$B 1M bMM EXCHANGE H /s-2- Prolegomena to a Study of the Ethical Ideal of Plutarch and of the Greeks of the First Century A. D. Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Require- ments for the Degree of ^Ph. D., at the University of Michigan. By GEORGE DEPUE HADZSITS, 1906 UNIVERSITY OF CINCINNATI CINCINNATI, OHIO. Prolegomena to a Study of the Ethical Ideal of Plutarch and of the Greeks of the First Century A. D. .4 l^hesis Presented in Partial fulfillment of the Require- ments for the Degree of Ph. D., at the University of Michigan By GEORGE DEPUE HADZSITS. 1906 UNIVERSITY OF CINCINNATI PKBSS CINCINNATI, OHIO. CONTENTS. PAGE Bibliography 5-6 Ivexica and Indices 7-10 Historical Introduction 11-14 The Problem and the Method of Research 15-18 Discussion 19-58 List of Words 59 Conclusions .. . 60-66 239403 BIBLIOGRAPHY. Arnold, W. T. Bergk, Theo. Benn, A. W. Bernays, J. Christ, W. Croiset, A. et M. Droysen, J. G. Eichhoff, A. Fried! aender, L. Finlay, Geo. Frazer, J. G. Gardthausen, V. Gregorovius, Ferd. Greard, Octave. Gomperz, Th. Holm, A. Hertzberg, G. PV. Hath, Edwin. Heinze, H. Holden, H. A. Hoffding, H. Karst, J. Kostlin, K. Kennedy, H. A. A. Marquardt, J. und / Mommsen, Th. I The Roman System of Provincial Ad- ministration. Grieehische Litteraturgeschichte. 7^he Philosophy of (Greece, considered in relation to the character and history of i/s people. Hh. M. Jg. 7, *. 92. Geschichte der griechischen Litteratur. Histoire de la Litterature Grecque. Geschichte des Hellenismus. Ueber die religiose sittlichc Weltansicht des Plutarchus. Sittengesch ichte . Greece under the Romans. Edition of Pausanias. Augustus u. seine Zeit. The Rmperor Hadrian. De la Morale de Plutarque. Griechische Denker. The History of Greece. Gesch ichte Griechenlands . Essays on Biblical Greek. Plutarchische Untersuchungen . Plutarchus Lives. Ethik. Geschichte des hellenistischen Zeitalters. Geschichte der Ethik. Sources of New Testament Greek. Handbuch der Romischen Altertilmer, Vols. 4 and 6. Merivale, Chas. The History of the Romans under the Mommsen, Th. Miiller, Iwan. Miiller, F. Max. MahafiFy, J. P. Martha, C. Niese, B. Norden, Ed. Oakesmitli, Jno. Paulsen, Fr. Roberts, W. Rhys. Schmidt, L. Shuckburg-h, E. S. Sickinger, A. Trench, R. C. Thumb, A. Volkmann, R. Wundt, W. Windelband, W. Weissenberg-er, B. Wenley, R. M. Wedgwood, J. Wundt, Wm. Whitney, W. D. Wunderer, C. 2iegler, Th. teller, Edw. 77fc Provinces of the Roman Kmpire. Handbuch, Vol. 3. Lectures on the Science of Language. I ^roblems in Greek History. The (.wreck World under Roman Sway. Etudes Morales sur L? Antiqvite. Gcsehichte der Griechischen u. Makedon- ischen Staaten seit der Schlacht hei Chaeronea. Die Antike Knnstprosa. The Religion of Plutarch. System der Kthik. The Ancient Boeotians. Die Kthik der alt en Griechen. Augustus. l)e Linguae Lalinae apud Plutarchum ct Reliquiis ct Vestigiis. Plutarch: His Life, His Parallel Lires cnic His Morals. Synonyms of the Nezv Testament. Handbuch der Neugrtechischen Volks- sprache. Die Griechischc Sprache iiu Zeit alter des Hellenismus. Lehen, Schriftcn u. Philosophic dcs Plutarch. Ethics (Engl. Translation). .1 History of Ancient Philosophy. Die Sprache Puttarchs u. die Pseudoplut- arch ischcn Schriftcn . Plutarch and his Age; in " The \e-c World", June, iyoo. The Moral Ideal. T ~olkerpsychologie. Language and the Study of Language. (.'itate u. geflilgelte Worte bei Polybius. Geschichte der Kthik. Die Philosophic der Griecheu. LEXICA AND INDICES. (NoTE: We have taken all of our words through all of the following: indices and lexica; supplementing- this with wide reading, we have gathered the passages in which the terms are found. The discussion deals with each term sepa- rately, giving an historical treatment of the significance, meaning and development of each term. This work, it need hardly be added, does not lay claim to finality.) Index Homericus Aug. Gehring. Teubner, 1891. Appen- dix Hymnorum Vocabula Continens, 1895. Lexicon Homericum H. Ebeling. Teubner, 1885. Poetac Minores GraeciTh. Gaisford. Teubner, 1823. In- dices for Hesiod, Theognis, Archilochus, Solon, Simon- ides, Mimnermus, Tyrtaeus, Theocritus, Bion, Moschus. Hesiod^. A. Paley. London, Geo Bell, 1861. Greek Lyric Poets G. S. Parnell. London, Longmans, Green & Co., 1891. Greek Melic Poets B.. W. Smyth. Macmillan & Co., 1900. Bacchylides F. G. Keyon. Oxford, 1897. Fr. W. Blass. Teubner, 1898. Lexicon Pindaricum I. Rumpel. Teubner, 1883. Tragicae Dictionis Index spectans ad Tragicorum Graecorum Fragmenta A. Nauck. Lipsiae, 1892. Lexicon Aeschyleum J. Dindorf. Lipsiae, 1876. Lexicon Sophodeum Fr. Ellendt. Berlin, 1872. Euripidis Opera Omnia A. et J. M. Duncan. Glasguae, 1821. Vol. 9. Index Verborum . . Omnium. Chr. D. Beck. Concordance to the Comedies and Fragments of Aristophanes H. Dunbar. Oxford, 1883. Menandri et Philemonis Reliquiae Aug. Meineke. Berlin, 1823. Herodotus J. C. F. Baehr. Lipsiae, 1861. Lexicon to Herodotus (Schweighaeuser.) H. Carey. Ox- ford, 1843. Thucydides Fr. Goeller. London, 1835. K. W. Kriiger. Berlin, 1846. Lexicon Xenophonteum F. G. Sturzius. Lipsiae, 1801-4. Indices Graecitatis quos in singulos oratores Atticos confecit J. J. Reiskius. Oxford, 1828. Indices for Antiphon, Aeschines, Andocides, Deinarchus, Demades, Isaeus, Lysias, Lycurgus. Index Demosthenicus S. Preuss. Teubner, 1892. Index Andocideus, Lycurgeus, Dinarcheus L. L. Forman. Oxford, 1897. Index Lysiacus D. E. Holmes. Bonn, 1895. Isaei Orationes XI cum fragmentis G. F. Schoemann. Gryphiswaldiae, 1831. Hyperdis Orationes \ji cum fragmentis Fr. Blass. Teubner, 1894. Index Graecitatis Platonicae T. Mitchell. Oxford, 1832. Index Aristotelicus H. Bonitz. Berlin, 1870. Lexicon Theocriteum I. Rumpel. Teubner, 1879. Apollonii Argonautica R. Merkel. Teubner, 1854. Polybius Lexicon, Ed., Schweighaeuser. Lipsiae, 1789-1795. Lexicon Polybianum J. A. Ernesti. 