noises are unmusical discords 
 
SENSATION. 265 
 
 varying in degree. They readily become painful, and are 
 characterized as harsh, grating, piercing, shrill, etc. Since 
 we have no ear-lids to protect us, and as sounds go great 
 distances, turn corners, resound, and are very penetrating, 
 it comes that a noisy person is one of the most unavoidable 
 a:id disagreeable pests that afflict mankind. 
 
 § 239. The sensation of white light, as diffused solar 
 radiance, is distinctly pleasurable (§ 16). The effect is 
 massive or acute according as the light proceeds from a 
 surface or from points. In cheering influence, it ranks with 
 warmth, nourishment, and repose. Light does not exhaust 
 the nerves as rapidly as odor, savor, or even sound, and 
 hence its influence, though gentle, is by endurance power- 
 ful. Its enjoyment, however, requires alternation and 
 limitation. Exposure must be balanced b}^ the repose of 
 darkness. Almost instinctively we seek the cheerful day or 
 the well-lighted room, and on the other hand, the grateful 
 shade, when there is excess of light. 
 
 Color is attended by special sensations. Blue and green 
 are commonly reckoned as mild and refreshing; red as- 
 pungent and exciting. Perhaps this effect attributed to red 
 is not absolute, but arises from relativity; for, next to white 
 and shades of gray, we are most familiar with blue and green, 
 and hence red, being comparatively rare, is more stimulating. 
 As in sounds, so in colors there are agreeable harmonies and 
 contrasts, and disagreeable discords. 
 
 The sensation due to lustre is more pleasant than that 
 from color alone. Lustrous bodies, as opposed to dull, 
 reflect beams of light; as polished gems, metals, and woods;, 
 ivory, pearl, silk; hair, teeth, eyes. These owe their spe- 
 cially pleasing effect largely to their lustre. The common 
 use of the words dull, polished, and brilliant, to mark 
 intellectual character, and illustrious to replace renowned^ 
 indicates how highly we prize this shining quality. 
 
266 FEELING. 
 
 CHAPTER III. 
 
 EMOTION. 
 
 § 240. The discussion of emotions may be introduced by 
 a very brief notice of certain states which influence them. 
 These are the temperament, mood, and disposition of the 
 individual. 
 
 Temperament is a term used to designate a special stat- 
 ical relation between body and mind, certain fixed physical 
 and consequent mental characteristics. The physical organ- 
 ization determines a general cast of feeling, causing a ten- 
 dency to see, as it were, everything colored with some one 
 invariable hue. It determines to what moods the man shall 
 be most commonly subject, and inclines him to special kinds 
 of emotions. The temperaments have long been distin- 
 guished as the choleric, the sanguine, the melancholic, and 
 the phlegmatic. The corresponding mental traits in general 
 are irascible, hopeful, despondent, and impassive. Certain 
 external physical marks usually distinguish them, less mani- 
 fest in old age than in youth, and in many cases failing 
 entirely. ^ 
 
 1 The theory is ancient. Galen has an essay to show, " Quod animi mores 
 corporis temperamenta sequuntur." In the history of medicine it holds a 
 prominent place, but is now little regarded by practitioners. It is still recog- 
 nized in psychology. Dr. Leopold George treats of it ably and at length. 
 See Lchrbuch d. Psj/rhoJorjie. p. 125 sq. (1854). lie holds that jieoples are 
 distinguished by temperaments, that the Spanish and Italians are choleric, 
 the French sanguine, the English melancholic, the Germans phlegmatic. 
 More generally, the Malayan race is choleric, the Caucasian sanguine, the 
 Mongolian melancholic, the Negro phlegmatic. The four periods of life also 
 correspond to the four temperaments ; childhood is sanguine, youth melan- 
 cholic (sentimental'), manhood choleric, age phlcgmiitic. Lotze treats the 
 f-ubject in Mirrorosmus, ii, p. 24 sq. He would substitute sentiuu'ntal for 
 
EMOTION. 267 
 
 Mood or humor differs from temperament chiefly in being 
 less permanent. There is generally a physical predisposing 
 cause together with some casual fact. These being tempo- 
 rary, the consequent mood is transient. He whose liver and 
 finances are in disorder is likely for the time to be in an 
 ill-humor. Moods exist only in that they are a tendency 
 to a special class of feelings, yet they have received numer- 
 ous distinguishing names, as cheerful, glad, ga}^ hilarious, 
 lively, etc. ; opposed by sorrowful, sad, sulky, solemn, dull, 
 etc. Such contraries cannot coexist, but neither may exist. 
 Moods have characteristic expressions in the features, ges- 
 tures, gait, and tones of the voice. ^ 
 
 Disposition has the permanence of temperament, but is 
 wholly mental. Mind, though in a very important sense a 
 unit, has nevertheless, like the body, a constitution which 
 varies in different individuals as to the degree of its powers. 
 The subjective differences mark the disposition of the man, 
 influencing the kind and current of his feelings, especially 
 of his emotions. Thus we say that one is naturally, or 
 
 melancholic, a temperament marked by " a special receptivity for the feeling 
 the value of all possible relations," but indifferent to the bare facts. Wundt 
 distributes the temperaments thus : — 
 
 Strong. Weak. 
 
 Quick Choleric Sanguine. 
 
 iilow Melancholic .... Phlegmatic. 
 
 He says: "One should be sanguine amid the petty sufferings and joys of 
 daily life, melancholy in the serious hours of life's more important events, 
 choleric toward impressions that fetter one's profounder interests, phlegmatic 
 in the execution of the resolves that have been reached." — P/ii/s. Psych., ii, 
 p. 345 sq. 
 
 1 Anciently moods or humors were supposed to depend on the fluids of the 
 body, hence humor, from Juimere, to be moist. Their transient and variable 
 character is indicated in the Ger. Laune, from Lat. luna, the moon, upon 
 whose changes the moods, perhaps because they are changeable, were fancied 
 to depend. Cf. Eng. lunacij. Cheerfulness and melancholy, U Allegro and 
 n Penseroso, may be taken as generically representative of the opposed 
 classes. So also the temperaments may be reduced to two, the sanguineous 
 and the melancholic ; the phlegmatic being a mode of the former, and the 
 choleric a mode of the latter. 
 
268 FEELING. 
 
 perhaps by culture, of a cheerful, proud, meek, modesty 
 timid, gloomy, morose, suspicious, liberal, or sociable dispo- 
 sition. 
 
 § 241. As sensations are feelings correlative to perception, 
 so emotions and sentiments are correlative to intellect. 
 The specific difference between emotion and sentiment is 
 rationality. Sentiment is rational; emotion is non-rational. 
 This non-rational or irrational character of emotion is purely 
 negative, and means, not that it violates, but that it is not 
 determined by reason. No clear logical process is antece- 
 dent, but the feeling arises apparently on the bare emjjirical 
 presentation or representation of some fitting object. The 
 irrational brute is deemed capable of emotions, such as 
 surprise or fear, but not of sentiments, such as regret or 
 reverence, 
 
 A positive mark of emotion is its inhibiting influence on 
 the cognitive and other faculties, and so on reasonable con- 
 duct. Emotions, even when moderate, confuse thoughts, so 
 that to be clear we must be calm. At their height, they 
 attain overwhelming force, paralyzing other energies, in 
 accord with the law of inverse ratio. Wonder arrests volun- 
 tary activity, and astounds; sorrow dulls, abating interest 
 in things around; joy transports; fear ti-ansfixes, putting a 
 restraint upon both intelligence and action. Imagination 
 in certain cases is highly stimulated by emotion, but its 
 voluntary exercise being inhibited, the images are mere 
 phantasms. Fear especially has this effect, for even a slight 
 alarm may conjure up phantoms that terrify. 
 
 The diffusive effects of emotions are greater in variety and 
 intensity than those of any other class of feelings (§ 230). 
 More than any other they tend to go out naturally, that is, 
 instinctively, into forms of energetic ex])ression. In them 
 we are greatly moved, lience the word emotion. Facial 
 expression, voice, gesticulation, are called into i)lay, and 
 their language, very hard to repress, is so plain as to be read 
 
EMOTION. 269 
 
 by any observer. Every one knows the start of surprise, 
 the gaping eyes and mouth of stupid wonder, the shout of 
 joy, the groaning or sobbing of grief and sorrow, the smiles 
 of ghidness, the sighs of sadness, the scream of terror, the 
 shrinking of bashfuhiess, the burst of tears whether of joy or 
 of sorrow we cannot always tell. The organic effects are 
 powerful. The pale cheek of fear, and the flushed face of 
 joy, show a notable effect on the heart beats. Hysterics, 
 panting, paralysis, and even instant death are not infre- 
 quently the effects of emotion. 
 
 § 242. There are several distinct groups of emotions 
 whose members differ chiefly in degree. Some of these will 
 now be mentioned by way of illustration. It should be 
 observed that many others exist, many that have received no 
 names, and that complex states, as hope, are often spoken of 
 as emotions because of an emotional element. 
 
 Wonder is typical of a group which, in the order of 
 degree, runs about thus: surprise, admiration, wonder, 
 amazement, astonishment. Surprise, the least intense of 
 these, attends a sudden arrest of attention. By it we are 
 awakened, startled, stirred. To admire, in its original 
 sense, is to wonder at.^ But wonder is a stronger emotion. 
 In it we are transfixed and confounded. 
 
 These emotions are almost indifferent to pleasure and pain, 
 especially those in the lower degrees. True, we speak of 
 a pleasant or a painful surprise; but the pleasure or pain 
 seems to be not in the surprise, but in other feelings excited 
 by the surprising object. We are surprised and delighted, 
 or are surprised and grieved. 
 
 Wonder has been called the daughter of ignorance ; still 
 she is the mother of knowledge. " Admiratio est semen 
 
 1 From ad and mirnri ; whence also miracle. '• Wonder not, nor admire 
 not in thy mind." — Twelfth Night, A. 3, sc. 4. Horace says : — 
 
 '• Nil admirari prope res est, Nurnici, 
 Solaque, qua? possit facere et servare beatiim." — Epis., lib. 1, 6. 
 
270 FEELING. 
 
 sapientite," says Bacon. What is a wonder, a mystery, a- 
 miracle?^ An isolated, unexplained fact. It excites a rest- 
 less seeking to refer it to some cause or class. This done, 
 the wonder ceases, and we rest. 
 
 § 243. Fear is generic of a series which ma}^ be stated 
 tluis : apprehension, alarm, fear, flight, terror. The emotion 
 is ^jrospective, arising from the representation of evil to 
 come. It is, therefore, especially dependent on imagination, 
 which alone depicts the future ; and hence, persons of lively 
 and unrestrained imagination are most liable to fears. 
 
 The cause of fear is generall}^ involved in uncertainty or 
 ignorance. Before any great but evident, certain, and well- 
 understood evil, the mind stands in dread, which is thus a 
 sentiment rather than an emotion. Brutes no doubt feel fear 
 in all its degrees, but not dread. P^ear arises in prospect of 
 evil unknown in character and amount. Thus fear, as Avell 
 as wonder, is the offspring of ignorance ; but wonder gives 
 birth to science, and science strangles fear. Knowledge is 
 not only power, it is composure. A phenomenon, as a solar 
 eclipse, intelligently understood, may still inspire awe, but 
 no longer terror. One of the benefits of modern science is 
 the subduing of unreasonable fears.^ 
 
 1 Ger. Wunder, a miracle, a prodigy, a marvel. So in the last verse of the 
 scene in Auerbach's cellar in Faust : — 
 
 " Nun sag' mir eins, man soil kcin Wuuder glauben ! " 
 
 "With like meaning the third stanza of Vemis and Adonis begins : — 
 
 " Vouchsafe, Ihou wonder, to alight thy steed." 
 
 2 On the other hand, the ignorant are delivered from many fears to which 
 the enlightened are reasonably subject. Belarius says of Cloten : — 
 
 " Being Bcarce made up, 
 I mean, to man, lie had not appieliension 
 Of roaring terrors; for th' effect of judgment 
 Is oft the cause of fear." — Cyiubiliiw, A. 4, sc. 2. 
 
 " Real valor," says Scott, " consists not in being insensible to danger, but 
 m being prompt to confiMut and i-cpel it." — Pcrrril <>/ l/ic Piak, vol. 2, 
 p. 172, Black's ed. The true opposite of courage, then, is not fear. Again, 
 
EMOTION. 271 
 
 In all its degrees this emotion is painful. The pain is not 
 only unlike, but may be more severe than physical pain. The 
 cruelty of scaring a child is greater than that of striking it, 
 and the effect is likely to be more permanent. Yet excep- 
 tions must be allowed. The agreeable fascination of super- 
 stitious fear when moderate, as from a ghost story, is well 
 known ; and the fictitious terrors of the drama are a volup- 
 tuous excitement.^ 
 
 The organic influence of fear is chiefly a depression or 
 prostration of muscular energy, except in the one form of 
 running away from danger. Extreme terror may so paralyze 
 as to make even this impossible. Involuntary expressions are 
 starting, trembling, staring, huskiness, or perhaps speechless- 
 ness. The mouth and lips become dry and parched, the flow 
 of saliva being checked.^ T'le hair seems to stand on end, 
 and sometimes turns white.^ The blood rushes to the heart, 
 leaving the extremities pale. We are appalled, and dismayed 
 or weakened. Cold sweat, convulsions, insanity, and death 
 are not unusual effects of fright. 
 
 the antithesis of hope is not fear, but despondency, whose highest degree is 
 despair. The negative of fear is simply the feeling of security. 
 
 Godly fear, which is in contrast with servile fear, is a composite state, and 
 entirely compatible with the perfect l6ve that casteth out fear. See 1 John 
 4 : 18. 
 
 1 See Akenside's Pleasures of the Imagination, bk. i, 255 sq., ending: — 
 
 " Each tiembliug heart with grateful terrors quelled." 
 
 The solemn Eleusinian mysteries were intended, says Aristotle, to purify 
 the heart by pity and terror. 
 
 2 In India a suspected criminal is made to hold a mouthful of rice, and 
 after a little, to drop it out. If found dry, he is judged guilty, and vice versa. 
 It is needless to remark that this "Ordeal of the morsel of rice" may be a 
 fair test of fear, but not of guilt. 
 
 ^ That hair turns white under the influence of fear is a well-established 
 fact. That it seems to stand on end is unquestionable ; in the bristling of 
 animals it actually does so. The notion is very ancient ; e.g. : — 
 
 "Obstupui, steteruntque comae, et vox faucibus haesit." — ^neid, bk. ii, 774. 
 
 But see e.specially Job 4 : 15. Horror, from Lat. horrere, to bristle ; cf. 
 horripilation. 
 
272 FEELING. 
 
 § 244. Gladness, joy, bliss, rapture, contrast with sadness, 
 sorrow, grief, woe. The former are pleasurable emotions, the 
 latter are usually, but not necessarily, painful ; for, says 
 Plin}' : " Est quffidam etiam dolendi voluptas." 
 
 Joy arises generally on the fulfilment of ardent wishes, 
 especially if the gratification be sudden and the manner unex- 
 pected. Sorrow arises generally on the disappointment of 
 hope, or the experience of loss. Hence these emotions bear a 
 sjDccial relation to the desires. They are most familiar to us 
 in connection with affectionate desire, especially in the form 
 of personal love. We are glad on meeting a friend, we 
 rejoice at the restoration of a lost brother, and the highest 
 bliss of heaven is represented as the rapture of perfect love. 
 Tlie pains have like gradation, from the gentle longings of a 
 brief absence, to the overwhelming sorrow of a new-made 
 Qfrave.^ 
 
 The word rapture, indicating the highest joy, well expresses 
 the inhibiting effect of this emotion, in which we are, as it 
 were, seized upon and carried away even from one's self. 
 Transport and ecstasy, expressing the extremes of both joy 
 and sorrow, have a similar significance. 
 
 Joy quickens the blood, and often excites violent, and 
 sometimes fatal, palpitations of the heart. The ej^es are 
 animated and bright, and sometimes overflow with tears 
 while the mouth is wreathed with smiles. To these expres- 
 sions are added exclamations, clapping of hands, and other 
 lively gestures, which, when not restrained by a sense of 
 decorum, extend to leaping and dancing, with shouts and 
 
 1 " There is something in melancholy feelings," says Scott, " more natural 
 to an imperfect and suffering state than in those of gaiety, and when they 
 are brought into collision, the former seldom fail to triumph. If a funeral 
 train and a wedding procession were to meet unexpectedly, it will readily be 
 allowed that the mirtli of the last would be speedily merged in the gloom of 
 the other." — PercrU of the Pt'dk, ch. 4. Cf. Irving's true and beautiful 
 analysis in the sketch, "Tiie Widow and her Son." beginning: "What are 
 the distresses of the rich!" and in '• IJmal Fiuifrals," beginning: "The 
 sorrow for the dead is the only sorrow fnuu which we refuse to be divorced." 
 
EMOTION. 273 
 
 laughter. In the burst of grief there is violent agitation of 
 the whole frame, convulsive movements of the features, beat- 
 ing the breast, tearing the hair, rending the garments, wail- 
 ing, lamentation, sobs, sighs, and floods of tears. ^ Then 
 follow lassitude, debility, dejection of the countenance, and 
 languor in the eyes. Circulation is enfeebled, the face pale, 
 the muscles flaccid, and hence the head hangs, the eyelids 
 droop, and the features lengthen. 
 
 § 245. The emotion that accompanies love in its various 
 forms has no distinctive name. Love strictly taken is an 
 affection, a desire, but is attended by both emotions and 
 sentiments peculiar to it. These, together with the affection, 
 constitute the strongest, the most influential, and most uni- 
 versal passion of human nature. We distinguish fraternal, 
 filial, paternal, maternal, conjugal, and sexual love, and other 
 kinds, but the attendant emotions are so similar that they 
 may be accounted one. 
 
 The emotion, though often rising to a great height, is 
 usually gentle, tender, and pleasing, yet strong, even in its 
 mildest form. Its opposite is the painful emotion attending 
 hate. Jealousy is a complex passionate state, involving, 
 among other elements, both these opposites. The inhibiting 
 influence of the emotion on the intellect is well expressed by 
 the old myth that Love is blind. 
 
 The chief instinctive expressions of love are reducible to 
 gentle touch. As anger gives a blow, love offers or craves 
 a caress. Fondling or caressing may take the form of the 
 embrace, the kiss, or the hand-stroke, which under restraint 
 
 1 " In joyful moods the features are dilated ; the voice is full and strong ; 
 the gesticulation is abundant ; the very thoughts are richer. In the gambols 
 of the young, we see to advantage the coupling of the two facts, mental 
 delight and bodily energy. Introduce some acute misery into the mind at 
 that moment, and all is collapse, as if one had struck a blow at the heart." — 
 Bain, Senses and Intellect, p. 286. The gay dance is a conventional mode 
 of expressing gladness ; the grave march of a funeral train is a conventional 
 expression of sadness. 
 
274 FEELING. 
 
 are reduced to the hand-shake, linking of arms, and the like, 
 all these being forms of touch.^ 
 
 § 246. Sj^mpathy is not itself an emotion, but the experi- 
 ence of feelings, chiefly emotions, similar in kind to those 
 expressed by or known to exist in another person. It is a 
 mental contagion, a spontaneous, unreflecting, irrational im- 
 pulse, one that sets aside our own personality, and moves us 
 to partake of the pleasure or pain, the happiness or misery, 
 of others. The word is Greek. The corresponding Latin 
 word is compassion, but this is limited in usage to painful 
 states, and is more nearly synonymous with commiseration and 
 condolence. Compassion partakes of the nature of senti- 
 ment, and is a condescending term, indicating the feeling of 
 a superior toward an inferior.^ 
 
 1 The origin of this emotion has been sought for in sympathy. Doubtless 
 the two react upon and strengthen one anotlier, but they seem to be distinct 
 and equally original. " In considering the genesis of the tender emotion, in 
 any or in all of its modes, I am inclined," says Bain, "to put great stress 
 upon the sensation of animal contact, or the pleasure of the embrace. 
 Touch is the fundamental and generic sense, the first-born of sensibility [see 
 § 23, note 3]. Even after the remaining senses are differentiated, this primary 
 sense continues to be a leading susceptibility of the mind. The combined 
 jiower of soft contact and warmth amounts to a considerable pitch of massive 
 pleasure ; while there may be subtile intluences not reducible to these two 
 heads, such as we term, from not knowing anything about them, magnetic or 
 electric. The strong fact that cannot be explained away is that under tender 
 feeling there is a craving for the embrace. As anger is consummated by 
 knocking some one down, so love is completed and satisfied with an embrace. 
 Touch is both the alpha and the omega of affection. The naive remark of a 
 child, quoted by Darwin, is true to nature. To the question : ' What is 
 meant by being in good spirits? ' the answer was: ' It is laughing and talk- 
 ing and kissing.' " — Emotion^ and Will, p. 126 sq. 
 
 2 Anciently the brain was supposed to be the seat of intellect, the heart of 
 affection and volition, the spleen of latent- si)ite and melancholy, the liver 
 of valor and choler (x"'^'?, bile), and the bowels {to. airXd'yxva.) of compas- 
 sion. "And Jesus, moved with compassion ((rirXa7x>"0'^«is), put forth his 
 hand and touched him." — Mark 1:41. See also 2 Cor. G : 12, Phil. 1:8, 
 and Luke 1:78, where (xtrXdyx^^ is rendered " tender mercy." Cf. "Thou 
 thing of no bowels." — 'J'roil., A. 2, so. 1 ; cf. so. 2, 11. Pity is still more 
 strictly a sentiment. See § 262. 
 
EMOTION. 275 
 
 Sympathy awakens most strongly towards those we love, 
 less strongly toward strangers, and still less toward enemies. 
 The joys or sorrows of those to whom we are most closely 
 akin, move us most deeply, and in proportion as the points 
 of community diminish, the community of opinions, of situa- 
 tions, of fortunes, in like proportion diminish our sympathies. ^ 
 The opposite of sympathy is antipathy, an emotion of contra- 
 riety, involving disgust and repugnance. It is the positive 
 emotion we feel against foreigners, especially those of other 
 and inferior races, and against reptiles. The pure negative 
 of sympathy is indifference. 
 
