* REESE LIBRARY ^ UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA. ■■laesiioiis No. 6^6 ^ ^ CLn<. No. Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2007 with funding from IVIicrosoft Corporation http://www.archive.org/details/christianityideaOOwatsrich CHRISTIANITY AND IDEALISM j2^^ Christianity and Idealism The Christian Ideal of Life in its Relations TO THE Greek and Jewish Ideals and to Modern Philosophy BY JOHN WATSON, LL.D. PROFESSOR OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY IN QUEEN'S UNIVERSITY KINGSTON, CANADA NEIV EDITION, WITH ADDITIONS THE MACMILLAN COMPANY LONDON: MACMILLAN & CO., LTD. 1897 All rights reserved Copyright, 1896, By the MACMILLAN COMPANY. Copyright, 1897, By the MACMILLAN COMPANY. Set up and electrotyped December, 1896. Reprinted, with additions, August, 1897. Norlnootr ^cees J. 8. Cuihing & Co. - Berwick & Smith Norwood Mail. U.S.A. CONTENTS PAGE Preface to the Second Edition vii Introductory Preface xxi Part I THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE IN RELATION TO THE GREEK AND JEWISH IDEALS CHAPTER I Historical Connexion of Morality and Religion . . i CHAPTER II The Greek Ideal 23 CHAPTER III The Jewish Ideal 45 CHAPTER IV The Christian Ideal 60 CHAPTER V Medieval Christianity no V Vi CONTENTS Part II MODERN IDEALISM IN ITS RELATION TO THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE CHAPTER VI PAGE General Statement and Defence of Idealism . . .121 CHAPTER VII Idealism in relation to Agnosticism and the Special Sciences 153 CHAPTER VIII The Failure of Materialism 192 CHAPTER IX The Idealistic Interpretation of Natural Evolution . 216 CHAPTER X Idealism and Human Progress 237 CHAPTER XI Idealism and Christl^nity 256 PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION In the present edition of this little work, while the first part has been left unchanged, the second part has been enlarged by the addi- tion of three new chapters (the eighth, ninth, and tenth) and the intercalation of a dozen pages (pp. 268-280) in the last chapter of the book. The eighth chapter seeks to exhibit the inadequacy of Materialism, by showing that the Atomism upon which it rests is inconsis- tent both with science and with philosophy, and that in its struggle to reach consistency it ac- complishes its own euthanasia. It is from no desire to gain an easy victory over the crudest of all philosophical theories that space has been occupied in discussing its pretensions, but simply as a step in the orderly advance to a more adequate theory, and as an illustration of the double function which philosophy dis- charges: firstly, in freeing the fundamental viii PREFACE TO THE SECON-D EDITION- ideas of science from inconsistency, and, sec- ondly, in re-interpreting them from the point of view of the whole. In the chapter which follows, the same method is employed in the estimate of the evolutionary account of the world. In the tenth chapter an attempt is made to distinguish human progress from the prior stages of evolution, and to show that it presupposes the existence of a self-conscious or self-determining Principle as the ultimate source and explanation of reality in all its forms. The incidental discussion in this con- nexion of the main thesis of Mr. Kidd's Social Evolution — a thesis which I regard as demon- strably false — will, I hope, help to throw into relief the idealistic conception of human life as the progressive evolution of self-conscious reason. In the passage added to the last chap- ter I have tried to explain why I cannot accept the view that the Absolute may be super- rational, and to indicate, more clearly than was done in the former edition, what I regard as the true relation of the human to the divine spirit. I am only sorry that the plan of the work does not allow me to enter more thor- PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION ix oughly into the discussion of the last question, which is perhaps the most pressing metaphysi- cal problem of the present day. The additional matter contained in this edition will help to fill out the somewhat meagre outline of Idealism given in the for- mer edition. But I am still only too con- scious of the inadequacy of the discussion. The present work is merely the preparation for a system of philosophy, and cannot but share in the inevitable defects of every attempt to present the results of philosophical reflec- tion in a general form. At every step in its onward march philosophy sets its foot upon ashes beneath which fierce fires glow. Our age, as Kant said of his own, is an "age of criticism," when even the most cherished con- victions must submit to the "free and open scrutiny of reason"; and therefore any one who apparently ignores or makes light of difficulties which to some of his contemporaries seem of a formidable character is apt to be charged with superficiality, indifference, or dogmatism. I do not deny that many of the objections which have been urged against Idealism seem X PREFACE TO THE SECOATD EDITION' to me to be due mainly to misunderstanding, but I think I may claim that I have in no case been untrue to the free but austere spirit of philosophy, — a spirit which is hostile to all dogmatic utterances and acknowledges no authority but reason. If Idealism is to become but a new form of dogmatism, the life will go out of it, and only an empty husk will be left behind. We cannot even find an authoritative basis for truth in what Mr. Balfour calls our "ethical needs"; for these "needs" themselves require justification. Nor can I believe that any fruitful results can be reached by seeking to reinstate the "primacy of practical reason," or by falling back upon the vague formula that "life is more than thought." Reason cannot be divided against itself without self- contradiction, and the "life" which excludes " thought " is so much the poorer for its ex- clusiveness. Those who are fond of quoting Goethe's " Grau, theurer Freund, ist alle Theorie, Und griin des Leben's goldner Baum," should remember that the words are put into the mouth of Mephistopheles, "der Geist der PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION xi stets verneint," when he is in a mocking humour. To those who imagine, as Mr. Bal- four in his Foundations of Belief seems to do, that faith can be based upon a suicidal dis- trust of reason, I would commend the words of a great master in speculation, who is more frequently decried than read. "There is at present," says Hegel, "a strenu- ous and almost impassioned effort to rescue men, collectively and individually, from their immersion in the life of sense, and to turn their eyes to the stars ; as if they were entirely forgetful of the divine, and were about to con- tent themselves, like the worm, with dust and water. Once they had a heaven, furnished with a rich store of thoughts and images. The significance of the actual lay in the thread of light by which it was attached to heaven; guided by this thread, the eye, instead of dwelling upon what was immediately before it, sped onward to the divine Reality, — to what might be called the present yonder. The eye of the soul had to be forced to look towards the earth, and much time and effort were needed to impart the clearness of heaven xii PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION to the darkness and confusion in which the sensible was enveloped. What seems to be needed now is just the opposite: so firmly is the soul attached to the earth, that an equal force is required to lift it to the things above. The spirit is so poor, that, like the traveller in the desert, who thirsts for a simple draught of water, it seems to long but for the bare feeling of the divine to refresh it. When the spirit can be satisfied with so little, we can easily estimate how great has been its loss. . . . But, in truth, spiritual force is to be measured by its expression : its depth is only so deep as it dares to expand and to lose itself in its manifestations. When those who claim that truth is revealed in an immediate intuition pretend that they have penetrated to the very heart of reality, and that they alone are the exponents of a true and pious philosophy, they are unaware that, instead of offering up their desires to God, by their con- tempt for precise and definite ideas they are in reality the victim of their own arbitrary conceits. Because they envelope their self- consciousness in mist, and forego the use of PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION xiu their intellect, they fondly imagine that they are ' the beloved ' to whom God ' giveth wis- dom in sleep.' It hardly needs to be said that what comes to them in sleep are merely dreams." ^ Philosophy, as I understand it, must refuse all weak compromises. It is not a thing of the chair, or even an instrument for preserving the threatened interests of civilisation, but a resolute and independent effort to grasp the true nature of the real; and no one can live in its spirit who is not willing to follow the lead of ideas with docility and singleness of purpose. This, however, does not mean that it moves in a region of abstractions ; on the contrary, it can be successful in its quest for truth, only as it follows the maxim, " im Gan- zen, Guten, Schonen resolut zu leben." In this effort after comprehensiveness lies the special difficulty of its problem. None of the phases of human life can be ignored; yet each is so complex in itself, while all are so intimately related to one another, that it is hard to main- tain the proper perspective and assign to each ♦ Hegel's Phdnomenologie des Geistes, pp. 8, 9. xiv PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION its due importance. The task would, indeed, be impracticable, were it not that the essence of the past has been gathered up by succes- sive philosophies and presented in the clear medium of thought. At the present day, as it seems to me, the main problem is to inter- pret anew, by the aid of existing philosophies, the purified results of science, the highest intuitions of art, and the matured religious consciousness in a comprehensive and self- consistent way. The present volume is a small contribution to the solution of that problem. To prevent misunderstanding, it may be as well to add a few words as to the relation of the first part of the work to the second. The Christian ideal of life, as expressed by its'? Founder, seems to me to require no adven-f titious support, being in itself intrinsically) rational; but we cannot say the same thin^ of every system of doctrine which claims to be the sole representative of Christianity. The precise degree of truth which is con- tained in any given theological creed is a matter to be determined by careful investiga- PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION- xv tion, and would require rigorous and extended treatment. In the last chapter and in various passages throughout the work, I have indi- cated, I hope with sufficient clearness, that in my opinion the form in which the fundamental ideas of Christianity are present in the popu- lar consciousness is not adequate to the liv- ing truth as it was expressed by the Master; and one object which I had in view in writ- ing the work was to disengage the essence of Christianity from elements which for histori- cal reasons have come to be regarded as in- separable from it, though they are in reality antagonistic to its spirit. On the other hand, I do not sympathise with those who speak of the development of Christian doctrine as if it were nothing but an obscuration of primi- tive Christianity; much less with those who strangely hold that Christianity received its ultimate formulation in the . Nicene creed. These views logically lead to the acceptance of the ideas of its Founder, or of the church, on mere authority, and therefore contradict the spirit and even the words of the Master. The ideas of Jesus seem to me, I confess, so xvi PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION penetrative and profound that I am unable to conceive of anything higher in principle; but, like all fruitful ideas, their full meaning can be grasped only when they are viewed in the light of the whole development of human- ity in all its phases. I cannot believe that the Christian conception of life will ever be transcended; but I should have to shut my eyes to obvious facts, were I to deny that it has undergone development and must undergo further development as time goes on. For development is not mere change, but the liv- ing process by which a fruitful principle reveals the breadth and depth of its power. In this process the speculations of Christian thinkers, from St. Paul downwards, have had their place, and no mean or unimportant place; and I do not think that a time will ever come when philosophical reflection upon these high themes shall have said its last word. Such reflection must be fr^e and untrammelled, or it is almost worthless. Philosophy, it is true, is somewhat slow-footed, and to certain minds its method is cold and distasteful, especially when it is predominantly analytic, as Goethe PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION xvii complained that it is apt to be. I confess to a certain sympathy with those who take this view; but I think that what offends them is not so much philosophy itself, as certain phi- losophies which, from various causes, fall into abstraction, and not least those which live in the atmosphere of common sense or the rarer atmosphere of the special sciences. It is be- cause Idealism, as here set forth, seems to me to express in terms of thought what in religion and in the highest art is expressed in terms of feeling and imagination, that I venture to commend it to those who feel the need, in an age of reflection, of being true to the intellect as well as the heart. Surely it is almost a truism that the only convincing Apologia which in these days can be made for a religion is to give adequate grounds for holding it to be fundamentally rational. If this thesis were really indefensible, there can be little doubt that Christianity must some day be added to the list of " creeds outworn." The additional matter contained in this vol- ume was recently given as part of a course of lectures, delivered before the Theological xviii PREFACE TO THE SECOJVD EDITION Alumni Association of the university with which I have the honour to be connected. For the last few years it has been my duty to give a short course of lectures on some topic bearing upon the relations of philosophy and theology. This lectureship was instituted by Sir Sandford Fleming, C.M.G., the Chan- cellor of Queen's University, and it is with special pleasure that I take this public oppor- tunity of thanking him for the stimulus which it has given to my own studies. It is proper to add that, as I am allowed perfect free- dom in the choice of a subject, the lectures of this session were written with a view to their subsequent publication as part of this book, should a second edition be called for. In their preparation I have been indebted to Stallo's Concepts and Theories of Modern Physics, Herbert's Realistic Assumptions of Modern Science, Paulsen's Introduction to Philosophy, and one or two recent articles of Dr. Le Conte. In a more indirect way I have re- ceived great aid from Mr. Bradley's Appear- ance and Reality, which seems to me the most suggestive and original metaphysical work of PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION xix our day. While I agree with many of the criti- cisms of defective theories made by these writers, I am unable to accept their positive philosophy as a whole, though I regard them as each in his own way contributing to that general idealistic view of the world, which, as I believe, is cer- tain to survive by its intrinsic reasonableness. I am happy to be able to supplement the criticism of Transcendental Geometry con- tained in Chapter VII by one or two passages from a paper read before the Royal Society of Canada by a distinguished mathematician. " It is argued," says Professor N. F. Dupuis, " that a four-dimensional space may possibly be pro- jective into a figure of three dimensions." This analogy " proves nothing whatever A plane can be projected into a line only when the plane to be projected is normal to the plane of pro- jection. But it is impossible to know, from anything in the nature of the projection itself, whether the original was higher or of the same dimensions as the projection. . . . Reasoning from analogy, all that we are justified in saying is, that, if there be such a thing as a four- dimensional space, our solid figures may possi- bly be projections from figures in that space, XX PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION- although we fail to conceive how such a projec- tion could be effected. But we are certainly not justified in assuming that there is a four- dimensional space, unless we can first know something about the nature of a figure in such space. ... It is said that the mathematician frequently works upon the assumption of a four- dimensional space, as when he employs four co-ordinates for the sake of homogeneity, and in many similar operations. Now, in the oper- ations here referred to, the mathematician is employing the symbolic language of algebra, in which the symbols stand for and denote quan- tities or magnitudes and operations, which by a circumlocution can always be expressed in words. . . . To say that, because o^ denotes the square on the line-segment x, and ^ denotes the cube on the same, therefore x"" must denote a four-dimensional figure of equal dimensions on the line-segment, is no proof of anything, unless we assume, to begin with, that every homogeneous algebraic expression must have an interpretation in real geometry, which is a glaring example oi petitio principal Queen's University, Kingston, Canada, 26th July, 1897. INTRODUCTORY PREFACE The present work has grown out of lect- ures recently delivered before the Philosophi- cal Union of the University of California. What is called Part I. is the expansion of a lecture on "The Greek and Christian Ideals of Life," and the remainder contains the sub- stance of two lectures in defence of Idealism, with a good deal of additional matter. The historical matter of the first part does not pretend to be a complete presentation of the development of religion. It was my first intention to attempt such a presentation, but I soon found that it was impossible to com- press so abundant a material within the limits assigned to me, and I have therefore con- fined myself to a statement of the general course of religious development, with a more particular consideration of the Greek and Jewish ideals of life, as compared with the xxii INTRODUCTORY PREFACE Christian. In treating of these topics, I have avoided all polemical discussion, aiming rather to give the results of many years of reading and reflection, than to occupy space with a consideration of conflicting views. The chap- ter on the Christian Ideal is based upon a study of the synoptic gospels, as read in the light of modern historical and philosophical criticism. Here, above all, it seemed advisable to avoid as far as possible all purely doc- trinal topics, concentrating attention entirely upon the conception of life which may be, as I think, constructed from the sayings of Jesus himself. I am by no means indifferent to the development by theologians of the fundamental ideas of the Founder of Christianity, but it seems to me that the wonderful power and persuasiveness of those ideas is most apparent when they are exhibited in their naked purity. It seems almost necessary to say a word or two upon the use of the term " Idealism." The objection has been raised that no school of thought has an exclusive right to the title. In answer to this objection perhaps I can- not do better than try to explain why I INTRODUCTORY PREFACE xxiii think the term " Idealism " rfiay be fairly employed to designate the general theory which is here advocated. I presume it will be admitted that the originator of the philosophical doctrine of Idealism was Plato, and that Plato conceived of the first principle of all things as reason (Noi)?), also maintaining that it is in virtue of reason, as distinguished from sensible percep- tion, that man obtains a knowledge of that principle. Now, modern Idealism, as I under- stand it, agrees with Plato on these two points, and therefore its claim to the name does not seem either arrogant or unreason- able. No system has a right to call itself " idealistic," in the Platonic sense, which does not in some form accept the doctrine of the rationality and knowability of the real. Applying this test, we must exclude Agnosti- cism, which denies that we can know the real as it is in itself; Scepticism, which re- fuses to admit that we can make any abso- lute affirmation whatever, either positive or negative ; and Sensationalism or Empiricism, which finds in the sensible and its custom- xxiv INTRODUCTORY PREFACE ary modes of conjunction the only knowable world. To call by the name of Idealism, as is sometimes done, a doctrine which reduces all knowable reality to individual states or feelings, is surely an unwarrantable use of the term. If it is said that, interpreted in the wide sense here given to it. Idealism must include systems differing so greatly as those of Des- cartes and Hegel, or of Spinoza and Lotze, I entirely agree. The systems of Descartes, Spinoza, Leibnitz, Kant, Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, and Lotze all seem to me to be forms of Idealism, and the only question is how far any of them can claim to be true to the principle that "the real is rational." The test, therefore, of an idealistic philosophy is its ability to provide a system of ideas which shall best harmonise with the principle upon which Idealism is based; or, rather, the suc- cess of an idealistic philosophy must consist in its ability to prove that "the real is rational," and that man is capable of knowing it to be rational. I am very far from affirm- ing that the hurried sketch of an idealistic INTRODUCTORY PREFACE xxv philosophy here presented fulfils that demand: all that is attempted is to expose the irrele- vancy of certain objections which have been made from a misunderstanding of what Ideal- ism affirms, and to indicate the main line of thought which it must follow, and the main conclusions to which it leads. It may help to indicate the points in which Idealism, as here presented, differs from some of the great historical forms which it has assumed, if I state wherein these seem to be defective. In doing so, it will not be possi- ble to enter into detail, or to support by rea- soned proof the conclusions to which I have been led. I shall therefore have to assume a general acquaintance with the history of philosophy on the part of the reader, and I beg him to take the criticisms which I shall make simply as results, the evidence for which I hope to give in detail on another occasion. Plato may be called the Father of Idealism, though, no doubt, his doctrine was a develop- ment from the Idealism implied in the Nou? of Anaxagoras, and still more clearly in the Socratic view of universals. How far, then, xxvi /INTRODUCTORY PREFACE may it be said that Plato was untrue to his central idea of the rationality and knowability of the real? His main defect, as it seems to me, was in virtually opposing the real to the actual or so-called "sensible." This defect is obvious in his theory, or one of his theories, that Art consists in the " imitation " of ordinary " sensible " actuality. The simi- lar defect in his Philosophy of Religion it will not be necessary to exhibit here, as I have dealt with it in the body of the work; but a word may be said in regard to his defective Theory of Knowledge. Just as Plato at last rejects Art on the ground that it only represents or imitates the "sensible," so he shows a decided tendency to separate the universal from the particular. He does, indeed, maintain that whatever is real must be self-active ; but in separating reason, as it exists in us, from sensible perception, he virtually empties reason of all content, and makes its objects pure abstractions. The philosophy of Aristotle is beset by similar defects, though in him the contrast of the real or ideal and the actual is less INTRODUCTORY PREFACE xxvii rigid and is more obviously rfi process of being transcended. Like Plato, he starts from the " mimetic " theory of Art, but he is led to make assertions which are contra- dictory of his starting-point. Thus he virtually asserts (i) that Art is such an in- terpretation of the actual as serves to bring out its deeper meaning, (2) that it gives rise to a feeling of self-harmony, and (3) that its object is spiritual forces in their deepest reality. Yet, since he never abandoned the view that Art is an " imitation " of the sensible, it cannot be said that he attained to a self-consistent theory. The reason for this discrepancy comes to light in his Philosophy of Religion, where he does not get beyond the idea of God as a self-centred Being, and is therefore forced to conceive of the world as related to God in an external or arbitrary way. Similarly, in his Theory of Knowledge, he shrinks from the admission that the actual is rational. There is always in things, as he thinks, a recalcitrant element or "matter," which is the source of "contingency" or "chance." It is not merely that human xxviii mTRODUCTORY PREFACE knowledge cannot completely comprehend the actual, but the actual is itself imperfect, and therefore the ideal " forms " as they exist for the divine reason, being entirely free from " matter," are essentially different from the actual, in which " form " is always more or less sunk in " matter." When we pass from ancient to modern philosophy, we find the same problem of the reconciliation of the real and the actual con- fronting us; but the antagonism seems more difficult of solution, because the contrast of the finite and the infinite has been sharpened by the explicit claim of the individual to ac- cept nothing which does not commend itself to his reason. By Descartes, two opposite methods are employed, — the method of abstraction and the method of definition. In the use of the former, he is led to maintain that the only permanent or unchanging attribute of body is geometrical extension ; in employing the latter, he assumes that there are a number of real things, each having a definite or limited amount of extension. Spinoza turns INTRODUCTORY PREFACE xxix the former view against the latter, pointing out that there is nothing in the idea of pure extension which entitles us to conceive of it as broken up into parts. There can there- fore, he argues, be no individual bodies, but only a single substance without parts or limits. Leibnitz, again, agrees with Spinoza in holding that pure space has no limits, but the inference he draws is that space is not an attribute of real substance, but a pure abstraction, derived from our experience of the order which obtains among the confused objects of sense. Thus all the spatial deter- minations of things, as merely confused ideas, have no existence from the point of view of thought; a view which converts the actual into pure illusion. To Descartes it seemed that the human mind cannot comprehend the ends which God must be supposed to have in creation, and therefore he maintained that we must give up the vain search for final causes. " All God's ends are hidden in the inscrutable abyss of his wisdom." Descartes, however, tacitly assumed that there are such ends, if only we XXX INTRODUCTORY PREFACE could discover them. Such a doctrine is mani- festly self-contradictory, and therefore Spinoza was only following out this side of the Car- tesian doctrine to its lojijical result when he denied final causes altogether. Leibnitz, on the other hand, refused to admit that human knowledge is limited to the orderly movements of nature, as both Descartes and Spinoza as- sumed, and therefore he maintained that, with- out the idea of final cause, or activity directed towards an end, we cannot explain the world at all. We must therefore conceive of every real being or " monad " as self-active and pur- posive. Each " monad " is ever striving to make explicit what is already contained ob- scurely in it, and each " represents " the whole world from its own point of view, so that all "monads," without any actual connexion with one another, harmonise in their perceptions. Now (ci) it is a pure assumption that there are absolutely independent "monads," in which there already exists obscurely all that after- wards comes to more or less clear expression ; an assumption which has no better warrant than the preconception that identity is incom- INTRODUCTORY PREFACE xxxi patiblc with development. (Jb) It is equally an assuinption that each monad " represents " the world. On the l.eibnitzian hypothesis of purely individual beings, each shut up within itself, there can be no way of proving that there is any world to " represent." The only real individuality, as I should maintain, is that of a being which knows itself because it knows other beings, {c) When he comes to explain the " harmony " of the monads with one another, Leibnitz has to fall back upon the idea of the selective activity of the divine will. Out of all the possible worlds which lay before the divine mind, that was chosen which was the best on the whole. Here, therefore, in the final result of the Leibnitz- ian philosophy, we see the fundamental dis- crepancy which vitiates his whole system. The actual world after all is not rational, but only as rational as God could make it; a theory which leaves us no ground for in- ferring the rationality of God at all, but on the contrary presupposes an absolute limit in the divine mind. Thus the Idealism of Leibnitz, suggestive as it is, ultimately breaks xxxii INTRODUCTORY PREFACE down in contradiction. Can we, then, accept the Critical Idealism of Kant ? I cannot do more here than indicate the defects in the philosophy of Kant which prevent us from regarding it as final. Its fundamental imperfection is the abstract op- position of the empirical and the ideal, as if the former were not implicitly the latter. This opposition meets us first in his theory of knowledge, in which a virtual contrast is drawn between what is knowable and what lies beyond the boundaries of knowledge. Such a contrast is ultimately unmeaning. The only reality by reference to which we can criticise the knowable world of ordinary experience is a reality which includes, though it further elucidates, that world. Failing to recognise this truth, the philosophy of Kant is vexed by the perpetual recurrence of self- contradiction in some new form, a self-con- tradiction which is never finally transcended, (i) In the Esthetic, Kant adopts the com- promise, that space and time belong to the subject, while individual things in space and time are relative to an unknown object. But, INTRODUCTORY PREFACE xxxiii as these individuals must enter into know- ledge, he is compelled to regard the unknown object as a mere blank, and such an object cannot be contrasted with anything; it is, in fact, merely the known w^orld stripped of its determinateness and hypostatised. Kant is here really criticising the known world by an abstract phase of itself, and pronouncing the former to be lower instead of higher than the latter. The pure object can only be regarded as higher than the known world, in so far as the spatial and temporal world is seen to be a lower form of the knowable world. In this sense, no doubt, we may say that the undefined object, or thing in itself, indicates the world as it exists in idea, i.e, the world as completely determined. (2) In the Analytic, Kant takes another step in the process by which he gives a higher meaning to the thing in itself. The whole of the knowable world is now shown to involve the unifying activity of the knowing subject, though with the reservation that the object is conceived as the source of the undefined "manifold of sense." But, in truth, there is xxxiv INTRODUCTORY PREFACE no undefined " manifold " for knowledge, and hence the thing in itself is, even more pal- pably than before, a magni nominis umbra, (3) This is partly recognised by Kant him- self when he goes on to consider the Un- conditioned in its three forms, — the soul, the world, and God. (a) His criticism of Rational Psychology is virtually a recognition of the truth, that the pure or unrelated sub- ject is a mere fiction of abstraction. Yet he does not draw the proper inference, that the real subject exists only in and through its relations to the object. Such a subject is not mechanically determinable, being self- conscious and self-active, but it does not and could not exist, were not the system of nature what it is. (b) Kant's criticism of Rational Cosmology is valid, so far as it points out that the reflective understanding seeks to affirm one of two related terms as if they were mutually exclusive; but Kant does not see that the reconciliation of these opposites is possible without recourse being had to the unknowable region of " noumena." (c) The criticism of Rational Theology is INTRODUCTORY PREFACE xxxv valid as against the dualistic separation of being and thought, the world and God; but Kant's own solution is inadequate, because he regards these oppositions as holding ab- solutely within the sphere of the knowable, whereas they are really oppositions which carry their own refutation with them. When he passes from the Theoretical to the Practical Reason, Kant at last recognises that the self-conscious subject is synthetic or productive ; in other words, that here the real object is not opposed to the subject as something unintelligible, but, on the contrary, is bound up with the very nature of the subject. But the shadow of the " thing in itself " still haunts him, and therefore he con- ceives this objective world as merely an ideal which demands realisation, but which can never be realised. The way out of this difficulty is to recognise that the ideal is the real: that morality is not a mere "beyond," but is actually realised objectively in human institutions, which themselves have perma- nence only as they are in harmony with the eternal nature of the world, or, in other words, with the nature of God. xxxvi INTRODUCTORY PREFACE In the Critique of Judgment Kant makes a final effort to overcome the duahsm with which he started. In aesthetic feeHng he finds a sort of unconscious testimony to the unity of the phenomenal and the real, and in organised beings he meets with a phase of things which refuses to come under the head either of the phenomenal or the noumenal. Thus, " as by a side gesture," Kant points beyond the abstractions of the sensible and the supersensible to their actual concrete unity; but the preconception with which he started prevents him from identifying the ideal and the real, and the most he can per- suade himself to say is, that man is entitled to a rational faith in God, freedom and im- mortality, though these are objects which lie beyond the range of his knowledge. I should be sorry if what has been said should suggest the idea that philosophy is merely a series of brilliant failures, in which each new thinker vainly strives to prove the unprovable proposition, that the actual world when properly understood is rational; rather, as it seems to me, faith in the rationality of INTRODUCTORY PREFACE xxxvii the universe is the incentive and presupposi- tion of all philosophical progress. Nor are the failures of successive philosophies in any case absolute; with each step in advance the problem becomes clearer and more easy of solution. How far the outline of Idealism contained in the second part of this essay is free from the objections which I have tried to indicate, must be left for the reader to determine. Perhaps I may venture to say that, if it has any special value, that value lies in the attempt to reconcile the reality of individual things, and especially the freedom and individuality of man, with the fundamental principle of Idealism, that the actual properly understood is a manifestation in various degree of one self-conscious and self-determining spiritual Being. It would be difficult to enumerate all the books to which I have been directly or in- directly indebted, especially in the prepara- tion of the first part of this essay; but I must not omit to mention the various works of the Master of Balliol, and of Professor Pfleiderer, as well as Leopold Schmidt's Die xxxviii INTRODUCTORY PREFACE Ethik der alien Griechen, Mr. J ebb's Growth and Influence of Classical Greek Poetry, with the introductions in his edition of Sophocles, Mr. Bosanquet's History of Esthetic, Dr. Driver's Introduction to the Literature of the Old Testament and Isaiah, Weber's System der altsynagogalen palastinischen Theologie, Schiirer's History of the fewish People, Keim's fesus of Nazara, and Weizsacker's Das Apos- tolische Zeitalter. In preparing the chapter on the Christian Ideal I also received valu- able assistance from my colleague, Professor Macnaughton. JOHN WATSON. Queen's University, Kingston, Canada, October i, 1896. PART I THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE IN RELATION TO THE GREEK AND JEWISH IDEALS THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE CHAPTER I HISTORICAL CONNEXION OF MORALITY AND RELIGION Christianity, as it issued fresh from the mind of its founder, embodied a conception of life which brought religion into indissol- uble connexion with morality. The whole human race was conceived of as in idea a single spiritual organism, in which each man gains his own perfection by self-conscious identification with all the rest, and this com- munity of life was held to be possible only because man is identical in nature, though not in person, with the one divine principle which is manifested in all forms of being. Man, it was therefore held, is unable to come to unity with himself until he has surrendered his whole being to the influence UNIVERSITY 2 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE of the Holy Spirit. On this view there is no basis for the moral ideal, and no possi- bility of its realisation, apart from the relig- ious ideal ; for man cannot accept as the standard of his life an ideal which is not in absolute harmony with the ultimate prin- ciple of the universe ; nor, even if he did, could his effort to realise it be anything but the struggle with an alien power too strong for him, — a struggle as futile as the attempt of the Teutonic giant of the northern Saga to lift the deep-seated earth from its foun- dations. AiKrming that the life of man is moral, just in so far as it is in harmony with the divine nature, Christianity rests upon the belief that "goodness is the nature of things," and therefore it maintains that evil, which it regards as positive and an- tagonistic to good, exists in order to be transcended, and must succumb to the all- conquering power of goodness. Accordingly, man's religious faith, which alone gives mean- ing to his moral effort, is for the individual the source of a joyous consciousness of unity with himself, just because in overcoming the CONNEXION OF MORALITY AND RELIGION 3 world he overcomes his own lower self. It is true that the evil which exists without and within him can never be completely abol- ished, but it is always in process of being abolished; and therefore the Christian is en- abled to preserve his optimism even in face of the worst forms of evil. No one will deny that in this triumphant faith Jesus and his first followers lived, but the objection may be raised, that the simple faith of an earlier age is not possible for us in these days, or at least not until the doubts and perplexities, which the facts of experience, the results of science, and the deepened reflection of our time inevitably suggest, have been fairly weighed and re- solved. The wounds of reflection, it may be said, are too deep to be healed by a child- like faith in God and man, which rests rather upon sentiment than upon rational evidence. Many will go even further, and maintain that morality not only can, but must, be divorced from religion, and that in any case it does not depend for its support upon any form of religious belief. 4 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE Various reasons may be given for this sep- aration of morality from religion, but they will all be found to rest ultimately on the assumption that it is not possible for man, with his limited faculties and knowledge, to get behind the veil of phenomena and grasp reality as it is in itself. Thus the real be- comes simply a name for that which lies beyond the range of our finite vision, land morality is therefore conceived as merely that course of conduct which we must adopt in order to make the most of the circumstances in which we happen to be placed. So firm a hold has this doctrine taken of the mod- ern mind, that not merely those who reject Christianity, but even some of its professed champions, such as Mr. Balfour, regard moral ideas as the only foundation upon which even a " provisional theory " of life can be based ; and we even find Browning, in one of his moods, suggesting that the limitation of knowledge is essential to the stability and progress of morality. An attempt will be made, in the second part of this essay, to show that religion and CONNEXION- OF MORALITY AND RELIGION 5 morality cannot be separated from each other without the destruction of both, and that the essential identity of the human and divine natures, which is the central idea of Chris- tianity, is the legitimate result of philosoph- ical reflection. Meantime, it may be pointed out that the whole history of man goes to show that the connexion of morality with^ religion is so close that no advance in the one has ever taken place without a corre- sponding advance in the other. What is distinctive of Christianity is not the union of morality with religion, but the comprehen- siveness of the principle upon which that union is based. Every religion embodies the highest ideal of a people, and the morality which corresponds to it is the special form in which that ideal is sought to be realised. It follows that, when the religious ideal is no longer an adequate expression of the more developed consciousness of a people, the moral ideal is also perceived to be in need of revision. Thus the history of re- ligion is inseparable from the history of morality. 6 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE That religion and morality have, as a mat- ter of fact, always been connected in the closest way, might be proved by a detailed examination of the whole history of religion ; but, as the proof would lead us too far afield, one or two instances where the con- nexion seems at first sight to be broken will have to suffice. (i) It has been maintained that in early times religion had nothing to do with moral- ity. That this view is untenable, it will not be difficult to show. One of the earliest forms of religion is the belief in a god or totem, who is at once some being lower than man, and yet is regarded as the ancestor of a particular family or tribe. The theory of Mr. Spencer, that this form of religion orig- inated in the worship of ancestors and was afterwards developed into totemism, cannot be accepted, because it assumes that primi- tive man was at a higher stage of devel- opment than his descendants. If primitive man was able to draw a clear distinction between himself and lower forms of being, it is inconceivable that his descendants should CONNEXION OF MORALITY AND RELIGION 7 have seen no fundamental distinction between them. The truth seems to be that the totem, which is ahnost always a plant, an animal, or other natural object, is viewed as divine because it forms the medium for that haunting sense of something incomprehensi- Sble and therefore divine, of which even early- man is not entirely destitute. The totem is . the form in which this feeling is objectified, and it then becomes the vehicle for the ideal union of the family or tribe. Thus the re- ligion of early man is bound up with the elementary moral ideas which rule his life. The only social bond of which he can con- ceive is that of the family or tribe. More- over, the members of each family or tribe, while they are closely related to one another, are usually hostile to other families or tribes ; and hence the morality which corresponds to this phase of religion is based upon hatred of all who fall beyond its limited range. Here, therefore, the correspondence of religion and morality is obvious: a religion in which the object of worship is common to the members of a certain stock naturally goes with a form 8 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE of morality which involves hatred of the members of all other stocks. This hatred, as it is inseparable from the moral ideas of early man, finds its expression in his relig- ion : and hence the totems of other families or tribes are regarded as evil spirits, whose baneful influence can be counteracted only by cunning and magical spells. (2) Perhaps it may be conceded that the morality of early man is a faithful reflex of his religion, but it may be held that their connexion is dissolved when an advance has been made to a more developed form of society. It is easy to understand that, in the earlier stages of human history, whatever is sanctioned by religion should be blindly followed ; but at a more advanced stage, when reflection begins to claim its rights, it may seem that progress in morality is rather hindered than aided by religion. Was it religion, it may be asked, which led in Greece to the higher morality of the age of Pericles } Would it not be truer to say that the relig- ion of Greece was far behind its morality, and offered a stubborn resistance to its progress.'