1789-1795. BabriusW. G. Rutherford. Macmillan & Co., 1883. Diony sins of Halicarnassus: Epistola ad Pompeium, Indicium de Thucydide, Libellum de Us quae Thucydidi propria sunt C. G. Kriig-er. Halis Saxonum, 1823. De Structura Orationis J. Upton. London, 1747. xat^v K/aitris G. Holwell. London, 1778. i roiiv d^^attov pyropow vTro/Aviy/xarwr/xot. The Three Literary Letters W . Rhys. Roberts. Cam- bridge, 1901. Index Graecitatis in Plutarchi Opera D. Wyttenbach, Lip- siae, 1835. Rpicteteae Philosophiae Monumenta I. Schweighaeuser. Lipsiae, 1779, Appian I. Schweig-haeuser. Lipsiae, 1785. Luciani Opera I. P. Reitzius. Amsterdam, 1743-46. Dio Cassius F. G. Sturzius. Lipsiae, 1824. Y. P. Boissevain. Berlin, 1898-1901. Herodian Th. G. Irmisch. Lipsiae, 1805. Philostrati Opera C. L. Kayser. Teubner, 1870. AthenaetisG. Kaibel. Teubner, 1887-90. Sextus Empiricus Im. Bekker. Berlin, 1842. Timaei Sophistae Lexicon Vocum Platonicarum D. Ruhn- kenius. Lipsiae, 1828. Der Atticismus: Diony sius von Halikarnass bis auf den ziveiten Philoslrattis W. Schmid. Stuttgart, 1887-97. Rhetores Graecil^. Spengel. Teubner, 1854-85. Epigrammata Graeca ex Lapidibus Conlecta G. Kaibel. Berlin, 1878. Lexicon Technologiae Graecorum Rhetoricae I. Chr. Th. Ernesti. Lipsiae, 1795. Greek Lexicon of the Roman & Byzantine Periods. 146 B. C.-1100 A. D. K. A. Sophocles. Boston, 1870. Lexicon^. G. Liddell and R. Scott. New York, 1889. 9 Synonyms of the New Testament R. C. Trench. New York, 1854. Lexicon of the New Testament Greek H. Cremer (Trans. W. Urwick). Edinburgh, 1878. Greek- English Lexicon of the New Testament J. H. Thayer. New York, 1897. English-Greek Lexicon C. D. Yonge. New York, 1893. Modern Greek and English Lexicon P. D. Sakellarios, Jno. Pervanoglu. (Athens, 1894). A Modern Greek and English {and English- Greek} Lexicon N. Contopoulos. London, 1880. (Athens, 1889). A Modern Greek Lexicon R. A. Rhousopoulos. Leipzig, 1900. A.Qr)aravpip(0v , a/Ae'0vya)v, yA.MrxpoA.oyta, erot/utoAoyos, Kara. AaAta, Karu^pt'curo-o/zcu, apyoAoyta, Trpoo-eTTi^Te'w, Trpoo-eTrco-^jaatvca^ crvve- 16 It is our belief that a philological-psychological study of the mental state of the Greeks of the first century, furnishes valuable clues, tending to elucidate the obscure problems of Greek ethics and religion of that period. An insight into the inner life of thought and feeling of the Greek people may enable us to apprehend the true nature of a very complex age, by no means as yet thoroughly under- stood. Anticipating the statement of our conclusions, it may perhaps be apposite to state, here, that one might seriously doubt the validity of the generalization that the Greek society of this era was "a fossil society, feeding upon its own traditions and petrified beyond the hope of ren^ovation or healthy growth" 7 . Nor is it absolutely true that "the ideal of the Conscience belonged to the great foe of Greece" 8 . Rather, that very ideal was growing and developing within the limits of Greek experience, and as shown by the language, ^s ? 8iaypt.aiv(a, KarevAoyeto, KTa7reivoa>. The constant reference to private, affairs and vir- tues is noteworthy; the interests of the individual constitute the starting- point for the development of this system of ethics. There is abundant evidence of interest in petty concerns; the very large number of new double compound terms evinces, if not a desire for exact expression or of restoring" to words the force they have lost, a fondness for pompous and picturesque effects, a tendency toward elaboration and an attention to detail, just as characteristic of decadent literature as of the arts. Another group deserving attention is that of "strengthened" terms: these words, while showing that tendency toward exaggeration charac- teristic of language in its decline, are a mockery of an age that we know was characterized by feeble feelings, lesser impulses, minor am- bitions, of which the numerous late diminutives are a truer expression . This large body of words gives a picture of a society, "hastening to ex- plain everything in its decline", but at the same time aspiring to lofty virtues. We are at first surprised that Plutarch seems to have borrowed so little from the Latin ethical vocabulary, but, as is well known, his "Demosthenes" begins with an apology for his slight knowledge of Latin. Apart from public life, Latin was never so widely learned in Greece as Greek was in the Roman world, all the time from the Scipios to Marcus Aurelius. (Cic. Arch. 23. Senec. Consol. ad Helv. 6.8. Juv. 15.110. Quint, i. 1.12. Suet. Claud. 42. Plut. i.564$.) 7. Mahaffy. c.12. "The Greek World Under Roman Sway." 8. Wedgwood, p. 129. 17 that infallible formula of a people, the Greek temperament was undergoing a subtle transformation, knowledge of which ought to correct the only too often preferred charges of 44 stagnancy" and a " contemptible decadence", made against the Greek of the first century. While it is true that Plutarch "rehabilitates the ancient sanctions of morality and of religion" 9 , at the same time, unconsciously, perhaps, he be- comes the high priest of a new moral aspiration. 9. Wenley. "Plutarch and His Age", p. 267. 18 DISCUSSION. The keen versatility and vivacity of the Greek mind naturally took delight in new language formations; this neologistic tendency was as ancient as Homer 1 , and was ver} r marked throughout the entire history of the people, as we see, for example, in Aeschylus, Aristophanes, the rhetori- cians 2 , Thucydides 3 , Demosthenes, Polybius and Plutarch. The mental activity of the race, thus, in time, produced a vocabulary of extraordinary variety, to which free fancy contributed, as much as need. When Polybius 4 uses the term KcuvoAoyia, (not occurring in Greek literature before his time), we are left in doubt whether he has coined a new term or is employing (as was possible for one who was writing in the "common dialect" and employing a less pure vocabulary), a word, current be- fore his day but which had not yet crept into formal litera- ture; this problem is of less consequence to us however, than the problems suggested by the use of the word in Polybius and in later writers. Polybius attributes Ktui/oAoyia to Greek ambassadors, whose "strange phraseology" vexed the Roman senate; the latter fact is significant, as the more conserva- tive 5 Romans would no t y unnaturally, be vexed at Athenian volubility. 