 Sympathy is a blessing that gives and takes. Even the 
 laws of common decorum require us to assume at least the 
 appearance of sadness or of gladness, to smile at meeting, to 
 sigh at parting, to be sorrowful in the house of mourning, 
 and joj'ful in the house of feasting. To know that another 
 shares our emotions has an especial charm, whether it be for 
 encouragement in arduous struggle, or for endurance in 
 affliction.^ Thus sympathy lightens distress, heightens de- 
 light, and prolongs pleasurable thrills.'^ 
 
 1 As we like those to whom we are like, and dislike those to whom we 
 are unlike, so kind induces a fellow feeling that makes us wondrous kind. 
 Cf. Hamlet's first speech: "A little more than kin, and less than kind." 
 Sympathy with kind has given us the beautiful words kindness and humanity. 
 "Homo sum, humani nihil a me alienmn puto." — Terence, Heaiit. Tim., 
 A. 1, sc. 1. 
 
 Poetically, sympathy extends to brutes, and even to inanimate nature. 
 
 " Can man forbear to join the general smile 
 Of Nature? The love of Nature works 
 And warm's the bosom, till at last sublimed 
 To rapture, and enthusiastic heat, 
 We feel the present Deity, and taste 
 The joy of God, and see a happy world." 
 
 — Thompson The Seasons, v, 869 sq. 
 
 2 Madame de Sevigne dit a sa fille malade : '• J'ai mal a votre portrine." 
 Dumas fils dit: "On souffre moins en souffrant dans deux coeurs." In 
 diffusing gladness, we give and gain ; in sharing sadness we lessen pain. 
 In short, it is the wedding-ring motto: "Sorrows I divide, joys I double." 
 ' ' .Jede qual wird leichter, wenn man sie ausprechen kann vor dem Freunde 
 der mit uns f iihlt. ' ' 
 
 3 Aristotle quaintly says : " It is not easy to maintain a glow of mind by 
 
276 FEELING. 
 
 The influence of numbers is remarkable. The actor or 
 orator is inspired by a crowded house. Tumultuous applause 
 is infectious, and arouses an enthusiasm impossible in a thin 
 assembly. The devotion of a large body of worshippers is 
 easily worked up by sympathy into fanaticism. The esprit 
 de corps of a regiment, of a political party, of a nation or 
 race, tells with accumulated force. Panic is sympathetic 
 fear. It is wholly irrational, and is greatly enhanced by 
 numbers. A herd of cattle, a mass of people, are equally 
 liable to be panic-stricken. The contagion spreads with 
 wonderful rapidity, and often leads to senseless and needless 
 disaster. 
 
 Since sympathy is an experience of a similar feeling, its 
 expression is the expression of that feeling. We weep with 
 those that weep, and we follow even the pathos of the voice 
 of suffering when we take up the lament.^ Laughter is 
 catching, and when one of a company yawns, the rest are 
 infected. We shrink when we see the incision of the sur- 
 geon's knife ; and a mob, looking on a rope-dancer, will 
 throw their bodies into contortions, and take the posture 
 requisite to save the fall. 
 
 one's self, whereas in company with some one else, and in relation to others, 
 this is easier." — Mc. Eth., bk. 9, t)5. 
 
 In order to sympathize, there must have been a prior experience of similar 
 feelings. The range of experience fixes the range of possible sympathies. 
 Sympathy cannot be wider, but may be narrower than experience. No man 
 can have sympathy, proper, for the pains of childbirth, or the cares of 
 maternity. The timid man cannot comprehend the composure of the cour- 
 ageous in face of peril. The cold man cannot understand the woes of an 
 ardent lover. The impulsive man cannot sympathize with cautious delibera- 
 tion. But one may harden his heart, and contemplate all the ills that llesh 
 is heir to, without a responsive throb. 
 
 " He jests at scars, that never felt a wound." — /?. and J., A. 2, sc. 1. 
 
 1 " Ut ridentibus arrident, ita flentibus afflent 
 Iluniaiii vultus. Si vis me flere, dolendum est 
 I'rimum ipsi tibi ; tunc tua me infortunia la>dont." 
 
 — Horace, ad Pisones, 101 sq. 
 
SENTIMENT. 277 
 
 CHAPTER IV. 
 
 SENTIMENT. 
 
 § 247. The mark of sentiment is rationality ; that is to 
 say, it is correlative to an intellectual intuition, or to the 
 result of a logical process involving pure ideas. Indignation, 
 for example, relates to the idea of personal worth ; and a 
 claim to personality can be made only by a rational being. 
 A being destitute of pure reason is incapable of sentiment. 
 In the passions of a raging lion there is no indignation, but 
 only such emotions as attend anger. It is impossible to 
 insult a brute, but a man may easily be wounded in his 
 self-esteem. Sentiment is the echo of reason. ^ 
 
 We cannot always clearly distinguish sentiment from emo- 
 tion, for the two often coexist and intermingle ; and more- 
 over, sentiment itself, when intense, becomes emotional in 
 character, at least so far as to produce an inhibiting effect 
 on other faculties. But in extreme cases, as between the 
 burst of sympathetic sorrow and the calm though strong 
 sentiment of pity, the distinction is clear. 
 
 A satisfactory classification of sentiments has hardly been 
 attained. For present treatment we divide them into the 
 sensuous and the pure, and subdivide the pure into the intel- 
 lectual and the moral. 
 
 § 248. The sensuous sentiments are those experienced in 
 the contemplation of objects of sense, presented or repre- 
 sented. The chiefest is the sentiment of beauty. 
 
 1 " Pascal definissait les passions 'des precipitations de pens6es.' M. 
 Wundt definerait voluntiers les sentiments des precipitations de raisonne- 
 ments,:' — Revue de D. J/., Oct. 15, '83, p. 301. 
 
278 FEELING. 
 
 We should clearly distinguish the sentiment of beauty, 
 and its objective cause or that in an object which makes it 
 beautiful. An object having this quality is approved by the 
 aesthetic judgment, or judgment of taste ; and correlative to 
 this judgment is the aesthetic feeling, or sentiment of beauty. 
 The cause or occasion is the objective fact of beauty ; the 
 effect is the subjective feeling of beauty ; the two mediated 
 by the judgment of taste. 
 
 Now, with that character in objects which renders them 
 beautiful, we have strictly nothing to do. The matter belongs 
 to the separate and somewhat obscure science of aesthetics. 
 Nor are we here concerned with the judgment of taste, as to 
 whether it be a pure intuition or a deduction from intuition, 
 or whether it be a consequence of experience and associa- 
 tion, or what may be the laws which should regulate its 
 decisions. Though these be psychological questions, they do 
 not belong to the present topic. We are to consider only 
 the feeling, the sentiment. 
 
 It is highly and always pleasing. Perhaps none of our 
 sentiments, unless certain moral sentiments be exceptions, 
 are so thoroughly delightful and have so little alloy. A 
 beautiful object excites the intellectual faculties to a free 
 and full activity, Avhose reflex, therefore, gives pleasure. 
 But many other objects do this, and we should not call 
 every one that gives pleasure beautiful. Yet this is a com- 
 mon habit both in speech and writing. Therefore let us 
 note some limitations. 
 
 We hear of physical beauty and of intellectual beauty and 
 of moral beauty ; and indeed Avriters on testhetics usually 
 pursue the subject under these three heads. Many intel- 
 lectual and moral sentiments are highly pleasing, and are 
 perhaps in other respects similar to the sentiment of beauty, 
 and hence the word is loosely applied to them. But strictly 
 and properly tlie true sentiment of beauty arises only on the 
 contemplation of certain ol)jects of sense, presented or repre- 
 sented. All true beauty is pln'sical beauty, and it is exclu- 
 
SENTIMENT. 279 
 
 sively a sensuous sentiment. Its objects are objects eitber 
 in nature or art, or in imagination. In tbese intellect dis- 
 cerns the quality of beauty, and thereupon arises the correla- 
 tive sentiment. 
 
 Beauty, says Plato, is the shining of the ideal through the 
 sensible. It is a union of the intellectual with the sensual, 
 of the o-eneral with the individual. It is the pure idea mani- 
 fest in material things, or, as Jouffroy says, it is the invisible 
 expressed by the visible. These definitions recognize that a 
 sensuous element is an essential condition of the beautiful. 
 By the union of the intellectual with the sensual is meant 
 the intellectual manifest in sensuous forms ; that is to say, 
 by shape, movement, color, or sound. Take from the Venus 
 of Milo the matter, that is, the marble, with the shape or 
 figure, that is, the statue itself, and preserve only the pure 
 idea — its beauty has disappeared altogether. 
 
 Though sensuous in that it is excited only by objects of 
 sense, beauty is not a sensation. In the absence of a real 
 object of sense, and therefore of sensation, memory recalls, or 
 imagination creates, beautiful objects ; and since ideal objects 
 are faultless, and free from the grossness of reality, the senti- 
 ment, when excited by ideal objects, excels in pl^rit3^ delicacy, 
 and refinement. Hence the especial charm of poetry and 
 fiction, and a superiority of literary over other fine arts. Nor 
 is -beauty an emotion. The irrational brute is believed to be 
 capable of both sensation and emotion, but not of the feeling 
 of beauty, it being experienced only by rational beings. Nor 
 is it a desire, for beauty pleases without interest in the 
 object. 1 
 
 Though not a sensation, the ajsthetic feeling, being sensu- 
 ous, is directly conditioned on sense-perception. But none 
 
 1 See Kant's Critique of Judgment. Beauty tends strongly to excite desire, 
 especially the desire of possession. As it is impossible to attempt a thing 
 unless we beUeve it practicable (§ 202), so is it impossible to desire a 
 thing unless we believe it attainable (§ 255). A sunset sky is often very 
 beautiful, but we have no interest in it, i.e. we do not desire it. 
 
280 FEELING. 
 
 of the organic senses, or smell, or taste, or touch, or muscular 
 sense, can give rise to it.^ This is the more worthy of note 
 since the aesthetic feeling and judgment borrow the name of 
 the sense of taste, and in reference to beauty, we speak of the 
 pleasures and decisions of taste .^ Hearing and sight alone 
 are sesthetic senses ; that is to say, audible or visible objects 
 only, either present to sense, or represented by memory or 
 imagination, can become the basis of sesthetic sentiment, give 
 rise to it, and truly combine with it. 
 
 § 249. The sentiment of the sublime, of the picturesque, 
 and of the ludicrous are akin to, yet differ from, that of 
 beauty. The beautiful soothes, the sublime agitates ; the 
 beautiful attracts without repelling, the sublime at once does 
 both ; the beautiful affords a feeling of unmingled pleasure 
 in the full and unimpeded activity of our cognitive powers, 
 whereas the feeling of sublimity is a mingled one of pleasure 
 and pain — of pleasure in the consciousness of strong energy, 
 of pain in the consciousness that this energy is vain. It is 
 highly probable that the essence of the sublime is the idea of 
 infinity. The indefinitely great, transcending our grasp of 
 thought, suggests, or for consciousness is equivalent, to infin- 
 ity and so becomes sublime.^ 
 
 1 An exception should perhaps be taken in favor of the congenitally bhnd, 
 who probably appreciate beauty of figure given in handling. 
 
 2 Fr. gout^ from Lat. gustare, whence also 'disgust.' Ger. Schmack, a 
 taste, hence a smack, a kiss. Also Geschmack, whence Geschmackslehre, 
 aesthetics, or the theory of taste. The Grk. ai'ffdijais means, primarily, per- 
 ception by touch. 
 
 James Russell Lowell said very neatly : ' ' Good taste is the conscience of 
 the mind, and conscience is the good taste of the soul." 
 
 3 "Baffled in an attempt to reduce an object, such as the extent of the 
 starry heavens, their millennial cycles, or the omniiiotence that projected 
 them, within tlie limits of the faculties by wliicli it must be comprehended, 
 the mind at once desists from the ineffectual effort, and conceives the object 
 not by a positive, but by a negative notion ; it conceives it as inconceivable, 
 and falls back into repose, which is felt as pleasing by contrast to the con- 
 tinuance of a forced and impeded energy." — Hamilton, Meta., p. G29. 
 
 " Ml' qii.T(Iam divina voliiptas 
 Percipit, atque honor." — Lucketius, De Re. Nat., iii, 28. 
 
SENTIMENT. 281 
 
 Of the pleasing sentiments of the picturesque and the ludi- 
 crous it is sufficient to observe that as in beauty and sublimity 
 there is an ascent of the object above a median level, so in 
 the picturesque and the ludicrous there is a descent below 
 this plane of indifference.^ A corresponding contrast exists 
 between the feelings, yet they pass readily and quickly from 
 the highest to the lowest extreme. The painful contrary of 
 the sentiment of beauty is disgust at ugliness or deformity ; 
 but the sentiment of the ludicrous, exciting laughter, is a 
 sort of mental nausea ejecting the logically absurd.^ 
 
 § 250. The pleasurable sentiment of utility is quite dis- 
 tinct from that of beauty, though often confounded with it. 
 Beautiful objects please directly and of themselves. Useful 
 
 1 Unity amid variety is perhaps tlie essence of beauty. But variety with- 
 out unity, if tliere be no discord, is pleasing. Now a picturesque object is 
 one determinately varied, and so abrupt in its variety, presenting such an 
 irregularity of broken lines and angles, that to reduce it to unity is evidently 
 impossible. So, giving up unity, the mind falls into pleasing play amid this 
 variety. In a landscape a church spire is not picturesque but graceful ; a 
 dilapidated windmill is not graceful but picturesque. A race-horse has 
 beauty, but a rough donkey with his panniers makes a better picture. A 
 stylishly dressed lady, however beautiful, is not picturesque, as the fashion- 
 plates prove ; but a peasant or a ragged beggar girl is a favorite subject with 
 the painters. The waste and calm ocean is sublime ; a ship sailing on its 
 placid bosom is beautiful, a wreck upon its rugged cliffs is picturesque. 
 
 - The sentiment or sense of the ludicrous is a highly agreeable mental 
 titillation attending an appreciation of wit or humor. Aristotle tells us that 
 it arises from ' ' some error in truth or in propriety, neither pernicious nor 
 painful " ; Cicero, from "that which without impropriety notes and exposes 
 an impropriety," or from "a sudden conversion into nothing of a long-raised 
 and highly wrought exi^ectation " ; Kant, from "the sudden transformation 
 of a sense expectation into nothing" ; Hobbes, from "a sudden glory aris- 
 ing from a sudden conception of some eminency in ourselves, by comparison 
 with the infirmity of others " ; Johnson, from " a kind of discordia concors, a 
 combination of dissimilar images, or a discovery of occult resemblances in 
 things apparently unlike"; Hamilton, from "wit, which, like a flash of 
 lightning, discovers similarities between objects which seemed contradic- 
 tory" ; Bain, from "the degradation of some person or interest possessing 
 dignity, in circumstances that excite no other strong emotion." Bat Spencer 
 rejects -degradation as a governing circumstance, saying: "There are many 
 
282 FEELING. 
 
 objects please indirectly and not of themselves, but by rela- 
 tion to an end which as means they are fitted to attain. 
 "■ Pvilcrum esse quod per se ipsum, aptum auteni quod ad 
 aliquid accomodatum deceret." ^ Neither conditions, neither 
 determines, neither explains the other, though they often 
 coexist. A Greek column affords both kinds of pleasure, it 
 being both beautiful in form and useful in support. But an 
 object may be useful without beauty, as a canal ; or beautiful 
 without utility, as a cascade. It is sometimes said that the 
 sentiment of utility arises in view of a means to ulterior 
 pleasure. Still it is as remote as ever from the sentiment of 
 beauty. 
 
 § 251. Under the pure or non-sensuous sentiments, let us 
 first note those that are intellectual and not ethical. They 
 are intellectual in that they attend the exercise of our logi- 
 cal faculties in connection with pure intuition, the ultimate 
 basis of all true sentiment. 
 
 The simplest one that does not require a personal object is 
 perhaps the sentiment of truth. This is the pleasant feeling 
 we experience on recognizing that our conception corresponds 
 to its object, that the judgment is true. It is the pleasure 
 of knowledge. It is distinguishable specifically from, though 
 
 instances in which no one's dignity is implicated, as when we laugli at a 
 good pun." The instance seems badly chosen, for in punning a good word 
 is usually dragged down to a base level, or if not, yet wit itself is therein 
 brought low, or at least the punster degrades himself in condescending to 
 quibble. 
 
 As to expression: "The lips are, of all features, the most susceptible of 
 action, and the most direct index of the feelings. If an idea be exceedingly 
 ludicrous, it is in vain that we endeavor to restrain their relaxation and com- 
 press them." — Bkll, Essaij, ch. (5. "During excessive laughter, tlie whole 
 body is thrown backward and shakes, or is almost conv\ilsed, the res]iiration 
 is much disturbed, the head and face become gorged with blood. Tears are 
 freely shed. Hence it is scarcely possible to point out any difference between 
 the tear-stained face of a person after a paroxysm of laughter and after a 
 bitter crying fit." — Dahwin, Ej-prcxninn, ch. 8. 
 
 ' St. Au'xustine in f'nufi'usifois. lib. iv, cap. 2;'). 
 
SENriMEyr. 283 
 
 always accompanied by, a high degree of that general belief 
 which attends all forms of knowing (§ 227).^ In 'iie observa- 
 tion of the facts of nature or art, in the identities established 
 by science, the abstractions, generalizations, inductions, deduc- 
 tions, and classifications that constitute progress in knowledge, 
 there is a keen positive enjoyment, often referred to as intel- 
 lectual delight. Contrary statements, opinions, or appear- 
 ances are disagreeable, operate as a painful jar, and stimulate 
 a desire for reconciliation that greatly promotes the exten- 
 sion and perfection of knowledge. 
 
 The sentiment of truth often rises to enthusiasm, and is 
 attended by a devotion that shows it to be one of the most 
 powerful elements of human nature. Science as well as 
 religion has had its army of martyrs. But the sentiment, as 
 merely subjective, determines nothing in regard of objective 
 truth and error, and men will lay down their lives in support 
 of an error mistaken for truth, as readily as in testimony of 
 truth itself. 
 
 The charm of property is also a powerful sentiment. It is 
 perhaps a greater stimulant to human industry than want. 
 Hunger presses ; but having beckons. It will speedily con- 
 vert a wilderness into gardens. It builds cities, and heaps 
 up useless riches. 
 
 The pleasure of pursuit must not be unnoticed. It is 
 often greater than that of possession. After the chase, who 
 cares for the game ? Suspense is in itself a painful feeling, 
 
 1 Mere belief is not markedly pleasurable. Doubt or uncertainty, when 
 predominant, is an uneasy, disagreeable and painful feeling. We earnestly 
 seek to escape it, and often, when a legitimate resolution of the doubt is not 
 at hand, the situation is so intolerable that we escape by violence, by a 
 plunge into belief, or, more simply, by adopting a groundless belief. This 
 accounts for much error (§ 219). The tenacity with which we cling to our 
 beliefs, refusing to listen to reason against them, is perhaps largely due to 
 our unwillingness to fall into doubt and uncertainty. The transition from 
 predominant doubt to predominant belief is highly agreeable. But probably 
 this pleasure is merely relative, the pleasiire of relief (§ 228). The feeling 
 of belief is one of settled steadiness, with but little of pleasure or pain. 
 
284 FEELING. 
 
 but it seems to be an essential ingredient in the intense pleas- 
 ure of pursuit, for " the end of uncertainty is the death of 
 interest." ^ 
 
 The pleasurable sentiment attending freedom arises upon 
 release from restraint. Consciousness of restraint is painful, 
 it being a suppression of natural energy. Indeed in these 
 opposites we have the recognized basis of all pleasure and 
 pain (§ 228). We speak here more particularly of physical 
 restraint as opposed to freedom of movement and speech and 
 conduct. Confinement is a severe punishment that may 
 amount to torture, especially with the young. The pleasure 
 of release is proportionally great. As liberty is merely the 
 negative of constraint, so the pleasure of liberty is merely 
 relative, existing only by contrast; it is the pleasure of 
 deliverance. When the contrast disappears the pleasure 
 would also disappear, were it not that the fact of liberty sug- 
 gests the positive pleasures of pursuit. Otherwise pleasure 
 is felt, not in the mere negative fact of freedom, but in the 
 free exercise of one's powers. 
 
 § 252. Pure intellectual sentiments that require a personal 
 object are numerous, and as in the previous section a few 
 typical examples must suffice. 
 
 1 Heart of Mid-Lothian, ch. 1. The attraction of a plot, as it is gradually 
 unfolded in a drama or novel, is in an ideal pursuit. The pleasure of field 
 sports lies chiefly in the interest of suspense in pursuit. The search and 
 uncertainty make a charmed interval of delay, and when the game is started 
 there comes a good run. The fascination of gambling finds much of its 
 explanation here, and the more the uncertainty, the more the excitement. 
 In many activities of life the contest pleases more than the victory. The 
 past does not interest, the present does not satisfy, the future alone engages 
 us. " Man never is, but always to be, blest." " Things won are done, joy's 
 soul lies in the doing." — Troil., A. 1, sc. 2. 
 
 " No endeavor is in vain, 
 Its rcwiircl is in the doing, 
 And the rapture of pursuinir 
 Is the prize the vanquished gain." 
 
 So is it in the pursuit of truth. We enjoy the search more than the find- 
 ing. Says Malebranche : "Si jc tcnais la verite captive dans ma main, 
 j'ouvrirais la main afin de poursuivre encore la v6rit6." 
 
SENTIMENT. 285 
 
 The person that excels in power, intellect, or goodness, we 
 honor. This sentiment is somewhat different in kind and 
 desrree from admiration or esteem. Admiration is also a 
 response to excellence, but is more condescending than 
 honor. Esteem refers to the useful qualities of those who 
 do well their part in life. Industry, integrity, and good 
 sense command esteem at least, perhaps admiration, but 
 hardly honor. The opposites are disdain, contempt, and 
 scorn. These, like the ludicrous, have special physical 
 expressions.! 
 
 A judgment of the ability and good will of another toward 
 us is attended by the sentiment of trust or confidence, a con- 
 soling, cheering, and elevating feeling. The reverse judg- 
 ment is attended by suspicion and distrust. Some persons, 
 especially children, are naturally trustful, others suspicious. 
 Faith is a complex feeling, combining trust and belief with 
 hope, which last consists of a desire and an expectation also 
 involvinof belief. 
 