* CONNEXION OF MORALITY AND RELIGION 9 " The Greek poets," as Mr. Max Muller says, " had an instinctive aversion to anything ex- cessive or monstrous, yet they would relate of their gods what would make the most savage of Red Indians creep and shudder." Does not this fact clearly show that morality advances independently of religion, and may even be in conflict with it ? The answer to this argument for the sepa- ration of morality and religion is not far to seek. The moral ideas of the age of Pericles were no doubt antagonistic to the older religious ideas preserved in Greek my- thology, but they were in perfect harmony with the religious ideas which really ruled the best minds. The sanctity which attaches to religion long preserves traditional forms of belief from being openly assailed, but this is quite consistent with a transformation of the whole spirit of the earlier faith. In estimat- ing the character of a religion we must in all cases make allowance for the survival of ideas which have lost their power and mean- ing, and concentrate our attention upon the new content which is preserved in the old lO THE CHRIST/ AN- WEAL OF LIFE earthen vessels. The application of this prin- ciple, which is universal in its range, is in the present case obvious. The Greek relig- ion, like the religion of every progressive people, was in continuous process of develop- ment; but in its later phases it retained elements which, though they were not ex- plicitly rejected, occupied a very subordinate place and were practically ignored. The real religious beliefs of Greece in the age of Pericles were embodied, not in its mythology, but in the interpretation of the legends given by Pindar, ^schylus, and Sophocles. When this is once seen, it becomes obvious that the religion of Greece, so far from being at any time on a lower plane than its morality,, was in all cases an expression of the highest ideal of which the Greek was capable, an ideal which he was seeking to realise in the various forms of his social life. (3) As the morality of Greece seems at first sight to be in advance of its religion, so it may appear that the religious ideal of the Jews is entirely divorced from their moral conceptions. The continual refrain of their CONNEXION OF MORALITY AND RELIGION 1 1 great prophets, especially those of the eighth century, is that Israel, while she accepts the lofty ideal of God revealed long ago to their fathers, has, in practice, forsaken the Lord, and is governed by the lowest ethical ideal. When, however, we penetrate beneath the form of the prophetic utterances, it becomes obvious that the Jews are no exception to the rule that the moral and religious ideas of a people are the precise counterpart of each other. The Jewish prophet refers the higher conception of God, with which he is himself inspired, to an original revelation given by God to his people in the past, while in truth that conception has been gradually evolved out of a lower and cruder form of faith. It is no doubt true that the religious ideal upon which he insists is far in advance of the moral ideas of his time, but it is equally in advance of its religious ideas. The mass of the Jewish people had never freed themselves from the earlier idea of a tribal god who was gracious to Israel and terrible to her enemies; and hence their morality was not in harmony with that ideal 12 THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE of an absolutely holy God, " of purer eyes than to behold iniquity," which had disclosed itself in the higher consciousness of the prophets. The religious conceptions of the Jewish people as a whole were, therefore, in entire harmony with their moral conceptions. The contradiction is not between a pure and lofty religion and a low moral ideal, but be- tween the lower ideal, religious and moral, beyond which the people had not advanced, and the higher ideal embodied in the pro- phetic utterances. It is no doubt a radical distinction between the Greek and the Jew- ish religion, that the former was simply an idealised transcript of society as it actually existed, while the latter, in its higher form, was a picture of a righteous kingdom that was placed in some far-off future; but this distinction, important as it is, does not im- ply that the Jewish religion created a di- vorce between the ideal and the actual. For, though the prophets continually speak of a time when Israel shall " return " to the Lord, this " return " is in reality an advance to a higher form of religion and morality. The CONNEXION OF MORALITY AND RELIGION 13 ideal of the future is always conceived to consist in a religious reformation which will manifest itself in a moral regeneration; and though, at a very late age, the hope of de- liverance from outward and inward evil by a natural process of development had been lost, the Jewish mind never entirely aban- doned its belief in the triumph of good and the destruction of evil. It is thus evident that throughout the whole history of Israel religion was in the most intimate connexion with morality. Without seeking further to elaborate a point which seems almost self-evident, it may now be assumed that as a matter of historical fact there never has been any real antagonism between the religion and the morality of a people, but, on the contrary, the most intimate connexion. How, indeed, should it be otherwise, since every religion is an attempt to prevent the life of man from dissolving into a chaos of fragments by referring it to a principle which reduces it to order and coherence ? There can be no morality without the belief in a life higher 14 THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE than sense and passion, and this beHef must draw its support from faith in a divine prin- ciple which ensures victory to the higher life. We must not forget, however, that re- ligion, like morality, ia a process which can reach its goal only when the divine princi- ple is so comprehensive that it explains the whole of life, and leaves no difficulty un- solved. Thus the religious and moral ideals of a people, though they sum up all that is best and noblest in its life, may fall far short of an ultimate explanation. That nei- ther the Greek nor the Jewish ideal had reached a satisfactory conception of the true nature and relation of God, man, and the world, it will not be hard to show; and it is therefore obvious that a higher synthesis was imperatively demanded. But the impor- tant question, it will be said, is not whether Greece and Judea failed, — a proposition no one is likely to dispute, — but whether Chris- tianity is not also another, even if it be a more splendid, failure. That this is the only really important question for us may be at once admitted, but it will hardly be denied CONNEXION OF MORALITY AND RELIGION 15 that a clear conception of what the Christian ideal of life in its permanent essence is, and wherein its superiority to other ideals con- sists, is a necessary preparation for an intelli- gent estimate of its claim to be the ultimate ideal of life. To answer these questions thor- oughly would involve a critical estimate of all the religions of the world. In the pres- ent essay, nothing so ambitious will be at- tempted ; but perhaps a careful examination and comparison of the Greek, Jewish, and Christian ideals of life may be as convincing as a wider survey. Before entering upon this task it may help to illustrate somewhat more fully the thesis of the present chapter, that religion and morality have always developed pari passu, if we glance at the different paths which the religious consciousness has followed among different peoples, and the goal which they have severally attained. There seems reason to believe that all re- ligions are either totemistic or have devel- oped from totemism. We may, therefore, regard this form of religion as, if not the 1 6 THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE earliest, at least a very early form of religion. Traces of it are found even in those nations in which civilisation originated, and which reached a much higher ideal of life, such as the Chinese, the Indian, the Greek, and the Jewish ; and indeed it is, as we have seen, the natural form in which the ideal of the family or the tribe is embodied, since that ideal is based entirely upon the tie of blood. We may thus regard totemism as the orig- inal matrix from which all other forms of religion were developed. Totemism, however, gives way to a higher form of religion, whenever a people advances to anything like a settled form of society. This second stage of religion, among all the great nations of antiquity, except the Jewish, whose religious development is unique, con- sists in the worship of the divine as mani- fested in those universal powers of nature — the heavens, the sun, the winds, etc. — which exercise so large an influence upon the natural life of man, while yet they are altogether beyond the control of his will. Now it is easy to see how a people, who CONNEXION OF MORALITY JM) )fELIGION \J embodied their religious ideal in these great natural powers, should also have a higher moral ideal than races which never got beyond the stage of totemism. Early man found in his totem something higher than himself, but the divinity he ascribed to it was not so much in the object as in his own mind, or at least it was only in the object in the sense that nothing can exist which is not in some way a manifestation of the divine. But, when the divine is found in objects, which in force or splendour surpass the weak physical energy of man, the object selected is not altogether inadequate as a symbol of that spiritual power which man is feeling after; and as it is a universal object, it is not an inappropriate medium of the new ideal of a social unity embracing a number of tribes allied in blood. Thus the worship of the great powers of nature supplies a religious ideal which helps to unite all the members of allied tribes by the bond of a common faith. From the worship of these natural powers the higher races advance to the stage of what is ordinarily called polytheism. The transi- 1 8 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE tion is effected by the tendency to personify those powers, and thus to bring them nearer to man. It is at this point that a highly significant divergence takes place, a diver- gence which determines the direction in which the subsequent development takes place. The Egyptian and Indian do indeed personify the gods, and thus for the time lift them out of the lower rank of mere powers of nature, but they do not humanise them. Hence their polytheism takes the form of what Mr. Max Miiller has called henotheism. The ten- dency to unity, as well as multiplicity, is in operation from the very dawn of religion. Even races who have not advanced beyond the primitive stage of totemism always have a god who is regarded as higher than the other totems, and in nature-worship the heavens is naturally taken as the highest embodiment of the divine. The tendency to unification is therefore present from the first, but in the henotheistic phase of polytheism it assumes the peculiar form that each god becomes at the time of worship the only one who is present to the consciousness of the wor- CONNEXION- OF MORALITY AND RELIGION 19 shipper, and hence to him are attributed for the time being all the attributes which at other times are distributed among a number of gods. Now the importance of directing attention to this tendency to henotheism is that it explains why the Egyptian and Indian religions developed, not into monotheism, but into pantheism. The Greek religion, on the other hand, not only personified but human- ised the gods, and the clearly cut types thus formed became a permanent possession of the race. Hence, when the Greek finally abandoned polytheism, his religion developed into monotheism, not into pantheism ; and so long as he remained polytheistic the in- stinct for unity was satisfied by conceiving of Zeus as the Father and Ruler of the gods, or later as the representative of their united will. Now, whether polytheism assumes the henotheistic or the Greek form, it is obvious that it presents an ideal which serves to unite all the members of a nation by a common worship. Nor does it seem fanciful to say that polytheism is the natural form which the religious ideal assumes among nations 20 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE which have been either formed into a single political unit by a combination of tribes allied in blood, or into a number of independent units united only by the bonds of a common descent and a common religion ; in any case, it serves as the vehicle for the religious ideal of peoples who cannot conceive of a wider bond than that of the nation, or of the nation as other than a political unity based upon the natural tie of blood. Polytheism, therefore, tended to perpetuate absolute dis- tinctions of caste, or of master and slave, and it naturally fostered a proud contempt for all who belonged to another nation, and therefore could not claim descent from the gods of their country. Here, therefore, we have another proof, if further proof were needed, of the close correspondence between religion and morality. Polytheism, as has already been indicated, develops either into pantheism, or into mon- otheism. When it is of a henotheistic type, as in the case of the Egyptians and Indians, it naturally takes the former direction ; the Greek religion, with its definitely characterised CONNEXION OF MORALITY AND RELIGION 21 human types, as naturally follows the latter direction. Both the Egyptian and the Hindu are deficient in that poetic and artistic fac- ulty, which is characteristic of the Greek, and hence they never succeed in imparting freedom and spirituality to their gods. With the rise of reflection the tendency to unity, which has already shown itself in their hen- otheism, carries them beyond the tendency to multiplicity, and as their gods have not been conceived as endowed with intelligence and will, they come to conceive of the divine as a purely abstract being, of which nothing can be said but that it is. To this relig- ious ideal corresponds the ethical ideal. If the divine nature is absolutely without dis- tinction, man can become divine only by the destruction of all that constitutes his separate individuality. Thus pantheism leads to the dissolution of all fixed moral distinc- tions, and therefore to the denial of any radical distinction between good and evil. " Whatever is, is right." It can therefore look with perfect calmness upon the wildest aberrations of passion, and it leads in men 22 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE of a higher type to asceticism, only because it regards passion as a form of that universal illusion, or Maya, which supposes the finite to be real. The Greek religion, as the product of a ♦ race of poets and artists, whose nature re- sponded gladly to all the divine beauty and order of the world and of human life, could not thus pass into a joyless pantheism. Hence, under the influence of its poets and philosophers, it developed into a monothe- ism, in which the divine was conceived as a single spiritual Being, endowed with in- telligence and will. It is significant that the Greeks only reached this stage, when their narrow civic state had already revealed its inadequacy, and when the bond of nation- ality, which had been hitherto preserved by loyalty to the national faith, had lost its power. Thus the wider conception of re- • ligion was reflected in the virtual dissolution of civic and national morality. It is time, how- ever, to consider more carefully the strength and weakness of the Greek ideal of life. This will be done in the following chapter. CHAPTER II THE GREEK IDEAL Starting, like the other Indo-European peoples, from the worship of the great powers of nature, the Greeks developed a form of religion which is the highest type of poly- theism. This religion was the embodiment of that love of beauty, truth, and freedom, which is distinctive of the Greek spirit. In the Homeric poems, the transition from the worship of nature has already been made. The gods are not only personified, but hu- manised. Turning his eyes to the expanse of heaven, the early Greek expressed his consciousness of the divine in the majestic form of Zeus, whose nod shook the whole heavens and the earth. The physical splen- dour of the sun became for him the radi- ant form of Apollo, shooting down gleaming arrows from his silver bow. Thus was grad- 23 24 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE ually formed, not without the addition of new elements and even new gods, sometimes borrowed from Semitic sources but invari- ably transmuted into higher form, the pan- theon of glorious shapes which filled the imagination of Homer. The divine nature is conceived as manifested in distinct types, each possessed of intelligence and will, and embodied in human forms, which exhibit the utmost perfection of physical beauty. These gracious forms only differ from man in the perfection of their spiritual and physical qual- ities, and in their freedom from decay and death. Thus the Greek expresses in his re- ligion his ideal of perfect manhood as the complete harmony of soul and body. Were it possible to secure and retain for ever physi- cal, intellectual, and moral beauty, the ideal of the early Greek would be realised. That ideal, however, was one which did not sepa- rate the good of the individual from the good of society. Achilles is distinguished, not merely by splendid physical beauty, powers, and eloquence, but by his burning indignation against wrong: and, when he THE GREEK IDEAL 25 carries his resentment against Agamemnon to an extreme which threatens the destruction of the whole Greek host, he is punished by an untimely death. So Zeus is the imper- sonation of a wise and just ruler, Apollo the divine type of the poetic and religious mind, Athena the ideal of valour directed and kept in check by wise self-restraint. The Greek gods are thus the expression of the Greek ideal of a society in which the highest natural qualities are valued as a means to the realisation of a free community. The Homeric king is not a despot, but the guardian of the sacred customs on which the rights of his subjects are based. He does nothing without consulting his council of elders, and the public assembly consists of the whole body of citizens. The world of the gods is an idealised counterpart of the heroic form of society; and, in fact, the early Greek could only conceive of the di- vine as a community of gods, living in each other's society, and sympathising with the fortunes of men. The Homeric gods are thus the embodi- 26 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE ment of that free and joyous existence which was the ideal of life of the early Greek. The Greek religion is essentially a religion of this world ; for, though the Greek believed in a shadowy realm of the dead, his heart was set upon the beauty, the joy, the sunlight of this world, and he looked forward to the future life, without dread, indeed, but with a melancholy resignation. With his intrepid intellect he had a clear and sober apprehension of the shortness of life and the limitations of hu- manity, but he had not yet lost the fresh exuberance of the youth of the world; and in devotion to his country and faith in divine justice, he found all that was needed to satisfy his highest desires. Entirely free from a slavish dread of the gods, he came into their presence with joyous confidence. He did not forget that his destiny lay on the knees of the gods, but, having perfect faith in their justice, he did not prostrate himself before them with the abject submission of the Asiatic. The charm of this conception of life has never failed to exercise a peculiar fascination, and indeed it contains elements which must THE GREEK IDEAL 2/ be embodied in the modern ideal, though these must be transmuted into a higher form. Its fundamental defect is that it can be approxi- mately realised only by those who possess exceptional gifts of nature and fortune, and that it conceives of the highest life as simply the expansion of the natural life. The Greek was destitute of that profound consciousness of the Infinite which was characteristic of the Jewish religion, and therefore of the wide interval between man as he is and as he ought to be. No doubt in his deepest nature man is identical with God, but his deepest nature reveals itself only when he turns against his immediate self. Of this truth the Greek had no proper apprehension, and therefore he never got beyond the ideal of a perfect natural life, in which the spiritual and natural were in harmony with each other, and of a State in which the individual citizen found his com- plete satisfaction in devotion to the common weal. That this limited ideal could not be permanently satisfactory is shown by the grad- ual emergence of a deeper conception of life, which as time went on came more and more 2S THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE into the foreground, until it finally led, in the poets and philosophers, to a complete trans- formation of the earlier belief. Though the Greek religion is the highest form of polytheism, it has, like all polytheistic religions, the fundamental defect of having no adequate idea of the unity and spirituality of the divine nature. This defect is, in the Greek form of polytheism, made all the more prominent by the individuality ascribed to the gods. The gods, as embodied in sensible human form, are limited in space and time, and hence their relation to man is inadequately conceived. There can be no proper compre- hension of the unity and spirituality of the divine nature, so long as the divine is con- ceived as merely the perfection of the natural. Beings who are regarded as limited in space and time cannot be the source of all reality, and their relation to man can only be external. Hence the Greek gods themselves were con- ceived as having come into existence at a definite time, and their action upon men was represented as their actual sensible appearance to their favourites. Athena presents herself THE GREEK IDEAL 29 in human shape to Achilles, and persuades him to abandon his purpose of slaying Aga- memnon ; Aphrodite hides Paris in a cloud when he flees from the spear of Menelaus. Thus the life of man is represented as directly interfered with by the gods, so that man seems to be merely a puppet in their hands. This defect is inseparable from the pictorial form of the religion, which necessarily represents the spiritual as on the same plane with the natural. Even in Homer, however, there are ele- ments which show that the Greek religion must ultimately accomplish its own euthana- sia. There was in it from the first a latent contradiction which could not fail to mani- fest itself openly at a later time. The very concreteness and humanity of the gods was at variance with the instinct for unity, which could neither be suppressed nor reconciled with the polytheistic basis of the traditional faith. To a certain extent that instinct was satisfied by the conception of Zeus as the " Father of gods and men," whose authority, though it is not absolute, is higher than that 30 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE of the other gods. But this conception could only be temporarily satisfactory; and, indeed, even in Homer, there is already indicated a deeper sort of unity, which is inconsistent with this mere unity of the pictorial imagina- tion. For Homer, Hke his successors, was strongly impressed with the belief that the life of man is subject to divine control, and that his destiny is determined in accordance with absolute principles of justice. Paris violates the sacred bond which united host and guest, and punishment falls upon him- self and all his kindred. The Trojans break the oath to which they had solemnly sworn, and draw down upon themselves the punish- ment which they deserved. There was thus an absolute faith in the righteous judgments of the gods. Such a faith could not be reconciled with the caprice, partiality, and lawlessness, which were ascribed to the gods in their individual character. For they are represented as not only violating accepted moral laws, but as at variance with one an- other, and guilty of gross favouritism. This unreconciled antagonism was partly due to THE GREEK IDEAL 3 1 the survival of earlier and less elevated ideas of the divine nature, to which custom and tradition lent an adventitious sanctity, but it was also inseparable from the anthropomor- phism of the Greek religion. The conflict of competing ideas is especially apparent in the conception of Zeus, whose character as an individual is widely different from what has been called his official character as the exponent of the common will of the gods. Sometimes Homer speaks of Zeus as reward- ing or punishing men; sometimes this power is vested in the gods as a whole. In the Iliad Zeus is called the guardian of oaths, while yet Agamemnon speaks of the suffer- ings inflicted by " the gods " upon those who swear falsely. In the Odyssey there are even passages in which an abrupt transition is made from the gods to Zeus, as when Telema- chus invokes the gods, " If perchance Zeus will punish the wickedness of the suitors (I. 378)." This tendency to conceive of Zeus as the sole administrator of justice, which is manifest even in the Homeric poems, becomes more and more pronounced, so that 32 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE in the period between Homer and the Per- sian wars, it is almost invariably Zeus who is spoken of as the guardian of moral order. Thus, without any explicit rejection of poly- theism, there was a continual tendency to transcend it. Isocrates, who is the spokes- man, not of philosophers like Anaxagoras, but of the educated common sense of his time, explains the poetic representation of Zeus as king of the gods by the natural tendency to figure the divine government after the fashion of an earthly state. Besides this explicit criticism of the popular faith, the striving after a higher idea of the divine is shown in the reverential feeling which led the worshipper, in calling upon one of the gods to add, " or by whatever name thou mayst desire to be called." But nothing shows more clearly the tendency to go be- yond the earlier mode of thought than the indefinite terms by which the divine power is designated by the prose writers. They still, no doubt, speak of " the gods," but they usually employ such expressions as " the divine," "the god," ''the daemonic," when they THE GREEK IDEAL 33 have to speak of the moral government of the world. There is thus in the development of Greek thought a clearly marked tendency to unity, manifesting itself, on the one hand, in the conception of Zeus as the exponent of the common will of the gods ; and, on the other hand, in the conception of "something divine," which was not definitely embodied in the gods of the popular faith. It has been held that the Greek conception of a " fate," to which the gods as well as men are subject, indicates a certain pantheistic tendency in the Greek mind, which was only kept in check by the opposite tendency to conceive of the divine as personal. This view seems to imply that every attempt to transcend particularism and anthropomorphism indicates a movement towards pantheism. It seems more natural to say that the movement be- yond polytheism may be either towards pan- theism or monotheism, and that the special direction which the movement takes will be determined by the peculiar form of the poly- theism which forms the starting-point. In 34 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE the Greek mind, which humanised the gods, the reaction against particularism was nat- urally towards monotheism. The idea of "fate "was therefore conceived, not as a mere external necessity, but as a rational law, and the gods were regarded as subject to it only in the sense that even the divine nature was not beyond law. The more firmly the conception of a moral government of the world was grasped, the clearer was the apprehension of the apparent exceptions to it. In Homer and Hesiod, faith in divine justice assumes the simple form of a belief that the pious man is directly re- warded by a happy and fortunate life. In the Odyssey Ulysses says, that when a king is pious and just, the land is fruitful and the people prosperous. Hesiod declares that on the just man, who keeps his oath, Zeus be- stows more renown and a fairer posterity than on the unjust. It was a popular belief that impiety never fails to be punished by blind- ness, madness, or death. To the objection that the innocent were sometimes unfortunate, it was answered that they were involved in THE GREEK IDEAL 35 the misfortunes of the wicked. The similar difficulty that the wicked are often prosperous was met by saying that divine justice, though it may be delayed, always overtakes them in the end. The same idea is expressed in the well-known saying of an unknown poet, that " the mills of the gods grind slow but very small." A further modification of the idea of divine retribution was that, though the wicked man may himself escape, misfortune is sure to fall upon his posterity. We also find among the Greeks a growing scepticism of the reality of divine justice, but the best minds surmounted this scepticism by a deeper view of the relation between the divine and human, — a view which was most fully devel- oped by i^schylus and Sophocles. In these poets, in fact, the current religious and moral ideas were so deepened as to result in an ethical monotheism, though they never con- sciously surrendered the polytheism of the popular faith. ^schylus, the poet of the men who fought at Marathon and Salamis, has unbounded faith in the gods of his country. At the same time 36 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE his plastic imagination works freely on the mass of legendary material which he found ready to his hand, and into the old bottles he pours the new wine of a higher conception of the divine nature and the destiny of man. This transforming process is exhibited in his reconstruction of the myth of Prometheus. Zeus, the representative of intelligence and order, when he has dethroned Chronos, finds on the earth the miserable race of men. Their champion, the Titan Prometheus, steals " the flashing fire, mother of all arts," and conveys it to men in a hollow reed. For his insolence and deceit he must undergo proportional pun- ishment, until he has repented and submitted to the sovereign will of Zeus. Suffering but intensifies his proud and rebellious spirit, and it is only after long ages of punishment, and through the influence of Heracles, the god- like man, whose life has been spent in toil for others, that he is at last induced to give up his purpose of revenge. There seems little doubt that here, as elsewhere, ^schylus seeks to show that the world is governed with abso- lute justice, and that the true lesson of life is THE GREEK IDEAL 37 to submit to the divine will. When man sets up his own rebellious will against the Ruler of the universe, he must expect divine pun- ishment. The triple Fates and the mindful Erinyes jealously guard the sanctity of the primal ties. The doom of Troy is the divine punishment for violated hospitality. Aga- memnon perishes because his hands are stained with his daughter's blood, ^schy- lus explicitly rejects the old doctrine of the envy of the gods : it is sinful rebellion against the divine law which brings punishment in its train. The sins of the fathers are no doubt visited upon the children, but the curse never falls upon those whose hands are pure. The house of Atreus seems the prey of a malign, inevitable fate, but only because in each new representative there is a frenzy of wickedness, an infatuate hardening of the heart. When, therefore, a pure scion of this accursed stock appears, the curse is removed: he suffers in- deed, but his end is peace; and at last he returns in honour to reign over the house which he has cleansed. Thus the Erinyes become the Eumenides: the stern law of jus- 38 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE tice turns at last a gracious face to those who fear and honour the gods. But, while ^schylus conceives of Zeus as the divine representative of the whole order of society, the divine law is still conceived by him as an external law to which man must submit. Sophocles, on the other hand, while he endorses the conception of a divine law of justice, seeks to show that this law operates in man as the law of his own reason. CEdipus unwittingly violates the sacred bond of the family, and punishment inevitably follows; but his punishment is also the. recoil upon himself of his defiant self-assertion, and therefore, when he recognises that his suffering was not un- merited, he is at last reconciled to the divine will and comes to harmony with himself. Yet even in Sophocles the limitation of the Greek ideal of life is manifest; for, though he views suffering as a means of purification from self- assertion and overweening pride, he does not reach the conception that in self-sacrifice the true nature of man is revealed ; the highest point to which he attains is the conception that man can reach happiness only by vol- THE GREEK IDEAL 39 untary submission to the divine will, which is also the law of his own reason. It is only in Euripides that we find something like an anticipation of the Christian idea that self- realisation is attained through self-sacrifice. In Euripides, however, this result is reached by a surrender of his faith in the divine justice. Man, he seems to say, is capable of heroic self-sacrifice at the prompting of natural affec- tion, but this is the law of human nature, not of the divine nature. Thus in him morality is divorced from religion, and therefore there is over all his work the sadness which inevitably follows from a sceptical distrust of the exist- ence of any objective principle of goodness. This division of religion and morality could not be final, and hence the attempts of Plato and Aristotle to restore the broken harmony by a higher conception of the divine nature. Though the transformation of the Greek religion by the great poets of Greece was a continuous movement towards a more spiritual view of the divine nature, it did not involve an explicit breach with polytheism, except in the case of Euripides. /Eschylus and 40 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE Sophocles, though they virtually affirm the unity and spirituality of the divine will, are not in conscious antagonism to the popular faith. Such an antagonism was, however, in- evitable, so soon as philosophical reflection arose, and proceeded to ask how far mythology could be accepted as historical truth. The question could not be raised without pro- ducing a temporary scepticism. The first philosophers were therefore almost entirely negative in their attitude towards the tradi- tional faith.''^ It was only with Socrates and his followers that a perception of the rational element implied in mythology was appre- hended. Hence, while Plato is severe in his condemnation of the unworthy representa- tions of the divine nature in Homer and Hesiod, he recognises that the imaginative form which that faith assumed was a neces- sary stage in the education of the race and of the individual. Poetry is a " lie," no doubt, but it is a " noble lie." Plato is here seeking to separate the form from the * "Whether there are gods or not I cannot tell," said Protagoras; " life is too short for such obscure problems." THE GREEK WEAL 4 1 matter, the spirit from the earthly tabernacle in which it is enclosed. The divine, as he contends, is not immoral, malicious, or de- ceitful. What he is really seeking to show is that the divine nature transcends the sensible, and is the ultimate source of all truth, beauty, and goodness. Plato does not, in the first instance, reject the pictorial representations of the popular imagination, which he no doubt regarded as inseparable from the poetic garb endeared to the Greek heart by the hallowing associations of ages; but he insists that the gods must not be portrayed as violating the sanctities of moral law, as inflicting evil upon man from envy, or as appearing in lower forms. The gods are absolutely good, truth- ful, and beautiful, and therefore are eternally and unchangeably the same. It is obvious, however, that Plato does not at bottom believe that the divine nature can be represented in sensible form at all, and hence we cannot be surprised that, with his imperfect theory of art as an " imitation " of sensible reality, the more he reflects upon the distorting influence of all imaginative representations of the divine 42 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE nature, the more dissatisfied he becomes, until at last he concludes, though with great re- luctance, that there is no place for the poet in that ideal city of which he dreamed such beautiful, philosophical dreams. The prepara- tion for this extreme view is already made in the contention that poetry is a "lie," even if it is a " noble lie," and in the denial that evil can in any sense proceed from God, or that the divine can ever be manifested except in its own absolutely perfect form. For the representation of what is false, though it may be necessary as an educational device, has no ultimate justification ; the Manichean separa- tion of evil from the divine is at the same time the exclusion of God from the actual world ; and the only perfect form of the divine must be the supersensible. Thus, by the natural development of Greek thought, Plato is at last led to maintain a spiritual monotheism, re- sembling in its main features the conception of God, which by an independent path was reached by the Hebrew people in the later stages of their history. In his revolt from the pictorial representations of the divine, he THE GREEK IDEAL 43 is led to conceive of God as dwelling in a transcendent region beyond the actual world, and this, though a necessary step in the evolution of the religious consciousness, is not the last word of religion. The Infinite cannot be severed from the finite, God from man, without becoming itself finite, unless we are prepared to regard the finite as pure illu- sion. Nor does Aristotle, though he protests against the Platonic separation of the real and the ideal, succeed in avoiding the rock on which Plato's philosophy of religion makes shipwreck; for he too conceives of God as a purely contemplative being, alone with Him- self, and self-sufficient in His isolation, who acts upon the world only as the sculptor hews and shapes the block of marble, which can never be quite divested of its material gross- ness. If this is at all a fair account of the the- ology of Plato and Aristotle, we must admit that their solutions are not final. The nega- tive movement by which the creations of art and the products of the religious conscious- ness in its imaginative form have been re- 44 THE CHRISTIAN' IDEAL OF LIFE jected, and the first unquestioning faith in the outward manifestation of reason in nature and human life "sickHed o'er with the pale cast of thought," is only imperfectly supple- mented by a positive movement in which the real is virtually declared to lie beyond the actual. For, so long as the world of our experience is regarded as containing an irrational element, the human spirit must either fall back baffled upon the phenomenal, or seek to fly beyond the " flaming walls of the world " by some other organ than reason. It is, therefore, not surprising that Plato and Aristotle were succeeded, on the one hand by the individualistic philosophies of the Stoics, Epicureans, and Sceptics, and on the other hand by the Neo-platonists and Gnostics, who in despair of reason took ref- uge in a supposed "immediate intuition" or " ecstasy." CHAPTER III THE JEWISH IDEAL The religion of Greece, as we have seen, developed from a humanistic polytheism, through the influence of its great poets and philosophers, into monotheism. Even in its polytheistic stage there was a marked ten- dency towards unity, but this tendency was not realised until Plato affirmed the unity and spirituality of the divine nature. The religion of Israel reached the same point by a more direct path. There seems to be clear evidence that Israel had passed from a primitive totemism to the worship of great powers of nature before the captivity in Egypt. Evidence of the former stage is to be found in the household gods or tera- phim, and of the latter in the early concep- tion of Jehovah as the God of the tempest, who had His seat on Mount Sinai. What is 45 46 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE unique in the development of the religion of Israel is that it passed without a break from the worship of nature, to the worship of Jehovah, without going through the in- termediate stage of polytheism. This pecul- iarity arose from the whole character and history of the people. Unlike the Greeks, the people of Israel had no artistic faculty, and what moved them in nature was not the beauty of the world, but the tremendous energy manifested in its more terrible aspects. The divine power they saw manifested in the thunder, and in the tempest which broke on the mountains of Sinai and rolled across the desert. This great and terrible Lord was, from the time of their deliverance from ser- vitude in Egypt under their great leader Moses, the common object of worship of all the tribes. Thus even before their politi- cal union, the behef in Jehovah was the bond which kept them united as a people, and after the loss of their national independence it kept them separate and distinct from all other nations. It is true that, after their settlement in Canaan, there was a continual THE JEWISH IDEAL 47 struggle between those who worshipped only Jehovah and those who saw no harm in com- bining His worship with that of other gods; but the great name of Jehovah never failed to reunite all the tribes in their struggle for independence, and so to prevent them from being merged in the surrounding tide of Canaanite life. And when the monarchy was founded, and the religion of Jehovah became the national religion, the intense conscious- ness of their great past and the anticipation of a still greater future made it impossible that their faith in Jehovah should ever be completely lost. Up to the time of the great prophets, Jeho- vah was conceived only as the greatest of all gods, the God of Israel, who went before them in battle and led them to victory, and who was pledged to aid His people in their time of need. Thus the religious faith of Israel was bound up with a belief in the permanence of its nationality. It was the work of the great prophets to free the con- ception of Jehovah from its exclusively na- tional character. In effecting this change. 