1. Eustathius, 1801, 27, calls Homer a KaivoAoyos Sc rts TTOO/TIJS. 2. Dionysius of Halicarnassus, (De lyys. p. 458) speaking of Greek literary styles, of the use of figures, of hyperboles, of KumKoi ^vOnpia Trapa/JaAAovres ev/oeovtv, 3. Aes. Pr. 320, 908, 926. 4. Eur. Fr. xxii. 2; Hi. 2; xxx. 4. 23 success and wealth, with little charity for their opposites. In the second place 5 ,wravo? is predicated of Andromache, of Orestes, of Herakles, and we find a new suggestion, not openly expressed but clearly implied, of leniency toward sub- mission and humility; but the circumstances are of the most trying- nature and these alone render humility excusable. Submission or humility does not necessarily entail loss of honor or self-respect. It does not, regardless of causes, awaken a strong revulsion of feeling. In the third place 6 , the word is used of Odysseus, of Orestes and of Pylades, of Agamemnon, and of Helen and falls from hostile lips; it signifies baseness, cowardice, disgrace, and is a term of strong condemnation. The treatment of the word shows a development of the idea, a growth and quickening of the moral consciousness. The three distinct senses of the word that we have observed, are still more clearly marked in Demosthenes; the tendencies we have noticed before are more sharply defined. Demosthenes uses the word first 7 , of Philip, of the Athenian army, of Thebes with the old implications of weakness, of humiliation, insignificance, lack of pride, and always with an association of scorn and contempt. The term is, however, also used in a milder sense 8 ; it is used of Athens, in her final struggles, in her helplessness, with deep reproach to be sure and with a suggestion of loss of prestige and earlier reputa- tion and of pride, but still with no loss of honor. That it was possible to associate and even identify the idea with /xcVpios is an indication of a movement toward greater leniency, on the part of the Athenian public, the common people to whom Demosthenes 'made his pleas, and in whom humility inspired pity. In the third place 9 , that other sense of posi- tive evil has become thoroughly established. In Aristotle, we see the earlier meaning more clearly. The tone of Demosthenes is mild, that of Aristotle reminds us of the past; the former is decidedly a man of his age; the 5. Eur, Andr. 165. 971. Her. F. 1406. (cf. Xen. Cyr. 5.1.5.) 6. Eur. Hec. 245. Orest. 1411. Iph. A. 339. Troad. 1018. Fr. ii. 1. 7. Dem. i. 9; 4.23; 9.21; 16.24; 19.325; 61.25. 8. Dem. 8.67; 1074; 13.25; 21. 183-6; 45.4; 7.45. 9. Dem. 18. 108; 18. 178. 24 latter has inherited more of the earlier temper; the former speaks the note of the struggling democracy, the latter, the eulogy of the once proud state. We have, here, indications of the old pride, of scorn for weakness, together with a care- ful effort to attain moderation in all matters; hence the TaTravot were certain to meet with censure in Aristotle, as the word meant, to him, a failure to attain that mean, whether the word had a social, moral or political application. This is an aristocratic society the exercise of whose virtues requires wealth and leisure and noble birth. The raTreivo? 10 is humble, cannot be liberal, is easily a flatterer, and is servile; for him Aristotle can have no words except of con- demnation. This probably represents the essentially Greek attitude and o raTreivos incurs the strong displeasure of the Greek, less because he may be base or wicked than because he is low. Sox^/ooo-vn/ is the mean opposed to 3/3/ois, and not Ta7reti/oTiys ! Here, most clearly, we see the slight recognition of humility, the absence of mercy toward the lowly, the assertion of an old confidence within conscious, artistic limits. We find the three significations we have noticed before, still more clearly defined in Plutarch. He could say : ;(0pov 8e . . TO TifJLwpLav irapaXiirctv Kaipov irapaa-Xovros eTrieiKc's tori (90 F), evye'veia KaXov /u,ei/, aAAa Trpoydvwv aya66v (5 D), and v, while occurring in the Septuagint, does not recur, again, until Plutarch's time, and becomes common, only later, in the Patristic literature. The feeling, of which it is an expression, is a funda- mental one which would effect all thought, feeling and con- duct. In the Septuagint on the one hand, and in the New Testament and in a large body of Patristic literature on the other, the virtue of ra7ruvopoorvvr} is accepted without reserva- tion; it is constantly encouraged and recommended with other virtues; nor is it merely an ideal that provokes exhor- tation, but often, by implication, and frequently, expressly, is acknowledged a fact in Greek life. "Humility" then, was 12. Plut. 11. 357 A; ii. 599 B; ii. 806 A; ii. 822 D; ii. 1069 C. 13. N. T. Math. 11.29; Luc. 14.11; Peter i. 5.5; LXX. Pr. 1619. 14. See discussion of Tairivopo(rvvr). 15. Plato. L,egrg. iv. 716 A (cf. Origin, i. 1312 C.) 16. Plutarch favored slavery and was an aristocrat. 26 a factor in the evolution of Greek character 1 , as early as the time of the Septuagint 2 ' 8 and as late as the fourth century after Christ, and was operating in Greek communities in Asia Minor and Alexandria in the East, and in Rome, in the West. While it is impossible to determine to what extent such suggestions were immediately operative, the fact remains that the suggestion was there, and, certainly, later, bore fruit. Ignatius 4 , writing to the Ephesians, exhorts them to be Ta7rvopove?. Plutarch 15 with all his generosity, feels a reserve toward this virtue, which to his mind implies, at least, a loss of noble spirit and thus ap- proaches dangerously near baseness. Josephus 16 relates how the Roman Galba, accused, by the soldiers, of Ta7rcivo^poy, was treacherously put to death. Such " weak-mindedness", approaching "meanness" or "cowardice", was associated by Arrian 17 with the vice of KoXaKeia. Thus, while in the first century A. D., Greek Ethics did not, as yet, welcome the idea of humility, still the idea was a present force that was at work in the Greek consciousness and, in time, produced great psychic changes. Although the idea did not receive complete acceptance in Plutarch's day, yet it was not ostracized, and the Greek mind gradually became accustomed to it, more so, even in the first century A. D., than the above study would seem to indicate. The 13. Herm. Sim. 7; Vis. 3.10. 