 The sentiment of pity arises in view of another's helpless- 
 ness, trouble, misfortune, distress, pain. It is often, though 
 not necessarily, attended by sympathy ; for the rich may pity 
 the poor, the wise the ignorant, the innocent the guilty, but 
 cannot properly be said to sympathize with them. It is a 
 condescending sentiment, highly pleasurable, but easily turns 
 to contempt. It excites a desire to afford relief, and thus is 
 a source of beneficence. Like sympathy it is greatly pro- 
 moted by nearness of relation, of kind or kin, and then in its 
 gentle, continuous form it becomes loving-kindness (§ 246). 
 As though it were the very essence of our nature, it is often 
 
 1 "The most common mode of expressing contempt," says Darwin, "is 
 by movement about the nose or round the mouth. The nose may be sliglitly 
 •turned up, which apparently follows from the turning up of the upper lip. 
 These actions are the same with those we employ when we perceive an offen- 
 sive odor. We seem to say to the despised person that he smells offensively, 
 in nearly the same manner as we express to him, by half shutting our eyelids 
 or turning away our faces, that he is not worth looking at." — Expression, 
 ch. 11. 
 
28G FEELING. 
 
 called humanity ; and a j)itiless, liard-hearted deed of cruelty 
 we pronounce inhuman. ^ 
 
 § 253. In the exercise of self-perception or introspection 
 (§ 108 S(|.), we recognize as belonging to ourselves attributes 
 which when observed in other persons excite in us the senti- 
 ments of esteem, admiration, and honor, or their opposites. 
 This discovery produces a peculiar effect. There is great 
 pleasure in contemplating our own excellence or absolute 
 worth ; great pain in view of our inferiority or lack of esti- 
 mable qualities. These sentiments are known as self-esteem, 
 self-complacency, self-confidence, self-conceit, vanity ,2 pride. 
 Opposites are humiliation, mortification, chagrin, humility. 
 The pleasure or pain of these feelings is greatly intensified 
 when our character or conduct calls forth open manifestations 
 of corresponding regard from those around us. 
 
 The sentiment of personal honor is at once most powerful, 
 delicate, and sensitive. It cannot be touched in a hisrh-minded 
 person without stirring and putting into commotion his whole 
 being. An appeal to it is sometimes more binding than an 
 oath, and a trespass upon it makes life intolerable. 
 
 The thought of being dishonored by another excites the 
 sentiment of humiliation. We feel as if thrown to the 
 ground and degraded. We are cast down, but not destroyed. 
 When, however, our own judgment also condemns us, the 
 humiliation may turn to mortification. We are then cast 
 down and destroyed, figuratively put to death. 
 
 The sentiment of humility is different from humiliation. 
 It is not painful, and does not involve a sense of dishonor. Jt 
 is the opposite of false pride. It admits of a high estimate 
 of one's self as compared with others, but implies a low esti- 
 
 ^ Pity, tliougli originally the same word as piety, docs not convey a 
 distinctively religious sense. It has been thought that a sort of self-pity 
 explains " the luxury of grief." Kant wondered that there could be " so much 
 kindness and yet so little pity in the world." 
 
 2 "La vanit6, c'est le mal de tons; il y en qui en meurent, mais le plus 
 grand nomlirc en vit." 
 
SENTIMENT. 287 
 
 mate as compared with an ideal standard. When this stand- 
 ard is ethical, humility becomes a moral sentiment.^ 
 
 § 254. Pure moral sentiments are now to be considered. 
 They are pure in being non-sensuous. They differ from the 
 exclusively intellectual class in being both intellectual and 
 ethical. Their essential basis is an intuition of moral law by 
 pure reason ; the cognitions to which they are correlative 
 always involve ethical elements. The vast, weighty, and 
 all-pervading feeling or sentiment of moral obligation, the 
 sentiment of duty, attending the intuition of moral law in its 
 specific applications, may be taken as generic, or as implying 
 the moral sentiments generally.^ 
 
 Inasmuch as moral law unconditionally commands us to 
 perform our duties, implying that we are able to fulfil them, 
 there is attributed to man an absolute worth, an absolute dig- 
 nity. The sentiment which the manifestation of this worth 
 inspires is called respect. One cannot be said to feel respect 
 for another, nor self-respect, except in view of moral worth 
 or dignity. Disrespect excites indignation, leading to resent- 
 ment. Indignation is a painful sentiment, yet as a revolt and 
 self-assertive of worth, it consoles. When respect rises into 
 reverence, the ethical element is not merely unquestionable, 
 but becomes predominant. The reverence we have for Cato 
 is because we see in his character and conduct an embodi- 
 ment and manifestation of moral law. The omnipotence and 
 omniscience of Deity may excite our highest admiration and 
 awe ; but only before the white-heat of his holiness do we 
 feel reverence, deepening into veneration and adoration. 
 
 Another class of moral sentiments arises as correlative to 
 
 1 " The first and last step in tlie education of the scientific judgment," 
 says Faraday, "is liuinility." — See liis admirable lecture in Christian 
 Thought for Nov. 1884, "The kingdom of men," says Bacon, "which is 
 founded in knowledge, cannot be entered in any other manner than as the 
 kingdom of God is entered, namely, by becoming as little children." Humility 
 is the ground (humus) whence all the virtues spring. 
 
 2 On these feelings, see Edinburgh Eeview for 2d quarter of 1883, p. 236 sq> 
 
288 FEELING. 
 
 a moral jiulginent on the agent. This judgment keeps a par- 
 ticuhir action in view, but bears on the agent rather than on 
 the action. It does not rehxte to his general character, but 
 to him as doing some specific act or acts. This agent may be 
 some other person ; then, according to my judgment, I expe- 
 rience sentiments of approbation or disapprobation, exciting a 
 disposition to reward or punish him. The agent may be my- 
 self in conscious action; then, according to my judgment on 
 my own conduct, I experience self-approbation or self-con- 
 demnation, self-reproach, shame, • remorse, together with a 
 sentiment of ill-desert, that sometimes prompts a self-surren- 
 der to justice. If I habitually practise self-excuse, self- 
 respect diminishes, the sentiment of shame is blunted, and 
 the result is shamelessness. This may consist with pride, but 
 not with self-respect. While self-condemnation is a lasting 
 pain, self-approbation is one of the purest and most intensely 
 pleasurable feelings of which the mind is capable. 
 
 Gratitude, the sentiment awakened by the good offices of 
 another, is both natural and ethical, but not necessarily relig- 
 ious. It inspires love, prompting a return of pleasure for 
 pleasure received, and is itself an added pleasure. It enters, 
 along with kindness, largel}^ into the forms and substance of 
 true politeness, and is the special and chief lesson taught by 
 the parable of the Good Samaritan. It is essential in good 
 character and is ennobling. Gratitude to God is its most 
 obligatory form. The lack of gratitude to a benefactor is 
 considered brutish, and nothing is more abhorrent or inflicts 
 keener pain than positive ingratitude, a return of evil for 
 good. This vanquished Ca3sar, and maddened Lear. 
 
 The sentiment of justice, or what is obligatory in the mutual 
 relations of life, is closely allied to gratitude. Much may be 
 and is due to those from whom nothing has been received ; 
 to accord it is justice. Injustice, like ingratitude, injures 
 not only the receiver, but the doer of it. Socrates asks: 
 " Which is tlie greater evil, to do or to suffer wrong ? " 
 
PART FIFTH. 
 DESIRE. 
 
 CHAPTER I. 
 
 ITS RELATIONS. 
 
 § 255. Desire is logically defined as the subjective cona- 
 tion (§ 71). More fully, it is a conscious activity marked by 
 a want implying an impulse or tendency relative to an object 
 seemingly fitted to the want (§ 74). It has two specific 
 modes, desire proper and aversion. 
 
 The relation of desire to the other generic powers is im- 
 jjortant, and should be carefully considered. Let us observe 
 first its relation to cognition. 
 
 Although desire is strictly a subjective state, it is often 
 said to have an object, that is, the thing desired. But it is 
 evident that the object thus spoken of is properly an object 
 of cognition, which being in some sense known, comes to be 
 desired. A thing wholly unknown, neither presented nor 
 represented, cannot be desired. Ignoti nulla cupido. In order 
 to desire, there must be a logically antecedent and causally 
 coexisting cognition of an object, with its correlative feeling. 
 Desire is, therefore, conditioned on cognition .^ 
 
 1 "In cognition there exists no want ; and the object, whether objective 
 or subjective, is neither sought for nor avoided ; whereas, in conation tliere 
 is a want, and a tendency supposed, which results in an endeavor, either to 
 obtain the object, when tlie cognitive faculties represent it as fitted to afford 
 the fruition of the want ; or to ward off the object, if these faculties represrrt 
 
 289 
 
290 DESIRE. 
 
 Desire impels toward the attainment of an end. But an 
 end requires means. Hence, not only is the end to be cog- 
 nized, but the means must be conceived, thus calling into 
 exercise the teleologic judgment. Then the conceived means 
 also comes to be desired in order to the desired end. So it is 
 that desires are conditioned secondarily and specifically on 
 the teleologic judgment. 
 
 An end may be desirable, that is, fitted to excite desire, 
 but if judged unattainable, it cannot be truly desired. It is 
 pronounced hopeless, desire being essential in hope. Hence 
 it is that desire is conditioned also on a practical judgment, 
 that is, on a judgment that the end is possibly attainable. In 
 still other words, it is limited to what is deemed practicable 
 in the future, implying expectation and hope.^ 
 
 Desire has respect to the future alone. I cannot desire 
 what is past, for it has ceased to be ; nor what is present, for 
 it is already in hand ; I desire only what may or can be. 
 Therefore it is definitely conditioned on imagination, which 
 alone represents the future. Moreover, since desires impel 
 to actions, and are therefore practical in character, they are 
 still more especially conditioned on the practical imagina- 
 tion which represents also the means requisite to the end 
 or final cause of the primary desire (§ 202). 
 
 § 256. It is very important to observe closely what desire 
 has in common with feeling, and especially by what it is 
 distinguished therefrom, the two being commonly confused 
 
 it as calculated to frustrate the tendency of its accomplishment." — Hamil- 
 ton, Meta-i p. 572. 'OpeKTiKbv 5i ovk dvev (pavracrLas. — Auistotle, Ylepi i^vxv^f 
 Hi, 30. 
 
 1 To wish has a -wider meaning than to desire. Thej' are often used 
 synonymously, the object lying in the future, e.g. I wish, I desire, I hope, 
 etc., to be there. In other cases a wish relates to what is deemed desirable 
 but impracticable, coupled with regret, the object lying in the past, present, 
 or future, e.(/. I wish (not desire) I had been there ; I wish I were now 
 there ; I wish I could be tiiere. Wish and regret are positive and negative 
 correlatives, e.g. I wish I could go ; I regret I cannot go. 
 
ITS RELATIONS. 291 
 
 and treated indiscriminately, usually under the title of sensi- 
 bilities (§ 225 and § 231, note). 
 
 Both desire and feeling are wholly subjective states, and 
 both are modes of consciousness ; but while feeling is char- 
 acteristically a state of self-consciousness, a mode of con- 
 sciousness and nothing more, desire is a state of consciousness 
 and something more as a specific difference ; it is conscious- 
 ness of a want, or rather a conscious want, together with an 
 impulse toward the object wanted. This want and impulse 
 are wholly absent from feeling. Feeling gives rise to desire, 
 and coexists with it, and is modified by it ; but the intimacy 
 of this relation should make us only the more careful to mark 
 clearly the important distinction between them. 
 
 Pleasure and pain are, on all hands, admitted to belong to 
 feeling ; that is, all feelings are either pleasant or painful 
 (§ 228). But this is not commonly admitted to be a mark 
 of feeling exclusively characterizing it, and so distinguishing 
 it from desire. On the contrary, desires are usually consid- 
 ered as in themselves states of pain exciting an' effort to 
 escape, and their satisfaction is regarded as equivalent to 
 pleasure.^ This view confuses distinct psychical powers, 
 obscures the doctrine of conation, especially of motive, by 
 making pleasure and pain all dominating, and so leads to 
 utilitarianism in morals, and to pessimism in philosophy. 
 
 Yet it seems that a very little consideration is sufficient to 
 clear the confusion. Pleasure and pain belong to feeling 
 only, and so mark it off. Desire is marked by want, a state 
 of unrest, which must be distinguished from pain, implying 
 an impulse leading to satisfaction, which must be distin- 
 
 1 So Kant, as quoted by Hamilton: "We find ourselves constantly im- 
 mersed in an ocean of nameless pains, which we style disquietudes or desires ; 
 and the greater the vigor of life an individual is endowed with, the more 
 keenly is he sensible to the pains. Man thus finds himself in never-ceasing 
 pain ; and this is the spur for the activity of human nature. Pleasure is 
 nothing positive ; it is only a liberation from pain, and therefore, only some- 
 thing negative. The mind is harassed by a multitude of obscure uneasinesses, 
 and it acts for the mere sake of changing its condition." — Meta., p. COO. 
 
292 DESIRE. 
 
 guished from pleasure. Certain feelings, pleasant or painful, 
 excite desire ; certain others attend it ; certain others arise on 
 its gratification. All these must be set apart from the desire 
 itself, as dissimilar antecedents and consequents, and not 
 mistaken for essential characteristics or inherent marks. 
 
 The distinction becomes clearer on observing that the unrest 
 of desire is often attended by highly pleasurable feelings ; as 
 in the enjoyment of many kinds of pursuit, urged by a desire to 
 attain an object.^ On the other hand, a satisfaction is often 
 eagerly sought which, it is well known, will be attended by 
 painful feelings throughout, as in nursing the sick, or engag- 
 ing in a duel.2 Thus the propulsion of desire to satisfaction 
 
 1 See § 251. " Sordet cognita Veritas," says Seneca. 
 
 " All things that are 
 Are with more spirit chased than enjoyed." — M. of V., A. 2, sc. 6. 
 
 " Our hopes, like towering falcons, rise 
 At objects in an airy height; 
 But all the pleasure of the game 
 Is afar off to view the flight." — Prior. 
 
 Says Aristotle : " The end of philosophy is not knowledge, but the energy 
 conversant about i^nowledge." And Jean Paul Richter says : " It is not the 
 goal, but the course, which makes us happy." 
 
 Pursuit may properly be taken in a wide sense as meaning the activity 
 excited by any and all desires. That it is pleasurable is in direct contradic- 
 tion of the doctrine that desires are pains. Pleasure attends normal activity. 
 Surely, desires have a normal action. Dissatisfaction is the unrest of desire. 
 When neither overstrained nor impeded, it is not a painful, but a normal 
 activity. The fulfilment of desire is satisfaction, satiety (from satis, enough), 
 and in it the desire ceases to be. A distinguishable result of pursuit, in its 
 wide sense, is gratification, i.e. my desire is gratified. This generally implies 
 a pleasant feeling, with a continuance of the desire. When pursuit is followed 
 by success, taken in a similarly wide sense, this is often, though not alwa\ s, 
 pleasant. It may be an inferior degree of pleasure, momentary as compared 
 with that of pursuit ; yet there is usually a pleasure in success, experienced 
 though unsought. '' Mais le souffrance empoisonne les succes qiii ne sont pas 
 legitimes." — Coisin. 
 
 -The duellist wants "satisfaction." He knows very well that all its 
 concomitants and all its consequents are painful, yet he insists upon it, and 
 eagerly seeks it. Othello, too, wanted "satisfaction," with all its horrors. 
 Anger, a malevolent desire, seeks its en 1 in disregard of present and prospec- 
 tive pain. The miser in his misery continues to indulge his avarice. Duties 
 
ITS RELATIONS. 293 
 
 often overrides and disregards all consideration of pleasure or 
 pain, either present or prospective, or both. In general, it is 
 true, Ave desire what will give pleasure, and have an aversion 
 for what gives pain; but numerous exceptions in practice 
 indicate that pleasure or enjoyment is only one of the many 
 and various ends desired, and that present or prospective 
 pain is only one of many that excite aversion. 
 
 Another mark of difference between feeling and desire is 
 that feeling, pleasant or painful, belongs exclusively to the 
 present, whereas desire and aversion have reference exclu- 
 sively to the future, the impulse being either to maintain a 
 continuance of the present state, or to exchange it for 
 another. Hence, also, desire is more persistent than feeling. 
 
 Feeling stands related to desire as cause to effect. The 
 sensations of an empty stomach excite desire for food, those 
 of a full one excite loathing. Pity excites inclination to 
 help ; indignation arouses anger ; wonder, curiosity. When 
 there is no feeling, there cannot be desire. In this important 
 sense desire is conditioned on feeling. 
 
 § 257. Desire is the subjective element in conation, correl- 
 ative to volition, the objective element. These complement 
 and condition each other. That the exercise of volition or 
 will is conditioned on desire is obvious. There can be no 
 choice except between desired objects, and no effort except 
 by the impulse of desire. In this relation desires are called 
 motives, being the efficient causes of efforts, and so of 
 actions.^ On the other hand, desire is conditioned on the 
 
 are often irksome, sometimes painful, but we do them. Many men grumble 
 "when paying debts, and perhaps no one enjoys "paying for a dead horse." 
 But why multiply cases? A very little observation would seem sufficient to 
 convince us that we often, nay, almost constantly, pursue desired ends in 
 utter disregard of the pleasure or pain that attends them, or that is conse- 
 quent upon them. Indeed, we look upon the one who merely seeks pleasure 
 and avoids pain, the mere pleasure-seeker, with contemptuous scorn. 
 
 1 A motive moves us. The word expresses the prompting, impulsion, 
 pressure, tendency, propensity, or inclination of desire. These words are 
 originally mechanical. The term motive is sometimes, though less properly, 
 applied to the final cause, the end or object desired. 
 
294 IJESIEE. 
 
 existence of will ; for it implies preference, which implies 
 choice, an element of volition ; and again the impulse of de- 
 sire implies a tension or pressure to an endeavor or effort, 
 another element of volition. Clearly there can be no impulse 
 except in the presence of something impelled. The relation 
 of desire and volition, therefore, is similar to that of feelhig 
 and cognition. They always coexist, conditioning and com- 
 plementing each other. 
 
 It is well to observe that strong will implies strong desire, 
 and weak will weak desire. But strong desire may be 
 accompanied by a weak will, and weak desire by strong 
 will. Strong desires in conflict are generallj^ equivalent to a 
 weak desire, but sometimes in this case will shows an inde- 
 pendent strength in repressing one of the opposites, and con- 
 forming determinately to the other.^ 
 
 § 258. Thus far we have had in view only the rational 
 •desires, that is, desires in which the impulse arouses delibera- 
 tion, involving thought, which serves to guide the choice and 
 effort of volition. These desires are not merely conditioned 
 on the cognition of an object, but they are also regulated by 
 intelligent choice between alternatives. But desires, probably 
 all of them, have also primarily an unintelligent exercise, 
 without deliberation and without choice, as in the natural 
 prompting or propensity of hunger, of curiosity, of anger, 
 and of maternal love (§ 195). The primary impulse, at 
 least, is blind and fatal and unregulated, and the consequent 
 volition is not free, but consists merely of a dii-ectly deter- 
 mined effort. We discover here the class of purely psychical 
 instincts, co-ordinate with the physical and the psycho-ph}si- 
 cal instincts heretofore indicated (§§ 36, 230). 
 
 1 III a previous section it is said that I cannot desire the unattainable. 
 It follows that I cannot try to attain it, the desire being a necessary antece- 
 dent to the voluntary effort. Accordingly, it was said, in discussing the 
 practical imagination : " I cannot even altenipt what T judge and believe to 
 be impracticable" (§ 202). Judging the end unattainable, I cannot truly 
 desire it, and so cannot really try to reach it. 
 
ITS KINDS. 295 
 
 CHAPTER II. 
 
 ITS KINDS. 
 
 § 259. The impulse, tendency, or pressure of desire is 
 either towards taking or towards giving. The want calling 
 for satisfaction must therefore be understood to imply, in some 
 cases, a lack craving supply, as, I want to know ; in other 
 cases, a wish to bestow, as, I want to help. This furnishes a 
 primary division. Again, the desires that crave are fairly 
 subdivided into those that have a physical basis, the appetites, 
 and those that are purely psychical, which we shall call the 
 appetences.! This distribution, connecting with that to be 
 found in § 231, appears in the following : — 
 
 SCHEME OF DESIRES. 
 
 II. Conation. 
 
 1. Subjective conation, or Desire. 
 
 A. Craving. 
 
 (1) Appetite. 
 
 (2) Appetence. 
 
 B. Giving. 
 
 (1) Affection. 
 
 The craving desires incline toward impersonal objects. 
 They urge me to appropriate what seems fitted to benefit my- 
 self, and so accounted a gain. The giving desires incline 
 toward persons. They urge me to bestow from my own 
 resources what seems fitted to benefit another. Let us make 
 a further distribution. The subjoined lists are by no means 
 
 1 Appetence is the same V70rd as appetite, from ad and petere, to seek for 
 (see next note), and has been hkewise narrowed to the same meaning. 
 Justified by its etymology, we nevertheless make bold to use it as the mucb- 
 needed name of the second class of desires. 
 
296 DESIRE. 
 
 exhaustive. They are given for the sake of more specific 
 statement, and as a basis for subsequent discussion. 
 
 APPETITES. 
 
 APPETENCES. 
 
 AFFECTIONS. 
 
 For Food. 
 
 For Living. 
 
 For Kindred. 
 
 Drink. 
 
 Pleasure. 
 
 Friends. 
 
 Sleep. 
 
 Property. 
 
 Country. 
 
 Sex. 
 
 Knowledge. 
 
 Mankind. 
 
 Movement. 
 
 Power. 
 
 God. 
 
 Each of the craving desires has its opposite aversion. 
 Appetite is opposed by disinclination, distaste, disgust, con- 
 sequent generally upon satiety ; appetence also by disinclina- 
 tion, or the more purely negative disregard or indifference. 
 These contraries have not been included in the foregoing dis- 
 tribution, it being deemed superfluous, since each positive 
 implies its negative. Beside the benevolent affections men- 
 tioned, there is a series of aversions, the malevolent affec- 
 tions ; as anger, envy, jealousy, misanthropy, etc. Some 
 further notice of these will be taken subsequently. 
 
 § 260. Appetite is the craving produced by a recurring 
 need of corporeal life.^ Appetites correspond in general 
 with sensations. They are always preceded and attended by 
 sensations as causes. The sensation, however, may exist 
 without the appetite; as, I may feel dry without being 
 thirsty, especially when my attention is otherwise engaged. 
 The sensations that induce appetite belong chiefly to the 
 sensus vagus (§§ 29, 233). When any member of this sense 
 excites in us a want tending to the appropriation of some 
 material thing which will satisfy or appease it, this is properly 
 an appetite. As the basis is physical, so also in general is 
 that which appeases.^ 
 
 1 The Romans and the Latinists used the word appetite as coextensive 
 with desire. Thus Cicero: " Motus animorum duplices sunt; alteri, cogita- 
 tionis ; alteri, appetitus. Cogitatio in vero exquirendo maxime versatur ; 
 appetitus impellit ad agendum." Cf. § 71, note. 
 