48 THE CHRISTIAN' IDEAL OF LIFE they were but developing what was impHcit in the conception from the first. He who was at first conceived to be manifested in the great and terrible aspects of nature came to be regarded as raised entirely above nature, and the God of battles was transformed into the God of holiness. Hence, though Jeho- vah is still conceived as standing in a more intimate relation to Israel than to other na- tions, it is maintained that this relation can continue only if Israel is pre-eminent in righteousness. " You only have I known of all the families of the earth, therefore I will punish you for all your iniquities." Israel must no longer regard herself as secure of the divine favour, irrespective of her conduct: if she continues to dishonour Jehovah, her nationality will be destroyed. This is the idea which Isaiah insists upon with such fervour and power. Even when the king- doms of Judah and Israel were in the full tide of prosperity, the prophet discovered in them the seeds of decay. The upper class was materialised, and the lower class full of superstition and practical unbelief. The re- THE JEWISH IDEAL 49 suit was inevitable : their cities will be wasted and the land left desolate, though, as the prophet believes, there will always be a rem- nant to form the nucleus of a new and re- generate nation. Jehovah will employ the great heathen powers as an instrument for the punishment of Israel. A people who fail in the practice of justice and mercy cannot hope for the favour of a righteous and holy God. It is obvious that in this new conception the old idea of Jehovah as the God only of Israel has been virtually transcended. Ac- cordingly the prophets deny that there is any God but Jehovah, and, therefore, declare that He has relations to other nations as well as to Israel. He governs the world, not in the interests of one nation only, but in the in- terests of righteousness. He is the Creator of all things, and the Ruler of the universe, though He has specially revealed Himself to Israel. In the later prophets a further advance is made. Jehovah is not only the God of na- tions, but He is directly related to the indi- ' 01 UNIVERSITY cauforh^ 50 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE vidual soul. This advance followed as a natural consequence of the conception of God as a God of righteousness. A God who is beyond nature, and is essentially spiritual, cannot be permanently conceived as related only to the nation. Holiness depends upon the inner state of the soul, and therefore the relation of man to God is a personal one. Hence Jeremiah and Ezekiel assert personal responsibility. " Every one shall die for his own iniquity," says Jeremiah ; and Ezekiel declares that " the soul that sinneth, it shall die." With the conception of God as absolutely holy, and the demand for perfect purity of heart and conduct, there arose the conscious- ness of the opposition between the finite and the infinite, the actual and the ideal. Thus the religion of Israel, unlike the Greek, is a religion of prophecy. The prophet, main- taining that man was originally made "a little lower than God," and contrasting with this perfect relation his present sinfulness, looks forward to a time when the unity with God which has been lost shall be restored. THE JEWISH IDEAL 5 1 The higher conception of religion and mo- rality taught by the prophets was not imme- diately accepted by the people, though the successive reforms narrated in the histories show that it had commended itself to the best minds. It was only with the exile that the people obtained a firm grasp of the idea that they were the custodians of the one true religion. This conviction finds its most perfect expression in the second Isaiah, who declares that the peculiar mission of Israel is to make known the true God to the heathen. There will always be a faithful "remnant" entirely devoted to the service of Jehovah, who, even if they suffer for the sins of others, will be the means of leading many to right- eousness. With the cessation of the fresh spring of prophetic utterance, the Jewish conception of God tended to become more and more ab- stract. The way was prepared for this change by the formation, under Ezra and Nehemiah, of a sort of theocratic commonwealth, a com- pact and homogeneous little state, devoted mainly to the worship of Jehovah. With the 52 THE CHRtSTIAN' IDEAL OF LIFE establishment of this community, the separa- tion of Israel from the rest of the world, and the subsequent worship of the letter of scripture, were inevitable. Jerusalem became the universally acknowledged centre of the religion and worship of Jehovah, to which from time to time Israelites from all parts of the earth flocked to offer sacrifice in the temple. Though this centralisation of sacri- ficial worship was a bond of union to the despised race, it was not effective as a na- tional bond, while on the other hand it was hostile to the wider bond of humanity. Indi- rectly, the centralisation of worship in Jeru- salem gave rise to the institution of the synagogue. This change had important con- sequences. Religion became no longer merely national, but individual. The most beauti- ful flower of this personal religion was its sacred lyrical poetry. Many of the psalms, most of which are admitted to belong to the centuries after the exile, express the pure and pious feeling called forth by the reading of the Law and the prophets in the synagogue. There was, however, another consequence of THE JEWISH IDEAL 53 the change. The importance of the sacer- dotal cultus in Jerusalem receded into the background. The Levite became of less con- sequence than the Rabbi skilled in the Law. Thus the Law came to be the centre of all the thoughts of the pious Israelite. The whole education of the people, in the family, the school, and the synagogue, was intended to make them a "people of the law." No longer did Jehovah reveal His will through the direct inspiration of a prophet. A final revelation of Himself had been given in the Law, and the sole duty of His people was to find out by a careful examination of the words of Scripture what had been revealed once for all. Shut out from the direct conscious- ness of God, the conception of His nature became more and more abstract. He was "the Holy One," the "Absolute," raised to an infinite distance above the world and man, even to name whom was profane. Religion thus came to be regarded, not as the com- munion of man with God, but as the right relation of man before God. The Law took the place formerly occupied by God. It is 54 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE identified with the eternal wisdom, which arose from the unknown depths of the divine nature ; it is the image or daughter of God, which was before the creation of the world, and in the contemplation of which the divine life is passed. As expressing the whole nature of God, the Law is the ultimate revelation, valid for all time and even for eternity; it is the true food of the soul, the tree of life, the source of all knowledge. The essence of re- ligion, therefore, consists in love of the Law, as exhibited in its study and in observance of its precepts. Thus the Law at once unites Israel to Jehovah, and separates her from the whole heathen world, which by its rejec- tion of the Law at Sinai adopted a hostile attitude toward Jehovah. As conformity to the Law was the standard and source of all righteousness, God was bound by the terms of the covenant entered into with Israel to recompense the pious Israelite in proportion to his observance of its precepts. As this proportion was not always observed, it was held that at some future time the balance would be restored. THE JEWISH IDEAL 55 The whole religious life thus revolved around these two poles, — conformity to the Law and the hope of future reward. Under such a purely external conception, religion and mo- rality were emptied of life. For that free and spontaneous devotion to goodness which is of the very essence of the spiritual life, was substituted the mechanical observance of rules imposed by external authority. The Law was to be obeyed, not because it expressed the true nature of man, but because it had been ordained by Him who had power to reward and punish. As its various precepts were not seen to flow from any principle, the moral life was conceived to consist in strict obedience to every detail of the Law. Where all was equally imposed by God, every require- ment of the Law had the same absolute claim to obedience. Thus there was, in St. Paul's phrase, " a zeal for God, but not according to knowledge." To the conscientious Israelite, life was made an intolerable burden, while the rigid adherent of the Law could hardly escape from a proud and boastful self-righteousness. The logical consequences of this legalistic 56 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE religion and morality are most clearly seen in the life and theory of the Pharisees, who carried out to its extreme the spirit which rules the whole post-exilic period. It has sometimes been said that the Pharisees were the patriotic party, as contrasted with the Sad- ducees, who were always ready to sacrifice their country and even the national religion from motives of worldly prudence. It would seem, however, that the main spring of action in the Pharisees was not love of country, but love of the Law. And by the Law they meant, not so much the written as the " oral " law, which had been gradually formed by the labours of the scribes. " The Pharisees," says Josephus, " have imposed upon the people many laws taken from the tradition of the fathers, which are not written in the Law of Moses." Such an extension of the Law was inevitable. A law accepted upon authority necessarily gives rise to casuistry, the moment an attempt is made to make it a complete guide of life; and the precedents thus established naturally come to be regarded as an unfolding of what is already contained in the law. What distinguished THE JEWISH IDEAL 57 the Pharisees was their claim to peculiar strictness in the interpretation and observance of the Law, or rather of the " traditions of the fathers," and especially of the laws relating to cleanness and uncleanness. They regarded themselves as the true Israel, in distinction not only from the heathen, but from the less scrupulous of their own countrymen. That ex- cessive zeal for the letter of the Law was their ruling motive seems to be proved by their attitude to successive dynasties. During the Maccabean conflict, they adopted the popular cause; but when the insurrection proved suc- cessful, and the Asmoneans showed indiffer- ence to the Law, the Pharisees turned against them. Their zeal for the Law won the people to their side, and henceforth they completely ruled the public life. Even the direction of public worship was in the hands of the Phari- sees, though the priestly Sadducees were nominally the head of the Sanhedrim. The Sadducees were the wealthy, aristocratic party, and therefore belonged mainly to the priest- hood, which, as far back as the Persian period, governed the Jewish state and formed its 58 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE nobility. They differed from the Pharisees in acknowledging only the Pentateuch and the prophets as binding, to the exclusion of the whole mass of legal decisions which had been established by the Pharisaic scribes. The Sadducees held fast by the older faith, mainly because they were averse to the big- otry and exclusiveness of the Pharisees. As a matter of fact their position as men of affairs, and their contact with foreign culture, had made them comparatively indifferent to the religion of their fathers. The Messianic hopes of the Pharisees were the natural complement of their legal- ism. They believed that, in terms of the covenant made at Sinai, God was bound to reward those who obeyed the Law, and there- fore that the political and individual evils to which the saints were subjected could only be temporary. They therefore looked for- ward to a time when the whole world would be united under the sceptre of Israel into a universal monarchy, over which the Messiah should be ruler and judge. In this glorious era, the pious individual would also be re- THE JEWISH IDEAL 59 warded. The general belief was in a "res- urrection of the just," though some also expected a general resurrection, when the wicked should be punished and the right- eous rewarded. The reign of the saints was to be ushered in by the direct intervention of God, when the rule of Satan and his angels should give place to the rule of God and His anointed. The Messiah, the King of Israel, chosen by God from all eternity, should come down from heaven, where He was already in communion with God, and establish upon earth the reign of righteous- ness and peace. While this was the form which the Messianic hope assumed in the minds of the scribes and Pharisees, there were not wanting men of a finer type, in whose minds it was accompanied by the ex- pectation of the triumph of good over evil, and of the deliverance of man from the evil of his own heart. A consideration of the atti- tude of Jesus toward the Law and the Mes- sianic hopes of his time will help to bring out the distinctive features of the Christian, as distinguished from the Jewish, ideal of life. CHAPTER IV THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL The first step toward the overthrow of the whole set of legaHstic ideas, character- istic of later Judaism, was taken by John the Baptist. It is true that the Baptist did not break with the legal piety of his time, but his watchword, " Repent, for the king- dom of heaven is at hand," was in essence a denial of the principle upon which legal- ism rested. For, according to that principle, the delay of the kingdom of heaven was not due to the unrighteousness of Israel, but to the inscrutable designs of providence, which permitted Satan with his host of angels to afflict the saints and deprive them of the reward to which their diligent observance of the Law entitled them. The reign of the saints could only come with the miraculous advent of the Messiah. The Baptist, on the 60 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL 6 1 other hand, found the explanation of the delay in the manifestation of the kingdom of heaven in the sinfulness of men, not in the inscrutable designs of God. Hence he called for repentance, and, by demanding from every one a confession of sin, he vir- tually denied that the Pharisees were justi- fied in regarding themselves as righteous. The evils from which men suffered were not due to the malevolence of evil spirits, but to their own corrupt hearts. No doubt the blessings of the kingdom of heaven could only come from above, but only those need hope to participate in them who were conscious of the evil of their own hearts, and sought the righteousness of God. The king- dom of heaven was at hand, and the neces- sary preparation for it was a "change of mind." The effect of this message upon the Phari- sees could only be to arouse their indigna- tion and rancour; for, in demanding from all a confession of sin and a change of heart, the Baptist struck a powerful blow at their self-righteousness and spiritual pride; and, 62 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE in virtually affirming that righteousness did not consist in the scrupulous observance of the Law, he denied the very foundation upon which they based their expectation of future reward. To those finer spirits, on the other hand, who were painfully conscious of their own weakness and sinfulness, the preaching of the Baptist came as a welcome solution of their spiritual perplexities, and helped to restore their faith in the justice of God. Among those who at once discerned the significance of the Baptist's summons to repentance was Jesus, who submitted to bap- tism, as a sign of his belief in the funda- mental truth of John's doctrine, and, indeed, in the beginning of his ministry, adopted as his own the watchword, " Repent, for the kingdom of heaven is at hand." But, while Jesus thus endorsed the new way of right- eousness, it soon became evident that he gave to it another and a deeper meaning. In the Beatitudes this new point of view is already indicated. Repentance is by the Bap- tist conceived as the moral preparation for a deliverance from evil which is still future; THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL 63 by Jesus it is regarded as consisting in a personal consciousness of the infinite love of God. Thus the moral revolution is insepar- able from the religious. The kingdom of heaven is already present in the souls of those who have an absolute faith in the goodness of God, a faith which finds expres- sion in unselfish devotion to their fellow-men, and which rejoices in revilings and persecu- tions as the process through which goodness gradually overcomes evil. The ideal of life which is indicated in the Beatitudes was an entire reversal of the cur- rent conception, especially as it had been formulated in the teaching of the scribes and Pharisees. Even the method of exposi- tion was new; for, whereas the accepted teachers in all cases sought to deduce con- clusions from the letter of scripture, by a laborious and ingenious system of exegesis, Jesus threw out his ideas in the form of aphorisms, which shone by their own light. And if his method was thus free and un- conventional, how much more revolutionary seemed to be the substance of his teaching! 64 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE Ignoring the authority of the Law and the prophets, he seemed to assert an independent basis for the new truth which he proclaimed, and, in making righteousness consist entirely in a spiritual regeneration, he apparently despised the whole body of truth which had been revealed by God himself to Moses and the prophets. It was, therefore, charged against him that, in abrogating the Law, he was destroying the very foundation of relig- ion and morality. The objection is one which never fails to be made when the princi- ple of external authority is attacked. When Socrates sought to trace back the customary religious and moral ideas of his time to their principle, he was accused of denying the gods of his country, and corrupting the minds of the youth ; and the similar charge was brought against St. Paul, that in destroying the au- thority of the Law, he was virtually the advocate of licentiousness and impiety. The answer of Jesus was, that so far from abro- gating the Mosaic law he '' fulfilled " it ; i,e, brought to light the principle which gave it its binding force. The Law, as he contends, THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL 65 is of eternal obligation, and cannot be abol- ished so long as heaven and earth endure. " Think not that I came to destroy the law and the prophets; I came not to destroy but to fulfil." The new way of life does not abolish the Law, but shows that it cannot be abolished. On the other hand, the old way of basing it upon external authority and cus- tom destroys its very foundation. The source of all morality is to be found, not in the ex- ternal act, but in the inner spirit from which the act proceeds, and when this is once seen it becomes evident that the legalism of the scribes and Pharisees is antagonistic to any genuine morality. The Law which is thus declared to be eter- nal and indestructible is the Law in its moral, as distinguished from its ceremonial, part. It is the Law as interpreted from the point of view of the prophets. This distinction of the ethical from the ceremonial part of the Law is of itself an important advance. It is a distinction which could have no meaning for the scribes and Pharisees, who had no criterion by which to separate between what 66 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE was based upon the unchanging nature of man and what held good only under special circumstances and at a given stage in the development of humanity. For, as we have seen, a law which is accepted purely upon authority, is all equally binding. But this is not all ; for not only does Jesus distinguish the ethical from the ceremonial part of the Law, but he goes back beyond the traditional morality of his day to the fundamental moral ideas expressed in the Law and the prophets, and disengages the principle upon which they rest. Thus he is enabled to grasp the Law in its purity and universality, and to contrast it with the unspiritual interpretations of the scribes. Take, e.g. the command : " Thou shalt not kill." The scribes, in accordance with their usual conception of morality as a sys- tem of external rewards and punishments, add the gloss: "Whosoever shall kill, shall be in danger of the judgment." The sanc- tion of the Law is thus made to consist, not in the sacredness of human life, but in the fear of punishment here or hereafter. THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL 6/ The principle upon which the Law is based is therefore destroyed. The appeal is to a purely selfish motive, and with that appeal the whole moral aspect of the Law disap- pears. Jesus, on the other hand, insists that the command rests upon the purely moral principle of love, and that the Law is vio- lated in its essence, not merely in this ex- treme expression of hatred, but in hatred in all its forms, or rather in that evil disposi- tion which is the source of all hatred. The outward act has no moral meaning in itself; murder is not the mere taking away of life, but the taking away of life from hatred to one's fellow-man ; and therefore anger, want of sympathy, and contempt, as springing from the same corrupt source, the unloving heart, are worthy of the most extreme punishment, the "hell of fire." Thus the Law is seen to exclude the whole range of malevolent pas- sions and even the faintest taint of hatred. Jesus was therefore justified in saying that the righteousness of his followers must "ex- ceed the righteousness of the scribes and Pharisees," and "exceed" it not merely in 68 THE CHRISTIAN' IDEAL OF LIFE degree, but in kind. The distinction, in fact, is infinite. The scribes, in conceiving moral- ity to consist solely in conformity to an ex- ternal rule, irrespective of the motive from which the act proceeded, virtually did away with the whole principle of morality; and, by their reduction of morality to a system of external rewards and punishments, they vio- lated the very essence of morality, which rests upon the universal principle of brotherly love. To this it is added that morality is the pre- requisite of all true worship: no genuine re- ligious act can be performed by the man who nourishes in his heart a grudge against his neighbour. Lastly, Jesus traces back the ethical principle of love to one's neighbour to a fundamental identity in the nature of God and man : hatred brings upon the man who nourishes it its own punishment, just because he is violating what is his own real self; and hence, though he may escape external punish- ment, he cannot possibly escape the most ter- rible of all punishments, — that which consists in the loss of the blessedness which springs from the consciousness of unity with God. THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL 69 The same principle is applied * to other moral laws; in all cases Jesus traces back the command to its source in the nature of man as identical in nature with God. At the close of his treatment of this theme he expands the principle of morality so as to embrace all men, and he elevates it into in- finity. The Law had said: "Thou shalt not hate thy brother in thine heart, thou shalt not be angry with the children of thy peo- ple, thou shalt love thy neighbour as thyself (Lev. xix. 17, 18)." From this precept came the characteristic Pharisaic deduction : " Thou shalt be angry with the stranger, thou shalt hate thine enemies." Thus national hatred was not only condoned, but was actually made a principle of action, and surrounded with all the sanctity and solemnity of a divine com- mand. Now even Plato reached the concep- tion that " it was better to suffer than to do injustice." Jesus goes altogether beyond this negative attitude. "Love your enemies, and pray for them that persecute you." This is, indeed, a " new commandment." It is the very core of Christian ethics — that which 70 THE CHRISTIAN' IDEAL OF LIFE gives it its superiority, and makes it incon- ceivable that its principle can ever be tran- scended. Moreover, this supreme ethical principle is immediately connected with the distinctively Christian idea of God, as the "Father" of men, whose love has absolutely no limits. As a symbol of this all-embracing love, he " maketh his sun to rise on the evil and the good, and sendeth his rain on the just and the unjust." " Therefore," con- cludes Jesus, "Ye shall be perfect as your heavenly Father is perfect"; ix, man, finite and sinful as he is, is yet capable of living a divine life, of repeating on an infinitesimal scale the large all-embracing charity of his heavenly " Father." Jesus has thus vindicated the " Law " as an expression of the fundamental moral ideas which constitute the soul of society. It is evident, however, that in tracing back those ideas to their source, he has raised them to a plane which was never dreamt of before ; in other words, he has virtually abolished the conception of man and God upon which the Jewish religion rested. At the same time THE CHRISTIAN' IDEAL 71 the new way of life is not an absolute change, but a development. The moral laws won for humanity by the toil and suffering of the Jewish people were not lost, though they underwent expansion and specification by the appreciation of the principle of universal brotherhood. Of this double relation Jesus was perfectly conscious. Hence, while on the one hand he affirms the eternal obliga- tion of the Law, he asserts with equal deci- sion that the new principle which he brought to light separates the new world from the old as by an impassable barrier. " From the days of John the Baptist until now the king- dom of heaven suffereth violence, and men of violence take it by force. For all the prophets and the Law prophesied until John." The '* kingdom of heaven," as he implies, is for the first time revealed as it is, i.e. as actually present, and men are pressing into it now that it has been revealed. The prophets spoke only of a future kingdom, living merely in the hope that somehow and at some time God would bring about the reign of righteousness upon the earth. Now 72 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE men live in the glad consciousness that the reign of righteousness, which to the prophets seemed afar off, has actually begun. Hence Jesus speaks of the Baptist as having reached a higher stage of truth than the prophets. " Verily I say unto you, among them that are born of women, there hath not arisen a greater than John the Baptist." But he immediately adds: "Yet he that is but little in the kingdom of heaven is greater than he." So radical is the change introduced by the new revelation that it lifts those who accept it to a higher plane of truth than the Baptist, who still conceived of the kingdom of heaven as future, and who had not dis- covered the central truth that the kingdom of heaven was capable of being realised the moment it was discovered to consist in an unlimited love to God and man. Thus Jesus was perfectly aware that old things had passed away, and all things had become new. Nor had he any doubt of the absolute truth of his own doctrine. " All things have been deliv- ered unto me of my Father; and no one knoweth the Son, save the Father, neither THE CHRISTIAN ibS^t ' yt^ doth any know the Father save the Son, and he to whomsoever the Son willeth to reveal him." The revelation which he had to make to the world was an entirely new revelation. " Verily I say unto you that many prophets and righteous men have earnestly desired to see what ye see, and have not seen it, and to hear what ye hear and have not heard it." Yet, while he declares that his gospel is new, Jesus has too much insight into the pre- sentiment of the truth, which half consciously worked in the highest minds of the past, not to be aware that the principle which he brought into the full light of day had been vaguely felt by religious men in all ages. The princi- ple of evolution of which so much is now said has never been applied more precisely to the development of religious ideas than by Jesus. The ideas of Jesus are all so closely connected, flowing as they do from a single principle, that it is impossible to treat of one aspect of his teaching without some reference to the other aspects. Hence it has not been possible to speak of his attitude towards the Law without to some extent anticipating what 74 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE has now to be said in connexion with his atti- tude to the Messianic hopes of his country- men. In what follows it will be advisable to consider this question in relation to (i) the general' view of the scribes, (2) the higher view, rather felt than clearly formulated, by men of a more spiritual type. The points of agreement between these two classes of mind lay in the conviction that the world had been given over to wicked men and to the machinations of the devil and his angels ; but that a time was coming when this state of things would be completely reversed, and a reign of righteous- ness set up upon the earth under the Messiah. But while there was a general agreement on these points, there was a radical difference in the conception of " righteousness," and as a consequence in the conception of the Messiah. Let us look first at the general view of the scribes and Pharisees. (i) As we have already seen, their dissatis- faction with the evil of the present was closely connected with their legalistic ideas. To them it seemed that, by the terms of the covenant made between God and His own peculiar peo- THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL 75 pie, Israel had a right to national indepen- dence, and even to sovereignty over all nations, as a reward for her devotion to Jehovah; or at least she was entitled to expect this reward when she fully implemented her part of the contract. Starting from this legal point of view, the evil of the present was explained as flowing from a failure to fulfil the terms of the covenant. God "does not exercise His king- ship to its full extent, but on the contrary ex- poses His people to the heathen world-powers, to chastise them for their sins." By " sins " the Pharisees, of course, meant a want of conform- ity to the Law. Because of this disobedience, pain and sorrow prevailed, and especially those mental diseases which were directly re- ferred to demoniac possession. For the same reason Israel groaned under the iron despot- ism of Rome. It is obvious that the future kingdom of God, which was to be ushered in by the Messiah, could only be conceived as consisting in the absence of pain and suffering, in dominion over the heathen, and in the rule of the saints, i.e. of those who were rigid in the practice of the Law. *j6 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE Now the Pharisaic ideal of a kingdom of heaven, consisting in the absence of pain and suffering, in earthly sovereignty, and in the rule of Pharisaic saints, was one which Jesus could not possibly endorse. Denying in limine the whole conception upon which it rested, he could admit neither the Pharisaic conception of the present, nor their vulgar ideal of the future. The legalistic idea of a contract be- tween God and Israel, the terms of which were that the pious Israelite who conformed to the letter of the Law had a right to freedom from suffering and to external sovereignty, was for him a profoundly immoral and irreligious conception ; and the assumption that the gov- ernment of God was not just and righteous was to him blasphemous. The world had never ceased to be the object of God's loving care, and therefore the coming of the king- dom of God could not mean a sudden and miraculous manifestation of His power. The spirit of God was present in the world of nature and in the consciousness of man. The obstacle to the reign of righteousness was in the blindness and sin of man, not in God. It THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL jj was want of faith, and the sin which inevitably flowed from it, that explained the suffering and evil of the present. We have seen how Jesus opposes to the legalism of the Pharisees his conception of a righteousness which consists in active efforts for the moral purification of the individual soul, a purification which could proceed only from love to God and man. Absolute faith in the goodness of God was the key-note of all his teaching. But if, as Jesus maintained, the essential nature of God is love for all creatures, and especially for man, how did he explain the existence of suffering and evil.? How was the righteous government of God to be reconciled with the apparent triumph of evil } The optimism which shuts its eyes to the misery and wickedness of the world was to him a false and delusive creed. The wretchedness and evil of man were only too palpable. Jesus faced the facts with a perfectly clear consciousness of their force. No one was ever more sensitive to the suf- ferings of others than he; but he refused to see in suffering a proof of the indifference or 78 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAI OF LIFE injustice of God. His explanation of suffer- ing was that it is a necessary step in the whole process by which man is lifted to a higher plane. To the Pharisees suffering was the result of the want of obedience to the Law, and therefore it seemed to them that, with the advent of the Messiah, and the de- struction of all who transgressed the Law, suf- fering would disappear. Jesus also believes in the gradual disappearance of suffering, but he refuses to connect it with external conform- ity to the Law. The destruction of suffering must come from the efforts of loving hearts, not from any miraculous change in the con- ditions of human life. Suffering is not, or at least not merely, a punishment for sin, but a divinely ordained means for calling out the higher energies of the soul. As in the view of the Pharisees suffering was the result of transgression of the Law, so also was the oppression of Israel by heathen powers. Hence they believed that, when the Messiah should come, the independence of Israel would be restored, and the whole world should come under the sway of " the saints." THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL 79 Now, it has been maintained that Jesus, as an ardent patriot, shared in the hopes of his countrymen, and looked forward to the future sovereignty of Israel. This view cannot be accepted. For (a) even if Jesus cherished the hope of the external sovereignty of Israel, he could not possibly accept the ideal of the Pharisees. An Israel in which the whole gov- ernment should be in the hands of " saints " of the Pharisaic type was something too dread- ful to contemplate. No doubt Jesus was in- tensely patriotic in the sense of desiring that Israel should be the leader in the spiritual regeneration of the world, and it is probable that in the earlier days of his ministry he cherished the hope of persuading his coun- trymen to accept the new revelation. But, whether this was so or not, it is manifest that he came to see that the deep-rooted prejudices and externalism of the mass of the people, and the malignant opposition of the ruling classes, were too strong to be over- come. Recognising this clearly, it was im- possible for him to believe that Israel should be raised to a supremacy over the heathen. So THE CHRISTIAN' IDEAL OF LIFE (b) Belief in the future rule of Israel was in- separably connected in the Jewish mind with the advent of a Messiah, who should ascend the throne of David and rule over a subject world. When, therefore, Jesus admitted to his disciples that the Messiah had already come in his own person, he plainly acknow- ledged that he had abandoned the whole set of ideas upon which the future political su- premacy of Israel was based. The kingdom of heaven had already come, and it was not an earthly but a spiritual kingdom. In this kingdom he who was least was greatest, and indeed the spiritual power of the true Messiah — the power of loving service — was contrasted with the earthly power which consisted in rul- ing over a subject people, [c] While main- taining that the kingdom of heaven has already come, Jesus counsels submission to the established power of Rome, showing that in his mind the rule of righteousness was not dependent upon the political supremacy of Israel. His answer to the mother of Zebe- dee's children has been strangely cited as a proof that he looked forward to the earthly THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL 8 1 rule of the "saints." Nothing, in fact, could more clearly show that, in his mind, the king- dom of heaven was entirely independent of earthly power. To the naive materialism of the good woman, who desired that her two sons should sit, one on his right hand and the other on his left, he answered: "Can ye be baptised with the baptism wherewith I have to be baptised?" In other words, he de- clares rank in the kingdom of heaven to con- sist in enlarged possibilities of loving service, not in outward pomp and sovereignty. And he significantly adds: "To sit on my right hand or on my left is not mine to give," i.e, the future is in the hands of God. The atti- tude of Jesus, as we may be sure, was one of such absolute trust in God, that he was quite prepared to accept the continued political de- pendence of Israel, if that were the will of God; and indeed towards the end of his life he seems to have seen perfectly clearly that the popular conception of the Messiah, which, in spite of all his efforts to turn it into a new channel, had taken firm hold upon the public mind, and was encouraged for their own ends 82 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE by the Pharisees, could only result in the com- plete subjugation of Israel and the destruction of the temple service. In any case, the king- dom of heaven was so purely spiritual in its character that it could not possibly be con- nected in the mind of Jesus with the political supremacy of Israel. No doubt he wisely limited his efforts to "the lost sheep of the house of Israel," but this limitation was never in his mind connected with a belief in the future political sovereignty or even indepen- dence of Israel, but only with his ardent de- sire to secure the spiritual salvation of his countrymen, and through their instrumental- ity of the whole human race. The bitter- ness and hatred of the Pharisees, and of all who cherished ambitious hopes for the future of Israel, is largely explained by -the way in which Jesus trampled upon all their cher- ished prejudices and political expectations. Not only did he tear off the garb of self- righteousness which they had wrapped around them ; not only did he denounce them as ene- mies of true religion and morality; but he counselled what they regarded as a tame sub- THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL 83 mission to the oppressive heathen power of Rome. Such a profound antagonism of ideals could only have one issue : the worldly material ideal must triumph for a time, only to be ulti- mately overcome by the intrinsically stronger ideal. Of this issue Jesus was clearly con- scious, and therefore he warned his disciples that he would be the victim of the unholy rage of the rulers and their blind followers ; while yet he announced with absolute confidence that the good cause would ultimately prevail. His optimism was therefore so profound and so robust, that even the worst expression of hatred and rancour did not destroy his faith. The passionate hatred with which he was pur- sued to the death was interpreted by him as a perversion of the inextinguishable desire for goodness which is inseparable from the con- sciousness of self. " Father, forgive them, for they know not what they do," is the expres- sion of an optimism which rises triumphant over even the worst form of evil. (2) The attitude of Jesus towards those pious souls who were disturbed by the ap- parent triumph of evil without and within, §4 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE was very different from the stern and un- compromising antagonism which he displayed toward the Pharisees. What disturbed the ordinary pious Jew was, not so much the prosperity of the wicked, as the prosper- ity of the heathen. Israel was the chosen people of God, and yet the " sinners of the Gentiles," Le, the unholy nations, who had left Jehovah and given themselves up to idolatry and unclean rites, seemed to receive greater favour from God than the people whom He had chosen and who had remained faithful to Him. His special perplexity was the apparent injustice of God. A partial answer was no doubt found in the belief that God was chastising His people for their sins, and that He made use of the heathen, wicked as they were, as the instruments of His will. But the pious Jew never aban- doned the belief that in some far-off time the favour of God would be restored to Israel, and that an awful day of reckoning would come for the heathen. Now, Jesus does not absolutely deny that there is a certain justification in the con- THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL 85 trast between the heathen and the Jew. To him also, the moral wickedness of the heathen and the grossness of their religious concep- tions seem palpable; but he entirely denies the assumption that the Jew has any claim upon God to be freed from oppression, or that there is anything incompatible with the justice of God in the political oppression of Israel. The first assumption arises from conceiving of righteousness as obedience to an external law; the second, from a mis- apprehension of the true end of life. Hence he seeks to show that the course of the world is not to be explained on the legal- istic supposition of an external system of rewards and punishments, or of a special claim on the part of the Jew to the favour of God. The righteous man has no right to an external reward for his righteousness; the Jew has no claim as a Jew to the favour of God. For the end of human life is not external prosperity, but the develop- ment of the spirit. When this is once ad- mitted, the difficulty arising from the apparent triumph of the wicked assumes an entirely S6 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE new aspect. External prosperity is no test of spiritual elevation. " What shall it profit a man if he gains the whole world and loses his life } " The true nature of man is seen, not in his desire for the perishable things of this world, but in " hunger and thirst after righteousness." Nothing can satisfy man but the growth in him of the divine spirit, and he in whom that spirit dwells is not disturbed by the want of those things which are the mere accidents of existence, not its essence. What is called the pros- perity of the wicked is not true prosperity. This is the idea which Jesus enforces in that part of the Sermon on the Mount which he seems to have addressed to those who came to hear him, attracted by some- thing kindred in themselves. " Lay not up for yourselves treasures upon earth; but lay up for yourselves treasures in heaven." The true life does not consist in the attainment of finite and limited ends, but in the pos- session of that which is eternal and im- perishable. The beginning of spiritual life, therefore, consists in an entire surrender of THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL 87 the finite. But this is only the negative side of his teaching: the positive side is the direction of the whole being to the infinite and eternal, or the laying up of "treasures in heaven." This, of course, does not mean that man is to separate himself from all earthly concerns, and set his affections upon the future life, in the sense of looking for- ward to a reward which it is hopeless to expect in the present life. The "heavenly treasures " do not consist in outward quali- fications, either there or here, but in a "change of mind," which transforms the whole spirit, and throws a new light upon all things. " If thine eye be single, thy whole body shall be full of light." So when the " mind's eye " is single, the whole world assumes a new aspect. This transformation of the soul is the new creation of the world : the mind to which everything seemed an in- soluble riddle now sees the confused and indistinct mass of objects fall into their proper place in the organic unity of the whole. All finite ends are universalised when they are viewed by reference to God, and 88 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE all worthy action is then seen to consist in the service of God. " Ye cannot serve God and mammon." ^ Now, if the true life of man consists in the service of God, the wicked must not be re- garded as prosperous, but as miserable in the extreme. They have lost what Dante calls the "good of the intellect," — that rational good which is the source of all joy and peace. There can be no need to "justify the ways of God" by any far-fetched attempt to explain why wickedness is rewarded and righteous- ness punished. Wickedness is never rewarded, and righteousness is never punished. It is no reward to " lose one's life " : it is no pun- ishment to " save one's life." For he who seeks the lower misses the higher, while he who seeks the higher has the lower "added to him." In other words, devotion to uni- versal or impersonal ends — to all that makes for the good of the whole — is the secret of blessedness. By giving up his exclusive self man gains a wider self, which is the true self. And this true self is but another name for life in God. For the only reason why in THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL 89 this higher Hfe man is in unity with himself is because he is in unity with the whole ten- dency of the world, i.e. with the will of God. In his earlier teaching Jesus seeks to com- mend the new way of truth by showing that the love of God is revealed in nature as well as in human life. We have seen how, in later Judaism, the decay of prophetic inspiration and devotion to the letter of the Law resulted in ultimately making God a name for an in- definable Power, not revealed in the world, but concealed behind an impenetrable veil. Thus the tendency, which was always pres- ent in the Jewish religion, reached its climax. Now Jesus entirely reverses this conception of a purely transcendent God. God is in- deed the Creator of the world, but He is best seen, not in the great and terrible forces of nature, but in its silent and orderly processes, and in the purposive energy which works in the life of flower and bird and beast. He does not stand apart from nature in lonely isolation, but His spirit pervades all things and quickens them by its presence. Hence in his parables Jesus finds the evidence of 90 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE God's goodness in the ordinary occurrences of the homely earth.