14. Clem. R. i.2; i.19; i.30; i.44 (cf. also Or. Sib. 8.481) i.48 (cf. also C1.A1. L532B). 15. Plut. ii. 336 E; ii. 475 E. 16. Jos. B. J. 4.9.2. 17. Arr. Epict. i.9.10; 3.24.56. 28 presence of other virtues, such as dh/e&KaKta, ptrpiarrdOcui and dyatfoTToua, closely related to "humility", demonstrates this! Still it is difficult to resist the conclusion that the Greek temper was still essentially proud 1 * . As the prejudice, however, against *' humility" broke down, there was wide room for sympathy, equality and kind- ness. At the same time that dyafloTrotta, dvc&KaKta and ficrpioira. 0ea flourish, (forces that would help to break down that prejudice and to create the necessary environment for "humility") real strength, including audacity, courage and /xcyaXoepyta, gradually vanishes, and an epoch of weakness is ushered in, also fostering a constantly growing humility 19 ', for these virtues inevitably acted and reacted upon one another 20 . The previous study of nanim and of Ta7ruvopoW/jia, associated with ev? & rov e/oetv dveiKaKa>s. Themistius 9 defines the dveiKaKia of Sthenelus, by Opposing to him rbv & ov o-reyovra vppw; no comment follows. Thus after Cicero, we find in Greek literature, outside of Plutarch, a decided appreciation of the virtue of dve&KaKia and signs that the virtue was cultivated. Its scope is not so clearly defined as in Plutarch, though it implies, at least, an 2. Cic. Alt. 5.11. 3. N. T. Tim. ii. 2.24. 4. Epict. Ench. 10. Arr. Epict. 3.20.9. 5. L,ucian: Judic. Voc. 9; Asin. 2; De. Par. S3. 6. Hdn. 3.8. 7. Poll. 5.138. 8. Diog-. L,. 221. 9. Themist. 271 B. 33 endurance of abuse, a considerable humility and control of anger 10 . The extent of Plutarch's 4 * forbearance'' was remarkable, overcoming Tipo/xa, leading- to acts of charity toward the feeble and even toward a foe, bringing about extreme mild- ness toward erring servants, and inducing the cultivation of dopyijo-t'a, ei'a and with /aeyaA.oi/a>xi, on the hypothesis that weakness may be strength. Plutarch's broad interpretation of dve&KaKi'a may, perhaps, have been far in advance of the average conception of the virtue, but even this implies an actual exercise of dve&KaKia in the pagan world, though its scope may generally have been more limited. From the Septuagint 12 with its approval of dvei*aKui and imtiKaa toPorphyrogenitus 13 who bears witness to the inclu- sion of this virtue in the body of Christian ideals, we have, in Ecclesiastic Greek, an important line of evidence touching the feeling entertained toward avcgiKaKia by a large community of Greek speaking people, distributed over the entire pagan world. In Justin Martyr 14 , dve&Kcuoa is not only strongly approved, but partially defined by reference to exhortations of Christ 1 5 and by association with dopy^o-ia and viro^ovr). Clemen- tin 1 6 refers to an incident of self-control in Peter's life and the 10. While we find such older terms as cyx/m-reia, jca/orepta, aopyrjo-ta, etc -> in the passages, cited above, yet dve&KaKia, as under- stood in the first century A. D. and afterwards, was a virtue that hardly fitted into the older pagan world, and the dveiKaKux of Epictetus could hardly have corresponded to the virtue of the Homeric Greek, which Themistius calls dveiKaKia. 11. Plut. ii. 90 K, 464 C, 489 C, i. 220 E, i. 290 F, ii. 459 C. 12. L,XX. Sap. 2.19. 13. Porph. Cer. i.62. 16; 574.7. 14. Just. M. Apol. i.16. 15. N. T. Matth. 5. 39.40; ItAav0/o7rias vTrep/JoAi/. The evidence drawn from this source, covering- a wide period of time and extending over a great reach of territory, demonstrates the unreserved practice of &vciKa,KM on the part of those to whom Judaism and Christianity appealed. The practice of this virtue involved a degree of patience, of humility, of weakness and meekness, submission to misfor- tune, of philanthropy, with complete suppression of pride, which only piety and religious zeal could have inspired. 20 In the matter of ''forbearance", then, Plutarch occupied a middle ground, between the position taken by most pagan Greeks of the first and second centuries A. D., on the one hand, and that of the Christians of the same period and later. If Plutarch was not ready to make concessions that seemed necessary and noble to Christians, he was, neverthe- less, ahead of his age in generosity. The essential weakness of /xerpioTrdfleia reappears in its offspring virtue of dveiKa/a'a; but in the case of the latter virtue, Plutarch is more aware of that lack of strength than in the case of the former. Progressus in dve&KaKi'a was, significantly enough, accom- panied by a development of do/oy^o-ca, which, a "defect" in Aristotle, is highly praised by Plutarch, though an amiable weakness. If able to embrace the virtue of dve&KaKia, as in- terpreted by Plutarch, the old Greek pride was .broken, his character was tempered and humbled; it meant a new toler- ance, which was sure to destroy the old idea of rt/xwpta and to be of the utmost consequence to slaves. The inherent possi- bilities of the Plutarchean dve&Ka/aa appear, however, in their 17. Basil, iv. 460.B. 18. Macar. 233 D. 19. Bus. ii. 989 C. 20. We find in the passages (14-19) such older words as dopyiycrta, VTTO/XOVT/, irpa.6rr)<: all of which, whatever their his tory, eventually helped to make dvei/ca/a'a possible. 