 2 Appease, from ad pacem, at peace. Plenty, from plenns, full. Since 
 appetites orighiate in, and are attended by, sensations, their excessive indul- 
 gence is called, in a bad sense, sensuality. 
 
ITS KIJSBS. 297 
 
 Hunger, a desire for food, is rightly the typical appetite. 
 It is due to a state of the stomach. Thirst is distinguishable 
 as a call for cooling liquid in a dry and heated state of 
 the air-passages and skin. The desire for fresh air may be 
 regarded as an appetite, having its origin in pulmonary sensa- 
 tions. Drowsiness, or a desire for sleep, should perhaps be 
 included. These have reference to the maintenance of life. 
 Carnal concupiscence, the sexual appetite, has reference to 
 the propagation of life. It is compatible with sexual love, 
 but should be marked as quite distinct.^ The foregoing are 
 natural appetites, and each has its instinctive, original, and 
 powerful phase. Morbid and artificial appetites are acquired 
 under the influence of habit, and are transmittible by heredity ; 
 as, the appetites for tobacco, liquor, and opium. It would 
 be hard to distinguish from appetites the nameless longings 
 which arise in great number and variety out of numerous 
 subjective sensations, — such as weariness, restlessness, faint- 
 ness, etc. 2 In general, these prompt an escape from pain, 
 and so mio-ht be referred to the class of aversions. 
 
 But moreover, we need light and sound and muscular 
 exercise for health and comfort, and the deprivation of any 
 one of these brings on a disagreeable state of unrest which 
 longs for relief. But this is not strictly appetite. Even 
 taste, apart from stomachic sensations, hardly affords a basis 
 for an appetite. Still, such is the recurring need, and so 
 thoroughly subjective is the craving for physical exercise, 
 that we have ventured to include this in the list as repre- 
 sentative of a large and important class of corporeal wants 
 not elsewhere considered. 
 
 1 To list or listen, Anglo-Saxon lustan, to incline or lean towards ; an 
 expression of desire. Lust means, primarily, desire in general, but has 
 acquired a bad sense ; as, lust for gold. There is a tendency to limit the 
 meaning to the above-named appetite. 
 
 '■' When one wants to sneeze, it has been said, he would rather do that 
 than anything else in the world. Certainly, not for the pleasure of it, though 
 there be pleasure in it. The want attending excrementation in general may 
 be construed as appetitive aversion. 
 
298 DESIRE. 
 
 Besides their physical character, another mark distinguishes 
 appetites from the remaining desires. It is their periodicity. 
 They arise at intervals, more or less regular, and become 
 temporarily appeased and quiescent on satisfaction. Hence 
 the term satisfaction, with its cognates, to satisfy, to satiate, 
 satiety, etc., is better applied to appetites than to psychic 
 desires, which are rarely satisfied. 
 
 § 261. The desires marked in the scheme as appetences 
 are psychic desires. Appetence is the craving produced -by 
 a recognized need of mental life. In a loose and genei'al 
 way, appetences may be said to correspond to emotions as 
 their causes ; e.g. wonder begets curiosity. Like sensation 
 and emotion, appetite and appetence seem to be common to 
 man and brute ; appetites predominating in the brute, appe- 
 tences in man, perhaps because the latter call for higher 
 intelligence. Aj)petence is more persistent than appetite, 
 and is gratified rather than satisfied ; for instead of ceasing, 
 it is often stimulated by supply. Like appetite it is directed 
 to things, or to persons viewed as mere things. It takes 
 the form both of desire proper and of aversion. In the one, 
 it craves things seemingly fitted to gratify ; in the other, it 
 avoids things distasteful. In either case, the attainment is 
 accounted a personal gain. Being cravings, longings for a 
 gain, appetences as well as appetites are primarily altogether 
 selfish in their aims and ends. 
 
 In noting a few illustrative examples of the appetences, 
 we name, first, the desire to continue in life, leading to 
 effoj'ts for its conservation. This has a powerful instinctive 
 exercise, manifest in a blind impulse to self-preservation in 
 case of danger ; but also an intelligent exercise, manifest 
 in careful provision for its needs, and in energetic actions 
 thouglitf ully combined to compass the end. It enters largely 
 into all human conduct, and is so strong that, when life is 
 threatened, it commonly overrides all other interests, and 
 is profou:;d]y oblivious even of duty. The natural terror of 
 
ITS KINDS. 1^99 
 
 death is assuaged by the belief that it is not annihihxtioii, 
 that there is an after-life ; and we are also consoled by the 
 thought that we shall still live in our descendants. Circum- 
 stances may induce a morbid aversion to life. Tedium has 
 already been noted as productive of this effect. " I'm aweary, 
 I'm aweary ; would to God that I could die ! " Hence, and 
 for other bad reasons, suicide. 
 
 We next observe that there is undoubtedly a universal 
 desire for pleasure and an aversion to pain. Accordingly, 
 one is prone to seek things calculated to please, and to avoid 
 those that give pain. In the Epicurean, the mere pleasure- 
 seeker, this desire overrides and subordinates all others. He 
 makes not only his appetites and appetences, but even his 
 affections subserve this end. He desires certain things solely 
 for the pleasant feeling they excite, and earnestly avoids all 
 those that offend, never admitting a present pain except as 
 a means to some ulterior pleasure. Now all men at times 
 seek pleasure merely for its own sake, but in the nobler 
 characters this is only occasional. In general, they set for 
 themselves higher and more varied ends, and pursue these in 
 total disregard of the pleasures or pains that may occur 
 either in the process or in the result. Let it be emphasized 
 that pleasure is only one of the many objects of natural 
 ■desire, and pain only one, and by no means the greatest, 
 object of aversion. There are a multitude of evils recognized 
 as far greater than pain.^ 
 
 Another appetence is curiosity or inquisitiveness, — these 
 words being taken in a wide and good sense, the desire for 
 knowledge. This also has a notable instinctive exercise, and 
 in its higher, intelligent form is a powerful incentive to 
 action, improvement, and progress. It is figuratively spoken 
 
 1 The Hedonists said that pain is the greatest of evils. The Stoics denied 
 in toto that pain is an evil. The Peripatetics, however, allowed pain to be 
 an evil, hut affirmed that vice is a greater evil. This last is more in accord 
 'With the views now prevalent in Christendom. 
 
 01? THE ' 
 
300 DESIRE. 
 
 of as a hunger and thirst for knowledge, which liowcver 
 hxrgely gratified, is never properly satisfied-^ 
 
 Acquisitiveness is the desire for property in things. When 
 extreme, it is called avarice, and, with reference to appetite, 
 greed. Its influence in determining the aL-tivities of human 
 life should be remarked (§ 251). 
 
 Ambition, or the desire for power, is directed toward per- 
 sons, but commonly regards and treats them, not as persons, 
 but as mere things. Napoleon Avas " a sceptered hermit." 
 In its petty forms, as in small politics, it disregards the feel- 
 ings and rights of others, and is thoioughly selfish ; but when 
 regulated by a sense of duty (§ 266) and guided by genius, 
 it commands not onl}- admiration, but esteem.^ 
 
 Sociality, the desire for society, is an approach toward 
 affection, yet views otliere as means rather than as ends, and 
 so is selfish. We are gregarious animals, seeking to consort 
 with our fellows, and to be in the fashion. Ofttimes, how- 
 ever, we find it grateful and healthful to be alone ; and 
 sometimes there springs up a morbid aversion to society. 
 Sociality is akin to sympathy (§ 246). Out of it arises imi- 
 tativeness, a psychic instinct, marked in children, but disa])- 
 pearing with culture ; and emulation, a psychic desire, notable 
 in maturer persons, and increasing with culture. Approba- 
 tiveness, or the desire for the esteem of others, is also social 
 in its impulse. A lack of it is unnatural and injurious, a 
 negative mark of defective character. 
 
 § 262. Affection, or love, is an impulse or inclination 
 toward other persons, disposing us to give out from our own 
 
 ' Suppose some one says to me : " T have bad news for you." " What is 
 it ? " " Be content not to know." " No ; tell me." " It will give you very 
 great pain." " Nevertheless, tell me at once ; I want to know." Indeed, I 
 may become almost frantic under the impulse. How can such familiar expe- 
 rience be explained by those wlio would resolve all impulses into a desire for 
 pleasure and an aversion to pain ? 
 
 2 The famous speech of Cardinal Wolsey, in K. Henry VIII, A. 3, at the 
 close of 8c. 2, is too well known to allow of quotation. 
 
ITS KINDS. 301 
 
 resources what may benefit or injure them. In a loose and 
 general way, it may be said that affections correspond to 
 sentiments as their caiuses ; e.g. pity begets a desire to relieve. 
 They are attended, however, by a special class of emotions 
 (§ 245). The brute is supposed to be incapable of them, 
 except in instinctive or in rudimentary forms, and so they 
 are accounted especially human. Practically their tendency 
 is the reverse of the appetites and appetences, for they do not 
 take, but give. Moreover, they are exercised toward persons 
 or sentient beings only, not at all toward mere things, for 
 they presuppose, not only intelligence in the subject, but also 
 a possible harmony or discord of affection in the object. In 
 pure exercise they contrast with the craving desires in being 
 wholly unselfish.^ 
 
 Affections are subdivided into the benevolent and the 
 malevolent.2 We may call it love and hate. Benevolent 
 affection is modified according as it is consequent upon the 
 sentiments of pity, kindness, gratitude, reverence, etc., the 
 object being esteemed inferior, equal, or superior in its nature 
 or experience. 
 
 Our first example of benevolent affection is kinship, or the 
 love of kindred, especially the family tie. This exhibits the 
 varieties of conjugal, parental, maternal, filial, and fraternal 
 love. It has notably in each case, but especially in maternal 
 love, a strong instinctive exercise.-^ Very often these affec- 
 
 1 Affection, unlike appetite and appetence, has primarily a passive sense ; 
 we are affected thus and so. Perhaps the fact that this class of desires 
 readily becomes passionate, or, more probably, the primarily recipient state 
 of the subject, induced the use of this passive term. 
 
 2 The reader should note the etymology of benevolent and malevolent, of 
 ■benignant and malignant, of beneficent and maleficent. 
 
 3 Some one has well said that labor of every kind is in itself bitter, but is 
 sweetened by love. Even the pains of childbirth are qualified and assuaged 
 by the awakening feelings of maternity. George Sand discovered in herself 
 the strength of maternity, and her best works are devoted to depicting its 
 transcendent power. Sexual love, the commonplace of the novelist, is shown 
 to be light in comparison, and the profound love which every fair man has 
 for his mother is still a shallow depth of what the mother has for her son. 
 
302 DESIRE. 
 
 tions are coraj^ressed, by association, into the love of home» 
 But it is not the phice or home that truly is loved, but those 
 belonging to it. " 'Tis home where the heart is." Affection 
 expands, with diminishing force, to collateral* kindred. 
 
 Another form is friendship, or the love of our fellows 
 whom we like, i.e. to whom we are like in important respects, 
 and with whom, therefore, we agree, or whom we lind agreea- 
 ble and congenial.! Hence arise fraternities or brotherhoods, 
 clubs, societies, and churches. An important modification is 
 the love of a benefactor, arising from the sentiment of grati- 
 tude (§ 254). 
 
 The tribal affection should not be overlooked, notable in 
 clans and clanship. Its strength is best indicated, perhaps, 
 by the antipathy between different races, which, as it has a 
 marked instinctive exercise, seems native, ineradicable, and 
 within limits, justifiable. 
 
 Patriotism, or the love of one's country, has a wider circum- 
 ference and a more generous flow. It embraces fellow-citi- 
 zens, all living under a common government. Anciently it 
 was accounted one of the greatest of virtues, involving hos- 
 tility toward all outsiders as gentiles and barbarians. Chris- 
 tianity is gradually suppressing this hostility in favor of 
 pliilanthropy, but does not forbid strong patriotic affection. 
 This love is not, as commonly thouglit, toward the country 
 itself, which as a senseless thing cannot experience benefit, 
 and so cannot be loved. The love is for the people, and for 
 their sake one labors to improve the government and the 
 country .2 It is by association and personification that we 
 
 1 The variety of cognate terms is worth noting ; genesis, genus, and genius 
 or the divine element or tutelar deity (like enthusiasm, iv 6eb%). More 
 especially gentle, genteel, genial, and generous, of. kindly. Let us add that 
 the genial element enters into all forms of real courtesy, for true politeness 
 is love in trillcs. 
 
 ■- " I call that my country," said .John Winthrop, " wheie I may most 
 glorify God, and enjoy the presence of my dearest friends." — Green's Short 
 History, p. 498. 
 
ITS KINDS. 303 
 
 become attached to places and to things, and speak of loving 
 them, as though they were sentient beings. 
 
 Philanthropy is the love of mankind at large. '■'■ Hoino 
 sum., humani niliil a me alienum puto" called forth the plau- 
 dits of even a Roman theatre. But the brotherhood of man 
 is eminently a Christian doctrine, in opposition to the racial 
 and patriotic hostilities of heathendom. 
 
 The love of God, or piety in its best and largest sense, is 
 the climax of the affections. It enforces and embraces them 
 all. If a man say, I love God, and hateth his brother, he is a 
 liar. We should love God for his own sake, and all others 
 for God's sake. 
 
 § 263. Malevolent affections may be typified by hate, and 
 anger or resentment, impelling us to inflict pain and in- 
 jury.i They also follow sentiments, such as indignation, 
 dishonor, etc. 
 
 Hatred is more persistent than anger; the latter being 
 a hot, transitory passion, the former cold and continuous. 
 Closely akin to these is the savage impulse to revenge, which 
 inflicts injury merely in the indulgence of the resentful and 
 malicious impulse. To avenge is to inflict just retribution. 
 upon an evil doer, and so may be a righteous action. 
 
 Jealousy is consequent upon suspicion, and arises when we 
 imagine that some one is aiming to deprive us of what is our 
 own, and dearly prized. In some natures it needs only '^ a 
 trifle light as air " to arouse the impulse, which readily 
 passes or rushes to a blind and deadly passion.^ 
 
 1 They are all akin to insanity. We say, in common speech, the man is 
 mad. 
 
 2 It is the custom to regard Othello as especially illustrating jealousy. 
 This is questionable. Coleridge, a very subtile analyst, boldly denies that 
 the Moor was jealous. Indeed, his struggle seems not so much between love 
 and jealousy, as between love and honor. Leontes, in Winter''s Tale, is a 
 more notable victim of the passion. Othello has much of our sympathy ; 
 Leontes, we despise. It were curious to consider how much of the purity of 
 society is due to the lurking and threatening of this passion. It is a powerful 
 protective. 
 
304 DESIRE. 
 
 Envy is the desire to reduce another to our own level, or 
 below. It differs from emulation, which desires merely to 
 rise to or above another. This is not malevolent, and is 
 ennobling. But envy, besides being a malevolent and igno- 
 ble impulse, is altogether without an excuse, or wholly evil. 
 Each of the foregoing has its defensive or punitive element, 
 whereas envy is simply injurious. 
 
 Cruelty is an odious malevolence. It has degrees, from 
 mere indifference, on through wantonness, up to the nameless 
 form that finds pleasure in giAdng pain. It is horrible to 
 know that there is ever a pleasurable thrill in the flesh of the 
 arm that strikes a blow, that there are men who enjoy using 
 the whip. Cruelty implies pain ; yet the surgeon is not 
 cruel, nor is it cruel to punish. It is more, too, than giving 
 needless pain. Cruelty is pain-giving trespass. It is the 
 trespass, and not the pain-giving, that makes it wicked ; yet 
 it is rather the pain-giving that makes it harrowing and 
 damnable in the eyes of pity. Like envy, cruelty is utterly 
 without excuse. 
 
 Lastly, misanthropy, or hatred of mankind, sometimes takes 
 merel}^ a negative form by withdrawing from all society, but 
 also may be positively injurious. In the one case it injures 
 by disregarding social duty, in the other by doing violence 
 to social rights. 1 
 
 • 
 
 1 Moliere's Alceste, and Timon of Athens, are fine illustrations of the two 
 phases indicated. The melancholy Jaques was hardly a misanthrope. lago 
 is the incarnation of envy. 
 
ITS REGULATION. 305 
 
 CHAPTER III. 
 
 ITS KEGULATION. 
 
 § 264. Desires often conflict ; that is, the gratification of 
 some one is incompatible with the gratification of some other. 
 This conflict arises between members of the same class, but 
 more notably between members of different classes. In gen- 
 eral there is a conflict between the craving desires which would 
 take, and the affections which would give. In instinctive 
 exercise the appetites are strongest, the affections weakest, 
 though exceptional cases occur. In rational exercise there is 
 recognized a gradation in dignity or worth and excellence, 
 the inverse of instinctive strength, affection being highest in 
 the scale, and appetite lowest. This superiority of affection 
 is due to its having the larger share of the rational element, 
 to its call for self-denial, and to the intimate relation between 
 the exercise of affection and observance of moral law. But 
 there is nothing in the nature of either class to give it the 
 supremacy of control. Hence there appears a need for some 
 controlling principle or consistent principles. ' These are 
 found in the regulative desires (not exhibited in the fore- 
 going scheme) which are fitted by their nature to subordinate 
 and regulate all others. 
 
 It is commonly said that the will regulates the desires, 
 suppressing this, enhancing that. True ; but, as every exer- 
 cise of Avill is conditioned on an antecedent desire, what 
 desire or desires are the antecedents of this special exercise 
 of will, in which it acts as an intermediary ? The answer is, 
 the regulative desires. 
 
 § 265. The regulative desires are two: interest, or the 
 desire for happiness, and the impulse to duty, or the desire to 
 
306 DESIRE. 
 
 do right. The former is often called self-love ; but this 
 improperly confuses it with the affections, or modes of love.^ 
 The latter may fairly be called the moral impulse, but is to 
 be distinguished from conscience. 
 
 Interest urges us to seek and appropriate the means to our 
 own happiness as an end.^ Thus it is strictly egoistic or 
 selfish in its direction and tendency, and therefore intimately 
 related to the craving desires, the appetites and appetences. 
 
 The moral impulse urges us to pay our dues in the widest 
 sense, for this is the meaning of duty, and what we owe we 
 ought to pay.^ Thus it is strictly altruistic in its direction 
 and tension, and therefore intimately related to the affections. 
 
 It might seem from the foregoing that the regulative 
 desires are themselves in essential opposition, that duty con- 
 flicts with interest, and impels us away from our own happi- 
 ness. But not necessarily so. The relation is conceived 
 more truly thus : Interest, seeking one's own happiness in 
 violation or disregard of duty, never finds it. Its selfish dic- 
 tates are misleading, injurious, and wrong, and the outcome 
 therefore a failure. Duty, seeking the good of others, impels 
 
 1 The definition of affection or love (§ 202) excludes the notion of self- 
 love, or love of one's self as impossible, self-contradictory, and absurd. 
 Strictly, there is no such thing ; loosely, it is a synonym of selfishness. In 
 this sense, good usage admits the phrase, e.g. "Thou shalt love thy neighbor 
 as [thou lovest] thyself." 
 
 2 Happiness is harmony between our wants and condition. A utilitarian 
 would define it as the maximum of pleasure, satisfaction, gratification, and 
 contentment in life, implying a minimum of their opposites. See Pope's 
 rhapsody in Essay on Man, beginning : — 
 
 " Oh, happiness! our being's end and aim." 
 Prudence, wisdom, policy, expediency, dictate that we should often forego a 
 present gnitification for a future and greater gratification, in order to secure 
 the maxhnum. 
 
 8 Ought is an old preterite of to owe ; and this formerly had the double 
 meaning of to be indebted and to own, to possess. For example : — 
 
 " Be pleased, then. 
 To pay that duty which you truly owe 
 To him that owes it." — A'. John, A. 2, bc. 1. 
 
 Altruism is from Lat. niter, another, and is in opposition to egoism. 
 
ITS REGULATION. 307 
 
 away from interest but not from happiness ; for in its perfect 
 exercise, true happiness, or what is the same, the highest 
 good, is attained, though unsought. This genuine happiness 
 is tliat defined by Aristotle as "the energy of the soul, accord- 
 ing to the best virtue, in a complete life." ^ It appears, then, 
 that the moral impulse has at least the office of control over 
 interest also, and therefore it alone is rightfully supreme 
 over all desires. 
 
 § 266. What now, more particularly, are the relations of 
 the regulative to the subordinate desires ? The moral impulse 
 or desire to do duty, being altruistic, is in general accord with 
 the benevolent affections. ^ It urges them from their merely 
 natural exercise up to the higher plane of moral obligation, 
 regulating them in due proportion among themselves. In 
 regard of the two lower classes, it counteracts their interested, 
 selfish, egoistic tendencies, impelling them to a disinterested 
 exercise toward a higher altruistic end. For example, interest 
 impels me to seek food, knowledge, property, power, etc., 
 each for its own sake, or rather for the sake of the gratifica- 
 tion it will afford me, the end being altogether selfish. The 
 impulse to duty, in view of the higher end, the good of 
 others, urges me to seek these things in order to increase my 
 ability to serve others, or to use what I obtain in such ser- 
 ^dce.^ When the inferior desires stretch toward this higher 
 
 1 Nic. Ethics, bk. i, ch. 6. " L'erreur des utilitaires est cle s'etre trompes 
 sur la definition du bonheur. Le bonheur n'est pas, comme le pretend 
 Bentham, la plus grande somme de plaisii- possible ; c'est le plus haut etat 
 d'excellence possible, d'oCi r^sulte le plaisir le plus excellent." — Janet, La 
 Morale, ch. 4. 
 
 - Also with the malevolent affections (except envy and cruelty) within 
 certain limits, for there is " a righteous anger." 
 
 3 The gratification of the craving desires is still exiDerienced, but it is not 
 that which is sought. They still crave and enjoy fruition, but crave in order 
 to give. E.g. One desires to win my esteem, not for his or its own sake, 
 not that he may enjoy it, but to be in position more effectually to promote 
 my welfare. Not less, but the more, does he win and enjoy it. 
 
308 DESIRE. 
 
 end, interest or selfishness disappears ; duty and love reign 
 supreme. The process is one of constant self-denial or self- 
 sacrifice, and character and conduct are purified and perfected 
 in the realization of absolute unselfishness. 
 