- There is a tender and solemn light on the most familiar things be- cause God is felt to be present in them, not hidden behind them. Especially in the life and growth of nature Jesus finds evidence of the continuous and loving care of God. With penetrative imagination he sees the formative activity of God working in the beauty with which He clothes the grass of the field, which to-day is and to-morrow is cast into the oven ; in the lilies, clothed in a glory exceeding all the splendour of human art ; in the insignificant mustard-seed, which expands in harmony with all the skyey influ- ences into the organic unity of root, stem, leaves, and blossoms, with the birds swaying in its branches. Thus God works not upon but through the things which have come from His hands. Nature is not a dead ma- chine, wielded by the hands of omnipotence, but it is instinct with that eternal principle of life which exhibits itself in the ever-recur- ring cycle of changes, inorganic and organic. To the eye of Jesus, nature is thus a mani- THE CHRIST/AN- IDEAL 91 festation of the wisdom and loving care of God; and he asks if it is credible that He who takes such pains to fashion and provide for the life of plant and animal is less inter- ested in man. " Behold, the birds of the heaven, that they sow not, neither do they reap, nor gather into barns, and your heav- enly Father feedeth them. Are not ye of much more value than they?" The "free and friendly eyes" with which Jesus in the earlier years of his ministry con- templated nature never deserted him; but, as the malevolence and opposition of the scribes and Pharisees with their blinded followers increased, the problem of evil demanded even a deeper faith. There was to him no real trial of faith in the external prosperity of the wicked, for he saw that the wicked received precisely the reward which their acts de- manded; but the apparent success of the op- position to the work of God seemed to demand another explanation. Having absolute faith in the saving power of love, he yet found that in the majority of his countrymen his revelation only provoked a more bigoted be- 92 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE lief in their own unspiritual ideas and a hatred of the truth that was growing in in- tensity until, as he foresaw, the sacrifice of his own life would be the inevitable result. A similar result, it was evident to him, must follow the diffusion of the truth in all ages. The conflict of principles must ever call into play all that is best and all that is worst in man. "Think not that I came to send peace on the earth : I came not to send peace, but a sword." How is this weakness of the good cause to be explained 1 Has God in truth, as the majority believed, given over the world to the rule of Satan.? The answer of Jesus reveals the infinite depth of his optimism. The triumph of the evil cause is no triumph, but a defeat. For in what does it consist.? It cannot kill the truth itself, which is eternal, but only the body of those whose lives are a witness of its power. There is nothing in life so pathetic as the temporary triumph of a bad cause; for that triumph means that for a time men in their delusion are shut out from the bless- edness of unity with God, and therefore with THE CHRISTIAN IDEAJL 93 themselves. On the other hand, those who live in the truth have the whole tendency of things on their side, and conscious of this they cannot be touched in the centre of their being. Still the problem remains: why does evil apparently triumph? A partial answer is, that its triumph is only apparent — it 'is never complete, and it has no permanency. But more than this : its temporary triumph is essential to the full disclosure of all that the truth contains. The false principle must show its bitter fruits, and must accomplish its perfect work before it completely reveals its true nature. Hence, the more it outwardly triumphs and shows its evil nature, the more surely is the way prepared for its final over- throw. "Where the carcase is, there are the vultures gathered together." Man ca7i only seek for truth and goodness, and if for a time he turns his energies against the good cause, it is not in the spirit of a being who desires evil — for man is not a devil, but in his real being a "son of God" — but in his confusion of the true with the false. Hence the outward success of the bad cause is a 94 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE real failure. Just as man cannot find rest in any finite end, so he can never be satisfied permanently with anything short of the truth. It is the truth he is really seeking, and at last the truth must prevail. Thus Jesus finds in the worst form of evil a "soul of good- ness." The world is through and through the product of divine love. Now, with this grasp of the principle that the good cause must ultimately prevail, while yet it implies a conflict with the opposite principle of evil, Jesus saw that the kingdom of heaven was a process, a development of the higher in its struggle with the lower. Nothing can ultimately withstand the princi- ple of goodness ; but in his blindness and evil will man may for a time turn his ener- gies against it. Hence the slow growth of the "kingdom of heaven," — a growth so slow that it often seems to be arrest or even retro- gression. This idea is expressed by Jesus in a variety of figures. The kingdom of heaven is compared to the leaven, which was "hid in three measures of meal till the whole was leavened." The mrst striking expression of THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL 95 the idea, however, is given in that wonderful parable preserved in the oldest of the gospels, the gospel of Mark: "So is the kingdom of heaven as if a man should cast seed into the ground, and should sleep and rise day and night, and the seed should spring and grow up, he knoweth not how. For the earth bringeth forth fruit of herself; first the blade, then the ear, then the full corn in the ear. But when the fruit is ripe, immediately he putteth in the sickle, for the harvest is come." The attitude of Jesus towards the Messianic hope of his countrymen at once follows from his conception of the kingdom of heaven as already present, and yet as a process of conflict with evil. Holding these views he could not possibly believe in any sudden or miraculous change which should break the continuity be- tween the present and the future. Hence he refused to attest his divine mission by signs and wonders. When the Pharisees, in their usual crass materialism, demanded a " sign," — i.e, demanded that Jesus should virtually deny the presence of God in the ordinary processes of nature and in the normal experiences of 96 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE human life — his answer was : " An evil and adulterous generation seeketh after a sign, and there shall no sign be given to it but the sign of the prophet Jonah." What he meant was, as Luke saw, that no " sign " could authenti- cate his mission but the truth which he pro- claimed. Truth "shines by its own light," and if men " will not hear Moses and the prophets, neither would they believe if one were to rise from the dead." Hence Jesus, though he em- ploys the apocalyptic imagery current in his day, entirely transforms the current conception of the future success of the kingdom of heaven. The triumph of good over evil, as he affirms, is not to be effected by catastrophe and revolution, but only by the persistent labours of those who live in the truth. His faith does not rest upon a superstitious belief in a sudden interposition from heaven. In his eyes good can be developed only through the loving efforts of those in whom the divine Spirit operates, and who "let their light so shine among men that others, seeing their good works, glorify their Father which is in heaven." Thus his optimism flows from abso- THE CHRIST/ AN WEAL 97 lute trust in the goodness of God, and in a rec- ognition that man in his ideal nature is a " son of God." For this reason he beHeves that to the success of the kingdom it is essential that each individual should have a personal experi- ence of the truth. This is indicated by the images of the leaven and the mustard-seed. He does not expect the triumph of goodness from any external arrangements of society, or rather he conceives of these as but the par- tial expression of a truth which must first exist in those whose hearts are open to the truth. At the same time, since the very essence of Jesus' teaching is the essentially social nature of man, the principle which he announced could not but manifest itself in a transformation of social and political institu- tions, though these can never be more than a partial expression of the idea of a king- dom in which the spirit of God is present in each, member of the whole, at once dis- tinguishing and uniting them in an organic unity. In this conception of a spiritual commu- nity, in which each has found himself by los- 98 THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE ing himself, Jesus finds the answer to that longing for deliverance from the evil of their own hearts which was the saving salt in the aspirations of the pious souls of his own day. Just as he refuses to postpone the kingdom of heaven to some far-off day, when good shall conquer evil, maintaining that evil is already overcome in principle ; so he tells those who " labour and are heavy-laden," long- ing for a deliverance in which they have but faint belief, that the way to the conquest of evil in themselves is now open. And the secret is in identification with their brethren, the sons of the one Father. This was the secret of that triumphant optimism which nothing could destroy in him. This idea is expressed in the title which he most frequently applied to himself, the " Son of Man." This term is often used in the Old Testament, — for in- stance, in Ezekiel, — to express the weakness and dependence of man, as contrasted with the power and majesty of God. In Daniel, again, it refers not to a personal Messiah, but to the collective body of the saints, as contrasted with the great, victorious beasts. THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL 99 the symbols of the powerful world-empires. " The core of Daniel's Messianic hope is the universal dominion of the saints." * Now if, as seems probable, Jesus adopted the term from Daniel, he meant by it to indicate, not merely the spirituality of his kingdom, but his own identity with the whole race. In any case, the essential meaning of the title is that Jesus conceived himself as part and parcel of humanity: in other words, he found the secret of life in complete identification with its joys and sorrows, its successes and sins. And because he was thus identified with man, he is also called the " Son of God." He was one with the Father in nature, though not in person, since he was conscious of himself as the medium through which the eternal love of God was revealed and communicated to men. Nothing can, in his view, withstand the power of love. Man, weak and sinful as he is, must suc- cumb to the omnipotence of goodness, for goodness is the spirit of the living God. It was with a full sense of the importance of ♦ Schurer's History of the Jewish People, 2. 2. 138. lOO THE CHRISTlAJSr IDEAL OF LIFE the question that, towards the close of his life, he asked the disciples : " Who do ye say that the Son of Man is ? " And when Peter, in a flash of insight, answered : " Thou art the Christ, the Son of the living God," he immediately goes on to warn the disciples that he must " suffer many things of the elders and chief priests and the scribes, and be killed." He was the Messiah, just because it was his mission to effect the deliverance of mankind, not through outward triumph, but through suffering and death. To the disciples, with their preconception of a Mes- siah who should come invested with miracu- lous power and dignity, this was a "hard saying " ; and the same apostle, who had for a moment got a glimpse of the divine human- ity of Jesus, now exclaims in horror : " Be it far from thee. Lord: this shall never be unto thee." Thus even Peter puts himself on the side of those who imagined that a suffering Messiah was a contradiction in terms. He had not learned the lesson of the divine life and teaching of the Master, and therefore Jesus rebukes him for the mate- THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL ,o, rialism of his conception : " Thou art a stum- bling-block unto me: for thou mindest not the things of God, but the things of men." It is not by self-assertion and outward tri- umph, but by suffering and death, that the true Christ and his followers can save the world: "Whosoever would save his life shall lose it: and whosoever shall lose his life for my sake shall gain it." As he transforms the ordinary idea of the Messiah, so Jesus gives to the belief in a final judgment of the world a new and deeper meaning. The wicked and the right- eous are no longer distinguished as those who obey the law from those who violate it, but as those who love from those who are indifferent to their fellow-men. The whole system of external rewards and punishments is swept away, and in its place we have the one fundamental distinction of those whose lives are ruled by the spirit of brotherhood, and those who live for themselves. Under the guise of the current imagery of a Last Judgment, when all men shall be gathered together to receive their final sentence, Jesus 102 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE inculcates the truth that the spiritual status of men is already determined by the prin- ciple which is outwardly expressed in their actions. " Inasmuch as ye did it unto one of these my brethren, even these least, ye did it unto me." Thus while he leaves untouched the current belief in a future judgment, he brings to the test of human action an entirely new standard. Not the pious works upon which men pride themselves, but the unselfish life, determines the eternal destiny of man. He who lives the divine life is he who, like the Master, has merged his own good in the good of the whole, and who has proved his love of man by the ordinary tender charities which seem so little, but mean so much. From what has been said we can understand the sense in which Jesus speaks of " Faith." To the scribes and Pharisees religion meant acceptance of the teaching of the doctors of the Law, as based upon their interpretations of scripture. Thus for the ordinary Jew there was a double wall of partition raised between him and God. Not only had he no direct con- sciousness of the divine nature, and therefore THE CHRISTIAN WEAL ,03 of his own nature, but even the revelations of truth which were contained in scripture came to him through the distorted medium of tradi- tion. No doubt it was impossible to read the inspired words of legislator and prophet with- out catching something of their spirit; but so overlaid was the sacred text with the prosaic and deadening interpretations of the scribes, which were dinned into his ears at home, at school, and in the synagogue, that it was hard for him to pierce through the mass of tradi- tional ideas to the truth which they over- laid and obscured. One consequence of this traditionalism was an incapacity to judge for himself when a new revelation of truth was presented to him. This was one of the great obstacles which Jesus met in his effort to bring his countrymen into living contact with the truth. The leaden weight of custom lay heavy upon the minds of "the people of the Law," and only by a powerful effort could they shake off the mass of prejudice and supersti- tion which they had been taught to regard as the revelation of God. And this intellectual difficulty was intensified by the spiritual arro- I04 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE gance which had been engendered in their minds by the traditional belief in their unique position as the people of Jehovah. Thus the Jew had to free both his intellect and his con- science from the fetters of traditionalism be- fore he was in a position to look straight at the truth. This explains why Jesus insists upon " faith " as a child-like attitude. Only those from whose minds and hearts the arti- ficial veil of custom and pride of race had been removed were in a position to accept the new revelation of truth. It is in this sense, and not in the sense of unreasoning credulity, that he commends the " faith " of those who welcomed the truth. Thus for him " faith " is that open- ness to light which is a form of reason ; it is, in fact, reason in its purest form. What Jesus called upon men to believe he supported, not by an appeal to authority, but by an ap- peal to truth itself. He asked them to look with open eyes at the evidences of God's good- ness as exhibited in the world of nature ; to examine their own hearts, and to read the say- ings of the holy men of old with intelligence and insight. To the persistent demand for THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL 05 supernatural " signs " of his divine mission, he refused to listen, seeing in them but another form of that crude materialism which infected all their ideas. A saving " faith " he found in those few whose consciousness of their own weakness and sinfulness was so strong that, under the influence of his life and words, it removed the mist of tradition from their minds, and overcame the racial pride so natural in a Jew. " Faith " is thus that union of intellect- ual candour and moral simplicity which flows from the vision of God. It cannot be trans- ferred externally from one person to another, but is possible only in him who has surren- dered all that ministers to self-righteousness and selfishness. It is thus another name for the consciousness of unity and reconciliation with God, and for that ''enthusiasm of hu- manity" which flows from it. " Faith," in other words, is the personal side of the whole con- sciousness of the "kingdom of heaven," as Jesus understood it : it is the spirit which operates in every member of those who are reconciled with God, and are therefore at unity with themselves and with one another. I06 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE No doubt this faith has various degrees, but in essence it is always the same. It is also recognised by Jesus that it grows from age to age; for, while he speaks of the Law and the prophets as giving a revelation of the divine nature, he also maintains that he has himself given a higher revelation of God than was possible to them. " Many prophets and righteous men have earnestly desired to see what ye see and have not seen it, and to hear what ye hear and have not heard it." Here, as always, Jesus holds by both sides of the truth: the essential identity of the religious consciousness in all ages, and the process of expansion which it undergoes as it comes to a fuller consciousness of what it contained implicitly from the first. There is one other aspect of Christ's teaching which must not be passed over. Although the Messianic hope was usually connected in the Jewish mind with the ap- pearance of an earthly Messiah, and the resurrection of the dead for judgment, it was also held by many that after the long reign of the saints there should follow an eternity THE CHRISTIAN TD^AL ,07 of bliss or woe in another world. Now, although Jesus gave a new meaning to the kingdom of heaven, and insisted that it already existed in the consciousness of those who were reconciled to God and devoted to the good of humanity, he also held the doc- trine of personal immortality. When the Sadducees came, demanding a proof of im- mortality, he appealed to the words of script- ure: "I am the God of Abraham and the God of Isaac and the God of Jacob," add- ing that "God is not the God of the dead but of the living." There was an especial appropriateness in this reply as directed against the Sadducees, who prided them- selves upon being faithful to the teaching of scripture, as distinguished from the tradi- tional interpretation accepted by the Phari- sees. But, as we have seen, Jesus does not accept even the teaching of the "Law and the prophets " without first bringing to bear upon it the light of his own higher con- sciousness, and hence we may be certain that these words were more than an argu- mentum ad hominem, intended to silence the I08 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE Sadducees. The meaning of Jesus seems to be that, as the consciousness of the Hving God involves the consciousness of man as identical in his essential nature with God, we must believe in the eternal continuance of this fundamental relation. To see what man is in his true nature is to know that his life comes from God, and that only in the consciousness of his union with God does he learn what in essence he is. The essence of man is his life, ix, his conscious existence, and this must be as eternal as God. The true destiny of man is to live in union with God, and this destiny cannot be taken from him by God whose son he is. Thus Jesus, as he conceives of God as the ever-living Father, also conceives of men as beings with an immortal destiny. The future existence of man he also conceives as a higher stage of being, when they shall be " as the angels," i.e, shall enjoy a clearer vision of God, and when goodness shall at last have overcome evil, and no longer be forced to engage in perpetual conflict with it. While Jesus thus maintains the personal THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL lO) immortality of man, he does not base upon it a proof of the reality of his view of life; on the contrary, he bases immortality upon the belief in God and the essential identity in nature of God and man. For he asserts that those who will not be convinced of the truth by " Moses and the prophets " would not believe " even if one were to rise from the dead." The order of ideas in his mind therefore is God, sonship, immortality. It is our knowledge of the nature of God which reveals to us his Fatherhood, and his Father- hood is the proof of the immortality of his children. CHAPTER V MEDIAEVAL CHRISTIANITY In the last chapter an attempt has been made to present the Christian ideal of life, as set forth by its Founder. No attempt will here be made to deal with that impos- ing edifice of doctrine which was built up by St. Paul and the other apostles and by the subsequent reflection of Christian theologians; but it will help to throw the teaching of Jesus into bolder relief, if we contrast with it the Christianity of the Middle Ages. When we pass from the religion of Jesus to mediaeval Christianity, we seem to have entered into another world. The free and genial glance with which our Lord contem- plated nature, the triumphant optimism of his conception of human life, and his absolute faith in the realisation of the kingdom of MEDIAEVAL CHRISTIANITY m heaven here and now, have been replaced by a hard and almost mechanical idea of the external world, by a stern denunciation of the utter perversity and evil of society, and by the postponement of the kingdom of heaven to the future life. How has this re- markable change come over the Christian consciousness? To answer this question would be a long task, and I shall only state three main characteristics in the mediaeval conception of life, trying to indicate how they originated. (i) The first characteristic to which I shall refer is the universal belief that the "king- dom of heaven," to use the term which Jesus so often employs, could not be realised in this life, but was entirely a thing of the future life. We can trace the gradual growth of this con- viction. The crucifixion of their Lord was a terrible shock to his disciples, and there is good reason to believe that for a moment it caused their belief in his Messiahship to waver. But, as the divine life and sayings of the Master came back to their remembrance, they began to understand what he had him- 112 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE self always affirmed — that his kingdom was a spiritual one, which could be realised only by the destruction of evil and the triumph of righteousness. Yet they still clung to the idea that so great a revolution could be accomplished only by a sudden and miracu- lous change; and hence in the Apostolic Age the Christian, imperfectly liberated from the materialism of the ordinary Messianic concep- tion, imagined that the complete triumph of righteousness would take place in a few years by the second coming of the Lord to estab- lish upon earth the reign of peace and good will. Living in this faith, the primitive com- munity of Christians made no attempt to interfere with existing institutions, civil or ecclesiastical, but were content to prepare for the imminent advent of the Lord. But as time went on, and still the Lord did not appear, his advent came to seem more and more remote. Meantime the Christian found himself living in the midst of the decaying civilisation of Rome, and there was little won- der that the conversion of the world should seem an almost impossible task: — MEDIEVAL CHRISTIANITY 113 Stout was its arm, each thew and bone Seemed puissant and alive, — But ah ! its heart, its heart was stone, And so it could not thrive. "How can these bones live?" he naturally exclaimed. How can this mass of corrup- tion be transformed into the divine image? Moreover, try as they might to avoid collision with the secular power of the Roman empire, the Christians found that they could not meet together for mutual encouragement and stimulation, without drawing suspicion upon themselves as a secret society plotting the overthrow of the empire ; and, indeed, though they had no such purpose, the Christian ideal was antagonistic to the pagan, and must at last meet with and overcome it, or be itself subdued. The outward symbol of this war of ideals was the persecutions to which the Christians were subjected in the second and third centuries. Thus the present world came to appear more and more a wilderness through which the little band of Christians was com- pelled to march, sad and solitary, on their way to the heavenly land. This sombre cast 114 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE of thought never vanished from the Christian consciousness till the modern age, and per- haps it cannot be said to have quite vanished even now. One might have supposed that the more hopeful spirit of an earlier age would have come back when Christianity had, by its resistless energy, compelled the Roman empire, in the person of Constantine, to make terms with it. But the inrush of the fierce northern hordes into the Roman em- pire, and their facile conversion to Chris- tianity, confirmed in a new way the "other- worldliness " of the Church. For Christianity, to their rude and undisciplined minds, was in all its deeper aspects unintelligible, and its doctrines could only be accepted in blind and unquestioning faith. A superstitious rever- ence for the Church did not restrain them from the wildest excesses of passion, and the only curb to their brutal violence and self- will was the hope of future reward or the dread of future retribution. Thus mediaeval Christianity, unable to overcome the barbar- ism and lawlessness of the world, in a sort of despair sought comfort in the future life. MEDIEVAL CHRISTIANITY ijr This is the spirit which rules the whole of the Middle Ages, and it was one of the tasks of the Reformation to awaken anew the con- sciousness of the infinite significance of the present life as a preparation for the future life, and to quicken all the institutions of so- ciety and all the powers of the individual soul with the divine spirit of pristine Christianity. (2) A second characteristic of the mediaeval period is a belief in the absolute authority of the Church in all matters of faith and wor- ship, and the consequent distinction between the clergy and the laity. This idea had its roots in the same principle as that which led to the conception of religion as essentially the hope of a future world. The rude bar- barian could not comprehend the doctrines of the Church, nor could his self-will be broken except by a power to which he was forced to bend his stubborn will. Hence the Church demanded implicit faith in its teach- ing, and absolute submission to its authority. Nor is it easy to see how otherwise the soil could have been prepared in which the new seed of the Reformation was to grow. The Il6 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE discipline of the mediaeval Church was, on the whole, as salutary as it was inevitable ; but dis- cipline is justifiable only as a preparation for the exercise of independence and reason; and hence the time inevitably came when men, hav- ing outgrown the stage of pupilage, asserted their indefeasible right to a rational liberty. This was the claim made by Luther when he unfurled "the banner of the free spirit." (3) The last characteristic of the Middle Ages to which I shall refer is the opposition of faith and reason. To come to its full rights as the universal religion Christianity had to free itself from all that was accidental and temporary in the conceptions of its first ad- herents. The first step in this process was taken when St. Paul disengaged it from the accidents of its Jewish origin and presented its essence in a clear and definite form. But the process could not end here, for every age has its own preconceptions and its own diffi- culties. When Christianity went beyond the boundaries of Judea, it had to meet and over- come the dualism of Greek thought, as it had met and overcome Jewish narrowness and ex- MEDIEVAL CHRrSTIANITY 1,7 clusiveness. The victory was only imperfectly accomplished. The reconciling principle of the essential identity of the human and divine could not be abandoned without the destruc- tion of the central idea of Christianity, but the Church did not entirely escape the danger of making theology a transcendent theory of the absolutely inscrutable nature of God. At this imperfect stage of development Christian dogma was for a time arrested, so that when re- flection arose with Scholasticism the doctrines of the Church were assumed to be expressions of absolute truth, although they contained certain mysterious and incomprehensible ele- ments. There is indeed in the development of Scholasticism itself a growing consciousness of the antagonism of reason to the dogmas of the Church as commonly understood, a con- sciousness which in Occam even reaches the form of a belief that there are doctrines which are not only " beyond " but " contrary to " rea- son ; but the schoolmen never lost their faith in the truth of the dogmas, though they passed from credo ut intelligam to iiitelligo ut credam, and ended with credo quia impossible. When Il8 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE i'v thus came to be explicitly affirmed that the doctrines of the Church contained not merely j/^/^rrational but irrational elements, the be- ginning of the end was near ; for reason, frus- trated in its attempt to find unity with itself in an authoritative creed, could only fall back in despair upon a universal scepticism or set about a reconstruction of the creed itself. Thus Scholasticism dug its own grave as well as the grave of mediaeval theology, and pre- pared the way for that great modern move- ment which began with the Renaissance and the Reformation and is still going on. Of one thing we may be sure, that nothing short of a perfect harmony of science, art, and religion can permanently satisfy the liberated human spirit. At such a harmony it is the hard task of philosophy to aim, and only in so far as it is secured can we hope for the return of that half-vanished faith in the omnipotence of good- ness with which Jesus was so abundantly filled. It is therefore proposed, in the second part of this work, to ask how far an idealistic phi- losophy enables us to retain the fundamental conception of life which was enunciated by the Founder of Christianity. PART II MODERN IDEALISM IN ITS RELATION TO THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE CHAPTER VI GENERAL STATEMENT AND DEFENCE OF IDEALISM In his Foundations of Belief, Mr. Balfour raises an objection to the idealistic theory of knowledge, a consideration of which may help to bring out more clearly what is here meant by Idealism. This objection is di- rected primarily against what is claimed to be the doctrine of the late T. H. Green, but it is thought to apply with equal force against all who hold the idealistic view of the world. In what follows no attempt will be made to defend Green from Mr. Balfour's attack. It does not appear to me true that Green reduced the world to a " network of relations " ; but it seems better to avoid all disputes which turn upon the interpretation of an author who is not here to defend himself, and therefore I shall deal from an independent point of view with the difficulty 121 122 THE CHRISTIAN- WEAL OF LIFE which Mr. Balfour has stated with his usual force and clearness. The main charge made by Mr. Balfour against Idealism is that it " reduces all ex- perience to an experience of relations," or " constitutes the universe out of categories." Now, it is no doubt true, says our author, that we cannot reduce the universe to " an unrelated chaos of impressions or sensa- tions " ; but " must we not also grant that in all experience there is a refractory element which, though it cannot be presented in iso- lation, nevertheless refuses wholly to merge its being in a network of relations } " If so, whence does this irreducible element arise .^^ The mind, we are told, is the source of re- lations. What is the source of that which is related } The " thing in itself " of Kant " raises more difficulties than it solves," and indeed, the followers of Kant themselves point out that this hypothetical cause of that which is " given " in experience cannot be known as a cause, or even as existing. But "we do not get rid of the difficulty by get- ting rid of Kant's solution of it. His dictum STATEMENT AND DEFENCE OF IDEALISM 123 still seems to remain true, that * without mat- ter categories are empty.' And, indeed, it is hard to see how it is possible to conceive a universe in which nothing is to be permitted for the relations to subsist between. Rela- tions surely imply a something which is re- lated, and if that something is, in the absence of relations, ' nothing for us as thinking be- ings,' so relations in the absence of that something are mere symbols emptied of their signification." * Mr. Balfour, it would seem, rejects the sensationalist theory that knowledge is re- ducible to an association of individual feel- ings, and he also rejects the Kantian refer- ence of impressions of sense to a "thing in itself"; but he is unable to see how the world can be explained without the retention of a "matter" to supply the concrete filling for the otherwise empty categories. His own view would therefore seem to be that the knowable world involves two distinct ele- ments, a " matter of sense " and the concep- tions or relations by which that "matter" is ♦ Balfour's Foundations of Belief. Am. ed., pp. 144-5- i24 THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE formed. Where he differs from Idealism, as he understands it, is in denying that all reality can be reduced to relations of thought or pure conceptions. The force of Mr. Balfour's criticism, therefore, depends upon two assump- tions : firstly, that it is possible to retain the Kantian doctrine of a "matter of sense" after the rejection of Kant's assumption of a "thing in itself"; and, secondly, that Ideal- ism seeks to construct the world out of empty conceptions or relations of thought. Both of these assumptions I venture to chal- lenge. (i) The Kantian doctrine of a " matter of sense" stands or falls with the assumption of a "thing in itself." In the Esthetic the problem of knowledge is put by Kant in this way: What is the element in the perception of objects as in space and time which belongs to the subject, and what is the element which belongs to the object .?* Kant's answer is, that the "form" under which objects are re- lated spatially and temporally is due to the subject, the "matter" so related to the ob- ject. Now, in this contrast of " form " and STATEMENT AND DEFENCE OF IDEALISM 125 "matter," it is obviously assumed that the subject has a nature of its own independently of the object, and the object a nature of its own independently of the subject; in other words, that, as existences, subject and object are unrelated to each other. On the other hand it is admitted by Kant that there can be no knowledge until the subject comes into relation to the object. Now, the assumption of the independent existence of subject and object is no doubt a very natural assumption, because, when we begin to explain knowledge, we already have knowledge. But we must not forget that, in accounting for the origin of knowledge, we have no right to assume the very knowledge we are seeking to explain. We cannot start from the independent existence of subject and object unless we can show that an indepen- dent subject and object can be known. Before we ask what is contributed by the subject, and what comes from the object, we must be sure that the separation of subject and object is admissible. If there is no known subject which does not imply a known object, the ele- 126 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE ment belonging to the one cannot be sepa- rated from the element belonging to the other. When Kant asks " by what means our faculty of knowledge should be aroused to activity but by objects," he forgets that neither object nor subject exists for knowledge prior to know- ledge, and that to ask how the subject should be '' aroused to activity " by the object is to ask how a non-existent object should act upon a non-existent subject. This question cannot be answered, because it is self-contradictory, for to a self-contradictory question no answer can possibly be given. But though Kant starts from the opposi- tion of subject and object, he takes, in the Esthetic, the first step to effect its over- throw. The real object, he says, no doubt exists apart from the subject, but the known object does not. For, in the perception of objects, the relations of space and time are the manner in which the subject, when " aroused to activity," comes to have a con- sciousness of objects. So far, therefore, as knowledge goes, the object is not an inde- pendent existence, but an existence in and STATEMENT AND DEFENCE OF. IDEALISM 127 for a conscious subject. Now this view leads to an important change in our ordinary con- ception of the world. When we assume an objective world, fully formed and complete in itself, apart from the subject, we manifestly make the subject a mere passive spectator of a world from which it stands apart; and when we assume a subject with a complex nature of its own, we make the world en- tirely foreign to the subject. But the mo- ment we ask how this objective world becomes known to the subject, we find that the independence of each alternately disap- pears in the other. Thus, if the object is apprehended by the subject, and only in this apprehension exists for it, the whole objec- tive world is absorbed into the subject. On the other hand, if we ask what is the con- tent of the subject, we find that it is the object, and thus the subject is absorbed in the object. Kant, however, does not carry over the object as a whole into the subject, but draws a distinction between the element which comes from the object and the ele- ment which is added by the subject. In 128 THE CHRISTTAJSr IDEAL OF LIFE this way the identification of subject and ob- ject is partially arrested, and an intermediate region is assumed in which subject and ob- ject enter into relation with each other. This is the region of knowledge. But, while this union of subject and object is the condition of knowable reality, subject and object still remain apart as existences. Here, then, we have the " thing in itself," as it appears in the Esthetic, The compromise which Kant here adopts is obviously untenable. If we are to as- sume the independent existence of subject and object, we must not at the same time assume that the one is dependent for its reality upon the other. Since the spatial and tem- poral relations have a meaning only within knowledge, they can no more belong to the subject than to the object, but only to the subject in so far as there has arisen for it the consciousness of an object determinable under those relations. Why, then, does Kant maintain that space and time are forms of perception, not determinations of the real ? FJe does so because he has not completely STATEMEATT AMD DEFENCE OF (PEALISM 129 freed himself from the dualism of subject and object with which he starts. A subject as- sumed to exist apart from the object must be regarded as a pure blank so far as know- ledge is concerned; and when it begins to know we must suppose it to be affected by the object. Thus it is regarded as purely recep- tive in its relation to the object, and there- fore it has to wait for the action of the object upon it. Now when we ask whether the sub- ject can be purely receptive, or whether it must not be affirmed to be at once receptive and conscious of being receptive, it becomes manifest that the whole conception of a purely receptive subject is unmeaning. If the sub- ject is receptive without being aware of it, it will simply exist in a series of individual states, without referring those states either to an object or to itself. For such a subject there can be no objective world ; for; as Kant himself tells us, the consciousness of objects implies "the reference of sensation to objects in perception." On the other hand, if the subject not only exists in a series of affec- tions, but is conscious of affections as coming 130 THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE from the object, it must distinguish them as its own and yet relate them to the object. But so far as it does so, the object is within knowledge, not a thing existing by itself. Thus the object has no existence for the sub- ject except as the subject distinguishes it from and yet relates it to itself. The object is the product of its own activity, and hence the subject cannot be receptive in regard to it. A subject which is not self-active is for itself nothing. In truth, a purely receptive subject is a contradiction in terms. It is only be- cause Kant does not distinguish between a subject which is purely sensitive — and only by an abuse of language can this be called a " subject " at all — and a subject which is conscious of its states as involving perma- nent relations, that he allows himself to speak of the subject as receptive in relation to the object. Whatever the object is, it is for a subject, and any other object is a fiction of abstraction. We may legitimately contrast the object as known in fuller determinateness with the object as less determinate, but the object is in either case a known object, not STATEMENT AND DEFENCE OF ./DEAUSAf 131 a " thing in itself." To contrast a known with an unknown object is the greatest of all ab- surdities, because an unknown object is simply nothing for the subject, and therefore cannot b^ contrasted with anything. It follows from what has been said that there can be no opposition between the " mat- ter " and the " form " of knowledge : no oppo- sition, that is, between a " matter " which comes from the object and a "form" contrib- uted by the subject. We must therefore deny that affections of sense as such enter into or form any element in knowable objects. Kant himself admits that such affections do not exist as an object for consciousness, but are merely the "manifold" out of which ob- jects are formed: they are the "matter" which becomes an object, when the subject combines its determinations under the form of time into an image or perception. But when the "manifold of sense" becomes an object, it is no longer a "matter" to which the subject has to give "form," but is already a formed matter. The subject does not first receive the " matter of sense," and then impose upon 132 THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE It its own forms ; only in so far as the " mat- ter" is already formed does it exist for the subject at all. The so-called " manifold of sense " is therefore just the distinguishable aspects of the world as these exist for the conscious subject. This world is indeed " manifold " in the sense of being infinitely concrete ; but its concreteness is not that of an aggregate of particulars, but of a " cosmos of experience," in which all the particulars distinguished are held together in the unity of a single world, which exists only for a com- bining self-active subject. (2) The denial of the fiction of a "matter of sense," entirely destitute of the unifying activity of intelligence, is therefore a very different thing from the denial of all differ- ences and the reduction of reality to a "net- work of