35 bloom, only later, in the ecclesiastical literature. The pos- sible effects of ave&KdKia were far-reaching. The record of the actual effects of di/ei/caKia in Plutarch's day indicates the great circle of its activity, the numerous directions in which it was affecting Greek Ethics and Greek Life. While the weakness of /u,ei7>io7ra0a was veiled, no similar doubt existed about di/ci/poi'A.ai/0- powria, a>s dya&wroios eo*Tiv. Hermas 11 throws further light on the position of the aya0o7roids in life, whose virtues include WMTTIS, a\.yOeia, VTTO/AOV^, TO X^P 015 VTrrjptTtlv and i\oevia. The "Testamenta Patriarch arum" 12 and Diog- netus 13 simply re-affirm the position of Clemens Romanus, while Clenlens Alexandrinus 1 4 defines the ayaOoTroda of the perfect man, who submerges his own interests in the greater benefits of all others. Clemens Alexandrinus, Paulus Alex- andrinus 15 and Eusebius 16 use the term, also, in an astrono- mical sense, of the stars. lamblichus' 17 statement is another predication of this virtue, of the gods. 5. Artem. 4.59. 6. Ptol. Tetrab. 38, 19.48; Bibl. i.19. 7. Hermes Tr. latrotn. 388.10. 8. Sext. Emp. M. ii. 70. 9. Clem. R. 2.10; i.2; i.344. 10. Athenag. 952A. 11. Hermas, Mand. 8; Vis. 3.9. 12. Patriarch. 1337 C. 13. Diognet. 1176 A. 14. Clem. Al. i. 1348 A. 692 C, (ii. 460A. 15. Paul. Al. iv. init. 16. Eus. P. E. 275 D. 17. Iambi. 52.18. 37 The governing motive of dyaOotroua is not far to seek; its religious character is very pronounced ! The unrestricted limits within which we find the activity, implied in a'ya007roua, exercised, is, also, most important, as it clearly indicates the breadth of the sympathy of the age that first brought the idea prominently forward in literature, which means, in life. The sacrifice, necessary for dveiKcuaa, grows apace with the development of aya&wroud; but that sacrifice was a possibility through the religious impulse back of it. While the evidence drawn from Plutarch himself is slight, that obtained from other sources renders clearer to our minds the possible and the probable status of dyaOo-n-oua. for Plutarch and his age. These side lights establish the same impression that our previous study of Ta7ravoocrw77, per pioira&eia and dve&KaKta has created. The four virtues are so closely involved that it is almost impossible to dissociate them; contemporaneous, in fact, they must have acted upon one another, withal that each had its own special functions. It is not impossible to conceive of aya&wroua 18 a s the crown of them all, pledge and product of their sincerity. KoLvaxf>\ia l and and /^yaXax^eXifc are clearly closely related. We find both of the words, for the first time, in literature of the first century A. D. or shortly before. Each activity was, plainly, a possibility in the atmosphere, created by the earlier feelings implied by ra.ireivopoxs to-riv ayovos, and (2) to his characterization of Joseph's upright states- manship and judgment as /cou/axM-eT?. Perhaps one could hardly speak dogmatically of the true meaning of KoivA>/s, as applied by Plutarch to Antigonus, successor of Alexander. Diodorus Siculus 4 clearly limits the possible Koivwpoarvvr), /JLerpiOTrdOtia, aveiKaKta and aya&wroad, and expressed by Kotvox^fiAta. Whether the wide philanthropy of Koivu>poo8oia is found in the Septuagint and in Aristeas and in Polybius, but appears much more frequently in and after the first century A. D.! There is no ambiguity about the meaning of the word, no question about the exist- ence of "frivolity" and "conceit", no doubt about the feeling entertained toward these. From the testimony of the Septuagint 2 that idols have come into the world through the Kevo8o&a of men (frivolous- mindedness), to that of Aristeas 3 that the tastes of the Kcvo8ooi are inferior, we pass to Polybius 4 who not only con- 12. As shown by our study of /xerpiOTra^cta, aveiKa/aa, dya0O7roua; we do not mean moral weakness. 13. EJven in the direction of KOivox^eAta, which might have been fully realized, if /xcyaAoepyia had been genuine. 14. The /xyaA.o- compounds in the older literature, whether of mind, of soul, courage, labor, speech, reputation or generosity, are numerous: /AyaAo-0v/u.os, -yva>/M,a>v, -o8oos, -0800/305, -ovota, -77*01/77/309, -Trpay/uxoi/, -TrpeVeia, -O-XTJ/AODV, -, .^u;(ta, //.eyc-ATp/opta, /txeyaAr/vopca. /u,eya. Aoepyta represents no new concept, but a return in thought (cf. also /xeyaA.o7roie'a>) to the past, glowing with great deeds. 1. Kevoeov, /cevoAoyc'w, KCVOTT/S (and also /xtKpoAoyia) are terms found in the older literature, as well as a number of other KCVO- com- pounds, less important. The idea of Ktvo8oia is not an altogether new one, but the frequent use of the word in later literature gives it great significance. 2. LrXX. Sap. 14.14. 3. Aristeas 2. 4. Polyb. 3.81.9; 27.6.12; 10.33.6; 39.1.1. 43 demns Hasdrubal, the Carthaginians, Polyaratus for which he associated with other evils as dXa^oveta and but also, through Hannibal, complains that ^poirei-aa, 0V/AOS aAoyos, Ki/o8oi'a and TVOOS. Further, Kcvo8o&a is included in a category of other social evils, presumably con- temporaneous. o KcvoSo^os was a fact in the life of Marcus Aurelius 9 , who scorns such a one and his "little glory", 8oapuH/. According to Arrian 10 and Epictetus, the law takes cognizance of the *evo8oos who is set down with the aAao>v. Lmcian 11 humorously represents Hermes as begging Zeus to lay aside dA.aoveia, a/xatfta, Kcvo8ota, TV&a. Polycarp 14 had said to the Roman proconsul, with scorn, t KevoSo&Is. Clemens Romanus 1 5 in a letter to the Corinthians promises them salvation, if they cast off injustice, strife, malice, slander, pride, "vain- glory". Ignatius 16 betrays his aversion to KcvoSo&a, by prais- ing those who have in place of it, love of the Lord. In the language of the Tatian 17 the same feeling exists. Kuse- bius 18 ridicules a certain Lacydas for his *voSo&a, while, fin- ally, in ChrySOStomUS 19 we read: o yap TeraTreivayieVos KCU TrX^crtov, OVK aAAo rt S&rat Traces, which, open to but one interpretation, brings the same conviction that the previous testimonies have created. We have, thus, abundant evidence of the long-continued, wide-spread evil of KevoSo&a, which, signifying, now, "friv- olity", now, "conceit", meaning frivolous-mindedness, vanity, vain-glory is combated as an existing evil ! not only in the Plutarchean age (when the Kevo8oos was a well-known type of the day), but before and after that time as well, an evil deep-rooted in the character of the Greek of the first century A. D.I Such a mental state implies a loss of greater or more serious interests. It is a state of mind that belongs to men of lesser intellectual stature; it is significantly enough but once applied to a Roman, and then, hypothetically. With its signification of "frivolity", its effect on politics is obvious; meaning also "conceit", its influence in the realm of ethics upon the new ethical standard would be equally deleterious. It was an excess, doubtless, of Kevo8ota that pro- voked the opposition to it that we have noted; that very excess carried with it the possibility of a cure and might in time inspire the opposite virtue of real modesty which the Christian Fathers exhorted. As long, however, as *evoooia flourished, there was little 14. Polyc. 