 § 267. The moral impulse is conditioned on cognition in a 
 special manner. The moral law is an objective imperative 
 discerned intuitively by pure reason as of universal and 
 supreme obligation. Its authority is directed to the will of 
 every person, commanding riglit action. But as the will is 
 conditioned on desire, the behest of the moral law would 
 be inoperative and idle, were there not in every person a 
 desire, however weak, to do right, that is, to obey the law. 
 Thus the moral impulse complements and is conditioned on 
 the intuitively cognized moral law. 
 
 In popular usage, the term conscience is applied to any 
 and every mental exercise connected with our moral conduct. 
 In scientific use, the term is limited by definition to the moral 
 exercise of some one faculty, either of thought, feeling, or 
 desire. We follow Kant in applying it exclusively to the 
 source and condition of all morality, and define accordingly : 
 Conscience is pure reason discerning moral law. In this 
 view, the moral impulse is not conscience, nor is moral senti- 
 ment, nor moral judgment, nor righteous choice ; but all 
 these are conditioned on and consequent upon conscience, 
 the discernment by pure intuition of a primary truth in the 
 form of law. These considerations have led us to the very 
 threshold of Ethics. 
 
PART SIXTH. 
 
 VOLITION. 
 
 CHAPTER I. 
 
 ITS RELATIONS. 
 
 § 268. The fourth and last of the generic powers, complet- 
 hig the mental cycle, is volition or will.^ It is defined as the 
 objective conation ; the faculty or activity in whose exercise 
 mind chooses between alternative actions conceived as pos- 
 sible, and strives accordingly to modify its own state merely, 
 or to superinduce muscular movement. It is the function of 
 the ego to determine the time, manner, and measure of the 
 activity, mental and physical. Not that it must, but only 
 that it may do so. Activities, spontaneous and instinctive, 
 occur without such determination.^ 
 
 1 See § 71. The circuit is in the order of condition and conditioned (§ 81). 
 
 2 See § 52, note. The distinction is merely between the active ego and 
 its activity. It is self-determining. Kant says of man that his will is his 
 very self ; it lies in bis innermost nature ; it is his primary essence, and may 
 be most nearly identified with the ego. 
 
 A person (see the curious origin and etymology of the word) is sometimes 
 deiiued as an intelligent being capable of self-determination. This is insuffi- 
 cient. We should add : and consciously subject to moral law. As conscious 
 subjection to law implies both intelligence and power of self-determination 
 as conditions, these may be omitted, and the definition stated thus: A 
 person is a being conscious of obligation. But this is true only of the imper- 
 fect person ; he only is under law. A perfect person is a being conscious of 
 holiness. The conception of Deity is that of a perfectly harmonious person- 
 ality infinitated. 
 
 309 
 
310 VOLITION. 
 
 Volition or will is, like cognition, an objective faculty in 
 that it is immediately related to an object. The object of 
 cognition is a fact, something to be known ; the object of 
 volition is an act, something to be done. Thus attention in 
 cognition corresponds to intention in volition. The normal 
 aim of cognition is truth ; the normal aim of volition is duty. 
 The opposites are error and wrong. Logic states the laws 
 of thought, and the subjective result of their observance is 
 knowledge. Ethics states the laws of conduct, and the sub- 
 jective result of their observance is virtue.^ 
 
 § 269. Besides the foregoing contrasts, volition or will 
 bears a double relation to cognition. It is superior to cogni- 
 tion as controlling it ; inferior as dependent on it for intelli- 
 gent guidance. 
 
 For any and every action, external or internal, will is de- 
 pendent or conditioned on practical imagination, which as a 
 necessary antecedent represents by anticipation the act to be 
 done (§ 202), For every judicious action it is also depend- 
 ent on a logical judgment, and in case of a means to an end, 
 on the teleological judgment. For every moral action it is 
 furthermore dependent on the intuition of moral law, which 
 furnishes the major premise from which are deduced the 
 specific actions requisite in doing duty. Thus intelligence 
 guides volition .2 
 
 Volition controls cognition in the determination of atten- 
 
 1 Propositions, the expression of cognition, are true or false ; actions, the 
 expression of volition, are right or wrong. The violation of logical law is 
 error ; the violation of ethical law is sin. I cannot believe seeming error, nor 
 desire seeming evil. Truth and right are natural ends, but I may carelessly 
 or ignorantly disregard either, and so incur its opposite. In this sense only 
 can logical law be violated ; but ethical law may be knowingly and wilfully 
 violated, since, unlike logical law, it implies a choice between possible 
 alternatives, one right, the other wrong. 
 
 ' Pure reason is legislative ; it discovers and propounds law. Thought is 
 judicial ; it interprets and applies law. Will is executive of the behests of 
 law. Thus we find, original in the essence of human nature, the approved 
 functions of the Departments of State. 
 
ITS RELATIONS. 311 
 
 tion. That is to say, I am able to concentrate my cognitive 
 consciousness on an object, now on this, now on that. I do 
 so at will, and by the power of will (§§ 87, 89). By this 
 means memory recalls (§ 188), imagination constructs (§ 197), 
 and thought abstracts and elaborates (§ 205). This deter- 
 mination of attention is the special function of will, and it is 
 important to observe that it has no other direct controlling 
 power, which is to say, it immediately or directly controls 
 cognitive exercise by determining attention, and that what- 
 ever controlling influence it has over other activities is mediate 
 and indirect, the medium being attention (§ 229). 
 
 § 270. According to what has just been said, volition bears 
 no direct relation to the feelings. It is conditioned on them 
 only remotely through the desires. It controls them only 
 indirectly by giving or refusing attention to the objects which 
 excite the feelings. The feeling, however, may persist for a 
 time after abstraction from the object, owing to physical diffu- 
 sion (§ 230). 
 
 Volition is directly conditioned on desire, which furnishes 
 motive to choice, and efficient cause to the subsequent effort 
 (§ 257). The volitional control of desire, like that of feel- 
 ing, is indirect, and through or by means of attention trans- 
 ferred to or from desired objects of cognition. A complete 
 withdrawal of consciousness from a desired object at once 
 determines the complete cessation of the desire. The resist- 
 ance to be overcome is due mainly and is proportional to the 
 intensity of the desire, and can be counteracted only by virtue 
 of some other desire with wdiich the will accords. 
 
 § 271. Our experience in first apprehending an object is 
 the product of our constitution and environment, and not 
 voluntary. Also it is true that will can neither cause nor 
 inhibit the rise of either a feeliner or a desire. In their in- 
 cipience they too are spontaneous and involuntary. But the 
 continuance, or the increase, or the diminution and termina- 
 
312 VOLITION. 
 
 tion of the conceptions, feelings, and dispositions attendant 
 on an object are under control according as attention is be- 
 stowed on the object, or withdrawn by concentrating on 
 another. This is subjective control. 
 
 Objective control, or the control of the voluntary muscles, 
 is more obscure. Commonly it is understood that the will 
 acts immediately on the motor brain centres, and that through 
 the motor nerve connections the muscular contraction or re- 
 laxation is produced. But we always represent what we 
 intend to do before doing it. Indeed, this is essential to 
 every intelligent voluntary act (§ 202). ^ Now as there is 
 necessarily an antecedent mental image of the movement, on 
 which idea attention more or less intense is bestowed, it 
 would seem that here also the direct exercise of will is to 
 give attention, and that the physical movement is mediately 
 j^roduced. But the nexus of the mental effort and the sub- 
 sequent physical change is unknown. The action passes 
 beyond the sphere of consciousness, and reappears in the 
 sphere of observation. 
 
 1 See especially the note, on the impulse to realize an idea. On voluntary 
 locomotion, see § 105. The view here taken of objective control, that atten- 
 tion to the idea of the physical action is the immediate act, and that the 
 physical action itself is remote, is confirmed by the fact that should the latter 
 fail entirely {e.g. through unknown paralysis), the volition or action of the 
 will is nevertheless complete (§ 275). 
 
ITS ELEMENTS. 313 
 
 CHAPTER II. 
 
 ITS ELEMENTS. 
 
 § 272. An analysis of an exercise of volition discovers five 
 essential facts, which seem to be ultimate, as follows : — 
 
 First: The idea of something to be done, of an act in order 
 to an end. The act is conceived by the agent as possible, the 
 end desirable ; e.g. making a bargain, or suppressing anger. 
 This is an exercise of cognitive intelligence by means of 
 attention.^ 
 
 Second: An impulse urging the action. Conflicting im- 
 pulses may co-exist. The one that prevails, or that with 
 which the volition finally accords, is called the motive. This 
 is an exercise of desire.^ 
 
 The idea of an act and end, and the impulsion of the 
 motive, are not elements of volition, but are necessary ante- 
 cedents or conditions of its exercise. 
 
 Third: A preference of the conscious ego for one line of 
 action rather than another, or for non-action. This is the 
 exercise of choice or election. 
 
 Fourth : Intention, or the resolution upon choice to do this 
 or that action, either instantly or in due time, according to 
 opportunity. 
 
 Fifth: A nisus or striving to effectuate the choice, con- 
 straining a change of mental state only, or superinducing 
 
 1 The act is properly the object of volition ; the end is not properly the 
 object, though often so called. In order to the effort the act must be con- 
 ceived as possible ; e.g. a sane man cannot try to fly. In the healing of the 
 withered hand (Mark 8 : 1-5) the effort showed faith. 
 
 2 The end is sometimes but improperly called the motive. We should 
 clearly distinguish motive from final cause. 
 
314 VOLITION. 
 
 muscular motion. It is expressed by: I try. This is the 
 voluntary effort. 
 
 Choice, intention, and effort are the elements of volition.^ 
 
 § 273. Choice or election is a phenomenon sui generis^ dis- 
 coverable only within the domain of consciousness, and hav- 
 ing no analogue in the material universe.^ There are two 
 special conditions precedent, corresponding to the general 
 conditions of volition already cited. These are : — 
 
 First : Alternativity of possible actions, implying indepen- 
 dence of objective control or causation.-^ 
 
 ^ The schoolmen distixiguished three movements of will circa finem, — vel- 
 leity, intention, fruition. Also three movements circa media, — consent or 
 the approving the means, election or the choosing the fittest, and application 
 or the using that elected. 
 
 2 Motives in their influence upon choice have been likened to weights in a 
 balance. See Leibnitz in Letters between L. and Clarke, pp. 157 and 165 ; 
 Bayle's Dictionaire, ad verb ; Edwards on Frcedum of the Will ; and Thum- 
 mig, quoted by Hamilton in Held, pp. 610, 611, note. The illustration does 
 not illustrate. It is misleading and false. The movement of a balance by a 
 weight is a case of rigid causation. There is no alternative. The necessity 
 is strict, absolute. Therefore, instead of likeness, there is extreme contrast, 
 contrariety, in contradiction of the very essence of choice (if there be any 
 such thing) which is liberty. It is " Hobson's choice." — Spectator, No. 509. 
 
 Intelligence may fairly be likened to a balance, and reasons to the weights. 
 Intellect deliberates (from de and librare. to weigh, from libra, a balance). 
 It weighs the facts and the reasons with a view to choice or decision. But 
 in using this metaphor we should be careful to observe that weights are 
 causes or forces necessitating, whereas reasons are not at all causes or forces, 
 and do not (except in case of rigid demonstration) necessitate the resulting 
 judgment according to any fixed law. 
 
 =' The outward action may be restrained or constrained. This, in legal 
 phrase, is "positive duress." A man may be tied hand and foot, and so 
 restrained from doing his will. See John 21 : 18. Or he may be overmas- 
 tered, and so constrained to do what he would not. E.g. in taking prisoners 
 during our war, a revolver well aimed was called jocosely "a persuader." 
 But the subjective volition cannot be reached. There is a vulgar saying that 
 "anybody can lead a horse to water, but all the world cannot make him 
 drink." It contains a profound truth. The complete isolation of each will 
 from every other is well wortliy of note. There is only one Being in the 
 universe who can determine my will, and to do so would be destructive of 
 His gift of liberty. 
 
ITS ELEMENTS. 315 
 
 Second : An equal plurality of impulses, counter-checking 
 and restraining each other until a conclusion is reached, and 
 the choice made. 
 
 Over these conditions precedent, deliberative intelligence 
 presides. It considers the alternatives, and gives judgment 
 in favor of one rather than another, but does not necessarily 
 determine the election. It is influenced, but not determined 
 by the impulses. Its procedure is logical, ascertaining what 
 is right, true, best, and therefore most desirable among the 
 impelled actions. The choice made does not always corre- 
 spond with the judgment rendered. That it do so is normal 
 and natural, but not necessary or invariable. For example, 
 shall I go or stay ? There may be many good reasons why 
 I should stay, as my ease, my profit, my duty, and accordingly 
 I judge it best to stay. But curiosity, perhaps, urges me to 
 go, and so despite my judgment I choose to go. Familiar 
 experience of this sort shows that the judgment and the 
 choice are distinct, and that the one does not strictly deter- 
 mine the other. 
 
 Choice or election, let us repeat, is largely independent ; 
 yet not entirely of judgment, which presumes to dictate it ; 
 nor of an impelling desire, which conditions it; but, being 
 variously conditioned, it is free, at liberty between the pos- 
 sible alternatives. This is the essential notion of choice ; no 
 choice, no freedom; no liberty, no choice. The question 
 before us, in the subsequent chapter, is whether there be such 
 a thing as choice or election. 
 
 § 274. We have named intention as an element of volition. 
 Observe the distinction between choice in abeyance, and 
 choice made. In the former, I am vacillating under the in- 
 fluence of opposed reasons and conflicting desires, and then 
 choosing ; in the latter, the question concerning the alterna- 
 tives is resolved, that is, I have resolved, my resolution is 
 taken, I have determined what to do. This, the issue of 
 choice, or completed choice, is intention. 
 
316 VOLITION. 
 
 Intention is static rather than dynamic. It is a state of 
 mind lying between clioice and effort, between election and 
 fruition. Its duration is indefinite. The effort and act often 
 follow the choice without apparent interval, still we call them 
 intentional. But often also, having resolved what to do when 
 opportunity offers, my intention may continue for any length 
 of time awaiting occasion. When this occurs, then, but not 
 until then, the effort takes place, blindly it may be, that is, 
 without further deliberation, and the thing is done. An act 
 is intentional when it conforms to the election. ^ 
 
 § 275. Effort is the remaining element of volition. It is 
 characterized as a nisus or striving, and is the final and com- 
 plete expression of the free personality or ego. It is conse- 
 quent upon and subsequent to choice, effectuates intention, 
 and is an ultimate fact of consciousness.^ As choice issues 
 in intention, so intention issues in attention, whose effort is 
 the immediate action. 
 
 Voluntary effort strives to produce some definite change 
 
 1 We limit the term to the intention to do an act. Good usage speaks also 
 of the intention with which it is done, i.e. the purpose of the agent. This 
 generally is its legal sense. — See Austin's Jurisprudence, Lee. 19 sq. 
 
 It is a common doctrine in Ethics that moral quality lies wholly in the 
 intention. But are we not told : Thou shalt not covet ; and is it not wrong 
 to deliberate between right and wi'ong ? 
 
 The old nuuldle about the proper use of the words shall and icill has hardly 
 been cleared up. It may prove helpful to point out that at bottom viU is 
 active, shall passive. E.g. " I will go to-morrow," is an immediate expres- 
 sion of my subjective activity in the choice or decision. Afterward my inten- 
 tion, under which I am passive, is expressed by: "I shall go to-morrow." 
 This principle solves many of the perplexities clearly. But see the tractate 
 On Shall and Will, by Sir Francis Head. 
 
 ■■^ In the consciousness of effort or strain, we have experience of cause 
 producing effect. In no other case have we direct knowledge of the nexus 
 of cause and effect. In the sphere of observation we liave only succession 
 of phenonu'ua; but because of our experience of power in tlie effort causing 
 change, we attribute to unconditional antecedents generally a producing 
 power. See Mansel's Meta., p. 2.30 sq. ; and Calderwood's Moral Vliil., 
 J). 184 sq. (viX. of 187l*) for di.scussion aud authorities ^r« and contra. 
 
ITS ELEMENTS. 317 
 
 of mental state only, or to superinduce muscular movement.^ 
 Neither result may be attained, but in the effort the sub- 
 jective voluntary action is complete, though the proposed 
 consequents be imperfect or entirely null. 
 
 1 The immediate cause of the effort is not the precedent choice, nor the 
 intention, but that impelling desire which hy choice has now become the 
 motive (§§ 257, 272). 
 
 It has already been pointed out that reasons are not causes or forces 
 (§ 273, note). Desires, however, are causes or forces. But we must beware 
 of mechanical notions, especially in view of the terms having a mechanical 
 origin which are used to express this efficacy, as impulse, tension, etc. Con- 
 flicting desires do not neutralize each other ; they do not disappear like oppo- 
 site pressures ; they are merely a mutual restraint until a preference is allowed. 
 When one thus becomes a motive causing the effort, it is not at all, as in 
 mechanics, a composite resultant of the several forces, a sort of mental 
 diagonal, but all others losing efficacy, the one, the motive of the effort and 
 act, exerts its full energy. This is clearly manifest in persons having marked 
 decision of character. 
 
318 VOLITION. 
 
 CHAPTER III. 
 
 ITS FREEDOM. 
 
 § 276. In respect of the exercise of volition there are two 
 opposed doctrines, that of liberty and that of necessity, with 
 modifications of each. 
 
 Strict necessity is fatalism. This extreme doctrine philos- 
 ophers of the necessitarian school generally reject. Some 
 would prefer that their doctrine should be called determin- 
 ism.i They do not wholly deny freedom, but they give it 
 a special definition. They say the will is free when acting 
 according to its nature, and that it is its nature to be deter- 
 mined by desires. Every scheme of necessity or determinism 
 represents desires as controlling the will, and voluntaiy acts 
 as effects which follow from their mental causes as certainly 
 and invariably as physical effects follow physical causes. 
 
 The opposed libertarian doctrine presents a greater variety 
 of modes. In general, however, it allows that desires influ- 
 ence the will, but denies the determination. It exhibits the 
 will as controlling the other faculties, including desires, which 
 solicit and impel, but do not compel. Desires are merely 
 occasions, not causes of volition. The outcome accords with 
 the desire that prevails, but it prevails only by permission. 
 Thus the doctrine represents the will as controlling desire, 
 and not desire as determining the will. 
 
 § 277. Am I free ? The question is very old ; it is the 
 
 1 Fatalism is a Mohammedan doctrine. On determinism, i.e. that will 
 always is according to its antecedents, not that it must be, which is necessity, 
 see Mill's Logic, bk. vi, ch. 2, and Ex. of Hamilton, ch. 20. 
 
ITS FREEDOM. 319 
 
 problem of the ages, says Hume.^ Its solution has engaged 
 the attention of the best thinkers the world has known, and 
 upon it a vast literature has accumulated. Yet it is a prob- 
 lem unsolved, and seemingly hopeless. An apology, then, is 
 needed for even the humblest attempt to throw light upon it. 
 The apology is in its importance. 
 
 Who, or rather what am I,. if not free ? I am not a person, 
 but merely a thing. If not free, I originate nothing ; I am 
 not the beginning, nor indeed the end of anything, but a 
 mere channel. In that case, too, I am active only in the 
 sense that a rolling stone or a climbing vine is active ; strictly 
 speaking, I am wholly passive, tossed about as the winds may 
 blow. I am not a creator, but a creature of circumstances. 
 My conceptions are impressed upon me, my knowledge is not 
 acquired but given, my emotions are tides, my impulses mere 
 transmissions. 
 
 Kant names the doctrine of freedom as one of the three 
 great ends of philosophy. Does it not,, in an important 
 sense, lie at the beginning of all philosophy ? For unless I 
 be free, there is no pliilosophy. A power to discriminate the 
 true and false is not enough ; there must also be ability to 
 choose and use the true rather than the false. Unless there 
 be this power of intelligent choice, there can be no search 
 after truth ; for search implies freedom. Anything, then, 
 beyond barren rudiments of knowledge is impossible, and all 
 science, all philosophy is an idle dream. ^ 
 
 Moreover, freedom is the postulate of ethics. Unless I be 
 free, there is for me no right and wrong, no duty, no obliga- 
 tion, no responsibility, no morality or virtue, no sin or crime, 
 
 1 " The most contentious question of metaphysics, the most contentious 
 science:'' — Human Understanding, § 8. From the day of Pelagius the 
 controversy has never ceased. 
 
 2 " The freedom of the will is so far from being, as it is generally consid- 
 ered, a controvertible question of philosophy, that it is the fundamental 
 postulate without which all action and all speculation, philosophy in all its 
 branches, and human consciousness itself, would be impossible." — Mansel, 
 Meta., p. 320. 
 
820 VOLITION. 
 
 no good or ill desert ; conscience is a chimera, religion a 
 delusion, and Deity a myth.^ 
 
 A question whose answer involves the answers to so many 
 momentous questions, touching all that is noble and most 
 cherished in ourselves and in our relations to others, is one 
 that cannot be dismissed. It obtrudes on every thoughtful 
 mind ; it will not down. If we would establish our claim to 
 the dignity of personality, it must be answered. If we would 
 have a through-going philosophy, it must be answered. If 
 we would have a theory of morals to guide our conduct, it 
 must be answered. One may be pardoned, then, for asking, 
 " Am I free ? " and venturing to think about it. Let us think 
 closely, moving slowly and carefully where so many have 
 lost the way, assured that a single step in the right direction 
 will be of value, and well worth our pains. 
 
 § 278. An objection to our procedure might, perhaps, be 
 raised at the outset. Has it not just been said that all search 
 after truth implies freedom? If so, then your proposed 
 search concerning freedom must presuppose it, and the at- 
 tempt begs the question. 
 
 The answer is easy. The logical presumption, as we shall 
 immediately show, is decidedly in favor of liberty. The 
 question is philosophical, tlie doubt is formal and speculative, 
 not at all actual and practical, and occurs only in construct- 
 ing a philosophical system. When the question arises, the 
 libertarian, having the presumption, is not chargeable with 
 petition in assuming the I'cality of libert}^ and proceeding 
 upon this, as the condition of all investigation, to examine 
 its logical grounds. 
 
 The objection may, however, be retorted fairly upon the 
 
 1 "The only lihorty that T care a straw for," says Mr Huxley, "is the 
 liberty or freedom to do rigiil. As for the freedom to do wroiij;, anybody is 
 welcome to deprive me of that as completely as possible." This surely was 
 meant for a serious jest, t'oi' it is a self-contradiction, a Imll. In order that 
 ciuiduct ho morally ri.^ht, wrnni;- must be possible. 
 