relations." Mr. Balfour's charge that Idealism reduces the world to relations, and therefore involves the absurdity of relations with nothing to relate, rests upon a misunder- standing of the idealistic theory of thought or intelligence as the constitutive principle of all knowledge and all reality. What Ideal- STATEMENT AND DEFENCE OF JDEALISM 133 ism maintains is that the knowablc world exists only for a thinking or self-conscious subject, and that even the simplest phase of knowledge involves the activity of that sub- ject. It is very inadequate and misleading to speak of thought as if it consisted solely in the relation of separate elements to one another. When thought is thus conceived, it is easy to understand why those who affirm that the world exists only for thought are supposed to be constructing reality out of pure abstractions. It is not difficult to show that this conception is a survival of the old untenable opposition of perception and thought, as dealing respectively with the par- ticular and the universal. Let us take a simple case by way of illustration. I perceive a speck of light in the surrounding darkness. Taking the old abstract view, we have here the simple apprehension of a particular sen- sible object, without any exercise of the activ- ity of thought. The latter comes into play only when I compare various perceptions with each other. Such a doctrine was virtually disposed of when Kant showed that the sim- 134 ^-^^ CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE plest perception already involves the synthetic activity of thought. My apprehension of the speck of light is by no means simple. The moment I have the sensation, my mind goes to work, seeking to put it in its proper place in relation to the rest of my experience. There are no doubt occasions in my indi- vidual life in which this interpretative power is almost entirely in abeyance, as when I have just awaked from sleep, or emerged from a swoon. But even in these states the activity of intelligence is not entirely absent; for I at least distinguish the speck of light from the surrounding darkness; I locate it with more or less accuracy; and I distinguish it from myself as a particular object. Now we have here one of the simplest forms in which the thinking subject builds up for him- self an intelligible world. Without the sensi- tivity to light, there would be for the subject no object at all; but without the interpreta- tive activity of thought the sensitivity would have no meaning, Le. it would not be grasped as a particular phase of a single world. Per- ception is, therefore, not the mere presence of STATEMENT AND DEFENCE OF WEAUSM 135 a particular sensation or image, but the dis- crimination of its elements, and the compre- hension of these as involving certain fixed conditions under which they occur. If we exclude the interpretative activity of thought there is for us no object; and, therefore, no knowledge. It is only because this grasp of the particular as an instance of fixed con- nexion in experience is overlooked, that per- ception is supposed to be possible without the combined distinction and unification which is due to the activity of the thinking subject. But this activity is not the external relation of individual sensations. Sensibility as such is not an object of knowledge, but only partic- ular sensations grasped as indicating fixed con- nexions in their occurrence. Hence thought is present in what is called sensation, in so far as sensation enters into our experience; and when present it interprets sensation by refer- ence to its fixed conditions. The content of sensation does not fall without, but within thought; and it is this thought content which constitutes the world of our perception. That world is from the first a connected whole, in 136 THE CHRISTIAIV WEAL OF LIFE which every element is on the one hand re- ferred to a single world, and on the other hand to a single subject. Nor can the one be separated from the other, for the unity of the world is made possible by the unifying activity of the subject. It must also be ob- served that this unifying activity is not the activity of a principle which merely operates through the individual subject: it is essen- tially the activity of a self-determining sub- ject, which is conscious of a single world only in so far as in every phase of its experience it is self-active. The degree in which the world is comprehended is proportionate to the self-activity of the intelligent subject; and thus the world, while it never loses its unity, is continually growing in complexity and sys- tematic unity. There is a single self-consist- ent world, because the world is a systematic unity, and because reason in all self-conscious beings is an organic unity, identical in nature, but distinct in its individual activity. Mr. Balfour assumes that the denial of a given " matter of sense " is the same thing as the denial of all determinate reality. But, in STATEMENT AND DEFENCE OF IQEALISM 137 truth, the denial of the former is essential to the preservation of the latter. It is only in so far as the sensible is discriminated by thought, that there is any determinate object of knowledge; and it is only in so far as these discriminated elements are combined by the activity of a single subject, that there is any unity of experience. The thinking subject cannot have before him any object without grasping it by thought, or interpret- ing his immediate feelings by reference to the idea, explicit or implicit, of a connected system of reality. What Idealism maintains, therefore, is that the impossibility of having the consciousness of any object which cannot be combined with the consciousness of self is a proof that the world is a rational system. The whole process of knowledge consists in the ever more complete reduction of partic- ulars to the unity of an organic whole; and, though it is true that a complete knowledge of the world is never attained. Idealism affirms that, were knowledge complete, the world would be found to be rational throu^i^h and through. Perhaps what has been said will 138 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE help to show that what Idealism denies is not that the world is concrete, but that its. concreteness can be explained by any theory which starts from the fiction of an irreducible "matter of sense," i.e, a "matter" assumed to be absolutely opaque to a rational being. Mr. Balfour assumes that thought deals purely with abstractions or relations, and it is on this ground that he charges Idealism with "constituting the universe out of cate- gories." The falsity of this view has already been indicated, but the point is so important that it seems advisable to dwell upon it somewhat more fully, especially as even Mr. Bradley seems to me to have lent the weight of his authority to what I must regard as the survival of an obsolete mode of thought. There can be no thought whatever, whether it takes the form of conception, judgment, or inference, unless thought is itself a principle of unity. This unity, however, must not be conceived as working by the method of ab- straction, but as manifesting itself in the dis- tinction and combination of differences. We can, no doubt, fix our attention upon the unity STATEMENT AND DEFENCE OF WEAL/SM 139 which is implied in every act of thought, but we cannot affirm that thought is a unity which excludes differences. Thought is thus the universal capacity of combining differ- ences in a unity. Now, if thought is by its very nature a unity, there can be no absolute separation between the various elements which it combines — no separation, that is, within thought itself. It is perhaps not impossible that there are real elements which thought cannot reduce to unity, but within thought itself there can be no such elements: ele- ments which are not combined are not thought. We cannot therefore regard the organism of thought as made up of a num- ber of independent conceptions or ideas hav- ing no relation to one another; the whole of our conceptions taken together form the unity which thought by its activity consti- tutes. Conception is thus the process in which the distinguishable aspects of the real world, or what we believe to be the real world, are combined in the unity of a single system. This process may be viewed either as a progressive differentiation or as a pro- I40 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE gressive unification. And these two aspects are essentially correlative: conception reaches a higher stage according as it unites a greater number of differences, and it cannot unite without distinguishing. It is of great impor- tance to keep hold of this truth. To neglect it is to make a consistent theory of know- ledge impossible. If conception is a process of abstraction, thought can by no possibility comprehend reality. The importance of the subject will excuse a few remarks upon the nature of "conception" and its relation to judgment. Conception may be regarded as the termina- tion or as the beginning of a judgment, accord- ing to our point of view. In the former case conception condenses, or holds in a transpar- ent unity, the distinguishable elements which have been combined in a prior judgment, or rather it is the synthetic unity of a number of prior judgments. Thus the conception "light" comprehends the prior judgments by which the object "light" has entered into the world of our thought. Hence it is that judgment has been supposed to be STATEMENT AMD DEFENCE OF IDEALISM 141 merely the analysis of a given conception. But no analysis of a conception can yield more than has previously been combined. The name "light" stands for more or fewer judgments according to the stage of thought of the individual who employs it. A so-called analytic judgment is simply the explicit state- ment of judgments already made, and adds nothing to the wealth of the thought- world. It is true that the resolution of a conception into the judgments which it presupposes may be the occasion of a new judgment. It is so when we for the first time observe that a con- ception does presuppose a number of judg- ments; but in this case we have done more than merely analyse the conception into its constituent elements : we have brought to light the nature of conception and its relation to judgment. It is characteristic of every real judgment — every judgment which is more than the repro- duction of a judgment formerly made — that it combines in a new unity elements not pre- viously combined. Can we then say that judg- ment is the combination of conceptions } Not 142 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE if we mean by this that the conceptions remain in the judgment what they were prior to the judgment. A conception being the condensed result of prior judgments in which distinguish- able elements of reality have been united, it forms the starting-point for new judgments, but each of these new judgments is the further comprehension of the real, and there- fore the conception grows richer in content with each judgment. Thus if, starting from the ordinary conception of " light," we go on to judge that it is "due to the vibration of an aether," we do not simply add a new predicate to the subject, but the conception is itself transformed and enriched. Judg- ment is thus conception viewed as in pro- cess, and a conception is any stage in that process. The distinction is purely relative. In judgment thought unifies the elements which it discriminates ; in conception the elements are viewed as united even while they are discriminated. For it must be observed that thought never unifies with- out discriminating: the whole process of thought is concrete throughout, and, as STATEMENT AND DEFENCE OF IDEALISM 143 knowledge develops, becomes more and more concrete. We are therefore entitled to say that for the thinking subject reality is in continual process, and we are also entitled to say that there is neither thinking subject nor thought reality outside of the process of thought. A real world which is not capable of being thought is for the subject nothing, and a subject which is not capable of think- ing the real world is also nothing. If this view is correct, it is misleading to say, with Mr. Bradley, that "in judgment an idea is predicated of a reality." * For the reality of which we judge is a reality which exists only for thought, and it has no content except that which it has received in the pro- cess by which it is constituted for thought. Mr. Bradley tells us that whatever we regard as real has two aspects, (^) existence, (^) con- tent, and that "thought seems essentially to consist in their division." Now, it is no doubt true that, if we suppose the real to be some- thing which exists apart from thought, we shall have to divide or separate the " what " ♦ Appearance and Reality, p. 163. 144 ^-^^ CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE from the " that." But there is for us no real in addition to the real which is thought. Such a real is a pure abstraction, and means no more than the empty possibility of the real. We cannot separate in this hypothetical real between the " that " and the " what," because, having no content, it is neither a " that " nor a "what." The real only comes to be for us in so far as there has gone on a process of discrimination and unification within a sin- gle reality, by means of which the real has been constituted as a thought or ideal reality. What Mr. Bradley calls the " that " seems to me merely a name for the unity which is in- volved in every phase of the process by which reality is thought ; and what he calls the " what " is a name for the elements which thought distinguishes and combines in the unity of the real. The " that " has therefore no determinateness when it is separated from the " what " ; it is simply pure being, or the bare potentiality of a thought reality. Mr. Bradley allows himself to speak of the " what " as if it were first " presented " in unity with the " that," and of judgment as if it consisted in the STATEMEJ^T ANP DEFENCE OF IDEALISM 145 " division " of the " what " from the " that." But surely there is no " what " except that which thought has already made its own. The sub- ject of any judgment has already a content, it is true, and this content we may express in the form of a series of judgments ; but these judg- ments will merely reproduce the judgments formerly made : they will add nothing to knowledge. Every new judgment, on the other hand, determines the conceived reality from which we start : it transforms the reality for thought, and thus enriches it by a new determination. There would be no reason for judging at all if judgment merely consisted in detaching a "content " from " existence," and then proceeding to attach it to "existence." The " existence " and the " content " are one and indivisible, and as the one grows, so also does the other. Mr. Bradley says that "an idea implies the separation of content from existence." And no doubt in every judgment the " content " is held suspended in thought before it is predicated of the subject. But, in the first place, so long as it is so held, there is no judgment: judgment consists in determin- 146 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE ing the subject by the predicate. And, in the second place, the content which is thus predi- cated of the subject is not the content which is already involved in the subject, and there- fore we cannot say that judgment consists in the separation of the " what " from the " that." When the scientific man affirms that light is due to the vibration of an aether, he does not separate the " content " already involved in the conception of the luminous object, and then predicate this " content " of the subject ; what he does is to determine the already qualified subject by a totally new " content " which it did not previously possess, and in this deter- mination of the subject the judgment consists. It thus seems to me that- Mr. Bradley gives countenance to two fallacies ; first, that the subject is a mere " that " instead of being the condensed result of the whole prior process of thought ; and, secondly, that judgment con- sists in the separation of a given content from the " that," a content which is then attributed to the "that"; whereas judgment consists in the predication of a new content, which de- velops and enriches the " that." Whatever STATEMENT AND DEFENCE OF IDEALISM 147 difficulty attaches to this view arises, as it seems to me, from the assumption that reahty exists apart from the process by which it is thought. And no doubt reality is not made by thought in the sense of being the creation of the individual thinking subject, but it is made for the subject in the sense that nothing is or can be real for him which is not revealed to him in the process by which he thinks it as real. When Mr. Bradley says that "the subject has unspecified content which is not stated in the predicate" (168), he is evidently confusing " the subject " with reality, as it would be could it be completely determined by thought. But such a subject is not the "that" which is distinguished from the " what," for the " that " is merely the abstraction of reality, — the abstract idea of reality in general which is no reality in particular. Such a subject has no " unspecified content," because it has no content whatever. But if by the " subject " is meant the complete system of reality, it is no doubt true that it has " unspecified content which is not stated in the predicate." No single judgment can express 14S The christian ideal of life the infinite wealth of the totality of reality. And not only is this true, but no single judg- ment can express the wealth of reality even as it exists for the subject who frames the judg- ment. We can only express the nature of reality in the totality of judgments which ex- press the nature of reality as known to us, and it is manifestly an inadequate or partial view which seeks to limit known reality to that as- pect of it which is expressed in a single judg- ment. But we must go still further; not only is known reality not expressed in any single judgment, but it is not expressed in the whole system of judgments which embody the know- ledge of man as it exists at any given time. Our knowledge is not complete, and I do not see how it ever can be complete. In that sense reality or the absolute must always be un- known. But unless reality in its true nature is different in kind from the reality which we know, it must be thinkable reality. Any other reality than that which is thinkable can have no community with thought reality, but must be absolutely unknowable. It is not main- tained that there is no reality which is not STATEMENT AND DEFENCE OF IDEALISM 149 thought by us, but only that the reality which we know is thought reality. This reality enters into our thought and forms its content, and as the content continually expands for us, so the reality continually expands. Reflecting upon this characteristic of knowledge, we get the notion of a completely determined reality, a reality which would be present to thought if thought were absolutely complete. Such a reality we do not possess, and it is therefore natural to say that there is a defect in the character of our thought which prevents us from grasping reality in its completeness. This explanation seems to me to rest upon the assumption that reality cannot be thought because thought deals only with abstractions. But, as I have maintained above, thought is never abstract; it contains within itself the whole wealth of reality, so far as reality is known to us. The defect is not in the char- acter of thought, as distinguished from feeling or intuition, but in the very nature of man as a being in whom knowledge is a never-ending process. What I contend for, then, is not that man has complete knowledge of reality, — a I50 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE contention which is manifestly absurd, — but that reality in its completeness must be a think- able reality. Any other view seems to me to lead to the caput mortuum of the thing-in-itself, the reality which cannot be thought because it is unthinkable. When, therefore, Mr. Bradley says that it is an untenable position to maintain that " in reality there is nothing beyond what is made thought's object" (169), I agree with a caveat. That there is nothing which is not made " thought's object " is manifestly untrue, if the "thought" here spoken of is thought as it exists for man. But, if it is meant that there is in reality something which cannot be made the object of thought, because it is unthinkable, I do not see what sort of reality this can be; to me it seems to be merely a name for a metaphysical abstraction. Reality that cannot be thought is a sort of reality to which I find myself unable to attach any meaning, and until I find some one who can give a meaning to it, I refuse to admit its possibility. But I feel certain that such a person cannot be found, for the obvi- ous reason that if this supposititious reality STATEMENT AND DEFENCE OF IDEALISM \ 5 i had a meaning, it would no longer be un- thinkable. If these considerations are at all correct, the only reality which has any meaning for us is reality that is capable of being thought. And this reality is not for us stationary, but grows in content as thought, which is the faculty of unifying the distinguishable elements of reality, develops in the process by which those elements are more fully distinguished and unified. The reality which thus enters into and constitutes our thought is therefore not abstract but infinitely concrete. For, as we have seen, the process of thought is not the mere transition from one conception to another, but it is the internal development of conception, which is at the same time the development of the conceived world. The reality, therefore, which thus arises for us in the process of thought is a system, in which there is revealed an ever greater diversity brought back into an ever more complete unity. And this reality is the absolute, so far as the absolute enters into and consti- tutes our known world. To seek for the 152 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE absolute beyond the thought reality, which alone exists for us, is to seek the living among the dead; if the absolute is not revealed to us in the reality that we know, it is for us nothing. CHAPTER VII IDEALISM IN RELATION TO AGNOSTICISM AND THE SPECIAL SCIENCES I. AGNOSTICISM In the preceding chapter an attempt has been made to explain and defend the gen- eral doctrine of Idealism, which affirms that the knowable world is identical with the world as it really is, and is a systematic or rational unity. This doctrine is of course diametrically opposed to Agnosticism. In a former work* it was maintained that Agnosti- cism is a self-contradictory theory, because in affirming an absolute limit to human know- ledge, it assumes the knowledge of a realm of reality distinct from the realm of phenomena, and tacitly affirms that there are two kinds of intelligence, corresponding to these two realms. Two objections have been raised which it may * Comte^ Mill^ and Spencer, Chap. II. 153 154 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE be well to consider. It is objected, firstly, that my criticism applies only to a dogmatic affir- mation or denial of a noumenal reality; and, secondly, that even if such a reality is ad- mitted, it is not a legitimate inference that its advocates are bound in consistency to assume two kinds of intelligence. (i) As to the first point, it must be an- swered, that a purely sceptical attitude is impossible. Such an attitude would mean, presurnably, that he who assumes it refuses to say whether there is any reality other than that which is known by us: there may, or may not, be such a reality, but we are not in a position to give any answer either positive or negative. Now, it is hard to see how any one can affirm that we are unable to say whether that which we call reality is or is not reality, without basing his affirmation upon some limitation in the nature of our faculty of knowledge. Surely the inability on our part to determine whether we have any knowledge of reality or not, implies that our faculty of knowledge is by its very nature unable to distinguish between truth and false- IDEALISM IN RELATION TO AGNOSTICISM 155 hood. But if we cannot distinguish between truth and falsehood, no proposition whatever can be held by us to be either true or false; and therefore our affirmation that we cannot distinguish between truth or falsehood can- not be accepted as true. If it is not true, there is no affirmation whatever, but only the delusive appearance of affirmation; and to such a delusive appearance we can attach no meaning; it may be either the affirmation or denial of reality or some tertium quid ; it is, in fact, that logical monster, an affirmative- negative proposition. In short, if you make any judgment whatever which means any- thing, you have assumed the reality of your judgment, though not of what you affirm or deny in your judgment; and thus you have assumed that so far at least you have touched solid reality. A purely sceptical attitude is thus a contradiction in terms, — an affirmation which affirms nothing, or a denial which denies nothing. The most complete sceptic that ever lived assumed that his scepticism was real, and to that extent he was a dogmatist. 156 THE CHRISTIAN WEAL OF LIFE (2) It is further maintained that even if the distinction between the phenomenal and the real is admitted, it does not follow that there must be two kinds of intelligence corre- sponding to these two realms. After what has been said, it must be obvious that this objection is unsound. For, if our intelligence is not capable of knowing reality, it must be because of an absolute limit in the character of our intelligence, and if that limit were re- moved reality, admitting it to exist, would be capable of being grasped by us. Now, the dogmatic phenomenalist, and even, as has been shown, the so-called sceptical phenome- nalist, assumes that there is reality. No western thinker, so far as I know, has had the courage to affirm that there is no reality whatever: that sublime height has been reached only in the east. Now, if there is reality at all, it must be comprehensible by some intelligence. It may be said that there is no such intelligence, or at least that we cannot know that there is such an intelli- gence. But surely we are entitled to de- mand that no affirmation should be made IDEALISM IN RELATION TO AGNOSTICISM 157 which is meaningless. The phenomenalist, then, admits that there is reahty, and in so doing he assumes that he fs saying some- thing which has a meaning for himself, and for others who hear or read what he says. Now what is a reality which is not a real- ity for some intelligence .^^ Make any predi- cation you like about it, and you will find that, if you mean anything at all, you mean that it is present to an intelligence. If you refuse to make any predication about it, it is not reality but pure nothingness. Hence you cannot say: "There is reality," without assuming that reality has a meaning, and to say that it has a meaning is to say that it is relative to some intelligence. Now the phe- nomenalist affirms that reality is not the object of his intelligence, and therefore it must be the object of some other intelli- gence, or it is nothing at all. And this other intelligence cannot involve an absolute limit, as our intelligence is assumed to do, because if it did it would not grasp reality but only appearance ; in other words, the phenomenalist in affirming the absolute limitation of his own 158 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE intelligence has tacitly assumed an intelli- gence free from limits. I was therefore right in saying that from the doctrine of the rela- tivity of knowledge it is a legitimate infer- ence that there are two kinds of intelligence, one absolutely limited and the other abso- lutely unlimited. The absurdity of this doc- trine I shall not again insist upon: I shall only repeat that an intelligence which is absolutely limited would never know that it was absolutely limited, since in that case it would be beyond the assumed limits. Now if it is admitted that there is a ra- tional or intelligible system of things, it is obvious that with this single system all the sciences must deal. Reality is one, and to suppose it split up into bits by the concen- tration of attention upon one phase of it, is to be the victim of an abstraction. When in geometry we define a point or line, we are not dealing with a "mere idea," but with a fixed relation holding for every subject for whom there is any reality whatever. Simi- larly, all the judgments of geometry imply that there are unchanging relations in the IDEALISM IN RELATION TO AGNOSTICISM 159 one system of reality which alone is or can be known, and these unchanging relations constitute the objectivity of that system, so far as it comes within the view of geometry. This does not mean that there is a world constituted of nothing but geometrical rela- tions, but it does mean that a world from which all geometrical relations are eliminated is unthinkable. If geometrical relations are not determinations of the real world, all the sciences of nature are made impossible, and, as a consequence, the whole of the philo- sophical sciences as well. What is said of spatial relations, of course, holds good also of temporal relations. And when we pass from the mathematical determination of reality to the dynamical — from space and time to matter and motion — the same principle of explanation still applies. For dynamical re- lations are real aspects of the one system of reality, while yet they do not exhaust its nature. It is as great a mistake to deny that those relations are determinations of the absolute as to aflfirm that in them we have reached an exhaustive definition of it. A i6o THE CHRISTTAN IDEAL OF LIFE world of matter and motion is real in the same sense that a world of space or a world of time is real; without dynamical relations there could be no reality whatever, but a reality consisting of these relations alone — a world of pure matter and motion — is as im- possible as a world of pure space or pure time. They are real, unchangeable aspects of existence, but they are no more than aspects. For, though there would be no real world were the relations or laws of dynamics not unchangeable, there are other aspects of real- ity which still further define existence. Cer- tain of these aspects are brought to light by physics, chemistry, and biology. Here again we may say that what the sciences affirm they affirm of the absolute, but we cannot say that now at last we have reached the ultimate or complete determination of it. All the sciences, from mathematics to biology inclusive, are abstract in this sense, that there are other aspects of reality which they presuppose. These new aspects of the one single system of reality form the subject- matter of the philosophical sciences, which \ IDEALISM IN RELATION TO MATHEMATICS i6l again presuppose logic or metaphysic as the science which deals directly with the in- terrelation of all the principles upon which the other sciences are based. II. MATHEMATICS The view which has just been indicated implies that mathematics is a science, i,e, contains propositions which are true or hold of reality. These propositions are, as I be- lieve, true formulations of fundamental condi- tions or relations by which the real world is characterised, though they are certainly not a formulation of all those conditions. What is held is not that mathematics formulates " the intellectual conditions of sensible real- ity," if this means that there is an absolute separation between " sensible reality " and an- other reality which may be defined as non- sensible. There are not two realities, but only one. What is called " sensible reality " is either the fiction of a world supposed to be given in immediate sensation, or it is a term for certain aspects of the one reality. 1 62 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE the only reality there is. To speak of "sen- sible reality " as contrasted with non-sensible or supersensible reality is to fall back into that untenable phenomenalism, the contradic- tory character of which has already been main- tained. Mathematics, then, concentrates its attention upon certain very simple conditions or relations of the one and only reality, and, as I believe, is successful in formulating their nature. It may be objected, however, that this view of mathematics takes no account of the re- cent doctrine that Euclidean geometry merely states the conditions of our space of three dimensions. Now it might fairly be answered that it is incumbent upon the advocates of imaginary geometry to reconcile their doctrine with any tenable theory of knowledge. Does their hypothetical space of four or more di- mensions contradict our space of three dimen- sions? If it does, they deny the principle of contradiction, contradict themselves, and can prove neither the reality of a space of four nor a space of three dimensions, since they cannot prove the reality of any space IDEALISM IN RELATION TO MATHEMATICS 163 whatever, or of anything else. It seems ad- visable, however, to deal more directly with the question. The discussion will necessarily be brief, but I shall try to indicate the main points. Let me repeat that I do not for a moment deny the value of imaginary geome- try as a system of mathematical symbols. I should as soon think of denying the value of the Cartesian co-ordinates. What I deny is the philosophical doctrine based upon the symbolic constructions of mathematics, — the doctrine that a space of four or more dimen- sions is a possible reality. I must also warn the reader that I cannot deal with the mutu- ally discrepant philosophical views of those who argue for the phenomenality of our space of three dimensions. I shall further limit my- self mainly to Riemann and Helmholtz. I may mention, however, that I find the conclusions which I reached several years ago endorsed by such eminent logicians as Sigwart and Wundt, not to speak of Lotze. (i) I find Riemann, then, arguing in this way : Space is a logical species of which the logical genus is extended magnitude or mul- 1 64 THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE tiplicity {Mannigfaltigkeit) ; hence, though our space is the only one of which we have actual experience, it is not the only possible space. If it is objected that Riemann is "antiquated," let me cite Bruno Erdmann. I have not read Erdmann's treatise, having ceased to take any interest in the question after my study of Riemann and Helmholtz, but I quote the state- ment of his view from Wundt's Logik (I. 440). His view is, then, that " modern geometry has been able to find a more general conception, under which space may be subsumed as a particular species, and from which therefore by the introduction of determinate conditions the fundamental properties of space may be developed analytically." Now I have no hesi- tation in saying that this supposed sub- sumption of space under a logical genus is a blunder, which the best modern logicians have clearly exposed. The whole idea of determin- ing the real relations of things by the forma- tion of an ascending series of abstractions is utterly untenable, resting as it does upon the mediaeval idea of logic as a purely formal science. The real world as it exists for our IDEALISM IN RELATION TO MATHEMATICS 165 conceptual thought is not obtained by abstrac- tion from full-formed individuals given in per- ception, but by a concrete process in which the first immediate judgments of perception are transformed by the comprehension of the fundamental relations, implied in those judg- ments, and brought to light in the complex process in which knowledge is developed. To run up and down a logical " Porphyry's tree " is a travesty of the process of thought, which corresponds to nothing " in heaven above, or the earth beneath, or the waters under the earth." But, even if we grant that the subsump- tion of logical species under a genus is a valid process, it would not prove that our space is only one of several possible species of space. For the whole account of the formation of logi- cal species rests upon the presupposition that the ultimate datum from which we start is the individual. Now the individual in this case is our three-dimensional space, and hence we cannot reason from the general conception of extended magnitude to the possible reality of several species of space. We can get nothing out of the conception of extended magnitude 1 66 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE but what we have put into it ; hence, when we descend the logical tree which we have pre- viously ascended, we shall find at the end just what we had at the beginning, and what we had at the beginning was an individual space of three dimensions. Riemann so far admits this as to say that our space of three dimen- sions rests upon " experience," but he still supposes that conception is wider than " ex- perience," and hence that there is nothing to hinder us from supposing a space of four or more dimensions. There is, of course, noth- ing to hinder us from thinking of a space of four or more dimensions, but the possible reality of such a space cannot be deduced from the abstract conception of extended mag- nitude. That conception is limited by what is already contained under it, and there is only one space contained under it, not several species of space. I hold, then, that in rea- soning from logical genus to logical species, Riemann has fallen into the logical mistake of supposing that possible reality can be deter- mined by logical possibility. In support of what I have said let me quote a few sentences IDEALISM IN RELATION TO MATHEMATICS 167 from Wundt. Referring to Erdmann, he says: " This view must at least be so far corrected, that the question cannot be in regard to a relation of genus and species in the ordinary- logical sense. If a genus is to be formed, several species must be given which possess certain common marks. But in this case only one space is given to our perception." And then he goes on to point out that " we can never possess an actual image of spaces differ- ent from ours." " An opposite view," he con- tinues, " seems to be maintained by some mathematicians, who hold that we can make a sensible picture of spaces of another kind, as e.g. a space which consists merely of a plane or of a spherical or pseudo-spherical surface."''^ This brings us to what I regard as another fallacy of those who maintain the possible reality of a space other than ours. (2) Helmholtz seeks to commend his view that a space other than ours can not only be thought but presented to the imagination, by the fiction of beings living in a plane, or a sphere, and limited in their consciousness to * Wundt's Logik: I. 440-1. 1 68 THE CHRrSTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE the plane or the sphere. The whole supposi- tion seems to me absurd and self-contradictory. There is no difficulty whatever in thinking of beings limited to a plane or sphere; for such beings are to all intents and purposes identical with the plane or sphere ; but what we cannot do is to think of their consciousness as super- ficial or spherical. A superficial or spherical consciousness has no meaning whatever that I can discover. Now, if our supposititious beings have not a superficial or spherical conscious- ness, we must suppose that the plane or the sphere is an object which they can think and reason about. But, if they have before their consciousness only a plane or a sphere, they will not have any geometry such as we pos- sess, because a plane is the boundary of a solid, and a curve is relative to a tangent. Such beings would therefore have no geome- try whatever. This seems obvious if we carry out Helmholtz's suggestion, and suppose beings limited to 2i point. Will any one affirm that a point has any meaning except as the boundary of a line } In short, a plane or sphere is intelligible only because it is a figure in our IDEALISM JN RELATIOIV TO MATHEMATICS 169 three-dimensional space. To reason from the curvature of a plane or sphere to the curvature of space seems to me a palpable fallacy. Space has no curvature, though figures in space have. Let me again support my view by a quotation from Wundt. " When we deal with the geome- try of the plane," says Wundt, "our spatial idea is no other than in the geometry of space ; we merely leave out of consideration all spatial relations except the plane ; we do the same in the investigation of the geometrical proper- ties of spherical or pseudo-spherical surfaces. Those relations of space from which we thus abstract have no existence apart from our idea; on the contrary, we require our com- plete space-perception, not only for the idea of a curved surface, but even for the idea of a surface or a line, for we can no more im- agine the surface than the line except as in space : we imagine both not as independent spaces, but as figures in space." "^ (3) It is supposed that because functions of magnitude can be converted into geometrical relations of a thinkable space, there may be * Ibid. I. 441. 170 THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE beings who enjoy the consciousness of a space of n dimensions. Surely this is an untenable inference. We can think of systems in which four, five, or any number of elements are re- quired, instead of the three elements which space demands for the determination of the position of a point. But, in order to give a geometrical meaning to analytical operations, we have to refer to our space of three dimen- sions. " It is self-evident," says Wundt, " that mathematical speculations, which infer that our space must be related to a four-dimensional magnitude in the same way as the surface is related to our space, cannot of themselves be the basis for the imaginability of a space of four or more dimensions. This question stands upon precisely the same level as that with which the older ontology occupied itself, viz. whether the actual world is or is not the best of all possible worlds."* I will conclude with a passage from Sigwart. " The result of these enquiries," says Sigwart, " is not that it is left to experience to decide whether we are to assume the plane space of Euclid, or a * Ibid. 1. 443. IDEALISM IN RELATION TO THE SCIENCES i/i space which is in some way curved ; but only that from the purely logical standpoint of analysis the quantitative relations of space are not to be derived as the necessary form of a manifold which varies in three directions, but that on the contrary they are actual, be- cause based upon an unanalysable necessity of our space-perception, which is essentially dif- ferent from any law which can be expressed in numbers and numerical relations. They open up no possibility of extending our space- perception, or of representing a non-Euclidian geometry not merely in analytical formulae, but also for actual perception ; we remain sub- ject to those laws of space according to which we first think of it, and it is as certain that Euclid will remain unrefuted in geometry, as it is that Aristotle in his principle of contradic- tion has outlived the Hegelian logic' » # III. THE PHYSICAL SCIENCES I conclude, then, that there is nothing in the speculations of " pangeometry " to support * Sigwart's Logic. English tr., II. 566. 