10. 15. Clem. R. i.35. 16. Ignat. 697 A.B. 17. Tatian. 832 B. 18. Eus. (Numen. apud) iii.!209A. 19. Joan. Chrys. vii. 43 A. 45 hope for raTreivo^poo-uny, and the evil of KcvoSo&a, "conceit", without doubt, was one of the forces that interfered with the development of raTravo^pocrwr/ 2 . The weakness of "friv- olity" (K/o8o|ia) co-operated with that of /xerpioTrafleia and of dve&Ka/a'a, and helps to explain the negative element in ayaOowoda and the negative nature of /AtyaAoepyia, while the "vanity" of *evo8ox would prevent the state of equality essential for a Utopian Kou>o>eA.ta. Vanity, pride? conceit 21 were, as every one knows, essen- tial qualities of the pagan world. But the Greek world had not, before this, reached the point where it could pronounce that judgment upon itself, which we read in the word KevoSota itself, and hear proclaimed in literature from Polybius to Heliodorus. The study of Kevo8ox admirably shows the position of the Greek of the first century A. D., who is still Greek, to the extent that he is "vain", KevoSoos, but un-Greek, in that he condemns that pride and holds it sinful or "frivolous". Here we find (as in /AeyoAoepyia) the possible genesis of a melancholy, which manifests itself more pronouncedly in II eptavToA.oy t'a . Let us subordinate TrepiairroA.oyi'ct to KvoSoi'a, to which it is very closely related. The word TrepiavToAoyi'a appears for the first time in Plutarch. The quality of "boastfullness" that it refers to, is one that existed long before Plutarch and one for which there were many other expressions. t'a, /xeyaAvyyopi a, KOJOLTTO^O), /co/x,7rea> ? vj/^AoAoyeo/Aai, , ), crrw/xvXt'a, OTo/AUH; this is a partial list of the earlier terms denoting- "boasting-". In view of these many terms, the appearance of 7repiavToA.oyi'a is all the more remark- able.) The coinage of this new term and, no less, the continuance, in use, of the group of older terms, evince the persistence of certain 20. Cf. previous study of 21. We need but to recall ^avvoriys, /ouxratoT^s, ayAatd, avflaSta, oy/U /ACOTOTIJS per /ncyaA.oi/'vxi'a, virepftoXrj & xavvor^s rt? 46 features of Greek character, certain qualities that were a heritage of the past (cf. also TaTruvopoa"uvrj discussion) and which were not easily surrendered ! (The vitality of the term is of much significance and is such as to dispel any suspicion that, because the cases of occurrence of the term are rather infrequent the quality was of little consequence in life.) Plutarch's (Plut. ii. 29B; ii. 41C; ii. 539C) condemnation of TrepiavToAoyta is expressed in no uncertain terms; together with p,eyaA- it is contrasted with arvia and /AeTpwmys; it is characterized as e's and avfXf.v6f.pov and the moralist adds: pyo> 8'ov TroAAot rrjv arfitav OLVTOV oVaTrc^evyaaiv. Sextus Bmpiricus (Sext. EJmp. 77-. Y. i- 62.) mocks the dogmatists whom he criticizes as rerv^xofiei/wv KCU TrepiavToAo yowTwv. lamblichus (Iambi. 91.8; Myst. 90.9) stigmatizes TrepiavToAoyux, calling it TO aTrarrjXov. Porphyrius, (Porphyr. Aneb. 32.12) claiming that TO TreptavToAoyetv was common to gods, demons and other superior beings, and was token of the god's presence, is contradicted by lamblichus, who grants them truth, instead of "boasting". Origen's (Origen. i. 752B) words are significant: eviSetv & rri KCU TO> TOV 'Irjo-ov r)Qa Travra^ov 7Tfpuo~Tafjivov TT/v TrepiavToAoytav /cat Sta TOVTO AeyovTOs: "Kav eyto CITTW Trept /w,avTOi, y fjMpTvpui fwv ovK Icmv oA^T/s." Eustathius (Eust. 100. 37; 897.2) describing Nestor, says, without disapproval, TOIOVTOS ovv 6 Ne'oTwp wv TroXXaxov TrcpiavToXoyei, while, in another passage, interpreting Homer, his language is as follows: IO-TCOV 8c KCU on *c TOV ivTavOa Kvpto. XCKTOV/M6VOV KO/XTTCIV TO KO/XTTCI^CIV TTttp^/CTttl, O TTttptt TOt? Vpocrvvi] and ttve&KaKta. But just as far as KevoSo^ta interrupted the progress of Tairwopojnos, CVT/KOOS. IleiflT/vios may have been formed after analogy of Trcto-t^aXivos or TrtiOapx"*-', what motive was behind the creation of this new term it were difficult to determine. ) is another member of the new vocabulary of the first century A. D. and reveals considerable regarding the problem of "obedience". When Plutarch (Pint. ii. 592 B; ii. 90 B; ii. 442 C; ii. 102 F; ii. 369 C; ii. 1029 E; i. 58 D; i. 176 A; i. 596 C; i. 878 F.) refers to Roman or to Spartan life, "obedience" is explicitly represented as due to the authority of law and of administration; these instances are, perhaps, cited as usual in Plutarch's Laves for emulation. Within the limits of Greek conduct, reason and divine power are in control and exact "obedience". Philo (Philo. i. 184.5.) also imagines reason as mistress of the soul, while to the mind of Clemens Alexandrinus (Cl. Al. i. 1012 B; ii. 460 A. ) the supreme power is vested in God, whose example is fol- lowed in worldly affairs and to whom "obedience" is due. (We also find the term in M. Anton, (i. 17), who rejoiced in a wife, 7rei#r/nos and r)v , and other similar lines do not represent the prevailing 10. Clem. Al. i. 532 B; i. 216 B. 11. Diog. L. 6.26; 9.68. 12. Diogenes L/aertius is probably no more quoting- exactly, here, than before, in the case of p; Tpio7ra0tta. (Cf. previous treatment of that word. ) 13. Stob. 534.23. 