ITS FREEDOM. 321 
 
 advocate of necessity. If the search after truth imply lib- 
 erty, then you that deny liberty can support your denial only 
 by virtue of the reality of this prior condition. You tacitly 
 claim to be free in the attempt to disprove freedom. In 
 denying it, you assume it. Your proffered argument, then, 
 is an essential self-contradiction, absurd in the very under- 
 taking, ah initio null, whatever be its content. 
 
 § 279. It is a significant fact, admitted by all parties, that 
 every man practically believes in the freedom of his own will, 
 and consequently in that of all other men. The conviction 
 is deep-seated, immovable, and universal, and is the under- 
 lying basis of all human conduct, individual, social, and 
 political. This gives a clear logical presumption in favor of 
 the reality of libert}', and justifies speculation concerning it. 
 
 The necessitarian pronounces the common conviction of 
 men in this matter a delusion. The burden of proof, then, 
 lies in the first instance on the advocate of necessity, and 
 until his argument is fairly elaborated, there is no occasion 
 for counter proof. Then the libertarian, having a presump- 
 tion so strong and well founded, may be content with a dis- 
 proving reply as sufficient to settle the question in favor of 
 liberty. 
 
 This logical situation is so far recognized by the necessita- 
 rian, that at least he accepts the omis probamU, and as the 
 attacking party, produces in the first instance the reasons 
 for his doctrine. 
 
 § 280. Let us, then, at once attend to the argument for 
 necessitated or determined will, in opposition to its freedom, 
 stated as simply, directly, clearly, and cogently as possible : — 
 
 (1) Every change is caused; 
 A volition is a change ; 
 .•. A volition is caused. 
 
 But like causes have like effects. Hence, whatever is caused 
 is determined in kind and degree, or necessitated to be what 
 
322 VOLITION. 
 
 it is, by its cause. Taking this immediate inference as i 
 major premise we have : — 
 
 (2) Whatever is caused is necessitated; 
 A volition is caused ; 
 .*. A volition is necessitated. 
 
 The first major premise : Every change (or event) is 
 caused, is an intuitive necessary truth, known as the axiom 
 of change. The second major is a direct inference from the 
 intuitive necessary truth : Like causes have like effects, 
 known as the axiom of uniformity in nature.^ The minor 
 premise in (2) is the conclusion of (1). There remains the 
 minor in (1) : A volition is a change. Who will question 
 it? So then this process, being a simple and strictly 
 logical deduction, mainly from the two axioms or law of cau- 
 sation, claims to be a close demonstration that a volition is 
 necessitated, or that no act of will is free. 
 
 § 281. To the foregoing argument the advocates of liberty 
 have made various rei^lies. 
 
 Some blindly cut the knot, saying : Nevertheless, in spite 
 of law and logic, I am free, for I am conscious of liberty .^ 
 
 1 Many necessitarians, especially the empiricists (§§ 125-6), do not admit 
 any truth to be intuitively necessary ; nevertheless they hold the axioms 
 here named to be irrefragable. 
 
 2 "Liberty is the consciousness of the ability to decide differently, to act 
 differently. The human will in the consciousness of itself is exalted to the 
 consciousness of liberty. We impute to ourselves in our consciousness liberty 
 of willing. The impulses which operate on our wills present themselves to 
 our consciousness not as coercive causes, but are rendered motives by the 
 soul itself. Thus our willing and acting are to our consciousness free." — 
 Ulkici. 
 
 " Every man is conscious of a power to determine in things which he con- 
 ceives to depend upon his determination." — 1\eii>. 
 
 " The free agency of man cannot be speculatively proved, neither can it 
 be speculatively disproved ; but wc may claim for it as a fact of actual reality, 
 though of inconceivable possibility, the testimony of consciousness." " Man 
 is conscious of his liberty to act." — Hamilton. 
 
 "I desire to thrust out my arm in open space, and my desire is carried 
 into effect. Here is the positive consciousness of freedom. I try to thrust it 
 
ITS FREEDOM. 323 
 
 If this were shown to be true, there is or ought to be un end 
 of dispute. If freedom be a fact of consciousness, then it 
 neither needs nor is capable of proof or disproof; but as 
 original and certain, given in our very nature, it cannot be 
 denied (§ 69). Those who take this high ground, however, 
 are usually not content to rest there, but descend from it and 
 enter with zeal into the controversy, thereby betraying a lack 
 of confidence in their claim. 
 
 And indeed the claim cannot be admitted, the statement 
 is not true. I am conscious of a deep and ineradicable con- 
 viction that I am free, but consciousness of a belief is easily 
 and should be clearly distinguished from a consciousness of 
 the object, of the liberty. The notion of liberty is a pure 
 essential negative, the absence of constraint.^ Now I cannot 
 be conscious of the absence of a thing, but only unconscious 
 of its presence (§ 62). This unconsciousness of constraint 
 proves nothing. Moreover, it is conceivable that constraint 
 may unconsciously exist, I being determined by causes, as the 
 necessitarian affirms, while under a delusion that I am free. 
 But the conceivable possibility of delusion shows that this is 
 not a fact of consciousness (§ 69). 
 
 Let us scrutinize the point yet more closely. I represent 
 
 through a wall and am resisted. Here is the positive consciousness of coer- 
 cion. The idea of freedom is as positive as tliat of restraint, both being, at 
 different times, presented in actual consciousness." — Mansel. 
 
 "The almost overwhelming proof [of necessity] seems, however, more 
 than balanced by a single argument on the other side — the immediate affirma- 
 tion of consciousness in the moment of deliberate volition. It is impossible 
 for me to think at such a moment that my volition is completely determined 
 by my formed character, and the motives acting upon it. The opjiosite 
 conviction is so strong as to be absolutely unshaken by the evidence 
 brought against it. . . . Let us scrutinize this consciousness of freedom." — 
 
 SlDGWICK. 
 
 1 "The conception of liberty is properly negative, as the substance of the 
 conception is nothing more than the denial of causal necessity. We think 
 simply the absence of all that hinders and limits." — Schopenhauer. So 
 also Kant in Bechtslehre, p. 28 (ed. S. und R.), and Flchte in Kritik aller 
 Off(')ihari(7ig, § 2, describe freedom as merely an absence of the feeling of 
 compulsion. See § 251. 
 
324 VOLITION. 
 
 to myself two contrary courses, seemingly possible alterna- 
 tives. I think and believe I can elect either. I am conscious 
 of this judgment and conviction, but not of the ability, the 
 power itself. Can is potential; the supposed election, if 
 ever made, is future, is not yet existent, and so is not a fact 
 of consciousness (§ 60). Having decided which to take, I 
 am not conscious that I could have chosen the other, for the 
 act is past; is no longer existent (§ 61).^ While actually 
 and now deciding for this course rather than that, evidently 
 I am. not conscious I might be choosing otherwise, since it, 
 too, is non-existent.2 Therefore, "the power of contrary 
 choice " (a famous phrase, which taken strictly is in itself 
 absurd) is not, on any interpretation, a fact of consciousness. 
 
 § 282. Other libertarians cut the knot openly. Allowing 
 the law of causation to be positive dictum of intelligence, 
 they find themselves compelled, in order to escape the conse- 
 quences of this doctrine, to deny that the law, though uni- 
 versal in form, should be allowed as universal in fact. 
 Admitting its application to other mental modes, they would 
 exempt volition. They hold volition to be a cause that is 
 not an effect, an uncaused cause, a free cause, an absolute 
 beginning, a power of absolute origination. This they grant 
 is wholly inconceivable ; that by a necessity of thought every 
 so-called origination is only an apparent, not a real, com- 
 mencement; that we cannot conceive an absolute beginning; 
 that we cannot, therefore, conceive a free volition. Never- 
 theless, volition is free.^ 
 
 1 " In the idea that instead of the prevailinc; impulse another might liave 
 determined the will lies the consciousness of lilKTty." — Windt. 
 
 2 " Telle est la nature de ma voluntfi qu'en faisant une chose elle a la 
 conscience de pouvior faire le contraire." — Cousin. 
 
 8 " Will is that kind of causality attributed to living agents, in so far as 
 they are possessed of reason ; and freedom is such a property of that causal- 
 ity as enables them to originate events independently of foreign causes deter- 
 mining it We can tliink of but two kinds of causality with respect to 
 
 that which happens, — causality according to nature, and causality derived 
 
ITS FREEDOM. 325 
 
 Upon what ground they thus subordinate the law of causa- 
 tion to the doctrine of liberty does not appear. To derogate, 
 in the interest of the latter, from the strict universality of 
 the former, seems quite arbitrary, a rather violent exercise 
 of freedom. But to exempt the phenomena of volition from 
 causality cannot be valid, for this represents mind itself as a 
 complement of contradictions. Moreover, the law, as neces- 
 sary axiomatic truth, is essentially and strictly universal, and 
 to affirm an exception to an axiom is to affirm, not what is 
 merely incomprehensible, but what is self-contradictory and 
 absurd.^ 
 
 § 283. Another proposed escape from the grip of the logic 
 of necessity admits that mental states are caused, but insists 
 that the law is modified in its application to mental phe- 
 nomena, more particularly to volition. We are told that 
 while causation operates both in the sphere of matter and of 
 mind with certainty and unvarying uniformity, yet in its 
 mode of exercise in the two spheres there is a wide difference. 
 In this difference is discovered a modification of the law, and 
 such a modification as provides for freedom.^ 
 
 from liberty. By liberty I understand the ability to originate of our- 
 selves. . . . Reason gives the idea of a spontaneity which can of itself begin 
 to act, without needing the precedence of any other cause to determine it to 
 action in accordance with the law of causal connection. On this transcen- 
 dental idea of liberty is grounded the practical notion of it, and the transcen- 
 dental creates in the practical that precise element of difficulty which has 
 always surrounded the question whether liberty is possible." — Kaxt. 
 
 1 " A free will would then be one which is not determined by grounds, is 
 consequently determined by nothing whatever, and whose individual acts 
 originate in itself absolutely and in a completely original way. But all 
 clear thinking is quenched by this conception, the conception of the liherum 
 arbitrium indifferentice, and yet this is the only clearly defined, fixed, and 
 decided conception of what is styled liberty of will. To maintain that to a 
 particular man, in a particular set of circumstances, two conflicting modes 
 of acting are possible is perfectly absurd." — Schopenhauer. 
 
 2 " It has been tacitly assumed that if the will is free, in the sense of being 
 superior to motives, it must be so by superiority to the law of causality also, 
 although such a view really violates the nature of the problem, and that to 
 
326 VOLITION. 
 
 I would be glad to see a statement of the law in its modi- 
 fied form. I must confess I do not understand what may be 
 meant by a modified axiom. One may be variously expressed, 
 but in substance it is- adamant, or else not an axiom. Nor 
 do I understand any better what may be meant by a modified 
 application of an axiom. Wherein it applies, it must apply 
 in like manner to all. Within its sphere, it is not only unal- 
 terable but universal, else it is not intuitive truth. It is 
 freely granted that mental phenomena are Avidely different 
 from physical phenomena ; but do they not undergo change ? 
 Is not a volition a change, an event, something that happens 
 or occurs or takes place? If so, then volition is caused. 
 There seems no escape from this conclusion. No juggling 
 with words, or twisting of the axiom will avail beyond mak- 
 ing a temporar}^ cuttle-fish darkness. 
 
 But it is the law of uniformity especially that is thought 
 to be inapplicable strictly to mind. It is alleged that the 
 exercise of volition is very variable, sometimes amounting to 
 mere caprice ; that while volition is truly caused, it is not 
 true of it that like causes always produce like effects ; that 
 under the influence of different circumstances like causes 
 produce in volition various effects. To this we reply that 
 any circumstance which has any influence whatever is a part 
 
 the extent of making it irrational. For whatever be the nature of the prob- 
 lem, it certainly does not stand thus : Is volition an uncaused event '• Are 
 there facts in consciousness which cannot be attributed to any cause ? " 
 
 " The theory [of necessity] must be tested by an examination of the facts 
 of consciousness, with the view of ascertaining the laws of exercise applying 
 to mental causes or forces. And when we thus pass from the physical to the 
 mental, we at once recognize a complete difference in the laws of exercise 
 governing the forces of the two spheres. There is much which is common to 
 both. Effects ' certainly and invariably ' follow their causes in both spheres. 
 In both, causes are as invariable in their nature, and as certain in their 
 results. But there is an essential difference between the mental and the 
 physical. There is in the mental world an adjustment of forces, which is 
 not found in the material world, except wlicn man interposes to make the 
 adjustment. . . . There are facts which go to show that causality in mind 
 is not exactly analogous with causality in matter." — Caldekwoou. 
 
ITS FREEDOM. 327 
 
 of the cause, and the varying effect is due to variety in the 
 cause. If like causes do not always produce like effects, 
 then we must give up our axiom. Shall we do so ? Is it 
 not far more rational to conclude that the lack of uniformity 
 in volition is only apparent, and that a thorough investiga- 
 tion of the causes affecting it would bring to liglit a perfect 
 uniformity of exercise? Why or how volition should be 
 exempt from the law in all its rigidity and universality is hard 
 to see. In external nature there is a similar apparent lack 
 of uniformity in complex cases, but the physicist proceeds 
 with unwavering faith, or rather with clear certainty, upon 
 the principle of uniformity, to evolve simplicity out of com- 
 plexity, and to reduce multiplicity and variety to scientific 
 unity. Unless the same process be applicable to human 
 nature, if to be free is to be lawless, a science of mind would 
 seem impossible. 
 
 § 284. There remain two extreme views to be noticed. 
 The first would escape the argument for necessity by deny- 
 ing that the law of causation is applicable at all to mental 
 phenomena. It is said that causation belongs to the material 
 universe, spontaneity to the spiritual universe. Spontaneity 
 is described, not as obscure causation, but as an acting from 
 internal rather than from external force, as a property which 
 accounts for changes arising under influence perhaps, but not 
 caused. It is contrasted Avith uniform play of fixed law in 
 the physical world. Causation is the law of connection be- 
 tween phj^sical facts ; spontaneity is the ground of connection 
 between mental facts. These two sets of facts are as distinct 
 in their dependencies as in the fields in which they occur, 
 and the law governing the one is not to be transferred to the 
 other.i 
 
 i"All pure intellectual action is spontaneous, beyond causation, and 
 ready to be played upon by the will. The feelings, intellectual and spiritual, 
 are also spontaneous, that is, referable to powers of mind and not to phys- 
 ical forces. . . . The actions of the mind, though free, first through its 
 spontaneous powers, and second through its choices, none the less stand in 
 
328 VOLITION. 
 
 With reference to this denial that causation applies to the 
 mental sphere, let us ask: Is not the rap of a gavel the 
 cause of attention ? Is not light the cause of vision ? And 
 on the other hand : Is not grief the cause of tears ? Is not 
 anger the cause of strife ? It would seem here beyond ques- 
 tion that a physical force causes a mental state ; and on the 
 other hand, that a mental state causes physical change. 
 Causation, then, connects the two spheres, and if in the one 
 case a mental state is an effect, and in the other a cause, how 
 can it be said that causation does not apply to mind ? Can it 
 be true that causation enters in upon mind, and departs from 
 mind, and yet does not apply within mind ? Does not the 
 thought of St. George cause me to think of the dragon ? Is 
 not pleasure a cause of love ; pain a cause of aversion ? If 
 these be not causal relations, I know not what to call them, 
 or what law regulates them ; for the law of spontaneity, as 
 distinguished from causation, has not, so far as I know, been 
 formulated. It is freely granted that mental forces and 
 physical forces are very widely different species, but they 
 seem to be of the same genus ; they are all forces, for to 
 their action are attributed changes, and that is the meaning 
 of force.i That a mental impulse causes mental change is 
 
 determinate constitutional relations, and remain to be operated under i,lieir 
 appropriate laws. . . . There is order that is not causal order, to wit, thought 
 order, emotional order. . . . "Will is germinant, the only germinant thing in 
 the universe ; all else is flow. Liberty is spontaneity exercised in choice. 
 Spontaneity is self-centered power as opposed to transmitted power. On 
 spontaneity rests the potential — what can be as opposed to what uuist 
 be." — Bascom. 
 
 "The human will, as the power of self-manifestation, self-assertion, and 
 self-determination, is simply the highest grade of that spontaneity which 
 pertains to every living being." — Ulrici. 
 
 "Personality, the metaphysical ego, possesses a spontaneous originating 
 force, and accepts or declines the motions suggested by desire or impulse, 
 substituting for them its own autocratic veto or t'o?o." — West. Bev., -Tuly, 
 1882, p. 64. 
 
 1 " La force proprement dite, c'est ce qui rfigit les actes, sans rfigler les 
 voluntes." — Comte. 
 
ITS FREEDOM. 329 
 
 hardly less true than that a physical impulse causes physical 
 
 cliange. 
 
 It should be observed in general, and very suitably in this 
 connection, that in perception an objective fact is known 
 only by virtue of a subjective phenomenon. The change 
 within us is attributed to a cause without us precisely for the 
 reason that we know the change must have had a cause, and 
 we know of none within producing it. When successive 
 subjective phenomena, as for example the effects on me of 
 lightning and thunder, seem to have no subjective causal 
 connection, we posit an objective causal connection between 
 the objective facts. When successive subjective phenomena 
 seem related as cause and effect, we do not seek an external 
 explanation, and do not call the act perception. Hence 
 mental phenomena are the primordial, fundamental phe- 
 nomena, and perhaps in strictness the only plienomena. 
 Subjective changes alone are known immediately ; all others 
 are inferred from these. It follows that the law of causation 
 applies originally and primarily to mind, and if there be any 
 transference of it, this does not take place from the physical 
 to the mental sphere, but rather from the mental to the physi- 
 cal, and it is a law of mind that is applied in explaining the 
 facts of the external world. 
 
 § 285. At an opposite extreme from the foregoing is the 
 view of those who grant the causal relation throughout all 
 mental activities, and seek to save liberty and responsibility 
 by the definition that he is free who is not hindered or pre- 
 vented from acting according to his nature.^ This is called 
 free agency as distinguished from free will. In a free 
 
 1 u 
 
 • By freedom or liberty in an agent is meant being free from hindrance 
 or impediment in the way of doing or conducting, in any respect, as he 
 ^ills."_ Edwards. Tliis definition is used also by some of the most rigid 
 necessitarians ; e.g. "By liberty we can only mean a power of acting, or not 
 acting, according to the determination of the will." — Hume. "Liberty is 
 the absence of all the impediments to action that are not contained in the 
 nature and intrinsical quality of the agent." — Hobbes. 
 
330 VOLITION. 
 
 agent, desires are motives which cause or excite volition. 
 An object awakens a desire which, as a motive, arouses voli- 
 tion, and an action is the result. When desires conflict, the 
 strongest prevails. Self-determination is a conception which 
 is self-contradictory. Liberty and necessity are not opposed 
 to each other, but may coexist. 
 
 We have here a definition of liberty different from that 
 under which we have been working. It is, indeed, justified 
 by usage. We say that the emancipated slave is free, that 
 an unbridled horse is at liberty, that a plant grows freely in 
 its native wilds, and that a machine is free to move when the 
 stay is withdrawn. That I am, ordinarily, in this sense, free, 
 no one can deny. It is, however, a freedom not from antece- 
 dent determinants, but from subsequent impediments ; not a 
 subjective, but an objective liberty ; a liberty not found in the 
 internal exercise of the will, but in its external exercise, in 
 the carrying-out its intent ; a merely functional liberty which 
 it has in common with the automaton. Such liberty is 
 entirely consistent with causal necessity.^ 
 
 But the liberty which is essential to j)ersonality and 
 responsibility is quite another thing. It is not the absence 
 of restraint, but the absence of constraint ; not the absence 
 of subsequent hindrance or prevention, but the absence of 
 antecedent compulsion or coercion. Those who advocate the 
 scheme of free agency allow causal constraint or compulsion, 
 and are content with functional liberty. They invert or per- 
 vert the definition of liberty as applied to the human will ; 
 for a free-will, as distinguished from the bond-will of the 
 necessitarian, is not a will free to act according to its nature, 
 
 1 Objective freedom is the absence of objective preventing cause. Subjec- 
 tive freedom is the absence of subjective constraining cause. 
 
 Tlie compromising sclieme of free agency fails to save the responsibility 
 of the agent. Liberty to do what I intend, or hindrance, may indeed involve 
 the re.sponsibility of another who lets, provided he be thoroughly free ; but 
 it cannot involve mine, since my act, as to its moral quality, i.s complete 
 subjectively in my intention. If this be necessitated, I am not responsible, 
 the act has no moral quality. 
 
ITS FREEDOM. 331 
 
 that is, free from impediments in accomplishing its intent, 
 but a will whose nature it is to act freely, that is, free from 
 determinants in forming its intent. The question in dispute 
 is whether, in this sense, I am free. Functional freedom is 
 granted, of course, as prerequisite ; but am I free from causal 
 constraint or determination ? ^ 
 
 The scheme of free agency is manifestly the scheme of 
 necessity in disguise. It accepts the necessitarian logic as 
 conclusive, but by means of a modified definition it appropri- 
 ates the libertarian terminology. This merely verbal inver- 
 sion avails nothing. It leaves the causal ai'gument for neces- 
 sity unscathed, untouched.^ 
 
 1 The following definition of liberty, by the prince of modern necessita- 
 rians, is unexceptionable : " That being alone can be called free which exists 
 solely from the necessity of its nature, and is determined by itself alone to 
 action." — Spixoza. The term "necessity" here means merely functional 
 necessity, which is properly only a limitation, not a constraint or coercion. 
 That is to say, every being in its normal action is limited to the performance 
 of its natural functions. Necessity in this sense is not inconsistent with 
 causal liberty, as shown in the following: "Absolute liberty consists with 
 absolute necessity. In God we can think of no act which does not proceed 
 from the internal necessity of His nature. Such an act also is the original 
 one of man's self -consciousness ; it is absolutely free, for it is determined by 
 nothing external to the ego ; it is absolutely necessary, for it proceeds from 
 the internal necessity of the nature of this ego. . . . That only is free which 
 acts in accordance with the laws of its own essential nature, and is deter- 
 mined by nothing else, either within itself or exterior to itself. Hence the 
 individual act is the result of the free essential nature, and thus results of 
 necessity." — Schelling. Let us add that functional necessity and func- 
 tional liberty are the positive and negative views of one and the same 
 limitation. 
 