172 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE the view of phenomenalists either that our consciousness has certain forms of perception pecuHar to itself, as Hehnholtz maintains, or as others hold that there may be an external world which lies in a space of four or more dimensions. To set forth all the objections which beset these views would be to write a whole system of philosophy, but I hope I have at least succeeded in indicating some of them. The world of the mathematician is, however, very far from being reality in its completeness; it exists only as the construc- tion of the mathematician, though that con- struction rests upon unchangeable relations or conditions of the one reality which alone exists. Hence, when we pass to the physical sciences we have made a considerable advance in the determination of those relations or con- ditions. There are, however, two fundamen- tal mistakes which we must here seek to avoid: the mistake of supposing that science merely " describes " the world of sensible per- ception, as Kirchhoff seems to say, and the mistake of imagining that the laws of science are more than an abstract or partial determi- IDEALISM IN RELATION TO THE SCIENCES 173 nation of reality. The theory of knowledge which many scientific men advance, when they leave their proper task and assume the role of the logician, is usually a curious mixture of these opposite errors. Our first view of the world naturally is that things lie before us in perception, and that, in order to know them, we must take them as they present themselves, carefully excluding all preconceptions, and accurately observing their qualities and determining the quantity of each quality. Without observation of this kind there can be no science of nature, but it can hardly be said yet to be science ; or, at least, it can be called science only when the observer is guided in his selection of facts by ideas of relation. What underlies scientific observation is a faith in the pres- ence in nature of conditions or relations which remain permanent under all the changes of particulars. It must be observed, therefore, that science transforms the ordi- nary view of the world by penetrating to those permanent conditions or relations which are not obvious to perception, but are only 174 THE CHRISTIAN WEAL OF LIFE brought to light by the persistent endeavour to find the identical in the different. The reality which science discovers is in one way an ideal world, a world which exists only as a construction of the scientific intellect, but it is at the same time a much truer appre- hension of reality than that ordinary view of things from which science is developed, though it may be said that the ordinary view contains implicitly more than science does justice to. Thus the physicist and chemist virtually set aside all the sensible relations of things, — not because these fall outside of the real world, but because they do not come within the scope of their science, — leaving them to be dealt with by the more concrete sciences of physiology and psy- chology. If, therefore, we fail to observe the transformation which science effects in our ordinary view of the world, we shall fall into the mistake of supposing that it is merely a "description" of sensible objects, and if we insist upon the reality of the abstract world of relations upon which science, for its own purposes, concentrates attention, we shall fall IDEALISM IN RELATION TO THE SCIENCES 175 into the opposite mistake of hypostatising this abstract world, and identifying it with the real world in its completeness. These two defects are closely related to each other; for it is just because we overlook the partial or abstract character of the laws of science that we convert relations into vague and shadowy things ; and it is because we do not see that science adopts a negative attitude towards immediate perception that we suppose it to leave sensible reality as it was before sci- entific insight has broken it up, and are led to regard laws of nature as a refined tran- script of the sensible, instead of being, what they are, a purely conceptual world of fixed conditions and relations, implied no doubt in the world of ordinary observation, but not brought into clear consciousness and made an object of direct consideration. Thus Comte tells us that science confines itself to the investigation of the laws of the resem- blance, coexistence, and succession of phe- nomena, and he assumes that these laws are simply the generalised restatement or descrip- tion of the phenomena themselves. But a 176 THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE law is something more than a generalised re- statement or description of phenomena, if by " phenomena " we mean the objects of ordinary- observation. For a law is contrasted with phenomena as the permanent relation in the changing particular, as that which is identical in spite of all differences, as the principle by reference to which particulars are seen to be more than mere phenomena or transitory phases of reality. Were it not possible to penetrate to such permanent, identical, or unchanging relations, we should have no science of nature. It is nothing to the point that no law is final, for the develop- ment of science, like all other developments, consists in an ever fuller comprehension of fixed relations, or what are usually called " uniformities," a development which does not simply set aside the relations already discov- ered, but combines them in a higher syn- thesis; indeed, if this were not the case, science would at every fresh advance throw down all that it had laboriously built up and start de novo. Now, if we keep in mind these two aspects IDEALISM IN RELATION TO THE SCIENCES lyy of a scientific law, — that it is, on the one hand, the revelation of a principle which is estab- lished only by a necessary but in a sense an artificial simplification of reality, and that this principle is, after all, only a permanent rela- tion of the changing, — we shall, I think, be led to see that a law of nature, as it is not a " description " of phenomena, so it is not a description of "uniformities." A "uniformity," if we are to give the word anything like its ordinary meaning, is naturally regarded as a customary or frequent repetition of a given resemblance, sequence, or coexistence ; and it is in this sense that Mill and many scientific men who make an incursion into the field of logic are disposed to interpret a law. It was in contrast to this doctrine that I ventured to challenge Mill's view of induction as based upon " resemblance," instead of " identity." * The "identity," of course, as any one who reads what I have said with ordinary care will see, is not that of a changeless " substance " or " thing," — I do not admit the reality of such fictions at all, — but of a relation. No two * Comtet Millt and Spencer ^ pp. 92-3. N 178 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE individuals are alike ; but in all their differ- ences they may agree in a certain feature, and this agreement is the basis of induction. Now, when we ask what bearing this view of a law of nature has upon the question of the relativity of knowledge, it is no answer to say that science is entirely neutral. In one way that is a bare tautology. Science as such is not a theory of knowledge ; and, of course, having no theory of knowledge, it does not tell us what the ultimate nature of reality is ; but the question is whether the view of reality, which in the pursuit of his special object the scientific man naturally adopts, can be re- garded as ultimate. The attempt to answer this question leads us into the region of phi- losophy, and compels us to ask what is the general view of reality upon which science is based ; and the answer, as we may be certain, cannot fail to be coloured by the general the- ory of knowledge which commends itself to those who seek to answer the question. A phenomenalist theory of knowledge will find support in science for its doctrine, because it will interpret scientific conclusions from that IDEALISM IN RELATION TO THE SCIENCES 179 ■.J' point of view, and so in other cases. I have tried to explain why I cannot accept the phe- nomenalist interpretation. I cannot accept it, because, as it seems to me, it does not do jus- tice to the real advance beyond ordinary obser- vation which science makes, and because it does not take due note of the abstract or par- tial character of the scientific view of reality. On this last point I should like to say a word or two. We are too apt to talk glibly of "laws of nature " or " uniformities of nature," not seeing that two discrepant views of reality are con- cealed beneath this ambiguous phraseology. Is " nature " simply a term for an aggregate of phenomena? or is it a real unity or organic system ? Mill tells us that we cannot properly speak of the " uniformity " of nature, but only of " uniformities" of nature. Now, waiving the objection I have already made that science deals with identities and not with uniformities, and interpreting the term " uniformity " in its higher sense, it is obvious that to deny any identity or unity in nature is to deny that reality is an organic system. But this is the I go TH^ CHkIST/AI\r IDEAL OF LIFE same as saying that all we can know of reality is that in point of fact we find certain relations which, so far as our experience goes, have not changed, but which, for aught we can show, might change at any moment. Thus, under the denial of the uniformity or unity of nature, Mill and others assume the phenomenalist view of knowable reality; and when they are asked to substantiate their assumption, they fall back upon a sensationalist theory of knowledge, and a metaphysical theory of the absolute limitation of our knowledge to phe- nomena. To one who rejects the sensation- alist epistemology and is convinced of the self-contradictory character of the phenome- nalist metaphysic, the denial of the systematic unity of the real seems a denial of all know- ledge and of all reality. I content myself with pointing out this result of the ordinary view of laws of nature as implying nothing but observed uniformities, having already dwelt sufficiently upon what I regard as the defects of sensationalism and phenomenalism. To me it seems to be one of the gifts which a true philosophy conveys, to bring to light that IDEALISM IN RELATION TO BIOLOGY i8l organic unity of nature which is implicit in science. For " nature " has no meaning apart from a unifying intelligence, and to deny the unity of nature is to deny the unity of intelli- gence and to make all knowledge impossible. I admit, however, or rather contend, that the organic unity of reality lies beyond the horizon of the specialist in physics, and even in chem- istry ; but the biologist, from the character of the objects with which he deals, is almost inva- riably more readily disposed to hold that the real world is an organic unity. In proof of this it is enough to refer to Darwin himself, whose whole doctrine is inspired by the idea of such a unity, though he fails to give a philosophical formulation of it; and to the recent developments of biology, which have been more and more in this direction. IV. BIOLOGY The doctrine of natural selection, while it compels us to abandon the external or me- chanical idea of teleology associated with the name of Paley, is incompetent to explain 1 82 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE knowledge or morality. To this view it has been objected that the doctrine of evolution, as held by Darwin and many of his followers, cannot be identified with the doctrine of natural selection, and that I have therefore confused true Darwinism with the views of Wallace and Weismann. This objection does not seem to me to affect in any way the point which I sought to establish. My aim was to show that, without assuming any- thing but what is admitted by all biologists, a certain philosophical conclusion, not con- templated or even denied by certain biolo- gists, must yet be reached. That conclusion was that an immanent teleology may be legiti- mately deduced from the doctrine of natural selection. It was not necessary for my pur- pose to embroil myself in the questions at issue between Wallace, Weismann, and others, while by doing so I should have given occa- sion for the retort that teleology has nothing to do with the biological doctrine of evolu- tionary descent. That this is no fanciful dan- ger may be shown by a single extract from Huxley's account of the reception of the IDEALISM IN RELATION TO BIOLOGY 183 Origin of Species in Darwin's Life and Letters. "Having got rid," says Huxley, " of the belief in chance and the disbelief in de- sign, as in no sense appurtenances of evolution, the third libel upon that doctrine, that it is anti-theistic, might perhaps be left to shift for itself. . . . The doctrine of evolution does not even come into contact with theism, con- sidered as a philosophical doctrine." * To this view I entirely assent ; but, as it seems to me, we may, accepting the scientific doctrine of evolutionary descent, go on to base upon it a philosophical argument in favour of a teleo- logical view of the world. It may be said, however, that it is illegitimate to speak of Darwinism as synonymous with the doctrine of natural selection. And no doubt it is true that, in the wider sense of the term, the biological doctrine of evolution, as held by Darwin, admitted other factors than natural selection; but it will be admitted that the great achievement of Darwin was the destruc- tion of the old rigid separation of species by the theory of natural selection. This was all * Darwin's Life and Letters : Am. ed., I. $55-6. 1 84 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE that I contended, and all that my argument required me to deal with. In taking this view I might have supported myself by the authority of Huxley. In the essay already quoted, that eminent biologist says : " The suggestion that new species may result from the selective action of external conditions upon the variations from their specific type which individuals present ... is the central idea of the Origin of Species and contains the quintessence of Darwinism^ ^ And again, a few pages further on: "Whatever may be the ultimate fate of the particular theory put forth by Darwin [the "particular theory," as the context shows, being natural selection], I venture to afiirm that, so far as my know- ledge goes, all the ingenuity and all the learn- ing of hostile critics has not enabled them to adduce a solitary fact, of which it can be said this is irreconcilable with the Darwinian theory." t Here Huxley tells us that natural selection is " the quintessence of Darwinism," and that opponents have not adduced " a soli- tary fact, of which it can be said this is irrecon- * Ibid. I. 548-9. t Ibid. I. 552. IDEALISM IN RELATION TO BIOLOGY 185 cilable with the Darwinian theory," meaning the theory of natural selection. Surely what Huxley here means is that what was dis- tinctive of Darwin was the doctrine of natural selection. It seems unnecessary to dwell fur- ther upon this point, but it may be worth while, for other reasons, to cite a few of Darwin's own expressions. To begin with, what did Darwin call his first great book ? He called it The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection. In the autobiography he says : " The old argument from design in nature, as given by Paley, which formerly seemed to me so conclusive, fails, 7tow that the law of natural selection has been discovered. . . . There seems to be no more design in the variability of organic beings, and in the action of natural selection, than in the course which the wind blows." * This pas- sage leaves no doubt whatever that in Dar- win's own mind his theory was incompatible with teleology. On another occasion Dar- win writes : " It is not that designed varia- tion makes, as it seems to me, my deity * Ibid, I. 278-9. 1 86 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE ' natural selection ' superfluous, but from seeing what an enormous field of undesigned varia- bility there is ready for natural selection to appropriate." Now I have no desire to nar- row Darwin's theory more than he narrowed it himself. I know that Darwin, with his large candour and what may be called his uncon- scious idealism, follows the facts wherever they lead him, and suggests modifications of his doctrine which, as he says on one occasion, " lessen the glory of natural selection " ; but I think no one can deny that he always and consistently rejected teleology, and rejected it mainly " now that the law of natural selection has been discovered." Now, my argument was, rightly or wrongly, that the law of natural selection itself, when we see all its philosophi- cal — not its scientific — implications, compels us to aflirm an immanent teleology, and that it is from not taking note of these implications that Darwin himself and many of his followers suppose that knowledge and morality may be explained by the method of science. It there- fore seems to me that science does not estab- lish teleology, but that a comprehensive view IDEALISM IN RELATION TO BIOLOGY 187 of living beings, and much more of man, does establish teleology. But, after all, it is mainly a question of definition whether we call a theory scientific or philosophical; and I am quite contented to rest my case on the broad view that Darwin and many of his followers are wrong in denying teleology, though they are perfectly right in denying that mechanical form of teleology which is associated with the name of Paley. It is important to observe that a teleological view of the world does not exclude but pre- supposes the law of natural causation. We must therefore be careful to avoid regarding " purpose " as a sort of deus ex machina, which is to be invoked when the ordinary scientific explanation has not yet been discovered. Such a conception of " purpose " in nature seems to me a survival of the obsolete idea of external teleology, from which the doctrine of develop- ment has helped to free us. I have no belief in a teleology which does not presuppose the inviolability of the natural law of causation. If a break could be found in that law, we should have to fall back upon the idea that 1 88 THE CHRISflAN IDEAL OF LIFE there is no system of nature, but merely a par- tial and imperfect arrangement of parts. The teleology which is here maintained is based upon the recognition of a fixed order in nature. What is held is, that living beings by their very nature contain in them a principle of unity which is realised within the inviolable system of natural law. The theory of natural selection assumes, firstly, that the laws of nature are inviolable. This is at bottom another way of saying that, when we come to the study of nature, we pre- suppose that it is a system of facts, so perfect that there is no break or flaw in it. Hence living beings, as well as inorganic things, are within this system, and there can be no such dissolution of continuity as that which is sug- gested by the view of purpose as external or mechanical. Secondly, natural selection as- sumes that in each living being there is a tendency or impulse to maintain itself and to continue the species. In saying that the doc- trine of natural selection rests on this assump- tion, it is not meant that the biologist need be aware of it, or that he employs it in his specific IDEALISM IN RELATION TO BIOLOGY 189 enquiries. The specialist is hardly ever aware of the preconceptions from which he starts. What is maintained is, that reflection upon the theory of natural selection compels us to take this view. It has been said that the impulse to self-maintenance is "something wholly conditioned upon and resident within the material nature of the organism." What is to be understood by the " material nature of the organism " } Is it meant that the craving for food, for example, can be attributed to " the material nature of the organism " ? If so, that impulse must be capable of being expressed in terms of matter and motion. This seems to me a mere confusion of thought, resting upon a physical metaphor which conceals the char- acteristic fact that sensibility does not belong to the " material nature of the organism," but is the differentia of a certain class of living beings. Thirdly, if there were no adaptation what- ever between organisms and their environ- ment, it would be impossible for them to exist at all. It is objected that there is also harmony between "a piece of ice and 90 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE the water in which it floats." No doubt ; but the kind of harmony to which I refer, as is implied by the two preceding characteristics, is one which exists only in a being which is internally purposive, and that cannot be said of the piece of ice. It is no doubt true that when we have discovered that living beings are purposive, we can no longer speak of nature as if it were merely a mechanical system ; but, as Kant points out, it is living beings which first clearly suggest to us that nature is purposive. And if it is true, as I have maintained, that we cannot differentiate living from non-living beings without apply- ing the idea of purpose, we are entitled to' say that reality as a whole must be inter- preted from the new point of view of an immanent teleology. It is only by an arti- ficial truncation of reality, such as is a neces- sary device in the pursuit of the physical sciences, that we are led to suppose that nature is merely a mechanical system. The peculiar phenomena of living beings compel us to revise our first inadequate view, and to say that real existence is not merely a me- IDEALISM IJV RELATION TO BIOLOGY 19 [ chanical but a teleological system. Having gone so far, we can hardly refuse to take the last step, and admit that the existence of self-conscious beings again compels us to revise our view of reality, and to admit that the only completely satisfactory explanation of it is that which refers the world to a self- conscious, rational, and spiritual principle. "^ * Though I still think that teleology may be established simply from the principle of natural selection, I have, in this second edition, sought to show that, if we accept the view of those biologists who hold that organic evolution involves other factors, — a view with which I agree, so far as a layman in science has any right to an opinion, — the argument receives additional strength. See Chapter IX. CHAPTER VIII THE FAILURE OF MATERIALISM In the last chapter we have been mainly occupied in the consideration of certain inad- equate conceptions of reality which are the natural result of a limited view of the world. Success in the pursuit of any one of the special sciences demands intense concentra- tion of energy, and almost inevitably leads those engaged in it to overlook other aspects of reality without which a consistent view of the world as a whole is impossible. In the present chapter it is proposed to consider what is really a metaphysical doctrine, though it is apt to claim for itself the combined au- thority of all the sciences. This doctrine, to which the general name of Materialism may be given, is now, as it always has been, con- nected with the belief in the existence and indestructibility of certain ultimate particles 192 THE FAILURE OF MATERTALISM 1 93 or atoms. It maintains, in the words of Haeckel, that " all natural phenomena without exception, from the motion of the celestial bodies and the fall of the rolling stone up to the growth of the plant and the conscious- ness of man, are subject to the same great law of causation, being ultimately reducible to atomic mechanics.'- "^ It is obvious that such a theory as this, when pressed to its logical consequences, is incompatible with the conception of any reality which cannot be resolved into ultimate atoms and the forces which operate between them, and is therefore diametrically opposed to the idealistic view, that the world is the expression of self-con- scious reason. The conception that there are indivisible and indestructible atoms, and that all the changes which take place in the world are ultimately reducible to the transposition of these atoms, seems to me merely a survival of our first uncritical interpretation of experi- ence. It is supposed that there exist an in- finite number of particular things, lying side * Haeckel, Freie Wissenschaft und freie Lehre^ pp. 9, lO. 194 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE by side in space, each of which has an inde- pendent existence and a peculiar nature which is inseparable from it. Those things no doubt enter into relations with one another, and are therefore subject to change ; but these relations and changes do not affect their real nature. Now science, in its efforts to determine the essential properties of things, soon discovers that it must abstract from the immediate sensible properties which they seem to pos- sess, and concentrate its attention upon those fixed relations between things, which are con- stant in all their changes, and can be ex- pressed in precise mathematical formulae. If the new conception of reality demanded by this changed point of view were frankly ac- cepted, the assumption of the independent existence and nature of particular things would be discarded, and the world would now be regarded as a system of mutually re- lated elements, none of which has any reality apart from the rest. But there are two rea- sons why this conclusion is received with hesitation. In the first place, it is instinc- tively felt that the reality of a thing can- THE FAILURE OF MATERIALISM 195 not be resolved entirely into its relations to other things: that, in Mr. Balfour's words, "it is hard to see how it is possible to con- ceive a universe in which nothing is to be permitted for the relations to subsist between." The truth lying at the basis of this conviction, as I have already tried to show, is, that the world must be conceived of as an individual system, in which the distinguishable elements do indeed possess reality, but not separate and independent existence. But this truth is apt to be misinterpreted to mean that each element has a residuum of reality after all its relations to other things have been set aside. Hence, secondly, it comes to be supposed that there are real things, which, though they are destitute of all sensible qualities, are yet sep- arate and independent, and possess an abso- lutely unchanging nature. Finding that all sensible objects are capable of indefinite divis- ion and transformation, the scientific man is apt to assume that this division and transfor- mation must stop somewhere, and hence that bodies are composed of indivisible and un- changeable atoms. These, then, are the real 196 THE CHRlST/AAr IDEAL OF LIFE or substantial things. The relations into which they enter in their intercourse with one another do not affect the atoms them- selves. Atomism thus retains the original assumption of common sense, that there are real individual things which are unaffected by the accidental or unessential changes which they undergo, merely substituting in- visible atoms for ordinary sensible objects. This doctrine is not Materialism, but it is the foundation of the simplest and most con- sistent form of Materialism. Atomism, both in its ordinary form and in the more refined theory of Lord Kelvin, seems to me to involve the fallacy of sub- stantiating an abstraction. If we attempted to determine the nature of a centre apart from a circumference, we should manifestly fall into the mistake of assuming that a centre is conceivable apart from a circumference; an assumption which is as absurd as to suppose that a stick may have only one end, or that a thing may have an inside without an out- side. A centre is relative to a circumference, one end of a stick to the other end, an in- THE FAILURE OF MATERIALISM 197 side to an outside. Now the same principle applies in the determination of the physical world: mass is real, but it is no more con- ceivable apart from force or motion than a centre apart from a circumference. Separate mass from motion, either actual or possible, and it can neither be known nor thought. Why is it affirmed by the man of science that " mass " is a necessary element in the world as known to us? The answer is, that if we take any two bodies of the same vol- ume and the same degree of solidity and im- penetrability, it is found that they may differ in their accelerations, or changes of motion, under the action of the same force or the transference of the same motion. '* Mass," in other words, is but another name for " inertia." The measure of mass is the amount of force or motion which must be communicated to a given body in order to produce a determi- nable rate of acceleration or deflection, and the measure of a force is the rate of change of momentum. There is therefore no inertia apart from force or motion ; the inertia and the force are correlative. Mass and motion 198 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE are no doubt real, but they are real only in union with each other. It is also true that without these inseparable elements there would be no reality whatever, just as there can be no reality apart from the spatial and tem- poral relations which they presuppose. Hence it is utterly illegitimate to separate mass and motion, and to suppose that either could exist without the other: they are correlative aspects of that system of bodies which we call the physical universe, but apart from that system or from each other they have no meaning whatever. For just as mass has no reality except in union with force, so force has no reality apart from mass. If we sup- pose the mass of a body reduced to zero, any force must produce a motion infinitely great, and the body would be everywhere, i.e. nowhere. The atomic doctrine, in substan- tiating mass or inertia, and conceiving it as an independent reality, contradicts the fun- damental ideas of science. There are in the physical world no ultimate unchangeable units: there is a perpetual transformation of energy, and in this transformation its total THE FAILURE OF MATERIALISM 199 quantity is constant, but this constancy is due, not to the unchangeabihty of ultimate units, but to the perfect correlation of the dis- tinguishable elements of mass and motion. The mass of a body is always relatively, but not absolutely, the same ; the energy of a material configuration is constant, but it is the constancy of a balanced system. It follows, from what has been said, that the physical sciences, in virtue of the fundamental ideas with which they operate, are limited to that aspect of the world in which it is con- ceived of as a mechanical system, i.e. a system in which nothing is considered except mass and motion. Hence the laws of physical sci- ence cannot explain what is characteristic of living and conscious beings, — unless, indeed, the activities of these beings can be ex- pressed in terms of mass and motion. But, as the sentence quoted from Haeckel shows, there is a class of thinkers who maintain that not merely the growth of the plant and the sensitivity of the animal, but even the consciousness of man, must ultimately be "reduced to atomic mechanics." It is this 200 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE application of the atomic doctrine which is usually called Materialism. In the scientific sense of the term, Materialism is the doctrine that the ultimate elements of the world are mass and motion, a doctrine which naturally suggests the philosophical theory that all the phenomena of the world must be explained by these elements alone. Many thinkers, how- ever, who maintain the scientific doctrine, re- fuse to draw the necessary inference from it, preferring to say that matter and mind are parallel and independent, but equally real. How this modified form of Materialism arises in the effort to avoid the difficulties of the more logically consistent form, we shall imme- diately see; at present I propose to consider Materialism in its extreme form, as formulated by such men as Buchner and Max Nordau. Materiahsm, as thus understood, maintains that mental processes are, in reality, physical processes, the former being in the last analy- sis functions of the nervous system. The antecedent and concomitant phenomena of conscious states are certain physiological processes in the brain and nervous system, THE FAILURE OF MATERIALISM 201 and these states must therefore be regarded as a special form of motion, which does not differ in kind from other forms of motion, and is, therefore, subject to the law of the conservation of energy. Sensation is that mode of motion which arises in the brain as the result of the stimulation of a peripheral organ; impulse is the translation of a move- ment in the brain into the movement of muscular fibres. In dealing with this theory, the first thing we have to do is to be perfectly clear as to what it means. Does it mean (i) that mental processes are the effect of physical processes .f* or (2) that mental processes are themselves physical processes .^^ These two views are by no means identical, and yet no clear distinc- tion is drawn between them by the exponents of Materialism. Buchner, for example, tells us that "matter in motion acts on the mind through the mediation of the sense-organs, and causes motion in it," and that "this in turn produces material movements in nerves and muscles." The meaning of this state- ment would seem to be that mental states 202 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE are the effect of movements in the brain, but are distinct from those movements. But we find in this writer another class of statements, in which mental processes are identified with physical states of the brain. Thus he says: " Thought can and must be regarded as a special form of the general motion of nature, which is as peculiar to the substance of the central nerve-elements as contraction is to the muscles, or the motion of light to the world-ether." In support of this conclusion he appeals to the experiments which show that mental processes require time for their occurrence. The " necessary conclusion fol- lows that the psychical act, or act of thought, occurs in an extended, impenetrable and composite substratum, and that such an act is, therefore, nothing but a form of move- ment." =^ Now if Materialism is understood to mean that thought is simply a movement in the brain, it does not seem worth one's while wasting many words in refutation of it. * Buchner's Kraft und Staff, as quoted in Paulsen's Introduction to Philosophy t Am. tr., p. 8i. THE FAILURE OF MATERIALISM 203 Whatever thought is, it is certainly not motion. No doubt mental processes occupy time, but it is absurd to assume that nothing occupies time except that which is in motion. Time is a form in which all changes occur, and as mental processes involve change they of course occupy time ; but, unless on the untenable supposition that the only possible form of change is motion, there is no reason whatever for affirming that mental processes are movements. To this view it is suffi- cient to answer, with Professor Paulsen, that " thought is not motion, but thought." * And yet it will be found that the main strength of Materialism lies in the assumption that thought is a mode of motion. For it is main- tained that to mental as well as physical pro- cesses the law of the conservation of energy is applicable; and that law, as we have seen, has no meaning except as applied to the rela- tive movements of bodies. If, then, thought is not a mode of motion, the only refuge of Materialism is to say that physical movements are related to mental pro- * Paulsen's Introduction to Philosophy, p. 83. 204 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE cesses as cause to effect. Now if we adopt this view, we must surrender the doctrine of the conservation of energy. According to that doctrine, all energy manifests itself in motion, and only upon this supposition can it be shown to be incapable of increase or diminution. But if nervous movement is the cause of sensation, in the latter a new product is generated which is distinct from the former; and this requires us to suppose that, in addi- tion to the energy expended in producing the nervous movement, there is another source of energy in the universe. Materialism, however, cannot admit the existence of more than one form of energy without becoming dualistic, and hence it must maintain that nervous energy is transformed into sensation, in the same way as mechanical energy is transformed into heat or light. But in that case the total quantity of energy in the universe must be lessened by the amount transformed into sen- sation, and the law of the conservation of en- ergy will break down when it is applied to the total process of motion, actual and possible, as exhibited in a physical system. We are THE FAILURE OF MATERIALISM 205 therefore reduced to this alternative: either there are two sources of energy in the uni- verse, — one giving rise to mental states and the other to motion, — or the scientific doc- trine of the conservation of energy is false. If we adopt the former view, we must aban- don the theory of the interaction of physical and mental processes, and maintain that there is no causal relation between them ; if we adopt the latter view, the whole super- structure of physical science falls to pieces. It was not to be expected that the very foun- dation upon which science rests should be abandoned, and hence we find that, though they unwarrantably continue to speak of body acting upon mind, the advocates of Material- ism are usually led to put forward a doctrine which is really a surrender of Materialism, — the doctrine that mental states are not effects, but concomitants, of nervous movements. In this way they seek to maintain the constancy of the total quantity of energy without doing open violence to the nature of mind. Is it true, then, that mind is merely something which accompanies, without influencing or 206 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE being influenced by nervous movements ? Do mental processes, in other words, lie entirely outside the chain of physical events, corre- sponding to, but entirely independent of them ? This is the view maintained by Clifford, who writes : " The two things are on two utterly different platforms — the physical facts go along by themselves, and the mental facts go along by themselves. There is a parallelism between them, but there is no interference of one with the other. . . . The mind, then, is to be regarded as a stream of feelings, which runs parallel to and simultaneous with a cer- tain part of the action of the body." It seems obvious that, on this theory, there are in the universe two independent sources of energy, — that which manifests itself in physical changes, and that which is ex- pressed in mental changes. And these two series of changes, though they have no con- nexion with each other, are yet precisely correspondent: so that we must assume a pre-established harmony between them. We thus reach the strange conclusion that two absolutely independent series, in some utterly THE FAILURE OF MATERIALISM 207 inexplicable way, always change concurrently. But if each series is entirely independent of the other, the physical changes would evi- dently be precisely what they are, even were there no mental changes : and, conversely, the mental changes would go on even if the physi- cal changes were annihilated. This conclusion is so paradoxical, that we cannot be surprised to find an attempt made to show that, though the two series are distinct, they yet are in- separably associated, so that neither takes place apart from the other. " When any one is pleased, stimulated, cheered, by food, wine, or bracing air," says Professor Bain, "we call the influence physical; it operates on the viscera, and through these upon the nerves, by a chain of sequence purely physi- cal. When one is cheered by good news, by a pleasing spectacle, or by a stroke of success, the influence is mental; sensation, thought, and consciousness are part of the chain; although these cannot be sustained without their physical basis. The proper physical fact is a single, one-sided objective fact; the mental fact is a two-sided fact, one 208 THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE of its sides being a train of feelings, thoughts, or other subjective elements.'"*' Here it is implied that conscious acts are only occasional concomitants of nerve-changes. Up to a certain point there is a single physi- cal series, then the series becomes two-sided, and once more it becomes single. What, then, gives rise to the mental side of the twofold fact } It cannot be the physical energy of the organism, for that energy expresses itself only in motion. Hence the mental aspect must be due to a new source of energy, entirely independent of the physical. But this brings us back to the old difficulty of two parallel and independent series, corresponding but having no real connexion with each other. To speak of these two series as identical is to use words without meaning ; it is, in fact, to affirm iden- tity and separation at the same time. We have now dealt with the various forms which Materialism assumes, and in every case we have found that it leads to insuperable difficulties, (i) A consistent Materialism is forced to the conclusion that mental processes * Bain's Mind and Body ^ p. 134. THE FAILURE OF MATERIALISM 2O9 are not different in their fundamental nature from physical processes, but, like them, are a mode of motion. This doctrine explains mental processes by assuming that they are what they manifestly are not. (2) Hence Ma- terialism is led to maintain that acts of mind, while they are not movements, are effects of movement. But this view is incompatible with the scientific principle of the conserva- tion of energy. (3) To obviate this objection it is ai^rmed that mental and physical pro- cesses are entirely independent of each other, and yet perfectly correspond. (4) But some explanation of this correspondence is required, and it is suggested that mental acts and nerve- changes are a single fact with two "faces" or " aspects." This doctrine, however, does not get rid of the diflficulty that mental acts are an entirely different product from physical movements, and must therefore be referred to an independent source of energy. Thus we are driven back upon the theory of parallelism, — the theory that there are two independent streams of changes, which have no known connexion with each other, and which there- 210 THE CHRIST/A AT WEAL OF UFE fore, to all intents and purposes, constitute two separate and independent worlds. Under the stress of this difficulty, writers like Mr. Spen- cer take refuge in the idea of a reality, to us unknown, and even unknowable, which mani- fests itself in two disparate ways, but which in itself is an absolute unity. Such a view leads to the conclusion that our intelligence is by its very nature incapable of reducing to unity the two independent spheres of mind and nature. We are, indeed, compelled to assume that in itself reality is one, but the limitations of our knowledge prevent us from understanding how it can be one. We are, in fact, asked to admit that what appears to us as absolutely distinct is yet somehow, we know not how, absolutely identical. This is nothing less than the assumption that our intelligence is in contradiction with itself: that in the region of knowledge we find an absolute dualism which can never be overcome, while yet reality, as it is in itself, must by its very nature transcend that dualism. Surely it is a much less intolerable alternative to sup- pose that the asserted "fundamental incohe- THE FAILURE OF MATERIALISM 211 rence" in our knowledge is due, not to the nature of knowledge itself, but to a false theory of knowledge. We have therefore to ask whether the unity of knowledge cannot be preserved at a less cost than the sacrifice of all knowledge of reality. Is it true that mind and nature are absolute opposites, and that we can only maintain their ultimate unity by a leap into the dark abyss of the unknowable .