14. 5i/ KcvocTTrovStav. It is little likely, we think, that Socrates knew this word which we find, first, in Hipparchus and in Cicero. 50 spirit of the earlier age, nor is melancholy characteristic, in general, of the Greek nature, which, active, boastful, talkative, fickle, not above lying, beaut3 7 -loving, speculative and brave, was not pessimistic. We find no Lucretius, no Rubaiyat in Greek literature ! The consciousness of the folly and futility and emptiness of human endeavor does, however, assert itself more strongly after the great conquests, and the presence of this word, under consideration, is no less a sign of that feeling than was the rise of a School of Skeptics much earlier. But the Greek was not incurably pessimistic and even TIJS 8c Ka/ctas di/aTreTrA^o-Ttu Trai/ra Trpay/xara KCU iras 6 /3ios Ta/oaTTO/acvo? Kai /xvySev ^a>v /xcpos KaOapbv prfi avf.TriXffirrov , a>s OVTOI Aeyowi, (i.e. the Stoics) atcr^tcrrov OTI Spa/txaTwv airdvTwv Kai are/o- Trco-raTov 1 5 represents onty one side of Stoicism, and even such strong condemnations provoked, in time, only a feeling of equality and of wider sympathy, but not of despair. Thes ad- ness of Kevoo-Trov&a is, however, indisputable. KevooTTouSox, involving TViA.o7rovos and of 4>iAaA.i}0T75, is, like KcvoSo&'a, twin-sister of /u,i*/oo/oyta, and becomes a true expression of a petty age that worshiped ^eyaAoepyia as a distant ideal ! Pride, feebleness and sadness were conspicuous among the qualities of the Greek of Plutarch's centur ! We find /xaraio., compounded with nouns of action 1 occa- sionally before the first century A. D., but such cases are sporadic in comparison with the numerous later occurrences. MaratoTrovta is applied to a wide range of activities, being even predicated, though negatively, of God and of Nature. MaratoTTovta is by no means a new idea in Greek life, within which, from Homer's time on, much TTOI/OS or O-TTOV^ must have seemed /xdVaios. The later interpretation of what constituted /xaraioTTovta is also quite a universal one, and Polybius and Livy, Strabo and Pheidias, Plutarch and Plato, Lmcian and Homer might easily have been in agreement, touching the 15. Plut. ii. 1066 A. (cf. too ii. 478 A. seq). 1. We have taken into consideration, /Lumuorrovia, -TrovTj/Aa, -Trpayta, -epyta. 51 folly of what is termed t^raioirovia. But as in the case of Kvo(T7rov8ia, the later close association of /uarcuo- with a con- siderable number of other ideas is significant; the words thus formed w^ere not fashioned for a day, and suggest the growth of a feeling of /WXTCUOTT/S! Polybius 2 records his own keen disapproval of /w.aTcuo7rovia, as well as that of the Romans. The scholiasts 3 of Aristophanes and of Sophocles used the term /AaratoTroveo) to define less well- known words from their authors; Qopvfteiv and Kova \.a\tiv, also employed to illuminate the same text, at the same time also explain the commentator's attitude toward an existing /AaToioTrona. Strabo 4 finds an example of ^wnuorw^, in the case of an Egyptian temple of barbaric KOTOO-KCWJ, which, to his mind, possessed little of grace. Philo 5 denies that the quality of /xaraioTrovux can be predicated either of Nature or of God. His conception of /AaraioTrovia is graphically stated: vyirtttiv TraiSwv . . . . o t 7roAA.ouas Trap' aiytaXots dflv/oorrcs if/d/JLfjLov yecuAo^ovs 8iavrTa\vapiav, Kpiphan- 2. Polyb. 9.2.2; 25.5.11. 3. Schol. Ar. Plutus. 575; Soph. O. T. 887. 4. Strabo. 806. 5. Philo. 2.500; 2.98.52. 6. Plut. ii. 119 D. 7. L,uc. Dial. Mort. 10.8. 8. Iambi. Vita Pyth. 24. 9. Clementina, i. 60 B; i. 27. B. 10. Just. Frag-. 1585 A. 11. Olymp. A. 41 C. 52 ius' 1 * condemnation of /u-aTcuocpyia { s not less unequivocal. Philostorgius 18 , also, draws from his own experience for an illustration of /txaraioo-TrovSta, which is used of idle, trivial oc- cupation 14 . We have, thus, a record of a -wide-felt disapproval of a wide-spread iMraunrovial In the light of the evidence furnished by Ko/oo-Trou&a, the development is strongly suggested of an atmosphere of idleness and of inactivity, or one of labor and zeal that were trivial and therefore condemned. The words of Plutarch 1 ' 5 are, perhaps, significant in this connection: KCU /xdAi? av vvv o\rj ['EAAas] 7rapa7ra> vcpovn. Evidence of the Same weariness appear in the language of Strabo 16 who writes of Athens that her navy was "almost extinct, that little re- mained of her Long Walls, and of the lower cit_y no more than a small part of the maritime quarter". Thebes was hardly deserving of the name of village, and the same was true of all the Boeotian towns except Tanagra and Thespiae. Dion 17 gives a more picturesque description of Thebes when he says that "only a single statue stood erect among the ruins of the ancient market-place". Pausanias 18 in the second century, is our best witness of "shrunken or ruined cities, deserted villages, roofless temples, shrines without images and pedestals without statues, faint vestiges of places 12. Epiph. i. 417 A. 13. Philostorg-. H. E. 11.1. 14. MaTuiooTTrov&a is found in Suicer, with this comment: ovupntv SiaAAaTToucm/ at TOJV av0pa>7ra>i/ /txaTaiooTrovSiai. Eu.stathius (543) uses ^aratoTrpayta of the idle, lazy, useless exertion of Homeric heroes. Of the numerous fjM.ra.io- compounds, some are, of course, earlier, some later, in origin; /xaraioAoyco), like ^wpoAoyia, /xi/cpoAoyta, \vapia and AuAf'o) and KCvoAoyta belong-s to the older literature. We have chosen and treated /xaratOTrovta, because of its close relation with Kei/oorrov&a. MaTaiore^vta is also interesting and is defined by Quintilian (2.20.3) as "supervacua artis imitatio, quae nihil sane neque boni neque mali habeat, seel vanum laborem". 15. Plut. ii. 414 A. 16. Strabo. ix. 1 and 2. 