 It is causal necessity, or the presence of causal constraint, which is denied 
 by the advocates of free-will. It is inconsistent with and in strict opposition 
 to causal liberty, or the absence of causal constraint. Its definition is fairly 
 stated in the following : ' ' That being is necessitated or coerced which is 
 determined by another as to a definite mode of its existence and action." — 
 Spinoza. 
 
 Much confusion in the controversy has arisen from a neglect of the dis- 
 tinction between the functional and the causal. 
 
 2 Relative to this famous scheme of Jonathan Edwards, we would refer to 
 the counter treatise of Roland G. Hazard, of Rhode Island, and especially 
 to that of Albert T. Bledsoe, formerly of the University of Virginia. 
 
332 VOLITION. 
 
 § 286. The Alps cannot be overturned. Tlie axioms of 
 change and uniformity are steadfast and eternal. The ar- 
 gument for necessity is impregnable at these points, and 
 so far is demonstrative. Yet it seems that libertarians have 
 constantly tried either to set aside or to undermine these 
 intuitive truths.^ For our part, we shall not break a lance 
 against their iron front. Let us seek elsewhere a point of 
 attack. On looking at the first minor premise in the necessi- 
 tarian argument as stated in § 280, we observe that it is not 
 an axiom. It reads : A volition is a change. Clearly this is 
 not an intuitive truth, though it seems obviously, palpably 
 true, and is usually at once admitted as quite unquestion- 
 able. But perhaps here is a joint in the harness. Let us 
 examine it; for if the argument be vulnerable, it is vulner- 
 able only here. 
 
 A volition or complete act of will consists, by general con- 
 sent, of at least two clearly distinct elements, choice and 
 effort. As these are not mutually conditioned, but each is 
 operative alone, it is evident that they should be used in tlie 
 argument, not conjointly, but separately. If we ask, then, 
 respecting effort, considered not as a force, but as a conscious 
 act, a phenomenon : Is it a change ? the answer that it is 
 consciously a change or event seems the only one that can be 
 given. It follows that it is caused, and so necessitated, or 
 not fi-ee. Hence liberty is not to be found in this component 
 of volition. 
 
 Let us settle at once the causal relations involved. The 
 effort is obviously the cause directly of voluntary attention, 
 and more remotely of muscular motion ; but the cause of the 
 effort is not quite so clear. Setting aside certain physical 
 strivings, which, though mere reflex physical acts, are often 
 
 ^ The empiricists are commonly necessitarians ; the Intuitionists, liberta- 
 rians. The former could consistently be libertarians by denying the univer- 
 sality of the axioms and claiming freedom to be an exceptional experience. 
 But how can the intuitionist consistently avoid being a necessitarian, holding, 
 as he does, to the strict universality of intuitive truth ? 
 
ITS FREEDOM. 333 
 
 spoken of as involuntary efforts, and limiting ourselves to 
 effort as implying mental determination, we observe that it 
 is caused directly, immediately by the prevailing desire or 
 motive (§ 257). This becomes apparent when we consider 
 that the appetites often operate instinctively and blindly, 
 that is, without hesitation, consideration, or deliberation, im- 
 pelling towards gratification, causing an effort to appropriate 
 their satisfying objects. Such acts are unintelligent. Let 
 us particularly remark the absence of any intelligent choice, 
 the guide being natural instinct or ingrained habit. Again, 
 we observe that higher desires conditioned on intelligence, 
 such as anger or curiosity, sometimes act as instinctive 
 impulses, directly causing a strenuous effort to attain their 
 objects, without any pause of deliberation, without any note 
 of an alternative, ^^ithout any exercise of choice. There are 
 many cases, then, which agree only in the presence of ante- 
 cedent desire and subsequent effort. On the other hand, we 
 observe that whenever there is strictly no desire, there is no 
 effort. Hence, by the double method of agreement and dif- 
 ference, we may inductively infer that desire is the cause, 
 and the only cause, of effort.^ Desires whose gratifications 
 are inconsistent restrain each other until preference is given 
 (§ 275, note). And when alternative means to a desired 
 end are contemplated, the effort is thereby suspended until 
 choice of the means is made. But when the desire is not 
 hindered, its direct effect is voluntary effort. 
 
 § 287. We will now attend to the other element of voli- 
 tion, choice. Making this the minor term of the first syllo- 
 gism in § 280, we have : Choice is a change, or event ; and 
 must conclude : Choice is necessitated. 
 
 But let us consider for a moment the character of the 
 notion choice, that is, the election of one of two available 
 alternatives (§ 273). Its very essence is freedom. A free 
 choice is a pleonastic phrase ; a constrained choice is a 
 
 1 For the method, see Mill's Logic, bk. ill, ch. 8, § 4. 
 
334 VOLITION. 
 
 contradiction in terms. No liberty, no choice ; no choice, 
 no liberty. The question is not whether I am free in choos- 
 ing, which is a confusion of words, but whetlier there be 
 really such a thing as choice. It is conceded that if there 
 be liberty, it is to be found only in this residue, for all other 
 mental states are caused. But is there a residue? Is not 
 what we call choice only a delusive notion? Is choice real? 
 To grant that it is, is to grant liberty. To deny liberty, is to 
 deny choice. 
 
 Now the argument against liberty should not grant in a 
 premise what it proposes to disprove ; it should not say that 
 choice is a change, thereby admitting that there is such a 
 thing as choice and liberty. It should premise hypothetically, 
 thus : If there be choice, it is a change ; and conclude thus : 
 If there be choice, it is necessitated ; and then add : But 
 this consequent is absurd ; choice cannot be necessitated, and 
 therefore choice is not, there is no such thing. 
 
 This logical form is unexceptionable, but the truth of the 
 conclusion depends upon the truth of the j^remise : If there 
 be choice, it is a change. This premise we nov/' deny, say- 
 ing : Though there be choice, it is not a change. If we can 
 establish this denial, the stubborn argument for necessity 
 becomes worthless because of a false premise, and its boasted 
 conclusion falls away unproved. Moreover, a proof that 
 a choice is not a change will place choice wholly outside 
 the category of causation, entirely beyond the reach of any 
 causal argument whatever. Unless this be done, there is no 
 escape from the logic of necessity. 
 
 § 288. To avoid confusion we must distinguish the act 
 from the fact, the doing from what is done. The distinction 
 is nice, but real. In what is called choosing, a mental mode 
 appears in, and then disappears from, consciousness ; it is a 
 psychical phenomenon. As a mental act, then, a choice is 
 a change, is an event, and therefore is caused, is necessitated. 
 That is to say, I am caused to choose. In all cases wherein 
 
ITS FBEEDOM. 335 
 
 a supposed alternative is presented, that fact necessitates 
 that there be a choice, though not at all what the choice 
 shall be, not at all which alternative shall be elected. Not 
 always between two positive contrary alternatives am I 
 necessitated to choose ; I may reject both ; but between every 
 positive and its contradictory negative lies an alternative 
 must. I must go or stay, I must accept or decline, I must 
 turn aside or not, I must act or not act ; there is no middle 
 between A and non-A. So the mere presence of recognized 
 alternatives determines that I must choose. Even " not to 
 decide is to decide," as Bacon says; that is, I practically 
 choose to let things take their own course .^ 
 
 But between this constrained act of choosing and the sub- 
 sequent effort to realize it, lies the choice as made, the 
 intention. Evidently the choosing as an act is to be dis- 
 tinguished from the choice as a fact. That I decide is an 
 act ; that my decision is to do this rather than that is merely 
 a fact. I must decide, must elect, but whether my election 
 shall fall on this or that is quite another thing. The mak- 
 ing an election is a movement forward under causal in- 
 fluence ; the election itself is not a movement forward, but 
 merely the determination in which one of two lines the 
 movement shall be made. This is the very essence of choice, 
 and the question now before us is whether the determination 
 in choice be self-determination, or rather, an uncaused fact, 
 or whether it be caused and so necessitated. 
 
 § 289. Now can we say of a choice that it is a change ? 
 Change from what to what ? Two roads lie before me. On 
 
 1 It is said that the Owenites make use of the following argument : — 
 Whoever necessarily goes or stays is not a free agent ; 
 But every one necessarily either goes or stays ; 
 Therefore, no one is free. 
 Whately would call this Fallacia compositionis, the term, " goes or stays," 
 being used first divisively and then collectively. Obviously, to say that one 
 must go, or that he must stay, is very different from saying that he must do 
 one of the two ; hence, ambiguous middle. 
 
33G VOLITION. 
 
 reaching the fork, shall I take the right or the left ? I take 
 the left. The taking the left is an event ; the solution of 
 the question is an event; but the mere preference of the left 
 instead of the right is not an event, is not in itself a change 
 from something prior, which is not this, to this. I have not 
 at all altered my course. In the line of progress every step 
 is an event ; but when there are alternative paths, my prefer- 
 ence for one while believing that I could take the other is 
 not, in itself alone considered, an event. The change from 
 indecision to decision is caused by the presence of alterna- 
 tives between which I must choose ; but the decision in favor 
 of A rather than B is not a change fi-om B to A, nor from 
 non-A to A, for by the very terms themselves the state imme- 
 diately prior was one of indecision. Comparing the states of 
 mind before and after, evidently there is a change ; but com- 
 I)aring the choice exclusively with its conceivable alternative, 
 evidently there is no change. 
 
 Choice cannot be defined, since the notion is sui generis., 
 simple and ultimate. We cannot analyze its content, and 
 thereby show that it bears no mark of change. We can only 
 dwell attentively upon the notion as formed from certain 
 conscious activities, and ask ourselves whether it be in har- 
 mony with, or in opposition to, the notion of change. A 
 change implies an event, and an event may be fairly defined 
 as what was not and has begun to be. Noav su2)pose that 
 some opportunity for action occurs. Shall I act or not act? 
 I elect inaction. In this election there is no change, nothinor 
 €omes into being. Should I elect action, still in this election 
 there is no change from that to this, no alteration, but only 
 a decision in favor of this rather than that. We repeat that 
 the passing from indecision to decision is a change ; but that 
 the decision for this rather than for that is not a chancre. 
 The latter is a choice, and therefore a choice is not a change. 
 
 § 290. If upon this showing it be granted that choice is 
 not a change, we may proceed one ste]) beyond. Let us 
 
ITS FREEDOM. 337 
 
 invert the axiom : Every change is caused, or is an effect, to: 
 Every effect is a change. This is not admissible as a formal 
 logical conversion, but the latter proposition is nevertheless 
 true ; for it is an analytical judgment a priori., the predicate 
 merely unfolding what is contained in the subject. An 
 effect, to be an effect, implies a change, else nothing would 
 be effected. Taking this as a major, we have the following 
 simple reasoning : — 
 
 Every effect is a change ; 
 Choice is not a change ; 
 .-. Choice is not an effect ; or, is not caused. 
 
 By this, choice is taken entirely out of the category of 
 causation, and, like space, time, unity, identity, infinity, etc., 
 it stands apart, alone, peculiar, a summum genus, wholly dis- 
 tinct in kind from all things else, and must therefore be 
 investigated, not comparatively, but as an independent and 
 original fact. 
 
 By the discovery of a false premise in the necessitarian 
 argument, it is completely invalidated, and so, for aught that 
 appears, choice and liberty may be real. By the discovery 
 that the fact called choice does not lie in the category of 
 causation, we are enabled to reach a further conclusion. 
 Choice being uncaused, it is eo ipso unconstrained. Freedom 
 is the absence of causal constraint. Hence choice is free. 
 In other words, we have found an unconstrained, uncaused 
 fact in the election of one of two available alternatives. We 
 have found freedom in the fact called choice. Therefore 
 choice is real, and human liberty is real, and I am free. 
 
 § 291. To the foregoing discussion we add a very brief 
 consideration of two important points. It has already been 
 indicated that freedom is a postulate of ethics (§ 277). It 
 is co7iditio sine gua non (not causa essendi) of responsibility. 
 Without subjective freedom in action, there can be no re- 
 sponsibility for action. On the other hand, responsibility is 
 
338 VOLITION. 
 
 the logical condition (^causa cognoscendi) of freedom. If one 
 be responsible for his conduct, we know he must be free in 
 determining his conduct. There must be liberty of choice 
 between available alternatives, otherwise the moral law 
 would be a tyrannical imperative, an expression of injustice 
 by demanding the impossible. Whoever admits moral qual- 
 ity in action, must admit freedom in determining the action, 
 and for those who hold to intuition of moral law the argu- 
 ment is a demonstration, though indirect, and not an expla- 
 nation of freedom. Any proof that there is right and wrong 
 in human conduct is also a proof of human liberty. 
 
 § 292. It might fairly be asked whether choice, in its 
 freedom from causal constraint, be independent of antece- 
 dents. Not at all. A desire for each available alternative 
 is prerequisite. A motiveless choice would be only casual- 
 ism, and the free act of an indifferent would be, morally and 
 rationally, as worthless as a preordained activity, or rather 
 as a passion of a determined will. But the desire is merely 
 conditio sine qua non (not causa essendi^ of the choice. 
 
 Moreover, election occurs only in view of reasons. Mere 
 caprice — that is, choice and action without regard of any 
 reason — is unknown to the human mind. In instinctive 
 action there is no exercise of choice, but in intelligent ac 'ion 
 there is choice, and deliberating intelligence furnishes the 
 ground of the choice (§§ 269, 273). Influenced greatly by 
 desire, the reason for the choice may be a very poor reason, 
 a very weak reason, a very stupid or even absurd reason, yet 
 it stands as the reason why I choose this rather than that. 
 The reason does not determine the election in a causal sense, 
 but merely furnishes ground or occasion for the determina- 
 tion and action. Thus it is that choice has necessary though 
 not determining antecedents. 
 
INDEX. 
 
 The number refers to the page. For general topics, see Table of Contents. 
 
 Absolute identity, doctrine of, 141. 
 Abstraction vs. attention, 83. 
 
 — the process of, described, 218. 
 Action at a distance, 117. 
 Affection or love, definition of, 300. 
 Altruism vs. egoism, 30(i. 
 Ambition, an appetence, 300. 
 Anatomy of the brain, 31, 32 n. 
 
 _Apperception, modern use of, 79 n. 
 
 — definition of, 85 n. 
 
 Appetence, the word how used, 298, 
 
 295 n. 
 Appetite, its meaning, 296. 
 A priori and a posteriori, 48 u. 
 Aquinas, Thomas, on here and now, 
 
 88 n. 
 
 — definition of truth, 232 n. 
 Area of consciousness, 64. 
 Argument for necessity, 321. 
 
 — for liberty, 332, 337. 
 
 Aristotle, on the sense of touch, 19 n. 
 
 — on a priori and a posteriori, 48 n. 
 
 — on principles, 48 n. 
 
 — on definition of mind, 51 n. 
 
 — on subject and object, 53 n. 
 
 — on habit, 55 n. 
 
 — quoted under consciousness, 57 n. 
 — ■ on similarity, 61 n. 
 
 — on certainty, 112. 
 
 — tabula rasa, 118. 
 
 — on substance, 133 n. 
 
 — on seat of the soul, 148 n. 
 
 — on preference, 186 n. 
 
 — on recollection, 195 n. 
 
 — on Platonic ideals, 214 n. 
 
 — on common notions, 227 n. 
 — • on definition of truth, 232 n. 
 
 — on the feeling of belief, 247 n., 248 n. 
 
 Aristotle, on pleasure and pain, 250. 
 
 — on expression of feeling, 254 n. 
 
 — on sympathy, 275 n. 
 
 — on the ludicrous, 281 n. 
 
 — on condition of desire, 290 n. 
 
 — oh end of philosophy, 292 n. 
 
 — on definition of happiness, 307. 
 Arnold, on sweetness and light, 240 n. 
 Association, law of, 179. 
 Attention, definition of, 79. 
 
 — etymology of, 79 n. 
 
 — as a faculty, 80 n. 
 
 — expectant, 82. 
 
 — plural, 83. 
 
 Augustine, on recollection, 195. 
 
 — on utility, 282. 
 Automatic muscular action, 28. 
 
 Bacon, on classification of error, 237 n. 
 
 — on value of truth, 238. 
 
 — on humility, 287 n. 
 
 Bain, on mental and bodily states, 44 n. 
 
 — on law of relativity, 60 n. 
 
 — on materialism, 140 n. 
 
 — on concomitance, 143 n. 
 
 — on monism, 144 n. 
 
 — on retention, 190. 
 
 — on brain action, 204 n. 
 
 — on pleasure and pain, 250 n., 251 n. 
 
 — on the caress, 261 n. 
 
 — on sweetness, 262 n. 
 
 — on expression of joy, 273 n. 
 
 — on the tender affection, 274 n. 
 
 — on the ludicrous, 281 n. 
 Baldwin, on apperception, 85 n. 
 
 — on the idea of space, 101 n. 
 Bascom, on spontaneity of volition, 
 
 327 n. 
 
 339 
 
340 
 
 INDEX. 
 
 Beauty, a sensuous sentiment, 277. 
 
 — detiuitious of, 279. 
 Belief, the doctrine of, 247. 
 
 — opposite of doubt, 248, 283 n. 
 Bell, Sir Charles, on nerves, 27 n. 
 
 — on expression of the ludicrous, 282 n. 
 Berkeley, his idealism, i;i4. 
 
 — on vision of distance, 172 n. 
 
 — on symbolic thought, 230 n. 
 Bernstein, on objects of perception, 
 
 15 n. 
 Binaural audition, experiment on, 9. 
 Binocular vision, experiment on, 12. 
 Blackie, Four Phases, 7 n. 
 Boschovich, on substance, 133 n. 
 Bowne, on materialism, 137. 
 Brain, the object of perception, 15. 
 
 — anatomy of, 31, 32 n. 
 Brown-Scquard, on pain, 200. 
 Buliier, on primary truth, 112 n. 
 
 Calderwood, on idealism, 130 n. 
 
 — on will and causation, 325 n. 
 Capacity, a power to be changed, 55. 
 Cardaillac, on area of consciousness, 
 
 05 n. 
 Carpenter, on muscular sense, 22 n. 
 
 — on a case of reflex action, 28 n. 
 
 — on unconscious cerebration, 34 n. 
 
 — on attention, 82 n. 
 
 — on correlation of nerve and mind 
 
 force, 141 n. 
 Cause and effect, their nexus, 31G n. 
 Cerebral nerves, 27. 
 
 — hemispheres, the cortex, 32. 
 Cerebration, unconscious, .33. 
 Cerebro-spinal system, 2(). 
 Certainty as a criterion of truth, 70, 
 
 234 n. 
 
 — the feeling of, 247. 
 
 Change, a condition of consciousness, 
 
 (iO. 
 Characteristics of pure intuitions, 110. 
 Choice, its essential character, 333. 
 
 — its conditioning antecedents, 314, 
 
 338. 
 
 — not a change, 335. 
 
 Cicero, on the meaning of faculty, 55 n. 
 
 — (Ill the beau ifleal, 214 n. 
 
 — III! the ludicrous, 281 n. 
 
 Cicero, on appetite, its wide sense, 
 
 290 n. 
 Classification, the process of, 223. 
 Clifford, on the organ of sight, 15 n. 
 
 — on the wide meaning of feeling, 
 
 239 n. 
 Cognition, definition and distribution 
 
 of, 73. 
 — • general discussion of, 77. ■**^ 
 
 — condition of other faculties, 79. -/O 
 
 — correlative to feeling, 239. • 
 
 — law of the correlation, 241. 
 Coleridge, on expectant attention, 82. 
 
 — on sensation and perception, 92 n. 
 
 — on fancy as a source of error, 2.38 n. 
 Color-blindness, 12 n. t' 
 Comparison the basis of jiidgment, 78. 
 Comte, definition of forc^^8 n., 328 n. 
 
 — on idealism, 135. 
 Conation, the meaning of, 72 n. 
 Conception, the process of, 219. 
 Condillac, sensationalism, 119 n. 
 Conditio essendi et cognoscendi, 128 n., 
 
 338. 
 Condition, definition of, 59 u. 
 Conscience, definition of, 308. 
 Consciousness, its etymology, 56 n. 
 
 4 
 
 — its content, 57. 
 
 — definitions of, 58 n. 
 
 — its conditions, 59. 
 
 — its limitations, 02. 
 
 — area of, CA. 
 
 — modes of, 72. 
 
 — ancient distriliution, 73 n. 
 
 — of self, a feeling, 245. 
 
 — of freedom of will, 322. 
 Control of feelings, 252. 
 Cousin, on consciousness, 56 n. 
 
 — on pure reason, 130 n. 
 
 — on the beau ideal, 214 n. 
 
 — on illegitimate success, 292 n. 
 
 — on consciousness of liberty, 324 n. 
 Criterion of pure truth, 113, 2;U n. 
 Crucdty, a malevolence, 304. 
 Curiosity, an appetence, 2J)9. 
 Cycle, the historical, 220 n. 
 
 Darwin, on expression of emotion, 2.%n. 
 
 — on expression of the liuHcrous, 282 n. 
 
 — on expression of ((intciupt, 285 u. 
 
INDEX. 
 
 341 
 
 Delboeiif, on psycho-physics, 39. 
 Denioeritus, on the sense of touch, 18 n. 
 Denomination or naming, 221. 
 Descartes, on mind and matter, 45 n. 
 
 — on thought and extension, 51 n. 
 
 — on the true, 112 n., 114 n. 
 
 — on origin of ideas, 122. 
 
 — his idealism, 133. 
 
 — on seat of the soul, 149 n. 
 
 — on imagination, 200 n. 
 
 — on dreaming, 206 n. 
 
 — on criterion of truth, 2'M n. 
 
 — his enthymeme modified, 246 n. 
 
 — on pleasure and pain, 251 n. 
 Desire, defined and distributed, 74, 289. 
 
 — cause of voluntary effort, 317 n., 332. 
 Determinism, doctrine of, 318. 
 
 — vs. necessity, 318 n. 
 Difference, shock of, 61, 243. 
 Diffusion of feeling, 253. 
 Disposition, its varieties, 267. 
 Distraction vs. attention, 82. 
 Doubt, negative of belief, 248. 
 
 — a painful feeling, 283 n. 
 Dualism, the doctrine of, 144. 
 
 — argument in favor of, 146. 
 
 Edwards, scheme of free agency, 329. 
 
 — definition of liberty, 329 n. 
 Ego vs. non-ego, 52. 
 Egoism vs. altruism, 306. 
 Empirical science, 48. 
 Empiricism, the doctrine of, 118. 
 