^^ Can we say nothing of reality except that we can say nothing of it.f^ Now we have seen that the scientific view of the world rests upon the two ideas of mass and motion, and that these two ideas are strictly correlative. There are no independent realities corresponding to the conception of ultimate atoms : there is but one system of nature, in which each element possesses reality only in its relations to other elements. But this idea of a system of mutually related ele- ments still leaves us with a very inadequate comprehension of reality as a whole. As Materialism is forced to admit, there lie out- side of it the whole of the mental processes, since the system of nature is limited to those 212 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE changes which are expressible in some form of motion. It is impossible to avoid the conclu- sion that the conception of nature as a system of actual and possible movements presupposes a unity of a deeper and more comprehensive kind. The inadequacy of the scientific view, when it is taken as an ultimate explanation of reality, it is not hard to show. That view explains all the changes which occur in the world by referring them to other changes. But in this way we are referred from one change to another, without ever reaching an ultimate explanation. We fall into an infinite series, whether we attempt to reach com- pleteness in the way of coexistence or of succession : the world of nature, as we soon discover, has no completeness either in ex- tension or in time; we cannot find an infi- nitely small or an infinitely large unit, nor can we find an absolute beginning or end in the process of the world. The true reality, as we are forced to conclude, is only partially appre- hended when it is conceived as a mechanical system. It is, however, a fundamental mistake to fall back upon the idea of an indefinable THE FAILURE OF MATERIALISM 213 something — we know not what — lying be- yond the system of nature ; for on that suppo- sition, the system of nature is a pure illusion ; what we must hold is, that a conception of the orderly process of change, as presupposing constant relations in the way of quantity, is the first inadequate grasp of the truth that the universe is a rational or intelligible system. Thus, on the one hand,, the scientific concep- tion of the world is partial or relative, while, on the other hand, it is absolute in the sense that the fixed relations of moving bodies to one another must be presupposed in any true theory of the universe. The tacit presuppo- sition of science is that the world is one, and yet the unity which it reaches is never com- plete. Thus, it may be fairly said that the scientific view of the world contradicts itself. The contradiction, however, springs from the struggle between the explicit conception of the world as defined in the idea of energy, and a deeper conception of it which is only implicit. For, though the world as defined by science is not a complete unity, we cannot discard the presupposition that the world really is a com- 214 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE plete unity without falling into hopeless incon- sistency. It is impossible for us to know that the universe is not a unity, since we cannot lift ourselves out of the universe we know, any more than we can jump over our own heads. What we have to observe, therefore, is, that the scientific view of the world as an ordered system of movements presupposes a single principle to which all movements must be referred. We have experience of certain changes, which are relative to other changes, but ultimately all these changes imply a prin- ciple of change which is self-originating. This self-active source of all motion is tacitly implied in the doctrine of the conservation of energy. Energy manifests itself as a perpetual process in varying forms of motion, but these manifes- tations in no way diminish or exhaust it. Pres- ent in all these forms, it yet remains identical with itself, or perpetually goes out of itself without losing its self-identity. Thus, while the doctrine of the conservation of energy em- phasises the permanence of energy in all the changes of the world, it yet tacitly implies the outgoing of energy in an eternal process of THE FAILURE OF MATERIALISM 215 change. Now it is this latent aspect of the doctrine which is brought to light and em- phasised in the principle of evolution. The transition from the one idea to the other, which has taken place in the development of modern thought, is therefore not an accident, but is itself an illustration of the evolution of ideas. It will, therefore, be advisable to con- sider what are the philosophical implications of the evolutionary view of the world. CHAPTER IX THE IDEALISTIC INTERPRETATION OF NATURAL EVOLUTION That the doctrine of the conservation of energy naturally leads on to the idea of the world as involving a process of development, is instinctively felt even by those who are the most ardent adherents of the atomic or me- chanical theory of the world. Thus Tyndall, who firmly believed that atoms were " real things," and spoke of the "clear, sharp, me- chanically intelligible atomic theory," yet " dis- cerned," in what he calls " matter," " the promise and potency of every form and qual- ity of life." Now it is obvious that if "mat- ter" is conceived of as ultimate indivisible atoms, it cannot contain the "promise and potency " of anything whatever. For the very conception of such atoms implies that, in all the changes of the world, they are absolutely 216 IDEALISM AND NATURAL EVOLUTION 21/ unchangeable. They were present in the primitive nebulous mist in the same unchang- ing rigidity and completeness as now, and they must remain unaltered so long as the world endures. They are, in the language of Mr. Balfour Stewart, "immortal beings," and in- deed the only " immortal beings " of which the atomic doctrine has any knowledge. There is, therefore, on this view no possibility of " matter " developing into anything ; what it is in the beginning it must remain to the end. It may perhaps be answered that what Tyn- dall meant to say was, that the primitive atoms were ca'pable of ever new transpositions and groupings, and that " every form and quality of life " arises in this way. But even if we admit that there is nothing in the nature of a living organism which cannot be explained in terms of atoms and their relative move- ments, — a very large admission, indeed, — the atomic doctrine is confessedly incompetent to account for the simplest mental act. This is maintained by Tyndall himself, when he tells us that " the passage from the physics of the brain to the corresponding facts of conscious- 2l8 THE CHRISTIAN- WEAL OF LIFE ness is unthinkable." But if there is an im- passable gulf between physical and mental changes, how can it possibly be affirmed that "matter" contains "the promise and potency of every form and quality of life " ? Is it not obvious that what is here called "matter" is a name for reality as a whole ? What Tyn- dall must mean is that the world, even in its earliest form, contains implicitly all that is involved in its subsequent stages. We have therefore to ask what is implied in this new way of regarding the world. This question has, to some extent, been dealt with in con- nexion with the doctrine of Natural Selection ; but it is proposed in this chapter to examine the scientific doctrine of evolution in its widest sense, as held by those thinkers who seek to connect the successive stages in the history of the world in an unbroken series, and who deny that Natural Selection of itself is adequate to the explanation of biological evolution. The principle of evolution, it is held, when it is taken in a sufficiently comprehensive sense, explains the whole process of the world. The present universal cosmical order has been IDEALISM AND NATURAL EVOLUTION 219 gradually evolved. The details of the process are not precisely known, but the generally ac- cepted view is that known as the Nebular Hypothesis, which explains the origin of the present stellar, solar, planetary, satellitic, and meteoric systems in accordance with known laws of motion. This first stage of evolution, which may be called the cosmical, was fol- lowed by the chemical stage. In the former, the action of chemical affinity was prevented by the dissociative activity of intense primal heat ; but as the earth gradually cooled, chemi- cal affinity came into play, and compounds were formed. By repeated combinations and recombinations, these compounds became more complex and unstable, and finally resulted in protoplasm, the most complex and unstable of all known substances. Thus protoplasm is the last product of chemical evolution, and the beginning of organic evolution. The third phase of evolution consists in the new process of organisation, which is effected by the co- operation of at least five factors, and results in the gradual formation of higher and higher forms, culminating in man. These factors are : 220 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE (i) the pressure of a changing environment, (2) use and disuse of organs, (3) natural selec- tion, (4) sexual selection, (5) physiological selection. The last phase of evolution is that of human progress, which is distinguished from the others in being rational or self- conscious* I propose to ask what are the philosophical implications of this doctrine, admitting the scientific evidence for it to be satisfactory. If it is accepted, there can be no doubt that it makes the purely mechanical or materialistic conception of the world incredible. For, whereas in the mechanical theory all the changes in the world are reduced to ultimate atoms and their movements, in the evolutionist view we must maintain that the world can be explained only by conceiving it as a unity which contains within itself the principle of its own development. There was a time, it is held, when chemical action was in abeyance. This state of things was followed by the opera- * The details of this evolutionary process are given with great clear- ness and impressiveness by Dr. Le Conte in the Monist, for July, 1895, pp. 481-500. IDEALISM AND NATURAL EVOLUTION 221 tion of chemical affinity and the formation of compounds. It is thus obvious that we can no longer speak of the world as a mechanical system, but only as a system which is at once mechanical and chemical. Hence the attempt to explain the world on purely mechanical principles must necessarily end in failure. But this attempt is made by those who hold that all forms of existence are reducible to "atomic mechanics." The evolutionist view, on the contrary, admitting that the world origi- nally appeared as a mechanical system, holds that it developed into a system in which a new form of energy came into play, — the energy of chemical affinity. Now this new form of energy is not added from without, but is in- volved in the system of the universe; and hence we must hold that the world is a self- developing unity, ' — a unity which is not a dead unchanging identity, but an identity which originates new forms of energy. The idea of evolution, in other words, combines the ideas of identity and difference, and combines them in such a way that the identity originates the difference, without ceasing to be identity. 222 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE There is thus at once differentiation and inte- gration, with the result that the world exhibits more perfect unity and greater variety. And if we follow the process of evolution into its next stage, we find the same truth exemplified. Chemical compounds are succeeded by organ- isms, which are self-maintaining and self-propa- gating. But, according to the evolutionist doctrine, this new form of energy is involved in the one single system, and to that system we must attribute the power of creating life. Nor can we identify life with chemical affinity, much less with mechanical force : we can only state the facts by saying that, as the world developes from a mechanical into a chemical system, so it developes from a chemical into an organic system. It is thus manifest that we can discover the true nature of the world only by following it through all its phases, and that the attempt to define it in its completeness by leaving out the later and more developed forms can only result in a partial and distorted con- ception of its real nature. Upon such an ab- stract view Materialism is based, and hence an evolutionistic Materialism is a contradiction in IDEALISM AND NATURAL EVOLUTION 223 terms. This will become still clearer if we consider what is implied in the various so- called " factors " of organic evolution. (i) The first " factor " is said to be the "pres- sure of a changing environment." Now it should be observed that the " changing envi- ronment" must not be conceived as acting upon the living being in a purely mechanical way. When it is said that the changes of function and structure are "produced" by the environ- ment, the whole effect seems to be ascribed to the environment. For the special purposes of biology this may be adequate, but in seeking to interpret the fact in its full significance, we must remember that the effect would not take place at all, unless the thing acted upon were a living being, and indeed a living being having a certain specific nature. The true " cause," therefore, is not the environment, but the environment as relative to the specific nature of the living being. There is, in fact, no "environment" apart from the living being. What is really meant by the "pressure of a changing environment " is the change which takes place in a living being under certain con- 224 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE ditions, internal and external ; in other words, the adaptability of a living being to changing conditions. But this adaptability implies the capacity on the part of the living being of maintaining itself under changing conditions, or its power of recovering itself from the action upon it of forces that would otherwise destroy it. Thus the seemingly mechanical relation of organism and environment is not really mechanical: it differs from mechanism in im- plying a tendency to individuation or self- maintenance. Apart from this tendency, — which Plato and Aristotle called the " idea " or "form," — there is no life; and hence to speak of the " pressure of a changing environment " is really to imply that a living being converts the environment into the means of its own life. (2) The second "factor" employed in expla- nation of the evolution of living beings is that of "use and disuse." Here again the biologist naturally looks at the question from the point of view of external causation. What he wishes to explain is the fact that organs increase or diminish, and it is enough for him to point to the fact that the change is IDEALISM AND NATURAL EVOLUTION 225 concurrent with use or disuse, and may be partially transmitted to descendants. But it is none the less true, that the use or disuse of an organ is but another aspect of that tendency to self -maintenance or individuation which we have already seen to be inseparable from the living being. It has indeed been even said that the use of an organ implies "consciousness and voHtion." To this state- ment I should demur, on the ground that " con- sciousness " and " volition " only exist where the knowing or willing subject distinguishes itself from the object known or willed, whereas organs are used by living beings which make no such distinction. But what is meant prob- ably is, that no living being uses or disuses an organ except under the impulse to self-main- tenance. The use or disuse of an organ implies that the being possessing it is an individual with a differentiation of parts, en- abling it to make the environment an instru- ment of its own life. It is in the effort after self-maintenance that the living being uses an organ, and it is because an organ has ceased to minister to that end that it ceases to be 226 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE used and finally disappears or becomes rudi- mentary. It thus seems to me that the two first " factors " are in essence the same. The pressure of the environment is at bottom the same principle of adaptation to external con- ditions as the use or disuse of an organ, the latter being merely a more specific case of the former. (3) Natural selection, unlike the first two factors, brings into prominence the connexion of living beings with one another. By the principle of inheritance certain variations occur in offspring, and where they are favourable to the existence of the beings possessing them, these beings tend to survive and to per- petuate the variations in their descendants. After what has been said above,* the reader need only be reminded that natural selection presupposes the tendency to self-maintenance and the adaptability of the organism to the environment, and therefore the evolution of ever higher forms of being. For though the variations in offspring are due to obscure con- ditions, no one doubts that the conditions are ♦ Chapter VII., pp. 181-191. IDEALISM AND NATURAL EVOLUTION 22/ there, and are therefore inseparable from the system of nature. There is nothing "for- tuitous" in the variations which arise from inheritance, in the conditions which make certain variations favourable to the perpetua- tion of the beings possessing them, or in the transmission of such variations when they occur. (4) The factor of " sexual selection " is mani- festly a special way in which the higher evolu- tion of living beings is secured and perpetuated. It operates only in the higher animals, and therefore appears only in the later stages of biological evolution. It does not seem to me to involve " consciousness and will," in the sense in which we employ these terms in speaking of man, but it certainly involves feeling and impulse. The animal is the me- dium of the tendency to race-maintenance and to the perpetuation of higher forms. Here, in fact, we see the tendency to the evolution of more perfect beings becoming, so to speak, inward, — a tendency which is exemplified in the whole process of evolu- tion. 228 THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE (5) The last factor, the "segregation of varie- ties within the limits of inter-fertility," brings into prominence the fact that there is a fixed limit to the possible varieties of living being. The unity of nature not only implies the de- velopment of ever higher forms of being, but it also implies a formative tendency which operates in fixed ways, and tends to that in- dividuation of type which is as essential to an organic system as the tendency to the formation of new types. Thus we are once more brought to the conclusion that nothing in nature is merely accidental ; that, on the contrary, wide as is the range of possible variations, there are fixed limits which cannot be transcended ; in other words, that living beings only differ from lower forms of exist- ence in being the embodiment of a higher and more complex law. To the question whether we can speak of the various stages of evolution as differing in kind, or only in degree, it has been answered that what we call a difference in kind is merely a "great difference in degree." This seems to me only a half-truth. The distinction, for IDEALISM AND NATURAL EVOLUTION 229 example, between human progress and animal evolution cannot be called merely a difference in degree, because the former is possible only under condition of the formation of ideals. This point will be considered more particu- larly in the next chapter; meantime it may serve to show that in the process of evolu- tion there are well-marked stages which can- not be explained away. On the other hand, it must not be forgotten that the principle of evolution does not allow us to interpolate arbitrary breaks in the process of the world. If evolution fails at one point, it logically fails at all points. At the same time the principle of evolution does not demand that the transi- tion from one stage to another should occur without qualitative differentiation. The world is an organic system, but for that very reason its various members are qualitatively distinct. It is the same principle which expresses itself in all the phases which we distinguish, and which have presented themselves one after the other, but we cannot resolve the later and higher phase into the earlier and lower. For the higher does not abolish the lower, but in- 230 777^ CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE corporates it in a higher unity. Hence the later phase introduces a new element not found in the earlier. Any attempt to resolve the one into the other will simply abolish the distinction between them, and the whole idea of evolution will disappear. If chemical affinity introduces no element not already present in mechanical force, there is no distinction be- tween them, and therefore no evolution. There can, in fact, be no evolution unless there is pro- gressive differentiation. Neglect of this dis- tinction leads to some such doctrine as that of Leibnitz, which rests upon the idea of prefor- mation rather than evolution, and all the at- tempts of recent speculators to prove the rationality of the world by a revival of monad- ism, seem to me an abortive effort to abolish the qualitative distinctions without which there can be no genuine organic unity of the world. It is true, on the other hand, that the progres- sive differentiation exhibited in the process of the world does not destroy the unity of the whole ; it is the same unity which is revealed in the earlier as in the later stages, but this unity only reveals its perfection as it gradually IDEALISM AND NATURAL EVOLUTION 23 1 unfolds itself. In the cosmical stao^e of evolu- tion we have the unity of a mechanical system, in which every part exhibits the equal and in- different stress of gravitation ; in the chemical stage, there is a selective activity of certain elements for one another; in the biological stage, the principle of individuation prevails, at first in an uncertain and indefinite way, and then, as we rise in the scale of life, in a more and more perfect form. It thus appears that the attempt to reduce the successive phases in the evolution of the world to a distinction of degree is due to the false assumption that the later stage con- tains nothing which is not already operative in the earlier stage, whereas evolution by its very nature consists in progressive specification. The unity which evolution demands is origi- native or creative : it is a unity which by its own self-activity generates new forms of reality. Nor need we shrink from admitting such a unity, when we consider that, even if we con- fine our attention to the cosmical stage, we are ultimately compelled to refer the process of change which is perpetually going on in the 232 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE world to an eternal, self-active, and creative energy. This is the truth which lies at the basis of the theological doctrine, that the con- servation of the world is a continual creation. The mechanical doctrine, which hypostatises " matter," seems to get rid of this self-determin- ing principle only because it assumes the eter- nity of " matter " ; but as " matter " is nothing but an aspect of the changing world, unwarrant- ably substantiated as an independent reality by the analytic activity of thought, — that "tre- mendous power which gives life to the dead," as Hegel well calls it,* — we are entitled to say that in its isolation it is pure nothing. What we actually know is a world in which there is perpetual change, yet no exhaustion of energy ; a world, in other words, which exists only be- cause there is an infinite source of energy which is eternal and indestructible. This being so, the process of evolution merely makes more explicit the nature of that inexhaustible energy which reveals itself, not only in the constancy of mechanical force, but in the origination of new forms of finite reality, as exhibited in ♦ Hegel's Phdnomenologie des Geistes, p. 25. IDEALISM AND NATURAL EVOLUTION 233 chemical affinity and in the production of higher and higher modes of Hfe. It is evident from what has been said, that any one who properly realises what the prin- ciple of evolution involves has transcended the whole point of view which is occupied by the special sciences, including the science of biol- ogy. For the object of these sciences is to ex- plain the special conditions under which certain changes occur. It is true that science is im- plicitly beyond itself, if one may put the matter in this paradoxical way. The presupposition of every science, not excluding that which operates with the mechanical ideas of mass and motion, is that there is one system, within which all changes occur, and apart from which they could not take place. But though this is the presupposition of all the sciences, it is not made a definite object of reflection. It is for this reason that the scientific man is apt to endorse a philosophical view of the world, which, if it were true, would make an end of his science. Occupied in tracing the transformation of one form of energy into another, he is led to sup- pose that he can apply the same method of 234 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE explanation to the whole, and hence he treats the world as if it involved no principle of unity. The same method is applied to living beings, with the result that no differences are found in them but those of degree of complexity. He speaks of the evolution of living beings, but he thinks of it as simply the successive appearance of new and more complex beings, produced by the mechanical interaction of the organism and the environment. Now the principle of evolu- tion, when we recognise what it really implies, compels us to view the process of the world in an entirely different way. Instead of looking at the successive forms which arise one after the other, and dealing only with their external relations to the environment, we have to con- ceive the whole process as the development of one principle, the true nature of which can be understood only in the final form which it assumes. From this vantage-ground, we look back upon the various stages in the process, and view them as steps towards a predeter- mined goal. Thus it becomes evident that the meaning of the earliest stage is partially re- vealed in the stage which succeeds it, and that IDEALISM AND NATURAL EVOLUTION 235 ultimately the last stage explains all the rest. Hence none of the earlier stages can be re- garded as expressing the nature of the whole, while yet each is a prophecy of the next. The mechanical view of the world is therefore inadequate, not merely because it fails to explain the highest stage, but because it fails to explain even the lowest stage. Just because it treats the lowest stage as if it were ultimate, it fails to grasp the truth that this stage is but the im- perfect revelation of a principle not fully dis- closed. When we look at the matter in this way, we see that cosmic evolution is the first step toward the creation of forms which con- tain in themselves the explicit meaning of the whole. Hence we find, as we should expect, that the higher animals already suggest that self-conscious comprehension of the meaning of the world, which is characteristic of man; nay, the whole creation " groans and travails " toward the goal which in man is attained in idea. In the cosmical stage, the principle of unity manifests itself in the law of gravitation, by which every particle is kept in its place ; in the second stage, it is seen in the more explicit 236 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE form of chemical compounds ; in the plant and animal, we have the unity of an organism ; in man, we find the unity of a personal self. We have therefore to ask what is implied in this last and highest stage of evolution. CHAPTER X IDEALISM AND HUMAN PROGRESS If the philosophical interpretation of evolu- tion which has been outlined in the preceding chapter is sound, it is obvious that there is no escape from the conclusion that the world must be conceived as in its temporal process the gradual manifestation of a principle which is at least an ever-living and self-determining reality, and that these finite forms of reality, as they successively emerge, assume more and more the form of an organic unity in which the life of the whole is realised in each. But though we are thus compelled to conceive the ultimate principle as creative and living, and therefore as so far truly revealed only in the highest form of life, we have not yet been led to maintain that it is self-conscious or rational. Only when we pass to man, the last term in 237 238 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE the process, do we begin to see that no other conception is adequate. The higher animals no doubt foreshadow the self-conscious reason of man, but there seems to me no evidence that they possess reason, in the sense that they are capable of comprehending the prin- ciple which gives meaning to nature in all its forms. No being can properly be called "rational" which is not capable of explicitly grasping the universal in the particular, or, what is the same thing, which is not capable of abstracting from the immediate life of feel- ing and making that life in its ideal tendency the object of intelligent purpose. Reason therefore implies the capacity in man of re- turning upon himself and making himself an object. And, as he cannot contemplate him- self as an object without becoming aware that as an individual he is but a "part of this par- tial world," reason implies the more or less explicit consciousness of a unity which is the presupposition of all selves and all objects. These three ideas — the world, the self, and God — are inseparably united in the self-con- sciousness of man, and all human develop- IDEALISM AND HUMAN PROGRESS 239 ment or progress consists in their progressive specification by reference to one another. Now if it is true that the life of man is car- ried on in the medium of reason, it is obvious that human progress cannot be adequately in- terpreted by any theory which fails to allow for the transformation effected by the pres- ence of reason. If the rational life consists in making the immediate life in its ideal ten- dency or meaning an object, the evolution of man begins on a higher level than the other stages of evolution which precede and prepare the way for it. As rational or self-conscious, human evolution not only cannot be explained mechanically, but it cannot even be explained biologically, especially when biology speaks in terms of mechanics. At the same time, the rational life of man rests upon and presup- poses his natural life, and can be realised only by a comprehension of that life, and a subordination of it to ideas which are in har- mony with the whole nature of things. The rational life thus implies insight into the laws of nature and of human nature, and this again means that it is social. We may 240 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE therefore say that the whole process of hu- man evolution consists in the gradual reali- sation of reason in the individual and in society, and the gradual comprehension of the meaning of both when viewed in their relation to the world and God. The pro- gress of man is thus from one point of view a transcendence of nature ; from another point of view, it is simply the self-conscious develop- ment of the end toward which evolution was tending from the first. It is a transcendence of nature, because in grasping the meaning of natural law, including the law of his own sensitive life, man is enabled to create a higher nature within nature ; it is a develop- ment of nature, because man is himself the highest product of nature, or rather of that universal principle which is manifested in nature. Nevertheless, we have to recognise that the higher life of humanity is not an original endowment, but must be won by con- tinual toil and effort. The easy optimism, which finds the world a very comfortable and pleasant place to live in, is as superficial as the pessimism which condemns the world IDEALISM AMD HUMAN PROGRESS 241 because it is full of pain. No doubt the rational life must bring satisfaction, but only because it lifts man into union with the prin- ciple of all existence ; and this elevation can only be the result of strenuous effort, involv- ing the sacrifice of all that, however pleasant in itself, hinders the development of the race. The world is by its very nature fitted for the development of the rational life, but we must accept the conditions under which alone that life can be realised. The past history of man shows us that human progress is a con- tinual subordination of the immediate con- ditions of life to higher ends. " Men in society," says Huxley, " are undoubtedly sub- ject to the cosmic process. As among other animals, multiplication goes on without ces- sation and involves severe competition for the means of support. The struggle for ex- istence tends to eliminate those less fitted to adapt themselves to the circumstances of their existence. The strongest, the most self-assertive, tend to tread down the weaker. But the influence of the cosmic process on the evolution of society is t he gre ater, the y^^ OF THK * y UNIVERSITY 242 THE CHRISTIAN' IDEAL OF LIF^ more rudimentary its civilisation. Social pro- gress means a checking of the cosmic process at every step and the substitution for it of another, which may be called the ethical process ; the end of which is not the survival of those who happen to be fittest, in respect of the whole of the conditions which exist, but of those which are ethically the best." * These are perhaps the wisest, as they are almost the latest, words which Huxley ever wrote. Without attempting to reconcile them with his other utterances, we may take them as a late admission that human progress is not a mechanical, but a rational process. If social progress consists in "checking the cos- mic process," there must be in man a higher nature which enables him to discover the hidden meaning of that process and to work in harmony with it. Hence I cannot endorse the language in which Huxley subsequently characterises the relation of man to the uni- verse. " In man," he says, " there lies a fund of energy, operating intelligently and so far. akin to that which pervades the universe, * Huxley's Evolution and Morality ^ p. 32. IDEALISM AND HUMAN PROGRESS 243 that it is competent to influence and modify the cosmic process. In virtue of his intelH- gence, the dwarf bends the Titan to his will." ^ It is strange that a writer who comes so near to the idealistic conception of existence should fall back upon the agnostic idea of an inscrutable Power, which is con- ceived as irrational and hostile to man, though somehow man is so cunning as to outwit it. Is man, then, not the product of this Power? Could the "dwarf" bend the "Titan" to his will, if the " Titan " were determined to thwart him ? Is it not manifest that, if man can subdue nature to himself, it must be be- cause nature is meant to be subdued.'^ The conception of a struggle between man and the principle which sustains human life as well as nature, involves the absurdity of a principle which is at war with itself. Obvi- ously this new Manichaeism is no more satis- factory than the old. The rational process of human life implies that nature and human nature are not opposed ; in other words, that the principle manifested in both is reason. ♦ Ibid. p. 35. 244 THE CHRISTIAN' IDEAL OF LIFE It may help to bring into clearer relief what is here contended, namely, that human pro- gress consists in the gradual realisation of rea- son, if we consider the most recent attempt to interpret social evolution from the point of view of the biological law of natural selection. In his Social Evolution, Mr. Kidd claims to have discovered the " natural law " of human progress, — a law which he even thinks may effect as great a revolution in sociology as the law of gravitation in physical science. Man, he contends, is "absolutely subservient to a fundamental physiological law," the "law of retrogression " ; and this law can be counter- acted only by " the prevalence of conditions in which selection can prevail." Reason urges man to suspend the "struggle for existence," which is the necessary condition of progress; and were it not that religion proves too strong for reason, and " supplies the ultimate sanction for that effort and sacrifice necessary to the continuance of the process of evolution," the progress of man would be arrested. (i) Mr. Kidd, then, contends that natural selection, which he identifies with a " struggle IDEALISM AND HUMAN PROGRESS 245 for existence," is the sole principle of progress both in man and in beings lower than man. Now, even if it is admitted that natural selec- tion is the sole factor in organic evolution, it is not hard to show that Mr. Kidd has inter- preted it in a sense which entirely changes its meaning. Natural selection, in the biological sense, is a principle which operates indepen- dently of individual effort. It is based upon the inheritance of favourable characteristics, and the transmission of these to descendants. But human progress does not depend upon the inheritance and transmission of such charac- teristics, but upon the ideas developed by reason and communicated through the ra- tional medium of language and social insti- tutions. Strangely enough, Mr. Kidd himself enters into an elaborate argument to show that the development of reason is the necessary condition of progress, and yet he seems un- aware that he has thus taken the ground from under his own feet. Reason is not accumu- lated by inheritance, but constitutes a spiritual medium which is independent of or rather transcends inheritance. And when Mr. Kidd 246 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE assumes that " natural selection" and "struggle for existence " are convertible terms, he is plainly confusing what is accidental with what is essential. In biological evolution it is true that numerous beings are sacrificed, but there is no " law of retrogression " such as Mr. Kidd invents to suit his preconceived theory. Beings " survive," not because of the " struggle for existence," but in spite of it, as is proved by the fact that in artificial selection, where individuals are placed in the most favourable conditions, the rate of progress is much more rapid than in nature, where the " struggle for existence " is unchecked. The development of higher and higher forms of being is due to the inheritance of favourable variations, and hence the law of biological evolution is a law of progress, not of retrogression. But even if it were true that living beings in a state of nature are subject to a "law of retrogres- sion," it would not follow that man is under the same law; for the "advantages" which enable individuals and societies to progress are not inherited, but are developed and commu- nicated irrespective of inheritance. No doubt, IDEALISM AATD HUMAN PROGRESS 247 in imperfect forms of society, the social heri- tage is communicated unequally, but in no form of society is the individual left to struggle with nature on the basis purely of his inher- ited tendencies. Even slaves participated in the advantages secured by the combined rea- son of the race. (2) Mr. Kidd 's special contribution to soci- ology, however, is his assertion that in man there are two opposite factors, — reason and religion, — and that progress consists in the subordination of the former to the latter. By "reason" Mr. Kidd means a purely intel- lectual faculty, the function of which is to determine what is of advantage to the indi- vidual, as distinguished from what is of advan- tage to the race. Man has certain natural inclinations, which are purely selfish; and reason points out the means by which these may be satisfied. Now it is of course true that reason enables a man to be selfish : it is, in fact, the prerogative of a rational being to be capable of selfishness. To be rational is to be a self, and to be a self is to be capable of selfishness. But no being is capable of 248 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE selfishness who is not also capable of unself- ishness. When Mr. Kidd, like Hume, makes reason the "slave of the passions," he seems to be totally unaware that any one has ever challenged this palpable fallacy. The "pas- sions," or "natural inclinations," are not selfish. It is only when they are interpreted by reason, or made a self-conscious end, that they become selfish. To eat when one is hungry is not selfish, but it may become an instance of self- ishness if a man eats what belongs to some- body else. To be selfish or unselfish is, therefore, a rational form of activity, and is possible only to a rational being. Mr. Kidd first assumes the natural inclinations to be selfish, and then assumes that a rational being will forfeit his reason if he looks beyond his natural inclinations. But if he is rational, he must look beyond his natural inclinations; and when he does so, his reason will be of a very narrow and irrational type, if he is unable to learn from experience that he can find sat- isfaction only in the development of all his powers, and that this development is possible only by seeking the good of all Moreover, IDEALISM AND HUMAN PROGRESS 249 ■.A on Mr. Kidd's own showing, the natural incli- nations of man have been inherited from his animal progenitors. But the animals care for others as well as themselves, and hence if reason is merely an instrument for the satis- faction of the natural wants, must its function not be as much social as selfish } If Mr. Kidd's conception of " reason " is in- adequate, how shall we characterise his idea of " religion," which he describes as " ultra- rational " or "supernatural"? These epithets do not mean, in Mr. Kidd's mouth, what they are apt to suggest to the unwary reader. Re- ligion is not, in his view, of divine or ultra- human origin. " The religious feeling," as he explains, " is not only just as much a part of man's nature as any other, but it is the most characteristic part of it. . . . It is not beyond him : it is only beyond his reason." * What, then, is religion? Finding the definitions hitherto given unsatisfactory, Mr. Kidd gives one of his own. " A religion is a forrA of belief, providing an ultra-rational sanction for that large class of conduct in the individual * Nineteenth Century, February, 1895, P- 232, note. 2 so THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE where his interests and the interests of the social organism are antagonistic, and by which the former are rendered subordinate to the latter in the general interests of the evolution which the race is undergoing." * Now, in the first place, this is not a definition of religion at all ; it attempts to tell us what religion does, not what it is. But, secondly, the explanation of this defect is that religion is conceived simply as a blind impulse, and is therefore indefinable. For we are told that a religion "must necessarily maintain itself by what is often a vast system of beliefs and ordinances," but which " fall under the head of theology." t But when we have purified religion of all its " beliefs and ordinances," what remains ? Ob- viously every object of religion will disappear, and in the absence of an object there can be nothing but an unreasoning impulse, operating blindly in the direction of the social good. It is not surprising that Mr. Kidd should speak of religion as " beyond reason " ; one is only surprised that he did not describe it as "be- neath reason." * Kidd's Social Evolution^ p. 103. f Ibid. p. 104. IDEALISM AND HUMAN PROGRESS 251 Now we have already seen that " reason " is for Mr. Kidd the organ of the purely selfish inclinations. Combining our two results, we reach the conclusion that human progress is the resultant of two blind tendencies, — a selfish and a social, — the latter being stronger than the former. If this is true, we need not trouble ourselves about the future of the race, and indeed to do so would be superfluous, since the future will be determined by the stress of the stronger impulse. The only refutation such a doctrine needs is to be plainly stated. It would be hard to say whether in it reason or religion is most degraded ; and, in truth, the degradation of the one is the necessary counterpart of the degradation of the other. Reason must be religious and religion rational, or human progress is inconceivable. A clear conception of what is meant by calling man " rational " is so important that I may be excused for adding a few words on this point. It is a fundamental mistake to assume that " reason " is absolutely exclusive of feeling. To be " rational " is not to be a purely intellectual machine, the function of 252 THE CHRISTIAN' IDEAL OF LIFE which is to manipulate what Mr. Bradley calls "bloodless categories." Such a being cannot be conceived as even possible, for it is mani- fest that, having no interest in one object more than another, his intellect would never get into play at all. Nor, again, is " reason " exclusive of will: in truth, will is the activity of a rational being, and only of a rational being:. Hence the fundamental mistake of writers like Schopenhauer and Von Hartmann, who speak of the " will " of a plant or animal, and even of a stone, not seeing that no being has will that is not self-conscious. And of course " reason " implies knowledge, i,e, the conception of a real object as present to a subject. Thus "reason" involves the three correlative aspects of feeling, willing, and know- ing ; and no living being can be " rational," or indeed can be conceived, who merely feels, or merely knows, or merely wills. It is therefore manifest that " reason " is not a special faculty possessed by self-conscious beings, but ex- presses what is implied in their nature as self-conscious. And as in man self-conscious- ness is not an endowment, but a process, the IDEALISM AND HUMAN PROGRESS 253 rational life is necessarily progressive. Com- plete self-consciousness is the goal of all human effort; and complete self -consciousness would consist in experiencing the world, the self, and God in the totality of their relations to one another. As none of these objects can be separated from the others, we are compelled to infer that the principle which gives mean- ing to all existence must be self-conscious or rational. And as this principle must be con- ceived as ultimate, the only conception of reality which is beyond doubt is that of a self-determining, self-conscious, and self-mani- festing reason. This conclusion, as it seems to me, cannot be avoided by any one who takes a comprehen- sive view of evolution. From the evolutionist point of view the meaning of the earlier stages must be interpreted in the light of the final stage, for it is only in the final stage that reality as a whole reveals what it truly is. But as the last stage, that of self-conscious reason, is incon- ceivable without the prior stages, we must refer these prior stages as well as the last to a single principle. Nor is it difficult to see that. 254 THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE in a universe which is the expression of reason, the inviolability of natural law is a necessary presupposition. A universe without law is a contradiction in terms : it would be a universe in which there was no order or coherence. Reason, it is true, is not mere conformity to law, but without conformity to law there can be no reason. And as in the supreme rational principle there can be no evolution from a lower to a higher form, — which would involve the absurdity of an infinite principle which was finite, — there can be no evolution in the world which is inconsistent with the fundamental condition of there being a world