17. Dion. Chr. vii. Or. p. 136. Dind. 18. Frazer: Pausanias. p. xiv. Intr. (with ref's) vol. i. 53 that once had a name and played a part in history". It is well-known that through imperial favor Greece enjoyed, for two centuries, a high degree of tranquillity and of repose; this but encouraged her own settled calm, her state of leth- argy and of exhaustion. When men are strong- and are vitally engaged in their own occupations, which are all- absorbing, then /aaratoTrovta and Ko/oo-TrouSux are foreign to their lives; the temper of this age, however, of Plutarch's age was not far removed from "/xaratOTrys /xaTv, ewrev 6 7S, /Maraiorr/s /x,aTcuoT7;Tta is evidenced no less than his belief that the evil was a universal one in time and place. Plutarch's 2 sweeping denunciation of ^lo-aScA^wi grew out of the bitterness of his conviction that i\a\\r]\ia, d8eA.^>OTi^, iXopoia, likewise was favorable toward a universal friendship; the leveling tendency of these habits of thought broke down narrow, local prejudices and made for the cosmopolitanism, represented by 6 K While ^oTTottd, with a moral suggestion, was not unknown to Aristotle 1 & 2 , while to rhetoricians after Callistratus ^Ooiroua was well-known as a rhetorical term, in the first centur} 7 A. D. the word acquired a deep ethical significance of genuine value ! The positive moral signification that the word then carries points, perhaps, to a deeper interest in the moral activity that the term defines ! Plutarch's well-known moral purpose, both in the 44 Mor- alia" and in the ' 'Lives" 3 , lends special interest to his frequent use 4 of the term yOoTroda. His discriminating use of 1. Arist. irX. i. 955a 32. This case in Aristotle seems to be unique. 2. Another passage, Rh. iii. 7., illustrates a step in the formation of the term, eav TO. ovofjua.ro. ot/caa Aey?; rfj !ci, irouqcrti TO rjOos. 3. Plut. Pericl. 2. 4. Plut. i. 71 B; i. 961 D; ii. 814 A; ii. 660 B; ii. 799 B; i. 153 B; i 112 B; ii. 1U53 D; ii. 450 F; 1.53 A. 56 i.e., in associating- it with peace, bravery and justice in the case of the Romans, and with <povifav and with noble pleasures in the case of the earlier Greeks suggest elements of his own moral ideal. Plutarch allows a wide range of rjOoTToiia, applying it to Spartans, to Sicilian Greeks and to his own times, socially and politically. There is no question of his own concern for philanthropy and fora "formation of character" which shall be secure! Philo 5 , in the interests of an actual JjOorroda, declares the possibility of its realization through religion and through philosophy. In the absence of an exacter definition of the ?0<>s, we can only conclude the presence of a desire for a noble "character formation". Strabo 6 , in a dissertation on the humanizing results of Roman conquest, counts ^Wood among- the signs of civiliza- tion. 'HfloTroua mig-ht, of course, according to the significa- tion of the ?0os, have a bad sense, as when referring- to the ayo>y^v TWV irapa rot? KtvatSots 8iaA.eKra>v *at rfjs rjfloTrouas, in Ionia. The stricter moral sense, with an exhortation to practice, recurs in Clemens 7 of Alexandria: TrpaK-riKo? & wv 6 TratSaywyos, irporepov fiev as 8ta0rjpo(rvvr)^ /AerpioTra&ia, ave&KUKi'a, dya&wroua, KOIVCO- . Spengel. 15. Bust. 1955.54 and 49. 16. avrjOoiroirjTos occurs in Cic. ad Alt. 10.10.5, meaning "immoral". 58 LIST OF WORDS. PAGK KcuvoAoyta . . . . . 19 Evpeo-iAoyta ..... 20 TaTravo? ..... 22 .... 26 .... 29 .... 32 .... 36 ia and MeyaAox^eAi/s . . 38 MeyaAoepyi'a ..... 41 Kevo8oux . . . . . 43 IlepiuvToAoyia .... 46 UuOrjVLOS ..... 48 KevocrrrovSta, ..... 48 MttTatOTrona . . . . . 51 Mta-aSeX^ta ..... 54 Kocr/xoTToXtrr/? . . . . 55 'H007TOI&X 56 59 CONCLUSIONS. In the previous discussion it has been shown that all of these words are expressions, concrete symbols of real facts in the Greek life of the first century A. D. The ethical move- ments that these words evidence were genuine factors in the life of the age that Plutarch represents. There w)(ere certain virtues in process of development, that were encour- aged, some of them more fully realized, others less so; there were certain vices whose existence was deplored and condemned. The words themselves are partial evidence of the ethical situation, inasmuch as we can be certain that they were vital, (compare Chapter on "Method", also KawoXoyta and cvpeo-iAoyia) ; their acceptance in the language, their long history shows them to be precipitates of genuine thinking and feeling of serious import. The extent of that ethical vocabulary, (which goes back in its beginning at least to the time of Pol3 T bius, and which developed in the time of Plutarch and includes both new ideas and old ones reinforced or altered), is further evidence of the width and depth of the moral agitation of the first century A. D. The ideas and conduct these words portray were determinative, and quite full testimony of such conduct is received from the lit- erature before and after Plutarch's time representing actual conditions in life, as well as ideals 1 . The moral ideal of Plutarch is our immediate concern, but while we can establish certain data of his ethical stan- dard, some of these data appear to be true for the whole century as well, as we find the same attitude observed in further literary and other sources of the same time as that of the great representative Boeotian; this attitude, develop- 1. It is thought that a complete study of the history of the entire ethical vocabulary found in Plutarch must make quite clear the nature of the moral ideal of the Greeks of the first century A. D., which is by no means as yet fully understood. 60 ing before, finally became established in the first century A. D. and continued long after, not only in time but also in place 2 . That moral agitation, which was undoubted^ sincere and deep rooted, is, in part at least, defined by the study we have made of a portion of the ethical terminolog} 7 , which is no less a positive record of moral progress than the marbles of a fallen temple are witness of an ancient glory 3 . Plutarch's ethical ideal included the virtues of and combated the evils of Kei/o8oia, TreptavroXoyta, ta, /xaraioTrovta; the ethical movement had a definite relation to the past but was also firmly established in the new conditions of the later age. Taireivopo7ri'a; ayaOairoua had a clear religious implication and Kou/o>po