 — reply to, 120. 
 
 Envy, a malevolence, 304. 
 Error, its primary cause, 236. 
 Experience and experiment, 95 n. 
 Extension given in vision, 13. 
 
 — opinions of Miiller and others, 13 n. 
 
 — and intension, law of, 222. 
 External reality perceived, 96. 
 
 Facts of consciousness, 68. 
 
 — their importance, 71. 
 Faculty, a power to change, 55. 
 Faith, its elements stated, 285. 
 Familiarity, the basis of memory, 244. 
 Faraday, on humility, 287 n. 
 Fatigue, the sensation of, 260. 
 
 Fear, a painful emotion, 270. 
 
 Fear, its organic effects, 271. 
 Fechner's law of sensation, 39. 
 Feeling, defined and distributed, 74, 
 256. 
 
 — extent of meaning, 239 n. 
 
 — law of correlation, 241. 
 Ferrier, D., on blindness, 11 n. 
 
 — on functions of brain, 33 n. 
 
 — on mind and brain, 138 n. 
 
 — on duality of brain, 147 n. 
 Fichte's nihilism, 135 n. 
 Free agency, scheme of, 329. 
 Freedom, the sentiment of, 284. 
 
 — a postulate of philosophy, 319. 
 
 — a postulate of ethics, 319, 337. 
 
 — presumption in favor of, .321. 
 
 — objective vs. subjective, 330. 
 
 — argument in favor of, 332, 337. 
 Fritsch and Hitzig, experiments of, 
 
 33 n. 
 
 Gassendi, illustration of retention, 
 
 191 n. 
 Generalization, process of, 219. 
 General truth, of three kinds, 115. 
 Generic powers, scheme of, 72. 
 Genesis of mediate perceptions, 159. 
 George, Dr. L., on temperaments, 266 n. 
 Gibbon, on Julian's attention, 84 n. 
 Gmelin, on odors, 2 n. 
 Goclenius, on sensoriura, 34 n. 
 Goethe, in illustration of consciousness, 
 
 77 n. 
 
 — on multiplicity of suggestion, 182 n. 
 
 — on fancy, 208 n. 
 
 — on wonder, 270 n. 
 Gratitude, a moral sentiment, 288. 
 Gray and white nerve substance, 31. 
 Gurney on hallucination, 203 n., 207 n. 
 
 Habit, law of, 55 n., 85. 
 
 Hall, Dr. Marshall, on reflex action, 
 
 29 n. 
 Hamilton, on the object perceived, 15 n. 
 
 — on touch, its modifications, 18 n. 
 
 — on sul)Stance, 51 n., 133 n. 
 
 — on consciousness and extension, 51 n. 
 
 — on subject and object, 53 n. 
 
 — on definition of consciousness, 58 n. 
 
 — on latent activities, 66 n. 
 
842 
 
 INDEX. 
 
 Hamilton, on facts of consciousness, 
 68 n., 247 n. 
 
 — on content of consciousness, 71 n. 
 
 — on division of faculties, 73 n. 
 
 — on plural attention, 84 n. 
 
 — on immediate ijerceptiou, 99 n., 
 
 145 n. 
 
 — on externality, 102 n., 103 n. 
 
 — on innate forms, 124 n. 
 
 — on idealism, 136 n. 
 
 — on mind and matter, 138 n. 
 
 — on seat of the soul, 149. 
 
 — on representation, 151 n. 
 
 — on association, 178 n. 
 
 — on retention, 190 n. 
 
 — on imagination v><. memory, 199. 
 
 — on conception and naming, 221. 
 
 — on criterion of truth, 234 n. 
 
 — on tedium, 242 n. 
 
 — on feeling and desire, 245. 
 
 — on pleasure and pain, 249 n. 
 
 — on distribution of feelings, 256 n. 
 
 — on the sublime, 280 n. 
 
 — on the ludicrous, 281 n. 
 
 — on cognition vs. conation, 289 n. 
 
 — on will as a balance, 314 n. 
 
 — on consciousness of liberty, 322 n. 
 Happiness, definition of, 306 n., 307. 
 Hartley, on law of transference, 181 u. 
 
 — on association, 186 n. 
 Hartmanu, on the unconscious, 66 n. 
 Hearing, its organ and excitant, 7. 
 
 — its percept, sound, 8. 
 
 — its percept intercranial, 9. 
 
 — analogous with seeing, 14. 
 Helmholtz, on nervous rate, 36, 40. 
 
 — on native and empirical, 101 n. 
 Helvetius, illustration of preference, 
 
 185 n. 
 Herbart, on thought, 217 n. 
 
 — on pleasure and pain, 251 n. 
 Hering, on psycho-physics, 39. 
 H(irscliel, on external reality, 130 n. 
 Hobbes, example of suggestion, 180 n. 
 
 — on cliange of sensation, 242 n. 
 
 — on the ludicrous, 281 n. 
 
 — on definition of liberty, 329 n. 
 Honor and dishonor, sentiments of, 
 
 285, 2m. 
 Horace, on wonder, 269 n. 
 
 Horace, on sympathetic feeling, 276 n. 
 Houdin's automatic skill, 30 n. 
 Humboldt, on delicacy of smell, 3 n. 
 Hume, on idealism, 134. 
 
 — on external reality, 158 n. 
 
 — on tlights of imagination, 210 n. 
 
 — on the question of freedom, 319. 
 
 — on definition of liberty, 329 n. 
 Humility, the sentiment of, 287. 
 Hunger, the typical appetite, 297. 
 Huxley's materialism, 141 n. 
 
 — on freedom to do right, 320 n. 
 
 Idea, note on the word, 154 n. 
 Idealism, various forms of, 133. 
 
 — self-contradictory, 1.35. 
 Illusion and delusion, 161 n. 
 Imagination, definition of, 198. 
 
 — distinguished from memory, 199. 
 Immediate perception, 96. 
 Individual, definition of, 228 n. 
 Inference (\s. intuition, 79. 
 Inhibition of emotion, 268. 
 Innate truth, 122. 
 
 Instincts, the physical, 29. 
 
 — the psycho-i)hysical, 253. 
 
 — the psychical, 294. 
 Intension, the law of, 222. 
 Interest vs. duty, 305. 
 Introspection, the power of, 106. 
 Intuition, kinds of, 87. 
 
 — derivation of the word, 87 n. 
 Intuitionism, 122. 
 
 — extreme view of, 124. 
 
 — prevalent view, 125. 
 
 — self-contradictory, 126 n. 
 
 — preferred view, 12(). 
 
 Irving,' Washington, on sorrow, 272 n. 
 
 Janet, on error of Benthamites, 307 n. 
 Jealousy, a malevolence, 303. 
 Johnson, Dr., on tlie ludicrous, 281 n. 
 JoiifTroy, on attention, 84 n. 
 Joy and sorrow, tlieir expression, 272. 
 Judgments, of two kinds, 224. 
 
 Kant, sensus fixus et vagus, 1. 
 
 — on a priori et a posteriori, 48 n. 
 
 — on noumena and plienomena, 49 n. 
 
 — on division of faculties, 73 n. 
 
INDEX. 
 
 o4o 
 
 Kant, on motion, 102 n. 
 
 — oil strict universality, 114. 
 
 — ou forms of cognition, 123. 
 
 — on substance, 133 n. 
 
 — on idealism, 134. 
 
 — ou Hume, 134 n. 
 
 — on seat of the soul, 149. 
 
 — ou errors of sense, IGl n. 
 
 — on Plato's imagination, 210 n. 
 
 — on criterion of truth, 233. 
 
 — on intelligent questions, 233 n. 
 
 — on knowing and feeling, 241 n. 
 
 — on pleasure and pain, 250 n., 251 n. 
 
 — on distribution of feelings, 256 n. 
 
 — on the ludicrous, 281 n. 
 
 — on desires as i^ains, 291 n. 
 
 — on the will as the ego, 309 n. 
 
 — on volition as a free cause, 324 n. 
 Kirehmanu, on the ego, 53 n. 
 
 Ladd, on physiological psychology, 35 n. 
 
 — on psycho-physics, 40. 
 
 — on introspection, 46. 
 
 — on seeing depth, 1G5 n. 
 Language of feeling, 255 n. 
 Latent activities of mind, 65. 
 
 Le Conte, on retinal inversion, 168 n. 
 Leibnitz, on mind and matter, 45 n. 
 
 — on area of consciousness, 65 n. 
 
 — on certainty of consciousness, 70 n. 
 
 — on reply to Locke, 122. 
 
 — on innate truth, 123. 
 
 — on substance, 133 n. 
 
 — on symbolic thinking, 230 n. 
 Lewes, on dynamical presence, 149 n. 
 Liberty, argument in favor of, .3.32, .3.37. 
 Limitation, law of, 80. 
 
 Limits of consciousness, 62. 
 Local signs, Lotze on, 19 n. 
 Localization of sense-centres, 32. 
 Locke, on substance, 50 n. 
 
 — on sources of knowledge, 118. 
 
 — ou limits of imagination, 200 n. 
 Longet, on dreams of sweets, 262 n. 
 Longinus, on recollection, 195 n. 
 Lotze, on local signs, 19 n. 
 
 — ou apperception, 79 n. 
 
 — on spirit as an entity, 147 n. 
 
 — on localizing percepts, 176 n. 
 
 — on self-consciousuGss, 24(1 n. 
 
 Lotze, on temperament, 266 n. 
 Love and jealousy, emotions of, 273. 
 
 — or affection, definition of, 300. 
 Lustre, the sensation of, 265. 
 
 Macaulay, on creative ability, 203 n. 
 Magliabecchi's memory, 196 n. 
 Malebranche, on attention, 86. 
 
 — on truth, 2.37. 
 
 — on pursuit of truth, 284 n. 
 Mausel, on the object perceived, 15 n. 
 
 — on forms of cognition, 124. 
 
 — on the individual, 228 n. 
 
 — on symbolic thought, 231 n. 
 
 — on freedom as a postulate, 319 n. 
 
 — on consciousness of liberty, .322 n. 
 Materialism, the doctrine of, 136. 
 Matter and mind, logically defined, 50. 
 McCosh, on mind and matter, 45 n. 
 
 — on self-evidence, 129 n. 
 
 Mediate cognition and inference, 150 n. 
 Mediate percej^tion, 92, 158. 
 
 — genesis of, 159. 
 Memory defined, 187. 
 
 Mill, J. S., on consciousness, 58 n. 
 
 — on latent activities, 66 n. 
 
 — ou consciousness and philosophy, 
 
 71 n. 
 
 — his power of attention, 83 n. 
 
 — on action and passion, 97 n. 
 
 — on empiricism, 119, 122 n. 
 Milton, cited, 149 u., 154 n. 
 
 — on phantasy, 204 n. 
 
 — on reason vs. fancy, 227 n. 
 Mind, logically defined, 50. 
 
 — derivation of the word, 50 n. 
 
 — defined a posteriori, 51. 
 
 — a unit, 75. 
 
 Misanthropy, a malevolence, .304. 
 Mitchell, Dr., on the lAautom limb, 
 
 174 u. 
 Mnemonics, 197. 
 Modes of consciousness, distribution of, 
 
 72. 
 Montaigne's memory, 196 n. 
 
 — on opinion, 249 n. 
 Mood vs. temperament, 267. 
 
 Motive, as eflScient cause of effort, 293. 
 
 — its meaning, 293 n. 
 
 — as final cause, 313 n. 
 
344 
 
 INDEX. 
 
 Motive, as weight in a balance, 314 n. 
 Miiller, on causes of sensation, 15 n. 
 
 — sketch of, 'M'). 
 
 — on externality, 101 n. 
 
 — on retinal inversion, 168 n. 
 
 — on physical effects, 205 n. 
 jVIuscular sense, its percept, 20. 
 
 — illustrations of, 21. 
 
 — action, control of, 312. 
 
 Nativism vs. experience, 101 n. 
 Necessity, of two kinds, 113 n. 
 
 — modified view of, 129. 
 
 — doctrine of, 318. 
 
 — argument in favor of, 321. 
 Nervous circuit, 28. 
 Nihilism of Hume, 134. 
 
 — ofTFichte, 135 n. 
 
 Non-ego consciously perceived, 97-99. 
 
 Observation and reflection, 81. 
 Occam's law of parcimony, 80 n. 
 Owenite argument for necessity, 335 n. 
 
 Pain and pleasure, 249. 
 Parcimony, Occam's law of, 80 n. 
 Pascal, on distraction, 82 n. 
 
 — on materialism, 138 n. 
 
 — on imagination causing error, 236 n. 
 Passivity of perception, 94. 
 Patriotism a benevolence, 302. 
 Percept, the, an external reality, 96. 
 Perception, defined, 91. 
 
 — vs. sensation, 92 n. 
 
 — passivity of, 94. 
 
 Peripatetic division of faculties, 73 n. 
 Person, definition of, 309 n. 
 Phantasy, dreams, 203. 
 Phantom limb, 174. 
 Plienonienon defined, 49. 
 Philanthropy, a benevolence, 303. 
 Physical effects of feeling, 253. 
 Physiological jjsychology defined, 35. 
 
 — its value estimated, 42. 
 
 — vs. pure psychology, 44. 
 Physiology of tlu^ l)rain, .H3 n. 
 Pity, the sentiment of, 285. 
 Plato's theory of ideas, 214 n. 
 
 — definition of truth, 232 n. 
 
 — view of pleasure and pain, 250 n. 
 
 Plato's definition of beauty, 279. 
 Pleasure and pain, 249. 
 
 — appetence for, 299. 
 Plural attention, 83. 
 
 Porphyry, on the individual, 228 n. 
 Porter, on the idea, 157 n. 
 Power and poteutial,*55. 
 Powers, scheme of generic, 72. 
 
 — scheme of specific, 75. 
 Pre-existence of the .soul, 194 n. 
 Preference, law of, 184. 
 Presentation, definition of, 87. 
 
 — vs. representation, 88, 150. 
 Priestly, on association, 180. 
 Principles, philosophic meaning of, 48 n. 
 Psychology, pure and mixed, 44. 
 
 — defined, 47. 
 
 Psychological judgment vs. inference, 
 
 79. 
 Psychometry, 40. 
 Psycho-physics, 37. 
 Pure intuition or reason, 108. 
 Pure pain, 24, 259. 
 Pursuit, pleasure of, 283, 292. 
 
 Qualities of body, 100. 
 
 Rate of nervous propagation, 40. 
 Rational psychology, 49 n. 
 Reason, pure, 108. 
 Reflection, 107. 
 Reflex action, 28. 
 
 — vs. diffusion of feeling, 253. 
 Reid, on the object perceived, 15 n. 
 
 — on immediate perception, 145 n. 
 
 — on consciousness of liberty, 322 n. 
 Relativity, law of, 60. 
 Representation vs. presentation, 88, 
 
 150. 
 Repetition, theory of, 187. 
 Retention, theories of, 189. 
 Ril)ot, on German psj'chology of to-day, 
 
 36 n. 
 
 — on psycho-physics, 40. 
 
 — on physiological psychology, 43. 
 Richelieu's power ol attention, 86 n. 
 
 Sand, George, on maternity, 301 n. 
 Schelling, on liberty and necessity, 
 331 n. 
 
INDEX. 
 
 345 
 
 ■Scheme of generic powers, 72. 
 
 — of specific powers, 75. 
 
 — of feelings, 257. 
 
 — of desires, 21)5. 
 
 Sclioolmeu, on consciousness, 57 n. 
 
 — on area of consciousness, 65 n. 
 SL-hopenliauer's idealism, 135. 
 
 — on liberty a negative notion, 323 n. 
 
 — on will as undetermined, 325 n. 
 Science defined and divided, 47. 
 Scott, his power of attention, 81 n. 
 
 — on true valor, 270 n. 
 
 — on sorrow, 272 n. 
 .Scottish philosophy, 97 n. 
 Seat of the soul, 148. 
 
 Seeing and hearing analogous, 14. 
 Self-perception defined, 105. 
 Seneca, on idea and image, 154 n. 
 Sensation vs. perception, 92, 240, 258. 
 Senses, distribution of, 1. 
 Sensor and motor nerves, 27. 
 Sensory vs. sensorium, 34. 
 
 — the object immediately perceived, 15. 
 Sensus Jixus and vagus, 1. 
 
 — vagus, 23, 258. 
 —fixus, 2G0. 
 
 Sentiment, its mark, 277. 
 Shakspeare cited, n., 55 n,, 142 n., 
 
 153 n., 185 n., 195 n., 203 n., 204 n., 
 205 u., 206 n., 207 n., 208 n., 212 n., 
 242 n., 271 n., 274 n., 275 n., 276 n., 
 284 n., 292 n., 300 n., 303 n., 306 n.- 
 
 Shall and will, 316 n. 
 
 Shelly, on memory and hope, 199 n. 
 
 Shock of difference and similarity, 61, 
 243. 
 
 Sidgwick on consciousness of liberty, 
 323 n. 
 
 Sight, its organ, its objectivity, 10. 
 
 — its primary percept, 11. 
 
 — its secondary percept, 13. 
 
 • — its analogy to hearing, 14. 
 
 — its octave of colors, 14 n. 
 .Similarity, shock of, 61, 243. 
 
 — law of, 178. 
 
 Smell, its organ and excitant, 2. 
 
 — Valentin and Humboldt on, 3 n. 
 
 — proximate cause of, 4. 
 
 — classification of, 261. 
 .Sociality an appetence, 300. 
 
 Space, apprehension of, 13 n., 19 n. 
 
 — origin of the notion of, 101 n. 
 Specific powers, scheme of, 75. 
 Spencer, on touch, 19 n. 
 
 — on substance, 51 n. 
 
 — on external reality, 96 n. 
 
 — critical of Mill, 119 n. 
 
 — on concomitance of mind and brain, 
 
 143 n. 
 
 — on mind as motion, 144 n. 
 
 — on organized memory, 192 n. 
 
 — on perception vs. memory, 206 n. 
 
 — on pleasure and pain, 251 n. 
 — • on tlie ludicrous, 281 n. 
 Spinal cord and nerves, 27. 
 Spinoza, on sulistance, 50 n. 
 
 — on aflirmation, 60 n. 
 
 — on absolute identity, 142 n. 
 
 — on liberty and necessity, 331 n. 
 Spontaneity in voluntary action, 327 n. 
 Stewart, definition of consciousness, 
 
 58 n. 
 
 — on idealism, 136 n. 
 
 — on names, 222 n. 
 SubcoDscious activities, 65. 
 Subject vs. object, 53. 
 
 Substance, scholastic definition of, 50 n. 
 
 — a necessary idea, 132. 
 Sympathetic system, 26. 
 Sympathy and compassion, 274. 
 
 Tactile corpuscles, 17 n. 
 Tangibility, the tactile percept, 18. 
 Taste, its organ and excitants, 5. 
 
 — its delicacy, 6 n. 
 
 — its analogy to smell, 7. 
 
 — its classification, 262. 
 Temperament, mood, disposition, 266. 
 Temperature, sense of, 24. 
 Thompson, Prof. S. P., on audition, 10 n. 
 Thomson, Dr. Wm., on criterion of 
 
 truth, 2;J4 n. 
 Thought, defined and discussed, 216. 
 Tieck, on the regnant ego, 53 n. 
 Time of nervous propagation, 40. 
 
 — of psychic action, 41. 
 Touch, its organ, 17. 
 
 — its primary percept, 18. 
 
 — its secondary percept, 19. 
 
 — its sensation, 261. 
 
340 
 
 INDEX, 
 
 Ti'cndeleiibiirjj, cited on scienoe, 48 n. 
 Truth, detinitioiis ol', 'iol, 'I'M ii. 
 
 — the seutiment of, 282. 
 Turcot, on Innate ideas, 127 ii. 
 Tyndall, on nund and matter, 45 n. 
 
 — on concomitance, 142 n. 
 
 Unconscious cerebration, 33. 
 
 — activities, G5. 
 
 Unconsciousness not j^rovable, 63. 
 Uh-ici, on consciousness oi: liberty, 
 
 322 n. 
 
 — on spontaneity ol volition, 328 n. 
 Unity of mind, 75. 
 
 Utility vs. beauty, 281. 
 
 Varigny, on physiology of brain, 31 n. 
 Vibrations of luminiferous ether, 14 n. 
 Volition, ol)ject and elements of, 75, 313. 
 
 — special function of, 83, 311. 
 
 — or will, defined, 309. 
 
 — as an uncaused cause, .324. 
 
 — its freedoiu defended, 318, .332. 
 Volney, on a case of couching, 165 n. 
 
 Weber, on circles of sensation, 17 n. 
 
 — on muscular sense, 22 n. 
 
 — on sense of tonperature, 24 n. 
 
 — on pure pain, 24 n. 
 
 ' Weber, liis experiments, •'><). 
 
 — his law formulated, 37v 
 Wheatstone, on unity in vision, 164 n. 
 
 — on vision of distance, 170 n. 
 White and gray nervous matter, 31. 
 WiU or volition, special function of, 85, 
 
 311. 
 
 — defined, 309. 
 
 — its isolation, 314 n. 
 Wish vs. desire, 290 n. 
 Wolf, on psychology, 49 n. 
 
 — on criterion of truth, 234 n. 
 Wordsworth, on immortality, 194 n. 
 
 — on imagination, 209 n. 
 Wonder, an emotion, 269. 
 Wundt, on sight, 7 n. 
 
 — on local signs, 20 n. 
 
 — his wide research, 37. 
 
 — on Fechner's law, 39. 
 
 — on the conception of soul, 52 n., 132 n. 
 
 — on consciousness, 58 n. 
 
 — on the unconscious, OG n. 
 
 — on apperception, 79 n. 
 
 — on innervation, 102 n. 
 
 — on vision of direction, 167 n. 
 
 — on thought, 216 n. 
 
 — on temperament, 267 n. 
 
 — on consciousness of liberty, 324 n. 
 
 TIHIVBRSIT7] 
 
14 DAY USE "** 
 
 RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED 
 
 This book is due on tBn^ aate stamped below, or 
 
 on the date to which renewed. 
 
 Renewed books are subject to immediate recall. 
 
 7 DAY USE 
 
 SUMMER 
 
 niiRiM 
 
 SESSIOL, 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 i 
 
 
 
 
 LD 21-50m-12,'61 
 (04796810)476 
 
 General Library 
 
 University of California 
 
 Berkeley 
 
U.C. BERKELEY LIBRARIES 
 
 CDE^MflflTMb