at all, namely, that it must be a cosmos. It is the tacit recog- nition of this necessity of thought which leads the scientific man to attach so much importance to the inviolability of natural law. To deny that inviolability, as he feels, is to make all science impossible. Thus he conceives of nature as a system of laws, the same yesterday, to-day, and forever. What dominates his mind is at bottom the same idea as that which in another form led the Hebrew prophet to speak of " the law of the Eternal." But, as " natural IDEALISM AND HUMAN PROGRESS 255 law" is, from the evolutionist point of view, nothing but a form in which the divine reason is partially expressed, it is obvious that it can no longer be regarded as an external necessity imposed upon man from without, to which he must submit because he cannot escape from its remorseless grasp. Why should he desire to escape from the very principle without which he could not even exist ? Without the fixed order and system of physical nature, the subse- quent stages of evolution would be impossible ; and hence the attempt to find breaks in the order, or in the evolution of the world, is a blind attempt to convert the universe into chaos. CHAPTER XI IDEALISM AND CHRISTIANITY The conclusion to which we have been brought is that the ultimate conception by means of which existence must be explained is that of a self-conscious and self-determin- ing principle. Now it is important to see precisely what is involved in this conception, and to remove from it all elements which are inconsistent with its purity and with the position assigned to it as the only adequate explanation of the world as a whole. A thorough discussion of this topic would de- mand a complete system of metaphysic, but it may be possible in brief compass to show the inadequacy of certain definitions of God or the absolute, and to indicate the defini- tion which it would be the task of a com- pletely reasoned system to establish. When this has been done, an attempt will be made 256 IDEALISM AND CHRISTIANITY 257 to give an outline of the relation of the world, and especially of man, to the abso- lute. A consideration of these two questions will of itself be sufficient to show that Ideal- ism is in essential harmony with the Chris- tian ideal of life, as held by the Founder of Christianity, however it may differ, at least in form, from popular Christian theology. (i) The absolute is very inadequately con- ceived when it is defined simply as sub- stance. This view is the inevitable result of opposing mind and nature, or thought and reality, to each other as abstract opposites. For, if mind excludes nature and nature mind, we are compelled to seek for the unity of both in that which is neither, but is some- thing beyond both. This "something," how- ever, cannot be further defined, and hence it remains for knowledge absolutely indetermi- nate. Now it is strangely supposed that such an elimination of the distinction of nature and mind is the logical result of the idealis- tic conception of the absolute. When it is maintained that there can be no abstract separation of mind and nature, subject and 258 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE object, it is argued that mind and nature are identified, and hence it is said that we must fall back upon a unity which is manifested indifferently in both. This objection seems to me to rest upon a misconception of what Idealism affirms. What is really maintained is that the conception of nature as an inde- pendent reality is a conception which, if taken in its strict sense, contradicts itself. If nature is an independent reality, it can have in it no principle of unity. For the highest principle by which it can be determined is that of the interdependence of its parts, and this principle still leaves the parts external to one another, while it explains the process of nature as the changes which are produced in each part by the action upon it of the others. But such a conception does not take us be- yond the idea of an aggregate of parts only externally or mechanically related to one another. On the other hand, when mind is separated from nature, it can only be con- ceived as an abstract unity which, as having no differences within itself, must for ever remain in its abstractness. Now Idealism re- IDEALISM AND CHRISTIANITY 259 fuses to admit that nature and mind are thus separated. It regards nature as the manifes- tation of mind, and mind as the principle of unity implied in nature. Hence, for the me- chanical conception of nature as a system of interdependent parts undergoing correspon- dent changes, is substituted the organic idea of nature as a system which develops towards an end. This view transforms the concep- tion of nature, not by denying that it is a system, but by regarding it as a system which is rational, and therefore is intelligible to all beings in whom reason operates. Now, if we have to interpret nature from the point of view of reason, the key to nature is to be found in mind. Hence the absolute cannot be adequately conceived merely as the unity which is beyond the distinction of nature and mind, but only as the unity which is implicit in nature and explicit in mind. When, therefore, we seek to determine the relation of particular forms of being to the absolute, the question is how far each is the explicit manifestation of rationality. No form of reality can be regarded as " mere 26o THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE appearance," but only as the more or less adequate manifestation of the principle which is the source and explanation of all reality. When, therefore, we speak of an " individual " reality, we must remember that its individu- ality is constituted by its relation to the whole. On the other hand, an individual reality can- not be defined as nothing but the sum of its relations to other individual realities. The conception of reality as determined purely by the relations of one thing to another over- looks the principle of unity which is present in all alike. This is true even of inorganic things. Each atom of oxygen or hydrogen is nothing apart from its relations, but each par- ticipates in the universal, so that an atom of each is always determined by the relations into which it is capable of entering, while yet it manifests the character peculiar to all atoms of its own kind. The individuality in this case is of a very simple character. Much more obvious is the principle of individuality in the case of living beings, which do not persist in the same unchangeable relations, but exhibit a whole series of relations to the IDEALISM AND CHRISTIANITY 26 1 environment. Hence we can only describe the nature of a living being by pointing out the cycle of changes through which it passes. The living being is thus distinguished from the non-living by the greater complexity of its relations, and by the more express exhibi- tion of its individual unity. But it is espe- cially in self-conscious beings that individuality and universality reach their higher stage. Speaking generally, we must therefore say that a being is more truly individual, the more perfectly it contains within itself the principle of the whole. We cannot therefore say that the absolute is manifested equally in all be- ings; indeed, strictly speaking, it is only in self-conscious beings that the true nature of the absolute is revealed. Now, if it is true that only as reason is developed in a being does it express what is the true principle of the whole, it is manifest that the absolute cannot be realised, as it truly is, in beings lower than man, and that even in man it is not realised in its absolute completeness. By this conception of the immanence of the absolute in all forms of being, together with 262 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE the recognition that in man at his best the absolute is most fully manifested, we are en- abled to see that the conception of the abso- lute as merely the unchanging substance which persists in all forms of changing existence is quite inadequate. Such a con- ception, on the one hand, abolishes all the distinctions of one being from another, mak- ing them all equally unreal; and, on the other hand, it denies that the absolute is a self- revealing subject, immanent in all forms of being, but manifested truly only in those that are self-conscious. (2) The absolute is inadequately conceived when it is defined as the power which is manifested in all particular forms of reality, or, in other words, simply as the first cause or creator of the world. The conception of power or force is that of a negative activity which manifests itself in overcoming some other power which is opposed to it. The mechanical conception of energy is the " power of doing work," and is always explained as manifested in opposition to that which resists it. All energy is therefore by its very nature IDEALISM AND CHRISTIANITY 263 limited. When, therefore, we speak of infinite power, we virtually transcend the conception of energy, for " infinite " power must be the energy which includes in itself all forms of energy. Such a conception takes us beyond the conception of power altogether. The only kind of power which can be called infi- nite is that power which is self-determinant, and such a power is found only in self-con- scious energy, which is truly infinite because it returns upon itself or preserves its unity in all its manifestations. In self-conscious energy, object and subject are identical. In man this energy of self-consciousness is not complete, because man is not completely self- conscious. But in the absolute there must be complete self-consciousness. Now, if we are compelled to conceive of the absolute as complete self-consciousness, there is in the absolute the perfect unity of subject and ob- ject. And as such a unity admits of no degrees, there can be no absolute origination of reality, for this would mean the absolute origination of some phase of the absolute. The ordinary conception of creation as the 264 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE origination of the world out of nothing con- veys a truth in the form of a self-contradiction : it expresses the idea of self-determining activ- ity in the imaginative form of a transition from nothing to reality as taking place in time. A blank nothing is imagined, which is at bottom merely the abstraction from all deter- minate reality, and then it is imagined that this blank nothing is succeeded by determi- nate reality. The conception of causality, as it is employed in determining the relation of one phase of reality to another, is transferred to the relation between the absolute and de- terminate reality. Now, as we have seen, the conception of causal connexion has no mean- ing except as expressing the dependence of particular phases of reality upon one an- other, and ultimately we are compelled to rec- ognise that such interdependence of particular phases of reality presupposes a self-determin- ing principle. When we have reached this point of view, we have transcended the cate- gory of causality, and it is therefore inadmis- sible to employ it in seeking to explain the relation of the parts to the whole. But this IDEALISM AND CHRTSTf^miTY 265 is what is done in the ordinary conception of creation, though the inadequacy of the con- ception is virtually admitted when the creation of the world is figured as the origination of it from nothing. For "nothing" is represented as if it were a material to which a definite form was given by the action upon it of an external cause. It is obvious that this crude way of conceiving the relation of the world to the absolute must be discarded. The world cannot be separated from the absolute, but must be regarded as the manifestation or ob- jectification of the absolute, or, in other words, as the absolute itself regarded in its abstract opposition to itself. This opposition, how- ever, is merely a distinction ; for that which is opposed to the absolute is the absolute itself. . (3) The absolute is not adequately con- ceived as a person, although no doubt the conception of personality is much more ade- quate as a predicate of the absolute than that of power. By a " person " we mean a being that is an individual, and, further, an indi- vidual who is capable of conceiving himself as a self. But personality emphasises the ex- 266 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE elusive aspeet of self-activity, and thus one person is separated frdm and opposed to another. On this basis of exclusive selfhood all rights are based, a right being the expres- sion of the self in that which has no self. Now, so far as the absolute is affirmed to be a person, the main idea is that the absolute is self-conscious, and to this extent it is true that the absolute is a person. But the abso- lute is not properly conceived as a person in the sense of being an exclusive self-centred individual. The conception of personality is inadequate even when applied to man, for it is not true that man is merely a person. The first consciousness of exclusive or adverse re- lations to others must be supplemented by the conception of man as essentially spirit, that is, as a being whose true self is found in relation to what is not self. Man is there- fore not adequately conceived as an exclusive self, but only as a self whose true nature is to transcend his exclusiveness and to find himself in what seems at first to be opposed to him. In other words, man is essentially self-separa- tive: he must go out of his apparently self- IDEALISM AND CHRISTIANITY 267 centred life in order to find himslelf in a truer and richer life. This conception of a self- opposing subject must be applied to the ab- solute. The absolute is not an abstract person, but a spirit, i.e, a being whose essen- tial nature consists in opposing to itself beings in unity with whom it realises itself. This conception of a self-alienating or self-distin- guishing subject seems to me the fundamental idea which is expressed in the doctrine of the Trinity. We can conceive nothing higher than a self-conscious subject, who, in the in- finite fulness of his nature, exhibits his per- fection in beings who realise themselves in identification with him. What Schiller ex- presses in a figurative way seems to me to be the necessary result of philosophy: — " Freundlos war der grosse Weltenmeister, Fiihlte Mangel, darum schuf er Geister, Sel'ge Spiegel seiner Seligkeit. Fand das hochste Wesen schon kein Gleiches, Aus dem Kelch des ganzen Wesenreiches Schaumt ihm die Unendlichkeit." There is at present a tendency to main- tain that the absolute must -be defined as 268 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE something higher than a self-conscious sub- ject. This view seems to me to rest upon the false assumption that the distinction of subject and object is a mark of limitation. But it can only be a mark of limitation on the supposition that the object is in some way disparate from the subject, i.e. contains an element which is incomprehensible. The view which is here maintained is that, in the absolute, subject and object are absolutely identical ; in other words, that the subject is its own object. If it is objected that in that case there is no distinction between them, the answer is that as the subject compre- hends all reality, there is in the absolute no distinction between subject and object, but there is an infinity of distinctions within the absolute. The absolute, in other words, is essentially self-distinguishing. To this conception of the absolute an objec- tion may be raised, based upon the idea of evolution. According to the philosophical in- terpretation of evolution given above, the true nature of the absolute is revealed only in the last stage of evolution, and as, in this stage. IDEALISM AND CHRISTIANITY 269 rational or self-conscious life emerges, ration- ality or self-consciousness, as it is fairly main- tained, must be predicated of the absolute. But if the world has already gone through yarious stages, — the cosmical, chemical, bio- logical, and rational, — why should it not have still other stages to go through ? Why should not the absolute reveal itself to future ages in higher forms, forms as much beyond the self- conscious as the self-conscious is beyond the stages prior to it ? There is nothing in the principle of evolution, it may be said, to pre- clude this supposition. Man, at every stage in his development, has been prone to imagine that he had reached the ultimate conception of reality, and therefore the majority of men have always for a time stubbornly resisted the new and higher conception to which the best minds of the age have been irresistibly drawn. Must we not, then, refuse to admit that the concep- tion of the absolute as self-conscious is ulti- mate.? It is not meant that the absolute may in future ages be discerned to be lower than self-conscious, but that it may then be con- ceived, and to some extent is now conceived, as 270 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE higher than self-conscious. Can we, in any case, conceive of the absolute as it is in itself? Must not even our highest idea of it be analogi- cal? Surely the absolute must in its inner nature infinitely transcend its manifestations as known to us. This new argument for the unknowability of the absolute seems to me to lead to the same abyss of emptiness as the old. If the absolute is super-rational or beyond self-consciousness, we can form no conception whatever of its nature ; for with the abolition of the distinction and unity of subject and object, all definite thought disappears in an abstract being which is for us pure nothing. It is a gratuitous as- sumption that a super-rational absolute is higher than a self-conscious absolute. How can we possibly speak of an object of which we know nothing, as either higher or lower than that which we do know? Such predicates have a meaning only within the sphere of our know- ledge, not beyond it. It is not possible to limit a conception by a mere negation. If I say that the conception of the world as a purely mechanical system is inadequate, I do so IDEALISM AND CHRISTIANITY 27 1 because I possess the higher conception of the world as the manifestation of a self-crea- tive principle. I examine the conception of a world in which one element is referred to another, this second to a third, and so on ad infinitum; and I come to the conclusion that such a conception of the world is inadequate, since ultimately I must posit a reality which is self-dependent and therefore self-originative. But, unless I had the higher conception, I should never discern the inadequacy of the lower. Any one, therefore, who maintains that the absolute must be conceived as beyond the distinction of subject and object, must have a positive conception of this higher unity, or he is rejecting the only conception which has mean- ing for him in favour of a conception which is perfectly indefinite. In truth, a perfectly indefi- nite conception is not a conception at all, since all thought implies distinction. To maintain that the absolute may be beyond the distinction of subject and object is to say nothing whatever. This simple consideration seems to me to dispose of the objection to the conception of the absolute as self-conscious, which is drawn 272 THE CHRISTIAN' IDEAL OF LIFE from the idea of evolution. To suppose a stage of evolution to arise when the distinction of subject and object will be transcended is self- contradictory, because with the disappearance of that distinction there would also disappear the distinction of one stage from another. The principle of evolution has meaning only for a rational or self-conscious being, and unless we are capable of comprehending the nature of reality we cannot affirm that there has been any evolution. A recent writer has gone so far as to suggest that, as our intelligence has been evolved from non-intelligence, we have no right to deny that, in some subsequent age of the world, our intelligence may develope into a form in which the principle of contradiction will be overthrown, so that what are now to us abstract opposites may then be seen to be iden- tical. But surely we have a right to deny what is absolute nonsense. Apparently the writer does not see that, in the hypothetical stage sug- gested by him, in which our intelligence has transcended all the distinctions which we now make, it will have transcended the distinction between one stage of evolution and another, IDEALISM AND CHRlSTlAmTY 273 and will therefore deny that there lias been any evolution. But if all evolution is an illusion, what meaning can there be in saying that our intelligence may evolve into a higher stage, in which the law of contradiction is transcended ? Any one who judges at all — and even to set up a false theory is to judge — must presuppose that his judgment means something; but it cannot mean anything, if to affirm may be to deny, and to deny may be to affirm. The supposition that the absolute may be super-rational is obviously untenable. At the same time there is a certain amount of truth in the contention that the absolute is not fully re- vealed in man. For in man the rational life is a process, and a process which is never com- plete, and indeed never can be complete ; in the absolute there must be process, because there is infinite self-conscious energy, but there can be no transition from lower to higher. We must agree with Mr. Bradley, that " progress and decay are alike incompatible with perfec- tion." "^ " The improvement or decay of the universe," as he says, " seems nonsense, un- * Bradley's Appearance and Reality y p. 499. T 274 THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE meaning or blasphemous." ^ The absolute is self-complete, and apart from such self-com- pleteness it could not be self-originative or creative of other forms of being. But the per- fection of the absolute is destroyed if we either separate it from any form of finite being or give independent reality to any form of finite being. To suppose that the absolute is self-complete apart from the finite, is to fall into the absurdity of an absolute which is limited ; to affirm the independence of the finite is to set up a finite absolute. Thus we are brought face to face with the difficulty, that if human reason has no reality apart from the divine reason, we seem to be affirming that the former is merely a par- tial aspect of the latter, so that man is but tfie passive medium of the divine reason. Now Christianity solves this difficulty by the doc- trine of the Holy Spirit. It affirms *at once that man is the author of his own destiny, and yet that he cannot realise his true life unless the spirit of God works in him. The Christian consciousness has always held fast by this idea, and the church has persistently refused to * Ibid. p. 501. IDEALISM AND CHRISTIANITY 275 accept any compromise which would separate the unity of the divine and the human spirit. The language of St. Paul : " I am crucified with Christ; nevertheless I live, yet not I, but Christ liveth in me," has been echoed by pious minds in all ages: such language is in truth the spontaneous utterance of the religious con- sciousness. We have therefore to ask whether philosophical reflection does not enable us to see that we have here an idea which reason pronounces to be absolutely true. The main obstacle to an acceptance of the truth which is embodied in the doctrine of the Holy Spirit seems to me to arise from the mechanical way in which we are wont to con- ceive of the relation between the human and the divine spirit. Now this mode of concep- tion is inadequate even when applied to the physical world, and it becomes more and more inadequate the higher the object to which it is applied. As we have seen, the physical world is inexplicable except on pre-supposition of an eternal creative energy, which expresses itself in the incessant transformations constituting what may be called the life of nature. This 2/6 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE creative energy is unthinkable apart from its manifestations, and yet these do not exhaust it, but constitute the phases in which its nature is expressed. On the other hand, no single phase is possible apart from the absolute nature of the whole, and therefore we have to conceive even this stage of the world as implying an organic unity or system, in which the whole determines the parts, while the parts are essential to the whole. If we treat any part as self-complete in its isolation, we fall into the untenable doctrine of atomic Materialism ; if we deny the reality of the parts, we commit ourselves to an equally untenable Pantheism; we have therefore to affirm at once the reality of the parts in the whole, and of the whole in the parts. And when we pass to the second stage in the process of the world, we find the idea of organic unity forcing itself upon us still more persistently. Here we have a distinct advance towards in- dividuation and organic system, for chemical elements are not related to each other in the same indifferent way as particles which are viewed simply as exhibiting the stress of gravi- tation: certain elements will combine and IDEALISM AND CHRISTIANITY 277 others will not, and they combine only in defi- nite proportions. A still more marked indi- viduality is displayed in living beings: here, in fact, we first have an individual in any well- marked sense. But living beings more per- fectly realise the idea of individuality, just because they contain the whole in themselves in a more explicit form. For the living being presupposes the whole system of the world as physical and chemical, and in its own organism it unites physical and chemical changes with the new and higher form of unity which consti- tutes its life. When finally we pass to rational beings, we find not only the manifestation of individuality in a higher sense, but we find also a closer relation to the whole. It is the special pre- rogative of the self-conscious being that for him not only his own individual life, but the life of all forms of existence, and even the ultimate principle of all existence, can be re- produced in idea. Thus he is at once the most truly individual, and the most truly uni- versal. The whole is present in him, not merely in the sense that he is affected by it. 2/8 THE CHRIST/AN- IDEAL OF LIFE but in the sense that by his own self-con- scious activity he is capable of living in it in an ideal way; it does not operate through him, but in him. It is true that he would not be self-active were not the whole what it is. Without gravitation there would be no system of nature, without chemical affinity there would be no life, and without life there would be no mind. And yet mind is not a mere external synthesis of physical, chemi- cal, and vital forces, but a new form of reality including and transcending these. Man is thus a self-active or self-determining being, not because he is separable from the whole, but because he is capable of living in the whole. The creative activity which is pres- ent in all forms of being is present also in man, but in man it is present through his self-activity. Thus while he can know noth- ing which is not a manifestation of the abso- lute, and realise nothing which is contradictory of its nature, and experience no permanent sat- isfaction which is not the reflex of his unity with it, he could neither know, will, nor feel, were he not self-determinant or free. The IDEALISM AND CHRISTIANITY 279 absolute, in other words, in the case of man, expresses its originative activity in the pro- duction of beings, who are themselves self- active or free, though not self-creative. Man is not free in the sense of being self-originat- ing, but he is free in the sense of being able to comprehend the nature of the absolute, and to bring his life into harmony with it; he is also free in the sense of being able to live in opposition to that revelation of the absolute which in more or less explicit form is inseparable from his self-consciousness. Human life is, therefore, a life of moral re- sponsibility. The divine spirit can be present in man only as man is conscious of it, and identifies himself with it. Thus we can see how the Holy Spirit may be immanent in man, while yet man lives in the freedom of a "son of God." It is in this sense that I should maintain the immanence of God in man ; what is affirmed is the union of spirit with spirit, not the external and mechanical relation of one force as acting upon another. If the mechanical conception is inadequate to express the unity of the distinguishable 28o THE CHRISTIAN- IDEAL OF LIFE elements in the physical world, how much more inadequate must it be to express the self-conscious unity of man with God. I think we may now conclude that the Chris- tian conception of God and man is not only in harmony with the results of modern science and historical criticism, when these are inter- preted from the comprehensive and self-con- sistent point of view of an idealistic or spiritual philosophy, but that the principle of Christian- ity thus acquires a definiteness and persuasive force which is attainable in no other way, and which is missed by those who shut themselves up within the narrow circle of traditional forms of thought. The results of science and phi- losophy are no doubt hostile to many cherished prejudices which are due to the survival of pagan or mediaeval superstitions, but they can- not touch the living heart of Christianity itself. It has already been maintained that the world, as the manifestation of God, is pur- posive. It must be observed, however, that this purpose is not something superadded to the world, but is implied in its very nature. It is important to make this observation, be- IDEALISM AND CHRISTIANITY 28 1 cause the whole objection to the teleological view of the world arises from confusing mechanical with immanent teleology. The idealistic view is therefore hostile to the con- ception of Providence as the external adapta- tion of events to an end. Mr. Balfour tells us that one cannot "think of evolution in a God-created world without attributing to its Author the notion of purpose slowly worked out."* It is of course obvious that the con- ception of God implies that the process of evolution is towards an end ; but this process cannot be adequately described as a "prefer- ential exercise of divine power." We cannot conceive of the world as first created, and then directed towards an end. The reality of the world implies the continuous self- determination of God, and this self-determi- nation involves the process by which the world is maintained as an organic whole. We cannot, therefore, separate the evolution of the world from its existence. If we do so, we fall into the difficulty urged by Kant against the argument from design, that we ♦ Foundations of Beliefs p. 328. 282 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE presuppose a "matter" to which the divine Architect gives shape. Such a "matter" is unthinkable. The nearest approach we can make to it is in some such conception as that of the primitive matter from which, according to the nebular theory, the complex forms of our solar system have been evolved. But in this nebulous matter there is already implied the " promise and potency " of all forms of life, and hence it can only be called " matter " in the relative sense of being a less developed form of the world than is realised in the sub- sequent stages of evolution. The purpose, then, which must be affirmed is not exter- nally added to the world, but is already im- plied in the very existence of the world. The world is an organic whole, in which each part exists and has its proper nature only in and through the others. Hence the evolution from lower to higher forms is not a matter of accident, but is inseparable from the exist- ence of the world. A distinction, however, must be drawn between different orders of being. It is only in the case of man that we can speak not only of evolution, but of con- IDEALISM AND CHRISTIANITY 283 scious evolution or progress. "The scientific doctrine of evolution has enabled us to see that the law of all finite forms of being is a law of development; in other words, that the real is not the actual as it first appears in time, but the ideal which is implicit in the actual, and which is present in it as the active principle determining the process in which it is manifested. In the case of beings lower, than man this process does not reach the stage of a self-conscious development ; or, at least, even the highest animals have only an indefinite consciousness of self, and, there- fore, can hardly be said to be capable of ideals. Man, however, not only develops, but he is capable of grasping the law of his own development, and, therefore, of con- trasting with his immediate self an ideal of himself in which is embodied his conception of what he ought to be, as distinguished from what he is. This capability of return- ing upon himself and setting up ideals is the fundamental condition of human progress. The ideal, however, while it is contrasted with the actual, is never in contradiction to 284 ^^^ CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE the actual ; it is but the actual grasped in its ideal nature, as that end towards which all prior development has been striving. Were it otherwise, the progress of man would be impossible. It is thus obvious that, on the one hand, progress consists in conformity to the purpose which is involved in the whole nature of things, and, on the other hand, that this purpose can be realised only through the free activity of man. The spiritual life of man cannot be imparted to him from without ; it consists in the conscious realisa- tion of the ideal. It is, therefore, a very inadequate conception of life which is ex- pressed in the formula that there is a " Power not ourselves which makes for righteousness." The " Power " which makes for righteousness is the conscious willing of righteousness, i£, the conception and realisation of the meaning of the world. It is true that righteousness can be realised only because it is the true law of man's being; but it is a law which operates only in and through his self-con- scious life. It is, then, the very nature of all finite IDEALISM AND CHRISTIANITY 285 forms of being that their reality consists in a process by which they come to be what in idea they are. In the case of man, whose development is a self-conscious process, the development of goodness consists in the tran- scendence of his immediate or natural life. So far as the life of man is merely natural, he is neither good nor evil ; it is only because he is capable of abstracting from the imme- diate life of feeling that he is moral. And with this capacity is bound up the possi- bility of willing evil. The question as to the existence of evil has been obscured by the manner in which the problem has been put. The church fathers, conceiving of man as independently created, maintained that he was originally perfect in wisdom and holi- ness, and that evil was introduced into the world by the sin of the first man. It need hardly be said that this explanation not only explains nothing, but is self-contradictory and out of harmony with all that we know of primitive man. It explains nothing, because moral evil cannot be externally transferred from one person to another ; the very idea of 286 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE moral evil being that it proceeds from a free act. It is self-contradictory, because a perfect being could have no disposition to will evil. And it is incompatible with the results of scientific discovery, which make it certain that primitive man began at the lowest and not the highest stage. The state of perfec- tion ascribed to primitive man is, therefore, the goal and not the starting-point of human- ity. Man was, therefore, in his original state evil, in the sense that evil is inseparable from the life of a being who can attain to good only through freedom, which involves the freedom to fall into error and evil. The original state of man was one in which he had the most inadequate conception of the world, himself, and God. The progress of man has involved a continual struggle with the cruder ideal of an earlier age. The spir- itual life is not a primitive endowment, but the result of long-continued pain and travail. Evil is not an accident ; it is inseparable from the process by which man transcends his im- mediate life. It is only through the ex- perience of evil that man has obtained a IDEALISM AND CHRISTIANITY 287 consciousness of the depths as well as the heights of his nature. On the other hand, the process of human life has been a contin- ual transcendence of evil. The desire of man is for goodness and God, and his experience that evil is in contradiction to his true self makes it impossible for him to rest in it. Hence even at the earliest stage man is never absolutely evil ; he hates his enemy, it is true, but he sacrifices his natural im- pulses, and even his life, for his family or tribe. Thus the imperfect development of his moral life is the counterpart of his im- perfect knowledge of himself. The deliverance of man from the evil which belongs to his nature, as a being whose life is a process, is possible only through the comprehension of himself as in his ideal nature identical with God. The mediaeval conception of salvation cannot be accepted in the form in which it is stated. Man, it was argued, might conceivably have been liberated from sin in two ways : either God might have pardoned him out of pure mercy, or man might have expiated his sin by a 288 THE CHRISTIAN' IDEAL OF LIFE humility correspondent to the magnitude of his guilt. But the former, it was held, con- flicts with the justice of God; and the latter is impossible, because man could not undergo a humiliation proportionate to the self-asser- tion implied in disobedience to the will of God. Hence God offered up his Son in man's stead, thus reconciling infinite justice with infinite mercy. It is impossible to state this highly arti- ficial doctrine without seeing that it is the product of conflicting ideas which are not properly reconciled with each other. The starting-point is the conception of personal sin, one of the central ideas of Christianity. Sin is then identified with crime, and there- fore God is conceived as an inexorable judge. But sin is not crime, nor can God be re- garded as a judge. Crime is a violation of the personal rights of another ; it is an offence against the external order of the state, which must be expiated by an external punishment. Sin, on the other hand, is not a violation of rights, but a desecration of the ideal nature of the sinner, the willing of himself as in his iDEALiSM AKtD CHRISTIANITY 2^9 essence he is not. Hence sin requires no external punishment to bring it home to the sinner: it brings its own punishment with it in the destruction of the higher life, the real- isation of which is blessedness. In man, by virtue of the divine principle in him, the con- sciousness of God is bound up with the con- sciousness of himself, and he cannot do violence to the one without doing violence to the other. Hence God is not a judge, allotting punish- ment according to an external law, but the perfectly holy Being, by reference to whom man condemns himself. No external punish- ment can transform the inner nature. The criminal, after undergoing punishment, may be more hardened in crime than ever, and yet society must punish him, because its func- tion is to preserve the social bond, which by his act the criminal has assailed. But reli- gion has in view not the preservation of social order, but the regeneration of the individual: it deals with the inner nature of man, not with the result of his act upon society; and hence, unless it transforms and spiritualises him, it entirely fails of its end. 290 THE CHRISTIAN IDEAL OF LIFE The sin of Adam, according to the mediae- val theory, consisted in pride, or the attempt to equalise himself with God. The truth im- plied in this view is that in so far as man seeks to realise his true self in separation from God, and therefore in willing his own good in isolation from the good of his fellow- men, he brings upon himself spiritual death. But this truth is obscured by the vulgar notion that sin is the attempt of man to equalise himself with God, — a notion obvi- ously based upon the conception of God as a Ruler whose majesty must be asserted. This pagan conception, drawn mainly from the idea of Caesar, as the representative of order and law, is entirely foreign to the Chris- tian idea of God. Even Plato saw that "in God there can be no envy ; " and mediaeval thinkers themselves virtually deny this false conception of God, when they speak of the incarnation as an expression of the infinite love of God. Here, in fact, we come upon the only purely Christian idea in the whole doctrine. Stripped of its artificial form, what is affirmed is that it is the very nature of IDEALISM AND CHRISTIANITY 29 1 God to communicate himself to finite beings ; that, loving his creatures with an infinite love, he can realise his own blessedness only in them. Man can therefore be saved from sin only as he realises in his own life the self- communicating spirit of God. In taking upon himself the burden of the race, he lives a divine life. This is the secret which Jesus realised in his life, and to have made this secret practically our own is to be justified by faith. The Christian ideal of life, as here under- stood, is broad enough to embrace all the elements which in their combination consti- tute the complex spirit of the modern world. Every advance in science is the preparation for a fuller and clearer conception of God ; every improvement in the organisation of society is a further development of that com- munity of free beings by which the ideal of an organic unity of humanity is in process of realisation ; every advance in the artistic interpretation of the world helps to individu- alise the idea of the organic unity by which all things are bound together. The ideal of 29^ THE CHRIST/AN- IDEAL OF LIFE the Church has tended to limit Christianity to the direct promotion of the moral ideal, to the exclusion of the more comprehensive ideal which recognises that the goal is the full development of all the means by which the full perfection of humanity is realised. The Christian ideal, as embodied in the teach- ing of Jesus, was free from this limitation. It saw God in the orderly processes of nature and in the beauty of the world, as well as in the loving service of humanity. In principle it therefore embraced all that makes for the higher life. The Christianity of our day must free itself from the narrow conception of life by which Protestantism has tended to limit its principle. , It must recognise that the ideal of Christian manhood includes within it the Greek ideal of clear thought and the love of beauty, as well as the Jewish ideal of righteousness, and the Roman ideal of law and order, harmonising all by the divine principle of love to God and man, on the basis of that free spirit which has come to us mainly from our Teutonic ancestors. OUTLINES OF SOCIAL THEOLOGY. By WILLIAM DEWITT HYDE, D.D., President of Boivdotn College. .i2mo. Cloth. Price $1.50. " It is a most thoughtful, wholesome, and stimulating book. It is suggestive and thought-provoking, rather than exhaustive, and that is a merit of only good books." — Evangelical Messenger. "Altogether it is a book for the times — fresh, vigorous, intelligent, broad, and brave, and one that will be welcomed by thinking people." — Christian Guide. " President Hyde does not aim to upset established religion, only to point out how the article we now have may be improved on its social side, as to which there will be no dispute that it is wofuUy lacking. His argument is sound and sensible, and his book DESERVES TO BE WIDELY READ." — Pkila, Evening Bulletin. HEREDITY AND CHRISTIAN PROBLEMS. By AMORY H. BRADFORD, D.D. i2mo. Cloth. Price $1.50. " It is a most timely corrective to the drift of popular exaggeration, and it is a most clear and forcible presentation of many widely misun- derstood truths." — From a letter to the Author from Bishop Potter. " A popular and instructive discussion of the vexed question of her- edity. . . . Dr. Bradford discusses it in a robust, intelligent, straightfor- ward, and thoroughly Christian way, and his book will be a solid help to every student of human nature." — The Christian Advocate. " The really fine and characteristic feature in the scheme of reform presented by Dr. Bradford is his faith in Christianity as a divine and spiritual power in the world, set to operate along the lines of certain intelligent methods." — The Independent. THE MACMILLAN COMPANY, 66 FIFTH AVENUE, NEW YORIC_ THIS BOOK IS DUE ON THE LAST DATE STAMPED BELOW AN INITIAL FINE OF 25 CENTS WILL BE ASSESSED FOR FAILURE TO RETURN THIS BOOK ON THE DATE DUE. THE PENALTY WILL INCREASE TO 50 CENTS ON THE FOURTH DAY AND TO $1.00 ON THE SEVENTH DAY OVERDUE. JUH 28 m^ « 933n'58GRX Oct 1934 ^•Jan'SOC. MAR 5 1956 LIBRARY USE JUN 1 9 1956 RECD LO JAN 6 19SB, JUN 1 1 1968 fS I.ECEJVED 25'68-5PM LD 21-50m-l '3; TB /M87